E8E00 LOLI wil OLNOHOL 4O AL lll AIND) a ROA THE INFLUENCE OF DARWIN ON PHILOSOPHY And Other Essays in Contemporary Thought BY JOHN DEWEY Professor of Philosophy in Columbia University NEW YORK — HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY | Be ie D431 4 1910 cop.2 CopyriGuHt, 1910, BY HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY Published April, 1910 PREFACE Aw elaborate preface to a philosophic work usually impresses one as a last desperate effort on the part of its author to convey what he feels he has not quite managed to say in the body of his book. Nevertheless, a collection of essays on various topics written during a series of years may perhaps find room for an independent word to indicate the kind of unity they seem, to their writer, to possess. Probably every one acquainted with present philosophic thought—found, with some notable exceptions, in periodicals rather than in books—would term it a philosophy of transition and reconstruction. Its various repre- sentatives agree in what they oppose—the ortho- dox British empiricism of two generations ago and the orthodox Neo-Kantian idealism of the last generation—rather than in what they proffer. The essays of this volume belong, I suppose, to what has come to be known (since the earlier of them were written) as the pragmatic phase of the newer movement. Now a recent German critic has described pragmatism as, ‘“ Epistemologically, nominalism; psychologically, voluntarism; cosmo- logically, energism; metaphysically, agnosticism ; ethically, meliorism on the basis of the Bentham- ili iv : PREFACE Mill utilitarianism.” * It may be that pragmatism will turn out to be all of this formidable array; but even should it, the one who thus defines it has hardly come within earshot of it. For whatever else pragmatism is or is not, the pragmatic spirit | is primarily a revolt against that habit of mind which disposes of anything whatever—even so humble an affair as a new method in Philosophy— by tucking it away, after this fashion, in the pigeon holes of a filing cabinet. There are other vital phases of contemporary transition and revi- sion; there are, for example, a new realism and naturalistic idealism. When I recall that I find myself more interested (even though their repre- sentatives might decline to reciprocate) in such phases than in the systems marked by the labels of our German critic, I am confirmed in a belief that after all it is better to view pragmatism quite vaguely as part and parcel of a general move- ment of intellectual reconstruction. For other- wise we seem to have no recourse save to define pragmatism—as does our German author—in terms of the very past systems against which it is a reaction; or, in escaping that alternative, to re- gard it as a fixed rival system making like claim to i 1 The affair is even more portentous in the German with its capital letters and series of muses: “ Gewiss ist der Pragmatismus erkenntnisstheoretisch Nominalismus, psy- chologisch WVoluntarismus, naturphilosophisch Energismus, metaphysisch Agnosticismus, ethisch Méeliorismus auf Grundlage des Bentham-Millschen Utilitarismus.” PREFACE v completeness and finality. And if, as I believe, one of the marked traits of the pragmatic movement is just the surrender of every such claim, how have we furthered our understanding of pragmatism? Classic philosophies have to be revised because ’~they must be squared up with the many social and intellectual tendencies that have revealed themselves since those philosophies matured. ‘The conquest of the sciences by the experimental method of inquiry; the injection of evolutionary — ash ideas into the study of life and society; the ap- plication of the historic method to religions and morals as well as to institutions; the creation of the sciences of “origins” and of the cultural development of mankind—how can such intellec- tual changes occur and leave philosophy what it was and where it was? Nor can philosophy re- main an indifferent spectator of the rise of what may be termed the new individualism in art and letters, with its naturalistic method applied in a religious, almost mystic spirit to what is primi- tive, obscure, varied, inchoate, and growing in nature and human character. The age of Darwin, Helmholtz, Pasteur, Ibsen, Maeterlinck, Rodin, and Henry James must feel some uneasiness until it has liquidated its philosophic inheritance in cur- rent intellectual coin. And to accuse those who are concerned in this transaction of ignorant con- tempt for the classic past of philosophy is to over- vi PREFACE look the inspiration the movement of translation draws from the fact that the history of philosophy | has become only too well understood. Any revision of customary notions with its elimination—instead of “solution”—of many traditionary problems cannot hope, however, for any unity save that of tendency and operation. Elaborate and imposing system, the regimenting and uniforming of thoughts, are, at present, evi- dence that we are assisting at a stage performance in which borrowed—or hired—figures are maneu- vering. Tentatively and piecemeal must the re- construction of our stock notions proceed. As a contribution to such a revision, the present collec- tion of essays is submitted. With one or two exceptions, their order is that of a_ reversed chronology, the later essays coming first. The facts regarding the conditions of their first ap- pearance are given in connection with each essay. I wish to thank the Editors of the Philosophical Review, of Mind, of the Hibbert Journal, of the Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, and of the Popular Science Monthly, and the Directors of the Press of Chicago and Columbia Universities, respectively, for permission to reprint such of the essays as appeared orig- inally under their several auspices, JoHN DEWEY Cotumpia UNIVERSITY, An Pp New Yorx Crry, March 1, 1910. arry CONTENTS y Tue Inrivence or Darwinism on PHILOsoPHY Nature AND Its Goop: A CoNVERSATION . ' INTELLIGENCE AND Morats . . . . \y. Tue Experimenta, THEorRY oF KNOWLEDGE . Tue INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION FoR TRUTH . \ A SuHorr Catecuism ConcerNniING TRUTH . Beviers aND EXISTENCES . .. 1. « yv ExperRieNce AND OBsectTive IDEALISM. ln Vv Tue Posturate or Immepiate Empiricism . > . *“ CONSCIOUSNESS” AND EXPERIENCE . ‘ ; Tue SIGNIFICANCE OF THE PROBLEM OF KNowL- EDGE 7 J s a 2 s e . e Lh” Ne —e , | THE INFLUENCE OF DARWINISM ON PHILOSOPHY * I HAT the publication of the “Origin of Species *? marked an epoch in the develop- ment of the natural sciences is well known to the layman. That the combination of the very words origin and species embodied an intellectual revolt and introduced a new intellectual temper is easily overlooked by the expert. ‘The conceptions that had reigned in the philosophy of nature and knowl- edge for two thousand years, the conceptions that had become the familiar furniture of the mind, rested on the assumption of the superiority of the fixed and final; they rested upon treating change and origin as signs of defect and unreality. In laying hands upon the sacred ark of absolute permanency, in treating the forms that had been regarded as types of fixity and perfection as 2A lecture in a course of public lectures on “ Charles ~~ Darwin and His Influence on Science,” given at Columbia University in the winter and spring of 1909. Reprinted from the Popular Science Monthly for July, 1909, —— 2 DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY originating and passing away, the _“ Origin of Species’? introduced a mode of thinkin —e that in the end. was. bound to transform the 1 MIE athe the | knowledge, abil hence _ the “treatment. of oe H politics, and religion. ‘No wonder, then, that the publication of Dar- win’s book, a half century ago, precipitated a crisis. The true nature of the controversy is easily con- cealed from us, however, by the theological clamor that attended it. The vivid and popular features of the anti-Darwinian row tended to leave the im- ' pression that the issue was between science on one | side and theology on the other. Such was not the case—the issue lay primarily within science itself, as Darwin himself early recognized. The theolog- ical outcry he discounted from the start, hardly “noticing it save as it bore upon the “ feelings of his female relatives.” But for two decades before final publication he contemplated the possibility of being put down by his scientific. peers as a fool or as crazy; and he set, as the measure of his success, the degree in which he should affect three men of science: Lyell in geology, Hooker in botany, and Huxley in zoology. ~ Religious considerations lent fervor to the con- troversy, but they did- not provoke it. _Intellectu- ally, religious emotions are not creative but. con- servative. ‘They attach themselves readily to the current view of the world and consecrate it. They DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY 8 steep and dye intellectual fabrics in the seething vat of emotions; they do not form their warp and woof. There is not, I think, an instance of any large idea about the world being independently generated by religion. Although the ideas that | ‘~ rose up like armed men against Darwinism owed | _ their intensity to religious associations, their origin | and meaning are to be sought in science and philos- _ ophy, not in religion. II Few words in our language foreshorten intel- lectual history as much as does the word species. The Greeks, in initiating the intellectual life of Europe, were impressed by characteristic traits of the life of. plants and animals; so impressed indeed that they made these traits the key to defining nature and to explaining mind and society. jAnd truly, life is so wonderful that a seemingly successful reading of its mystery might well lead men to believe that the key to the secrets of heaven and earth was in their hands/ The Greek rendering of this mystery, the Greek formulation of the aim and standard of knowledge, was in the | course of time embodied in the word species, and it controlled philosophy for two thousand years. To understand the intellectual face-about expressed in the phrase “ Origin of Species,” we must, then, 4 DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY understand the long dominant idea against which it is a protest. Consider how men were impressed by the facts of life. ‘Their eyes fell upon certain things slight in bulk, and frail in structure. To every appear- ance, these perceived things were inert and passive. Suddenly, under certain circumstances, these things—henceforth known as seeds or eggs or germs—begin to change, to change rapidly in size, form, and qualities. Rapid and extensive changes . occur, however, in many things—as when wood is _ touched by fire. But the changes in the living thing are orderly; they are cumulative; they tend constantly in one direction; they do not, like other changes, destroy or consume, or pass fruitless into wandering flux; they realize and fulfil. Each suc- cessive stage, no matter how unlike its predecessor, preserves its net effect and also prepares the way for a fuller activity on the part of its successor. In ‘living beings, changes do not happen as they seem to happen elsewhere, any which way; the earlier * changes are regulated in view of later results. This progressive organization does not cease till there is achieved a true final term, a 7éA0S, a com- pleted, perfected end. This final form exercises in turn a plenitude of functions, not the least note- worthy of which is production of germs like those from which it took its own origin, germs capable of the same cycle of self-fulfilling activity. DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY 5 But the whole miraculous tale is not yet told. The same drama is enacted to the same destiny in countless myriads of individuals so sundered in time, so severed in space, that they have no oppor- tunity for mutual consultation and no means of interaction. As an old writer quaintly said, “things of the same kind go through the same formalities ’—celebrate, as it were, the same ceremonial rites. , This formal activity which operates throughout ' . a series of changes and holds them to a single © ' course; which subordinates their aimless flux to its own perfect manifestation; which, leaping the boundaries of space and time, keeps individuals distant in space and remote in time to a uniform | type of structure and function: this principle | seemed to give insight into the very nature of | reality itself. To it Aristotle gave the name, é76os. | This term the scholastics translated as species.“ * * The force of this term was deepened by its application to everything in the universe that ob- w serves order in flux and manifests constancy | . through change. From the casual drift of daily weather, through the uneven recurrence of seasons and unequal return of seed time and harvest, up to the majestic sweep of the heavens—the image of eternity in time—and from this to the unchang- ing pure and contemplative intelligence beyond na- ture lies one unbroken ‘fulfilment of ends. Nature Be Ea A 6 DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY as a whole is a progressive realization of purpose |” strictly comparable to the realization of purpose in any single plant or animal. | ‘The conception of eidos, species, a fixed form and final cause, was the central principle. of knowl- edge as well as of nature. Upon it it. rested the logicof science. Change as change is ; mere flux. and lapse; it insults intelligence. Genuinely to know is to grasp a permanent end that realizes itself through changes, holding them thereby with- in the metes and bounds of fixed truth. Completely to know is to relate all special forms to their one single end and good: pure contemplative intelli- gence. Since, however, the scene of nature which directly confronts us is in change, nature as directly and practically experienced does not sat- isfy the conditions of knowledge. |Human ex- perience is in flux, and hence the instrumentalities of sense-perception and of inference based upon observation are condemned in advance. ) Science is compelled to aim at realities lying behind and beyond the processes of nature, and to carry on its search for these realities by means of rational forms transcending ordinary modes of perception and inference. ~~ ‘There are, indeed, but two alternative courses. We x > must either find the appropriate “objects _ and — organs of ‘knowledge. in..the mutual interactions of changing things; or else, to escape t the ‘infee- Or i hE iS seca ee: DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY 7 tion of change, we must seek them in some trans-— cendent and supernal. region. ' The human ‘mind, deliberately as it were, exhausted the logic of the changeless, the final, and the the transcendent, before it t essayed adventure on the pathless.. wastes. of _ generation and transformation. We dispose all too easily of the efforts ‘of the schoolmen to in- terpret nature and mind in terms of real essences, : hidden forms, and occult faculties, forgetful of the seriousness and dignity of the ideas that lay behind. We dispose of them by laughing at the famous gentleman who accounted for the fact that opium put people to sleep on the ground it had a dormitive faculty. But the doctrine, held in our own day, that knowledge of the plant that yields the poppy consists in referring the peculiarities of an individual to a type, to a universal form, . a doctrine so firmly established that any other method of knowing was conceived to be unphilo- sophical and unscientific, is a survival of precisely the same logic. This identity of conception in the-scholastic and anti-Darwinian theory may well suggest greater sympathy for what has become unfamiliar as well as greater humility regarding the further unfamiliarities that history has in store. —~ Darwin was not, of course, the first to question -~ the classic philosophy of nature and of knowledge. | The beginnings of the revolution are in the phys- 8 « DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY ical science of the sixteenth and seventeenth cen- turies. When Galileo said: ** It is my opinion that of so many and so different alterations and gen- erations which are incessantly made therein,” he expressed the changed temper that was coming over the world; the transfer of interest from the per- manent to the changing. When Descartes said: “The nature of physical things is much more easily conceived when they are beheld coming grad- ually into existence, than when they are only con- sidered as produced at once in a finished and per- fect state,” the modern world became self-conscious of the logic that was henceforth to control it, the logic of which Darwin’s “ Origin of Species ” is the latest scientific achievement. Without the methods of Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo, and their successors in astronomy, physics, and. chemistry, Darwin would have been helpless.in the organic , Sciences. But prior to Darwin the impact of the + new scientific method upon ] life, 1 mind, and politics, had been arrested, because between these ideal or _ moral interests and the i inorganic. _ world intervened the kingdom of plants and animals. The gates of the garden of life were barred to the new ideas; and only through this garden was there access } _ to mind and politics. The influence of Darwin. . upon philosophy. resides.in..his having conquered _ “i - the phenomena. of life for the principle of transi- » 7 iN ( 4) tf Vad asia AND PHILOSOPHY 9 tion, and thereby freed the new logic for _applica-/ if tion to mind and morals and life. When he sai ‘of species what Galileo had said of the earth, | @ pur s¢ muove, he emancipated, once for all} | genetic and experimental ideas as an organon of, asking questions and looking for explanations. Til The exact bearings ‘upon philosophy of the new logical outlook — are, “of < course, as yet, un- \certain and “inchoate.@ © We live in the twilight of intellectual transition. One must add the rash- ness of the prophet to the stubbornness of the partizan to venture a systematic exposition of the influence upon philosophy of the Darwinian. - é il ‘ ) 4—4 LS Yee vie benvehe J method.- At best, we can but inquire as to its \/ general bearing—the effect upon mental temper and complexion, upon that body of half-conscious, half-instinctive intellectual aversions and prefer- ences which determine, after all, our more de- liberate intellectual enterprises. In this vague in-) quiry there happens to exist as a kind of touch- pe 1ST NA stone a ‘problem _ “of long historic currency that has also been much discussed in Darwinian litera-/ ture. IT refer” to the old problem of ‘design: versus Aenea. F tion, first or r final, of things: As we have already seen, the classic notion of Pi naemneetieatnnceuins, Al pee ath na Cnet Na ena ae t i t é 10 DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY * th Species carried with it the idea of a | In | ( ‘all ll living forms, a specific type is present directing the earlier stages of growth to the realization of its own perfection. Since this purposive regula-_ tive principle is not visible to ‘the senses, it follows that it must be an ideal or rational ‘force. Since, however, ‘the ‘perfect. form. is _gradually approxi- mated through the sensible changes, i it also follows (that m and through a sensible realm a rational ) ) ideal force is working out ‘its own ultimate mani- ( | festation. These inferences were extended to i ‘nature: (a) She does nothing in vain; but all for an ulterior purpose. (b) Within natural sensible events jthere is therefore contained a spiritual causal force, which ‘as\spiritual escapes perception, but is apprehended by an enlightened reason. (c) The manifestation of this principle brings about a subordihetion of matter and sense to its own. realization, and this ultimate fulfilment is the goal of nature and™ n. The design argu- ment thus operated in two directions, Purpose> fulness accounted for the intelligibility of nature .and the possibility of science, while the absolute _or cosmic character of this | purposefulness_ (gave sanction. and worth to the moral and _ religious en- deavors of. man, _ Science was underpinned and “morals _ authorized. by, one and | the same principle, _and their mutual agreement was eternally guaran- | “teed.| aed ’ ae : wv DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY 11 This philosophy remained, in spite of sceptical and polemic outbursts, the official and the regnant philosophy of Europe for over two.thousand years, The he expulsion of fixed first and final causes from en Obey A . astronomy, » physics, and chemistry h had indeed given the doctrine something. .of a shock. But, on the other hand, increased acquaintance » with the. de- tails of | plant : and. animal life operated as a coun- terbalance and perhaps" even strengthened _ the argument from design. The marvelous. adapta- tions of organisms to their environment, of organs ‘ to the organism, of unlike parts of a complex organ—like the eye—to the organ itself; the fore- shadowing by lower forms of the higher; the preparation in earlier stages of growth for or—- gans that only later had their functioning—these things were increasingly recognized with the prog- ress of botany, zoology, paleontology, : and 1 embry- ology. Together, they added such ‘prestige | to the ‘design argument that by the late eighteenth cen- tury it was, as approved by the sciences of or-| ganic life, the central point of theistic and ideal- 1 istic philosophy. The Darwinian principle of natural selection }--~ mE it at straight under | this philosophy. If all organic adaptations are due simply to constant variation x _ and the el elimination. of those variations which. are eh harmful i % __ the. struggle for existence that as ane a out by excessive “reproduction, th there ines jae ¢ ae x ' ety = ali ' 12 DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY ( is no call for a prior intelligent causal force to __ | ) plan and preordain them. Hostile critics charged ( Darwin with materialism and with making chance the cause of the universe. Some naturalists, like Asa Gray, favored the Darwinian principle and attempted to reconcile it with design. Gray held to what may be called | design on the installment plan.) If we conceive the “stream of variations ” to be itself intended, we may suppose that each successive variation was designed from the first to be selected. In that case, variation, struggle, and selection simply de- fine the mechanism of “ secondary causes ” through which the “ first cause” acts; and the doctrine of design is none the worse off because we know more of its modus operandi. Darwin could not accept this mediating pro- posal. He admits or rather he asserts that it is “impossible to conceive this immense and won- derful universe including man with his capacity of looking far backwards and‘ far into futurity as the result of blind chance or necepsi nde nevertheless he holds that since variations are in useless as well as useful directio; AS» 7and. since the latter are sifted out simply by ‘the stress of the conditions of struggle for existence, the design argument as applied to living beings is unjustifi- “able: and its lack of support there deprives it "16 Life and Letters,” Vol. I, p. 282; cf. 985. DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY (13 ) of scientific value as applied to nature in. general. If the variations of the pigeon, which under arti- ficial selection give the pouter pigeon, are not pre- ordained for the sake of the breeder, by what logic do we argue that variations resulting in natural species are pre-designed? * IV So much for some of the more obvious facts of the discussion of design versus chance, as causal \ principles of nature and of life as a whole. We brought up this discussion, you recall, as a crucial instance. What does our touchstone indicate as ‘to the bearing of Darwinian ideas upon philoso- — phy? Inthe first place, the new logic outlaws, flanks, dismisses—what you will—one type of. _ problems and substitutes for it another. type. , - Philosophy f forswears i inquiry after absolute te origins | oO May, | | and absolute finalities in order to explore e specific Y / ' values and the specific conditions that enerate ‘| “Darwin concluded that the impossibility, of { assigning the world to chance as a whole and to » design in its parts indicated the insolubility of the question. Two radically different reasons, 1“ Life and Letters,” Vol. II., pp. 146, 170, 245; Vol. L, pp. 283°84. See also the closing portion of his “ Variation of Animals and Plants under Domestication.” 14 DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY however, may be given as to why a problem is insoluble. One reason is that the problem is too high for intelligence ; the other is that the question in its very asking makes assumptions that render the question meaningless. The latter alternative ‘is unerringly pointed to in the celebrated case of design versus chance. Once admit that the sole verifiable or fruitful object of knowledge is the _ particular set of changes that generate the object of study together with the consequences that then | flow from it, and no intelligible question can be asked about what, by assumption, lies outside. To assert—as is often asserted—that specific -values of particular truth, social bonds and forms of beauty, if they can be shown to be generated by concretely knowable conditions, are meaningless and in vain; to assert that they are justified only when they and their particular causes and effects have all at once been gathered up into some in- clusive first cause and some exhaustive final goal, is intellectual atavism. Such argumentation is re- version to the logic that explained the extinction of fire by water through the formal essence of aqueousness and the quenching of thirst by water through the final cause of aqueousness. Whether used in the case of the special event or that of life as a whole, such logic only abstracts some aspect of the existing course of events in order to reduplicate it as a petrified eternal principle y DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY 15 by which to explain the very changes of which it is the formalization. When Henry Sidgwick casually remarked in a . letter that as he grew older his interest in what ; Id was altered i into i 11 terest kind of a world it is anyway, his voicing ‘ of a common y expexisuee of our own day illustrates also the nature of that intellectual transform: tion | effected by the Darwinian, logic. Interest. shifts M4 from the wholesale essence back of special changes | to ‘the. “question_of how. special. changes serve and defeat concrete. purposes; shifts from an intelli- Ny. gence that it_shaped things once for all to o the particular intelligences which things are even now shaping ; shifts from an ultimate goal c of f good | to to the direct increments of “justice | , and happiness | that intelligent administration of existent condi- i tions may beget and that present carelessness or _ stupidity will destroy or forego. 4 In the second place, the classic type of logic } inevitably. set_philosophy upon proving that life } must have certain qualities and values—no matter — how experience presents the matter—because of some remote cause and eventual goal. The duty of wholesale justification inevitably accompanies all thinking that makes the meaning of special occur- rences depend upon something that once and for all lies behind them. The habit of derogating from present meanings and uses prevents our look- 16 DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY ing the facts of experience in the face; it prevents serious acknowledgment of the evils they present and serious concern with the goods they promise but do not as yet fulfil. It turns thought to the business of finding a wholesale transcendent remedy for the one and guarantee for the other. One is reminded of the way many moralists and theo- logians greeted Herbert Spencer’s recognition of | an unknowable energy from which welled up the phenomenal physical processes without and the conscious operations within. Merely because Spencer labeled his unknowable energy “ God,” this faded piece of metaphysical goods was greeted as an important and grateful concession to the reality of the spiritual realm. Were it not for the deep hold of the habit of seeking justification for ideal values in the remote and transcendent, surely this reference of them to an unknowable absolute would be despised in comparison with the demonstrations of experience that knowable ener- ____ gies are daily generating about us precious values. The displacing of this wholesale type of philos- ophy will doubtless not arrive by sheer logical dis- proof, but rather by growing recognition of its futility. Were it a thousand times true that opium produces sleep because of its dormitive en- . ergy, yet the inducing of sleep in the tired, and the recovery to waking life of the poisoned, would not be thereby one least step forwarded. And were € DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY 17 it a thousand times dialectically demonstrated that life as a whole is regulated by a transcendent prin- ciple to a final inclusive goal, none the less truth ' and error, health and disease, good and evil, hope and fear in the concrete, would remain just what ’ and where they now are. To improve our edu-} cation, to ameliorate our manners, to advance our) politics, _we must have recourse to specific. condi- tions m3 generation. ra Finally, the 1 the new, logic introduces res esponsibility ¥ de into ) the intellectual life. To idealize and ration- | alize the universe at large i is after all a confession — of inability to master the courses of things that . specifically concern us. As long as mankind suf- | fered from this impotency, it naturally shifted a — burden of responsibility that it could not carry — over to the more competent shoulders of the trans- | cendent cause. But if insight into specific con- , ditions of value and into specific consequences of | _ ideas is possible, philosophy must in time become ( a” -e method of Jocating and interpreting the more ; | serious of the conflicts that occur in life, and a a ( ~ method of projecting ways for dealing with them: || ) a method of moral and political diagnosis _ and | ty ‘ prognosis. , The claim to formulate a priori the. legisla- tive constitution of the universe is by its nature a claim that may lead to elaborate dialectic de- velopments. But it is also one that removes Yt $A 18 DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY these very conclusions from subjection to experi- mental test, for, by definition, these results make no differences in the detailed course of events. But a philosophy that humbles its pretensions to the — work of projecting hypotheses for the education | ‘ and conduct of mind, individual and social, is thereby subjected to test by the way in which the ideas it propounds work out in ctice. In hav- ing modesty forced upon it, philosophy also ac- quires responsibility. Doubtless I seem to have violated the implied promise of my earlier remarks and to have turned both prophet and partizan. But in anticipating the direction of the transformations in philosophy to be wrought by the Darwinian genetic and ex- perimental logic, I do not profess to speak for any save those who yield themselves consciously or unconsciously to this logic. No one can fairly deny that at present there are two effects of the | Darwinian mode of thinking. On the one hand, re 0 filet Rate | Sse hand, there is as definitely a recrudescence of absolutistic philosophies; an assertion of a type ESRI Se of philosophic knowing distinct from that of the // sciences, one which opens to us another kind of | reality. from that to which the sciences give ac- * cess; an ppt _through experience. to SOME: OD toe it canes aral pg 2 oa er | thére-are making many sincere and vital effortsp” » | to revise our traditional philosophic conceptions. in accordance ‘with, ‘its. _demands.... On the other DARWINISM AND PHILOSOPHY 19 that essentially goes beyond experience. This re- » action affects popular creeds and religious move- ments as well as technical philosophies. The very conquest of the biological sciences by the new ideas has led many to proclaim an explicit and rigid _ separation of philosophy from science. Old ideas give way slowly; for they are more than abstract logical forms and categories. They are habits, predispositions, deeply engrained atti- tudes of aversion and preference. Moreover, the conviction persists—though history shows it to be a hallucination—that all the questions that the human mind has asked are questions that can be answered in terms of the alternatives that the ques- tions themselves present. But in fact intellectual progress usually occurs through sheer abandonment of questions together with both of the alternatives they assume—an abandonment that results from their decreasing vitality and a change of urgent interest. We do not solve them: we get over them. Old questions are solved by disappearing, evapo- rating, while new questions corresponding to the changed attitude of endeavor and preference take their place. Doubtless the greatest dissolvent in contemporary thought of old questions, the great-. est precipitant of new methods, new intentions, new_/| problems, is the. one effected, by the. scientific revo- |. lutiop that found its climax in the “ Origin of | Species.” NATURE AND ITS GOOD: A CONVERSATION * '. A GROUP of people are scattered near one another, on the sands of an ocean beach; wraps, baskets, etc., testify to a day’s outing. Above the hum of the varied conversations are heard the mock sobs of one of the party. Various voices. What's the matter, Eaton? Eaton. Matter enough. I was watching a. beautiful wave; its lines were perfect; at its crest, © the light glinting through its infinitely varied and delicate curves of foam made a picture more rav- ishing than any dream.’ And now it has gone; it will never come back. So I weep. Grimes. That’s right, Eaton; give it to them. Of course well-fed and well-read persons—with their possessions of wealth and of knowledge both gained at the expense of others—finally get bored ; then they wax sentimental over their boredom and are worried about “ Nature” and its relation to life. Not everybody takes it out that way, of course; some take motor cars and champagne for that tired feeling. But the rest—those who aren’t *Reprinted from the Hibbert Journal, Vol. VII., No. 4, July, 1909. 20 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION 21 in that class financially, or who consider themselves too refined for that kind of relief—seek a new ‘sensation in speculating why that brute old world out there will not stand for what you call spiritual and ideal values—for short, your egotisms. The fact is that the whole discussion is only a _ symptom of the leisure class disease. If you had to work to the limit and beyond, to keep soul and body together, and, more than that, to keep alive the soul of your family in its body, you would know the difference between your artificial prob- lems and the genuine problem of life. Your philo- sophic problems about the relation of “ the uni- verse to moral and spiritual good” exist only in the sentimeg$alism that generates them. The gen- uine question is why social arrangements will not _» permit the amply sufficient body of natural re- sources to sustain all men and women in security and decent comfort, with a margin for the culti- vation of their human instincts of sociability, love of knowledge and of art. As I read Plato, philosophy began with some _ sense of its essentially political basis and mission— a recognition that its problems were those of the organization of a just social order. But it soon got lost in dreams of another world ; and even those of you philosophers who pride yourselves on being ‘so advanced that you no longer believe in “ an- other world,” are still living and thinking with 22 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION reference to it. You may not call it supernatural ; but when you talk about a realm of spiritual or ‘ ideal values in general, and ask about its relation to Nature in general, you have only changed the labels on the bottles, not the contents in them. For what makes anything transcendental—that i at is, in common language, supernatural—is simply and and — only aloofness from practical affairs—which af-_ din ta theip Utinate onalyee are the business of — making « living. _ a Eaton. Yes; Grimes has about hit off the point of my little parable—in one of its aspects at least. In matters of daily life you say a man is “ off,” more or less insane, when he deliberately goes on looking for a certain kind of result from condi- tions which he has already found to be such that they cannot possibly yield it. If he keeps on look- ing, and then goes about mourning because stage money won’t buy beefsteaks, or because he can- not keep himself warm by burning the sea-sands here, you dismiss him as a fool or a hysteric. If you would condescend to reason with him at all, you would tell him to look for the conditions that will yield the results; to occupy himself with some of — the countless goods of life for which, by_intelli- gently directed search, adequate means may be found. _ - Well, before lunch, Moore was reiterating the | old tale. ‘ Modern science has completely trans- Peers cis sh NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION 23 formed our conceptions of Nature. _It has stripped the universe bare not only of all the moral values which it wore alike to antique pagan and to our © medieval ancestors, but also of any regard, any preference, for such values. They are mere inci- dents, transitory accidents, in her everlasting re- distribution of matter in motion; like the rise and fall of the wave I lament, or like a single musical note that a screeching, rumbling railway train might happen to emit.” This is a one-sided view; but suppose it were all so, what is the moral? Surely, to change our standpoint, our angle of vision; to stop looking for results among condi- tions that we know will not yield them; to turn our ~» gaze to the goods, the values that exist actually and indubitably in experience; and consider by what natural conditions these particular values may be strengthened and widened. gaa ‘Insist, if you please, that Nature as a whole does not stand for good as a whole. Then, in ~heaven’s name, just because good is both so plural _ (so “ numerous ”) and so partial, bend your ener- ' gies of intelligence and of effort to selecting the specific plural and partial natural conditions which will at-teast render values that-we do have more secure and more extensive. Any other course is the way of madness; it is the way of the spoilt child who cries at the seashore because the waves do not stand still, and who cries even more franti- 24 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION cally in the mountains because the hills do not melt and flow. But no. Moore and his school will not have it so: we must “ go back of the returns.” All this science, after all, is a mode of knowledge. Ex- amine knowledge itself and find it implies a com- plete all-inclusive intelligence; and then find (by taking another tack) that intelligence involves sentiency, feeling, and also will. Hence your very physical science, if you will only criticise it, ex- amine it, shows that its object, mechanical nature, is itself an included and superseded element in an all-embracing spiritual and ideal whole. And there you are. Well, I do not now insist that all this is mere dialectic prestidigitation. No; accept it; let it go at its face value. But what of it? Is any value more concretely and securely in life than it was before? Does this perfect intelligence enable us to correct one single mis-step, one paltry error, here and now? Does this perfect all-inclusive goodness serve to heal one disease? Does it rectify one trangression? Does it even give the slightest _ inkling of how to go to work at any of these _ things? No; it just tells you: Never mind, for they are already eternally corrected, eternally healed in the eternal consciousness which alone is really Real. Stop: there is one evil, one pain, which the doctrine mitigates—the hysteric senti- NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION 25 mentalism which is troubled because the universe as a whole does not sustain good as a whole. But that is the only thing it alters. The “ pathetic fallacy ” of Ruskin magnified to the nth power is the motif of modern idealism. Moore. Certainly nobody will accuse Eaton of tender-mindedness—except in his logic, which, as certainly, is not tough-minded. His excitement, however, convinces me that he has at least an ink- ling that he is begging the question; and like the true pragmatist that he is, is trying to prevent by action (to wit, his flood of speech) his false logic from becoming articulate to him. The ques- tion being whether the values we seem to appre- hend, the purposes we entertain, the goods we pos- sess, are anything more than transitory waves, Eaton meets it by saying: “ Oh, of course, they are waves; but don’t think about that—just sit down hard on the wave or get another wave to but- tress it with!”? No wonder he recommends action instead of thinking! Men have tried this method before, as a counsel of desperation or as cynical pessimism. But it remained for contemporary pragmatism to label the drowning of sorrow in the intoxication of thoughtless action, the highest achievement of philosophic method, and to preach wilful restlessness as a doctrine of hope and illu- mination. Meantime, I prefer to be tender-minded in my attitude toward Reality, and to make 26 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION that attitude more reasonable by a tough-minded logic. | Eaton. I am willing to be quiet long enough for you to translate your metaphor into logic, and show how I have begged the question. Moore. It is plain enough. You bid us turn to the cultivation, the nurture, of certain values in human life. But the question is whether these are or are not values. And that is a question of their relation to the Universe—to Reality. If Reality substantiates them, then indeed they are values; if it mocks and flouts them—as it surely does if what mechanical science calls Nature be ultimate and absolute—then they are not values. You and your kind are really the sentimentalists, because you are sheer subjectivists. You say: Ac- cept the dream as real; do not question about it; - add a little iridescence to its fog and extend it till it obscure even more of Reality than it natu- rally does, and all is well! I say: Perhaps the dream is no dream but an intimation of the solidest and most ultimate of all realities; and a thorough examination of what the positivist, the materialist, accepts as solid, namely, science, re- veals as its own aim, standard, and presupposi- tion that Reality is one all-exhaustive spiritual Being. | ; 4 Eaton. This is about the way I thought my begging of the question would turn out. You in- NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION = 27 / cof sist upon translating my position into terms of L your own; I am not then surprised to hear that it would be a begging of the question for you to hold my views. My point is precisely that it is only as long as you take the position that some Reality beyond—some metaphysical or transcendental real- ity—is necessary to substantiate empirical values | that you can even discuss whether the latter are © genuine or illusions. Drop the presupposition that you read into everything I say, the idea that the reality of things as they are is dependent upon some- thing beyond and behind, and the facts of the case just stare you in the eyes: Goods are, a multitude of them—but, unfortunately, evils also are; and all grades, pretty much, of both. Not the con- trast and relation of experience in toto to some- thing beyond experience drives men to religion and then to philosophy; but the contrast within ex-< perience of the better and the worse, and the con- sequent problem of how to substantiate the former and reduce the latter. Until you set up the no- tion of a transcendental reality at large, you can- not even raise the question of whether goods and evils are, or only seem to be. The trouble and the joy, the good and the evil, is that they are; the hope is that they may be regulated, guided, in- creased in one direction and minimized in another. Instead of neglecting thought, we (I mean the pragmatists) exalt it, because we say that intelli- 28 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION gent discrimination of means and ends is the sole final resource in this problem of all problems, the control of the factors of good and ill in life. We say, indeed, not merely that that is what intelli- gence does, but rather what it is. Historically, it is quite possible to show how under certain social conditions this human and practical problem of the relation of good and in- telligence generated the notion of the transcen- dental good and the pure reason. As Grimes re- minded us, Plato-—— Moore. Yes, and Protagoras—don’t forget him; for unfortunately we know both the origin and the consequences of your doctrine that being and seeming are the same. We know quite well that pure empiricism leads to the identification of being and seeming, and that is just why every deeply moral and religious soul from the time of Plato and Aristotle to the present has insisted upon a transcendent reality. Eaton. Personally I don’t need an absolute to enable me to distinguish between, say, the good of kindness and the evil of slander, or the good of health and the evil of valetudinarianism. In ex- perience, things bear their own specific characters. Nor has the absolute idealist as yet answered the question of how the absolute reality enables him ‘ to distinguish between being and seeming in one single concrete case. The trouble is that for him $ NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION 29 all Being is on the other side of experience, and all experience is seeming. Grimes. I think I heard you mention history. I wish both of you would drop dialectics and go to history. You would find history to be a strug- gle for existence—for bread, for a roof, for pro- tected and nourished offspring. You would find history a picture of the masses always going under—just missing—in the struggle, because _ others have captured the control of natural re- sources, which in themselves, if not as benign as the eighteenth century imagined, are at least abun- .. dantly ample for the needs of all. But because of the monopolization of Nature by a few persons, most men and women only stick their heads above the welter just enough to catch a glimpse of better things, then to be shoved down and under. The _ only problem of the relation of Nature to human — good which is real is the economic problem of the exploitation of natural resources in the equal in- _terests of all, instead of in the unequal interests of a class. The problem you two men are discuss- ing has no existence—and never had any—outside of the heads of a few metaphysicians. The latter would never have amounted to anything, would never have had any career at all, had not shrewd monopolists or tyrants (with the skill that charac- terizes them) have seen that these speculations about reality and a transcendental world could be at 80 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION distilled into opiates and distributed among the » masses to make them less rebellious. That, if you would know, Eaton, is the real historic origin of the ideal world beyond. When you realize that, you will perceive that the pragmatists are only half-way over. You will see that practical ques- tions are practical, and are not to be solved merely by having a theory about theory different from the traditional one—which is all your pragmatism comes to. Moore. If you mean that your own crass Phi- listinism is all that pragmatism comes to, I fancy you are about right. Forget that the only end of action is to bring about an approximation to the complete inclusive consciousness; make, as the pragmatists do, consciousness a means to action, and one form of external activity is just as good as another. Art, religion, all the generous reaches of science which do not show up immediately in the factory—these things become meaningless, and all that remains is that hard and dry satisfaction of economic wants which is Grimes’s ideal. Grimes. An ideal which exists, by the way, only in your imagination. I know of no more convinc- ing proof of the futile irrelevancy of idealism than the damning way in which it narrows the content of actual daily life in the minds of those who up- hold idealism. I sometimes think I am the only true idealist. If the conditions of an equitable and NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION 31 _ ample physical existence for all were once secured, I, for one, have no fears as to the bloom and harvest , of art and science, and all the “ higher ” things of leisure. Life is interesting enough for me; give it a show for all. Arthur. I find myself in a peculiar position in respect to this discussion. An analysis of what is involved in this peculiarity may throw some light on the points at issue, for I have to believe that analysis and definition of what exists is the essen- tial matter both in resolution of doubts and in steps at reform. For brevity, not from conceit, I will put the peculiarity to which I refer in a personal form. I do not believe for a moment in some different Reality beyond and behind Nature. . I do not believe that a manipulation of the logical _ implications of science can give results which are ' to be put in the place of those which Science herself | yields in her direct application. I accept Nature ' as something which is, not seems, and Science as her faithful transcript. Yet because I believe these things, not in spite of them, I believe in the existence of purpose and of good. How Eaton can believe that fulfilment and the increasing realiza> g realiza- EA eee ie Oa Naren tomedoes unless_ exist in the world which is revealed Be cpetdeennies ose aoe tecead ade Moore can believe that a manipulation of the method of knowledge can yield considerations of a 32 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION totally different order from those directly obtained by use of the method. If purpose and fulfilment exist as natural goods, then, and only then, can consciousness itself be a fulfilment of Nature, and be also a natural good. Any other view is inex- plicable to sound thinking—-save, historically, as a product of modern political individualism and lit- erary romanticism which have combined to produce that idealistic philosophy according to which the mind in knowing the universe creates it. The view that purpose and realization are pro- foundly natural, and that consciousness—or, if ' you will, experience—is itself a culmination and climax of Nature, is not a new view. Formulated by Aristotle, it has always persisted wherever the traditions of sound thinking have not been ob- scured by romanticism. The asa! scientific doc- _ trine of evolution confir ; “and specifies the meta- physical insight of Astelle. This doctrine sets forth in detail, and in verified detail, as a genuine — characteristic of existence, the tendency - toward cumulative results, the definite trend of things to- ward culmination and achievement. It describes the-universe as possessing, in terms of and by right. of its own subject-matter (not as an addition of subsequent reflection), differences of value and im- portance—differences, moreover, that exercise se- lective influence upon the course of things, that is to say, genuinely determine the events that occur. NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION =. 33 It tells us that consciousness itself is such a cumu- lative and culminating natural event. Hence it is ‘relevant to the world in which it dwells, and its determinations of value are not arbitrary, not obi- ter dicta, but descriptions of Nature herself. Recall the words of Spencer which Moore quoted this morning: “ There is no pleasure in the con- sciousness of being an infinitesimal bubble on a globe that is infinitesimal compared with the total- ity of things. Those on whom the unpitying rush of changes inflicts sufferings which are often with- out remedy, find no consolation in the thought that they are at the mercy of blind forces,—which cause indifferently now the destruction of a sun and now the death of an animalcule. Contemplation of a universe which is without conceivable beginning or end and without intelligible purpose, yields no satis- faction.” I am naive enough to believe that the only question is whether the object of our “ con- - sciousness,” of our “ thought,” of our “ contempla- tion,” is or is not as the quotation states it to be. If the statement be correct, pragmatism, like sub- jectivism (of which I suspect it is only a variation, putting emphasis upon will instead of idea), is an invitation to close our eyes to what is, in order to encourage the delusion that things are other than they are. But the case is not so desperate. Speak- ing dogmatically, the account given of the uni- verse is just—not true. And the doctrine of evo- 34 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION ution of which Spencer professedly made so much s the evidence. A universe describable in evolu- ionary terms is a universe which shows, not indeed esign, but tendency and purpose; which exhibits chievement, not indeed of a single end, but of a ultiplicity of natural goods at whose apex is con- ciousness. No account of the universe in terms erely of the redistribution of matter in motion is omplete, no matter how true as far as it goes, for it ignores the cardinal fact that the character of matter in motion and of its redistribution is such as cumulatively to achieve ends—to effect the world of values we know. Deny this and you deny evolution; admit it and you admit purpose in the only objective—that is, the only intelligible—sense of that term. I do not say that in addition to the mechanism there are other ideal causes or factors which intervene. I only insist that the whole story be told, that the character of the mechanism be noted—namely, that it is such as to produce and sustain good in a multiplicity of forms. Mechan- ism is the mechanism of achieving results. To ig- nore this is to refuse to open our eyes to the total aspects of existence. Among these multiple natural goods, I ebiat, is consciousness itself. One of the ends in which Na- ture genuinely terminates is just awareness of it- self—of its processes and ends. For note the im- -plication as to why consciousness is a natural good: NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION = 85 not because it is cut off and exists in isolation, nor yet because we may, pragmatically, cut. off and cultivate certain values which have no existence be- yond it; but because it is good that things should be known in their own characters. And this view carries with it a precious result: to know things as they are is to know them as culminating in con- sciousness ; it is to know that the universe genuinely achieves and maintains its own self-manifestation. A final word as to the bearing of this view upon Grimes’s position. To conceive of human history as a scene of struggle of classes for domination, a struggle caused by love of power or greed for gain, is the very mythology of the emotions. What we call history is largely non-human, but so far as it is human, it is dominated by intelligence: history vw is the history of increasing consciousness. Not that intelligence is actually sovereign in life, but that at least it is sovereign over stupidity, error, and ignorance. The acknowledgment of things as they are—that is the causal source of every step in progress. Our present system of industry is not the product of greed or tyrannic lust of power, but of physical science giving the mastery over the mechanism of Nature’s energy. If the existing system is ever displaced, it will be displaced not by good intentions and vague sentiments, but by a more extensive insight into Nature’s secrets. Modern sentimentalism is revolted at the frank 86 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION naturalism of Aristotle in saying that some are slaves by nature and others free by nature. But '\ let. socialism come to-morrow and somebody—not anybody, but somebody—will be managing its ma- chinery and somebody else will be managed by the machinery. I do not wonder that my socialistic friends always imagine themselves active in the first capacity—perhaps by way of compensation for doing all of the imagining and none of the executive management at present. But those who are man- aged, who are controlled, deserve at least a mo- ment’s attention. Would you not at once agree that if there is any justice at all in these positions of relative inferiority and superiority, it is because those who are capable by insight deserve to rule, and those who are incapable on account of igno- rance, deserve to be ruled? If so, how do you dif- fer, save verbally, from Aristotle? Or do you think that all that men want in order to be men is to have their bellies filled, with assur- ance of constant plenty and without too much ante- cedent labor? No;-believe me, Grimes,men—are men, and hence their aspiration is for the-divyine— even when they know it-not;-their desire-is_for the ruling element, for intelligence. Till they achieve that they will still be discontented, rebellious, un- ruly—and hence ruled—shuffle your social cards as much as you may. Grimes (after shrugging his shoulders contempt- NATURE'S GOOD: A CONVERSATION 37 uously, finally says): There is one thing I like about Arthur: he is frank. He comes out with what you in all your hearts really believe—theory, supreme and sublime. All is to the good in this best of all possible worlds, if only some one be defining and classifying and syllogizing, accord- ing to the lines already laid down. Aristotle’s God of pure intelligence (as he well knew) was the glorification of leisure; and Arthur’s point of view, if Arthur but knew it, is as much the intellectual snobbery of a leisure class economy, as the luxury and display he condemns are its material snobbery. There is really nothing more to be said. Moore. To get back into the game which Grimes despises. Doesn’t Arthur practically say that the universe is good because it culminates in intelligence, and that intelligence is good because it perceives that the universe culminates in— itself? And, on this theory, are ignorance and error, and consequent evil, any less genuine achieve- 7 ments of Nature than intelligence and good? And on what basis does he call by the titles of achievement and end that which at best is an infinitesimally fragmentary and transitory epi- sode? Ti said Eaton begged the question. Arthur seems to regard it as proof of a superior intelli- gence (one which realistically takes things as they are) to beg the question. What is this Nature, this universe in whic evil il is as stubborn a fact as Ke | een 38 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION good, in which good is constantly destroyed by the very power that produces it, in which there re- sides a temporary bird of passage—consciousness doomed to ultimate extinction—what is such a Na- ture (all that Arthur offers us) save the problem, the contradiction originally in question? A com- placent optimism may gloss over its intrinsic self- contradictions, but a more serious mind is forced to go behind and beyond this scene to a permanent good which includes and transcends goods defeated and hopes suborned. Not because idealists have refused to note the facts as they are, but precisely because Nature is, on its face, such a scene as Arthur describes, idealists have always held that it is but Appearance, and have attempted to mount through it to Reality. Stair. Ihad not thought to say anything. My attitude is so different from that of any one of you that it seemed unnecessary to inject another varying opinion where already disagreement reigns. But when Arthur was speaking, I felt that perhaps this disagreement exists precisely because the solv- ent word had not been uttered. For, at bottom, all of you agree with Arthur, and that is the cause of your disagreement with him and one another. You have agreed to make reason, intellect in some sense, the final umpire. But reason, intellect, is the principle of analysis, of division, of discord. When I appeal to feeling as the ultimate organ NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION —_ 39 of unity, and hence of truth, you smile courteously ; say—or think—mysticism; and the case for you is dismissed. Words like feeling, sensation, imme- diate appreciation, self-communication of Being, I must indeed use when I try to tell the truth I see. But. I well know how inadequate the words are. And why? Because language is the chosen tool of intelligence, and hence inevitably bewrayeth the truth it would convey. But remember that words are but symbols, and that intelligence must dwell in the realm of symbols, and you realize a way out. These words, sensation, feeling, etc., as I utter them are but invitations to woo you to put your- selves into the one attitude that reveals truth— an attitude of direct vision. The beatific vision? Yes, and No. No, if you mean something rare, extreme, almost abnormal. Yes, if you mean the commonest and most convinc- ing, the only convincing self-impartation of the ul- timate good in the scale of goods; the vision of blessedness in God. For this doctrine is empirical ; mysticism is the heart of all positive empiricism, of all empiricism which is not more interested in denying rationalism than in asserting itself. The mystical experience marks every man’s realization of the supremacy of good, and hence measures the distance that separates him from pure materialism. And since the unmitigated materialist is the rarest of creatures, and the man with faith in an unseen 40 NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION good the commonest, every man is a mystic—and the most so in his best moments. : What an idle contradiction that Moore and Ar- thur should try to adduce proofs of the supremacy of ideal values in the universe! ‘The sole possible proof is the proof that actually exists—the direct » unhindered realization of those values. For each value brings with it of necessity its own depth of being. Let the pride of intellect and the pride of will cease their clamor, and in the silences Being speaks its own final word, not an argument or ex- ternal ground of belief, but the self-impartation of | itself to the soul. Who are the prophets and teachers of the ages? ‘Those who have been ac- cessible at the greatest depths to these communica- tions. | Grimes. I suppose that poverty—and possibly disease—are specially competent ministers to the spiritual vision? The moral is obvious. Economic . changes are purely irrelevant, because purely ma- terial and external. Indeed, upon the whole, ef- forts at reform are undesirable, for they distract attention from the fact that the final thing, the vision of good, is totally disconnected from ex- ternal circumstance. I do not say, Stair, you per- sonally believe this; but is not such a quietism the logical conclusion of all mysticism? Stair. This is not so true as to say that in your efforts at reform you are really inspired by the NATURE'S GOOD: A CONVERSATION 41 divine vision of justice; and that this mystic vision and not the mere increase of ‘quantity of eatables and drinkables is your animating; moti ve. Grimes. Well, to my mind this whole affair of mystical values and experiences comes down to a simple straight-away proposition. The submerged masses do not occupy themselves with such ques- tions as those you are disc ssiing. They haven’t the time even to consider whether they want to consider them. Nor does the occasional free citi- zen who even now exists—ajs‘poradic reminder and prophecy of ultimate democracy—bother himself about the relation of the cosmos to value. Why? Not from mystic insight any more than from meta- physical proof; but because he has so many other interests that are worth',while. His friends, his vocation and avocations, his books, his music, his club—these things engagse him and they reward him. To multiply such jmen with such interests— that is the genuine problem, I repeat; and it is a problem to be solved only, through an economic and material redistribution, Eaton. Gladly, Statir, do all of us absolve our- selves from the responsibility of having to create the goods that life—call it God or Nature or Chance—provides. has we cannot, if we would, absolve ourselves fro: responsibility for maintain- ing and extending ichese goods when they have happened. ‘To find {it very wonderful—as Arthur — 42 NATURE’S: GOOD: A CONVERSATION does—that intelligence perceives values as they are is trivial, for it is only an elaborate way of saying that they hve happened. To invite us, ceasing struggle and effort, to commune with Being through the moments of insight and joy that life provides, is to bid us to seli'-indulgence—to enjoyment at the expense of those upon whom the burden of con- ducting life’s affairs falls. For even the mystics still need to eat and drink, be clothed and housed, and somebody must do these unmystic things. And to ignore others in the interest of our own perfec- tion is not conducive to genuine unity of Being. : Intelligence is, indeed, as you say, discrimina- tion, distinction. But why? Because we have to act in order to keep secure amid the moving flux of circumstance, some slight but precious good that Nature has bestowed ; and because, in order to act successfully, we must act after conscious selection '—after discrimination of means and ends. Of course, all goods arrive, as; Arthur says, as natural results, but so do all bads, and all grades of good and bad. ‘To label the restilts that occur culmina- tions, achievements, and then argue to a quasi- ' moral constitution of Nature because she effects such results, is to employ a logic which applies to the life-cycle of the germ that, in achieving itself, kills man with malaria, as well as to the process of human life that in reaching its fullness cuts short the germ-fulfilment. It is putting the cart before NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION — 43 the horse to say that because Nature is so consti- tuted as to produce results of all types of value, therefore Nature is actuated by regard for differ- ences of value. Aoi till it produces a being who strives and who thinks in order that he may strive more effectively, does not know whether it cares more for justice or for cruelty, more for the ravenous wolf-like competition of the struggle for existence, or for the improvements incidentally in- troduced through that struggle. Literally it-has no mind of its Nor would the mere intro- HiGhee SPC condcloueriee that pictured indiffer- ently the scene out of which consciousness devel- oped, add one iota of reason for attributing eulo- gistically to Nature regard for value. But when the sentient organism, having experienced natural values, good and bad, begins to select, to prefer, and ee and in order thatit may make the most_gallant fight. ; possible picks—out and gathers together in n_ perception and thought what is fav and what hostile, then and e has at last achieved significant regard for good. And this is the same—thing as the birth of intelligence. ence. For the holding an end i in view and the selecting and or- | ganizing out of the natural flux, on the basis of this end, conditions that are means, is intelligence. Not, then, when Nature produces health or effi- ciency or complexity does Nature exhibit regard AA NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION for value, but only when it produces a living organ- ism that has settled preferences and endeavors. The mere happening of complexity, health, adjust- ment, is all that Nature effects, as rightly called accident as purpose. But when Nature pro- duces an intelligence—ah, then, indeed Nature has achieved something. Not, however, because this in- telligence impartially pictures the nature which _ has produced it, but because in human conscious- ness Nature becomes genuinely partial. Because in consciousness an end is is preferred, is selected for Maintenance, and bec not a world just _as it is in toto images the conditions and obstacles of the continued mainte- nance of the selected good. For in an experience where values are demonstrably precarious, an in- telligence that is not a principle of emphasis and valuation (an intelligence which defines, describes, and classifies merely for the sake of knowledge,) is a principle of stupidity and catastrophe. As for Grimes, it is indeed true that problems are solved only where they arise—namely, in ac- tion, in the adjustments of behavior. But, for _ good or for evil, they can be solved there only with - method ; and ultimately method is intelligence, and ~ intelligence is method. The larger, the more hu- man, the less technical the problem of practice, the more open-eyed and wide-viewing must be the cor- responding method. I do not say that all things NATURE’S GOOD: A CONVERSATION = 45 that have been called philosophy participate in this method ; I do sa aay esreters et a catholic and fai and far- ole phy. / And dieat technical ‘iikieophy 3 is to. go the way of dogmatic theology, it must loyally identify itself with such a view of its own aim and destiny. Be INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS? as XCEPT the blind forces of nature,” said Sir Henry Maine, “nothing moves in this _world whichis not Greek in its origin.” And if we ask why this is so, the response comes that the Greek discovered the business of man to be pursuit of good, and intelligence to be central in this quest. — The utmost to be said in praise of Plato and Aris- totle is not that they invented excellent moral the- ories, but that they rose to the opportunity which the spectacle of Greek life afforded. For Athens presented an all but complete microcosm for the study of the interaction of social organization and individual character. A public life of rich diver- sity in concentrated and intense splendor trained the civic sense. Strife of faction and the rapid oscillations of types of polity provided the occasion for intellectual inquiry and analysis. The careers of dramatic personalities, habits of discussion, ease of legislative change, facilities for personal ambi- *A public lecture delivered at Columbia University in March, 1908, under the title of “Ethics,” in a series of lectures on “Science, Philosophy, and Art.” Reprinted from a monograph published by the Columbia University Press. 46 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 47 tions, distraction by personal rivalries, fixed atten- tion upon the elements of character, and upon con- sideration of the effect of individual character on social vitality and stability. Happy exemption from ecclesiastic preoccupations, susceptibility to natural harmony, and natural piety conspired with } frank and open observation to acknowledgment of the réle played by natural conditions. Social in- stability and shock made equally pertinent and ob- vious the remark that only intelligence can confirm the values that natural conditions generate, and that intelligence is itself nurtured and matured only in a free and stable society. In Plato the, resultant analysis of the mutual implications of the individual, the sovial and the natural, converged in the ideas that morals and -philosophy are one: namely, a love of that wisdom which is the source of secure and social good ; that mathematics and the natural sciences focused upon «the problem of the perception of the good furnish the materials of moral science; that logic is the method of the pregnant organization of social con- “ditions with respect to good ; that politics and psy- chology are sciences of one and the same human nature, taken first in the large and then in the little. So far that large and expansive vision of Plato. But projection of a better life must be based upon reflection of the life already lived. The in- ¢ } 48 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS evitable limitations of the Greek city-state were in- evitably wrought into the texture of moral theory. The business of thought was to furnish a sub- stitute for customs which were then relaxing from the pressure of contact and intercourse without and the friction of strife within. Reason was to take the place of custom as a guide of life; but it 7 was to furnish rules as final, as unalterable as those of custom. In short, the thinkers were fascinated by the afterglow of custom. They took for their own ideal the distillation from custom of its essence ' —ends and laws which should be rigid and invari- able. Thus Morals was set upon the track which it dared not leave for nigh twenty-five hundred ' years: search for the final good, and for the single moral force. Aristotle’s assertions that the state exists by na- ture, and that in the state alone does the individual achieve independence and completeness of life, are indeed pregnant sayings. But as uttered by Aris- totle they meant that, in an isolated state, the Greek city-state, set a garlanded island in the waste sea ,of barbaroi, a community indifferent when not hostile to all other social groupings, in- dividuals attain their full end. In a social unity which signified social contraction, contempt, and antagonism, in a social order which despised inter- course and glorified war, is realized the life of excellence! INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 49 There is likewise a profound saying of Aristotle’s that the individual who otherwise than by accident is not a member of a state is either a brute or a god. But it is generally forgotten that elsewhere Aristotle identified the highest excellence, the chief virtue, with pure thought, and identifying this with the divine, isolated it in lonely grandeur from the life of society. That man, so far as in him lay, should be godlike, meant that he should be non- social, because supra-civic. Plato the idealist had shared the belief that reason is the divine; but he was also a reformer and a radical and he would have those who attained rational insight descend again into the civic cave, and in its obscurity labor patiently for the enlightenment of its blear-eyed inhabitants. Aristotle, the conservative and the definer of what is, gloried in the exaltation of in- telligence in man above civic excellence and social need ; and thereby isolated the life of truest knowl- / edge from contact with social experience and from responsibility for discrimination of values in the course of life. Moral theory, however, accepted from social cus- tom more than its cataleptic rigidity, its exclusive area of common good, and its unfructified and irre- sponsible reason. The city-state was a superficial layer of cultured citizens, cultured through a par- ticipation in affairs made possible by relief from economic pursuits, superimposed upon the dense ‘ 50 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS te... ee mass of serfs, artizans, and laborers. For this di- vision, moral philosophy made itself spiritual spon- sor, and thus took it up into its own being. Plato wrestled valiantly with the class problem; but his outcome was the necessity of decisive demarcation, after education, of the masses in whom reason was asleep and appetite much awake, from the few who were fit to rule because alertly wise. The most generously imaginative soul of all philosophy could not far outrun the institutional practices of his | people and his times. ‘This might have warned his successors of the danger of deserting the sober — path of a critical discernment of the better and the worse within contemporary life for the more ex- citing adventure of a final determination of abso- lute good and evil. It might have taught the prob- ability that some brute residuum or unrationalized social habit would be erected into an apotheosis of pure reason. But the lesson was not learned. Aristotle promptly yielded to the besetting sin of all philosophers, the idealization of the existent: he declared that the class distinctions of superiority and inferiority as between man and woman, master and slave, liberal-minded and base mechanic, exist and are justified by nature—a nature which aims at embodied reason. What, finally, is this Nature to which the philos- ophy of society and the individual so bound itself? It is the nature which figures in Greek customs one INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 51 and myth; the nature resplendent and adorned which confronts us in Greek poetry and art: the animism of savage man purged of grossness and generalized by unerring esthetic taste into beauty and system. The myths had told of the loves and hates, the caprices and desertions of the gods, and behind them all, inevitable Fate. Philosophy translated these tales into formule of the brute fluctuation of rapacious change held in bounds by the final and supreme end: the rational good. The animism of the popular mind died to reappear as cosmology. Repeatedly in this course we have heard of sci- ences which began as parts of philosophy and which gradually won their independence. Another statement of the same history is that both science and philosophy began in subjection to mythological animism. Both began with acceptance of a nature whose irregularities displayed the meaningless vari- ability of foolish wants held within the limits of order and uniformity by an underlying movement toward a final and stable purpose. And when the sciences gradually assumed the task of reduc- ing irregular caprice to regular conjunction, phi- losophy bravely took upon itself the task of sub- stantiating, under the caption of a spiritual view of the universe, the animistic survival. Doubtless Socrates brought philosophy to earth; but his in- junction to man to know himself was incredibly 52: INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS compromised in its execution by the fact that later philosophers submerged man in the world to which | philosophy was brought: a world which was the heavy and sunken center of hierarchic heavens lo- cated in their purity and refinement as remotely as possible from the gross and muddy vesture of earth. | The various limitations of Greek custom, its hostile indifference to all outside the narrow city- state, its assumption of fixed divisions of wise and blind among men, its inability socially to utilize science, its subordination of human intention to cosmic aim—all of these things were worked into moral theory. Philosophy had no active hand in - producing the condition of barbarism in Europe’. ‘ { from the fifth to the fifteenth centuries. By an unwitting irony which would have shocked none so much as the lucid moralists of Athens, their philosophic idealization, under captions of Nature and Reason, of the inherent limitations of Athenian society and Greek science, furnished the intellectual tools for defining, standardizing, and justifying all the fundamental clefts and antagonisms of feudal- ism. When practical conditions are not frozen in men’s imagination into crystalline truths, they are naturally fluid. They come and go. But when intelligence fixes fluctuating circumstances into final ideals, petrifaction is likely to occur; and philosophy gratuitously took upon itself the re- INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 53 sponsibility for justifying the worst defects of barbarian Europe by showing their necessary con- nection with divine reason. The division of mankind into the two camps of the redeemed and the condemned had not needed philosophy to produce it. But the Greek cleavage of men into separate kinds on the basis of their position within or without the city-state was used to rationalize this harsh intolerance. The hier- archic organization of feudalism, within church and state, of those possessed of sacred rule and those whose sole excellence was obedience, did not require moral theory to generate or explain it. But it took philosophy to furnish the intellectual tools by which such chance episodes were emblaz- oned upon the cosmic heavens as a grandiose spiritual achievement. No; it is all too easy to explain bitter intolerance and desire for domina- tion. Stubborn as they are, it was only when Greek moral theory had put underneath them the distinction between the irrational and the rational, between divine truth and good and corrupt and weak human appetite, that intolerance on system and earthly domination for the sake of eternal excellence were philosophically sanctioned. The health and welfare of the body and the securing for all of a sure and a prosperous livelihood “~ were not matters for which medieval conditions fos- tered care in any case. But moral philosophy 54 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS was prevailed upon to damn the body on principle, and to relegate to insignificance as merely mun- ‘ dane and temporal the problem of a just industrial order. Circumstances of the times bore with suffi- cient hardness upon successful scientific investiga- tion; but philosophy added the conviction that in any case truth is so supernal that it must be super- naturally revealed, and so important that it must be authoritatively imparted and enforced. Intelli- gence was diverted from the critical consideration of the natural sources and social consequences — of better and worse into the channel of meta- physical subtleties and systems, acceptance of which was made essential to participation in the social order and in rational excellence. Philosophy bound the once erect form of human endeavor and ». progress to the chariot wheels of cosmology and theology. Since the Renaissance, moral philosophy has re- _ peatedly reverted to the Greek ideal of natural ex- — cellence realized in social life, under the fostering care of intelligence in action. The return, how- ever, has taken place under the influence of demo- ' cratic polity, commercial expansion, and scientific reorganization. It has been a liberation more than a reversion. This combined return and emancipa- tion, having transformed our practice of life in the last four centuries, will not be content till it has written itself clear in our theory of that practice. a em INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 55 Whether the consequent revolution in moral philos- ophy be termed pragmatism or be given the hap- pier title of the applied and experimental habit of mind is of little account. What is of moment is that intelligence has descended from its lonely iso- lation at the remote edge of things, whence it operated as unmoved mover and ultimate good, to take its seat in the moving affairs of men. Theory may therefore become responsible to the practices that have generated it; the good be connected with nature, but with nature naturally, not meta- physically, conceived, and social life be cherished in behalf of its own immediate possibilities, not on the ground of its remote connections with a cosmic reason and an absolute end. There is a notion, more familiar than correct, that Greek thought sacrificed the individual to the state. None has ever known better than the Greek that the individual comes to himself and to his own only in association with others. But Greek thought subjected, as we have seen, both state and individual to an external cosmic order ; and thereby it inevitably restricted the free use in doubt, in- quiry, and experimentation, of the human intelli- gence. The anima libera, the free mind of the sixteenth century, of Galileo and his successors, was the counterpart of the disintegration of cos- mology and its animistic teleology. The lecturer on political economy reminded us that his subject 56 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS began, in the Middle Ages, as a branch of ethics, though, as he hastened to show, it soon got into better association. Well, the same company was once kept by all the sciences, mathematical and physical as well as social. According to all ac- counts it was the integrity of the number one and the rectitude of the square that attracted the attention of Pythagoras to arithmetic and geom- etry as promising fields of study. Astronomy was the projected picture book of a cosmic object les- son in morals, Dante’s transcript of which is none the less literal because poetic. If physics alone re- mained outside the moral fold, while noble essences redeemed chemistry, occult forces blessed physi- © ology, and the immaterial soul exalted psychology, physics is the exception that proves the rule: mat- ter was so inherently immoral that no high-minded science would demean itself by contact with it. If we do not join with many in lamenting the stripping from nature of those idealistic properties in which animism survived, if we do not mourn the secession of the sciences from ethics, it is because the abandonment by intelligence of a fixed and static moral end was the necessary precondition of a free and progressive science of both things and morals; because the emancipation of the sciences from ready made, remote, and abstract values was necessary to make the sciences available for creat- ing and maintaining more and specific values here INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 57 and now. - The divine comedy of modern medicine and hygiene is one of the human epics yet to be written ; but when composed it may prove no un- worthy companion of the medieval epic of other worldly beatific visions. The great ideas of the eighteenth century, that expansive epoch of moral perception which ranks in illumination and fervor along with classic Greek thought, the great ideas of the indefinitely continuous progress of humanity and of the power and significance of freed intelli- gence, were borne by a single mother—experi- mental inquiry. The growth of industry and commerce is at once cause and effect of the growth in science. Democ- ritus and other ancients conceived the mechanical theory of the universe. The notion was not only blank and repellent, because it ignored the rich social material which Plato and Aristotle had or- ganized into their rival idealistic views ; but it was scientifically sterile, a piece of dialectics. Con- tempt for machines as the accouterments of de- spised mechanics kept the mechanical conception aloof from these specific-and controllable experi- ences which alone could fructify it. This concep- tion, then, like the idealistic, was translated into a speculative cosmology and thrown like a vast net around the universe at large, as if to keep it from , coming to pieces. It is from respect for the lever, ' the pulley, and the screw that modern experimental 58 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS and mathematical mechanics derives itself. Mo- tion, traced through the workings of a machine, was followed out into natural events and studied just as motion, not as a poor yet necessary device for realizing final causes. So studied, it was found to be available for new machines and new applica- tions, which in creating new ends also promoted new wants, and thereby stimulated new activities, new discoveries, and new inventions. The recognition that natural energy can be systematically applied, through experimental observation, to the satisfac- tion and multiplication of concrete wants is doubt- v less the greatest single discovery ever imported into the life of man—save perhaps the discovery of language. Science, borrowing from industry, re- paid the debt with interest, and has made the con- trol of natural forces for the aims of life so in- evitable that for the first time man is relieved from overhanging fear, with its wolflike scramble to pos- sess and accumulate, and is freed to consider the more gracious question of securing to all an ample and liberal life. The industrial life had been con- demned by Greek exaltation of abstract thought and by Greek contempt for labor, as representing the brute struggle of carnal appetite for its own satiety. ‘The industrial movement, offspring of science, restored it to its central position in morals. When Adam Smith made economic activity the moving spring of man’s unremitting effort, from << INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 59 the cradle to the grave, to better his own lot, he recorded this change. And when he made sympa- thy the central spring in man’s conscious moral en- deavor, he reported the effect which the increasing intercourse of men, due primarily to commerce, had in breaking down suspicion and jealousy and in liberating man’s kindlier impulses. Democracy, the crucial expression of modern life, is not so much an addition to the scientific and industrial tendencies as it is the perception of their social or spiritual meaning. Democracy is an absurdity where faith in the individual as in- ~ dividual is impossible; and this faith is impossible when intelligence is regarded as a cosmic power, not an adjustment and application of individual tendencies. It is also impossible when appetites and desires are conceived to be the dominant factor in the constitution of most men’s characters, and when appetite and desire are conceived to be mani- festations of the disorderly and unruly principle of nature. To put the intellectual center of gravity in the objective cosmos, outside of men’s own ex- periments and tests, and then to invite the applica- tion of individual intelligence to the determination of society, is to invite chaos. To hold that want is mere negative flux and hence requires external fixation by reason, and then to invite the wants to give free play to themselves in social construction and intercourse, is to call down anarchy. Democ- 60 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS racy is estimable only through the changed con- ception of intelligence, that forms modern science, / and of want, that forms modern industry. It is essentially a changed psychology. The substitu- tion, for a priori truth and deduction, of fluent doubt and inquiry meant trust in human nature in the concrete; in individual honesty, curiosity, and sympathy. The substitution of moving com- merce for fixed custom meant a view of wants as the dynamics of social progress, not as the pathol- ogy of private greed. The nineteenth century in- deed turned sour on that somewhat complacent op- timism in which the eighteenth century rested: the ideas that the intelligent self-love of individuals would conduce to social cohesion, and competition among individuals usher in the kingdom of social welfare. But the conception of a social harmony of interests in which the achievement by each in- dividual of his own freedom should contribute to a like perfecting of the powers of all, through a fraternally organized society, is the permanent contribution of the industrial movement to morals —even though so far it be but the contribution of a problem. Intellectually speaking, the centuries since the fourteenth are the true middle ages. They mark the transitional period of mental habit, as the so- called medieval period represents the petrifaction, under changed outward conditions, of Greek ideas. INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 61 The conscious articulation of genuinely modern tendencies has yet to come, and till it comes the ethic of our own life must remain undescribed. But the system of morals which has come nearest to the reflection of the movements of science, de- mocracy, and commerce, is doubtless the utilitarian. Scientific, after the modern mode, it certainly would be. Newton’s influence dyes deep the moral thought of the eighteenth century. The arrange- ments of the solar system had been described in terms of a homogeneous matter and motion, worked by two opposed and compensating forces: all be- cause a method of analysis, of generalization by analogy, and of mathematical deduction back to new empirical details had been followed. The im- agination of the eighteenth century was a New- tonian imagination; and this no less in social than in physical matters. Hume proclaims that morals is about to become an experimental science. Just as, almost in our own day, Mill’s interest in a method for social science led him to reformulate the logic of experimental inquiry, so all the great men of the Enlightenment were in search for the organon of morals which should repeat the physical triumphs of Newton. Bentham notes that physics has had its Bacon and Newton; that morals has had its Bacon in Helvétius, but still awaits its Newton; and he leaves us in no doubt that at the moment of writing he was ready, modestly but - 62 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS firmly, to fill the waiting niche with its missing figure. ~ The industrial movement furnished the concrete imagery for this ethical renovation. The utili- tarians borrowed from Adam Smith the notion that through industrial exchange in a free society the individual pursuing his own good is led, under the » guidance of the “ invisible hand,” to promote the general good more effectually than if he had set out to do it. This idea was dressed out in the atomistic psychology which Hartley built out from Locke—and was returned at usurious rates to later economists. : From the great French writers who had sought to justify and promote democratic individualism, came the conception that, since it is perverted political institutions which deprave individuals and bring them into hostility, nation against nation, class against class, individual against individual, the great political problem is such a reform of law and legislation, civil and criminal, of administra- tion, and of education as will force the individual to find his own interests in pursuits conducing to the welfare of others. Tremendously effective as a tool of criticism, op- erative in abolition and elimination, utilitarianism failed to measure up to the constructive needs of the time. Its theoretical equalization of the good of each with that of every other was practically Rial INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 63 perverted by its excessive interest in the middle and manufacturing classes. Its speculative defect of an atomistic psychology combined with this narrowness of vision to make light of the construc- tive work that needs to be done by the state, before all can have, otherwise than in name, an equal chance to count in the common good. Thus the age-long subordination of economics to politics was revenged in the submerging of both politics and ethics in a narrow theory of economic profit; and utilitarianism, in its orthodox descendants, prof- fered the disjointed pieces of a mechanism, with a monotonous reiteration that looked at aright they form a beautifully harmonious organism. _ Prevision, and to some extent experience, of this failure, conjoined with differing social traditions and ambitions, evoked German idealism, the trans- cendental morals of Kant and his successors. Ger- man thought strove to preserve the traditions which bound culture to the past, while revising these traditions to render them capable of meeting novel conditions. It found weapons at hand in the conceptions borrowed by Roman law from Stoic ' philosophy, and in the conceptions by which Prot- estant humanism had re-edited scholastic Catholi- cism. Grotius had made the idea of natural law, natural right and obligation, the central idea of German morals, as thoroughly as Locke had made the individual desire for liberty and happiness the 64 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS focus of English and then of French speculation. Materialized idealism is the happy monstrosity in which the popular demand for vivid imagery is most easily reconciled with the equally strong de- mand for supremacy of moral values ; and the com- plete idealistic materialism of Stoicism has always given its ideas a practical influence out of all pro- portion to their theoretical vogue as a system. To the Protestant, that is the German, humanist, Natural Law, the bond of harmonious reason in nature, the spring of social intercourse among men, the inward light of individual conscience, united Cicero, St. Paul, and Luther in blessed union; gave a rational, not superrational basis for morals, and provided room for social legislation which at the same time could easily be held back from too ruthless application to dominant class in- terests. Kant saw the mass of empirical and hence irrele- vant detail that had found refuge within this lib- eral and diffusive reason. He saw that the idea of reason could be made self-consistent only by strip- ping it naked of these empirical accretions. He then provided, in his critiques, a somewhat cum- brous moving van for transferring the resultant pure or naked reason out of nature and the ob- jective world, and for locating it in new quarters, , with a new stock of goods and new customers. The ~ new quarters were particular subjects, individuals ; * r INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 65 the stock of goods were the forms of perception and the functions of thought by which empirical flux is woven into durable fabrics ; the new customers were a society of individuals in which all are ends in them- selves. There ought to be an injunction issued that Kant’s saying about Hume’s awakening of him should not be quoted save in connection with his other saying that Rousseau brought him to him- self, in teaching him that the philosopher is of less account than the laborer in the fields unless he con- tributes to human freedom. But none the less, the new tenant, the universal reason, and the old home- stead, the empirical tumultuous individual, could not get on together. Reason became a mere voice which, having nothing in particular to say, said Law, Duty, in general, leaving to the existing social order of the Prussia of Frederick the Great the congenial task of declaring just what was ob- ligatory in the concrete. The marriage of free- dom and authority was thus celebrated with the understanding that sentimental primacy went to the former and practical control to the latter. The effort to force a universal reason that had been used to the broad domains of the cosmos into the cramped confines of individuality conceived as merely “ empirical,” a highly particularized crea- ture of sense, could have but one result: an explo- sion. The products of that explosion constitute the Post-Kantian philosophies. It was the work of 66 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS ‘Hegel to attempt to fill in the empty reason of Kant with the concrete contents of history. The voice sounded like the voice of Aristotle, Thomas of Aquino, and Spinoza translated into Swabian German ; but the hands were as the hands of Mon- tesquieu, Herder, Condorcet, and the rising his- torical school. The outcome was the assertion that history is reason, and reason is history: the actual is rational, the rational is the actual. It gave the pleasant appearance (which Hegel did not strenu- ously discourage) of being specifically an idealiza- tion of the Prussian nation, and incidentally a sys- tematized apologetic for the universe at large. But in intellectual and practical effect, it lifted the idea of process above that of fixed origins and fixed ’ ends, and presented the social and moral order, as well as the intellectual, as a scene of becoming, and it located reason somewhere within the struggles of life. Unstable equilibrium, rapid fermentation, and a succession of explosive reports are thus the chief notes of modern ethics. Scepticism and tradition- alism, empiricism and rationalism, crude natural- isms and all-embracing idealisms, flourish side by | side—all the more flourish, one suspects, because side by side. Spencer exults because natural science reveals that a rapid transit system of evolution is carrying us automatically to the goal of perfect man in perfect society; and his English idealistic INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS __.- 67 contemporary, Green, is so disturbed by the re- moval from nature of its moral qualities, that he tries to show that this makes no difference, since na- ture in any case is constituted and known through a spiritual principle which is as permanent as na- ture is changing. An Amiel genteelly laments the decadence of the inner life, while his neighbor Nietz- sche brandishes in rude ecstasy the banner of brute survival as a happy omen of the final victory of nobility of mind. ‘The reasonable conclusion from such a scene is that there is taking place a trans- formation of attitude towards moral theory rather than mere propagation of varieties among theories. The classic theories all agreed in one regard. They all alike assumed the existence of the end, the swm- mum bonum, the final goal; and of the separate moral force that moves to that goal. Moralists have disputed as to whether the end is an aggre- gate of pleasurable state of consciousness, enjoy- ment of the divine essence, acknowledgment of the law of duty, or conformity to environment. So they have disputed as to the path by which the final goal is to be reached: fear or benevolence? rever- ence for pure law or pity for others? self-love or altruism? But these very controversies implied that there was but the one end and the one means. , The transformation in attitude, to which I re- ferred, is the growing belief that the proper busi- 68 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS ness of intelligence is discrimination of multiple and present goods and of the varied immediate “ means of their realization; not search for the one remote aim. The progress of biology has accus- tomed our minds to the notion that intelligence is not an outside power presiding supremely but stat- ically over the desires and efforts of man, but is a method of adjustment of capacities and con- ditions within specific situations. History, as the lecturer on that subject told us, has discovered it- self in the idea of process. The genetic standpoint makes us aware that the systems of the past are neither fraudulent impostures nor absolute revela- tions ; but are the products of political, economic, and scientific conditions whose change carries with it change of theoretical formulations. The recog- nition that intelligence is properly an organ of ad- justment in difficult situations makes us aware that past theories were of value so far as they helped carry to an issue the social perplexities from which they emerged. But the chief impact of the evo- lutionary method is upon the present. Theory having learned what it cannot do, is made respon- sible for the better performance of what needs to be done, and what only a broadly equipped intelli- gence can undertake: study of the conditions out of which come the obstacles and the resources of adequate life, and developing and testing the ideas that, as working hypotheses, may be used to dimin- INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 69 ish the causes of evil and to buttress and ex- pand the sources of good. This program is indeed vague, but only unfamiliarity with it could lead one to the conclusion that it is less vague than the idea that there is a single moral ideal and a single moral motive force. From this point of view there is no separate body of moral rules; no separate system of motive pow- ers; no separate subject-matter. of moral knowl- edge, and hence no such thing as an isolated ethical science. If the business of morals is not to specu- late upon man’s final end and upon an ultimate standard of right, it is to utilize physiology, an- thropology, and psychology to discover all that can be discovered of man, his organic powers and propensities. If its business is not to search for the one separate moral motive, it is to converge all the instrumentalities of the social arts, of law, edu- cation, economics, and political science upon the construction of intelligent methods of improving the common lot. If we still wish to make our peace with the past, and to sum up the plural and changing goods of -~ life in a single word, doubtless the term happiness is the one most apt. But we should again ex- change free morals for sterile metaphysics, if we imagine that “ happiness ” is any less unique than the individuals who experience it; any less complex — than the constitution of their capacities, or any less 70 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS variable than the objects upon which their capaci- ties are directed. ; . To many timid, albeit sincere, souls of an earlier century, the decay of the doctrine that all true and worthful science is knowledge of final causes seemed fraught with danger to science and to mor- als.’ The rival conception of a wide open universe, a universe without bounds in time or space, without final limits of origin or destiny, a universe with the lid off, was a menace. We now face in moral sci- ence a similar crisis and like opportunity, as well as share in a like dreadful suspense. The abolition of a fixed and final goal and causal force in nature did not, as matter of fact, render rational convic- tion less important or less attainable. It was ac- companied by the provision of a technique of per- sistent and detailed inquiry in all special fields of fact, a technique which led to the detection of un- suspected forces and the revelation of undreamed of uses. In like fashion we may anticipate that the abolition of the final goal and the single motive power and the separate and infallible faculty in morals, will quicken inquiry into the diversity of specific goods of experience, fix attention upon their conditions, and bring to light values now dim and obscure. The change may relieve men from responsibility for what they cannot do, but it will promote thoughtful consideration of what they may do and the definition of responsibility for what INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 71 they do amiss because of failure to think straight and carefully. Absolute goods will fall into the background, but the question of making more sure and extensive the share of all men in natural and social goods will be urgent, a problem not to be escaped nor evaded. Morals, philosophy, returns to its first love; love of the wisdom that is nurse, as nature is mother, of good. But it returns to the Socratic principle “ equipped with a multitude of special methods of in- quiry and testing; with an organized mass of knowledge, and with control of the arrangements by which industry, law, and education may concen- trate upon the problem of the participation by all men and women, up to their capacity of absorption, in all attained values. Morals may then well leave to poetry and to art, the task (so unartistically performed by philosophy since Plato) of gathering together and rounding out, into one abiding pic- ture, the separate and special goods of life. It may leave this task with the assurance that the re- sultant synthesis will not depict any final and all- inclusive good, but will add just one more specific good to the enjoyable excellencies of life. Humorous irony shines through most of the harsh glances turned towards the idea of an ex- perimental basis and career for morals. Some shiver in the fear that morals will be plunged into anarchic confusion—a view well expressed by a 72 »§ INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS recent writer in the saying that if the a priori and transcendental basis of morals be abandoned “ we shall have merely the same certainty that now ex- ists in physics and chemistry ”! Elsewhere lurks the apprehension that the progress of scientific method will deliver the purposive freedom of mar bound hand and foot to the fatal decrees of iron necessity, called natural law. The notion that laws govern and forces rule is an animistic sur- vival. It is a product of reading nature in terms of politics in order to turn around and then read politics in the light of supposed sanctions of na- ture. This idea passed from medieval theology into the science of Newton, to whom the universe was the dominion of a sovereign whose laws were the laws of nature. From Newton it passed into the deism of the eighteenth century, whence it mi- grated into the philosophy of the Enlightenment, — to make its last stand in Spencer’s philosophy of the fixed environment and the static goal. No, nature is not an unchangeable order, un- winding itself majestically from the reel of law under the control of deified forces. It is an in- definite congeries of changes. Laws are not gov- ernmental regulations which limit change, but are convenient formulations: of selected portions of change followed through a longer or shorter period of time, and then registered in statistical forms that are amenable to mathematical manipulation. INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 73 That this device of shorthand symbolization pres- ages the subjection of man’s intelligent effort to fixity of law and environment is interesting as a culture survival, but is not important for moral theory. Savage and child delight in creating bogeys from which, their origin and structure be-, ing conveniently concealed, interesting thrills and shudders may be had. Civilized man in the nine- teenth century outdid these bugaboos in his image of a fixed universe hung on a cast-iron framework of fixed, necessary, and universal laws. Knowl- edge of nature does not mean subjection to predes- tination, but insight into courses of change; an insight which is formulated in “ laws,” that is, methods of subsequent procedure. Knowledge of the process and conditions of phys- ical and social change through experimental science and genetic history has one result with a double ame : increase of control, and increase of responsi- bility ; increase of power to direct natural change, and increase of responsibility for its equitable direc- tion toward fuller good. Theory located within progressive practice instead of reigning statically supreme over it, means practice itself made respon- sible to intelligence; to intelligence which relent- lessly scrutinizes the consequences of every prac- tice, and which exacts liability by an equally re- lentless publicity. As long as morals occupies it- self with mere ideals, forces and conditions as they 74 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS are will be good enough for “ practical ” men, since they are then left free to their own devices in turning these to their own account. As long as moralists plume themselves upon possession of the. domain of the categorical imperative with its bare precepts, men of executive habits will always be at their elbows to regulate the concrete social condi- tions through which the form of law gets its actual filling of specific injunctions. When freedom is conceived to be transcendental, the coercive re- straint of immediate necessity will lay its harsh hand upon the mass of men. In the end, men do what they can do. They refrain from doing what they cannot do. They do what their own specific powers in conjunction with the limitations and resources of the environ- ment permit. The effective control of their powers is not through precepts, but through the regula- tion of their conditions. If this regulation is to be not merely physical or coercive, but moral, it must consist of the intelligent selection and de- termination of the environments in which we act; and in an intelligent exaction of responsibility for the use of men’s powers. Theorists inquire after the “‘ motive ” to morality, to virtue and the good, under such circumstances. What then, one won- ders, is their conception of the make-up of human nature and of its relation to virtue and to good- ness? The pessimism that dictates such a ques- INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS 75 tion, if it be justified, precludes any consideration of morals. The diversion of intelligence from discrimina- tion of plural and concrete goods, from noting their conditions and obstacles, and from devis- ing methods for holding men responsible for their concrete use of powers and conditions, has done ¥ more than brute love of power to establish in- equality and injustice among men. It has done more, because it has confirmed with social sanc- tions the principle of feudal domination. All men require moral sanctions in their conduct: the consent of their kind. Not getting it otherwise, they go insane to feign it. No man ever lived ~ with the exclusive approval of his own conscience. Hence the vacuum left in practical matters by the remote irrelevancy of transcendental morals has to be filled in somehow. It is filled in. It is filled in with class-codes, class-standards, class-approvals —with codes which recommend the practices and habits already current in a given circle, set, calling, profession, trade, industry, club, or gang. These class-codes always lean back upon and support themselves by the professed ideal code. This latter meets them more than half-way. Being in its pre- tense a theory for regulating practice, it must dem- onstrate its practicability. It is uneasy in isolation, and travels hastily to meet with compromise and accommodation the actual situation in all its brute 76 INTELLIGENCE AND MORALS unrationality. Where the pressure is greatest— ° in the habitual practice of the political and eco- nomic chieftains—there it accommodates the most. Class-codes of morals are sanctions, under the caption of ideals, of uncriticised customs ; they are recommendations, under the head of duties, of what the members of the class are already most given to doing. If there are to obtain more equable and comprehensive principles of action, exacting a more impartial exercise of natural power and re- source in the interests of a common good, members of a class must no longer rest content in responsi- bility to a class whose traditions constitute its conscience, but be made responsible to a society whose conscience is its free and effectively organ- ized intelligence. In such a conscience alone will the Socratic in- junction to man to know himself be fulfilled. } Va 4 \ THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE * T should be possible to discern and describe a knowing as one identifies any object, concern, or event. It must have its own marks; it must offer characteristic features—as much so as a thunder-storm, the constitution of a State, or a leopard. In the search for this affair, we are first of all desirous for something which is for itself, contemporaneously with its occurrence, a cognition, not something called knowledge by another and from without—whether this other be logician, psychologist, or epistemologist. The “ knowl- edge” may turn out false, and hence no knowl- edge; but this is an after-affair; it may prove to be rich in fruitage of wisdom, but if this outcome be only wisdom after the event, it does not concern us. What we want is just some- thing which takes itself as knowledge, rightly or wrongly. * Reprinted, with considerable change in the arrange- ment and in the matter of the latter portion, from Mind, Vol. XV., N.S., July, 1906. 77 78 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY © I ‘This means a specific case, a sample. Yet in- stances are proverbially dangerous—so naively and graciously may they beg the questions at issue. Our recourse is to an example so simple, so much on its face as to be as innocent as may be of as- sumptions. ‘This case we shall gradually compli- cate, mindful at each step to state just what new elements are introduced. Let us suppose a smell, just a floating odor. This odor may be anchored by supposing that it moves to action; it starts changes that end in picking and enjoying a rose. This description is intended to apply to the course of events witnessed and recounted from without. What sort of a course must it be to constitute a knowledge, or to have somewhere within its career that which deserves this title? The smell, im- primis, is there; the movements that it excites are there; the final plucking and gratification are ex- perienced. But, let us say, the smell is not the smell of the rose; the resulting change of the or- ganism is not a sense of walking and reaching; the delicious finale is not the fulfilment of the move- ment, and, through that, of the original smell; “‘ is not,” in each case meaning is “ not experienced as ” such. We may take, in short, these experiences in a brutely serial fashion. ‘The smell, S, is replaced (and displaced) by a felt movement, K, this is re- THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 79 placed by the gratification, G. Viewed from with- out, as we are now regarding it, there is S-K-G. But from within, for itself, it is now S, now K, now G, and so on to the end of the chapter. Nowhere is there looking before and after; memory and anticipation are not born. Such an experience neither is, in whole or in part, a knowledge, nor does it exercise a cognitive function. Here, however, we may be halted. If there is anything present in “ consciousness ” at all, we may be told (at least we constantly are so told) there must be knowledge of it as present—present, at all events, in “ consciousness.” There is, so it is argued, knowledge at least of a simple appre- hensive type, knowledge of the acquaintance order, knowledge that, even though not knowledge what. The smell, it is admitted, does not know about any-. thing else, nor is anything known about the smell (the same thing, perhaps) ; but the smell is known, either by itself, or by the mind, or by some sub- ject, some. unwinking, unremitting eye. No, we must reply; there is no apprehension without some i (however slight) context; no acquaintance which is not either recognition or expectation. Ac- quaintance is presence honored with an escort; presence is introduced as familiar, or an associate springs up to greet it. Acquaintance always im- plies a little friendliness ; a trace of re-knowing, of 80 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY anticipatory welcome or dread of the trait to fol- low. ! . This claim cannot be dismissed as trivial. If valid, it carries with it the distance between being and knowing: and the recognition of an element of mediation, that is, of art, in all knowledge. This disparity, this transcendence, is not something which holds of our knowledge, of finite knowledge, just marking the gap between our type of con- sciousness and some other with which we may con- trast it after the manner of the agnostic or the transcendentalist (who hold so much property in joint ownership!), but exists because knowing is _ knowing, that way of bringing things to bear upon things which we call reflection—a manipulation of things experienced in the light one of another. ** Feeling,” I read in a recent article, “ feeling is immediately acquainted with its own quality, with its own subjective being.” * How and whence this duplication in the inwards of feeling into feel- *I must remind the reader again of a point already sug- gested. It is the identification of presence in consciousness pees knowledge as such that leads to setting up a mind (ego, subject) which has the peculiar property of knowing (only so often it knows wrong!), or else that leads to supplying “sensations” with the peculiar property of sur- veying their own entrails. Given the correct feeling that knowledge involves relationship, there being, by supposition, no other thing to which the thing in consciousness is related, it is forthwith related to a soul substance, or to its ghostly offspring, a “subject,” or to “consciousness” itself, THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 81 ing the knower and feeling the known? into feeling as being and feeling as acquaintance? Let us frankly deny such monsters. Feeling is its own »quality ; is its own specific (whence and why, once more, subjective?) being. If this statement be dogmatism, it is at least worth insistent declara- tion, were it only by way of counter-irritant to that other dogmatism which asserts that being in “ con- sciousness ” is always presence for or in knowledge. So let us repeat once more, that to be a smell (or anything else) is one thing, to be known as smell, another ; to be a “ feeling ” one thing, to be known as a “ feeling” another.* The first is thinghood ;~ existence indubitable, direct; in this way all things are that are in “consciousness ” at all.? The second is reflected being, things indicating and call- ~ ing for other things—something offering the possi- bility of truth and hence of falsity. The first is ~~ * Let us further recall that this theory requires either that things present shall already be psychical things (feelings, — sensations, etc.), in order to be assimilated to the knowing mind, subject to consciousness; or else translates genuinely naive realism into the miracle of a mind that gets out- side itself to lay its ghostly hands upon the things of an external world. ? This means that things may be present as known, just as they be present as hard or soft, agreeable or disgusting, hoped for or dreaded. The mediacy, or the art of interven- tion, which characterizes knowledge, indicates precisely the way in which known things as known are immediately present, oa 82 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY genuine immediacy; the second is (in the instance discussed) a pseudo-immediacy, which in the same breath that it proclaims its immediacy smuggles in another term (and one which is unexperienced both ‘ in itself and in its relation) the subject or “ con- sciousness,” to which the immediate is related.* But we need not remain with dogmatic asser- tions. To be acquainted with a thing or with a person has a definite empirical meaning; we have only to call to mind what it is to be genuinely and empirically acquainted, to have done forever with _ this uncanny presence which, though bare and sim- ple presence, is yet known, and thus is clothed upon and complicated. To be acquainted with a thing is to be assured (from the standpoint of the experience itself) that it is of such and such a character ; that it will behave, if given an oppor- tunity, in such and such a way; that the obviously and flagrantly present trait is associated with fel- low traits that will show themselves, if the lead- ings of the present trait are followed out. To be *If Hume had had a tithe of the interest in the flux of perceptions and in habit—principles of continuity and of organization—which he had in distinct and isolated exist- ences, he might have saved us both from German Erkennt- nisstheorie, and from that modern miracle play, the psychol- ogy of elements of consciousness, that under the egis of science, does not hesitate to have psychical elements com- pound and breed, and in their agile intangibility put to shame the performances of their less acrobatic cousins, physical atoms, ss aaa THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 88 acquainted is to anticipate to some extent, on the basis of prior experience. I am, say, barely ac- quainted with Mr. Smith: then I have no extended body of associated qualities along with those palpa- bly present, but at least some one suggested trait occurs ; his nose, his tone of voice, the place where I saw him, his calling in life, an interesting anec- dote about him, etc. To be acquainted is to know what a thing is like in some particular. If one is } acquainted with the smell of a flower it means that the smell is not just smell, but reminds one of © some other experienced thing which stands in con- tinuity with the smell. There is thus supplied a condition of control over or purchase upon what is present, the possibility of translating it into terms of some other trait not now sensibly present. Let us return to our example. Let us suppose that § is not just displaced by K and then by G. Let us suppose it persists; and persists not as an unchanged § alongside K and G, nor yet as fused with them into a new further quale J. For in such events, we have only the type ‘already considered and rejected. For an observer the new quale might be more complex, or fuller of meaning, than the ‘ original S, K, or G, but might not be experienced as complex. We might thus suppose a composite photograph which should suggest nothing of the complexity of its origin and structure. In this case we should have simply another picture. fap SE. 84 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY But we may also suppose that the blur of the photograph suggests the superimposition of pic- tures and something of their character. Then we get another, and for our problem, much more fruit- ful kind of persistence. We will imagine that the final G assumes this form: Gratification-terminat- ing-movement-induced-by-smell. The smell is still present; it has persisted. It is not present in its original form, but is represented with a quality, an office, that of having excited activity and thereby terminating its career in a certain quale of grati- fication. It is not S, but = ; that is § with an increment of meaning due to maintenance and ful- filment through a process. S§ is no longer just smell, but smell which has excited and thereby se- cured. Here we have a cognitive, but not a cognitional thing. In saying that the smell is finally experi- enced as meaning gratification (through interven- ing handling, seeing, etc.) and meaning it not in a hapless way, but in a fashion which operates to effect what is meant, we retrospectively attribute ' intellectual force and function to the smell—and this is what is signified by “ cognitive.” Yet the smell is not cognitional, because it did not know- ingly intend to mean this; but is found, after the event, to have meant it. Nor again is the final experience, the = or transformed S, a knowledge. Here again the statement may be challenged. 4 =“ THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 85 - Those who agree with the denial that bare presence of a quale in “consciousness” constitutes acquaint- ance and simple apprehension, may now turn against us, saying that experience of fulfilment of meaning is just what we mean by knowledge, and this is just what the & of our illustration is. The point is fundamental. As the smell at first was presence or being, less than knowing, so the fulfil-~ ment is an experience that is more than knowing. Seeing and handling the flower, enjoying the full | meaning of the smell as the odor of just this beautiful thing, is not knowledge because it is more. than knowledge. As this may seem dogmatic, let us suppose that the fulfilment, the realization, experience, is a knowledge. Then how shall it be distinguished from and yet classed with other things called knowl- edge, viz., reflective, discursive cognitions? Such knowledges are what they are precisely because they are not fulfilments, but intentions, aims, schemes, symbols of overt fulfilment. Knowledge, perceptual . and conceptual, of a hunting dog is prerequisite in order that I may really hunt with the hounds. The hunting in turn may increase my knowledge of dogs and their ways. But the knowledge of the dog, qua knowledge, remains characteristically marked off from the use of that knowledge in the fulfilment experience, the hunt. The hunt is a realization of knowledge; it alone, if you please, verifies, vali- 86 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY dates, knowledge, or supplies tests of truth. The prior knowledge of the dog, was, if you wish, ‘hypothetical, lacking in assurance or categorical certainty. The hunting, the fulfillmg, realizing experience alone gives knowledge, because it alone completely assures ; makes faith good in works. Now there is and can be no objection to this definition of knowledge, provided it is consistently adhered to. One has as much right to identify knowledge with complete assurance, as I have to identify it with anything else. Considerable justi- fication in the common use of language, in common sense, may be found for defining knowledge as com- plete assurance. But even upon this definition, the fulfilling experience is not, as such, complete assur- ance, and hence not a knowledge. Assurance, cog- nitive validation, and guaranteeship, follow from it, but are not coincident with its occurrence. It gives, but is not, assurance. The concrete con- struction of a story, the manipulation of a machine, the hunting with the dogs, is not, so far as it is fulfilment, a confirmation of meanings previously entertained as cognitional; that is, is not contem- poraneously experienced as such. To think of prior schemes, symbols, meanings, as fulfilled in a subsequent experience, is reflectively to present in their relations to one another both the mean- ings and the experiences in which they are, as a matter of fact, embodied. This reflective at- THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 87 , titude cannot be identical with the fulfilment ex- perience itself; it occurs only in retrospect when the worth of the meanings, or cognitive ideas, is critically inspected in the light of their fulfilment ; or it occurs as an interruption of the fulfilling experience. The hunter stops his hunting as a fulfilment to reflect that he made a mistake in his idea of his dog, or again, that his dog is everything he thought he was—that his notion of him is confirmed. Or, the man stops the actual construction of his machine and turns back upon his plan in correction or in admiring estimate of its value. The fulfilling experience is not of itself ~ knowledge, then, even if we identify knowledge with fulness of assurance or guarantee. More- over it gives, affords, assurance only in reference to a situation which we have not yet considered.* Before the category of confirmation or refuta- tion can be introduced, there must be something which means to mean something and which there- fore can be guaranteed or nullified by the issue— and this is precisely what we have not as yet found. We must return to our instance and introduce a further complication. Let us suppose that the smell quale recurs at a later date, and that it recurs neither as the original S nor yet as the *In other words, the situation as described is not to be confused with the case of hunting on purpose to test an idea regarding the dog. 88 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY final 3, but as an S’ which is fated or charged , with the sense of the possibility of a fulfilment like unto =. The S’ that recurs is aware of some- _ thing else which it means, which it intends to effect through an operation incited by it and without which its own presence is abortive, and, so to say, unjustified, senseless. Now we have an experience ‘which is cognitional, not merely cognitive; which is contemporaneously aware of meaning something beyond itself, instead of having this meaning as- cribed by another at a later period. The odor knows the rose; the rose is known by the odor; and the import of each term is constituted by the re- lationship in which it stands to the other. That is, the import of the smell is the indicating and demanding relation which it sustains to the enjoy- ment of the rose as its fulfilling experience; while this enjoyment is just the content or definition of what the smell consciously meant, %¢., meant to mean. Both the thing meaning and the thing meant are elements in the same situation. Both are present, but both are not present in the same way. In fact, one is present as-not-present-in- the-same-way-in-which-the-other-is. It is present » as something to be rendered present in the same way through the intervention of an operation. We must not balk at a purely verbal difficulty. It suggests a verbal inconsistency to speak of a thing present-as-absent. But all ideal contents, THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 89 all aims (that is, things aimed at) are present in just such fashion. Things can be presented as absent, just as they can be presented as hard or soft, black or white, six inches or fifty rods away from the body. The assumption that an ideal content must be either totally absent, or else / present in just the same fashion as it will be when it is realized, is not only dogmatic, but self- contradictory. The only way in which an ideal content.can be experienced at all is to be presented as not-present-in-the-same-way in which something else is present, the latter kind of presence afford- ing the standard or type of satisfactory presence. When present in the same way it ceases to be an ideal content. Not a contrast of bare existence over against non-existence, or of present conscious- ness over against reality out of present conscious- ness, but of a satisfactory with an unsatisfactory mode of presence makes the difference between the “‘ really ” and the “ ideally ” present. In terms of our illustration, handling and en- joying the rose are present, but they are not present in the same way that the smell is present. They are present as going to be there in the same way, through an operation which the smell stands sponsor for. The situation is inherently an uneasy one—one in which everything hangs upon the performance of the operation indicated; upon the adequacy of movement as a connecting (90) THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY link, or real adjustment of the thing meaning and the thing meant. Generalizing from the instance, we get the following definition: An experience is a knowledge, if in its quale there is an experienced ' distinction and connection of two elements of the following sort: one means or intends the presence of the other in the same fashion in which itself is already present, while the other is that which, while not present in the same fashion, must become so present if the meaning or intention of its com- panion or yoke-fellow is to be fulfilled through the operation it sets wp. II We now return briefly to the question of knowl- edge as acquaintance, and at greater length to that of knowledge as assurance, or as fulfilment which confirms and validates. With the recurrence of the odor as meaning something beyond itself, there is apprehension, knowledge that. One may now say I know what a rose smells like; or I know what this smell is like; I am acquainted with the rose’s agreeable odor. In short, on the basis of a present quality, the odor anticipates and forestalls some further trait. We have also the conditions of knowledge of the confirmation and refutation type. In the working out of the situation just described, in the trans- THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY _ 91 formation, self-indicated and self-demanded, of the tensional into a harmonious or satisfactory situa- tion, fulfilment or disappointment results. The odor either does or does not fulfil itself in the rose. The smell as intention is borne out by the facts, or is nullified. As has already been pointed out, the subsequent experience of the fulfilment type is not primarily a confirmation or refutation. Its import is too vital, too urgent to be reduced in itself just to the value of testing an intention or meaning.” But it gets in reflection just such veri- 7 ficatory significance. If the smell’s intention is / unfulfilled, the discrepancy may throw one back, in reflection, upon the original situation. Inter- esting developments then occur. The smell meant a rose; and yet it did not (so it turns out) mean a rose; it meant another flower, or something, one can’t just tell what. Clearly there is something *Dr. Moore, in an essay in “Contributions to Logical Theory ” has brought out clearly, on the basis of a criticism of the theory of meaning and fulfilment advanced in Royce’s “ World and Individual,” the full consequences of this distinction. I quote one sentence (p. 350): “ Surely there is a pretty discernible difference between experience as a purposive idea, and the experience which fulfils this purpose. To call them both ‘ideas’ is at least confusing.” The text above simply adds that there is also a discernible and im- portant difference between experiences which, de facto, are purposing and fulfilling (that is, are seen to be such ab extra), and those which meant to be such, and are found to _be what they meant. 92 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY else which enters in ; something else beyond the odor _as it was first experienced determined the validity of its meaning. Here then, perhaps, we have a transcendental, as distinct from an experimental reference? Only if this something else makes no difference, or no detectable difference, in the smell itself. If the utmost observation and reflection can find no difference in the smell quales that fail and those that succeed in executing their inten- tions, then there is an outside controlling and dis- ' turbing factor, which, since it is outside of the sit- uation, can never be utilized in knowledge, and hence can never be employed in any concrete test- ing or verifying. In this case, knowing depends upon an extra-experimental or transcendental fac- tor. But this very transcendental quality makes both confirmation and refutation, correction, criti- cism, of the pretensions or meanings of things, impossible. For the conceptions of truth and error, we must, upon the transcendental basis, sub- stitute those of accidental success or failure. Sometimes the intention chances upon one, some- times upon another. Why or how, the gods only know—and they only if to them the extra-experi- - mental factor is not extra-experimental, but makes a concrete difference in the concrete smell. But fortunately the situation is not one to be thus de- scribed. The factor that determines the success or failure, does institute a difference in the thing THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 93 which means the object, and this difference is de- tectable, once attention, through failure, has been called to the need of its discovery. At the very least, it makes this difference: the smell is infected with an element of uncertainty of meaning—and this as a part of the thing experienced, not for an observer. This additional awareness at least brings about an additional wariness. Meaning is more critical, and operation more cautious. But we need not stop here. Attention may be fully directed to the subject of smells. Smells may become the object of knowledge. They may take, pro tempore,’ the place which the rose formerly occupied. One may, that is, observe the cases in which odors mean other things than just roses, may voluntarily produce new cases for the sake of further inspection, and thus account for the cases where meanings had been falsified in the issue; discriminate more carefully the peculiari- ties of those meanings which the event verified, and thus safeguard and bulwark to some extent the employing of similar meanings in the future. Su- perficially, it may then seem as if odors were treated after the fashion of Locke’s simple ideas, * The association of science and philosophy with leisure, y y~ with a certain economic surplus, is not accidental. It is ’ practically worth while to postpone practice; to substitute theorizing, to develop a new and fascinating mode of prac- tice. But it is the excess achievement of practice which makes this postponement and substitution possible. on 94 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY or Hume’s “ distinct ideas which are separate existences.” Smells apparently assume an inde- pendent, isolated status during this period of in- vestigation. ‘ Sensations,” as the laboratory psy- chologist and the analytic psychologist generally studies them, are examples of just such detached things. But egregious error results if we forget that this seeming isolation and detachment is the outcome of a deliberate scientific device—that it is simply a part of the scientific technique of an in- quiry directed upon securing tested conclusions. Just and only because odors (or any group of qualities) are parts of a connected world are they signs of things beyond themselves; and only because they are signs is it profitable and necessary to study them as if they were complete, self-en- closed entities. In the reflective determination of things with reference to their specifically meaning other things, experiences of fulfilment, disappointment, and go- ing astray inevitably play an important and recur- rent réle. They also are realistic facts, related in realistic ways to the things that intend to mean other things and to the things intended. When these fulfilments and refusals are reflected upon in the determinate relations in which they stand to their relevant meanings, they obtain a quality which is quite lacking to them in their immediate occur- rence as just fulfilments or disappointments ; viz., ae THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 95 the property of affording assurance and correction —of confirming and refuting. Truth and falsity are not properties of any experience or thing, in and of itself or in its first intention ; but of things ? where the problem of assurance consciously enters im. Truth and falsity present themselves as sig- nificant facts only m situations im which specific meanings and their already experienced fulfilments and non-fulfilments are intentionally compared and contrasted with reference to the question of the worth, as to reliability of meanmg, of the given meaning or class of meanings. Like knowledge j itself, truth is an experienced relation of things, and it has no meaning outside of such relation,’ any more than such adjectives as comfortable applied to a lodging, correct applied to speech, persuasive applied to an orator, etc., have worth apart from the specific things to which they are applied. It would be a great gain for logic and epistemology, if we were always to translate the noun “ truth” back into the adjective “ true,” and this back into ‘the adverb “truly ”; at least, if we were to do so until we have familiarized ourselves thoroughly * It is the failure to grasp the coupling of truth of mean- ) ing with a specific promise, undertaking, or intention ex- pressed by a thing which underlies, so far as I can see, the criticisms passed upon the experimental or pragmatic view of the truth. It is the same failure which is re- sponsible for the wholly at large view of truth which char- acterizes the absolutists, 96 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY with the fact that “truth” is an abstract noun, summarizing a quality presented by specific affairs in their own specific contents. III I have attempted, in the foregoing pages, a de- scription of the function of knowledge in its own terms and on its merits—a description which in intention is realistic, if by realistic we are content to mean naturalistic, a description undertaken on the basis of what Mr. Santayana has well called ** following the lead of the subject-matter.” Un- fortunately at the present time all such undertak- ings contend with a serious extraneous obstacle. Accomplishing the undertaking has difficulties enough of its own to reckon with; and first attempts are sure to be imperfect, if not radically wrong. But at present the attempts are not, for the most part, even listened to on their own account, they are not examined and criticised as naturalistic at- tempts. They are compared with undertakings of a wholly different nature, with an epistemological theory of knowledge, and the assumptions of this extraneous theory are taken as a ready-made stand- ard by which to test their validity. Literally of course, “epistemology” means only theory of knowledge; the term might therefore have been employed simply as a synonym for a descriptive THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 97 logic; for a theory that takes knowledge as it finds it and attempts to give the same kind of an account of it that would be given of any other natu- ral function or occurrence. But the mere mention of what might have been only accentuates what is. The things that pass for epistemology all assume that knowledge is not a natural function or event, but a mystery. Epistemology starts from the assumption that certain conditions lie back of knowledge. The mystery would be great enough if knowledge were constituted by non-natural conditions back of knowledge, but the mystery is increased by the fact that the conditions are defined so as to be incom- patible with knowledge. Hence the primary problem of epistemology is: How is knowledge tiberhaupt, knowledge at large, possible? Because of the incompatibility between the concrete occur- rence and function of knowledge and the conditions back of it to which it must conform, a second problem arises: How is knowledge in general, knowledge tiberhaupt, valid? Hence the complete divorce in contemporary thought between epis- temology as theory of knowledge and logic as an account of the specific ways in which particular beliefs that are better than other alternative beliefs regarding the same matters are formed; and also the complete divorce between a naturalistic, a bio- logical and social psychology, setting forth how 98 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY the function of knowledge is evolved out of other natural activities, and epistemology as an account ‘of how knowledge is possible anyhow. It is out of the question to set forth in this place in detail the contrast between transcendental epis- temology and an experimental theory of knowl- edge. It may assist the understanding of the lat- ter, however, if I point out, baldly and briefly, how, out of the distinctively empirical situation, there arise those assumptions which make knowledge a mystery, and hence a topic for a peculiar branch of philosophizing. As just pointed out, epistemology makes the possibility of knowledge a problem, because it assumes back of knowledge conditions incompatible with the obvious traits of knowledge as it em- pirically exists. These assumptions are that the organ or instrument of knowledge is not a natural object, but some ready-made state of mind or con- ' sciousness, something purely “ subjective,” a pecu- liar kind of existence which lives, moves, and has its being in a realm different from things to be known; and that the ultimate goal and content of knowledge is a fixed, ready-made thing which has no organic connections with the origin, pur- pose, and growth of the attempt to know it, some kind of Ding-an-sich or absolute, extra-empirical ** Reality.” (1) It is not difficult to see at what point in THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 99 the development of natural knowledge, or the signi- fying of one thing by another, there arises the notion of the knowing medium as something rad- ically different in the order of existence from the thing to be known. It arises subsequent to the re- Me ~, peated experience of non-fulfilment, of frustration and disappointment. The odor did not after all mean the rose; it meant something quite different ; and yet its indicative function was exercised so forcibly that we could not help—or at least did not help—believing in the existence of the rose. This is a familiar and typical kind of experience, one which very early leads to the recognition that “things are not what they seem.” There are two contrasted methods of dealing with this recog- nition: one is the method indicated above (p. 93). We go more thoroughly, patiently, and carefully into the facts of the case. We employ all sorts of methods, invented for the purpose, of examin- ing the things that are signs and the things that are signified, and we experimentally produce vari- ous situations, in order that we may tell what smells mean roses when roses are meant, what it is about the smell and the rose that led us into error; and that we may be able to discriminate those cases in which a suspended conclusion is all that circum- stances admit. We simply do the best we can to regulate our system of signs so that they become as instructive as possible, utilizing for this purpose cet 100 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY (as indicated above) all possible experiences of success and of failure, and deliberately instituting eases which will throw light on the specific em- pirical causes of success and failure. Now it so happens that when the facts of error were consciously generalized and formulated, namely in Greek thought, such a technique of spe- cific inquiry and rectification did not exist—in fact, it hardly could come into existence until after error had been seized upon as constituting a funda- mental anomaly. Hence the method just outlined of dealing with the situation was impossible. We can imagine disconsolate ghosts willing to postpone any professed solution of the difficulty till subse- quent generations have thrown more light on the question itself; we can hardly imagine passionate human beings exercising such reserve. At all events, Greek thought provided what seemed a sat- isfactory way out: there are two orders of ex- istence, one permanent and complete, the noumenal region, to which alone the characteristic of Being is properly applicable, the other transitory, phe- nomenal, sensible, a region of non-Being, or at least of mere Coming-to-be, a region in which Be- ing is hopelessly mixed with non-Being, with the unreal. The former alone is the domain of knowl- edge, of truth; the latter is the territory of opinion, confusion, and error. In short, the contrast with- _im experience of the cases in which things suc- THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 101 cessfully and unsuccessfully maintained and exe- cuted the meanings of other things was erected into a wholesale difference of status in the intrinsic characters of the things involved in the two types of cases. With the beginnings of modern thought, the region of the “ unreal,” the source of opinion and error, was located exclusively in the individual. The object was all real and all satisfactory, but the “ subject” could approach the object only through his own subjective states, his “ sensa- tions ” and “ideas.” The Greek conception of two orders of existence was retained, but instead of the two orders characterizing the “ universe ” itself, one was the universe, the other was the individual mind trying to know that universe. This scheme would obviously easily account for error and hallucination; but how could knowledge, truth, ever come about such a basis? The Greek problem of the possibility of error became the modern problem of the possibility of knowl- edge. Putting the matter in terms that are inde- pendent of history, experiences of failure, disap- pointment, non-fulfilment of the function of mean- , Ing and contention may lead the individual to the _ path of science—to more careful and extensive investigation of the things themselves, with a view to detecting specific sources of error, and guard- ong nd 102 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY ing against them, and regulating, so far as possible, the conditions under which objects are bearers of meanings beyond themselves. But im- patient of such slow and tentative methods (which insure not infallibility but increased probability of valid conclusions), by reason of disappointment a person may turn epistemologist. He may then take the discrepancy, the failure of the smell to execute its own intended meaning, as a wholesale, rather than as a specific fact: as evidence of a contrast in general between things meaning and things meant, instead of as evidence of the need of a more cautious and thorough inspection of odors and execution of operations indicated by them. One may then say: Woe is me; smells are only my smells, subjective states existing in an order of being made out of consciousness, while roses exist in another order made out of a radically different sort of stuff; or, odors are made out of ‘* finite *’ consciousness as their stuff, while the real things, the objects which fulfil them, are made out of an “ infinite” consciousness as their material. Hence some purely metaphysical tie has to be called in to bring them into connection with each other. And yet this tie does not concern knowledge; it does not make the meaning of one odor any more correct than that of another, nor enable us to discriminate relative degrees of correctness. As a principle of control, this transcendental connec- So | site. THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 103 tion is related to all alike, and hence condemns and justifies all alike.* ; It is interesting to note that the transcenden- talist almost invariably first falls into the psycho- logical fallacy ; and then having himself taken the psychologist’s attitude (the attitude which is in- terested in meanings as themselves self-inclosed ‘‘ ideas ”) accuses the empiricist whom he criticises of having confused mere psychological existence with logical validity. That is, he begins by sup- posing that the smell of our illustration (and all the cognitional objects for which this is used as a *The belief in the metaphysical transcendence of the ob- ject of knowledge seems to have its real origin in an empirical transcendence of a very specific and describable sort. The thing meaning is one thing; the thing meant is another thing, and is (as already pointed out) a thing pre- sented as not given in the same way as is the thing which means. It is something to be so given. No amount of care- ful and thorough inspection of the indicating and signifying things can remove or annihilate this gap. The probability of correct meaning may be increased in varying degrees— and this is what we mean by control. But final certi- tude can never be reached except experimentally—except by performing the operations indicated and discovering whether or no the intended meaning is fulfilled in propria persona. In this experimental sense, truth or the object of any given meaning is always beyond or outside of the cognitional thing that means it. Error as well as truth is a necessary function of knowing. ._But the non-empirical account of this transcendent (or beyond) relationship puts all the error in one place (our knowledge), and all the truth in another (absolute consciousness or else a thing-in-itself). 104 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY symbol) is a purely mental or psychical state, so that the question of logical reference or inten- tion is the problem of how the merely mental can ‘know ” the extra-mental. But from a strictly empirical point of view, the smell which knows is no more merely mental than is the rose known. We may, if we please, say that the smell when involving conscious meaning or intention is “ men- tal,” but this term “ mental ” does not denote some separate type of existence—existence as a state of consciousness. It denotes only the fact that the smell, a real and non-psychical object, now exer- cises an intellectual function. This new property involves, as James has pointed out, an additive relation—a new property possessed by a non- mental object, when that object, occurring in a new context, assumes a further office and use." To be “in the mind” means to be in a situation in which the function of intending is directly concerned.” Will not some one who be- lieves that the knowing experience is ab origine a strictly “ mental” thing, explain how, as matter | of fact, it does get a specific, extra-mental refer- "ence, capable of being tested, confirmed, or re- *Compare his essay, “Does Consciousness Exist?” in the Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, Vol. 1., p. 480. Compare the essay on the “ Problem of Consciousness,” by Professor Woodbridge, in the Garman Memorial Volume, entitled “ Studies in Philosophy and Psychology.” THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 105 futed? Or, if he believes that viewing it as merely mental expresses only the form it takes for psychological analysis, will he not explain why he so persistently attributes the inherently “ mental” characterization of it to the empiricist whom he criticises? An object becomes meaning when used empirically in a certain way ; and, under - certain circumstances, the exact character and worth of this meaning becomes an object of solici- tude. But the transcendental epistemologist with his purely psychical “ meanings ” and his purely extra-empirical “ truths ” assumes a Deus ex Ma- china whose mechanism is preserved a secret. And as if to add to the arbitrary character of his as- sumption, he has to admit that the transcendental a priori faculty by which mental states get ob- jective reference does not in the least help us to discriminate, in the concrete, between an objective | reference that is false and one that is valid. (2) The counterpart assumption to that of pure aboriginal “ mental states ” is, of course, that of ) an Absolute Reality, fixed and complete in itself, of which our “ mental states ” are bare transitory hints, their true meaning and their transcendent goal being the Truth in rerum natura. If the organ and medium of knowing is a self-inclosed order of existence different in kind from the Object to be known, then that Object must stand out there | in complete aloofness from the concrete purpose $ 106 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY and procedure of knowing it. But if we go back to the knowing as a natural occurrence, capable of description, we find that just as a smell does not mean Rose in general (or anything else at large), but means a specific_group of qualities whose ex- perience is intended and anticipated, so the func- tion of knowing is always expressed in connections between a given experience and a specific possible wanted experience. The “ rose ” that is meant ina particular situation is the rose of that situation. When this experience is consummated, it is achieved as the fulfilment of the conditions in which just that intention was entertained—not as the fulfil- ment of a faculty of knowledge or a meaning in general. Subsequent meanings and subsequent ful- filments may increase, may enrich the consummat- ing experience; the object or content of the rose as known may be other and fuller next time and so on. But we have no right to set up “a rose” at large or in general as the object of the knowing odor; the object of a knowledge is always strictly correlative to that particular thing which means it. It is not something which can be put in a wholesale way over against that which cognitively refers to it, as when the epistemologist puts the “ real ” rose (object) over against a merely phenomenal or em- pirical rose which this smell happens to mean. As the meaning gets more complex, fuller, more finely ‘discriminated, the object which realizes or fulfils THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 107 the meaning grows similarly in quality. But we cannot set up a rose, an object of fullest, complete, ¥ and exhaustive content as that which is really meant by any and every odor of a rose, whether it consciously meant to mean it or not. The test of the cognitional rectitude of the odor lies in the specific object which it sets out to secure. This is the meaning of the statement that the import of each term is found in its relationship to the other. It applies to object meant as well as to the mean- ing. Fulfilment, completion are always relative terms. Hence the criterion of the truth or falsity of the meaning, of the adequacy, of the cognitional thing lies within the relationships of the situation and not without. The thing that means another by means of an intervening operation either suc- ceeds or fails in accomplishing the operation in- dicated, while this operation either gives or fails to give the object meant. Hence the truth or falsity of the original cognitional object. IV From this excursion, I return in conclusion to a brief general characterization of those situations in which we are aware that things mean other things and are so critically aware of it that, in order to increase the probability of fulfilment and to decrease the chance of frustration, all possible 108 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY pains are taken to regulate the meanings that at- tach to things. These situations define that type of knowing which we call scientific. There are things that claim to mean other experiences; in which the trait of meaning other objects is not dis- covered ab extra, and after the event, but is part of the thing itself. This trait of the thing is as real- istic, as specific, as any other of its traits. It is, therefore, as open to inspection and determination as to its nature, as is any other trait. Moreover, since it is upon this trait that assurance (as distinct from accident) of fulfilment depends, an especial interest, an absorbing interest, attaches to its de- _ «termination. Hence the scientific type of knowl- ' edge and its growing domination over other sorts. We employ meanings in all intentional construc- ' tions of experience—in all anticipations, whether artistic, utilitarian or technological, social or moral. The success of the anticipation is found to depend upon the character of the meaning. Hence the stress upon a right determination of these meanings. Since they are the instruments upon which fulfilment depends so far as that is controlled or other than accidental, they become themselves objects of surpassing interest. For all persons at some times, and for one class of persons (scientists) at almost all times, the determination of the meanings employed in the control of ful- filments (of acting upon meanings) is central. THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 109 The experimental or pragmatic theory of knowl- edge explains the dominating importance of sci- ence; it does not depreciate it or explain it away. Possibly pragmatic writers are to blame for the tendency of their critics to assume that the practice they have in mind is utilitarian in some narrow sense, referring to some preconceived and inferior use—though I cannot recall any evidence for this admission. But what the pragmatic theory has in mind is precisely the fact that all the affairs of life which need regulation—all values of all types ~ —depend upon utilizations of meanings. Action is not to be limited to anything less than the carry- ing out of ideas, than the execution, whether stren- uous or easeful, of meanings. Hence the surpass- ing importance which comes to attach to the care- ful, impartial construction of the meanings, and to their constant survey and resurvey with reference to their value as evidenced by experiences of ful- filment and deviation. That truth denotes truths, that is, specific veri- fications, combinations of meanings and outcomes reflectively viewed, is, one may say, the central point of the experimental theory. Truth, in gen- eral or in the abstract, is a just name for an ex- perienced relation among the things of experience: that sort of relation in which intents are retro- spectively viewed from the standpoint of the ful- filment which they secure through their own natural 110 THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY \_ operation or incitement. Thus the experimental theory explains directly and simply the absolutistic tendency to translate concrete true things into the general relationship, Truth, and then to hyposta- tize this abstraction into identity with real being, Truth per se and im se, of which all transitory things and events—that is, all experienced realities —are only shadowy futile approximations. This type of relationship is central for man’s will, for man’s conscious endeavor. ‘To select, to conserve, to extend, to propagate those meanings which the course of events has generated, to note their pecu- liarities, to be in advance on the alert. for them, to search for them anxiously, to substitute them for meanings that eat up our energy in vain, defines the aim of rational effort and the goal of legitimate ambition. The absolutistic theory is the transfer of this moral or voluntary law of selective action into a quasi-physical (that is, metaphysical) law of indiscriminate being. Identify metaphysical be- ing with significant excellent being—that is, with those relationships of things which, in our moments of deepest insight and largest survey, we would continue and reproduce—and the experimentalist, rather than the absolutist, is he who has a right to proclaim the supremacy of Truth, and the su- periority of the life devoted to Truth for its own sake over that of “ mere” activity. But to read back into an order of things which exists without THE EXPERIMENTAL THEORY 111, the participation of our reflection and aim, the | quality which defines the purpose of our thought | and endeavor is at one and the same stroke to mythologize reality and to deprive the life of thoughtful endeavor of its ground for being. | THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION FOR TRUTH * I MONG the influences that have worked in contemporary philosophy towards distinte- gration of intellectualism of the epistemological type, and towards the substitution of a philosophy of experience, the work of Mr. Bradley must be seriously counted. One has, for example, only to compare his metaphysics with the two fundamental contentions of T. H. Green, namely, that reality is a single, eternal, and all-inclusive system of relations, and that this system of relations is one in kind with that process of relating which consti- tutes our thinking, to be instantly aware of a changed atmosphere. Much of Bradley’s writings is a sustained and deliberate polemic against in- tellectualism of the Neo-Kantian type. When, however, we find conjoined to this criticism an * Reprinted, with many changes, from an article in Mind, Vol. XVI., N.S., July 1907. Although the changes have been made to render the article less technical, it still re- mains, I fear, too technical to be intelligible to those not familiar with recent discussions of logical theory. 112 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 113 equally sustained contention that the philosophic conception of reality must be based on an exclu- sively intellectual criterion, a criterion belonging * to and confined to theory, we have a situation that > is thought-provoking. The situation grows in in- terest when it is remembered that there is a general and growing tendency among those who appeal in philosophy to a strictly intellectualistic method of defining “ reality,” to insist that the reality reached by this method has a super-intellectual content: that intellectual, affectional, and volitional fea- tures are all joined and fused in “ ultimate ” real- ity. The curious character of the situation is that Reality is an “ absolute experience ” of which the intellectual is simply one partial and transmuted moment. Yet this reality is attained unto, in philo- sophic method, by exclusive emphasis upon the in- tellectual aspect of present experience and by sys- tematic exclusion of exactly the emotional, volitional features which with respect to content are insisted upon! Under such circumstances the cynically- minded are moved to wonder whether this tremen- dous insistence upon one factor in present ex- perience at the expense of others, is not because this is the only way to maintain the notion of *‘ Absolute Experience,” and to prevent it from col- lapsing into ordinary every-day experience. This paradox is not peculiar to Mr. Bradley. Looking at the Neo-Kantian movement in the broad in its 114 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION modern form, one might almost say that its prom- inent feature is its insistence upon reaching a ‘“‘ Reality ” that includes extra-intellectual fac- tors and phases, traits that are ideal in a moral and emotional sense, by an exclusive recognition of the function of knowledge in its isolation. — Such being the case, an examination of Mr. Bradley’s method and criterion may have far- reaching implications. First, let us set before ourselves the general points of Mr. Bradley’s in- | dictment of intellectualism.* Knowledge or judg- ment works by means of thought; it is predication of idea (meaning) of existence as its subject. Its final aim is to effect a complete union or harmony of existence and meaning. But it is fore-doomed to failure, for in realizing its end it must employ means which contradict its own purpose. This inherent incapacity lurks in judgment with respect to subject, predicate, and copula. The predicate or meaning necessary to complete the reality pre- sented in the subject can be referred to the latter and united with it only by being itself alienated from existence. It heals the wounds or deficiencies of its own subject (and in the end all deficiencies are to the modern idealist discrepancies) only on condition of inflicting another wound,—only by * sundering meaning from a prior union with exist- - *I follow chiefly Chapter XV. of “Appearance and Reality ”—the chapter on “ Thought and Reality.” 4 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 115 ence in some other phase. This latter existence, therefore, is always left out in the cold. It is as if we wanted to get all the cloth in the world into one garment and our only way of accomplishing this were to tear off a portion from one piece of goods in order to patch it on to another. The subject of the judgment, moreover, as well as the predicate, stands in the way of judgment fulfilling its own task. It has “ sensuous infini- tude” and it has “immediacy,” but these two traits contradict each other. The details of the subject always go beyond itself, being indefinitely related to something beyond. “In its given con- tent it has relations which do not terminate within that content” (ibid., p. 176), while in its imme- diacy it presents an undivided union of existence and meaning. No subject can be mere existence any more than it can be mere meaning. It is al- ways existent or embodied meaning. As such it claims individuality or the character of a single subsistent whole. But this indispensable claim is inconsistent with its ragged-edged character, its indefinite external reference, which is indispensable to it as subject that it may require and receive further meaning from predication. With respect to the copula the following quo- tation from the “ Principles ” of Logic (p. 10) may serve: “ Judgment proper is the act which refers the ideal content (recognized as such) to the 116 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION reality beyond the act.” In other words, judg- ment as act (and it is the act which is expressed in the copula) must always fall outside of ’ the content of knowledge as such; yet since this act certainly falls within reality, it would have to be recognized and stated by any knowledge pre- tending to competency with respect to reality as a whole. These considerations, stated in this way, are highly technical and presuppose a knowledge not merely of Mr. Bradley’s own logic, but also of the logical analysis of knowledge initiated by Kant _and carried on by Herbart, Lotze, and others. Their main import may, however, be stated in comparatively non-technical form. Human ex- perience is full of discrepancies. Were experience purely a matter of brute existence (such as we some- times imagine the animals’ experience to be) it would be totally lacking in meaning and there would be no problems, no thinking, no occasion for thinking, and hence no philosophy. On the other hand, if experience were a complete, tight-jointed / union of existence and meaning, there would be no dissatisfaction, no problems, no cause for efforts to patch up defects and contradictions. Existences, things, would embody all the meanings that they suggest; while abstract meanings, values that are merely ideal, that are projected or thought of but not fulfilled, would be totally unheard of. But our experience stands in marked contrast to both THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 117 these types of experience. It is neither an affair of meaningless existence nor of existence self-lumi- nous with fulfilled meaning. All things that we experience have some meaning, but that meaning is always so partially embodied in things that we cannot rest in them. They point beyond them- selves; they indicate meanings which they do not fulfil; they suggest values which they fail to em- body, and when we go to other things for the fruition of what is denied, we either find the same situation of division over again, or we find even more positive disappointment and frustration—we find contrary meanings set up. Now all thinking grows out of this discrepancy between existence _ and the meaning which it partially embodies and partially refuses, which it suggests but declines to express.. Yet thinking, the mode of bringing ex- istence and meaning into harmony with each other, . always works by selection, by abstraction; it sets up and projects meanings which are ideal only, footless, in the air, matters of thought only, not of sentiency or immediate existence. It emphasizes the ideal of a completed union of existence and meaning, but is helpless to effect it. And this helplessness (according to Mr. Bradley) is not due to external pressure but to the very structure of thought itself. From every point of view knowledge operates under conditions, (and these not externally imposed \ 118 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION » but inherent in its own nature as judgment,) that render it incapable of realizing its aim of complete union of existence and meaning. Granted the argument, and it is difficult to imagine a more serious indictment against the pretensions of phi- losophy to reach “ Reality ” via the exclusive path of knowledge. The presence of contradiction is Mr. Bradley’s criterion for “ appearance,” just as its absence is his criterion for “ reality.” It thus goes with- out saying that knowledge and truth which we can attain are matters of appearance. Contradiction between existence and meaning is its last word. This is not merely a logical deduction from Mr. Bradley’s position, but is expressly stated by him. ‘Thus the truth belongs to existence, but it does not as such exist. . . . Truth shows a dis- section but never an actual life” (“ Appearance and Reality,” p. 167). Again, “every truth is | appearance since in it we have divorce of quality from being” (ibid., p. 187). ‘ Even absolute truth seems in the end to turn out erroneous. . Internal discrepancy belongs irremovably to truth’s proper character. . . . Truth is one aspect of experience and is therefore made im- perfect and limited by what it fails to include ” (ibid., pp. 544-545). Nothing could be more explicit as to the inherently contradictory char- acter of truth, both as an ideal and as an accom- Saeike ne f THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 119 plished fact; nothing more positive as to the un- reality or appearance-character of truth. We cannot, on Mr. Bradley’s method, stop here. Not only is knowledge—working as it does through thought which is always partial, selective, abstrac- tive—doomed to failure in accomplishing its task, but the existence of the contradiction between the suggestion of meanings by existence and this reali- zation in existence is itself due to thought. Speaking of thought he says: “ The relational form is a compromise on which thought stands and which it develops.” And all the particular anti- nomies which he discusses are interpreted as having their basis in the category of relation (ibid., p- 180). In his section on Appearance he goes through various aspects and distinctions of the world, such as primary and secondary qualities, substance and its properties, relation and qualita- tive elements, space and time, motion and change, causation, etc., pointing out irreconcilable discrep- ancies in them. He does not, in a generalized way, expressly refer them to any common source or root. But it seems a fair inference that the relational character of thought is at the bottom of the whole trouble: so that we have in the cases mentioned precisely the same situation in concreto which is set forth in abstracto in the discussion of thought. The contradictions brought up are in every case resolved into the fundamental discrep- =m 120 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION ancy supposed to exist between relations and ele- ments related. In each case there is the ideal of a final unity in which relations and elements as such disappear, while in every case the nature of — relation is such as to prevent the desired con- summation. In at least one place, it is expressly declared that it is the knowledge function which is responsible for the degradation of reality to ap- pearance. ‘ We do not suggest that the thing always itself is an appearance. We mean its character is such that it becomes one as soon as we judge it. And this character we have seen throughout our work, is ideality. Appearance consists in the looseness of content from existence. . And we have found that everywhere throughout the world such ideality prevails ” (ibid., p. 486, italics not in the original). It is not then strictly true that the divorce of mean- ing and existence instigates thought; rather thought is the unruly member that creates the divorce and then engages in the task (in which it is self-condemned to failure) of trying to establish the unity which it has gratuitously destroyed. Thinking, self-consciousness, is disease of the naive unity of thoughtless experience. On the one hand there is a systematic discredit- ing of the ultimate claims of the knowledge func- tion, and this not from external physiological or psychological reasons such as are sometimes alleged THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 121 against its capacity, but on the basis of its own interior logic. But on the other hand, a strictly logical criterion is deliberately adopted and em- ployed as the fundamental and final criterion for the philosophic conception of reality. Long fa- miliarity has not dulled my astonishment at finding exactly the same set of considerations which in_ the earlier portion of the ‘book are employed to condemn things as experienced by us to the region of ‘Appearance, employed in the latter portion of the book to afford a triumphant demonstration of the existence and character of Absolute Reality. The argument I take up first on its formal side, and then with reference to material considerations.” The positive conception of Reality is reached . by the conception that “ ultimate reality must be % such that it does not contradict itself; here is an absolute criterion. And it is proved absolute by the fact that either in endeavoring to deny it or even in attempting to doubt it, we tacitly assume its validity ” (ibid., pp. 136-187). That is to say, when one sets out to think one must avoid self- contradiction; this avoidance, or, put positively, the attainment of consistency, harmony, is the basic « law of all thinking. Since in thinking we set out to attain reality, it follows that reality itself - must be self-consistent, and that its self-consistency * The crux of the argument is contained in Chapters XIII. and XIV., on the “General Nature of Reality.” a ee 122 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION determines the law of thought. Or, as Mr. Brad- ley again puts the matter, “In order to think at ‘all you must subject yourself to the standard, a standard which implies an absolute knowledge of reality; and while you doubt this, you accept it, and obey, while you rebel” (ibid., p. 158). The absolute knowledge referred to is, of course, the knowledge of the thoroughly self-consistent, non-contradictory character of reality. Every reader of Mr. Bradley’s book knows how he goes on from this point to supply positive content to reality ; to give an outline sketch of the characters it must possess and the way in which it must possess them in order to maintain its thoroughly self- consistent character. It is, however, only the strictly formal aspect of the matter that I am here concerned with. On this side we reach, I think, the heart of the matter by asking, in reference to the first quota- tion: Absolute for what? Surely absolute for the process under consideration, that is absolute for thought. But the significance of this absolute for thought is, one may say, “ absolutely ” (since we are here confessedly in the realm just of thought) determined by the nature of thought itself. Now this nature has been already referred by considera- ‘, tions “ belonging irremovably to truth’s proper character,” to the world of appearance and of in- ternal said a tate Yes, one may say (speaking THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 123 formally), the criterion of thought is absolute— that is to say absolute or final for thought; but how can one imagine that. this in any way alters the essential nature and value of thought? If knowledge works by thought, and thought institutes appearance over against reality, any further fact about thought—such as a statement of its criterion —falls wholly within the limits of this situation. It is comical to suppose that a special trait of thought c: can be employed to alter the fundamental and essential nature of thought. The criterion of thought must be infected by the nature of thought, instead of being a redeeming angel which at a critical juncture transforms the fragile creature, thought, into an ambassador with power plenipo- . tentiary to the court of the Absolute. There really seems to be ground for supposing that the whole argument turns on an ambiguity in the use of the word “absolute.” Keeping strictly within the limits of the argument, it means nothing more than that thinking has a certain principle, a law of its own; that it has an appro- priate mode of procedure which must not be vio- lated. It means, in short, whatever is finally con- trolling for the thought-function. But Mr. Brad- ley immediately takes the word to mean absolute in the sense of describing a reality which by its very _nature is totally contradistinguished from appear- +ance—that is to say, from the realm of thought. —— / 124 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION Upon the ambiguity of a word, the systematic in- dictment of intellectualism becomes the corner- stone of a systematically intellectualistic method of conceiving reality ! Mr. Bradley has himself recognized the seeming contradiction between his indictment of thought and his use of the criterion of thought as the ex- clusive path to a philosophic notion of the real. In dealing with it, he (to my mind) comes within an ace of stating a truer doctrine, and also ex- hibits even more clearly the weakness of his own _ position. He goes so far as to put the follow- ing words into the mouth of an objector, and to accept their general import: “ All axioms, as a matter of fact, are practical . . . for none of them in the end can amount to more than the im- pulse to behave in a certain way. And they can- not express more than this impulse, together with the impossibility of satisfaction unless it is com- plied with” (p. 151). After accepting this (p. 152) he goes on to say: “ Take for example the law of avoiding contradiction. When two elements will not remain quietly together, but collide and struggle, we cannot rest satisfied with that state. ‘Our impulse is to alter it and, on the theoretical side, to bring the content to such shape that the variety remains peaceably in one. And this in- ability to rest otherwise and this tendency to alter in a certain way and direction is, when reflected THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 125 upon and made explicit, our axiom and our in- tellectual standard ” (p. 152; italics mine). The retort is obvious: if the intellectual cri- terion, the principle of non-contradiction on which his whole Absolute Reality rests, is itself a prac- ? tical principle, then surely the ultimate criterion for regulating intellectual undertakings is prac- tical. To this obvious answer Mr. Bradley makes reply as follows: “ You may call the intellect, if you like, a mere tendency to a movement, but you must remember that it is a movement of a very special kimd. . . . Thinking is the attempt to satisfy a special impulse, and the attempt im- plies an assumption about reality. . . . But why, it may be objected, is this assumption better than what holds for practice? Why is the theo- retical to be superior to the practical end? Ihave never said that this is so, only here, that is, in meta- physics, I must be allowed to reply, we are acting theoretically. . . . The theoretical standard | within theory must surely be absolute”? (p. 153. The italics again are mine; compare with the quo- tation this, from p. 485: “ Our attitude, however, in metaphysics must be theoretical.” So, also, p.., 154, “ Since metaphysics is mere theory and since theory from its nature must be made by the intel- lect, it is here the intellect alone which is to be satisfied ”’). = Grant that intellect is a special movement or | 126 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION mode of practice; grant that we are not merely acting (are we ever merely acting?) but are “ spe- cially occupied and therefore subject to special con- ditions,” and the problem remains what special kind of activity is thinking? what is its experienced” differentia from other kinds? what is its commerce | with them? When the problem is what special kind of an activity is thinking and of what nature is the consistency which is its criterion, somehow we do not get forward by being told that thinking is a special mode of practice and that its criterion is consistency. The unquestioned presupposition of Mr. Bradley is that thinking is such a wholly sep- » arate activity (the “ intellect alone ” which has to - be satisfied), that to give it autonomy is to say that it, and its criterion, have nothing to do with -. other activities; that it is “ independent” as to “ew * criterion, in a way which excludes interdependence in function and outcome. Unless the term “ spe- v cial” be interpreted to mean isolated, to say that thinking is a special mode of activity no more nulli- fies the proposition that it arises in a practical con- test and operates for practical ends, than to say that blacksmithing is a special activity, negates its being one connected mode of industrial activity. _ His underlying presupposition of the separate character of thought comes out in the passage last quoted. ‘Our impulse,” he says, “ is to alter the conflicting situation and, on the theoretical side, THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 127 to bring its contents into peaceable unity.” If « 66 one substitutes for the word “on” the word |“ through,” one gets a conception of theory and of thinking that does justice to the autonomy of the operation and yet so connects it with other activities as to give it a serious business, real pur- pose, and concrete responsibility and hence testi- bility. From this point of view the theoretical activity is simply the form that certain practical activities take after colliding, as the most effective and fruitful way of securing their own harmoniza- * tion. The collision is not theoretical; the issue in ¢ “ peaceable unity ” is not theoretical. But theory names the type of activity by which the trans- formation from war to peace is most amply and securely effected.* Admit, however, the force of Mr. Bradley’s contention on its own terms and see how futile is *The same point comes out in Mr. Bradley’s treatment of the way in which the practical demand for the good or satisfaction is to be taken account of in a philosophical con- ception of the nature of reality. He admits that it comes in; but holds that it enters not directly, but because if left , outside it indirectly introduces a feature of “ discontent ” ane on the intellectual side (see p. 155). This, as an argument for the supremacy of the isolated theoretical standard, loses all its force if we cease to conceive of intellect as from the start an independent function, and realize that intel- lectual discontent is the practical conflict becoming deliber- ately aware of itself as the most effective means of its own rectification. —_— 128 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION _ the result. It is quite true, as Mr. Bradley says (p. 153), that if a man sits down to play the meta- physical game, he must abide by the rules of think- ing; but if thinking be already, with respect to reality, an idle and futile game, simply abiding by the rules does not give additional value to its stakes. Grant the premises as to the character of thought, and the assertion of the final character of the theoretical standard within metaphysics— since metaphysics is a form of theory—is a warn- ing against metaphysics. If the intellect involves self-contradiction, it is either impossible that it should be satisfied, or else self-contradiction its its satisfaction. , y f f f OF 4 ur" 7 — # ae A Ce re tree re : wa & / fet 9 * HU MAALAE j bes a * A hte : ; : “ off ae F a ah rAsrad II wy ( “er J Let us, however, turn from Mr. Bradley’s formal proof that the criterion of philosophic truth must be exclusively a canon of formal thought. Let _ us ignore the contradiction involved in first making ¥ the work of thought to be the producing of appearance and then making the law of this thought the law of an Absolute Reality. What about the intellectualist criterion? The intellectu- alism of Mr. Bradley’s philosophy is represented in the statement that it is “the theoretical stand- ard which guarantees that reality is a self-consist- ent system” (p. 148). But how can the fact that rod THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 129 the criterion of thinking is consistency be employed to detérmine the nature of the consistency of its object? Consistency in one sense, consistency of reasoning with itself, we know; but what is the nature of the consistency of reality which this con- sistency necessitates? Thinking without doubt | must be logical; but does it follow from this that | the reality about which one thinks, and about which _ one must think consistently if one is to think to any purpose, must itself be already logical? The pivot — of the argument is, of course, the old ontological argument, stripped of all theological irrelevancies and reduced to its fighting weight as a metaphys- ical proposition. Those who question this basic principle of intellectualism will, of course, question it here. They will urge that, instead of the con- sistency of “ reality ” Testing on the basis of consistency i in the reasoning process the latter de- / rives its meaning from the material consistency at which it aims. They will say that the definition of the nature of the consistency which is the end of thinking and which prescribes its technique is to be reached from inquiry into such questions as these: What sort of an activity in the concrete is © thinking? what are the specific conditions which it has to fulfil? what is its use; its relevancy; its purport in present concrete experiences? The more it is insisted that the theoretical standard— consistency—is final within theory, the more ger- 130 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION mane and the more urgent is the question: What then in the concrete is theory? and of what nature is,the material consistency which is the test of its formal consistency? * Take the instance of a man who wishes to deny the criterion of self-consistency in thinking. Is he refuted by pointing to the “ fact ” that eternal reality is eternally self-consistent? Would not his obvious answer to such a mode of refutation be: “What of it? What is the relevancy of that proposition to my procedure in thinking here and now? Doubtless absolute reality may be a great number of things, possibly very sublime and pre- cious things; but what I am concerned with is a particular job of thinking, and until you show me the intermediate terms which link that job to the © asserted self-consistent character of absolute real- ity, I fail to see what difference this doubtless * This suggests that many of the stock arguments against pragmatism fail to take its contention seriously enough. They proceed from the assumption that it is an account of truth which leaves untouched current notions of the nature of intelligence. But the essential point of prag- matism is that it bases its changed account of truth on 4 changed conception of the nature of intelligence, both as to its objective and its method. Now this different account of intelligence may be wrong, but controversy which leaves standing the conventionally current theories about thought and merely discusses “truth” will not go far. Since truth -- is the adequate fulfilment of the function of intelligence, the question turns on the nature of the latter. THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 131 wholly amiable trait of reality has to make in what, I am here and now concerned with. You might as | well quote any other irrelevant fact, such as the | height of the Empress of China.” We take an-- other tack in dealing with the man in question. We call his attention to his specific aim in the situ- | ation with reference to which he is thinking, and | point out the conditions that have to be observed | if that aim is to fulfil itself. We show that if he does not observe the conditions imposed by his aim his thinking will go on so wildly as to defeat it- self. It is to consistency of means with the end —of the concrete activity that we appeal. “ Try thinking,’ > we tell such a man, “ experiment with it, taking pains sometimes to have your reasonings consistent with one another, and at other times deliberately introducing inconsistencies; then see what you get in the two cases and how the result reached is related to your purpose in thinking.” We point out that since that purpose is to reach a settled conclusion, that purpose will be defeated un- less the steps of reasoning are kept consistent with | one another. We do not appeal from the mere con- sistency of the reasoning process—the intellectual aspect of the matter—to an absolute self-con- sistent reality; but we appeal from the material character of the end to be reached to the type of the formal procedure necessary to accomplish it. With all our heart, then, the standard of think- 182 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION ing is absolute (that is final) within thinking. But what is thinking? The standard of black- smithing must be absolute within blacksmithing, but what is blacksmithing? No prejudice pre- vents acknowledging that blacksmithing is one practical activity existing as a distinct and rele- vant member of a like system of activities: that it is because men use horses to transport persons and goods that horses need to be shod. The ultimate criterion of blacksmithing is producing a good shoe, but the nature of a good shoe is fixed, not by blacksmithing, but by the activities in which horses are used. The end is ultimate (abso- lute) for the operation, but this very finality is evidence that the operation is not absolute and self-inclosed, but is related and responsible. Why must the fact that the end of thinking is ultimate for thought stand on any different footing? Let us then, by way of experiment, follow this suggestion. Let us assume that among real objects in their values and significances, real oppositions and incompatibilities exist; that these conflicts are both troublesome in themselves, and the source of all manner of further difficulties—so much so that they may be suspected of being the source of all man’s woe, of all encroachment upon and destruc- tion of value, of good. Suppose that thinking . is, not accidentally but essentially, a way, and the _ only way that proves adequate, of dealing with THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 138 these predicaments—that being “in a hole,” in difficulty, is the fundamental “‘ predicament ” of in- telligence. Suppose when effort is made in a brute way to remove these oppositions and to secure an arrangement of things which means satisfaction, fulfilment, happiness, that the method of brute at- tack, of trying directly to force warrings into peace fails; suppose then' an effort to effect the transformation by an indirect method—by inquiry into the disordered state of affairs and by framing views, conceptions, of what the situation would be like were it reduced to harmonious order. Finally, suppose that upon this basis a plan of action is worked out, and that this plan, when carried into overt effect, succeeds infinitely better than the brute method of attack in bringing about the de- sired consummation. Suppose again this indirec- | tion of activity is precisely what we mean by think-_ ing. Would it not hold that harmony is the end and the test of thinking? that observations are per- tinent and ideas correct just in so far as, overtly acted upon, they succeed in removing the unde- sirable, the inconsistent. But, it is said, the very process of thinking makes a certain assumption regarding the nature of real- ity, viz., that reality is self-consistent. This state- ment puts the end for the beginning. The assump- tion is not that “ reality ” is self-consistent, but that by thinking it may, for some special purpose, 134 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION or as respects some concrete. problem, attain greater consistency. Why should the assump- tion regarding “reality” be other than that specific realities with which thought is concerned are capable of recetvmg harmonization? To say that thought must assume, in order to go on, that _ reality already possesses harmony is to say that , thought must begin by contradicting its own direct \. data, and by assuming that its concrete aim is vain and illusory. Why put upon thought the onus of introducing discrepancies into reality in order just to give itself exercise in the gymnastic of removing them? The assumption..that.concrete..thinking makes about “ reality ” is that things just.as they exist may acquire through activity, guided by thinking, a certain character which it is excellent for them to possess; and may acquire it more _lib- erally and effectively than by other methods. One might as well say that the blacksmith could not think to any effect concerning iron, without a Platonic archetypal horseshoe, laid up in the heavens. His thinking also makes an assumption about present, given reality, viz., that this piece of iron, through the exercise of intelligently di- rected activity, may be shaped into a satisfactory horseshoe. The assumption 1s practical: the as- sumption that a specific thing may take on in a specific way a specific needed value. The test, moreover, of this assumption is practical ; it con- THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 135 sists in acting upon it to see if it will do what it pretends it can do, namely, guide activities to the required result. The assumption about reality is not something in addition to the idea, which an idea already in existence makes; some assumption about the possibility of a change in the state of things as experienced is the idea—and its test or criterion is whether this possible change can be effected when the idea is acted upon in good faith. In any case, how much simpler the case becomes when we stick by the empirical facts. According to them there is no wholesale discrepancy of ex- istence and meaning; there is simply a “ loosen- ing” of the two when objects do not fulfil our plans and meet our desires; or when we project inventions and cannot find immediately the means for their realization. The “ collisions ” are neither physical, metaphysical, nor logical; they are moral and practical. They exist between an aim and the means of its execution. Consequently the object of thinking is not to effect-some wholesale and “ Absolute” reconciliation of meaning and existence, but to make a specific adjustment of things to’ our purposes and of our purposes to things at just the crucial point of the crisis. Mak- ing the utmost concessions to Mr. Bradley’s ac- count of the discrepancy of meaning and existence in our experience, to his statement of the relation 186 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION of this to the function of judgment (as involving namely an explicit statement at once of the actual sundering and the ideal union) and to his account of consistency as the goal and standard, there is still not a detail of the account that is not met _ amply and with infinitely more empirical warrant by the conception that the “ collision’. in-which , thinking starts and the “ consistency.” in which it terminates Vy ee, and pee WA i (dar SA, cutee sree ia At vl Pa » | pe St y: ot fra % vis cs q | : II aos DEAE This brings us explicitly to the question of truth, “truth” being confessedly the end and ~ standard of thinking. I confess to being much at a loss to realize just what the intellectualists conceive to be the relation of truth to ideas on one _ side and to “ xeality ” on_the other. My My difficulty occurs, I think, because they describe so little in analytical detail; in writing of truth they seem rather to be under a strong emotional influence— as if they were victims of an uncritical pragma- ~ tism—which leaves much of their thought to be guessed at. The implication of their discussions assigns three distinct values t to the term “ truth.” On the one hand, truth is something which char- acterizes ideas, theories, hypotheses, beliefs, judg- ments, propositions, assertions, etc.,—anything whatsoever involving intellectual statement. From THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 187 this standpoint a criterion of truth means the test of the worth of the intellectual intent, import, or claim of any intellectual statement as intellectual. This is an intelligible sense of the term truth. In the second place, it seems to be assumed that a certain kind of reality is already, apart from ideas or meanings, Truth, and that this Truth is the criterion of that lower and more unworthy kind of truth that may be possessed or aimed at by ideas. But we do not stop here. The conception hat all truth must have a criterion haunts the intellectualist, so that the reality, which, as con- trasted with ideas, is taken to be The Truth (and the criterion of their truth) is treated as if it itself had to have support and warrant from some other _ Reality, lying back of it, which is its criterion. This, then, gives the third type of truth, The Absolute Truth. (Just why this process should not go on indefinitely is not clear, but the neces- sity of infinite regress may be emotionally pre- vented by always referring to this last type of truth as Absolute). Now this scheme may be “true,” but it is not self-explanatory or even easily apprehensible. In just what sense, truth is (1) that to which ideas as ideas lay claim and yet is (2) Reality which as reality is the criterion of truth of ideas, and yet again is (3) a Reality which completely annuls and transcends all refer- ence to ideas, is not in the least clear to me: nor, 138 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION till better informed, shall I believe it to be clear to any one. In his more strictly logical discussions, Mr. Bradley sets out from the notion that truth refers to intellectual statements and positions as such. But the Truth soon becomes a sort of transcen- dent essence on its own account. The identifica- tion of reality and truth on page 146 may be a mere casual phrase, but the distinction drawn be- tween validity and absolute truth (p. 362), and the discussion of Degrees of Truth and Reality, in- volve assumptions of an identity of truth and reality. Truth in this sense turns out to be the criterion for the truth, the truth, that is, of ideas. But, again (p. 545), a distinction is made between “ Finite Truth,” that is, a view of reality which would completely satisfy intelligence as such, and “ Absolute Truth,” which is obtained only by _ passing beyond intelligence—only when intelligence as such is absorbed in some Absolute in which it loses its distinctive character. It would advance the state of discussion, I am sure, if there were more explicit statements regard- ing the relations of “ true idea,” “ truth,” “ the criterion of truth” and “reality,” to one an- other. A more explicit exposition also of the view that is held concerning the relation of verification and truth could hardly fail to be of value. _Not infrequently the intellectualist_admits_that_the win THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 139 process of verification is experimental, consisting in séttiig on foot various activities that express , the intent of the idea and confirm or refute it ac- cording to the changes effected. This seems to mean that truth is simply the tested or verified belief as such. But then a curious reservation is introduced; the experimental process finds, it is | said, that an idea is true, while the error of the | pragmatist is to take the process by which truth | is found_as.one by which.it.is.made. The claim | of “making truth” is treated as blasphemy against the very notion of truth: such are the con- sequences of venturing to translate the Latin ** verification ” into the English “ making true.” If we face the bogie thus called up, it will be found that the horror is largely sentimental. Sup- ere seemeg sinh pose we stick to the notion that truth is a char-\ acter which belongs to a meaning so far as tested \ through action that carries it to successful comple- tion. In this case, to make an idea true is to modify and transform it until it reaches this suc- cessful outcome: until it initiates a mode of response which in its issue realizes its claim to be the method of harmonizing the discrepancies of a given situa- tion. The meaning is remade by constantly acting upon it, and by introducing into its content such icharacters as are indicated by any resulting fail- ures to secure harmony. From this point of view, verification and truth are two names for the same eeu wmrenay: 140 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION thing. We call it “ verification” when-we-regard it as |_ process ; ‘when the development of the idea is .strung out and exposed to view in all that makes it true. We call it “truth” when we take it as product, as process telescoped and condensed. Suppose the idea to be an invention, say of the telephone. In this case, is not the verification of the idea and the construction of the device which carries out its intent one and the same? In this case, does the truth of the idea mean anything - else than that the issue proves the idea can be carried into effect? There are certain intellectu- alists who are not of the absolutist type; who do not believe that all of men’s aims, designs, projects, that have to do with action, whether industrial, social, or moral in scope, have been from all eternity registered as already accomplished in real- ity. How do such persons dispose of this prob- lem of the truth of practical ideas? Is not the truth of such ideas an affair of mak- mg them true by constructing, through appropri- ‘ate behavior, a condition that satisfies the re- quirements of the case? If, in this case, truth means the effective capacity of the idea “ to make good,” what is there in the logic of the case to forbid the application of analogous considerations to any idea? I hear a noise in the street. It suggests as its meaning a street-car. To test this idea I go to THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 141 _ the window and through listening and looking in- tently—the listening and the looking being modes of behavior—organize into a single situation ele- ments of existence and meaning which were previ- ously disconnected. In this way an idea is made true; that which was a proposal or hypothesis is no longer merely a propounding or a guess. If I had not reacted in a way appropriate to the idea it would have remained a mere idea; at most a candidate for truth that, unless acted upon upon the spot, would always have remained a theory. Now in such a case—where the end to be accom- | plished is the discovery of a certain order of facts —would the intellectualist claim that apart from the forming and entertaining of some interpreta- tion, the category of truth has either existence or meaning? Will he claim that without.an.original practical uneasiness introducing a practical-aim of inquiry there must have.been,.whether-or~no, an idea? Must the world for some-purely-intellectual reason be intellectually reduplicated? Could not that occurrence which I now identify as a noisy street-car have retained, so far as pure intelligence is concerned, its unidentified status of being mere physical alteration in a vast unidentified complex of matter-in-motion? Was there any intellectual mecessity that compelled the event to arouse just this judgment, that it meant a street-car? Was — there any physical or metaphysical necessity? a eal nil 142 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION Was there any necessity save a need of characteriz- ing it for some purpose of our own? And why should we be mealy-mouthed about calling this need practical? If the necessity which led to the formation and development of-an intellectual judg- ment was purely objective (whether physical or metaphysical) why should notthe-thing have also to be characterized in countless millions. of other ways ; for example, as to its distance from some crater in the moon, or its effect upon the circulation of my blood, or upon my irascible neighbor’s temper, or bearing upon the Monroe Doctrine? In short, do not intellectual positions and statements mean new and significant events in the treatment of things? It is perhaps dangerous to attempt to follow the inner workings of the processes by which truth is first identified with some superior type of Real- ity, and then this Truth is taken as the criterion of the truth of ideas; while all the time it is held that truth is something already possessed by ideas as purely intellectual. But there seems to be some ground for believing that this identification i is due to a twofold confusion, one having to do with ideas, and the other with things. As to the first. point: After an idea is made true, we “naturally say, in retrospect, “it was true all the time.” Now this truism is quite innocuous as a truism, being just a restatement of the fact that the idea has, as matter of fact, worked successfully. But it may be re- ~ “J THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 143 garded not as a truism but as furnishing some ad- ditional knowledge; as if it were, indeed, the dawn- ing of a revelation regarding truth. Then it is said that the idea worked or was verified because it was already inherently, just as idea, the truth; the Pragmatist, so it is said, making the error une erie etnin: of supposing that it is true. because it works. If one remembers that what the experimentalist. means is that the effective working of an idea.and_its... truth are one and the same thing—this working being neither. the.cause nor. the evidence.of truth” but its nature—it is hard to see the point of this statement. A man under peculiarly precarious circumstances has been rescued from drowning. A by-stander remarks that now he is a saved man. “Yes,” replies some one, “but he was a saved man all the time, and the process of rescuing, while it gives evidence of that fact, does not constitute it.” Now even such a statement as pure tautology, as characterizing the entire process in terms of its Issue, is objectionable only in the fact that, like all tautology, it seems to say something but does not. But if it be regarded as revealing the earlier condition of affairs, apart from the active process by which it was carried to a happy conclusion, such a statement would be monstrously false ; and would declare its falsity in the fact that, if acted upon, the man would have been left to drown. In like fashion, to say, after the event, that a given idea 144 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION was true all the time, is to lose sight of what makes an idea an idea, its hypothetical character; and thereby deliberately to transform it into brute dogma—something to which no canon of verifica- tion can ever be applied. The intellectualist al- most always treats the pragmatic account as if it were, from the standpoint of the pragmatist as well as from his own, a denial of the existence of truth, while it is nothing but a statement of its nature. When the intellectualist realizes this, he will, I hope, ask himself: What, then, on the pragmatic basis is meant by the proposition that an idea is true all the time? If the statement that an idea was true all the time has no meaning except that the idea was one which as matter of fact succeeded through action in achieving its intent, mere reiteration that the idea was true all the time or it could not have succeeded, does not take us far.’ * Such a statement as, for example, Mr. Bradley’s (Mind, Vol. XIII., No. 51, N.S. p. 3, article on “Truth and Practice”) “The idea works . . . but is able to work because I have chosen the right idea” surely loses any \.argumentative force it may seem to have, when it is recalled that, upon the theory argued against, ability. .to work and ‘ rightness are one and the same thing. ‘If the wording is changed to read “ The idea is able to work because I have chosen an idea which is able to work” the question- begging character of the implied criticism is evident. The change of phraseology also may suggest “the crucial and pregnant question: How does any one know that an idea is able to work excepting by setting it at work? THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 145 Op tie sie ote reality is identified with truth; then on the principle that two things that are equal to the same thing are equal to each other, truth as idea and truth as_reality are taken to-be.one_and the same thing. Wherever there is an improved or tested idea, an idea which has made good, there is a concrete existence in the way of a completed or harmonized situation. The same activity which proves the idea constructs an inherently satisfied situation out of an inherently dissentient one,—for it is precisely the capacity of the idea as an aim and method of action to determine such transformation that is the cri- terion of its truth. Now unless all the elements in the situation are held steadily in view, the specific way in which the harmonized reality affords the criterion. of truth (namely, through its function - of being the last term ofa process of-active de- termination ) is lost from sight; and the achieved existence in its merely existent. character, apart 7 from its ym its practical or fulfilment character, i is treated | as The Truth. But when the reality is thus sepa- rated fromthe process by which it is achieved, when it is taken just as given, it is neither truth nor a criterion of truth. It is a state of facts like any other. The achieved telephone i is a criterion | of the validity. of_a_ certain prior idea in so far as it is the fulfilment of activities that embody the nature.of-that-ideas-but just_as telephone, as } 146 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION | /a machine actually in existence, it is no more truth "nor criterion of truth than is.a.crack in the wall or a cobble-stone.on.the street. The intervening term that mediates and com- pletes the confusion of truth with ideas on one hand and “ reality ” on the other, is,.I think, the fact that ideas after they have been tested in action are employed in the development and grounding of further beliefs. There are cases in which an idea ceases to exist as idea as soon as it is made true; this is so as matter of fact and it is impossible to conceive any reason why it should not be so in point of theory. Such is the case, I take it, with a large part—possibly the major portion—of the ideas that mediate the smaller and transient crises of daily practice. I cannot imagine the situation in which the truth to which I have referred above— the verification of a certain idea about a certain noise—would ever function again as truth—save as I have given it a function in this paper by using it as a corroboration of a certain theory. Such ideas mostly cease, giving way to a matter-of- fact status: say, the perception of the noisy street- car. One at the time may say “ My idea re- garding that noise was a true idea”; or one may not even go so far as that, he may just stop with the eventual perception. But the tested idea need not ever recur asa. factor.of-proof-in any other problem, Such, however, is _ conspicuously not THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 147 the_case with our scientific.ideas. In its first value, the idea or hypothesis of gravitation en- tertained by Newton, stood, when verified, on exactly the same level as the hypothesis regard- ing the noise in the street. Theoretically, that truth might have been so isolated that its truth character would disappear from thought as soon as a certain factual condition was ascer- tained. But practically quite the opposite has happened. ‘The idea operates in many other in- quiries, and operates no longer as mere idea, but as proved_idea. Such truths get an “ eternal” status—one irrespective of application just now V and here, because there are so many nows and heres in which they are useful. Just as to say an idea was true all the time is a way of saying im retro- spect that it has come out in a certain fashion, so to say that an idea is “ eternally true” is to indicate prospective modes of application which are indefinitely anticipated. Its meaning, there- fore, is strictly pragmatic. It does not.indicate a property inherent in the idea as intellectualized existence, but_denotes...aproperty..of_use_and_ employment. Always at hand when needed is a good enough eternal for reasonably minded persons. if THE pyretanenopadss ' CRITERION < gh Vr? a | / arae' © a IV p _ Ihave gone from the very general considerations which occupied us in the earlier portions of this article to matters which relatively at least are specific. I conclude with a summary in the hope that it may bind together the earlier and the later parts of this paper. 1. The condition which antecedes..and provokes any particular exercise of reflective knowing is al- ways one of discrepancy, struggle, “ collision.” This condition is practical, for it involves the habits and interests of the organism, an agent. This does not mean that the struggle is merely personal, or subjective, or psychological. The agent or individual is one factor in the situation—not the situation something subsisting in the individual. The individual has to be identified in the situation, before any situation can be referred—as in psy- chology—to the individual. But the discrepancy calls out and controls reflective knowing only as the fortunes of an agent are implicated in the crisis. Certain elements stand out as obstacles, as interferences, as deficiencies—in short as unsatis- factory and as requiring something for their com- pletion. Other elements stand out as wanted—as required, as a satisfaction which does not exist. This clash (an accompaniment of all desire) be- tween the given and the wanted, between the pres- THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 149 ent and the absent, is at once the root and the typ pe of that peculiar paradoxical rélation between existence and meaning which Bradley insists upon - as the « _essence of judgment. It is is not irrational _ in the se that. we are cosas with appearance we att dealing with a x prmctieal affair. tie = 2. The intellectual or. reagan ATE a, and define it. It is, as it were, the practical ainae held off at arm’s length for inspection and in- vestigation. In this way brute blind reaction against the ufsatisfactoriness. of the situation is ee suspended. Action is turned. into the channel of z observing, of of inferring, of reasoning, or. defining means and end. It is this change in the quality- of" ‘activity, from. direetly-overt;- to-indirect, or in- quiring with view to stating, that constitutes the specific nature. of reflective ‘practice to which Mr. Bradley ‘calls attention. The discovery of the na-_ ture of the conflict supplies materials for the fact or existence side of the judgment. The concep- | tion or projection of the object in which the con-| flict would be terminated furnishes material for the meaning side of the judgment. It is ideal because anticipatory, just as the fact side is ~ existential, because reminiscent or recording. | Hence the two are necessarily both distin- guished from and yet referred to each other: only 150 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION through location of a problem can a solution be conceived ; only in reference to the intent of finding a, solution can the elements of a problem be selected and interpreted. (In origin and in destiny, this correlative determination of existence and meaning is tentative and experimental. The aim of the subject of the judgment is not to include all possible reality, but to select those elements of a reality that are useful in locating the source and nature of the difficulty in hand. The aim of the predicate is not to bunch all possible meaning and refer it in one final act indiscriminately to all ex- istence, but to state the standpoint and method through which the difficulty of the particular-situa- tion may most effectively be dealt with. The selec- tion of what is relevant to the characterization of the problem and the projection of the method of dealing with it are theoretic, hypothetic, intel- lectual :—that is, they are tentative ways of view- ing the matter for the sake of guiding, economiz- ing, and freeing the activities through which it may really be dealt with. 3. The criterion of the worth of the idea is. thus the capacity. of the idea (as a “definition of the end or outcome in terms of what is likely to be service- able as a method) to operate in fulfilling the object for the sake of which it was.projected. Capacity of operation in this fashion is the test, measure, or criterion of truth. Hence the criterion is practi- THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 151 cal in the most overt sense of that.term.. We may, if we choose, regard the object in which the idea terminates through its use in guiding action, as the criterion; but if we so choose, it is at our peril that we forget that this object serves as criterion in its capacity of fulfilment and not_as shéer objective existence. 4. Difficulties overlap ; problems recur which re- semble each other in the kind of treatment they demand for solution. Various modes of activity with their respective ends, going on at some time more or less independently, get organized into single comprehensive systems of behavior. 'The so- lution of one problem is found to create difficulties | elsewhere; or the truth that_is.made~in-the-solu- tion of one problem is found to afford an effective | method of dealing with questions arising appar- ently from unallied sources. Thus certain. tested idéas in “performing a constant or recurrent func- tion secure a a_certain ‘permanent | status. The pro- spective use of such truths, the satisfaction that we anticipate in their employ, the assurance of control that we feel in their possession, becomes relatively much more important than the circum- stances under which they were first made true. In becoming permanent resources, such tested ideas get a generalized energy of position. They are truths in general, truths “ in themselves ” or in the abstract, truths to which positive value is assigned 152 THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION on their own account. Such truths are the “ eter- nal truths ” of current discussion. 'They naturally and properly add to their intellectual and to their practical worth a certain esthetic quality. They are interesting to contemplate, and their con- templation arouses emotions of admiration and reverence. ‘To make these emotions the basis of assigning peculiar inherent sanctity to them apart from their warrant in use, is simply to give way to that mood which in primitive man is the cause of attributing magical efficacy to physical things. Esthetically such truths are more than instrumen- talities. But to ignore both the instrumental and the esthetic aspect, and to ascribe values due to an instrumental and esthetic character to some in- terior and a priori constitution of truth is to make fetishes of them. ced We may not exaggerate the permanence and stability of such truths with respect to their re- curring and prospective use. It is only relatively that they are unchanging. When applied to new cases, used as resources for coping with new diffi- culties, the oldest_ of truths are to some extent remade. Indeed it is only through such applica- tion and such remaking that truths retain their freshness and vitality. Otherwise they are rele- gated to faint reminiscences of an antique tradi- tion. Even the truth that two and two make four has gained a new meaning, has had its truth in THE INTELLECTUALIST CRITERION 153 some degree remade, in the development of the modern theory of number. If we put ourselves in the attitude of a scientific inquirer in asking what is the meaning of truth per se, there spring up before us those ideas which are actively employed in the mastery of new fields, in the organization of new materials. This is the essential difference between truth and dogma; between the living and the dead and decaying. Above all, it is in the region of moral truth that this perception stands out. Moral truths that are not recreated in appli- cation to the urgencies of the passing hour, no mat- ter how true in the place and time of their origin, are pernicious and misleading, i.e., false. And it is perhaps through emphasizing this fact, embodied: in one form or another in every system of morals and in every religion of moral import, that one most readily realizes the character of truth. A SHORT CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH * UPIL. I am desirous, respected teacher, of forming an independent judgment concern- ing the novel theory of truth that you are said to profess. My eagerness is whetted because the theory as expounded to me by my old teacher, Professor Purus Intellectus, so obviously contra- 4 venes common sense, science, and philosophy that I do not understand how it can be advanced in good faith by any reasonable man. Teacher. As you are already somewhat ac- quainted with the theory (or at least with what it purports.to be), perhaps if you will set forth in order your objections, it will appear that the theory that you are acquainted with is not ad- vanced by any reasonable persons, and that by understanding the theory as it is you will also be led to embrace it. Pupil: Objection One. Pragmatism makes truth a subjective affair, namely the satisfaction afforded individuals by ideas, while everybody *A paper read in the spring of 1909 before the Philo- sophical Club of Smith College and not previously published. : 154 A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH = 155 knows that the truth of ideas depends upon their relation to things. | Teacher: Reply. If I were to reply that I hold to existences independent of ideas, existences prior to, synchronous with, and subsequent to ideas, that might seem to you to express only my personal opinion and to have no logical connection with pragmatism. So I beg to remind you that, ac-y cording to pragmatism, ideas (judgments and reasonings being included for convenience in this term) are attitudes of response taken toward ex- tra-ideal, extra-mental things. Instinct and habit express, for instance, modes of response, but modes inadequate for a progressive being, or for adapta- tion to an environment presenting novel and un- mastered features. Under such conditions, ideas are their surrogates. The origin of an idea is thus in some empirical, extra-mental situation which provokes ideas as modes of response, while their meaning is found in the modifications—the “ differ- ences *—they make in this extra-mental situation. Their validity is in turn measured by their capac- ity to effect the transformation they intend. Origin, content, and value—all alike are extra- ideational. The satisfaction upon which the pragmatist dwells is just the better adjustment of living beings to their environment effected by. transformations of the environment through form- ing and applying ideas. far 156 A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH Pupil: Objection Two. But, as I understand it and as you have yourself confessed in your lan- .guage, these external things, while they may be external to the particular idea in question, are em- pirical; they are just other experiences and so mental after all. You hold, I have been informed, that truth is an experienced relation, instead of a relation between experience and what transcends it; why then be mealy-mouthed (pardon my eager- ness if it leads me astray) in admitting that the whole business is intra-mental? Teacher: Reply. Your objection combines and confuses two things. To disentangle them is to answer the objection. (1) The notion of trans- cendence has a double meaning; first, it denotes that which lies inherently and essentially beyond experience. It is interesting to note that the op- ponents of pragmatism have been forced by the exigencies of their hostility to resuscitate a doc- trine supposedly dead: the doctrine of unexperi- enceable, unknowable ‘‘ Things in Themselves.” And as if this were not enough, they identify Truth with relationship to this unknowable. Thereby in behalf of the notion of Truth in general, they land in scepticism with reference to the possibility of any truth in particular. The pragmatist is bound to deny such transcendence. (2) That he is thereby landed in pure subjectivism or the reduc- tion of every existence to the purely mental, follows A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH = 157 only if experience means only mental states. The critic appears to hold the Humian doctrine that experience is made up of states of mind, of sensa- tions and ideas. It is then for him to decide how, _ on his basis, he escapes subjective idealism, or “mentalism.” The pragmatist starts from a much more commonplace notion of experience, that of the plain man who never dreams that to experience a thing is first to destroy the thing and then to substitute a mental state for it. More particu- and activities, rather than of states of conscious- ness. ‘T’o criticise the pragmatist by reading into him exactly the notion of experience that he denies and replaces, may be psychological and unregener- ately “ pragmatic,” but it is hardly “ intellectual.” Pupil: Objection Three. You remind me, curi- ously enough, of a contention of my old instructor to the effect that the pragmatist, when criticised, always shifts his ground. To avoid solipsism and subjectivism, he falls back on things independent of ideas, adducing them in order to pass upon the truth or falsity of the latter. But thereby he only covertly recognizes the intellectualistic standard. Thus he swings unevenly between a denial of sci- ence and a clamorous reiteration, in new phrase- ology, of what all philosophers hold. a larly, the pragmatist has insisted that experience’ is a matter of functions and habits, of active ad-. justments and re-adjustments, of co-ordinations 158 A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH Teacher: Reply. Your words have indeed a familiar sound. Apparently, the average intel- lectualist has got so accustomed to taking truth as a Relation at Large, without specification or analysis, that any attempt at a concrete statement of just what the relationship is appears to be a denial of the relation itself; in which case, he in- terprets an occasional reminder from the prag- matist that the latter is, after all, attempting to specify the nature of the relation, to be a sur- render of the pragmatist’s own case, since it ad- mits after all that there is some relation! However that may be, the pragmatist holds that the relation in question is one of correspondence between existence and thought; but he holds that correspondence instead of being an ultimate and unanalyzable mystery, to be defined by iteration, is precisely a matter of cor-respondence in its _ plain, familiar sense. A condition of dubious and ~ conflicting tendencies calls out thinking as a method of handling it. This condition produces its own appropriate consequences, bearing its own fruits of weal and woe. The thoughts, the estimates, intents, and projects it calls out, just because they are attitudes of (response) and of attempted adjustment (not mere “ states of consciousness ”’), produce their effects also. The kind of interlock- ing, of interadjustment that then occurs between these two sorts of consequences constitutes the A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH 159 correspondence that makes truth, just as failure to respond to each other, to work together, consti- tutes mistake and error—mishandling and wan- dermg. This account may, of course, be wrong— may ‘involve a maladjustment of consequences— but the error in the account, if it exists, must be specific and empirical, and cannot be located by general epistemological accusations. Pupil: Objection Four. Well, even admitting this version of pragmatism, you cannot deny it still contravenes common sense; for, according to you, the correspondence that constitutes truth does not exist till after ideas have worked, while common sense perceives and knows that it is the antecedent agreement of the ideas with reality that. enables them to work. If you make the truth of the ex- istence of a Carboniferous age, or the landing of Columbus in 1492, depend upon a future working of an idea about them, you commit yourself to the most fantastic of philosophies. Teacher: Reply. May I recall to your atten- tion the accusation of “ shifting ground ” when hard pressed? The intellectualist began, if I re- member correctly, with conceiving truth as a re- lation of thought and existence ; has he not, in your last objection, substituted for this conception an identification of the bare existence or event with truth? Which does he mean? How will he have it? The existence of the Carboniferous age, the 160 A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH discovery of America by Columbus are not truths; they are events. Some conviction, some belief, some judgment with reference ito them is necessary to introduce the category of truth and falsity. And since the conviction, the judgment, is as mat- ter of fact subsequent to the event, how can its truth consist in the kind of blank, wholesale rela- tionship the intellectualist contends for? How can the present belief jump out of its present skin, dive into the past, and land upon just the one event (that as past is gone forever) which, by definition, constitutes its truth? I do not wonder _ _ the intellectualist has much to say about “ trans- cendence ” when he comes to dealing with the truth of judgments about the past; but why does he not tell us how we manage to know when one thought lands straight on the devoted head of something past and gone, while another thought comes down on the wrong thing in the past? Pupil. Well, of course, knowledge of the past is very mysterious, but how is the pragmatist any better off? _ Teacher. The reply to that may be inferred from what has already been said. The past event has left effects, consequences, that are present and that will continue in the future. Our belief about it, if genuine, must also modify action in some way and so have objective effects. If these two sets of effects interlock harmoniously, then the A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH . 161 judgment is true. If perchance the past event had no discoverable consequences or our thought of it can work out to no assignable difference any- where, then there is no possibility of genuine judg- ment. Pupil. You have, perhaps, anticipated my next objection, which was that upon the pragmatic theory (by which truth is constituted by future consequences) there are no truths about what is past and gone, since in respect to that ideas can make no difference. For, I suppose, you would say that the difference made is in the effects that continue, since ideas may work out to facilitate or to ‘confuse our relations to these effects. Never- theless, I am not quite satisfied. For when I say it is true that. it rained yesterday, surely the object of my judgment is something past, not future, while pragmatism makes all objects of judgment future. Teacher: Reply. You confuse the content of a judgment with the reference of that content. The content of any idea about yesterday’s rain certainly involves past time, but the distinctive or characteristic aim of judgment is none the less to give this content a future reference and function. Pupil: Objection Five. But your argument re- quires an absurd identification of truth and veri- fication. To verify ideas is to find out that they 162 A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH were already true; or possessed of the truth rela- tion prior to its discovery in verification. But the pragmatist holds that the act of finding out that ideas are true creates the thing that is found. In short, you confuse the psychology of ie out with the reality found out. Teacher: Reply. Many intellectualists have now gone so far as to admit that verification is the testing of a judgment by the consequence it imports, the difference it makes—its working. But they still deny any organic connection between the “‘ antecedent ” truth property of ideas and the verification (or “ making true”) process. Surely they admit either too much or too little. (i) If an idea about a past event is already true because of some mysterious static correspondence that it possesses to that past event, how in the world can its truth be proved by the future consequences of that idea? Why is it that the intellectualist has not produced any positive theory about the relation of verification to his notion of truth? (11) Moreover, if verification consists in the ex- perimental working out of a belief, the intellectu- alist thereby admits that his own theory of truth can be known to be true only as it is verified by its workings. But if the theory that truth is a ready- made static property of judgments is true, how in the world can it be verified by making any spe- cific differences in the course of events? Every- A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH 163 where we have to proceed as if the pragmatic theory were the right one. (iii) If he admits that the pragmatic theory of verification is true, what meaning remains to the statement that the idea had the truth property in advance? Why, simply that it had the property of ability to work —an ability revealed by its actual working. How can a given fact be an objection to the pragmatic theory when that fact has a definitely assignable meaning on the pragmatic theory, while upon the anti-pragmatic theory it just has to be accepted ~ as an ultimate, unanalyzable fact? As to your remark about verification being merely psychological, I have something to say. Colleagues of mine are steadily at work in various laboratories on various researches, forming hypotheses, experimenting, testing, corroborating, refuting, modifying ideas. One of them, for ex- ample, recently put an immense pendulum in place in order to repeat and test Foucault’s experiment with reference to the earth’s rotation. Do you re- gard such verification processes as erg psycho- logical? Pupil. I don’t know. Why do you ask? Teacher. Because if the objector means that such experimental provings are merely psycholog- ical, he has of course relegated to the merely psy- chological (wherever that may be) all the tech- nique of all the physical sciences—a rather high 164 A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH price to pay for the confutation of the pragma- tist. The intellectualist is thus in the dilemma either of conceding to the pragmatist the whole sphere of concrete scientific logic or else of himself regarding all science as merely subjective? Which horn does he choose? Pupil: Objection Siz. I noticed a moment ago that you spoke of the pragmatic theory of © truth being true. Surely the pragmatist does not live up to his reputation of having a sense of humor when he claims assent to his theory on the ground that it is true. What is this but to admit intellectualism ? Teacher: Reply. My son, we are evidently nearing the end. Naturally, the pragmatist claims his theory to be true in the pragmatic sense of truth: it works, it clears up difficulties, removes obscurities, puts individuals into more experi- mental, less dogmatic, and less arbitrarily sceptical relations to life; aligns philosophic with scientific method; does away with self-made problems of epistemology ; clarifies and reorganizes logical the- ory, etc. He is quite content to have the truth of his theory consist in its working in these various ways, and to leave to the intellectualist the proud possession of a static, unanalyzable, unverifiable, unworking property. Pupil: Objection Seven. Nevertheless, the prag- matist is always appealing to the judgments of A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH § 165 others to corroborate his own judgment. Surely this admits the principle of a judgment that is correct, true, ™m se. Teacher: Reply. The pragmatist says that judgment is pragmatic, i.¢., originated under con- ditions of need for a survey and statement, and tested by efficiency in meeting this need. And then you think you have refuted him by saying that any appeal to judgment is intellectualistic! Such begging of the question convinces me that the radical difficulty of the intellectualist is that he conceives of the pragmatist as beginning with | a theory of truth, when in reality the latter begins with a theory about judgments and meanings of which the theory of truth is a corollary. Pupil: Objection Eight. Nevertheless, you are endeavoring to convert your opponent to a certain theory. Surely that is an intellectual undertak- ing, and in theory (at least) the theoretical cri- terion, as Mr. Bradley has well said, must be supreme. Teacher: Reply. A little reflection will convince you that you are going around in the same old circle. Since men have to act together, since the individual subsists in social bonds and activities, to convert another to a certain way of looking at things is to make social ties and functions better adapted, more prosperous in their workings. Only if the pragmatist held the intellectwalist’s position, 166 A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH would he appeal to other than what is ultimately a practical need and a practical criterion in en- deavoring to convert others. Pupil: Objection Nine. Still the pragmatic criterion, being satisfactory working, is. purely personal and subjective. Whatever works so as to please me is true. Either this is your result (in which case your reference to social relations only denotes at bottom a nwmber of purely subjectivistic satisfactions) or else you unconsciously assume an intellectual department of our nature that has to be satisfied; and whose satisfaction is truth. Thereby you admit the intellectualistic criterion. Teacher: Reply. We seem to have got back to our starting-point, the nature of satisfaction. The intellectualist seems to think that because the pragmatist insists upon the factor of human want, purpose, and realization in the making and testing of judgments, the impersonal factor is therefore denied. But what the pragmatist does is to insist that the human factor must work itself out in co-operation with the environmental factor, and that their co-adaptation is both “ correspondence ” and “ satisfaction.” As long as the human factor is ignored and denied, or is regarded as merely psychological (whatever, once more, that means), this human factor will assert itself in irresponsible ways. So long as, particularly in philosophy, a flagrantly unchastened pragmatism reigns, we A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH 167 shall find, as at present, the most ambitious intel- lectualistic systems accepted simply because of the personal comfort they yield those who contrive and accept them. Once recognize the human fac- tor, and pragmatism is at hand to insist that the believer must accept the full consequences of his beliefs, and that his beliefs must be tried out, through acting upon them, to discover what is their meaning or consequence. ‘Till so tested, he insists that beliefs, no matter how noble and seem- ingly edifying, are dogmas, not truths. ‘Till the testing has been worked out very completely and patiently, he holds his beliefs as but provisional, as working hypotheses, as methods :—and he recog- nizes the probability that, as additional modes of testing develop, more and more so-called truths will be relegated to the category of working hypo- theses—till the dogmatic mind is crowded out and starved out. At present, the ignoring by philos- ophers of the part played by personal education, temperament, and preference in their philosophies is the chief source of pretentiousness and insin- cerity in their systems, and is the ground of the popular disregard for them. Pupil. What you say calls to mind something of Chesterton’s that I read recently: “ I agree with the pragmatists that apparent objective truth is not the whole matter ; that there is an authoritative need to believe the things that are necessary to 168 A CATECHISM CONCERNING TRUTH — the human mind. But I say that one of those necessities precisely is a belief in objective truth. Pragmatism is a matter of human needs and one of the first of human needs is to be something more than a pragmatist.” You would say, if I under- stand you aright, that to fall back upon a sup- posed necessity of the “ human mind ” to believe in certain absolute truths, is to evade a proper demand for testing the human mind and all its works. Teacher. My son, I am glad to leave the last word with you. This enfant terrible of intellectu- alism has revealed that the chief objection of abso- lutists to the pragmatic doctrine of the personal (or “subjective’”’) factor in belief is that the pragmatist has spilled the personal milk in the absolutist’s cocoanut. BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES?* I ELIEFS look both ways, towards persons and toward things. They are the original Mr. Facing-both-ways. They form or judge—justify or condemn—the agents who entertain them and who insist upon them. ‘They are of things whose immediate meanings form their content. To be- lieve is to ascribe value, impute meaning, assign import. The collection and interaction of these appraisals and assessments is the world of the common man,—that is, of man as an individual and not as a professional being or class specimen. Thus things are characters, not mere entities ; they *Read as the Presidential Address at the fifth annual meeting of the American Philosophical Association, at Cam- bridge, December 28, 1905, and reprinted with verbal re- visions from the Philosophical Review, Vol. XV., March, 1906. The substitution of the word “ Existences” for the word “ Realities” (in the original title) is due to a sub- sequent recognition on my part that the eulogistic historic associations with the word “Reality” (against which the paper was a protest) infected the interpretation of the paper itself, so that the use of some more colorless word was desirable, 169 ~ 170 BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES behave and respond and provoke. In the behavior that exemplifies and tests their character, they help and hinder; disturb and pacify; resist and comply; are dismal and mirthful, orderly and deformed, queer and commonplace; they agree and disagree; are better and worse. Thus the human world, whether or no it have core and axis, has presence and transfiguration. It means here and now, not in some transcendent sphere. It moves, of itself, to varied incremental | meaning, not to some far off event, whether divine or diabolic. Such movement constitutes conduct, for conduct is the working out of the commitments of belief. That believed better is held to, asserted, affirmed, acted upon. The moments of its crucial fulfilment are the natural “ transcendentals ”’; the decisive, the critical, standards of further estima- tion, selection, and rejection. That believed worse is fled, resisted, transformed into an instrument for the better. Characters, in being condensations of belief, are thus at once the reminders and the prognostications of weal and woe; they concrete and they regulate the terms of effective apprehen- sion and appropriation of things. This general regulative function is what we mean in calling them characters, forms. For beliefs, made in the course of existence, reciprocate by making existence still farther, by developing it. Beliefs are not made by existence BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES 171 in a mechanical or logical or psychological sense. ""* Reality ” naturally instigates belief. It ap- praises itself and through this self-appraisal man- ages its affairs. As things are surcharged valua- tions, so “ consciousness ” means ways of believing and disbelieving. It is interpretation; not merely existence aware of itself as fact, but existence dis- cerning, judging itself, approving and disapprov- ing. This double outlook and connection of belief, its implication, on one side, with beings who suffer and endeavor, and, its complication on the other, with the meanings and worths of things, is its glory or its unpardonable sin. We cannot keep con- nection on one side and throw it away on the other. We cannot preserve significance and de- cline the personal attitude in which it is mscribed and operative, any more than we can succeed in making things “states” of a ‘‘ consciousness ” whose business is to be an interpretation of things. Beliefs are personal affairs, and personal affairs are adventures, and adventures are, if you please, shady. But equally discredited, then, is the uni- verse of meanings. For the world has meaning as somebody’s, somebody’s at a juncture, taken for better or worse, and you shall not have completed your metaphysics till you have told whose world | is meant and how and what for—in what bias and | to what effect. Here is a cake that is had only = 172 BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES by eating it, just as there is digestion only for life as well as by life. So far the standpoint of the common man. But the professional man, the philosopher, has been largely occupied in a systematic effort to discredit the standpoint of the common man, that is, to disable belief as an ultimately valid principle. Phi- losophy is shocked at the frank, almost brutal, evocation of beliefs by and in natural existence, like witches out of a desert heath—at a mode of production which is neither logical, nor physical, nor psychological, but just natural, empirical. For modern philosophy is, as every college senior recites, epistemology; and epistemology, as per- haps our books and lectures sometimes forget to tell the senior, has absorbed Stoic dogma. Passionless imperturbability, absolute detachment, complete subjection to a ready-made and finished reality— physical it may be, mental it may be, logical it may be—is its professed ideal. Forswearing the reality of affection, and the gallantry of adventure, the genuineness of the incomplete, the tentative, it has taken an oath of allegiance to Reality, objective, universal, complete; made perhaps of atoms, per- haps of sensations, pefhaps of logical meanings. This ready-made reality, already including every- thing, must of course swallow and absorb belief, must produce it psychologically, mechanically, or logically, according to its own nature; must in any BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES 178 case, instead of acquiring aid and support from belief, resolve it into one of its own preordained creatures, making a desert and calling it harmony, unity, totality.’ Philosophy has dreamed:the dream of a knowl- edge which is other than the propitious outgrowth of beliefs that shall develop aforetime their ul- terior implications in order to recast them, to rectify their errors, cultivate their waste places, heal their diseases, fortify their feeblenesses :—the dream of a knowledge that has to do with objects having no nature save to be known. Not that their philosophers have admitted the concrete realizability of their scheme. On the 1 Since writing the above I have read the following words of a candidly unsympathetic friend of philosophy: “ Neither philosophy nor science can institute man’s relation to the universe, because such reciprocity must have existed before any kind of science or philosophy can begin; since each investigates phenomena by means of the intellect, and in- dependent of the position and feeling of the investigator; whereas the relation of man to the universe is defined, not by the intellect alone, but by his sensilive perception aided by all his spiritual powers. However much one may assure and instruct a man that all real existence is an idea, that matter is made up of atoms, that the essence of life is cor- porality or will, that heat, light, movement, electricity, are different manifestations of one and the same energy, one cannot thereby explain to a being with pains, pleasures, hopes, and fears his position in the universe.” Tolstoi, essay on “ Religion and Morality,” in “ Essays, Letters, and Mis- cellanies.” 174 BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES contrary, the assertion of the absolute “ Reality ” of what is empirically unrealizable is a part of the scheme; the ideal of a universe of pure, cogni- tional objects, fixed elements in fixed relations. Sensationalist and idealist, positivist and trans- cendentalist, materialist and spiritualist, defining this object in as many differing ways as they have different conceptions of the ideal and method of knowledge, are at one in their devotion to an iden- tification of Reality with something that connects monopolistically with passionless knowledge, belief purged of all personal reference, origin, and out- look.* ; What is to be said of this attempt to sever the cord which naturally binds together personal atti- tudes and the meaning of things? This much at least: the effort to extract meanings, values, from the beliefs that ascribe them, and to give the former absolute metaphysical validity while the latter are sent to wander as scapegoats in the wil- * Hegel may be excepted from this statement. The habit of interpreting Hegel as a Neo-Kantian, a Kantian en- larged and purified, is a purely Anglo-American habit. This is no place to enter into the intricacies of Hegelian exegesis, but the subordination of both logical meaning. and of mechanical existence to Geist, to life in its own develop- ing movement, would seem to stand out in any unbiased view of Hegel. At all events, I wish to recognize my own personal debt to Hegel for the view set forth in this paper, without, of course, implying that it represents Hegel’s own intention. BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES 175 derness of mere phenomena, is an attempt, which, as long as “ our interest’s on the dangerous edge of things,” will attract an admiring, even if sus- Picious, audience. Moreover, we may admit that the attempt to catch the universe of immediate experience, of action and passion, coming and going, to damn it in its present body in order ex- pressly to glorify its spirit to all eternity, to vali- date the meaning of beliefs by discrediting their natural existence, to attribute absolute worth to the intent of human convictions just because of the absolute worthlessness of their content—that the performance of this feat of virtuosity has developed philosophy to its present wondrous, if formidable, technique. But can we claim more than a succés d’estime? Consider again the nature of the effort. The world of immediate meanings, of the world em- pirically sustained in beliefs, is to be sorted out into two portions, metaphysically discontinuous, one of which shall alone be good and true “ Real- ity,” the fit material of passionless, beliefless knowl- edge; while the other part, that which is excluded, shall be referred exclusively to belief and treated as niere appearance, purely subjective, impressions or effects in consciousness, or as that ludicrously abject modern discovery—an epiphenomenon. And this division into the real and the unreal is accomplished by the very individual whom his own 176 BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES “absolute” results reduce to phenomenality, in terms of the very immediate experience which is infected with worthlessness, and on the basis of ‘preference, of selection that are declared to be unreal! Can the thing be done? Anyway, the snubbed and excluded factor may always reassert itself. The very pushing it out of “ Reality ” may but add to its potential energy, and invoke a more violent recoil. When affections and aversions, with the beliefs in which they record themselves and the efforts they exact, are re- duced to epiphenomena, dancing an idle attendance upon a reality complete without them, to which they vainly strive to accommodate themselves by mirroring, then may the emotions flagrantly burst forth with the claim that, as a friend of mine puts it, reason is only a fig leaf for their nakedness. When one man says that need, uncertainty, choice, novelty, and strife have no place in Reality, which is made up wholly of established things behaving by foregone rules, then may another man be pro- voked to reply that all such fixities, whether named atoms or God, whether they be fixtures of a sensa- tional, a positivistic, or an idealistic system, have | existence and import only in the problems, needs, _ struggles, and instrumentalities of ‘conscious - agents and patients. For home rule may be found in the unwritten efficacious constitution of ex- perience. BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES 177 That contemporaneously we are in the presence of such a reaction is apparent. Let us, in pursuit of our topic, inquire how it came about and why it takes the form that it takes. This considera- tion may not only occupy the hour, but may help diagram some future parallelogram of forces. The account calls for some sketching (1) of the historical tendencies which have shaped the situa- tion in which a Stoic theory of knowledge claims metay ‘1ysical monopoly, and (2) of the tendencies that have furnished the despised principle of be- lief opportunity and means of reassertion. II Imagination readily travels to a period when a gospel of intense, and, one may say, deliberate passionate disturbance appeared to be conquering the Stoic ideal of passionless reason ; when the de- mand for individual assertion by faith against the established, embodied objective order was seem- ingly subduing the idea of the total subordination of the individual to the universal. By what course of events came about the dramatic reversal, in | which an ethically conquered Stoicism became the ‘ conqueror, epistemologically, of Christianity? How are our imaginations haunted by the idea of what might have happened if Christianity had 178 BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES found ready to its hand intellectual formula- tions corresponding to its practical proclama- tions! That the ultimate principle of conduct is affec- tional and volitional ; that God is love; that access to the principle is by faith, a personal attitude; that belief, surpassing logical basis and warrant, works out through its own operation its own ful- filling evidence: such was the implied moral meta- physic of Christianity. But this implication needed. to become a theory, a theology, a formulation; and in this need, it found no recourse save to | philosophies that had identified true existence with —————— the proper object of logical reason. For, in Greek thought, after the valuable meanings, the meanings of industry and art that appealed to sus- tained and serious choice, had given birth and status to reflective reason, reason denied its an- cestry of organized endeavor, and proclaimed itself in its function of self-conscious logical thought to be the author and warrant of all genuine things. Yet how nearly Christianity had found prepared for it the needed means of its own intellectual statement! We recall Aristotle’s account of moral knowing, and his definition of man. Man as man, he tells us, is a principle that may be termed either desiring thought or thinking desire. Not as pure intelligence does man: know, but as an organization of desires effected through reflection BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES 179 upon their own conditions and consequences. What if Aristotle had only assimilated his idea of theo- retical to his notion of practical knowledge! Be- cause practical thinking was so human, Aristotle rejected it in favor of pure, passionless cognition, something superhuman. Thinking desire is ex- perimental, is tentative, not absolute. It looks to the future and to the past for help in the future. It is contingent, not necessary. It doubly relates to the individual: to the individual thing as ex- perienced by an individual agent; not to the uni- versal. Hence desire is a sure sign of defect, of privation, of non-being, and seeks surcease in something which knows it not. Hence desiring reason culminating in beliefs relating to imperfect - existence, stands forever in contrast with passion- less reason functioning in pure knowledge, logic- ally complete, of perfect being. I need not remind you how through Neo-Platon- ism, St. Augustine, and the Scholastic renaissance, these conceptions became imbedded in Christian philosophy ; and what a reversal occurred of the original practical principle of Christianity. Be- lief is henceforth important because it is the mere antecedent in a finite and fallen world, a temporal and phenomenal world infected with non-being, of true knowledge to be achieved only in a world of completed Being. Desire is but the self-con- sciousness of defect striving to its own termination 180 BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES in perfect possession, through perfect knowledge of perfect being. I need not remind you that the ‘prima facie subordination of reason to authority, of knowledge to faith, in the medieval code, is, after all, but the logical result of the doctrine that man as man (since only reasoning desire) is merely phenomenal; and has his reality in God, who as God is the complete union of rational insight and being—the term of man’s desire, and the fulfilment of his feeble attempts at knowing. Authority, “ faith ” as it then had to be conceived, meant just that this Being comes externally to the aid of man, otherwise hopelessly doomed to misery in long drawn out error and non-being, and disciplines him till, in the next world under more favoring auspices, he may have his desires stilled in good, and his faith may yield to knowledge:—for we forget that the doctrine of immortality was not an appendage, but an integral part of the theory that since knowledge is the true function of man, happi- ness is attained only in knowledge, which itself exists only in achievement of perfect Being or God. For my part, I can but think that medieval absolutism, with its provision for authoritative supernatural assistance in this world and assertion of supernatural realization in the next, was more logical, as well as more humane, than the modern absolutism, that, with the same logical premises, bids man find adequate consolation and support in BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES 181 the fact that, after all, his strivings are already eternally fulfilled, his errors already eternally transcended, his partial beliefs already eternally comprehended. The modern age is marked by a refusal to be satisfied with the postponement of the exercise and function of reason to another and supernatural sphere, and by a resolve to practise itself upon its present object, nature, with all the joys thereunto appertaining. The pure intelligence of Aristotle, thought thinking itself, expresses itself as free inquiry directed upon the present conditions of its own most effective exercise. The principle of the inherent relation of thought to being was pre- served intact, but its practical locus was moved down from the next world to this. Spinoza’s “ God or Nature ” is the logical outcome; as is also his strict correlation of the attribute of matter with the attribute of thought; while his combination of thorough distrust of passion and faith with complete faith in reason and all-absorbing passion for knowledge is so classic an embodiment of the whole modern contradiction that it may awaken ad- miration where less thorough-paced formulations call out irritation. In the practical devotion of present intelligence to its present object, nature, science was born, - and also its philosophical counterpart, the theory of knowledge. Epistemology only generalized in 182 BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES its loose, although narrow and technical way, the question practically urgent in Europe: How is science possible? How can intelligence actively and directly get at its object? Meantime, through Protestantism the values, the meanings formerly characterizing the next life (the opportunity for full perception of perfect being), were carried over into present-day emo- tions and responses. The dualism between faith authoritatively sup- ported as the principle of this life, and knowledge supernaturally realized as the principle of the next, was transmuted into the dualism between intelli- gence now and here occupied with natural things, and the affections and accompanying beliefs, now and here realizing spiritual worths. For a time this dualism operated as a convenient division of labor. Intelligence, freed from responsibility for and preoccupation with supernatural truths, could occupy itself the more fully and efficiently with the world that now is; while the affections, charged with the values evoked in the medieval discipline, entered into the present enjoyment of the delecta- tions previously reserved for the saints. Direct- ness took the place of systematic intermediation ; the present of the future; the individual’s emo- tional consciousness of the supernatural institu- tion. Between science and faith, thus conceived, a bargain was struck. Hands off; each to his own, BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES 183 , was the compact ; the natural world to intelligence, ’ the moral, the spiritual world to belief. This (natural) world for knowledge; that (supernatu- ral) world for belief. Thus the antithesis, unex- pressed, ignored, within experience, between belief and knowledge, between the purely objective values _ of thought and the personal values of passion and Y volition, was more fundamental, more determining, than the opposition, explicit and harassing, within knowledge, between subject and object, mind and matter. This latent antagonism worked out into the open. In scientific detail, knowledge encroached upon the historic traditions and opinions with which the moral and religious life had identified itself. It made history to be as natural, as much its spoil, as physical nature. It turned itself upon man, and proceeded remorselessly to account for his emotions, his volitions, his opinions. Knowl- edge, in its general theory, as philosophy, went the same way. It was pre-committed to the old notion: the absolutely real is the object of knowl- edge, and hence is something universal and im- personal. So, whether by the road of sensational- ism or rationalism, by the path of mechanicalism or objective idealism, it came about that concrete selves, specific feeling and willing beings, were relegated with the beliefs in which they declare themselves to the “ phenomenal.” 184 BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES IIl So much for the situation against which some contemporary tendencies are a deliberate protest. What of the positive conditions that give us not mere protest, like the unreasoning revolt of heart against head found at all epochs, but some- thing articulate and constructive? The field is only too large, and I shall limit myself to the evolution of the knowledge standpoint itself. I shall suggest, first, that the progress of intelligence directed upon natural materials has evolved a pro- cedure of knowledge that renders untenable the inherited conception of knowledge; and, secondly, that this result is reinforced by the specific results of some of the special sciences. 1. First, then, the very use of the knowledge standpoint, the very expression of the knowledge preoccupation, has produced methods and tests that, when formulated, intimate a radically differ- ent conception of knowledge, and of its relation to existence and belief, than the orthodox one. The one thing that stands out is that thinking is inquiry, and that knowledge as science is the outcome of systematically directed inquiry. For a time it was natural enough that inquiry should be interpreted in the old sense, as just change of subjective attitudes and opinions to make them square up with a “ reality ” that is already there BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES 185 in ready-made, fixed, and finished form. The rationalist had one notion of the reality, i.¢., that it was of the nature of laws, genera, or an ordered system, and so thought of concepts, axioms, etc., as the indicated modes of representation. The empiricist, holding reality to be a lot of little dis- crete particular lumps, thought of disjointed sen- sations as its appropriate counterpart. But ~ both alike were thorough conformists. If “ real- ity ” is already and completely given, and if knowl- edge is just submissive acceptance, then, of course, inquiry is only a subjective change in the human “‘ mind ” or in “ consciousness,’”’—these being sub- jective and “ unreal.” But the very development of the sciences served to reveal a peculiar and intolerable paradox. _ Epistemology, having condemned inquiry once for all to the region of subjectivity in an invidious _ sense, finds itself in flat opposition in principle and Yin detail to the assumption and to the results of the | sciences. Epistemology is bound to deny to the results of the special sciences in detail any ulterior objectivity just because they always are in a proc- ess of inquiry—in solution. While a man may not be halted at being told that his mental activities, since his, are not genuinely real, many men will draw violently back at being told that all the dis- coveries, conclusions, explanations, and theories of the sciences share the same fate, being the products 186 BELIEFS AND EXISTENCES of a discredited mind. And, in general, epistemol- ogy, in relegating human thinking as inquiry to a merely phenomenal region, makes concrete approx- ‘Imation and conformity to objectivity hopeless. Even if it did square itself up to and by “ reality ” it never could be sure of it. The ancient myth of Tantalus and his effort to drink the water before him seems to be ingeniously prophetic of modern epistemology. ‘The thirstier, the needier of truth the human mind, and the intenser the efforts put forth to slake itself in the ocean of being just beyond the edge of consciousness, the more surely the living waters of truth recede! When such self-confessed sterility is joined with _ consistent derogation of all the special results of the special sciences, some one is sure to raise the cry of “ dog in the manger,” or of “‘ sour grapes.” I start and am flustered by a noise heard. Em- ae. anette teagan onal aE “ pirically, that noise is fearsome; it really i is, not merely phenomenally or subjectively so. That is what it is experienced as being. But, when I ex- perience the noise as a known thing, I find it to be innocent of harm. It is the tapping of a shade against the window, owing to movements of the wind. The experience has changed; that is, the thing experienced has changed—not that an un- reality has given place to a reality, nor that some transcendental (unexperienced) Reality has changed,’ not that truth has changed, but just and only the concrete reality experienced has changed. I now feel ashamed of my fright; and _ the noise as fearsome is changed to noise as a wind- ? curtain fact, and hence practically indifferent to my welfare. This is a change of experienced ex- istence effected through the medium of cognition. 1 Since the non-empiricist believes in things-in-themselves (which he may term “atoms,” “ sensations,” transcendental unities, a priori concepts, an absolute experience, or what- ever), and since he finds that the empiricist makes much of change (as he must, since change is continuously experi- enced) he assumes that the empiricist means his own non- empirical Realities are in continual flux, and he naturally shudders at having his divinities so violently treated. But, once recognize that the empiricist doesn’t have any such Realities at all, and the entire problem of the relation of change to reality takes a very different aspect. THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM 231 i i The content of the latter experience cognitively re- | garded is doubtless truer than the content of the ‘earlier ; but it is in no sense more real. To call it ‘truer, moreover, must, from the empirical stand- point, mean a concrete difference in actual things experienced.’ Again, in many cases, only in retro- spect is the prior experience cognitionally regarded at all. In such cases, it is only in regard to con- jAtrasted content im a subsequent experience that the determination “ truer ” has force. Perhaps some reader may now object that as matter of fact the entire experience is cognitive, but that the earlier parts of it are only imperfectly so, resulting in a phenomenon that is not real; r while the latter part, being a more complete cog- nition, results in what is relatively, at least, more real.* In short, a critic may say that, when I was . *It would lead us aside from the point to try to tell just what is the nature of the experienced difference we call truth. Professor James’s recent articles may well be con- sulted. The point to bear in mind here is just what sort of a thing the empiricist must mean by true, or truer (the noun Truth is, of course, a generic name for all cases of “Trues”). The adequacy of any particular account is not a matter to be settled by general reasoning, but by finding out what sort of an experience the truth-experience actually is. *I say “relatively,” because the transcendentalist still holds that finally the cognition is imperfect, giving us only some symbol or phenomenon of. Reality (which is only in the Absolute or in some Thing-in-Itself)—otherwise the — _ 232 THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM frightened by the noise, I knew I was frightened ; otherwise there would have been no experience at all. At this point, it is necessary to make a dis- ‘tinction so simple and yet so all-fundamental that I am afraid the reader will be inclined to pooh- pooh it away as a mere verbal distinction. But to see that to the empiricist this distinction is not verbal, but genuine, is the precondition of any un- derstanding of him. The immediatist must, by his postulate, ask what is the fright experienced as. Is what is actually experienced, I-know-I-am- frightened, or I-am-frightened? I see absolutely no reason for claiming that the experience must be described by the former phrase. In all proba- bility (and all the empiricist logically needs is just one case of this sort) the experience is simply and just of fright-at-the-noise. Later one may (or may not) have an experience describable as I- know-I-am- (or-was) and improperly or properly, frightened. But this is a different experience— that is, a different thing. And if the critic goes on to urge that the person “ really’’ must have known that he was frightened, I can only point out that the critic is shifting the venue. He may be tight, but, if so, it is only because the “ really ” curtain-wind fact would have as much ontological reality as the existence of the Absolute itself: a conclusion. at which the non-empiricist perhorresces, for no reason obvious to me—save that it would put an end to his transcendentalism, THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM = 233 is something not concretely experienced (whose na- ture accordingly is the critic’s business) ; and this is to depart from the empiricist’s point of view, to attribute to him a postulate he expressly repudiates. The material point may come out more clearly if I say that we must make a distinction between a thing as cognitive, and one as cognized.’ I should define a cognitive experience as one that has certain bearings or implications which induce, and fulfil themselves in, a subsequent experience in which the relevant thing is experienced as cog- nized, as a known object, and is thereby trans- formed, or reorganized. The fright-at-the-noise in the case cited is obviously cognitive, in this sense. By description, it induces an investigation or in- quiry in which both noise and fright are objectively stated or presented—the noise as a shade-wind fact, the fright as an organic reaction to a sudden acoustic stimulus, a reaction that under the given circumstances was useless or even detrimental, a maladaptation. Now, pretty much all of experi- ence is of this sort (the “ is ” meaning, of course, is experienced as), and the empiricist is false to his principle if he does not duly note this fact.? But *In general, I think the distinction between -ive and -ed one of the most fundamental of philosophic distinctions, and one of the most neglected. The same holds of -tion and -ing. * What is criticised, now as “ geneticism” (if I may coin 234 THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM he is equally false to his principle if he permits himself to be confused as to the concrete differences in the two things experienced. There are two little words through explication of which the empiricist’s position may be brought out—“ as” and “that.” We may express his presupposition by saying that things are what they are experienced as being; or that to give a just account of anything is to tell what that thing is experienced to be. By these words I want to in- dicate the absolute, final, irreducible, and inex- pugnable concrete quale which everything experi- enced not so much has as is. To grasp this aspect of empiricism is to see what the empiricist means / by objectivity, by the element of control. Sup- pose we take, as a crucial case for the empiricist, an out and out illusion, say of Zollner’s lines. These are experienced as convergent; they are ‘truly ” parallel. If things are what they are experienced as being, how can the distinction be drawn between illusion and the true state of the case? There is no answer to this question except by sticking to the fact that the experience of the lines as divergent is a concrete qualitative thing or that. It is that experience which it is, and no the word) and now as “ pragmatism” is, in its truth, just the fact that the empiricist does take account of the ex- perienced “ drift, occasion, and contexture ” of things experi- enced—to use Hobbes’s phrase. fee vo} ] SS” THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM 235 other. And if the reader rebels at the iteration of such obvious tautology, I can only reiterate that the realization of the meaning of this tautology is the key to the whole question of the objectivity of experience, as that stands to the empiricist. The lines of that experience are divergent; not merely seem so. The question of truth is not as to whether Being or Non-Being, Reality or mere Appearance, is experienced, but as to the worth of a certain concretely experienced thing. The only way of passing upon this question is by sticking in the most uncompromising fashion to that ex- perience as real. That experience is that two lines with certain cross-hatchings are apprehended as convergent; only by taking that experience as real and as fully real, is there any basis for, or way of going to, an experienced knowledge that the lines are parallel. It is in the concrete thing as experienced that all the grounds and clues to its own intellectual or logical rectification are con- tained. It is because this thing, afterwards ad- judged false, is a concrete that, that it develops into a corrected experience (that is, experience of a corrected thing—we reform things just as we reform ourselves or a bad boy) whose full content is not a whit more real, but which is true or truer.? * Perhaps the point would be clearer if expressed in this way: Except as subsequent estimates of worth are intro- duced, “ real”. means only existent. The eulogistic connota- 236 THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM ff If any experience, then a determinate experi- __ ence; and this determinateness is the only, and is ” the adequate, principle of control, or “ objectiv- ‘ity.” The experience may be of the vaguest sort. I may not see anything which I can identify as a familiar object—a table, a chair, etc. It may be dark; I may have only the vaguest impression that there is something which looks like a table. Or I may be completely befogged and confused, as when one rises quickly from sleep in a pitch-dark room. But this vagueness, this doubtfulness, this confu- sion is the thing experienced, and, qua real, is as “ good” a reality as the self-luminous vision of an Absolute. It is not just vagueness, doubtful- ness, confusion, at large or in general. It is this vagueness, and no other; absolutely unique, abso- lutely what i¢ is.1 Whatever gain in clearness, in fullness, in trueness of content is experienced must grow out of some element in the experience of this experienced as what it is. To return to the illu- sion: If the experience of the lines as convergent is illusory, it is because of some elements in the tion that makes the term Reality equivalent to true or genuine being has great pragmatic significance, but its con- 4 fusion with reality as existence is the point aimed at in the "above paragraph. | One does not so easily escape medieval Realism as one thinks. Either every experienced thing has its own deter- minateness, its own unsubstitutable, unredeemable reality, or else “generals” are separate existences after all. THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM 237 thing as experienced, not because of something de- fined in terms of externality to this particular ex- perience. If the illusoriness can be detected, it is « because the thing experienced is real, having within its experienced reality elements whose own mutual tension effects its reconstruction. Taken con- cretely, the experience of convergent lines con- tains within itself the elements of the transforma- tion of its own content. It is this thing, and not some separate truth, that clamors for its own reform. There is, then, from the empiricist’s point _ of view, no need to search for some aboriginal that ~ to which all successive experiences are attached, and which is somehow thereby undergoing continu- ous change. Experience is always of thats; and the most comprehensive and inclusive experience of the universe that the philosopher himself can * obtain is the experience of a characteristic that. From the empiricist’s point of view, this is as true of the exhaustive and complete insight of a hypo- thetical all-knower as of the vague, blind experi- ence of the awakened sleeper. As reals, they stand \e the same level. As trues, the latter has by definition the better of it; but if this insight is in any way the truth of the blind awakening, it is because the latter has, in its own determinate quale, _ elements of real continuity with the former ; it is, ex hypothesi, transformable through a series of experienced reals without break of continuity, into J 238 THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM the absolute thought-experience. There is no need of logical manipulation to effect the transforma- tion, nor could any logical consideration effect it. If effected at all it is just by immediate experiences, each of which is just as real (no more, no less) as either of the two terms between which they lie. Such, at least, is the meaning of the empiricist’s | contention. So, when he talks of experience, he does not mean some grandiose, remote affair that is cast like a net around a succession of fleeting experiences; he does not mean an indefinite total, | comprehensive experience which somehow engirdles an endless flux; he means that things are what they are experienced to be, and that every experi- ence is some thing. From the postulate of empiricism, then (or, what is the same thing, from a general consideration of the concept of experience), nothing can be deduced, not a single philosophical proposition.’ The reader * Excepting, of course, some negative ones. One could say that certain views are certainly not true, because, by hypothesis, they refer to nonentities, i.e., non-empiricals. But even here the empiricist must go slowly. From his own standpoint, even the most professedly transcendental “statements are, after all, real as experiences, and hence negotiate some transaction with facts. For this reason, he cannot, in theory, reject them in toto, but has to show con- cretely how they arose and how they are to be corrected. In a word, his logical relationship to statements that pro- fess to relate to things-in-themselves, unknowables, inexperi- enced substances, etc., is precisely that of the a hiatre to the Zélliner lines. . THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM 239 may hence conclude that all this just comes to the truism that experience is experience, or is what it is. a one attempts to draw conclusions from the bare oncept of experience, the reader is quite right. But the real significance of the principle is that of a method of philosophical analysis—a method iden- tical in kind (but differing in problem and hence in operation) with that of the scientist. If you ” wish to find out what subjective, objective, phys- ical, mental, cosmic, psychic, cause, substance, pur- pose, activity, evil, being, quality—any philo- sophic term, in short—means, go to experience and ” see what the thing is experienced as. Such a method is not spectacular; it permits of no offhand demonstrations of God, freedom, im- mortality, nor of the exclusive reality of matter, or ideas, or consciousness, etc. But it supplies a way of telling what all these terms mean. It may seem insignificant, or chillingly disappointing, but only upon condition that it be not worked. Philo- sophic conceptions have, I believe, outlived their usefulness considered as stimulants to emotion, or as a species of sanctions; and a larger, more fruit- ful and more valuable career awaits them consid- ered as specifically experienced meanings. [Nore: The reception of this essay proved that I was un- reasonably sanguine in thinking that the foot-note of warn- ing, appended to the title, would forfend radical mis- apprehension. I see now that it was unreasonable to expect that the word “immediate” in a philosophic writing could 240 THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM (' be generally understood to apply to anything except know!l- _ edge, even though the body of the essay is a protest | against such limitation. But I venture to repeat that the a essay is not a denial of the necessity of “ mediation,” or re- flection, in knowledge, but is an assertion that the inferential factor must exist, or must occur, and that all existence is _ direct and vital, so that philosophy can pass upon its nature —as upon the nature of all of the rest of its subject-matter \_—only by first ascertaining what it exists or occurs as. I venture to repeat also another statement of the text: I do not mean by “immediate experience” any aboriginal stuff out of which things are-evolved, but I use the term , to indicate the necessity of employing in philosophy the | direct descriptive method that has now made its way in ‘all the natural sciences, with such modifications, of course, as the subject itself entails. There is nothing in the text to imply that things exist in experience atomically or in isolation. When it is said that a thing as cognized is different from an earlier non-cognition- ‘ally experienced thing, the saying no more implies lack of ‘continuity between the things, than the obvious remark | that a seed is different from a flower or a leaf denies their \continuity. The amount and kind of continuity or dis- creteness that exists is to be discovered by recurring to what actually occurs in experience. ‘Finally, there is nothing in the text that denies the existence of things temporally prior to human experiencing of them. Indeed, I should think it fairly obvious that we experience most things as temporally prior to our ex- periencing of them. The import of the article is to the effect that we are not entitled to draw philosophic (as dis- tinct from scientific) conclusions as to the meaning of prior temporal existence till we have ascertained what it is to experience a thing as past. These four disclaimers cover, I think, all the misapprehensions disclosed in the four or five controversial articles (noted below) that the original essay evoked. One of these articles (that of Professor eyes j - THE POSTULATE OF EMPIRICISM 241 Woodbridge), raised a point of fact, holding that cogni- tional experience tells us, without alteration, just what the things of other types of experience are, and in that sense transcends other experiences. This is too fundamental an issue to discuss in a note, and I content myself with re- marking that with respect to it, the bearing of the article is that the issue must be settled by a careful descriptive survey of things as experienced, to see whether modifica- tions do not occur in existences when they are experienced as known; i.e. as true or false in character. The reader interested in following up this discussion is referred to the following articles: Vol. II. of the Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, two articles by Bake- well, p. 520 and p. 687; one by Bode, p. 658; one by Wood- bridge, p. 573; Vol. III. of the same Journal, by Leighton, p. 174.] “ CONSCIOUSNESS ” AND EXPERIENCE? 1 VERY science in its final standpoint and work- ing aims is controlled by conditions lying out- side itself—conditions that subsist in the practi-, cal life of the time. With no science is this as obviously true as with psychology. Taken with- out nicety of analysis, no one would deny that psy- chology is specially occupied with the individual ; that it wishes to find out those things that proceed peculiarly from the individual, and the mode of their connection with him. Now, the way in which the individual is conceived, the value that is attrib- uted to him, the things in his make-up that arouse interest, are not due at the outset to psychology. The scientific view regards these matters in a re- flected, a borrowed, medium. They are revealed in the light of social life. An autocratic, an aristocratic, a democratic society propound such different estimates of the worth and place of individuality ; they procure for the individual as an individual such different sorts of experience; * Delivered as a public address before the Philosophic Union of the University of California, with the title “ Psychology and Philosophic Method,” May, 1899, and pub- lished in the University Chronicle for August, 1899. Re- printed, with slight verbal changes, mostly excisions, R42 / //, CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 243 they aim at arousing such different impulses and at organizing them according to such different pur- poses, that the psychology arising in each must show a different temper. In this sense, psychology is a political science. - While the professed psychologist, in his conscious — procedure, may easily cut his subject-matter loose from these practical ties and references, yet the starting point and goal of his course are none the less socially set. In this conviction I venture to introduce to an audience that could hardly be expected to be interested in the technique of psy- chology, a technical subject, hoping that the human meaning may yet appear. There is at present a strong, apparently a grow- ing tendency to conceive of psychology as an ac- count of the consciousness of the individual, con- sidered as something in and by itself; conscious- ness, the assumption virtually runs, being of such an order that it may be analyzed, described, and explained in terms of just itself. The statement, as commonly made, is that psychology is an ac- count of consciousness, gua consciousness ; and the phrase is supposed to limit psychology to a certain definite sphere of fact that may receive adequate discussion for scientific purposes, without troubling itself with what lies outside. Now if this concep- tion be true, there is no intimate, no important connection of psychology and philosophy at large. 244 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE That philosophy, whose range is comprehensive, whose problems are catholic, should be held down by a discipline whose voice is as partial as its _ material is limited, is out of the range of intelli- gent discussion. But there is another possibility. If the indi- vidual of whom psychology treats be, after all, a social individual, any absolute setting off and apart of a sphere of consciousness as, even for sci- entific purposes, self-sufficient, is condemned in ad- vance. All such limitation, and all inquiries, descriptions, explanations that go with it, are only preliminary. “Consciousness” is but a symbol, an anatomy whose life is in natural and social operations. ‘To know the symbol, the psychical letter, is important ; but its necessity lies not within itself, but in the need of a language for reading the things signified. If this view be correct, we cannot be so sure that psychology is without large philosophic significance. Whatever meaning the individual has for the social life that he both in- corporates and animates, that meaning has psy- chology for philosophy. This problem is too important and too large to suffer attack in an evening’s address. Yet I ven- ture to consider a portion of it, hoping that such things as appear will be useful clues in enter- ’ ing wider territory. We may ask what is the effect upon psychology of considering its material as CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 245 something so distinct as to be capable of treatment without involving larger issues. In this inquiry we take as representative some such account of the science as this: Psychology deals with conscious- ness ** as such ” in its various modes and processes. It aims at an isolation of each such as will permit accurate description: at statement of its place in — the serial order such as will enable us to state the laws by which one calls another into being, or as will give the natural history of its origin, matur- ing, and dissolution. It is both analytic and syn- thetic—analytic in that it resolves each state into its constituent elements; synthetic in that it dis- covers the processes by which these elements com- bine into complex wholes and series. It leaves alone—it shuts out—dquestions concerning the validity, the objective import of these modifica- tions: of their value in conveying truth, in effect- ing goodness, in constituting beauty. For it is just with such questions of worth, of validity, that philosophy has to do. Some such view as this is held by the caeae majority of working psychologists to-day. A va- riety of reasons have conspired to bring about general acceptance. Such a view seems to enroll one in the ranks of the scientific men rather than of the metaphysicians—and there are those who distrust the metaphysicians. Others desire to take problems piecemeal and in detail, avoiding that ex- 246 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE cursion into ultimates, into that never-ending pan- orama of new questions and new possibilities that seems to be the fate of the philosopher. While no temperate mind can do other than sympathize with this view, it is hardly more than an expedient. For, as Mr. James remarks, after disposing of the question of free-will by relegatimg it to the domain of the metaphysician :—‘* Metaphysics means only an unusually obstinate attempt to think clearly and + consistently °—and clearness and consistency are not things to be put off beyond a certain point. When the metaphysician chimes in with this new- found modesty of the psychologist, so different from the disposition of Locke and Hume and the Mills, salving his metaphysical conscience with the remark—it hardly possesses the dignity of a con- viction—that the partial sciences, just because they are partial, are not expected to be coherent with themselves nor with one another; when the meta- physician, I say, praises the psychologist for stick- ing to his last, we are reminded that another mo- tive is also at work. There is a half-conscious irony in this abnegation of psychology. It is not the first time that science has assumed the work of Cinderella; and, since Mr. Huxley has happily reminded her, she is not altogether oblivious, in her modesty, of a possible future check to the pride of her haughty sister, and of a certain coronation that shall mark her coming to her own. CONSCIOUSN ESS AND EXPERIENCE 247 But, be the reasons as they may, there is little doubt of the fact. Almost all our working psy- chologists admit, nay, herald this limitation of their work. I am not presumptuous enough to set myself against this array. I too proclaim | myself of those who believe that psychology has to do (at a certain point, that is) with “ conscious-| ness as such.” But I do not believe that the limi-. tation is final. Quite the contrary: if “ conscious-| ness” or “state of consciousness” be given in- telligible meaning, I believe that this conception is the open gateway into the fair fields of philosophy. For, note you, the phrase is an ambiguous one. It may mean one thing to the metaphysician who proclaims: Here finally we have psychology rec- ognizing her due metes and bounds, giving bonds to trespass no more. It may mean quite another thing to the psychologist in his work—whatever he may happen to say about it. It may be that the psychologist deals with states of consciousness as the significant, the analyzable and describable form, to which he reduces the things he is study- ing. Not that they are that existence, but that they are its indications, its clues, in shape for handling by scientific methods. So, for example, does the paleontologist work. Those curiously shaped and marked forms to which he is devoted are not life, nor are they the literal termini of his endeavor; but through them as signs and records 248 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE he construes a life. And again, the painter-artist — might well say that he is concerned only with colored paints as such. Yet none the less through them as registers and indices, he reveals to us the mysteries of sunny meadow, shady forest, and twilight wave. These are the things-in-themselves of which the oils on his palette are phenomena. So the preoccupation of the psychologist with states of consciousness may signify that they are the media, the concrete conditions to which he purposely reduces his material, in order, through them, as methodological helps, to get at and under- stand that which is anything but a state of con- sciousness. To him, however, who insists upon the _ fixed and final limitation of psychology, the state of consciousness is not the shape some fact takes from the exigency of investigation; it is literally _ the full fact itself. It is not an intervening term; it bounds the horizon. Here, then, the issue de- fines itself. I conceive that states of conscious- ness (and I hope you will take the phrase broadly enough to cover all the specific data of psy-§ chology) have no existence before the psychologist begins to work. He brings them into existence. What we are really after is the process of ex- perience, the way in which it arises and behaves. We want to know its course, its history, its laws. We want to know its various typical forms; how each originates; how it is related to others; the CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 249 part it plays in maintaining an inclusive, expand- ing, connected course of experience. Our problem as psychologists is to learn its modus operandi, its method. The paleontologist is again summoned to our aid. In a given district he finds a great number and variety of footprints. From these he goes to work to construct the structure and the life habits of the animals that made them. The tracks exist undoubtedly ; they are there; but yet he deals with them not as final existences but as signs, phe- nomena in the literal sense. Imagine the hearing that the critic would receive who should inform the paleontologist that he is transcending his field of scientific activity; that his concern is with foot- prints as such, aiming to describe each, to analyze it into its simplest forms, to compare the different kinds with one another so as to detect common ele- ments, and finally, thereby, to discover the laws of their arrangement in space! Yet the immediate data are footprints, and foot- prints only. The paleontologist does in a way do all these things that our imaginary critic is urging upon him. The difference is not that he arbitrarily lugs in other data; that he invents entities and faculties that are not there. The difference is in his standpoint. His interest is in the animals, and the data are treated in whatever way seems likely to serve this interest. So with the psycholo- 250 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE gist. He is continually and perforce occupied with minute and empirical investigation of special facts—states of consciousness, if you please. But _ these neither define nor exhaust his scientific prob- 'lem. They are his footprints, his clues through | which he places before himself the life-process he is - studying—with the further difference that his foot- prints are not after all given to him, but are de- veloped by his investigation.* The supposition that these states are somehow existent by themselves and in this existence provide the psychologist with ready-made material is just the supreme case of the “ psychological fallacy ”: the confusion of experience as it is to the one ex- periencing with what the psychologist makes out of it with his reflective analysis. The psychologist begins with certain operations, acts, functions as his data. If these fall out of * This is a fact not without its bearings upon the question of the nature and value of introspection. The objection that introspection “alters” the reality and hence is untrust- worthy, most writers dispose of by saying that, after all, it need not alter the reality so very much—not beyond repair— and that, moreover, memory assists in restoring the ruins. It would be simpler to admit the fact: that the purpose y of introspection is precisely to effect the right sort of altera- tion. If introspection should give us the original experi- ence again, we should just be living through the experience over again in direct fashion; as psychologists we should not be forwarded one bit. Reflection upon this obvious proposi- tion may bring to light various other matters worthy of note, ae CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 251 sight in the course of discussion, it is only because having been taken for granted, they remain to control the whole development of the inquiry, and to afford the sterling medium of redemption. Acts such as perceiving, remembering, intending, lov- ing give the points of departure; they alone are. concrete experiences. To understand these ex- periences, under what conditions they arise, and what effects they produce, analysis into states of consciousness occurs. And the modes of conscious- ness that are figured remain unarranged and un- important, save as they may be translated back into acts. To remember is to do ata as much as to shoe a horse, or to cherish a keepsake. To pro- pose, to observe, to be kindly affectioned, are terms of value, of practice, of operation; just as diges- tion, respiration, locomotion express functions, not observable “ objects.” But there is an object that may be described: lungs, stomach, leg-mus- cles, or whatever. Through the structure we pre- sent to ourselves the function; it appears laid out before us, spread forth in detail—objectified in a word. The anatomist who devotes himself to this detail may, if he please (and he probably does please to concentrate his devotion) ignore the function: to discover what is there, to analyze, to measure, to describe, gives him outlet enough. But nevertheless it is the function that fixed the 252 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE point of departure, that prescribed the problem and that set the limits, physical as well as intel- lectual, of subsequent investigation. Reference to ‘function makes the details discovered other than a jumble of incoherent trivialities. One might as well devote himself to the minute description of a square yard of desert soil were it not for this trans- lation. States of consciousness are the morphol- . ogy of certain functions." What is true of anal- ysis, of description, is true equally of classifica- tion. Knowing, willing, feeling, name states of consciousness not in terms of themselves, but in terms of acts, attitudes, found in experience.? ? Thus to divorce “structure psychology” from “ function psychology ” is to leave us without possibility of scientific + comprehension of function, while it deprives us of all standard of reference in selecting, observing, and explaining the structure. . *The following answer may fairly be anticipated: “ This is true of the operations cited, but only because complex processes have been selected. Such a term as ‘knowing’ does of course express a function involving a system of intricate references. But, for that very reason, we go back to the sensation which is the genuine type of the ‘state of consciousness’ as such, pure and unadulterate and un- sophisticated.” The point is large for a footnote, but the following considerations are instructive: (1) The same psychologist will go on to inform us that sensations, as we experience them, are networks of reference—they are perceptual, and more or less conceptual even. From which it would appear that whatever else they are or are not, the sensations, for which self-inclosed existence is claimed, are not states of consciousness. And (2) we are told that -— CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 2538 Explanation, even of an “‘ empirical sort” is as impossible as determination of a “ state ” and its classification, when we rigidly confine ourselves to modifications of consciousness as a self-existent. Sensations are always defined, classified, and ex- plained by reference to conditions which, according to the theory, are extraneous—sense-organs and stimuli. The whole physiological side assumes a ludicrously anomalous aspect on this _basis.*- While experimentation is retained, and even made much of, it is at the cost of logical coherence. 'To experiment with reference to a bare state of con- sciousness is a performance of which one cannot imagine the nature, to say nothing of doing it; while to experiment with reference to acts and the conditions of their occurrence is a natural and straightforward undertaking. Such simple proc- esses. as association are concretely inexplicable when these are reached by scientific abstraction in order to ac- count for complex forms. From which it would appear that they are hypothecated as products of interpretation and for purposes of further interpretation. Only the delu- sion that the more complex forms are just aggregates (in- stead of being acts, like seeing, hoping, etc.) prevents recognition of the point in question—that the “state of consciousness” is an instrument of inquiry or method- ological appliance, *On the other hand, if what we are trying to get at is just the course and procedure of experiencing, of course any consideration that helps distinguish and make com- prehensible that process is thoroughly pertinent. A 254 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE we assume states of consciousness as existences by themselves. As recent psychology testifies, we again have to resort to conditions that have no ‘place nor calling on the basis of the theory—the principle of habit, of neural action, or else some connection in the object.* 3 We have only to note that there are two oppos- ing schools in psychology to see in what an un- scientific status is the subject. We have only to consider that these two schools are the result of assuming states of consciousness as existences per se to locate the source of the scientific scandal. No matter what the topic, whether memory or association or attention or effort, the same dual- isms present themselves, the same necessity of choosing between two schools. One, lost in the dis- tinctions that it has developed, denies the func- tion because it can find objectively presented only states of consciousness. So it abrogates the func- tion, regarding it as a mere aggregate of such states, or as a purely external and factitious re- *It may avoid misunderstanding if I anticipate here a subsequent remark: that my point is not in the least that “states of consciousness” require some “ synthetic unity ” or faculty of substantial mind to effect their association. Quite the contrary; for this theory also admits the “ states of consciousness” as existences in themselves also. My contention is that the “state of consciousness” as such is always a methodological product, developed in the course and for the purposes of psychological analysis. eee CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 255 lation between them. The other school, recogniz- ing that this procedure explains away rather than explains, the values of experience, attempts to even up by declaring that certain functions are them- selves immediately given data of consciousness, ex- isting side by side with the “ states,” but indefi- nitely transcending them in worth, and appre- hended by some higher organ. So against the elementary contents and external associations of the analytic school in psychology, we have the complicated machinery of the intellectualist school, with its pure self-consciousness as a source of ulti- mate truths, its hierarchy of intuitions, its ready- made faculties. To be sure, these “ spiritual fac- ulties ” are now largely reduced to some one com- prehensive form—Apperception, or Will, or Atten- tion, or whatever the fashionable term may be. But the principle remains the same ; the assumption of a function as a given existent, distinguishable in itself and acting upon other existences—as if the functions digestion and vision were regarded as separate from organic structures, somehow act- ing upon them from the outside so as to bring co- operation and harmony into them!* This division into psychological schools is as reasonable as would be one of botanists into rootists and flowerists; of *The “functions” are in truth ordinary everyday acts and attitudes: seeing, smelling, talking, listening, remember- ing, hoping, loving, fearing. 256 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE those proclaiming the root to be the rudimentary and essential structure, and those asserting that since the function of seed-bearing is the main thing, the flower is really the controlling ‘ synthetic ” principle. Both sensationalist and intellectualist suppose that psychology has some special sphere of “reality ” or of experience marked off for it within which the data are just lying around, self- existent and ready-made, to be picked up and assorted as pebbles await the visitor on the beach. Both alike fail to recognize that the psychologist first has experience to deal with; the same experi- ence that the zoologist, geologist, chemist, mathe- matician, and historian deal with, and that what characterizes his specialty is not some data or ex- istences which he may call uniquely his own; but the problem raised—the problem of the course of the acts that constitute experiencing. Here psychology gets its revenge upon those who would rule it out of possession of important philo- sophical bearing. As a matter of fact, the larger part of the questions that are being discussed in current epistemology and -what is termed meta- physic of logic and ethic arise out of (and are hopelessly compromised by) this original assump- tion of “ consciousness as such ”—1in other words, are provoked by the exact reason that is given for denying to psychology any essential meaning for epistemology and metaphysic. Such is the CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 257 | irony of the situation. The epistemologist’s prob- lem is, indeed, usually put as the question of how the subject can so far “transcend” itself as to get valid assurance of the objective world. The very phraseology in which the problem is put re- veals the thoroughness of the psychologist’s re- venge. Just and only because experience has been reduced to “ states of consciousness”? as independ- ent existences, does the question of self-transcend- ence have any meaning. The entire epistemolog- ical industry is one—shall I say it—ofa Sisyphean nature. Mutatis mutandis, the same holds of the metaphysic of logic, ethic, and esthetic. In each . case, the basic problem has come to be how a mere state of consciousness can be the vehicle of a system of truth, of an objectively valid good, of beauty which is other than agreeable feeling. We may, in- deed, excuse the psychologist for not carrying on the special inquiries that are the business of log- ical, ethical, and esthetical philosophy ; but can we excuse ourselves for forcing his results into such a shape as to make philosophic problems so arbi- trary that they are soluble only by arbitrarily wrenching scientific facts? Undoubtedly we are between two fires. In plac- ing upon psychology the responsibility of discov- ering the method of experience, as a sequence of acts and passions, do we not destroy just that limitation to concrete detail which now constitutes RINT Pr Aine i, 258 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE it a science? Will not the psychologist be the first to repudiate this attempt to mix him up in matters philosophical? We need only to keep in mind the specific facts involved in the term Course or Process of Experience to avoid this danger. The immediate preoccupation of the psychologist is with very definite and empirical facts—questions like the limits of audition, of the origin of pitch, of the structure and conditions of the musical scale, etc. Just so the immediate affair of the geologist is with particular rock-structures, of the botanist with particular plants, and so on. But through the collection, description, location, classification of rocks the geologist is led to the splendid story of world-forming. The limited, fixed, and sepa- rate piece of work is dissolved away in the fluent and dynamic drama of the earth. So, the plant leads with inevitableness to the whole process of life and its evolution. In form, the botanist still studies the genus, the species, the plant—hardly, indeed, that ; rather the special parts, the structural elements, of the plant. In reality, he studies life itself; the structures are the indications, the signature through which he renders transparent the mystery of life growing in the changing world. It was doubtless necessary for the botanist to go through the Linnean period—the period of engagement with rigid detail and fixed classifications; of tear- CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 259 ing apart and piecing together; of throwing all emphasis upon peculiarities of number, size, and appearance of matured structure; of regarding change, growth, and function as external, more or less interesting, attachments to form. Examina- tion of this period is instructive; there is much in contemporary investigation and discussion that is almost unpleasantly reminiscent in its suggestive- ness. The psychologist should profit by the inter- vening history of science. The conception of evo-_ lution is not so much an additional law as it is a face-about. The fixed structure, the separate form, the isolated element, is henceforth at best a° mere stepping-stone to knowledge of process, and when not at its best, marks the end of comprehen- sion, and betokens failure to grasp the problem. With the change in standpoint from self-in- cluded existence to including process, from struc- tural unit of composition to controlling unity of function, from changeless form to movement in growth, the whole scheme of values is transformed. Faculties are definite directions of development; elements are products that are starting-points for new processes; bare facts are indices of. change; static conditions are modes of accomplished ad- justment. Not that the concrete, empirical phe- nomenon loses in worth, much less that unverifiable * metaphysical ” entities are impertinently intro- duced; but that our aim is the discovery of a 260 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE process of actions in its adaptations to circum- stance. If we apply this evolutionary logic in psychology, where shall we stop? Questions of limits of stimuli in a given sense, say hearing, are in reality questions of temporary arrests, adjust- ments marking the favorable equilibrium of the whole organism; they connect with the question of the use of sensation in general and auditory sensa- tions in particular for life-habits; of the origin and use of localized and distinguished perception ; and this, in turn, involves within itself the whole question of space and time recognition; the signi- ficance of the thing-and-quality experience, and so on. And when we are told that the question of the origin of space experience has nothing at all to do with the question of the nature and signifi- cance of the space experienced, the statement is simply evidence that the one who makes it is still at the static standpoint; he believes that things, that relations, have existence and significance apart from the particular conditions under which they come into experience, and apart from the special service rendered in those particular con- ditions. Of course, I am far from saying that every psy- chologist must make the whole journey. Each in- dividual may contract, as he pleases, for any sec- tion or subsection he prefers; and undoubtedly the well-being of the science is advanced by such divi- CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 261 sion of labor. But psychology goes over the whole ground from detecting every distinct act of ex- periencing, to seeing what need calls out the special organ fitted to cope with the situation, and discov- ering the machinery through which it operates to keep a-going the course of action. But, I shall be told, the wall that divides psy- chology from philosophy cannot be so easily treated as non-existent. Psychology is a matter of natural history, even though it may be admitted that it is the natural history of the course of ex- perience. But philosophy is a matter of values; of the criticism and justification of certain validi- ties. One deals, it is said, with genesis, with con- ditions of temporal origin and transition; the other with analysis, with eternal constitution. I shall have to repeat that just this rigid separation of _ genesis and analysis seems to me a survival from a pre-evolutionary, a pre-historic age. It indicates not so much an assured barrier between philosophy and psychology as the distance dividing philos- ophy from all science. For the lesson that mathematicians first learned, that physics and chemistry pondered over, in which the biological disciplines were finally tutored, is that sure and delicate analysis is possible only through the pa-t- tient study of conditions of origin and development. The method of analysis in mathematics is the method of construction. The experimental method — 262 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE is the method of making, of following the history of production; the term “ cause” that has (when taken-as an existent entity) so hung on the heels of science as to impede its progress, has universal meaning when read as condition of appearance in a process. And, as already intimated, the concép: tion of evolution is no more and no less the dis- covery of a general law of life than it is the gen- eralization of all scientific method. Everywhere analysis that cannot proceed by examining the suc- cessive stages of its subject, from its beginning up to its culmination, that cannot control this examination by discovering the conditions under which successive stages appear, is only prelimi- nary. It may further the invention of proper tools of inquiry, it may help define problems, it may serve to suggest valuable hypotheses. But as science it breathes an air already tainted. There is no way to sort out the results flowing from the subject-matter itself from those introduced by the assumptions and presumptions of our own reflec- tion. Not so with natural history when it is — worthy of its name. Here the analysis is the un- folding of the existence itself. Its distinctions are not pigeon-holes of our convenience; they are stakes that mark the parting of the ways in the process itself. Its classifications are not a grasp at factors resisting further analysis; they are the patient tracings of the paths pursued. Noth- CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE — 263 ing is more out of date than to suppose that ) interest in genesis is interest in reducing higher | forms to cruder ones: it is interest in locating the / exact and objective conditions under which a given fact appears, and in relation to which ac cordingly it has its meaning. Nothing is more naive than to suppose that in pursuing “ natural history” (term of scorn in which yet resides the dignity of the world-drama) we simply learn something of the temporal conditions under which a given value appears, while its own eternal essential quality remains as opaque as before. Na- ture knows no such divorce of quality and circum- stance. Things come when they are wanted and as they are wanted; their quality is precisely the response they give to the conditions that call for them, while the furtherance they afford to the movement of their whole is their meaning. The severance of analysis and genesis, instead of serv- ing as a ready-made test by which to try out the empirical, temporal events of psychology from the rational abiding constitution of philosophy, is a brand of philosophic dualism: the supposition ‘that values are externally obtruded and statically set in irrelevant rubbish. There are those who will admit that “ states of consciousness ” are but the cross-sections of flow of behavior, arrested for inspection, made in order that we may reconstruct experience in its life- 264 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE history. Yet in the knowledge of the course and method of our experience, they will hold that we are far from the domain proper of philosophy. Experience, they say, is just the historic achieve- ment of finite individuals; it tells the tale of ap- proach to the treasures of truth, of partial vic- tory, but larger defeat, in laying hold- of the treasure. But, they say, reality is not the path to reality, and record of devious wanderings in the path is hardly a safe account of the goal. Psychol- ogy, in other words, may tell us something of how we mortals lay hold of the world of things and truths; of how we appropriate and assimilate its contents; and of how we react. It may trace the issues of such approaches and apprehensions upon the course of our own individual destinies. But it cannot wisely ignore nor sanely deny the distinc- tion between these individual strivings and achieve- ments, and the “ Reality ” that subsists and sup- ports its own structure outside these finite futilities. The processes by which we turn over The Reality into terms of our fragmentary unconcluded, in- conclusive experiences are so extrinsic to the Real- ity itself as to have no revealing power with refer- ence to it. There is the ordo ad universum, the subject of philosophy; there is the ordo ad m- dividuum, the subject of psychology. Some such assumption as this lies latent, I am convinced, in all forswearings of the kinship of CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 265 psychology and philosophy. Two conceptions hang together. The opinion that psychology is an account only and finally of states of consciousness, and therefore can throw no light upon the objects with which philosophy deals, is twin to the doctrine that the whole conscious life of the individual is not organic to the world. The philosophic basis and scope of this doctrine lie beyond examination here. But even in passing one cannot avoid re- marking that the doctrine is almost never consist- ently held; the doctrine logically carried out leads so directly to intellectual and moral scepticism that , the theory usually prefers to work in the dark background as a disposition and temper of thought rather than to make a frank statement of itself. Even in the half-hearted expositions of the process of human experience as something merely annexed to the reality of the universe, we are brought face to face to the consideration with which we set out: the dependence of theories of the individual upon the position at a given time of the individual prac- tical and social. The doctrine of the acci- dental, futile, transitory significance of the indi- vidual’s experience as compared with eternal real- ities ; the notion that at best the individual is simply realizing for and in himself what already has fixed completeness in itself is congruous only with a certain intellectual and political scheme and must modify itself as that shifts. When such re- / ff 266 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE arrangement comes, our estimate of the nature and importance of psychology will mirror the change. _ When man’s command of the methods that con- trol action was precarious and disturbed; when the tools that subject the world of things and forces to use and operation were rare and clumsy, it was unavoidable that the individual should sub- mit his perception and purpose blankly to the blank reality beyond. Under such circumstances, external authority must reign; the belief that hu- man experience in itself is approximate, not in- trinsic, is inevitable. Under such circumstances, reference to the individual, to the subject, is a re- sort only for explaining error, illusion, and uncer- tainty. The necessity of external control and ex- ternal redemption of experience reports itself in a low valuation of the self, and of all the factors and phases of experience that spring from the self. That the psychology of medievalism should appear only as a portion of its theology of sin and salva- tion is as obvious as that the psychology of the Greeks should be a chapter of cosmology. As against all this, the assertion is ventured that psychology, supplying us with knowledge of the behavior of experience, is a conception of de- mocracy. Its postulate is that since experience fulfils itself in individuals, since it administers itself through their instrumentality, the account of CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE 267 the course and method of this achievement is a significant and indispensable affair. - Democracy is possible only because of a change in intellectual conditions. It implies tools for get- ting at truth in detail, and day by day, as we go along. Only such possession justifies the surrender of fixed, all-embracing principles to which, as uni- versals, all particulars and individuals are subject for valuation and regulation. Without such pos- session, it is only the courage of the fool that would undertake the venture to which democracy has committed itself—the ordering of life in re-| sponse to the needs of the moment in accordance with the ascertained truth of the moment. Modern life involves the deification of the here and the now; of the specific, the particular, the unique, that which happens once and has no measure of value save such as it brings with itself. Such dei- fication is monstrous fetishism, unless the deity be there; unless the universal lives, moves, and has its SLES — = being in experience as individualized. This con- *This is perhaps a suitable moment to allude to the ab- sence, in this discussion, of reference to what is some- times termed rational psychology—the assumption of a separate, substantialized ego, soul, or whatever, existing side by side with particular experiences and “ states of con- sciousness,” acting upon them and acted upon by them. In ignoring this and confining myself to the “states of con- sciousness” theory and the “natural history” theory, I may appear not only to have unduly narrowed the concerns 258 CONSCIOUSNESS. AND EXPERIENCE viction of the value of the individualized finds its further expression in psychology, which undertakes to show how this individualization proceeds, and in ‘what aspect it presents itself. Of course, such a conception means something for philosophy as well as for psychology ; possibly it involves for philosophy the larger measure of transformation. It involves surrender of any claim on the part of philosophy to be the sole source of some truths and the exclusive guardian of some | at issue, but to have weakened my own point, as this doc- trine seems to offer a special vantage ground whence to defend the close relationship of psychology and philosophy. _The “narrowing,” if such it be, will have to pass—from limits of time and other matters. But the other point I cannot concede. The independently existing soul restricts and degrades individuality, making of it a separate thing outside of the full flow of things, alien to things experi- enced and consequently in either mechanical or miraculous relations to them. It is vitiated by just the quality already objected to—that psychology has a separate piece of reality apportioned to it, instead of occupying itself with the manifestation and operation of any and all existences in reference to concrete action. From this point of view, the “states of consciousness” attitude is a much more hopeful and fruitful one. It ignores certain considerations, to be sure; and when it turns its ignoring into denial, it leaves us with curious hieroglyphics. But after all, there is a key; these symbols can be read; they may be translated into terms of the course of experience. When thus translated, selfhood, individuality, is neither wiped out nor set up as a miraculous and foreign entity; it is seen as the unity of reference and function involved in all things when fully experienced—the pivot about which they turn. CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE — 269 values. It means that philosophy be a method; not an assurance company, nor a knight errant. It means an alignment with science. Philosophy may not be sacrificed to the partial and superficial — clamor of that which sometimes officiously and pre- tentiously exhibits itself as Science. But there is a sense in which philosophy must go to school to the sciences; must have no data save such as it receives at their hands; and be hospitable to no method of inquiry or reflection not akin to those in daily use among the sciences. As long as it claims for itself special territory of fact, or peculiar modes of access to truth, so long must it occupy a dubious position. Yet this claim it has to make until psychology comes to its own. ‘There is some- thing in experience, something in things, which the physical and the biological sciences do not touch; something, moreover, which is not just more ex- periences or more existences; but without which their materials are inexperienced, unrealized. Such sciences deal only with what might be experienced ; with the content of experience, provided and as- sumed there be experience. It is psychology which tells us how this possible experience loses its barely hypothetical character, and is stamped with cate- gorical unquestioned experiencedness; how, in a word, it becomes here and now in some uniquely individualized life. Here is the necessary transi- tion of science into philosophy; a passage that 270 CONSCIOUSNESS AND EXPERIENCE carries the verified and solid body of the one into the large and free form of the other. [ Nore: I have let this paper stand much as written, though ‘now conscious that much more is crowded into it than could properly be presented in one paper. The drift of the ten years from ’99 to ’09 has made, I venture to believe, for in- creased clearness in the main positions of the paper: The revival of a naturalistic realism, the denial of the existence of “consciousness,” the development of functional and dynamic psychology (accompanied by aversion to interpre- aye tation of functions as faculties of a soul-substance)—all of these tendencies are sympathetic with the aim of the paper. There is another reason for letting it stand: the new func- tional and pragmatic empiricism proffered in this volume has been constantly objected to on the ground that its con- ceptions of knowledge and verification lead only to sub- jectivism and solipsism. The paper may indicate that the identification of experience with bare states of consciousness represents the standpoint of the critic, not of the empiricism criticised, and that it is for him, not for me, to fear the subjective implications of such a position. The paper also clearly raises the question as to how far the isolation of “ consciousness ” from nature and social life, which charac- terizes the procedure of many psychologists of to-day, is responsible for keeping alive quite unreal problems in phi- losophy.] THE SIGNIFICANCE OF THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE * T is now something over a century since Kant called upon philosophers to cease their discus- sion regarding the nature of the world and the principles of existence until they had arrived at some conclusion regarding the nature of the know- ‘ing process. But students of philosophy know that Kant formulated the question “ how knowl- edge is possible” rather than created it. As mat- ter of fact, reflective thought for two centuries before Kant had been principally interested in just this problem, although it had not generalized its own interest. Kant brought to consciousness the controlling motive. ‘The discussion, both in Kant himself and in his successors, often seems scholas- tic, lost in useless subtlety, scholastic argument, and technical distinctions. Within the last decade in particular there have been signs of a growing weariness as to epistemology, and a tendency to * Delivered before the Philosophical Club of the Univer- \ sity of Michigan, in the winter of 1897, and reprinted with slight change from a monograph in the “ University of Chi- cago Contributions to Philosophy,” 1897. a7 72 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE turn away to more fertile fields. The interest shows signs of exhaustion. Students of philosophy will recognize what I mean when I say that this growing conviction of futility and consequent distaste are associated with the outcome of the famous dictum of Kant, that | perception without conception is blind, while con- ception without perception is empty. The whole ‘course of reflection since Kant’s time has tended to justify this remark. The sensationalist and the rationalist have worked themselves out. Pretty much all students are convinced that we can reduce knowledge neither to a set of associated sensations, nor yet to a purely rational system of relations of thought. Knowledge is judgment, and judgment -|requires both a material of sense perception and an ordering, regulating principle, reason; so much seems certain, but we do not get apy further. Sensation and thought themselves seem to stand out more rigidly opposed to each other in their own natures than ever. Why both are necessary, ,and how two such opposéd factors codperate in bringing about the unified result of science, be- comes more and more of a mystery. It is the continual running up against this situation which accounts for the flagging of interest and the desire to direct energy where it will have more outcome. This situation creates a condition favorable to taking stock of the question as it stands; to in- - ~~ ~ THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 273 quiring what this interest, prolonged for over three centuries, in the possibility and nature of knowl- edge, stands for; what the conviction as to the necessity of the union of sensation and thought, together with the inability to reach conclusions re-_ garding the nature of the union, signifies. I propose then to raise this evening precisely this question: What is the meaning of the problem of knowledge? What is its meaning, not simply for reflective philosophy or in terms of epistemol- ogy itself, but what is its meaning in the historical movement of humanity and as a part of a larger and more comprehensive experience? My thesis is perhaps sufficiently indicated in the mere taking of this point of view. It implies that the abstract- ness of the discussion of knowledge, its remoteness from everyday experience, is one of form, rather than of substance. It implies that the problem of knowledge is not a problem that has its origin, its value, or its destiny within itself. The problem is one which social life, the organized practice of man- kind, has had to face. The seemingly technical and abstruse discussion of the philosophers results from the formulation and statement of the question. I suggest that the problem of the possibility of knowledge is but an aspect of the question of the relation of knowing to acting, of theory to prac- tice. The distinctions which the philosophers raise, the oppositions which they erect, the weary tread- 274 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE mill which they pursue between sensation and thought, subject and object, mind and matter, are not invented ad hoc, but are simply the concise re- ports and condensed formula of points of view and practical conflicts having their source in the very nature of modern life, conflicts which must be met and solved if modern life is to go on its way un- troubled, with clear consciousness of what it is about. As the philosopher has received his prob- lem from the world of action, so he must return his account there for auditing and liquidation. More especially, I suggest that the tendency of all the points at issue to precipitate in the opposi- tion of sensationalism and rationalism is due to the fact that sensation and reason stand for the two yforces contending for mastery in social life: the radical and the conservative. The reason that the contest does not end, the reason for the necessity of the combination of the two in the resultant state- _ ment, is that both factors are necessary in action; one stands for stimulus, for initiative ; the other for ‘ control, for direction. I cannot hope, in the time at my command this evening, to justify these wide and sweeping asser- tions regarding either the origin, the work, or the final destiny of philosophic reflection. I simply hope, by reference to some of the chief periods of the development of philosophy, to illustrate to you something of what I mean. THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 275 At the outset we take a long scope in our survey and present to ourselves the epoch when philosophy was still consciously, and not simply by implica- tion, human, when reflective thought had not devel- oped its own technique of method, and was in no danger of being caught in its own machinery—the time of Socrates. What does the assertion of Socrates that an unexamined life is not one fit to be led by man; what does his injunction “ Know thyself? mean? It means that the corporate motives and guarantees of conduct are breaking down. We have got away from the time when the individual could both regulate and justify his course of life by reference to the ideals incarnate in the habits of the community of which he is a member. ‘The time of direct and therefore uncon- scious union with corporate life, finding therein stimuli, codes, and values, has departed. The de- velopment of industry and commerce, of war and politics, has brought face to face communities with different aims and diverse habits; the development of myth and animism into crude but genuine scien- tific observation and imagination has transformed the physical widening of the horizon, brought about. by commerce and intercourse, into an in- tellectual and moral expansion. The old supports fail precisely at the time when they are most needed —hbefore a widening and more complex scene of action. Where, then, shall the agent of action 276 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE turn? The “ Know thyself ” of Socrates is the re- ply to the practical problem which confronted _Athens in his day. Investigation into the true ends and worths of human life, sifting and test- ing of all competing ends, the discovery of a method which should validate the genuine and dismiss the spurious, had henceforth to do for man what consolidated and incorporate custom had hitherto presented as a free and precious gift. With Socrates the question is as direct and prac- tical as the question of making one’s living or of governing the state; it is indeed the same question put in its general form. It is a question that the flute player, the cobbler, and the politician must face no more and no less than the reflective philos- opher. The question is addressed by Socrates to every individual and to every group with which he comes in contact. Because the question is practi- cal it is individual and direct. It is a question which every one must face and answer for himself, just as in the Protestant scheme every individual must face and solve for himself the question of his final destiny. Yet the very attitude of Socrates carried with it the elements of its own destruction. Socrates could only raise the question, or rather demand of every individual that he raise it for himself. Of the answer he declared himself to be as ignorant as THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 277 was any one. The result could be only a shifting of the center of interest. If the question is so all- important, and yet the wisest of all men must con- fess that he only knows his own ignorance as to its answer, the inevitable point of further considera- tion is the discovery of a method which shall enable the question to be answered. This is the signifi- cance of Plato. The problem is the absolutely in- evitable outgrowth of the Socratic position; and yet it carried with it just as inevitably the separa- tion of philosopher from shoemaker and statesman, ‘and the relegation of theory to a position remote for the time being from conduct. If the Socratic command, “ Know thyself,” runs against the dead wall of inability to conduct this knowledge, some one must take upon himself the discovery of how the requisite knowledge may be obtained. A new profession is born, that of the thinker. At this time the means, the discovery of how the aims and worths of the self may be known and measured, becomes, for this class, an end in itself. Theory is ultimately to be applied to prac- tice ; but in the meantime the theory must be worked out as theory or else no application. This repre- sents the peculiar equilibrium and the peculiar point of contradiction in the Platonic system. All philosophy is simply for the sake of the organiza- | tion and regulation of social life; and yet the phi- | losophers must be a class by themselves, working 278 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE out their peculiar problems with their own partic- ular tools. : With Aristotle the attempted balance failed. ‘Social life is disintegrating beyond the point of hope of a successful reorganization, and thinking is becoming a fascinating pursuit for its own sake. The world of practice is now the world of com- promise and of adjustment. It is relative to par- tial aims and finite agents. The sphere of abso- > lute and enduring truth and value can be reached only in and through thought. The one who acts compromises himself with the animal desire that inspires his action and with the alien material that forms. its stuff. In two short generations the divorce of philosophy from life, the isolation of reflective theory from practical conduct, has com- pleted itself. So great is the irony of history that this sudden and effective outcome was the result of the attempt to make thought the instrument of action, and action the manifestation of truth reached by thinking. But this statement must not be taken too liter- ally. It is impossible that men should really sepa- rate their ideas from their acts. If we look ahead a few centuries we find that the philosophy of Plato and Aristotle has accomplished, in an in- direct and unconscious way, what perhaps it could never have effected by the more immediate and practical method of Socrates. Philosophy became THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 279 an organ of vision, an instrument of interpreta- tion ; it furnished the medium through which the world was seen and the course of life estimated. Philosophy died as philosophy, to rise as the set and bent of the human mind. Through a thousand and. devious and roundabout channels, the thoughts of the philosophers filtered through the strata of human consciousness and conduct. Through the teachings of grammarians, rhetoricians, and a va- riety of educational schools, they were spread in diluted form through the whole Roman Empire and were again precipitated in the common forms of speech. Through the earnestness of the moral propaganda of the Stoics they became the working rules of life for the more strenuous and earnest spirits. Through the speculations of the Sceptics and Epicureans they became the chief reliance and consolation of a large number of highly cultured individuals amid social turmoil and political dis- integration. All these influences and many more finally summed themselves up in the two great media through which Greek philosophy finally fixed the intellectual horizon of man, determined . the values of its perspective, and meted out the boundaries and divisions of the scene of human action. These two influences were the development of | Christian theology and moral theory, and the or- ganization of the system of Roman jurisprudence. 280 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE There is perhaps no more fascinating chapter in the history of humanity than the slow and tortu- ous processes by which the ideas set in motion by ‘that Athenian citizen who faced death as serenely as he conversed with a friend, finally became the intellectually organizing centers of the two great movements that bridge the span between ancient civilization and modern. As the personal and im- mediate force and enthusiasm of the movement initiated by Jesus began to grow fainter and the commanding influence of his own personality com- menced to dim, the ideas of the world and of life, of God and of man, elaborated in Greek philosophy, served to transform moral enthusiasm _ and personal devotion to the redemption of hu- ~ manity, into a splendid and coherent view of the universe ; a view that resisted ‘all disintegrating in- fluences and gathered into itself the permanent ideas and progressive ideals thus far developed in the history of man. | We have only a faint idea of how ie was ac- complished, or of the thoroughness of the work done. We have perhaps even more inadequate conceptions of the great organizing and central- izing work done by Greek thought in the political sphere. When the military and administrative genius of Rome brought the whole world in sub- jection to itself, the most pressing of practical problems was to give unity of practical aim and THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 281 harmony of working machinery to the vast and confused mass of local custom and tradition, re- ligious, social, economic, and intellectual, as well as political. In this juncture the great adminis- trators and lawyers of Rome seized with avidity upon the results of the intellectual analysis of so- cial and political relations elaborated in Greek philosophy. Caring naught for these results in their reflective and theoretical character, they saw in them the possible instrument of introducing or- 'der into chaos and of transforming the confused and conflicting medley of practice and opinion into a harmonious social structure. Roman law, that formed the vertebral column of civilization for a thousand years, and which articulated the outer order of life as_ distinctly as Christianity controlled the inner, was the outcome. Thought was once more in unity with action, philosophy had become the instrument of conduct. Mr. Bosanquet makes the pregnant remark “ that the weakness of medieval science and philosophy are connected rather with excess of practice than with excess of theory. The subordination of phi- losophy to theology is a subordination of science to a formulated conception of human welfare. Its essence is present, not wherever there is metaphys- ics but wherever the spirit of truth is subordinated to any preconceived practical intent.” (‘* His- tory of Esthetics,” p. 146.) Vv. jon 282 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE Once more the irony of history displays itself. Thought has become practical, it has become the regulator of individual conduct and social organi- zation, but at the expense of its own freedom and power. The defining characteristic of medieval- ism in state and in church, in political and spiritual life, is that truth presents itself to the individual only through the medium of organized authority. There was a historical necessity on the external as well as the internal side. We have not the re- motest way of imagining what the outcome would finally have been if, at the time when the intellectual structure of the Christian church and the legal structure of the Roman Empire had got themselves thoroughly organized, the barbarians had not made their inroads and seized upon all this accumulated and consolidated wealth as their own legitimate prey. But this was what did happen. As a re- sult, truths originally developed by the freest possible criticism and investigation became exter- nal, and imposed themselves upon the mass of in- dividuals by the mere weight of authoritative law. The external, transcendental, and super- natural character of spiritual truth and of social control during the Middle Ages is naught but the mirror, in consciousness, of the relation existing between the eager, greedy, undisciplined horde of barbarians on one side, and the concentrated achievements of ancient civilization on the other. — THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 283 There was no way out save that the keen barbarian whet his appetite upon the rich banquet spread before him. But there was equally no way out so far as the continuity of civilization was concerned save that the very fullness and richness of this banquet set limits to the appetite, and finally, when assimilated and digested, it be transformed into the flesh and blood, the muscles and sinew of him who sat at the feast. Thus the barbarian ceased to be a barbarian and a new civilization arose. But the time came when the work of absorption was fairly complete. The northern barbarians had eaten the food and drunk the wine of Greco- Roman civilization. The authoritative truth em- bodied in medieval state and church succeeded, in principle, in disciplining the untrained masses. Its very success issued its own death warrant. To say that it had succeeded means that the new people had finally eaten their way into the heart of the ideas offered them, had got from them what they wanted, and were henceforth prepared to go their own way and make their own living. Here a new rhythm of the movement of thought and action begins to show itself. The beginning of this change in the swing of jthought and action forms the transition from the Middle Ages to the modern times. It is the epoch of the Renaissance. The individual comes to a new birth and asserts his own individuality and 284 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE demands his own rights in the way of feeling, do- ing, and knowing for himself. Science, art, re- . ligion, political life, must all be made over on the basis of recognizing the claims of the individual. Pardon me these commonplaces, but they are necessary to the course of the argument. By his- toric fallacy we often suppose, or imagine that we suppose, that the individual had been present as a possible center of action all through the Middle Ages, but through some external and arbitrary in- terference had been weighted down by political and intellectual despotism. All this inverts the true order of the case. The very possibility of the individual making such unlimited demands for him- self, claiming to be the legitimate center of all ,action and standard for all organization, was de- ' pendent, as I have already indicated, upon the in- tervening medievalism. Save as having passed through this period of tremendous discipline, and having gradually worked over into his own habits and purposes the truths embodied in the church and state that controlled his conduct, the individ- ual could be only a source of disorder and a dis- turber of civilization. The very maintenance of the spiritual welfare of mankind was bound up in the extent to which the claim of truth and reality to be universal and objective, far above all indi- vidual feeling and thought, could make itself valid. The logical realism and universalism of scholastic ee THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 285 philosophy simply reflect the actual subjection of the individual to that associated and corporate life which, in conserving the past, provided the princi- ple of control. : But the eager, hungry barbarian was there, im- plicated in this universalism. He must be active in receiving and in absorbing the truth authorita- tively doled out to him. Even the most rigid forms of medieval Christianity could not avoid postulat- ing the individual will as having a certain initiative with reference to its own salvation. The impulses, the appetite, the instinct of the individual were all assumed in medieval morals, religion, and politics. The imagined medieval tyranny took them for granted as completely as does the modern herald of liberty and equality. But the medieval civil- ization knew that the time had not come when these appetites and impulses could be trusted to work themselves out. They must be controlled by the incorporate truths inherited from Athens and Rome. — The very logic of the relationship, however, re- quired that the time come when the individual: makes his own the objective and universal truths. He is now the incorporation of truth. He now has ) the control as well as the stimulus of action within himself. He is the standard and the end, as well as the initiator and the effective force of execution. Just because the authoritative truth of medieval- 286 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE ism has succeeded, has fulfilled its function, the individual can begin to assert himself. Contrast this critical period, finding its expres- "sion equally in the art of the Renaissance, the re- vival of learning, the Protestant Reformation, and political democracy, with Athens in the time of Socrates. Then individuals felt their own social life disintegrated, dissolving under their very feet. The problem was how the value of that social life was to be maintained against the external and in- ternal forces that were threatening it. The prob- lem was on the side neither of the individual nor of progress ; save as the individual was seen to be an intervening instrument in the reconstruction of the social unity. But with the individual of the four- teenth century, it was not his own intimate com- munity life which was slipping away from him. It was an alien and remote life which had finally be- come his own; which had passed over into his own inner being. ‘The problem was not how a unity of social life should be conserved, but what the in- ‘dividual should do with the wealth of resources of which he found himself the rightful heir and ad- ministrator. The problem looked out upon the future, not back to the past. It was how to create a new order, both of modes of individual conduct and forms of social life that should be the appro- priate manifestations of the vigorous and richly endowed individual. a THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 287 Hence the conception of progress as a rul- ing idea; the conception of the individual as the source and standard of rights ; and the problem of knowledge, were all born together. Given the freed individual, who feels called upon to create a new heaven and a new earth, and who feels himself , gifted with the power to perform the task to which he is called:—and the demand for science, for a method of discovering and verifying truth, becomes imperious. The individual is henceforth to supply control, law, and not simply stimulation and initia- tion. What does this mean but that instead of any longer receiving or assimilating truth, he is now to search for and create it? Having no longer the truth imposed by authority to rely upon, there is no resource save to secure the authority of truth. The possibility of getting at and utiliz- ing this truth becomes therefore the underlying and conditioning problem of modern life. Strange as it may sound, the question which was formulated | by Kant as that of the possibility of knowledge, is the fundamental political problem of modern life. Science and metaphysics or philosophy, though seeming often to be at war, with their respective adherents often throwing jibes and slurs at each other, are really the most intimate allies. The philosophic movement is simply the coming to con- sciousness of this claim of the individual to be able oe = 288 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE to discover and verify truth for himself, and thereby not only to direct his own conduct, but to become an influential and decisive factor in the or- ganization of life itself. Modern philosophy is the formulation of this creed, both in general and in its more specific implications. We often forget that the technical problem “ how knowledge is pos- sible,” also means “ how knowledge is possible ” ; how, that is, shall the individual be able to back himself up by truth which has no authority save that of its own intrinsic truthfulness. Science, on the other hand, is simply this general faith or creed asserting itself in detail; it is the practical faith at work engaged in subjugating the foreign terri- tory of ignorance and falsehood step by step. If the ultimate outcome depends upon this detailed and concrete work, we must not forget that the earnestness and courage, as well as the intelligence and clearness with which the task has been under- taken, have depended largely upon the wider, even if vaguer, operation of philosophy. But the student of philosophy knows more than that the problem of knowledge has been with in- creasing urgency and definiteness the persistent and comprehensive problem. So conscious is he of the two opposed theories regarding the nature of science, that he often forgets the underlying bond of unity of which we have been speaking. These two opposing schools are those which we THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 289 know as the sensationalist and the intellectualist, the empiricist and the rationalist. Admitting that the dominance of the question of the possibility and nature of knowledge is at bottom a funda- mental question of practice and of social direc- tion, is this distinction anything more than the clash of scholastic opinions, a rivalry of ideas meaningless for conduct? I think it is. Having made so many sweeping assertions I must venture one more. Fanciful and forced as it may seem, I would say that the sensa- tional and empirical schools represent in conscious and reflective form the continuation of the princi- ple of the northern and barbarian side of medieval life; while the intellectualist and the rationalist stand for the conscious elaboration of the principle involved in the Greco-Roman tradition. Once more, as I cannot hope to prove, let me expand and illustrate. The sensationalist has staked himself upon the possibility of explaining and justifying knowledge by conceiving it as the { grouping and combination of the qualities directly given us in sensation. The special reasons ad- vanced in support of this position are sufficiently technical and remote. But the motive which has kept the sensationalist at work, which animated Hobbes and Locke, Hume and John Stuart Mill, Voltaire and Diderot, was a human not a scholastic one. It was the belief that only in sensation do eo —s 290 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE we get any personal contact with reality, and | hence, any genuine guarantee of vital truth. Thought is pale, and remote from the concrete stuff of knowledge and experience. It only formu- lates and duplicates ; it only divides and recombines that fullness of vivid reality got directly and at first hand in sense experience. Reason, compared with sense, is indirect, emasculate, and faded. Moreover, reason and thought in their very generality seem to lie beyond and outside the in- dividual. In this remoteness, when they claim any final value, they violate the very first principle of the modern consciousness. What is the distin- guishing characteristic of modern life, unless it be precisely that the individual shall not simply get, , and reason about, truth in the abstract, but shall make it his own in the most intimate and personal way? He has not only to know the truth in the sense of knowing about it, but he must feel it. What is sensation but the answer to this demand for the most individual and intimate contact with reality? Show me a sensationalist and I will show you not only one who believes that he is on the .side of concreteness and definiteness, as against ‘washed-out abstractions and misty general no- / tions: but also one who believes that he is identified with the cause of the individual as distinct from ' that of external authority. We have only to go to our Locke and our Mill to see that opposition THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 291 to the innate and the a priori was felt to be oppo- sition to the deification of hereditary prejudice and to the reception of ideas without examination or criticism. Personal contact with reality through sensation seemed to be the only safeguard from opinions which, while masquerading in the guise of | absolute and eternal truth, were in reality but the _ prejudices of the past become so ingrained as to insist upon being standards of truth and action. Positively as well as negatively, the sensational- _ ists have felt themselves to represent the side of progress. In its supposed eternal character, a general notion stands ready made, fixed forever, without reference to time, without the possibility of change or diversity. As distinct from this, the sensation represents the never-failing eruption of the new. It is the novel, the unexpected, that which cannot be reasoned out in eternal formula, but must be hit upon in the ever-changing flow of our experience. It thus represents stimulation, excitation, momentum onwards. It gives a con- stant protest against the assumption of any theory or belief to possess finality; and it supplies the ‘ever-renewed presentation of material out of which to build up new objects and new laws. The sensationalist appears to have a good case. He stands for vividness and definiteness against abstraction; for the engagement of the individual in experience as against the remote and general 292 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE thought about experience; and for progress and for variety against the eternal fixed monotony of the concept. But what says the rationalist? What value has experience, he inquires, if it is sim- ply a chaos of disintegrated and floating débris? What is the worth of personality and individuality when they are reduced to crudity of brute feeling and sheer intensity of impulsive reaction? What is there left in progress that we should desire it, when it has become a mere unregulated flux of transitory sensations, coming and going without reasonable motivation or rational purpose? Thus the intellectualist has endeavored to frame / the structure of knowledge as a well-ordered econ- omy, where reason is sovereign, where the perma- nent is the standard of reference for the changing, and where the individual may always escape from his own mere individuality and find support and reinforcement in a system of relations that lies outside of and yet gives validity to his own passing states of consciousness. Thus the rationalists hold that we must find in a universal intelligence a source of truth and guarantee of value that is sought in vain in the confused and flowing mass of sensations. 3 The rationalist, in making the concept or gen- eral idea the all-important thing in knowledge, be- \ eves himself to be asserting the interests of order as against destructive caprice and the license of ue THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 293 momentary whim. He finds that his cause is bound up with that of the discovery of truth as the necessary instrument and method for action. Only by reference to the general and the rational can the individual find perspective, secure direc- tion for his appetites and impulses, and escape from the uncontrolled and ruinous reactions of his own immediate tendency. The concept, once more, in its very generality, in its elevation above the intensities and conflicts of momentary passions and interests, is the conserver of the experience of the past. It is the wisdom of the past put into capitalized and funded form to enable the individual to get away from the stress and competition of the needs of the passing mo- ment. It marks the difference between barbarism and civilization, between continuity and disintegra- tion, between the sequence of tradition that is the necessity of intelligent thought and action, and the random and confused excitation of the hour. When we thus consider not the details of the positions of the sensationalist and rationalist, but the motives that have induced them to assume these positions, we discover what is meant in saying that the question is still a practical, a social one, and that the two schools stand for certain one- sided factors of social life. If we have on one side the demand for freedom, for personal initiation into experience, for variety and progress, we have 294 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE on the other side the demand for general order, for continuous and organized unity, for the con- ‘servation of the dearly bought resources of the past. This is what I mean by saying that the sensationalist abstracts in conscious form the position and tendency of the Germanic element in modern civilization, the factor of appetite and im- pulse, of keen enjoyment and satisfaction, of stim- ulus and initiative. Just so the rationalist erects _ into conscious abstraction the principle of the ' Greco-Roman world, that of control, of system, of order and authority. That the principles of freedom and order, of past and future, or conservation and progress, of incitement to action and control of that incitation, are correlative, I shall not stop to argue. It may be worth while, however, to point out that exactly the same correlative and mutually implicating con- nection exists between sensationalism and rational- -ism, considered as philosophical accounts of the origin and nature of knowledge. The strength of each school lies in the weakness | of its opponent. The more the sensationalist ap- | pears to succeed in reducing knowledge to the as- sociations of sensation, the more he creates a de- mand for thought to introduce background and relationship. The more consistent the sensational- ist, the more openly he reveals the sensation in its own nakedness crying aloud for a clothing of THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 295 | value and meaning which must be borrowed from —_ reflective and rational interpretation. On the other hand, the more reason and the system of relations that make up the functioning of reason are magnified, the more is felt the need of sensa- tion to bring reason into some fruitful contact with the materials of experience. Reason must have the stimulus of this contact in order to be incited to its work and to get materials to operate with. The cause, then, why neither school can come to rest in itself is precisely that each ab- stracts one essential factor of conduct. This suggests, finally, that the next move in philosophy is precisely to transfer attention from the details of the position assumed, and the argu- ments used in these two schools, to the practical motives that have unconsciously controlled the discussion. The positions have been sufficiently elaborated. Within the past one hundred years, within especially the last generation, each has suc- . ceeded in fully stating its case. The result, if we remain at this point, is practically a deadlock. Each can make out its case against the other. To stop at such a point is a patent absurdity. If we are to get out of the cul-de-sac it must be by bring- ing into consciousness the tacit reference to_ action | that all the time has been the controlling factor. In a word, another great rhythmic movement is seen to be approaching its end. The demand for ~rer 296 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE science and philosophy was the demand for truth and a sure standard of truth which the new-born | _ individual might employ in his efforts to build up me a new world to afford free scope to the powers stirring within him. The urgency and acuteness of this demand caused, for the time being, the transfer of attention from the nature of practice to that of knowledge. The highly theoretical and abstract character of modern epistemology, com- bined with the fact that this highly abstract and theoretic problem has continuously engaged the attention of thought for more than three centuries, is, to my mind, proof positive that the question of knowledge was for the time being the point in which the question of practice centered, and through which it must find outlet and solution. We return, then, to our opening problem: the meaning of the question of the possibility of knowl- edge raised by Kant a century ago, and of his assertion that sensation without thought is blind, thought without sensation empty. Once more I recall to the student of philosophy how this asser- tion of Kant has haunted and determined the course of philosophy in the intervening years—how his solution at once seems inevitable and unsatisfac- tory. It is inevitable in that no one can fairly deny that both sense and reason are implicated in every fruitful and significant statement of the world; unconvincing because we are after all left THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 297 . with these two opposed things still at war with ' each other, plus the miracle of their final combina- tion. When I say that the only way out is to place the whole modern industry of epistemology in relation __ to the conditions that gave it birth and the func- / tion it has to fulfil, I mean that the unsatisfactory character of the entire neo-Kantian movement lies , in its assumption that knowledge gives birth to it- self and is capable of affording its own. justifica- tion. The solution that is always sought and never found so long as we deal with knowledge as a self-sufficing purveyor of reality, reveals itself when we conceive of knowledge as a statement of — action, that statement being necessary, moreover, to the successful ongoing of action. The entire problem of medieval philosophy is that of absorption, of assimilation. The, result was the creation of the individual. Hence the prob- lem of modern life is that of reconstruction, re- form, reorganization. ‘The entire content of ex- perience needs to be passed through the alembic of individual agency and realization. The indi- vidual is to be the bearer of civilization; but this involves a remaking of the civilization that he bears. Thus we have the dual question: How can the individual become the organ of corporate ac- tion? How can he make over the truth authorita- tively embodied in institutions of church and state 298 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE into frank, healthy, and direct expressions of the simple act of free living? On the other hand, how can civilization preserve its own integral value and import when subordinated to the agency of the individual instead of exercising supreme sway over him? The question of knowledge, of the discovery and statement of truth, gives the answer to this ques- tion; and it alone gives the answer. Admitting that the practical problem of modern life is the maintenance of the moral values of civilization through the medium of the insight and decision of the individual, the problem is foredoomed to futile failure save as the individual in performing his , task can work with a definite and controllable tool. ‘This s tool i is s science. But this very fact, constitut- ing ‘the dignity of science and measuring the im- portance of the philosophic theory of knowledge, conferring upon them the religious value once at- taching to dogma and the disciplinary significance once belonging to political rules, also sets their limit. ‘The servant is not above his master. / When a theory of knowledge forgets that its / value rests in solving the problem out of which it has arisen, viz., that of securing a method of action; when it forgets that it has to work out the condi- tions under which the individual may freely direct himself without loss to the historic values of civili- zation—when it forgets these things it begins to al THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 299 cumber the ground. It is a luxury, and hence a social nuisance and disturber. Of course, in the very nature of things, every means or instrument will for a while absorb attention so that it becomes the end. Indeed it is the end when it is an indis- pensable condition of onward movement. But when once the means have been worked out they must operate as such. When the nature and method of knowledge are fairly understood, then interest must transfer itself from the possibility of knowledge to the possibility of its application to life. The sensationalist has played his part in bring- ing to effective recognition the demand in valid knowledge for individuality of experience, for per- _ sonal participation in materials of knowledge. The rationalist has served his time in making it clear once for all that valid knowledge requires organization, and the operation of a relatively per- manent and general factor. The Kantian episte- mologist has formulated the claims of both schools in defining judgment as the relation of percep- tion and conception. But when it goes on to state | that this relation is itself knowledge, or can be found in knowledge, it stultifies itself. Knowledge can , define the percept and elaborate the concept, but their union can be found only in action. The ex- perimental method of modern science, its erection into the ultimate mode of verification, is simply this — 300 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE fact obtaining recognition. Only action can rec- oncile the old, the general, and the permanent with the changing, the individual, and the new. It is action as progress, as development, making over the wealth of the past into capital with which to do an enlarging and freer business, that alone can find its way out of the cul-de-sac of the theory of knowledge. Each of the older movements passed away because of its own success, failed because it did its work, died in accomplishing its purpose. So also with the modern philosophy of knowledge; there must come a time when we have so much knowledge in detail, and understand so well its method in general, that it ceases to be a problem. It becomes a tool. If the problem of knowledge is not intrinsically meaningless and absurd it must in course of time be solved. Then the dominating interest becomes the wse of knowledge; the condi- tions under which and ways in which it may be most organically and effectively employed to direct ‘conduct. Thus the Socratic period recurs; but recurs with the deepened meaning of the intervening weary years of struggle, confusion, and conflict in the growth of the recognition of the need of patient and specific methods of interrogation. So, too, the authoritative and institutional truth of scholasti- cism recurs, but recurs borne up upon the vigorous and conscious shoulders of the freed individual who THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 301 is aware of his own intrinsic relations to truth, and who glories in his ability to carry civilization —not merely to carry it, but to carry it on. Thus another swing in the rhythm of theory and practice begins. How does this concern us as philosophers? For the world it means that philosophy is henceforth ">a method and not an original fountain head of truth, nor an ultimate standard of reference. But what is involved for philosophy itself in this change? I make no claims to being a prophet, but I venture one more and final unproved state- ment, believing, with all my heart, that it is justi- fied both by the moving logic of the situation, and _ by the signs of the times. I refer to the growing | transfer of interest from metaphysics and the the- | ory of knowledge to psychology and social ethics— | including in the latter term all the related concrete social sciences, so far as they may give guidance ‘to conduct. | There are those who see in psychology only a particular science which they are pleased to term purely empirical (unless it happen to restate in changed phraseology the metaphysics with which they are familiar). They see in it only a more or less incoherent mass of facts, interesting be- cause relating to human nature, but below the natu- ral sciences in point of certainty and definiteness, as also far below pure philosophy as to con.pre- An me. 802 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE hensiveness and ability to deal with fundamental issues. But if I may be permitted to dramatize a little the position of the psychologist, he can well afford to continue patiently at work, unmindful of the occasional supercilious sneers of the episte- mologist. The cause of modern civilization stands and falls with the ability of the individual to serve as its agent and bearer. And psychology is naught but the account of the way in which individual life is thus progressively maintained and reorganized. Psychology is the attempt to state in detail the machinery of the individual considered as the instrument and organ through which social action operates. It is the answer to Kant’s demand for the formal phase of ex- perience—how experience as such is constituted. Just because the whole burden and stress, both of conserving and advancing experience is more and more thrown upon the individual, everything which sheds light upon how the individual may weather the stress and assume the burden is precious and imperious. Social ethics in inclusive sense is the correla- tive science. Dealing not with the form or mode or machinery of action, it attempts rather to make out its filling and make up the values that are necessary to constitute an experience which is worth while. The sociologist, like the psycholo- gist, often presents himself as a camp follower of THE. PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE 303 genuine science and philosophy, picking up scraps here and there and piecing them together in some- what of an aimless fashion—fortunate indeed, if not vague and over-ambitious. Yet social ethics represents the attempt to translate philosophy from a general and therefore abstract method into a working and specific method; it is the change from inquiring into the nature of value in general to inquiring as to the particular values that ought to be realized in the life of every one, and as to the conditions which render possible this realization. There are those who will see in this conception of the outcome of a four-hundred-year discussion con- cerning the nature and possibility of knowledge a derogation from the high estate of philosophy. There are others who will see in it a sign that phi- losophy, after wandering aimlessly hither and yon in a wilderness without purpose or outcome, has )/ finally come to its senses—has given up metaphys- ical absurdities and unverifiable speculations, and become a purely positive science of phenomena. But there are yet others who will see in this move- ment the fulfilment of its vocation, the clear con- sciousness of a function that it has always striven to perform; and who will welcome it as a justifica- tion of the long centuries when it appeared to sit apart, far from the common concerns of man, busied with discourse of essence and cause, ab- sorbed in argument concerning subject and object, 804 THE PROBLEM OF KNOWLEDGE reason and sensation. To such this outcome will appear the inevitable sequel of the saying of Soc- rates that “ an unexamined life is not one fit to be led by man”; and a better response to his in- junction “ Know thyself.” THE END INDEX INDEX Absolutism, 18, 25, 98, 102, 109-110, 121-123, 130-132; Essay IV., 142-153, 176, 180-181 Acquaintance, and knowl- edge, 79-82 Action, and problem of knowledge, Essay XI, 271-304 A priori, 206-213, 292-294 Appearance, and reality, 26- 28, 118-121 Aristotle, referred to, 5, 32, 35, 37, 48, 50, 78, 221, 278 Assurance, 85-88 Awareness, 93 Behavior, and _ intelligence, 44 Belief, Essay -VI., 169-197 Bosanquet, B., 281 Bradley, F. H., Essay IV., 112-153 Change, its supposed un- reality, 1; in modern science, 8-9; and law, 72; and thought, 133; of truth, 153; of experience, 222-224, 259-260 eee metaphysic of, 178 Cognitive, 84-85, 230-233 Conflict, and thinking, 116- 117, 126-127, 132, 148-149 Consistency, as_ criterion, 128-136 Consciousness, as end of nature, 34-35; is partial, 43; and knowledge, 79- 80, 102, 171; Essay X., 242-270; non-existence of, 247-248 Correspondence, 158 Cosmology, and morals, 54 Custom, as background of morals, 48, 52 Darwin, his influence on philosophy, Hssay I., 1-19; quoted, 2, 12 Democracy, moral meaning of, 59-60, 266-267 Descartes, 8 Design, see Teleology Economic Struggle, 21, 29, 35, 41, 50 Economics, influences on morals, 57-59 Empiricism, 200-202; Essay TX., 226-241, 289-291 Epistemology, versus logic, 95-107, 172, 185, 201, 296- 298 Error, and becoming, 100 | Evolution, of species, 1, 83 and design, 12-13; and teleology, 32-35; and in- telligence, 42-43 Experience, Essay 198-225 Experiment, and knowledge, Essay IV., 77-111 VIL., 307 - 308 Feeling, 80-81 Final Cause, see Teleology Functions, true data of psychology, 250-255 Galileo, 8 Genesis, and value, 261-264 Good, is concrete and plural, 15-17, 23, 27; of Nature, Essay II., 20-45; and evo- lution, 31-35, 43; and mysticism, 39, 42; Greek view of, 46-50; medieval view of, 52-54; as fixed, 67 Gordon, K., 215n. Gray, Asa, on evolution and design, 12 Happiness, nature of, 69 Hegel, 65, 174 n. Hobbes, 203 n. Hume, 82n.; 204n. Idealism, 28, 38, 191, Essay VITI., 198-225, 228 Ideality, 89, 120, 219-225 Ideas, nature of, 134, 155; their verification, 141 ff.; are hypothetical, 144, 150- 151, 187 Individual, 244, 265-68, 285, 297 Intellectualism, Hssay IV., 1192-153, 159 Intelligence, is discrimina- tive, 39, 42, 75; is the good of nature, 44; and Morals, Essay 11I., 46-76; cosmic and personal, 55, 59; as biological instru- ment, 68; indirection of activity, 133, 149 Introspection, 250 n. INDEX James, Wm., 104, 194 n., 202, 222 n., 246 Judgment, Bradley’s theory of, 114-117; of the past, 160-61, 165; Kant’s theory of, 272 Kant, 63-65, 206-213, 271 Knowledge, its proper ob- ject, 6, 10, 14; and nature, 41; and freedom, 73; The Experimental Theory of, Essay IV., 77-111; de- fined, 90; and_ inquiry, 184-189; Essay XI., prob- lem of, 271-304 Locke, 93, 202-204, 217-218 Maine, Sir Henry, quoted, 46 Meaning, and knowledge, 87- 90; and judgment, 116- 117, 200 Mechanism, 23, 34, 57 Memory, 220 Moore, A. W., 91n. ores Essay IlI., 46-76 ysticism, 38-40, 42 Naturalism, 195 Nature, teleology of, 10; The Good of, Essay II, 20-45; animistic character of, 51; change in, 72 Newton, influence of, 61, 72 Organization, of experience, 208-211 Perception, ambiguity of term, 214-219 Philosophy, changes in, 14- 19; political nature of, 21; defined 45; and _ science, INDEX 51; and psychology, 189- 191; Essay X., 242-270 Plato, 21, 47, 49, 72, 219n., 278 Pragmatism, 25, 31, 33, 55, 95n., 109, 130n., 144; Ee- say V., 154-168, 193 Psychical, 81n., 104 Psychology, and philosophy, Essay X., 242-270, 301 Rationalism, Essay XI., 271- 304 “ Reality,” 98, 105, 113, 129, 169 n., 172, 228, 264 Relation, and appearance, 119-120 Santayana, G., 96, 224n. Sciences, developed out of morals, 56, and industry, 57-58; as mode of knowl- edge, "108; and philosophy, 268-270, 287 Sensation, 94, 262 n. Sensationalism, Essay XI., 271-304 Social Ethics, 302-304 Socrates, 51, 76, 275, 304 Species, equivalent to scholastic ‘form, 3-4; as eternal and teleological, 4- 5; basis of knowledge, 6-7 Spencer, Herbert, 16, 33, 66 Spinoza, 181 309 Stoicism, 172, 279 Stuart, H. W., 214n. Subjective, 98, 155, 204n,, 270 Teleology, of life, 4; of nature, 10, 32; basis of . idealism, 11; concrete, 15, 22; and evolution, 32-35; subjective, 223-224 Theory, 124-127 Thinking, practical charac- ter of, 124-127 Tolstoi, 173 n. Transcendence, of knowl- edge, 103 n., 156-157 Transcendental, and super- natural, 22, 29, 282; view of knowledge, 24, 27; freedom, 74 Truth, criterion of, 92, 95, 107-111; Essay IV., 112- 153; absolute, 137; iden- tified with existence, 138, 145; eternal, 147, 152; Essay V., 154-168; 230- 231, 237, 282 Utilitarianism, 62 Verification, making true, 139 ff., 162-164 Woodbridge, F. J. E., 104 n,, 240 n. Meaty Th Tp Meee) CET; Pi TARE Arou Wee ens ha : ie oes : - 2 at : ys rf # 4 ; 6! ; \ t : : - , ; WOOT be Ear . B Dewey, John 945 The influence of Darwin DA3TY, on philosophy cad, Ib 1910 7 COpee PLEASE DO NOT REMOVE CARDS OR SLIPS FROM THIS POCKET UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO LIBRARY