MR TOR one 6 on ap stn team agent agus fesse \ NS SN SS WS \ WY AN XMS ISX \\ QRS AWN AS RG AACS WS NX . AG RG \\ MQ S AA WS i thea SY SY WS AY . AX AN AG N SAS AS S > \ \ NX SQA SS SS AC AS WAV NS : War a 4-4 Received__ MAY 16,, 1941 Re ae Accession No. =! eS? . Nr 9 wl R TT; fad Given By ae se aoe a) iockefeller Founcation Place, ew York’ City @ €200000 TOEO ODO WA IOHM/18WW , i : 7 a4 1 | Works by WILLIAM JAMES, M.D., Ph. et Litt.D., LL.D.; Correspondent of the Institute of France; Professor of Philosophy at Harvard University. The Principles of Psychology. 2vols. 8vo. $4.80, net. New York: Henry Holt & Co. 1890. Psychology: Briefer Course. 12mo. $1.60, zet. New York: Henry Holt & Co. 1892. The Will to Believe, and Other Essays in Popular Philosophy. 12mo0. $2.00. New York: Longmans, Green & Co. 1897. Is Life Worth Living? 18mo. sc cents, wet. Philadel phia: S. B. Weston, 1305 Arch Streer. 1896. Human Immortality: Two Supposed Objections to the Doctrine. 16mo. $1.00. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin & Co. 1808. Talks to Teachers on Psychology: and to Students on Some of Life’s Ideals. 12mo. $1.50, met. New York: Henry Holt & Co. 1899. The Literary Remains of Henry James, Edited, with an introduction, by Witt1am JAmeEs. With Portrait. Crown 8vo. $2.00. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin & Co. 1885. The Foundations of Ethics. By Joun Epwarp Maupe, Edited by Wittiam JAMeEs. 12mo. $1.50. New York: Henry Hot & Co. 1887. x ie — AMERICAN SCIENCE SERIES--ADVANCED COURSE EE sPRINCIPLES OF mee bi OlOG Y BY WILLIAM JAMES PROFESSOR OF PSYCHOLOGY IN HARVARD UNIVERSITY IN TWO VOLUMES VOL. fF NEW YORK HENRY HOLT AND COMPANY 1910 Copyright, 1899 BY HENRY HOLT & CO. CAMELOT PRESS, PRINTERS, NEW YORE TO MY DEAR FRIEND rs FRANCOIS PILGLON, AS A TOKEN OF AFFECTION, AND AN ACKNOWLEDGMENT OF WHAT I OWE TO THE CRITIQUE PHILOSOPHIQUE. PRHEFACEH. THE treatise which follows has in the main grown up in connection with the author’s class-room instruction in Psychology, although it is true that some of the chapters are more ‘metaphysical,’ and others fuller of detail, than is suitable for students who are going over the subject for the first time. The consequence of this is that, in spite of the exclusion of the important subjects of pleasure and pain, and moral and esthetic feelings and judgments, the work has grown to a length which no one can regret more than the writer himself. The man must indeed be sanguine who, in this crowded age, can hope to have many readers for fourteen hundred continuous pages from his pen. But wer Vieles bringt wird Manchem etwas bringen ; and, by judi- ciously skipping according to their several needs, I am sure that many sorts of readers, even those who are just begin- ning the study of the subject, will find my book of use. Since the beginners are most in need of guidance, I sug- gest for their behoof that they omit altogether on a first reading chapters 6, 7, 8, 10 (from page 330 to page 371), 12, 13, 15, 17, 20, 21, and 28. The better to awaken the neophyte’s interest, it is possible that the wise order would be to pass directly from chapter 4 to chapters 25, 24, 25, and 26, and thence to return to the first volume again. Chapter 20, on Space-perception, is a terrible thing, which, unless written with all that detail, could not be fairly treated at all. An abridgment of it, called ‘ The Spatial Quale, which appeared in the Journal of Speculative Philosophy, vol. xu. p. 64, may be found by some per- sons a useful substitute for the entire chapter. I have kept close to the point of view of natural science throughout the book. Kvery natural science assumes cer- Mf vi PREFACE. tain data uncritically, and declines to challenge the ele- ments between which its own ‘laws’ obtain, and from which its own deductions are carried on. Psychology, the science of finite individual minds, assumes as its data (1) thoughts and feelings, and (2) a physical world in time and space with which they coexist and which (3) they know. Of course these data themselves are discussable ; but the dis- cussion of them (as of other elements) is called meta- physics and falls outside the province of this book. This book, assuming that thoughts and feelings exist and are vehicles of knowledge, thereupon contends that psychology when she has ascertained the empirical correlation of the various sorts of thought or feeling with definite conditions of the brain, can go no farther—can go no farther, that is, as a natural science. If she goes farther she becomes metaphysical. All attempts to explain our phenomenally given thoughts as products of deeper-lying entities (whether the latter be named ‘Soul,’ ‘Transcendental Ego,’ ‘Ideas,’ or ‘ Elementary Units of Consciousness’) are metaphysical. This book consequently rejects both the associationist and the spiritualist theories; and in this strictly positivistic point of view consists the only feature of it for which I feel tempted to claim originality. Of course this point of view is anything but ultimate. Men must keep thinking; and the data assumed by psychology, just like those assumed by physics and the other natural sciences, must some time be overhauled. The effort to overhaul them clearly and thoroughly is metaphysics ; but metaphysics can only perform her task well when dis- tinctly conscious of its great extent. Metaphysics fragmen- tary, irresponsible, and half-awake, and unconscious that she is metaphysical, spoils two good things when she in- jects herself into a natural science. And it seems to me that the theories both of a spiritual agent and of associated ‘ideas’ are, as they figure in the psychology-books, just such metaphysics as this. Even if their results be true, it would be as well to keep them, as thus presented, out of psychology as itis to keep the results of idealism out of physics. I have therefore treated our passing thoughts as inte- PREFACE. Vil gers, and regarded the mere laws of their coexistence with brain-states as the ultimate laws for our science. The reader will in vain seek for any closed system in the book. It is mainly a mass of descriptive details, running out into queries which only a metaphysics alive to the weight of her task can hope successfully to deal with. That will perhaps be centuries hence; and meanwhile the best mark of health that a science can show is this unfinished-seeming front. The completion of the book has been so slow that several chapters have been published successively in Mind, the Journal of Speculative Philosophy, the Popular Science Monthly, and Scribner’s Magazine. Acknowledgment is made in the proper places. The bibliography, I regret to say, is quite unsystem- atic. I have habitually given my authority for special experimental facts ; but beyond that I have aimed mainly to cite books that would probably be actually used by the ordinary American college-student in his collateral reading. The bibliography in W. Volkmann von Volkmar’s Lehrbuch der Psychologie (1875) is so complete, up to its date, that there is no need of an inferior duplicate. And for more recent references, Sully’s Outlines, Dewey’s Psy- chology, and Baldwin’s Handbook of Psychology may be advantageously used. Finally, where one owes to so many, it seems absurd to single out particular creditors; yet I cannot resist the temptation at the end of my first literary venture to record my gratitude for the inspiration I have got from the writ- ings of J.S. Mill, Lotze, Renouvier, Hodgson, and Wundt, and from the intellectual companionship (to name only five names) of Chauncey Wright and Charles Peirce in old times, and more recently of Stanley Hall, James Putnam, and Josiah Royce. HARVARD University, August 1890. CONTENTS. CHAPTER I. PAGE THE SCOPE OF PSYCHOLOGY, . ‘ in ie: Mental Manifestations depend on Cerebral Contlitions: ie Pursuit of ends and choice are the marks of Mind’s presence, 6. CHAPTER II. THE FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN, . : : f : 4 Ae Reflex, semi-reflex, and voluntary acts, 12. The Frog’s nerve- centres, 14. General notion of the hemispheres, 20. Their Education—the Meynert scheme, 24. The phrenological con- trasted with the physiological conception, 27. The localization of function in the hemispheres, 30. The motor zone, 31. Motor Aphasia, 37. The sight-centre, 41. Mental blindness, 48. The hearing-centre, 52. Sensory Aphasia, 54. Centres for smell and taste, 57. The touch-centre, 58. Man’s Consciousness limited to the hemispheres, 65. The restitution of function, 67. Final correction of the Meynert scheme, 72. Conclusions, 78. CHAPTER III. On SomE GENERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY, er The summation of Stimuli, 82. Reaction-time, 85. Cerebral blood-supply, 97. Cerebral Thermometry, 99. Phosphorus and Thought, 101. CHAPTER IV. HABIT, . ; P ; . ; 2 ; : : . 104 Due to plasticity of neural matter, 105. Produces ease of action, 112. Diminishes attention, 115. Concatenated perform- ances, 116. Ethical implications and pedagogic maxims, 120. CHAPTER V. THE AUTOMATON-THEORY, . ; . 128 The theory described, 128. See Fa it; 133, Redan against it, 138. / 751 i 1x x CONTENTS. CHAPTER VI. PAGE THE MIND-STUFF THEORY, . : : ‘ - : . 145 Evolutionary Psychology demands a Mind-dust, 146. Some alleged proofs that it exists, 150. Refutation of these proofs, 154. Self-compounding of mental facts is inadmissible, 158. Can states of mind be unconscious? 162. Refutation of alleged proofs of unconscious thought, 164. Difficulty of stating the connection between mind and brain, 176. ‘The Soul’ is logically the least objectionable bypothesis, 180. Conclusion, 182. CHAPTER VII. THE METHODS AND SNARES OF PSYCHOLOGY, . ‘ . 183 Psychology is a natural Science, 188. Introspection, 185. Experiment, 192. Sources of error, 194. The ‘ Psychologist’s fallacy,’ 196. CHAPTER VIII. THE RELATIONS OF MINDS TO OTHER THINGS, . ; . 199 Time relations: lapses of Consciousness—Locke v. Descartes, 200. The ‘unconsciousness’ of hysterics not genuine, 202. Minds may split into dissociated parts 206. Space-relations ; the Seat of the Soul, 214. Cognitive relations, 216. The Psychol- ogist’s point of view, 218. Two kinds of knowledge, acquaint- ance and knowledge about, 221. CHAPTER IX. THE STREAM OF THOUGHT, . 3 F : , P . 224 Consciousness tends to the personal form, 225. It is in con- stant change, 229. It is sensibly continuous, 237. ‘Substantive’ and ‘transitive’ parts of Consciousness, 243. Feelings of rela- tion, 245. Feelings of tendency, 249. The ‘fringe’ of the object, 258. The feeling of rational sequence, 261. Thought possible in any kind of mental materia, 265. Thought and lan- guage, 267. Consciousness is cognitive, 271. he word Object, 275. Every cognition is due to one integral pulse of thought, 276. Diagrams of Thought’s stream, 279. Thought is always selective, 284. CHAPTER X. THE CONSCIOUSNESS OF SELF, . : 3 ; ; . 291 The Empirical Self or Me, 291. Its constituents, 292. The material self, 292. The Social Self, 293. The Spiritual Self, 296. Difficulty of apprehending Thought as a purely spiritual activity, CONTENTS. x1 PAGE 299. Emotions of Self, 305. Rivalry and conflict of one’s different selves, 309. Their hierarchy, 318. What Self we love in ‘ Self- love,’ 317. The Pure Ego, 329. The verifiable ground of the sense of personal identity, 332. The passing Thought is the only Thinker which Psychology requires, 338. Theories of Self-con- sciousness: 1) The theory of the Soul, 342. 2) The Associationist theory, 350. 3) The Transcendentalist theory, 360. The muta- tions of the Self, 373. Insane delusions, 375. Alternating selves, 379. Mediumships or possessions, 398. Summary, 400. CHAPTER XI. ATTENTION, ; d ; , : : : . 402 Its neglect by English psychologists, 402. Description of it, 404. To how many things can we attend at once? 405. Wundt’s experiments on displacement of date of impressions simultaneously attended to, 410. Personal equation, 413. The varieties of attention, 416. Passive attention, 418. Voluntary attention, 420. Attention’s effects on sensation, 425 ;—on discrimination, 426 ;— on recollection, 427 ;—on reaction-time, 427. The neural pro- cess in attention: 1) Accommodation of sense-organ, 434. 2) Preperception, 438. Is voluntary attention a resultant or a force? 447. The effort to attend can be conceived as a resultant, 450. Conclusion, 458. Acquired Inattention, 455. CHAPTER XII. Wanonprrem .- ~f) 2.) |. ret: . 459 The sense of sameness, 459. Conception defined, 461. Con- ceptions are unchangeable, 464. Abstract ideas, 468. Universals, 473. The conception ‘of the same’ is not the ‘same state’ of mind, 480. CHAPTER XIII. DISCRIMINATION AND COMPARISON, . : . : . 483 Locke on discrimination, 483. Martineau ditto, 484. Simul- taneous sensatious originally fuse into one object, 488. The principle of mediate comparison, 489. Not all differences are differences of composition, 490. The conditions of discrimina- tion, 494. Thesensation of difference, 495. The transcendental- ist theory of the perception of differences uncalled for, 498. The process of analysis, 502. The process of abstraction, 505. The improvement of discrimination by practice, 508. Its two causes, 510. Practical interests limit our discrimination, 515. Reaction- time after discrimination, 528. The perception of likeness, 528. The magnitude of differences, 530. The measurement of dis- xii CONTENTS. PAGE criminative sensibility : Weber’s law, 5383. Fechner’s interpreta- tion of this as the psycho-physic law, 537. Criticism thereof, 545. CHAPTER XIV. | ASSOCIATION, : < , , : : : : . 550 The problem of the connection of our thoughts, 550. It depends on mechanical conditions, 558. Association is of objects thought-of, not of ‘ideas,’ 554. The rapidity of association, 557. The ‘law of contiguity,’ 561. The elementary law of association, 566. Impartial redintegration, 569. Ordinary or mixed associa- tion, 571. The law of interest, 572. Association by similarity, 578. Elementary expression of the difference between the three kinds of association, 581. Association in voluntary thought, 583. Similarity no elementary law, 590. History of the doctrine of association, 594. CHAPTER XV. THE PERCEPTION OF TIME, . ; s A ; 4 . 605 The sensible present, 606. Its duration is the primitive time- perception, 608. Accuracy of our estimate of short durations, 611. We have no sense for empty time, 619. Variations of our time-estimate, 624. The feeling of past time is a present feeling, 627. Its cerebral process, 632. CHAPTER XVI. Memory, . ‘ : : ; : ; : . 643 Primary memory, 643. Analysis of the phenomenon of mem- ory, 648. Retention and reproduction are both caused by paths of association in the brain, 658. The conditions of goodness in memory, 659. Native retentiveness is unchangeable, 663. All im- provement of memory consists in better thinking, 667. Other con- ditions of good memory, 669. Recognition, or the sense of famil- iarity, 673. Exact measurements of memory, 676. Forgetting, 679. Pathological cases, 681. Professor Ladd criticised, 687. PSYCHOLOGY. CHAPTER I. THE SCOPE OF PSYCHOLOGY. PsycHoLoay is the Science of Mental Life, both of its phenomena and of their conditions. ‘I'he phenomena are such things as we call feelings, desires, cognitions, reason- ings, decisions, and the like; and, superficially considered, their variety and complexity is such as to leave a chaotic impression on the observer. The most natural and con- sequently the earliest way of unifying the material was, first, to classify it as well as might be, and, secondly, to affiliate the diverse mental modo» thus found, upon a simple entity, the personal Soul, of which they are taken to be so many facultative manifestations. Now, for in- stance, the Soul manifests its faculty of Memory, now of Reasoning, now of Volition, or again its Imagination or its Appetite. This is the orthodox ‘spiritualistic’ theory of scholasticism and of common-sense. Another and a less obvious way of unifying the chaos is to seek common ele- ments im the divers mental facts rather than a common agent behind them, and to explain them constructively by the various forms of arrangement of these elements, as one explains houses by stones and bricks. The ‘association- ist’ schools of Herbart in Germany, and of Hume the Mills and Bain in Britain have thus constructed a psychology without a soul by taking discrete ‘ideas,’ faint or vivid, and showing how, by their cohesions, repulsions, and forms 2 PSYCHOLOG ¥. of succession, such things as reminiscences, perceptions, emotions, volitions, passions, theories, nd all the other furnishings of an individual’s mind may be engendered. The very Self or ego of the individual comes in this way to be viewed no longer as the pre-existing source of the representations, but rather as their last and most com- plicated fruit. Now, if we strive rigorously to simplify the phenomena in either of these ways, we soon become aware of inade- quacies in our method. Any particular cognition, for ex- ample, or recollection, is accounted for on the soul-theory by being referred to the spiritual faculties of Cognition or of Memory. These faculties themselves are thought of as absolute properties of the soul; that is, to take the case of memory, no reason is given why we should remember a fact as it happened, except that so to re- member it constitutes the essence of our Recollective Power. We may, as spiritualists, try to explain our mem- ory’s failures and blunders by secondary causes. But its successes can invoke no factors save the existence of certain objective things to be remembered on the one hand, and of our faculty of memory on the other. When, for instance, I recall my graduation-day, and drag all its incidents and emotions up from death’s dateless night, no mechanical cause can explain this process, nor can any analysis reduce it to lower terms or make its nature seem other than an ultimate datum, which, whether we rebel or not at its mysteriousness, must simply be taken for granted if we are to psychologize at all. However the associationist may represent the present ideas as thronging and arranging themselves, still, the spiritualist insists, he has in the end to admit that something, be it brain, be it ‘ideas,’ be it ‘ asso- ciation,’ knows past time as past, and fills it out with this or that event. And when the spiritualist calls memory an ‘irreducible faculty, he says no more than this admission of the associationist already grants. And yet the admission is far from being a satisfactory simplification of the concrete facts. For why should this absolute god-given Faculty retain so much better the events of yesterday than those of last year, and, best of all, those THE SCOPE OF PSYCHOLOG Y. 3 of an hour ago? Why, again, in old age should its grasp of childhood’s events seem firmest ? Why should illness and exhaustion enfeeble it? Why should repeating an ex- perience strengthen our recollection of it? Why should drugs, fevers, asphyxia, and excitement resuscitate things long since forgotten ? If we content ourselves with merely affirming that the faculty of memory is so peculiarly con- stituted by nature as to exhibit just these oddities, we seem little the better for having invoked it, for our explanation becomes as complicated as that of the crude facts with which we started. Moreover there is something grotesque and irrational in the supposition that the soul is equipped with ‘ elementary powers of such an ingeniously intricate sort. Why should our memory cling more easily to the near than the remote? Why should it lose its grasp of proper sooner than of abstract names? Such peculiarities seem quite fan- tastic ; and might, for aught we can see a priori, be the precise opposites of what they are. Evidently, then, the faculty does not exisi absolutely, but works under conditions , and the quest of the conditions becomes the psychologist’s most interesting task. However firmly he may hold to the soul and her re- membering faculty, he must acknowledge that she never exerts the latter without a cve, and that something must al- ways precede and remind us of whatever we are to recollect. “ Anidea!” says the associationist, “an idea associated with the remembered thing; and this explains also why things repeatedly met with are more easily recollected, for their as- sociates on the various occasions furnish so many distinct avenues of recall.” But this does not explain the effects of fever, exhaustion, hypnotism, old age, and the like. And in general, the pure associationist’s account of our mental life is almost as bewildering as that of the pure spiritualist. This multitude of ideas, existing absolutely, yet clinging together, and weaving an endless carpet of themselves, like dominoes in ceaseless change, or the bits of glass in a kaleidoscope,—whence do they get their fantastic laws of clinging, and why do they cling in just the shapes they do ? For this the associationist must introduce the order of experience in the outer world. The dance of the ideas is +t PSYCHOLOG Y. a copy, somewhat mutilated and altered, of the order of phenomena. But the slightest reflection shows that phe- nomena have absolutely no power to influence our ideas until they have first impressed our senses and our brain, The bare existence of a past fact is no ground for our re- membering it. Unless we have seen it, or somehow under- gone it, we shall never know of its having been. The expe- riences of the body are thus one of the conditions of the faculty of memory being what it is. And a very small amount of reflection on facts shows that one part of the body, namely, the brain, is the part whose experiences are directly concerned. If the nervous communication be cut off between the brain and other parts, the experiences of those other parts are non-existent for the mind. The eye is blind, the ear deaf, the hand insensible and motionless. And conversely, if the brain be injured, consciousness is abolished or altered, even although every other organ in the body be ready to play its normal part. A blow on the head, a sudden subtraction of blood, the pressure of an apoplectic hemorrhage, may have the first effect; whilst a very few ounces of alcohol or grains of opium or hasheesh, or a whiff of chloroform or nitrous oxide gas, are sure to have the second. The delirium of fever, the altered self of insanity, are all due to foreign matters circulating through the brain, or to pathological changes in that organ’s substance. The fact that the brain is the one immediate bodily condition of the mental operations is indeed so universally admitted nowadays that I need spend no more time in illustrating it, but will simply postulate it and pass on. The whole remainder of the book will be more or less of a proof that the postulate was correct. Bodily experiences, therefore, and more particularly brain-experiences, must take a place amongst those con- ditions of the mentallife of which Psychology need take account. The spiritualist and the associationist must both be ‘cerebralists, to the extent at least of admitting that certain peculiarities in the way of working of their own favorite principles are explicable only by the fact that the brain laws are a codeterminant of the result. THE SCOPE OF PSYCHOLOGY. 5 Our first conclusion, then, is that a certain amount of brain-physiology must be presupposed or included in Psychology.* In still another way the pyschologist is forced to be something of a nerve-physiologist. Mental phenomena are not only conditioned a parte ante by bodily processes; but they lead to them a parte post. That they lead to acts is of course the most familiar of truths, but Ido not merely mean acts in the sense of voluntary and deliberate muscular performances. Mental states occasion also changes in the calibre of blood-vessels, or alteration in the heart-beats, or processes more subtle still, in glands and viscera. If these are taken into account, as well as acts which follow at some remote period because the mental state was once there, it will be safe to lay down the general law that no mental modifica- tion ever occurs which is not accompanied or followed by a bodily change. The ideas and feelings, e.g., which these present printed characters excite in the reader’s mind not only occasion movements of his eyes and nascent movements of articulation in him, but will some day make him speak, or take sides in a discussion, or give advice, or choose a book to read, differently from what would have been the case had they never impressed his retina. Our psychology must there- fore take account not only of the conditions antecedent to mental states, but of their resultant consequences as well. But actions originally prompted by conscious intelli- gence may grow so automatic by dint of habit as to be apparently unconsciously performed. Standing, walking, buttoning and unbuttoning, piano-playing, talking, even saying one’s prayers, may be done when the mind is ab- sorbed in other things. The performances of animai instinct seem semi-automatic, and the reflex acts of self- preservation certainly are so. Yet they resemble intelli- gent acts in bringing about the same ends at which the ani- mals’ consciousness, on other occasions, deliberately aims. * Of. Geo. T. Ladd: Elements of Physiological Psychology (1887), pt m1, chap. rr, §§ 9, 12. 8 PSYCHOLOG Y. Shall the study of such machine-like yet purposive acts as these be included in Psychology ? The boundary-line of the mental is certainly vague. It is better not to be pedantic, but to let the science be as vague as its subject, and include such phenomena as these if by so doing we can throw any light on the main business in hand. It will ere long be seen, I trust, that we can; and that we gain much more by a broad than by a narrow conception of our subject. At a certain stage in the devel- opment of every science a degree of vagueness is what best consists with fertility. On the whole, few recent for- mulas have done more real service of a rough sort in psy- chology than the Spencerian one that the essence of mental’ life and of bodily life are one, namely, ‘the adjustment of inner to outer relations.’ Such a formula is vagueness incarnate; but because it takes into account the fact that minds inhabit environments which act on them and on which they in turn react; because, in short, it takes mind in the midst of all its concrete relations, it is immensely more fertile than the old-fashioned ‘ rational psychology,’ which treated the soul as a detached existent, sufficient unto itself, and assumed to consider only its nature and properties. I shall therefore feel free to make any sallies into zoology or intc pure nerve-physiology which may seem instructive for our purposes, but otherwise shall leave those sciences to the physiologists. Can we state more distinctly still the manner in which the mental life seems to intervene between impressions made from without upon the body, and reactions of the body upon the outer world again? Let us look at a few facts. If some iron filings be sprinkled on a table and a mag- net brought near them, they will fly through the air for a certain distance and stick to its surface. A savage see- ing the phenomenon explains it as the result of an attrac- tion or love between the magnet and the filings. But let a card cover the poles of the magnet, and the filings will press forever against its surface without its ever oc- curring to them to pass around its sides and thus come into THE SCOPE OF PSYCHOLOGY. 7 more direct contact with the object of their love. Blow bubbles through a tube into the bottom of a pail of water, they will rise to the surface and mingle with the air. Their action may again be poetically interpreted as due to a longing to reccmbine with the mother-atmosphere above the surface. But if you invert a jar full of water over the pail, they will rise and remain lodged beneath its bottom, shut in from the outer air, although a slight deflection from their course at the outset, or a re-descent towards the rim of the jar when they found their upward course im- peded, would easily have set them free. If now we pass from such actions as these to those of living things, we notice a striking difference. Romeo wants Juliet as the filings want the magnet; and if no obstacles intervene he moves towards her by as straight a line as they. But Romeo and Juliet, if a wall be built between them, do not remain idiotically pressing their faces against its opposite sides like the magnet and the filings with the card. Romeo soon finds a circuitous way, by scaling the wall or otherwise, of touching Juliet’s lips directly. With the filings the path is fixed; whether it reaches the end depends on accidents. With the lover it is the end which is fixed, the path may be modified indefinitely. Suppose a living frog in the position in which we placed our bubbles of air, namely, at the bottom of a jar of water. The want >f breath will soon make him also Jong to rejoin the mother-atmosphere, and he will take the shortest path to his end by swimming straight upwards. But if a jar full of water be inverted over him, he will not, like the bubbles, perpetually press his nose against its unyielding roof, but will restlessly explore the neighborhood until by re-descending again he has discovered a path round its brim to the goal of his desires. Again the fixed end, the varying means! Such contrasts between living and inanimate perform- ances end by leading men to deny that in the physical world final purposes exist at all. Loves and desires are to-day no longer imputed to particles of iron or of air. No one supposes now that the end of any activity which they may display is an ideal purpose presiding over the 8 PSYCHOLOG ¥. activity from its outset and soliciting or drawing it into being by a sort of vis a fronte. The end, on the contrary, is deemed a mere passive result, pushed into being a tergo, having had, so to speak, no voice in its own production, Alter the pre-existing conditions, and with inorganic ma~ terials you bring forth each time a different apparent end. But with intelligent agents, altering the conditions changes the activity displayed, but not the end reached; for here the idea of the yet unrealized end co-operates with the con- ditions to determine what the activities shall be. The pursuance of future ends and the choice of means for their attainment are thus the mark and criterion of the presence of mentality ina phenomenon. We all use this test to dis- criminate between an intelligent and a mechanical per- formance. We impute no mentality to sticks and stones, because they never seem to move for the sake of anything, but always when pushed, and then indifferently and with no sign of choice. So we unhesitatingly call them senseless. Just so we form our decision upon the deepest of all philosophic problems: Is the Kosmos an expression of intelligence rational in its inward nature, or a brute ex- ternal fact pure and simple? If we find ourselves, in con- templating it, unable to banish the impression that it is a realm of final purposes, that it exists for the sake of some- thing, we place intelligence at the heart of it and havea religion. If, on the contrary, in surveying its irremediable flux, we can think of the present only as so much mere mechanical sprouting from the past, occurring with no reference to the future, we are atheists and materialists. In the lengthy discussions which psychologists have carried on about the amount of intelligence displayed by lower mammals, or the amount of consciousness involved in the functions of the nerve-centres of reptiles, the same test has always been applied: Is the character of the actions such that we must believe them to be performed for the sake of their result? The result in question, as we shall here- after abundantly see, is as a rule a useful one,—the animal is, on the whole, safer under the circumstances for bringing it forth. So far the action has a teleological character; THE SCOPE OF PSYCHOLOGY. 9 but such mere outward teleology as this might still be the blind result of vis a tergo. The growth-and movements of plants, the processes of development, digestion, secretion, etc., in animals, supply innumerable instances of per- formances useful to the individual which may nevertheless be, and by most of us are supposed to be, produced by automatic mechanism. The physivlogist does not con- fidently assert conscious intelligence in the frog’s spinal cord until he has shown that the useful result which the nervous machinery brings forth under a given irritation remains the same when the machinery is altered. If, to take the stock instance, the right knee of a headless frog be irri- tated with acid, the right foot will wipe it off. When, how- ever, this foot is amputated, the animal will often raise the left foot to the spot and wipe the offending material away. Pfliiger and Lewes reason from such facts in the follow- ing way : Ifthe first reaction were the result of mere machin- ery, they say ; if that irritated portion of the skin discharged the right leg as a trigger discharges its own barrel of a shot- gun; then amputating the right foot would indeed frustrate the wiping, but would not make the left leg move. It would simply result in the right stump moving through the empty air (which is in fact the phenomenon sometimes observed), The right trigger makes no effort to discharge the left barre] if the right one be unloaded ; nor does an electrical ma- chine ever get restless because it can only emit sparks, and not hem pillow-cases like a sewing-machine. If, on the contrary, the right leg originally moved for the purpose of wiping the acid, then nothing is more natura] than that, when the easiest means of effecting that purpose prove fruitless, other means should be tried. Every failure must keep the animal in a state of disappointment which will lead to all sorts of new trials and devices; and tran- quillity will not ensue till one of these, by a happy stroke, achieves the wished-for end. In a similar way Goltz ascribes intelligence to the frog’s optic lobesand cerebellum. We alluded above to the manner in which a sound frog imprisoned in water will dis- cover an outlet to the atmosphere. Goltz found that frogs deprived of their cerebral hemispheres would often exhibit 10 PSYCHOLOGY. a like ingenuity. Such a frog, after rising from the bottom and finding his farther upward progress checked by the glass bell which has been inverted over him, will not per- sist in butting his nose against the obstacle until dead of suffocation, but will often re-descend and emerge from under its rim as if, not a definite mechanical propulsion upwards, but rather a conscious desire to reach the air by hook or crook were the main-spring of his activity. Goltz con- cluded from this that the hemispheres are not the sole seat of intellect in frogs. He made the same inference from observing that a brainless frog will turn over from his back to his belly when one of his legs is sewed up, although the movements required are then very different from those excited under normal circumstances by the same annoying position. They seem determined, consequently, not merely by the antecedent irritant, but by the final end,—though the irritant of course is what makes the end desired. Another brilliant German author, Liebmann,* argues against the brain’s mechanism accounting for mentai action, by very similar considerations. A machine as such, he says, will bring forth right results when it is in good order, and wrong results if out of repair. But both kinds of result flow with equally fatal necessity from their conditions. We cannot suppose the clock-work whose structure fatally determines it to a certain rate of speed, noticing that this speed is too slow or too fast and vainly trying to correct it. Its conscience, if it have any, should be as good as that of the best chronometer, for both alike obey equally well the same eternal mechanical laws—laws from behind. But if the brain be out of order and the man says “ Twice four are two,” instead of ‘Twice four are eight,” or else “ I must go to the coal to buy the wharf,” instead of “I must go to the wharf to buy the coal,” instantly there arises a conscious- ness of error. The wrong performance, though it obey the same mechanical law as the right, is nevertheless con- demned,—condemned as contradicting the inner law—the law from in front, the purpose or ideal for which the brain should act, whether it do so or not. ee * Zur Analysis der Wirklichkeit, p. 489. THE SCOPE OF PSYCHOLOGY. 1} We need not discuss here whether these writers in draw- ing their conclusion have done justice to all the premises involved in the cases they treat of. We quote their argu- ments only to show how they appeal to the principle that no actions but such as are done for an end, and show a choice of means, can be culled indubitable expressions of Mind. I shall then adopt this as the criterion by which to cir- cumscribe the subject-matter of this work so far as action enters into it. Many nervous performances will therefore be unmentioned, as being purely physiological. Nor will the anatomy of the nervous system and organs of sense be described anew. ‘The reader will find in H. N. Martin’s ‘Human Body,’ in G. T. Ladd’s ‘ Physiological Psychol- ogy, and in all the other standard Anatomies and Physi- ologies, a mass of information which we must regard as pre- liminary and take for granted in the present work.* Of the functions of the cerebral hemispheres, however, since they directly subserve consciousness, it will be well to give some little account. * Nothing is easier than to familiarize one’s self with the mammalian brain. Get asheep’s head, a small saw, chisel, scalpel and forceps (all three can best be had from a surgical-instrument maker), and unriivel its parts either by the aid of a human dissecting book,such as Holden’s‘Manual of Anatomy,’ or by the specific directions ad hoe given in such books as Foster and Lawgley’s ‘Practical Physiology’ (Macmillan) or Morrell’s ‘Comparative Anatomy and Dissection of Mammalia’ (Longmans). CHAPTER II. THE FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. Ir I begin chopping the foot of a tree, its branches are unmoved by my act, and its leaves murmur as peacefully as ever in the wind. If, on the contrary, I do violence to the foot of a fellow-man, the rest of his body instantly responds to the aggression by movements of alarm or defence. The reason of this difference is that the man has a nervous system whilst the tree has none; and the function of the nervous system is to bring each part into harmonious co-operation with every other. The afferent nerves, when excited by some physical irritant, be this as gross in its mode of oper- ation as a chopping axe or as subtle as the waves of lighi, conveys the excitement to the nervous centres. The com- motion set up in the centres does not stop there, but dis- charges itself, if at all strong, through the efferent nerves into muscles and glands, exciting movements of the limbs and viscera, or acts of secretion, which vary with the animal, and with the irritant applied. These acts of response have usually the common character of being of service. They ward off the noxious stimulus and support the beneficial one; whilst if, in itself indifferent, the stimulus be a sign of some distant circumstance of practical importance, the animal’s acts are addressed to this circumstance so as to avoid its perils or secure its benefits, as the case may be. To take a common example, if I hear the conductor calling ‘All aboard!’ as I enter the depot, my heart first stops, then palpitates, and my legs respond to the air-waves falling on my tympanum by quickening their movements. If I stumble as I run, the sensation of falling provokes a movement of the hands towards the direction of the fall, the effect of which is to shield the body from too sudden a shock. If a cinder enter my eye, its lids close forcibly and a copious flow of tears tends to wash it out. 12 THE FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 13 These three responses to a sensational stimulus differ, however, in many respects. The closure of the eye and the Jachrymation are quite involuntary, and so is the disturbance ° of the heart. Such involuntary responses we know as ‘reflex’ acts. The motion of the arms to break the shock of falling may also be called reflex, since it occurs too quickly to be deliberately intended. Whether it be instinc- tive or whether it result from the pedestrian education of childhood may be doubtful ; it is, at any rate, less automatic than the previous acts, for a man might by conscious effort learn to perform it more skilfully, or even to suppress it alto- gether. Actions of this kind, into which instinct and volition enter upon equal terms, have been called ‘semi-reflex.’ The act of running towards the train, on the other hand, has no instinctive element about it. Itis purely the result of edu- cation, and is preceded by a consciousness of the purpose to be attained and a distinct mandate of the will. It is a ‘vol- untary act.’ Thus the animal’s reflex and voluntary per- formances shade into each other gradually, being connected by acts which may often occur automatically, but may also be modified by conscious intelligence. An outside observer, unable to perceive the accompany- ing consciousness, might be wholly at a loss to discriminate between the automatic acts and those which volition es- corted. But if the criterion of mind’s existence be the choice of the proper means for the attainment of a supposed end, all the acts seem to be inspired by intelligence, for appropriateness characterizes them all alike. This fact, now, has led to two quite opposite theories about the relation to consciousness of the nervous functions. Some authors, finding that the higher voluntary ones seem to require the guidance of feeling, conclude that over the lowest reflexes some such feeling also presides, though it may be a feeling of which we remain unconscious. Others, finding that reflex and semi-automatic acts may, notwithstanding their appro- priateness, take place with an unconsciousness apparently complete, fly to the opposite extreme and maintain that the appropriateness even of voluntary actions owes nothing to the fact that consciousness attends them. They are, accord- ing to these writers, results of physiological mechanism pure 14 PSYCHOLUGY. and simple. In a near chapter we shall return to this controversy again. Let us now look a little more closely at the brain and at the ways in which its states may be sup- posed to condition those of the mind. THE FROG’S NERVE-CENTRES. Both the minute anatomy and the detailed physiology of the brain are achievements of the present generation, or rather we may say (beginning with Meynert) of the past twenty years. Many points are still obscure and subject to controversy ; but a general way of conceiving the organ has been reached on all hands which in its main feature seems not unlikely to stand, and which even gives a most plausible scheme of the way in which cerebral and mental operations go hand in hand. The best way to enter the subject will be to take a lower creature, like a frog, and study by the vivisectional method the functions of his different nerve-centres. The frog’s nerve-centres are figured in the accompany- ing diagram, which needs no further ex- planation. I will first proceed to state what happens when various amounts of the anterior parts are removed, in different frogs, in the way in which an ordinary student removes them; that is, with no ex- treme precautions as to the purity of the operation. We shall in this way reach a very simple conception of the functions of the various centres, involving the strongest possible contrast between the cerebral Fig, 1. ¢ H, Cerebral hemispheres and the lower lobes. | This Optic Thalami; OL; sharp conception will have didactic ad- Cuceaiin tiie O; vantages, for it is often very instructive Medulla Oblongata; ; 5 ° SC,Spinal Cord. to start with too simple a formula and correct it later on. Our first formula, as we shall later see, will have to be softened down somewhat by the results of more careful experimentation both on frogs and birds, and by those of the most recent observations on dogs, THE FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 15 monkeys, and man. But it will put us, from the outset, in clear possession of some fundamental notions and distine- tions which we could otherwise not gain so well, and none of which the later more completed view will overturn. If, then, we reduce the frog’s nervous system to the spinal cord alone, by making a section behind the base of the skull, between the spinal cord and the medulla oblon- gata, thereby cutting off the brain from all connection with the rest of the body, the frog will still continue to live, but with a very peculiarly modified activity. It ceases to breathe or swallow; it lies flat on its belly, and does not, like a normal frog, sit up on its fore paws, though its hind legs are kept, as usual, folded against its body and immediately re- sume this position if drawn out. If thrown on its back, it lies there quietly, without turning over like a normal frog. Locomotion and voice seem entirely abolished. If we sus- pend it by the nose, and irritate different portions of its skin by acid, it performs a set of remarkable ‘defensive’ movements calculated to wipe away the irritant. Thus, if the breast be touched, both fore paws will rub it vigorously; if we touch the outer side of the elbow, the hind foot of the same side will rise directly to the spot and wipe it. The back of the foot will rub the knee if that be attacked, whilst if the foot be cut away, the stump will make ineffectual movements, and then, in many frogs, a pause will come, as if for deliberation, succeeded by a rapid passage of the opposite unmutilated foot to the acidulated spot. The most striking character of all these movements, after their teleological appropriateness, is their precision. They vary, in sensitive frogs and with a proper amount of irritation, so little as almost to resemble in their machine- like regularity the performances of a jumping-jack, whose legs must twitch whenever you pull the string. The spinal cord of the frog thus contains arrangements of cells and fibres fitted to convert skin irritations into movements of defence. We may call it the centre for defensive movements in this animal. We may indeed go farther than this, and by cutting the spinal cord in various places find that its separate segments are independent mechanisms, for appro- priate activities of the head and of the arms and legs respec- 16 PSYCHOLOG ¥. tively. The segment governing the arms is especially active, in male frogs, in the breeding season; and these mem- bers alone with the breast and back appertaining to them, everything else being cut away, will then actively grasp a finger placed between them and remain hanging to it for a considerable time. The spinal cord in other animals has analogous powers. Even in man it makes movements of defence. Paraplegics draw up their legs when tickled; and Robin, on tickling the breast of a criminal an hour after decapitation, saw the arm and hand move towards the spot. Of the lower fune- tions of the mammalian cord, studied so ably by Goltz and others, this is not the place to speak. If, in a second animal, the cut be made just behind the optic lobes so that the cerebellum and medulla oblongata remain attached to the cord, then swallowing, breathing, crawling, and a rather enfeebled jumping and swimming are added to the movements previously observed.* 'There are other reflexes too. The animal, thrown on his back, immediately turns over to his belly. Placed in a shallow bowl, which is floated on water and made to rotate, he re- sponds to the rotation by first turning his head and then waltzing around with his entire body, in the opposite direc- tion to the whirling of the bowl. If his support be tilted so that his head points downwards, he points it up; he points it down if it be pointed upwards, to the right if it be pointed to the left, etc. But his reactions do not go farther than these movements of the head. He will not, like frogs whose thalami are preserved, climb up a board if the latter be tilted, but will slide off it to the ground. If the cut be made on another frog between the tha- lami and the optic lobes, the locomotion both on land and water becomes quite normal, and, in addition to the reflexes already shown by the lower centres, he croaks regularly whenever he is pinched under the arms. He compensates rotations, etc., by movements of the head, and turns over from his back; but still drops off his tilted * It should be said that this particular cut commonly proves fatal. The text refers to the rare cases which survive. THE FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. a iy board. As his optic nerves are destroyed by the usual operation, it is impossible to say whether he will avoid obstacles placed in his path. When, finally, a frog’s cerebral hemispheres alone are cut off by a section between them and the thalami which pre- serves the latter, an unpractised observer would not at first suspect anything abnormal about the animal. Not only is he capable, on proper instigation, of all the acts already described, but he guides himself by sight, so that if an obstacle be set up between him and the light, and he be forced to move forward, he either jumps over it or swerves to one side. He manifests sexual passion at the proper season, and, unlike an altogether brainless frog, which em- braces anything placed between his arms, postpones this’ reflex act until a female of his own species is provided. Thus far, as aforesaid, a person unfamiliar with frogs might not suspect a mutilation; but even such a person would soon remark the almost entire absence of spontane- ous motion—that is, motion unprovoked by any present in- citation of sense. The continued movements of swimming, performed by the creature in the water, seem to be the fatal result of the contact of that fluid with its skin. They cease when a stick, for example, touches his hands. This is a sensible irritant towards which the feet are automatic- ally drawn by reflex action, and on which the animal re- mains sitting. He manifests no hunger, and will suffer a fly to crawl over his nose unsnapped at. Fear, too, seems to have deserted him. In a word, he is an extremely com- plex machine whose actions, so far as they go, tend to self-preservation ; but still a machine, in this sense—that it seems to contain no incalculable element. By applying the right sensory stimulus to him we are almost as certain of getting a fixed response as an organist is of hearing a certain tone when he pulls out a certain stop. But now if to the lower centres we add the cerebral hemispheres, or if, in other words, we make an intact ani- mal the subject of our observations, all this is changed. In addition to the previous responses to present incitements of sense, our frog now goes through long and complex acts of locomotion spontaneously, or as if moved by what in our- 18 PSYCHOLOGY. selves we should call an idea. His reactions to outward stimuli vary their form, too. Instead of making simple defensive movements with his hind legs like a headless frog if touched, or of giving one or two leaps and then sit- ting still like a hemisphereless one, he makes persistent and varied efforts at escape, as if, not the mere contact of the physiologist’s hand, but the notion of danger suggested by it were now his spur. Led by the feeling of hunger, too, he goes in search of insects, fish, or smaller frogs, and varies his procedure with each species of victim. The physiologist cannot by manipulating him elicit croaking, erawling up a board, swimming or stopping, at will. His conduct has become incalculable. We can no longer foretell it exactly. Effort to escape is his dominant reaction, but he may do anything else, even swell up and become per- fectly passive in our hands. Such are the phenomena commonly observed, and such the impressions which one naturally receives. Certain general conclusions follow irresistibly. First of all the following: The acts of all the centres involve the use of the same muscles. When a headless frog’s hind leg wipes the acid, he calls into play all the leg-muscles which a frog with his full medulla oblongata and cerebellum uses when he turns from his back to his belly. Their contractions are, how- ever, combined differently in the two cases, so that the re- sults vary widely. We must consequently conclude that specific arrangements of cells and fibres exist in the cord for wiping, in the medulla for turning over, ete. Similarly they exist in the thalami for jumping over seen obstacles and for balancing the moved body; in the optic lobes for creeping backwards, or what not. But in the hemispheres, since the presence of these organs brings no new elementary form of movement with it, but only deter- mines differently the occasions on which the movements shall occur, making the usual stimuli less fatal and machine-like ; we need suppose no such machinery directly co-ordinative of muscular contzactions to exist. We may rather assume, when the mandate for a wiping-movement is sent forth by FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 19 the hemispheres, that a current goes straight to the wiping- arrangement in the spinal cord, exciting this arrangement as a whole. Similarly, if an intact frog wishes to jump over a stone which he sees, all he need do is to excite from the hemispheres the jumping-centre in the thalami or wherever it may be, and the latter will provide for the de- tails of the execution. It is like a general ordering a colonel to make a certain movement, but not telling him how it shall be done.* The same muscle, then, is repeatedly represented at different heights; and at each it enters into a different combination with other muscles to co-operate in some special form of concerted movement. At each height the movement is dis- charged by some particular form of sensorial stimulus. Thus in the cord, the skin alone occasions movements; in the upper part of the optic lobes, the eyes are added; in the thalami, the semi-circular canals would seem to play a part; whilst the stimuli which discharge the hemispheres would seem not so much to be elementary sorts of sensation, as groups ot sensations forming determinate objects or things. Prey is not pursued nor are enemies shunned by ordinary hemisphereless frogs. Those reactions upon complex cir- cumstances which we call instinctive rather than reflex, are already ‘n this animal dependent on the brain’s highest lobes, and still more is this the case with animals higher in the zoological scale. The results are just the same if, instead of a frog, we take a pigeon, and cut out his hemispheres as they are ordi- narily cut out for a lecture-room demonstration. There is not a movement natural to him which this brainless bird cannot perform if expressly excited thereto; only the inner promptings seem deficient, and when left to himself he spends most of his time crouched on the ground with his head sunk between his shoulders as if asleep. * T confine myself to the frog for simplicity’s sake. In higheranimals, especially the ape and man, it would seem as if not only determinate com- binations of muscles, but limited groups or even single muscles could be innervated from the hemispheres. 20 PSYCHOLOGY. GENERAL NOTION OF HEMISPHERES. All these facts lead us, when we think about them, to some such explanatory conception as this: The lower centres act from present sensational stimuli alone; the hemispheres act from perceptions and considerations, the sensations which they may receive serving only as suggesters of these. But what are perceptions but sensations grouped together? and what are considerations but expectations, in the fancy, of sensa- tions which will be felt one way or another according as” action takes this course or that? If I step aside on seeing a rattlesnake, from considering how dangerous an animal he is, the mental materials which constitute my prudential reflection are images more or less vivid of the movement of his head, of a sudden pain in my leg, of a state of terror, a swelling of the limb, a chill, delirium, unconsciousness, etc., etc.,. and the ruin of my hopes. But all these images are constructed out of my past experiences. They are repro- ductions of what I have felt or witnessed. They are, in short, remote sensations ; and the difference between the hemi- sphereless animal and the whole one may be concisely ex- pressed by saying that the one obeys absent, the other only present, objects. The hemispheres would then seem to be the seat of mem- ory. Vestiges of past experience must in some way be stored up in them, and must, when aroused by present stimuli, first appear as representations of distant goods and evils; and then must discharge into the appropriate motor channels for warding off the evil and securing the benefits of the good. If we liken the nervous currents to electric currents, we can compare the nervous system, C, below the hemispheres to a direct circuit from sense- organ to muscle along the line 8S... OC... M of Fig. 2(p. 21). The hemisphere, H, adds the long circuit or loop-line through which the current may pass when for any reason the direct line is not used. Thus, a tired wayfarer on a hot day throws himself on FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 21 the damp earth beneath a maple-tree. The sensations of delicious rest and coolness pour- ing themselves through the direct line would naturally discharge into the muscles of complete exten- sion: he would abandon himself to the dangerous repose. But the loop-line being open, part of the current is drafted along it, and awakens rheumatic or catarrhal reminiscences, which prevail over the ppg tons of sense, and make ee: the’'man arise and pursue his way to where he may enjoy his rest more safely. Presently we shall examine the manner in which the hemispheric loop-line may be supposed to serve as a reservoir for such reminiscences as these. Mean- while I will ask the reader to notice some corollaries of its being such a reservoir. First, no animal without it can deliberate, pause, post- pone, nicely weigh one motive against another, or compare. Prudence, in a word, is for such a creature an impossible virtue.. Accordingly we see that nature removes those func- tions in the exercise of which prudence is a virtue from the lower centres and hands them over to the cerebrum. Wher- ever a creature has to deal with complex features of the en- vironment, prudence is a virtue. The higher animals have so to deal; and the more complex the features, the higher we call the animals. The fewer of his acts, then, can such an animal perform without the help of the organs in question. In the frog many acts devolve wholly on the lower centres ; in the bird fewer ; in the rodent fewer still; in the dog very few indeed; and in apes and men hardly any at all. The advantages of this are obvious. Take the prehen- sion of food as an example and suppose it to be a reflex performance of the lower centres. The animal will be con- demned fatally and irresistibly to snap at it whenever presented, no matter what the circumstances may be; he can no more disobey this prompting than water can refuse to boil when a fire is kindled under the pot. His life will again and again pay the forfeit of his gluttony. 22 PSYCHOLOGY. Exposure to retaliation, to other enemies, to traps, to poisons, to the dangers of repletion, must be regular parts of his existence. His lack of all thought by which to weigh the danger against the attractiveness of the bait, and of all volition to remain hungry a little while longer, is the direct measure of his lowness in the mental seale. And those fishes which, like our cunners and sculpins, are no sooner thrown back from the hook into the water, than they automatically seize the hook again, would soon expiate the degradation of their intelligence by the extinc- tion of their type, did not their exaggerated fecundity atone for their imprudence. Appetite and the acts it prompts have consequently become in all higher vertebrates func- tions of the cerebrum. They disappear when the physiol- ogist’s knife nas left the subordinate centres alone in place. The brainless pigeon will starve though left on a corn- heap. Take again the sexual function. In birds this devolves exclusively upon the hemispheres. When these are shorn away the pigeon pays no attention to the billings and coo- ings of its mate. And Goltz found that a bitch in heat would excite no emotion in male dogs who had suffered large loss of cerebral tissue. Those who have read Dar-. win’s ‘ Descent of Man’ know what immense importance in the amelioration of the breed in birds this author ascribes to the mere fact of sexual selection. The sexual act is not performed until every condition of circumstance and senti- ment is fulfilled, until time, place, and partner all are fit. But in frogs and toads this passion devolves on the lower centres. They show consequently a machine-like obe- dience to the present incitement of sense, and an almost total exclusion of the power of choice. Copuiation occurs per fas aut nefas, occasionally between males, often with dead females, in puddles exposed on the highway, and the male may be cut in two without letting go his hold. Every spring an immense sacrifice of batrachian life takes place from these causes alone. No one need be told how dependent all human social elevation is upon the prevalence of chastity. Hardly any factor measures more than this the difference between civili« FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 23 zation and barbarism. Physiologically interpreted, chastity means nothing more than the fact that present solicitations of sense are overpowered by suggestions of esthetic and moral fitness which the circumstances awaken in the cerebrum ; and that upon the inhibitory or permissive in- fluence of these alone action directly depends. Within the psychic life due to the cerebrum itself the same general distinction obtains, between considerations of the more immediate and considerations of the more remote. In all ages the man whose determinations are swayed by reference to the most distant ends has been held to possess the highest intelligence. The tramp who lives from hour to hour; the bohemian whose engagements are from day to day; the bachelor who builds but for a single life; the father who acts for another generation ; the patriot who thinks of a whole community and many generations ; and finally, the philosopher and saint whose cares are for humanity and for eternity,—these range themselves in an unbroken hierarchy, wherein each successive grade results from an increased manifestation of the special form of action by which the cerebral centres are distinguished from all below them. In the ‘loop-line’ along which the memories and ideas of the distant are supposed to lie, the action, so far as it is a physical process, must ve interpreted after the type of the action in the lower centres. If regarded here as a reflex process, it must be reflex there as well. The current in both places runs out into the muscles only after it has first run in; but whilst the path by which it runs out is deter- mined in the lower centres by reflections few and fixed amongst the cell-arrangements, in the hemispheres the reflections are many and instable. This, it will be seen, is only a difference of degree and not of kind, and does not change the reflex type. The conception of all action as conforming to this type is the fundamental conception of modern nerve-physiology. So much for our general pre- liminary conception of the nerve-centres! Let us define it more distinctly before we see how well physiological ob- servation will bear it out in detail. 24 PSYCHOLOG Y. THE EDUCATION OF THE HEMISPHERES. Nerve-currents run in through sense-organs, and whilst provoking reflex acts in the lower centres, they arouse ideas in the hemispheres, which either permit the reflexes in question, check them, or substitute others for them. All ideas being in the last resort reminiscences, the question to answer is: How can processes become organized in the hemi- spheres which correspond to reminiscences in the mind ?* Nothing is easier than to conceive a possible way in which this might be done, provided four assumptions be granted. ‘These assumptions (which after all are inevitable in any event) are: 1) The same cerebral process which, when aroused from without by a sense-organ, gives the perception of an object, will give an idea of the same object when aroused by other cerebral processes from within. 2) If processes 1, 2, 3,4 have once been aroused to- gether or in immediate succession, any subsequent arousal of any one of them (whether from without or within) will tend to arouse the others in the original order. [This is the so-called law of association. | 3) Every sensorial excitement propagated to a lower centre tends to spread upwards and arouse an idea. 4) Every idea tends ultimately either to produce a movement or to check one which otherwise would be pro- duced. Suppose now (these assumptions being granted) that we have a baby before us who sees a candle-flame for the first * [ hope that the reader will take no umbrage at my so mixing the physical and mental, and talking of refiex acts and hemispheres and remi- niscences in the same breath, as if they were homogeneous quantities and factors of one causal chain. I have done so deliberately ; for although I admit that from the radically physical point of view it is easy to conceive — of the chain of events amongst the cells and fibres as complete in itself, and that whilst so conceiving it one need make no mention of * ideas,’ { yet suspect that point of view of being an unreal abstraction. Reflexes in centres may take place even where accompanying feelings or ideas guide them. In another chapter I shall try to show reasons for not abandoning this common-sense position ; meanwhile language lends itself so much more easily to the mixed way of describing, that I will continue to employ the latter. The more radical-minded reader can always read ‘ ideational process’ for * idea.’ FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 25 time, and, by virtue of a reflex tendency common in babies of a certain age, extends his hand to grasp it, so that his fingers get burned. So far we have two reflex currents in play: first, from the eye to the extension movement, along the line 1—1—1—1 of Fig. 3; and second, from the finger to the movement of drawing back the hand, along the line 2—2—2—2, If this were the baby’s whole nervous system, and if the re- flexes were once for all organic, we should have no alteration in his behavior, no matter how often the experience recurred. The retinal image of the flame would always make the arm shoot forward, the burning of the finger would always send it back. But we know that ‘the burnt child dreads the fire,’ and that one experience usually protects the fingers forever. The point is to see how the hemispheres may bring this result to pass. We must complicate our diagram (see Fig. 4). Let the current 1—1, from the eye, discharge upward as well as downward when it reaches the lower centre for vision, and arouse the perceptional process s' in the hemispheres ;_ let the feeling of the arm’s exten- sion also send up a current which leaves a trace of itself, m'; let the burnt finger leave an analogous trace, s°; and let the movement of retrac- tion leave m*. ‘These four processes will now, by virtue of assumption 2), be associ- ated together by the path s'—m'—s’—m’*, running from Peete the fst to the Tas no tha plana, ything touches off s’, ideas of the extension, of the burnt finger, and of the retraction will pass in rapid succession =) MMi, = MWS Fia. 3. SJ 1) ANY! UA Mp 26 PSYCHOLOG ¥Y. through the mind. The effect on the child’s conduct when the candle flame is next presented is easy to imagine. Of course the sight of it arouses the grasping reflex; but it arouses simultaneously the idea thereof, together with that of the consequent pain, and of the final retraction of the hand; and if these cerebral processes prevail in strength over the immediate sensation in the centres below, the last idea will be the cue by which the final action is discharged. The grasping will be arrested in mid-career, the hand drawn back, and the child’s fingers saved. In all this we assume that the hemispheres do not natively couple any particular sense-impression with any special motor discharge. They only register, and preserve traces of, such couplings as are already organized in the reflex centres below. But this brings it inevitably about that, when a chain of experiences has been already regis- tered and the first link is impressed once again from without, the last link will often be awakened in idea long before it can exist in fact. And if this last link were previously coupled with a motion, that motion may now come from the mere ideal suggestion without waiting for the actual impres- sion to arise. Thus an animal with hemispheres acts in an- ticipation of future things ; or, to use our previous formula, he acts from considerations of distant good and ill. If we give the name of partners to the original couplings of impressions with motions in a reflex way, then we may say that the func- tion of the hemispheres is simply to bring about exchanges among the partners. Movement m”, which natively is sensa- tion s”’s partner, becomes through the hemispheres the partner of sensation s’, s* or s*. It is like the great com- mutating switch-board at a central telephone station. No new elementary process is involved ; no impression nor any motion peculiar to the hemispheres; but any number of combinations impossible to the lower machinery taken alone, and an endless consequent increase in the possibilities of behavior on the creature’s part. All this, as a mere scheme,* is so clear and so concordant * [shall call it hereafter for shortness ‘the Meynert scheme;’ for the child-and-flame example, as well as the whole general notion that the hemi- spheres are a supernumerary surface for the projection and association of FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 27 with the general look of the facts as almost to impose itself on our belief; but it is anything but clear in detail. The brain-physiology of late years has with great effort sought to work out the paths by which these couplings of sensa- tions with movements take piace, both in the hemispheres and in the centres below. So we must next test our scheme by the facts discovered in this direction. We shall conclude, I think, after taking them all into account, that the scheme probably makes the lower centres too machine-like and the hemispheres not quite machine-like enough, and must consequently be softened down a little. So much I may say in advance. Meanwhile, before plunging into the details which await us, it will somewhat clear our ideas if we contrast the modern way of looking at the matter with the phrenological concep- tion which but lately preceded it. THE PHRENOLOGICAL CONCEPTION. In a certain sense Gall was the first to seek to explain in detail how the brain could subserve our mental opera- tions. His way of proceeding was only too simple. He took the faculty-psychology as his ultimatum on the mental side, and he made no farther psychological analysis. Wherever he found an individual -vith some strongly-marked trait of character he examined his head; and if he found the latter prominent in a certain region, he said without more ado that that region was the ‘organ’ of the trait or faculty in question. The traits were of very diverse ccn- stitution, some being simple sensibilities like ‘weight’ or ‘color;’ some being instinctive tendencies like ‘alimen- tiveness’ or ‘amativeness ;’ and others, again, being com- plex resultants like ‘conscientiousness, ‘individuality.’ Phrenology fell promptly into disrepute among scientific men because observation seemed to show that large facul- sensatidns and movements natively coupled in the centres below, is due to Th. Meynert, the Austrian anatomist. For a popular account of his views, see his pamphlet ‘Zur Mechanik des Gehirnbaues,’ Vienna, 1874. His most recent development of them is embodied in his ‘ Psychiatry,’ a clinical treatise on diseases of the forebrain, translated by B. Sachs, New York, 1885. 28 PSYCHOLOGY. ties and large ‘bumps’ might fail to coexist; because the scheme of Gall was so vast as hardly to admit of accurate determination at all—who of us can say even of his own brothers whether their perceptions of weight and of time are well developed or not ?—because the followers of Gall and Spurzheim were unable to reform these errors in any appre- ciable degree ; and, finally, because the whole analysis of faculties was vague and erroneous from a psychologic point of view. Popular professors of the lore have nevertheless continued to command the admiration of popular audiences ; and there seems no doubt that Phrenology, however little it satisfy our scientific curiosity about the functions of dif- ferent portions of the brain, may still be, in the hands of intelligent practitioners, a useful help in the art of reading character. A hooked nose and a firm jaw are usually signs of practical energy ; soft, delicate hands are signs of refined sensibility. Even so may a prominent eye be a sign of power over language, and a bull-neck a sign of sensuality. But the brain behind the eye and neck need no more be the organ of the signified faculty than the jaw is the organ of the will or the hand the organ of refinement. These correlations between mind and body are, however, so frequent that the ‘characters’ given by phrenologists are often remarkable for knowingness and insight. Phrenology hardly does more than restate the problem. To answer the question, “ Why do I lke children?” by saying, “Because you have a large organ of philoprogeni- tiveness,” but renames the phenomenon to be explained. What is my philoprogenitiveness ? Of what mental ele- ments does it consist? And how can a part of the brain be its organ? A science of the mind must reduce such complex manifestations as ‘ philoprogenitiveness’ to their elements. A science of the brain must point out the func- tions of its elements. A science cf the relations of mind and brain must show how the elementary ingredients of the former correspond to the elementary functions of the latter. But phrenology, except by occasional coincidence, takes no account of elements at all. Its ‘faculties,’ as a rule, are fully equipped persons in a particular mental attitude. Take, for example, the ‘faculty’ of language. It involves FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 29 in reality a host of distinct powers. We must first have images of concrete things and ideas of abstract qualities and relations; we must next have the memory of words and then the capacity so to associate each idea or image with a particular word that, when the word is heard, the idea shall forthwith enter our mind. We must conversely, as soon as the idea arises in our mind, associate with it a mental image of the word, and by means of this image we must innervate our articulatory apparatus so as to repro- duce the word as physical sound. To read or to write a language other elements still must be introduced. But it is plain that the faculty of spoken language alone is so complicated as to call into play almost all the elementary powers which the mind possesses, memory, imagination, association, judgment, and volition. A portion of the brain competent to be the adequate seat of such a faculty would needs be an entire brain in miniature,—just as the faculty itself is really a specification of the entire man, a sort of homunculus. Yet just such homunculi are for the most part the phrenological organs. As Lange says: ‘* We have a parliament of little men together, each one of whom, as happens also in a real parliament, possesses but a single idea which he ceaselessly strives to make prevail’’—benevolence, firmness, hope, and the rest. ‘‘Instead of one soul, phrenology gives us forty, each alone as enigmatic as the full aggregate psychic life can be. In- stead of dividing the latter into effective elements, she divides it into personal beings of peculiar character. . . . ‘Herr Pastor, sure there be a horse inside,’ called out the peasants to X after their spiritual shepherd had spent hours in explaining to them the construction of the locomotive. With a horse inside truly everything becomes clear, even though it be a queer enough sort of horse—the horse itself calls for no explanation! Phrenology takes a start to get beyond the point of view of the ghost-like soul entity, but she ends by populating the whole skull with ghosts of the same order.” * Modern Science conceives of the matter in a very differ- ent way. Brain and mind alike consist of simple elements, sensory and motor. ‘ Allnervous centres,” says Dr. Hugh- lings Jackson,+ “from the lowest to the very highest (the * Geschichte des Materialismus, 2d ed., 1. p. 345. + West Riding Asylum Reports, 1876, p. 267. 30 PSYCHOLOG Y. substrata of consciousness), are made up of nothing else than nervous arrangements, representing impressions and movements. ...I do not see of what other materials the brain can be made.” Meynert represents the matter similarly when he calls the cortex of the hemispheres the surface of projection for every muscle and every sensitive point of the body. The muscles and the sensitive points are represented each by a cortical point, and the brain is nothing but the sum of all these cortical points, to which, on the mental side, as many ideas correspond. Ideas of sensation, ideas of motion are, on the other hand, the ele- mentary factors out of which the mind is built up by the associationists in psychology. ‘There is a complete parallel- ism between the two analyses, the same diagram of little dots, circles, or triangles joined by lines symbolizes equally well the cerebral and mental processes: the dots stand for cells or ideas, the lines for fibres or associations. We shall have later to criticise this analysis so far as it relates to the mind; but there is no doubt that it is a most convenient, and has been a most useful, hypothesis, formulating the facts in an extremely natural way. If, then, we grant that motor and sensory ideas variously associated are the materials of the mind, all we need do to get a complete diagram of the mind’s and the brain’s relations should be to ascertain which sensory idea corresponds to which sensational surface of projection, and which motor idea to which muscular surface of projection. The associa- tions would then correspond to the fibrous connections be- tween the various surfaces. This distinct cerebral localization of the various elementary sorts of idea has been treated as a ‘postulate’ by many physiologists (e.g. Munk); and the most stirring controversy in nerve-physiology which the present generation has seen has been the localization- question. THE LOCALIZATION OF FUNCTIONS IN THE HEMISPHERES. Up to 1870, the opinion which prevailed was that which the experiments of Flourens on pigeons’ brains had made plausible, namely, that the different functions of the hemi- FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 31 spheres were not locally separated, but carried on each by the aid of the whole organ. MHitzig in 1870 showed, how- ever, that in a dog’s brain highly specialized movements could be produced by electric irritation of determinate regions of the cortex ; and Ferrier and Munk, half a dozen years later, seemed to prove, either by irritations or excis- ions or both, that there were equally determinate regions connected with the senses of sight. touch, hearing, and smell. Munk’s special sensorial localizations, however, disagreed with Ferrier’s; and Goltz, from his extirpation- experiments, came to a conclusion adverse to strict local- ization of any kind. The controversy is not yet over. I will not pretend to say anything more of it historically, but give a brief account of the condition in which matters at present stand. The one thing which is perfectly well established is this, that the ‘central’ convolutions, on either side of the fissure of Rolando, and (at least in the monkey) the calloso-marginal convolution (which is continuous with them on the mesial surface where one hemisphere is applied against the other), form the region by which all the motor incitations which leave the cortex pass out, on their way to those executive centres in the region of the pons, medulla, and spinal cord from which the muscular contractions are discharged in the last resort. The existence of this so-called ‘motor zone’ is established by the lines of evidence successively given below : (1) Cortical Irritations. Electrical currents of small intensity applied to the surface of the said convolutions in dogs, monkeys, and other animals, produce well-defined movements in face, fore-limb, hind-limb, tail, or trunk, according as one point or another of the surface is irritated. These movements affect almost invariably the side opposite to the brain irritations : If the left hemisphere be excited, the movement is of the right leg, side of face, etc. All the objec- tions at first raised against the validity of these experiments have been overcome. The movements are certainly not due to irritations of the base of the brain by the downward spread of the current, for: a) mechanical irritations will produce them, though less easily than electrical; 6) shifting the 32 PSYCHOLOGY. electrodes to a point close by on the surface changes the movement in ways quite inexplicable by changed physical conduction of the current; c) if the cortical ‘centre’ for a certain movement be cut under with a sharp knife but left in situ, although the electric conductivity is physically unaltered by the operation, the physiological conductivity is gone and currents of the same strength no longer pro- duce the movemen’s which they did; d) the time-interval between the application of the electric stimulus to the cor- tex and the resultant movement is what it would be if the cortex acted physiologically and not merely physically in transmitting the irritation. It is namely a well-known fact that when a nerve-current has to pass through the spinal cord to excite a muscle by refiex action, the time is longer than if it passes directly down the motor nerve: the cells of the cord take a certain time to discharge. Similarly, when a stimulus is applied directly to the cortex the muscle contracts two or three hundredths of a second later than it does when the place on the cortex is cut away and the elec- trodes are applied to the white fibres below.* (2) Cortical Ablations. When the cortical spot which is found to produce a movement of the fore-leg, in a dog, is excised (see spot 5 in Fig. 5), the leg in question becomes peculiarly affected. Atfirstitseems paralyzed. Soon, how- ever, it is used with the other legs, but badly. The animal does not bear his weight on it, allows it to rest on its dorsal surface, stands with it crossing the other leg, does not remove it if it hangs over the edge of a table, can no longer ‘give the paw’ at word of command if able to do so before the opera- tion, does not use it for scratching the ground, or holding a bone as formerly, lets it slip out when running on a smooth * For a thorough discussion of the various objections, see Ferrier’s ‘Functions of the Brain,’ 2d ed., pp. 227-234. and Francois-Franck’s ‘Lecons sur les Fonctions Motrices du Cerveau ’ (1887), Legon 31. The most minutely accurate experiments on irritation of cortical points are those of Paneth, in Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol 37, p. 528.—Recently the skull has been fearlessly opened by surgeons, and operations upon the human brain per- formed, sometimes with the happiest results. In some of these operations the cortex has been electrically excited for the purpose of more exactly localizing the spot, and the movements first observed in dogs and monkeys have then been verified in men. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 33 surface or when shaking himself, etc., etc. Sensibility of all kinds seems diminished as well as motility, but of this I shall speak later on. Moreover the dog tends in voluntary movements to swerve towards the side of the brain-lesion in- stead of going straightforward. All these symptoms gradu- ally decrease, so that even with a very severe brain-lesion the dog may be outwardly indistinguishable from a well dog after eight or ten weeks. Still, a sight chloroformization will reproduce the disturbances, even then. There is a cer- tain appearance of ataxic in-coérdination in the movements —the dog lifts his fore-feet high and brings them down with more strength than usual, and yet the trouble is not ordi- Fig. 5.—Left Hemisphere of Dog’s Brain, after Ferrier. A. the fissure of Sylvius. B, the crucial sulcus. O, the olfactory bulb. J, IJ, III, IV, indicate the first, second, third, and fourth external convolutions respectively. (1), (4), and (5) are on the sigmoid gyrus. nary lack of co-ordination. Neither is there paralysis. The strength of whatever movements are made is as great as ever—dogs with extensive destruction of the motor zone can jump as high and bite as hard as ever they did, but they seem less easily moved to do anything with the affected parts. Dr. Loeb, who has studied the motor disturbances of dogs more carefully than any one, conceives of them en masse as effects of an increased inertia in al] the processes of innervation towards the side opposed to tbe lesion. All such movements require an unwonted effort for their exe- cution; and when only the normally usual effort is made they fall behind in effectiveness.* * J. Loeb: ‘ Beitriige zur Physiologie des Grosshirns; Pfliiger’s Ar- chiv, xxxix. 293. I simplify the author’s statement. 34 PSYCHOLOGY. Even when the entire motor zone of a dog is removed, there is no permanent paralysis of any part, but only this curious sort of relative inertia when the two sides of the body are compared; and this itself becomes hardly notice- able after a number of weeks have elapsed. Prof. Goltz has described a dog whose entire left hemisphere was de- stroyed, and who retained only a slight motor inertia on the right half of the body. In particular he could use his right Z ON foo BG gAiiPVEMENTS OF ay WG A AND E0or 065 Page ACs es : SS =". °° RETRACAYTION ~ “s §, PROTRACTION . sae PLATYSMA Ly Fie. 6.—Left Hemisphere of Monkey’s Brain. Outer Surface. paw for holding a bone whilst gnawing it, or for reaching after a piece of meat. Had he been taught to give his paw before the operations, it would have been curious to see whether that faculty also came back. His tactile sensi- bility was permanently diminished on the right side.* In monkeys a genuine paralysis follows upon ablations of the cortex in the motor region. This paralysis affects parts of the body which vary with the brain-parts removed. The monkey’s opposite arm or leg hangs flaccid, or at most takes a small part in associated movements. When the entire region is removed there is a genuine and permanent hemiplegia in which the arm is more affected than the leg; and this is * Goltz: Pfliiger’s Archiv, x11. 419. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 35 followed months later by contracture of the muscles, as in man after inveterate hemiplegia.* According to Schaefer and Horsley, the trunk-muscles also become paralyzed after destruction of the marginal convolution on both sides (see Fig. 7). These differences between dogs and monkeys show the danger of drawing general conclusions from experiments done on any one sort of animal. I subjoin the figures given by the last-named authors of the motor regions in the monkey’s brain.t OVEMENTS Offre xion AT en TOES AND / KNEE MS NGS] AT aT oy, is FOOT, LE wip _/MOVEMENTS if Gutej OF RoTATIO; 1D LAT. Le TAIL ano Fig. 7.—Left Hemisphere of Monkey’s Brain. Mesial Surface. In man we are necessarily reduced to the observation post-mortem of cortical ablations produced by accident or disease (tumor, hemorrhage, softening, etc.). What results during life from such conditions is either localized spasm, or palsy of certain muscles of the opposite side. The cor- tical regions which invariably produce these results are homologous with those which we have just been study- ing in the dog, cat, ae, etc. Figs. 8 and 9 show the result of * «Hemiplegia’ means one-sided palsy. ¢ Philosophical Transactions, vol. 179, pp. 6. 10 (1888). In a later paper (id. p. 205) Messrs. Beevor and Horsley go into the localization still more minutely, showing spots from which single muscles or single digits can be made to contract. 36 PSYCHOLOG ¥Y. 169 cases carefully studied by Exner. The parts shaded are regions where lesions produced no motor disturbance. Fic. 8.—Right Hemisphere of Human Brain, Lateral Surface. Those left white were, on the contrary, never injured with- out motor disturbances of some sort. Where the injury to \\\ VV auLSQULANLVNVUUANUUNNNH \ rear, Mesial Surface. Fic. 9.—Right Hemisphere of Human Brain. the cortical substance is profound in man, the paralysis is ’ a permanent and is succeeded by muscular rigidity in the paralyzed parts, just as it may be in the monkey. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 37 (3) Descending degenerations show the intimate connec- tion of the rolandic regions of the cortex with the motor tracts of the cord. When, either in man or in the lower‘ani- mals, these regions are destroyed, a peculiar degenerative change known as secondary sclerosis is found to extend downwards through the white fibrous substance of the brain in a perfectly definite manner, affecting certain dis- tinct strands which pass through the inner capsule, crura, and pons, into the anterior pyramids of the medulla oblon- gata, and from thence (partly crossing to the other side) downwards into the anterior (direct) and lateral (crossed). columns of the spinal cord. (4) Anatomical proof of the continuity of the rolandic: regions with these motor columns of the cord is also clearly given. Flechsig’s ‘Pyramidenbahn’ forms an uninter- rupted strand (distinctly traceable in human embryos, before its fibres have acquired their white ‘medullary sheath’) passing upwards from the pyramids of the me- dulla, and traversing the internal capsule and corona radi- ata to the convolutions in question (Fig. 10). None of the inferior gray matter of the brain seems to have any connec- tion with this important fibrous strand. It passes directly from the cortex to the motor arrangements in the cord, de- pending for its proper nutrition (as the facts of degenera- tion show) on the influence of the cortical cells, just as motor nerves depend for their nutrition on that of the cells of the spinal cord. Electrical stimulation of this motor strand in any accessible part of its course has been shown in dogs to produce movements analogous to those which excitement of the cortical surface calls forth. One of the most instructive proofs of motor localization in the cortex is that furnished by the disease now called aphemia, or motor Aphasia. Motor aphasia is neither loss of voice nor paralysis of the tongue or lips. The patient’s voice is as strong as ever, and all the innervations of his hypoglossal and facial nerves, except those necessary for speaking, may go on perfectly well. He can laugh and cry, and even sing; but he either is unable to utter any words at all; ora few meaningless stock phrases form his only speech ; or else he speaks incoherently and confusedly, mispronounc- 38 PSYCHOLOG ¥. ing, misplacing, and misusing his words in various degrees, Sometimes his speech is a mere broth of unintelligible syl- lables. In cases of pure motor aphasia the patient recog- Cortica/ : , end SS *, SS SQ ) - C5 b, S ! \ &%, % In », %. | N Sy i Ip SN \ Be a ® pe Q 1» an St! SS 4 7) \\ Ady iil asta : LPO TT Sh RH Fic. 10.—Sehematic Transverse Rection of Brain showing Motor Strand.—After Edinger. N spinal nizes his mistakes and suffers acutely from them. Now whenever a patient dies in such a condition as this, and an examination of his brain is permitted, it is found that FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 39 the lowest frontal gyrus (see Fig. 11) is the seat of injury. Brocea first noticed this fact in 1861, and since then the gyrus has gone by the name of Broca’s convolution. The eo Fig. 11.—Schematic Profile of Left Hemisphere, with the parts shaded whose destruction causes motor (¢ Broca’) and sensory (‘ Wernicke *) Aphasia. injury in right-handed people is found on the left hemi- sphere, and in left-handed people on the right hemisphere. Most people, in fact, are left-brained, that is, all their delicate and specialized movements are handed over to the charge of the left hemisphere. The ordinary right- handedness for such movements is only a consequence of that fact, a consequence which shows outwardly on account of that extensive decussation of the fibres whereby most of those from the left hemisphere pass to the right half of the body only. But the left-brainedness might exist in equal measure and not show outwardly. This would happen wherever organs on both sides of the body could be goy- erned by the left hemisphere ; and just such a case seems offered by the vocal organs, in that highly delicate and special motor service which we call speech. Either hemi- sphere can innervate them bilaterally, just as either seems able to innervate bilaterally the muscles of the trunk, ribs, and diaphragm. Of the special movements of speech, how- 40 PSYCHOLOGY. ever, it would appear (from the facts of aphasia) that the left hemisphere in most persons habitually takes exclusive charge. With that hemisphere thrown out of gear, speech is undone ; even though the opposite hemisphere still be there for the performance of less specialized acts, such as the various movements required in eating. It will be noticed that Broca’s region is homologous with the parts ascertained to produce movements of the lips, tongue, and larynx when excited by electric currents in apes (cf. Fig. 6, p. 34). The evidence is therefore as com- plete as it well can be that the motor incitations to these organs leave the brain by the lower frontal region. Victims of motor aphasia generally have other disorders. One which interests us in this connection has been called agraphia: they have lost the power to write. They can read writing and understand it; but either cannot use the pen at all or make egregious mistakes with it. The seat of the lesion here is less well determined, owing to an in- sufficient number of good cases to conclude from.* There is no doubt, however, that it is (in right-handed people) on the left side, and little doubt that it consists of elements of the hand-and-arm region specialized for that service. The symptom may exist when there is little or no disability in the hand for other uses. If it does not get well, the ‘patient usually educates his right hemisphere, ie. learns to write with his left hand. In other cases of which we shall say more a few pages later on, the patient can write both spontaneously and at dictation, but cannot read even what he has himself written! All these phenomena are now quite clearly explained by separate brain-centres for the various feelings and movements and tracts for associat- ing these together. But their minute discussion belongs to inedicine rather than to general psychology, and I can only use them here to illustrate the principles of motor locali- zation.t Under the heads of sight and hearing I shall have a little more to say. * Nothnagel und Naunyn ; Die Localization in den Gehirnkrankheiten (Wiesbaden, 1887), p. 34. + An accessible account of the history of our knowledge of motor aphasia is in W. A. Hammond’s ‘ Treatise on the Diseases of the Nervous System,’ chapter VII. a FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 41 The different lines of proof which I have taken up establish conclusively the proposition that all the motor impulses which leave the cortex pass out, in healthy animals, from the convolutions about the fissure of Rolando. When, however, it comes to defining precisely what is involved in a motor impulse leaving the cortex, things grow more obscure. Does the impulse start independently from the convolutions in question, or does it start elsewhere and merely flow through? And to what particular phase of psychic activity does the activity of these centres corre- spond? Opinions and authorities here divide; but it will be better, before entering into these deeper aspects of the problem, to cast a glance at the facts which have been made out concerning the relations of the cortex to sight, hearing, and smell. Sight. Ferrier was the first in the field here. He found, when the anguwar convolution (that lying between the ‘intra parietal’ and ‘external occipital’ fissures, and bending round the top of the fissure of Sylvius, in Fig. 6) was ex- cited in the monkey, that movements of the eyes and head as if for vision occurred ; and that when it was extirpated, what he supposed to be total and permanent blindness of the opposite eye followed. Munk almost immediately declared total and permanent blindness to follow from de- struction of the occipital lobe in monkeys as well as dogs, and said that the angular gyrus had nothing to do with sight, but was only the centre for tactile sensibility of the eyeball. Munk’s absolute tone about his observations and his theo- retic arrogance have led to hisruinas anauthority. But he did two things of permanent value. He was the first to distinguish in these vivisections between sensorial and psychic blindness, and to describe the phenomenon of rest?- tution of the visual function after its first impairment by an operation ; and the first to notice the hemiopic character of the visual disturbances which result when only one hemisphere is injured. Sensorial blindness is absolute insensibility to light; psychic blindness is inability to rec- ognize the meaning of the optical impressions, as when we 42 PSYCHOLOGY. see a page of Chinese print but it suggests nothing to us, A hemiopic disturbance of vision is one in which neither retina is affected in its totality, but in which, for example, the left portion of each retina is blind, so that the animal sees nothing situated in space towards its right. Later observations have corroborated this hemiopic character of all the disturbances of sight from injury to a single hemi- sphere in the higher animals; and the question whether an animal’s apparent blindness is sensorial or only psychic has, since Munk’s first publications, been the most urgent one to answer, in all observations relative to the function of sight. Goltz almost simultaneously with Ferrier and Munk reported experiments which led him to deny that the visual function was essentially bound up with any one localized portion of the hemispheres. Other divergent results soon came in from many quarters, so that, without going into the history of the matter any more, I may report the existing state of the case as follows :* In fishes, frogs, and lizards vision persists when the hemispheres are entirely removed. This is admitted for frogs and fishes even by Munk, who denies it for birds. All of Munk’s birds seemed totally blind (blind senso- rially) after removal of the hemispheres by his operation. The following of a candle by the head and winking at a threatened blow, which are ordinarily held to prove the retention of crude optical sensations by the lower centres in supposed hemisphereless pigeons, are by Munk ascribed to vestiges of the visual sphere of the cortex left behind by the imperfection of the operation. But Schrader, who operated after Munk and with every apparent guarantee of completeness, found that all his pigeons saw after two or three weeks had elapsed, and the inhibitions resulting from the wound had passed away. They invariably avoided even the slightest obstacles, flew very regularly towards certain perches, etc., differing toto celo in these respects with certain simply blinded pigeons who were kept with * The history up to 1885 may be found in A. Christiani: Zur Physi- ologie des Gehirnes (Berlin, 1855). FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 43 them for comparison. They did not pick up food strewn on the ground, however. Schrader found that they would do this if even a small part of the frontal region of the hemispheres was left, and ascribes their non-self-feeding when deprived of their occipital cerebrum not to a visual, but to a motor, defect, a sort of alimentary aphasia.* In presence of such discord as that between Munk and his opponents one must carefully note how differently sig- nificant is loss, from preservation, of a function after an opera- tion on the brain. The loss of the function does not neces- sarily show that it 72s dependent on the part cut out; but its preservation does show that it is not dependent: and this is true though the loss should be observed ninety-nine times and the preservation only once ina hundred similar excisions. That birds and mammals can be blinded by cortical abla- tion is undoubted; the only question is, must they be so? Only then can the cortex be certainly called the ‘seat of sight.’ The blindness may always be due to one of those remote effects of the wound on distant parts, inhibitions, extensions of inflammation,—interferences, in a word,— upon which Brown-Séquard and Goltz have rightly insisted, and the importance of which becomes more manifest every day. Such effects are transient; whereas the symptoms of deprivation (Ausfallserscheinungen, as Goltz calls them) which come from the actual loss of the cut-out region must from the nature of the case be permanent. Blindness in the pigeons, so far as it passes away, cannot possibly be charged to their seat of vision being lost, but only to some influence which temporarily depresses the activity of that seat. The same is true mutatis mutandis of all the other effects of operations, and as we pass to mammals we shall see still more the importance of the remark. In rabbits loss of the entire cortex seems compatible with the preservation of enough sight to guide the poor animals’ movements, and enable them to avoid obstacles. Christiani’s observations and discussions seem conclusively * Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 44, p. 176. Munk (Berlin Academy Sitzsungs- berichte, 1859, xxx) returns to the charge, denying the extirpations of Schrader to be complete: ‘‘ Microscopic portions of the Sehsphire must remain.” 44 PSYCHOLOGY. to have established this, although Munk found that all his animals were made totally blind.* In dogs also Munk found absolute stone-blindness after ablation of the occipital lobes. He went farther and mapped out determinate portions of the cortex thereupon, which he considered correlated with definite segments of the two retin, so that destruction of given portions of the cor- tex produces blindness of the retinal centre, top, bottom, or right or left side, of the same or opposite eye. There seems little doubt that this definite correlation is mythologi- eal. Other observers, Hitzig, Goltz, Luciani, Loeb, Exner, etc., find, whatever part of the cortex may be ablated on one side, that there usually results a hemiopic disturbance of both eyes, slight and transient when the anterior lobes are the parts attacked, grave when an occipital lobe is the seat of injury, and lasting in proportion to the latter’s extent. According to Loeb, the defect is a dimness of vis- ion (‘hemiamblyopia’) in which (however severe) the centres remain the best seeing portions of the retina, just as they are in normal dogs. The lateral or temporal part of each retina seems to be in exclusive connection with the cortex of its own side. The centre and nasal part of each seems, on the contrary, to be connected with the cortex of the opposite hemispheres. Loeb, who takes broader views than any one, conceives the hemiamblyopia as he con- ceives the motor disturbances, namely, as the expression of an increased inertia in the whole optical machinery, of which the result is to make the animal respond with greater effort to impressions coming from the half of space opposed to the side of the lesion. Ifa dog has right hemiamblyopia, say, and two pieces of meat are hung before him at once, he invariably turns first to the one on his left. But if the lesion be a slight one, shaking slightly the piece of meat on his right (this makes of it a stronger stimulus) makes him seize upon it first. If only one piece of meat be offered, he takes it, on whichever side it be. When both occipital lobes are extensively destroyed total blindness may result. Munk maps out his ‘Seh- * A. Christiani: Zur Physiol. d. Gehirnes (Berlin, 1885),chaps. 1, rT, Iv. H. Munk: Berlin Akad. Stzgsb. 1884, xxiv. ———————— =) ee FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 45 sphare’ definitely, and says that blindness must result when the entire shaded part, marked A, 4, in Figs. 12 and 13, is involved in the lesion. Discrepant reports | of other observations he explains as due to incomplete Fie. 12. Fie. 13. The Dog’s visual centre according to Munk, the entire striated region, A, A, being the exclusive seat of vision, and the dark central circle, A’, being correlated with the retinal centre of the opposite eye. ablation. Luciani, Goltz, and Lannegrace, however, con- tend that they have made complete bilateral extirpations of Munk’s Sehsphire more than once, and found a sort of crude indiscriminating sight of objects to return in a few weeks.* The question whether a dog is blind or not is harder to solve than would at first appear; for simply blinded dogs, in places to which they are accustomed, show little of their loss and avoid all obstacles; whilst dogs whose occipital lobes are gone may run against things fre- quently and yet see notwithstanding. The best proof that they may see is that which Goltz’s dogs furnished: they carefully avoided, as it seemed, strips of sunshine or paper on the floor, as if they were solid cbstacles. This no really blind dog would do. Luciani tested his dogs when hungry (a condition which sharpens their attention) by strewing * Luciani und Seppili: Die Functions-Localization auf der Grosshirn- rinde (Deutsch von Fraenkel), Leipzig, 1886, Dogs M, N, and$. Goltz in Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 34, pp. 490-6; vol. 42, p. 454. Cf. also Munk: Berlin Akad. Stzgsb. 1886, vir, vir, pp. 113-121, and Loeb: Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 39, p. 337. 46 PSYCHOLOGY. pieces of meat and pieces of cork before them. If they went straight at them, they saw; and if they chose the meat and left the cork, they saw discriminatingly. The quarrel is very acrimonious; indeed the subject of localization of functions in the brain seems to have a peculiar effect on the temper of those who cultivate it experimentally. The amount of preserved vision which Goltz and Luciani report seems hardly to be worth considering, on the one hand; and on the other, Munk admits in his penultimate paper that out of 85 dogs he only ‘succeeded’ 4 times in his opera- tion of pr fee complete blindness by complete extirpa- tion of his ‘ Tenens. ** The safe conclusion for us is that Luciani’s diagram, Fig. 14, represents something like the Fig. 14.—Distribution of the Visual Function in the Cortex, according to Luciani. truth. The occipital lobes are far more important for vision than any other part of the cortex, so that their com- plete destruction makes the animal almost blind. As for the crude sensibility to light which may then remain, noth- ing exact is known either about its nature or its seat. In the monkey, doctors also disagree. The truth seems, however, to be that the occipital lobes in this animal also are the part connected most intimately with the visual function. The function would seem to go on when very small portions of them are left, for Ferrier found no ‘appreciable impair- ment’ of it after almost complete destruction of them on both sides. On the other hand, he found complete and perma- nent blindness to ensue when they and the angular gyri in addition were destroyed on both sides. Munk, as well as * Berlin Akad. Sitzungsberichte, 1886, vi, vu, p. 124. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 47 Brown and Schaefer, found no disturbance of sight from destroying the angular gyri alone, although Ferrier found blindness to ensue. This blindness was probably due to inhibitions exerted in distans, or to cutting of the white optical fibres passing under the angular gyri on their way to the occipital lobes. Brown and Schaefer got complete and permanent blindness in one monkey from total destruc- tion of both occipital lobes. Luciani and Seppili, perform- ing this operation on two monkeys, found that the animals were only mentally, not sensorially, blind. After some weeks they saw their food, but could not distinguish by sight between figs and pieces of cork. Luciani and Seppili seem, however, not to have extirpated the entire lobes. When one lobe only is injured the affection of sight is hemiopic in monkeys: in this all observers agree. On the whole, then, Munk’s original location of vision in the occipital lobes is confirmed by the later evidence.* In man we have more exact results, since we are not driven to interpret the vision from the outward conduct. On the other hand, however, we cannot vivisect, but must wait for pathological lesions to turn up. The pathologists who have discussed these (the literature is tedious ad libi- tum) conclude that the occipital lobes are the indispensable part for vision inman. Hemiopic disturbance in both eyes comes from lesion of either one of them, and total blindness, sensorial as well as psychic, from destruction of both. Hemiopia may also result from lesion in other parts, especially the neighboring angular and supra-marginal gyri, and it may accompany extensive injury in the motor region of the cortex. In these cases it seems probable that it is due to an actio in distans, probably to the interruption of * H. Munk: Functionen der Grosshirnrinde (Berlin, 1881), pp. 36-40. Ferrier : Functions, etc., 2ded., chap. rx, pt. 1. Brown and Schaefer: Philos. Transactions, vol. 179, p. 321. Luciani u. Seppili, op. cit. pp. 131-138. Lannegrace found traces of sight with both occipital lobes de- stroyed, and in one monkey even when angular gyri and occipital lobes were destroyed altogether. His paper is in the Archives de Médecine Expérimentale for January and March, 1889. I only know it from the abstract in the Neurclogisches Centralblatt, 1889, pp. 108-420. The reporter doubts the evidence of vision in the monkey. It appears to have consisted in avoiding obstacles and in emotional disturbance in the presence of men, 48 PSYCHOLOG ¥. fibres proceeding from the occipital lobe. There seem te be a few cases on record where there was injury to the occipital lobes without visual defect. Ferrier has collected as many as possible to prove his localization in the angular gyrus.* A strictapplication of logical principles would make one of these cases outweigh one hundred contrary ones. And yet, remembering how imperfect observations may be, and how individual brains may vary, it would certainly be rash for their sake to throw away the enormous amount of positive evidence for the occipital lobes. Individual variability is always a possible explanation of an anomalous case. There is no more prominent anatomical fact than that of the ‘de- cussation of the pyramids,’ nor any more usual pathologi- cal fact than its consequence, that left-handed hemorrhages into the motor region produce right-handed paralyses. And yet the decussation is variable in amount, and seems sometimes to be absent altogether.t If, in such a case as this last, the left brain were to become the seat of apoplexy, the left and not the right half of the body would be the one to suffer paralysis. The schema on the opposite page, copied from Dr. Seguin, expresses, on the whole, the probable truth about the regions concerned in vision. Not the entire occipital lobes, but the so-called cunei, and the first convolutions, are the cortical parts most intimately concerned. Nothnagel agrees with Seguin in this limitaticn of the essential tracts. A most interesting effect of cortical disorder is mental blindness. This consists not so much in insensibility to optical impressions, as in inability to understand them. Psychologically it is interpretable as loss of associations be- tween optical sensations and what they signify; and any interruption of the paths between the optic centres and the centres for other ideas ought to bring it about. Thus, * Localization of Cerebral Disease (1878), pp. 117-8. + For cases see Flechsig : Die Leitungsbahnen in Gehirn u. Riickenmark (Leipzig, 1876), pp. 112, 272; Exner’s Untersuchungen, etc., p. 83 ; Ferrier s Localization, etc., p. 11; Francois-Franck’s Cerveau Moteur, p. 63, note. t E. C. Seguin: Hemianopsia of Cerebral Origin, in Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, vol. x1. p. 80. Nothnagel und Naunyn: Ueber die Localization der Gehirnkrankheiten (Wiesbaden, 1887), p. 10. OO ee FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 49 printed letters of the alphabet, or words, signify certain sounds and certain articulatory movements. If the con- nection between the articulating or auditory centres, on the one hand, and the visual centres on the other, be ruptured, [ES TOGN ES R.N.F \ (| Nl ( ye \ T \ \ o \ 7. \ i lms P.0-G- 105 bo. Fic. 15.—Scheme of the mechanism of vision, after Seguin. The cuneus convolution (Cu) of the right occipital lobe is supposed to be injured, and all the parts which lead to it are darkly shaded to show that they fail to exert their function. FO. are the intra-hemispheric optical fibres. P.O. C. is the region of the lower optic cen- tres (corpora geniculata and quadrigemina). T. O. D. is the right optic tract; C, the chiasma; F’. L. D. are the fibres going to the lateral or temporal half T of the right retina; and F’. C. S. are those going to the central or nasal half of the left retina. O. D. is the right, and O. S. the left eyeball. The rightward half of each is there- fore blind: in other words, the right nasal field, R. N. F., and the left temporal field, L. T. F., have become invisible to the subject with the lesion at Cu. we ought a priori to expect that the sight of words would fail to awaken the idea of their sound, or the movement for pronouncing them. We ought, in short, to have alexia, or inability to read : and this is just what we do have in many 50 FSYCHOLOG ¥. cases of extensive injury about the fronto-temporal regions, as a complication of aphasic disease. Nothnagel suggests that whilst the cuneus is the seat of optical sensations, the other parts of the occipital lobe may be the field of optical memories and ideas, from the loss of which mental blind- ness should ensue. In fact, all the medical authors speak of mental blindness as if it must consist in the loss of visual images from the memory. It seems to me, however, that this is a psychological misapprehension. A man whose power of visual imagination has decayed (no unusual phe- nomenon in its lighter grades) is not mentally blind in the least, for he recognizes perfectly all that he sees. On the other hand, he may be mentally blind, with his optical imagination well preserved ; as in the interesting case pub- lished by Wilbrand in 1887.* In the still more interest- ing case of mental blindness recently published by Lissauer,t though the patient made the most ludicrous mistakes, call- ing for instance a clothes-brush a pair of spectacles, an um- brella a plant with flowers, an apple a portrait of a lady, ete. etc., he seemed, according to the reporter, to have his men- tal images fairly well preserved. It is in fact the momen- tary loss of our non-optical images which makes us mentally blind, just as itis that of our non-auditory images which makes us mentally deaf. I am mentally deaf if, hearing a bell, I can’t recall how it looks; and mentally blind if, see- ing it, I can’t recall its sound or its name. As a matter of fact, 1 should have to be not merely mentally blind, but stone-blind, if all my visual images were lost. For although I am blind to the right half of the field of view if my left occipital region is injured, and to the left half if my right region is injured, such hemianopsia does not deprive me of visual images, experience seeming to show that the unaffected hemisphere is always suflicient for pro- duction of these. To abolish them entirely I should have to be deprived of both occipital lobes, and that would de- prive me not only of my inward images of sight, but of my * Die Seelenblindheit, etc., p. 51 ff. The mental blindness was in this woman’s case moderate in degree. + Archiv f. Psychiatrie, vol. 21, p. 222. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 51 sight altogether.* Recent pathological annals seem to offer a few such cases.t Meanwhile there are a number of cases of mental blindness, especially for written language, coupled with hemianopsia, usually of the rightward field of view. These are all explicable by the breaking down, through disease, of the connecting tracts between the occipital lobes and other parts of the brain, especially those which go to the centres for speech in the frontal and temporal regions of the left hemisphere. They are to be classed among distur- bances of conduction or of association; and nowhere can I find any fact which should force us to believe that optical images need{ be lost in mental blindness, or that the cerebral centres for such images are locally distinct from those for direct sensations from the eyes. § Where an object fails to ‘be recognized by sight, it often happens that the patient will recognize and name it as soon as he touches it with his hand. This shows in an interest- * Nothnagel (doc. cit. p. 22) says: ‘‘ Dies trifft aber nicht zu.” He gives, however, no case in support of his opinion that double-sided cortical lesion may make one stone-blind and yet not destroy one’s visual images ; so tbat I do not know whether it is an observation of fact or an @ priori as- sumption. + In acase published by C. §. Freund: Archiv f. Psychiatrie, vol. xx, the occipital lobes were injured, but their cortex was not destroyed, on both sides. There was still vision. Cf. pp. 291-5. tI say ‘need,’ forI do not of course deny the possible coexistence of the twosymptoms. Many a brain-lesion might block optical associations and at the same time impair optical imagination, without entirely stopping vision. Such a case seems to have been the remarkable one from Charcot which I shall give rather fully in the chapter on Imagination. § Freund (in the article cited above ‘Ueber optische Aphasie und Seelenblindheit’) and Bruns (‘ Ein Fall von Alexie,’ etc., in the Neuro- logisches Centralblatt for 1888, pp. 581, 509) explain their cases by broken- down conduction. Wilbrand, whose painstaking monograph on mental blindness was referred to a moment ago, gives none but a prior? reasons for his belief that the optical ‘ Erinnerungsfeld’ must be locally distinct from the Wahrnehmungsfeld (cf. pp. 84, 93). The @ prior? reasons are really the other way. Mauthner (‘Gehirn u. Auge’ (1881), p. 487 ff.) tries to show that the ‘mental blindness’ of Munk’s dogsand apes after occipital mutila- tion was not such, but real dimness of sight. The best case of mental plindness yet reported is that by Lissauer, as above. The reader will also do well to read Bernard : De l’Aphasie (1885) chap. v: Ballet: Le Langage Intérieur (1886), chap. vir; and Jas. Ross’s little book on Aphasia (1887), p. 74. 52 PSYCHOLOGY. ing way how numerous the associative paths are which all end by running out of the brain through the channel of speech. The hand-path is open, though the eye-path be closed. When mental blindness is most complete, neither sight, touch, nor sound avails to steer the patient, and a sort of dementia which has been called asymbolia or aprawia is the result. The commonest articles are not understood. The patient will put his breeches on one shoulder and his hat upon tbe other, will bite into the soap and lay his shoes on the table, or take his food into his hand and throw it down again, not knowing what to do with it, etc. Such dis- order can only come from extensive brain-injury.* The method of degeneration corroborates the other evi- dence localizing the tracts of vision. In young animals one gets secondary degeneration of the occipital regions from destroying an eyeball, and, vice versa, degeneration of the optic nerves from destroying the occipital regions. The corpora geniculata, thalami, and subcortical fibres leading to the occipital lobes are also found atrophied in these cases. The phenomena are not uniform, but are indispu- table ;+ so that, taking all lines of evidence together, the special connection of vision with the occipital lobes is per- fectly made out. It should be added that the occipital lobes have frequently been found shrunken in cases of ia- veterate blindness in man. Hearing. Hearing is hardly as definitely localized as sight. In the dog, Luciani’s diagram will show the regions which directly or indirectly affect it for the worse when injured. As with sight, one-sided lesions produce symptoms on both sides. The mixture of black dots and gray dots in the diagram is meant to represent this mixture of ‘ crossed’ and ‘ uncrossed’ con- nections, though of course no topographical exactitude is aimed at. Of all the region, the temporal lobe is the most important part; yet permanent absolute deafness did not * For a case see Wernicke’s Lehrb. d. Gehirnkrankheiten, vol. 1. p. 554 (1881). he + The latest account of them is the paper ‘ Uber die optischen Centren u. Bahnen’ by von Monakow in the Archiv fiir Psychiatrie, vol. xx. p. 714, FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 53 result in a dog of Luciani’s, even from bilateral destruction of both temporal lobes in their entirety. * In the monkey, Ferrier and Yeo once found permanent deafness to follow destruction of the upper temporal con- volution (the one just below the fissure of Sylvius in Fig. Fie. 16.—Luciani’s Hearing Region. 6) on both sides. Brown and Schaefer found, on the con- trary, that in several monkeys this operation failed to notice- ably affect the hearing. In one animal, indeed, both entire temporal lobes were destroyed. After a week or two of depression of the mental faculties this beast recovered and became one of the brightest monkeys possible, domineering over all his mates, and admitted by all who saw him to have all his senses, including hearing, ‘ perfectly acute.’ t Terrible recriminations have, as usual, ensued between the investigators, Ferrier denying that Brown and Schaefer’s ablations were complete, t Schaefer that Ferrier’s monkey was really deaf. In this unsatisfactory condition the sub- ject must be left, although there seems no reason to doubt that Brown and Schaefer’s observation is the more important of the two. In man the temporal lobe is unquestionably the seat of the hearing function, and the superior convolution adjacent to the sylvian fissure is its most important part. The phe- nomena of aphasia show this. We studied motor aphasia a few pages back; we must now consider sensory aphasia. * Die Functions-Localization, etc., Dog X; see also p. 161. + Philos. Trans., vol. 179, p. 312. ¢ Brain, vol. xr. p. 10. § Ibid. p. 147. 54 PSYCHOLOGY. Our knowledge of this disease has had three stages: we may talk of the period of Broca, the period of Wernicke, and the period of Charcot. What Broca’s discovery was we have seen. Wernicke was the first to discriminate those cases in which the patient can not even understand speech from those in whick he can understand, only not talk; and to aseribe the former condition to lesion of the temporal lobe.* The condition in question is word-deafness, and the disease is auditory aphasia. The latest statistical survey of the subject is that by Dr. Allen Starr.+ In the seven cases of pure word-deafness which he has collected, cases in which the patient could read, talk, and write, but not understand what was said to him, the lesion was limited to the first and second temporal convolutions in their posterior two thirds. The lesion (in right-handed, i.e. left-brained, persons) is always on the left side, like the lesion in motor aphasia. Crude hearing would not be abolished, even were the left centre for it utterly destroyed; the right centre would still provide for that. But the linguistic use of hearing appears bound up with the integrity of the left centre more or less exclusively. Here it must be that words heard enter into association with the things which they represent, on the one hand, and with the movements necessary for pronouncing them, on the other. Ina large majority of Dr. Starr’s fifty cases, the power either to name objects or to talk coherently was impaired. This shows that in most of us (as Wernicke said) speech must go on from auditory cues; that is, it must be that our ideas do not innervate our motor centres directly, but only after first arousing the mental sound of the words. This is the immediate stimulus to articulation ; and where the possibility of this is abolished by the de- struction of its usual channel in the left temporal lobe, the articulation must suffer. In the few cases in which the channel is abolished with no bad effect on speech we must suppose an idiosyncrasy. The patient must innervate his speech-organs either from the corresponding portion of the other hemisphere or directly from the centres of ideation, * Der aphasische Symptomencomplex (1874). See in Fig. 11 the con- volution marked WERNICKE. ~ + ‘The Pathology of Sensory Aphasia,’ ‘ Brain,’ July, 1889. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 55 those, namely, of vision, touch, etc., without leaning on the auditory region. It is the minuter analysis of the facts in the light of such individual differences as these which con- stitutes Charcot’s contribution towards clearing up the subject. Every namable thing, act, or relation has numerous properties, qualities, or aspects. In our minds the proper- ties of each thing, together with its name, form an associated group. If different parts of the brain are severally con- cerned with the several properties, and a farther part with the hearing, and still another with the uttering, of the name, there must inevitably be brought about (through the law of association which we shall later study) such a dynamic connec- tion amongst all these brain-parts that the activity of any one of them wiJl be likely to awaken the activity of all the rest. When we are talking as we think, the wetimate process is that of utterance. If the brain-part for that be injured, speech is impossible or disorderly, even though all the other brain- parts be intact: and this is just the condition of things which, on page 37, we found to be brought about by limited lesion of the left inferior frontal convolution. But back of that last act various orders of succession are possible in the associations of a talking man’s ideas. The more usual order seems to be from the tactile, visual, or other properties of the things thought-about to the sound of their names, and then to the latter’s utterance. But if in a certain individual the thought of the look of an object or of the look of its printed name be the process which habitually precedes articulation, then the loss of the hearing centre will pro tanto not affect that individual’s speech. He will be mentally deaf, i.e. his wnderstanding of speech will suffer, but he will not be aphasic. In this way it is possible to explain the seven cases of pure word-deaf- ness which figure in Dr. Starr’s table. If this order of association be ingrained and habitual in that individual, injury to his visual centres will make him not only word-blind, but aphasic as well. His speech will become confused in consequence of an occipital lesion. Naunyn, consequently, plotting out on a diagram of the hemisphere the 71 irreproachably reported cases of 56 PSYCHOLOGY. aphasia which he was able to collect, finds that the lesions concentrate themselves in three places: first, on Broca’s centre ; second, on Wernicke’s ; third, on the supra-marginal and angular gyri under which those fibres pass which con- nect the visual centres with the rest of the brain* (see F ig. 17). With this result Dr, Starr’s analysis of purely sensory cases agrees. jo) as . sz. oe ae Fie. 17 Ina later chapter we shall again return to these differences in the effectiveness of the sensory spheres in different individuals. Meanwhile few things show more beautifully than the history of our knowledge of aphasia how the sagacity and patience of many banded workers are in time certain to analyze the darkest confusion into an orderly display.t There is no ‘centre of Speech’ in the brain any more than there is a faculty of Speech in the mind. The entire brain, more or less, is at work in a man who uses language. The subjoined diagram, from Ross, shows the four parts most critically concerned, and, in the light of our text, needs no farther explanation (see Fig. 18). * Nothnagel und Naunyn: op. cit., plates. + Ballet’s and Bernard’s works cited on p. 51 are the most accessible documents of Charcot’s school. Bastian’s book on the Brain as an Organ of Mind (last three chapters) is also good. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 57 Smell. Everything conspires to point to the median descending part of the temporal lobes as being the organs of smell, Even Ferrier and Munk agree on the hippocampal gyrus, Fia. 18, though Ferrier restricts olfaction, as Munk does not, to the lobule or uncinate process of the convolution, reserving the rest of it for touch. Anatomy and pathology also point to the hippocampal gyrus; but as the matter is less interest- ing from the point of view of human psychology than were sight and hearing, I will say no more, but simply add Luciani and Seppili’s diagram of the dog’s smell-centre.* Of * For details, see Ferrier’s ‘Functions,’ chap. rx. pt. 11, and Chas, K. Mills: Transactions of Congress of American Physicians and Sur geons, 1888, vol. I. p. 278. 58 PSYCHOLOG ¥. -—. Taste we know little that is definite. What little there is points to the lower temporal regions again. Consult Ferrier as below. Touch. Interesting problems arise with regard to the seat of tactile and muscular sensibility. Huitzig, whose experiments on dogs’ brains fifteen years ago opened the entire subject Fic. 19.—Luciani’s Olfactory Region in the Dog. which we are discussing, ascribed the disorders of motility observed after ablations of the motor region to a loss of what he called muscular consciousness. The animals do not notice eccentric positions of their limbs, will stand with their legs crossed, with the affected paw resting on its back or hanging over a table’s edge, etc.; and do not resist our bending and stretching of it as they resist with the un- affected paw. Goltz, Munk, Schiff, Herzen, and others. promptly ascertained an equal defect of cutaneous sensi- bility to pain, touch, and cold. The paw is not withdrawn when pinched, remains standing in cold water, ete. Fer- rier meanwhile denied that there was any true anesthesia produced by ablations in the motor zone, and explains the appearance of it as an effect of the sluggish motor responses of the affected side.* Munkt and Schiff }, on the * Functions of the Brain, chap. x. § 14. + Ueber die Functionen d. Grosshirnrinde (1881), p. 50 tLezioni di Fisioloria sperimentale sul sistema nervoso encefalico (1873), p. 527 ff. Also ‘Brain,’ vol. rx. p. 298. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 59 contrary, conceive of the ‘motor zone’ as essentially sen- sory, and in different ways explain the motor disorders as secondary results of the anesthesia which is always there. Munk calls the motor zone the Fiihlsphire of the animal’s limbs, ete., and makes it codrdinate with the Sehsphiire, the Horsphiire, etc., the entire cortex being, according to him, nothing but a projection-surface for sensations, with no exclusively or essentially motor part. Such a view would be important if true, through its bearings on the psychology of volition. What is the truth? As regards the fact of cutaneous anesthesia from motor-zone ablations, all other observers are against Ferrier, so that he is proba- bly wrong in denying it. On the other hand, Munk and Schiff are wrong in making the motor symptoms depend on the anesthesia, for in certain rare cases they have been observed to exist not only without insensibility, but with actual hyperesthesia of the parts.* The motor and sensory symptoms seem, therefore, to be independent variables. In monkeys the latest experiments are those of Horsley and Schaefer,+ whose results Ferrier accepts. They find that excision of the hippocampal convolution produces tran- sient insensibility of the opposite side of the body, and that permanent insensibility is produced by destruction of its continuation upwards above the corpus callosum, the so- called gyrus fornicatus (the part just below the ‘calloso- marginal fissure’ in Fig. 7). The insensibilityis at its maxi- mum when the entire tract comprising both convolutions is destroyed. Ferrier says that the sensibility of monkeys is ‘entirely unaffected’ by ablations of the motor zone,t and Horsley and Schaefer consider it by no means necessarily * Bechterew (Pfliiger’s Archiv., vol. 35, p. 187) found no anesthesia in a cat with motor symptoms from ablation of sigmoid gyrus. Luciani got hyperesthesia coexistent with cortical motor defect in a dog, by simulta- neously hemisecting the spinal cord (Luciani u. Seppili, op. czt. p. 284). Goltz frequently found hyperesthesia of the whole body to accompany motor defect after ablation of both frontal lobes, and he once found it after ablating the motor zone (Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 34, p. 471). + Philos. Transactions, vol. 179, p. 20 ff. ¢ Functions, p. 375. 60 PSYCHOLOGY. abolished.* Luciani found it diminished in his three ex. periments on apes.t In man we have the fact that one-sided paralysis from disease of the opposite motor zone may or may not be accompanied with anesthesia of the parts. Luciani, who Fie. 20.—Luciani’s Tactile Region in the Dog. believes that the motor zone is also sensory, tries to minim- ize the value of this evidence by pointing to the insufficiency with which patients are examined. He himself believes that in dogs the tactile sphere extends backwards and forwards of the directly excitable region, into the frontal and parietal lobes (see Fig. 20). Nothnagel considers that pathological evidence points in the same direction;+ and Dr. Mills, care- fully reviewing the evidence, adds the gyri fornicatus and hippocampi to the cutaneo-muscular region in man.§ If one compare Luciani’s diagrams together (Figs. 14, 16, 19, 20) one will see that the entire parietal region of the dog’s skull is common to the four senses of sight, hearing, smell, and touch, including muscular feeling. The corresponding re- gion in the human brain (upper parietal and supra-marginal gyri—see Fig. 17, p. 56) seems to be a somewhat similar place of conflux. Optical aphasias and motor and tactile disturbances all result from its injury, especially when that is on the left side.|| The lower we go in the animal scale the * Pp. 15-17. + Luciani u. Seppili, op. cit. pp. 275-288. LOD ctl pile: § Trans. of Congress, etc., p. 272. || See Exner’s Unters. iib. Localization, plate xxv. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 61 less differentiated the functions of the several brain-parts seem to be.* It may be that the region in question still represents in ourselves something like this primitive condi- tion, and that the surrounding parts, in adapting themselves more and more to specialized and narrow functions, have left it as a sort of carrefour through which they send cur- rents and converse. That it should be connected with musculo-cutaneous feeling is, however, no reason why the motor zone proper should not be so connected too. And the cases of paralysis from the motor zone with no accom- panying anesthesia may be explicable without denying all sensory function to that region. For, as my colleague Dr. James Putnam informs me, sensibility is always harder to kill than motility, even where we know for a certainty that the lesion affects tracts that are both sensory and motor. Persons whose hand is paralyzed in its movements from compression of arm-nerves during sleep, still feel with their fingers ; and they may still feel in their feet when their legs are paralyzed by bruising of the spinal cord. In a simi- lar way, the motor cortex might be sensitive as well as motor, and yet by this greater subtlety (or whatever the peculiarity may be) in the sensory currents, the sensibility might survive an amount of injury there by which the motility was destroyed. Nothnagel considers that there are grounds for supposing the muscular sense to be exclusively connected with the parietal lobe and not with the motor zone. “ Disease of this lobe gives pure ataxy without palsy, and of the motor zone pure palsy without loss of muscular sense.” + He fails, however, to convince more competent critics than the present writer,t so I conclude with them that as yet we have no decisive grounds for locating muscular and cutaneous feeling apart. Much still remains to be learned about the relations between musculo-cutaneous sensibility and the cortex, but one thing is certain: that neither the occipital, the forward frontal, nor the temporal lobes seem to have anything essential to do with it in man. * Cf. Ferrier’s Functions, etc., chap. tv and chap. x, §§ 6 to 9. + Op. cit. p. 17. ¢ E.g. Starr, loc. cit. p 272; Leyden, Beitrige zur Lehre v. d. Localiza- tion im Gehirn (1888), p. 72. 62 PSYCHOLOGY. It is knit up with the performances of the motor zone and of the convolutions backwards and midwards of them. ‘The reader must remember this conclusion when we come tc the chapter on the Will. I must add a word about the connection of aphasia with the tactile sense. On p. 40 I spoke of those cases in which the patient can write but not read his own writ- ing. He cannot read by his eyes; but he can read by the feeling in his fingers, if he retrace the letters in the air. It is convenient for such a patient to have a pen in hand whilst reading in this way, in order to make the usual feel- ing of writing more complete.* In such a case we must suppose that the path between the optical and the graphic centres remains open, whilst that between the optical and the auditory and articulatory centres is closed. Only thus can we understand how the look of the writing should fail to suggest the sound of the words to the patient’s mind, whilst it still suggests the proper movements of graphic imitation. These movements in their turn must of course be felt, and the feeling of them must be associated with the centres for hearing and pronouncing the words. The injury in cases like this where very special combinations fail, whilst others go on as usual, must always be supposed to be of the nature of increased resistance to the passage of certain currents of association. If any of the elements of mental function were destroyed the incapacity would necessarily be much more formidable. A patient who can both read and write with his fingers most likely uses an identical ‘graphic’ centre, at once sensory and motor, for both operations. I have now given, as far as the nature of this book will allow, a complete account of the present state of the locali- zation-question. In its main outlines it stands firm, though much has still to be discovered. The anterior frontal lobes, for example, so far as is yet known, have no definite functions. Goltz finds that dogs bereft of them both are incessantly in motion, and excitable by every small stimulus. They are * Bernard, op. cit. p. 84. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 63 irascible and amative in an extraordinary degree, and their sides grow bare with perpetual reflex scratching; but they show no local troubles of either motion or sensibility. In monkeys not even this lack of inhibitory ability is shown, and neither stimulation nor excision of the prefrontal lobes produces any sympwms whatever. One monkey of Horsley and Schaefer’s was as tame, and did certain tricks as well, after as before the operation.* It is probable that we have about reached the limits of what can be learned about brain- functions from vivisecting inferior animals, and that we must hereafter look more exclusively to human pathology for light. The existence of separate speech and writing centres in the left hemisphere in man; the fact that palsy from cortical injury is so much more complete and endur- ing in man and the monkey than in dogs; and the farther fact that it seems more difficult to get complete sens drial blindness from cortical ablations in the lower animals than in man, all show that functions get more specially local- ized as evolution goes on. In birds localization seems hardly to exist, and in rodents it is much less conspicuous than in carnivora. Even for man, however, Munk’s way of mapping out the cortex into absolute areas within which only one movement or sensation is represented is surely false. The truth seems to be rather that, although there is a correspondence of certain regions of the brain to certain regions of the body, yet the several parts within each bodily region are represented throughout the whole of the corre- sponding brain-region like pepper and salt sprinkled from the same caster. This, however, does not prevent each ‘part’ from having its focus at one spot within the brain- region. The various brain-regions merge into each other in the same mixed way. As Mr. Horsley says: “There are border centres, and the area of representation of the face merges into that for the representation of the upper limb. If there was a focal lesion at that point, you would have the movements of these two parts starting together.” + + Trans. of Congress of Am. Phys. and Surg. 1888, vol. I. p. 348. Beevor and Horsley’s paper on electric stimulation of the monkey’s brain is the most beautiful work yet done for precision. See Phil. Trans., vol. 179, p. 205, especially the plates. 64 PSYCHOLOG Y, The accompanying figure from Paneth shows just how the matter stands in the dog.* I am speaking now of localiza. tions breadthwise over the brain- surface. It is conceivable that there might be also localizations depthwise through the cortex. The more superficial cells are smaller, the deepest layer of them is large; and it has been suggested that the superficial cells are sensorial, the deeper ones motor;t or that the superficial ones in the motor region are correlated with the extremities of the organs to be moved (fingers, etc.), the deeper ones with the more central segments (wrist, elbow, etc.).{ It need hardly be said that all such theories are as yet but guesses. We thus see that the postulate of Meynert and Jackson which we started with cn p. 30 is on the whole most satisfactorily corroborated by subsequent objective research. tc The lighest centres do probably Fia. 21.—Dog’s motor centres, right contain nothing but arrangements hemisphere, according to Paneth. —The points of the motor region *omy , , 4 are correlated as follows Sith for ML esenting I and muscles: the loops with the orbi- movements, and other arrangements cularis palpebrarum; the plain 2 crosses with the flexor, the crosses : 1: inscribed in circles with ie ex- for coupling the activity of these tensor, digitorum communis of arrangements together.§ Currents the fore-paw; the plain circles : Z with the abductor pollicis pouring in from the sense-organs longus; the double crosses with 4 the extensor communis of the first excite some arrangements, hind-limb. * Ptliiger’s Archiv, vol. 37, p. 523 (1885). + By Luys in his generally preposterous book ‘The Brain’; also by Horsley ¢ C. Mercier: The Nervous System and the Mind, p. 124. § The frontal lobes as yet remain a puzzle. Wundt tries to explain them as an organ of ‘apperception’ (Grundziige d. Physiologischen Psychologie, 3d ed., vol. 1. p. 233 £.), but 1 confess myself unable to appre- hend clearly the Wundtian philosophy so far as this word enters into it, so must be contented with this bare reference.—Until quite recently it was FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 65 which in turn excite others, until at last a motor discharge downwards of some sort occurs. When this is once clearly grasped there remains little ground for keeping up that old controversy about the motor zone, as_ to whether it is in reality motor or sensitive. The whole cortex, inasmuch as currents run through it, is both. All the currents probably have feelings going with them, and sooner or later bring movements about. In one aspect, then, every centre is afferent, in another efferent, even the motor cells of the spinal cord having these two aspects insepara- bly conjoined. Marique,* and Exner and Panetht have shown that by cutting rownd a ‘motor’ centre and so sepa- rating it from the influence of the rest of the cortex, the same disorders are produced as by cutting it out, so that really it is only the mouth of the funnel, as it were, through which the stream of innervation, starting from else- where, pours ;{ consciousness accompanying the stream, and being mainly of things seen if the stream is strongest occipitally, of things heard if it is strongest temporally, of things felt, etc., if the stream occupies most intensely the ‘motor zone.’ It seems to me that some broad and vague formulation like this is as much as we can safely venture on in the present state of science; and in subsequent chapters I expect to give confirmatory reasons for my view. MAN’S CONSCIOUSNESS LIMITED TO THE HEMISPHERES. But is the consciousness which accompanies the activity of the cortex the only consciousness that man has ? or are his lower centres conscious as well ? This is a difficult question to decide, how difficult one only learns when one discovers that the cortex-conscious- ness itself of certain objects can be seemingly annihilated aggregate of other centres. Fortunately this custom is already on the wane. * Rech. Exp. sur le Fonctionnement des Centres Psycho-moteurs (Brus- sels, 1885). + Piliger’s Archiv, vol. 44, p. 544. $1 ought to add, however, that Francois-Franck (Fonctions Motrices, p. 870) got, in two dogs and a cat, a different result from this sort of ‘ cir: cumvallation.’ 66 PSYCHOLOGY. tor’s hand, and yet be proved by circumstantial evidence to exist all the while in a split-off condition, quite as ‘ ejective’* to the rest of the subject’s mind as that mind is to the mind of the bystanders.t The lower centres themselves may conceivably all the while have a split-off consciousness of their own, similarly ejective to the cortex-consciousness ; but whether they have it or not can never be known from merely introspective evidence. Meanwhile the fact that occipital destruction in man may cause a blindness which is apparently absolute (no feeling remaining either of light or dark over one half of the field of view), would lead us to suppose that if our lower optical centres, the corpora quadrigemina, and thalami, do have any consciousness, it is at all events a consciousness which does not mix with that which accompanies the cortical activities, and which has nothing to do with our personal Self. In lower animals this may not be so much the case. The traces of sight found (supra, p. 46) in dogs and monkeys whose occip- ital lobes were entirely destroyed, may possibly have been due to the fact that the lower centres of these animals saw, and that what they saw was not ejective but objective to the remaining cortex, ie. it formed part of one and the same inner world with the things which that cortex per- ceived. It may be, however, that the phenomena were due to the fact that in these animals the cortical ‘ centres’ for vision reach outside of the occipital zone, and that destruc- tion of the latter fails to remove them as completely as in man. This, as we know, is the opinion of the experiment- ers themselves. For practical purposes, nevertheless, and limiting the meaning of the word consciousness to the per- sonal self of the individual, we can pretty confidently answer the question prefixed to this paragraph by saying that the cortex is the sole organ of consciousness in man.t If there * For this word, see T. K. Clifford’s Lecturesand Essays (1879), vol. 11. p. 72. + See below, Chapter VIII. t Cf. Ferrier’s Functions, pp. 120, 147, 414. See also Vulpian: Lecons sur la Physiol. du Syst. Nerveux, p. 548; Luciani u. Seppili, op. czt. pp. 404-5; H. Maudsley: Physiology of Mind (1876), pp. 188 ff., 197 ff., and 241 ff. In G. H. Lewes’s Physical Basis of Mind, Problem LV: ‘ The Reflex Theory,’ a very full history of the question is given. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 67 be any consciousness pertaining to the lower centres, it is a consciousness of which the self knows nothing. THE RESTITUTION OF FUNCTION. Another problem, not so metaphysical, remains. The most general and striking fact connected with cortical in- jury is that of the restoration of function. Functions lost at first are after a few days or weeks restored. How are we to understand this restitution ? Two theories are in the field: 1) Restitution is due to the vicarious action either of the rest of the cortex or of centres lower down, acquiring func- tions which until then they had not performed ; 2) It is due to the remaining centres (whether cortical or ‘lower’) resuming functions which they had always had, but of which the wound had temporarily inhibited the exercise. This is the view of which Goltz and Brown- Séquard are the most distinguished defenders. Inhibition is a vera causa, of that there can be no doubt. The pneumogastric nerve inhibits the heart, the splanch- nic inhibits the intestinal movements, and the superior laryngeal those of inspiration. The nerve-irritations which may inhibit the contraction of arterioles are innumerable, and reflex actions are often repressed by the simultaneous excitement of other sensory nerves. For all such facts the reader must consult the treatises on physiology. What concerns us here is the inhibition exerted by different parts of “ne nerve-centres, when irritated, on the activity of dis- tant parts. The flaccidity of a frog from ‘shock,’ for a minute or so after his medulla oblongata is cut, is an in- hibition from the seat of injury which quickly passes away. What is known as ‘surgical shock’ (unconsciousness, pallor, dilatation of splanchnic blood-vessels, and general syncope and collapse) in the human subject is an inhibition which lasts a longer time. Goltz, Freusberg, and others, cutting the spinal cord in dogs, proved that there were functions inhibited still longer by the wound, but which re- established themselves ultimately if the animal was kept alive. The lumbar region of the cord was thus found to contain independent vaso-motor centres, centres for erec- 68 PSYCHOLOGY. tion, for control of the sphincters, ete., which could be excited to activity by tactile stimuli and as readily reinhib- ited by others simultaneously applied.* We may therefore plausibly suppose that the rapid reappearance of motility, vision, etc., after their first disappearance in consequence of a cortical mutilation, is due to the passing off of inhibitions exerted by the irritated surface of the wound. The only question is whether all restorations of function must be explained in this one simple way, or whether some part of them may not be owing to the formation of entirely new paths in the remaining centres, by which they become ‘educated’ to duties which they did not originally possess. In favor of an indefinite extension of the inhibition theory facts may be cited such as the following: In dogs whose dis- turbances due to cortical lesion have disappeared, they may in consequence of some inner or outer accident reappear in all their intensity for 24 hours or so and then disappear again. + In a dog made half blind by an operation, and then shut up in the dark, vision comes back just as quickly as in other similar dogs whose sight is exercised systematically every day.t A dog which has learned to beg before the operation recommences this practice quite spontaneously a week after a double-sided ablation of the motor zone.$ Occasionally, in a pigeon (or even, it is said, in a dog) we see the disturbances less marked immediately after the operation than they are half an hour later.| This would be impossible were they due to the subtraction of the organs which normally carried them on. Moreover the entire drift of recent physiological and pathological specu- lation is towards enthroning inhibition as an ever-present and indispensable condition of orderly activity. We shall see how great is its importance, in the chapter on the Will. Mr. Charles Mercier considers that no muscular contraction, once begun, would ever stop without it, short of exhaustion * Goltz: Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 8, p. 460; Freusberg: zbid. vol. 10, p. 174 + Goltz: Verrichtungen des Grosshirnz, p. 78. ¢t Loeb: Pfliger’s Archiv, vol. 29, p. 276. § Ibid. p. 289. | Schrader: tid. vol. 44, p. 218. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 69 of the system;* and Brown-Séquard has for years been accumulating examples to show how far its influence ex- tends. + Under these circumstances it seems as if error might more probably lie in curtailing its sphere too much than in stretching it too far as an explanation of the phenomena following cortical lesion. ¢ On the other hand, if we admit no re-education of cen- tres, we not only fly in the face of an @ priori probability, but we find ourselves compelled by facts to suppose an almost incredible number of functions natively lodged in the centres below the thalami or even in those below the corpora quadrigemina. I will consider the a priori objection after first taking a look at the facts which I have in mind. They confront us the moment we ask ourselves just which are the parts which perform the functions abolished by an operation after sufficient time has elapsed for restoration to occur ? The first observers thought that they must be the cor- responding parts of the opposite or intact hemisphere. But as long ago as 1875 Carville and Duret tested this by cutting out the fore-leg-centre on one side, in a dog, and then, after waiting till restitution had occurred, cutting it out on the opposite side as well. Goltz and others have done the same thing.§ Ifthe opposite side were really the seat of the restored function, the original palsy should have appeared again and been permanent. Butit did not appear at all; there appeared only a palsy of the hitherto unaffected side. The next supposition is that the parts surrounding the cut-out region learn vicariously to perform its duties. But here, again, experiment seems to upset the hypothesis, so far as the motor zone goes at least; for we may wait till motility has returned in the affected limb, and then both irritate the * The Nervous System and the Mind (1888), chaps. m1, vi; also in Brain, vol. xi. p. 361. + Brown-Séquard has given a résumé of his opinions in the Archives de Physiologie for Oct. 1889, 5me. Série, vol. 1. p. 751. ¢ Goltz first applied the inhibition theory to the brain in his ‘ Verrich- tungen des Grosshirns,’ p. 39 ff. On the general philosophy of Inhibition the reader may consult Brunton’s ‘Pharmakology and Therapeutics,’ p. 154 ff., and also ‘ Nature,’ vol. 27, p. 419 ff. § E.g. Herzen, Herman u. Schwalbe’s Jahres-bericht for 1886, Physiol Abth. p. 38. (Experiments on new-born puppies.) 70 PSYCHOLOGY. cortex surrounding the wound without exciting the limb to movement, and ablate it, without bringing back the vanished palsy.* It would accordingly seem that the cere- bral centres below the cortex must be the seat of the regained activities. But Goltz destroyed a dog’s entire left hemi- sphere, together with the corpus striatum and the thalamus on that side, and kept him alive until a surprisingly small amount of motor and tactile disturbance remained.t These centres cannot here have accounted for the restitution. He has even, as it would appear,{ ablated both the hemispheres of a dog, and kept him alive 51 days, able to walk and stand, The corpora striata and thalami in this dog were also prac- tically gone. In view of such results we seem driven, with M. Francois-Franck,§ to fall back on the ganglia lower still, or even on the spinal cord as the ‘vicarious’ organ of which we are in quest. If the abeyance of function between the operation and the restoration was due exclusively to inhibi- tion, then we must suppose these lowest centres to be in reality extremely accomplished organs. They must always have done what we now find them doing after function is restored, even when the hemispheres were intact. Of course this is conceivably the case; yet it does not seem very plausible. And the @ priori considerations which a moment since I said I should urge, make it less plausible still. For, in the first place, the brain is essentially a place of currents, which run in organized paths. Loss of function can only mean one of two things, either that a current can no longer run in, or that if it runs in, it can no longer run out, by its old path. Either of these inabilities may come from a local ablation; and ‘restitution’ can then only mean that, in spite of a temporary block, an inrunning current has at last become enabled to flow out by its old path again— e.g., the sound of ‘give your paw’ discharges after some * Francois-Franck : op. cit. p. 882. Results are somewhat contradictory. + Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 42, p. 419. ¢ Neurologisches Centralblatt, 1889, p. 372. § Op. cit. p. 387. See pp. 878 to 388 for a discussion of the whole question. Compare also Wundt’s Physiol. Psych., 3d ed., 1. 226 ff., and Luciani u. Seppili, pp. 248, 298. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRALN. Tt weeks into the same canine muscles into which it used te discharge before the operation. As far as the cortex itself goes, since one of the purposes for which it actually exists is the production of new paths,* the only question before us is: Is the formation of these particular ‘vicarious’ paths too much to expect of its plastic powers? It would cer- tainly be too much to expect that a hemisphere should receive currents from optic fibres whose arriving-place with- in it is destroyed, or that it should discharge into fibres of the pyramidal strand if their place of exit is broken down. Such lesions as these must be irreparable within that hemisphere. Yet even then, through the other hemisphere, the corpus callosum, and the bilateral connections in the spinal cord, one can imagine some road by which the old muscles might eventually be innervated by the same in- coming currents which innervated them before the block. And for all minor interruptions, not involving the arriving- place of the ‘cortico-petal’ or the place of exit of the ‘cortico- fugal’ fibres, roundabout paths of some sort through the affected hemisphere itself must exist, for every point of it is, remotely at least, in potential communication with every other point. The normal paths are only paths of least resistance. Ifthey get blocked or cut, paths formerly more resistant become the least resistant paths under the changed conditions. It must never be forgotten that a current that runs in has got to run out somewhere ; and if it only once succeeds by accident in striking into its old place cf exit again, the thrill of satisfaction which the consciousness connected with the whole residual brain then receives will reinforce and fix the paths of that moment and make them more likely to be struck into again. The resultant feeling that the old habitual act is at last successfully back again, becomes itself a new stimulus which stamps all the exist- ing currents in. It is matter of experience that such feel- ings of successful achievement do tend to fix in our memory whatever processes have led to them; and we shall have * The Chapters on Habit, Association, Memory, and Perception will change our present preliminary conjecture tbat that is one of its essentia! uses, into an unshakable conviction. 72 PSYCHOLOGY. a good deal more to say upon the subject when we come te the Chapter on the Will. My conclusion then is this: that some of the restitution of function (especially where the cortical lesion is not too great) is probably due to genuinely vicarious function on the put of the centres that remain; whilst some of it is due to the passing off of inhibitions. In other words, both the vicarious theory and the inhibition theory are true in their measure. But as for determining that measure, or saying which centres are vicarious, and to what extent they can learn new tricks, that is impossible at present. FINAL CORRECTION OF THE MEYNERT SCHEME. And now, after learning all these facts, what are we to think of the child and the candle-flame, and of that scheme which provisionally imposed itself on our acceptance after surveying the actions of the frog? (Cf. pp. 25-6, supra.) It will be remembered that we then considered the lower cen- tres en masse as machines for responding to present sense- impressions exclusively, and the hemispheres as equally exclusive organs of action from inward considerations or ideas ; and that, following Meynert, we supposed the hemi- spheres to have no native tendencies to determinate activity, but to be merely superadded organs for breaking up the various reflexes performed by the lower centres, and com- bining their motor and sensory elements in novel ways. It will also be remembered that I prophesied that we should be obliged to soften down the sharpness of this distinction after we had completed our survey of the farther facts. The time has now come for that correction to be made. Wider and completer observations show us both that the lower centres are more spontaneous, and that the hemi- spheres are more automatic, than the Meynert scheme allows. Schrader’s observations in Goltz’s Laboratory on hemisphereless frogs* and pigeons t give an idea quite different from the picture of these creatures which is classically current. Steiner's { observations on frogs * Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 41, p. 75 (1887). + Jbid., vol. 44, p. 175 (1889) ¢ Untersuchungen tiber die Physiologie des Froschhirns, 1885. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 73 already went a good way in the same direction, showing, for example, that locomotion is a well-developed function of the medulla oblongata. But Schrader, by great care in the operation, and by keeping the frogs a long time alive, found that at least in some of them the spinal cord would produce movements of locomotion when the frog was smartly roused by a poke, and that swimming and croaking could sometimes be performed when nothing above the medulla oblongata remained.* Schrader’s hemisphereless frogs moved spontaneously, ate flies, buried themselves in the ground, and in short did many things which before his observations were supposed to be impossible unless the hemispheres remained. Steinert and Vulpian have re- marked an even greater vivacity in fishes deprived of their hemispheres. Vulpian says of his brainless carpst that three days after the operation one of them darted at food and ata knot tied on the end ofa string, holding the latter so tight between his jaws that his head was drawn out of water. Later, “they see morsels of white of egg; the moment these sink through the water in front of them, they follow and seize them, sometimes after they are on the bottom, sometimes before they have reached it. In captur- ing and swallowing this food they execute just the same movements as the intact carps which are in the same aqua- rium. ‘The only difference is that they seem to see them at less distance, seek them with less impetuosity and less per- severance in all the points of the bottom of the aquarium, but they struggle (so to speak) sometimes with the sound carps to grasp the morsels. It is certain that they do not confound these bits of white of egg with other white bodies, small pebbles for example, which are at the bottom of the water. The same carp which, three days after operation, seized the knot on a piece of string, no longer snaps at it now, but if one brings it near her, she draws away from it by swimming backwards before it comes into contact with * Toc. cit. pp. 80, 82-8. Schrader also found a diting-reflex developed when the medulla oblongata is cut through just behind the cerebellum. + Berlin Akad. Sitzungsberichte for 1886. t+ Comptes Rendus, vol. 102, p. 90. 74 PSYCHOLOG Y. her mouth.” * Already on pp. 9-10, as the reader may re: member, we instanced those adaptations of conduct to new conditions, on the part of the frog’s spinal cord and thalami, which led Pfliiger and Lewes on the one hand and Goltz on the other to locate in these organs an intelligence akin to that of which the hemispheres are the seat. When it comes to birds deprived of their hemispheres, the evidence that some of their acts have conscious purpose behind them is quite as persuasive. In pigeons Schrader found that the state of somnolence lasted only three or four days, after which time the birds began indefatigably to walk about the room. They climbed out of boxes in which they were put, jumped over or flew up upon obstacles, and their sight was so perfect that neither in walking nor flying did they ever strike any object in the room. They had also definite ends or purposes, flying straight for more convenient perching places when made uncomfortable by movements imparted to those on which they stood ; and of several possible perches they always chose the most con- venient. “If we give the dove the choice of a horizontal bar (#eck) or an equally distant table to fly to, she always gives decided preference to the table. Indeed she chooses the table even if itis several meters farther off than the bar or the chair.” Placed on the back of a chair, she flies first to the seat and then to the floor, and in general “ will for- sake a high position, although it give her sufficiently firm support, and in order to reach the ground will make use of the environing objects as intermediate goals of flight, show- ing a perfectly correct judgment of their distance. Although able to fly directly to the ground, she prefers to make the journey in successive stages... . Once on the ground, she hardly ever rises spontaneously into the air.” + Young rabbits deprived of their hemispheres will stand, run, start at noises, avoid obstacles in their path, and give responsive cries of suffering when hurt. Rats will do the same, and throw themselves moreover into an attitude of defence. Dogs never survive such an operation if per- formed at once. But Goltz’s latest dog, mentioned on p. * Comptes Rendus de l’Acad. d. Sciences, vol. 102, p. 1580. + Loc. cit. p. 216. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 75 70, which is said to have been kept alive for fifty-one days after both hemispheres had been removed by a series of ablations and the corpora striata and thalami had softened away, shows how much the mid-brain centres and the cord can do even in the canine species. Taken together, the number of reactions shown to exist in the lower centres by these observations make out a pretty good case for the Mey- nert scheme, as applied to these lower animals. That scheme demands hemispheres which shall be mere supple- ments or organs of repetition, and in the light of these observations they obviously are so to a great extent. But the Meynert scheme also demands that the reactions of the lower centres shall all be native, and we are not absolutely sure that some of those which we have been considering may not have been acquired after the injury ; and it further- more demands that they should be machine-like, whereas the expression of some of them makes us doubt whether they may not be guided by an intelligence of low degree. Even in the lower animals, then, there is reason to soften down that opposition between the hemispheres and the lower centres which the scheme demands. The hemi- spheres may, it is true, only supplement the lower centres, but the latter resemble the former in nature and have some small amount at least of ‘spontaneity’ and choice. But when we come to monkeys and man the scheme well-nigh breaks down altogether; for we find that the hemispheres do not simply repeat voluntarily actions which the lower centres perform as machines. There are many functions which the lower centres cannot by themselves perform at all. When the motor cortex is injured in a man or a monkey genuine paralysis ensues, which in man is incurable, and almost or quite equally so in the ape. Dr. Seguin knew a man with hemi-blindness, from cortical injury, which had persisted unaltered for twenty-three years. ‘Traumatic inhibition’ cannot possibly account for this. The blindness must have been an ‘ Ausfallser- scheinung,’ due to the loss of vision’s essential organ. It would seem, then, that in these higher creatures the lower centres must be less adequate than they are farther down in the zoological scale ; and that even for certain elementary 76 PS YCHOLOG Y. combinations of movement and impression the co-operation of the hemispheres is necessary from the start. Even in birds and dogs the power of eating properly is lost when the frontal lobes are cut off.* The plain truth is that neither in man nor beast are the hemispheres the virgin organs which our scheme called them. So far from being unorganized at birth, they must have native tendencies to reaction of a determinate sort.+ These are the tendencies which we know as emotions and instincts, and which we must study with some detail in later chapters of this book. Both instincts and emotions are reac tions upon special sorts of objects of perception ; they de- pend on the hemispheres; and they are in the first instance reflex, that is, they take place the first time the exciting ob- ject is met, are accompanied by no forethought or delibera- tion, and are irresistible. But they are modifiable to a certain extent by experience, and on later occasions of meeting the exciting object, the instincts especially have less of the blind impulsive character which they had at first. All this will be explained at some length in Chapter XXIV. Meanwhile we can say that the multiplicity of emo- tional and instinctive reactions in man, together with his extensive associative power, permit of extensive recouplings of the original sensory and motor partners. The conse- quences of one instinctive reaction often prove to be the inciters of an opposite reaction, and being suggested on later occasions by the original object, may then suppress the first reaction altogether, just as in the case of the child and the flame. For this education the hemispheres do not need * Goltz: Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 42, p. 447; Schrader: zbéd. vol. 44, p. 219 ff. It is possible that this symptom may be an effect of traumatic inhibition, however. + A few years ago one of the strongest arguments for the theory that the hemispheres are purely supernumerary was Soltmann’s often-quoted observation that in new-born puppies the motor zone of the cortex is not excitable by electricity and only becomes so in the course of a fortnight, presumably after the experiences of the lower centres have educated it to motor duties. Paneth’s later observations, however, seem to show that Soltmann may have been misled through overnarcotizing his victims (Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 37, p. 202). In the Neurologisches Centralblatt for 1889, p. 518, Bechterew returns to the subject on Soltmann’s side with: out, however, noticing Paneth’s work. FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. 77 to be tabule rase at first, as the Meynert scheme would have them; and so far from their being educated by the lower centres exclusively, they educate themselves.* We have already noticed the absence of reactions from fear and hunger in the ordinary brainless frog. Schrader gives a striking account of the instinctless condition of his brainless pigeons, active as they were in the way of loco- motion and voice. ‘The hemisphereless animal moves in a world of bodies which .. . are all of equal value for him.... He is, to use Goltz’s apt expression, impersonal... . Every object is for him only a space-occupying mass, he turns out of his path for an ordinary pigeon no otherwise than for a stone. He may try to climb over both. All authors agree that they never found any difference, whether it was an in- animate body, a cat, a dog, or a bird of prey which came in their pigeon’s way. The creature knows neither friends nor enemies, in the thickest company it lives like a hermit. The languishing cooing of the male awakens no more im- pression than the rattling of the peas, or the call-whistle which in the days before the injury used to make the birds hasten to be fed. Quite as little as the earlier observers have I seen hemisphereless she-birds answer the courting of the male. A hemisphereless male will coo all day long and show distinct signs of sexual excitement, but his activ- ity is without any object, it is entirely indifferent to him whether the she-bird be there or not. If one is placed near him, he leaves her unnoticed. ... As the male pays no at- tention to the female, so she nEes none to her young. The brood may follow the mother ceaselessly ae for food, but they might as well ask it from a stone. ... The hemi- * Miinsterberg (Die Willenshandlung, 1888, p. 134) challenges Meynert’s scheme 7m toto, saying that whilst we have in our personal experience plenty of examples of acts which were at first voluntary becoming second- arily automatic and reflex, we have no conscious record of a single origi- nally retlex act growing voluntary.—As far as conscious record is concerned, we could not possibly have it even if the Meynert scheme were wholly true, for the education of the hemispheres which that scheme pestulates must in the nature of things antedate recollection. But it scems to me that Miinsterberg’s rejection of the scheme may possibly be correct as regards reflexes from the lower centres. Everywhere in this depaitme:t of psy: chogenesis we are made to feel how ignorant we really arc 78 PSYCHOLOG ¥. sphereless pigeon is in the highest degree tame, and fears man as little as cat or bird of prey.” * Putting together now all the facts and reflections which we have been through, it seems to me that we can no longer hold strictly to the Meynert scheme. If anywhere, it will apply to the lowest animals; but in them especially the lower centres seem to have a degree of spontaneity and choice. On the whole, I think that we are driven to sub- stitute for it some such general conception as the following, which allows for zoological differences as we know them, and is vague and elastic enough to receive any number of future discoveries of detail. CONCLUSION. All the centres, in all animals, whilst they are in one aspect mechanisms, probably are, or at least once were, organs of consciousness in another, although the conscious- ness is doubtless much more developed in the hemispheres than it is anywhere else. The consciousness must every- where prefer some of the sensations which it gets to others ; and if it can remember these in their absence, however dimly, they must be its ends of desire. If, moreover, it can identify in memory any motor discharges which may have led to such ends, and associate the latter with them, then these motor discharges themselves may in turn become desired as means. This is the development of will ; and its realization must of course be proportional to the possible complication of the consciousness. Even the spinal cord may possibly have some little power of will in this sense, and of effort towards modified behavior in consequence of new experiences of sensibility. t ; * Pfliiger’s Archiv, vol. 44, p. 280-1. + Naturally, as Schiff long ago pointed out (Lehrb. d. Muskel-u. Ner- venphysiologie, 1859, p. 213 ff.), the ‘ Riickenmarksseele,’ if it now exist, can have no higher sense-corsciousness, for its incoming currents are solely from the skin. But it may, in its dim way, both feel, prefer, and desire. See, for the view favorable to the text: G. H. Lewes, The Physiol- ogy of Common Life (1860). chap. rx. Goltz (Nervencentren des Frosches 1869, pp. 102-130) thinks that the frog’s cord has no adaptative power. This tuy be the case in such experiments as his, because the beheaded frog’s FUNCTIONS OF THE BRAIN. ao All nervous centres have then in the first instance one essential function, that of ‘intelligent’ action. They feel, prefer one thing to another, and have ‘ends.’ Like all other organs, however, they evolve from ancestor to descend- ant, and their evolution takes two directions, the lower centres passing downwards into more unhesitating autom- atism, and the higher ones upwards into larger intellectu- ality.* Thus it may happen that those functions which can safely grow uniform and fatal become least accompanied by mind, and that their organ, the spinal cord, becomes a more and more soulless machine; whilst on the contrary those functions which it benefits the animal to have adapted to delicate environing variations pass more and more to the hemispheres, whose anatomical structure and attendant consciousness grow more and more elaborate as zoological evolution proceeds. In this way it might come about that in man and the monkeys the basal ganglia should do fewer things by themselves than they can do in dogs, fewer in dogs than in rabbits, fewer in rabbits than in hawks,+ fewer in hawks than in pigeons, fewer in pigeons than in frogs, fewer in frogs than in fishes, and that the hemispheres should correspondingly do more. This passage of functions for- ward to the ever-enlarging hemispheres would be itself one of the evolutive changes, to be explained like the develop- ment of the hemispheres themselves, either by fortunate variation or by inherited effects of use. The reflexes, on this view, upon which the education of our human hemi- spheres depends, would not be due to the basal ganglia short span of life does not give it time to learn the new tricks asked for. But Rosenthal (Biologisches Centralblatt, vol. iv. p. 247) and Mendelssohn (Berlin Akad. Sitzungsberichte, 1885, p. 107) in their investigations on the simple reflexes of the frog’s cord, show that there is some adaptation to new conditions, inasmuch as when usual paths of conduction are interrupted by a cut, new puths are taken. According to Rosenthal, these grow more pervious (i.e. require a smaller stimulus) in proportion as they are more often traversed. * Whether this evolution takes place through the inheritance of habits acquired, or through the preservation of lucky variations, is an alternative which we need not discuss here. We shall consider it in the last chapter in the book. For our present purpose the modus operandi of the evolution makes no difference, provided it be admitted to occur. + See Schrader’s Observations, Joc. cit. 80 PSYCHOLOGY. alone. They would be tendencies in the hemispheres them. selves, modifiable by education, unlike the reflexes of the medulla oblongata, pons, optic lobes and spinal cord. Such cerebral reflexes, if they exist, form a basis quite as good as that which the Meynert scheme offers, for the acquisition of memories and associations which may later result in all sorts of ‘changes of partners’ in the psychic world. The diagram of the baby and the candle (see page 25) can be re-edited, if need be, as an entirely cortical transaction. The original tendency to touch will be a cortical instinct ; the burn will leave an image in another part of the cortex, which, being recalled by association, will inhibit the touch- ing tendency the next time the candle is perceived, and excite the tendency to withdraw—so that the retinal picture will, upon that next time, be coupled with the original motor partner of the pain. We thus get whatever psycho- logical truth the Meynert scheme possesses without en- tangling ourselves on a dubious anatomy and physiology. Some such shadowy view of the evolution of the centres, of the relation of consciousness to them, and of the hemi- spheres to the other lobes, is, it seems to me, that in which it is safest to indulge. If it has no other advantage, it at any rate makes us realize how enormous are the gaps in our knowledge, the moment we try to cover the facts by any one formula of a general kind. CHAPTER III. «- ON SOME GENERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY. Tue elementary properties of nerve-tissue on which the brain-functions depend are far from being satisfactorily made out. The scheme that suggests itself in the first instance to the mind, because it is so obvious, is certainly false: I mean the notion that each cell stands for an idea or part of an idea, and that the ideas are associated or ‘bound into bundles’ (to use a phrase of Locke’s) by the fibres. If we make a symbolic diagram on a blackboard, of the laws of association between ideas, we are inevitably Jed to draw circles, or closed figures of some kind, and to connect them by lines. When we hear that the nerve-cen- tres contain cells which send off fibres, we say that Nature has realized our diagram for us, and that the mechanical substratum of thought is plain. In some way, it is true, our diagram must be realized in the brain; but surely in no such visible and palpable way as we at first suppose.* An enormous number of the cellular bodies in the hemispheres are fibreless. Where fibres are sent off they soon divide into untraceable ramifications ; and nowhere do we see a simple coarse anatomical connection, like a line on the black- board, between two cells. Too much anatomy has been found to order for theoretic purposes, even by the anat- omists ; and the popular-science notions of cells and fibres are almost wholly wide of the truth. Let us therefore rele- gate the subject of the intimate workings of the brain to * T shall myself in later places indulge in much of this schematization. The reader will understand once for all that it is symbolic; and that the use of it is hardly more than to show what a deep congruity there is between mental processes and mechanical processes of some kind, not necessarily of the exact kind portrayed. 81 82 PSYCHOLOGY. the physiology of the future, save in respect to a few points of which a word must now be said. And first of THE SUMMATION OF STIMULI in the same nerve-tract. This is a property extremely im- portant for the understanding of a great many phenomena of the neural, and consequently of the mental, life; and it behooves us to gain a clear conception of what it means be- fore we proceed any farther. The law is this, that a stimulus which would be inadequate by itself to excite a nerve-centre to effective discharge may, by acting with one or more other stimuli (equally ineffectual by themselves alone) bring the discharge about. The natural way to con- sider this is as a summation of tensions which at last over- come a resistance. The first of them produce a ‘latent excitement’ or a ‘ heightened irritability ’—the phrase is immaterial so far as practical consequences go; the last is the straw which breaks the camel’s back. Where the neural process is one that has consciousness for its accom- paniment, the final explosion would in all cases seem to involve a vivid state of feeling of a more or less substantive kind. But there is no ground for supposing that the ten- sions whilst yet submaximal or outwardly ineffective, may not also have a share in determining the total conscious- hess present in the individual at the time. In later chapters we shall see abundant reason to suppose that they do have such a share, and that without their contribution the fringe of relations which is at every moment a vital in- gredient of the mind’s object, would not come to conscious- ness at all. The subject belongs too much to physiology for the evidence to be cited in detail in these pages. I will throw into a note a few references for such readers as may be in terested in following it out,* and simply say that the direct *Valentin: Archiv f. d. gesammt. Physiol., 1873, p. 458. Stirling: Leipzig Acad. Berichte, 1875, p. 372 (Journal of Physiol., 1875). J. Ward: Archiv f. (Anat. u.) Physiol., 1880, p. 72. H. Sewall: Johns Hopkins Studies, 1880, p. 30. Kronecker u. Nicolaides: Archiv f. (Anat. u.) Physiol., 1880, p. 437. Exner: Archiv f. die ges. Physiol., Bd. 28, p. 487 (1882). Eckhard: in Hermann’s Hdbch. d. Physiol., Bd. 1. Thl. m1. p. 31. Francois-Franck: Lecons sur les Fonctions motrices du Cer- GHNERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY. 83 electrical irritation of the cortical centres sufficiently proves the point. For it was found by the earliest experimenters here that whereas it takes an exceedingly strong current to produce any movement when a single induction-shock is used, a rapid succession of induction-shocks (‘ faradiza- tion’) will produce movements when the current is com- paratively weak. A single quotation from an excellent investigation will exhibit this law under further aspects: ‘* Tf we continue to stimulate the cortex at short intervals with the strength of current which produces the minimal muscular contrac- tion [of the dog’s digital extensor muscle], the amount of contraction gradually increases till it reaches the maximum. Each earlier stimula- tion leaves thus an effect behind it, which increases the efficacy of the following one. In this summation of the stimuli... . the foliowing points may be noted: 1) Single stimuli entirely inefficacious when alone may become efficacious by sufficiently rapid reiteration. If the current used is very much less than that which provokes the first begin- ning of contraction, a very large number of successive shocks may be needed before the movement appears—20, 50, once 106 shocks were needed. 2) The summation takes place easily in proportion to the shortness of the interval between the stimuli. A current too weak to give effective summation when its shocks are 3 seconds apart will be capable of so doing when the interval is shortened to 1 second. — 3) Not only electrical irritation leaves a modification which goes to swell the following stimulus, but every sort of irritant which can produce a contraction does so. If in any way a reflex contraction of the muscle experimented on has been produced, or if it is contracted spontaneously by the animal (as not unfrequently happens ‘by sympathy,’ during a deep inspiration), it is found that an electrical stimulus, until then inoperative, operates energetically if immediately applied.” * Furthermore : ‘‘In a certain stage of the morphia-narcosis an ineffectively weak shock will become powerfully effective, if, immediately before its appli- veau, p. 51 ff., 889.—For the process of summation in nerves and muscles, ef. Hermann: ibid. Thl. 1. p. 109, and vol. 1. p. 40. Also Wundt: Physiol. Psych., 1. 243 ff.; Richet : Travaux du Laboratoire de Marey, 1877, p. 97; L’Homme et l’Intelligence, pp. 24 ff., 468; Revue Philosophique, t. xxr. p. 564. Kronecker u. Hall: Archiv f. (Anat. u.) Physiol., 1879 ; Schonlein . did. 1882, p. 357. Sertoli (Hofmann and Schwalbe’s Jahres- bericht, 1882. p. 25. De Watteville: Neurologisches Centralblatt, 1883, No. 7. Griinhagen: Arch. f. d. ges. Physiol., Bd. 34, p. 301 (1884). * Bubnoff und Heidenhain : Ueber Erregungs- und Hemmungsvorgiinge innerhalb der motorischen Hirncentren. Archiv f. d. ges. Physiol., Bd. 26, p. 156 (1881). 84 PSYCHOLOGY. eation to the motor centre, the skin of certain parts of the body is exposed to gentle tactile stimulation. . .. If, having ascertained the subminimal strength of current and convinced one’s self repeatedly of its inefficacy, we draw our hand a single time lightly over the skin of the paw whose cortical centre is the object of stimulation, we find the cur- rent at once strongly effective. The increase of irritability lasts some seconds before it disappears. Sometimes the effect of a single light stroking of the paw is only sufficient to make the previously ineffectual current produce a very weak contraction. Repeating the tactile stimu- lation will then, as a rule, increase the contraction’s extent.” * We constantly use the summation of stimuli in our practical appeals. If a car-horse balks, the final way of starting him is by applying a number of customary incite- ments at once. If the driver uses reins and voice, if one bystander pulls at his head, another lashes his hind quarters, and the conductor rings the bell, and the dis- mounted passengers shove the car, all at the same moment, his obstinacy generally yields, and he goes on his way re- joicing. If we are striving to remember a lost name or fact, we think of as many ‘cues’ as possible, so that by their joint action they may recall what no one of them can recall alone. The sight of a dead prey will often not stimulate a beast to pursuit, but if the sight of movement be added to that of form, pursuit occurs. “ Briicke noted that his brain- less hen, which made no attempt to peck at the grain under her very eyes, began pecking if the grain were thrown on the ground with force, so as to produce a rattling sound.” + “Dr. Allen Thomson hatched out some chickens on a carpet, where he kept them for several days. They showed no in- clination to scrape, . . . but when Dr. Thomson sprinkled a little gravel on the carpet, . . . the chickens immediately began their scraping movements.” + A strange person, and darkness, are both of them stimuli to fear and mistrust in dogs (and for the matter of that, in men). Neither circum- * Archiv f. d. ges. Physiol., Bd. 26, p. 176 (1881). Exner thinks (7id. Bd. 28, p. 497 (1882) ) that the summation here occurs in the spinal cord. It makes no difference where this particular summation occurs, so far as the general philosophy of summation goes. +G Hi. Lewes: Physical Basis of Mind, p. 479, where many similai examples are given, 487-9. ; t Romanes: Mental Evolution in Animals, p. 168. GENERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY. 85 stance alone may awaken outward manifestations, but to- gether, i.e. when the strange man is met in the dark, the dog will be excited to violent defiance.* Street-hawkers well know the efficacy of summation, for they arrange themselves in a line upon the sidewalk, and the passer often buys from the last one of them, through the effect of the reiterated so- licitation, what he refused to buy from the first in the row. Aphasia shows’ many examples of summation. A patient who cannot name an object simply shown him, will name it if he touches as well as sees it, ete. Instances of summation might be multiplied indefinitely, butit is hardly worth while to forestall subsequent chapters. Those on Instinct, the Stream of Thought, Attention, Dis- crimination, Association, Memory, Aisthetics, and Will, will contain numerous exemplifications of the reach of the prin- ciple in the purely psychological field. REACTION-TIME. One of the lines of experimental investigation most diligently followed of late years is that of the ascertain- ment of the time occupied by nervous events. Helmholtz led off by discovering the rapidity of the current in the sciatic nerve of the frog. But the methods he used were soon applied to the sensory nerves and the centres, and the results caused much popular scientific admiration when described as measurements of the ‘velocity of thought.’ The phrase ‘ quick as thought’ had from time immemorial signified all that was wonderful and elusive of determina- tion in the line of speed; and the way in which Science laid her doomful hand upon this mystery reminded people of the day when Franklin first ‘eripwit celo fulmen, fore- . *See a similar instance in Mach: Beitriige zur Analyse der Empfin- dungen, p. 36, a sparrow being the animal. My young children are afraid of their own pug-dog, if he enters their room «fter they are in bed and the lights are out. Compare this statement also: ‘‘ The first question to a peasant seldom proves more than a flapper to rouse the torpid adjustments of his ears. The invariable answer of a Scottish peasant is, ‘What’s your wull? —that of the English, a vacant stare. A second and even a third question may be required to elicit an answer.” (R. Fowler: Some Obser- vations on the Mente! State of the Blind, and Deaf, and Dumb (Salisbury, 1843), p. 14.) 86 PSYCHOLOG Y. shadowing the reign of a newer and colder race of gods. We shall take up the various operations measured, each in the chapter to which it more naturally pertains. I may say, however, immediately, that the phrase ‘velocity of thought’ is misleading, for it is by no means clear in any of the cases what particular act of thought occurs during the time which is measured. ‘ Velocity of nerve-action’ is liable to the same criticism, for in most cases we do not know what particular nerve-processes occur. What the times in question really represent is the total duration of certain reactions upon stimuli. Certain of the conditions of the reac- tion are prepared beforehand ; they consist in the assump- tion of those motor and sensory tensions which we name the expectant state. Just what happens during the actual time occupied by the reaction (in other words, just what is added to the pre-existent tensions to produce the actual discharge) is not made out at present, either from the neural or from the mental point of view. The method is essentially the same in all these investiga- tions. A signal of some sort is communicated to the subject, and at the same instant records itself on a time-register- ing apparatus. The subject then makes a muscular move- ment of some sort, which is the ‘reaction,’ and which also records itself automatically. The time found to have elapsed between the two records is the total time of that observation. The time-registering instruments are of various types. Signal. Reaction. Reaction- line Time-line. Fia. 21. One type is that of the revolving drum covered with smol ed paper, on which one electric pen traces a line which the signal breaks and the ‘reaction’ draws again ; whilst another electric pen (connected with a pendulum or a rod of metal vibrating at a known rate) traces alongside of the former GENERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY. 87 line a ‘ time-line’ of which each undulation or link stands for a certain fraction of a second, and against which the break in the reaction-line can be measured. Compare Fig. 21, where the line is broken by the signal at the first arrow, and continued again by the reaction at the second. Ludwig’s Kymograph, Marey’s Chronograph are good ex- amples of this type of instrument. Another type of instrument is represented by the stop- watch, of which the most perfect form is Hipp’s Chrono- scope. The hand on the dial measures intervals as short aS qglgg Of a second. The signal (by an appropriate electric Fic. 22.—Bowditch’s Reaction-timer. F, tuning-fork carrying a little plate which holds the paper on which the electric pen M makes the tracing, and sliding .n grooves on the base-board. P, a plug which spreads the prongs of the fork apart when it is pushed forward to its extreme limit, and releases them when it is drawn back to a certain point. The fork then vibrates, and, its backward movement con- tinuing, an undulating line is drawn on the smoked paper by the pen. At Tisa tongue fixed to the carriage of the fork, and at K an electric key which the tongue opens and with which the electric penis connected. At the instant of opening, the ven changes its place and the undulating line is drawn at a different level on the paper. The opening can be made to serve as a signal to the reacter in a variety of ways, and his reaction can be made to close the pen again, when the line re- turns to its first level. The reaction time = the number of undulations traced at the second level. connection) starts it; the reaction stops it; and by reading off its initial and terminal positions we have immediately and with no farther trouble the time we seek. A still simpler instrument, though one not very satisfactory in its working, is the ‘ psychodometer’ of Exner & Obersteiner, of which I picture a modification devised by my colleague Professor H. P. Bowditch, which works very well. The manner in which the signal and reaction are con- nected with the chronographic apparatus varies indefinitely 88 PSYCHOLOG Y. in different experiments. Every new problem requires some new electric or mechanical disposition of apparatus.* The least complicated time-measurement is that known as simple reaction-time, in which there is but one possible signal and one possible movement, and both are known in advance. The movement is generally the closing of an elec- tric key with the hand. The foot, the jaw, the lips, even the eyelid, have been in turn made organs of reaction, and the apparatus has been modified accordingly.t The time usually elapsing between stimulus and movement les be- tween one and three tenths of a second, varying according to circumstances which will be mentioned anon. The subject of experiment, whenever the reactions are short and regular, is ina state of extreme tension, and feels,’ when the signal comes, as if it started the reaction, by a sort of fatality, and as if no psychic process of perception or volition had a chance to intervene. The whole succession is so rapid that perception seems to be retrospective, and the time-order of events to be read off in memory rather than known at the moment. This at least is my own per- sonal experience in the matter, and with it I find others to agree. The question is, What happens inside _of us, either in brain or mind? and to answer that we must analyze just what processes the reaction involves. It is evident that some time is lost in each of the following stages : 1. The stimulus excites the peripheral sense-organ adequately for a current to pass into the sensory nerve ; 2. The sensory nerve is traversed ; 3. The transformation (or reflection) of the sensory into a motor current occurs in the centres ; 4, The spinal cord and motor nerve are traversed ; 5. The motor current excites the muscle to the contract- ing point. per a 8 ect cee * The reader will find a great deal about chronographic apparatus in J. Marey: La Méthode Graphique, pt. u. chap. 11. One can make pretty fair measurements with no other instrument than a watch, by making a large number of reactions, each serving as a signal for the following one, and dividing the total time they take by their number. Dr. O. W. Holmes first suggested this method, which has been ingeniously elaborated and applied by Professor Jastrow. See Science’ for September 10, 1886. + See, for a few modifications, Cattell, Mind, x1. 220 ff. GENERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY. 89 Time is also lost, of course, outside the muscle, in the joints, skin, etc., and between the parts of the apparatus; and when the stimulus which serves as signal is applied to the skin of the trunk or limbs, time is lost in the sensorial conduction through the spinal cord. The stage marked 3 is the only one that interests us here. The other stages answer to purely physiological processes, but stage 3 is psycho-physical; that is, it is a higher-central process, and has probably some sort of con- sciousness accompanying it. What sort? Wundt has little difficulty in deciding that it is con- sciousness of a quite elaborate kind. He distinguishes between two stages in the conscious reception of an im- pression, calling one perception, and the other apperception, and likening the one to the mere entrance of an object into the periphery of the field of vision, and the other to its coming to occupy the focus or point of view. Inattentive awareness of an object, and attention to it, are, it seems to me, equivalents for perception and apperception, as Wundt uses the words. To these two forms of awareness of the impression Wundt adds the conscious volition to react, gives to the trio the name of ‘psycho-physical’ processes, and assumes that they actually follow upon each other in the succession in which they have been named.* So at least I understand him. The simplest way to determine the time taken up by this psycho-physical stage No. 3 would be to determine separately the duration of the sev- eral purely physical processes, 1, 2, 4, and 5, and to sub- tract them from the total reaction-time. Such attempts have been made. t But the data for calculation are too * Physiol. Psych., m. 221-2. Cf. also the first edition, 728-9. I must confess to finding al! Wundt’s utterances about ‘apperception ’ both vacil- lating and obscure. I see no use whatever for the word, as he employs it, in Psychology. Attention, perception, conception, volition, are its ample equivalents. Why we should need a single word to denote all these things by turns, Wundt fails to make clear. Consult, however, his pupil Staude’s article, ‘ Ueber den Begriff der Apperception,’ etc., in Wundt’s periodical Philosophische Studien, 1. 149, which may be supposed official. For a minute criticism of Wundt’s ‘apperception,’ see Marty. Vierteljahrschrift f. wiss. Philos., x. 346. + By Exner, for example, Pfliiger’s Archiv, vu. 628 ff. D0 PSYCHOLOGY. inaccurate for use, and, as Wundt himself admits, * the pre- cise duration of stage 3 must at present be left enveloped with that of the other processes, in the total reaction-time. My own belief is that no such succession of conscious feelings as Wundt describes takes place during stage 3. It is a process of central excitement and discharge, with which doubtless some feeling coexists, but what feeling we cannot tell, because it is so fugitive and so immediately eclipsed by the more substantive and enduring memory of the impression as it came in, and of the executed move- ment of response. Feeling of the impression, attention to it, thought of the reaction, volition to react, woud, undoubt- edly, all be links of the process under other conditions,+ and would lead to the same reaction—after an indefinitely longer time. But these other conditions are not those of the experiments we are discussing; and it is mythological psy- chology (of which we shall see many later examples) to con- clude that because two mental processes lead to the same result they must be similar in their inward subjective con- stitution. The feeling of stage 3 is certainly no articulate perception. It can be nothing but the mere sense of a reflex discharge. The reaction whose time is measured is, in short, a reflex action pure and simple, and not a psychic act, A foregoing psychic condition is, it is true, a pre- requisite for this reflex action. The preparation of the attention and volition; the expectation of the signal and the readiness of the hand to move, the instant it shall come; the nervous tension in which the subject waits, are all con- ditions of the formation in kim for the time being of a new path or are of reflex discharge. The tract from the sense- organ which receives the stimulus, into the motor centre which discharges the reaction, is already tingling with pre- monitory innervation, is raised to such a pitch of he:ghtened irritability by the expectant attention, that the signal is instantaneously sufficient to cause the overflow.{ No other * P. 222. Cf. also Richet, Rev. Philos., v1. 395-6. + For instance, if, on the previous day, one had resolved to act on a signal when it should come, and it now came whilst we were engaged in other things, and reminded us of the resolve. t ‘‘I need hardly mention that success in these experiments depends in a high degree on our concentration of attention. If inattentive, one gets GENERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY. 91 tract of the nervous system is, at the moment, in this hair- trigger condition. The consequence is that one sometimes responds to a wrong signal, especially if it be an impression of the same kind with the signal we expect.* But if by chance we are tired, or the signal is unexpectedly weak, and we do not react instantly, but only after an express perception that the signal has come, and an express yoli- tion, the time becomes quite disproportionately long (a second or more, according to Exner +), and we feel that the process is in nature altogether different. In fact, the reaction-time experiments are a case to which we can immediately apply what we have just learned about the summation of stimuli. ‘ Expectant attention’ is but the subjective name for what objectively is a partial stimulation of a certain pathway, the pathway from the ‘centre’ for the signal to that for the discharge. In Chapter XI we shall see that all attention involves excitement from within of the tract concerned in feeling the objects to which attention is given. The tract here is the excito-motor are about to be traversed. The signal is but the spark from without which touches off a train already laid. The per- formance, under these conditions, exactly resembles any reflex action. The only difference is that whilst, in the ordinarily so-called reflex acts, the reflex arc is a permanent result of organic growth, it is here a transient result of previous cerebral conditions. + very discrepant figures. . . . This concentration of the attention is in the highest degree exhausting. After some experiments in which I was con- cerned to get results as uniform as possible, I was covered with perspiration and excessively fatigued although I had sat quietly in my chair al] the while.” (Exner, loc. cit. vit. 618.) * Wundt, Physiol. Psych., 0. 226. + Pfliger’s Archiv, vir. 616. ¢ In short, what M. Delbceuf calls an ‘organe adventice.’ The reaction- time, moreover, is quite compatible with the reaction itself being of a reflex order. Some reflexes (sneezing, e.g.) are very slow. The only time- measurement of a reflex act in the human subject with which I am acquainted is Exner’s measurement of winking (in Pfliiger’s Archiv f. d. gesammt. Physiol., Bd. vu. p. 526, 1874). He found that when the stimulus was a flash of light it took the wink 0.2168 sec. to occur. A strong electric shock to the cornea shortened the time to 0.0578 sec. The ordinary ‘reaction-time ’ is midway between these values. Exner ‘ reduces’ his times by eliminating the physiclogical process of conduction. His ‘reduced 92 PSYCHOLOGY. T am happy to say that since the preceding paragraphs (and the notes thereto appertaining) were written, Wundt has himself become converted to the view which I defend. He now admits that in the shortest reactions “there is neither apperception nor will, but that they are merely brain-refleces due to practice.” * The means of his conver- sion are certain experiments performed in his laboratory by Herr L. Lange, + who was led to distinguish between two ways of setting the attention in reacting on a signal, and who found that they gave very different time-results. In the ‘extreme sensorial’ way, as Lange calls it, of reacting, minimum winking-time’ is then 0.0471 (bid. 531), whilst his reduced reac- tion-time is 0.0828 (cid. vir. 637). These figures have really no scientific value beyond that of showing, according to Exner’s own belief (vu. 531), that reaction-time and reflex-time measure processes of essentially the same order. His description, moreover, of the process is an excellent description of a reflex act. ‘‘ Every one,” says he, ‘‘ who makes reaction-time experi- ments for the first time is surprised to find how little he is master of his own movements, so soon as it becomes a question of executing them with a maximum of speed. Not only does their energy lie, as it were, outside the field of choice, but even the time in which the movement occurs depends only partly upon ourselves. We jerk our arm, and we can afterwards tell with astonishing precision whether we have jerked it quicker or slower than another time, although we have no power to jerk it exactly at the wished-for moment.”—Wundat himself admits that when we await a strong signal with tense preparation there is no consciousness of any duality of ‘ appercep- tion’ and motor response; the two are continuous (Physiol. Psych., 1. 226).—Mr. Cattell’s view is identical with the one I defend. ‘‘I think,” he says, ‘‘that if the processes of perception and willing are present at all they are very rudimentary. . . . The subject, by a voluntary effort [before the signal comes], puts the lines of communication between the centre for” the stimulus ‘‘and the centre for the co-ordination of motions ... inastate of unstable equilibrium. When, therefore, a nervous impulse reaches the” former centre, ‘‘ it causes brain-changes in two directions; an impulse moves along to the cortex and calls forth there a perception corresponding to the stimulus, while at the same time an impulse follows a line of small resist- ance to the centre for the co-ordination of motions, and the proper nervous impulse, already prepared and waiting for the signal, is sent from the centre to the muscle of the hand. When the reaction has often been made the entire cerebral process becomes automatic, the impulse of itself takes the well-travelled way to the motor centre, and releases the motor impulse.” (Mind, xr. 232-3.)—Finally, Prof. Lipps has, in his elaborate way (Grundtatsachen, 179-188), made mince-meat of the view that stage 3 involves either conscious perception or conscious will. * Physiol. Psych., 5d edition (1887), vol. 11. p. 266. + Philosophische Studien, vol. 1v. p. 479 (1888). GENERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY. 93 one keeps one’s mind as intent as possible apon the ex- pected signal, and ‘ purposely avoids ’* thinking of the move- ment to be executed; in the ‘extreme muscular’ way one ‘does not think at all’ + of the signal, but stands as ready as possible for the movement. The muscular reactions are much shorter than the sensorial ones, the average differ- ence being in the neighborhood of a tenth of a second. Wuadt accordingly calls them ‘shortened reactions’ and, with Lange, admits them to be mere reflexes; whilst the sensorial reactions he calls ‘complete,’ and holds to his original conception as far as they are concerned. The facts, however, do not seem to me to warrant even this amount of fidelity to the original Wundtian position. When we begin to react in the ‘extreme sensorial’ way, Lange says that we get times so very long that they must be rejected from the count as non-typical. “Only after the reacter has succeeded by repeated and conscientious practice in bringing about an extremely precise co-ordina- tion of his voluntary impulse with nis sense-impression do we get times which can be regarded as typicai sensorial reaction-times.” + Now it seems to me that these excessive and ‘ untypical’ times are probably the real ‘ complete times,’ the only ones in which distinct processes of actual percep- tion and volition occur (see above, pp. 88-9). The typicai sensorial time which is attained by practice is probabiy another sort of reflex, less perfect than the reflexes pre- pared by straining one’s attention towards the movement. § The times are much more variable in the sensorial way than in the muscular. The several muscular reactions differ little from each other. Only in them does the phe- nomenon occur of reacting on a false signal, or of reacting before the signal. Times intermediate between these two types occur according as the attention fails to turn itself exclusively to one of the extremes. It is obvious that Herr Lange’s distinction between the two types of reaction 1s a highly important one, and that the ‘extreme muscuiar * Loc. cit. p. 488. + Loc. cit. p. 487. t Loc. cit. p. 489. § Lange has an interesting hypothesis as to the brain-process concerned in the Jatter, for which I can only refer to his essay. 94 PSYCHOLOGY. method,’ giving both the shortest times and the most con- stant ones, ought to be aimed at in all comparative investi- gations. Herr Lange’s own muscular time averaged 0.123 ; his sensorial time, 0’’.230. These reaction-time experiments are then in no sense measurements of the swiftness of thought. Only when we complicate them is there a chance for anything like an intellectual operation to occur. ‘They may be complicated mm various ways. The reaction may be withheld until the signal has consciously awakened a distinct idea (Wundt’s discrimination-time, association-time) and then performed. Or there may be a variety of possibie signals, each with a different reaction assigned to it, and the reacter may be uncertain which one he is about to receive. The reaction would then hardly seem to occur without a pre- jimimary recognition and choice. We shall see, however, in the appropriate chapters, that the discrimination and choice involved in such a reaction are widely different from the intellectual operations of which we are ordinarily con- scious under those names. Meanwhile the simple reaction- time remains as the starting point of all these superinduced complications. It is the fundamental physiological con- stant in all time-mexsurements. As such, its own variations have an interest, and must be briefly passed in review.* The reaction-time varies with the individual and his age. An individual may have it particularly long in respect of signais of one sense (Buccola, p. 147), but not of others. Old and uncultivated people have it long (nearly a second, in an oid pauper observed by Exner, Pfliiger’s Archiv, vir. 612-4). Children have it long (half a second, Herzen in Buccola, p. 152). Practice shortens it to a quantity which is for each indi- vidual a minimum beyond which no farther reduction can be made. The aforesaid old paupex’s time was, alter much practice, reauced to 0.1866 sec. (loc. cit. p. 626). * The reader who wishes to know more about the matter will find a most faithful compilation of all that kas been done, together with much original matter, in G. Buccola’s ‘Legge del Tempo,’ etc. See also chap- ter xvi of Wundt’s Physiol. Psychology ; Exner in Hermann’s Hdbch., Bd. 2, Thi. m. pp. 252-280; also Ribot’s Contemp. Germ. Psych. chap. VIII. GHNERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY. 95 Fatigue lengthens it. Concentration of attention shortens it. Details will be given in the chapter on Attention. The nature of the signal makes it vary.* Wundt writes: ‘‘T found that the reaction-time for impressions on the skin with electric stimulus is less than for true touch-sensations, as the following averages show: Average, wee Sounds e- ree ence eee ORG Tesee: 0.0221 see. | LISS. 0 eR OR ea 05222" te 0.0219 ‘ Electric skin-sensation...... 0:201 “* De@illay Ce Mouch=SensAniONs).. 4-6... -.0s21o 0.0134 ‘ ‘‘T here bring together the averages which have been obtained by some other observers : Hirsch. Hankel. Exner. SONG Ee Oboe ne cere 0.149 0.1505 0.1360 Meile tee sees tes Ose 0.200 0.2246 0.1506 Skin-sensation. .... ....0.182 0.1546 021337 7 Thermic reactions have been lately;measured by A. Goldscheider and by Vintschgau (1887), who find them slower than reactions from touch. That from heat espe- cially is very slow, more so than from cold, the differences (according to Goldscheider) depending on the nerve-ter- minations in the skin. Gustatory reactions were measured by Vintschgau. They differed according to the substances used, running up to half a second as a maximum when identification took place. The mere perception of the presence of the substance on the tongue varied from 0.159 to 0.219 (Pfliiger’s Archiv, XIV. 529). Olfactory reactions have been studied by Vintschgau, *The nature of the movement also seems to make it vary. Mr. B. I. Gilman and I reacted to the same signal by simply raising our hand, and again by carrying our hand towards our back. The moment registered was always that at which the hand broke an electric contact in starting to move. But it started one or two hundredths of a second later when the more extensive movement was the one to be made. Orchansky, on the other hand, experimenting on contractions of the masseter muscle, found (Archiv f. (Anat. u.) Physiol., 1889, p. 187) that the greater the amplitude of contraction intended, the shorter grew the time of reaction. He _ explains this by the fact that a more ample contraction makes a greater appeal to the attention, and that this shortens the times. + Physiol. Psych., 11. 2238. 26 PSYCHOLOG Y. Buccola, and Beaunis. They are slow, averaging about half a second (cf. Beaunis, Recherches exp. sur l’ Activité Cérébrale, 1884, p. 49 ff). It will be observed that sownd is more promptly reacted on than either sight or touch. Taste and smell are slower than either. One individual, who reacted to touch upon the tip of the tongue in 0.125, took 0.993 to react upon the taste of quinine applied to the same spot. In another, upon the base of the tongue, the reaction to touch being 0”.141, that to sugar was 0.552 (Vintschgau, quoted by Buccola, p.103). Buccola found the reaction to odors to vary from 0”.334 to 0.681, according to the perfume used and the individual. The intensity of the signal makes a difference. The in- tenser the stimulus the shorter the time. Herzen (Grund- linien einer allgem. Psychophysiologie, p. 101) compared the reaction from a corn on the toe with that from the skin of the hand of the same subject. The two places were stimulated simultaneously, and the subject tried to react simultaneously with both hand and foot, but the foot always went quickest. When the sound skin of the foot was touched instead of the corn, it was the hand which always reacted first. Wundt tries to show that when the signal is made barely perceptible, the time is probably the same in all the senses, namely, about 0.332” (Physiol. Psych., 2d ed., 11. 224). Where the signal is of touch, the place to which it is applied makes a difference in the resultant reaction-time. G. S. Hall and V. Kries’ found (Archiv f. Anat. u. Physiol., 1879) that when the finger-tip was the place the reaction was shorter than when the middle of the upper arm was used, in spite of the greater length of nerve-trunk to be traversed in the latter case. This discovery invalidates the measurements of the rapidity of transmission of the current in human nerves, for they are all based on the method of comparing reaction-times from places near the root and near the extremity of a limb. The same observers found that signals seen by the periphery of the retina gave longer times than the same signals seen by direct vision. The season makes a difference, the time being some hun- GENERAL CONDITIONS OF BRAIN-ACTIVITY. 97 dredths of a second shorter on cold winter days (Vintschgau apud Exner, Hermann’s Hdbh., p. 270). Intoxicants alter the time. Coffee and tea appear to shorten it. Small doses of wine and alcohol first shorten and then lengthen it; but the shortening stage tends to disap- pear if a large dose be given immediately. This, at least, is the report of two German observers. Dr. J. W. Warren, whose observations are more thorough than any previous ones, could find no very decided effects from ordinary doses (Journal of Physiology, vu. 311). Morphia lengthens the time.