ANTINOMIANISM OF MODERN HISTORIANS 211 dant, but awkwardly scarce;1 and the question on which the possibility of ascertaining 'laws of Nature1 in this episode of history turned was the question whether the significant known integral events were actually numerous enough to provide a basis for generalizations. This experience is described in the following testimony from the pen of a practised investigator of the working of 'laws of Nature' on the economic plane of latter-day Western social life : 'The volume of economic statistics is certainly imposing—it is even intimidating at first sight. But on closer inspection the mass proves to consist less of a multiplication of independent observations upon parti- cular phenomena than of observations upon a vast variety of phenomena, and of the infinite detail in which certain processes must be observed.. . . As an investigator gets deeper into a quantitative analysis of business cycles, his first impression that the statistical data to be dealt with are embarrassingly abundant turns into a conviction that they are painfully inadequate.'2 The agnostics who put their finger on the scarcity of significant known events as their ground for denying the possibility of discerning 'laws of Nature' in the history of Man in Process of Civilization were thus at any rate nearer the mark—mistaken though they too might be—than their fellow agnostics whose identical denial was based on the contradictory thesis that the hoppers in their factory had been choked by a plethora of overproduction. This case for agnosticism on the ground, not of a redundancy in the data, but of an insufficiency, is judiciously presented in the following passage from the pen of a distinguished twentieth-century Western historian: 'The reading public asks for a final interpretation of History, and for an answer to the question why civilisations rise and fall. Is there, as Hume thought, a tidal movement in human affairs and nothing more than this tidal ebb and flow ? Is there no hope of stability or of unmixed achieve- ment in the temporal sphere ? Or can it be said that, in spite of ages of regression towards barbarism, historians are able to bring evidence of progress towards a desirable end ? *To these questions British historians are not very ready to give an answer, and, in general, the answers which are given are not put forward by the most learned or the most profound scholars. In the preface to his History of Europe, H. A. L. Fisher wrote that he had no ultimate philo- sophy of history. Such a view does not imply scepticism, or even lack of belief in the possibility of a final synthesis. The difficulty at present is that the data are insufficient.3 To a historian the history of the World of Man is a very short history. The years of the astronomers and the geolo- gists reach beyond a historian's reckoning; a small fraction only of these vast epochs is covered by the period during which Man, with knowledge * See I. i. 455-6. * Mitchell, W. C.: Business Cycles: The Problem and Its Setting (New York 1927, National Bureau of Economic Research, Inc.), pp. 203 and 205. 3 'It is not—to my mind—altogether paradoxical to say also that we know too much. I mean, we know so many facts which lend themselves to arrangement in patterns that of this Study).