LIBRARY INIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA

8T. LOUIS EXHIBIT

University of California.

THE INTELLECT.'1

An Introduction to

PHILOSOPHY.

[Or, Elements of PSYCHOLOGY,

Empirical and Rational.)

By Rev. E. JANES, A. M.

W. B. Hardy, Publisher, Oakland, CAL., $1.25.

0?

Pres. Mark Hopkins, Williams College ;- "It shows extended research, careful discrimination a*ft€t good judgment, and I congratulate you on having produced such a work."

Prof. Francis Bowen, Harvard College ; - "I have examined it with attention and pleasure. It shows much reading and careful thought; the style is concise, but lucid, so that much matter' is brought in- to small compass, and it is thus well ad- apted for use as a text-book."

;CT.

)PHY.

OAKLAND, CAL., W. B

1884.

Prof. Geo. P. Fisher, Yale College;—

"From the hurried examination which I have thus far been able to devote to its pages, I am persuaded that it is the fruit of thorough study and reflection. I am glad that you have dealt so much with Lotze."

Prof. G. S. Morris, Univ. of Michigan; "I have examined it attentively, and think it well adapted to the purpose for which it is intended." Rev. Joseph Cook, Boston;—

''I value very highly your contrasted citations from Lotze and ot! The "PACIFIC" of Sept, 10th, 1884;—

''This book of Mr. Janes is short, but comprehensive; it is condensed, but clear and interesting iu style and in manner of treatment. It is in accord with the best theistic thought. . . It is fully abreast of recent discussion. . . The views of oppo- sing schools of philosophy are clearly and fairly stated. . .An interesting feature of the book is the "Historical Sketch" of the leading philosophers."

HUMAN PSYCHOLOGY.

(RIRST DIVISION.)

THE INTELLECT,

AN INTRODUCTION TO PHILOSOPHY.

BY REV. E. JANES, A. M.

OAKLAND, CAL.,

W. B HARDY.

1884.

COPYRIGHT, 1884,

By E.JANES, Oakland, Cal. C&A^/rnsiTT--*

PACIFIC PRESS,

Printers, Electrotypers, and Binders. lath and Castro Sts., ) ( 529 Commercial St.

H

Oakland. f \ San Francisco

*BF 43 \

PREKACB.

MY purpose in writing this book has been, to furnish something adapted to the use of ordinary college classes, and other young per- sons who may desire an introduction to the study of philosophy. I was led to see the need of such a book by actual experience in teaching. I found that the existing text-books were unsatisfactory for a variety of reasons.

Of the American books on this subject, nearly all were written a num- ber of years ago, and are now somewhat out of date. Within twenty years some substantial progress has been made in psychology, and several important researches have appeared. Most of these text-books, moreover, have paid little or no attention to the German literature of the subject. Many contain mere sketches of the Intellect, giving the most space to the Emotions and the Will. Some are too large, difficult, and ill-arranged. Some are too abstruse in style .and matter.

Some of the ablest text-books are too one-sided. For example, Prof. Bain's Mental Science is an able exposition of the Associational psychology, but gives no adequate knowlege of anything else.

In composing this book I have endeavored constantly to keep in mind the needs of students, and to avoid the above defects. In doing so I have had the advantage of testing large parts of it by actual experiment with young students of the subject, whose suggestions, sometimes uncon- scious, have been valuable to me at many points.

Attention is requested to the following features of the present work, as the objects at which I have aimed.

i. It is a small book, as all text-books should be; yet it contains, I believe, more matter strictly on the intellect than any other American text- book, except that of President Porter. Though small enough to be read through by a college class in one term, it is yet large enough to contain a fair introduction to the study of philosophy, and give the attentive stu-

PREFACE.

dent some idea of the literature of the subject. In striving to accomplish this, the two following features have become specially important.

2. Condensation and brevity have been aimed at, as far as consistent with clearness. Obscurity, prolixity, and unnecessary abstrusity are equally out of place in a text-book.

3. In treating those parts of the subject which require illustration by instances, I have given but a few in each case, selected from the best. A vast mass of such material has been accumulated in the easily accessible works of Carpenter, Maudsley, Ribot, Sully, Taine, etc. I deem it not worth while to reprint very many of these examples, or to require students to study them. The teacher can read to the class, with better effect, his own- selection of them, and will find new material constantly in current literature.

4. The arrangement is progressive. It begins with the senses, after only the most necessary preliminaries, and ascends through Perception to the metaphysical questions involved in Psychology.

5. It quotes freely from the best authorities, and from those only. The "Dictate" from the lectures of Lotze, published after his death, have been very often made use of. Herbert Spencer is frequently quoted, though not so often with approval as Lotze. Bain has been constantly referred to, and his great merits acknowledged, but hi^ errors, as I deem them, pointed out. Hamilton and Porter have, of course, been constantly in my hand. I owe much also to Drbal's " empirische Psychologies

6. In the historical sketch an attempt has been made to cause each great philosopher described, to appear to the student, not as a mere bun- dle of doctrines, but as a personality, a man. A full account of their opin'ons would be often too abtruse and always too prolix for such a work, but much is gained if interest can be excited in the great names of phi- losophy.

A full and careful index has been added, showing the number of times each important authority has been quoted or cited.

If this book shall help to make the study of psychology and philoso- phy more attractive and more accessible to students or general readers, I shall feel rewarded for my labor.

It is my intention to prepare a brief treatise, similar in plan to the present one, on the second and third divisions of the general subject of Human Psychology, the Emotions, including Pleasure and Pain, and the Will. E. J.

Oakland, CaL, June, 1884.

INTRODUCTION.

PHILOSOPHY is the science of first principles, that is, the principles which underlie all science and all knowledge. Though often derided by those who say, " Let us study phenomena, and leave abstractions to take care of them- selves," philosophy is yet justified even by these ungrateful children, for they, too, are constrained, even unconsciously, to resort to metaphysical principles, and have each a philosophy of his own.

" The adepts in any of the special sciences never come to a full understanding of their own subjects of inquiry without encroaching on metaphysical ground, and even our physicists find themselves studying and teaching metaphysics unawares." (Bowen.) "We are compelled in every explanation of natural phenomena to leave the sphere of sense, and pass to things which are not objects of sense, and are defined by abstract conceptions." (Helmholtz.)

Indeed, the most characteristic conceptions of modern physical science, evolution, development, morphology, con- servation of energy, correlation of forces, pangenesis all are philosophical ideas, not subject to observation. "When the

6 THE INTELLECT.

doctrine of morphology was first explained to Schiller, he exclaimed, 'This is not an observation, but an idea.'" " The fundamental ideas of modern science are as transcendental as any of the axioms of ancient philosophy," (Lewes.) "The highest generalizations of physical research bring us face to face with certain conceptions which are purely ideal and rational, that is, metaphysical ideas. Such are the ideas of substance, cause, force, life, order, proportion, law, purpose, unity, identity." (Cocker.)

Philosophy, then, is a necessity of the human mind; even those who assail it do so with its own weapons. "Aristotle long ago remarked that we are compelled to philosophize in order to prove that philosophy itself is illusory and vain." (Bowen.) Many modern scientific writers "are endeavoring to substitute for philosophy proper a species of speculative physical science, in which, however, careful analysis will always detect an unsuspected residuum of purely metaphysical prin- ciples." (Cocker.)

Philosophy may therefore be said to be a defence of funda- mental truth. Errors in science, in ethics, in theology, in government, in legislation, are usually founded on abstract principles, assumed, perhaps unconsciously, without proof, or without the application of the criteria of truth. To detect and expose such errors requires us to recur to first principles, and establish them on firm and reasonable bases, to define those fundamental truths without which science and reasoning are alike impossible. The science of geometry depends on the abstract conception of space, arithmetic on number, law on right, ethics on duty, physics on cause, esthetics (the science of criticism) on beauty.

In English the word philosophy is often used in connection with the names of the sciences, as philosophy of geometry, philosophy of physics, of law, of education, of art, etc. This

INTRODUCTION. 7

does not imply that each of these subjects is a branch of philosophy, nor that each has within itself a different kind of philosophy, but denotes the abstract principles, the meta- physical ideas of 'each science or subject, as philosophically determined.

Philosophy may thus be defended as a delightful pursuit and exercise of the mind. As Moli&re's M. Jourdain was delighted to find that he had been talking prose all his life, so it is very pleasant for an acute mind to find that the questions and difficulties which naturally arise within itself have been experienced, discussed, and answered by other such minds in all the ages. To many minds the pursuit of knowledge is the highest of all pleasures; much more, then, is there attractiveness in the highest kind of knowledge, in pure science, where ulti- mate truth is sometimes difficult and disputed, but, when found and proved, embraces all being in its scope, and brings together all the sciences in a fascinating unity.

Philosophy, besides being necessary and valuable for its own sake, is useful:—

i. For training the mind to a philosophical temper, a candid love of truth, a calm confidence in itself. " There is a philosophic spirit which is far more valuable than any limited acquirements of philosophy; ... a spirit which is quick to pursue whatever is within the reach of human intellect, but which is not less quick to discern the bounds that limit every human inquiry; . . . which knows how to dis- tinguish what is just in itself from what is merely accredited by illustrious names; . . . adopting a truth which no one has sanctioned, and rejecting an error, of which all approve, with the same calmness as if no judgment were opposed to its own; ... yet applauding gladly whatever is worthy of applause in a rival system, and venerating the very genius which it demon- strates to have erred." (Dr. T. Brown.)

8 THE INTELLECT.

2. For counteracting some injurious tendencies of the cur- rent devotion to physical studies. " The utility of metaphy- sics rises in proportion to the progress of the natural sciences, and to the greater attention which they engross." (Sir W. Hamilton.) The natural tendency of exclusive attention to any one class of studies is toward a narrow-minded dogmatism. In these times physical studies need no recommendation; they are forced upon the attention of every person who thinks or studies at all. There is no danger that physics will be neg- lected for philosophy, but quite the opposite. A symmetrical culture demands that some attention be paid to the first prin- ciples of knowledge, the nature of reasoning, the limitations of the mind, the existence of the soul and God.

3. For developing intellectual power. "The intellect" says Aristotle, " is perfected not by knowledge but by activity." Says Malebranche, " If I held truth captive in my hand I should open my hand and let it fly, in order that I might again pursue and capture it." " Energy," says Hamilton, " is the means by which our faculties are developed. All profitable study is a silent disputation, an intellectual gymnastic. . . . It is this condition, imposed upon the student, of doing every- thing himself, that renders the study of the mental sciences the most improving exercise of intellect." But it is not only the power of abstract thought which is developed and strengthened by the study of philosophy; clearness and accuracy of thought and of language are cultivated by these studies as by no others; and only those accustomed to philosophical discussions can appreciate the great scarcity of these all-important qualities in the world of thought and literature.

The term metaphysics is often used as the equivalent of philosophy; indeed, some writers formally define the one term by the other. The best and most recent usage, however, tends to restrict the term metaphysics to a more narrow province.

INTRODUCTION. 9

Philosophy is, in this usage, a more general term, covering all study of abstract principles. The term science was formerly much used in the same signification, and the science of any thing was said to be the knowledge of its principles and causes. But science is now generally used to denote the knowledge of phenomena, experimentally ascertained. Thus we have the "sciences " of botany, of mineralogy, consisting almost en- tirely of classification and description; and even the " science of psychology" is sometimes understood to mean the mere description and classification of the phenomena of the senses and the intellect. The term empirical psychology is also used for this, the concrete, and rational psychology for the abstract or metaphysical part, of this science.

According to Lotze, the problem of philosophy is to bring the separate departments of thought into unity and connection, and especially to investigate those ideas which are principles of judgment in life and in the various sciences. And the term philosophy means either the investigation which has this end in view, or the systematic presentation of the results so obtained. (Dictate, Logik, etc., §88.)

Lotze also says that metaphysics has for its aim to reconcile all the contradictions into which we are led by unscientific thought and by the separate pursuit of the different sciences. He divides metaphysics into three parts, (i) ontology, which asks, what are being, existence, action, etc.; (2) cosmology, which asks, what are space, time, motion, etc.; (3) rational psychology, which treats of the connection between the ob- jective world and the spiritual world, or the problem of knowl- edge. (Dictate, Metaphysik, §§i, 6.)

Mansel divides metaphysics into two parts, " (i) psychology, or the science of the facts of consciousness as such; (2) ontol- ogy, or the science of the same facts considered in their rela- tion to realities existing without the mind." (Metaphysics, 29.)

io THE INTELLECT.

" Philosophy of nature " (German natur-philosophie), is a very useful term, meaning, not natural philosophy, which in English has come to mean physics, but the rational explana- tion of the laws of matter. Under this title Lotze discusses matter, force, inertia, attraction, life, development, as well as space, time, and motion, which also appear in metaphysics.

Logic, which discusses the principles of reasoning, ethics, which discusses the principles of obligation, and theology proper, which discusses the being and attributes of God, are often called departments of philosophy.

There is a tendency in some quarters to use the term phi- losophy in a restricted sense, nearly equivalent to ontology. "Philosophy is the science of the Absolute." (Schelling.) "Philosophy is the science of Being." (Morris.) "It is the investigation of those principles on which all knowledge and all being ultimately rest." (Fleming.)

We approve rather of the following definitions : " Philosophy is the science of sciences." (Ulrici.) " Philosophy is a rational explanation of things existing and of things occurring." (Calderwood.) "A knowledge of things by their causes." (Aristotle.) " Philosophy is the science of first principles. (Morell.) " Philosophy is the attainment of truth by the way of reason." (Ferrier.)

We remark in general that many writers use all these terms with culpable vagueness and uncertainty, not informing them- selves of the received uses of words, or not strictly adhering to their own definitions.

DEFINITIONS.

Psychology is the science of the mind. Science is accurate knowledge, systematically arranged.

The mind is that which knows, feels, and wills. The real- ity and nature of this subject of these peculiar phenomena is reserved for discussion after we have studied the phenomena.

The term " Psychology " is the best to designate this science, for the following reasons:

1. It nas long been in use in other languages. In Latin psychologia can be traced as far back as 1594. In German and French psychologic is said to have been in use over two centuries.

2. It covers the exact field intended, including all the phenomena of mind, but excluding the combinations of ab- stract thought. It admits a comparison of the human mind with the mind of the lower animals, if any light can be so ob- tained. Other terms include too much or contain too little. " Mental Science," may include metaphysics and logic. "Science of Mind," includes only the intellect, and "science" is now very generally understood to mean physical and natural science only. " Mental Philosophy " properly means rational psychology, including the intellect alone, and has, moreover, the effect of placing this science among a large class of sub- jects to which the term philosophy is, in English, applied, such as Natural Philosophy, Philosophy of Literature, Philosophy of Government, of Education, even of Cookery.

3. It corresponds with many other names of sciences in

12 THE INTELLECT.

English; Geology, Theology, Physiology, Philology, etc., and like them, forms an adjective in cal and an adverb in cally.

Human psychology is the science of the mind of man. The description of the manifestations of mind in the lower animals would enlarge the subject too much, and, though great expec- tations were at one time indulged of the enlarged and accurate knowledge of the human mind to be gained by the methods of physiology and biology, very small results can, as yet, be pointed out, and comparative psychology is still a somewhat unfruitful science. The present subject, therefore, is the intellect of man, explanations or arguments derived from comparison with the mind of brutes being, however, not at all excluded.

The usual division of the powers, or faculties, or functions, of the mind is into three great classes or kinds, called the in- tellect, the sensibilities, and the will. The first great division, the intellect, which forms our present subject, is further divided into three, the presentative, representative, and reasoning powers, or faculties.

The term faculty does not denote or imply an organ or separate part of the mind, but a mode of operation of the whole mind. It is a mistake to suppose that philosophers have generally committed the error of dividing the mind into sep- arate parts or organs. Scarcely a work on the subject can be found which does not contain a caution as to the real import of the word faculty. Nor is it meant or implied that the mind can- not act in more than one way at the same time. We can think, feel, and act, all at once. We can perceive and remem- ber a<~ the same moment. We can see and hear at the same time.

THK INTKLLBCT.

PART I.

PRESENTATIVE POWER.

The presentative power is the faculty of observation or ex- perience, including sensation, perception, and consciousness. When considered as it is by us, in immediate connection with all the elements involved in it, it is properly styled the faculty of cognition or knowledge. But we adopt this classification and division because it is very common and sufficiently con- venient, not because it is ideally perfect or without any objec- tions. In fact every act of perception involves the activity of each of the great divisions of the mental powers. The mind acting as intellect, knows some external object; the mind act- ing as sensibility, has feeling, experiences pleasure, pain, disgust, interest, or some other feeling, as excited by some relation of the object; the mind acting as will, chooses to what part of the object or to which of several objects the attention shall be directed, so that that particular object or part of an object is alone perceived.

But again, the intellect may be said to exert all its faculties in perception. Sensation must furnish the materials, but the very method of sensation, as we shall see, is discrimination,

14 THE INTELLECT.

distinguishing the different states of the sense-organs, and dis- crimination is usually classed as a function of the judgment, under the reasoning power. Perception is inseparable from consciousness, and its method again, is discrimination, dis- tinguishing between different objects, and between external objects and the ego. Moreover, perception is to such an ex- tent cultivated by experience that practically, as we shall see, we never perceive without former perceptions being supplied by the memory, while the imagination very often comes in to construct in full the object which is really perceived only in part. Thus we shall be forced, on any system, to repeat our- selves occasionally, and to treat separately things which never actually occur in separation.

Prof. A. Bain has attempted to escape these difficulties by starting from the first principles of knowledge, which are, he says, agreement and similarity; but he is forced to add a third thing, retentiveness or memory, which is not at all a principle parallel with the other two, but a faculty, taken from the old subdivision, which even he cannot wholly escape. And his arrangement leads him into numerous repetitions, several cross- divisions, and some contradictions. We judge it to be far better to adhere to the old method, classifying the powers of the mind rather than the results of their action or the ultimate elements of knowledge.

Under the head of presentative power we shall discuss sen- sation, perception, and the necessary or a priori elements in- volved in them, with several connected topics; giving then an historical sketch, with some critical discussions. We begin with sensation, as the lowest and simplest mental act.

SENSATION.

Sensation is "an impression made upon the mind through the medium of the organs of sense; feeling, awakened by ex- ternal objects or by some change in the internal state of the body." (The Webster Dictionary.) Every part of the body is supplied with nerves, which may be roughly compared to telegraphic wires, and which are capable of conveying im- pressions from their outer extremities to the brain. Whether they transmit their messages by chemical change in their sub- stance, or by some molecular disturbance similar to electrical action, is not definitely known. The description of these nerves, of the brain, and of the organs of sense, belongs to the science of physiology, and the explanation of their mechanical action belongs to physics, optics, acoustics, etc.

But a knowledge, however intimate, of the organs and their action, can throw no light on sensation proper. How it is that impulses on the nervous system, occasioned by external objects, are taken up by the mind and transformed into knowl- edge, is utterly inexplicable. Philosophers of all schools de- clare the problem insoluble. Even materialists admit that if we could trace all the movements of every molecule of the brain, we could still no more understand how a nerve-thrill occasions a state of consciousness than " the appearance of the Djin when Aladdin rubbed his lamp." (Huxley.) Herbert Spencer says, that, " A unit of feeling has nothing in common with a unit of motion." And Lotze says, " However we com- bine the motions of the nerve-atones, it never becomes self-

16 THE INTELLECT.

evident that the last will no longer be motion but must pass over into sensation." (Dictate, Psychologic, §3.)

Three things are necessary to a sensation, first an impres- sion on the extremity of a nerve, second the transmission of the impression in some way to the brain, third the action of the mind. The first is self-evident and is denied by no one. The second can be proved by experiments. When the affer- ent nerve of the leg is divided, or injured by disease, tickling the sole of the foot causes violent convulsions, but does not occasion sensation. The third is proved by every-day facts, as, for example, when one goes about looking for some article which is in his hand all the while, or for a pair of spectacles which are on the top of his head, or when the busy student, absorbed in his book, fails to hear the clock strike in the same room.

Yet it is not always easy to decide how far the power of the brain goes, and at what point the activity of the soul begins. Hence we use the word mind, which denotes the whole think- ing power and does not draw a sharp line between the body and the soul, postponing the discussion of the immateriality of the soul until we are prepared for the question by study of its phenomena.

A sensation proper is an act of the mind, not of the object. The activity of the object in making an impression on the organ of sense is not sensation, but only the occasion of it; and the activity of the organ and the nerve in receiving and transmitting the impression is not sensation, but only the con- dition of it. Nor is the impression itself sensation, as we have shown, but the condition of it.

The mind receiving these signals from the external world, interprets them by its own active power, and this is an act of sensation, and the result of it is a sensation. " Between the mind of man and the outer world are interposed the nerves of

SENSATION. 17

the human body, which enable the mind to interpret the im- pressions of that world into the facts of consciousness." (Tyn- dall, Fragments, 167.)

It is true the word sensation may be used in a wider sense, and is actually used by some writers to denote an impression which does not reach consciousness. But this use of the word is not sanctioned by the best authority, as is shown by the following quotations from writers of widely different schools. Ci Sensation proper is not purely a passive state, but implies a certain amount of mental activity." (Morell.) "Sensation properly expresses that change in the state of the mind which is produced by an impression upon an organ of sense." (Flem- ing.) " Sensation is the feeling which is the result of a single impression on any part of the sensitive organism." (Calder- wood.) " Some physiologists, it is true, have spoken of sen- sation without consciousness; but it seems very desirable, for the sake of clearness and accuracy, to limit the application of the word to the mental change; especially since the term ' im- pression ' serves to designate that change in the state of the nervous system which is its immediate antecedent." (Car- penter, Mental Physiology, 148.) "Where action is perfectly automatic, feeling does not exist." " As the psychical changes become too complicated to be perfectly automatic, they become incipiently sensational." (Herbert Spencer, Psychology, I, 478, 480.) "The sensation arises when the nervous process is transmitted through the nerves to the conscious center, often spoken of as the sensorium, the exact seat of which is still a matter of some debate." (Sully, Illusions, Chap. 3.)

In discussing the intelligence of the lower animals, however, it is not easy to decide at what precise point, as we descend the scale of being, the term sensation should be dropped. The oyster, for example, has organs called ocelli, or pigment spots, from forty to two hundred in number, and when a

2

1 8 THE INTELLECT.

shadow falls on these spots it closes its shell. This action cannot be supposed to show knowledge or to imply conscious- ness. "These ocelli, by their number, position, and office, indicate that they are the medium of an automatic impulse." (Bascom, Comparative Psychology, 138.) In certain annelida, according to Dr. Carpenter, eyes are found in the tail, which seem to direct the movements of that part alone.

Evolutionist writers regard such impressions as the rudi- ments of true sensation. Mr. Herbert Spencer describes mind in these low animal types as " a confused sentiency, formed of recurrent pulses of feeling." " At a stage above this, mind is probably present under the form of a few sensations, which, like those yielded by our own viscera, are simple, vague, and incoherent. And from this upwards the mental evolution exhibits a differentiation of these simple feelings into the more numerous kinds which the special senses yield." (Psychology, I, 189.)

The automatic actions of the lowest animals correspond to those feelings and actions in man which are called reflex, such as sneezing, coughing, breathing, the sucking of new-born infants, etc. In the higher animals, as the horse, the dog, we may suppose that sensations are like our own, for some sort of con- sciousness undoubtedly exists. But this point will be better noticed under the head of consciousness.

Sensation cannot occur without a physical organism. If the soul, or the immaterial part of the mind, could know objects directly, without any nerves or sense-organs, such knowing would be intuition, not sensation.

The nature of the activity of the mind in sensation is that it is a discriminating one, distinguishing like from unlike and the same from different. It is only change in the state of the organism which makes sensation possible. " Idem sentire ac non sentire ad idem reridunt" (Hobbes.) " Every mental

SENSATION. 19

experience is necessarily twofold. In every feeling there are two contrasting states; in every act of knowledge two things that are known." " This change of feeling is completely ex- pressed by the word discrimination, and is the basis of all our intelligence; as pleasure or pain it is nothing, but as the com- mencement of knowledge it is all-important." (Bain, The Senses and the Intellect, 8, 91.)

An impression on the organs which is not discriminated or attended to by the mind soon ceases to be a sensation. The roar of the cotton-mill is not heard by the weavers; the smell of the tannery does not offend the tanner. In such cases con- stant use probably produces a modification of the sensory ap- paratus, so that the receptive power is dulled. On the other hand, constant discriminative use cultivates the organs, so that a far smaller stimulus of the nerves suffices to occasion a sen- sation. A watch-maker or engraver has far more delicate sight and touch than other men. Blind persons cultivate touch and hearing to a wonderful degree.

How this discrimination occurs is unknown. "Search as we will the nature of waves of light, we never discover any reason why they are seen as light and not heard as sound, just as little why they are perceived as red, blue, or green." (Lotze.) Different nerves respond to different stimuli; the nerve of the ear is not affected by light waves, nor that of the eye by sound waves; nor can either bring into consciousness by any mistake, an impression appropriate to another, nor any hint of the proc- ess of sensation itself. A pain in the finger does not appear in consciousness as a decay of tissue, nor as an engorgement of the capillary vessels, nor as a dissociation of the atoms of the molecules of the tissues, nor as a vibration nor any action of the nerve, but as a pain. An impression of sound-waves upon the ear does not reach the mind as a picture of a bell, or any other sonorous object, nor as a vibration of the air, nor as

20 THE INTELLECT.

a process in the ear, nor as an activity of the nerve and brain, but as a sensation of sound. The result of the process of sensation is not an idea, nor an image, as taught by John Locke and many others, but a sensation.

We proceed to classify acts of sensation, or sensations.

SENSATIONS.

Sensations may be distinguished according to their nature in three different ways.

1. According to their peculiar nature with reference to the object which occasions them; as, sensations of light, sound, smell, pain, heat, etc. This peculiarity is usually called quality.

2. According to the strength of the occasioning impulse; as faint, moderate, intense. It is quite probable that the inten- sity of the sensation and the intensity of the exciting impulse do not vary in the same ratio. According to Weber, if the intensity of the sensation fncreases in an arithmetical ratio, that of the impulse must increase in a geometrical ratio. For example, a sound, to be twice as loud in sensation, must be occasioned by four times as violent an impulse.

3. According to the peculiar nature of the sensation as agreeable, disagreeable, or indifferent. This peculiarity is called by the Germans tone. Bain calls it quality.

Sensations may be again distinguished according to their con- tent, or significance, into internal and external, or bodily and mental.

i. Internal sensations, or feelings, relate to the condition and needs of the body, and may be divided into local and

SENSATIONS. 21

general. Local internal sensations involve only one or a few nerves, and are such as hunger, thirst, pain from a slight injury, tickling, sneezing, nausea, pricking caused by impeded circu- lation (foot-asleep), tingling caused by striking the nerve in the elbow (crazy-bone), etc. General internal sensations in- volve entire provinces of the nervous system, and are such as fatigue, exhilaration, shuddering, the depresssion of dyspepsia, spasm, cramp, the shock of a severe injury, etc.

2. External sensations relate to impressions received from the outside world, and may be sub-divided into general and special. Special external sensations are those which involve special external organs, provided with short nerves called sen- sorial nerves, all situated within the skull. They are sight, hearing, smell, and taste. General external sensations are those which depend upon nerves pervading the whole body, even the special sense-organs themselves. They are touch, heat and cold, motion or position of the muscles, pressure and re- sistance.

It will be seen that the old division of five senses is very defective. If we are to speak at all of the five senses, how- ever, we may divide them into two classes, direct and indirect; those which receive impressions by direct contact with the external object, touch, taste, and smell; and those which re- ceive impressions through a medium, hearing and sight.

The internal sensations are not of importance to our present purpose, and are sufficiently explained by physiology. We need only attend to those which, when interpreted and com- bined by the mind, convey to us impressions from the outside world.

Before we discuss the different senses in detail we need to define and explain the term perception, so that we can speak intelligently of the perceptions of each sense under the appro- priate head.

PERCEPTION.

Perception is the knowledge of the external world. Its method or process is the combination and interpretation of the sensations, by the activity of the mind itself. Sensations may exist without perception, but perception cannot exist with- out sensation.

" Perception is the power of the soul to localize its sensa- tions." (Lotze.)

" Perception is the act by which the mind refers sensations to their source." (Murphy.) " The mental recognition of the object is dependent on a higher process [than sensation], to which the name perception is now accorded." (Carpenter, Mental Physiology, 177.) "As the soul translates neural affections into subjective sensations, so the soul, in perception, translates the subjective sensation into objective cognition, a translation of a translation." (Cocker, Psychology, 92.) "In order that sensation may become perception there needs the spontaneous energy of the intellect, which distinguishes and recognizes the state of the sensibility, and ' streaming out through the instruments of sense,' refers that state to an ex- ternal excitant or source." (Martineau.) " Perception groups or organizes several sensations into one idea." (Maudsley, Physiology of Mind, 272.)

The term perception was formerly used in a far wider sense, including the whole of cognition, and is still used figuratively to denote the apprehension of abstract truth. In philosophy it was restricted by -Reid to apprehension through sense alone,

PERCEPTION. 23

and is now generally used in this sense. Hence the term sense-perception, used by some, does, not seem necessary, since all perception is understood to be sense-perception.

We are obliged in English to use the verb " to perceive" in a somewhat figurative meaning, because the verb "to sense" is not in good usage. Thus we say, " I perceived a smell of musk," where we ought to be able to say, " I sensed a smell of musk," or might correctly say, " I perceived musk by the smell." The verb "to sense," or some exact equivalent, is a term needed in English philosophy, in which confusion has sometimes arisen for the want of it.

The product of perception is called a percept. A sensation of light may be produced by pressing on the eyeball or by an electric current, but this is not perception, nor its product a percept. When, however, a distant light excites a sensation of light through the eye, the mind perceives the light, through the sensation of light, and forms a percept of a light. Then, if other percepts be combined with this one, until the mind perceives, for example, a red lantern of globular form, this process is still called perception, but the completed result of the combination is called an object, or mental object. If the eye be color-blind, the knowledge derived from these sensa- tions may be defective; if the mind be inattentive, or under the influence of association, or prejudice, or excitement, the data of the senses may be misinterpreted, and false results be reached. A large dose of the drug santonine makes all objects appear yellow.

Original or natural perception is the use of a single sense, without aid from experience or the assistance of the other senses. Cultivated or acquired perception is perception as corrected by experience and by the combination of different sensations. This is really a process of association. Thus, we have no natural perception of distance; but by walking or

24 THE INTELLECT.

reaching out we establish connections between sensations, by which we ever after seem to perceive distance. Compound perceptions are those which are occasioned by a number of impulses of the same kind; as color from many rays of light, form from many impressions of direction, a musical note from many vibrations of the atmosphere.

The complete presentation of an object is almost always ef- fected through many impressions of one sense or more than one. A star or a distant lamp is seen as a single point of light, and but one sensation is involved, unless it twinkles or changes its place so that we follow its motion with the eye. Ordinary objects, however, occasion more than one kind of sensations, or else a definite series of sensations of the same sense. These sensations, being of common origin, have co- herence among themselves in memory, so that if one, or some of them be experienced again or rec.illed in any way, the others are suggested, and the object, with all its sensible qualities, is perceived or remembered. For example; an orange occasions sensations of smell, color, form, touch, taste, and pressure. After these are firmly agglutinated by habit, any one of them, when repeated, may call up all the rest, and we may perceive the orange with all these qualities, or remember it as having them all, and not merely color, or odor, or form, alone.

The senses of sight and touch are by far the richest in this kind of associations, and especially in connection with each other. This is very important, as we shall see, for the knowl- edge of form, distance, and solidity, the acquired perceptions of sight. It was upon this that Berkeley founded his theory of vision.

The subject of association in general falls under the rep- resentative power, and the acquired perceptions of each sense are more naturally placed each under its own sense.

The universal or necessary elements involved in sensation

THE SENSES. 25

and perception, whether called a priori concepts, intuitive ideas, or by any other name, cannot be intelligently discussed until we have described the sensations of the different senses and the perceptions derived from them. It should be noticed that some writers use only the term sensation, including under sen- sation and the association of sensations all that we call per- ception. This is against philosophical usage, and is con- nected with their peculiar theories of the mind, to which we shall return further on.

THE SENSES.

We begin with the simplest and least complicated, and the one having, in itself considered, the least intellectual content.

SENSE OF SMELL.

The sense of smell is attached to a portion of the mucous membrane which lines the nostrils and nasal passages, called the pituitary membrane. Here is spread out a network of fine branching nerves which have the power of responding to certain chemical properties of some bodies. The excitation of the nerve is probably effected through the oxidation, that is, decomposition, of the molecules of the object, which must be presented in the form of a gas or fine powder, and carried by a current of air in respiration. Solid bodies in a state of fine powder are usually, however, so irritating as to cause sneezing and interfere with the normal action of the sensorial nerve. Gases may also be irritating in the same way, as ammonia. Some refer this irritation to the sense of touch, (Bain), but it is more probably to be referred to an over-

26 THE INTELLECT.

stimulation of those particular nerves which are adapted to transmit impulses due to chemical qualities.

A gas or vapor may be exceedingly diffuse and yet produce a strong odor. A very small amount of matter from a volatile substance may give rise to sensation. It is said that a grain of musk will emit a strong odor for years without any perceptible diminution in weight. According to the experiments of Pick a two-millionth of a milligram is sufficient to excite a sensation of smell.

Sensations of smell require a longer time than any other for discriminative attention. When we wish to distinguish a faint odor or a new one, we " take a good sniff." Yet the organ soon becomes weaned and ceases to respond, if the same stimulus is long continued. A constant odor is not perceived. The tanner does not smell his tannery. Students in a close lecture room do not perceive the foulness of the air; but if one goes out for a moment into fresh air and then returns, he finds it overpowering. This shows also the necessity of con- trast, and goes to establish what we have said of discrimina- tion as the basis of all sensation. Smells can only be de- scribed by reference to our previous experience. The terms, pungent, nauseating, sweet, acrid, ethereal, fragrant, applied to smells, have no meaning except through experience. The same is plainly true of those which consist in comparisons, as, like a rose, like musk, etc.

In general, substances which are useful for food and drink have agreeable smells, while those which are injurious have disagreeable ones. Hence this sense is far more acute in the lower animals than in man. The dog, however, though his smell seems miraculously acute, does not seem to distinguish smells, or even tastes, as disagreeable and agreeable.

Some smells cause faintness in sensitive persons, and the sweetest perfume becomes sickening if too often repeated. " Non bene olet qui semper bene olet" (Martial.)

SENSE OF TASTE. 27

The perceptions of this sense are entirely acquired. The mind knows sensations of smell only as in the nose, and re- ceives through them no knowledge whatever of the external world. Possibly from a number and variety of simple smells constantly changing, we might conclude, even if we had no other sense, that they had an external cause; but that would be inference, not perception. We refer smells to objects be- cause we are familiar with objects through the other senses. Smell itself can never inform us of the existence of anything but our own organism, as affected in some unknown way.

SENSE OF TASTE.

The sense of taste is attached to the upper surface of the tongue, the palate, and perhaps part of the pharynx. As these parts, especially the tip of the tongue, are capable of delicate sensations of touch also, it is almost impossible to separate these from sensations of taste. This probably can be done only in one case, that of a strong odor admitted to the mouth, which gives a sensation of taste in the back part of the mouth, where the current of air converges, with no sensation of touch.

The mucous membrane of these parts is studded with little papillae, thick-set at the tip of the tongue, which are sup- plied with nerves having the capacity of being excited by cer- tain chemical qualities of some bodies, when these are in a liquid state or dissolved in a liquid. No solid body can be tasted unless it is soluble in the saliva, and no substance can be tasted unless it is capable of passing through the mucous membrane of the papillae. The researches of Graham on dialysis, taken in connection with his remarkable investiga- tions on that condition of bodies called the colloid state, are of interest here. They go to show that nearly all bodies that can be tasted belong to the crystalloid class, not the colloid class. Now bodies of the colloid class do not penetrate one another

28 THE INTELLECT.

freely, and animal membranes belong to this class. Hence starch, gum, albumen, gelatine, etc., have no real taste of their own, while crystalloid bodies, or those flavored with a crystalloid principle, are capable of exciting strong taste-sensations. (Bain, The Senses and the Intellect, 141.)

The excitation of the nerves of taste is probably effected through oxydation, that is, decomposition of molecules of the body tasted.

The number of adjectives that can be applied to tastes is larger than in the case of smells; tastes are more describable. Yet usually these descriptions amount to little more than com- parison with sensations previously experienced.

The amount of matter required to occasion a sensation of taste is in some cases very small, yet far less small than occa- sions a sensation of smell. Valentin says that a fiftieth of a milligram of quinine is the least that can be tasted. The in- tensity of the taste depends not only on the nature of the object tasted, but also in part on the amount of matter brought in contact with the organ, and, partly, on contrast; and a suffi- cient time must be allowed for solution of a solid body in the saliva, in order that the sensation may accumulate its force.

It is held by some authorities that there are three kinds of papillae, the real organs of taste, one for bitters, one for salts and one for acids. In general, those substances which are useful have pleasant tastes, while those which are injurious are disagreeable. The perceptions of taste, like those of smell, are all acquired. Sensations of taste tell us only of an exci- tation of the organ, nothing of the external world. Neither sense gives any information concerning the chemical proper- ties of bodies. After those properties have been learned by us in other ways and associated with certain tastes and smells, the taste or smell will recall that knowledge. It does not originate any such knowledge. "Sensations of taste and chemical properties are heterogeneous in nature." (Lotze.)

SENSE OF' TASTE. 29

The impossibility of separating sensations of taste entirely from those of touch, and the extreme delicacy of the sense of touch in the tip of the tongue, with the great mobility of the tongue, give an obstinate impression that we know the external world through taste. But a little reflection upon these facts will enable us to separate them in thought, and compel us to admit that taste is as entirely subjective as smell.

In the case of these two senses, smell and taste, the object in perception is not, strictly speaking, the same as that which excites the nerves by a peculiar impulse. What we actually smell and taste is small particles of the object, detached or volatilized, or dissolved in the saliva. What we perceive, by the aid of association and combination with the other senses, is, not these particles, but the object from which they come. We know nothing about the detached particles until science reveals them to us. When we smell an orange we have a sen- sation of a peculiar smell, occasioned by certain volatile parti- cles of matter; but, aided by previous experience or by the other senses, we know this smell to be the perfume of an orange; and this is acquired perception. What we perceive is the orange. The formation of these acquired perceptions is vastly assisted by the inseparable connection between taste and touch.

These two senses, taste and smell, are the least intellectual of all the external senses. Taste is usually considered the least intellectual of all, that is, when taken by itself. " We are inclined to think that what are called the ignoble senses are wholly impercipient and would never, by the mere suc- cession of feelings, waken into consciousness the distinction between subject and object, or reveal their own organic seat." (Martineau.)

30 THE INTELLECT.

SENSE OF HEARING.

The organ of hearing is the external ear, with the exceed- ingly complex apparatus connected with it, the description of which belongs to physiology.

Sound is due to waves of alternate condensation and rare- faction in the atmosphere, caused by the vibration of sonorous bodies, the further discussion of which belongs to physics. The waves of air affect the auditory nerve by causing com- pression of its filaments, after being transmitted through the internal parts of the organ.

The most important distinctions in sensations of sound are intensity, pitch, and quality, or timbre. Sounds differ in in- tensity or loudness according to the amplitude of the vibra- tions of the sounding body, and consequent amplitude of the atmospheric waves. They differ in pitch according to the rapidity of those vibrations, rapid vibration being known in sensation as a high sound, and slow vibration as a low sound. Sounds are inaudible if their pitch is either too high or too low, and the range of audibility is said to be about ten octaves, or from twenty vibrations in a second to 38,000. The squeal of a bat is audible to some persons and not to others. The low- est notes of a pipe-organ are heard by some persons as separate beats or pulses of sound, not as musical notes, showing that noise is audible at a lower pitch than musical sounds.

Noise and music differ as follows; a musical sound is caused by regular and continuous vibrations, and is comparatively rich in overtones; a noise is due to irregular and discontinu- ous vibrations, comparatively without overtones. Hence the human voice is between the two, and easily passes into music. When the articulation is a little drawled we call it sing-song; when the sounds are dwelt upon and prolonged with regularity, it is called singing, or music.

SENSE OF HEARING. 31

The differences of quality between different musical instru- ments or different voices are due chiefly to the varying richness of the overtones, and Helmholtz has shown that the vowel- sounds of language differ in the same way, in their overtones. Pure tones, without overtones, can hardly be produced, and are of insipid quality. Hence every single musical tone is in reality a complex harmony, and its richness depends upon the degree of its complexity. (On the overtones, etc., see Tyn- dall, On Sound )

How different sounds affect the auditory nerves in different ways is unknown. Some conjecture that there is a different filament corresponding to each audib'e pitch, and thus the ear is a kind of key-board, and each of the overtones is separately heard and combined with the others in a kind of harmony. Others think that sounds differ in pitch because the elements of sensation differ in length. (Taine.) But this is only a re- statement of the problem.

Sensations of sound do not, in primary, natural sensation, give any knowledge of anything outside the organ. It is only by combination with other senses, by cultivation, and by asso- ciation, that sounds come to suggest to us the object by which they are caused, with its various relations. If a sound is fa- miliar, we can tell something of its distance by its loudness or faintness. If it is entirely unknown, we cannot judge of it at all.

The directions of sounds can be perceived to some extent through variations of intensity in the two ears, especially on revolving the head; if it is loudest when the ear is turned in a certain direction, we judge its source to be in that direction. In a dense fog the sound of the steam-whistle or fog-horn seems to come from the point whence we are expecting it to come, whatever that may be. But if on going in a certain direction, the sound increases in loudness, we judge its source

32 THE INTELLECT.

to lie in that direction. The judgment of direction is at best, however, easily mistaken. This is the reason why ventrilo- quists so easily deceive us by directing our attention and ex- pectation in certain directions. It also explains why so many accidents occur in crowded channels in foggy weather, in spite of the greatest caution.

The discriminating power is capable of great cultivation, both with reference to musical sounds and articulate language, and even noises. The mind receives a vast number and variety of sensations through the ear.

The sounds of articulate language are only arbitrary sym- bols, whose meaning is laboriously learned by the mind. If the attention is directed strongly on the sounds, as in listening to a foreigner or a person with an unfamiliar brogue, we often miss the meaning and have to ask for a repetition. When we pay strict attention to the meaning we scarcely notice the in- dividual sensations of sound.

Sensations of sound may be excited abnormally; certain drugs cause roarings in the ears; we seem to hear sounds in dreams.

It is affirmed by some that the mind perceives the external world directly through the sense of hearing. The following considerations will probably suffice to prove the negative.

(i) The organ of sense does not in hearing, as in touch, come into direct contact with the object, but a medium, the air, must intervene and convey the vibration to the organ, a kind of instrument for adapting these vibrations to the sensory nerves. Yet there is no apparatus, as in sight and touch, for following the outline of an object and thus gaining percep- tion of form and solidity. (2) Moreover, if there were such an apparatus, its action would plainly not give pure percep- tions through sound, but acquired perceptions through the muscular sense of the movements and the different

SENSE OF HEARING. 33

positions of the organ, cultivated by memory, experience, and association. Indeed we can to a certain extent, as has been said, vary the sensations of sound by moving the head and body and thus judge of the source of sound. But this is not an original or natural, but an acquired perception.

"That knowledge of this kind is founded on experience only is obvious from the fact that when the usual or the as- sumed conditions or occasions of our knowledge are changed, we make mistakes in respect to the place, direction, and dis- tance of a sound, and that mistakes in respect to these lead to error in regard to the object which occasions it. ... The humming of a mosquito may be mistaken for a distant cry of alarm or the sound of a trumpet. In such cases the sound must first be removed by our mistaken judgment to a greater distance, in order that it may be ascribed to a false oc- casion." (Porter, Human Intellect, 160.) " The knowledge of distance and direction of sounds is in reality an association between sounds and movements or muscular ideas." (Bain, The Senses and the Intellect, 362.)

(3) Again, the sense of hearing cannot convey to us any knowledge of the external world under those modes which are called primary qualities of matter, and are held to be insepa- rable from the very being of matter, -extension, weight, etc. It is true that in order to produce a sound a body must have extension, hardness, weight, all the necessary qualities of mat- ter; but when we say that a sound which we have heard must have proceeded from a body having these qualities, that is in- ference, not direct perception.

SENSE OF SIGHT.

The eye is a camera obscnra, provided with six muscles, by which it is rotated in all directions. It is furnished with a movable curtain in front, the eyelid, to exclude the light and ward off danger. It has an adjustable aperture for the ad-

34 THE INTELLECT.

mission of light, the pupil, and a double-convex lens, of ad- justable convexity. It is provided with a receiving curtain, the retina, on which an inverted image of the object is de- picted, and which is a very complex structure, containing the terminations of a vast number of nerve-fibres, which convey impressions to the brain.

The retina of the human eye has a small depressed spot which is more thickly set with nerve-terminations than the rest of the surface. Distinct vision of very small objects re- quires a discriminative power which is confined to this spot, but the retina is capable of receiving impressions of light, color, and direction, throughout a considerable segment of a sphere. Sixty degrees from the sensitive spot discriminative power is said to be one hundred and fifty times less than in that spot; that is, a body, in order to make a distinct impres- sion on that part of the retina must be one hundred and fifty times larger than to affect the sensitive spot. Yet a fainter light can be detected by the outside portions of the retina than by the central portion. Fixed stars which cannot be seen directly in front can sometimes be seen by turning the head a little to one side.

The sensitive spot of the retina, being necessary for minute and accurate vision, is evidently of vast importance for the in- tellectual culture and progress of the human race. (Le Conte, Sight.) Nearly all the rotation of the eyeballs, so conspicuous in man, is for the purpose of bringing this sensi- tive spot into range with some definite object, for accurate and careful vision.

In most of the lower animals this spot is wanting. We may hence suppose that they receive equally clear impressions on a far larger part of the retina than men, that they use far less rotation of the eyeball, and that they are capable of far less discrimination of minute objects. All of these are confirmed

SENSE OF SIGHT. 35

by observation. A cat can catch sight of a rat with extreme quickness, and follow its motions with wonderful closeness, since no motion of the eyeball need intervene to direct her movements, at least for moderate distances. But undoubtedly she could not see to split one of the hairs on the mouse's back, as many a man could do. A skittish horse seems to see objects in all directions, which his rider does not see, but as the horse does not see them clearly enough to recognize them, he is afraid of them. Such an animal always goes more steadily in a dark night.

There is a limit to minuteness of vision, depending on the fineness of the structure of the retina. According to Weber and Volkmann two bright lines must be separated by from one six-thousandth to one twelve -thousandth of an inch, in order to produce a double sensation. That is, if nearer together than this, they will be seen as one line.

The organ of sight, like that of hearing, cannot come into contact directly with an object, but requires an intervening medium to convey the particular vibrations which occasion the sensation. This medium is a supposed elastic, imponderable fluid, the ether, whose vibrations are far more rapid, and are propagated at a far higher rate of speed than any others known to us, and striking upon the terminations of nerve- fibres at the back of the eye, occasion sensations of sight.

Difference in color is due to difference in length of the light- waves, since all travel at the same speed. The vibrations which occasion the sensation of red color are the shortest and most rapid. Plow different rates of vibration occasion differ- ent sensations of color cannot be said to be well understood. The best conjecture is that there is a different kind of nerve- terminations for each of the primary colors, scattered all over the retina, by combination of which all sensations of color are formed. But microscopic examination discloses only two

36 THE INTELLECT.

kinds of minute bodies making up the sensitive coat of the retina, while the primary colors are ordinarily supposed to be three in number. Recent investigations, however, tend to show that there are four primary colors, in two couples, each of two complementary colors. Each of the colors of a pair is supposed to cause an opposite action in the same sensitive body of the retina, thus reducing the kinds of sensitive bodies required to two, which corresponds with the theory given above, which is known as the view of Hering.

According to Le Conte, the phenomena of color-blindness confirm this view. A person who is genuinely color-blind (not merely indiscriminative) is deficient in the red-green couple, while the yellow-blue couple is unimpaired. (Sight, 62.) The phenomena of subjective complementary colors also favor this view. If you look intently at a surface of bright red, then at a white surface, the latter seems to have a greenish tint.

Other colors pair themselves also, in such a way as to favor the theory of two contrary pairs of colors, and two kinds of sensitive bodies in the retina. Possibly also what are called negative images may help support this view. If you look out of a window, in the sunlight, and then shut your eyes, you seem to see the window still, with light and shade reversed; the sash appears brilliant, and the panes of glass appear dark. White and black may be opposites in their retinal effect, in the same way as red and green. The details of these inquiries belong to optics and physiology; we are concerned with them now only in their relation to the mind.

This theory only shov/s, however, how the ether-vibrations may excite corresponding vibrations in the brain, and does not at all touch the mystery of how the sensation is produced; indeed the process in the brain is probably still more compli- cated, for the ether- waves do not seem to cause nerve- vibra-

SENSE OF SIGHT. 37

tions directly, but to cause a chemical change in the retinal coating, which excites in turn the sensory nerve to its own peculiar form of action. It is quite possible, however, that the action in the nerve itself is a chemical action or change.

The only sensations directly occasioned by the action of light on the retina are those of light and color, including the so-called colors of white and black. It is evident that this class of sensations can be occasioned by objects having no apparent size. A fixed star has no disc; and a light may be seen as red, white, or green, and yet be so distant as to be a mere point in the field of view. In such a case there is a sen- sation of direction involved, which is entirely separate from the sensation of light or color, and which is different for each part of the field of vision, because rays of light from each part fall on a particular part of the retina. There is also an automatic tendency of the eye to revolve, in such a case, un- til the sensitive spot is brought into line with the object, and it is -from this, as we shall see, that our knowledge of direc- tion, and hence of form, is chiefly derived.

Such a sensation does not give any knowledge of the ex- ternal world; it might be merely a subjective sensation. We know that subjective sensations of light can be occasioned by pressure on the eyeball, by a blow on the head, or by a cur- rent of electricity, and that these have direction. When you shut your eyes and press a finger on the side of one eyeball, the resulting sensation of light appears to affect the opposite side of the retina, and a constant relation may be traced be- tween the directions of the two.

Now suppose the object to be a colored surface, and we have a plurality of indications of direction at the same time. If the object fills the whole field of vision, we have all the possible points of direction at once, and this gives us a per- ception of color without limits; for in such a case a limit of

38 THE INTELLECT.

direction could only be found by turning the head or rotating the eyeball, which is not the present supposition. It is a mat- ter of dispute whether in such a case there would be any per- ception of colored extension external to us.

We hold that there is no such perception until voluntary motion of the receiving organ is added to mere receptive sensation, and that this is proved by the experience of persons born with cataract of both eyes and afterward cured. Such persons, those of them at least whose blindness had been most complete, on looking , out of a window, for instance, for the first time, could see nothing but blotches of color, which seemed to be in contact with their eyes. The point, however, is not one of importance, for the following reason. Even though we do have a percep- tion of something outside of us, it is not knowledge of a defi- nite thing, not any true knowledge of the external world as it really is, for its real existence is definitely extended in space of three dimensions.

But suppose the field of vision to be divided between two colors. There would then be discriminative sensations of color, and the points of direction would give us a knowledge of whether each was on the right or left, above or below. But still the sensations arising would be mere " blotches of color in contact with the eye." Indeed, this is exactly the experi- ence of the blind-born persons referred to; they did not per- ceive the boundary lines between the colors, as extended and external, any more than the blotches of color themselves; we have seen that sensations of direction may be subjective, as well as those of light.

Take now the case of a colored surface of definite extent; the directions of the angles or of many points in the boundary line, give us the perception of form or of extended figure. But this perception is obtained through the muscular sensation of the rotation of the eyeball. By this voluntary motion of

SENSE OF SIGHT, 39

the organ, making the circuit of the object, especially going around . it in reverse order, and leaping, or rather measuring, across from one point to another, we gain a definite knowledge of an extended reality outside of us, real as meeting our vol- untary activity, and remaining while we study it. The fact also that impressions on the retina are not strictly instantane- ous, but have a duration of about one-eighth of a second, is of assistance in enabling us to perceive the whole of a line, or more than one angle, at a time; since the impression of one part remains until the other is reached. (Bain, The Senses and the Intellect, 236.)

Without this muscular feeling of voluntary activity, in the rotation of the eyes, or something equivalent, such as move- ments of the head and body, we cannot obtain through vision any true knowledge of the external world. This point is sometimes disputed; but, even if we yield it, and admit that the external world would be perceived in motionless vision, the fact remains, that it is not the external world in its full reality, but only colored surface, which is perceived, or ex- istence in space of two dimensions, not of three. The fol- lowing considerations, however, are probably sufficient to es- tablish our view, that form is not perceived through simple sensations of light and color.

i. What is difference of direction? When the extreme points of an object send to the eye rays of light which differ in direction by a certain amount, what relation does that ex- press ? Merely that the eye would have to be rotated through that number of degrees to bring both successively to the same spot of the retina. There is a natural tendency to direct the sensitive spot of the retina to the first point, and then to the one which is to be compared with it, of course by rotating the eyeball. This rotation, even when not actually performed, seems to be the measure of difference of direction, and so of size, and hence of figure.

40 THE INTELLECT.

2. Although the outside of the retina is very sensitive to light, so that we can see a faint star best by turning the head to one side, yet the accurate discrimination of form is .confined to a small area, and is vastly more perfect in the sensitive spot; so that for clear, distinct vision the sensitive spot must be turned successively toward all the parts of an object, or else the object must be small enough for its image to fall entirely within that spot.

3. In the case of small objects, all the rays of which fall upon the sensitive spot at once, we may often by close atten- tion, detect a motion of the eye around or across the object, where it has been unsuspected before. It is quite probable that when we see a small object for the first time, as in learn- ing the alphabet, we study it, feel around it with the eye, a process which is unnecessary afterwards, when it has become thoroughly known.

"Our notions of form are manifestly obtained by working on the large scale, or by the survey of objects of such mag- nitude as to demand the sweep of the eye in order to compre- hend them. We lay the foundations of our knowledge of vis- ible outline in circumstances where the eye must be active and must mix its own activity with the retinal feelings. The visual idea of a circle is first gained by moving the eye around some circular object of considerable size. Having done this we transfer the fact of motion to similar circles. So that when we look at a little round body we are already pre-occupied with the double nature of visible form, and are not in a posi- tion to say how we should regard it if that were our first ex- perience of a circle." (Bain, The Senses etc., 373.) Chil- dren learning their letters are always taught with large letters. In rapid reading it is certain that we do not wait for a complete impression or image of each letter.

4. Nearly all modern authority is on this side of the ques-

SENSE OF SIGHT. 41

tion. We have already quoted Professor Bain. Many writers deny that we perceive the external world at all through the senses, but declare that our knowledge of it is entirely a mat- ter of inference. (Dr. T. Brown.) Others hold that it is only through the sensation of resistance to muscular exertion that we gain this knowledge. (Pres. Mark Hopkins.) But we hold that when a visible surface has an outline which we follow by muscular movements of the eye, and then follow in reverse order, while the object remains the same, it quite as really resists our activity, and is quite as really demonstrated to be real being thereby, as though we took it in our hands and found all its angles and edges with our fingers. Of course, however, vision gives us in this way but two dimensions of space, not solid matter in its full reality.

The following observations upon persons cured of con- genital cataract of both eyes, are of general interest and not without bearing upon this question also, as showing that these patients can at first distinguish nothing but color and direc- tion. In the celebrated case, among the earliest recorded, of a boy twelve years of age, couched by Cheselden, the patient, being taken to a window and told to look out, saw nothing but great blotches of color, which seemed to be in contact with his eyes. This apparent contact with the eyes, common in such cases, is probably due to the habit of perceiving by touch, that is, bodily contact, necessarily formed by blind per- sons. (Taine, On Intelligence, 306.)

Caspar Hausar, who was kept prisoner in a dark room until his seventeenth year, afterwards said that when he was liber- ated, on looking out of a window " it seemed to him as if there were a shutter quite close to his eyes, covered with con- fused colors of all kinds, in which he could recognize or dis- tinguish nothing singly." (Taine, op. cit. 308.)

Wardrop's patient, a lady of forty-five, recognized the direc-

42 THE INTELLECT.

tion of a passing carriage, and asked what that large dark ob- ject was. Cheselden's patient was unable for some time to distinguish the cat -from the dog, until one day taking her up he felt her all over, saying, " so puss, I shall know you another time." Home's second patient, being shown a square card could not at first distinguish it from a circle; but after studying it for some time, not being allowed to touch it, said he had found a corner, and then readily found the other corners. In a case witnessed by Dr. Carpenter, the patient, a boy of nine years, could recognize the direction of a lighted candle at once.

It should be noticed that most sufferers from cataract are not entirely deprived of sensations of light, but can dis- tinguish day from night, or even a window from a blank wall. The eye is perfect but the light cannot reach it, except very faintly. This limited sensitivity to light strongly resembles that of the lowest animals which have any such capacity. We have seen that the oyster shuts its shell when a shadow falls upon its ocelli. "The Hydra habitually shuns the light, chooses the dark side of the vessel in which it is placed." " The rudimentary eye, consisting, as in a Planaria, of some pigment grains, may be considered as simply a part of the sur- face more irritable by light than the rest. Some idea of the impression it is fitted to receive may be formed by turning our closed eyes toward the light, and passing the hand backwards and forwards before them." (Herbert Spencer, Psychology,

I, 3IO> SM.)

Why are not objects seen inverted, since the image on the retina is inverted ? The inversion of the image is a conse- quence of the mechanical structure of the eye. The light from the upper part of the object must fall on the lower part of the retina, because the center about which the eyeball re- volves lies between the pupil and the retina. As the object

SENSE OF SIGHT. 43

goes up the image goes down. The rays of light necessarily cross each other in the eye. " It is therefore a prejudice to hold that vision by an inverted image is a mystery, while erect vision would be natural. Like every geometrical property of space, this is entirely lost in the transfer to consciousness." (Lotze, Dictate, Psychologic, §36.)

The perception of direction is an interpretation of signs by the mind; direction is a relation, not a concrete thing like light, or like a stick which can be touched, and it is a combi- nation of directions which gives us perception of form. To see the upper part of an object the eye has to be turned up- ward, which gives us an impression of height, or of being above, although the image of this part of the object goes to the lower part of the retina. The mind does not see the im- age on the retina, it sees the distant object by means of it, and by means of the muscular sensations of moving the eyeball from one position to another, which sensations are just as real as the image on the retina. The image on the retina is only known through the sciences of physiology and optics, not at all by sensation.

The rays of light coming from various directions excite sensations which are interpreted as above or below according as we would have to move the eye up or down to direct the axis of the eye upon the object, to " bring it to bear " upon the object. An absolute standard of direction is afforded us by the action of gravity; the direction in which things fall is called "down," and the opposite is called "up."

We have said that there is some dispute as to whether vision alone can give the perception of an external world as ex- tended in two dimensions. As to the third dimension, in- volved in distance and solidity, there is practically no dispute. These are acquired perceptions, in which, however, the prin- ciple of binocular vision is of great importance, but much is

44 THE INTELLECT.

also due to associations of the sense of touch, and accu- mulated experience.

The eye as an optical instrument is capable of being ad- justed, to a certain extent, for various distances. For very near objects a change in the shape of the lens, which becomes more convex to the extent of one forty-eighth of an inch, en- ables us to see minute objects more clearly, producing a some- what microscopic effect. This change produces a feeling of strain and fatigue, and is usually said to be voluntary. For objects somewhat further away there is a rotation of the eyes, converging their axes, thus increasing the visual angle, and giving us clearness and distance at once, enabling us to judge of the distance of objects whose size is known, or of the size of those whose distance is known. The full explanation of these mechanical adjustments belongs to the science of optics.

The perception of distance is entirely acquired. " The very meaning of distance is such as cannot be taken in by mere sight. The possibility of a certain amount of locomotion is implied in the very idea of distance. Distance cannot be per- ceived by the eye, because the idea of distance by its very nature implies feelings and measurements out of the eye and located in the other active organs, the locomotive and other mov- ing members." (Bain, The Senses and the Intellect, 366.)

A multitude of observations confirm this theory of the per- ception of distance. An infant reaches out its hands, evi- dently for objects at some distance, and only slowly learns what is and what is not within its reach. In the case of couching for cataract witnessed by Dr. Carpenter, already men- tioned, the patient, several days after the operation, being told to take hold of a watch, groped for it like an infant. War- drop's patient, after three months, recognized a grass-plot by its greenness, but could not judge of its distance, and put out her foot to see if it was close by. Yet this patient was forty- five years of age, and had never been quite blind.

SENSE OF SIGHT. 45

In all such recorded cases the judgment of distance has been slowly acquired, and the same process may be observed in children. When we look at an object and then reach out to it or walk to it, the real distance, as thus experimentally learned, becomes associated in the mind with the proper con- vergence of the axes of the eyes, with distinctness or vague- ness of outline, with brightness or dimness of color, and other signs of distance. A vast number of such experiences, con- tinued through years, cultivate the judgment of distance and make one skillful at estimating it.

But the errors into which we fall show that the whole is an acquired art. A landsman at sea cannot judge of distance because he is accustomed to rely on intervening objects. The stranger in Colorado judges mountains at a great distance to be hills near by, owing to the unaccustomed clearness of the atmosphere. The moon appears larger and nearer in the horizon than when in the zenith. Etc.

Some of the lower animals have a certain amount of in- stinctive judgment of distance which appears to be automatic. A chicken, for example, will dart at and pick up food when hardly out of his shell. But it should be noticed, what is generally overlooked, that this action of the chicken is not like what we call judgment of distance in a grown-up person.

The chicken's object is very near, and the only adjustment necessary to enable him to strike it is a convergence of the axes of the eyes. It is more like threading a needle than judging of a mountain. And this is about all the knowl- edge of distance which a chicken ever acquires. Even when mature, objects a quarter of a mile away are for him non- existent. The intellectual judgment and comparison of dis- tance is a different thing from the automatic convergence of the eyes at an object a few inches away, and even though the latter existed in human infants it would not prove the existence of the former. i

46 THE INTELLECT.

So far as distance, as an abstraction, comes under the idea of space, it will be discussed hereafter.

The perception of solidity is similar to that of distance, only the assisting sensations are those of touch. The signs of solidity, namely, shadow, foreshortening, and perspective, are a kind of language, which we learn and interpret. A sphere appears, to vision alone, just like a circle, but after handling and seeing spheres we come to join the shading with spherical solidity, and imagine that we see the latter directly.

The perception of solidity is also greatly assisted by what is called binocular vision. Since the two eyes are placed some three inches apart, each one receives, if the object is not too distant, an image of a slightly different portion of the object, and thus the combination of the two images gives aid to the perception of solidity. The stereoscope is an instrument de- vised by Wheatstone to take advantage of this principle. It is held by the best authorities, however, that the mode in which it operates is that one eye receives the principal impres- sion and the other supplies those additional particular sensa- tions which it has received more than or apart from the first. (Le Conte, Sight.) It is well known that nearly every person has one eye very much stronger than the other, and habitually uses that one, by itself, far more than he is aware of.

The theory that the perception of solidity is entirely intel- lectual is confirmed, as in the case of distance, by numerous observations and experiments. Cheselden's patient, " for some time after distinct vision had been attained, saw everything flat, as in a picture." (Carpenter, Mental Physiology, 188.) Wardrop's patient could distinguish an orange on the mantle- piece, but could form no notion of what it was. " It has long been known," says Carpenter, (op. cit. 195.) "that when a seal is looked at through a microscope, it will appear sometimes projecting like a cameo, sometimes excavated as an intaglio,"

SENSE OF SIGHT. 47

a phenomenon which does not occur with the binocular micro- scope.

Wheatstone has devised an instrument called the pseudo- scope, which effects a " conversion of relief," making, for ex- ample, the outside of a basin look like the inside. " But this ' conversion of relief/ is generally resisted, for a time at least, by the preconception of the actual form which is based on actual experience; and it only takes place immediately, in cases in which the converted form is as familiar to the mind as the actual form." Thus, looking at the inside of a mask with a pseudoscope, it at once appears to be the outside of a mask, especially if colored like the outside; but looking at the out- side of a mask a lengthened gaze is required to make it look like the inside. " In the case of the living human face, how- ever, it seems that no protraction of the pseudoscopic gaze is sufficient to bring about a ' conversion of relief,' " the associa- tions of so familiar an object being too strong to be overcome by optical expedients. (Carpenter, op. cit. 191.)

"The whole technical power of painting," says Ruskin, " depends on our recovery of what may be called the inno- cence of the eye; that is to say, of a sort of childish percep- tion of these flat stains of color merely as such, without con- sciousness of what they signify, as a blind man would see them if suddenly gifted with sight." (Elements of Drawing, Quoted in Porter, 155.)

This theory of the indirect perception of distince and solidity is a striking instance of progress in psychology. It was demonstrated by Berkeley in 1709 from theoretical con- siderations. The defective state of the sciences at that time, especially ignorance concerning the muscular sensations, made his argument less satisfactory and checked its reception. (Bain, Mental Science, 189.) In some points, too, his form of the theory has been abandoned; for example, he held tnat we have

48 THE INTELLECT.

no knowledge of extension through the eye; tliat the eye gives color only; that there is no necessary connection be- tween visible and tangible extension. None of these points are now held to be a part of the true theory.

This theory, although so contrary to all o.ur natural unre- flecting beliefs concerning vision, has made its way, in spite of all difficulties, because, like the undulatory theory of light, it explains every new case which arises and is confirmed by all new discoveries in the sciences of optics, physiology, and psychology, until it is now accepted by almost every person whose opinion is of any value. Some able men have recently opposed it, as Bailey and Abbot, but they have opposed the theory as Berkeley held it, not as improved by more recent writers in the light of modern science.

A question arises in connection with binocular vision, why do we not see double, since we use two eyes, which may, to a certain extent, act separately? The folio wing "considera- tions will probably remove the difficulty.

1. Form and distance being given by muscular sensations of the eyes, the same set of those sensations in either eye produces the same image, that is, locates the object in the same apparent place, and the two images correspond or are superimposed. If the ad- justment of these muscles be altered, by pressinga little on the side of one eye with the finger, or by a voluntary effort, we do see double. (Drbal, Empirische Psychologic, 138. Le Conte, Sight.)

2. We do not, as above said, have two entirely distinct images which are confounded or mixed or superimposed, but one principal image, supplemented in some particulars by another. If the two images were superimposed they would not correspond exactly, since they are not taken from the same point of view. The effect of binocular vision depends on this very fact, that the images are not exactly alike; that is,

SENSE OF TOUCH.

49

our vision of solid objects is not absolutely single, but is, to a certain extent, and in a certain sense, double, but is interpreted by the mind as single. (Bain, Mental Science, 192.)

3 The perception of distance and solidity is, as has been said, an intellectual phenomenon, an interpretation of signs. Hence the mind incorporates with the sensations involved, all the knowledge which it has previously gained in any way, and each perception of this kind is really the result of a long course of training. Hence, even if we do see double at first, the eyes and the mind may be adjusted to see single. This is proved by cases in which persons have been rendered cross- eyed by injury to the head. In such cases, if the divergence is not too great, the eyes are brought into harmony again by one or two years' practice, new associations of the muscular sensa- tions of sight being established in that time.

"It is no more necessary that the two eyes should give two separate and complete pictures to the mind, than that the two hands embracing the same ball should suggest two balls; or that the thumb and finger grasping a pen should suggest two pens." (Bain, The Senses and the Intellect, 302.)

SENSE OF TOUCH.

In one meaning of the term Sense of Touch, this sense is attached to the whole surface of the body, even to the special organs of sense. It has in fact been called "the general sense," and some writers have even attempted to show that the other senses are all developments and refinements of the sense of touch. (Herbert Spencer, Psychology, I, 400.) In the tips of the fingers and tongue the sense of touch has a remarkable development, and the nerves of touch are there so specially sensitive as to constitute them, it might almost be said, a special organ of sense.

In other words the entire skin, is capable of receiving im- 4

50 THE INTELLECT.

pressions of pressure, pain, and temperature, but the tips of the fingers and tongue are usually employed in voluntary seek- ing for information of the external world.

Some sensations which are probably occasioned through the same nerves with those of touch are not of importance for this part of psychology, and are better classed under organic sensations; they are sensations of heat and cold, pain and pleasure, tickling, etc.

Experiments have been made by Weber to determine the comparative discriminative power of touch in different parts of the body. The blunted points of a pair of compasses are placed at different distances apart on different parts of the body; when they are too close together they are perceived as one, not as two. The smallest distance at which they can be distinguished as two varies from one thirty-sixth of an inch at the tip of the tongue, to about one tenth at the tips of the fingers, about one fifth on the lips, and three inches on the back. It is probable that in order to produce a double sen- sation the points must be in areas supplied by different and distinct nerve-branches, and separated by at least one such area. Thus each such area would correspond to a separate organ of sense, supplied by a special nerve, branching to every part of the area; for there is no part of the skin where a pin- point can be set down without causing pain.

Under the perception of points should be classed percep- tions of roughness or smoothness. The face of a brush, for example, gives a plurality of points, and we can judge to some extent whether they are scattered or close.

Light pressure is usually classed under touch, but when pressure is heavier the muscular feeling of resistance becomes involved, and the two cannot be distinguished. By support- ing the hand, as on a table, muscular sensation can be elimi- nated as far as possible, and it is then found that the tips of

SENSE OF TOUCH. 51

the fingers can distinguish between twenty ounces and nine- teen and a half ounces.

By moving the hand along the surface or edge of an object, we get a perception of continuance of the sensation, com- bined with the muscular feeling of motion. This kind of per- ception is greatly assisted by the fact that we have two hands and several fingers, giving an effect somewhat like that of two eyes in binocular vision.

In this way we gain a knowledge of solidity, of the external world as having three dimensions, assisting the sense of sight and furnishing associations which go to form the acquired per- ceptions of sight. The similarity of compound touch to bi- nocular vision is curiously illustrated by an experiment resem- bling that in which the eyes are made to see double by a slight pressure on one of them. If a boy's marble be pressed by the forefinger and at the same time by the second finger, so crossed over as to bring the inside edges of both fingers against the marble, it will seem to be two separate marbles.

When our own body is the object of touch, the double sensations, active and passive, especially when combined with vision, give perceptions of the parts of the body as in a pe- culiarly close relation with the perceiving subject. In this way, and not by direct consciousness, we get a knowledge of the body as extended and having solidity, and come even to regard it as a part of the external world, distinct from the sub- ject or ego.

The sense of touch is caj able of very wonderful cultiva- tion, especially where exclusive attention is directed to it, as in the case of blind persons. " There is nothing essential to the highest intellectual processes of science and thought, that may not be attained in the absence of sight." (Bain.)

52 THE INTELLECT.

MUSCULAR SENSATION.

The muscles are all supplied with nerves of sensation as well as motion, and these convey a variety of sensations, some of which are organic, as fatigue, strain, pain, pleasure of mo- tion, passive feeling of support, cramp, etc., and are not of psychological importance.

The intellectual or discriminative sensations of muscle are of two kinds, that of resistance and that of motion or changed place. Those of the first kind are always combined with sensations of touch, since pressure cannot be brought to bear upon the muscles without first affecting the skin. In the case of resistance, as in supporting a weight in the unsupported hand, it is said that an ordinary person can distinguish be- tween thirty-nine and forty ounces. (Bain.) But the muscles soon become tired and then lose their discriminative sensi- tiveness, which is absorbed in the sensation of strain and pain- ful fatigue.

The sensation of resistance, as when we grasp anything firmly in the hand, gives vividness to our knowledge of exter- nal reality in connection with touch. Indeed, it is held by some that here alone do we get a knowledge of the external world as extended and really existing. (Hopkins, Outline Study of Man.)

We have already stated our own view, that we know real be- ing external to us whenever we exercise toward it a voluntary activity of the apparatus of perception, which we cannot do in taste, smell, hearing, or simple vision, but can do in com- pound vision, and still more perfectly in touch. Muscular sensations of motion and resistance imply, we hold, more than being and space, namely causation, a subject which will arise for discussion later on. Even Bain says, " the sense of re- sistance is primarily the feeling of expended energy." (The

MUSCULAR SENSATION. 53

Senses and the Intellect, 178.) "There is no feeling of our nature of more importance to us than that of resistance. Everything we touch, at the same time resists, and everything we hear, see, taste, or smell, suggests something that resists. It is through the medium of resistance that every act by which we subject to our use the objects and laws of nature is per- formed." (James Mill.)

In moving a limb, as in the sweep of the arm through space, we have a series of sensations corresponding to the motion, but we need the help of sight, in general, to make the muscu- lar combinations accurate. Extend the arms, then shut the eyes, and try to bring the two forefingers together; they will not, usually, meet exactly. Yet habitual actions can be per. formed with surprising accuracy even in the dark; fix your eye on the door knob in a familiar room, then let some one ex- tinguish the light, and try to walk to the door and touch the knob. Very often the knob is touched with perfect correct- ness. In throwing a missile the co-ordination of motions, guided by sight, but trained by previous experience, is wonder- fully accurate.

A curious combination of tactual and muscular sensations occurs when we take a stick in the hand and " feel for " some- thing with it, especially if sensations of sight be somehow eliminated. Besides the sensation of resistance directly given by the stick in the hand, we have the muscular sensations of movement, and also the resistance which the stick meets with at its other end and which is transmitted to the hand; we thus seem to feel the object directly.

Similarly in using tools, we seem to feel the tool, often, as a continuation of our muscular and sensitive system. The carpenter can tell by the feeling whether his plane is cutting well or ill, though the real variations of muscular sensation must be almost infinitesimal. Lotze has elaborated this subject,

54 THE INTELLECT.

attributing to this peculiar "projection of sensations" all skill in the use of instruments and hence all industrial progress. (Microkosmus II, 195 Drbal.)

A similar class of sensations is not uncommon. Thus, if a fly walks on the ends of our hair, when it is short, we seem to feel him at that place, not in the skin, where the nerves affected really are. Or, if something strikes one of our teeth, we seem to feel the blow in the enamel or bone, which has no nerves, not in the gum, where the nerves really are. A cat's whiskers seem to be capable of similar discrimination. The antennae of insects probably act in the same way. But this so-called " projection of sensation " seems to be an acquired perception, similar to the localization of sensation, which we shall soon refer to. It is probable that all precise localization is acquired, and if so, it cannot be much more difficult to lo- calize a sensation in the hair, or tht teeth, or the nails, or a stick held in the hand, than in the foot or the hand.

Muscular sensations have a tendency to become joined to- gether automatically in rythmical series, and the series goes on without any intervenation of the will, when once begun. One learning to play the piano strikes each key by a separate voli- tion, with full attention; but a skillful player, playing a familiar piece can do it without attention, and even talk about some- thing else all the while. So in learning to walk, the child has to give full attention to each step, and then often fails to get just the right muscular adjustment. Later in life the move- ments of walking may even go on automatically when the man, overcome with fatigue, has fallen asleep.

LOCALIZATION. 55

TOPICS CONNECTED WITH SENSATION AND PERCEPTION.

I. LOCALIZATION.

Many of our sensations are instantly referred by us to the part of the body in which the originating impulse was received. This is called localization of sensations. It does not always occur. When the attention is directed to the interpretation of the sensation, the localizing reference is absent. When we look at an object, we do not think of the eye, we are not con- scious of the eye at all. But if the light becomes so strong as to cause pain, the attention is drawn to the organ, and we perceive the eye as affected by the light. So in hearing, we do not think of the ear unless the sound is so loud or so harsh as to be very disagreeable, in which case we at once perceive the ear as affected. Sensations of touch, pressure, tempera- ture, and resistance, seem always to be accompanied by the localizing sensation.

Dr. Carpenter says it is doubtful whether the localization is " primary or secondary; a congenital intuition or an acquired instinct." (Mental Physiology, 149.) The weight of author- ity is in favor of calling it an entirely acquired perception. On this theory the child has to learn to know its own body and limbs, and to recognize the places of its various sensa- tions, and does this by the combined sensations of touch and sight, and especially that peculiar double sensation described above, in which the organism is both active and passive at the same time. In this way, it is said, we learn to know the body as in one sense belonging to the external world, and yet in most intimate connection with the soul. The following con- siderations are relied upon to establish this view.

i. Even adult persons often find the localizing power defi-

56 THE INTELLECT.

cient. One cannot always tell which of his teeth is aching, until, by applying the tongue, he " finds out " which one it is; that is, acquires the localizing perception.

2. Frequent mistakes are made in localizing sensations. We refer sensations to insensible parts, the hair, the teeth, even a stick, as described above. After the amputation of a limb the patient continues to have sensations of pain, tickling, pricking, etc., which he refers to the part which has been am- putated. In many cases these disappear after a few years, when new associations have been established. Organic feel- ings are often misleading as to the real seat of disease or in- jury. Disease of the heart causes pains in the arms. Acid in the stomach causes a pain over the eyes. The first warning of hip-disease is sometimes a pain in the knee.

3. Observations on infants are held to confirm this view. It is a long time before they can indicate the seat of a pain. In the pain of colic they draw up the feet in a peculiar manner, it is true, but this may be a spasm caused by the great inten- sity of the pain, not a sign of its location.

On the other side the following considerations may be men- tioned.

1. Many of those who hold localization to be entirely ac- quired are idealists, and hold that all sensations are subjective, and that the mind projects its own sensations into space, which is also its own creation. They are thus obliged to account for the localization of sensations in the same way. This meets to a great extent the argument from authority.

2. After amputation of a limb the patient has sensations apparently in the severed limb, in many cases through the rest of his life, though prolonged for many years. This is held to indicate an inherent, specific, capability in the nerve, as in the sensory nerve, to occasion only one sensation, no matter what the stimulus may be. Such a capability would give dim

LOCALIZATION. 57

and vague experiences at the beginning of life, when all the powers are undeveloped and uncertain, but would develop with the gradual perfection of the organism.

3. Localization certainly becomes automatic, and probably is so from the first, so far as it exists. According to Dr. Car- penter, also, it is a reflex activity.

4. The muscular sense seems to be in a certain way a local- izing sense in itself, and is possibly the basis on which com- plete localization is built up. It seems impossible to believe that the muscular sensations by which, for example, we know the movement and position of the arm, give us no knowledge in themselves, but only through association.

The true state of the case seems to us well expressed by Presi- dent Porter. " All sensations are attended with a more or less distinct and definite relation of place in the sensorium. This re- lation of place is at first very indefinitely apprehended; indeed, it may not be attended to at all; but there must be furnished, in the original experiences of the soul, the means of discerning such a relation, provided the attention is directed to the sen- sation." (Human Intellect, 130.) We conclude, then, that localization is a power which can be largely improved and de- veloped by experience and association, but becomes or is au- tomatic, and is founded in original endowment, the structure of the nervous system.

Some writers describe a kind of extension of localization, under the name of projection of sensations, affirming that when we look at an object we are only referring our subjective sensations to a certain point in space, and thus we construct the external world out of our inner consciousness. (Drbal, empirische Psychologic, 155.) This is true only in hallucina- tions and dreams. M. Taine, indeed, plainly asserts that all our knowledge is hallucination. But the difference between our ordinary life and a dream is plain to right-thinking men,

58 THE INTELLECT.

and is only lost sight of by those who have already adopted the presupposition of idealism. The only phenomena which can properly be called projection of sensations have been described above under the sense of touch.

II. ILLUSIONS AND HALLUCINATIONS.

Illusions are errors in the perception of real objects. The senses themselves, in their normal action, do not mistake, but the errors of illusion arise from a wrong interpretation by the mind, when some unaccustomed circumstance, altering the significance of the usual signs, has been overlooked. When a man seems ten feet high in a fog, it is because the dimness of outline due to the fog is associated in our minds with distance, and we judge him to be farther away than he really is.

When we direct our eyes upon a spot in the window, objects beyond seem double, but when we direct our attention to dis- tant objects, the spot on the window seems double; effects easily explained by the principle of binocular vision. When a voice, re-echoed from a building or a cliff, seems to proceed from thence, though the speaker is in the opposite direction, it is plain that the sound-waves, as they really reach us, are rightly judged to proceed from the direction of the echo. When we see the two rails of a railway track apparently com- ing together in the distance, it is because the real object of vision is the distance between the rails, and this object neces- sarily subtends a smaller angle as the distance increases. When a stick, obliquely inserted in the water, appears bent, it is be- cause the mind assumes the refraction of light to be unchanged in the new conditions. When the full moon looks larger near the horizon than in the zenith, it is because the number of intervening objects makes us judge it more remote than when no objects are between, and hence larger. When a stump seen in the twilight, seems to be a robber with a gun, it is be-

FEELING IN SENSATION. 59

cause the excited imagination is prepared to construct such an object, and the slight resemblances reported by vision are misinterpreted.

Hallucinations are subjective sensations, caused by abnormal action of the brain or mind. A blow on the head makes one see stars. Pressure on the eyeball causes a flash of light to appear. Electric currents stimulate several of the senses so as to cause false perceptions. Dreams will be spoken of under the head of Imagination. Visions, ghosts, and phantasms are not very uncommon. The case of Brutus is celebrated. Martin Luther is said to have seen the devil frequently. Pascal, having nearly fallen into the river, with nerves weakened by asceticism, saw a fiery gulf beside him, and could not get rid of it. Benvenuto Cellini, in a dark prison, thought himself visited by the holy virgin Mary.

Perhaps the most remarkable case is that of Nicolai, a book- seller of Berlin, who was visited by mary of these dream-peo- ple. The so-called dreams of opium, haschish, and other drugs, seem to the victim as real as actual events. The delu- sions of insane persons are fundamentally of the same charac- ter, and by constant repetition and brooding upon them be- come " fixed ideas," which dominate the patient's mental life, and impel to all sorts of extraordinary actions. It is well known that nervous children sometimes take images in the mind for percepcions. (Dr. Clark, Visions.)

III. FEELING IN SENSATION.

A curious question has been raised how far sensation is ac- companied by feeling. This question is somewhat complicated by the various meanings in which the words feeling, and to feel, are used in English, viz:

i. Feeling is used of the sense of touch; we feel of a thing, and say it feels soft, smooth, hard; or we feel it to be soft, rough, sticky, etc.

6o THE INTELLECT.

2. Feeling is used for the emotions, including pleasure, pain, disgust, interest, gratitude, and all the sentiments, or finer feel- ings.

3. For all the sensations and emotions together. " All sen- sations are feelings, but all feelings are not sensations. Sensa- tions are those feelings which arise immediately and solely from a state of the bodily organism." (Fleming, Vocabulary of Philosophy.)

4. Professor Bain uses feeling to include most of those sen- sations which we have called organic and muscular, and also the emotions proper. Thus he says, " Feeling includes all our pleasures and pains, and certain modes of excitement, or of consciousness simply, that are neutral or indifferent as regards pleasure and pain. The pleasures of warmth, food, music; the pains of fatigue, poverty, remorse; the excitement of hurry and surprise; the supporting of a light weight, the touch of a table, the sound of a dog barking in the distance, are feelings. The two leading divisions of the feelings are commonly given as sensations and emotions." (Mental Science, 2.)

Evidently he does not here intend to include the discrimina- tive feelings of the special senses. But the distinction is not an easy one to carry out. It obliges him to treat of feelings twice, in two connections, first among the sensations, and then after the intellect, as emotions. And he is not thoroughly con- sistent in applying the term. Thus, he speaks of muscular feelings, organic feelings, feelings of respiration, of heat and cold, hunger, nausea, and disgust, and yet calls many of them sensations.

5. To feel is used in the meaning of to believe. We say, " I feel it to be true," " I cannot help believing it, because I feel it is so." This is a popular, colloquial use.

Some authorities teach that every sensation is accompanied by feelings of pleasure or pain, or rather an agreeable or dis-

FEELING IN SENSATION. 61

agreeable feeling. (German lust and un lust.) According to Lotze, sensation and feeling, though different in nature are always conjoined, yet not derived from one another. The relation between simultaneous impressions or states acts as an impulse upon the soul, and arouses a new activity, the soul re" sponding in the shape of feeling. (Dictate, Psychologic §46.) Drbal, following Herbart, says that all feelings, including emo- tions, arise from the conflict and hindrance, or co-incidence and mutual strengthening (forderung) of ideas, but that weak or momentary relations of ideas do not produce feeling, and are not further noticed by us. (empirische Psychologic, 200.)

President Porter introduces the element of feeling into his very definition of sensation, which he calls "the subjective ex- perience which the soul, as animating an extended sensorium, has of its own states as pleasurable or painful." (The Human Intellect, 128.) He does not account for this combination, nor explain the origin of feeling in connection with sensation, nor do we understand that he makes any use of it. Writers of the sensational or of the Herbartian school can make great use of the principle, because they derive all the emotions from these simple feelings.

Lotze divides feelings into sensuous, esthetic, and moral. The first are such as the feelings of harmony or discord of sounds and colors, agreeable and disagreeable sensations of smell, taste, touch, the last rising at one extreme into pain; these are personal, as depending on each one's physical organism. The second are the pleasures and pains (rather displeasures) of taste, aroused by beauty and ugliness, etc., in which the per- sonal element is wanting, and which are universal in their application, since all men may derive pleasure from the same picture or statue. The third is moral approbation or disap- probation. Professor Bain, as we have seen, gives a similar extent to the term feeling.

62 THE INTELLECT.

But President Porter compares the pain of a cut or blow with the pain of the death of a friend, and says, " the one is ex- perienced by the soul as connected with an organism, while the other is felt in the soul without reference to the sensorium at all. We should prefer to say that the pain of a cut belongs to the body alone, as an organic sensation, while the pain caused by the death of a friend belongs to the mind, and can- not be derived from, related to, or classified with the other in any way. But, however stated, this correct doctrine removes the need of any mention of pleasure and pain as universal elements of sensation. It may be true that if we could ab- stract our attention sufficiently from the mental content of our sensations, we should find that they are all, or were originally, accompanied with feeling. The child learning to read may do so with pleasure or with pain and disgust. But the skillful reader has none of either feeling in consciousness; his atten- tion is entirely absorbed by the meaning of what he reads, and the higher feelings which it arouses in him. When we hear a piece of news or read it in the newspaper, the articulate sounds of the voice or the black characters on a white ground, are neither agreeable nor disagreeable in the sensations which they directly occasion, but only in the intellectual content of their meaning.

Sir W. Hamilton elaborated a theory that feeling and knowl- edge are in inverse ratio in every act of perception, or, as he phrased it, the more intense the sensation proper or subjective consciousness, the more indistinct the perception proper or objective consciousness. But he himself was obliged to re- strict this by saying " above a certain limit," for it is obvious, as we have seen, that some sensations have no content of feel- ing, and some never appear in consciousness at all, but excite automatic actions, if any, and hence have no mental content. It is disputed, however, whether these last are properly call'"-1 sensations.

FEELING IN SENSATION. 63

One of Hamilton's illustrations is that of a dog, to which, though his " sense of smell is so acute, all odors seem in themselves indifferent." It might be difficult to prove that odors are indifferent to a dog, though it is quite possible that he abstracts his attention from the feeling and gives it entirely to discrimination, as we ourselves often do. Another illustra- tion is the human skin in the sensation of touch. The tips of the fingers are more discriminative, but less sensitive to pain than the arm or the back. But the explanation seems to be that the skin is thicker at the tips of the fingers; a pin or a sliver there, if it really reaches the nerves, causes sharper pain than elsewhere; and the heel, where the skin is thickest of all, has almost no discriminative sensibility. Yet there is a good deal of truth in Hamilton's comparison, which we think, however, can all be covered by the following statements better than by laying down a universal dogma.

1. The sensations may be arranged in a series, from those which have no mental content but are wholly feeling, to those which have no content of feeling but are all mental. A tooth- ache is all pain; a glance at the sun is nearly all pain; a sweet taste is part pleasure and part discrimination; a pleasant musical air has more complicated and difficult discrimination; in reading a book the mental process is complicated and diffi- cult, gathering up the arbitrary symbols and interpreting them into sounds, combining these into words and interpreting out of them the author's meaning, with all the subsidiary trains of thought and association going on at the same time; sensuous feeling is usually entirely absent, unless, indeed, feeling be ex- pressly defined so as to include all sensation.

2. The attention may be directed to either element, when they are combined, to the exclusion of the other. In comparing two samples of cloth to see if they are of exactly the same color we have sensation about as pure as it can be found, yet

64 THE INTELLECT.

discrimination is intense; we know nothing of the colors as agreeable or the contrary, for the moment, but only know them as alike or different.

Mr. Herbert Spencer, criticising this doctrine of Hamilton's says, " It would seem not so much that sensation and percep- tion vary inversely, as that they exclude each other with de- grees of stringency which vary inversely." (Psychology II, 248.)

IV. ATTENTION.

Attention is a necessary condition of perception, and con- sists in the narrowing or concentration of the activity of the mind upon one or a few sensations to the exclusion of others. It may be either voluntary or spontaneous. When a number of different sensations are occasioned by different objects at the same time, they may only cause confusion, and no one of them may originate a perception. If one of them or one set of them is much stronger than the others, so as to overbear them, it will force the recognition and attention of the mind, and occasion a perception. Or if one of them calls up a more exciting image than the others, owing to previous associations or familiar knowledge, the voluntary attention of the mind is instantly directed to this one. Thus, if I am intently reading a book, the clock may strike in the same room, but the well- accustomed sound cannot force its way among the set of sen- sations which I am receiving from the printed page. But the sound of a distant fire-bell, or the gnawing of a rat close by, is a more exciting set of sensations, and I stop reading and give my attention to the new sound.

The will often determines a change in the flow of the nerve- currents, and a particular organ with its set of nerves is rendered more active; this is called innervation. We often suspend the action of one organ to render another more acute, shut the eyes or hold them fixed, in order to catch a faint

ATTENTION. 65

sound. We do not hear what a friend is saying to us while we are watching an exciting scene in a play, or scrutinizing a distant object with a glass; when we are through we ask him to repeat, innervate the ear, that is, give him our attention, and hear him then distinctly.

If any sensation is extremely intense this attracts the atten- tion, and the mind knows nothing through the sensation. If you look at the sun you cannot see anything, but the intensity of sensation is painful and injurious. With a bit of smoked glass to render sensation less intense you can see an eclipse at its very beginning. An intense pain overpowers all the facul- ties; while your tooth is being pulled you can neither per- ceive nor reason. But, on the other hand, soldiers in bat- tle often receive severe flesh wounds without knowing it, so in- tense is their excitement. That attention is necessary to per- ception is also shown by every-day occurrences, such as when one goes around looking for a thing which is in his hand, or for glasses which are on his forehead.

In spontaneous attention it is only the direction of the atten- tion which is automatic, the continuance of it is voluntary.

" In attention we submit to an impression, we keep the mind steady in order to receive the stamp." (Coleridge.) "Attention is concentrated observation." (Calderwood.) " The greater or less energy in the operation of knowing is called attention, which is another term for tension or effort." (Porter.) " Hie content of our mind at each moment can be only very limited, and we can entertain simultaneously only a very small number of ideas." (Drbal.)

No power of the mind is more susceptible of cultivation than attention. Young children cannot fix their minds on one thing more than a few minutes. To teach scholars how to study, to train the power of attention, is perhaps the most difficult office of the teacher. 5

66 THE INTELLECT.

It is a curious question how many objects can be attended to by the mind at the same time. Dugald Stewart pro- pounded a theory that the number is only one, and that in comparing two objects the mind goes with almost infinite ra- pidity from one to the other. This theory is disproved by the commonest experience. The most important part of all our knowledge is the knowledge of relations, which presupposes at least two objects in the mind at once.

Yet it is probable that the most complete, intense attention can be given to only one set of sensations at the same time. The truth seems to be that the mind can distribute its activity among several objects to some extent, but cannot perceive them all with the same vividness. Mr. Herbert Spencer says; " Consciousness cannot be in two equally distinct states at the same time." (Psychology, II, 250.) But he also says; "I find that there may sometimes be detected as many as five simultaneous series of nervous changes, which in various de grees rise into consciousness so far that we cannot call any of them absolutely unconscious. When walking there is the loco- motive series; there may be a tactual' series; and there is the visual series; all of which are subordinate to the dominant consciousness formed by some train of reflection." (Ib. I, 398.)

A still more curious subject connected with attention is the influence of excited attention and expectation in producing illusions and hallucinations, and even bodily disorders. Sir Walter Scott, soon after the death of Lord Byron, having been engaged in reading an account of the departed poet, on going into another room, saw an exact representation of Lord Byron before him. Sensible that it was an illusion he examined the object, and found it to be a screen covered with coats, shawls, etc. (Carpenter, Mental Physiology, 207.)

During the burning of the Crystal Palace in London, many

QUALITIES OF MATTER. 67

spectators saw the chimpanzee, which was known to have escaped from his cage, writhing around one of the iron ribs of the building in the midst of the flames. But the object turned out to be a tattered piece of blind, tossed about in the wind. (Id. ib. 208.) Hypochondriacs come to have the very disease they fancy. The victims of witchcraft pine away and die, because they believe they are bewitched, and so brood over their fate with intense attention. Many wonderful cures have been wrought by the king's touch, by holy water, by mesmeric passes, all due to expectant attention.

Baron Reichenbach discovered a new force which he called odyle, and performed many wonderful experiments to prove it, all with excitable and nervous persons. But Mr. Braid per- formed the same experiments without any odyle, through ex- pectant attention alone. His patients, being taken into a dark room and told that there was a magnet in a certain corner, used to see the magnetic force issuing from it in the form of flames of fire, although there was really no magnet there. Mr. Home, the "medium" was proved to have floated out of one window and in at another by the testimony of two witnesses; but another witness who was present saw nothing of the kind. (See the works of Carpenter, Maudsley, Abercrombie, Tuke, Brodie, Sully.) The ventriloquist and the conjuror deceive us by directing our attention where they wish, quite as much as by their dexterity.

V. QUALITIES OF MATTER.

The question naturally arises in connection with perception, how it is that matter can affect our sense-organs. The power of occasioning sensation in any particular way has usually been called a quality, and the description and classification of the qualities of matter has been a topic of some importance. It is obvious that in order to occasion sensation the qualities of matter must exist, or its powers must be exerted, in certain re-

68 THE INTELLECT.

lations and under certain conditions. Qualities are called by such names as color, weight, hardness, size, smell, etc. But in order to have color a body must be in the light; and in order that it should have color for us, we must have eyes, must look at the body, and must give our attention to what we look at. In order to have smell a body must be volatile, to have taste it must be soluble, and that it may have these quali- ties for us, it must come into proper relation with our nerves of sensation.

It is commonly said, and is an obvious thought, that the qualities of matter are entirely in our minds, not in the objects which we perceive; that there is no color, no sound, unless an eye or an ear be present to see and to hear. There is a sense in which this is true. Sweetness does not exist in sugar as sweetness, but as a peculiar combination of atoms of oxygen, hydrogen, and carbon, probably held in combination by their coincident or rythmical vibrations, and ready to change their combination under certain influences, in such a way as to af- fect the organ of taste. So color does not exist in the object as color, but as a power of checking some of the light-vibra- tions, and reflecting others unchanged, probably because some of the vibrations of light are in accord or in rhythm with its own atomic vibrations and some are not.

There is then really some power in the object of impressing or influencing objects around it by its activities, and hence of affecting our sense-organs, which are a set of instruments, vary- ing in delicacy and nature from a pair of scales for measuring gravity, to a photographic .plate for recording the vibrations of light. The popular mode of speech is justifiable and proper. The roar of the ocean and the colors of the flowers are real things, motions or actions of matter, not indeed sensations; but then they could never be sensations, in any proper use of language, but only occasions of sensation; and no one ever

QUALITIES OF MATTER. 69

said that they were sensations. The terms, color, sound, hard- ness, etc., are used, however, to denote both our sensations and the qualities or activities of bodies which occasion those sen- sations. Some writers confound these meanings, and we need to bear the distinction carefully in mind.

The most common division of the qualities of matter has been into two classes, primary and secondary. This distinction may be said to date back to the earliest period of philosophy. Democritus distinguished between those qualities which are known by touch and all others, and denied that the latter give any real knowledge of matter.

Aristotle used the terms common sensibles or percepts, and proper sensibles or percepts, the former being magnitude (extension), figure, motion or rest, and number. According to Sir W. Hamilton " he anticipated Descartes, Locke, and other modern philosophers, in establishing, and making out by appropriate terms, a distinction precisely analogous with that taken by them of the primary and secondary qualities of mat- ter." (Philosophy, ed. by Wight, 313.)

Descartes re-introduced this division into philosophy in the modern period. According to him our knowledge of the pri- mary qualities is clear, that is, intuitive, self-evident; but of the secondary qualities we have only an "obscure and con- fused conception of something which occasions the appropriate sensation." (Porter, Human Intellect, 637.)

But as he taught that the essence of matter is extension, as the essence of mind is thought, the knowledge of extension and the qualities depending on it, was, for him, a real knowl- edge of matter as it is. And we shall find this doctrine -ef ex- tension, as the essential attribute of matter, pervading subse- quent classifications.

Locke's division, though some advance upon that of Des- cartes, is yet essentially the same, and accounted for in the

yo THE INTELLECT.

sane way; that is, the primary qualities are those which we perceive directly, intuitively, as they really are, while the secondary are merely affections of the mind caused by bodies. He says: " A power to produce any idea in our mind, I call quality of the subject wherein that power is; '' and divides qualities into, "first, such as are utterly inseparable from the body in what estate soever it be," such as solidity, extension, figure, motion or rest, and number, and secondly, " such quali- ties which in truth are nothing in the objects themselves but powers to produce various sensations in us by their primary qualities, that is, by the bulk, figure, texture, and motion of their insensible parts, as colors, sounds, tastes, etc." (Essay on Human Understanding, Book 2, Ch. 8.)

However interesting or even useful this division may be, the reason given for it is unsatisfactory. We can no more con- ceive matter without secondary qualities than without primary. We can indeed imagine the sky to be green and the grass blue, but we must conceive every object to have some color (count- ing white and black as colors), if it is exposed to light at ally capable of emitting sound, if struck in the air; having some chemical reactions, similar to those occasioning smell and taste, having some degree of hardness or softness, heat or cold, elas- ticity or rigidity, etc.

Moreover, it is just as easy to conceive matter to be without figure and solidity as without color; the ether, if it transmits light, must be matter, yet it does not retard the motions of the planets; a gas diffused in another gas can hardly be said to have form. Again, number is not a quality of matter, but a logical necessity of the perception of different objects; we must know them as one or many, if we know them at all. And motion or rest is no quality of matter, though all matter, so far as we know, is in constant motion.

The advance of physical science since Locke's time leaves

QUALITIES or MATTER. 71

little room for doubt that the primary qualities of matter de- pend as much on the " bulk, figure, and motion, of their in- sensible parts,'' or molecules, as do the secondary. When we feel a body as heavy, pressing down on the hand, the sensa- tion results from an activity of the body, pulling itself toward the center of the earth. The atoms of matter are supposed to be in constant vibration, and the regularity and continuity of these vibrations define its form and solidity. In fact, it is now a common theory that the very essence of matter is the activity of its "insensible parts," which are in themselves only centers of force, having a merely supersensual existence.

The most complete and elaborate classification of the qual- ities of matter is that of Sir W. Hamilton. His division is three-fold, primary, secundo-primary, and secondary. The primary qualities are deduced "from the simple datum of sub- stance occupying space," and fall into two divisions, the prop- erty of filling space, or geometrical solidity, and the property of being contained in space, or physical solidity.

Geometrical solidity which is defined as "the necessity of trinal extension, in length, breadth, and thickness," is devel- oped into three qualities, divisibility, magnitude, and figure. Physical solidity, defined as ultimate or absolute incompres- sibility, is really equivalent to be:ng or existence; he calls it impenetrability. The attribute of being contained in space is explicated into two, mobility or motion and rest, and situa- tion or position. The author well says that these " primary are less properly denominated qualities, and deserve the name only as we conceive them to distinguish body from not body, corporeal from incorporeal substance." They are indeed deductions from the conception of matter as reality whose essence is extension, and not properly qualities at all.

The secundo-primary qualities "are all contained under the category of resistance or pressure." Resistance or pressure

72 THE INTELLECT.

may have three sources, co-attraction, repulsion, and inertia. The first involves gravity and cohesion: gravity gives the quali- ties heavy and light, cohesion gives hard and soft, solid and fluid, tough and brittle', etc. Repulsion is developed into com- pressible and incompressible, elastic and inelastic. Inertia gives movable and immovable. The secondary qualities are such as color, sound, flavor, the feelings of heat, sneezing, shuddering, setting-the-teeth-on-edge, etc.

" The primary determine the possibility of matter abso- lutely; the secundo-pnmary, the possibility of the material universe as actually constituted; the secondary the possibility of our relation as sentient existences to that universe." " The primary may be roundly characterized as mathematical; the secundo-primary, as mechanical; the secondary, as physiologi- cal." (Metaphysics, Bowen's ed., 340.)

Our remarks upon Locke's division are also applicable to Hamilton's second and third classes. Considered as qualities of bodies, these are activities, powers of affecting other bodies; and since we can transform these motions into sensation, and interpret these sensations in perception and thought, the activ- ity of objects toward us seems to differ from their activity to- ward other things, but it is not really different. All the quali- ties of matter, except those metaphysical qualities which are not properly so called, are similarly related to perception. Even impenetrability is declared by Lotze to be, not a prop- erty but an activity of matter, somewhat, we suppose, as the pressure of gases is due to molecular vibration. " Bodies do not react on one another because they are impenetrable, but they are impenetrable because they react on one another." (Dictate Naturphilosophie, §19.)

Mr. Herbert Spencer's classification differs from Hamilton's only in terminology. He calls the three classes "body as presenting statical, statico-dynamical, and dynamical attri-

SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE. 73

butes." This nomenclature is not more felicitous than Hamil- ton's; for all qualities of bodies which appear in perception must be dynamical, must ex"ert force or influence of some kind; and all must be statical, must have continuous, inde- pendent existence.

SUBSTANCE AND ATTRIBUTE.

When we speak of qualities the question necessarily arises, Qualities of what? The term quality, or attribute, implies substance. The two are really inseparable, like the correla- tive terms, husband and wife, triangle and three sides. Are qualities, then, one thing and objects another? Are qual- ities something which the object may have or not have, and which may exist by themselves, apart from objects ? Mr. Mill replies that qualities only exist, there is no substance, or substratum, matter is only a permanent possibility of certain sensations. Berkeley is generally, though erroneously, under- stood to have held the same view. Hume distinctly denied the existence of the real thing to which the qualities belong. Kant maintained that there is such a real existence, or noume- non, but that it is unknowable. In this he is followed by Herbert Spencer and many others. Other philosophers have in general held to the reality of substance.

Undoubtedly the constitution of our minds is such that when we perceive an object we perceive it as really existing; our minds act in this relation under the category of being, and we can never practically accept the belief that the object is nothing but a set of sensations. No argument can make this any clearer. But there is not in nature or in conscious- ness anything corresponding to the separation of the object into substance and attribute, real thing and quality. This separa- tion is purely logical, and has an effect somewhat like divid- ing the mind awkwardly into different faculties.

74 THE INTELLECT.

Substance apart from quality is only an abstraction, for there is no real being without attributes. Being without attributes is equivalent to non-being. To say that the noumenon is un- knowable apart from phenomena is mere platitude, for of course we can only know what is in relation to us, and know it by those relations. We know the object as related to us by- its qualities or activities, and there is no object without quali- ties or activities. " Sensible qualities," says Lotze, '-show us how things act, not what they are." (Dictate, Metaphysik, §16.) Not what they are, that is, apart from their action; but they are just as they act.

"The 'underlying substance' of the schools, the 'thing in it- self of Kant, are mere names, which signify either being in the abstract or being in the concrete. If it is being in the abstract, then it must- be synonymous with matter as knowable, that is, it is only a concept, which can be separate from its relations in thought but never in fact. If it is being in the concrete, then this must be known with its relations and never apart from them. In either case the substance or thing in itself cannot be known by itself." (Porter, Human Intellect, 632. See also Bowne's Metaphysics, 48.)

CONSCIOUSNESS.

This important subject may be said to be transitional, be- tween topics connected with perception, and the necessary elements of perception.

Every perception, feeling, or act of will, is accompanied by a knowledge of self as the perceiving, feeling, or willing agent. This is called consciousness, a very appropriate designation, since by its etymology it means a with-knowing. It can be separated from other acts of the mind only logically, not prac- tically. It is an inseparable element of every act of perception, omitted hitherto in our discussions, in order to avoid complica-

CONSCIOUSNESS. 75

tion, and because its importance demands separate and fuller treatment. "We know and we know that we know; these propositions," says Hamilton, " logically distinct, are really identical."

The facts of memory make this clear. When we remember anything, a. former perception, or feeling, or action, the ele- ment of self is perfectly clear. All philosophers are agreed that there is here an irresistible belief in the identity and con- tinuity of the past perception and the present memory, how- ever they may explain it or try to explain it away.

Professor Ferrier has most ingeniously based a whole system of metaphysics on the postulate, or ultimate datum, which he considers self-evident, that consciousness of self accompanies all knowledge. " All cognition is a knowledge of self plus an object."

It would be well if the term could be confined to this mean- ing, self-knowledge, as implied in all mental action. But gen- eral usage gives it a wider meaning, and we cannot hope to make this useful restriction. It is commonly used in the sense, of "introspection, or introspective attention/' (Bain); "the power by which the soul knows its own acts or states," (Porter); " the immediate knowledge which the mind has of its sensa- tions and thoughts, and, in general, of all its present operations." (Morell.)

Hence consciousness is often spoken of as a faculty of the mind. Such phrases are almost inevitable, and yet they are misleading; for consciousness is parallel with all the faculties, a condition of them all, not properly to be considered a faculty, co-ordinate with, for example, perception, or imagination. If the power of knowing that we know is a faculty, parallel with preception, imagination, etc., then we are required to suppose another and higher faculty to embrace both in one unity of feeling; but this faculty would be consciousness in the usual sense, hence the first is a useless supposition.

76 THE INTELLECT.

Less positively incorrect, but still objectionable and to be avoided, are all figurative ways of speaking of consciouness, as a witness (Cousin), a light (Hickok), a dry light (Coleridge), a revealer, etc.

Consciousness is often said to be the source of all our knowl- edge of the operations of the mind, and psychology has even been called " an inquiry into the facts of consciousness. All that we can truly learn of mind must be learned by attending to the various ways in which it becomes conscious." (Fleming.)

Cultured consciousness, or introspection, is indeed an im- portant source of knowledge in psychology, but not the only one; much may be learned by observation and comparison, and these are important checks upon the errors and deceptions of introspection. John Locke deserves credit for calling at- tention to this source of knowledge, under the name of reflec- tion. He taught, however, that what we know in consciousness is the operations of the mind, not the mind itself. Among his followers, says President Porter, "it has passed into a posi tive dogma that the soul in consciousness cognizes the opera- tion only, and nothing besides."

The correct formula is, we know the ego as modified in its changing states, whether of perception or feeling or action, limited by whatever relations. We place the ego first because it is "unchanged and permanent," while the "states are vary- ing and transitory," to quote the words of President Poiter, who continues, correctly and clearly: "It is of the very nature and essence of a psychical state to be the act or experience of an individual ego. We are not first conscious of the state or operation, and then forced to look around for a something to which it is to be referred, or to which it may belong; but what we know, and as we know it, is the state of an individual per- son. . . . The fact of memory proves it beyond dispute." (Human Intellect, 95.)

CONSCIOUSNESS. 77

On the other hand, some have denied the possibility of this philosophical consciousness. Compte dogmatically asserted that consciousness is one state, perception, or feeling another, and two such cannot exist together; an absurdity which every one's experience disproves. Herbert Spencer says "no one is conscious of what he is, but of what he was the moment before." It is a sufficient reply to this, that all other philoso- phers are agreed to call this kind of knowledge, characterized by the element of past time, by the name of memory, not con- sciousness; and that it rests on the same assumption with Compte's, that the mind cannot do two things at once, which is entirely gratuitous.

We do not intend to affirm that consciousness is always equally clear and forcible in every act of the mind, nor that it is intuitive in the sense of being incapable of culture. The infant has blurred and inaccurate perceptions and confused feelings, and of course its consciousness is equally blurred, yet real and easily demonstrated. It cannot tell you that it knows the ego from the non-ego, neither can it tell you that it has a pain in its stomach. Yet it knows that the pain is in its own stomach, not in yours; knows that its mother is not the same being as itself; knows, in some dim way, itself as a separate being or entity. Before even this dim state of knowl- edge arises, we may say that the child has not consciousness in the full sense of the term. "As long as the sensations are confused together, and are not discriminated, . . . the soul remains in this elementary condition of comparative un- consciousness. This is the condition of the infant [at birth]. It is also the condition into which the developed man relapses in swooning, distraction, intoxication, or approaching sleep." (Porter, Human Intellect, 100.)

But as soon as discrimination begins, and the actions are no longer quite automatic, consciousness is real, though its

7 8 THE INTELLECT.

content may be slight and dim. The philosopher, accustomed to introspection and familiar with abstract terms, can argue better about himself, and describe his feelings better than the ignorant laborer; but he is not any more certain of his own identity, more sure that it is he himself, and not another, who experiences all his sensations.

Even the brute, though he cannot express any distinction between the ego and the non-ego, has consciousness more or less developed. The dog knows whether you whip him or another dog, knows whether it is he or another dog that has a bone. In the lower orders of the animal creation it is not easy to say how far down consciousness can be traced, but we may say confidently that it cannot exist where the actions are demonstrably automatic, as in the oyster, etc., noticed under the head of sensation.

" It is probable," says President Bascom, " that sensibility to physical pain and pleasure, and the appetites, were the first mental facts to appear in consciousness. . . . This also is the order of development in human life. The infant enters on a conscious activity first through the sensibilities, the appetites, and is trained for months in this school. . . . But the ap- petites must almost immediately be supported in conscious- ness by the special senses There seems to be

good ground to believe that consciousness arises slowly with the increase of that unity in the nervous system which puts it under the control of a single center, gathers the senses about that center, and knits the organic life as closely as does con- sciousness our intellectual activity; . . . that conscious- ness becomes the specialized function of the cerebrum, from a previously weak, vague, and confused form. . . . . The clearest proof of consciousness in doubtful territory is memory. This faculty is the basis of experience, and not till it has been obtained can the facts of conscious-

CONSCIOUSNESS. 79

ness, if any are present, be organized into knowledge. The action of memory is also more readily discriminated from au- tomatic action than is the conscious from the unconscious use of the senses." (Comparative Psychology, 180-188.)

Recent observations by Sir J. Lubbock, Kirby and Spence, etc., go to show that the intellect of the insects, ants, bees, wasps, etc., has been greatly overestimated, that memory is al- most lacking to them, and hence consciousness must be dim and vague, and those actions which seem so wonderful, almost entirely automatic.

Philosophical consciousness, or careful introspection, is as capable of culture and improvement by education as any other power of the mind. " Men differ more widely in respect to the energy and effect with which they use this power than in respect to any other." (Porter, Hum. Int., 87.) By direct- ing the attention to the various elements of perception, the ob- ject, the sensational process, the element of self, we learn to observe ourselves, the action of our senses and minds.

The uncultured consciousness does not distinguish between mind and body. To the child or the savage his self is his body, with all the powers he has, mental and physical; and when he has the feeling, " it is I who perceive this object," he has no notion of an immaterial self, distinct from the body. Socrates is represented by Plato as going through a long ex- planation, and asking many questions, before he can make the distinction between the two kinds of ego clear even to his grown-up pupils. After many comparisons, such as that of a shoemaker's knife, and a shoemaker's hand, as equally instru- ments, he at length extorts an apparently unwilling concession of the point.

Under religious and moral instruction especially, the feeling may be very early aroused; but it is essentially an acquired one, a product of the cultured consciousness. We are con-

8o THE INTELLECT.

scious of self as the subject of thought, feeling, and action. If we have not learned that thought is not a function of the body, or that the soul is a distinct entity from the body, then consciousness cannot present to us such an ego.

Some strange opinions concerning the ego have been held by philosophers, in their anxiety to carry out preconceived theories. Mr. J. S. Mill held that the mind is a series of sen- sations and feelings. But he was compelled to admit that it must be conceived as a series of sensations which isaware of itself! Such a mind would be like a string of beads without any string. Again, on reaching the subject of memory, Mill saw the impossibility of explaining it without a person or entity of some sort to be the continuous subject of a continuous action, and frankly declared that memory was the final inexplicability which he could not manage on his system. The nature of self will be more conveniently discussed when 'we come to speak of the soul.

AUTHORITY OF CONSCIOUSNESS.

Consciousness is necessarily the court of final appeal in all matters that come within its range. " The facts of conscious- ness are the most certain of all facts. The objects which con- sciousness presents are, if possible, more real and better at- tested than the objects of sense. . . . We may doubt whether this or that object be a reality or a phantasm, but we cannot doubt that we doubt." (Porter, Hum. Int., 115.)

The difficulties which arise about this matter turn on false assumptions as to what consciousness can do, or false reports of what it really does, or else are mere verbal disputes. If an insane man tells us that he is conscious of being made of glass, he is mistaken; but he would be equally mistaken if he said that he was conscious of being made of flesh and blood and bones. No such subject comes within the range of conscious-

UNCONSCIOUS PERCEPTION. 81

ness. If a man tells us that he is conscious that two straight lines cannot enclose a space, we reply, it is impossible, and it would be dangerous to admit such language, for it opens the door to endless dogmatism. The mind has no organ for truth, though it has command of certain tests by which truth may be tried. When the mind is conscious of being in a certain state, of receiving certain sensations, or experiencing certain feel- ings, there can be no reasonable doubt about the truth of it. But some abnormal condition of the body or mind may have orig- inated the state or impression. The insane man is conscious that his limbs feel hard and smooth, like glass, to him. He is right, but his perceptions originate in his own mind, dominated by a " fixed idea." The mathematician has an immediate per- ception that two straight lines cannot enclose a space; but what he is conscious of is the perception, not the fact.

One of the most celebrated dicta in the history of philoso- phy is Descartes', " Cogito, ergo sum." It was intended as a refutation of absolute skepticism. Whatever I doubt, I can- not doubt that there is something which doubts and thinks; to do so is to destroy the doubt itself and render all reasoning impossible. When Descartes was asked to explain his dictum he substituted for ergo, scilicet, c'est-a-dire, showing that this is the correct interpretation of his words. "In consciousness I am confronted, not with a thought, but with a being. What- ever else may be unreal, whether idea, phantasm, or specula- tion, this acting and suffering self is a reality, not a mere phe- nomenal as contrasted with a transcendental ego, nor an ego inferred or suggested, but an ego directly known to be." (Por- ter, Human Intellect, 99.)

UNCONSCIOUS PERCEPTION.

An interesting question arising in connection with the sub- ject of consciousness, is the extent to which mental action may be unconscious. The phenomena called by Dr. Carpenter

82 THE INTELLECT.

"unconscious cerebration," and by Sir W. Hamilton "latent modifications of consciousness," will be discussed under the head of Association. We have already seen under the head of Sensation that some writers use the term "sensation" of im- pressions which are entirely automatic, and do not appear in consciousness, but the more general and better usage is against this.

In some cases, however, the point may be a doubtful one. When a student, absorbed in his book, does not notice the clock striking in the same room, he afterwards, in some cases, recalls having heard it. In such a case he may have had the sensations, occasioned by the sound, at the time, but, attention being intently directed elsewhere, no perception was formed, and the sensations were automatically recorded. More proba- bly, however, the supposed remembering of the sound is an im- agination, a phantasm, suggested by the fact being learned that the clock really has struck. Some remarks made under the head of Attention are applicable to this point.

Sir W. Hamilton applies the term, Unconscious Mental Action, to the elements of compound sensations. For ex- ample, the roar of the ocean at a distance is made up of the noise of many waves, each one of which, by itself, is inaudible. Hamilton contends "that they produce a certain modification, beyond consciousness, on the percipient subject." But no proof can be given of such a view. It is far more probable that each impulse by itself is too weak, in compound sensa- tions, to affect the sense-organ.

Psychology " is unable to advance any proof of unconscious elements or processes in the human mind. Such proof is, in- deed, in the very nature of the case, unattainable." (Sully, Pessimism, 192.)

USES OF THE TERM CONSCIOUSNESS. 83

USES OF THE TERM CONSCIOUSNESS.

A subjective division of consciousness has been adopted by President Porter, into two kinds, natural or spontaneous, and reflective or philosophical. But these are really different stages in the cultivation of introspection, and are not distinct enough to deserve separate mention as different kinds of consciousness.

An objective division may be mentioned, into, first, the feel- ing of self as a necessary element in perception, and second, the knowledge of the mind and its states, of the mind as modi- fied.

Sir W. Hamilton used the term consciousness sometimes in the usual sense, a knowledge of the mind and its states, some- times in a wider sense, as "a comprehensive term for the com- plement of our cognitive energies." He says that "conscious- ness and immediate knowledge are terms universally converti- ble." He extends the term consciousness to knowledge of the external world, and says " I am conscious of the inkstand." Worst of all, he does not strictly adhere, in all cases, to the same meaning of the term throughout the same argument. The extended use of consciousness as equivalent to knowledge, he probably derived from the German word "bewusstsein," which denotes, as President Porter remarks, rather a be-know- ing, than a with-knowing, and is commonly used to mean know- ing in general. It is not too much to say that Hamilton lent his great influence to confuse the nomenclature of philosophy in English on this important topic, by thus teaching the duality of consciousness.

Mr. Herbert Spencer also uses consciousness as equivalent to knowledge. He also speaks of being conscious of space, of time, and of motion, and even says in one place, "we are scarcely at all conscious of the space behind us." He also calls dreaming "sleep-consciousness." This use of the term has some advantages with reference to space and time, but it

84 THE INTELLECT.

is better to call these necessary elements in perception than to say we are conscious of them.

Dr. Cocker Carrie's this confusion still farther by making two cross-divisions, each threefold. He divides consciousness sub- jectively considered, somewhat as President Porter does, into spontaneous, representational, and reflective; objectively into knowledge of self, of the world, and of God.

The terms Christian consciousness, and God-consciousness, have been borrowed from the German by some writers. In place of the latter term, "intuition of God" is in better English usage, and even better expresses the real meaning of the German; "necessary idea of God" is also frequently used in this meaning.

NECESSARY ELEMENTS OF PERCEPTION. I. SPACE.

We have seen, when discussing the senses separately, that through sensations of sight, under certain conditions, we know external objects as extended in two directions, as having sur- face-extension; and that through sensations of touch and mus- cular motion, under certain conditions, we know objects as ex- tended in three directions, as having solidity. This obviously introduces a new subject, that of Space, which we could not delay at that point to examine, and whose importance demands separate treatment,

The question what space is in itself, belongs to metaphysics, and we shall only discuss it so far as it is incidental to our present purpose.

As to the cognition of space, two great theories divide philosophers. On the one hand it has been held by the ma- jority that our knowledge of space is previous to all experi-

SPACE. 85

euce of things in space,so that we bring to our perceptions of the external world this a priori concept, or intuitive idea of space. On the other hand, John Locke attempted to show and his followers still hold, that all our knowledge of space is derived entirely from sensations. The first school, holding that our ideas of space, time, cause, etc., are necessary elements of cognition, not derived from experience, are called intuitional- ists, a priori philosophers, or various other names of similar significance. Those who derive all these from experience are called sensationalists, experientialists, experience philosophers, etc.

John Locke's polemic against intuitive ideas had great force against the crude way of viewing the subject at that time in vogue, and has resulted in a change of the entire situation. It is no longer held by the intuitionalists that the mind is equipped with ready-made 'knowledge previous to experience, nor that this knowledge springs up in completeness on the oc- casion of the first experience; but these principles are gener- ally considered, with more or less clearness and consistency, to be conditions of thought, formulas or categories under which the mind acts, necessary or primary elements of cogni- tion. To this point we shall return.

It is often overlooked, however, by the intuitionalist philos- ophers, that our objective knowledge of space as a quality or relation of actually existing bodies, is a product of experience. On this point Sir W. Hamilton has suggested a useful distinc- tion. He says that space is known a priori, extension a posteriori; that is, the term extension should be applied to space as filled by bodies, or measured by the distances be- tween bodies, while the term space should be reserved to mean an eternal condition of the existence of the material universe, the abstract something which makes these concretely-known relations possible. It would be well if the terms could be

86 THE INTELLECT.

used in this way, but the attempt so to restrict them would be hopeless, especially as so many recent writers purposely con- found the two, and attempt to reduce all space to exten- sion.

When we begin our mental life we first learn the space- relations of the objects close about us; then the parts and furniture of the room and house; then the trees, houses, etc., objects which we see from day to day; next cities, mountains, seas, the globe on which we live. The moon, too, is compara- tively easily reached by this space-construction, its distance being easily comparable with those which we have already learned. Thence we ascend to the planets and the stars, where, for any real understanding, we must use a new standard of measurement, no longer miles but diameters of the earth, or of its orbit. Thus we " place ourselves " in the universe, and learn our space relations (extension-relations.)

But on the other hand the experience-philosophers overlook the most important point, that not a single object can be per- ceived as extended, not a single distance can be compared or estimated or imagined, not a single step taken in this process of so-called generalization, which does not involve space as an element in cognition. If I see a tall and a short man to- gether, I cannot tell in what the difference between them con- sists, unless I have at the time of comparing them, in and with the act of comparison, and as a kind of category which I apply in that act, a knowledge, in my mind, if not in words, of bigness or size. So, if the points of a pair of compasses are placed upon my skin, not too near together, so that the two sensations are exactly alike except in place, I could not know that this is the particular in which they differ, if I had not, in and with my double sensation, some cognition of what difference in place depends upon, that is, space. So, also, if I look upon a colored object and feel around it with my eyes,

SPACE. 87

following its outline by rotation of the eyes, I perceive the points and parts of the object as extended, that is, under space-relations, implying, as before, some cognition of space.

It is not meant by this that in the process of perception space is perceived as a third thing, different from self and the object, yet known by the senses. We do not see, hear, smell, or feel space; it is not sensible, but intelligible, knowable by a direct, inexplicable act of the intellect. When an object is perceived at ail it is known under this relation, a space-rela- tion.

Nor is it meant that the mind clearly distinguishes, and says to itself, " I know this object as in space, and I know space;'' this is the end of mature reflection, not the beginning of per- ception.

The reason why our perceptions of material objects are thus conditioned is that the objects themselves exist under space-relations, and cannot exist in any other way. It is im- possible for us, while in this semi-material state of being, to conceive any other kind of existence, that is, not under space relations. We cannot imagine to ourselves a pure spirit, that is, one without parts or distances, existing outside of all space-relations. Nor can we imagine space as infinite, but when we remove its boundary in thought, another forms itself beyond.

Space may thus be said to be a necessary form of all our perceptions, and may even be said to be a form latent in the mind, by which it knows the external world; for the mind does not, at first, consciously and explicitly recognize space as a separate entity, but nevertheless cannot think the material world without it; much as one cannot speak without grammar, even though he does not know what the word grammar means. The knowledge of space may thus be said to be a priori, in the Kantian sense, that is, prior to experience, because it is

88 THE INTELLECT.

implied in the very first experience of the actual world; it is a condition of experience, logically antecedent, though practi- cally simultaneous; the mind has an aptitude, a capacity for knowing objects in this way, a necessary, innate power of per- ceiving things under this form, and in no other way, because things actually exist under this form and in no other way.

It has been held by many philosophers that space has no real existence by itself, but is a mere relation among objects, or a product of the mind. Leibnitz taught that space " is only the order of things coexisting, as time is the order of things successive." Mr. H. Spencer, if we understand him correctly, adopts the same view. He says: " The idea of space in- volves the idea of coexistence, and the idea of coexistence in- volves the idea of space." (Psychology. II, 201.) But space cannot be the mere sum or abstract of the relations of things, or the mere order of things, for it is that which makes all these possible; " the principle, without form, order, or relation in itself, which makes possible an infinite number of forms, or- ders, and relations of things." (Lotze, Dictate Metaphysik,

§5iO

Kant taught that space is ideal, a mere subjective form im- posed by the mind on things. In this view; " The idea of space has no objective validity, it is real only relatively to phenomena, to things in so far as they appear out of us; it is purely ideal in so far as things are taken in themselves, and considered independently of the forms of the sensibility." (Fleming, Vocabulary of Philosophy.)

Herbart taught that space is an idea, necessarily arising in every mind from the conflict of other ideas. (Lotze.) But all ideal deductions of space, says Lotze, " smuggle in the specific quality of space (spatialness, raumlichkeit) among the abstract concepts out of which they deduce it, though it is the very thing to be deduced." (Dictate, Metaphysik, §55.)

SPACE. 89

Since Kant's time some form of the ideal theory of space has been held by nearly every German philosopher. But this theory of what space is in itself is not a necessary result of Kant's theory of the cognition of space. He was, rather, forced into this position by his arbitrary assumption "that there is no correspondence between things as they really are and things as they appear to us. ... We can admit the positive portion of Kant's theory, then, namely the a priori cognition of space and time, without accepting the skeptical doctrine which he has needlessly and unreasonably appended to it, the doctrine, that is, that space and time in themselves are unreal, and illusions." (Bowen, Modern Philosophy, 279.)

The reality of space and time rests on the same basis as all the ultimate principles of knowledge, namely, necessity. We cannot think of matter without space, or events without time, any more than we can think of a plurality of objects without number.

Sir W. Hamilton says that Kant has demonstrated the a priori nature of space, to the conviction of every one capable of understanding the subject. We accept this with the limita- tions suggested above. We prefer the formula that space, subjectively considered, is a necessary element in perception, and objectively considered is a necessary condition of the ex- istence of matter.

Lotze has endeavored to escape the difficulties of the ideal theory by holding space to be a product of the inner states of things or elements. These elements act upon one another and upon us by virtue of their inner states; which actions cause them to be related to one another as though in space- relations, and to appear to us in the same way. " According to the common view space t's, and things are in it; according to ours, things are, and there is nothing between them, but space is in them." (Dictate, Metaphysik, §55.) This is evi-

90 THE INTELLECT.

dently only a refinement of Leibnitz's doctrine that space is a relation of matter. It also ascribes occult, if not super- natural, powers to the atoms of matter.

A real definition of space is impossible. All the so-called definitions are either synonyms or but partial descriptions. If we say that space is a condition of all material existence as extended, this is mere tautology, for u extended " implies space. If we leave out the word " extended," we have no definition of space, but a fact, perhaps the most important one, about space. Space, like force, life, motion, is a word which is in- capable of further explication.

Many striking remarks have beep made about space, which really do nothing toward defining it. Dr. Clarke held that space is an attribute of the Deity. Sir Isaac Newton was charged with saying that space is the sensorium of God. Lotze said that a blind man's space, (not merely his knowledge of space), is different from the space of those who can see.

A curious speculation has been indulged in some quarters, that space may have more than three dimensions, and " m- dimensional space" has become a not-uncommon phrase. This theory evidently depends upon the doctrine that space is ideal. If space is a real thing, or even a real relation between real things, all directions and distances can be reduced to three co-ordinates. Lotze, though himself holding to a modified ideal theory of space, answers this notion of m-dimensioned space conclusively. " The relations of things which such minds," (namely those minds to which space has more than three dimensions,) " would perceive, would be entirely different from those which we observe. Such an intuitive form would have no similarity to our space, and it is only by an illogical play with conceptions that it can be called any kind of a modi- fication of our space-intuition." (Dictate, Naturphil. §31.)

The exposition of the abstract relations of space consti-

SPACE. 91

tutes the science of geometry. The discussion of the postu- lates of geometry belongs to metaphysics.

The above doctrine concerning space receives strong confirma- tion from the phenomena of dreams. In dreams the percep- tions through which we generally cognize space being absent, space-relations are wanting to our thoughts. We spend an hour climbing a familiar stair-way, and then suddenly find our- selves transported to a distant city, with no sense of incon- gruity. We leap over a wall, but cannot step over a gutter. The somnambulist can walk over roofs and cliffs, because, his sight being dormant he has no perceptions of the depths around him, and so his equilibrium is not disturbed by fear, and he is guided by the sense of touch. Blind persons often exhibit the same strange security.

Our view of space, both objectively and subjectively, is also confirmed by what is known of the lower animals. They evi- dently have empirical knowledge of space; that is, they perceive objects under space-relations, and adjust their actions to those relations. Yet they have no intuition of its abstract relations, and no power of constructing a geometry. The hare and the dog both know which is gaining on the other, whether the distance between them is increasing or diminishing, and the perceived fact automatically produces eager impulses and in- tense exertions. But neither knows that a straight line is the shortest distance between two points, or that velocity must be measured in terms of space and time; nor has either any ca- pacity of acquiring such truths. The lowest intelligences, however, which are capable of perceiving objects at all, have plainly the power of perceiving them under space-relations.

"There is no more mystery," says President Bascom, "in the animal's fitting his action to spaces without distinctly con- sidering them than there is in man's doing the same thing. The apparently voluntary movements of the animal are as au-

92 THE INTELLECT.

tomatically co-ordinated to spaces as are its stages of digestion to the length of the intestinal canal." (Comparative Psychol- ogy, 231.) The adjustment of our own actions to space-rela- tions is also to a great extent automatic, either originally or by long practice. When we throw a stone or strike with an axe, space-relations are necessary conditions of the action, and some latent cognition of space is implied in the perceptions concerned. But abstract reasoning about space, or the dis- covery of its abstract properties, or the description of the cog- nition or intuition of space, are things which only the philoso- pher has within his reach. They are unintelligible to the unin- structed man, the brute has no capacity even of acquiring them.

"These truths, instead of being the first which are con- sciously possessed and assented to, are the last which are reached, and by only a few of the race are ever reached at all. . The mind must be exercised to some extent in philo- sophical studies before it can comprehend their import and application." (Porter, Human Intellect, 502.) II. TIME.

Time and Space are usually spoken of together, and are in- deed inseparable in experience. We can only measure each by the other. Yet time, as an element in perception, does not resemble space either in itself or in the method of our knowl- edge "of it. Time has been called the form of our inner expe- rience, as space is the form of our outer experience. But it is involved 'in all our experiences, and especially in memory. Perception, as we have seen, takes place by means of discrimi- nation, and discrimination implies a succession of impressions and succession involves time.

The schools of philosophy differ concerning time precisely as they do concerning space. The empirical philosophers teach that time is a generalization from observed succession of

TIME. 93

events. This is true of our empirical knowledge of time; we learn to know a minute, a year, a century, and in this knowl- edge time, space, and motion are inseparably connected. When we say: "I can run so many yards, or repeat so many words in a minute," we maan, " I can do this while the clock- pendulum swings a certain number of times," or use some sim- ilar standard of measurement, thus comparing times with motions and with times, and the subjective succession with the external one.

But the possibility of knowing these successions as such, and of making these comparisons, is the very thing to be ac- counted for; and we could never perform these mentil actions, if we had not some native endowment in correspondence or congruity with the nature of things, beyond the mere ability to perceive one thing and then perceive another. To know two events in succession and compare them, requires consciousness and memory; but memory is knowledge of the past, and hence the first act of knowledge involves some obscure knowledge of what time is, or at least some action of the mind under the category or form of time.

Kant taught that time, like space, is a form which the mind imposes on the events which it knows, empirically valid, but in itself an ideal existence only. The difficulties of this theory have been noticed under the head of space. Lotze attempts to escape these by denying that events are necessarily s,ucces- sive. He says that our ideas (presentations, vorstellungen) of events are necessarily successive, and so we get an irresistible impression that the events themselves are in succession, that is, under the form of time. (Dictate, Metaphysik, §57.)

But this is only ingeniously begging the question; no reason why events are successive to us can be assigned, except that they are really in succession. When we cognize a change in any object we know it as having a beginning and an end, and

94 THE INTELLECT.

the parts in irreversible order, so that those which are last can- not be known as first. To say that this is -a form imposed by the mind, and the events are not really, perhaps, in succession, is entirely gratuitous.

Time has an onward flow, and can never run up stream, but must always run onward. This we know directly, and this is the intuition or a priori cognition of time. Our impression that events, when known, are real, and real in the succession as known, is irresistible and correct. Our estimate of the proportion of comparative time may be distorted by disorder of the brain, or by defect of perception, as in dreams, but such facts only render plainer the fact that time remains through all, a real relation, an eternal reality. The contrary cannot be proved, but is merely assumed by the ideal philosophers.

That time is not ideal is shown by the following considera- tions:—

1. We have decided that space is real, and, if so, time can- not be ideal. The same arguments apply for the most part, and the connection of the two is so intimate that one alone cannot be ideal.

2. The same event may be perceived by many different minds, and by them known to be contemporaneous with sub- jective experiences or with other external events; and events are thus irresistibly and necessarily felt to have a common measure of duration, which is capable also of division and comparison, and therefore is objective.

3. Time is, indeed, in one sense, a form or quality of the inner experience of the mind. But this experience is condi- tioned in the main by external events, and is directly known to be so. When our experience is not controlled by constant im- pressions from the outside world, but runs its own course, as in dreams, all proportion of time-relations is lost, though the general intuition or concept of time remains. In a dream we

TIME. 95

seem to be an hour crossing a street, and no longer time in crossing the ocean. De Quincey, in his opium-reveries, seemed to live a hundred years in an hour. A long dream is often interpolated between a sensation which awakens us and our awakening, though to an observer the awakening seems instan- taneous. Time then must be real, since the mind is ordinarily dominated by events in this regard, and when it is not so, its ex- perience becomes fantastic and irrational.

4. Memory, the most inseparable quality or power of mind, requires and implies time.

5. The lower animals exhibit phenomena of the same order with reference to time, though incapable of idealism or ab- straction. A dog, if you strike him several times knows that the blows are not simultaneous. He knows time-relations in physical events, and knows nothing about time beyond these. "By no one fact," says President Bascom, "is the intellectual progress of man from the animal to the rational plan of life more clearly indicated than by the length of the periods he takes into consideration in his daily conduct. It is difficult to induce the savage to put forth exertions which provide for wants beyond those of the hour; while the civilized man is only too much disposed to forecast the wants of remote years, and weigh down the present with the work of providing for them." (Comparative Psychology, 234.)

Like space, time is incapable of being defined. The defi- nitions usually given are tautological or incomplete. If we say; " Time is that which makes events possible as succesc sive," this is mere tautology, for succession is the very thing to be explained. If we say; "Time is an idea or form in the mind," it cannot be proved that it may not be this and also something more. We cannot define time or space " be- cause the very attributes which we must employ imply both. . . . Every object and event has properties or attributes

(.)() THE INTELLECT..

which imply the existence of these entities. In knowing that these objects exist, we know that time and space exist as their actual conditions." (Porter, Hum. Intellect, 566.)

Aristotle defined time to be the measure of motion. Dr. Reid said; " We may measure duration by the succession of thoughts in the mind, as we measure length by feet and inches, but the notion or idea of duration must be antecedent to the measurement of it, as the notion of length is antecedent to its being measured."

Dr. S. Clarke said; " Space and duration are immediate and necessary consequences of God's existence, and without them his eternity and ubiquity would be taken away."

" Sir Isaac Newton maintained that God, by existing, consti- tutes time and space." (Fleming.)

Schopenhauer has with great ingenuity drawn up a list of axioms showing the curious parallelism between space and time, in twenty-eight pairs. We select a part of them from Pro- fessor Bowen's translation. (Modern Philosophy, 179.)

1. There is but one time, and all times are parts of this one. Space, the same.

2. Time cannot be thought away, but everything in time can be thought away or imagined as non-existent. Space, the same.

3. Time has three divisions, past, present, and future. Space has three dimensions, length, breadth, and thickness.

4. The present moment is without duration. The mathe- matical point is without extension.

5. Time makes arithmecic possible. Space makes geometry possible.

6. The indivisible (single) of arithmetic is the unit. The indivisible (single) of geometry is the mathematical point.

7. Time has no beginning or end. Space has no limits or boundaries.

8. Time has no rest. Space has no motion.

CAUSATION. 97

9. Time itself has no duration, but all duration is in it. Space has no movement, but all movement is in it.

10. Movement is possible only in time and space.

11. Time is everywhere present Space is eternal.

12. Time in itself is empty or void, being perfectly inde- terminate. Space, the same.

13. Time makes the change of attributes possible. Space makes the persistence or unchangeableness of substance pos- sible.

14. We know the laws of both a priori.

Time cannot be seen, felt, or heard; it is intelligible, not sensible, is known directly, like space, by an inexplicable act of the intellect.

III. CAUSE.

When our perceptions are conditioned by our own activity, not merely moving the organ to receive the sensation, as in sight and touch, but actually creating the condition of the sensation itself, as in the case of muscular resistance or press- ure, a new element is here introduced; the consciousness in- volved is different from what we have previously discussed. When we undertake to lift, or move, or compress any heavy or hard object, we receive from it muscular sensations due to its weight or solidity. But we also have a sense of effort put forth, a feeling of voluntary power, quite different from any consciousness involved in any other class of sensations. And, especially if we succeed in moving the object, there is a feel- ing that our voluntary effort has done something, has made a change in the external world, has exhibited power of efficiency, in a word, has become a cause. Cause, then, is a necessary element in some of our perceptions.

But this is not all. The idea of causation necessarily and irresistibly arises in the mind on every similar occa. sion. For example, if I push a book along my table, I know 7

98 THE INTELLECT.

that my hand exerts force> power, efficiency, and actually causes the motion of the book. Now, suppose I roll a ball along the table. Its motion continues after the motion of my hand has ceased; yet I know intuitively, that is, directly and irresistibly, that this continued motion was caused by my hand. Again, suppose that the rolling ball strikes against another ball, and sets it in motion. In this case also I know, intuitively, irresistibly, that the change of state of the second ball from rest to motion, was caused by the first ball, as the motion of the first ball was caused by my hand.

We do not mean that our knowledge of cause is derived entirely from the case of voluntary activity, and then carried over by inference or analogy to other cases. This is an error to which we shall refer later on. But the case of voluntary causation is easier to understand, because a part of the process appears in consciousness.

We affirm that in every case where causation is simple enough to be readily traced, the conception of efficient cause is equally a necessary element of all such perceptions. For example, if I see a croquet-ball moved by a blow from another one, I cannot help believing that the first ball caused the mo- tion of the second. But a good deal of mechanical knowl- edge is required to trace the motion of a locomotive to the chemical energy of combustion; a child or a savage might well suppose its motions voluntary. Yet when any compli- cated machine is once understood, we cannot help tracing causation through every one of its parts.

" In our ordinary observation," says Lotze, "it is completely intuitive that a new motion is produced by the impartation of motion through a blow or impulse." (Dictate, Naturphiloso- phie, §17.)

We admit that we cannot perceive the efficient force going over from the cause to the object of its activity, nor explain

CAUSATION. 99

how it goes over. "The nature of efficiency," says Lotze, "is inexplicable." We cannot hear, feel, or taste causation, any more than we can see, hear, or feel time or space; all we per- ceive, in the plainest cases, is the cause in action, and the effect. Causation is intelligible, not sensible. But it is not for that reason any the less real. " The concept of efficiency " [ Wirkeri\, says Lotze, " is indispensable to our comprehension of nature [ Wdtauffassung^ and all attempts to deny the reality of efficiency and yet conceive the course of nature [ Weltlauf} are abortive." (Dictate, Metaphysik, §46.)

This "intuition" is irresistible because it is correct. This " necessary element of cognition " is a law of the mind because it corresponds to a law of the universe; and the mind, if it knows the world at all, must know it as it really is. Just as the mind perceives objects under space-relations because they ex- ist under space-relations.

A cause is an efficient antecedent, or an assemblage of such antecedents (for causes are rarely if ever single), not simply an inseparable antecedent.

But this is not all. Not only is causation real, but it is uni- form. The same causes, under the same circumstances, always produce the same effects. This axiom may be considered as a deduction from the axiom that causation is real efficiency, un- der the operation of the logical principle of identity. What- ever a thing is, that it will of course continue to be under the same circumstances. Whatever efficiency, active force, any- thing may have, that it will of course continue to have, under the same circumstances. If we see one ball pushed by another we cannot help believing that the first ball exerts actual power on the second, and that it will continue to do so, all things re- maining the same; that if the motion of the first continues, the motion of the second must continue also; that if the opera- tion be repeated under the same circumstances, the same re- sults will be repeated.

ioo THE INTELLECT.

This axiom is stated by some writers as a second " necessary cognition" or "intuitive idea," parallel with the first. Some also make it universal, referring to all events whatever Presi- dent Porter, for example, says: " we assert that the mind intui- tively believes that every event is caused, that is, every event is produced by the action of some agent or agents." But he directs his argument chiefly toward proof of the reality of cau- sation, and does not keep the two points rigidly separate, but sums up thus: "If it [causality] cannot be resolved into some other relation equally general or more general than itself, we must conclude that it is original, and intuitively discerned and believed." (Human Intellect, 572-73.) This does not discriminate between the two axioms.

It seems to us a decisive objection to this second axiom that it is a statement of a supposed general fact. According to our view of the necessary elements of cognition, the mind acts under them in connection with specific perceptions or thoughts. The mind knows space by knowing a material object under space-relations, because it cannot perceive such objects any other way. But it does not have intuitive knowledge of the fact that all matter exists under space-relations. We afterwards infer that fact as a ground of our knowledge of space-relations. So with causation; when we perceive a simple case of causa- tion, we necessarily know that there is efficient activity being exerted, and that this will continue to be exerted and will pro- duce the same results, under the same circumstances. Our own view is that this is involved in the " intuition " or " neces- sary idea " of causation as a real, active, efficiency; and that the universality of causation, or the truth that every event has a cause, is an inference on this basis from our experience.

Now it is admitted by philosophers of all schools that our belief in the reality of causation is original and irresistible to primitive thought. But many of them have held that this be-

CAUSATION. 101

lief, though irresistible, is fallacious. The whole sensational school, led by Hume, Brown, Mill, and Bain, declare that there is no more in causation than we perceive by the senses; that efficient causation is a figment of the mind; that invariable connection of antecedent and consequent is all that really ex- ists under that name in nature.

•'When a spark falls upon gunpowder," says Dr. Brown, " and kindles it into explosion, every one ascribes to the spark the power of kindling the inflammable mass. But let any one ask himself, what it is which he means by the term, and, without contenting himself with a few phrases that signify nothing, reflect, before he gives his answer, and he will find that he means nothing more than that, in all similar circumstances, the explosion of gunpowder will be the immediate and uniform consequence of the application of a spark." (Lecture 7, p. 68.)

Similar words might be quoted from many other writers. But the common-sense of mankind rejects the theory as inade- quate and idealistic, and will never accept it. Such skepticism will always be confined to philosophers, and even among them it is far from universal. Those who are not driven by the exi- gencies of a pre-assumed system, generally admit that the human mind is in some kind of correspondence with the universe, so that its normal action with reference to things must be correct.

The fact is that Hume, having determined beforehand to account for everything by experience, without any a priori or necessary principles of cognition, and finding the problem of causation insoluble on that theory, was obliged to discharge cause of all its real meaning in order to bring it within the scope of his theory.

So Dr. Brown, in the words of Sir W. Hamilton, " professes to explain the phenomenon of causality, but, previous to ex- planation, he evacuates the phenomenon of all that desiderates explanation." Their successors have pursued the same easy

102 THE INTELLECT.

method. But even Mr. Fiske, the celebrated evolutionist, ad- mits that they have gone too far.

" That matter, as objectively existing, may exert upon matter some constraining power, which, as forever unknowable by us, may be called an occulta vis, I readily grant. Thought is not the measure of things, and it was therefore unphilosophical in Hume to deny the existence of any such unknown power." (Cosmic Philosophy, I, 155.)

Writers of this class, however, usually bring back implicitly that which they have explicitly denied and expelled. For they all admit that the sequence of antecedent and consequent is invariable in nature, so that the course of nature can be un- derstood and predicted. Mr. Mill says in his Logic: "To certain facts, certain facts always do and as we believe always will succeed. The invariable antecedent is termed the cause, the invariable consequent the effect."

Now this invariability must have a ground or reason, and no ground for it can be conceived except reality of causation; all attempts to find another ground have failed. We shall refer to some of these attempts hereafter.

Having degraded " uniform causation " to " uniform suc- cession," these writers have sought for another formula for the ground of induction, the final axiom of all reasoning, and have found it in the phrase " uniformity of nature." Professor Bain declares that the uniformity of nature is known intuitively, and makes it the ultimate principle and postulate of all reasoning. Mr. Mill derives it from experience, though he makes it the basis of induction. But by thus leaving out causation from the axiom of causation, they have destroyed its validity. The complete uniformity of nature is by no means intuitively true. " That nature is uniform in her different departments and throughout her domain is by no means an instinctive belief. As intelligent and scientific, man has reached particular

CAUSATION. 105

uniformities, as of the seasons, of tides, of comets, only after such induction as each case seems to demand. This he has done, not on the ground of uniformity of nature, for the question in each particular case was whether nature would be uniform in that case, but solely on the ground of the uniform- ity of causation." (Hopkins, Outline Study of Man, 169.)

Mr. Mill, perhaps because his candor and fairness enabled him to see some of the difficulties of this subject which are lightly passed over by others of his school, seems to have fallen into some confusion of thought. Mr. Lewes mentions a remarkable instance of this. " That Mr. Mill was somewhat confused on this point, may be seen in his surprising conclu- sion that the orbital movement of a planet is not a case of causation." (Problems of Life and Mind, II, 340.) Again, Mill says in his Logic; " The uniformity in the succession of events, otherwise called the law of causation, must be received not as a law of the universe, but of that portion of it only which is within the range of our means of sure observation, with a reasonable degree of extension to adjacent cases." But the " uniformity of nature " is a very different thing from the "law of causation." In the words of Dr. McCosh; " The grand metaphysical question is not about the uniformity of nature, but about the relation of cause and effect."

On the subjective side of this theory, namely its method of accounting for our belief in causation, we find these writers generally agreed in attributing it to association.

Hume bluntly calls it the result of use and custom. Dr. Brown admits that there is an " original principle of our nature," which he calls " intuitive expectation," and that we believe in the causal connection of two events if we see them occur together only once, not merely from custom, but that the association is immediate and original.

Mr. Mill derives the belief by induction, and denies that it

104 THE INTELLECT.

extends further than induction carries it. " In distant parts of the stellar regions," he says, " where the phenomena may be entirely unlike those with which we are acquainted, it would be folly to affirm confidently that this general law prevails." But he bases induction in the last analysis on inseparable as- sociation, and so does not differ essentially from Hume.

We may perhaps admit that association and induction are competent to account for the idea of causation as these writ- ers understand it, mere invariability of succession in nature, without prejudicing the argument for real and uniform causa- tion. And it is not always easy to determine in which sense the term causation is used by them. What they attempt to account for by association, however, is the instinctive belief, which they declare to be fallacious, in the reality of causa- tion.

The association-theory on this point is open to a similar objection with their theory of space. It overlooks the most important point, containing the real thing to be explained, that every one of the experiences from which they say this belief is derived, really implies its existence in full force. If we see a ball move after being struck by another ball, the be- lief that the first has caused the motion of the second and would do so again in like circumstances, is just as irresistible on the first occasion as after a thousand repetitions.

Dr. Brown, indeed, escaped this difficulty, but since he de- nied the reality of causation, he was left in the position of affirming an intuitive principle of our nature, and yet denying its validity, a contradiction which should lead to universal skepticism; for if the very powers of the mind are fallacious, all knowledge and all reasoning must be impossible. Or rather, it" any philosopher declares that the faculties on which and with which he has built his system are deceptive, he can claim no value for the system.

CAUSATION. 105

Causation, then, subjectively considered, is a priori in the sense that it is a power and an irresistible tendency in the mind to cognize objective causation on proper occasion, as real and uniform; a congruity in this respect between the mind and the universe.

" A careful analysis of the causal judgment, as it is styled, reveals the fact that it is not a necessary inference, but a posi- tive affirmation of a fact. Its true test is self-evidence, and nothing but a perceived fact can be self-evident." (Professor Ormond, Princeton Rev., 1882.)

And Mr. Lewes says; " All believe irresistibly in particular acts of causation. Few believe in universal causation; and those few not till after considerable reflection."

It may also be truly said, in a certain sense, that our knowl- edge of causation is derived from experience, for it is only in and through experience that we know anything about it, and when we say that causation is universal or that nature is uni- form, we are generalizing from experience.

We have said that our knowledge of what causation is, as involving real efficient power, is derived from or rather given in our own sense of voluntary muscular exertion. Some writ- ers, especially the Frenchman, Maine de Biran, have attempted to show that our belief in the reality, necessity, and uniform- ity of causation, is derived by inference and induction from this subjective experience, that is, our volition. But this theory is open to the following objections.

(i) Induction itself must rest on some axiom not derived from experience: namely, as we shall show in the proper place, the axiom that causation is uniform, which is either a part of the "causal judgment" or an immediate deduction from it. But the theory professes to account for this very axiom by in- duction. (2) This theory, if adopted, is inevitably pushed to the conclusion that all causation is spiritual and there are no

106 THE INTELLECT.

material causes; that matter has no inherent forces: hence that there is but one agent in the universe, the Creator, who causes all events directly and voluntarily, conclusions almost uni- versally rejected by philosophy as well as common sense.

(3) Muscular exertion, or "volition/' is a case of physical causation, and subject to the " causal judgment,5' the " int ui- tion " of the reality and uniformity of causation, as much as any other. If I roll a ball against another, and the second ball is moved, I have an " intuition " or " necessary judgment " that the motion of the second ball is caused by the first, and that the motion of the first ball is caused by my hand, and that the motion of my hand is caused by myself, ego; how the motion passes over through the series is unknown. The only difference between the cases is that in one the proc- ess is given partly in consciousness and paiily in perception, in the other it appears only in perception. The spiritual prin- ciple of volition or " choice," has nothing to do with either. This runs up into a higher realm, and introduces to us a new kind of causation, where the effect is a spiritual, si ate and the cause an inexplicable act of personal will.

Some celebrated theories concerning causation demand a brief discussion. Sir W. Hamilton has discussed the theories of causation with his usual learning and vigor. He has made a list of eight possible theories; but as (according to President Porter) the division is more ingenious than correct, we do not copy it. His own doctrine is derived from that of Kant, and is too abstruse to be given fully here, but belongs rather to meta- physics. According to this view, when an object is presented to us, we necessarily know it as existing, and cannot conceive of it as non-existent in the past or the future; yet we know from experience that it did have a beginning in its present form. It is impossible to conceive either the beginning or annihilation of any part of the complement of existence

CAUSATION. 107

possessed by any object. " But to say that a thing previously existed under different forms, is only in other words to say, that a thing had causes." (Metaphysics, Bowen's ed., 554.)

It is evident that this doctrine of the constancy of the sum of existence, either in the universe or in one object, is a vast as- sumption. It is only another form of one of the latest and most sweeping, not to say most doubtful, of the inductions of modern science. (See Bowne's Metaphysics, 107.)

Again, this theory assumes, as Hamilton expressly declares, two intuitive ideas or forms of thought, existence and time. It also requires the principle of the impotence of the mind, and the law of the conditioned, "the law that the conceivable has always two opposite extremes, and that the extremes are equally inconceivable." If causation really exists in nature, it is far more simple and natural to suppose that it is intelligible, knowable by the human mind directly.

Hamilton's own " law of parcimony," otherwise known as "Occam's razor," "which forbids, without necessity, the multi- plication of entities, powers, principles, or causes," cuts down his theory of causation. It is simpler to assume it at once, as a fourth necessary element in cognition, with being, time, and space, than to assume so much from which to derive it.

The most ingenious attempt to explain away the reality of efficient causation is the monadology of Leibnitz. This theory, indeed, was intended to explain also the union of soul and body, the nature of animal and vegetable life, and all the other mysteries, physical and theological, of the universe. A monad, according to Leibnitz, is one of the ultimate elements of ex- istence, either physical or spiritual; a supersensual entity, neither a pure, hard atom, nor a mere idea, nor an immaterial spirit, but partaking of all three natures. These monads were created by the Supreme Power all different, and each one en- dowed with active force. " The Deity conferred upon his

io8 THE INTELLECT.

creatures from the first a certain measure of efficiency, which is the ultimate principle of all the various phenomena that they produce." Hence the career of each monad is predetermined, and it pursues its own course from the beginning, with the ap- pearance of exerting and receiving efficient activity, but with- out the reality of it.

Monads, on this theory, are of different orders, correspond- ing to different orders of being, from a stone to a human body and soul. In a crystal, or a plant, or an animal body, there is a governing monad, or one which is said to govern, because "all the others act together harmoniously, as if they were directed by one central power." In the lower orders sensation and thought are latent, "in the human soul they rise to full consciousness."

This strange mixture of physics and metaphysics seems too fantastic to be seriously offered as an explanation of causation or of the relation between soul and body, and is indeed no longer so put forward. But it contains some very remarkable anticipations of recent scientific theories. It rests on the doctrine of continuity; each monad pursues its career without a break; there can be no leaps or sudden transitions in nature. " What is called the uniformity of physical law is never broken." But this is equivalent to modern evolutionism. Again, the recent doctrine of heat as a mode of molecular motion pre- supposes molecules like Leibnitz's monads, full of spontaneous, active force. And Darwin's " cell-gemmules " and Herbert Spencer's " physiological units " are only Leibnitzian monads of a higher order. " They are now held up as the most ad- vanced results of inductive science, or, if you will, as the sup- posed limits or goals, toward which the sciences depending on observation and analysis are tending and preparing the way. But to the eagle-eyed thought of Leibnitz, they were necessary deductions from the single axiom, first propounded by him as

CAUSATION. 109

dominating the universe of existing things, the principle of suf- ficient reason." (Bowen, Modern Philosophy, 118-125.)

''Pre-established Harmony" is the phrase which describes Leibnitz' substitute for causation.

Another celebrated theory to account for all things, and es- pecially the interaction of bodies with one another, and of mind with matter, is that of Monism. This is the doctrine that all real being is one, and all apparently separate entities, or elements, or atoms, are but manifestations of this being "which alone is self-existent, and in which all things have their being. . . . This being, as fundamental, we call the infinite, the absolute, and the independent. In- calling it the infinite we do not mean that it excludes the co-existence of the finite, but only that it is the self-sufficient source of the finite. In call- ing it the absolute, we do not exclude it from all relation, but deny only external restriction and determination. Everything else has its cause and reason in this being." (Bowne, Meta- physics, 131.)

Lotze (whom Professor Bowne follows rather closely), says that it is impossible consistently to conceive of interaction be- tween two elements which are independent of one another, self-existent. *• The states of a cannot go out to b, and vice versa, ... If action at all is to be made to seem pos- sible, this assumption of the self-existence of things must be utterly denied. . . . And this can only be accomplished through the assumption that all individual things are substan- tially one, . . . that they are from the beginning modifi- cations of one single being, which we provisionally designate by the names, the Infinite, the Absolute. . . . Action be- tween two finite beings is thus only apparent, not real. In reality the Absolute acts upon itself." (Dictate, Metaph. §48.)

This theory is evidently at the opposite pole from that of Leibnitz, and incurs the danger of lapsing into pantheism. In

no THE INTELLECT.

this extreme form its most celebrated modern supporters have been Spinoza, Schelling, and Hegel. Many, however, profess to hold it in a sense consistent with the personality of God.

Aristotle divided causes into four kinds, a distinction often referred to in philosophy, and with which the student should be familiar. They are (i) material cause, or that out of which anything is made; (2) formal cause, or the form, idea, arche- type, or pattern of a thing: (3) efficient cause, or the principle of change or motion which produces the thing; (4) final cause, or the end or purpose for which a thing is made. (Fleming.)

Efficient cause, the third in the order above, is of course that which we have been discussing. The fourth, final cause, or design in nature, must be briefly noticed.

TELEOLOGY.

The doctrine of final causes, or design in nature, commonly called Teleology, has been the subject of much discussion in recent years. Formerly, nearly all philosophers held that the adaptations found throughout nature, by which the parts of the universe minister to one another, working together in a chain of causation, are proof that the scheme of things has been planned by intelligence as well as upheld by power.

"I had rather believe," said Lord Bacon, ""all the fables in the Legend and the Talmud and the Alcoran, than that this universal frame is without a mind. . . . For while the mind of man looketh upon second causes scattered, it may sometimes rest in them, and go no further; but when it be- holdeth the chain of them, confederate and linked together, it must needs fly to Providence and the Deity/' (Essay 16.)

In more recent times, the progress of physical science, in- troducing the conceptions of law, uniformity, development, and evolution, has weakened the belief in design, and has been supposed to weaken the argument for it. Indeed, some scien- tific men have undertaken a polemic against the teleological con-

TELEOLOGY. 1 1 1

ception, which they have carried on in a spirit that has merited and received the name of " teleophobia."

No doubt there have been some crude statements of the theory of design in nature. Sometimes the whole universe has been subordinated to human interests, and sometimes a specific purpose has been assumed, such as a mere display of power, or the pleasure of the Creator, in creative action. But "it is especially necessary that those who oppose teleology should deal with its scientific [well-reasoned] forms, and should not waste their attacks upon forms which have never kept up with the advance of the investigation." (Euken.)

A correct statement of the doctrine of design is not at all affected by the progress of science, the extension of the realm of causation, or the hypothesis of evolution. But rather, the more all natural events are seen to be joined together in a single scheme, the more wonderful does that scheme become, and the more the mind " must needs fly to Providence and the Deity." The old view of nature saw in it a number of separate kingdoms, and a series of separate creations. The modern view, after extending the boundaries of each one of these kingdoms almost indefinitely, joins them all in a vast unity. But the vastness of this unity, does not, as some seem to suppose, make it self-existent, without an intelligent design or Cause; nor does this remove it from human thought any further than before.

Teleology has nothing to do with efficient causation, but belongs to a higher sphere of thought. The positive argu. ment for design in nature, as for the existence of an intelli- gent, personal Creator, belongs to Natural Theology.

ti2 THE INTELLECT.

IV. IDENTITY AND SIMILARITY.

The fact was mentioned in introducing the subject of sen- sation that the activity of the mind in sensation is a discrimi- nating one. The very process by which an impression be- comes known to the mind, that is, becomes a sensation in the lull sense of the word, is a change in consciousness, in other words a conscious change in the sentinent organism. But this implies two states, not identical but different, and either similar or dissimilar; involving not only an impression occa- sioned by some object, but a knowledge of something about that impression.

" We know that if the idea of red and at the same time the idea of blue are excited in the mind, the two do not combine to form the idea of violet. . . . Every comparison, es- pecially every relation between two elements, presupposes that both points of relation remain separate, and that a represent- ing activity passes from one to the other, and the mind be- comes conscious of the change which it experiences from the ideaof a to that of £. We do this when we compare red with blue, and there arises the new idea of qualitative similarity which we ascribe to both. If we see at the same time a strong light and a weak one, we do not have the sensation of a single light which is the sum of both; but both remain separate, and, passing from one to the other, we are conscious of another change of state, a quantitative more-or-less of the same im- pression.

" Finally, if two axactly similar impressions are separately made upon us, they do not blend into a third; but because we compare them as before and in the transition from one to the other find no change of state, there arises in us the new idea of identity.

"These new ideas which we may consider as of a higher or-

IDENTITY AND SIMILARITY. 113

der, are by no means resultants of the interaction of the origi- nal simple ideas, as in mechanics a third motion is com- pounded of two others. The first ideas, as mere impulses, arouse in the mind a reaction, through which arise the new ideas ©f similarity, identity, and their opposites." (Lotze, Dictate, Psychologie, §21-22.)

These two principles, identity with its inseparable correla- tive diversity, and similarity with its inseparable correlative dissimilarity, are necessary forms of all knowledge, in its most rudimentary form of simple sensation, or the elaborately com- bined and associated form of acquired perception. " Saying what a thing is, is saying what it is like, what class it belongs to." (H. Spencer, Psychology, II, 131.)

Simple perception may know an object as distinct from self, as having real being, and as existing under space-relations. But complete perception knows an object as the same or dif- ferent, similar or dissimilar with others; recognizes it as be- longing to a new class, or as a new object hitherto unknown.

This is often called the relativity of knowledge, a phrase which is used, however, in a great variety of meanings. Mr. Mill means by it the doctrine, " that we only know any- thing as distinguished from something else; that two objects are the smallest number required to constitute consciousness; that a thing is only seen to be what it is by contrast with what it is not." But we hold it self-evident that the mind can per- ceive one object alone, distinguished only from the ego.

Sometimes the relativity of knowledge means the doctrine that we can only know objects so far as they are related to our faculties, and so far as we have faculties of knowledge. This no one will deny, but it should be called, as Dr. McCosh sug- gests, "the limited knowledge of man," not "relativity."

Sir W. Hamilton applies this name to the Kantian doc- trine that we can never know the ultimate reality of thinrs

0

ii4 THE INTELLECT.

the thing-in-itself, but only phenomena, which phenomena may, for all we know, be partly due to the action of our minds. This is sheer assumption. The thing-in-itself, apart from its phenomena or attributes, is not only unknowable but impossi- ble. We do know the true reality of an object, through its qualities, so far as we know it at all. Again, " To suppose that in perception or cognition proper we mix elements de- rived from our subjective stores, is to unsettle our whole con- victions as to the reality of things. By assuming this middle place between Reid and Kant, this last of the great Scottish metaphysicians has been exposed to the fire of the opposing camps of idealism and realism." (McCosh, Defence of Fundamental Truth 234.)

The last-mentioned meaning of "relativity of knowledge" is probably the most common one, and the most appropriate. But some writers confuse this meaning with the one first mentioned, and it would be well if so ambiguous a phrase could be ban- ished from philosophy.

Many writers also confuse the application of the principles of identity and similarity to sensation, as being a change of consciousness, and their application to perception, as a cogni- tion of an object that is different from self, and similar or dis- similar with other objects. The distinction is a clear one and is worth making.

These principles are necessary laws of intelligence, so far as we can know anything about intelligence in our present state of being. Accordingly we find that the minds of the lower ani- mals act under the same conditions. If you strike a dog several blows, he knows that they are not all one and the same blow. There are involved here, then, time, number, and identity- diversity. If the dog sees you or any one else pick up a similar stick on another occasion, he knows this stick is like the other one, and expects the like pain, which he runs

IDENTITY AND SIMILARITY. 115

away to avoid. His knowledge may be merely association, but it involves the principles of similarity and of self, just as truly as the feelings of pain, fear, and hatred.

In short, all sensations and perceptions which take place in a material organism and give knowledge of material things, take place under the relations of identity-diversity or similar- ity-difference; which, therefore, viewed in connection with the mind, may be called categories, or a priori concepts, or intuitive ideas; and viewed in connection with things may be called relations. (The word relation, however, is often used in a quite different meaning, as when gravity is said to be a "relation" between two bodies.) Not conditions of the ex- istence of things, but conditions of things as related to us. We call them, with space, time, and cause, necessary elements of cognition, but do not assign precisely the same origin or scope to each.

Professor Bain has founded his entire system on these prin- ciples. "The primary attributes of intellect are (i) conscious- ness of difference, (2) consciousness of agreement, and (3) re- tentiveness. Every properly intellectual function involves one or more of these attributes and nothing else." (Mental Science, 82). He elsewhere defines agreement by similarity, and uses the term identity, while he develops " retentiveness," into the power of association. He strives, with great ingenuity, to show how, with these, the whole structure of knowledge is built up.

We have seen reason to believe that he has but little success in accounting for space, time, or cause, as subjective principles. But it is especially to be remarked as an important inconsist- ency in this scheme, that it really assumes original and neces- sary principles just as truly as the opposite theory, which Bain so vigorously combats. The only difference is that it does not assume so many of them.

The question in what identity consists, has received a good

n6 THE INTELLECT.

deal of attention. Different kinds of identity have been dis- tinguished; as identity of a stone or any inorganic substance, of a tree, an animal, of a person. It is plain that identity of an organized being cannot consist in absolute sameness of mate- rial particles, for these are constantly changing; besides, a tree may lose many of its branches and leaves, and yet be the same tree, and a man who has lost an arm or a leg is still the same man.

John Locke held that identity in plants and animals consists in continuance of the same organization, and that life consists in that organization in which all the parts minister to one another. (Essay, Bk. II. C. 27, §4.) This comes very near to the modern doctrine that " the phenomena of living bodies can be explained by the mechanical and chemical forces be- longing to matter." It also approaches the modern definition of an organism as "a structure in which all the parts are mut- ually means and ends."

Personal identity is still more difficult of definition. Con- sciousness, in connection with memory, testifies to the reality of personal identity, and declares that the subject of past ex- periences is the same with the subject of present memory and present experience. "As the knowledge of personality is given in consciousness, that of personal identity is secured by the aid of memory." (Calderwood.)

Locke makes personal identity to consist in consciousness. But this is insufficient, as is shown by the extravagances into which he is led by it. For he says: "It must be allowed that if the same consciousness can be translated from one thinking substance to another, it will be possible that two thinking sub- stances may make but one person." . . " But if it be possible for the same man to have distinct, incommunicable consciousness at different times, it is past doubt that the same man would at different times make different persons." He

NECESSARY ELEMENTS OF COGNITION. 117

also argues that if we suppose two distinct consciousnesses acting in the same body, one by night the other by day, the day-man and the night-man would be two as distinct per- sons as Socrates and Plato. (Essay, Bk. II, C. 27, §23.)

The fact is, everybody knows by his own experience what is meant by identity, though nobody can define it or say exactly in what it consists.

The relation of Similarity is capable of analysis, and has been divided by Mr. Herbert Spencer, and provided with a characteristic nomenclature. His disciple, Mr. John Fiske, states it as follows. Similarity and dissimilarity are divided into: (i) "cointension and non-cointension, as when we per- ceive that two sounds are equal in degree of loudness," or that two temperatures are different; (2) "co-extension and non- co-extension, as when " the color of an orange is recognized as accompanied " by sweetness and not by viscidity; " (3) " con- nature and non-connature, as when greater warmth is mentally assimilated to less warmth, but distinguished from blueness or roughness." (Cosmic Philosophy, II, 118.)

GENERAL REMARKS ON THE NECESSARY ELEMENTS OF COGNITION.

Next to the theory of vision, that department of psychology which has made the greatest progress is this, the doctrine of "a priori concepts," "intuitive ideas," or, as we prefer to call them, necessary elements of cognition. It is also to be noted that this is the border-land between psychology and metaphy- sics.

The doctrine of "intuitive ideas" was vigorously assailed by John Locke. But the mode of the attack, and also of the de- fence, shows how ill-reasoned, vague, and incorrect were some modes of thought current at that time, and, indeed, not wholly unknown even at the present day.

n8 THE INTELLECT.

One of the so-called intuitive truths on which Locke spends his strength most freely, is the fact that a thing cannot be and not be at the same time. To the modern reader this proposi- tion, however true, seems of a very different rank. For it is plainly a logical rule, amounting to this, that contradictory at- tributes are not to be predicated of the same subject. Locke proves that the rule does not exist consciously and formally in the mind of the ignorant, the child, or any but a philosopher; which is not at all the same thing as proving that they do not think under the rule, when they think correctly.

The argument for the a priori cognition of space, time, and cause, as at present understood, is not affected by Locke's rea- soning. He himself, moreover, in the positive, constructive, part of his Essay, tacitly assumes principles of thought which are called a priori or intuitive by more modern and more sys- tematic writers.

Locke's polemic was of vast importance in philosophy, and was in a sense completely successful. But, far from settling the question, it led the way to better definitions, more careful thought, and deeper study. The two schools still keep up their traditional opposition, but each has partly shifted to the other's ground, and sensationalism must be said to have lost the battle.

The more recent empirical philosophers, who consider them- selves the special followers of Locke, have attempted to ac- count for space, time, and cause, subjectively considered, with- out admitting any necessary or a priori elements of cognition. We have already examined this attempt in connection with the subjects of causation and space.

It is important to notice that writers of this school, while denying intuitive ideas, yet rely upon some principles of thought which are really of the same order. Professor Bain not only, as we have seen, admits a knowledge of identity and similarity as original to the mind, but also declares that the

NECESSARY ELEMENTS OF COGNITION. 119

uniformity of nature is an innate principle. " We can give no reason, or evidence, for this uniformity, and, therefore, the course seems to be to adopt this as the finishing postulate. And undoubtedly, there is no other issue possible." (Logic, 671.)

Mr. Mill cannot perhaps be quoted so specifically to the same effect; but in his Logic his statements are often qualified by such phrases as "it is more rational to suppose," and "with a reasonable degree of extension to other cases." And " the observant student notices that in the most important portions of his discussions he is ever and anon introducing, with a naive innocency of bearing, at once refreshing and irritating, under the names of ' belief,' ' persuasion,' ' natural prompt- ing,' and the like, the very a priori, universal, organic, rational, and recreative element, which he would exclude, and which he then seeks to make it appear that he has deduced, either strictly, or, in his phrase, (a strange phrase for a logician to employ) ' as far as any human purpose requires,' from pure observation and ' objective,' physico-psychological ' experi- ence.' " (Morris, British Thought and Thinkers, 325.)

Mr. Herbert Spencer recognizes the impossibility of ac- counting for these principles by association alone, and ad- vances the theory that they are the product of association and inheritance combined. This has been called the " psycho- genetical hypothesis," by Mr. Lewes who speaks of "inherited intuitions," and '• laws of thought registered in modifications of structure which have been transmitted from parent to child." But this theory does not escape the chief difficulty of the theory of association pure and simple. It only gives a longer time for association to work in, and does not at all show how it can have any power at any time to evolve a necessary prin- ciple of thought. What is to be accounted for is not the con- crete knowledge of space, time, cause, etc., but the fact that

120 THE INTELLECT.

the mind cannot help acting under these forms and categories in perception and thought, even in the lowest stages of mental life.

" In the contest over this concept, the question is not about something known previous to experience. . . . Just as little do we dispute about a something ready-made in the mind, for we recognize here only a striving activity. . . . But we discuss as the main question, not only of philosophy, but of all science, and of psychology especially, the fact that in mental activity something essential, original, and legitimate is recognized. It shows that one is behind the times in his knowledge of modern philosophy, if he presents the dilemma whether knowledge is furnished ready-made in the mind or is created from without, for he thus leaves out of considera- tion the question to the development and defence of which the most prominent thinkers of the last century have devoted their strength." (Euken, Fundamental Concepts, translation, 90.)

Association can do nothing to account for these principles of cognition, thus received and denned, even though it be prolonged backward through the endless ages of evolution. The limits of association were tacitly admitted by Mr. Mill when he admitted that on that basis two and two might possi- bly equal five.

In short, there is no safe ground between the bold sensa- tional theory of Condillac, which resolved all states of the mind into sensations by simply calling them such, and a rea- sonable recognition of a necessary element in thought and perception; "for Hume did certainly show that a consistent empiricism must become sensational, and Kant, that experience, in Locke's sense, involves a multitude of a priori elements." (Bowne, Metaphysics, 508.)

On the other hand, the so-called a priori school have greatly changed their ground since the time of Locke, made impor-

NECESSARY ELEMENTS OF COGNITION. 121

tant concessions and introduced valuable distinctions. The more recent method is thus expressed by President Porter. " While these truths stand first in the order of thought, they are last to be reached in the order of time. This implies that we are, in some sense, indebted to experience for their ac- quisition. It is equally clear that experience does not give them authority." (Human Intellect, 504.) First uncon- sciously but necessarily used in concrete perception and thought, they are afterwards abstracted and generalized into laws or principles.

It was formerly the custom (and some traces of the custom still remain), to treat these principles all in a lump, assuming that they are all alike in origin and nature. We have shown above how, in our opinion they should be treated each by itself. We append a table of these principles, with the connection in which each is first exercised and known.

1. Being, or substance, or real existence; Through any perception that gives knowledge of the external world. We spoke of this under the Qualities of Matter.

2. Self; Through any mental activity. We spoke of this under Consciousness.

3. Space; Through any real perception involving voluntary exertion.

4. Time; Through the series of states of consciousness.

5. Cause; Through resistance and the perception of ac- tion.

6. Identity and similarity are relations conditional to all knowledge.

Of the others which are frequently enumerated, number and quantity need no exposition, and are merely relations of objects; right belongs to ethics; the infinite and the absolute to metaphysics; the idea of God to theology; the idea of beauty to esthetics.

122 THE INTELLECT.

It will have been noticed that we are not satisfied with the usual names applied to these principles. The term "intui- tion " is objectionable because it has come to have a vague and semi-mysterious implication, as though intuition were a short road to knowledge, a superhuman way of attaining to truth. It is true, however, that the real meaning of the word intuition is not open to the same objections. It means, " im- mediate knowledge, direct perceiving or beholding of an ob- ject or principle " (Calderwood); " the immediate affirmation by the intellect, that the predicate does or does not pertain to the subject, in what are called self-evident propositions." (Hamilton.) The corresponding German word (Anschauung) is constantly used, since Kant, to denote perception under the forms of time and space. " Intuition," therefore, is a word liable to misunderstanding at best.

The term "a priori concept" has some evident advantages; but these principles are active in cognition long before they become concepts at all, which, indeed, they need not do to be useful, but only to become authenticated. The term "idea" is too vague and uncertain for use in philosophy, and has never recovered from being overworked by John Locke.

The term " principle " is perhaps without serious objection; but the phrase "necessary element" seems to suit better our view that the mind operates under certain conditions, some of which are imposed upon it by its intimate connection with a physical organism, some by the nature of the objects of its knowledge, and some by the nature of all thought.

Sir W. Hamilton has enumerated no less than twenty-three different names which have been applied to these principles by different writers.

is THERE A "REGULATIVE FACULTY?"

Since the time of Coleridge it has been common among English writers to use the name of Reason for a supposed

NECESSARY ELEMENTS OF COGNITION. 123

faculty of producing " intuitive ideas." Sir W. Hamilton em- ployed the term Regulative Faculty.

If our analysis has been correct, this theory of a special faculty is untenable and unnecessary. The mind in each of its kinds of activity must act under certain conditions, and must evolve whateVer products the conditions and objects of its ac- tivity require. When the mind knows an external object, it knows it in space, and cannot know it otherwise. There is no need of a special faculty to produce the space, nor is space a product of the mind, but a necessary condition of material existence, and hence inseparable from preception. So the mind when it judges, must judge according to the relations of identity and similarity, and can judge in no other way, for these are conditions of all judgment.

To find out what these principles are, and distinguish them, and show their universality, is the work of generalization and analysis, exercising the various other powers of the mind.

If any one affirms that he is conscious of forming these ideas or applying them by a special faculty, we can only say that we can detect no such power in ourselves, and, according to our theory, it is unnecessary.

CRITERIA OF FIRST PRINCIPLES.

We need some standard or rule of judgment by which to decide what principles are entitled to places on our list. It has already been intimated that the chief criterion is necessity. The intellect is " constrained by the spontaneous workings of its nature to receive them as true." (Porter.) It is not meant by this that their reality and validity are never denied in terms, but that those who deny them and try to disprove them, make use of them in the very process of their reasoning. Nor are these principles used only by philosophers. As all who speak at all must speak according to some kind of grammatical rules, even though they do not know what grammar means, so all

124 THE INTELLECT.

who think or perceive must do so under the forms, laws, or categories appropriate to each act, whether they can or cannot define and describe them. f Few reach that speculative stage where these principles become definite, generalized concepts, and most who do so are pledged to one school or another long before reaching so advanced a stage of thought. But "we are justified in appealing from the philosophy of men to their words and actions. What all men inadvertently confess in their casual assertions, what they imply in the very form of their language, . . what is assumed in all investigations and reasonings without the attempt to give any reasons for its truth, these are all taken [by us] to be or to involve univer- sal and necessary truths of Intuition, however difficult it may be to define them correctly, to reconcile them with the dicta of a received philosophy, or to show their place in any order of systematic arrangement." (Porter, Hum. Intel. 510.) We have applied this method of reasoning, to some extent, to the doctrines of Mr. Mill and Professor Bain.

We have attempted to show in discussing each of these principles that it is a necessary principle, and we judge that to be the only and sufficient criterion. Many writers, however, have laid down three or more criteria. President Porter gives three, universality, necessity, and logical dependence and origi- nality. Dr. Cocker gives five, self-evidence, originality, sim- plicity, necessity, and universality. Sir W. Hamilton lays down but one, which he calls by the double name of univer- sality and necessity, and says that it was first proved by Lei- bnitz. It is evident that necessity alone is sufficient if it can be proved; also that universality can hardly be susceptible of complete proof, though an approximation to such proof would go far to raise a presumption of necessity. Various other cri- teria are thus useful for proving necessity, and may be called tributary to the one true and sufficient criterion, necessity.

DOCTRINE OF PERCEPTION. 125

DOCTRINE OF PERCEPTION.

We are now in a position to state our view of perception in a connected way, with the proper limitations and distinctions.

The lowest and simplest form of mental action is sensation. Note the term, mental action. Some writers held that sensa- tions are impressions, which combine themselves, transform themselves, interpret themselves, evolve out of themselves not only knowledge but consciousness. We hold that the simplest sensation is an act, a function, and implies an actor, a subject; that knowledge pre-supposes some one who knows, who has interpreted sensations into knowledge under the necessary forms and categories of thought.

A sensation requires an ego as a condition of its existence, and involves a knowledge or feeling of this ego. Some writers use the term sensation in a narrower sense, to denote only the impression of the sense-organ, and say that we are conscious of our sensations, or unconscious of them, as the case may be, and that having a sensation and knowing that we have it are two different things. This use of the term is objectionable.

The method of sensation is discrimination between different states of consciousness, implying the action and the validity of the categories of identity and similarity.

It is probable that the adult mind never experiences a sim- ple sensation, wholly separate from others and unaccompanied by associative suggestion. Our simple sensations become firmly connected with one another and with various ideas, in- terpretations, feelings, imaginations, etc., so that when they are repeated, or even when similar ones are experienced, a great deal of knowledge is revived or suggested by association, be- yond that which is conveyed directly by the single sensation in point. This is called acquired or cultivated perception.

When the sense-organ is voluntarily moved or modified to

126 THE INTELLECT.

adapt it to the object, as in rolling the eye or moving ine fingers, simple natural perception of the external world takes place. We perceive it directly, under the category of being, by an inexplicable act of the mind, as something real, existing outside of us. This is the true meaning of the term substance. What the object is in its qualities, what its properties are, we learn by interpretation of the sensations occasioned by it.

We also, in this kind of perception, know the external ob- ject under the form of space, under space relations, as exist- ing in space. " External world " means, normally, objects ex- ternal to the particular sense-organ; and the other parts of the body are at first perceived .and explored just the same as other objects. Later on in our experience a distinction is estab- lished between the body and the rest of the external world.

When we exercise or resist force we recognize self or the moving object as a cause; that is, we know it as the cause of the change which has occurred, in addition to perceiving it as being and as being in space; and we know this cause not as mere succession, but as actual efficiency acting uniformly. Some writers hold that our belief in causation as real efficiency is a result of long-continued association. But they also hold that real efficiency is a delusion, that there is no connection of events in nature but invariable succession.

THEORIES OF PERCEPTION.

We shall now briefly describe some of the more noted theories -of perception, in the historical method. But some preliminary remarks and definitions will be necessary.

A distinction must be drawn between the metaphysical part of a theory of perception and the psychological part, though they are in practice inseparable. The psychological part has been more backward in development, and has indeed been for the most part a late product. It is only in recent times that light and sound have been correctly understood, and

THEORIES OF PERCEPTION. 127

hence a correct doctrine of the most important sensations has been beyond the reach of all but very recent philosophers. Indeed, the psychological part of perception may perhaps be all brought under the theory of vision. It has even been said that "theories of sense-perception are to a great extent theo- ries of vision." (Porter.)

The sense of sight is so complicated, involving not only a special sensibility to light and color, but so many different kinds of muscular sensation, that it presents for study a won- derful combination of phenomena, optical, physiological, and mental. Accordingly, since the true theory of vision has been established and almost universally accepted, many im- portant questions concerning perception may be regarded as settled.

But by the term " theory of perception " is usually meant, theory of the knowledge of the external world in perception. This has been in dispute among philosophers from the earliest times. How mind can come into contact with matter, how knowledge and thought arise in consequence of the presence of an external object, how much the mind contributes and how much the object, these difficult, probably insoluble questions, constitute the metaphysical part of a theory of per- ception.

The solution of these questions has always been seriously affected by the condition of philosophy at the time, the reign- ing metaphysical and theological dogmas of an age usually permeating all its speculations.

A preliminary classification of theories is necessary. These fall into two great classes, theories of immediate or presenta- tive perception, and theories of mediate or representative per- ception. This distinction refers to the psychological process, not to the physical one; to what goes on in the mind, not what goes on in the air or the ether or the nerve.

Immediate, presentative, or intuitive perception denotes a

128 THE INTELLECT.

direct knowledge of the object in perception. This object, however, may be held to be either real or ideal, a real exter. nal object according to the natural belief of men, or a sub- jective ideal object, a phenomenon in or of the mind. Those who hold the object to be externally real may be called real- ists, as believing in a material, external, extended object; or natural realists as holding the natural, primary opinion con- cerning the external world; or natural dualists as opponents of the theory of monism or absolute identity.

Those who deny the reality of the external object may be called idealists as opposed to realists, or as believing in noth- ing but ideas; or monists as believing in the absolute identity of the subject and object, the unity of the universal essence.

Idealists, again, may differ in various ways, holding that the mind and the object are both ideal, being correlated phases of the same essence; or that the mind is the author of all its own perceptions; or that all perceptions are infused in the mind by the immediate act of a supernatural power.

These two theories, natural realism and idealism, are, says Sir W. Hamilton, "the only systems worthy of a philosopher; for, as they alone have any foundation in consciousness, so they alone have any consistency in themselves."

The representative theory of perception may be said to be a mixture of the other two. Those who hold to it believe in the reality of the external world, yet deny that we can know it except by inference. They may thus be called cosmothetic idealists, or hypothetical realists. They all hold that the object* in perception is not the external object itself, but a representa- tion or idea or image of it in the mind. Obviously the source and nature of this image may be the subject of various sub- sidiary hypotheses.

Sir W. Hamilton has drawn out these distinctions to the last degree of tenuity. (Philosophy, Wight's ed., 264. Metaphysics, Bowen's ed., 352.)

HISTORICAL SKETCH. 129

HISTORICAL SKETCH.

It is important for the student to gain some acquaintance with the greatest names in philosophy and their relative great- ness and position. Hence our sketch, though necessarily very brief, will not be confined strictly to theories of perception.

We pass over the earliest Greek philosophers, about whom little is really known.

PLATO, (429-347 B. c.) the greatest writer and thinker of antiquity, was not a system-maker, and it is not easy to decide from his dialogues what his real opinions were. He made a distinction between two kinds of knowledge, that of the senses, which he held to be illusive and untrustworthy, and that of the intellect, which he held to be certain, lofty, and rational. He has been called an idealist, but that is on ac- count of his doctrine of ideas, and not with reference to his doctrine of perception; for he taught that sensation is a joint product of the action of the external object and the sentient agent. He did not, however assign a definite part to each of these elements in perception.

Plato is remarkable for the beauty and versatility and dra- matic power of his style; for the vast range of his intellectual activity; for his surprising anticipations of modern discoveries and theories; for his insight into moral and religious truth, and his firm belief in the unity and goodness of God; and for his wonderfully stimulating power over many of the finest minds in all subsequent ages.

ARISTOTLE, (384-322 B. c.) made advances in the knowl- edge of the operation of the senses, especially vision, in which he approached wonderfully near to the modern theory that vision depends on the vibrations of an invisible medium. It has always been in dispute, however, whether Aristotle meant that perception is through a corporeal emanation from the ol>-

130 THE INTELLECT.

ject, thus anticipating modern scientific knowledge in the case of sight and hearing, or that perception is through a mental form, an incorporeal impression, thus anticipating some of the modern representationists.

Aristotle held to a common or general sense, underlying all the special senses, for which some recent writers use, in Eng- lish, the term "coenaesthesis." He also taught that imagination (phantasy) pictures and retains before the mind the impressions of sense, thus being a condition of memory.

He opposed reason to sense, teaching " that sense is re- stricted and individual, thought free and universal; and that while sense deals with the concrete and material aspect of phenomena, reason deals with the abstract and ideal. But while reason is thus in itself the source of general ideas, it is so only potentially " it requires sense-presentations which it M unifies and interprets." (Wallace, Outlines of Philosophy of Aristotle, 91).

Aristotle is remarkable as the author of the science of formal logic, which has received no substantial improvements since his day; for his interest in every department of physical science and the zeal with which he examined and classified natural objects; for his practical and political wisdom; for the wonder- ful ascendancy of his influence and the unreasoning deference paid to his authority throughout many centuries of the Chris- tian era, after the re-discovery of his works.

The schoolmen, through the middle ages, for the most part followed Aristotle as closely as they could, though not always understanding him correctly, and being somewhat influenced too, by the less precise, less practical, more poetic spirit of Plato. Being largely absorbed in theology, and having scarcely any more scientific knowledge than Aristotle had possessed they were able to add almost nothing to his psychological doctrines, and could only dispute about " intelligible species " or " perceptible forms." We cannot give space to any of them.

HISTORICAL SKETCH. 131

DESCARTES (1576-1650), is commonly called the father of modern philosophy. Putting aside the authority of Aristotle and all others, he doubted everything. " There would have been little merit in such an assumption of independence at a later day, after it had become the fashion; but it was an un- precedented step at the beginning of the seventeenth century." (Bowen.)

His doubt, however, was not that of the skeptic; he did not doubt for the sake of doubting, but in order to test systemat- ically the foundations of truth. " My whole design" he said, "looks to the attainment of certainty." He was "the prince of dogmatists; " his method was dogmatic or deductive, not inductive. He found the first basis of certainty in the axiom, cogito, ergo sum; thought, the existence of which cannot be denied, implies a thinker, a thinking being, an ego. This personal existence becomes " the type of all reality, and the measure of all certainty."

He afterwards developed this into a doctrine of innate ideas. But " by innate ideas he does not mean ready-made ideas, complete images or pictures, in the mind of the infant. He means that the mind infused by the Deity into every human body has certain natural predispositions which compel it to adopt certain beliefs, as soon as it begins to reflect and to exercise its faculties. Such are the ideas of God, of substance, of unity, and a host of others, which he never essayed to enumerate." (Mahaffy, Descartes, 165.)

He drew a sharp distinction between matter and mind, teaching that extension is the essence of matter and thought the essence of mind. The mind, finding itself the subject of certain affections called sensations, infers that external objects exist as the cause of these sensations. The body, however, is a part of the external world, a mere machine or automaton, acted upon by the qualities of objects, and undergoing changes

132 THE INTELLECT.

which are interpreted by the mind. The medium through which sense-impressions are conveyed to the brain is the "animal spirits," an invisible, imponderable fluid. How these sensations are imparted to the mind he does not explain.

In thus assuming to know the essence of matter and mind Descartes opened the door to vast errors. The logical conse- quences of such assumptions would be too much for any sys- tem to support; and though he himself did not follow them to the end, his followers did so, and soon involved themselves in contradictions and fantastic theories, as we shall see. " There is scarcely a theory of sense-perception," says Pres. Porter, "in which some erroneous assumption of Descartes may not be traced."

He did not teach that perception is by means of representa- tive ideas, but such is plainly the natural outcome of his sys- tem, and some of his followers soon began so to hold. He taught that in perception we only infer the existence of an external object, with the aid of habit and association. He did not himself push the natural implications of this further than to say that it is possible to suppose there is no external reality which corresponds to our ideas of matter. But it was not many years before Berkeley arose to make this dogma world- renowned.

Descartes was indeed a truly great man. Besides stimulat- ing and directing several generations in philosophy, he led the way in physics and mathematics, being the originator of the modern application of mathematics to physics, and of algebra to geometry. " We to whom the scholastic theories are things long past, cannot now feel the novelty and the boldness of Descartes' conception, that all nature can be represented in algebraic formulae, and its laws expressed in definite equations." " He swayed not only his followers but his opponents for a whole century; and he gave to certain sciences, especially to

HISTORICAL SKETCH. 133

optics, to physiology, and to physical astronomy, an impulse which has never been exhausted." (Mahaffy, Descartes, 69, 204.)

His followers in philosophy, accepting his opposition be- tween mind and matter, began to hold that neither could ever act upon the other, and to devise theories to account for their apparent interaction.

LEIBNITZ (1646-1716), is usually mentioned in connection with Descartes, though the interval in time is somewhat great, and Leibnitz lived long enough to reply to Locke, and dispute with Newton the honors of the calculus.

To solve the great problem of body and mind, and other problems as well, he invented his celebrated hypothesis of pre- established harmony, already described. He held that God has pre-arranged from eternity parallel courses of events, so that, although matter and spirit cannot act upon one another, yet "a mode of one always coincides with a mode of the other."

This can hardly be called a theory of perception, but is rather a hypothesis of how to get along without perception.

Leibnitz' great influence in philosophy was chiefly through his metaphysical doctrines. His psychological suggestions were chiefly worked out by his followers, a few of whom we shall mention. But if this wonderful man did little for psychology it is because he did so much for almost every other department of human knowledge. Of him it was said that he drove all the sciences abreast. He shared with Sir Isaac Newton the glory of discovering the infinitesimal calculus, and the notation which he devised was far superior to that of Newton. His theory of monads seems like an anticipation of the modern atomic theory, of Darwin's cell-gemmules, and of Spencer's physiological units. His doctrine of space and time is almost the same with that of Kant. He seems to have seen that heat

134 THE INTELLECT.

is a mode of motion, and that space is occupied by an impon- derable ether. Matter, he taught, is nothing but force, which is now the latest theory of metaphysical physics. His scheme of optimism, embodied in a theodicy or vindication of the Divine government of the universe, though ridiculed by Vol- taire in his " Candide," is celebrated and influential in literature and theology to this day.

He was a statesman, a politician, an instructor of princes, a man living in courts, acquainted with diplomacy, and familiar with affairs.

This brief sketch displays a marvelous genius, perhaps equaled in comprehensiveness by Aristotle alone among the sons of men. If such a man could find no way of explaining the interaction of body and mind but the fantastic hypothesis of pre-established harmony, it goes far to show that this knot, though anybody can cut it, is to be untied by no human mind.

The most immediate follower of Leibnitz was Wolf (1679- 1754), who, in a mechanical way, developed some of his master's doctrines into a system of representational psychology. We only mention him as a transition to the next name.

HERBART, (1776-1841), may be called the next in this suc- cession, developing and applying the hints of Leibnitz, though some call him a successor of Kant, to whom he owed much.

He was a very able and extremely ingenious thinker, and his speculations have not received, especially in this country, all the attention they merit. His psychology is derived from Leibnitz' monadology. " The soul is a simple, spaceless es- sence, of simple quality. It is located at a single point within the brain. When the senses are affected, and motion is trans- mitted by the nerve to the brain, the soul is penetrated by the simple, real essences which immediately surround it. Its qual- ity then performs an act of self-preservation in opposition to the disturbance which it would otherwise suffer from the

HISTORICAL SKETCH.

135

whether partially or totally opposite quality of each of these other simple essences; every such act of self-preservation on the part of the soul is an idea. All ideas (representations) endure, even after the occasion which has called them forth has ceased. When there are at the same time in the soul several ideas, which are either partially or totally opposed to each other, they cannot continue to subsist together without being partially arrested; they must be arrested, that is become unconscious, to a degree measured by the sum of the intensi- ties of all these ideas with the exception of the strongest." (Ueberweg, History of Philosophy II, 265.)

Herbart applied mathematics to the discussion of sensations and ideas, to a surprising extent. His philosophy may be called an attempt to combine idealism and materialism.

LOTZE (1817-1881), adopted some of the methods of Her- bart, especially the use of mathematics, and certainly reached similar conclusions on many points, though he strenuously denied being Herbart's disciple. Lotze stands very high in recent German philosophy, and is noted for candor, breadth, acuteness, ingenuity, and moral purpose. He was perhaps more nearly a follower of Leibnitz than of any one else. We have already quoted him many times.

We must now ascend again the stream of philosophy to Descartes, and trace the development of his hints in Mal- ebranche, parallel with Leibnitz, and in Locke, who took a decidedly different direction.

MALEBRANCHE (1638-1715), was another who pushed Car- tesianism beyond itself. According to him, mind, having no extension, cannot be touched or affected in any way by matter; they are separated from each other by the "whole diameter of being." He accounted for perception by the "vision of all things in God," and this is the usual catch-word of his philos- ophy. What we perceive is not objects themselves but ideas

136 THE INTELLECT.

or representations of objects. These ideas do not proceed from the object, nor are they produced by the mind, nor by the constant action of divine power, but they "-exist in God, and human minds behold them there, through their union with him." (Bowen.)

If this be a theory of perception at all, it is plainly one of representative perception, with strong leanings toward idealism and Pantheism.

Malebranche was a great writer. " His writings, which are voluminous, had great popularity and success, for he was one of the founders and masters of ornate and eloquent French prose, the contemporary and rival of Pascal, Bossuet, and Fenelon, and perhaps superior to them all in lofty flights of the imagination, in the wealth and vivacity of his illustrations. . Perhaps no other writer, except Plato, suffers so much by cold analysis and abridgment." (Bowen, Modern Phil., 74.)

SPINOZA (1632-1677), a Spanish Jew by descent, whose family, exiled through persecution, had settled in Holland, developed the philosophy of Descartes in another direction. By an obvious step he reduced Descartes' two substances, mind and matter, to one substance with two fundamental attri- butes, extension and thought, thus becoming the leader of modern Pantheism. His metaphysics has had vast influence in the history of philosophy, but it does not concern us here, and his psychology is not of sufficient importance or clearness to occupy our time. We mention him as displaying the re- markable way in which the suggestions of Descartes were taken up and developed in many directions by the acutest minds of the age.

JOHN LOCKE (1632-1704), is usually thought of as a fine example of English common-sense, from his using common every-day language without technicalities. In this respect, however, his success has not been encouraging, for his neglect

HISTORICAL SKETCH. 137

of terminology and technicality involved him in obscurity and contradiction, and has caused endless uncertainty and contro- versy.

The catch-word of his system is, " all knowledge is derived from sensation and reflection." The most important novelty of his great work, the Essay on Human Understanding, was the denial of innate ideas, which occupied the first book, and which was a direct reply to Descartes. His ablest critics hold, however, that he introduces under the head of reflection, those a priori concepts which, in a crude and unphilosophical form, he had disproved at the outset.

" He protests against innate ideas, but nevertheless admits all that Descartes had ever maintained, viz., that the human mind must infallibly attain certain universal truths in the ordi- nary exercise of its powers. . . . Though he hardly men- tions Cartesian theories except to refute them, his whole essay teems with assumptions taken from the system he decries." (Mahaffy, Descartes, 203.)

By ''reflection " Locke is admitted to have meant introspect- ive or reflective consciousness.

By his denial of intuitive ideas he has had an immense in- fluence on subsequent speculation, and the whole modern sensationalist school dates its own origin from him and looks up to him as its great original. J. Stuart Mill calls Locke "the unquestioned founder of the analytic philosophy of mind." Like most of his followers, he misunderstood the doctrine of intuitive ideas, at least in the real intention of its supporters and the more careful statements of recent times.

He assumes that the mind resembles in the first place a piece of white paper, on which ideas are to be written by sen- sation, in which the mind is passive. But in fact " he finds it impossible to carry out his first fancy of the mind as a purely neutral tint, or as a mere faculty of passive receptivity. * . v

138 THE INTELLECT.

. . Mind, for Locke, is like a mirror, conscious of the images reflected on its surface. The images do not explain the consciousness. Accordingly, the ' white paper ' theory, so far as it seemed to imply that mind was blankly passive and receptive, and only that, is practically modified in the progress of Locke's inquiries. The ' white paper ' turns out to be capable of ' operations,' and to possess 'powers.'" (Morris, British Thought and Thinkers, 196.)

Indeed he made these admissions in such a way that some have claimed them to be his true doctrine. His "prevail- ing tendency, however, is certainly not in this direction." His admissions are unconscious and his great work has proved a fountain of empiricism and skepticism. Yet it has greatly advanced the truth also by the controversies it has kindled, compelling better definition and statement.

Locke held that the objects of perception are the qualities of matter, the primary qualities being known directly and the secondary through them, the obscure idea of substance being involved. He did not probably hold a theory of representa- tive perception by means of ideas, though much of his lan- guage seems to imply this, and he is so understood by many.

Though Locke embroiled himself with the clergy by declar- ing that the substance of the soul might possibly be material, and by rejecting the usual proofs of the existence of God, yet he was a man of irreproachable life, and a Christian believer.

BERKELEY (1684-1753), is' known as the great idealist. Ac- cepting Locke's theory or supposed theory of representative and passive perception, he saw that on this theory matter was an unknown and unknowable something, the occasion of our perceptions, and that it was not only impossible to prove that any such thing really exists, but absurd to impute causation to such an inert, passive unperceived substratum as this "sub- stance," in which the qualities of matter were supposed to in-

HISTORICAL SKETCH.

here. Matter, then, as the substratum of qualities, the cause of sensations, is, he says, an unnecessary hypothesis. Ma- terial substance, being an abstract idea, and its qualities exist- ing only in the perceiving mind, the universe can only exist in the mind of the Divine Being, and can have no real separate being of its own. Thus Berkeley did not, as is usually stated, deny the existence of matter, but spiritualized, or idealized it.

Berkeley's positive contributions to the theory of perception have been spoken of under Vision, and their value is ines- timable. But his theory has also proved fruitful in meta- physics, having been the source of the whole vast stream of modern idealistic philosophy.

Through Hume he awakened the mighty speculative genius of KANT, who taught that the mind, by a complicated process, constructs its own perceptions, the qualities of matter being relative to our faculties only, and the reality of matter a lt noumenon" unknown and unknowable. This scheme of cosmothetic idealism, or ideal realism, soon became absolute idealism in the hands of his successors, (the greatest of whom was Hegel) and was reared into the .most extraordinary struct- ure of absiract thought the world has ever seen. Thus phi- losophy, having made the tour of Great Britain, through Locke in England, Berkeley in Ireland, and Hume in Scotland, re- turned to Germany, enriched and strengthened, to run a won- derful course in its chosen land.

HUME ( 1 7 1 i-i 7 7 6), the prince of skeptics, applied Berkeley's mode of reasoning to the phenomena of mind as well as mat- ter, and thus produced a system of skepticism the most thoiough-going ever framed.

We must now return and trace the principal stream of phi- losophical tendency from the works of John Locke, namely, that which developed the sensationalistic or materialistic side of his philosophy. He was not a materialist, though he declared

140 THE INTELLECT.

that matter might possibly think, and that the soul might pos- sibly be made of matter.

But his doctrine that all knowledge is derived from sensa- tion and reflection received a most unexpected development. It was not noticed that reflection with him was really introspect- ive consciousness, finding or producing a priori concepts or necessary truths, and it was promulgated, on Locke's authority, that all knowledge is derived from sensation alone, that all the faculties of the mind are but transformed sensation and asso- ciation.

This scheme is called empirical, as deriving everything from experience, a term introduced by Kant; or experiential, a term recently gaining ground (perhaps because the word empirical has another application, namely, to a physician who experiments on his patients, a quack); or sensational, as deriving all knowl- edge from sensations and all faculty from sensation; or asso- ciational, as accounting for the transformation of sensations by the law of association; or materialistic, as not really leaving room for any immaterial soul or mind.

This development of the more obvious and popular side of Locke has been the strongest current in English thought, and was almost the only current of French thought throughout the eighteenth century. A great similarity runs through this whole school of writers.

CONDILLAC (1715-1780), was the chief apostle of this new gospel of sensation in France. He taught that the mind is passive in sensation, that all ideas are but transformed sensa- tion, and yet that bodies are only collections of sensations, being nothing but qualities, without any substratum of real be- ing, and qualities being entirely subjective.

This curious combination of materialism and pseudo-ideal- ism is common to many others of the school, even down to the present time. Huxley propounds it in the crudest fashion.

HISTORICAL SKETCH. 141

J. Stuart Mill confessed its difficulties as insuperable and yet adhered to it. Bain attempts to defend it, and Herbert Spencer takes it for granted.

DR. THOMAS BROWN (1778-1820), professor at Edinburgh, was strongly under the influence of this kind of thought. He was remarkable for the eloquence and enthusiasm with which he lectured, and the great popular reputation which he ac- quired throughout Great Britain and the United States.

Brown was the first properly to distinguish the muscular sensations, from which he derived our knowledge of space and of the external world. Like his school in general he confused sensation and perception and denied efficiency in causation. He had remarkable ingenuity as well as eloquence and great boldness. He was treated with great harshness of criticism by Hamilton, who, of course, had Brown greatly at advantage by his superiority of learning. Hamilton accused Brown of plag- iarism; but if the sins of philosophers in this way should be marked, who shall stand? Not even, it is hinted, Sir W. Ham- ilton himself.

JAMES MII*L (1773-1836), is chiefly known now as the father of John Stuart Mill, but his treatise is one of the best of his school, free from the prolixity of Brown, and less in- tended for the popular ear.

J. S. MILL (1806-1873), a great name in English thought, was not a special student of psychology. His greatest works are his treaties on political economy and logic. His inacquaint- ance with the history of philosophy led him into errors, and his criticisms of Hamilton were often ineffective. He is very remarkable in psychology for the frankness with which he ac- knowledged the inadequacy of his own, and his father's system, to answer the great questions of philosophy.

He defines mind as " a series of feelings, or, as it has been called, a thread of consciousness, however supplemented by

i42 THE INTELLECT.

believed possibilities of consciousness." But he admits that this theory of mind " has intrinsic difficulties. . . . which it seems to me beyond the power of metaphysical analysis to remove." And he adds, "if we speak of the mind as a series of feelings, we are obliged to complete the statement by call- ing it a series of feelings which is aware of itself as past and future." "The truth is, we are here face to face with that final inexplicability at which, as Sir W. Hamilton observes, we inevitably arrive when we reach ultimate facts." (Examina- tion, I, 262.) It seems plain to us that Mr. Mill made this particular inexplicability for himself, though we admit that there are enough of them in the universe ready-made; but as stated by him it is more, it is an absurdity.

He declares that our irresistible belief in the reality of the external world is a product of association. (I, 237.) He de- fines matter ther2fore as a "permanent possibility of sensation. If I am asked whether I believe in matter, I ask whether the questioner accepts this definition of it. If he does, I believe in matter. ... In any other sense than this I do not." (1,243.) " The belief in such permanent possibilities seems to me to include all that is essential or characteristic in the be lief in substance." (I, 246.) This assumes that the only thing to be accounted for is the power which matter has of occasioning sensations, and also implies a wrong conception of what a sensation is, a false use of the term sensation. Being is thus reduced "to less than its own shadow, namely, only to a ' permanent possibility ' (whatever that may mean) of its shadow, projected in the form of feeling." (Morris, British Thought and Thinkers, 330.)

We have referred to Mr. Mill so often in the preceding pages that it is not necessary here to discuss his psychology further.

ALEXANDER BAIN (1818-), Professor at Aberdeen, an asso- ciate, disciple, and friend of J. S. Mill, is a voluminous writer

HISTORICAL SKETCH. 143

on the phenomena of mind. Adopting the associational theory he has very ingeniously strengthened some of its weak points.

He insists upon a principle of spontaneous activity in human nature, which he makes a " primitive element of the Will." This may, perhaps, partly meet the objection against the sen- sational system, that it makes sensations active but the mind passive.

He teaches that it is natural for man to believe; that we are irresistibly impelled to believe in what we perceive or what is told us, until corrected by experience. The " intuitionist " form of this principle would be that the testimony of conscious- ness is correct beyond appeal, so far as it goes, and the errors of perception are to be explained in other ways.

He holds to three primitive principles, consciousness of agreement and of difference, and retentiveness; thus implicitly introducing two categories of the understanding, identity-di- versity, and similarity-dissimilarity, and surreptitiously assum- ing, under memory, the principles of Self and Time.

He holds that the basis of induction is a belief in the uni- formity of nature; but the only rational ground for such uni- formity is reality of causation, which he denies, and the belief in which he derives from experience, having first reduced it to mere succession.

His system thus really rests upon necessary principles of cognition, and so shows, it seems to us, a decided progress in the school, though a progress under the surface and as it were, in spite of itself.

HERBERT SPENCER (1820-), has devoted his life to the elaboration and defence of the theory of evolution. His Psychology is more taken up with the development of nerves in a mass of organized matter, and the evolution of mind out of "nervous shocks," than with psychology in the usual sense.

144 THE INTELLECT.

His theories of the origin and nature of mind will be better discussed later on. His theory of perception makes it involve classification.

"Special perception is possible only as an intuition of a like- ness or unlikeness of certain present attributes and relations [sensations] to certain past attributes and relations." (II, 132.) In another place this " intuition " becomes association. " The primary and essential association is between each feeling and the class, order, genus, species, and variety of preceding feel- ings like itself. ... A feeling cannot form an element of mind at all, save on condition of being associated with prede- cessors more or less the same in nature." (I, 256.)

Every perception, he says, implies a judgment, a " saying what a thing is." " And the saying what a thing is, is the say- ing what it is like, what class it belongs to." (II, 131.)

He holds to the immediate knowledge of the external world in perception, " The thing primarily known is not that a sensa- tion has been experienced, but that there exists an outer ol> ject." (11,3690

He admits that there is a real substratum of material exist- ence, but affirms that this reality is unknown and unknowable. The Cosmic Philosophy of Prof. John Fiske is a more lumin- ous exposition of this system than Mr. Spencer's own, and comparatively free from tedious prolixity.

We must now turn to the succession of writers who have opposed both the idealistic and the sensational systems arising from Locke, and who belong chiefly to the school of the so- called Scottish philosophy.

THOMAS REID (1710-1796), Professor at Edinburgh, ex- plicitly reintroduced those "intuitions" which Locke had implicitly assumed, under the authority of common-sense, or the necessary beliefs common to all men. He was a natural realist in his doctrine of perception, though not always clear or

HISTORICAL SKETCH. 145

consistent. He taught that the mind is active in perception, but did not distinguish between natural and acquired percep- tion.

He is chiefly known to the present generation through the elaborate commentary of his greatest disciple, Sir W. Hamilton, but his services to philosophy were important, though less brilliant and less renowned than those of some lesser men.

SIR WM. HAMILTON (1788-1856), was the foremost in learn- ing and power of all the philosophers whom Great Britain has produced. He left no complete treatises, and his opinions have to be gathered from his lectures to students and his notes on the works of Reid, whose disciple he was in the main. His writings have been gathered up in Wight's " Hamilton's Phi- losophy," and Bowen's " Hamilton's Metaphysics."

His metaphysical theories were largely derived from Kant. His law of the conditioned he expressed thus: " All that is conceivable in thought, lies between two extremes, which, as contradictory of each other, cannot both be true, but of which as mutual contradictories, one must." To illustrate this he drew up a table of contradictions similar to Kant's antimonies.

In regard to perception, he was a natural realist, holding that we have a direct knowledge of the non-ego, yet there is some dispute whether by the non-ego he meant the qualities of mat- ter only, or matter as being. He insisted on the distinction be- tween sensation and perception, and thus did good service.

We have quoted Hamilton so often already that further notice here is unnecessary.

NOAH PORTER, President of Yale College, may be called the true successor of Sir W. Hamilton. Like him, he has great learning but is not a system-builder. Like him, he is a natural realist but qualifies this position as follows: " In original perception, the object directly apprehended is the sensorium as

excited to some definite action." He does not explain, as we io

146 THE INTELLECT.

understand, how the change is made from perceiving the sen- sorium to perceiving the object through the sensorium. For he insists that the object in complete perception is not the qualities of matter, but the external world itself, as being. He makes prominent the distinction between sensation and percep- tion, and also that between natural and acquired perception.

He teaches that the intellect is active in " sense-perception;" that sensation is always either pleasant or painful. He dis- tinguishes two kinds of consciousness, and three non-egos. He uses, throughout, the word "soul," where others use ''mind."

President Porter's great work, The Human Intellect, is of immense value for reference, and by far the greatest psycho- logical work yet produced in America.

Many other names of great philosophers might be referred to, but we have preferred to select a few of the greatest, in the hope of impressing upon the student, (i) That philosophy has occupied many of the greatest minds of the race. (2) That its conclusions are of practical importance in life. (3) That psychology is not unprogressive, but advances from age to age in the defmiteness of its problems, in the clearness of its con- clusions. A vast deal of vagueness and obscurity has been dissipated, and men know, at least far better than of old, what they are disputing about. Moreover, on some topics, as the sense of sight, substantial unanimity has been reached; while on others great concessions have been made by the principal schools.

PART II.

REPRESENTATIVE POWER.

The representative power may be defined as the power which the mind has of entering into conscious states which are similar to its former states or to combinations of them. It is best treated under the heads of Memory, Association, and Imagination.

I. MEMORY.

Memory has by some been subdivided. Sir W. Hamilton divides it into three separate powers, called Conservative, Reproductive, and Representative. But of these three the first two are only auxiliary to the third, and by themselves use- less, even if really existing.

It would be of no use to preserve knowledge if it could not be reproduced, that is, brought up again by the unconscious power of association; it would be of no use when thus associ- ated, if it could not be represented, that is, brought fully into conscious possession. Moreover, the way in which retention takes place is so wholly unknown, and so entirely out of con- sciousness, that it is a gratuitous assumption to say that there is a separate power of the mind for this purpose.

It is better then to use ''retention" or "retentiveness" of the simple capacity of not forgetting, which is not an act of the mind at all.

The word " memory," if used in psychology, ought proba- bly to be restricted to this meaning. " Recollection " and

148 THE INTELLECT.

"reminiscence" are commonly used of the act of recalling any fact formerly known, by means of association, and are gener- ally defined as voluntary reproduction. But strictly speaking there is no such thing as voluntary reproduction; all we can do is to set in motion the automatic, unknown machinery of as- sociation, and wait for it to produce the result.

Memory, in the full, complete sense, or Recollection, im- plies four things, (i) A state of consciousness in past time. (2) The return of a representation of that state to conscious- ness, not exactly the same state itself. (3) The intuitive knowl- edge that this new state is a representation of something past, involving the element of time. (4) The recognition of the past state as having belonged to the same ego, involving the element of self.

Some would place between the first and second another con- dition of recollection, namely the retention of some trace or sign Of the first state by which it may be recalled. But of such a trace we really know nothing. All we know is that we experienced a certain state, and when a proper stimulus occurs, starting the right train of association, a representation of that state appears in consciousness, but not the state itself.

It is taught by some recent writers that memory is a repro- duction of the same state, only weaker. This is an error. We insist upon the self-evident fact, that the state of mind called memory is not the same in kind as that called presen: tation, or perception, or any original experience, but is a re- presentation, as different from presentation as the "idea " of a tree is from a tree, or the picture of a man from a man.

It is often stated by recent writers on the subject that memory is the renewal of past sensations and the ideas they have ex- cited. But memory does not reproduce sensations. If a sen- sation be really reproduced, in the literal meaning of the term, it is even then a new sensation, not the same one; and if it be represented, the product is not a sensation at all.

MEMORY. 149

Thus, if you are nauseated on seeing a friend go on board a ship, that is because the sight of the ship, with all the associa- tions of sea-sickness formerly experienced, excites reflex sen- sations just like the former ones. But they are new sensations, not identical with the old ones; and they are real sensations, not mere representations of old ones. Memory proper has nothing to do with such a case.

If the name of an absent friend is mentioned, and you picture his face before you in the mind, that is imagination, not memory. But neither is it sensation. If the representation of his face becomes so vivid as actually to excite reflex sensa- tions, so that you think you see him before you, that is hallu- cination, not memory. The number of persons who have im- agination strong enough to recall a face so as to paint it, is very small; though very many can compare the image so produced with " memory " (in the popular sense) and decide as to the faithfulness of the picture. It is easier, too, to recall the expression of a face than to picture in the imagination a representation of the features, because the expression is a men- tal product in the first place.

When we wish to recall a smell, a sound, a taste, etc., we " recall " first the object which produced it, and sometimes the representation excites reflex sensations very distinctly.

It is very difficult to recall a word by the mere sound of it as heard, or the looks of it as seen, if the meaning is unknown. Few can do it at all, and they seem to do it by imagination, reproducing the sound or form of the word "before the mind's eye or ear."

It is the " idea," the mental product, the presentation, which is reproduced in memory, in the form of a representation. If this is strong enough it may excite a reflex sensation, like the original one, not identical with it. The representation of a sensation or group of sensations is imagination, an imaging

15° THE INTELLECT.

forth by the mind to itself. (Carpenter, Mental Physiology, 431-)

All the products of the representative power are subjective, thought objects, subject-objects. They cannot be compared with object-objects of any kind; they cannot be described. They may be compared with other subject-objects, sensations, perceptions, emotions, as men may be compared with trees, houses, beasts, birds. But the two classes of objects are in- commensurable.

It has been remarked by various writers, including even Hamilton, that the wonderful thing and hard to account for, is not remembering, but forgetting. This remark springs from the physical analogies which have long been common in con- nection with this subject, and which modern science has not weakened. The memory used to be compared to a receptacle, a casket; to shelves and pigeon-holes. At the present day we hear much of nerve-vibrations, of traces left in the brain, of permanent combinations of brain-cells, etc.

No doubt there must be some physical machinery of memory, as there is of sensation and emotion. Physiology and path- ology have done something, and may do much more, towards tracing out the process in the brain, and explaining the mechani cal part of the problem. But if all this were made as plain as the optical part of vision has been made by modern science, this would not go one step toward solving the real difficulty of the case, namely, how a trace in the brain can be transmuted into conscious memory, or how permanent connections of brain-cells can appear in consciousness as associated sensations or " ideas."

The problem is the same which confronts us in studying sensation. If we can no more tell how a nerve-thrill can oc- casion a state of consciousness than how the Djinn appeared when Aladdin rubbed his lamp (Huxley), we are equally un-

MEMORY. 151

able, of course, to tell why a trace in the brain should occa- sion a representation of consciousness, and why a connection of such traces should cause ideas to adhere together, or why the decadence of such traces should cause disappearance of these representative states. The question of forgetting is no more difficult and no easier than that of remembering, and both are utterly inexplicable.

Many of the facts, however, which tend to show the depend- ence of memory on the brain, and which are relied on to ex- plain memory by some writers, who are forgetful of the above considerations, are very curious and instructive.

Disease affects the memory most strangely. In the delirium of fever, an ignorant woman once repeated long passages of Hebrew which she had heard many years before, and of which she had never understood a word. Many foreigners, long set- tled in America, having nearly forgotten their native tongue, have been known to return to its use on their death-bed. Dr. Scandella, ill with yellow fever, spoke on the first day French only, on the second English only, but on the day of his death only Italian, his native language. (Ribot, Diseases of the Memory.)

Sir Henry Holland, when overcome with fatigue at the bot- tom of a mine in Germany, forgot the German language com- pletely; but it was restored to him by rest and food. Sir Walter Scott, having composed his romance of Ivanhoe in ill- ness, could not afterwards recall a single incident or character in it. A person has been known to forget, after a violent ill- ness, all his acquired knowledge, which however returned to him instantaneously, some months afterward. After a severe injury to the head, the patient usually forgets not only the ac- cident itself but all events which occurred within several hours previous. A well educated man, after an attack of fever and ague, lost, it is said, all knowledge of the letter f. (Winslow.)

152 THE INTELLECT.

Somnambulists often remember during one fit of somnam- bulism what they did, or suffered, or where they hid articles, dur- ing the previous attack; but cannot so remember in the inter- vening time.

It is quite certain that there are different kinds of memory, corresponding to the different kinds of mental aptitude^ or to peculiarities of sensation. Some persons, nearly idiotic, have had a wonderful memory for words. Some remember words best, some principles, some events, some numbers; some re- call sights best, some sounds,

Led by such analogies some writers have maintained that there is no general faculty of memory, but that each :>f the senses has its own memory. This of course involves the ?en- sational view of the mental functions. But even on that view it would be more consistent to say that memory is a general function of the nervous system.

There can be no doubt that memory is as much dependent on the nerves and brain as other mental functions, but there is no reason to suppose that it is more so, and no satisfactory hypothesis has yet been constructed of the manner and extent of this physiological dependence.

To the theory that memory is a function of the immaterial part of the mind, the soul, it has been objected that it is in- conceivable that the soul, which is an undivided unit, existing in a single point of space, can retain a vast number of dis- tinct impressions, and be able to reproduce a corresponding number of states. But this is an argument ex ignorantia. We do not really know anything about the mode of existence of the soul, whether it is an absolutely unitary being, or has parts and powers; whether it exists in one or many points of space, or inhabits the whole brain. Lotze holds that the soul is a single element, and of simple quality, but yet may be present at more than one point of space at the same time.

MEMORY. 153

The same argument may be retorted against the materialists. It is inconceivable that the almost infinite number of separate elements which go to make up the series of our mental life, should be each one represented by a combination of brain- cells. Each spoken word, for instance, has several sounds, and each sound is produced by several impulses of the vocal organs. Each written word also has several letters, and the combinations between the sounds and the letters form another vast series. Yet many persons have at command as many as ten thousand words. Some can use fluently three or more languages, with command of three or four thousand words in each. Then, a prodigy of learning occasionally arises who knows twenty languages, is familiar with a hundred authors, can re- peat whole volumes, and knows a dozen sciences. Add to this the vast number of elements of knowledge comprised in our daily life, all our knowledge of places, persons, facts, the properties of matter, etc., and the number of separate things remembered will be seen to be vastly greater than the four hundred million nucleated cells, computed to exist in the brain.

But each act of the brain must involve more than one cell, probably many thousands; they cannot leave their places to enter new situations, and if they could do so registration would thereby be lost. Thus even the physical difficulties of this scheme are insuperable, and we conclude that the fact of retention is inexplicable.

The process of reproduction is capable of some further elucidation through the principle of association, under which head we shall recur to some phenomena of memory.

154 THE INTELLECT.

II. ASSOCIATION.

This principle accompanies or pervades nearly every activ- ity of the mind.. We have already seen that different sensa- tions, occasioned by the same object, cohere together, so that any one will suggest all the rest, and occasion a complete pre- sentation of the object; also, that a sensation, being once found by experience to be a sign of distance or solidity, ever afterwards suggests that perception, when it is repeated. So, peculiar sensations may be associated with certain perceptions, as nausea with the sight of a ship, in the example cited above. Or, perceptions and emotions may be agglutinated. A dog is filled with fear at the sight of a whip. A timid person shud- ders at seeing a gun. A familiar tune may excite emotions of joy or of sadness according to the circumstances of the hearer.

Professor Bain has described various modes of association, with remarkable minuteness and concreteness; showing, for example, how it applies to the use of language, to mechanical inventions, to the fine arts, to oratory, to poetry, to business, to handicrafts, etc. This has been called a " natural history of the human mind." It is ingenious, instructive, and inter- esting, but it throws no light on the law or cause of associa- tion.

The operation of this principle can only be observed in connection with representation. We cannot know whether sensations or presentations cohere together, until they are rep- resented together in memory or imagination. Hence the laws of association are always stated in a form which implies repre- sentation.

The most general law of association is this: Ideas tend to be represented together which were formed together or near one another in any sense, that is, in time, place, interest, emo-

ASSOCIATION. 155

tion, action, dependence, cause, or any relation in which they can coexist. The principle on which this depends is that the mind acts more readily in the same manner or a similar man- ner with any in which it has acted before.

Sir W. Hamilton, following St. Augustine and others, states the law as follows; " Thoughts suggest each other which had previously constituted parts of the same entire or total act of cognition." He calls this a law of redintegration. But if literally interpreted this law does not include all the phe- nomena. Mere similarity is often the connecting link between ideas, and so is contrast; but these are not naturally or easily included under redintegration.

Aristotle laid down three laws of association, namely, that ideas are associated by contiguity in time or space, by re- semblance, and by contrariety. Other schemes have been proposed. Hume gives resemblance, contiguity in time and place, and cause and effect. Dr. T. Brown introduced a two- fold classification of primary and secondary laws. For the first he adopted Aristotle's three laws; by the second he at- tempted to show why, when several ideas are in equally close association with the suggesting idea, according to the primary laws, only one is actually suggested. The secondary princi- ples are such as vivacity, frequency of repetition, recentness, the amount of interest or emotion involved, the natural pre- disposition of body or mind, of which he gives nine. But obviously such a list could be drawn out indefinitely, for any object may have a vast number of associations. For example, if gems are spoken of, we think of the diamond as the finest; if hardness is mentioned, we recall the diamond as the hardest of minerals; if combustibility, we recall the diamond, and Sir Isaac Newton's prediction of its combustibility from its re- fracting power; if refracting power, the same; if preciousness, we recall the diamond in that connection, and so on. It is

156 THE INTELLECT.

not worth while to attempt to classify these. One example is as good as a thousand.

We must beware of attributing efficiency to the laws or rules which have been discovered in association^ or the principles on which it may be supposed to act. Laws, rules, and principles of action in nature, are only abstractions from actual phenom- ena, not real beings which guide events. The error is one not infrequent in all science, and needs no special attention in psychology. A relation between two ideas is an abstraction, and can have no real efficiency. Ideas do not appear in con- sciousness together because there is a relation between them, but the mind, which formed them in the first place, recalls them, and for some unknown reason recalls those more easily which it first formed together, arrd this we call a relation be- tween the ideas.

Association throws some light on the process of reproduc- tion. Obviously the simplest case of reproduction, would be one in which the whole series of our past ideas was recalled successively, being associated by the principle of contiguity in time, until that idea is reached which fits in with our present experience.

Something like this has occurred to persons in extreme dan- ger, as while falling over a precipice, or when almost drowned. In such cases the sufferer sometimes sees, as it were, all the events of his life sweeping before him with inconceivable rapid- ity, so that he seems to live over again his whole life in a moment of time. In repeating a " piece " one is often obliged to begin again at the beginning, and can then go through without hesitation. Dr. Leyden, who was celebrated for his extraordinary memory, could repeat an act of Parliament, or any long document, after once reading it. "But when he wished to recall any particular point in anything which he had read, he could only do it by repeating to himself the whole " from the beginning to that place. (Abercrombie.)

ASSOCIATION. 157

Now, taking a case of this sort, as the simplest one, suppose the series of ideas to be represented byAbCdeFgHij K, etc., where the large letters stand for the more important ideas, and the small letters for the less important ones. Then the less important ideas, serving only the office, in that partic- ular series, of connecting together the more important ones, might be dropped out, during frequent repetitions of the series, and only the latter would remain, and would be associated together, so as to recall or suggest one another. We may sup- pose this process repeated until A is connected directly with Z, and, the next time Z comes into consciousness, this new coherence being established, A will be suggested immediately.

Or we may suppose that a new principle intervenes and supersedes that of contiguity in time, when the series is re- peated. For example, some of the ideas, A C F H, etc., may refer to the same subject. Then, on repetition of the series, the next step would be to drop out such steps as do not be- long to that subject, and the new series might be A C F H R Z, from which would result after a few more repetitions, the so-called immediate coherence of A and Z.

Something like this seems to occur when we try to think of a name and are at first unable to do so, because we cannot get hold of any short series of links between the present idea and the past one. In such cases what is needed is time for the machinery of reproduction to operate. Guided by experience we always say, " no matter, it will come to me," and remove our attention from the matter. Very often the automatic apparatus of suggestion does actually reproduce the name after a time, and, if the process is repeated with the same name after a few hours, it is much shorter, and finally the connection becomes " immediate."

Another indication of the correctness of this analysis is the fact that some past events, having become established in con-

158 THE INTELLECT.

sciousness by frequent reference, owing to their importance for our life, are far more distinctly and exactly placed in our recollection than others. Hence we use them as reference- points for more quickly reproducing the latter. Thus we say, "I remember the storm of May 3, 1874, because it was the day before I was married." Old people commonly reinforce their statements in this way: " Brother Joshua came to visit us in the year 1865; because he was here when the news of Lin- coln's assassination arrived." In courts of justice those wit- nesses are always esteemed the best who remember events in their connection, recalling them by several threads, and giving parallel, associated events, by which to check the correctness of the principal ones. Shakespeare understood this. Dame Quickly says, in Henry IV, "Thou didst swear to me upon a parcel-gilt goblet, sitting in my dolphin chamber, at the round table, by a sea-coal fire, upon Wednesday in Whitsun-week, when the prince broke thy head for liking his father to a sing- ing-man of Windsor; thou didst swear to me then, as I was washing thy wound, to marry me, and make me my Lady thy wife."

According to Mr. Herbert Spencer, memory, when it is " immediate " or perfect, is automatic, like instinct, a part of organization; and only associative or suggestive memory really deserves the name. " Instinct may be regarded as a kind of organized memory, memory may be regarded as a kind of in- cipient instinct." (Psychology, I, 445.) "Memory necessa- rily comes into existence whenever automatic action is imper- fect." (448.) " As fast as those connections among psychical states which we form in memory grow by constant repetition automatic, they cease to be a part of memory." (450.)

If we correctly understand this distinction, it agrees with the view already given. The real difference in the two kinds of memory is in the length of the process, the number of in-

DREAMS. 159

tervening suggestive links. When these are all dropped, as explained above, the connection "between psychical states" becomes immediate, that is, automatic. But, properly speak- ing, all associative suggestion is automatic or unconscious.

Associative representation is the chief activity of the mind in dreams, somnambulism, hypnotism, and hallucination, making a transition to the subject of the imagination. In these, asso- ciation has its own way, unrestricted by either the will, or the actual facts of the external world.

i. DREAMS.

In sleep the circulation of the blood in the brain is checked and almost suspended; hence there is not enough activity in the nerve-centers to produce motion in response to a stimulus either of the sense from without or of the mind from within. All the senses are partly dormant, and the sensations which are received become so feeble that they only recall past ideas. Since communication with the external world is suspended, the ordinary checks upon representation, furnished by the relations of space and time are wanting, and the various elements of our experience are combined in lawless, fantastic fashion. We have no sense of incongruity, in dreams, when we suddenly find ourselves in a distant city, nor when we spend an hour in crossing a street or ascending a stairway.

That the will is dormant, and the mind wholly under the sway of association, is shown by the fact that dreams are some- times inspired by whispering in the ear of a sleeping person. A young military officer was once caused in this way to fight a duel in a dream. He thought that he was insulted, challenged, taken to the field, and that he killed his antagonist. But, be. ing told to fly, his efforts to do so awakened him.

Nearly every one knows the terrible night-mare sensation of being unable, in a dream, to move, in order to escape from danger. This is undoubtedly a real experience, expressing the

160 THE INTELLECT.

actual fact. The representative power is active, but the slug- gish brain cannot respond to it by moving the limbs. Homer compares the pursuit of Hector by Achilles around the walls of Troy, to such a dream. (Iliad, Bk. 22, Line 200.)

It is a wonderful part of the phenomena of dreaming that we remember our dreams. This is largely an acquired power. Persons who tell their dreams, soon learn to remember them and to have them oftener. Those who never tell them seldom remember them.

The cause of dreaming and the cause of the particular dream which occurs, may be quite distinct. Thus one may dream perhaps, because he ate too much supper, or because he is lying on his back, or because the wind makes a gentle noise; but he dreams of being at sea because he read about a ship the day before; or dreams about home because he is away from home. Dr. Gregory relates that once, having a bottle of hot water at his feet, he dreamed that he was walking on Mount Etna. A person who had a blister on his head dreamed that he was scalped by Indians.

Since all outside distractions or checks are removed in dreams, if any one subject or train of thought has excited the mind while awake, to such an extent that the mind spontan- eously dwells upon it, excluding other suggestions, some very surprising results appear, though really no more inexplicable than any dream. Thus, Coleridge composed the poem of Kubla Khan in a dream. Dr. Franklin often unraveled politi- cal combinations in his dreams. Condorcet habitually solved mathematical problems in his sleep. This kind of dreaming runs into somnambulism; for the dreamer sometimes rises and writes down the problem or stanza in his sleep, though he does not remember, when he awakes, that he has done so.

This phenomenon has been called "unconscious cerebration" (Carpenter), " unconscious mental modification " (Hamilton),

SOMNAMBULISM. 161

"insensible perception" (Leibnitz), etc. Various theories of brain-action have been devised to explain it. Great numbers of wonderful examples have been accumulated, and may be found in easily accessible books. But there can be no proof that this kind of mental action is unconscious, at the time; but only that it is not remembered.

There is no necessity for assuming any new principle, other than associative suggestion, in connection with dreaming or somnambulism. The facts all come under these. In some cases a dream of this kind is forgotten, while the results remain in the mind, and a problem can be solved or a thought expressed which could not be before. But this does not show that the activity of the mind was unconscious at the time.

Some writers have failed to distinguish between this phe- nomenon and ordinary associative recollection, and have con- fused together the examples of both. " Unconscious cerebra- tion " is only mysterious and inexplicable in fact, just as all association, and indeed all mental action is so. On dreaming, in general, see also Sully, Illusions, Chapter 7. 2. SOMNAMBULISM.

Somnambulism is an acted dream. In this the motor cen- ters and nerves have sufficient circulation to support activity, while some of the senses are still dormant. Representation goes on and is acted out, and the patient's consciousness is the same as in a dream.

In this state many strange occurrences take place, due to concentration of the mind on one topic. Those senses which are not dormant are in a state of exalted activity, and the pa- tient performs so many actions, guided by touch alone, or touch and hearing, with eyes firmly fixed and sightless, that observers feel certain he can see through a wall, or see with the back of his head or with his hand.

1 62 THE INTELLECT.

No extravagant supposition of new senses or strange spirit- ual powers is necessary. The somnambulist is like a blind person, who learns more by touch than other people do be- cause he concentrates his attention upon it.

3. HYPNOTISM.

The state called somnambulism can be induced artificially, and is then called hypnotism, or mesmeric sleep. In this state the phenomena of sleep and somnambulism are curiously blended. The will being entirely dormant, the patient's ac- tions are a dream suggested by the operator, like the duel de- scribed above. He sees flames of fire issuing from a magnet, sees them where the operator says there is a magnet, even if none be really there. His thoughts and actions are at the mercy of associative suggestion.

This state may even be voluntarily assumed by some persons. It has been known in many countries and ages in the form of religious trance or extasy. The spiritualistic trance-speaker, if not an imposter, is in this state. He speaks much more flu- ently than he could in his natural condition, because his at- tention is concentrated on his language, and all distractions are excluded. But he says nothing new, nothing which he did not know before, and nothing of any importance. Persons in this state, however, sometimes recall things which they had for- gotten and could not recall in their normal condition. Many of these phenomena are best discussed in connection with the subject of the Will.

4. HALLUCINATION.

Hallucination is a waking dream. Owing to some disorder of the brain, caused by disease or the action of opium, alco- hol, haschish, etc., the ideas called up by association, as in dreams, excite the nerves and centers of vision, and produce subjective or reflex sensations of sight. Nearly all patients in violent fever suffer in this way.

IMAGINATION. 163

The case of Brutus has been mentioned. The case of Nicolai, a bookseller of Berlin, is famous and typical. But the phenomena are too common and too slight in psychological importance to justify further attention here.

Representation here goes on, and excites a reflex activity of the visual centers, as somnambulism of the motor centers. For further details and examples, see Sully on Illusions.

III. IMAGINATION.

By all these abnormal phenomena of association the trans- ition is made to the imagination, which is association, guided by the will and watched by consciousness, and thus having the appearance of a creative power. Two observations were long ago made which confirm this explanation, (i) Imagina- tion produces nothing absolutely new, but only combines ob- jects in new ways, or parts of objects to make up new wholes, or changes the properties of objects, or alters the degree or proportion of their different qualities. (2) Imagination is confined to material things, objects of sense. This last is only true of the ordinary, established use of the term imagi- nation. It is often used now in a figurative, extended sense, as we shall see.

In imagination the wider excursions of the suggestive power are restrained by the will, the relations of space and time are not lost sight of, because the senses are not dormant, and all is normal. As already said, imagination, in its usual meaning, is the power of representing objects. To recall a face so that you can paint it, is an act of imagination in the ordinary sense. To form from this face a different one, by heightening the ex- pression, improving some features, adding beauty or any pe- culiar character, is called an act of creative imagination, and the face thus produced is called an ideal face.

The different activities of the imagination have often, been distinguished and classified. Sir W. Hamilton limits

164 THE INTELLECT.

the word to its literal meaning, and says that the terms productive and creative are very improperly applied to the imagination. President Porter distinguishes three offices of the imagination, (i) the combining and arranging office, (2) the idealizing office, (3) the office of forming standards of action. But he adds four special applications of the imagination, the poetic, the philosophic, the ethical, and the religious. And it must be noticed that he treats of the phantasy as a separate division of the representative power, including some things which most writers place under imagination.

We propose the following division of the field of activity of the imagination into five parts, (i) Imagination in the com- mon, literal meaning. (2) Reverie. (3) Poetic or artistic imagination. (4) Mechanical or scientific. (5) Ethical or moral. In every one of these the imagination produces the ideal by combining the real. It has but one method.

i. Ordinary imagination is the representation of objects when they are out of actual sight, so that they appear before the mind's eye just as they really are. The difference between this and the activities of associative representation noticed above, dreaming, hypnotism, etc., is that they are all abnormal, some part of the mental force being dormant, while this is per- fectly normal and regular.

This view is confirmed by the following definitions. " The image making power. The power to create or reproduce an object of sense previously perceived." (The Webster Die.) " The faculty of representation by which the mind keeps be- fore it an image of visible forms." (Calderwood.) " Mental representation of the absent object, 'passive imagination.'" (Krauth.) " Imagination as reproductive, stores the mind with ideal images, constructed through the medium of atten- tion and memoiy, out of our immediate perceptions." (Mor- ell.) Shakespeare compares it with the poet's pen.

IMAGINATION. 165

'* . . . as imagination bodies forth The forms of things unknown, the poet's pen Turns them to shapes, and gives to airy nothing A local habitation and a name."

Simple imagination has decided limitations, (a) It is con- fined to things actually seen or known, either directly or through descriptions and pictures. A person born on the prairie, who has never seen a mountain, cannot imagine one. One who has never been at sea cannot picture to himself the raging deep. The dweller in the tropics cannot imagine the arctic ice. But all can body forth before the mind, to some extent, the descriptions they have heard and the pictures they have seen.

(b) It is limited to natural objects and qualities. It cannot produce a new color, present an object out of space, an event out of time, or a pure unembodied spirit. But it can com- bine arbitrarily all natural forms and qualities; it can create centaurs, the heads of men on the bodies of horses; or mer- maids, part woman, part fish; or angels, beautiful women with wings; mice as large as elephants; diamonds as large as houses; a nation of pigmies, or of giants, or of fairies; a Titania, a Caliban, a Satan, all the heroes of romance.

Imagination sometimes interferes with the correctness of narrative, making it untruthful by interpolating objects trans- planted from other senses or evoked by association. Old per- sons sometimes relate having seen events which occurred be- fore they were born, the descriptions heard in childhood being reproduced by the imagination as actual experiences.

2. Reverie is a voluntary, waking dream. The subject of it gives himself up to the power of association, and imagines him- self passing through a series of events or experiences of va- rious kinds. This power may be cultivated by practice until reverie becomes as capricious, as absorbing, as apparently real as a dream. It may become a confirmed habit, a luxury,

1 66 THE INTELLECT.

a dissipation. It produces new experiences by combining events known or heard of, in a series, making personages, themselves the creation of a similar process, pass through pleasing or diverting scenes, like a stage-play. The poet and the novelist can use this half-conscious play of associative representation to weave their tales, as the kaleidoscope is used by designers of new patterns for carpets and wall-papers.

3. In the poetic or artistic imagination we approach more nearly what is called the creative power of this faculty. Shakespeare says,

"The lunatic, the lover, and the poet, Are of imagination all compact."

Here the ideal element begins to be felt. It is not easy to de- fine the ideal. Some have even denied its existence, and held that the imagination only combines the disjecta membra of ex- perience. But the testimony of the most elevated, noblest minds is very general to the existence, value, and force of an ideal element.

We do not indeed affirm that the ideal is a product solely of the imagination, nor would we say that it is formed or con- structed by any faculty. It is a way of viewing certain subjects, a method of thought and a style of feeling, a product of the emotional and reasoning powers, combined with the imagina- tion.

The painter, the sculptor, the poet, the orator, have lofty views of the value of their respective arts, deep feelings ex- cited by great excellence, strong desires to attain what is worthy, a thorough conviction that great success is attainable in these arts. Now a wide knowledge of art and literature, gained under the impulse of such feelings and convictions as these, not merely furnishes the imagination with a stock of ma- terials, and supplies the mind with the loftiest standards of comparison for the artist's own work, but impresses him with

IMAGINATION. 167

a belief in the nobility of true excellence, and with a passion for success. Under these influences he is never satisfied with what he has done, always feels that he or some one else can do better, and never gives up striving for a higher success.

This mode of thinking and feeling is called a love of the ideal, a worship of the ideal, a service of the ideal, the forma- tion of ideals; not because the imagination forms a definite standard of excellence, for if definite it would not be ideal; but because all the concrete examples which furnish its stock in trade are seen to be imperfect and surpassable. Thus the popular phrase is perfectly justifiable, that we judge ideally, or by an ideal standard; but it is not strictly accurate to say that the imagination constructs such a standard.

Under this head may be placed another remarkable com- bination of the representative and reasoning powers, the so- called mathematical imagination. A line without breadth and perfectly straight, a surface without thickness and perfectly plane, may be said to be ideals, which can never be realized in fact, but which the imagination supplies to every geomet- rical construction. So number is never really abstract, but always concrete, and when we speak of three, or ten, alone, we exercise an abstracting imagination.

The power to isolate a relation of space or of number, re- move it from the concrete, and make this abstraction seem real to us, may well be called imagination, and requires culture in this peculiar line to make it available, as does the artist's feeling of the ideal.

The solution of problems in or by mathematics often comes under the next head, of the scientific imagination.

4. The scientific imagination is used in the framing of hy- potheses. The scientific investigator, seeking the explanation of a phenomenon, frames a supposition; " What if it be thus and so ? " All his knowledge of natural laws, and all possible

1 68 THE INTELLECT.

suppositions which seem to him reasonable, as to new laws of nature, form the material out of which his imagination forms a hypothesis. He then tests this by experiment, calculation, any means in his power. If the result is unfavorable, the proc- ess has probably suggested a new supposition, which can be tried in like manner. Thus Newton formed the hypothesis that the force which binds the moon to the earth, and the earth to the sun, is the same as that which attracts bodies on the surface of the earth, giving them weight. His calculations failed to confirm the supposition. He calculated that the moon would be deflected fifteen feet in a minute, while it is really deflected but thirteen. He laid his calculations aside. Thirteen years afterwards Picard measured an arc of a merid- ian, and found a new value for the earth's diameter. Newton then went over his calculations again, with this new value in- serted, and found them correct. The result confirmed his theory and made him famous. (Fiske, Cosmic Philosophy, I, in.)

"Without an active imagination, philosophical invention and discovery are impossible." (Porter, Hum. Intel., 369.) Prof. J. Tyndall's essay on the Scientific Uses of the Imagina- tion is valuable in this connection.

Every great mechanical invention is the result of a similar process; only, when the first guess proves to be right, it seems an inspiration, though really the result of long mechanical practice or study, supplying the imagination with a fund of materials. But in fact every great mechanical triumph has been the outcome of a vast number of hypotheses constructed in iron and wood, <>fter laid aside and altered, perfected by many steps. The power-loom, the spinning-machine, the locomotive, the sewing-machine, the reaper, the thresher, the chronometer, the blast-furnace, the iron ship, have each been developed by successive efforts of the scientific or mechanical imagination.

IMAGINATION. 169

5. The ethical and religious imagination. Some of the re- marks made upon the artistic imagination are applicable here. The literary artist may produce an ideal character, just as the painter produces an ideal face, by improving, heightening, strengthening, in a word idealizing, an actual one. But he cannot do this unless he has an " ideal standard " already in his mind; but as in art, so here, this does not mean a definite, detailed standard, but an aspiration, a love of moral beauty. The details of the creation will be supplied by the imagination out of the experience, habits, education, observation, etc., of the author, in more or less accordance with public opinion and the tastes of the time.

Moral ideals and rules, however, are difficult to carry in the mind and apply correctly to all actions, in the various and complicated circumstances of life. They are best presented, therefore, concretely, in the person of some one who inspires our admiration, and whom we can imitate. Nearly all relig- ions have their great heroes or founders, whom the people are bidden to imitate. The Christian religion has this great ad- vantage, that it satisfies this longing of the human heart far better than any other religion, and presents in the person of Christ an ideal which abounds in divine perfections, and yet is not perfect in such a way as to repel and discourage the be- liever, but attracts him with a deep sympathy and arouses him to the best thoughts, feelings, and actions.

The " creative imagination " may find ample play in apply- ing the teachings of Christ and his example to all the circum- stances of modern life, answering the questions;— What would He command if He were here ? What would He do if He wtre in my place?

The imagination has no application to spiritual beings. It is limited to the analogies of our present life. Our attempts to imagine pure, unembodied spiritual beings, only result in

i yo THE INTELLECT.

human forms made of thin, transparent matter. Still less can we imagine the Infinite Spirit, the Divine Being. We may form concepts of power, wisdom, and goodness, perhaps of in- finity. We may attempt to join all these together. But for us to imagine a Being of infinite wisdom, power, and goodness, would be for the finite to represent, to image forth, the in- finite. We believe that such a Being exists, but that does not imply that we can image to ourselves his mode of existence.

The words " conception " and " conceive " are sometimes used in connection with the imagination. This may be allow- able in popular language or conversational discourse, but in philosophical language these terms have long been applied in the best usage, to the reasoning power, the faculty of thought- knowledge, of abstractions, and should not now be changed. Dugald Stewart is the only philosopher of note who has used conception in the sense of imagination.

The critics of Mr. Herbert Spencer affirm that he neglects this distinction, and uses the term " conceive " in the sense of imagine. " To think a thing as possible," he says, " is the same as to imagine it." (Psychology, n, 179.) This ob- viously injures the cogency of his celebrated antinomy of the reason, his doctrine that anything must necessarily be true if we cannot " conceive " the opposite; a doctrine which, how- ever, we should reject on other grounds.

PART III. THE REASONING POWER.

The reasoning power is also called the Understanding by Coleridge, Hickok, and many others; the Elaborative Faculty, by Hamilton; Discursive Reason, by Whewell; Dianoetic Fac- ulty, by Aristotle; etc. The correct term should be Reason corresponding to "reasoning," which is used to express what the faculty does. But "reason" has been used by so many writers since Coleridge, to define a supposed faculty of regula- tion which produces a priori concepts or intuitive ideas, that we cannot hope to restore its proper use. We keep as near it as possible in the term " reasoning power."

The functions of the reasoning power may be divided into judgment, abstraction, generalization, and reasoning proper. A product of the Judgment, when actually expressed, is called a judgment, and the phrase in which it is expressed is called a proposition. A product of abstraction is called a concept or notion. A product of generalization is a class. Reasoning proper is of three kinds, analogy, induction, and deduction. The judgment is by some called the faculty of comparison, and considered a separate division, co-ordinate with the understand- ing and the reason. (Kant;

One cause of the confusion of nomenclature on this sub- ject, is the influence of Locke's Essay. "This work is quite as much a treatise on logic and metaphysics as on psychology. It scarcely professes to give a complete and systematic view of the powers of the soul, but is chiefly occupied with the analy-

172 THE INTELLECT.

sis of ideas. . . . Locke gave a direction to all subse- quent writers, even to those who differ from him most materi- ally. Even Reid, in treating of the higher powers, groups them all under Judgment, which he treats quite as much from a logical as from a psychological starting-point." (Porter, Hu- man Intellect, 381.)

JUDGMENT.

We place Judgment first because it is concerned in all the activities of the intellect. In logic the phrase, an act of judg- ment, is used in a more restricted sense, and means the com- paring of two notions which are already formed. For exam- ple, when I say, "grass is green," the concepts "grass" and "green" are both furnished, and the logical judgment only unites them in a judgment, and the phrase expressing this is called a proposition.

But in psychological usage, the judgment is active also in perception. I cannot perceive the grass as green without dis- tinguishing green from other colors. Discrimination, as we have seen, is the very basis of knowledge. A judgment is then, psychologically, an act of the mind, which applies the catego- ries of identity and similarity. For example, suppose I see a distant light in the midst of darkness; I perceive it as some- thing different from the darkness. If it continues for a time, I judge it to be the same, identical, not different. If it changes to a red light, I ju jge it to be qualitatively different, not iden- tical, but similar. If another light of the same color appears, I judge the two to be not identical, but different, separately existent, but alike in one thing, color.

All knowledge implies judgment; we can not know any ob- ject except in some relation. " The secondary, comparative, and logical judgments are all founded on those which are pri- mary, natural, and psychological." (Porter, op. cit, 432.)

When we see a red light, as above, if we know by previous

JUDGMENT. 173

experience that the name of this peculiarity is " red," we apply that knowledge at once, and form the proposition, expressed or implied, " this light is red." If we have never learned the name "red," we can only say, " it is like the other light, like the one I saw last night," and begin the process of forming concepts, classifying, and making names. But if some one tells us, " the name of that color is red," the process is abridged; we attach the name to the concept, and have it ready in the memory for the next similar occasion.

Ordinarily, we learn the name when we learn the object, and the classifying judgment is made for us. When this is not the case a tentative process of naming and classification necessarily begins. When Captain Cook landed some goats on an island of the Pacific, the natives called them horned hogs; on a sim- ilar occasion horses have been called large dogs; the hog and the dog being the only beasts known to them, and the cloven feet of the former classing them with goats. The Romans at first called the elephant bos lucanus, lucanian ox, having first seen them in Lucania. Children often classify in the same imperfect way, calling a cow's horns handles, the gums the fat of the teeth, etc.

In perception we also distinguish the object as different from self, which involves a knowledge of self as different from the object, and is a true act of judgment.

Judgment, therefore, can hardly be called a separate faculty or mental power; or at least the fact should be noticed that it does not isolate itself from other activities. We have already remarked upon the inseparable connection of the various powers of the mind. Each one involves others, and perhaps, if our knowledge were wider and deeper, we might see that each involves and depends upon all the others. It would hence be far better to say, " the mind in perception acts under the categories of identity and similarity, under the condition

174 THE INTELLECT.

of consciousness, under the form of space, under the limita- tions of the senses," than to say "the mind has a faculty of judgment, another of consciousness, etc., and all together make up the power of knowledge." But convenience and common usage compel us to adhere to the ordinary names.

The further discussion of the judgment and its operations belongs to the science of logic. We shall discuss briefly the concept, and the operations of generalization and reasoning, so far only as they seem to require mention as psychological processes. Their complete treatment is far more in keeping with the subject of logic. The logical text-book of President McCosh is especially noteworthy and valuable for its full anu clear treatment of the concept.

THE CONCEPT.

The concept is a product of abstraction and generalization. Let us take a simple example, a red apple. We can, by an act of " analytic attention," called abstraction, think of the quality or attribute "red," apart from the other attributes which make up the mental object, apple. Lotze uses the instance of a tree, which we see at one time covered with green leaves, and at another after it has lost its leaves, and so find that we can sep- arate the attribute, green, from the object tree. (Dictate, Logik, §20.) To the same effect Mr. Herbert Spencer says that we have the "power of recognizing attributes as distin- guished from the objects possessing them, ... a power to recognize attributes in themselves, apart from particular bodies." (Psychology, I, 344-)

This process is called abstraction. The quality or attribute of redness, for example, when we separate it in thought from the being of a single object, is called an abstractum. This does not imply that we can imagine the quality really to exist by itself, apart from any substance to which it belongs, or that we can imagine an apple or a tree without any color. But,

THE CONCEPT. 175

suppose there are several red apples, we can compare them, by an act of judgment, and know that they agree in this respect, know that they all have the same attribute of "red," that is, they all have a like power of occasioning the sensation called red.

This quality, when viewed as the common property of all the members of a class which makes them to be a class, is called a concept. The concept is therefore a " general," a " universal." Now, in what sense this universal really exists, and what its nature is, has been the object of dispute among philosophers and logicians for many centuries. It is not a part of our present plan to give a history of these disputes.

But we affirm that the concept is a mental product, resem- bling in this respect a percept, or a representation. " The con- cept is a purely relative object of knowledge. ... As a mental product and a mental object, it is purely relative, being formed by the mind and understood by the mind as in- differently common to single objects as so to speak, held ever ready by the mind to be affirmed of, and restored to, the single object to which it relates." (Porter, Human Intellect, 392. See also Bowne's Metaphysics, 30.)

Professor Jevons defines concept as; " That which is con- ceived; the result of the act of conception; nearly synony- mous with general notion, idea, thought." Mr. Spencer's re- marks, quoted above, are of the same tenor. Lotze compares mere sensations to round bodies out of which no building can be reared; as only prism-shaped bodies can be formed into a wall, so sensations must be formed into classes, concepts, mental products, before we can think with them. (Dictate, Logik, §6.)

We may remark here that the logical term " notion," and the German " begriff" are generally used in a wider meaning than that given for " concept."

1 76 THE INTELLECT.

Concepts may be classified in various ways. We mention only the division into simple and complex concepts. Those called simple contain but a single attribute, as redness, sour- ness. Those called complex comprehend many attributes, as man, horse. So we may rise from one order of abstrac- tion to another, until we reach such complex objects of thought as nation, civilization, religion, education, nature.

The term classification is used oftener in a higher and wider meaning, of the systematic arrangement of natural ob- jects under higher and lower genera. This operation depends on analysis and comparison. An object is presented to the mind in perception as a complex of properties, parts, and re- lations. It is impossible to compare two objects without sep- arating in thought these properties and relations. We may then, on comparison, form a class of those objects which agree in every observable attribute. Such a class would be in most cases very small. Or, we may form a class of all those ob- jects which agree in only one given attribute, and such a class would usually be very large.

This introduces the distinction between the comprehension and the extension of concepts. The former denotes the num- ber of attributes in which the objects agree, the latter the number of individual objects which belong to the class. The two are therefore always in inverse ratio; for, the slighter the resemblance the larger the class, and the more exact the resem- blance the smaller the class.

We must now briefly describe the three great schools of opinion on this point. We quote the graphic description of Professor Bain. " It was believed by a certain school of phi- losophers, deriving from Plato, that there exists, in the universe of being, a circle in general, or circular form without substance, size, or color; that in like manner, there are archetypal forms of man, of just, of good, etc. After a severe controversy which

THE CONCEPT. 177

raged in the scholastic period, this view was abandoned."

This was the view called realism, and its catchword was, universalia ante rem.

" Another mode of regarding the fact of community in di- versity, is to suppose that the mind can represent to itself, in a notion, the points of agreement by themselves, and can leave entirely out of sight the points of difference. This is con- ceptualism." The catchword of this theory is, universalia in re.

Professor Bain then goes on to describe his own view, which is nominalism and the catchword of which is, uni- versalia post rem. "The final result of the generalizing proc- ess is the abstract name. Such names as motion, weight, breadth, whiteness, melody, roughness, polarity, wisdom, jus- tice, beauty, are called abstract names, as signifying qualities or attributes without reference to the things that possess the qualities. They seem to separate the points of community of agreeing objects themselves, an operation impossible in fact, and even in thought, but supposed by a kind of fiction to be possible." (Bain, Logic, 52.)

We grant that it is impossible so to separate the qualities of objects in fact, and even in imagination, but deny that it is therefore impossible in thought. Yet the quality, when thus thought separately from the object, is not a concept, but only an abstract; it becomes a universal, a concept, when thought as the common quality of several objects, that which makes them a class.

" It is said," says Lotze, " that the unlike parts of our ideas destroy one another, and the similar parts are simply left be- hind, and form the universal. But the simple ideas are not lost; they remain, alongside of the universals, which are added as a new product. Moreover, the general concept is not some- thing which can be represented, pictured, like the examples

12

178 THE INTELLECT.

from which it is derived. Thus, * color in general ' cannot be represented in the mind. Neither can ' animal in general.'

" Such general concepts are not, then, products of a coali- tion of many single ideas, for then they would have the same character [be of the same order] with their components. The names we give them, ' color ' for example, merely summon up a series of single impressions, but with the added thought that we mean, not them, but that in them which is common, though it can never be separated from them as a distinct repre- sentation." (Lotze, Dictate, Psychologic, §23.)

Lotze is usually called a nominalist; but the above passage may fairly be understood as agreeing with the quotations from President Porter, and with our own view.

It is plain, however, that Bain and Mill were required by consistency to be extreme nominalists. For, on their view of the mind, universals must be formed by the automatic action of sensations. Sensations that are more frequently repeated make a deeper impression on the brain, so that when a series of objects occasion sensations, those which are alike are strengthened, while those which are unlike are crowded out and forgotten. Of course on such a theory there is no mental product, no elaboration by the active power of the mind in perception, and hence none in conception. Conception is re- duced to imagination, the power of imaging forth real objects.

But those who hold that the mind is active, interpreting and combining sensations, and forming a mental product by means of them, a percept, should have no difficulty in believing that the mind can superinduce upon this a still higher stage of mental products, the concept.

It is admitted that names are essential to the effective use of concepts, perhaps even to the formation of all but the more simple ones. Still analysis and classification of objects can undoubtedly go on to some extent without language. The

THE CONCEPT. 179

lower animals can form classes of concrete objects, can clas- sify men as different from other animals, sweet grasses as dif- ferent from bitter herbs, etc., but they cannot form concepts of the higher degrees, or true abstracta. Such concepts as justice, truth, beauty, are unknown to them, for these require language to deal with them and make them useful, as well as a higher abstractive power of thought to make them possible.

The general name is really a different product, as is ad- mitted by Bain himself. " The abstract name is not absolutely required for ordinary speech, nor indeed for science. . . . Justice expresses the same thing as just actions. . . . The term signifies just actions in so far as just, or viewed solely with reference to their being just." (Logic, 53.)

But this would be the forming of a concept as a mental product, not a mere name, and would inevitably become con- ceptualism. " What the mind considers is not the name but the meaning or import of the name." (Porter, Human In- tellect, 416.^)

The conceptualist, in like manner sometimes glides into the territory of the realist, by treating concepts as existing by them- selves, apart from the objects from which they are derived, for- getting that they are but mental products, symbols. President McCosh says: " Conceptualism has often taken a wrong form. It does so when it regards the conception combining the objects as an idea in the sense of image. This was the mistake of Locke. . . . But if it avoids these mistakes and over- sights, which are not parts of the doctrine properly understood, conceptualism is the true theory. For in general notions, [concepts] the essential element is the grouping by the mind of objects by common properties, and putting in the group all objects possessing the properties." (Logic 92.)

Dr. McCosh adds the following striking statement of the

i8o THE INTELLECT.

real truth contained in each of these theories, realism, con- ceptualism, and nominalism. "There are universalia ante rent in the Divine Mind. There are universalia in re in natural classes. There are universalia post rem in human concepts and terms."

REASONING PROPER.

Reasoning may be called mediate judgment, or the com- parison of simple judgments. For example, returning to our red apples, if we judge concerning them that they are red, or round, or small, or that they agree or disagree in any way, this is an immediate or simple judgment. If we say, " red apples are good, therefore these apples are good," this is a mediate judgment, that is, one with a middle term, a comparison of judgments.

The two chief forms of reasoning are Deduction and Induc- tion. In the first, as in the example given above, the middle or general term is supplied, with which the first simple judg- ment is to be compared. In the second the general term is to be found. Thus, if I eat a good many red apples and find them all good, I may infer that all red apples are good, and this would be induction.

A complete deductive argument is called a syllogism. The following is an example of the simplest form of syllogism. All men are mortal; the king is a man; therefore the king is mor- tal. Three judgments are involved; the one we have placed first is called the major premise, the second the minor premise, the third the conclusion. The middle term (here man) ap- pears in both premises. The minor term (here king) appears in the conclusion and in one premise. The major term (here mortal) appears in the conclusion and in one premise. With- out a middle term, or with two middle terms there can obviously be no *7alid conclusion.

There are many forms of syllogism, but they can all be re-

REASONING PROPER. 181

duced to this simple form or its corresponding negative, as is shown in any text-book of logic.

Now what is the principle on which this kind of reasoning depends ? Why are we obliged to admit the conclusion when we have admitted that the premises are correct and that the process is regular. Take the simple form, A is equal to B, B is equal to C, therefore A=C. Here the principle of reasoning evidently is, things which are equal to the same thing are equal to one another. But this form, though it resembles a syllo- gism is not one in reality, for all its terms have exactly the same extent, and there is no middle term. But its resemblance may aid us in seeing what kind of a principle or axiom is to be sought.

Strange as it appears, this axiom has been the subject of much dispute. The best known form of the axiom is Aristotle's dictum de om,ni et nullo, which is: " Whatever is true of a class is true also of whatever comes under the class."

Sir W. Hamilton has endeavored to reduce the relation to be expressed to one of extent, and gives the axiom as follows: " Whatever is part of a part, is part of its containing whole." This, though useful for advancing Hamilton's peculiar theories, does not differ, so far as our purpose is concerned, from that of Aristotle.

J. Stuart Mill, at the opposite extreme, reduces the relation to one of content, and gives the axiom thus: " Whatever possesses any mark possesses that which it is a mark of." He says that a middle term may be dispensed with, and that we really reason from particular to particular, without using any general. This, however, does not settle the question; every one knows that we actually reason in that way, but the ques- tion is, Is not the middle term implied when it is not expressed? Mr. Mill would say "The king is a man, and therefore mortal. I know that he is mortal immediately, since he belongs to the human race."

182 THE INTELLECT.

But evidently the middle term is implied, and the ordinary syllogism is only the full expression of the implication. Prof. Bain says: " We have to prove that some object is mortal, not expressly named a man, but designated by some other title, as 'king.' We cannot say, 'men are mortal,' therefore 'kings are mortal;' such an inference can be made only through an in- termediate assertion, 'kings are men.'" (Logic, 156.)

Mr. Herbert Spencer denies that any axiom which it is pos- sible to frame can be "capable of expressing the ratiocinative act." He says: " Reasoning is the indirect establishment of a definite relation between two things. . . Every ratiocin- ative act is the indirect establishment of a definite relation between two things, by the process of establishing a definite relation between two definite relations." " Reasoning presup- poses classification, and classification presupposes reasoning. . . . . They are the different sides of the same thing, the necessary complements of each other." (Psychology, II, 115, 1 1 8.)

This implies, evidently, the " relation- view of propositions," which is, " that every proposition really asserts the manner in which two ' nameble things ' are related to each other." Both terms, that is, of the proposition, are subjects. Mr. Sidgwick says that this theory was suggested by Mill and really appears in parts of his logic, though not avowed by him. (Fallacies

53.)

The theory seems to be merely an attempt to eliminate abstraction and the concept, like that of Bain and Mill men- tioned above, but pushed a little further. It is a result of nominalism, an attempt to use real things in argument, with- out mental products. The full discussion of it belongs to logic. We subjoin a few authorities.

" Syllogism in the strictest sense is inference from the gen- eral to the particular or individual, and in all its forms, infer-

DEDUCTION. 183

ence proceeds from the general." (Ueberweg's Logic, transla- tion, 333.)

" A syllogism is a combination of two judgments, necessitat- ing a third judgment as a consequence of their mutual relation." (Mansel.)

" A syllogism is an enunciation in which, certain assertions being made, by their being true it follows necessarily that another assertion, different from the first, is true also." (Aris- totle.)

The general term is, then, necessary to the syllogism, which is the test-form to which all forms of deductive reasoning can be reduced.

It is sometimes objected that the conclusion of the syllogism does not advance beyond the premises, but is really affirmed in them. Indeed it is a formal canon of books of logic that the conclusion must contain nothing which is not already in- cluded in the premises. This is often called a petitio principii and said to destroy the value of this kind of argument. Its value is certainly reduced by this consideration below the claims of many logicians, but not by any means destroyed.

" It does not follow that the deductive process is therefore superfluous, inasmuch as it may be necessary to develop or draw out that which is already implied or folded up in the premises." (Whately, Logic.)

" Deductive inference may be described as a process of in- terpretation. . . . The deductive inference that the pope is mortal, presupposes an examination of the pope's personality. If this resembles the usual type of humanity, we identify him with the subject 'men' in our general proposition." (Bain, Logic, 211.)

Complete or syllogistic statement of an argument may often be more convincing, or its fallacy may be more easily detected, from bringing the terms more distinctly before the mind. By

184 THE INTELLECT.

supplying the major premise in each of the following argu- ments, its validity or fallacy will be more clearly seen.

"A slave is a human being, and therefore ought not to be held in bondage."

"He is not thirsty, and therefore is not suffering from fever."

"No war is popular, because a war increases taxation."

"The Reformation was accompanied and followed by many disturbances, and is therefore to be condemned."

"All plants contain cellular tissue, hence no animals are plants."

The value of deduction for enlarging our real knowledge is seen to best advantage in the mathematical sciences. No doubt, in a sense, all the truths of geometry are wrapped up in its postulates and axioms; and all the truths of speculative as- tronomy are contained in the law of gravitation. But the in- terpretation, unfolding, explication, of these facts in a shape fit for the human mind to grasp, is a task for the ingenuity and ability of generations of mathematicians and astronomers.

A further question arises; How do we know the major premise is correct, that its statement is true? In mathematical reasoning the truth of the major premise may be contained in the definitions or previously deduced from them. In geome- try, if we define a line as the shortest distance between two points, we may rightly take as a major premise, " all straight lines are shorter than bent ones." Or, if the definition of a triangle implies that it has three sides, we may correctly assert this universally in the major premise.

But in most reasoning there may be room for doubt at this point. How do we know that all men are mortal ? Unless we know this on certain grounds, it is not valid to say that the king is a man and therefore mortal. It is plain that we cannot prove it by simple enumeration, for all men are certainly not dead yet. This introduces us to reasoning by induction.

INDUCTION. 185

INDUCTION.

Induction is the deriving of generals from particulars. "That part of the reasoning process which proceeds from par- ticulars to generals." (Calderwood.) " The arriving at gen- eral propositions by means of observation." (Bain, Logic, 231.)

" Induction is a kind of argument which infers, respecting a whole class, what has been ascertained respecting one or more individuals of that class." (Whately.)

" Induction is the process by which we conclude that what is true of certain individuals of a class is true of the whole class, or that what is true at certain times will be true under similar circumstances at all times." (Mill.)

The following is the best definition of induction as actually employed in science: "The legitimate inference of the un- known from the known, that is, of propositions applicable to cases hitherto unobserved and unexamined from propositions which are known to be true of the cases observed and examined." (Fowler, Inductive Logic, 9.)

Sir Isaac Newton correctly stated the nature of induction in the following passage: "As in mathematics, so in natural phi- losophy, the investigation of difficult things by the method of analysis ought ever to precede the method of composition. This analysis consists in making experiments and observa- tions and in drawing general conclusions from them by induc- tion. And although the arguing from experiments and obser- vations by induction be no demonstration of general conclu- sions, yet it is the best way of arguing which the nature of things admits of, and may be looked upon as so much the stronger by how much the induction is more general." (Quoted by Lewes, Problems, I, 51.)

To reason by induction, then, is to take certain facts, as found by observation or experiment, and place them as rep-

i86 THE INTELLECT.

resentatives of the whole class of objects to which they be- long, assuming that what is true of these few objects is true of the whole class. Obviously the cogency of all arguments founded on such a basis depends on the accuracy and extent of the observations, or else on the nature of the experiments.

For example, if I find that a shilling and a feather fall in the same time in a vacuum, I do not need to try a thousand experi- ments on different objects, gold, paper, wood, lead, before I admit the universality of the fact. A few repetitions with the same objects, simply to eliminate possible errors, are as con- vincing as a hundred, and I am prepared to declare the gen- eral truth that all bodies, not merely silver and feathers, fall with the»same speed in a vacuum.

" When the chemist has shown by a single experiment that nitrogen will not support combustion, we believe it will be just the same through all future time. If we withhold our assent it is from a doubt whether the experiment was properly made." (Fiske, Cosmic Philosophy, I, 55.)

But when the argument concerns more complicated subjects, politics, morals, or even animal life, the danger of mistake is vastly greater, and the number of instances must be propor- tionately larger. A negative conclusion also introduces diffi- culty and doubt. For example,

Aristotle mentioned it as a curious fact that no animal ever died on the sea-shore at the ebbing of the tide. Pliny said this was a mistake, and the statement was true only of man.

The delusion was scientifically disproved only so recently as 1727, and probably still lingers in popular superstition.

To prove the effect of a medicine in disease, as quinine in ague, would evidently require a careful elimination of disturb- ing causes, and many observations. But when a barometer was carried for the first time to the top of a high hill, the press- ure of the atmosphere in all places and times was proved at

INDUCTION. 187

a stroke, never again to be doubted by any one capable of reasoning and acquainted with the subject.

There are some who declare that the step taken by the mind in induction is from particular to particular, not from particu- lars to generals. For example, if I take a barometer to the top of a mountain and the mercury falls, I infer that if I take it upon yonder mountain the mercury will also fall, or that if I bring another barometer upon the same mountain it will fall. But there is just as much ground for drawing the conclusion of one mountain as another, one barometer as another, just as much ground for applying it to all as to one. .The general term is therefore latent, if not expressed.

The axiom on which induction rests has been stated in many forms. The most usual form is that given by Professor Bain, the " Law of the Uniformity of Nature," which he calls the " most fundamental assumption of all human knowledge." " This axiom," he says, is the common ground of all inference, whether avowedly inductive, or induction disguised under the forms of deduction. Without this assumption experience can prove nothing. . . . This must be received without proof; it can repose on nothing more fundamental than itself. If we seem to offer any proof for it, we merely beg it in another shape." (Logic, 227.)

We must call attention to the fact that Bain here distinctly assumes an intuitive origin for this axiom. Mr. Mill, while accepting the axiom as the basis of induction and as true in itself, insists that it is itself derived from experience.

Mr. Herbert Spencer resorts to the law of contradiction as the ultimate test of truth; that is, the law that anything is true if we cannot conceive [imagine] the truth of the opposite. But the contradiction or non-contradiction is to be perceived by human faculties, whose correct and continued operation is thus taken for granted. The dictum can attain no higher certainty

i So THE INTELLECT.

than its source. But the correct and continued operation of the human faculties is a part of the uniformity of nature, and therefore this axiom seems to rest upon the other, and to have no higher certainty.

President Porter does not base induction on any one axiom but mentions six principles or assumptions " which are a priori to the ordinary processes of inductive inquiry." These are, (i) The relation of substance and attribute. (2) The reality of causative energy. (3) The relations of time and space. (4) That nature " is consistent with herself, or uniform in her methods of revealing or suggesting what man is prompted to interpret or explain." (5) That "physical forces are regulated and controlled by design." (6) " That the rational methods of the divine and human intellect are similar."

Many writers accept the uniformity of nature as an axiom, without noticing that in thus making the unchangeableness of nature an intuitive truth, they exclude the possibility of miracles and of creation, if not of intelligent design. It is not at all surprising that evolutionists should rest everything upon the uniformity of nature. Moreover, sensationalists and others who disbelieve in the reality of causation, naturally adopt the same axiom, for they cannot rise higher, to the really intuitive axiom of causation, having excluded it by their assumptions.

But we affirm that the principle or fact of the uniformity of nature is not an axiom in any proper sense of the word, but a generalization from the facts of nature. It is but another name for the ceign of law, the fact that all physical phenomena are subject to law, that is, certain uniformities of causation which men observe, and classify, and call laws. This concep- tion of universal law is a late one in the history of the human mind. Early man supposes the fact to be that all unusual phenomena are the work of supernatural causes. And even in an educated and scientific generation, there are thousands who

INDUCTION. 189

believe in magic of various kinds, by which disease is cured, and other effects are produced without means.

Again, if the world has had a beginning, or if miracles have ever interrupted the chain of causation, or if the world is guided by infinite intelligence toward a moral end, then the assertion of the uniformity of nature, the universality of law, is not correct.

As we have shown when discussing causation, the true axiom is, the uniformity of causation. President Hopkins^ treating of the axiom underlying induction, says : " There is none, except the uniformity of causation. By this we mean that the same causes, operating under the same circumstances, will produce the same effects. Instead of this, modern science assumes as the axiom of induction that nature is uniform. . . . This is the one postulate of mere scientists on which their whole structure rests. But so far is the general proposition that nature is uniform from being at the basis of our induction that it is itself the result of induction." (Outline Study of Man, 1 68.)

This principle of the uniformity of causation evidently de- pends on the reality of efficiency in causation. Indeed, it amounts to this axiom or intuition, that cause is real efficiency, plus the logical principle of identity.

Mr. Lewes states the latter thus: "The validity of conclu- sions rests on the preservation of homogeneity in the terms and the identity of their ratios." (Problems I, 91.) It is always understood as a necessary condition of reasoning that the terms of a judgment remain the same while the judgment lasts. For example, if I say, "Water quenched my thirst yesterday and to-day, hence water has always this property of quenching thirst," I assume that the state of my system will be the same, in any future experiments, that no fever will be present disturb- ing my circulation, that the properties of water will remain the

190 THE INTELLECT.

same, that it will not be impregnated with salt or poison, and will not be lukewarm, etc. All these are really identical prop- ositions, as much so as, a equals a, or, what is is, or, water is water, or, thirst is thirst; while they are so, they will be so.

Indeed, as we showed under causation, if the " uniformity of nature " is true, and so far as it is true, it must have its rational ground in real efficiency of causation.

But much that is called induction is not really so. For example, if I find that water quenches my thirst to-day, I shall probably resort to water to-morrow when I am thirsty. But this does not necessarily imply induction. It may be mere associative expectation, and we find it constantly exercised by the lower animals. It is not induction unless a general truth be derived by the mind, as, in this case, that water always quenches thirst, the circumstances remaining the same.

Of course, the reduction of all reasoning to association or associative expectation is favorable to the hypotheses of evolu- tion and sensationalism. And we contend that the only escape from what is false in these theories, is to be found in the true doctrine of causation. We also contend that this is the only solid bases for induction. Mill bases induction on another induction, as the Hindus found the earth on an elephant, which stands on a tortoise; and Bain is obliged to assume an intuitive axiom, contrary to all his principles.

Further elaboration of the theory of reasoning does not seem necessary to psychology, but belongs to the science of Logic.

THE LOWER ANIMALS.

The curious differences and more curious resemblances be- tween the intelligence of the lower animals and that of the human race, have led to many speculations. Most philoso- phers have been content, however, to ignore the whole subject, and therefore, we cannot quote many great names in support of our conclusions. The truth on this subject lies between two extreme parties.

On the one hand, it was formerly the custom to consider the intelligence of the brutes of a totally different kind from that of man, something mysterious and inexplicable, more the result of divine guidance and implantation than human rea- son.

On the other hand the evolutionist writers of the present day minimize the difference between man and the brutes, and teach that both forms of intelligence are of the same charac- ter, differing only in degree of development and in the nature of the environment.

Mr. H. Spencer has elaborately endeavored to show that there is a gradation by insensible degrees from the lowest forms of sentient existence to the highest achievements of hu- man thought; that there is no break in the progress, no place where a new principle comes in to give a new meaning to as- sociation and sensation. He is therefore obliged to undertake to demonstrate that all reasoning is only comparison, induc- tion is only association, concepts are not mental products but brain products or images, and all the realities of things are un- knowable.

192 THE INTELLECT.

We affirm that the reasoning power is the special endow- ment of man, and constitutes, with the knowledge of moral distinctions, his crown of supremacy over the creation. Even Mr. Lewes sees this truth, and states it as follows.

" When it is said that animals, however intelligent, have no intellect, the meaning is that they have perceptions and judg- ments, but no conceptions, no general ideas, no symbols for logical operations. They are intelligent, for we see them guided to action by judgment; they adapt their actions by means of guiding sensations, and adapt things to their ends. Their mechanism is a sentient, intelligent mechanism. But they have not conception, or what we especially designate as thought, that is, that logical function which deals with gener- alities, ratios, symbols, as feeling deals with particulars and ob- jects." (Problems, I, 142.)

Mr. Lewes proceeds, it is true, to explain this away to some extent, by saying that language is the necessary instrument of these processes of conception and reasoning, without which man would be a mere animal. " Language is the creator and sustainer of that ideal world in which the noblest part of hu- man activity finds a theatre." (154.) This contains an im- portant truth and one often overlooked. The necessity of language to abstract thought is often underestimated. But language is a possession of man, not a faculty. It is the in- tellect of man which requires language, not language which produces intellect.

Many of the brutes have organs well enough adapted for some kind of articulate speech, and some can imitate very well the sounds of the human voice. They could learn to speak if they had any occasion to do so, but they have no thoughts that need any expression beyond the power of cries and gest- ures. " There is no occasion for language proper, and no ability to acquire it, without the power of abstraction. . . .

THE LOWER ANIMALS. 193

So long as the mind deals only with concrete things, their im- ages and the impressions left by them on the memory, they themselves serve as a sufficient attachment to experience, and the only attachment of which it can avail itself. The moment, however, the mind reaches an abstract relation, separates the place, time, and causal dependencies of things from the things themselves, it requires language to designate, retain, and im- part these products of thought. . . . Speech is the su- preme instrument of abstract thought, and all thought proper is abstract." (Bascom, Comparative Psychology, 214.)

The lower animals have no abstract ideas, can form no con- cepts, and can thus have no material of reasoning in the true sense of the word. It is true they perform many actions which are often attributed to reasoning; but in this matter three points should be remembered, (i) There is much con- fusion in the way in which such words as reasoning, induction, thought, etc., are used, and the observers of animals are sel- dom trained to accuracy and carefulness in the use of logical and philosophical terms. (2) There is much looseness of description current on such subjects, although a mere un- noticed trifle may be of fundamental importance toward a right or wrong theory of the subject. There is also much ex- aggeration. (3) Most writers are somewhat under the influ- ence of prejudgment, naturalists in favor of evolution, phi- losophers in favor of the glory of abstract thought.

The mental life of the brutes is associative, and association is an automatic coherence of impressions. They are capable of what some call induction, but that kind of induction is really associative expectation, as we have seen. Real induc- tion results in a universal.

A careful inspection of the most wonderful instincts and feats of intelligence authentically recorded of animals, shows that in manv cases association and automatic action are suffi- 13

194 THE INTELLECT.

cient to account for what has been called the work of reason, and it may fairly be said that probably in all such cases the real difficulty is no greater.

Instinct is a kind of automatic intelligence. " Instinct," says Mr. Herbert Spencer, " may be regarded as a kind of or- ganized memory." (Psychology, I, 445.) It has grown up with the organism, and is really a part of the organism. This is shown by the fact that those animals most remarkable for instinct are incapable of changing their habits, or learning any- thing new, or adapting themselves to new circumstances. A nation of ants or bees is like the Chinese nation. Supersti- tions, habits, customs, ingrained in the brain by centuries of stupid repetition, become so nearly automatic that such a peo- ple cannot conceive of a change, of an improvement, of a dif- ferent order of society. So the ants and bees, having become fully adapted to their environment remain the same even when the environment is changed, with instincts as unchange- able as the superstitions of arrested civilization.

Bees, though taken to a tropical climate, continue to lay up honey, where it is useless to them. Hens often set without eggs. Beavers in captivity sometimes build dams in the cor- ners of the foom. Sir John Lubbock tried to make ants build a bridge, but they would not even lay a bit of straw across a crack in the ground, could not learn anything new. He also showed that " ants and bees communicate little with each other, far less than has been supposed; that they do not report directions and plans, and have but a limited knowledge of them, and move chiefly by scent. They are inattentive to sounds, guide themselves but little by vision, and have very acute scent and touch. These are the senses which favor or- ganic development, while vision, and above all hearing, min- ister to reflection." (Bascom, op. cit, 154.)

" Parasites on bees that could be easily removed by com-

THE LOWER ANIMALS. 195

panions are allowed to remain, the sufferer receiving no aid.

. . If we compare bees and ants with birds, we shall find the latter more free and variable in their constructive methods, not because they show more skill than the insects, but because a larger share of intelligence and a smaller share of instinct go to their composition."

The automatic nature of instinct may also be seen directly. Many instincts are the result of structure, or at least correlated with a peculiar structure. The bee could not build cells with- out the power of secreting wax; the two capabilities are cor- relative. The silk- worm and the spider must be able to spin, and the hornet to make paper, the fighting-ant to secrete poison, and the beetle to generate a strong odor, or their wonderful in- stincts could not be shown to exist. "The organ and the function correlate, and find their simple expression in the in- stinctive action. . . . Nor is it easy to understand how the two could have arisen otherwise than together as parts of the same organic development. . . . The organs can hardly be supposed to have existed without the function, wait- ing for experience to impart it; nor could experience direct its use till the function was present." (Bascom, op. cit. 157, 175.)

A multitude of examples might be quoted of the stupidity of animals, showing their inability to learn, to form new habits, to adapt themselves to new circumstances. The number of such anecdotes is hardly inferior to the stories of their wonder- ful instincts. A young chicken cannot learn from a young turkey the useful art of catching flies. " A hen will adhere to her empty nest, even after violent dissuasion." " After bring- ing a caterpillar to her nest, the wasp always leaves it before the entrance and goes in to see if everything is in order within the cavity. During this absence of the wasp Fabre removed her booty to some distance, forty times in succession. Forty times the wasp brought it back, but each time examined her

196 THE INTELLECT.

nest afresh before she attempted to put her prey into it." (Brehm, in Bascom, 225.)

The training which men sometimes bestow upon the brutes never develops reason, but only forms new associations. Ham- erton remarks of a wonderfully trained company of dogs, that when their master died, no one else could get them to do a single trick. " When the ox obeys a word of command, there is in this obedience no more comprehension of language than when he is quickened by a goad."

If instinct were of the same nature as reasoning, it would be of a vastly higher degree, and would show a stage of knowl- edge in the bee and the spider far above, not below, that of man. If the comb of the bee were planned and made as a man's house is made, it would imply an amount of mathemati- cal knowledge attainable by few men even in this developed age. Such an argument would prove too much. Accordingly, the usual attempt is to reduce the intelligence of man to as- sociation, or automatic action.

Man does not have these strange unreasoning actions, in so far as he does not need them, being guided by a higher asso- ciative power, or by true reason. The new-born child cries when the cold air reaches his lungs, and sucks when his lips feel the breast, and these are automatic actions, like those of wasps and bees. But beyond these he has hardly a trace of instinct proper.

Yet men do actually lead, to a great extent, an associative life, similar to that of the highest of the brutes. Many of our actions and series of actions are guided by habit, require no reasoning, and exhibit no mental activity but association. Who has not heard even a long conversation without a trace of in- tellect, in the sense of reasoning power? Instinct and real intelligence, are always in inverse ratio, as also are association and reasoning. When the mind of a nation becomes stereo-

THE LOWER ANIMALS. 197

typed in superstition and custom, it forgets to a great extent its privilege of true thought, and lives an associative life, little above the brutes.

Beast-minds must of course act in the same manner as the human mind, so far as they are conditioned by the nature of the objects of knowledge. Since the external world exists in space, and cannot otherwise exist, it must be known, if known at all, under relations of space, both by men and by brutes. But the abstract idea of space, the generalized concept, is some- thing which no beast-mind can frame.

There is no approach in the animals to any such capacity. To affirm that they form abstracts and concepts implies a false idea of what abstracts and concepts are, confusing them with images, representations. These two theories are logically in- separable;— (i) That the mind of man is a gradual develop- ment from the intelligence of brutes, without any difference in kind. (2) That concepts and abstracts are the result of the action of a series of objects on the mind, not of the mind on a series of objects.

As to the question, whether the mental life of the animals is a manifestation of an immaterial principle, nothing is really known about it. Some reference will be made to it under the next head.

NATURE OF THE MIND.

Having studied the phenomena of intellect we are prepared to ask understandingly the question: What is the mind, the subject of these phenomena ? Is the term mind only another name for the brain, acting in certain higher relations? Can the phenomena we have described be accounted for on the supposition that thought and feeling and choice are products of the interactions of nerve-cells in the brain? Or are the powers we have discussed too peculiar, too wonderful, too dif- ferent from the properties of matter, to admit such a supposi- tion ? Must we pass over into the realm of the inconceivable, the immaterial, the spiritual, in order to find an agent capable of these functions ?

A theory of the mind not uncommon in ancient times, is that the mind is a product of the harmonious blending of all the powers of the body. The favorite illustration was that as a musical instrument produces music when all its parts are at- tuned and proportioned, so the body produces the soul or mind. But this comparison really favors the opposite theory, for a musical instrument requires a player, or it makes no music, the soul corresponds not to the music, but to the player. But dropping this unfortunate comparison, the soul cannot con- sist in a mere consensus (inbegriff} of all the atoms of the body. The materials of the body are constantly changing. Several times in an average life, it is supposed, they are all removed and replaced, yet the personality remains the same. Limbs

NATURE OF THE MIND. 199

may be lost, senses destroyed, yet the mind not seriously im- paired. The whole body therefore cannot be the producer of the mind.

A somewhat similar view is the modern theory that the mind is a series of sensations and feelings. This is rather held dog- matically than attempted to be proved by the sensationalist school of writers. Especially since Mr. Mill admitted that this series of sensations must be held to be aware of itself as past and future, and that "this theory has intrinsic difficulties which it seems to me beyond the power of metaphysical analysis to remove," the theory has had but little vitality of its own. We have already referred to the difficulties of this view. It is really indistinguishable from materialism. For, to say that a series of sensations passively received makes up the mind is to say that the mind is a function of the brain. All other phi- losophers mean by the mind that which thinks, that which has a series of sensations. It is absurd to say that a series of sen- sations has a series of sensations, either actively or passively. This view can really mean nothing but that the brain is the mind. These writers are thus endeavoring, by using the term mind in a new and strange signification, not equivalent to "that which thinks," to escape the charge of materialism.

Mr. H. Spencer has grafted the associationalist psychology upon the hypothesis of evolution. He recognizes the absurd- ity of defining mind as a series of sensations. " The feelings called sensations cannot of themselves constitute mind. . . Mind is constituted only when each sensation is assimilated to the faint forms of antecedent like sensations." (Psychology, I, 185.) This means, we suppose, that memory is an essential power of mind. Again; " The progress of correspondence between the organism and its environment necessitates a gradual reduction of the sensorial changes to a succession, and by so doing evolves a distinct consciousness, a conscious-

200 THE INTELLECT.

ness that becomes higher as the succession becomes more rapid and the correspondence more complete." (I, 403.)

Why successive changes necessitate consciousness Mr. Spencer does not explain; but these and other passages seem to imply that, at a certain stage of progress, there arises a new kind of being, capable of memory and consciousness. Accordingly, he has a chapter on the "Substance of Mind," in which he undertakes to prove that if there be any substance underlying the phenomena it must be unknowable. " If every state of mind is some modification of this substance of mind, there can be no state of mind in which the unmodified substance of mind is present." (I, 146.) Very true! Substance is known only through phenomena, as all philosophers admit. Being, apart from quality, relation, or phenomenon, is equiva- lent to non-being. Again he says: " Knowledge implies something known, and something which knows." (II, 307.)

But in many other passages Mr. Spencer speaks of mind very much as do Bain and Mill. He speaks of " the succes- sive changes which constitute intelligence." (I, 403.) He says; "The proximate components of mind are of two broadly contrasted kinds, feelings and the relations between feelings." (I, 163) "The multitudinous forms of mind known as different feelings may be composed of simpler units of feeling." (I, 156.)

The origin of mind he describes as follows. " As soon as the organism, feebly sensitive to a jar or vibration propagated through its medium, contracts itself so as to be in less danger from the adjacent source of disturbance, we perceive a nas- cent form of the life classed as psychical." (I, 392.) But such actions are plainly automatic; mind, then, on this theory* is not that which thinks and feels, but something made up of nervous shocks. Indeed, he uses this very phrase " nervous shocks " in just this way. Professor Fiske, in " Cosmic Phi-

NATURE OF THE MIND. 201

losophy," tendered the amendment, " psychical shocks," which Mr. Spencer accepted as expressing his meaning, showing that in his view nervous shocks and psychical shocks are only differ- ent names for the same phenomena.

Mr. Spencer admits, in the following passages, that his theory is inadequate to account for the phenomena commonly known as mental action. " Even could we succeed in proving that mind consists of homogeneous units of feeling of the nature specified, we should be unable to say whai the mind is. . . Let it be granted that all existence distinguished as subjective is resolvable into units of consciousness, similar in kind to those which we know as nervous shocks, each of which is a correlative of a rythmical motion of a material unit or group of such units. Cam we then think of the subjective and ob- jective activities as the same ? Can the oscillations of a mole- cule be represented in consciousness side by side with a nerv- ous shock, and the two be recognized as one ? No effort enables us to assimilate them. That a unit of feeling has nothing in common with a unit of motion becomes more than ever manifest when we bring the two into juxtaposition." (I,

157, 158.)

All views of this character proceed on the supposition that matter is not the dead, merely space-filling reality of the ordi- nary view, but afar different thing, "having within it the promise and potency of all terrestrial life," and so of mental phenomena also. " Materialistic views which really have any faith in their own affirmations, proceed from the assumption that ' matter ' is something far better than the name denotes, or than it appears from the outside, but has a property of its own, out of which spiritual states are developed, just as out of another property are developed extension, impenetrability, etc." (Lotze, Dictate, Psychologic, §60.)

But to affirm that there is but one substance, a " two-faced

2O2 THE INTELLECT.

somewhat," with two sets of attributes, physical on one side and mental on the other, is a doctrine not practically distin- guishable from pantheism. It matters little whether we call the one substance Matter, or God, and the system pantheism, or materialism, or cosmism, it meets with all the difficulties and objections of pantheism.

The psychological objection to such a scheme is, that it can- not account for the phenomena of the unity of consciousness, and the individuality of minds, (i) Unity of consciousness cannot arise from a congeries of material atoms. The phi- losophers who hold this theory make much of atoms, molecules, elements, nerve-cells, and the interaction of these elements, whether these things are consistent with their monism or not. A consciousness resulting from a consensus of such atoms or elements should be manifold or fragmentary. All analogies of reasoning require that, in order to produce a unitary con- sciousness out of such a collection of elements, there should be some dominant entity, perduring throughout the changes of the atoms, and making use of them for higher ends.

" It is impossible," says Lotze, " on this view to conceive that unity of consciousness which is a fact of experience, and which must not be arbitrarily withdrawn because it is mysteri- ous, in order to explain the rest more easily." And he goes on, in a passage too long for quotation, to show that all physical analo- gies, such as the new force which is the resultant of the com- position of forces, are inapplicable and misleading. (Dictate, Psychologic, §61.)

What has to be accounted for is not simply a series of feelings, but a "series aware of itself;" the ineradicable be- lief in the unity and identity of the thinking principle of each person. (See D*bal, empirische Psychologic, 15.)

(2) The conscious separate individuality of each mind, is inexplicable on such a theory. If matter be a continuous sub-

NATURE OF THE MIND. 203

stance, underlying with its single being all atoms and molecules, and endowed with divine as well as material attributes, this might be conceived to account for a kind of diffused intelli- gence or omniscience, as in the pantheistic hypothesis, or to account for a consciousness residing in each molecule sepa- rately, but it cannot account for an individual consciousness, of limited extent. Mr. Spencer, accordingly, speaks constantly of " mind," the origin and composition and substance of mind, not of "a mind," my mind, or your mind.

" The notion of an indefinite thought-stuff, which admits of integration, implicitly assumes the materiality of thought, and results from the fancy that thoughts may be found among external objects. But thoughts are acts, and not stuff or material. As such they must have a subject. My thoughts demand a subject, and that subject is myself. As such sub- ject or agent, I am a substance, in the only intelligible sense of that word." (Bowne, Metaphysics, 382.)

It is then mere assumption to declare that the brain is capa- ble of producing all the mental phenomena, without any higher principle, by reason of the double set of attributes pertaining to the atoms or molecules of which it is composed. And a multitude of facts about the brain go to show this result correct.

i. Structure and development of brain and mental capacity are not always in proportion, either in man or in the lower animals. The brain of the mollusk is not less developed than that of the insect, but the latter is capable of far higher " psy- chical action," even higher than fishes and amphibia, though these far more nearly resemble man in nervous structure. The monkey tribe most resemble man, but elephants and dogs are more intelligent. The brain of the dolphin is commonly said to be the most developed of the lower animals, but no great mental gifts accompany it. The brain-structure of the pachy- derms, elephants and swine, do not differ much, it is said, but

204 THE INTELLECT.

the difference in intellect is great. The brains of idiots, ac- cording to Longet, are sometimes larger and with completer convolutions than those of highly gifted men.

2. Disease or accident has removed parts of the brain with- out destroying the integrity of thought or memory. Longet relates a case where a young man lost an entire hemisphere of the brain without conspicuous loss of mental power. Volkman describes the case of a man who shot two balls into his head, lost a large quantity of brain, and became blind, but was stronger in intellect than before.

3. Size of brain, either absolute or relative, furnishes no criterion of mental ability. Elephants and whales have larger brains than men. But some animals are said to have larger brains in proportion to their weight than men. If the author- ity of Cuvier be not sufficient to establish this last proposition, we may yet affirm, on the authority of Huxley, that the differ- ences in cranial capacity among men are far greater than between men and apes. But the mental differences among men, on the contrary, are far smaller than between men and apes.

These considerations seem sufficient to establish the view that the brain is not an adequate cause of mental action. " The uncritical imagination is, of course, much impressed by the excessive fineness of the elements, and by the darkness which surrounds brain-physiology; and this darkness and mystery pass for argument. . . . But the question as to the reality of the soul does not depend on brain-physiology at all. The question turns on the nature of consciousness and on the im- possibility of producing the one from the many and the iden- tical from the numerically changing. So long as these ideas are hostile and mutually exclusive, so long will materialism be impossible as a rational theory." (Bowne, Metaphysics, 375.)

The phenomena of the human intellect, then, seem to re-

NATURE OF THE MIN

quire as their ground a simple, individual, unitary substance in each person, of a different nature from matter, yet able to be in connection with a material organism.

This supposition does not indeed obviate all difficulties. It would be to be supposed that on such a subject human faculties would be able to trace but a very little way the hidden reality. We make no pretensions to solving all the problems, or an- swering all the questions which can arise. But, on the other hand, the most candid representatives of evolutionism and empiricism also disclaim all such pretensions. "The latest results," says Mr. Fiske, " of scientific inquiry, whether in the region of objective psychology cr molecular physics, leave the gulf between matter and mind quite as wide as it was judged to be in the time of Descartes." (Cosmic Philosophy, II, 445.)

But if we accept the doctrine of the individuality, unity, sim- plicity, and immateriality of the human soul, there arises an interesting question, How far do the mental phenomena of the lower animals compel us to the same conclusion with refer- ence to beast-souls? Very little is known on which to base an argument on this point, but the following considerations seem to us of weight.

1. We know- so little about the consciousness of the brutes that we cannot confidently say whether it is of such a nature, as to require a simple and individual subject in each animal.

2. It is not at all certain that immateriality involves either immortality or moral freedom; so that we may perhaps admit an immaterial substratum of physical life, or of the mental life of the brutes, without in the least derogating from the superior dignity of the human soul and intellect.

3. We have seen reason to believe that man has mental powers higher in kind and not simply in degree than those cf the brutes. If this be accepted, we may perhaps even hold that man's physical system and associative mental life are the

206 THE INTELLECT.

product of evolution, but that at a certain time God breathed into man a nobler spirit, endowed him with personality and immortality.

Another solution should be mentioned, as ot import c in the history of thought, namely the theory of metempsychosis. Philosophers of a certain turn of mind have been wont in all ages to believe that souls pass through lower stages of existence in various lower animals before entering human bodies, and may return again to the bottom round of the ladder of being, to begin once more their weary ascent, as a punishment for sin. This is poetic imagination, not sober speculation.

Another interesting question is the location of the soul in the body. If it be immaterial we cannot probably properly speak of it as being in any point or points of space. Yet many writers, though accepting the immateriality of the soul, have sought to discover its location in the body. Descartes placed it in a part of the brain called the pineal gland, which however, is not a gland at all, and is now known to be of no more importance to the mental life than any other part of the brain. Others have located it in the whole cerebrum, and some in the whole body.

Lotze, accepting the Herbartian doctrine that the soul is a single element, a monad, yet declares that it may occupy more than one point of space at the same time, in the brain or the body.

More important is the question of the relation of soul and body. That there is such a connection, that each has a wonderful power over the other, has been a commonplace of philosophy for many ages. A vast number of instances, many of them very familiar, might be repeated. How soul and body operate on each other, either in these abnormal ways, or in ordinary perception or volition, cannot be said to be within the range of human investigation. The pantheistic or monistic explanation, that

NATURE OF THE MIND. 207

they are both of the same essence, seems at first promising. But on reflection we see that it is just as hard to understand how changes in one set of qualities can produce changes or motions in another set of qualities of the same substance, as it is to understand how two distinct substances can operate on one another. Monism, whether it spiritualizes matter or materializes spirit, can afford no real assistance.

The mystery and difficulty may, however, be divided, if not diminished by the reflection that action and reaction between two atoms of matter are just as inexplicable and mysterious as the mutual influence of soul and body. But here we are look- ing over the boundary of the field of metaphysics, to enter which the present is not a proper occasion. (See Bowne's Metaphysics, 113.)

The subject of the immortality of the soul belongs to the science of theology.

INDEX.

ABSOLUTE, the, 109.

ABSTRACTION, 174.

ANIMALS, the lower, sensation in, 1 8 ; vision in, 34, 42 ; judgment of distance by, 45 ; consciousness in, 78 ; intellect of, 79 ; knowl- edge of space by, 91; knowledge of time by, 95 ; knowledge of identity-similarity by, 114; the nature of their intelligence, 190; cannot truly reason, 179, 193 ; their stupidity, 195; nature of their minds, 205.

ANIMAL Spirits, in Descartes' the- ory of perception, 132.

A PRIORI school, 85 ; concepts, 117.

ARISTOTLE, sketch of, 129 ; on the necessity of philosophy, 6 ; on its utility, 8 ; definition of phi- losophy, 10 ; on the qualities of matter, 69 ; association of ideas, 155 ; his dictum de omni et nullo. 181 ; definition of the syllogism, 183 ; curious delusion mentioned by, 1 86.

ASSOCIATION of sensations, 23 ; in hearing, 33 ; in vision, 47 ; in muscular sensation, 54 ; in local- ization. 56 ; in illusions, 58; not the source of the causal judg- ment, 103, 104 ; not the agent in perception, 125; of ideas, 154; law of, 155 ; often called induc- tion, 190; forms the mental life of the brutes, 193 ; and a large part of the life of men, 196.

ASSOCIATIONAL School, 140.

ATTENTION, 64.

AXIOM of the syllogism, 181 ; of induction, 187.

BACON, on design in nature, no.

BAIN, sketch of, 142 ; on the men- tal faculties, 14 ; discrimination, 19 ; tone of sensations, 20 ; irri- tating smells, 25 ; colloid bodies, 28; perception of distance, 33, 44, 47 ; perception of form, 39, 40 ; binocular vision, 49 ; sense of touch, 51 ; muscular sense, 52 ; feeling, 60 ; causation, 101 ; uniformity in Nature, 102 ; iden- tity and similarity, 115,118; the- ory of perception, 143 ; realism and nominalism, 176 ; the syllo- gism, 183 ; induction, 185 ; uni- formity, 187.

BASCOM (President John), on the eyes of oysters, 18 ; conscious- ness in the lower animals, 78 ; their knowledge of space, 91 ; of time, 95 ; they have no need of language, 192 ; their instincts unimprovable, 195.

BERKELEY, sketch of, 138 ; theory of vision, 24, 47 ; of matter, 73, 139-

BOWEN (Prof. Francis), on the ne- cessity of philosophy, 5, 6; Kant's theory of space, 89 ; Descartes, 131 ; Malebranche, 135.

BOWNE (Prof. B. P.), on Kant's thing-in-itself, 74 ; monism, 109; sensationalism, 120 ; the concept, 175 ; brain and mind, 204.

INDEX.

209

BRCHV?*, sketch of, 141 ; on the philosophical spirit, 7; the ex- ternal world, 41; causation, 101, 103, 104 ; on association of ideas, 155.

CALCULUS, the infinitesimal, 133.

CALDERVVOOD, definition of philos- ophy, 10 ; of sensation, 17 ; of attention, 65; on identity, 116; definition of intuition, 122 ; of imagination, 164; induction, 185.

CARPENTER (Dr. W. B.), defini- tion of sensation, 17, 1.8; defini- tion of perception, 22 ; on per- ception of solidity, 46 ; the pseu- doscope, 47 ; localization, 55, 57 ; attention, 66.

CAUSATION, 97-110.

CLASSIFICATION, 173, 176.

COCKER (Prof. B. F.), on scienc and philosophy, 6 ; definition o perception, 22 ; on conscious- ness, 84 ; criteria of necessary principles, 124.

CCEN.^STHESIS, or vital sense, 130.

COGNITION, necessary elements o , 117.

COLLOID state, 27.

COLOR, 35 ; color-blindness, 36.

COMPOUND perceptions, 24.

COMPTE, on consciousness, 77.

CONCEPTION, 170.

CONCEPT, the, 174 ; concepts, 176.

CONCEPTUALISM, 179.

CONDILLAC, notice of, 140.

CONSCIOUSNESS, 74; authority or, 80 ; uses of the term, 83.

CRITERIA of necessary principles, 123.

DEDUCTION, 180.

DESCARTES, sketch of, 131; on th qualities of matter, 69 ; h.s ' ' Cogito, ergo sum , " 8 1 .

DESIGN in nature, no.

DIRECTION, perception of, 43.

DISTANCE, perception of, 44.

DRBAL (Dr. M. A.), on binocula' vision, 48 ; projection of sensa- tions, 57; feeling in sensation. 61 ; attention, 64 ;- unity of thj mind, 202.

DREAMS, 91, 159.

EGO, the, 76, 80.

EMPIRICAL School, 118, 140.

EUKEN (Prof. Rudolph), on teleol- ogy, in ; necessary elements of cognition, 120.

EXPERIENTAL philosophy, 140.

EXTENSION, perception of, 37.

EXTERNAL world, knowledge of, in smell, 27 ; in taste, 29 ; in hearing, 32 ; in vision, 39 ; in touch, 51 ; in muscular sensa- tion, 52.

EYE, the, 33, 44.

FACULTY, defined, 12.

FEELING in sensation, 59 ; uses of term feeling, 60.

FERRIKR (Prof. James), definition of philosophy, 10; his system of metaphysics, 75.

FISKE (John), on causality, 102 ; similarity, 117 ; Cosmic Philoso- phy, 144 ; on induction, 186 ; the gulf between matter and mind, 205.

FLEMING (Prof. Wm.), definition of philosophy, IO ; of sensation, 17, 60 ; on Kant's Theory of Space, 88. The additions to Fleming's Vocabulary of Phil s- ophy, by Calderwood and Krauth, are assigned to their own names.

FORGETTING, 150.

FORM, perception of in vision, 38.

FOWLER (Prof. Thomas), on in- duction, 185.

GRAHAM, on dialysis and the col- loid state, 27.

HALLUCINATION, 59, 162.

HAMILTON (Sir \Villiam), sketch of, 145 ; on the value of phil >so- phy, 8 ; feeling and sensation, 62 ; qualities of matter, 71 ; con- sciousness, 83 ; space, 85, 89; causation, 101, 106; relativity of knowledge, 113; intuition, 122; regulative faculty, 123 ; criterion of necessary principles, 124; the- ories of perception, 128; on as- sociation of ideas, 155; imagi-

210

INDEX.

nation, 163 ; his axiom of the syllogism, 181.

HEARING, sense of, 30.

HELMHOLTZ, on the necessity of philosophy, 5 ; on sound, 31.

HERBART, sketch of, 134 ; on feel- ing in sensation, 6 1 ; space, 88 ; his theory of perception, 134.

HOBBES, on sensation, 1 8.

HOMER, on dreams, 160.

HOPKINS (President Mark), on the knowledge of the external world, 41, 52 j causation, 103 ; the ax- iom of induction, 189.

HUME, notice of, 139 ; on sub- stance, 73 ; causation, 101 ; as- sociation, 155.

HUXLEY, on sensation, 15 ; com- bines materialism and pseudo- idealism, 140.

HYPNOTISM, 162.

HYPOTHESIS, 167.

IDEALISM, 128.

IDENTITY, 112,

ILLUSIONS, 58.

IMAGINATION, 163.

INDUCTION, 185 ; necessity of a general term for, 187 ; ofien con- fused with associative expecta- tion, 190.

INSTINCT, 193.

INTUITIVE ideas, 117.

INVERSION of the image in vision, 42.

JEVONS, on the concept, 175.

JUDGMENT, 172.

KANT, noticed, 139 ; on substance, 73 ; space, 88 ; time, 93 ; the Judgment, 171.

LANGUAGE, consists of arbitrary symbols, 32 ; how fa.' necessary for reasoning, 192.

LAW of Parcimony, 107.

LE CONTE (Prof. Joseph), on the sensitive spot of the retina, 34 ; primary colors, 36 ; binocular vision, 46, 48.

LEIBNITZ, sketch of, 133; on space, 88 ; his monadology, 107 ; his theodicy, 134.

LEWES (G. H ), on science and philosophy, 6 ; causation, 105 ; "inherited intuitions," 119 ; in- duction, 189 ; the intellect of the lower animals, 192 ; lan^ua^e, 192.

LOCALIZATION, 54.

LOCKE, sketch of, 136; on ideas, 20 ; qualities of matter, 70 ; con- sciousness, 76 ; space, 85 ; iden- tity, 116; "intuitive ideas," 117; theory of perception, 137 ; on the reasoning power, 171.

LOGIC, origin of, 130.

LOTZE, sketch of, 135 ; definition of philosophy, etc., 9 ; use of "natur- philosophic," 10 ; on sensation, 16, 19 ; perception, 22 ; sense of taste, 28 ; inverted imnge in vision, 43 ; muscular sensation, 53 ; feeling in sensa- tion, 61 ; impenetrabilry, 72 ; qualities of matter, 74 ; space, 88, 89 ; Herbart's doctrine of space, 88 ; m-dimensional space, 90 ; time, 63 ; causation, 98 ; monism, 109 ; identity and simi- larity, 112 ; the concept, 174-5 > universals, 177 ; materialism, 201 ; unity of the mind, 202 ; the soul a monad, 206. IAHAFFY (Prof. J. P.), on Des- cartes, 131-2.

MAINE DE BIRAN, on causation, 105.

vlALEBRANCHE, notice of, 135.

MANSEL, definition of metaphysics, 9; of the syllogism, 183.

MARTINEAU (Rev. James), on per- ception, 22 ; the ignoble senses, 29.

MATHEMATICAL reasoning, 184.

MATTER, qualities of, 67 ; essence of, according to Descartes, 69 ; nature of, 71, 134, 140, 201 ; knowledge of, 127 ; Mill's defi- nition of, 142 ; evolutionist view of, 201.

McCosH (President James), on cau- sation, 103 ; relativity of knowl-

INDEX.

211

edge, 113; Sir Wm. Hamilton, 114; conceptualism, 179; uni- versals, 180.

MECHANICAL imagination, 168.

MEMORY, 95, 147.

METAPHYSICS, defined, 8.

METEMPSYCHOSIS, 206.

MILL (James), 141.

MILL (John Stuart), sketch of, 141; on substance and attribute, 73; causation, 102 ; uniformity, 103 ; relativity of knowledge, 113; necessary principles, 119; limits of association, 120; definition of matter, 142 ; his axiom of the syllogism, 181 ; induction, 185.

MIND, sensational theory of, 80, 199 ; unity of, 202 ; individual- ity, 203 ; immateriality, 203 ; mind and brain, 204.

MONADOLOGY, 107.

MONISM, 109, 207.

MORRIS (Pro!. Geo. S.), definition of philosophy, 10 ; on Mr. J. S. M.il, 119.

MUSCULAR sensation, 52.

NECESSARY elements of perception, 84.

NECESSITY, the criterion of "intui- tive ideas," 124.

NEWTON (Sir Isaac), on space and time, 96 ; gravitation, 168 ; in- duction, 195.

NOISE and music, 30.

NOMINALISM, 177-8.

NOUMENON, 74.

OCCAM'S razor; 107.

ODYLE, Reichenbach's, 67.

PANTHEISM, 202, 207.

PERCEPT, definition of, 23.

PERCEPTION, involves the whole intellect, 13 ; definitions of, 22 ; different kinds of, 23 ; in smell, 27 ; in taste, 29 ; in hearing, 32; in simple vision, 37 ; in associ- ated vision, 39 ; in persons cured of cataract, 41 ; of direction, 43 ; of distance, 44 ; of solidity, 46 ; in touch, 51 ; in muscular sen- sation, 53 ; of one's own body,

55 ; errors in, 58, 66 ; in inverse ratio with feeling, 62 ; of matter, 73 ; unconscious, 81 ; necessary elements of, 84 ; under space- relations, 87 ; under causation, 98; under identity, 113; doc- trine of, 125; theories of, 126.

PHILOSOPHY, defined, 5, 9, 10 ; necessity of, 6 ; pleasures of, 7 ; departments of, 10.

PLATO, sketch of, 129.

PORTER, sketch of, 145 ; on per- ception in hearing, 33 ; localiza- tion, 57; feeling in sensation, 60 ; attention, 65 ; substance, 74; consciousness, 77, 80, 8l, 83 ; space, time, etc., 92, 95 ; causation, 100 ; necessary prin- ciples, 121, 124; sense-percep- tion, 127 ; theory of perception, 146 ; on imagination, 164 ; on induction, 1 88.

.RE-ESTABLISHED harmony, 109,

133-

PRESENTATIVE power, defined, 13;

how discussed, 15. PSH.UDOSCOPE, 47. PSYCHOLOGY, defined, n, 12. QUALITIES of matter, 67 ; quality

and substance, 73. REALISM, 128, 176. REASON, the, 122, 171. REASONING power, 171. -SEASONING proper, 180.

vECOLLECTION, 147. lEGULATIVE faculty, 122.

IEICHENBACH, on hypnotism, 67. REID, notice of, 144 ; use of the

term perception, 22 ; on time,

95.

RELATIVITY of knowledge, 113. REMINISCENCE, 148. REPRESENTATIVE power, 147. REPRODUCTION, 147, 156. RETENTIVENESS, 147. REVERIE, 165. RUSKIN, on perception in vision,

SCHELLING, definition of philoso- phy, 10.

212

INDEX,

SCHOOLMEN, the, 130. SCHOPENHAUER, on space and time

95-

SCIENCE, and metaphysics, 5, 6.

SCIENTIFIC imagination, 167.

SCIENTIFIC induction, 186.

SELF, 79.

SENSATION, defined, 15, 17 ; de scribed, 16; nature of, 18 ; cuI ture or loss of, 19; feeling in,

59-

SENSATIONAL school, 140.

SENSATIONS, classified, 20 ; cohe- rence of, 24; projection of, 54 ; rhythm of, 54 ; unconscious, 82.

SENSE-PKRCEPTION, 23.

SENSORIUM, defined, 17.

SHAKESPEARE, on memory, 158 ; imagination, 165 6.

SIDGWICK (Prof. A.), on the rela- tional view of propositions, 182.

SIGHT, sense of, 33.

SIMILARITY, 112.

SMELL, sense of, 25.

SOLIDITY, perception of, 46.

SOMNAMBULISM, 91, 152, 161.

SPACE, 84, 90.

SPENCER (Herbert), sketch of, 143; on sensation, 15, 17, 18 ; rudi- mentary vision, 42 ; the sense of touch, 49; feeling in sensation, 64 ; attention, 66 ; qualities of matter, 72 ; consciousness, 77, 83; space, 88; identity, 113; similarity, 117 ; necessary prin- ciples, 119; the unknowable, 144; memory, 158; conception, 170; the concept, 174; the syl- logism, 182; his "law of con- tradiction," 187; on the intellect of the lower animals, 191 j com-

bines the associational psychol- ogy with evolutionism, 199.

SPINOZA, notice of, 136.

SUBJECTIVE sensations, 32.

SUBSTANCE, 73.

SYLLOGISM, the, 180; definitions of, 182.

TAINE (H. A.), on the pitch of sounds, 31 ; persons cured of cataract, 41 ; theory that percep- tion is hallucination, 57.

TASTE, sense of, 27.

TELEOLOGY, 1 10.

TELEOPHOBIA, in.

THING-IN-ITSELF, of Kant, 74,

TIMK, 92 ; time and space, 9$.

TOUCH, sense of, 49.

TYNDALL (John), on perception, 17 ; on sound, 31.

UEKERWEG, on Herbart, 135; defi- nition of the syllogi-m, 183.

UNCONSCIOUS perception. Si; cer- ebration, 160.

UNDERSTANDING, the, 171.

UNIFORMITY of Nature, 188.

JNIVERSALS, 177, 180.

VENTRILOQUISM, 32.

VISION, 33 ; in the lower animals, 34, 42» 45 » minuteness of, 35 ; in persons cured of cataract, 41 ; binocular, 46, 48 ; importance of in perception, 127-8.

VISION of all things in God. 135.

WALLACE (Prof. Edwin), on Aris- totle's doctrine of perception, 130.

WEBER, on discriminative touch, 50.

VHATELY, on the syllogism, 183; on induction, 185.

mi '~^'^(~\r\ I "N -M ,-r

BERKELEY LIBRARIES