UC-NRLF

Outlines of Lectures

-on

THE TAXATION OF LAND VALUES

By Louis F. Post

Published by The Public, Ellsworth Building, Chicago 1912

Price: 30 Cents

OUTLINES

OF LECTURES ON

THE TAXATION OF LAND VALUES

An Explanation with Illustrative Charts, Notes, and

Answers to Typical Questions, of the Land-Labor-

and-Fiscal Reform Advocated by Henry George

By LOUIS F. POST

Published by

The Public, Ellsworth Building, Chicago 1912

First edition: Copyright, 1894, as "Post's Outlines." Second edition (revised): Copyright, 1899, as "The Single Tax." Third edition (1906): Copyright, 1899, as "The Single Tax." Fourth edition (revised): Copyright, 1912, as "The Taxation of Land Values."

By Ivouis F. Post.

TO THE MEMORY OF WILLIAM T. CROASDALE

BORN IN 1843 DIED IN 1891

FOUNDER AND EDITOR OF THE WILMINGTON "EVERY EVENING- EDITOR OF THE BALTIMORE "DAY" EDITOR OF HENRY GEORGE s "STANDARD"

"A Singletaxer is a person who does something for the Singletax. ' ' Croasdale.

270343

PREFACE TO FOURTH EDITION

When the contents of this volume first appeared, I was using the Charts in lecturing in the United States and Canada on such subjects as "The Single Tax," "Absolute Free Trade," "The Labor Question," " Prog- ress and Poverty," "The Land Question," "The Ele- ments of Political Economy," "Socialism," and " Hard Times."

For the purpose of securing homogeneity of theme for book publication, I adapted the principal points of all those lectures to one lecture and published it in 1894 under the title of "Outlines of Post's Lectures."

That edition having been exhausted, a second, some- what revised, was published in 1899 under the more appropriate title of "The Single Tax." The third, also exhausted now, was issued under the same title and without revision in 1906.

A fourth edition having been asked for, from Great Britain as well as the United States and Canada, it has seemed best to alter the title and the text to conform to a habit of speech which, originating in Great Britain and spreading elsewhere, tends to substitute for the term "single tax" the descriptive phrase "taxation of land values."

Such difference as there is between taxation of land values and the single tax will be explained in the text of this edition.

Originally the Charts were printed in the body of the text, the Illustrative Notes as foot notes in fine type,

6 Preface to Fourth Edition

and the Questions and Answers in an appendix. But in all editions except the first, the Charts have been insert- ed between pages of the text, though as near as possible to the portions of text they illustrate ; and in this edition, not only are the Charts so placed, but the Illustrative Notes, in larger type than before, are put into an appen- dix, while the Questions and Answers are placed in the body of the book as Part Four.

Except for verbal alterations necessitated by the changes noted above, and for the substitution of illus- trative information of a later date, the present edition is the same as the earlier ones.

The questions in Part Four embody the substance of all questions actually put to me in the course of a lecturing experience of three years in every part of the country. I think them fairly representative, as a whole, of the questions usually asked about the substitution for

all other taxes of a tax on land values.

Louis F. POST. Chicago, May i, 1912.

TABLE OF CONTENTS

PAGE

FRONTISPIECE WILLIAM T. CROASDALE 3

PREFACE TO FOURTH EDITION 5

PART ONE— TAXATION METHODS

CHAPTER I— ENUMERATION OF METHODS 9

CHAPTER II— THE EXCLUSIVE LAND VALUE METHOD... 11

PART TWO LAND VALUE TAXATION AS A TAX REFORM

CHAPTER I DIRECT AND INDIRECT TAXATION 13

CHAPTER II— THE Two KINDS OF DIRECT TAXATION 14

CHAPTER III— LAND VALUE TAXES ARE IN PROPOR- TION TO BENEFITS 15

CHAPTER IV CONFORMITY TO GENERAL PRINCIPLES

OF TAXATION 17

SECTION 1 Interference with Production 18

SECTION 2 Cheapness of Collection 18

SECTION 3— Certainty 18

SECTION 4 Equality 19

PART THREE LAND VALUE TAXATION AS AN INDUSTRIAL REFORM

CHAPTER I— INVOLUNTARY POVERTY 20

CHAPTER II— THE SOURCE OF WEALTH 22

CHAPTER III THE PRODUCTION OF WEALTH 26

SECTION 1 Division of I/abor 27

SECTION 2 Trade 28

SECTION 3 The L/aw of Division of Ivabor and Trade... 29 SECTION 4 Dependence of Labor upon L/and 33

8 Table of Contents

PAGE

PART THREE— CONTINUED

CHAPTER IV— THE DISTRIBUTION OP WEALTH 35

SECTION 1 Explanation of Wages and Rent 36

SECTION 2— Normal Effect of Social Progress upon

Wages and Rent 38

SECTION 3 Significance of the Upward Tendency of

Rent 39

SECTION 4 The Effect of Confiscating Rent to Pri- vate Use 40

SECTION 5— Effect of Retaining Rent for Common Use..45 SECTION 6— L/and Value Taxation Tends to Retain

Rent for Common Use 46

SECTION 7 A Reminder 47

CHAPTER V— CONCLUSION 47

PART FOUR— ANSWERS TO TYPICAL QUESTIONS

CHAPTER I— ELEMENTARY 49

CHAPTER II REVENUE PROBLEMS 49

CHAPTER III— SPECIAL INSTANCES 52

CHAPTER IV— ECONOMIC EFFECTS 55

CHAPTER V— L,ABOR QUESTIONS 56

CHAPTER VI— BUSINESS QUESTIONS 58

CHAPTER VII— MONEY 62

CHAPTER VIII— MISCELLANEOUS PROBLEMS 64

APPENDIX EXPLANATORY AND ILLUSTRATIVE NOTES

THE TAXATION OF LAND VALUES

PART ONE Taxation Methods

CHAPTER I

ENUMERATION OF METHODS

One of the methods of raising public revenues is by Land Value Taxation.

Land value taxation is any tax1 levied on land owners in proportion to the value of their land, irrespec- tive of its improvements.

In most countries land value taxes are familiar enough in connection with other taxes. This is so in the United States, where real estate taxes are (a) in part taxes according to the value of improvements, and (6) in part taxes according to the value of land.2

Land value taxation may thus supply (a) a greater or less proportion of the public revenues, the rest being obtained from taxes on improvements, personal property, incomes, business licenses, and so on ; or (#) it may be exclusive, public revenues being raised from no other source.

When land value taxation is exclusive, it is appro- priately enough called the Single Tax, meaning only one tax and that upon land values.

The Single Tax (exclusive land value taxation) may

1 0 The Taxation of Land Values

vary in degree, from (a) a rate that will supply revenues sufficient only for the bare needs of government, to (#) a rate high enough to appropriate to public use approximately the entire annual value of land.

The annual needs of a government might coincide approximately with the annual value of the land within its jurisdiction, in which case there would be no practi- cal difference between a land value tax sufficient merely for public needs, and one high enough to appropriate approximately all annual land values. Theoretically, however, the difference is to be observed ; for there is a difference in theory and there might be in practice.

We may make the following enumeration of different kinds or degrees of land value taxation :

1. Land value taxation together with taxation on improvements and personal property. This is commonly known as the General Property Tax.*

2. Land value taxation together with taxation on improvements, personal property being disregarded or exempt. This is commonly known as the Real Estate Tax.1'

3. Land value taxation to the exclusion of all other revenue taxes, but limited to the needs of government. This may be distinguished as the Single Tax Limited?

4. Land value taxation, whether exclusively such or not, which begins with a low rate or none on land of mod- erate value and increases progressively in rate on land of higher values, with a view to encouraging small hold- ings and discouraging large ones, is known as the Progressive Land Value Tax.

5. Land value taxation to the exclusion of all other revenue taxes, and to the full rental value approximately of the land. This might be called simply the Single Tax.6

The first three items in the foregoing enumeration,

The Exclusive Land Value Method 1 1

being fiscal in character, belong especially in Parts One and Two of this volume. The fourth and fifth belong more strictly in Part Three, as methods of industrial reform. The chief object of the fourth is to discourage large holdings and to encourage small ones ; the object of the fifth, comprehending that of the fourth, is to take land values for common use while leaving private earn- ings to individual earners.

It is to be observed, howeyer, that all are fiscal, for any of them would produce public revenues ; and that all are industrial, for any of them would tend to promote freedom of industrial production and justice in the dis- tribution of industrial products.

CHAPTER II

THE EXCLUSIVE LAND VALUE METHOD

Land value taxation to the exclusion of all other revenue taxes, but limited to the needs of government, was proposed by Henry George in " Progress and Pov- erty" in 1879, as the best known fiscal method, and one that would moreover, by force of its own excellence for revenue purposes, develop into the simplest means of securing to the community as a whole the value of land, and to each individual the value of his work, thereby at once supplying abundant public revenues and settling the labor question on the basis of justice. Henry George expressed the idea in these words : * ' Abolish all taxation save that upon land values." 1

This proposal, long known as The Single Tax,8 is coming to be better and more favorably known as Land Value Taxation.9 Under its operation all classes of workers, whether manufacturers, merchants, bankers, professional men, clerks, mechanics, farmers, farm-

1 2 The Taxation of Land Values

hands, or other working classes, would, as such, be wholly exempt from taxation.

It is only as men own land that they would be taxed, the tax of each being in proportion, not to the area, but to the value of his land.

And no one would be compelled to pay a higher tax than others if his land were improved or used while theirs was not, nor if his were better improved or better used than theirs.10 The value of its improvements would not be considered in estimating the value of a holding; site value alone would govern.11 If a site rose in the market, the tax would proportionately increase ; if it fell, the tax would proportionately diminish.

Land value taxation, therefore, when carried to the point of the Single Tax (whether limited or not) may be concisely defined as a tax upon land alone, in the ratio of value and irrespective of its improvements or its use.

PART TWO Land Value Taxation as a Tax Reform

CHAPTER I

DIRECT AND INDIRECT TAXATION

Taxes are either direct or indirect; or, as they have been aptly described, "straight" or "crooked."

Indirect taxes are those that may be shifted by the first payer from himself to others ; direct taxes are those that cannot be shifted.18

The shifting of indirect taxes is accomplished by means of their tendency to increase the prices of com- modities upon which they fall. Their magnitude and incidence13 are thereby disguised. It was for this reason that a French economist of the eighteenth century de- nounced them as "a scheme for so plucking geese as to get the most feathers with the least squawking." u

Indirect taxation costs the real tax-payers much more than the government receives, partly because the middlemen through whose hands taxed commodities pass are able to exact compound profits upon their taxes,16 and partly on account of the extraordinary expenses of original collection ; 16 it favors corruption in government by concealing from the people the fact that they contribute to the support of government; and it tends, by obstructing production, to crush legitimate industry and to establish monopolies.17 The questions

1 4 The Taxation of Land Values

it raises are of vastly more concern than the sum total of public expenditures.

Whoever calmly reflects and candidly decides upon the merits of indirect taxation must reject it in all its forms.

But to do that is to make a great stride toward the taxation of land values exclusively. For this is a form of direct taxation. Land value taxes cannot be shifted.18

CHAPTER II

THE TWO KINDS OF DIRECT TAXATION

Direct taxes fall into two general classes : (a) taxes that are levied upon taxpayers in proportion to their ability to pay, and (#) taxes that are levied upon them in proportion to the benefits received by them from the public.

Income taxes are the principal ones of the first class ; the land value tax is the only important one of the second class.

There should be no difficulty in choosing between the two. To tax in proportion to ability to pay regard- less of benefits received, is not in accord with any prin- ciple of just government. The land value tax, therefore, as the only important tax in proportion to benefits, comes nearest to being an ideal tax.

But here we encounter two plausible objections.

One arises from the common but mistaken notion that men are not taxed in proportion to benefits unless they pay taxes upon every kind of property they own that comes under the protection of government; the other is founded in the assumption that it is impossible to measure the value of the public benefits that each individual enjoys.

Land Value Taxes are in Proportion to Benefits 1 5

Though the first of those objections ostensibly accepts the doctrine of taxation according to benefits,19 yet, as it leads to attempts at taxation in proportion to wealth, it, like the other, is really a plea for taxation according to ability to pay. The two objections stand or fall together.

Neither objection would any longer have weight were the fact once generally perceived that the value of the service which the public gives to each individual is fairly measured by land value taxation. We should then no more think of taxing citizens in proportion to their ability to pay regardless of the benefits they receive from the public, than an honest merchant would think of charging his customers in proportion to their ability to pay regardless of the value of the goods they buy of him.

CHAPTER III

LAND VALUE TAXES ARE IN PROPORTION TO BENEFITS

To perceive that land value taxation would justly measure the value of public benefits which every indi- vidual respectively enjoys, we have only to consider that the mass of individuals everywhere and now, in paying for the land they use, actually pay for public benefits in proportion to what they receive.

He who would enjoy those benefits must use land where the benefits can be enjoyed. He cannot, for in- stance, carry land from where government is poor to where it is good ; neither can he carry it from where the benefits of good government are few or enjoyed with difficulty to where they are many and fully enjoyed. He must rent or buy land where the benefits of govern- ment are available, or forego them. And unless he buys or rents where they are greatest or most available, he must forego them in degree. Consequently, if he would

1 6 The Taxation of Land Values

work or live where the benefits of government are avail- able, and does not already own land there, he will be compelled to rent or buy at a valuation which, other things being equal, will depend upon the value of the government service that the site he selects enables him to enjoy.20 Thus does he pay for the service of government in proportion to its value to him. But he does not pay the public, which provides the service ; he is required to pay land-owners.

The economic principle pursuant to which land- owners are thus able to charge their fellow-citizens for the common benefits of their common government, points to the true method of taxation. With the excep- tion of such other monopoly property as is analogous to land titles, and which in the purview of the Single Tax is included with land for purposes of taxation,21 land is the only kind of property that is increased in value by government ; and the increase tends to be in proportion to the public service which its possession secures to the occupant.

Therefore, by taxing land in proportion to its value, and exempting all other property, kindred monopolies excepted that is to say, by adopting exclusive land value taxation we should be levying taxes according to benefits.22

Nor would this be in any sense class taxation, In- deed, the cry of class taxation is rather impudent for owners of valuable land to raise against land value taxes, when it is considered that under existing systems of tax- ation such land-owners are exempt.23

Even the poorest and most degraded classes in the community, besides paying land-owners for such public benefits as come their way, are compelled by indirect taxation to contribute to the support of government.

But land-owners as a class go free. They enjoy the

Conformity to General Principles of Taxation 1 7

protection of the courts, and of the police and fire de- partments, and they have the use of schools and the benefit of highways and other public improvements, all in common with the most favored, and upon the same specific terms ; yet, though they go through the form of paying taxes, and if their holdings are of considerable value pose as "the taxpayers" on all important occa- sions, they, in effect, and considered as a class, pay no taxes. Enjoying the same intangible benefits of govern- ment that others do, many of them as individuals and all of them as a class receive in addition a pecuniary benefit which government confers upon no other class of prop- erty-owners. The value of their property is enhanced in proportion to the benefits of good government and other characteristics of social improvement which its occupants enjoy. To tax them alone, therefore, is not to discriminate against them ; it is to charge them for what they get from the public.2*

CHAPTER IV

CONFORMITY TO GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF TAXATION

Land value taxation conforms most closely to the essential principles of Adam Smith's four classical maxims, which are stated by Henry George25 as follows :

"The best tax by which public revenues can be raised is evidently that which will closest conform to the following conditions: (i) That it bear as lightly as possible upon production so as least to check the increase of the general fund from which taxes must be paid and the community maintained.26 (2) That it be easily and cheaply collected, and fall as directly as may be upon the ultimate payers so as to take from the people as little as possible in addition to what it yields to the government.27 (3) That it be certain so as to

1 8 The Taxation of Land Values

give the least opportunity for tyranny or corruption on the part of officials, and the least temptation to law- breaking and evasion on the part of the tax-payers.28 (4) That it bear equally so as to give no citizen an advantage or put any at a disadvantage as compared with others." 29

SECTION I. Interference with Production.

Indirect taxes^tencLto check production and to cause scarcity by obstructing the processes of production. They fall upon men as they work, as they do business, as they invest capital productively.30 But land value taxes which must be paid and be the same in amount regardless of whether the taxpayer works or plays, or whether he invests his capital productively or wastes it, or whether he uses his land for the most productive purposes31 or in lesser degree or not at all, lay no penal- ties upon industry and thrift. Therefore they conform to the first maxim quoted above.

SECTION 2. Cheapness of Collection.

Indirect taxes are passed along from first payers to final consumers through many exchanges, accumulating compound profits as they go, until they take enormous sums from the people in addition to what the government receives.32 But land value taxes take nothing from the people in excess of the tax. Therefore they conform to the second maxim quoted above.

SECTION 3. Certainty.

No other tax, direct or indirect, conforms so closely to the third maxim. "Land lies out of doors." It can- not be hidden; it cannot be "accidentally" overlooked. Nor can its value be greatly misapprehended or mis- stated. Neither under-appraisement nor over-appraise-

Conformity to General Principles of Taxation 19

ment is possible to any important extent without the connivance of the whole community.88 The land values of a neighborhood are matters of common knowledge. Any intelligent resident can justly appraise them, and every other intelligent resident can fairly test the appraisement. Therefore the tyranny, corruption, fraud, favoritism, and evasions which are so common in connection with the taxation of imports, manufactures, incomes, personal property, and buildings the values of which, even when the object itself cannot be hidden, are so distinctly matters of minute special knowledge that only experts can fairly appraise them would be out of the question if land value taxation were substituted for existing fiscal methods.3*

SECTION 4. Equality.

In conforming to the fourth maxim, the ]and va.lne tax bears more equally that is to say, more justly than any other tax. It is the only tax that falls upon the taxpayer in proportion to the pecuniary benefits he receives from the public,35 and its tendency, accelerating with increase of the tax, is to leave to every one the full fruit of his own productive enterprise and effort.36

PART THREE

Land Value Taxation as an Industrial Reform

CHAPTER I

INVOLUNTARY POVERTY

Great, however, as are the merits of land value tax- ation as a revenue system, its merits as an industrial reform are of vastly greater importance.

Urgent need for industrial reform, fundamental in character but simple in detail and progressive in tend- ency, is evident from the persistence of involuntary poverty among producers notwithstanding our miracu- lous industrial progress.

The fact is obvious. General manifestations of poverty are so common that even good men look upon it as a providential provision for enabling the rich to drive camels through needles' eyes by exercising the modern virtue of organized giving.37 Its acute manifestations in recurring periods of "hard times"38 are like epidemics of a virulent disease, which excite the most contented to fear that they, even they, may become its victims. Its occasional spasms of violence threaten society with chaos on one hand, and, through panic-stricken efforts at restraint, with despotism on the other. And it persists and deepens despite the continuous increase of wealth-producing power.39

That much of our poverty is involuntary may be

Land Value Taxation as an Industrial Reform 21

proved, if proof be necessary, by the magnitude of char- itable work which aims to help only the "deserving poor" ; and as to undeserving cases the cases of volun- tary poverty who can say but that they, if not due to birth and training in the environs of degraded poverty,40 are the despairing culminations of long-continued strug- gles to maintain respectable independence? 41 How can we know that they are not essentially like the rest invol- untary and deserving? It was a profound distinction that a clever writer of fiction42 made when he wrote of "the hopeful and the hopeless poor." There is, indeed, little difference between voluntary and involuntary pov- erty, between the "deserving" and the "undeserving" poor, except that the "deserving" still have hope, while from the "undeserving" all hope if they ever knew any has gone.

But it is not alone to objects of charity that the question of poverty calls attention. There is a keener poverty, which pinches and goes hungry, but is beyond the reach of charity because it never complains. And back of all and over all is the fear of poverty, which chills the best instincts of men of every social grade, from recipients of out-door relief who dread the poor- house, to millionaires who dread the possibility of poverty for their children if not for themselves.43 Most men would rather die than lose a steady job or accumu- lated property. Why do they fear if no one need be poor?

It is poverty and fear of poverty that prompt men of honest instincts to steal, to bribe, to take bribes, to oppress, either under color of law or against law, and what is worse than all because it is not merely a de- praved act but a course of conduct that implies a state of depravity to enlist their talents in hireling work against their convictions.44 Our civilization cannot long

22 The Taxation of Land Values

resist such enemies as poverty and fear of poverty breed; to intelligent observers it already seems to yield.45

But how is the development of these social enemies to be arrested ? Only by tracing involuntary poverty to its cause, and, having found the cause, deliberately removing it.

Poverty of the involuntary kind cannot be traced to its cause, however, without serious thought ; not mere reading and school study and other tutoring, but thought.** To jump at a conclusion is very likely to jump over the cause, at which no class is more apt than the tutored class.47 We must proceed step by^step from familiar and indisputable premises.

CHAPTER II

THE SOURCE OF WEALTH

The first necessity is to make sure that we know the source of those things that abolish poverty by satisfying want.48 But it is quite unnecessary to specify all, and tediously to trace each to its origin in detail. In search- ing for the source of one we shall by generalization dis- cover the source of all the rest.

As a common thing of this kind, the production of which is a familiar process, BREAD is probably the best example for our purpose. Let us, then, carefully trace bread to its source.

To make the results of our inquiry clear to the eye we will construct a chart as we proceed.

The chart should begin, of course, with a classifica- tion ot IZreadwith reference to Man, for it is as an object for satisfying the wants of man that we consider bread at all. And then our first inquiry should be : Is Bread a

PLATE I

Objects

BREAD

CHART A

£xternal Ofr/stb

BREAD

A BAKER A LOT -'LAND AN OVEN A FIRE FLOUR YEAST SALT WATER

roRTME OVEN ANDm BAK[R 70 5TAN[) ON

CHART B

PLATE II

Ofyects

BREAD

. Co"1'

A BAKER""

A LOT "'LAND AN OVEN

A FIRE

FLOUR

YF.AST

SALT

WATER

rition

CHART C

Grtificial

External Olr/ects

BREAD

A BAKER.

A LOT'' LAND—,

AN OVEN

A FIRE

FLOUR

YEAST

SALT

WATER

Man

Objects

£xlernal Objects

CHART D ,

The Source of Wealth 23

part of the personality of Man, or is it an object external to him?

The answer is so simple that a child could make no mistake. Obviously, Bread is external to Man. It must, therefore, be classified with what for brevity we will call "External Objects", meaning objects that are external to man. And inasmuch as bread is a product produced, as we have already noted, by a familiar manufacturing process, and must therefore have constituents, we will indicate upon the chart a place for classifying Constituents as well as one for classifying Product.

The chart up to this point of completion is distin- guished on Plate I as Chart A.

Now let the necessary constituents of bread be insert- ed. Any housewife, any kitchen girl, knows what they are as well as the most expert baker or learned chemist. In Chart B of Plate I, which is a continuation of Chart A, they are named in the place reserved for them : A baker, a lot of land, an oven, a fire, flour, yeast, salt and water.

Having noted all the constituents of Bread, let us classify them in respect of their relations to Man, for the satisfaction of whose wants bread is intended.

Reference to the same Chart B will show that all these Constituents may be classified either as Man the baker falling within that category or as objects external to man, namely, External Objects. This classification is made in Chart C, Plate II.

There is, however, a still further classification. Though all the Constituents classified in Chart C as External Objects are alike in the one particular that they are external to Man, some of them may nevertheless differ from others in respects which, for clear thinking, must be distinguished. Let us see. Compare the first two External Objects the lot of land and the oven. A

24 The Taxation of Land Values

radical difference at once appears. The lot of land is a Natural External Object. The oven is an Artificial External Object. The lot exists independently of man's art; the oven can have no existence whatever, as an oven, but for man's art49 When the remaining External Objects are considered the same difference appears. All of them, Bread included, differ from the lot of land precisely as the oven does; they are artificial.50 Let us note this difference upon our chart, which now takes the form of Chart D, Plate II.

Having thus classified or generalized the constitu- ents of bread, it is no longer necessary to name them individually. We may consequently simplify the chart by erasing them, together with the word "bread" itself, retaining only the class names. It will be more appro- priate, too, if for the terms "constituents" and "classi- fication," we substitute the term "factor". All this is done in Chart E, Plate III.

But grave danger of confusion is here disclosed. Artificial External Objects, as will be seen by reference to Chart E, are classified both as the "product" and as a "factor". Yet it cannot be that any factor of a product is exactly the same as the product itself. There must be some difference, and this difference we shall try to discover.

Turn to Chart D on Plate II, which specifies the artificial constituents of Bread, namely : oven, fire, flour, yeast, salt, water. How do these artificial factors differ from the artificial product, bread ? Simply in this, that the artificial factors are unfinished bread, while the product is finished bread.61 The difference, then, be- tween Artificial External Objects as a factor, and Arti- ficial External Objects as a final product, is that as a factor they are unfinished, and as a product they are finished.

PLATE III

External Otyectt

CHART E

r<

flfft fatal

fl**

Natural Extend Otyect*

na

l flxteffial Ofa'tet*

CHART F

(WEALTH)

(LABOR)

Ot/ect>

(LAND)

'Jftificial lixtemal Olr/ects

(CAPITAL)

CHART G

PLATE IV

O///ects

(WEALTH)

(LABOR)

t/rol External Ot/'ecte

(LAND)

CHART H

c|UCt

WEALTH

Pe"

LABOR LAND

CHART I

The Source of Wealth 25

Let us note the distinction upon the chart. It is done in Chart F, Plate III.

The language of the chart may now be supplement- ed with the technical terms of political economy. When comprehended and used with discrimination, these dis- tinguish the differences we have discovered with equal precision and greater brevity than the more cumbrous terms upon which we have so far relied.52 See Chart G, Plate III.

At this point we find all essential differences distin- guished. Every factor of industry and every material object of desire that can be imagined falls into one or another of the four classes of the chart.53 And from mere inspection of the chart we may see, what was promised when we began its construction, that in search- ing for the source of one of the objects that satisfy human wants we have discovered the source of all. For it is self-evident that the material wants of men are satisfied in no other way than by the consumption of finished artificial objects, technically termed Wealthy and the chart shows that such objects have their source in the combination of the three ''factors", namely:

(1) the activities of man, technically termed Labor;

(2) natural objects external to man, technically termed Land; and (3) unfinished artificial objects, technically termed Capital.

But while these three factors combine to produce all the material objects that tend to satisfy human wants, they do not constitute the ultimate source of those objects. Our analysis is not yet ended ; the chart is still incomplete.

Reflection assures us that all artificial objects, finished and unfinished, resolve upon final analysis into two factors : (a) the activities of man, and (b) natural external objects ; or, in technical language, all Wealth,

26 The Taxation of Land Values

finished and unfinished, resolves upon final analysis into Labor and Land. In final analysis, therefore, Capital is eliminated. It expresses nothing which the two remaining factors do not imply; for it is by the conjunc- tion of those two factors that Capital is produced.5* Un- finished artificial objects and their technical term, Capi- tal, should therefore be erased from the chart. The result appears in Chart H, Plate IV.

Thus all artificial objects external to man (Wealth), are found to have their ultimate source in the conjunc- tion of man's activities (Labor) with natural objects external to man (Land).

Finally, by dropping cumbersome expressions alto- gether, and using only technical terms, we complete this series of charts55 with Chart I, which formulates the final analysis of productive industry. This chart may be read as follows : Wealth is produced solely by the application of labor to land.™

This, then, is the final analysis of the processes that are primarily necessary for the abolition of poverty. In the application of Labor, which includes all human effort,57 to Land, which includes the whole material uni- verse outside of man,68 we find the source of Wealth, which includes all the artificial things that satisfy want. 59 This is the first great truth upon which the Single Tax philosophy rests.

CHAPTER III

THE PRODUCTION OF WEALTH

When considered in connection with primitive modes of production, the vital importance of that truth is clear.60 If primitive modes prevailed, involuntary poverty could be readily traced either to direct enslave-

The Production of Wealth 27

ment through ownership of Labor, or to indirect en- slavement through ownership of Land.61 There could be no other cause. If both causes were absent, every individual might, if he wished, enjoy all the Wealth that his own powers were capable of producing in the prim- itive modes of production, and under the limitations of common knowledge, that belonged to his environment.82 But in the civilized state this principle is so entangled in the complexities of division of labor and trade as to be almost lost in the maze. Many, even of those who recognize it, fail to grasp it as a fundamental truth. Yet it is no less vital in civilized than in primitive modes of production.

SECTION i. Division of Labor.

The essential difference between primitive and civilized modes of production is not in the accumulation of Capital, which characterizes the latter ; it is in the greater scope and minuteness of its division of Labor.63 Capital is an effect of division of Labor rather than a cause. Division of Labor augments labor power and relieves man from the perpetual pursuit of mere subsist- ence. It makes civilization possible,6* by the production and utilization of capital on a large scale.

The productive power of division of Labor may be illustrated by considering it as a means for utilizing dif- ferences of soil and climate. If, for example, the soil and the climate of two sections of a country, or of two different countries (for the effects of division of Labor are not dependent upon political geography65), differ inversely, one being better adapted to the production of corn than of sugar, and the other on the contrary being better adapted to the production of sugar than of corn, they will yield more wealth in corn and sugar with divis- ion of Labor than without it.

28 The Taxation of Land Values

Let us imagine a Mainland and an Island, which, as to the adaptability of their soil and climate to the pro- duction of corn and sugar, so differ that if the people of each should raise their own corn and their own sugar they would produce, with a given unit of Labor force, only 22 of Wealth n in corn and n in sugar as shown on Plate V, Chart A. Production in that man- ner would ignore the opportunities afforded by nature to man for utilizing differences of soil and climate. But by such a wise division as Labor would adopt in similar circumstances, if unrestrained, the same unit of Labor force immensely increases the product, as shown on Plate V, Chart B.

Nor is it alone because it utilizes differences of soil and climate that division of Labor is so effective. Its effectiveness is enhanced in still higher degree by its lessening of the labor force necessary to accomplish any industrial result, whether in mining, manufacturing, transporting, storekeeping, professional employments, agriculture, or the incidental occupations. Minute divis- ion of labor, instead of accounting for poverty, makes it all the more unaccountable.

SECTION 2. Trade.

But division of labor is dependent upon trade. If trade were wholly stopped there would be no division of labor;66 if it be interfered with, division of labor is ob- structed.67 In Chart B on Plate V, which illustrates the effect of division of labor without trade, the Mainland gets 20 of corn but no sugar, and the Island gets 20 of sugar but no corn. Yet each wants both sugar and corn ; and if they freely trade, their wants in these respects will be better satisfied than if each raises its own corn and its own sugar. Compare Chart A on Plate V, with Chart C on the same plate.68 The comparison69 illustrates

PLATE V

MAINLAND ISLAND

TOTAL

CORN SUGAR TOTAL

10 / //

10

CHART A

22

CORN

SUGAR

TOTAL

MAINLAND

20

0

20

ISLAND

0

20

20

TOTAL

20

20

fO

CHART B

*

CORN

SUGAR

TOTAL

MAINLAND

10

10

20

ISLAND

/o

(0

20

TOTAL

20

20

fo

CHART C

The Production of Wealth 29

the advantage to each individual, community and country, of division of labor and trade over more primitive modes of production. It is like the advantage of raising weights by means of block and tackle,70 over doing it by direct application of power.

And what this series of charts illustrates regarding two places and two forms of wealth, is true in principle of all places and all forms of wealth. That every one is better served when each does for others what relatively he does best, in exchange for what relatively they do best, is as true of communities and nations as it is of individuals. Indeed, it is true of communities and nations because it is true of individuals; for it is in- dividuals that trade, and not communities or nations as such.71

SECTION 3. The Law of Division of Labor and Trade.

Now, what is it that leads men to conform their conduct to the principle illustrated by Chart C ? Why do they divide their labor and trade its products ? A simple, universal and familiar law of human nature moves them. Whether men be isolated, or be living in primitive communities, or in advanced states of civiliza- tion, their demand for consumption determines the direc- tion of Labor in production ,72

That is the law. Considered in connection with a solitary individual, like Robinson Crusoe upon his island, it is obvious. What he demanded for consump- tion he was obliged to produce. Even the goods that he collected from stranded ships desiring to consume them, he was obliged to labor in order to produce them to places of safety. His demand for consumption always determined the direction of his labor in production.73 And when we remember that what Robinson Crusoe was to his island in the sea, civilized man as a whole is to

30 The Taxation of Land Values

our island in space, we may readily understand the application of the same simple law to the great body of labor throughout the civilized world.74 Nevertheless, the complexities of civilized life are so likely to disguise its relations to questions like that of the persistence of poverty, as to make illustration desirable.

Chart A on Plate VI classifies about every kind of Wealth that man requires, and also Personal Services which do not crystalize in material products such ser- vices as those of lawyers, barbers, doctors, teachers, actors, household workers, and so on. The circle of various colors represents the commercial reservoir into which Wealth and Personal Services are poured by Labor, and from which they are drawn for use, each color indicating a particular class.

Let us suppose now that Personal Servants tap the commercial reservoir for food. They do it by applying at retail stores for what will relieve their poverty as to food. Food then flows out to them75 as indicated by the blue arrow, which we now insert in the chart, thereby advancing the illustration to Chart B, Plate VI.

How would the outflow of food affect managers of retail stores ? Every merchant's office-boy knows. It would admonish them to order further supplies from wholesalers. Wholesalers would fill those orders, and replenish their stock by ordering from manufacturers. Manufacturers would thereupon send all over the world for materials ; would call for new machinery and better machinery; would order new buildings and repair old ones, and would scour the country for workingmen to come into their factories and renew their lowered stocks of goods. Thus all kinds and all grades of labor that could assist in producing food, from farm hands to inventors, from bookkeepers to sailors, would feel the influence of the demand for food in a demand for their

PLATE VI

CHART A

CHART B

PLATE VII

CHART C

CHART D

The Production of Wealth 3 1

labor. What Personal Servants really do in demanding food is to direct the expenditure of labor to the produc- tion of food and food-producing implements and mater- ials. Demand for consumption determines the direction of labor in production. We indicate this point upon the chart by running a blue arrow from Food-makers to the food reservoir, as in Chart C, Plate VII.

No complaint may now arise of lack of work in food-producing lines.76 But work is only a means to an end. It is done for the compensation it yields ; and how are Food-makers to be compensated ? In services from Personal Servants ? Suppose they are not in want of services ? But they must be in want of something ; if they need nothing they have no poverty to relieve. Let it be clothing that they lack. Then they are compen- sated for making food by taking clothing from retail stores in exchange for their unpaid claim against Per- sonal Servants. Clothing thereupon flows out of the commercial reservoir to them as food flowed out to Per- sonal Servants ; and with similar effect, namely, the setting to work of all clothing-making labor, from sheep- raisers and cotton-growers to sewing-women and sales- men. Demand for consumption has determined the direction of labor in production. The yellow arrows in Chart D, Plate VII, denote this.

The poverty of Food-makers as to clothing is thus removed. They are working all they care to at food making, their own chosen employment, and they are paid in clothing, their own chosen compensation. So long as Personal Servants withdraw food and Clothing- makers supply clothing, Food-makers cannot be poor. Business will be brisk with them, labor will be in demand and wages will be high. That all the other workers may enjoy the same prosperity we shall see in a moment.

Clothing-makers pour clothing into the commercial

32 The Taxation of Land Values

reservoir because they wish to take something out, and know that in this way they can get a larger quantity and better quality of what they require than if they under- take to make it themselves. They are skilled in making clothing ; they are not skilled in other ways. Accord- ingly they utilize the claim against Personal Servants, which has now passed to their credit in exchange for clothing, by drawing from the commercial reservoir the particular commodity they desire. Suppose it to be shelter. They proceed as Personal Servants and Food- makers have already done, and so set Shelter-makers at work. Shelter-makers in turn utilize the claim against Personal Servants which has now been credited to them, by taking luxuries out of the reservoir. This sets Lux- ury-makers at work. Luxury-makers then pass the claim over in exchange for services, and Personal Ser- vants redeem it by rendering such services as Luxury- makers demand.77 Everybody is now paid for his own products with the products of others. Through similar demands for more or better food, more or better cloth- ing, more or better shelter, more or better luxuries, more or better personal services, the interchanges may be per- petuated indefinitely ;78 and these demands will be made until all wants are satisfied until involuntary poverty is abolished.79

Let the illustration be now advanced to show the perpetual flow of trade which this action and reaction of demand and supply maintain, and we have Chart E, Plate VIII.

Thus each class of workers by its demands for con- sumption determines the direction of the labor of some other class. And in more minute and final analysis every person by his own demands for consumption determines the direction of his own labor in production as truly as Crusoe determined his. The demands of

PLATE VIII

CHART K

CHART F

PLATE IX

CHART G

LABOR

WAGES

LAND

RENT

CHART H

The Source of Wealth 33

Personal Servants for food, of Food-makers for clothing, of Clothing-makers for shelter, of Shelter-makers for luxuries, and of Luxury-makers for services, by enabling all to procure what they require in exchange for what is demanded of them, influence each as to the kind of employment to adopt.80

Let us now complete the illustration. When we began it we noted a distinction between Personal Ser- vants, who render mere intangible services, and the other classes, who produce tangible wealth. But essentially there is no difference. By referring to the chart and observing the course of the arrows, Food-makers are seen working for Personal Servants precisely as Personal Servants work for Luxury-makers. It is enough there- fore to distinguish the different kinds of labor,81 as shown in Chart F, Plate VIII.

For simplicity, the workers have been divided into great classes, and each class has been supposed to serve only one other class. But the actual currents of trade are infinitely complex. It would be impossible to follow them in detail, or to illustrate their particular movements in any simple way. And it is unnecessary. The prin- ciple illustrated by the charts on Plate VIII is the essen- tial principle of all division of labor and trade, however minute the details and intricate the movements; and any person of ordinary intelligence who wishes to under- stand will need only to grasp the essential principle as illustrated by the charts to be able to apply it to the complex experiences of every-day industrial life. All legitimate trade is the interchange of Labor for Labor.88

SECTION 4. Dependence of Labor upon Land.

We have now seen that division of labor and trade, the distinguishing characteristics of civilization, not only increase labor power, but grow out of a law of human

34 The Taxation of Land Values

nature which tends, by maintaining a perpetual revolu- tion of the circle of trade, to cause opportunities for mutual employment to correspond to desire for wealth. Surely there could be no lack of employment if the circle flowed freely in accordance with the principle here illustrated ; work would abound until want was satisfied. There must therefore be some obstruction.

That indirect taxes hamper trade, we have already seen,83 but the obstruction must be more fundamental.

As we learned at the outset, all the material wants of men are satisfied solely by Labor from Land. Even personal services cannot be rendered without the use of appropriate land.8* Let us then introduce into the illus- tration, in addition to the different classes of Labor, the the corresponding classes of Land-owning interests, indi- cating them by black balls as in Chart G, Plate IX. Every class of labor now has its own parasite.

The arrows which run from one kind of Labor to another, indicating an out-flow of service, are respectively offset by arrows that indicate a corresponding in-Jlow of service ; but the arrows that flow from the various classes of Labor to the various Land-owning interests are off-set by nothing to indicate a corresponding return.

What possible return could those interests make ? They do not produce the land which they charge laborers for using ; nature provides that. They do not give value to it ; Labor as a whole does that. They do not protect the community through the police, the courts, or the army, nor assist it through schools and post offices ; organized society does that to the extent to which it is done, and the Land-owning interests contribute nothing toward it other than a part of what they exact from Labor.85 As between Labor interests and Land-owning interests the arrows can be made to run in only one direction.

The Distribution of Wealth 35

Suppose, then, that as productive methods improve, the exactions of the Land-owning interests so expand so enlarge the drain from labor as to make it increas- ingly difficult for any class of workers to obtain the Land they need in order to satisfy the demands made upon them for the kind of Wealth they produce or service they render. Would it then be much of a problem to determine the cause of poverty, or to explain hard times? Assuredly not. It would be plain that poverty and hard times are due to obstacles placed by Land-owning inter- ests in the way of Labor's access to Land.

We thus see that in the civilized state as well as in the primitive, the fundamental cause of poverty is divorce of Labor from Land.8' But the manner in which that divorce is accomplished in civilized condi- tions remains to be explained.

CHAPTER IV

THE DISTRIBUTION OF WEALTH

The next chart, Chart H on Plate IX, displays the fundamental principle of Production which we consid- ered at the beginning, and also the fundamental principle of Distribution, which is yet to be considered. In the development of the latter will be found the explanation of the divorce of Labor from Land.

This chart reminds us that Labor (human exertion), by application to Land (natural materials and forces external to man), produces Wealth (the generic term for all those things that tend to satisfy the material wants of man), and so tends to abolish poverty. No man's poverty can be abolished in any other way, unless it be by gifts, or vulgar robbery, or legalized spoils.

The illustration shows also that Wealth distributes

36 The Taxation of Land Values

ultimately into Wages87 (a fund made up of the aggre- gate of the earnings of individual laborers), which cor- responds to Labor ; and Rent88 (a fund made up of the aggregate premiums for specially desirable locations), which corresponds to Land.89

SECTION i. Explanation of Wages and Rent.

It is differences in the desirableness of land that divide Wealth into the two funds Wages and Rent.

Labor naturally applies itself to that land from which, considering all the existing and known circumstances, most Wealth can be produced with least expenditure of labor force. Such land is the best. So long as the best land exceeds demand for it, laborers are upon an equality of opportunity, and the entire product goes to each of them as Wages in proportion to the labor force they respectively expend. But when the supply of the best land falls below demand for it, some laborers must resort to land where, with an equal expenditure of labor force, they produce less wealth than those who use the best land. The laborers thus excluded from the best land naturally offer a premium for it, or what is the same thing, offer to work for its owners for what they might obtain by working for themselves upon the poorer land. Thus we have the differentiation of Rent from Wages. Rent goes to land-owners as such, irrespective of whether they labor or not ; Wages go to laborers as such, irre- spective of whether they own land or not.90

To illustrate : On Plate X, Chart A, are four num- bered spaces, representing land which varies in produc- tiveness to a given expenditure of labor force,91 from 4 down to i. There is also an open space at the right, representing land that is yet so poor as to yield nothing to the given expenditure of labor force.

For simplicity, let the market be equally convenient

PLATE X

J

0

WAGES

CHART A

0

RLNT 0

CHART B

PLATE XI

WAGES J

RENT / 0

CHART C

WAGES

RENT J

/ 0

CHART D

The Distribution of Wealth 37

to each space. Let it be assumed also that one space is as accessible to Labor as another, and that the differences in their productiveness are known. Now to which space would Labor first resort ? Obviously to that which would yield most Wealth to the given expenditure of Labor force the space to the extreme left.

Suppose, then, that Labor appropriates only as much of the best space as is required for use say half of it. We may note the fact with red color upon the plate, as in Chart B, Plate X. Here we see that Wages are 4 and Rent o. The laborers, as such, take the entire product, dividing it among themselves in proportion to their ser- vices. There is no Rent, because other laborers find equally good opportunities to produce in the unmonop- olized (uncolored) part of the same space ; the supply of the best land exceeds the demand for it, and of course none of it commands a premium.92

But if demand for land should continue until the best space was monopolized,98 and some laborers were forced to resort to the next, the best space would then command a premium;94 Rent would rise and Wages would fall. Even though but few laborers were actually forced to the poorer space, they would be perpetual competitors for the advantages of the better space. The effect may be illustrated by indicating with red on Plate XI the overflow of Labor from the first into the second space, as shown in Chart C. This illustrates the elemen- , tary principle of Distribution, that Wages fall and Rent "" rises as demand for land forces labor to land of lower productiveness.95 The principle may be more impress- ively illustrated by supposing that demand for spaces in the chart advances so far as to include all the closed spaces, except part of the poorest productive one. See Chart D, Plate XI. We now find that all Wages have fallen to the level of Wages on the poorest land that

38 The Taxation of Land Values

yields anything to the given unit of Labor force ; while the Rent of all but that has risen, at the expense of Wages, in proportion to its superior productiveness.*6

Reflection will convince us that this must be so. Wages for a given expenditure of Labor force are no more anywhere, for any great length of time, other con- ditions being the same, than the like expenditure of Labor force will produce from the best land to be had for nothing. Rent takes up the difference.97

SECTION 2. Normal Effect of Social Progress upon Wages and Rent.

In the charts on Plates X and XI the effect of social growth is ignored.98 We now illustrate that effect.

Social growth increases the productive power of Labor. Let us suppose, then, that the given expenditure of Labor force as applied to the first closed space in the charts, is increased by social growth to 100; as applied to the second, to 50; as applied to the third, to 10; as applied to the fourth, to 3 ; and as applied to the open space, to i." If there were no increased demand for land, the effect on Wages and Rent would then be as shown on Chart E, Plate XII. The productiveness of the poorest land in demand having risen from i (Chart D on Plate XI) to 3 (Chart E on Plate XII), Wages on all the land in use rise accordingly from i to 3. They can- not be less anywhere than at the place of least produc- tiveness. By the same economic law, Rent remains at zero for the fourth space in the chart, that of the least productiveness, and rises in the other spaces respectively from i, 2 and 3 to 7, 47 and 97. A little study of the charts will show why.

The lesson to be learned is that Wages as well as Rent tend to rise with increased productive power ; but as a quantity and not as a proportion.100 As a. proportion

The Distribution of Wealth 39

of product, not only does Rent tend to rise with increased productive power, but Wages tend to fall.

We may see and understand this phenomenon if we observe that increase in the productive power of Labor, like increase in the number of laborers (which is indeed much the same thing in economic principle and effect), tends to increase demand for land. The fact, both as to numbers and power, as well as effect, is indicated on Charts D and E as compared with Chart C ; and this is a fact which observation of business life will show.101

SECTION 3. Significance of the Upward Tendency of Rent.

Now, what is the meaning of the tendency of Rent to rise with social progress, while Wages tend propor- tionally to fall? Does it not plainly indicate that if Rent be treated as public revenue, advances in produc- tive power will tend, through orderly and natural growth, to the realization of the best industrial ideals ? Is it not likewise a plain warning that if Rent be treated as private capital, improvements in productive power will tend to make slaves of the many and masters of a few ?

Does it not mean that common ownership of Rent is in harmony with natural social law, and that its private appropriation is disorderly and destructive? Caused and increased by social growth,108 the benefits of which should be common, and attaching to land, which should be a common inheritance, Rent emphatically asserts itself as a natural fund for public expenses.108

If there be at all such a thing as design in the uni- verse, then has it been designed that Rent, the earnings of individuals jointly as a social whole, shall be taken for the support of the community, and that Wages, the earnings of individuals as individuals, shall be left to

40 The Taxation of Land Values

each individual earner in proportion to the value of his service.

SECTION 4. The Effect of Confiscating Rent to Private

Use.

By giving Rent to individuals, society ignores this just law.10* It thereby creates social disorder. Upon society, then, and not upon a Providence which has provided bountifully, nor upon the disinherited poor, rests responsibility for poverty in civilized conditions.

Let us trace the connection and try to make it clear by means of the charts, beginning again with the white spaces on Chart A, Plate X. As before, the first-comers take possession of the best land. Their doing so is shown in Chart B of Plate X. There is no Rent here ; the whole product goes to Wages. This effect has been already explained, and it is obvious from inspection of the chart itself. But the first-comers instead of leaving for others space they do not themselves need for use, as in Charts B, C, D and E now appropriate the whole of the best space, using only part, but claiming ownership of the rest. By distinguishing the used part with red color, and that which is appropriated without use with blue, we have Chart F, Plate XII.

But what motive is there for appropriating more of the best space than is used ? Simply that the appropri- ators may secure the pecuniary benefit of future demand for the best land. What will enable them to secure that ? Our legal system of land monopoly, which con- fiscates Rent from the community that earns it, and gives it to land-owners who, as land-owners, earn nothing.105

Observe the effect now upon Rent and Wages.

When other men come, instead of finding half of the best land still common and free, as in Chart B of Plate X, they find all of it owned. They are therefore obliged

PLATE XII

WAGES -3

RCNT // // 7

CHART K

WAGES

RENT

CHART F

PLATE XIII

WAGES 3

RENT / 0

CHART G

WAGES -3 -3

RENT / 0

CHART H

The Distribution of Wealth 41

to go upon poorer land or else to buy or rent from owners of the best. How much will they pay for the best? Not more than i if they want it for use and not to hold for a higher price in the future ; for that represents the full difference between its productiveness and the pro- ductiveness of the next best. But if the first-comers, reasoning that the next best land will soon be scarce and theirs will then rise in value, refuse to sell or to rent at that valuation, the new-comers must resort to land of the second grade, though the best be as yet only partly used. Consequently land of the first grade commands Rent before it otherwise would.

As the seller's price under these circumstances is arbitrary, it cannot be stated in the charts ; but the non- speculative buyer's price is limited by the superiority of the best land over that which he can get for nothing. The charts may be made to show this, as in Chart G, Plate XIII. The inevitable effect is to make Rent at the expense of Wages. As that effect is illustrated by the chart, Rent rises from o (Chart F, Plate XII) to i (Chart G, Plate XIII), and Wages fall from 4 to 3.

Owing to the success of the appropriators of the best land in securing more than their fellows for the same expenditure of labor force, a rush is then made for unappropriated land not so much to use it as to enable the appropriators to put Rent into their own pockets when further demand for land makes even the poorer land valuable.108 We may suppose, for illustration, that all the remainder of the second space of Chart G on Plate XIII, and the whole of the third, are thus appro- priated. The effect is noted in Chart H of Plate XIII. At this point Rent does not increase nor Wages fall. The reason is that there is no increased demand for land for use. The holding of inferior land for higher prices, when demand for use is at a standstill, is like owning

42 The Taxation of Land Values

lots in the moon interesting but not profitable. But let more land be needed for use, and the element of profit enters in. The new demand for land must be supplied from the open space which yields but i to the given labor force, or else from the better grades which are monopo- lized. That is, producers must go to the frontier for free land, being able there to produce only i to the unit of labor force; or become tenants of the owners of the better grades, paying in annual rent the differ- ence between the productiveness of the better land and that of the free land at the frontier ; or buy the better land at a premium price ; or hire out on wages for piece- work or on some form of time wages. The effect would be the same in any case. No producer could get more for the given expenditure of labor force than he could get where land was free. As illustrated by the charts this would be only i. If he got more, it would not be as producer from or on the land ; it would be as monop- olizer of the land. The surplus of his production would go to land-owners (to himself if he owned the land, to others if he did not) either directly on Rent account or indirectly through lowered Wages, as illustrated by Chart I, Plate XIV. The figure i as an item of Rent in paren- theses on this chart indicates potential Rent. Producers would give that much for the privilege of using the space, but owners hold out for better terms ; therefore neither Rent nor Wages is actually produced, though both might be. The figure i as an item of Wages in parentheses on the same chart, indicates potential Wages the increase of the Wages fund that would result if the land were used, other things being the same.

Notwithstanding that but little space is in produc- tive use on Chart I (indicated with red), the Wages fund is lowered to the same point by the mere monopoly of

The Distribution of Wealth 43

space (indicated with blue), that it would be at if all the space above the poorest were fully used. It thereby appears that under a system which confiscates Rent from the public for private uses, ownership of land for spec- ulative purposes causes Wages to fall to the minimum long before they would if land were owned only for use. In illustrating this effect we have again ignored the element of social growth. Let us now assume as before (Chart E, Plate XII), that social growth has increased the productive power of the given expenditure of labor force to 100 when applied to the best land, to 50 when applied to the next best, to 10 when applied to the next, to 3 when applied to the next, and to i when applied to the poorest.

Labor would not be benefited now as it was when with the same chart we illustrated the effect of appropri- ation of land only for use. Although much less land is actually used (Chart J ), Wages are only i in Chart J, whereas they were 3 in Chart E ; yet the only difference between these two charts is that all the monopolized land in Chart E is fully used, and much of it in Chart J is held out of use. The prizes which expectations of future social growth dangle before the cupidity of men as rewards of land monopoly, raise demand for land so as to make it more than ever difficult to get any without a great price, in comparison with its productiveness.

Turn again to those two charts and study them. The fourth grade land (capable of yielding 3 to a given expenditure of labor force) is monopolized in expectation of future use; and "surplus labor" is consequently crowded out to the open space that originally yielded nothing (Charts F, G, H and I), but which in conse- quence of increased labor power now yields i (Chart J) as much as the poorest closed space originally yielded to the given expenditure of labor force.107 Wages are

44 The Taxation of Land Values

therefore reduced, according to the economic law already explained, to the present productiveness of the open space, as in Chart J, Plate XIV.

If we assume that i for the given expenditure of labor force is the least that Labor can live upon, the downward movement of Wages will be here held in equi- librium. This is sometimes alluded to as "the iron law of Wages." They cannot fall below i, for that would reduce labor power by starvation ; but neither can they rise above i, no matter how great the increase of pro- ductive power, so long as monopolization of unused land is permitted and pays.

Some producers would continually be pushed back to land which increased productive power would have brought up in productiveness from o to i, and by per- petual "jug-handled" competition for work, they would so regulate the labor market that the given expenditure of labor force, however much it produced, could no- where secure more than i in Wages108 the productive- ness, that is, of the grade of land to be had for nothing. This tendency would persist until some labor was driven to land which, despite the increase in productive power of labor, would not yield the accustomed living without still. further increase of productive power. Competition for work would then compel all laborers to increase their expenditure of labor force, and to do it over and over again as progress went on and lower and lower grades of land were monopolized, until human endurance could go no further.109 Either that, or they would be obliged to adapt themselves to a lower scale of living.110 In fact, they do both.

The incidental disturbances of general readjustment are what we call "hard times."111 These culminate in a collapse of speculative land values, which lets unused land into the market at lower prices, and by reducing

PLATE XIV

WAGES / / (/) /

RENT

(/) 0

CHART I

WAGES / /(/)//

RENT // ( )

CHART J

PLATE XV

/o

3

RENT

CHART K

The Distribution of Wealth 45

Rent revives industry. Thus increase of labor force, a lowering of the standards of living, and depression of Rent, co-operate to bring on what we call "good times." But no sooner do "good times" return than renewed demands for land set in, Rent rises again, Wages fall again, and "hard times" duly reappear. The end of every period of "hard times" finds Rent higher and Wages lower, as a proportion of product even if not as a quantity, than at the end of the previous period.118

This result is produced by the disorderly system under which society diverts Rent from common to indi- vidual uses. That maladjustment is the fundamental cause of poverty. And progress, so long as the malad- justment continues, instead of tending to remove pov- erty as naturally progress should, actually generates and intensifies it. Poverty persists with increase of produc- tive power because laud values, when Rent is privately appropriated, tend to even further increase.

There can be but one outcome : for individuals, suffering and degradation ; for society, lawlessness and destruction or decay.

SECTION 5. Effect of Retaining Rent for Common Use.

If society retained Rent for common purposes, all incentive to hold land for any other object than immed- iate use would disappear. The effect may be illustrated by a comparison of Chart J on Plate XIV with Chart K on Plate XV.

There is but one difference between those two charts. In Chart J, Rent is confiscated to private use; whereas in Chart K, Rent is retained for common use. All the labor force indicated with red in Chart J, does not more than utilize the space to the left and part of the adjoining space on Chart K. This would elevate Wages to what could be produced with the given labor force

46 The Taxation of Land Values

from the poorer of the two spaces. Thus, in the figures of the charts Wages would rise from i (Chart J) to 50 (Chart K) ; and increase of Rent would not enrich land- owners at the expense of other classes, but would enrich the whole community.113

As illustrated by those two charts, so would it be in fact let the degree be less or more in the actual indi- vidual and social life of mankind.

SECTION 6. Land Value Taxation Tends to Retain Rent for Common Use.

To retain Rent for common use it is not necessary to abolish land-titles, nor to let land out to the highest bidder, nor to invent some new mechanism of taxation, nor in any other way formally to change existing modes of owning land, or existing processes for collecting public revenues. " Great changes can be best brought about under old forms."11* Let land be held nominally as it is now. Let taxes be collected by the same pro- cesses as now. But abolish all taxes except those that fall upon actual and potential Rent, that is to say, upon land values. Nothing else is necessary. Nor is any- thing further necessary except to increase land value taxes as Rent increases. If all revenue taxes were cen- tralized upon land values (even within the limitations of the narrowest needs of government economically admin- istered) it is doubtful if land-owners could any longer confiscate enough Rent to make speculation in land monopoly very profitable. Though some surplus were still absorbed by them, the getting of Wealth by produc- ing it would be so much more easy than by confiscating Rent to private use, to say nothing of its being so much more respectable, that speculation in land values would lose much of its attractiveness. At any rate the question of surplus Rent in excess of the necessities of govern-

The Distribution of Wealth 47

ment economically administered may be readily decided when the Single Tax principle, that Rent justly belongs to the community and Wages to the individual, shall have been recognized by society to the extent of the Single Tax Limited to the extent, that is, of the adop- tion of exclusive land value taxation. 116

SECTION 7. A Reminder.

It is assumed, of course, that the reader of this Chapter understands that Land does not mean agricul- tural land alone ; that Rent does not mean payments by tenants to owners for occupancy of buildings or other use of these or other improvements ; that Wealth does not mean stocks and bonds or land; and that Wages does not mean alone the payments that an employer makes to hired workmen.116

Lest there be some such misapprehension, however, frequent recurrence to Plates I to IV inclusive, and IX, may be advisable.

"Wealth" is the technical term for labor products. "Labor" is the technical term for human effort of an industrial character. "Land" is the technical term for the natural resources of men that are external to them- selves. "Wages" is the technical term for that share in the aggregate of current production (currently produced Wealth) which remains after the deduction of enough of the whole to equalize advantages of location. The technical term for this advantage-equalizing share of current production is "Rent."

CHAPTER V

CONCLUSION

In "Progress and Poverty", after reaching his con- clusion that the command of the land, which is necessary

48 The Taxation of Land Values

for labor, is in effect command of all the fruits of labor save enough to enable labor to exist, Henry George says :

So simple and so clear is this truth that to fully see it once is always to recognize it. There are pictures which, though looked at again and again, present only a confused labyrinth of lines or scroll-work a landscape, trees, or something of the kind until once attention is called to the fact that these things make up a face or a figure. This relation once recognized is always after- ward clear.117 It is so in this case. In the light of this truth all social facts group themselves in an orderly relation, and the most diverse phenomena are seen to spring from one great principle.

Many events subsequent to his writing have gone to prove that Henry George was right. Each new phase of the social problem makes it still more clear that the disorderly development of our civilization is explained fundamentally, not by pressure of population, nor by the relations of employers and employed, nor by scarcity of money, nor by the drinking habits of the poor, nor by individual differences in ability to produce wealth, nor by an incompetent or malevolent Creator. It is explained, as he has said, by "inequality in the ownership of land." And each new phase makes it- equally clear that the remedy for poverty is not to be found in famine and disease and war ; nor in strikes, which are akin to war ; nor in suppression of strikes by force ; nor in coinage of money ; nor in liquor prohibition or high license ; nor in technical education ; nor in anything else, however excellent for its own purpose, short of approximate equality in the ownership of land. Remove all those evils, and land monopoly would be so much the stronger.

Equality as to the use of Mother Earth, that and that alone secures to every one an equal opportunity to participate in production and full ownership by each producer of his own share. This is justice, this is order. Unless our civilization have it for a foundation, new forms of slavery wrll assuredly lead on into new forms of barbarism.118

PART FOUR Answers to Typical Questions

CHAPTER I

ELEMENTARY

Q. Do you regard the Single Tax as a panacea for the cure of all kinds of social disorder ?

A. Not a panacea but a necessary condition. When William Ivloyd Garrison the younger announced his conversion to the Single Tax in a letter to Henry George, he took pains to state that he did not Relieve it to be a panacea, and Mr. George replied : ' ' Neither do I ; but I believe that freedom is, and the Single Tax is the tap-root of freedom." Your question may be answered in much the same way. Freedom is to social order what pure air is to physical health, and the Single Tax principle makes freedom possible.

CHAPTER II

REVENUE PROBLEMS

Q. Would the Single Tax yield revenue sufficient for all kinds of government?

A. The late Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., the distinguished lawyer and economist of New York, estimated that sixty-five per cent, of the Rent that the land in the United States now yields or offers to its owners, would be sufficient. But whether it would or not is as yet an unimportant question. If all revenues ought to be raised from land values, then no revenues should be drawn from other sources while any land value remains in private pos- session. Until land values are exhausted, taxation of industry cannot be excused either on moral or on economic grounds.

Q. In an interior or frontier town, where land has but little value, how would you raise enough money for schools, highways, and other public needs?

50 The Taxation of Land Values

A. There is no town whose finances are reasonably managed in which the land values are insufficient for local needs. Schools, highways, and so forth, are not local but general, and should be maintained from the land values of the State at large or of the nation.

Q. What disposition would you make of the revenues that exceeded the needs of government?

A. They who ask this question ought to settle it with those who want to know whether the Single Tax would yield revenue enough. I do not believe that public revenues under the Single Tax would exceed the just needs of economical government. In better highways, better sidewalks, better wharves, better schools, better public service of various kinds, we should find sufficient demand for all our revenues. But the question of deficiency or surplus is one to be met when it arises. The present question is the wisdom and the justice of applying land values to common use, as far as they will go or as much of them as may be needed as the case may prove to be.

Q. If the full rental value were taken would it not produce too much revenue and encourage official extravagance? If only what was needed for an economical administration of government, would not land still have a speculative value?

A. In the first part of your question you are thinking of a vast centralized government as administering public revenues. With revenues raised locally, each locality being assessed for its proportion for the State and the nation, there would be no such danger. The possibility would be still further reduced by the fact that private business would then offer greater pecuniary prizes than public office would, wherefore public office would be sought for higher purposes than as money-making opportunities. As to the second part of your question, the speculative value of land would be wiped out as soon as the tax on land values was high enough, and that on improvement values low enough, to make production more profitable than speculation. And this point would be reached long before the whole rental value was absorbed in taxation. It is doubtful if land speculation could thrive if only 50 per cent. , or even so little as 25 per cent. , of annual land values were taken for public purposes, provided improvements were exempt.

Q. If a land-owner builds, does not that increase the value of his land and consequently the amount of the tax he would have to pay? If so, would not he be taxed for his improvement?

A. No. Upon the value of the building he would never pay any tax. It is true that his improvement might attract others to

Answers to Typical Questions 5 1

the locality in such numbers as to make land there scarcer and con- sequently dearer. His own lot would in that case rise in value with the other land and be taxed more, just as the rest would be. But that would not take any of his labor in taxes ; he would still have his building free of taxation. Thus : If on a lot worth $1,000 a building worth $1,000 were erected, making the whole worth $2,000, the tax would fall only upon the $1,000 which represents the value of the lot. If land then became so scarce, relatively to demand for it, that the lot rose in value to $2,000, the tax would be doubled; but the owner's improvement would still be exempt. When his property was worth $2,000 he was taxed on $1,000, the value of the lot, leaving the other $1,000, the value of the build- ing, free; and now, though he is taxed on $2,000, the value of the lot, his $1,000 worth of building is still free.

Q. If a man owns a city lot with a $5,000 building on it, what, under the Single Tax, would hinder another man, perhaps with hostile intent, from bidding a higher tax than the first man was able to pay, and thus ousting him from his building?

A. The question rests upon a misapprehension of method. The Single Tax is not a method of nationalizing land and renting it to the highest bidder. It is a method of taxation. And it would not only hinder, it would prevent the unjust ousting of another from his building. The Single Tax falls upon land-owners in proportion to the unimproved value of their land ; and this value is determined by the real estate market by the demands of the whole community and not by occasional and arbitrary bids. No one could oust a man from his building by bidding more for the land on which it stood than the occupier was paying ; the Single Tax would not be increased in any case unless the land upon which it fell was in so much greater demand in the market that the owner could regularly let it for a higher rent, and this would not be so unless the neighboring land were similarly affected.

Q. What would be the expense of collecting the Single Tax as compared with that of collecting present taxes?

A. Much less. It is easier to assess fairly, and easier to col- lect fully ; the machinery of assessment and collection would be simpler and cheaper, and it would not enable first payers to col- lect the tax with profits upon it from ultimate payers.

Q. How would you estimate land values?

A. As we do it now. As real estate dealers estimate them. As appraisers in partition would estimate them. Read Note 34 in Appendix.

52 The Taxation of Land Values

CHAPTER III

SPECIAL INSTANCES

Q. How would you value the land of a farm when all the land of the neighborhood was fully improved?

A. By ascertaining the value per square rod of the adjacent highway. The value of that, for the purpose of adding it to the farms along which it runs, would denote the land value of the farms. Read Notes 11 and 34 in Appendix.

Q. How can mines be taxed without increasing the price of the output?

A. By taxing the royalty not the product, but the royalty ; or, what is essentially the same, by taxing the capitalized value of the mine, not as a going concern, but as a natural mineral deposit. This would tend rather to lower than increase the price of the product and raise miners' wages. Read Note 11 in Appendix.

Q. How would the Single Tax be assessed on a railroad which passes through a farm worth (without its improvements) $30 an acre?

A. According to the value, not of the adjacent farms, but of the total right of way ; much as the value of a navigable river might be determined if it were private property.

Q. How would you assess the land value tax of a man who, by making levees, had reclaimed land from the Mississippi ? Say that the land when reclaimed was worth $50 an acre, but that the levees cost a great deal less.

A. The fact that the levees cost less than the value of the land when reclaimed, shows that the opportunity for reclaiming such land has a value. That value, the value of the opportunity to reclaim, is the land value of the property and would be the basis of the tax.

Q. How would you adjust mortgages to the Single Tax scheme?

A. Mortgages are modified deeds, and mortgagees are land- owners conditionally and in degree. I would make no adjust- ment, but would warn mortgageors and mortgagees to adjust their interests as they see fit when they make their mortgages, just as I would warn buyers and sellers of land to guard their correlative interests between themselves by their contracts. Full notice has been given that as soon as possible and as fast as possible we purpose inducing the people to bring about a condition in which

Answers to Typical Questions 53

land values will be taken for public use and improvement values be left for private use. Persons who in the face of this notice neglect to protect themselves in their contracts have no one else to blame if, when the change comes, they suffer pecuniary loss in the readjustment.

Q. How would the Single Tax affect leases already made? Would the loss of declining values fall upon the owner or the lessee?

A. That would depend upon the covenants in the lease. It behooves tenants to see to it that their leases contain provisions in this respect. If they fail to protect themselves they cannot complain in case they suffer when the Single Tax comes into operation. They will have had ample warning, and their misfor- tune will be chargeable to their own negligence.

Q. Should the whole rental value of land be taken for com- mon use, or only enough for government purposes?

A. Only enough for government purposes. When the people see that this method of taxation improves business, increases wages, cheapens land, and generally promotes prosperity, they will not hesitate to increase taxes so long as public improve- ments are needed or public enterprises desired and land values are unexhausted. As is said in " Progress and Poverty " (book viii, ch. ii) : " When the common right to land is so far appre- ciated that all taxes are abolished save those which fall upon rent, there is no danger of much more than is necessary to induce them to collect the public revenues being left to individual land- holders. ' '

Q. How would the tax be collected from those who neglect- ed or refused to pay?

A. As taxes on real estate are now collected. Or, if neces- sary or desired, as individuals collect rent from tenants who refuse to pay by suing for the tax, or evicting the occupant, or both. I think, however, that the public would deal more kindly with occcupants than landlords do. I think it would compensate them for loss in respect of improvements where such loss was really suffered.

Q. How would you reach the bondholder, or the man with money alone?

A. Why should we wish to reach him if his bonds or his monies represent labor products to which he has honestly acquired a just title ? This question is a legitimate offspring of the theory that men should be taxed according to their ability to pay, the

54 The Taxation of Land Values

merits of which are considered on pages 14 to 17. It is a question which may also have been suggested by the fact that ' ' bond- holders" and "men of money" are so often men who have special privileges. There is a feeling that it would be unfair to allow such special privileges to escape taxation, and indeed it would be. But inquiry will show that the most important of these privileges rest in the ownership of land, and that the bond-holders ' ' and ' ' men of money ' ' whom the questioner probably has in mind, are in fact great landlords; that is to say, that their fortunes consist of evidences of title to landed privileges. When land values were taxed, the great source of unearned in- comes— land monopoly would be practically abolished, and bond- holders and men of money would be only those who earn what they have. Such property no one should, and few ever would, wish to expropriate.

Q. In your lecture you tell of a meteorite which a poor man found, but which the law gave to the owner of the land on which it fell. (See Note 105.) Wouldn't the owner, or possessor, or whatever you choose to call him, of that land get the meteorite just the same if the Single Tax were in force ?

A. Yes, if only one meteorite fell upon his land. But if meteorites got into the habit of falling there, the land would grow in value ; then the Single Tax would operate, by taxing land val- ues, to take the value of those meteorites for common use, less the labor expended upon them, the value of which would go to the laborer. I told of the one meteorite to illustrate a principle. But as a practical question we need deal only with land upon which, speaking in metaphor, meteorites have a habit of falling. The occasional diamond, the nugget of gold, or other valuable thing found here or there as one of the accidents of the day, are of no practical moment ; it is the diamond fields, the gold mines, the especially fertile or conveniently located farming spots, the centers of trade, and similar valuable opportunities for labor, that are of moment as factors in social problems.

Answers to Typical Questions 55

CHAPTER IV

ECONOMIC EFFECTS

Q. Would not the Single Tax increase the rent of houses?

A. No. It takes taxes off buildings and materials, thus making it cheaper to build houses. How can house rent go up as the cost of building houses goes down ? Read page 14 and the related Notes.

Q. Do not the benefits of good government increase the value of houses as well as of land?

A. No. Houses are never worth any more than it costs to reproduce them. Good government tends to diminish the cost of house building; how, then, can good government increase the value of houses? You are confused by the fact that houses, being attached to land, seem to increase in value, when it is the land and not the house that really increases. It is the same mistake that a somewhat noted protectionist made when he tried to show that there is an " unearned increment ' ' to houses as well as to lands. He did so by instancing a lot of vacant land which had risen in value from $5,000 to $10,000 and comparing it with a house on a neighboring lot which, as he said, had also increased in value from $5,000 to $10,000. At the moment when he wrote, the house to which he referred could have been reproduced for $5,000 ; and had he reflected or made inquiries, he must have discovered that it was the lot on which the house stood, and not the house itself, which had increased in value.

Q. What difference would it make to tenants whether they paid land rent to the community or to private owners?

A. Much the difference that it makes to partners whether they pay money into the partnership or to outsiders. When tenants pay to the community they are paying in part to them- selves ; and what others pay they share in, for they are part of the community. They are also exempt from taxes. And since there would be no inducement to speculate in land if rent went to the community, building land would be more plentiful and rents for residences would consequently be lower.

Q. Would not the merchant shift his land value tax by add- ing it to the price of his goods?

A. No. Read Note 15 in Appendix.

56 The Taxation of Land Values

Q. Would not the tax on land values increase the value of land?

A. No. Read Note 18 in Appendix.

CHAPTER V

LABOR QUESTIONS

Q. What good would the Single Tax do to the poor? and how?

A. Constantly keeping the demand for labor above the sup- ply of labor, it would enable them to abolish their poverty by their industry.

Q. Hasn't every man who needs it a right to be employed by the government?

A. No. But he has a right to have government secure him in the enjoyment of his equal right to the opportunities for em- ployment that nature and social growth supply. If government secured him in that respect, and he could not get work, it would be because (1) he did not offer the kind of service that people wanted; or (2) he was incapable. His remedy, if he did not offer the kind of service that people wanted, would be either to make people see that they were mistaken or to go to work at something else ; if he was incapable, his remedy would be to make himself capable. In no case would he have a right to government inter- ference in his behalf, either through schemes to make work, or by bounties, or tariffs, or in any other special way.

Q. Would working people whose savings are in savings banks or insuracce companies which own land or have mortgages upon land, lose by the shrinkage in land values?

A. Not if the companies were managed intelligently. Well managed companies would shift their investments as they ob- served the persistent decline of land values. They would do it even as soon as conditions appeared that would naturally cause land values to shrink. But working people could well afford to give up all their present savings for the permanent employment and high wages that the Single Tax would bring about. It is not thrifty working people but rich idle people who would lose by the Single Tax.

Q. If taxes have to be paid by labor, what difference does it make to laborers whether they are levied in proportion to land values, or otherwise?

Answers to Typical Questions 57

A. When taxes are levied upon earners in proportion to earnings, they take what the earners would otherwise keep ; but when they are levied upon land-owners in proportion to land val- ues, they take what the earners must in any event lose.

Q. Under the Single Tax could employers cut wages to the starvation point?

A No. Under the Single Tax, employers would be constant- ly bidding for workmen, instead of workmen constantly bidding for employers as is the case now. It is the ' ' oversupply ' ' of labor that makes starvation wages possible, and the Single Tax would abolish that ; not by reducing the supply of labor, the Malthusian idea, but by allowing effective demand for labor to freely increase.

Q. What effect would the Single Tax have on immigration ? Would it cause an influx of foreigners from different nations?

A. If adopted in one country of great natural opportunities, and not in others, its tendency would not only be to cause an influx of foreigners, but also to make their coming highly desir- able. Our own experience in the United States, when we had an abundance of free land and were begging the populations of the world to come to us, offers a faint suggestion of what might be expected

Q. Will not the employer be able under the Single Tax to undersell the laborer to sell goods for less than cost, at least temporarily and thereby force him to accept the employer's terms?

A. With employers continually hunting for men to help them fill their orders, and bidding against each other to get men, as would be the case under the Single Tax, such a contingency would be in the highest degree improbable. It is practically im- possible. Nothing short of a trust, an absolutely perfect trust, of all employers the world over could cause it. Kven then, plenty of very useful land of all kinds being free and labor pro- ducts being exempt from taxation, all persons outside the trust could resort co-operatively to the land, and the trust would be obliged to take them in as the alternative of falling to pieces under their competition.

58 The Taxation of Land Values

CHAPTER VI

BUSINESS QUESTIONS

Q. Is not ownership of land necessary to induce its improve- ment? Does not history show that private ownership is a step in advance of common ownership?

A. No. Private use was doubtless a step in advance of com- mon use. And because private use seems to us to have been brought about under the institution of private ownership, private ownership appears to the superficial to have been the real advance. But a little observation and reflection will remove that impression. Private ownership of land is not necessary to its private use ; and so far from inducing improvement, private ownership retards it. When a man owns land he may accumulate wealth by doing nothing with the land, simply allowing the community to increase its value while he pays a mere nominal tax, upon the plea that he gets no income from the property. But when the possessor has to pay the value of his land every year, as he would have to under the Single Tax, and as ground renters do now, he must improve his holding in order to profit by it. Private possession of land, without profit except from use, promotes improvement ; private ownership, with profit regardless of use, retards improve- ment. Bvery city in the world, in its vacant lots, affords proof of the statement. It is the lots that are owned, and not those that are held upon ground-lease, that remain vacant.

Q. Would not the full Single Tax destroy the basis of all credit land values?

A. A tax of 100 per cent, of annual ground rent would wipe out land values, which are but a capitalization of ground rent ; and 100 per cent, of capitalized value, would leave the owner only a moderate percentage of annual ground rent enough, however, for his service as a collector. But land values are not the basis of credit. Merchants do not prefer mortgages on land as security for commercial debts, unless they hope to get ownership of the land through foreclosure. The true basis of every man's credit, from the consumer at the cross-roads store to the great retail mer- chant at the factory or the jobbing house, is honesty, opportunity and ability. He who will pay his debts if he can, and has an opportunity to earn enough to pay them with, and is able to make good use of the opportunity, needs no land values to offer as a basis for commercial credit. He has the ideal basis of all credit.

Answers to Typical Questions 59

This basis of credit every honest man would have if the Single Tax were in operation.

Q. Would the Single Tax benefit the debtor class? If so, how?

A. It would. By abolishing monopoly of opportunities to work, and thus enabling debtors to earn enough, while decently supporting themselves, to pay their debts. When debtors deserve sympathy, it is not because they are in debt, but because they are forced by existing institutions to go into debt in order to work, and are then so hampered and harried by the same institutions as to make orderly repayment usually impossible and bankruptcy almost inevitable.

Q. What would be the effect of the Single Tax if you still left railroad, telegraph, money, and other monopolies, in private hands?

A. The real strength of all monopolies is land monopoly. Observe, for example, the land holdings of the inside rings of railroads. Abolish land monopoly, and the power of all the others will go, as Samson's strength went with the cutting of his hair. Retain land monopoly, and the abolition of every other kind will avail nothing in the end.

Q. How is it possible to determine what part of a man's product is due to land, and what part is due to labor?

A. All products are due wholly to union of land and labor. Labor is the active force, land is the passive opportunity. With- out both there can be no product. But the part of a man's pro- duct that he individually earns, as distinguished from the part that he obtains by virtue of advantageous location, is determined by the law of Rent by what his location is worth.

Q. What is the value of a man's labor?

A. What he can get for it under competition in a truly free market. There is no other test.

Q. Is there no danger that under the Single Tax scheming men of great intellect would be able to take advantage of their less intelligent brethren, and by the competitive system corral everything as they do now?

A. If they did, it would not be by the competitive system, but because the competitive system was still imperfect. Compe- tition is freedom, and such a thing as you suggest could not be done where freedom prevailed. I believe that the Single Tax would perfect competition. If it did, and at any rate to the ex- tent that it did, every one would get what he earned.

60 The Taxation of Land Values

Q. Why does not labor-saving machinery benefit laborers?

A. Suppose labor-saving machinery were ideally perfect so perfect that no labor was needed. Could that benefit laborers, so long as land was monopolized ? Would it not rather make land- monopolists completely independent of laborers? Of course it would. Well, the labor-saving machinery that falls short of being ideally perfect has that tendency. The reason that it does not benefit laborers is because, by enhancing the value of land, it restricts opportunities for employment.

Q. Under the Single Tax theory what right have you to tax the value of "made land," like the Back Bay of Boston? Is not such land produced by labor?

A. The surface soil is produced by labor. But the founda- tion— the bottom of a bay, a swamp, a river, or of a hole, is not. "Made land" does not differ industrially from a house. Its materials are produced from one place to another and adjusted to meet the demand. But nature in the case of " made land," as in that of houses, supplies the materials and the foundation. The value of the Back Bay of Boston is chiefly the value of a location a communal value. The Single Tax would not take the value of ' ' made land " ; it would take the value of the location where the ' ' made land " is.

Q. Why does land tend to concentrate in the hands of a few? A. Because material progress and speculation in land monop- oly tend to ihcrease its value.

Q. Does not the growth of a community increase the value of other things as well as of land? For example, does it not add to the profits of professional men, or of any other business that is dependent upon the presence and growth of the community, as truly as it does to the value of land?

A. Granted that the growth of a community primarily tends to increase profits, the increased profits tend in turn to attract men there to share them. This intensifies competition and tends to lower profits. At the same time it increases demand for land and tends to enhance the value of that. It therefore cannot be said that the growth of a community finally increases the value of other things as well as of land. In fact it does not. Appropriate houses in cities are no dearer than appropriate houses in the country, differences in the cost of production being allowed for. And although some professional men get very high wages in thickly populated cities, the average comfort of professional men in cities is no higher than in the country, if as high. Moreover,

Answers to Typical Questions 61

even if labor values as well as land values were increased by com- munal growth, it must never be forgotten that labor values must always be worked for by the individual, whereas land values are never worked for by the individual. A lawyer may command enormous fees, but he gets no fee at all unless he works for it ; but when land commands enormous rent, the owner gets it with- out doing the slightest work. As to the good will of a business, if its value is personal it belongs to the owner who has earned the confidence of the community ; if it is locational it is land value.

Q. Is there any land question in places where land is cheap ? In Texas, for example, you can get land as cheap as two dollars an acre. Is there a land question there?

A. There is no place where land is cheap in the sense of the question. Land commands a low price in many places ; but it is poor land, not cheap land. It is probably true that in Texas there is land that can be had for two dollars an acre, but it would yield less profit to each unit of labor and capital expended upon it than land in New York City which costs hundreds of thousands of dollars an acre. The valuable New York land is the cheaper of the two. The land question is the question in every place where land costs more than it is worth for immediate use.

Q. Though some people have made money by owning land, isn't it true that others have lost? And don't the losses more than off- set the gains?

A. Possibly. But that has no bearing upon the question. What men lose through investments in land, the community does not gain ; but what they gain the community does lose. As be- tween land speculators and the community, losses cannot justly be charged against gains.

Q. What is the difference between speculation in land and in other kinds of property?

A. If all the products of the world were cornered by specu- lators, but land were free, new products would soon appear and the ill effects of the speculation would quickly pass away. But if all the land were cornered by speculators, though everything else were free, the people would immediately and thenceforth be dependent upon the speculators for a chance to live. That illus- trates the difference.

Q. How can it be possible that speculative land values cause business depressions when, as any business man will tell you, the whole item of land value whether ground rent or interest on purchase money is one of the smallest items in every business?

62 The Taxation of Land Values

A. You overlook the fact that the item of speculative rent is the only item which the business man does not get back again. The cost of his goods, the expense of clerk hire, the rent of his building, the wear and tear of implements, are all received back, in the course of normal business, in the prices of his goods. Even his ground rent, to the extent that it is normal (i. e., what it would be if the supply of land were determined alone by land in use, and not affected by the land that is held out of use for higher values), comes back to him in the sense that his aggregate profits are that much greater than they would be where ground rent was less. But the extra ground rent which he is obliged to pay in consequence of the abnormal scarcity of land, is a dead weight ; it does not come back to him. He cannot recoup his excessive ground rent or purchase price unless or until his site rises in true value to the level of its speculative value. Therefore, even if infinitesimal in amount, as compared with the other expenses of his business and that is by no means admitted it is the one ex- pense which may break a thriving business down. Besides, it is not alone the ground rent paid by the business man for his loca- tion that bears down upon his business prosperity ; the weight of abnormally high land values in general presses upon business in general, and by obstructing the flow of trade forces the weaker business units to the wall. It is not quite safe to deduce general economic principles from the ledgers of particular business houses.

CHAPTER VII

MONEY

Q. Which is the more important, land or money?

A. This is like asking whether to a thirsty man water or a cup is the more important. L/and is a necessity, money a conven- ience. The use of money is to facilitate trade. But we can live without trade. Even to trade, money is not indispensable. Trade can be carried on by means of primitive barter or by book- keeping, and in a very high degree it is so carried on. But we cannot so much as live, either in solitude or in society, without appropriate land. "Give me all the money in the world," said an objector once; "and you may have all the land." And this was the answer : ' ' The first thing I should do would be to order you to give me your money or get off my land."

Answers to Typical Questions 63

Q. Would you let money escape taxation, and so favor money lenders?

A. It is a curious fact that this question is most popular among people who clamor for cheap money. How they expect to cheapen money by taxing its lenders on their loans is a puzzle. To tax money lenders is to discourage money lending, and there- by to increase interest on loans. Yes, we should let money escape taxation. It escapes taxation now, which in itself is a politic reason for exempting it; but we should exempt it (by taxing nothing but land values) for the additional and better reason that a man's money is his own and the community has no right to it, while a man's land value is the community's and the man has no right to it. This would not favor money lenders in any invidious sense. It would favor both lenders and borrowers ; lenders by making their loans more secure, and borrowers by enabling them to borrow on easier terms.

Q. Would the Single Tax abolish interest?

A. I do not think so. Interest properly understood is a form of wages, and so far from abolishing it, the Single Tax, which would tend to increase all forms of wages, would tend to increase interest. But many forms of land rent and other monop- oly profits are often confounded with interest, and by force of association have given to interest a bad name ; all these would be greatly minimized if not wholly abolished by the Single Tax. It is impossible to answer this question intelligibly to everyone who asks it, without requiring him to be specific; for it is seldom that two persons agree as to what they mean by ' ' interest. ' ' The Western farmer used to think of the high rate that he paid, part- ly for risk, partly from his ignorance of the modus operandi of banking, and partly because legitimate banking facilities were scarce in his community ; the Wall Street operator thinks of the premiums that he pays for currency in times of stress to tide him over from day to day ; others think of ' ' interest ' ' on government bonds, and others of dividends of companies with valuable land monopolies. None of these payments are really interest, and the Single Tax would tend to rid society of them. But that advan- tage which the workmen enjoy with implements and materials already earned, over those who have yet to earn them, an advan- tage which is expressed in money and as interest upon capital, will not, I should think, be abolished by anything that man can do, no more than the advantage of skill in production can be or ought to be abolished. The value of such advantages is part of

64 The Taxation of Land Values

the wages of the labor that creates the capital or acquires the skill.

Q. Would not the Single Tax take away the home place, and so tend to crush out the home sentiment?

A. When the home place now becomes valuable, it is parted with.

Q. Yes ; but when the home place is parted with now, the home owner is compensated by the high price he gets.

A. Then your question does not turn upon the home senti- ment but upon the dollar sentiment. As a matter of sentiment, the condition would be no worse in any case than now, and in many cases far better ; as a matter of dollars, the question is one of justice and not of the home. Under the Single Tax any one who wanted a home could have it, and never be obliged to aban- don one home for another, unless such changes took place in the neighborhood as to make the place inappropriate for homes. He could not then, as he does now, play dog in the manger, saying to the community, ' ' I will not use this place for appropriate purposes, nor will I allow any one else to do so. ' ' If the com- munity felt that special hardship were involved, it could relieve it generously out of the land value fund.

CHAPTER VIII

MISCELLANEOUS PROBLEMS

Q. Is not the right of ownership of a gold ring the same as the ownership of a gold mine ? and if the latter is wrong is not the former also wrong?

A. If it be wrong for you to own the spring of water which you and your fellows use, is it therefore wrong for you to own the water that you lift from the spring to drink? If so how will you slake your thirst? If you argue in reply that it is not wrong for you to own the spring, then how shall your fellows slake their thirst when you treat them, as you would have a right to, as trespassers upon your property? To own the source of labor products is to own the labor of others ; to own what you produce from that source is to own only a product of your own labor. Nature furnishes gold mines, but men fashion gold rings. The right of ownership differs radically.

Answers to Typical Questions 65

Q. Is it true that men are equally entitled to land? Are they not entitled to it in proportion to their use of it ?

A. Yes, they are entitled to it in proportion to their use of it ; and it is this title that the Single Tax would secure. It would allow every one to possess as much land as he wished, upon the sole condition that if it has a value he shall account to the com- munity for that value and for nothing else. All that he produced from the land above its value would be absolutely his, free even from taxation. The Single Tax is the method best adapted to modern times, and to orderly social conditions, for limiting possession of land to its use. By making it unprofitable to hold land except for use, or to hold more than can be used profitably, it constitutes every man his own judge of the amount and the character of the land he can use.

Q. Is it right that land values should bear all the taxes for the support of public institutions, while labor products go un- taxed?

A. Yes. Public institutions increase the value of land but not of labor products. Read Notes 20 and 24 in Appendix.

Q. Our city raises $20,000 for fire protection. Is it fair to tax land, which doesn't get that protection, and let houses go free though they do get it?

A. Is not the land worth more with your fire protection than it would be without it? Which would be better for the owners of land in your city, to pay the $20,000, or to have no fire protection? Read Note 24 in Appendix.

Q. Rich man with large mansion ; poor widow with small house on same sized lot adjoining. The two pay the same tax. Is that right?

A. There is no reason in justice why the community should not charge poor widows as much for monopolizing valuable land as it charges rich men. In either case it confers a special privi- lege and should be paid what the privilege is worth. The ques- tion is seldom asked in good faith. Poor widows who live on lots adjoining large mansions aren't they scarce? and when found, what are they but land-grabbers? In our sympathy for such widows, let us not forget the hosts of widows who not only do not live next to mansions, but have no place in the whole wide world whereon to live but by some landlord's consent.

Q. If land and labor are equally indispensable factors of production, why are they not equally entitled to the product?

66 The Taxation of Land Values

A. The laborer justly owns his labor, but the land-owner cannot justly own his land. The question is not one of the relative rights of men and land, but of men and men.

Q. Should not the poor man be compensated for the loss of his land value?

A. No, and reasons are numerous. Among them are these : The poor man's rights in the community and in common prop- erty are neither more nor less than the rich man's; the better conditions for the poor man which the Single Tax would bring about would more than off-set his loss in land values ; the poor man has no land values worth speaking of.

Q. How would you compensate the man who has bought a lot in order to make a home upon it, but is not yet able to build ?

A. By letting him, when he is ready to build, have a better lot for nothing. The Single Tax would do this by discouraging the cornering of land which now makes all good lots scarce. When land was no longer appropriated except for use, and that would result from the operation of the Single Tax, there would be an abundance of building lots to be had for the taking, which would be far more desirable than the kind to which men who cannot afford to build homes now resort when they buy lots for a home.

Q. If the value of land be destroyed by the Single Tax, would not justice require that land-owners be compensated?

A. No. I/and is for the use of all, and rent is caused by the community. To legally vest land-ownership in less than the whole, excluding those to come as well as any that are here, is a moral crime against all the excluded. Therefore no government can make a perpetual title to land which is or can become morally binding. Neither can one generation vest the communal earnings of future generations in the heirs or assigns of particular persons by any morally valid title. This they attempt to do when they make grants of land. There is both divine justice and economic wisdom in the command that ' ' the land shall not be sold in per- petuity." All titles to land are subject in the forum of morals to absolute divestment as soon as the people decide upon the change.

Q. If a man buys land in good faith, under the laws under which we live, is he not entitled to compensation for his individ- ual loss when titles are abolished?

A. There is no sounder principle of law than that which, distinguishing the contractual from the legislative powers of gov-

Answers to Typical Questions 67

ernment, prescribes that government cannot tie up its legislative powers. Now, land grants and taxation are so clearly matters of general public policy that no one can successfully dispute that they are legislative and not contractual in essential character. Tax- ation is so by municipal law as well as in essential moral principle ; land grants would be so by municipal law if landed interests had not perverted the law. It follows that titles to land values, and privileges of more or less exemption from taxation, are morally voidable at the pleasure of the people; for no legislature can morally divest future legislatures of legitimate legislative power. Nor can they divest the people of such power. The reserved right of the people to terminate grants of land value, is as truly a part of every grant of land as if it were written expressly in the body of the instrument. Moreover, notice was given when Henry George published ' ' Progress and Poverty, ' ' and has been reiter- ated until the whole civilized world has now become cognizant of it, that an effort is in progress to do what is in effect this very thing. This notice is a moral cloud upon every title. He who buys now, buys with notice. It will not do for him when the time to end those grants comes, to say: " I relied upon the good faith of the government whose laws told me I might buy." He has notice, and if he buys he buys at his peril, so far as his ex- pectations of appropriating ground rent or a higher selling value are concerned. Men cannot be allowed to make bets that the effort to retain land values for common use will fail, and then, when they lose their bets, to call upon the people to compensate them for the loss. Read the chapter on ' ' Compensation ' ' in Henry George's "Perplexed Philosopher."

Q. If the ownership of land is immoral, is it not the duty of individuals who see its immorality to refrain from profiting by it ?

A. No. The immorality is institutional, not individual. Every member of a community has a right to land and an interest in the rent of land. Under the Single Tax both rights would be conserved. But under existing social institutions the only way of securing either it to own land and profit by it. To refrain from doing so would have no reformatory effect. It is a mental eccen- tricity to believe or profess to believe that institutional wrongs and individual wrongs are upon the same plane and must be cured in the same way by individual reformation. But individuals cannot change institutions by refraining from profiting by them, any more than they could dredge a creek by refraining from

68 The Taxation of Land Values

swimming in it. Institutional wrongs must be remedied by in- stitutional reforms.

Q. What is your opinion of socialism ?

A. About the same as Henry George's. Read his opinion in chapter xxviii of his ' ' Protection or Free Trade . ' '

APPENDIX Explanatory and Illustrative Notes

The headings and reference figures correspond to those of the text

PART ONE, CHAPTER I, PAGES 9 TO 11

1. The word "tax" is used comprehensively in the United States for local as well as State or national levies for public reve- nue, except that custom house exactions are usually called ' 'tariffs' ' or "duties." In Great Britain, however, the word "tax" is usually understood to designate Imperial levies, local taxes being called ' ' rates. ' ' In this volume the words " tax " and ' 'taxation' ' are used indiscriminately for fiscal exactions, whether national or local, direct or indirect, tariff, duty, excise, or license.

2. In the city of New York, according to the report of the Tax Department for 1910, the value of improvements was stated to be $2,490,206,348, whereas the value of the land alone was stated to be $4,001,129,651. As the tax rate that year in New York was about 1.8 per cent., it may be computed that improvement taxes amounted to about $44,000,000, while the taxes on land values amounted to about $72,000,000, a total of about $116,000,000 on real estate.

3. "The general property tax" is common in the United States and Canada ; but there is a tendency in both countries to- ward modification, it being generally conceded that this form of tax is a bungling fiscal method and hopelessly unfair in operation. To the general property tax in the United States there are often added inheritance taxes, franchise taxes, occupation taxes, and other forms, some of which might be included in the theory of the general property tax.

4. The real estate tax, as part of the general property tax, is universal in the United States ; until recently it was likewise universal in Canada, where it is still general. In both countries, however, it is everywhere supplemented with other taxes in greater

70 The Taxation of Land Values

or less variety and degree, some of which belong in the category of the general property tax and some do not. Although personal property is not exempt in the United States, personal property taxes are extensively ' ' dodged. ' ' For an excellent presentation of this subject see the American Magazine (New York) for Dec- ember, 1910, and January, 1911, et seq., in a series of articles by Albert Jay Nock, under the title of "The Things That Are Caesar's."

5. The nearest actual approach to this system is in some of the municipalities of New Zealand, Australia, and Canada. In Canada the city of Vancouver is conspicuous, although other Canadian cities, notably Edmonton, Victoria, and New Westmin- ster, are making successful experiments of the same kind. British Columbia has long had laws permitting municipalities to use their own discretion in taxing different classes of property. Under those laws it has been common for municipalities in that Canadian Province to value land for taxation at 100 per cent, of its market value and improvements at less, thereby establishing a tendency toward " the single tax limited." Vancouver was among these. In 1896 that city reduced improvement valuations to 50 per cent, of market value, leaving land at 100 per cent.; the valuation of im- provements was reduced in 1906 to 25 per cent.; and in March, 1910, to zero. As there are no taxes of moment in Vancouver now but those upon land values (except Provincial and Dominion taxes) , Vancouver may be said to be operating, as a municipality, under the principle of ' ' the single tax limited. ' ' No such experiment is legally possible in the United States, except in Oregon. Al- though efforts have been under way in New York since the early 90' s of the last century to secure legislation allowing New York localities the option privileges afforded those of British Columbia, these efforts have so far been balked by the legislature ; but at the election of 1910 in Oregon, where the legislature is subject to the Initiative and Referendum, this privilege was accorded to all the counties of Oregon by an Initiative vote of 44,171 to 42,127, a favorable majority of 2,044.

6. The Single Tax, unlimited by governmental needs, has not been adopted anywhere. But in some countries notably Germany and Great Britain taxation of the ' ' unearned incre- ment" as it is called, has been adopted in moderate and varying forms. It seems to be attaining popularity elsewhere. An ' ' un- earned increment " is an increase of the capitalized value of the rental possibilities of a given piece of land (over its previous cap-

Appendix 7 1

ital value at a given time or under given circumstances), in con- sequence of social growth or other cause apart from the owner's improvements, which enhances demand for it and therefore aug- ments its market price. The British (I/loyd George) budget of 1909 imposed a tax of 20 per cent, on ' ' unearned increments. ' ' For example : A holding officially valued in 1909 at ^100,000, if it were sold in 1924 for ^"120,000 (or, in certain circumstances, were then revalued at that amount), would have an "unearned increment" of ^"20,000, and upon this the tax would be 20 per cent. The owner would therefore keep ^16,000 of the increased social value, and the government would get ^"4,000. Some single taxers object to taxation of the "unearned increment," as being a process of division between society and successful investors in land, and as having no tendency toward the destruction of land- lordism, but rather a tendency to encourage land speculation with the state for a partner in the profits. This criticism does not seem to me valid ; its effect would most likely be to discourage efforts at promoting the single tax in places where movements for the taxation of ' ' unearned increments ' ' offer the only present leverage, or the best, for practical single tax work. True enough, unearned increment taxes do not take the entire rental value, nor enough of the capital value to deprive the owner of an unearned profit. Neither would any kind of land-value tax, short of the "single tax unlimited." But it does take a part of the land value of properties on which it falls, which is certainly better than taking none ; and, what is probably more important with this and all other kinds of land value taxation than the mere fact of the tax, is the nature of the agitation. Everywhere opposed as confiscation of private interests in land, it is everywhere defended as the taking for the community of what belongs to the community. Such agitations are especially promotive of the full single tax idea. That ' ' unearned increment ' ' taxes do not discourage speculation in land, and therefore fall short of the principal object of the single tax unlimited, is doubtless true ; but it is as certainly true that, defective though they may be in forcing vacant land upon the market, they do relieve industry from tax burdens, which is another prime object of the single tax. Their chief value, how- ever, is their tendency to develop an appreciation in public opin- ion of the fundamental fact that land values are community values and belong to the community. For a lucid explanation of the complex law for the taxation of ' ' unearned increment ' ' in Germany, see an article by Robert C. Brooks, of the University

72 The Taxation of Land Values

of Cincinnati, in the " Quarterly Journal of Economics" for Aug- ust, 1911. Professor Brooks characterizes the German law as "one of the largest and most significant practical applications of the single tax idea that has ever been attempted ;" and to the objection that the ' ' unearned increment ' ' tax of that law ' ' has ' no teeth in it, ' " he says that ' ' a fairer statement would be that it has simply cut its milk teeth and may be expected to develop mature molars and incisors later."

PART ONE, CHAPTER II, PAGES 11 TO 12

7. "Progress and Poverty," book viii, ch. ii.

8. In "Progress and Poverty," book viii, ch. iv, Henry George speaks of ' ' the effect of substituting for the manifold taxes now imposed, a single tax on the value of land ; ' ' but the term did not become a distinctive name until 1888. The first general movement along the lines of ' ' Progress and Poverty ' ' began with the New York City election of 1886, when Henry George polled 68,110 votes as L/abor candidate for mayor, and was defeated by the Democratic candidate, Abram S. Hewitt, by a plurality of only 22,442, the Republican, Theodore Roosevelt, polling but 60,435. Following that election the United Labor Party was organized on State lines, and at the Syracuse Convention in Aug- ust, 1887, it came to represent the central idea of " Progress and Poverty." Coincident with the organization of the United lyabor Party the Anti-Poverty Society was formed ; and the two bodies, one representing the political and the other the religious phase of the idea, worked together until President Cleveland's tariff mes- sage of 1887 appeared. In this message Mr. George saw the timid beginnings of that open struggle between Protection and Free Trade to which he had for years looked forward as the political movement that must culminate in the abolition of all taxes save those upon land values, and he responded at once to the senti- ment of the message. But many Protectionists who had followed him, now broke away from his leadership, and the United lyabor Party and the Anti-Poverty Society were soon dissolved. Those who understood Mr. George's real position regarding the land question readily acquiesced in his views as to political policy, and a considerable movement resulted, which, however, for some time lacked an identifying name. This was the situation when Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., wrote for the Standard an article on

Appendix 73

taxation in which he illustrated and advocated the land value tax as a fiscal measure. The article had been submitted without a caption, and Mr. George, then editor of the Standard, entitled it "The Single Tax." This title was at once adopted by the "George men," as they were often called, and has since served as the name of the movement it describes. Though ' ' the single tax" is the English form of "1'impot unique," the name of the French physiocratic doctrine of the eighteenth century, the names have no historical connection. See ' ' lyife of Henry George, ' ' by Henry George, Jr., chapter ix, p. 496 and 496 n.

9. ' ' I/and-value taxation ' ' is the almost exclusive term in Great Britain. There are special reasons, one of which is that in that country, unlike the United States, there was no Imperial real estate taxation of importance until the adoption of the L,loyd George Budget of 1909. Prior to this the only real estate taxes were (1) survivals of the land- value tax of the time of William and Mary, based upon valuations of 200 years ago and very much reduced by commutations, and (2) "rates" (local taxes) based not upon capital values regardless of use but upon actual rentals. Occasion was thereby furnished for that British agitation for the taxation of land values of which the I/loyd George Budget was the first triumph.

10. When it is remembered that some land in cities is worth millions of dollars an acre, that a small building lot in the busi- ness center of even a small village is worth more than a whole field of the best farming land in the neighborhood, that a few acres of coal or iron land are worth more than great groups of farms, that the right of way of a railroad company through a thickly settled district or between important points may be worth more than its rolling stock and trackage, and that the value of workingmen's cottages in the suburbs is trifling in comparison with the value of city residence sites, the absurdity of the plea that the Single Tax would discriminate against farmers and small home owners and in favor of the rich is apparent. The bad faith of this plea is evident when we consider that under existing sys- tems of taxation the farmer and the small home owner are com- pelled to pay in taxes upon improvements, food, clothing, and other objects of consumption, much more than the full annual value of their bare land.

11. The difference between site value and improvement value is much more definite than it is often supposed to be. Even in

74 The Taxation of Land Values

what would seem at first to be most confusing cases, it is easily distinguished. If in any example we imagine the complete des- truction of all the improvements, we may discover in the remain- ing value of the property in the price it would after such des- truction fetch in the real estate market the value of the site as distinguished from the value of the improvements. This residuum of value would be the basis of computation for levying the Single Tax. The distinction is frequently made in business life. When- ever in the course of ordinary business affairs it becomes necessary to estimate the value of a building lot or to fix royalties for mining privileges, no difficulty is experienced, and substantial justice is done. And though the exigencies of business seldom require the site value of an improved farm to be distinguished from the value of the improvements, yet it could doubtless be done as easily and justly as with city or mining property. Unimproved land attached to any farm in question, or unimproved land in the neighborhood, if similar in fertility and location, would furnish a sufficiently accurate measure. If neither existed, the value for enclosure of the contiguous highway would always be available. It should not be forgotten, either, that land for which the demand is so weak that its site value cannot be easily distinguished from the value of its improvements must be land of but little value. The objection that the value of land cannot be distinguished from the value of improvements is among the most frivolous of the objections that have been raised to the Single Tax by people with whom the wish that it may be impracticable is father to the thought that it really is so. Equally frivolous is the objection that land values cannot be scientifically appraised. This objection has been demolished by W. A. Somers, for years a Minnesota assessor, who is the inventor of the Somers system of scientific land valuation . The Somers sys- tem won the confidence of Tom I/. Johnson, Mayor of Cleveland, and its use in the first quadrennial valuations of Cleveland in 1910, under the personal supervision of Mr. Somers, was a demon- stration of its exceptional value. It is described in The Public, of Chicago, at pages 604, 608 and 827 of volume xiii. Mr. Somers superintends the use of his system by a corporation of Cleveland, Ohio, which is engaged in the business of valuing land. This fact has raised against him the objection that he has ' ' commercialized ' ' his system, and that the employment of his corporation by tax authorities to assist them in their official duties is a " farming out" of taxes. The objection appears to be far-fetched. It should be made known for whatever it may be worth ; but so far

Appendix 75

as Single Taxers are concerned, the point is not whether the system has been ' ' commercialized ' ' but whether variations in land value can be ascertained by means of it with economy and approximate accuracy. On this point Tom L/. Johnson, whose judgment in such a matter rightly commanded respect, has testified strongly in the affirmative.

12. "Taxes are either direct or indirect. A direct tax is one which is demanded from the very persons who it is intended or desired should pay it. Indirect taxes are those which are de- manded from one person in the expectation and intention that he shall indemnify himself at the expense of another."— John Stuart Mill's Prin. of Pol. EC., book v, ch. Hi, sec. 1. t "Direct taxes are those which are levied on the very persons who it is intended or desired should pay them, and which they cannot put off upon others by raising the prices of the taxed articles. . . Indirect taxes on the other hand are those which are levied on persons who expect to get back the amount of the tax by raising the price of the taxed articles." Laughlin's Elements, par. 249. 1 Taxes are direct ' ' when the payment is made by the person who is in- tended to bear the sacrifice." Indirect taxes are recovered from final purchasers.— Jevons' s Primer, sec. 96. If " Indirect taxes are so called because they are not paid into the treasury by the person who really bears the burden. The payer adds the amount of the tax to the price of the commodity taxed, and thus the taxation is concealed under the increased price of some article of luxury or convenience." Thompson's Pol. EC., sec. 175. U Read chapter iii, of book viii, " Progress and Poverty."

13. Jevons defines the incidence of a tax as "the manner in which it falls upon different classes of the population."— Jevons 's Primer, sec. 96. If Sometimes called "repercussion," and refers ' ' to the real as opposed to the nominal payment of taxes. ' ' Ely 's Taxation, p. 64.

14. Though his language was blunt, the sentiment does not essentially differ from that of ' ' statesmen ' ' of our day who meet all moral and economic objections to indirect taxation with the one reply that the people would not consent to pay enough for the support of government if public revenues were collected from them directly. This means nothing but that the people are actu- ally hoodwinked by indirect taxation into sustaining a government that they would not support if they knew it was maintained at their expense ; and instead of being a reason for continuing indi-

76 The Taxation of Land Values

rect taxation, would, if true, be one of the strongest of reasons for abolishing it. It is consistent neither with the plainest prin- ciples of democracy nor the simplest conceptions of morality.

15. A tax upon shoes, paid in the first instance by shoe manufacturers, enters into manufacturers' prices, and, together with the usual rate of profit upon that amount of investment, is recovered from wholesalers. The tax and the manufacturers' profit upon it then constitute part of the wholesale price and are collected from retailers. The retailers in turn collect the tax with all the intermediate profits upon it, together with their own usual rate of profit upon the whole, from final purchasers the consumers of shoes. Thus what appears on the surface to be a tax upon shoe manufacturers, proves upon examination to be an indirect tax upon shoe consumers, who pay in an accumulation of profits upon the tax considerably more than the government receives. The effect would be the same if a tax upon their leather output were imposed upon tanners. Tanners would add to the price of leather the amount of the tax, plus their usual rate of profit upon a like investment, and collect the whole, together with the cost of hides, of transportation, of tanning and of selling, from shoe manufacturers, who would collect with their profit from retailers, who would collect with their profit from shoe con- sumers. The principle applies also when taxes are levied upon the stocks or sales of merchants, or the moneys or credits of bankers ; merchants add the tax with the usual profit to the prices of their goods, and bankers add it to their interest and discounts. It must not be supposed, however, that recovery of indirect taxes from the ultimate consumers of taxed goods is arbitrary. When shoe manufacturers, or tanners, or merchants add taxes to prices, or bankers add them to interest, it is not because they might do otherwise but choose to do this ; it is because competition compels them. Manufacturers, merchants, and other tradesmen who carry on competitive businesses must on the average sell their goods at cost plus the ordinary rate of profit, or go out of business. It follows that any increase in cost of produc- tion tends to increase the price of products, and that any fall in cost tends to decrease the price. Now, a tax upon the output of business men, which they must pay as a condition of doing their business, is as truly part of the cost of their output as is the price of the materials they buy or the wages of the men they hire. Therefore, such a tax upon business men tends to increase the price of their products. And this tendency is more or less marked

Appendix 77

as the tax is more or less great and competition more or less keen. It is true that a moderate tax upon monopolized products, such as trade-mark goods, proprietary medicines, patented articles and copyright publications is not necessarily shifted to consumers. The monopoly manufacturer whose prices are not checked by the cost of production, and are therefore as a rule higher than com- petitive prices would be, may find it more profitable to bear the burden of a tax that leaves him some profit, thereby retaining his entire custom, than to drive off part of his custom by adding the tax to his usual prices. This is true also of a moderate import tax to the extent that it falls upon goods that are more cheaply transported from the place of production to a foreign market where the import tax is imposed than to a home market where the goods would be free of such a tax products, for instance, of a farm in Canada near to a New York town, but far away from any Canadian town. If the tax be less than the difference in the cost of transportation the producer will bear the burden of it ; otherwise he will not. The ultimate effect would be a reduction in the value of the Canadian land. Examples which may be cited in opposition to the principle that import taxes are indirect, will upon examination prove to be of the character here described. Business cannot be carried on at a loss not for long. Therefore taxes on business must as a rule be borne not by the business house but by its customers.

16. "To collect taxes, to prevent and punish evasions, to check and counter-check revenues drawn from so many distinct sources, now make up probably three- fourths, perhaps seven- eighths, of the business of government outside of the preservation of order, the maintenance of the military arm, and the adminis- tration of justice." Progress and Poverty, book iv, ch, v.

17. For a brief and thorough exposition of indirect taxation, read George's "Protection or Free Trade," ch. viii, on "Tariffs for Revenue."

18. This is usually a stumbling block to those who, without much experience in economic thought, consider land value taxa- tion for the first time. As soon as they grasp the idea that taxes upon labor products shift to consumers, they jump to the conclusion that similarly taxes upon land values would shift to users. But this is a mistake, and the explanation is simple. Taxes upon what men produce make production more difficult and so tend toward scarcity in the supply of products, which stimulates prices ;

78 The Taxation of Land Values

but taxes upon land, provided the taxes be levied in proportion to value, tend towards plenty in the supply of land (meaning market supply of course) because they make it more difficult to hold val- uable land idle, and so they depress prices. Taxes on products are added to their price, for all competing products must pay the tax; but taxes on land values are not added to the price of land, for competing land of no price would pay no tax. If ' ' A tax on rent falls wholly on the landlord. There are no means by which he can shift the burden upon any one else. . . A tax on rent, therefore, has no effect other than its obvious one. It merely takes so much from the landlord and transfers it to the state." John Stuart Mill's Prin. of Pol. EC., book v., ch. Hi, sec. 1. f "A tax laid upon rent is borne solely by the owner of land." Bascom*s Tr.,p. 159. 1 "Taxes which are levied on land . . . really fall on the owner of the land." Mrs. Fawcetfs Pol. EC. for Beginners, pp. 209, 210. 1 ' 'A land tax levied in proportion to the rent of land, and varying with every variation of rent, . . will fall wholly on the landlords." Walker's Pol. EC., ed. of 1887, p. 413, quoting Ricardo. f'The power of transferring a tax from the person who actually pays it to some other person varies with the object taxed. A tax on rents cannot be transferred. A tax on commodities is always transferred to the consumer." Thorold Rogers' s Pol. EC., ch xxi, 2ded.,p. 285. 1 "Though the landlord is in all cases the real contributor, the tax is com- monly advanced by the tenant, to whom the landlord is obliged to allow it in payment of the rent." Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations, book v, ch. ii, part ii, art. i. \ " The way taxes raise prices is by increasing the cost of production and checking supply. But land is not a thing of human production, and taxes upon rent cannot check supply. Therefore, though a tax upon rent compels land-owners to pay more, it gives them no power to obtain more for the use of their land, as it in no way tends to reduce the sup- ply of land. On the contrary, by compelling those who hold land on speculation to sell or let for what they can get, a tax on land values tends to increase the competition between owners, and thus to reduce the price of land." Progress and Poverty, book viii, ch. Hi, sudd. ii. 1 Sometimes this point is raised as a question of shifting the tax in higher rent to the tenant, and at others as a question of shifting it to the consumers of goods in higher prices. The principle is the same. Merchants cannot charge higher prices for goods than their competitors do, merely because they pay higher ground rents. A country storekeeper whose business

Appendix 79

site is worth but a few dollars, charges as much for sugar, probably more, than a city grocer whose site is worth thousands. Quality for quality and quantity for quantity, goods sell for about the same price everywhere. Differences in price are altogether in favor of places where land has a high value. This is due to the fact that the cost of getting goods to places of low land value, distant villages for example, is greater than to centers which are places of high land value. Sometimes it is true that prices for some things are higher where land values are high. Tiffany's goods, for instance, may be more expensive than goods of the same quality at a store on a less expensive site. But that is not due to higher land value ; it is because the dealer has a reputa- tion for technical knowledge and honesty (or has become a fad among rich people), for which his customers are willing to pay whether his store is on a high priced site or on a low priced one. Though land value has no effect upon the price of goods, it is easier to sell goods in some locations than in others. Therefore, though the price and the profit of each sale be the same, or even less, in good locations than in poorer ones, aggregate receipts and aggregate profits are much greater at the good location. And it is out of this aggregate, and not out of each profit, that rent is paid. For example : A cigar store on a thoroughfare supplies a certain quality of cigar at fifteen cents. On a side street the same quality of cigar can be bought no cheaper. Indeed, the cigars there are likely to be poorer, and therefore really dearer. Yet ground rent on the thoroughfare is very high compared with ground rent on the side street. How, then, can the first dealer, he who pays the high ground rent, afford to sell as good or bet- ter cigars for fifteen cents than his competitor of the low priced location? Simply because he is able to make so many more sales with a given outlay of labor and capital in a given time that his aggregate profit is greater. This is due to the advantage of his location. And for that advantage he pays a premium in higher ground rent. But the premium is not charged to smokers ; the dealer of the side street protects them by his competition. It represents the greater ease, the lower cost, of doing a given vol- ume of business upon the site for which it is paid ; and if the state should take any of it, even the whole of it, in taxation, the loss would be finally borne by the owner of the advantage which attaches to that site by the landlord. Any attempt to shift it to tenant or buyer would be promptly checked by the competition of neighboring but cheaper land. 1 ' 'A land tax, levied in proportion

80 The Taxation of Land Values

to the rent of land, and varying with every variation of rent, is in effect a tax on rent ; and as such a tax will not apply to that land which yields no rent, nor to the produce of that capital which is employed on the land with a view to profit merely, and which never pays rent ; it will not in any way affect the price of raw produce, but will fall wholly on the landlords." McCulloch's Ric- ardo, 2d ed. , p. 107. 1 Moreover, prospective taxes on land values are capitalized and deducted from purchase price in land sales, so that land buyers pay no taxes on their land unless it rises in value, and then only on the increase. This is demonstrated in Fillebrown's "A. B. C. of Taxation," which is valuable also on other points regarding taxation of land values. Among its fiscal statistics are those of a kind which, since they are also of later date, may be substituted for illustrative uses for the computa- tions of James R. Carret, the Boston conveyancer, which have appeared in note 13 of previous editions of this book.

PART TWO, CHAPTER II, PAGES 14 TO 15

19. It is often said, for instance, by its advocates, that house owners should in justice contribute to the support of the fire de- partments that protect them ; and it is even gravely argued that houses are more appropriate subjects for taxation than land, because they need protection, whereas land needs none. Read Note 24.

PART TWO, CHAPTER III, PAGES 15 TO 17

20. I/and values are lower in all countries of poor govern- ment than in any country of better government, other things being equal. They are lower in cities of poor government, other things being equal, than in cities of better government. I/and values are lower, for example, in Juarez, on the Mexican side of the Rio Grande, where government is poor, than in Kl Paso, the neigh- boring city on the American side where government is better. They are lower in the same city under poor government than under improved government. L/et the city authorities anywhere pave a street, put water through it and sewer it, or make any other improvement, and building lots in the neighborhood rise in value. Kverywhere that the ' ' good roads ' ' agitation has borne fruit in better highways, the value of adjacent land has in-

Appendix 81

creased. Instances of this effect as results of public improvements might be collected in abundance. Every man must know of some within his own experience. And it is perfectly reasonable that it should be so. L/and and not other property must rise in value with desirable improvements in government, because, while any tendency on the part of other kinds of property to rise in value is checked by greater production, land cannot be reproduced. Imagine an utterly lawless place, where life and property are con- stantly threatened by desperadoes. He must be either a very bold man or a very avaricious one who will build a store in such a community and stock it with goods. But suppose such a man should appear. His store costs him more than the same building would cost in a civilized community ; mechanics are not plentiful in such a place, and materials are hard to get. The building is finally erected, however, and stocked. And now what about this merchant's prices for goods? Competition is weak, because there are few men who will take the chances he has taken, and he charges all that his customers will pay. A hundred per cent. , five hundred per cent. , perhaps one or two thousand per cent, profit rewards him for his pains and risk. His goods are dear, enormously dear dear enough to satisfy the most contemptuous enemy of cheapness ; and if any one should wish to buy his store, that would be dear too, for the difficulties in the way of building continue. But land is cheap! This is the type of community in which may be found the land, so often mentioned and so seldom seen, which "the owners actually can't give away, you know! " But suppose now that government improves. An efficient admin- istration of justice rids the place of desperadoes, and life and property are safe. What about prices then? It would no longer require a bold or desperately avaricious man to engage in selling goods in that community, and competition would set in. High profits would come down. Goods would be cheap as cheap as anywhere in the world, the cost of transportation considered. Builders and building materials could be had without difficulty, and stores would be cheap, too. But land would be dear! Im- improvement in government increases the value of that, and of that alone.

21. Railroad franchises, for example, are not usually thought of as land titles, but that is what they are. By an act of sovereign authority they confer rights of control for transportation purposes over narrow strips of land at terminals (especially at terminals), and between terminals and along trading points. The value of

82 The Taxation of Land Values

this right of way is a land value. The same is true of street fran- chises, water power, etc.

22. Each occupant would pay to his landlord the value of the public benefits in the way of highways, schools, courts, police and fire protection, etc., that his site enabled him to enjoy. The landlord would pay a tax proportioned to the pecuniary benefits conferred upon him by the public in raising and maintaining the value of his holding. And if occupant and owner were the same, he would pay directly according to the value of his land for all the public benefits he enjoyed.

23. While the land-owners of the City of Washington were paying something less than two per cent, annually in taxes, a Congressional Committee (Report of the Select Committee to In- vestigate Tax Asseessments in the District of Columbia, composed of Messrs, Tom L. Johnson, of Ohio, Chairman; Wadsworth, of New York, and Washington, of Tennessee. Made to the House of Representatives, May 24, 1892. Report No. 1469}, brought out the fact that the value of their land had been increas- ing at a minimum rate of ten per cent, per annum. The Wash- ington land-owners as a class thus appear to have received back in higher land values, actually and potentially, about ten dollars for every two dollars that as land-owners they paid in taxes. If any one supposes that this condition is peculiar to Washington, let him make similar estimates for any progressive locality and see if the land-owners there are not favored in like manner. But the point is not dependent upon increase in the capitalized value of land. If the land yields or is capable of yielding to its owner an income in the nature of ground rent, then to the extent that this actual or possible income is dependent upon government, the landlord is in effect exempt from taxation. No matter what tax he pays on account of his ownership of land, the public gives it back to him to that extent.

24. Take for illustration two towns, one of excellent govern- ment and the other of inefficient government, but in all other respects alike. Suppose you are hunting for a place of residence and find a suitable site in the town of good government. For simplicity of illustration let us suppose that the land there is not sold outright but is let upon ground rent. You meet the owner of the lot you have selected and ask him his terms. He replies :

"Two hundred and fifty dollars a year."

c ' Two hundred and fifty dollars a year ! ' ' you exclaim. ' 'Why,

Appendix 83

I can get just as good a site in that other town for a hundred dollars a year. ' '

' ' Certainly you can, ' ' he will say. ' ' But if you build a house there and it catches fire it will burn down ; they have no fire de- partment. If you go out after dark you will be ' held up ' and robbed ; they have no police force. If you ride out in the spring, your carriage will stick in the mud up to the hubs, and if you walk you may break your legs and will be lucky if you don't break your neck ; they have no street pavements and their side- walks are dangerously out of repair. When the moon doesn't shine the streets are dark, for they have no street lights. The water you need for your house you must get from a well ; there is no water supply there. Now in our town it is different. We have a splendid fire department, and the best police force in the world. Our streets are macadamized and lighted with electricity; our sidewalks are always in first class repair ; we have a water system that equals that of New York ; and in every way the pub- lic benefits in this town are unsurpassed. It is the best governed town in all this region. Isn't it worth a hundred and fifty dollars a year more for a building site here than over in that poorly gov- erned town ? ' '

You recognize the advantages and agree to the terms.

But when your house is built and the assessor visits you officially, what would be the conversation if your sense of the fit- ness of things were not warped by familiarity with false systems of taxation? Would it not be something like what follows?

"How much do you regard this house as worth? " asks the assessor.

"What is that to you? " you inquire.

' ' I am the town assessor and I am about to appraise your property for taxation."

" Am I to be taxed by this town ? What f or ? "

"What for?" echoes the assessor in surprise. "What for? Is not your house protected from fire by our magnificent fire de- partment ? Are not you protected from robbery by the best police force in the world? Do you not have the use of macadamized pavements, and good sidewalks, and electric street lights, and a first class water supply? Don't you suppose those things cost something? And don't you think you ought to pay your share? "

"Yes," you answer with more or less calmness, " I do have the benefit of those things and I do think that I ought to pay my share toward supporting them. But I have already paid my share

84 The Taxation of Land Values

for this year. I have paid it to the owner of this lot. He charges me two hundred and fifty dollars a year one hundred and fifty dollars more than I should pay or he could get but for those very benefits. He has collected my share of this year's expense of maintaining town improvements ; you go and collect from him. If you do not, but insist upon collecting from me, I shall be pay- ing twice for those things, once to him and once to you ; and he won't be paying at all, but will be making money out of them, although he derives the same benefits from them in all other respects that I do."

It is bad public policy, to say nothing of the bad civic morals, to reckon what the community ought to get by what it needs. This policy is a survival of the old idea that taxes are tribute. On the hypothesis that taxes are compensation for service, we must reckon what the community ought to get by the value of what it gives.

PART TWO, CHAPTER IV, PAGES 17 TO 19

25. "Progress and Poverty," book viii, ch. iii.

26. This is the second part of Adam Smith's fourth maxim. He states it as follows : ' ' Every tax ought to be so contrived as both to take out and to keep out of the pockets of the people as little as possible over and above what it brings into the public treasury of the state. A tax may either take out or keep out of the pockets of the people a great deal more than it brings into the public treasury in the four following ways : . . Secondly, it may ob- struct the industry of the people, and discourage them from applying to certain branches of business which might give main- tenance and employment to great multitudes. While it obliges the people to pay, it may thus diminish or perhaps destroy some of the funds which might enable them more easily to do so."

27. This is the first part of Adam Smith's fourth maxim, in which he condemns a tax that takes out of the pockets of the people more than it brings into the public treasury.

28. This is Adam Smith's second maxim. He states it as follows : ' ' The tax which each individual is bound to pay ought to be certain and not arbitrary. The time of payment, the man- ner of payment, the quantity to be paid, ought all to be clear and plain to the contributor and to every other person. Where it is otherwise, every person subject to the tax is put more or less in the power of the tax gatherer."

Appendix 85

29. This is Adam Smith's first maxim. He states it as fol- lows: "The subjects of every state ought to contribute towards the support of the government as nearly as possible in proportion to their respective abilities, that is to say, in proportion to the revenue which they respectively enjoy under the protection of the state. The expense of government to the individuals of a great nation is like the expense of management to the joint tenants of a great estate, who are all obliged to contribute in proportion to their respective interests in the estate. In the observation or neglect of this maxim consists what is called the equality or inequality of taxation. ' ' In altering this maxim Henry George says ("Progress and Poverty," book viii, ch. iii, subd. 4): ' 'Adam Smith speaks of incomes as enjoyed ' under the protec- tion of the state ' ; and this is the ground upon which the equal taxation of all species of property is commonly insisted upon that it is equally protected by the state. The basis of this idea is evidently that the enjoyment of property is made possible by the state that there is a value created and maintained by the com- munity, which is justly called upon to meet community expenses. Now, of what values is this true? Only of the value of land. This is a value that does not arise until a community is formed, and that, unlike other values, grows with the growth of the com- munity. It only exists as the community exists. Scatter again the largest community, and land, now so valuable, would have no value at all. With every increase of population the value of land rises ; with every decrease it falls. This is true of nothing else save of things which, like the ownership of land, are in their nature monopolies." Adam Smith's third maxim refers only to conveniency of payment, and gives countenance to indirect taxa- tion, which is in conflict with the principle of his fourth maxim. Mr. George properly excludes it.

30. ' ' Taxation which falls upon the processes of production interposes an artificial obstacle to the creation of wealth. Taxa- tion which falls upon labor as it is exerted, wealth as it is used as capital, land as it is cultivated, will manifestly tend to discour- age production much more powerfully than taxation to the same amount levied upon laborers whether they work or play, upon wealth whether used productively or unproductively, or upon land whether cultivated or left waste." Progress and Poverty, book viii, ch. iii, subd. 1.

31. It is common, besides taxing improvements as fast as

86 The Taxation of Land Values

they are made, to levy higher taxes upon land when put to its best use than when put to partial use or to no use at all. This is upon the theory that when his land is used the owner gets full income from it and can afford to pay high taxes ; but that he gets little or no income when the land is out of use, and so cannot afford to pay much. It is an absurd but perfectly legitimate illus- tration of the pretentious doctrine of taxation according ability to pay. Examples are numerous. Improved building lots, and even those that are only plotted for improvement, are usually taxed more than contiguous unused and unplotted land which is equally in demand for building purposes and equally valuable. So coal land, iron land, oil land and sugar land are as a rule taxed more as land when opened up for appropriate use than when lying idle or put to inferior uses, though the land value be the same. Any serious proposal to put land to its appropriate use is com- monly regarded as a signal for increasing the tax upon it.

32. "All taxes upon things of unfixed quantity increase prices, and in the course of exchange are shifted from seller to buyer, increasing as they go. If we impose a tax on money loaned, as has been often attempted, the lender will charge the tax to the borrower, and the borrower must pay it or not obtain the loan. If the borrower uses it in his business, he in his turn must get back the tax from his customers, or his business becomes unprofitable. If we impose a tax upon buildings, the users of buildings must finally pay it, for the erection of buildings will cease until building rents become high enough to pay the regular profit and the tax besides. If we impose a tax upon manufactures or imported goods, the manufacturer or importer will charge it in a higher price to the jobber, the jobber to the retailer, and the retailer to the consumer. Now, the consumer, upon whom the tax thus ultimately falls, must not only pay the amount of the tax, but also a profit on this amount to every one who has thus advanced it for profit on the capital he has advanced in paying taxes is as much required by each dealer as profit on the capital he has advanced in paying for goods." Progress and Poverty , book viii, ch. Hi, subd. 2.

33. The under-appraisements so common at present, and alluded to in Note 31, are possible because the community, ignor- ant of the just principles of taxation, does connive at them. Under-appraisements are not secret crimes on the part of asses- sors ; they are distinctly recognized, but thoughtlessly disregarded

Appendix 87

when not actually insisted upon by the people themselves. And this is due to the dishonest ideas of taxation that are taught. i,et the vicious doctrine that people ought to pay taxes according to their ability, give way to the honest principle that they should pay in proportion to the benefits they receive, which benefits, as we have already seen, are measured by the land values they own, and under-appraisement of land would cease. No assessor can be- fool the community in respect of the value of the land within his jurisdiction. And with the cessation of general under-appraise- ment, favoritism in individual appraisements would also cease. General under-appraisment fosters unfair individual appraisements. If land were generally appraised at its full value, a particular unfair appraisement would stand out in such relief that the crime of the assessor would be exposed. But now, if a man's land is appraised at a higher valuation than his neighbor's equally valuable land, and he complains of the unfairness, he is promptly and effectually silenced with a warning that his land is worth much more than it is appraised at, anyhow, and if he makes a fuss his appraisement will be increased. To complain further of the deficient taxation of his neighbor is to invite the imposition of a higher tax upon himself.

34. If you wish to test the merits in point of certainty of land value taxation as compared with other taxes, go to a real estate agent in your community and, showing him a building lot upon the map, ask him its value. If he inquires about the improve- ments, instruct him to ignore them. He will be able at once to tell you what the lot is worth. And if you go to twenty other agents, their estimates will not materially vary from his. Yet none of the agents will have left his office. Each will have inferred the value from the size and location of the lot. But suppose when you show the map to the first agent you ask him the value of the land and its improvements. He will tell you that he cannot give an esti- mate until he examines the improvements. And if it is the highly improved property of a rich man he will engage building experts to assist him. Should you ask him to include the value of the contents of the buildings, he would need a corps of selected experts, including artists and liverymen, dealers in furniture and bric-a-brac, librarians and jewelers. Should you propose that he also include the value of the occupant's income, the agent would throw up his hands in despair. If without the aid of an army of experts the agent should make an estimate of these miscellaneous values, and twenty others should do the same, their several esti-

88 The Taxation of Land Values

mates would be as wide apart as ignorant guesses usually are. And the richer the owner of the property the lower as a propor- tion would the guesses probably be. Now turn the real estate agent into an assessor, and is it not plain that he could appraise land values with much greater certainty and cheapness than he could appraise the values of all kinds of property? With a plot map before him he might fairly make almost all the appraise- ments without leaving his desk at the town hall. And there would be no material difference if the property in question were a farm instead of a building lot. A competent farmer or business man in a farming community can, without leaving his own door- yard, appraise the value of the land of any farm there; whereas it would be impossible for him to value the improvements, stock, produce, etc., without at least inspecting them.

35. The benefits of government are not the only public ben- efits whose value attaches exclusively to land. Communal devel- opment from whatever cause produces the same effect. But as it is under the protection of government that land-owners are able to maintain ownership of land and through that to enjoy the pecuniary benefits of advancing social conditions, government confers upon them as a class not only the pecuniary benefits of good government, but also the pecuniary benefits of progress in general.

36. ' ' Here are two men of equal incomes that of the one derived from the exertion of his labor, that of the other from rent of land. Is it just that they should equally contribute to the expenses of the state? Evidently not. The income of the one represents wealth he creates and adds to the general wealth of the state ; the income of the other represents merely wealth that he takes from the general stock, returning nothing." Progress and Poverty, book viii, ch. iii, subd. 4.

PART THREE, CHAPTER i, PAGES 20 TO 22

37. Not all charity is contemptible. Those charitable people, who, knowing that individuals suffer, hasten to their relief, de- serve the respect and affection they enjoy. That kind of charity is neighborliness ; it is love. And perhaps in modern circum- stances organization is necessary to make it effective. But organ- ized charity as a cherished social institution is a different thing. It is not love, nor is it inspired by love ; it is simply sanctified

Appendix 89

selfishness, at the bottom of which will be found the blasphemous notion that in the economy of God the poor are to be forever with us that the rich may gain heaven by alms-giving. Suppose a hole in the sidewalk into which passers-by continually fall, breaking their arms, their legs, and sometimes their necks. We should respect charitable people who, without thought of themselves, went to the relief of the sufferers, binding the broken limbs of the living, and decently burying the dead. But what should we think of those who, when some one proposed to fill up the hole to prevent further suffering, should say, "Oh, you mustn't fill up that hole ! Whatever in the world should we charitable people do to be saved if we had no broken legs and arms to bind, and no broken-necked people to bury? " Of some kinds of charity it has been well said that they are "that form of self-righteousness which makes us give to others the things that already belong to them. ' ' They suggest the old nursery rime :

"There was once a considerate crocodile, Which lay on the bank of the river Nile. And he swallowed a fish, with face of woe, While his tears flowed fast to the stream below. 'I am mourning,' said he, 'the untimely fate Of the dear little fish which I just now ate.' " Read Chapter viii of ' ' Social Problems, ' ' by Henry George, en- titled, "That We All Might Be Rich."

38. Differences between ' ' hard times ' ' and ' ' good times ' ' are but differences in degrees of poverty and in the people who suffer from it. Times are always hard with the multitude. But the voice of the multitude is too weak to be heard at ordinary times through the ordinary trumpets of public opinion. They are not regarded nor do they regard themselves as people of any im- portance in the industrial world, so long as the general wheels of business revolve. It is only when poverty has eaten its way up through the various strata of struggling and pinching and squeez- ing and squirming humanity, and with its cancerous tentacles touched the superincumbent layers of manufacturing nabobs, merchant princes, railroad kings, great bankers and great land- owners, that we hear any general complaint of "hard times."

39. "Could a man of the last century a Franklin or a Priestly have seen, in a vision of the future, the steamship taking the place of the sailing vessel, the railroad train of the wagon, the reaping machine of the scythe, the threshing machine of the flail ; could he have heard the throb of the engines that in

90 The Taxation of Land Values

obedience to human will, and for the satisfaction of human desire, exert a power greater than that of all the men and all the beasts of burden of the earth combined ; could he have seen the forest tree transformed into finished lumber into doors, sashes, blinds, boxes or barrels, with hardly the touch of a human hand ; the great workshops where boots and shoes are turned out by the case with less labor than the old-fashioned cobbler could have put on a sole ; the factories where, under the eye of a girl, cotton be- comes cloth faster than hundreds of stalwart weavers could have turned it out with their hand-looms ; could he have seen steam hammers shaping mammoth shafts and mighty anchors, and deli- cate machinery making tiny watches ; the diamond drill cutting through the heart of the rocks, and coal oil sparing the whale ; could he have realized the enormous saving of labor resulting from improved facilities of exchange and communication sheep killed in Australia eaten fresh in Bngland, and the order given by the I/ondon banker in the afternoon executed in San Francisco in the morning of the same day ; could he have conceived of the hundred thousand improvements which these only suggest, what would he have inferred as to the social condition of mankind ? It would not have seemed like an inference ; further than the vision went it would have seemed as though he saw ; and his heart would have leaped and his nerves would have thrilled, as one who from a height beholds just ahead of the thirst-stricken caravan the living gleam of rustling woods and the glint of laughing waters. Plainly, in the sight of the imagination, he would have beheld these new forces elevating society from its very foundations, lifting the very poorest above the possibility of want, exempting the very lowest from anxiety for the material needs of life. . . And out of these bounteous material condi- tions he would have seen arising, as necessary sequences, moral conditions realizing the golden age of which mankind have always dreamed. . . More or less vague or clear, these have been the hopes, these the dreams born of the improvements which give this wonderful century its pre-eminence. . . It is true that disappointment has followed disappointment, and that discovery upon discovery, and invention after invention, have neither lessened the toil of those who most need respite, nor brought plenty to the poor. But there have been so many things to which it seemed this failure could be laid, that up to our time the new faith has hardly weakened. . . Now, however, we are coming into collision with facts which there can be no mistaking.

Appendix 9 1

. . And, unpleasant as it may be to admit it, it is at last becom- ing evident that the enormous increase of productive power which has marked the present century and is still going on with acceler- ating ratio, has no tendency to extirpate poverty or to lighten the burdens of those compelled to toil. It simply widens the gulf between Dives and Lazarus, and makes the struggle for existence more intense. The march of invention has clothed mankind with powers of which a century ago the boldest imagination could not have dreamed. But in factories where labor-saving machinery has reached its most wonderful development little children are at work ; wherever the new forces are anything like fully utilized large classes are maintained by charity or live on the verge of recourse to it ; amid the greatest accumulations of wealth, men die of starvation, and puny infants suckle dry breasts; while everywhere the greed of gain, the worship of wealth, shows the force of the fear of want." Progress and Poverty , Introduction.

40. The leader of one of the labor strikes of the early eighties, a hard-working, respectable, and self-respecting man, told me that the deprivations which he himself suffered as a workingman were nothing as compared with the fear for the future of his children that he felt whenever he thought of the repulsive sur- roundings, physical and moral, in which, owing to his poverty, he was compelled to bring them up. \ Professor Francis Way- land, Dean of the Yale law school, wrote in the Charities Review for March, 1893 : ' ' Under our eyes and within our reach children are being reared from infancy amid surroundings containing every conceivable element of degradation, depravity and vice. Why, then, should we be surprised that we are surrounded by a horde of juvenile delinquents, that the police reports in our cities teem with the exploits of precocious little villains, that reform schools are crowded with hopelessly abandoned young offenders? How could it be otherwise ? What else could be expected from such antecedents, from such ever-present examples of flagrant vice? Short of a miracle, how could any child escape the moral contag- ion of such an environment? How could he retain a single vestige of virtue, a single honest impulse, a single shred of respect for the rights of others, after passing through such an ordeal of iniquity? What is there left on which to build up a better char- acter? " In the Arena of July, 1893. Helen Campbell said : "It would seem at times as if the workshop meant only a form of preparation for the hospital, the workhouse and the prison, since the workers therein become inoculated with trade diseases, mutil-

92 The Taxation of Land Values

ated by trade appliances, and corrupted by trade associates till no healthy fiber, mental, moral, or physical remains." This testi- mony bears a distant date but it is as true now as when it was uttered ; and similar testimony only recently uttered is abundant. But no further citation is necessary to arouse the conscience of the merciful and the just ; and any amount of proof would not affect those self-satisfied mortals whom Kipling describes when he says that "there are men who, when their own front doors are closed, will swear that the whole world's warm."

41. Some years ago a gentleman now well and favorably known in New York public life a judge these many years told me of a ragged tramp whom he had brought, more to gratify a whim perhaps than in any spirit of philanthropy, from a neigh- boring camp of tramps to his house for breakfast. After break- fast the host asked his guest, in the course of conversation, why he lived the life of a tramp. This in substance was the tramp's reply : "I am a mechanic and used to be a good one, though not so exceptionally good as to be safe from the competition of the great class of average workers. I had a family a wife and two children. In the hard times of the seventies I lost my job. For a while we lived upon our little savings ; but sickness came and our savings were used up. My wife and children died. Every- thing was gone but self-respect. Then I traveled, looking for work which could not be had at home. I traveled afoot ; I could afford no other way. For days I hunted for work, begging food and sleeping in barns or under trees ; but no work could I get. Once or twice I was arrested as a vagrant. Then I fell in with a party of tramps and with them drifted into the city. Winter came on. I still had a desire to regain my old place as a self-respecting man, but work was scarce and nothing that I could do could I find to do except some little job now and then which was given me as pennies are given to beggars. I slept mostly in station houses. Part of the time I was undergoing sentence for vagrancy. In the spring I tramped again. But now I did not hunt for work. My self-respect was gone so completely that I had no ambition to regain it. I was a loafer and a jail-bird. I had no family to sup- port, and I had found that, barring the question of self-respect, I was about as well off as were average workmen. After years of tramping this opinion is unchanged. I am always sure of enough to eat and a place to sleep in not very good often, but good enough. I should not be sure of that if I were a workingman. I might lose my job and go hungry rather than beg. I might be

Appendix 93

unable to pay my rent and so be turned upon the street. I might marry again and have a family which would be condemned to the hard life of the average workingman's family. And as for soci- ety, why, I have society. Tramps are good fellows sociable fel- lows, bright fellows many of them. L/ife as a tramp is not half bad when you compare it with the workingman's life, leaving out the question of self-respect, of course. You must leave that out. No man can be a tramp for good until he loses that. But a period of hard times makes many a chap lose it. And as I have lost it I would rather be a tramp than a workingman. I have tried both.

By the way, Mr. , this is a very good cigar this brand of

yours. I seldom smoke much better cigars. ' ' The facts in detail of this man's story may have been false; they probably were. But so were the facts in detail of Bunyan's "Pilgrim's Progress." There is, however, a distinction between fact and truth, and no matter how false the man's facts may have been, his story like Bunyan's was essentially true. Much of the poverty that upon the surface seems to be voluntary and undeserving comes from a growing feeling among those who work hardest that, as Cowper describes it, they are

"getting down buckets into empty wells,

And growing old with drawing nothing up."

At Victoria, B. C., in the spring of 1894, I witnessed a canoe race in which there were two contestants and but one prize. Ivong before the winner had reached the goal his adversary, who found himself far behind, turned his canoe toward the shore and dropped out of the race. Was it because he was too lazy to paddle? Not at all. It was because he realized the hopelessness of the effort.

42. H. C. Bunner, once editor of Puck,

43. A well known millionaire is quoted as saying : "I would rather leave my children penniless in a world in which they could at all times obtain employment for wages equal to the value of their work as measured by the work of others, than to leave them millions of dollars in a world like this, where if they lose their inheritance they may have no chance of earning a decent living. ' ' This millionaire was Tom Iv. Johnson. What he said was in reply to a question at a public meeting in St. I/ouis in 1893.

44. "From whence springs this lust for gain, to gratify which men tread everything pure and noble under their feet ; to which they sacrifice all the higher possibilities of life ; which con- verts civility into a hollow pretence, patriotism into a sham, and

94 The Taxation of Land Values

religion into hypocrisy ; which makes so much of civilized exist- ence an Ishmaelitish warfare, of which the weapons are cunning and fraud? Does it not spring from the existence of want? Carlyle somewhere says that poverty is the hell of which the modern Englishman is most afraid. And he is right. Poverty is the open-mouthed, relentless hell which yawns beneath civilized society. And it is hell enough. The Vedas declare no truer thing than when the wise crow Bushanda tells the eagle bearer of Vishnu that the keenest pain is in poverty. For poverty is not merely deprivation ; it means shame, degradation ; the searing of the most sensitive parts of our moral and mental nature as with hot irons ; the denial of the strongest impulses and the sweetest affec- tions ; the wrenching of the most vital nerves. You love your wife, you love your children ; but would it not be easier to see them die than to see them reduced to the pinch of want in which large classes in every civilized community live? . . From this hell of poverty it is but natural that men should make every effort to escape. With the impulse to self-preservation and self-gratifi- cation combine nobler feelings, and love as well as fear urges in the struggle. Many a man does a mean thing, a dishonest thing, a greedy and grasping and unjust thing, in the effort to place above want, or the fear of want, mother or wife or children." Progress and Poverty, book ix, ch. iv.

45. "There is just now a disposition to scoff at any implica- tion that we are not in all respects progressing. . . Yet it is evident that there have been times of decline, just as there have been times of advance ; and it is further evident that these epochs of decline could not at first have been generally recognized. He would have been a rash man who, when Augustus was changing the Rome of brick to the Rome of marble, when wealth was aug- menting and magnificence increasing, when victorious legions were extending the frontier, when manners were becoming more refined, language more polished, and literature rising to higher splendors he would have been a rash man who then would have said that Rome was entering her decline. Yet such was the case. And whoever will look may see that though our civilization is apparently advancing with greater rapidity than ever, the same cause which turned Roman progress into retrogression is operating now. What has destroyed every previous civilization has been the tendency to the unequal distribution of wealth and power. This same tendency, operating with increasing force, is observable in our civilization to-day, showing itself in every progressive

Appendix 95

community, and with greater intensity the more progressive the community. . . The conditions of social progress, as we have traced the law, are association and equality. The general tend- ency of modern development, since the time when we can first discern the gleams of civilization in the darkness which followed the fall of the Western Empire, has been toward political and legal equality. . . This tendency has reached its full expres- sion in the American Republic, where political and legal rights are absolutely equal. . . It is the prevailing tendency, and how soon Europe will be completely republican is only a matter of time, or rather of accident. The United States are, therefore, in this respect, the most advanced of all the great nations in a direction in which all are advancing, and in the United States we see just how much this tendency to personal and political freedom can of itself accomplish. . . It is now . . evident that political equality, co- existent with an increasing tendency to the unequal distribution of weath, must ultimately beget either the despotism of organized tyranny or the worse despotism of anarchy. To turn a republican government into a despotism the basest and most brutal, it is not necessary to formally change its constitution or abandon popular elections. It was centuries after Caesar before the absolute master of the Roman world pretended to rule other than by authority of a Senate that trembled before him. But forms are nothing when substance has gone, and the forms of popular government are those from which the substance of freedom may most easily go. Extremes meet, and a government of universal suffrage and theoretical equality may, under conditions which impel the change, most readily become a despotism. For there despotism advances in the name and with the might of the people. . And when the disparity of condition increases, so does uni- versal suffrage make it easy to seize the source of power, for the greater is the proportion of power in the hands of those who feel no direct interest in the conduct of goverment ; who, tortured by want and embruted by poverty, are ready to sell their votes to the highest bidder or follow the lead of the most blatant demagogue ; or who, made bitter by hardships, may even look upon profligate and tyrannous government with the satisfaction we may imagine the proletarians and slaves of Rome to have felt, as they saw a Cali- gula or Nero raging among the rich patricians. . . Now, this transformation of popular government into despotism of the vilest and most degrading kind, which must inevitably result from the unequal distribution of wealth, is not a thing of the far future.

96 The Taxation of Land Values

It has already begun in the United States, and is rapidly going on under our eyes. . . The type of modern growth is the great city. Here are to be found the greatest wealth and the deepest poverty. And it is here that popular government has most clearly broken down. . . In theory we are intense democrats. . . But is there not growing up among us a class who have all the power without any of the virtues of aristocracy? . . Industry everywhere tends to assume a form in which one is master and many serve. And when one is master and the others serve, the one will control the others, even in such matters as votes. . . There is no mistaking it the very foundations of society are being sapped before our eyes. . . It is shown in greatest force where the inequalities in the distribution of wealth are greatest, and it shows itself as they increase. . . Though we may not speak of it openly, the general faith in republican institutions is, where they have reached their fullest development, narrowing and weakening. It is no longer that confident belief in republicanism as the source of national blessings that it once was. Thoughtful men are beginning to see its dangers, without seeing how to escape them ; are beginning to accept the view of Macaulay and distrust that of Jefferson. And the people at large are becoming used to the growing corruption. The most ominous political sign in the United States to-day is the growth of a sentiment which either doubts the existence of an honest man in public office or looks on him as a fool for not seizing his opportunities. . . Thus in the United States to-day is republican government running the course it must inevitably follow under conditions which cause the unequal distribution of wealth. ' ' Progress and Poverty, book x, ch. iv.

46. "The power to reason correctly on general subjects is not to be learned in schools, nor does it come with special knowl- edge. It results from care in separating, from caution in com- bining, from the habit of asking ourselves the meaning of the words we use, and making sure of one step before building an- other upon it and above all, from loyalty to truth." Henry George's Perplexed Philosopher, p. 9.

47. "Harold Frederic, when the I/ondon correspondent of the New York Times, reported Mr. Gladstone as having said in substance, in one of his campaign speeches, that the older he grew the more he began to conclude that the highly educated classes were in public affairs rather more conspicuously foolish

Appendix 97

than anybody else. Mr. Frederic thought that the Tories had since done much to ' breed a suspicion that therein Gladstone touched the outskirts of a great and solemn truth.' But it need- ed not the action of the Tories to breed that suspicion. In this country as well as in England it is plain to any close observer that the highly educated classes, or to speak with more exactness, the highly tutored classes, when compared with the common people, are in public affairs but little better than fools. The explanation is simple. The common people are philosophers unencumbered with useless knowledge, who look upon public affairs broadly, and moralists who pry beneath the surface of custom and precedent into the heart of public questions. The minds of the tutored classes, on the contrary, are dwarfed by close attention to particulars to the exclusion of generals, and distorted by such false morality as is involved in tutorial notions regarding vested rights."— The Standard, July 27, 1892. f The tendency of tutoring to elevate mere authority above observation and thought is well illustrated by the story of two classes in a famous school. The primary class, being asked if fishes have eyelids, went to the aquarium and observed ; the senior class being asked the same question, went to the library and consulted authorities. If "One may stand on a box and look over the heads of his fellows, but he no better sees the stars. The telescope and microscope reveal depths which to the unassisted vision are closed. Yet not merely do they bring us no nearer to the cause of suns and animalcula, but in looking through them the observer must shut his eyes to what lies about him. . . A man of special learning may be a fool as to common relations." Henry George^s Perplexed Philo- sopher, Introduction.

PART THREE, CHAPTER II, PAGES 22 TO 26

48. For it is ability or inability to satisfy his wants that de- termines whether or not a man is poor. He who has the power to procure what he wants, as he wants it, and in satisfactory quality and quantity, is not poor. No matter how he gets the power, provided he keeps out of the penitentiary, he is accounted rich.

49. This difference is frequently ignored, even by political economists ; but it should be plain to any intelligent mind that no reasoning can be trusted which does not distinguish a difference so radical.

98 The Taxation of Land Values

50. As to the flour and the yeast, there is no doubt of this. And it is equally true though not so obvious of the fire, which but for the art of man would not exist in the oven ; of the water, which but for that would not be at hand ; and of the salt, which without man's art would be in neither proper form nor place. It follows that, either as to form or place, or as to both, all the external objects, except the lot of land, are artificial. The bread itself is of course artificial.

51. It is because man desires bread that he constructs ovens, builds fires in them, grinds flour, digs or evaporates salt, prepares yeast, or carries water to the dough-trough. And going farther back, it is because he desires bread that he raises grain, erects mills, and produces machinery for bread-making. This is plain enough in a community of one like that of Robinson Crusoe. But it is just as true in a community of millions. In the com- munity of one the solitary individual performs all the work neces- sary to produce bread because he wants bread. In the great society individuals divide their work, some doing one part and others other parts; but the motive, still the same, is desire for bread. All the processes of industry to the extent that they are directed to the production of bread, whether they be in the depart- ments of mining, of lumbering, of railroading, of navigation, of engineering, of farming, of storekeeping, of baking, or what not, are steps or stages in bread-making ; and every artificial object produced for the purpose of faciliating bread-making is to that extent unfinished bread. But bread itself, from the time it comes into the possession of the consumer (for it is not complete until the final deliverer has accomplished his work regarding it), is a finished object. The essential difference, then, between the arti- ficial objects that are classified as ' ' product ' ' and those that are classified as ' ' factors ' ' is that the former are finished and the latter are unfinished. 1 Professor Marshall (Marshall's Prin., book it, ch. Hi.} divides artificial objects into "goods of the first order, which satisfy wants directly, such as food, clothing, etc. ; goods of the second order, such as flour mills, which satisfy wants, not directly but indirectly, by contributing toward the production of goods of the first order ' ' ; and ' ' goods of the third order, ' ' under which he arranges "all things that are used for making goods of the second order, such as the machinery for making milling machinery. ' ' He says we might carry the analysis further if nec- essary, and so we might ; but though we dragged it out into an interminable catalogue, every artificial item beyond ' ' goods of the

Appendix 99

first order ' ' would be an unfinished artificial object and for all purposes of economic reasoning nothing else. His own classifica- tion into "consumers' goods" (finished artificial objects), and "producers' goods" (unfinished artificial objects) is complete.

52. It makes no difference what terms are adopted, for they serve only as symbols ; but it is of vital importance that the same terms shall never symbolize things that essentially differ. The technical terms that usage forces upon us in connection with our subject are especially liable to abuse in this respect because they are also loose colloquial words. The term ' ' wealth " is a be- wildering example. It has been used to symbolize as of one class such diverse things as building lots, houses, farm sites, farm im- provements, deeds, mortgages, water power, promissory notes, warehouse receipts and the goods they call for, book accounts, and slaves, thus confusing three or four different kinds of things, in- stead of distinguishing one kind from all others. Made to include building lots and farm sites and water power, the term is a symbol for natural objects ; made to include houses, farm improve- ments, and goods, it is a symbol of artificial objects; by including slaves it symbolizes man ; and by including deeds, promissory notes, warehouse receipts, and book accounts, it symbolizes noth- ing but evidences of legal title as between individual men. When the same term is used to include things so essentially different as "Natural Objects External to Man," "Artificial Objects External to Man," "Man" himself, and indicia of title, it is hopeless to use it in reasoning about the mutual relations of those things.

53. For example : Flour, which is unfinished bread, and therefore unfinished wealth ( ' ' Capital " ) , appears upon analysis to be a compound of grain, a mill site, and a miller. The mill site and the miller are respectively land and labor ; but the grain and the mill are unfinished wealth ( ' ' Capital ' ' ) and may be further analyzed. Passing the mill for a moment to analyze the grain, we find it composed of a farmer, a farm site, and farming im- provements and implements. The farm site, like the mill site, is land ; and the farmer, like the miller, is labor; but the improve- ments and implements, like the mill and the grain, are unfinished wealth Capital, and may be still further analyzed. And so on. If analyzed to the last, every constituent of bread, and every con- stituent of that constituent, would resolve into lyabor and I^and. To follow them step by step would be tedious work and require much special knowledge. It would involve consideration of fac- tories and factory sites, stores and store sites, railroads and railroad

1 00 The Taxation of Land Values

sites, mining and mines, lumbering and forests, rivers, docks, oceans, and ships. But analysis in full detail is not necessary. The conclusion is obvious the moment it is understood.

54. The primary error in most socialistic reasoning on economics consists in ignoring the fact that Capital is but a pro- duct of Ivabor and L,and ; or what in effect is the same thing, in dis- regarding the necessary inference that L/and is the only implement of labor. Many socialists insist that they do not ignore it ; but that, while acknowledging L/and to be the primary implement of L/abor, they see in this only an abstract formula, having at the present stage of civilization no practical importance. Society, they urge, is impossible without Capital ; and he who would live in society must have Capital, or be the slave of those who do have it. Therefore, they argue, Capital is in the social state as indis- pensable as land. Their reasoning hinges upon the mistaken assumption that Capital is an accumulation of the past instead of being a product of the present. As one socialistic author puts it, " Though labor may have originally preceded Capital, yet it is now as absurd to place one before the other as it is to attempt to say whether the hen originated the egg or the egg the hen. ' ' The explanation of the division of labor and trade, one effect of which is overlooked by socialistic philosophies, affords a better opportun- ity than the present for considering this elementary economic error of socialism, and a brief discussion of the subject will be given in that connection. (See Note 86.) But it may be ex- plained here that much of the confusion of thought on this sub- ject among socialists is due to unquestioning acceptance for their economic thinking of analyses of business bookkeeping. For business accounts it is well enough to enter under the head of " Capital" all objects or values that serve as capital in the par- ticular business. But this is not enough for general economic purposes, where all interests are considered. For such purposes, we must know not alone whether business men call certain objects or values Capital in their own business, but also whether there are any fundamental economic differences of which this or that particular business may not need to take account. Now, there can hardly be a more fundamental economic difference than that which we distinguish by the terms ' ' natural ' ' and ' ' artifici- al." These terms distinguish such differences as that of metals in their original state in the earth, from manfactures of metal ; and while the manufacturer may properly account a mineral deposit as part of his capital along with his machinery, the

Appendix pW»\5.J 101

economic investigator who does so is like the school boy who has not yet learned to distinguish between plus and minus. It is from ignoring distinctions between natural capital and artificial capi- tal, that large corporations are considered as capitalists only, and not as landlords. In economic fact they may be enormously greater landlords than capitalists. The report of the Commission of Corporations of the United States shows that the so-called capital of the Steel Corporation (steel trust), for instance, is so largely of ore-deposit holdings that ' ' in the ore is its highest degree of concentration and control."

55. It may seem at first like a great waste of time and space to have gone through this long analysis for no other purpose at last than to demonstrate the self-evident fact that I/and and I/abor are the sole original factors in the production of Wealth. But it will have been no waste if it enables the reader to grasp the fact firmly. Nothing is more obvious, to be sure. Nothing is more readily assented to. Yet by college professor and economic author and socialistic leader and business man alike, this simple truth is cast adrift at the very threshold of economic argument or investigation.

56. There is ample authority among economic writers for this conclusion. Professor Ely has enumerated Nature, L/abor and Capital as the factors of production, but he describes Capital as a combination of Nature and L/abor. Ely's Introduction, part ii, ch. Hi. 1 Say described industry as ' ' nothing more or less than human employment of natural agents." Say's Trea., book i, ch. ii. 1 And though John Stuart Mill and numerous others wrote of L/and, Labor and Capital as the three factors of produc- tion, as did Professor Jevons also, most of them, like Jevons, recognize the fact, though in their reasoning they often fail to profit by it, that Capital is not a primary but a secondary requis- ite. —Jevons 's Pol, EC. , sees. 16, 19. 1 Henry George says: ' ' L/and, lyabor and Capital are the factors in production. The term L/and includes all natural opportunities or forces ; the term Ivabor, all human exertion ; and the term Capital, all wealth used to produce more wealth. . . . Capital is not a necessary factor in production. L/abor exerted upon L/and can produce Wealth without the aid of Capital, and in the necessary genesis of things must so produce Wealth before Capital can exist." Progress and Poverty, book in, ch. i. 1 Also : * ' The complexities of production in the civilized state, in which so great a part is borne by exchange, and so much

102 Tite Taxation of Land Values

labor is bestowed upon materials after they have been separated from the land, though they may to the unthinking disguise, do not alter the fact that all production is still the union of the two factors, I/and and Labor." Id., ch. viii. H By intel- ligent observers no authority is needed. In all the phenom- ena of human life, whether primitive or civilized, the lesson of the Chart stands out in bold relief. Nothing can be produced without L/abor and lyand ; and nothing can be named which under any circumstances enters into productive processes that is not resolvable into either the one or the other. To satisfy all human wants mankind requires nothing but human labor and natural material, and each of them is indispensable.

57. "The term labor includes all human exertion in the production of wealth." Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. ii.

58. "The term L/and necessarily includes, not merely the surface of the earth as distinguished from the water and the air, but the whole material universe outside of man himself, for it is only by having access to land, from which his very body is drawn, that man can come in contact with or use nature." Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. ii.

59. ' ' As commonly used the word ' wealth ' is applied to any- thing having exchange value. But . . Wealth, as alone the term can be used in political economy, consists of natural pro- ducts that have been secured, moved, combined, separated, or in other ways modified by human exertion, so as to fit them for the gratification of human desires." Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. ii.

PART THREE, CHAPTER III, PAGES 26 TO 35

60. If we imagine upon a lonely island a solitary man, with- out capital, without clothing, without adequate shelter, what would be our explanation of his poverty? We could not say that it was caused by a superabundance of goods by ' ' over-produc- tion ' ' ; nor should we be any more likely to attribute it to scarity of money. We should first ask if the land of the island were barren. Upon being assured that it would yield far more than the solitary inhabitant could consume, we should ask if he were physically or mentally incapable of producing the things he re- quired. If told that not only was he quite capable, but that in the years he had been upon the island he had continually improved in industrial knowledge, in inventive acuteness, in man-

Appendix 1 03

ual dexterity, and in muscular power, and yet that he was scarcely if any better able to satisfy his wants than when first cast ashore, we might ask if he were lazy. If informed that he was not lazy, that he worked almost as many hours as ever and quite as hard and far more productively, we should ask if he were the chattel slave of an exacting master. Satisfied that this was not the case, we should then say: "The only explanation left is that in some way that man's opportunities to use the island are restricted the Ivabor of the island and the L/and of the island do not freely meet. ' ' And if we were thereupon advised that a neigh- boring cannibal chief, who claimed the island as his private property, had granted the lone inhabitant permission to live, upon the sole condition that he yield tribute for the land, and that the tribute had a way of advancing as the worker's productive power in- creased, we should understand the cause of his poverty. And we should advise him to find a way at once of throwing off that can- nibal's yoke, and to postpone all secondary questions until their proper settlement could operate for his own benefit instead of the cannibal's.

61. The ownership of the I/and is essentially the ownership of the men who must use it. ' ' I^et the circumstances be what they may the ownership of land will always give the ownership of men to a degree measured by the necessity (real or artificial) for the use of land. . . Place one hundred men upon an island from which there is no escape, and whether you make one of these men the absolute owner of the other ninety-nine, or the absolute owner of the soil of the island, will make no difference either to him or to them." Progress and Poverty, bookvii^ ch. ii.

I^et us imagine a shipwrecked sailor who, after battling with the waves, touches land upon an uninhabited but fertile island. Though hungry and naked and shelterless he soon has food and clothing and a house all of them rude to be sure, but comfortable. How does he get them? By applying his L/abor to the I/and of the island. In a little while he lives as comfortably as an isolated man can. Now let another shipwrecked sailor be washed ashore. As he is about to step out of the water the first man accosts him: ' ' Hello, there ! If you want to come ashore you must agree to be my slave." The second replies: "I can't. I come from the United States where they don't believe in slavery." "Oh, I beg your pardon. I didn't know you came from the United States. I had no intention of wounding your patriotism, you know. But say, they believe in owning land in the United States, don't they? ' '

1 04 The Taxation of Land Values

"Yes." "Very well; you just agree that this island is mine, and you may come ashore a free man." "But how does the island happen to be yours? Did you make it? " " No I didn't make it. " " Have you a title from its maker? " " No, I haven't any title from its maker." "Well, what is your title, anyhow? " " Oh, my title is good enough. I got here first." Of course he got there first. But he didn't mean to, and he wouldn't have done it if he could have helped it. But the newcomer is satisfied and says: "Well, that's a good United States title, so I guess I'll recognize it and come ashore. But remember, I am to be a free man. " " Certainly you are. Come right along up to my cabin. ' ' For a time the two get along well enough together. But on some fine morning the proprietor concludes that he would rather lie abed than scurry around for his breakfast ; and not being in good humor, perhaps, he roughly commands his ' ' brother man ' ' to cook him a bird. "What? " exclaims the brother. "I tell you to go and kill a bird and cook it for my breakfast. " " That sounds big," sneers the second free and equal member of the little community; ' ' but what am I to get for doing this ? " " Oh, " the first replies languidly, ' ' if you kill me a fat bird and cook it nicely, then after I have had my breakfast off the bird you may cook the gizzard for your own breakfast. That's pay enough. The work is easy. " " But I want you to understand that I am not your slave, and I wont do that work for that pay. I'll do as much work for you as you do for me, and no more." "Then, sir," the first comer shouts in virtuous wrath, " I want you to understand that my charity is at an end. I have treated you better than you deserved in the past, and this is your gratitude. Now I don't propose to have any loafers on my property. You will work for the wages I offer or get off my land ! You are perfectly free. Take the wages or leave them. Do the work or let it alone. There is no slavery here. But if you are not satis- fied with my terms, leave my island!" The second man, if accustomed to the usages of some labor unions, would probably go out and to the music of his own violent language about the "greed of capital," destroy as many bows and arrows as he could, so as to paralyze the bird-shooting industry ; and this proceeding he would call a strike for honest wages and the dignity of labor. If he were accustomed to social reform notions of the ' ' goo-goo ' ' variety, he would propose arbitration, and be mildly indignant when told that there was nothing to arbitrate that he had only to accept the other's offer or get off his property. But if a per-

Appendix 1 05

ceptive and red-blooded man, he would notify his comrade that the privilege of owning islands in that latitude had expired.

62. While in the Pennsylvania coal regions several years ago I was told of an incident that illustrates the power of perpetuat- ing poverty which resides in the monopoly of land. The miners were in poverty. Despite the lavish protection bestowed upon them by tariff laws at the solicitation of monopolies which had dictated our tariff policy, the men were afflicted with poverty in many forms. They were poor as to clothing, poor as to shelter, poor as to food, and to be more specific, they were in extreme poverty as to ice. When the summer months came they lacked ice because they could not afford to buy, and they suffered. But owing to the undermining of the ground and the caving in of the surface here and there, there were great holes into which the snow and the rain fell in winter and froze, forming a passable quality of ice. Now it is frequently said that intelligence, industry and thrift will abolish poverty. But these virtues did not succeed among the men of whom I speak. They were intelligent enough to see that this ice if they saved it would abolish their poverty as to ice, and they were industrious enough and thrifty enough not only to be willing to save it, but actually to begin the work. Preparing little caves to preserve the ice in, they went into the holes after a long day's work in the mines, and gathered what, so far as the need of ice was concerned, was to abolish their pov- erty in the ensuing summer. But the owner of that part of the earth a man who had neither made the earth, nor the rain, nor the snow, nor the ice, nor even the hole telegraphed his agent forbidding the removal of ice except upon payment of a certain sum per ton. The miners couldn't afford the terms. They con- trolled the necessary L/abor, and were willing to give it to abolish their poverty ; but the necessary L/and was placed beyond their reach by an owner. In consequence of that, and not from any lack of intelligence, industry or thrift on their own part, their poverty as to ice was perpetuated.

63. It is failure to realize this that accounts for the theory of colleges and Socialists that laborers in the civilized state are dependent upon accumulated capital as well as upon land for opportunities to produce. See ante, Note 54, and post, Note 86.

64. Here are two men at a given point. Bach has an errand to do a mile to the east, and each has one to do a mile to the west. If each goes upon his own errand each will travel a

106 The Taxation of Land Values

mile out and a mile back in one direction and the same in the other, making four miles' travel apiece, or eight miles in all. But if one does both errands to the east and the other does both to the west and they trade results, they will travel but two miles apiece, or four in all. By division of labor they free half their energy and half their time for use at other work, or at study, or at play, as their inclinations dictate.

65. No more than are the effects of a healthful climate. Protectionists who argue that there should be free trade between villages, cities, counties and States in the same nation, but pro-- tection for nations, thus making the effect of trade to de pend up on the invisible political boundary line that separates communities, are like the Negro woman who, when her house, without being physically moved had been politically shifted from North Carolina to Virginia by a change of the boundary line, expressed her satis- faction in the remark that she was very glad of it, because she "allus yearn tail dot dat yah Nof K'line was an a' mighty sickly State," and she was glad she didn't " live dyeah no mo' ! "

66. Men who devoted themselves to specialties, unable to exchange their products for the objects of their desire, which alone would be the motive for their special labor, would abandon specialties and resort to less civilized methods of supplying their wants.

67. Division of labor, whether adopted to take advantage of the different varieties of land, or to secure the benefits of special skill in labor, cannot continue without trade ; and to the degree that trade is impeded, to that degree division of labor will languish. It is only under absolute free trade between all people and in respect of all products that division of labor can flourish. Any interference with it is economically an enslavement of labor in a degree proportioned to the degree of interference.

68. It will be seen from this chart that the people of the two places, by dividing their given expenditure of labor in such man- ner as to utilize the natural advantage peculiar to each place, secure a clear profit of 18. And this is a substantial profit, consisting not merely of figures upon paper, but of real wealth artificial external objects which serve to satisfy human desires.

69. The people of the Mainland have now sent 10 of their corn to the Island, and the people of the Island have paid for it by sending 10 of their sugar to the Mainland. For simplicity the

Appendix 1 07

cost of effecting the trade is omitted. It does not affect the prin- ciple. If the cost were so high that more sugar and corn could be got without division of labor than with, division of labor would be abandoned as unprofitable; if low enough to admit of any profit at all, the trading would go on, unless restrained, precisely as if it involved no cost. It may be well to state, however, that th.e nearer we get to no cost in trading the better are we off. Hence, any tariff on trading, whether domestic or foreign, like railroad or shipping rates for frieght, is prejudicial ; for tariffs add to the cost of trading just as freight rates do. Protection has that for its object. When it does not add enough to the price of a foreign product to prevent importation it fails of its purpose. And though revenue tariffs have no such object they produce the same effect, only in minor degree.

70. If every man were obliged, unassisted by the co-opera- tion of others, to supply his own needs directly by his own labor, few could more than meagerly satisfy even the simplest of those desires which we have in common with lower animals. Though each labored diligently the aggregate of wealth would be exceed- ingly small compared with the necessities of those who wished to consume it, while in variety it would be very limited and in qual- ity of the very poorest kind. But by division of labor, which has been carried to marvelous lengths and is still developing, produc- tive power is so enormously increased that the annual wealth products of the present time, in quantity and quality, in variety, usefulness and beauty, almost appear to be the work of giants and fairies.

71. Mankind as a whole may be likened to a great man, with eyes to see, brain to invent aud direct, nerves for intercommuni- cation, ard various muscles for various actions. As different parts of the bodies of men do different things, each part contributing co-operatively to the general result, so it is with the body economic, whose different parts individual men contribute in different ways to the common good. Trade is to the body economic what digestion is to the physical body. To prohibit it is to deprive the great man of his stomach ; to restrict it is to give him dyspepsia. Says Emerson in the " American Scholar, " an oration delivered at Cambridge in 1837 : ' ' It is one of those fables which out of an unknown antiquity convey an unlocked for wisdom, that the gods in the beginning divided man into men, that he might be more helpful to himself ; just as the hand was divided into fingers, the

108 The Taxation of Land Values

better to answer its ends." Reflection upon the labor-saving power of trade makes it clear that the notion of protectionists that free trade is prejudicial to home industry has no foundation. It would interfere with "home industries" that could be better conducted elsewhere ; but by that very fact it would strengthen the industries that belonged at home. When we decide to buy foreign goods we do not thereby decide to employ foreign labor instead of American labor ; we decide that the American labor shall be employed in making things to trade for what we buy, instead of making the identical things that we buy. And we get a better net result or we wouldn't do it. Free trade and labor- saving machinery, which belong in the same industrial category, increase the aggregate wealth of a country where they flourish. Whether or not they tend to impoverish individuals or classes, depends upon the manner in which the increased wealth is dis- tributed. If they do so tend, the remedy surely does not lie in the direction of obstructing trade and smashing machines so that less wealth may be produced with given labor, but in altering the conditions that promote unjust distribution.

72. The term ' ' production ' ' means not creation but adapta- tion. Man cannot add an atom to the universe of matter ; but he can so modify the condition of matter, both in respect of form and of place, as to adapt it to the satisfaction of human desires. To do this is to produce wealth. "Consumption" is the ultimate object of all production. We produce because we desire to consume. But consumption does not mean destruction. Man has no more power to destroy than to create. His power in consumption, like his power in production, is limited to changing the condition of things. As by production man changes things from natural to artificial conditions in order to satisfy his desires, so by consumption he changes things from artificial to natural conditions in the process of satisfying his desires. Production is the drawing forth of desired things, of Wealth, from the I/and ; consumption is the returning back of those things to the I/and. If ' ' All labor is but the movement of particles of matter from one place to another." Dick's Outlines, p. 25. \ "Production con- sists merely in changing things." Ely's Intro., partii,ch.i; Mill's Prin., book i, ch. i, sec. 2. If " As man creates no new matter but only utilities^ so he destroys no matter, but only utili- ties. Consumption means the destruction of utility." Ely's Intro. , part v, ch. i, p. 268. If Production means ' ' drawing forth. ' ' —Jevons's Primer, sec. 17. f "Man cannot create material things.

Appendix 1 09

. . His efforts and sacrifices result in changing the form or arrangement of matter to adapt it better for the satisfaction of wants." Marshall's Prin., book it, ch. in, sec. 1. V It is sometimes said that traders do not produce ; that while the cabi- net maker produces furniture, the furniture dealer merely sells what is already produced. But there is no scientific foundation for this distinction."' Id. 1f"As his [man's] production of material products is really nothing more than a rearrangement of matter which gives it new utilities, so his consumption of them is nothing more than a disarrangement of matter which diminishes or destroys its utilities."— /tf. 1 "In like manner as by produc- tion is meant the creation not of substance but of utility, so by con- sumption is meant the destruction of utility and not of substance or matter." Say's Trea. , book ii, ch. i. 1 "All that man can do is to reproduce existing materials under another form, which may give them a utility they did not before possess, or merely enlarge one they may have before presented. So that in fact there is a creation not of matter but of utility ; and this I call production of wealth. . . There is no actual production of wealth without a creation or augmentation of utility. " Say's Trea., book i, ch. i.

73. Isn't it significant that while Robinson Crusoe had un- satisfied wants he was never out of a job?

74. Demand for consumption is satisfied not from hoards of accumulated wealth, but from the stream of current production. Broadly speaking there can be no accumulation of wealth in the sense of saving up wealth from generation to generation. Ima<]ine a man satisfying his demand for eggs from the accumulated stores of his ancestors ! Yet eggs do not differ in this respect from other forms of wealth, except that some other forms will keep a little longer, and some not so long. The notion that a hoarding instinct must be aroused before the great and more lasting forms of wealth can be brought forth is a mistake. Houses and locomotives, for example, are built not because of any desire to accumulate wealth, but because we need houses to live in and locomotives to trans- port us and our goods. It is not the saving, but the serving, instinct that induces the production of these things; the same instinct that induces the production of a loaf of bread. 1f Artificial things do not save. No sooner are the processes of production from land complete than the products are on their way back to the land. If man does not return them by means of consumption, then through decay they return themselves. Mankind as a whole

1 1 0 The Taxation of Land Values

lives literally from hand to mouth. What is demanded for con- sumption in the present must be produced by the labor of the present. From current production, and from that alone, can current consumption be satisfied. ' ' Accumulated wealth ' ' is, in fact, not wealth at all in any considerable degree. It is merely titles to wealth yet to be produced, A share of stock in a mining company, for example, is but a certificate that the owner has an undivided property interest in a natural mineral deposit and the machinery constructed to operate a mine there, and that he is legally entitled to a proportion of the wealth produced and to be produced from that deposit. Titles to future wealth may be both legally and morally valid. This is so when they represent past labor or its products loaned in free contract for future labor or its products; for example, a contract for the delivery of goods of any kind to-day to be paid for next week, or next month, or next year, or in ten years, or later. Or they may be legally but not morally valid. This is so when they repre- sent the profits of a franchise (whether paid for in labor or not) to exact tribute from future labor ; for example, a franchise to confiscate a man's labor through ownership of his body, as in slavery, or a franchise to confiscate the products of labor in gen- eral through ownership of land. Or they may be both legally and morally invalid, as when they are obtained by illegal force or fraud from the rightful owner.

75. If it be asked how Personal Servants can draw the food out of the retail stores unless they have money, let the questioner inform himself as to the ways in which business is done. No man, unless he be a notorious cheat or in extraordinary bad luck, needs money in order to obtain goods at retail stores, provided he has or can presently get profitable employment. All he needs is em- plojinent, or an early prospect of employment, and a reputation for honesty. There is therefore no unwarranted assumption in the example, even if we exclude the use of money from consider- ation. See Note 77.

76. Farmers, millers, bakers, ranchers, butchers, fishermen, hunters, makers of food-producing implements, food merchants, railroad men, sailors, draymen, coal miners, metal miners, build- ers, bankers who by exchanging commercial paper facilitate trade, together with clerks, bookkeepers, foremen, journeymen, com- mon laborers, and other hired workmen in all these various branches of food production, find work seeking for them instead

Appendix 1 1 1

of their seeking for work. To specify the labor that would be profitably affected by this demand would involve the cataloguing of all workmen, all business men, and all professional men who either directly or indirectly are connected with food industries, and the naming of every grade of such labor, from the newest apprentice to the largest supervising employer. Would not this be putting an end to ' ' hard times ' ' ? For what is the most striking manifestation of ' ' hard times ' '? Is it not ' ' scarcity of work " ? Is it not that there are more men seeking work than there are jobs to do? Certainly it is. And to say that, is not to limit " hard times" to hired men. The real trouble with the business man when he complains of ' ' hard times ' ' is that peo- ple do not employ him as much as he expects to be employed. Work is scarce with him, just as with those he employs, or as he would phrase it, ' ' business is slack. ' ' I^et there be ten men and but nine jobs, and you have "hard times." The tenth man will be out of work. He may be a good union man who abhors a "scab" and will not take work away from his brother workman. So he hunts for a job which does not exist, until all his savings are gone. Still he will not be a "scab," and he suffers depriv- ation. But after a while hunger gets the better of him, and he takes one of the nine jobs away from another man by underbid- ding. He becomes a "scab." And who can blame him? any one would rather be a " scab ' ' than a corpse. Then the man who has lost his place becomes a * ' scab ' ' too, and turns out some one else by underbidding. And so it goes again and again until wages fall so low that they but just support life. Then the poor house or a charitable institution takes care of the tenth man, who thereafter serves the purpose of a possible labor competitor to prevent a rise in wages. Meanwhile, diminished purchasing pow- er, due to low wages, bears down upon business generally. But let there be ten jobs and but nine men. Conditions would be in- stantly reversed. Instead of a man all the time seeking a job, a job would be all the time seeking a man ; and wages would rise until they equaled the value of the work for which they were paid. And as wages rose, purchasing power would rise, and business in general would flourish. If general demand freely directed general production, there would always be ten jobs for nine men, and no longer only nine jobs for ten men. It could not be otherwise while any wants were unsatisfied.

77. The mechanism of these exchanges should be explained : Personal Servants upon demanding food may pay money for

1 1 2 The Taxation of Land Values

it. The retailers might thereupon pass the money along, and it would ultimately return to Personal Servants. Or the Personal Servants may give notes payable at a future time, which being endorsed over would at last be redeemed by them in services. Or they may give checks on banks, which assumes previous work done by them or the discounting of their notes by the banks. As the world's exchanges are almost wholly adjusted by means of checks, and other commercial paper which is in effect the same as checks, let us illustrate that mode by a series of charts adapted from Jevons. If We will begin with two traders, A and B. They have no money, but every time that one demands anything of the other he must offer in exchange something that the other wants. There must be what is called ' ' a double coincidence ' ' of demand and supply ; each must want what the other has. This is primi- tive barter. It may be represented by the following chart :

-B

In the civilized state, even in its beginnings, primitive barter must be obstructive to trade, and it gives way to the use of cur- rency—some common medium which is taken for goods not be- cause the taker wants it but because he knows that he can read- ily exchange it for the goods that he does want. With cur- rency in use, when A wants anything of B he is not obliged to find something that B wants. All he needs is currrency. Thus currency reduces the friction of trading.

But as the volume of trade augments, demand for currency in- creases ; and because it is scarce, or troublesome or dangerous to transmit, or all together, easier means of exchange are resorted to, and bookkeeping takes the place of currency as currency took the place of primitive barter. At this stage, when A wants any- thing of B, B charges him ; and when B wants anything of A, A charges him. Their mutual accounts being adjusted, the small balance is paid with currency. Thus the demand for currency is greatly lowered by bookkeeping, and the friction of trading is correspondingly reduced.

Now let us bring in two more traders, C and D :

Though all four of these traders keep mutual accounts, the settlement of balances requires more currency than before, and scarcity of currency,

Appendix

113

together with the danger and expense of transmission, evolves an extension of bookkeeping. A common book- keeper, called a ' ' Bank, ' ' is employed, and all need for currency disappears:

Balances are now settled by checks, and all accounts are ad- justed in the central ledger at the bank.

But the introduction of another group of traders, another community, renews the demand for currency, and another bank appears. Thus:

&AMK

And now the two banks are in the same position that A and B were in before any bank came. They keep mutual accounts, but they must have currency to settle their balances. And if we bring in more communities the demand for currency further in- creases. Thus :

Now the four banks are in the same situation that A, B, C and D were in before there were any banks. This evolves a bank of banks a clearing house :

114

The Taxation of Land Values

All necessity for currency once more disappears.

These charts illustrate the principle by which mutual trading is effected. In practice, the need of currency is never wholly done away with, but the tendency is constantly in the direction of doing away with it. And it is said that over ninety per cent, of the trading transactions of the world are adjusted in this manner, and less than ten per cent, by means of currency.

The clearing-house principle extends over the civilized world. In illustration of this, observe the following chart :

NEW YORK

BERllfl

PAWS

Appendix 1 1 5

These five cities are like the five banks. The bookkeeping of each city is conducted by local banks and clearing-houses, and the central bookkeeping by those of the market town of the world, which at present is lyondon. In this way the mobility of labor is in effect enormously increased. Ivabor in every corner of the world is brought into close trading relations with labor everywhere else, so that only war, pestilence, protection and land monopoly interfere with the full freedom of its movement.

78. Personal Servants, on the basis of their employment by Ivuxury-makers demand more food, which keeps Food- makers at work ; Food-makers demand more clothing, which keep8 Clothing-makers at work ; Clothing-makers demand more shelter, which keeps Shelter-makers at work ; Shelter-makers demand more luxuries, which keeps L/uxury-makers at work ; I/uxury- makers demand more services, which keeps Personal Servants at work. And so on indefinitely. If now we add progressive inven- tion, so that every one produces more and more wealth with less and less labor, instead of finding poverty upon the increase, in- stead of being harried by periodical "hard times," we shall find business brisk and every one becoming richer and richer. That is to say, though all work less than before, each obtains better results from others while giving better results in exchange. And should we improve the verisimilitude of the illustration by bring- ing in the fact that all workers in civilized society are specialists in a much more minute degree than the division into Clothing- makers, Food-makers, etc., would imply that every one who works does over and over some one thing in one of these branches, as the making of shoes or the baking of bread, or even only part of a thing, as the cutting of shoe soles, and that while giving out a great deal of his own product he demands in pay a little of every other kind of product the same effect would regularly result. Every man who demands anything for consumption thereby determines the direction of I^abor toward the production not only of that thing, but also of all the artificial materials and implements, from the simplest tool to the most expensive and complex mach- ines that are used in its production. The actual process is much more intricate than that of the charts, but the charts illustrate the principle so that any intelligent person who understands them can apply it to the most complex affairs of industrial life, f ' ' This principle is so simple and obvious that it needs no further illus- tration, yet in its light all the complexities of our subject disap- pear, and we thus reach the same view of the real objects and

1 1 6 The Taxation of Land Values

rewards of labor in the intricacies of modern production that we gained by observing in the first beginnings of society the simpler forms of production and exchange. We see that now, as then, each laborer is endeavoring to obtain by his exertions the satis- faction of his own desires ; we see that although the minute div- ision of labor assigns to each producer the production of but a small part, or perhaps nothing at all, of the particular things he labors to get, yet, in aiding in the production of what other pro- ducers want, he is directing other labor to the production of the things he wants in effect, producing them himself. And thus if he makes jackknives and eats wheat, the wheat is really as much the produce of his labor as if he had grown it for himself and left wheat-growers to make their own jackknives." Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. iv.

79. There is no end to man's wants. IP'The demand for quantity once satisfied, he seeks quality. The very desires that he has in common with the beast become extended, refined, exalted. It is not merely hunger, but taste, that seeks gratification in food ; in clothes, he seeks not merely comfort, but adornment ; the rude shelter becomes a house ; the undiscriminating sexual attraction begins to transmute itself into subtile influences, and the hard and common stock of animal life to blossom and to bloom into shapes of delicate beauty." Progress and Poverty , book ii,ch. iii. f A labor agitator was arguing the labor question with a rich man, the judge of his county, when the judge as a clincher asked : "What do workingmen want, anyway, that they haven't got? " Promptly the agitator replied with the counter-question : ' ' Judge, what have you got that you don't want? "

80. Regarding society as a unit, the operation of the law is no less indisputable in social than in solitary conditions. The demands of society as a whole determine the degree of activity for each department of production, much as Robinson Crusoe's demand for baskets imposed greater activity upon his arms than upon his legs, or as his demand for goats imposed greater activity upon his legs than upon his arms. But it is not necessary to regard society as a unit in order to see that in the social as in the solitary state, labor in production is expended in the direction of demand for consumption. Each individual, in the social as in the solitary state, produces the identical wealth that he demands for consumption. The man, for example, who wants a coat, and to get it makes shoes that he does not want, but with which he hires

Appendix 1 1 7

some one to make him a coat, really produces the coat ; while he who wants shoes, and to get them makes coats which he does not want, but which he trades for shoes, really produces shoes. Similarly, through the whole range of industry, each individual hires other individuals to do what he wants done, and pays for it by doing for others what they want done. The condition is one of reciprocal hiring. Under the common sense legal maxim, qui facit per alium facit per se (what one does by another he does himself), as sound in economics as in jurisprudence, each laborer, by inducing others to make the things that he demands, in order to exchange them for what he makes, really produces what he demands. But for his demands, supplemented by his labor, these things would not be produced. True it is that in general trade goods are usually made in advance of specific demand for them. But it would be superficial reasoning to infer from this that pro- duction determines consumption instead of being determined by it. The collection of commodities in the market is analogous to the collection of water in reservoirs for the accommodation of in- habitants of cities. Water is so collected in advance of specific demand, not to induce the people to consume water, but because, being accustomed to consuming water, they make a steady demand for it. And this demand determines the supply. There are large reservoirs for large cities and small ones for small cities. So with the commercial reservoir. Stores are filled with goods in advance of specific demand, not to induce demand but in obedience to it. There is an approximate constancy to the demand for wealth, upon which labor relies, and in consequence of which wealth is continually in process of completion. Though orders be supplied from existing stock, the stock is at once replenished in accordance with the demand upon it. And this is equivalent to the proposi- tion that demand for consumption determines the direction in which labor will be expended in production. . For it makes no difference in economic principle whether a shoe dealer takes his customer's measure and makes him a pair of shoes, or keeps shoes in stock, and when he sells a pair buys another like them. In either case the shoe dealer is providing shoes pursuant to order. In the one he anticipates the order and has the goods ready when they are called for ; in the other he obliges his customer to wait until the goods can be made. Though production may often seem to precede demand, as when goods are stored months in advance of any possible demand for consumption, and may sometimes pre- cede it actually, as when a new nostrum is placed upon the market,

1 1 8 The Taxation of Land Values

the fact remains that general production in any direction rises and falls with the rise and fall of general demand for consumption in other words, is determined by that demand. And this law regu- lates the supply of wealth not only as to quantity, but also as to quality and variety.

81. "This, then, we may say is the great law which binds society 'service for service.' " Dick's Outlines, p. 9.

82. In the light of this principle how absurd are some of the explanations of hard times. Overproduction! when an infinite variety of wants are unsatisfied which those who are in want are anxious and able to satisfy for one another. Hatters want bread, and bakers want hats, and farmers want both, and they all want machines, and machinists want bread and hats and machines, and so on without end. Yet while men are against their will in par- tial or complete idleness, their wants go unsatisfied ! Since pro- ducers are also consumers, and production is governed by demand for consumption, there can be no real overproduction until demand ceases. The apparent overproduction which we see overproduc- tion relatively to ' ' effective demand ' ' is in fact a congestion of some things due to an abnormal underproduction of other things, the under production being caused by obstruction in the way of L/abor. Scarcity of capital! when makers of capital in all its forms are involuntarily idle. Scarcity of capital, like scarcity of money, is only a loose expression for lack of employment. But why should there be any lack of employment while men have unsatisfied wants which they can reciprocally satisfy? Too much competition ! when competition and freedom are the same. It is not freedom but restraint, not competition but monopoly, that obstructs the action and reaction of demand and supply which we have illustrated in the chart.

83. See page 13 of the text, and Notes 15 and 16 of Appendix.

84. Demand for food is not only demand for all kinds and grades of Food-makers, but also for as many different kinds of land as there are different kinds of labor set at work. So a demand for clothing is not only a demand for Clothing- makers, a demand for shelter is not only one for Shelter- makers, a demand for lyuxuries is not only one for I/uxury- makers, a demand for services is not only one for Personal Servants, but these demands are also demands for appropriate land pasture land for wool, cotton land for cotton, factory land, water fronts, railroad rights of way,

Appendix 1 1 9

store sites, residence sites, office sites, theater sites, and so on to the end of an almost endless catalogue.

85. See pages 16 and 17 of text, and Notes 23 and 24 of Appendix.

86. Persons with socialistic inclinations argue that while it is true that L/abor and lyand are the only things necessary in primi- tive conditions, Capital also is necessary in civilized conditions. (See ante. Note 54.) And some of them want to know, sometimes with something like a sneer, what clerks and mechanics and book- keepers and other specialists in our highly organized industry would do with land even if it were freely open to them. ' ' They don't know how to make food, and they can't eat sand! " I once heard a socialist exclaim. The same notion is widespread among that large class of single tax opponents in church and college whom the late Wm. T. Croasdale described as ' ' people who believe in socialism, but don't believe in putting it into practice. " The idea is best expressed perhaps by a brilliant socialistic writer, Charlotte Perkins Gilman, in the following lines :

1 ' Free land is not enough. In earliest days When man, the baby, from the earth's bare breast Drew for himself his simple sustenance, Then freedom and his effort were enough. The world to which a man is born to-day Is a constructed, human, man-built world. As the first savage needed the free wood, We need the road, the ship, the bridge, the house, The government, society, and church, These are the basis of our life to-day As much necessities to modern man As was the forest to his ancestor. To say to the new born, ' Take here your land ; In primal freedom settle where you will, And work your own salvation in the world ; ' Is but to put the last-come upon earth Back with the dim fore-runners of his race, To climb the race's stairway in one life! Allied society owes to the young The new men come to carry on the world Account for all the past, the deeds, the keys, Full access to the riches of the earth. Why? That these new ones may not be compelled

1 20 The Taxation of Land Values

Each for himself to do our work again ; But reach their manhood even with to-day, And gain to-morrow sooner. To go on, To start from where we are and go ahead That is true progress, true humanity."

In This Our World.

If one man were turned loose alone upon the earth, or shut off from trading with his fellows, it might in great degree be true, as Mrs. Gilman says, that he would be put ' ' back with the dim forerunners of his race, to climb the race's stairway in one life ; ' ' but her criticism does not apply to millions of free men who freely trade. To them the land would be enough. Even though they were denied existing roads and ships and bridges and houses, they would soon make new ones, and starting "from where we are," would "go ahead." For free land means access to all natural materials and forces, and free trade means unob- structed industrial intercourse between laborer and laborer. These are the essential conditions, the only conditions, of all produc- tion— even of the most civilized. The root of the socialistic idea is the thought that we are dependent for modern life upon accumulated capital. This is a mistake. Modern life depends, not upon accum- ulated capital, but upon accumulated knowledge made effective by interchange of labor. A laborer who operates some great machine seems to be dependent upon the owner of his machine for opportunity to work ; but the only people upon whom he really depends are laborers who are competent co-operatively to make such machines, and who have access to both the land from which the materials must be drawn and that upon which they must group themselves while doing the work. When socialists lay stress upon the importance of accumulated capital they are attrib- uting to accumulated capital the power that resides in land and trade ; for to control these is to command the benefits of accumu- lated knowledge. Since the production of a machine precedes its use, the inference is almost irresistible, upon a superficial consid- eration, that opportunities to labor and compensation for labor are governed by the existing supplies of machinery to which labor is allowed access. But this is of a piece with the old notion of classical political economy that opportunities to labor are depend- ent upon the existing supplies of subsistence that are devoted to the maintenance of laborers. The inference is wrong in either form. When we once grasp the essential truth of the law illus- trated in the text, that the production of subsistence, or machinery,

Appendix 1 2 1

or any other unfinished object, that is to say, of Capital, is but a form of general wealth production, and that all forms of wealth production are in obedience to demand, we clearly see that labor is in no respect dependent upon Capital either for employment or compensation. In the social as in the solitary state, L/abor and L/and are the only factors of wealth production. It is not Capital but L/and that supplies materials to L/abor for its subsistence and its machinery. Instead of capitalists supplying laborers with subsistence and machinery, laborers themselves continuously pro- duce subsistence and machinery from the materials that land sup- plies. Capitalists neither employ nor pay laborers ; laborers employ and pay one another, f Keir Hardie, the distinguished L/abor member of the British Parliament, once objected in a public speech that while the Single Tax considers the relation of men to the land it ignores the relation of men to one another. For the the latter reason he considered himself as ' ' more than a Single Taxer. ' ' Mr. Hardie had evidently ignored the fact that the Single Tax includes the principle of free trade ; or else the fact that free trade, supplementing free land, would accomplish with reference to the relations of men to men what he criticized the Single Tax for ignoring. Free trade is that phase of the Single Tax which considers the relation of men to men, even as its other phase con- siders the relation of men to the land. \ Much of the Socialistic misapprehension of the Single Tax is due to confusions of I/and with Capital, as if they were identical. For business purposes this identification is immaterial. Whether the "capital" of a business house consists, for instance, of the money value of land, or of machinery, etc., or of both, makes no difference so far as the mere question of marketable assets is concerned. But when the question is political, the difference is very great. Taxation, for instance, operates upon land values and machine values quite differently ; and rights of ownership have a different moral sanc- tion and different industrial origins and economic effects. For political purposes the difference between land as the natural environment and opportunity for Labor ^ and artificial tools as products of labor must be distinct. \ Most of the so-called ' ' capital ' ' of our time is not Capital in contradistinction to I/and ; it is land the value of which is capitalized. In every effective instance of the power of Capital over L/abor, the capital mentioned consists of a commercial mixture of artificial capital and natural capital of machinery produced by L/abor and land produced by Nature. The commercial mixture is effected by means of evidences

1 22 The Taxation of Land Values

of title, such as railroad stocks which represent tracks, etc., (labor products), and grants of exclusive rights of way (land); and it is the land titles hidden in those stocks that are greatest if the rail- road is at all a capitalistic menace. To insist that Capital (as distin- guished from L/and) is monopolistic because "capital ' ' , the commer- cial mixture of land and labor products, is so, seems very much like asserting that soda water is intoxicating because men may get drunk on whisky and soda, f The object of Socialism and that of the Single Tax is the same abolition of the exploitation of labor. The Single Tax proposal proceeds upon the theory that abolition of land monopoly will abolish exploitation of labor. Socialists insist that abolition of capital monopoly also is necessary. This is conceded by Single Tax advocates, but they consider that abolition of land monopoly makes monopoly of capital impossible. In reply, Socialists point to powerful capitalists who own little land ; to which the Single Taxer responds that their ' ' capital ' ' proves to be nearly all land when you investigate the source of their incomes. Apart, however, from socialistic misapprehensions as to the seat of capitalistic power, Socialism sets up a demand for government by the labor class. If by this is meant hired man class alone, the Single Tax advocate would disagree ; but in so far as Socialism does not make that limitation, the Single Tax advocate agrees. Tf The one solid rock upon which the Single Tax theory rests, more- over, is that no socialistic progress can be secure, however good it may be in itself, unless it is preceded or accompanied by abolition of land monopoly. Control of the land is the corner stone of all power. Because it rests upon land monopoly Capital is formidable ; until land monopoly is abolished, L/abor will be weak. Karl Marx told the whole story in a few words when in his Gotha- platform letter, reprinted in the National Socialist Review (Chicago, May, 1908), he said: "In the society of to-day, the means of labor are monopolized by the landed proprietors. Monopoly of landed property is even the basis of monopoly of capital and by the capitalists." ^f Read " Progress and Poverty," book i, chs. iii, iv, and v. Also read ' ' The Story of My Dicta- torship," chs. v, vi, vii, and viii.

PART THREE, CHAPTER IV, PAGES 35 TO 47

87. " What is paid for labor of any kind is called wages. We are apt to speak of the payments given to the common day laborer only as wages ; and we give finer names to payments made for

Appendix 1 23

some other kinds of service. Thus we speak of the doctor's or the lawyer's fee ; of the judge's salary ; of the teacher's income ; of the merchant's profit; of the banker's interest, and of the professor's emoluments. They are all in reality only payments for labor of different kinds, or for different results of labor, that is, they are all wages."— Dick's Outlines, p. 23. 1 "Wages is what goes to pay for the trouble of labor."— Jevons's Primer, sec. 39. l"His [the manager's] share is called the wages of superintendence, and although usually much larger than the share of a common laborer, it is really wages of the same nature." Id. , sec. 41. V'The common meaning of the word wages is the compensation paid to a hired person for manual labor. But in political economy the word wages has a much wider meaning, and includes all returns for exertion. For, as political economists explain, the three agents or factors in production are land, labor and capital, and that part of the produce which goes to the second of these factors is styled by them wages. . . It is important to keep this in mind. For in the standard economic works this sense of the term wages is recognized with greater or less clear- ness only to be subsequently ignored." Progress and Poverty, book i, ch. ii.

88. Rent ' ' is what is paid for the use of a natural agent, whether land, or beds of minerals, or rivers, or lakes. The rent of a house or factory is, therefore, not all rent in our meaning of the word." Jevons^s Primer, sec. 40. l"The term rent in its economic sense . . differs in meaning from the word rent as commonly used. In some respects this economic meaning is nar- rower than the common meaning ; in other respects it is wider. It is narrower in this : In common speech, we apply the word rent to payments for the use of buildings, machinery, fixtures, etc. , as well as to payments for the use of land or other natural capabilities ; and in speaking of the rent of a house or the rent of a farm, we do not separate the price for the use of the improve- ments from the price for the use of the bare land. But in the economic meaning of rent, payments for the use of any of the products of human exertion are excluded, and of the lumped pay- ments for the use of houses, farms, etc., only that part is rent which constitutes the consideration for the use of the land that part paid for the use of buildings or other improvements being properly interest, as it is a consideration for the use of capital. It is wider in this : In common speech we only speak of rent when owner and user are distinct persons. But in the economic

1 24 The Taxation o Land Valu e s

sense there is also rent where the same person is both owner and user. Where owner and user are thus the same person, whatever part of his income he might obtain by letting the land to another is rent, while the returns for his labor and capital are that part of his income which they would yield him did he hire instead of owning the land. Rent is also expressed in a selling price. When land is purchased, the payment which is made for the ownership, or right to perpetual use, is rent commuted or capitalized. If I buy land for a small price and hold it until I can sell it for a large price, I have become rich, not by wages for my labor or by inter- est upon my capital, but by the increase of rent. Rent, in short, is the share in the wealth produced which the exclusive right to the use of natural capabilities gives to the owner. Wherever land has an exchange value there is rent in the economic meaning of the term. Wherever land having a value is used, either by owner or hirer, there is rent actual ; wherever it is not used, but still has a value, there is rent potential. It is this capacity of yielding rent which gives value to land. Until its ownership will confer some advantage, land has no value." Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. ii.

89. " The primary division of wealth in distribution is dual, not tripartite. Capital is but a form of labor, and its distinction from labor is in reality but a subdivision, just as the division of labor into skilled and unskilled would be. In our examination we have reached the same point as would have been attained had we simply treated capital as a form of labor, and sought the law which divides the produce between rent and wages ; that is to say, between the possessors of the two factors, natural substances and powers, and human exertion which two factors by their union produce all wealth. Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. v. ^ Care must be taken not to confuse the hire of a house, com- monly and legally termed "rent, " with economic Rent. House rent is really Wages ; it is compensation for the labor of house building. But economic Rent is not compensation for anything the owner does ; it is simply differential premiums for the varying advantages of different locations.

90. Ivand of every kind may vary in desirableness from other land of the same kind. Certain farming land, for example, is so fertile that it will yield to a given application of labor two bushels of wheat to every bushel that certain other farming land will yield ; and it is obvious that, other things being equal, farmers

Appendix 1 25

would prefer the more fertile land. But some fertile land lies so far away from market that less fertile land lying nearer is more productive, because it costs less to exchange its products for what their producer demands ; in such cases farmers would prefer the less fertile land. The same principle applies to all kinds of land. Building lots at or near a center of residence or business are pref- erable for most purposes of residence or business to lots equally good in other respects which are far away. Now, the land thajt is preferable is of course most in demand ; and if it be all in use, with demand for it unsatisfied, competition for the preference sets in, and gives value to it. All land cannot be equally desirable. Some excels in fertility. Some is rich with mineral deposits, a species of fertility. On some, towns and cities settle, thereby adding to the productiveness of the labor that uses it, because these sites are thus made centers of co-operation or trade. And yet produc- tion in the civilized state requires that the producer shall have exclusive possession of the land he needs. This necessity inevit- ably gives to some people more desirable land than others have, even though all should have an abundance. Consequently the returns to equal labor are unequal. The man who has land that is more fertile or better located than that of another gets more wealth than the other in return for a given expenditure of labor. If, for example, one with given labor produces 10 bushels of corn from fertile land, equal, say, to $5 worth of any kind of wealth in the market, and the other with the same labor produces 8 bushels of corn, or $4 worth of any kind of wealth in the market, the first receives 2 bushels (or $1) more for his labor than the other receives for his, though each labors with equal effort, skill, and intelligence. Or, if the fertility of the land be the same, but its situation in reference to the market be such that the cost of trans- portation still preserves the relation of $5 to $4, the same inequal- ity of wages results. It is this phenomenon that gives rise to Rent. Rent is the market value of just such differences in the quality of opportunity as are here illustrated. It is a premium for choice land, for preferential locations, for site, for space. This premium is a very different thing from compensation for individual labor. Nor is the difference modified when premium-owners first obtain Wages for work, and with them buy the premium-commanding land. Rent can no more be turned into compensation for individ- ual labor by exchanging labor products for mere legal power to exact it, than a man can be turned into Wealth by exchanging Wealth for him. Whether the fruits of purchase or of conquest or of

1 26 The Taxation of Land Values

fraud, Rent always constitutes that part of Wealth which is de- ducted from current production as premiums for superior oppor- tunities for production. Wages and Rent are both drawn from Wealth, and both go often to the same individual and in the same form of payment, as when a freehold farmer consumes the grain he raises from more fertile land than his neighbors have, or a city freeholder occupies or receives hire from his house and lot ; but Wages flow from Wealth to labor as compensation for production, while Rent flows from Wealth to land-monopolists in premiums for allowing I/abor to produce Wealth from superior locations. Wages are appurtenant to Labor ; Rent is appurtenant to I/and. It is as laborer that the individual takes Wages, but as land- monopolist that he takes Rent.

91. A unit of labor cannot be definitely measured save by the value of some labor product. The day's labor of one may produce less than an hour's labor of another. But for purposes of illustration it is competent to refer to a unit of L/abor force as an abstraction, intending thereby to denote all the Labor of muscle and brain requisite to acquire the necessary knowledge and skill and to produce wealth to a given value from given natural sources.

92. "No land ever pays rent unless in point of fertility or situation it belongs to those superior kinds which exist in less quantity than the demand." Mill's Prin., book ii, ch. xvi, sec. 2. 1 ' ' The produce of labor constitutes the natural recompense or wages of labor. In that original state of things which precedes both the appropriation of land and the accumulation of stock, the whole produce of labor belongs to the laborer." Smith's Wealth of Nations, book i, ch. viii. 1 ' ' Rent or land value does not arise from the productiveness or utility of land. It in no wise represents any help or advantage given to production, but simply the power of securing a part of the results of production. No matter what are its capabilities, land can yield no rent and have no value until some one is willing to give labor or the results of labor for the privilege of using it ; and what any one will thus give, depends not upon the capacity of the land, but upon its capacity as compared with that of land that can be had for noth- ing. I may have very -rich land, but it will yield no rent and have no value so long as there is other land as good to be had without cost. But when this other land is appropriated, and the best land to be had for nothing is inferior, either in fertility, situation or other quality, my land will begin to have a value and

Appendix 1 27

yield rent. And though the productiveness of my land may de- crease, yet if the productiveness of the land to be had without charge decreases iu greater proportion, the rent I can get, and consequently the value of my land, will steadily increase. Rent, in short, is the price of monopoly, arising from the reduction to individual ownership of natural elements which human exertion can neither produce nor increase." Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. ii.

93. "Rent is the effect of a monopoly; though the monopoly is a natural one, which may be regulated, which may even be held as a trust for the community generally, but which cannot be prevented from existing. . . If all the land of the country belonged to one person he could fix the rent at his pleasure.

The effect would be much the same if the land belonged to so few people that they could and did act together as one man and fix the rent by agreement among themselves. . . The only remaining supposition is that of free competition. " Mill's Prin., book ii, ch. xvi, sec. 1. 1 Rent "considered as the price paid for the use of land is naturally a monopoly price. ' ' Smith's Wealth of Nations, book i, ch. xi.

94. The line of separation between the poorest land thus commanding a premium, and the best land for which labor will not pay a premium, was formerly called the "margin of cultiva- tion," probably because the law of rent was not understood with reference to any but agricultural land ; but it may now be better called the "margin of production," since the law of rent applies to all kinds of land, including, of course, the building lots of cities. The premium for land falls not into the fund termed Wages, but into the fund termed Rent. When Rent appears, Wages consists not of the entire product of labor, but of so much of that product as might with the same expenditure of labor force be produced from the best land that commands no premium. The remainder goes to the owners of the land from which it is in fact produced, in proportion to the advantages which their land respectively contributes to its production. This excess is the premium. It is what constitutes Rent as distinguished from Wages. And both the amount of the general fund Rent, and the amount of rent which each land-owner obtains, are deter- mined by the competition of I/abor for superior opportunities. Thus, in the beginnings, all Wealth would be Wages ; but as labor was forced from better to poorer lands, or, what is the same

1 28 The Taxation of Land Values

thing in its principle of operation, as greater capabilities attached to particular lands in consequence of social development, good government, industrial improvement, etc. , Rent would arise, and as a proportion of the gross Wealth-product, would increase as I/abor was forced to poorer land or new capabilities were added to land by society. The law derived from these phenomena is known as Ricardo's law of rent. Henry George formulates it as follows : ' ' The rent of land is determined by the excess of its produce over that which the same application can secure from the least productive land in use." Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. ii. H As will be noticed, the law is the law of Wages as well as the law of Rent. For whatever determines the proportion of Wealth taken as Rent necessarily determines the proportion left as Wages. With reference to that part of this note which reads, "as greater capabilities attached to particular lands in consequence of social development, good government, industrial improvement, etc.," a British student of the subject, A. W. Madsen, has asked this question : ' ' As Labor and Land are the two factors in the produc- tion of Wealth, is it not a mistake to say that these new capabili- ties will be added to land rather than to Labor ? " In explanation of this question, he adds: " If new capabilities were added to all land, including the land at the margin of cultivation, does it fol- low that Rent will rise? It seems that Rent would rise on all land above the margin only if new capabilities were added to that land in varying proportions. ' ' Taking my statement as it appeared in previous editions of this book, and as I retain it here for purposes of correction, I think the criticism may be sound ; for I seem to have mentioned the value of greater capabilities attaching to par- ticular land as added to land in general. I might be understood, therefore, as implying that they would be evenly instead of differ- entially distributed in Rent. The statement should be altered so as to read : "As greater capabilities attached to particular lands in consequence of social development, good government, industrial improvement, etc. , Rent on the particular land so affected would arise or increase ' ' , etc. The concrete illustration is a city. Mr. George summarizes this point ( ' ' Progress and Poverty, ' ' ch. ii of book iv, p. 241) as follows: "To recapitulate: The effect of in- creasing population upon the distribution of wealth is to increase rent, and consequently to diminish the proportion of the produce which goes to capital and labor, in two ways : First, By lowering the margin of cultivation. Second, By bringing out in land special capabilities otherwise latent, and by attaching special capabilities

Appendix 1 29

to particular lands. I am disposed to think that the latter mode, to which little attention has been given by political economists, is really the more important. ' '

95. Though figures are used, these charts are to be under- stood not as mathematical demonstrations , but simply as sugges- tive illustrations.

96. The labor that was forced to the poorest lands would continually bid for the opportunities that the better lands offered, until an equilibrium was reached at the point shown in the pre- vious chart, where the given expenditure of labor is as well com- pensated in one place as in another. If laborer and land-owner be different persons, the laborer receives what is distinguished as Wages, and the land-owner what is distinguished as Rent. If the same person, he receives Wages as laborer and Rent as land- owner.

97. But we must not jump to the conclusion that there is any essential wrong in Rent. Rent is nature's method of measuring the value of the differences in natural opportunity which different laborers, owing to variations in land, are obliged to accept. And, what in practice is more important, it is nature's method of meas- uring the value to each individual of those advantages which con- sist in accumulations of common knowledge, in co-operative effort, in good government, in a word, in the benefits that society as a whole confers as distinguished from those which each individual earns. The question is not one of the rightfulness or the wrong- fulness of Rent. Personal freedom necessitates Rent, for it necessitates the private possession of land, and private possession of land, some locations being more desirable than others, makes Rent inevitable. Nothing short of communism could abolish it. The real question is, What shall society do with Rent? Shall it give it to individuals, or use it for common purposes? 1 " Were there only one man on earth, he would have a right to the use of the whole earth. When there is more than one man on earth, the right to the use of land that any one of them would have, were he alone, is not abrogated ; it is only limited. . . It has become by reason of this limitation, not an absolute right to use any part of the earth, but (1) an absolute right to use any part of the earth as to which his use does not conflict with the equal rights of others (i. e., which no one else wants to use at the same time), and (2) a co-equal right to the use of any part of the earth which he and others may want to use at the same time." A Per-

1 30 The Taxation of Land Values

plexed Philosopher, p. 45. U It is in the adjustment of co-equal rights that Rent occurs.

98. ' ' The effect of increasing population upon the distribution of wealth is to increase rent . . in two ways : First, By lowering the margin of cultivation. Second, By bringing out in land special capabilities otherwise latent, and by attaching special capabilities to particular lands." Progress and Poverty, book iv, chs. ii and Hi. If ' ' When we have inquired what it is that marks off land from those material things which we regard as products of the land, we shall find that the fundamental attribute of land is its extension. The right to use a piece of land gives command over a certain space a certain part of the earth's surface. The area of the earth is fixed ; the geometric relations in which any partic- ular part of it stands to other parts are fixed. Man has no con- trol over them ; they are wholly unaffected by demand ; they have no cost of production ; there is no supply price at which they can be produced. The use of a certain area of the earth's surface is a primary condition of anything that man can do ; it gives him room for his own actions, with the enjoyment of the heat and the light, the air and the rain which nature assigns to that area ; and it determines his distance from, and in a great measure his rela- tions to, other things and other persons. We shall find that it is this property of land, which, though as yet insufficient prominence has been given to it, is the ultimate cause of the distinction which all writers are compelled to make between land and other things. ' ' Marshall* s Pr in., book iv, ch. ii, sec. i.

99. Of course social growth does not go on in this regular way. The charts are merely illustrative ; they are intended to illustrate the universal fact that as any land becomes a center of trade or of other industrial or social relationship its value rises.

100. ' ' Perhaps it may be well to remind the reader, before closing this chapter, of what has been before stated that I am using the word wages not in the sense of a quantity, but in the sense of a proportion. When I say that wages fall as rent rises, I do not mean that the quantity of wealth obtained by laborers as wages is necessarily less, but that the proportion which it bears to the whole produce is necessarily less. The proportion may diminish while the quantity remains the same or increases." Progress and Poverty, book Hi, ch. vi.

101. The condition illustrated in the last chart would be the result of social growth if all land but that which was in full use

Appendix 1 3 1

were common land. The discovery of mines, the development of cities and towns, and the construction of railroads, the irrigation of arid places, improvements in government, all the infinite con- veniences and labor-saving devices that civilization generates, would tend to abolish poverty by increasing the compensation of labor, and making it impossible for any man to be in involuntary idleness, or underpaid, so long as mankind was in want. If de- mand for land increased, Wages would tend to fall as the demand brought lower grades of land into use ; but they would at the same time tend to rise as social growth added new capabilities to the lower grades. And it is altogether probable that, while progress would lower Wages as a proportion of total product, it would in- crease them as an absolute quantity. ^ The British critic quoted in a previous note, Mr. Madsen, suggests with reference to the above clause of this note as it appeared in previous editions and is here reproduced, that "this is a very indefinite conclusion to come to as the result of an economic argument, ' ' because econo- mists ought to be ' ' able to say definitely how wages will be affected by tracing definite causes to their effects and stating pos- itively whether wages will rise or fall." Political economy as a science is one of tendencies. Economists may tell what the gen- eral tendency of given general conditions will be ; but they cannot tell what specific effects will occur, for all the facts are not avail- able. They can predict, for illustration, that if one man be given an absolute monopoly of the planet with power to retain it, he will be supported by the labor of other men ; but they cannot tell what proportion each will give him nor how much he will get. The comparison of proportional with quantitative wages is consid- ered with some fullness by Henry George in ' ' Progress and Pov- erty," book iv, chapter iv. The primary effect of labor-saving improvements is doubtless to delay the need for lower grades of land ; but the secondary effect though the first in point of time, if general and confident expectation of improvement has set in is to hurry the demand, even if not the need, for lower grades of land. It is suggested that if we devoted ourselves as a nation to the growing of wheat, labor-saving devices would enable us to grow the same quantity on less land and therefore give the bene- fit to wages. This is true as a tendency; and it is because it is true as a tendency that, under the influence of the expansiveness of human desires and the consequent intensity of monopolization of land, it is not true as a fact of actual experience. Able to get a larger quantity of wheat with less labor, we continue doing the

1 32 The Taxation of Land Values

same labor, thereby increasing our production of wheat, in order to swap the excess for sealskin coats, or other objects of previous- ly ungratified desires. The effect is a tendency to an increase in the demand for wheat land, and consequently to an increase of Rent rather than of Wages.

102. Here, far away from civilization, is a solitary settler. Getting no benefits from government, he needs no public revenues, and none of the land about him has market value. Another settler comes, and another, until a village appears. Some public revenue is then required. Not much, but some. And the land has a little value, only a little ; perhaps just enough to equal the need for public revenue. The village becomes a town. More revenues are needed, and land values are higher. It becomes a city. The public revenues required are enormous, and so are the land values. *U This criticism has been made : "If the tendency is for wages to fall, under natural conditions, would this not mean that the value of the services of an individual wage- earner would decrease with social progress? " The question results from inattention to the point noted in Note 101 (96 of old edition) as to proportional and quantitative wages, and also to the point regarding speculation in land values. It has been the chief object of the Rent diagrams to illustrate this very thing. With social progress wages tend to fall as a proportion of product. Under natural conditions the value of the services of an individual would therefore fall, as a proportion of product. But as the product is greater, so the indi- vidual's absolute wages are greater. Individually he is richer from less labor ; and socially he should be better off from the common use of increased land values. That would be the natural result. But when land monopoly (an unnatural factor) is intro- duced, giving the increasing values of land to individuals instead of the community, a speculative pressure sets in. I^and is held out of use for higher prices. This diminishes the market supply of land. Thereby its price is increased out of proportion to its greater productiveness. Consequently wages diminish not only as a proportion relatively to product, but also as an absolute quantity. It is not merely social progress that produces the quantitative reduction of wages ; it is social progress under land monopoly. This is the theme of ' ' Progress and Poverty, ' ' and the phenomenon from which the book gets its name.

103. Society, and society alone, causes Rent. Rising with the rise, advancing with the growth, and receding with the de-

Appendix 1 33

cline of society, it measures the earning power of society as a whole as distinguished from that of the individuals. Wages, on the other hand, measure the earning power of the individuals as distinguished from that of society as a whole. We have distin- guished the parts into which Wealth is distributed as Wages and Rent; but it would be correct, indeed it is the same thing, to regard all wealth as earnings, and to distinguish the two kinds as Communal Earnings and Individual Earnings. And how can society be justly supported in any other way than out of its own earnings ? 1 Criticising the theory that ' ' rent is simply payment for public service," my British reviewer, Mr. Madsen, says: "It would seem to me that the sum of the Wages of all the laborers [meaning all workers] is the earning power of the nation as a whole, and that Rent is purely the payment that these individual laborers must make to one another as compensation for the advantageous positions which they occupy in producing wealth." That seems to me to be a true statement well made ; but doesn't it mean precisely what Note 98 of the former edition (the first par- agraph of Note 103 of this edition) means? The critic may have been misled by the term public service, assuming that this term implies that rent is determined by service rendered by the public through government. That would be a mistake. The idea is that Rent is determined by social service, which includes not only governmental or like public service, but also that untraceable com- mon service which every individual renders to the whole, over and above what he renders to himself, when he engages in special- ized production. It is a social or co-operative phenomenon is Rent ; and although the more fertile spots will yield Rent when others do not, this is true only in co-operative (i. e. specialized) industry. Kven then, the proportion of Rent due to exceptional fertility (including mineral deposits, etc., in that term) is prob- ably very slight in comparison with the proportion due to social or co-operative concentrations. To call Rent the wages of society as a whole, in contradistinction to individual Wages, may be a poor figure of speech, but it is at any rate a figure that conforms closely to the fact.

104. "Whatever dispute arouses the passions of men, the conflict is sure to rage, not so much as to the question ' Is it wise? ' as to the question, ' Is it right? ' This tendency of popular discussions to take an ethical form has a cause. It springs from a law of the human mind ; it rests upon a vague and instinctive recognition of what is probably the deepest truth we can grasp.

1 34 The Taxation of Land Values

That alone is wise which is just ; that alone is enduring which is right. In the narrow scale of individual actions and individual life this truth may be often obscured, but in the wider field o'f national life it everywhere stands out. I bow to this arbitrament, and accept this test." Progress and Poverty, book vi, ch. i. The reader who has been deceived into believing that Henry George's proposition is in any respect unjust, will find profit in a perusal of the entire chapter from which the foregoing extract is taken. If As an illustration of the weakness of the opposing position, the argument advanced by one of the most distinguished men of his time may be read to advantage. It will be found in "Land and Its Rent," by Gen. F. A. Walker. Gen. Walker was so naively lucid, that one has only to read his book thoughtfully to realize not only that he was wrong, but that if his is the best answer to George, George must have been right. That Gen. Walker was not strongly logical may be inferred from his contro- versy of 1883 with Henry George, which is reproduced in the Appendix to George's "Social Problems;" that he was strong neither logically nor morally in reference to civic relationships, is evident from the final paragraph of his preface to ' ' I/and and Its Rent," mentioned above. Alluding there to his discussion of Henry George's views in the body of "I/and and Its Rent," Gen. Walker says : ' ' For the spirit in which he discusses the views of a writer who deliberately proposes that government shall confis- cate the entire value of landed property, without compensation to those who, under the express sanction and encouragement of gov- ernment itself, have inherited or bought their estates, the author has no apology to offer. Every honest man will resent such a proposition as an insult. ' ' This point can have no logical or moral force unless it applies to the value not only of land, but of every other kind of property which may at any time be inherited or bought "under the express sanction and encouragement of government;" for Gen. Walker gives no reason for considering landed property especially sacred. It follows, if Gen. Walker thought straight morally and reasoned straight logically, that every honest man would resent as an insult any proposition to confiscate in any way the entire value of any kind of property ' ' without compensation to those who, under the express sanction and encouragement of government itself, have inherited or bought ' ' it. If that position is sound, the sacredness of property is determined not by the moral law but by governmental sanctions irrespective of the moral law. Could any contention be more absurd, either in logic

Appendix 1 35

or in morals? If slavery exists, government must not abolish it without compensating slave owners ! And this, notwithstanding that Abolitionists who have always opposed it, and slaves who have been born or kidnapped into it, and their descendants as long as the compensation debt lasted, would be taxed to pay for the losses of those who have favored and profited by slavery. So long as that compensation was withheld, not only would slave- owners continue to profit, but the slaves must continue to suffer confiscation of their work. Query : Could an individual slave con- fiscate from his master the entire value of himself as a slave, by running away, without exciting the resentment of "every honest man" of the kind for whom General Walker spoke? Observe that the question of whether landed property and slave property are morally on the same level is not involved in General Walker's code of civic morality. The moral question he raises, and the only one, is not whether landed property and slave property are morally the same. He holds that the value of any kind oj property whatever, if inherited or bought ' ' under the express sanction and encour- agement of government, ' ' can not be confiscated morally without compensation to its owners.

105. It is reported from Iowa that a few years ago a workman in that State saw a meteorite fall, and, securing possession of it after much digging, he was offered $105 by a college for his " find." But the owner of the land on which the meteorite fell claimed the money, and the two went to law about it. After an appeal to the highest court of the State, it was finally decided that neither by right of discovery, nor by the right of labor, could the workman have the money, because the title to the meteorite was in the man who owned the land upon which it fell.

106. The text speaks of Rent only as a periodical or continu- ous payment what would be called ' ' ground rent. ' ' But actual or potential Rent may atways be, and frequently is, capitalized for the purpose of selling the right to enjoy it, and it is to selling value that we usually refer in the United States, Canada and Australasia, when dealing in land. I/and which has the power of yielding Rent to its owner will have a selling value, whether it be used or not, and whether Rent is actually derived from it or not. This selling value will be the capitalization of its present or pros- pective power of producing Rent. In fact, much the larger pro- portion of land that has a selling value is wholly or partly unused, producing no Rent at all, or less than it would if fully used. This

1 36 The Taxation of Land Values

condition is expressed in the chart by the blue color. 1 ' ' The capitalized value of land is the actuarial ' discounted ' value of all the net incomes which it is likely to afford, allowance being made on the one hand for all the incidental expenses, including those of collecting the rents, and on the other for its mineral wealth, its capabilities of development for any kind of business, and its advantages, material, social, and aesthetic, for the purposes of residence. "—Marshall's Prin., book vi, ch. ix, sec. 9. "The value of land is commonly expressed as a certain number of times the current money rental, or in other words, a certain ' number of years' purchase' of that rental ; and other things being equal, it will be the higher the more important these direct gratifications are, as well as the greater the chance that they and the money income afforded by the land will rise. ' ' Id. , note. \ ' 'Value . . means not utility, not any quality inhering in the thing itself, but a quality which gives to the possession of a thing the power of ob- taining other things in return for it or for its use. . . Value in this sense the usual sense is purely relative. It exists from and is measured by the power of obtaining things for things by exchang- ing them. . . Utility is necessary to value, for nothing can be valuable unless it has the quality of gratifying some physical or mental desire of man, though it be but a fancy or whim. But utility of itself does not give value. . . If we ask ourselves the reason of . . variations in . . value . . we see that things having some form of utility or desirability, are valuable or not valuable, as they are hard or easy to get. And if we ask further, we may see that with most of the things that have value this diffi- culty or ease of getting them, which determines value, depends on the amount of labor which must be expended in producing them ; i. <?., bringing them into the place, form and condition in which they are desired. . . Value is simply an expression of the labor required for the production of such a thing. But there are some things as to which this is not so clear. I/and is not produced by labor, yet land, irrespective of any improvements that labor has made on it, often has value. . . Yet a little examination will show that such facts are but exemplifications of the general prin- ciple, just as the rise of a balloon and the fall of a stone both exemplify the universal law of gravitation. . . The value of everything produced by labor, from a pound of chalk or a paper of pins to the elaborate structure and appurtenances of a first-class ocean steamer, is resolvable on an analysis into an equivalent of the labor required to produce such a thing in form and place ;

Appendix 1 37

while the value of things not produced by labor, but nevertheless susceptible of ownership, is in the same way resolvable into an equivalent of the labor which the ownership of such a thing enables the owner to obtain or save. ' ' A Perplexed Philosopher, ch.v.

107. The paradise to which the youth of our country have so long been directed in the advice, "Go West, young man, go West," is truthfully described in "Progress and Poverty," book iv, ch. iv, as follows : ' ' The man who sets out from the Kastern seaboard in search of the margin of cultivation, where he may obtain land without paying rent, must, like the man who swam the river to get a drink, pass for long distances through half- tilled farms, and traverse vast areas of virgin soil, before he reaches the point where land can be had free of rent i. e., by homestead entry or pre-emption."

108. Henry Fawcett, in his work on "Political Economy," book ii, ch. iii, observes with reference to improvements in agri- cultural implements which diminish the expense of cultivation, that they do not increase the profits of tne farmer or the wages of his laborers, but that " the landlord will receive in addition to the rent already paid him, all that is saved in the expense of cultiva- tion." This is true not alone of improvements in agriculture, but also of improvements in all other branches of industry.

109. "The cause which limits speculation in commodities, the tendency of increasing price to draw forth additional supples, cannot limit the speculative advance in land values, as land is a fixed quantity, which human agency can neither increase nor diminish ; but there is nevertheless a limit to the price of land, in the minimum required by labor and capital as the condition of engaging in production. If it were possible to continuously reduce wages until zero were reached, it would be possible to continuously increase rent until it swallowed up the whole produce. But as wages cannot be permanently reduced below the point at which laborers will consent to work and reproduce, nor interest below the point at which capital will be devoted to production, there is a limit which restrains the speculative advance of rent. Hence, speculation cannot have the same scope to advance rent in coun- tries where wages and interest are already near the minimum, as in countries where they are considerably above it. Yet that there is in all progressive countries a constant tendency in the specula- tive advance of rent to overpass the limit where production would

1 38 The Taxation of Land Values

cease, is, I think, shown by recurring seasons of industrial paraly- sis."— Progress and Poverty, book iv, ch. iv.

110. As Puck once put it, "The man who makes two blades of grass to grow where but one grew before, must not be surprised when ordered to ' keep off the grass.' "

111. "That a speculative advance in rent or land values in- variably precedes each of these seasons of industrial depression is everywhere clear. That they bear to each other the relation of cause and effect, is obvious to whoever considers the necessary relation between land and labor. " Progress and Poverty, book v, ch. i.

112. What are called "good times" reach a point at which an upward land market sets in . From that point there is a down- ward tendency of wages (or a rise in the cost of living, which is the same thing) in all departments of labor and with all grades of laborers. This tendency continues until the fictitious values of land give way. So long as the tendency is felt only by that class which is hired for wages, it is poverty merely ; when the same tendency is felt by the class of labor that is distinguished as ' ' the business interests of the country," it is "hard times." And "hard times" are periodical because land values, by falling, allow "good times " to set in, and by rising with "good times " bring "hard times" on again. The effect of "hard times" may be overcome, without much, if any, fall in land values, by sufficient increase in productive power to overtake the fictitious value of land.

113. The laborer would receive in Distribution all that he earned and no more than he earned in Production ; and that is the natural law. In social conditions, where industry is subdi- vided and trade is intricate, it is impossible to say arbitrarily what is the equivalent of given labor. Hence, no statute fixing the compensation for labor can really be operative. All that we can say is that labor is worth what men freely contract to give and take for it. But it must be what they freely contract to take as well as what they freely contract to give ; and men are not free to contract for the sale of their labor when labor generally is so divorced from land as to abnormally glut the labor market and make men's sale of their labor for almost anything the buyer offers, the alternative of starvation. Laborers may be as truly enslaved by divorcing Labor from lyand as by driving laborers with a whip.

Appendix 1 39

114. "Such dupes are men to custom, and so prone To rev'rence what is ancient and can plead A course of long observance for its use, That even servitude, the worst of ills, Because delivered down from sire to son Is kept and guarded as a sacred thing. ' '

Cowper.

It is only custom that makes the ownership of land seem rea- sonable. I have frequently had occasion to tell of the necessity under which the city of Cleveland, Ohio, found itself, of paying a land-owner several thousand dollars for the right to swing a draw- bridge over his land. When I described the matter in that way, the story attracted no attention ; it seemed perfectly reasonable to the ordinary lecture audience. But when I described the tran- saction as a payment by the city to a land-owner of thousands of dollars for the privilege of swinging the draw "through that man's air," the audience invariably manifested its appreciation of the absurdity of such an ownership. The idea of owning air was ridiculous ; the idea of owning land was not. Yet who can ex- plain the difference, except as a matter of custom? To the same effect was the question of the Rev. F. Iv. Higgins to a friend. While stationed at Galveston, Texas, Mr. Higgins fell into a dis- cussion with his friend as to the right of government to make land private property. The friend argued that no matter what the abstract right might be, the government had made private property of land, and people had bought and sold upon the strength of the government title, and therefore land titles were morally absolute. "Suppose," said Mr. Higgins, "that the government should vest in a corporation title to the Gulf of Mexico, so that no one could fish there, or sail there, or do any- thing in or upon the waters of the Gulf without permission from the corporation. Would that be right?" "No," answered the friend. "Well, suppose the corporation should then parcel out the Gulf to different parties until some of the people came to own the whole Gulf to the exclusion of everybody else, born or un- born. Could any such title be acquired by these purchasers, or their descendants or assignees, as that the rest of the people if they got the power would not have a moral right to abrogate it?" ' ' Certainly not, ' ' said the friend. ' ' Could private titles to the Gulf possibly become absolute in morals? " " No. " " Then tell me," asked Mr. Higgins, "what difference it would make if all the water were taken off the Gulf and only the bare land left ? ' '

1 40 The Taxation of Land Values

115. The late Thomas G. Shearman, Esq., of New York, author of the famous magazine article on ' ' Who Owns the United States ? ' ' and of the work on public revenues entitled ' ' Natural Taxation," estimated that sixty- five per cent, of the present annual value of the land in the United States would pay all the present expenses of American government Federal, State, county, and municipal. If Mr. Shearman's estimate did not mean that he purposed a tax upon annual values. In harmony with Henry George's views he advocated the taxation of capital values. The effect would be the same ; for capital value is the capitalzation in the market of annual value, and a tax estimated upon capital values would be paid out of or constitute a deduction from annual values. If, for illustration, a lot of land were yielding, or with proper use would yield, $100 in annual ground rent, it would command a capital value of about $2,000 (disturbing influences ignored for simplicity of calculation) in a land market where com- mercial interest was five per cent. To tax this capital value two per cent, would reduce the net annual ground rent from $100 to $60, for the annual tax would be $40 and would have to be paid out of the income. This would reduce the capital value from $2,000 ("twenty years' purchase" of a net annual ground rent of $100) to $1,200 ("twenty years' purchase" of a net annual ground rent of $60); and inasmuch as the next year's tax at two per cent, on the $1,200 of capital value would not yield $40 to the public treasury, but only $24, it has been objected that a baffling problem arises. This, however, is a mistake. Although the old rate would not on the lower capital value raise the old revenue, a higJier rate would, and without making any difference to the tax payer. For instance : A tax of 3>£ per cent, on the lower capitalization of $1,200 in the above illustration would yield $40 to the public and leave $60 to the tax payer ; and that rate would produce the same result every year so long as no alteration in the annual ground rent value occurred and commercial interest remained at five per cent. It has been estimated that a tax of 45 per cent, on capital value would take for public use continually enough of annual ground rent value to leave to the tax payer margin sufficient only to pay fairly for land management, and to leave no sufficient basis for injurious specu- lation in land. Take, for illustration, the previous example of a lot of land with an annual ground rent of $100. If it were certain that this income must bear a tax calculated at 45 per cent, upon its capital value in a market where commercial interest rules at

Appendix 141

five per cent., the selling value would be about $200; for that value, after payment of 45 per cent, taxes calculated upon it, thus taking $90 out of the $100, would leave $10, which would be the income that investors would probably expect for assuming the risks and managing the affairs of such an investment. None of these figure are offered as precise, except for purposes of simple illustrative calculation, but they are not far from what may be reasonably regarded as approximate. 1 Mr. Alex. W. Johnston, an Australian writer on economics (author of ' ' L/aw and liberty, ' ' published by Angus and Robertson, Sydney, New South Wales) objects to any taxation upon the capital value of land. He argues that, whereas "the state has a perfect moral right to appropriate rent for revenue ' ' it has no ' ' moral right to impose a tax on the capital value of land because that is an immoral method," being " artificial, arbitrary and variable ' ' and not based upon principle 4 ' only a partial and half-hearted application of a principle which seeks justice for the people. ' ' The answer is that land is now recognized as private property, that this makes annual ground rents private incomes, that these are on sale in the market at capitalized values, and that wherever such conditions obtain the wisest way of beginning to get those incomes for public use is by taxing capital values. This would not take all that belongs to the public, but the rest would be, as Henry George wrote, only a matter of ' ' keeping on. ' ' And shall we refuse to take less of what belongs to us, until we can take all? Mr. Johnston quotes Abraham I/incoln as saying that ' ' nothing is settled until it is settled right. ' ' Sound doctrine that ; but Mr. Johnston makes strange use of it when he says that Lincoln ' ' might have added : What is less than right is all wrong. ' ' This ignores the law of progress, which may be rendered as "one blessed thing after another ' ' blessed if in the right direction and the reverse if in the wrong direction. Before anything now wrong can be settled right, we must begin to settle it right. In countries where the land market is a ground-rent market, ground-rent might be appro- priated for public use directly, either by taxation or upon some plan of public ownership and leasing of land. But in countries where the land market is a capital- value market, the United States or Canada for instance, any attempt to begin getting ground rent otherwise than by taxing capital values would be like trying to split logs with the thick end of the wedge. 1 Whether the Single Tax ever should or would pass from a tax estimated on capital values to one estimated on annual ground rents, is a ques-

1 42 The Taxation of Land Values

tion for the future. The time to determine this will be when the people have so clearly recognized the common right to land as to be in a frame of mind to deal intelligently with the best method of securing it. 1 The ' ' Single Tax L/imited ' ' has made consider- able practical progress since the text of this book was originally written, seventeen years ago. A large number of municipalities in New Zealand get all local revenues from land value taxation, and this is true also of a large number in Australia. In Canada, too, the method is in full local operation in several cities, notably Vancouver. England has made advances toward it, and so has Germany, while Norway and Denmark are giving it serious con- sideration, as are some of the States of the American Union. The fullest account of these advances of which I know in book form may be found in the late Max Hirsch's " I/and- Value Taxation in Practice," an Australian book, obtainable at "The Single Tax" office, Melbourne, Victoria. Owing to the author's untimely death the record ends before the greatest advances were made. Full accounts are to be found in the files of The Public, a weekly review, published at Chicago, Illinois, U. S. A., since April 1, 1898. In producing prosperous conditions the ' ' Single Tax Ivim- ited ' ' wherever introduced has been manifest. But fears have arisen that reaction may set in because the land value taxes are not high enough to keep pace with increasing land values. Any such reaction would be in harmony with the doctrines of ' ' Prog- ress and Poverty." These teach that improvements in govern- ment tend to increase land values ; and inasmuch as land value taxation, in lieu of taxes on industry, is an improvement in govern- ment— an improvement of the highest order according to "Progress and Poverty ' ' it must be expected that land value taxation will tend to increase land values. If, then, the land value tax is not increased commensurately, speculation in land will tend to revive. All this was anticipated by Henry George when he wrote as follows in Chapter ii of Book viiiof " Progress and Poverty ": ". . . it will not be enough merely to place all taxes upon the value of land. It will be necessary, where rent exceeds the present gov- ernmental revenues, commensurately to increase the amount de- manded in taxation, and to continue this increase as society pro- gresses and rent advances. But this is so natural and easy a matter, that it may be considered as involved, or at least under- stood, in the proposition to put all taxes on the value of land. That is the first step, upon which the practical struggle must be made. When the hare is once caught and killed, cooking him

Appendix 1 43

will follow as a matter of course. When the common right to land is so far appreciated that all taxes are abolished save those which fall upon rent, there is no danger of much more than is necessary to induce them to collect the public revenues, being left to individual land holders. ' ' If The objection that upon the first applications of the "Single Tax I/united," land owners begin after awhile to reap their old advantages, is no argument against the "Single Tax Unlimited." The former is only in the way of a beginning. Such criticisms of it are like those of the little boy who said to his father as he saw him going with a shovel toward the barn : ' ' Pa, what are you going to do? " ' ' Going a- fishing, ' ' said the father. "May I go with you?" "Yes, I guess so." And the little chap trudged along, asking questions as he went. ' ' Pa, can you catch fish with a shovel ? " " Yes, ' ' said his father. ' ' Pa, what kind of fish can you catch with a shovel? " " Pa, how do you catch fish with a shovel ? ' ' and so on and on until they fetched up at the back of the barn, where the father began to dig. Thereupon the questioning was renewed. "Why, pa, you don't catch fish here do you?" "We begin to, my son," was the answer. ' ' But, pa, I thought you caught fish in the creek. ' ' ' 'We do, but we ain't at the creek yet." There was silence until the boy saw his father putting angle worms into a tin cup. He was thoughtful a moment, childishly thoughtful, and then he broke out : ' ' Why, pa, them ain't fish, is they ? " ^ Some helpful inves- tigations into the sufficiency of land value taxation have been made in recent years. Among the publications reporting these are the Blue Book of the British government, the periodical reports of the Tax Department of New York City, and data of taxation in Oregon counties procured under the direction of Wm. S. U'Ren of Oregon City, Oregon. The Rhode Island Tax Reform Association of Providence published a pamphlet in 1911, prepared by John Z. White of Illinois, which gives the names and taxes of every taxpayer of 1910 in Woonsocket, R. I. , and shows how much each would have paid under the ' ' Single Tax I/imited. ' ' Another useful publication in this connection is Benjamin C. Marsh's "Taxation of I/and Values in American Cities, the Next Step in Exterminating Poverty, ' ' which is published by the author (320 Broadway, New York City); and a convenient hand book for speakers and writers as well as students is " The A. B. C. of the I/and Question," prepared by James Dundas White, 1^1^. D., M. P. , and published by the L<and Values Organization of London (20 Tothill St. and 376 Strand).

1 44 The Taxation of Land Values

116. This idea of the concealed picture was graphically illus- trated with a story by James G. Maguire, at that time a judge of the Superior Court of San Francisco and afterward a Member of Congress from California, in a speech at the Academy of Music, New York City, in 1887. In substance he said :

"I was one day walking along Kearney street, San Francisco, when I noticed a crowd around the show window of a store, look- ing at something inside. I took a glance myself, and saw only a very poor picture of a very uninteresting landscape. But as I was turning away my eye caught the words underneath the picture, ' Do you see the cat? ' I looked again and more closely, but saw no cat in the picture. Then I spoke to the crowd :

" ' Gentlemen,' I said, ' I see no cat in that picture. Is there a cat there ? '

' ' Some one in the crowd replied :

1 ' Naw, there ain't no cat there. Here's a crank who says he sees the cat, but nobody else can see it.'

' ' Then the crank spoke up :

" ' I tell you there is a cat there, too. It's all cat. What you fellows take for a landscape is just nothing more than the out- lines of a cat. And you needn't call a man a crank either, because he can see more with his eyes than you can."

"Well," the Judge continued, " I looked very closely at the picture and then I said to the man they called a crank :

" 'Really, sir, I cannot make out a cat. I can see nothing but a poor picture of a landscape.'

" 'Why, Judge,' he exclaimed, 'just look at that bird in the air. That's the cat's ear.'

" I looked, but was obliged to say :

" ' I am sorry to be so stupid, but I can't make a cat's ear of that bird. It is a poor bird, but not a cat's ear.'

" 'Well, then,' the crank urged, 'look at that twig twirled around in a circle. That's the cat's eye.'

" But I couldn't make an eye of it.

" 'Oh, then,' said the the crank a little impatiently, 'look at those sprouts at the foot of the tree, and the grass. They make the cat's claws.'

"After a rather deliberate examination, I reported that they did look a little like a claw, but I couldn't connect them with a cat.

" Once more the crank came back at me. 'Don't you see

Appendix 1 45

that limb off there? and that other limb under it? and that white space between? Well, that white space is the cat's tail.'

' ' I looked again and was just on the point of replying that there was no cat there so far as I could see, when suddenly the whole cat burst upon me. There it was sure enough, just as the crank had said ; and the only reason that the rest of us couldn't see it was that we hadn't got the right point of view. But now that I saw it I could see nothing else in the picture. The land- scape had disappeared and a cat had taken its place. And do you know, I was never afterward able, upon looking at that picture, to see anything in it but the cat. ' '

From this story as told by Judge Maguire has come the slang of the Single Tax agitation. To ' ' see the cat " is to understand the Single Tax.

PART THREE, CHAPTER V, PAGES 47 AND 48

117. "Progress and Poverty," book v, ch. ii, page 293.

118. "Our primary social adjustment is a denial of justice. In allowing one man to own the land on which and from which other men must live, we have made them his bondsmen in a degree which increases as material progress goes on. This is the subtile alchemy that in ways they do not realize is extracting from the masses in every civilized country the fruits of their weary toil ; that is instituting a harder and more hopeless slavery in place of that which has been destroyed ; that is bringing political despot- ism out of political freedom, and must soon transmute democratic institutions into anarchy. It is this that turns the blessings of material progress into a curse. It is this that crowds human beings into noisome cellars and squalid tenement houses; that fills prisons and brothels; that goads men with want and con- sumes them with greed ; that robs women of the grace and beauty of perfect womanhood ; that takes from little children the joy and innocence of life's morning. Civilization so based cannot con- tinue. The eternal laws of the universe forbid it. Ruins of dead empires testify, and the witness that is in every soul answers, that it cannot be. It is something grander than Benevolence, something more august than Charity it is Justice herself that demands of us to right this wrong. Justice that will not be denied ; that cannot be put off Justice that with the scales carries the sword." Progress and Poverty, book x, ch. v.

THIS BOOK IS DUE ON THE LAST DATE STAMPED BELOW

AN INITIAL FINE OF 25 CENTS

WILL BE ASSESSED FOR FAILURE TO RETURN THIS BOOK ON THE DATE DUE. THE PENALTY WILL INCREASE TO SO CENTS ON THE FOURTH DAY AND TO $1.OO ON THE SEVENTH DAY OVERDUE.

MAR 24 1933 29 IS35

LD 21-50m-l,'33

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA LIBRARY

t