ARISTOTLE'S PSYCHOLOGY

A TREATISE ON THE PRINCIPLE OF LIFE

{DE ANIMA and PARVA NATUBALIA,

TRANSLATED WITH INTRODUCTION AND NOTES

BY

WILLIAM ALEXANDER HAMMOND, M.A., Ph.D.

ASSISTANT-PROFESSOR OF ANCIENT AND MEDIAEVAL PHILOSOPHY IN CORNELL UNIVERSITY

bonbon SWAN SONNENSCHEIN & CO., Lim.

NEW YORK : THE MACMILLAN CO. 1902

4255

GLASGOW : PRINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PRESS BY ROBERT MACLEHOSE AND CO.

r

^0

WILLIAM WATSON GOODWIN,

ELIOT PROFESSOR OF GREEK LITERATURE, EMERITUS,

IN HARVARD UNIVERSITY,

MY FIRST TEACHER IN THE WRITINGS OF ARISTOTLE,

THIS BOOK IS GRATEFULLY INSCRIBED.

PREFACE.

The comparative inaccessibility of the Parva naturalia (they exist in English only in Taylor's paraphrase) has induced me to prepare an English version of these im- portant tractates. To this I have added a translation of the Be anima, in order that English readers might have in a single volume a practically complete account of Aris- totle's psychological theories. Such a work seemed to me to be all the more necessary at the present time in view of the need of available primary sources for historical research in philosophy and psychology. An adequate history of psychology has not as yet been written.

The translation of Aristotle's works, owing to their crabbed Greek, their puzzling lacunae and breviloquence, oftentimes they are almost unintelligible jottings intended, perhaps, for lecture-notes or for later elaboration which they never received, has at no time been regarded by scholars as an easy or attractive task. It is only their immense historical significance and the intrinsic value of their content that could induce one now-a-days to set hand to the work. The Be anima and Parva naturalia

cannot be said to be in a more satisfactory condition

vii

Vlll PREFACE

than the other writings of Aristotle. I have, however, attempted no speculative reconstruction, such as has been applied with some success to the Politics by Barthelemy- St.-Hilaire and Susemihl. The attempt has not been very fortunate in the case of Essen's restoration of the De anima, and, so far as I know, his predecessors in the same endeavour have not been more successful. Growing distrust of the radical treatment of texts seems to me a hopeful mark of critical scholarship. My translation is based on the text of the late Wilhelm Biehl (Teubner series), whose emendations I have constantly compared with the Berlin edition, and with whose conservative judgment I have generally found myself in accord. Where I have deviated from his text, I have stated my reading in a foot-note. In 1897 I made a careful examination of Codex E (Parisiensis Regius 1853), the best of the MSS. for the texts here translated, but as Biehl collated this Codex in the same year and published his Parva natur- alia the year following, my work was rendered unneces- sary. In any case, I was not interested primarily in textual questions, excepting in so far as the establishment of the text was ancillary to the establishment of doctrine. I have aimed, therefore, to avoid the accumulation of notes of a purely scholastic kind, which in the present volume could only be marks of a diligent pedantry, and while I have neglected no source of information and assistance amongst ancient or modern commentators, I have rigidly excluded all such matter as had no real interest for the doctrinal exposition of the treatises in hand, or for the history of science.

PREFACE IX

M. Rodier's text of the De anima with translation and notes (2 vols., Paris, 1900) is a notable product of French scholarship, in which the widely scattered materials of interpretation have been brought together and utilized with singular industry and insight. M. Rodier's volumes have been prepared with a bias of interest different from that with which my own work is written, concerned, as they are, largely with questions of text, of philological criticism, and of the literary aspects of interpretation. They do not include the Parva naturalia. The aim of the present translation and introduction is rather to make easily acces- sible to English scholars the scientific content of these Aristotelian treatises, and thereby to facilitate inquiry into the history of philosophical and psychological ideas. For this reason my work does not duplicate the much wider and more ambitious investigations of M. Rodier, to whose scholarly labour I wish to pay my warmest tribute.

I desire further to record here my grateful acknowledg- ment of various and valuable help from my colleagues. Professors Bennett, Creighton, and Titchener. Professor Titchener has read the proof-sheets of the entire volume, and to him I am especially indebted for many suggestions and criticisms.

Cornell University, Ithaca, N.Y., July 29th, 1902.

CONTENTS.

INTKODUCTION.

PAGE

I. The Soul and Life xv

II. The Faculties of the Soul xxvi

III. Nutrition and Eeproduction xxix

IV. Sensation xxxv

Y. The Common or Central Sense 1

VI. Imagination and Memory lvi

VII. Practical Keason and Will lxiv

VIII. Creative Reason lxxi

DE ANIMA.

Book I. History of Psychological Theories

Chap. i. Methods of investigation, separability of the soul,

relation of soul to body 1

ii. History of theories, theory of Empedocles, theory

of Democritus, theory of Anaxagoras - - 10

iii. The soul and motion, pre- Aristotelian theories - 18 iv. The soul a harmony, the soul and the body, the

monadic theory - 26

v. The soul and the elements, the soul and its parts,

divisibility of the soul 32

Book II. Faculties of the Soul

Chap. i. The notion of substance, definition of the soul - 42 ii. Animate and inanimate, the principle of life, the

soul and body 48

iii. Various meanings of soul ----- 54

XU CONTENTS

PAGE

Chap. iv. Soul and final cause, the soul and nutrition,

principle of nutrition 57

v. Potential and actual, sensation and thought - - 64

vi. Sense-qualities ------- 69

vii. Vision and its medium 71

viii. Sound and its medium, definition of voice, vocal

utterance -------- 75

ix. The sense of smell 82

x. The sense of taste 85

xi. The sense of touch, the medium of touch - - 88 xii. Relation of sense-organ to stimulus, media of

sensation 93

Book III. Sensation, Imagination, and Thought

Chap. i. The ' common sensibles ' 95

ii. Sense-perception, the ' common sense ' - - - 99 iii. Imagination, imagination and truth, imagination

and light - 105

iv. Theory of reason, abstract thought - - - 112

v. Active and passive reason 117

vi. Thought and truth 119

vii. Thought and images, thought and its object- - 122

viii. Ideas and images - 126

ix. Powers of the soul, reason and desire - - - 128

x. Psychology and conduct, function of desire - - 132

xi. The moving principle 136

xii. Nutrition and sensation, sensation and well-being 138

xiii. Sense of touch - - - - - - - 142

PARVA NATURALIA.

On Sensation and the Sensible Chap. i. Purpose of sensation, importance of hearing - - 145 ii. The organs of sense, theories of vision - - 150

iii. The diaphanous, theory of colours, colour and

mixture * 157

CONTENTS Xlll

PAGE

Chap. iv. Nature of flavours, flavour and moisture, sense of

touch 164

v. Nature of smell, function of smell, smell and

respiration, smell and nutrition - - - 171 vi. Sense and magnitude, medium of sensation - - 180 vii. Fusion of sensations, co-ordinate sensations, simul- taneity, limits of perception - - - - 186

II. On Memory and Recollection

Chap. i. Memory and time, memory a picture, memory and

phantasm 195

ii. Association of ideas, processes of memory, recollec- tion 203

III. On Sleeping and Waking

Chap. i. Sleep and sensation, sleep and nutrition - - 213 ii. The central sense, form and matter, movements

in sleep 218

iii. Animal heat and sleep, food and sleep, the blood

and sleep 224

IV. On Dreams

Chap. i. Dreams and illusion .._-_. 231

ii. After-images, the eye and the mirror, illusion - 235 iii. Movement in dreams, imagination in dreams,

dreamless sleep - - 240

V. On Prophecy in Sleep

Chap. i. Prophetic dreams - 247

ii. Power of prevision, interpretation of dreams - 251

VI. On Longevity and Shortness of Life

Chap. i. The tenure of life - - 256

ii. Causes of destruction ------ 258

iii. The perishable and imperishable - - - - 260

iv. Length of life in plants and animals - - - 262

v. Causes of long life ------ 264

vi. Comparative longevity ------ 267

XIV CONTENTS

PAGE

VII. On Youth and Old Age, and on Life and Death

Chap. i. Life and Sensation ------ 270

ii. Unity of the life-principle 273

iii. Development of life --.._. 276

iv. Congenital heat - 279

v. Extinction and exhaustion ----- 281

vi. Regulation of animal heat ----- 284

VIII. On Respiration

Chap. i. Purpose of respiration 286

ii. Aquatic animals 288

iii. Lungs and gills - 290

iv. Theory of Democritus, heat and respiration - - 293

v. Plato's theory of circular movement - - - 296

vi. Pythagorean theory, respiration and nutrition - 298

vii. Theory of Empedocles regarding respiration - 299

viii. Animal heat, regulative function of respiration - 302

ix. Control of temperature, respiration of insects - 304

x. Function of lungs and gills ----- 307

xi. The windpipe and epiglottis - 309

xii. Respiration of whales and dolphins - - - 311

xiii. Lungs and the supply of blood - - - - 313

xiv. A theory of Empedocles, effect of environment - 315

xv. Physiology of heat-regulation - - - - 318

xvi. Position of heart and gills - - - 319

xvii. Birth and death 321

xviii. Causes of death - - 324

xix. Inhalation and exhalation 325

xx. Movements of the heart 326

xxi. Contraction and expansion of lungs, conditions of

life, natural history and medicine, - - - 328

Bibliography 331

INTRODUCTION.

I.

The Soul and Life.

Aristotle's theories regarding the structure and functions of the 'soul' are found chiefly in the De Anima1 and the tractates collectively known as the Parva Naturalia? These works belong to that part of the corpus which deals with what Aristotle understands by Physics, i.e. the world of corporeal substances, sub- stances subject to motion and rest. Mathematical bodies, not being subject to motion, are excluded. Soul is ascribed to all bodies whose principle of motion is inherent in their own nature. In other words, it is to all organic bodies that Aristotle applies the term ; to him the word ' soul ' is synonymous with the word ' life.' Accord- ingly, the higher phenomena of mental life are included among the vital activities. Aristotle, therefore, regards Psychology from the point of view of Biology.

The philosopher of Stagira is known chiefly through his works on Logic, Metaphysics, Ethics, and Politics. It was mainly through these disciplines that he dominated the intellectual development of the western world down to the era of modern science ; and yet his writings on Physics

1 See note, Translation, p. 1. 2See note, Translation, p. 145. xv

xvi INTRODUCTION

occupy more space (taking as a standard the Berlin edition, which contains, it is true, some spurious treatises) than all the other treatises put together. Suidas, indeed, gave him the title of the " Secretary of Nature," while Dante, who was conversant with the speculative or practical side of his philosophy, called him " the master of those that know." 1 The studies of Aristotle appear to have been concerned chiefly with the phenomena of nature, whose processes it was the primary function of his philosophy to explain.

The thing which most astonished Athenaeus (one of the most learned Greeks of the Ptolemaic era) in his reading of Aristotle's works, was the Stagirite's wonderful knowledge of animal life. He says in the Deipnosophists : " Aristotle, my dear Democritus, about whom the sages incessantly talk and whose accuracy they constantly praise, is a marvel to me. I should like to know from what Proteus or Nereus of the deep sea he learned what fish do, how they sleep, how they live. For he has told us in his writings all about these things, so that he has become, in the words of the comic poet, ' a wonder to fools.' " 2

In contrast with this trivial, popular conception of Aristotle's work, I quote here Aristotle's own words touch- ing his attitude towards the various spheres of scientific inquiry, words very significant for their singular catho- licity. " By way of introduction we observe that some members of the universe are ungenerated, im- perishable, and eternal, while others are subject to generation and decay. The former are excellent

2I1 maestro di color che sanno. Inferno, iv. 131. 2 Deipnosophistae, Bk. viii., chap 47.

THE SOUL AND LIFE XV11

beyond compare and divine, but are less accessible to knowledge. The evidence that might throw light on them and on the problems which we long to solve respecting them, is furnished but scantily by sensation, whereas respecting perishable plants and animals we have abun- dant information, living as we do in the midst of them, and ample data may be collected concerning all their different varieties if only we are willing to take sufficient pains. Both departments, however, have their special charm. The scanty conceptions to which we can attain of celestial things give us, from their excellence, more pleasure than all our knowledge of the world in which we live ; just as a half glimpse of persons whom we love is more delightful than a leisurely view of other things, whatever their number and dimensions. On the other hand, in certitude and in completeness our knowledge of terrestrial things has the advantage. Moreover, their greater nearness and affinity to us balance somewhat the loftier interest of the heavenly things that are the objects of the higher philosophy. Having already treated of the celestial world, as far as our conjectures could reach, we proceed to treat of animals, without omitting, to the best of our ability, any member of the kingdom, however ignoble. For if some have no graces to charm the sense, yet even these, by disclosing to intellectual perception the artistic spirit that designed them, give immense pleasure to all who can trace links of causation and are in- clined to philosophy." 1

1 Aristotle, On the Parts of Animals, translated by Ogle, London, 1882, p. 16.

Of

xvm INTRODUCTION

Aristotle regards the physical world as divided into two realms (the later and now obsolete division into three kingdoms : animal, vegetable, and mineral, is due to the alchemists): (1) th^_gj:gajaicLJffi:Qrld (ra e/x^X") > an(^ (2) the inorjramcjvorld (ra a\/svxa). The characteristic mark of the organic world is the possession of soul (\/svx>i), by virtue of which it is endowed with the power of self-move- ment. Its development and transformations are due to this native soul-force or life. Life is the universal form of organic activity ; sensation and the various elements of consciousness are specific forms. Nutritive life and mental life are different manifestations of a single psychical power, the latter representing a higher stage in the evolution of yjsvxy'h ' Life,' or the inherent capacity of a thing to effect changes in itself, has several meanings. Whatever possesses any of the following capacities is said to 'live', (1) reason; (2) sensation; (3) local movement; (4) in- ternal movement or transformation, viz. nutrition, growth, and decay. The last power is common to all living things, and is the basis for the further development of the higher powers. These various forms of self-movement are identical with the different types of life. The lowest and least complex of all the forms is the threptic or vegetal life manifested in the functions of nutrition, growth, and decay.

Aristotle conceived of Nature's processes as moving without a break in an ascending scale from the inanimate world to the most complex forms of animate existence.1 Natura nihil facit per saltum. There is an unbroken

1 Cf. Hist. anim. 5886 4 ; De part. anim. 681a 12.

THE SOUL AND LIFE xix

continuity in terrestrial life. The initial form of this is found in plant-life. The plant-organism is simpler than any other, its functions are confined to nutrition and reproduction. The function of growth or vegetation in plants is analogous to the nutritive functions in higher organisms. A process of conversion and assimilation is carried on in both cases and by analogous organs. Roots are analogous to the mouths of animals,1 or, as Aristotle elsewhere employs another analogy, they are like umbilical veins that take in nourishment from the earth as the embryo is maintained by its attachment to the uterus.2 Plants, furthermore, as Aristotle observed, exhibit the morphological tendency to develop their organs at the extremities, while animals tend to develop theirs at the centre.3

The transitional form of life in proceeding from plants to animals, or from phenomena of growth to phenomena of sensation, is found in the Zoophytes. There are some marine animals, Aristotle says,4 concerning which it is difficult to say whether they are plants or animals, for many of them grow on rocks and die if detached. To these transitional forms belong the sponges, holothurians, star-fishes, acalephae (sea-anemones), and sea-lungs.5 All of these possess a low degree of sensation, and some of them are incapable of movement. Aristotle's reason for classifying sponges amongst animals seems to have been

1 De an. 4126 3.

2Cf. Depart, anim. 650a 20, 6866 35; De gener. anim. 745623.

3 Cf. G. H. Lewes, Aristotle, pp. 187, 192. 4 Hist. anim. 5886 12.

5 Cf. Ogle, Aristotle on the Parts of Animals, p. 225.

y

XX INTRODUCTION

that they possess rudimentary sensation,1 although they are incapable of locomotion, and can be regarded only as belonging to the initial stage of animal development. Nature completes the transition from plant organisms to animals proper by an increased or added activity of the soul, in which are manifested the further phenomena of sensibility, with which desire is associated, and desire demands locomotion. An animal soul is a more complex and more highly developed form of the original life- principle.

While we in modern times, in popular language at least, differentiate the life found in the plant-world from that which is found in the animal-world (though the boundary between these two is not exactly denned) by the obvious distinctions of ' vegetable ' and ' animal ' life, Aristotle regards them as fundamentally the same. He looks upon the functions of sensation, locomotion, and conceptual thought as a higher development of the vital principle found in plants. We distinguish between sensation and conceptual thought without ascribing them to a different

I mind, as Plato did ; but Aristotle goes further and maintains that not only these, but also the function of nutrition, are due to the same unitary vital force. It is, however, a distinctly marked stage that nature makes in the develop-

i ment of the vital principle when sensation is exceeded and rational^ thought is reached. This new phenomenon is confined to man, and is the last stage in the evolution of \fsvxv- Soul is, therefore, in the opinion of Aristotle, the unity in which the principles of life, sense-perception, and 1 Hist. anim. 4876 9.

THE SOUL AND LIFE XXI

thought are embraced. These taken together form an ascending series in which the higher form always includes and presupposes the forms below it.1

The function of nutrition furnishes the basis of sensation ; sensation furnishes the basis of conceptual thought. The lower functions exist teleologically for the higher. Man, consequently, is the apex of creation, because all forms of life terminate in him as the complete development of what is contained implicitly and im- perfectly in the lower organisms. These forms of life or soul, as we have enumerated them, are the following :

1. The nutritive or vegetal life.

2. Perceptive power or the life of sensation.

3. Creative power or desire attended by the capacity

of local movement, sometimes called by Aristotle the kinetic soul.2

4. The life of intellect or reason, called the logistic or

dianoetic soul.

These, as I have pointed out, are various manifestations of a unitary life. The soul is not divided into separate faculties or parts. In every organism it is a unit. In this . respect Aristotle differs widely from Plato. The division (I of the soul into kinds is only a convenient abstraction. The soul's powers are not topographically separable as in the Platonic psychology. The difference in kind is merely a difference in mode of operation and expression, determined by the nature of the materials with which the

1 De an. 434a 23 ff. 2De an. 413a 23, 4136 12—31.

*Dean. 413627.

xxn INTRODUCTION

soul is concerned. Thought, growth, and decay are modes of the single life of the organism. Aristotle, therefore, conceived his entire psychology under a biological form.

Everything that moves itself contains a duality of moving principle and thing moved, i.e. a duality of ' form ' i and c matter,' to use Aristotle's metaphysical terminology. Every living thing, a plant no less than a man, is a composite being (cruvoXov), viz. a composite of soul and body. The soul is the cause of motion and change, and is therefore the ' efficient cause ' ; it is further that which determines the form or individuality of the organism, and is therefore the ' formal cause ' ; it is also the end for which the body exists, and is, for this reason, the 'final cause.' The body is the 'material cause' or condition of the composite, while the soul represents all of the principles of activity in the organism. Soul is defined by Aristotle as the "entelechy or complete realization of a natural body endowed with the capacity of life." 1 The soul or vital principle is not itself corporeal, although it is inseparable from the body, as form is inseparable from matter.2 Soul and body are not distinct things that do or can exist apart. Their separation is only notional. They no more exist apart than do concave and convex.

Soul_is to be found in every part of the body. This is observable in the case of graftings, where the entire parent form can be reproduced from a section. Insects live for some time after bisection, but they do not continue to live

1 Dean. 412a 20, 412&5.

2 This does not apply to the Prime Mover as pure 'form.' The relation of the active reason to the body is discussed below in the chapter on Reason (chap. viii.).

THE SOUL AND LIFE xxiii

on indefinitely, because they lack organs for maintaining life. As we go up the scale of living forms, this diffusion of soul throughout the body becomes less and less marked ; the higher the order of life the greater the centralization. In the case of animals, the body consists generally of three main divisions : the head, thorax, and abdomen. Aristotle points out * that if a wasp's head is cut off, the thorax and abdomen continue to live for a time ; if the abdomen is cut off, the head and thorax continue to live. In other words, the part which is conjoined with the thorax exhibits this continuance of vitality. For this reason it would appear that the anatomical centre is also the life-centre. This is, furthermore, on a priori grounds the best and most advantageous position. It is reasonable to suppose, therefore, that nature in her wise economy 2 has employed this central section as the vital centre.

This view, however, is not merely derivable from rational considerations, but is also supported by grounds of obser- vation. The life-centre may be localised not only in the thoracic region, but specifically in the heart. For this statement Aristotle adduces the following arguments : (1) disease of the heart is the most rapidly and certainly fatal ; (2) psychical affections, such as fear, sorrow, and joy cause an immediate disturbance of the heart ; (3) the heart is the part which is first formed in the embryo, and, as he says in the History of Animals? it appears in the egg of the chicken on the third day of incubation as a red spot (the

1 Dejuvent. 468a 21 ; De part. anim. 6676 22 ; De respir. 479a 5.

2 Cf . Leibniz's "choix de la Sagesse," Princ. 11; also N'ouv. Ess. II., ch. xxi, 13, Langley's translation, p. 183.

3 Hist. anim. 561a 6-12.

XXIV INTRODUCTION

punctum saliens of later writers) which palpitates and whose movements are those of an organism endowed with life.

The heart is at once the physiological and psychical centre of man. In as much as Aristotle identifies life with soul, it is a matter of consistency for him to place

I the seat of the soul in the vital centre. He rejects the doctrine of Plato and Diogenes of Apollonia, who re-

|| garded the brain as the organ of mind. To Aristotle the brain is merely a regulator for the temperature of the heart; the brain is bloodless and cool, and the blood and warm vapours from the heart rising to this are lowered in temperature. By this physiological device, conjoined with the service of respiration, Aristotle sup- poses that the system is maintained in a heat-equilibrium.

The material element in which the soul is immediately incorporated is heat or fire, but the soul is not identical with this, as Democritus thought. Nor is the vital heat ordinary fire, but some subtle principle analogous perhaps, as Ogle says,1 to that imponderable and hypothetical matter of the physicists known as Ether. In accordance with his theory, Aristotle was naturally forced to attribute vital heat to plants and the cold-blooded animals, but his grounds for this position are not to be found in any of the extant works. He had, of course, no knowledge of the chemical elements of oxygen and carbon. The vital caloric of the body is kept up by food which serves as fuel. This heat which, according to Descartes, is produced by fermentation or, according to Haller, by friction between

1 Aristotle, On Youth and Old Age, trans, by Ogle, Introd. p. 9.

THE SOUL AND LIFE XXV

the blood particles, is being constantly generated and constantly given off. To prevent an excessive production of animal heat, the respiration of the lungs, along with the cooling function of the brain above referred to, is the most important means. In the case of fishes the same thing is accomplished by bathing their gills in a medium of lower temperature than their bodies.

As to the cause of the natural and normal extinction of life, Aristotle says it is due to loss of balance in the production and consumption of heat. The heat is gradually extinguished when the generation of heat, as in old age, is not adequate to the demand of consumption. The length of life in any animal varies according to its material constitution and the suitability of its physical surroundings. As a general rule, animals or plants of great bulk x are long lived ; small ones are short lived ; sanguineous animals live longer than those that have no blood ; and a long period of gestation is usually correlated with long life. The purpose of the threptic soul is nutri- tion and reproduction. The food which is taken up into the vegetable or animal organism and nourishes it, has its end not merely in the continuance of the individual's life, but has a higher end in the formation of another life of like kind by reproduction. The function of the individual is not merely to live, but to reproduce and so to maintain life's continuity.

1 On the longerity of animals, see translation, pp. 256-265.

XXVI INTRODUCTION

II.

The Faculties of the Soul. Plato conceived three psychological elements which cor- respond roughly to cognition (vorjriicop), feeling {eirSv^TiKov), and conation (Qv[AO€iSe$) in terms of ethical value. Cogni- tion has the highest worth, and conation stands next in rank. Feeling has the lowest moral value. These are not faculties or Svvajneig of the soul, but ' parts ' (/mepr]). They consitute real entities in the psychophysical whole, just as the three divisions of government in the state have separate and real existence. The two lower parts, how- ever, have no share in pre-existence or immortality.1 These are never referred to as powers or faculties (Svvdneis).

The term ' faculty ' is applied by Plato to certain pro- cesses of the soul which are determined by the object to which they are directed or the results they accomplish. Sense-perception (ato-Otians), opinion (S6£a), and conceptual knowledge (e7rfo-T>//x^) are described by Plato as ' faculties.' 2 The faculties depend upon the reciprocal relation between subject and object. The 'parts' of the soul (the Platonic ' parts ' are the historical predecessors of the post- Platonic 'faculties'), on the other hand, are entities, situated in various regions of the body, and denote certain qualitatively distinct types of psychical life, arranged on a scale of ethical value. The seat of reason is in the brain, the topographically higher region being correlated with the reason's higher worth ; the conative part is situated in the

aCf. Siebeck, Geschichte der Psychologie, Th. I., Abth. i., p. 203. 2 Protagoras, 330A.

THE FACULTIES OF THE SOUL XXV11

thorax, more particularly the heart, so as to be the con- venient ally of the reason in the ethical regulation of the individual's life;1 the feelings and appetites are situated in the abdominal cavity, their upper boundary being the diaphragm and their chief organ the liver.

Plato's entire psychology, in which the soul's parts are separated into existentially distinct units with distinct

anatomical organs, is ethico-teleologically.. determined.

Aristotle's psychology, on the contrary, is biologically

determined; the soul is a unitary life functioning in

distinct modes or faculties.2 It is a single indivisible mind expressing itself in nutrition, sense-perception, imagination, memory, reasoning.3 To Aristotle there is a thinking substance, a 'soul/ which possesses certain distinct capa- cities. In the term 'faculty' or 'potentiality' there is implicit the idea of latent _or possible activity. Further, Suva/Ai? conveys the notion of being native and not acquired

In their action, manifestation, or processes, the faculties of Aristotle are merely a convenient classification of psychical phenomena into groups.4 They correspond to the fundamental divisions in organic life plant, brute, man. The psychological faculties or functions, therefore, represent the several stages in the development of the forms of organic life. The soul operates in every particular organism under one or other of these forms, viz. it effects

1 Timaeus, 70A ff. *Dejuvent. 4676 25.

3 See the chapter on the Creative Reason, chap. viii.

4Cf. Wundt's Grundziige der pliyaiologischen Ptycholoyie, 4te Aufi. Vol. i., pp. 10 ff.

xxvm INTRODUCTION

nutrition, or it experiences sensation, or it causes loco- motion, or it thinks, or in the highest organism it acts under all four forms. Sometimes Aristotle speaks even of five faculties, viz. the nutritive, sensitive, conative, loco- motive, and rational;1 again he speaks of four,2 and at other times of only three, owing to the identification of the orectic and sensitive powers.3

It is evident from this that Aristotle laid no great weight on any fixed enumeration of the faculties, and he expressly says that from one point of view these ' parts of the soul ' appear to be indefinitely large in number.4 If we regard the fundamental aspects, therefore, under which the soul mani- fests itself, Aristotle defines it as that principle by which we live, have sensation, and think.5 The vegetative or threptic life is confined to the phenomena of nutrition and reproduction6 ; sensitive life is confined to the pheno- mena of cognition when the object is spatially and temporally determinate, i.e. an individual thing; rational ' life is concerned with phenomena of cognition when the object is an universal or an abstraction.7 The stages in the development of organic life are differentiated from one another in terms of psychical activity ; plants live and reproduce; the lower animals live, reproduce, and have sensation ; man lives, reproduces, has sensation, and reasons. \ Each higher stage includes within itself the fundamental ! functions of the lower stages. Aristotle's view of

lDe an. 41 4a 31. 2 De an. 4136 12. 3 De an. 431a 14. 4 De an. 432a 24. 5 De an. 414a 12. 6De an. 413a 22 ff., 415a 25; De gener. anim. 740630. 7De an. 4176 22; Anal. post. 876 37; De insom. 4586 1 ff. ; 9996 27 ff.

NUTRITION AND REPRODUCTION XXIX

the physical world may be presented schematically as follows :

I I

Organic world Inorganic world

(tcl <;ix\pvxa>) {to. axf/vxa)

Vegetable life Animal life

(Nutrition

i " i

Lower animals Man

and reproduction).

(Nutrition, reproduction, (Nutrition, reproduction,

and sensation). sensation, noetic life).

III.

Nutrition and Reproduction.

Nutrition is the simplest form of organic movement. Every living thing must have the power of nutrition, for organic development is not possible without food. All sensation and noetic activity presuppose this nutritive faculty as their basis. To use Aristotle's phraseology, those organisms which assimilate form and matter at once and are incapable of assimilating form without matter, live exclusively a vegetative life. In other words, the process of vegetal growth is a physical process, i.e. the organism takes up certain corporeal substances into its physical structure, and it does so through the agency of an inherent psychical or vital principle.1

In sensation, on the other hand, the form of the object (without its matter) is taken up by the agent. The signifi- cance or form of the object is assimilated by sensation ; the matter of the object is assimilated when the nutritive

1 De an. 4246 1.

XXX INTRODUCTION

power appropriates it. Indeed, the whole of the psychical life is carried on by means of assimilation. The threptic power by the instrument of heat converts foreign substances into forms similar to organic structures, and into these structures the substances are then absorbed. Analogically the data of sensation and experience are assimilated into the concept, and the qualities of things are assimilated into the forms of sense-perception. The entire process of psychical life is a process of conversion, in which objects are reduced to terms of likeness with the subject or agent.

There was a pre-Aristotelian controversy as to whether nutrition is effected by the like or the opposite.1 Aristotle says that assimilation implies indeed original opposition, but the unlike undergoes in digestion a process whereby it is rendered like, and as such is taken up by the organism as part of its physical structure. In their ultimate phases, therefore, the like is nourished by like. Such is Aristotle's conclusion on this academic question of the Early Greek schools, a discussion which had concerned itself mainly with Epistemology, i.e. with the question whether the per- ception of a quality is due to the possession of a like or an opposite quality in the agent.

Food after it has been concocted and assimilated becomes the means (1) of nourishment, (2) of growth, (3) of reproduction. It nourishes in so far as it sustains the life of an individual and enables it to persist ; it causes growth in so far as it acts quantitatively and enables the

1 De an. 416a 25 ; cf. also on the Empedoclean and Anaxagorean theories of sensation, translation, pp. 35, 150, 166.

NUTRITION AND REPRODUCTION xxxi

individual to attain its normal mass in development;1 it makes reproduction possible by conversion of a part of the food into seminal matter.2 One must observe three main facts in nutrition, viz. the cause, the object, and the means. The cause is the elemental soul or threptic energy ; the object is the body animated by the soul ; the means is the food. Food, however, can maintain the life of an individual only for a limited time. The continuity of life is accordingly provided for by the deposit of semen, which contains potentially all the elements of the organism ; thereby the propagation of a life similar to that of the parent is secured.3 This is the highest and most important service of the threptic power, because it gives to perishable creatures an approximate immortality by perpetuating the species, and this is what every creature instinctively aims at. It is the final cause of every creature's natural life.4 All of nature's activity is purposive. Food is utilized for specific ends and in specific ways. No single substance is adequate for the nourishment of a physically complex body, and every organic body is complex. Even the lowest organisms, plants, employ various substances for their nutrition. Food, in as much as it is the material for the formation of body, must contain all the body's substances. Food, must consequently, be multiform. There is, however, one element in food which is more nutritive than any other, viz. the sweet. It is this element in edible things that is mainly causative of growth, and Aristotle makes a curious

1 De an. 416& 10 ff. 2 De gener. anim. 725a 15 ff.

3 Cf. Aristotle, On the Parts of Animals, tr. by Ogle, pp. 239, 240. 4Z>e an. 415 a 29.

xxxil INTRODUCTION

use of this element to explain the relative longevity of bees.1 Fat is to be classified amongst sweet substances.

Food undergoes no process in the mouth beyond that of mastication.2 Aristotle knew nothing of salivary glands, yet mastication, though not itself a digestive process, is a necessary preliminary to digestion. From the organ of seizure and mastication the food passes to the stomach, where it undergoes what Aristotle calls concoction. This is accomplished by animal or psychical heat, a form of heat which in its vivifying power differs from ordinary heat and is supplied mainly from the spleen and liver. The solid and indigestible portions pass off by the lower bowel, while the fluid portion,3 which alone is employed in nutrition, is absorbed by the blood-vessels and intestines. The stomach and intestines are to animal organisms what the ground is to plants ; 4 the roots as channels of nourish- ment for the plant correspond to the blood-vessels in the animal. The veins have exceedingly fine invisible open- ings such as the pores in unglazed pottery, and these minute openings permit the nutritive fluid to ooze through into them, and by them it is carried from the mesentery to the heart. Their content is not yet blood, it is an in- completely prepared serum (txcop)-5 In the heart, the warmest organ of the body, to which this serum is now immediately carried from the mesentery by the veins, it is re-concocted and converted into blood. It is then ready for

1 De long, et brev. vit. 467a 4.

2 De part. anim. 650a 10 ff.

3 De somno, 456a 30 ff. ; De part. anim. 6516 5 ff. ; De gener. anim. 7266 2.

4 De part. anim. 678a 7 ff.

5 Hist. anim. 521a 12 ff., 52162; Depart, anim. 651a 18.

NUTRITION AND REPRODUCTION XXXlll

assimilation into the organs, for building up their waste, and for adding to their growth. The amount of blood thus generated is very small in proportion to the materials consumed, otherwise the body would grow to enormous bulk. The blood in its final state of concoction is carried by the arteries and veins from the heart to all parts of the body. Each organ assimilates such elements as are adapted to its growth. The process of nutrition goes on most actively during sleep.1 Such parts of the blood as cannot be utilized in organic anabolism are excreted in the form of sweat, bile, and nature's various means of relief through waste, while surplus nutritious matter takes the form of excess fat, seminal deposit, nails, hair,2 and other masses whose quantitative permanence is unnecessary for the maintenance of life.

The two fundamental concepts with which Aristotle's entire philosophy operates, viz. form and matter, or actuality and potentiality, are derived from his observation of organic life. Potential matter in the organic world is being constantly transformed by an inherent life-movement into significant structures, and a formative or psychical principle is constantly active in converting passive matter to definite ends. Without the soul the body is motionless, and the organs of the body are organs only homonymously3 a dead hand is only the homonym of a hand, it has the name of a hand without its significance or function. All life (not only what is modernly understood by vital

1 De somno, 455a 1.

2 Cf. Aristotle, On the Parts of Animals, tr. by Ogle, p. 202. De gener. anim. 735a 8 ; De an. 4126 14, 21.

C

xxxiv INTRODUCTION

phenomena, but all rational life) is a form of motion, of which there are several varieties : yevecris, augrjcris, clWolwo-is, <j>opa. The most elementary form of organic movement is, as has been said, growth (augricris).1 The soul is in every part of the body, and, although not itself corporal, it is inseparable from the body. This diffusion of soul is more apparent the lower we go in the scale of animate exist- ence.2 Organic centralization increases in direct ratio with the complexity of the organism, but even in the lowest forms of animal life there is a certain degree of centraliza- tion, lowest of all in the plants. The only form of life which is separable from the body is that of the active reason, and even this, so far as its real content is concerned, is an ' entelechy of the body.'

Heat is the soul's material substrate, in which the soul is immediately incarnate. The soul is not itself heat. " Birth is the original suffusion of the nutritive soul with heat, and life is the maintenance of this heat." 3 The manner in which this heat is maintained by the fuel of food through concoction has been already described. Not only must the body have this heat in order to live, but the heat must be regulated and kept within normal limits. There must be some physiological provision for the reduction of temperature ; otherwise the fuel in the stomach would constantly generate heat to excess, especially during the process of digestion. Mechanism for reducing temperature in the pulmonate

1 Phys. 260a 25 ff.

2 Dean. 4116 20, 4136 20.

3 De respir. 479a 29. Birth or genesis means for Aristotle not the separation of the young from the mother's body, but the process of fecundation.

SENSATION xxxv

animals is furnished by the lungs 1 and brain, in aquatic animals by the gills. Death comes to all organisms when the supply of vital heat fails ; the organs of nutrition and respiration become through lapse of time incapable of supplying and regulating this heat, it being both inade- quately generated and inadequately controlled, and so " the fire of life is snuffed out." 2 When the basal psychical function ceases, the higher life of mind is no longer possible, for the soul is not divided into parts, but is an unit.

IV.

Sensation. The immediate instruments for the apprehension and in- terpretation of the external world are the peripheral sense- organs. Sensation, which marks the boundary between the animal and plant worlds, is explained by Aristotle as a form of motion, viz. a qualitative change 3 (aWotaxri?) in a sense-organ. The sense-process and the sense-object are one in the actual sensation. Sound and hearing, for example, although notionally distinct, are identical in the act of sensation.4 The sense-organ is potentially what the

1The organs known to us as 'lungs' were regarded by Aristotle as the right and left halves of an azygous organ. Consequently he always speaks of ' lung ' in the singular. He found the organ to be actually single in certain snakes (Hist. anim. 508a 28 ff.), and when it is double the two divisions have a common outlet in the trachea. I have, however, in con- formity with the demands of English speech, translated his singular by a plural. See the translation, pp. 286 ff.

2Derespir. 479a 18.

zDe somno, 4596 4 ; Phys. 247a 7 ; De an. 4156 24.

4 De an. 424a 25 4256 26, 418a 1.

xxxvi INTRODUCTION

sense-object is actually. To make a further use of Aristotle's terminology, the organ assimilates the significance or form of a thing without its matter.1 Life rises above the uncon- scious process of nutrition, when in sensation the external world is transformed into a conscious world, a world of meaning. The sense receives an impression or picture of an object, as wax receives an impression of a seal-ring without the bronze or gold of the ring.2 The sense is thus, in a way, identical with the object ; it differs from the object, how- ever, in its mode of being. The sense apprehends a quali- tative element belonging to an individual,3 but not the individual as such.

Sensation is a process that belongs to both soul and body.4 The sensation itself is psychical, but its instrument is physical. The eye and vision are related to each other as matter and form.5 Vision consists in a certain relation- ship or condition of harmony. Excessive stimuli destroy this harmony, just as the harmony of strings is destroyed by striking them violently.6

Without contact there can be no action of one thing upon another. This law, which applies to the whole of nature, necessitates the assumption of a continuous medium from object to subject, for there must be some sort of contact if the object of sense is to affect a sense-organ. A medium is further necessary because no sensation results

1 De an. 424a 27, 426a 26, 4316 26. 2De an. 424a 19 ff. ; De mem. 450a 30.

3 Anal. post. 876 28, 100a 16 ff. ; De an. 424a 21 ff.

4 De somno, 457a 7 ; De sensu, 436a 6 ; De an. 402a 4 ff. * Dean. 4126 18 ff.

b De an. 424 a 32.

SENSATION XXXV11

when organ and object are in immediate contact.1 The intervening medium, however, is in contact with both organ and object and transmits a stimulus from the latter to the former, without which no sensation would result. The medium is different in different senses.

In considering the subject of sensation it is necessary to observe, in addition to the faculty itself, three conditioning factors : (1) the organ, (2) the object, (3) the medium. There are five senses, and at the beginning of the third book of the De anima 2 Aristotle attempts to prove that this enumeration is exhaustive.

1. Sight.

The sense of sight is the most important for life,3 although hearing has a higher significance for purely intellectual life, because of the meaning conveyed by the spoken word.

a. The Organ of Sight The psychologists preceding Aristotle and contemporary with him regarded the sense- organs as composed severally of the elements, but as there were for the pre-Socraties only four elements (fire, earth, air, and water), whereas there were five senses, they were in straits about a fifth element with which to pair a fifth sense.4 Further, they differed in the elements assigned to the several sense-organs. Plato, e.g., coupled vision with fire, whereas Democritus coupled it with water. Aristotle,

1 De an. 4216 17, 4236 20; De gener. et corr. 322622 ; Phys. 245a 4.

2 De an. 4246 22 ff; cf. also Hist. anim. 532629.

3 Metaph. 980a 21 ; De sensu, 437a 5 ff.

4 Desensu, ma 19 ff.

*•

dement*, an«i

ii* ■■■■

«m 4_»U i •cetmml of ■— wy

.-•:»u«. pp. M

u liWHpthM ol mi «;i M * •«* .

k, feat tepoa

< the M>

* » - a 1 1 ff.

,, Leading bom

although he did

i which he had

The

thai t! i the chameleon is

and with r dl,bui i

The

ith the

, is doe risible'

,. ; i ia

xxxvill INTRODUCTION

likewise, regards the sense-organs as composed of the

elements, and as to the constitution of the eye he agrees

with Democritus. The eye's power of vision is due to the

element of water in it, the organ being in constitution

analogous to the medium through which its stimulus is

transmitted, i.e. a translucent medium.1 Hearing is due to

the air immured in the inner ear. Smell is correlated with

one or both of the foregoing elements (air and water), and

touch and taste are correlated, perhaps, in some special

manner with earth. The sense-organs are thus coupled

with their media and not with their objects.2 The real

organ of vision is the pupil {Koprj)? which is within the eye

and is composed of the element of water, and the best eye

is the one whose proportion of water is best adjusted.4 In

order that light may penetrate to the interior, it is

necessary that the eye be translucent, and water, because

it is more easily fixed and kept in place, is better adapted

to this purpose than air would be.5 The water of which

the pupil is composed is derived from the brain.6 Aristotle

1 De an, 4246 28 ff.; De sensu, 4386 3ff.; Depart, anim. 647a 2 ff.

2 The account of the sense-organs given in the Parva Naturalia [De sensu, 4386 3 ff.) differs somewhat from this {e.g. smell is correlated with fire). The discrepancy is to be explained (cf. translation, pp. 96, 150) by the fact that in the Parva Naturalia Aristotle is reporting current opinions (evidently so in his description of smell as a smoke-like exhalation), or it may be accounted for by the theory (held by Torstrik, but impossible to establish) that the De sensu is an earlier treatise than the De anima.

3 De part. anim. 653625; Hist. anim. 4916 21; De sensu, 438a 16 ; De an. 425a 4.

4 De gener. anim. 780a 22 ; De sensu, 4386 5 ff.

5 De sensu, 438a 1 Off. Cf. Theophrastus, De sensu, 39. Diogenes of Apollonia believed air to be the essential element in the composition of all the senses.

6 Hist. anim. 492a 21, 495a 11 ff.

SENSATION xxxix

speaks of three conduits or iropoi leading from the eye to the brain, which may refer to the ramus ophthalmicus, opticus, and oculomotorius, although he did not, of course, regard these as nerves, of the function of which he had no knowledge whatever. The optic nerve he recognized as a duct, and noted the fact that the eye of the chameleon is continuous with the brain.1 The term -n-opog is, indeed, used later on to mean nerve.2 The connection, however, here referred to by Aristotle is not a connection between peripheral and central organ. The duct between eye and brain serves only physiological purposes, and the connec- tion is, strictly speaking, not with the brain at all, but only with the empty occiput and the vascular membrane surrounding the brain.3 The brain, as has been pointed out, is not the central sense-organ. The peripheral organs of sight and hearing are not only connected with the vascular membrane of the brain, but they are also con- nected with the heart,4 which is the sensory centre as it is also the vascular centre. Because the eye is connected with the brain and derives its water from that source, it is moist and cold like the brain.5 Its power of vision is due to the translucence of its composition.6

b. The Object of Sight. The object of vision is the visible7

1 Hist. anim. 492a, 21, 495a 11 ff.; De gener. anim. 7436 35.

2 Galen, De usu part. in. 12, quoted by Ogle, Aristotle On the Parts of Animals, p. 176, note 19.

3 De part. anim. 6566 16.

4 Hist. anim. 495a 4, 514a 18 ff.; De sensu, 439a 2, 444a 10 ; Depart, anim. 6526 16, 6566 24; De juvent. 469a 10 ff.; De gener. anim. 7436 25, 781a 20.

5 De gener. anim. 744 a 5 ff. 6 De sensu, 438 a 12. 7De an. 418a 26, 422a 20, 424a 10.

xl INTRODUCTION

and the invisible, for opposites are subject-matter of the same faculty of perception and of the same science.1 The visible includes colour and certain phenomena which Aristotle calls anonymous, whose characteristic is brightness.2 Colour is a qualitative accident that has the power of exciting or moving a diaphanous medium.3 Vision consists neither in an efflux from the visible nor in an image thrown off by the visible, as the Atomists and Empedocles4 supposed, but in the excitation of a translucent medium by means of colour and in a qualitative stimulation of the organ of vision by means of the medium so affected. The diaphanous medi- ates colour, and light is that which converts the poten- tially diaphanous into the actually diaphanous. Colour sets the actually diaphanous in motion and is mediated in the form of motion from a remote object to the sense- organ. The diaphanous is not itself visible, but the colour with which it is charged is visible. The actuality of the diaphanous is light.5 The diaphanous as such is colour- less,6 but has the capacity of being illuminated and charged with colour. The colour constitutes its light in an acci- dental sense,7 i.e. light is no particular colour. Light is not somatic nor the efflux of any body ; it is not fire,8 but depends on the presence of fire,9 or is a subtle species of fire. As the diaphanous is actually translucent only in light, so colour is visible only in light. Fire, on the other hand, is visible in both darkness and

1Dean. 411a 3; Top. 1056 5; Metaph. 1061a 18.

2 Dean. 418a 27.

3 Top. 1036 31 ; Categ. 969 ; De an. 4186 1, 419a 10.

4De sensu, 438a 2. 5 De an. 4186 9, 419a 11. 6 De an. 4186 28.

1 De sensu, 439a 18. * De an. 4186 14. 9 Top. 134628.

SENSATION xli

light,1 for it creates for itself a translucent medium by diffusing light. Colour, then, is a condition belonging to light, as light is a condition attaching to the diaphanous. The diaphanous belongs to water and air, the media of vision, and to some extent to other bodies,2 but has no independent existence. It is not a substance. Colour is further defined by Aristotle as a quality of the superficies of a body in a diaphanous medium. So the Pythagoreans called colour a visible superficies. There are seven primary colours derivable from the basal colours, white and black.3 They are : white, black, yellow, violet, green, and blue. The other sort of ' visible,' called by Aristotle ' anonymous,' consists in brightness produced by a smooth, polished surface, such as is found in certain fish-heads, scales, eyes, and phosphorescent substances.4 This is not properly colour, but a fiery phenomenon which has the power of diffusing light and creating visibility.

c. The Medium of Sight. The medium of sight is the diaphanous, viz. air and water and certain other translucent bodies.5 They are the media by virtue of their trans- parency, which belongs to them not as air or water, but because they possess something in common with the eternal empyrean.6 The medium itself is neutral and colourless, being thus adapted to saturation with and transmission of any colour. Aristotle rejects the emanation theory of colour, and resolves it into a form of movement of a medium, approximating herein more closely than his

1 De an. 4186 2, 419a 23. 2 De sensu, 439a 20 ff.

3 De sensu, 4396 20 ff., 442a 19 ; cf. also translation, p. 87, note 2.

4 De an. 419a Iff.; De sensu, 4376 5. 5 De an. 4186 6. 6De an. 4186 7 ; De sensu, 438a 12.

xlii INTRODUCTION

predecessors to the modern hypothesis of ether vibrations. Colour excites the pellucid element, which then transmits the colour-motion from the object to the sense-organ. This movement does not, however, consist in an undulatory process, but in a qualitative change, whose spatial propaga- tion is not discernible,1 and which appears to be instan- taneously complete.

2. Hearing.

a. The Organ of Hearing. As the real organ of vision is composed of water, similarly the real organ of hearing consists of air.2 Air is immured in the inner ear and is immovable there, i.e. it cannot be dispersed. This fact enables it to detect all distinctions in communicated motions. We hear in water, because it cannot penetrate to the congenital air,3 but we hear through water as through any other foreign body. Aristotle ascribes hearing to fishes, but nowhere explains how they hear, although in the History of Animals he devotes several paragraphs to the subject of sensation in the lower animals.4 The congenital air has its own internal movements, which account for certain phenomena of sound, such as the hearing of sound when there is no external stimulus.5 A duct or channel leads from the ear to the rear of the brain, the occiput, which Aristotle supposed to be hollow and filled with air. This 7ro/oo? is perhaps the external and internal meatus, or

1 De sensu, 4466 20 ff., 4386 3 ff.

2 Be part. anim. 656616 ; De an. 4196 34, 425a 4. 3De an. 4196 18, 420a 11 ; De gener. anim. 781a 23.

4 Hist. anim. 5326 30 ff., 5336 1 ff. 5 De an. 420a 17.

SENSATION xliii

possibly he considered the communication to be established by the Eustachian tube, which was known to him.1

b. The Object of Hearing. The object of hearing is sound.2 Sound is produced by the concussion of two hard, smooth bodies, especially hollow bodies, in a medium.3 Air or water may serve as a resisting body and emit sound, when either is so quickly and violently struck as to pre- vent its (air's or water's) gradual and noiseless disper- sion.4 Each of these acts then in the same way as a hard body, and the adjacent water or air serves as a medium for the communication of the sound. The qualities of sound are given in terms of pitch, the extremes of which are high and low, or acute and grave.5 The high or acute is due to a swift motion, and the low or grave is due to a slow motion. Mere sound is noise. Voice is significant sound, produced by an animal, and accompanied by a mental image.6

c. The Medium of Hearing. The medium of hearing as of sight is air or water.7 These two media are in their own nature both colourless and soundless, but capable of trans- mitting colour and sound to sense-organs. The spatial propagation of sound is not instantaneous, but is discernible in time, as one can learn from the blow of an axe seen in the distance, the sound of which is perceived at an interval later.8 For the transmission of sound the air must form an un- interrupted continuum from stimulus to organ.9 The

1 Hist. anim. 491a 30, 492a 20; De part. anim. 656a 18; De gener. anim. 781a 31. 2De an. 418a 11 ; De insom. 45866.

sDe an. 4196 6 ff., 4206 14 ; De sensu, 446630 ; De coelo, 291a 1 ff. 4 De an. 420a 7. 5 De an. 420a 28. 6 De an. 4206 25 ff.

' De an. 4196 18. 8 De sensu, 446a 24 ff. 9 De an. 420a 3.

xliv INTRODUCTION

stimulus must not be too slight, otherwise it is not trans- mitted, nor too excessive, otherwise it disturbs the function of the organ.1 Sensation demands a kind of proportion between stimulus and organ, from which there issues a normal organic process.

3. Smell.

a. The Organ of Smell. The organ of smell is composed of air or water,2 of the former in the case of respiring animals, and of the latter in the case of aquatic animals. In respiring animals the organ of smell has a covering, which is lifted in inspiration and is analogous to an eyelid ; without inspiring, smell is not sensed by them.3 In aquatic animals this covering is lacking, as the analogous eyelid is lacking in hard-eyed animals.4 The nostrils, or physiological organs of smell, are passages for inhalation and exhalation, and are very mobile ; whereas in the case of the ear, man has no muscular control of it, as most of the lower animals have.5

b. The Object of Smell. The object of smell is the odorous and its opposite.6 Smell is very poorly developed in man, being inferior in accuracy to that of many of the lower animals.7 It is difficult to determine the essential qualities of smell, because of this imperfect development in man, and because smells are confused with the pleasant and un- pleasant.8 Smell is intimately connected with the sense

1 De an. 420a 24, 421 6 9, 422a 26, 426a 28 ff. 2 De an. 425a 5.

3 De an. 4216 14, 422a 1 ; De sensu, 4446 22. 4 De sensu, 443a 3.

5 Hist. anim. 492a 28, 492615.

6De an. 4216 3ff. ; De sensu, U4cb 20 ff.

7 De sensu, 441a 1 ; De an. 421a 10. 8 De an. 421a 12.

SENSATION xlv

of taste,1 and many smells are described in terms of analo- gous flavours, e.g. smells are called sweet, piquant, oily, harsh, pungent, terms that belong properly to taste. It is not, however, to be assumed that because a given thing has a sweet flavour it will also have a sweet smell. On the contrary, sweet-smelling objects often have an unpleasant taste and conversely. The object of smell is described as a property of the dry, while flavour is the sapid-moist.2 That the dry property is not a smoke-like exhalation, as certain pre-Aristotelians held, is proved by the fact that aquatic animals are endowed with smell, and a smoke-like exhalation could not be transmitted in water.3 Besides, this would resolve the odorous into a physical efflux, an explanation of sensation in general which Aristotle rejects.4 The odorous consists in the saturation of a medium (air or water) with a sapid dry element.5

Although the sense of smell is poorly developed in man, he is the only animal that is capable of perceiving smell as fragrance, i.e. in an aesthetic way.6 The lower animals have no appreciation of malodour as such.

c. The Medium of Smell. The medium of smell is air or water.7 Water mediates smell for the aquatic animals.8 Man, however, and all respiring animals whose sense of smell is dependent on inspiration, cannot smell in water.9 Although the media of smell are the same as the media of

1 De sensu, 4406 28, 4436 8 ; De an. 421a 17.

2 De an. 422a 4 ff. sDe sensu, 4386 23, 443a 20 ff. 4 De sensu, 4436 2. 5 De sensu, 443a 3 ff.

6 De sensu, 4436 27 ff. , 445a 1. 7 De an. 419a 28 ff. , 422a 2.

8 De sensu, 443a 1 ff, 4446 5 ff; De an. 419a 35, 4216 10.

9 De an. 422a 2 ; De sensu, 4Mb 10 ff.

xlvi INTRODUCTION

sight, viz. air and water, these are media for sight by virtue of their translucence, and for smell by virtue of their capacity to exude dry savour. By the peripatetic Theo- phrastus they are called transolent (Slocr/ma).1

4. Taste.

a. The Organ of Taste. Aristotle's view regarding the organ of taste is difficult to determine. He maintains the doctrine that all the senses function by means of a medium, and that sensation does not take place when the sense- object and sense-organ are in immediate contact.2 In accordance with this doctrine he says the tongue is not the organ but the medium of taste, and yet he sometimes speaks in a popular way of the tongue as the organ of taste.3 Strictly speaking, the organ of taste is something more internal.4 The organ proper is within the flesh and is fitted with a conductor to the central organ or sensorium (i.e. the heart).5 It is even possible that Aristotle regards the heart as the organ of taste and the tongue as at once the medium and ancillary organ.6 It would seem, how- ever, from his general account of the senses that they all have a medium, and that all of them have conduits from the peripheral organ to the sensory centre.7

b. The Object of Taste. The object of taste is at once

1 Cf. translation, p. 75, note 1. 2 Cf . translation, p. 73, note 2.

3 De part. anim. 647a 19, 6536 23 ff.; Hist. anim. 533a 26; De an. 4225 2 ff.

4 De an. 423a 2ff. ; De part. anim. 6566 36. 5 De sensu, 439a 1.

6 Cf. Baumker, Des Aristoteles Lehre von den aussern und innern Sinnesvermogen, p. 55.

7 Cf. the notes on duct or wbpos above, under the organ of sight.

SENSATION xlvii

gustable and tangible. Taste is therefore a special form of the tactual or haptic sense. It is not perceived through the medium of a foreign body but through an anatomical medium, in which respect it differs from the senses of sight, hearing, and smell. The latter are marked by actio in distans, while taste and touch operate by immediate contact. This immediate contact is not the direct contact of the sense-object with the sense-organ, which is found in no sense, but the direct contact of the sense-object with our physical organism as a transmitting medium. Touch is more exquisitely developed in man than in any other creature, and taste, as a kind of touch, shares in this per- fection. The gustable or flavour is the sapid-moist. Gustable juices are developed in water or in a moist element.

There is a great variety of opinions as to how these qualities originate in water.1 Water is not to be regarded as panchymic in the sense of containing originally the germs of all flavours, as was held by Empedocles, but as primarily neutral and only potentially chargeable with flavour. It may be so charged by the processes of nature or by artificial means.2 Flavours in the moist are especially developed under the influence of heat. The primary elements taken alone are tasteless;3 flavour arises only in their combinations, and it is only in forms of combina- tion that the elements are fit for food.4 Flavour and the nutritive are closely connected, sweet being the most

1 De sensu, 441a 1 ff. 2 De sensu, 4416 12 ff.

3 De sensu, 443a 8 ff.; Meteor. 3586 18.

4 De sensu, 4416 24 ff.; De an. 4346 19 ff.

xlviii INTRODUCTION

important flavour in growth.1 The basal flavours are sweet and bitter,2 from which are derived the other flavours. The number of flavours, like the number of colours, is seven : sweet, bitter, salt, harsh, pungent, astringent, acid.3 c. The Medium of Taste. As pointed out above, the medium of taste is not outside the body, yet taste operates through a medium.4 We can, indeed, taste in water, but water in this case is not the medium ; it is charged with a gustable substance and so becomes the object, not the medium, of taste.5 The medium of taste is the tongue.6

5. Touch.

Touch and taste are the most fundamental and therefore the most universal of the senses, because they are necessary for the maintenance of animal life. No animal can exist without touch, and only animals can possess it. As it is necessary to animal life, any stimulus sufficiently excessive to destroy it, destroys not only the organ, as in the other senses, but life itself. The other three senses, especially sight and hearing, minister to higher well-being and fur- nish materials for intellectual life. Touch and taste are of primary importance for the maintenance of^phvjdcal_ well-being.7 Although the sense of sight is the most im- porTant of our senses for higher well-being, because of the great number and variety of sensations with which it furnishes us,8 yet that man is the most highly endowed

1 De sensu, 442a. 2ff. 2 De an. 4226 11 ; De sensu, 4.12b 16 ff.

3 Cf. translation, p. 87, note 2. 4 De an. 435 a 16, 422a 9.

5 De an. 422a 12. 6 De an. 423a 15, 4236 17, 26.

7 De sensu, 4366 10 ff. ; De an. 4146 2 ff.

8 Metaph. 980a 21 ; De sensu, 437 a 5ff.

SENSATION xlix

creature is shown more by his touch than by his sight, in which latter many of the lower creatures surpass him. Further, men of finest tactual sensibility are the best endowed intellectually.1

a. The Organ of Touch. As in the case of taste it is not made clear what the organ is, so it is not made clear in the case of touch. The organ is described merely as something intra-corporeal, i.e. it is not the superficies of the body. This may refer to the central organ as some suppose,2 or, as I think more probable, to some unde- fined and unknown peripheral organ within the flesh.3

b. The Object of Touch. The object of touch is the tangible (currov).4' Aristotle's expression contains the same tautology. Tactual distinctions are such as charac- terize the body as body. They include warm and cold, dry and moist, hard and soft.5 The objects of touch do not fall under a single category. The objects of sight fall under the category of colour ; those of hearing under the category of sound ; but the objects of touch are not reducible to this unity.6

c. The Medium of Touch. As it is the function of touch to apprehend the qualities of body as body, so it is a cor- poreal medium that transmits these qualities, viz. the flesh. This sense gets its name from contact, which is possible only between bodies. The body in general is the medium of touch, and the tongue is the medium both of touch and taste.

1 De an. 421a 15 ff. 2Cf. Zeller's Aristotle, Eng. tr., vol. ii., p. 66.

3 De an. 422622. 4Z>e an. 4346 12; De gener. et corrup. 3296 8.

5 De an. 4236 28 ff. 6 De gener. et corrup. 330a 25 ; De an. 4226 32.

d

1 INTRODUCTION

From the foregoing it will be seen that Aristotle hampered as he was by the lack of scientific research in physiology and physics amongst his contemporaries, struck boldly out into the terra incognita of psychophysics as a discoverer. His is not only the first attempt to create a psychology in any approximately scientific spirit, but it is the first attempt to formulate a psychology at all.

V.

The Common or Central Sense.

Aristotle's conception of a 'common sense' (koivov aicrOrjTrjptov)1 has no logical or historical connection with the Scottish philosophy of common sense. Sir William Hamilton, in his elaborate note appended to the works of Reid),2 gives four meanings in which the term ' common sense ' has been employed in ancient and modern times : 1. It was employed by Aristotle and the Peripatetics to signify sense proper, and denoted that faculty by which the various reports of the individual senses are reduced to the unity of a common apperception. 2. It has been applied not to sense proper, but to those cognitions and con- victions which we are supposed to receive from nature and which all men possess in common, whereby we test the truth of knowledge and the morality of acts. This is the meaning in which it is employed in the Scottish philo- sophy. McCosh called it the Intuitive Philosophy, i.e. the

1 De an. 425a 14 ff . ; De somno, 455a 21; De long, et brev. vit. 467&2S, 469a 12.

2 ReicTs Works, edited by Hamilton, vol. ii., pp. 751 ff.

THE COMMON OR CENTRAL SENSE li

philosophy which regards the common intuitions of the mind as the criteria of truth.

Dugald Stewart objected to the term ' common sense ' on the ground of its ambiguity, and preferred to call these common convictions " the fundamental laws of human belief." Common sense, he asserts, is nearly synonymous with mother-wit, and good sense is only a more than ordinary share of common sense. These primary or intui- tive truths are what Aristotle calls ultimate principles (apyai), but not principles of common sense. He says in the Nicomachean Ethics : x " What all men believe, that we affirm to be ; and he who rejects this belief will advance nothing that is more convincing," which is the equivalent of the dictum : quod semjoer, quod ubique, quod ab omnibus. These universal beliefs, which Aristotle regards as the fundamental principles of human knowledge, are akin to the ' fundamental laws ' of Stewart. The doctrine of the sensus communis, however, is quite distinct from this.

3. Common sense, when used with an emphasis on the adjective or substantive, indicates that kind of intelligence, the lack of which causes one to be accounted mad or foolish.

4. It denotes an acquired perception of the duties and pro- prieties expected from each member of society ; a sense of public spirit, a feeling of obligation towards the commonweal. The last three meanings are all metaphorical, and do not refer to sense proper, but to certain intuitions which, like sensation, are characterized by immediacy, originality, and presumed trustworthiness. Thus we speak metaphorically of a ' moral sense,' a ' logical sense,' or an ' aesthetic sense.'

1 Eth. nic. 1173a 1.

Hi INTRODUCTION

Aristotle employs 'common sense' to signify a specific aspect in the psychological process of sense-perception. The act of sense-perception is not completed in the peri- pheral sense-organs, but only in the central sense.1 There are, as enumerated, in the previous chapter, five peripheral organs of sense : the eye, ear, tongue and throat, nose, skin and flesh. These are stimulated by objects in the outside world, which by contact with the organ work some change (aXXoloocTLs) in it. The contact is effected through a medium which transmits a stimulus from the sense-object to the perceiving organ, and the change which the stimulus works in the peripheral organ is further transmitted by the blood or sense-duct to the sensor ium (central organ). In every sensation three factors are to be taken into account : (1) the organ, (2) the object or thing sensed, (3) the medium of transmission. In the case of vision, as explained in chap. IV., these factors are the eye, the thing seen, and the diaphanous or translucent medium, whether the latter be liquid or atmospheric.

Every sensation presupposes these three elements : organ, object, and medium. To each of the individual senses belongs the function of apprehending a particular quality tfSiov alaOtjTOp).2 In vision, only colour is sensed ; in hearing, only sound ; in smell, odour ; in taste, flavour and in touch, the qualities of body as body (hardness, etc.). These are all sensation-qualities, but they are not percepts. By means of sight, e.g., we have the sensation of green, but do not perceive an olive. An olive is a percept ; green is a sensation. An olive is made up of several ideas, of hard-

1De an. 4266 10 ff. ; De somno, 455 a 10 ff. 2 De an. 418 a 10 ff.

THE COMMON OR CENTRAL SENSE liii

ness, taste, colour, form, magnitude, etc., and these are unified in a particular thing, and they constitute it a single concrete object. The peripheral organs of touch, taste, and sight furnish us with several ideas or qualities belonging to s> concrete thing ; but it is only by the unifying function of the central or common sense that these various qualities are brought together for knowledge and seen to inhere in a single object; in other words, it is only then that a percept is formed. The function of sensation, therefore, belongs to the peripheral or external senses in so far as they mediate the qualities of an object to the sensorium or common sense. Perception} then, is one of the functions of the central sense.

Again, it is by means of the central sense that we recognize particular sensations as belonging to ourselves, and can hold them up before our minds as something known to us. We know that we see. In other words, we are conscious of a sensation. Consciousness,2 then, is a second function of the common sense. Locke made a distinction between what he called the external and the internal senses. The external sense gives us ideas of colour, sound, and other properties of body. The internal sense gives us ideas of thought, reasoning, memory, and the other operations of our own minds, and is another name for consciousness. This function, so far as it is limited to the consciousness of sensations and their meaning for perceptual knowledge, is ascribed by Aristotle to the common sense.

Again, there are in addition to the particular sense- qualities (Tom ala-OtjTa), such as odour, sound, colour, etc.,

1 De serum, 449 a 3 ff. 2 De an. 4256 12 ff. ; De sensu, 455 a 15 ff.

liv INTRODUCTION

certain properties attaching to things which Aristotle calls f common sensibles ' (koivol alaOtjTa).1 These are rest, motion, number, shape, and magnitude. They are called ' common ' because their apprehension does not belong directly to any particular sense (although they are perceived indirectly by each), and because they are cognized directly by the common sense. They differ from primary or simple sensibles in having no specific sense-organ. This is a third function of the sensorium commune. Again, the individual senses furnish us with colour, sound, etc., but it is not their function to discriminate, e.g., between sweet and white, or to differen- tiate degrees of bitter. This is a function of judgment,2 and it is ascribed by Aristotle to the common sense. The dis- crimination between true and false, between real and unreal in our perceptions is made not by the peripheral senses, but by the central sense. The sensatiojQ,j3ecause it is only a fact and as a sense-process pronounces, no judg- ment; is always true,3 but when the sensation is predicated of something and a judgment is expressed, error is possible. It is the internal or central sense that performs this office of judgment in the sphere of perceptual knowledge, and it is, therefore, to the central sense alone that, strictly speak- ing, truth and falsehood in this sphere can be ascribed.

Further, sleep,4 imagination,5 memory,6 and dreams,7 in so far as they signify the interruption of consciousness or the continued life and movement of residual sense-percep-

1De an. 418a 17, 425a 16; De mem. 450a 10. Cf. translation, p. 96, note 2.

2 De an. 426 & 14 ff. 3 De an. 4275 11, 428 a 12.

4De somno, 454a 23, 456a 1. 5 De insom. 460& 17.

6 De mem. 451a 17. 7 De insom. 4586 1 ff.

THE COMMON OR CENTRAL SENSE lv

tions, are functions of the sensorium. In summary, these various functions of the central or common sense are as follows : 1. The unification of the primary sensibles, or the complete act of sense-perception ; 2. Consciousness ; 3. The suspension of consciousness, or sleep ; 4. The cognition of the ' common sensibles,' magnitude, number, etc. ; 5. Judg- ment, in so far as judgment applies to the comparison, contrast, and discrimination of the deliverances of sense; 6. Imagination, or residual sense-images ; 7. Memory (in- cluding reminiscence), or the voluntary and involuntary reproduction of sensations; while lastly, 8. its content is the potentiality of reason.

As the peripheral senses have an object, a medium, and an organ, sojtlso hasjthe central sense. The objects are the common sensibles ' and the several particular sensations which are unified by the central sense into the perception of a single concrete thing ; the medium is the blood and the particular sense-organs ; and its own organ is the heart.1

1 De Juvent. 467628 ff., 469a 11. Aristotle's reasons for rejecting the brain as the sensory centre may be summarized as follows : 1. The brain of a living animal appears to be insensible to touch (Hist. anim. 520616). 2. Aristotle was unable to discover any brain in the invertebrates, except- ing the Cephalopods. The ganglia in other invertebrates, owing to his lack of instruments, escaped his notice. 3. The peripheral organs (eye, ear, and nose) are not, strictly speaking, connected with the brain, but only with the vascular membrane surrounding it. 4. The sense-ducts are con- nected with the heart, from which radiates the entire vascular system. 5. The heart is the primum vivens, vltimv/m moriens (De part. anim. 666a 20, 667a 20 ff. ; De juvent. 468628) in animal life, and as sensibility is the most fundamental animal characteristic, so the heart would appear to be the most fundamental organ of this characteristic. 6. With loss of blood sensibility is lessened. 7. The heart's action is plainly affected by pleasure and pain. 8. Its central, acropolis-like position indicates that nature's economy intended the heart to be the organ of government.

lvi INTRODUCTION

y

VI.

Imagination and Memory.1 The process of knowing, according to Aristotle, develops in three different stages : 1. The primary stage or simplest form of knowing is sensation (ala-Orja-ig) ; 2. The second stage is imagination ((pavrao-la), or the power of using images of absent objects; 3. The third stage is rational thought (vovs). Although imagination differs from sen- sation and conceptual thought, it is not possible without sensation; and thought, in turn, is not possible without imagination. Imagination is the persistence of a sense- impression after the removal of the sense-stimulus, described by Hobbes as "decaying sense,"2 and by Aristotle as a weaker 3 or less clear sense.

Imagination mediates between sensation and thought. Sensation furnishes the mind with a body of impressions and copies of the external world, the raw material which imagination and thought employ.4 Imagination is a store- house, as it were, of copies of sense-objects, which persist in the mind as images after the seen or heard objects have been removed. I no longer hear, e.g., the song that once stirred my sense, yet it sings and repeats itself in the auditor}^ imagery of my mind. I no longer see the player distraught with the woes of Oedipus, yet the picture of

1See translation, pp. 110 ff.

2 " Imagination therefore is nothing but decaying sense," Hobbes' Leviathan, Part I., ch. 2, p. 7. Oxford, 1881.

sBhet. 1370a 28.

4 Aristotle's distinctions between imagination and sensation are more minutely given in note 1, translation, p. 110.

IMAGINATION AND MEMORY lvii

his tragic face remains in my life of visual imagination. In this meaning, imagination is the power to hold the im- pression of sense after the sense-object has gone. Sensation refers to a present^ impression ; imagination refers to an impression of something that is no longer before us. Imagination is necessary, therefore, to the life of thought and memory, for without it mind would be only the ever- shifting scene of kaleidoscopic sense-impressions which, once gone, could never be revived. Imagination partakes of the nature of both thought and sensation ; like thought, it is a subjective, internal activity ; and like sensation, it is the passive receiver of images and forms from the external world.

The word fyavracria is used by Aristotle to mean both the faculty of imagination and the product of imagination. For the latter meaning, however, he ordinarily employs the word phantasm ((pavracr/uLa). There are three more or less distinct senses in which Aristotle makes use of the term phantasm : 1. Appearance ; 2. Phantasm or false appearance ; 3. An internal mental picture of an absent sense-object. It is in the last meaning that the term is usually employed in his psychological treatises. The word (pavracria is akin to <pao$ ('light'), and <j>avTa£ecr6ai (' to appear ') ; and there is in the word an implied distinction between the phantasm and the real ; it is appearance versus reality. Yet while the image is not the real thing but only the real thing's form, it may be a true copy of the real, and, as such, it is as true as sensa- tion. The two prominent elements expressed in the word, looked at etymologically, are form and light, without

lviii INTRODUCTION

which the sensible world is not revealed to us. As the eye reveals to us an external world of form and light, so phantasy reveals to us an inner world of forms, colour, \/ perspective, and light, an inner world corresponding in its imagery to the world of lighted space.

The psychophysical process by which imagination is produced is conceived by Aristotle as follows : Sensation is due to a movement set up in the sense-organ by a present stimulus. This movement has the power to persist after the stimulus has been removed. Just as one throws a pebble into the water and sets up a circular movement therein, and this moving circle creates a second by its energy, even after the pebble has disappeared, and the second circle in turn communicates its movement to a third, growing fainter the while, so a sense-stimulus sets up a movement in the sense-organ, which in turn communicates its movement to the blood, and the blood, under favourable circumstances, conveys it to the heart, which is the organ of consciousness and of the higher activities of the mind. By favourable circumstances Aristotle means cases where the movement is not inhibited or interfered with by counter-movements of sensation, and where the sensation is strong enough to persist. In the midst of the cross- currents of our motley life of sensation, the movements set up by given stimuli are constantly crossed and impeded by other movements, and there arises amongst them, as it were, a struggle for existence, to employ a much used formula of modern biology.1 Those movements which at the moment are strongest, reach the heart and become phantasms or

1 De insom. 461a, 1 ff.; De an. 4286 10 ff.

IMAGINATION AND MEMORY lix

conscious images. Similarly also to the fainter expression of the communicated movement in the illustration drawn from the pebble,1 the communicated movement in the phantasm is fainter than that in the original sensation.

In a passage in the Rhetoric already referred to, Aristotle describes a phantasm as a "weak sensation/' which is very like the view of Hobbes, who says : " All fancies are motions within us, reliques of those made in the sense." 2 These movements of the imagination are, as one might expect, especially characteristic of sleep, during which the sense-activity is suppressed. Dream -images are not always copies of the real world, but often merely a mass of confused, distorted forms having no apparent relation to actual things. Imagination, therefore, has two forms : (1) That of revived or residual sense-perceptions, i.e. copies or images of the real world, in which the imagination is passive or receptive ; (2) That of reconstructed or created images, in which the imagination is active and productive. The one form of imagination is called by Aristotle (pavracrla aicrOrjTiK}], the perceptual or reproductive imagination, and the other form (pavraa-la XoyicrTitai, the constructive or pro- ductive imagination.3 The latter belongs only to man, the

1 De insom. 461<x 20 ff. and note 1, translation, p. 242.

2 Leviathan, p. 12 (Part I., ch. iii). Cf. Freudenthal, Uebe,r dm Begriff des Wortes (pavTaaia bei Aristoteles, p. 24.

3 In modern psychology imagination and thought are less differentiated than in Aristotle's writings, where imagination is always either the reproduc- tion of sense-elements or their reconstruction into new images, without loss of their sensuous or picture character. Of constructive imagination Titchener says : " It is a ' thinking ' or judging not in words but in reproductive ideas. Psychologically, then, there is no difference between the ' imagination ' of the poet and the 'thought' of the inventor" [Outline of Psychology, p. 297).

lx INTRODUCTION

former to the brute creation as well as to man. Further, the imagery accompanying general notions and concep- tual thought is a creation of the productive imagination. The latter form of imagination is due to a free initiative power in the central organ, which may take the character of a logical construction of the elements of sense-imagery into a coherent complex, such as is exhibited in a creation of literary or plastic art; or it may take the form of arbitrary, incoherent, confused image-masses, as exhibited in sleep, in the delirium of fever, or in the excitement of vehement desire or violent passion. Such distortions and malformations, corresponding to no real things, are due mainly to physiological causes, especially to excessive heat and disordered movements in the blood. They occur mostly in sleep, because the activities of thought and sensation, which act as regulators of imagination by day, are suppressed in sleep, and, consequently, the activities of imagery have then complete control of the central organ. These phantasies, uncontrolled by waking consciousness, resemble the imagery of clouds, which, as Aristotle says,1 at one moment represent a centaur, at another a man, and are constantly shifting in their forms. Melancholy has great influence in the production of pictures of phantasy, because it generates excessive heat in the central organ ; so also have such pathological conditions as are found in ecstasy and madness, observable in the case of sibyls and religious maniacs, in whose minds the pictures of fancy are regarded as real objects. In these cases right judgment,

1 De insom. 4606 12, 4616 20; Metaph. 10246 22; Prob. 9953a iOff., 9576 10 ff.

IMAGINATION AND MEMORY lxi

which normally assists in the regulation of the image- making function, is inhibited. Imagination, then, is for Aristotle both an image-receiving and an image-producing power.1 As an image-receiving or image-holding power, it is the source of memory and recollection. This is the reproductive function of imagination. A memory or memory-image differs from a phantasm in two particulars : (1) memory regards the phantasm as a copy of something, while imagination regards it simply as a picture; (2) memory regards the thing, of which the phantasm is a copy, as having been seen or known by us. It is recog- nized as part of a past experience.

The deliberate and conscious calling up of this copy is recollection (avd/uLvrio-ii). Recollection depends on the original coherence of the movements or elements in experi-

1 That Aristotle employs imagination in these two senses is, I think, demonstrable. The terms above cited, (pavraaia alaOvrcKri and (pavraaia XoyLcrTLKr) (De an. 433629), are thus most consistently explained. Further, in the aims of art and the ends of conduct Aristotle employs imagination in the constructive or productive sense (De poet. 1455a 22 ft.; Eih. Nic. 11386 20 ff*. ), and he sharply distinguishes between the sense-imagination of the lower animals and the rational employment made of it by man (De an. 434a 6, 429a 1 ff. Cf. Frohschammer, Ueber die Principien der aristotelischen Philosophie, pp. 52 ff. ; and Teichmiiller, Aristotelische Forschungen, Vol. II., pp. 149 ff.). Again, it is possible to call before the mind an imaginary object, a new and more or less arbitrary construction, which is not possible in reproductive imagination or in discursive thought controlled by rigid laws of procedure (De an. 4276 15 ff.). Butcher, although he denies that Aristotle employed the term in a productive sense, yet in his account of phantasy implies (correctly, I think) that Aristotle did use the term in this meaning (Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and Fine Art, pp. 126 ff. and Preface, p. viii. Cf. also Freudenthal, op. cit., pp. 31, 45). It is not to be supposed, of course, that Aristotle thinks of two imaginations, but merely of two functions of this psychological power the one concerned with the reproduction of sense-elements, and the other with their logistic or rational reconstruction into new forms.

lxii INTRODUCTION

ence. By virtue of this original coherence one image is called up by another formerly connected with it. The laws of association in memory1 are described by Aristotle as (1) similarity, (2) contrast, (3) contiguity.2

Productive or active imagination, on the other hand, creates images that do not correspond with past experiences or sensations, but which have only an ideal or subjective existence. These images are the phantasies of dream-life, of delirium, of art-creation, etc. It is to the imagination that art appeals. The image-making power is the sub- jective source of art imitation ([xl/uyo-is). It is the function of imagination to clothe the idea in a picture or figured space and thus to mediate between the outward work of art and the internal idea. Art, in Aristotle's opinion, is essentially mimetic. Imitation in art is, in the first place, an imitation of a picture in the phantasy. Measured alongside the work of art, the mental picture or phantasy is an abstraction. The work of art is the concrete ideal, and here phantasy is active and creative. The mental image itself, however, is either a mimetic picture of the sensible real or it is a purified picture of the sensible real. When art is not merely mechanically reproductive or crudely mimetic, but is the purified or cathartic picture of the real, then (Aristotle says) poetry is more philoso- phical and more serious than history.3 History is par- ticular ; poetry and art are universal, idealistic.

1 Aristotle says that experience, which is akin to science and art, is derived from 'much memory' {Anal. post. 100a 5; Metaph. 9806 29). Cf. Hobbes' Leviathan (ch. ii., Part I. ), p. 7: "Much memory, or memory of many things, is called experience."

2 De mem. 451b 10 ff. a De poet. 1451?> 5 ff.

IMAGINATION AND MEMORY lxiii

The relation between phantasy and artistic genius is unfortunately scarcely more than touched upon by Aris- totle. Imagination is the normative and directing power in art, because it is imagination that places before the artist the end he wishes to attain, and this end is given in the form of a mental picture or image. The art-object exists in phantasy prior to its existence in reality. The creations of art are the projections of internal phantasms into the various forms of art-expression, into the form of fixed and arrested matter (sculpture and architecture),1 or into the form of fluent, rhythmic verbal symbols (poetry), or coloured superficies (painting), or melodious sequence of sounds (music). In every instance art is concerned with appearances ((pavrdor/uLaTa), and is, there- fore, always sensuous. It is clothed exclusively in imagery- drawn from the sense-world, even the rhythm of poetry being an imitation of aesthetic movement in a world of sensible motion.

The final function of imagination, in Aristotle's account, is to supply the schematic form in which the higher activities of conceptual thought are clothed. The reason needs general images for the schematism of general notions, and such schemata are supplied to vov$ by the productive imagination. Furthermore, imagination medi- ates the sense-world to the reason, and thought interprets the imaged world of sense in the forms of science and philosophy.

1 Architecture is not included amongst the fine arts by Aristotle, because it serves practical ends and its primary purpose is not to minister to the aesthetic emotions, and further because of its non-imitative character. Cf. Butcher, Aristotle's Theory of Poetry and Fine Art, pp. 146 fF.

lxiv

INTRODUCTION

VII.

Practical Reason and Will.

V

The practical reason differs in its function from the theoretic reason. These are_not : jLwiL^ejisj^^^ut^ one reason operative in two distinct fields, viz. in the field of knowledge and in the field of morality; and as the subject- matter and results in the two cases differ, so the two functions have received different names. The function of the theoretic reason is to discriminate between the true and the false; the function of the practical reason is to discriminate between the good and the bad.1 The former knows; the latter judges, weighs, evaluates, advises, and determines. The practical reason is concerned with de- liberation and conduct, with knowledge as applied to action ; the theoretic reason is concerned with knowledge as such. The theoretical reason gives no commands. The practical reason operates in the form of a practical syl- logism, whose conclusion is epitactic or imperative.

Aristotle describes this syllogism as follows : All de- liberate action is resolvable into a major and minor premiss, from which the given action logically issues. The major premiss is a general conception or moral maxim ; the minor premiss is a particular instance ; and the conclusion is an action involved in subsuming the particular instance under the general conception or law. The conclusion is not an abstraction, as in the case of a

lDe an. 431& 10, 433a 14, 434a 16 ; Eih. nic. 1144a 31 ff., 1147a 1 ff. ; De motu anim. 701a 7 ff.

PRACTICAL REASON AND WILL

Ixy

theoretical syllogism, but consists in an action and is jussive, e.g.1

Major premiss : All men should take exercise ;

Minor premiss : I am a man ;

Conclusion : I should take exercise ; Or,

Light meats are wholesome,

This is a light meat,

.'. It is wholesome. Our English phrase 'acting on principle' is, as Grant pointed out, the equivalent of Aristotle's practical syl- logism.2 The practical syllogism operates in the sphere of conduct, of choice and the variable 3 (to. evSexo/j-eva a\\co$ e'xeiv), n°t in the sphere of necessary truth as is the case with the speculative reason, whose aim is demonstrable truth, whereas the aim of the practical reason is the good, the prudent, the desirable. The content of the conclusion as knowledge is the essential matter for the former; the content of the conclusion as motive is the essential matter for the latter. The main business of the former is with the understanding, of the latter, with the will; the prin- ciple of ' sufficient reason ' is related to the understanding as the principle of ' final cause ' or motive is related to the will.4 In the practical syllogism obligation is vested in the conclusion, and the particular or minor premiss is more cogent than the major, i.e. it is not the general law, but the

1 De motu anim. 701a 27 ; Eth nic. 11416 18 ff.

2 The Ethics of Aristotle, edited by Sir A. Grant, 3rd ed., Loudon 1874, Vol. I., p. 269.

-Eth. nic. 1140a32ff., 1141a 1 ff.

4 Cf. Grant, op. cit., p. 263. Also De an. 432a 10 ff., translation p. 132.

e

lxiv INTRODUCTION

VII.

Practical Reason and Will.

The practical reason differs in its function from the theoretic reason. These are not two. reasons,_but_ one reason operative in two distinct fields, viz. in the field of knowledge and in the field of morality; and as the subject- matter and results in the two cases differ, so the two functions have received different names. The function of the theoretic reason is to discriminate between the true and the false ; the function of the practical reason is to discriminate between the good and the bad.1 The former knows; the latter judges, weighs, evaluates, advises, and determines. The practical reason is concerned with de- liberation and conduct, with knowledge as applied to action ; the theoretic reason is concerned with knowledge as such. The theoretical reason gives no commands. The practical reason operates in the form of a practical syl- logism, whose conclusion is epitactic or imperative.

Aristotle describes this syllogism as follows: All de- liberate action is resolvable into a major and minor premiss, from which the given action logically issues. The major premiss is a general conception or moral maxim ; the minor premiss is a particular instance ; and the conclusion is an action involved in subsuming the particular instance under the general conception or law. The conclusion is not an abstraction, as in the case of a

^De an. 431610, 433a 14, 434a 16 ; Eth. nic. 1144a 31 ff., 1147a 1 ff. ; De motu anim. 701a 7 ff.

PRACTICAL REASON AND WILL lxv

theoretical syllogism, but consists in an action and is jussive, e.g.1

Major premiss : All men should take exercise ;

Minor premiss : I am a man ;

Conclusion : I should take exercise ; Or,

Light meats are wholesome,

This is a light meat,

.". It is wholesome. Our English phrase 'acting on principle' is, as Grant pointed out, the equivalent of Aristotle's practical syl- logism.2 The practical syllogism operates in the sphere of conduct, of choice and the variable 3 (to. evSexo/J-eva a\\m e'xeiv), not in the sphere of necessary truth as is the case with the speculative reason, whose aim is demonstrable truth, whereas the aim of the practical reason is the good, the prudent, the desirable. The content of the conclusion as knowledge is the essential matter for the former; the content of the conclusion as motive is the essential matter for the latter. The main business of the former is with the understanding, of the latter, with the will ; the prin- ciple of ' sufficient reason ' is related to the understanding as the principle of ' final cause ' or motive is related to the will.4 In the practical syllogism obligation is vested in the conclusion, and the particular or minor premiss is more cogent than the major, i.e. it is not the general law, but the

1 De motu anim. 701a 27 ; Eth nic. 11416 18 ff.

2 The Ethics of Aristotle, edited by Sir A. Grant, 3rd ed., Loudon 1874, Vol. I., p. 269.

-Eth. nic. 1140a32ff., 1141a 1 ff.

4Cf. Grant, op. cit., p. 263. Also De an. 432a 10 ff., translation p. 132.

e

V

lxvi INTRODUCTION

application of the general law to a particular person, that stimulates to action.1

The virtue characteristic of the practical reason is prudence or practical insight ((ppovrjo-t?). "Prudence is neither a science nor an art ; it cannot be a science because the sphere of action is that which is variable ; it cannot be an art,2 for production is generically different from action;"3 and although Aristotle rejects the Socratic doctrine that virtue is knowledge (the sphere of moral life is pleasure and pain, rather than knowledge),4 he goes on to say that the " presence of the single virtue of prudence implies the presence of all the moral virtues." 5 Prudence, however, is not itself the whole of moral virtue : " moral virtue makes us desire the end, while prudence makes us adopt the right means to the end." 6 Although men act on general principles and laws, they do not perform general acts ; all acts are particular: and so Aristotle, in describing the practical reason and its characteristic moral quality of prudence, further differentiates it from the theoretic reason by saying it is concerned immediately with particulars (aicrOrjcri?, ecrxaTOV, irpaKTOv ayaOov, to icaO' etcacrTOv).7

The jussive character of its conclusion is, indeed, derived

1Dean. 434a 17.

2 Human activities are classified by Aristotle into three main groups : (1) knowledge, (2) action, (3) production (art). To these three groups of activities he assigns the following corresponding forms of science : (1) theoretic, (2) practical, (3) poetic. Cf. Metaph. 10256 20 ff.

s£th. nic. 114061 ff.

*Eth. nic. 11046 9.

5Eth. nic. 1145a 1 Peters' translation (4th ed., London, 1891), Bk. VI., 13, 6.

«Eth. nic. 1145a 5 (Bk. VI., 13, 7).

1 Eth. nic. 1141616, 28, 1142a 22, 1142a 25-30.

PRACTICAL REASON AND WILL lxvii

from the major premiss, but only by applying the major premiss to a particular instance. The empirical knowledge of particular facts is more immediately important. " Prud- ence x does not deal in general propositions only, but implies knowledge of particular facts also ; for it issues in action, and the field of action is the field of particulars. This is why some men who lack scientific knowledge, especially men of wide experience, are more efficient in practice than others that have such knowledge. Prudence is concerned with practice and needs both general truths and particular facts, but more especially the latter." 2 It is the particular or minor premiss that is most cogent in stimulating to action. The minor premiss, however, is immediately per- ceived and often obvious, and the practical syllogism then has the form of enthymeme.

The epitactic quality of the practical reason is not think- able apart from the virtue of the will. It can legislate, but not execute. Volition is not vested in it, although no moral volition is possible without it. However, as a legislative power it guides the will by enlightening it.

1 Walter identifies practical reason and prudence, and regards the doctrine of a vous irpanTiKos as a late interpretation of Aristotle, due to an incorrect translation of Albertus Magnus. Walter's distinctions, although very acute, seem to me not only unprofitable refinements, but of questionable bermeneutic soundness. The fact that the process here referred to is described by Aristotle as syllogistic and issuing in conduct {De an. 433a 1-16), and the frequent reference to practical reason as a distinct psychological power {irpa.KTi.Kbs vous, De an. 433a 16, Eth. nic. 1142a 25-30; di&vota Trpa/cri/oy, De an. 4336 18, Pol. 13256 18 ; \6yos irpaKTiKos, Pol. 1333a 25), seem to show that Aristotle regarded this not only as different from the theoretic function or reason, but also as different from (ppovrjais (prudence) as a moral quality. Cf. Walter, Die Lehre von der praktischen Vemunft, Jena, 1894, pp. 15 ff.

2 Eth nic. 11416 15 ff.

lxviii INTRODUCTION

By will Aristotle understands any effort towards the good. The lowest form of will is impulse; its highest form is rational desire. A

Aristotle, like Plato, developed his ethical doctrines in the closest connection with his psychological theories. His conception of the moral will and its function is determined largely by his theory of the practical reason. In his analysis of the elements of consciousness, he finds only what we should call ideational and affective elements. There is no reference to any third conative element. The two component elements in the ethical will are practical reason and desire (e7ri6ujuLia, opegig).1 Desire, as Aristotle employs it, is not a purely pathic or affective element. Feeling as such (theoretically) is completely passive, mere enjoyment of the pleasant or mere suffering of the painful. Aristotle, however, describes desire as an effort towards the attain- vy ment of the pleasant, i.e. he includes in it an activity or a conative element. It is feeling with an added quality of impulse (Trieb). More specifically and in detail the elements contained in it are : (1) An idea or presentative element. There can be no desire without cognition or imagination (opeKTiKov Se ovk avev (pai'Taclag).2 An animal cannot desire that of which it has no image. (2) An element of feeling. In every desire or aversion there is an element of pleasure or pain.3 (3) An element of effort or activity.4 Desire •* involves pursuit or avoidance, 'and in it is given a spring

1 De an. 4326 6 ff. , 433a 2 ff. , 4146 5, 433a 1—4336 30, 431a 12 ; De somno, 454631; Eth. nic. 1094a 21, 1139a 22, lllla32ff. 2 Dean. 4336 28.

zDe an. 413623, 434a 3; Eth. nic. 11756 27. 4 De an. 433a 9-21 ; Eth. nic. 11116 17, 1139a 22.

PRACTICAL REASON AND WILL lx

of action. The object of desire is the motive in conduct.1 The pleasure that is felt or anticipated is the object of effort and the initiator of movement, and it is through desire that the practical reason operates indirectly on actions. " Mere reasoning never sets anything in motion, but only reasoning about means to an end or practical reasoning," 2 i.e. reasoning which guides or modifies the desires.

This deliberative process of the practical reason, issuing in an imperative conclusion and combined with desire, con- stitutes for Aristotle the moral will. The reason alone does not produce action, and the desire alone is non-rational and non-moral. Aristotle, therefore, defines the moral will <7r/Doa//oeo7?)3 as desire penetrated by reason, or reason stimulated by desire (ope£i? StavotiriKi'i, vov$ o/oe/crtKo'?).4 The practical reason contains a jussive force and rightness, while desire supplies an active, appetitive quality. The moral will, therefore, is a complex of reason and desire, and is supposed by Aristotle to function under the follow- ing modes : (1) deliberate choice ; (2) purpose ; (3) freedom ; (4) fixed habit. By means of particular acts issuing from free and deliberate choice is generated the individual's moral character, which Aristotle describes as fixed habit (eft?) 5 or the persistent will.

Aristotle maintains the freedom of the will, and says it is in our power to be "worthy or worthless."6 This, he argues, is attested by our own consciousness of power to

1 De an. 4336 1 1 . 2 Eth. nic. 1 1 39a 36.

3 Eth. nic. 1106a3, 1113allff., I139a31, 33, 113964; De mot. anim. 7006 23. 4 Eth. nic. 1 1396 4, 1 1026 30.

5Categ. 86 28, 9a5; Eth. nic. 1106a 22, 1105625, 1157631. «Eth. nic. 1113614.

lxx INTRODUCTION

do or to refrain, by the common testimony men, by the rewards and punishments of rulers, and by the general employment of praise and blame. Particular acts are always in our power, and we are responsible for them, we may not contend that because they are determined by temperament or character, they are not free and we are not responsible.1 " We are masters of our acts from beginning to end, when we know the particular circum- stances ; but we are masters of the beginnings only of our habits or characters, while their growth by gradual steps is imperceptible, like the growth of disease. Inasmuch, however, as it lay with us to employ or not to employ our faculties in this wTay, the resulting characters are on that account voluntary." 2 In a certain sense we are creators of our own determinism, paradoxical as this may sound. Aristotle says in the Topics that man is determined in the sense that " a man's destiny is his own soul," 3 although its character is his own voluntary creation. It is true that by voluntary particular acts a man becomes volun- tarily just or unjust, "but it does not follow that, if he wishes it, he can cease to be unjust and be just, any more than he who is sick can, if he wishes it, be whole. And it may be that he is voluntarily sick, through living incontin- ently and disobeying the doctor. At one time, then, he had the option not to be sick, but he no longer has it, now that he has thrown away his health. When you have

1Eth. nic. 11136 5 ff. (Bk. III., ch. 5).

2Eth. nic. 11147)26 ff. (Peters' translation, 4th ed., London, 1891, Bk. III., ch. 5, end).

8 Top. 112a 38, ravr-qv (sc. i>vxw) yap endcxTOV ehcu daifxova.

CREATIVE REASON lxxi

thrown a stone, it is no longer in your power to call it back."1

In the foregoing I have had regard only to the moral will. In a general sense, however, perhaps akin to Schopenhauer's conception, Aristotle employs the term evepyeia (all organic effort) as will. This form of will or activity is, in his teleological view of the world, impulse to the good or a striving towards self-realization, whether in plant or animal. It manifests itself in psychical life in such various forms as nutrition, locomotion, sensation, and rational activity. The whole of psychical or organic life, therefore, is regarded from the standpoint of will or activity tending designedly towards the realization of a given potentiality. But will in the moral sense, the voluntas intellectiva of Thomas Aquinas and the will of modern ethics, is rationalized desire or feeling acting under forms imposed by reason.

VIII.

Creative Reason.2

Aristotle's account of the theoretical activity of reason is very meagre, wholly inadequate for any reconstruc- tion that is not speculative and tentative. Even the learned commentator Themistius says regarding the doctrine of the active reason : " The philosopher himself (i.e. Aristotle) is here more like a puzzled inquirer

lEth. nic. 1113&14ff.

2 This chapter is reprinted (with slight changes) from the Philosophical Review (Vol. XI., No. 3, May 1902).

lxxii INTRODUCTION

(cnropovvTi) than a teacher." 1 And Theophrastus, who succeeded Aristotle as Scholarch of the Lyceum and was intimately instructed in the Peripatetic doctrines, although he accepted the theory of a twofold reason (active and passive), was unable to explain it. How the reason could be at once native to man and yet enter from without, and how potentiality is related to actuality in reasoning, were difficulties which Theophrastus, as reported by Themistius,2 regarded as serious, if not insoluble. Thus the question regarding the nature of the active reason3 early became a matter of controversy, and it has continued a fruitful source of polemics among the Syrians, Arabs, and Christians for well-nigh two millenniums.

Eudemus explained the active reason in us by saying that it is God (not Oeiov but #eoc) in man (cf. Eih. Eud. 1248a 24). Similarly, Alexander of Aphrodisias (called Aristotle's exegete par excellence), who held a pantheistic view of the world, regarded the creative reason as the activity of the divine intelligence.4 The Syrians and Arabs were greatly influenced by Alexander. Avicenna, however, interprets the doctrine in terms of an emanation theory of the world, akin to Neo-Platonism. Intelligible forms are endowed with immaterial pre-existence in pure spirits, the highest created intelligences. From the highest they pass

1 Themistius, Comm. in Arist. lib. de anima, fol. lib.

2 Themistius, Paraphrasis librorum de anima, ed. Spengel, pp. 189, 8 ; 198, 13. (On Dean. III., 5.)

3 The term vovs ttol-^tlkos occurs nowhere in the writings of Aristotle, but the equivalent is given in to ttoltjtlkov and to ttolcIp irdvTa and by implica- tion in the antithesis to vovs irad^TtKos. Cf. De an. 426a 4, 430a 12, 430a 24.

4 Cf. Brentano, Die Psychologic des Aristoteles, Mainz, 1867, p. 7.

CREATIVE REASON lxxiii

into a second sphere, from the second into a third, and so on down into the last, which is the creative reason (intelligentia agens). From this creative (cosmic) reason intelligible forms pass into the soul, on the one hand ; as substantial forms they pass into material things, on the other hand. Subject and object are thus reconciled by means of the forms (intelligible for reason and substantial for concrete things) which emanate from a common source, viz. the creative reason. The substantial form, i.e. the class- notion immanent in sensible particulars, is correlated with the intelligible form, i.e. the concept immanent in reason, and therefore knowing subject and known object are only different aspects of one reality. Subject and object are unified in the creative reason. The passive reason, by means of phantasms or images, is able to apprehend the substantial forms (genera), and from the active reason it receives the light of intelligible forms (concepts). The intelligible forms from the active reason are combined in the passive reason with the sensible forms, and erected into the structure of empirical science. Every act of knowing implies receptivity from this dual source of emanated forms intelligible and substantial forms : a curious mix- ture of Aristotelianism with Neo-Platonism.

Averroes, the foremost Arabic exegete of Aristotle, and one of the most important intellectual figures of the Middle Ages, regards both the active (intellectus agens) and the passive reason (intellectus materialis) as spiritual entities distinct from the body and from each other. The former's activity consists in making sensible images intelligible, and thereby moving the passive reason. The passive reason

lxxiv INTRODUCTION

receives the phantasms which have been illuminated and made intelligible by the active reason. This dual reason (consisting of two separate entities) is the eternal in man : while the other powers that are concerned with the par- ticular originate with the body and perish with the body. In the interpretation of Avicenna, on the contrary, only the creative reason is eternal ; while the passive reason, depending on the life of sense-experience, perishes with the body. In the interpretation of Averroes, although the reason is immortal, individuality ceases with death; for differences in individuals are due to differences in their accumulated sensible images and phantasmata in the content of their experience. Rational activity, as such, is universally the same, and it is *only this universal, non- individual principle of reason that persists after death. All individuals are alike in participating in one rational life, and they are different in so far as reason has a different mass of images to illumine. The principle of individuation is in plastic matter, not in generic form, and reason is related to sensible images as form is related to matter.

Trendelenburg,1 in the commentary to his edition of the De anima, explains the passive reason as the sum of all the lower cognitive faculties, including the power of sense-perception. It is passive because it stands in the relation of receptivity to the object of cognition and is affected by it. The completion of its processes is, however, obtained only through the agency of the active reason. The derivation of the universal notion from particular 1 Cf . Commentary on De an. III. , § 5, 2 ff.

CREATIVE REASON lxxv

sensations is a function of the passive reason, in so far as the universal notion is regarded as part of the mind's content. The creative reason furnishes the ultimate prin- ciples of knowledge, i.e. it contains and applies the standard of truth and falsity in the conceptual world as the ' common sense ' passes judgment on the true and false in perceptual reality.1 The creative reason is not the divine spirit (although it is related to the divine), but belongs to the individual, and is not the same in all men. The rela- tion between the divine spirit and the creative reason in man is nowhere explained by Aristotle, beyond his saying in the Metaphysics that they are analogous principles.2

Ravaisson, in his Essai stir la metaphysiquue d'Aristote,2, says that the individual man, according to Aristotle, has only passive reason, which as the potentiality of all forms and ideas is analogous to primary matter. It is the uni- versal potentiality in the world of ideas. On the other hand, the creative activity which actualizes possible forms and produces all thoughts is the absolute reason. The sensible and the passively rational are fundamentally the same ; both exist in a single consciousness, and are operated on by the active reason. The entire passive reason (and so all individuality) is mortal. The creative reason is con- ceived by Ravaisson in the same way as by Alexander of Aphrodisias. Renan4 regards Aristotle's conception of the creative reason as similar to Malebranche's theory of seeing things in God, a conception suggested to Aristotle, perhaps, by the Anaxagorean doctrine of Nous.

1 Cf. Aristotle, De insom. 4616 2 ff. 2 Metaph. 1072b 18 ff.

3 Vol. I., pp. 5S6fF. 4Brentano, op.cit., p. 34.

lxxvi INTRODUCTION

Zeller considers the passive reason to mean the " sum of those faculties of representation which go beyond imagina- tion and sensible perception, and yet fall short of that higher thought which has found peace in perfect unity with itself." x It does not include the powers of sense- perception, as Trendelenburg thinks, nor is it identical with " fancy as the seat of mental pictures," as Brentano supposes.2 Von Hertling, in calling the passive reason " the cognitive faculty of the sensitive part," 3 would almost seem to identify it with the sensus communis. Zeller rejects these and all other explanations of Aristotle's theory, and wholly abandons the reconciliation of the twofold reason in one personality. He further considers it entirely unjustifiable, even in Aristotle's own theory, to apply the term nous to the ' passive reason.' Reason, he says, is in its essence "a single immediate apprehension of intelligible reality, constituting one indivisible act," 4 which it is not possible to interpret in terms of Aristotle's dual theory.

Wallace, whose interpretation of Aristotle is somewhat coloured by English Hegelianism, says : " Aristotle would seem to mean that while our intellectual powers are on the one hand merely receptive while they merely elaborate and, by processes of discursive thought, systematize the materials of thought these materials of thought only become so, only get formed into an intelligible world, by an act of reason which has gone on from the creation of

teller's Aristotle, Eng. tr., Vol. II., p. 102.

2 Zeller, op. cit., II., p. 103. 3Von Hertling, Materie und Form, p. 174.

4 Zeller, op. cit., II., p. 105.

CREATIVE REASON lxxvii

the world and is in turn employed by each of us. Shortly, then, the creative reason is the faculty which constantly interprets and, as it were, keeps up an intelligible world for experience to operate upon, while the receptive reason is the intellect applying itself in all the various processes which fill our minds with the materials of knowledge." 1

The foregoing account of Aristotle's theory of reason, as interpreted by his most notable commentators, exhibits very wide differences of opinion. This great diversity is due to the character of the data furnished by Aristotle data that are both meagre and ambiguous, precluding the possibility of any apodictic formulation of his doctrine. There has been no lack of ability or ingenuity expended on it. It is entirely hopeless, in my opinion, to try to discover any satisfactory explanation of the creative reason in the scanty passages of the third book of the Be anima, to which attention has been too exclusively directed. An explanation, if it can be found at all, can be found only in the light of Aristotle's general system of philosophy, and more especially in the light of his complete theory of know- ledge. I shall proceed at once to make my meaning plain.

It is clear that the theory of a twofold reason, as Aristotle held it, originated partly in the controversy regarding the distinction between conceptual and perceptual knowledge, and partly in Aristotle's metaphysical ideas regarding the distinction between form and matter. The controversy touching conceptual and perceptual knowledge had before Aristotle's time issued, on the one hand, in the extreme sensualism of the Sophists, and, on the other hand, in the 1 Wallace, Aristotle's Psychology, p. xcviii.

lxxviii INTRODUCTION

extreme rationalism Plato. Between these two Aristotle adopts a mediating position of empiricism. To him there are no innate ideas, and no body of rational truth totally independent of particular reality. All knowledge is per- ceptually derived, but the materials of perception cannot be converted into the fabric of scientific knowledge or into general concepts without a creative and supplementary act of reason. For Aristotle, as for Kant, conception with- out perception is empty. The content of perception is made into conceptual knowledge by a process of reason, and in this sense is a created content. Before this act takes place, the content of mind is passive matter awaiting a transforming and constructive process. At this point, Aristotle applies to psychical life the metaphysical dualism under which he views the entire organic world. Active reason stands to passive reason in the relation of form to matter.1 His metaphysics, then, and the distinction between conceptual and perceptual knowledge, explain the genesis of his theory of a twofold reason. The creative reason is the form-principle ; the pathic reason is the sum of matter that is formed into rational significance. Eeason receives its content from without; in other words, it is passive. However, if that were all, reason would be only a receptacle of sensations, perceptions, memory-images, and phantasmata. But transcending these pathic elements, reason has the informing power of changing their potentiality into the highest abstractions and most general notions and laws. In this way, reason, in its pathic aspect, becomes or receives all reality; while in its active character, it creates all

1 De an. 430a 10 ff.

CREATIVE REASON lxxix

reality by bestowing upon it a rational form. Without the latter the mind would be a mass of particulars, of unrelated manifold things, blind. The active reason creates an intelligible world in the sense of constructing its intelligi- bility, while its real content is given in the materials of the passive reason which are delivered from without. This content is potentially conceptual. The creative reason is thus primarily without content, an unwritten tablet.1 Between conceptual and perceptual knowledge, between the abstract and concrete, there is not for Aristotle the great impassable gulf that we find in Plato's epistemology. Although the discovery of the universal is an act of reason, yet the universal is potentially and immanently in the individual. The subject-matter of reason is the immanent universal, which in a certain sense is in the mind itself.2 Thought and sense-perception are neither identical nor are they to be completely sundered. Aristotle sharply criticises both of these extremes in his predecessors, holding the sophistic sensualism and Platonic rationalism to be equally one-sided and erroneous. In thought we think, it is true, what is potentially given in perception, and yet this object of thought must first be made rational by a creative act of reason. Reason creates its world in terms of itself (i.e. a rational world); and, as its subject-matter consists of abstract ideas, it thinks itself, and subject and object are identical.3 Aristotle is not a pure empiricist, although in certain passages he speaks as if all our ideas were derived from sense-perceptions4 and apart from sense-perception

1 De an. 430a 1. 2 De an. 4176 23.

3 De an. 429a 25, 430a 2, 4316 17. 4 De an. 432a 2 ff.

lxxx INTRODUCTION

there were no reality. In the Analytics, however, where he gives the most detailed account of the origin of our knowledge, he speaks of the highest principles of knowledge as immediate (to. a/meo-a) and as presupposed by mediately derived knowledge, being the latter 's starting-point.1 These ultimate principles are propositions whose predicates are given in the subject, i.e. ' analytical a priori judg- ments.'2 This knowledge is, however, merely potential (empty conception) until applied to the content of experi- ence. It does not contain any positive ideas, but, as in the case of the principles of contradiction and excluded middle, it comes to consciousness in the regulation and determination of cognitive data. These regulative, axiomatic principles are formed by the mind out of itself.3 The content of the concepts arrived at by induction, or by an ascent from particular to general, takes the form of mediate knowledge ; and the most universal of these concepts is only a "precipitate of a progressively refined experience,, and is due to the last act in successive generalizations upon a matter given in experience."4 Ideas derived from in- duction attain a degree of certainty not higher than the source from which they spring. On the other hand, the ultimate principles (a/>xa0 °^ reason are necessarily true,5 and such knowledge has the nature of an " intuition as contrasted with sensible perception."6 The apodictic syllogism, or highest form of scientific truth, proceeds from

1Ci. Zeller's Aristotle, Eng. tr., Vol. I, p. 197. Also Aristotle, Anal, post. 866 36, 94a 9, 1086 8; Eth. nic. 1141a.

2Zeller, op. cit., Vol. I, p. 198. 3 De an. 429628 ff.

4Zeller, op. cit., Vol. I, p. 201. 5 Aristotle, Anal. post. 1006 5 ff.

6Zeller, op. cit., Vol. I, p. 202.

CREATIVE REASON lxxxi

these ultimate principles as premisses. Induction, proceed- ing from the particular, is clearer to us because individual things of sense have more apparent certainty. Deduction and induction form the component elements of scientific method, but the function of the former is higher, being the interpretation of phenomena by the ultimate principles both of knowledge and existence, viz., by universal laws and causes.

Ultimate principles and universal forms are immanent both in the mind and in things. They are not mental categories projected upon the phenomenal world, but are discovered in the phenomenal world by reason. In a sense, reason finds itself in the world, and the fact of this im- manent community bridges the gulf between subject and object. On the plane of perceptual knowledge, the passage between subject and object is bridged by the function of the central sense, which is the active principle in converting received sensations into a conscious percept. The content of the central sense memory and phantasy as the pathic material of reason, is in turn converted into the form of conceptual knowledge by the creative activity of reason. Reason has no bodily organ, and so operates only on psychical elements, and not on elements physiologically mediated. Reason, then, confers on a potentially rational world its actually rational existence; and, moreover, in thinking the actually rational, it thinks itself. Without the active reason the conceptual world would be no more known in thought than the visible world would be seen without light.1 As light makes colour visible, so the

1 De an. 430a 15.

/

lxxxii INTRODUCTION

creative reason makes the the universal forms intelligible. Or, to use another analogy employed by Aristotle, the creative reason operates on the content of perceptual con- sciousness as an artist operates on his raw materials.1 The two main stages in the process of knowledge, perception and conception, are supplementary. Thought, on the one hand, requires a sensuous image,2 and perception, on the other, remains on a brute level when not illuminated and elevated into conceptual form by reason.

The creative reason is akin to the divine. Corresponding with his metaphysical conception of the divine in the universe, Aristotle regards the creative reason as the divine in the microcosm. It is no part of the entelechy of the body, but is transcendent (xoopio-ros, i.e. it has no bodily organ and is separable from organic life) and it enters the body from without (6vpa6ei>)? It acts, however, on the rational life of the organism, but it acts as the ' unmoved mover,' who is immanent in the world without being a part of it. The creative reason is not developed with the body, but enters the psychical element (whose immediate corporeal embodiment is the warm air or pneuma in the seed) at the moment of conception. Conception is the occasion, not the cause, of its entering into the womb.4 The question, how- ever, touching the preexistence and immortality of the soul is scarcely more than mentioned by Aristotle, and,

1 De an. 430a 12. 2De an. 431a 17, 432a 8 ; De mem. 4496 30.

3 De gener. anim. 7366 27 ff.

4 De gener. anim. 737a 5 ff. Granger in a valuable article in Mind (Vol. 18, New Series, Vol. 2, 1893, p. 317) thinks that a universal reason in Aristotle's psychology can be spoken of only in the sense in which one speaks of "a universal humanity." Cf. the same writer in the Classical Review, Vol. VI., pp. 298 ff.

CREATIVE REASON lxxxiii

indeed, it hardly falls within the scope of his psychology, which is an essentially biological discussion. It is only in treating of the nature of reason that he goes beyond the boundaries of empiricism and makes concession to the traditional view of the divine origin of the noetic power a concession that may have been prompted by his analo- gous view of the Prime Mover as the transcendent cosmic reason. Aristotle constructs his psychology, as he does his entire system of philosophy, on the basis of the deliverances of the special sciences of his day deliverances which were penetrated and interpreted by his unifying and organizing spirit. As Romanes says, " instead of giving his fancy free rein ' upon the high a priori road,' he patiently plods the way of detailed research." 1 Yet, after he has completely examined the data and psychical mechanism of empirical knowledge, he finds them inadequate to explain the whole of reality, and is forced to introduce a rational ego to explain the potential rationality of pathic experience. This noetic principle which rationalizes experience is in no wise connected with the physical organism, *and as it is not a part of the latter s entelechy, so it does not perish with its dissolution.2 It is the a priori condition of all rational knowledge, and, as such, it is not individual. Receptive or pathic reason,3 on the other hand, is simply

1 Contemporary Eevietv, Vol. 59, p. 284. a De an. 408& 18, 4136 20 ff.

3 No one familiar with Aristotle's use of terms, will discover an objection in his applying two designations to the same thing, viz. to his calling the sum of perceptual experience now sensus communis, and again passive reason. For as completed sense-experience, the sensus communis is form {ei8os), and as the raw material for some higher development it is poten- tiality {v\r)). That higher development is reason, which the common sense is potentially.

lxxxiv INTRODUCTION

the life of sensation as a potentially rational mass, and is connected with the physical organism, with which it perishes.1 Primarily, the creative reason is, as above noted, without content ; it is an unwritten tablet (ypa/uLimaTeiov).2 Its content is given in the passive reason, which is stored with phantasmata ultimately derived from sense and the free construction of imagination. Strictly speaking, the active reason does not think things, it does not create de novo; it merely interprets things, or rationalizes pheno- mena, by its spontaneous activity.3 Nevertheless, we have here not merely that which is given in sense-experience, but a new element, rationally derived, a new significance. Passive reason rises no higher than the deliverances of sense-perception and their re- wrought form in memory and phantasy. The sum of these is the sum of the content of the sensus communis ; this sum, regarded as potentiality, is the passive reason, on which the active reason operates in the creation of a rational and conceptual world. The creative reason does not, indeed, think anything apart from the passive reason,4 because without images derived from experience thought has no content and nothing to interpret or illumine. Its activity, however, is continuous,5 because its subject-matter, unlike a sense-object, is always present. Further, as the universal reason, it is as eternal and continuous as is the intelligibility of the eternal world.6

1 De an. 430a 25. 2 De an. 430a 1.

3 Cf . Scotus : ' ' nullus intellectus intelligit, nisi intellectus possibilis. . . . [intellectus agens] non intelligit, sed intelligere facit." Quoted by Schlott- mann in Das Vergangliche unci Unvergangliche in d. menschlichen Seele nach Arist. p. 48.

4 De an. 430a 25. 6 De an. 430a 22. ti De ccelo, 2796 12.

CREATIVE REASON lxxxv

Wo do not remember 1 the processes of the active reason an understanding of which in the individual is arrived at only by analysis because it is without passivity, and memory is a passive power.

Aristotle describes the creative reason (I draw from various passages) as follows : it is unmixed, transcendent, passionless, of divine nature, it suffers no change, is not born, it has no bodily organ, enters the body from without, and is immortal.2 The question of the reason's transcend- ence and immortality, although metaphysically interesting, has little epistemological significance, and Aristotle scarcely does more than raise the question, and while he espouses the view of transcendence and immortality, he does so hesitatingly and without dogmatism. Transcendence, in- deed, would seem to have no legitimate place in his biological view of the soul and to be irreconcilable with his definition of yfrv\ri as " entelechy of the body." It is a survival of the Platonic transcendentalism, with which Aristotle had been imbued during his life in the Academy, and whose spell he never quite shook off, a thing to be set down to his credit.

In the foregoing account of Aristotle's theory of reason I have endeavoured to show how his employment of the terms ' form ' and ' matter ' and his criticism of the Socratic-Sophistic controversy regarding conceptual and perceptual knowledge can be made to supplement certain dark passages in the De anima and the Analytics, and how

1 De an. 430a 23.

-De an. 408618-29, 413624, 430a 12 ff.; Eth. nic. 1177a 15; De gen. anim. 736615 ff.

lxxxvi INTRODUCTION

these various elements can be combined into an intelligible and consistent interpretation. Briefly summarized, this interpretation is as follows : Aristotle adopted a mediating position between the ultra-sensualism of the Sophists and the ultra-rationalism of Plato. The totality of knowledge is neither purely empirical nor purely rational, but a com- posite {avvoXov, as is every other combination of ' form ' and ' matter ') of sense experience and rational activity. In this composite, rational activity is related to sense-experience as elSog is related to uXrj. The sum of sense-data constitutes the potentiality of reason, i.e. it constitutes the passive reason, while their construction into actual rational significance constitutes the activity of creative reason ; the real content is given in the former, the formal content in the latter. The content, therefore, of the sensus communis regarded as rational potentiality is the vov$ iraOtjriKog ; the power which converts this potentiality into actual rational forms or meanings is the vovg ttouitikos. This conversion is identical with the erection of perceptual materials into a world of concepts and laws. The subject-matter of reason is an immanent universal, immanent at once in perceptual reality and in the reason itself. The process which the reason undergoes in discovering the universal is, therefore, the process of finding itself in the world. The conception of an equivalence between the universal forms existing in the mind and universal forms immanent in nature bridged for Aristotle the gulf between subject and object, two aspects of reality which he regarded as formally identical.

ABBREVIATIONS.

[ ] = words regarded by Biehl as not belonging to the text and to be deleted.

([ ]) = words inserted by the translator.

The marginal references, e.g. 402a, are to the pagination (with column a or b) of the Berlin (quarto) edition. The other marginal references, e.g. 2, 3, 4, are to the sections in the chapters of the Oxford (octavo) edition.

ARISTOTLE'S PSYCHOLOGY.

(DE ANIMA.)

BOOK THE FIRST.1

CHAPTEE I.

We regard knowledge as a good and precious thing, but 402 a we esteem one sort of knowledge more highly than

1 Bonitz regards the various chapters of De an. Bk. I. as Aristotle's, although he thinks that the order in which they are placed is due to another hand {Monatsbericht der Kbnigl. Preuss. Akad. d. Wiss., 1873, p. 481). The authenticity of Bks. I. and II. has never been seriously questioned. Bk. III., however, was held by Weisse to be spurious {Aristoteles von der Seele, pp. 278 flf.), but no scholar now, to my knowledge, accepts his view. The Aristotelian canon is much less questionable than the Platonic, and, as far as the acroamatic writings are concerned, has always remained compara- tively fixed. The objection of Bonitz to Bk. I. scarcely means more than that its Aristotelian content was subjected to editorial arrangement, which was not always skilful, a criticism that may be applied to every other treatise in the Opera. To attempt to determine how much latitude Andronicus and the succeeding editors allowed themselves, is merely to speculate. All of the works, without exception, are fragmentary and ill put together, but this has been explained generally by the time-honoured hypothesis (and still the most reason- able one) that the writings of Aristotle, as we have them, are lecture- notes or perhaps sketches for treatises, which he never put into finished form, the last part of his life being disturbed by quasi- religious persecution and spent practically in exile.

A

2 aristotle's psychology deanima

another either because of the acumen1 required for its discovery, or because it is concerned with better and more admirable objects : for both these reasons we should rightly assign the investigation of the soul 2 to the first rank. Further, it is supposed that a knowledge of the soul has an important bearing on all truth, and par- ticularly on that of the natural world. For the soul is, 2 as it were, the genetic principle 3 in living things. Our

1 This meaning of /car' &Kpl[3eiai> appears to be the only one admissible in the context. Cf. Passow, sub voc. The meaning which the term has when applied to metaphysical or abstract subjects {Eth. nic. 1141a 16; Metaph. 982a 25, 1078a 10; Anal. post. 86a 17), viz., 'exacti- tude ' in the sense of ' finally true ' or truth deduced from the first principles of reality, is not applicable here. Aristotle regards the materials of psychology as belonging to the natural and organic world, which to him is never the realm of necessary or exact truth. 'A/cpt/3eia in the ordinary sense of ' precision ' is ascribed to the mathematical disciplines in varying degrees {Met. 1053a 1, 995a 15; Anal. post. 87a 35), but this sense is also inadmissible here (cf. 402a 11). In addition to those meanings which refer to the science itself, the word also has a signification which refers to the demand made by the science on the investigator, viz., 'painstaking accuracy,' or 'acumen' (' Scharfsinn,' Passow). In the present passage this appears to be the only usable meaning. Vid. Wallace, Aristotle's Psychology, p. 196 ; Trendelenburg, Arist. Be an. 2nd ed. p. 156.

2i/uXV ('soul,' 'life,' 'mind,') is generally translated in the following pages by 'soul.' For a discussion of its meanings in Aristotle's writings vid. Introduction, Chap. i.

s>Apxn (principium) is included amongst the notions defined by Aristotle in his philosophical dictionary (Metaph. Bk. V.). Through him it became a philosophical term of the first importance, and has con- tinued so to the present time. In the sense of element (<xtolx^ov) we find it in use as early as Anaximander. The meanings enumerated in the Metaphysics are : In reference to ( 1 ) space and time = beginning ; (2) methods elementary steps in learning; (3) the physical = basis ; (4) the genetic = the moving cause; (5) the political = primary authority; (6) knowledge = principium cognoscendi, as e.g. the premises of a syllogism. The scholastics included these several meanings under principium essendi and principium cognoscendi, for which Aristotle has the corresponding expression, tov yv&vai /cat ttjs Ktvrjcrews dpxv {Met. 1013a 22).

bk. i. ch. i. METHODS OF INVESTIGATION 3

aim is to investigate and ascertain the{ essential nature ) of the soul, and, secondly, to discover those properties which attach to it as accidents. Certain of the latter are supposed to be conditions peculiar to the soul's own nature, and others are thought to be effects produced in living beings by the soul's agency.

Now, it is altogether the most difficult problem 3 to arrive at any fixed belief touching the soul. From the fact that the problem is one which is common to other subjects I mean the problem of finding the essence and real definition 1 of a thing it might perhaps appear to some that there is a single scientific method which applies to everything whose essence we wish to discover, as deductive proof applies to accidental pro- perties. We shall, therefore, be obliged to make inquiry into this question of scientific method. But if there is 4 no single and general method which applies to the ultimate nature of things, our investigation becomes in that case all the more difficult. And even if the question of method were cleared up, whether its form be that of deductive proof, or analysis, or some other procedure, there still remains a question of great diffi- culty and uncertainty, viz. from what principles are we to start our inquiry ? For different principles are employed in different subjects, as e.g. in numbers2 and in plane surfaces.

The first necessity, perhaps, is to determine under 5

1 For the meaning of to t'i £<tti see Schwegler's classic excursus in his Die Metaphysik des Aristoteles, Bk. IV., pp. 369 ff. Also Trendelen- burg in fiheinisch.es Museum, 1828, pp. 457 ff.

2 The different principles employed by arithmetic and geometry are the unit and extension.

4 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de anima

what genus soul is to be classified and what its nature is

I mean by this the question whether it is an individual

thing and self-subsisting entity, or whether it is a quality

or a quantity or classifiable in one of the other cate-

. gories 1 already enumerated, and further, whether it is a

\ potentiality 2 or rather an actuality. For this makes no dxX

402 b slight difference. We must also inquire whether the *

6 soul is divisible or whether it is without parts ; whether it is an entirety of one sort or not. And if it is not of one sort, we must further ask whether the differences are specific or generic. For nowadays the men 3 who discuss and investigate the soul appear to direct their inquiries

7 merely to the human soul. We must take pains to see whether there is a single definition that applies to the soul, just as e.g. there is a single definition that applies to animal, or whether a different definition is required for each kind of soul, just as a different definition is required for horse, dog, man, god, and we must further inquire whether the common notion ' animal ' 4 either is nothing

1 The categories or forms under which Being is known, are enumerated in the Toxica (103& 22) as follows : 1. Substance, 2. Quantity, 3. Quality, 4. Relation, 5. Place, 6. Time, 7. Position, 8. Possession, 9. Activity, 10. Passivity. All of them are reducible to subject [bvofxa, corresponding to the category of ' substance ') and predicate {prjixa., corresponding to the nine remaining categories).

2 For an explanation of the terms potentiality and actuality vid. note 1, p. 42.

3 It is not known to whom reference is made here. Simplicius {Comment, in lib. De an. ad loc.) thinks the Timaeus is referred to, which is hardly possible owing to Plato's treatment of the world-soul. Nor is it easy to see how Wallace (translating vvv ixev by "at present" as he does), can suppose the reference is to the older physiologers.

4 The question as to the nature of universals, which divided the Mediaeval Nominalists and Realists, was here clearly raised by Aristotle. Vid. Simplicius, Commentary ad loc.

bk. i. ch. i. METHODS OF INVESTIGATION 5

at all or else comes into existence only after the indi- vidual,— a question that might equally well be raised regarding any other general notion. If, however, there are not several souls, but only parts of a single soul, then the further question arises whether we should examine the soul as a whole before we examine the parts. It 8 is also hard to determine which of these parts is in its nature different from the other and whether we should first investigate the part or the part's function, e.g. whether we should first investigate the process of thought or the faculty of thought, sense-perception or the organ of sense-perception ; the same question applies to other cases. Now, supposing that the functions take precedence of the faculties in the order of investigation, a further question might arise here as to whether the complements of the faculties should be investigated before the faculties themselves, e.g. whether the investigation of the sensible object should precede the investigation of the sense-organ, and the object of thought precede the faculty of thought. Not only does the knowledge of the 9 essential nature of a thing seem to be helpful towards the understanding of the accidental nature and properties of substances, just as in mathematics the knowledge of the essential nature of straight or curved or of a line or surface is helpful in understanding how many right angles are contained in the angles of a triangle, but conversely, the knowledge of accidental properties con- tributes largely to the understanding of what a thing essentially is. For when we are able to give an account of the accidental properties of things, as we see them, either of all these properties or of most of them,

6 aristotle's psychology deanima

then we are best able to speak also of their essential nature. For the essential nature is the true starting- point in all deductive proof. And so in the case of definitions where not only no knowledge of the accidental properties is furnished, but where it is not easy even to 403^ conjecture what these properties are, it is evident that all such definitions are framed after the fashion of dialectics 1 and are void.

10 A further difficulty presents itself regarding the affections of the soul, viz. whether all these affections are common to the soul and to the body which contains it, or whether there is a something that is the exclusive property of the soul. And it is necessary, though not

ii easy, to solve this difficulty. In most cases the soul apparently neither acts nor is acted upon independently of the body, e.g. in the feelings of anger, courage, desire, <t/vu*W or in a word in sense-perception. Thought, however, » ^ Jb^ appears to be a (function) which more than any other j -b^" ij_Jth^_ej^ckisiye_ property of the souL, But if thought] is a sort of representation in terms of a sense-image, or^t^\ is impossible without this, then even thought could not )^\

12 exist independently of the body. If, then, there were any function or affection of the soul that were peculiar to it, it would be possible for the soul to exist separate and apart from the body.2 If, however, there is nothing

lI.e. distinctions thus made are merely verbal or eristic and have no real content.

2 The difficult question as to whether the soul is capable of existing separately from the body is not very clearly or definitely answered by Aristotle. According to Aristotle's classic definition, the soul is the "entelechy of a body endowed with the capacity of life." From this definition one would conclude that the soul cannot exist apart from

bk. i. ch. i. SEPARABILITY OF THE SOUL 7

which is its exclusive property, it cannot exist apart, but the case is similar to that of a straight line, which, as straight, has many properties, e.g. contact with a bronze globe at a given point, although the quality 'straight,' apart from some body, does not touch the globe. For it has no abstract existence, as it is always conjoined with some body. The same thing seems to hold good 13 of the properties of the soul : courage, gentleness, fear, pity, audacity, also joy, love, hate ; they are all associated with the body. For along with these psychical con- ditions the body is also somewhat affected. A proof 14 of this is the fact that sometimes when great and palpable misfortunes have befallen a man, he is not at all excited or moved to fear ; on the other hand, one is sometimes aroused by slight and insignificant mishaps, and then the body swells in rage and is in the same condition as when a man is stirred in anger. But this statement receives still more support from the fact that when nothing has happened which could awaken fear, men exhibit those emotions which characterize a man in fright. And if this is true, it is evident that the 15

the body, although it is not itself corporeal. It is that which gives to a particular body its individuality and meaning, and it consists of the following elements : power of nutrition, self -movement, sensation, memory, emotion, imagination, and reason. Amongst these functions of the soul, reason is peculiar to man, although reason in its passive form is based on sensible experience and is conjoined with the life of the body. There is, however, a further form of reason, which Aristotle characterizes as active reason (vovs ttoitjtlkos), whose existence is entirely separable from the body, and is immortal {De an. 403a 23). This form of reason is concerned with intuition or immediately apprehended truth, while the passive reason is occupied with mediated truth. There seems, however, to be no place for the former in Aristotle's definition of the soul cited above. Cf. Introduction, On the Active and Passive Reason.

8 aristotle's psychology deanima

emotions are ideas which find expression in the body. So that we have, for example, such definitions as the following : " Anger is a kind of movement of such and such a body, or part, or faculty, under this or that stimulus and due to this or that motive." It is for this reason that the study of the soul belongs to the province of the natural philosopher, either the soul in its entirety or such part of it as has to do with the body.

1 6 But the naturalist and the speculative philosopher would frame their definitions severally from different stand- points. For example, in reply to the question " What is anger ? " the speculative philosopher says it is the desire of retaliation or something of that sort, the naturalist says it is the seething of the pericordial blood

403 b or heat ; the one has furnished in his answer the matter,

17 the other the form or reason, of the thing. For the notion is the form of a thing, and it is necessary that this notion be embodied in a particular matter, if it is to exist. For instance, the notion of a house is that of a shelter, to protect us against injury from wind and rain and heat; the natural philosopher, however, will call it stones and bricks and wood, while the other grasps the notion embodied in these things and for which

18 they exist. Which of these, now, is the real physical philosopher % Is it the one who busies himself with the matter, but is ignorant of the notion ? or is it the inquirer who is occupied with the notion alone ? I answer, it is rather the man who combines both of these characters. But what is the genius of each of these two men ? Surely there is nobody who concerns himself merely with the properties of matter that are

bk. i. ch. i. RELATION OF SOUL TO BODY 9

inseparable and merely as inseparable ; but the physical philosopher has to do with all the functions and qualities of body and matter which are of such and such a kind. Such properties as are not subject-matter for the natural philosopher, are dealt with by someone else, in certain instances by a professor of one of the arts, perhaps, as e.g. by a builder or by a physician. But in the case of properties which are inseparable, although they attach to no particular body and may be abstractly regarded, with these the mathematician is concerned ; and in so far as the qualities are regarded as abstract or transcendent entities, the metaphysician is concerned with them. But we must now return to the point from which our discussion digressed. We were saying that the properties of the soul do not exist apart from the physicdjna^ things, in which such qualities

jis_couTage_and fear are expressed, and are not to be regarded as a line or surface.

CHAPTER II.

In our inquiry into the soul it is necessary for us, as we proceed, to raise such questions as demand answers ; we must collect the opinions of those predecessors1 who have had anything to say touching the soul's nature, in order that we may accept their true statements and be

2 on our guard against their errors. The initial step in our inquiry will be to set forth those attributes which are currently supposed to inhere in the soul's nature. Ani- mate nature is thought to be different from the inanimate mainly in two particulars, viz. in movement and sense- perception. And these, I may say, are the two traditional characteristics of the soul which we have received from earlier writers. Some of these writers, indeed, affirm that motion is the first and foremost characteristic of the soul, and in the belief that what, is itself unmoved cannot impart motion to anything else,

3 they suppose that the soul is a moving entity. This 404 « is the reason why Democritus declares the soul to be a

sort of fire or warm element. He asserts that, although

1 Aristotle begins here the first extant history of psychological

opinion.

10

bk. i. ch. ii. HISTORY OF THEORIES 11

atomic structures are infinite in variety, both fire and soul are composed of spherical atoms, similar to the particles, as we call them, seen in the air when sun- beams stream through a doorway, and these atoms, as collective seed-particles, he calls the elements of the universe. Leucippus also holds a similar view. It is the 4 spherical atoms, he says, that constitute the soul, because such forms can most easily penetrate through everything, and, being themselves in motion, can move everything else, the theory of these philosophers being that the soul is the principle which imparts motion to animals. It is 5 for this reason too that they regard respiration as the function that fixes life's limit. They think that the surrounding air presses together and expels the atomic bodies, which, because they are themselves never at rest, impart motion to animals, but that relief comes through respiration, because similar particles thereby enter into the body from without. These latter, by restraining the contracting and condensing element, prevent the spherical atoms which are already in animals from being entirely expelled. So long as they can do this, life continues. The theory which has been handed down from the 6 Pythagoreans appears to have the same import. For some members of this school maintain that the sun-motes in the air are the soul ; others declare that the soul is the principle which sets these in motion. They refer to these particles in their theory, because the particles appear to be in constant motion, even when there is a complete calm. The philosophers who regard the soul as a self-moved principle come to the same conclusion. For they all seem to regard motion as the most char- 7

12 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de anima

acteristic attribute of the soul, and while everything else is moved by the soul, the soul is self-moved. They came to this conclusion because they observed that nothing sets anything else in motion without being itself in 5 motion. In a similar spirit Anaxagoras also declares the soul to be the principle of motion, and this view is held by such others, if there are any, as assert that Eeason sets the All in motion.1

Anaxagoras does not, however, quite agree with Demo-

| critus. For Democritus absolutely identifies soul with

v reason, and considers truth to be that which appears

to the senses. Consequently, Homer is right in singing

of Hector that he lay " thinking awry." 2 Democritus

1 The pre- Aristotelian definitions of the soul here cited are classifiable into three main groups: (1) those that regard the kinetic or motive attributes of the soul as its fundamental characteristic ; (2) those that regard the intellectual and cognitive attributes as fundamental ; (3) those that attempt to combine these two elements of activity and knowledge.

2 No such reference as this is to be found in our present text of Homer, although the term dWocppoveovra occurs in II. xxiii. 698. Cf. also Ar. Metaph. iv. (iii.) 5. 10096 28. The word is here employed in the meaning of ' to think incorrectly,' while cfrpovelv signifies, when con- trasted with aWocppovely, 'to think correctly.' Hector lies senseless from a blow, and as thought, in the psychology of Democritus, origin- ates in sensation, his thinking cannot be true, but is paralyzed or per- verted proportionately to the disturbance in sensation. Error and mental disturbance (&\\o<ppoveiv) are explained by disturbance in the activity of the senses (cf. Siebeck, Geschichte der Psychologies Th. i. Abth. i. p. 129 ; Natorp, Forschungen zur Geschichte des Erkenntniss- problemes im Alterthum, pp. 171 ff.). Democritus makes a distinction, however, between the relative values of rational and perceptual know- ledge, between Xoyos and atadrjins, although both originate in external stimuli. The ultimate, and in this sense the real, nature of things is not discoverable by the senses, but only by rational thought. The true nature of the world consists of atoms and the void, and these are known not to our senses, but to our reasoning mind ; they are vorp-d. The data, however, for these rational truths are to be sought in the deliver- ances of the senses.

bk. i. ch. ii. THEORY OF EMPEDOCLES 13

does not employ reason as a specific faculty for the apprehension of truth, but asserts that soul and reason are identical. Anaxagoras, however, is less clear on 9 this point. For although he says in many passages 404 £ that reason is the cause of the beautiful and the true, in other passages he says that reason is the same as the soul, for it is found in all animals, great and small, high and low. Eeason, however, in the sense of intelli- gence, is not found equally in all animals, nor even in all men.

Such philosophers as fix their attention on move- 10 ment as the main fact in animate creation conceive of the soul as the most mobile principle. On the other hand, such philosophers as emphasize the knowledge and perception of reality, define the soul as the principle of things, some holding there are several such principles, others that this psychical principle is the only one. Empedocles, for instance, regards the soul as com- posed of all the elements, and he asserts that each of these elements is a soul. He says :

" Earth we apprehend by earth, water by water, And air divine by air, destructive fire by fire, And love we know by love, sad hate by hate."

In this way, too, Plato in his Timaetis1 constructs 11 the soul out of the elements; for we know like by like, and things are composed of elemental principles. A similar theory is given in his Discourses on Philosophy,2

1 Timaeus, 30 C, 35 A, 39 E.

2 No such work of Plato is known to us, and the reference is pro- bably to the oral discourses held by Plato in the Academy. Vid. Bernays, Die Dialoge des Aristoteles, p. 170 ; Heitz, Die verlorenen Schriften des Aristoteles, p. 180 ; Zeller, Phil. d. Qriechen, Th. 11. Abth. ii. 3te. Aufl. p. 64, note.

*»*^

14 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de anima

where he defines an animal, regarded absolutely, as a structure derived from the idea of unity and the primary elements length, breadth, and thickness ; other

12 things are similarly fashioned. Again, in a different way, Plato defines reason as unity, and science as two ; for the latter moves towards unity in a single course. He also defines opinion as the number of a plane surface and sense-perception as the number of a solid. Numbers were declared to be the actual forms and first principles of things and to be composed of the elements. But things are discerned partly by reason, partly by science, partly by opinion, and partly by sense-perception.

13 Numbers, however, are the forms of things, Since the soul was regarded by these Platonists as at once the principle of motion and the principle of knowledge, some of them included both these ideas in their definition, and explained the soul as a self-moving number.1 These philosophers differ, however, in regard to the kind and number of their principles. The most far-reaching difference is that between the philosophers who regard the elements as corporeal and those who regard them as incorporeal. There are others who define

405 a the elements as a composite of corporeal and incorporeal.

14 They differ also in regard to the number of the elements, some believing there is one only, and others that there are several, and their definitions of the soul vary with their theories of the elements. Amongst the primal elements they classified, not unreasonably, the principle of inherent

1 Xenocrates of Chalcedon (396-314 B.C.), successor of Speusippus as Scholarch of the Academy. Vid. Ueberweg-Heinze, Grundriss d. Geschichle d. Philosophic, Th. 1. p. 191, Sth ed.

bk. i. ch. ii. THEORY OF DEMOCRITUS 15

movement. And so some philosophers held the soul to be fire ; for fire is the finest and most nearly incorporeal of all the elements, and furthermore, it most readily receives and imparts motion. Democritus has explained 15 in a very neat way the cause of these phenomena. Soul and reason, he says, are identical, and belong to the primary and indivisible bodies, and are, furthermore, the principle of motion by virtue of their particles and atomic forms. Amongst these atomic forms, he regards the spherical as the most easily moved, and says that reason and fire are of this sort. Anaxagoras, on the 16 other hand, appears to say that the soul and reason are different, as we remarked above, and yet he employs them as essentially one, except that he regards reason as more than anything else the initial principle of the world. At any rate he asserts that reason is the only entity which is absolute, unmixed, and pure. But he 17 ascribes both attributes of knowledge and motion to the same principle, affirming that reason sets the universe in motion. Thales also, according to the traditional stories of him, appears to have conceived of the soul as a sort of kinetic principle, if it be true that he said the loadstone 18 has a soul because it moves iron. Diogenes, however, and certain others say that the soul is air, in the belief that it is the finest element and the ultimate principle. It is for this reason, also, that the soul knows and produces motion. On the one hand, it knows by virtue of the fact that it is primary and other things are derivatives from it. On the other hand, it is the principle of motion by virtue of its being the first element. Heraclitus, also, says the soul is the first 19

16 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

principle, since it is fiery vapor from which every- thing else is derived. It is also the most incorporeal of all the elements and is in constant flux. We apprehend that which is moved by what is in motion, and he believed, as did most others, that the real world is in

20 motion. Alcmaeon,1 too, appears to have held views of the soul very similar to these. For he says the soul is immortal because it is like the Immortals, and this property of immortality belongs to it by virtue of its perpetual motion. Now, all divine things are in

405 b perpetual motion, moon, sun, stars, and all the heavens.

21 Certain cruder thinkers, like Hippo, asserted that the soul is water. They appear to have based their belief on the nature of animal seed, which in all cases is moist. Hippo confutes those who say the soul is blood by the argument that the seed is not blood, and seed is the

22 elemental soul. Others, like Critias,2 regard the blood as the soul, on the supposition that the most charac- teristic attribute of the soul is sense-perception, and sense-perception is due to the blood. So all the elements, with the exception of earth, have received a vote. No one has represented earth as the principle of soul, unless it were certain philosophers who regarded the soul as composed of all the elements, or as identical

23 with them all. They all define the soul, one may say, in terms of three things : motion, sensation, and incor-

1 Alcmaeon, physician of Crotona, who is usually classified amongst the Pythagoreans, regarded self-movement as the essential character- istic of the soul. By means of this power of self- movement he appears to have explained the continuity of organic life, in addition to finding in it an argument for immortality. Vid. Siebeck, Oeschichte d. Psychol Th. 1. Abth. i. p. 91.

2 Critias, the leader of the Thirty Tyrants and uncle of Plato.

bk.i. ch.ii. THEORY OF ANAXAGORAS 17

poreality, and each of these is referred back to the ultimate elements. Therefore, with one exception,1 those who define the soul in terms of knowledge, make it an element or a derivative of the elements. For they say that we know like by like, and inasmuch as it is the soul that knows all things, it must consist of all the 24 elements. Those philosophers2 who maintain there is only one cause and one element, regard the soul as a unit, like fire or air. On the other hand, the philo- sophers who maintain that there are several elements, make the soul a plurality. Anaxagoras alone declares that the soul is affected by nothing and has nothing in common with anything else. But, if this is its nature, 25 he did not explain, nor is it evident from his writings, how the soul is to acquire knowledge and virtue. The philosophers who include contraries amongst their first principles 3 regard the soul as composed of contraries. On the other hand, those who include in their principles only particular contraries,4 such as heat and cold or similar opposites, likewise regard the soul as one of these. And so there are some who take into consideration the 26 derivation of the words, certain of them claiming that the soul is heat because the verb ' to live ' is derived from this,5 others claiming the soul is cold, because the name 'soul' is derived from respiration and refrigeration. These, then, are the traditional views of the soul, and these are the grounds on which they have been advanced.

1 Anaxagoras. 2 The Ionian physiologers.

3 The Pythagoreans, who regarded the soul as a harmony of contraries.

4Heraclitus, Empedocles, Hippo, and perhaps the pythagorizing Alcmaeon.

5 I.e. because Ifiv (' to live ') is derived from i;eiv ('to seethe ') or $vxv (' soul ') from xf/v&s (' refrigeration').

B

CHAPTEE III.

We must now proceed at once to the investigation of motion. For the view 1 that the soul is a self-moving 406 a entity, and capable of imparting motion, may not only be a false theory of its essence, but it may even be an impossibility for motion to inhere in it at all. We have already said2 that what imparts motion is not of neces-

2 sity itself in motion. Everything that is moved is moved in one of two ways : it is moved either by some other thing or from a principle within itself. We speak of objects moved by some other thing when they are moved by being within a moving body, e.g. sailors. But sailors are not moved in the same sense as that in which a ship is moved. The one is moved in its own nature ; the others are moved by being within a moving vessel.

3 This is clear when applied to the parts of the body ; walking is a motion that is peculiar to the feet, but it is also a property of man, though it is not a property of sailors at the moment in question. Now,

1 Criticism of the view of Plato. The paraphrast Themistius cites the Laws, Bk. 10, ed. Spengel. p. 26. Vicl. Laws, 896, and Phaedr. 245, 246.

*Phys. Bk. VII. , Ch. iv. and v., 245 6-258 a.

18

BK. I. CH. III.

THE SOUL AND MOTION 19

inasmuch as motion is employed in two senses, let us investigate the soul, and ask whether it is self- moved or only participates in movement. Movements are of four kinds : movement in place, qualitative 4 change, decay, and growth. The soul's movement, then, must be one, or several, or all of these. If it is not moved accidentally, its motion must be a natural attri- bute. If this is true, then space1 must be an attribute, for all of the aforesaid movements are spatial. If, 4he«, the essential nature of the soul is self-movement, its 5 movement will not be accidental, ;as in the case of the movement of a white object or of an object three cubits long. For what moves is body, of which these are only predicates. Space, therefore, does not belong to them. But space is an attribute of the soul, if the soul by its 6 own nature participates in motion. Again, if the soul is moved by virtue of its own nature, it can also be moved by external force. And if it can be moved by external force, it can also be moved by virtue of its own nature. The same conditions hold in regard to rest ; for in the state into which an object is moved by nature, in this

1 The arguments against the Platonic doctrines are, briefly summar- ized, as follows: Motion cannot be the soul's essential nature, (1) because this would require that the soul be spatial ; (2) the soul must be moveable by external force ; (3) it must be held in rest by external force, and these forced states of motion and rest are inconceivable ; (4) the composition of the soul will be determined by the character of its movements ; (5) it will experience the movements which it imparts, and as it effects spatial motion, so it will experience spatial motion, and may consequently enter into the body after having passed from it ; (6) if movement is the displacement of the object in motion and the soul's essential nature in movement, then motion would imply the soul's displacement out of its essential nature. Vid. Wallace's excellent note (Commentary ad loc), parts of which I have used in this con- nection.

20 aristotle's psychology deanima

state it also rests by nature. Likewise when an object is moved by external force into a certain state, it also rests in this state by force. It is not easy to give even a conjectural explanation of the character of forced states of motion and rest in the soul.

7 Again, if the soul's movement be upward, its composi- tion will be fire, and if downwards it will be earth, for these are the movements which are characteristic of these elements. The same reasoning holds good of the inter- mediate elements. Again, since the soul evidently sets the body in motion, it is reasonable that it also experi- ences^ those movements which it imparts. If this is true, it is also true conversely that the motion which the body

406^ experiences is experienced by the soul. Now, the body

8 is moved in space. The soul should therefore change place as the body does, and either the entire soul, or certain of its parts, should change position. If this is possible, then it would also be possible for the soul to enter again into the body after it had once passed out. From this would follow the impossible conclusion that animals once dead can rise again. In regard to move- ment in the sense of accident, the soul could be set in movement by some external body, for an animal

9 might e.g. be pushed by external force. One must not, however, suppose that a thing which in its essential nature is self-moved, is moved by anything else save in an accidental sense ; just as the absolute or final good cannot be the relative or secondary good. If the soul is moved at all, one would say that its

10 motion is caused by the objects of sense more than by anything else. However, if the soul moves itself, it

bk. i. ch. in. THE SOUL AND MOTION 21

must itself experience motion, so that on the supposition that every movement is the displacement of the object in motion, in so far as it is moved, the soul must suffer displacement out of its essential nature, provided its self-motion is not merely accidental. But it is to its essential nature that motion belongs. There are n also some who, like Democritus, and in a spirit similar to that of the comedian Philippus, say that the soul moves the body1 (in which the soul resides), just as it moves itself. For Philippus tells us that Daedalus made his wooden statue of Aphrodite capable of move- ment by pouring quicksilver into it. And Democritus 12 says much the same thing when he tells us that the spherical atoms, which are never at rest, move the whole body by their pull and push. But the question we have to ask is whether these same particles produce rest also. It is difficult or quite impossible to say how they are to do this. In a word, it is not in this way that the soul seems to set the body in motion, but rather by some act of volition or thought.

Similarly the Timaeus 2 explains on natural principles the soul's movement of the body : because it is self- moved, it also moves the body with which it is intimately bound up. The Timaeus regards the soul as 14 composed of the elements, and as divided into parts corresponding to harmonic numbers, in order that it may have an innate perception of harmony and possess in its entirety harmonic movements. Timaeus thus bent the straight line into a circle, which later he divided into two circles joined at two points, and further subdivided

1 I.e. by mechanical action. 2 Timaeus, 34 A, 36 C.

'

/l\#»

22 aristotle's psychology deanima

407 a the original circles into seven others, on the supposition 15 that the heavenly orbits correspond to the movements of the soul. Against this view one may say, in the first place, that it is incorrect to speak of the soul as a magnitude ; by the soul of the universe he evidently means some such thing as what we call reason. At any rate it cannot, of course, be the sensitive or the appetitive

O i6'.boul, for their motion is not circular.1 But reason is^one

j and continuous, as is also the process of thought. Now

I , . _

the process of thought consists of thoughts, and these in their succession form a numerical. unity, though not a unity in the sense of magnitude. Neither is reason, therefore, continuous in this sense, but it is either indivisible or not continuous in the sense of magnitude. For how, indeed, is it to think, if it is magnitude ? Does it think in its entirety or by means of some one of its parts ? If it thinks by means of one of its parts, it must be either as a magnitude or as a point, if 7 one can properly speak of a point being a part. Now, if it be as a point and the points are infinite in number, it is evident that it will never reach a conclusion ; if, on the other hand, it be as a magnitude, it will think the same thing many times or an infinite number of times. But the fact seems to be that ^Jhingjsjjapable of__being thought once forjill. If, however, it is enough that the soul should have contact in any of its parts, why need it

1 The action of sensation and appetite is direct {i.e. they are, as Aris- totle conceives them, directly from or to an object) and after the analogy of a straight line. The action of reason, on the other hand, which interprets things in terms of its own forms and laws, and in thinking ideas returns, in a sense, upon itself, is analogous to circular movement. The analogy is further evidenced by the continuity of its processes. Cf. our expression to ' revolve ' a thing in thought.

bk. i. ch. in. THE SOUL AND MOTION 23

move in a circle or have any magnitude at all ? But if

thought requires contact in a complete circle, what is the

significance of contact in any part ? Again, how is the 18

soul to think the divisible by means of the indivisible,

or that which has no parts by means of that which has

parts ? Eeason, however, must be a circle of this sort.

For thought is the movement of reason just as revolution

is the movement of a circle. If, then, thought is a

revolving movement, reason must be a circle of which

thought is the revolving movement. And, more than 19

this, reason must always think something, if circular

motion is perpetual. Now, this cannot be true, for the

thoughts which issue in conduct have certain limitations

(they are all determined by an end), and speculative

thoughts are determined by logical processes. Every

logical process is either definition or demonstration^

Demonstrations proceed from a premise and have some 20

form of termination in a syllogism or conclusion. And

supposing they do not issue in a conclusion, still they do

not turn back to the premise or starting-point, but

continually take a new middle and extreme term, and so kX<<J<L.cX^t

proceed in a straight line, whereas circular motion turns

back to the starting-point. All definitions, too, are 21

determinate. Further, if rotation completes itself several

times, one will necessarily think the same thought several

times. Again, thought seems more like rest and_

attention than like motion, and the same thing applies to the syllogism. More than this, whatever is difficult or contrary to nature cannot be pleasurable. Now, if motion is not an essential property of the soul, the soul must move 407 b contrary to its nature. And it must be painful for it to 22

24 aristotle's psychology deanima

be united with the body from which it cannot free itself, and such a union is even to be avoided, if it be true that the reason is better off when separated from the body a view commonly held and concurred in by many persons.

23 The cause, also, of the circular movement of the heavens is not clearly known. Circular movement is certainly not due to the essential nature of the soul, which moves in this way only accidentally, nor is it due to the body, for the motion of the latter is due to the soul. On the other hand, this motion is not ascribed to the soul because of its being a better form of motion, and yet it is just for this reason that God must have endowed the soul with circular movement, firstly, because

24 motion is better than rest, and secondly, circular move- ment is better than any other kind. Inasmuch as this inquiry belongs more properly to other branches of knowledge, let us dismiss it for the present. We may, however, note one contradiction found in this and most other theories of the soul. It consists in attaching the soul to the body and placing it therein, without deter- mining why this should be the case, and how the body is

25 related to the soul, although it would seem to be necessary to know this. For it is by virtue of this union that the one acts and the other is acted upon, that the one receives and the other imparts motion correlations which are not found in things with merely accidental

26 associations. These theories simply attempt to explain the nature of the soul, but add no explanation of the body as its receptacle, because they suppose (in the spirit of the Pythagorean myths *) that any soul can clothe

1 More particularly in the myth of transmigration.

bk. i. ch. in. PRE-ARISTOTELIAN THEORIES 25

itself in any body. This cannot be true, for every body appears to have a distinct form and character. __ Their doctrine is very much like saying that the carpenter's1 art clothes itself in flutes, whereas an art employs its own instrument, just as a soul employs its own body.

1 The carpenter's art finds its physical and material expression in a house but not in a flute ; further, it uses not a flute, but an axe, as its tool. A particular house is the expression of a particular art or of particular ideas, just as a particular body is the expression of a definite and individual soul. The soul is the entelechy and formative force of the body, and in it we look for the individuality and significance of the man. It is precisely on the relationship between soul and body that Aristotle lays especial stress in his definition of the former.

CHAPTEE IV.

There is another theory of the soul handed down from our predecessors, which to the minds of many persons is no less convincing than the theories already described. Account has been taken of it even in our popular treatises. This theory regards the soul as a sort of harmony.1 Harmony, say its advocates, is a mixture and combination of opposites. The body, too, is com-

2 posed of opposites. Although it is true that harmony is a sort of relation in mixed parts or a combination of parts, we maintain that it is impossible for the soul to be either of these. Again, although motion is not an attribute of harmony, yet almost all of the philosophers

408 a who hold the theory of harmony, I may say, ascribe motion to the soul. Another objection is that it is more fitting to apply the term harmony to conditions of health or to bodily qualities in general than to the

3 soul. This becomes most evident when one attempts to describe the effects and functions of the soul in terms

lrnie reference is to the theory discussed in the Phaedo by the guests of Socrates, Simmias and Cebes, pupils of the Pythagorean Philolaus. Vid. Phaedo, 86 A ff.

26

bk.1. OH.iv. THE SOUL A HARMONY 27

of harmony ; for it is difficult to find any correspondence between them. Now, if we have two sorts of harmony in mind when we use this term, viz. harmony in the primary sense, which means such composition of magni- tudes in objects possessing motion and position that they fuse together and admit nothing further that is homogeneous, and in the secondary sense, a ratio in mixed elements, we still object that in neither sense 4 does harmony apply to the soul. The composition of the parts of the body can be readily examined. There are manifold combinations of the parts, which may be effected in many ways. Of what parts, then, is reason a combination and how is the combination effected ? And I raise the same question regarding the sensitive and appetitive soul. It is equally absurd to regard 5 the soul as a ratio of mixture. The mixture of the elements, in the formation of flesh and bone, is not in the same ratio. If all the parts of the body are com- posed of mixed elements, and the ratio of this mixture constitutes harmony and soul, we have the absurd result that we possess many souls distributed through the entire body. One might demand from Empedocles an 6 answer to this question, for he says that every one of these mixed elements is determined by a given ratio.1 Now the problem arises whether the soul is this ratio or is something else begotten in the members. Again, is Love the cause of any chance mixture or only of a mixture in which a fixed ratio is observed ? And is Love this ratio or something transcending the ratio and different from it ? This theory, then, involves such 7

1 Cf. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, p. 227.

28 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de anima

difficulties as the foregoing. If the soul is different from the mixture or combination, why in the world is it that the soul is annihilated at the same moment as the existence of the flesh and the other parts of the living being ? Furthermore, if each part does not have a soul, on the ground that the soul is not the ratio of mixture, what is it that is destroyed when the soul

8 leaves the body ? It is therefore clear from the fore- going that one cannot regard the soul as a harmony or its motion as circular. It is, however, possible for it to be moved accidentally and to move itself, as e.g. that in which it is may be moved, and this in turn may be moved by the soul. But spatial movement is

9 otherwise impossible for the soul. One might with better reason raise objections against the movement of

408 £ the soul, by regarding the following facts. We speak

\ of the soul as feeling pleasure, pain, courage, fear, and

) anger, and as perceiving and thinking. Now all these

processes are apparently movements, and on this ground

10 one might suppose that the soul is moved. This, how- ever, is not necessarily so. For even if the feeling of pleasure or pain and the process of thinking be movements in the highest sense of the term, and each of these be a movement, it is possible that the movement is pro- duced by the soul just as the feeling of anger or fear is effected by a given movement of the heart and

j thinking by a movement either of this or of some other sort. Further, some of these movements are local, others are processes of change, but of what particular sort or how effected must be considered elsewhere. However,

11 to speak of the soul as feeling anger is like speaking

bk. i. ch. iv. THE SOUL AND THE BODY 29

of the soul as weaving, or building a house. It is better not to speak of the soul as feeling pity, or as learning £ « or thinking, but rather of man doing this through the jf09a/ " soul. We must not suppose, however, that this is so 12 because there is movement in the soul, but that move- ment sometimes proceeds to the soul and sometimes from it, as e.g. in sensation movement proceeds from outside objects, in recollection the movement is from the soul to excitations or fixed impressions lingering in the sense- organs. Now, reason appears to be an entity which is

j t /imjplanted^inTne hsoul^and is incapable of being destroy ecL; for if it were perishable it would be destroyed by the 13 decay of old age more than by anything else. As a matter of fact, the case is the same as that of the sense-organs ; for if the old man could have the eye of a young man he would see as well as the latter. Old age, then, does not come because the soul has undergone some change, but the change is in the soul's organ, the body, as is the case in drunkenness and disease. 14

nought and contemplation are, it is true, weakened

VJ3$M"'Nj^hen some (other internal organ) is destroyed, but the Y^^BBQ^Jbe itself is unaffected The processes of discursive thought and the feeling of loye or hate are not affections of the reason,1 but of (that which has reason' in it, in so far as it has it) Therefore, when this organism is destroyed there is no longer either memory or love. For 15 these are not affections of the reason, but of that (union Q^v^w^t^ wLJl, of soul and body Jwrncli has perished. Eeason, on the wUocj- C^ \^ other hand, is something of a divine nature, and is '^w-<*^iT(vt

1 These processes are not affections of the eternal and separable Active Reason, but only of the body in so far as it possesses psychical life.

30 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

unaffected by these changes. From these facts, therefore, it is clear that the soul is not in motion ; but if it is not in motion at all, it is clear that it is not self-moved.

1 6 By far the most unreasonable of the above-mentioned theories is the one which describes the soul as a self- moving number,1 involving, as it does, impossibilities. In the first place, it involves impossibilities regarding its movement and especially regarding the notion of number.

409 a For how are we to conceive of a monad, a thing which is without parts and without differences, as in motion, and by what impulse and in what manner ? If it imparts motion and is moved, it necessarily contains differences.

17 Again, since it is said that a line in motion generates a plane and a point generates a line, then the movements of monads will be lines, for a point is a monad which has position. And the number of the soul is, of course,

18 somewhere, and has position. Again, if from a number one subtracts a number or a unit, the remainder will be a different number. But plants and many animals, when

19 cut in two, live and appear to retain the same specific soul. It would also appear that there is no difference in speaking of monads and of small bodies. For if the atoms of Democritus are regarded as points, and quantity alone remains, there will still be in this quantitative element, as in everything continuous, a moving and a

1 The theory of Xenocrates. This theory is really a theory of harmony. Xenocrates appears to have conceived of the elements of the soul as commingled in such ratio as to produce a harmony (cf. Themistius, ed. Spengel. p. 61). The real nature of this harmony is due to the numerical ratio, and consequently the essential nature of the soul is found in number. This is merely an application of the number theory of the Pythagoreans to the explanation of the soul, to which, however, Xenocrates adds the important notion of self-movement.

bk. i. ch. iv. THE MONADIC THEORY 31

moved factor. And this consequence is due not to any difference inside, but merely to the fact that the elements are quantitative. There must, therefore, be something 20 which sets the monads in motion. But if the soul is the cause of animal movement, it will also be the cause of movement in the number ; the soul is therefore not at once the moving and the moved principle, but the moving principle alone. How then is it possible for the 21 soul to be moved ? There must be some difference between it and other monads. But what difference can there be in monadic points, excepting a difference in 22 position ? Therefore, even if the monads and points in bodies differ from each other, the monads will, neverthe- less, be in the same space as the points. For the monad will occupy the space of a point. Now what is to prevent an infinite number from occupying the same space, if two can occupy the same space ? This supposi- tion, however, is absurd ; for where the space occupied by bodies is indivisible, the bodies themselves are indivisible. 23 But if the points in bodies are the number of the soul, or if the soul is the number generated out of corporeal points, why is it that not all bodies have a soul ? For, presumably, there are points, even an infinite number of points, in all bodies. Again, how is it possible for souls to be separated and disintegrated from bodies,1 if it be true that lines cannot be divided up into points.2

1 Xenocrates and the Platonists in general supported the doctrine of immortality and the separability of the soul from the body. Aristotle here attempts to disprove the number theory of the soul by showing its incompatibility with the tenet of separability, and the consequent incon- sistency of the Xenocratean philosophy with itself.

2 Points are not parts of lines, but only definite positions or boun- daries.

CHAPTEE V.

The peculiar absurdity of the number-theory_consists, as we said above, on the one hand in the fact that those who advance it maintain the same position as the supporters of the theory that the soul is a subtle body ; on the other hand, in their explaining the movement of the body by 409£ means of the soul after the manner of Democritus. For if there is a soul in every body capable of sensation, there must be, on the supposition that the soul is body, necessarily two bodies in the same space. Again, those who maintain the numerical theory1 of the soul become involved in the absurdity either that there are many points in a single point, or that every body has a soul, unless they_make_ a distinction between r^ysi^al_an^l ^ j>jjyJ^ 2 psychical points. The consequence is that the animal is moved by number, in the same way in which we said Democritus explained its motion.2 For what is the difference whether we speak of the movement of small

xBy interpreting the number-theory of Xenocrates as self-moving monads, Aristotle reduces it to similarity with the atomic theory of Democritus, and applies the criticisms of the latter to the former.

2 The animal is moved by psychical monads, just as in the theory of Democritus it is moved by psychical atoms (cf. De an. 4066 20).

32

bk. I. ch. v. THE SOUL AND THE ELEMENTS 33

spherical bodies or of large monads or of monads at all ? For in either case the animal movement must be due to the motion of the monads. The above 3 objections and many similar ones may be raised against the third1 class of philosophers who combine motion and number in their theory. This is not merely an impossible definition of the soul ; it is even an impossible attribute. This becomes evident if one tries to explain in terms of 4 this motion2 the feelings and functions of the soul, such as deductions, sense-perceptions, pleasure and pain, and similar processes. It is not easy, as we said above,3 in terms of such a theory, to form even a conjecture of the nature of these functions. Of the three4 traditional 5 explanations of the soul, there is one which describes the soul as the most mobile element because of its self- movement ; there is another which describes it as the most subtle or incorporeal element. The difficulties and contradictions involved in these two have been pretty fully explained. There remains for us the consideration of the theory of its composition from the elements. The 6 soul is composed of the elements, certain philosophers say, in order that it may perceive and know all reality. But there are many difficulties which make this theory impossible. Its advocates assume that like is known by

1 Xenocrates and the pythagorizing Platonists.

2 In terms of number. ;J De an. 4086 32.

4 The explanations apparently referred to are : (1) that which regards the soul as a self -moving number (Xenocrates) ; (2) that which regards it as composed of the finest and most mobile atoms (Democritus), or of the subtlest substance (Anaxagoras), or perhaps as consisting of Har- mony (Plato) ; (3) that which regards it as composed of the elements. This third class of theories lays chief weight on the soul as an instru- ment of cognition.

C

34 ARISTOTLE 8 PSYCHOLOGY de anima

like, thus making the soul and its object in a sense £#• identical. But the soul knows not merely these elements ; it knows a great number, one would better say an infinite 7 number, of other things, derivatives of the elements. Let it be granted that the soul knows and perceives the elements in every real thing ; by what means is it to know or perceive the concrete object, e.g. what is God, or man, or flesh, or bone, or any other similar composite thing ? For the elements are not combined m any haphazard way to form things, but in a fixed ratio and composition, as Empedocles himself says in regard to bone i1

" Earth, the lovely, in her smelting pots, broad moulded, Obtained from sparkling Nestis 2 two parts of the eight ; Four from Vulcan's fire : so were white bones begotten."

c

There is, therefore, no advantage in having the ele- ments in the soul unless the ratios and combinations are also to be found in it. Each element will know its similar counterpart, but it will not know bone or man unless these also are to be found in it. One need scarcely say that this is impossible. For who could be in doubt whether a stone or man were to be found in the soul ? The same holds true of the good 3 and the not- good, and equally of other instances. Again, inasmuch as the term ' Being ' is employed in several meanings (it

1 Vid. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, p. 227 ; Ritter and Preller, Hist. Philos. Graec, 8th ed., p. 143.

2 Water.

3 To Aristotle the good is not an entity or element, and so is not explicable by the theory of Empedocles. The good is a relation, and consists in being a mean between two extremes, both of which (excess and defect) are evil.

bk. i. ch. v. THE SOUL AND THE ELEMENTS 35

denotes e.g. the individual concrete thing, or quantity, or quality, or some other particular category), the question arises whether the soul is composed of all these cate- gories. It is supposed that there are no elements which are common to all the categories. Is the soul, then, 10 composed only of the elements which fall under the category of substance ? If so, how does it cognize the other elements ? Are we to say that there are elements and specific principles which belong to every category of existence, and that the soul is composed of these ? The soul will then be a quantity, a quality, and a substance. Now, it is impossible to form a substance or anything but a quantity out of elements of quantity. These and similar objections may be urged against the theory that n the soul is composed of all the elements. Again, it is absurd to say that like is unaffected by like, and yet maintain that like perceives like, and that we know like by like. At the same time these writers regard per- ception, as well as thinking and knowing, as a sort of 12 affection and movement. The theory, as Empedocles1

1 Empedocles starts with the psychological principle that like is known by like. Consequently, if objective reality, which consists of the four elements (fire, earth, air, and water,) is to be known, then the knowing soul must be composed of the like elements. Aristotle's objections are as follows : (1) The soul not only knows the elements, but a great many other things, for which the Empedoclean theory that ' like is known by like ' makes no provision. (2) It is of no value that the soul consist of the elements, unless in some way it be made to con- sist of the ratios and combinations of these elements. How, e.j/., can man or stone be known, for no one supposes that either of these is in the soul ? (3) In what category is the soul to be classed ? It cannot be regarded as all of them, for the different categories have no common elements, and if it is referred to one or the other of the ten categories, it will know only the objects that belong to this category, while it will be ignorant of the others. (4) Empedocles is further in the dilemma of

36 aristotle's psychology de anima

states it, that things are severally cognized by means of somatic elements and that like elements are cognized by like, is open to many objections and difficulties, as is proven by what we have just said. For it is plain that such elements in animal bodies as are composed merely of 410 £ gross matter, like bones, sinews, and hair, do not perceive anything, not even objects like themselves. According to

13 the theory, however, they ought to perceive the like. Further, more ignorance than knowledge will attach to every element ; for it will know only one particular thing, while it will be ignorant of much, for its ignorance will extend to everything else. And Empedocles is in the dilemma of making God the most unintelligent of beings ; for he alone is ignorant of one of the elements, viz., Strife, while mortals know them all, because they

14 are formed from them all. There is, further, this general question to be raised : Why is it that all entities do not possess a soul, since everything is either an element or a derivative of one or several or all of the elements, and

15 must, therefore, know one thing or certain things or all things ? One might raise the further query : What is it that unifies these elements into objects ? The elements are like a corporeal substrate, while it is the unifying principle, whatever that may be, that is the main thing. But there can be no superior principle to dominate the soul. This impossibility applies most of all to reason. For reason is, with good cause, called nature's first-born

making God the most ignorant of beings, because one {vid. Ueberweg- Heinze, 8th ed., Th. 1., p. 83) of the elemental cosmical principles * Strife ' is excluded from his nature. (5) Again, why does not every element or combination of elements possess a soul ? (6) The theory of Empedocles provides no unifying principle.

bk. i. ch. v. THE SOUL AND THE ELEMENTS 37

ruler, although these philosophers regard the elements as the primary realities. All the philosophers who maintain 16 the doctrine that the soul is composed of the elements because it knows and perceives realities, and those who describe it as the most mobile entity, fall into the error of not referring to the soul in its entirety. For not every sentient creature is capable of movement.1 Certain animals are observed to be stationary in place. And yet this seems to be the only form of movement that could be meant when one says ' the soul moves the animal.' A similar objection may also be urged against those who 17 describe the soul and the sentient principle as composed of the elements, viz., that plants evidently live without participation in movement or sensation, while many animals are not endowed with thought. But even if one were to make a concession and regard reason as a part of the soul, in a sense similar to that in which the perceptive faculties are parts of the soul, still even then one would not be taking every form of soul into con- sideration, nor the whole of any particular soul. And this is just what happens in the account of the soul given 18 us in the Orphic verses, as we call them.2 For there we are told that the soul enters from the universe into individuals as they breathe, and that it is carried by the air. But this is impossible in the case of plants and alsb in the case of certain animals; because not all of 4" them breathe a fact which the supporters of this view 19

1 This objection appears to apply not to Empedocles, but to Demo- eritus and Xenocrates. Motion cannot belong to the essential nature of soul, for certain sentient creatures are stable and incapable of motion.

2 Aristotle evidently considered the Orphic origin of these early Cosmogonies as a doubtful tradition.

38 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

have overlooked. Even if we admit that the soul must be composed of the elements, it is not necessary that it be composed of all of them ; for either member of two contraries is competent to discern both itself and its

20 opposite. For example, by the concept of the straight we discern both the straight and the crooked ; the rule is the test for both, while the crooked is not a test either of itself or of the straight.

Certain philosophers1 maintain that the soul is diffused throughout the universe, which may account for Thales'2 thinking that all things are full of gods. This view is also

21 attended by certain difficulties. Why is it that the soul which is in the air or in the fire does not generate an animal, while such generation takes place in compound bodies, although they regard that which is contained in the former elements as superior to that which is con- tained in compound bodies. One might also ask the question : Why is it that the soul contained in the air is better and more imperishable than that which is found in the animal body ? There is a two-fold objection to

22 this theory : it involves an inconsistency and a paralogism. To speak of fire or air as animal is paralogistic : while not to call them animal, if they have a soul, is incon- sistent. They appear to think there is soul in these

23 elements on the ground that the whole is homogeneous with its parts. The result is, they must say that the

1 The reference here may be to the theories advanced in the Timaeus (30 B, 34 B; cf. Bartheleniy-St.-Hilaire, Psychol. (V Aristote, p. 155, and Themistius Comment, ad loc), or to the theories of Heraclitus or Empedocles or Diogenes of Apollonia. The theory of panpsychism is best represented by the post-Aristotelian Stoics.

2 Vid. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, p. 42.

bk. i. ch. v. THE SOUL AND ITS PARTS 39

soul is homogeneous with its parts, if it be true that animals become endowed with soul by taking into them- selves something from their environment. If, however, the diffused air is homogeneous, and the soul consists of heterogeneous parts, it is evident that some of its parts and not others will be contained in the air. The 24 consequence is that the soul must either consist of like parts or not be found in every element of the uni- verse.

From the aforesaid it is evident that knowledge does j not belong to the soul in virtue of its composition out of j the elements, neither is it right or true to say that it j is moved. But inasmuch as cognition, sense-perception, 25 and opinion, as well as appetite, volition, and desire in general are functions of the soul, and inasmuch as locomotion in animals is effected by the soul, and it is also by virtue of the soul that animals grow, reach their prime, and decay, the question arises whether each of these functions is to be ascribed to the entire soul. In other $u\b words, is it by means of the entire soul that w^ think, perceive, and are moved, and perforin and undergo every other process, or do we perform each different function by means of a different part ? Again, we may ask whether 26 the principle of life is found in each one of these parts or in several or in all of them. Or is something other than the soul l the cause of life ? It is true that some writers maintain the divisibility of the soul and that one part exercises thought and another part exercises desire.

1 According to Aristotle, life is one of the psychical functions, although the most elementary of all of them, and is a prerequisite to all other forms of psychical activity.

40

ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY

DE ANIMA

&**>"*-

*•»

17^*

yV* \

^*

27j If the soul is really divided in its nature, what is it that

J holds it together? It is certainly n^t_the_body ; for, on

the contrary, one supposes that the soul holds the body

together. At any rate, when the soul departs the body

is dissolved and disintegrated. If, therefore, it is some-

\ thing other than the body that makes the soul an unit

jwihis would assuredly be the soul itself, and we shall

be obliged to inquire again whether that unifying

principle is itself an unit or is composed of several parts.

28 If it is an unit, why should we not say at once that the soul is an unit ? But if it is divisible, reason will again ask what that principle is which holds it together, and so the process will go on ad infinitum. In regard to the parts of the soul, one might inquire concerning the power

29 which each of them has in the body. For if it is the soul as a whole that binds the entire body together, it would be fair to suppose that each part of the soul is the binding principle for some part of the body. This, how- ever, appears to be impossible. It is hard even to fancy what sort of part the reason will bind or in what way.

30 It is observed also that plants and certain insects, when divided, continue to live, because the sections possess souls, which are specifically, although not numerically, the same. Each part retains the power of sensation and locomotion for some time, and there is nothing strange in the fact that it does not continue to live,

31 because it has no organ for the maintenance of its nature. Nevertheless the parts of the soul are all found in every one of these bodily divisions, and they are of like kind with each other and with the entire soul ; of like kind with each other because they are mutually inseparable;

bk. I. ch. v. DIVISIBILITY OF THE SOUL 41

of like kind with the entire soul because it is divided into these as parts. Again, the fundamental principleof life in plants appears to be a kind of soul, and this is the only principle which animals and plants have in common. The principle of life can exist apart from sensation, but no sentient tiling can exist without life.

BOOK THE SECOND.

CHAPTEE I.

412 tf Let the foregoing suffice as a discussion of the traditional theories of the soul ; and now let us resume our subject from the start, and attempt to determine the nature of 2 the soul and its most general definition. One class of realities we call 'substance.' This 'substance' may be re- garded on the one hand as matter, which in itself is_no definite thing : on the other hand, as form and idea, in terms of which definite individuality is ascribed to a thing. A third meaning of substance is the composite of matter and form. Matter is potentiality ; form is actuality or realization.1 The latter may be looked at

1 The notions here under discussion belong to the most fundamental with which the philosophy of Aristotle operates. The soul is character- ized by several terms, chief of which are form and entelechy. Every individual or ' substantial ' thing is a composite of form and matter. Form is that which gives a thing its character or significance. It is form, therefore, that is the object of knowledge. Becoming consists in the process of matter assuming a definite form. Matter, consequently, represents the potentiality of a thing, and form its actuality. Viewed from the standpoint of causation or process, these two notions constitute the material and formal causes ; in other words, matter is the condition sine qua non, while the form is conceptual, efficient, and final cause.

42

bk. ii. ch. i. THE NOTION OF ' SUBSTANCE ' 43

in two ways, either as complete realization, comparable with perfected knowledge, or as realization in process, comparable with the activity of contemplation. The 3 notion of substance appears to be most generally employed in the sense of body, and particularly of physical body ; for this is the source of all other bodies. Some physical bodies have, and others have not, life. By life we under- stand an inherent principle of nutrition, growth, and decay. So that every natural body endowed with life would be substance, and substance in this composite sense. 4 The body, therefore, would not be soul, since body is of

These fundamental terms in Aristotle's metaphysics are applied by him to the explanation of the soul. Man is first of all an organic whole, the living force in which is the soul, while the body is the soul's organ. Soul is that which differentiates a living from an inanimate thing, (De an. 413a 33), and life signifies a process or a form of motion. Life implies, further, an active and a passive element; in other words, a moving principle and a thing moved, which in Aristotle's terminology are form and matter. Form here is equivalent to the moving or efficient cause. It is the energy or life that determines the growth of a particular body, or its transition, in Aristotelian language, from potentiality to actuality. Every living thing, then, is a composite of form and matter, or soul and body. In so far as the form is the perfected end or final cause, in so far Aristotle describes the soul as the entelechy of a natural organic body. In so far as it is an efficient power or moving cause, he describes the soul as the actuality or actualization (an inadequate translation of evepyeta). It is only in the "soul that body attains its true reality " (Wallace, Introd. p. xxxix.). Soul is the realization of the body, apart from which the body is only formless, undeveloped, potential matter. Entelechy (evreXex^ca) means the finished state of a thing (Phys. 202a 24) or a state in which a thing's potentiality finds its complete development. Actualization (evepyeia), on the other hand, means the active process by which the potential thing passes over into the completed state or it is the completed state in process. Entelechy is, therefore, more ultimate than actualization (hepyeia), although Aristotle frequently uses the terms synonymously. On the term evepyeia, vid. Grant's Aristotle's Ethics, Vol. I., pp. 231 ff. 4th ed., and Trendelenburg's Aristotle's De anima, 2nd ed., pp. 242 ff.

44 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de anima

such nature that life is au attribute of it. For body is not predicated of something else, but is rather itself sub- strate and matter. The soul must, then, be substance1 in this sense : it is the form of a natural body endowed with the capacity~bT life. In this meaning

5 substance is the completed realization. Soul, therefore, will be the completed realization of a body such as described. Complete realizatio^ is employed in two senses.2 In the one sense it is comparable with per- fected knowledge ; in another, it is comparable with the active process of contemplation. It is evident that we mean by it here that realization which corresponds to perfected knowledge. Now, both waking and sleeping- are included in the soul's existence : waking corresponds to active contemplation ; sleep to attained and inactive knowledge. In a given case science is earlier in origin3

6 than observation. Soul, then, is the jirst4 entelechy _

1 Substance is employed by Aristotle in three senses : (1) matter ; (2) form ; (3) the composite of matter and form or an individual thing. Cf. Zeller's Aristotle, Engl. tr. Vol. I. pp. 374 ff. ; Grote's Aristotle, p. 454.

2 These two senses are described by Aristotle in the terms entelechy and actualization (evepyeia), the former of which corresponds to ' per- fected knowledge ' and the latter to the process or activity of ' contem- plation. '

'■'' In the sense of being a dormant possession, or a potentiality which subsequent activity presupposes.

4 The ' first ' entelechy is variously explained by the different com. mentators from Simplicius down. The notion of ' first ' appears to refer to the distinction made in the previous Note. There is a primary and secondary substance {ovaia), the former of which refers to the individual, and the latter to the genera ; there is a primary matter (Trpdorr} v\rj, Metaph. 1049a 25), which signifies matter absolutely formless; there is, further, a primary soul (wpuTr) ■J/vxVi De an. 4166 22), which is the most fundamental or primary form of soul, viz., the nutritive function ; and similarly there is a first entelechy {irpwry) evreXexeia), which is the primary or most fundamental form of psychical life. It is primary or

bk. ii. ch. t. DEFINITION OF THE SOUL 4~>

of a natural body endowed with the capacity of life. I Such a~~5o3y one would describe as^organic. The parts of plants are also organs, although quite simple in char- 412 1> acter, cjj. the leaf is the covering of the pericarp, and the pericarp is covering of the fruit ; the roots are analogous to mouths, both being channels of nutrition. 7 If then we were obliged to give a general description applicable to all soul_or life, we should say that it is the first entelechy of a natural organic body. It is therefore unnecessary to ask whether body and soul are one, as one should not ask whether the wax and the figure are one, or, in general, whether the matter of a particular thing and the thing composed of it are one. For although unity and being are predicated in several senses, their proper sense is that of perfect realization.

We have now given a general definition of the souli g We have defined it as an entity which realizes an idea.l It is the essential notion which we ascribe to a body ' JrLo$ d mo* ^ of a given kind. As an illustration, suppose that an <vVcJm=b instrument, e.g. an axe, were a natural body. Here the notion of axe constitutes its essential nature or reality, and this would be its soul. Were this taken away it would no longer be an axe, except in the sense of a homonym. It is in reality, however, merely an axe, 9 and of a body of this sort soul is not the notional

first in the sense of being nearest to mere potentiality, and in the order of development stands next above body. It is also first in being a pre- requisite to all further development. The 'first entelechy of a body' is, consequently, the first manifestation of life which an organism displays. It corresponds to dormant knowledge or merely possessed science, which is potentiality (86i>a/us, e£ts) compared with the active employ- ment of science {ev^pyeta), and as potentiality, it is prior to the latter. (Cf. Zeller's Aristotle, Engl. tr. Vol. II. p. 3, note 1.)

/K^

46 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

essence and the idea, but soul applies only to a natural body of a given kind, viz. a body whose principle of (movement and rest is in itself.1 The principle expressed here should be observed in its application to par- ticular parts of the body. For if the eye were an

IO animal, vision would be its soul, i.e. vision is the notional essence of the eye. The eye, however, is the matter of vision, and if the vision be wanting the eye is no longer an eye, save in the meaning of a homonym, as a stone eye or a painted eye. What applies here to a particular member, must also apply to the entire living body ; for as the particular sensation is related to the particular organ of sense, so is the whole of sensation related to the entire sensitive organism, in so far as it has sensa-

ii tion. 'Potentiality of life' does not refer to a thing which has become dispossessed of soul, but to that which possesses it. Seed and fruit are potentially living bodies. As cutting is the realization of the axe, and vision is the realization of the eye, so is the waking state the : realization of the living body; and as vision and capacity 413 a are related to the organ, so is the soul related to the body. Body is the potential substrate. But as vision and pupil on the one hand constitute the eye, so soul and body in the other case constitute the living animal.

12 It is, therefore, clear that the soul is not separable from the body; and the same holds good of particular parts of the soul, if its nature admits of division, for in some cases the soul is the realization of these very parts ;

1 The meaning is that if an axe were a body with an inherent principle of movement, or in other words an animate body, then the notion of axe or axehood would constitute its soul. The soul, then, is the ' notional essence,' to use an Aristotelian phrase, of a living body.

bk. ii. ch. i. DEFINITION OF THE SOUL 47

not but that there are certain other parts where nothing forbids their possible separation, because they are not realizations of any bodily nature.1 And yet it is un- certain whether the soul as realization of the body is "~ separable from it in a sense analogous to the separability of sailor 2 and boat. Let this suffice as a definition and outline sketch of the soul.

1 The reference is to the Active Reason.

2 As the sailor is the directing and animating principle, as it were, of a boat and is able to leave it at will.

CHAPTER II.

Inasmuch as the certain and the conceptually more knowable is derived from what is uncertain,1 but sensibly more apparent, we must resume the investigation of the soul from this standpoint. For it is necessary that the definition show not merely what a thing is, as most definitions do, but it must also contain and exhibit the

2 cause of its being what it is. In reality, the terms of definitions are ordinarily stated in the form of con- clusions. What, e.g. is the definition of squaring ? The reply is that squaring is the conversion of a figure of unequal sides into a right-angled equilateral figure equal to the former. Such a definition is the expression of a conclusion. But to define squaring as the discovery

3 of a mean proportional line is to define the thing in

lrThe only certain and scientific knowledge to Aristotle is that of concepts or universals, although this is in a way derived from sensible data. Aristotle is not, however, a pure Empiricist. Sense-per- ception itself is not a passive reception of external impressions ; these furnish rather only the occasion of a given psychical activity, and rational thought is in still higher degree a matter of subjective initiation. He rejects, however, the Platonic theory of reminiscence ' and all other theories which assume the possession of a body of innate

truths.

48

ek. ii. ch. ii. ANIMATE AND INANIMATE 49

terms of its cause.1 Eesuming our inquiry, we say, therefore, that the animate is distinguished from the inanimate by the principle of life. But inasmuch as life is predicated in several senses, e.g. in the sense of reason, sensation, local movement and rest, and furthermore movement in the sense of nutrition, decay, and growth ;2 4

1The one definition describes the result accomplished, and the other the means and method of its accomplishment. Although Aristotle has great veneration for facts, to a degree remarkable in Greek philosophy, he constantly lays emphasis on the superior significance of relations and causes.

2 Aristotle's view of soul or the 'vital principle' (neither translation gives quite an adequate idea of the meaning of faxv, cf. Introduction, Chap. i. ) is different from that of Stahl and the Montpellier School of Animists. The latter regard the mind as the source of all vital phe- nomena, whereas Aristotle regards life as the source of mind, or rather, mind as only one of several forms of life. The distinction between the two views is made greater by Lewes (Aristotle, p. 223) than the facts justify, he having, as he supposes, made the discovery of this distinction. In reality Aristotle characterizes life as a psychical activity, though not necessarily intelligent. The organic activity in plants is psychical, although they have no sensation. Aristotle used life in a wider meaning than we do ; with him it included reason and sensation, as amongst the vital activities of organized beings. These combined activities constituted ' soul ' in distinction from the material substrate or body, in which they are manifested. Stahl (1660-1734), whose theory of the soul grew out of his physiological studies and was a reaction against mechanical and chemical theories, rejects the Aristotelian distinction of a vegetative and nutritive soul, and refers all these functions to rational thought. The three forms of vital movement for Stahl are the circulation of the blood, secretion, and excretion, all of which Aristotle includes amongst the activities of nutrition, save that the circulation of the blood takes the form of movement from the heart to the extremities and back again. Stahl says the cause of this is the mind ; Aristotle says it is the nutritive soul or the lowest form of vital activity. Both are vitalists in the repudiation of a mechanical explanation of life ; both are animists in referring the phenomena of life to the soul. They differ in that Stahl makes all these activities rational, while Aristotle regards as rational only specific activities in higher animal life. Cf. Lemoine, Le vitalisme et Vanimisme de Stahl, pp. 33 ff.

D

50 aristotle's psychology deanima

if any one of these is discerned in a thing we say that it has life. All plants, therefore, are supposed to have life ; for evidently they have within them a potency and principle whereby they experience growth and decay in opposite processes. For their growth is not merely upwards or downwards, but in both these directions alike and in every point where nutrition takes place, and they continue to live as long as they are capable of

5 nutrition. Now this faculty of nutrition is separable from the other forms of life, but the other forms cannot exist in perishable creatures apart from this principle of nutrition. This is made clear in the instance of plants ; for they have no other capacity of soul (or life)

413 £ than this nutritive one. Owing to this fundamental

6 principle of nourishment, therefore, life is found in all animated living things, but the primary mark which distinguishes an animal from other forms of life is the

fcjj^ possession of sensation. For even those creatures which

[yph^ are incapable of locomotion or change of place, but

which possess sensation, are called animals and are

not merely said to live. Touch is the primary form

7 of sensation and is found in all animals. But as the nutritive faculty is separable from touch and sensation in general, so touch can exist apart from the other forms of sensation. By the nutritive power we understand that part of the soul in which plants share ; and by the sensation of touch we mean that capacity which all animals possess. We shall later on give the ex- planation of these phenomena.

8 For the present let it suffice that the soul is the causal principle of the aforesaid phenomena, and is

bk. ii. oh. ii. THE PRINCIPLE OF LIFE 51

defined in terms of them, I mean, in terms of nutrition^

sensation, reason, motion. To the question whether each

of these forms of life is a soul or a part of the soul ;

and, if a part, whether in the sense that the part is

only notionally separable or really separable in space,

the reply is in some respects easy and in others

difficult. For in the case of plants, some of them appear 9

to live when they are divided up and the parts are

separated from each other, indicating that there is in

each of these plants in_actuality an unitary soul, but in ~\ ^^JU-^oJs,

potentiality several souls. And we observe the same

thing taking place in different varieties of soul, as e.g. in

the case of insects which have been dismembered. Here

each part is capable of sensation and locomotion, but if it

is capable of sensation it is also capable of imagination

and impulse. For where there is sensation, there is also

pleasure and pain, and where there is pleasure and pain ,^_ ,

there is necessarily also desire. Now in regard to reason_io ^^^^-cj^

and the speculative faculty, we have as yet no certain

evidence, but it seems to be a generically distinct type of 1

soul and it alone is capable of existing in a state of \

separation from the body, as the eternal is separable from (

the mortal.1 The remaining parts of the soul, however, n

are from the foregoing considerations evidently not

separable, as some assert.2 But that they are notionally

1 Amongst the uncertain and wavering statements of Aristotle regarding the separability of the rational soul and its immortality, this is one of the most explicit passages.

2 The reference appears to be to Plato who regarded the soul as con- sisting of three distinct faculties, the rational, spirited, and appetitive (Repub. 440 a, b, Timaeus, 69, 70), which were situated in different parts of the body, reason in the head, the spirited element in the thorax, and the concupiscent faculties in the lower body.

52 akistotle's psychology deanima

separable, is clear; for if perceiving is distinct from opining, the faculty of sensation or perception is dis- tinct from that whereby we opine, and each of these is in turn distinct from the faculties above mentioned.

12 Furthermore, all of these are found in some animals, while only certain of them are found in others, and in still others only a single one (and this is the cause of dis-

414 a tinctions amongst animals). The reason for this must be investigated hereafter. A parallel instance is found in regard to sensation ; some animals possess all the faculties of sense, others only certain of them, and still others only the single most fundamental one, viz. touch.

13 The principle by which we live and have sensation, then, is employed in a twofold sense. Similarly, we employ the principle by which we know in a twofold sense, viz. science and the knowing mind (for we say we know by means of each of these), and in a like manner the principle by virtue of which we are healthy is in one

14 sense health itself, and in another sense a part of the body or the whole of it. In these cases knowledge and health constitute the form, notion, idea, and, as it were, the realization of a potential subject, the one of a knowing subject and the other of a healthy one, (realization is supposed to attach to that which has power to effect changes and is found in a passive and recipient subject). The soul js that principle by whichL' iri_j^_ultimate sense we live and* feeland Ibnmk : so that f v. iTr it is a sort of idea and form, not matter and substrate.

15 Now, substance is employed, as we have said, in a three- fold meaning, viz. as form, as matter, and as a composite of these two. Amongst these meanings of substance

BK. II. CH. II.

THE SOUL AND BODY

53

matter signifies potentiality ; form signifies actuality or complete realization. Inasmuch as it is the composite which is the animate creature, body cannot be regarded as the complete realization of the soul, but the soul is the

v >fc (realizatiqi) of a given body. The conjecture, therefore

appears well founded that the soul does not exist apart

from a body nor is it a particular body. The soul is not

sV itself body, but it is a certain aspect of body, and is

m consequently found in a body, and furthermore in a body

jfcjcof such and such a kind. It is not to be regarded as it

^ was amongst our predecessors who thought that it is

introduced into body without prior determination of the

particular sort of body, although no casual subject

appears capable of undergoing any casual or haphazard

effect.1 This same result is also reached by an analysis

of the notion itself; for complete realization in every

instance is naturally found in a definite potentiality and in

From this it is evident that the

«Vc_

fc«oj

s

an appropriate matter. ♦a^souI is a kind of realization and expressed idea of a a' determinate potentiality.

1 Trendelenburg thinks the Pythagoreans^-are meant here, owing to their doctrine of transmigration of souls. The doctrine that one soul can clothe itself in different sorts of bodies is as impossible as that one craft can use the tools of other crafts indifferently. Cf. De an. 407& 22; vid. also note, p. 25.

52

ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY

DE ANIMA

« :

separable, is clear; for if perceiving is distinct from opining, the faculty of sensation or perception is dis- tinct from that whereby we opine, and each of these is in turn distinct from the faculties above mentioned.

12 Furthermore, all of these are found in some animals, while only certain of them are found in others, and in still others only a single one (and this is the cause of dis-

414 a tinctions amongst animals). The reason for this must be investigated hereafter. A parallel instance is found in regard to sensation ; some animals possess all the faculties of sense, others only certain of them, and still others only the single most fundamental one, viz. touch.

13 The principle by which we live and have sensation, then, is employed in a twofold sense. Similarly, we employ the principle by which we know in a twofold sense, viz. science and the knowing mind (for we say we know by means of each of these), and in a like manner the principle by virtue of which we are healthy is in one

14 sense health itself, and in another sense a part of the body or the whole of it. In these cases knowledge and health constitute the form, notion, idea, and, as it were, the realization of a potential subject, the one of a knowing subject and the other of a healthy one, (realization is supposed to attach to that which has power to effect changes and is found in a passive and recipient subject). The soul jts that principle by whi , in an ultimate sense we live and* feel and tnmk; so that/\y z\ it is a sort of idea and form, not matter and substrate.

15 Now, substance is employed, as we have said, in a three- fold meaning, viz. as form, as matter, and as a composite of these two. Amongst these meanings of substance

bk. ii. ch. ii. THE SOUL AND BODY 53

matter signifies potentiality; form signifies actuality or complete realization. Inasmuch as it is the composite which is the animate creature, body cannot be regarded as the complete realization of the soul, but the soul is the S~^w*J§^_ \J^ $£j (realization of a^ given body. The conjecture, therefore, |i6 ?*V~^'yy*^ appears well founded that the soul does not exist apart v^ * ^ ;

from a body nor is it a particular body. The soul is not £'^ w^^ ( y^yV itself body, but it is a certain aspect of body, and is ?-£~rt^— sLU^ consequently found in a body, and furthermore in a body ^JLJr^f sucn and such a kind. It is not to be regarded as it %j^~> was amongst our predecessors who thought that it is **• * introduced into body without prior determination of the particular sort of body, although no casual subject appears capable of undergoing any casual or haphazard 17 effect.1 This same result is also reached by an analysis of the notion itself; for complete realization in every ^ctol.'t v instance is naturally found in a definite potentiality and in an appropriate matter. From this it is evident that the ^9"* soul is a kind of realization and expressed idea of a '*j&°- determinate potentiality.

1 Trendelenburg thinks the Pythagoreans^are meant here, owing to their doctrine of transmigration of souls. The doctrine that one soul can clothe itself in different sorts of bodies is as impossible as that one craft can use the tools of other crafts indifferently. Cf . De an. 4076 22 ; vid. also note, p. 25.

CHAPTEE III.

In some creatures, as we have said, all of the above

mentioned psychic powers are found, in others certain of

them, and in still others only one. By powers we mean

. __v . here the power of * nutrition, of appetite, of "sensation,

. of v movement in space, and of rational thought. In

plants, only the nutritive power is found ; in other

414 £ creatures the power of sensation is added. If sensation

2 is added, impulse or appetite is also implied. For appetite includes desire and impulse and wish. All animals have at least one sense touch ; and to whatever creature sensation is given, to it are also given pleasure and pain, and objects appear to be pleasant or painful. Creatures which distinguish these, possess also desire ; for desire is an impulse towards what is pleasant. Further,

3 animals possess a sense for food, and this is the sense of touch ; for all animals are nourished by means of the dry and moist, the warm and cold, and it is touch which apprehends these. It is only incidentally that animals discern food through other sensible qualities ; neither sound nor colour nor smell con- tributes at all to food. Flavour, however, is one of the

54

bk. ii. ch. in. VARIOUS MEANINGS OF SOUL 55

haptic qualities.1 Hunger and thirst are desires ; hunger 4 is a desire of the dry and warm ; thirst a desire of the cool and moist, and flavour is a sort of seasoning in these objects. We must explain these subjects minutely hereafter ; for the present let the statement suffice, that amongst animals where we find touch we find appetite also. The subject of imagination in animals is uncertain and must be investigated later. In addition to these attributes we find amongst some 5 animals the power of local movement and in others we find the power of understanding and reason, as in man and in other creatures that are, if there be such, similar or superior to man. It is evident that a single definition can be applied to soul in the same way as a single definition can be applied to figure. As in the latter case, there is no figure beyond that of the triangle and its derivations, so in the former case there is no soul beyond those enumerated. A common definition might also be 6 applied to figures which would fit them all and be peculiar to no particular figure. The same holds good in the case of the above mentioned types of soul. It is, therefore, absurd,2 both in these instances and in others, to search for a common definition which shall not apply to any individual real thing nor to any peculiar and irre- 7

1 Touch is the most fundamental of all the senses, and taste is depen- dent upon it. These two are essential to the preservation of animal life. No animal can be without touch and nothing that is without it can be an animal. As the primary form of sensation, it is the lowest differential mark of animal life, distinguishing the animal from the vegetable.

2 Aristotle is referring to an absurdity not fully expressed here. The meaning appears to be that, although such a general definition might be framed, it would be void of any helpful content or significance, not being applicable to any particular form of reality.

•3*\

56 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY db anima

ducible species, thereby neglecting the particular meaning in the general. The facts touching the soul are parallel to this case of figure ; for both in figures and in animate creatures, the prior1 always exists potentially in the later, e.g. the triangle is contained potentially in the square and the nutritive power in that of sensation. We must, there- fore, investigate the nature of the soul in particular things,

8 e.g. in a plant, a man, or a lower animal. And we must 415 a consider the cause of their order of succession. The

sensitive soul, for example, presupposes the nutritive, but in the case of plants the nutritive exists apart from the sensitive. Again, the sense of touch is presupposed by all the other senses, but touch exists apart from them and does not presuppose them. Many animals have no

9 sense of sight, hearing, or smell. Some that are capable of sensation have also power of local movement, others have not; finally the smallest number possess the power of reason and understanding. Mortal creatures who possess the power of reason, possess all the other psychic faculties, but those which have each of these others do not all have the power of reason, and certain of them do not even possess imagination,2 while still others live by this alone. At another time we shall give an account of the speculative reason. It is evident, however, that this account touching each particular form of soul is also the most fitting description of the soul in general.

1 The logically prior is meant.

2 Imagination is of two sorts ((pavraaia aiadrjTiKri and (pavracria /3oi/\eiTi/oj 7} \oyi<rTiKr)), the one of which is the power of reproducing images of sense or of reviving spent sensations ; the other is the power of constructing the images that accompany thought, always, however, out of elements ultimately drawn from sensation. Cf. Introduction, On Imagination.

CHAPTER IV.

If one intends to make an investigation of the faculties of the soul, it is necessary first to inquire into their several natures, and then by the same method to inquire further into other related problems. If, then, one is obliged to describe the nature of each several faculty, e.g. the nature of the faculty of reason, of sense-perception, or of nutrition, one must first be able to say what thinking and sense-perception mean. For the activities and pro- cesses are notionally prior to the faculties to which they belong. If this is true, we must further observe the 2 objects of the activities before the activities themselves, and we should for the same reason first determine our position regarding these objects, e.g. regarding food, the sensible, and the intelligible. First, then, we must speak of food and generation. For the nutritive power is found in all living things, and is the primary and most uni- versal faculty of soul, by virtue of which all creatures 3 possess life. Its functions are to procreate, and to assimi- late food. In all animals that are perfect and not abnormal, or that are not spontaneously generated, it is the most natural function to beget another being similar to

57

58

ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY

DE ANIMA

itself, an animal to beget another animal, a plant another plant, in order that they attain, as far as possible, the 4*5^ immortal and divine1; for this is what every creature 4 aims at, and this is the final cause of every creature's natural life. We understand by final cause two things : the purpose aimed at, and the person who is served by the purpose.2 Since it is impossible for an individual to partake of the immortal and divine in its own continuous life, because no perishable creature continues self-identical and numerically one, it partakes therefore of the immortal in that way in which it is able to share it, one thing in a higher degree and another in a lower ; it does not itself abide, but only a similar self abides ; in its continuity it is not numerically, but only specifically, one. r^ The soul is the cause and principle of a living body. These terms are used in several senses. Corresponding to these differences, the soul is referred to as cause in three distinct meanings ; for it is cause in the sense of the source of movement, of final cause, and as the real 6 substance of animate bodies.3 That it is a cause in the sense of real substance is evident, for real substance is in every case the cause of being, and the being of animals is their life, and soul is the cause and principle of life. Furthermore, it_is the complete realization that gives us the real significance of a potential being. Soul is also

1 The only immortality possible for animals unendowed with Active Reason is that of the perpetuation of their species through propaga- tion.

2 For example, the end or purpose of a lamp may be said to be either (a) to give light, or (6) to serve the wants of the person who employs the light.

3 In other words, soul is used in the meanings of efficient, final, and formal cause.

bk. ii. ch. iv. SOUL AND FINAL CAUSE 59

evidently cause in the sense of final cause. For nature, like reason, acts with purpose, and this purpose is its end. In animals the soul is, by virtue of its nature, a principle 7 similar to this. For the soul uses all natural bodies as its instruments, the bodies of animals and the bodies of plants alike, which exist for the soul as their end. End is used in two senses : the purpose, and the person or thing which the purpose serves. Soul also means the 8 primary source of local movement. This power of local movement is not possessed by all living creatures. Trans- formation and growth are also due to the soul. For sense-perception is supposed to be a kind of trans- formation, and nothing is capable of sense-perception 9 unless it has a soul. The case is similar with growth and decay. For nothing grows or decays by natural processes unless it admit of nutrition, and nothing is capable of nutrition unless it has a soul. Empedocles ascribes downward growth to plants where they are rooted, because the earth naturally tends downward, and upward 416 a growth, because fire tends in that direction, and in these respects is not right. For Empedocles does not employ the terms up ' and ' down ' correctly. ' Up ' and ' down ' 10 are not the same for all things nor in all parts of the universe, for roots are to plants what the head is to animals, if one is to describe organs as identical or different in terms of their functions. In addition, what principle is it that n holds together these two elements of fire and earth, tending, as they do, in opposite directions ? For they will scatter asunder, if there be no hindering principle. And if there is such a principle, it is the soul and the cause of growth and nourishment. Some regard fire as 12

60 aristotle's psychology deanima

the real cause of nutrition and growth. For this seems to be the only body or element that feeds and increases itself. One might, therefore, conjecture that this is the element that causes growth and nutrition in animals and

13 plants. In a certain sense, it is true, fire is a co-ordinate cause, but not the absolute cause, of growth ; this is rather the soul. For the growth of fire is indeterminate so long as there is material to burn ; on the other hand, in all bodies developed in nature there is a limit and signifi- cance to size and growth. These attributes ([of limit and significance]) belong to soul, not to fire, to reason rather than to matter.

14 Since the same power of the soul is both nutritive and generative, we must first investigate nutrition ; for it is by this function of nutrition that the faculty in question is distinguished from other faculties. Nutrition is sup-

15 posed to take place by the law of opposites, although not every opposite is nourished by every other, but such opposites only as derive both their origin and their growth from each other.1 Many things are derived from one another, but they are not all quantitative

16 changes, as e.g. healthy from sickly. Nutrition is not

1 The body is composed of all four elements and its nourishment must include all of them. The animal waste is supplied out of these several elements, which are themselves characterized by opposite qualities, by means of the action of heat and cold. Blood is the final form into which vital heat cooks the raw food. Aristotle makes really little use of the physical explanations of the Pre-Socratics, who were satisfied to explain all cosmical phenomena by such opposing forces in nature as heat and cold, the moist and dry, the heavy and light, etc. Although Aristotle still makes use of these ideas, in his dynamical theory he sees the world full of final causes, while the purely physical forces of the Pre-Socratics are merely the instruments employed by soul or life.

bk.ii. ch.iv. THE SOUL AND NUTRITION 61

applied to these cases in the same sense, for while water is nutriment for fire, fire does not nourish water. The opposites of food and nourishment appear to apply par- ticularly to simple bodies. There is, however, a difficulty 17 here. For there are some who maintain that like is nourished by like, as like is also increased by like, while others, as we said, affirm the converse of this, viz., that opposites are nourished by opposites, on the ground that like is incapable of being affected by like. Food, however, undergoes transformation and is digested, and transformation is in every case toward the opposite or 18 the intermediate. Further, food is affected by the body which assimilates it ; the latter, however, is not affected by the food, just as the builder is not affected by his 416 b material, although the material undergoes change through him. The builder merely passes from a state of in- activity into one of activity. The question whether nourishment is to be understood to apply to the final 19 condition in which it is taken up by the body, or to its original condition, creates a difficulty. If both are meant, only in the one case the food is indigested and in the other digested, it would be possible to speak of nourishment conformably to both of the above theories ; for in so far as it is indigested, we should have opposite nourished by opposite ; in so far as it is digested, we should have like nourished by like ; so that in a certain 20 sense, it is evident they are both right and both wrong. Since nothing is nourished which does not share life, the object of nutrition would be an animate body as animate; so that food is determined by its relation to an animate object and is not accidental. There is a

62 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de anima

21 difference between the nourishment and the principle of growth ; in so far as the animate thing is quantitative, the notion of growth applies ; in so far as it is a particular substance, the notion of nourishment. For food pre- serves a being as a substantial thing, and it continues to exist so long as it is nourished. Nourishment is pro- ductive of generation, not the generation of the nourished thing, but of a being similar to it. For the former

22 exists already as a reality, and nothing generates, but merely preserves, itself. So then, such a principle of the soul as we have described is a power capable of pre- serving that in which this principle is found, in so far as it is found ; nourishment equips it for action. When,

23 therefore, it is deprived of nourishment, it can no longer exist. Since there are three distinct things here : the object nourished, the means of nourishment, and the power that causes nutrition, we shall say that it is the elemental soul that causes nutrition, the object nourished is the body which possesses this soul, and the means of nourishment is the food. And since it is fair to give everything a name in terms of its end, and since here the end of the soul is to generate a creature like to itself, the elemental soul might be called generative of

24 that which is like to itself. The means of nourishment is used in two senses, as is also the means of steering a ship ; for one may refer to the hand, or to the rudder, the one being both actively moving and moved ; the other only passively moved. All nutriment must be capable of being digested ; heat is the element which accom- plishes digestion. Everything animate, therefore, pos- sesses heat. We have explained now, in outline, what

bk. ii. ch. iv. PRINCIPLE OF NUTRITION 63

nutriment is. The subject must be more minutely treated later on in its proper place.1

1 Simplicius thinks the reference is to De gener. animal, and De gener. et corr. Sophonias refers to De gener. animal. (724a 14). The reference can hardly be to ITepi Tpo<f>r)s as Barthelemy-St.-Hilaire (who follows Trendelenburg) supposes. This latter treatise appears to have origin- ated in the Peripatetic School, but from the fact that it made the distinction between veins and arteries it cannot have been Aristotelian, and the reference in De somn. 456?> 5 must have been either to a pro- jected work or to the early chapters of the Histor. anim. or to the treatises enumerated by Simplicius. Cf. Zeller's Aristotle, Eng. tr., Vol. I. p. 92, note.

CHAPTER V.

Now that we have arrived at the foregoing conclusions, let us discuss in general the entire question of sense- perception. It consists, as we have said, in being moved and affected ; for it is supposed to be a sort of internal transformation. Some maintain that like is affected by 4iya like. In what sense this is possible and in what sense impossible, I have explained in a general treatise On

2 Activity and Passivity.1 A difficulty is raised by the question why it is that perceptions do not arise from the senses themselves, and why it is that without external stimuli they produce no sensation, although fire and earth, and the other elements of which we have sense- perception, are, either in their essential nature or in their attributes, found in the senses. It is, therefore, evident that the organ of sense-perception is not a thing in

3 actuality but only in potentiality. It is consequently analogous to the combustible which does not itself ignite without something to set it ablaze. Otherwise it would have burned itself and had no need of an

1 Philoponus thinks the reference is to Be yener. et corr. (cf.

3236 ff.).

64

bk. ii. ch. v. POTENTIAL AND ACTUAL 65

active fire. Inasmuch as we say that perceiving is used in two meanings (e.g. we call the capacity to hear and see, hearing and sight, although they may chance to be dormant, and we apply the same terms where the senses are actively exercised), so sense- perception also would be used in two senses, the one \ potential and the other actual. First of all let us understand that the terms affection, motion, and activity, are used in the same meaning. For motion is a sort of activity, although incomplete, as we have said elsewhere.1 Everything is affected and set in motion by an active agent and by something that exists in activity. . There- 5 fore in one sense a thing is affected by like, in another by unlike, as we have said ; for it is the unlike that is affected, but after being affected it is like.

We must, further, make a distinction touching potenti- ality and actuality, for we are now using these terms in a general sense. There is a sense in which we speak of 6 a thing as knowing, as when we call man knowing, because man belongs to the class of creatures that know and are endowed with knowledge. There is another sense in which we speak of a man as possessing the particular knowledge of grammar. In each of these cases a man 7 possesses knowledge potentially, but not in the same sense ; the former is knowing as belonging to a certain genus and as having a native endowment ; the latter is knowing in the sense of being able to exercise his know- ledge at will, when nothing external prevents. In a still different sense there is the man who is actually exercising his knowledge, and is in a condition of complete realiza-

1 Phys. 2016 31, 2576 8.

66 aristotle's psychology deanima

tion, having in the strict sense knowledge of a particular

8 thing, as e.g. A. The first two know in a potential sense ; the one of them, however, knows when he is transformed through a discipline of knowledge, and has passed re- peatedly out of an opposite condition ; the other knows

417^ in the sense of possessing arithmetical or grammatical science j1 and their passing from non-actual to actual

9 knowledge is different. Again, neither is the term ' pass- ivity ' used in an absolute meaning : in one meaning it is destruction by an opposite principle ; in another meaning, it is the preservation of the potentially existent by means of the actual and similar, just as potentiality is related to actuality. That which possesses potential knowledge, for instance, comes to the actual use of it a transition that we must either not call transformation (for the added element belongs to its own nature and tends to its own realization), or else we must call it a special kind of transformation. It is, therefore, incorrect to speak of thinking as a transformation when one thinks, just as the builder is not transformed when he is building a house.

10 That which conduces to actualization out of a potential

1 These three forms of knowledge illustrate three stages in the passage from undefined potentiality (5wa/zis) to complete and definite actuality (evepyeia). From mere rational potentiality, in which one has no definite latent knowledge, one passes into a knowing state by repeated application to a given science, and so from a non-knowing condition into a knowing one. On the other hand, if one possesses a particular science, as grammar, one has definite latent knowledge and passes into active knowing, not by acquisition, but by applying what one possesses in a dormant or inactive state. As a specific potentiality it represents a higher stage in the progress towards actuality, which in this case is the active exercise of specific knowledge. The primary potentiality is a person teachable, the second a person taught, and the actuality is a person actively employing what is taught.

ek. ii. ch. v. SENSATION AND THOUGHT 67

state in the matter of reasoning and thinking is not fairly called teaching, but must be given another name. Again, that which passes out of a potential state by learning or by acquiring knowledge at the hands of what actually knows and can teach, must either not be said to be affected as a passive subject, or we must admit two meanings of transformation, the one a change into a negative condi- tion, and the other into a positive condition and the thing's natural state.1

The first change2 in the sentient subject is wrought n by the generating parent, but after birth the creature comes into the possession of sense-perception as a species of knowledge. Active sensation is used in a way similar to active thinking. There is, however, this difference, that the objects which produce sensation are external, e.g. the visible and the audible, and similarly other sensible qualities. The reason for this is that active 12 sense-perception refers to particular things, while scientific^ knowledge refers to the universal. The^e_universals, how- >Ua1^Jc

ever, are, in a certain sense, in the mind itself. There- kA^- Q

< —1 <r^) , - t .

fore it is in one's power to think when one wills, but to & ^CU^^^J

experience sense-perception is not thus in one's power ; for a sensible object must first be present. This also holds good of those sciences which deal with sensible realities, and for the same reason, viz. because these sensible

lAiadecns signifies a transitional condition and e£ts a permanent, natural state. The former is either mere potentiality or an imperfect stage in the passage of a thing towards its natural realization. As such it represents a condition of privation or negation {aTeprjTLKri), compared with the positive, completed state at which a thing's nature aims.

2 By ' first change ' is here meant the native endowment with the potentiality to perceive and know.

68 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

13 realities belong to the world of particular and external phenomena.

To go into the details of these questions would be more suitable at another time. For the present so much may be regarded as fixed, viz. that the term ' potential ' is not used in any absolute sense, but in one case its meaning is similar to our saying that a boy has in him the potentiality of a general, and in another case to our saying that a man in his prime has that potentiality a distinction which also applies to the capacity for sense- *4 perception. Inasmuch as this distinction has no particular 418 tf name in our language, although we have remarked that the things are different and how they differ, we must simply employ the terms affection and transformation as applicable here. That which is capable of sense-per- ception is, as we have said, potentially what the sensible . . ^us actually. It is, therefore, affected at a moment when <wjJ3,v^ it is unlike, but when it has been affected it becomes like \J\fi. - and is as its object.1

t

1 In other words, sensation represents an ' affection ; or impression, and is the transformation of a potentially perceiving into an actually perceiving subject, in which case the sensible object is also converted or assimilated into a knowledge-form. In this sense it is made like the perceiving subject.

CHAPTER VI.

In discussing any form of sense-perception we must begin with the sensible object. The ' object of sense ' is used in three meanings, two of which touch the essential nature of sensation and one its accidents. Of the two first-named, one applies specially to each par- ticular sense, the other is common to them all. By 4 peculiar object of sense ' I mean a sense-quality which 2 cannot be apprehended by a sense different from that to which it belongs, and concerning which that sense cannot be deceived, e.g. colour is the peculiar object of vision, sound of hearing, flavour of taste. Touch,1 how- ever, discriminates several sense-qualities. The other particular senses, on the contrary, distinguish only their peculiar objects, and the senses are not deceived in the fact that a quality is colour or sound, although they may be deceived as to what or where the coloured or sonorous object may be. Such qualities are called the peculiar 3 objects of particular senses, whereas common objects are

1 Touch distinguishes the properties of body as body {De an. 4236 27), more specifically the qualities hard and soft, moist and dry, hot and cold, smooth and rough. Moreover, taste is, according to Aristotle, a kind of haptic function.

69

70 aristotle's psychology deanima

motion, rest, number, form, magnitude. Properties of the latter kind are not the peculiar objects of any sense, 4 but are common to them all. Motion is apprehended by touch and by sight. A thing is an object of sense accidentally, e.g. when a white object proves to be the son of Diares. The latter is perceived accidentally, for the person whom one perceives is an accident of the white object. Therefore, the sense as such is not affected by the sensible object ([as a person]). To the objects of sense, strictly regarded, belong such properties as are peculiarly and properly sense-qualities, and it is with these that the essential nature of each sense is naturallv concerned.

CHAPTER VII.

The object of vision is the visible. The visible is colour and something whose notion is expressible, but for which there is no single definite name.1 What I mean will be best explained as we proceed. The visible, then, is colour, and this is diffused upon that which is in itself visible,2 and by visible ' in itself,' I do not mean notionally visible, but something which has in itself the cause of the visible. All colour has the power to move the actually 4I8£ diaphanous and herein consists its nature. Therefore colour 2 is not visible without light, but every particular colour is seen in the light. For this reason we must first explain what light is. Light is something diaphanous. By dia- phanous I mean that which is visible, though not in itself and absolutely, but only by means of an agent, namely colour. Of such nature is air and water and many other bodies. 3 Water and air are not diaphanous as water and air, but because there is in both these elements the same property that is found in the eternal empyrean. The activity of

1Such phosphorescent and scintillating substances as mushrooms, horn, fish-heads, etc. Vid. De an. 419a 5.

2 Colour is not a substance but a property, a property diffused on the surface of a body and has the power to move a diaphanous medium. It is the coloured thing which is the substance or the per se visible.

71

72 aristotle's psychology deanima

4 this diaphanous, as such, is light. But where the diaphanous exists only potentially, there is darkness. Light is the colour, as it were, of the diaphanous, when the diaphanous is made really so by fire or by some such agent as the supernal body, for in the supernal body

5 there is something which is identical with fire. The nature of the diaphanous, therefore, and of light has been explained. Light is, namely, neither fire nor in a word any body nor the efflux of any body1 (for this would then also be a body), but it is the presence of fire or some such agent in a diaphanous medium. For two bodies can- not occupy the same place at the same time. Light appears to be the opposite of darkness. Darkness is the privation of a condition of the diaphanous, the presence of which

6 condition is light. Empedocles2 is wrong, as is every one else who has held a like theory, in thinking that light moves itself and at some time or other projected itself into the interval between the earth and the surrounding space, without our being conscious of it. For this is contrary to plain reason and to observed facts. In a small space, the fact might escape us, but in an interval that extends from east to west, to claim that the

7 fact escapes our notice is asking too much. It is the colourless that is receptive of colour, and the non- sonorous that is capable of sound. Colourless are the diaphanous and the invisible, or that which is scarcely visible, as for example, the dark. Of such nature is the diaphanous, but only when it is so potentially and not

1 Plato, Timaeus 67 C.

2 Burnet thinks that Empedocles was led to suppose that light takes some time to travel, although its speed is so great as to be imperceptible, by this theory of "effluences." Burnet, Early Greek Philos. p. 255.

bk. ii. CH.vii. VISION AND ITS MEDIUM 73

actually. For the same medium is sometimes dark and sometimes light. Not all objects are visible in the light, 8 but only the peculiar colour of each object. For certain 419 « objects are not visible in the light, but stimulate sensa- tion in the dark,1 as e.g. those fiery, shining phenomena that have no class-designation such as mushrooms, horn, and the heads, scales, and eyes of fish, while the peculiar colour of none of these objects is seen. The explanation 9 of their visibility is subject for a different treatise than the present. So much is now clear : it is colour that is visible in light. Therefore without light colour is not visible. For it is the essence of colour to set the actually diaphanous in motion, and the diaphanous in actuality is light. Clear evidence of this is the fact that 10 if one places a coloured object on the eye, it is not seen. On the contrary, it is the diaphanous, as e.g. the air, which is stimulated by colour, and the sense organ is stimulated by this contiguous medium. Democritus is wrong, then, in supposing that if the medium were a vacuum our vision would be accurate, even to the seeing of an ant in the sky. This is impossible, for vision takes place from the fact that the percipient organ undergoes u an effect, and this effect cannot be produced directly by the visible colour. So that there remains only the supposition that it is produced by a medium, and conse- quently there must be a medium. And were a vacuum produced, there would not only be no accurate vision, but no vision at all.2

1 Phosphorescent substances.

2 Aristotle says there are three things to be taken into account in sense- perception the organ, the object, and the medium, all of which are condiciones sine quibus non. The medium of vision is the diaphanous or

74 aristotle's psychology deanima

12 The reason why colour is visible only in the light has been explained. Fire, however, is visible in both light and darkness, and necessarily so, for it is by the agency of fire that the diaphanous becomes diaphanous. The

13 same statement applies also to sound and smell. For nothing when placed in actual contact with the sense- organ produces the sensation of sound or smell, but by means of odour and sound a medium is set in motion and through this the sense organ in each case is affected. But if one should place a sonorous or odorous object on the sense organ itself, no sensation would be produced. In the case of touch and taste, similar conditions hold good, although not apparently. The reason for this

14 will be evident later. The medium for sound is the atmosphere ; the medium for smell has no name. It is an element that is common to air and water, and as the diaphanous is related to colour, so there is a some- thing in water and air similarly related to an odorous body. For aquatic animals appear to be capable of the

4I9£ sensation of smell. But man and the respiring land- animals smell only in so far as they employ inspiration. The cause of these phenomena will be explained later on.

property of translucence found in air and water, a quality analogous to that found in the aether of the empyrean and in fire. The media of hearing (4196 18, 420a 11) and smell are air and water, and the medium of touch (and taste) is the flesh. In this connection it is to be noted that, while both air and water serve as media for smell, only air is a medium for man, and only water a medium for the aquatic animals. Man cannot smell in water. Cf. De an. 4216 8, 15, 19 ; 422a 4 -v Hist. anim. 534a 11.

CHAPTER VIII.

Let us now first of all discuss the subject of sound and hearing. Sound is twofold. It is one thing in actuality, and another in potentiality. Some things, we say, are incapable of sound, such as a sponge or wool, others are resonant, such as bronze and bodies that are hard and smooth, because they can emit sound ; that is, they have the power to create an actual sound through mediation 2 between the resonant object and the hearing. The actual 1 sound is always produced by something in reference to something and in a medium.1 A blow is the producing cause. It is, therefore, impossible for an object, taken alone, to produce a sound, for the striking agent and the struck object are different. Thus the sonorous body pro- duces sound by its relation to another body. A blow is 3 impossible without movement, and, as we have said, sound does not result from a blow upon any haphazard object. Wool, e.g. when struck produces no sound, but bronze

1 Theophrastus and the peripatetic commentators introduced the term 5t7/%es to describe the medium of sound and dioafiov to describe the medium of smell. Cf. Themistius, ed. Spengel, p. 115. Simplicius Comment in lib. De an., 419a 32. Philoponus Comment in lib. De an. (Ed. Acad. Reg. Bor.), 355. 14.

75

76 aristotle's psychology deanima

and whatever is hard and smooth do. Bronze is resonant because it is smooth. Hollow bodies, by reverberation, produce many reports after the first one, because the air, when it is once set in motion, can find no egress.

4 Furthermore, audition takes place in air and water, but to a less degree in the latter. But neither air nor water is the main thing in the case of sound. The percussion of solid bodies against each other and against the air must take place, and this takes place when the smitten

5 air resists and is not dissipated. Therefore if it is struck quickly and violently it produces sound, for the motion of the striking agent must anticipate the dispersion of the air, as if one were to strike a pile or rapidly shifting chain of sand. An echo is produced when from the air which is made unitary by means of the vessel that confines it and keeps it from dispersion, an oncoming mass of air is driven back again, like a rebounding ball.1 An echo is

6 apparently produced constantly, only it is not audible,

1 Sound, according to this explanation, is produced by smooth, resisting bodies. The production of sound depends on the following conditions : (1) an object to be struck, (2) a striking agent, (3) a com- municating medium, (4) a hearing organ, (5) the delivery of the blow .in such way that the diffluent air (medium) may not be dissipated and so conduct no sound. When the air is smitten quickly and vigorously, it is compressed before it can yield, and so emits a report, as the com- pressed air in a bladder makes a report on bursting (an illustration cited by Wallace from Pacius). An echo is the repercussion of air from the resisting side of a vessel or place that obstructs the dissipation of air, whereby instead of becoming soundless it is thrown back, like a ball, and made to sound again. The disturbed air communicates with the air in the ear, which being fast immured cannot be dissipated, but interprets without variation the reports brought to it by the move- ments of the external air. Disturbances in the condition of the internal air, e.g. through yawning, modify the accuracy of hearing. We, also, for the same reason hear better when inhaling than when exhaling {De gener. anim. 781a 31).

bk. ii. ch. viii. SOUND AND ITS MEDIUM 77

for the same conditions hold good of both sound and light. Light is constantly reflected (otherwise light would not be found everywhere, but there would be darkness outside the region illuminated by the sun), but the reflection is not similar to that which is caused by water or bronze or any other polished solid, where a shadow is cast whereby the light-area is delimited. A 7 void is correctly regarded as a chief factor in hearing. Now, the air appears to be a void, and this, when it is moved as a single and continuous element, is what produces hearing. But, because of the swift dissipation of the air, no sound arises unless the object struck be smooth. In this case, however, the air by reason of 420 < the even surface, is made one throughout, for the surface of a smooth body is one throughout.

A body is sonorous when it is capable of setting in motion up to the organ of hearing the single and con- tinuous air. Hearing is naturally related to the air, and owing to the fact that sound is in the air, the inner air 8 is set in motion by the moving outside air. Therefore, an animal does not hear in all parts of its body, neither does the air penetrate everywhere. And the psychical organ that is to be stimulated does not contain air in all its parts. The air in and for itself is, by reason of its facile dispersion, non-sonorous. But when it is restrained from dispersion, its motion produces sound. The air 9 within the ears is so deeply immured as to be in itself immovable, in order that it may detect all distinctions in communicated motions. For these reasons we hear in water, because the water has no access to the congenital air, nor does it penetrate even into the ear because of the

78 aristotle's psychology deanima

latter's convolutions. When, however, this does happen, hearing ceases. Neither do we hear when the membrane

io is diseased, just as the eye has no vision when its cornea is diseased. A test as to whether hearing is intact or not is found in the ears' continually resounding like a horn. The air in the ear has its own peculiar motion, although sound is foreign to this internal air and is not one of its properties. It is for this reason that we speak of hearing by means of a void and resonant organ, because we hear by means of something which contains confined air. The

ii question arises whether it is the striking agent or the object struck that produces sound. Or is it both of these, but each in a different sense ? Sound is a sort of motion of an object which is capable of being moved in the same way as the particles that rebound from smooth surfaces when one strikes them. Not every object, as has been said, produces sound when struck or when striking another object, as e.g. in the case of one sharp point striking another. On the contrary, the object that is struck must be smooth, so that the air may be thrown

12 off and agitated in a mass. Distinctions in resonant bodies are discernible in the actual sound they pro- duce. As without light no colours are visible, so without sound the acute and grave are not discernible. These terms are employed metaphorically and are drawn from

13 the tactual sense. The acute stimulates sensation quickly and strongly, and the grave slowly and in a small degree. It is not the acute,1 however, that is quick nor the grave that is slow, but merely the motion of the one is called

1 Perhaps a criticism of Plato [Timaeus 67 C), as Trendelenburg thinks.

bk. ii. ch. viii. DEFINITION OF VOICE 79

quick by reason of its swift action on the sense, and the other is called slow by reason of its tardy action. The analogy appears to apply to acute and dull in the sense of touch. The acute e.g. pricks and the blunt pushes, 420 b as it were, because the motion of the one is quick and of the other slow, so that the effect of the one takes place swiftly and of the other tardily. Let so much suffice for 14 the discussion of sound.

Voice is the sound produced by a living being. No 'v^n c*JL\ inanimate thing has voice, unless one speaks metaphori- cally, as e.g. the flute, lyre, and other inanimate instruments are said to have a certain range, melody, and expression, properties which are possessed also by the voice. Many animals are without voice, as the bloodless animals, and, amongst the sanguineous, fishes. This has its good reason, seeing that sound is a move- 15 ment of the air. Fishes that are said to have voice, such as those in the Achelous,1 produce a sound by means of their gills or some such organ. Voice is the sound made by a living creature, and made not by any accidental organ. But since nothing emits sound unless there is a striking agent, a thing struck, and a medium, viz. air, it would be reasonable to suppose that only those animals that breathe air possess voice. Now nature employs respiration for two purposes, just as she 16 employs the tongue both for the function of taste and of speech, of which functions taste is necessary (and therefore

deferred to in Hist. anim. (Bk. IV. Ch. 9, 5356 18) as Kairpos, said to make a grunting noise, which probably suggested the name {Kawpos meaning primarily a wild boar). It is not known to what fish this refers, although it has been thought to be the capros aper of the Aegean Archipelago. Cf. Aubert and Wimmer's Aristoteles' Thierkunde, p. 130.

80 aristotle's psychology deanima

is found in all animals generally), whereas the communi- cation of thought is given for the ends of higher living. So it is with respiration, which performs a function in reference to the internal warmth, and as such is neces- sary for living (the reason will be explained elsewhere), and another function in reference to speech, where it subserves the ends of higher living. The windpipe is the

*7 organ of respiration, and this organ in turn subserves another, the lungs, and it is in virtue of the latter that land animals have more heat than others. The pericardiac region first of all needs respiration,1 and, therefore, it is essential that the air be inspired inwards. And so it is the percussion of the inspired air, directed by the soul in those inward parts, against the windpipe,

18 as it is called, that constitutes voice. Not every sound of an animal is voice, as we have said (for it is possible to make noises with the tongue or such as people make in coughing), but the impact of the air must be animate and combined with some idea in order to be called voice. For voice is significantsounj and not merely the sound of respired air, as is the case in coughing. On the contrary, the animal by means of this respired air pro- 421 a duces an impact of the air already in the windpipe against

1 The organs through which cooling is effected are the brain and lungs, and in the case of fishes the gills. The need of cooling is found in different degrees in different animals. Bloodless animals need it least. Insects do not inhale, but they are provided with a substitute for inspiration in a supply of congenital air. (De respirat. Ch. 9, 4:74th 25 ff. ) The lungs of mammals contain most blood, while the lungs of birds and amphibious creatures are more spongy and contain most air. and the latter can consequently live longer without inspiring air. The air is carried through veins that lead from the lungs to the heart. Hist, animal. Bk. I. Ch. 17, 496a 27 ff.

bk. ii. ch. viii. VOCAL UTTERANCE 81

the trachea itself. This is proven by the impossibility 19 of vocal utterance when we noithor inhale ee*- exhale but simply hold our breath, because in holding the breath we thereby disturb this vocal process. Also, we see from this why it is that the fishes have no voice, being, as they are, without a windpipe. They lack this organ, because they are incapable of inhaling or exhaling air. The explanation of this is matter for a different treatise.

K^

CHAPTEK IX.

Smell and its object are less easy to define than the foregoing senses, for the nature of smell is not so clear to us as is that of sound and colour. The reason for this is the fact that this sense with us is inaccurate and less perfect than in many animals. Man has a poor sense of smell, and smells no odorous object without painful or pleasant association, because the sense-organ does not

2 sharply discriminate qualities. It is probable that the hard-eyed1 animals discriminate colours in the same way, and that distinctions in colour are not clear to them

3 except as they have the feeling of fear or not. So it is with smell in the human race. Smell has apparently some analogy to taste, and the species of flavours corre- spond to those of odours; but our sense of taste is more accurate because it is a sort of touch, and the sense of touch is the most accurately developed of all the senses in man. In the case of the other senses, man is inferior to many animals, but in discriminations of touch he is

4 far superior to the others. For this reason man is the most intelligent animal. A proof of this is the fact that within the human race the good or bad native endow-

1 Hist. anim. ii. 13, 505a 35 ; iv. 10, 537& 12 ; De part. anim. ii. 13, 6576 34. Such animals have no eyelids, as e.g. crabs.

82

bk. ii. ch. ix. THE SENSE OF SMELL 83

ment of individuals depends upon this sense organ, and

no other. Men who have hard flesh are poorly endowed ioA^n

intellectually, men who have soft flesh are gifted.1

As one flavour is sweet, another bitter, so it is with 5 smells. Although in some cases smell and flavour correspond to each other, I mean, for example, where we have a sweet smell and a sweet flavour, in other cases they are contraries. In like manner we refer the qualities of pungent, harsh, piquant, and oily to smells as 6 well as to flavours, but, as we have said, owing to the fact that smells are not so clearly discriminated as flavours, these terms are borrowed from taste on account of similarity in the sense objects. For the smell of 421 b saffron and honey is sweet, and the smell of thyme and similar herbs is pungent. The same holds good of other 7 qualities. Further, just as hearing and each particular sense distinguishes its own object, in the one case the audible and inaudible, in another case the visible and invisible, so also smell distinguishes the odorous and inodorous. And the inodorous is so called, in one case, from the fact that it is totally incapable of yielding smell ; in another case because the smell is faint or indefinite. Similarly one employs the term insipid.

Smell is transmitted through a medium, such as air or 8 water. For aquatic animals appear to smell ; so, too, sanguineous and bloodless animals, and the birds of the air, have this sense. Some of the latter are endowed with the power of scent and mark their prey from afar. It seems doubtful, therefore, whether the process of smell 9 in all these animals is alike. Man smells while inhaling,

1 Compare our expressions 'thick-skinned,' 'hide-bound,' etc.

84 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

but without inhaling and while exhaling or holding his breath, he does not smell, whether the object be remote 10 or near, not even if it be placed in the nose itself. That an object when placed upon the sense-organ itself is not perceived, is a fact common to all the animals. But not to perceive odours without inhaling is peculiar to man, as may be proven by experiment. Were it not so, the bloodless animals, inasmuch as they have no respira- tion, would have to possess a sense beyond those already named. But this is impossible, if it is true that they perceive smells, for the perception of the odorous, whether pleasant or unpleasant, is the sense of smell. Further- more, as these animals appear to be destroyed by strong- fumes, just as man e.g. is destroyed by pitch, sulphur, and similar fumes, they must have the sense of smell,

12 although they do not respire. The organ of smell in man appears to differ from that in the other animals, just as his eyes differ from those of the hard-eyed animals. For the eyes in man have a protection and, as it wTere, a sheath in the eyelids, and without moving or opening these he does not see. Whereas the hard-eyed animals have no such protection, but see at once whatever comes

13 into the field of vision. So also the organ of smell in 422 a some animals is uncovered, as the eye is ; while in others

that respire, it has a covering, which opens in inspiration

14 and by the dilation of veins and pores. For this reason the animals that breathe do not smell in water. For in order to smell they must inhale, and in water this is impossible. Smell is a property of the dry, as flavour is of the moist, and the organ of smell is potentially analogous to its object.

CHAPTER X.

The sapid is a tactual property, and this explains the fact that it is not perceived through the medium of any foreign body.1 For neither is the tactual so perceived. The body in which flavour, i.e. the gustable, is found consists in something moist as its matter, and this moist element is something tangible. Consequently, if we were in the water and something sweet were thrown into it, we should perceive it. The sensation, however, would not have been produced in us through a medium, but by the mingling of the sweet with the moist, as is the case 2 with a beverage. Colour, on the other hand, is not per- ceived by means of its being mingled with anything, nor by means of emanations. There is in the case of taste no medium ; in other respects, however, as colour is to the visible, so is taste to the sapid. Nothing can stimu- late the sensation of flavour apart from the moist, but an

1 The medium of touch is the flesh. The medium of taste is also the riesh, more particularly the tongue and throat (if Aristotle concurs in the popular opinion represented by Philoxenus, cf. Eth. nicom. iii. 10. 10. 1118a 33). These two senses, consequently, apprehend qualities only through immediate contact, while sight, hearing, and smell operate at a distance through the media of air and water.

85

S

86 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

object must possess moisture either actually or potentially,

3 as does salt. For salt is easily soluble, and melts on the tongue.

As sight is discriminative of the visible and invisible (for darkness is the invisible, and on this, too, sight exercises judgment), further of the extremely dazzling (for this is also invisible, but in a different sense from darkness), so, too, hearing is discriminative of sound and silence, of which the one is audible and the other inaudible, and of the crashing sound, as sight is dis- criminative of dazzling brightness (for as a tiny sound is inaudible, in a certain sense a great and crashing sound is also inaudible). The term invisible is used, on the one hand, in an absolute sense, and means the same as the term impossible does in other cases ; on the other hand, it is used in the sense of what is naturally meant to be seen, but is not seen, or only imperfectly seen, just as one applies the terms footless and seedless to animals and fruits that are imperfect. So also is taste

4 discriminative of the gustable and non-gustable ; the latter is that which has an insignificant or indistinct flavour, or a flavour that is subversive of taste. The potable and non-potable seem to be the final principles of taste ; taste implies both of them. The one is, how- ever, indistinct or destructive of taste, while the other is natural to the sense. The potable is common to the

422 b senses of touch and taste. Since the sapid is moist, it is necessary that the sense-organ be neither actually moist nor incapable of becoming moist. For taste is affected

5 by the sapid object as sapid. Consequently it is necessary for the organ of taste to be capable of becoming

BK.n. ch.x. THE SENSE OF TASTE 87

moist, without injury and without becoming intrinsically

moist.1 A proof is the fact that the tongue, when it is

very moist or very dry, is incapable of perceiving the sapid.

For in this case there arises merely a tactual impression

of the simple liquid, just as when one first tastes a strong

flavour and then essays another, or as everything seems

bitter to an invalid because his tongue is full of this 6

bitter moisture. The varieties of flavours, as in the case

of colours, are partly simple opposites such as sweet and

bitter, partly the affiliated qualities oily and salty, and

the intermediate qualities of pungent, harsh, astringent,

and acid. For these seem to include approximately all

the distinctions in flavours.2 So then the sapid sense is "Vrg^A p i

potentially of the same character as the sapid object

whicTTactually produces the sensation of taste.

1 Aristotle applies here to taste the metaphysical doctrine of poten- tiality and actuality which he employs everywhere in the explanation of organic life. All change is a transition from a potential state into a state in which a thing finds its end realized or in process of realization. So the sense of taste is only potentially taste until it is stimulated. In this process of actualization or realization the organ assimilates an objective quality and converts it into a subjective one, to use modern terminology, and this process Aristotle describes as the "sense becom- ing like the thing," or, specifically, the "capacity of the organ of taste to become moist, without being converted into moisture, or becoming intrinsically moist." The potentiality of the organ refers only to the assimilation of a property or sense-quality.

2 Aristotle distinguishes two fundamental colours, black and white (which on surfaces correspond to darkness and light), and two funda- mental tastes, bitter and sweet. Including black and white, there are seven primary colours, all of whose elements, however, are found in black and white, and they are produced from these two by processes of mixture. These colours are white, black (including grey, De sensu, 442a 22), yellow, red, violet, green, and blue. Analogously the seven primary tastes are based on bitter and sweet. The flavours are : sweet (including the fat or oily), bitter, salt, harsh, pungent, astringent, acid (cf. De sensu, 4. 442a 12).

CHAPTEE XL

The same kind of reasoning applies to the tangible and the sense of touch. If touch is not a single sense but several, then tangible objects must also be manifold. There is some doubt whether touch is manifold or unitary, and it is uncertain what the sense-organ is which apprehends the tangible. Is it the flesh in man, and in other animals something analogous to flesh, or is the flesh only the medium, while the primary

2 organ is something different and internal ? Every sense appears to apprehend only one contrary, e.g. sight senses black and white ; hearing, acute and grave ; taste, bitter and sweet. In touch, however, are found many opposites : hot and cold, moist and dry, hard and soft, and other similar opposites. There appears, however, to

3 be a solution for this difficulty in the fact that several opposites apply to the other senses also, as e.g. in sound there are not only the properties acute and grave, but also large and small, and smooth and hard, and similar qualities are applied to the voice. Similarly, different dis-

4 tinctions are applied to colour. But what forms the single substrate for touch, as sound does for hearing, is not clear.

bk. ii. ch. xi. THE SENSE OF TOUCH 89

Another question is whether the sense-organ is internal or not, or whether the flesh immediately senses touch- qualities. The fact that sensation is simultaneous with 423 a contact is no proof here. For as a matter of fact, if one 5 should prepare a membrane, as it were, and draw it over the flesh, one would still have the sensation of touch at the moment of contact, and yet it is plain that the sense- organ is not in the membrane. Even were it grown together with the flesh, the sensation would only the more quickly penetrate it. Consequently this part of the 6 body seems to be related to us as the air would be, were it grown to us round about. For we should then have to perceive sound, colour, and smell in each instance by means of a single sense-organ, and sight, hearing, and smelling would in that case have become a single sense.

However, as a matter of fact, since the media through which sense-movements are transmitted are different, the sense-organs themselves are different. In the case of 7 touch this is not clear ; for it is not possible that a living body should consist of air or water ; it must be a solid body. It remains that it is a body composed of earth and those two former elements, air and water, in such way as it is intended flesh and what is analogous thereto should be. Consequently, the body ([i.e. the flesh]) must be the natural medium for the sense of touch, by which the several sensations are mediated. That they are several 8 is evident from the character of touch on the surface of the tongue. For the tongue, as a single organ, dis- cerns all tactual and sapid qualities. Further, if the rest of our flesh were to discern sapid qualities, touch

90 aristotle's psychology deanima

and taste would be regarded as one and the same sense. But as a matter of fact they are regarded as two, because they are not convertible. 9 Since body has depth, i.e. the third dimension, wherever there is an intermediate body between two other bodies the question might be raised whether it is possible for these two bodies to be in contact with each other. Now, neither the moist nor the fluid is incorporeal, but each must necessarily be water or contain water. But objects which are in contact with each other in the water, inas- much as their extremities are not dry, must have water between them, in which their outer circumferences are

io submerged. Now, if this is true, it is impossible for two objects in water to be in contact with each other. The same holds good of the air (for air is conditioned in the same way towards the objects in it as water is towards objects in water, only in the former case the conditions are more elusive for us ([who live in an atmospheric medium]),

n just as aquatic animals fail to observe that the fluid is in 423/5 immediate contact with the fluid. A further question then arises, whether the same process of sensation applies to all senses alike, or whether in different senses the process is different, just as touch or taste was seen to function by means of immediate contact, while the other senses function from a distance. This last distinction is not real, but both the hard and soft we perceive through media, as we do also the sonorous, the visible, and the odorous; in the one case we have objects at a distance, in the other, close

12 at hand. This is the reason why the medium eludes our observation. For we do sense everything through a medium, but in the case of things close at hand, the

bk. ii. ch. xi. THE MEDIUM OF TOUCH 91

existence of the medium escapes us. And yet, as we said above, were we to perceive all tangible qualities through the medium of a membrane without knowing that a medium intervened, we should then be in the same condition as we now are in the media of air and water. For we appear now to be in contact with things them- selves, and not to apprehend them through a medium. 13 The tangible, however, differs from the visible and audible in that we perceive the latter by the medium producing a certain effect on us, while qualities of touch we do not perceive by means of the medium but simultaneously with it, as a man who is struck through his shield. For the struck shield does not strike him, but rather shield and man are simultaneously struck. In a word, flesh 14 and the tongue seem to be related to the sense-organ as air and water are severally related to sight, hearing, and smell. For were the sense-organ itself brought into con- tact with the object, sensation would not result either in the one case or the other, just as little as vision would result were one to lay a white object on the surface of the eye. By which it is evident that the organ of touch 15 must be internal,1 for in this way it would be parallel with the other senses. When objects are placed upon ^ i-a . « the sense-organ, sensation does not result ; on the other | ^J> hand, when placed upon the flesh, sensation does result. J^^a-'Ux -t^j. Flesh must, therefore, be merely the medium of touch.

The distinctions of body as body are tactual. By dis- 16 tinctions I mean such as characterize the elements viz. warm and cold, dry and moist, concerning which we have

1 The organ of taste and touch is the heart ; the media, as already explained, are the tongue and flesh.

92 aristotle's psychology deanima

spoken in an earlier treatise On the elements} The sense- organ which perceives these distinctions is touch, and the part in which the sense of touch, as we call it, is primarily found is potentially what tangible objects are actually.

1 7 For sensation means being affected in a certain waj ; so 424 a that whatever makes another thing to be in reality like

itself does so by virtue of that thing's having this nature in potentiality. Therefore we do not perceive hot and cold, hard and soft, in objects that have these qualities in like degree as ourselves, but we perceive the excesses, as if sense were a sort of mean between opposed sensible objects. And hence it discriminates sensible objects.

18 The mean is capable of judgment, for it becomes in refer- ence to each of the extremes another extreme. And as that which is to perceive white or black must not itself be actually white or black, but both of these potentially (and the same holds good of other instances), so also in the case of touch, it must not be either hot or cold in itself. Furthermore, as sight was said to discriminate in

19 a sense both the visible and invisible, and the other senses in like manner their opposites, so also touch discriminates the tangible and intangible. And by intangible I mean those things where tactual discrimina- tions are quite indistinct, as e.g. in the case of air, and those excesses of touch that are destructive of the sense. Each of the senses has now been treated in outline.

1 De gen. et corr. 329b 18-3306 9. On the lost treatise irepi (ttoixciuv see Heitz, Die Verlorenen Schriften d. Aristoteles, p. 76.

CHAPTEB XII.

In reference to sensation in general we must understand **■ that a sense is capable of receiving into itself sensible ^ forms without their matter, just as wax receives into itself the mark of a ring without its iron or gold ; it receives into itself a gold or bronze im- pression, but not as gold or bronze. In like manner also sense is impressed by every object that possesses colour or flavour or sound, not in so far as each of these objects bears a given name, but in so far as it has such and such a quality and expresses an idea. The 2 organ of sense is fundamentally that in which this power of being impressed exists. It has therefore an identity with the object that makes the impression, but in its mode of expression it is different. Otherwise that cl . Mv «--U--= which perceives would be a sort of magnitude; whereas""^^ v^-S^oL the mode of expression of the perceptive faculty and of -y^ 4X000 v sensation is not magnitude, but only a certain relation -iV«_ /s^^^w <n and potentiality of magnitude. From this it is clear why excesses in sensible objects destroy the sense-organs. 3 For if the stimulus be stronger than the organ, then the relation between them is destroyed, just as harmony and

tone are destroyed when the strings are struck too

93

94 aristotle's psychology dsamma

4 violently. Why is it, then, that plants have no sensation, having as they do a certain psychical endowment, and being affected by tangible qualities, for they experience

424 b e.g. cold and heat ? The reason is that they have no mean in their nature, nor such a principle as is capable of receiving into itself the forms of sensible objects ; on the

5 contrary they are affected materially. One might raise the question whether a thing which cannot smell can be affected by odour, or that which cannot see can be affected by colour, and so on. Supposing that the object

6 of smell is odour, odour produces the sensation of smell, if it produces anything at all ; so that nothing which is incapable of smelling can be affected by odour. The same reasoning applies to the other senses. Neither can sentient beings be affected further than they are in each case sentient. This is also evident from the following : neither light nor darkness, sound nor smell, acts upon bodies, but the media in which these qualities exist may act upon bodies, e.g. it is the air which is combined with thunder that rives the tree. Tangible

7 qualities, however, and flavours operate directly. If this were not so, how could inanimate bodies be affected and changed ? Do the other qualities then act directly also ? Or is it rather true that not every body is capable of being affected by smell and sound, and those which are so affected are indefinite and unstable, as e.g. the air ? For air emits odour as if it were affected by something. What is smelling, then, beyond this being affected by something ? Smelling surely means also perceiving, whereas the air by being affected is only niads the ready object of perception.

BOOK THE THIRD.

CHAPTEE I.

That there is no additional sense beyond the five we

have enumerated (I mean sight, hearing, smell, taste, and

touch), one may believe from the following considerations.

Granted that we really have perception of everything for 2

which touch is the appropriate sense (for all the qualities

of the tangible as such are apprehended by touch), it is

necessary that if any sensation is lacking, some organ

must also be lacking in us. Whatever we perceive by

contact is perceived by the sense of touch, with which we

are endowed. On the other hand, whatever we perceive

through media and not by direct contact, is perceived by

simple elements, such as air and water. The conditions

here are such that if several sensible objects which differ 3

from each other generically are perceived by a single

medium, then anyone who has a sense-organ analogous

to this medium must be capable of perceiving these

several sense-objects. For example, if the sense-organ

is composed of air and the air is the medium of both

sound and colour, the organ would perceive both these

sense-qualities. If, on the other hand, several elements

are mediators of the same sense-qualities, as e.g. colour is 425 a

95

96 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de anima

mediated both by air and water (for both are diaphanous), then the organ which contains one of these elements alone will perceive that which is mediated by both of

4 them. The sense-organs are composed exclusively of these two simple elements, air and water (for the pupil of the eye is composed of water, the hearing of air, smell of one or the other of these). Fire, however, belongs to no organ or it is common to them all (for nothing is sentient without heat). Earth belongs either to no organ or it is chiefly and in a special manner combined with touch. Nothing would remain, therefore, excepting air and water,

c to constitute a sense-organ. Some animals have, in actual fact, these organs as described. Animals which are perfect and not defective have all these senses. For even the mole, as one may observe, has eyes underneath its skin. Consequently, unless there are bodies other than those known to us, or qualities other than those which belong to earthly bodies, we may conclude there is no sense lacking in us.1

6 Neither is it possible that there should be any peculiar organ for the perception of common properties such as we perceive accidentally2 by means of the individual

xThe argument here, that there can be no senses beyond the five enumerated, is hopelessly obscure. The statement of the argument is probably fragmentary. Barthelemy-St.-Hilaire (Traite de I'Ame, p. 254, note) wrongly restates the argument, in his attempt to put an intelligible meaning into it, and Zeller's rehabilitation of it (Eng. tr. vol. I. p. 62) is not less obscure than the passage itself. The argument apparently aimed to show that we are equipped with sense-organs to cognize the qualities of all known bodies, and, as nature does not un- necessarily duplicate these organs, they must be complete.

2 Omit ov, which Biehl has incorporated into his text from Torstrik's conjecture, against the better reading of all the mss. The emendation entirely destroys the sense of the passage, it being the reiterated

bk. in. chap. i. THE ' COMMON SENSIBLE* ' 97

senses, e.g. common properties like motion, rest, form, magnitude, number, unity. For all these properties we perceive by means of motion, e.g. magnitude is per- ceived by motion. So also is form, for form is a sort of magnitude, and rest we perceive from the absence of 7 motion. We perceive numbers by the negation of con- tinuity and by the special senses, for each sensation is experienced as a unit. So, then, it is clearly impossible that any particular sense should apply to these common properties, such as motion. For this would be like one now perceiving the sweet by means of sight. This is s because we happen to have senses for both qualities ([i.e. for the sweet and for colour]), whereby when the given qualities coincide in one object, we recognize the object as sweet.1 Otherwise we do not perceive the sweet, excepting in the sense of accident, as e.g. when we recognize the son of Cleon not because he is Cleon's son, but because he is a fair object, which for the son of Cleon is an accident.

We have indeed a 'common sense' for the perception of 9 common qualities. I do not mean accidentally. It is there- fore not a particular sense, for in that case we should

doctrine of Aristotle that ' common properties ' are cognized by the '- sensus communis,' in its own nature, and by the individual senses only per accidens {De an. 425a 20, 25 ; 418a 9 ; 418a 24 ; De seii.su, 437a 8). Biehl seems to have been influenced by the ou Kara av/AfiefivKos of 425a 28 and its apparent contradiction of the present passage. There is, however, no contradiction, the ov /card, k.t.X. referring to the function of the ' common sense,' while the Kara crv/j.(3e(BriK6s refers to the function of the individual sense.

1 We cognize the quality sweet by means of sight only per accidens. We see a sweet thing e.g. when we see a grape with a given colour and contour, knowing by experience that the colour and contour are associated with a quality sweet to the taste.

G

98 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de anima

perceive in no other way than as just now described in 10 the illustration of Cleon. A sense, however, perceives accidentally the qualities that are peculiar to a different sense, not in their own nature but because of the unity of these qualities, as when two sense-qualities 425 b apply to the same object, e.g. in the case of bile that it is both bitter and yellow. Now, it is not the function of either particular sense to say that both these qualities inhere in one thing and it is owing to this fact that error arises, when in the case of a yellow substance one opines it to be bile. One might ask why we are endowed with 11 several senses and not with one only. Is it not that facts of sequence and coincidence, such as motion, magni- tude, and number, might the less escape us ? For if we possessed sight only, and this were limited to the percep- tion of whiteness, then all other distinctions would the more easily escape our knowledge, and because colour and magnitude are always coincident, they would appear to be identical. In point of fact, however, since these common qualities are found in different sense-objects, it is evident that the several qualities themselves are different.

CHAPTEK II.

But inasmuch as we perceive that we see and hear, we must have this consciousness of vision either by the instrument of sight or by some other faculty.1 The same faculty will then apply both to sight and to colour, the object of sight. In this case, either we shall have two senses for the same thing, or a sense will be conscious of itself. Further, if there is another sense for the perception of sight, either we shall have an infinite regressus, or a given sens^jnust_finally be cognizant of itself, in which case one would better admit this in the instance of the original sense itself, i.e. sight. Here, however, is 2 a difficulty. For, if sensation by means of sight is vision, and colour or that which possesses colour is what we see, then the seeing faculty itself must first of all have colour in order to be seen. It is plain, therefore, that sensation by means of sight is not employed in a single meaning. For even when we do not see, it is by means of sight that we judge both of darkness and light, although not in the same way. Furthermore, the seeing subject is in a

1 This function of consciousness is performed by the ' sensus com- munis.' Cf. Introduction, Chap. iv.

99

100 aristotle's psychology deanima

3 certain sense saturated with colour, since each sentient organ receives into itself the sensible object without its matter. This explains the fact that when objects of sense have been removed, the sensations and images still persist in the sense-organ.

4 The actualization of the object of sense and of the sense itself is one and the same process ; they are not, however, identical with each other in their essential nature.1 I mean, for instance, actual sound and actual hearing are not the same. For it is possible for one who has hearing not to hear, and for a sonorous body

5 not to emit sound at every instant. When, however, that which has the potentiality of hearing and that which has the potentiality of sounding, actually hear and actually emit sound, at that moment the realized hearing and the realized sound are simultaneously

426 a complete, and one would call them respectively the

6 sensation of hearing and the act of sounding. If, then, movement, activity, and passivity are implied in the produced object, it must be that actual sound and hearing exist in a potential state. For creative and motive activity is given in antecedent passivity.2 It is, therefore, not necessary for the moving principle to be itself in actual motion. For as action and passion find their expression in the object acted upon and not in the producing agent, so too the actualization of the sensible object and the sense-organ is_expresseil

7 in _the latter. The actualization of a sonorous body is sound or sounding ; the actualization of the

1 The one is the condition of the other.

2 That is, in a potential condition or a condition to be acted upon.

bk. in. chap. ii. SENSE-PERCEPTION 101

hearing organ is audition or hearing. For hearing is twofold and sound is twofold, and the same statement applies to other senses and sense-objects. In some instances the two have a distinct name, as e.g. hearing 8 and sounding ; in other instances one of the two is nameless. For the actualization of sight is called seeing, but the actualization of colour has no name ; the actual- ization of the organ of taste is called tasting, while the actualization of flavour is nameless. Inasmuch as 9 the actualization of the sense-object and the sense-organ is one and the same process, although the two things differ in their essential nature, it is necessary that hearing and sound, in this sense, should be both either destroyed together or preserved together ; and the same applies to flavour and taste, and to the other sense- correlates. This necessity does not, however, apply to the sense-correlates in their potential signification. On the contrary, the old naturalists were wrong here, ; \^ ju-uC~1 L^. supposing, as they did, that neither white nor black has : existence apart from sight, nor flavour apart from taste.1 In one way they were right and in another wrong. For i'o owing to the fact that sense and sense-object have a twofold signification, namely that of potentiality and that of actuality, their dictum was applicable to the one meaning, but not to the other. They applied it, however, 1 1 to things absolutely which are not predicated absolutely.

*By the old naturalists are probably meant Empedocles, Democritus, and the Protagoreans (Philoponus Comment, ad 426a 22. Ed. Berl. Ac. p. 475). Democritus distinguishes between the primary and secondary qualities of things, referring the latter (e.g. colour, flavour, etc.) to the perceiving agent, and the former (e.g. weight, density, etc.) to the object. Cf. Theophrastus, De sensu, 63.

102 ARISTOTLE 8 PSYCHOLOGY deanima

If harmony is voice of a certain kind, and if voice and hearing are in a sense one and the same, and in another sense not one and the same, and if, further,

12 harmony is a relation of parts, hearing must likewise be a relation of parts. It is for this reason ([i.e. because sensation is a kind of proportion]) that every excessive stimulus, whether acute or grave, disturbs hearing. In like manner the sense of taste is disturbed by excessive

426 b flavours, the sense of sight by extremely glaring or extremely faint colours, smell by excessive odours,

13 whether cloying or acrid. Consequently, qualities are agreeable when, pure and unmixed, they are reduced to proportion, as e.g. the pungent, sweet, or saline, or in the domain of touch, the warm and cool. It is then that properties are pleasant. In general, the mixed, rather than the acute1 or grave alone, is harmony. And sensation isproportion. Excessive stimuli either produce pain or pervert the organ.

14 Every sense is directed to its own peculiar sense- object ; it is given in the sense-organ as such, and it distinguishes the different qualities in its appointed sense-object, as e.g. white and black in the case of sight, sweet and bitter in the case of taste. And the same can be said of other senses. Now inasmuch as we distinguish white, sweet, and every sense-quality by its relation to a particular sense, by what instrument do we

15 perceive that these qualities differ from one another? We must do so by means of sensation, for they are sense- qualities. Is it not plain that the flesh is not the final organ of sense ? For the judging subject would then

1 Acute and grave are here used generically for extremes.

bk. in. chap. ii. THE ' COMMON SENSE ' 103

necessarily distinguish an object by contact. Neither is it possible by means of the distinct senses to judge that sweet is different from white, but it is necessary that both these qualities be cognized by some one faculty ; otherwise it would be like my perceiving one thing and you another, and so proving that they are different. A 16 single faculty must, therefore, say that they are different. For the sweet is actually different from the white. One and the same faculty, then, must affirm this. And as this faculty affirms, so do thought and perception agree. It is clear that we cannot judge of distinct qualities by different senses, and we can conclude from this that we cannot judge of them at distinct intervals of time. For it is one and the same principle in us which says that 17 the good is different from the bad. Further, it says that they are different and distinct at the moment when this affirmation is made. And when is not used here in an accidental sense, by which I mean : when does not apply merely to the time of the affirmation, e.g. I say now that it is different, but it applies also to the thing affirmed, I say that it is different now, i.e. the time applies to the assertion and thing coincidently. So the two elements 18 here are inseparable, and are given in an indivisible moment of time. It is impossible for the same thing or an indivisible entity to undergo opposite processes simul- taneously and in an indivisible moment of time. For if sweetness stimulates sensation or thought in one way, then bitter stimulates it in an opposite way and white- 427 a ness in some other way. Is, then, the judging principle1 something at once numerically indivisible and inseparable, 19

1 The judging principle is the 'common sense.'

104 aristotle's psychology dbanima

yet separable in the mode of its existence ? There is a sense, then, in which as divisible it perceives the divisible, and a sense in which as indivisible it perceives the indi- visible. For in its significant being it is divisible, but spatially and numerically it is indivisible. Or is this

20 not possible ? Potentially, indeed, one and the same indivisible thing may contain opposite properties, but not m^actuality ; in its realized self it is separate, and it is impossible for a thing to be at the same moment both black and white. So that it is not possible for even the forms of experience to undergo these opposites, if sensation and thought be such forms.1 Rather the case here is similar to what some call a point, which is divisible or

21 indivisible, as one regards it in its single or dual nature.2 In so far as it is indivisible, the judging principle is one and coincident with perception ; in so far as it is divisible, it is not one, for it employs twice and simultaneously the same mark. In so far as it employs a terminal mark as two, it distinguishes two things, and these are separable for it as a separable faculty.3 In so far as it regards the point as one, it judges singly and coincidently with perception.

In this way, then, let us state our definition of the principle by virtue of which we say that animals are sentient beings.

1 By the law of contradiction. Cf. Met. 10636 19 ; Cat. 126 10.

2 That is, as a single thing, or as the beginning of one line and the end of another.

:{In so far as the mind looks at this single thing from two stand- points, as beginning and end, it acts in a way distinct from perception ; in so far as it looks at it as a single object, apart from relations, it coin- cides with the act of perception.

CHAPTER III.

Inasmuch as the soul is defined mainly by means of two attributes, namely by locomotion on the one hand and by thought, judgment, and sensation on the other, it is supposed that thought and reflexion are a kind of sensation (for in both instances the soul discriminates and cognizes some reality), and even the old writers tell us that reflexion and sensation are identical, as e.g. Empedocles, who said : " Wisdom groweth in man in the face of a present object " ; and in another verse : " Hence is given unto them the power of reflecting ever and anon on diverse things " ; and the words of Homer have the 2 same meaning : " Such is the mind." For all of these ancient writers regard thought as something somatic, like sensation, and believe that both in sensation and thought like is apprehended by like, as we said in the beginning of this treatise.1 They should at the same 3 time have spoken of error, for to animals this is more 427/; natural than truth, and their souls pass most of their existence in error. According to this theory, as some 4 hold, either all phenomena must be true or else error

1 De. an. 4046 10 ff. 105

106

ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY

DE ANIMA

)C~*

consists in the contact of the unlike, for this is the opinion that is opposed to the cognition of like by like. Further, in this case error and knowledge of opposites seem to be identical. That sensation and reflexion, therefore, are not identical is evident. For all animals 5 share in the one, but few only in the other. Neither is thought,1 in which right and wrong are determined, i.e. right in the sense of pmc^^l_judgmeat, scientific knowledge, and true opinion, and wrong in the sense of the opposite of these not identical with sensation.

thought in this signification is For sensation when

applied to its own_peculiar objects is always true, and is inherent in all animals; but it is possible for discursive thought to be false, and it is found in no animal which is not also endowed with reason. Imagination, too, is different from sensation and discursive thought. At the same time, it is true that imagination is impossible without sensation, and conceptual thought, in turn, is impossible

6 without imagination. That thought and conception, how- ever, are not one and the same is evident. For imagina- tion is under our control, and can be stimulated when we wish (for it is possible to call up before our eyes an imaginary object, as one employs images in the art of mnemonics). Conception, on the other hand, is not

7 under our control. For it must be either false or true. Furthermore, when we conceive that something is terrible

1 ±$oe?v is used here as genus, of which (ppovrjais, tVicr?^?;, and 56£a dXrjdrjs are species. Thought is called (ppovr)<ns (prudence) when directed to a practical end, iTriaTrj/xr] (scientific knoioledge) when it is theoretical and the conclusion is demonstrable, 56£a &\T)6r)s (right opinion) when the conclusion is not reached by scientific procedure or is not demonstrable and yet is true.

BK. III. CHAP. III.

IMAGINATION

107

or fearful, we have at once a corresponding feeling, and the same may be said of what inspires courage. But in the case of imagination we are in the same condition as if we were to place a terrible or a courage-inspiring object before us in a picture. In conception itself there are distinct forms, such as knowledge, opinion, reflexion, and their opposites, concerning whose different meanings we shall speak later.

Since thinking differs from sense-perception, and in 8 one signification appears to be imagination and in another signification conception, we must proceed to the treat- ment of the latter, after we have defined imagination. 9 If imagination means the power whereby what we call a 428 a phantasm is awakened in us, and if our use of language here is not merely metaphorical, then imagination is one of those faculties or mental forces in us by virtue of which we judge and are capable of truth and error. And these faculties include sensation, opinion, scientific knowledge, and reasoning. That imagination is not to be con- founded with sense-perception is plain from the following 10 considerations. Sensation is either a mere power or a distinct act, like sight and seeing, but imagination is present when neither of these conditions is realized, viz. in the phantasms of dreams. Again, sensation is always present, but this is not true of imagination. If in reality it were identical with sensation, then all animals would have imagination. This does not seem to be the fact, as we find in the case of the ant, the bee, and the worm. Again, sensations are always true, while imaginations are n for the most part false. In the next place, we do not say when we are accurately observing a sense-object, that

106 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

consists in the contact of the unlike, for this is the opinion that is opposed to the cognition of like by like. Further, in this case error and knowledge of opposites seem to be identical. That sensation and reflexion, therefore, are not identical is evident. For all animals

5 share in the one, but few only in the other. Neither is thought,1 in which right and wrong are determined,

v/ i.e. right in the sense of practical judgment, scientific knowledge, and true opinion, and wrong in the sense of the opposite of these, thought in this signification is not identical with sensation. For sensation when applied to its own peculiar objects is always true, and is inherent in all animals: but it is possible for discursive thought to be false, and it is found in no animal which is not also endowed with reason. Imagination, too, is different from sensation and discursive thought. At the same time, it is true that imagination is impossible without sensation, and conceptual thought, in turn, is impossible

6 without imagination. That thought and conception, how- ever, are not one and the same is evident. For imagina- tion is under our control, and can be stimulated when we wish (for it is possible to call up before our eyes an imaginary object, as one employs images in the art of mnemonics). Conception, on the other hand, is not

7 under our control. For it must be either false or true. Furthermore, when we conceive that something is terrible

] Noely is used here as genus, of which ^/aov^crts, eVicT??/^, and 56£a aXrjdrjs are species. Thought is called (ppovrjaLs (prudence) when directed to a practical end, €7riaTr)fXT] (scientific knowledge) when it is theoretical and the conclusion is demonstrable, 56i-a d\r]d7js (right opinion) when the conclusion is not reached by scientific procedure or is not demonstrable and yet is true.

bk. in. chap. in. IMAGINATION 107

or fearful, we have at once a corresponding feeling, and the same may be said of what inspires courage. But in the case of imagination we are in the same condition as if we were to place a terrible or a courage-inspiring object before us in a picture. In conception itself there are distinct forms, such as knowledge, opinion, reflexion, and their opposites, concerning whose different meanings we shall speak later.

Since thinking differs from sense-perception, and in 8 one signification appears to be imagination and in another signification conception, we must proceed to the treat- ment of the latter, after we have defined imagination. 9 If imagination means the power whereby what we call a 428 a phantasm is awakened in us, and if our use of language here is not merely metaphorical, then imagination is one of those faculties or mental forces in us by virtue of which we judge and are capable of truth and error. And these faculties include sensation, opinion, scientific knowledge, and reasoning. That imagination is not to be con- founded with sense-perception is plain from the following 10 considerations. Sensation is either a mere power or a distinct act, like sight and seeing, but imagination is present when neither of these conditions is realized, viz. in the phantasms of dreams. Again, sensation is always present, but this is not true of imagination. If in reality it were identical with sensation, then all animals would have imagination. This does not seem to be the fact, as we find in the case of the ant, the bee, and the worm. Again, sensations are always true, while imaginations are n for the most part false. In the next place, we do not say when we are accurately observing a sense-object, that

108 aristotle's psychology deanima

we imagine it to be a man. We say this rather when we

12 do not clearly perceive [and when the perception may be true or false], and as we said above, we see imaginary pictures even when our eyes are closed. But neither is imagination one of those faculties whose deliverances are always true, as e.g. scientific knowledge and reason. For imagination can also be false. It remains to be considered whether it is opinion, for opinion can be either

13 true or false. Opinion, however, is followed by belief (for no man can have an opinion and not believe what he opines), and none of the lower animals possesses belief, although imagination is found in many of them. [Again, every opinion is followed by belief, as belief is followed by persuasion, and persuasion by reason. Now, some of the lower animals have imagination, but none of them

14 have reason.] It is plain, then, that imagination is not opinion combined with sensation, nor mediated by sensa- tion, nor a complex of opinion and sensation, and, for the same reason, it is clear that opinion has for its object nothing else than what sensation has for its object. I mean e.g. that imagination is the complex of an opinion of whiteness and a sensation of whiteness, and not the complex of an opinion of goodness and a sensation of

428 £ whiteness. To imagine, therefore, is to opine what, 5 strictly regarded, is a sense-object. Again, there are false appearances when we have correct conceptions, as, e.g. in the case of the sun which appears to be a foot in diameter, whereas we believe it to be larger than the inhabited earth. The consequence is that we must either have thrown aside our true opinion which we held, without the thing having changed and without any for-

bk. in. chap. in. IMAGINATION AND TRUTH 109

getfulness or change of conviction on our part ; or if one still holds it, it is necessary that the same opinion be both true and false. But an opinion has become false in a 16 case where an object, without our knowing it, has changed. Imagination, then, is not one of these faculties 17 nor a derivative of them.

Since one thins; when moved can communicate motion to another, and since imagination is held to be a form of motion which does not come into existence without sense-perception, but only in sentient creatures or in reference to objects to which sensation applies, and since motion is produced by the action of sense-perception, and thisln^tTdnliiust be equal to the strength of the sensa- tion, one can affirm that the motion of imagination would never be possible without sensation nor could it take place in non-sentient creatures. Further, the one who experiences it can act and be acted upon in many ways, and one's experiences may be true or false. This 18 truth or falsehood is due to the following causes. Sense- perception is true when it concerns its own peculiar objects; at any rate, there is involved in this case, the least possible amount of error. In the second place, sense- perception may concern the accidental, and here error begins to be possible. One is not mistaken in saying that a thing is white, but if one says the white object is this or that particular thing, error arises. In the third place, 19 error applies to common properties and concomitants of the accidental, in which peculiar properties are involved. I mean e.g. motion and magnitude, which are accidental properties of sensible objects, and concerning which we are especially liable to error in sense-perception. The

no aristotle's psychology deanima

motion set up by the activity of sensation will differ in

20 terms of the three following forms of sense-perception. The first movement is when the sense-perception continues present, and this is true ; the other two may be false whether the object is present or withdrawn, but are especially liable to error when the sense-object is removed.

If imagination contains nothing but the elements

429^ named and is what we have described it to be, it would

be a movement stimulated by actualized sense-perception.

21 Since sight is our principal sense, imagination * has

1 The words (pavraaia and (pdos are derived from cognate roots ((pav and (paF) and (paiveadai and (pavraaia are etymologically akin. Aristotle's statement that the one is derived from the other is not strictly correct. It has been shown that imagination is not atadyais (sensation), nor vovs (reason), nor kinarrifxr] (scientific knowledge), nor 56£a (opinion). It originates, however, in the sensus communis and is a movement set up there by a past sensation. A sensation when past may leave an after- effect in the sense-organ which again, unless some greater or cross - stimulus inhibits it, may pass to the heart (the organ of the ' common sense ') and there be revived as a pictorial image or phantasm, the real object being no longer present. This revival of a sense-image is imagination or phantasy ((pavraaia), and the image thus reproduced is a phantasm ((pavraa/xa). Sensation, therefore, is a prerequisite of im- agination, although the revival of the residual image of sense is emancipated from the action of the sense-organ itself. Aristotle dis- tinguishes imagination from sensation : ( 1 ) imagination is a function of the internal or ' common sense ' (De mem. 450a 10), sensation is a process of the external sense ; (2) imagination may be active in sleep, when the senses are inactive, or when the eye is closed one may have visual imagination (428a 16) ; (3) sensations, as such, are true, while imagina- tions are in large part false ; (4) sensation is possessed by all animals, imagination by certain ones only (428a 10). Again, imagination is distinct from reason (vovs) and scientific knowledge (e-marrifxT)), for (1) both the latter proceed by necessary steps and are consequently true, while imagination is sometimes true and sometimes false (42Sa 18) ; (2) the steps in rational or scientific knowledge are not in our control, they follow from inherent necessity, while the pictures of imagination are arbitrary (4276 18). Further, imagination is distinct from opinion

bk. in. chap. in. IMAGINATION AND LIGHT 111

derived its name from light, because sight is impossible without light. Because images persist and resemble sense-perceptions, animals regulate their actions to a large degree by imagination, some of them because they are incapable of reason, as the lower brutes, others because reason is sometimes veiled by passion, disease, or sleep, as is the case amongst men. Concerning imagination, what its nature is and what end it subserves, let the foregoing suffice.

(S6£a) : (1) opinion is accompanied by belief, which is not true of imagination ; (2) we may have a correct opinion about a thing, but our imagination about the same thing may be quite at variance with the opinion (4286 2). Further, it is not a combination of opinion and sensation as held by Plato (Soph. 264b, (rtififu&s aladrjcrews nai o6£t?s), because opinion and imagination may contradict, and consequently, in this case, must exclude, each other.

When the image is recognized as that of an object perceived in the past, with a consciousness of time, the imagination is then termed memory (fxv7j/j.r)) and the image is fivrjfjLovevfxa. If the reproduction of the image is conscious and deliberate, the act is recollection (cbd/^crts). Inasmuch as the latter act requires reflection, only man is endowed with it, although memory is shared by the brutes (De mem. 453a 6 ff).

There is another form of imagination which one may call the general- izing imagination, and which Aristotle regards as the source of the images that accompany conceptual thought. He says there is no thought without an image (403a 8, 431a 16). As sensation is to the imagination, so is the imagination to thought (431a 14). Residual images are, therefore, the intermediary links between sensation or sense-perception and thought. Regarded as after-sensation, imagina- tion is called (pavracria aladrjTLKT) ; regarded as the prerequisite of thought, it is called cpavraaia XoyiariKrj (4336 29). Imagination is a weak or spent sensation (aiad-qo-is aadev-qs, Rhet. 1370a 28) or in Hobbes' language a "decayed sensation." Cf. Freudenthal, Ueber den Begriff des Wortes (pavraala p. 24.

The imagination in its reproductive function is the source of memory, recollection, and the association of ideas ; in its productive or con- structive function, it is the origin of fancies and distorted pictures in dreams, fever, and melancholia. Without it language would be im- possible (4206 32), and it gives clearness to conceptual thought by clothing this in the schemata of sense (427a 16 ; 4316 4 ; 432a 9).

CHAPTEE IV.

Regarding that part of the soul by virtue of which one knows and reflects, whether it be a distinct part or whether it be distinct only notionally and not really, we have now to consider what its differential mark is, and by what process thinking is exercised. If thinking is like sense-perception, it would be either a kind of impression made by the object of cognition or some analogous

2 process. It must, then, be impassive and yet receptive of the form,1 and in its nature potentially like to the object of thought without being this object ; and as the sense-organ is related to the object of sense, in a similar

3 way thought must be related to the object of thought. Reason must, therefore, be unmixed, as Anaxagoras says, since it thinks everything, in order that it may rule, i.e. in order that it may know.2 It is the nature of thought

1 Sensation is described by Aristotle as the receptivity of the form or idea of a sensible thing without its matter {De an. ii. 12, 424a 18, beKTLKov t&v aicrdrjruv el8&v avev ttjs iiX?7s).

2 This interpretation of Anaxagoras is regarded by Burnet {Early Greek Philos. p. 283 fr. 6 and 293, note) as unhistorical. He thinks the power of Nous to ' rule ' means only the power to move and direct (Kvfiepvav). Aristotle himself gives precisely Burnet's interpretation of the Anaxagorean Nous in Phys. 2566 25 (/a^crews apxw ; Plato,

112

4

_ yvut^ La^«^

bk. in. ch. iv. THEORY OF REASON 113

to preclude and restrain the element that is foreign and adjacently seen. Its nature is, therefore, exclusively 4 potentiality. What we call reasonjn the soul (by reason I mean the instrument by which the soul thinks and forms conceptions) is, prior to the exercise of thought, no reality at all. It is, therefore, wrong to suppose that reason itself is mixed with the body. For in that case it would have certain qualitative distinctions such as warm or cold, or it would be a sort of instrument, like a sense-organ. But in point of fact it is nothing of the kind. Certain writers1 5 have happily called the soul the place of ideas, only this description does not apply to the soul as a whole, but merely to the power of thought, and it applies to ideas only in the sense of potentiality, and not of actuality."

Cratylux, 413c), and according to De an. 4056 22 and 4296 23, he would seem to have been unable to find any epistemological use for this Nous. The interpretation of Aristotle in the passage before us can, however, very well be a correct deduction from the principle of Anaxagoras, viz. that in order to rule and arrange all things best, the reason must also know all things, and it is not unlikely that Anaxagoras even made explicit mention of this ; it is certainly implied in the fragments. " Nous is the subtlest of all things and the purest [i.e. the least mixed], and it knows all and has all power " (fr. 123, Burnet p. 2S3). By virtue of its subtle nature, and its being unmixed with the elements (I am not concerned here with the moot question of its incorporeality), the Nous is able to penetrate everywhere, and so has the most 'far-seeing knowledge as well as most wide-reaching power. Nous must then be unmixed and pure to be almighty and all-knowing, and consequently the commentary of Aris- totle seems a legitimate construction to put upon Anaxagoras (cf. Zeller, Phil. d. Gr. Vol. I. 4th ed. p. 887 ; Trendelenburg, De an. 2nd ed. p. 385). In fact, it was precisely the element of knowing that was the important factor in the Anaxagorean Nous, as Orderer of the All.

1 Plato and the Academy.

2 Potentially, reason is that which becomes thought (there are no innate ideas) ; but the actual reason is identical with the actual thought, and in thinking its ideas the reason thinks itself (4296 9).

H

\w

iUUu4

114 aristotle's psychology deanima

It is evident from the sense-organ and from the nature of sensation, that the term impassivity is employed in a

6 different meaning in sensation and in thinking. For sense-perception cannot take place when the sense-

429 £ stimulus is excessive, as one does not hear sound in the midst of loud noises, neither can one see nor smell in the midst of excessively bright colours and strong odours. On the other hand, when the mind thinks a very profound thought, it thinks not in a lesser but in a deeper degree minor details. For the power of sensation is not independent of the body, while the mind is separable.

7 When reason becomes its several objects in the sense in which an actually learned man is said to be learned (and this takes place when he can exercise knowledge through his own agency), even then reason is in a certain sense potential, although this potentiality differs from that which preceded learning and discovery. In the latter

8 case, potentiality signifies the capacity of thinking itself.

There is a difference between concrete magnitude and the ultimate nature of magnitude, between water and the ultimate nature of water (the same distinction can be applied to other instances, though not to all, for in some cases they are identical). Concrete flesh and the ultimate nature of flesh one judges either by a different and distinct faculty or by the same faculty under differing conditions. Flesh is not separate from

9 matter, but like a snub-nose, it is a particular thing in a given something. By means of a sense-organ one discriminates heat and cold and those qualities of which flesh is a sort of register. On the other hand, reason judges of the essential nature of flesh either by a

bk. in. ch. iv. ABSTRACT THOUGHT 115

different and distinct faculty, or in the way in which a bent line is related to itself when straightened.1 We refer the straight line as we do the snub-nose to abstract entities,2 for they are both associated with the continuous. But the essential notion of a thing, if straightness and the straight line are different (and they are two things), is apprehended by a different power. The mind, then, judges in the two cases by means of a different power or by means of a power differently 10 conditioned. In a word, therefore, as there are things abstracted from matter, so there are things that concern the reason. If the mind is simple and impassive, and has nothing in common with anything else, as Anax- agoras 3 says, and if thinking means to be somehow 1 1

JThe bent line represents the concrete, distorted things of sense and the straight line the pure notion, and the two things correspond, apparently, to the distinction made above between to aapd dvai and <rap%, etc. Cf. Kirchmann and Wallace ad loc. Teichmuller's explana- tion (quoted by Wallace) of the bent line as representing reason, although ingenious, is not helpful here.

2 These conceptions belong to mathematical notions and figures, and are abstract when contrasted with a material thing, but concrete when contrasted with the essential notion. Mathematical ideas (including 1 snub-nose ' as a figure) occupy a middle place in their degree of abstraction between the pure notion and a sense-object. The mathe- matical and the sense-object both belong to the continuous or the extended in space {fxera crvvexovs). Cf. Phys. 194a 10; De an. 4316 15. Mathematical entities are separable from matter only in logical con- ception. Metaph. 1026a 7 ff. ; 1061a 28 ff.

3Anaxagoras gave no detailed account (as far as the fragments go) of the way in which we get our ideas of things, beyond the state- ment that the senses are too weak to discover the ultimate nature of reality, and that we know the existence of the 6/icuo/^peicu (as his successors called the original homogeneous seeds or particles of things) only by processes of reason. This latter by its subtle and pure nature is capable of penetrating everywhere {vid. note 2, p. 112) and making the finest distinctions. In his theory of sensation Anaxagoras says we

116 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

impressed, one might ask, How will thought be possible ? For it is only in so far as there is something common to two things that the one appears to act and the other to be acted upon. A further question might be raised, viz. whether the mind itself is the object of thought. If it is, mind will then either be found in other things, unless it is the object of thought in some way different from other objects, and unless the object of thought is a specific and single thing ; else it will have a mixed composition which makes it like other

12 things, the object of thought. According to our former definition, ' to be affected in reference to a common element/ means that the mind is potentially the object of thought, though perhaps not actually so until thought takes place. It must be that the case here is similar to that

430 a of the tablet on which nothing has been actually written. This is what takes place in the case of mind, and it is

13 the object of thought as other things are. Where entities are without matter, the subject and object of thought n *ft_ are identical. Speculative thought and the thing specu- latively known are one and the same. The reason why thought is noTcbntinuous must be investigated. On the other hand, when entities are material they are severally the object of thought only potentially ; mind is not an element in them (for reason is the potentiality

xT J of such objects in abstraction from their matter), whereas \^° (\ it is in the reason itself that the object of thought will

I be found. x . \> . / J-

do not apprehend like by like (Empedocles), but unlike by unlike, e.g. heat by cold, etc. Cf. Zeller Phil. d. Or. Vol. I. 4th ed. p. 908.

"):

CHAPTER V.

In the whole of nature there is on the one hand a material factor1 for every kind of thing (and this is what all things are in their potentiality), and another factor which is causative and productive of things, by virtue of its making all objects, as art stands related to the matter it employs. These distinctions must also hold good when applied to the soul. Reason is of such^ character that on the one hand it becomes all things, 1 and on the other creates all things, in this respect resembling a property like light. For light in a certain sense converts potential into actual colours, and reason, in the present meaning, is separate, impassive, and unmixed, being in its essential nature an energizing force. Now, action is always higher than passion and causal force higher than matter. Actual knowledge is identical 3 with its_ object. Potential knowledge, on the other hand, pre-exists in the individual ; regarded absolutely it does

1 ' Material factor ' does not necessarily mean a thing constituted of crass matter, but refers to the metaphysical distinction between ' form ' and 'matter,' which in other terms are ' actuality' and 'potentiality.'. In this meaning sensations as containing the potentiality of ideas are their 'matter.'

117

<\

^J***

>juj>

118 aristotle's psychology deanima

v l-^K*^ not so pre-exist. For mind does not at one moment think and at another not. In its separated state alone

~*T

reason is what it is, immortal and eternal. We have no memory of it, because this part of reason is impassive. The passive reason, on the other hand, is perishable, and without (ifothere can be no thought.2

2 Vid. Introduction, Chap) viii., and The Classical Review, Vol. VI. (1892), pp. 298 ff.

CHAPTER VI.

When thought is applied to indivisible terms, error does not arise. Where error and truth are both found is just in the combination of thoughts into a sort of unity. Empedocles1 e.g. says; "Wherefore the heads of many creatures sprang into life without necks," and later on by the attraction of Friendship they were joined to- gether. So, too, these disjoined ideas are combined 2 together by the reason, as e.g. the ideas of the incom- mensurable and the diagonal. If the ideas refer to the past or to the future, the element of time is added in 430 £ the mind and combined with the ideas. Error is always due to the combination. For even in the case where one might think the white not to be white, one has made the combination of the ' not- white.' 2 It is further possible to apply disjunction to everything. It is not 3 only possible for the statement ' Cleon is fair ' to be true or false, but this may be applied to the past or to the future. The unifying principle is in every case the

1 Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, pp. 226, 229. Ritter and Preller Hist. Phil. Gr. p 140a.

2 Omit </ccu> (\evKoi>y which Biehl adopts from Cod. t and Roper's conjecture against the better reading of all the other Codd.

119

120 aristotle's psychology deanima

reason.1 Since the simple or indivisible may be looked at from two standpoints, viz. either as potentiality or as actuality, there is nothing to prevent the mind from thinking the indivisible when it thinks of extension (which in its actual state is indivisible), and when it thinks it in an indivisible moment of time. For divisibility and indivisibility apply to time just as they

4 do to length. It is, therefore, impossible to say what the mind thinks in each half of a time-division. For the half does not exist, except in potentiality, if the division has not been made. But in the act of thinking each half separately, the mind divides the time also, and then the time corresponds in its division to the two lengths.2 If, however, the mind thinks the object as a whole composed of two halves, it does this also with regard to time in its relation to the

5 two halves.

That which is not quantitatively but only notionally indivisible, the mind thinks in an indivisible time and by an indivisible power of the soul. It does this, how- ever, accidentally and not in so far as the factors of thought and time are divisible, but in so far as they are indivisible. And there is also in these cases an objective factor which is indivisible, although perhaps not

6 a separate entity, that gives a unity to time and exten- sion. And this is likewise true of everything that is continuous, whether in time or space. The point and everything obtained by division, and whatever (like a point) is no longer divisible, are explicable in terms of

1 The principle that combines or unifies terms into judgments.

2 And the single length is then a unit and no longer a half.

bk. in. ch. vi. THOUGHT AND TRUTH 121

privation.1 Similar reasoning may be applied to other cases, as e.g. the way in which we know evil or black. For we know them somehow or other by means of their contraries. But the knowing mind must be these things potentially, and they must be reduced to unity in the mind itself. If, however, in the case of any causal 7 principle there is no opposite, then it knows itself, and is in actuality and is separate. A predication, as e.g. an affirmation, asserts something of something else, and is in every instance either true or false. This does not apply to the mind always, but when the mind asserts what a thing is in its essential nature and not what attaches to something as a predicate, then it is true. And just as sight is true when it concerns its own proper object, and on the other hand the opinion that a visible white object is or is not a man may not always be true, so it is with all immaterial entities.

1 As privation of extension.

CHAPTER VII.

431 a Actual knowledge is identical with its object. Potential knowledge is earlier in time in the individual, but taken absolutely it is not earlier in time. For all becoming proceeds from actual being. The sensible object appears to convert the potentially sensitive organ into an actually sensitive organ. For the sense-organ itself is not affected, and undergoes no change. That is the reason why we 2 have here to do with a form of motion different from motion in the ordinary sense. Motion was denned as a realization of the incomplete, but motion, absolutely regarded, is a different kind of activity, viz. the activity of the perfected thing. Mere sense-perception, then, is like a simple expression or a simple thought ; when, however, the sensation is pleasant * or painful, and thus corresponds to affirmation or negation, the thing is pursued or avoided. To feel pleasure or pain signifies to experience an activity in a mean function of the sense-organ relative to good or bad as such. Avoidance

1 When the simple term or thought is converted into a judgment, it takes the form (intellectually) of affirmation or negation, and the form (in practice) of doing or avoiding. In the one case we have truth or error, and in the other right or wrong.

122

bk. in. ch. vii. THOUGHT AND IMAGES 123

and pursuit in their actual natures are identical, and the 3 appetitive power whereby we desire or pursue a thing is not different from the power whereby we avoid a thing. They do not differ from each other or from the sensitive faculty. Only the expression of their being is different. Images are employed by the conceptual reason as sense- presentatious are by the sentient faculty. When the mind makes an affirmation or negation touching the good or bad, it avoids the one and pursues the other. The soul, therefore, never thinks without the use of images. 4 As the air produces such or such an effect on the pupil of the eye, and the pupil in turn produces another effect (the same illustration may be applied to hearing), and yet the ultimate interpreter or medium of sensation is a single power whose being is expressed in several ways, ([so it is with images1 in reference to thought.]) As to the faculty by which we discriminate sweet and warm, although the problem has been mentioned above, it must be again discussed as follows. There is some unitary principle, and this unitary principle has the 5 character of an ultimate term. Its deliverances are reduced to unity by means of comparison and numerical statement, and are related to each other as the outward things are related to each other. The question as to how the mind judges like qualities, does not differ from the question as to how it judges opposite qualities such

1 As the air is a condition of sensation, so are images conditions of thought. The illustration is not a very happy one, but the meaning appears to be that as there is an unitary principle of sense which elaborates its varied materials into a whole, so there is an unitary principle of thought which reduces these images (ultimately drawn from sense) to the form of connected concepts.

124 aristotle's psychology deanima

6 as white and black. Let A, the objectively white, be related to B, the objectively black, as the idea C is related to the idea D, or it may be stated conversely. Now, if the ideas CD attach to a certain thing, they will be related to each other ([in the concept]) just as AB are related to each other, they will form one and the same thing, though not identical in mode of being; and the former combination (CD) is analogous to the latter (AB) \ The same reasoning holds in case one were

431 b to apply A to a sweet object, and B to a white

7 object.

The reasoning mind thinks its ideas in the form of images; and as the mind determines the objects it should pursue or avoid in terms of these images, even in the absence of sensation, so it is stimulated to action when occupied with them. For example, when one sees that a beacon is lighted, and observes by means of the ' common sense ' that it is in motion,2 one comprehends that an

8 enemy is near. Sometimes by means of the images or ideas in the soul the mind reasons as a seeing person, and takes thought for the future in terms of things before one's eyes. When the mind there in its world of images says that a thing is pleasant or painful, here in the world of things it pursues or avoids, in a word, it acts. Apart from action the true and false belong to the same category as the good and bad. They differ, however, in

1 The illustration appears to mean that just as qualities are combined in a given thing and form an unitary object, so subjectively they form a single and unitary concept. They are identical in signifi- cance, though different in their mode of being.

2 Motion is one of the koivol alad-qTa and as such is not discerned by any individual sense but only by the 'common sense.'

bk. in. ch. vii. THOUGHT AND ITS OBJECT 125

the absolute character of the one and the relative character of the other.1

The mind thinks abstractions, as e.g. when it thinks 9 the snub-nosed, which in one sense is a snub-nose, and in another sense, if one thinks it actually, one would think it as a curvature without the flesh in which the curvature 10 is found. So too with mathematical figures, though in actuality not separate from bodies, the mind thinks them as separated, when it thinks them. In a word the mind is the thing when actually thinking it.2 Whether or not it is possible to think any abstraction when the mind itself is not separate from magnitude, must be investi- gated later.

1 The true and false are universally valid, regarded merely from the standpoint of cognition, but when regarded in the light of wrong and right they are relative to the individual. Or the passage may have another significance, viz. the notions of good and bad affect our wills and stimulate to action only when they are referred to particular objects. Vid. Kirchmann, p. 183.

2 In the act of thinking, subject and object are identical ; the think- ing mind is the idea thought.

CHAPTER VIII.

Looking at the main features of what has been said of the soul, let us reiterate the statement that it is in a sense all reality. For everything, whether sensible or intelligible, is psychical ; intelligible objects are in a sense knowledge, and sensible realities are sensations. How this is possible remains to be investigated. Con-

2 ceptual knowledge and sense-perception are each divided into two kinds, corresponding to their objects; potential knowledge corresponding to potential objects, and actual to actual. The sensitive and conceptual powers of the soul are, potentially regarded, the objective things, viz. the intelligible and the sensible. The soul, then, must be

3 either the things themselves or their form. It cannot, of course, be the things themselves. For a stone is not in the soul, but the form or idea of the stone. Consequently,

432a the soul is to be thought of as a hand; for a hand1 is the instrument of all instruments, and the reason is the form of all forms and sensation m the form of all sensible

4 realities. Since, however, there is no object, as is supposed,

1 As the hand is the master instrument, so the soul is the master interpreter and reduces all things to a significant form.

126

BK. III. CH. VIII.

IDEAS AND IMAGES

127

apart from sensible magnitudes,1 it follows that intelli- gible objects, -Jmean_abstraciions, as we call them, on the one hand, and the qualities and conditions of the sensibles, on the other, must be sought^ in the sense-forms. For 5 this reason, also, it would be impossible for one to learn anything or understand anything without sense-perception, and when one contemplates a thing, one is forced to con- template it in conjunction with an internal image. These, images are like sense-presentations, with the exception that they are without matter. Imagination is different from 6 affirmation and negation; for the true and the false are the combination of ideas into a judgment.2 In what way are the primary ideas 3 to be distinguished from imagination ? Or is it true that these 4 ideas are not themselves images, yet they cannot be produced independently of images ?

1 The world of magnitudes and objects in space are mediated to the imagination by means of sense-presentations (aiadrj/jLara), and to thought by means of sense-representations or images {(pavr da fxara).

2 Images ((pavrdafiara) of the productive imagination, although they may correspond to no reality, yet are not, strictly speaking, either true or false. Truth and falsehood belong only to judgments or to an image when something is predicated of it.

3 The primary ideas (irpCora vo^fiara) refer to our highest abstractions. Although these notions are not (pavrda/xara, their derivation is dependent on such images.

4 Read ravra (Torstrik) instead of tZLWo..

CHAPTER VIII.

Looking at the main features of what has been said of the soul, let us reiterate the statement that it is in a sense all reality. For everything, whether sensible or intelligible, is psychical ; intelligible objects are in a sense knowledge, and sensible realities are sensations. How this is possible remains to be investigated. Con-

2 ceptual knowledge and sense-perception are each divided into two kinds, corresponding to their objects ; potential knowledge corresponding to potential objects, and actual to actual. The sensitive and conceptual powers of the soul are, potentially regarded, the objective things, viz. the intelligible and the sensible. The soul, then, must be

3 either the things themselves or their form. It cannot, of course, be the things themselves. For a stone is not in the soul, but the form or idea of the stone. Consequently,

432a the soul is to be thought of as a hand; for a hand1 is the

(instrument of all instruments, and the reason is the form of all forms and sensation ii the form of all sensible

4 realities. Since, however, there is no object, as is supposed,

1 As the hand is the master instrument, so the soul is the master interpreter and reduces all things to a significant form.

126

bk. in. ch. viii. IDEAS AND IMAGES 127

apart from sensible magnitudes,1 it follows that intelli- gible objects, -Jme^jQ_abstraciions, as we call them, on the one hand, and the qualities and conditions of the sensibles, on the other, must be sought in the sense-forms. For 5 this reason, also, it would be impossible for one to learn anything or understand anything without sense-perception, and when one contemplates a thing, one is forced to con- template it in conjunction with an internal image. The_s& images are like sense-presentations, with the exception that they are without matter. Imagination is different from 6 affirmation and negation; for the true and the false are the combination of ideas into a judgment.2 In what way are the primary ideas 3 to be distinguished from imagination ? Or is it true that these4 ideas are not themselves images, yet they cannot be produced independently of images ?

1 The world of magnitudes and objects in space are mediated to the imagination by means of sense-presentations (aicrdrifxaTa), and to thought by means of sense-representations or images {(pavrdo-fxaTa).

2 Images (<pavTd<rfxa,Ta) of the productive imagination, although they may correspond to no reality, yet are not, strictly speaking, either true or false. Truth and falsehood belong only to judgments or to an image when something is predicated of it.

3 The primary ideas (irp&To. vo^ara) refer to our highest abstractions. Although these notions are not (pavrdo-fxaTa, their derivation is dependent on such images.

4 Read ravra (Torstrik) instead of rSWa.

CHAPTER IX.

Since the soul of living beings is defined in terms of two powers, viz. the power of judgment (which is the function of thought) and the power of sensation on the one hand, and the power of locomotion on the other, let the above suffice for our treatment of sensation and thought, and let us now consider the moving principle and ask what part of the soul it may be. The further question arises whether it is an individual part of the soul and separate, either concretely or notionally, or whether it is the entire soul. If it is only a part, we must ask whether it is a peculiar part and distinct from those usually described and already mentioned here, or whether it is

2 one of these. There is a difficulty at the start con- cerning the sense in which we are to employ the term

3 ' parts ' of the soul, and concerning their number. For in a certain way they seem to be innumerable, and not merely confined to those which certain writers distin- guish, viz. reason, will, and desire,1 and others classify as rational and irrational elements. For according to the differences by which they distinguish these parts,

1 Plato, Republic 441a (XoyurriKov, dv/xoeidis, iiridvfxrjTLKdv). 128

bk. in. ch. ix. POWERS OF THE SOUL 129

there seem to be other parts that are even more distinct from each other than these, concerning which we have just now spoken, viz. the nutritive part, which is found even in plants as well as in all animals, and the sensitive part, which one could not easily classify either as irrational or as rational. Again, the power of imagination, which is 4 different in its mode of being from the others, appears to 432^ be a distinct part, but in what particular it is identical with or different from the others, is very difficult to say, if one is to regard the parts of the soul as existing inde- pendently of one another. In addition to these, there is the desiderative part, which both notionally and function- ally might be supposed to differ from all the other parts. And yet it would be absurd to sever this from 5 the others. For it is in the thinking element that volition arises, and in the irrational element we have desire and passion. But if the soul has three distinct parts, then the desiderative element must be in all of them. Moreover, the question again comes up which we 6 raised just now, viz. what is the principle in animals that produces locomotion ? One might suppose that it is the generative and nutritive powers, found in all living things, that produce the motion involved in growth and decay common to them all. The subjects of inspira- tion and expiration, sleeping and waking, must be investigated later, for all of them present great difficulties. But regarding locomotion, we must inquire what it is 7 that gives animals the power of progressive movement. It is evidently not the nutritive power, for progressive movement is always towards some end and accompanied either by some image or desire. For where there is no

130 aristotle's psychology deanima

8 desire or revulsion, there is no motion, excepting where external force is used. Further, if motion were due to the nutritive power, plants would be capable of loco- motion and would have some organic member adapted to this motion. Soo, too, it cannot be the sensitive power that is the source of motion ; for there are many animals which have sensation and yet, throughout their existence,

9 are stationary and motionless. If, then, nature creates nothing in vain, neither does she omit anything that is necessary, save in cases of deformed or imperfect beings. And such animals as we have in mind are normal and not deformed. A test of perfection is the capacity to reproduce, to reach the prime of growth, and then decline. Consequently, such animals should also have organs of movement.1

io But neither is the thinking power nor what we call reason the cause of animal motion. For the contempla- tive power does not think upon what is to be carried into execution, neither has it anything to say touching what is to be avoided or pursued, whereas motion always belongs to that which pursues or avoids an object. On

ii the' contrary, when one contemplates anything, the mind does not bid one pursue or avoid ; e.g. the fearful or pleasant is often the subject of thought, but the feeling of fear is not suggested ; the heart, however, is agitated, or if the feeling is pleasure, some other organ is stirred. 433 a More than this, even when the reason commands and intelligence tells us to avoid or to pursue a thing, motion

JIf locomotion were a function of the sensitive soul, these animals that are endowed with sensation, and are normal, would not be stationary, as some of them are (cf. note 1, p. 171), but would move.

bk. in. ch. ix. REASON AND DESIRE 131

does not follow, but one acts according to one's desire, like an intemperate man. We observe, in general, that 12 the man versed in medicine does not heal, because it is something other than science that has the power of acting according to the principles of science.1 Neither, again, is desire the dominating principle2 in this motion; for continent men, though filled with desire and appetite, do not do the things for which they lust ; on the con- trary, they follow reason.

1 It is not science, but nature, the principles and laws of whose operation are formulated by science, that heals.

2 Neither desire nor reason taken alone is the principle of action in men, but the combination of these two. Cf. 433a- 23.

CHAPTER X.

There are two powers in the soul which appear to be moving forces desire and reason, if one classifies imagina- tion as a kind of reason. For many creatures follow their imaginations contrary to rational knowledge, and in animals other than man it is not thought nor rational procedure that determines action, but imagination. Conse-

2 quently, both of these, reason and desire, can produce locomotion I mean here the reason that considers ends and is concerned with conduct.1 It differs from the theoretical reason in having a moral end. Every desire

3 aims at something. It is the final end that is the initial cause in conduct.2 So that it is reasonable to regard these two principles, viz. desire and practical reason, as motor forces. For the object of desire stimulates us, and through it reason stimulates us, because the object of desire is the main thing in the practical reason. Imagina- tion, too, when it stimulates us to action, does not do so independently of desire. The one single moving force is

1 This is the epitactic reason {(ppovrjats iwiTaKTiKr)) of the Ethics (Eth. nic. vi. 10, 2). The theoretical reason deals with necessary truth, while the practical or epitactic reason deals with the contingent or what is matter of choice.

2 The end of action is motive or starting-point.

132

BK.ni. ch.x. PSYCHOLOGY AND CONDUCT 133

the object of desire. For even if there were two moving powers, reason and desire, still they would produce movement in accordance with some common idea. As a 4 matter of fact, however, reason does not appear to produce movement independently of desire. For volition is a form of desire, and when one is prompted to action in accord- ance with reason, the action follows also in accordance with volition. But desire prompts actions in violation of reason. For appetite is a sort of desire. Reason, then, is in every case right, but desire and imagination may be right or wrong. It is, therefore, always the object of 5 desire that excites action, and this is either the good or the apparent good yet not every good, but only the good in conduct, and this practical good admits of varia- tion.

Evidently the psychical power which excites to action has the nature of desire, as we call it. In analysing 6 the elements of the soul, if one analyses and distinguishes 433 b them in terms of powers, they become very numerous, as e.g. the nutritive, sensitive, rational, deliberative, and desiclerative. For these differ from each other more than do the desiderative and spirited elements. Although desires arise which are opposed to each other, as is the 7 case when reason and appetite are opposed, it happens only in creatures endowed with a sense of time. (For reason, on account of the future, bids us resist, while desire regards the present ; the momentarily pleasant appears to it as the absolutely pleasant and the absolutely good, because it does not see the future). The moving principle, which is the desiderative faculty as such, is specifically one, though numerically several motive forces

134 aristotle's psychology deanima

may be included in it. The main element here is the object of desire (for this by being the object of thought or imagination excites movement, while it is itself unmoved).

8 There are, then, three terms to consider here, first the motor power, secondly the instrument of motion, and thirdly the object set in motion. The motor power is twofold : on the one hand, it is an unmoved element, and on the other, a moving and moved element. The unmoved element is the good to be done ; the moving and moved element is the desiderative faculty (for the desiderative faculty in so far as it desires is moved, and desire in process of realization is a form of motion) ; the object which is set in motion is the animal. The instrument by which desire effects motion, is of course the body, and consequently it must be investigated where we have to

9 do with functions which are common to the body and the soul.1 One may, however, say summarily here that motion is organic in those cases where beginning and end are one, as e.g. in a joint. For here the convex and concave are beginning and end. Therefore the one is at rest and the other in motion, and while they are notion- ally distinct, they are concretely inseparable. Everything is set in motion by push or pull, and there must be con- sequently, a fixed point, as the centre in a circle, and this is the initial point of motion.2 In a word, then, as we said before, an animal in so far as it is capable of

1 The reference is probably to the Parva Naturalia. Cf. Zeller, Aristotle, Eng. tr. vol. i. p. 89 ; Freudenthal in Rhein. Museum, N.F., Bd. 24 (1869), p. 82; Rose De Aristot. librorum ord. et auct. p. 163.

2 As in the illustration of the socket-joint and the circle, there is a part at rest from which motion proceeds and a part in motion.

10

bk. in. ch. x. FUNCTION OF DESIRE 135

desire is capable of self-movement. Desire, however, is not found apart from imagination, and all imagination is either rational or sensitive in origin, and the lower animals share in it.

Analogously, the reason is not itself in movement but is that from whicii movement proceeds. The attractive thing on the one hand, and the commanding reason or desiring mind on the other, constitute the push and pull in animal life.

CHAPTEE XI.

We must inquire also into the nature of the moving principle in those imperfect animals which possess only 434 a the sense of touch. Is it possible for them to have imagination or desire ? They appear to feel pleasure and pain, and if these are felt they must necessarily have desire also. But how could they have imagination ? Or are we to say that just as their movements are indefinite,

2 so too this power is possessed by them, only it is in- definitely developed. Imagination derived from sensation is, as we said before, found in the lower animals, but deliberative imagination is found only in those animals which are endowed with reason. For whether one shall do this or that is, of course, a matter of deliberation, and there must be some single instrument of measurement at hand (for it is the greater good that is to be pursued), and

3 so the mind is able to make a single representation out of several images. The ground for supposing that animals do not have opinion is that they do not have the faculty for drawing rational conclusions, and opinion involves this. Consequently, their desire lacks the deliberative quality. Sometimes the desire overpowers

136

bk. in. ch. xi. THE MOVING PRINCIPLE 137

the deliberative element in man and excites to action. At other times the will overpowers the desire, and again, like a ball tossed to and fro, one desire overpowers another, as in the case of intemperance. In the workings of nature the higher element always has the greater authority and is the moving power. There are, then, three forms of movement.1 The faculty of conceptual 4 thought is not moved, but remains at rest. Since we have two principles in conduct, on the one hand the general conception 2 and notion, and on the other hand the particular notion (of which the one says a man of such and such a kind shall act in such a way, and the other that this particular man and I am that particular man shall act in a given way), it is the latter notion that incites to action, but the general one does not. Or both of them combined may lead to action, although the general notion is quiescent, and the par- ticular one active.

1 There is (1) the command issuing from the unmoved reason, which acts on desire in a manner analogous to motion in the form of ' push ' ; (2) when an object stirs the desire and through the desire the reason is awakened, the case is then analogous to motion in the form of ' attraction ' or ' pull ' ; (3) the completed process terminates in an act of bodily or physical movement.

2Cf. Eth. roc. vii. 3, 6, 1147a 1-10.

CHAPTER XII.

Every living thing must have a nutritive soul in order that it may live and continue to live from birth until death. What has been born must grow, reach its complete development and decline, and this is impossible without food. A nutritive power must, therefore, be given to everything that grows and dies ; but sensation

2 is not necessary to all living things.1 Whatever has a simple body cannot be endowed with the sense of touch (neither is animal life possible without touch), and whatever is incapable of interpreting the forms of things without their matter is also incapable of touch. An animal must have sensation, if it is true that nature creates nothing in vain. For everything in the natural world exists for a purpose, or is the condition of some-

3 thing that exists for a purpose. If, then, a body which is endowed with the power of movement were deprived of sensation, it would perish and would not attain the

434 ^ end for which nature strives. For how will it nourish itself? Amongst organisms fixed to one spot, a source of food is provided for them from which they naturally

1 Vegetable life exists only in the lowest or nutritive form. 138

bk. in. ch. xii. NUTRITION AND SENSATION 139

grow. It is, however, impossible for a body that is not stationary, and is produced by generation, to have life and a thinking mind, and yet not have sensation. No more is this possible in bodies that are not produced by generation. l For to what end will they lack sensation $ 4 It must be because such lack will be better either fori their soul or body. But neither is true. For the one' will thereby think none the better, nor the other last any the longer. Consequently, no moving body has a soul that is unendowed with sensation. If, however, the body is endowed with sensation, it must be either single or mixed. The former is impossible ; for in that case 2 5 it could not have touch, and touch is necessary. That is clear from the following grounds. Since every living creature is an animated body, and every body is tangible, and tangible is that which is sensed by means of touch, it follows necessarily that the animal body must be capable of the sensation of touch, if the animal is to 6 persist in life. The other senses, such as smell, sight, and hearing, perceive through other media than the tangible body. If, however, an animal on being touched were to experience no sensation, it would have no power to avoid certain things and pursue others. And if this were the case, the animal could not survive. Therefore, taste is a kind of touch, for it is concerned with food, and food is a tangible body. Sound, colour, and smell, on 7 the other hand, furnish no nutriment and do not con- tribute to growth and decay. Consequently, taste must

1 Even the eternal and unbegotten bodies (stars) have the power of sensation. Cf. De Coelo, 285a 29, 292b 2.

2 Touch implies the duality of perceiving soul and tangible body.

140 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY deanima

be a sort of touch, because it is a sense that concerns a tangible and nutritive object. Both of these senses ([touch and taste]) are necessary to every animal, and it is evident that no animal can exist without touch. The

8 other senses exist for the sake of higher well-being 1 and are not found indiscriminately in animal species, but only in certain of them, viz. in such as are capable of pro- gressive motion, and here they are necessary, For if such an animal is to survive it must not only apprehend an object by touching it, but must be able to do this at a distance. This result would be attained if the animal were capable of sensation through a medium, and the medium were impressed and set in motion by

9 the sensible object, and if the sense-organ were in turn stimulated by the medium. Just as a body moving in space causes a transfer of energy up to a certain point, and the propelling body causes another body to become propulsive, and through the mediate term motion is continued ; and as the initial agent moves and exerts propulsion without being itself propelled, while the last body in the series suffers propulsion without exerting it and the intermediate bodies (of which there may be many),

435 a both suffer and exert it ; so it is also with the process of change ([in sensation]), excepting that here change may take place while the object continues on a single spot. For example, when one dips an object in wax, movement of the wax takes place up to the point that immersion has taken place. A stone, however, would not be moved

1 Certain creatures are endowed merely with fitness for life, while the endowment of others fits them for aesthetic and moral life (ko\o0 ZveKa £r}v), Eih. nic. 1143a 15, 1170a 16, 1180a 10 ; rod e$ hexa, De an. 4356 21 ; De sensu 437a 1.

bk. in. ch. xii. SENSATION AND WELL-BEING 141

in this way at all, while water would be moved more 10 than wax. The most mobile element, both in its power *? to receive and communicate motion, is the air, provided it is confined and is a unit. Concerning the phenomenon of the reflection of light, then, it is better to suppose that the air, in so far as it is a continuous mass (and this is the case upon every smooth surface), becomes charged with form and colour, rather than that the visual image after it has once issued from the eye is reflected back to the eye.1 Consequently, the air reacting on the eye stimu- lates it, as if the impress in the wax were to penetrate through to its opposite extremity.2

1 The reference is to Empedocles, who believed there was a dual efflux or emanation from the eye and from the object (cf. Platos Menon 76c ff., Aristot. De sensu 438a 1 ff.) and to Plato (Timaeus, 45c).

2 That is, the visual image is supposed to penetrate through the mass of air, as it were, to the opposite side and so pass into the seeing organ, just as one might conceive the seal with its impress piercing entirely through the mass of wax into something capable of receiving it on the remote side.

CHAPTEE XIII.

Evidently an animal body cannot be simple. I mean that it cannot e.g. consist simply of the element of fire or air. For without touch one cannot have any other sensation. Every body endowed with soul has the capacity of touch, as we have already said. All the other elements, excepting earth, might become organs of sensation, but all of them produce sensation by the

2 instrument of intermediary bodies. Touch, on the con- trary, appears to act by immediate contact with bodies, and hence its name, and although the other sense-organs effect sensation by means of contact, yet the contact is indirect and mediated ; whereas touch is the only sense that acts by direct contact. So then no animal body can be constituted exclusively out of such elements ([as are fitted for mediate perception]), neither can it be

3 constituted exclusively out of earth. For touch is, as it were, the mediator of all tangible things, and the sense- organ is capable of receiving not only all the various qualities that attach to earth, but also the hot and cold and all other tactual distinctions. Therefore we have no sensation in our bones, hair, and other such parts,

142

bk. in. ch. xiii. SENSE OF TOUCH 143

because they are constituted out of the element of earth. For this reason also plants have no sensation, because 435^ they are composed of earth. Without touch there can 4 be no other sensation, but the organ of touch is not composed exclusively of earth nor of any other single element. It is plain, then, that this is the only sense, the deprivation of which necessitates the death of animals. For neither is it possible for anything that is not an animal to have this sense, nor is it necessary for anything that is an animal to have any sense beyond 5 it. Therefore, other sense-qualities, such as colour, sound, and smell, do not by their excess destroy an animal ; they only destroy the sense-organ, except in some acci- dental case, as where a push or blow accompanies the sound, and when other objects are set in motion by sights and smells which, by their contact, work destruc- tion.1 Flavour, in so far as it is conjoined with a 6 tactual nature,2 works destruction by virtue of this latter. But excess in tangible qualities such as heat, cold, or hardness, destroys the animal. For the excess of every sensible quality destroys the sense-organ, so that the tangible destroys the tactual sense, and it is in terms of this that life is defined. For it has been demonstrated that without the sense of touch a living creature is an impossibility. Consequently, excess 0A7 tangible impressions not only destroys the sense-organ, \ but also the animal itself, because this sense is the sole requisite to animal life. An animal possesses the other

1 Simplicius (ad loc. ) thinks that lightning is meant here.

2 Aristotle would appear to refer death by poison to its tactual qualities.

144 ARISTOTLE 8 PSYCHOLOGY deanima

senses, as we have said,1 not for the sake of life but of a higher life. It has sight, e.g. in order that it may see, since it lives in a medium of water, or air, or, in a word, in a diaphanous medium, and it has taste, because of the distinctions of pleasant and unpleasant, and in order that it may detect these qualities in its food and so desire it and be moved to obtain it. It possesses hearing in order that information may be communicated to it, and a tongue in order that it may communicate -*4rC' ( information to others.

\ \

\ \

Cf . De an. 4346 24.

(PARVA NATURALIA.) ON SENSATION AND THE SENSIBLE.1

CHAPTER I.

Now that we have treated, of the soul in its essential 436 ^ nature and of the faculties that belong to it, part by part, our next duty is to investigate the subject of living creatures and everything that has life, to determine what

1 The following opuscules of mixed physiological and psychological content are never cited by Aristotle under a general title, but always referred to separately. They were given the title Parva Naturalia by the scholastics, but even the learned Leonicus apparently does not know by whom {Comment, in Parva Natur. fol. 1530, p. 11), and Simon is only able to say ' ' denominatio a Latinis inventa est " ( Comm. in libr. de sensu, 1566, p. 1). The designation is used by Egidio Colonna (cf. Rhein. Museum, vol. 24, 1869, p. 81), who was a pupil of Thomas Aquinas, and we may assume that the title came into existence about the time of Thomas, when great interest was taken in the interpretation of the Aristotelian writings, although Freudenthal was unable to find it either in Albertus Magnus or in Thomas. The tractates discuss, in the main, the organic functions of animal bodies, and form at once a con- tinuation and supplement to the De anima and an introduction to the treatise On the Parts of Animals. They form thus a transition from Psychology to Zoology. In content they are mainly biological and physio- logical, concerned chiefly with the physiology of the senses. They supplement the De animain the following particulars: In the De anima the soul is regarded as the principle of organic life, which is manifested in the forms of cognition and physical vitality. The detailed consideration of the relatiou between these two things is left for the Parva Naturalia ; K 145

146 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de sensu

functions are specific1 and what functions are general. Let us then take what has already been said touching the soul for our basis, and as we proceed to the remaining inquiries let what is first by nature 2 be first in our dis-

2 cussion. The most important vital phenomena, whether one regards the specific or general attributes of animals, are those which are the joint concern of soul and body,3 such as sensation, memory,4 anger, desire, and impulse in general, and, one may add, pleasure and pain. These are

3 experienced by almost all animals. In addition to these, however, there are other attributes which are common to all animals that share in life, and others still that belong only to certain animals. The most important of the former class may be enumerated in four pairs, viz., sleeping and waking, youth and old age, inspiration and expiration, life 5 and death. We must study the nature

further, the nature of memory, the association of ideas, and the subject of dreams, are treated almost exclusively in the opuscules. Thebrief accounts of 'common sense,' pleasure and pain, and motion in the De anima are supplemented here. Further, such biological considerations as the con- ditions, disturbances, and duration of organic life were scarcely noticed in the De anima, but receive detailed treatment in the tractates On Youth and Old Age, Life and Death, and On Respiration.

1 Reason and Recollection e.g. are specific functions, while nutrition and growth are general and common to all living organisms.

2 By this is meant the elemental functions connected with the life of the body {koivo. ttjs ipvxv* ^ai T°v o-u/ulcltos i'pya), on which depend nutri- tion and reproduction, sleeping and wakiug, etc.

3 De an. 4336 19, 20.

4 Memory {fxprjfxr]) but not recollection (dvdimuyjaLs), which involves reflection, and is peculiar to man.

5 To these four pairs of biological phenomena is added a fifth below health and disease. Youth and old age, life and death are treated in one opuscule, sleeping and waking in another, inspiration and expiration in another, while the subject of health and disease was either not treated at all, or the treatise has been lost. No such treatise was known to Alexander Aphrodisiensis {Comment, ad 436a 17).

chap. i. PURPOSE OF SENSATION 147

of each of these phenomena and the causes of its occur- rence. The investigation, too, of the ultimate principles of health and disease is the province of the naturalist; for 4 neither health nor disease can apply to creatures when deprived of life. And so it happens, as I think, that most natural philosophers and those physicians who have a more philosophical understanding of their science, con- clude in the one case with the investigation of medicine, and in the other begin their practice with deductions 436 £ from the laws of nature and their application to medi- cine.1 The above-mentioned phenomena are evidently 5 the common property of soul and body. For they are all conjoined with sensation or are mediated by it. Some of them are modifications of sensation or persistent condi- tions of it, others are protective or preservative of sensation, while others still are destructive and negative. That sensation is mediated by the body to the soul is plain both with and without the use of rational proof. How- ever, regarding the essential nature of sense-perception and the reason why animals are endowed with it, we have 6 already stated our views in the treatise On the Soul.2 Every animal, in so far as it is a living creature, must have sensation. For it is in terms of this that we distinguish between animal and non-animal. Touch and 7 taste must belong to all animals individually, touch for reasons given in the treatise On the Soul2 and taste on account of food. For it is by taste that animals

xCf. 4806 25, where the tractate on Respiration closes with an almost verbatim repetition of this statement.

2 In the De an. the purpose of sensation is described as two-fold, (1) the survival of the animal, (2) the ends of higher living (cf. 420/- 20 ff., 4346 22 if.).

148 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de sensu

discriminate between agreeable and disagreeable in foods, and so reject the one and take the other; in a word flavour1 is an affection that belongs to the nutritive

8 soul. Sensations that are excited by external objects, such as smell, hearing, and vision, are found in animals capable of locomotion, and are given to all of them for the sake of their preservation, in order that they may scent their food and pursue it, and flee from what is harmful and destructive. In the case of animals endowed

437 a with intelligence, they are given for the sake of higher well-being. For these sense-perceptions convey to us various distinctions, out of which the knowledge of intel-

9 lectual and moral concepts is built up. Amongst the senses, vision is the most important, both in itself and for the necessities of life ; on the other hand, for the uses of reason, and accidentally, hearing is the most important.2

10 The power of vision informs us of many and various dis- tinctions, because all bodies are suffused with colour, so that by means of this sense more than by any other we perceive the common properties of objects (by common properties I mean form, magnitude, motion, number). Hearing, on the other hand, informs us merely of dis- tinctions in sound, and in some instances of distinctions in

1 That is, flavour as a property of food affects the process of growth or the nutritive soul. Touch is the lowest or most fundamental sense, and taste is a form of touch mediated by the tongue. These two serve the primary or lowest ends of life. Sight and hearing serve the higher or more intellectual needs.

2 Although sight conveys to us the greatest number of impressions touching the outside world, Aristotle considers hearing the most important of the senses intellectually, because it mediates oral instruc- tion. This is called per accidens, because per se the hearing mediates only sound, and it is accidental to the function of hearing that this sound should be significant or have meaning.

chap. i. IMPORTANCE OF HEARING 149

articulate voice. Indirectly, however, hearing contributes n the greatest share to our intellectual life. For it is the spoken and heard word that is the source of knowledge, and hearing is the source not in itself but accidentally. Language is composed of words, and every word is a symbol. This explains the fact that in cases where men 12 are deprived of one or the other of these senses from birth, the blind are more intelligent than the deaf and dumb.1

1This is no doubt correct, owing to the advantage the blind have over the deaf and dumb in the use of language. This advantage has been greatly modified, of course, by the development of linguistic instruction for the deaf and dumb. The necessity of language for thought is a still unsettled question. Cf. James, Principles of Psychology, Vol. I. p. 269, who considers language, in its ordinary meaning, unnecessary for thought. Sully ( The Human Mind, Vol. I. p. 420), on the other hand, says : " It seems safe, therefore, to conclude that apart from verbal or other general signs the full consciousness of generality does not arise." Romanes (Mental Evolution in Man, p. 149): " These unfortunate children [i.e. the deaf and dumb who are never taught finger-language] grow up in a state of intellectual isolation, which is almost as complete as that of any of the lower animals."

CHAPTEE II.

We have already treated of the function of the several special senses. Writers now-a-days attempt to correlate the senses with the physical elements 1 as found in the bodily members in which the sense-organs have their natural development. With the fifth sense they are hard pressed, not finding it easy to pair five senses with

2 four elements. All of them agree in regarding vision as connected with fire, on account of a certain phenomenon whose nature they misunderstand : viz. when the eye is pressed and moved it seems to scintillate.2 But this takes place in the dark or when the eyelids are shut, in which case darkness is produced. And there is also

3 another difficulty here. For if it is impossible for a perceiving and seeing subject to be unconscious of a seen object, then the eye must necessarily see itself. Why, then, does this not take place when the eye is at rest ? The explanation of this phenomenon, as well as the solution of the entire difficulty and of the apparent fact that vision is fire, is to be found in the following con-

1 Empedocles, Alcmaeon, Democritus, Plato.

2 Pressure on the optic nerve, of which Aristotle knew nothing, stimulates the sensation of light.

150

DE SENSU

THE ORGANS OF SENSE 151

siderations. It is the nature of smooth surfaces to shine 4 in the darkness, although they produce no light ; now we observe that the dark central portion of the eye has a 437 smooth surface. This becomes apparent when the eye is moved, because the single organ is thereby made double, an effect which is produced by the rapidity of the motion. In this way the seeing organ and the seen object appear 5 to be different.1 For the same reason, also, this effect fails to be produced, when the motion is not rapid and does not take place in the dark.2 For it is in a medium of darkness that a smooth surface naturally shines, as we see in the case of the heads of certain fishes 3 and in the juice of the cuttle-fish. The consequence is that when the eye is moved slowly, the seeing organ and seen object do not appear to be at once unitary and dual. When, on 6 the other hand, the movement is rapid the eye sees itself, as in the reflection of a mirror. Now, if vision were fire, as Empedocles declares and as we read in the Timaeus4 and if seeing resulted from the passage of light out of the eye as from a lamp, the question arises : Why is it that 7 we do not see in the dark also ? To say, as the Timaeus5 does, that the light when it passes out from the eye is extinguished in the darkness, is a totally empty assertion. For what is meant by an extinction of light ? The warm and the dry, it is true, are nullified by the moist and the cold, as one sees in the case of a coal fire

JThat is, the seeing eye, which according to Empedocles is fire, appears to be seen and so to be different from the eye itself. 2 Because the smooth surface shines only in the dark. aCf. Dean, 419a 5.

4 Timaeus, 42 e, 43 a ff. ; Meno 76 c.

5 Timaeus. 45 b : cf . also Theaetetus 156 c.

152 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de sensu

8 or a flame, but neither of these has anything to do with light. If, however, they * are attributes of light but are concealed from us owing to their subtle presence, then light ought to be extinguished in the day during rain, and darkness should increase in frosty weather. Flame and ignited bodies are so affected, but nothing of the sort takes

9 place in the case of light. Empedocles appears to hold the view that vision results from the eye's radiating light, as we said before. His own words, at any rate, are as follows 2 :

"As a man taking thought for his journey A lantern prepares, whose flame flashes light Through the blustering night, as he passes, And shutters he fastens, defence from winds, To scatter the breath of the blowing blasts, While the light pierces through, by its fineness, And gleams over the threshold unfailing ; So, of old,3 fire elemental was fixed 438a In membranes, and suffused4 the round pupil,

Held in thin tissues, a check to the water, While the fire pierces through, by its fineness."

10 Sometimes he gives the above explanation of vision, and at other times he explains it by means of emanations from visible objects.5

1 The warm and the dry.

2Cf. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, p. 231.

3 Instead of to t' read tot.

4 Instead of Xoxdi'ero read exeiyaro.

5 Each of these parts represents only half of the Empedoclean theory of perception. Light emanates from the fire in the eye, as from a lantern, and effluences come from sensible objects. These effluences enter into the pores or passages of the eye, and in proportion as these effluxes are fine or crass, they enter into the larger or narrower passages. The fire is in the interior of the eye, and between this and the outer covering is a mass of water held by a fine net. The fire in

chap. ii. THEORIES OF VISION 153

Democritus says that vision is due to water, and in this he is right ; but he is wrong in thinking that it consists in reflection. For reflection is produced because the eye is a smooth surface ; vision, however, does not take place in this smooth surface but in the seeing subject. Now, the condition to which he refers is only a reflection of light. He has, however, as I think, no clear idea whatever concerning the general nature of images " and reflection. It is also strange that it never occurs to him to raise the question why it is that the eye alone sees, while no other object in which images are reflected, has vision. His statement that vision partakes of the nature of water, is true ; but vision is not due to the fact that the eye is water, but to the fact that it is transparent, which characteristic it has also in common with the air. Water, however, is easier to fix and is 12 thicker than air, and it is for this reason that the eye and its pupil are composed of water.1 This can be proved also from actual facts. When the eyes are destroyed water is seen to flow out of them, and even in their quite embryonic stage the eyes are exceedingly limpid and brilliant. Further, the white of the eye2 in sanguineous *3 animals is fat and oily, which serves the purpose of keeping the humid element from congealing. Conse- quently, the eye can resist cold better than any other organ of the body. No one ever experienced the sensa-

the interior by reason of its fine, subtle nature, penetrates through these, as the light penetrates through the sides of the lantern and out through the atmosphere. In this way the images thrown off from things are illuminated. Cf. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, p. 265.

1 The aqueous and vitreous humours.

2 The sclerotica.

154 aristotle's psychology desensu

tion of cold in the interior of the eye. The eyes of bloodless animals are covered with a hard skin which furnishes protection. The theory is altogether

14 irrational which makes vision consist, as some hold, in a sort of radiation, and regards this radiation of something from the eye as extending to the stars, or as extending to some point and there effecting a combination with the object. It would be better to assume that this com- bination of the eye with its object were in the eye's original nature. But even this is nonsense. For what is one to understand by this combination of light with light ? Or how is such a thing to take place ? For

438 b nothing combines in a haphazard way with anything else.

15 Further, how can the internal light combine with an external one, for between them is the intervening membrane. Regarding the fact that there is no vision without light, we have spoken elsewhere.1 But whether the intervening medium between the visible object and the eye is light or air, it is in any case the motion through this medium that produces sight. And it is reasonable to regard the interior of the eye as composed

16 of water ; for water is diaphanous. And as nothing external is seen without light, the same thing applies to the internal. The internal also must, therefore, be diaphanous. Since this diaphanous is not air, it must be water. For the soul or the perceptive power of the soul is not found on the eye's surface, but evidently

17 within. Consequently, the eye's interior must be diaphanous and sensitive to light. And this we can see empirically. For cases have happened in war where

1 De an. 4186 1, 419a 9, 430a 16.

chap. ii. THE ORGANS OF SENSE 155

persons have received such a blow across the temples1 that the ocular conduits were severed and darkness seemed to ensue, just as when a lamp is put out, and this is due to the fact that the diaphanous, i.e. the pupil as we call it, was cut off, as in the snuffing of a 18 lamp. If, therefore, this takes place in some such way as we describe, it is evidently necessary to render an expla- nation of this kind and to correlate each sense-organ with one of the elements, viz. the seeing power of the eye we must derive from water, the sense for sound from the air, and smell we must associate with fire. For the organ of smell is potentially 2 what smell itself is 19 actually. The sensible object stimulates the sensation into actuality, and consequently the latter must have an antecedent potential existence. Smell 3 is a smoke-like exhalation,4 and this is derived from fire. It is for this 20 reason, too, that the organ of smell is especially assigned to the environment of the brain, for the material sub-

1 The eye must be translucent, and therefore composed either of air or water, in order to transmit vision to the inner soul, vision not taking place on the eye's surface. This is proven by the fact that when the optic passages are severed, as Aristotle supposes, by a blow on the temple, one becomes blinded.

2Cf. Dean. 417a 12 ff.

3 De an. 421a 7 ff.

4 Smell is considered by Aristotle one of the most difficult senses to analyze, which is due to the fact, he thinks, that it is very imperfectly developed in man. Taste is closely allied to it, but much better developed. The one is concerned with the sapid dry' (443a 7) and the other with the 'sapid moist.' Flavour is found in the moist only, while for respiring animals odour is found only in the dry. It can, however, exist in the moist as shown by the sense of smell in aquatic animals. For the latter reason it cannot be a ' smoke-like exhalation.' Aristotle appears here to be speaking only in terms of a current explanation. Cf. 443a 23 ff.

156 aristotle's psychology desensu

strate of cold is potentially warm. And the same explanation holds good for the development of the eye. It is formed from a part of the brain, for the brain is the 21 moistest and coolest member of the body. The organ of touch is derived from the element earth, and taste is a 439 a form of touch. Consequently, the organs of these two senses, taste and touch, are found to conduct towards the heart. The heart occupies a counterposition to the brain and is the warmest member of the body. Eegarding the sense-organs of the body let the above determinations suffice.

CHAPTER III.

In the treatise On the Soul1 I have given a general

to* ' ~" "• &'

account of the objects of sense in their application to the several sense-organs, such as colour, sound, smell, flavour and the tangible. I have explained their function and their activity, organ by organ. But we must also deter- mine what each of these things is apart from the organ, e.g. we must ask : What is colour ? What is sound ? What is smell ? What is flavour ? We must likewise inquire regarding the tactual, and we must begin with colour. Everything has a twofold significance, viz. that 2 of actuality and potentiality. It has been explained in the treatise On the Soul 2 in what way actual colour and actual sound coincide with and differ from the actual sensations of seeing and hearing. We must now explain what each of these sensible objects must be in order to produce sensation and its activity. We have already said in the above-named treatise regarding light that it is the colour 3 of a diaphanous medium, accidentally produced.3 Eor

1 De an. 418a 26— 424a 16. 2 De an. 4256 29 ff.

3 Neither colour nor light belongs to the essential nature of the pel- lucid medium, which may be charged at one time with one colour and at another time with another, or in the case of darkness it may suffer privation of light.

157

158 aristotle's psychology desbnsu

when anything fire-like is found in the diaphanous, its presence constitutes light and its absence signifies dark-

4 ness. What we understand by diaphanous is not a property peculiar to air or water or to any other so-called body, but it is a certain natural constitution and power,1 common to both these bodies and found also in certain others, in greater or less degree, but which has no independent and separate existence. And furthermore, as there must be a limiting surface in

5 bodies, so here also. Light is found in an indeterminate diaphanous. It is also evident that the diaphanous in bodies must have a surface, and that this surface is colour is plain from observed facts. For colour is found either in the boundary or it is itself the boundary. It is for this reason that the Pythagoreans 2 characterized the visible superficies as colour. Colour, indeed, is given in

6 the boundary properties of body, although it does not itself constitute that boundary. On the contrary, one must suppose that the same colour-quality3 which is

439^ observed on the exterior applies also to the interior.4 Both air and water are seen to be coloured, for even their

7 shimmer is colour. In these cases, however, air and

1 Aristotle rejected the view of Empedocles that light is motion and travels from heaven to earth (4186 20, 446<x 26). Light is not motion, although it is caused by movement or change (dXXoiWis). In its own nature it is a definite qualitative condition of the air or water, just as the frozen represents a condition of water (4466 28 447a 3).

2Cf. Plut. Epit. Mem. I. 15; Stobaei Ecloy. I. 15 quoted by Diels Box. Gr. p. 313.

3 The treatise On Colours {-rrepl xp^^tuv) is not genuine. Cf. Prantl, Aristot. fiber die Farben, pp. 82-84.

4 Aristotle appears to have in mind such objects as jewels, whose colour he considers not merely superficial but as penetrating through the substance.

chap. in. THE DIAPHANOUS 159

the sea, because of their unfixed character, do not have the same colour when viewed near at hand and from a distance. In solid bodies, on the other hand, the appearance of the colour is fixed, unless the surrounding medium makes it shift. It is evident, therefore, that the principle which is sensitive to colour is, in both the former and the latter instances, the same. The diaphanous,1 then, in so far as it is found in bodies (and it is found 8 more or less in them all), causes them to be satu- rated with colour. Inasmuch as colour is found in the boundary of bodies, it would also be found in the boundary of the diaphanous substance. Consequently, colour might be defined as the boundary of the diaphanous 9 in a definite body. Colour attaches also to diaphanous bodies themselves, such as water and other similar elements, and it is also found in all such bodies as have a surface-colour which is peculiar to the body 2 itself. There is then, on the one hand, the possibility that the positive principle which in the air produces light should also be contained in the diaphanous ; on the other hand, it is possible that this should not be the case, but that the condition then should be one of privation.

As in the case of air we have the two phenomena, light and darkness, so in bodies we have the two qualities, 10

1 The diaphanous is that which mediates colour, and light is that which converts the potentially diaphanous into the actually diaphanous. In other words, a diaphanous or pellucid medium, such as air or water, is not actually pellucid without light, but is dark. Colour has the power to set the diaphanous in motion (419a 10), by which means the images of remote surfaces affect the visual organ.

2 Fire or some positive principle such as is found in the aether is sup- posed to illumine the diaphanous ; the withdrawal of this is darkness or the privation of light.

160 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de sensu

white and black. Eegarding the other colours we must now decide, after analysis, in how many ways they can be produced. For black and white may be so juxtaposed that each of the two, on account of its minuteness, when taken alone will be invisible, while the combination of the two will be visible. The latter cannot be seen n either as white or black. But inasmuch as it must have some colour, and it can be neither of these two, it must be a mixed colour, and different in kind from the others. It is, then, a possible supposition that there are several 12 colours besides white and black, but their manifoldness is due to proportion.1 This proportion can be expressed by the relation of 3 : 2 or of 3 : 4, or colours can be related to each other in terms of other numbers, and some may not be expressible at all in terms of any proportion, but in terms of some incommensurable plus and minus. The same thing applies also to harmony of tones. Those colours which are expressed by harmonious numbers, as is also true of tone-harmonies, appear to be the most pleasing, 440 a such as sea-purple, crimson, and a few others like them ; they are few for the same reason that harmonious tones are few.2 The other colours are not numerically expres- sible. Or, is it true that all colours are numerically

1 White and black, the correlates of light and darkness, are the basal colours, as sweet and bitter are the basal flavours. Between these two extreme opposites there are intermediate colours, into which the primary colours are convertible by composition {Phys. 188a 32 ; 1886 21 ; 2296 14 ; Metaph. 1057a 23). These intermediate colours are red, violet, green, blue, and yellow. Gray is included in black, aud is not regarded as an independent colour, while yellow is perhaps included in white (442a 22). Cf. Goethe, Farbenlehre (ed. 1810), Bd. II. pp. 11-53.

2 In the first place because they do not form a continuum, and so are not infinitely or indefinitely divisible, and secondly because they are objects of feeling.

chap. in. THEORY OF COLOURS 161

expressible, although some colours depend upon a regular order, while others depend upon an irregular order, and the latter have this character when they are not pure ? This is one1 explanation of the genesis of colours ; another2 explanation is that they shine through one another, as we 13 see sometimes in the works of artists, when they superadd. a colour on a background of a different colour, e.g. when they wish to produce the effect of an object seen in the water or in the air. So it is also with the sun, which in its own nature appears white, but red when seen through mist and smoke. And many other colours will be pro- 14 duced in the same way as above described. That is to say, a certain proportion might be supposed to exist between the colours on the superficies and the colours in the depths, and others again may not be expressible in terms of 'proportion' at all. It is, therefore, absurd to 15 say with the ancients that colours are effluxes, and for this reason are visible. For in their opinion it is absolutely necessary that sensation be effected through contact, and it is consequently better to say at once that the medium of sensation is set in motion by the sensible object, and that in this way sensation is produced by contact and not by effluxes. In the case of juxtaposed 16 colours, just as one must suppose an invisible magnitude, so must one suppose an imperceptible moment of time, in order to explain the fact that the movements issue imperceptibly, and because they are simultaneously visible the impression is a single one. There is, however, no such necessity here, but the colour on the superficies

1 Viz. the number-theory which Aristotle rejects.

2 Also this theory of superposition is rejected.

162 aristotle's psychology desensu

when unmoved, and when set in motion by its substrate, produces unlike motions in the medium. Consequently, it appears different, and neither white nor black. So

17 that if an invisible magnitude is not possible, but every magnitude must be visible from a certain distance, so there must be here also a certain mixture of colours. In this way one may suppose that in objects viewed from a distance a certain common colour is seen. For that there

18 is no invisible magnitude is a matter that must be in- 440 b vestigated later. If a mixture1 of bodies takes place, then

it is not merely in the way that some think, viz. by the juxtaposition of minimal parts which are imperceptible to our senses, but also in the form of a general mixture of the entire substance together, as explained in outline in

19 our treatise On Mixture?- By the former method of com- position only those substances can be mixed which are capable of analysis into minimal parts, e.g. men, horses, or seeds. In the case of ' men,' a man is the minimal part;3 in the case of 'horses,5 a horse. Consequently, in both instances the mass is formed by juxtaposition of these minimal parts. We do not, however, speak of a

20 man being mixed with a horse. Whatever cannot be analysed into minimal ([homogeneous]) parts, is incapable of mixture in this sense, but only in the sense of total

1The first two theories, viz. the numerical and the superpositional, are here rejected in favour of the theory of substantial mixture.

2 This treatise (irepi /xi^ecos) has been lost. For Aristotle's definition of mixture, and his distinction between it and synthesis, see De gen. et corr. 328a 5 fF. The former implies homogeneity, while the latter may be merely mechanical juxtaposition. The former produces a whole, the latter an aggregate (321a 34).

3 Read iXaxwrov for iXaxicrros. Cf. Berliner Wochemchrift filr class. Philol., 1898, p. 998.

chap. in. COLOUR AND MIXTURE 163

mixture, which is what naturally takes place in most cases. In our treatise On Mixture we have already explained how this can take place. Where bodies are 21 mixed their colours must evidently be mixed also, and this is the principal cause of the multiplicity of colours, which is not explained by their being super- posed or by their juxtaposition. It is not true that what is mixed has one colour when viewed near by, and another when viewed at a distance, for it has one colour when viewed from all points. And colours will be manifold because of the possibility of manifold proportions 22 being employed in mixtures, some of which will be based on numerical proportion, others on that of disproportionate mass. Further, the same thing may be said of mixed colours as was said of juxtaposed and superposed colours. The explanation of the fact that we have fixed and definite varieties of colours, flavours, and sounds will be given later.1

1 Cf . De sensu, 4456 3 ff. ; 446a 20.

CHAPTEE IV.

We have now explained the meaning of colour and the cause of its multiplicity. We had already discussed the subject of sound and articulate speech in the treatise On the Soul} Smell and flavour now remain to be discussed. Both these terms signify almost identical natural affections, only each of them is found in a

2 different organ. The quality of flavours is more distinct to us than that of smells. The reason is that our sense

441 a of smell is inferior to the same sense in other animals, and is inferior to all our other senses, while we of all animals have the most accurate sense of touch, and taste

3 is a sort of touch.2

Water in its own nature has no flavour. And yet it is necessary that water should contain within itself the varieties of flavours, which owing to their infini- tesimal character are indiscernible, as Empedocles3 says, or else there must be in water some such matter as is

1 De an. 420/> 32. 2 De an. 423a 19.

3 Other than this we have no knowledge of the Empedoclean theory of taste, with the exception of the statement in fr. 139 that flavours depend upon adaptability to the sense-pores. Cf. Burnet, Early Greek Philos. p. 265.

164

desensu NATURE OF FLAVOURS 165

the universal germ-origin of flavours,1 and in this way all flavours are generated out of water, different flavours from different parts ; or again, supposing that water contains no qualitative differences, we must then find some other efficient cause of flavour, such as heat or the influence of the sun. The error of the Empedoclean 4 theory is very easy to detect. For we actually observe flavours undergoing change under the influence of heat, e.g. when we expose fruits to the sun by removing their pericarps or by heating them before a fire. They do not acquire this new flavour by drawing it out of the water, but by undergoing a change in the removal of the pericarp itself. When fruits are dried and stored they become in time, instead of sweet, pungent or bitter, or change their flavour variously, and when cooked they acquire, so to speak, all sorts of flavours. So too, the theory that water is a panspermic matter is impossible. 5 For we observe that out of one and the same thing, as out of the same food stuff, different flavours are generated. There remains the theory that water by undergoing some external influence, changes. It is plain 6 that the phenomenon which we call flavour is not due to the potency of heat. For water is the thinnest of all liquids, subtler than oil itself. Oil, however, is more expansile than water because of its viscous character,

1 1 think the reference here is more likely to Anaxagoras than to Democritus, as Wallace supposes (Aristotle's Psychology, Introd. p. lxvi), although both of them are said to have used the term Trava-rrep/xia. The description of the theory (441a. 19) as one of dynamism would conform better with the general principles of Anaxagoras than with the mechanical philosophy of Democritus. In strictness, wauaTrcpfxia is a term which Democritus could not legitimately use.

166 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de sensu

water being non-cohesive. For this reason it is harder to hold water in one's hand than it is to hold oil.

7 Now, since water is the only liquid which when heated exhibits no denser consistency than before, we must evidently look elsewhere for the cause of flavour. For all flavours are more dense when heated. Heat is a contributing cause ([not the sole one]). Apparently the

441 b flavours that are found in fruits have a prior existence

8 in the earth. In the same spirit many of the ancient physiologers 1 say that water is like the soil through which it passes, and this is particularly evident in the case of salt waters, for salts are a form of soil. Also, water that has been filtered through bitter ashes acquires

9 a bitter taste. Further, we often find springs that are bitter and others that are pungent, while others still have different flavours. The greatest variety of flavours is found, as one might suppose, amongst plants. It is the nature of moisture, as of other things, to be affected by its opposite and its opposite is the dry. Conse- quently, it is affected by fire, which is by nature dry.

10 Now, heat is the peculiar property of fire, and the dry is the peculiar property of the earth, as was said in the treatise On the Elements? Neither fire, nor earth, nor any other element, as such, acts or is acted upon. It is only in so far as each thing contains in itself the principle of opposition that it either acts or is acted upon.3

1 Lewes finds this idea expressed in Hippocrates. Cf. Aristotle, p. 250.

2 The reference is probably to De gen. et corr. 3296 18-330& 9. On the lost treatise we pi crToixeiuv see Heitz, Die verlorenen Schriften d. Aristoteles, p. 76.

::A thing acts or is acted upon through certain of the qualities possessed by it and through the action of opposing qualities.

chap. iv. FLAVOUR AND MOISTURE 167

As, therefore, those who dissolve a colour or an flavour in water, cause the water to absorb it, so nature acts upon the dry and earthy elements, and by filtering water through these elements and stimu- lating them into activity by heat, it causes the moist element to acquire a certain quality. This condition, 12 which is wrought in moisture by means of the above mentioned dry element, is flavour, and it consists in the conversion of a potential |taste into an actual one.1 For the sense-organ which is already in a condition of potentiality, passes over into a condition of actuality. The process of sensation does not resemble learning so much as it resembles contemplation. That flavours do not attach to everything dry, but only to the dry that 13 is nutritive, either as a positive or negative condition, one may conclude from the fact that the dry is not- found apart from the moist nor the moist apart from the dry. Neither one when taken alone is food-stuff for living creatures, but only when combined. In animal food it is the tactual elements which effect 14 growth and decay. And it is by virtue of the warmth or cold in the assimilated food that these phenomena are produced. For these are the properties that cause growth and decay. The administered food nourishes in 442 a so far as it is gustable. For everything is nourished by means of the sweet, whether pure or mixed. This 15 subject must be more definitely treated in the work

1The gustable or flavour {xv/xos) is described at 4416 19 as an effect produced in a moist substance by that which is dry. Flavour is therefore, the sapid moist, while the object of smell is described (443a 2) as the ' sapid dry. ' The odoriferous and the gustable (savour and flavour) are closely allied.

168 aristotle's psychology desensu

On Generation l ; for the present we only touch upon it so far as necessary. Heat disposes to growth and brings food into a prepared condition ; it absorbs what is light and rejects the salt and bitter because of their heaviness. What external heat effects in external bodies, is also produced by internal heat in animals

1 6 and plants. Nourishment, then, is caused by the sweet. The other flavours are mingled in food in the same way as the bitter and pungent, i.e. to serve as a relish. This is for the purpose of counterbalance, and because the sweet is over-nutritive and swims on the stomach.

As colours are a combination of white and black, so flavours are derived from sweet and bitter. They depend

17 severally on a proportion of more or less, on a proportion of mixture and motion either numerically expressible, or indeterminate. Those mixtures, however, which produce pleasure are numerically expressible. The oily flavour is to be classed with the sweet; the salt and bitter are closely allied, while the sour, pungent, astringent, and

18 acid are intermediary. And so the varieties of flavours and colours are pretty nearly the same in number; for there are six of each, if one regards, as is reasonable, the gray as a sort of black.2 We have then to include yellow in white, just as we referred the oily flavour to the

1 Aristotle is here referring to the subject of growth and decay, not to the nature of taste. The subject is treated in De gen. et corr. 320a 8ff.

2 And further, if one regards yellow as a species of white. Otherwise we have seven colours as enumerated at note 2, p, 87. I have retained Susemihl's conjecture for eirrd, adopted by Biehl (cf. Alexander Aphrod. Comment, ad loc). Prantl, however, calls the Aporia of Alexander " ungeschickt " (Aristot. Ueber die Farben, p. 117).

chap. iv. THE SENSE OF TOUCH 169

sweet, while crimson, sea-purple, green, and blue, are intermediary between white and black, and all other shades are combinations of these. As black is privation 19 of the white in a diaphanous medium, so the salt and bitter are privation of the sweet in a nutritive moist substance. Consequently the ashes of anything that has been burnt are bitter ; for the potable element has been consumed.

Democritus and most of the physiologers who treat the subject of sensation make the most remarkable blunder, for they resolve all sensible objects into the tangible. If, 442 b indeed, this is correct, each of the senses becomes evidently 20 a sense of touch. It is not difficult to see that this is impossible. Further, they treat the common functions of all the senses as special functions. For the perception of magnitude, figure, roughness, smoothness, and sharpness and bluntness in solid bodies, is the common function of all the senses, and if not of all, then at least the common function of sight and touch. It is in these perceptions, 21 therefore, that the senses are subject to error ; but they are not subject to error in their special sensations, e.g. sight is not fallible regarding colour nor hearing regarding sound. Again, these physiologers refer the special functions to the general, as Democritus does with white and black,1 the latter of which he identifies with the rough and the former with the smooth, and he

1 White is due to smooth atoms and their aggregation is a smooth surface. Black is due to rough and uneven atoms and their aggrega- tion is a rough and uneven surface (cf. Theophrastus, De sensu, 73). Further, however, the quality of the visible is affected by the rapidity of motion in the effluxes and by the condition of the air itself (Theoph. De .sensu, 80).

170 aristotle's psychology desensu

reduces flavours 1 to atomic forms. And yet it is either not the function of any sense to discern common properties, or else this power belongs to the eye more

22 than to any other organ. If, however, this power falls rather to the lot of taste, it is at any rate the function of the most delicate sense to discriminate the slightest distinctions, each after its kind, so that taste would have to discriminate common properties better than any other sense and be the most discerning judge of

23 atomic figures. Further, all sensible objects contain the principle of opposition, e.g. in colour black is the opposite of white, and in flavour bitter is the opposite of sweet ; but one figure does not appear to be the opposite of another figure, for to what sort of polygon would a circle be

24 opposed ? Further, the atomic figures being infinite in number, it necessarily follows that flavours are also infinite in number. For what is the explanation of the fact that one flavour produces a sensation and another flavour does not produce it ?

We have now treated the subject of the gus table and flavour. The other aspects of flavour receive their proper consideration in the treatise On the Physiology of Plants?

1 Flavour-qualities are explained by Democritus in a way similar to variations in colour, i.e. white and black are analogous to sweet and bitter. Sweet is due to round smooth atoms ; bitter to rough and angular ones (Theoph. De sensu, 65, 66).

2 The two books on plants {-repl (pvrQu) are frequently referred to by Aristotle (468a 31, 4676 4, 656a 3, 7836 20) and are mentioned in the catalogue of Diogenes Laertius, but were apparently lost as early as the time of Alexander Aphrodisiensis {fior. circa 220 a.d.); cf. Zeller, Aristotle, Eng. tr. Vol. I. p. 91.

CHAPTER V.

In like manner one must also treat of smell. For the same effect which is produced by the dry or the moist, is produced in another connection by savoury moisture in air and water equally. Now we observe that the diaphanous is a common principle in these two elements ; the element, however, is not odoriferous by virtue of its being diaphanous, but by virtue of its capacity to exude 4430 and throw off dry savour. For smell is exercised not only in the air but also in water. This is evidently so in the case of fishes and mollusks 1 ; for these are known 2 to be endowed with smell although there is no air

1 The Testacea (6<rrpa/c65ep/xa), as used by Aristotle, include the Mollusea (in the modern meaning), excepting the Cephalopods. They include also the Ascidians and Echini, although these are sometimes grouped by Aristotle amongst the Zoophytes. The Testacea form the lowest group in the animal scale, lacking as they do the power of locomotion and the higher senses, as sight and hearing. The Mollusea (fj.a\dKia) correspond to the modern Cephalopods, and the Crustacea (fxaXaKoo-TpcLKa) include the crabs, crayfish, lobster, etc., which have a soft interior and a shell -like exterior, the shell being, however, flexible and not brittle as in the case of the Testacea. These three classes and the Insecta (eVro^a) form Aristotle's four classes of bloodless animals. Cf. Ogle's Aristotle on the Parts of Animals, pp. xxix, 222; Meyer's Aristoteles Thierhunde, pp. 159 ff.

171

172 aristotle's psychology desensu

in the water (for the air comes to the surface when found in water) and they have no respiration. If one assumes that both air and water are moist elements, smell would be the dry sapidity in the moist and such

3 would be the nature of an odoriferous body. That this condition in an object is derived from a sapid element is a plain conclusion from things that do and do not emit smell. For the simple elements, such as fire, air, earth, and water, are non-odorous because the moist and dry in them are non-sapid, excepting when a combination is

4 produced. This is why even the sea has a smell ; it contains a sapid dry element. Salts are more odorous than nitre, as is proven by the oil derived from them. Nitre, in turn, is more odorous than earth. Further, a stone is inodorous, for it is without sapidity ; woods, on the other hand, are odorous, for they are sapid, and amongst woods those that are watery are less odorous.

5 Further, amongst metals gold is inodorous, for it is not sapid ; bronze, however, and iron are odorous. When the moist element is burned out of metals, the slag becomes still less odorous. Silver and tin are more odorous than some and less odorous than other metals ;

6 for they contain moisture. Some writers regard smell as a smoke-like exhalation which is common to earth and air [and all the naturalists fall back on this explanation of smell]. And so Heraclitus made the remark that if

7 all things were smoke, we should discern everything by our nostrils. Now, the naturalists all explain smell on this theory, some of them describing it as vapour, others as an exhalation, and others as a combination of both of these. Vapour is a kind of moisture, whereas a smoke-

chap.v. NATURE OF SMELL 173

like exhalation is, as we have said, common to air and earth. Water is derived from vapour, and a sort of earth is developed from smoke-like exhalation. But neither of these two seems to be the odorous. For vapour 8 is due to water, while smoke-like exhalation cannot possibly be generated in water. And yet creatures that live in the water have the sense of smell, as was said above. Again, exhalations here have the same meaning as emana- 443 b tions, and if the emanation theory was wrong, so is this wrong. It is clear that the moisture which is found in 9 the air (for the air also has a moist character) and in water is capable of deriving something from the sapid dry element and of being affected by it. Furthermore, if the dry element, when saturated, as it were, acts in moisture in the same way as it does in air, smells must evidently correspond to tastes. But precisely this fact is found in 10 certain flavours and savours. For there are pungent, sweet, harsh, astringent, oily smells, and one might say that rancid odours correspond to bitter tastes. As the former, therefore, are revolting to the taste, so rancid tastes are revolting to the smell. Evidently, then, that quality which in water is flavour, in air and water is smell. This explains why cold and frost blunt flavours 11 and obscure smells. For cold and frost nullify heat, which is the moving and active principle here.

There are two sorts1 of odorous objects ; for it is untrue that there are no varieties of odorous objects, as some maintain. Such varieties do exist. One must, however, explain in what sense this is true and in what 12 sense not true. One variety corresponds, as clearly

1 The agreeable and disagreeable.

174 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de sensu

explained, to flavour, and contains the pleasurable and painful accidentally. For owing to the fact that these smells concern our nutritive power, they are agreeable to those who have desire and disagreeable to those who are sated and feel no desire. Neither is the smell agreeable to those to whom the food which has the smell is disagreeable.

13 Consequently, these smells contain, as we said, the pleasant and painful accidentally, and this is the reason why they are common to all animals. There is another variety of smells which are pleasant in themselves, e.g. the fragrance of flowers. For they incite us in no respect, whether more or less, to food, nor do they in any way contribute to the stirring of any desire ; they have rather the opposite effect. What Strattis 1 says, mocking Euripides, is true :

When lentil-soup you cook, Pray, add no spices to it.

444 a By mixing such spices in their potations, men now-a-days

14 force pleasure, as is their habit, believing that the pleasure which is really derived from two sensations2 is

15 derived from only one. Smell of this sort is peculiar to man, but smell that is based on flavour is sensed by other animals,3 as remarked above. The varieties of the

1 Strattis, of Athens, the comedian (Jlor. 410 B.C.). Cf. Meinecke, Fragm. Com. Graec. p. 436.

2 The pleasures of eating and drinking are combined from smell and taste.

3 The qualities of smell are few and inexact, because of the lack of development of this sense in man {De an. 421a 10). Man possesses the most delicate sense of touch and the worst sense of smell. In the lower animals smell is merely a handmaid of touch, while in man it not only serves in this capacity but interprets the odoriferous world as pleasant and unpleasant per se, i.e. apart from its association with flavour.

chap.v. FUNCTION OF SMELL 175

latter, because the pleasant is incidental, are classified in terms of flavours, which does not apply to the former class, because there the smell is pleasant or disagreeable in itself. The reason why this class of smells is peculiar to man is because of the condition of his brain. For 16 man's brain is by nature cool, and the blood in its. surrounding veins is thin and pure, though easily chilled (which explains why the evaporation of food when cooled in this region causes catarrhal colds), and so this variety of smell has been developed in man as beneficial to his health.1 For no other function can be ascribed to this class of smells, although this function is evidently 17 exercised by them. Food, whether solid or liquid, although agreeable, is often harmful ; but the smell exhaled from savoury food indicates, one may say, what is absolutely and always beneficial to man in whatsoever 18 condition he is. Consequently, smell is mediated by respiration, not in all animals, but in man, the quad- rupeds and such other sanguineous animals as have a larger share in the employment of air. For smells being transmitted to the brain by virtue of the levity of the heat in them, the regions about the brain are thereby the more healthy. For the potency of smell is naturally warm. "'\N~ature employs respiration for two purposes ; 19 its main purpose is to assist the functioning of the chest ; its secondary function is to transmit smell. For in respiration the air produces, as it were in passage, motion in the nostrils.2"'* Smell of this sort is peculiar to 20

1 Owing to their warm, dry nature.

2 This sentence is out of connection with the following one, and the passage enclosed in asterisks should probably be inserted at the markf 4446 7.

176

ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY

DE SENSTJ

human nature, for man has, in proportion to his size, the largest and moistest brain of all animals. For this reason man is the only animal, one may say, that senses the smell of flowers and similar smells, and finds pleasure in them. For the warmth and movement in these 444 4 smells is proportional to the excess of moisture and coolness in the brain. To the other animals that are

21 endowed with lungs for respiration, nature has given the perception of another kind of smell, so as to avoid the creation of two sense-organs. It is enough for these respiring animals that they have the sensation of only one class of smells, while man discriminates both

22 classes. tThat the non-respiring animals possess the sense of smell is evident. For fishes and all the varieties of insects, on account of the connection between food and smell, distinguish smells with precision and at a distance, as we observe in the case of bees and that variety of small ants sometimes called cnips l and purple sea-fish, as well as in the case of many other similar animals which have a keen sense of smell for food. The organ of sensation

23 is not so clearly defined. One might, therefore, raise the question as to the organ of the sense of smell, although smell is mediated exclusively by respiration (this is plainly so in all respiring animals). None of the above- mentioned animals, however, respire, and yet they perceive smells, unless we are to assume an additional

1 The term ' Cnips ' has come into use in Zoology to describe a beetle allied to the Cryptarcha (cf. E. Reitter, Verh. Ver., Brunn, xii. 1873, p. 163). The reference here, however, appears to be to some small variety of ant such as the formica flava, or to the common red ant {monomorium pharaonis, cf. Comstock, Manual for the Study of Insects, p. 643).

SMELL AND RESPIRATION

177

sense beyond the five, and this is impossible. For it is 24 smell that senses the odorous, and these animals detect odour, though perhaps not in the same way as respiring animals. In respiring animals the breath lifts up a superficial membrane, a sort of cover, as it were (for which reason they do not smell without respiration), - whereas in the non-respiring animals1 this is lacking, just as over the eyes some animals have eyelids and without lifting these do not see, while others are hard-eyed and have no lids, and so do not need to lift any covering, but see at once from the moment they are able to see. And 25 so, too, no other animal feels discomfort from a smell which is intrinsically malodorous, unless it chances to be harmful. But by these harmful smells animals are sometimes destroyed, just as men often get a headache from coal-gas and frequently lose their lives. In the same way other animals are destroyed by sulphur and asphalt fumes, and because they are so affected by such 445 fumes they avoid them. But for malodour, as such, they 26 take no thought (although many vegetables have bad smells), excepting in so far as taste or food is influenced 27 by it.

Inasmuch as the number of the senses is uneven, and every uneven number has a middle term, it seems that smell occupies a middle position between the senses that

1 In aquatic animals gills perform a function analogous to the lungs in respiring animals. A similar function is performed in insects by the membrane at the junction of abdomen and trunk {De resp. 4786 15, 475a 8). The gills in fishes and the membrane in insects do not, how- ever, appear to mediate smell, as the lungs do in respiring animals. Owing to the semi-tangible nature of odour, it appears to act directly in these cases, i.e. by impinging immediately on the sense-organ without the assistance of inhalation.

M

176 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de sensu

human nature, for man has, in proportion to his size, the largest and moistest brain of all animals. For this reason man is the only animal, one may say, that senses the smell of flowers and similar smells, and finds pleasure in them. For the warmth and movement in these 444^ smells is proportional to the excess of moisture and coolness in the brain. To the other animals that are

21 endowed with lungs for respiration, nature has given the perception of another kind of smell, so as to avoid the creation of two sense-organs. It is enough for these respiring animals that they have the sensation of only one class of smells, while man discriminates both

22 classes. tThat the non-respiring animals possess the sense of smell is evident. For fishes and all the varieties of insects, on account of the connection between food and smell, distinguish smells with precision and at a distance, as we observe in the case of bees and that variety of small ants sometimes called cnips 1 and purple sea-fish, as well as in the case of many other similar animals which have a keen sense of smell for food. The organ of sensation

23 is not so clearly defined. One might, therefore, raise the question as to the organ of the sense of smell, although smell is mediated exclusively by respiration (this is plainly so in all respiring animals). None of the above- mentioned animals, however, respire, and yet they perceive smells, unless we are to assume an additional

1 The term ' Cnips ' has come into use in Zoology to describe a beetle allied to the Cryptarcha (cf. E. Reitter, Verh. Ver., Briinn, xii. 1873, p. 163). The reference here, however, appears to be to some small variety of ant such as the formica flava, or to the common red ant {monomorium pharaonis, cf. Comstock, Manual for the Study of Insect*, p. 643).

chap. v. SMELL AND RESPIRATION 177

sense beyond the five, and this is impossible. For it is 24 smell that senses the odorous, and these animals detect odour, though perhaps not in the same way as respiring animals. In respiring animals the breath lifts up a superficial membrane, a sort of cover, as it were (for which reason they do not smell without respiration), whereas in the non-respiring animals1 this is lacking, just as over the eyes some animals have eyelids and without lifting these do not see, while others are hard-eyed and have no lids, and so do not need to lift any covering, but see at once from the moment they are able to see. And 25 so, too, no other animal feels discomfort from a smell which is intrinsically malodorous, unless it chances to be harmful. But by these harmful smells animals are sometimes destroyed, just as men often get a headache from coal-gas and frequently lose their lives. In the same way other animals are destroyed by sulphur and asphalt fumes, and because they are so affected by such 445 a fumes they avoid them. But for malodour, as such, they 26 take no thought (although many vegetables have bad smells), excepting in so far as taste or food is influenced 27 by it.

Inasmuch as the number of the senses is uneven, and every uneven number has a middle term, it seems that smell occupies a middle position between the senses that

1 In aquatic animals gills perform a function analogous to the lungs in respiring animals. A similar function is performed in insects by the membrane at the junction of abdomen and trunk {De resp. 4786 15, 475a 8). The gills in fishes and the membrane in insects do not, how- ever, appear to mediate smell, as the lungs do in respiring animals. Owing to the semi-tangible nature of odour, it appears to act directly in these cases, i.e. by impinging immediately on the sense-organ without the assistance of inhalation.

M

178 aristotle's psychology desensu

operate by direct contact, viz. touch and taste on the one

28 hand, and those which function indirectly through a medium, viz. sight and hearing on the other hand. Consequently, the odorous object is something which affects foods (for these fall under the category of the tangible), and, further, it affects audition, because smells are sensed in the media of air and water. Smell, then, is in a way common to these two things, and is found in the tangible, the audible, and the diaphanous. It is with good reason, therefore, that smell has been compared to the imbruing and washing of a dry element

29 found in the moist and liquid. Eegarding the sense in which one may or may not apply the term ' species ' to odours, let the foregoing discussion suffice.

There is a view held by certain Pythagoreans, which is ill-founded. They hold that certain animals feed on

30 smells. Now we observe, in the first place, that food is a composite thing, for the creatures which are nourished are not simple, and consequently there is an excrement of food, sometimes within the animal itself, and sometimes external, as in the case of plants. Further, water when taken alone and unmixed is not fitted to yield nourish- ment, for what is assimilated into the body must be of a solid nature. Again, it is much less reasonable that air

31 can become solid matter. In addition to this, we observe that all animals have a receptacle for food, from which after its entrance the body assimilates it. The sense- organ, however, is situated in the head, and smell enters with a breath-like inhalation, so that it penetrates to the

32 respiratory region. That smell, as such, does not contri- bute to nourishment, is plain. That it does, however,

chap. v. SMELL AND NUTRITION 179

contribute to health, is evident from the sensation itself and from what has been said,1 so that what flavour is to the nutritive organ and to the parts nourished, this smell is to health. Let these, then, be our conclusions regard- 445 ^ ing the several sense-organs.

1 Namely from its association with food and from the effect of inhaled warmth on the head.

CHAPTER VI.

One might raise the question whether, supposing all bodies to be infinitely .divisible, the sensible qualities of bodies are also infinitely divisible, such qualities as colour, flavour, smell, sound, weight, cold, heat, lightness, rough- ness, and softness. Or must we say that this is impos- sible ? For every one of these qualities produces sensation. They all receive their name from their

2 capacity to stimulate sensation. Therefore sensation must be infinitely divisible, and every magnitude must be sensible. For it is impossible to perceive a white object without its having dimensions. Were this not true, it would be possible to have a body without colour or weight or any similar quality, in which case it would be

3 absolutely imperceptible, for these qualities constitute the sensible. The sensible then would have to be com- posed of the non-sensible. But it must be composed of sensible qualities, for it cannot be composed of mathe- matical elements. And, furthermore, what organ could we use for the discrimination and cognition of such elements ? Could we employ reason ? But they are not rational elements, neither does reason think the external

180

dbsensu SENSE AND MAGNITUDE 181

world, excepting in conjunction with sensation.1 At the same time, if this view of the infinite divisibility of sensible qualities were true, it would appear to furnish support for the advocates of atomic magnitudes. For in this way the 4 problem would be solved. It is, however, impossible. This subject has been discussed in our treatise On Motion? In the solution of these questions one will see why it is that the various forms of colour, flavour, sound, and other sensible qualities, are determinate. For in things that have extremes, the internal properties must also be determinate. The opposite is an extreme. Now, every 5 sensible quality implies opposition, e.g. in colours, white and black; in flavour, sweet and bitter. And in everything else the opposites form extremes. The continuous is there- fore divisible3 into infinite unequal parts, but into deter- minate equal parts. Now, whatever is not in its own nature continuous is divisible into determinate forms. Inasmuch 6 as qualities must be interpreted as forms, and inasmuch as continuity is always given in these, we must suppose a difference between the potential and actual. This is why the ten thousandth part of a visible grain of millet is unseen, although the eye rests upon it, and so too a 446 a quarter tone is undetected by hearing, although the whole

1 Reason thinks the external world only in terms of images, which are derived from sensation {De an. 432a 8).

2 The reference is to the last three books of the Physics, which are often referred to by Aristotle as -rrepl Kivrjaews (cf. 272a 30, 299a 10, 318a 3, 1049& 36). The particular reference here is to the discussion of ' continuity ' and ' divisibility' in Physics, 213a 21 ff.

3 All magnitudes are infinitely divisible {Phys. 206a 10 ff. ), and all number is capable of being infinitely increased. Although magnitudes are infinitely divisible, their infinity is only potential. The infinitely small particle has only a notional existence.

182 aristotle's psychology desensf

7 continuous melody is heard. But the interval from, mean to extreme is not appreciable to us. And the same thing applies to the excessively small amongst other sensible objects. They are discernible potentially, but not actually, and when regarded in isolation. A foot-line is contained in a two-foot line potentially, but actually only

8 after division has been made. When excessively small parts like these are separated off, it is reasonable to suppose that they would be lost in their environment,

9 just as a tiny particle of flavour is lost in the sea. Nevertheless, since this excessively small particle, when regarded in itself and in isolation, is imperceptible (for the excessively small has only a potential existence in a body that is more discernible), neither is any sensible object of this sort, in isolation, actually perceptible, and yet it is a sensible object, because it is so potentially, and will be actually so, when added on to something. We have now

io explained that certain magnitudes and qualities are imper- ceptible, and have stated the reason for this, and have shown in what sense things are perceptible, and in what sense they are not. When, however, inherent qualities are so constituted in reference to themselves as to be actually perceptible, and not merely so in conjunction with an entire body, but also when regarded alone, then

ii colours, flavours, and sounds, must be numerically limited. One might raise the question whether sensible objects or the movements excited by sensible objects whatever be the way in which sensation is effected by their activity are first transmitted to a medium, as appears to be the case with smell and sound. For a person standing near by has an earlier perception of a smell,

chap. vi. MEDIUM OF SENSATION 183

and a sound reaches one sometime after a blow. Is the 12 same thing true of the visible and of light ? According to Empedocles sunlight is first transmitted to a medium before it reaches the eye or the earth, and this seems to 13 be reasonable. For whatever is moved is moved from one point to another, so that a certain time must elapse in which motion from one point to another takes place. But all time is divisible, and consequently there is a moment when the ray is not yet visible, but is still in 446 £ transit in the medium. Also if everything at the same 14 moment hears and has heard, and in a word perceives and has perceived and there is no time process in sensations, nevertheless they lack this process in the same way 1 in which sound, after the blow has been struck, has not yet reached the ear.2 The shifting of 15 letters also shows this plainly, because their movement takes place in a medium. For people appear not to have heard what was said because the air3 has shifted. Is this true also of colour and light ? For it is not owing 16 to a particular condition that one thing sees and another is seen, like two equivalent terms. For it would not then have been necessary for either to be in a given position. For when things are equivalent, nearness or remoteness from each other makes no difference. It is 17 reasonable that succession in time should be found in sound and smell, for like air and water, they are

1 Read o^oi'ws for ofiojs.

2 The passage of time has taken place in the medium, although one may not be conscious of it. Aristotle defines time as the measure or number of motion (Physics, 219a 10 ff ; De coelo, 279a 14).

3 The letters have become shifted in the air or medium, so that one hears a word wrongly.

184 aristotle's psychology desensu

continuous, and yet their movement is divisible, and so it sometimes happens that the nearest and most remote persons perceive the same smell, and at other times this is not the case.

18 Some persons find a difficulty also in the following. It is impossible, some say, for different persons to hear, see, or smell the same thing in the same way. For it is impossible for several persons who are separate from each other to hear and smell alike ; in that event the

19 unitary object of sensation would have to be separated from itself. The primary stimulus, as a bell, frankincense, or a fire, is perceived by all as numerically one and the same, but in its peculiar qualities it is perceived with numerical differences, though in its essential nature as one and the same thing ; for which reason many persons see, smell, or hear the same thing at the same time. One is not concerned here, however, with bodies, but with qualities and motion (otherwise we should not have this phenomenon), which are impossible apart from body.

20 The question of light is different ; for light has a sub- stantial nature and is not a motion 1 ; in general the same determinations are not to be applied to trans- formation and motion. Spatial motions take place, as one might suppose, first into a medium (sound is thought to be the motion of something subject to spatial change),

447 # whereas that which undergoes transformation does so in a way different from spatial change. It is possible that transformation takes place in mass and not first by

1 Empedocles had described light as motion (cf. De an. 418& 20). Aristotle on the other hand regards it as a qualitative change in the diaphanous. It, therefore, represents a condition in a physical body (air or water), vid. note 1, p. 159.

chap. vi. MEDIUM OF SENSATION 185

halves, as in the case of water which freezes at once 21 entire. Nevertheless, if what is being heated or frozen should be of considerable bulk, one part is affected by the adjacent part, and the first part undergoes changes through its own alteration, and it is not necessary that the entire mass undergo alteration at the same time. Taste would also be subject to the same conditions as 22 smell, if we lived in a medium of water and perceived smells from a distance without contact. When we have a medium for the sense-organ, it is reasonable to suppose we do not receive all our impressions at once, excepting in the instance of light, on grounds already mentioned. And sight is also excepted on the same grounds, for light is the cause of sight.

CHAPTEE VII.

Another similar problem touching sensation arises here. viz. whether or not it is possible to experience two sensations at one and the same moment of time, supposing it to be true that the stronger stimulus always displaces the weaker. For this reason, persons do not see an object that falls upon the eye, if they chance to be deep in thought, or exercised by fear, or listening to a loud sound. Let

2 this serve as a fundamental truth and let us also observe that it is easier to perceive what is simple than what is mixed, e.g. it is easier to taste unmixed wine than mixed, and so with honey and colour, and it is easier to dis- tinguish the highest note when taken alone than when heard in accord with the octave, because the two things

3 obscure each other. This occurs in cases where a unity is produced from several elements. If, then, the stronger displaces the weaker stimulus, it must happen, in case they are simultaneous, that even the stronger stimulus becomes weaker than it would be if it were perceived alone. For the weaker when mixed with it detracts from its clearness, supposing it to be true that every-

186

desensu FUSION OF SENSATIONS 187

thing taken simply is more accurately perceptible. If the two are equal neither one will be perceived, for they will counteract each other equally. But it is impossible 4 to have a simple sensation. Consequently, we shall have either no sensation at all or a new one fused out of both elements. And this appears to be what actually happens with mixed elements, so long as they are mixed. Since 5 a fusion of certain things is possible and of others not, the latter are such as fall within the province of different senses. (For where extremes are opposite, fusion is possible, but it is not possible to form white and acute 447 £ into a unity, excepting in an accidental sense, not how- ever in the sense in which a union between acute and grave is possible.) It is, then, impossible to have a simultaneous sensation of these qualities. For the 6 stimuli being equal destroy each other, since a unitary stimulus is not derivable from them. If, however, they are unequal, the stronger stimulus produces the sensation ; for the soul more readily perceives two stimuli simul- taneously when only one sense is concerned in the single act of sensation, as e.g. acute and grave. For simul- taneous sensation on the part of a single sense is more easily attained than is the action of two senses, such as sight and hearing. But it is not possible to perceive 7 two things simultaneously with one sense unless they are fused. For the fusion will form a unity and a single sense can perceive a single thing and the single sensation is a chronological unit. So then one necessarily perceives fused stimuli simultaneously, because they are perceived by a sense-process which in actuality is single. The single sense in actuality perceives a numerically

188 aristotle's psychology desensu

single object ; the single sense in potentiality perceives a specifically single object.1 If the sensation, therefore, is in actuality single, it will interpret the sense-object

3 as a single thing. The sensations must then be fused. When they are not fused, the sensations will be in actuality two. However, there must be a single actuality which corresponds to a single potentiality and a single moment of time; for the stimulation and exercise of a single sense is once for all single and its potentiality is single. It is consequently impossible to

^ perceive two objects at one time with a single sense. But if two objects that fall under a single sense cannot be perceived simultaneously, this is plainly much less possible when they fall under two senses, as e.g. white and sweet.2 For the soul seems to denote what is numerically one not otherwise than in terms of simultaneity; the specifically one in terms of the discriminating sense and io the character of the thing. By this I mean that white and black, which are specifically different, are supposedly discriminated by the same sense ; also sweet and bitter are discriminated by the same sense, although a different sense from the former one. On the other hand, the method of perceiving opposites is different, while co- ordinated pairs are perceived in the self-same manner, e.g. just as taste perceives the sweet, so sight perceives the

1 Actual sensation concerns only a given quality, e.g. white ; potential sensation, on the other hand, concerns a given kind of quality, e.g. colour.

2 Aristotle concludes that the only way in which several sensations may be simultaneously experienced is by their fusion. By the process of fusion, however, they are reduced to unity and the sense experience is no longer manifold but unitary.

chap. vii. CO-ORDINATE SENSATIONS 189

white ; as the sense of sight perceives the black, so the former sense perceives bitter. Further, if the sense- 448 a processes of opposites are opposite to each other, and if it 1 1 is impossible for opposites to coexist in the same in- divisible thing, then where opposites fall under a single sense, as e.g. sweet and bitter, they cannot be perceived simultaneously. And similarly it can be proven that 12 things which are not opposites cannot be simultaneously perceived, for some colours partake of white and others of black and this applies equally to other sensations, e.g. amongst flavours certain ones have the character of sweet and others of bitter. Neither can fused objects be simultaneously perceived, for their ratios have the character of contrariety, e.g. the octave and the fifth, unless they are perceived as one. In this way and not 13 otherwise a single ratio of extremes is produced. For in any other case there will be produced at once the ratio of the many to the few, and of the uneven to the even, and on the other hand the ratio of the few to the many, and of the even to the uneven. If co-ordinates which 14 are specifically different, are further removed from each other and differ more than things that are specifically the same {e.g. sweet and white I mention as co-ordinates, but specifically different), and sweet differs from black more than white does, it would be still less possible for these opposites to be perceived simultaneously than it would be for opposites specifically the same. So that if the 15 latter are not simultaneously perceptible, neither would the former be.

In regard to the opinion of certain writers who treat the subject of harmony, and say that sounds do not

190 aristotle's psychology desensu

really reach us at the same moment, but only appear to do so and we do not notice this, the time being imper- ceptible, the question is whether their opinion is right or

16 not. Here, also, one might perhaps say that we only appear to hear and see at the same time, because the intervening time is not perceived. This is incorrect ; it is impossible for time to be imperceptible, or for us to be unconscious of it, but every moment is perceptible.1

17 For when one perceives one's self or something else in continuous time, it is impossible for one to be then unconscious that one is ; but if there is in continuous time a moment of such duration that it is altogether imperceptible, it is evident that one would then be unconscious of one's own existence, or would not know whether or not one sees and perceives. Further,

448 £ even if one has perception, time would not exist and there would be no object nor any moment in which sensation should take place, unless it were in the sense that one sees in a part of time or a part of the object, if there is a measure of time or object, which, owing to its smallness, is totally imperceptible. For if one sees the entire earth, one also perceives time itself in its continuity, and not in any of its isolated moments. Let

18 C B represent a time-division in which one has no perception. One sees, then, in a particular part of the whole or sees a particular part, just as one sees the entire earth, viz. by seeing a definite part of it, and how far one walks in a year, viz. by seeing how far one walks in a definite part of a year. But in the division B C there is no perception. Now, by virtue of

1 On the 'minimum visible ' see Lewes, Aristotle, p. 253.

chap. vii. SIMULTANEITY 191

perceiving the whole A B in some definite part of it, one is said to perceive even the entire earth. And 19 the same reasoning holds good of A C. For one always perceives in a part and a part, and it is impossible to perceive the entirety. And so every thing is per- ceptible, but one does not see what its extent is. For one sees the magnitude of the sun and of the four-cubit measure from a distance ; they are not seen, however, in their real size, but sometimes they seem indivisible, and one does not see the indivisible. The reason for this has been stated in the foregoing. 20 One concludes from this that there is no imperceptible time.1

We must take into consideration the above-mentioned problem, whether or not it is possible to have several simultaneous sensations. By 'simultaneous' I mean such as are experienced in the same part of the soul and in one indivisible moment of time. In the first place, then, 21 is it possible that the sensations be simultaneous in the sense that they are experienced in different parts of the soul, and not in one indivisible part, though by parts which are indivisible in the sense of forming a continuous whole ? Or, to take first what affects the single sense, as e.g. sight, shall we say that if different colours are sensed by different parts of sight, it will then have several parts specifically the same ? For its repeated sensations belong to the same species. But 22

1 Aristotle defines time (note 2, p. 183) as the measure or number of motion, but time cannot exist apart from mind, as number cannot exist apart from a calculator, and the sole calculator is mind (Phys. 223a 16 ff.).

2 Read Tavra (supported by most of the mss. ) for ravra.

192 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de sensu

if one says that, as in the instance of our two eyes, a certain unity and single activity is produced, so nothing prevents our regarding the soul in the same way. If, however, the combination of both forms an unit, then that which is perceived will be an unit, and if they remain uncombined, then the result will likewise be

23 uncombined. Again, the same sensations will be mani- fold, in the sense in which one speaks of sciences as

449 a manifold. For neither is there any actuality apart from its corresponding potentiality, nor is there any sensation apart from actuality. If one does not experi- ence simultaneously the sensations which occur in a single indivisible part of the soul, it is clear that one does not experience others simultaneously For it is simpler to perceive these several things simultaneously than it is to perceive generically different things simultaneously.

24 But if the soul senses sweet with one part and white with another part, the derivative of these two is either an unit or it is not an unit. But it must be an unit, for the perceiving organ is an unit. What is the unit, then, with which this organ is concerned ? For we have no unit from sweet and white. There must, therefore, be some unitary principle in the soul, whereby it perceives things as wholes,1 as remarked above, but things generic- ally different are sensed by different organs. Is then

25 the principle whereby we perceive sweet and white a single organ, in so far as these qualities are united. but when they are actually isolated, is it a different

1This function is ascribed to the 'common sense,' where the various experiences of the individual senses are fused into a whole or the percept. Cf. Introduction, Chap. iv.

chap. vii. LIMITS OF PERCEPTION 193

organ that senses each of them ? What applies to the things themselves, applies similarly to the soul. For numerically one and the same thing is white and sweet, and possesses many other qualities, unless the qualities be regarded as isolated from one another, and yet the essential nature of each quality is different. One must likewise conclude in reference to the soul that one 26 and the same principle (numerically regarded) perceives everything, although its mode of expression is different, in some cases generically different, and in others specifically different. Simultaneous sensations, therefore, are experienced in one and the same principle of the soul, but not in one and the same relation to this principle.

It is evident that every sensible object has a certain magnitude, and that it is impossible to perceive what is indivisible. There is a point from which it is im-27 possible for one to see, viz. a point of infinite removal, but the point from which vision is possible is deter- minate. The same applies to the odorous and audible and to such sensations as are not tactual. There is an extreme point of remoteness from which vision is no longer possible, and a point of nearness at which vision begins. This point must be indivisible, and what is 28 beyond it is not perceptible, and what is on this side of it must be perceptible. If, indeed, an indivisible thing is perceptible, then it will follow when one places it at the extreme point from which it is no longer visible, and again at the point where perception begins, that it is simultaneously visible and invisible. And this is impossible.

194 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de sbnsd

449^ We1 have now treated, in general and in particular, the subject of the organs and objects of sensation. In what remains, we must first investigate the subject of memory and of memory's process.

1Bekker in the editions of Berlin (quarto) and of Oxford (octavo) transfers this paragraph to the beginning of the tractate On Memory. For a critical examination of the arrangement of the text vid. Freudenthal in Rhein. Museum, Vol. 24, p. 393.

ON MEMORY AND RECOLLECTION.1

CHAPTER I

In regard to memory and its process, we must determine what its nature is, by what agency it is produced, and to what psychical organ the phenomenon of memory, as well as that of recollection, is to be ascribed. For

1 Aristotle makes the following distinction between memory (fxvrj/xr]) and recollection (dvd/j.vr)cns) : the former is the reproduction of a past experience accompanied by the consciousness that the experience has been previously had ; the latter is the deliberate reproduction of the same experience and is based on reflection. The former is possessed by the lower animals and the latter by man only. Plato had already made a distinction between memory and recollection (Phaedo, 73 B ff., Philebus, 34 B). The passive presence of residual sensations in the soul is memory, while their active recall to consciousness is recollection. In the Meno the whole of knowledge is resolved into recollection or reminiscence (dvdfivvcns), learning being only the stimulation or revival of knowledge congenitally in us. In a note which Grote meant to be added (directions to this effect are recorded in the MS.) to Chap. XX. of his Plato and the Other Companions of Sokrates, he says : " The doctrine of Reminiscence declared and illustrated by Sokrates in the Platonic Menon {irao-a fiddvais dv d^vncns) bears much analogy to the Development-Hypothesis espoused by Mr. Herbert Spencer ; an extension and special application of the large views opened by Mr. Darwin respect- ing the origin of species. Each individual animal is assumed to begin

195

196 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de mem.

the same persons are not endowed with good memory and good recollection, but as a rule phlegmatic natures remember well, while the quick and ready-witted are

2 apt at recollection.

First of all we must grasp what is understood by the object of memory. For one is often mistaken about this. The future cannot be the object of memory ; this is rather the object of conjecture and expectation (and we might even have a science of expectation, as some describe the subject of prophecy). Neither can the present be its subject-matter, for our senses are concerned with this. By sensation we do not have cognizance either of the future or of the past, but only of the

3 present. Memory, on the other hand, regards the past. No person would say that he remembers the present while 1 it is present, e.g. that he remembers seeing the white object while he sees it ; neither does one remember the object of contemplation, so long as the act of con- templation and thought continues. But one merely says that in the former case one sees, and, in the latter, one knows. When, however, one possesses knowledge or sen- sation which is not in actuality, then one remembers that the angles of a triangle are equal to two right angles, because one has learned it or thought it out, or, on the other

existence with a large stock of congenital predispositions and aptitudes engrained in its nervous system as the result of an ' infinitude of past experiences ' not indeed of its own but of its progenitors. Hence arise all its instincts, and many of its mental combinations which go beyond instinct. See Mr. Spencer's Psychology, pp. 577-583-619." Extract from the mss. of "Grote's Papers" in the Bodleian Library, Oxford (ms. add. D. 85, p. 37).

1 Read ore for on.

chap. i. MEMORY AND TIME 197

hand, has merely heard it or visually observed it, or found it out in some such way. For when memory actually takes place, one must say that the process in the soul is such that one formerly heard, perceived, or thought the thing. Consequently, memory is neither sensation nor conceptual 4 thought, but it is the condition or modified form of one of these, after the lapse of time. There is no memory of the present in the present moment, as we have said, but there is perception of the present, expectation of the future, and memory of the past. Consequently, all memory is associated with time. Therefore, only those creatures that have perception of time, have memory, and memory attaches to that organ whereby time is perceived.1 JSTow we have already discussed imagin- 5 ation in the treatise On the Soul 2 and we concluded there that thought is impossible without an image. For we find in thought the same conditions as in drawing 450 a figures. In the latter without needing a triangle of a definite magnitude, we nevertheless draw a triangle of definite size. So, too, the thinking mind, even if it does not think a magnitude, still places a quantitative body before its eyes, although it does not think it as such. If 6 it is the nature of the quantitative in an indefinite sense with which the mind is concerned, then thought represents it under the form of a definite quantity, but thinks it merely as quantity. The reason why it is impossible to think anything apart from continuity (even things that are not subject to the laws of time cannot be thought

xThe organ of memory aud the organ whereby we perceive time is the central organ or heart (451a 17).

2Cf. De an. 421b 14 ff. ; 434a ff.; 431a 17.

198 aristotle's psychology demem.

without time *) is a problem that belongs elsewhere.2 We must be conscious of magnitude and motion 3 by the same faculty whereby we are conscious of time. An

7 image is a product of sensation in general. Evidently, therefore, the cognition of these things is to be ascribed to the primary power of sense. Memory, even the memory of concepts, does not take place without an image. Consequently, memory concerns the faculty of thought accidentally and the primary power of sense intrinsically.4 It is, therefore, possessed by other animals, and is not peculiar to man and creatures endowed with opinion

8 and thought. If it were a property belonging to the conceptual powers, it would not be found in many animals outside of man, perhaps in none of the brutes, seeing that they do not, as a matter of fact, possess it because they all lack the sense of time. For in an activity of memory, as we remarked before, there is always the additional consciousness that one has seen or

9 heard or learned this in time past. Prior and later are properties of time. In reply to the question to what part of the soul memory is to be ascribed, it is plain that it belongs to the same part as imagination. The objects of

1 Aristotle is referring probably to the heavenly bodies and their eternal laws.

2 Topics of this kind Aristotle refers to the First Philosophy or Metaphysics.

3 Magnitude and motion are classified by Aristotle amongst the ' com- mon sensibles ' and as such they are perceived by the ' common sense ' whose organ is the heart.

4 In other words memory is a revived sense-experience and is due to the direct function of the primary organ of sense (the heart) ; it concerns the faculty of thought only accidentally, viz. in furnishing it with images which are converted into concepts that are essentially different from images.

chap. i. MEMORY IS A PICTURE 199

memory, intrinsically, are the same as the objects of imagination ; accidentally, they are such objects as are impossible without imagination.1

The question might be asked : How in the world is it that while a mental impression persists, although the thin^ itself is no longer at hand, one remembers what is not present ? Evidently we must regard this phenomenon 10 which through the mediation of sensation is produced in the soul and in that part of the body2 which possesses sensation (whose persistence we call memory), as similar to a painting. For an active stimulus stamps on the soul a sort of imprint of the sensation, analogous to stamping with a seal-ring. For this reason, too, persons who are n deeply moved by passion or by the ardour of youth do 450 £ not remember, just as if the effort and the seal were applied to running water. In other persons, because of their worn-out condition, like old buildings, or because of the hardness of their receptive principle, no impression is made. Consequently, the very young and the aged have 12 poor memories. For the former are in a fluent condition owing to their growth, and the latter are unstable owing to their decay.3 Likewise the excessively quick and the excessively slow seem to have poor memories. The

1 When the objects of imagination are recognized as past experiences or copies of past sensations they are called memories. They are, there- fore, in their essential nature or intrinsically the same as the objects of imagination. Objects of memory in an accidental sense are, perhaps, such elements as do not attach to the image as such, but are not possible without it, e.g. the circumstance that Coriscus (who is the image proper) was a native of Scepsis.

2 Namely, in the heart.

3 It is this passage which Reid distorts in his review of Aristotle's theory of memory. Cf. Works, ed. Hamilton, p. 353.

200 aristotle's psychology demem.

former are too moist and the latter too hard. Con- sequently, the image does not last in the souls of the

[3 former, and in the latter it does not fasten. If such is the truth regarding memory, the question arises whether one remembers the impression or the thing from which the impression was derived. For if it is this impression of ours which is the object of memory, then we do not remember what is absent. On the other hand, if it is the thing that we remember, how does it come that while we perceive this impression we remember what we do not perceive, viz. the absent thing?1 And if memory is analogous to an imprint or picture within us, why should the perception of precisely this thing be the memory of something else, and not the memory of just this picture ?

'4 For it is this impression which one contemplates and perceives in actual memory. In what sense then does one remember what is not present ? It would then be possible to see and to hear what is not present. Or is there a sense in which this is possible and in which it

[5 actually occurs ? For example, the animal in a picture is both animal and a copy, and both of these are one and the same thing ; but the mode of existence in the two instances is different, and it is possible to regard this picture both in the sense of animal and in the sense of image, and so it is with the image within us : we must regard it both as something in itself and as the image of something else. In so far as we regard it in its own

1 Aristotle explains further down (4506 30) that the image is not only a thing in itself which we have actually in consciousness, but it is also representative of the external and absent thing, which, though not in consciousness, is thus mediately or representatively remembered.

chap. i. MEMORY AND PHANTASM 201

nature, it is an idea or a mental representation ; in so far as we regard it as belonging to something else, it is a copy 16 or a memory. When, therefore, an actual stimulation of this image takes place, and when the soul perceives it in its own nature, it appears to come to expression as an idea or a phantasm; if however the soul regards it as belonging to something else, then, as in the case of a painting, the soul contemplates it as a copy and as the picture of Coriscus, without having ever seen him. The points of view here and in the case of our regarding a painted animal merely as an animal are different : what arises in the soul in the latter case is purely a thought ; in the 45 1 former case, because the object is there regarded as an image, it appears as a memory. And, consequently, there 17 are times when we do not know, regarding such psychical processes due to earlier sensations, whether they are produced by sense-experience, and we are in doubt whether they are a memory or not.1 At another time it happens we think and recall that we have heard or known the thing in the past. This takes place when 18 after contemplating a thing in its own nature, one shifts one's position and regards it as the copy of another thing. The converse of this also happens, as is shown by the case of Antipheron of Oreos and other ecstatics. For they asserted that their phantasms were real, and that they

xIt is often difficult to decide whether certain apparent memories are merely fictions of imagination or actual past experiences, because imagination is not merely reproductive {alad-qTLKT}) but productive {XoyiaTLKTj). It is, however, impossible to have an unconscious memory. So long as one is not conscious that a given experience or image has been had before, the thing is only a phantasm {(pavraa^a) and not a memory {ixvr)i±bvevfxa). Cf. 4526 26.

202 aristotle's psychology demem.

remembered the things. This phenomenon occurs when [9 one regards as a copy that which is not a copy. Exercise in repeatedly recalling a thing strengthens the memory. This, however, is nothing more nor less than the frequent contemplation of a thing as a copy and not as an object in itself. The nature of memory and of its process has now been explained as the persistent possession of an image, in the sense of a copy of the thing to which the image refers, and it has been further explained to what faculty in us this belongs, viz. to the primary power of sensation, and to that organ whereby we perceive time.

CHAPTEE II.

The subject of recollection remains to be treated. First of all we must take as presuppositions the truths which were established in the treatise On Argumentation} Accordingly, recollection is neither the recovery nor 2 acquirement of a memory. For when one learns or acquires an impression for the first time, one does not recover any memory (for none has preceded), nor does one acquire an initial memory. But when a persistent mental condition and impression is fixed in the soul, then we have memory. Consequently, memory is not produced simultaneously with the production of an impression. Further, in the indivisible complete moment when the 3 impression is first received, the impression and the know- ledge are recorded in the affected subject, if one can call this mental condition and impression, knowledge, (and

1 Themistius and Michael Ephesius think the reference is to the Probhmata. Bonitz, however, considers it more probable that Aris- totle is referring to the airopiai discussed in Ch. I. of the present tractate. Cf. Index to Bekker's Berlin edition sub. voc. 'ApicrTOTeXrjs, 99a 38. If the latter supposition is correct, one will have to give the words X6701 iirixctprj/ACLTiKol the unusual meaning of Initial Treatise, which, however, they might perhaps bear.

203

204 aristotle's psychology demem.

there is nothing to prevent our remembering, in the sense of accident, a certain thing which we know conceptually). But memory as such is not possible until after the lapse of time. For what we remember now, we have previously known or experienced, but what we experience now is

4 not in the present moment remembered. Further, it is 451 b evidently possible to have in memory what we do not

now recollect, but what was once perceived or experienced. When one re-acquires knowledge or sensation (or whatever the mental possession be to which we apply the term memory), ^it is then that one recollects one of the afore-

5 said mental possessions. The process of memory takes place, and memory ensues. Neither do the phenomena of recollection, if their occurrence is the repetition of a previous recollection, follow absolutely the same order, but sometimes they occur in one way and sometimes in another.1 It is possible for the same individual to learn and discover the same thing twice. Eecollection, then, must differ from learning and discovery, and there is need of greater initial latitude here than is the case with learning.2

6 Eecollection is effected, when one suggestion succeeds another in natural order. If the succession is a necessary one, it is plain that when the antecedent suggestion is given, it will excite the succeeding one. If, however, the

1 A given association may at one time awaken a recollection and at another time fail to do so (cf. 452& 1 ff.).

2 In the case of learning and discovery there is a definite and exact process by which a given result may be twice arrived at. In the case of recollection, on the other hand, there is not the same fixity of procedure. There are not only many forms of suggestion and associa- tion, but a given suggestion may not effect the same result in two instances.

chap. ii. ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS 205

succession is not a necessary one, but only customary, the recollection will be stirred generally. But it is a fact 7 that some persons by being impressed only once are trained * in a given way more than others after frequent impressions. And so there are some things which after we have seen once, we remember better than others do who have seen them frequently. When, therefore, we recollect, we awaken certain antecedent processes and continue this until we call up that particular experience, after which the desired one is wont to appear. That is 8 the reason why we hunt through a series in thought, beginning with an object presently before us, or with something else, or with an object that is similar, or opposite, or contiguous.2 In this way, recollection is awakened. For mental movements in these instances are identical in some cases, in others simultaneous with, the desired experience, and in other cases they involve a portion of it, so that there is a small remainder whose stimulation ensues. This then, is the way in which people try to recollect, and without 9 conscious effort they recollect in this way, when the desired experience is recalled as the sequence of another experience. For the most part, however, the desired experience is recalled only after several different suggestions, such as we have described, have preceded.

14 Trained' (idi<rd7)i>cu) means here the acquisition of a fixed habit {'idos) or disposition. In the case of other persons, impressions do not produce a fixed disposition, but are evanescent. Consequently in the latter, a suggestion is ineffective, while it results in recollection in those persons where the impression has become a fixity or 'habit.'

2 The laws of association, ordinarily treated as contiguity and similarity, are here stated by Aristotle as similarity, contrast, and contiguity.

206 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de mem.

One does not at all need to look at the remote and ask how we remember it, but at what lies near before us. For the same method applies to both cases, I mean the method of sequences,1 without any prior effort to find this sequence and without recalling it. For mental

10 movements follow one another, this one after that, by habituation. When a person wants to recall a thing, he will do the following : he will try to gain a starting- point in the process, in sequence to which the desired experience was had. Consequently, recollections which are awakened from the starting-point are most quickly

452 a and best effected. For just as things are mutually related in their order of succession, so also are the

11 mental processes. And such things as have a fixed order are easily remembered, as e.g. mathematical truths. Other things are remembered poorly 2 and with difficulty. Eecollection differs from re-learning in this, that there can be in the former case a sort of self-movement back to that which follows upon the original experience. When this is not done, but the recollection is prompted

12 by another person, then it is no longer memory. Often- times one is unable to recollect a thing, but after searching succeeds in finding it. This seeking and finding is what happens when one awakens a number of experiences and continues to do so until one sets that particular experi- ence in motion upon which the desired thing is attendant. Memory is the possession of an experience potentially

1 This series of sequences is compared by Themistius to a chain, in which if one link be lifted the next will likewise be moved and so on. Cf. Sir William Hamilton's note in Reid's Works, p. 894.

2 Read 0ai/Aws /ecu for cpavXa.

chap. ii. ASSOCIATION OF IDEAS 207

revivable. This process is effected, as was said above, in such way that it comes from the person's own effort and from the movements in his power. One must, however, 13 have a starting-point. And so persons appear sometimes to recall things from local1 suggestions. The reason is that one passes rapidly from one thing to another, e.g. - from milk to the suggested idea of white, from white to air, from air to the moist, and from this one recalls the late autumn, which is the season one was trying to think of. In general, it is the middle, too, of the entire series 14 that seems to be the starting-point for memory. For when a person does not remember earlier, then he does so when he comes to the middle point, or when he does not remember here, then at no other point at all, as is the case e.g. when one passes through the series ABGDEFGH? If one does not remember at H, one remembers when one comes to E, provided one is in quest of F or G. For from that point the movement of suggestion is possible in both directions, towards the point D as well as towards the point F.3 If, however, a person is not in 15 quest of one of these, he will remember on reaching C, and

1 There is no reason for adopting the conjecture of Sir William Hamilton {droira for dwb tottwv 452a 13), which Barthelemy-Saint-Hilaire (Commentary, ad loc.) considers necessary and which Hamilton charac- terises as "absolutely certain" (Keid's Works, p. 905 note).

2 Freudenthal {Rhein. Museum, xxiv. p. 410) thinks we have here a defective text, because in a series of eight elements there is no middle term. It seems, however, hopeless to get anything satisfactory out of the illustration by emendation or reconstruction.

3 Vid. Freudenthal's explanation in the Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophie (vol. ii. p. 2) and Siebeck's in his Unlersuchungen zur Philos. der Griechen (2te Aufl. p. 155). Sir William Hamilton simply distorts the text beyond recognition in order to obtain an intelligible translation, and even then achieves but a meagre success in his aim.

208 aristotle's psychology demem.

if not then, he will remember on reaching A, and this is the case always. But from the same point of suggestion one sometimes remembers and sometimes does not, the reason for which lies in the possibility of movement in more than one direction from the initial point, e.g. from E

16 to F or from E to D. If the movement is influenced by an old suggestion, it takes place in the direction of the more fixed habit.1 For habit is second nature. Conse- quently, we remember easily what we often ponder. For as one definite thin^ succeeds another in nature, so it

17 is also in our activity. Frequent repetition produces nature. Since we find in the realm of nature occurrences

452 £ that violate her laws and are clue to chance, much more do we find this in the realm of custom, to which the term nature cannot be applied in the same sense. The consequence is that a movement here sometimes takes place in one direction and sometimes in another, especially when the mind is distracted from a particular point to

18 something else. Therefore, when one has to remember a name, and remembers one like it, one commits a solecism in regard to it. This then is the way in which recollec- tion takes place.2

The most important thing here is the necessity of appreciating time, whether in a determinate or an in-

19 determinate form. There must be some power whereby we distinguish a longer from a shorter interval. It is natural that the same conditions which apply to magni- tudes, apply here also. For we think what is large and what is remote in space, not because thought extends to

1 Vid. Sully, The Human Mind, Vol. I. p. 201.

2 Namely, through the association of ideas.

CHAP. II.

PROCESSES OF MEMORY

209

the given point, as some say 1 in their explanation of vision (for we can think the non-existent as well as the existent), but because of an analogous process in the mind. For the figures and processes that correspond to things are in the mind itself. What difference will it 20 make, then, whether one thinks what is larger, or the other class of things that are smaller ? For all the internal elements are smaller, and the external have, as it were, a proportional magnitude to them. It is perhaps in the case of distances in space just as it is with figures, one has to assume the possession of another analogous figure in the mind itself. So, e.g. if one draws the lines AB and 21 BE, one produces CD, for AC and CD are proportional. Why does this produce the line CD rather than FG ? Or is this due to the fact that as AF is to AB, so H is to if? For these lines are drawn at the same time. And if one wants to think the line FG, one thinks similarly the line BE, and instead of HI one thinks KL. For these are related to each other as FA to BA.2

1 Empedocles.

2 Freudenthal [Rheiii. Museum, Vol. 24, p. 416) attempts to elucidate this hopelessly difficult passage by the figure :

In this figure Freudenthal makes AB, BE represent sense-impressions ; AF, FG external objects ; AC, CD, notions or concepts ; MH, HI, time objectively regarded ; MK, KL, time subjectively regarded. Consequently, so he goes on . . AB AC AF ., .

to explain: "d^t = 777^ 7^ means tnat

presentations of sense or images of (pavraaia are related to each other as the

0

F B

G /

A /

/ /

C

/D /

;

\ /

M

210 aristotle's psychology demem.

22 When the suggestion of the thing and the suggestion of time coincide, we have actual memory. When, however, one believes one does this without really doing it, one only believes that one remembers. For there is nothing to prevent one's being deceived and fancying that one remembers without this being actually the case. In actually remembering it is impossible that one should not believe one is remembering, but should be uncon- 3 scious of it. For this is just what constitutes memory. If, however, the suggestion of the thing and the sug- gestion of time are separated from each other, then no memory is awakened. The suggestion of time has a two- fold meaning. Sometimes a thing is not remembered in determinate time, e.g. that day before yesterday one 453 a did something or other ; in other instances one remembers in terms of time-measure. Memory, however, takes place even if one does not remember in the latter way.

24 People are wont to say that they remember, although they do not know just when a thing happened, in cases where they are ignorant of the determinate measure of the When.

We have already said that the same individuals are not endowed with good memory and good recollection.

25 Eecollection differs from memory not merely in the time- element, but also because many animals share the endow- ment of memory, while none of the known animals, one

AH A ~F corresponding notions. ~op= pTjf signifies that presentations of sense

are related to each other and the corresponding external objects are re-

A W TT FC HI

lated to each other. -^5=^7 or -dw=-fft signifies that external objects

are related to their sense-impressions as objective time to subjective time.

chap. ii. RECOLLECTION 211

may say, excepting man, is endowed with recollection. The reason for this is that recollection is a sort of syllo- 26 gistic process. In recollection one reasons that one has known or heard or had some such experience of the thing in question, and the process is a sort of inquiry.1 And this is naturally found only in those creatures which have the power of deliberation, and deliberation is a kind of syllogistic procedure.

That this condition affects the body, and that recollec- 27 tion is the search for an image in a corporeal organ,2 is proved by the fact that many persons are made very restless when they cannot recall a thing, and when quite inhibiting3 their thought, and no longer trying to remem- ber, they do recollect nevertheless, as is especially true of the melancholic. For such persons are most moved by images. The reason why recollection does not lie within 28 our power is this : just as a person who has thrown an object can no longer bring it to rest, so too one who recol- lects and goes in search of a thing, sets a corporeal some- thing in motion, in which the desired experience resides. Especially disturbed are such persons as have moisture 29 about the region of sensation ; for they do not easily come to rest after being stirred into motion, until they attain the thing sought for, or the movement has taken its proper course. Consequently, the feelings of anger and

1 In intentional recollection one employs the laws of association deliberately and through reflection ; in spontaneous recollection the same laws apply, but are not deliberately employed.

2 In recollection the organic process is from within to the organs of sense, while in sensation the process is from the periphery to the centre (De an. 4086 17).

3 Read, ical irdvv eTrtx0VTa$> 453a 17.

212 aristotle's psychology demem.

fear, when they once set up a movement, do not cease although opposing movements are started against them,

30 but on the contrary persist towards their own aim. This affection resembles names, melodies, and words, when these are given violent utterance. For after one has

31 ceased, the singing or speaking recurs involuntarily. Further, those whose upper body is too large, and also

453 b dwarfish persons, have less power of recollection than those of the opposite physical structure, because the former are too heavy about the organs of sensation, and because the initial movements cannot persist but are destroyed, and direct movement in the process of recollection cannot

32 readily take place. Also the exceedingly young and the very old do not recollect well on account of their move- ment ; for the latter are in decline, and the former in rapid growth. Furthermore, children are like dwarfs until they advance in age.

We have now treated the subject of memory and its process, its nature and the psychical organ whereby animals remember ; also the subject of recollection, in its nature, its forms, and its causes.

ON SLEEPING AND WAKING.

CHAPTEE I.

We must now consider the subject of sleeping and waking, and ask what they are and whether they are phenomena peculiar to the soul or common to the body 1 and the soul, and if they are common, we must further inquire to what particular organs of the soul and body they belong. Further, we must inquire to what cause this animal function is due and whether all animals share in both sleeping and waking. Or are certain animals endowed with the one, and others exclusively with the other, or are there creatures that are endowed with neither of them, and others with both ? In addition to this we must investigate the nature of dreams and explain why persons sometimes dream2 in sleep and at other times do not. Or shall we say that dreaming always occurs in sleep,

1 Aristotle had himself stated the mixed physiological and psychological character of these opuscules in referring to their subject matter as koivcl tt)s \pvxys nai cwjuaros (436a 7). See also note, 1, p. 145.

2 The subject of Dreams and Prophecy by Dreams is specially treated in separate opuscules. Vid. pp. 231 ff., 247 ff.

213

214 aristotle's psychology de somno

but we do not remember our dreams ? If this is true, what is the explanation ? A further question is whether or not it is possible to foresee future events, and if it is possible, in what sense are they foreseen ? Further, is it possible to foresee only such future events as are per- formed by man or also such as are caused by divine power, and does this foresight apply to what takes place in the course of nature or to the results of accident ?

2 First of all it is evident that both sleeping and waking are to be ascribed to the same organ, for they are contrary functions, and sleep is clearly the negative of waking. Now contraries, whether in the realm of nature or else- where, are always expressed in one and the same organ capable of receiving them and are affections of the same thing, I mean e.g. health and disease, beauty and ugliness, strength and weakness, sight and blindness, hearing and

454 a deafness. This is further evident from the following : it

3 is by the same sign that we recognise a person awake and one asleep. For when a person has sensation we regard him as awake and we believe that every waking person has sensation to a certain extent either of the

4 external world or of internal processes. If, then, waking consists in nothing else than in having sensation, it is evident that by virtue of that organ wherewith one has sensation, waking creatures are awake and sleeping

5 creatures are asleep. But since sensation is not the function exclusively either of the soul or the body (for where there is potentiality there is also a corresponding actuality; but what we understand by sensation in its actual sense, is a psychical process mediated by the body), it is plain that this phenomenon does not belong exclusively

chap. i. SLEEP AND SENSATION 215

to the soul, and on the other hand it is impossible for an inanimate body to experience sensation.1 In earlier 6 treatises2 we have analysed the parts of the soul as we call them, and explained that the nutritive part is different from the other powers in animate bodies, although no other power can exist independently of it. From this it is evident that such living creatures as are endowed only with the functions of growth and decay, do not ex- perience sleeping or waking, as e.g. plants. For they have no organ of sensation, whether separated from or conjoined with the organ of nutrition ; in potentiality and mode of expression these two organs are separable from one another. It is likewise true that there is no 7 creature that continuously wakes or continuously sleeps, but both these conditions are found in the same animals. If an animal has sensation, it is impossible that it should not sleep and wake. Both these phenomena refer to the experience of the primary organ of sensation.3 It is impossible that either of these conditions should be 8 continuously found in the same creature, e.g. that any species of animal should sleep or wake constantly, because whenever we find a natural function, as soon as the time is exceeded during which the function is capable of being exercised, the organ necessarily becomes impotent, just as the eye by exercising vision becomes unable to

1 'Aiadavo/xcu signifies consciousness as well as the physiological process of sensation.

2 Cf. De an. 415a 23 ff. ; 432a 23 ff. ; 434a 22 ff.

3 Namely, the heart. Plants have no central organ (De an. 4116 19), which is necessary to sensation, and without the latter they cannot be said to sleep or wake, sleeping and waking being respectively the activity and quiescence of sensation.

216 aristotle's psychology dbsomwo

perform this function. The same thing applies to the 9 hand, and to every other functioning organ. Now, if there is an organ to which the function of sensation belongs and the time is exceeded during which con- tinuous sensation is possible, then the organ will become

io powerless and no longer perform its function. If, there- fore, waking is defined in terms of this condition, viz. as the release of sensation from a state of impotency, and 454^ if of two contraries one must always be present and the other absent, and if waking is the contrary of sleeping, (and, consequently, one of the two must in every case be present), then sleep would be necessary. Consequently, if

ii this is the nature of sleep, and it consists in a loss of power through excess of waking, and excessive waking is sometimes pathological and sometimes normal (so that the incapacity and its recovery would also have the character of the pathological and normal), it follows that every waking creature must also sleep. For continuous activity is impossible. So, too, there is no creature that

12 can sleep continuously. For sleep is a condition of the sense-orsran which is like being? fettered and held im- mobile. Every sleeping thing, therefore, must have a sense-organ. By sense-organ we mean that which has the capacity of actual sensation. But to have actual sensation in its proper and strict sense and to sleep at the same time is impossible.1 All sleep, then, must be a condition from which waking is possible. Almost all

13 animals, whether their natural abode is the water, air, or

1"0n the whole, the quarrel between Descartes and Locke as to whether the mind ever sleeps is less near to solution than ever." James, Principles of Psychology, vol. i. p. 213.

chap. i. SLEEP AND NUTRITION 217

land, evidently have the power of sleep. For we see all varieties of fishes and molluscs sleeping and every other variety that has eyes. Also, the hard-eyed animals and the insects evidently sleep. The sleep, however, of all such animals is brief. And consequently an observer may not notice whether or not they share in sleep. 14 In the observation of crustaceans it has so far not been clearly established whether they sleep or not. If, however, the foregoing reasoning is convincing, then one will believe that sleep occurs in this class. That all animals, therefore, share in sleep is proven from the foregoing. For the definition of animal is given in terms of the possession of sensation. And we define sleep as in a certain sense the immobility and fettering, as it were, of sensation ; waking as the delivery and release from such condition. No plant can 15 participate in either of these conditions. For without sensation neither sleeping nor waking occurs. Creatures that are endowed with sensation feel pleasure and pain. And when these are felt, desire is also felt. None of these phenomena, however, is found in plants. A proof of this is that the nutritive part performs its own function better during sleep than in a waking state.1 4S5a For at this time nourishment and growth are more rapid, which shows that for these purposes there is no need of the additional power of sensation.

1 It is a generally accepted fact that nutrition is heightened during sleep, which is perhaps due to the fact that digestion during sleep is more regular, being free from mental work or disturbance. Amongst the lower animals it is usual to sleep after eating. Cf. Spitta, Die Schlaf- und Traumzustande, p. 19; Combe, Physiology of Digestion, 10th ed. p. 112.

CHAPTER II.

We must now inquire why it is that sleeping and waking occur, and to what sense, or senses, if there are

2 several, they are due. Since some animals have all the senses and others not, e.g. some do not have sight, whereas touch and taste are universal excepting in cases of abnormal creatures (and mention has made of these in the treatise On the Soul1), and further, since it is impossible for an animal in sleep to experience any sensation whatever, it is clear that we shall necessarily find this condition in all the senses during what we call sleep. For if an animal were to sleep in one part and not in another, then it would have sensation in sleep, which

3 is impossible. Now, in every sense there is a power which is peculiar to it and another power which it has in common with others, e.g. vision is peculiar to the eye, audition to the ear, and, similarly, peculiar powers belong to the other senses. But there is also a kind of common power that is associated with all the particular senses, by virtue of which one is conscious that one

1 De an. 425a 10 ; 4326 23 ; 4336 31. 218

chap. ii. THE CENTRAL SENSE 219

sees and hears. For by means of sight one does not perceive that one sees, and one discriminates and has 4 the power of discrimination between sweet and white, not by virtue of taste or sight, nor by means of the two combined, but by means of a certain power which is common to all the sense-organs. For sensation is unitary and the master-organ of sensation is unitary, although there is an essentially different character that belongs to each category of sensation, e.g. to sound and colour. This common element1 is allied more nearly to 5 the tactual than to any other sense. For the tactual can exist apart from all the other sense-organs, but the others cannot exist apart from it. This, however, was discussed in the studies On the Sotd.2 Sleeping and waking, then, are evidently an affection of this common sense, and are consequently found in all animals. For touch is the 6 only universal sense. Now, if sleep consisted in the fact that all the senses undergo something, then it is remark- able that in cases where it is not necessary, or in a certain sense not possible, for them to be simultaneously active, yet these same senses should become simultaneously in- active and immobile. On the contrary, it is more plausible to suppose that they are not at rest simul- taneously. But the explanation that we have given of 7 these phenomena is a rational one. For when the master- organ that rules over all the others and to which all the

1 The function of consciousness is ascribed to the central or common sense, whose organ, in common with that of touch, is the heart (De sensu 4386 30, 469« 12). The following sentence, in the text, does not mean that the common sense can exist apart from the special senses, but that both touch and the common sense are necessary to the others.

2 De an. 4136 32 ff. ; 4346 23. Vid. also Dejuvent. 4676 28 ff.

220 aristotle's psychology de somno

4553 others are directed, is affected, all the subordinate organs are necessarily affected with it ; on the other hand, when one of the latter is disabled it is not necessary that the

8 master-organ should be disabled also. But it is evident from many considerations that sleep does not consist in the inactivity and non-use of these special senses, nor in their incapacity to experience sensation. For this is just the sort of thing that happens in swooning : swooning is the exhaustion of the senses. And there are also certain other kinds of mental disturbances that resemble this. Also, by compressing the jugular vein, one loses

9 sensation. But whenever there is a loss of the use of sensation, it does not find its explanation in any chance sense nor is it attributable to any haphazard cause, but the explanation is found, as we just now said, in the primary organ of all sensation. For when this is disabled, all the other sense-organs are also necessarily unable to have sensations. When, however, one of these latter loses the power to act, the common sense is not necessarily disabled.

We must inquire to what cause sleep is due, and what

10 sort of an affection it is. Now there are several kinds

of cause 1 (for we speak of cause in the sense of the

1 Aristotle views the world under the aspect of processes dominated by two causal principles form and matter. He conceives of the latter as potentiality, which in a world of movement passes over into a condition of actuality. Actuality is synonymous with form. In organic processes these two things are separable only in abstraction. Form represents the completed condition towards which matter strives. Form is therefore the end, or otherwise expressed, the final cause. Further, as the completed notion of a thing, or that which a thing really and finally is, it is the essential or notional cause. The defi- nition of a thing is its notional cause. Cause {atria) is here, of course, employed in a sense foreign to English usage. There is no idea of

chap. ii. FORM AND MATTER 221

end or purpose; again as the principle of motion, as the material condition, and as the notion or form). First of all, then, when we say that nature acts with a purpose, we mean that this purpose is some good, that rest is provided for every creature whose nature it is to move, and that, being incapable of constant and con- tinuous pleasurable movement, this rest is a necessary n and useful thing (and the metaphorical term 'rest' is with perfect accuracy applied to sleep as repose). Conse- quently, sleep exists for the preservation of animals, and the waking state is its final cause and purpose. For 12 sensation and thought are the final purpose of all animals that possess either of these powers. These are their highest activities, and the highest is the end. Sleep, therefore, is a necessity for every animal. I mean here a hypothetical necessity, viz. that if an 13 animal is to preserve its nature, it must necessarily be provided with certain things, and where these things are found, other things are involved. We must next ask to what sort of bodily process and activity waking

agency in it, as there is in all English meanings of cause. It signifies, rather, ' principle. ' Further, form represents the inner Trieb or force in matter whereby it is in constant transition towards the realisation of its end. In this sense form is the efficient or moving cause. We have then form used in the various senses of (1) final principle, (2) notional principle (i.e. the notion or significance of a thing), and (3) the efficient principle. The first and third are conceived of as forces or causal agents, while the second is cause in the sense of being the source from which these forces issue. The two ultimate principles, then, which Aristotle employs for the explanation of all reality and all de- velopments are :

1. Form (the essential thing). 2. Matter (material condition).

(a) End or final cause.

(b) Motion or efficient cause.

222 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de somno

and sleeping are due. We must assume that the causes of sleeping and waking are the same or analogous in bloodless and sanguineous animals, and in the lower sanguineous animals and men. So that what we observe in the case of man, we shall have to apply to them all.

14 It has been already determined in other treatises that 456 a the origin of sensation is found in the same organ from

which motion originates. This organ is found in the middle division1 of the three topical sections of the body, and lies between the head and lower body. In sanguineous animals it is the pericardiac section, for all sanguineous animals have a heart, and this is the

15 primary source of motion, and of the higher sensation.2 Evidently the origin of movement and of breathing, and in general of refrigeration, is found in this section, and it is also evident that nature created the organs of respiration and of refrigeration, which latter is effected by means of moisture, for the purpose of maintaining the warmth in this part.3 But this subject will receive

16 separate treatment later.4 On the other hand, in the bloodless animals, the insects, and such animals as are incapable of breathing air, there is found in an organ corresponding to the lungs congenital air which rises and falls. This is evidently true in the case of insects with undivided wings, such as wasps and

1 Thorax.

2 The "higher sensation" appears to mean sense-perception or the apprehension of the 'common sensibles.' Cf. Introduction (chap, iv.) on the nature and function of the 'common sense.'

3 That is, for the purpose of maintaining normal animal heat, and for guarding against its excess.

4 Vid. the tractate On Respiration.

chap. ii. MOVEMENTS IN SLEEP 223

bees, also in flies and similar insects. But since it 17 is impossible to originate motion without power, the retention of the breath generates power breath derived from without in the case of respiring creatures, and con- genital breath in the case of non-respiring animals (this is the reason why, as we see, winged insects buzz when in motion, the sound being caused by the friction of the air striking on the diaphragm of these holoptera). Every 18 creature experiences movement whenever a sensation, whether its own or caused from without, is awakened in the primary organ of sensation.1 Now, if sleeping and waking are affections of this organ, it is clear in what region and in what ultimate organ, sleeping and waking have their origin. There are persons who are subject 19 to movements in sleep, and do many acts that belong to the waking state, and nevertheless without any image or sensation. For the dream is in a certain way a sense-perception. About this we must speak later. Why it is that we remember our dreams on waking, while we do not remember acts done in a waking state, has been explained in the Problems.2

1 Motion {kLv7)vis) is employed by Aristotle in several senses. He not only constantly speaks of intellectual processes as motions, but refers to movement in space as motion. The generic term is Kbrjais, which has the following varieties {Metaph. 10696 9 ; De an. 406a 12, 4326 9) : (1) Quantitative motion, or motion in reference to magnitude {Kara /meyedos), which signifies increase and decrease (averts ko.1 (pdiais) ; (2) Qualita- tive motion (/card to ttolov), or transformation (aXkoiuais) ; (3) Spatial motion or locomotion (/caret to ttov, called <pop&) ; (4) Substantial change {fxeTa^oXr) /car' overlay), or birth and destruction (yeveais /cat (pdopd). Aristotle declares, however, that the last named {Phys. 225a 26, 2256 10) is not a proper form of motion, on the ground that the non- existent cannot be said to experience motion.

2 The explanation here referred to is not found in the extant Problems.

CHAPTER III.

Following upon what has been said, we have to consider to what occurrences the phenomenon of sleeping and

2 waking is due and what is its origin. Now, it is plain that as soon as an animal has sensation, it must at once take nourishment and grow ; food in its final state is, in all sanguineous animals, blood, and in bloodless animals

456 b something analogous to blood. The blood is contained in the veins, the origin of which is found in the heart (a

3 fact which is demonstrated by dissection). When food has been introduced from without into those parts intended for its reception, an evaporation takes place in its transmission into the veins, and here it is transformed

4 into blood and is carried to its main organ. This subject was discussed in the treatise On Food} But we must resume it now for the sake of observing the origins of animal movement and of seeing to what affection of the

5 organ of sensation waking and sleeping are due. For sleep is not any random exhaustion of the power of

1 The work On Food (irepl rpofirjs) appears to be referred to in De an. 4166 31, but whether or not it was actually written is uncertain. It is not in the present Corpus of Aristotle's writings.

224

chap. in. ANIMAL HEAT AND SLEEP 225

sensation, as said above. Senselessness, choking, and swooning produce a similar exhaustion. And in some cases of swooning there has been found even a strong power of imagination. Now this creates a problem. 6 For if it is possible for a swooning person to fall asleep, then this imagination might be regarded as a dream. Also, people often talk when they are in a deep swoon and are to all appearances dead. To all these cases of swooning, however, we must suppose that the same explanation applies. But, as we have said, sleep 7 cannot be any and every incapacity to feel sensation; on the contrary this particular condition springs from the evaporation of food. For the evaporation must be thrown off to a certain extent, and then it must return and change again, like the ebb and flood of a shifting strait. 8 All animal heat tends to rise ; when, however, it reaches the upper parts, it turns about and courses down again in mass. Consequently, sleep is most easily produced after taking food. For a large quantity of moist crass 9 matter is then carried to the upper parts. This by remaining there produces heaviness and causes one to fall asleep. But when it descends and in turning throws off its heat, then sleep ensues and the animal slumbers. A proof of this is furnished by the action of narcotics ; for they all, whether liquid or solid, produce heaviness, e.g. the poppy, mandrake, wine, and bearded darnel. And those who droop their heads and nod into 10 slumber appear to be in this heavy condition ; they cannot lift their heads or eyelids. Sleep of this sort follows mostly on the taking of food. For there is then a strong evaporation from food. It further arises from

226 aristotle's psychology desomno

certain fatiguing efforts. For fatigue tends to waste, and 457 a waste-matter is like indigested food, when it is not cold, ii Certain diseases, such as are due to an excessive amount of moisture or heat, produce this effect of sleep, as is the case, e.g. in fever and lethargy. Further, early infancy produces it ; for children sleep a great deal because all

12 their food rises to the upper parts. A proof of this is seen in the excessive growth of the upper parts in propor- tion to the lower ones in early childhood, due to the fact that growth tends in that direction. It is to this cause also that epileptic conditions are due. For sleep is similar to epilepsy, in fact is epilepsy in a certain sense. And

13 so the beginning of this condition in many cases happens during sleep, and while asleep persons have an attack of it, but not while awake. For when a great mass of fumes is carried to the upper parts, in descending they press on the veins and produce constriction of the passage

14 through which respiration takes place. Consequently, wine is not good for children or for wet-nurses (for it makes no difference, perhaps, whether the wine is taken by the children or by the nurses), but they should drink it thinned with water and in small quanti- ties. For wine contains spirituous fumes, especially

15 wine of dark colour. In children the upper parts become so full of food, that during five months of life they cannot turn their necks. For a great quantity of moisture rises to the upper parts, just as it does in the case of persons who are very drunk. This phenomenon suggests a rational explanation of the fact that the

16 embryo remains at first quiet in the womb. Also, in general, persons with deep lying veins, of dwarf-like

chap. in. FOOD AND SLEEP 227

structure, and with large heads, are given to sleep. For the veins of the one class are small and so the moisture in its downward course cannot readily flow through them, while in the case of persons of dwarf-like structure and large heads, there is a great pressure and evaporation towards the upper parts. Large- veined persons are not 17 given to sleep because of the facility for the passage of blood l in the veins, unless there be some adverse con- ditions present. Neither are the atrabilious especially inclined to sleep. For their internal parts are cool and so no considerable evaporation takes place in them. Consequently owing to their dryness they are fond of eating. For the condition of their bodies is such that they seem to have eaten nothing. For the black bile, 18 being in its nature cool, cools the nutritive region and the other parts, where this excretion of bile is potentially present. From the foregoing, one sees that sleep is an 457 ^ internal concentration of heat and a natural reaction from the cause named. For this reason a person in sleep 19 moves a great deal. From the moment that the heat ceases to rise, however, the person becomes cool and owing to the cooling the eyelids fall shut. And so the upper and outer parts of the body are cool, while the inner and lower ones, e.g. the feet and the entrails, are warm. Yet 20 one might be in doubt as to the statement that the deepest sleep occurs after eating, that wine and other

1 The circulation of the blood was, of course, unknown to Aristotle. He knew only of its direct passage from the heart to the extremities and of its movement to the brain and return. (4566 23 ; De insom. 4616 7 ff). The brain, being the coldest organ of the body, performed the function, as Aristotle supposed, of reducing and regulating the tempera- ture of the blood.

228 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de somno

similar heating drinks are narcotic. To regard sleep as a cooling process is not reasonable ; it is rather caused by

21 heat. Or is one to suppose that analogously to the stomach which is warm when it is empty but as soon as it is filled becomes cool through its processes, so the channels and divisions of the head are cooled by the rise of evaporated matter ? Or are we to suppose that analogously to persons pouring warm water over them- selves and then suddenly shivering, so after the heat has risen, the collected cold produces a chill and in this way

22 counteracts the natural heat and drives it back ? Again, when a large quantity of food is taken, which drives the warmth upward, the stomach is cooled, until digestion takes place, just as fire is cooled when fresh wood is laid upon it. For sleep occurs, as we said, when crass evaporation under the influence of heat, rises through the

23 veins to the head. When this can continue no longer, because an excessive mass has been carried to the upper parts, then reaction takes place and the evaporated matter flows back to the lower parts. Consequently when the rising heat is withdrawn, men sink down (man is the only animal that stands erect), and when the heat returns, it causes lapse of consciousness, and later

24 awakens imagination. The explanation we have just given for the phenomenon of refrigeration is a possible one. The region about the brain, however, is the chief factor here, as we have said. The brain is the coldest part of the body, and in animals that have no brain

25 the part analogous to it is the coldest part. Just as water is evaporated by the sun's heat and, when it rises into the upper air, is cooled by the air's

chap. in. THE BLOOD AND SLEEP 229

temperature, and condensed falls to the earth once more in the form of water, so in the rise of heat to the 458a brain, the excessive evaporation is converted into viscid matter (for this reason catarrhal affections appear to come from the brain), whereas the evaporation that assists nourishment and is normal, returns to the lower parts condensed, and decreases the heat. The thinness 26 and slender structure of the veins about the brain con- tribute to refrigeration, and to the difficulty of their taking up the evaporation. This is the cause of re- frigeration, even in cases where the evaporation creates an excessive degree of heat. Waking takes place when 27 digestion has been completed, and the great amount of heat which is crowded into a small region out of the surrounding parts, has gained control ([over the cold]), and when, further, the crass blood has been separated from the purified blood. The thinnest and purest blood is in the head, the thickest and most turbid in the lower parts. The primary source of all blood is, as 28 we have said in this treatise and elsewhere,1 the heart. Between the two chambers of the heart there is a middle chamber connected with both. 2 The two

1 De part. an. 6486 4 ; de juvent. 4686 32 ; de respir. 4746 7.

2 According to Aristotle there are three cavities or chambers in the heart, which he calls right, left, and middle. The right cavity is the largest, the left one the smallest, and the middle one is middle-sized. The right cavity in Aristotle's conception is identical with the right ventricle, which he saw in a suffocated animal and in a disturbed state, so that it appeared larger than the middle cavity (the left ventricle). This in turn appears larger than the collapsed left auricle, which is Aristotle's left cavity. The fourth cavity or right auricle was merged by Aristotle in the great vein, because, as Huxley says (Nature, vol. xxi. p. 2), the vena cava inferior, the right auricle, and the vena cava superior and innominate vein, when distended with blood, appear "to

230 aristotle's psychology desomno

chambers severally receive blood from the two arteries, from the great artery and the aorta, and the sepa-

29 ration takes place in the middle chamber. The detailed treatment of this subject, belongs, however, more properly to other treatises. On account of the un- separated character of the blood after taking food sleep occurs and continues until the purest element is sepa- rated off and carried to the upper parts, and the more turbid element to the lower parts. When this is accom- plished, sleepers are released from the heaviness caused

30 by food and awake. The cause of sleep has, therefore, been explained as the reaction of crass vapour, which rises under the influence of its inherent heat on the primary organ1 of sensation. Sleep has also been explained as the inhibition of the primary sense-organ, and its incapacity for function, and as a necessary pheno- menon (for no animal can exist apart from the conditions which develop its nature), and sleep 2 exists for the sake of preservation, for rest preserves.

form one continuous column, to which the heart is attached as a sort of appendage." Consequently, instead of a right and left auricle and a right and left ventricle, Aristotle distinguished only three cavities, a right, a left, and a middle. Cf. De histor, anim. 496a 4 ff.

!The heart.

2 For the history of the various ancient theories of sleep see Spitta, Die Schlaf- und Traumzustande der menschlichen Seele, Tubingen, 1882, pp. 2 ff., and Radestock, Schlaf und Traum, Leipzig, 1879, pp. 240 ff.

ON DREAMS.

CHAPTEE I.

We must next investigate dreams and inquire first of all in what part of the soul this phenomenon occurs, 458 £ and whether it is an affection of the thinking power or of the sensible power. For it is solely by these two powers within us that we know at all.2 If the use of 2

1 Dreams are due to revived movements originally set up by external stimuli as well as to immediate sense-impressions. The former are centrally excited, to use a modern distinction, while the latter are peri- pherally excited (cf. 4606 25 ff., 462a 8 ff., 463a 7 ff., 779a 14). In our waking state these movements are for the most part obliterated or obscured by stronger currents of thinking or feeling. In sleep, when the blood is less disturbed, these dream-movements come to clear con- sciousness. So it is that a bodily discomfort that is not felt in waking stirs a dream in sleep. It also happens that a dream may lead to action by day. Dreams, which are images or after-motions of sensations, are regular or distorted in proportion to the amount of physical disturbance at hand and the number of cross-sensations (461a 16). Aristotle defines a dream as "a movement in the organs of sense produced by imagina- tion" (462a 8, cf. 462a 28). Dreams rise to the surface of conscious- ness when they are released from the stronger movements that restrain them, just as artificial frogs rise to the surface when the salt is melted off (4616 16).

2 Cf. De an. 429a 31, 4316 20 ff.

231

232 aristotle's psychology deinsom.

sight is vision, and of hearing audition, and of sense in general sensation, and, on the other hand, if there are common sensibles1 such as form, magnitude, number, etc., and particular sensibles, such as colour, sound, flavour, and, further, if it is impossible for any animal to see with its eyes closed and asleep, and if this applies equally to the other senses, then it is evident that we have no

3 sensation in sleep, and so it is not by means of sensa- tion that we experience dreaming. Neither are dreams mediated by opinion. For we not only say that an approaching object is a man or a horse, but also that it is white or beautiful, as to which qualities opinion2 apart from sensation makes no deliverances, whether true

4 or false. However, this is just what the soul does in sleep. For, as in waking, so in sleep, we believe we see that the approaching object is a man, and that it is white. Again, we think of other things along with the dream, just as is the case with perception in our waking state. For we also often think about what we perceive. So in sleep along with our imaginings we sometimes have

5 different thoughts. This would become apparent to anyone who would give attention on rising and try to remember. There have been persons who have in this way observed their dreams, as e.g. those who try to arrange their deliverances in accordance with the precepts of the mnemonic art.3 For it often happens in their case that along with the dream they put something else, an image

1 De an. 418a 15.

2Z>e an. 427b 20 ff., Post. Anal. 886 33 ff. Opinion refers to the contingent or to that which may or may not be true (ivdexo/mewa de ical ciXXws ^XeLV)'

3 Cf. Top. 1636 ff,, De an. 4276 19.

chap. i. DREAMS AND ILLUSION 233

before their eyes, in the place in question. And so it is 6 clear that not every image seen in sleep is a dream, and what we think conceptually we regard as true or false through the organ of opinion. So much is clear on this subject that the same agency which in disease produces illusion while we are awake, also produces the condi- tion of illusion in sleep. Even when we are in sound health and know the truth, still the sun appears to us to be only a foot in diameter. But whether the soul's 7 powers of imagination and sensation are the same or different, in any case dreams do not take place indepen- dently of seeing and some sort of sensation. For illusions of sight and hearing occur when a person really sees and hears something, although not the thing that he thinks he sees or hears. In sleep, however, there is according to the foregoing hypothesis no seeing, no hearing, no 459 a sensation at all. The hypothesis that there is no vision 8 is, therefore, untrue, and that sensation experiences no excitation is untrue; on the other hand, it is possible for sight and the other senses to undergo some change and things impinge on each of them to a certain extent, as in the sensation belonging to the waking state, though with a certain difference. Sometimes opinion declares that the seen object is false, as in the waking state; some- times it is held in check and conforms to the imagination. Evidently the affection which we call dreaming does not 9 belong to opinion or to the thinking part of the soul. Neither does it belong to the sense-part unqualifiedly. For it would then be possible to see and hear unqualifiedly. But we must consider in what sense and in what way it attaches to the part. Let us take this evident fact for a 10

234 aristotle's psychology deinsom.

starting-point, that if sleep is a condition of the sensitive part, so is dreaming. For sleeping and dreaming are not ascribable to different animal organs, but to the same ii organ. Inasmuch as we discussed imagination in the treatise On the Soul,1 and inasmuch as we find that the power of imagination is one with that of sensation, only that the mode of expression in the two cases is different, imagination being a process stimulated by an actual sensation, and since dreaming appears to be a form of imagination (for we call an imagination which we experience in sleep a dream, whether it is unconditioned or conditioned), it is evident that dreaming is a condition of the sensitive part,2 but of the sensitive part in its power to imagine.

1 De an. 427& 14, 429a 9. 2 Vid. Note 1, p. 231.

CHAPTER II.

We might best observe the nature of dreams, and the way in which they are caused, from the standpoint of what occurs in sleep. For sensible objects stimulate sensation in the several sense-organs, and the mental condition produced thereby is not only present during the active process of sensation, but persists after the sensation has gone. The phenomenon here seems to be similar to that observed in the case of thrown objects. For in the case of a thrown object, the 2 movement persists although the mover is no longer in contact with the thing. For the moving body communicates motion to a certain part of the atmos- phere, and this in turn sets another part in motion. And in this way motion is caused both in the air and in water until the body comes to rest. One must 459 £ suppose that something like this takes place also in qualitative 1 change. A body that is warmed imparts by means of its heat warmth to the adjacent body, and

J For Aristotle's conception of the various forms of motion, see Note 1, p. 223.

235

236 aristotle's psychology dbinsom.

this in turn distributes it further on until it reaches its

3 terminal point. This, therefore, is what must take place in the organ wherewith we experience sensation, since actual sensation is a kind of qualitative change. Conse- quently, this condition is found in the sense-organs not only during the process of sensation, but also after the process has ceased, and in their inner depths as well as

4 on the surface. This becomes evident when we have a sensation that continues over some time. For when we turn our senses to something else, the original sensation persists, as e.g. when we turn from the sun to a dark object. The result is that one sees nothing owing to the fact that the sense-process, stimulated by the light, still lurks in the eyes. And if one looks a long time at a single colour, whether it be white or green, things appear to be similarly coloured wherever we turn our eyes.1

5 Again, if we look at the sun or some bright object, and then shut our eyes, there appears to sharp observation, in the direct line which vision employs, first of all a colour like the actual one, which then changes to scarlet, then to

6 purple, until it passes into blackness and vanishes. Also, the senses are affected in this way when they turn quickly from objects in motion, e.g. from looking at a

1 Aristotle refers to the familiar phenomenon of 'after-images.' The fact that the attention was fixed (in Aristotle's illustration) a considerable time, and that he mentions the 'flight of colours,' shows that the reference is to ' positive after-images ' and not to ' primary memory images,' a distinction unknown, of course, to Aristotle. Cf. Sully, The Human Mind, vol. i. p. 278; James, Principles of Psychology, vol. i. p. 645; Ebbinghaus, Grundzilge der Psychologie, p. 244; Helmholtz, Handbuch der physiologischen Optik (ed. 1867), pp. 366 ff. ; Wundt, Human and Animal Psychology, pp. 108 ff. ; Titchener, Experimental Psychology, vol. i. part ii. pp. 48 f.

chap. ii. THE EYE AND THE MIRROR 237

river, and especially from looking at swiftly flowing streams. For objects at rest then seem to be in motion. And men are made deaf by loud noises, and their sense of smell is destroyed by strong odours, and so on. This evidently occurs as we describe it. 7

That sense-organs readily detect even minute distinc- tions is proven by the use of a mirror, concerning which fact one might stop at this point to investigate and make inquiries. From these inquiries it will at the same time become plain that just as sight is subject to an impres- sion, so it exercises an activity. When women look into 8 a very clear mirror1 after their menstrual flow, the mirror's surface becomes covered with a bloody cloud, and if the mirror is new the stain is hard to remove, but if it is old 9 the removal is easier. The reason is that the eye, as we 460 said, not only receives an impression from the air, but it also produces an impression and a movement, just as bright things do. For the eye is classed amongst objects that are bright and possess colour. Eyes are constituted in the same way, it is reasonable to suppose, as any other

1 Ancient mirrors were made of polished metal. The phenomenon here described is one of many of the old-wives' stories which Aristotle took up in his treatises and to which he appears to have given credence. Aristotle, we must remember, had no considerable body of critically sifted and scientifically accredited data to work with. He was depen- dent chiefly on his own observations and the reports brought to him by unskilled persons, in an age before people had concerned themselves about the laws of evidence. It is just this historical environment that shows us how great was the ordinarily sober judgment of Aristotle and how unparalleled his acumen in seeing the scientific significance of facts. It is, however, curious to note that Roger Bacon accepts the story as true : "quoniam si ipsa [mulier menstruata] aspiciat speculum novum, apparet nubes sanguinea in speculo ex violentia menstrui inficientis (Opus Majns, ed. Bridges, vol. i. p. 142). Cf. Lewes, Aristotle, p. 172.

238 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de insom.

bodily organ. And so they naturally contain veins.

io When, therefore, the menstrual flow takes place, owing to disturbance and flow of blood, there is a difference in the eyes, imperceptible to us, but nevertheless real (for the seed and the monthly flow have the same nature), and the air is set in motion by the eyes, and the air being continuous to the mirror, it imparts to the latter a cer- tain quality and an impression similar to the one it has itself received. The air affects the surface of the mirror.

ii But as the cleanest clothing is the most readily stained, so it is here. For a clean thing shows exactly whatever taint it receives, even the slightest effects, more than other things do. Bronze especially, owing to its smoothness, is affected by every contact (we must regard the contact of air as a kind of friction, as cleaning or washing), and owing to the purity of the bronze this contact, however

12 slight, becomes visible. The reason why stains are not readily removable from new mirrors is to be found in the fact that they are clean and smooth. For stains pene- trate deep into such mirrors and in every direction ; for owing to the mirror's pure surface the spots go deep and owing to its smooth polish they spread in all directions. In old mirrors the stain does not fasten, for it does not

13 penetrate so deep but stays rather on the surface. From these facts it is evident that movement is excited by slight distinctions, that sensation is swift, and further, that the sense-organ for colour not only receives impressions but also reacts on external objects. Facts regarding wine and the preparation of ointments also

14 furnish proof for these statements. For the prepared oil and wine readily take up the smells of adjacent

chap. ii. ILLUSION IN DREAMS 239

objects and they become tainted not merely with the smell of things thrown into them or mixed with them, but also of things that are placed or grow in their near neighbourhood.

In reference to our original inquiry let us lay down 460 £ one fundamental truth, which is evidenced by what has 15 been said, viz. that after the removal of the external sensible object, the experienced sensations persist. To this we must add that when under the influence of strong feeling we are easily deceived regarding our sensations, different persons in different ways, as e.g. the coward under the influence of fear and the lover under that of love have such illusions 2 that the former owing to a trifling resemblance thinks he sees an enemy and the latter his beloved. And the more impressionable the person is, the less is the resemblance required. Similarly 16 everybody is easily deceived when in anger or influenced by any strong desire, and the more subject one is to these feelings the more one is deceived. This is the reason why men sick of a fever1 sometimes think they see animals on the walls owing to some slight resemblance in the figures drawn there. And this tendency to illusion at times 17 keeps pace with the intensity of the emotional experience, so that in cases where the patient is not very sick, he is still conscious of the deception, but where his condition is more aggravated, he even rushes upon these animals. The explanation of this phenomenon is that the intellect

1 Aristotle here notes certain of the main causes of ordinary illusions and hallucinations, although the hallucination of fever-delirium is here described rather as illusion. The sense-stimulus is there in the picture on the wall, but the inference is false. Cf. James, Principles of Psychology, vol. ii. p. 86.

240 aristotle's psychology deinsom.

i 8 and the faculty in which our images * arise do not pass judgment with the same power. A proof of this is that the sun appears to us only a foot in diameter and there is many another fact which contradicts our imagination. Also by crossing the fingers 2 a single object under them appears to be two and yet we do not say there are two ;

19 for sight is more decisive than touch. If, however, touch were our only sense, our judgment would declare that the single object is two. The source of illusion is found in the fact that things, whatever they may be, are perceived not merely while the stimulation of the sense- object continues, but also during the further activity of the sense itself, if this movement is the prolongation of that awakened by the sensible object. I mean, e.g. the shore appears to sailors to move, although it is by some- thing other than the shore that the eye is set in motion.

1 Read y rd (pavTa.crp.aTa yiyveTai instead of ~d (pavrda/xaTa yiyveaQai (460& 17). The imagination, in Aristotle's psychology, does not pass judgment, although the 'common sense,' in which phantasms reside, has this power.

2 This is the oldest example of illusion, so far as I know, in the history of psychology (cf. James, Principles of Psychology, vol. ii. p. 86). The illustration has become classical. In the normal position of our ringers (from which part of our tactual world has been built up), it is impossible to place the radial side of the index finger and the ulnar side of the middle finger on a marble or similar small object at the same time. Consequently when we cross our fingers and perform this feat of touching the radial side of the one and the ulnar side of the other with a marble, we seem to touch two objects, because these two points on our skin are never touched by a single object at the same moment. Aristotle further refers to this instance of illusion in Probl. 9586 14, and Metaph. 1011a 33. For a detailed discussion of this and similar forms of illusion, viol. Henri, Uber die Raumwahmelimungen des Tastsinnes, pp. 67 ff.

CHAPTER III.

From these considerations it is clear that sense-processes, whether arising from external objects or bodily activities, take place not merely during the waking state, but occur also in sleep, and that at this time they appear even more numerous. For during the day they are 2 kept in the background by the combined activity of the senses and the intellect, and so are obscured, just 461 as a small fire is obscured when placed alongside a larger one, or as trivial pleasures or pains are obscured alongside of great ones, but when the latter have vanished then the smaller ones rise to view. At night, owing to the inactivity of the special senses and their incapacity to function, caused by the return flow of heat from the outer into the inward parts,1 these sense-movements are carried to the primary seat of sensation and become clear, when the disturbance has subsided. And we must suppose, as tiny whirlpools occur in rivers, so 3 each movement goes on continuously, frequently in the same direction, and again resolved into other forms through counter-influences. Consequently after eating, 4

1 Cf. De somno, 4576 20 ff. Q 241

242 aristotle's psychology deinsom.

and in the case of very young persons, as e.g. in children, dreams do not occur. For there is a strong: movement

5 excited by the heat in food. The case here is similar to what occurs in water when it is violently agitated, viz. sometimes no image is reflected and sometimes only an entirely distorted one,1 so that the thing appears different from the reality. On the other hand when the water is still we see clear and distinct images. So, too, in sleep the images and residual movements resulting from sensations are sometimes entirely obliterated by a move- ment greater than the given one, and sometimes visions appear confused and monstrous and the dreams are not marked by normal health, but are such as one finds in the atrabilious, in men sick of a fever, and in men that are drunken. For all these conditions are like flatulency,

6 and excite great movement and disturbance. But when in sanguineous creatures the blood has come to rest and is separated off,2 the movement of sensation that proceeds from each sense-organ and persists, awakens normal dreams and causes an image to appear and the person to

1 Cf. note 1, p. 231. Sensations cause after-movements like the ripples and circles in water agitated by a pebble. These movements repeat themselves in fainter form, clearly in still water, and with distorted, broken shapes where the water is disturbed by cross-movements. The circles or images are then confused or monstrous. If the movement is too violent, as after eating and in children, then, as in violently agitated water, no image or dream is produced.

2 That is, purified from crass elements. Although Aristotle makes a distinction between pure and crass blood, it is not certain that these are to be connected with the aorta and vena cava, or that they in any way correspond to arterial and venous blood. This separation takes place in the heart, which is at once the physiological and the psychical centre of animal life, the "acropolis of the body" {De part. anim. 670a 26).

chap. in. MOVEMENT IN DREAMS 243

believe that he sees something owing to the influences discharged from sight, and to hear owing to the influences discharged from hearing, and similarly with the other 7 senses. For by the transmission of this movement from these special organs to the primary seat * of sensation, one believes, in the waking state, that one sees and hears 461 b and perceives ; and because it sometimes happens that sight seems to be stimulated without its being really so stimulated, we say that we see, and because touch reports two movements, we believe a single object to be two. In 8 a word the primary sense affirms the deliverances of the special sense, when no other more decisive sense con- tradicts this. There is without doubt an appearance, but what appears is not in every case believed, unless the power of judgment is inhibited or is not exercised in its normal way. But as we said that some 9 persons are subject to illusion under one condition and others under another, so when asleep, one is deceived by the processes of sleep, by the excitations of the sense-organs, and by other affections of sensation, to such a degree that something which bears only a 10 slight resemblance to a given thing is thought to be that thing. For when one is asleep and the mass of blood recedes to the central organ, the movements in the blood, whether latent or actual, concentrate there.2 And the conditions here are such that if the blood is stirred, a particular movement rises to the surface and if this subsides, then another follows. They are related to each other like artificial frogs which rise to the surface of the water as soon as the salt on them is 11

1 To the heart. 2 Be. mmno, 4567; 23. Cf. note, p. 227.

244 aristotle's psychology deinsom.

melted off. And so these movements are latent in the blood, and as soon as the hindrance is removed they come to active expression. When set free in the small amount of blood remaining in the sense-organs, they stir themselves, exhibiting a likeness to things such as we see in clouds, which resemble men and centaurs in quickly

12 shifting forms. Each of these images is, as we have said, the residue of actual sensation. After the true sensation has gone, the image continues, and it is correct to say that it is something like Coriscus although not Coriscus. And at the moment of sensation the master-organ and judging faculty do not say that this is Coriscus, but only that owing to this sensation the real Coriscus is yonder

13 person. On experiencing this sensation the master-sense makes the above deliverance, provided it is not entirely inhibited by the blood, just as without sensation this movement is set up by the processes latent in the sense- organs. This latter, which resembles a thing, one then regards as the real thing. And the power of sleep is so

14 great that it causes us to be unconscious of this difference. If one presses one's fingers under the eyes and does not

462^ notice it, a single thing not only appears double but is believed to be so ; if the pressure is noticed the thing appears to be double but is not believed to be so, and this is what happens in sleep. If a person perceives that he is asleep and is aware of the sleeping condition in which the sensation occurs, then the appearance will be present indeed, but there is something in the person which says this is only a phantasm of Coriscus and is not Coriscus himself (for there is often something in the soul of the sleeper which says that the appearance is

chap. in. IMAGINATION IN DREAMS 245

only a dream). If, however, he is not conscious of the sleeping state, then nothing contradicts the imagination.

That the above statement is correct, and that we have 15 movements of imagination in the sense-organs, becomes clear, if in falling asleep and on waking, we attentively try to remember what happens.1 For sometimes one will detect, on waking, that the images which appear in sleep are movements in the sense-organs. In the case of certain young persons whose sight is thoroughly good, there appear before them, when it is dark, a multitude of moving images, so that they conceal themselves in fright. From all these facts one must conclude that a dream is 16 a kind of sleeping phantasm. For the imaginings in children just referred to are not dreams, nor is anything else which is seen when we have the free use of our senses. Neither is every imagination that occurs in sleep, a dream. For in the first place many persons 17 have in sleep the power, in some form or other, of perceiving sound, colour, flavour, or touch, although the sensation is weak and seems to come from afar. Persons who are asleep and open their eyes slightly, and then suddenly awake, have discovered the reality of the lamplight, which in sleep they saw only, as they thought, in a glimmer, and hearing the faint crowing of a cock, or the bark of a dog, they have, on waking, recognised them as loud voices. Some persons even reply to questions. 18 For it is possible that when one or the other of these states, waking or sleeping, is unquestionably present, the other may be present to some extent. In these cases

1 One may see from this that Aristotle was a careful observer of the phenomena of consciousness.

246 aristotle's psychology deinsom.

there can be no dream, neither can such processes of real thought as occur in sleep, along with fancies, be called

19 dreams.1 But a dream is that form of imagination that originates in the movement of sensation during the sleeping state as such.

It has occurred in certain instances that men have

20 never in their lives known themselves to have a dream ; 462 £ in other cases they have observed them when far

advanced in years without having noticed them earlier.

21 The reason why dreams do not occur in these cases seems to be closely allied to the reason which prevents their occurrence in children, and after eating.2 For persons who are by nature so constituted that a large amount of vaporous-matter ascends to their upper parts, or the return of this matter produces in them great move- ment, it is reasonable to suppose that in these cases there

22 are no dream-fancies. In advancing years there is nothing remarkable in the fact that dreams make their appear- ance. For where a certain ([physical]) change takes place, whether owing to age or to some internal affection, this changed condition ([regarding dreams]) must also occur.

1 The cases in which one distinguishes an actual external stimulus are not properly dreams.

2 The question whether or not there is dreamless sleep is not a settled one (cf. James, Principles of Psychology, vol. i. p. 199 ff. ). Hammond, Sleep and its Derangement, pp. 108 ff. The Cartesiaus, consistently with their definition of mind as a thinking entity, deny the possibility of a lapse of consciousness. Owing to its nature mind must always think. Kant says: "One can regard it aa certain that there can be no sleep without dreaming, and whoever says he has never dreamed, has only forgotten his dream." Anthro- pologie, 4te AufL, Leip., 1833, p. 105. The disposition of modern psychologists is to regard dreamless sleep as probable, but the question is not likely to be removed from the region of dispute. Cf. Wundt, Human and Animal Psychology, Eng. Tr., p. 324.

ON PROPHECY IN SLEEP.

CHAPTEE I.

Eegarding prophecy in sleep and the prophecy said to be derivable from dreams,1 it is difficult either to treat it with contempt or to believe in it. For the universal 2

1The attitude of Aristotle towards the widespread belief in the mantic character of dreams is marked by judicial fairness. He finally concludes, however, that where dreams have been found to be pro- phetic, this is due merely to accident. Belief in them prevailed and to a certain extent continues to prevail amongst all nations, and is attested by all literatures from the earliest times (cf. Tylor, Early History of Mankind, 3rd ed. p. 6 ff. ; Primitive, Culture, 3rd ed. vol. i. p. 121 ff.). "All argument is against it; but all belief is for it," as Tylor (vol. ii. p. 24) quotes from Dr. Johnson. This very accurately represents the state of Aristotle's mind toward the prophetic character of dreams. Greek literature especially is full of references to mantic dreams, and the general soothsaying usages in Greek religion fostered belief in them. Oneiros (Dream) is sometimes called a god {II. ii. 6), again the messenger of Zeus, and Hesiod (Th. 212) tells us that dreams are the children of Night without a father, and the divine origin of dreams is witnessed to by Socrates {Crito, 44 a) and Xenophon {Anab. iii. 112). Aristotle belonged to the same intellectual era as Socrates and Xenophon. We find a similar belief in the prophetic nature of dreams witnessed to by the Hebrew Scriptures and the New Testament {Gen. xxviii. 12, xl. 5-21 ; Numbers xii. 6 ; Matthew i. 20).

247

248 aristotle's psychology dedivin.

or widespread belief in the prophetic nature of dreams, based as it is on experience, lends support to this view, and it is not incredible that certain events are foreseen in dreams. There is a certain reasonableness in this, and so one might, in like manner, apply this belief to

3 other dreams. The fact, however, that one cannot dis- cover any intelligible cause for their occurrence, creates distrust in them. The theory of divine origin is absurd, because in addition to its irrationality, one observes that these dreams do not come to the best and wisest,

4 but to all sorts of men. But when their divine causa- tion is excluded, there is no other reasonable origin that one can assign. For it seems to transcend our power of understanding to discover an explanation of the story that certain persons foretell the future through legends on the pillars of Hercules or on the Borysthenes. Dreams,

5 taken either in their entirety, or partially, or singly, must then be causes or signs of events, or else they

6 must be accidental phenomena. ' Cause ' I understand in the sense of the moon's being the cause of the sun's eclipse,1 and fatigue being the cause of fever ; by ' sign ' I mean e.g. that a sign of an eclipse is a star's becoming visible in daylight or the roughness of the tongue in fever ; by an ' accidental phenomenon ' I mean e.g. that an eclipse of the sun happens while one is takiug a

463 a walk. For taking a walk is neither sign nor cause of an eclipse, neither is an eclipse the sign or cause

7 of taking a walk. Consequently no accidental pheno-

xCf. Anal. post. 986 1, 99a 1 ff. Cause contains inherently the explanation of a result ; sign is merely a concomitant or a precursor, and has only an accidental relation to the result.

chap. i. PROPHETIC DREAMS 249

menon takes place constantly or even as a rule. Is it, then, possible that some dreams are causes and others signs, e.g. of physical events? Well-educated physicians, at any rate, say that we should pay close attention to dreams. And this view is also regarded as reasonable by laymen who are investigators and philosophers. For the psychical movements that occur by day, unless they 8 are very full and vigorous, are unnoticed when they are experienced along with greater waking excitations. In sleep, however, the reverse is true. For then the trivial movements seem to be the important ones, as 9 is apparent from frequently observed facts regarding sleep. When slight noises fall upon the ear one thinks it lightens and thunders, and when a bit of mucus flows into the mouth one thinks one is tasting the sweet flavour of honey, and when a very slight heat is felt in any member one thinks one is walking through fire and is fever-hot. But when one awakes one dis- ic covers the real facts. Since, then, all beginnings are small, it is evident that the beginning of disease and other bodily affections on the point of development will be small, and these necessarily show themselves more in sleep than in the waking state. Yet it is really u not unreasonable to suppose that certain sleeping fancies are causes of actions peculiar to the individual. For when we are on the point of doing something or are in the midst of it or have accomplished it, it frequently happens that we are occupied and busy with the same thing in a distinct dream (the explanation of which is that the dream movement has been already started from origins in the day's activity); and as this is true,

250 aristotle's psychology dedivin.

so the converse must be true, viz. that the movements in sleep are often the starting points for the activities of the day, because the thought for the latter is already

12 started on its way in our nocturnal fancies. In this sense, therefore, certain dreams may be signs and causes. But most prophetic dreams are things of chance, especi-

463 b ally all those that transcend us and whose origination is not in our power, as e.g. a naval battle and remote events. The situation here is just like that of a man who thinks of a thing and in that instant the thing appears. For what is there to prevent this being also true of dreams ? It is even more likely that many

13 accidents of this sort should occur here. Just as, in the former case, thinking of a thing is neither sign nor cause of the thing's appearing, so here the beholder's dream is neither sign nor cause of the event, but only accident. Consequently most dreams do not come true. For chance is that which occurs neither constantly nor even as a rule.

CHAPTER II.

Since other animals1 than man have dreams, one may say, in a word, that dreams are not sent from God and do not occur for his ends. They are, however, daemonic. For their nature is daemonic, but not divine. This is 2 proven by the fact that very ordinary men have pro- phetic visions and true dreams, showing that God does not send them ; but such men as have a loquacious and atrabilious nature see all sorts of visions. And because these excitations are many and diversified they chance upon thoughts which correspond with reality, hitting the right thing here just as one sometimes hits in the game of " Odd and Even." 2 For in this instance the proverb applies : " Who often shoots will sometimes hit."

1 " Quippe videbis equos fortis, cum membra iacebunt, In somnis sudare tamen spirareque semper Et quasi de palma summas contendere viris, Aut quasi carceribus patefactis Venantumque canes in molli saepe quiete Iactant crura tamen subito vocisque repente Mittunt et crebro redducunt naribus auras."

Lucretius, De rev. nat. iv. 987 ff.

2 Read Bekker's conjecture apTiafyvTes instead of apna fxepi^ovres. 251

252 aristotle's psychology dedivin.

3 That many dreams do not come true is not strange. For even the signs in physical and heavenly processes, such as the signs of rain and wind, often fail. For if another movement sets in which is stronger than the one indicated, the indicated event does not take place. Also many well-

4 matured plans of what ought to be done fail of execution, because other more important motives arise. For not every expected event occurs, and one must not identify the future with the expected.1 Nevertheless one must say that there are certain causes to which this lack of fulfilment is due, and these are natural signs of the

5 non-occurrence of the given events.

In regard to dreams which are not due to such origins 464 a as we have mentioned, but to origins that either in point of time, place, or magnitude are extraordinary, or which are not to be described in this way at all, and yet the dreamer does not have in himself the cause in these cases, unless the prophetic character is accidental, it would be better to explain such foresight in the following way, rather than in the way employed by Democritus,2

1 'Ecrofxevov signifies the future absolutely and fieXXov the future con- tingently. Cf. De gen. et corr. 3376 6.

2 Democritus explains dreams by the same principles images and effluxes that he employs in the explanation of sensation. The images (ei'SwXa, simulacra) thrown off by things are complexes of atoms, which represent not merely the form, but also the inner qualities of things. They are the things in miniature, and are capable of conveying psychical processes, as well as physical features, from one person to another. Mind has an atomic composition, and it is owing to this fact that the opinions and feelings of friends are conveyed to us by their dream- images. Prior to Aristotle almost all philosophers, like Democritus, sought for an explanation of dreams outside the dreamer, dominated, as they were, in greater or less degree by contemporary superstition. Cf. Cicero, De divinat. i. 43 ; Plutarch, De plac. phil. v. 2, Quaest. con. viii. 10.

chap. ii. POWER OF PREVISION 253

who explains them by images and effluxes. Just as when 6 water or air is stirred, the stirred part sets another part in motion, and after this has come to rest a similar motion is continued up to a certain point, even in the absence of the moving agent, so nothing prevents a certain movement and sensation from reaching the soul in sleep, produced by those objects from which Democritus says images and effluxes are thrown off. And these movements, reaching the soul in some way or other, are more distinctly felt at night, because they are more readily dissipated when they enter by day (for the night air is less apt to be disturbed owing to the calmer nature of night), and they awaken sensation in the body on account of sleep, for persons when asleep detect slight internal processes more sharply than when awake. These 7 movements awaken fancies, out of which one foresees the future in events similar to the fancies. This power of prevision, then, occurs in any ordinary person, and not in the wisest. For if prevision were sent of God, it would 8 come by day and to the wise. In this manner, however, it is reasonable that prevision comes to ordinary men. For the minds of such persons are not given to careful thought, but are, as it were, reft and empty of all content, and when stimulated they follow the lead of the moving agent. The reason why certain persons afflicted with 9 ecstatic mania have prevision is that their own excitations do not distract them, but are rather thrown off by them, and, therefore, they have especial perception of processes foreign to them. That some persons have true dreams, 10 and that familiar acquaintances have prevision especially regarding each other, conies from the fact that acquaint-

254 aristotle's psychology dedi™.

ances concern themselves most about each other. For just as it is most true of intimate friends that they recognize and see each other at a distance better than others do, so it is also with these movements. For the movements of

ii acquaintances are more easily recognized. The atrabilious, like long-distance throwers, owing to the vehemence of their natures, hit their aim. And owing to their mobile 464 b disposition they have a quick fancy for sequence. For as Philaegides1 in his poems and insane persons recite and think out sequences that depend on similarity, as illus-

12 trated in the song of Aphrodite, so these dreamers string together a series of events. For owing to their passionate nature they are not swerved aside by extraneous move- ments.

The most skilful interpreter of dreams is he who can discern resemblances. For a plain dream can be interpreted by anybody. By resemblances I mean, as I said before, that the pictures of imagination

*3 are very like pictures in the water. In the latter, when the movement is violent, the reflection and picture bear no resemblance to the reality. And so a clever interpreter is one who can quickly distinguish and see at a glance in the confused and distorted picture the suggestion of a man, or horse, or whatever

J4 the given object may be. And as the picture in the water, so the dream can be similarly distorted, for

1 Philaegides is an unknown poet. Leonicus (quoted by Barthelemy- St.-Hilaire, Comment, ad loc.) conjectures Philaenis, a Greek poetess of Leucas, contemporary of the sophist Polycrates, to whom an obscene poem on Love was ascribed. Michael of Ephesus {Comment. ad loc. fol. 1527, p. 48) repeats the name Philaegides, as given in the text.

chap. ii. INTERPRETATION OF DREAMS 255

movement destroys the distinctness of dreams. We have now explained the nature of sleep and dreams, and have given the cause of their occurrence, and have further explained the entire subject of divination by means of them.

ON LONGEVITY AND SHORTNESS OF LIFE.

CHAPTER I.

We1 must now inquire into the causes why some animals live long and others only a short time, and into the general subject of longevity and shortness of

2 life. The initial point in our inquiry must be the stating of certain preliminary problems touching these phenomena. For it is not clear whether or not the cause of longevity and shortness of life is the same in animals and plants. Some plants are annuals, and

3 others attain great age. Further, one may ask whether amongst the creatures of nature the long-lived and the naturally healthy are identical. Or is shortness of life to be kept distinct from questions of disease ? Or is it true that some diseases cause the body whose nature is affected, to be short lived, while other diseases in no wise prevent long life ?

1 1 have removed the brackets from the passage 4646 19-30, being unable to see any good reason for following Biehl in regarding it as an interpolation.

256

chap. i. THE TENURE OF LIFE 257

Eegarding sleeping and waking we have already 4 spoken, and we must later on treat the subjects of life and death, and likewise disease and health, so far as they fall within the province of the philosophy of nature. At present we have to consider, as already 465 « said,1 the causes of longevity and shortness of life. This distinction of longevity marks entire genera in comparison with others, and again it marks certain members of one species in comparison with other members. By this I 5 mean there is a generic difference in longevity applicable e.g. to man and horse (for the genus man is longer lived than the genus horse), and again within the species one man is longer lived than another. For some men are long lived and others short lived, according to the districts they inhabit. Nations that inhabit warm countries live longer ; the inhabitants of cold countries 2 6 are less long lived. And amongst those that inhabit the the same locality there are also between individuals differences in this respect.

1 Retain the reading Kada-rrep, k.t.X. (465a 2) bracketed by Biehl.

2 This statement is not borne out by statistics, at least under present conditions. Nevertheless the statement may have been correct in Aristotle's time. Inasmuch as the North Countries were then inhabited by people of inferior civilization, it is likely that the period of life was less than it is now under conditions of higher civilization. The more civilized races protect the aged, and so contribute to longevity, besides being generally better equipped with means and methods for self-preservation. Cf. Lankester, Comparative Longevity, p. 107 ff. ; Van Oven, Decline of Life in Health and Disease, pp. 60, 61.

CHAPTER II.

We must understand what is easily destroyed in natural structures and what is destroyed with difficulty. Fire and water and other elements akin to them, without having their power, are, in their reciprocal action, the causes of generation and decay. Consequently, everything else, one may reasonably suppose, that is derived from or composed of these elements, shares in their nature, except- ing such things as are artificially composed of a great

2 many parts, like a house. The discussion of these other elements does not belong here. Many things are subject to destruction from causes peculiar to themselves, as e.g. knowledge, health, and disease. For these are destroyed when the things of which they are qualities are not destroyed but survive, e.g. the agency which destroys ignorance is recollection and learning; the agency which destroys knowledge is forgetfulness and error. Acci-

3 dentally, the destruction of other properties goes hand in hand with the destruction of the natural body. For when animals are destroyed the knowledge and health

4 that are in them are also destroyed. From this one might draw a conclusion regarding the soul. For if

258

chap. ii. CAUSES OF DESTRUCTION 259

the soul is not in the body by natural growth, but is there just as knowledge is in the soul, then it would be exposed to another destroying agency in addition to that to which it is liable in the destruction of the body. But this does not appear to be the case; the relation between soul and body must be differently understood.

CHAPTEE III.

465 £ Perhaps one might reasonably ask the question : Is there any place where the perishable is imperishable, as in the case of fire in the Empyrean, which is subject to no opposing influence ; for the properties that attach to opposites are incidentally destroyed by the destruc- tion of the thing itself. For opposites destroy one another. No opposite, however, which belongs to sub- stance is incidentally destroyed, for substance is not

2 predicated of any subject. Consequently, in whatsoever thing there is no principle of opposition, and where there is no such principle, there can be no destruction. For what is there to work destruction, if destruction is effected exclusively by opposites ? But there is no op- position present, either absolutely or in any particular part. Or is this true in one sense and in another false ? For whatever has matter cannot avoid being in some

3 sense subject to opposition. It can be everywhere hot or straight, but it cannot be in its entirety hot or straight or white. For these qualities would then be separate entities. Whenever the active and passive come together, if the one always acts and the other

4 is always acted upon, change must take place. Further.

260

chap. in. PRINCIPLES OF DESTRUCTION 261

if change necessarily produces a residue, then residue involves opposition. For change is always the result of opposition, and residue is that which remains from a state prior to change. But if the actually opposed were entirely excluded, a thing would, in this case, be im- perishable.1 Or is this untrue, but a thing in this event would be destroyed by its environment ? If this happens, 5 then the above explanation is adequate.2 If the destruc- tion is not so produced, one must suppose there is an actual inherent opposition in the thing, and that a residue is produced. For this reason the lesser flame is incidentally consumed by the larger one, because the food which the smaller one consumes in a long time in the form of smoke, is consumed by the larger one quickly. And so everything is in constant motion, constantly coming into existence and passing out of existence. And the environment either assists or opposes. 6 Constantly changing things may last a longer or a shorter time than their own nature prescribes, but nothing lasts for ever, where opposites exist. For at the very start, matter contains in itself the principles of opposition, so that if one employs the category of place, spatial change is involved ; if one employs the category of quantity, we have changes of growth and decay ; if one employs passivity, then qualitative change.3

1 That is, if the principle of opposition were excluded there would be no change, and if there were no change, a thing would be indestructible.

2 The environment, in that case, would supply the principle of opposition, and so the dogma of "no opposition, no destruction" would remain unchallenged.

3In other words, the whole of the terrestrial world is subject to corruptibility and change (Metaph. 1035a 25, 10696 24; De coelo 283a 30).

CHAPTEE IV.

466 a Neither are the largest creatures less exposed to de- struction than others (for the horse is shorter lived than man), nor the small animals (for many insects live only a year), nor, in general, are plants longer lived than animals (for some plants are annuals), nor are sanguineous animals, by virtue of their being sanguineous, long lived (for bees live longer than do certain sanguineous animals), neither are the bloodless animals, as such, long lived (for molluscs, which are bloodless, live only a year), nor land animals (for there are both plants and land animals that live only a year), nor sea animals (for 2 the crustaceans and molluscs are short lived). On the whole, the longest lived organisms are found amongst plants, an example of which is the palm.1 Next the sanguineous live longer than the bloodless animals, and the land animals longer than those that live in water.2

1 Apart from the age attained by man, and by certain insects and plants, little is accurately known about the longevity of organisms (Lankester, op. cit. p. 12).

2 Dr. Gunther (quoted by Lankester, op. cit. p. 13) says : "There is scarcely anything positive known of the age and causes of death of various fishes," but cases are reported of carp attaining the age of 150

262

chap. iv. DURATION OF LIFE 263

So that the longest lived animals are those where we find the combined marks of having blood and living on the land, as instanced in man and the elephant.1 It is a 3 rule also that the larger animals are longer lived than the smaller ones. And this characteristic of size applies to other examples of longest lived animals, as well as to the instances cited.

years, and pike 267 years (!) and elephants are reported to have lived as long as 500 years {ib. p. 59), but the statements are not properly authenticated. Trees are reported to have attained ages ranging from 335 years (Elm) to 3200 years (Yew), and even to above 4000 years (Taxodium). In the Popular Science Monthly (vol. ii. p. 250) the story is told of a carp killed at Chantilly aged 475 years. Weismann says that large trees have the longest life of all organisms in the world, and the "largest animals also attain the greatest age . . . and it would not be difficult to construct a descending series of animals, in which the duration of life diminishes in almost exact proportion to the decrease in the size of the body." Essays upon Heredity, Eng. Tr., p. 6. A general rule such as this would, of course, have many exceptions, as e.g. in the case of the eagle and horse, the former being inferior in size but superior in longevity.

1 Aristotle reports the age of an elephant at 200 years, or, according to another report, at 120 years, for his statement is made only on hearsay (ol \xkv 0a<n, Hist. anim. 6306 23).

CHAPTEK V.

The cause of all this might be discovered in the following facts. One must understand that an animal is by nature moist and warm, and life is also moist and warm, whereas old age is dry and cold, and so is death. And this is plain to observation. The matter in living bodies has these qualities of warm and cold, dry and

2 moist. As beings grow old they must then dry up, and so the moist should be constituted in such way as not to dry up easily. Now, fatty elements do not readily decay. The reason is that they contain air, and air compared with other elements is fire. But fire is not subject to decay. The amount of moisture should not be small, for a small amount is quickly dried out.

3 Consequently, larger animals and plants are, as a rule, longer lived than others, as we said before. For it is reasonable to suppose that the larger creatures possess a greater supply of moisture. But it is not merely for this reason that they are longer lived, for there are two causes of long life, a quantitative and qualitative cause- Consequently, there must not merely be a certain quantity

of moisture present, but this must also be warm, in order

264

chap. v. CAUSES OF LONG LIFE 265

that it be not easily congealed or dried up. It is for 4 this reason that man is longer lived than certain larger animals. For animals that are defective in the mass of moisture are longer lived, provided their excess in the 466 £ quality of this moisture is relatively greater than their defect in its quantity. Some animals have an oily, warmth, in consequence of which their moisture is not easily dried up or chilled. Others again have a moisture of a different sort. Further, whatever is meant to be difficult 5 to destroy should not throw off much residue. For this, whether it be due to disease or to nature, destroys a thing. Eesidue has the significance of opposition and is destructive of a thing either in its entire nature or in some part of it. Consequently, salacious animals and such as abound in seed age quickly. For seed is a residue and when it is thrown off produces dryness. For 6 this reason a mule lives longer than a horse or an ass, and women live longer than men, in cases where men are lascivious. And so male sparrows are shorter lived than females. Further, males subjected to hard labour are short lived, and on account of toil age more rapidly.1 For toil produces dryness, and old age is dry. In the 7 ordinary course of nature, and taking it all in all, men live longer than women.2 The reason for this is that the male is a warmer animal than the female. The same

1 Excessive expenditure in organic metabolism due to labour, violent activity, inordinate eating, etc., on the one hand, and waste in pro- pagation on the other, reduce the tenure of life.

2 Statistics show that females have a longer average of life than males (Lankester, op. cit. p. 117). A writer in the Saturday Review (vol. 79, p. 248) shows that in polygamous races, the males are shorter lived than the females.

266 aristotle's psychology del.etb.vit.

classes of animals live longer in a warm than in a cold climate, for the same reason that the larger animals

8 live longer than smaller ones. Particularly striking in this connection is the size of the naturally cold animals. So snakes, lizards, and rough-scaled reptiles found in warm localities and the testacea of the Eed Sea attain a great size. For warm moisture is the cause of growth

9 and life. In cold districts animal moisture is more watery and consequently easily congealed, so that animals with little or no blood, whether their habitation is the land or water, do not occur at all in the northern regions, or if they occur they are smaller and shorter

io lived. For frost impedes growth. Both plants and animals perish when they get no nourishment, for then they consume themselves. Just as a larger con- sumes and destroys a smaller flame by using up its food, so the natural warmth, whose primary function is digestion, consumes the matter in which it is found,

ii Aquatic animals are shorter lived than land animals, not because they are moist unqualifiedly, but because they 467 a are watery. Moisture of this sort is very perishable, because it is cold and easily congealed. For the same reason the bloodless animal is very perishable, unless it is protected by great size, because it contains no oily or sweet element. I say sweet, for animal fat is sweet. Consequently bees are longer lived than other animals that are larger.

CHAPTEE VI.

It is amongst plants that we find the longest lived organisms, and these attain a higher age than animals, in the first place because they are less watery and therefore not easily congealed. Secondly, they contain a viscous oily substance, and therefore, although they are dry and earthy, they nevertheless possess a moisture which is not easily dried out. We must now find an explanation for 2 the great age attained by trees. For a peculiar explan- ation applies to them which does not apply to animals, excepting insects. This peculiarity is that plants con- stantly renew themselves and so attain great age. For new shoots are put forth from time to time and others grow old. And the same thing is true of the roots. But this renewal does not take place in all parts at 3 once ; sometimes only the trunk and branches die and others grow up alongside of them. And when this happens other roots spring from the remaining part. And so it continues, one part passing out of existence and another part coming into being. Consequently, they live 4 long. Plants have a resemblance to insects, as already said. For life continues when they are divided, and out

267

268 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY del. etb. vit.

of one insect or plant two or several are produced. Divided insects, however, reach merely to the state of living, but are not able to continue long in life. For they have no organs, and the principle of life in the single part has no power to develop an organ. This principle in the plant, on the contrary, has the power of developing organs, for it contains in every case both root

5 and stem potentially. Consequently, the new and the ageing branch keep growing from this, differing little in their length of life, just as it is with grafts. In the grafting of shoots, one would say that in a certain sense this same process occurs, for the shoot is part of a plant. In the grafting of shoots, however, the conti- nuity of life occurs in a state of separation from the mother plant, while in the other cases the lives are

6 conjoined. The reason is that the inherent potential principle in the plant is all-pervasive.

There is, however, a point of identity between animals and plants. In animals the males are, as a rule, longer lived than the females. For their upper parts are larger than the lower ones (the male is more dwarflike1 than the female) ; the warm element is found in the upper

7 parts and cold in the lower ones. Also plants with 467 b large roots are longer lived than the others. Annuals

are not of this kind, but trees are. For the upper part and head of a plant is the root, but annuals have their main growth towards the lower2 parts and the fruit.

8 These questions will be examined in detail in the treatise

1 That is they have larger heads and shoulders.

2 Viz. towards the branches, which are analogous to the lower parts of man.

chap. vi. COMPARATIVE LONGEVITY 269

On Plants.1 For the present we have explained the cause of longevity and shortness of life in animals. There remain for our consideration the subjects of Youth and Old Age, Life and Death. And after these have been investigated, our treatise on animals 2 will have been finished.

1 The two books of Aristotle (Hist. an. 539a 20, De gen. an. 716a. 1), trepl <f)VTwv, appear to have been still in existence at the time of Herfnippus, but to have been finally supplanted by the completer work of Theophrastus on the same subject. Cf. Zeller, Philosophic d. Griech. Th. II. Abth. ii. 3te. Aufl. p. 98.

2 Owing to this statement Brandis (Handbuch d. Geschichte d. Philos. p. 1192, 93) thinks that only the first five tractates of the Parva naturalia were written immediately after the De anima, while the three following (viz. On Longevity and Shortness of Life, On Youth and Old Age, and On Respiration) were written after the completion of the treatises on Zoology. There is no reason why this should not be true, although proofs from cross-references in Aristotle's writings are never very cogent for their chronology, such references being often a later addition. It frequently happens that the treatise X cites the treatise Y, and the treatise Y cites the treatise X, such additions and references (particularly when at the beginning or end of a work) being added often by an editorial hand. The Topics, e.g. quotes the Analytics [Top. 162a 11, 165b 8), and is quoted by the A nalytics (A n. prot. 246 12, 64a 37, 65& 16).

ON YOUTH AND OLD AGE, AND ON LIFE AND DEATH.

CHAPTER I.

We must now treat of youth and old age, and of life and death. At the same time it may be necessary to explain the causes and conditions of respiration. For in some animals1 life and death are conditioned by respiration.

2 We have elsewhere treated more precisely of the soul, and it is clear that its ultimate nature cannot be corporeal, although it has its seat evidently in some part of the body, and in some part, too, that has a higher importance amongst the body's members.2 For the present we must

3 dismiss the other parts or powers of the soul (whatever may be the proper term to apply3 to them). In regard to

1 Only animals endowed with lungs or analogous organ may be said to respire. The employment of water by fishes serves a similar purpose (refrigeration or regulation of temperature), but is not respiration. In such animals as respire, life and death are conditioned by the perform- ance of this function.

2 In the heart.

3Cf. De an. 414a 30 ff., 433fr 1, 415a 25, 416a 20.

270

chap. i. LIFE AND SENSATION 271

creatures that are termed animals and have life, in cases where they are endowed with both attributes I mean with animality and life it must be that the principle whereby they live, and by virtue of which they are called animal, should be one and the same part.1 For it is 4 impossible for an animal as animal not to have life. On the other hand, it is not necessary for a thing to be an animal because it has life. For plants live, and yet they have no sensation, and it is in terms of sensation that we distinguish the animal from the non-animal. Numerically they are one and the same part, although in their mode of expression they are manifold and different.2 For it is not the same thing to be an animal and to have life. Since amongst our sense-organs there is one which 5 we call a kind of ' common sense,' where all our actual sensations must come together, this ' common sense ' must occupy a position midway between what we call the anterior and posterior parts of the body (by anterior3 is meant that which is situated towards the region of sensation, and by posterior that which is situated in the opposite region). Furthermore, since in all living organisms the body is divided into an upper and lower half (for all animals as well as plants have an upper and lower part), the nutri- tive principle should evidently4 occupy a position midway 468 *

1 I.e. nutrition and sensation are functions of one life-principle.

2 The fundamental mark of a living thing is the power of nutrition and propagation ; the fundamental mark of an animal is sensation. Both of these functions in the animal are performed by the central organ.

3 By anterior is meant upper, i.e. towards the region of the senses, which are mainly about the head.

4 Aristotle assumes this, of course, owing to his teleological view of nature. Nature operates in the way that is best.

272 aristotle's psychology dejuvent.

between them. The part which contains the organ for admitting food is called the upper part, and we use the term ' upper ' here in reference to the body itself and not in reference to the directions of the surrounding universe;1 by ' lower ' we mean the part whose primary function is

6 to void excrement. In this connection we find a wide difference between plants and animals. In man more than in any of the other animals, owing to his erect attitude, we find the upper part turned towards the upper part of the universe; in the other animals2 the upper part is turned in a direction midway between the upper and lower parts of the universe ; in plants, which are fixed on one spot and draw their nourishment from the earth, this upper part must in every case have a down-

7 ward direction. For roots in plants and mouths in animals are analogous organs, by means of which in the one case food is derived from the earth, and in the case of animals through themselves.3

1 Upper in reference to the universe signifies the direction in which flame and light substances move (cf. Phys. 200b 19, Metaph. 1065?? 13).

2 Cf. Sallust, De conjur. Cat. i.

3 Animal food in its final form is, in Aristotle's theory, the blood. Cf . De somno, 456a 34 ; De juvent. 469a. 1, 32 ; De part. an. 678a 6.

CHAPTEK II.

All perfectly developed animals are analysable into three parts one for the admission of food, a second for the voiding of excrement, and a third midway between these two. The last of these is called in larger animals the chest, and in the smaller some equivalent term is used ; * in some animals, however, it is more clearly articulated than in others. Again, such animals as are 2 capable of progressive motion have, in addition to the parts mentioned, other organs adapted to the service of movement and to carrying the entire trunk as legs, feet, and other organs that have the same function as these. The nutritive principle of the soul is situated in 3 a region central to these three parts, as is evident both from observation 2 and reason. In fact there are many animals which, after one or the other part has been cut off, even the head and the organ for seizing food,

1 The general thoracic region.

2 That is, on empirical and a priori grounds. If this central situa- tion is the best for the performance of functions in which the entire body is interested, then it is reasonable to suppose, Aristotle says, that nature has placed the nutritive principle here.

S 273

274 aristotle's psychology dejuvent.

continue to live in that part to which the middle is

4 conjoined. This fact may be plainly observed in the case of insects, such as wasps and bees. Also many animals besides insects, when cut in two, can continue to live by the functioning of the nutritive principle. This nutritive part is actually unitary, but potentially multiple, and the natural construction of these animals is the same as that of plants. For plants after they are divided continue to live in segments, and from a single

5 origin one can by section produce several 1 trees. Why it is that some plants cannot continue life after section, while others can be propagated, must be explained elsewhere.

468 3 jn this respect, however, plants and insects as a class are alike. It is necessary that the nutritive principle in those living things that possess it 2 should be actually

6 one, though potentially multiple. And the same holds good of the principle of sensation ; for the segments evidently have sensation. In reference to the main- tenance of their natural life, plants ([when divided]) are able to survive. Animals are not, for they lack organs for their preservation, wanting in some instances organs for the seizure of food, and in others for receiving it into the body, and in other instances wanting other organs in

7 addition to both of these. Such divisible animals

1 In the lower forms of animal life, as in vegetable life, organic functions are less centralized than in higher orders. In all of them, however, there is a certain amount of centralization, and even in insects life continues only a short time in any member after severance from the middle segment. Cf. above, 467a 20 ; Hist. an. 5316 30 ff . ; De an. 4116 23.

2 Ogle, in his translation of this tractate (London, 1897, p. 109) suggests for Zxovvlv, hrbfiois. Cf. , however, 479a 8, where we have the same use of ro?s '^xovcnv.

chap. ii. UNITY OF LIFE-PRINCIPLE 275

resemble a complex of several creatures grown together. In the most perfectly organized bodies, however, this phenomenon is not found, because their natures have been fashioned into the greatest possible unity. There are always, however, certain dissected members which exhibit slight sensation, because they are still under the influence of a certain psychical * affection. For after the entrails have been removed, bodily movements are still continued, as one observes in tortoises after the removal of the heart.

1 Aristotle knew nothing of the nature of reflex-movements, having no knowledge of the nervous system and regarding the heart and not the brain as the centre of psychical life. James {Principles, vol. i. p. 16) cites the case of Robin, who, on tickling the breast of a criminal an hour after decapitation, saw the arm and hand move towards the irritated point. Ogle {op. cit. p. 109) says that "insects, such as grasshoppers, from which the viscera have been entirely removed and replaced by cotton-wool as entomological specimens, if not pinned down, often fly away."

CHAPTEE III.

We have further proof of the central situation of the nutritive principle in the case of both plants and animals. In the case of plants we observe their generation from seeds, and we also note the phenomena of grafts and

2 slips. Generation from seeds takes place in every instance from the centre. All seeds are bivalvular, and the point at which their two halves are joined is the point from which generation begins and the middle in reference to the two parts. It is from this point that stem and root shoot forth in growing plants, and the

3 point of origin is also the central1 point. This pheno- menon may be observed in the case of the buds of grafts and slips, for the bud is in a sense the life-principle of the branch and at the same time its centre. It is the bud, therefore, which one removes or into which one inserts a graft, in order to produce branch or root from it, on the theory that the origin of life in branch or root

1 Similarly Aristotle regards the heart or animal centre as the part in which life originates, and notices that it is visible in very small aborted embryos, and is observable in the egg on the third day {De part. an. 665Z> 1).

276

chap. in. DEVELOPMENT OF LIFE 277

is the centre. In sanguineous animals the first organ in 4 development is the heart. This is plainly seen in those animals whose process of generation admits of observation. In bloodless animals the organ that is analogous to the heart must be the first de- veloped. We have already said in our earlier treatise, 5 On the Parts of Animals} that the heart is the organ from which the veins proceed, and that the blood in sanguineous animals is the ultimate source of nourish- 469 « ment, out of which the members are generated.2 Although regarding nourishment it is plainly the office 6 of the mouth to perform one certain task, and the office of the stomach to perform another task, yet the heart is the master-organ and sets the end for all the others. Consequently, in sanguineous animals it is 7 in the heart that we must look for the origin of nutrition and sensation. For regarding the preparation of food, the functions of the other organs are subordinate to the function of the heart. It must be true that the master-organ is that which works persistently towards the end and does not stop with that which is subordinate to the end, just as a physician persistently works towards health. At any rate, the dominating 8 organ of sensation in all sanguineous animals is found in the heart, for the 'common sense' which serves all the special senses must be situated there. There are two senses, taste 3 and touch, whose channels lead mani-

1 De part. an. 665a 15.

2 De somno 456a 34. Cf . also this tractate 469a 28 ff. ; De resp. 481a 11 ; De part. an. 678a 7 ; De gen. an. 740a 21.

3 Taste, as has been already said, is a sort of touch, and both taste and touch are connected with the heart by means of channels (iropoi), by

278 aristotle's psychology dejuvent.

festly to the heart, and what is true of these must be true of the other senses. Movement in the other sense- organs may be transmitted to the heart, but with the upper parts of the body these two senses ([touch and taste]) 9 do not communicate at all. Apart from these con- siderations, if the life-principle in all animals is situated in the heart, the sensory principle must evidently be found there also. For that by virtue of which we call a thing an animal is the same as that by virtue of which we say that it lives, and the differential mark of sensation is the same as the differential mark of a io living body. The reason why certain senses are, as we see, connected with the heart and others with the head (in consequence of which some philosophers l regard the brain as the organ of animal sensation), has been given in a separate treatise.2

which Aristotle probably understood the veins diffused through the flesh and leading to the central organ {De 'part, an. 656a 29). Their medium is elsewhere described as the flesh itself [De gen. an. 744a 1).

1 Plato and Diogenes of Apollonia.

2 Depart, an. 686a 5 ff.

CHAPTER IV.

From what we have said, based on observed facts, it is clear that the principle of sensation, as well as that of growth and nutrition, is situated in this organ ([the heart]) and in the middle of the three divisions of the body. On1 the basis of deduction we should say the same thing, because we see that nature, out of existing possibilities, does in every instance the best. Now, if each principle2 is situated in the central section, the parts3 (viz. that which finally elaborates the food and that which receives it) would thus perform in the best possible way their several functions. For to each of the parts the central organ will then be so related as is best, and the mid-position in a case such as this is the position

1 The editions of Bekker begin Chap. iv. here.

2 Namely, the principles of sensation and nutrition.

3 Aristotle's meaning appears to be that if the nutritive principle as well as the principle of sensation is lodged in the middle section, then the two parts of nutrition, viz. elaboration of food and its assimilation, would be best performed. In other words, the heart, as the organ of nutrition, would in this way be best placed for preparing food for distribution to the surrounding parts, and the surrounding parts, as receivers (to 8€ktlk6v), would be best served by a centrally situated source of supply.

279

280 aristotle's psychology dejuvent.

469^ that naturally belongs to a ruling principle. Again, one

2 must make a distinction between the user and the instru- ment used (and as they differ in function, so too, if possible, they should differ in position), as a flute and the hand that plays it are different in function and situation. If, then, to be an animal means to have the power of sensation, this power in the case of sanguineous animals must be found in the heart and in bloodless animals in

3 a corresponding organ. Every member and the entire animal body possess to a certain degree congenital heat. Consequently we see that during life animals are warm, but when dead and deprived of life they are cold.

4 The source of this heat in sanguineous animals must be sought in the heart, and in bloodless animals in the analogous organ. For all the organs (especially the dominating one) prepare and digest their food by means

5 of natural heat. Consequently, all the other parts of the body may become cold and yet life may continue, but when the master-organ becomes cold, life is destroyed entirely, because this is the source of heat for distribution to all other organs, and the soul is as it were suffused with fire in this organ, which in sanguineous animals is the heart, and in bloodless animals an organ analogous to the heart.

6 Life, then, must go hand in hand with the continuance of this heat, and what we call death is its discontinuance.

CHAPTER V.

There are two ways in which, as we see, fire may be extinguished, viz. it may either go out or be put out. In the former case we say the extinction is caused from within, in the other case it is caused by opposing forces ;x an example of the former is old age ; of the latter, external violence. Extinction in both cases, however, is due to the same ultimate cause, viz. the failure of fuel, for when fuel fails and the heart can no longer receive sustenance, extinction of the fire ensues. Cold, by 2 retarding digestion,2 arrests nourishment. And there are times when it extinguishes itself, as, e.g., when the heat is massed in too great quantity,3 owing to lack of

aIn either case the extinction is due to the ascendency of cold over its contrary heat. Only in the former case, according to Aristotle, the extinction is due to the normal failure of fuel through exhaustion ; in the latter case the extinction is due to unnatural or artificial exposure to cold or wet (which Aristotle calls opposing forces), thus abnormally checking the production of heat by the blood, and violently bringing the supply to an end.

2 Digestion (tt^xj/is) means ' cooking.'

3 Excessive heat is here conceived of as too rapidly exhausting the supply of fuel, as in the case of fever or in old age (owing to its diminished supply of fuel). In addition to this the lungs in old age

281

282 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de juvent.

respiration or lack of cooling. And when the heat accumulates in such mass, it soon causes an exhaustion of fuel, and this process of exhaustion takes place before

3 evaporation has time to develop. Not only, then, is a smaller fire extinguished by a larger one, but also the flame of a lamp is consumed within itself when immersed

47o a in a large flame, just as any other combustible would be consumed. The reason for this is that the larger flame uses the fuel contained in the smaller before other fuel can take its place, and the fire continues in constant process of development and in constant flow like a river,

4 but we do not observe this on account of its rapidity. It is clear, then, that if the heat is to continue (and this is necessary if life is to continue), there must be some

5 means of reducing the heat in the chief organ. An illustration of this may be had in what takes place in quenched coals. For if coals are kept closely covered in a common oven, the fire is quickly extinguished. Whereas if one in rapid alternation removes a lid and

6 sets it on again, the coals continue lighted a long time. Covering a fire with ashes also keeps it. For owing to the porosity of the ashes ventilation is not prevented, and the ashes, by admitting the surrounding air, protect the fire against extinction through excess of heat arising in

7 it.1 However, the explanation of the fact that opposite

become dry and hard, and do not so well perform their function of regulating the temperature. Cf. De respir. 4786 35, 479a 7 ; Meteor. 379a 5 ; De gen. an. 783& 7.

1 In other words, the surrounding air being admitted by the porous ashes prevents the excessive heat within from exhausting its fuel. Analogous to this is the reduction of the vital heat by the ventilation of the lungs.

chap. v. EXTINCTION OF HEAT 283

effects are produced by covering a fire with ashes and with an oven-lid (for the latter extinguishes it and the former keeps it a long time) has been given in our treatise On Problems.1

1 The question is not discussed in the extant Problems.

CHAPTER VI.

Since every living thing has a soul, and the soul, as we have said, cannot subsist without natural heat, we find that in plants adequate provision has been made for the preservation of natural heat through nutriment and the

2 surrounding air. For food produces refrigeration in organisms when it is first introduced, just as on its entrance it does in man. Whereas fasting creates heat and produces thirst. For air, when it is stagnant, always becomes heated, but when set in motion through the admission of food it is cooled, until the food has under-

3 gone digestion. On the other hand, if the surrounding air is excessively cold, owing to the season and the occur- rence of heavy frosts, plants are dried up, or if intense heat occurs in summer and the moisture derived from the soil is inadequate for refrigeration, the natural heat is extinguished and destroyed. In such seasons one says

4 that trees are frosted or suffer blight. And that is the reason why people pile certain kinds of stones * about the

1 Whether any particular variety of stone was used for this purpose is, so far as I am aware, unknown. Presumably nothing more is meant than that such stones were used as lent themselves to making a compact

284

chap. vi. REGULATION OF HKAT 285

roots or cover them with vessels of water, in order to 470 £ keep the roots of the plants cool. In the case of animals, since some of them are aquatic and others live in a medium of air, the refrigeration is derived from and through the media in which they live, i.e. in the one case water and in the other air. We must now begin a special inquiry touching the nature and manner of this process.

covering, thus shutting out the heat, or such stones as by their density- were poor conductors of heat. In any case the chief idea is that they performed the same service as lungs and gills in animals, viz. the service of refrigeration or the prevention of excessive heat, as Aristotle supposes.

ON KESPIRATION.

CHAPTER I.

A few of the earlier physicists 1 have treated the subject of respiration. But in regard to the purpose which it subserves in the animal organism, some of them have given no explanation whatever, and others, although they have discussed it, have been wrong in their statements and have lacked empirical knowledge of the facts. Further- more, they declare that all animals respire.2 This, however,

1 Diogenes of Apollonia, who explained thought as well as life by- means of respiration (Zeller, Phil, der Griechen, 4te Aufl. vol. i. p. 246), Empedocles (Burnet, Early Greek Philos. p. 230), Democritus (Zeller, op. cit. p. 810), Anaxagoras (cf. below 470& 20).

2 Aristotle confined respiration to the admission and expulsion of air (4806 10). In modern Physiology, respiration in a wide sense includes that form of internal respiration (properly a function of nutrition), which means the interchange of oxygen and carbon dioxide between the cells and the fluid that drenches them (cf. Ency. Brit. Art. on " Respiration "). Ordinarily, however, it is used to signify the expulsion of carbonic acid and the admission of oxygen, which is effected mainly through the lungs, gills, skin, and alimentary canal. Pulmonary respiration is the chief means of working this interchange, and it is to this that Aristotle's opuscle is confined, referring to other means of respiration as only analogous functions.

286

chap. i. PURPOSE OF RESPIRATION 287

is untrue. It will be necessary, therefore, to return to 2 these points, in order that we be not thought to make unfounded charges against writers who are no longer living. It is plain that all animals with lungs breathe. But amongst these, the animals that have a spongy, anaemic lung need respiration less than the others. Consequently they can remain, owing to their physical strength, a considerable time under water. All oviparous animals have a spongy lung, as is the case in 3 frogs.1 Again, water-tortoises and land-tortoises can remain a lone; time under water. In these animals the lung has little heat, because it has little blood. Conse- quently when it has been once inflated, it effects refrigera- tion by its motion and enables the animal to continue a long time under water without breathing. Even in these 4 cases, however, when the animal is forced to hold its breath too long, it is suffocated. For none of these animals can inhale water, as fishes do. All animals, on the other hand, whose lung is full of blood, have greater need of respiration, because of their greater heat. As to the animals that have no lung at all, they have no respiration at all.

1 In the frog the cavity of the lung is divided into a honeycomb of chambers or alveoli. Each septum of the lung, being rich in elastic tissue and equipped with a minute network of capillaries covered on each side with epithelium, is freely exposed to the air, and owing to the honeycomb structure of the lung the area of exposure to the air (and consequent exposure of the blood) is great (cf. Foster, Physiology, 6th ed. p. 557). Birds exhibit a reptilian rather than mammalian form of lung (Owen, Anatom. of Vertebrates, vol. ii., p. 269).

CHAPTER II.

Democritus of Abdera and certain other writers on the subject of respiration have not spoken definitely about the animals last named, but they appear to assert that all animals breathe. Anaxagoras, however, and Diogenes make the statement that all animals respire, and they say that fishes and oysters are endowed with

2 a sort of respiration. Anaxagoras declares that when 471a fishes discharge water through their gills, they inhale

the air that is developed in the mouth (for a vacuum does not exist), and so respire. Diogenes, on the other hand, says that when fishes discharge water through their gills, they inhale air by the action of the vacuum formed in the mouth, out of the water which surrounds the mouth, on the theory that water contains air.

3 These views, however, are untenable. For, in the first place, they leave out of account half of the truth, because their entire statement refers only to one aspect . of the case. For by respiration one understands partly in- spiration and partly expiration, and they have nothing to say in explanation of how the latter takes place

4 in lungless animals. And it is impossible for them

288

chap. ii. AQUATIC ANIMALS 289

to give any explanation. For when inspiration takes place, expiration must also follow by the same channel as that employed in inspiration, and these two things must succeed each other in constant alternation. The consequence is that exhalation must take place at the same moment that water is being received into the mouth, and in that case the one must impede the other by meeting. Secondly, if they exhale by the mouth or 5 gills at the moment when they discharge water, the consequence will be that inspiration and expiration will be simultaneous, and, according to the above assertion, this is the moment in which animals inspire. But simul- taneous inspiration and expiration is an impossibility. Consequently, if it is true that respiration involves both inspiration and expiration, and if it is further true that aquatic animals are not capable of expiration, it is clear that they are also incapable of respiration.

CHAPTER III

Again, the assertion that they inhale air from the mouth, or from the water through the mouth, is im- possible. For aquatic animals have no windpipe, because they have no lung, but the stomach is immediately adjacent to the mouth, and consequently the stomach would necessarily be the organ of inspiration. But if this were true here, the stomach would have this power in other animals also. As a matter of fact, it does not have this power. Further, if aquatic animals were re- moved from the water they would then clearly show this

2 capacity to respire ; but they do not show it. Further- more, we observe in those animals that respire and inhale air a certain movement in the organ of inhala- tion. This is not observable in fishes. They appear to move no organ about the stomach other than the gills, whether they are in the water or are thrown gasping on

3 the dry shore. Again, when any respiring animal dies 471 b from suffocation in the water, its breath, as it forcibly

leaves the body, is formed into bubbles, as one sees in the case of tortoises or frogs, or other animals of this sort, when they are forcibly drowned. "With fishes,

290

chap. in. RESPIRATION IN FISHES 291

however, this is not the case, whatever method one may use, because they contain no inhaled air. According to 4 the explanation of respiration above mentioned, it would be possible also for men to respire when in water. For if fish inhale air from water by means of their mouth, why should not men and other animals do the same thing ? They should inhale air from the mouth quite 5 as much as fishes. If the latter have this power, the former should have it also. But as this is not true in the one case, it evidently does not hold good in the other. Furthermore, if fishes respire, why is it that we see them die in the air and gasp as if suffocated ? l It is not owing to lack of food. The explanation given 6 by Diogenes is foolish. He says that fishes, when in the air, inhale too much air, and this is why they die, whereas in the water they inhale a moderate amount. But this should then be possible for land animals also. In point of fact, no land animal is suffocated by excessive inhalation. Further, if all animals respire, insects must evidently 7 respire also. Many of them, however, seem to live

1 Lewes (Aristotle, p. 176) says that the reason why fish die in the air was, when he wrote the note (1864), still awaiting an explanation. He was then not satisfied with the explanation of Flourens (Annales des sciences naturelles, 1830), which attributed suffocation to the collapse of the gills in the air, and the consequent inadequate aeration of blood, which no doubt is the chief cause, and Lewes' experiment in artificially separating the leaflets of the gills would not seem to be any adequate disproof. The number of respirations per minute in water has been experimentally investigated by McKendrick [Journal of Anatomy and Physiol, vol. xiv. 1879, p. 463) and found to vary in different fishes, ranging from 15 respirations (Rockling and Blue Wrasse) to 120 (Minnow and Stickleback). It is, however, no doubt true that rapid desiccation is a further cause of the dying of fish in the air, and the protection against this by the coat of slime on eels explains their living longer.

292 aristotle's psychology derespir.

when they are divided, not only when divided into two parts, but into several, as in the case of the centi- pedes. How or by what organ is it possible for these 8 parts to breathe ? The chief cause of the error of these writers was their ignorance of the internal organs, and also the fact that they did not grasp the truth of design in nature. For by asking to what end animals are endowed with respiration, and by making a test of their theory on the organs themselves, as, e.g., on the gills and lungs, they would soon have discovered the real explanation.

CHAPTER IV.

Democritus makes the statement, it is true, that respira- tion produces certain effects in the respiring animal, viz. it prevents the soul from being expelled from the body. He by no means says, however, that nature in creating 472 a this function did so with this end in view. For he is, on the whole, like the other physicists 1 and makes no application of any such causality. He maintains that the 2 soul and heat have one and the same nature, viz. they are elemental spherical atoms. Consequently, when these are compressed by the force of the surrounding air, inhalation comes to their assistance. For in the air there is a large 3 number of the atoms which he calls mind and soul. In the act of inhalation, then, and along with the entrance of the air, these atoms also enter, and, by counteracting the pressure, prevent the expulsion of the soul that resides in the animal body. It is for this reason that 4 life and death depend upon inspiration and expiration.

1 We are almost entirely dependent on this account of Aristotle for theories of respiration amongst the Presocratics. For the theories of Galen and Hippocrates see the article of Steinheim, " Antike Lehre d. Athmens " in Litt. Ann. d. gesamm. Heilkunde, vol. x. (1828), p. 257 ff.

293

294 aristotle's psychology derespir.

For when the surrounding medium by its pressure gains control and the outer air is no longer able to enter and counteract this control, respiration in the animal becomes impossible and death ensues. For by death one means the departure of these psychical atoms from the body due

5 to expulsion by the surrounding medium. The reason, however, why death necessarily comes at all to every animal, and why it does not come at any chance period, but in the course of nature only in old age, a violent death is contrary to nature, he has not in the least explained. And yet, because this phenomenon occurs evidently at one period and not at another, it behoved him to explain whether it is due to an external or to an

6 internal cause. Further, he has not a word to say regarding the origin of respiration, whether its cause is external or internal. And yet it is evidently not the external mind that comes to the rescue here, but the principle of respiration and of respiratory movement is due to an internal cause, and we are not to suppose that the force of the surrounding medium is any explanation. It is also absurd to think that the surrounding medium has at once the effect of extinguishing by compression, and on its entrance the opposite effect. The foregoing, in content and manner of statement, conforms closely to

7 the theory of Democritus. If one is to regard as true what was said a while ago, viz. that not all animals respire, then we must regard the Democritean explanation of death as not universally applicable, but only to those cases where animals breathe. But even to these cases it does not well apply, as is evident from facts observed by

8 all of us. For in warm weather, when we are more than

chap. iv. HEAT AND RESPIRATION 295

usually heated, we have greater need of respiration and we all breathe more rapidly. When, however, our environment is cool and contracts and chills the body, we hold our breath. This is the very moment, however, 9 that the air from without should enter and prevent the soul's expulsion. In point of fact it is the opposite that 472 takes place. For when excessive heat is accumulated, owing to its not being exhaled, that is the moment we need respiration, and inhalation is necessary to this. The truth is, men breathe rapidly when they are hot, because respiration has a cooling effect, at the very moment when ([according to the theory of Democritus]) they would be, to use a proverb, ' adding fire to fire.'1

1 Because Democritus regards the soul -atoms as identical with the heat-atoms.

CHAPTEE V.

The theory of circular push described in the Timaeus1 gives no explanation whatever of the way in which heat is maintained in animals other than man, whether the preservation of heat in the various animals is due to the same or different causes. For if the phenomenon of re- spiration is found in land animals alone, we must explain why they alone breathe. If, however, it occurs in other animals also, but by a different process, assuming that they can all respire, we must find an explanation for the 2 difference in process. Furthermore, the whole manner of explaining the phenomenon is fanciful. For Plato says that by the issuance of hot air from the mouth, the surrounding air is pushed forward and is transmitted through the pores of the flesh, and rests at the point from which the internal hot air issued. These elements thus effect a complementary displacement, owing to the fact that a vacuum is impossible. In the same way the

1 Timaeus, 79 A ff. Plato's explanation of the circular movement of inspiration and expiration is expressly applied by him to the lowering of animal heat, and not only in man but in all animals, as he says, " in the interior of every animal the hottest part is that which is around the blood and veins " ( Timaeus, loc. cit. ).

296

chap. v. plato's theory 297

inhaled air in turn, when heated, is discharged and the warm air within, issuing out through the mouth, continues this ' circular push/ And so this process, which is inspira- tion and expiration, goes constantly on. The logical 3 consequence of the theory is that expiration precedes inspiration, whereas the opposite is the fact, as the following proves. The two things are correlated phenomena. Now man's last act is expiration, conse- quently inspiration must form the beginning. Further, 4 the end which these processes (I mean inspiration and expiration) subserve in the animal body is not taken into account at all by the philosophers who advocate this theory. They treat them merely as unessential phe- nomena. We see, however, that they are the master- factors in life and death. For when a breathing animal is unable to respire, at that moment death ensues. Further, it is absurd to suppose that the issue of hot 5 air through the mouth and the entrance of air again by the mouth should be observable by us, whereas the entrance of the breath into the thorax and its discharge should not be observable.1 It is also strange that respiration should mean the introduction of heat.2 Observation shows the contrary, for expired air is 6 hot, whereas inspired air is cool. And when the atmosphere is warm animals pant in respiring and they draw their breath frequently, because the entering air 473 a does not adequately cool them.

1 That is through the pores into the thorax.

2 Respiration to Plato means the introduction of heat only in so far as it means the maintenance of heat and the supply of fuel ( Timaeua, 79 E).

CHAPTER VI.

We must also reject the theory that the purpose of respiration is nutrition, which presupposes the feeding of internal heat by means of the breath. According to this view, inspiration is similar to throwing fuel on a

2 fire, and expiration follows when the fire is fed. We again urge the same objections to this theory as we did to the theories enumerated above. The same process, or something analogous to it, should be found in all

3 animals, for they all have vital heat. In the next place, the advocates of this theory should explain how heat is generated out of the breath. The whole view is fanciful. According to our observation generation of heat is due much rather to food. A further consequence of their theory is that food is received and excrement discharged at the same orifice,1 which is not seen in any other instance.

JThe reference may be to the Pythagoreans (cf. De sensu 445a. 16), who asserted that certain animals are fed by the inspiration of smells. But we have no details about their doctrine. Inasmuch, however, as food here appears to be fuel for vital heat, the reference to Plato is possible, who in the ' circular push ' theory would seem to admit food and discharge waste by the same orifice.

298

CHAPTER VII.

Empedocles also has a theory of respiration, although he does not explain the purpose of respiration, nor does he say definitely whether all animals are endowed with respiration or not. In treating of respiration through the nostrils, he fancies he is dealing with the main factor in this process. He is here mistaken, 2 for there is respiration through the windpipe, which leads from the chest, as well as respiration through the nostrils, and without a windpipe the nostrils themselves could not respire at all. Animals may even be deprived of respiration through the nostrils and suffer no harm, but if the use of the windpipe is shut off they die. In certain animals, indeed, respiration through the nostrils is employed by nature for the secondary function 3 of smell. Although almost all animals are endowed with the sense of smell, they do not all employ the same organ for this purpose. On this subject, however, we have spoken elsewhere more in detail.1 4

Empedocles asserts that inspiration and expiration take 473 * place through particular veins, in which there is blood,

1 Cf. De an. 421a 7 ff. ; Be sensu, 4446 16. 299

300 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de respir.

although they are not entirely filled with blood, and that these veins are provided with channels that lead into the outer air, channels which are too minute for the admission of crass matter, but large enough for air. Now, the blood is so constituted as to move up and down, and after its downward motion the air streams in and inspiration takes place ; on its upward motion expiration into the outer air ensues a process which resembles what we observe in the Clepsydra : l

5 Thus all things breathe and breathe out air again.

Long bloodless tubes the body's surface reach, And at their close-packed vents are nostrils fixed Pierced through ; and so a passage way is cut For air, while yet the blood is hidden held. When yielding blood along these channels ebbs, Then bursts the surging air with tempest's wave Within. But when the blood rebounds, the air Is then expired again, as one may see A child with smooth bronze water-clock at play. Upon her comely hand she sets the tube, And dips it in the yielding water's sheen, Of which no drop slips in the vessel's form. Upon the close-packed vents the air doth press Within, until the maid her hand removes And frees the urgent stream, which entrance makes, Whose even flow drives back the yielding air. So, too, when e'er the waters full free flow Hath filled the deep bronze tube, and maiden hand The passage firm hath blocked, then doth the air, The eager outer air, the vents make fast And hold in its restraint the inner stream Whose waters at the narrow gates complain, 474 a Until the maiden lifts her hand. And now

Is true the converse of what was before : The air flows in the water's equal stream

1 Burnet {Early Greek Philos. p. 230) gives a valuable elucidation of this passage.

chap. vii. EMPEDOCLES 301

Flows out. Thus also 'tis with fluent blood That coursing through our limbs now hurries back To inner depths, and straightway air pours in With surging swell. Again the blood returns From its retreat ; then forthwith yields the air, Exhaled once more, in nature's even course.1

These are his words on the subject of respiration. As 6 we have already said, animals that visibly respire do so by means of the windpipe as well as by means of the mouth and nostrils. Now, if Empedocles is speaking of respira- tion in this sense, we must inquire how far his explanation harmonizes with the facts. Apparently the facts con- tradict his theory. For in inspiration the receptacle is 7 expanded like a brazier's bellows. Expansion, however, is naturally explained by heat and by blood which takes the place of heat ([but it is not explained by air in the theory of Empedocles]). In expiration, on the other hand, contraction and collapse take place, as in the bellows, excepting that the cases are not quite parallel in this respect, viz. the bellows do not admit and discharge air by the same orifice, whereas in inspiration and expira- tion the same orifice is used. If, however, he is here 8 referring merely to respiration through the nostrils, he is quite wrong. For respiration is not a function which is peculiar to the nostrils ; on the contrary, along the passage near the uvula, at the extreme end of the roof of the mouth, part of the air passes here through the openings of the nostrils and part of it through the mouth, and this applies equally to inspiration and expiration.

1 Vid. Fragments of Empedocles in Mullach's Fragmenta Philos. Graec. (Paris, 1883), vol. i., pp. 10, 11.

CHAPTEE VIII.

It was said above that life and the possession of soul are accompanied by a certain degree of heat.1 For even the process of concoction, by which food is prepared for animal life, cannot be accomplished without soul and

2 heat ; all this is effected by fire. Consequently, such a fundamental process as this must be situated in the primary region of the body and in the primary organ of this region, and here it is that we must look for this

474^ elementary nutritive soul. This is the middle region between the orifice for admitting food and that for discharging excrement. In bloodless animals the primary organ has no name, in sanguineous animals it is the heart.

3 The food out of which animal members are generated is the blood. The blood and blood-vessels must have the same starting-point. For the one, as vessel and receptacle exists for the other. The originating point for these vessels in sanguineous animals is the heart. They do not

4 traverse the heart ; they all issue from it and are

1Even plants, Aristotle correctly remarks (although he gives no reason for the statement), exhibit vital heat (De part. an. 650a 6 ; De vit. et mort. 470a 22).

302

CHAP. VIII.

ANIMAL HEAT 303

attached to it, as is evident from dissection, i Now, the other functions of the soul cannot be performed indepen- dently of the nutritive principle (the reason for which has been stated in the treatise On the Soul),2 and the nutritive principle in turn cannot subsist without natural heat. For it is through natural heat that nature has endowed the nutritive principle with warmth. Fire may- be destroyed, as we said before, in two ways : by extinc- tion and by exhaustion. Extinction is effected by opposing 5 forces. Consequently even when the fire is massed it may be extinguished by environing cold, and when scattered it is more easily quenched. This extinction by external force applies to animal heat as well as to inanimate fire. For animals die when dismembered by instruments or when congealed by excessive cold. Exhaustion, on the 6 other hand, follows from excessive heat. For if the sur- rounding heat is great, and the internal supply of fuel is not maintained, the fire ceases to burn, not from extinction by cold, but from exhaustion. Consequently there must be some cooling process, if survival is to be attained ; for this comes to the rescue and prevents extinction.

1 There is no doubt that Aristotle practised dissection of animals, although he probably never dissected the human body. His conclusions in reference to the latter were drawn from the anatomy of other animals, whence also the Asclepiads derived their knowledge, and his errors are such as are due to this source of information and to his specu- lative views as to anatomical structures {e.g. the bloodlessness of the brain, its not extending to the back part of the skull, and its function as a cooling apparatus). Further, the feelings of the Greeks regarding the sacredness of the human body were much stronger than ours, and neither Hippocrates nor Galen is supposed to have dissected man. Cf. Hist. an. 4946 22, 513a 12 ; Huxley, Nature, vol. xxi. ; Lewes, Aristotle, p. 165.

2 Be an. 416a 10 ff., 434a 22.

CHAPTER IX.

Some animals are aquatic and others have their existence on the dry land. In the case of the very small and bloodless specimens of both classes, the cooling produced by their surroundings, whether air or water, is adequate to protect them against the above-mentioned extinction. For being endowed with little heat they need little protection. Animals of this kind are, consequently, in

2 the rule short-lived, for a slight change on one side or 475« the other destroys the balance. The longer lived insects

(which, like all insects, are bloodless1) have a fissure just below the middle part in order that cooling may be effected through the membrane, which at this point is very thin. For inasmuch as they have more heat they have more need of cooling. Bees, for example, some of which live as long as seven years, and the other insects

3 that hum, such as wasps, cockchafers, and locusts, belong to this class. They produce this noise by their breath, as if

xThe blood of insects is ordinarily a colourless liquid, sometimes yellowish or greenish, and rarely red, and was not regarded by Aristotle as blood. Cf. Owen, Gompar. Anatom. and Physiol, of Invert. An. p. 383.

304

chap. ix. CONTROL OF TEMPERATURE 305

by panting. As the natural breathing within rises and falls, it produces friction against the membrane in the middle region. For insects keep this region in motion just as animals that breathe the outer air1 maintain motion by their lungs or fishes by their gills. This 4 motion is similar to what would take place if one should suffocate a respiring animal by holding its mouth ; for then this swelling movement would be produced by the lungs. In the latter case, however, such motion is inadequate for cooling, although it is adequate in the 5 case of insects. By means of friction against a membrane they produce a humming noise, as we said, in much the same way as children make a noise through a perforated reed after stretching a thin membrane in it.2 And it is in this way, too, that the singing locusts produce their song. They possess greater heat than other varieties, and have a fissure in the middle region. In the songless locusts this fissure is lacking. Sanguineous animals endowed with 6 lungs that contain little blood and are spongy, can live a long time without respiration, because the lungs are capable of great expansion, containing as they do little blood or fluid. Consequently, their own peculiar

1 All insects breathe air, which enters chiefly through the thoracic and first abdominal spiracles. In the case of insects living in the water respiration is effected by branchiae or false gills, which are supposed to absorb air from the water. Cf. Packard, The Study of Insects, p. 40 ; Owen, Compar. Anatom. and Physiol, of the Invert. An., p. 368.

2 Insects produce sounds by the vibration of their wings, by the vibration and friction of the abdominal segments, and by rubbing the head against the anterior wall of the thorax. The shrilling of the male cricket (a sexual call) is produced by the friction of the fore wings against the hind wings (cf. Packard, The Study of Insects, pp. 362, 563). Aristotle further describes the methods by which insects produce sounds in the Hist. Anim., 5356 4 fF.

U

306 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de respir.

motion is adequate for cooling through a considerable

7 period. Finally, however, it is unable to continue this, and without respiration it suffocates, as we said before. That form of exhaustion which consists in destruction through lack of cooling is called suffocation, and animals that die in this way are said to be suffocated. We have

8 already remarked that insects do not respire. One can observe this plainly in the case of small insects, such as flies and bees, for they can swim a long time in a liquid,

475 b provided it is not too hot or too cold. And yet animals which have less strength require more frequent respira-

9 tion. They are destroyed, however, and are suffocated, as we say, when the belly is filled with water and the heat of the middle region quenched. From this we can understand how it is that such insects get up again after being covered for some time with warm ashes. We also

io observe that bloodless aquatic animals live in the air longer than do sanguineous animals that take in sea- water, as the fishes. For the former have little heat, and consequently the air is adequate to cool them for a considerable time, as is the case with Crustacea and

ii polyps. And yet it is finally inadequate for life, because they possess little heat; for even fishes are often dug out of the earth and found to be living, although motionless. Animals that are endowed either with no lungs at all or with lungs containing little blood, need the least frequent respiration.

CHAPTER X.

In regard to bloodless animals we have said that some of them owe their survival to the surrounding air, others to the water. In the case of animals that have blood and a heart, all those that are provided with lungs take in air and effect cooling by means of inspira- tion and expiration. Now, viviparous animals are 2 provided with lungs, not those, however, that bear their living young outside of themselves (for the cartila- ginous fishes are viviparous, but not within their own bodies *), and amongst oviparous animals those that have wings are provided with lungs, as, e.g. birds, and further, such animals as have scales, like the tortoises, lizards, and snakes. Viviparous animals have a lung well 3 filled with blood, whereas most of the oviparous animals have spongy lungs. Therefore, as we said before, the latter need less frequent respiration. All of them, however, 4 do breathe, even those that live and maintain their existence in the water, such as hydras, frogs, crocodiles,

1 Mammalia are Aristotle's "internally viparous." By "externally viviparous " he means the ovoviparous, which are without placental attachment.

307

308 aristotle's psychology derespir.

fresh-water tortoises, tortoises of the sea and land, and seals. For all of these animals, and others similar to them, bear their young on the land, and sleep either on land or in the water with their mouths above the surface 476 a for respiration. Animals, on the other hand, that have

5 gills, are cooled by taking in water. To this class belong the cartilaginous fishes and other apodous animals, including all fishes. For their organs of locomotion are after the analogy of wings ([rather than feet]). Amongst animals that have feet, only one, so far as has been

6 observed, has gills, viz. the tadpole, as we call it. But no case has ever been seen of the possession of lungs and gills together. The reason is that the lungs are designed for cooling by the admission of air (even the name irvev/uiwv, ' lungs/ seems to have been derived from their reception of irved/jLa, ' air '), and gills are designed for cooling by the admission of water. But only one organ is used for one purpose, and one method of

7 cooling is adequate for each animal. And so, since we know that nature makes nothing in vain, and since one of these two organs would be useless, some animals are provided with gills and others with lungs, but no animal with both.1

1Ogle (op. cit. p. 125) points out that Aristotle cannot have been acquainted with the Dipnoi or Amphipneusta, in both of which groups gills and lungs co-exist.

CHAPTEE XL

Since every animal needs food for its subsistence and cooling for its persistence, nature employs for these two purposes one organ.1 And as in some animals the tongue is employed for the double purpose of tasting and communicating thought, so in those which are provided with lungs, the mouth serves for the masti- cation of food as well as for inspiration and expiration of air. In those, on the other hand, that have no 2 lungs and do not respire, the mouth serves for the mastication of food, but gills are provided for cooling where cooling is needed. In what way the functioning of the aforesaid organs effects cooling, we shall explain 3 later. In order not to hinder the admission of food, a similar method is employed by respiring animals and by those that take in water. For in the former case they avoid respiring and swallowing their food at the same instant, otherwise they would choke by admitting liquid or solid food into the lungs through the windpipe.

lCi. De part. an. 659a 22, 683a 19 ff. Elsewhere Aristotle refers also to the nostrils as organs subserving respiration. De part. an. 6406 15, 659a 30. Cf. also above 473a 17 ff.

309

310 aristotle's psychology derespir.

For the windpipe lies in front of the oesophagus, through which food finds its way into the stomach. In the

4 sanguineous quadrupeds the windpipe is provided with a sort of lid called the epiglottis. In birds and ovi-

476 £ parous quadrupeds, on the contrary, there is no such lid, but they attain the same end by contracting the windpipe.1 When food is being swallowed, the ovipara contract the windpipe, whereas the vivipara close the

5 epiglottis. And after the food has passed, in the one case the windpipe is expanded, and in the other the epiglottis is opened, and air is admitted for the purpose of cooling. In regard to those animals that are pro- vided with gills, they discharge the water through these and then admit food through the mouth. They have no windpipe, so that they can suffer no harm by the wrong discharge of water into it, but only by

6 the entrance of water into the stomach. For this reason, the discharge of water and the swallowing of food is done rapidly, and their teeth are sharp, and in almost all instances are serrated, for they cannot chew their food.

1 In the mammalia food is prevented from passing into the windpipe during deglutition by the epiglottis, which is possessed by no other animals, while in other vertebrates this function is performed by the closing of the larynx through muscular constriction (De part. an. 664?) 22). Cf. also Hist. an. 535a 29 ff. and De an. 4206 29, where the functions of these organs in speech are treated.

CHAPTEE XII.

Eegarding the cetaceous aquatic animals, such as dolphins, whales, and such others as have what is known as a spout- organ, one might feel some doubt, yet even these conform to our theory. For they are apodous, and although they have lungs they take in sea-water. The ground for this apparent exception is given in the foregoing explanation ; for the end to which they take in water is not cooling. 2 This is produced in their case by means of respiration, for they have lungs. Consequently, they sleep with their mouths above the water's surface, and dolphins, it is certain, snore. Again, when they are caught in nets, they soon suffocate from lack of respiration. It is in order to breathe, then, that we observe them lying on the sea's sur- face. Since, however, they are forced to take their food in 3 the water, they must on swallowing discharge the water, and for this reason they are all provided with a spout-organ. When they have taken in water they discharge it through this spout-organ, just as fishes do through their gills. A proof of this fact is the position of the spout-organ. It 4 does not lead to any of the blood-filled organs, but is situated in front of the brain and discharges the

311

312 aristotle's psychology derespir.

water * here. For the same reason the molluscs and crustaceans admit and discharge water. I mean the sea- crayfish and crabs, as we call them. They make no use of it

5 for cooling, for they are endowed with only a small amount of heat and are in every case bloodless, so that they are

477 a kept cool enough by the surrounding water. But it is discharged on account of their food, viz. in order that the water may not enter at the moment of swallowing. The

6 crustaceans, such as the sea-crayfish and crabs, discharge the water through the plaited folds along their shaggy covering ; the purple fish and polyps discharge it through the hollow passage above the head. These

7 questions have been treated with greater detail in the History of Animals? Concerning the phenomenon of the admission and discharge of water, we have said that it is due, in certain cases, to the need of cooling, and in others to the fact that aquatic animals are obliged to swallow their food in the water.

2Ogle {op. cit. p. 127) cites Cuvier {Begne animal, i. 285) as giving the same explanation of the purpose of the blowhole, and says it is still the popularly received, although erroneous, view. Its actual use is to provide an additional safeguard (besides the epiglottis) against the entrance of water into the air passages.

2 Hist. an. 525a 30 ff.

CHAPTEK XIII.

We must next describe the method by which cooling is effected in respiring animals and in those provided with gills. We have already said that animals which have limgs respire. As to the reason why some animals have 2 this organ and why those that have it need respiration, it is because the higher order of animals are endowed with greater heat. At the same time it must be that they are endowed with a higher order of soul. For such beings are of a higher order than plants. Consequently, animals 3 whose lungs are more abundantly supplied with blood and heat are of greater bodily dimensions than others ; and the animal that is supplied with the purest and most abundant blood, i.e. man, is the most erect of all animals, and his upper structure points to the upper region of the universe true of him alone because he has lungs constituted as we have described. The essential character both of man and of other animals must, therefore, be ascribed as much to this as to any other organ. This, 4 then, is the purpose of the lungs. One must suppose that the material conditions and moving cause have constructed these animals in this way, as they have also operated to

313

314 ARISTOTLE'S PSYCHOLOGY de respir.

produce other animals with a different constitution. For some are composed chiefly of earth, like plants, others chiefly of water, like aquatic animals. And amongst the winged and terrestrial animals, the one class is composed chiefly of air and the other of fire. And they severally have their place in regions akin to their own natures.

CHAPTER XIV.

Empedocles * was wrong in saying that the aquatic animals are warmest and contain most fire, and, being 477 defective in cold and fluid, they seek refuge from constitutional excess of heat in a medium to which their nature is opposed. For water is cooler than air. It is, however, altogether unintelligible how animals born 2 on dry land can change their place of abode to water. For they are, in almost all cases, apodous. And yet, when speaking of their primary constitution, he asserts they are born on the dry land and later leave this and migrate to the water. Again, our observation shows 3 that they are not warmer than land animals ; for some of them are absolutely bloodless, while others are almost

1 The writings are no longer extant from which Aristotle derived these views of Empedocles. Lucretius, who was a follower of Epicurus, and an admirer of Empedocles (cf. De rer. not. i. 66, 716 ff.), gives expression to the same view {De rer. nat. v. 793), that land animals cannot have migrated from water {salsis lacunis) to the land ; on the contrary, all animals are land-born (a terra quoniam sunt cuncta creata). The theory of Empedocles was allied to the ancient myth of the Autochthons. Anaximander, on the contrary, taught the evolution of animals from the moist element under the influence of the sun's heat (Ritter and Preller, Philos. graec. p. 19a).

315

316 ARISTOTLE'S PSYCHOLOGY de respir.

so. But what kind of animals we should call warm and what kind cold, is a subject itself that requires investiga- tion. Eegarding the explanation given by Empedocles, his contention is, in a certain sense, correct, although

4 what he says is not entirely true. For it is true that regions and seasons which exhibit characteristics opposed to abnormal conditions in animals tend to preserve them, and yet their normal nature is best preserved in a place of abode similar to their own constitution. For the matter out of which animals are severally constituted must not be confounded with the varying states and conditions of

5 this matter. I mean, e.g. if a thing were formed of wax or ice, its preservation would not be secured by placing it in a hot environment. For, owing to the opposed nature of its surroundings, it would be quickly destroyed, for heat melts that which consists of the contrary nature. Again, if a thing were composed of salt or nitre, nature would not carry it and set it down in a wet environment, for water dissolves substances of a

6 warm, dry constitution. If, therefore, the fluid and solid constitute the matter out of which all bodies are formed, it is reasonable to suppose that fluid and cold structures will be found in a moist environment ; solid structures, on the other hand, in a solid environment. Consequently, trees do not grow in water, but in the earth ; although,

7 according to this same theory of Empedocles, they should migrate to the water, because of their being predominantly dry, or, to use his expression, " predominantly fiery." This migration would be to water not because it is cold, but because it is fluid. The natural constitution of matter, therefore, conforms to the environment in which

chap. xiv. HEAT AND ENVIRONMENT 317

it is found the moist, e.g. is found in water, the warm 8 in the air. Acquired conditions, however, are better 478 a regulated through an opposite environment, excessive heat through cold surroundings, and excessive cold through warm surroundings. For the environment reduces the excess in these conditions and brings them to an equable mean. This reduction is to be sought in an environment adapted to the particular constitution of the thing and in the variations of ordinary climate. For acquired conditions may be opposed to the place of abode, but this is impossible in the case of the original constitution.

Touching the theory of Empedocles that animals are 9 divided into aquatic and land animals on the basis of differences in natural heat, and touching the explanation of the phenomenon that the one class has lungs and the other not, let the foregoing discussion suffice.

CHAPTER XV.

The reason why animals with lungs can take in air and respire, especially such as have lungs well filled with blood, is to be found in the fact that the lungs are porous and filled with tubes. The lungs contain more blood than any other organ in what we call the viscera.

2 Animals whose lungs are abundantly supplied with blood need rapid refrigeration, because of the delicate balanc- ing of the natural heat, and because the cooling process must penetrate through the entire interior, owing to the great supply of blood and heat. Air can easily meet both these demands. For owing to its rarity, it rapidly penetrates everywhere, and effects cooling.1 This is not

3 true of water. It is also plain from this why it is that animals which have lungs well filled with blood breathe best. It is due to the fact that the warmer the nature the greater is the need of cooling, and at the same time that the air fills the lungs, it passes readily to the original source of animal heat in the heart.

1 Empedocles and Plato supposed that the air penetrated through the pores of the skin, which in their theories became channels of venti- lation.

318

CHAPTER XVI.

The way in which a passage is made between heart and lungs must be studied through dissection, and in the History of Animals} Animal nature, in general, needs cooling, because of the vital fire in the heart. This is accomplished by means of respiration, excepting in those cases where animals are provided with a heart only but no lungs. When they have a heart but no lungs, as is 2 the case in fishes, whose natural abode is water, cooling is attained by water through the use of the gills. In regard to the relative positions of heart and gills, one must study them ocularly in dissection and their nicer philosophy in 478 £ the History of Animals. To give a summary descrip- tion, however, the case is as follows : One might suppose 3 that the position of the heart in land and aquatic animals was different ; as a matter of fact, it is the same in both. For the direction in which the animal's head naturally inclines is the direction in which the heart's apex is turned. But inasmuch as the heads of land animals do not incline in the same direction as

1 Cf . Hist. an. 496a 5 ff., 5116 24, where an historical account of theories regarding the anatomy of the blood-ducts is given.

319

320 ARISTOTLE'S PSYCHOLOGY de respir.

those of aquatic animals, the heart's apex in the latter

4 case is turned towards the mouth. A sinewy vein-like tube extends from the extremity of the heart1 to a central point, where all the gills are united. This is the largest of all the tubes, but there are others on each side of the heart which extend to the several extremities of the gills, whereby cooling is produced and transmitted to the heart, the water being constantly piped through

5 the gills. The rapid swelling and falling motion of the thorax in inhaling and exhaling air serves the same purpose in respiring animals that the movement of gills does in fishes. Kespiring animals suffocate in a small quantity of air that remains unchanged ; for each medium ([water as well as air]) soon becomes hot, and contact

6 with the blood heats them. When, however, the blood becomes hot, the process of cooling is impeded. Also when respiring animals become unable to inflate their lungs, or aquatic animals to move their gills, whether owing to disease or to the weakness of old age, their end must be at hand.

1 The aortic bulb, which Aristotle took to be the heart's apex.

CHAPTEE XVII.

Birth and death are phenomena common to all animals, although there are specific differences in their modes of occurrence. Death is not everywhere the same, although in its varied forms there is a common element. Death ensues from violence or from the ordinary course of nature. Death is violent when due to an external cause, natural when due to internal processes. The latter conforms to the original organic structure, and is not an adventitious condition. In plants this process is called decay ; in 2 animals, senility. Death and decay attach to all organ- isms alike that are complete, and to the incomplete also, but in a different way. Under incomplete, I understand such things as eggs, and seeds of plants which as yet have not taken root. Death is caused in all things by lack of heat ; in complete organisms by its failure in that part where the vital principle is lodged. This principle 3 is lodged, as we said above, in the middle region, where the upper and lower parts are conjoined. In plants it is the point at which stem and root unite ; in sanguineous animals, it is the heart ; in bloodless animals, in an organ 479 « analogous to the heart. In some of the bloodless animals

X 321

322 aristotle's psychology de respir.

we find many vital centres potentially, though not

4 actually. For this reason certain insects, when divided, continue to live, and such sanguineous animals as are not highly organized live a considerable time after the removal of the heart, as is true of tortoises. Tortoises continue to move their feet1 so long as their shell is not removed, because their organization is of a lower order, resembling

5 in this respect the insects. The vital principle succumbs in its possessor when the heat which is its accompaniment is not reduced by cooling. For otherwise, as we have

6 often remarked, it is consumed by its own agency. When, therefore, the lungs or gills respectively become hardened, or dried up and earthy through lapse of time,2 it is impossible for these organs to function, to dilate and contract. And finally, when a further demand is made

7 upon them, the fire of life is extinguished. Consequently, death quickly ensues in old age, even on the appearance of trivial ailments. This is due to the fact that there is little heat left in old age, most of it having been exhaled in a long life, and if any extra strain is put upon the lungs, life is speedily quenched. For the fire within, being now but a tiny feeble

8 flame, is extinguished by a slight movement. That is also the reason why death in old age is painless, for death comes to the aged with no element of violence in it, rather the dissolution of the soul occurs quite

9 without their feeling it. Diseases which make the lungs

1 Ogle [op. cit. p. 132) points out that this passage shows that Aristotle occasionally vivisected animals, and cites the following passages : Hist. an. 5036 23; De gen. an. 765a 26, 7746 31.

2 Or through the hardening (by drying) effects of fever or accretions of matter on the lungs' surface.

chap. xvii. EXTINCTION OF LIFE . 323

hard, whether by tubercles or deposits or by excessive morbid heat, as in fevers, produce an acceleration of the breathing, because the lungs are incapable of full expansion and contraction. And finally, when motion is no longer possible, men exhale their breath and die.

CHAPTER XVIII.

Birth, then, is the original suffusion of the nutritive soul with heat, and life is the maintenance of this heat. Youth is commensurate with the growth of the primary organ of cooling, old age with the wasting of the organ, and the prime of life with the middle period between the

2 two. Death and violent destruction mean respectively the exhaustion * and extinction of the vital heat (for it is

479 b destroyed from both causes) ; exhaustion is given in the nature of the thing itself, and is caused by lapse of time

3 and by the completion of a normal term of life. In plants this is called decay ; in animals, death. Death in old age is due to the exhaustion of the organism that comes from senile inability to effect cooling. We have now explained the meaning of birth, life, and death, and have treated the causes of these phenomena in animals.

1 Extinction (<r(3fois) is violent or artificial; exhaustion (/xdpavais) is natural or due to the inherent nature of the thing itself. Cf. De vit. et mort. 4696 23 ; De resp. 4746 14.

324

CHAPTEE XIX.

Fbom these considerations one may clearly see why it is that respiring animals are suffocated in water, while fishes are suffocated in the air.1 For in one case cooling is effected by the medium of water ; in the other by that of air, and both of them are deprived of this by the change in their place of abode. We have further to 2 explain the movement 2 in gills and lungs respectively, exhalation and inhalation in the one case, and the admission and discharge of water in the other. We have also to explain the structure of the organ of respiration in what follows.3

1 Vid. note 1, p. 291.

2 i.e. by the movements of these organs the cooling medium (air or water) is admitted to the organism and the temperature regulated.

3 The explanation follows in Chapter xxi. Ogle (p. 132) considers Chapter xx. an interpolation.

325

CHAPTER XX.

There are three phenomena regarding the heart, which might be supposed to have the same nature, but are different, viz. palpitation, pulsation, and respiration.

2 Now, palpitation is a compression of heat in the heart, owing to cooling in other parts of the body produced by excretion or waste, such as we see in the disease called palpitation of the heart, as well as in other diseases, and in fear also. In fear the upper regions of the body are cold, and their heat is discharged and collected in the heart, where palpitation is caused, and the heat being thus compressed into a small space, it sometimes happens that animals are suffocated and

3 die from fear and its morbid conditions. The pheno- menon of pulsation, however, that occurs in the heart, and which, as we see, is a constant process, is similar to the throbbing in an abscess. In the latter the move- ment is painful owing to abnormal change in the blood. This process continues to a point where the blood is

4 concocted and converted into pus. The condition is analogous to boiling. For boiling takes place when water is evaporated by heat, and it bubbles up owing to

326

chap. xx. MOVEMENTS OF THE HEART 327

its increase in volume. The development of abscesses is arrested when the pus is not evaporated and the liquid becomes very thick ; the process in boiling is arrested 480 a when the confining vessel is overflowed. The supply of 5 moisture derived from food and its expansion through heat produces pulsation in the heart, the expansion extending to the heart's outer covering. And this is a constant process, for the flow of fluid to the heart, out of which the blood is generated, is constant. It is in the heart that blood is first formed. One can observe this 6 plainly in the growth of an embryo.1 For before the veins are distinguishable the heart is seen to contain blood. Pulsation, for this reason, is more marked in youth than in old age. For the process of evaporation is stronger in youth. The blood vessels all pulsate, and 7 they do so simultaneously, for they are all connected with the heart and originate in it. The heart, however, is in constant motion. So, too, the blood vessels are in constant motion, and simultaneously with each other, as long as the heart moves. Palpitation, then, is a re- action in the heart due to the compression of heat by the cooling of other parts of the body ; pulsation is the evaporation of the moist element as it becomes heated.

xCf. note 1, p. 276.

CHAPTER XXI.

Respiration is due to the increase of the heated element, in which the nutritive principle is lodged. As all other bodily elements need maintenance, so does this element of vital heat, and even in a greater degree than the others, for it is the source of maintenance for the other elements. When it is increased, it necessarily expands the organ in which it 2 is found. One must conceive the structure of this organ to resemble a brazier's bellows. For neither lungs nor heart differ very much from a form such as is illustrated by a bellows. Both are double.1 The nutritive principle must be situated in the centre of the vital power.2 The lungs then increase and expand, and, by expanding, the part in which they are lodged must also expand. We see this [3 when we respire. For the thorax is then expanded, because the inherent principle in this part is expanded. Owing to this expansion, as one sees in the bellows, cold air must be introduced from without and, by 480 b its cooling effect, the excess of internal heat is lowered.

1 There was a double as well as single form of bellows in use in ancient Greece.

2 Ogle adopts a conjecture of Mr. Poste ^vktlktjs for (pvaiKrjs.

328

chap. xxt. CONDITIONS OF LIFE 329

But just as the organ was expanded owing to the increase 4 of heat, so now it necessarily contracts when the heat is diminished, and by contracting, the air which was inhaled is again discharged air that was cold when admitted, but warm when discharged owing to contact with the heat inherent in the organ, especially in the case of animals whose lungs are well-filled with blood. The air enters through a mass of pipes, canals as it were, with which the lungs are provided, and blood vessels extend alongside each of these pipes, so that the entire lung appears to be filled with blood. The admission of air is termed inspiration, 5 and its discharge, expiration. The process of respiration is continuous, so long as life and this organic motion continue. Life, therefore, is given in the processes of inspiration and expiration. The movement of the gills in fishes is produced in the same way. For by the 6 expansion of the blood's heat in its course through the members, the gills are lifted and water passes through. When, on the other hand, the heat retreats to the heart through the channels and cooling is effected, the gills are lowered and the water passes out. The expansion of the heart's heat is constant and its re-admission when cooled is constant. And so in animals provided with lungs, life and death are ultimately conditioned by respiration, and in fishes by the admission of water.

This, then, is a statement of our views of life and death 7 and of almost all the questions germane to them. It is the province not only of the physician, but also of the natural philosopher, up to a certain point,1 to discuss questions of health and disease. We must not, however,

1 Reading /ue'xp' tov for fJ-^xP1 T°v-

330 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY de respir.

forget how these two classes of men differ and how they regard a subject from different points of view, although experience shows that both professions are, to a certain extent at least, conterminous. For the better educated and more painstaking physicians are conversant with the laws of nature and deem it correct to derive their principles of practice from this source, while the best trained philosophers l of nature almost always conclude with a discussion of the principles of medicine.

1 Cf. De sensu, 436a 19 ff.

BIBLIOGRAPHY.

*** The following works have been found valuable in the preparation of the present volume. Further titles are referred to in the notes. Only such works are included as have immediate reference to the Psychology. For a more varied and complete bibliography see M. Schwab, Bibliographie d'Aristote (Paris, Librarie H. Welter, 1896).

Alexandri Aphrodisiensis praeter commentaria scripta minora de

anima cum Mantissa. Ed. Bruns. Berolini, 1887. Aristotle. De anima. Recen. A. Torstrik. Berolini, 1862.

De anima. Becog. et comment, illust. Trendelenburg. Ed. altera,

Berolini, 1877.

De anima. Becog. W. Biehl. Lipsiae, 1884.

De anima lib. B secundum recensionem vaticanam. Ed. H. Rabe.

Berolini, 1891.

Barva naturalia. Becog. W. Biehl. Lipsiae, 1898.

Opera omnia, ex recensione Bekkeri. 5 vol. Berolini, 1831-1870.

Opera omnia, ex recensione Bekkeri. 11 vol. Oxonii, 1837.

Opera omnia graece et latine. 5 vol. Parisiis, Didot, 1848-1869. Barthelemy-St.-Hilaire, Psychologie (Traite" de l'ame), trad, par

Barthelemy-St.-Hilaire. Paris, 1846.

Psychologie (Opuscules), trad, par Barthelemy-St.-Hilaire. Paris,

1847. Baumker, C. Des Aristoteles Lehre von den aussern und innern

Sinnesvermogen. Leipzig, 1S77, pp. 91. Beare, J. I. Aristotle's Parva Naturalia. Hermathena, vol. ix. (1894),

pp. 1-29.

Notes on Aristotle's Parva Naturalia. Hermathena, vol. x. (1899),

pp. 455-473. Beck, H. Aristoteles de sensuum actione. Berolini, 1860, pp. 55. Bender, W. Schrift iiber die Seele. Ubers. von Bender. Stuttgart,

1872.

Die kleinen naturwissenschaftlichen Schriften (Parva Naturalia).

tjbers. von Bender. Stuttgart, 1873. Biehl, W. Uber die aristotelische Definition der Seele. Leipzig, 1863. Verhandlungen der 21sten. Versammlung deutscher Bhilologen und Schulmanner zu Augsburg, pp. 94-102,

Uber den Begriff vovs bei Aristoteles. Linz, 1864, pp. 20.

Biese, R. Die Erkenntnisslehre des Aristoteles und Kant's in Vergleichung ihrer Grundprincipien. Berlin, 1877, pp. 74.

Bobba, B. La dottrina dell' intelletto in Aristotile. Torino, 1896, pp. 479.

331

332 aristotle's psychology

Bonitz, H. Aristotelische Studien. Wien, 1863-67.

tjber das erste Buch der aristotel. Schrift uber die Seele.

Monatsber. der Konigl. Preuss. Akad. d. Wiss., 1873, pp. 481 ff.

Brentano, F. Von der mannigfachen Bedeutung des Seienden nach Aristoteles. Freiburg i/B., 1862, pp. 220.

Die Psychologie des Aristoteles, insbesondere seine Lehre vom vovs

TronjTiKos. Mainz, 1867, pp. 252.

Offener Brief an Herrn Professor Dr. Eduard Zeller. Leipzig,

1883, pp. 36. Bullinger, A. Des Aristoteles Erhabenheit uber alien Dualismus. Miinchen, 1878, pp. 94.

Aristoteles' Nus-Lehre. Dillingen, 1882, pp. 73.

Chaignet, A. E. Essai sur la psychologie d'Aristote. Paris, 1883. Collier, C. Treatise on the Principle of Life. Translated by C.

Collier. Cambridge, 1855. Deinhardt, J. H. Der Begriff der Seele mit Riicksicht auf Aristoteles.

Hamburg, 1840. Eberhard, E. Die aristotelische Definition der Seele und ihr Werth

fur die Gegenwart. Berlin, 1868, pp. 62. Essen, E. Die I. und II. Biicher der aristotelischen Schrift uber die

Seele. Jena, 1892, 1894. Freudenthal, J. Uber den Begriff des Wortes cpavraaia bei

Aristoteles. Gottingen, 1863, pp. 59.

Uber das Buch 7repl tQv kolvCjv adjfx.aTos /ecu ^vxv? epywv. Rheinisches

Museum, vol. xxiv. (1869), pp. 81-93, 392-419.

Zu Aristoteles de memoria, 452. Archiv fur Geschichte der Philos. ,

1888, pp. 5-13.

Frohschammer, J. Uber die Principien der aristotelischen Philo- sophic und die Bedeutung der Phantasie in derselben. Miinchen, 1881, pp. 143.

Granger, F. Aristotle's Theory of Reason. Classical Review, Vol. vi. (July, 1892).

Aristotle's Theory of Reason. Mind, Vol. xviii. (1893), pp. 307-318. Grote, G. Aristotle. London, 1872, 2 vols.

Giithling, K. E. Die Lehre Aristoteles von den Seelentheilen.

Liegnitz, 1S82, pp. 11. Hammond, W. A. Aristotle's Doctrine of (pavraala. Proceedings of

the Amer. Philol. Assoc, Vol. xxxii.

Aristotle's Doctrine of the Central or Common Sense. Proceed-

ings of the Amer. Philol. Assoc, for July, 1897, pp. ix. ff.

Aristotle's Doctrine of \pvxh as biological principle. Psychol.

Rev., Vol. v. (1898), pp. 159 f.

Theory of the Will in Aristotle's Ethics. Psychol. Review, Vol.

vi. (1899), pp. 169 f. Hartenstein, G. De psychologiae vulgaris origine ab Aristotele

repetendo. Lipsiae, 1846, pp. 19. Heman, K. Zur Geschichte der Lehre von der Freiheit des mensch-

lichen Willens. Erstes Heft. Leipzig, 1887, pp. 194.

BIBLIOGRAPHY 333

Hepner, E. Abhandlung von dem Gedachtniss und der Wieder- erinnerung. Ubersetzt von E. Hepner, 1824.

Abhandlung vom Schlafe und vom Wachen. Aus dem Griecbischen

iibers. von E. Hepner. Breslau, 1824.

Hertling, G. F. von. Materie und Form und die Definition der Seele bei Aristoteles. Bonn, 1871, pp. 178.

Joannis Philoponi in Aristotelis De anima libros commentaria. Ed. Hayduck. Berolini, 1897.

Kampe, F. F. Die Erkenntnisstheorie des Aristoteles. Leipzig,

1870, pp. 334. Kirchmann, G. H. von. Drei Biicber von der Seele. Ubers. und

erklart von G. H. von Kirchmann. Berlin, 1871. Kreuz, F. A. Drei Biicher von der Seele. Ubers. von Kreuz.

Stuttgart, 1847.

Kleine Abhandlungen iiber die Seele. Ubers. von Kreuz.

Stuttgart, 1847. Lewes, G. H. Aristotle. A chapter from the History of Science.

London, 1864, pp. 404. Meyer, J. B. Die Thierkunde des Aristoteles. Ein Beitrag zur

Geschichte der Zoologie, Physiologie, und alten Philosophic.

Berlin, 1855, pp. 520. Michaelis, K. G. Zu Aristoteles de anima iii. 3. Neu-Strelitz, 1882,

pp. 20. Muller, Johannes. Aristoteles iiber den Traum. Eine physiolo-

gische Urkunde. Coblentz, 1826. Uber die phantastischen Gesichtserscheinungen. Coblentz, 1826. Neuhauser, J. Aristoteles Lehre von dem sinnlichen Erkenntniss-

vermogen und seinen Organen. Leipzig, 1878, pp. 132. Ogle, W. On Youth and Old Age, Life and Death, and Respiration.

Trans, with introduction and notes by W. Ogle. London, 1S97,

pp. 135. Partzsch, T. Aristoteles Lehre von der Seele nach ihren Grundziigen.

Dresden, 1873, pp. 35. Philibert, H. Du principe de la vie suivant Aristote. Paris, 1865. Philippson, L. "T\rj dvOpcowivr}. Partes duae. Berolini, 1831, pp. 252. Poppelreuter, H. Zur Psychologie des Aristoteles, Theophrast,

und Strato. Leipzig, 1892, pp. 52. Pouchet, G. La biologie aristotelique. Paris, 1885. Ritter, B. Die Grundprincipien der aristotelischen Seelenlehre.

Jena, 1880, pp. 32. Rodier, G. Aristote. Trai^e de l'ame. Traduit et annote par G.

Rodier. 2 vols. Paris, 1900. Schell, J. H. Die Einheit des Seelenleben aus den Principien der

aristotelischen Philosophic entwickelt. Freiburg i/B., 1873,

pp. 209. Schiebold, F. O. De imaginatione disquisitio. Lipsiae, 1882, pp. 70. Schlottmann, K. Das Vergangliche und Unvergangliche^in der

menschlichen Seele nach Aristoteles. Halle, 1873, pp. 57.

334 ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY

Schneider, L. Die Unsterblichkeitslehre des Aristoteles. Passau,

1867, pp. 141. Siebeck, H. Die Lehre des Aristoteles von dem Leben und der

Beseelungd. Universums. Zeitsch. fiirPhilos. undphilos. Kritik.

Bd. 60 (1872), pp. 1-39.

Geschichte der Psychologic Theil I. Abth. i., ii. Die Psycho-

logic bis Thomas von Aquino. Gotha, 1880, 1884, pp. 284, 531.

Untersuchungen zur Philos. der Griechen. Zweite Aufl. Frei-

burg i/B., 1888, pp.279.

Aristoteles. Stuttgart, 1899, pp. 142.

Simplicii in libros Aristotelis de anima cornmentaria ed. Hayduck.

Berolini, 1882. Sommerfeld. Die Psychologie von Aristoteles und Beneke. Gross-

Glogau, 1879, pp. 12. Sophoniae in libros Aristotelis de anima paraphrasis ed. Hayduck.

Berolini, 1883. Sperling, K. Aristoteles Ansicht von der psychologischen Bedeu-

tung der Zeit. Marburg, 1888, pp. 73. Susemihl, F. Zu Aristoteles Psychologie. Philologus, Bd. 46 (1886),

pp. 86. Teichmuller, G. Neue Studien zur Geschichte der Begriffe. Heft III.

Die praktische Verunft bei Aristoteles. Gotha, 1879, pp. 453. Themistii in libros Aristotelis de anima paraphrasis ed. Heinze.

Berolini, 1S99. Voigt, M. W. Uber die menschliche Seele. Ubersetzt und mit

Aumerkungen begleitet von M. W. Voigt. Leipzig, 1803. Volkmann, W. F. Die Grundziige der aristotelischen Psychologie.

Aus den Quellen dargestellt. Prag, 1859. Waddington, Ch. De la Psychologie d'Aristote. Paris, 184S. pp.

384. Wallace, E. Aristotle's Psychology. In Greek and English, with

introduction and notes by Edwin Wallace. Cambridge, 1882,

pp. cxxviii, 327. Walter, J. Die Lehre von der praktischen Verunft in der griech.

Philos. Jena, 1874, pp. 573. Weisse, C. H. Von der Seele und von der Welt. Ubersetzt und

mit Anmerkungen begleitet von C. H. Weisse. Leipzig, 1829. Wilson, J. Cook. Conjectural Emendations. Journal of Philol.

Vol. xi. (1882), pp. 119-124. Wolff, W. Von dem Begriffe des Aristoteles liber die Seele und

dessen Anwendung auf die heutige Psychologie. Bayreuth, 1S48,

pp. 16. Zeller, E. Uber die Lehre des Aristoteles von der Ewigkeit des

Geistes. Abhandl. der Akad. d. Wiss., Bd. xlix., pp. 1033 ff.

Berlin, 1882. Aristotle and the Earlier Peripatetics, translated by Costelloe and

Muirhead. London, 1897, 2 vols. Ziaja, J. De sensu. Cap. 1 bis 4396 18. Ubersetzt und mit Anmerkungen versehen von J. Ziaja. Breslau, 1887, pp. 15.

INDEX.

Abstraction, 125.

Actuality, 43, 63 f.

Affections, nature of, 29.

After-image, 236.

Air, as medium, 76 ff.

Alcmaeon, 16.

Anaxagoras, on respiration, 288 ;

on soul, 12-17. Anger, definition of, 8. Animals, classification of, 171 ;

distinguished from plants, 272 ;

longevity of, 263, 266, 304;

ovoviviparous, 307. Animate, 10. Animism, 49. Appetite, 133. Association of ideas, 205. Atomic theory, vid. under Demo-

critus.

Birth, 324.

Blood, circulation, 227 ; effect on dreams, 242 ; movements in, 243.

Body, dissection of, 303 ; divisions of, 273 ; elements in, 60 ; poten- tiality, 46 ; relation to soul, 40- 53.

Brain, organ of cooling, 80, 228 ; size in man, 176.

Categories, 4.

Cause, meanings of, 58, 220, 248.

Chance, 250.

Cognition, 35.

Colour, explanation of, 71, 158, 160; number of, 168; primary colours, 87.

Common sense, in consciousness, 99 ; in judgment, 103 ; in sense- perception, 97 ; in unification, 192.

Common sensibles, 97 ff., 232.

Conception, 106.

Conduct, reason and desire in,

131. Consciousness, in sleep, 215-253. Continuity, 120, 181. Critias, 16.

Death, 261.

Deduction, 6.

Definition, 6, 8, 23, 48.

Deliberation, 136.

Democritus, atomic theory, 32 ; dreams, 252 ; theory of soul, 11, 15, 21, 30, 32, 37 ; primary and secondary qualities, 101 ; respira- tion, 288-294; touch, 169; vision, 153.

Desire, 54, 123, 133, 137.

Diaphanous, 71, 73, 158 f., 171.

Diogenes of Apollonia, 15, 288, 291.

Disjunction, 119.

Divisibility, 39 ff., 120.

335

336

ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY

Dreams, atribilious, 254 ; memory of, 246 ; observation of, 245 ; origin of, 231, 251 ; prophetic, 248, 250.

Echo, 76.

Emotions, S.

Empedocles, on evolution, 315 growth, 59 ; harmony, 27 knowledge, 35 ; light, 72 movement of blood, 300 ; respira tion, 299 f. ; soul, 13, 27, 34 taste, 164 ; vision, 151 f.

Entelechy, 42, 44.

Environment, 317.

Epiglottis, 310.

Error, 119.

Eye, 153-155.

Faculties, vid. under Soul; classi- fication of, 54, 57, 58.

Feelings, physically expressed ideas, 6-8.

Flavour, vid. under Taste. Democritus on, 170 ; haptic quality, 55 ; primary flavours, 87 ; theories of, 164-167,

Form, 42, 53, 220.

Frogs, artificial, 244.

Good and bad, 124.

Hard flesh, 41.

Harmony, relation to soul, 26 ff. , 102 ; Xenocrates on, 30.

Hearing, importance of, 144, 148, 149 ; nature of, 76 ff. ; organ of, 78.

Heart, centre of life, 275 ; connec- tion with lungs, 318 ; first organ to develop, 277 ; organ of nutrition, 302 ; organ of sensa- tion, 279 ; palpitation, 326 ; structure of, 229.

Heat, animal, 280, 303, 322 ; con- trolled by respiration, 295.

Heraclitus, 15.

Hippo, 15.

Ideas, association of, 205.

Illusion, example of, 240 ; in dreams, 239.

Imagination, control of, 106 ; de- finition of, 107, 110 ; distin- guished from memory, 201 ; in dreams, 234, 242, 245 ; organ of 240 ; productive and reproduc- tive, 56 ; relation to thought, 109, 123, 127, 198 ; relation to desire, 135 ; residual sensation, 244.

Immortality, 51, 58.

Insects, live after division, 274 ; respiration of, 305.

Ionian physiologers, 17-

Judgment, function of common sense, 103 ; function of thought ; 128 ; inhibition of in sleep, 243.

Knowledge, actual and potential, 122 ; kinds of, 1, 48 ; two powers of knowing, 231.

Leucippus, 11.

Life, centralisation of, 276 ; con- nection with vital heat, 280, 322 ; destruction of, 258, 281, 324 ; duration of, 256, 262, 267, 304 ; in insects, 268 ; meanings of, 49 ; relation to respiration, 293, 329 ; seat of, 271 ; unity of, 275.

Light, cause of vision, 152, 185 ; diaphanous, 71; motion, 184; nature of, 157.

Locomotion, 129.

Longevity, 256, 265.

Lungs, coexist with gills, 308 ; function of, 80, 30S ; organ of refrigeration, 318 ; organ of respiration, 306 ; spongy, 307 ; structure of, 328.

Magnitude, relation to sensation, 162, 181.

Man, most intelligent animal, 82.

Matter, 42.

Medicine, connection with philo- sophy of nature, 147, 330.

INDEX

337

Medium, condition of sense-per- ception, 73 ff., 183 ; for percep- tion at distance, 140 ; of sound, 75 ; of touch, 89 ff.

Memory, definition of, 195 ; im- print of seal-ring, 199 ; in youth and old age, 199 ; processes of, 209 ; object of, 196 ; relation to imagination, 111, 201; relation to reason, 29 ; relation to time, 197, 210 ; seat of, 202 ; why strengthened by exercise, 202.

Method, kinds of, 3.

Monad, soul a, 30.

Motion, Democritus on, 21 ; de- fined, 19, 37, 223 ; in conduct, 133, 137 ; in sleep, 242 ; Platonic theory of, 19 ; relation to light, 72 ; relation to sensation, 65, 238 ; relation to soul, 18, 23, 28, 30, 37.

Myths, Pythagorean, 24.

Nature, purpose in, 59, 221. Nominalism, 4. Number-theory, 32. Nutrition, faculty of, 57, 62 f.,

138 ; organ of, 273 ; relation to

smell, 174 ; seat of, 271, 276 ;

shared by plants, 50 ; sweet in,

168.

Old age, 270, 324.

Opinion, not possessed by lower animals, 136 ; relation to imagi- nation, 111.

Orphic verses, 37.

Palpitation, 326 f.

Parva Naturalia, 145.

Perception, limits of, 193 ; per- ceptibility and magnitude, 182 ; unity in, 192.

Phantasy, vid. under Imagination.

Philaegides, 254.

Philosophy of nature, relation of to medicine, 147, 330.

Plants, differentiated fromanimals, 272 ; duration of life in, 267 ;

heat in, 284, 302 ; soul in, 41, 50 ; without sensation, 94.

Plato, 'circular push,3 296; Dis- courses on Philosophy, 13 ; facul- ties of soul, 51 ; on motion, 14 ; nature of the soul, 13, 21, 33 ; Timaeus, 51, 151 ; on vision, 151.

Pleasure and pain, 51, 122.

Potentiality, meaning of, 4, 44, 64-68, 87; relation to know- ledge, 66, IOC.

Pre- Aristotelian psychology, 11 ff., 26 ff.

Predication, 121.

Principle, meaning of, 2.

Proof, demonstration, 23.

Psychology, pre- Aristotelian, 10 ff.

Pulsation, 326.

Pythagoreans, myths, 24; nature of soul, 11, 17, 24, 26, 53; respiration, 298.

Qualities, primary and secondary, 101.

Realism, 4.

Reason, active, 47, 112-118; Anaxagoras on, 12 ; divine nature of, 29 ; epitactic, 130, 132 ; in- destructible, 29; practical, 124, 125, 135; relation to imagina- tion, 110 ; separability from body, 24 ; thinks abstractions, 125 ; thinks external world, 181 ; time necessary to, 197; unify- ing principle, 120.

Recollection, definition of, 195 ; deliberation in, 211; different from memory, 204; how pro- duced, 206; in youth and old age, 212; movement from within, 29; not shared by lower ani- mals, 211.

Reflex-movement, 275.

Refrigeration, organs of, 80; pur- pose of, 284.

Respiration, in aquatic animals, 289, 291, 311 ; functions of, 297 ; in insects, 305; organ of, 301;

338

ARISTOTLE S PSYCHOLOGY

in old age, 320; Plato's theory of, 296; purpose of, 286; in whales, 311.

Sapid, defined, 85, 86.

Sensation, activity of, 237; com- mon sense, 70, 97, 99; co- ordination in, 189; definition of, 93, 112; duration of, 190; in dreams, 233 ; fusion, 187 ; medium, 182; mean, 92; move- ment from without, 29 ; organs of, 96 ; necessary to animal life, 138 ; persistence of, 239 ; purpose of, 147 ; qualitative change, 236; relation to heart, 277; relation to thought, 106; seat of, 279; simultaneity in, 186; in sleep, 241, 249. Vid. under the particular senses.

Sense-object, 69, 102.

Sense-perception, 64 ff., 101.

Sense-quality, 69, 181.

Senses, correlated with physical elements, 150; five, 95 ff. ; higher and lower, 140, 148.

Sensibility, relation to magnitude, 180, 193.

Sensibles, common, 97 ff., 232.

Sight, vid. under Vision; impor- tance of, for higher life, 144, 148.

Sign, definition of, 248, 252.

Simultaneity of sensations, 190ff.

Sleep, cause of, 218, 224, 226 f., 230; consciousness in, 215, 244; function of, 216; heaviness in, 225; mantic character of, 247; movements in, 223; necessary to animal life, 216, 221 ; organ of, 215, 222; sensation in, 241 ; tractate on, 213 ff.

Smell, air affected by, 94; classifi- cation of smells, 83, 173 ; ex- halation, 155 ; inaccurate in man, 82, 164; in air and water, 171, 177; medium required by, 74, 84 ; middle position of, 177; nature of, 82 ff. ; relation to flavour, 83, 164, 174; relation to respiration, 175; 'sapid dry,' 172; theories of, 173 ff.

Soul, Alcmaeon on, 16; Anaxa- goras on, 16; atomic theory of, 11 ; body related to, 6, 7, 9, 29, 40, 53, 58, 146; centralisa- tion of, 274; Critias on, 16; definition of, 45-52, 55, 56; Democritus on, 11, 15; Dio- genes on, 15; elements related to, 33 f., 37, 38; Empedocles on, 13 ; etymology of word, 17 ; faculties of, 40, 51, 54, 57, 133 ; final cause, 59 ; fire, 60 ; har- mony, 26 f. ; Heraclitus on, 15 ; Hippo on, 16; immortality of, 6, 7, 31, 47, 51 ; knowledge, 41 ; Leucippus on, 11 ; life, 39, 49 ; motion, 10, 19 ff., 30, 37; num- ber-theory, 30, 32 ; nutrition, 50, 61 ff., 271 ; Plato on, 13, 51 ; pre- Aristotelian theories of, 10 ff., 13, 33; principle in plants, 41; reality, 126; separability of, 6f., 31, 47, 51; substance, 42; Thales on, 15; unity of, 40, 51 ; Xenocrates on, 30.

Sound, of insects, 305 ; nature of, 75 ff.

Stimuli, excessive, 93, 102.

Substance, meanings of, 42, 44, 52.

Taste, accurate in man, 82 ; nature of, 85 f . ; primary flavours, 87 ; touch and, 139, 164.

Temperature, regulation of, 80.

Thales, soul kinetic, 15 ; pan- psychism, 38.

Theophrastus, on sound, 75.

Theories of soul, history of, 11 ff.

Thought, vid. under Reason, defi- nition of, 106 ; dependent on will, 67 ; discursive, 29 : identi- cal with object, 125 ; inde- pendence of body, 6 ; image necessary to, 6, 197; somatic, 105,

Time, 191.

Touch, accuracy of, in man, 82 ; analogy to hearing, 79 ; direct action of, 142 ; function of, 69; fundamental character of, 50, 52, 54-56, 139, 142, 143;

INDEX

339

medium of, 85, 89-91 ; nature of, 88 ff., 169; organ of, 89; taste and, 55.

Universals, nature of, 4 ; in the mind, 67.

Vision, vid. under Sight ; con- nected with fire, 150; Demo- critus on, 153 ; effect on object, 237 ; Empedocles on, 152 ; eye as organ of, 155 ; medium of, 141 ; nature of, 71 ; Plato on, 151; theories of, 150 ff.

Voice, significant sound, 79-81.

Waking, definition of, 214. Whales, spout-organ in, 312. Will, kinetic aspect of reason,

129-131. Windpipe, 309. Words, symbols, 149.

Xenocrates, 30-33.

Youth, and old age, 270.

GLASGOW : PRINTED AT THE UNIVERSITY PR&SS BY ROBERT MACLEHOSE AND CO.

BOSTON UNIVERSITY

1 l?n D1D3S Ab30

DO NOT REMOVE

CHARGE SLIP FROM THIS POCKET

IF SLIP IS LOST PLEASE RETURN BOOK

DIRECTLY TO A CIRCULATION STAFF MEMBER

BOSTON UNIVERSITY LIBRARIES

771 Commonwealth Ave. Boston, Mass. 02215

mm

&95

« bosk

mm

JBI

m%

Mi

WhrE

HP

&£&

!&'!$?7\#?.;<

^H

HI

raftni&iira

■w

^M

^8B

h

i§^

«KS&JMfr,;^gc

^€

Mini " =

^^^^^^^^^^^^^B

|

1

■1

1

■■

'

,