\iH\V. ov V\BR^RY THE JOURNAL OF SPECULATIVE PHILOSOPHY. Vol. VI. EDITED BY WM. T. HAERIS -•-•-♦^-♦-< H<«^, i ST. LOUIS, MO.: THE R. P. STUDLEY COMPANY, PRINTERS, CORNER MAIN & OLIVE STS 18 72. Entered according to Act of Congress, in the year 1872, by WILLIAM T. HARRIS, In tlie Office of the Librarian of Congress at Washington. . . ■ '^ CONTENTS Anti-Materialism G. S. Hall. 216 Correspondence — Dr. Rosenkranz and Dr. HoflFmanu ; Dr. Michelet and Dr. Hartmann; Dr. Stirlino; and Dr. Vera; Philosophy iu Europe Edito?: 175 Difference between the Dialectic and Synthetic Methods A. E. Kroeger. 184 Do the Correlationists Believe in Self-Movement? Editor. 289 Fichte's Facts of Consciousness (translation) A. E. Kroeger. 42, 120, 332 Hartmann on the Dialectic Method (translation) Louis F. Soldan. 159 Hegel's Philosophy of Art — Chivalry (translation) Sue A. Longxuell. 125, 252 Interpretation of Kant's Critic of Pure Reason Simon S. Laurie. 222 Is Positive Science Nominalism or Realism? Editor. 193 Lotze on the Ideal and Real (translation) Max Eberhardt. 4 Metaphysical Calculus... .Editor. 1 Parmenides of Plato S. H. Emery, Jr. 279 Pedaofoofics as a System, by Roseukranz (translation) Aima C. Brackett. 290 Philosophy of Law J. H. Stirling. 313 Rosenkranz on Hegel's Phenoraenoloo^y (translation) G. S. Hall. 53 * Rosenkranz on Heo-el's Logic (tran^slation) G. S. Hall. 97 Rosenkranz on Heo-el's Philosophy of Right (translation). .G?. S. Hall. 258 Rosenkranz on Hegel's Philosophj^^of History (trans.) G. S. Hall. 340 Shakespeare's Merchant of Venice D. J. Snider. 130, 361 Shakespeare's Tragedy of Julius Caesar D. J. Snider. 234 System of Empirical Certitude John C. Thompson.142 Theories of Mental Genesis John Weiss. 197 Trendelenburg on Hegel's System (translation) Thomas Davidson. 82, 163, 360 BOOK NOTICES. By the Editor— Vem'sWritincr^. 94; Jovvett's Plato. 187; Werther's Works, 190; Barzellotti. La Morale nella Filosofia Positiva, 191 ; Ulrici, Compendium der Logik, 192; Porter, Science of Nature vs. Science of Man. 284; Alcott, Concord Daj^s, 376; Hickok. Creator and Creation, 383. By A. E. Kroeger— DtiWf^ Works. 93. By Thomas Davidson — Uebervveg's History of Philosophj', 96. By Anna C. Brackett— Channmg''s Wanderer. 95; Bartol's Radical Problems, 287. f .- THE JOUR'^AL If O F SPECULATIVE PHILOSOPHY. Vol. VI. January, 1872. No. 1. THE METAPHYSICAL CALCULUS. In the province of raatliematics, tliouglit is engaged in as- certaining and delining quantitative functions, and in trans- forming these into equivalents. When it has found the numerical equivalent of a given function, its goal is reached. To use the words of another'^: "Speculative [pure] mathe- matics is the science of the functional laws by which to con- vert figure and force into number. Its first division creates functions by establishing the laws of derivation — Geometry and Mechanics ; — the second division computes the functions either in form or value — Algebra or Calculus, and Arith- metic." There is a certain analogy between mathematics and meta- 'physics in objects and methods. In general, the problem in metaphysics is to find the equiv- alent forms of Mind and Matter, — to find the equivalent of each in terms of the other. And this involves, as in mathe- matics, preliminary sciences, wherein " functions are created by establishing the laws of derivation." In other words, each province — Mind and Matter — must first be reduced to its ele- mental functions, its simplest terms found, and its entire em- pire reduced to corresponding equivalents in those simplest terms. Then comes the necessity of a bridge — the discovery of an equivalence between the terms of Mind and Matter — « Jour. Spec. Phil., vol. v., p. 178. Vol. vi.— 1 2 The Metaphysical Calculu,s. and over this bridge the investigator carries his science to its completion. If one is skeptical as to tlie existence of such a bridge, he has only to retlect a moment to perceive that the two great classes of thinkers really assume its existence in all their investigations. If he reflects still further, he is likely to find that even his own skeptical stand-point presupposes such a bridge. The materialist assumes that all i)henomena have their material equivalents, and that Matter and Force is the sub- stantial mode of existence, while Mind is one of its many phases. Hence to him all mental phenomena have equiva- lent terms of matter and force, and the object of his philoso- phy is to ascertain and fix these terms and their relations. He asks : what is the physical equivalent of thought and feel- ing ? What movement of the brain, what change of texture or consumption of tissue is concomitant with thought, feeling, or volition ? This leads him to inquire into the structure and function of nerves and brain, and the relations of dijfferent qualities and quantities of food and drink to the modifica- tions of intellectual products. His psychology seeks the laws of derivation of the complex from the simple, and ex- plains all thought as modified sensation. ''Thought is a secretion of the brain just as bile is a secretion of the liver." In this mode of scientific procedure matter is assumed as the substantial and as the most knowable; systematic knowl- edge will result from ascertaining the physical composition and laws of phenomena in general. The idealist — using a somewhat inadequate expression as a name for the opposite class of thinkers — assumes that all phenomena have their mental equivalents, that Mind or Thinking Being is the substantial, and that the material world is only one of its processes. Matter is the phenomenon or appearance of Sj^irit. " The Ego is the actual substance or Being, and at the same time it is subject or free activity. It is that whose being or essence consists in the act of posit- ing itself, i. e. of creating or producing itself. Before I be- came self-conscious, I did not exist as Ego. The Ego is its ov^n object. In the act of thinking itself, it is the active sub- ject and the product of its act. Its being is Freedom, Exist- The Metaphysical Calculus. 3 ence for itself; it is absolute subject. The determinations of objects are determinations of the Ego. All true being is knowing. The basis of the universe is not unspiritual — the antithesis of si3irit — whose connection with sj^irit can never be comprehended — but sj)irit itself. No death, no lifeless matter, but everywhere life, spirit, intelligence, a realm of spirits throughout its entire extent. Again, all actual Know- ing is Being; it posits absolute reality and objectivity ; or the Ego is substance and the content of all reality." In this statement of Fichte we have the general outcome of the G» i man philosophic movement since Kant. Kant's problem was j)recisely to ascertain the mental equivalent in the act of cog- nition. The result of his labors, supplemented by those of his successors, is a complete reduction and formulation of the mental factors in the various realms of Knowing. What ac- tivity of the mind is involved in thinking the idea of Space, and how its idea differs from that of Time, Motion, Matter, or how these differ from one another and from any other ideas, all this sort of information is given us with the utmost pains- taking and minuteness ; the results being stated in terms of mental activity : this idea is dehned thus and so, i. e. its think- ing requires such and so much consciousness of the entire cir- cular movement of thought. The idea of Space, for example, is a consciousness of that part of the activity of thinking wherein the separation or distinction of the Ego from itself is involved. Any arc of the entire circular activity of thinking may be made the object of consciousness, and, according to its extent and completeness, the depth and generality of the idea, which is the object contemplated, varies. Thus the idea of Time is a consciousness of the opposite phase involved in the activity which thinks space. That activity is common to thought and to Being, and that all objectivity, no matter how intuited, perceived, or conceived, involves movement of some sort, and that its thinking is accomplished through an inter- nal constructive movement of thought — this seems to be the basis of the great reactionary system of Trendelenburg which brings the ancient Greek and the modern German systems of Philosophy close together. Again, if one were to discard both views and attempt to take a skeptical position denying the possibility of a bridge 4 Lotze on Tdealism and Realism. tVuni iiiiiul to nuitter, it is certain that lie would not defend liimself suooessfully. The materialist takes his stand on sensuous pereeption and posits as substantial, certain meta- physical entities such as matter, force, and the like, naively supposing that they are realities cognized by him through his senses. The idealist takes his stand on self-consciousness, and from the universal and nivessary principles found there he constructs his science. The skeptic, if he employ a proce- dure at all, must assume logical principles borrowed from the materialist or from the idealist. If he stands on the anti- nomy of the two systems like Kant, he will like Kant furnish a basis for the strict conclusions of a Fichte quoted above. To say there is no bridge from mind to matter is to deny the possibility of knowing that there is such a thing as matter, for the assertion sets out from mind. The utilitarian will be most astonished when he examines the manifold applications that the German scientific explor- ers have made with this idealistic method of ascertaining the mental equivalent of cognitions. In fixing with absolute pre- cision the exact content of the various writings of Aristotle, in settling the numerous ethnological questions that arise in connection with philological researches in the higher sciences, social, political, and theological, they have the mastery of a method that gives them the vantage ground; they can solve the antinomies by pure thought; those who cannot, must work out the solutions with expenditure of life itself. Thought alone makes life valuable, and has power to protect and pre- serve it. IDEALISM AND REALISM IN THEIR RELATION TO THE THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE. From Herman Lotze's " Mikrokosmus." By Max. Ebekiiakdt. Philosophy is a mother who is served with ingratitude at the hands of her children. At one time she was all in all to them; Mathematics and Astronomy, Physics and Physiol- ogy, no less than Ethics and Politics, sprang into existence Lotze on Idealis'in and Realism. 5 from her maternal fold. But soon her daughters had esta- blished their own affluent homes, and each one the sooner in proportion to the rapid progress made under her maternal influences, conscious of what she now had wrought \)j dint of her own labor, they withdrew from the control of Philoso- phy, who, not being able to follow them into the minutia3 of their new departments of life, became troublesome by her monotonous recurrence to impertinent counsels. And thus, after all of her offspring had branched off from the common stock, Philosophy shared the dubious lot of retaining the insoluble part of all problems as her undisputed province. Placed upon this reserve, she has still maintained her vital- ity, ever pondering over the old hidden enigmas, and ever sought in lonely quietude by those who founded their hopes upon the unity of human knowledge. The connection of phenomena had been thoroughly investi- gated by the empirical sciences ; they showed how many and how multiform the links are that form the series of actions uniting a cause with its ultimate effect ; but what it is which connects two coexistent links of the series, eluded their grasp ; they neither said what the things were in themselves, nor in what that interaction of things consisted by means of which the state of one might produce a change in the state of the other. The religious and moral life of man, as regards itself, has de- veloped the belief in that which is of absolute value, in what should be, as enjoined by an imperative duty, and which, if Reality is to have any meaning whatever, must be the most real of all ; but the world of forms and facts, wherein alone it would realize itself, lay before it, a strange domain, being neither a creation of its own, nor even, as it seemed, reconci- lable with it. This state of things prompted the agitation of the two questions again and again as to the peculiar nature of Being, whose appearance to us we observe, and as to the relation which this world of existing reality sustains to the Avorld of values that should be. And, ere the lirst two were answered, arose the third, as to the capacity for truth j)os- sessed by our cognition in general ; and as to its relation, there, to the existing reality — here, to that which ought to be in it and through it. Certitude in our thoughts is attainable by reducing them C Lotze on Idealism and liealism. to the cei'taint}" of others previously demonstrated, or to the evidence of immediate or intuitive truths, neither in need of, nor susceptible of, demonstration. The conlidence we liave, parti}' in the laws of Thought which etlect that reduction or generalization, partly in the simple and direct cognitions to which these laws lead us, may be saved from prejudices whose power of persuasion is but fortuitous, by repeatedly and closely examining the ob- ject of our research; whilst it could no longer be preserved by any sort of demonstration from a doubt which would turn into a possible error, and shake our confidence even in that which we always find to be a necessity of thought. A skep- ticism, however, that did not show the error of certain preju- dices from particular contradictions liable to be pointed out, and the possibility of correcting them, but were only desirous of repeating, without provocation, the idle question, whether all things, in the end, might not be entirely different from the manner in which we of necessity must think them, would, to- getlier with Certitude, destroy all the value which we attach to reality. That this, however, shall not be — that the world cannot be an incongruity without meaning — this conviction of a moral faith is the last ground upon which we base our trust in the capacity for truth possessed by our cognition, and in the possibility of any knowledge whatever. But the extent of knowledge is not determined, as yet, by this con- viction. Only of our own being have we any immediate conscious- ness ; in regard to an external world, all our knowledge is based upon representations which are but changeful states of our own selves. What certainty have we, then, that this image of an external world is not a dream evolved by our nature i The cautious man asks this, while the imprudent one asserts it ; he forgets that it must, indeed, be so in both cases, whether things be external to us or not ; even an actual world outside of us could be represented by us only in im- ages composed of affections of our being. The subjective nature of our presentative faculty does not, therefore, decide upon the existence or non-existence of the world that it be- lieves to be representing to itself. The attempt, however, to conceive the world's image simply as the native product of Lotze on Idealism and Realism. 7 the mind was generally early repudiated by the even tenor of science ; it was always found essential, to this end, to assume within us just as may impulses foreign to the nature of our mind, and not deducible from it, as the ordinary view imagined us to receive from without. Reserving for future discussion what is of importance in these contemplations, we follow for the present the conviction to which Philosophy has ever returned, that our representative faculty springs from the reciprocation with a world independent of us. If this be the case, however, could the act of representation be more than the effect of things — could it be their corre- sponding copy ? and could truth, for the recognition of which we possess a capacity, consist in the agreement of Thought with Being ? We speak of the image of an object when an}^ combination of other agencies produces the same impression upon our perception which the object itself would have caused ; from the similitude of its effects upon us, therefore, do we recognize one thing to be the image of another. Can this very effect, which both produce within us, ever be iden- tical with them in such a degree, that in the observing gaze of a stranger our cognitions would be accepted as an image of the object ? Wherever there is reciprocation — and cogni- tion is but the particular instance of such an effect between the objects and the percipient mind — there the nature of the one element never turns into the other, remaining identical with itself and unchanged; but every hrst element serves only as an encouragement for every second one to realize from among the many states of which its own nature is sus- ceptible, a certain particular one — that one, namely, which, according to a general law of this nature, is an adequate re- sponse to the quality and quantity of the stimulus to which it was subjected. Hence, there is a correspondence between the external causes acting upon us, and certain images with- in us, which loe produce, a correspondence between a change of those causes and a variation of these, our internal or men- tal states. But no particular representation is a likeness of the cause whose product it is, and even the relations between these unknown elements which we imagine we recognize, are not, in the lirst place, the \%yj relations existing between them abstractly ; they are the forms in which we perceive . 8 Lotze on Idealism and RealUm. them. And this state we do not consider a human imperfec- tion ; we rather conceive it as inherent in the nature of every knowledge depending upon reciprocation with its object. All beings who are subject to this condition suffer the like conse- .quence : they never behold tilings, as they are in themselves, when no one sees them, but only as they appear when they are seen. Limited in this manner to phenomena, knowledge is still not devoid of all relation to the Existent itself. For we must not complain of its delusiveness as though a mere semblance were presented, while the essence which gives birth to this semblance were beyond our ken, absolutely avoiding all com- parison with the former, and questionable even in its very existence. We cannot consider the fundamental forms of cognition as mere forms of human perception, into which the objects, in themselves entirely differently constituted, drop, without admitting that, in order to drop into these forms, the objects must, of course, conform to them in the same manner as anything must fit the mesh of the net by which it is to be caught. Or, not using any figure of speech, every phenome- non, in order to ajDpear at all, presupposes an essential being whose internal relations furnish the principles determining the form of its appearance. From an analysis of the forms of our intuition in whicli perception directly seizes its ob- jects, the conviction may be secured that these forms with which we are so familiar are not applicable to the objects themselves ; but still we must seek in the nature of things and their true mutual relations the conditions which permit us to perceive them in those forms. It may thus be doubtful whether space and time, as such, may not consist in the act of representation merely, which comprehends the multifari- ous ; but it cannot be doubtful that then the Existent need not be subject of itself to an order devoid of time and space, which, while acting upon us, is converted into the forms of coordination and sequence. The sensation which presents any object to us, or calls forth any act, is certainly not iden- tical with its cause ; but it is equally certain that we consider two objects or acts as identical, alike, or different, if their im- pressions upon us be identical, alike, or different; and the degrees of their affinity we estimate according as the differ- Lotze on Idealmn and> Realism. 9 ences are greater or less in their impressions. We thus inev- itably conceive that which apparently exists and transpires, presented by perception simply in the form of the Phenome- nal, as being in perfect correspondence with that which truly exists in the things themselves or transpires between them, and which, for that reason, is by no means devoid of trutli and a due conformity to Law. To renounce these premises would not add to our certitude, but would simply produce a fruitless, self-contradictory affliction of thought. Although Semblance tlius points to Being, yet it points to mere formal relations of the Existent and their changes ; the essence of things which subsist and move in these relations remains inscrutable. And for the very reason that the na- ture of things remains unknown, the actions taking place among them cannot be comprehended from their nature ; only the semblance, the result of experience can teach us to surmise what in truth is taking place. In this manner phi- losophical research follows the same course which, as we have seen, the natural sciences have taken; it commences with the separate phenomena, mysterious and contradictory, presented by experience, and guided by the general laws of Thought, it endeavors to arrive at the form of what in truth exists and transpires, which must serve as its efficient cause to explain what is strange and contradictory in the material furnished by our perceptions. There may be many a glori- ous success even within this limited scope of its problem attending this spirit of Realism, which is content in reducing given data of Semblance to data of Being which we must of necessity assume ; not only that it may succeed in ej.ucidat- ing the causal nexus in a certain analogous series of pheno- mena, but the comparison of the knowledge obtained may also afford a prospective glance at that which, as the true Reality, lies at the foundation of the whole phenomenal world. Yet even this final result will not, in the main, re- move the character of a mere matter of fact by virtue of this principle, and thus it will ever give rise to the ojDposition of that idealistic disposition of the human soul which does not recognize true Being in facts that exist merely because they exist, or must of necessity be assumed because something else exists, but gives countenance to such a fact only as the 10 Lotze on Tdcalism and Realism. t'cu'm of tiui' Ijt'iiig, which, through the dignity of Thought that it represents, proves its mission, its right, its potency, to pUice itself at the summit of Reality as the ultimate datum, as the highest formative principle. With the bold assertion that Thought and Being are iden- tical. Idealism confronts the profession of Realism that the nature of things is unknowable. Although Idealism has sometimes ventured to assert this, it does not necessarily fol- low that it will ever be possible for human cognition to pene- trate by the activity of thought the quiddity of all things and to reproduce them in thoughts ; the limits which the linitude of our nature imposes upon this extension of our actual in- ■ sight into the essence of things are too obvious. But, to a power of cognition free from these limits, things would no longer be impenetrable; they would not be as much beyond all comprehension as, for instance, light is beyond the faculty of hearing, sound beyond the faculty of sight ; as actualized thoughts rather would they be recognized by the cognitive faculty of man, the latter recognizing itself in them. Thus, though not exactly taken as an assertion with regard to the relation of our knowledge to its object, but rather as a con- viction with reference to the nature of being-in-itself, this proj)osition imperceptibly imparts a different meaning to Being, or the nature of things, from that given to it by cur- rent opinion. For, that content by which one thing is distin- guished from another, the natural consciousness believes to have within its immediate reach, partly in sensation, partly in representations which primarily attach to sensations and embrace their elements. The more mysterious does it seem, that this content has the virtue of presenting itself to the mind as something existent, self-subsistent, tangible, in gen- eral, as a thing ; whoever would discover the hidden source of extension, fulness, hardness, elasticity, or whatever per- tains to objectivity, would, as man would naturally suppose, iiave found the true j^eculiar nature of the thing, — not that by which one is distinguished from the other, but that in which they all are alike, the nature of their being, the Reality. Can, then. Idealism claim the ability to solve this i)roblem ? Certainly to no greater extent than that to which Realism has also professed to solve it; what it is that causes things Lotze on Idealism and Realism. 11 to he, and why it is that they are related to one another ; how- it is finally brought about that something follows from these relations ; in what manner an event, a state of becoming and acting, are possible : all this remains as impenetrable a mys- tery to Idealism as it does to its opponent. Admitting, for a moment, everything we may concede, although this theory may not know how all this is brought about, it may still suc- ceed in proving a connection, according to which, supposing this very Being to exist in a manner inconceivable, there must also be, in a manner alike inconceivable, that very state of becoming and acting, and no other ; even then, however, Idealism would have fathomed but the meaning and the ra- tional connection of particular determinations, which we before comprehended as a totality under the name of Being ; wholly unknown would it be still how this inner connection of reality can be. And this it was that the proposition, pre- sented in a bold and striking manner, promised to fulfil when it declared Being identical with Thought; we were led to imagine that the very element through which Being as Being- was first distinguished, in a manner ^Drecluding all agreement, from Thinking or the state of being thought, might finally represent itself to be an impercej)tible difterence, and this Being be wholly dissolved in thoughts. Now it appears that Idealism, too, in regard to the two ideas by dint of whose fusion we think the Existent, that of the What and that of its Being, leaves this very Being equally unexplained. But, however injudicious it was to speak in that proposi- tion of Being, it was just as inexpedient, on the other hand, to mention Thought as that which is to be identical with it ; as long, at least, as this name is to distinguish with a fixed meaning a particular act of. the mind from others. And this seems to be the meaning ; for to sensuous perception Ideal- ism also does not concede that it seizes the truth of things ; it abandons both, and reserves to Thought, as a higher and peculiar activity, the privilege of detecting, behind the decep- tive wrappings in which the world of perception crowds upon us, the true Being. But this hope is based upon a widely difi'used error. That for which language has coined a name, we are generally very prone to consider a product of Thought, although its aid in determining the subj ect that a name serves I'J Lotze on Idealism and Realism. to denote is often very insignificant, and I'reqnently wholly valueless. As far as sensnons inii)ressions are concerned, we are, of conrse, readily convinced that no art applied in logical operations cau snpply to the blind or deaf the want of per- ception with regard to color orsonnd: that, therefore; blue and sweet are no conceptions thonght by us, but impressions we experience, that their names are but signs of speech which remind us of a content, in which thought shares at most but to the extent that it points out its dependent character by virtue of the adjective form it imparts to it. But in the more general conceptions which are everj'where entwined with our perceptions, investing them with form and import in the ideas of Being, of Becoming, of Activity, and of any relation point- ing from one element to another, we believe the more posi- tively that we find true products of Thought, and of that alone. And still the import of Being is not capable, by the activity of Thought, of being rendered .intelligil)le to him who does not intuitively know what is meant thereby ; only by way of analysis can Thought, in removing all irrelevant conceptions which are not intended, teach us how to trace the meaning oi the word that is apprehended only by direct intuition. Nobody will discover a definition with regard to Becoming which does not embrace under another name its most essen- tial characteristics — the conception of a transition from one event to another, or of the act of transpiring in general. Thought can aid in defining this conception only by elu- cidating both the jjoints between which that mysterious tran- sition takes place, between those which are namable only, but not capable of being further analyzed in thought. And equally be}ond the reacli of all logical operations is the con- cept of Activity. We can easily believe that we may yet re- duce it to the more abstract one of the Conditioning, although it then would be questionable whether the reverse would not be more correct; but would it then be possible to determine by a further analysis of thought what the idea of the Condi- tioning actually signifies ? Apparently, perhaps — in reality, certainlv not — under this or that name Thought will after all be but capable of merely designating the ideas of an essen- tial connection of different events, without, however, being- able to generate it by dint of its own activity. Lotze on Idealism and Realism. 13 And here tlie objection nia}^ be urged that 1 unnecessarily dwell upon that which is self-evident ; it may be said that Thought as a relative and synthetic activity would, of course, be compelled to presuppose the elements to be put in relation and synthesis, as having been furnished from some other source. I really aim at nothing else than to render this con- viction very apparent for the moment, and to deduce its conse- quences. For, after some consideration, we are soon convinced that those elements secm-ed by Thought in this manner, as having originated elsewhere, contain nothing else than the sum total of those cognitions of true Being and Eventuation which formerly were predicated of it as its inherent proper- ties. In all cases, Thought is but an introactive agency that places the primitive intuitions of the internal and external perceptions in reciprocal relations, these being predetermined by fundamental ideas and laws the origin of which we can- not trace ; logical forms proper, peculiar to itself, it develops only in the attempt at applying this truth which we find within us, to the diverse variet}^ of perceptions, and the con- sequences drawn from them. Hence, there is nothing less justiliable than the assertion that Thought, as it is, is iden- tical with Being, and capable of absorbing it without anv residue ; in all instances there rather remain unabsorbed, in its ideal How, the particular traces which mark the special features of the great Entity we have distinguished b}^ the name of Being. With more truth we should have said : JBeine- perceives itself; we — inasmuch as we are^ — know, feel, per- ceive, or experience rightly that which is said to be ; being- active, we know full well what we mean, though without the power of expressing it, when not only speaking of a periodi- city of phenomena but of a state in which the one is con- ditioned by the other. And, in this sense, all the world has always known what Being or Reality denotes, for every one has inwardly experienced the meaning of these words; having, however, found it difficult or impossible to express, by dint of logical categories, what he has so vividly experienced. Philosophy has been equally unsuccessful in supplying this deficiency ; it has invariably given us onh' names for the ex- periences of life; and living and moving in names, it sometimes has experienced less vividly that which has presented itself 14 Lot:re on Idealism and Beallsm. as tlie object of its efforts. Consequent upon such considera- tions it will in the spirit of Idealism be insisted upon, that this point should now at K'nu'th be dropped; it is admitted, that we do not know how things can exist and act, but their essence does not consist in their actuality, but rather in what they are and act. Is. tiien, this content of things more sus- ceptible of thought than the manner in which we have souglit to determine it ( Whatever Thought may be, it is an activity of the mind : and if it be not this, it is at all events a variable series of states which the mind experiences. Now, how can a succession of states depict and reproduce anything else than their like again i — can it apprehend the essence which is sub- ject to these states^ It Avill only then be possible when we a\Id another to our former assumptions, and no longer con- sider what things are, but what they experience, as their very essence and their true being which Philosophy is in quest of. Thus Idealism, by a course whose particular stages we can- not liere point out, would admit that it, at all events, neither knew liow things were, nor what they were ; but certainly what they signify. And this, their true being, is also know- able. What everything is in itself, that very nature of it by which it is at all, and is enabled to vindicate itself effectually and to be something different from others, this may forever remain an impenetrable mystery to Thought. But in the forms of their destinies, their changes, their evolution, their activity, and tlieir participation in the grand, connecting scheme of Reality, — in all these respects things are, it is said, apj)rehensible by Thought, and comparable with one another ; the essential import of every one of them, so far as it consists in this, is of itself exhaustible in thought, no matter whether we human beings can find this thought or not. Thus Ideal- ism, like Realism, is confinlbd to a cognition of that which transpires in and between things remaining unknown ; but in the import which this fact presents, it imagines that it possesses all essential truth ; things do but exist for the pur- pose of realizing this fact. A similar conviction has always been entertained and ex- pressed in other forms by Faith, inasmuch as it has held the woild to be of divine creation. It thereby denies as emphati- cally as philosophical Idealism that there is resident in things Lotzt on Idealism and Realism. 15 any being, or part of their being, which they are invested with by means of themselves. All they are, they are by the will and intent of God ; their most peculiar being consists in that Avhich God has meant or intended with them, in their signiii- cance as to the unity of the great scheme of Life. To fathom this scheme is not what Faith claims, but its idea of God is full of different rays beaming upon one another, as it were, which cast their illumining lights also upon the world cre- ated below. The idea of an immutable and just God harmo- nizes with the rigorous laws of the i^henomenal world ; the intinite fulness of His beatihc Being conforms to the beauty of the latter — His sanctity with the order of events in tlie world of morality. To trace back to these creative attributes of God all particular incidents of Reality, was neither at- tempted, nor was it considered possible ; it was sufficient to believe, despite the contradiction of numerous- perceptions, in the verity of these attributes in general, and to derive anew in particular instances, from a selection of preferred phenomena, the vivid feeling of their efficiency prevailing throughout the universe. In two respects philosophical Idealism sought to transcend this belief. It tirst took exception to the loose nianner in which Religion spoke of a personal God, in which it permit- ted Him to evoke things from naught into reality, and to place Himself in a state of reciprocation with these realized nulli- ties; the metaphysical import of all these proceedings was to be discovered and raised into the light of comprehension. None of these efforts, upon the purport of which the con- clusion of our considerations invites us to enter more fully, have been successful ; whilst criticising all ideas which Faith had anthropomorphosed of the relation of God to the world, they have left remaining in forms of speech generally artiti- cially obscured, as a final outcorning, the assertion merely, that a single highest Idea permeates all phenomena of the actual world with its formative and authoritative principles, without explaining how. And for the ver}^ reason that Ideal- ism could at most but seize upon the import of the world and not furnish the proof of its reality, everything that pointed to this enigma was eliminated from its consideration. There was no longer any mention of God, for this name sig- 16 Lotze on. Idealisim and Realisiri. nitres nauglii uitliout the predicates of actual power and etiiciency ; there could only be mention of the Idea whose content, whether in this or that manner alike incomprehen- sible, actually constituted the very being and import of the world. But for that very reason the liope was entertained of being able to express fully and systematically the whole tenor of this Idea in thoughts, and by this second etfort greatly to surpass Faith, which knew but in general terms the intent of God — this remaining, in its particulars, in- scrutable. This promise, likewise, could be realized only by abstracting from the nature of the subject what remained inconceivable to Thought. For, as a matter of course, the living forces which Faith had contemplated as resident in God, presented themselves to Thought in a manner just as inconceivable as the sensuous impressions furnished by per- ception. For them, too, we invent names; their content we merely experience, and do not seize by means of Thought. What is good or bad remains just as inconceivable as what is blue or sweet ; only after an immediate feeling has taught us the presence of merit and demerit in the world, and the difficulty of distinguishing them. Thought may develop from out of that which we thus experience, certain criteria which afterwards assist us in subordinating anything par- ticular in the one or the other of those two general intui- tions. Is it possible to lind in concepts the peculiar vivifying nerve of Justice ? We may talk much of a balance of pow- ers, of a conformity among a(;tive and passive states, of weal or woe falling back upon him who has caused them ; but what process of Thought explains the interest we exhibit in these phenomena only when they signify that which we call a Retribution ^ Love and Imtred, are they thinkable ? can their quiddity be exhausted in concepts? In whatever pro- cess of transforming duality into unity, or in whatever mode of separating what might be one, we should be desirous of perceiving their signihcance : we shall forever announce but an enigma. For the enigma is the j)ointing out of criteria, from which the full, living content to which they belong does not spontaneously How, but must be devined, as it does not lie in them. Now, this whole, living content which Faith apprehended in the personal being of God, Philosophy not Lotze on Idealism and Realism. 17 only expected to reproduce in Thought ; it imagined that it conferred upon Him, who is more than all that may be called Idea, an honorable distinction by raising Him from the ob- scurity of that which is experienced and felt with all the energies of heart and soul to the dignity of a concept as an object of pure Thought. Nature and Humanity are alike subject to this treatment, which reduces the true import of all things and events to the formal manner of their appearance, and which looks upon things and events themselves merely as being designed for the realization of these forms. The creatures of nature exist, according to this view, in order to take rank in a system of classification, and to secure to the logical categories of the General, Particular, and Individual, an abundance of pheno- mena ; their living actions and their reciprocation take place in order to celebrate the mysteries of the Differential, the Opposite, of Polarity, and Unity. — to perform a rhythm in whose oscillations xlffirmation. Negation, and mutual Limita- tion, succeed one another. Man, engaged in the contempla- tion of the Spiritual world, would at one time, under the influence of Realism, view Thought and all spiritual life sim- ply as the highest forms in which those mysterious powers, Affirmation, Negation, Contrariety and its extinction, would become manifest ; and at another time, more given to Ideal- ism, he would consider Thought to be the true being and object of all things, looking upon those forms wherein that which merely exists and transpires is presented to him as the faint prelude to the more potent theme of thought. But he went not beyond the attempt at recognizing Thought as the most essential attribute of mind — as the acme of Tliought, the thinking of Thought, the pure self-reflection of the logical activity of the mind. Existence and the dignity of the moral world were, of course, not forgotten ; but the Imperative in the moral nature of man had also to submit to this proce- dure by which everything was reduced to formal relations ; it seemed as if it ought to be only to the extent it repeated, in the forms of its realization, those esteemed relations which stood for the true nature of Being. Right here, in pointing out these errors, we drop this sub- ject. Tacitly passing by much that is considered great and Vol. vi.— 2 18 The Trinity and the Double Procession. momentous l\v the disciples of this seliool, tliis brief sketch shows a spiiil of partiality in merely ])oiiitiiig out what was apt to serve as an introduction to the object we had in view in these disquisitions. Philosophy is at present neither ex- clusively controlled by the false Idealism we have been last opposiuii", nor is it possible to avoid the mistake into which it has fallen ; but we do not deem it proper as yet to set forth the conviction we desire to hold as our ultimatum. Only, as a preliminary enunciation we m.i\.j say : The Essential of things does not consist in thoughts, and Thought is ijot capa- ble of apprehending it ; but the whole Mind may nevertheless expei'ience, in other forms of its activity and its atlections, the necessary import of all Being and activity, and then Thought serves as a means of placing what was exj)erienced in that connection which its nature requires, and in experien- cing it more intensely as the mind succeeds in controlling that connection. Very old errors they are which oppose this insight. It was long before the vivid imagination of man recognized in Thought the rein which secures to its course steadiness, certainty, and truth; it may take just as long before it will be known that the rein cannot generate the motion it is to control. The shadow of Antiquity, its mischievous over-esti- mation of the Logos ^ hangs still over us, and does not per- mit us to perceive either in the Real or the Ideal that by dint of which both are more than all Reason. THE TRINITY AND THE DOUBLE PROCESSION. By Fkancis A. Hknky. If it be admitted that truths concerning what we call the Infinite, the Absolute, and the Divine, supply a key to the comprehension of this mysterious universe in which, we know not how, we find ourselves, supply an explanation of this life which each of us is somehow living without memory of its beginning or foresight of its end, then it follows that the sci- ence which treats of these truths has a right to its old name of scientia scientiarum, and may fairly be considered the The Trinity and the Double Procefision. 19 most important study which can occupy mankind. But now- adays very few will make this admission or accept this consequence. Men's intellects are ruled by a philosophy of relativity and nescience which denies the reality or cogniza- bility of the Infinite and Absolute, and by a physical sciencer which declares all supra-mundane concerns to be "essentially questions of lunar iDolitics," and conceives that it only "shows a proj>er regard for the economy of time" when it " declines to trouble itself about them at all." These are dark days cer- tainly for Speculative Theology, and embittered too by that memory of happier things which is the crown of sorrows. For time was when she herself sat upon the throne of intel- lectual despotism, and Physical Science hid its face, and worked in holes and corners, and Free Thought was brought to the scaffold and the stake. But if wdiile Theology wan- ders unregarded and uncared for now, she is brought to see that her own tyranny over men provoked their rebellion and explains their contempt, adversity will not be without its uses ; and when she acknowledges that perfect liberty is due to thought, and perfect charity to error, she may regain, for she will then deserve, her old ascendancy. Meantime who- ever writes upon theological subjects must content himself with the tit audience though few, and to such an audience it may not be uninteresting to consider briefly the fundamental question of all Theology, namely, the essential constitntion of the Divine existence. This is expressed in the Christian religion by the doctrine of the Trinity, a doctrine which is taught from Scripture as a mystery, and which is not explained because not understood philosophically nor sought to be so understood. The doc- trine as contained in the Catholic formularies is briefly this : The one God is three Persons ; the three Persons are co-eter- nal and in every respect co-equal, so that each Person is in the full sense God, and yet there are not three Gods, but one God ; God is one and singular, yet that Singular is not one Person but three Persons. Thus expressed the doctrine is the closest contradiction, for the gist of every statement of it is that there is a unity of One and Three taken in the same sense. The unity and the plurality are the same thing, in the same respect, and from the same point of view. It is true 20 7Vie lyinity and the Double Procession. ' dirteieiit terms are used for each ; the unity is said to be of Substance and the triplicity of Persons, but these terms are only for convenience in speaking now of the unit}^ and now of the plurality. Without sncli distinct terms ordinary men could hardly frame any conception of the doctrine even as a contradiction, but it should be remembered that they are terms of economy and do not inhere in the object. When ifoi) is said to be one in Substance and three in Person, it ■Cannot be meant that He is one in a different respect from that in which He is three, as if the unity and the plurality lay side by side and the mind could go from one to the other, because, in the hrst place, the terms are equivalent in mean- ing. Personality is Substance, and Substance can be nothing- else than Personality. Again, the moment the plurality is isolated from the unity, the Persons present themselves as individually independent: Godhead is rather their attribute than their substance, and the result is Tritheism, not the Christian Trinity. Furthermore, if God is One in one respect and Three in another respect, there is no longer any difficul- ty, it is true, but there is also no new or important truth. All that is deep and distinctive in the doctrine vanishes along with the incomprehensibility ; there is no longer any mys- tery, and the Trinitarian controversy appears inexi)Ucable madness. Sameness /;/ one respect is not identity but only similarity, and dillerence in one respect is only dissimilarity, not essential difference. If this were all it means, the doc- trine might be predicated of eveiything in the universe, for we know that everything is tlie same as another thing in some respect and different from it in others, but no thing in the universe is the same as another in one respect and also different from it in the same resptect, and Just this is what Christianity means by the Trinity, although it does not profess to understand it. The doctrine is expressed as a contradiction because what is contradictory is here what is essential, and the difficulty cannot be removed for the under- standing without maiming or perverting the idea. The unity is in and through the plurality, and the pluralit}^, as such, is unity. Now if it be objected to the doctrine that thus stated it is incomprehensible and inconceivable, the common answer is The Trinity and the Doiible Procession. 21 that although it cannot be understood it is to be believed; that it is properly not contrary to reason but above and beyond reason, and so matter for faith. The answer is not satisfac- tory. For, in the first place, it is not possible to believe in an unintelligibility, if by belief is to be understood any mental activity. Faith in an unintelligible is purely a negative attitude of mind, for it is necessarily nothing more than sus- pension of thought ; it is simply the non-holding of an opin- ion to the contrary of the unintelligible proposition ; no man can go further than this with his faith, let him try as he will. In the second place, the distinction between contrary to and above reason is a sophism as here used. If the doctrine of the Trinity be fairly presented, it is directly contrary to rea- son as that term is commonly used. The true answer is that its being inconceivable and incomprehensible is no objection to the doctrine of the Trinity, because conceivability and com- prehensibility are no criteria of any concrete truth. Take the notion of infinite space ; it is equally impossible to conceive of it as limited — for then it is not infinite — and as illimita- ble, for conception can only represent the bounded. In like manner it is impossible to comprehend logically the com- monest facts of experience. For instance, all forms of motion embody a contradiction logically insoluble. A body cannot move where it is not, for it must be there first ; and it cannot move where it is, for it is there and not elsewhere : therefore it cannot move at all. Thus it is no new or alarming circum- stance if a truth cannot be conceived or comprehended, for there is a certain subject-matter which from its very nature is inconceivable and incomprehensible. Tlie fact is, one must know how to suit his instruments to the work to be done, and not conclude a task to be impossible because some instra- ments are foun'd inadequate. One must know the different powers and the difi'erent uses of sensuous representation, lo- gical reasoning, and pure thinking. Logical reasoning is the activity of the abstract, and abstraction-making understand- ing. It holds fast to certain half principles which state only one phase of the totality of an object — such as the i)rinciples of Identity, of Contradiction and the Excluded Middle, which it calls "laws of thought" — by which it judges and deter- mines of everything. Very useful within its proper sphere, it 2'i The I'ruiity and iJie Double Procession. becomes disori;-;iiuzing and obstnictive when it carries itself outside that sphere. For it linds the actual world, the eter- nal system of thinirs, existing somehow illogically. This persistent contradiction of logic by actujiUty would puzzle it into silence if it were not so sure that it is right, and so satis- iied with its lucid demonstration of how everythini:: must be that it ignores or denies the fact of its existence otherwise. Driven helplessly round and round the circle of its own cate- gories, Understanding cannot lind the return from the abstract to the concrete and actual, but dwells forever in a shadow- world of its own creation. A great deal is said by religious people about the danger of" abstract speculation uj)on revealed truth, but the danger consists entirely in the inquirer's igno- rant or unconscious use of abstract categories for universal principles. " Common sense"" places implicit faith in such categories and uses them without distrust — hen(;e that what is one should be also thre(» appears to it absurd — and al- though when it applies these categories to the totality, that is, uses them for imiversal principles, it falls at once into as many insoluble antinomies, it accepts this mishap with a good grace, and consoles itself with the philosoph}' of nes- cience and the limits of human thought, never thinking of investigating the categories in themselves to see how far they are adequate to the measure of all truth. Such investigation would discover that the laws of formal logic, being only forms of the abstract and partial, are not forms of the true but of the untrue. Considered dialectically they refute themselves, and show theii- dej^endence upon more concrete and synthetic principles. In the speculative procedure, on the contrary, form and inatter are united, not sundered and held apart as in the logical. Hence the thought is a whole, and corre- sponds with the actual, or rather is the actual, thougJit. Speculative philosophy has nothing to do with abstractions; its cardinal princij)Ie is the falsit}^ of any abstraction when taken for a universal, and its idealism is simpl}^ the inward or essential tiiith of things. And now let us see how the Trinitarian doctrine, which is a stumbling-block to Conception and to the Understanding foolishness, appears to pure reason. Reason calmly accepts the triune God of Christianity as the highest actualization of The Trinity and the Double Procession. 23 its greatest principle of Idealism, and the highest exemplifi- cation of what it has found to be the fundamental cosmical fact. That fact is self-conservation through self-diremption, and that principle the essential conjunction of contradicto- ries. For the Trinitarian principle which was brought into religion by Christianity, was to a great extent anticipated by philosophy. To Plato belongs the honor of having first apprehended the secret of the universe to be spirituality, and penetrated the triune nature of its constitution, and Aristotle developed and systematized his master's discovery. If we inquire how it is that the doctrine of Trinity in Unity com- mends itself so immediately to the speculative reason, this will best appear on consideration of the character and work- ing of that reason as it sifts and tries by the dialectic the categories of thought. Take the category which directly un- derlies the Trinitarian doctrine, that of Distinction. All distinction originates in relation, and its lirst or imme- diate form is identity and ditterence, in which these are pos- ited abstractly, or held as true in separation. This is the view of common sense and formal logic. Let us examine it. I. It holds that each thing is an identity, and distinct from all other things. (1) A is A, and not anything but A. It will be seen that "A is A" while it states directly only iden- tity, indirectly states difference as well. If A is only A, it is not B or C, that is, it differs from them. How far does it dif- fer ? It cannot differ uniinersally ; for if A and B are deter- mined existences, they are both alike in possessing being and determination ; and if they are pure simples, one must be pure being and the other pure nought; and then they do not differ at all, for neither possesses content; both are the same abstraction. Hence A is like B in at least one respect ; they have one predicate in common, the summuni genus, (2) A is then like B in one respect and unlike it in another respect. Xow the respect in which A is like B differs from the respect in which it is unlike B. Therefore the difference falls wholly in A. For A being both like and unlike B, in so far as it is unlike B it is unlike itself as it is like B. A and B have something in common ; and so wherein A differs from B, it differs from that in itself which resembles B. Thus the object A appears to be a self-opposed. II. Hence simple 24 Tlu Trin\t>i and the Double Procession. difference rests upon opposition. Is this the ultimate dis- tinction^ Let us see. (1) The two sides of opposition are called positive and negative ; they are the logical contraries. These are correlatives. Tiie positive is such only through its relation to the negative, and conversely the negative is negative only relatively to the positive. (2) If A is what it is only through B, then B determines A in- So far as A is A; and if B is wliat it is only through A, then A determines B in so far as B is. Now take up tliis reciprocity in its unity. (3) A determines B, hut, since B likewise determines A, it appears that the determination which proceeds from A returns again to A through B. That is, A determines itself through determining B. III. Hence opposition rests upon self-deter- mination. The determination which proceeds from either side returns to that side again, and is what determines that side. It is a circular movement; one half is called positive and the other half negative; if these halves are viewed sepa- rately we have opposition, but either positive or negative grasped in its whole compass includes the other. Thus sim- ple difference reduces to antithesis, and antithesis resolves in self-determination. The ultinuite distinction is self-distinc- tion, and this also is the only true identity. The immediate form of self-determination is contradiction. A is A, but (also) A is not A ; the non-being of A as A is it& true being. But since A itself is not A. it is its own ground, and preserves itself in its contradiction. Still the difference is not annihilated in the identification. Self-relatign is self- negation and this is self-direjni)tion. Hence arises a duality; self becomes its own other. But since that Other is only the self become, it is at once identical and non-identical, and so self-nugatory and non-abiding. It appears inasmuch as it is Other, and disappears in that it is also Self. Hen(;e the Other is the manifestation of an Essence, or the Phenomenon. It is not Essence in totality, for then it would be ijermanent; nor is it emi)ty phenomenon, or appearance of nothing ; but it is Essence in self-opposition, out of its true being ; hence its dis- appearance, or return from Otherness, manifests its nugato- riness as Other, and so its whole being as Essence. Such being' the form of tlie universal to pure thought, let us see how it is in actuality, and we shall find that no less in TTie Trinity and the Double Procession. 25 ttie latter than in the former abstract identity is nnll, for Na- ture is nothing else than the realization of the dialectic we have just pursued. It is at once to be observed in tlie con- templation, of Nature that the sensuous object undergoes change. Through its relation to other things it passes from one st^te of being to another. Hence the state which it occu- pies at any one'Time is no more real than that which it occu- pies at another, as is shown by its changing from the one to the other. Against its definite being as a This is placed its indefinite being, or capacity of becoming a different ; e. g. against the liquidity of water, its vaporous and solid condi- tions. Hence the being of the thing resides not in its state at a given time — for no state is commensurate with the whole compass of its being — but rather in its relation to the totality of conditions — that is, to the being of all other things — upon which depends its transition from state to state. Its being lies in its immanent relativity, but relativity is negativity \ it has its being therefore in its non-being — not in the imme- diate, positive identity which it is, but in the universal which it is not; — properly therefore it never is^ but always is not. Its true actuality would be the simultaneous realization of its whole circle of potentiality, or its ideal totality, but the sensuous thing never attains this actuality, and therein precisely lies its finitude. As an identity it changes and passes away because it is out of itself, out of its whole being ; it is, but even more it is not ; — the flower points beyond itself to fruit and seed, and hurries to fade and fall that it may re- alize its aspirations. The finite .thing then, as a non-abiding^ is ^ jjlienonienon ; the variable particular appears and mani- fests a Generic wiiich is constant, or infinite. It is this Ge- neric which is, and not the particular as such. For if there were nothing but finite particulars, they could not disappear and reappear ; once they were gone, existence would come to an end. But the whole movement of finitude manifests its infinitude. Change, which is destruction and death to the unsubstantial particular, is in the Generic only a process of self-identification, or self-affirmation. Change, as such, can- not be regarded as the universal (the position of Ileraclitus)^ for it lacks the into-itself-returniug movement which is its self-preservation. In the Generic, Change is immanent change, *20 The Trlnitu and the Double Procession. remainin^'ius of the Father an actual prius, and it arose horn his inabilit}^ to think from the Idea, or under the " form of eternity." The battle was fought, however, rather on the ground of consequences than of principle, and the principle was not quite dehnitelj' exploded. Hence, as Dr. Scliatf says,* " the Nicene fathers still taught, like their pre- decessors, a certain sirb ordination ism which seems to conflict with their doctrine of consubstantiality" (of the Son) •"Father, Son, and Spirit, all have the same divine essence, yet not in a coordinate way, but in an order of subordina- tion." The Father was considered the primal divine subject, to whom alone absoluteness belongs, since He has the essence of Himself and from no other : the Son, on the contrary, has the essence by communication from the Father in a seconda- ry, derivative way; hence a certain inferiority was held of the Son to the Father, which inferiority was still more ap- plicable to the Hoh' Ghost. Scriptural argument for this theory of subordination was found abundantly, but, as Dr. Schaff reniiuks,* "all such passages refer to the historical relation of the Father to the incarnate Logos in his estate of humiliation (the relation of the Essence to the Phenomenon, as such), not to the eternal, metaphysical relation of the Father to the Sou." Where, as in many instances, Christ as- serts His inferiority to the Father, such assertion cannot be allowed to contradict other j)assages in which His co-equal- ity and essential unity with the Father are distinctly stated. For in the former cases He is to be understood as speaking solely from that earthly estate of humiliation in which His * History of the Christian Ciiurch, by Philip Schaff, D.D.. vol. ii. p. 681. The Trinity wild the Double Procession. ' 39 full divinity was temporarily laid aside. As incarnate He was out of His true being, and whereinsoever He was infe- rior to the Father He was in the same kind and in the same degree inferior to Himself as He is in that true being of co- equal Godhead. For the doctrine of the Trinity is precisely this, that the divine essence is not such that it can be held entire by a single Personality, and be by Him communi- cated. That essence is immanent reciprocity. Just in that the Father is determined as Father, as o-i>xy, and source, lies His incompleteness as God. The generation of the Son is the demonstration that He is as necessary to the Father as the Father. The Father as necessarily looks forward to the Son and Spirit for his completion as they look backward to Him for their origin. This point is distinctly brought out in the 25th article of the Athanasian Creed: " And in this Trin- ity none is before or after another ; none is greater or less than another ; but the whole Three Persons are co-eternal together and co-equal." This "remnant of ante-JNicene subordinationism'' still survived however, and so, when the doctrine of the Holy Ghost came afterward to be considered, His necessary Procession from the Son as well as from the Father was not seen into, being obscured from men's view by their monarchian theory. It must be matter of regret that so important a point as the Double Procession should not have been clearly stated by the creed-making Councils, but have been left an open question to become the occasion of a wide and lasting schism. But, at least, the doctrine was by no means denied. The intent of the Constantinopolitan Creed in affirming the Procession from the Father was not to limit such Procession to Him and exclude the idea of Procession from the Son also, for no such idea was in the mind of its framers. Their statement was simply aimed at the Pneuma- tomachi, and intended to affirm the divinity of the Spirit by giving Him a relation to the Father as immediate as that of the Son. AVhether the Procession were single or double was a point lelt unsel tied by the Council because left untouched. Nor are the Greek Fathers at one upon the question. Ac- cording to Dr. Scliatf, some — as Athanasius, Basil, and the * lb. p. G83. 40 The Trhilty and the Douhle Procession'. Gregories — give the Prooessioii from the Father witliout de- nying it from the Son also; others — as Epiphanius, Marcel- lus of Ancyra, and Cyril of Alexandria — derive the Spirit from both Father and Son; and othe^fs — Theodoret and The- odore of Mopsnestia — "would admit no dependence of the Spirit upon the Son.'" It would seem that these last rather misunderstood than denied the double Procession, which is far from subordinating the Third Person to a Second, itself subordinate (what seems the ground of their objection), but is, on the contrary, the negation of the subordination of that Second, and the perfect co-equality of the Three. The difference with regard to the point between the Greek and Latin churches arose from the fact that while the former stopped with the Nicene statement of the Trinitarian doc- trine, the latter carried on its development to the formation of the Athanasian Creed. In this work of development St. Augustine was chietlv eminent, and his services the most considerable. Their main effect was to eliminate the subor- dination or monarchian view, bringing out more sharply the con substantiality of the Three Persons and their numerical unity, and in consequence asserting the Procession from the Son. His presentment of the doctrine gradually met with universal acceptance in the West, and at length the insertion of the famous clause Filioque in the Nicene Creed by the Council of Toledo, A. D. 589, gave the doctrine of the double Procession a place in the Catholic symbol. The questions relating to the Filioque separate into three classes : those concerning the doctrine considered in itself; those concerning the Scriptural authority for the doctrine; and those concern- ing the historical right of the clause to a place in the creed. The last two points do not belong to the present considera- tion, but a suggestion or two may be allowed. As to the second : — while there is no direct or distinct state- ment of this doctrine in the Scriptures, as there is of scarcely any doctrine of speculative Theology, it may safely be claimed that it has as ami:)le scriptural warrant as any other doctrine of a like character. The very same language and expressions from which the Procession from the Father is inferred are, with one exception, used to denote the relation to the Son. Some have doubted the double Procession on the strength of this The Trinity and tlie Double Procession. 41 exception — John xv. 26: "the Spirit of truth which proceedeth from the Father" — and the absence of anj^ corresponding pas- sage asserting with the same expressness Procession from the Son. But if this language of our Lord be construed as denying the Procession from Himself as eternal God, there are many other of His utterances, made after He had " emptied Him- self" of His divinity and taken upon Him the form of a servant, which must be construed as a still more express denial of as many attributes of deity, and which taken together amount to a denial of His divinity altogether. In short, we are not to expect from the God incarnate, speaking of Himself in His then condition, a characterization of His true or absolute con- dition as pure Spirit. The evidence for such a doctrine as this is to be gathered out of a wise and comprehensive study of the whole Scripture ; no single text is of weight to prove or disprove it ; else the personality of the Holy Ghost, for in- stance, might be shaken by repeated expressions which har- monize much more closely with the notion of an emanation or influence than with that of a person. And if this and other admitted doctrines rest ui^on Scriptural language not perfectly distinct, and expressions not entirely unquestionable, it can be no prejudice to the double Procession — one among the least likely to be explicitly taught — that it has no firmer ground. It may also be remarked that there seems to be an argument for the Latin doctrine in the very term Procession. If the Procession is as exclusively from the Father as the generation is, it is difficult to see why a different and more general term should be employed to describe what is after all the same thing, production. But the difference in terms becomes intel- ligible and indispensable when we consider that one states a production which is necessarily by a single agent, and the other production in general, in which two or more producers may concur. As to the historical question, it is to be borne in mind that the right of the clause Filioque to a place in the creed is' a point entirely distinct from the truth of the doctrine it expresses. This latter point was never in dispute between the Greek and Latin Churches. The Eastern Church simply claimed that no articles of faith were of authority unless pro- mulgated by a general council, and ratified by the acceptance 42 J^icJ/fe's Facts of ConscioifS?iess. of the whole Church. But it was not until three hundred years after the Council of Toledo that any controversy arose between the two communions. And then, when in character, interests, and modes of life, the people of the East and West liad drifted apart, when the active and arrogant ambition of the Roman see had roused the jealousy of Constantinople, the question of the Procession was recurred to as a recent doc- trinal centre around which more worldly and personal causes of discord might array themselves. As between the Greek Church and the Anglican or American, the feud is an ana- chronism, and for the separation between us to Qontinue with- out an etfort made by either party to remove the barrier — as it were, onl}' carelessly left up — is surely a reproach to both. "We may admit that the Greek position with regard to articles of faith is technically the safest and best, and such admission should lead them to recognize and assent to the Augustinian doctrine of the Western Church as, however irregularly intro- duced, unquestionably the true, and the crowning and com- pleting truth of the great doctrine of the Trinity. FACTS OF COXSCIOUSNESS. Translated from the German of J. G. Fichte. by A. E. Kroegek. :^ <3<=> zc XX. FACTS OK CONSCIOUSNESS IN KEGAKD TO I UK I'KACTICAL PACULTV. CHAPTER I. The Causality of the Ego being checked by a non-Ego is posited as Impulse — the Check of the non-Ego as a Material World, and from the positing of both a Tendency of the Ego to overcome that check is ijosited. In Book First we have considered immediate external per- ception as a causality of the presupposed absolute life through its immediate being. How far this view will prevail in our Second Book will shortly ax)pear. Nevertheless it is evident that we -must commence our investigation with such a caus- ality, and hence we do so now, though in another manner. It is, however, to be remembered, that the word Being is here Ficlite's Facts of Consciousness. 43 taken stiictl}^ to signify an absolutely upon-itself reposing being. 1. Let us then assume that such a causality of life through its immediate being is checked : what will then arise in the checked life ? That causality, in so far as it is in the life, can surely not be annihilated itself ; only its manifestation can be checked; that causality or determined activity and free- dom remains in the life, but in a manner as a causality which has no causality. How do we term this in language ? I be- lieve, an Tiiipiilse. Hence through the checking of the caus- ality there arises in life an impulse; and this is theiirst place where we have deduced, in its proper connection and from its possibility, an independent being of mere and separate free- dom, which in onr first book we merely postulated. If we ascribe to life an actual causality, freedom always must im- mediately and inseparably dissolve in the being produced by it, and can have no separate being of its own at all. 2. An independent being of freedom is, according to our previous results, consciousness. Hence there must arise in life, under the above condition, a consciousness of the impulse by virtue of a limitation. Now, an immediate and self-made consciousness of an actual limitation is called Feeling., and the general faculty of such a consciousness is called Sensu- ousness : and since in the present instance consciousness is directed upon the actual condition of life itself, this feeling is a feeling of self, and this sensuousness an inner sensu- ousness. I add this remark : that which thus limits life can be held to be, firstly, a force, and a force stronger than the life, and which, as opposing itself to life, must then be posited outside of it as an independent being ; which assumption is the basis of an objective dogmatism, a transcending beyond free life. But it may, perhaps, also be held to be a limitation within that life itself, not however in so far as that life is free, but in a higher being of that life, in relation to which that being of the life whereof we have hitherto spoken would then be only a lower and subordinated being ; an assertion, which, if proved, would cancel the above dogmatism and found an im- manent idealism. 3. Life has now been elevated above its stage of immediate 44 Fic?ite^s Facts of Consciousness. causality into the region of consciousness. Hence if there really is an impulse in the life it must have i;nmediate caus- ality in that same region of consciousness. Bnt how will consciousness be able to connect with this feeling of an im- pulse, and what manner of consciousness will it be when it thus connects i Let us investigate this. First of all. life contains absolutely through its being free- dom a determined faculty ; and this faculty has arrived at an independent existence only through the being checked of its immediate causality, since in its unchecked causality it was always evaporating into and llowing together with being. Now since every independent being of freedom results in consciousness, the check produces immediately, together with the consciousness of the impulse, a consciousness of the faculty ; Avith this distinction, that the latter, as not express- ing an actual condition but merely a possible activity of life, is called by us, not feeling, as we call the impulse, but con- templation. Now let us stop at this contemplation of the real faculty to have causality within the sphere of being. It is, as we have seen, a faculty to progress within time through a series of conditions to the intended end. It is this faculty which is to arise on the occasion of an impulse to exercise real causality, and which is to enter contemplation immediately when it thus arises. The matter stands thus : in this state of affairs, imme- " diately free life is absolutely checked, and cannot progress a single step within the sphere of being. Let us call this limit, which at the same time expresses the intended causality, D. Now this D it cannot immediately attain, being checked. But there may be a point, A, which life is able to produce through immediate causality, and if this point A is produced life may be able to produce another point, B — A being the condition of the realization of B ; and again, B being pro- duced, life may be able to realize C, and thus, finally, the originally intended D. If a contemplation or conception of this series arises in life, it must therein behold its own faculty to produce D. Now this faculty to produce D lay undoubtedly concealed in life and in its absolute being originally ; but that' it has Flclde's Facts of Consciousness. 45 now become an actual faculty of life, completely within its free power, and that having thus gotten the faculty within its power, life can at once proceed to realize it, is effected solely by means of the conception life has now attained of it. Only rlirough the conception has life gotten possession of this faculty, for before the conception it had not got it; and we here obtain an insight into the very important proposition, that the conception liberates and can become the ground of an actual faculty. IN'ay, the very superiority of conscious- ness over unconscious nature consists in this, that the latter always works blindly whatever it can produce, whereas the former can moderate its work by conceptions and can regu- late them according to a rule. 4. As soon as the impulse to have causality exists and con- tinues, there arises in consciousness a desire to form the just described conception of a possible causality to produce a certain end from the contemplation of the faculty in general. The question now is, through what is this forming of such a conception conditioned ? I maintain that, besides the already described contemplation of the faculty in general, it is condi- tioned also by an image of the checking power, or resistance ; for if the conception of that possible causality is to arise in the mind — which it does by means of quiet reflection and consideration — the faculty as well as the resistance must be taken hold of by the mind, compared with each other and calculated, until it is found that a certain direction of the faculty will necessarily conquer the resistance. But how does such an image of the resistance arise? Evidently it is not a matter of feeling, for feeling involves only the imjDulse, which can lead at the utmost to the conception of a limita- tion; nor of contemplation, for contemplation is directed only upon the faculty. We know this image as the condition of the conception of our possible causalit}^ ; but this conception is a product of free imagination, which is here — supposing a knowledge of the faculty as well as of the resistance— alto- gether production, and consciously and considerately pro- ductive, since it proceeds in accordance with the rule given it by both premises. Thus it appears that the image of the resistance must also be created by productive imagination, not consciously however — since itself is not intended to be 46 F'icJitc.^s Facts of Consciousness. created, but only that the creation thereof is conditioned by it — but blindly, and absolutely in consequence of the im- pulse which craves its satisfaction. In short, in producing this image of a resistance, the productive power of imagina- tion must have causality absolutely through its being, i. e. as a productive j)0wer of imagination. 5. How, then, will such an image result:' Firstly, as that of an absolute resistance, and hence as posited outside of the Ego into the sj^here of Being itself, since Being itself is opposited to life or to the Ego. This positing outside is pre- cisely what we have characterized in Book First as objective thinking. Secondh^, as the image of a resistance in an im- age ; for it is resistance only in an image and its other rela- tions, whereof hereafter, belong to feeling and cannot enter the image from that feeling ; hence as resisting that very im-^ aging and annulling its freedom. For let us consider, that here, where imaging first begins, we have still the whole infinite freedom of imaging or abso- lute positing. This freedom is limited in its infinity and this limitation is imaged. Hence there are in this image two ele- ments in reciprocal relation and opposition with each other: 1. The infinite faculty of j)ositing, grasped in the unity of the image, and which we have above described a8 Extension — an empty extension, which, as the image of the faculty itself, is everywhere penetrable by, and transparent to, the Ego; 2. The opposition to this infi nite faculty of positing, namely, Just the same kind of an infinite positing on the part of the resistance, whereby that transparency and penetrability axe cancelled. The whole, which arises from these two compo- nents, is the image o£ matter. , But again, the image of the resistance is most certainly posited. Hence there must be pictured also an opposition to this positing ; otherwise that image would not be the image of a resistance. It is posited, through the positing of the Ego generally, as being ; but now the resistance must, moreover, posit itself with this its being ; and this its own being which the resistance posits together with that being, which it de- rives from the general positing of the Ego, results in a further determined being, or a quality. Let us make clear this latter fact by a further and pro- Fid lie's Facts of Consciousness. 47 founder consideration of the external sense. The external sense is, according to the above, a limitation of productive imagination through the self-positing of a resistance gener- ally. Thus the collective sense, feeling or the sense of touch, is nothing but the power of imagination to extend, in a state of limitedness. Through this sense we perceive matter as im- penetrable. Now we say at present nothing about this sense as furnishing, besides this impenetrability, still other quali- ties of matter: warmth, coldness, &c. The easiest to be com- prehended sense for quality is sight, which is distinguished from feeling as a collective sense, that the latter expresses only the positing in the act, whereas* seeing is the image of the positedness, and of a positedness which is transparent to itself as such. "I see an object" signilies : "The positing of it is completed and I am limited to its positedness." But I do not see through the object signified : the inner condition of the object has not been posited through me, hence is also not known to me, but is posited through the object itself. The limit of this my positing and of the itself-positing of the object is then characterized by a further determination of my seeing, which is ascribed to the object ; that is, my seeing is no longer a pure seeing, but the seeing of a color, as the fur- ther determination of pure seeing. These three components form an organic whole amongst themselves, as has already been proved in the first book ; and hence it is absolutely impossible that an external objec- tive being should be formed without having sensuous quali- ties and being immaterial. Hence it is also impossible that matter can be without qualit^^or that a quality can be oth- erwise than adherent to a material body. 6. With this investigation our whole view is changed and expanded. In our first book we considered what we then called external perception, in its own triplicity as a for-itself- existing and separate affair. But now we have found it to be a mere link of a greater organic whole, consciousness. For the synthetic period, which we have described, consists of the following three chief components: 1. A feeling — namely, of an impulse ; 2. A contemplation — namely, of the real faculty to have causality within the sphere of being ; and 3. An im- age of the resistance. And since this latter image is produced 48 Ficlite\'< Facts of Consciousness. by the free and absolutely productive power of imagination, without consciousness of freedom, we may very properly call the whole labor in this ima2:ing a thinking, since this new view brings even that which foi'merly we called sensuous affection and contemplation into the one general sphere of thinking. 7. Now let us ask : wherein lies the focus of external per- ception when we consider it as a separate matter ; that is to say, in what condition of it doth life manifest itself? Evi- dently in the creating of the image. Not the contemj)lation of extension, which occurs in it. is the focus and central point of its condition ; this extension is merely imaged and objec- tively posited, and when thus posited, an opposition is given to it. Again : not sensuousness is that focus and central point ; for sensuousness is only the real point of conflict of the opposites, and as such it also is not immediate, but is objectively posited. Finally: the third component of exter- nal perception, the positing, is certainly immediate, since it is the act of imaging or the creating of an image ; but it is also posited in the same undivided moment as objective, thus becoming the particular sense for quality, as has been illustrated in the above example of seeing. Hence the whole external perception is not a consciousness at all, but simply an object of consciousness, created by the absolute produc- tion of the jjower of imagination for consciousness. Thus it appears that the thinking which occurs in it is a double thinking, being firstly an actual thinking, as the creating of an image, and secondly a thought thinking, as the objectiv- ated sense for quality ; and ffk. contemplation which occurs in it is likewise double, being firstly an actual contemplation, in the creation of extension, and secondly a contemplated contemplation, in that the freedom of it finds a resistance in matter. Thus, then, the external sense is not an actual sense, but merely the image of the only true sense which remains, of the internal sense. All this might, in fact, have been discov- ered in mere observation from the circumstance that space as well as the external sense generally is posited outside of the real internal essence of the Ego, the external sense being even embodied into a tool of the senses. Ficlite's Facts of Consciousness. 49 8. Thus the matter stands, therefore. That act of the pro- ductive power of imagination cannot, however, arise to con- sciousness, "but melts together immediately with its product. Hence external perception appears to be not an object of consciousness, such as we have shown it to be, but as a true consciousness, and moreover as an immediate and uncondi- tioned consciousness ; and thus it happens that the external world is made to appear to ordinary consciousness as an immediate object of consciousness. Now, how have we proceeded that we should have arrived at an insight of the opposite as the truth ^ We have through means of thinking gathered up external perception into a higher connection, and thus have brought the connecting link, which remains hid- den to common consciousness, before our artiticially created consciousness. Owlj thus, indeed, could that insight have been arrived at. Hence whosoever does not undertake this thinking together with us, or, though trying to do so, is not penetrated by its evidence because he does not proceed in the right manner, simply does not get that insight ; and all his asserting, getting angry, and averring that he cannot do better, helps him nought. "We know it right well, and more- over can prove to him, which he cannot do, that he really cannot look at the matter other than in the waj^ he does, sim- ply because he does not fulfil the conditions of the other view. Should some one, however, interpret our proposition as asserting that we merely imagine things — as indeed some pretended philosophers have actually interpreted it — he would thereby simply exhibit his inhnite lack of understand- ing, his absolute incapacity to be taught, and to enter into other ideas than those he already possesses, and to take hold of two thoughts in such a manner as not to have forgotten the first when he gets to the second. We imagine in the higher regions of freedom, where we can also leave off ima- gining. But that imaging, whereof we have spoken, we can- not leave off at all under the presupposition of an impulse which we shall likely find to belong absolutely to the life of consciousness. Such an imaging is absolutely necessary, and for that very reason its result forces itself upon us. And thus, I think, we have deduced also external |)erception. 9. The clear result is this : that which has been suggested Vol.vi.— 4 50 F'icJite's Facts of Consciousness. by the relation of life lias here been under consideration, aucC which may perhaps remain as the only true, namely, a lim- itation of life, is not at all touched in the object of external perception. That object is a mere opposition to the power of imagination, and is not at all anything- by itself, as indeed it does not pretend to be ; it is simply the product of a relation to anotlier. to the power of imagination. For surely that through which the thing really exists, and hence can alone enter into connection with us. and whicli therefore must surely constitute its essence, is its force or j^ower; but power- is nothing material, nor manifests itself, to any external sense ; it is simply thought. Hence this power, something altogether unsensuous and supersensuous, were the real thing. What, then, can this sjmce-lilling matter claim to be, with its qualities, and how can it ever pass for the real thing? 10. Nevertheless the pi'elindnary question arises here, re- quiring however, also, only a preliminary answer at j)resent: how is such an image of a resistance usually connected in its general form with the conception of the desired causality? Evidently thus : the whole resistance, to which the impulse relates in its totality and which we seek to get at in parts by proceeding through its various conditions, must be together, and in this, its being together, it is posited in space. In it is, at the same time and as one, that which afterwards in time becomes a many-fold and a succession. Hence the problem is to hunt uj) in space a point — corresponding to the A de- scribed in 8 — wherein the causalit}- may commence. For instance : in nuitter, this resisting power to be overcome is the connection of the parts, and this connection is to be broken first in one point, and from that one to the next. 11. The image of the immediate causality of the Ego is a straight line ; hence also all such immediate causalit}^ ap- pears as occurring in lines — pressure, impact, &c. If an unsurmountable resistance occurs, the causality moves off in another straight line, and the result is a straight-lined angle. Causality in curved lines occurs only mediatel}' and with considerateness, according to a rule : for instance, around a given centre ; whereas the straight line breaks out imme- diately and without any considerateness, being indeed the very outbreak of free construction. Curvedness is the exact FlcTites Facts of Consciousness. 51 opposite of freedom, or its limitation ; for which reason, in- deed, nniversal space is necessarily figured as a globe. People have inquired after the ground of the three dimen- sions,of space. Now, firstly, all that is needed is to get at the correct conception of dimension, which will show itself as soon as we shall exhibit its ground. Secondly, it is simply needed to know where to look for this ground ; namely, not in the region of conceptions, but of contemplations ; for here is a mere contemplation, and the problem is a limitation of contemplation. "Show me the ground of the three dimensions" signifies nothing but : " Put me on a stand-point where this contemplation will necessarily occur to me." This stand-point ' is, for instance, not that of the point ; for from me as a centre an infinite number of lines are possible, and if these were called dimenaions space would have an infinite number of di- mensions. The stand-i:)oint of the required contemplation is rather that of the line as the image of freedom, and hence also of time. This line (freedom), having but one dimension, must be limited by the above resistance in all possible ways. But there are three such ways : it is limited in length at both ends, in breadth again at both ends, whereby space changes from the line into a plane, and finally in height and depth, whereby space changes from a plane to a geometrical body. These are the three possible directions in which to recon- struct original space, that is, if we start from and presuppose the line. Hence, in true opposition to the image of the Ego's causality, space has dimensions, and three of them. 12. We have called external perception generallj' a tlilnlc- ing : previously we said that it was a production of an abso- lute power of imaging. Hence in so far as we hold both propositions seriouslj', which we do, we consider all thinking as producing through an absolute power of imaging, and vice xersa. Thinking is, therefore, nothing passive, receptive, or anything like that. — If former philosophers had made the conception of thinking clear in this way, they would have necessarily ere this put Philosophy' on the right track. — Above, we described thinking as a going out of an inner and immediate consciousness. Bnt this inner is feeling and con- templation, both as the immediate being of freedom, and is thus immediate consciousness. IN'ow we say thinking goes out of it. In what manner ( Certainly not in the way of Be- Tvi J^^ic7/f('s' 7'^ai'fs' of Co)h'^c/o>/.wrf!S. ing, whicli indeed does not occur liere at all, l)ut in the man- ner of consciousness, which does occur here. But since this is a going out of immediate consciousness, it must be an im- aging, and moreover an absolute imaging, a pure creating of a new consciousness. To ]>e snie, a creating according to a rule, and by no means blind and lawless, as those assume who understand us to say that we merely imagine things. This established conception of thinking will be found to conlirm itself altogether. Here we particularly think a re- sistance of the productive power of imagination, or thinking itself in its most universal form ; hence we have here the absohitely first thinking. Productive imagination produces itself — of course, in an image — and images a resistance to this thus produced itself. This is, in short, the here-occurring function of thinking, or of the absolute power of imaging; which power is here immanent, transcendent, remaining in and going out of itself. With another kind of thinking, of which we shall speak hereafter, it will be different. En it the power of imaging will image not itself, but another faculty given to it before in con- templation, and will image an op])osition to this faculty, in which latter function alone it is pure thinking. 13. We also in philosophizing, simply as such, must think; that is, produce absolutel}'- through the power of im- aging. What we have just said may be divided into two chief parts. Firstly, we had to note : under such and such a pre- suj)position (of an impulse, &c.), a picture of a resistance must be created. This "must" expresses that another thinking will connect with the first one, as the presupposed thinking, immediately and as inseparable from it; hence this "must" expresses that through the immediate causality of thinking itself the second thinking will grow out of the first one with- out any action on the part of freedom ; and thus the second link must have arisen — if our assertion is correct — in every one of our readers who has thought the first link correctly, and must so have arisen without any act of his own freedom. The desired evidence must have tak(»n hold of him imme- diately. It is quite otherwise with the second part of what has b^en said, namely, with the question : what will this im- age of a resistance result in i ( 53 ) HEGEL'S PHENOMENOLOGY OF MINI). Transhited tVoin tlie (Jcnium* ofK. Uosenkranz, hj- G. S. Hall. It was natural that during HegePs intimate association with Schelling, his expression should become somewhat colored bv the latter, in whom we may observe the converse of this influence. When Schelling left Jena in the spring of 1803, Hegel returned more to his own individuality. He resumed also the collegia which he had somewhat neglected during his activity as an author. He lectured especially upon logic and metaphysics, and also upon a philosophical encyclope- dia, totam 'pMlosopldw scieniiam, pliilosopldam logices, na- turce et mentis. This distinguished him from Schelling, who did not lecture at all upon logic or metaphysics, and had critically treated the various philosophical sciences, only once, in the lectures on the methods of academic study. A systematic totality was what lay at Hegel's heart. He col- lected himself gradually for its production, and intended to bring it out in two parts, of which the first was to contain a critical justification of his stand-point, and the second the svstem itself. The first only, at the close of his abode in Jena, was brought to press, and appeared in Bamberg, 1807 : "'The Phenomenology of Mind, or the Science of the Experi- ence of Consciousness.'' This work included, first, the theory of consciousness; second, a critical review of history, to see at what result the history of mankind has arrived in respect to science. It united psychology with the philosophy of history. Hence it has been called a psychology confused by history, or a his- tory distracted by psychology. It is easy to represent it as a monstrosity if narrow criteria are applied, but the inner unity of Hegel's thought was to haye consciousness criticise itself by its development, not only in respect to form, but in respect to contents. The title " Science of Consciousness " indicates the content. The mind of mankind itself is sum- moned to state what form of consciousness it assumes as present, as now final. The chief title " Phenomenology of * A chapter from " Hegel als Deutscher National Philosoph," Leipzig, 1870. 54 HegeVf< IVtenomenology of Mind. yV\\\i\" ivoalls the pheiionu'iioloi'v of Ijaiuberfs "Oi'a;anon." Mind advances in its oonsciousnoss from step to step. Each lower stage is shown npon the next higher to have been a rehitive error. Init it is not therefoie iiothing, bnt a necessary condition of the higher. This, whiMi it is entered npon, seems to be theliighest, bnt progress rednces this to a mere seeming. It is therefore not entirely false, bnt only relatively so, in that it was tjiken as nltimate. In designating the phenomenology as that of mhid, Ilegel indicates the difference wdiicli existed between himself and Fichte, Schelling, and previ) realization of rational self- consciousness through itself; (c) individuality, which is real in and for itself. Observing reason applies itself {a) to na- ture ; (&) to purity of self-consciousness and its relation to external reality ; (c) to the immediate reality of self-con- sciousness. Objects of nature are described, arranged, and investigated, according to their laws. Inorganic as well as organic nature is appropriated by observation as rational. Reason observes — and so does self-consciousness in its puri- ty— how it follows logical laws in thinking, and how it is subject to psychological laws in its development; for indi- viduality, in its reciprocity with the circumstances which casually surround it, evolves nothing which was not involved in its instincts, propensities, and faculties. The great influ- ence which is wont to be ascribed to circumstances is valid 62 Hegd's Phenomeuoloyy of Mind. only in so far as the individual admits and incorporates them into his activity. Hence in immediate reality as it appears in phvsioffnomv and in the brain (or, since this cannot be^ directly perceived, in the skull), observation recognizes the existence of self-consciousness. The mental is one with the^ material, as brain and spinal marrow. Without brain, ob- serving reason can find no self-consciousness, no thinking, no mind. The antithesis of observation is the attempt of self- con- sciousness to realize the conception of reason through itself — not to find, but to produce, the reality of the conception. Hegel distinguishes here (a) pleasure and necessity ; {!>) the law of the heart, and the frenzy of self-conceit; (c) virtue, and the way of the world. Under the stand-point jjleasure and necessity, he included that form of self-consciousness which reason seeks in the satisfaction of the appetites and passions in pleasure ; but experiences that enjoyment has a limit, and that pleasure is contravened by necessity arising out of itself. Pleasure would make all a means of enjoy- ment ; but the world, the Universal, is not to be consumed. The consciousness for which pleasure has decayed, seeks happiness in the heart ; to make itself and all being happy, becomes its law. But the world, by its nature and its insti- tutions, renders this high undertaking difficult ; so that, as soon as it experiences this contradiction, the good heart in its self-conceit revolts to frenzy. Self-consciousness, there- fore, concludes to renounce happiness, and to follow the law of the heart. In duty it recognizes law as general necessity, and is ready to sacrifice its individualit}' to it. Virtue must perform dut}" for its own sake. All inclination must be ex- cluded. The Good exists only through virtue ; if it be not realized, it is a mere thought. Virtue is thus brought into conflict with the way of the world, foi' the w^orld, as such, is not virtuous. It guards individuality, and contends against vice only so far as it violates public law or becomes crime. Up to this limit individuality, even in its infirmities and vices, is allowed wide scope. Virtue revolts at the wickedness of the world, and spends itself in pompous delineations of its conflicts, its purity, its nobility, its incomj)arableness, its sacrifices. It thinks it very sad that virtue must so often HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. 63 succumb. The vicious world, strange to relate, does not col- lapse, but preserves itself in tolerable order. Individuality, by its varieties, produces manifoldness and interest. The world cannot dispense with it, nor indeed can virtue; for without it there can be nothing to contend against, nothing to be resigned to. Without the existence of tempta- tion, of vice, the hero of virtue would liave no cause for pride. Thus it is individuality which, by the resignation of virtue to it, has shown it itself preeminent. It is in and for itself real, i.e. it no longer seeks out of itself what it possesses within. In its immediacy it is indeed oiily natural individiuility, but as the certainty of reason it appears {a) as animal kingdom of mind ; {!>) as law-giving ; (c) as law-proving reason. As animal kingdom of mind, it produces itself in works in which it gives its peculiarity an objective expression. Such a work is not absolutely universal, for this it can represent only according to what individuality in its particularity is able to do ; and therefore the latter modestly asserts that it intended merely a contribution to the Universal, and that it designed what was done to be referred not to itself, but to the subject. But the work also stands in relation to others who apprehend and judge of it. Since these are also individual ties, their judgment is also colored by this peculiarity, although they likewise modesth' insist that not themselves, but the subject alone is concerned. Thus deception arises from both sides. The producer makes the subject his own, wishes to display himself in it — to put his own talent, culture, skill, mind to account. Thus not only the subject, but essentially he him- self, is concerned in the work. The critic, on the other hand, rightly says that he must judge of the work as good, bad, or inditierent, only because the subject demands it ; but, at the same time, the judgment is his, and expresses his penetra- tion, erudition, taste, and mind. It is, therefore, his own indi- viduality which comes into account in his judgment, and he deceives himself and others if he asserts that it remains neu- tral. When this deceit is recognized on both sides, conscious- ness ascends to that instance in which both producer and critic have to subject themselves to the conception of reason as law. Reason is the criterion which must be applied both to production and judgment. Reason gives laws, j)ractical, 64 Hefj/el's Phenomenology of Mind . HBsthetic, &-C, But these numerous laws, which exist with and through each other, require in turn a demonstration of how far thov are rational and at one with each other. Law-pioving reason seeks not, as it were, to annul laws, but to retine them by its critique, to liberate them from their isolation and one-sideduess, and imperfect construction, in order, in them, to become absolutely certain of the truth of reason. This is the result of the develoj)ment of reason, i.e. of the stand-point of mind. Mind is self-certain of reason as its truth. It is {a) inimediatel}^ the true mind, or the morale; {h) self-estranged mind, or culture ; (c) mind certain of itself, or morality. To these conceptions Hegel limits the concep- tion of mind, which he distinguishes from that of religion. True mind, as moral, appears, according to Hegel, (a) in the ethical world ; {h) in ethical action ; (c) in the condition of rio-lits. The moral world is immediately included in the family and the nation, for lier«? freedom and necessity are indistin- guishabiy one. ]S"atural individuality, its external reality, pleasure and its limits, necessity, the good heart and its vani- ty, creative activity and criticism, law-giving and law-proving reason, are annulled in ethics. Man and woman as husband and wife, the latter as parents, parents as trainers of children, children as brother and sister, stand in spiritual relationship by virtue of their natural connection. Brother and sister sus- tain the purest relationship, because here the sexual passion is not concerned as it is between parents, after whose death the brother is the natural supporter and protector of the sis- ter. All families are individual in one people. Only the princely family in its individuality is at the same time the collectivity of the state. The ethical act springs from the ethics of the people, in which the reason of mind is present. The law which animates the ethical appears partly as divine, partly as human ; as divine in piety, which is especially cher- ished by woman, who is ordained by nature as guardian of the hearth ; as human in the law of the state, whose prime guardian is the prince. Divine and human law may collide, which for the individual is his fate. He bears the guilt of his fate, but in it becomes conscious of: the right which summoned him to the doing of his deed. He acted because, as a member HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. 65 of the family or state, he could act only so, and not otherwise. Right itself, in turn, acquits him of his guilt and his wrong — as Orestes, Creon, Antigone, rightly did wrong, wrongly did right. The consciousness of right makes man a person, and in the atomic individualization of personality, ethical unity resolves itself into the multiplicity of the indifferent masses, which again can be held together only by a single person as a despotic power. Right is cold and egotistic as long as it seeks only to accomplish itself. When husband goes to law with wife, parents with children, brothers and sisters with each other, the spirit of the ethical has vanished. The indi- vidual insists on his right whatever consequences may fol- low, but just for this reason right is cold and regardless. Mind which is estranged from itself presents itself {ci) in the world of its estrangement, partly as culture, partly as belief; (6) it becomes eclair cissement in that it opposes and makes an end of superstition ; (c) in absolute freedom estrangement has the sense of self-renunciation for something other than we ourselves really are. The right of person inheres therein as far as in this act the entire will is expressed. The imj)or- tance which the individual attains outside himself in society, depends upon whether he possess power or riches. Power is attained by state service ; riches, by augmenting posses- sions. In the former, he acts nobly when he devotes his efforts and his activity, even to the sacrifice of his own life, to the state ; in the latter, when his possessions, even to self- retrenchment, are given up to benefit the poor. Still the state is not without distrust of those in power, who serve it, lest they misuse their power against it. The client, the pauper, is not without inner indignation that benefits must be pre- sented to him. It seems to be chance that a person can ele- vate himself by means of power, riches, or indeed both — for power may lead to riches and riches to power — since indivi- duality, as such, is originally a stranger no less to power and honor than to riches. It can lose as well as possess both: Mind, therefore, seeks a possession which is inalienable from its individuality, and which can be affected by no mu- tations of power or riches. This possession is culture, which the individual gives himself. But culture is estrangement from his immediate naturalness, for it makes of man some- Vol. vi.— 5 Q6 HegeVs Fhenonienoloyy of Mind. thing other tliaii lie is by race, sex, &c. It raises hi in above the liazard of power or riches, for it is the self-consciousness of mind in its universality which can be snatched away by no fate. In cultured society the individual is signiiicant, not because lie is powerful or lich, but because he is cultured. Each signiiies only what he has made of liimself by culture. But there are of necessity different departments, grades, peculiarities, in culture; therefore it becomes its essential .interest to set up a standard of culture for individuals, for just here is shown liow one is cultured ; for the criteria which one api)lies characterize the stand-point of, his own culture. Judgments also become involved in contradiction; nay, one comes to appear talented by so much the less as he agrees with the judgment of others, or indeed with the judgment of the multitude. Thus arises a universal disintegration of mind, in which the chaos of various cultures and naturally contradictory judgments begets finally a chaotic; confusion, above which only faith emerges, which subordinates culture as a vanity of the present. Before God is no respect of per- sons. Neither might, nor riches, nor culture, entitle one to blessedness ; heaven demands from its own, not the evidence that they are talented, but the poor in spirit are blessed if they are pure in heart. But faith which is indifferent to it, agrees with culture in that it estranges the mind from imme- diate reality, for it transports it to the representation of a Beyond, of which, hcie, we can have no experience. In this fantastic world it is (^uite at home wntli its representations, and discerns that all must be just as it is. The eclair cAssement overtakes it nevertheless, because on the one side it clings to the supersensuous, yet on the other cannot deny that it wishes to hnd the sujiersensuous in the sensuous. Eclalrclsnement is the unavoidable product of culture which seeks satisfaction only in thought, and pushes forward faith with its double housekeeping in the present and in the Beyond. Faith, as genuine, does not think of making the sensuous the ground of blessedness, but it always contradicts itself by the weight which it lays upon the sensu- ous ; for, in spite of its insight into the transitoriness of what is earthly, and the nothingness of what is external, it believes in sacred i)laces, times, and pictures ; it believes in sanctifi- HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. 67 cation by washing, and by partaking of consecrated food and drink ; by acts of sense, pilgrimages, fasts, sconrgings, &c. It believes that eternal truth is contained in writings which have been preserved by chance, &c. Esx^ecially it represents the Beyond again in a form which is really only a copy of the human, of the Present. Its gods, angels, devils, have human shape. Angels play on harps, sing, &c. Faith revolts against this critique, which lacerates its very heart, just as the talented consciousness of culture revolts against its own distraction because the latter derisively expresses it. Eclaircissement has its truth in the thought of the useful- ness of things, for therein it attains the unity of being and of thought. Prosaic as the category of use may be, it still con- tains the thought of the end and aim for which things are present as means. It twines itself through all things as the bond which unites them to each other. All is useful. In nature, earth is useful to plants, plants to animals, animals to animals. All nature is useful to man, man to man ; and even religion is useful, for it constrains man patiently to en- dure the pains of the Present in view of the future To Be. The category of usefulness also contains the unity of thought and being of the idea and its reality, which, as deism and ma- terialism, are widely separate ; on the one hand, into the abstraction of a supreme essence, and into matter on the other. Its metaphysics knows only things and their proper- ties; and among things, useful or natural, full as many have hurtful relations, for what is useful in one respect harms in the opposite ; yet through this twofoldness of all things eclaircisse'ntent affirms the ever uniform stability of the world. As the true, the moral mind is merged in the condition of right ; so likewise the culture of the self-estranged mind is; merged in absolute freedom and terror. The thinking of the eclaircissement has disposed of all, and has left to conscious- ness, at last, only the thinking of thinking, for eclaircissement supremely respects the logic of the understanding that twice two is four. If pure thinking would give itself a content, it must determine itself as will ; but the will, conformably to the stand-point of thinking, will have to be a pure will, which wills itself in its universality. Yet since in its reality the will is always individual, universality as such can hold only a (38 HegeVs IVt en om en ology of Min d. negative relation to will when it wills to realize itself. It becomes a fanaticism which wonld exterminate the existing order of things. In so far as will assnmes the form of govern- ment, the purpose of which is to care for the general well- being, and to realize the will of all, it becomes an object of suspicion to individuals, because as such they possess the possibility of dissenting from the will of the government which assumes the stand-point of universality. To meet the danger thus arising, nothing remains but to put such to death. But individuals conversely become objects of suspicion to government, because it is government tliat,in their determin- ations, they do not seek the pure will of all, but rather some special end. (Tovernment is therefore accused of being par- 4iisan. and its members in turn are executed. A new govern- ment is instituted, which in a short time succeeds no better. The terror of death is the result of absolute freedom, which detects slavery in every ethical relation, in family, rank, office ; and fears, pei'secutes, and slays every individual who does not seem to come out into tlie colorless abstraction of freedom as absolute. In the dissolution of the world of culture, the onl\' stability is the mind's certainty of itself, or morality. The individual w^ho ascends the scaffold, not because he has committed a crime, but because he has expressed an opinion other than absolute freedom has declared valid by the stamp of univer- sality, dies with the certainty of having remained true to himself, of having acted correctly, morally. This certainly exalts liim above death, and destroys the terror which it is said to inspire. The moral view of the world looks above the Present far beyond into a relationship in which all the con- tradictions of histor}'^ shall be conciliated. In reality, to be sure, the highest good, the harmony of virtue with happiness, is not yet present, but is striven for as that which should be. If it had not to contend with vice, virtue would not be virtue. Without instincts, desires, passions, temptation, it would be without the material of conflict — would be an unemploj'ed, inactive virtue. It should prosper externally, for through its exertions to overcome the allurements of vice it acquires a certain claim upon happiness; but exjoerience shows that the virtuous often find the world very unfriendly, while the HegeVs Phenomenology of Hind. 69 vicious find it very comfortable. While, then, virtue, postu- lates happiness, although it confesses that in reality it by no means corresponds with the conception, its claim is no less unfounded than when the envy with which it looks askance at the i)rosperity of the vicious claims to be called virtuous. The moral order of the universe, according to Hegel, is a dissimulation \r)ersteThbng\ which its bad conscience, that it is not really virtuous or free from sensuousness, conceals un- der the comj)laint of the difficulties which assail the virtuous, and against the course of the world when the bad thrive and the good suffer hardship. And yet conscience can in fact become self-certain, because it is determined not by feeling, but by the conception of duty which is clear and unambigu- ous. The nev7 difficulty which now arises consists in the fact that duty which would perfect virtue as pure duty for its own sake, resolves self into a plurality of duties, so that although each individual is determined for himself, he may fall into doubt which to perform, or at least which to perform first. But in fulfilling one duty other duties may be violated, though it be only by omitting their performance. Hence, to act with perfect morality, it seems best not to act at all, for in so doing- one stains himself in some way with finitude. By the deter- mination of an act, no one can avoid exciting contradiction, or reaping blame. The fear of degrading its high ideal by expres- sion in action, of soiling it by contact \\'\\\\. vulgarity, drives back the jesthetic soul into itself to refresh itself in the purity of its inactivity, and with other {esthetic and congenial souls to fall into criticism of those who act and therefore err. The erring, however, who confesses his sin, thereby annihilates it. Should the aesthetic soul close itself aa^ainst him, it would itself become wicked. It must pardon him who confesses his wickedness ; for as he became wicked, so can he become good again. Thus the good must recognize the essence of equal freedom in the wicked, and, if he has confessed, cannot hard- heartedly hold itself aloof in privileged exclusiveness. The forgiveness of the wicked is the breaking through of religion, for it is the mind's act of majesty to make what has been done as though it were not done. In the act mind becomes con- scious of its sovereignty over nature and history. The wick- edness which I repent of, is as though it had not occurred. 70 HcgeVs PJieiiomenoloy y of Mind. I break ott' fioin my past, estrange myself from it, cast it from me as a nullity. In relitcion. mind as liuinan ascends to unitv with the divine, to certainty of absolute truth ; for this unity is truth. This sphere, in turn, begins as such from the bottom to build itself up. step by step, to perfection, viz. from the natural religion, through art-religion, to revealed religion. In natural reli- gion, mind beliolds the absolute still in natural existence, in the heavenly bodies, in plants, aninuils, until, as Hegel expresses it, like a master-workman, it encloses the hull of mind, its corpse, in the habitation which it, has prepared for it out of stone. Buiding now becomes the cultus. With it, mind passes over to art-religion, which venerates the divine in the Beautiful, which it produces in statues of deities hu- manly beautiful, in the beautifully formed contestants at gymnastic sports, and in epic, lyric and dranmtic poetry. In Phenomenology, Hegel has treated art only as religion, be- cause it here simply gains the siguilicance of the absolute, and in no sense serves as an ornament for prosaic ends, or as a means of recreation. But this jesthetic religion, after it has passed through the earnestness and pain of tragedy, dissolves into the frivolity and pleasure of comedy, after it has made all, even the gods of the nether world, its wanton sport. Now it becomes evident what mind is. Trust in the gods has van- ished— the oracles are dumb — the altars empty — hymns are words without power— priests are needy, weak mortals like others — the statues of the gods are but cold figures to which Faith no more lends a soul — Consciousness shudders back into itself in this mental waste, and can no longer save itself from the despair of its absolute misfortune by the scorn of comic perversion. God can be found as the true Clod neither in nature nor in art, but reveals Himself as such only in the real man who knows that he is one with Him in self-con- sciousness. God has not onl}^ human form, is the esthetic God, but becomes a man who can be felt, seen, heard. The absolute substance appears as an actual subject, which also really dies, i.e. the divine is the essence of the human self- consciousness ; all disunion is extinguished in the Atonement. Religion, therefore, already knows what truth is ; but its knowledge is j^et imperfect, for it has not yet the form of HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. 71 pure self-consciousness, of the conception, but of intuition and representation. Indeed, revealed religion cannot yet de- tach itself from the sense-colored breadth of representation. It goes back into the past, or forward to the future. In the course of the year, on its festal days, it lives through the cir- cle of its representatives in which truth presents itself to it in historical forms. It remains, therefore, to give to the abso- lute content absolute form. This is the hnal stand-point of phenomenally absolute knowledge, a beyond which has no passage to another, because in it not only truth but also certainty is posited as absolute. To elevate religious repre- sentation into the form of thought, is to dissolve it as repre- sentation ; to dissolve does not mean to destroy its content, l)ut to free it from its contradiction of representing the eter- nal in forms of adjacency and succession. That which should be absolutely conformable to self-consciousness, must belike itself pure idea, which, as absolute presence, is independent of time and space. Religious consciousness forgets itself mo- mentarily in its representations, but falls back from them into itself again, xlbsolute knowledge conceives not only its object in and for itself, but it conceives itself also in its knowledge. The position which Hegel has given to absolute knowledge, i.e. to speculative philosophy, became later the occasion of much opposition, since priests and theologians very naturally found in it an insufferable presumption which degraded reli- gion to a " mere representation." We will here only remark that science cannot dispense with the critique of faith, and faith can assume no privileged immunity from being really thought. The particular science of faith struggles against being dissolved in the general science of nature and of mind ; but really it cannot escape this fate, because this is neces- sarily involved in the relation between representation and thought. The miracles of faith are incomprehensible because they lack a rational nature. The}^ can be represented, but not thought. Thought can find a general content symboli- cally expressed, an abiding truth ; but, with this discovery, thought elevates its truth above its sensuous actuality, and transforms it into allegory. Miracles are to remain for faith an individual fact, which it devoutly gazes upon ; for science, 72. HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. they are to become a universality which is absolutely true. "When we glance back upon the Phenomenology in its to- tality, we must admit that it is a work which can be ranked in no traditional department, but at the same time we cannot refrain from the opinion that its greatness lies in its strange- ness and uniqueness. An ordinary schoolmaster's under- standing, which revolves with economical exactitude within the paragraphs of the text-book, never would have hit upon such a monstrosity. The nuistership with which Hegel cha- racterizes each particuLar stand-point of mind may pardon the occasional artifice of its deductions. His appositeness justifies, upon reflection, the apparent strangeness of his ex- pression. When, e. g., Hegel calls culture the self-estranged mind, the word has acquired the partial meaning of confusion of mind, like the French word aliener. All culture sustains a negative relation to our immediateness. We have in schools Greek and Latin, which we do not speak in life, but in which we estrange ourselves from our every-day reality ; our com- panions travel among " strangers "" in order to exalt them- selves above the narrowness of liome-life, &c. Hence the expression " estrangement '' is quite right. Each new stand- point which consciousness enters upon is absolute for it so long as it deals with it ; as, conversely, the world — in itself ever the same — is new for every new generation. It was with deep design that Hegel included the practical side of mind in the Phenomenology, a deduction of absolute knowledge from dogmatism and skepticism ; realism and idealism would not have corresponded to the totality of mind. The forms of con- sciousness which Phenomenology exhibits in a long series^ are constant elements of mind wliicli lie between the extremes of sensuous certainty and absolute knowledge, and which hence always and every where reproduce themselves; in their individualization thev mav likewise modify the form of their appearance. Each is relatively the whole, but it is first in the absolutely free self-consciousness of spirit that it com- prehends itself as the idea of truth. No one will deny that sensuous certainty and perception, that the conflict of self- consciousness for recognition, that stoicism and skepticism, that the efforts of the unhappy self-consciousness to solve the HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. 73 contiacliction between heaven and earth, — are stand-points which ceaselessly renew themselves among men. The case is the same with reason, which can never become weary of observing the nature of natural phenomena, in order therein to find itself. It has been supposed, in considering the laws of physiognomy, that Hegel intended, with Lichtenburg, to deride a presumptive science, and that only a transient mania of his time induced him to incorporate this matter ; but the interest of mind to rediscover itself in the eternal reality of its form is constant. Our interest will always be excited in observing the physiognomy and cranial development of a Raphael, Schiller, Napoleon, Talleyrand, Socrates, and oth- ers, and therein tracing the expression of their minds. The realization of rational self-consciousness in pleasure and ne- cessity, in the good heart and in the frenzy of conceit, or in virtue and the course of the world, astonishes us at first by the originality of its delineation ; but it makes, nevertheless^ a constant factor in the phenomenal knowledge of mind. Among the Greeks, e. g., it was the Cyrenian school which gave utterance to the experience that pleasure has its limits in necessity, and the Hegesians, who proceeded upon the attempt to constantly fulfil pleasure, concluded upon suicide because the}'- found it impossible. The author of the Kohe- leth, among the Hebrews, expressed the same experience of the vanity of all" things. Individuals ever repeatedly attempt to make pleasure their principle, but in the satisfaction of their desires they ever find the experience unavoidable, that in enjoyment they have subjected themselves to a necessity inseparable from pleasure. It is the same with the good heart and virtue in their one-sidedness and inexj)erience. "When Hegel shows that virtue may be overcome by the course of the world, it may seem that he places no high estimate upon virtue, but only that virtue succumbs in the conflict with the course of the world, which wrongly estimates its own princi- ple, the right of individuality, and regards its own sacrifice .as the Absolute. Eating and drinking, sleeping and beget- ting of childi'en, working and recreation from labor in sport, and the accumulation of x^roperty, will ever strike out new courses. The existence of monks and nuns presupposes as its condition the existence of the course of the world, from 74 HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. which tliey retreat behind hii^;)! walls. Individuality then makes its appearance as that which is real in and for itself. This stand-i)t)int also makes a constant element of the becom- ing mind, which produces itself as its object in what it cre- ates, in which it deposits its entire peculiarity, but thereby calls out the Judgment of other individualities. This "ani- mal kingdom of mind," as Hegel sportively and wdttily ex- presses himself, is likewise a constant element of history ; and, to become convinced that this is the case, it is only necessary to read prefaces to books wiiicli are published, to lind tlie assurance that their authors are concerned only in their respective subject-matter, to which they otter their mod- est contribution, or, on the other hand, to read the critiques of books in which the reviewers assert, with praise or blame, that they are concerned only about the subject-matter. Law- giving and law-proving reiison are constantly ])resent in the constitutional conflicts of states. It is proposed, for instance, to abolish the death penalty ; the law is subjected to criti- cism, the grounds which sustain the proposition are exam- ined, &c., w^hether they are in accordance with reason. In the description of mind it has been said that Hegel at first had before his eyes the Hellenic ethics as iEschylus and Sophocles depicted it, but in the dissolution of the true ethi- cal mind in the legal condition which strengthens the ego- ism of persons, the Roman empire. Then he makes the process of the estrangement of mind complete itself in Feudalism and Catholicism ; but the culture of humanism, on the otlier hand, reacts in eclaircissement^ and absolute freedom culminates in the terrorism of the French revolution. In the stand-point of morality he alludes to the dualism of German j)hilosophy in the Fair Saint, especially to Jacobi's ALL-WILL and Waldemar. It may. be unhesitatingly granted that from the phases of history he derived his colors for these stand-points, but it does not follow that these are not con- stant elements in all history. Hegel depicts — in the act of the ethical mind — e.g. blood revenge, w^ith unmistakable reference to Orestes and (Edipus ; but blood revenge is a con- stant element of the ethical in the family, among all peoples who are making the transition from the sphere of their natu- ral condition to that of the state. The Arab who avenges the HegeVs Flienomenology of Mind. 75 death of his father, is in this respect as ethical as Orestes. That Hegel ojjposes right, as private right, to the ethical, is likewise to be understood generally, although Roman juris- prudence carried out the conception of personal atomism most perfectly. When children as heirs of their patrimony do not quarrel about their respective sliares, but seek to ter- minate the strife by judicial decision, the very spirit of the ethical has vanished. Even Aristophanes, in his comedies, attacked the bad disposition of the citizens, who became en- tangled in their private interests and their lawsuits about Tneum and tniim, and allowed the ancient virtue of Marathon, which guided itself in view of the whole, to fall into decay. Culture in a distinct sense, where the word denotes primitive civilization, is also a constant element among all people, who, by reverence of the power of the state, or by the splendor of riches, have elevated themselves above the signilicance of the individual, to self-consciousness of mind. When Hegel here, in characterizing the peculiar distraction to which this stand- point leads, borrows a few features from Diderot's dialogue, Rameaiis Ne^^lieio, one must not be so narrow as to believe that he thought only of the intellectual French society of the 18th century. This language, which levels all difference of station ; which expresses with spirit all the phenomena of mind, even the most depraved ; which discloses with shame- less publicity all the contradictions of mind. — attracts inte- rest to itself whenever the individual, by way and manner of speaking, attests that he is a man of culture, and when com- parison of tendency of independence and of degree of culture is the chief topic of the general discourse. Lucian among the Greeks, Petronius among the Romans, Heine among the Ger- mans, discover a language similar to that of Diderot among Frenchmen. Eclalrcissement is no less a constant element of history, for it arises from culture. The Sankhya philoso- phy of the Indians is an eclair cissement of their Mythology. The doctrine of the sophists was an eclaircissement among the Greeks, as in modern times the movement of the ITtli and 18th centuries. Over against the popular belief of the Greeks, Plato with his critique of their Mythology appeared as an apostle of eclaircissement, and, like those in England, France and Germany, would substitute morals in its place. 76 HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. The stuiid-])oint of absolute freedom, i.e. of that freedom which wills tlie will only as universal, may seem to be so designated by Hegel as though only the hrst French revolu- tion hovered befoi-e him ; but in itself this form of conscious- ness is a constant element of history, where democratic and communistic tendencies pass over into fanaticism. This element was present in the German peasant war, among- the English Puritans, and the social reformers of the Paris revolution of February, as well as among the Jacobins, who overthrew the Girondists. Morality is depicted with extraor- dinary accuracy bv Hegel; no one can doubt that here he detects one of the most general stand-points of mind : but the turn which Hegel gives to it — viz. in making religion, or the certaint}^ of the unity of the huiuan and divine mind, to emerge from the wicked man's confession of guilt and from his pardon — may seem- peculiar. Otherwise, morality ap- pears as that inclination Avhicli religion absorbs in itself, as private right absorbs the aesthetic; morale (ethical condition). But morality has exalted itself above this stand-point; and now Hegel shows how mind, apprehending itself in con- science, passes over from the isolation of its self-certainty, through pardon of the wicked, to the truth of the commu- nity. This is one of his most profound and beautiful devel- opments. That religion is construed as a constant element of mind is of course self-evident, and the question can only arise how far the differences between natural religion, art- religion, and revealed religion, are constant. This question is answered by the fact that every man must in childhood pass through the stages of fetichism and pantheism, which compose the essence of natural religion. Even if people ex- isted no longer in a state of nature, still the contemplation of nature in sun, moon, plants, and animals, would precede the representation of a creative God, even for children who grew up within the pale of a revealed religion. Children often sustain the same relation to animals which men in a state of nature do in animal worshij). Hegel treated art-religion in general as the presentation of art, because only as religion does it make the beautiful a pure Absolute. Art lies without as a moment in the stand-points of production and culture. The beautiful is now, to be sure, the absolute in respect to HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. 77 form, but only the {esthetic stand- point sublimates the truth of the absolute and must subordinate itself to it, as occurs in revealed religion, Avliich makes art a means in its cultus. Roman Catholicism, in architecture, sculjjture, music, and poesy, has produced as excellent works of art as the Greek a,rt-religion, but religion as such has ever distinguished itself from these works even when superstition has confounded them. Finally, absolute knowledge exists in all philosophical en- deavor as a constant element, for philosophy must strive for such a certainty of truth that even the formal side of knowl- edge may be complete, that certainty may become true, and truth certain. Philosophy is, therefore, capable of endless de- velopment, since neither its breadth nor the depth of knowl- edge can have a limit. Tliat all moments of the experience of consciousness make up constituent elements of mind, Hegel distinctly affirms in saying that phenomenology has the same content as a system of science. The latter is not power, nor is it riches. The difference lies in the fact that that which phenomenology presents as a stand-point of phenomenal knowledge in the relation between consciousness and its ob- ject, so that knowledge during its becoming does not conceive itself until by its mutation it has arrived at a result, although we who observe its process can apprehend it before it be- comes clear to itself — that this appears in the system as a pure, organic conception, no longer confused with consciousness. The sequence of the conceptions is in general the same in both spheres, although with the difference which is condi- tioned by the nature of consciousness. In the history of con- sciousness, self- consciousness, reason, mind, religion, and ab- solute knowledge, follow in order ; but in history many modifi- cations occur through freedom, chance, arbitrariness, which are eliminated from the necessity of the system. The stand-point of natural religion, e.g., may be interrupted by the violent in- trusion of revealed religion ; for what wide extremes may be united in consciousness ! Take a New Zealander of to-daj^, as he may be seen and spoken to in London, who in his youth has participated in cannibal feasts, but is now converted to Methodist Christianity. Thirty or forty years ago he ate hu- man flesh, now at the Lord's table he partakes of the body and 78 HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. blood of Christ. An imi)ortant point of tlie succession is that eacli liiixlier stand-point elevates each lower into itself, and reduces it to a moment wliich disap})ears in itself. That Aviiicli in ail earlier stage had absolute significance for consciousness, loses it in the liiglnM-. The most earnest occu- pations of earlier ages, as Hegel expresses it, sink in an advanced stage to be childish ])hiys. It might be asked whether many of the elements wliich TIegel adduces have not now entirely vanished. Under art-religion, for example,, he speaks of living art-work, and understands thereby the reverence in which the Greeks held beauty, and the strength and sup])lciit'ss of the human body. The Greeks, indeed,, deilied beautiful men because they were beautiful. This element exists among us no longer as a religion. We build temples to no man now because he is beautiful, but in the cir- cus we admire the beauty, strength, and gymnastic virtuoso- ship, of the human body, i.e. the living art-work. It is de- graded to a mere moment of secularity, but it is not wanting. The successive connection of the forms of consciousness, which advances from sensuous certaintv to absolute knowledge, is therefore necessar}^ If we have attained a certain grade of consciousness we must advance to philosophy: and hence, not only in Greece but in China and India, nor only among Christians but among Moliamedans, not only among Euro- peans but among Americans, we see philosophers arise; for even the practical, gain-seeking, pure utilitarianism of the Yankees has not prevented the appearance among them of a- Parker, an Emerson. Hegel preceded his Phenomenology by an extended pre- face, in which he defined his relation to the dominant views respecting the essence and method of philosophy still more distinctly than in the introduction to his article concerning the difference between the systems of Fichte and Schelling. He strongly contended, moreover, against the degeneracy of Schelling's philosophy, which among many of its adherents had sunk to a mere formalism, and whicli sought to conceal the want of scientific earnestness partly by fantastic deco- ration, and partly by the assumption of dictatorial imperti- nence and prophetic unction. Hegel contended no less against the insipidity of eclair cissement, which sought a narrow satis- HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. 79 faction in the temporal, than against the pseudo-geniality of romanticism, which was designed to supersede the pains and the thoroughness of learning, by simple inspiration. He gave a careful critique of the method of the scientific knowledge, which, with precipitate construction according to superficial antitheses, is not adequate to the task. The truest method, he affirms, is the dialectic, which makes the negative an im- manent moment of development, because negation is not only negative, but at the same time positive ; for its result is not pure nullity, but rather a higher determination, in which that which was denied is ideally preserved. Nothing is lost to this method, but it enriches itself, in its progress from negation to negation, b}^ an equal number of positions. He expresses this thought in such a manner as to affirm that the philosopher must entirely abstract from himself, and in the movement of conception reserve for himself only the attitude of a spectator. " Substance must be grasped as subject" ; — with these words, which have become so full of fate for his philosophy, he would indicate that the idea for itself is inde- pendent; that, although we think it, it determines itself en- tirely independent of us, and that its relation to other ideas can really proceed only from it and not from us. When, e.g., we think the idea of identity, it, and not we, is the ground that the next idea is that of difference. It is not we who de- termine identity to difference, but identity determines itself to difference, for difference has a meaning only as difference of identity. The idea of identity moves, therefore, of itself to its opposite idea, to difference, and leaves to the philoso- pher only the observation of this process. It is, in fact, the original sense of the word that substance in itself is subject. Substance here signifies the essential content, subject the form of knowledge. The subject must here be not the knowing philosopher, but the idea itself. Still the philosopher is also the subject which thinks the idea, but his thinking is not bound to the self-determination of the idea, into which the philosopher, with absolute renun- ciation of his own individual subjectivity, must think him- self. Hegel's thought may be thus explained : In common logic, it is said that in judgment we join a predicate to a sub- ject. In this the subject appears as passive, and receives the 80 HegcVs Phenomenology of Mind. predicate throuirli us. Aecording to this logic, it is we wlio bind tlie predicate to the subject by the copula. Hegel reverses the matter by saying that it is the subject which determines itself to its predicate ; for, if this be not the case, it is in vain that we join a predicate to a subject, becanse the Judgment can be only in so far true as the predicate either inheres in the subject as a casual and relative determination, or is immanent in it as a necessary and absolute natura sua. When I judge, ''This circle is large," this judgment is true only in so far as greatness inheres in it. But greatness la only a relative determination in the relation of this circle to others. A circle may just as well be relatively small. If I judge, "The circle is a self-enclosed curve," this judgment is a necessary, absolute one, for without this determination the circle would not be a circle. Thus it is the idea of a circle itself that immanently determines itself to its predicate. It is not I who produce this idea, but the idea which produces itself in me. The predicate of the subject circle, by which it is a circle, does not depend upon me. I recognize it, I utter it, I make it my object; but I do not produce it. But the circle, because it is a circle, produces itself in the object. By the example which I have just chosen, I am reminded that, in the jjreface of the Phenomenology, Hegel would make of mathematics merely a science of the understanding, partly because its content, space in geometry, and unity in arith- metic, is so meagre, and partly because the construction of mathematics turns upon formal identity. A synthetic or an analytic course rather than the dialectic must be referred to mathematics. But when, as Hegel affirms, truth can become certain of itself only in the form of dialectic method ; when further, according to him, mathematics forms a necessary member in the system of science ; when, finally, it is the con- ception of space with which the idea as nature first found its existence, — it is hard to see why mathematics should be an exception to all other content. That it never has been, is no reason why it never should be treated dialectically. The con- ception of the one of quantity, &c., i.e. of arithmetic, Hegel has already presented dialectically in the first part of his Logic: "Why should geometry dispense with the dialectic ?" Quantity does not even exclude qualitative distinctions, but HegeVs Phenomenology of Mind. 81 is partly a moment of them and partly qualitatively distin- guished in itself; for an arithmetical progression, e.g., is not only qualitatively different from a geometrical progression, or the acute angle is not only quantitatively but qualitatively different from an obtuse angle. The one is smaller, the other larger, than a right angle; and just for this reason they are opposites in form. The lack of rational nature [begriffslosig- kelt\ which Hegel charges upon quantity, is only relative. Through the integral and differential calculus, and through descriptive geometry, modern mathematics has in fact alrea- dy become dialectic. Hegel believed that an example of the dialectic method was afforded in the Phenomenology itself. Without boast- ing, yet with profound self-feeling, he expressed in the pre- face the consciousness of having found that method which the future would confirm as the only true one. Though it be acknowledged that he is right, that henceforth without the dialectic method philosophy would no longer be in a condi- tion to satisfy the conceptions of science, and that it no less than others cannot submit to an arbitrary treatment ; still it cannot be denied that the method is open to great danger, and that it no less than others may degenerate to arbitrary treatment. The philosopher shall remain out of the question. The idea shall determine itself through itself, shall adopt nothing into itself from without. This is the postulate. It is, indeed, justified; but, in tine, it is the philosopher even here who advances with his thoughts as thinking subject from conclusion to conclusion, and what he holds to be a necessary correlation describes as such. Just this description is the most dangerous moment, for its extent, its tone, its address, remains more dependent upon the philosopher than its form would indicate. Experience has subsequently shown that the descriptive manner of the Hegelian school, especially through imitation of the Phenomenology, degenerated into a mere assertory procedure, which was in no respect better than the polarities of Schelling's philosophy, the antitheses and syntheses of Fichte's, or the categories of Kant. The dialectic, which was to have engendered the most active self- "^ movement of science, stiffened into the most arbitrary and lifeless dogmatism, which often became the more contradic- Vol. vi.— a 82 Trend eleiiburg on HegeVs System. toiT the moiv ir set up pretension to absolute infallibility. If the application of the dialectic method had been guarded from everv error, llesiel himself, for instance, would not have set the example of altering the position of ideas in his sys- tem. "Without the Logic, the danger would have become still fjreater. For profound penetration into the essence of science, for sharp criticism of the delusions behind Avhicli scientism has taken refuge in order to preserve itself in the public mart as authority, for noble dignity of scientific temper, for spirited apprehension of tlu^ entire turning-point of the age, — the pre- face to Hegel's Phenomenology can only be compared with that which Kant introduced in the second edition of his Cri- tique of Reason. This is its counterpart in literature. THE LOGICAL QUESTION IN HEGEL'S SYSTEM. Translated from tlic German of TKENDELENiiURC, by Tiios, Davidson. [Gontinved from our last iminher. — Ed.] In the first place, the Negation is the inborn impulse which drives pure thinking along from stage to stage. No sooner is a concept produced than it turns over, from its own inner nature, into its negation, and we have before us the problem of thinking a positive and a negative together. This problem is solved by the creation of a mediator}^ concept which recon- ciles the two antitheses. Thus the progress of the Dialectic is conditioned by the Negation. The investigation showed that the apjDlied negation cannot be a pure logical negation, the relation of not-A to A, but that it must be real opposition in order to produce a Contra- ry— an OjDposition. But since the Contrary does not run oflT into indefinite contradiction or opposition, into mere unlim- ited negation, but is on the contrary another Positive, which, concrete and limited in itself, contains the negation of An- other [somewhat] only as one relation, it became apparent at once that the real opposition — the negation of the Dialectic — was not to be reached in any merely logical way. Not only Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 83 was this sliown in general terms, "but the same demonstration was further applied to the most important concepts oi" the system (e.g. to repulsion and attraction, to whole and force, to substance and causality, to nature and spirit), and it was proved in the particular cases that the negativit}' always goes beyond its logical essence, and the opposition does not spring from the pure thought, as is pretended, but from the apprehensive intuition, which arbitrarily condenses the inde- tinite looseness of the logical negation into a positive form, and, in that form, seizes and holds it. If, now, the antithesis is supposed to be evolved from the thesis by negation, so likewise thesis and antithesis are car- ried lip by Id entity to a concept which stands above them, and is designated as their truth. The identity, therefore, appears in the result as the real unity, as the force of concretion. If, however, we probe it to the bottom, we tind that it is far short of what it professes to be ; that it is nothing but the reflec- tion of a relative, logical likeness — an abstraction which bleaches and blots out. Becoming^ in Hegel's Logic, is the first act of identity. Being and Nothing being comprehended under it. Pure Being, we are told, is empty Being — Nothing ; and empt}" Being is pure Being. The one is what the other is. The two are identical, and, thought as such, they are Becoming. In spite of this, this identity of the reflection is ■only a self-annihilating comjiromise. withoTit a trace of living unity to transform in a real manner Being into Nothing, and Nothing into Being. It is the completed levelling of two con- cepts, viz. pure Being and empty Being, while it is anj^thing but a case of mutual intus-susception or interpenetration. In such identity, the antitheses blunt each other, instead of bestirring themselves and becoming one as they should do. What is here summarized in the well-known example of dia- lectic Becoming, reappears, as the Investigations prove, in the most essential concepts of the system, e.g. where the Finite unites with itself in the Infinite ; where the freedom of the concept is conjured out of the necessity of substance; where the idea is defined as the absolute unit}'^ of concept and objec- tivity. The power of unity over the greatest antitheses rests on the identity of such impotent assimilation. The real in- terpenetration is forced in. Compared with the boldness of 84 Trenddciibunj on HeycVs System. the idea of reconciling- antitlie:>(>s \\\x\\ each other, the proof which pure thonuht has to olt'er for the fact appears rather intiriu. Its trutli has its origin in something quite different fruui any such mere logical act. Thus the hinges of the system break down. The investigation showed further that a(1 injinitum pro- cession, a meie indirect proof, was frequently misused in order to obtain a pt)siti\e creation of an opposite. It turned out, likewise, that the Immediate, which cannot appear in the pure thought as sensuous, is nevertheless tacitly intro- duced int() the sensuous apprehension. After such results, the internal connection — the glory of the system — could not hold out. Notwithstanding, this too was subjected to- a special investigation. Then, indepen- dently of the necessary consequences of the points already made, it became manifest in many other places that the intrin- sic connection which asserts the self-development of science from its own most undisputed ground, viz. the concept, in opposition to kncwledge derived from without, is merely ap- pearance, bold assertion. When the determinations of science, in the dialectic and internal contemplation of the concept, had to make a stej) in advance, instead of doing this unas- sisted, they betrayed, when examined more closely, the foreign impulse of external experience. What ought to ori- ginate from itself is simply borrowed. Anticipations of con-^ cepts, and foreign matter, picked \\\) at random, were shown to exist in the most important creations of the Dialectic ; the former, for example, in Measure, in the Freedom of the Con- cept, in the Totality of the Unconditioned, in the Transition of the Idea into Nature, already frequently alluded to ; the latter, in the logical treatment of Matter, in the logical cate- gories of Mechanism, Chemistry, Life, &c. We are thus led to consider the relation of the dialectic method to the mate- rial of experience. Hegel had almost asserted, in regard to this, that the dialectic process presupposes the facts of expe- rience, but that it exalts them into the true rational form. Who could have refrained from admiring, with an admiration amounting to astonishment, in Hegel himself — from his Phe- nomenology down to his jjosthumous Lectures — the extreme universality of his empirical knowledge ! And no one asserted Trendelenlmrg on HegeVs System. 85 that Hegel could have meant that the philosopher ought to " suck the world out of his tinger-ends." But tlie qiu^stion here was not one touching his subjective knowing or his opin- ions, but one relating to the objective relation of his absolute method ; and then it was shown that this method, strictly confined to itself, and advancing by means of borrowed crutches, had, by its very nature, no opening, whether d'^or or window, to let in experience, and because it nevertheless tacitly and stealthily oj)ens a back door to it, it occupies an uncritical position to experience, with its indefinite exjDres- sion regarding presupposition, and is perhaps more uncritical than unspeculative, but careful. Empiricism. It is impossible to find a place for experience, without making holes in the internal connection of the self-i)roductive Concept. The speculative method undertook to show that the pro- cess whereby the concepts were produced was likewise the process which produced the thing. Thus the dialectic and the genesis of the thing seemed necessarily to coincide. On closer examination, however, it became apparent that the dia- lectic process in most cases inverts the genesis of the thing, or passes over it without concern, and without touching it. In view of this surprising discrepancy, the advantage which had just been gained had to be abandoned, and refuge to be taken in a distinction which had not originally lain in the plan, that the eternal birth of the pure concept was not the temporal development of the becoming thing, and that the two did not necessarily coincide. The dialectic then admit- ted itself to be, in individual cases, a methodical liysteron- proteron. If, in the dialectic method, the syllogism and its figures came to assume such importance that the dictum was trum- peted abroad, " God is a syllogism ; the state is a syllogism ; the planetary system is a syllogism,'' &c., on closer examin- ation there turned out to be in this doctrine an obscurity and confusion which distinctly showed themselves in the appli- cation. Here too, in a word, the dialectic topsy-turvy showed itself in the very dictum itself. If we were to construe men- tal maladies according to the same type — if we were to say, for example, that Pietism unites itself with Mysticism to form Phariseeism, as the Hegelian terminology would express it, 80 Trendelenburcj on HegeVs System. we might also say, with equal right, ''Everything iiTatioiial is a svllos:isni.'" Tims the doctrine lias overshot itself. .Vfter siicli results, neither the leading thought of the dia- lectic method nor the carrying out of it could be recognized, and the ijuestion now came to be, whether openly to abandon the philoso})hical prejudice of the present, or to refute the charo:es brouii'lit against the system. So far, neither one thing nor the other was done. The for- mer was diflicult; along with the dialectic method, it would have been necessary to abandon Hegel's S3'Stem as a system; for the two are one, just as the critical system and Kant's system are one. The second looked easier perhaps, and yet it did iu)t take place. Perhaps silence was meant for a refu- tation. Erdnumn })ublished his well thought-out Outlines of Logic and Metaphysics in 1841. In certain turns of phrase and remarks, he seemed to have reference to the Investigations just mentioned, nay, even in places to yield points to them. But he did not mention this fact, and left it to be guessed by the initiated. Erdniann changes several things in the mat- ter, and almost everything in the expression, which he to some extent managed so dexterously as to take the j)oint oif any objection that had been made. But the Investigations had attacked the thing itself, and could hardly be brought to silence by a change in the mode of ex})ression. An}^ one who will take the trouble to compare it with this new presen- tation may satisfy himself on the point. Besides this, it might easily be shown that the altered expressions, where they mean anything at all, imply a change of view, and an alteration in the thing. It would be desirable to see these differences discussed within the school itself, in order to show their magnitude. Erdmann's Logic, although written in the spirit of Hegel, is not altogether HegeTs old logic. Treating matters in an opposite spirit, aj)peared in 1841 Werder's Logic, a Commenta.ry and Supplement to HegeVs Science of Logic. It belongs to the idea of a commentary, that it shall smooth over difficulties and disentangle intrica- cies. Up to that time, all philosophical c(^mmentaries had been written with this purpose — e.g. commentaries on Aris- totle, for thousands of years. This Commentary to Hegel's Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 87 Logic took no notice of the Investigations., directed against it, and probably did not consider the doubts expressed as worth discussion. As for the rest, he invented a new logical category, calling the opponents of the system " the Lord's heaviest cross," and those who could not accept the concept of Clod set up by the pure thinking, and therefore rejected it, ^' God's sorest suffering, a passion to which the history of the Passion is but a shadow.'' Still, there were some innovations in this Logic too, and, although it had appeared as a supj)le- ment, it was rather an annihilation of the original, as even the adherents of the system seemed to admit. Particularly remarkable was the correction which appeared at the very beginning. The identity of pure Being and Nothing in the production of Becoming had always excited opposition, and difficulties of various kinds had been found in it. Among other things, people had found it impossible to think the identity of Being and Nothing, because, after all, Nothing- appeared to be less than pure Being — to be a minus ; people could not conceive how two empty abstractions — pure Being and pure Nothing — could mutually complement each other, so as to form the concept of Becom/ing. These difficulties were settled by an emendation. It was asserted that Hegel had been wrong in holding the difference between pure Being and Nothing to be inexpressible — a mere opinion. The dif- ference was quite considerable. It was discovered that Nothing is more than pure Being, a 'plus ; that Nothing is the most comprehensive something. " In Nothing, Being, of itself, breaks the silence in itself. Nothing is Being's coming to consciousness, the rise of perception in it, its glance into itself, the salient point of its originality. In Nothing the sacred ambiguity of the emptiness of Being dis- closes itself. That it is nothing else than Self -Being., Being - tJiroaglt-iUelf ; that it, singly and alone, is full of itself, — this is its emptiness, this is Nothing. Thus Nothing is Be- ing's knowledge of its fulness, of its repletion from itself, of its free action, of its self-creation ; and, stirring itself in itself, in the energy of this Knowing, Being is no longer Being, but Becoming." " When I say Nothing, I know more than when I say Being, because it is more ; because it is Being revealing itself, bursting its husk — because it is naked Being, the spirit 88 Trend elenhurg on HegeVs System. of Being, Being in Being/' Finally, when the Commentary deeljired the dialectic to he the '^Reverie of Logic," and treat- ed it as snch, pure thinking, as far at least as principle was concerned, became vague thinking. The Hegelian school has thus far allowed this Logic to pass muster, without rejecting or disowning it. In fact, the great differences which subsist within the school seem all to rest, pretty much in the same way as the schisms in the Church used to do ; tlie Church forgot these^ when she had to combat with heretics or heathens outside. Gabler gave a lengthy review of the Logical Investigations in the Jahrbiicher fur loissenschaftlicJie Kritik, Oct., 1841, No. 65 sq.. Art. I. In this, however, he has criticised a re- sult without its premises — the twentieth section, without the nineteen that precede it and foi-m its basis. The diale(;tical question, in the lirst place, is nc)t touched upon at all, my understanding of it being merely set aside as an "incompre- hensible misunderstanding.'' As no harm is done by such assertions, we wait to see the proof of them in the second article; otherwise we might turn the tables and repeat the comj^liment of ''incomprehensible misunderstanding.'' The aim of the criticisms is to show that the Logical Investiga- tions know less of God than the dialectic method, which is absolut(3ly and directly the thinking of God. This we will- ingly acknowledge, if the dialectic method be true ; but we had proved that it is false, and therefore realh' knows noth- ing. If one, therefore, meant to argue in this way, he could not aftbrd to omit the opposite proof. At all events, until it appears, his assertion has no foundation. Other critics have taken it for granted that the w^hole ques- tion has been set at rest by this veto of Gabler's. For exam- ple, we lind iu a polemical article: ''The main objection, derived from Hegel's unexplained assumption of movement, is developed in the Logical Investigations., and duly weighed by Gabler in a criticism of that work." The truth is, that in that criticism not a word is said about such objections, and we cannot say that we at all admire the spirit of such tactics. No explanation, such as the above words would imply as having been made, was intended b}^ Gabler, who, at the end of his criticism, openly states that he will deal Avith the Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 80 lieavj^ charges brought against Hegel's philosophy, in a second article. In support of the dialectic method, which thinks the thought of God, reference is repeatedly made to the Christian Logos (Cf. inter al. Gabler's Criticism, p. 570). We take the refer- ence to mean tliis : Through Ilim and for Him all is created, and He is before all, and all exists in Him. If, then, He be the head of the body— that is, of the Church — He belongs to us, and we may comprehend Him in pure thought. This conclu- sion will hardly be permitted to any one who understands the Christian Logos in the sense demanded by the entire con- text. The same Logos that in the beginning was God — the world-creating Logos — redeems men from the dominion of darkness and sin. It is this function that is the inheritance of the Church ; but from this to attempt to authenticate, by a sort of Christian testimony, the act of the pure idea, which produces the world-creating Logos out of itself, is something quite new, and hardly coincides with the notion of the Apostle Paul, who openly says to the Church that '' now we know but in part, ''^ and "behold but as through a glass dark- ly." If from words like these any one were to conclude that the Christian view of the Universe was universal skepticism, he would be as far from the truth as he who should cite the Christian Logos in authentication of the stand-point of the speculative method. Such confusion of thought only tends to warp unbiassed investigation. Reference has been made by various persons, and on vari- ous occasions, to the Phenomenology, as properly preceding the Logic of Hegel. "The Thinking which in the Phenomen- ology works itself up out of the phenomena, in the Logic produces itself freely — plays with itself" (Werder, p. 25). This is, perhaps, implied in Gabler's remark (Art. I., p. 519), that in the d priori (process) of dialectic movement, "man's reproductive reflection has already swallowed the whole of the d posteriori''^ (das menschliche reproductive iVac/^denken Piabe] das gauze Aposteriorische hereits im Leibe). The expression can signify nothing but the digestion in the Phe- nomenology. As to the Phenomenology, there seem to be only two posi- tions possible for it. Either it is a link in the system, and 90 Trendelc^nhurfi on HegeVs System. then it is a part ot' the phiU)sophy of the subjective spirit — and this, iiuhu'd, is the position assigned to it by Hegel in the Encycldpcclia, — or it is a propaedeutic, meant to educate the consciousness up to the speculative stand-point, in which case its place is before the system, and it stands in the exter- nal relation of an introduction. Hegel, in the BfiCf/clopeditf. i)roduced his system as a whole, and it is the most complete outline of a system, whether we consider the whole or the parts, that the history of philoso- phy is acquainted with. We must accept the relations in which he here places the different branches to one another, as he gives them. Since then, in- the Encyclopedia, the Plie- nomenology follows long after the Logic, the Nature- PliUoso- pliy and the Anthropology coming in between, we perpetrate a bad piece of anticipation if we appeal to the Phenomenol- ogy for the investigation of the dialectical method laid down in the Logic — an anticipation which rends Hegel's system to pieces. In view of the great unity which was HegePs aim, we have thought it our duty to follow the Encyclopedia, which was so often revised by him. If we assume the second stand-point, and consider the Phe- nomenology as a propaedeutic to the absolute method, or to the stand-point of Speculative Logic, then it stands outside of the system, and has, as a preparatory exercise, a subjective imjjortance, but no influence on the objective foundation of the system, which, on the contrary, aims, starting with the Logic, to produce itself from itself, and to comprehend itself in itself. The Phenomenology , then, is a propaedeutic to the Logic, as creeping is a propaedeutic to walking, arithmetic a propaedeutic to the logical syllogism. In this case no less than in the other, the appeal to the Plienomenology is an inconsistency, a mere subterfuge, which, however, does not escax)e the eye of the clear-sighted. If the appeal to the Phenomenology were admissible, this work ought to be always read before the Logic, which is never done, or, if it ever is, only by way of introduction. If it were so read, there would result a somewhat odd circum- stance. In the course of the whole, certain sections would occur thrice; e.g. life, first in the Phenomenology as a phe- nomenon, then in the fjogic as an idea, and lastly in the Phi- Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 91 losophy of Nature. What is tlie object of tliis? It is bad enough that life, for example, is treated twice, once in the Logic and once in the Philosopliy of Nature; and it has been shown that the idea of life produced from the pure concept is nothing more or less than intuition — which, indeed, is contemned, but which, in a clarihed and enfeebled form, is accepted. If we admit, as was shown, that the means employed by the dialectic method are false, it is of no avail to appeal to the dialectic Phenomenology. Altogether, people should not be always quite so ready with the Phenomenology in their talk ; it is, and ever will be, a liljer lauclatus magis quam lectus. Thus, likewise, is barred the attempt to defend the dialec- tic method by the aid of the Phenomenology. But its defenders hold in reserve a brilliant retreat for themselves, by ascribing all objections brought against the absolute dialectic to mere imagination, which, in its very nature, say they, is incapable of reaching the pure concept. Any one who questions the products of the absolute concept, occupies the stand-point of the imagination, and, therefore, has no right to speak. When the pure concept is hedged round in this way, it becomes as unapiDroachable as the Holy of Holies. All ptossibility of coming to any understanding ceases, and one might as well try to make something out of the illuminations of a visionary, who treats all opposition precisely in this way, as out of speculative science. Be this as it may, all objections — to speak in the language of the school — are due to an "immanent" criticism of the concept, to its own demands, assertions, and consequences. Never, in the history of philosophy, did the logical ques- tion assume so much importance as at present. Whereas, for- merly, the attack had been directed against " the speculative theology" tlank, it now approaches closer to the centre, which supports the whole — the Logic. The contest regarding the logical question is a contest for the existence of the system. All the consequences which have developed themselves from Hegel, stand or fall with it. Profound investigation of objective reality and perspicuity of style will not reappear in philosophy until that false and exaggerated admiration of the dialectic unity of method, 92 Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. wliirli still fetters men's minds, whenever a new work ap- pears, written at'Oording to this method, shall have given way ; and philosopliical science will then again speak an intelligible lantrnaue, as huiiKiii beino-s are wont to do, when it is com- pelled to give uj) its unintelligible, divine utterances — alias dialectic categories. Tlie dialectic method is a logical hypothesis. Is it, then, so dithciilt to come to clearness about its essence — its truth or untruth '. If b}- scientific procedure we mean one that is essentially necessary and universal, then the (piestion that must arise for decision is simply this: Is Hegel" s dialectic method of pure tliinliing a scientific procedure f In view of the investigations already made, w^e must an- swer this question with a round negative. We do not mean by this that the dialectic method does not possess relatively even a certain scientific value. Such, indeed, it possesses, as a preparative, measured by the standard of the Aristotelian dialectic, inasmuch as it forces the concepts more sharply against each other, and delines them more clearly, whereas in the sense of being an absolute method it has no value whatever. Such it is not. It has exercised a powerful scien- tific influence by stretching the demands of Logic, but in so doing it has ovier-str etched itself. It possesses inerely the imj^ortance of a relative reflection, but it is not an absolute production. The proof of this has been adduced, the refutation has yet to be brought forward. Verily, it wdll not be brought by the differences w^hich have already manifested themselves within the Hegelian Logic, and whereof, we hear, moi-e may yet be expected. After a long period of haughty stability, such mov- ing and bustle are signs of internal insecurity and actual dis- turbance. But a wT^rk so rigidly carved out of one thought as Hegel's Logic will go far to verify the saying : Sint ut sunt., amt non sint. Mending and bolsteiing up will be of no avail, as Plato warns us in the Statesman : '" My good friend, it isn't safe to w^hittle here ; it is much safer to cut right through the middle : one is much surer to come upon ideas." The undersigned is prepared, with all seriousness, to take up the investigation anew, provided ojpposite arguments of Book Notices. 93 auy moment are brought against him. But until a refutation is undertaken, let our friends at least leave off singing their old song about mental languidness and convenience, when scientific men do not recogni/e the dialectic method. A short time ago, something of this kind might have been read in a certain preface. If the investigation is shunned, the arrow may return and strike him who discharged it. Science cannot live on criticism, which only expels what the living organism cannot assimilate. Where criticism reigns alone with its negativity, we are seized with a dull, heavy sense of discomfort, wliicli necessarily accompanies such a process of decomposition. Decomposition and assimi- lation ought, on the contrary, as in breathing, to form but one activity. Then criticism, instead of repressing the life of science, increases it by purifying it. But since even Logic cannot satisfy itself with the mere critical result which re- jects the dialectic method of pure thinking, the Logical Investigations entered, in a positive sense, into the facts of human thought, and tried to show that the science of the idea does not go down, but, on the contrary, becomes all the more certain, when the dialectic method, with its false sanc- tions, is rejected. BOOK NOTICES. ■ Works of Dr. H. K. Hugo Delfk: 1. Ideas of a Philosophical Science of Spirit and Nature. Husum. 1865. 2. Cecilia; or. Concerning the Truth of the Super sensuous. A Dialogue with a Postscript. Husum, 1807. 3. Fundamental Doctrines of Philosophical Science. Husum, 1869. 4. Dante Alighieri and the Divine Comedy. Leipsig, 1870. 5. The Idea of the Divine Comedy. A Study. Leipsig, 1871. The two works on Dante by Mr. DelfFhave attracted so much attention in Germany, that it may not be considered out of place in this Journal to bring them also to the notice of the American public, and especially of those whom Longfellow's translation of the Italian poet must have inter- ested more or less in Dante-literature generally. Mr. Delff's works on the Divine Comedy have this distinguishing merit, that the author brings to his task the results of a life-long study of mystical literature, to which Dante's work is generally held to belong. This thorough knowledge of the mystical writings of all times enables the author to illustrate his ex- position in the most varied and instructive manner. Most particularly felicitous is his sketch of the political, ecclesiastical, and philosophical revo- lutions and conditions that preceded Dante, and that form the basis from which Mr. Delfi" starts his interpretation of Dante's life and Avorks. This sketch evinces, moreover, a rare comprehension of the early status of the 94 Book Notices. Christian Clmrch; and tlie manner in which the gradual rise of the Komau papacy and tlie substitution of new (iCcumenical Council dogmas for the original reinda JiiJei is developed, deserves the highest jiraise. Mr. DeltVs philosophical and religious views, of course, pervade also the Dante-essays; but are more particularly developed in the three above- named purely philosophical works, which we are sorry that space forbids us to characterize at length. In these days, when il requires great bold- ness on the part of a piiilosophical writer to speak otherwise than slight- ingrlv of relisfion. it is certainlv interestiuir to see Mr. Delfl' taking an enthusiastic stand in delencc of religio4i, — nay more, ot Christianity, and still more of Catholicism and mysticism. In the dovelopment of these views Mr. Deltf is probably more nearly related to Bander than to any other (jJerman writer, though he exhibits originality enough of his own. Of our own writers in the same direction, Mr. Alcott comes nearest to him. The most interesting parts of Mr. Delff's works are his i)oleinics against the current " natural philosophy," but chielly his religious expositions and unfoldings of psychological pheno- mena.'such as arc rarely treated by men of science. In these regions his erudition can fully exhibit itself, and his vivid, graceful style throws a peculiar charm over the subjects treated. Thus the dialogue "Cecilia" may even be called brilliant in its development of the author's most cher- ished convictioii>. a. e. k. II Cavour e Libera Chiesa in Libera Staio. Per A. V^era. Professore di Filosofia nella Universita de Napoli. Napoli: Detken & Rocholl. 1871. Professor Vera is making his deep insights into the Philosophy of His- torv and Religion tell in the formation of public opinion at this important juncture in the affairs of Italy. We see by the advertisement on the last page of the above work that this active author has in press a new (enlarged) edition of his French transla- tion of Hegel's Logic, and also a translation of Hegel's Philosophy of Reli" gion, with Introduction and Commentary. Revue des Cours LUic'raires de la France et de Vetranger. Paris. July, 1871. The two numbers received contain two articles by Professor Vera of Na- ples: the first on "The great Mosaic at Pompeii,"' a genial characterization of the celebrated artistic representation of the battle between Alexander and Darius (at Issus?) ; the second article is the opening lectureof a course on the Uistory of Pliilosophy, and treats of the epoch of Socrates. At the close he touches on the present state of afl'airs in Italy, and concludes thus : " The true regeneration of a people sprinsrs from a new thought, from a new Idea, from a new breath of the Eternal S])irit — a breath which, as before remarked, i-evives the past, but revives it transformed and elevated to a high degree of energy, consciousness, and liberty. Now, without wishing to exaggerate and to attribute to Philosophy a monopoly of intel- ligence, I believe 1 can alfirm that there is no science which can better cause such a thought [i.e. regenerating new thought]. For Philosojihy acts on the soul in many ways. In the first place, it extirpates those evil seeds in it — torpor, ignoiance, error — which weaken it, corrui)t it, and render it insensible to the light of truth. And since it lives in the I'egion of thought andof absolute verities, it possesses more than any other science the faculty of understanding and of manifesting the Idea, and of causing it to pene- trate the mind, thereby regenerating the inner man; for the outer man Book Notices. 95 cannot be regenerated until the inner has been. You see then, gentlemen, how that in lighting the battles of Intelligence, and above all lighting them in a free disinterested si>irit, we accomplish a Avork than which none is higher nor m .>re advantageous to ourselves, to our country, and to huma- nity.'' Another article in one of the numbers, under the caption ''Contempo- rary Philosophy in Italy," speaks approvingly of Raphael Mariano's work of that name, and of his " Essay on Hegelian Philosophy"; it tlien notices Louis Ferri's work on the " History of Philosophy in Italy in the Nine- teenth Century." It speaks, linally, of Count Mamiani's -'Confessions of a Metaphysician," and of his later work, the "Cartesian Meditations Re- vived in the Mueteenth Century," of which it says: "Taking as a model that methodic system of doubt extended to all our knowledge, this work rises by rigorous demonstration to philosophic faith in the spirituality and immortiility of the soul, in the eternity of ideas, in the existence of a personal God, in the uuiversijl and indefinife progress of Creation * * * The twofold consciousness of the activity and piissivity of the Ego give to it the perception or direct intuition of its relations with other beings upon which it acts or which act upon it, and it includes thus in one common cer- titude its own existence, external nature, the ideal world, and the Absolute Being." The Wanderer: A Colloquial Poem. By Wm. Ellery Chaiuiing. Boston: James R. Osgood & Co. 1871. The preface, by Emerson, serves as an honest introduction, which leads one on into seveii (luier. still poems, full of tiie i)erfume of nature. Often the irrt'gtilaiity of the rhythm jars, and yet through the whole there is a certain serene melody. One is assured, however, that the poet did not write witli a purpose to suit the ta^te of any reader. If sometimes a figure is a little overstrained, one does not feel that it was done for effect, but because the thought so shaped the woids; e.g. "Kaeh hoar this laugtiiiig boy tenacious cuught A tist-full of existence, spread it mit Flat on its back, and dried it in the sun Of all his breezy thoughts, to shape its truth " Or this, where, after speaking of the grinding of the submerged mountain- tops by floating icebergs, he says, •'Till all the furrowed surface deeply carved, The saline torment took its hand away, And left a course of splinters in dry air To mocii the ballled thinker of an orb Where soraewbat thinks, superior to himself." Or this: ' ' I sometimes caught an echo of the past. Lessons of sunk "religions, sounding faint." The poems are colloqttial in the sense that they seem as if they were fi-agments of an utterance in an age before men "forgot tlie fashion of leis- ure." There is no unity to be sought or found in them, but a clear, pure current of fine thought and fancy. The picture of the scholar, at the end of the last [)oem, is one of the finest passages, and leads one's thotights irre- sistibly back to the preface, as if it were a portrait. a. c. b. A History of Philosophy from Thales to the Present Time. Bj^ Dr. Friedrich Ueberweg. late Professor of Philosophy in the University of Konigsberg. Translated from the Fourth German Edition, by George S. Morris, A.M., Professor of Modern Languages in the Cniversity of Michigan. With Addi- tions by Noah Porter, D.D., LL.D., President of Yale College. With a Pre- face bj-' the Editors of the Philosophical and Theological Library. Vol. I.: History of the Ancient and Mediawal Philosophy. New York: Chas. Scrib- ner & Company. 1872. 96 Book Notices. Tliis first volume of the rhilosophieal Division of the Philosophical and The- (ilo>ri(;il Library, comliu-tiil by l)rs. Henry 1>. Smith and Philip Schatf. of the Union Theoloirical Seminary. New York, will be apt to i)r<'iudie<' many in favor of tlie whole enterprise; and deservedly, for it is an admirable book, admirably translated. It has often been remarked, how much superior American transla- tions of German works are to Enjrlish ones; and nothincience of Logic. Hegel orally designated tlie Phenomenology in Berlin as the work in wliich he had made his "voyage of discovery." Til is expression can relate only to the concrete content of natnre and history wliich he w^ronght over in it, and not to the general idea of consciousness, which also retained the same moments in the system of the philosophy of mind. Hegel conceded, however, by that expression, that he could have brought in a still more extended content into the Phe- nomenology than he did. When, later, he reduced the rela- tion of the knowing subject to speculation (so far as con- cerns the beginning of speculative thinking), to the transition through skepticism, and to the simple resolution to will to- think the truth absolutely, it must not be forgotten that no one would come to this resolve whose consciousness had not previously in some wa}^ completed in experience all its other content. Hegel's division of consciousness remained (1) conscious- ness. (2) self-consciousness, (3) rational self-consciousness. To this, the following division of the Logic would correspond: (1) objective logic, (2) subjective logic, (3) absolute logic. The lirst w^ould have contained the categories of being in general ; the second, the moments of the idea ; the third, the canon of the absolute idea. That Hegel confounded this tri- chotomy with another in the Logic — viz. being, essence, idea — is explained by the fact that he distinguished the idea of idea itself again into (1) the subjective, (2) the objective, (3) the idea. Hence one of the greatest difficulties of the Logic has arisen. We will here touch only upon the point adduced by criticism, that the same categories occur in the Phenome- nology and in the Logic; so that the Logic was properly already contained in the Phenomenology. This is quite right, but it cannot be otherwise. First, the con- tent of phenomenology, as well as that of every other science, is formally ruled by logic. It cannot dispense with logical forms, which must therefore become manifest in its articula- tion. Second, the logical categories must themselves become objects of consciousness in concrete forms. Consciousness must, in the course of its culture, become master of the idea of logical forms. The existence of the logical in the concrete matter of consciousness cannot be excluded from its experi- ence. Sensuous certainty, for example, cannot do otherwise The Essential in the Hegelian System. 113 than make being, as definite being, its object. The senses make their appearance as the mediation of the certainty that some- thing now and here looks red, tastes sweet, or feels smooth, &c. ; bnt sense does not know that this something, as red, is distinguished from another, e.g. a green something. This knowing is an act of consciousness which distinguishes that excitation of the nerves of sight which we designate as red, from another as green. The animal does not attain this ob- jectivization of its sensations, but rests in sensation. Red and green are distinguished even for the eye of the animal, but the animal cannot conclude this is red. It does not know that red is a different color from green. It knows nothing of There and noio. It knows nothing of an individual object. It is, indeed, a self-feeling individualization, but knows not itself as subject in opposition to an object. It is conscious- ness which makes the sensuous an object, and thereby be- comes certain of itself, i.e. knows being as distinct, as this definite being. Thus apprehension cannot perfect itself with- out the categories of the essential and the unessential, of the thing and its properties, &c. THE ESSENTIAL AND THE UNESSENTIAL IN THE HEGELIAN METHOD. The great problem which Hegel proj)osed in his Logic, centred itself about his conception of the dialectic method, which he regarded as the only true one. It consisted in the Platonic method, made profound by the method of Aristotle's metaphysics, and more accurately determined by the forms of Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Subjectively it was to constitute the absolute organ of all genuine knowing, but objectively it was also to contain the immanent rythmus of ontological development which is immanent in reality. What Kant had distinguished on the one side as understanding, judgment, and reason, and on the other as idea, reflection, and syllogism, was to become united in the abstract, reflected, and speculative determinations of the logical idea. Its course was to be not merely analytic from the individual to the general, not merely synthetic from the general to the indi- vidual, but regressive and progressive at the same time, be- cause the general unity was to distinguish itself from itself, VoL vi.— 8 114 T'he Essential in tlie Hegelian System. and only ultimately to be determined to its genuine concrete idea. In tli(> treatment of the Plienomenolosrv and of the Logic, Hegel himself gave an example of this method. He had made the idea expound itself, and thereby build itself up to a new idea. Idea as such is identical with itself, but through its diiferentiation it produces new ideas, and in that deijree changes itself. This must be rightly understood. The idea of a point, e.g., is always the same ; but in so far as the point moves it be- gets another, the other of itself, in which it sublates itself as the true. The line again, by moving in different ways, pro- duces the difference of straight and crooked. The point makes itself analytically a line, but synthetically it remains contained in it ; the line makes itself analytically a straight or a crooked line, but synthetically it is posited as a line in the one as well as in the other. The soul of this dialectic was thus here, as with Plato and Aristotle, the negative of the idea, the antithesis which it brought forth out of itself. This is the incontrovertible truth of this process. Closely connected with this, however, is the unessential, so easily possible in its presentation, viz. error in regard to that which is posited as the negative. Hegel's thought strove toward the absolute independence of the idea from the philosopher. The part of the latter should be only that of looking on its movement. In the above illustration it is not I who make the point be- come a line ; but it itself, by moving itself, produces itself as a line. I look upon this its self- formation. This highest ideal of all scientific investigation was not insured in its real- ization against the contingency of the philosopher, for here in the transition from the general to the special the distinc- tion necessary in itself could very easily be varied, and the immanent antithesis be falsified. Even the abstract general- ity might be transposed with the concrete, the first with the last. Then, despite all claim of infallibility, the method fell into fallacious construction. In Hegel himself examples may be found where he is deluded and vacillating in this respect ; e.g. in the Philosophy of Right, under the conception of the state power, he has set up royal sovereignty as the first, there- fore abstract, moment ; while in the second edition of the En- cycloi)edia it is the final and concrete moment. The Essential in the Hegelian System. 115 Among the adherents of Hegel, the difteiences are still greater. Opponents of his philosophy receive these as proof of the falsity of his method, while the ground lies only in its uncritical use. Hegel wished manifestation of the idea, but the school often fell back to the mere construction of the philosophy of Schelling through precipitate and external ap- plication of the logical categories. That which can be called the unessential in Hegel's method has been especially evoked by the fact that the idea of antithesis became confounded with that of contradiction. Hegel took up the antinomy from Kant's dialectic with great satisfaction. While Kant placed contradiction only in our knowledge. Hegel said it should belong also to actuality itself. Contradiction, as real, is also possible, and can therefore become actual. It is not merely a phenomenon of our intelligence. Hegel now affirmed that, in the development of the idea, antinomies everywhere present themselves which must be solved into a higher unity. He did not intend to explain the contradiction as that which is true, for that which is true cannot contradict itself, but he discerned the foundation of all life, of all activity, in the fact that in the phenomenal world antithesis grew into contradic- tion, which latter manifested the unity in whose depth it sank away. The higher a particular being stands, and the more sides it has, so much the more easily can it involve itself in manifold contradictions. Hegel, therefore, took up contra- diction as a constitutive moment into his system, and aroused endless contradiction thereby, because by this it was cus- tomary to understand the absurdity of something unthinka- ble, logically impossible. Contradiction is also antithesis ; but antithesis as such, brought to the tension of negative actuosity mrsus identity, is not contradiction, but in the world of phenomena it may every moment become contradic- tion. The antithesis of positive and negative electricity is in itself ever and everywhere present, but only in the thunder- storm does it become a contradiction which solves itself in lightning. Egoness, as individualization of mind, is imme- diately antithetical to its universality, but it becomes bad only when it negates it in actu and with consciousness. Physical selfishness is not yet ethical egotism. It cannot be 110 The Essential in the Hegelian System. denied that Hegel's philosophy has not distingnished the contradictory, the contrary, and the repugnant, with suffi- cient care, and has caused confusion thereby ; but still less can it bt» denied tliat the zeal Avhich would again exile con- tradiction from philosoph}- witliout surmounting it, has re- sulted in the most lamentable shallowness. The idea in-and-for-itself is, to be sure, Avithout contradic- tion ; but in its development, contradiction produces itself in the steps of transition. It must, therefore, always be meas- ured on the higlier. Eiidemonism is the quite consequent issue of psychology. In itself there is nothing contradictory in being happy, in the satisfaction of one's instincts and appe- tites, but this principle leads to the contradiction of pleasure with itself, and this contradiction is solved not by psychol- ogy but by ethics. Man shall be more than happy — he shall be free. When, therefore, Hegel is reproached with discerning truth in contradiction, an error is made ; the contradiction which begets itself is in the same degree sublated ; unity continues, not only negative but affirmative, through the totality of the development. The unity with which an idea begins is abstract identity : from this proceeds its diflference ; these station themselves over against one another in order to sublate them- selves into a higher unity. Thus backwards this is concrete, but forwards it manifests itself as a contradiction which sinks ;away in the depth of a higher unity opposed to it, which nevertheless in the beginning of its formation, or immediate- ly, is only an abstract identity. The abstract in-and-for-itself is without contradiction, but the different steps of the phe- nomenal universe, re-interlinked with one another through contradiction (since it demands solution) into living unity. That which is true, therefore, in the Hegelian method is the unrest of the negative, which makes its appearance in every sphere save that of the pure absolute. But this unrest is at the same time full of the repose which accrues to every moment of the whole as necessary and for itself positive. The higher step negates that which is presupposed and lower, and includes it in itself (as Hegel was wont to say) as its negative identity, but does not destroy it in its relative inde- HegeVs Encyclopedia. Ill pendence. When, e.g., man as a microcosm comprehends the macrocosm of all nature compendiously in himself, the per- sistence of nature in itself is not destroyed. The transition of one idea to another is no gradual meta- morphosis as students of nature so readily seek to derive the origin of new forms by successive transformation of those already existing, but the existence of the higher grade is posited through the idea of the idea. The lower grade often reveals types in which the higher already has its analogy. It is the types which may deceive, but they are only the hu- moristic prelude, not yet the thing itself; as the Rosaceje envelope their kernel with the superfluity of a flesh which is yet no real, feeling flesh — as the ape seems to foreshadow the human form, yet is separated from man by an impassable gulf — as relief extends picture-like over surfaces, but is as yet no painting. Hegel could not call his method merely synthetic, because the higher step is the teleological ground of the lower ; in its execution however, which he was not able himself to carry on to its completion— i.e. in the lectures published after his death — he has often, it is true, contented himself with a synthetic derivation. Here then, as with Spi- noza, dogmatism entered, and in such a manner that presen- tation not infrequently sunk into that form which Hegel most abhorred in philosophy — to narration ; in the school this in- creased still more — the trichotomies of the idea were decreed only in an assertorical manner. The discipline of thought, as Hegel had named the method, was quite thrown oft' to make way for the most motley anarchy. THE ENCYCLOPEDIA. It was natural that a mind which found itself upon so high a stand-point of scientific unity must approach the wish to live in a sphere adequate to itself. Hegel longed for aca- demic activity. The favor of fortune came to him in various offers. He had already decided upon Heidelberg, when notice was also taken of him from Berlin. There were especially two men, quite opposed to each other, who were instrumental in his appointment, Paulus and Daub. With the flrst he had stood in relations of per- sonal friendship since Jena. With the latter he became 1 1 8 HegeVs Encyclopedia. acquainted in Heidelberg, and through him was gradually alienated from Paulus, who observed the fact with great dis- pleasure. Paulus was the most decided opponent of Roman- ticism, and could not pardon Hegel's sympathy for Daub and Creuzer, which lie, in common with Voss, construed into a suspicion of crypto-catholicism. Hegel had never expressed himself publicly against Paulus, but Paulus persecuted him, when he was dead, in pamphlets and periodicals, and espe- ciall}' in a work which he entitled " Geister revue."' He waged this polemic under the name " Magis arnica Veritas.''^ Many bitter things whi(di were retailed, ever more sarcastically, ever in wider circulation, owe their origin to their attacks under this pseudonym. In Heidelberg, Hegel must have felt the necessity of giving to the public a presentation of his philosophy in its totality, for the Phenomenology of Mind had been a propaedeutic work, and logic had been only the first j)art of his system. Both were, moreover, in a dialectic form so strict that they could have been understood only by the narrow^ circle of philosophers. Hegel's predecessor in Heidelberg had been Fries. With his totally different apprehension of specula- tion, it w^as necessary for Hegel to take pains to present in outline to the students the difference of his philosophy from that of Fries, at least in its chief moments. He proposed, therefore, a guide for his lectures which he named " Encyclo- pedia of the Philosophical Sciences." By the word Encyclopedia he wanted, as he himself said, to designate the unity of science, which composes a circle of circles. Beginning from itself, it "widens itself to ever new determinations, which at the same time constitute deeper in- sights of the principle, until an ultimate stage is attained beyond which progress cannot be made, and with which knowing reverts into its beginning. Ever since Bacon, European science has striven toward totality. Since he had given to it only a psychological foundation in reason, mem- ory, and X)hantasy, the unity remained external. The French Encyclopedia of Diderot and D'Alembert followed out, in the organization of sciences, essentially the plan of Bacon, but split up in execution into the atomistic multiplicity of the alphabetical article. In Germany, the division of the HegeVs Encyclopedia. 119 Leibnitz- Wolff philosophy into theoretical and practical sci- ences had acquired validity and had been adopted by Kant, although he set up a higher division in the Architectonique of the Critique of Pure Reason ; the physiology of pure rea- son, the metaphysics of nature and the metaphysics of ethics — or science of the idea of that which should be in general, of that which is, and of that which should be. This tricho- tomy Hegel elevated to the distinct grasp of the idea, (1) as logic, (2) as nature, (3) as mind. Every system since then? which, in the place of this simple articulation, would place another, has fallen. One very important step of Hegel was the presentation of natural philosophy. It should, conse- quently, have followed the Logic as an independent whole. Now it appears as an integral part of the total cycle of sci- ces, in an abbreviated form, which scarcely suffices to make clear the inner connection of nature with the idea as logic and as mind. Still more scanty and difficult of understanding was the composition of the last part of the philosophy of mind. Its division into the idea of the subjective, objective, and abso- lute mind, was, to be sure, of convincing simplicity ; but the presentation of absolute mind as art-religion, revealed reli- gion, and philosophy, must at once awaken doubt. Why was art apprehended at the same time as religion ( Why was religion, as revealed, distinguished from the idea of religion in general ? Why was the absoluteness of knowledge placed only in philosophy, which, as human activity, is not yet free from ignorance, error, and doubt, i.e. is infected with proble- matic knowing ? Why was it not plainly enunciated whether the absolute mind also exists in-and-for-itself as subject, or whether Hegel under this word had in view only art, religion, and science, within the phenomena of the human mind ? In the enigmatical paragraphs, only one very scanty extract from the last chapter of the Phenomenology can be detected. We shall see later what weighty consequences are attached to this indistinctness. As Hegel wished to give a clue for his lectures, he omitted the proper dialectic development, and gave only a list of defi- nitions in which he had much practice in the notes for the philosophical propaedeutics at the gymnasium, and had at- 120 J^icJife's Facts of Consciousness. rained great skill in using modes of expression. This form^ moreover, has not been without intiuence upon the school^ because it favored its dogmatism and abjured stricter phi- losophy. It is no exaggeration to affirm that, with the ex- ception of Euclid, no text-book exists of such concentrated precision. Every word in this laconic language is freighted with n\eaning. To logic, luitural philosophy, and psychology, Hegel ap- pended remarks in which he gave a trenchant criticism of those views which contradicted his own. In this way he skilfully incited to free retiection. FACTS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. Transl-.ited from the German of J. G. Fichte, by A. E. Krokgkr. :^0 0 3£. XX. FACTS OK COXSCIOUSNKSS IN REGARD TO TIIK PIJACTICAL FACULTY. CHAPTER II. The Tendency of the Ego to overcome Ike Check of the non-Ego is posited as a material Body. A. — We have seen how the Ego, limited to a mere impulse and without any immediate cansality, through its mere Being contemplated its power to arrive in time at an end through conditional states ; calculating that power, at the same time, the resistance that was also contemplated in the image, and thus completing a plan of its causality. It appears imme- diately that it can fix this manifold of conditions and of time in no other unity-conception than the conception of itself, and that hence it must in this connection necessarily think itself here, moreover, as a real princij^le — and not merely^ as in the previous book, as the principle of a reproduction through the power of imagination — and furthermore abso- lutely d priori., without any real causality having preceded, since the whole synthetical period starts from a complete annihilation of such causality. Now that which offers the resistance is matter, and the purpose is to separate this matter, get it out of its place, or FicMe's Facts of Consciousness. 121 remove it. But matter can be moved out of its place in space onlj^ through other matter ; and thus it appears that the Ego, as a working power in a material world, must itself be mat- ter, hence an immediately given, determined, and in-space- limited body. Moreover, in this body it must be possible that the conception can become immediately the cause of a motion of its matter, in order that by this designedly moved matter the dead external matter may be moved. Such a mo- bility of matter through the mere conception may very prop- erly be called organization, by means whereof one body becomes an organ to work upon the rest of the material world. The Ego, in its image of a causality upon matter, would thus turn into an organized body. A causality executed by means of this organization upon the material world, must be accompanied always by the above described external sense in order to judge to what extent the intended plan has been executed, and what still remains to be done. Hence this sense must be thoroughly united and constitute one with that organ, and must therefore be represented in matter in the same way. From this there results a material Ego with an external sense and organ. Thus. I say, the Ego must appear absolutely d priori. We do Dot learn by experience that we act; we have no percep- tion of it as we have of our passive states. That causality of ours presupposes a free conception created through abso- lute self-activity. This conception, and our possible causal- ity in accordance with it, are internally contemplated — for thus we have described and accomplished it in the above — as a mere faculty, even in advance of the actual accomplish- ment of the intended causality ; and it is already in this exe- cuted and completed prototype of such a causality that the Ego appears necessarily as a material organ. Through what then, and through what facultj'', is the Ego formed into a material body ? Evidently through the pro- ductive power of imagination, precisel}^ like the image of the resistance itself, and at the same occasion, and in virtue of the same law. The conception of the intended causality, the determined prototype of this causality, was to be sketched. To do this made necessary an image of the check or resist- ance, in order to calculate the effect of the power on it ; so 1*22 FicTite'S Facts of Consciousness. again an image of the power is necessary in order to calcu- late the effect of the resistance on it. But the resistance is placed in matter, and hence the power of the Ego must be placed in the same medium of matter in order to make such a calculation possible. From this it follows that just as the image of the resistance, external perception, was not con- sciousness, but an object of consciousness, so also the image of the Ego as a material body is not consciousness, but an object of consciousness; or, expressing it more strictly: ma- teriality is the absolute d priori form of self-consciousness in its causality upon the original clieck, the form of the Ego's self-contemplation through its external sense, just as time is the Ego's for'u of self-contemplation through its internal sense. Xow the causality of the Ego upon that original <^heck may either be merely prototyped, to which region we have liitherto coniined ourselves, or it may be actually exe- cuted, and contemplated in the actual realization. But in both cases the form, there of free imaging and here of con- templation, remains the materiality of the Ego. B. — Now let us assume the Ego to be completely ready with this conception of its desired causality and all the con- structions that condition this conception, and let us ask : has the actual causality now real existence or not? I say, it has by no means existence as yet even through the completest conception, but is only now possible. The Ego, which at first was enchained and deprived of all its power to have causality, has now, through the mere conception, completely freed itself in such a manner that it can begin the proposed causality at the conceived point of beginning — as soon as it does begin it — needing only itself for this causalit3^ But if this perfect possibility is to be changed into actual- ity, what must occur, what is the real point of transition, the requisite complementum possihiUtatis / This question is very important, partly because it has hitherto never been thoroughly investigated by philosophers, and partly on ac- count of its vast consequences for our whole system. This transition to actual causality is doubtless a change of its present condition. Let us. then, make this present condi- tion very clear to ourselves, in order to see wherein it can be Fichte's Facts of Co/isciousness. 123 changed. At present, it has its causality in the conception only. True, that causality is thoroughly determined and completed ; but this its being is only in thought, and van- ishes as soon as the act of thinking vanishes, since with it the thought itself vanishes. The being of this causality is held in this present state only through the continuing free- dom of thinking, and falls down as soon as this freedom w^ith- draws its hand. Probably it is this relation that is to be changed in such a manner that the being of that causality becomes independent of the thinking, in which case it would be called actual. But how is such a change to occur ? Let us explain the whole matter to ourselves in the following way : There is a double relation to immediale consciousness. Wherever any immediate consciousness occurs, not except- ing feeling and contemplation, an absolutely free and unde- termined power of imaging is to be posited as the swnimum modificabile. This power is always being limited w^hen a determined consciousness is to occur ; but it can be so lim- ited in a twofold way. Firstly, by the immediate activity of the Ego itself, which manifests itself as activity to create a certain product, an image. In this case the summum modi- ficahile is immediately directed upon that activity, and it beholds the product only through this activity ; hence if that determined activity leaves, the product also leaves conscious- ness, and its being in consciousness is cancelled. This is the •case ^\\t\\ all mere thoughts, and hence also with the described image of that possible causality. Secondly, the summxLm modijicahile is absolutely and immediately limited, and not by any free activity conditioning this limitation, as is the case in the above described limitation of the absolute pro- ductive power of imagination. Now, since such a limitation is altogether unconditioned, the Being, which enters into our consciousness, is represented also as an unconditioned Being, which no withdrawal of that freedom can possibly cancel, since it is not condi- tioned by it. Hence to say that the Ego must realize the conception of its causality in an act, is to say that the Ego must move from the region of a Being, which can be annihilated at any mo- ment by the withdrawal of freedom, or the region of concep- 124 FlcMe-s F'acts of Consciousness. tion, into the region of the immediately eoniined power of imagination, wherein everytliiiig assumes a lixed, x^ermanent, and on-itself-reposing Being. X(^w, into tliis region it is transposed already by its mate- rial body. Hence it must make Itself an actually working- material body in order to enter the form of actualit}^ ; and since in this region everything remains permanent, the pro- ducts of its freedom thus accomplished will certainly also stay permanent. The transition of the Ego from the mere thinking of a pos- sible causality to the actual realization of that causality con- sists, therefore, in this, that the Ego frees itself in its whole personality from the freedom of mere conception, and surren- ders itself to its original existence as a j)rinciple in the region of the absolutely limited power of imagination. But this transition occurs with absolute freedom. This is the reason why in thought we can take back every resolve, but cannot think a deed as not done, since the deed irrevocably binds our own contemplation of Being. A deed we can take back only by another actual deed, through which we destroy the product of the first deed and put a new one in its place. Remarks. — 1. The transition of the Ego from the mere con- ception to an actual causality can be described as a confining of its previously (in the region of conception) unchained free- dom ; but it can also be regarded — when we consider that conceptions are mere pictures, but causality the true actual — as a liberation from emptiness and the acquiring of a higher freedom ; and thus we have regarded it above. In either case it is necessary, according to the above established principles, that an immediate consciousness of this transition should occur, which consciousness will appear as a consciousness of self-determination, since it is the transition of the Ego from one form of its power into the oj)posite form through another higher power of its own, which higher power soars between both. 2. Whatsoever falls into the region of the absolutely lim- ited power of imagination, receives an unconditioned and permanent Being. In this form the Ego appears as a mate- rial body, and hence this is its permanent Being. As a Think- Hegel's PMlosopliy of Art. 125 ing essence, for instance, tlie Ego appears to itself only when thinking, but the Ego may also not think at all. Its .bodily existence, however, it always retains, even in deepest sleep or in swoons. Thns, also, the products of the Ego in the mate- rial world retain their existence as long as the matter, which they have modified, remains, and may survive their origina- tor centuries in the material world. HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY OF ART. Translated from the second volume of Hegel's ^Esthetics, by MissS. A. Longwell. Chivalry. — I. Honor. The motive of honor was unknown to ancient classic art. In the Iliad, the anger of Achilles furnishes the spirit and moving princij)le upon which the whole broad production is dependent ; but what we, in the modern sense, understand by honor, is not involved here. Achilles finds himself really injured only in this, that his actual share of the booty, which is his reward of honor, his recompense, has been taken from him by Agamemnon. This ofi'ence pertains to something real, to a gift, to which a distinction had certainly been attached, an acknowledgment of glory and of bravery, and Achilles becomes angry because Agamemnon insults him, and does not render him. in the presence of the Greeks, the honors that are due him. But this ofi'ence does not penetrate to the ultimate point of the personality as such, so that Achilles is appeased by the return of the booty and the addi- tion of more gifts and bounties. Agamemnon finally grants this reparation, although, according to our modern ideas, they have injured each other in the grossest way possible. Through insulting words they have only made themselves angry, while the real oflence is cancelled in a way just as real and special. Romantic honor, on the contrary, is of quite another type. In it the ofi'ence touches not the real essential value, possession, condition, duty, etc.; but the per- sonality as such, the opinion that the individual has of him- self, the value that he attributes to himself. This value, in the 126 HegeVs Philosophy of Art. present stage, is just as infinite as the subject is in its own view inlinite. In lionor man has tlierefore the readiest affirm- ative consciousness of his iniinite subjectivity, independently of its content. Now that which the individual possesses par- takes, through honor, of his personality, wliich has an abso- lute value in his own eyes, and ouglit to have the same in the eyes of others. The measure of honor is not in what the sub- ject really is. but in what it imagines itself to be. The tend- ency of the imagination is to generalize, so that I can place my entire personality in this particular object which pertains tome. "Honor is only an appearance" people are accustomed to say. Certainly this is the case ; but it is better suited to the present stand-point to regard it more seriously. It is not only the appearance, the mere external reflection of the abso- lute personality. The image of that which in itself is infinite, is itself something inflnite. Through this infinity even the manifestation of honor becomes the true existence of the subject in liis highest reality ; and every particular quality, which honor illuminates and makes its own, is, through this illumination, raised already to an infinite value. Honor, thus understood, determines a sure foundation in the romantic world, and presupposes that man has emerged just as fully from the merely religious sphere and internal world as he has entered into the living actuality, and that he now brings into this relation only himself in his pure per- sonal independence and absolute availability for existence. Honor may have the most varied content : for, indeed, all that I am, that I do, that is done to me by others, pertains to my honor. I can, therefore, attribute to honor the merely substantial even, loyalty to princes, devotion to native land, vocation, accomplishment of paternal duties, matrimonial faith, uprightness in business, conscientiousness in scientific investigations, etc. But, in the point of view of honor, all these, in themselves valid and legitimate duties, are not yet sanctioned and recognized as such through themselves, but only as I identify them with my personality and allow it to become an aff"air of honor. Therefore the man of honor thinks of himself first, in all things ; and the question is not whether anything in and of itself is right, but whether it is fitting for him, whether it becomes his honor to engage his faith HegeVs Philosophy of Art. 127 that lie will be obliged to keep. Thus he may even commit the most reprehensible actions, and yet be a man of honor. He creates arbitrar}^ purposes, presents himself in a certain character and causes himself to be bound, by himself and others, to this, in which no necessity or obligation has place. Then the imagination scatters difficulties and chimerical em- barrassments in the way, because it is an affair of honor to maintain the once assumed character. So Diana considers it as opposed to her honor to confess the love which she feels, because she had once been thought to deny an au- dience to Love. In general, honor gives value to contingency, since it avails only through the subject, and not through its own inherent reality. We see, therefore, in the romantic representation, on one side, that which is authorized in-and-for- itself as the expressed law of honor, while the individual at the same time unites with the consciousness of right the unlimited self-con- sciousness of his personality. Honor demands or prohibits something, then compels the whole subjectivity to establish itself in the significance of this demand or prohibition, so that an offence may not be overlooked, pardoned, or made good through any transaction ; and no compensation is ad- missible. But, conversely, honor can become something quite formal and artificial, in so far as it includes nothing except the mere ego, which is for itself infinite, or perhaps accepts an entirely wrong conception as obligatory. In this state honor remains, especially in dramatic representation, a cold and dead subject throughout; while its aims, instead of a real meaning, express but an abstract subjectivity. In the suc- cession of events, only the essential ideas of right off'er to the mind a regular connection and necessary development. This lack of deep meaning is clearly manifest when the subtlety of reflection, in itself contingent and trifling, that stands in contact with the subject, shows itself within the compass of honor. The subject is never exhausted, for a minute analysis discovers a crowd of distinctions, particularities which taken in themselves are insignificant, that may yet become import- ant and furnish material for an affair of honor. The Spaniards have especially built upon this casuistry of reflection concerning points of honor, in their dramatic poets, 128 HegeVs Ph ilosopliy of Art. aud represent ilieir heroes as reasoning upon this subject. So, for example, the fidelity of the wife, investigated in the most insignilicant eircumstances possible, and even the mere suspicion of others, indeed the mere possibility of such a sus- picion even when the husband knows the suspicion to be false, becomes an allair of honor. This leads to collisions as no satisfaction is to be obtained, because we have nothing sub- stantial before us. and therefore, instead of subduing a neces- sary opposition, can obtain only a limited painful experience. Also in tlie French drama there is often mere honor, M'holly abs.tract in itself, which is to avail as the chief interest. But in this regard, the Alarcus of Herr Friedrich von Schlegel is still more frigid and insipid. The hero murders bis noble wife. Why ( For the sake of honor ; and this honor lies in his desire to marry the king's daughter, for whom lie cher- ishes no affection, in order to become the king's son-in-law. This is a despicable pathos and a base conception, which dis- plays itself as something noble and infinite. Now since honor dwells not only in myself as a manifesta- tion of my personality, but also in the conception and recog- nition of others, who must again on their side demand the same recognition of their honor, it is therefore essentially susceptible. For how far, and in reference to what I shall extend the demand, depends entirely upon my choice. The smallest offence can be to me in this respect significant. Man stands within the concrete truth, with many things in mani- fold relations ; and the sphere of that which he will consider his own, and in which he will place his honor, may expand indefinitely ; so in the self-dependence of the individual and in his reserved personality, which is also embraced in the principle of honor, there are endless disputes and conten- tions. Therefore the offence generally depends not upon the sense in which I must feel myself injured; for that which is denied, touches the personality that has created such a sense for itself, and now imagines itself assailed in this ideal infi- nite point. Consequently, every injury to reputation is re- garded as something in itself infinite, and can therefore be made good only in an infinite way. There exist, it is true, many grades of offence and just as many grades of satis- faction. Hegel's PhilosopJiy of Art. 129 But what tlie person usually regards in this sphere as an offence, the measure of this offence, and the reparation, de- pend wholly upon the subjective free will, which has the right to advance even to the most scrupulous reflections and most irritable sensitiveness. When such a satisfaction is demand- ed, the offender as well as the person injured must be recog- nized as a man of honor. For what I wish is the recognition of my honor by my equal. But in order to have honor for and through him. I must esteem him as a man of honor, infinite in his personality, the injury that he did me and my subjective enmity toward him notwithstanding. So the prin- ciple of honor has in general this determining foundation, that no one through his own actions can give to another a right over himself: and therefore, whatever he may have done and committed, he is considered, after as before, a being of infinite nature, invariably the same, and will be regarded and treated as such. Since honor depends, in its controversies and reparations, in this regard, upon the personal independence which knows itself circumscribed by nothing, but manifests itself clearly, we see that again appear which determined in the heroic manifestation of the ideal a sure foundation, namely, this same independence. In honor, we have not only the energy of will and its spontaneity, but personal independence is here bound with the conception of itself, and this conception ex- presses precisely the only purport of honor ; so that it mani- fests its personality and its whole subjectivity in the external and existing. Honor is consequently its own reflected self- dependence, which has only this reflection for its being, and it is left plainly contingent whether its significance is the customary and necessary, or the accidental and insignificant. Vol.Ti.— 9 ( i:^o ) THE MERCHANT OF VENICE. By D. J. Snidek. The main-spring of the action in "Merchant of Venice" is the contest between Antonio and Shylock. Every means culminates in this end, every incident contributes either to call forth their struggle, or to harmonize it after it has arisen. A glance at the leading events of the play will show that this is the one central j)oint from which the entire action radiates, which organizes and vivifies the whole piece. The incidents relating to Portia, which at the first look seem somewhat re- mote from the main action, bring forth in fact the profoundest mediation of the drama. Bassanio loves Portia, and applies to his friend Antonio, the wealthy merchant, for the money to carry on his courtship in a suitable style of magnilicence. For magnificent it must be, since it requires such a large amount of money, and besides it appears already to have exhausted his own purse. In this fact we see the motive for the account of this elaborate wooing; Shakespeare has brought before us lords and princes, %vitli grand retinues, sueing foi" the hand of the fair Portia ; to compete with these, Bassanio has to apply to the merchant for the ducats. But the merchant's ventures are all at sea — he has not the cash on band — hence he must go to the money-lender. This brings him into contact with the Jew, and the main circum- stances of the play are thereafter rapidly developed. Thus Portia was indirectly the cause of Antonio's falling into the hands of the Jew; and hence the poet makes her the instru- mentality by which Antonio is released. And even the inci- dents of the last act, which take place after the culmination of the i)lay, are logically necessary for the harmonization of the lesser contradictions which have been called forth by the grand struggle. Every part must be rounded off with the perfection of art ; no shreds are left to draggle from the edges of this w^ell-wove garment ; our poet is like the sculptor, who finishes the finger-nail as exquisitely in its way as he does the face, the expression of intelligence. But the question next arises, What do these two men rep- resent ? What principles does each one maintain ? For men The Merchant of Venice. 131 without a grand motive lying at the basis of their action, and giving color to their endeavor, can have no interest for us. It is the conflict of these principles, represented and carried into execution by men, that excites our sympath}^, our fear, our delight. The flrst thing which we find much stress laid upon, is that Shylock is a Jew, a circumstance which should excite our careful consideration. The poet evidently intends to portray the Jewish character, or rather the Jewish conscious- ness. Antonio's religion Is not specially dwelt upon ; but he is, of course, a Christian, as well as those around him. The- Jew thus finds himself in a Christian world, acting and deal- ing with men of a strange race and strange morality, and with ends in life far difl'erent from his own. Hence the possibility of a conflict both of nationalities and of moralities. The colli- sion, therefore, which supplies the nerve of the play may be stated, in a general form, to be between Christianit}^ and Judaism. But mark! it is not between these religions as dogmatic systems of theology, but as realized in the practical life of men. Antonio is a Christian, not that he goes to church and makes long prayers and daily rehearses the creed; he does none of these things as far as we know ; but a general spirit of brotherhood and generosity animates all his actions ; a liberality which we may fairly call Christian is ingrained into his very nature, and is the well-spring of his conduct in his dealings with his fellow-men. On the contrary, Shylock exhibits Judaism as it must influence the doings of those who act according to its principle. To be sure, the religious ele- ment is brought into more prominence in his character than in Antonio's, but only for the purpose of showing the moral consequences of that system of belief. Shylock carries out in his life the faith that is in him with the utmost logical rigor and bitterness. And here we desire to lay stress upon an important fact. Shakespeare has nowhere in any of his dramas made religion as such the principal motive. This was, no doubt, intentional on his part, for no man understood the concrete nature of religion — religion as determining the conduct of mankind — better than he. In this form he uses it continually. But to make men die for an abstract principle of Theology, Shakespeare utterly refused, and he was right. For we all say that religion means nothing unless carried out 18-J 7Vie Merchant of Venice. in life, and just there Shakespeare seizes it, religion inaction. Bar then in tliis spliere tlic reliffions form vanishes; for a man niav be of the liiirhest worth and integrity, and still re- fuse to fonforni to the required observances; who can tell the difterence between such a num and the most worthy church member in their actions towards their fellow-men ^ Now the drama represents just this: man in action. Hence, if it be universal, it must take not the religious but the ethical basis, for all men recognize that. A number of poets of very high rank have tried to embody a religious theme in the drama, as Oalderon. Corneille. and Massinger. But the judgment of mankind has not pronounced these efforts the highest pro- ducts of the dramatic art. In fact the real religious drama is found in the old miracle-plays, and it has always been con- sidered a great advance in dramatic form, when that kind of plays disappeared into the regular drama. This i^rogress is an historical fact: the old Moraliters with their abstract vir- tues, their dtMuons and angels, devils and gods — in general, with their wlioll}" external way of representation developed into motives an^l ends, into freedom, into Shakespeare. For he puts the demon and the angel inside of man, where they belong. No longer is aliuman being lured on to a deed which he seemingl}' cannot help, by some irresistible power outside of his o\vn nature. This, then, is the difficulty with the reli- gious drama : in its machinery — or, if you j^lease, in its me- diations— the self-determination of man is obscured and often lost. Ileuce this form of the drama has disappeared with the advancing consciousness of Freedom, and Shakespeare has taken special pains to discard it in all its forms. But to return. We said that the collision was betw^een Christianity and Judaism, not as dogmatic systems of The- ology but as realized in the practical life of men. They are thus internal, subjective, and determine human conduct. It is the conflict of two hostile moralities, and the struggle is ethical rather than religious. AVe feel that the consciousness of the two men is entirely different, that their notions of right and wrong are in many respects directly opposite. Shylock cannot help being a Jew in character no more than being a Jew in nationalty. He is no vulgar villain ; he acts accord- ing to his princii)le, according to his end in life ; given his The Merchant of Venice. 138 moral basis, his deeds must follow. He is really not a comic character; on the contrary, he belongs rather to tragedy, for he is the bearer of one of the two grand colliding principles, and it is his principle which has gone down in history, and which mnst again go to the wall in every conflict with the profounder phases of modern spirit. We see the destiny im- pending over him ; but he yields, as the Jews always have done, and is preserved. The poet has thus made him the type of his race, which avoids the life-and-death collision ; for, like him, the Jew has lived among all nations without being swallowed up ; he possesses that happy admixture of stubborness and submission, which has kept him from being destroyed on the one hand and from being absorbed on the other. The cause of this strange preservation lies in the nature of the Jewish faith ; it is not for all men, but for the peculiar people of God ; hence it is not a religion of propa- gandism, and thus avoids any struggle with dominant sys- tems. Still, it maintains its individuality, and has a tenacity which can only spring from the profoundest conviction, or rather from a complete limitation of Intelligence beyond which the Hebrew mind cannot pass. Thus we see renewed, though in a different form, the contest which took place 1800 years ago, on the plains of Judea — the contest which forms, perhaps, the most important period in history, and upon the result of which our entire modern civilization has turned. No wonder, then, that this play has been so popular, and has said so much to mankind, when the content of the modern world and the momentous struggle for its existence loom up in the background. AYe cannot help noting again what per- manent and universal themes the poet seizes upon as mate- rials for his all-comprehensive genius ; for here it is the col- lision between two of the grandest world-historical ejiochs, between the old and new dispensation, which lays the imper- ishable foundation of the play. But this statement that the collision is between Judaism and Christianity is still abstract, and hence we next ask. What is the content of these two systems of religion, espe- cially in their influence upon the practical life of mankind? What objects do these two men place before themselves, to be attained by their living? in other words, What is their i:?4 Tlie Mercliant of Venice. cMid ill Life.' This gives the central point, the germinal unit from whieh all action springs. Antonio is a mercliant, but it is plain that his end in life is not mone}*, nor can it be any Christian's. Antonio's purse is open to all his friends; he is the centre of a jolly crowd of good fellows, though he him- self is inclined to be melancholic ; in such a position, we can easil}' see it is not diflicult to get rid of money. A deeper phase of his moral nature is his hatred of usury; he has re- lieved many a poor victim from the clutches of Shylock, and has denounced the meanness and cruelty of the latter on the Kialto with extremest vehemence. He realizes in the high- est sense of the expression that man is above property — that is enough to show his Christianity. Money is to him only a means — a means of eniovment for himself and friends on the one hand, and for helping his fellow-mortals on the other. Antonio is truh' merciful ; he is the practical embodiment of the holy declaration, '-without charity I am nothing." Chris- tianity always insists upon the neighbor, who has the same rights as yourself; he is a person as well as yourself in the thought of universal Reason, or, as Holy Writ saith, "in the sight of God." Nay, more ; its cardinal doctrine is mercy, — which means that man, within certain limits, is to be shielded from the consequences of his deeds. Man is a finite being — God made him so — and in so far as he is finite, he cannot be held responsible for the lesults of his actions. He is ignorant and hence liable to err; Mercy says that he shall not suffer from his mistakes : but he is also weak and hence liable to transgress ; Mere}* says that he must receive pardon, if the transgression be repented of. Here the conflict arises : Jus- tice demands rigid accountability ; it asserts that man must be responsible for all his acts, while mercy tries to shield even the crouching criminal. These reflections, which may seem a little irrelevant, develop the motive for the most celebrated speech in the play, where Portia divinely discourses of mercy : "The quality of mercj' is not strained; It droppetli as the gentle rain from heaven, rpon the place beneath; it is twice ble-sM ; It ble.-^seth him that gives and him that takes. 'Tis mightiest in the mightiest; it becomes The throned monarch bcttter than his crown ; His sceptre shows the force of temporal ))Ower, The Merchant of Venice. 135 The attribute to awe and majesty. Wherein doth sit the dread and fear of kinad: is he justilied in (loiiiii; so or iiot^ AVe see the contra- diction— the rip:ht to a loaf of bread, on the one hand, against a hnnian life on the other. All of us would say in such a case: Property is the lower, and must be subordinate when it conflicts with hunianitv. Mercy overrides Justice. But the Jew must remain deaf to such considerations, for his highest end is Property; how. tlieii. can he acknowledge a higher? But Shylock's ground of right is still more devoid of a con- tent than the case just mentioned, for he can get back his Property trebled. No ; his bond calls for a pound of llesh ; that and nothing else will satisfy him. Thus the collision is narrowed down to a mei-e empty form of law against the ex- istence of an individual. Law is2)ushed in this way to the extreme limit of self-contradiction, for Law which was made to protect and ])reserve mankind has now become the direct instrument of their destruction ; is not that self-contradicto- ry? But it is the Law, and Law must have its course, says Portia: only mercy can soften its severity and annul its wrong. Hence her appeal for mercy which we have already quoted. But the Jew cannot relent: the character would be "Utterly illogical and untrue if he did. The letter of the Law, then, is to be followed wdth the utmost rigidity ; this is the Jew's own basis, "But, hold I'' says Portia, " the bond men- tions no blood." If you want the letter, you can have it to your heart's content. Portia abandons her first defence, that of mercy, and takes the weapons of the Jew and turns them against him. This contradiction rests upon the fact, that a law, a bond, a contract — yea, language itself — cannot describe the Particular, for they are in their nature general. We all know how cumbersome legal formulas are; with what weari- some detail they try to describe a title, a piece of land, or a testamentary act : it results from this circumstance. Hence if an absolute adherence to the letter is insisted upon, neither Shylock's nor any other bond is possible. Many lawyers have made objection to this point taken by Portia; they say that no court in Christendom would have decided that ai)ound of flesh did not include the blood, though the bond may not have expressly said so. This may be the case, but it does not affect the truth of Shakespeare's representation. His design was to show how formal Law contradicts itself, and to exhibit The Merchant of Venice. 139 the Jew beaten at his own game. From this moment Shy lock subsides ; he sees the point and is completeh' non-plussed. The might of the Form of Law was never more powerfully presented. The judge, the people, and Justice itself, are all on the side of one innocent man, yet they are unable to res- cue him from the clutches of an odious wretch who has the form alone on his side. Still, the poet must find for us some reconciliation with the Law: it would be most ridiculously inadequate if it did not furnish some means for reaching the Jew. This it does, inasmuch as it is made to seize the crime of Shylock just in its truly vulnerable point — criminal inten- tion. This is Portia's next point against hiui. lie has willed the death of a citizen, of which the punishment is confiscation and death. We have seen this motive lying behind all his actions, notwithstanding his howling for Right and Justice. Still we must not suppose that he was a common villain, an lago. or Richard, or Edmund. The subjective side was little emphasized by the Jewish faith ; if men conformed to Law and Relio:ion. it mattered little about motives. Under the old dispensation, the man who committed the most justifiable homicide had to flee the country, and the person who ate pork was damned. Hence -when Shylock is arraigned for his subjective intention, we may fairl}^ assume that this princi- ple lies beyond his consciousness. It is the product of the modern world and Christianity. Still Shylock is saved be- cause he is ready to yield to formal Law when that turns against him ; hence the Law cannot well destroy him. This characteristic is the direct antithesis of the modern spirit whose tendency is rather to break down formal Law, to sacri- fice it to the Individual. Shylock. however, is punished with a truly poetic justice : avarice loses its money, religious and national bigotry sees the Jewish house of Shylock go down forever by the marriage of the daughter with a Christian. It is not the design of Shakespeare to make the Law con- temptible, but to exhibit its limitation. Even the old Romans recognized this limitation — although theirs was essentially the law-giving consciousness — in the well-known maxim: Sumrnum Ju,s, sunima injuria. But it has been left to mod- ern Jurisprudence to recognize and embody its own finitude within itself; in other words, to establish a system of mercy. 140 The Merchant of Venice. The pariloniiiu' power is lodged in the executive by law ; thus the higliest officer of the state, out of his own heart, out of his own intiniti^ subjectivity, reverses the legal decision, and hence is bv Law above Law. The .Fudge has to adminis- ter tlie formal [jaw even in its injustice, and therefore he often, after giving a condemnatory sentence, turns around and signs a paper recommending executive clemency. But the Jurisprudence of X'enice had not yet recognized this dis- tinction. It was a commercial state, its prosperity depended greatly upon the security of Property, hence the iuHexibility of. its Law ; for tlu? Right of Property was deemed of almost paramount imjiortance. Hence its Law cannot save Antonio, though it can condi'mn Shyhx^k. But wliat if the Jew would still insist upon taking his pound of flesh i Then he must have it, and the play becomes a tragedy. Antonio loses his life by the letter of the Law, and Shylock is executed for murder. ]3ut the play cannot admit of this solution. For thus the character of the ^^dw would be wholly untrue, as we have before stated; nor can the poet allow Antonio to perish for a mere mistake. This- would be totally averse to his moral code. Hence the diffi- culty demands mediation and the conclusion must be happy. The piece is, therefore, neither a tragedy nor a comedy, but a middle species of play, wiiich may be called, for want of iu better word, a drama, in a sjjecial sense. But we shall not take up these distinctions now ; we hope to elaborate them in full at some future time. Shylock ranks as one of the most perfect characterizations in Shakespeare. How com})lete in every respect ! How viv- idly does he rise up before us ! Not nuMvly his physical appearance but his entire spiritual nature stand forth in the plainest lineaments. In fact, we feel as if we know him better than we could possibly have done in real life. The poet has laid open the most hidden recesses of character, has portrayed him in the most diverse relations with a truth and fulness unapproached and unapproachable. We ask ourselves, whence this com2)leteness, this richness, this concreteness of characterization? If we wish to see the inlinite difference upon the same subjects, compare Shylock with the best efforts of other di-amatists. Take " L'Avare," by Moliere. Placed The Merchant of Venice. 141 l>y the side of Shylock, how meagre and unsatisfactory ( Can we get at the ground of this extraordinary superiority ^ First, we should say that Sliylock is something more than mere iivarice ; he has a deeper motive in his nature, and his greed for gain is only one of its manifestations. It is true that his end in life is Thrift, as before stated ; but that end is the offspring of his moral and spiritual being, of his religion. Everything goes back to this centre. Shylock is a Jew, one of the "peculiar people"; in all his actions, this deepest X>rinciple of his faith and his consciousness wells out ; given the motive, he marches logically to its consequences. Thus we have arrived at an absolute spiritual unity in the man. The second reason for the transcendent excellence of this characterization is the breadth which it exhibits. The activ- ities of Shj^lock embrace quite the totality of Life ; we see him in his family, in business, in the state, in social relations, in morality, in religion. We behold him brought into contact with every essential form of society, and he acts in them, brings his j)rinciple to the test thj-ough them. Not is he plunged into them from the outside, but is brought into living relation with them. Hence the concreteness, the j)erfection, the complete individualization of character. But it is differ- ent with L'Avare. How limited is the range of the piece in this respect! Harpagon almost descends to the common miser, cut off from the world, in obscurity, dirt and rags, holding fast to his money-bags. His niggardliness in his household, his tyranny in his family, and an example of his extortionate usury, express quite all that we see of him. This is not Shy- lock, who is exhibited in many more and also far more im- portant relations, who sees the world and grapples with it in all its essential forms ; this is what gives content and con- creteness to his character. Hence the Harpagon of Moliere is empty, almost like an abstract personification of avarice ; in fact, it is a meagre caricature compared with the Shylock of Shakespeare. But it gives occasion to many laughable incidents and situations ; this was what Moliere wanted ; he sought for predicaments, and not for characters. But here this essay must close. The subordinate jDerson- ages of the play have hardly been mentioned, though worthy of the highest admiration. Especially the character of Portia 142 Empirical Certihide. is enticing. One question at least must be noticed: Has not Shakespeare sinned ai^ainst the higliest principle of Art — namely, self-determination— in making Portia's choice of a husband depend upon tlie merest accident? We answer^ no ; and it is most interesting to observe what care he has taken to insist upon tlie right of subjective choice, and with wliat consummate skill he has turned a purely external inci- dent into an emblem of Free-Will. For the selection of the caskets indicates the character and end of the (dioosers ; thus we understand the nature of their motives, and hence their respective deserts. Therefore the result of their choice is not accidental, but inherent in their character. But a full elabo- ration of this subject cannot now be entered upon. EMPIRICAL CERTITUDE. By John C Tiiomi'Son. We conceive and shall attempt to demonstrate that Berke- ley's error lies in two mistaken notions ; tirst, that the image or appearance is given in sensation ; and secondly, thtit our minds are so constituted that we are forced to believe in a corresponding reality to the appearance ; — both of which are caused by the fundamental fallacy which attributes many separate faculties to the mind, as memory, will, a reasoning power, &c. The conditions of the argument are two proposi- tions, which may be thus expressed : {a) Mere consciousness is the fundamental form of all the modes of the thinking activity, and not a spe- cial mode of the activity. {U) Error can enter the human mind only under cover of an inferred identity. The second above proposition is intended as a corollary to Descartes' test of certitude, namely, that we have a perfectly clear and distinct idea only of our own existence {cogito, erga sum), and our certainty of any other thing is more or less reliable as it approaches the certainty of our existence. It will not be questioned that Sensation is the first stage of experience. Sensation, in our sense of the word, is the sim- Empirical Certitude. ' 14B plest complex fact, having two factors, of which one, the psy- chological, when detached from the other, the physical (as in memory), is knowledge; but undetached (as in sensation), it is feeling, or pure consciousness. Mind and matter, it is true, have nothing in common known to us, but it is nevertheless a psychological fact that pure consciousness (meaning the highest measure of consciousness) is only experienced in the act in which they are brought in contact (meaning the imme- diate cognition of a mateiial motion). The psychological side of the sensation is then an act of consciousness. And the power to be conscious is alone the Ego, an essential activ- ity, which would lose itself in space and remain forever un- conscious were it not to encounter some resistance, in the effort to overcome which, it becomes conscious of something not self, and in the same act necessarily conscious of self. The other factor of the sensation, which may be called the physical side or material moiety, is the mere motion of a nerve of sense. It may be that the nervous system, with all its phe- nomena of ganglia and sensational centres, acts as described by Bain and Spencer (and generally the school of modern physiologists), and that an image — for instance, a landscape — pictured on the retina, is communicated to consciousness^ as they say ; but nevertheless we know that, whether or not all its constituent parts are thus presented simultaneously, the image, as an image, is not cognized until the sensations of which it is constituted fall into their proper relations to one another. By the infant's mind, in the beginning of life, no image is cognized at all, but only the several parts of the image. In other words, until with experience Consciousness has mastered the appearance, nothing is presented but a lake of lioating lines and colors in bewildering confusion. So the artist knows that the picture on his canvass he has himself constructed with countless minor strokes. Commencing now with the first stage of experience. As- suming the Mind to be a single faculty, it is unnecessary to consider our physiological conditions further than that the act of consciousness in sensation is a mental act having a corresponding material fact, namely, the other moiety of the sensation. It is, in strictness, an act of consciousness caused by the motion of a nerve of sense ; but, in common parlance, 144 Empirical Certitude. it is the consciousness of the affection, or motion, of the nerve. To know, perceive, or be conscious, are then, in sensation at least, convertible terms. But since the mental moiety of a sensation is an act of consciousness, or one motion of a single power, while the material moiety is a motion of the attenu- ated nerve tissue, it follows that of a hundred such material motions hap]>eniug simultaneously in the nervous system, only one becomes the material moiety of a sensation by the Power of Consciousness (Mind) being drawn thereto ; while the ninety-and-nine others, uuperceived, are mere tremors of nerve tissue. So that however speedily acquaintance with the nerves of sense may be acquired in the lirst stage of ex- perience, that knowledge is not acquired but once, but by parts: and is. in fact, a general knowledge of the motions of the nerves of sense, composed of a particular acquaintance with the motions of each nerve, or class of nerves. We pro- ceed now to show that the unassisted exercise of the Power of Consciousness not only results in such acquaintance with the nei"ves of sensation, but retains all of those particular knowledges, thoughts, or ideas. The Mind being an essential activity, in the condition of a continued act of consciousness would be at rest; and, from that state of rest, its motion would consist in the activit}^, be- ing arrested. For, to know, perceive, or be conscious, being the one motion of the Mind (an essential activity), it follows that when a thing is known, perceived, or cognized, the Mind no longer knows, perceives, or is conscious of it. To explain this seeming paradox, let us suppose A, the material moiety of the first sensation. The mental moiety of that sensation, whether we call it an idea, a perception, or an act of con- sciousness, we take to be in fact the act of consciousness of the greatest vivacity. Such sensation would be an affirma- tion of existence satisfying to the fullest extent the Cartesian axiom, cogito, ergo sinn. We are. for the sake of argument, supposing our physiological conditions to be such that A, the j)sychological side of the lirst sensation, is a more perfect act of consciousness than that experienced in the sexual or- gasm, or a draft of cold water in fever, or the inhalation of fresh air by a diver on coming to the surface. Supposing thus A, the lirst sensation, let us suppose a continuation of it Empirical Certitude. 145 and we suppose it lost to consciousness. Why so ? Because, prior to the idea A, the Mind was a certain entity, to wit, the unconditioned Ego ; but, subsequent!}', it was the Mind con- ditioned by the idea A. Then the continuation of A awakens no consciousness, because if it could again take in the idea A it would have the same idea duplicated, which is absur- dity. The perception of A was the arresting of the uncondi- tioned activity. But when the Power cognizes A and nothing- else, A is no longer known, perceived, or cognized, because the Activity has then no other motion but the idea A, and in that one motion is at rest. The form would be an essential activity and its mode the idea A. When however we suppose the mind having the idea A, to know, perceive, or become conscious of B, the material moiety of the second sensation, we see that it has at once gained in- definitely more than the two ideas A and B. For whereas at the perceiving of A there was in consciousness no other idea,, on the contrary at the perceiving of B there was already in consciousness the idea A ; and as the perception of B was a change of the Ego from its then condition to the condition of knowing B, necessarily in that change is an active conscious- ness of both A and B. Because consciousness means the Ego's consciousness of itself, the Ego ; and, being an essential activ- ity ,[that involves the consciousness of its own changes of mo- tion. It cannot change from one condition to another without being conscious that it does so ; involving the consciousness of, 1st, the condition from which it changed; 2d, the act of changing ; 3d, the condition to which it changed. And all but so many successive thoughts, ideas, or acts of conscious- ness ; for the Activity being a single power, all thought is a succession of phenomena : co-existence of phenomena is im- possible. So far, then, there is certainly no other psychological fac- tor engaged but the single faculty of Consciousness : yet the exercise of that facult}^ alone in the first two sensations in- volves an act of comparison, because it is the setting off" of two contrasted ideas in the mind. But, in the supposed in- stance, is the knowing of B as large an act of consciousness as was the knowing of A ? No. Because the knowing of A was the act of the unconditioned Power, and therefore the Vol. vi.— 10 14(1 Empirical Certitude. purest art of (.'onsciousness, meaning of the highest vivacity. Whereas the knowing of B was the change of the Mind from its condition of A to tliat of B, and, 1. In so far as there are properties in comvion to A and B there is no change at all. Motion consists not in the cliange effected, but in the act of changing; and here, as to the properties in common, there was no act of changing. Hence, having the idea A, the acqui- sition of B is the active consciousness only of those proper- ties of B wlierein it differs from A ; i.e. the individifality of B. In other words, in knowing B, the hither boundary of B is at the forward extremity of the act of consciousness, while its other boundary is somewhere in A, and includes so much of A as is common to A and B. Of course the same is true of the change of the Activity from B to C, from C to D, and so on. Now the condition of the mind prior to the first idea A, and then its condition subsequent to that idea but prior to B, the second idea, are both unnatural conditions, for the rea- son that, in either instance, as above shown, it is the being at rest of an essential activity, the being unconscious of a sole power of consciousness. But subsequent to the perception B, if never another idea should be acquired, the Ego would forever continue changing from the one idea to the other. Of <'ourse it would pass from the one idea to the other upon some property in common to the two. And, of course also, if the two ideas have nothing in common, the Activity would for- ever remain unconscious (lost) in the channel in which it was left. Such property in common is the nexus, or bridge of identity, connecting the two ideas. To fall into an idea having no point of identity with another, and to fail to be recalled by sensation, would leave the Mind detached from all it knows. So death separates; and so birth starts the soul anew, with or witliout ideas d priori, as Plato or Aris- totle may be in the right. In any sensation, the act of consciousness caused by the motion of the nerve is a consciousness not of the motion of the nerve (material moiety of the sensation) but of itself, the mental moiety. And as the material moiety is a particular motion of the nerve, so the mental moiety is equally an indi- Empirical Certitude. 147 vidual act of consciousness. They have nothing else in com- mon. But, attenuated as is that common property, in it is involved this fundamental psychological law, viz.: 2. Although it is true that the act of consciousness in sensation is a purely subjective fact, yet the individuality of each material moiety is corre- lated by a corresponding individuality of each mental moiety. We say, conventionally, that one thought suggests another ; but that is in effect to say that every thought, act of con- sciousness, or idea, has its nexus of identity with some other thought; and the Ego, an essential activity, would forever thus pass from one thought to another ; because change, so soon as effected, becomes rest, and motion consists in the act of changing. For example, in sensation we are conscious of the act of touching, but not of continued contact. And, S. Except in the stage of sensation, every psychological act supposes two ideas ; the second following the first and conditioned by it. We can by no conception escape from that law. To do so would be to conceive an unconditioned idea, which is impos- sible. In sensation each psj^chological act is conditioned by its physical correlate, the material moiety of the sensation ; while in all other stages of experience every thought is con- ditioned by two other thoughts, namely, its immediate ante- cedent and its immediate sequent. The supposed necessity for Memory and Volition, separate mental faculties, is begotten by our experience of material force, erroneously, though almost unavoidably, applied to mental action. For, seeing every material force exhausted in the exercise, and of itself coming to an end, it is too easily suggested that the same is true of the Mind ; an essential ac- tivity, to which therefore a persistent idea would be a blank. Perhaps it is easier to accept phenomena in sensation, and perception (of images), as being mere acts of consciousness, than to admit that a sej^arate faculty. Memory, is not assured to us in the facts of consciousness. Yet the proposition will stand the test of any analysis. For, in supposing the mental moiety A, unless we suppose that idea to remain after the cessation of its corresponding material moiety, we in fact suppose the psychological side of the sensation to be also 148 Empirical Certitude. subject tt) rho hiw of iiuitciial force. In other words, when A is known, as it woukl add nothing to that knowledge to con- tinue the presentation of A, so it would be strange if it should take from that knowledge to cease the presentation of it. As to Yolition, to elect which of the simultaneousl}^ occurring motions the mind shall perceive, tliat faculty is demonstrably naught ; and for the plain reason that the perception must precede the choice. Before, however, proceeding to the second stage of experi- ence, namely, that of the perception of images, let us pause brieli}^ to consider what general, or universal, ideas are ac- quired in the stage of sensation. After the tirst sensation the Mind, in any two thoughts, certainly experiences that idea which of all others is declared by the Platonist to be an intuition — the idea, namely, of Time. For, every thought being a single motion of the Mind, necessarily any two given thoughts, or ideas, must occur at different times. Co-existence of ideas in consciousness being impossible, it follows that the Ego is conscious of itself in its change from the one idea to the other, which is to say is conscious that the one proceeds and the other comes after. This is no more than to say that it changes, and is conscious of changing, from A to B instead of from B to xV. Truths are but perceived relations; the idea of time is nothing else. We cannot conceive a Universe with- out Time, it is true, but only because we cannot conceive our own non-existence ; for our existence is no more than a suc- cession of phenomena strung upon the consciousness of a continuing personal individuality. And this universal and necessary idea of Time, which is no more than the self-con- sciousness, in every act of consciousness, that the act differs from its antecedent and its sequent, is involved in any two conceivable acts of consciousness, or thoughts.* * -'The perception of Space must precede that of Time, for it is only tlirough the former that we can reach the latter." — (Jour. Spec. Phil., vol. i.. No. 3. p. 177.) This general error, as we consider it. is a consequence of the general loose idea of sensation, supposing the image, if not also the conception of external reality, to be given in sensation ; and which, consequently, refers the first per- ception of successive motions not to the consciousness of successive phenomena in the tirst stage (sensation), or the second (perr-eption of images), but to the third, namely, the intelligible movements of bodies in Siiace. Empirical Certitude. 149 When, therefore, it is said that experience is incapable of guaranteeing an}^ universal and necessary idea, it is mani- fest that the assertion holds good only upon the assumption that the perception of images, and the reference of them to ■external cause, is the first stage of experience. Whereas neither the image nor the notion of externality are found in sensation at all ; and those truths of universal and necessary acceptation, called sometimes ideas d 'priori., are such onl}^ to the extent that they were in the Mind prior to the conception of an external cause to the image. Having in fact been ac- quired in sensation, the stage of immediate apprehension, of which the first act (to wit, the idea A, the mental moiety of the first sensation) is not only antecedent to all the catego- ries, because antecedent to tlte idea of Relation., but is, for the same reason, antecedent to all those truths of universal and necessary acceptation ; except, perhaps, the idea of pleasure or pain, the originals of good and bad. Those universal and necessary truths, acquired in the first stage of experience, are Time, Individuality (including Identity), and Relation. These may, with absolute certainty, be referred to the stage of na- ked sensation, because the definition of consciousness (self- consciousness) assures us that they are experienced in any succession of phenomena, however early ; and the facts of con- sciousness assure us, with a certainty equal to the certainty of our own existence, that they are still more clearly and distinctly exercised and confirmed in the second stage of ex- perience, namely, that of the perception of images. Every mental moiety, or psychological side, of a sensation is neither more nor less than that act of pure consciousness, the realiza- tion of our own existence. And those necessary truths (their originals) are certainly acquired in that stage of experience, because the Power of Consciousness cannot change from A to B without being conscious of the change. If A and B were not individual acts, their identity would be complete, and consequently as to the second thought there would be no mo- tion of the Ego at all, but the space of the second thought, B, would be to consciousness a blank. In what the}' difi'er, and in what they are the same, consists their Relation ; the con- sciousness of which is included in the self-consciousness of the change from the one idea to the other. Every two phe- 150 Empirical Certitude. nomena therefore, experienced in succession, involve an act of comparison ; and, 4. Every act of co7npa7'iso7i involves the general ideas Good or Bady Time, Individuality, Identity, Relation. Relation is the tertium quid of Individuality and Identity. If there were no Identity there could be no Relation, because the Individuality of entities would be complete ; and so, if there were no Individuality there could be no Relation, be- cause complete Identity would constitute a one-ness. Coming now to the second stage of experience, that of the apprehension of sensuous images, it is manifest that the im- age is simply the perception of many simultaneous motions of an organ in their relations to one another. Take for exam- ple the visual image. That nerve (the optic) is the smaller base of a truncated cone ; upon it are converged the rays of light reflected on the eyeball. Were the rays to fall with equal force, as from a concave surface of snow, there would be no image, because of the identity of the sensations. But where the rays strike with unequal force, an image, oi-, in. other words, natural conjunction of sensations, is the result; because each idea, the mental moiety of a constituent sensa- tion, has its own individuality, as well as its point of identity with its immediate antecedent and sequent. Thus it is that the picture painted by the pencils of light on the retina is the correlate of the image in consciousness, since each mental moiety of a sensation is the correlate of its material moiety. And thus, also, J. The image in consciousness is not a representation of the affection of the organ, but, on the contrary, the affection of the organ is a correlate of the image ; and in the instance of the visual image it is a picture in vir- tue of that fact. The colors, the harmony, the pleasure, are all afl'ections of the soul, while the correlative aflection of the organ is no more than a certain number of simultaneous mo- tions of a nerve of sense : and which form a picture only because, being individually objects of immediate conscious- ness (material moieties of sensations), they seem to be identi- cal with their corresponding mental moieties, which together constitute that harmonious conjunction of ideas we call an Empirical Certitude. 151 image. The consciousness of the many simultaneous impres- sions on the retina was at first a particular apprehension of individuals, but with continued experience becomes an ap- prehension of the many in their relations to one another, i.e. each to its immediate antecedent and sequent: which api^re- hension is the image in consciousness, as completely an indi- vidual thought as the sensation itself, by virtue of the ever self-determining action of the Activity. (See the psychologi- cal law expressed in Rule 8.) It is naught to say that each organ has its specific mode of being affected ; for that each one of the five special senses is in fact a special sense of touch, to be admitted needs only to be suggested. The nerves of the special sense of Touch, deter- mining to the surface of the body, which come in contact with solid foreign bodies, are moved only by the consequent com- pression of the fiesh tissue in which they are contained. But when we consider the other four special senses, we see that they difi'er from the sense of Touch only as " the hand of lit- tle employment hath the daintier sense." And that while so placed in the physical system as to be not subject to the in- fluence of contact with solid foreign bodies, they are severally subject to the influence of contact with external matter more attenuated, each answering in its own manner to its peculiar stimulus. The image, therefore, to whichsoever organ it may belong, is an infallible proposition, because it is a natural conjunction of infallible ideas ; the ideas of the first category, naked sensations, each one of which is individually a mere assertion of existence ; and the image asserts nothing more. If Logic is the science of affirmation, and if Affirmation is the active exercise of the Mind, then the thoughts, or idpas, in sensation are nothing but affirmations of existence. iVnd if Judgment is that operation of the Mind by which joining different ideas together it affirms or denies something, then, 6. An image is but another affirmation of existence, in which there is no more possibility of mistake than in the affirmations of mere sensations, ideas of the first category. Now, the only thought, or idea, in which something is af- firmed immediately, and not involving other ideas, is the affirmation of existence in sensation. Of those immediate 152 Empirical Certitude. atiinniitions. the constituent number perceived in their proper rehitions (considered as sensations), or in their logical se- quence (considered as ideas), is tin? image, another aflirmation of existence. That the conjunction of ideas constituting the image cannot be expressed in words is true, but since the result, the judgment, can be designated by an arbitrary term, we violate no rule of logic in calling the image a proposi- tion ; and, 7. It is an infallible proposition, because a proper conjunction of the infal- lible ideas of the first category ; affirming nothing but e.ristence, and carrying loith it no inferred identity with something else. The facts of consciousness assure us that every idea in the ■first category (mental moiety of a sensation) is a totality, an individual idea. But the facts of consciousness assure us with equal positiveness that the image is a totality ; and that, in fact, S. A consciousness of the individuality {self-determination) of phenomena is the fundamental law of thought ; loithout which not only is no certi- tude possible, but no reason is possible. To strike it from the Mind would be the obliteration of every idea, as to smear the artist's paint while still wet upon the canvass would be the effacement of his picture. Or. per- haps, it is a better figure to say that the mind, thus without thought, would compare to the present ever self-determining action of the Activity, as ink spilled on the pai^er, to the same ink separated into letters, the letters into syllables, the syl- lables into words, tlie words into sentences. For, assuming the Activity to be a single faculty of consciousness, what Mill and others have designated as comi)lex ideas, or clus- ters of ideas, should in iigure be represented neither by sur- face nor by cubic, but by lin<;ar measurement. Xow, first, would such attainment of the image by the con- junction of sensations be a logical process? and secondly, is such the constitution of the image ^ As to the first. After the immediate affirmation of exist- ence in sensation, any other affirmation is the result of, and presupposes, a concatenation of ideas logically leading to the affirmation. But the image, or idea, in the second category is a concatenation of sensations (the psychological sides or Empin'cal Certitude. 153 mental moieties, ideas in the first category) into a single idea ; an affirmation itself of existence, and one which not merely presupposes, but in fact includes, the train of ideas on which it depends. It is, therefore, the perfection of a logi- •cal process. Now as to the second aspect of the question : namely, ad- mitting such to be a logical process, is the image the result of that process I That it is sc, we have tlie assurance of con- sciousness. First: in the fact that while the analogy of the different genera of images is complete, only one genus, the. visual, is a jjerception {seriatim, but with the infinite quick- ness of thought) of the simultaneous afleclious of the organ ; while, on the contrary, the others are constituted in every instance of an appreciable succession of sensations. There are, indeed, but two other genera, namely, the tactile and the auditory. The nasal and gustator}^ senses present no images, their ideas belonging to the first category, that of naked sen- sation, always. Secondly : in the fact that while in two of the genera the image can be alwaj'S thus analyzed into its constituent ideas, in all three — the visual as well as the other two — the intrusion of an idea having no point of identity with its antecedent and sequent (or so slight as to give it undue individuality) destroys the concatenation ; the Mind jjassing at once from the milder consciousness of the second category to the more acute consciousness of the first. Such an idea, intruding or out of place, in the auditory image is a false note in music. An instance, in the visual image, is the sensation caused by an inharmonious stripe or check in a shawl or dress pattern ; in the tactile image, is caused by a raised point or line while the hand is feeling a smooth surface. Coming now to the third stage of experience, we see that necessarily the ideas of that category are constituted ideas, or judgments; the constitution of each being an harmonious conjunction of idea of the two former stages. We say neces- sarily so, because otherwise the nature of the Activit3^ as we have followed it from its condition of tabula rasa through the first and second stages of experience, is changed in the third. In the first and then in the second stage we have seen the Mind, from the proper nature of the Activity itself, in a mere succession of phenomena to cognize, first, ideas of naked sen- J 54 Empirical Certitude. sation individually ; next, the live Universals corresponding- to tlu' live special senses, under some one of which each sev- eral sensation falls ; and lastl}^, in the same progress of the Activity, to construct the image. Now, if it Xw. so that the images of different genera have nothing further in common, then knowUnlge transcending that of experience must be pos- tulated to enable the mind to arrive at the idea of an external cause to the image in consciousness. But if, on the contrary,, any one of the general ideas, or truths, of universal and ne- cessary acceptation, acquired in the first or second stage of experience, shall form a point of identity between two images of ditferent genera, then the same law of consciousness which in the progress of the Activity constructed the image out of sensations, will likewise construct the ontological idea out of imae:es. Now, experience soon points out a connecting link of iden- tity common to two images of different genera, and one which is the very largest possible evidence of a common cause, as we come afterwards to express it : the identity, namely, of Time. So soon as that (as an inevitable) point of identity is established in consciousness, the mere conception of two sev- eral images in that relation to one another is in itself the idea of a common cause. For any two phenomena successively experienced involve an act of comparison, and here the act of comparison hnds no other nexus of the two ideas save simultaneousness of creation. Neither at that stage of expe- rience, nor ever afterwards, have two images of different genera (the tactile and visual for example, or either or both with the auditory) any other possible identity in conscious- ness than the reference of them to a common cause by reason of simultaneous appearance. It is to be borne in mind that while the several simultaneous images have so little in com- mon, yet have they nothing at all antagonistic, not being conflicting impressions on a common organ. The ideas of Distance and of Space are judgments (in the third stage of experience) constituted of images of Touch (judgments of the second stage) ; for not only is our body, to the Ego, an object like any other external matter, but the organic senses, such as those of the alimentary canal and of muscular activity, are in fact modes of the sense of Touch. The sensations conse- Empirical Certitude. 155 quent on stretching forth the arm, for instance, constitute an image of that special sense, the same as do those consequent on grasping an object with the hand. So likewise of the con- catenation of sensations consequent on any similar exercise of the person, or parts thereof. That the idea of Distance is a judgment, or proposition, resulting from a sufficient expe- rience of those images, we shall not pause to argue, because, as it seems to us, one who would question it would be equally ready to question his own existence. An infant, in the act of grasping an object, is conscious of two several images, nam'ely, the visual and the tactile. The two have the iden- tity of Time only. An object not within his grasp presents to him the visual image alone ; but then add the advantage of distance within reach, and straightway he has the other image, that of touch, again simultaneous with the visual im- age. The same experience, continued, not only results in the knowledge, as a Universal proposition, that, having the vis- ual or the auditory image, or both, or a sensation of smell, the additional experience of a certain distance brings within the grasp a tactile image also ; but likewise results in the knowledge, as a Universal proposition, that the visual and auditory images and the sensations of smell are cognized with more or less distinctness according to the distance of the object. And since the experience of continued distance be- yond that at which the tactile image is attained, results in a loss of all the images, necessarily a sufficient experience re- sults in the knowledge that the cause (potentiality of attain- ment) of the appearances is at a certain distance from us. In that is our idea of Space, which is neither more nor less than the impossibility of divesting the mind of a conception of the potentiality of Distance, in all directions from an}^ given point. Every accident of infancy throws the sensations of smell and images of touch, of sight, and of sound, into con- catenations whose results are the ideas of distance, of direc- tion, of space. Experience of the identity of time to the several images causes the presence of one to suggest the other two, or the presence of two to suggest the third. Wherefore it is that the infant soon comes to grasp at any object he may see in obedience to that law of nature which causes the muscular system to obey thought ; or turns his eye in the direction of IfHi Empirical Certitude. a voice addressed Xo liini. ]>ut, as before observed, although the ideas of distance, space, and direction, are concatenations •of images of Touch, yet the ideas of a common cause to the several images of different genera leads directly to the per- ception of a certain relati(^n in the distinctness of the visual and the auditory image to tlie distance of the object. So that although the young infant will grasp at the moon and stars, yet with but a little additioiuil experience he begins to meas- ure with his eye, and to grasp only at those things within his reach. Tims a landsman, for the lirst time in his life on the sea shore, is ready to cast a pebble at an object far beyond his throw ; and supposes the ship to be a mile off, which is really live. Descartes, in his sixth Meditation, referring to the decep- tions practised not by Nature but by our inconsiderate judg- ments, cites the instance that " stars, towers, and all other distant bodies, are of the same tigure and size as they appear to our eyes at a distance." These and similar instances (and which Descartes righth^ called inconsiderate judgments) have been, since the day of Berkeley, attempted to be accounted for thus — to borrow the words of a modern fashionable writer : "A little knowledge of ox)tics appears to explain the difference, but does not. At fifty yards you say the tower appears round, but it really is square. At fifty yards, we reply, it appears round, and at one yard it appears square. It is neither. Both round and scjuare are conceptions of the mind, not attributes of things : they have a subjective, not an objective, existence." Now, so long as the suggestion of external reality is attri- buted to the mere cognizance of the image, certitude is not demonstrable, because we turn our back to the experience which led to the belief, thus going down the stream in search of its fountain. The suggestion of squareness, in the given instance, is no part of the visual apjoearance at all. It belongs, on the contrary, to our knowledge of Extension (or place in Space), which is a judgment or idea in the third category, constituted of certain ideas of the second category — namely, images of Touch. But for our knowledge derived from that sense, experience to the end of time of the sense of sight, unassisted, would leave us at last with the tower appearing equally round at the distance of one j^ard and of fifty. But, Empirical Certitude. 157 as we have shown, a certain appearance of tactile images having resulted in the idea of Distance, a continued experi- ence in the knowledge of distance assures us that the visual image is cognized with greater or less distinctness according to our distance from the object. At the distance of fifty yards, and while the visual image is not distinct, it has a greater identity with the distinct image of a round tower than a square one. But, as the distance is diminished and the image becomes more distinct, its identity with the distinct im- age of a round tower becomes less, and with that of a square tower greater. So that when, finally, we are conscious of a distinct image, w^e are as conscious of the image of a square tower as of our own existence. And whereas the approach satisfies us of the squareness of the object, a return to the distance of fifty yards does not in the least cause a return to the opinion that the tower is round; because of the square image, or appearance, we have as clear and distinct an idea as we have of our own existence, but of the round appearance we have not. Not only is the idea of roundness or of square- ness not given by the sense of sight, but no idea of external- ity at all is given in the visual image, or any other image, unassisted. That idea, as we have shown, is a judgment in the third category, and is, in eft'ect, the logical result of a concatenation of ideas of the previous stages of experience, self-determined by the Activity into a single idea. It is, in- deed, no more than the idea that the several simultaneous images are referable to a common cause. Extension is the idea obtained by natural induction (i.e. by the action of the ever self-determining Activity) from a sufficient experience of the images, or judgments, of Touch. A blind man has the idea of extension as well as one who can see ; and, therefore, 9. When we say that we see the object to be square, we can only mean that ive are conscious of a visual image such as Experience assures us has its identity (common cause) with a square image of Touch. The author, to subserve his purpose, must seek another illus- tration in some instance in which the object shall, under the same conditions, present at one time a round appearance and at another a square one. That instance, we apprehend, can not be found. The distant tower never appears square ; the oar dipped into water never appears straight. 158 Empirical Certitude. From the expeiienre of images of the. sense of Touch, re- sult tlie ideas of Space and Distance ; as also from the same experience the idea of Extension, or place in space. The simultaneous images of the different senses having but one nexus, the identity of time, the logical induction is that their cause is in that place in space at which the image of touch is attainable. For the reason that after we have arrived at the ideas of Space, Distance, and Extension, we know that we are conscious of the image of sight, or visual image, as clearly and distinctly as we are conscious of our own existence, only when we can add to it the image of Touch ; or, in other words, verify the inferred identity. But as the tactile image is only attainable by the annihilation of distance, it follows that the greatest distinctness of the visual image is only attainable by the annihilation of distance — equivalent to the attainment of the image of Extension. And when it is said that the tac- tile image is simultaneous with the greatest consciousness of all the images, we say in effect that the cause of extension is the cause of all the images. The cause of Extension must be where Extension is, or else we should separate cause and ef- fect. But the meaning of Extension is place in Space. There- fore the idea of that place in Space is affirmed by each one of the several images, each confirming the testimony of the others. When, therefore, the visual appearance affirms the object to be square, what it in fact affirms is that at the dis- tance of a yard is the cause of itself, the visual image ; and that the same cause has such a place in space (Extension) as will cause a square tactile image. The knowledge that it will do so results from many simultaneous experiences of the like visual images and square tactile images. And when a sufficient experience has resulted in the knowledge that the cause of a certain visual image is also the cause of a certain tactile image, the cognizance of the visual image, in the act of informing us of its own cause, informs us also of the poten- tial cause of a corresponding tactile image. In other words, when the object at the distance of one yard appears square, it is that we are conscious of a certain visual image, the cause of which, experience has taught us would prove to be also the cause of a square tactile image, were the distance annihi- lated and the extension of the object realized by the organs of Touch. Reply to Criticism " On the Dialectic Method.'''' 159 Here then, in the third stage of experience, is the first pos- sibility of an error in the affirmations of Consciousness, and that error comes in (b; The only form in ichich it is possible for error to enter the hum a mind, namely, under cover of an inferred identity. The proposition is that the visual image is caused by an external object whose cause is also potentially the cause of a certain image of extension. The error comes of the failure to verify each step of the induction. But as the proposition is the simplest conceivable, being composed of but two particu- lars, it may always be resolved into its parts, and the induc- tion thereupon either verified or corrected — not only with perfect rigor logically, but with the clearness and distinct- ness of the consciousness of our own existence. For the par- ticulars of the proposition are images of the second category, ideas in which severally error is impossible because severally they affirm nothing but existence. So long as the image affirms nothing but itself, an act of consciousness, error is impossible : loJien, hotoever, the image seems to affirm the po- tential cause of another than itself.^ then it does not affirm with the same confidence as it affirms itself : for the reason that it is then no longer an individual affirmation, but is one •of the parts of a proposition in the third category, which proposition it is that affirms the oar dipped into water to be l)roken, the distant tower to be round. ON THE DIALECTIC METHOD. (E. V. HART?.rANN's Reply, in the Philosophische Monatshe.fte, to the Criticism of his Essaj^ ''•On the Dialectic Method." by Prof. Michelet.) Translated from the German by Louis Soldax. If the anatomical knife pierces the vital nerve of any being we must not be astonished at the appearance of spasmodic convulsions ; their non-appearance, on the contrar}', would be an indication of a failure to hit the right point. In this way it can be but flattering for my essay that it called forth a violent eff"usion of wrath from Professor Michelet as the 160 Hartmann/s Reply to Criticism of his Essay representative of Hegelianism, and the above consideration renders more excusable the irritated and personal tone of his criticism, which in some places steps beyond the limits of what is becoming. If I have not hesitated "to print the whole trash," though Mr. Michelet, as he did not omit publicly to state, had previously had the kindness, gratefully acknowl- edged by me. to communicate to me in writing all his objec- tions to my wliole manuscript ad, inarginem ; if these objec- tions could not move me to even any changes worth naming, it is plain enough that I felt very little hurt by his thunder- bolts, and very little touched by the anticipation of " stand- ing before the eyes of the public at large the repjoof which I iirst sent him in a confidential letter."' Xot what Mr. Michelet wrote causes me to break my si- lence, but wliat he did not write. I will explain what I mean. All that Mr. Miclielet says can essentially be classified under two headings. Under the first, Hegel's assertions and tarns,which in the respective chapters I had critically ana- lyzed and annihilated, are simply repeated as if they were still "alive and kicking" and my critique did not exist. This mode of acting may be very convenient, and perhaps sufficient to produce a bad opinion of my essay with those who do not know if, but the serving up again of the sufficiently known dialectic phrases will not pass for a refutation. Under the second heading, wherever I infer the most immediate conse- quences from Hegel, the objection is raised that I did not understand Hegel, inasmuch as he never said such a thing ; as if I did not know this just as well. But he who asserts, asserts also the consequences, and only the proof of having inferred incorrect consequences can refute them. But such proof Mr. Michelet brings nowhel'e, reproaching me, on the contrary, with not knowing that Hegel said just the opposite of those inferred consequences. It is all the worse for me that I show, a few lines below, that I know the passage in which the opposite is said, for now I am made responsible for the contradiction which I have exposed in Hegel's thoughts, as though for one which I have committed myself. I shall gladly pass over in silence the compiling and quot- ing of fragments torn out from their connection which was intended to exhibit to the reader what absurdities I had writ- " On the Dialectic Metliod,'' by Prof. Micheletr 161 ten. I shall not speak about Mr. Michelet's peculiar habit of denying all erudition in the History of Philosophy to all but those who approve of the intentional misrepresentations in Hegel's History of Philosophy ; for science tabled this mat- ter long ago. All this could not have brought me to a word of reply, for whosoever feels interested in the subject may read my little pamphlet, and will there find the best refu- tation. But Mr. Michelet, though discussing most of my chapters, even giving their titles, has omitted altogether to mention two chapters which happen to be the most important ones; he has ignored them in a critique extending over sixteen pages, in which he allowed room even to the most insignificant thrusts and reflections. To explain the meaning of this in- teresting fact, I must give a short outline of the thread of my critique. 1. I point out in Hegel's Dialectics the hitherto seldom no- ticed dualism between an esoteric side which must decline every justification outside of itself, standing purely on rea- son, and an exoteric side which finds the former stand-point practically untenable, and makes the inconsistent attempt of justifying itself before the understanding. (Against this Mr. Michelet could show nothing but the repetition of some of the most common dialectic phrases.) 2. I show that the exoteric side essentially seeks its justifi- cation in the proof that contradiction is contained in all being and in all thinking, with the intention of inciting the under- standing by this knowledge to throw itself into the arms of reason. (That this means the setting aside of the principle of contradiction I proved strictly, but Mr. Michelet responded by the strange imputation that I intended to deny the ex- istence of contradiction in thoughts and actions of men in general ; while he quotes my words on the next page, " that contradiction is only found where it was made previously"; in which expression I say distinctly enough that " contra- diction is found," but only as the product (and therefore at the same time as the indication) of error ; as error is pos- sible only in conscious, discursive thought, and not in the unconscious, intuitive thought, which Hegel terms objective thought. What kinds of antitheses form a contradiction in Vol. vi.— 11 162 Hartm ami's Reply to Criticism of Ids Essay, &c. their union, aiul uii Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. everythiim- in neutral colors, and waiting till the forms of life have grown old ere it treat them, or in its forgetting the eagle which tiies toward the sun, and beginning its flight only at the approach of twilight, like Minerva's owl. We have a liv- ing faith in the vigorous power of thought. But, for that very reason, we are ready to protest when a philosophy coquets with Freedom, and deals more with the flimsy, captivating- word " freedom " than with solid knowledge ; or when, as if it enjoyed a monopoly of freedom of thought, like a dema- gogue in Plato's sense, it tries, with glib talk about Freedom, to ingratiate itself with the mob, or, what tends in the same direction, woos the favor of popular opposition against sup- posed oppressors. What, after all, do those accusations of want of freedom, brought against the author of the Logical Investigations^ mean i It is one thing to impute interested motives, another to refute a w^ork, the fruit of long years of patient thought. Under any circumstances, it would be better to tear the work to pieces before the eyes of the public, if it will not hold to- gether, and to leave the author's private views entirely out of the question. Such, indeed, used to be the practice in the "closed circle" {geschlossenen Bunde) of the Hegelian school, whenever it could be applied to works of a hostile character. Now that other methods are appealed to, every unbiassed person will be able to find out the value and grounds of such imputations. The man who utters them cannot believe them himself, if he can cease feeling disconcerted and out of hu- mor, and reflect on the plain facts. Or, does he not reflect that the Undersigned, whom, in tolerably plain terms, he degrades into the logical creature of a higher judgment not his own, was, already at the time when he himself received a call to propagate Hegel, occupying a position — though, indeed, a lonely one — at the same university, teaching as he does now, or that he has used his eff'orts in undisguised opposition to Hegel as long as he has been reading in his spirit ? Perhaps he has never been made aware that the same Society for Sci- entific Criticism, which has now, in the interest of the dialec- tic method, backed his insinuations, fourteen years ago, in Hegel's life-time and at Hegel's desire, returned a criticism presented by the Undersigned, because it contained objections Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 167 to the dialectic method (which is still a matter under discus- sion), and especially against its application to Aristotle. It hardly requires the adduction of these facts to place the equivocal character of those imputations in their proper light, or, rather, in their own shadow. It is true that their hostile tone is repeatedly laid to the account of necessary self-defence (pp. 85, 176, &c.), the whole existence and reputation of the Hegelian Philosophy being at stake. This may be ; but the question related to the matter itself, and is not answered by attacking the author. We shall, therefore, unliesitatingly resume the discussion of the matter itself, about which alone we have hitherto contended, and shall begin, where we find ourselves most at home, with its history. As we have promised to report upon the present state of the question, we would ask, in the first place, what has been done for or against Hegel's dialectic method since our first article ? In the notices which appeared of the Logical Inijestiga- tions, judgments have been pronounced upon the dialectic method from the most diverse quarters. We shall not appeal to the voices of men, who, like the prematurely deceased Kopp, the eminet student of ancient philosophy, H. Ritter, E. Reinhold, Striimpel, known through his writings on Her- bart, accepted the unfavorable criticism. One of these went so far as to say that the question was merel}^ a local one, over which science need not spend so very much time. When we consider all the antecedents of these men, we need not be surprised if certain persons do not hesitate to declare their judgment biassed, however unbiassed it may really be. When, however, men who were originally devoted to the dialectic method, do not refuse their assent to the criticism whose results were communicated in the former essay, we perhaps get some idea of the strength of the cause. First, the Deutsche JahrMicher (April, 1842, No. 83, sqq.) gives a criticism signed by Wirth. As it overlooks the most essential portions of the work, and treats it as if these were not in it, one can hardly expect that it will meet with much favor. It is there, however, stated expressly that those "' who believe in the stability of the Hegelian Logic, or even admit that it is formally and quantitatively perfectible," are in 168 Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. error. Even the objective frame in which Hegel set his logic is admitted to be by no means the only possible one for the formal to exist in, it being a wholly unliistorical prejndice of our time to think that the choice lies only between the two, &c. So Hegel's Logic, was seen suddenly to give way, where a champion had been expected. Weisse, whojnever}^ contest against Hegel, alfirms the dia- lectic method to be the abiding amid the transient, and who has himself employed it in his former writings and even in his metaphysics, while he complains that in the Logical In- vestigations the new form has not been sufficiently tested, nevertheless elsewhere asserts with an unreserved frankness for which we sincerely thank him, that Hegel's dialectic method has in fact been refuted, and proved to be a method impossible in the general, and belying its own concept in the particular. ''Among the numerous objections," he continues, "which the author raises both against the dialectic movement of the Logic and the realistic-philosophy portions of the He- gelian system, there will perhaps not be found one which could be refuted from the Hegelian premises and with strict adhe- rence to the Hegelian concept of method. With loords which, as everybody knows, that school is readj^ with, wherever thought fails, of course it might be done ; although even in the unmasking of this abuse, which is maintained with words — with the dialectic terminology — the author has displayed a merciless acumen, so that it would require no small amount of audacity to meet him again with the same artilices." (J. H. Fichte's ZeitschHft, 1842, v. 2, p. 273.) We may, perhaps, not be blamed, if, as an offset against the bitterness of one opponent, we adduce these words coming from another oppo- nent of our opinion, in order to enable our readers to find their bearings. In the contest against the dialectic method, there appeared an unexpected auxiliary in an able and vigorously written treatise : " The Psychology of the Hegelian School. By Dr. F. Exner, Professor of Philosophy in Prague," The author, aware that the Hegelian school have staked their whole for- tune upon the dialectic method, as bold gamblers do upon one throw, and that it derives all its knowing from the appli- cation of the method, pursues this method through the whole Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 169 of psychology, and does not leave it a single nook into which it can skulk to hide itself. It is of great value, in a subject as concrete as psychology is, to have made clear what kind of science, or rather what scientific monstrosities, the boasted dialectic method gives birth to. When certain writers com- plain that the negative has never received fair treatment (Gabler, p. 171), they may take comfort in this one example, as an offset against all its successful performances. (Exner, p. 55 sqq.) Will the dialectic method ever be able to raise its head again, after it has suffered discomfiture throughout a whole science ? In philosophical literature, however, no clear decision has been reached. It is true that there have appeared no works^ written in the strict dialectic method, according to the disci- pline of the old Hegelian method. But while the vibrations which proceeded from Hegel's Logic are ceasing, an echo of it is still repeated, and, in conjunction with old melodies, produces new tunes. In Wirtli's Dialectic are united dialectic and combination ; in a recently begun History of Philoso- phy, which, in its excellent mode of presentation, strives evi- dently to attain freedom of form, dialectic alternates with analogy. Dr. George, in his work entitled Principle and Method of Pliilosopliy ., has shown, with great acumen, the pe- culiar defects in the philosophies of Hegel and Schleierma- cher, and, finding them standing in opposition to each other, he has improved the one method by the other, and melted them down into a new process. Care will have to be taken that the difficulties connected with the ]3roduction of concepts — difficulties which occur both in Hegel and Schleiermacher — are not all transferred to the new process. Without disre- spect to this new attempt, we must say that we have a certain dread of mongrel systems, as when we see Hegel revised by Schleiermacher, or, in another work that lately appeared, Hegel amended by Kant, or in a third, written in a peculiar spirit, Hegel and Herbart worked up together. But in most of these attempts, if not in all, there comes out, as clearly as any literary fact can, the silent or expressed admission that Hegel's dialectic method, at least in original form, is not all that it ought to be. Dr. Marlieinelce, in his work : Introduction to Public Lee- 170 Trendelenburg on HegeVs 81 /stem. tures on the Significance of the Hegelian Philosophy in Christian Theology (1842, p. 80), writes: "The Hegelian plii- losophy is not a philosophy having a particular and delinite principle. We cannot, therefore, say in one word, or in one sentence, what Hegelian philosophy is, or wherein it consists, as the phrase is. Its principle loe must look for in the method^ whose discovery was Hegel's everlasting prerogative, and one which, hitherto, has met with but very slight opposition." It is not unusual for banking-houses, wiien they wish to remove the impression that they are on the eve of failure, to speak on 'change of the very slight losses which they have experi- enced. At all events, we would call special attention to the important words of the above statement: "The principle of the Hegelian philosoj^hy we must look for in its method." Hitherto we had been of the same opinion, and, in view of Hegel's lectures and writings, we are unable to take the mat- ter otherwise. We supposed that in particular the older school was willing to make the same admission. But, as in the Hegelian school generall}^ discord is stronger than har- mony, it seizes the older disciples in this fundamental thought, although, according to the writings of Marheineke and (rabler, these appeared to hold more closely together. Even Marheineke and Gabler disagree. Gabler teaches us that the dialectic method is not to be made the first thing or the principle. He tells us that we had been placing our batteries wrong, directing them against the dialectic method, and expecting thereby to destro}^ the Hegelian philosophy, {p. 113 sqq.) We shall pass over the clever mutatio controversioi, as common logic calls it. In the Logical Investigations not a single word was said of destroying the Hegelian philosophy — though we might derive some superior instruction about how to proceed in such an attempt from the reply of our oppo- nent (p. 101 sqq.)— but of testing the dialectic method. What result the refutation of it would have upon the existence of the system, we knew, might be left to take care of itself. All those demands which claim that we ought to have defined philosophy (p. 101 sqq.), or at least stated the difference be- tween human and divine thinking (p. 152 sqq.), are invented merely to give the impression that there is something else Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 171 in question than the clearly expressed subject of the dia- lectic method. We are satisfied if it is proved false, and leave to others the task of some day coming at Hegel's philosophi- cal system with the prescription given on p. 101 : " When people try to break down a philosophical system, the ques- tion comes to be, what belongs to that system ?" There are, perhaps, more points of attack than one. We are satisfied with ours, and merely ask, in the spirit of Marheineke, whether Hegel's system will still be considered alive when the " moving soul," the dialectic method, has gone out of it. But why, after all, cannot the dialectic method be put in the foreground and made the principle ? We hear the rea- sons (p. 114 sqq.) : "Otherwise," we are told first, "we should have the opponents of Hegel upon us, and they make it a special business to represent the dialectic method as a mere invention of subjective thinking, without any internal neces- sity or unity with objective nature." This argument, taken in connection with appended historical explanations, looks as if we might translate it : We must look for another prin- ciple, since this one no longer sustains itself. The second reason is given us in the words (p. 115): "If the method itself were the absolute principle, the definition of the absolute would have to be : The Absolute or God is the dialectic method, — which Hegel would certainly have indignantly re- jected." Any one who takes the dialectic method as having the importance which Hegel attributed to it, as that in which pure form produces the content of reason, and any one who has before his eyes such passages as § 237 of the Encyclope- dia, in which we are expressly told that nothing remains to the absolute idea, as form, but the '■''method'''' of the content, "the determined knowing of the preservation of the mo- ments," will be in great doubt about this supposed indigna- tion of Hegel's, which might have had reference merely to the unwary expression. In both of these proofs, which are so external, lies the whole force and the whole depth of the reasons which are supposed sufficient to give the dialec- tic method another position than that which it has hith- erto occupied, and to defend it and (through it) the system against attack. However, we shall leave this new difference, which is hardly inferior to any one of the old ones, to be set 172 Trend eleiiburg on HegeVs System. tied bv rlu)st' who must be more concerned about tlie last refuge of the school, at least of the old one, and about the last token of union, than an opponent can be supposed to be. It seems, however, to be a matter of solid earnest that the real signilicance of the Hegelian system consists in a certain mode of seizing the Absolute, to which Gabler has been at last led. Are we, then, to suppose that the presupposition- less dialectic method has been given up ? Yes ; and all the tremble spent in investigating it .' as throv^n away upon a mere phantom of the imagination. For we are told in the preface (p. vii.): "Among the bogles, with which some peo- ple try to scare others, is the hughear of pure tlimkmg.'''' If Germany had so short a memory that the proud doctrine of the presuppositionless pure thinking no longer rang in its ears, it would at least have Hegcd's Logic and Encyclopedia to inform it what pure thinking means in fact and in name. We read, for example, in the Encyclopedia, § 19: "Logic demands that it should have the power — in opj)osition to all intuitions, even the abstract sensuous images of geometry — to withdraw itself into pure thought, to grasp it and move in it." (Cf. §§ 14, 17, 78, &c.) We read similar statements not only in innumerable other works which owe their origin to Hegel, of the power and the feats of y^wq thinking, but even in Gabler's own text-book, " Introduction to Philosophy" — Lehrhuch der pliilosopliischen Fr op cedent ik. Erlangen, 1827 — e.g., p. 31 sq. : "In the assertion that 'the object is as it is known,' there is truth contained, if the knowing is an actual pure knowing, and such determinations of the object are treated as belong to it through this knowing, which is at the same time pure thinking." From this one may judge whether the "bugbear of pure thought" is merely a new-spun "chi- mera" which niisapi)reliension has laid on the shoulders of Hegel's i>liilosophy. For long years, and indeed until quite recently, ])ure thinking was the common watchword of the initiated, whereby Hegel's disciples recognized each other, and passed as the central life-fountain of " sjjeculation"; and now people assert in all seriousness that when one has turned against this and struck it, he has not shot through the heart of the system, but only into the air. Against this new acceptation we could not possibly have Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 173 fought, simply because it was not in existence ; and even if it had been in existence, we should have been obliged to decline discussing it, because, in the Logical Inx)estigations, we had under consideration the original form of the Hegelian system, and not any of its numerous varieties. When, how- ever, our opponent everywhere brings up this new accepta- tion (although we meet it here for the first time and only in dim outlines), as if we ought to have known it, the question comes to be whether, after all, this new acceptation is really so very much different from the old original doctrine of pure thinking which we investigated. We are told on page 15C : "Pure thinking is nothing more or less than that which, retreating back into itself, from its external distraction and manifoldness, and raising itself in \i^ pure actimty of form, already determined in and for itself, to the fountain of primal content of tliougJit, reproduces and regains thus an ideal thought"; p. 159 : " The pure knowledge whose aim is abso- lute truth will reach that aim in no other form save that of the absolute thing. ^^ " It is the method which remains iden- tical with the t?dng itself." If we take these passages, as we might take others, in their connection, we can see very dis- tinctly wherein Grablers view differs from the view of those who recognize thinking only in man, and who hold that God is self-conscious only in the thinking human being. For he defines the content of human thinking as one that has been previously thought by God ; he designates human thinking as "a second thinking which returns to its origin, in the re- thinking of that which has been previously thought through all eternity." Whether the deduction of this statement, given on pp. 123 sqq., be sufficient, we will not undertake to say. The bolder view, represented mainly by Strauss, seems to us more consistent, and is more of a piece with the whole spirit of the Hegelian philosophy. We do not desire, however, to pronounce any judgment on this, and are willing to accept Gabler's view for the time and for the present purpose. Is, then, by this long discussion, which is more a flourish of trumpets over the religious conscience of the Hegelian phi- losophy, than a treatment of the logical question, the internal difficulty of pure thinking removed ? Are the demonstrated contradictions of the presuppositionless dialectic solved? The 174 Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. cause is not at all bettered thereby. It is true that it seems to be so ; for throughout the whole of the reply, wherever the Logical Investigations, following Hegel, spoke of cognizing, by an important and careful correction, recognizing is substi- tuted, and wherever, following Ilegel, they spoke of the pro- duction of thinking, reproduction is substituted. Where, then, has Hegel, in all his works, spoken half as much of re- thinking, of re-cognizing, of re-production, as Gabler has done in this one book ? However, we need not be deceived by the words. In the reply, they are not understood to mean, that that which is received through the senses is reproduced from the unity of its concept, or that which is cognized through experience in the individual from the necessity of the whole and tlie universal. The words recognition and reproduction do not apply to the antithesis existing between the receptive perception and the thinking which manipulates the matter thereof, but only to the fact that the content of the thought has been previously thought by God, and that therefore the creation of the divine spirit is created anew in the human spi- rit. If this altered mode of expression, giving us recognition and reproduction, related to the condition of all experience, the relation of the Phenomenology to the system would at once come in question ; but Gabler will not condescend (p. 205) to an explanation upon this fundamental point, which, as our first article showed, stands so much in need of one. Is any- thing gained, then, by his correction ? We investigated human thinking, and asked, whether it has at its command any such creative dialectic as Hegel has asserted and employed. We returned an answer in the negative, because the concepts upon which the dialectic rests broke down, and because the means which it employed were mere delusions. Has our author anything to say in reply ? Does he deny the creative dialec- tic? Far from it. He shows (pp. 158-sqq., 168) that the for- mal activity of the human and of the divine thinking are the same. But since the form produces the content, as Hegel es- sentially teaches, the formal activity of the human (the pure) thinking jjroduces the content of the divine thinking, "the ab- solute thing," and is therefore, as far as the system of thoughts is concerned, as creative as the divine thinking. If this is the truth, and any one who will read Gabler's reply may Correspondence. 175 convince himself of it (pp. 156, 159 sqq.), the new view, as far as our objections are concerned, is not one whit better than the old one." We shall, therefore, hardly be expected to investigate very closely this new construction of the divine spirit (pp. 144 sqq.) which moves along with the old formulas of self-differentiation and mediation, of in-itself and for-itself. It employs the already discredited dialectic instruments, as if they were unassailed, or as if they had safely escaped from attack — which no one will assert, since our author very wise- ly declines to enter upon a discussion of them (p. 204). A person who does not wish to go {geJien) the long examination of human thinking takes a short leap into the divine think- ing, and is more at home there than in his own Ego. Is he, then, prophet or philosopher, theosophist or logician ? Per- haps, in both cases, neither ; for the first requires enthusiasm, the second strictness. But a person puts on the appearance of metaphysical profundity when he deals more easily with the divine thinking than with the first and most individual phenomenon, which one has to study the whole of physics in order to understand. CORRESPONDENCE Dr. Carl Rosenkranz, of the University of Konigsberg, writes us regarding his differences with Dr. Hoffmann. In vol. vii. of the PhilosopMsche Monatshefte (Berlin), pp. 267 -274, and, again, pp. 313-320, he reviews at length the posi- tion of the latter as taken in various periodicals and books, especially in the Journal of Speculative Philosophy. In vol. i. Jour. Sp. Phil., p. 180, we published a letter from Dr. Hoff- mann on the Philosophy of Baader. In vol. ii., p. 55, Dr. Rosenkranz replies to a remark in the former, and points out briefiy and clearly the difference between his position and that of Baader. The chief point concerned Baader's concept of the negative and of its realization in the world. Dr. Rosen- kranz unfolds his theory of antithesis and contradiction. Again, in vol. v., p. 87, we published an extract from a letter of Dr. Hoffmann's in connection with a translation of a por- 176 Correspondence. tion of his pamphlet on Theism and Pantheism. A passage ill this letter speaks of Dr. Rosenkraiiz as making "Hegel assert the personality of God and deny individual immortal- ity to man." Under the date of April 4th, 1871, we received another letter from Dr. Hoffmann, from which we quote the following extracts : " The January number of your Journal has lately arrived, and I was especiall}^ pleased with the article, ' Theism and Pantheism.' I do not consider it correct that Hegel is ex- plained in St. Louis theistically, but it gives me evidence that I stand with the philosophers of your city, in fundamental questions, on the basis of identical or at least nearly related conviction. Now whether Hegel ought to be interpreted this way or not, it is of the greatest importance that the philoso- phers of St. Louis endeavor to found and to propagate a the- istic philosophy, for only a theistic philosophy can stand; and upon the building of a superstructure upon it, depends the future of humanity, its elevation to the higher steps of culture, the civilization of the barbarian and semi-barbarian tribes, a future confederation of all states and nations, and still more than this if we extend our view beyond that which is earthly. My writings concerning Hegel's Philosophy, which I have published in the last few years, are scattered through Dr.Bergmann's PhilosophiscTie Monatsliefte^ Leonardi's Neuer Zeit, in Deutschland of AVilhelm Hoffmann in Berlin, and in the Allgemeiner Anzeiger fur das evang. Deutscliland. You would find in these writings that I have not left unnoticed the Hegelian literature of the year 1870." (He speaks further of the collection of his miscellaneous writings for jjublication, and of the published reviews of for- mer works of his that have appeared in Germany, and of the important discussion which he undertook in his Blitzstrdlil gegen Rom^ rendered now more important from the position taken by Dr. Dollinger and from the recent acts of the Impe- rial Parliament at Berlin. He speaks sadly of the death of his son, a lieutenant in the 9th infantry, killed at the battle of Worth, Aug. 6th, 1870, " pierced by three French bullets while advancing at the head of his troops." But the heart of a German father beats proudly when he adds : " He fell for a great cause. The results of these grand victories will be Correspondence. 177 tremendous for the whole of Europe, and without doubt bene- ficial. The restoration of the German Empire on a national basis makes an onward move in the history of the world. North America and United Germany will certainly approach each other. German literature will exert its influence in every direction, and in Germany science will be cultivated as never before. The union of Germany owes much to the culture of science and art ; Germany knows this and will not forget it." He says, in conclusion:) "I have just finished an essay on Hegel's Philosophy in St. Louis, which I shall send to-day to Dr. Bergmann for the PMlosopldsclie MonatsJieftey This article appeared in vol. vii., pages 58 to G3, of the journal named, and was the immediate occasion of the article of Dr. Rosenkranz in the same journal, as well as of the letter above referred to, from which we now quote the following extracts (translated for this journal by Mr. Arthur Amson) ; it is dated Konigsberg*, August 14th, 1871 : " You will permit me now to enter more closely ujdou a matter which concerns us both. In an article, ' Theism and Pantheism,' you have, in speaking of Hegel, adopted an in- terpretation of his system to which I adhere, and which is also represented on the part of the English by Dr. Stirling ('Secret of Hegel'). Hegel not only does not deny God, freedom, and immortality, but he teaches them as the high- est consequences of his speculation. He rejects atheism and pantheism in the clearest words. Freedom is the soul of his ethical view of the world. In regard to immortality, he has nowhere pronounced a credo in catechism-form ; but the man- ner in which he expresses himself in his ' Philosophy of Reli- gion,' in treating of the Egyptian religion, can surely leave no doubt on the subject. " Professor Hoffmann of Wiirzburg, a man whom for 3^ears I have truly honored, has been induced by your essay to insert in one of the numbers of Bergmann's FliilosopMsclie Monatshefte an essay which bears the title, ' The Hegelian Philosophy in St. Louis, in North America.' In this article he opposes your interpretation of Hegel, from his own stand- point, which is that of Baader's philosophy, and then turns to a special polemic against me. For many years he has writ- ten polemical articles against me in various periodicals. I Vol. vi.— 12 178 Correspondence. have made no reply to tliese attacks, because it is painful to me to quarrel publicly with an old friend. But now I cannot forbear to break my silence, and briefly to tell my honored friends in St. Louis at least, how I believe I stand in relation to the accusations of Hoffmann. •' Hott'mann is frightened at the thought that Hegel could, in fact, be a theist; he apparently considers theism, so far as a scientitic knowledge is concerned, as a kind of prerogative of Baader's system. He thinks it settled, in regard to Hegel, that he was a pantheist. To me he ascribes 5e/?^i-pantheism, since he cannot deny that I have declared expressly for theism. •' Wherein is this tendency to pantheism supposed to con- sist '. He says that I deny the freedom of God in the act of creating, and that I teach a self-realization of God in the world. He infers this from the fact that I assume the I'evela- tion of the essence of Gc^d in nature and in history. How this revelation could be conceived without the real activity of God is incomprehensible to me. But I have never thought that God is exhausted in nature and in history ; that there is no difference between Him as a manifestation of His Being, and Him as a subjec^t. . •' You have, as you once informed me, my ' System of Sci- ence.' In the last section of it, ' On Philosophy,' I have ex- pressed myself in regard to the improvements which the so- called proofs for the existence of God would have to undergo. These improvements I treated in detail in the introduction to the second edition of my 'Encyclopedia of the Theological Sciences (1845), under the heading, ' Phenomenological The- ogony (in opposition to Schelling's ' Theogonic Realism'). To this I may still refer. " But Hoffmann took no notice of this, and yet I should be- lieve, when one accuses an author of semi-pantheism, that an entire system of theology, if he has built up such a one, would surely be considered the best source of information. I have also published an exhaustive criticism of Strauss' Olauhens- lehre, and in it also have verified my conception of God, as opposed to the world. But of it, also, my friend Hoffmann takes no notice. On the other hand, he has expressed his entire agreement with a work of mine in Hilgenfeld's Jour- Correspondence. 179 nal of Scientific Theology, ' Materialism and Cxerman Theol- ogy,' wherein I expounded and reviewed the entire literature of materialistic theories, and repeatedly has he called on me, by letter, for a separate reprint. How could he concur with me if I were a semi-pantheist, or if I believed God, imme- diately as a subject, to be confounded in the processes of nature and history ? "Hoffmann now comes to a point, on which I expressed myself once before in your journal. This is Nature in God, which is said to be misapprehended by me, and to be cor- rectly taught only by Baader. That nature must lie in the essence of God, inasmuch as otherwise he could not create it, is certain. I expressed myself afterwards at length in my treatise on Hegel's ' Nature-Philosophy,' which was sent to you on its appearance. Hoffmann ignores this. I have no idea of that mysterious nature of Baader's, which is said to exist without space and time, without matter, without finity. Previous to its creation, nature is only 'potentially in God. I will not again take up the quarrel on the integrity of nature, on which conception I printed a Latin dissertation in 1834. In the first volume of my Studien (1839), there is a longer treatise, ' The Glorification of Nature,' which treats on this subject. Where, then, are the refutations of these works? " Of freedom I shall not speak, since Hoffmann admits that I acknowledge its reality. But I can only teach the freedom of man by assuming, that he is as free from God as God is. from him. "But I must still say one word in regard to immortality. He affirms that he was unable to see it clearly from my printed expressions. But he says that he heard from a mu- tual friend of ours, that I believed it. There, however, exists a quite definite document of mine on this point, which is printed at the end of ray ' Critical Explanations of the Hege- lian System' (1840). " In this I related with all openness, how I certainly had forsaken the belief in immortality for a long succession of years, but, through science itself, had come to abandon this stand-point, because the difficulties of proving non-immor- tality continually presented themselves more clearly before my mind. It is curious that Hoffmann should derive his in- formation, whether I believe in immortality, through letters, ISO Correspondence. siiu-e 1 wrote a * Psyc'liolouhlicly. •• When I had said in your periodical that the concept of death is inseparable from that of life, Hoffmann inferred from this that I had finally clearly denied immortality. I here- upon wrote to him that I should not be able to convince my- self of the immortality of cats and dogs and vermin, although I should be found to do this if I considered everything liv- ing to be immortal : but that immortality presupposes, as an essential condition, the existence of consciousness. Indi- viduality, such as the animal possesses, is not yet subjecti- vity. Ideal power, and even subjectivity, do not make up the entire concept of personality. '' Moreover, it seems to me that in science, science — i.e. de- monstration— Is the principal thing. Here we have to deal with objective proofs, while every freedom of individual fantasy is to be accorded to belief. In the problem of immortality^ the greatest difficulty will always lie in the fact that we are completely incapable of forming any adequate idea of the nature of a condition after death. It is just the same with [he concept of God, which we are forced to think, since we must think the Absolute not only as an absolute substance, but also as an absolute subject. But we are not able to im- agine the absolute spirit, and for that reason it is common in our times to deny its existence. '' It occurs to me, finall}^ that I, perhaps, am the Geraiau philosopher who has contended most against atheism and materialism, because, in 1866, I published a book on Dide- rot's Life and Works, in two volumes, the fruit of many vears' research ; and that Diderot may be considered the most intellectual representative of that stand-point. I sent the book to Hoffmann, and he expressed to me his entire satis- faction therewith ; all the more, therefore, does his present polemic surprise me. The name of Hegel does not even occur once in the book, because I thought I must solve my problem entirely within the last century. '' Pardon these lucubrations, which I thought I owed you, Correspondence. 181 since Hoffmann condemns you as a theist to the same cate- gory with myself. " To the honored members of the Philosophical Society my best respects." Dr. C. L. Michelet and Dr. E. v. Hartmann. In the present and last previous number of this Journal we have given a part of the polemic excited by the appear- ance of Dr. E. V. Hartmann's work on Hegel's Dialectic. His great work on the ' Philosophy of the Unconscious ' was re- viewed in vol. iv., No. 1. We have received the third edition of that remarkable work, which is very much enlarged — con- taining now over 800 pages. By reason of its popular style — which seems largely inherited from Schopenhauer, and per- haps ultimately traces to an English or French origin — the work has been very largely circulated and read. It is just now advertised that a translation of it will soon appear in Boston from the house of Roberts Brothers. Since the publication of the organ of the Philosophical So- ciety of Berlin — Der Gedanlte — ceased with its 7th volume in 1867, when Dr. Bergmann, one of the editors, started the Philosopliische Monatshefte, Dr. Michelet, the other editor, commenced an irregular periodical called " Der Gedanlie : Fliegende Blatter in zwanglosen Heften,'' thus nominally continuing Der OedanTce into its eighth volume. In this vol- ume he attacked Dr. Hartmann in the critique translated and published in this journal, while Dr. Hartmann and others re- ])lied in the Philosopliische Monatshefte. The third number of Der Oedanlce is chietiy taken up with an account of the celebration of the centennial anniversary of the birth of Hegel. On this occasion a monument was erected to his memory, surmounted with a very excellent bust of the philosopher. The oration of Dr. Michelet, delivered at the ceremony of un- covering the monument, will be given to our readers in due time. A letter received from Dr. Michelet when the contri- butions to the monument were in progress, contains the fol- lowing interesting passage : "Even if you do not at all represent yourself as an adhe- rent of Hegel, yet I see from the tone of your periodical what large store you set by Hegel, and how much he seems wor- 18'2 Correspondence. thy tho homage of both hemispheres. I woiihi go into pairieuhirs only in lehition to tlie famous question of the Beginning of Phih)sopliy [see Jour. Sp. Phil., vol. i.. No. 4]. The author of the article does not agree with Paul Janet's objections against Hegel. That Hegel's reasoning in regard to the Beginning comes to a false conclusion, as M. Janet urges, ' since the beginning of knowledge and the beginning of being are two ditt'erent things,' is a statement that I should more sharply refute thus : When we make a beginning in philosophy, since it must be something immediate, we can- not yet nuike the distinction between being and cognition. They are, perhaps, both the same, as, indeed, the Irish bishop, Berkeley, has asserted expressly. The answer of Ja- net's is particular!}^ infelicitous: 'The thinking being knows itself before it knows the being which it thinks.' For self- thinking is, as Fichte has also said, to posit oneself imme- diately as being. And even Descartes said : ' Cogito, ergo sum.'' The antithesis between cognition and existence is a much later one, and one lying far behind the beginning, at which we only arrive by means of the dialectic. I therefore say : Philosoph3\ since it is an absolute beginning, begins with the beginning ; as the French say, ' II faut com,mencer par le commencement.'' Here we do not yet at all know whether we or the thing begins, or whether we as well as the thing- begins, because it is only subsequently that, out of this im- mediate unity, we shall derive the distinction between the thinking subject and the thought object. " But the conception of the beginning itself contains noth- ing else than being, pure being. For what, in conception, is about to b<-gin {id quod inchoatum est), is not as yet any- thing determined or definite, and we know as yet nothing determinate of it, but simply know that it is." The third number, above mentioned as containing the ora- tions delivered at the centennial celebi-ation, contains also a fine photograph of the monument as it now stands. />/•. ./. //. Stirling, Dr. Vera, and Philosophy in Europe. From Dr. Vera we learn that he expects to get out a new edition of his French translation of Hegel's Logic, "greatly enlarged, in fact nearly doubled in size. After the Logic, it ■ Correspondence. 183 will be the turn of the Philosophy of Religion." The latter work has been announced as " in press " for several years, and has been anxiousl}^ looked for. It seems that the war *set things back, and that Dr. Vera now intends to postpone the translation of the Philosophy of Religion for a year or two. He is still Professor at the University of Naples. Dr. Hutchinson Stirling, author of the "Secret of Hegel,'' is publishing a series of Lecures on the Philosophy of Law in the Journal of Jurisprudence at Edinburgh. They were de- livered to the members of the Juridical Society in November and December, 1871. The first of these is a very entertain- ing "Introduction to Philosophy in general," and the others unfold step by step, in a style such as only Dr. Stirling can write, the ideas of Rights in general, of Property, of Criminal jurisprudence. They furnish an exceedingly valuable con- tribution to Philosophical literature, and should be largely read in America now that so much thought is directed to- wards the foundation-ideas of government. Unless otherwise republished in this country, we propose to reprint these lec- tures in this journal, commencing with the October number. We are glad to learn also that there is a prospect of a publi- cation of Dr. Stirling's critique of Buckle, in the North Ameri- can Review. His strictures on Professor Huxlej'-'s Protoplasm, which have been republished in New Haven by Messrs. Chat- field & Co., are soon to appear in a second edition much en- larged. We hope to publish also a review of Berkeley, from the same pen, eventually. Writing in the fall of 1871, Dr. Stirling speaks of the death •of Dr. Ueberweg, and pronounces him the most earnest and sincere thinker of his time. His work on the History of Phi- losox)hy, translated for us by Professor Morris of Michigan University, we have already noticed. We are expecting soon the second volume, and shall again have an opportunity to speak of it. It seems that the place made vacant in the Uni versity of Konigsberg by the death of Dr. Ueberweg, has just been filled by the appointment of Dr. A. J. Bergmann t)f Ber- lin, well known as the editor of the PMlosopMsclie Monats- hefte. That periodical passes under the editorial charge of Dr. E. Bratuscheck, docent in the University of Berlin, whose articles in the Phil. Monatshefte have attracted much atten- 184 Di\ference between the Dialectic d- Sf/nthetic Method. tioii. In mir next iiuniber we hope to give an account of the contents of the articles that have appeared in the last three- volumes of that lounial. THR DIFFKRENCK BETWERN THE DIArjRCTIC M RTIIOD- OF HEGEL AND THE SYNTHETIC METHOD OF KANT AND KICHTR. \\y A, ]•-. Kkoi.gek. There are two pfirties holding opposite judgments regard- ing the relation of Hegel's dialectic method to the method of Kant and Fichte's system of transcendentalism. It seems. that the question should be considered settled by Hegel's own statement in his History of Philosophy, where he substan- tially avers that the method of Fichte's Science of Knowledge is the same as his own, just as he there modestly concedes to Schelling the contents of his system ; he claiming for himself only the merit of being the lirst who fused the true absolute system with the true absolute method. But this declaration of Hegel's has not been considered satisfactory ; and all re- cent historians of Philosophy are more or less at loggerheads- with each other on this point. To settle the question it will, therefore, be necessary to examine the two methods ; that is,. to see how Fichte, following Kant, proceeds in his philoso- phizing, and how Hegel proceeds in his. For this purpose it is not necessary to consider beforehand whether or not philosophy can be true only in so far as its method is true, philosophy being intact nothing but the absolute method; though it may not be out of place to state historically that both Fichte and Hegel agree upon this j)oint, both answer- ing in the affirmative. Fichte, then, in all his various representations of the Sci- ence of Knowledge, and indeed in all his scientific writings, proceeds as follows : He states, and calls upon his readers to verify it in con- templation, that in every act of thinking there are two ingre- dients, whereof neither one can be deduced from the other,, but both of which claim equal validity ; that hence every act Difference hetween the Dialectic & Synthetic Method. 185 of thinking is a synthetical act embracing two opposites, and that it is the sole province of philosophy to discover and ex- plain how this synthesis is possible ; that is, how it happens that we must in every act of our mind hold two opposites, in part related and in part opposed to each other. The problem of philosophy, therefore, is altogether, as Kant very correctly had stated before, to discover the abso- lute ground of all synthetical judgments. Now this absolute tinal ground Fichte — as before him Kant — states to be this : the Ego, or an absolutely active self-conscious activity, could not be an Ego, could not be self- conscious of itself as such absolute activity, if there did not appear in every act of its self-consciousness also a non-Ego ; the reason being this : an absolute activity could never be- come conscious of itself if it were not checked in its activity ,^ and thus, as it were, thrown back into itself with what would now be a consciousness of both itself and a check. Nowr having once named itself as absoliite activity by the name Ego, it could certainly not look upon the check of that activ- ity as also Ego, but would rather have to look upon and name it its opposite, non-Ego. Coming thus to consciousness, it would, therefore, lind as its primitive nature and act, as indeed that which constituted its nature and act, a synthesis of non-Ego and Ego ; and this primitive and original synthesis could not otherwise than manifest itself in every other one of its acts. What must be noticed here is the statement, that neither can the Ego be explained from the non-Ego, nor the non-Ego from the Ego ; that neither is analytically contained in the other as part of it, but that both are in fact complete and utter opposites ; that is, must be so conceived, and cannot be conceived otherwise. Their union, the union of the thesis of a pure Ego and the antithesis of a checking non-Ego, results in the synthesis of a self-conscious Ego ; that is, of a rational absolute mind in a material limited body, or, more accurately expressed, in a system of such rational individuals, each one of which, as such a synthetic unity, is that very trinity which theologians by a fallacy of reasoning apply to the conception of the totality of the Egohood and call it the triune God. Hegel's proceeding diifers from the above synthetic in this, ISO Difference between the Dialectic d- Syntlietic Ateiliocl. that lie does not concede, or at least does not seem to con- cede, this partly absolute oppositedness of the two elements of the synthesis ; and looks only to their relatedness. Thus he does not say, that immediately togetlier with the concep- tion of Being another entirely opposite, though also related, conception of non-Being is joined when we think Becoming; but he says, or seems to say; that the conception of Being involves as one of its parts the conceptif)n of non-Being; that the latter conception can, therefore, be analytically gathered from the tirst ; though, if he does so mean, it is not possible to see how Being could change into Becoming, since the ele- ment of non-Being would not alter the character of Being at all, and Being, after non-Being had been pointed out as one of its characteristics, would still remain simply Being and nothing else. If Hegel does not so mean, he has chosen a most unfortunate way of expressing himself; but his own averment in his History of Philosophy would, as we have said, seem to suggest that he did not so mean. If he did so mean, however, then there is a difference and a most vital one between Fichte's synthetic and Hegel's dialectic method, a difference which will now be apparent to every one. It may be mentioned in passing, as perhaps of interest to those who have read Trendelenburg's criticism of Hegel's me- thod in this Jourjial, that Trendelenburg's objection to the ■dialectic method — that it surreptitiously takes and applies the contemplation of local motion from empirical consciousness — is simply absurd. Local motion occurs between two bodies in space, and the conception of local motion can be applied, of course, to nothing else. Trendelenburg's criticism, there- fore, implies that he considers the conceptions of Being and non-Being — which are alluded to by Hegel as moving in a dialectic way — as things in space; and one is tempted to ask him, whether he considers them of globular oj' triangular form, &c. The absurdity is clear. It is not from local motion that the general conception of motion issues ; indeed, the very reverse is the case, the activity of thinking, being the primitive source of the conception of movement. And even in common language we thus speak of thoughts as moving, &c. Hegel is thus perfectly justified, and introduces no sur- reptitiously obtained conception wiien he speaks of a dialectic Book Notices. 187 movement as the equivalent for the sequence of certain con- ceptions in thinking. It is a strange evidence of the general superlicialit}^ of " thinkers " that such things should require notice ; stranger still that this evident absurdity should have been considered by Trendelenburg a wonderful discovery, overthrowing the gigantic fabric of Hegel's Logic ! But these continual misapprehensions and disputes make it all the more clear, how necessary for the exactness of a pure science is a system of signs to replace words, and leave it a matter of deep regret that Leibnitz, who had such a system projected, did not carry out his design, he being of all the great minds of science beyond doubt most peculiarl}^ gifted to have given it best shape. The real objection, as already suggested, to the word "movement" in that famous paragraph of the Logic is this, that Hegel speaks as if the conceptions of Being and non-Being moved. Now, mere conceptions as they are, they of course cannot, in proper use of language, be said to move ; but the thinking of them is, in all language, quite properly called a moving from one to the other. The question, how- ever, Avhether Hegel meant this or not, does not involve any unauthorized making use of the conception of local motion, but simply the point, above discussed, whether Hegel meant his dialectic method to be the same as Fichte's synthetical method or not. BOOK NOTICES. The Dialogues of Plato, traii.slated into English, with Analyse.^ and Introduc- tions, by B. Jowett, M.A.. Regius Protessor of Greek in the University of Oxford. 4 vols. New York: Charles Scribuer t^- Co. 1871. This reprint, which costs the student just one half the price of the ori- ginal English edition, should be in every library, public or private. More- over, every one should read it; many people own a copy of Plato, but how few read and understand hi in ! Professor Jowett has spared no pains to make a free translation — one that seems vernacular English. It has im- mense advantages in this respect over any former translation. We com- mend the work to all interested in Philosophy. Let them read Emerson's essay on Plato in the "Representative Men," then Hegel's lecture on Plato in Vol, IV. of this Journal, and then read Jowett's translation, and study his Introductions. Die Rechisstellung des Weiben iiinei-halb der Ehe. Ein Vortrag von Max Eber- hardt. Chicago: Meniinger & Shick. 1871. 188 Bool- Xotices. F/ifih-ie/i Vchcnccg. von A. Lunqr. [Eine Gediichtnissrede.] Berlin: Ernst Sie^:- fried, Mittlor & riolin. 1871'. [Sent us by Dr. Collyns Simon.] The Jounml of P.^vchological Medicine : A (^)ii;irt('rly Review of Diseases of the Nervous Svsteln, Medical .Turisprudenee. and Anthropology. p]dited by Wni. A. Hammond. M.D. Vol. 5, No. 4. October, 1871. New York: 1). Api)le- ton «!c Co. This number contains amon«,^ other articles an elaborate one entitled, "Medi- co-Letfal Notes on the Case of Edward H. liulolf; with Observations upon, and Measurements of. his Cranium. Brain, ite.; by Geo. Burr. M.D." In another, entitled " A Letter to the Editor on some Recent Contributions to Mental Sci- ence, Medical Jurisprudence, and Anthropology; by Geo. E. Day. F.R.S.," is given a vi ry interesting account of Huxley's recent lecture on Bishop Berkeley. Das VeHialfniss von Schule nnd Staat. Hamburg, 1871. [Sent us by Dr. A. G. Todtenhaupt.] Ueber die Qrundunq eine^s Wissensc/iaff I ic/ioi Volks-le/irer-Se.ininars ntutbhiirigig lion Kirche tmd Staat. Ein Gegenvorschlag gegen die beabsichtigte Grundunis; einer Hamburgischen Akademie. von A. G. Todtenhaupt. Schtde iind Staat. Aus dem Franzilsisclicn des Professor Tiberghien in Briiesel; iiebersctzt, von J. II. Hamburg: NVilhelui Jowien. 1S71. [Sent also by Dr. A. G. T. ZHtschriff fiir PJdloHophie nnd Pldl. Kritik. LIX Bandes. erstes und zweites dtschria fiir P/iilosop/iie und P/iil. Kritik. Hefte. ilalle: C. E. M. i:*fefler. 1871. Contents of No. 1 : I. Philosophizing — Extract from a Speech by Prelate G. Mehrinr/. II. Contributions to the History and Criticism of Philosophy, noticed by Dr. Arthur Ricliter. HI. Logic, or Science of Knowing with respect to the relation between Philosophy and Theology, its Outlines presented by Rudolph Seydel. D.Phil.. &c.; reviewed by Prof. Dr. v. Reichlin-Meldegg. IV. Logic and Metaphysics, by Prof. Dr. Leonliard Rabus: Part 1st— Theory of Knowledge, Kistorj- of Logic, System of Logic, togetlier with a Clironological Survey of the Literature of Logic, and an Aipiiabetical Index to its Contents; reoiewed by Dr. Reichlin-Meldegg. V. Tlie Complete Logic: A Book for Schools and Students, compiled from tlie stand-point of Natural Science, and intended for a criticism of previous books on Logic. &c.; by Prof. Dr. J.Hoi)pe; reviewed by Dr. Reich- lin-Meldegg. VI. Psychologie Naturelle: A Study upon the Treatment of Aliens and Criminals; by Dr. Prosper Despine; reviewed by F. A. v. Hartsen. VII. Speculative Anthropology looked at from a Christian-Pliilosophical Stand- point; by Dr. Carl AVerner; reviewed by Prof. Dr. Sengler. VIH. The Doc- trine of Berkeley : A short tinal reply to T. Collyns Simon. LL.D.; by Prof. Ueberweg. IX. Correction of Certain Statements in Ulrici's Defence; by Dr. R. Hoppe. X. Correction of tlie Foregoing ••Corrections"; by Dr. Ulrici. Beiti-age zur Kenntniss des Amerikanischen Schulwesens [Review of the St. Louis School Report continued through five numbers of the GemeinnUtzige Wochen- schrift. published at Wurzburg. Germany], by Prof. L. Grasberger. Bulletin of the Wisconsin Academy of Sciences. Arts, and Letters^ Nos. 4 «fc 5 (Feb. and July, 1871); published by the Academy, at Madison, Wis. Contents: I. List of Officers of the Academy. II. Executive Proceedmgs of the Fourth Meeting. III. Scientific Communications presented at the Fourth Meeting. IV. Executive Proceedings at the Fifth Meeting. V. Scientific Com- munications presented at the Fifth Meeting. [Sent us by Dr. J. W. Hoyt, Presi- dent of the Academy.] Book Notices. 189 Ja/ires Bericht ilber tlie Doroiheenstaedtisehe Real-Schule. 1870 and 1871. The Report for 1870 contains, besides the school advertisement, a learned arti- cle by Dr. F. Frederichs, principal of the school, on Berkeley's Idealism. This is followed in the Eeport for 1871 by a discussion of the Phenomenal Idealism of Berkeley and of Kant, a contribution also by Dr. Frederichs. These articles belong to the wide-spread movement occasioned by the translation of Berkeley's chief work by Dr. Ueberweg and the polemical articles of Dr. Collyns Simon, of which we have spoken in vol. v.. p. 283. of this Journal. La Filosofia della Scuole Italiane. Anno ii., vol. iii., disp. 1, 2 & 3; vol. iv., disp. 1&2. Firenze : M. Cellini. 1871. Contents No. 1 — I. Acts of the Literary and Philosophical Society: id) The Future of Metaphysical Speculation ; [b) Letter on the same topic. II. The Inca- pacity of the Human Will, and other Hypotheses of the Materialists (T. Collyns Simon, LL.D.), being a Letter to Dr. Herzen, author of Physiological Analysis of the Free Hutnrui Will. HI. Ethics of Positive Philosophy : Speculations on the Intention, the Moral Good, and the Useful (Prof. G. Biirzellotti). IV. Philo- sophical and Literary Notice on Bergmann's First Principles of a Theory of Con- sciousness (Prof. Luigi Ferri). Contents No. 2 — I. Acts of the Litei'ary and Philosophical Society: (a) Act of approval of three MSS.; {h) Influence of Philosophy on the German National Spirit (Dr. Giuseppe Desours, of Tournay). II. Philosophical Conversations (Prof. F. Bonatelli). III. Incapacity of the Human Will, and other Hypotheses of the Materialists (T. Collyns Simon, LL.D.) IV. Analysis and Criticism of New Works; Literary and Philosophical Notices (Prof. Luigi Ferri). Contents No. 3 — I. Acts of the Literary and Philosophical Society : (a) Philo- sophical themes; {b) Literary themes; (c) The Philosophy of Religion — (1) The Intiuite its own Limit, (2) The Conception of Life applied to God. (3) Pecou- sideration of the Conception of the Infinite, (4) The Real Relation of the Creator to the Created, (5) General Treatment of the Divine Attributes, (6) Conclusion. II. Incapacity of the Human AV^ill, and other Hypotheses of the Materialists (T. Collyns Simon. LL.D.) III. The Circle of Science (Profs. Bonatelli and Mamia- ni). IV. Analysis and Critical Notices of New Works; Literary and Philoso- phical Notices. V. Index to vol. iii. Vol. IV., No. 1 — Contents : I. Summary of Acts of the Society for the Promo- tion of Philosophy and Letters. II. Philosophical Conversations. III. Letter of T. Collyns Simon to Dr. Herzen on the ''Limitations of the Human Will, and other Hypotheses of Materialists." IV. Theory of Relation: (a) Reid's Doctrine and its Insufficiency ; (6) Theories of contemporaneous English Psychologists; (c) The Facts of Perception newly Examined : (rl) Other Distinctions solving the Ditficulty and confirming the New Doctrine; (e) Objections Answered; {{, Facts of Reception. V. Ethics of Positive Philosophy (continued): VI. Analy- sis of New Works. VII. Philosophical and Literary Notices. No. 2 — Contents: I. Summary of Acts of Philosophical Society. II. Human Cognition. III. Notes on the Article on Relation and Perception. IV. Influence of Philosophy on the German National Spirit. V. Theory of the Objectivity of the Idea, by Count Terenzio Mamiani. VI. Analysis and ^'riticism of Nev Works. WORKS OF C. A. WERTHEH, DR. PHIL. 1. Die Krafte der Unorganische Natur in ihrer Einheit und Enttrickelung. Des- sau, 1852. 2. Was ist Lebenskraft? Versuch einer Antwort auf diese Frage. Dessau. ]S54. 190 Book Notices. S. Lebem-Setlen-und Geisteskraft. oder die Kriiffe der Organischeii Natui- in ihrei' Einheii uud Enficickelung. Erster Theil : Die Pflaiizc unci da? Thier. Halle, 1S60. 4. Zicfiier Theil: Der Meiisch als Geistt'cres Iiidividmim nacli seiner Biklniig unci Eiitwiekoliin^ auf der (irmidlacre der Xatiir. Nordliausen. ISdT. The above-named works constitute a coniplet<^ sketch of Philosophy in out- line. Conimencinjr with the Inorganic, our author — after an iitroduction in which he jusiilie.*; liis method of investiijatioii and discusses the various stand- points and categories used in a Pliilosoi)hy of Xature — considers, /7>.s^, the forces which constitute matter or manifest it, .such as magnetism, electricity, chemical atllnity. I'fcc. ; second, tiie forces which 7nove matter. The former forces are the static ones that give form and .shape to matter ; the latter forces relate to mo- tion as wt 11 in molecules as in masses. Ascending from the Inorganic. Dr. Werther grapples with the problem: What is organism or vital foreeV Sharply discriminating this from the mechanical and physical realms of force, he comes to the wider and deeper idea that subordinates those spheres and exhibits itself as linal cause. The "Absolute force" he defines as self-determination. To this not merely the Inorganic and the Organic realms are necessary, but the realm of Mind. lie traces step by stej) the organic forces through the life of the Plant and through that of the Animal until its elevation to consciousness. The struggle for self- revelation, checked in the lower forms, at length achieves its purpose. A sketch of Man as a ''pneumatic individual" — i.e. as a being of instinct, a mere soul — is followed by a portrayal of his higher life in the activities of think- ing and willing. Thought and will are the polar manifestation of the p.sychical force, or, as he calls it, the ■•pneumatic" force. "As f/wught. the conscious activity represents the objectivated multiplicity in the unity of the subject ; as will, it represents the unity of the subject in a determinateness of objectivated multiplicity." Thus they are two antithetic activities, inseparably connected and in continual reciprocal action. There are three stages of progress in the perfection of the soul-power. I. The thinking activity reaches only the phase of forming judgments, of joining predicates to subjects — the dei-criptive stage — while the corresponding development of the will manifests itself only in moving to realize purposes, i.e. simple ends and aims. It is the interaction of this stage of the will with that of the thinking that elevates it to the next higher, that of the refecting fhinking and the irilling in accordance v;ith principles . IT. Here sub- jectivity begins to assert an equal right with objectivity. Thinking by its activ- ity develops abstractions, and posits them as the truth of the objective. To will to realize a purpose is a free act: no inorganic or merely organic being can do this: only a being possessed of a soul can form purposes. But it is far in advance of that stage to be able to will one's action in conformity to principles. Through the mediation of this form of will with the thinking that reflects, the psychical power rises to the third and highest stage of development : HI. The thinking activity of Eeason and the activity of the Will for the realization of Ideals, are the highest antithesis of the soul-power. In the activity of Reason the antithesis of subject and object is reconciled, and objectivity comes to be a moment of sub- jectivity which proves itself the Absolute form. The thinking Reason stands in unity with Faith, and seizes the revelation of the Infinite Unity in the Finite by means of thought-representations, while Faith seizes the same through the liv- ing sacrifice of the individual to this Revelation. All thinking and knowing is brought to a unity; and thus .S'cience is formed. The Will becomes ethical in BooTc Notices, 191 adopting as its principle tlie absolute ideal, and thus also becomes free. This ideal is self-determination. The threefold combination of individuals gives rise to the manifestation of the Family, the State, the Christian Religion. The pro- cess of completely realizing this unfolds successively the course of human his- tory. Arrived at this point, our author pauses and takes a rapid survey of the phases that enter now into this highest unity. It will be observed that the peculiarity of Dr. Werther's exposition consists in uniting the theoi-etical and practical sides of Mind and treating their development as the result of reciprocal action. Other branches of the Hegelian school treat first the Theoretical and then the Practical. A certain resemblance to the popu- lar methods in which subjects of natural science are treated, is also observable^ and makes a vivid impression on the reader. La Morale, ndla FUosofia Positica : studio critico di Giacomo Darzellotti, Pro- fessore diFilosotia hel R. Liceo Dante di Firenze. Florence: 1871. We have already spoken in this journal (vol. v., p. 94) of the great revival of Philosophy in Italy, and of the two centres of its activity, Florence and Naples. Among the most notable philosophical laborers in Florence is Professor Barzel- lotti, author of the critique above named . In his handling of the subject, one is very strongly reminded of Cousin's method. He investigates the ideas of experience and lav; as they have been presented in the Posilivist school ; then unfolds the two extremes of opinion on the subject of free will, and how the positivists essay a middle ground. Alexander Bain's analysis of the physical and psychological conditions accompanying volition is stated and criticised. John Stuart Mill's theory of volition passes next under review. The concepts of cause and force are investigated: " i^sychology becomes in the English school a natural history of the mind." In Part Second the author investigates the subject of final causes and motives, sketching the history of discussion on this subject, and drawing distinctions be- tween the intuitive and utHistic schools. Absolute obligation is contrasted with materialistic theories. The inductive system of morality, taught by the positiv- ists and illustrated in the writings of Mr. Lecky, is well detined as regards its outcome. Theories of happiness, utilitarianism, })iet.hods of investigation, are dis- cussed. The prevailing method in Germany after Kant is Reduction ; in Eng- land after Bacon, is Analysis. The method of Reduction does not seek the rela- tion of psychical activity to its organs— of Psychology to Physiology— but the relation of the ■various forms of psychical activity to each other and to a coriunon foundation. Feeling. Association is the fundamental psychological law in the English school. In Part Third our author takes leave of the English — having discussed suffi- ciently the old writers, Hobbes, Cudworth, Clarke, Locke, Butler, Ilutcheson, Hume, Price, Paley, Brown, and Bentham, as well as the contemporary moral- ists, Mill, Bain, Spencer, and others. He turns now to the theory of Comte himself and the French positivists. Their system of "social physics" makes im- possible any science of Character. The abstract universal of society annuls each individual as eflectively as the abstract force of the correlatlonists destroys the identity of particular forces. With some important remarks as to the future direction of investigation, the book closes. Introduzione alia FUosofia della Storia: Lezioni di A. Vera, raccolte e publicate con I'approvazione deH'autore da Raffaele Mariano. Florence: 1869. In this work the Philosophy of History is worked up with admirable intro- 192 Book Notices. Auctions caieulattd to initiate thcMoailcr into all the o^reat philosopliical ques- tions. It deserves to be translated into Eniesls. all the germs which have subsequently taken form. It carried everywhere a latent sensibility for the creative law out i»f which it came. It swept along with a dim drift of the Personality that lirst conceived and then put it on the way to self-expression. It mounted thus by the ascending scale of animals, and its improvements in structure were prepara- tions to reach and repeat Personality, to report the original consciousness of the Creator that He was independent of structure. At length it became detached from the walls of the womb of creation, held only for nourishment by the cord of structure tilKit could have a birth into individualism. Then the interplay of mind and organism began, with an in- herited advantage in favor of Vitality. Now Vitality, thus developed and crystallized into personality, tends constantly back towards its origin. The centrifugal movement through all the animals is rectitied by the centripetal movement in man. The whole series of effects musters in him to recur to an effecting Cause." Prof. Ha^ckel of Jena, in his Biological Studies,^' makes the following statement: "Protoplasm, or germinal matter, also called cell-substance or primitive slime, is the single material basis to which, without exception and absolutely, all so-called ' vital phenomena ' are radically bound. If the latter are re- garded as the result of a peculiar vital force independent of the protoplasm, then necessarily also must the physical and chemical properties of every inorganic natural body be re- garded as the result of a peculiar force not bound up with its substance." Very well, why not ? Even the vague motions, like the incoherent simmer of a crowd of people on a great square, which take place in the molecules of the densest substance, are dumb gropings of some Force, arrested for the present in the substance, and not to be detected transgressing its lim- its. But something is there which shares and testifies to a universal tendency towards evolution into other substances and into organic forms. Physical and chemical forces attest the presence of Vitality, as well as the mental functions which use the structural results of those forces. Something * See Toledo Index, Apnl 29, 187J. Theories of Mental Oenesis. 213 independent of: the material basis must have endowed it with its movements and qualities. It certainly could not have originated itself or its forces. Something anterior to the ma- terial basis must include and transmit a tendency of Vitality towards mental and moral functions, which are at once inde- pendent of the basis and yet closely allied to it. Let us observe now if any contribution may be made to idealism from another quarter. The empirical method has not busied itself much with the phenomena of musical sensi- bility, though, to be consistent after including the imagina- tion in its genesis of mind from external sensations, it ought to construct the sense of Harmony and the inventive genius of the composer in the same way, since imagination plays so large a part therein. Some physical facts which at first threaten to support a pure empiric origin for mental func- tions, turn out upon cross-questioning to belong to the other side of the case, and to contribute, toward some more ideal statement. The German Helmholtz, who has made some profound studies of the laws of Harmony, in his examination of the structure of the human ear, found that the cochlea, or snail- formed cavity, contained a liuid, across which three membranes were thrown — an upper, middle, and under. In the middle compartment he discovered innumerable microscopic disks, lying next each other like the keys of a piano : one end of each of them is attached to the vessels of the auditory nerve, the other end to the outstretched membranes. These disks are the sensitive points which receive the vibrations of musi- cal instruments, and transmit them to the brain in the form of notes and tones. A single string will give off different vibrations from its upper and its middle section. Does the ear solve the sound of a complex vibration made by these waves of different length, or does it receive the sound as a whole ? Answering this, Helmholtz says that the physical ear funds tlie wave-forms into a sum of simple waves, which is the result of their concurrence ; since any wave-form you please can be constructed out of a combination of simple waves of different lengths. And as in the instruments, so in the ear, the ground tone wakes the corresponding upper tone. When vibrations play upon the disks in the ear, it is as if 214 Theories of Mental Genesis. the}' pla^'ed upon banks of keys; and the iirst physical im- pressions are produced, sorted, combined, and then transmit- ted as so much seasoned material to be used in manufacturing music. Then occurs the wonderful moment when Something beyond these microscopic feelers digests the prey they catch into human moods and emotions. What leaps the genius takes, through and across what an iinbridged abyss, upon these stepping-stones of disks, to gather the waifs and strays that tioat upon the manifold sea of Harmony ! There is no such startling proof that Nature has at length developed a ti'anscending Person in mankind ; perhaps whole races died for it, dissonances and partial chords, or constructed upon vicious intervals, before Harmony could respond to its own laws. At length an essential differentiation seems to have taken place, an abstraction which compels sensations to subserve its subtlest emotions. For at one end of this process is nothing but the disks vibrating in their fluid : at the other end is something rarely and radically different — the gamut of the human heart, the sj^mphony upreared by intellect and feeling, the song exhaling into the mist that sheathes the eye, the lyric whose silvery trumpets summon bravery and nobleness from every drop of blood. Now, atmospheric vibrations and the structure of the ear enclosing the microscopic disks are the objects which provide empirical sensations. The temperament, culture and inher- ited susceptibility of the musical composer's brain collect and organize these sensations into the modes of harmony, and reject all dissonance. But when, and by which of the two parties in this transaction, was the earliest step taken toward such a complicated result i There was a time when there was nothing but an atmosphere capable of vibrating, and nothing but an ear capable of receiving the accidental throng of natu- ral noises. There was a time when the first fibre of a plant, the first tense string of some creeping vine, twanged to some chance touch : when the wood of the forest first revealed its resonant capacity, when the dried reeds first sighed and whis- tled in the wind. This was all the appeal which Nature had to make. Did it originate the sequence of melodies and con- struct the theory of harmony ? What is a dissonance ? Is it merely a physical repugnance of the disks for interfering and Theories of Mental Genesis. 215 contrarious vibrations ? Whence, then, the repugnance of the disks ? There are tribes of men whose ears have not been furnished with it. There are civilized Indo-Germanic peo- ple who cannot tell a chord from a discord. It is not credible that the crude objectivity of natural vibrations gradually selected out of Nature a harmonious ear. Nature has no harmony which could effect such a selection ; she has never sorted and combined and weeded out her noises. She is uni- sonous, monotonous, or full of jar and clash; she has no art to reconcile the voices of the sea, the air, the birds of the for- est : each creature has its note and its key, and the air itself is a Babel of cross-purposes. The empirical sensations pro- duced by modern music are drawn from things which vibrate by a law that the things do not possess, and never could have suggested. Harmony has been imposed from within upon their isolated qualities ; and an orchestra, so far from being an induction, is an intuition. The Composer listens to its combinations before they are played. His subjectivity has imparted to every instrument its peculiar quality by gradual selection among the woods, reeds and metals of Nature, and by discovery of the isolated shapes which correspond best to atmospheric conditions. His inductive experiments have been presided over by a sense which no induction could have fur- nished. What, for instance, is the temperament of a piano but a metaphysical compromise between the imperfections of the material and the law of intervals ? Harmony, in short, is a refutation which the materialist himself might welcome ; but it kills his theory as effectually as the poison poured into the auditory tube, which made a ghost of Hamlet's father. It is much easier to tolerate the doctrine that a slice of meat, well-assimilated, becomes the poet's happy thought, than to understand how wafts of common air could be transformed into the mighty uplifting of the soul when the orb of music passes over our flat life, and draws emotion into every barren €reek, and dashes its tonic against the heart. Physics must allow an essential difference between a vibration and a well- cooked mutton chop ; and it is in favor of the stimulating and edifying quality of the chop. Music has been called the image of motion. But when the ear is struck, something else than a wave is propagated. It would be more just to say that Music is imagination set in motion. 216 Anti-Materialism. The sea-tide writes its diary accurately enough in the sand- ripples. But air did not imprint these footsteps so massive and deep that our own are lost as wq try to follow ; yet there is no dismay, for in the bosom of each trace lies home's direc- tion,— by which we know that a Beethoven had just passed. I claim, then, against a strictly logical empirical method, three classes of facts. First, the authentic facts of the moral sense whenever it appears as the transcender of the ripest average utility. Second, the facts of the Imagination as the anticipator of mental methods by pervading every thing, with personality, by imputing Life to Object, or by occasional direct suggestion. Third, the facts of the harmonic sense as the reconciler of discrete and apparently sundered objects, as the prophet and artist of Number and mathematical ratio, as the unifier of all the contents of the soul into the acclaim which rises when the law of Unity fills the scene. Upon these facts I chiefly sustain myself against the the- ory, consistently explained, which derives all possible men- tal functions from the impacts of Objectivity. ANTI-MATERIALISM.* By G. S. Hall, To a concise though popular restatement of the younger Fichte's, Fontlage's, and Leopold Schmidt's construction of the ego as person, modified as he believes it to have been by Lazarus and Lotze, the author joins a vigorous and original polemic against " materialism in natural science and theol- ogy" which he calls an "absurd and therefore impossible form of subjective idealism." This he does in the interest of speculative jjhilosophy, which he would rescue from present discredit and neglect, and to which he would restore an ulti- mate character as the mediating unity of theology and natu- ral science. The barren abstractions of the absolute 2)hilosophy canied thought into so rare an atmosphere that its utmost effort was * Five Lectures on Philosophical Subjects, by Ludvvig Weis. Berlin, 1871. Anti- Materialism. 217 required to sustain itself ; progress was impossible ; and its prime function of diverting and impelling action was virtu- ally abdicated. Thougbt must strike root as well as climb. Antffius-like, it has now reverted to earth. Its own law of gravity has brought it down to the fact and thing of sense. This is, however, its most dangerous extreme ; for as thought approximates sensation it acquires an inertia which is hard to be overcome. The objects of sense are phenomenal and unstable to thought. Outer and immediate distinctions are superficial, and must be transcended. "Natural science knows its objects only in some of their external relations." Causal and inductive reasoning, as too often applied, mere- ly enlarges the boundaries of the fact, without revealing its true nature. The present tendency of physical science is, by resolving the object of sense into properties, laws, or forces, to press on toward the real nature of the thing in itself. In doing the former, it acquires a subjective character, indeed becomes philosophy in the disguise of a new nomenclature, seeks like it the central principle of all being and devel- opment. So, too, in religion thought must neither lose itself in ecsta- sies of emotion or feeling, nor bind itself to the form or letter of revelation. The latter, whatever its content or origin, is worthless if it be not re-affirmed by reason. This is not making reason supreme ; it is theologising in the true sense of the word. Theology, even if it rest upon inspired appre- hension, of revelation, is individual, and even tentative. Dogmatism, formalism, and literalism, culminating in the doctrine of infallibility, constitute the religious materialism of the age, which he terms extreme, reactionary, and all- pervading. The radical question of philosophy at its present stage is, "What is the essence of man?" The author here follows the philological theory of Lazarus and Steinthal. Physically man is higher, though not essentially different from, ani- mals. Darwinism, which is as yet an open question, cannot affect his present or future. The human and animal soul alike are first manifest in what Lotze terms " general feel- ing"; in which the whole sum and elasticity of disposable vital force are set over against the outer world. This is the 2 1 8 Anti- Materialism . most generic form of external consciousness. Through tlie senses, whicli are organs of the soul's intercourse with the external world, this general feeling becomes localized and specitic. These separate sensations are " so combined as to correspond with the external pattern," and perception is the result. By means of the mental pictures thus formed, and which begin to exist independently of the outer object, the animal soul remembers, thinks, &c., with great accuracy within the narrow held of instinct. In the impulse to escape from the pressure of the outer world upon the senses, nerves of sensation react on nerves of motion, and an interjectional language is formed, expressing, like sensation, very general relations. The animal soul never distinguishes its percep- tion of the sound from its perception of the object; never hears itself speak. With this distinction self-consciousness, or, as it may be called at this stage, verbal consciousness, begins. "A perception of a perception, or a conception, arises," to which the animal never attains. As sound and perception become associated, these interjections become ob- jective, and the inner perception of the sound also becomes vocal by the more subjective and generic principle of ono- matopoeia. This process continued under the law of natural (i.e. rational) selection until this language of language was finally resolved into the fundamental phonetic types or roots of articulate speech. These may be said to " exist by na- ture," or, according to Professor Heyse, "As material objects produce their own peculiar sound, so must it also be with the most perfect organization under the working of nature." The fact of the existence of such an original power in man, which, in forming roots out of the natural cries of sensation, transformed itself into reason, and which alone distinguishes man from animals, must be regarded as ultimate. It was an instinct which ceased to exist when its function was per- formed. Starting then anew from these roots, of which the few hundred known to philology were doubtless but a small fraction, but which were very generic in signification, (as is indicated by the fact that most of them are known to have been originally predicates,) words have constantl}^ become more specific in meaning and more individual in form. The individual finds a ready-made vocabulary, in which words Anti- Materialism. 219 are mere counters, with a capricious or fortuitous value, and with little trace of original meaning. A feeling of imperfec- tion and inseciirity arises which impels to a new harmoniza- tion of the spoken logos with the logos of reason, a process which now goes on in the full light of consciousness. Now is realized of single words what was in a measure true of them even as roots, that they are inadequate expressions of thought. By sentences (logical formula) reason attempts, not a mere enumeration of properties or conceptions, but " such an arrangement of them as is conditioned by their relation to the total content'' of consciousness. In this way knowledge is translated from external to internal relations, and becomes self-knowledge. Consciousness reaches its highest and most intimate self-involution in the conscious- ness of the ego as such. Indeed knowledge is uncertain and hypothetical till it has reached its ultimate form of self- certainty. Conditioned by the intellectual, though springing at first from physical relations, is the practical nature of man. Ac- tion realizes thought. As knowledge is phenomenal and for- mal, motives are external and mechanical; but as the former become self-certain, the latter resolve themselves into the pressure of self -feeling . The ultimately rational and neces- sary act of man is self-realization. In self-certainty and self- realization consists the essence of man as siperso7i. Greek philosophy, with its slave states, never rose to this full con- ception of the nature of man. The mediaeval doctrine of innate ideas allowed no free, personal self-determination^; nor was the nature of the mind rightly conceived as a tabula rasa, receiving impressions of sense. Kant first conceived the soul as a principle which won ideas by its own activity. The ego of the elder Fichte was merely the ego of self-con- sciousness. His son laid the true foundation of philosophy and ethics in personality as the common ground of thought and action. Lazarus' well-known law has shown how every perception must be complemented by an inner apperception : i.e. that since all new knowledge must have points of contact with the old, the reproduction of similar conceptions in conscious- ness is an indispensable condition of belief. Faith cannot 220 Anti'3fateriaUsm . rest upon the external ^-rounds of luitliorit}^ or testimony, or it would be, as science holds, a lower form of knowledge ; yet, like knowledge, it may arise from these, or even from aesthetic grounds. Neither is faith a "higher organ of knowl- edge, above sense, understanding, or reason." It is subject to the law and conditions of all belief; and pursues the same way as knowledge to self-certainty. " Faith without rational grounds is a psychological impossibility." The sepa- rate use of the word received an early sanction in philology, and Greek philosoi)hy taught a higher innate knowledge above consciousness. Kant made faith and knowledge utter- ly antagonistic. The word faitli., as indicating such a dis- tinction, should be banished from the field of theory. In a practical sense, however, the distinction remains. Here knowledge denotes acquaintance with means and methods, while faith, in the sense of fidelity, faithfulness, denotes "self-committal to what one is self-certain of." It is confi- dence in the purpose or end in view. It is the force of per- sonal conviction impelling to the realization of that end, and thus " higher than mere knowledge." But self-realization is self-enlargement, though neither are selfish, such external motives as love of being observed, or higher, the love of esteem or of glory ; in short, all which is detrimental to self, or to other selves, is selfish. Even the enthusiasm which sacrifices self to its cause, is apt to react into pride of voluntary humility. The feeling of satisfaction which is inseparable from every act of self-realization, and which is the last refuge of selfish utilitarianism, is not a motive. The earliest instinct of self-realization is traced through its phenomenal stages, and is shown to be the most irrepressible act of conscious life, and to culminate in Zo?)^, which "unself- ishly realizes itself by seeking the enlargement of others by helping them to like independence." Division of labor in the fields of science, the degeneration of the doctrine of personal freedom, which demands a fixed and positive basis, into individual and arbitrary license ; the development of material life, which causes superstition to settle over the higher fields of thought, perversion and mis- understanding of the leading principles of philosophy, de- Anti- Materialism. 221 tached from their systematic connection, and especially the false antagonism of philosophy and religion, are enumerated as the prominent causes of the present decadence of philo- sophic studies. Every department of truth is spun over with the dicta of sects, or parties, or of individual assertion ; and so-called positive truths have suspended the force of original conviction on the ultimate question of human being and des- tiny. True philosophy, on the other hand, which consists "in working over forms of thought," or in elevating conceptions to ideas, is at the same time " the might of personality and the necessary task of each." It begins with the all-constru- ing ego, which itself cannot be construed. The individual passes three phenomenal stages on the way to complete per- sonality: 1. Language, the immediate reflex of the object, the truth of apprehension ; 2. Reason, the truth of thought or self-certainty ; 3. Action, the realization of certainty. Phi- losophy contemplates three objects, God, man, nature ; ori- gin, perfection, and process of all things. The content and the form of thought must be carefully distinguished ; e.g. God is first present in the sense of dependence which arose when man first distinguished himself from objects of nature around him. All representations of God, of which the Jew- ish and Christian are most perfect, have the same contents, but an inadequate form ; while, on the other hand, one may be self-certain of God, with very imperfect conception of him. Man's essence consists in self-determination and self-cer- tainty reproducing each other. He became self-certain of good and evil by an act in the fall ; and, in turn, all moral action is a product of self-certain conviction, ]S"ature (and history) affords field for experiment and investigation where general though not universal results are obtained, as well as a field where deduction can lay off its content in tangible forms of time and space. But only when thought shall ^'per- fectly agree with its object" shall we become self-certain of what is in the world. Space forbids any lengthened consideration of the theolo- gical bearings of the work. We have chosen simply to repro- duce its contents, not merely because it is the pronunciamento of a well-known physicist against the tendencies of natural science, but because mediating between materialism and ide- 2!?'2 Interpretation of Kant's Kritik of Pure Reason. alisiii, the seductive extremes of modern thought, it affords a safe and prospective stand-point from which to observe the course of recent phik)sophy and science in Germany, and be- cause it adds still another to the favorable and easy points of contact between the German and American mind. KAA'T'S CRITICISM OF PURE REASON: AN INTEIll'RETATION AND CRITICISM, I5y Simon S. Laukik. Prefatory RemarKvS. — I have called what follows an "in- terpretation," because, while the text of Kant is closely and stringently adhered to, I have aimed rather at giving the actual substance of such proposition than at a translation. I am satislied that it is only when so presented that German philosophy will tind in America and England intelligent students. The criticism is close, strict, and concise; and the only apology to be offered for its unattractive and unin- teresting character is that it aims at being scientiiic, and is addressed consequently only to those who are already fa- miliar with metaphysical questions, and accustomed to the severe toil which the study of them demands even from the most competent. The next jiart will contain to the end of the ^jsthetic. KANT'S KRITIK OF PURE REASON. I. Of the Distinction between Pare and Empirical Knowledge. In respect of Time no knowledge antecedes experience. How else than by means of objects (Gegenstiinde) could the knowing faculty be stirred into activity? [At bottom is not this onlj^ to say that there can be no knowledge without an object ; and in this sense, inasmuch as all cognitions involve objects or matter of cognition, there can be no knowledge without experience. All objects of knowl- edge, whatsoever their source, are, in so far as known, expe- rience. Therefore the origin of all knowledge is experience, but not therefore the source. N. B. — There is a want in this first chapter of a sufficient distinction between experience generally and 5ew5d-experi- ence.] Interpretation of KanVs Kritilc of Pure Reason. 223 Those knowledges which have not their origin in experi- ence— [that is to say, ^e^ise- experience, or what?] — we call a priori. Have we truly a priori cognitions — cognitions loholly independent of experience ? [What kind of experience ? I may again ask.] Those a priori cognitions are alone pure which have no mix- ture of sense: e.g. "Every Change has its Cause" is a priori,' but mixed, because "change" is a notion [Begriff] got from l^Sense'] experience. • II. We are in po.'isessio7i of certain a priori Tinovledge, and even the common understanding is never without such. If a proposition is thought along with necessity, it is a judgment a priori., therefore one wholly (schlechterdings) so; if deduced from no other, or, if deduced, yet deduced from that which is itself necessary. Again, the universality of induction is only provisional, thus : " So far as ice hatje observed. All bodies are heavy ; therefore, All bodies are heavy." This is not true and strict universality. Where true and strict universality belongs to a proposition, it is ipso facto a priori. Universality and necessity are the two marks by which we know an a ^no?'/ judgment. The one really involves the other. [That is to say, experience — by which is meant sense- experi- ence— cannot yield true universals. Can it not? If I have exhausted the facts, I can safely affirm strict universality. If I have tested all stones and found all heavy, then the propo- sition "All stones are heavy" is strictly universal. It is not an induction proper, but a colligation. Though universal, is it necessary? is it a priori? Not so. Universality is not, then, a test of the a priori ; universality does not involve ne- cessity. But necessity involves universality ; therefore, the sole criterion, keeping within the Kantian sphere, is Neces- sity. Again, "All men are rational," "All animals die," — are these universals strict and true? Yes. Do they convey to us the notion of Necessity ? Yes : and yet they are experience- inductions — observations of sense not yet completed; for we have not yet seen all animals die. There may, then, be neces- sary propositions which are not a priori.~\ That such universal, necessary, and therefore a priori cogni- tions exist, it is easy to show. Take mathematical propo- 224 Interpretation of KanVs Krltik of Pure Reason. sitions g-eiierally for example ; also the proposition, " Every change must have a cause. ■'' Tlie necessity bound up with such propositions cannot be explained as a habit of mind engendered by association, as Hume says : for the necessity vanishes under the explanation. Moreover, a priori cogni- tions can be established as indispensable to the possibility of Experience — as that which gives to experience certitude (Gewissheit). [Is not this to beg the question, there may be no "certitude," whatever certitude! may mean ? Of course, if Certitude of experience is a fact, and if this is possible only in so far as experience rests on a priori Judgments, then a priori judg- ments exist : and there is no use of arguing further as to the fact of their existence. Our business would then be only to 'collect them. But there may be no certitude in experience : if so, what then ? Again, if by Certitude of experience be meant the element of the "necessary" which is bound up with exi)erience-judgments, the argument will run thus: "There is a necessary in propositions : Experience cannot give this necessariness : Therefore the necessariness is a priori.'''' Now it seems to me, that, given this element of apparent necessity in propositions, it is our business as philosophers to take it up as an alleged necessity not yet demonstrated, and to ana- lyze it with a view to ascertain its source and ground by the unveiling of its place and manner of genesis. It is not enough merely to say that, if Hume be right, the element of Neces- sity ganzlich verloren gehen wiirde (p. 35).] There is a necessity not only in judgments but also in Be- griffe (notions, concepts); e.g. abstract from a bodily object its qualities of hardness, color, &c., and still there remains the space it occupied which you cannot think away. There is also that whereby you think the object as "Substance," or dependent on Substance, which cannot be thought away. [On the lirst point I remark, that when I have thought away all the sens<»;-qualities of a body, I have thought away also its ligure and extension : in fact it is thought away erdirely. and the space which remains is not the body, nor the space of the body, but merely space. Space as such I cannot think away, but determined space or ligure and localization I can, and in rhe above case do think away. — As to the second point : I cannot think away the " Substance " of a material object so long as the object is before my consciousness in any shape, hower mutilated as regards "qualities"; but if all its qualities disappear from my consciousness, I affirm that Interpretation of KanVs Kritik of Pure Reason. 225 its "substance" also disappears. At the same time it has to be affirmed that there exists the notion of "Substance,'' and that it seems not to be given in sense ; and further, that it seems to have more to do with the thing before me than any thing- else has. But to demonstrate its a priori character I must find another argument than the necessity with which it clings to my concept of an object. I cannot venture to beg the ques- tion as to the a-priority of the necessary. I must analyze the notion "substance" and find out whence it springs, and I must also analyze the notion "necessary" and find out what it truly means.] III. Philosophy needs a Science ivhich shall determine the possibility , the prin- ciples, and the range, of all knowledge of a priori. Still more important is the fact that certain cognitions go beyond the limits of experience by means of notions, con- cepts {Begriffe), which have no corresponding experience- object. Precisely in these super-sensible cognitions lie the most important questions of "Reason" ( Vernunft), viz. God. Freedom, Immortality. The science which deals with these is called Metaphysic, which (unfortunately) undertakes its task without a prior demonstration of the capabilities of Vernunft. When once we have left behind us the ground of experi- ence we ought to inquire how the understanding (Yerstand) could attain to all these a priori cognitions which we wot of, and what range and validity they have. We are led by the success which attends the a priori reasoning of Mathematics to expect equally great results in other and different regions without making sure that we stand on a foundation of certi- tude (and to think that we have got them). What deceives us in this process is that the chief business of the Vernunft is the Analysis of Concepts (Begriffe), and we seem to our- selves to be thereby adding to the content of our knowledge new Insights when we are merely explicating and elucidating what is already there. This experience does give a true a priori cognition — [how ? I suppose in so far as it yields "necessary" propositions (identical)] — which has a sure and useful issue ; and Reason (Vernunft) inadvertently insinu- ates affirmations (Behauptungen) of a totally different kind, by which it adds to the given Begriffe alien a priori Begriffe Vol. vi.— 15 2*26 [nferpretation of KanVs Kritilx of Pure Reason. without knowing or asking how they lind their way here. — [Illustration wanted here.] — Our tirst business, then, is to in- vestigate this twofold kind of cognition — [that is, the kind whereby we truly obtain new insights, and the kind w^hich is merely analytic]. [The defect in Kant's argument, already indicated at an earlier point, still hangs about the above reasoning. The criterion of the a priori is '•Necessity*' (not Universality, of which we have already disposed); but is it legitimate to con- clude, as it were^er saltum, that what is ^'- necessary''^ in a Judgment or concept has its source outside sense-experienced And tliis I take to be the strict meaning of a pi'iori. Note, that Kant says that Vernunft is the power by which we analyze concepts or notions. Also that he once (in the above chapter) uses reines Verstand as an equivalent for Vernunft.] IV. Of the Distinction of Analytic and Synthetic Judgments. The two kinds of judgments are the Analytic and Synthe- tic. By an analytic judgment is meant a judgment in which the predicate is merely an explication of what is already con- tained in the subject. A synthetic judgment is a judgment in which the predicate is an ampliation of the subject — a clear addition to the content of the concept. "All bodies are extended" is analytic, for in "Body" is alread}^ contained Extension, which I by the above judgment merely bring into clearer consciousness. "All bodies are heavy" is synthetic, because "heavy" is not thought in the mere concept "body," and is a clear addition to that concept. The former are Erlau- terungsurtheile or explicatory judgments, and the latter Er- weiterungsurtheile or ampliative judgments. [I remark on this, that the predicate " heavy " is doubtless, for the most part, ascertained after the predicate Extension; and consequently is, at a certain stage in the progress of my knowledge. Synthetic : thereafter, however, analytic. True, Extension is contemporaneous with the first presentation of "Body" to my consciousness, and thus it may be regarded as analytic in quite a special manner ; but what shall we say of one born blind whose first acquaintance with "body" was "weight" '{] Judgments of Experience (Erfahrungsurtheile) are wholly Synthetic. It would be absurd to ground an analytic judg- Interpretation of Kant's Kritik of Pure Reason. 227 ment on experience. Experience could not give to it its necessary character which it has by virtue of the Law of con- tradiction. [By this is meant that analytic judgments as such cannot be grounded on experience ; but the attributes which at lirst go to constitute the subject, and which in an analytic judgment I merely draw out, are in truth themselves primarily based on Experience. An analytic necessity is not at bottom, there- fore, an a priori cognition. Its necessity is explained by the Law of contradiction. Body is given in Sense qua extended : therefore "Body" with the predication extension is so given in Sense. This being so, the notion "Body'' with all that is implied in it is a ^o^^mo?'/ unless I can show that there is an attribute implicit in it which is not given in Sense.] But in synthetic judgments a priori we are bereft of tliis help of experience. When I say, " Whatever happens has a Cause," I, in so far as "whatsoever happens" is concerned. afllrm a fact of sense-experience, and at the same time a priori to the "happening": but where do I get the univer- sal and necessary Begriff, " Cause^'^ which I import into the Judgment, and which cannot be the object of Experience, because it is necessary, and Experience can give only the contingent? On such Synthetic or Ampliative Grundsatze — [he ought to say Principien] — rests the whole of Speculative knowledge a priori in its final aim. [For this notion, "Cause," I have to account. It is not given in Sense. As Synthetic and yet not given in sense, therefore, it demands explanation and vindication. Kant, it will be seen, assumes that the notion is a priori because it is necessary and universal ; but it is evident that it might he possible to account for its necessity, or seeming necessity, without involving ourselves in apriority. Here however, let it be noted, we truly come on a "notion" which we may, as a matter of fact, ransack Sense in vain to find, and which therefore is strictly a priori.'] In all Theoretical Sciences of Vernunft, synthetic a puiori Judgments are contained as Principles. MATHEMATICAL JUDGMENTS ARE WHOLLY SYNTHETIC A PRIORI. First of all, mathematical propositions are necessary, and, therefore, a priori. 228 Interprdation of KanVs 2\^ritik of Pure Reason. [To this I again deinur. 11" tliev are analytic necessaries, they are then not because necessary therefore a priori, in the strict signitication.] Next they are ISyntlietic. That 7 + 5 = 12 seems at first sight Analytic; but how can we get anything like the number 12 out ot the summation 7 and 5. The notion "Twelve" is not thought through the union of 7 and ."> ; and I may analyze the notion of such a possible summation ever so long without find- ing 12 therein. To find this, 1 must go beyond the notion of the Sum and resort to sensibh3 perception, and. stai'ting from 7, add five units in the shape of fingers or points. Thus I see 12 spring out of this process. In the notion of the sum 7-|-5, I have thought, it is true, that o is to be added to 7, but in that thought the equality of this sum with the number "12" is not thought. [In other words, Kant means to say that the result 12 is not already contained in 7 + 5, and that therefore it is some- thing new. synthetic, ampliative. And it is also, as we alrea- dy know, •• necessary,'' and, therefore (according to Kant), a priori. Here again I must object to the assumed a-priority of the "necessary." An analytic judgment is necessary-, and yet the predicate is not therefore ascertained a priori — i.<\ outside sense experience. A true a priori proposition is al- ways necessary, but a necessary i)roposition is not always a priori. What, however, we have chiefly to do with here is the syn- thetic character of the above numerical judgment. It seems to me that it is not synthetic. There is nothing in 7+5 which can yield 12 any more than it could yield 20, except in so far as 7 and 5 are mere verbal signs for 7 units and 5 units respec- tively ; and it is by my sensible perception of the accumula- tion of these units one on another that I see that they yield a larger quantity of units, which for shortness sake I call 12, just as I have already called so many units 7 and so many units 5. "Twelve" is nothing but 7 + f + 1 + 1 + 1 + 1, which I gather into unity under the designation "Twelve" and the sign 12. Kant admits that by the above process I can see 12 "spring out" of 7 + 5, but affirms that the "notion" 7 + 5 can- not contain in it 12. I would ask: Is it denied that when I say 7 + 5, I ipso facto affirm 12 even though I have not yet discovered either a name or a sign for the said cumulation or sum !• If this is not denied, then 12 is contained in the notion 7+5. — Again, what does Kant mean by the ^'■notion^'' of 7+5^ Interpretation of KanVs Kritik of Pure Reason. 229 This can only mean the notion of 7 units and the notion of 5 units thrown into union. The weakness of Kant's position is shown by his advising us to take large numbers if we would see the truth of this Synthetic character of the Judgment. But if we would see clearly what a thing is in thought, we must, on the contrary, rest on its simplest forms. Had K. taken 7+1 he would have found it hard to show that the notion 8 was not contained in the notion of this sum, and that the predicate was synthetic. Or what would he say to 1 + 1 = 2 ?] So with Pure Greometry : A straight line is the shortest be- tween two points" is a synthetic proposition. [Now the question we have here to ask ourselves is, what do we mean by "straight"^ We must look at tilings and not be the slave of words. By " straight " we mean that which does not deviate in its progress from point to point by going- round or zigzag; and by "shortest" we mean that which covers least ground. It being so, the proposition becomes this : •' That line between two points is the shortest which does not go ever so little round, or zigzag, or out of its way," And this is an identical or analytic proposition, and not syn- thetic] There are, it is true, certain fundamental propositions (Crrundsatze) in Geometry which are analytic ; but these are not Princvpien, e.g. "«= (x"; («+/>)>«;" the whole is greater than its part." [True ; but these are in no sense inore analytic than the so- called synthetic proposition above considered.] In Physics also are to be found certain synthetic judgments a priori as Principien : e.g. " In all changes of the material world, the quantity of matter remains unchanged." It is clear that this is not only necessary, and therefore a prio7'i, but also synthetic; for in the notion "Matter'' I do not think the permanence of matter, but only its presence in Space through the filling of the same. I in the above proposition go beyond the notion of "matter" to add something which is not thought in it. [Perhaps I do not quite understand the above proposition ; for I cannot detect the grounds on which it is even to be pre- sumed to be synthetic a priori. I do not see its necessity in any proper signification of that word. That it might be shown 230 [nterpretation of Kanf\s Kritik of Pure Reason. to be synthetic a posteriori is i)i)ssil)le ; but that it should be synthetic a priori in the si<;nitication of being at once neces- sary and also an niii]»liati(>n of" our Isuowledii-e of matter not given in sense. I cannot see. There are various ways of h)oking at the proposition : for example, "Change in particular nuitter cannot lessen or in- crease the total quantity of matter." Now I might ask, wliy should change, simply as change, lessen quantity ? Is it not the fact that in the word "Change" T think the non-lessening of matter^ In any case I certainly ilo not think the lessen- ing; and the proposition is identical or analytic. — Or put it thus : ''It is not possible to lessen or increase the total quan- tity of matter by changing particular matter." T confess I cannot see the necessary a priori synthetic character of this proposition any more than in the proposition, "It is not pos- sible to kill an elephant by means of a pea-shooter" — whicli, if necessar}" in any i)roper sense, is analytically necessary. By the very terms of the proposition matter is only changed, not lessen<'d or increased; and to say that "Change'" is not annihilation nor creation, is merely negatively to define "Change." — Perhaps, however, the necessary synthetic pro- position is an underl^ang one, viz. "Matter is indestructible." But a proposition put so generally is not necessary, nor a pri- ori, nor synthetic a priori : it is either given primarily in our notion of matter, or it is synthetic a posteriori and a synthesis of experience. In the latter case it is an induction of exx)eri- ence ; in the former, it is equivalent to saying, "Matter as pre- sented primarily to Consciousness is composed of particles or atoms ultimately indestructible ; therefore, ])ai"ticular mat- ter or body, however it may be affected by Force, is not qua (atomic) matter destructible." — This proposition is either (a) anassumption, and therefore invalid; or {b) an inductive con- clusion of experience, and therefore neither necessar}'^ nor a priori; or (c) an analytic judgment.] In Metaphysic also there needs must be synthetic a priori cognitions. Yernunft has not only to expli'^ate by analysis, but also to extend knowledge by a priori synthesis, and that in regions where Experience cannot follow, as e.g. in the pro- position, "The World must have a lirst beginning." [Truly this is Synthetic and not the synthesis of experi- ence ; therefore, a priori. Much of Kant's reasoning is invalidated by the unsatisfac- tory use of a priori as an ecjuivalent for necessary and vice versa.'] Interpretation of Kant's Krit'ik of Pure Reason. 2?A VI. The U n ivo'sal PnonLEM {or Task) of Pare Reason. The problem of Pare Reason is contained in the question, "How are sj^nthetic judgments a priori possible?" Hume held that they were impossible, and accounted for such (apparent) judgments (confining himself however solely to the question of Cause and Eiiect) as being the product of Experience to which Custom had given the semblance of necessity. Had he seen that mathematical propositions are synthetic a prior L he could not have made this blunder ; for his position would have made Pure Mathematics impossible. [As already stated, there is, to my thinking, only an analytic necessity in Mathematical judgments.] The solution of the above problem is bound up with the possibility of the use of Pure Reason in all sciences, and an- swers the questions : 1. How is Pure Mathematics possible? 2. How is Pure Physics possible i There is a natural disposition in Reason towards Meta- physic (metaphysica naturalis). It loill ask certain ques- tions. The answers to these hitherto have been involved in unavoidable contradictions. Still it must be possible to say whether we can know or not, to judge respecting the capability or incapability of Yernunft to answer the questions which it puts, and to what extent we may trust it ; — all which yields this Query : Is Metaphysic as Science possible ?" The Criticism of Reason (Vernunft), consequently, leads to Science as opposed to Dogmatism, which uncritically makes large afiirmations, to which equally plausible affirmations on the other side may be opposed, and leads consequently to Skepticism. Its range of inquiry is not very wide, for it has to deal not with objects, but with Yernunft itself, its capabilities, audits own self-given queries. All Dogmatic Metaphysics we must regard as non-existent, since it merely analyzes the a priori notions which our Yer- nunft already has ; whereas our true aim is to ascertain how 232 Inteiyretatioii of Kant's Kritik of Pure Reason. we come by these notions, and to determine their valid appli- cation to the objects of knowledge. VII. /rfca and Division of a Particular Science under the name of a Kkitik of PcRE Reason. From what has been said, the " Idea" of a special science will have been now attained, wliich we may designate the "Kritik of Pure Reason." For Reason is the faculty which gives us the Principien of a priori cognitions, and therefore Pure Reason contains the Principien of a priori knowing. [That is to say (I suppose), Yernunft (which also, as we have seen, analyzes notions) yields us the pkinciples which un- derlie all a priori cognitions, and also contains the Principles whereby we know a priori. I cannot understand the dou- ble use of the word Principien above. Perhaps I misun- derstand the passage. It may merely mean. Pure Reason is the faculty by which we know a priori, and it further con- tains in itself the grounds of our a priori knowledge ; — wliich is much as if we said that it holds in its bosom the substance of a priori knowledge as Forms. This, doubtless, is the meaning.] An Inbegriff or Compendium of those Principien whereby we are enabled to acquire cognitions a priori would be an Organon of Pure Reason, — the complete application of which would yield a System or Doctrine. It is not, however, our purpose to do more than furnish a critique with a view to define the sources and limits of Pure Reason. This may be regarded as a Propjedeutic to a system. [Should he not say — •• to define the limits of the activity of that which I have called Pure Reason, and the sources of the Princif)ien which it yields";! I would then understand Prin- cipien to mean the affirmation of synthetic a priori judgments as free from content as possible, i.e. an abstract statement, e.g. "A thing cannot at the same time be itself and another": or a Formula, e.g. A = A.] Kant next goes on to define Transcendental Knowledge as being the Knowledge which has to do, not with objects, but with our mode of cognizing objects in so far as it is a priori. A system of such Begriffe would be a system of Transcen- dental Philosophy. Interpretation of Kant's Kritik of Pure Reason. 233 [That is to say, the Rational forms of a priori or necessary thought — or, to put it otherwise, the forms of Reason in a pri- ori or necessary Knowing — are called '• Transcendental^ — An illustration is wanted here. The word Begriffe is loosely used.] The form? of cognition of analytic necessaries are also Transcendental; but it is only the Synthetic a priori which constitute the subject of the Kritik. Did it occupy itself also with the Analytic, it would then embrace the whole of hu- man knowledge a priori, and thus realize the complete Idea of a Transcendental Philosophy. [It occurs to us here to wonder how Kant will keep clear of the criticism of Analytical necessaries. He can do so only by bringing within the range of the SyntJietic much which is in truth Analytic, as he has alread}^ done in the case of Ma- thematical Judgments.] This Kritik will consist of two great Divisions : Firsts the Doctrine of the Elements of Pure Reason ; Second, the Doctrine of the Method of Pure Reason. By way of Preface, it is only further necessary to say- that there are two stems of human Knowledge (perhaps springing out of a common root), viz. Seiise and Understand- ing^ through the former of which objects are given^ and through the latter of which objects are thought. In so far as the Sense-faculty contains Vorstellungen a pri- ori, it belongs to the Transcendental Philosophy ; and, as the conditions under which all objects are given, it must take priority in treatment over that through which objects are thought. [ Yorstellungen a priori mean IS'ecessary Presentation to Consciousness in perception. These, however, come within Kant's scope only if they are synthetic. I suspect he already loses sight of his own self-imposed restrictions as to the proper range of the Kritik.] ElS^D OF II^TRODUCTIOX. '234 The Tragedy of Julius Cirsar. THK TllAUEDY OF JULIUS C.HSAR liV SHAKESPEARE. By D. J. S.MDKR. The Drama represents man inaction. It exliibits him in the inlinite web of his complications, with influences passing out from him and coniino- back to him, and thereby portrays in the shortest space and in the most striking manner the relative worth of human deeds. Nor does it rest content with the mere external doings of man ; on the contrary, it pene- trates his innermost nature, and probes the j)rofoundest depths of his spiritual being. For it unfolds motives, ends, convictions; and, in fact, these subjective elements constitute its most important feature. Thej^ form the basis of what is called character, and their true logical subordination is ex- hibited in the denouement of the piece. The Drama is the most concrete and therefore the highest of all the forms of Poetry. The Epos is the product of national childhood ; it contemplates man in an intellectual infancy which demands the continuous supervision of the Gods. It therefore lays stress upon the Objective, the Uni- versal ; not, however, as mediated through the spirit of man, but as an existence standing outside of him ?ind determining his actions. Hence the tinge of Fate which prevails in all Epic Poetry, for the contradiction between Freedom and Necessity is not yet developed by this early consciousness. Still self-determination may and in fact ought to peer through these external forms in a naive, unconscious manner ; such is the case with Homer, who often seems to make the Gods his sport. The Epos therefore may be said to be essentially reli- gious, and seeks to unfold if not to justify the ways of Provi- dence to man. The Lyric Poet, on the contrary, portrays his own emo- tions, desires, reflections ; in fine, the entire content of his own subjectivity. His strain may be one of joy and happi- ness, but it is most commonly an incessant lamentation about his own injured and unappreciated self, or a stinging censure of the cold, heartless world. He thus falls out with the ex- isting order of things, becomes negative and sceptical, assails and undermines the ancient faith and simple epical feeling. The Tragedy of Julius Ccesar. 235 So old Simonid.es was accused of impiety. But to mention all the phases of the lyrical form of poetry would be impossi- ble, for it is as varied and boundless as the nature of man, a,nd extends into all periods of civilization. Its general characteristic however is subjective, and it portrays man in reflection. But in the Drama all this is changed. Man starts up from the repose in which he has been describing and nursing his emotions, and begins to act ; that is, he begins to give his subjective nature validity in the objective world. His feel- ings, passions, hopes, ends, are no longer satisfied with quiet, lyrical description, but must take on the form of reality. Nor again are these ends which he is trying to realize always merely subj.ective ; on the contrary, they represent objective principles of universal validity, as the Right, the Ethical, the State. Hence the Dramatic is the concrete unity of the Epic and Lyric ; not a mixture of the two, but an entirely new spe- cies. It unites the subjective side of the one with the objec- tive side of the other, b}^ making the objective world inherent in the subject, and thus filling its emptiness and giving it content ; and, on the other hand, it gives validity to the sub- ject in the objective world through his own activity. The Drama presents an action like the Epos ; but it must aban- don the principle of external divine interference, and put in its stead the self-conscious, self-acting individual. Hence no demons, angels, or Gods, are allowed to perform the media- tions of the Drama in its highest manifestations ; all is hu- man and expressive of human freedom. For there can only be one reason why the Drama is the highest of all the forms of Art : it most adequately represents self-determination — man as a free and hence responsible being. If, therefore, the Epical consciousness is essentially religious and the Lyrical negative and even sceptical, the Dramatic, on the other hand, is Ethical. But the Ethical is not a single principle, but includes a series of principles w^hich form a regular gradation from the lowest to the highest. Hence ii is possible for a lower prin- ciple to collide with a higher. It is just this conflict which constitutes the source of all dramatic action. As the science of Ethics, if truly elaborated, would show all these principles. 236 The T raged ;/ of Julius CiPsar. in their proper relation and subordination, from a theoretical point of view, so the Drama in a praotieal way, by means of human action, exliibits in \ ictory or defeat, success or failure, the true relation and subordination of these same ethical y>rinciples. It calls man before its tribunal, and unfolds to him the conse(|uences of his deeds, not in an abstract form^ but in the form of the deed itself. If we consider the Drama in this light, it is not the trivial, sportive toy which furnishes amnsement for an idle hour, but it assumes immense propoi'tions. We shall iind that it is only another form of proposing the greatest of problems, a new way that people have of looking at the profoundest ques- tions of human existence. For the Drama is certainl}^ based upon the ethical world, its collisions must rest upon elements inherent in the ethical order of things, and its solutions if true — which is the same as artistic — must be in accordance with this order. Therefore, to Judge of the Drama, we have to know something of this ethical world, its contradictions and its harmonies, its principles and the order of their subordina- tion ; or, if we do not know these things already, the Drama may be able to give the lequisite instruction. And further- more, since the ethical world is the realization of Reason, we are led through the Drama to ask ourselves the more impor- tant question. What is the absolutely Rational ? — not as an idle question of speculation, but as the vital fount of action, as the guiding thread of Life ought we to consider such a theme. The Rational in the Drama and the Rational in Thought and Action cannot well be different ; indeed the one is only the adumbration of the other. So the Drama in its high- est utterances takes up the pi'oblem of Life, and solves it in its own peculiar manner. The clash of appetites and passions, the conflict of rights and duties, the alarming hand of P^'ate reaching over, grasping after all, and, most prominently, the benelicent form of Freedom standing on a heap of broken chains, are there portrayed, the opposing forces reconciled and reduced to one harmonious, well-ordered system. Thus we may learn a practical as well as an aesthetic truth of incal- culable value, that the Rational in the Drama is the Rational in Life. By these remarks we hope it may be seen that the Dramatic Art is no mere abstraction apart from or opposed The Tragedy of Julius Cwsar. 237 to tlie real world — no plaything to amuse those refined and elegant natures who long to tly away from this grovelling sphere to realms ideal, there to bathe in the sunlight of eter- nal truth ; but it clings to earth, and is the most intensely human of all Art. Nor has mankind ever failed to appreciate its significance as furnishing a refiex of the highest endeavors and greatest achievements of the race. There is one man to whom we all instinctively turn with the certainty of finding a rational basis — Shakespeare. Criti- ■clsm has worn itself almost threadbare upon him, and we often are sated with the interminable talk about him, the most of which is so unsatisfactory ; still we have always to come back to his works as the unfailing source of the highest Intellectual and artistic enjoyment. People feel that his is the greatest name in all literature, perhaps in all history. But this is not enough : we must know what is the special form of that greatness. And so the question arises, wherein Is Shakespeare the greatest of authors i We cannot say in the perfection of form, for herein others perhaps surpass him ; nor in the mastery of language, for this is a knack which may be learned, and moreover means little by itself; nor in the beauty of his images, for they are often confused, incongru- ous, and far-fetched ; not even in characterization, nor in the management of an action, in the strict sense of the term. Great as his excellence in these things, it has been attained sometimes at least by far inferior writers. There can be no doubt in the statement that the unique and all-surpassing greatness of Shakespeare lies in his comprehension of the ethical order of the world. Though this side of his genius has been always most inadequately stated, and commonly has been passed over entirely in the essays of his critics, still men have instinctively felt that his works were the truest literary product of modern times, because they were the most perfect and concrete presentation of realized rationality. Men see in him their highest selves, and hence must take him as their greatest exponent. The contrast in this respect with even the best creations of nearly all other poets is most strik- ing. We read them, we are charmed with the imagery, the thoughts, the rhythmic flow of the verse. But when we come to the end of one of these works we are confused, lost ; we 24^8 The Tragedy of Julius CiFsar. analyze it more closely, and find that the Whole, however beautiful its individual parts, is an ethical chaos. But Shake- speare, in this sphere as elsewhere, is all harmony ; no con- tradictions cloud his poetical horizon, nor does he ever make the denouement a logical annihilation of the whole play. To throw out some hints towards a comprehension of this highest side of Shakespeare's genius is our present purpose. To this end we have selected "Julius 0;i3sar,'' as exhibiting Shakespeare's ethical world in its completest if not in its con- cretest form. But first it would perhaps be well to enumer- ate some of the elements of this ethical world. Those most obvious and most commonly recognized are the Individual. Family, and State. These elements have their limits against one another ; hence they fall into conflict, and one must be subordinated to the other. That is, the individual may assert himself acrainst the demands of Familv or State, or the Fam- ily may come into collision with the State. It is evident that there must be a gradation of rank in these powers ; one must be above another, else strife and confusion can only result. But above all these there is a fourth principle, which has not the taint of finitude which rests upon the others. For even the State, to which every individual must bow and every princi- ple yield, whose absolute supremacy is expressed in the fact that its safety is the highest law, seems notwithstanding to be exposed to the might of the destroying angel. The Past is strown with the wrecks of States ; the empires of the Ori- ent, Greece, Rome, the Middle Ages, have arisen and passed away : and so we must acknowledge a Power above the State which cjills it into being and also puts an end to its existence. What this Power is, we need not now discuss : w^e only wish to recognize and name it : let us call it the Spirit of World- History ; or, more concisely, the World-Spirit ; or, in the lan- guage of religion, God in History. Only let us not imagine that it is some far-off Power wholly external to man, whose arm descends and smites him to the earth without his know- ing whence it cometh or whither it goeth. Furthermore, all these Principles can only be vitalized through the Individual. Taken alone, they are mere abstrac- tions and of no force ; but when a man goes forth armed with them, and makes them the basis of his action, they move the The Tragedy of Julius Ccesar. 239 world. It is only in this way they can collide and form the foundation of a drama. An individual thus hecomes the bearer of some grand ethical principle, and can come into conflict Avitli another individual who is fulfilling the same destiny in a ditterent sphere. For instance, a person may assert the right of individual conscience— certainly a valid principle — against the majesty of law which is the command of the State ; or, like Antigone, may prefer duty toward Family to obedience to civil authority ; or, finally, there may be a still higher colli- sion, that between the defenders of the State on the one hand and the supporters of the World-spirit on the other. Such is the collision between nations struggling for independence and their conquerors, the collision of Carthage with Rome, of the Pole with the Russian, of the Hungarian with the Aus- trian. We feel for the fallen nation, we may even weep over an heroic people defeated and prostrate, still in the end we are compelled to say : It is just; the World-Spirit, whose right it is to judge the nations, has decided against them. Now it is just this collision which Shakespeare has pre- sented in "Julius Caesar." For C^esar is the representative of the World- Spirit ; he appears upon the stage of History as the destroyer of his country's liberties, hence the grand con- flict of his life was with the State. It is indeed this fact which has caused him to be calumniated by nearly twenty centuries of writers and speakers. But note that Shakespeare does not join in this cry of execration. To him Caesar's career is not political, but world-historical ; not limited to a single state, but having the world as its theatre. To him C;esar stands at the head of that eternal and infinite movement in whose grasp the nations are playthings. But, on the other hand, let us not forget that this movement was nothing ex- ternal to Rome ; it was the movement of Rome herself ; the Roman Constitution was sapped perhaps before the birth of Caesar. He only carried out the unconscious national will ; he saw what Rome needed, and possessed the strength to execute it, and this is his greatness, and in fact the only real political greatness. That one man can overturn the form of government permanently against the will and spirit of a whole people is preposterous. That such was not Shakespeare's view is shown by the termination of the play. The conspira- '240 The Tragedij of Julius Ccesar. tors are overthrown aiul the su})porters of Cassar are success- ful. But this will be more fully pointed out hereafter. The State has also its representatives in this conflict — Cas- sius and Brutus, more esi^ecially the former. They were the bearers of the spirit of the old Roman Constitution, and were strong enough to destroy the individual Ga'sar, but by no means the movement which he represented. The thought of Caesar remained, and Octavius simply steps into his place, conquers, and has peace — shuts the temple of Janus for the tirst time in generations. That is, Cjesar's revolution is ac- complished, and the Roman people acquiesce. With this explanation, we may now consider some of the incidents of the play. The lirst scene introduces us to the grand background upon which the whole drama is painted — the Roman people. Shakespeare has most truthfully depicted the populace as fickle and faithless, without any substantial fixity of purpose within itself. Hence we hurry into the next scene to find the element which gives consistency and stabil- ity to this mass. Here the two great men of the time appear, like gladiators, each one bent on the destruction of the other. C?esar has arrived at the summit of his greatness ; he is ready to receive the crown and be called king, whose functions in- deed he already performs. This fact is to be particularly noted, as it will answer many objections that have been raised against the play. The critics are much troubled because Cve- sar does not say or do anything great, and declare that he is inadequately portrayed. But the poet represents him at the consummation of his deeds, and as the founder of a new or- der of things ; greater he could not well be. To be sure, a drama might be written which would exhibit C;esar at an earlier period of his life, in the bloom of his activity, energy, and military genius. But such a drama could never present the collision which Shakespeare intended, nor in the faintest degree exhibit the ethical ideas which lie at the basis of this "Julius Caesar." For in the present piece it is absolutely necessary that Cfesar as the representative of the World- Spirit be assailed, and that his assailants perish. Equally devoid of insight is the reproach of another critic, that Caesar comes upon the stage only to be slain : for the play assumes Cfesar in the plenitude of his power ; this is its first presup- The Tragedy of JitUus Ccesar. 241 position. The second presupposition is the deep liostility of Cassius to the government of Caesar. These are the two gla- diators who in this second scene leap forth stripped for the fight. Cassius is in ability only inferior to Cfesar, and Caesar is perfectly aware both of his hatred and of his talents. Cas- sius is first shown in the play overcoming the scruples of Brutus and alienating him from the party of Caesar. With what skill does he introduce the subject, with what logical force are all the motives adduced, until Brutus, partly by the most delicate fiattery and partly by adroit appeals to his mo- ral nature, is completely won. A further proof of Cassius' ability is that he essayed Brutus first of all, for the name of Brutus was the greatest and most venerable in Rome, going back even to the expulsion of the kings ; and Brutus himself was perhaps the most respectable character in Rome, and con- sequently of the greatest influence among his fellow-citizens. With him, the conspiracy might be a success ; without him, it was impossible. In the third scene, we have Cassius work- ing upon an altogether different character. Casca is the des- perado of the conspirators, a man possessed of the greatest physical courage, but without an iota of moral courage. He will rush upon an enemy and stab him, but turns deathly pale at a clap of thunder. Whatever is human he is ready to meet, but that which he conceives to be divine or super- natural is a source of the direst terror. This man Cassius must have ; no respectable man could have been found w^ho possessed equal audacity. In fact every conspiracy or vigi- lance committee has just such an instrument, whose function it is to do work which no decent man is willing to perform, but which must be done. When we observe that Casca was the first one that stabbed Caesar, we know exactly where to place him. Cassius needs this man, and it is curious to note with what consummate tact he proceeds. Knowing the weak side of Casca's character to be his superstition, he brings all his force to bear upon this single point. There is only one result which can follow. Thus far we are all admiration for the intellect of Cassius, but several things have transpired under his direction at which the rigidly moral man must shrug his shoulders. He has no doubt taken advantage of the weakness of Brutus and Vol. vi.— 16 242 The Tragedy of Julius Ccesar. Casca. and deceived them both ; he has declared that to be truth which he himself could not have believed, especially to Casca ; he has laid a most unrighteous snare for poor Brutus by writing him anonymous letters which the latter took to be calls from the people ; finally, he designs the assassina- tion of a human being, an act which can hardly be justified from any purely moral point of view. Further on in the play we sliall find many other deeds of an equally doubtful nature. How, then, is Cassius to be understood ? Shall we take the common statement, that it is a case of great intellect without any moral perceptidns ? But if we look at another side, we behold a character of the noblest stamp, of surpassing bright- ness. With what energy does he strive to restore the old Roman state — with what industry does he collect every frag- ment of opposition to the mighty Ctesar — with what readiness does he die for his country ! To be sure, he knows the might of place and ])elf, but he only uses them as instruments to his great end. There is only one clue to his conduct. His highest end was the State, and everything which came in conflict with this end had to be subordinated. It was a time of strife and n;volution, the ancient landmarks of society were swept away, the prescribed limits of order obliter- ated. No man ever saw more clearly than Cassius the finitude, one-sidedness and inadequacy of the merel}^ moral stand-point in such a period, and consequently he pro- ceeded to disregard it entirely. Suppose he did deceive or assassinate a man, provided he thereby saved the State? In fact, what is war but lying, cheating, robbing, and kill- ing, for one's country? And the man who can do these things most successfully and on the most gigantic scale is the hero, is the great general. To be sure, all this is done to our enemy ; but that can be no justification ; the moral obligation lies between fellow-men, and not fellow-countr^-men. When Cassius no longer has this end in view, he is as moral as any other man — in fact, an exemplary character. His abstinence is especially contrasted with the debauchery of Antony ; lie is moderate in desires, meagre in shape, a great student and observer of men, — all of which point to a temperate and stea- dy life. His chief characteristic, then, is the subordination of moral to political ends: he is the statesman, his thought The Tragedy of Julius Cmsar. 243 and activity find their limits in the State, liis world is his country. His point of view is stated by himself: In such a time as this it is not meet That every nice oflence should bear his commment. His reasoning is : To be sure, Lucius Pella has taken bribes^ but that offence can by no means be balanced against his ser- vices and abilities, or his inlluence ; therefore let it pass, for we need the united efforts of all against the common enemy. A distinguished American officer once expressed this subor- dination of moral to political duties in -the following toasts "My country — may she ever be right; but, right or wrongs my country." This is, perhaps, only the feeling of patriot- ism ; but the insight of Cassius was deeper, for he compre- hended intellectually that the right of the state is superior to any individual right of conscience, whenever these rights come in collision. Bat the cyclus of characters, in order to be complete, must have its moral representative. This is Brutus. The poet has treated this character with such evident delight, has thrown around it such a halo of virtue, that it seems to be the lead- ing one of the play. The honor, sincerity and nobleness of the man, the purity of his motives, his unimpeachable integ- rity in a corrupt age, the perfect fulfilment of every duty of the citizen, are brought out in their most glowing colors ; even his family relations are introduced to crown the moral beauty of his character. All the virtues of private life seem to cen- tre in this man, and we heartily join in the encomium of Antony : . This was the noblest Koman of them all; His life was gentle, and the elements So mixed in him, that Nature might stand up And say to all the world : This was a man. But alack the day ! he was called upon, or thought he was called upon, to act in times of revolution, when all the ancient prescribed landmarks were swept down, and when even the clearest and most logical head could scarcely find its way out of the confusion. Now what does this man, of the keenest sense of honor, of the most truthful nature, proceed to do? First, to desert, and then to assassinate, his dearest friend. His motive, he says, was the general welfare, but immediately 244 The Tragedy of Julius Camr. thereafter declares that C:esar had as yet done nothing hostile to the public good. And so this contradiction runs through all his acts and sayiuirs. It is evident that he had violated this fundamental })rinciple of his nature, his pro- foundest intellectual conviction. As far as his insight goes, the act is wrong. Cassiiis can consistently do such a deed, for liis stand-point is the State : and in its preservation, every- thing— men. property, and principles — are to be submerged. But poor Brutus ! what is his next stej)? He tries to justify the deed. Listen to his soliloquy, for nothing can more com- pletely show tlie inadequacy of the moral point of view, and it is besides a fine specimen of moial reasoning not unknown in our day : It must be by his death: and for my part I know no pei-sonal cause to spurn at him, But for the p^eneral. lie would be crowned ; — How that miofht change his nature, there's the question. It would seem that he was not aware of the great change which had actually taken place in the Roman Constitution, and does not know that the formal coronation of Cfesar would produce no alteration in the real condition of things. This fatal lack of all political sagacity in the leader would destroy any party or any cause. To continue : It is the bright day that brinofs forth the adder And that craves war}- walkinfj. Crown him That, And tlien I grant we put a sting in Iiini That at his will he way do danger with. Possibility is here made the basis of action. That all prac- tical wisdom is based on directly the opposite .principle needs hardly to be stated. Moreover, all crimes can easily be justified in this way, since a man has onl}' to plead some indefinite possibility. The abu.se of greatness is when it disjoins Remorse from power; and. to speak truth of Csesar, I have not known when his atfection swayed More than his reason. From this it would appear that Brutus thought that Cfiesar was still a good man and unworthy of death. It was only what Ca3sar might become, that can furnish any defence for the deed. TTie Tragedy of Julius Ccesar. 245 But 'tis a common proof That lowliness is young- ambition's Indder Whereto tlie climber upward turns his face; But when he once attains tlie topmost round He then unto the ladder turns his bacl<, Looks into the clouds, scorning the base degrees By which he did ascend; so Ccesar may. Then, lest he may, prevent. Possibility is again announced as the basis of action. The logical nature of this category is not very difficult of compre- hension. In the Possible the Real and the Unreal are not yet difterentiated, therefore it cannot have any determina- tion. But action is something determined, and since the Pos- sible has no such element in itself, the subject alone can make the necessary determination. Everything is possible, and j ust as well impossible. Who is to determine ? Only the indivi- dual, and he must also act on this determination. Thus subjectivity asserts its absolute validity, and this is what is meant by the subjective or moral point of view which in this play is represented by Brutus. And since the quarrel Will bear no color for the thing he is, (what he now is, cannot justify our act — another declaration that CjBsar had as yet done nothing which merited death,) Fasliion [state] it thus : that what he is, augmented Would run to tliese and these extremities; And thoefore thinly him as the serpent's a^.^^. Which hatched would as his kind grow mischievous, And kill him in the shell. If you cannot iind a real crime, draw on your imagination and you are sure to discover one. It will be noticed that in the foregoing soliloquy no charge is made against any act of Caesar's. And yet the world has generally held that it is not moral perversity which utters these declarations — nay, that it is moral greatness. What, then, is the matter? Brutus is not able to subordinate the xiarious sjgheres of moral duty lolien tliey come in conflict. He recognizes them all, to be sure, but not in their true limitations. Hence when they col- lide with one another, he becomes a mass of confusion, strife, and contradiction. Herein lies his immeasurable inferiority to Cassius, who clearly comprehends these limitations and 246 The Tragedi/ of Julius Cn'sar. acts upon them. It is intellectual weakness, the inability to rise out of merely moral considerations in political alfairs. The trouble is with Brutus' head, not his heart. He intends to do the right thing, only he does not do it. He acts not so much in opposition to, as outside of, his real intellectual con- viction ; for mark ! he is not at all inwardly convinced by his own specious reasonings. He gets beyond his intellectual sphere, is befogged, and lost. So after all we see that intellect is necessary to the highest moral action. We have had much talk of late concerning the cultivation of the intellect to the neglect of morality. But it seems that Shakespeare has here contrasted these two sides of liuman nature in the most effective manner, decidedly to the disadvantage of the latter. For Brutus is a man of intense moral susceptibility, yet of small mental calibre ; the result is that his mistakes and (w^hat is worse) his transgressions are appalling. Shake- speare has thus illustrated a truth which it will do no hurt to repeat now-a-days, that the content of a moral act can only be given by intelligence, and that the cultivation of intellect is in so far the cultivation of morality in its true sense. Hence our schools are our best, and indeed are fast becoming our only moral teachers. To be sure, submission does not always follow insight; men often know the right, but do it not: still we can hardly ascribe this to their knowing it, nor should we assert that they w^ere better of!" if they had known it. For in the one case there is a possibility of their becoming good men ; but if they have no comprehension of the good, it is imi^ossible. In ordinary times of civil repose, we should sa}^ of Brutus, what a noble citizen! JNo one (^ould be more ready to fulfil his duties to his family, liis fellow-men, and his country. But it must be recollected that these duties w ere the prescribed usages, customs, and beliefs, of his nation ; they were given to him, transmitted from hi^ ancestors. But when prescrip- tion no longer points out the way, such a man must fall, for he has no intellectual basis of action. Still the morality of mankind in general is prescriptive, and does not rest upon rational insight ; they follow the footsteps of their fathers. Hence it is that most people think that Brutus is the real hero (jf the i)lay, and that it is wrongly named. But this was The Tragedy of Jullws Ctv.i^nr. 247 certainly not Shakespeare's design, for it was very easy to- construct a drama in which Brutus shoukl api!)ear as trium- phant, by having it terminate at the assassination of Csesar with a grand flourish of daggers, frantic x)i"Oclamations of libert}^, and " sic semper tyrannis.'" Shakespeare, however, takes special pains not to do any such thing, but to show the triumph of Caesar's thought in the destruction of the conspi- rators. Still Brutus remains the favorite character with the multitude, because they do not and cannot rise above his stand-point, and to-day he is often taken as the great proto- type of all lovers of liberty. The effect of intellectual weakness combined with strong moral impulses appears, then, to be tlie meaning of this char- acter. It is amazing to observe its contradictions and utter want of steadiness of purpose ; nor are they at all exagger- ated by the poet. This man, who could assassinate his best friend for the public good, cannot, when a military leader, conscientiously levy contributions for his starving soldiers ; "For," says he, "I can raise no money by vile means." That is, he would sacrifice that very cause for which he committed the greatest crime known to man, to a moral punctilio. This may be moral heroism, but it is colossal stupidity. Further- more, in every instance in which Cassius and he difl'ered about the course to be pursued, Brutus was in the wrong. He, out of moral scruples, saved Antony, against the advice of Cassius ; this same Antony afterwards destroyed their army and with it their cause. Moreover, the battle of Phil- lippi, the fatal termination of the conflict, was fought in dis- regard of the judgment of Cassius. And finally he dies with a contradiction upon his lips, for he says that Cato was a coward for committing suicide, and then declares that he will never be taken captive to Rome alive, and shortly afterwards falls upon his own sword. Perhaps, however, he came to the conclusion that his country needed his death, for he said in his celebrated si)eech, *' I have the same dagger (which slew CrCsar) for myself when it shall please my country to need my death." This oft-quoted and favorite sentence seems to be usually regarded as expressing the very quintessence of moral sublimity and heroic self-sacrifice. But one naturally asks who is to be judge whether his country needs his death 248 The Tragedf/ of Julius Crrsar. — the couiitiy or himself? If the country, then he would be a criminal publicly condemned, and there would be no neces- sity for his dagger, since his country would furnish him both instrument and executioner free of charge. But if he was to be the judge himself, why did he commit such villainous acts that in his own opinion his country needed his death ? All this was intentional no doubt on the part of Shakespeare, for it comports toD well with the contradictory character of Bru- tus to admit of any other supposition. One imagines that if the old bard could have foreseen all the froth}^ vaporings and mock-sentimentality to which this innocent absurdity has given rise, he would still be laughing in his grave. Such is the true irony of the great poet, so much insisted on by some critics, which portrays the tinitude of individuals, classes, even whole historical periods, so adequately that they them- selves take delight in the picture. This difference in character between Brutus and Cassius must lead to a collision, and accordingly we liave the celebra- ted quarrel in the 4th Act. Hej-e we see the respective stand- points of the two men fully exhibited ; Brutus is haughty, insulting, and j)lumps himself upon his moral integrity, though it seems that he was ready to take and indeed asked for some of the money which Cassius had rai.3ed by "vile means"; Cassius, on the contrary, keeps restraining himself,, though exasperated iti the highest degree, and ultimately . leads the way to reconciliation. No personal feelings can dim to his eye the great end which he has in view, nothing must be allowed to i)ut it in Jeopardy; hence the quarrel^ which would otherwise doul)tless have terminated their friendship, if not have ended in a personal encounter, is healed as speedily as possible. There is a mightier collision pending which hushes all lesser strifes. A further contrast to Brutus is Antony. This loose reveller is true to his friend Csesar and avenges him, but the rigid moralist abandons and slays him. Antony is, moreover, a man of pleasure, and acts from impulse; Brutus jjretends to be a philosopher and to be guided by fixed principles. "I am no orator as Brutus is, but a plain, blunt man, that love my friend." Antony's highest end was personal devotion to one whom he loved ; he in nowise comprehends the move- The Tragedy of Julius Ccesar. 249 ment of either Cassius or Caesar. Thus both Antony and Brutus are quite on the same spiritual plane, and hence An- tony can justly reproach Brutus for his faithless conduct with a cogency which the latter can by no means answer : Witness the hole you made iu Cassar's heart Cry in Of long live, hail Ccesar! Yet Antony does most ample justice to the motive of Brutus, and seems to place all worthiness of an action in the motive, — a point of view, ir noi^ds hardly be said, purely moral and subj ecti ve : This was the noblest Roman of them all; All the conspirators, save only he, Did what they did in envy of ,^reat Caesar ; He only in a general honest thought And common good to all made one of them. These lines are often quoted as Shakespeare's actual opinion of Brutus ; but they are spoken by Antony, to whom they appropriately belong, and to nobody else. It is by no means certain that Shakespeare's own views are to be found always in the utterances of his characters. The dramatic poet ex- presses his convictions in the action, in the collision, and, above all, in the catastrophe. Judging by this standard, we should most decidedly aver that the above lines did not ex- press Shakespeare's personal ojjinion. Both Antony and Brutus, therefore, have quite the same intellectual stand- point, though dilfering much in their outward lives ; but the one was true to it, the other was not. Brutus ought to have acted as Antony, to be faithful to his deepest convictions, and to have remained friendly or at least indifferent to Cffi- sar. Cassius alone can intellectually slay Caesar. Such appears to be the general purport of this play. Much might be said upon its formal excellence — the poetic beauty, rhetorical finish, and unusual clearness of the language, mak- ing it a favorite with many who read nothing else of Shake- speare— the logical arrangement of the parts, the happy con- secution of motives ; but all this we shall leave to our reader to follow up at his leisure. Some of Shakespeare's fairest gems of characterization are found in the minor personages of the play, as Portia, the absolute type of wifehood, and Lu- cius, the faithful slave ; but their basis is plain and needs not 250 The Tragedy of J alius Cicsar. to be specially developed. Moreover, the mediations em- ployed are deserving of the most careful study on account of their truth and profundity, as when for example in the third act the Poet makes popular oratory the means by which the tide is turned against the conspiiators, and thus assigns its place as one of the chief political instrumentalities in the ancient and modern world. Also those curious supernatural manifestations, as the cry of the soothsayer, "Beware the ides of March," the ai)pearance of the ghost of Cfesar, the presence of a lion in the streets, the wrathful signs of the heavens, seem to demand some rational explanation as well as the strange anthropological phenomena, as the presenti- ments of CiCsar and Brutus, and the dreams of Calpurnia and Cinna the Poet. Here is a side which Shakespeare al- waj^'S elaborates in full, but which can be best treated in a separate paper. The object at present is to bring into prom- inence the ethical world of Shakespeare and its immense sig- nilicance, for these same collisions are taking place to-day, and indeed their true solution constitutes the comprehension of and mastery over the practical world. To recapitulate ; there are three leading moments in the drama: 1. Caesar in the consummation of his world-histori- cal career, on the pinnacle of his power and glory ; 2. The reaction of the State against him headed by Cassius ; 3. The negation of this reaction, the restoration and absolute valid- ity of the Cjesarean movement. Hence we see that Cjesar is the real hero, and that the piece is justlj" entitled "Julius CfBsar." We also see, I think, that the collision is between the World-Spirit and the Nation, and that in this struggle three typical characters participate, forming a complete cyclus of characterization. Cfusar represents the world- historical stand- jjoint, Cassius the jjolitical, Brutus the moral. CcSsar perishes ; the ancient national sentiment rises up for a moment and destroys the individual, for, being of flesh and blood, an assassin may rush upon him and stab him to the heart ; but his thought is not thus doomed to perish. Next to him comes Cassius, whose great mistake was that he still had faith in his country ; a pardonable error, if any, to mor- tals! He did not, and perhaps could not, rise above the purely political point of view ; to him the State was the ulti- The Tragedy of Julius Cmsar. 251 mate efhical principle of the Universe. Hence he did not com- prehend the world-historical niovemeht represented by Ca3- sar, but collided with it and was destroj^ed. To me a painful, melancholy character ; with all his greatness, devotion, and intelligent activitjs still finite and sliort-sighted. The mis- take of Brutus is that he had anything to do with the matter at all — that he took part, or at least a leading part, in this revolution. The collision lay wholly beyond his mental ho- rizon; hence he represents nothing objective, is the bearer of no grand ethical principle, like Csesar and Cassius. He pre- sumed to lead when he was intellectually in total darkness, trusting alone to his own good intentions. We do not blame him because he was ignorant, but because he did not know that he was ignorant. Every rational being must at least comprehend its own limits, must know that it does not know. We may laud the motive but lament the deed; still man, as endowed with Reason and Universality, cannot run away from his act and hide himself behind his intention, but must take the inherent consequences of his deed in their total cir- cumference. Brutus is no doubt the sphinx of the play, and has given much trouble to critics on account of the contradictions of his character. He seems both moral and immoral — to be actu- ated by the noblest motives for the public good, yet can give no. rational ground for his act. Indeed we are led to believe that his vanit}^ was so swollen by the flattery of Cassius that it hurried him unconsciously beyond the i^ale of his convic- tions. Still Brutus was undoubtedh^ a good citizen, a good husband, and a good man. But any one of these three rela- tions may come into conflict with the others ; which, then, is to be followed? If a man has not subordinated tliese spheres into a system — which can only be done by Intelligence — he cannot tell what course to pursue. Sometimes he may follow one, sometimes another, for in his mind they all possess equal validity. Hence such a person can only be inconsistent, va- cillating and contradictory in his actions ; and such a person was Brutus — a good, moral man, who recognized all duties, but did not comprehend their limitations, and hence fell be- neath their conflict. ( 252 ) HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY OF ART. Tr.'.nslated from Uic second volume of Hegel's jEsthhtics, by Missb. .V. Longwell. Chivalry. — II. Love. The second sentiment that plays a dominant part in the representations of romantic art is love. {a) If the fundamental character of honor is the personal snbjectivity as it manifests itself in its absolute indepen- dence, the highest degree of love, on the contrary, is self- forgetfulness, the identification of the subject with an indi- vidual of the other sex. It is the yielding of its indepen- dent consciousness, its particular individuality, which is for the first time compelled to have its self-knowledge in the consciousness of another. In this respect, love and honor are opposed to each other. But conversely we can regard love as the realization of a principle which already exists in hon- or, in so far as it is the necessity of honor to see the infinitude of person which he assumes recognized by another. This recognition is first genuine and total, when not only my per- sonality in the abstract, or in a concrete, particular, and therefore limited sense, is honored by others, but when I, entirel}^, with all that I am and comprehend in myself, as I have been, am, and shall be, pervade the consciousness of another, constitute its real will, thought, tendency, and most intimate possession. Then this other lives only in me, as I live only in him. Each becomes in this complementary unity first for himself, and they place their w^hole world and soul in this identity. In this resj)ect there is the same intrinsic infinity of the subject which gives to love its importance in romantic art, an importance which is still enhanced through the higher wealth that the idea of love comprehends. Love does not depend upon refiection and the casuistry of the understanding, as may often be the case with honor, but finds its origin in emotion, and has at the same time, where sex is concerned, the foundation of spiritualized natural rela- tions. However, this diff'erence is essential only because the individual puts into this union his soul, the spiritual and infi- nite element of his being. This renouncing of self in order HegeVs Philosoplnj of Art. 253 to be ideiititied witli another — this devotion, this disinterest- edness, in which the subject iinds again the plenitude of his being — this self-forgetfulness, so tliat the lover exists not, cares not for himself, but finds the sources of his being in another, — constitute the infinite character of love. And its' chief beautj is that it does not remain mere impulse and feel- ing;; but imao-ination, under the charm of love, creates its own world, makes all else, that otherwise pertains to interest, surroundings, purposes of the actual life and being, an orna- ment of this feeling, draws all into this circle, and only in reference to this assigns to anything a value. Particularly in feminine characters is love most beautiful, since this sacrificing, this disinterestedness, is carried by them to its highest degree. They conform the whole intel- lectual and moral life to this emotion, find in it alone an anchor to existence, and, if deprived of love by adversity, vanish as a light that is extinguished at the first rough breath. In this subjective fervor of emotion, love does not appear in classic art, and generally it only makes its appearance as a kind of manifestation of subordinate moment, or only by the side of sensuous enjoj^ment. In Homer either no great stress is placed upon love, or it appears in its most worthy form in domestic life, as, for example, the conjugal fidelity of Penelope, or, as the tender solicitude of the wife and mother, in Andromache, or otherwise in moral relations. On the con- trary, the tie that unites Paris and Helen is acknowledged as immoral — it is the cause of the horrors and necessity of the Trojan war; and the love of Achilles for Briseis has little internality and depth of emotion, for Briseis is a slave, sub- missive to the hero's will. In the Odes of Sappho, the lan- guage of love rises indeed to lyric enthusiasm, 3^et it is rather the expression of a flame which consumes, than that of a sen- timent which penetrates to the depths of the heart and fills the soul. Love appears in another phase in the graceful lit- tle songs of Anacreon, It is a more serene, more general pleasure, which knows neither infinite sorrows, nor the ab- sorption of the entire existence in a single sentiment, nor the submission of an oppressed and languishing soul. It par- takes freely of immediate pleasure without attaching to the exclusive possession of precisely this person and no other — 254 HegeVs PUlosoxjny of Art. a demand whit'h is as foreign to its thought as the monastic- resohition entirely to ignore the rehition of sex. The high Tragedy of the Ancients, likewise, does not know the passion of love in its romantic meaning. Especially in iEschylus and Sophocles it claims no real interest. For although Antigone is the destined wife of H^emon, and he^ unable to save his beloved, destroys himself for her sake, yet he manifests before Creon only objective relations, and not the subjective power of his passion, which he does not even experience in the acceptation of an ardent modern lover. Euripides treats love as a more real pathos — in Phjedra, for example ; yet even here it appears as a crirjiinal aberration, caused by ardor of blood and by a troubled mind, as incited by Venus, who wishes to destroy Hyppolytus because this young prince refuses to sacrifice upon her altars. So we have indeed in the Venus di Medici a plastic representation of love which heaves nothing to be desired, in delicacy and perfec- tion of form, but the expression of the subjective. Such as romantic art demands is entirely lacking. The same is true in Roman poetry. After the destruction of the republic, and in the accompanying laxity of morals, love appears more or less as a sensuous pleasure. In the Middle Ages, on the con- trary, although Petrarch, for example, regarded li'is sonnets as trilles,and based his reputation upon his Latin poems and works, yet he immortalized himself by this ideal love, which under the Italian heaven is united in an ardent imagination with the religious sentiment. The sublime inspiration of Dante also had its source in his love for Beatrice. This love appeared in him as a religious love, while his energy and boldness attained the energy of a religious artistic intuition, through which he dared that which no one before him had ventured, namely, to exalt himself as supreme judge of the world, and to assign men to Hell, to Purgatory, and to Heaven. As a contrast to this exaltation, Boccacio represents love, in its vivacity of passion, frivolous, without morality ; while he brings before our eyes, in his various tales, the customs of his time and country. In the German Minnesingers love ap- pears sentimental, tender without copiousness of imagination, playful, melancholy, and monotonous. With the Spaniards it is imaginative in expression, chivalric, subtile sometimes HegeVs Philosophy of Art. 255 in seeking and defending its rights and duties, of which it makes so many points of personal honor; it is also enthusi- astic when displayed in its highest brilliancy. Among the modern French it becomes, on the contrary, more gallant, inclined to frivolity, a sentiment created for poetry. Some- times it is pleasure without passion, sometimes passion with- out pleasure, a sublimated entirely reflexive sentiment and susceptibility.. {b) The world and real life are full of conflicting interests. On one side stands society with its actual organization, do- mestic life, civil and political relations, law, justice, customs^ etc. ; and in opposition to this positive reality rises love, a passion which germinates in noble, ardent souls, which now unites itself with religion, now subordinates it, forgets it even, and, regarding itself alone the essential, indeed the only or highest necessity of life, is able not only to determine to re- nounce all else and to flee with the beloved into a wilderness, but may besides deliver itself to all excesses, even to the re- nouncing of human dignity. This opposition cannot fail to occasion numerous collisions, for the other interests of life also make valid their demands and rights, and thereby affect love in its pretensions to supremacy. (1) The flrst and most frequent collision which we have to mention, is the conflict between love and honor. Honor has in itself the same infinity as love, and may assume a signifi- cance that is an absolute hindrance in the way of love. The duty of honor may demand the sacrifice of love? In a certain class of society, for example, it would be incompatible with honor to love a woman of inferior rank. The difference in rank is the necessary result of the nature of things ; and, besides, it is admitted. Now, since secular life is not yet re- newed through the complete conception of true freedom, in which position, vocation, etc., of the subject, as such, disap- pear, so it is always more or less birth which assigns to man his rank and position ; and these conditions are still regarded as absolute and eternal by, although not through, honor, in so far as it makes its own position an affair of honor. (2) But secondly, besides honor, the permanent substantial powers themselves, state interests, patriotism, domestic du- ties, etc., may also conflict with love and forbid its realiza- 256 HegeVs Philosophy of Art. tion. Especially in modern representations, in wliicli the objective relations of life have already attained complete va- lidity, is this a very popular theme. Love then appears as a poweuful right of the subjective nature, so opposed to the other rights and duties that the heart itself banishes these duties as subordinate, or acknowledges them, and comes into conflict with itself and the power of its own passion. The Maid of Orleans, for example, rests upon this last collision. (3) Yet, thirdly, there may exist in general external rela- tions and impediments which oppose themselves to love : the general course of events, the prose of life, misfortunes, pas- sion, prejudice, wilfulness of others, and events of various kinds. Consequently much hatred is often involved, because the perversity, the crudeness, the wild fierceness of foreign passions, are placed in opposition to the tender beauty of love. Particularly in recent Dramas, Tales, and Romances, we often see the same external collisions. They interest chiefly tlirougli our sympathy with the sufferings, hopes and disappointments of the unhappy lovers. The conclusion, according as it is happy or unhappy, satisfies or moves us. Sometimes these productions simply entertain us. This kind of conflict however, which depends upon mere contingency, is of a subordinate nature. (c) Love presents in all these respects, it is true, an ele- vated character in so far as it remains in general not onl}^ an affection of the sexes for each other, but manifests in itself a rich, beautiful, noble nature ; and is, in its unity with others, living, active, brave, self-sacrificing. But romantic love has likewise its limits ; namely, there is wanting in its compre- hension the general and universal. It is only the personal sense of the individual subject that shows itself satisfied, not with permanent interests and the objective value of hun>an existence — with the well-being of the family, of the state, and of native land — with professional duties, freedom, and reli- gion,— but aspires only to find itself reflected in another, and to have its passion shared. This comprehension corresponds neither to its formal ardor, nor truly to the totality which must be in itself a concrete individuality. In the family, in marriage even, in a moral point of view both public and pri- vate, the subjective perception exists as such, and the union HegeVs Philosopliy of Art. 257 with exactly this and no other individual, may not be the principal thing upon which it depends. But in romantic love all turns upon this principle, the mutual love of two indivi- duals. Indeed, only this or that individual exists who linds his subjective particular ty in the contingency of caprice. To every one his beloved appears as to the maiden her lover, always incomparable ; each hnds the other the supreme type of beaut}' and perfection. But if it is true that each one makes of the beloved a Venus or something more, it happens that there are many who pass as the same, for, as indeed all know, there are in the world many excellent maid- ens, pretty or good, who all, or at least the majority, find their admirers, lovers, and husbands, to whom they appear beautiful, virtuous, and lovely. Only this exclusive and ab- solute preference is purely an affair of the heart, an entirely personal choice ; and the unlimited pertinacity indispensable in finding in just this one his life and his highest conscious- ness, proves itself the eternal choice of necessity. There is recognized in this manifestation the higher freedom of the subjectivity and its abstract choice — freedom, not merely, as the Phjedra of Euripides, for pathos, but concerning the abso- lutely individual will from which it proceeds ; choice seems, at the same time, a caprice and stubbornness of the particu- lar individual. Therefore collisions with love retain ever a phase of con- tingency and authorized wantonness, especially when love conflicts with substantial interests; because it is the sub- jectivity as such which opposes its demands, in and for themselves invalid, to that which must make the claim to its own reality dependent upon recognition. The personages in the high Tragedies of the Ancients, Agamemnon, Cly- temnestra, Orestes, ffidipus, Antigone, Creon, etc., have like- wise, it is true, an individual purpose ; but the reality, the pathos, that was the motive of their acts is of absolute au- thority, and precisely on that account in itself also of general interest. The destiny that befalls them as the result of their acts does not affect us because there is an unhappy destiny, but because there is an unhappy being that at the same time loves absolutely ; while pathos, which affects not until it has obtained satisfaction, has a necessary significance. If the Vol.vi.— 17 258 Hegel as Publicist. guilr of Clytemn^sti'ca is not punished in this particular case, if the wrontj: which Antigone as sister experienced is not re- dressed, then there is in itself a wrong. But these sufferings of love, these heart-rending liopes, this being in love, these intinire anxieties which a lover experiences, this eternal feli- city and blessedness that he imagines, are not in themselves of general interest, but pertain only to himself. E\ery man indeed has a heart for love and the right to find happiness in loving; but there is no injustice done if he ex- actly in this case, among these and those circumstances, in respect to precisely this maiden, does not attain his aim. For there is no necessity that he interest himself in this capri- cious maiden, and that we should be interested in an affair so accidental which has neither extension nor universality. This is a phase of coldness that manifests itself in the devel- opment of this ardent passion. HEGEL AS PUBLICIST. Translated from the Gorman of Dr. K. Kosenkkanz, by G. S. Hall. When compendiums are printed, their style is usually mea- gre and skeleton like ; the paragrai)hs of the Hegelian Ency- clopedia, on the contrary, preserve for us a lively, didactic prose, in the intensive fullness of which it is throughout felt that a high geniality has imposed such a limitation upon itself with freedom. Behind these well-weighed words, the rich spirit may be conjectured which is able to broaden each into an entire world of meaning and to defend each in its own peculiar signilicance. The Heidelberg professors had made the "Heidelberg Year- book'' a critical organ, which, at the time of Hegel's sojourn there, was at the acme of its highest prosperity. At first it represented the stand-point of Romanticism, which at the time of the French dominion had a national patriotic significance. Daub, Creuzer, and Goerres, who had previously' been united in the editorship of the " Studien," exercised at first the great- est influence upon it. At the time of Hegel, Paulus had as- Hegel as Pahlidst. 259 sumed its editorship. He procured Hegel's coopemtioii. The latter furnished only two criticisms, which however for phi- losophy as well as for himself were of great signilicance. One was upon Jacobi, the other upon the W tirtumberg Con- stitution. In the "Critical Journal,'* which he published with Schel- ling, he had sharply attacked the stand point of Jacobi. iS^ow, as Jacobi, at the close of his career, began to publish his col- lective works, he desired to explain himself once more to him, and, aside from all positive differences, to become, out of re- spect for his endeavors, reconciled with him. This he could not do without atfecting Schilling, who in the meantime had come to a most violent rupture with Jacobi. Every recogni- tion of Jacobi on the part of Hegel, although it be cxualihed, must ofl'end Schelling, however much Hegel might empdiasize Schelling's scientific right as opposed to Jacobi. This is a point which for the further relations of both philosophers is so often overlooked. That which is, however, often still more overlooked, was that in this critique Hegel was necessitated to pronounce with reference to atheism. The reproach of atheism was first raised against Ficlite by the government of Saxony — against Schelling by a philoso- pher, by Jacobi. The latter saw in Schelling's philosophy renewed Spinozism. Against this Hegel had decidedly pro- nounced in the "Phenomenology of Mind," and had expressly recognized the Christian religion as absolutely true. Later, in his Logic, he had subjected Spinozism to extended criti- cism and had shown its untenableness. He accorded right, therefore, to Jacobi in finding Spinozism defective, because, in the conception of the Absolute, it suppresses the moment of subjectivity. It follows hence that substance is to be appre- hended, not merely as being and essence, but also as subject; i.e. not merely as causal necessity, but also as self-determin- ing and self-conceiving freedom. The introduction to the third part of his Logic, which he entitled Subjective Logic, has no other purpose. Hegel must, therefore, admit to Jacobi that he could find no satisfaction in Spinozism. It is impos- sible for one to express himself clearer than Hegel has here done upon the point whether Grod is to be known only as substance, or at the same time as subject. The Absolute is 260 Hegel as Publicist. not as it were only so far subject as it becomes so in plants, animals, and man, but ir is subject in and for itself. When Jacobi, however, affirmed that we could apprehend the Absolute onl}^ in faith, only in feeling and not in thought, in self-conscious conception, Hegel denied it in the most de- cisive way. .lacobi had even advanced to the paradoxical proi")osition that all demonstrative philosophy must lead to atheism. Ilegel, on the other hand, proved the necessity of proof if the question of science was at all involved. The ten- derness with which Hegel treated Schelling as well as Jacobi, without in the least sacrilicing positive sharpness or his own dignity, makes this critique one of the most exemplary po- lemics. While he allowed no doubt to remain that he appre- hended the Absolute in and for Itself as subject, there was offered to him, on the other hand, an opportunity to express himself in a popular manner upon the conception of the state, which he had done in the short paragraphs of the Encyclope- dia only in very general and often dark outlines. Now came the proceedings of the Diet of Wiirtemberg upon the new constitution of the state, vvhich, through the confederacy of the Rhine, had grown into a kingdom. The state, even after the war of emancipation, was still a con- glomeration of the most diverse j)articular rights. It needed to be transformed upon the principle of the freedom of per- son and of property ; the equality of all citizens before the law ; the uniform distribution of the burdens of taxation ; freedom of religion and freedom of the press ; the legal par- ticipation of the citizens in legislation, and the responsibility of ministers. The kings of Wiirtemberg recognized this necessity, and laid the plan of a constitution before the aris- tocracy. It met with determined opposition, because it must of course demand the surrender of many privileges. These were named by the aristocracy " good old German rights," and the royal presumption in proposing to sacrifice them to the common good was rejected with indignation, while the constitution was suspected of being a means of despotism. It was not only the nobility who were hostile, but especially the guild of advocates and notaries, who feared that under a new constitution they would lose much of their influence and of their incomes, because the incessant collisions of multitu- Hegel as PuhUcist. 261 dinous privileges was the occasion of innumerable suits at law, by conducting which they were able to watch over and phinder the rest of the citizens. After violent contests, in which all the animosity of political passions was let loose, the kingdom finally accomplished its work. The proceedings were printed, and Hegel undertook their criticism. So far as the public was concerned, he here entered a sphere of activity which was entirely new, fur the question was now not upon the judgment of a philosophical system by any single author, but upon the political act of two princes of a neighboring state, of the same stock as that from which Hegel was de- scended, the capital of which was his early home, and the constitution of which, as early as the close of the preceding century, he had made the subject of an unpublished reformi- tory article. Upon which side should he, as a philosopher, take his stand in his critique ? Upon the side of the so-called good old right of the aristocracy ? Impossible ; for this right was the prerogative of feudalism, the privilege of the guild, the purchased monoj)oly of the rich. He must, therefore, take his stand with the kings, for they were, in this case, the rep- resentatives of rational freedom, of the true idea of the state. That this took place in a small German state does not af- fect its importance. The reproach has been made that Hegel gloritied the pett}^ Schwabian kingdom with Asiatic Hattery. The inhabitants of "Wurtemberg themselves, later, became proud of their constitution, and the contests in their cham- bers have exercised a politically-shaping influence upon all Crermany. The names of U bland and Pfizer were as popular in Berlin as in Stuttgart. Hegel always had strong political instincts. It was natural that the occurrences in his narrow fatherland should interest him intensely. He was patriotic so far as to recognize the independence of nationality as one of the essential conditions of a healthy state life ; but he was not patriotic in the polemic, fanatic sense, the G-ermanic ten- dency of which proceeded from Fichte, Fries, and others, who attempted to organize the student corps into an exclusively German party. In his opening address at Heidelberg, Hegel had emphasized the maintenance of our nationality itself as a chief moment, through which the higher advancement of scientific thought might be secured among us. No modern 26-2 Hegel as Publicist. state can make national purism its principle, because the purity of race? is everywhere impaired. Germans have everywhere come in contact with Roman, Celtic and Slavic elements, and the reason of the state must subject itself to the peculiarity of its population. The Jews, scattered among all nations, are careful that this be not forgotten. That which in his youth had so interested Hegel in the French revolu- tion, y'l/.. the creation of a state in accordance with the Idea, now attracted him strongly in the proceedings in his father- land. In France it was the people who wrested the modern state from the kingdom, while in Wiirtemberg it was the kingdom which must win the free constitution from the j^eo- ple. In the introduction to his critique he delineated this noteworthy situation in a masterly way, such as was possi- ble only from a profound understanding of history. Hegel's style has nothing of what is wont to be called rhetoric in the ordinary sense, for all phrases, all Ciceronian ornate et eojyi- ose dicere. was opposed to his strictly matter-of-fact nature. The German language stood at his command in rare compass, to give to his thoughts the most happy and manifold utter- ance. The dramatic vividness with which he depicted the course of the proceedings of the Diet is incomparable. The loftiness of his style passes over now and then to the bitter comique. with which he lashes the hypocrisy of that egoism which perverts the words fatherland, freedom, right, lidelity, and uses them against laws and princes in order to conceal its own private interests. The case which Hegel treated as a concrete one is the same in all history. It is the conHict of the progress of freedom with j^ositive right, which over asainst the self-consciousness of more cultured reason has become a wrong, and struggles against dissolution because it has hitherto been accredited as a recognized chartered right. On this point Hegel had a perfectly philosophical conscious- ness, and the incisive words with which he expressed it will ever renewedly awaken the liveliest interest in the historian and the pliilosopher. Those who know the course of real aifairs will not wonder that the passion of the reactionary party which Hegel, with his firm frankness and truly states- manlike superiority had found so sensitive, turned upon him with rage because he defended the princes in their constitu- Hegel, Prussia, and the Philosophy of Right. 263 tional endeavors, and abused him as a servile man. Hegel has never uttered a word respecting this suspicion; he was above such insinuations of the crowd. It is, however, unpre- cedented that now, after several decades, his enemies are not weary of i^ersecuting him, on account of this critique, as an, anti-popular servant of kings, without being able to adduce a single actual proof for such bitter disparagement. Even a historian like Gervinus, in his history of mod- ern times, is not free from this acridity which has become traditional. Dr. Haym's groundless aspersion of Hegel, in his work "Hegel and His Time," as if he would have pur- chased, by his criticism of the government of Wiirtemberg, the chancellorship of the University of Tubingen, I have an- swered in my " Hegel's Apology before Dr. Haym." The proof which I demanded for the foundation of such an insin- uation has not yet to my knowledge been furnished. Since the July revolution, Germans have made great pro- gress in political science. In this they were very backward when Hegel wrote. Hegel lacks the declamatory pathos in which Fichte was so great, as well as the diplomatic dex- terity of a Genz ; but the philosophic sobriety which perme- ates his political inspiration imparts to his language, in its apt acuteness, a peculiar nobility. The great philosopher enchants us ever by the exalted naivety of his soul, which knows no other cultus than the truth ; and this naivety, re- plete with a deep infusion of history, makes the philosopher a classic publicist, who judges his age, and knows how, fit- tingly, to say to it what it has to do. HEGEL, PRUSSIA, AND THE PHILOSOPHY OF RIGHT. The local spirit of the beautiful cit}^ of Heidelberg seems to favor the so-called positive sciences rather than philoso- phy, and Spinoza indulged perhaps a proper instinct when he refused the call of the elector of the Palatinate to a pro- fessorship there. And yet Hegel's efficiency during the two years, 1816 and 1817, in which he lectured there, was of com- paratively great significance. He prepared, however, in 1818 to go to Berlin, with which he had previously had relations. In this, as in all that is historical, the element of chance can be discerned, but for Prussia as well as for Hegel it was 264 Hegel, Prussia, and the P/u'losop7n/ of Rigid. necessity. Prussia is the philosophic state par excellence in Gei'uumy. whicli has allowed no great German philosopher since Leibnitz to remain outside it. The chair which Ficlite had occupied liad been vacant since 1814. Solger proposed Hegel for the place. In the biograph}'- of Fries the corre- spondence is given whicli DeWette carried on with him con- cerning this call. Fries wished especially to come to Berlin. DeWette, his theological disciple, left no means untried to influence the majority of the Senate in his favoi-. In this elec- toral contest, and the passionate agitations which attended it, tlie two parties may be seen which in the University of Berlin opposed one another even more resolutely, and in which was reflected the great antithesis whicli pervaded the entire age. At the beginning of the century, Hegel had almost abhor- red Prussia on account of its bureaucracy and its court ser- vice, and had foreseen the fate of the Prussian army at Jena. But this state had undergone a new birth which showed that it yet bore within itself a great future. This future is at the same time the future of Germany itself, for the Ultramonta- nists and the South-Germans may abuse Prussia as much as they will ; still Germany will not again get rid of Prussia, for ir is the only German state that can save united Germany and conduct it to a higher national plane. ''^ The Congress of Vienna would not round off Prussia; it gave to it the Rhine province as an enclave between Hessia, Nassau, Rhinic Bava- ria, France, Belgium and Holland, and thus imposed \\\)0i\ it the Watch on the Rhine. Eventually, the Rhinic province with Westphalia could be again snatched from Prussia, and be declared an independent kingdom for any prince. Prussia must make vast endeavors so to organize its own military power that it could be ready to commence war with France at way moment. It was thus that it became stronger than its. intriguing enemies had intended. Its geographical position brought it into immediate territorial contact with Russia as well as with France, as was the case with no other German state. It bordered on Austria and (with the exception of Wiirtemberg and Baden) nearly all the German middle and * This was wrilteii iu ]8(j«. — Ed. Hegel, Prussia, and the Philosophy of Right. 265- smaller states. Although the wasp-like contour of the Pius- sian state was made the occasion of much reproach, 3'et it was from the very fact of its many-sided border-contacts that it rose to an influence over all Germany, which rendered the foundation of the Zollverein possible as the first real unifi- cation of the German states. With the Rhine it had also- taken into its domain the last of the great streams which flow from south to north into the sea. Cologne, under the Prus- sian administration, rose to renewed prosperity as a commer- cial city. Besides the encouragement of material interests^ Prussia had undertaken through the Rhine provinces the- difficult task of winning the confidence of the other Rhinie provinces, for the intensity of the prejudices with which these^ were then filled against the Prussian government can scarcely yet be correctly represented, Hegel entered the Prussian state as a stranger. He felt in Berlin that an intense thought-life pervaded the entire atmo- sphere. This predominance of North-German reflection im- pressed him favorably with Berlin, because it responded to- his character as a philosopher. He unduly transferred the impression which Berlin made upon him to the entire Prus- sian state, just as most Frenchmen and Englishmen are wont to do who conceive the one-sided views of Berlin to be the- exhaustive expression of the entire Prussian community. Hegel began to interest himself in Prussia as a model state, but as a philosopher he cherished still another ideal which by no means tallied with the actual condition of Prussia. That, which the great Prussian statesmen and military he- roes of that epoch strove for, surpassed, in its tendency, the Hegelian conception of the state, in the greater participation which it allowed to the people in legislation. In a state where the system of defence obliged all citizens without ex- ception to defend the land from invasion, they would admit all to participate in legislation. In a state where munici2:)al communities administered their own affairs, the question of a bureaucratic omnipotence of the ministers as in France could not arise. In a state where rights of seigniory and tute- lage were removed, where the possession of land and industry were left free, where access to all state offices was conditioned. ^&6 Hegel, Prussia, and the Philosophy of Right. only upon proof of competency, — in such a state mediaeval -conditions, forms, institutions, could find no longer a footing. Rejuvenated, well-matured Prussia was built from 1810 to 1815 upon democratic foundations, which were given by the monarch himself. The elevation of the entire system of instruction by Wilhelm von Humboldt and von Altenstein, the establishment of the universities of Berlin, Breslau and Bonn, and the more munilicent endowment and equipment of those at Halle and Konigsberg, was accomplished in a democratic sense, for Prussia had made attendance at schools compulsory upon all. But after Napoleon had been conquered, and espe- cially after his death, the reaction of the aristocracy and hier- archy against the political establishments of Prussia grew stronger even in Prussia itself. It resulted in that sad policy of restoration which now we are wont to call, from its most prominent representative, the policy of Metternich. This pol- icy invaded Prussia, and began to imprint upon the govern- ment a political character of distrust for the people. The immediate result was that the people found no legislative representation, but provincial diets were established in their stead. The combinations of the student-corps furnished occasion and pretext to the governments to persecute the democratic movement as revolutionary. Fichte, in his discourses in Ber- lin on the German nation, had declared the then passing gene- ration incapable of achieving a renaissance by reason of the general depravity, and he called on the better trained young men to save the nation. These young men had actually fol- lowed with enthusiasm the call of the king into the war with France, and, thirsting for freedom and braving death, had shed their blood upon the battle-held. They dreamed of a great united German kingdom with an emperor at its head. In songs of wondrous beauty they sang of the indissoluble fra- ternity of Germans, and of the future glory of the new king- dom which was to arise from it. And not youths alone grew eloquent over the resurrection of the old Barbarossa, whom the saga makes to slumber with sword in hand, now in Kyflf- haiiser on the golden An, now under the mountain near Salz- burg; but many men joined this movement, and, old and Hegel, Prussia, and tlie Philosopliy of Right. 267 young, united in societies for plij^sical cultun? in gymnastic halls and in Turner expeditions. The danger of this tendency lay in over-exciting patriotic feeling, and in over-stimulating national purism for want of deeper political conceptions. The attack on President von Ibell and the murder of Kotzebue by Sand were outbursts of an enthusiasm which had degenerated to fanaticism. As the student-corps conceived it to be a holy resolve to murder Kotzebue, they might with the same pro- priety resolve to remove b}- assassination a prince who was displeasing to them. Princes trembled upon their unsteady thrones before such ^ secret tribunal, and the military trials filled not only for- tresses with their sacrifices, but occasioned, after the reso- lutions of Carlsbad, a fanatical tendencj^ to censure all liber- alistic movements. Hegel, no doubt, harmonized with the .governments in their opposition to these movements and ex- cesses of the students ; he certainly never approved of the frequently terrible severity of the Inquisition. "What could he do ? He sought to save the young by oflering to them rational conceptions of right and of the state. Many in ma- turer 3^ears have thanked him for reconciling them with the present by his instruction — by explaining to them, instead of the Utopian ideal of their morbid aspiration, the organism of the state. While he won the love of very many sturdy mem- bers of the student-corps, he remained filled with inappeasa- ble indignation against the leaders of the corps and especially toward Fries. He published in 1821 a text-book on the Philosophy of Kight and of the State, in which he more widely developed the brief hints in the paragraphs of his Encyclopedia. As in the latter so here in this presentation he assumed a more dogmatic tone, and in the numerous remarks which were directed against views which deviated from his own, a more polemic tone than that which he had allowed to pervade the dialectic genesis of the Phenomenology and the Logic. The didactic end he had in view might justify this form, for he sought only to establish a foundation for his lectures ; but it remains a subject of regret that he treated so important material only in the form of categorical dictation, for the element of proof became therefor too meagre. Within this limit his language, 208 Hegeh Prussia, and the Flulosopliy of Riglif. like tilt' styh" of inscriptions on monuments, is uniformly significant. Since he presented the dialectic here only in the general construction, he became for the lirst time intelligible to the public at large, which has an apj)etite only for the results of thought. It is quite inconceivable how the construction of servility to the Prussian government can be put upon this work, as if in his paragraphs he had copied the Prussian state as it wa» empirically presented to him. Hegel did not l)ecome false in Prussia to that conception of the state which he had defended in Bavaria against the Wiirtemberg reaction. Prussia was then not a constitutional state ; there was no publicity or oral procedure in the maintenance of justice, no freedom of the press, no equality of citizens before the law, no participation of the people in legislation or assent on their part to taxa- tion,— and all this Hegel taught as a philosophic necessity. When in renuirks he lashed the caricatures which often dis- torted the idea in the field of every-day reality, even this was ([uite in order, and even this contributed to clarify concep- tions. In order to bring him under the suspicion of the crowd, tiiese caricatures, painted with satirical colors, have been ex- cerpted and peddled about as his own delinitions. That wiiich distinguished Hegel from preceding philoso- l)hers was the conception of constitutional monarchy as the absolute form of the state. He well knew that a state could pass through different constitutional forms, but as a philoso- pher he considered this the onl}^ form which fully correspond- ed to th(^ idea of freedom. It is a very common opinion that a philosopher can only be a republican in politics, although it is generally added by way of lament that the imperfection,, and especially the moral weakness of man, renders the reali- zation of a republic very difficult. Hegel contradicted this current view by the emphasis with which he insisted on mon- archy. Many make this a ground of reproach against either the profundity, or, still w^orse, against the sincerity, of \\m thought, lie was, however, in thorough earnest with his deduction of monarchy, and he had taught it in Jena just as well as in Heidelberg and Berlin. He had a rich political experience, having made himself acquainted with the most diverse constitutions, including those of the republics at Bern Hegel. Prussia, and the Philosopliy of Right. 269 and Frankfurt. He had witnessed the rise of the French re- public and its transition to despotism, the fall of the Polish and the German elective monarchies as well as the impotence of hereditary monarchies, which cherished only dynastic ego- tism and which had never been organically united with the people. He did not, however, derive his proof of the neces- sity of hereditary monarchy from experience or from com- parative studies, but from the conception of the sovereignty of the state, which must exist self-consciously in a real per- son and which must be securely removed from the instability of parties. Such an influx of nature into history would be fortuitous and unphilosophical, if, in the first place, the royal family itself had not been mediated historically, so that its call to the governmental functions was a natural fact ; and secondly, if the ruler had not the freedom to renounce the throne if he felt himself uncalled to rule. Montesquieu was the first who, in his Esprit des Lois, made the conception of a constitutional government popular and put forward the view of the separate organization of the powers of govern- ment. Hegel is the philosopher who taught, not like K&-nt, the general necessity of the representative system, but who identified the idea of constitutional monarchy with that of the fully developed, rational state. He was very far from deifying the person of the prince in the sense of the abstract legitimist theory, for he often said that in a well-organized state ver}^ little depended on the s]3ecial excellence of the ru- ler; he was only the essential conclusion of the ascending series, the personal summation of the entire state — the dot on the "i," which without it would be a mere perpendicular mark. His tendency to relegate the person and the individu- ality of rulers to relative indifterence was exhibited in his polemic with Haller, who sought with his restorational pol- icy to make rulers, by the grace of God, the private posses- sors of land and people. If we compare this legal and political philosophy of Hegel with the principles which he had earlier advocated at Jena, we shall find the same fundamental idea, viz. that of realizing a system of ethics in the state, and shall at the same time see how untiringly he had labored, and revised his labor, in the development of this idea. In his original system, the plan \ 270 HcgeJ^ Prussia, and the Philosoph]/ of Rigid. Aviis at the same time the most simple and the most inclusive^ because there he omitted the contraposition of h^gality and morality. He tliere divided jurisprudence into three parts. In the lirst, he treated the elementar}^ distinctions of rights viz. freedt)m, personality, labor, acquisition of property, ex- change and commerce, and up to the origin of the family. In the second, he treated the negation of all these jiositive ele- mt^nts, the violation of Riglit — trespass and crime — in all its forms, and the entire world of Injustice. In the third, he pre- sented ethics, whicli in laws and customs constitutes the will directed to the realization of the good, and in courts consti- tutes the negation of the negation caused by injustice. Later^ he construed ethics as the higher unity of legality and mo- rality, so that the system is finally divided thus: (1) right in itself, (2) morality. (3) ethics. Under the latter he sub- sumed the idea of the family, of civil society, and of the state^ and closed with a perspective into universal history. Hegel had great horror of a state founded merely upon right, wliere only the externality of jiersonal justification nmde the frigid- ity of egoistic rectitude a dominant principle. In this respect^ also, he bore a certain grudge against Roman jurisprudence- He regarded with great aversion a state in which the moral ideal held the sceptre, and where all should be made to de- pend upon good intention, upon subjective consciousness, and upon the confiict of virtue with vice. This moral stand-point, which goes to the extreme of calling the vanity of its own conceit " warmheartedness," and, as satirized in the Xenia, "does the behests of duty with horror," and which finally ends in the complacent pride whicli, in order not to soil itself, does nothing at all, — this stand-point of abstract internality he treats with almost malicious disparagement. Hegel de- sired a state which should neither stiffen into the mechanism of a merely external right, nor gi'ow stolid in the virtuous feeling of mere internality. An ideal here ever hovered be- fore him similar to that which Holderlin has depicted with such asj)iration in his Hyperion, and from which he has oomxjlained that the Germans stood so far removed. He ap- proached here nearer to Fries and to DeWette than he thought, and Michelet has now openly acknowledged this in his Phi- losophy of Right by the development of the idea of unions Hegel, Prussia, and the Philosophy of Right. 271 and associations. Hegel was so strongly possessed with the idea of the state as the " terrestrial C-rod," as he termed it^ that in this enthusiasm he can be compared only with Plato,, to whom he expressly appeals in the preface of his text-book^ although, as he expressly showed in the extended criticism in his History of Philosophy, he rejected the content of this state. Hegel was convinced that his construction of practical phi- losophy was the only correct one, and that his method was correspondingly correct. In a remark in the Psychology,, which Boumann had printed, he expressed himself with the greatest distinctness, because the antithesis of the objective and the subjective in right and morals was absolutely can- celled by the unity of both in ethics. With such divisions of the subject, one must not look to the right hand or to the left,, but must submit himself entirely to the necessity of the idea. I confess still that I have ever found ground of offence in the position he assigns to morality. With such transitions — as those from subject to object, or from object to subject — alone,, it is not accomplished. The relation of the general to the special and of the abstract to the concrete is also involved. The most general conception of the entire practical sphere is the conception of good ; for the conception of will in gene- ral, without reference to its content, falls to the sphere of psy- chology. The domain of psychology extends as far as the formal freedom which seeks happiness in the satisfaction of the appetites and passions, i.e. as far as Eudsemonism. Eth- ics, on the other hand, proceeds from the necessity with which good determines the will as with the truth of its contents. That will only which recognizes and which realizes good, or its law, is really free. Hegel did not forget these elementary determinations; but, instead of making them constitute the lirst part of the Ethics, he treated them only in the form of an Introduction. The general conception of good can be realized only through the power of the individual will to which it prescribes duty as the categorical imperative. This is the sphere of morality, which describes the special essence of action. It is an old dispute in morals whether the conception of duty must pre- cede that of virtue, or the converse. This dispute rests U2Jon the fact that we reflect upon the contents of action according- 272 Hegel, Prussia, and the Fhilosopliy of Rigid. to our concrete determinations. Each of these may be pre- sented as a duty or as a virtue. Hegel condemned the lati- tude with which this was wont to be done by rightly declar- ino- that each moment of the moral life could issue either in the form of duty or of virtue. Family piety, e.g., becomes the duty of filial, paternal and fraternal love. It need there- fore, according to Hegel, only be added to the conception of piety that it constitutes now the duty and now the virtue of the members of the family ; and likewise with all the rela- tions of family and of state. We find, therefore, in Hegel uo special doctrine of duty and of virtue, because the ethical orgaaism embraces them as its vital development. This thought of Hegel is quite correct, and by means of it the use- less and extensive repetitions of content in the ordinary treat- ment of morals is dispensed with. The meagreness to which he reduced the morale does not result from this. Hegel de- votes only three chapters to morals, viz.: (1) design and guilt ; (2) intention and well-being ; (3) the good and conscience. But the idea of duty contains an entire system of determinations which through the moral organism are entirely independent from its concrete contents, e.g. the difference between categori- cal, hypothetical and disjunctive dutj", or the diS'erence be- tween the duty of love and that of compulsion. The same is true of the conception of virtue, the peculiar field of wiiich lies in the diflTerence of virtues, as physical, intellectual, and practi- cal and physical training, and in the formation of character. There is no doubt that the acquisition of all virtues is our duty ; but it does not follow thence that the conception of virtue must precede that of duty, for virtue is dependent upon the conception of duty. I must first know what I ought to do before I venture to act. The realization of duty is virtue. ccustom them to practise them. With every virtue, the conception of duty, that it is something which ought to 5e, is posited. The conception of action as something Avhich must precede the' virtuous act, can be only perfected in the conception of duty as complementary to a necessary action. The transition from morality to ethics Hegel makes through Hegel, Prussia, and the Philosophy of Right. 273 the conception of conscience in so far as it can sublate itself througli its reflexion. According to him, the eternal laws of ethics, which man must obey without equivocation, are the positive negation of all moral skepticism. But this is the dif- ference of right in general from morality ; for right is the will which is valid not for me alone, but for all others as Good, In morality, I stand only before my forum internum, before conscience ; in right, also, before the forum externum, before recognition through general consciousness. That right attains also the external form of a law fixed by authority or by letter, detracts nothing from its high significance, any more than does the fact that empirical rights can exist which in their content are unethical, like i\\e jus primce noctis of the French feudal lords. The circumstance that right can be practised without moral disposition detracts still less from its signifi- cance ; for right itself is not responsible for this. I must pro- ceed consciously in the practice of right, and must regard in so doing the well-being of others. The internality of the mo- ral stand-point for itself, which is therefore so often appre- hended as the stepping-stone to religion, appears higher than the mere externalit}^ of positive right ; but there is manifestly nothing in right in itself which hinders the existence of moral- ity. Hegel always accepts right in itself only as formal ; he cannot deny, however, that ethics assumes essentiall}' the form of right. Private, then, as well as public right embraces the same content which exists as the ethical {Sitte). The de- cay of all ethical organisms takes place when morality evacu- ates them, and leaves only the naked, atomic person with the demands of his denuded rights. Hegel makes the transition from right itself to morality through the idea of imputation, which leads to the idea of premeditation and guilt, and, fur- ther on, to intention and well-being. These, however, are ideas which right, in the conception of will and of action in general, already presupposes for itself, as appears imme- diately in the idea of wrong. The distinction of ethics from right and from morality rests, according to Hegel, upon the fact that right and duty are always posited as unity, as correlatives, in their deter- minations. This reciprocity is by no means wanting to per- sonal right ; for the right of my own personal freedom evokes, Vol. vi.— IS 374 Hegel. Prussia, and the IViilosopliy of Right. as my liulir, the duty to respect the right of another; and not to treat him as a slave; the riglit to acquire property is iden- tical with the duty to respect that of another; the service which is engaged to me hj a bargain with anotlier, involves the duty of a return service on my part, etc. A Crusoe upon a lonely island can live very morally, but there exist for him only du- ties ; right exists for him only ^;c>^e?i/ia, and can only develop itself actu when at least one other person lives with him, be- cause only witli this other would a recognition of his willing and acting become possible. He might, indeed, be immoral toward himself; he might be lazy, intemperate, unchaste, etc., but a crime or trespass he could not commit. The full division of right is left incomplete by Hegel be- cause it revolves only about property. He distinguishes (1) property, (2) fraud, (3) wrong. But fraud is itself a wrong, and the division must rather, according to his own dialectic rule of the negation of the negation, be thus : (1) personal right (personal freedom, property, contract) ; (2) wrong; (3) punishment. These are the elementary ideas of all right which can be separated from morality only violently by abstraction. Contract, e.g., imposes upon me the duty of tidelity and consciousness in the execution of the stipulation. Fraud is not only an action which affects right, but it is at the same time immoral ; for through it I violate the duty of truthfulness. I do not question that in ethics right and mo- rality should be one ; but I ascribe right to ethics, which, even in its loftiest formations, cannot dispense with the ob- jective form of right. The constitutions of nations, on the higher planes of state-culture, are not mere naiTie traditions, but written laws, in which they with consciousness express what conception of ethics and of good they have. The anti- thesis of ethics within itself is the individual right of the single j)erson, and the particular right of the organic com- munity, of family, of civil society, and of state. Particular sublates itself as universal right, which is brought out in the history of the state as the right of mankind in and for itself, and which we are therefore wont to call the right of universal citizenship. In his earlier plan of ethics, Hegel concluded with the conception of colonization, by which a state transcends its own limits, producing other states. The Hegel, Prussia, and the PMlosojyhy of Right. 275 tlioiight, however, of including the conception of history itself in the system of philosopliy was more correct. Hegel had avoided making use of the traditional terminol- ogy in his Philosophy of Right, unquestionabl}^ because it was not congruent to his ideas. He, therefore, named private right " abstract right," in order to indicate that in it abstrac- tion was still made from morality, to which he lirst passed with the conception of imputation. This is, however, an error, for imputation [responsibility] is in general a concep- tion identical with that of freedom. " Concrete " ought to be opposed to "abstract" right. Instead of that, Hegel goes en- tirely out of the conception of right over into that of moral- ity. In ethics, which contained that which he was obliged to> call "concrete right," he did not make use of the word "right'^ at all in the headings : he speaks only of family, of civil, society, of state : only in the latter does he distinguish an internal state-right from an external. It is not to be denied that the Kantian division of public right as state-right, right of nations, and right of the universal citizen, is more simple and more compendious. But where is church right? This is mentioned by Hegel only in a remark, in which he subordinates the church as a. religious society to the ethical supervision of the state. Here- he occupies precisely the stand-point of the eGlaircissement, but in this point eclaircissement is right. Th^faith of a. church should be left free from the state, for the sphere of religion is higher than that of j)olitics. But in so far as the church, as such, comes to external manifestation, it should be treated, as every other society, for a state-church is as bad as a church-state. It is, in fine, the church which has to do chiefly with the fostering of morality and with the cultivation of conscience. But all the blame which can be attached to Hegel's construction arises from the profound idea which he had formed of the state, in which he saw the realization of ethics. Hence it was that he subsumed family, society, and state, under the conception of ethics ; for with this category he wished to say at the outset that the state was an end to itself, and not a mere means for the security of persons in demanding their eudtemonistic ends or their tern- '2TG Hegcl^ Prussia, and the riiilosopliy of llicpit. poral interests. It is society which exercises its functions in the sphere of cnltivated egoism, but in whicli that which the individual produces immediately for liis own use, in the satisfaction of his necessities is converted into a contribution to the well-being of all. The family is the stand-point of the nature-state, of the patriarchal constitution. Society is the stand-point of the culture-state and of the constitution of community. It integrates the family in itself, but produces only the state so far as it rests upon necessity. The state which proceeds from the consciousness of freedom, and with it permeates all its communities, families, and individuals, is the true state. When Hegel is represented as though he had had in mind a centralized or bureaucratic state in which the omniscience or omnipotence of the government destroyed all individual vitality, as Fichte did in his exclusive, commercial state, he is entirely misunderstood. Stalil, who after Hegel distinguished himself greatly in the elaboration of natural right, directed against him a sharp polemic which derived its material from individual propositions wrested from their con- nection, and from methodic maladroitness. But if we regard the content w^e find that Stalil fully agrees with Hegel in see- ing in the state the s^'stem of self-organizing ethics, and in constitutional monarchy the most perfect form of state. The two Greek words etlios and pathos^ which Stahl so much uses, signify on^- that which Hegel expresses by the German word SittlicTikeit (ethics). E.uge in particular has attacked the Hegelian system on the side of democracy. Ruge, an old member of the student-corps, is indebted to the study of Hegel for all the categories with which he has often so hap- pily and successfully figured as a publicist. He cannot for- give Hegel for considering representation of the people in legislation as organized, not atomically according to the mere census, but as socially founded on caste by means of a landed aristocracy, and by elected representatives of munici- pal corporations. By the orthodox Protestant and by the ul- tramontane Catholic party Hegel's deification of the state was rejected because he would not have the state a mere mechan- ism, a centralized or military state, but would rather trans- fuse it with the self-consciousness of vital freedom. The political dominion of the churefe was at any rate made en- Hegel, Prussia, and the Fldloso'pliy of Rigid. 277 tirely superliuoiis by the Hegelian conception of the state. The state was for Hegel the absolute might in all judicial and ethical relations. He did not make it absolute, however, in a sense that precluded him from knowing and recognizing another higher sphere. This was the sphere of art, religion, and science, for the external culture of which the state should be solicitous, but which internall}^ in its essence must be left free. Here Hegel has expressly admitted that the state itself must have the interest to presuppose in its citizens the exist- ence of a religious disposition, through which it exalts itself above all that is empirical, and above the history of one's own state, into direct relation to the pure absolute. Hegel opposed religious fanaticism most strenuously ; and most strenuously has he defended that which ultramontanism scornfully treats as temporal, viz.: work, property, marriage, moral conviction as basis of action, without need of a con- fessor ; but religion itself he did not reject. He was impla- cable against all superstition, and as a philosopher he was able to treat it psychologically, while at the same time as a philosopher he must scout it. Hence it was that he gave the political precedence to Protestantism over Catholicism, be- cause the former demands freedom of thought and conscience, and thereby harmonizes with the principle of political self- determination ; while Catholicism allows the criticism of sci- entitic investigation only outside the dogmas it has fixed, and by the institution of oral confession it reserves to itself the leading of conscience by its priests. The state is the peculiar work of freedom of mind, in which it has to deal with its own creations, and becomes revealed as spirit for itself. Right and ethics are therefore in them- selves holy through the good which constitutes their content, and do not first become so through the blessings of a church. Sanctification, in a specific sense, belongs to religion in so far as it is the purification of our will which arises from its im- mediate relation to the Divine will, which is the personal principle of all legality. Religion is internally connected with right and with science, but in their own necessity they are independent of it. The laws of esthetic formation are now less independent than those of logic. Art proceeds ac- cording to the former, science according to the latter. Reli- *278 Hegch Prussia, and the Phnosojyliy of Rigid. gioii, so far as it is presentative, or in the forms of worship, must foUow ;rsthetical laws ; so far as it is scientilic, or in the form of theolofjv. ir must foUow h:»2:i('al laws; but for itself it follows its own law, as it springs from the relation of man to God, as the peculiar content of religion. Hegel's doctrine of the state could satisfy none of the par- ties in the midst of which it appeared. By demanding con- formity to law, he stood opposed to feudalism, which is so ready to claim itself a ]>atriarchal constitution ; by demand- ing monarchy, he stood opposed to abstract democracy, which complacently calls itself i^opular sovereignty ; by demand- ing representation of the people, bureaucracy of state offi- cers, and freedom of the press, sworn courts, the independ- ence of corporations, he opposed the aristocracy ; by de- manding the subordination of religion, as it appears in the church, to the sovereignty of the state, and the emancipation of science from the authority of the church, he stood op- posed to the hierarchy ; by demanding ethics as the absolute end of the state, he opposed the industrial state, which seeks to entangle the people in the slavery of factory work by the bait of riches and material comfort ; and by the demand of a constitution, he opposed the despotism of eclaircissement, which seeks to do all for, and nothing through, the people. We say nothing here of that cosmopolitan socialism which he contrasts with the historical and national character of the state. Hegel's contradiction was not, as it may appear, that of a 3'et unprejudiced, youthful, naivety, but that of a criti- cally elaborated and matured judgment which was fully con- scious of its range. Hence, he thoroughly embittered all par- ties against himself. They turned upon and derided him, now as servile, now as radical. With true manly courage, Hegel held his position against them all, as the appended remarks, w^hich after his death Gans had printed from his lectures on the philosophy of right, show. A half century has elapsed since its lirst appearance. The progress of time has actually transcended Hegel in very many points, e.g. in that of the political culture of the masses; but in its chief features the Hegelian state remains still the most rational, and the expression which it attained in Hegel's presentation, tlie most beautiful. In treating of ordinary, The Parmenicles of Plato. 279 . natural right, his language savors of Roman right, in the manner of the definitions in the Institutes and the Pandects. Fichte cast off this dry method in his system of natural right, but did it in a confused way; while Hegel labored with artistic circumspection, and from the treasmy of the German language he coined the jDurest gold. THE PARMENIDES OF PLATO. By S. H. Emkry, Jr. [In Quincy and Jacksonville (Illinois) there are two flonrishing philosophical clubs that have been prosecutinor vigorously the study of Plato. The bravery that attacks Plato, and especially the Parmenides, deserves the highest admi- ration. Mr. S. H. Emery, Jr., member of the club at Quincy, writes under date of April 21, 1872, as follows; "I have read the first three hypotheses, viz., i. a., i. 6., and what should be called (it seems to me) i. c, although Jowett includes it in i. b. I make of the first hypothesis: (i. a.) The One considered as indefinite immediate — indeterminable ajid undetermining is Nothing, (i. b.) Of the second: the One considered as self-determining — subject-object — is and is the totality ; all the categories are embraced in it. (i.e.) Of the third: the becoming of the One is in eternit}', and through all its self-determining it re- mains self-identical." The following essay is an outline of his view of this "great master-work of ancient dialectic." Its author modestly says: "All I claim at all is — to have seen something of the main purpose of the dialogue." — ^Editor.] Now that we have finished our first attempt to discover the true meaning of this most celebrated Platonic Dialogue, it will be an advantage to review the whole matter and see what we have gained. As to the form of the Dialogue, we find it divided into two main divisions — the first a preliminary discussion be- tween Socrates and Parmenides, which leads easily and natu- rally to the second part, in which Parmenides gives Socrates an example of the true philosophica Imethod. It has occur- red to me (although I will confess that my acquaintance with the early Philosophies is not sufficient to enable me to be sure that I am right), that Plato intends by this arrangement of the characters to intimate that the Eleatic Philosophy, le- gitimately extended, goes deeper than the Socratic teachings. As to the matter, we find the Dialogue devoted wholly to the consideration of Ideas in themselves, or, as Socrates calls them, "Ideas in the abstract." 280 The Parmeiiides of Plato. The main hypothesis of the Dialogue is, "If xlbstract Ideas are," and is introduced by Socrates at the very outset. The Absolute in itself having been thus presupposed, the problem is to tind the connection between it and existing things. The tirst connection tried is '"Participation" — ''Things par- take of the Ideas." This is soon shown to be inadequate. Parmenides then asks Socrates if he has not found these "Abstract Ideas *' by abstracting from existing things ; and Socrates says, "Yes.'' Parmenides then shows that this process leads to an "Inlinite Progress," from which Socrates endeavors to escape by inquiring if the Ideas may not be subjective only ; that is, mere generalizations, without any real being for their ground — an entire relinquishing of Ideas as real essence ; but Parmenides makes him admit that there cannot be cognitions w^ithout a something cognized, and this something is the Idea. Socrates then substitutes " Assimi- lation" for "Participation." Parmenides shows that this also leads to an "Infinite Progress," and then proceeds to explain to Socrates that his method is inadequate ; that if Ideas are posited as distinct from (separated and apart from) existing things, and we attempt to find a connection in this external way, we shall never accomplish anything, — but Ideas must be contemplated in their own proper movement, by the true Dialectic method. I believe that this first part of the Dialogue is intended by Plato to present and refute possible erroneous views of the " Platonic Ideas," which w^oulcl assume them as set ofi" somewhere — isolated from existing things by a chasm which cannot be bridged. The second part shows us the "Platonic Ideas" in their true aspect. The One and the Many are considered in two series of hypotheses — nine in all. In the first series are developed the consequences which follow from the hypothesis, " If the One is"; and in the second series are developed the conse- quences which follow from the hypothesis, "If the One is not." This division into nine hypotheses is really only a matter of form, as the whole content is actually developed from the hypothesis, " If One is." Let us now examine this second part of the Dialogue in detail. • TTie Parmenides of Plato. 281 First, "If One is, the One cannot be Many," There fol- lows, then : " The One is not a whole and will not have parts. " The One is unlimited. " The One is formless. " The One cannot be in any place. " The One can neither have rest nor motion. " The One is neither the same nor other in relation to itself or other. "The One can neither be older nor younger than itself, nor of the same age with itself. " Tlierefore the One does not partake of Time, and is not in any time. "And if not of Time, then not of Being. " Then the One is not and is not One, and is neither named, nor uttered, nor conceived, nor known ; nor does anything that is, perceive One." So the One that cannot be Many is disposed of, and the outcome is plain. The Abstract — Inde- terminate— Undeterminable — One — is nothing — can be nei- ther known nor uttered. Let us make a fresh start, then, from the hypothesis : "If One is." There follows, then : " One partakes of Being. " One becomes infinite in number. " If One is, number is. " One broken up into parts by existence must be infinite Many. " One partakes of a figure. " One is in itself and in Other. " One is the same with itself and Others. " One is other than itself and Others. " One is both like and unlike Others. " One is both like and unlike itself. " One touches and does not touch itself and Others. " One is equal to and greater and less than itself and Others. " One is equal to and more and less in number than itself and Others. " One is and becomes older and younger than itself and Others. " One neither is nor becomes older or younger than itself and Others." 2S'2 The Pannenlcles of Plato. This. then, is the One which is — the Self-determining One — which includes all Categories and is ISIany as well as One. In the tirst consideration, the One is viewed in its abstract iden- tity and the attempt is made to hold fast to that, but it is useless. The next hypothesis unites the two lirst: "If One is both One and Many, and neither One nor Many" — that is, If One considered in its wliole truth is both One and Many, and held in indetinite immediateness is neither One nor Many — then the One becomes : The becoming of the One in its various forms (some of which are specilied) is not in Time but in Eternity, and in its becoming the One remains self-identical. •' These, then, are the affections of the One." Could there be a more complete statement of the One? The One is in eternal becoming, remaining self-identical. The fourth hypothesis, "If One is, what will happen to the Many ?" portrays the true character of the Being : i^or-Itself of the One. The Others are shown to be inlinite in their ground, but finite in their particularity ; that is, the For- Itself Being of the One is infinite variety posited in indivi- dual things. The categories which are potential in the One exist in the Others, and the Others are a complete image of the One ; but it must be always particularly borne in mind that the Others are not the One; that back of the created is the Creator. The fifth hypothesis shows the result of attempting to se- parate the Others from the One, and, as might be expected, they prove to be nothing. The result of the first series of hypotheses is, therefore, that — The One, when truly considered, is all things ; when otherwise considered, is nothing ; and the others are simi- larly aff'ected. The first hypothesis of the second series is, "If One is not." Upon consideration, it appears that this is something quite different from an absolute denial of Being to the One. As we proceed, we find that it is a consideration of the One which is from the side of its Being-In-Other. We see, first, that The Parmenides of Plato. 283 there is a knoAvledge of One ; then that the One is different from the Others and has determinate quality. We are considering the One on the side of 'variety, not of unity ; bnt we find that, when so considered, the One has Likeness, Unlilveness, Greatness. Smallness, Equality, Ine- quality, Motion, Rest, &c. We also find that Non-Being is as necessary to the One as Being, neither being complete without the other. We find that the One, when it is moved, is changed, and we recognize the "Finite sphere," Origin, and Decease ; but we see also that the change is within the One — that it includes Life and Death — so that it comes into being and j)erishes, and neither " comes into being nor perishes," The seventh hypothesis is the same as the sixth, but the "tzo^" is accepted as absolute denial of being. The conclu- sion is soon reached, and from this point of view is inevita- ble, viz. : The One which is not, has and is nothing at all. The eighth hypothesis is, "If One is not, what becomes of the Others?" This leads to a consideration of the Others in themselves ; that is, it is an attempt similar to that of the {so called) natural philosophers, who investigate phenome- na from the phenomenal side, pretending ignorance of the ground on which they depend. We find, however, that before we have proceeded far the One appears, and that all the cate- gories which we found to exist in the Others when we consid- •ered them truly — that is, from the side of the Being of the One — now cvppeaf to exist in them when considered from the phenomenal side ; and we find further, when we come to the ninth hypothesis (which bears the same relation to the eighth that the seventh bears to the sixth), that, no matter how hard we may try to leave the One out of our consideration, if we could succeed in our attempt, nothing would be left. It is only the immanent presence of the One in its Not-Being which enables the Others to even a/ppear ; for, "If One is not, nothing is." As a summing up of the whole content, we find (to use HegeFs words) : " The One, whether it is or is not, is the Many as well as it itself, and in relation to another as well *-?S4 Book Notices. as for itself — all throughout is not as well as is ; it appecurs and does not appear."' Or: The One is the Totality — All that is — Being and Non-Being — One and Many, NoTK. — I make a distinction between "Bein,;e relations are constant, that is, always the same in the same circumstances. The constant resemblances which link phenomena together, and the constant sequences which unite them as ante- cedent and conseqtient, are termed tiicir laws. The laws of phenomena are all we know respecting them. Their essential nature, their ultimate causes either elfirient or linal, are unknown and inscrutable to us." Dr. Porter calls attention to the fact that this philosophy, as thus expounded, is properly if not emphatieaily metaphysical. And yet Couite claims to have demonstrated that the human mind passes through the stages of The- ology and Metaphysics as crude and undeveloped youthful stages of growth, and tinally comes to the stage of J'ositivi.sm as the highest form of develop- ment. •' That the Positive Philosophy is metaphysical in the proper sense of the tei*m is too obvious to admit of question. Its problem is metaphysi- cal. It proposes not only to discover the criteria of the processes which are common to all the special sciences, but it sets these forth as the criteria of every true science." That is to sa} , it deals with the universal and ne- cessary, and announces the forms of all knowledge. " Like every other metaphysical system, it concerns itself with relations. But constant rela- tions are what in all systems exalt observed phenomena to the dignity of Science. Other systems recognize more relations — those of causation or force — mayhap those of design. Comte's metaphysics hold to fewer, those of sequence and similitude. To use a ligure of clothing, while other sys- tems honor, by recognition and use, the habiliments which obvious neces- sity and universal u-sage have sanctioned, this sect appear among the sans culottes of phih^sophers, on tho principle that the fewer clothes we have the nearer we come to naked truth, and the less occasion we have to look after our clothes, or the less we are tempted to think more of the clothes than of the man." After showing that Comte, while condemning the metaphysical proce- dure of setting up abstractions as real agencies, yet actually does this every- where, always appealing to " sequence and similitude " as the most real facts in the world, Dr. Porter lakes up the system of Jolui Stuart Mill. His theory of mind reduced to " a series of feelings witl'i a background of the pos.sibilities of feeling"; his delinition of matter as " a permanent pos- sibility of sensations"; his theory of the process of induction as "the result of repeated experiences of sensations so closely combined as to have become practically in-eparable" ; his theory of ultimate beliefs as " derived from induction, even those beliefs concerning the sequence and similitude of phenomena upon which the whole process of induction depends, depend on induction — all come from inseparable association"; — these four doc- trines, or i)art« of the same doctrine, are exhibited in their vicious circle. BooTc Notices. 287 From Mill, Avith "his admirable candor in confessing difficulties of his own, and with something more than admirable unconsciousness tliat his confessions amount to a complete surrender of everything for which he would contend," our author tui'us to the cerebraUsts, to Alexander Bain and his school, who claim that the analysis of the brain and its functions is the only basis for a solid science of the soul. To this he remarks that even if brain convohitions and nerve vibrations explain ditferences of develop- ment in mind, they do not explain nature, and hence do not suffice as a basis for philosopliy. Lastly, he comes to the Law of Evolution as set forth by Herbert Spen- cer. AVhile Mr. Spencer gives full ciedit to the science of Man, yet as he hides all the difficulties of his system behind abstract entities like/byce and evolution, and claims inscrutability for them, he becomes one of the worst sticklers for a priori ideas and methods ; "worst" because he does not pro- ceed consciously, and hence not critically, to work. "The study of man is not necessarily the study of psychology or specu- lative philosophy. Man is made manifest in history, philology, literature, art, politics, ethics, and theology. The thoughts of man have recogidzed and accepted those principles and institutions, those manners and laws, that civilization and culture, which give security and grace to the present life, which awaken the anticipations and confirm the faiths which reach into another. The study of all these is a study o( the humanities. ^^ w. T. H. Radical Problems. By C. A. Bartol. Boston: Roberts Brothers. 1872. For sale by Soule, Thomas & Wiusor. Contents: I. Open Questions. II. Individualism. IIT. Transcendentalism. IV. Radicalism. V. Theism. VI. Naturalism. VII. Materialism. VILI. Spi- ritualism. IX. Faith. X. Law. X[. Origin. XEI. Correlation. XIII. Cha_ racter. XIV. Genius : Father Taylor. XV. Experience. XVI. Hope. XVIL Ideality. No one who reads these essays could fail to know from internal evidence that the author was from Boston or its vicinity, and he would be quite safe in assuming that he had lived somewheie on the line of the Eastern Rail- road. The illustrations are so often drawn from objects well-known only in Boston and its environs, that one who is not acquainted with that local- it)' must necessarily lose much of the pleasure with which a Bostonian follows the train of thought. It is everywhere taken for granted that all must know about these things. This peculiarity makes one conscious all the time that the essays were written with a particular audience in view. Those acquainted with the attitude taken by the celebrated author will not fail here and there also to detect traces of the personal pain which he has sometimes suffered from the misrepresentation of his views. In reading the volume through — and one will not be likely to lay it down unfinished — one has a glimpse of a sensitive, eager mind, keenly alive to all the actual problems of the day; of a thought which follows closely the daily events of the world and history, and reads in them all the action of broad and deep motive-powers, — these lyiug behind, and asserting every day under new aspects their claim for recognition and solution. The author 288 Book Kotlces. is no dreamy thinker who seeks to evolve from his own consciousness the Truth of the world. Kather he seizes it on the wing, at once perceives and photoyraphs its many forms, and so gives us material for thought. For example, the Franoo-Prussiau war, Siioridan's managemenr of tiie Indians, the portraits of Fiskc and Gould on the new Fall-liiver boats, Darwin's theories, the correlation of forces, — all play continually into and out of his illustrations. Through all the essays the poetic thought shows itself clear- ly. To it, everywhere, each one individual is only the image of the all. From this universality in the treatment of the subjects, it easily follows that the reader will often find himself in doubt as to the title of the essay which he is reading. It seems that the title might be transferred and no one be the wiser; for through all the essays it is one thought that runs, only one thing that is to be said. The whole book is a plea for absolute freedom of thought; an earn- est expression that growth, active development, is a necessity of life, in wliatever form it present itself. In every essay we come continually face to face with an illustration where something is not large cnongh to contain something else. The rolling-stock on tlie railroad was not ample enough to accommodate tlie number of passengers and the amount of freight; the country barn is not large enough for the increasing harvests, and so on in- definitely. If there is one thing which Dr. Bartol must say, and say so that no one who reads or hears can forget it , it is that the old is not large enough to contain the new; or one might more truly put it in the opposite torm, and say that the new is not large enough to contain the old. The transient can only for a time display the eternal and abiding; the phenomenal is only the shifting play of the real light of Truth. The content [)erpetua]ly shivers its form, only to make for itself another and one more adequate. For such an utterance so forcibly given, so earnestly impressed, so illu- mined from all sides by perpetually shifting lights of illustration, one can- /not fail to be grateful to the eloquent speaker. The mind of the writer is so quick, and so alive to all the phases, whether humorous or serious, of the thought in hand, that the style is sometimes involved, and the meaning, for the instant, difficult to grasp; and the frequent omission of relative pronouns, and, in some cases, care- less punctuation, increases the difficulty ; and again, in some passages, one seems to be reading a scries of proverbs, as for instance on page 7. From the same cause result figures of speech carelessly used, as when we are told of a "'flock of islands beating at our windows." And sometimes the writer's keen sense of the ludicrous lowers for a moment the dignity of the subject. But these faults are, as has been said, only the result of the A^ersa- tile, appreciative, and poetic mind of the writer, and are soon forgotten, while the impulse to thought given by the perusal of the essays will be in- valuable. One is only lelt to regret that the localization as to time and place of sO many of the illustrations may withhold the volume from the permanent place in our libraries wliich from its thought it has a right to claim. A. c. u. THE JOURNAL OF SPECULATIVE PHILOSOPHY. VoL VI. October, 1872. No. 4r. DO THE CORRBLATIONISTS BELIEVE IN SELF-MOVEMENT ? Self-movement, spontaneity, and freedom, are in some sense synonyms. He who cannot think self-movement, cannot think freedom. Materialistic philosophy is distinguished from spir- itual philosophy, or idealism, through the fact that the former thinks all phenomena under the categories of cause and effect, or of external determination ; while the latter thinks all pheno- mena as arising in the last analysis through self-determination, or through final causes. Plato and Aristotle agree in this latter view, and with them stand the other great thinkers of the race, such as Leibnitz, Spinoza, and Hegel. That any hypothesis results, when strictly tortured in the logical crucible, in positing causa sui as its necessary condition, is the demonstrated outcome of Spinoza's Ethics, as well as Hegel's Logic and the twelfth book of Aristotle's Metaphysics. The feeblest and most dogmatic thinking (i.e. thinking which has to do with mere opinions) is best satisfied with mechanical causes. It is cultured thought which learns to perceive Neces- sity and Universality in its ideas. The highest thinking identi- fies necessity and freedom through the idea of self-determination. Since the course of histor}'^ and the laws of development alike point to a progress from the simple to the complex, from the im- plicit to the explicit, from the acorn to the oak, — we look with confidence to see a growth in the scientific mind from age to age. In the great intensity with which Natural Science is pursued, there is occasion for great improvement in methods of thinking. Vol. vi.— 19 290 Pedagogics as a System. Depth and Exhaustiveness — Comprehension — will be gained. This can be seen alread}' in the foremost ranks. Those who uphold the theory of Correlation set out with ma- terialistic hypotheses, and nothing is further from their expecta- tions than the support of spiritual, ideal conclusions. They think in fatalistic forms, and do not admit self-determination. Spen- cer says (Ps^-chology, § 220) that psychical changes (thoughts, &c.) conform to law, or else a science of Psychology is impos- sible : and "if they do conform to law, there cannot be any such thing as free-will." And yet the idea of Correlation, when redu- ced to its lowest terms, gives us self-movement pure and simple. One force becomes another and the second a thii'd, and so on ; the first is an equivalent and may be derived from the last. The action of the first produces the second and the rest, and the rest produce it : thus its energy reverts to itself — no matter how long the series of links may be. Its action is the cause of its action, and hence it becomes causa sji/'. But the thought of this total of action is not a mere force, still less a material somewhat ; it is a vital system, a whole, a monad. This thought once grasped, materialism passes over to idealism ; fatalism gives way to free personality. PEDAGOGICS AS A SYSTEM. By Dr. Karl Rosenkranz, Doctor of Theology and Professor of Philosophy at the University of Konigsberg. Translated by Axna C. Brackett. [Inquiries from teachers in different sections of the country as to the sources of information on the subject of Teaching as .a Science liave led me to believe that a translation of Rosenkranz's Pedagogics may be widely acceptable and useful It is very certain that too much of our teaching is simply empirical, and as Germany has, more than any other country, endeavored to found it upon universal truths, it is to that country that we must at present look for a remedy for this empiricism. Based as this is upon the profoundest system of German Philosophy, no more suggestive treatise on Education can perhaps be found. In his third part, as will be readily seen, Rosenkranz follows the cJassificatiou of National ideas given in Hegel's Philosophy of History. The word " Pedagogics," though it has unfortunately acquired a s-oniewhat unpleasant meaning in English — thanks to the writers who have made the word '"pedagogue" so odious — deserves to be redeemed for future use. I have, therefore, retained it in the translation. In order thnt the reader may see the general scope of the work, I append in tabular form the table of contents, giving however, under the first and second parts, only the main divisions. The minor heads can, of course, as they appear in the translation, be easily located. — TV.] Pedagogics as a System. 291 'in its General Idea P.VRT I. in Its Special Elements Pakt II. Education Analysis. fits Nature its Form its Limits f Physical < Intellectual L Moral f Passive in its Particular Systems Pakt III. National Active Individual r Family . . ■I Caste . . I L Monkish . f jNIilitary , ■I Priestly . I Industrial f Esthetic , J Practical , CMna. India. Thibet. Persia. EgJlit. Phffinicia. Greece. Rome. I Abstract Indi- vidual ( Northen I Barbarif sorthem I'ians. Theocratic Jews. Monkish Humanita- rian Chivalric .for Civil Life for Special Callings to achieve an Ideal of Culture ' • Jesuitic. ! Pietistic. fThe Huma- nities. The Philan- thropic Movem't. . for Free Citizenship. IXTRODUCTIOX. § 1. The science of Pedagogics cannot "be derived from a simple principle with such exactness as Logic and Ethics. It is rather a mixed science which has its presuppositions in many others. In this respect it resembles Medicine, with which it has this also in common, that it must make a dis- tinction between a sound and an unhealthy system of educa- tion, and must devise means to prevent or to cure the latter. It may therefore have, like Medicine, the three departments of Physiology, Pathology, and Therapeutics. § 2. Since Pedagogics is capable of no such exact defini- tions of its principle and no such logical deduction as other sciences, the treatises written upon it abound more in shal- lowness than any other literature. Short-sightedness and arro- gance find in it a most congenial atmosphere, and criticism 292 Pedagogics as a System. and declamatory bombast tlourisli in perfection as nowliere else. The literature of religious tracts might be considered to rival that of Pedagogics in its superficiality and assurance, if it did not for the most part seem itself to belong, through its ascetic nature, to Pedagogics. But teachers as persons should be treated in their weaknesses and failures with the utmost consideration, because they are most of them sincere in contributing their mite for the improvement of education, and all their pedagogic practice inclines them towards admin- istering reproof and giving advice. § 3. The charlatanism of educational literature is also fos- tered by the fact that teaching has become one of the most profitable employments, and the competition in it tends to increase self-glorification. — When "Boz" in his "Nicholas Nickleby" exposed the horrible mysteries of an English boarding-school, many teachers of such schools were, as he assures us, so accurately described that they openly complained he had aimed his caricatures directly at them. — § 4. In the system of the sciences, Pedagogics belongs to the Philosophy of Spirit, — and in this, to the department of Practical Philosophy, the problem of which is the compre- hension of the necessity of freedom ; for education is the con- scious working of one will on another so as to produce itself in it according to a determinate aim. The idea of subjective spirit, as well as that of Art, Science, and Religion, forms the essential condition for Pedagogics, but does not contain its principle. If one thinks out a complete statement of Prac- tical Philosophy (Ethics), Pedagogics may be distributed among all its grades. But the point at which Pedagogics itself becomes organic is the idea of the Family, because in the family the difference between the adults and the minors en- ters directly through the naturalness of spirit, and the right of the children to an education and the duty of parents towards them in this respect is incontestable. All other spheres of education, in order to succeed, must presuppose a true family life. They may extend and complement the busi- ness of teaching, but cannot be its original foundation. — In our systematic exposition of Education, we must not allow ourselves to be led into error by those theories which Pedagogics as a System. 293 do not recognize the family, and which limit the relation of husband and wife to the producing of children. The Platonic Philosophy is the most worthy representative of this class. Later writers who take great pleasure in seeing the world full of children, but who would subtract from the love to a wife all truth and from that to children all care, exhibit in their doctrine of the anarchy of love only a sickly (but yet how prevalent an) imitation of the Platonic state. — § 5. Much confusion also arises from the fact that many do not clearly enough draw the distinction between Pedagogics as a science and Pedagogics as an art. As a science it busies itself with developing a priori the idea of Education in the universality and necessity of that idea, but as an art it is the concrete individualizing of this abstract idea in any given case. And in any such given case, the peculiarities of the person who is to be educated and all the previously existing circumstances necessitate a modification of the universal aims and ends, which modification cannot be provided for before- hand, but must rather test the ready tact of the educator who knows how to make the existing conditions fulfil his desired end. It is exactly in doing this that the educator may show himself inventive and creative, and that pedagogic talent can distinguish itself. The word "art" is here used in the same way as it is used when we say, the art of war, the art of gov- ernment, &c. ; and rightly, for we are talking about the possibility of the realization of the idea. — The educator must adapt himself to the pupil, but not to such a degree as to imply that the pupil is incapable of change, and he must also be sure that the pupil shall learn through his experience the independence of the object studied, which re- mains uninfluenced by his variable personal moods, and the adaptation on the teacher's part must never compromise this independence. — § 6. If conditions which are local, temporal, and individual, are fixed as constant rules, and carried beyond their proper limits, are systematized as a valuable formalistic code, una- voidable error arises. The formulae of teaching are admirable material for the science, but are not the science itself. § 7. Pedagogics as a science must (1) unfold the general idea of Education ; (2) must exhibit the particular phases into 294 Pedagogics as a System. whicli the general work of Education divides itself, and (3) must describe the particular standpoint upon which the gen- eral idea realizes itself, or should become real in its special processes at any particular time. § 8. The treatment of the tirst part offers no difficulty. It is logically too evident. But it would not do to substitute for it the histor}^ of Pedagogics, simply because all the concep- tions of it which appear in systematic treatises can be found there. — Into this error G. Thaulow has fallen in his pamphlet on Pedagogics as a Philosoi3hical Science. — § 9. The second division unfolds the subject of the physi- cal, intellectual and practical culture of the human race, and constitutes the main part of all books on Pedagogy. Here arises the greatest difficulty as to the limitations, partly be- cause of the undefined nature of the ideas, partly because of the degree of amplitication which the details demand. Here is the field of the widest possible differences. If e.g. one studies out the conception of the school with reference to the qualitative specialities which one may consider, it is evident that he can extend his remarks indefinitely ; he may speak thus of technological schools of all kinds, to teach mining, navigation, war, art, (Src. § 10. The third division distinguishes between the different standpoints which are possible in the working out of the con- ■ ception of Education in its special elements, and which there- fore produce different systems of Education wherein the gen- eral and the particular are individualized in a special manner. In every system the general tendencies of the idea of educa- tion, and the difference between the physical, intellectual and practical culture of man, must be formally recognized, and will appear. The How is decided by the standpoint which reduces that formalism to a special system. Thus it becomes possible to discover the essential contents of the history of Pedagogics from its idea, since this can furnish not an in- definite but a certain number of Pedagogic systems. — The lower standpoint merges always into the higher, and in so doing first attains its full meaning, e.g. : Education for the sake of the nation is set aside for higher standjooints, e.g. that of Christianity ; but we must not suppose that the na- Pedagogics as a System. 295 tional phase of Education was counted as nought from the Christian standpoint. Rather it itself had outgrown the limits which, though suitable enough for its early stage, could no longer contain its true idea. This is sure to be the case in the fact that the national individualities become indestructi- ble by being incorporated into Christianity — a fact that con- tradicts the abstract seizing of such relations. — § 11. The last system must be that of the present, and since this is certainly on one side the result of all the past, while on the other seized in its possibilities it is determined by the Future, the business of Pedagogics cannot pause till it reaches its ideal of the general and special determinations, so that looked at in this way the Science of Pedagogics at its end returns to its beginning. The Jirst and second divisions al- ready contain the idea of the system necessary for the Present. FIRST PART. The General Idea of Ktlucation. § 12. The idea of Pedagogics in general must distinguish, (1) The nature of Education in general ; (2) Its form ; (3) Its limits. I. The JSfature of Education. § 13. The nature of Education is determined by the nature of mind — that it can develop whatever it really is only by its own activity. Mind is in itself free ; but if it does not actual- ize this possibility, it is in no true sense free, either for itself or for another. Education is the iuHuencing of man by man, and it has for its end to lead him to actualize himself through his own efforts. The attainment of perfect manhood as the actualization of the Freedom necessary to mind constitutes the nature of Education in general. — The completely isolated man does not become man. Soli- tary human beings w^ho have been found in forests, like the wild girl of the forest of Ardennes, sufficiently prove the fact that the truly human qualities in man cannot be developed without reciprocal action with human beings. Caspar Hau- ser in his subterranean prison is an illustration of what man 296 Pedagogics as a Systeiii. would be by himself. The first cry of the child expresses in its appeals to others this helplessness of spirituality on the side of natiu-e. — § 14. Man, therefore, is the only fit subject for education. "We often speak, it is true, of the education of plants and animals ; but even when we do so, we apply, unconsciously perhaps, other expressions, as "raising" and "training," in or- der to distinguish these. "Breaking" consists in producing in an animal, either by pain or pleasure of the senses, an activ- ity of which, it is true, he is capable, but which he never would have developed if left to himself. On the other hand, it is the nature of Education only to assist in the producing of that which the subject would strive most earnestly to de- velop for himself if he had a clear idea of himself. We speak of raising trees and animals, but not of raising men ; and it is only a planter who looks to his slaves only for an increase in their number. — The education of men is quite often enough, unfortunate- ly, only a " breaking," and here and there still may be found examples where one tries to teach mechanically, not tlirough the understanding power of the creative word, but through the powerless and fruitless appeal to physical pain. — § 15. The idea of Education may be more or less compre- hensive. We use it in the widest sense when we speak of the Education of the race, for we understand by this expres- sion the connection which the acts and situations of differ- ent nations have to each other, as different steps towards self-conscious freedom. In this the world-spirit is the teacher. § 16. In a more restricted sense we mean by Education the shaping of the individual life by the forces of nature, the rhythmical movement of national customs, and the might of destiny in which each one finds limits set to his arbitrary will. These often mould him into a man without his knowledge. For he cannot act in opposition to nature, nor offend the ethi- cal sense of the people among whom he dwells, nor despise the leading of destiny without discovering through experience that before the Nemesis of these substantial elements his subjective power can dash itself only to be shattered. If he perversely and persistently rejects all our admonitions, we leave him, as a last resort, to destiny, whose iron rule must Pedagogics as a System. 297 educate him, and reveal to him the God whom he has misun- derstood. — It is, of course, sometimes not only possible, but necessary for one, moved by the highest sense of morality, to act in op- position to the laws of nature, to offend the ethical sense of the people that surround him, and to brave the blows of des- tiny ; but ^uch a one is a sublime reformer or martyr, and we are not now speaking of such, but of the perverse, the frivo- lous, and the conceited. — § 17. In the narrowest sense, which however is the usual one, we mean by Education the influence which one mind exerts on another in order to cultivate the latter in some understood and methodical way, either generally or with reference to some special aim. The educator must, therefore, be relatively finished in his own education, and the pupil must possess unlimited confidence in him. If authority be wanting on the one side, or respect and obedience on the other, this ethical basis of development must fail, and it demands in the very highest degree, talent, knowledge, skill, and prudence. — Education takes on this form only under the culture which has been developed through the influence of city life. Up to that time we have the naive period of education, which holds to the general powers of nature, of national customs, and of destiny, and which lasts for a long time among the rural populations. But in the city a greater complication of events, an uncertainty of the results of reflection, a working out of individuality, and a need of the possession of many arts and trades, make their appearance and render it impossible for men longer to be ruled by mere custom. The Telemachus of Fenelon was educated to rule himself by means of reflec- tion ; the actual Telemachus in the heroic age lived simply according to custom. — § 18. The general problem of Education is the development of the theoretical and practical reason in the individual. If we say that to educate one means to fashion him into morality, we do not make our deflnition sufficiently comprehensive, be- cause we say nothing of intelligence, and thus confound edu- cation and ethics. A man is not merely a human being, but as a reasonable being he is a peculiar individual, and differ- ent from all others of the race. 298 Pedagogics as a System. § 19. Education must lead the pupil by an interconnected series of efforts previously foreseen and arranged by the teacher to a definite end ; but the particular form which this shall take must be determined by the peculiar character of the pupil's mind and the situation in which he is found. Hasty and inconsiderate work may accomplish much, but only systematic work can advance and fashion him in conformity with his nature, and the former does not belong to education, for this includes in itself the idea of an end, and that of the technical means for its attainment. § 20. But as culture comes to mean more and more, there becomes necessary a division of the business of teaching among different persons, with reference to capabilities and knowledge, because as the arts and sciences are continually increasing in number, one can become learned in any one branch only by devoting himself exclusively to it, and hence becoming one-sided. A difficulty hence arises which is also one for the pupil, of preserving, in spite of this unavoidable one-sidedness, the unity and wholeness which are necessary to humanit}^. — The naive dignity of the happy savage, and the agreea- ble simplicity of country people, appear to very great advan- tage when contrasted on this side with the often unlimited narrowness of a special trade, and the endless curtailing of the wholeness of man by the pruning processes of city life. Thus the often abused savage has his hut, his family, his cocoa tree, his weapons, his passions ; he fishes, hunts, plays, fights, adorns himself, and enjoys the consciousness that he is the centre of a whole, while a modern citizen is often only an abstract expression of culture. — § 21. As it becomes necessary to divide the work of teach- ing, a difference between general and special schools arises also, from the needs of growing culture. The former present ill different compass all the sciences and arts which are in- cluded in the term "general education," and which were classified by the Greeks under the general name of Encyclo- paedia. The latter are known as special schools, suited to particular needs or talents. — As those who live in the country are relatively isolated, it is often necessary, or at least desirable, that one man should Pedagogics as a System. 299 be trained equall}^ on many different sides. The poor tutor is required not only to instruct in all the sciences, he must also speak French and be able to play the piano. — § 22. For any single person, the relation of his actual edu- cation to its infinite possibilities can only be approximately determined, and it can be considered as only relatively fin- ished on any one side. Education is impossible to him who is born an idiot, since the want of the power of generalizing and of ideality of conscious personality leaves to such an un- fortunate only the possibility of a mechanical training. — Sagert, the teacher of the deaf mutes in Berlin, has made laudable efforts to educate idiots, but the account as given in his publication, " Cure of Idiots by an Intellectual Method, Berlin, 1846," shows that the result obtained was only exter- nal ; and though we do not desire to be understood as deny- ing or refusing to this class the possession of a mind in po- tential it appears in them to be confined to an embryonic state. — II. The Form of Education. § 23. The general form of Education is determined by the nature of the mind, that it really is nothing but what it makes itself to be. The mind is (1) immediate (or potential), but (2) it must estrange itself from itself as it were, so that it may place itself over against itself as a special object of attention; (3) this estrangement is finally removed through a further ac- quaintance with the object — it feels itself at home in that on which it looks, and returns again enriched to the form of im- mediateness. That which at first appeared to be another than itself is now seen to be itself. Education cannot create ; it can only help to develop to reality the previously existent possibility; it can only help to bring forth to light the hid- den life. § 24. All culture, whatever may be its special purport, must pass through these two stages — of estrangement, and its remo- val. Culture must hold fast to the distinction between the subject and the object considered immediately, though it has again to absorb this distinction into itself, in order that the union of the two may be more complete and lasting. The subject recognizes then all the more certainly that what at 300 Pedagogics as a System. lirst appeared to it as a foreign existence, belongs to it as its own property, and that it holds it as its own all the more by means of culture. — Plato, as is known, calls the feeling with which knowl- edge must begin, wonder ; but this can serve as a beginning only, for wonder itself can only express the tension between the subject and the object at their first encounter — a tension which would be impossible if they were not in themselves identical. Children have a longing for the far-off, the strange, and the wonderful, as if they hoped to find in these an expla- nation of themselves. They want the object to be a genuine object. That to which they are accustomed, which they see around them every da}^, seems to have no longer any objec- tive energy for them ; but an alarm of fire, banditti life, wild animals, gray old ruins, the robin's songs, and far-off happy islands, kc. — everything high-colored and dazzling — leads them irresistibly on. The necessity of the mind's making itself foreign to itself is that which makes children prefer to hear of the adventurous journeys of Sinbad than news of their own city or the history of their nation, and in youth this same necessity manifests itself in their desire of trav- elling.— § 25. This activity of the mind in allowing itself to be absorbed, and consciously so, in an object with the purpose of making it his own, or of producing it, is Work. But when the mind gives itself up to its objects as chance may present them or through arbitrariness, careless as to whether they have any result, such activity is Play. Work is laid out for the pupil by his teacher by authority, but in his play he is left to himself. § 26. Thus work and play must be sharply distinguished from each other. If one has not respect for work as an im- portant and substantial activity, he not only spoils play for his pupil, for this loses all its charm when deprived of the antithesis of an earnest, set task, but he undermines his re- spect for real existence. On the other hand, if he does not ^ive him space, time, and opportunity, for pla^^, he prevents the peculiarities of his pupil from developing freely through the exercise of his creative ingenuity. Play sends the pupil back refreshed to his work, since in play he forgets himself Pedagogics as a SysteTn. 301 in his own way, while in work he is required to forget him- self in a manner prescribed for him by another. — Play is of great importance in helping one to discover the true individualities of children, because in play they may betray thoughtlessly their inclinations. This antithesis of work and play runs through the entire life. Children anti- cipate in their play the earnest work of after life ; thus the little girl plays with her doll, and the boy pretends he is a soldier and in battle. — § 27. Work should never be treated as if it were play, nor play as if it were work. In general, the arts, the sciences, and productions, stand in this relation to each other: the accu- mulation of stores of knowledge is the recreation of the mind which is engaged in independent creation, and the practice of arts fills the same office to those whose work is to collect knowledge. § 28, Education seeks to transform every particular condi- tion so that it shall no longer seem strange to the mind or in anywise foreign to its own nature. This identity of conscious- ness, and the special character of anything done or endured by it, we call Habit [habitual conduct or behavior]. It con- ditions formall}^ all progress ; for that which is not yet be- come habit, but which we perform with design and an exer- cise of our will, is not yet a part of ourselves. § 29. As to Habit, we have to say next that it is at first inditferent as to what it relates. But that which is to be considered as indifferent or neutral cannot be defined in the abstract, but only in the concrete, because anything that is indifferent as to whether it shall act on these particular men, or in this special situation, is capable of another or even of the opj)osite meaning for another man or men for the same men or in other circumstances. Here, then, appeal must be made to the individual conscience in order to be able from the depths of individuality to separate what we can permit to ourselves from that which we must deny ourselves. The aim of Education must be to arouse in the pupil this spir- itual and ethical sensitiveness which does not recognize any- thing as merely indifferent, but rather knows how to seize in everything, even in the seemingly small, its universal hu- man significance. But in relation to the highest problems he 302 Pedagogics as a System. must learn that what concerns his own immediate personality is entire!}^ indifferent. § 30. Habit lays aside its indifference to an external action through reflection on the advantage or disadvantage of the same. AVhatever tends as a harmonious means to the reali- zation of an end is advantageous, but that is disadvantageous which, by contradicting its idea, hinders or destroys it. Ad- vantage and disadvantage being then only relative terms, a habit which is advantageous for one man in one case may be disadvantageous for another man, or even for the same man, under different circumstances. Education must, therefore, accustom the youth to judge as to the expediency or inexpe- diency of any action in its relation to the essential vocation of his life, so that he shall avoid that which does not promote its success. § 31. But the ahsolute distinction of habit is the moral dis- tinction between the good and the bad. For from this stand- point alone can we finally decide what is allowable and what is forbidden, what is advantageous and what is disadvan- tageous. g 32. As relates to form, habit may be either passive or ac- tive. The passive is that which teaches us to bear the vicis- situdes of nature as well as of history with such composure that Ave shall hold our ground against them, being always equal to ourselves, and that we shall not allow our power of acting to be paralyzed through any mutations of fortune. Passive habit is not to be confounded with obtuseness in re- ceiving impressions, a blank abstraction from the affair in hand which at bottom is found to be nothing more than a seliishness which desires to be left undisturbed ; it is simply composure of mind in view of changes over which we have no •control. While we vividly experience joy and sorrow, pain and pleasure — inwoven as these are with the change of sea- sons, of the weather, &c. — with the alternation of life and death, of happiness and misery, we ought nevertheless to harden ourselves against them so that at the same time in our consciousness of the supreme worth of the mind we shall build up the inaccessible stronghold of Freedom in ourselves. — Active habit [or behavior] is found realized in a wide range of activity which appears in manifold forms, such as skill. Pedagogics as a System. 303 dexterity, readiness of information, &c. It is a steeling of the internal for action upon the external, as the Passive is a steeling of the internal against the influences of the external. § 33. Habit is the general form which instruction takes. For since ifc reduces a condition or an activity within our- selves to an instinctive use and wont, it is necessary for any thorough instruction. But as, according to its content, it may be either proper or improper, advantageous or disadvan- tageous, good or bad, and according to its form may be the assimilation of the external by the internal, or the impress of the internal upon the external, Education must procure for the pupil the power of being able to free himself from one habit and to adopt another. Through his freedom he must be able not only to renounce any habit formed, but to form a new one ; and he must so govern his system of habits that it shall exhibit a constant progress of development into greater freedom. We must discipline ourselves, as a means toward the ever-changing realization of the Good in us, con- stantly to form and to break habits. — We must characterize those habits as bad which relate only to our convenience or our enjoyment. They are often not blamable in themselves, but there lies in them a hidden danger that they may allure us into luxury or effeminacy. But it is a false and mechanical way of looking at the affair if we suppose that a habit which has been formed by a cer- tain number of repetitions can be broken by an equal number of denials. We can never renounce a habit utterly except through a clearness of judgment which decides it to be unde- sirable, and through firmness of will. — § 34. Education comprehends also the reciprocal actign of the opposites, authority and obedience, rationality and indi- viduality, work and play, habit and spontaneity. If we ima- gine that these can be reconciled by rules, it will be in vain that we try to restrain the youth in these relations. But a failure in education in this particular is very possible through the freedom of the pupil, through special circumstances, or through the errors of the educator himself. Awd for this very reason any theory of Education must take into account in the beginning this negative possibility. It must consider be- forehand the dangers which threaten the pupil in all possible 304 Pedagogics as a System. ways even before they surround liim, and fortify liim against tlieni. Intentionally to expose him to temptation in order to prove his strength, is devilish ; and, on the other hand, to guard him against the chance of dangerous temptation, to wrap him in cotton (as the proverjb says), is womanish, ridic- ulous, fruitless, and much more dangerous ; for temptation comes not alone from without, but quite as often from with- in, and secret inclination seeks and creates for itself the opxH)rtuuity for its gratilicatiou, often perhaps an unnatural one. The truly preventive activity consists not in an abstract seclusion from the world, all of whose elements are innate in each individual, but in the activity of knowledge and disci- pline, modified according to age and culture. — If one endeavors to deprive the youth of all free and in- dividual intercourse with the world, one only falls into a continual watching of him, and the consciousness that he is watched destroj^s in him all elasticity of spirit, all confidence, all originality. The police shadow of control obscures all independence and sj^stematically accustoms him to depend- ence. As the tragi-comic story of Peter Schlemihls shows, one cannot lose his own shadow without falling into the sad- dest fatalities ; but the shadow of a constant companion, as in the pedagogical system of the Jesuits, undermines all naturalness. And if one endeavors too strictly to guard against that which is evil and forbidden, the intelligence of the pupils reacts in deceit against such efforts, till the educa- tors are amazed that such crimes as come often to light can have arisen under such careful control. — § 35. If there should appear in the youth any decided moral deforjnity which is opposed to the ideal of his education, the instructor must at once make inquiry as to the history of its origin, because the negative and the positive are very closely connected in his being, so that what appears to be negligence, rudeness, immorality, foolishness, or oddity, may arise from some real needs of the youth which in their development have only taken a wrong direction. § 36. If it s^iould appear on such examination that the negative action was only a product of wilful ignorance, of ca- price, or of arbitrariness on the part of the youth, then this calls for a simple prohibition on the part of the educator,, no Reproof and Punishment. 305 reason "being assigned. His authority must be sufficient to the pupil without any reason. Only when this has happened more than once, and the youth is old enough to understand, should the prohibition, together with the reason therefor, be given. — This should, however, be brief; the explanation must retain its disciplinary character, and must not become ex- tended into a doctrinal essay, for in such a case the youth easily forgets that it was his own misbehavior w^hich was the occasion of the explanation. The statement of the reason must be honest, and it must present to the youth the point most easy for him to seize. False reasons are morally blama- ble in themselves, and they tend only to confuse. It is a great mistake to unfold to the youth the broadening consequences which his act may bring. These uncertain possibilities seem to him too powerless to affect him particularly. The severe lecture wearies him, especially if it be stereotyped, as is apt to be the case with fault-finding and talkative instructors. But more unfortunate is it if the painting of the gloomy background to which the consequences of the wrong-doing of the youth may lead, should fill his feelings and imagination prematurely with gloomy fancies, because then the represen- tation has led him one step toward a state of wretchedness which in the future man may become fearful depression and degradation. — § 37. If the censure is accompanied with a threat of punish- ment, then we have the same kind of reproof which in daily life we call "scolding;" but if reproof is given, the pupil must be made to feel that it is in earnest. § 38. Only when all other efforts have failed, is punishment, which is the real negation of the error, the transgression, or the vice, justifiable. Punishment inflicts intentionally pain on the pupil, and its object is, by means of this sensation, to bring him to reason, a result which neither our simple prohi- bition, our explanation, nor our threat of punishment, has been able to reach. But the punishment, as such, must not refer to the subjective totality of the youth, or his dispo- sition in general, but only to the act which, as result, is a manifestation of the disposition. It acts mediately on the dis- position, but leaves the inner being untouched directly ; and Vol. vi.— 20 306 Correction versus Satisfaction of Justice. this is not only demanded by justice, but on account of the sophistry that is inherent in human nature, which desires to assign to a deed many motives, it is even necessary. g 89. Punisliment as an educational means is nevertheless essentially corrective, since, by leading the youth to a proper estimation of his fault and a positive change in his behavior, it seeks to improve him. At the same time it stands as a sad indication of the insufficiency of the means previously used. On no account sliould the youth be frightened from the com- mission of a misdemeanor, or from the repetition of his nega- tive deed through fear of punishment — a system which leads always to terrorism : but, although it may have this effect, it should, before all tilings, impress upon him the recognition of the fact tliat the negative is not allowed to act as it will without limitation, but rather that the Good and the True have the absolute power in the world, and that they are never without the means of overcoming anything that contradicts them. — In the statute-laws, punishment has the opposite office. It must first of all satisfy justice, and only after this is done can it attempt to improve the guilty. If a government should proceed on the same basis as the educator it would mistake its task, because it has to deal with adults, whom it elevates to the honorable position of responsibility for their own acts. The state must not go back to the psychological ethical gene- sis of a negative deed. It must assign to a secondary rank of importance the biograx)liical moment which contains the deed in process and the circumstances of a mitigating charac- ter, and it must consider first of all the deed in itself. It is quite otherwise with the educator; for he deals with human beings who are relatively undeveloped, and who are only growing toward responsibility. So long as they are still under the care of a teacher, the responsibility of their deed belongs in part to him. If we confound the standpoint in which punishment is administered in the state with that in education, we work much evil. — § 40. Punishment as a negation of a negation, considered as an educational means, cannot be determined a priori, but must always be modified by the peculiarities of the individual offender and by the peculiar circumstances. Its administra- Three Kinds of Punishment. 307 tion calls for the exercise of the ingenuity and tact of the educator. § 41. Generally speaking, we must make a distinction "be- between the sexes, as well as between the different periods of youth ; (1) some kind of corporal punishment is most suita- ble for children, (2) isolation for older boys and girls, and (3) punishment based on the sense of honor for young men and women. § 42. (1) Corporal punishment is the production of physical pain. The youth is generally whipped, and this kind of pun- ishment, provided always that it is not too often administered or with undue severity, is the proper wa}^ of dealing with wil- ful defiance, with obstinate carelessness, or with a really per- verted v.ill, so long or so often as the higher perception is closed against appeal. The imposing of other physical pun- ishment, e.g. that of depriving the pupil of food, partakes of cruelty. The view which sees in the rod the panacea for all the teacher's embarrassments is censurable, but equally un- desirable is the false sentimentality which assumes that the dignit}^ of humanity is afi'ected by a blow given to a child, and confounds self-conscious humanity with child-humanity, to which a blow is the most natural form of reaction, in which all other forms of influence at last end. — The fully-grown man ought never to be whipped, because this kind of punishment reduces him to the level of the child, and, when it becomes barbarous, to that of a brute animal, and so is absolutely degrading to him. In the English schools the rod is much used. If a pupil of the first class be put back into the second at Eton, he, although before exempt from flogging, becomes liable to it. But however necessary this system of flogging of the English aristocracy may be in the discipline of their schools, flogging in the English army is a shameful thing for the free people of Great Britain. — § 43. (2) By Isolation we remove the off'ender temporarily from the society of his fellows. The boy left alone, cut off from all companionship, and left absolutely to himself, suffers from a sense of helplessness. The time passes heavily, and soon he is very anxious to be allowed to return to the com- pany of parents, brothers and sisters, teachers and fellow- pupils. 308 Sense of Honor in tlie Pupil. — To leave a cliild entirely to himself without any supervi- sion, even if one shuts him up in a dark room, is as mistaken a practice as to leave a few together without supervision, as is too often done where they are kept after school, when they give the freest rein to their childish wantonness and commit the wildest pranks. — § 44. (3) This way of isolating a child does not touch his sense of honor at all, and is soon forgotten because it relates to only one side of his conduct. It is quite diit'erent from pun- ishment based on the sense of honor, which, in a formal manner, shuts the youth out from companionship because he has attacked the principle which holds society together, and for this reason can no longer be considered as belong- ing to it. Honor is the recognition of one individual by others as their equal. Through his error, or it may be his crime, he has simply made himself unequal to them, and in so far has separated himself from them, so that his banish- ment from their society is only the outward expression of the real isolation which he himself has brought to pass in his inner nature, and which he by means of his negative act only betrayed to the outer world. Since the punishment founded on the sense of honor affects the whole ethical man and makes a lasting impression upon his memory, extreme caution is necessary in its application lest a permanent injury be in- flicted upon the character. The idea of his perpetual con- tinuance in disgrace, destroys in a man all aspiration for improvement. - — Within the family this feeling of honor cannot be so ac- tively developed, because every member of it is bound to every other immediately by natural ties, and hence is equal to every other. Within its sacred circle, he who has isolated himself is still beloved, though it may be through tears. However bad may be the deed he has committed, he is never given up, but the deepest sympathy is felt for him because he is still brother, father, &c. But first in the contact of one family with another, and still more in the contact of an indi- vidual with any institution which is founded not on natural ties, but is set over against him as a distinct object, this feel- ing of honor appears. In the school, and in the matter of ranks and classes in a school, this is very important. — Limits of Education. 309 § 45. It is important to consider well this gradation of punishment (which, starting with sensuous physical pain, passes through the external teleology of temporary isolation up to the idealism of the sense of honor), both in relation to the different ages at which they are appropriate and to the training which they bring with them. Every punishment must be considered merely as a means to some end, and, in so far, as transitory. The pupil must always be deeply conscious that it is very painful to his instructor to be obliged to pun- ish him. This pathos of another's sorrow for the sake of his cure which he perceives in the mien, in the tone of the voice, in the delay with which the punishment is administered, will become a purifying fire for his soul. III. The Limits of Education. % 46. The form of Education reaches its limits with the idea of punishment, because this is the attempt to subsume the negative reality and to make it conformable to its positive idea. But the limits of Education are found in the idea of its nature, which is to fashion the individual into theoretical and practical rationality. Thfe authority of the Educator at last becomes imperceptible, and it passes over into advice and ex- ample, and obedience changes from blind conformity to free gratitude and attachment. Individuality wears off its rough edges, and is transfigured into the universality and necessity of Reason without losing in this process its identity. "Work becomes enjoyment, and he finds his play in a change of activity. The youth takes possession of himself, and can be left to himself. — There are two widely differing views with regard to the limits of Education. One lays great stress on the weakness of the pupil and the power of the teacher. According to this view. Education has for its province the entire formation of the youth. The despotism of this view often" manifests itself where large numbers are to be educated together, and with very undesirable results, because it assumes that the indivi- dual pupil is only a specimen of the whole, as if the school were a great factory where each piece of goods is to be stamped exactly like all the rest. Individuality is reduced 310 The Limits of Individuality. "by the tyranny of siicli despotism to one uniform level till all originality is destroyed, as in cloisters, barracks, and orphan asylums, Avhere only one individual seems to exist. There is a kind of Pedagogy also which fancies that one can thrust into or out of the individual pupil what one will. This may be called a superstitious belief in the power of Education, — ' The opposite extreme disbelieves this, and advances the pol- icy which lets alone and does nothing, urging that individu- ality is unconquerable, and that often the most careful and far-sighted education fails of reaching its aim in so far as it is opposed to the nature of the youth, and that this individu- ality has made of no avail all efforts toward the obtaining of any end which was opposed to it. This representation of the fruitlessness of all pedagogical efforts engenders an indiffer- ence towards it which would leave, as a result, only a sort of vegetation of individuality growing at hap-hazard, — § 47. The limit of Education is (1) a Subjective one, a limit made by the individuality of the youth. This is a definite limit. Whatever does not exist in this individu- ality as a possibility cannot be developed from it. Education can only lead and assist ; it cannot create. What Nature has denied to a man, Education cannot give him any more than it is able, on the other hand, to annihilate entirely his original gifts, although it is true that his talents may be suppressed, distorted, and measurably destroyed. But the decision of the question in what the real essence of any one's individuality consists can never be made with certainty till he has left behind him his years of development, because it is then only that he first arrives at the consciousness of his entire self; besides, at this critical time, in the first place, much knowledge only superficially acquired will drop off; and again, talents, long slumbering and unsuspected, may first make their appearance. Whatever has been forced upon a child in opposition to his individuality, whatever has been only driven into him and has lacked receptivity on his side, or a rational ground on the side of culture, remains at- tached to his being only as an external ornament, a foreign outgrowth which enfeebles his own proper character. — We must distinguish from that affectation which arises through a misunderstanding of the limit of individuality, the Limit in the Means of Education. 311 way whicli many children and young persons have of sup- posing when they see models finished and complete in grown persons, that they themselves are endowed by Nature with the power to develop into the same. When they see a real- ity which corresponds to their own possibility, the presenti- ment of a like or a similar attainment moves them to an imitation of it as a model personality. This may be some- times carried so far as to be disagreeable or ridiculous, but should not be too strongly censured, because it springs from a positive striving after culture, and needs only proper direction. — § 48. (2) The Ohjectixie limit of Education lies in the means which can be appropriated for it. That the talent for a certain culture shall be present is certainly the first thing ; but the cultivation of this talent is the second, and no less necessary. But how much cultivation can be given to it ex- tensively and intensively depends upon the means used, and these again are conditioned by the material resources of the family to which each one belongs. The greater and more valuable the means of culture which are found in a family are, the greater is the immediate advantage which the culture of each one has at the start. With regard to many of the arts and sciences this limit of education is of great signifi- cance. But the means alone are of no avail. The finest edu- cational apparatus will produce no fruit where correspond- ing talent is wanting, while on the other hand talent often accomplishes incredible feats with very limited means, and, if the way is only once open, makes of itself a centre of attrac- tion which draws to itself with magnetic power the necessary means. The moral culture of each one is however, fortu- nately from its very nature, out of the reach of such de- pendence. • — In considering the limit made by individuality we recog- nize the side of truth in that indifference which considers Education entirely superfluous, and in considering the means of culture we find the truth in the other extreme of pedagogi- cal despotism, which fancies that it can command whatever culture it chooses for any one without regard to his indi- viduality.— § 49. (3) The Absolute limit of Education is the time when the youth has apprehended the problem which he has to 312 Arrival at tTie age of Majority. solve, has learned to know the means at his disposal, and has acquired a certain facility in using them. The end and aim of Education is the emancipation of the youth. It strives to make him self-dependent, and as soon as he has become so it wishes to retire and to be able to leave him to the sole responsibility of his actions. To treat the youth after he has passed this point of time still as a youth, contradicts the very idea of Education, wliich idea finds its fullilment in the attain- ment of majority by the pupil. Since the accomplishment of education cancels the original inequality between the educa- tor and the pupil, nothing is more oppressing, nay, revolting to the latter than to be prevented by a continued dependence from the enjoyment of the freedom which he has earned. — The opposite extreme of the protracting of Education be- yond its proper time is necessarily the undue hastening of the Emancipation. — The question whether one is prepared for freedom has been often opened in politics. When any people have gone so far as to ask this question themselves, it is no longer a question whether that people are prepared for it, for without the consciousness of freedom this question would never have occurred to them. — § 50. Although educators must now leave the youth free, the necessity of further culture for him is still imperative. But it will no longer come directly through them. Their pre-arranged, pattern-making work is now supplanted by self- education. Each sketches for himself an ideal to which in his life he seeks to approximate every day. — In the work of self-culture one friend can help another by advice and example ; but he cannot educate, for education presupposes inequality. — The necessities of human nature produce societies in which equals seek to influence each other in a pedagogical way, since they establislf by certain steps of culture diff'erent classes. They presuppose Education in the ordinary sense. But they wish to bring about Educa- tion in a higher sense, and therefore they veil the last form of their ideal in the mystery of secrecy. — To one who lives on contented with himself and without the impulse toward self- culture, unless his unconcern springs from his belonging to a savage state of society, the Germans give the name of Philistine, and he is always repulsive to the student who is intoxicated with an ideal. ( 313 ) LECTURES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW. By James Hutchison Stirling. I. An Introduction to Philosophy in General* GentlemejS- : — My first word must be one of apology. Tliat an individual who is not a lawyer should address a distin- guished society of lawyers, and on their own science, has that in it — in direct statement at least — to suggest only audacity and presumption. This I have felt from the first ; and I have, all along, experienced a genuine reluctance to accept this place. Nevertheless, you yourselves have so willed it, and I have simply obeyed. I comfort myself with the thought, too, that it is not strictly into law that I am required to go, but rather into philosophy, though only so far as philosophy has legal bearings. I comfort myself, moreover, with this other circumstance — that, viewing the state of your information in this connection, whether private or public, I shall not be ex- pected by you to handle this subject propria Marte, but by the aid of another or others. Indeed, I may say at once that the result of my examination of a goodly pile of books, sup- plied to me by your own courtesy, was to convince me that not only was Hegel's statement the most valuable in itself, but that all the others of any importance were so saturated with it as to be unintelligible without Us intelligence. The production of this intelligence, besides, is one of the most important things that at the present moment requires to be effected, at the same time that it is one in which my own slight ability is as likely to be serviceable as in any other, perhaps. The philosophy of law, then, which I shall exhibit to you is that which has been presented in full detail by Hegel in the separate volume expressly published by himself, and named " Outlines of the Philosophy of Right, or Natural Right and Political Science in Ground Plan " — constituting, as I believe, the most valuable product of its author. Of the rest — Tren- delenburg, Roder, Hildenbrand, Heron, Austin, and all the * Delivered to the Juridical Society, Edinbui-gh, Nov. 9, 1871, and published in the Journal of Jurisprudence. Reprinted with the consent of the author and publisher. — Er>, 314 Lectures on the others — I hope to be able to say a word before concluding. Let me recommend to you noio only Hildenbrand, a work most accurate, most elegant, yet most easy, though steeped withal in the light of Hegel — a work, too, that shames our English books on the subject into impotent beggary. ;My situation, then, gentlemen, before you is a somewhat peculiar one ; and when I refer to it now, and all it implies, together with certain other circumstances of time, number, &c., known to some of you, as bearing on the composition of these lectures themselves, I wish to be understood as suggest- ing a few considerations in appeal to your indulgence, and I have no doubt that, with your well-trained minds, they will ver3- readily be taken^adl avlsandmn. It is m}' duty now, then, so far as my ability permits, to make you acquainted with the Philosophy of Right in the compass and character in which it presents itself, in its own place, within the system of Hegel. But that, as these very words suggest, entails some consideration of the system it- self in which it is imbedded, and of which it forms a part ; for only through a sufficient conception of that, the whole, with which it is in connection, and from which it rises, can we ever hope to arrive at an adequate knowledge of this, the part. Besides, it is an affair of common knowledge as regards Hegel, that, in his expositions, no matter presents itself which is not the product of his peculiar dialectic, at the same time that that dialectic itself takes origin from a single principle. A preliminary word, then, will be necessary on the general system of Hegel, its dialectic, and principle. In short, I fear I shall be necessitated to disclose to you — the " Secret of He- gel." Xow, do not for a moment fear, however, that I am going to inflict on you anything verj^ detailed or very ab- struse. Whatever I shall tell you shall be very short, and very plain, and, after all, perhaps, no such tax on your atten- tion. The possibility of this, of course, may — and very ex- cusably, perhaps— be doubted. For example, it is told of one of my best friends that, a gentleman finding him occupied with my work on Hegel, and inquiring what he thought of " the Secret;' he answered, " Why, I think tlie author has kept it!" I believe I saw from the papers too, lately, that some gentleman, examined somewhere as to the state of philosophy PMlosophy of Law. 315 at Oxford, and asked particularly as to whether the Hegel- ianism supposed to be there now prevalent was in any way due to the " Secret of Hegel," had boldly answered — " No ; that book only makes the dark darker ! " I fain hope there may be mercy for this gentleman ; but, in view of the state of conscience he must yet come to, I really am tempted to be- lieve that he will have a great fear in the end of going to — a Terj bad place ! But, joking apart, the "Secret" of Hegel is once for all open, and there need be no such very great difficulty in its regard — hard though Hegel may be to read after revelation of every secret. It appears to me that Mr. Lewes himself has at last found this to be the case. Not that I believe him yet truly to judge 'E.Qgel; but in the re-written article "Hegel," of the new edition of his " History of Philosophy," just pub- lished, he will be found to quote from my work on Hegel at least one passage in which it appears to me the Secret is very fairly named. But, be all that as it may, I think I shall have no difficulty in finding, in characterization of the general procedure of He- gel, the short preliminary word we require here. If it is possible to shut up Kant in a sentence, it is equally possible, in a sentence, to shut up Hegel. But Kant has been so shut up, and, as I believe, more than once. Here, from the " Note " on Kant in the second and third editions of the trans- lation of Schwegler, is what I consider one such sentence : " The sensations of the various special senses, received into the universal di^riori forms of space and time, are reduced into perceptive objects, connected together in a synthesis of experience, by the categories." Those who do not under- stand such phrases as " universal d priori forms," " percep- tive objects," "synthesis of experience," "categories," &c., will probably know just as little of Kant after this sentence as they did before it. Nevertheless, that is no impeachment of the truth of the assertion that this sentence does contain all the broad outlines of the cognitive theory of Kant ; and perhaps a word or two of explanation will demonstrate this — an explanation which I hope you will presently find to be in place. We can all fancy an ego, an I — fancy it as a unit or unity, as the primal unit, the primal unity. Well, to feel, 316 Lectures on the to know, this iiuit must be, so to speak, charged with some- thing, an object. Now this object, whatever it be, has parts ; it possesses a certain breadth ; it is, as compared with the unit into which it is received, a complex, a manifold ; and it is by- connecting the various units of this manifold to each other and to itself that the primal unit or unity, the ego or I, can come to possess, or, what is the same thing, to Tcnow an object. In an act of cognition, the primal unit, the I, then, reduces into its own unity the plurality of some manifold or object given to it. But the I does not effect this its function of unity, its uniting power, only in a single way. The I is strictly judgment, or the / in act is strictly judgment ; and judgment, as we know from logic, has twelve subordinate forms or func- tions, which functions are arranged by threes under the more general functions of quantity, quality, relation, and modality. We see now, then, the general constitution of the subjective factor in an act of knowledge, of what concerns the I as I. As regards the other factor in the same act, the object again, it is always a many or manifold of special sense in space and time. Now, as for space and time, they are (to Kant) neither notions nor sensations ; not the latter (sensations), for they are not due to any special sense, and they have not objects like other special sensations ; and not the former (notions), for, viewed in the relation of wholes and parts, they are seen to have the constitution, not of something intellectually or logi- cally understood, but of something sensuously perceived. Time and space, then, Kant reasons, being neither notions nor sensations, and being at the same time universal and neces- sary, must be pronounced general perceptive forms, d priori, or native to the mind, and lying in the mind from the first as necessary pre-conditions of special sense.' This last — special sense — again, is, in all its forms, a mere affection of the sub- ject exposed to the object. For, in all cases, an unknown ob- ject, or, as Kant calls it, a transcendental object, is to be sup- posed to act on special sense and excite the correspondent subjective affection. Here now, then, we have a view of Kant's whole world ; so far, at least, as cognition is concerned. There are the various affections of the various special senses (colors, feels, &c.) ; these are received into the general per- ceptive forms of space and time ; and, finally, through the Philosophy of Law. 317 twelve different categorical modes of it, they are reduced into the unity of self-consciousness, or the ego. Should I repeat the sentence, and say now, then, " the sensations of the va- rious special senses, received into the universal c^^r/ori forms of space and time, are reduced into perceptive objects, con- nected together in a synthesis of experience, by the catego- ries," I think it will perhaps be less difiicult for you to real- ize what is meant by Kant's cognitive theory being shut up in it. As for Hegel, we must understand him to have started from these constructions of Kant, and only to have modified them. To him Kant's great want was that of process, process deduc- tive, process interconnective. Starting with the I, the ego, he (Hegel) would have, like Fichte, the whole foison of the uni- verse derived from its one primal and, so to speak, constitutive act. Accordingly, it is not enough for Hegel to take up, like Kant, abstract logic as it presents itself, and say, there are twelve classes of logical judgment, and these represent twelve functions of unity in self-consciousness, or the ego. Hegel must see the ego develop out of its own self, according to its own law, according to its own rhythm, according to its own principle, according to its own special, original, and primitive nature — develop into the entire system of its own constituent inner furniture or contents. And in this we see, too, how Hegel differs from Fichte. Fichte assumes a sort of external law of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, according to which he externally develops the ego into its own. constitutive va- riety. Hegel will have nothing to do with such externality of procedure ; he must see the ego unfolding itself into its native variety, according to its own native principle, accord- ing to its own inner nature. Well then, having accomplished this — and you are simply to consider it done — having developed the ego, by its own law, into its own inner contents, Hegel will not, like Kant, only conceive it endowed further with two subjective percep- tive forms, two subjective cones of projection, and a variety of special sensational affections, which, received into and ex- ternalized by these cones, becomes reduced by the categories, or functional unities of the ego, into the innumerable special objects, and the one system, of experience. No; that is for 318 Lectures on tlie him still external, and still arbitrary procedure ; it is for liim unwarranted procedure, wliicli he must reject; and he con- ceives instead, after the internal process has reached its full sum. tlie same law to continue, and externalization of the whole internal sum to be the next result — externalization, that is, into this outward world of things. There is Nous to Hegel, thought, whicli, in obedience to its own law, mvolved into its own inner constituent sum ; is further, in obedience to the same law. evolved into its own obiter constituent sum, and that is the formed universe as it exists around us. In rela- tion to Kant, then, it is to shut up Hegel in a single sentence to say he conceives the ego to develop into its own categories, and these being complete, externalization to result from the same common law. Still Hegel, unlike Kant, thinks not of the particular ego — yours and mine — in this process, but of the universal ego. So, to him, the ego completed in its own inner, is Nous, thought, universal self-consciousness — God, " as He is in His eternal essence before the creation of nature or any finite spirit." This is fairly the amount of the preten- sion of Hegel when he so describes his logic as such " expo- sition" (Darstellung) of God. But, this being the case, then God's universe to Hegel is plainly but the contre-coup — the counter-stroke of God's own inner nature. This universe is only to him in externality what God is in internality, or it is in externality only what self -consciousness is in internality. These, then, are the leading ideas of these two men, Kant and Hegel, so far as theory^ or cognition^ is concerned; and if one sees in them great similarity, one sees in them also great difference. In Kant's world there is no knowledge of any noumenal existence. Although he postulates things in them- selves— that is, independent outer objects — to set up the affec- tions of sense in us, these affections (only further manipu- lated from within) alone constitute for him all that can be called things. And though he postulates a logical unity for self-consciousness, he kjiows no existential unity to corre- spond to the word soul : what we call our affections from within, as well as what we call our affections from without, are only 'phenomenally known. In fact, all that Kant knows are phenomenal affections, phenomenally projected into opti- cal spectra of externality, and then Icgically gathered in into PMlosopTiy of Law. 319 unities again. Whether as regards the subject or as regards the object, he is quite destitute of any noumenal knowledge. Without is but sensation, witliin is but sensation ; both are but stretched on two spectral skeletons, time and space, to be construed thence into what is called experience. The logical element is the only one in Kant that seems to possess any noumenal character, and that, too, rather in reference to xia- lidity than to existence. There is room in Kant — that is, for attaching to his logical element the character of noumenal or objective Tialidity, but scarcely that of noumenal or objective existence; for self-consciousness being only logical in his eyes, his whole logical element is left without any substan- tial basis of support — unless in the mere postulate of an inner thing in itself, as there is a postulate of outer things in them- selves. Now Hegel, though starting from these ideas, and deeply influenced by the importance of the logical element, still arrives in the end at a construction very different. The ego is not phenomenal to him, but noumenal ; then the furni- ture of the ego is not limited to these twelve categories, but •develops, and with rigorous necessity in every step, into a Tast rich system. The spectral perceptive forms of space and time again do not exist for him in that character : they are the universals of externality, but externality to him is neces- sary, objective, and actual. These, then, are great improve- ments on the scheme of Kant, and there results a theory which, supplied with an actually external time and space, .and an actually external world, is not repugnant to com- mon sense. It is in his conception of externality and ex- ternalization, indeed, that we have one of the happiest characteristics of Hegel. " God said, Let there be light ; and there was light": the summed internality burst into its accu- rately correspondent externality : the flash of light was the birth of the universe. Directly we understand Hegel's dia- lectic, there is no difficulty at all in conceiving internalization .as internalization here, and externalization as externalization there, but both together as mutually complementary co- factors, as correspondent pieces of one whole : they are the ■counterparts of the single tally. And in that case, also, it is not difficult to understand that all further characters of exter- nality will flow from the very idea of externality as external- 320 Lectures on the ity. There will be consequently a boundless possibility of outness, a boundless side by side of particulars, all material, but boundlessly differeiit. It is but in obedience to the gen- eral conception, too, that externality itself is not an absolute chaos ; that the shadow of the tree of intellect falls on it, con- trolling it, and that it returns in circles, narrowing and nar- rowing, up to the thought, the internality from which it start- ed, or from which it fell. In regard to this Hegelian theory of exterualization, I recollect one of our most famous citizens to have exclaimed to me, " I cannot take in all that d d nonsense. Do you mean to say that thought made granite ?" But I really do not see this to be so very difficult : it lies in the fact that in externality as externality there must be boundless material difference : granite is simply one of the differences. Altogether, I must acknowledge myself to find Hegel's 23lan of exterualization the happiest ever yet pro- posed — a plan necessary even when we say, as we do say> and 7?iust say, God made the world ; for it answers the ques- tion of hoio — precisely that question how God, how thought, made granite, for example.* From this account it will be evident, then, that Hegel is an idealist only as Aristotle is an idealist : he, like the Greek, * The moment the idea of externality as externalitj^ is seized, the great diffi- culty will be found at an end. One ought to ask one's self, what must the idea of externality — what must c.r.tcnudity itself be? Or, suppose you have iiiternal- ity completed — an ego, a boundless intussusception of thoughts, all in each other, and through or thorough each other, but all in the same geometrical point — what must its externalization — and its exterualization is accurately exter- nalization as externalization — be? Its externalization — it being an iwternaliza- tion— must plainly be the opposite of its ownself: whatever internalization is, externalization will be not; just as darkness and cold are precisely what light and heat are not. Or, taking it from the other end, we see that externality is infi- nite out a)id outness. inUnite difference, under infinite external necessity (or, what is the same tiling here, contingency)', while internality again is, and must be, infinite in and inness, infinite identity, under infinite internal necessity ("or, what is the same thing here, ruason). We can see here, too, the origin and meaning of Hegel's constant words, negation, and the negative. Externality is the negative of internality. But the former is the particular, while the latter is the universal : therefore the particular is always the negative of the universal. This may serve to show how deeply logic enters into e:cistence. The same connection finds mean- ing for Hegel's perjietual abstract. Abstraction, in general, is to take any char- acter in isolated self-identity; and that is the same thing as wresting any one 7noment apart from its connection with the rest into isolated self-identity — the work of understanding, not reaso7i. Philosophy of Law. 321 would simply reduce all things to notions, would simply re- duce all things to an ultimate generalization; and for what is ordinarily called idealism, he has not only no sympathy, "but an absolute contempt. Absolute or objective idealism is to him only the thinking of the universe ; but suhjectim idealism is that spurious idealism which would make exter- nality due to the internality of each particular subject, and then, for that simple act, take a big air as if it were philoso- phy. Hegel rejects such conception and such pretension ut- terly, and he is never tired of telling us so. In effect, it is a very insufficient reflection this, that because a knower can only know Avithin, therefore there is no independent external universe ; but that is really the bulk of what is called sub- jective idealism. There is another side from which the work of Hegel may be regarded. It is that of explanation in general, explana- tion as such. Man may go on as much as he likes in his merely animal capacity, marrying, doing business, journey- ing here and there, and enjoying his senses in general : he finds always in the end that that is not enough ; that he must think as well as live and enjoy ; above all, that he must think existence ; that he must inquire why, once for all, all this is here, lohy is it, whence is it, loMther does it go ? All that may be summed up in the single phrase : he demands explana- tion. Now, of course, there are a great many explanations now-a-days. Since Bacon, and, above all, Newton, there is what is called science. Explanation is sought for as regards the stars, and there is astronomy. Explanation is sought for as regards the atmosphere, and there is electricity, say. Ex- planation is sought for as regards the constituents of the earth, their inter-relations, their inter-combinations, e, an actual denizen, an actual thing present in t//at loMcli is. The Red Indian who exclaims of all that he sees, of thunder and lightning, of the gas when it is lit in a theatre possibly, Manoul Manou ! does not explain : he only exclaims ; he only excites the imagination of his hearers into the vision of a monster, of a creature of fancy, of a mere Yorstellung, that is only assum- ed, or said to have such and snch power, to be such and such a cause. It does not explain rain to say there is a spout above the clouds, although there are minds which would find them- selves quite contented with such a mere hypothetical image. Such mere hypothetical, mcarioics image of phantasy is not enough for Hegel, then : he must liud in that which actually is an all-fertile, an all-competent single principle. And here we see at once the reason of Hegel's dislike to the intidel god, the Gallic god, le dieu franc.-ais — that Hre supreme of Enlightenment, of the Illumination, that is an empty abstrac- tion, a barren image of phantasy on which all only is to be liung. But that is no prejudice to Hegel's prostration before God, before the true God, before that which is the eternal centre and root, and eveilasting substance of the world. He really and truly believes in God, but not in god that is only a topical god — a circumscribed, limited, particular something that is fancied up there — an enormous big man in the air that it is not absurd for Lalande the astronomer to try to see with his telescope. He has thought too much for that, he has read too much for that, he knows his catechism too well for that. He kn<.)ws that God is a Spirit ; that we cannot by physical searching find God out, but that we must worship Him in spirit and in truth. To that, at all events, his own words fairly amount. This apart then, Hegel, believing himself to acknowledge the true God, and averse only to the abstract god of the Auf- klarung, would find an explanation of all that is in some actual constituent of all that is. And that is thought, rea- son ; that is self- consciousness. Self-consciousness he finds to be the one aim of existence : all that is, is, he finds ouhj Philosophy of Law. 825 for self -consciousness. That is the one purpose of existence. Nature itself is but a gradual and graduated rise up from the dust of the field to the self-consciousness of man. This we can see for ourselves ; in the inorganic scale, up and up to the organic, and, in this latter, up and up to man. All is ex- plained only when it it is converted into thought, only when it is converted into ourselves, only when it is converted into self-consciousness. But if all only is for self-consciousness — if all can be converted into self-consciousness — if self-con- sciousness is the substance and the ultimate of all, then self- consciousness can be regarded as that which instituted all. self- consciousness can be regarded as the prius of all : all is only there for it, and to be explained into it. In this way it is seen, then, that self-consciousness is the principle of all ; in other words, that self-consciousness is the principle of ex- planation sought. Hegel's work, consequently, is but one of ultimate generalization, of ultimate Induction. Of actual facts, he finds self-consciousness the dominant one, the key to, and the raison d^etre of, all the rest. What follows, then, is that Hegel should apply this key. Of course, there are many men now-a-days, as I may just stop to remark, who only scorn as futile any such attempt as this of Hegel ; and to the sentiments of these men we ;j^nd from Xenophon that Socrates long ago gave voice and author- ity. " For he did not, like most of the others, debate of the nature of this all, speculating as to how what the Sophists call the woiid came into being, and by what necessities the various heavenly bodies were produced and he won- dered if it Avas not evident to these men that it was impossi- ble for man to find out these things." These words occur in the very first chapter of the Memorabilia, and there are more beside them to the same efi'ect, with general derision of these high speculative philosophers, who yet. as is further pointed out, with all their claims, have hardly an opinion in common. This th(^ opinion of Socrates is a very decided one, then. Hegel knows it well, too, but he does not let it trouble him. Rather, in direct opposition to Socrates, and to Socrates as piaised by Cicero, he boldly exclaims, "Philosophy cannot be worth anything to the lives and homes of men unless it come down from heaven ; and it is the one duty left us to 326 Lectures on the carry it up into heaven." In this, it is certain that, apart from that of Socrates, the highest names can be placed on tlie side of Hegel. Indeed it is difficult to find a single name on the whole bright file wliicli did not belong to one whose reflection was such as fell within the censure of Socrates. Plato and Aristotle directly followed him ; but the favorite speculation of both lay, we may say, in the hea'vens, and this not less in the case of the real Aristotle than in that of the ideal Plato. These names shall suffice, then, for the side of Hegel, and we shall let all the others, modern or ancient, pass. In a word, as I said already, reason demands an explanation of existence as existence ; and we must obey reason. On the part of Hegel, Ave shall see now. then, his applica- tion of the key d self-consciousness for this purpose. It was by induction, as we saw, that Hegel came to this key. Self- consciousness is in the world of facts, and all these other facts are only for it. It is the ultimate and essential drop of the universe, and explanation is only the reduction of all things into it. All things, indeed, stretch hands to it, rise in succes- sive circles ever nearer and nearer to it. Now, what is self- consciousness ? Its constitutive movement is the idealization of a particular through a universal into a singular, or, tak- ing it from the other end, it is the realization of a universal through a particular into a singular. Now that may appear a very hard saying, but it is a very simple one in reality : it is only a general naming of the general act of self-con- sciousness. In every act of self-consciousness that is, there is an object and a subject. The object on its side is a mate- rial externality of parts, while the subject on the other side again is an intellectual unity, but a unity that has within it, or behind it, a whole word of thoughts. It is by these thoughts the subject would master the object, reduce it into itself. These thoughts, then, that thus master the object, are the universals under which it is subsumed, and it, as so sub- sumed, is but the particular to these universals. The outward world, then, consists only of the particulars of the universals that constitute the inward world. I think this will be readily seen to be true. We can only think by generalizing, and generalizing is the reduction of particulars to universals. Evidently, then, in every act of self-consciousness particulars Pliilosopliy of Law. B27 meet universals in a singular. "We were right, consequently, in describing the constitutive movement of self-consciousness to be the idealization of a particular (the object) through a universal (the thought) into a singular (the subject). When we consider, moreover, that self-consciousness is the original substantial principle, the veritable prius of all, we shall see also that it is not incorrect to describe the constitutive move- ment of self-consciousness as the realization of a universal through a particular into a singular. Now, that is the No- tion— that is the Secret of Hegel. The mtal act of self con- sciousness is the notion. The single word notio involves all the three elements, a knowing (universal) of something (par- ticular) in a Icnower (singular). An act of knowing — idealiza- tion quite generally — is the reduction of a particular through a universal into a singular ; but e contra^ creation — and that is realization quite generally — is the exemplification of a uni- versal to a singular through a particular. This, then, is the one ground-notion which Hegel, by virtue of its own law, its own rhythm, as triple in its own form, and so triple that its units, though different from, are yet related to, and identical with, each other — this, I say, is the one ground-notion which Hegel sees develop before him out of its own self into the sum of its own inner constituent system of notions. That inner system he then calls idea. The notion is the first and the ever-present substance — every one of the derivative no- tions is but the notion — but the completed internal system of these notions, or of the notion, is the idea. The idea now, then, is the entire and complete universal, and it is only in obedience to the one ever-present law that it sunders into the particular — Nature. Nature again, the particular, returns to the universal in the singular. Mind, which gradully rises from its primal involution in nature up through all its forms to the Absolute Spirit. Universal, particular, and singular, are the three moments •of the notion, and everything organic^ everything true in this world is — however abstract its element — a concrete of these three moments, which can be seen to take on in the course of the development a thousand names, as thesis, antithesis, syn- thesis ; or a form which is a great favorite in my own expla- nations, simple apprehension, judgment, and reason. This 328 Lectures on the notion may be illustiated in a variety of ways. Wliat is or- gatiisation, for example — wluit is an organization to any pur- pose? Ketiect on it as you may, you will lind that it is the reduction of a many of particulars to the unity of a singular through the menstruum of universals — the plan and what it implies. Every concrete is but such organization. The family, for example : there is no perfect family where there is not the fuJjiUed IDEA, where each of the three moments, universal, particular, and singular, has not full justice accorded it. So the state ; a state must be idea — perfect harmony of univer- sal, particular, and singular, else it is imperfect and not a state. The state is the accomplished idea of the self- devel- oping notion : here free-will, and in it, if perfect, each of the moinentSy has its due jilace and its due scope. But is not the universe itself the best illusti'ation ? The universe itself i& but the realization of the universal through the particular in the singular ; and all that is said when we pronounce the sin- gle word — self-consciousness. Hegel's work now, then, can evidently be called simply the ultimate generalization. He sees that if we would ultimately explain, we must fairly generalize explanation itself. Expla- nation is always the reduction of an object into self-con- sciousness ; ultimate explanation, then, must be a reduction of all into self consciousness. But self-consciousness is a fact, it is something in rerum, natura, a principle actually exist- ing: Hegel's work, then, is in so mau}^ words the linal and universal induction. 13 lit 3'ou will say, perhaps, the self-consciousness that is in nature is ours — there is no other self-consciousness in nature than ours : are we to suppose that Hegel views my self-con- sciousness, your stdf-consciousness, his self-consciousness, as God ? In one way, I cannot deny this. Still Hegel's idealism, as I said already, is no subjective idealism : he does not con- (,'eive nature to be an externalization of the indimdualsubjecVs categories, notions, but of those cf the universal subject, of those of the universal self-consciousness. But Hegel, we might object further, would certainly admit that every individual linite subject might die, and yet the universe vrould subsist. What in that case were God ? Would not Hegel seem simply to conceive then a potential God — a God as it were asleep in Philosophy of Law. 329 nature — and who had yet to be realized afresh in other Unite self-consciousness ? There are professing adherents of Hegel — Ruge and the so-called party of German critics — who seem to entertain some such conception. I, for my part, admit that such may appear to be the case, so far as Hegel's develop- ments apart from time, apart from history, are concerned ; but I assert such an appearance no longer to obtain the mo- ment the development has entered the domain of spirit. In the sphere of religion especially, Hegel, as is well known, sums up his development in Christianity as the revealed re- ligion, and in the midst of numerous expressions that are unmistakably theistic. I may quote here what I said in the newspapers {Courant, Dec. 21, 1868) on this head three years ago: — "We are bound to accept Hegel's own professions. Again and again, and in the most emphatic manner, he has asserted himself not only to be politically conservative, but religiously orthodox — a Lutheran Christian. If we accept, as we do, his first assertion without difficulty, we have no right to deny his second. Indeed, however pantheistic the construc- tion, so to speak, in space may appear, the tables, as inti- mated, are wholly turned in the construction in time, and Hegel ends not only b}^ profession, but by philosophy, a the- ist and a Christian." I may say also, that this statement met at the time with the complete approbation of the non-Hegelian Professor Ue- berweg — non-Hegelian, but before his death, as both corre- spondence and actual published writings led me to believe, less and less so. Ueberweg, whose premature death — the pre- mature death of perhaps the most indefatigable philosophical student of his time — we are now justly lamenting, wrote me that his belief was quite mine as expressed in the quotation I have read, and that it was impossible to establish a nega- tive against such a religious claim for Hegel. Of course, it is to be allowed that Hegel philosophizes Christianity, and that his understanding of much is not such as John Knox would have accepted. Nevertheless, this is to be said, that Hegel would have claimed accord — substantially — even with John Kno:5i:. We believe the same historical fact and facts, he would have said ; only you see them in the Vorsiellungy while I see them in the Begriff. That at all events is really 330 Lectures on the the true nature of the case; and it is a j)iece of wisdom that is much needed at present. That single distinction between Vorstellung and Begriff is fitted to bring about perfect recon- ciliation between the beliefs of the less educated and those of the more educated, and give the Church peace. I may add, too, that every objection from the religious side that may be taken to the i'ole assigned by Ilegel to self-consciousness will disappear on due consideration of the text: "In His own im- age God created man." Returning again for a moment to the principle of self- consciousness itself, let me point out another advantage pos- sessed by it as a principle of explanation. It contains within itself both difference and identity^ and a little reflection will make it plain that there can be no possible explanation of this world Avitbout a principle that contains both elements. The origiu of difference in identity is the point and focus of the whole problem; but we have that at once in self- consciousness. Thought, reason, self-consciousness, is the one single necessity, the primal d-vdyxTj^ that that could not not be, and alone that that could not not be ; but thought, reason, self-consciousness, is by nature a duplicity in unity, difference in identity, for to know is to be always two things in one; what knows and what is known are for ever different but for ever identical. And so it is that evolution is possible ; for, after all, the w^ork of Hegel is certainly an evolution. It must be regarded, however, as only Si poten- tial one, only one in idea, not one that takes place or ever took place in time. And this gives it a vast superiority over ordinary evolution doctrines. To suppose that there ever was a natural first germ that naturally grew into another — as, for example, that the oyster ever grew into a man — is to suppose an absurdity. The evolution is — there — in idea — and that is really by power of the idea — but it never took place in natu- ral fact. All that ingenuity which would explain the pea- cock's tail by the loves of the female (whose comparative plainness then remains unaccountable) is but perverse and a waste of time — a waste of time in this, too, that science is quite unable to allow the explanation itself time enough. It would be easy to bring forward sufficient ingenuity to explain the spider's web — by a drop of accidental fluid accidentally Philosophy of Law. 331 emitted by some certain spider one fine day, that gave that accidental advantage which is necessary ; but would such Ingenuity, such Vorstellung, such mere fancy, be scientitic explanation ? The method of natural conjecture in fact, how- ever amusing, leads nowhere. But let us now, in conclusion, just ghiiice at Hegel's evolu- tion that precedes and results in the notion of law, to which all that I have yet said is only preliminary ; and I trust I have your excuse for spending so much time on what is only preliminary, my conviction being that any shorter previous explana^tion would have been futile. Hegel's system, as is now pretty well known, is contained in three great spheres — the Science of Logic, the Philosophy of Nature, and the Phi- losophy of Spirit. Here we see at once that what we have before us is the Notion. Logic is the universal, Nature is the particular, and Spirit is the Singular. Logic, having devel- oped into full Idea, passes into the particular as the particu- lar, into externalization as externalization, in Nature ; and Nature, rising and collecting itself, through sphere after sphere, from externality itself in the form of space, up to natural internality in the form of organic life, passes into Soul, which is the first form of Spirit. The instrument of the evolution all along, we are to understand, is the Notion in its three Moments. Omitting any closer consideration of the evolution in Logic and Nature — vast wholes of philosophy though they be — we shall pass to that of Spirit ; and here, too, we must be but perfunctory only until we reach our own subject. The three heads under which Spirit is treated are Subjective Spirit, Objective Spirit, and Absolute Spirit — obviously again in agreement with the three moments of the Notion. Under Subjective Spirit we have mind rising through its oion faculties to its own higher forms — -or the faculties themselves are represented but as successive stages of devel- opment in mind itself — and all as ever in obedience to the notion. Thus, theoretical spirit, or the spirit that knows, cognition that is, being complete, passes into practical spirit, the spirit that acts, the spirit that has will ; and will can only realize itself in the objective world of Law — in the State. And here we have reached at last our own subject. The in- troduction has been long, but not longer, I believe, than was 332 Fi elite's Facts of Consciousness. absolutely necessary to enable us to understand the move- ment of He2:el — that dialectic which we shall hnd as active in what concerns Right, Law, as elsewhere. Now. however, I think we may (^insider ourselves fully instruits : and at our next meeting we shall eliect the transition from the theo- retical to the practical spirit, and enter on the objective do- main of the latter — on the domain of will, and of law as its realization. FACTS OF CONSCIOUSNESS. Translated from the German of J. G. Fichte, by A. K. Kroeger. ^ O O XS. XX. FACTS OF COXSCIOUSXESS IX REGARD TO THE I'HACTICAl. FACILIV. CHAPTER III. The Tendency of the Ego to overcome the Check is posited us a Multipli- city of material Bodies, or as a System of Individuals. That which I actually — that is, in the region of my self- conlined power of imaging — produce through my causality is to confine my own external causality, so that no retraction of my thinking can retract its being. Na.y, what is more, even the contemplation of other beings like myself is to be bound b}^ it, as likewise by my own bodily existence. This is here simply my assertion, and presented simply as a mere pure fact of consciousness. Now this assertion in- volves the following : 1. There do exist outside of myself beings like myself. 2. These beings are bound to recognize me, by virtue of my bodily existence, as a being like themselves. 3. They are also bound to perceive the products of my ac- tivity in the material world. The latter two propositions I may safely take for granted after having assumed the first one. The whole is here repre- sented simply as a fact of consciousness without any deduc- tion or (what our deductions here are) junction with a higher link, since we have here as yet no higher link wherewith we Fichte^s Facts of Consciousness. 333 « •<'ould. bring tin's fact into conjunction, being as yet busy in the endeavor to get at such a higher link b}^ ascending from •our present point. Hence we haA e at present to see simply what this fact involves ; that is. to connect it with what is already known to us, and to comprehend it from that stand- point. First of all: liow do 1 get at all at that presupposition? How does the picture and the thought of such beings like me ontside of myself arise in me:' It is not only wonderful but ■contradictory to all our previous supi)osition. The life of free- dom and of consciousness has hitherto been represented as one ; all our deductions have been made from the oneness, and only by its means have we proved and explained. But now this one life evidently dirempts into many lives, which in their essence are to be like each other; hence this one life is here repeated in many forms, and repeated. How does this repetition occur ? Don't let us, by any means, ask as yet from what ground it occurs, for that question can probably be answered only in another place; but, through what fact does this positing of other beings outside of us occur i A. — In order to prepare our investigation, let us once more answer in all possible clearness the oft-answered question : how do I make myself a real principle i As an imaging prin- ciple I already have myself, and contemplate myself as such through the immediate internal contemplation of freedom. But, apart from this internal contemplation, I have another form of immediate consciousness, namely, my immediately through-itself- limited productive power of imaging. I at- tempt to apply also this second form to the Ego contemplated in the first described manner, and I find that this my produc- tive power of imaging is limited by this Ego also immediately and in a two-fold manner, namely, 1st, by that Ego as a ma- terial body ; and 2d, by the products of that Ego as a material body in a material world. Have I now, then, completely externalized the Ego, and placed it, through thinking, out of the region of immediate internal contemplation, in the region of external percep- tion? Yes and no. The bodily presentation of the Ego and its causality in the material world are externalized ; but the self-determinilig of this causality, the conception and plan 834 FicJite's Facts of Consciousness. that pivoedo it, remain as yei mere objects of internal contem- plation, and in so far tlie Ego has not yet been externalized. Bnt that causality, as the external, is conditioned by that self-derermining-. ur by that conception, as the internal, and without an internal we shall never get an external. Hence this Ego gets compli'tely externalized neither by tlie mere external contemplation or productive thinking, nor by the mere internal contemplation, but only by an absolutely in- separable synthesis of both. B. — I trv still further whether I cannot set this Eg:o — even be3'ond this synthesis and precisely as it occurs in this syn- thesis, namely, as composed of internal and external self- contemplation — by means of productive thinking from the now completed inner contemplation ; that is, wliether I can- not get hold of it in that purely original thinking, whereby it would — as an absolute giving out of the internal — get utterly cut off from this given internal contemplation, and would receive for the Ego of this internal contemplation an altogether peculiar on-itself-reposing Being ; becoming for this Ego a true non-Ego, j ust as happened in the case of the first product of free thinking, the merely material object of external perception, only in a much higher degree. I say, for the Ego of this hitherto described internal contemplation, although in-and-for-itself it may well be an Ego, since it has been tliought as such. I try and I lind that I not only can but must do so. The productive x)ower of imagination in attempting to realize such a tliinking finds itself compelled to realize it, that is, finds itself limited by the existence of such external Egos, and moreover — as results from the original form of the power of imaging — by an infinite number of possible Egos. The Ego must be externalized through thinking, and can be so externalized infinitely. Now, in what particular case this conception must be applied and realized we shall have to specify hereafter. C. — Let us, firstly, consider the form of this original think- ing of the Ego, that is, of externalizing. To be sure, the inner Ego is also thought and received into the form of indej)end- ent Being ; it is not thought, however, through the absolute original thinking, but by means of the inner c6ntemplation. Ficlite's Facts of Consciousness. 335 Now that previously described thinking of the mere material object of external perception appeared — at least in our tirst investigation — as grounded and conditioned through another, through the necessity to draft a conception of tlie activity which the impulse desires to achieve. Now we have no con- dition given for the thinking of an Ego be3'ond the Ego of immediate internal contemphition ; we liave posited it as an absolute fact. Hence this thinking is, at least here, an alto- gether unconditioned determination of pure and absolute thinking, and is therefore thought simply because it is thought, and thinking, itself, involves this particular think- ing. We cannot say, I think — produce — other Egos; but rather, universal and absolute thinking thinks — or thinkingly produces — those other Egos, and my own Ego amongst them. Hereafter we shall, perhaps, find a ground even of this think- ing; but it is already evident here that that ground cannot be of the same nature as the grounds and conditions here- tofore. D. — Let us now proceed to ascertain the contents of this absolute thought. The Ego is thought absolute — precisely as it was generated above through the absolute synthesis of internal and external contemplation, and as the uniting central point of both. Hence the thought Ego receives internally its immediate self-contemplation — its faculty of conception, of self-determination, &c.; and externally a mate- rially organized body and a possible causality in the mate- rial world, precisely as pertains to the first Ego, from which we started in our internal investigation. Now, the signiticant part here is this : the immediately internal contemplation is repeated, for the present at least, twice. But these two internal contemplations are separated by an absolute gulf, and neither of them can look into the other, since each one is not contemplated but thought by the other. What is this gulf? Evidently it is ur>on this distinction that I base my asser- tion, this is TTiy Ego ; and that I admit of my neighbor's Ego, although it is just like mine : this is not mine but his Ego; words that he, speaking of me, repeats in the same manner. Now, what does this duplication of the Ego into my Ego signify here ? Evidently it is the basis of the fundamental 336 Flchte's Facts of Consciousness. chanu'ter (^f the individual as such. What, then, is this character f Just remember how we arrived at all at an Ego. Knowl- edge retiected itself, and found and seized itself in the act, which act may thus be well called an altogether immediate (and if wc have named this internal an external) contempla- tion. J)iir ir was this contemplation which, gathered into the lixed form of thinking, tirst gave rise to an Ego, first as a knowing intelligence, and next as a principle : and this indeed was the origin of the lirst and in all our previous in- vestigations single, Ego : nor would any Ego have arisen without that reflection and self-contemplation of knowledge. Hence it follows that the actual existence of an Ego is grounded upon an absolute fact of immediate self-contempla- tion, namely, the self-contemplation of knowledge. At present this Ego is to be multiplied ; there are to be many Egos. This immediate self-contemplation must, there- fore, occur many times: that is, its fact must be multiplied, since every such fact is the ground of an Ego. Vice versa, to say that many Egos are posited, is to say that the fact of inner contemplation is posited as having occurred many times. That knowledge, which is internally contemplated in this fact, may well remain one and the same ; for we have neither said, nor does it result from our deduction, that this knowledge is repeated and posited many times. It is sim- ply the altogether seemingly accidental fact of contempla- tion, or of the reflection of that knowledge, which is posited many times ; and it is only thus that a manifold Ego of internal contemplation has flrst arisen. Now, with this ori- ginal fact of inner contemplation as its essential birth-place, there connects another Ego, which develops itself as a power of other internal contemplations, of an impulse, of a faculty, of freely-created conceptions. All that further occurs in internal contemplation is gathered into the unity of the Ego thought in virtue of that fact. Thus the Ego of each indi- vidual is that Ego which he has thought in virtue of that absolutely primary and original self-contemplation of knowledge which lirst gave him existence, and to which he now relates all that may occur in the same internal contem- plation. Hence the expression, r/r// Ego. The Ego which Fichtes Facts of Consciousness. 337 involves the my, and whereof "my" is the adjective, is the absolutely original Ego which has arisen through the imme- diate fact of self-contemplation. The second Ego, alluded to here, is the progression of the first original Ego in time ; and this progression occurring with freedom, and thus remaining under the control of the lirst original Ego, the original Ego appropriates it as its own and calls it its Ego. Hence that which we have described is the essential character of the individual as such, and through which the spheres of inter- nal contemplation, as based upon separate facts, separate from and mutually exclude each other. Result: the individuals as such are absolutely separate in themselves, complete single worlds, without an}" connection whatever. E. — Now, if we stopped here, life in the background as the matter of the manifold facts of reHection might well remain one and the same, as we have just now maintained; but it could certainly never arrive at a unity, at least in conscious- ness, since all consciousness would be altogether individual. Indeed it would even remain inexplicable how we. who con- fess ourselves to be individuals, could think such a unity, though it were simply problematically, and how we could possibh'- make ourselves understood about the matter. Hence if consciousness is to remain consciousness of the one life, as we have maintained from the iirst it must, that unity which was cancelled by individuality must be restored in that same consciousness. This must be restored of course ; firstly, since the inner contemplation is precisely the medium of cancel- ling the unity by going beyond this medium, by its opposite, which is thinking; and which, since it is a representation of the original and absolute unity, must be an original think- ing; and secondly, it must be restored just in so far as it is cancelled : that is, those individuals that have been separated into many lives in inner contemplation, must again be united in thinking as such and as remaining such ; in other words, they must all occur in the one same thinking. F. — Consider well what has been said. That thinking, which has as yet been described only factically in its rela- tive form as the opposite of inner contemplation, and hence as a going beyond that contemplation, obtains here, where Vol. \\.—-n 338 Fichte's Facts of Consciousness. its peculiar aiai inner essence is made apparent, an altogether difterent and higher signilicance. It becomes an immediate self-representation of life, as a one and in its unity. Hence it can be only a single thinking, corresponding, and agreeing with itself. This thinking is the representation or consciousness of life. Hence this thinking must occur everywhere where life enters the form of consciousness. This form it has entered in the individuals. Hence it must occur in these individuals, and, moreover, in all of them. It is in itself one, and must there- fore occur in all in the same manner. I say, the one life represents itself in this thinking in its nnity. But the individual as such is not at all life in its unity, but merel}^ a fragment of it. AVe cannot, ther(;fore, say at all that the individual as such thinks that thinking; or, if we do say so, we must add that it thinks that thinking not as an individual, but as the one and same life. It is in this thinking no longer a particular separate Ego, but the one and universal Ego. After a while we shall arrive at very remarkable applications of this proposition. If this thinking does occur in tlie individual, it will appear of course under the condition of free reflection, and not other- wise, in inner contemplation ; not as a product of the Ego, however, but simply as the expression of an absolute fact. Remarks. — The Science of Knowledge has generally been understood as ascribing effects to the individual — for instance, the production of the whole material world, &c. — which can- not at all be ascribed to it. Now, how is the Science of Knowl- edge, in truth, related to this objection? Thus: those who raised that objection fell into their misunderstanding pre- cisely because they themselves ascribed to the individual far more than appertains to it, and thus committed the very error which tlie}^ imputed to the Science of Knowledge. Hence, having once misunderstood the first principles of that science, they find that error in it even to a further extent than they themselves are inclined to grant to it. But they are alto- gether mistaken ; it is not the individual, but the one imme- diate spiritual life, which is the creator of all appearances, and hence also of the api)earing individuals. Hence the Sci- ence of Knowledge holds so very strictly, that this one life Ficlite's Facts of Consciousness. 339 be thought purely and without any substrate ; for the indi- vidual serves precisely as such substrate, and hence arise all ' their errors. Reason — or universal thinking, or knowledge simply — is higher and more than the individual. To be una- ble to think any other reason than one which an individual possesses as his accidence is to be unable to think reason at all. Hap23y the individual whom reason possesses ! Result: the described absolute thinking represents a com- munity of individuals. G. — This thinking is expression of life generally, and there- fore occurs necessarily wherever life arrives at consciousness. But life arrives at consciousness, as we have said above, in the individuals. It follows, therefore, that all actually exist- ing individuals — all points wherein knowledge has arrived at a contemplation of itself — must be necessarily thought from the stand-point of each individual. Just as I, indivi- dual, think the others, so the others again think me ; and as many as I think, so many think me. Thus all think the same community or system of individuals, with this only differ- ence, that each has another starting-point, another sphere of inner contemplation from which he starts. Each one thinks all the others through absolutely original thinking, but he does not think himself so; himself he produces through the described synthesis of both contemplations. H. — An Ego is necessarily thought as in an organized body. Hence each individual thinks necessarily all the others thus; for Egohoods and organized materiality are absolutely united in original thinking, or in the law of thinking, and hence they are so likewise in actual thinking, or in the following out of that thinking. Thus the previously first question, as to where the concep- tion of the Ego is applicable in actuality, is here answered as follows : wherever an organized body appears to the external sense, or — as we know better now — to the absolute thinking of a material world. It is not to be understood as if we con- cluded from the form of the body to the Ego, — neither imme- diately, for how could such a conclusion from one world to its direct opposite be possible ? nor mediately, because I, individual, have such a body, for how can I know that this body is not merel}'^ accidental, but belongs essentially and 340 HegeVs Phil^osophp of Histortj. absolutelv romvEn;(i? But the matter stands thus : V)otli, the thought of the K'jro auiritual grounds, and is therefore stronger than mcn-e nationality. Faith in the God of Abraham, and not parentage, which is only of secondary importance, makes the Jew a Jew. Moses, when very old, did not hesitate to espouse a negress. His brothers and sisterS' disapproved, but Jehovah punished them. Jesus expressed the freedom of faith from external hereditary descent, by ask- ing the Pharisees, who were proud of their genealogy, if the}'" did not believe God could raise up seed to Abraham from every stone. As Semites, the Jews did not deny a realistic sense for the goods of this world: they conquered Canaan, a land flowing wn'th milk and honey ; but the idea which in- spired them, and pervaded their entire life, was that of holi- ness. A closer analysis of their ethical organization shows that in real humanity they stood higher, before Christianity, than all other nations, although the history of the Jews is crowded with traces of the most depraved and abominable transgression, because in no people has the might of passion been shown in greater intensity against the law of God. By their faith ihey were free Froru the demoniac might of Nature which represses all other nations. This point alone makes it impossible to coordinate them with the other nations of antiquity. They were free from the pressure of history when its weight threatened to crush them, by the belief that their God still held out universal dominion to them. This faith consoles them to the present day., and causes them to regard Christianity as an episode in their his- tory. The Jews, like the Chinese, honor family piety, but they do not make it an exclusive principle. Like the East Indians they divided into tribes, but have not petrified in castes ; and the tribe of Levi, to which the discharge of priestly func- tions is committed, does not therefore enjoy the precedence of a holier or more divine tribe, for all are a priestly nation. IlegeVs Philosophy of History. 349 Holiness is the injunction upon every Jew, but he need not like the Buddhist become a monk and a beggar. The Jews are soldiers, and, up to the revolt of Bar-Chochba under Ha- drian, have shown an incomparable bravery which was ade- quate to contend with the most powerful nations. They did not set out. like the Persians, upon a career of conquests, but were content with that of Canaan as tlic ancient settlement of the descendants of Abraham. The Jew pursues agricul- ture and pasturage like the Egy])tJans, and trade like the Ba.bylonians and PlHTMiiciant;. without cariying this activity to a ruinous extent. In the constitution, he proceeds, like the Greek, from the conception of the community. The seventy elders constitute a senate — the aristocratic Roman element; the monarchical element can consequent!}^ reside only in God, who reveals His will to the people through the prophets. The kingdom was an inconsequence for the Jews, and the j^rophet Samuel expressly dissuaded tliem from it. After a short period of prosj)erity their state was brought to desolation through this very cause. After their return from exile, the centre of their entire organization fell more exclusivel}^ to the high-priests. The prophets, as the free representatives of the entire people, exercised the same function which we now call freedom of the press. The chief moment of the ori- ginal German state, feudalism, was not wanting among the Jews, inasmuch as they held all Canaan as a fief of Jeho- vah, which every fifty years should be returned to Him. I believe, therefore, that the position of the Jews in universal history is found by contrasting them, as the only true Theo- crats, with the nations of antiquity, but at the same time, in this antithesis, to place them higher than they. The Jews, like the Germans, are an absolute migratory people, which persists through all other peoples. The Germans generally lose their nationality among other nations and fuse with them, while the Jews know how to maintain theirs in every act of life. In the sketch which Hegel has given at the conclusion of his Philosophy of Right, he mentions the Israelitic people, on their entrance into the Germanic world, as that people among whom the ceaseless pain of the absolute separation of man from God made the transition to absolute atonement of God with men. This I believe to be the correct position of 350 Trendelenhurg on HegeVs System. the Jews. The following division of universal history results : (1) the National state, (2) the Theocratic state, (3) the state of Humanity. He concludes with the Germans because, with- in the Caucasian race, they are in fact that race to which the initiative of all further movement in universal history falls. From Europe they have spread themselves by navigation into everj^ quarter of ti. > world. They compel innumerable peoples in a state of natu. •\ who have previously stood outside the process of universal history, either to enter into it or to vanish. They compel, also, the old historical nations of the Orient to remove their rigid exclusiveness, and to attempt self-regeneration by a higher principle. THE LOGICAL QUESTION IN HEGEL'S SYSTEM. Translated from the German of Trendelenburg by Thos. Davidson. (Continued.) It has been often enough repeated, and Germany knows the formula by heart, that Hegel's great merit is that he defines God as a subject, in contradistinction to Spinozism which defines Him as substance. In the reply this is like- wise enlarged upon (p. 116 ei alibi). It may, perhaps, have been necessary to call attention on every possible occasion to this, inasmuch as a modern Spinozism has developed itself out of Hegel. An appeal is made to the consciences of those opponents who "assault Hegel with murderous intent, and mercilessly mangle him," not to condemn a philosophy in which God is assumed to be spirit (p. 131). Hegel's highest absolute principle is made to depend upon the significance of subject (p. 116), and the Logical Investigations are treated cavalierly because they do not touch this point — this solu- tion, given by Hegel — of the fundamental question of all phi- losophy. Is this last true? In a philosophy of cognition the mere dogma counts for nothing, while the process by which it is reached and proved counts for everything. The question therefore is, how this applies to Hegel. In him, the said process is based on the important and difficult part of the Logic {Encyclopcedia., § 150 sqq.), in which it is supposed Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 351 to be shown how, according, to dialectic reason, the necessity which is the attribute of substance passes over into the free- dom of the idea. There and nowliere else in Hegel is the primum moxiens which draws the thinking on from substance to subject. In the Logical limestigations^ therefore (I., p. 50 sqq.*), this most important of all dialectic transitions, upon which the weight of the whole system rests, was carefully considered, and shovv^n to be witliout any support, and to give way and vanish as soon as it is touched. While sub- stance may get outside of itself, subject, we are told, is with itself {apud se). But it was shown that this being-with-itself of Hegel's rests merely upon a vague, feeble comparison — a play of similar expressions. It was demonstrated that the process by which it was reached would apply as well to blind emanation as to free creation from the idea of purpose, and that, hence, it contains no progress from the doctrine of sub- stance to subject. The logical difficulty was at the same time made apparent; for it was the logical question that was under discussion. How does the reply venture to speak as if no no- tice had been taken of this determination, which is supposed to condition all the rest? Does it go even so far, seeing that it appeals so often to the elevation of substance to subject, as to remove those inherent obstacles which were shown to ex- ist? It was easier to pass over the objections raised without one word of comment. If, however, it is true that, in Hegel, the doctrine which is so warmly recommended in the reply rests, in its deepest metaphysical basis, .on this sole point of the Logic, then that doctrine must stand or fall with it. That, in its new shape, it seeks for a new support, is of no consequence ; if it is to continue true to Hegel, it cannot get round this original ground ; while, if it does not continue true to Hegel, it no longer comes within the limits of our discussion. In Hegel's Logic, the point in question is one of the bold- est turns taken by the negativity. If, as is the case, the reply accuses us of not having considered closely enough this fun- damental law of all thinking, wliich is likewise a fundamen- tal law of all being, what we have said above is a sufficient . . X * Third edition, p. 51 sqq. — Tr. 352 Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. refutation of the charge. Wh^' should the reply at all insist upon investigations, seeing that itself does not condescend to any of those proposed to it? It is, however, the opposite of correct to assert that the Negativity has not been investi- gated. The Negativity, the perpetual spui- of tlie dialectic movement of thought, so highly extolled again in th<' reply, rests, in Hegel's view, on negation and identity ; and indeed on the latter, inasmuch as it is the negation of negation. Both these logical appliances were fully and fairly put to the test, both in their princii)le and in their different applica- tions, and rejected as ambiguous and untenable {Log. Inn. I., pp. 30-56). Sometimes, in Hegel, the Negativity shoots olf on the leaping-pole of the progressus in infinitum; but it also broke down under the hands of criticism {Log. Inv. I., pp. 55 sq.) Before Gabler asserted that the author of the Logi- cal Lit esti gat Ions., having no knowledge of the fact that the negativity was the soul in the forms of dialectic development, or of thf' manner of its operation, had not specially made it a subject of criticism, he might have read those jjassages, or else he might have shown what logical element^ besides those discussed, was contained in the negativity. It was incumbent upon him, not to repeat in vague terms a eulogy on negativ- ity, but simply, in accordance with this fundamental law, to employ the energetic negation of negation on the negation of our criticism, so as not to allow the negativity to stick fast in the negation, but to bring it out in the positivity claimed for it. But there was not even an attempt made in this direction. " Negativity " is an imposing word ; as an abstraction, it keeps the intuition suspended and the mind in wonderment. As Plato in the Philehus tells us that the youth triumphed as if they had found a treasure of wisdom, when they made their first acquaintance with the One and the Many, and, in their enthusiasm, applied it to every concept, so precisely it is with the cognate fundamental law of negativity: for, of course, everything is intrinsically negative, in everything there is tiux, in everything there is distinction; and what is easier than to place the aim " which repels itself from itself" under negativity ? But the result is much less considerable in the case of the negativity than in that of the great treasure- house of "The One and the MauA^": for it is such an abstrac- Trendeleiiburg on HegeVs System. 353 tion as no longer represents an original and productive Uni- versal, but has upset itself and thus lost all tangibility. If we are honored with some sprinklings of praise, because the principle of motion brought forward in the Logical Innestiga- tions is similar to negativity, we object to any such kinship. Negativity is like a large mantle, of which many folds can be made, to stow away the most various things. It is, as our investigation has shown, entirelj^ indefinite and ambiguous. Against it the Logical Intiestigations rebelled, and endea- vored to free the conceptive faculty from the spell with which this and similar words had bound it. They restored to intuition its freedom, and thereby to thought its defi- niteness, by proving that movement, which outlines and produces a picture, was the intellectual principle of intui- tion and form. The Proteus of negativity would do well to keep at a respectful distance from it ; he would meet his death in it. In the Logical Livesti gat ions, and in the brief statement afterwards published, the result of the inquiry into the dia- lectic method went to show that it was per se impossible. Our author feels, in spite of his attempt to make the position of the dialectic method less fatal, that still Hegel's philoso- phy becomes an impossible system, and therefore enters the strongest protests against this ruling. Is the existence of the case a proof of its intrinsic possibility ? That will not pass muster ; for, as the reply itself says, the very questions at issue are those of existence and recognition. Or, was the judgment in the Logical Ininestigations merely a feint an- nounced with a flourish of trumpets ? Neither can that be asserted. For the judgment was well supported by the proofs brought forward in the course of a long investigation. It was proved, and in the statement of the position of the question again asserted, that all the logical means used by the dialec- tic method fell to pieces, and, measured by the standard of their own purpose, were sadly insufficient and even impossi- ble. The simple conclusion was, that the dialectic method was intrinsically impossible, because its means were so. From this demonstration, apart from good assurances, which are not spared, but which avail nothing, there is but one means of escape. It would have to be shown that those logi- Vol. vi.— 23 3 354 Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. cal means (negation, identity, progress in infinitum) really perform wliat tliey promise, and, just because they perform it, have an energic actuality over and above their intrinsic possibility. Has this been done ? The reply takes the shorter way of preferring not to touch the point at all (p. 204). "We are perfectly satisfied with this, since, supported by the old grounds, we may again pronounce the judgment that the dia- lectic method of pure thought is in itself impossible, and add that it has not been rendered a whit more possible by the reply in question. Hegel's Logic asserted that, as opposed to all intuition, even to the geometric figure, it moved in the element of pure thought, and, without any presupposition, developed from this alone an uninterrupted ''immanent" series of metaphys- ical concepts. We, on the other hand, showed, both in general and in particular, that the presuppositionless logic everj^where presupposes the principle and the general activ- ity of intuition, and thus in secret possesses a picture which in public it contemns ; we showed that, instead of developing from itself a closely-knit series, it smuggled in the despised intuitions of experience, diluted and weakened, and gave them out as products of its own soil. What has the reply to say to this thorough-going proof? "The manifest discovery," it says, (p. 193 sqq.) "does not touch the thing itself — the pure concepts — in their distinct form, but merely their origin — the source from which they come into thought"; it does not touch the what of the pure immaterial concepts and determinations of thought, but rather tTieir origin in tliouglit. In the first instance, this is certainly the whole question. Did the asser- tion of presuppositionless thinking, and of immanent inter- connection, mean anything else than that the concepts did not How from a foreign source, e.g. from intuition, but from the native one of pure thought? Only the delusiveness of this magnificent promise was to be shown. Tlie reply, if we understand it correctly, admits this proof — and how much is thereby admitted ! — but it consoles itself with the distinction that the question of the whence does not touch the what. Is this possible in the present instance ? Hitherto, for exam- ple, it was asserted in Hegel's Logic, that continuous and discrete, extensive and intensive magnitude, attraction and Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 355 repulsion, all occurring in the first part of the Logic, not as concrete examples and applications, but as the purest deter- minations, were to be seized as concepts of the pure think- ing without intuition, and therefore without that movement which produces the geometrical figure. If the opposite of this it has been proved, it touches the -what of the pure con- cepts so far, that there are no such "pure concepts" in dis- junct form. The author of the reply is perhaps aware of this ; for he glides rapidly over the dangerous point, and vents his spleen in heavy charges of empiricism and materialism, with which he loads the Logical Investigations. TVe shall not waste a word on these charges, since the per- son who can believe that such accusations will cling to the work, cannot have read it, or must have read it merely with the eyes on his face. It is true that it does not deal with any sort of dialectic idealism, which, unconcerned about any con- nection with the other sciences, and despising any contradic- tion which the latter, with the support of facts, might raise against Philosophy, dwells on the royal heights of the pure idea, with an empire all to itself, perfectly secure against being confounded with empiricism. If, however. Philosophy is, as Schleiermacher somewhere calls it, the central science, and there is no centre except with reference to the circumfer- ence, just as there is no circumference save with reference to the centre, then surely the time has come at last to strive for further progress, and to bring about a living connection be- tween the central and the peripheral sciences. Logic must become a metaphysic of the actual sciences, in the sense that it must comprehend their real principles in order to compre- hend the act of thinking within its sphere, and thus to become a true logic. Are we to be accused of empiricism because we deal with experience in this sense ? The fact that we are so accused is indeed perfectly intelligible from the stand-point of dialectic idealism, but not from that of imjDartial criti- cism, which would have justice enough to remark and to recognize, that we on all occasions and even in the very midst of experience look only for its spiritual origin, i.e. the very thing which has not experience in it. It was our wish, in writing the previous article, to treat the logical question in Hegel's system by itself, and to keep 356 TrendeJenhurg on HegeVs System. apart, as something altogether foreign, our own logical inves- tigations in so far as they investigate positively the essence of cognition. In the reply, the two are commingled, and defence, as is perfectl}^ fair, is supplemented by attack. We must therefore add a few words in regard to the method of criticism, in order to remove from the question at issue the false lights and shadows that are thrown upon it from this quarter. Firstly, there is one thing characteristic. In a long book written to criticise another, the reader looks in vain for the real content of the latter, as forming the basis of the criti- cism. He looks in vain for an outline of the Investigations, for a sketch of their method, for the sum of their results, for a presentation of the fundamental thought. Only from such a survey could he derive a notion of what the Logical Inves- tigations specially attempt, and whether they unite to form a spiritual whole. A person who knows a system only by the headings of the paragraphs, is not likely to find it in them ; whereas the person who is able to follow it through the windings of the investigations and to restate it in his own words, will not miss it. When the reader of the reply puts it down, he is as wise respecting the purpose and essence of the Logical Investigations as he was before he took them up ; or, what is perhaps worse, his head is filled with the most contradictory judgments, since the reply is a perfect conglo- merate of appreciation and depreciation, respect and disre- spect. At one time, the author of the Logical Investigations is a disciple of Aristotle, who, be it remembered, is counted \>j Hegel among the speculative philosophers ; at another time, he is an empiricist and a materialist, utterly destitute of anything speculative: according to one passage, he fights with Hegel for the present world- consciousness ; at another, he is related only to Bacon and Locke, although these are long ago buried for German science; — at one time, his phi- losophy is valuable as a propaedeutic which might pass for Hegelian ; at another, he has written only for "business men" (p. 177); — at one time, the Logical Investigations appear to merit a place among literary productions ; at another, they are described as a mere rude compilation, without plan or principle (pp. 178 sqq.), so that the reader cannot help won- Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 357 dering why, for the sake of such a book, our author under- took to write another book, and why he found himself com- pelled by it to put his old system into a new shape ; — at one time, the reply attributes to the development of the catego- ries and principles {principia) a value which it afterwards lowers by the additional assertion that Hegel also has them, only in a somewhat different shape (?!); — at one time, he denies to the enumeration (which, a moment before, he called development) every claim to system ; — in another place, it honors the organic world-view with which the Logical Inves- tigations close with a certain amount of applause ; at another, it hints that this world- view is such as might be suitable for children, although, of course, it would be of no use to them, as they do not philosophize (p. 188). But has Gabler quite perused, or quite overlooked, the Logical Livestigations, about which he has written a book? We must be allowed to express our doubts. He would hard- ly, for example, have ventured (pp. 184 sq.), in plain terms, to refer the author of the Logical Livestigations to Hegel's treatment and derivation of the categories, if he had remem- bered that the same had been subjected to a careful examin- ation {Log. Intl. H., pp. 62 sqq.), in which they were shown to be entirely unequal to developing the possibility of this con- cept, and proving the necessity of its dominance. He would hardly, had he known the whole, have given all kinds of good counsels, which the Logical Investigations had long ago fol- lowed of their own accord (e.g. cf. p. 184 ad Jin., with Log. Invest, n., pp. 62 sqq.) He would hardly have hinted — we cannot understand the passage otherwise (p. 187) — that the Logical Investigations, pregnant with materialism, " looked upon thought as a mere accessory, or something merely secondary and superinduced," if he had considered, what is pointedly shown (H., pp. 62 sqq.), that the world, penetrated as it is with purpose, can be understood only by admitting the priority of thought. He would hardly have charged the Logical Investigations with a blind reverence for nature (e.g. p. 179), if he had only remarked their general tendency, which is to prove that the comprehension of nature, in move- ment and in purpose, is derived entirely from the original Spiritual in nature. He would hardly have ventured to tax 358 Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. tlie wliole view with vulgar empiricism (pp. 193, 197, &c.), if he had considered that same general tendency, and if he had been aware of the war which the Logical Investigations wage with empiricism, and that too in the very midst of the facts? for the sake of this tendency (e.g. I., pp. 206 sqq., 274, sqq., &"c.) He would scarcely have had the hardihood to assert (p. 200) that the Logical Investigations abandon the a-priority of time and space, while, on the contrary, they everywhere strive to prove that the spiritual a-priority of movement with its products, time and space, alone affords a key to the great scientific, ^ pr/on fact of. pure mathematics, and use every effort to show that the objectivity of these categories is not thereby excluded, and that the same a-priority is the basis of all empiricism (cf. the whole of Investigations 5 a,nd 6, pp. 124-277). He would hardly have ventured to squeeze a single expression respecting the idea, till he brought out of it the result, that, according to the Logical Investigations., it is only as substance (Spinozan?!) that God lies at the basis of the world (p. 189), if he had remembered that the idea is idea only through the creative thought of aim {Zweclc) (H., pp. 359 sqq.) He would hardly have ventured to counsel the Logical Investigations to follow the fundamental principle of the Hege- lian system, which is, at the same time, the logical principle of form, through the sphere of philosophy, and prove it insuffi- cient and incapable of explaining anything, if he had reflected that the section on the dialectic method and the criticism of the Hegelian notion of aim have performed said task, and that it is precisely Hegel's logical principle of form that so com- pletely breaks down in the detailed examination of his devel- opment of the judgment (II., pp. 190 sqq., and the syllogism (II., pp. 251 sqq.) He would scarcely have said that the Logi- cal Investigations were unacquainted with the Hegelian syllogism, and acted as if they had confounded it with the scholastic syllogism, if he had remembered how (II., pp. 251- 279) they first turn it round and consider it from all sides, before they declare that Hegel's twisted theory of three times three syllogisms, which are supposed to produce and classify the system of things in their reality, was manufactured and untrue. These facts are incredible, but they are facts. If our author could overlook all these and many other things, where, Trendelenburg on HegeVs System. 359 with such defects of knowledge and misconceptions in regard to matters of fact, remains the right to criticize ? The author of the reply cannot get rid of himself. For what is peculiar in the writings of others, for the specific in the tout ensemble of the doctrine of his opponents, he has no eye, and, therefore, no expression. He evidently feels hostile to an investigation which pursues a path different from his, and which takes iDains, in dealing with the elements of thought, till, after quiet progress, it comes at last to a point at which the elements necessarily coalesce in the fact of a whole. Ever and everywhere the absolute comes up in his writing, as if it were the only question, and as if human thinking, which, after all, in the broad sphere of the sciences, thinks the finite in the first instance, did not move at all in the finite. It shows itself likewise in the outward form, so that he never succeeds in bridling and controlling the association of his own ideas long enough to make those of other people his own. For while, as a general rule, people are not given to interrupting each other, he everywhere interlards other people's state- ments with interjections and remarks of his own. "When these parentheses and interjections are taken away, there re- mains very little counter-argument. But parentheses will hardly pass for discussions, or interjections for solid judg- ments. After all, there is a great difference between real and manufactured consequences. Real ones lie in that which is based upon a principle, and such of those scientific conse- quences as do not appear in the Logical In'vestigations will be shown hereafter in the further carrying out of the thought. Manufactured consequences, on the other hand, lie in one- sided half-truths picked up at random, and in words caught and pressed into service (p. 189). We decline to accept any ransom for the captives taken in our work ; they will get freed without our help, in the mind of the intelligent reader. The objections raised in the reply are altogether not of a kind to prevent us in any way from continuing our superstructure on the basis of the Logical Investigations. At the same time, it is quite natural that our opponents should try to make us oc- cupy an "obsolete stand-point" {uberwunderer Standpunct), one assigning us to empiricism, a second to Aristotle, a third to Kant, a fourth to Herakleitos. Let us, think they, dress 360 Treiidelenhurg on HegeVs System. him up in some old worn-out dress of the world- spirit ; and the present, which wants fashion, will not look at him. There is, perhaps, reason in that. How manj^ stand-points,* however, Hegel has made obsolete, is shown by the present rebellion of all. It is the aim of the reply to force the examination of human tliought ever toward the Absolute, and to maintain Hegel's Absolute, — although in a new shape, which will per- haps be as little recognized by foes or friends as Gabler is inclined to recognize the dressing up of Hegel's in the gold frame of fancy and the trappings of poetry (p. IV.) But as this new shape, like every other shape which calls itself an emanation from Hegel, rests on the dialectic method, every- thing, as was shown in the previous article, reduces itself to the question whether the dialectic method of pure thinking is correct. If it is false, there arises from it no knowledge, and no new mode of seizing the Absolute. It is therefore of no use to swing round in one's own circle ; the question al- ways comes up again : What has been done to redeem the dialectic method ? for it is the basis of the whole. In the previous article, the main points at issue were clear- ly set forth ; they were, 1°. The suppositionless beginning; 2°. The immanent interconnection ; 3°. The significance of the negation ; 4°. The power of identity ; 5°. The application of the progressus in infinitum ; 6°. The methodical hysteron-proteron of the dialectic de- velojjment; 7°. The delusiveness of the Hegelian syllogism. Among these, again, the assertion of the absence of presup; position, the negation, and the identity, stand prominent as the real pillars of the whole edifice. In the reply, there is as good as nothing on all these points — at least, there is scarcely one word looking at all like a refutation, or really bringing home a misappreliension. It brings no danger except to the cause wliich the reply defends, when it refuses to occupy itself with all these things, or, as we say, does not stand up and hold its own. Thus, then, the Logical Question in HegeVs System stands at precisely the same point where it stood at The Merchant of Ve7iice. 361 the close of the previous essay ; there is not a single iota cleared up. At best, we have been shown, by one example, how it can not be cleared up. We are told in the Theaitetos of Plato, in connection with that movement, to which Hegel compared the negativity, con- cerning the disciples of the profound Herakleitos : — "About these speculations of Herakleitos which, as you saj^, are as old as Homer, or even older still, the Ephesians themselves, who profess to know them, are downright mad, and you can- not talk with them about them. For, in accordance with their text-books, they are always in motion ; but as for dwelling upon an argument or a question, and quietly asking and an- swering in turn, they are absolutely without the power of doing this ; or, rather, they have no particle of rest in them, and they are in a state of negation of rest which no words can express. If you ask any one of them a question, he will produce, as from a quiver, sayings brief and dark, and shoot them at you ; and if you inquire the reason of what he has said, you will be hit by some other new-fangled word, and loill maTce no way with any of them, nor they with one another^ THE MERCHANT OF VENICE. By D. J. Snidbr. ' [_Conclusion of the Article in the Ajyril nu')nhei\'\ In a late number of the Journal there was a partial analy- sis of Shakespeare's "Merchant of Venice." We now propose to complete that criticism by extending it to other parts of the same drama. But lirst it will be well to recapitulate the results arrived at in the former essay. Only the leading col- lision of the play was there developed, that between Shy lock and Antonio. The first characteristic to be observed in re- spect to these two characters is that the one was a Jew and the other a Christian ; hence the historical collision involved in the drama was between the Hebrew and the modern world. But, in the second place, this collision was elevated from a merely natural to a spiritual basis by the ends which these two men proposed ; that of Shylock being the acquisition of 362 The Mercliant of Yenice. gain, in general Thrift; while that of Antonio, though he was a nieirhant, subordinated money to higher purposes. In the third place, Shylock's end— Property— is absolutely contirmed and protected b}^ Law, which possesses objective validity, and cannot be assailed with impunity. With this mighty principle Antonio falls into conflict by his bond, for bonds and all contracts must be held sacred if property be protected. Hence Law enforces Shylock's end and seizes upon Antonio. But Formal Law manifests its lim- itation tlirough its own self-contradiction and thus annuls itself,— this is the point made by Portia in her celebrated defence whereby Antonio is saved. But this result cannot be final, for it is purely negative and terminates in the annulment of Law ; hence we pass to a higher principle wliich takes up and harmonizes within itself the negation before mentioned, namely, the principle of Mercy, which in its turn saves the Jew. When Law becomes self-contradic- tory, annihilates' its own end, destroys that which it was made to protect, there must be some way of abating its action, and this is accomplished by a system of mercy. But let it not be forgotten that within its own sphere Law is paramount, and cannot be interfered with from any quarter. The reason why the Jew does not perish, though he has willed and tried to commit murder, is that he was the real object of mercy, since he was arraigned for subjective intention which lay outside of his consciousness. Hence he was in truth not responsible. iSTor could the court and Portia reasonably condemn the Jew after they had maintained the cause of mercy with such per- sistency and power. It would be a flagrant inconsistency to demand that for Antonio which they the next moment refuse to Shylock. Hence the piece is not a tragedy. Moreover, it will be seen at the very outset that this play, if it be true to thought and history, cannot have a tragic termination. Chris- tianity has triumphed in the world, and its representative, who is here Antonio, cannot perish in such a conflict. Nor can the Jew suffer death at the hands of Christians, for their doctrine is forgiveness and mercy. Hence the difficulty must be mediated. But who is to perform the act of mediation ? This question brings us to the third leading character of the drama — Portia. Tlie Merchant of Venice. 363 But before we go on let us speak of a possible misunder- standing. By the foregoing remarks, or in the previous essay, it is not meant to assert or to be implied that the Jews of the present day are Shylocks. On the contrary, they have risen out of the narrow limits of nationality and religion as com- pletely as any other people. No one can deny them their full share of the culture, liberality and genius of modern times. Nor is the historical position of this nationality to be underestimated. It has certainly contributed the largest in- gredient to our modern civilization, and it alone of all world- historical peoples of antiquity is in existence to-day. Shy- lock, however, represents the ancient Hebrew, with all his peculiarities, east into the modern world. He is the product of two influences : first, the original Jewish character ; second- ly, that character in a strange land, persecuted and outlawed by society. Hence the bitterness which overflows his whole existence, and poisons not merely his social relations, but his own domestic hearth. In America these external restraints are removed, there is hardly a prejudice except what is im- ported, and no one would think of distinguishing in any pub- lic relation the Jews from the common body of citizens. But to resume. Portia is the third great character of the play, and in importance stands quite on a par with Antonio and Shylock. Her function is mediatorial ; in fact, she may be called the grand mediatrix of the entire drama. In her we see the instrumentality by which the main results are brought about. Through her courtship with Bassanio, Antonio comes into the power of the Jew by means of the loan. At her house all the personages of the play assemble and the wooing is done. Moreover, she accomplishes the rescue of Antonio, which is the main mediation of the poem. The great princi- ple of which she is the bearer may be termed the Right of Subjectivity. She asserts the validity of the Internal and the Spiritual against the crushing might of externality. But she does not deny the Right of the Objective in its true limita- tion. Only when this Objective becomes destructive of its end and self-contradictory, as in the case when the Law was about to murder Antonio, does she place a limit to it and in- voke a higher principle. Her struggle is with legality and proscription asserting themselves in spheres where they do 364 The Merchant of Yenice. not belong. Bnt in relations when this contradiction no longer appears, she is the most ethical of women. In the Family her snbordination is complete, almost devout. In fact, we shall see that all her acts have one end and one impelling motive : devotion to her husband, an absolute unity with his feelings and interests ; in other words, subordination to the Family. She vindicates the Right of Subjectivity to herself in order that she may obtain the one whom she really loves, without which princple, it need hardly be said, the true exis- tence of the Family is impossible. So peculiar is this char- acter, so difficult is it to ascertain its unity, and so important is its place in the drama, that we shall be justified in looking somewhat minutely at all the circumstances in which it has been placed by the poet. First comes the long array of suitors, among whom were to be seen the nobility from every part of Europe — nay, even from Afri(;a. The motive for this elaborate display, as we have before intimated, was to show the necessity of Bassa- nio's borrowing large sums of money to compete with these nobles, and also to exhibit Portia in all her dignity and splen- dor. But Portia has quite disregarded the outward glitter of wealth and rank, and has seemingly sought out a follower in the retinue of a lord instead of the lord himself — "a Venetian, a scholar, and a soldier, that came hither in the company of the ^Slarquis of Montferrat." So at the outset w^e see that she cares naught for the External, but lays stress upon the Inter- nal. The poet has thus given us an inkling of her inclination that we may not be in the dark about her choice. Moreover, we already know of the inclination of Bassanio from the very first scene of the play, and he too Is aware of Portia's preference for himself. This point, then, let us carefully bear in mind, that the poet has already let us into the secret, unknown to the outside world, that Portia and Bassanio love one another, and that each one knows of the other's love. The two peo- ple, therefore, belong together ; they alone can form a rational union, since they possess the absolute j)rereciuisite of the Family, namely, recixDrcjcal love. Under ordinary circumstances nothing would remain but that the happy pair should go to the nearest church, and, in common parlance, have the knot tied. But to this blissful The Merchant of Venice. 365 consummation there is a great obstacle. Portia's father is dead, and has left a will which seems to bind her choice of a husband to a hopeless accident. Three caskets, made of gold, silver, and lead, respectively, are to be set before his daugh- ter's suitors for selection, and that casket which contains her image carries with it her hand in marriage. Hence we find her lamenting in almost her first words that she cannot choose whom she would, nor refuse whom she disliked. But she recognizes the binding validity of the last request of her parent, and thus we have one of Shakespeare's favorite col- lisions, which may be stated as the Right of Choice against the will of the parent. Both sides have their validity, and it is just this validity of both sides which makes it a genuine collision. None will deny the right of the parent over the child, and this right was less circumscribed in former times than at present. But though the parent ma}^ no longer have any legal right, he has still the right of respect, and no child with a truly ethical feeling such as Portia undoubtedly pos- sessed would withhold obedience. Such is the one side. But the other side is what we have termed the Right of Choice, or, in general terms, the Right of Subjectivity. This demands that the daughter should have absolutely the right of select- ing her partner for life. She has to bear the responsibility of her choice, for she must live with him. The husband and wife constitute that unity called the Family : it is a unity of emotion; each party finds true life in the other. This emo- tion, by which both are melted together into one common existence, is called love. So if we have a true unity, or a true Family, there is the indispensable condition of love. Now it is just this important element that the will of Portia's father fiings to the winds by exposing the choice of her to mere accident. It does not demand reciprocal love, which is the only basis of rational marriage. Such is the problem which Portia has to solve, and such is the mental conflict which we find her undergoing. Let us, then, carefully observe how she manages the matter. All the suitors have taken their departure except two (not including Bassanio), who are more determined or less punc- tilious than the rest. The causes of this withdrawal are not given, but may be easily imagined ; we may suppose they 366 Tlie Merchant of Venice. were men of lionor, and would refuse to acquire a wife by lot, to take the hand without the heart. Portia, too, may have shown in an unmistakable manner lier dislikes, or, finally, they may have found the last condition too hard, viz. that they must swear never to woo another woman. Whatever the reason may have been, they all vanish after they had served the poefs purpose. But those who remain demand to have the caskets placed before them. The first one who goes through with the process of selection is the Prince of Moroc- co, who chooses by the outside appearance, and seems to rest his claim upon physical courage. He takes the golden casket, whose glitter typilies the brilliant exterior. Of course, such a choice is directly antagonistic to the character of Portia, and it is logically impossible that he can become her hus- band. The second one, the Prince of Arragon, chooses only to a certain extent by the outside, since he takes the silver casket, and he rests his claims upon merit. Now merit is a most excellent thing, but we all know that it can never sup- pi}' the place of love. It is no uncommon occurrence that the more deserving are passed by and the less worthy are cho- sen, and Avho will say that it is not justifiable ? Both Princes fail. Why? Because they lack the subjective element — love ; at least, the love of Portia. For, as before stated, in order to form a true basis of the family relation, love must be reciprocal — each one must feel and find his or her own har- monious existence in the other. Rank, wealth, courage and merit are much in their places, but they can never be substi- tuted for affection. Thus we see that the rejection of these suitors was not a mere fortuitous circumstance, but a logical necessity of the play. Now comes Bassanio. He has both the requisite elements, loves and is loved ; for the poet has carefully told us all this beforehand. We have no doubt of his success from the start. It is curious to trace the etherial, almost imperceptible influ- ences which the poet brings to bear upon Bassanio to deter- mine his choice. First, his state of mind, all a-glow with affection ; no wonder that he disregards the exterior of things, for love is blind. Then Portia in the same condition, and giving expression to it in words ; to which we may add, in imagination, her looks. Finally, the music, and the vague The Meroliant of Venice. 367 hints of the song, until the feeling of internality is intensified to such a degree as to be irresistible. The very air seems to whisper in the ear of Bassanio, " Take the leaden casket," since it is the negation of all outside show and glitter. In it he finds the picture of Portia, a most fitting symbol of the internal nature of the characters of both Bassanio and Por- tia, as well as of their relation to one another — the image of the loved one imprinted on the heart. The same principle which causes the rejection of the two Princes must bring about the triumph of Bassanio. The moments of a rational marriage are now complete, Portia and Bassanio have all the elements of a true union. Such is undoubtedly the logic of the play. Thus the choice of caskets, which seemed to rep- resent a horrible Chance about to crush out the rights of hu- man nature, is spiritualized into the highest forms of freedom. Portia wins, and moreover wins through the very instruments which threatened her happiness, converts them to weapons for her own rescue. The choice exhibits the ends and mo- tives of the chooser, and, in so far as these are finite and fall short of the Rational, failure results. In this sphere, namely, the unity which forms the basis of the marriage relation, the Rational is the Right of Subjectivity. But does Portia really give any hint to Bassanio which of the caskets to choose? It will be recollected that it was for- bidden her in her father's will to tell this secret. A suspi- cions circumstance is the introduction of a song during the choice of Bassanio, which the previous choosers did not have the benefit of. Hence one is inclined to scrutinize closely the meaning of this song. It is somewhat enigmatic, yet its gen- eral purport may be stated to be: "Don't choose by the eye, by the glittering outside, for it is the source of all delusion." Hence Portia, after observing with the greatest care all the formalities of her father's will, breaks it just at the point of its conflict with her subjective right. This is done so deli- cately by her that it is scarcely perceived; still it is none the less real. Thus she stands here as the grand bearer of the Right of Subjectivity in its special form of Love versus Obe- dience to the will of the parent. We have already several times called attention to the fact that Shakespeare has been very careful to show the mutual 368 The Mercliant of Venice. affection of both parties. Tliese were the two that "belonged together, and were bound to come together in spite of all ob- stacles. The two Princes exhibit various phases of conflict with tliis principle of love, wliich was finally to triumph. Otherwise the poem would be irrational, which in Art is the Ugly, Here we may note a distinction between Shakespeare and an inferior poet. The latter, instead of hedging Chance on all sides and making it the lowest possible factor, would have given it full scope. For he seeks dramatic effects by surprise. Shakespeare, on the contrary, always prepares, never surprises. He elaborates the motives and ends, and marches to their lo2:ical conclusion. "VVe feel that so it is, * — ■ / and cannot be otherwise ; the process has all the rigid neces- sity of Reason. But the novelist or playwright seeks to pro- duce a " sensation" through unexpected tiirns and incidents. The true Artist, however, aims to have every action, and especially every crisis, properly raotited — to use a German exjDression — and to banish accident altogether. So ends the first part of Portia's career; she has solved the problem of marriage. Now a wholly new field awaits her. Ui3 to this point (towards the end of the third act) the drama has produced three happy pairs of lovers, Portia and Bassa- nio, jSTerissa and Gratiano, Jessica and Lorenzo, who are all brought together in the pleasant halls of Belmont, Portia's country-seat. Bat those very means which caused this bliss- ful union have in another direction called forth a terrific col- lision. Suddenly upon this tender scene there lights the demon of ill news ; word comes to Bassanio that his dearest friend Antonio, to whom he owes all his present happiness, is in imminent danger of being sacrificed by the Jew. It falls like a thunderbolt in their midst and scatters the company in every direction. Leaving Lorenzo and Jessica behind, they all quit Belmont at once, animated with one purpose — to res- cue Antonio. Bassanio goes direct to his friend ; Portia hits upon an indirect mode of procedure which need not be here detailed. The main point to be noticed is that Portia suc- ceeds, Bassanio does not. This is specially emphasized by the poet : Bassanio with all his money, or rather her money, fails, wliile Portia is the chosen mediatrix. With what skill she fulfilled her mission has been shown in the previous The Merchant of Venice. 369 essay. It will be recollected that the collision which she is now called upon to mediate is there stated to be between Formal Law and what may be termed the Right of Mercy. Now it is essentially the same struggle through which Portia has just passed; she had been able to master the difficulty and assert her principle. Having thus gone through the lire herself, and knowing the frequent injustice of formal author- ity, she now sallies forth in defence of injured innocence. It is true that her father's will was enforced by prescription rather than by law. But it is the same principle fundamen- tally, and in both cases Portia steps forth as the champion of the Right of Subjectivity. It is confessed that Antonio is wholly innocent ; he has not even willed, much less commit- ted, any wrong, yet he is about to be sacrificed on the altar of legality. She comes, therefore, to cut the toils of the law when they have entangled a pure heart. It will thus be seen that she has been educated to meet just this crisis by her own experience. But, however well fitted for the task she may be, there must be some motive to impel her forth. It has already been stated that, in the external course of the drama, Portia was the primal cause, or rather occasion, of Antonio's falling into the hands of the Jew. Bassanio needs money to carry on his courtship ; he applies to his friend Antonio, who resorts to the Jew, and thus becomes his victim. Hence it is not at all out of place that she should become the instrument to make good the evil which she had unwittingly done. But when it is added that this same man was the dearest friend of her husband, and the chief means of her obtaining the one whom she loved, the motive must be for her all-powerful. Portia is a truly ethical character — she is one with her husband in feeling and interest. Her whole struggle hitherto has been in order that she might make a rational marriagp, unite with the man of her heart. Anything, therefore, which ati'ects him profoundly, must aff'ect her in an equal degree, as she is an organic member of that unity called Family. Now Bassanio is so deeply attached to Antonio that he would even sacrifice his hard-won wife to efi'ect the rescue of Antonio. It is this sympathy, this oneness of feeling with her husband, which impels her to undertake the difficult enterprise. The pang Vol. vi.— 24 370 The Mercliant of Venice. whii'li thrills liis heart must pierce hers ; the impulse which drives him forth cannot leave her behind. That woman ex- pressed uncousciousl}" the deepest principle of her nature who said to her sick husband, "My dear, I have a pain in vour breast." But wIh' should the mediatorial character be sustained by a woman? In this respect, also, we claim the poet is true to human nature. For it is just the subjective side of mind which is prominent in woman and distinguishes her from man, who lays much more stress upon the validity of the ob- jective world. So strong is this tendency in him that he is apt to disregard the other element. Hence we see in the trial- scene that the judge and citizens are all on the side of Anto- nio, yet they quail before that objective reality called Law, By no means let it be understood that these remarks are directed against Law ; on the contrary, it is the greatest con- servative power of Immanit}', But it has its limitations, and these we are insisting upon. Nor will it be denied that wo- man is the fittest person to plead for mercy, since it tallies so thoroughly with her subjective, emotional nature. So appro- priate is all this that we feel that Portia never unsexes her- self, nor even manifests any of the unlovely traits of strong- mindedness, though her adventures mav well strike terror into any imitators. Now, what is the secret of this characterization? Shake- speare has made Portia assume the most hazardous disguises and perform the boldest acts, acts from which any woman mio-ht well shrink ; and yet we feel that she is always womanly — na}^. the most womanly of women. The great majority of Shakespeare's prominent female characters have one trait, however varied they may otherwise be: subordina- tion to the Family. It is a devotion to husband, parent, child, lover; they live but for one object — to be absorbed into the i^xistence of another. By themselves, they feel that they are nothing; only in the unity of feeling, interest and existence with another do they have an}^ liax)piness in life. The com- plete cancellation of the individual through emotion, not con- sciously but instinctively, is the grand characteristic which Shakespeare gives to his women ; that is, to those whom he wishes to portray as good and dutiful. On the contrary, his Tlie MercTiant of Venice. 371 bad women are, for the most part, marked by quite the oppo- site of this quality. Such are the limits in which Shake- speare's female characters move. Now that just this trait forms the charm of woman few men will deny. Though wit, fancy, learning, may call forth admiration, there must be something quite different to subdue. It is not servitude, but the willing subordination to the higher end, self-sacrifice in its most exalted form. We believe that it is this considera- tion which makes us ever respect Portia ; her motive is pure devotion to her husband, complete oneness with his interests and friendsliij)s, added no doubt to gratitude toward that man (Antonio) who has been chiefly instrumental in making her the happiest of mortals. For Antonio is a stranger to her, so far as we know ; why should she assume the disguise and run the risk of an ignominious exposure and tarnished reputation ? No ; she has that complete harmony and unity with her husband, that his joys are her joys, his sorrows her sorrows, and she has the same interest in her husband's ^ friend as the husband himself. Thus she is a truly ethical character, ethical in the sense that she instinctively subordi- nates herself to the highest end of woman. Such is the motive which impels Portia forth to the rescue of Antonio. Just here occurs the seeming contradiction in her character. Hitherto she has asserted boldly and strongly her individual rights ; she has trampled upon custom and even law when they have stood in the way of her purposes. But the moment she is united with Bassauio, all is changed. She jdelds up her whole being to another, who is, of course, equally' devoted to her; this daring and resolute will is now at peace and submissive ; and her expression of subordina- tion is as absolute as language can make it : "thonofh for mvself alone I would not be ainbitious in my wish. To wish luj'self much better; yet for you I would be trebled twenty times myself. . . . She is not bred so dull but she can learn ; Happiest of all in that her o^eutle spirit Commits itself to yours to be direcied As from her lord, her o-overnor. her kin^. Myself and what is mine to you and yours Is'now converti^d; but now I was the lord Of this fair inansiou, master of my servants, Queen of myself, and even now, but now This house, these servants, and this same myself, Are yours, my lord." 372 Tlie Merchant of Venice. Kow what is tlie solution of these contradictoiy traits ? Por- tia insists upon the subjective principle only in order that 7iei' union loith her husband may be more complete. She has struggled for the Right of Choice. To wluit end? Since the oneness of the muniage-tie is based upon emotion, she insists that emotion in this sphere must have absolute validity. Ever}' hindrance must be set aside ; the more intense and unobstructed the affection, the more perfect the bond of unity. Thus she lias asserted her individuality with the single purpose that her subordination might in the end be more complete, and that her marriage might be truer and more rational. A great many persons are inclined to rebel at this sudden swallowing up of individuality, and at the first glance it does seem a hard destiny. Yet it will reqiiire but little examina- tion of the actual world to discover that all true living is cou- pled with just such abnegation of self, indeed that life would otherwise be imiDOSsible. Goethe in his later writings has often laid much stress upon the Renunciation of the Indi- vidual; and the great poets, philsophers, and moralists, in their own different ways, have repeated the same lesson. To live for a universal end is not merely desirable but necessary, and forms the basis of moral action. All organization, socie- ty, state, demand the subordination of particular ends, mo- tives, and desires ; otherwise institutions of every kind would be quite impossible. The truth is, the individual would per- ish through his own self-contradiction were he not subsumed. So the family organism requires the same renunciation from man and woman ; both must sacrifice their self-will and sub- mit themselves to the higher end. In fact, love is the emo- tional, and hence unconscious and unwilled cancellation of the individual ; it means that a person finds his whole hap- piness, indeed even his existence, not in himself but in anoth- er. It is from these considerations that we 2)erceive Portia's character to be a harmonious Whole, spi'inging from one cen- tral thought, and true in the profoundest sense to human na- ture. Portia thus stands as the type of the rational woman, rational in what she resists and in what she accepts, rational in rebellion and in submission. She is a strong character, yet not strong-minded in the special sense of this term ; she Tlie Merchant of Venice. 373 withers not, like a delicate flower, at the first rude blast, but maintains her individual right till to yield becomes duty. The remaining characters need not be long dwelt upon. Bassanio is made worthy of Portia by his devotion to his friend, and she perceives him to be a true man. He is even ready to sacrifice his new bride on the altar of friendship, through which alone he has gained her. Bassanio is the means by which Antonio has come into difficulty ; Bassanio's prosperity has been Antonio's adversity, but he is willing to forego it all for the sake of the friend to whom his good luck is owing. Thus his devotion is complete, every shade of self- ishness is stripped oif, and we behold the worthy husband of Portia. Gratiano and Nerissa serve chiefly as mirrors for the leading characters to reflect motives, thoughts, and senti- ments. They have little distinct individuality, yet are very necessary to show other persons. Nerissa does little but ex- hibit her mistress, and the same function is performed for Antonio by Solanio and Solarino. One of the under-currents of the play, which however soon mingles with the main stream, is the story of Jessica, the daughter of the Jew. Here again we have the assertion of the right of choice against the will of the parent, the same collision as Portia's. But it is in a whollj^ different soil and atmosphere, and hence the fruit is different. Portia respects all the formalities of her deceased father's testament; Jessica tramples without scruple upon all the commands and prejudices of a living father, and steals his money besides. Portia's father was said to have been wise and just ; we know the character of Shylock, and what his daughter's education must have been. Hence the great difference in the moral character of the two children. The same collision occurs in the clown Gobbo, but in a form so low, so devoid of content, that it becomes ridiculous — in fact, a burlesque. It appears here as duty to a master who starves and abuses against the right of running away. Gobbo suc- ceeds, after a subtle piece of argumentation, in reconciling his conscience with his desire, and then takes to his heels. Thus in Portia, Jessica, and Gobbo, there is seen a gradation of the same collision. The fourth act terminates the leading collision of the play, that between Shylock and Antonio. The one has been pun- 374 Tlie MercTiant of Venice. ished, the otlier rescued. Why, then, is the fifth act added? It is because the minor' complications, which are brought about by the leading collision and form a necessary element of it, are not yet solved. Portia and Bassanio have been vio- lently separated, likewise Gratiano and Nerissa, b}^ the main struggle ; when this is at an end, there is no longer cause for separation ; but they must quickly rebound to their former union, which is their only rational existence. Hence the ii§- turn, which is the theme of the fifth act, is a logical moment of the whole drama. If there be mediation, it must be com- plete in everj' part. Moreover, Bassanio and Gratiano are as yet ignorant of the share their wives have had in accomplish- ing the great mediatorial act. To be sure, we, the audience, or the reader, know all about the matter, but it is certainly not our duty to supply the missing elements of a work of art. If such were the case, the greatness of the poem would depend upon the greatness of the hearer or reader ; that is, his ability to make it perfect. In short, a drama, or any work of art, must be complete in itself, an Objective Whole, not dex3end- ent upon any bod}" to supply its omissions, and the charac- ters must be intelligible not merely to us but to one another. Hence the fifth act may be called the Return ; the characters pass out of the realm of difference and contradiction into the world of harmony. It opens with an idjdlic strain which at once ushers us mto the nature of the place; we are now in the land of love ; Lorenzo and Jessica in responsive song celebrate the heroes and heroines of romantic devotion. Next the sweet strains of music arise, the language of emotion and harmony. So there is diffused over the whole scene the at- mosphere of love and concord. Finally, the parties return separately from their struggle into the land of harmony ; the rescued Antonio is there as the mark of triumph. The diffi- culty about the rings is only temporary ; their hearts are right, and that is the main thing ; for it would ill become Portia, after her crusade against the most weighty formali- ties, to insist upon the formality of a ring. Even the ships return to smooth over the last trouble; and the concord is perfect when the story of the disguise is told. It is worth noticing that Shakespeare has here localized his themes ; the abode of quiet is at a distance from the place of strife ; so TTie Mercliant of Venice. 375 Belmont is the land of Harmony and Love, which they leave in the hour of struggle, and to which they come back in the hour of peace. This may be a violation of that critical canon which demands Unity of Place, but it is a rule which Shake- peare very often follows, and which it would not be difficult . to j ustify. To sum up in a few words our results. The collision is be- tween Antonio and Shylock, and is mediated by Portia. Its logical basis is the contradiction between the Objective as realized in the institutions of Reason and the Subjective, or the individual side of man. The former undertakes to crush the latter, through which alone it had existence, for it is pos- ited by the Subjective; hence it becomes contradictory of itself and is negated. The Subjective, since it is not univer- sal, is in its turn a new self-contradiction, and hence a nega- tion of itself, which results in its subsuming itself under the Objective. So Portia asserts subjectivity only to end in sub- ordinating herself to one of the forms of objective reality — the Family. The external movement of the drama may be divided into three parts: 1. The Union; 2. The Separation ; 3. The Re- turn. Each of these parts is determined and complemented by the others. The Union, by which is meant the bringing together of the three pairs, has produced the collision between Antonio and Shylock, whicli then returns and dissolves it, for this Union cannot consistently destroy the one who brought it about. Hence the second step, the Sej)aration, re- sults necessarily from the first. But the parties must over- come this direniption, for they are rationally united, and the collision itself must be mediated; hence the obstacles are re- moved, and there follows the third stage of the movement, namely, the Return. This when completed is the same as the first Union, but with the collision which was involved in it harmonized. Here the play must end ; no further action is possible. Or, to take more abstract terms, we may express these three stages as Thesis, Antithesis, Synthesis. That this movement is a type of the movement of Reason itself, needs not to be told to the Thinker. Every spiritual process in- volves the same moments, and a work of Art as the child of imaginative Reason must bear the image of the parent. 376 Booli Xotices. BOOK notices; Concord Days. By A. Bronson Alcott. Boston: Roberts Brothers. 1872. There are two sides or phases to the "Practical." The practical includes what is iii?;trumental, subsidiarj- — a means to an end. This, so far as man is concerned, has relation first to his bodily wants : food, clothing, and shel- ter— to tlioir satislaclion and f-upply ; secondly, the ministration toward liis spiritual wants which crave culture, or (lie ascent above individual limita- tions, and the realization of the generic ideal of humanity or Mind. In other word's, the practical endivivor of Man must neutralize his immediate and slavish dei)endence on Nature (relieve him from the sensuous importunity of hiinger, heat and cold, external intrusion), and it must enable him to realize in himself as particular individual the universal, or the conscious- ness of his entire species — the human race. The first phase of the Practical looks to providing the means for the sus- tenance of the body; the body is, however, an instrument for the soul, or for tiie purposes of conscious being. Hence this iihase looks to the creation of an in>ti iinient./or an instrninent — thus a double mediation. The second phase of the Practical is ministrative directly to the final end, the Consciousness of Man. Subtract consciousness, and the possibility of the practical altogether vanishes. There must be a conscious adaptation in any one or all of its phases. A complete and entire consciousness of it — a comprehension of its entire scope — may be found, however, in few peo- ple. This necessary knowledge commonly takes on a partially unconscious form, the form oi conviction, or religious faith. The individual looking out upon the wo)Id of in-ti'umentaiities, the infinite complex of mediations, is unable to trace it through to the end, and therefore borrows from the SEER his insight in the form of a Divine Revelation, and by its light believes that he possesses a personality which is absolute end and beyond all subservi- ence to mere outward uses. The Practical as regards provision for bodily wants has an incidental higher use. It is not simply for the neutralization of the physical pangs and inconvenience — the rendering of the same a nullity — that the bulk of human endeavor goes to the supply of the body. If all this were merely to still the Cerberean dog, the economy of Providence might be doubted. In stilling the clamor of the body, man is obliged to resort to social and political combination. The division of labor in Civil Society, the institu- tion of the Family and the State, — all these are initiated to relieve man from the degrading slavery to bodily sensation. But only " initiated" for these institutions, all serve directly a spiiitual end; when Spirit can pro- vide for the body incidentally while providing in the most direct way for the Soul, then it has achieved freedom, for the External no longer sways or swerves. In these great institutions — Family, Society, and the State — mankind arrives at the necessary conditions of spiritual combination. These it would organize therefore as mere forms, were there no material need to goad it Book Notices. ' 377 on — provided, once for all, that mankind had achieved rational insight into the means and demands of cultnre. But as the consciousness of the Race develops in Time, and is a historical existence and not an Absolute one, it follows that the bodilj' necessities with their prickinji: pangs are useful as initiatives, — nay, even necessary. Here the divine Providence is manifest: Nature urges herself to complete introversion, and the '' breath of Life" is compelled to sustain itself by contest with the clay dwelling in which it finds itself. In satisfying the phj^sical, the spiritual is excited to activity, and gradually gains ascendance and independence. The " mask of life" and the subjection of the Spiritual to material ends is seen to be only Maya — a mere delusion of the senses. All this servitude and slavery has been only for self-knowledge, and for the freedom of the self from the self — the realization of the Universal in the Particular. In Jordan's beautiful ver- sion of the ^' Sigfridsage,^' the spiritual lineaments of that old Northern- Mythologic presentation of this greatest Fact of Existence are thus por- trayed:* " Und hinunter in's Nachtreicli der nichtigen Schatten Versauk von der Seele Brunhildens der Selbstschein, Die qualvoUe Liige der Larve des Lebens, Der Traum des Tropfens der sich getrennt hat Vom ewigen Urquell : er sei uur was Eigues, Er konne si eh mehren olme zu minderu, Er konne zerstoren oliiie zu sterben Mordern und niartern, ohne ^Mitpein, Er dilrfe verdammend in lieillosem Diinkel Zum librigen Dasein "Du" uur sagen, Ohne dass achzend die Antwort laute: ch, das Urall, bin In dir wie Aussen; Unheil iiben ist eigenes Elend Und wo du folterst da miisst du flihlend Die Bosheit biissen ; den Alles BIST du." The blind Samson grinds in the mill, not for others but for himself; the imprisonment in sensuous being must be broken hv pain and stern renun- ciation. When it is done, down falls that lying torment, the Mask of Life * In Mr. Davidson's translation : " And down to the night-realm of shadowy nothings Sank the seeming of self from the soul of Brunhilde, The martyring lie of the mask of living, The dream of the drop that hath withdrawn it From the primal source, as itself were something, Weening to wax, while nothing waneth; To rend asunder and yet not suffer; To doom to perdition, secure of dying; To murder and mangle and not be maimed; i With damning conceit and Sflf-assertion, To say Thou, in addressing the rest of Existence, Nor hear the answer, in agony echoe'1 : — 'I, the prime All, am within as without thee; "Who worketh woe, to himself doth work it. Attempt to torture, thou shalt in aton-ment Ache for thine evil, for thou art all things.' " 378 Book jVotices. (die qualvolle Liige der Larve des Lebeus), and the soul looks through the interval upon the unveiled Eternal Verities. The Universal, the Absolute^ God, is tlie root of this Ego which I call myself, and when I free myself from the glare of the senses (which cause selfishness in place of self-cou- sciousness) I shall live aud have my being in the presence of this great fact. '•Before 1 was a Me, in God then was I God, As soon as I sliall die 1 shall again be God," says Angelus Silesius. And Ficlite, in a sonnet, says (in Seeley's transla- tion) : '* The Eternal One Lives ill my life and sees iu my behoidiiig. Nought is but God, and God is nought but Life. Clearly the veil of things rises before thee. It is THYSELF! What though tlio Jlortal die? Aud hence there lives but God in thiae endeavors, If thou wilt look through tliat which lives beyond this death The veil of things shall seem to thee as veil, And unveiled thou shalt look upon the Life diviue." But there is a possibility of undervaluing that portion of our life which is called secular to distinguish it from the direct, conscious seeking of the Divine. As already stated, the whole realm of the Secular — the Family, Society, aud the State — is also directly tributary to tlie diviue life of Mau. It is not a mere instrumentality for the purpose of silencing the beast of the body, but ratlier is it the propaedeutics of luiman combination aud commuuication wherein spiritual life becomes a reality, a fixed fact. The division of labor aud exchange of productions are the apparent ends of in- dustry, but the cunning of Spirit uses them merely as means for the circu- lation of ideas. The real Practical result is the addition to consciousness of new foreign material — the appropriation of points of view that were alien to it. By solving (spiritually digesting) the contradiction between its own ideas and those of tlie new people with whom it comes in contact^ it rises to more universal and truer ideas. The contrast between this com- merce and the material commerce is to be marked. Iu material commerce the goods are to be consumed and rendered null ; in the commerce of ideas, both parties gain, and neither lose anytliing. By this discussion we have only sought the stand-point of the Idealist- Wliether he be the mystic, the religious man, or the speculative philoso- pher, he regards the world as a " fleeting show," considered by itself, and the great fact of the Universe to be the Immanence of Spirit, of the Divine Person. In this he is not necessarily "impractical," but is quite likely to be intensely the contrary. Mr. Alcott, the author of " Concord Days," is widely known as one of the most uncompromising idealists in our time, or in all time. His early acceptance of the doctrine of *• The Lapse" nearly as Plotinus taught it, together with his remarkable original statements of it, make him note- wor- thy in the history of modern thought. A brief discussion will make this apparent. Boole Notices. 379 MK. A. B. ALCOTT'S APERCU, AND ITS CONSEQUEN<3ES AND RELATIONS TO OTHER SYSTEMS. I. Mr. Alcott's first principle is Person — or the absolute self-reflection — that whicli knows itself purely. Hence it is a speculative stand-point. All stand-points arc material which posit at the basis a fixed or rigid substance, a realized multiplicity, whether the same be called simply matter, force, law, form, cause, essence, ideas, or archetj^pes, &c., &c.; wliile, on the other hand, all stand-points ai'e speculative which posit a self-moving, self-making pure act at the ba- sis, whether they call it God, Person, or Idea, its proper names, or any of the other terms mentioned. A demonstration that Person or Idea is the Absolute Princi[)le, and that nothing else can be, would run somewhat as follows: a. Being is either dependent oi- independent: if the latter, it is by itself; and if the former, it exists in another whicli is independent. h. Actual Being is either determined through itself or another: if the latter, it is finite, not self-contained, not a totality; if the former, it is self- contained and infinite. c. Hence all being is self-determined and independent, or else exists in and through a self-determined and independent. d. That which is self-determined or self-made is not subordinate to Time and Space, but generates them in its own process; for if it were subordi- nate to Time and Space, it would be extei-nally detei-mined, and thus a dependent somewhat. e. This self-determined Being is what we name God, Spirit, or Idea (in the sense of person). Remarks. — In this proof we have taken the leflective method : a very deficient form, because we are forced to jump from one beginning to an- other. AVe have an insight into the true stand-points at first, and then construct a bridge to get to them. The genetic or dialectic method, on the other hand, unfolds the progress of discovery as well as its grounds. The method used above is similar to the mathemathical method. It jumps across the river to get a plank to make a bridge with. Of course, itself does not need a bridge; it kindly makes one for others. But the genetic method gives the wings with which the discoverer flew across the chasm. All these strictures on the method employed heie will become evident on looking at the beginning, which is gratuitously assumed without explaining why it is done. In the Geometric demonstration I di-aw this construction and that, but give no explanation of the why. Thus it is an external procedure when contrasted with the dialectic method. Thus one may have a speculative stand-point and not a speculative pro- cedure. It may be without any procedure, a mere positing of the various degrees of the finite ; or these degrees may have the reflective nexus exem- plified. Or, finally, the dialectic may be given, and in this case the whole system is speculative. This prepares us for a view of the second stage in Mr. Alcott's Philosophy — 380 Book Notices. THE DkSCENT {Ahfall) OR LAPSE OF THE SOUL, AS PRESENTED BY MR. ALCOTT. n. a. The first Principle, or God, is a Person — a self-dctermiuiug, or crea- tive, self-diromp(inj<^, or self-dissecting. 6. Ho creates that which is most like Himself — hence self-determined or creative beings. They difler from the Absolnte Person only in degree; they are jmre souls. c. These pure souls may lapse or may not. They have the possibility of lapse, since they are free. d. Those that lapse create thereby bodies for themselves; and, lapsing still further, generate the lower animals; and, these continuing the lapse, beget the plant-world; and thence results. the inorganic world. e. The limit to the lapse is the atom [i.e. complete self-externality, or space, or chaos]. This Scheme has the following advantages as a view of the world: A. (a) It recognizes Person as the only substantial, and all else as de- pendent thereon. This is the opposite of the materialistic scheme. (6) It places next to the Person, as the substance, that which is most like it, as being the most substantial; that which is least personal, is least substantial and most dependent, hence is placed last as depending on the dependent. B. It represents all creation as thruiigh thought. (a) The total thought of God thinks the total, and thus Himself as His own object, or Pure Spirit. It is only finite thinking, i.e. an act of thought, which seizes only one moment of the totality, that creates an imperfect being. The finite thought thinks a part or phase as though it were a totality, and thus takes it out of its truth ; hence arises untruth. In this sense, the theory of the finite rest- ing on lapse is deepest truth. (b) It implies that thinking creates its thought (the deep fundamental thought of Aristotle) ; hence seeing creates what it sees. The divine, har- monious, pure, unlapsed soul comprehends or seizes all in the One or Per- son ; while the lapsed soul, in the form of sense and understanding, creates spectres, i.e. gives validity to abstractions, and thus cannot cancel them and arrive at their negative unity in pure thought. This leads us to the consideration of the positive value of this scheme. III. This order of stating the genesis is an order of rank or caste. a. Each lower form has its explanation in the next higher or more con- crete. The soul sees its moments scattered and isolated in the lower forms in such a manner that each is deficient and demands to be complemented by another, 6. When we consider the inorganic, we find strange properties — such, for example, as gravity, inertia, or light and heat ; we ascend to the organic world and see what all these meant. The lower forms of the organic, such as vegetation, likewise have their explanation in the iiigher or animal forms, Boole Notices. 381 and the animal has its explanation in man. Thus this system formally jus- tifies itself. According to Plotinus, ''The soul appetizing is tlie animal. The world of Yegetation is the merely reproductive soul. The world-soul is the im- mediate eflective agency of the intellect which is its own object. The longing of the individual, specinl soul gives it a body; with the body it retains fancy and memory. Brl )w it is the sense-world, and then feeling, desire, and the vegetative life." In the Fifth Ennead, he has this order: — I. The One; II. The Intellect (dualism). The Primal Essence in its return to itself sees itself, and thus arises knowing or intellect; thus the Primal Essence is diremptcd in its unity; as diremption (or intellect") it produces the lower orders. Proclus considers the One as uncognizable in itself, and to be cognizable only as it is in its process and return. The relation of the unity to the dis- tinctions which it produces is that of the procession fi'om itself. He shows by a dialectic more or less external how all determinations cancel them- selves and return to the One. In these outlines it will be seen that Proclus is the student of Plato, and that Plotinus is Aristotelian in method. And, what is more surprising to preconceived uotions concerning Mr. Alcott, he, like Plotinus, is rather an Aristotelian than Platonist. Plato's highest principle is the Comprehension or genus fidia). This is the universal particular and individual as one process, hence dialectic throughout. Plato is therefore dialectical, always moving from the Many to the One, like Proclus. His dialectic is more or less mixed with reflec- tions, seldom pure; and his great inferiority to Aristotle is in this, that he does not enunciate so clearly the self-thinking thought to be the first Principle. When the logical idea finds all its xjresuppositions, so that its moments or phases become equal to the total, we have the Idea, in which the dialec- tic vanishes. There is no longer an external negative unity cancelling the moments, for each moment is its own negative unity, and thus a complete totality. Each one is in the image of the whole, and the whole thus attains extant being, so that in the sphnre of the idea we have the identity of Being or immediateness and Comprehension or subjectivity. This is seized by Aristotle in its immediate or elementary phase, and hence he has the ap- pearance of proceeding empirically; for he seizes each stage as a totality, and leaves out the dialectic — unlike Plato. The complete Philosopher should show the genesis of the Idea dialecfically, but this is Plato's side. Aristotle assumes it. Plato is always demonstrating the dialectical evolu- tion of the Idea, but leaves the work unfinished. From tMs we shall be able to point out the missing links in Mr. Alcott's Philosophy. He leaves out the dialectic entirely, and hence we have no historical Comprehension, but each step is treateri as a totalitj' or an idea. When this becomes entirely insufficient, he has recourse to concrete dialec- tical terms, such as appear iu Psychology, or even Physiology, as "appe- tite," "desiie," &c. The starting-point, too, or the genesis whose soul is the dialectic, is rigid, and we advance by reflections or else begin anew 382 Book Notices. Willi each link, inakiiiir :i discrete degree. Now, to the mind of the oracle all this is present. The totality hovers before it, but in such an immediate form that the iiorrnanont variable cannot be seized. Hence it is tliat the steps are seized isolatedly, Avliilo the mediation of tlie same remains un- consciously in the subject and is not explicitly stated. Of course, wlion the dialectic is left out the series maybe inverted with- out any obvious impropriety. Thus in the present instance we are taught that tlic most perfect created beings were created first instead of last — which is the ^[osaic order and that of the ordinary conception. The appa- rent difliculty would entirely vanish if the creation of the first pure soul were considered dialectically; for then the links would fall between the Absolute Idea and its realization as Pure Spirit as cancelled moments, and hence not as real evil. As all these intermediate links would have their explanation and raison d'etre in the Final Cause or perfect spirit, the pre- dicate evil or good could not be api)lied to them, and hence the obstacle which Plotinus sought to remove (the real existence of evil as a creatiou of ilie Absolute) is shown to have no absolute existence, but only a rela- tive one to finite consciousness (the reflective understanding). This, per- haps Ave have reason to believe it, is the true view of those who explain creation through the lapse. They cling to that form of stating it in order to emphasize the hierarchy of Spirit and the dependence of destiny upon Choico, or ihe freedom of the AVill. In the " Concord Days'* we have the art-form of a Diary, the extracts running through the months from April to Sexitember inclusive. A second volume, we are told, will continue through the remaining months. It pre- sents us the picture of a literary artist looking over and arranging his choice hours of the day, eliminating from the record of life its j)etty collisions, and, vintner-like, giving us the expressed serenity and wisdom. Thinkof intercq^urse with one whose life is in intimate communion with the wisest and best of the race. Familiar with Plato, Pythagoras, Boeh- me, More, Glanvil, Coleridge, and the rapt mystics of all time, he moves about in the atmosphere of the Paradiso. It is the atmosphere of Aspira- tion and Prayer, like that of a Gothic cathedral; of serenity and purity, ]ike that of a Greek temple. One reads books of Correspondence and Dia- ries chiefly for the society into which they admit him. The more elevated the tone of exposition and oi the characters portrayed, the subtler the pene- tration of its cultivating iniluencos. The Dialogues of Plato and the Lives of Plutarch have accomplished a wonderful work in this respect. "We have in the volume before us the poetry of private life — its univer- sal aspects portrayed. The looseness of form permits private reflections, choice bits of quotation, scenery-painting, personal biography, disquisi- tions on politics and social science, neighborhood gossip, correspondence, poems from favorite authors, essays on the genius of present and past literary men, and mj'stic glances into the profounder realms of philosophic speculation. This freedom of form justifies much that in an ordinary book would be considered one-sided, as for example what is said of Car- lyle and Goethe. Boole Notices. 383 The Basic Outline of Universology : An Introduction to the newly-discovered Sci- ence of the Universe; its Elementary Principles; and 1he first staires of their development in the Special Sciences. Tog<'ther with Preliminary Notices of Alwatoy the newl.y- discovered Scientific Universal Uanp:nn^e, resultinfr Ironi the Principles of Universoloofy. By Stephen Pearl Andrews. New York: Dion Thomas. 1872. Pages cxix and 764. Price, $5. CoJiicwjfs .• Introduction ; Kotices to tlic Reader; Vocabulary. Chapter I. — Genera! Statement and Distribution of the Subject; Classification of the whole field of Human Knowlcdg-e. Chapter II. — Definitions and Illustra- tions of yl«f/^o_9?/ and Correspo7idence; General Statement of the Evolution of Tlionght, hitherto; Principles of Ortranization and Evolution. Chapter III. — Analog^/ more accuiately Defined ; Scientific Analogy as the Basis oi' Universology; the three Fundamental Laws of Universal Scieiice, Unism, Duisvi, and Trinism, stated, illustrated, and defined. Cliapter JY .— JST um- ber; its Universal Aspects; of the Various Numerical Series, and of tlie Meanings of Numbers ; Introductory Ti^eatment of the Analogues of Form ; Parallel Distribution and Tabulation of the total scientific domain and of the several systems and departments of Philosophy ; the Great Crisis; Sug- gestive Programme of Human Destiny. Chapter V. — Form; the Sci- ence of Pure and Abstract Moi phology ; and its Relations to Univei-sology, with diagrammatic Illustrations; Points, Lines, Surfaces, and Solids, with their Symbolism or Correspoiidential Signification. Cliapter VJ. — Mor- pliology and Universology (continued) ; their Relations to Tinman Des- tiny; the Grand ReconcUiatioii of all Intelledual Conceptions, and the Prospective Harmony of tlic Organic Social Life of Man. Digested Index. Creator and Creation; or. The Knowledge in the Reason of God a)id His Wu/-h. B}'' Laurens P. Hickok, D.D.. LL.D. Boston: Lee & Shepard, Publishers. New York: Lee, Shepard & Dillingham. 1S7'2. Dr. Hickock is widely known in this country and abroad as one of the pioneers of Philosophy in America. He is a veteran in the service, and one may easily ascertain the importance of his labors by visiting our Edu- cational institutions here in the West, and conversing with tho^c teachers and professors who have to deal with Psychology or any other form of Phi- losophy. He will find that, in i)roportion to the depth and originality of the views presented for his consideration, a ready acknowledgmeiil of obli- gation to the writings of Dr. Hickok will be confessed. Among those whose profound study of Kant enabled them to come be- fore the world with a new version of Philoso|.'liy founded on the Critical system, Dr. Hickok stands in the foremost rank. Such as Hamilton, Balmes, Cousin, indeed, have failed in attaining so positive a grasp of the categories of pure thought as our author. His merit lies primarily in seizing the Kantian criterion of a priori ideas — universality and necessity — and in holding this firmly and confidently. In discriminating carefully between ideas and ooinions, by means of this criterion the speculative philosopher will find his first task. Tiie moral philosopher, likewise, will find no other foundation for lii-j science. The increasing influence of Positivism and (lie various materialistic schools of thought may be considered the occasion of the present book, and 384 Book Notices. its welcome will be cordial among tJiose who have expei-icuced the vicious circle described in the preface thus: *' An assumed Revelation may be studied and its facts arranged with much learning; but when a profound skepticism meets us, and drives us back of the facts, and a^ks for the validity of ])rophecy, and miracles, and inspiration; and even for the being of a God who can foreknow, and work miracles, and inspire human messengers, — we are thrown directly back ni>oii these old assumjUions of Nature's connections. No sense-experience pul> witliin the coiiMiou>ness anytliing by which Logic alone can enable us to know thai which beyond Nature supporls and connects Nature; and thus the logical nndursianding is driven helplessly to swing on the circle, of taking the Bible's God to make and hold together Nature, and then to take Nature's God to make and reveal the facts of the Bible." Among the admirable things in this book will be found the able treat- ment of I'ositivism and the solution of the Darwiniau problem. Aristotle, indeed, when he set up the doctrine of Final Cause as the ultimate expla- nation of all Natural i)hciiomena, knew the last word on Natural Selection as a philosophic tiieory. "Not sex instinct, but the Absolute Ideal, deter- mines the higher unity of all species," says our author. In his attempt at a speculative construction of Nature, his chapters ou Antagonist force, Diremptive force, and Revolving force; on Life, Sense, and Reason, — are profound and suggestive, resting as they do upon a chapter devoted to Space and Time — a chapter that Kant himself might have wi'itten. But we must mention the descriptive sketch of the histori- cal development of Critical Philosophy, which he divides into three stages or epochs: — \st, Kant's Critique of i*ure lleason ; 2d, Fichte's Science of Knowledge; 'dd, Hegel's Science of Logic. To the latter he concedes: '•That it is the entire compass of all knowledge, so far as the subjective proce55 of knowing is concerned. The most searching criticism will iind scarcely anything, X)erhaps uttei'ly nothing, to object to it as a process com- plete of the science of Thinking.'- When the question is asked, " What is this Avorth intrinsically, as philosophy of knowing overt realities?^'' we think some other predicate than "worihless" will be given if one remem- bers that all this is but the genetic unfolding of the Universal and Neces- sary, which is equally objective and subjective, inasmuch as it furnishes iiot only the forms of pure thought but the logical conditions of all phenomena. As the a priori science of Mathematics gives us the means of cognizing matter and motion, so the a priori system of pure thought gives us the ideas through which to interpret human history, science, and institutions; and a?so natural phenomena and the empirical sciences. The recognition of pure thonirht as embodied and realized in the world of man and matter is Hegel's chief work, and throughout its entire extent empirical results are taken as the raw material. On page 128-9, it is difficult to agree with Dr. Hickok when he seems (contrary to the general purpose of his book) to teach that God's Absolute thought is not solid enough for the real world; i.e. that Creation is not God's thought; or that the Absolute thinking-pro- cess is confined to a subjective time and space which cannot be the time and space of human, conscious experience. Not only Hegelians, but the followers of Mal» branche and Berkeley — indeed the whole race of Platon- Ists and Aristotelians — must enter protest against that. V University of Toronto Library DO NOT REMOVE THE CARD FROM THIS POCKET Acme Library Card Pocket LOWE-MARTIN CO. limited