DERIVATION OF CHIEF THEORIES 157 saturation coefficients for the specific factors are also included, then the symmetry is appreciably reduced.1 And generally the results of all subsequent calculations, based on the correlation matrix, con- form much better with general expectation, if communalities alone are included and specific factors excluded. Thurstone, for example, having first expressed the * factorial matrix ' as the sum of three * components,' F^ + Dl + Z)2 ([84], p. 54), in most of his later deductions ignores the matrices D± and Z>2, which contain the ' n specific factors ' and the * n error factors,' and, as I have done, bases his arguments on the c reduced correlation matrix ' R = F^F^ ([84], pp. 66*tseq.). Thus Thurstone, whose theory is essentially a generalization of Spearman's, begins by including specific factors in Spearman's sense of the phrase : for, like Spearman, Stephenson, and most other members of the English school, he assumes that all tests or traits have precisely the same variance (p. 62). But in practice he confines himself to the extraction of general or common factors only, and would in principle make the number of those factors a minimum (p. 73). Hence, for Thurstone as for Spearman, the specific factor of a test must again be simply the balance left over from the arbitrarily assumed variance when the portion due to general or common factors has been deducted. In fact, the amount of variance due to the specific factor in a given test j (our sf) is explicitly set equal to I — hj2 — Cj2, where cf is defined as the 6 error variance,' and hf as the ' common factor variance '—usually termed * communality ' for short (our g2 + 2/p/; p. 68). Thus the specific variance of a test is not an independently determined quantity at all. It may be added that, on the theory held by Spearman and Thurstone, the simplest type of mental process (one therefore which would have the smallest number of common factors and would usually be the one measurable with the least amount of error) has the same total variance as the most complex type of mental process ; it must therefore contain a specific factor having the greatest amount of individual variability in the popu- lation tested. Now this is not only contrary to what we should expect a priori from the additive nature of variance, but also in conflict with direct observation : for, wherever we can measure a trait in absolute terms, we find that the more complex mental processes nearly always show a far wider range of individual variation than the simpler, and usually involve a larger amount 1 This is shown in computations made by Woods and later by Davies and Eysenck, who tried the symmetry criterion with both forms of the correlation matrix.