VARIOUS USES OF FACTORS 23 the inductive * guesswork' has been fortified by three different appeals—first, by emphasizing the simplicity of the conclusions drawn; secondly, by emphasizing the positive analogies within the phenomena compared; thirdly, by relying on a priori plausibility to supplement the a posteriori inferences. (a) The Appeal to Simplicity.—Natura est simplex, said Newton ; and factorists commonly begin by declaring that the aim of factor-analysis, as of every form of scientific analysis, is to discover the simplest possible formulation of the facts.1 Conversely, when a simplified formulation has been successfully attained, its very simplicity is supposed to guarantee its truth—a guarantee which could never be claimed on inductive principles alone. Thus, the tables of correlations met with in psychology often show patterns 1 The section * On the Nature of Science ' with which Thurstone opens his statement of the * factor problem ' ([84], chap. I, pp. 44 et seq.} suggests this standpoint. " To discover a scientific law," he says, " is merely to discover that a man-made scheme serves to unify, and thereby to simplify, comprehension of a certain class of natural phenomena." Similarly, Kelley, in introducing his * new method of analysis/ defends it on the ground of * simplicity,' and adds: " to create such simplicity is a basic purpose of factorization" ([84], p. 3). Analogous phrases could be quoted from Spearman, Thomson, Guilford, and many others who have discussed the aims of factor-analysis. The same postulate is more particularly invoked where the mathematical analysis alone would not lead to a unique solution. A striking instance, as we shall see, is Thurstone's proposal to accept that particular mathematical solution which conforms to the requirements of * simple structure.* This is in keeping with a well-known practice of physicists, Thus, Jeffreys, in analysing experimental data obtained to illustrate the quantitative laws of mechanics, observes that, as a matter of fact, the law or formula that every physicist would accept ** is only one of an infinite number of laws that would fit the data equally well: its special quality, that distinguishes it from the other possible laws, is its simplicity " (Scientific Inference, p. 37 : his italics.) A more general discussion of the problem from a logical standpoint is under- taken by Johnson in connexion with * functional induction.' " The mathe- matician," he writes, would " point out that there are an infinity of different functions that would exactly fit any finite number of cases of covariation. ... To escape this threatening annihilation of inductive inference, we may indicate two fundamental criteria . . .: first, reliance is placed upon the character of the formula itself, in particular on its comparative simplicity ; second, its higher credibility depends upon its analogies with other well- established formulae " (Logic, Pt* II, chap, xi, pp. 250-1).