[Ill 1 1 IBS IN UK I i '• » il Mi ' I I I - II mm I ! i I ■ ,i! 1 SHUIII! III II -t.es> Ci- ' REESE LIBRARY UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA. Received... ^r&*■ 2~S~/3 0—' Shelf Ni C* A REVIEW OF EDWARDS'S "INQUIRY INTO THE FREEDOM OF THE WILL.*' CONTAINING I. STATEMENT OF EDWARDS'S SYSTEM. II. THE LEGITIMATE CONSEQUENCES OF THIS SYSTEM. III. AN EXAMINATION OF THE ARGUMENTS AGAINST A SELF- DETERMINING WILL. BY HENRY PHILIP TAPPAN. I am afraid th«lf Edwards's book (however wett rivKanl,) has done much harm in Enjland/as it ha3 secured a favourable hearing to the same doc- trincs, which, sihca^tha, time of Clarke, had been generally ranked among the most dangerous errocs of Hobbes and his disciples." — Dugald Stewart. NEW-YORK : JOHN S. TAYLOR, THEOLOGICAL PUBLISHER AND BOOKSELLER, BRICK CHURCH CHAPEL, 1839. Entered according to the Act of Congress, in the yoar 1839, by HENRY PHILIP TAPPAN, in the Clerk's Office of tho District Court of the United States, for the Southern District of New-York. 2 sr/3 *- Q, F. Hopkine, Printer, 2 Ann-street. INTRODUCTION. Discussions respecting the will, have, unhappily, been confounded with theological opinions, and hence have led to theological controversies, where predilections for a particular school or sect, have generally prejudged the conclusions of philosophy. As a part of the mental constitution, the will must be subjected to the legitimate methods of psycho- logical investigation, and must abide the result. If we enter the field of human consciousness in the free, fearless, and honest spirit of Baconian observation in order to arrive at the laws of the reason or the imagination, what should prevent us from pursuing the same enlightened course in reference to the will I Is it because responsibility and the duties of morality and religion are more immediately con- IV INTRODUCTION. nectcd with the will ? This, indeed, throws so- lemnity around our investigations, and warns us of caution ; but, at the same time, so far from re- pressing investigation, it affords the highest reason why we should press it to the utmost limit of con- sciousness. Nothing surely can serve more to fix our impressions of moral obligation, or to open our eye to the imperishable truth and excellency of religion, than a clear and ripe knowledge of that, which makes us the subjects of duty. As a believer in philosophy, I claim unbounded liberty of thought, and by thinking I hope to arrive at truth. As a believer in the Bible I always antici- pate that the truths to which philosophy leads me, will harmonize with its facts and doctrines. If in the result there should appear to be a colli- sion, it imposes upon me the duty of re-examining both my philosophy and my interpretation of the text. In this way I may in the end remove the difficulty, and not only so, but even gain from the temporary and apparent collision, a deeper insight into both philosophy and religion. If the difficul- INTRODUCTION. V ty cannot be removed, then it remains a vexed point. It does not follow, however, that I must either renounce the philosophical conclusion, or remove the text. If the whole of philosophy or its leading truths were in opposition to the whole of revelation or its leading truths, we should then evidently be placed on the alternative of denying one or the other ; but as the denial of philosophy would be the destruction of reason, there would no longer remain in our being any principle on which a re- velation could be received. Such a collision would therefore disprove the claims of any sys- tem to be from Heaven. But let us suppose, on the other hand, that with every advance of phi- losophy the facts of the Bible are borne aloft, and their divine authority and their truth made more manifest, have we not reason to bless the re- searches which have enabled us to perceive more clearly the light from Heaven? A system of truth does not fear, it courts philosophical scruti- ny. Its excellency will be most resplendent 1* VI INTRODUCTION. when it lias had the most fiery trial of thought. Nothing would so weaken my faith in the Bible as the fact of being compelled to tremble for its safety whenever I claimed and exercised the pre- rogative of reason. And what I say of it as a whole, I say of doctrines claiming to be derived from it. Theologists are liable to impose upon them- selves when they argue from the truths of the Bible to the truths of their philosophy ; either un- der the view that the last are deducible from the former, or that they serve to account for and confirm the former. How often is their philoso- phy drawn from some other source, or handed down by old authority, and rendered venerable by associations arbitrary and accidental ; and in- stead of sustaining the simplicity of the Bible, the doctrine is perhaps cast into the mould of the philosophy. It is a maxim commended by reason and con- firmed by experience, that in pursuing our inves- tigations in any particular science we are to con- INTRODUCTION. Vll fine ourselves rigorously to its subjects and meth- ods, neither seeking nor fearing collision with any other science. We may feel confident that ulti- mately science will be found to link with science, forming a universal and harmonious system of truth ; but this can by no means form the princi- ple of our particular investigations. The appli- cation of this maxim is no less just and necessary where a philosophy or science holds a relation to revelation. It js a matter of the highest interest that in the developements of such philosophy or science, it should be found to harmonize with the revelation ; but nevertheless this cannot be re- ceived as the principle on which we shall aim to develope it. If there is a harmony, it must be discovered ; it cannot be invented and made. The Cardinals determined upon the authority of Scripture, as they imagined, what the science of astronomy must be, and compelled the old man Gallileo to give the lie to his reason ; and since then, the science of geology has been at- tempted, if not to be settled, at least to be limited VIU INTRODUCTION. in its researches in the same way. Science, however, has pursued her steady course resistless- ly, settling her own bounds and methods, and se- lecting her own fields, and giving to the world her own discoveries. And is the truth of the Bi- ble unsettled ? No. The memory of Gallileo and of Cuvicr is blessed by the same lips which name the name of Christ. Now we ask the same independence of research in the philosophy of the human mind, and no less with respect to the Will than with respect to any other faculty. We wish to make this purely a psychological question. Let us not ask what phi- losophy is demanded by Calvinism in opposition to Pelagianism and Arminianism, or by the lat- ter in opposition to the former ; let us ask simply for the laws of our being. In the end we may present another instance of truth honestly and fearlessly sought in the legitimate exercise of our natural reason, harmonizing with truths revealed. One thing is certain ; the Bible no more pro- fesses to be a system of formal mental philoso- INTRODUCTION. IX phy, than it professes to contain the sciences of astronomy and geology. If mental philosophy is given there, it is given in facts of history, indi- vidual and national, in poetry, prophecy, law, and ethics : and as thus given, must be collected into a system by observation and philosophical criti- cism. But observations upon these external facts could not possibly be made independently of observations upon internal facts — the facts of the conscious- ness ; and the principles of philosophical criticism can be obtained only in the same way. To him who looks not within himself, poetry, history, law, ethics, and the distinctions of character and con- duct, would necessarily be unintelligible. No one therefore can search the Bible for its philoso- phy, who has not already read philosophy in his own being. We shall find this amply confirmed in the whole history of theological opinion. Eve- ry interpreter of the Bible, every author of a creed, every founder of a sect, plainly enough reveals both the principles of his philosophy and their in- * INTRODUCTION. flucnce upon himself. Every man who reflects and aims to explain, is necessarily a philosopher, and has his philosophy. Instead therefore of pro- fessing to oppose the Bible to philosophy, or in- stead of the pretence of deducing our philosophy solely and directly from the Bible, let us openly declare that we do not discard philosophy, but seek it in its own native fields ; and that inasmuch as it has a being and a use, and is related to all that we know and do, we are therefore determined to pursue it in a pure, truth-loving spirit. I am aware, however, that the doctrine of the will is so intimately associated with great and venerable names, and has so long worn a theo- logical complexion, that it is well nigh impossible to disintegrate it. The authority of great and good men, and theological interests, even when we are disposed to be candid, impartial, and in- dependent, do often insensibly influence our rea- sonings. It is out of respect to these old associations and prejudices, and from the wish to avoid all unne- INTRODUCTION. XI cessary strangeness of manner in handling an old subject, and more than all, to meet what are re- garded by many as the weightiest and most con- clusive reasonings on this subject, that I open this discussion with a review of M Edwards's Inquiry into the Freedom of the Will." There is no work of higher authority among those who deny the self-determining power of the will ; and none which on this subject has called forth more gene- ral admiration for acuteness of thought and logi- cal subtelty. I believe ttiere is a prevailing im- pression that Edwards must be fairly met in order to make any advance in an opposite argument. I propose no less than this attempt, presumptuous though it may seem, yet honest and made for truth's sake. Truth is greater and more venera- ble than the names of great and venerable men, or of great and venerable sects: and I cannot be- lieve that I seek truth with a proper love and veneration, unless I seek her, confiding in herself alone, neither asking the authority of men in her support, nor fearing a collision with them, how- ill INTRODUCTION. ever great their authority may be. It is my inter- est to think and believe aright, no less than to act aright : and as right action is meritorious not when compelled and accidental, but when free and made under the perception and conviction of right principles; so also right thinking and believ- ing are meritorious, either in an intellectual or moral point of view, when thinking and believing are something more than gulping down dogmas because Austin, or Calvin, or Arminius, presents the cup. Facts of history or of description are legitimate- ly received on testimony, but truths of our moral and spiritual being can be received only on the evidence of consciousness, unless the testimony be from God himself; and even in this case we ex- pect that the testimony, although it may tran- scend consciousness, shall not contradict it. The internal evidence of the Bible under the highest point of view, lies in this : that although there be revelations of that which transcends conscious- ness, yet wherever the truths come within the INTRODUCTION. XI11 sphere of consciousness, there is a perfect harmo- ny between the decisions of developed reason and the revelation. Now in the application of these principles, if Edwards have given us a true psychology in re- lation to the will, we have the means of knowing it. In the consciousness, and in the conscious- ness alone, can a doctrine of the will be ultimate- ly and adequately tested. Nor must we be in- timidated from making this test by the assump- tion that the theory of Edwards alone sustains moral responsibility and evangelical religion. Mor- al responsibility and evangelical religion, if sus- tained and illustrated by philosophy, must take a philosophy which has already on its own grounds proved itself a true philosophy. Moral responsi- bility and evangelical religion can derive no sup- port from a philosophy which they are taken first to prove. But although I intend to conduct my argu- ment rigidly on psychological principles, I shall endeavour in the end to show that moral respon- 2 XIV INTRODUCTION. sibility is really sustained by this exposition of the will; and that I have not, to say the least, weakened one of the supports of evangelical reli- gion, nor shorn it of one of its glories. The plan of my undertaking embraces the fol- lowing particulars : I. A statement of Edwards's system. II. The legitimate consequences of this sys- tem. III. An examination of the arguments against a self-determining will. IV. The doctrine of the will determined by an appeal to consciousness. V. This doctrine viewed in connexion with moral agency and responsibility. VI. This doctrine viewed in connexion with the truths and precepts of the Bible. The first three complete the review of Edwards, and make up the present volume. Another vol- ume is in the course of preparation. A STATEMENT OF EDWARDS'S SYSTEM. Edwards's System, or, in other words, his Philo- sophy of the Will, is contained in part I. of his " Inquiry into the Freedom of the Will.'' This part comprises five sections, which I shall give with their titles in his own order. My object is to arrive at truth. I shall therefore use my best endeavours to make this statement with the ut- most clearness and fairness. In this part of my work, my chief anxiety is to have Edwards per- fectly understood. My quotations are made from the edition published by S. Converse, New-York, 1829. "Sec I. — Concerning the Nature of tub Will." Edwards under this title gives his definition of the will. "TAe will is, that by which the mind chooses anything. The faculty of the will, is that power, or principle of mind, by which it is ilcasing or ap- pears most agreeable to the mind. This conclusion is in perfect accordance with the position with which Edwards set out: that edwards's system. 25 will is always as the preponderating desire ; in- deed, that the will is the same in kind with de- sire, or with the affections ; and an act of will or choice, nothing more than the strongest desire in reference to an immediate object, and a desire producing an effect in our mental or physical be- ing. The determination of will is the strongest excitement of passion. That which determines will is the cause of passion. The strength of the cause lies in its perceived tendency to excite the passions and afford enjoyment. As possessing this tendency, it is called good, or pleasing, or agreeable ; that is, suiting the state of the mind or the condition of the affections. The "good" which forms the characteristic of a cause or motive is an immediate good, or a good " in the present view of the mind." (p. 21.) Thus a drunkard, before he drinks, maybe supposed to weigh against each other the present pleasure of drinking and the remote painful consequences: and the painful consequences may appear to him to be greater than the present pleasure. But still the question truly in his mind, when he comes to drink, respects the present act of drinking only ; and if this seems to him most pleasing, then he drinks. " If he wills to drink, then drinking is the proper object of the act of his will ; and drink- 3 2G STATEMENT OF ing, on some account or other, now appears most agreeable to him, and suits him best. If he chooses to refrain, then refraining is the imme- diate object of his will, and is most pleasing to Ipiii." The reasoning is, that when the drunkard drinks, we are not to conclude that he has chosen future misery over future good, but that the act of drinking, in itself, is the object of choice ; so that, in the view he has taken of it, it is to him the greatest apparent good. In general we may say, in accordance with this principle, that when- ever the act of choice takes place, the object of that act comes up before the mind in such a way as to seem most pleasing to the mind ; it is at the moment, and in the immediate relation, the great- est apparent good. The man thus never chooses what is disagreeable, but always what is agree- able to him. Proper use of the term most agreeable, in relation to the Will. "I have chosen rather to express myself thus, that the will always is as the greatest apparent good, or as what appears most agreeable, than to say the will is determined by the greatest appa- rent good, or by what seems most agreeable ; be- Edwards's system. -~ cause an appearing most agreeable to the mind, and the mind's preferring, seem scarcely distinct. If strict propriety of speech be insisted on, it may more properly be said, that the voluntary action, which is the immediate consequence of the mind's choice, is determined by that which appears most agreeable, than the choice itself." (p. 21, 22.) Here the perception or sense of the ?nost agreeable is identified in express terms with volition or choice. " The will is as the most agreeable," — that is, the determination of icill, which means its actual choice, as a fact of the consciousness is em- braced in the sense of the most agreeable ; and as the voluntary action, or the action, or change, or effect, following volition, in any part of our be- ing,— as to walk, or talk, or read, or think, — has its cause in the volition, or the " mind's choice," — so it is entirely proper to say, either that this voluntary action is determined by the voli- tion or that it is determined by the sense of the most agreeable. Edwards's meaning plain- ly is, that the terms are convertible : volition may be called the cause of voluntary action, or the sense of the most agreeable may be called the cause. This is still a carrying out of the position, that the icill is as the desire. " The greatest apparent good" being identical with "the most 28 STATEMENT OF agreeable," and this again being identical with the most desirable, it must follow, that whenever, in relation to any object, the mind is affected with the sense of the most agreeable, it presents the phenomenon of "volition" or "choice;"' and still farther, that which is chosen is the most agreea- ble object, and is known to be such by the sim- ple fact that it is chosen ; for its being chosen, means nothing more than that it affects the mind with the sense of the most agreeable, — and the most agreeable is that which is chosen, and can- not be otherwise than chosen ; for its being most agreeable, means nothing more than that it is the object of the mind's choice or sense of the most agreeable. The object, and the mind regarded as a sensitive or willing power, are correlatives, and choice is the unition of both : so that if we regard choice as characterizing the object, then the object is affirmed to be the most agreeable ; and if, on the other side, we regard choice as characterizing the mind, then the mind is affirmed to be affected with the sense of the most agree- able. Cause of Choice, or of the sense of the most agreeable. "Volition itself is always determined by that EDWARDS'S SYSTEM. in or about the mind's view of the object, which causes it to appear most agreeable. I say in or about the ?nind's viae of the object ; because what has influence to render an object in view agreea- ble, is not only what appears in the object view- ed, but also the manner of the view, and the state and circumstances of the mind that views." (p. 22.) Choice being the unition of the mind's sensi- tivity and the object, — that is, being an affection of the sensitivity, by reason of its perfect agree- ment and correlation with the object, and of course of the perfect agreement and correlation of the object with the sensitivity, — in determin- ing the cause of choice, we must necessarily look both to the mind and the object. Edwards ac- cordingly gives several particulars in relation to each. I. In relation to the object, the sense of the most agreeable, or choice, will depend upon, — 1. The beauty of the object, "viewing it as it is in itself," independently of circumstances. 2. " The apparent degree of pleasure or trouble attending the object, or the consequence of it," or the object taken with its "concomitants" and con- sequences. 3. " The apparent state of the pleasure or trou- 3* 80 STATEMENT OP blc that appears with respect to distance of time. It is a thing in itself agreeable to the mind, to have pleasure speedily ; and disagreeable to have it delayed." (p. 22.) II. In relation to mind, the sense of agreeable- ness will depend, first, upon the manner of the mind's view ; secondly, upon the state of mind. Edwards, under the first, speaks of the object as connected with future pleasure. Here the manner of the mind's view will have influence in two respects : 1. The certainty or uncertainty which the mind judges to attach to the pleasure ; 2. The liveliness of the sense, or of the ima- gination, which the mind has of it. Now these may be in different degrees, com- pounded with different degrees of pleasure, con- sidered in itself; and "the agreeableness of a proposed object of choice will be in a degree some way compounded of the degree of good supposed by the judgement, the degree of apparent proba- bility or certainty of that good, and the degree of liveliness of the idea the mind has of that good." (p. 23.) Secondly : In reference to objects generally, whether connected with present or future pleas- ure, the sense of agreeableness will depend also edvvards's system. 31 upon " the state of the mind which views a pro- posed object of choice." (p. 24.) Here we have to consider U the particular temper which the mind has by nature, or that has been introduced or established by education, example, custom, or some other means ; or the frame or state that the mind is in on a particular occasion." (ibid.) Edwards here suggests, that it may be unneces- sary to consider the state of the mind as a ground of agreeableness distinct from the two already mentioned : viz. — the nature and circumstances of the object, and the manner of the view. "Per- haps, if we strictly consider the matter," he re- v- marks, " the different temper and state of the mind makes no alteration as to the agreeableness of objects in any other way, than as it makes the objects themselves appear differently, beautiful or deformed, having apparent pleasure or pain at- tending them ; and as it occasions the manner of the view to be different, causes the idea of beauty or deformity, pleasure or uneasiness, to be more or less lively." (ibid.) In this remark, Edwards shows plainly how completely he makes mind and \j object to run together in choice, or how perfect a unition of the two, choice is. The state of the mind is manifested only in relation to the nature and circumstances of the object ; and the sense of ;{>_' STATKMEN'T or agrccablcness being in the correlation of the two, (In st nse of tie most agn < able or choice is such a perfect unition of tiie two, that, having described the object in its nature and circumstances in re- lation to the most agreeable, we have compre- hended in this the state of mind. On the other hand, the nature and circumstances of the object, in relation to the most agreeable, can be known only by the state of mind produced by the pres- ence of the object and its circumstances. To give an example, — let a rose be the object. When I describe the beauty and agreeableness of this object, I describe the state of mind in rela- tion to it ; for its beauty and agreeableness are identical with the sensations and emotions which I experience, — hence, in philosophical language, called the secondary qualities of the object : and so, on the other hand, if I describe my sensations and emotions in the presence of the rose, I do in fact describe its beauty and agreeableness. The mind and object are thus united in the sense of agreeableness. I could not have this sense of agreeableness without an object ; but when the object is presented to my mind, they are so made for each other, that they seem to melt together in the pleasurable emotion. The sense of the most agreeable or choice maybe illustrated in the same EDWAIlDS's SYSTEM. 33 way. The only difference between the agreea- ble simply and the most agreeable is this : the agreeable refers merely to an emotion awakened on the immediate presentation of an object, with- out any comparison or competition. The most agreeable takes place where there is comparison and competition. Thus, to prefer or choose a rose above a violet is a sense of the most agreea- ble of the two. In some cases, however, that which is refused is positively disagreeable. The choice, in strictness of speech, in these cases, is only a sense of the agreeable. As, however, in every instance of choosing, there are two terms formed by contemplating the act of choosing itself in the contrast of positive and negative, the phrase most agreeable or greatest apparent good is con- venient for general use, and sufficiently precise to express every case which comes up. It may be well here to remark, that in the sys- tem we are thus endeavouring to state and to illus- trate, the word choice is properly used to express the action of will, when that action is viewed in relation to its immediate effects, — as when I say, I choose to walk. The sense of the most agreea- ble, is properly used to express the same action, when the action is viewed in relation to its own cause. Choice and volition are the words in com- 34 \ti:ment of nion use, because men at large only think of choice and volition in reference to effects. But when the cause of choice is sought after by a philosophic mind, and is supposed to lie in the nature and cir- cumstances of mind and object, then the sense of (he most agreeable becomes the most appropriate form of expression. Edwards concludes his discussion of the cause yj of the most agreeable, by remarking: "However, I think so much is certain, — that volition, in no one instance that can be mentioned, is otherwise than the greatest apparent good is, in the manner which has been explained." This is the great principle of his system ; and, a few sentences af- ter, he states it as an axiom, or a generally admit- ted truth : " There is scarcely a plainer and more universal dictate of the sense and experience of mankind, than that when men act voluntarily and do what they please, then they do what suits them best, or what is most agreeable to them." In- deed, Edwards cannot be considered as having attempted to prove this ; he has only explained it, and therefore it is only the explanation of a sup- posed axiom that we have been following out. This supposed axiom is really announced in the first section : " Will and desire do not run coun- ter at all : the thing which he wills, the very same edwards's system. 35 he desires ;" that is, a man wills as he desires, and of course wills what is most agreeable to him. It is to be noticed, also, that the title of part I. runs as follows : " Wherein are explained and stated various terms and things, &c." Receiving it, therefore, as a generally admitted truth, " that choice or volition is always as the most agreea- ble," and is itself only the sense of the most agree- able, what is the explanation given ? 1. That will, or the faculty of choice, is not a faculty distinct from the affections or passions, or that part of our being which philosophers some- times call the sensitivity. 2. That volition, or choice, or preference, being at any given moment and under any given cir- cumstances the strongest inclination, or the strong- est affection and desire with regard to an imme- diate object, appears in the constitution of our be- ing as the antecedent of effects in the mind itself, or in the body ; which effects are called volunta- ry actions, — as acts of attention, or of talking, or walking. 3. To say that volition is as the desire, is equiv- alent to saying that volition is as the "greatest apparent good," which again means only the most agreeable, — so that the volition becomes again the sense or feeling of the greatest apparent good. 36 STATEMENT OF There is in all this only a variety of expressions tor the same affection of the sensitivity. i. Determination of will is actual choice, or the production in the mind of volition, or choice, or the strongest affection, or the sense of the most agreeable, or of the greatest apparent good. It is therefore an effect, and must have a determiner or cause. 5. This determiner or cause is called motive. In explaining what constitutes the motive, we must take into view both mind and object. The object must be perceived by the mind as some- thing existent. This perception, however, is only preliminary, or a mere introduction of the object to the mind. Now, in order that the sense of the most agreeable, or choice, may take place, the mind and object must be suited to each other ; they must be correlatives. The object must pos- sess qualities of beauty and agreeableness to the mind. The mind must possess a susceptibility agreeable to the qualities of the object. But to say that the object possesses qualities of beauty and agreeableness to the mind, is in fact to affirm that the mind has the requisite susceptibility; for these qualities of the object have a being, and are what they are only in relation to mind. Choice, or the sense of agreeableness, may therefore be called the unition of the sensitivity and the object. edwards's system. 37 Choice is thus, like any emotion or passion, a fact perpetually appearing in the consciousness ; and, like emotion or passion ; and, indeed, being a mere form of emotion and passion, must ultimate- ly be accounted for by referring it to the consti- tution of our being. But inasmuch as the consti- tution of our being manifests itself in relation to objects and circumstances, we do commonly ac- count for its manifestations by referring them to the objects and circumstances in connexion with which they take place, and without which they would not take place ; and thus, as we say, the cause of passion is the object of passion : so we say also, in common parlance, the cause of choice is the object of choice ; and assigning the affections of the mind springing up in the presence of the object, to the object, as descriptive of its qualities, we say that choice is always as the most beauti- ful and agreeable ; that is, as the greatest appa- rent good. This greatest apparent good, thus ob- jectively described, is the motive, or determiner, or cause of volition. In what sense the Will follows the last dictate of the Understanding. "It appears from these things, that in some 4 38 STATEMENT OF sense the will always follows ih< Inst dictate of the understanding. But then the understanding must be taken in a large sense, as including the whole faculty of perception or apprehension, and not merely what is called reason or judgement. If by the dictate of the understanding is meant what reason declares to be best, or most for the per- son's happiness, taking in the whole of its dura- tion, it is not true that the will always follows the last dictate of the understanding. Such a dictate of reason is quite a different matter from things appearing now most agreeable, all things being put together which relates to the mind's present perceptions in any respect." (p. 25.) The " large sense " in which Edwards takes the understand- ing, embraces the whole intellectual and sensitive being. In the production of choice, or the sense of the most agreeable, the suggestions of reason may have their influence, and may work in with other particulars to bring about the result ; but then they are subject to the same condition with the other particulars, — they must appear, at the moment and in the immediate circumstances, the most agreeable. It is not enough that they come from reason, and are true and right ; they must likewise suit the state of the mind, — for as choice is the sense of the most agreeable, that only as an EDWARDS S SYSTEM. 311 object can tend to awaken this sense, which is properly and agreeably related to the feelings of the subject. Where the suggestions of reason are not agreeably related, " the act of the will is de- termined in opposition to it." (ibid.) " Sec. III. — Concerning the meaning of the terms Necessity, Impossibility, Inability, &C AND OF CoNTINGENCE." After having settled his definition of choice or volition, and explained the cause of the same, Ed- wards takes up the nature of the connexion be- tween this cause and effect : viz. motive and vo- lition. Is this connexion a necessary connexion ? In order to determine this point, and to explain his view of it, he proceeds to discuss the meaning of the terms contained in the above title. This section is entirely occupied with this preliminary discussion. Edwards makes two kinds of necessity : 1. Ne- cessity as understood in the common or vulgar use ; 2. Necessity as understood in the philosoph- ical or metaphysical use. 1. In common use, necessity "is a relative term, and relates to some supposed opposition made to the existence of a thing, — which opposition is 40 STATEMENT OF overcome or proves insufficient to hinder or alter it. The word impossible is manifestly a relative term, and has reference to supposed power exert- ed to bring a thing to pass which is insufficient for the effect. The word unable is relative, and has relation to ability, or endeavour, which is in- sufficient. The word irresistible is relative, and has reference to resistance which is made, or may be made, to some force or power tending to an effect, and is insufficient to withstand the power or hinder the effect. The common notion of ne- cessity and impossibility implies something that frustrates endeavour or desire." He then distinguishes this necessity into gene- ral and particular. "Things are necessary in general, which are or will be, notwithstanding any supposable opposition, from whatever quar- ter :M e. g. that God will judge the world. " Things are necessary to us which are or will be, notwithstanding all opposition supposable in the case from us." This is particular necessity: e. g. any event which / cannot hinder. In the discussions " about liberty and moral agency," the word is used especially in a particular sense, be- cause we are concerned in these discussions as individuals. According to this common use of necessity in edwards's system. 41 the particular sense, "When we speak of any thing necessary to us, it is with relation to some supposable opposition to our wills ;" and " a thing is said to be necessary" in this sense "when we cannot help it, do what ice will." So also a thing is said to be impossible to us when we cannot do it, although we make the attempt, — that is, put forth the volition ; and irresistible to us, which, when we put forth a volition to hinder it, over- comes the opposition : and we are unable to do a thing " when our supposable desires and endeav- ours are insufficient," — are not followed by any effect. In the common or vulgar use of these terms, we are not considering volition in relation to its own cause ; but we are considering volition as itself a cause in relation to its own effects : e. g. suppose a question be raised, whether a cer- tain man can raise a certain weight, — if it be af- firmed that it is impossible for him to raise it, that he has not the ability to raise it, and that the weight will necessarily keep its position, — no ref- erence whatever is made to the production of a volition or choice to raise it, but solely to the con- nexion between the volition and the raising of the weight. Now Edwards remarks, that this com- mon use of the term necessity and its cognates being habitual, is likely to enter into and confound 4* 42 STATi:.Mi..vr or our reasonings on subjects where it is inadmissi- ble from the nature of the case. We must there- fore be careful to discriminate, (p. 27.) 2. In metaphysical or philosophical use, neces- sity is not a relative, but an absolute term. In this use necessity applies " in cases wherein no insuf- ficient will is supposed, or can be supposed ; but the very nature of the supposed case itself ex- cludes any opposition, will, or endeavour." (ibid.) Thus it is used " with respect to God's existence before the creation of the world, when there was no other being." " Metaphysical or philosophical necessity is nothing different from certainty, — not the certainty of knowledge, but the certainty of things in themselves, which is the foundation of the certainty of knowledge, or that wherein lies the ground of the infallibility of the proposition which affirms them. Philosophical necessity is really nothing else than the full and fixed connex- ion between the things signified by the subject and predicate of a proposition which affirms some- thing to be true ; and in this sense I use the word necessity, in the following discourse, when I en- deavour to prove that necessity is not inconsistent with liberty" (p. 27, 28, 29.) "The subject and predicate of a proposition which affirms the existence of something, mav ^ ib. UlTIVEESIl edwards's system. V^ Oa . 48 have a full, fixed, and certain connexion, in seve ral ways."' " ] . They may have a full and perfect connex- ion in and of themselves. So God's infinity and other attributes are necessary. So it is neces- sary, in its own nature, that two and two should be four." 2, The subject and predicate of a proposition, affirming the existence of something which is al- ready come to pass, are fixed and certain. 3. The subject and predicate of a proposition may be fixed and certain consequentially, — and so the existence of the things affirmed may be " consequentially necessary." " Things which are perfectly connected with the things that are neces- sary, are necessary themselves, by a necessity of consequence." This is logical necessity. " And here it may be observed, that all things which are future, or which will hereafter begin to be, which can be said to be necessary, are neces- sary only in this last way," — that is, "by a cou- nt > ion with something that is necessary in its own nature, or something that already is or has been. This is the necessity which especially be- longs to controversies about acts of the will." (p. 30.) Philosophical necessity is general and particu- 44 BTATBMBHT OP far. 1. "The existence of a thing may be said to be necessary with a general necessity, when all things considered there is a foundation for the certainty ofits existence." This is unconditional necessity in the strictest s< nse. 2. Particular necessity refers to " things that happen to particular persons, in the existence of which no will of theirs has any concern, at least at that time ; which, whether they are necessary or not with regard to things in general, yet are necessary to them, and with regard to any voli- tion of theirs at that time, as they prevent all acts of the will about the affair." (p. 31.) This particular necessity is absolute to the individual, because his will has nothing to do with it — whether it be absolute or not in the general sense, does not affect his case. " What has been said to show the meaning of terms necessary and necessity, may be sufficient for the explaining of the opposite terms impossible and impossibility. For there is no difference, but only the latter are negative and the former posi- tive." (ibid.) Inability and Unable. " It has been observed that these terms in their EDWARDS S SYSTEM. 45 original and common use, have relation to will and endeavour, as supposable in the case." That is have relation to the connexion of volition with effects. " But as these terms are often used by philosophers and divines, especially writers on controversies about free will, they are used in a quite different and far more extensive sense, and are applied to many cases wherein no will or endeavour for the bringing of the thing to pass is or can be supposed :" e. g. The connexion be- tween volitions and their causes or motives. Contingent and Contingency. " Any thing is said to be contingent, or to come to pass by chance or accident, in the original meaning of such words, when its connexion with its causes or antecedents, according to the estab- lished course of things, is not discerned ; and so is what we have no means of foreseeing. But the word, contingent, is abundantly used in a very different sense ; not for that, whose connexion with the series of things we cannot discern so as to foresee the event, but for something which has absolutely no previous ground or reason, with which its existence has any fixed connexion." (p. 31. 32.) W STATEMENT OF Contingency and chance Edwards uses as eqai valent terms. In common use, contingency and chance arc relative to our knowledge — implying that we discern no cause. In another use, — the use of a certain philosophical school, — he affirms that contingency is used to express absolutely no cause ; or, that some events are represented as existing without any cause or ground of their ex- istence. This will be examined in its proper place. I am now only stating Edwards's opinions, not discussing them. Sec IV. Of the Distinction of natural and moiial Necessity and Inability. We now return to the question : — Is the con- nexion between motive and volition necessary? The term necessary, in its common or vulgar use, does not relate to this question, for in that use as we have seen, it refers to the connexion between volition considered as a cause, and its effects. In this question, we are considering voli- tion as an effect in relation to its cause or the motive. If the connexion then of motive and vo- lition be necessary, it must be necessary in the philosophical or metaphysical sense of the term. ED\VARDS?S SYSTEM. 47 Now this philosophical necessity Edwards docs hold to characterize the connexion of motive and volition. This section opens with the following distinction of philosophical necessity: " That ne- cessity which has been explained, consisting in an infallible connexion of the things signified by the subject and predicate of a proposition, as in- telligent beings are the subjects of it, is distin- guished into moral and natural necessity." He then appropriates moral philosophical necessity to express the nature of the connexion between mo- tive and volition: "And sometimes by moral ne- cessity is meant that necessity of connexion and consequence which arises from moral causes, as the strength of inclination, or motives, and the connexion which there is in many cases between these, and such certain volitions and actions. And it is in this sense that I use the phrase moral necessity in the following discourse." (p. 32.) Natural jihilosophical necessity as distinguished from this, he employs to characterize the connexion between natural causes and phenomena of our being, as the connexion of external objects with our various sensations, and the connexion between truth and our assent or belief, (p. 33.) In employing the term moral, however, he does not intend to intimate that it affects at all 48 STATEMENT of the absoluteness of the necessity which it distin- guishes ; on the contrary, he affirms that "moral necessity may be as absolute as natural necessity. That is, the effect may be as perfectly connected with its moral cause, as a natural necessary effect is with its natural cause. It must be allowed that there maybe such a thing as a sure and perfect con- nexion between moral causes and effects ; so this only (i. e. the sure and perfect connexion.) is what I call by the name of moral necessity" (p. 33.) Nor does he intend " that when a moral habit or motive is so strong that the act of the will in- fallibly follows, this is not owing to the nature of things" But these terms, moral and natural, are convenient to express a difference which really exists; a difference, however, which "does not lie so much in the nature of the connexion as in the two terms connected. ." Indeed, he soon after admits " that choice in meiny cases arises from na- ture, as truly as other events." His sentiment is plainly this — choice lies in the great system and chain of nature as truly as any other phenomenon, arising from its antecedent and having its conse- quents or effects : but we have appropriated na- ture to express the chain of causes and effects, which lie without us, and which are most obvious to us ; and choice being, " as it were, a new prin- edwards's system. 19 ciple of motion and action," lying within us, and often interrupting or altering the external course of nature, seems to demand a peculiar designa- tion, (p. 34.) Edwards closes his remarks on moral necessity by justifying his reduction of motive and volition under philosophical necessity. " It must be ob- served, that in what has been explained, as signi- fied by the name of moral necessity, the word ne- cessity is not used according to the original design and meaning of the word ; for, as was observed before, such terms, necessary, impossible, irresisti- ble, &c. in common speech, and their most proper sense, are always relative, having reference to some supposable voluntary opposition or endea- vour, that is insufficient. But no such opposi- tion, or contrary will and endeavour, is supposa- ble in the case of moral necessity ; which is a certainty of the inclination and will itself; which does not admit of the supposition of a will to op- pose and resist it. For it is absurd to suppose the same individual will to oppose itself in its present act ; or the present choice to be opposite to, and resisting present choice : as absurd as it is to talk of two contrary motions in the same moving body at the same time. And therefore the very case supposed never admits of any trial, whether an 5 .">() - i \ TEW \ C of opposing or resisting will can overcome tliis nc- 'y." (p. :::..) This passage is clear and full. Common ne- cessity, or necessity in the original use of the word, refers to the connexion between volition and its effects ; for here an opposition to will is supposablc. I may choose or will to raise a weight ; but the gravity opposed to my endea- vour overcomes it, and I find it impossible for me to raise it, and the weight nccessaj-ily remains in its place. In this common use of these terms, the impossibility and the necessity are relative to my volition ; but in the production of choice itself, or volition, or the sense of the most agreeable, there is no reference to voluntary endeavour. Choice is not the cause of itself: it cannot be conceived of as struggling with itself in its own production. The cause of volition does not lie within the sphere of volition itself; if any opposi- tion, therefore, were made to the production of a volition, it could not be made by a volition. The mind, with given susceptibilities and habits, is supposed to be placed within the influence of objects and their circumstances, and the choice takes place in the correlation of the two, as the sense of the most agreeable. Now choice cannot exist before its cause, and so there can be no edwards's system. 51 choice in the act of its causation. It comes into existence, therefore, by no necessity relating to voluntary endeavour ; it comes into existence by a philosophical and absolute necessity of cause and effect. It is necessary as the falling of a stone which is thrown into the air ; as the freez- ing or boiling of water at given temperatures ; as sensations of sight, sound, smell, taste, and feel- ing, when the organs of sense and the objects of sense are brought together. The application of the epithet moral to the necessity of volition, evi- dently does not alter in the least the character of that necessity. It is still philosophical and abso- lute necessity, and as sure and perfect as natural necessity. This we have seen he expressly ad- mits, (p. 33 ;) affirming, (p. 34,) that the differ- ence between a moral and natural necessity is a mere difference in the "two terms connected,"' and not a difference " in the nature of the con- nexion." Natural and moral Inability. " What has been said of natural and moral ne- cessity, may serve to explain what is intended by natural and moral inability. We are said to be naturally unable to do a thing, when we cannot 52 STATEMENT OF do it if we will, because what is most commonly called nature does not allow of it, or because of some impeding defect or obstacle that is extrinsic to the will ; either in the faculty of the understand- ing, constitution of body, or external objects." (p. 35.) We may make a voluntary endeavour to know something, and may find ourselves unable, through a defect of the understanding. We may make a voluntary effort to do something by the instrumentality of our hand, and may find our- selves unable through a defect of the bodily con- stitution ; or external objects may be regarded as presenting such a counter force as to overcome the force we exert. This is natural inability ; this is all we mean by it. It must be remarked too, that this is inability not metaphysically or jjJiiloso- phically considered, and therefore not absolute in- ability ; but only inability in the common and vul- gar acceptation of the term — a relative inability, relative to volition or choice — an inability to do, although we will to do. What is moral inability ? " Moral inability consists not in any of these things ; but either in the want of inclination, or the strength of a con- trary inclination, or the want of sufficient motives in view, to induce and excite the act of will, or the strength of apparent motives to the contrary- edwards's system. 58 Or both these may be resolved into one ; and it may be said, in one word, that moral inability con- sists in the opposition or want of inclination. For when a person is unable to will or choose such a thing, through a defect of motives, or prevalence of contrary motives, it is the same thing as his being unable through the want of an inclination, or the prevalence of a contrary inclination, in such circumstances and under the influence of such views.'" (ibid.) The inability in this case does not relate to the connexion between volition and its consequents and effects ; but to the production of the volition itself. Now the inability to the production of a volition, cannot be affirmed of the volition, because it is not yet supposed to exist, and as an effect cannot be conceived of as producing itself. The inability, therefore, must belong to the causes of volition, or to the motive. But motive, as we have seen, lies in the state of the mind, and in the nature and circumstances of the object ; and choice or volition exists when, in the correlation of mind and object, the sense of the most agreeable is pro- duced. Now what reason can exist, in any given case, why the volition or sense of the most agree- able is not produced ? Why simply this, that there is not such a correlation of mind and object as to •v 54 STATEMENT OF produce this sense or choice. But wherein lies the deficiency? We may say generally, that it lies in both mind and object — that they are not suited to each other. The mind is not in a state to be agreeably impressed by the object, and the object does not possess qualities of beauty and agreeablencss to the mind. On the part of the mind, there is either a want of inclination to the object, or a stronger inclination towards another object : on the part of the object, there is a want of interesting and agreeable qualities to the par- ticular state of mind in question, or a suitableness to a different state of mind : and this constitutes " the want of sufficient motives in viewr, to induce and excite the act of will, or the strength of appa- rent motives to the contrary." And both these may clearly be resolved into one, that above men- tioned, viz. a want of inclination on the part of the mind to the object, and a stronger inclination towards another object ; or, as Edwards expresses it, " the opposition or want of inclination."' For a want of inclination to one object, implying a stronger inclination to another object, expresses that the state of the mind, and the nature and cir- cumstances of the one object, are not correlated ; but that the state of mind, and the nature and cir- cumstances of the other object, are correlated. edwards's system. 55 The first, is a " want of sufficient motives ;" the second, stronger " motives to the contrary." Mo- ral inability lies entirely out of the sphere of voli- tion; volition, therefore, cannot produce or relieve it, for this would suppose an effect to modify its cause, and that too before the effect itself has any existence. Moral inability is a metaphysical ina- bility : it is the perfect and fixed impossibility of certain laws and principles of being, leading to certain volitions ; and is contrasted with physical inability, which is the established impossibility of a certain volition, producing a certain effect. So we may say, that moral ability is the certain and fixed connexion between certain laws and prin- ciples of being, and volitions ; and is contrasted with natural ability, which is the established con- nexion between certain volitions and certain ef- fects. Moral inability, although transcending the sphere of volition, is a real inability. Where it exists, there is the absolute impossibility of a given voli- tion,— and of course an absolute impossibility of certain effects coming to pass by that volition. The impossibility of water freezing above an es- tablished temperature, or of boiling below an es- tablished temperature, is no more fixed than the impossibility of effects coming to pa.ss by a voli- 56 STATEMENT OF tion, when there is a moral inability of the voli- tion. The difference between the two cases does not lie " in the nature of the connexion," but " in the two terms connected." Edwards gives several instances in illustration of moral inability. " A woman of great honour and chastity may have a moral inability to prostitute herself to her slave." (ibid.) There is no correlation between the state of her mind and the act which forms the object contemplated, — of course the sense of the most agreeable or choice cannot take place ; and while the state of her mind remains the same, and the act and its circumstances remain the same, there is, on the principle of Edwards, an utter in- ability to the choice, and of course to the conse- quents of the choice. " A child of great love and duty to his parents, may be thus unable to kill his father." (ibid.) This case is similar to the preceding. "A very lascivious man, in case of certain op- portunities and temptations, and in the absence of such and such restraints, may be unable to for- bear gratifying his lust." There is here a corre- lation between the state of mind and the object, in its nature and circumstances, — and of course the sense of the most agreeable or choice takes place. edwards's system. 57 There is a moral ability to the choice, and a mor- al inability to forbear, or to choose the opposite. " A drunkard, under such and such circumstan- ces, may be unable to forbear taking strong drink." (ibid.) This is similar to the last. " A very malicious man may be unable to ex- ert benevolent acts to an enemy, or to desire his prosperity ; yea, some may be so under the pow- er of a vile disposition, that they may be unable to love those who are most worthy of their es- teem and affection." (ibid.) The state of mind is such, — that is, the disposition or sensitivity, — as not to be at all correlated to the great duty of loving one's neighbour as one's self, — or to any moral excellency in another : of course the sense of the most agreeable is not produced ; and in this state of mind it is absolutely impossible that it should be produced. " A strong habit of virtue, a great esteem of holiness, mav cause a moral inability to love wickedness in general." (p. 3G.) " On the other hand, a great degree of habitual wickedness may lay a man under an in- ability to love and choose holiness, and render him utterly unable to love an infinitely Holy Be- ing, or to choose and cleave to him as the chief good." (ibid.) The love and choice of holiness is necessarily produced by the correlation of the 58 STATEMENT or mind with holiness; and the love and choice of holiness is utterly impossible when this correlation does not exist. Where a moral inability to evil exists, nothing can be more sure and fixed than this inability. The individual who is the subject of it has absolutely no power to alter it. If he were to proceed to alter it, he would have to put forth a volition to this effect ; but this would be an evil volition, and by supposition the individual has no ability to evil volitions. Where a moral inability to good exists, nothing can be more sure and fixed than this inability. The individual who is the subject of it, has abso- lutely no power to alter it. If he were to pro- ceed to alter it, he would have to put forth a voli- tion to this effect ; but this would be a good vo- lition, and by supposition the individual has no ability to good volitions. General and habitual, particular and occasional Inability. The first consists " in a fixed and habitual in- clination, or an habitual and stated defect or want of a certain kind of inclination, (p. 36.) The second is " an inability of the will or heart to a particular act, through the strength or defect EDWARDS * SYSTEM. 59 of present motives, or of inducements presented to the view of the understanding, on this occa- sion." (ibid.) An habitual drunkard, and a man habitually so- ber, on some particular occasion getting drunk, are instances of general and particular inability. In the first instance, the slate of the man's mind has become correlated to the object ; under all times and circumstances it is fixed. In the second instance, the state of the man's mind is correlated to the object only when presented on certain oc- casions and under certain circumstances. In both instances, however, the choice is necessary, — "it not being possible, in any case, that the will should at present go against the motive which has now, all things considered, the greatest advantage to induce it." " Will and endeavour against, or diverse from present acts of the will, are in no case supposa- ble, whether those acts be occasional or habitual ; for that would be to suppose the will at present to be otherwise than at present it is." (ibid.) The passage which follows deserves particular attention. It may be brought up under the fol- lowing question : Although will cannot be exerted against pres- ent acts of the will, yet can present acts of the 60 STATEMENT OF will be exerted to produce future acts of the will, opposed to present habitual or present occasional acts ? " But yet there may be will and endeavour against future acts of the will, or volitions that are likely to take place, as viewed at a distance. It is no contradiction, to suppose that the acts of the will at one time may be against the act of the will at another time ; and there may be desires and endeavours to prevent or excite future acts of the will ; but such desires and endeavours arc in many cases rendered insufficient and vain through fixedness of habit : when the occasion returns, the strength of habit overcomes and baffles all such opposition." (p. 37.) Let us take the instance of the drunkard. The choice or volition to drink is the fixed correlation of his disposition and the strong drink. But we may suppose that his disposition can be affected by other objects likewise : as the consideration of the interest and happiness of his wife and chil- dren, and his own respectability and final happi- ness. When his cups are removed, and he has an occasional fit of satiety and loathing, these con- siderations may awaken at the time the sense of the most agreeable, and lead him to avoid the oc- casions of drunkenness, and to form resolutions of amendment; but when the appetite and longing edwards's system. 61 for drink returns, and he comes again in the way of indulgence, then these considerations, brought fairly into collision with his habits, are overcome, and drinking, as the most agreeable, asserts its supremacy. " But it may be comparatively easy to make an alteration with respect to such future acts as are only occasional and transient ; because the occa- sional or transient cause, if foreseen, may often easily be prevented or avoided." (ibid.) In the case of occasional drunkenness, for in- stance, the habitual correlation is not of mind and strong drink, but of mind and considerations of honour, prudence, and virtue. But strong drink being associated on some occasion with objects which are correlated to the mind, — as hospitali- ty, friendship, or festive celebrations, — may ob- tain the mastery ; and in this case, the individual being under no temptation from strong drink in itself considered, and being really affected with the sense of the most agreeable in relation to ob- jects which are opposed to drunkenness, may take care that strong drink shall not come again into circumstances to give it an adventitious ad- vantage. The repetition of occasional drunken- ness would of course by and by produce a change in the sensitivity, and establish an habitual liking 6 69 STATEMENT OF for drink. " On this account, the moral inability that attends fixed habits, especially obtains the name of inability. And then, as the will may re- motely and indirectly resist itself, and do it in vain, in the case of strong habits ; so reason may resist present acts of the will, and its resistance be in- sufficient : and this is more commonly the case, also, when the acts arise from strong habit." ^K^ In every act of the will, the will at the moment is unable to act otherwise ; it is in the strictest sense true, that a man, at the moment of his act- ing, must act as he does act ; but as we usually characterize men by the habitual state of their minds, we more especially speak of moral inabil- ity in relation to acts which are known to have no correlation to this habitual state. This habitu- al state of the mind, if it be opposed to reason, overcomes reason ; for nothing, not even reason itself, can be the strongest motive, unless it pro- duce the sense of the most agreeable ; and this it cannot do, where the habitual disposition or sen- sitivity is opposed to it. Common usage with respect to the phrase want of power or inability to act in a certain way. " But it must be observed concerning moral in- edwards's system. 63 ability, in each kind of it, that the word inability is used in a sense very diverse from its original import. The word signifies only a natural inabil- ity, in the proper use of it ; and is applied to such cases only wherein a present will or inclination to the thing, with respect to which a person is said to be unable, is supposable. It cannot be truly said, according to the ordinary use of language, that a malicious man, let him be never so malicious, cannot hold his hand from striking, or that he is not able to show his neighbour a kindness ; or that a drunkard, let his appetite be never so strong, can- not keep the cup from his mouth. In the strictest propriety of speedy a man has a thing in his pow- er if he has it in liis choice or at his election ; and a man cannot be truly said to he unable to do a thing, when he can do it if he will." (ibid.) Men, in the common use of language, and in the expression of their common and generally re- ceived sentiments, affirm that an individual has any thing in his power when it can be controlled by volition. Their conception of power does not arise from the connexion of volition with its cause, but from the connexion of volition as itself a cause with its effects. Thus the hand of a ma- licious man when moved to strike, having for its antecedent a volition ; and if withheld from strik- (Jl STATEMENT OF ing, having for its antecedent likewise a volition ; according to the common usage of language, he, as the subject of volition, has the power to strike or not to strike. Now as it is " improperly said that he cannot perform those external voluntary actions which depend on the will, it is in some re- spects more improperly said, that he is unable to exert the acts of the will themselves ; because it is more evidently false, with respect to these, that he cannot if he will ; for to say so is a downright contradiction ; it is to say he cannot will if he docs will : and, in this case, not only is it true that it is easy for a man to do the thing if he will, but the very willing is the doing." (ibid.) It is improper, according to this, to say that a man cannot do a thing, when nothing is wanting but an act of volition ; for that is within our pow- er, as far as it can be within our power, which is within the reach of our volition. It is still more improper to say that a man is enable to exert the acts of the will themselves, or uifable to produce volitions. To say that a man has power to produce volitions, would imply that he has power to will volitions ; but this would make one volition the cause of another, which is absurd. But, as it is absurd to represent the will as the cause of its own volitions, and of course edwards's system. 65 to say that the man has ability to produce his volitions, it must be absurd likewise to represent the man as unable, in any particular case, to pro- duce volitions, for this would imply that in other cases he is able. Nay, the very language is self- contradictory. If a man produce volitions, he must produce them by volitions ; and if in any case he is affirmed to be unable to produce voli- tions, then this inability must arise from a want of connexion between the volition by which the required volition is aimed to be produced, and the required volition itself. So that to affirm that he is unable to will is equivalent to saying, that he cannot will if he will — a proposition which grants the very point it assumes to deny. " The very willing is the doing,"' which is required. Edwards adopts what he calls the " original " and u proper," meaning of power, and ability, as applied to human agents, and appearing, " in the ordinary use of language," as the legitimate and true meaning. In this use, power, as we have seen, relates only to die connexion of volition with its consequents, and not to its connexion with its antecedents or motives. Hence, in reference to the human agent, " to ascribe a non-perform- ance to the want of power or ability," or to the want of motives, (for this is plainly his meaning,) 6* GC BTATEMBNT OF u is not just/' " because the thing wanting/' that is, immediately wanting, and wanting so far as thi. agent himself can be the subject of remark in respect of it, " is not a being able? that is, a having the requisite motives, or the moral ability, "but a being willing, or the act of volition, itself. To the act of volition, or the fact of 'being willing,'" there is no faculty of mind or capacity of nature wanting, but only a disposition or state of mind adapted to the act ; but with this, the individual can have no concern in reference to his action, because he has all the ability which can be pre- dicated of him legitimately, when he can do the act, if he will to do it. It is evident that there may be an utter moral inability to do a thing — that is the motive may be wanting which causes the volition, which is the immediate antecedent of the thing to be done ; but still if it is true that there is such a connexion between the volition and the thing to be done, that the moment the volition takes place the thing is done ; then, according to Edwards, the man may be affirmed to be able to do it with the only ability that can be affirmed of him. We can exert power only by exerting will, that is by putting forth volitions, — by choosing, of course we cannot exert power over those motives which edwards's system. 67 are themselves the causes of our volitions. We are not unable to do anything in the proper and original and legitimate use of the word when, for the want of motive, we are not the subjects of the volition required as the immediate antecedent of the thing to be done ; but we are unable in this use when, although the volition be made ; still, through some impediment, the thing is not done. We are conscious of power, or of the want of power only in the connexion between our actual volitions and their objects. " Sec. V. Concerning the Notion of Liber- ty, AND OF MORAL AGENCY." What is liberty ? " The plain and obvious meaning of the words freedom and liberty, in common speech, is power, opportunity, or advan- tage that any one has to do as he pleases. Or, in other words, his being free from hinderance, or impediment in the way of doing, or conducting in any way as he wills. And the contrary to liberty, whatever name we call it by, is a person's being hindered or unable to conduct as he will, or being, necessitated to do otherwise.'' (p. 38.) Again, " That power and opportunity for one to do and conduct as he will, or according to his choice, is all G8 STATEMENT OF that is meant by it; without taking into the meaning of the word, anything of the cause of that choice, or at all considering how the person came to have such a volition ; whether it was caused by some external motive, or internal habitual bias ; whether it was determined by some internal antecedent volition, or whether it happened without a cause ; whether it was necessarily connected with some- thing foregoing, or not connected. Let the person come by his choice any how, yet if he is able, and there is nothing in the way to hinder his pursuing and executing his will, the man is perfectly free, according to the primary and common notion of freedom." (p. 39.) This is Edwards's definition of liberty, and he has given it with a clearness, a precision, and, at the same time, an amplification, which renders it impossible to mistake his meaning. Liberty has nothing to do with the connexion between volition and its cause or motive. Liberty relates solely to the connexion between the voli- tion and its objects. He is free in the only true and proper sense, who, when he wills, finds no impediment between the volition and the object, who wills and it is done. He wills to walk, and his legs obey : he wills to talk, and his intellect and tongue obey, and frame and express sentences. If his legs were bound, he would not be free. If edwards's system. G9 his tongue were tied with a thong, or his mouth gagged, he would not be free ; or if his intellect were paralysed or disordered, he would not be free. If there should be anything preventing the volition from taking effect, he would not be free. Of what can the attribute of Liberty be affirmed ? From the definition thus given Edwards re- marks, " It will follow, that in propriety of speech, neither liberty, nor its contrary, can properly be ascribed to any being or thing, but that which has such a faculty, power, or property, as is called will. For that which is possessed of no will, can- not have any power or opportunity of doing ac- cording to its will, nor be necessitated to act con- trary to its will, nor be restrained from acting agreeable to it. And therefore to talk of liberty, or the contrary, as belonging to the very ivill itself, is not to speak good sense ; for the will itself, is not an agent that has a will. The power of choosing itself, has not a power of choosing. That which has the power of volition is the man, or the soul, and not the power of volition itself. And he that has the liberty, is the agent who is pos- sessed of the will ; and not the will which he is possessed of." (p. 38.) 70 stati:mi:nt of Liberty is the attribute of the agent, because the agent is the spiritual essence or being who is the subject of the power or capacity of choice, and \u< liberty consists as we have seen in the unimpeded connexion betwen the volitions pro- duced in him and the objects of those volitions. Hence, free will is an objectionable phrase. Free agent is the proper phrase, that is, an agent having the power of choice and whose choice reaches effects. Moral Agent. " A moral agent is a being that is capable of those actions that have a moral quality, and which can properly be denominated good or evil in a moral sense, virtuous or vicious, commenda- ble or faulty." (p. 39.) In what lies the capability of actions having a moral quality ? " To moral agency belongs a moral faculty, or sense of moral good and evil, or of such a thing as desert or worthiness, of praise or blame, re- ward or punishment ; and a capacity which an agent has of being influenced in his actions by moral inducements or motives, exhibited to the view of the understanding or reason, to engage to a conduct agreeable to moral faculty." (p. 40.) edwards's system. 71 A moral agent is a being who can perform mo- ral actions, or actions which are subject to praise or blame. Now the same action may be commit- ted by a man or by a brute — and the man alone will be guilty: why is the man guilty? Because he has a moral sense or perception by which he distinguishes right and wrong : the brute has no such sense or perception. The man having thus the power of perceiving the right and wrong of ac- tions — actions and their moral qualities may be so correlated to him as to produce the sense of the most agreeable or choice. Or, we may say generally, moral agency consists in the possession of a reason and conscience to distinguish right and wrong, and the capacity of having the right and wrong so corre- lated to the mind as to form motives and produce volitions. We might define a man of taste in the fine arts in a similar way; thus, — a man of taste is an agent who has the power of distinguishing beauty and ugliness, and whose mind is so cor- related to beauty that the sense of the most agree- able or choice is produced. The only difference between the two cases is this : that, in the latter, the sense of the most agreeable is always produced by the beauty perceived ; while in the former, the right perceived does not always produce this sense ; on the contrary, the sense of the most STATEMENT OF agreeable is often produced by the wrong, in oppo- sition to the decisions of reason and conscience. I have now completed the statement of Ed- wards's system, nearly in his own words, as con- tained in part I. of his work. The remarks and explanations which have been thrown in, I hope will serve to make him more perfectly understood. This end will be still more fully attained by pre- senting on the basis of the foregoing investigation and statement, a compend of his psychological system, independently of the order there pursued, and without largely introducing quotations, which have already been abundantly made. COMPEND OF EDWARDS'S PSYCHO- LOGICAL SYSTEM. I. There are two cardinal faculties of the mind. 1. The intellectual — called reason or understand- ing. 2. The active and feeling — called will or affections. II. The relation of these to each other. The first precedes the second in the order of exer- cise. The first perceives and knows objects in their qualities, circumstances, and relations. The edwards's system. 73 second experiences emotions and passions, or desires and choices, in relation to the objects per- ceived. III. Perception is necessary. When the un- derstanding and its objects are brought together, perception takes place according to the consti- tuted laws of the intelligence. IV. The acts of will or the affections are ne- cessary. When this faculty of our being and its objects are brought together, volition or choice, emotions, passions, or desires take place, accord- ing to the constituted nature and laws of this faculty. The objects and this faculty are correlates. In relation to the object, we may call this faculty subject. When subject and object are suited to each other, that is, are agreeable, affections are produced which we call pleasant ; when they are not suited, that is, are disagreeable, affections take place which are unpleasant or painful. Every ob- ject in relation to subject, is agreeable or disagree- able, and produces accordingly, in general, affec- tions pleasant or painful. In the perfection and harmony of our being, this correspondence is universal ; that is, what is known to be agreeable is felt to be pleasant ; — what is known to be disagreeable is felt to be 7 ' I STATEMENT OF painful. But, in the corruption of our being, this is reversed in respect of moral objects. Although whal is right is known to DC agreeable, that is, suited to us, it is felt to be painful. But the wrong which is known to be unsuited,is felt to be pleasant. It must be remarked here, that pleasant and agreeable, are used by Edwards and others, as synonymous terms. The distinction I have here made is at least convenient in describing the same objects as presented to the understanding and to the will. V. The emotions and passions, volitions or choices, are thus produced in the correlation of subject, that is the will, and the object. In as- signing the causes of these affections, we may re- fer to the nature of the will, which is such, as to receive such and such affections when in the pre- sence of such and such objects : or, we may re- fer to the objects, and say their nature and cir- cumstances are such as to produce such and such affections in the will : or, we may refer to both at once, and say that the affections arise from the state of the mind, and from the nature and cir- cumstances of the object. VI. The affections of the will stand connected with changes or effects in other parts of our be- ing, as stated antecedents. First, they stand thus EDWARDS S SYSTEM. -■> connected with muscular action, — as walking, talking, striking, resisting, &c. Secondly, they stand thus connected with mental operations, — as fixing the attention upon any subject of thought and investigation, or upon any imagination, or any idea of the memory. VII. The affections of the will, when thus con- nected with effects in other parts of our being, have a peculiar and striking characteristic. It is this : that the effect contemplated takes place at the moment it appears the most agreeable, — the greatest apparent good : which, as Edwards uses these phrases, means, that at the moment the effect contemplated produces the most pleas- ant affection, — the most intense sense of the agreeable, — it takes place. Thus, when walking seems most pleasant, we walk ; when talking, we talk ; when thinking on a particular subject, then we think on that subject. Such is the constitution and law of our being. The play of the different parts is reciprocal. Perception must bring up the objects, and the affections of will immediately fol- low. The most agreeable are dwelt upon by the mind, and perception again takes place particu- larly with regard to these ; and according as ob- jects affect the will, do all the activities of our bein£ come forth. 'U STATEMENT or VIII. Various terms and phrases in common use can be easily explained by this system : — Choice is the sense or the affection of the most pleasant and agreeable. Preference is its syno- nyme, with scarcely a shade of difference. They both have respect to the act of selection. Volition is another name for this affection of will, and is used more particularly in relation to effects or changes following the aflection. Desire is a nas- cent choice. The strongest desire, at a given moment, is choice. Emotion is an affection, pleas- ant or painful, according to the quality of the ob- ject, but not ripened into desire. It is the first sudden affection arising from an object present- ed ; and with respect to certain objects, it ex- presses all the enjoyment possible in relation to them, — for example, the emotion of sublimity, produced by an object which can hold no other relation to us. But then the sublimity of the ob- ject may be the motive which causes the choice of gazing at it ; that is, it connects this act of contemplation with the sense of the most agree- able. Passion is emotion accompanied by desire in reference to other relations with the object. Thus the emotion of beauty awakened by a flower may be accompanied by the desire of possessing EDWARD* S 8TSTEM. 77 -S11 ^1 it ; and if this desire becomes the strongest de- sire at the moment, then the passion has the cha- racteristic which makes it choice, and some cor- responding effects take place in order to possess it, — as walking towards it, stretching out the hand, &c The determination of will is the production or causation of choice. It is used in reference to the immediate and particular choice, in opposition to all other choices. The will itself is the capacity of being affected by objects with emotion, passion, and desire, — and with that form of passion which we call the sense of the most agreeable or choice, and which is connected with effects or consequents as their stated antecedent. The motive is the cause of choice, and is com- plex. It lies in the nature and susceptibilities of the will, and in the nature and circumstances of the object chosen. IX. The will and reason may be opposed ; that is, what reason commands may seem disagreea- ble to the will, and of course reason cannot be obeyed. Reason can be obeyed only when her commands produce the sense of the most agree- able. X. The terms necessity, and freedom or liber- 7* 1 8 STATEMENT OS ty arc opposed in reference to will. Freedom or liberty is the attribute of the man — the human soul. The man is free when his volitions or choices are unimpeded, — when, upon choosing to walk, he walks, &c. The man is not free, or is under necessity, when his volitions or choices are impeded, — when, upon choosing to walk, he finds his legs bound or paralysed, &c. Then it is im- possible for him to walk, — then he has no Wh rty to walk, — then he is under a necessity of remain- ing in one place. Necessity in any other use is metaphysical or philosophical necessity, and is applied out of the sphere of the will : as the necessity of truth, — the necessity of being, — the necessary connex- ion of cause and effect. Hence, The connexion between volitions or choices, or the sense of the most agreeable with the motive or cause, is necessary with a philosophical neces- sity. The necessity of volitions in reference to motives is also called moral necessity. This term moral is given, not in reference to the nature of the connexion, but in reference to the tenns con- nected. Volitions belonging to responsible and moral beings are thus distinguished from those phenomena which we commonly call natural. XL An agent is that which produces effects. edwards's system. 79 A natural agent is that which produces effects without volition. A moral agent is one producing effects by volitions, accompanied with an intellec- tual perception of the volitions and their effects, as right or wrong, and a sense of desert, or of praise- worthiness, or blameworthiness, on account of the volitions and their effects. Brutes or irresponsible beings are agents that have volitions, but have no reason to perceive right and wrong, and consequently have no sense of desert ; and as they cannot perceive right and wrong, they cannot be made the subjects of moral appeals and inducements. XII. Moral responsibility arises first, from the possession of reason ; secondly, from the capacity of choice ; thirdly, from natural ability. Natural ability exists when the effect or act commanded to be accomplished has an establish- ed connexion with volition or choice. Thus we say a man has natural ability to walk, because if he chooses to walk, he walks. Natural ability differs from freedom only in this: — The first re- fers to an established connexion between volitions and effects. The second refers to an absence of all impediment, or of all resisting forces from be- tween volitions and effects. Hence a man is naturally unable to do any- Ml STATl'-MKNT OF thing when there is no established connexion be- D volition and that thing. A man is natural- ly unable to push a mountain from its scat. He has no liberty to move his arm when it is bound. M>nil inability is metaphysical or philosophical inability. Philosophical inability in general refers to the impossibility of a certain effect for tho want of a cause, or an adequate cause. Thus there is a philosophical inability of transmuting metal ; or of restoring the decay of old age to the freshness and vigour of youth, because we have no cause by which such eflects can be produced. There is a philosophical inability also, to pry up a rock of a hundred tons weight with a pine lath, and by the hand of a single man, because we have not an adequate cause. Moral inability re- lates to the connexion between motives and vo- litions in distinction from natural ability, which relates to the connexion between volitions and ac- tions consequent upon them : but the term moral as we have seen, does not characterize the na- ture of the connexion, — it only expresses the quality of terms connected. Hence moral inabili- ty, as philosphical inability, is the impossibility of a certain volition or choice for the want of a mo- tive or cause, or an adequate motive. Thus there is a moral philosophical inability of Faul denying edwards's system. 81 Jesus Christ, for there is plainly no motive or cause to produce a volition to such an act. There is a moral philosophical inability also, of a man selling an estate for fifty dollars which is worth fifty thousand, because the motive is not adequate to produce a volition to such an act. Philosophical necessity and inability, are abso- lute in respect of us, because beyond the sphere of our volition. XIII. Praiseworthincss or virtue, blameworthi- ness or guilt, apply only to volitions. This indeed is not formally brought out in the part of Ed- wards's work we have been examining. His dis- cussion of it will be found in part IV. sec. I. But as it is necessary to a complete view of his sys- tem, we introduce it here. He remarks in this part, " If the essence of virtuousness or commendableness, and of vicious- ness or fault, does not lie in the nature of the dis- position or acts of the mind, which are said to be our virtue or our fault, but in their cause, then it is certain it lies no where at all. Thus, for in- stance, if the vice of a vicious act of icill lies not in the nature of the act, but in the cause, so that its being of a bad nature will not make it at all our fault, unless it arises from some faulty deter- mination of ours as its cause, or something in us Bfl STATEMENT OF tliat is our fault, &c." (page 190.) "Disposition of mind," or inclination, — "acts of the mind," " acts of will," here obviously mean the same thing; that is, they mean volition or choice, and arc distinguished from their cause or motive. The question is not whether the cause or motive be pure or impure, but whether our virtuousness or viciousness lie in the cause of our volition, or in the volition itself. It plainly results from Ed- wards's psychology, and he has himself in the above quotation stated it, that virtuousness or vi- ciousness lie in the volition itself. The charac- teristic of our personality or agency is volition. Jt \ our volitions that we are conscious of doing or forbearing to do, and therefore it is in respect of our volitions that we receive praise for well-doing, or blame for evil-doing. If these volitions are in accordance with conscience and the law of God, they are right ; if not, they are wrong, and we are judged accordingly. The met- aphysical questions, how the volition was pro- duced, and what is the character of the cause, is the cause praiseworthy or blameworthy, are questions which transcend the sphere of our vo- litions, our actions, our personality, our responsi- bility. We are concerned only with this: — Do we do right ? do we do wrong 7 What is the na- ture of our volitions ? EDWATIDS'S SYSTEM. 83 Nor does the necessary connexion between the motives and the volitions, destroy the blamewor- thiness and the praiseworthiness of the volitions. We are blameworthy or praiseworthy according to the character of the volitions in themselves, considered and judged according to the rule of right, without considering how these volitions came to exist. The last inquiry is altogether of a philosophical or metaphysical kind, and not of a moral kind, or that kind which relates to moral agency, responsibility, and duty. And so also we are blameworthy or praise- worthy for doing or not doing external actions, so far only as these actions are naturally con- nected with volitions, as sequents with their sta- ted antecedents. If the action is one which ought to be done, we are responsible for the doing of it, if we know that upon our willing it, it will be done ; although at this very moment there is no such correlation between the action and the will, as to form the motive or cause upon which the existence of the act of willing depends. If the action is one which ought not to be done, we are guilty for doing it, when we know that if we were not to will it, it would not be done : although at this very moment there is such a correlation between the action, and the state of the will, as to 9 I BTATEMBHT OF form the cause or motive by which the act of willing comes necessarily to exist. The meta- physial or philosophical inquiry respecting the correlation of the state of the will and any action, or respecting the want of such a correlation, is foreign to the question of duty and responsibility. This question relates only to the volition and its connexion with its consequents. This does not clash at all with the common sentiment that our actions are to be judged of by our motives ; for this sentiment does not respect volitions in relation to their cause, but external actions in relation to the volitions which produce them. These external actions may be in them- selves good, but they may not be what was willed ; some other force or power may have come in between the volition and its object, and changed the circumstances of the object, so as to bring about an event different from the will or inten- tion ; although being in connexion with the agent, it may still be attributed to his will : or the im- mediate act which appears good, may, in the mind of the agent be merely part of an extended plan or chain of volitions, whose last action or result is evil. It is common, therefore, to say of an exter- nal action, we must know what the man intends, before we pronounce upon him ; which is the same edwards's system. 85 thing as to say we must know what his volition really is, or what his motive is — that is, not the cause which produces his volition, but the volition which is aiming at effects, and is the motive and cause of these effects; — which again, is the same thing as to say, that before we can pronounce upon his conduct, we must know what effects he really intends or wills, or desires, that is, what it is which is really connected in his mind with the sense of the most agreeable. Edwards and Locke. Their systems are one : there is no difference in the principle. Edwards represents the will as necessarily determined — so does Locke. Ed- wards places liberty in the unimpeded connexion of volition with its stated sequents — so does Locke. They differ only in the mode of developing the necessary determination of will. According to Locke, desire is in itself a necessary modification of our being produced in its correlation with ob- jects ; and volition is a necessary consequent of desire when excited at any given moment to a degree which gives the most intense sense of uneasiness at that moment. " The greatest pre- 8 80 STATEMENT OF EDWARDs's SYSTEM. sent uneasiness is llie spur of action that is con- stantly felt, and for the most part, determines the will in its choice of the next action." (book 2. ch. 21, § 10.) According to Edwards, desire is not distinguishable from will as a faculty, and the strongest desire, at any moment, is the volition of that moment. Edwards's analysis is more nice than Locke's, and His whole dcvelopement more true to the great principle of the system — necessary deter- mination. Locke, in distinguishing the will from the desire, seems about to launch into a different psychology, and one destructive of the principle. II. LEGITIMATE CONSEQUENCES EDWARDS'S SYSTEM. II. THE LEGITIMATE CONSEQUENCES OF EDWARDS'S SYSTEM. These consequences must, I am aware, be deduced with the greatest care and clearness. The deduc- tion must be influenced by no passion or prejudice. It must be purely and severely logical — and such I shall endeavour to make it. I shall begin with a deduction which Edwards has himself made. I. There is no self-determining power of will, and of course no liberty consisting in a self-deter- ming power. A self-determining power of will is a supposed power, which will has to determine its own voli- tions. Will is the faculty of choice,, or the capacity of desire, emotion, or passion* Volition is the strongest desire, or the sense of the most agreeable at any given moment. 8* 90 CONSEQUENCE- or Volition arises from the state of the mind, or of the will, or .sensitivity itself, in correlation with the nature and circumstances of the object. Now, if the will determined itself, it would deter- mine its own stale, in relation to objects. But to determine is to act, and therefore, for the will to determine is for the will to a^t ; and for the will to determine itself, is for the will to determine itself by an act. But an act of the will is a volition ; therefore for the will to determine itself is to create a volition by a volition. But then we have to account for this antecedent volition, and it can be accounted for only in the same way* We shall then have an infinite,, or more properly* an indefinite series of volitions, without any first vo- lition j consequently we shall have no self-deter- miner after all, because we can arrive at no first determiner^ and thus the idea of self-determina- tion becomes self-destructive. Again, we shall have effects without a cause, for the series in the nature of the case never ends in a first* which is a cause per se-. Volitions arc thus contingent, using this word as a synonyme of chance^ the negative of cau-e. Now that tins is a .legitimate deduction,, no one can question. If Edwards's psychology be right, arul if self-determination implies a will to will, or EDWAKDS S SYSTEM. !>1 choosing a choice, then a self-determining power is the greatest absurdity possible. II. It is clearly deducible from this also, that God can exercise a perfect control over his intel- ligent creatures, or administer perfectly a moral government consisting in the influence of motives. To any given state of mind, he can adapt mo- tives in reference to required determinations. And when an individual is removed from the motives adapted to his state of mind, the Almighty Provi- dence can so order events as to bring him into contiguity with the motives. If the state of mind should be such that no motives can be made available in reference to a particular determination, it is clearly supposable that he who made the soul of man, may exert a direct influence over this state of mind, and cause it to answer to the motives presented. Whether there are motives adapted to every state of mind, in reference to every possible determination re- quired by the Almighty Lawgiver, so as to render it unnecessary to exert a direct influence over the will, is a question which I am not called upon here to answer. But in either case^ the divine sovereignly, perfect and absolute, fore-determining and bringing to pass every event in the moral as well as the physical world ; and the election of a 92 CONSEQUENCES OF certain number to eternal life, and the making of this election sure, are necessary and plain conse- quences of this system. And as God is a being all-wise and good, we may feel assured in con- nexion with this system, that, in the working out of his great plan, whatever evil may appear in the progress of its developement, the grand con- summation will show that all things have been working together for good. III. It is plainly deducible from this system that moral beings exert an influence over each other by the presentation of motives. And thus efforts may be made either to the injury or bene- fit of society, IV. If, as Edwards contends, the sense of re- sponsibility, the consciousness of guilt or of recti- tude, and consequently the expectation of punish- ment or reward, connect themselves simply with the nature of the mere fact of volition — that is, if this is a true and complete representation of con- sciousness in relation to this subject, then upon the mere fact of volition considered only in its own nature, and wholly independently of its causes, can the processes of justice go forth. Thus we may view the system in relation both to God and to man. edwards's SYSTEM. 93 In relation to God. It makes him supreme and absolute — foreseeing and fore-determining, and bringing everything to pass according to infinite wisdom, and by the energy of an infinite will. In relation to man. It shuts him up to the consideration of the simple fact of volition, and its connexion as a stated or established antece- dent with certain effects. He is free to accom- plish these effects^ because he can accomplish them if he will. He is free to forbear, because he can forbear if he will. It is affirmed to be the common judgement of men, and of course universally a fact of consciousness, that an indi- vidual is fully responsible for the doing of any- thing which ought to be doner if nothing is want- ing to the doing of it but a volition : that he is guilty and punishable for doing anything wrong, because it was done by his volition ; that he is praiseworthy and to be rewarded for doing any- thing right, because it was done by his volition. In vain does he attempt to excuse himself from right-doing on the plea of moral inability ; this is mi tn physical inability, and transcends the sphere of volition. He can do it if he will — and there- fore he has all the ability required in the case. Nothing is immediately wanting but a willing- ness, and all his responsibility relates to this ; he 91 CONSEQUENCES OF can do nothing, can influence nothing, except by will; and therefore that which goes before will is foreign to his consideration, and impossible to his effort. In vain does he attempt to excuse himself for wrong-doing on the ground of moral necessity. This moral necessity is metaphysical necessity, and transcends the sphere of volition. He could have forborne to do wrong, if he had had the will. Whatever else may have been wanting, there was not wanting to a successful resistance of evil, anything with which the agent has any concern, and for which he is under any responsibility, but the volition. By his volitions simply is he to be tried. No court of justice, human or divine, that we can conceive of, could admit the plea — "I did not the good because I had not the will to do it," or " I did the evil because I had the will to do it." " This is your guilt," would be the reply of the judge, "that you had no will to do the good — that you had a will to do the evil." We must now take up a different class of de- ductions. They are such as those abettors of this system who wish to sustain the great interests of edwards's system. 95 morality and religion do not make, but strenuously contend against. If however they are logical de- ductions, it is in vain to contend against them. I am conscious of no wish to force them upon the system, and do most firmly believe that they are logical. Let the reader judge for himself, but let him judge thou l the most free of all beings, because nothing car, impede his will. His volitions arc always the antecedents of elfects. But obviously \vc do not alter the relation, when we change the terms. If liberty lie in the stated antecedence of volition to effects, and if libcrt\ if measured by the necessity of the relation, then when the antecedent is changed, the relation re- maining the same, liberty must still be present. For example : when a volition to move the arm is followed by a motion of the arm, there is liber- ty : now let galvanism be substituted for the vo- lition, and the effect as certainly takes place ; and as freedom is doing as we please, or will, " with- out considering how this pleasure (or will) comes to be as it is ;" that is, without taking its motive into the account. So likewise, freedom may be affirmed to be doing according to the galvanic impulse, "without considering how'" that impulse " comes to be as it is." If we take any other instance of stated ante- cedence and sequence, the reasoning is the same. For example, a water wheel in relation to the mill- stone : when the wheel turns, the mill-stone moves. In this case freedom may be defined : the mill- stone moving according to the turn of the wheel, M without considering how" that turn of the wheel edwards's system. 1J7 " comes to be as it is." In the case of human freedom, freedom is defined, doing according to our volitions, without considering how the volition comes to be as it is ; doing " according to choice, without taking into the meaning of the word any- thing of the cause of that choice." (p. 39.) If it be said that in the case of volition, we have the man of whom to affirm freedom ; but in the case of the wheel and mill-stone, we have nothing of which liberty can properly be affirmed. I reply, that liberty must be affirmed, and is pro- perly affirmed, of that to which it really belongs ; and hence as volition is supposed to belong to the spiritual essence, man ; and this spiritual essence is pronounced free, because volition appears in it. and is attended by consequences : — so, likewise, the material essence of the wheel may be pro- nounced free, because motion belongs to it, and is followed by consequences. As every being that has volition is free, so likewise every thing that hath motion is free : — in every instance of cause and effect, we meet with liberty. But volition cannot be the characteristic of lib- erty, if volition itself be governed by necessity : and yet this system which affirms liberty, where- evcr there is unimpeded volition, makes volition a necessary determination. In the fact of unimpe- 128 consequences or dcd volition, it gives liberty to all creatures that have volition ; and then again, in the fact of the necessary determination of volition it destroys the possibility of liberty. But even where it affirms liberty to exist, there is no new feature to charac- terize it as liberty. The connexion between voli- tion and its stated consequences, is a connexion as necessary and absolute as the connexion be- tween the motive and the volition, and between any antecedent and sequent whatever. That my arm should move when I make a volition to this effect, is just as necessary and just as incompre- hensible too, as that water should freeze at a given temperature : when the volition is impeded, we have only another instance of necessity, — a lesser force overcome by a greater. The liberty therefore which this system affirms in the fact of volition and its unimpeded con- nexion with its consequents, is an assumption — a mere name. It is a part of the universal necessity arbitrarily distinguished and named. As liberty does not reside in human volition, so neither can it reside in the divine volition. The necessary dependence of volition upon motive, and the ne- cessary sequence of effects upon volition, can no more be separated from the divine mind than from ours. It is a doctrine which, if true, is im- EDWAKDS's SYSTEM. 129 plied in the universal conception of mind. It be- longs to mind generically considered. The crea- tion of volition by volition is absurd in itself — it cannot but be an absurdity. The determination of will by the strongest motive, if a truth is a truth universally ; on this system, it contains the whole cause and possibility of volition. The whole liberty of God, it is affirmed, is contained in this, to do as pleases him, or, in other words, that what he wills is accomplished, and necessa- rily accomplished : what pleases him is also fixed in the necessity of his own nature. His liberty, therefore, by its own definition, differs nothing from necessity. If the movements of mind are necessary, no argument is required to prove that all being and events are necessary. We are thus bound up in a universal necessity. Whatever is, is, and cannot be otherwise, and could not have been otherwise. As therefore there is no liberty, we are reduced to the only remaining alternative of fatalism. Edwards does not indeed attempt to rebut wholly the charge of fatalism, (part iv. § vi.) In relation to the Stoics, he remarks: — "It seems they differed among themselves ; and probably the doctrine of fate as maintained by most of them, was, in some respects, erroneous. But 130 CONSEQUENCES OF whatever their doctrines was, if any of them held such a fate, as is repugnant to any liberty, consist' ing in our doing as we please, I utterly deny such a fate." He objects to fatalism only when it should deny our actions to be connected with our pleasure, or our sense of the most agreeable, that is our volition. But this connexion we have fully proved to be as necessary as the connexion be- tween the volition and its motive. This reserva- tion therefore does not save him from fatalism. In the following section, (sec. vii.) he repre- sents the liberty and sovereignty of God as con- sisting in an ability " to do whatever pleases him." His idea of the divine liberty, therefore, is the same as that attributed to man. That the divine volitions are necessarily determined, he repeated- ly affirms, and indeed represents as the great ex- cellence of the divine nature, because this neces- sity of determination is laid in the infinite wisdom and perfection of his nature. If necessity govern all being and events, it i • cheering to know that, it is necessity under the forms of infinite wisdom and benevolence. But still it remains true that necessity governs. If " it is no disadvantage or dishonour to a being, necessarily to act in the most excellent and hap- py manner from the necessary perfection of his edwards's system. 131 own nature,'' still let us remember that under this representation he docs act necessarily. Fate must have some quality or form ; it must be what we call good or evil : but in determining its qual- ity, we do not destroy its nature. Now if we call this fate a nature of goodness and wisdom, eternal and infinite, we present it under forms beautiful, benign, and glorious, but it is neverthe- less fate, — and as such it governs the divine vo- litions ; and through the divine volitions, all the consequents and effects of these volitions ; — the universe of being and things is determined by fate ; — and all volitions of angels or men are de- termined by fate — by this fate so beautiful, be- nign, and glorious. Now if all things thus pro- ceeding from fate were beautiful, benign, and glo- rious, the theory might not alarm us. But that deformity, crime, and calamity should have place as developements of this fate, excites uneasiness. The abettors of this system, however, may per- haps comfort themselves with the persuasion that deformity, crime, and calamity, are names not of realities, but of the limited conceptions of man- kind. We have indeed an instance in point in Charles Bonnet, whom Dugald Stewart men- tions as - a very learned and pious disciple of Leibnitz." Says Bonnet — "Thus the same chain \'.)2 CONSEQUENCES OF embraces the physical and moral world, binds the past to the present, the present to the future, the future to eternity. That wisdom which has ordained the existence of this chain, has doubtless willed that of every link of which it is composed. A Caligula is one of these links; and this link is of iron. A Marcus Aurelius is another link ; and this link is of gold. Both are necessary parts of one whole, which could not but exist. Shall God then be angry at the sight of the iron link ? What absurdity ! God esteems this link at its proper value. He sees it in its cause, and he approves this cause, for it is good. God beholds moral monsters as he beholds physical monsters. Happy is the link of gold ! Still more happy if he know that he is only fortunate. lie has at- tained the highest degree of moral perfection, and is nevertheless without pride, knowing that what he is, is the necessary result, of the place which he must occupy in the chain. The gospel is the allegorical exposition of this system ; the simile of the potter is its summary." He might have added, " Happy is the link of iron, if he know that he is not guilty, but at worst only unfortu- nate ; and really not unfortunate, because holding a necessary place in the chain which both as a whole and in its parts, is the result of infinite wis- dom." edwards's system. 133 If anything more is required in order to estab- lish this consequence of the system we are exam- ining, I would call attention to the inquiry, wheth- er after a contingent self-determining will there remains any theory of action except fatalism ? A contingent self-determining will is a will which is the cause of its own volitions or choices — a self- conscious power, self-moved and directed, and at the moment of its choice, or movement towards a particular object, conscious of ability of choos- ing, or moving towards, an opposite object. Now what conception have we to oppose to this but that of a will not determining itself, — not the cause of its own volitions, — a power not self- moved and directed, — and not conscious of abili- ty at the moment of a particular choice, to make a contrary choice ? And this last conception is a will whose volitions are determined by some power antecedent to itself, not contingently, but necessarily. As the will is the only power for which contingent self-determination is claimed, if it be proved to be no such power, then no such power exists. The whole theory of action and causality will then be expressed as follows : 1. Absolute and necessary connexion of mo- tives and volitions. 2. Absolute and necessary connexion of volitions and effects. 3. Absolute 12 134 COHSBQUEKCEfl OF and necessary connexion of all sequenls and an- tecedents in nature. 4. Absolute and necessary connexion of all things existent with a first and necessary principle or cause. 5. The necessaiy determination of this principle or cause. Denying a contingent self-determining will, this theory is all that remains. If liberty be affirmed to reside in the 2d particular of this theory, it be- comes a mere arbitrary designation, because the nature of the relation is granted to be the same ; it is not contingent, but necessary. Nor can lib- erty be affirmed to reside in the 5th ; because in the first place, the supposed demonstration of the absurdity of a contingent self-determining will, by infinite series of volitions, must apply to this great first principle considered as God. And in the second place, the doctrine of the necessary de- termination of motive must apply here likewise, since God as will and intelligence requires mo- tives no less than we do. Such determination is represented as arising from the very nature of mind or spirit. Now this theory advanced in op- position to a self-determining will, is plainly the negation of liberty as opposed to necessity. And this is all that can be meant by fatalism. Liberty thus becomes a self-contradictory conception, and fatalism alone is truth and reality. EDWARDs's SYSTEM. 135 XVII. It appears to me also, that pantheism is a fair deduction from this system. According to this system, God is the sole and universal doer — the only efficient cause. 1. His volition is the creative act, by which all beings and things exist. Thus far it is generally conce- ded that God is all in all. " By him we live, and move, and have our being." 2. The active powers of the whole system of nature he has constituted and regulated. The winds are his messengers, The flaming fire his servant. However we may conceive of these powers, whether as really pow- ers acting under necessary laws, or as immediate manifestations of divine energy, in either case it is proper to attribute all their movements to God. These movements were ordained by his wisdom, and are executed directly or indirectly by his will. Every effect which we produce in the ma- terial world, we produce by instrumentality. Our arms, hands, &x. are our first instruments. All that we do by the voluntary use of these, we at- tribute to ourselves. Now if we increase the in- strumentality by the addition of an axe, spade, or hammer, still the effect is justly attributed in the same way. It is perfectly clear that to whatever extent we multiply the instruments, the principle is the same. Whether I do the deed directly 186 CONSEQUENCES OF with my hand, or do it by an instrument held in my hand, or by a concatenation of machinery, reaching from "the centre to the utmost pole," — if I contemplate the deed, and designedly accom- plish it in this way, the deed is mine. And not only is the last deed contemplated as the end of all this arrangement mine, all the intermediary movements produced as the necessary chain of antecedents and sequents by which the last is to be attained, are mine likewise. I use powers and instruments whose energy and capacity I have learned by experience, but in whose constitution I have had no hand. They are provided for me, and I merely use them. But God in working by these, works by what his own wisdom and power have created ; and therefore a fortiori must every effect produced by these, according to his design, and by his volition as at least the first power of the series, be attributed to him, — be called his doing. He causeth the sun to rise and set. " He causeth the grass to grow for the cattle, and herb for the service of man." " lie watereth the hills from his chambers." This is not merely poetry. It is truth. Now the system we arc considering goes one step further; it makes human volitions as much the objects of the eternal design, and as really the EDWAKDs's SYSTEM. 137 effects of the divine volition, as the rising of the stars, the flight of the lightning, the tumult of the waters, or the light which spreadeth itself like a garment over creation. Every volition of created mind is God's act, as really as any effect in nature. We have seen how every volition is connected with its motive ; how the motive lies in a pre- constitution ; how the series of antecedents and sequents necessarily runs back and connects itself with the infinite wisdom. God's volition is his own act ; the effect immediately produced by that volition is his own deed. Let that effect be the creation of man : the man in all his powers and susceptibilities is God's work ; the objects around him are God's work ; the correlation of the objects with the sensitivity of man is God's work ; the volition which necessarily takes place as the result of this correlation is God's work. The volition of the man is as strictly attributable to God, as, according to our common apprehen- sions, the blow which I give with an axe is attri- butable to me. What is true of the first man, must be equally true of the man removed by a thousand generations, for the intermediary links are all ordained by God under an inevitable ne- cessity. God is really, therefore, the sole doer — the only efficient, the only cause. All beings and 12* 138 CONSEQUENCES OF things, all motion and all volition, are absolutely resolved into divine volition. God is the author ol' all beings, things, motions, and volitions, and as much the author of any one of these as of any other, and the author of all in the same way and in the same sense. Set aside self-determining will, and there is no stopping-place between a hu- man volition and the divine volition. The human volition is but the divine, manifested through a lengthened it may be, but a connected and neces- sary chain of antecedents and sequents. I see no way of escaping from this, as a necessary and le- gitimate consequence of the necessary determina- tion of will. And what is this consequence but pantheism ? God is the universal and all-perva- ding intelligence — the universal and only power. Every movement of nature is necessary ; every movement of mind is necessary ; because neces- sarily caused and determined by the divine voli- tion. There is no life but his, no thought but his, no efficiency but his. He is the soul of the world. Spinosa never represented himself as an athe- ist, and according to the following representation appears rather as a pantheist. " He held that God is the cause of all things ; but that he acts, not from choice, but from necessity ; and, of con- sequence, that he is the involuntary author of all EDWARDS S SYSTEM. 139 the good and evil, virtue and vice, which are ex- hibited in human life." (Dugald Stewart, vol. 6. p. 276, note.) Cousin remarks, too, that Spinosa deserves rather the reproacli of pantheism than of atheism. His pantheism was fairly deduced from the doctrine of necessary determination, which he advocated. XVIII. Spinosa, however, is generally consid- ered an atheist. " It will not be disputed," say3 Stewart, M by those who comprehend the drift of his reasonings, that in point of practical tendency atheism and Spinosism are one and the same." The following is Cousin's view of his system. It apparently differs from the preceding in some respects, but really tends to the same conclusions. "Instead of accusing Spinosa of atheism, he ought to be reproached for an error in the other direction. Spinosa starts from the perfect and infinite being of Descartes's system, and easily demonstrates that such a being is alone a being in itself; but that a being, finite, imperfect, and relative, only participates of being, without pos- sessing it, in itself: that a being in itself is one necessarily : that there is but one substance ; and that all that remains has only a phenomenal ex- istence : that to call phenomena, finite substances, is affirming and denying, at the same time ; 1 40 CONSEQUENCES OF whereas, there being but one substance which possesses being in itself, and the finite being that which participates of existence without possessing it in itself, a substance finite implies two contra- dictory notions. Thus, in the philosophy of Spi- nosa, man and nature are pure phenomena ; sim- ple attributes of that one and absolute substance, but attributes which are co-eternal with their sub- stance : for as phenomena cannot exist without a subject, the imperfect without the perfect, the finite without the infinite, and man and nature suppose God ; so likewise, the substance cannot exist without phenomena, the perfect without the imperfect, the infinite without the finite, and God on his part supposes man and nature. The error of his system lies in the predominance of the re- lation of phenomenon to being, of attribute to sub- stance, over the relation of effect to cause. When man has been represented, not as a cause, volun- tary and free, but as necessary and uncontrollable desire, and as an imperfect and finite thought ; God, or the supreme pattern of humanity, can be only a substance, and not a cause — a being, per- fect, infinite, necessary — the immutable substance of the universe, and not its producing and creating cause. In Cartesianism, the notion of substance figures more conspicuously than that of cause ; edwards's system. 141 and this notion of substance, altogether predomi- nating, constitutes Spinosism." (Hist, de la Phil, torn. 1. p. 4GG.) The predominance of the notion of substance and attribute, over that of cause and effect, which Cousin here pronounces the vice of Spinosa's sys- tem, is indeed the vice of every system which contains the dogma of the necessary determina- tion of will. The first consequence is pantheism ; the second, atheism. I will endeavour to explain. When self-determination is denied to will, and it is resolved into mere desire, necessitated in all its acts from its pre-constituted correlation with ob- jects, then will really ceases to be a cause. It becomes an instrument of antecedent power, but is no power in itself, creative or productive. The reasoning employed in reference to the human will, applies in all its force to the divine will, as has been already abundantly shown. The divine will therefore ceases to be a cause, and becomes a mere instrument of antecedent power. This antecedent power is the infinite and necessary wisdom ; but infinite and necessary wisdom is eternal and unchangeable ; what it is now, it al- ways was ; what tendencies or energies it has now, it always had ; and therefore, whatever vo- litions it now necessarily produces, it always ne- 142 CONSEQUENCES OF ccssarily produced. If we conceive a volition to have been, in one direction, the immediate and necessary antecedent of creation ; and, in another, the immediate and necessary sequent of infinite, and eternal, and necessary wisdom ; then this vo- lition must have always existed, and consequently, creation, as the necessary effect of this volition, must have always existed. The eternal and infi- nite wisdom thus becomes the substance, because this is existence in itself, no antecedent being con- ceivable ; and creation, consisting of man and na- ture, imperfect and finite, participating only of ex- istence, and not being existence in themselves, are not substances, but phenomena. But what is the relation of the phenomena to the substance ? Not that of effect to cause; — this relation slides en- tirely out of view, the moment will ceases to be a cause. It is the relation simply of phenomena to being, considered as the necessary and insepara- ble manifestations of being ; the relation of attri- butes to substance, considered as the necessary and inseparable properties of substance. We can- not conceive of substance without attributes or phenomena, nor of attributes or phenomena with- out substance ; they are, therefore, co-eternal in this relation. Who then is God ? Substance and its attributes ; being and its phenomena. In other edwards's system. 143 words, the universe, as made up of substance and attributes, is God. This is Spinosism ; this is pan- theism ; and it is the first and legitimate conse- quence of a necessitated will. The second consequence is atheism. In the denial of will as a cause per se, — in resolving all its volitions into the necessary phenomena of the eternal substance, — we destroy personality : wo have nothing remaining but the universe. Now we may call the universe God ; but with equal propriety we call God the universe. This destruc- tion of personality, — this merging of God into necessary substance and attributes, — is all that we mean by Atheism. The conception is really the same, whether we name it fate, pantheism, or atheism. The following remark of Dugald Stewart, shows that he arrived at the same result : " What- ever may have been the doctrines of some of the ancient atheists about man's free agencv, it will not be denied that, in the history of modern phi- losophy, the schemes of atheism and of necessitv have been hitherto always connected together. Not that I would by any means be understood to say. that every necessitarian must ipso facto be an atheist, or even that any presumption is afford- ed, by a man's attachment to the former sect, of Mi CONSEQUENCES OF his having the slightest bias in favour of the lat- ter : hut only that ever}' modern atheist I have heard of has been a necessitarian. I cannot help adding, that the most consistent necessitarians who have yet appeared, have been those who followed out their principles till they ended in Spinosism, — a doctrine which differs from athe- ism more in words than in reality." (Vol. 6, p. 470.) Cudworth, in his great work entitled " The true Intellectual System of the Universe," shows clearly the connexion between fatalism and atheism. This work seems to have grown out of another undertaking, which contemplated spe- cifically the question of liberty and necessity, and its bearing upon morality and religion. The pas- sage in the preface, in which he informs us of his original plan, is a very full expression of his opin- ion. " First, therefore, I acknowledge," says he, " that when I engaged the press, I intended only a discourse concerning liberty and necessity, or, to speak out more plainly, against the fatal neces- sity of all actions and events ; which, upon what- soever grounds or principles maintained, will, as we conceive, serve the design of atheism, and un- dermine Christianity, and all religion, as taking away all guilt and blame, punishments and re- edwards's system. 145 wards, and plainly rendering a day of judgement ridiculous." This opinion of the tendency of the doctrine of a necessitated will, is the germ of his work. The connexion established in his mind be- tween this doctrine and atheism, naturally led him to his masterly and elaborate exposition and refutation of the latter. The arguments of many atheists might be re- ferred to, to illustrate the connexion between ne- cessity and atheism. I shall here refer, how- ever, to only one individual, remarkable both for his poetic genius and metaphysical acumen. I mean the late Piercy Bysshe Shelley. He openly and unblushingly professed atheism. In his Queen Mab we find this line : " There is no God." In a note upon this line, he remarks : " This nega- tion must be understood solely to affect a creative Deity. The hypothesis of a pervading spirit, co- eternal with the universe, remains unshaken." This last hypothesis is Pantheism. Pantheism is really the negation of a creative Deity, — the identity or at least necessary and eternal co-exist- ence of God and the universe. Shelley has ex- pressed this clearly in another passage : "Spirit of nature! all-sufficing power, Necessity ! thou mother of the world !"' In a note upon this passage, Shelley has ar- 13 1 50 CONSSQUZlfCE gw .I the doctrine of the necessary determination of will by motive, with an acuteness and power scarcely inferior to Collins or Edwards. lie makes, indeed, a different application of the doc- trim i, but a perfectly legitimate one. Collins and Edwards, and the whole race of necessitarian theologians, evidently toil under insurmountable difficulties, while attempting to base religion upon this doctrine, and effect their escape only under a fog of subtleties. But Shelley, in daring to be perfectly consistent, is perfectly clear. He fear- lessly proceeds from necessity to pantheism, and thence to atheism and the destruction of all mor- al distinctions. " We are taught," he remarks, u by the doctrine of necessity, that there is neither good nor evil in the universe, otherwise than as the events to which we apply these epithets have relation to our own peculiar mode of being. Still less than with the hypothesis of a God, will the doctrine of necessity accord with the belief of a future state of punishment." I here close my deductions from this system. If these deductions be legitimate, as I myself can- not doubt they are, then, to the largest class of readers, the doctrine of necessity is overthrown : it is overthrown by its consequences, and my ED\VARP>"> SYSTEM. 1 17 argument has the force of a rcductio ad absurd um. If a self-determined will appear an absurdity, still it cannot be as absurd as the contrary doctrine, if this doctrine involve the consequences above giv- en. At least, practical wisdom will claim that doctrine which leaves to the world a God, and to man a moral and responsible nature. A question will here very naturally arise : How can we account for the fact that so many wise and good men have contended for a neces- sitated will, as if they were contending for the great basis of all morality and religion l For ex- ample, take Edwards himself, as a man of great thought and of most fervent piety. In the whole of his treatise, he argues with the air and manner of one who is opposing great errors as really con- nected with a self-determined will. What can be stronger than the following language : " I think that the notion of liberty, consisting in a contin- gent self-determination of the will, as necessary to the morality of men's dispositions and actions, is almost inconceivably pernicious ; and that the contrary truth is one of the most important truths of moral philosophy that ever was discussed, and most necessary to be known." The question is a fair one, and I will endeavour to answer it. 1. The impossibility of a self-determining will 1 18 CONSEQUENCES OF as being in itself a contradictory idea, and as leading to the consequence of affirming the exist- ence of elVects without causes, takes strong hold of the mind in these individuals. This I believe, and hope to prove in the course of this treatise, to be a philosophical error; — but it is no new thills for great and good men to fall into philoso- phical errors. As, therefore, the liberty consisting in a self-de- termining will, or the liberty of indifference, as it has been technically called, is conceived to be ex- ploded, they endeavour to supply a liberty of spontaneity, or a liberty lying in the unimpeded connexion between volition and sequents. Hobbes has defined and illustrated this liberty in a clearer manner than any of its advocates : " I conceive,'' says he, " liberty to be rightly de- fined,— the absence of all impediments to action, that are not contained in the nature and intrinsi- cal quality of the agent. As for example, the water is said to descend freely, or is said to have liberty to descend by the channel of the river, be- cause there is no impediment that way ; but not across, because the banks are impediments : and though water cannot ascend, yet men never say, it wants the liberty to ascend, but the faculty or power, because the impediment is in the nature of EDWAKDS'S SYSTEM. 149 the water, and intrinsical. So also we say, he that is tied, wants the liberty to go, because the impediment is not in him, but in his hands; where- as, we say not so of him who is sick or lame, be- cause the impediment is in himself," — that is, he wants the faculty or power of going : — this con- stitutes natural inability. Liberty is volition act- ing upon physical instrumentalities, or upon men- tal faculties, according to a fixed and constituted law of antecedents, and meeting with no impedi- ment or overcoming antagonistic power. Natu- ral ability is the fixed and constituted antecedence itself. Hence there may be natural ability with- out liberty ; but liberty cannot be affirmed with- out natural ability. Both are necessary to con- stitute responsibility. Natural ability is volition known as a stated antecedent of certain effects. Liberty is this antecedent existing without impedi- ment or frustration. Since this is the only possible liberty remaining, and as they have no wish to be considered fatalists, they enlarge much upon this ; not only as the whole of liberty actually existing, but as the full and satisfactory notion of liberty. In basing responsibility and praise and blame- worthiness upon this liberty, an appeal is made to the common ideas, feelings, and practices of men. Every man regards himself as free when he does 13* 150 CONSEQUENCES OF as he pleases, — when, if he pleases to walk, he walks, — when, if he pleases to sit down, he sits down, Sec. If a man, in a court of justice, were to plead in excuse that he committed the crime because he pleased or willed to do it, the judge would reply — " this is your guilt, that you pleased or willed to commit it : nay, your being pleased or willing to commit it was the very doing of it." Now all this is just. I readily admit that we are free when we do as we please, and that we arc guilty when, in doing as we please, we commit a crime. Well, then, it is asked, is not this liberty suffi- cient to constitute responsibility ? And thus the whole difficulty seems to be got over. The rea- soning would be very fair, as far as it goes, if em- ployed against fatalists, but amounts to nothing when employed against those who hold to the self-determining power of the will. The latter receive these common ideas, feelings, and prac- tices of men, as facts indicative of freedom, be- cause they raise no question against human free- dom. The real question at issue is, how are we to account for these facts ? The advocates of self- determining power account for them by referring them to a self-determined will. We say a man is free when he does as he pleases or according to his volitions, and has the sense of freedom in edwards's system. 151 iiis volitions, because he determines his own voli- tions ; and that a man is guilty for crime, if com- mitted by his volition, because he determined this volition, and at the very moment of determining it, was conscious of ability to determine an oppo- posite volition. And we affirm, also, that a man is free, not only when he docs as he pleases, or, in other words, makes a volition without any im- pediment between it and its object, — he is free, if he make the volition without producing effects by it : volition itself is the act of freedom. But how do those who deny a self-determining pow- er account for these facts ? They say that the volition is caused by a motive antecedent to it, but that nevertheless, inasmuch as the man feels that he is free and is generally accounted so, he must be free : for liberty means nothing more than " power and opportunity to do and conduct as he will, or according to his choice, without taking in- to the meaning of the word any thing of the cause of that choice, or at all considering how the per- son came to have such a volition," — that is, the man is free, and feels himself to be so, when he does as he pleases, because this is all that is meant by freedom. But suppose the objection be brought up, that the definition of liberty here given is assumed, ar- 152 ( oN^EQUENCES OF bitrary, and unsatisfactory ; and that the sense or consciousness of freedom in the act of volition, and the common sentiments and practices of men in reference to voluntary action, are not ade- quately accounted for, — then the advocates of necessitated volition return to the first argument, of the impossibility of any other definition, — and affirm that, inasmuch as this sense of freedom does exist, and the sentiments and practices of men generally correspond to it, we must believe that we are free when volition is unimpeded in its connexion with sequents, and that we are blame or praiseworthy, according to the perceiv- ed character of our volitions, — although it can- not but be true that the volitions themselves are necessary. On the one hand, they are compelled by their philosophy to deny a self-determining will. On the other hand, they are compelled, by their moral sense and religious convictions, to up- hold moral distinctions and responsibility. In or- der to do this, however, a quasi liberty must be preserved : hence the attempt to reconcile liber- ty and necessity, by referring the first exclusively to the connexion between volition and its se- quents, and the second exclusively to the connex- ion between the volition and its antecedents or motives. Liberty is physical ; necessity is meta- EDWAItDS's SYSTEM. 153 physical. The first belongs to man ; the second transcends the sphere of his activity, and is not his concern. In this very difficult position, no better or more ingenious solution could be devis- ed ; but that it is wholly illogical and ineffectual, and forms no escape from absolute and universal necessity, has already been abundantly proved. 2. The philosophers and divines of whom we are speaking, conceive that when volitions are supposed to exist out of the necessary determina- tion of motives, they exist fortuitously and with- out a cause. But to give up the necessary and universal dependence of phenomena upon causes, would be to place events beyond the divine con- trol : nay, more, — it would destroy the great a posteriori argument for the existence of a God. Of course it wrould be the destruction of all mo- rality and religion. 3. The doctrine of the divine foreknowledge, in particular, is much insisted upon as incompati- ble with contingent volitions. Divine foreknow- ledge, it is alleged, makes all events certain and necessary. Hence volitions are necessary ; and, to carry out the reasoning, it must be added like- wise that the connexion between volitions and their sequents is equally necessary. God fore- sees the sequent of the volition as well as the vo- 164 CONSEQUENCE- OF litidii. The theory, however, is careful to pre- serve the name of liberty, because it fears the de- signation which properly belongs to it. 4. By necessary determination, the sovereignty of (-'id ami the harmony of his government are preserved. His volitions are determined by his infinite wisdom. The world, therefore, must be ruled in truth and righteousness. These philosophers and divines thus represent to themselves the theory of a self-determining will as an absurdity in itself, and, if granted to be true, as involving the most monstrous and disas- trous consequences, while the theory which they advocate is viewed only in its favourable points, and without reaching forth to its legitimate con- sequences. If these consequences are urged by another hand, they are sought to be evaded by concentrating attention upon the fact of volition and the sense of freedom attending it : for exam- ple, if fatalism be urged as a consequence of this theory, the ready reply is invariably — " No such necessity is maintained as goes to destroy the lib- erty which consists in doing as one pleases ;" or if the destruction of responsibility be urged as a consequence, the reply is — "A man is always held a just subject of praise or blame when he acts voluntarily." The argumentation undoubt-- edwards's system. 155 edly is as sincere as it is earnest. The interests at stake are momentous. They are supposed to perish, if this philosophy be untrue. No wonder, then, that, reverencing and loving morality and re- ligion, they should by every possible argument aim to sustain the philosophy which is supposed to lie at their basis, and look away from consequences so destructive, persuading themselves that these consequences are but the rampant sophistries of infidelity. It is a wonderful fact in the history of philoso- phy, that the philosophy of fate, pantheism, and atheism, should be taken as the philosophy of re- ligion. Good men have misapprehended the phi- losophy, and have succeeded in bringing it into fellowship with truth and righteousness. Bad men and erring philosophers have embraced it in a clear understanding of its principles, and have both logically reasoned out and fearlessly owned its consequences. XIX. Assuming, for the moment, that the defi- nition of liberty given by the theologians above alluded to, is the only possible definition, it must follow that the most commonly received modes of preaching the truths and urging the duties of religion are inconsistent and contradictory. A class of theologians has been found in the 156 COMBSQUBlfCBfl OF church, who, perhaps without intending absolute- ly to deny human freedom, have denied all abili- ty on the part of man to comply with the divine precepts. A generic distinction between inability and a want of freedom is not tenable, and cer- tainly is of no moment, where, as in this rase, the inability contended for is radical and absolute. These theologians clearly perceived, that if vo- lition is necessarily determined by motive, and if motive lies in the correlation of desire and object, then, in a being totally depraved, or a being of radically corrupt desires, there can be no ability to good deeds : the deed is as the volition, and the volition is as the strongest desire or the sense of the most agreeable. Hence these theologians refer the conversion of man exclusively to divine influence. The man cannot change his own heart, nor employ any means to that end ; for this would imply a volition for which, according to the supposition, he has no ability. Now, at the same time, that this class represent men as unable to love and obey the truths of reli- gion, they engage with great zeal in expounding these truths to their minds, and in urging upon them the duty of obedience. But what is the aim of this preaching ? Perhaps one will reply, I know UNIVERSIT EDWARDS S SYSTKM. the man cannot determine himself to obedience, but in preaching to him, I am presenting motives which may influence him. But in denying his ability to do good, you deny the possibility of moving him by motives drawn from religious truth and obligation. His heart, by supposition, is not in correlation with truth and duty ; the more, therefore, you preach truth and duty, the more intense is the sense of the disagreeable which you awaken. As when you present objects to a man's mind which are correlated to his feelings, the more clearly and frequently you present them, the more you advance towards the sense of the most agreeable or choice. So when you present ob- jects which are not correlated to his feelings, the more clearly and frequently you present them, the more you must advance towards the sense of the most disagreeable, or positive refusal. If it be affirmed, in reply to this, that the pre- sentation of truth forms the occasion or condition on which the divine influence is exerted for the regeneration of the heart, then I ask, why do you urge the man to repent, and believe, and love God, and discharge religious duty generally, and rebuke him for sin, when you know that he is utterly unable to move, in the slightest degree, towards any of these affections and actions, and 14 158 CONSEQUENCES OF utterly unable to leave off sinning, until the divine influence be exerted, which brings his heart into correlation with religion, and makes it possible for him to put forth the volitions of piety and duty? It can be regarded in no other light than playing a solemn farce, thus to rebuke and urge and per- suade, as if the man ought to make some exertion when you feel convinced that exertion is impossi- ble. It certainly can form no occasion for divine interposition, unless it be in pity of human folly. If you say that such a course does succeed in the conversion of men, then we are constrained to believe that your philosophy is wrong, and that your practice succeeds, because inconsistent with it, and really belonging to some other system which you know not, or understand not and deny. A total inability to do good makes man the passive subject of influences to be employed for his regeneration, and he can no more be consid- ered active in effecting it than he is in the process of digesting food, or in the curative action of DO * medicines upon any diseased part of his system. If you urge him to exert himself for his regenera- tion, you urge him to put forth volitions which, according to this philosophy, are in no sense pos- sible until the regeneration has been effected, or at least commenced. edwards's system. 159 I will go one step farther in this reasoning : — on supposition of total inability, not only is the in- dividual a passive subject of regenerating influ- ences, but he is also incapable of regeneration, or any disposition or tendency towards regeneration, from any influences which lie merely in motives, produced by arraying objects before the mind. Motive, according to the definition, exhibited in the statement of Edwards's system, lies in the nature and circumstances of the object standing in correlation with the state of mind. Now the state of mind, in an unregenerate state, is a state represented by this system itself, as totally adverse to the objects of religion. Hence, there is no conceivable array of religious truth, and no con- ceivable religious exhortation and persuasion that could possibly come into such a relation to this state of mind as to form the motive of a religious choice or volition. It is perfectly plain, that be- fore such a result could take place, the state of mind itself would have to be changed. But as the array of religious truth and the energy of reli- gious exhortation must fail to produce the requir- ed volitions, on account of the state of mind, so neither can the state of mind be changed by this array of truth or by this exhortation. There is a positive opposition of mind and object, and the 100 CONSEQUENCES OF collision becomes more severe upon every attempt to bring them together. It must follow, therefore, that preaching truth and duty to the unregcnerate, so far from leading to their conversion, can only serve to call out more actively the necessary de- termination, not to obey. The very enlightening of the intelligence, as it gives a clearer perception of the disagreeable objects, only increases the dis- inclination. Nor can we pause in this consequence, at human instrumentality. It must be equally true, that if divine interposition lies in the presentation of truth and persuasions to duty, only that these are given with tenfold light and power, it must fail of accom- plishing regeneration, or of producing any tenden- cy towards regeneration. The heart being in no correlation with these, — its sense of the disagree- able,— and therefore the energy of its refusal will only be the more intense and decided. If it should be remarked that hope and fear are feelings, which, even in a state of unregeneracy, can be operated upon, the state of things is equally difficult. No such hope can be operated upon as implies desire after religious principles and enjoy- ments ; for this cannot belong to the corrupt na- ture ; nor can any fear be aroused which implies a reverence of the divine purity, and an abhor- EDW.VUDs's SYSTEM. 10] rence of sin. The fear could only relate to dan- ger and suffering ; and the hope, to deliverance and security, independently of moral qualities. The mere excitement of these passions might awaken attention, constrain to an outward obedi- ence, and form a very prudent conduct, but could effect no purification of the heart. There is another class of theologians, of whom Edwards is one, who endeavour to escape the difficulties which attend a total inability, by making the distinction of moral and natural inability : — man, they say, is morally unable to do good, and naturally able to do good, and therefore he can justly be made the subject of command, appeal, rebuke, and exhortation. The futility of this dis- tinction I cannot but think has already been made apparent. It may be well, however, inasmuch as so great stress is laid upon it, to call up a brief consideration of it in this particular connexion. Moral inability, as we have seen, is the impos- sibility of a given volition, because there are no motives or causes to produce it. It is simply the impossibility of an effect for the want of a cause : when we speak of moral cause and effect, accord- ing to Edwards, we speak of nothing different from physical cause and effect, except in the quality of the terms — the relation of the terms is the same. 14* 1G'2 CONSEQUENCES OF The impossibility of a given volition, therefore, when the appropriate motive is wanting, is equal to the impossibility of freezing water in the sun of a summer's noon-tide.* When objects of volition are fairly presented, an inability to choose them must lie in the state of the mind, sensitivity, desire, will, or affections, for all these have the same meaning according to this system. There is no volition of preference where there is no motive to this effect ; and there is no motive to this effect where the state of the mind is not in correlation with the objects presented : on the contrary, the volition which now takes place, is a volition of refusal. Natural inability, as defined by this system, lies in the connexion between the volition considered as an antecedent, and the effect required. Thus I am naturally unable to walk, when, although I * "It is remarkable that the advocates for necessity have adopt- ed a distinction made use of for other purposes, and forced it into their service ; I mean moral and natural necessity. They say natural or physical necessity takes away liberty, but moral ne- cessity does not : at the same time they explain moral necessity so as to make it truly physical or natural. That is physical ne- cessity which is the invincible effect of the law of nature, and it is neither less natural, nor less insurmountable, if it is from the laws of spirit than it would be if it were from the laws of matter." — (Witherspoon's Lectures on Divinity, lect. xiii.) BDWABDS's system. 103 make the volition, my limbs, through weakness or disease, do not obey. Any defect in the powers or instrumentalities dependent for activity upon volition, or any impediment which volition cannot surmount, constitutes natural inability.* Accord- ing to this system, I am not held responsible for anything which, through natural inability, cannot be accomplished, although the volition is made. But now let us suppose that there is no defect in the powers or instrumentalities dependent for activity upon volition, and no impediment which volition cannot surmount, so that there need be only a volition in order to have the effect, and then the natural ability is complete: — I will to walk, and I walk. Now it is affirmed that a man is fairly respon- sible for the doing of anything, and can be fairly urged to do it when all that is necessary for the doing of it is a volition — although there may be a moral inability to the volition itself. Nothing it seems to me can be more absurd than this distinction. If liberty be essential to * Natural inability, and a want of liberty, arc identified in this usage ; for the want of a natural faculty essential to the perform- ance of an action, and the existence of an impediment or antag- onistic force, which takes from a faculty supposed to exist, the liberty of action, have the same bearing upon responsibility. H*>1 CONSEQUENCES OF responsibility, liberty, as we have clearly shown, can no more lie in the connexion between volition and its effects, than in the connexion between vo- lition and its motives. One is just as necessary as the other. If it be granted to be absurd with the first class of theologians to urge men to do right when they are conceived to be totally una- ble to do right, it is equally so when they are conceived to have only a natural ability to do right, — because this natural ability is of no avail without a corresponding moral ability. If the volition take place, there is indeed nothing to pre- vent the action ; nay, "the very willing is the do- ing of it ;" but then the volition as an effect can- not take place without a cause ; and to acknow- ledge a moral inability, is nothing less than to ac- knowledge that there is no cause to produce the required volition. The condition of men as represented by the second class of theologians, is not really different from their condition as represented by the first class. The inability under both representations is a total inability. In the utter impossibility of a right volition on these, is the utter impossibility of any good deed. When we have denied liberty, in denying a self-determining power, these definitions in order edwards's systkm. 1G5 to make out a quasi liberty and ability, are noth- ing but ingenious folly and plausible deception. You tell the man, indeed, that he can if he will : and when he replies to you, that on your own principles the required volition is impossible, you refer him to the common notions of mankind. According to these, you say a man is guilty when he forbears to do right, since nothing is wanting to right-doing but a volition, — and guilty when he does wrong, because he wills to do wrong. According to these common notions, too, a man may fairly be persuaded to do right, when noth- ing is wanting but a will to do right. But do we find this distinction of natural and moral ability in the common notions of men ? When nothing is required to the performance of a deed but a vo- lition, do men conceive of any inability whatever ? Do they not feel that the volition has a metaphysi- cal possibility as well as that the sequent of the volition has a physical possibility ? Have we not at least some reason to suspect that the phi- losophy of responsibility, and the basis of rebuke and persuasion lying in the common notions of men, are something widely different from the scheme of a necessitated volition ? This last class of theologians, equally with the first, derive all the force of their preaching from 10G CONSEQUENCES OF a philosophy, upon which they arc compelled to act, but which they stoutly deny. Let them car- ry out their philosophy, and fur preaching no place remains. Preaching can produce good ellects only by producing good volitions ; and good volitions can be produced only by good motives: but good mo- tives can exist under preaching only when the subjects of the preaching are correlated with the state of mind. But by supposition this is not the case, for the heart is totally depraved. To urge the unregeneratc man to put forth vo- litions in reference to his regeneration, may con- sist with a self-determining power of will, but is altogether irrelevant on this system. It is urging him to do what he cannot do ; and indeed what all persuasion must fail to do in him as a mere passive subject. To assure him that the affair is quite easy, because nothing is required of him but to will, is equivalent to assuring him that the af- fair is quite easy, because it will be done when he has done it. The man may reply, the affair would indeed be quite easy if there existed in me a motive to produce the volition ; but as there does not, the volition is impossible. And as I cannot put forth the volition without the motive, so neither can I make the motive which is to pro- edwards's system. 107 duce the volition — for then an effect would make its cause. What I cannot do for myself, I fear neither you, nor indeed an angel from heaven will succeed in doing for me. You array the truths, and duties, and prospects of religion be- fore my mind, but they cannot take the character ot motives to influence my will, because they are not agreeable to my heart. You indeed mean well ; but do you not per- ceive that on your own principles all your zeal and eloquence must necessarily have an opposite effect from what you intend ? My affections not being in correlation with these subjects, the more you urge them, the more intense becomes my sense of the most disagreeable, or my positive refusal ; and this, my good friends, by a necessity which holds us all alike in an inevitable and ever- during chain. It is plainly impossible to escape from this con- clusion, and yet maintain the philosophy. All efforts of this kind, made by appealing to the common sentiments of mankind, we have seen are self-contradictory. It will not do to press forward the philosophy until involved in difficulty and perplexity, and then to step aside and bor- row arguments from another system which is as- sumed to be overthrown. There is no necessity 1G8 COlfSSQUBHCKS OF more absolute and sovereign, than a logical nc- i ! \ . ■ Will. The Cardinal principles of Edwards's system in the sections we have been examining, from which the above consequences are deduced, are the three following: 1. The will is always determined by the strong- est motive. 2. The strongest motive is always " the most agreeable." 3. The will is necessarily determined. * It is but justice to remark here, that the distinction of moral and natural inability is made by many eminent divines, without intending anything so futile as that we have above exposed. By moral inability they do not appear to mean anything which really render the actions required, impossible ; but such an impediment as lies in corrupt affections, an impediment which may be re- moved by a self-determination to the use of means and applian- ces graciously provided or promised. By natural ability they mean the possession of all the natural faculties necessary to the performance of the actions required. In their representations of this natural ability, they proceed according to a popular method, rather than a philosophical. They affirm this natural ability as a fact, the denial of which involves monstrous absurdities, but they give no psychological view of it. This task I shall impose upon myself in the subsequent volume. I shall there endeavour to point out the connexion between the sensitivity and the will, both in a pure and a corrupt state, — and explain what these natural faculties are, which, according to the just meaning of these divines, form the ground of rebuke and persuasion, and constitute respon- sibility. edwards's system. 1G9 I shall close this part of the present treatise with a brief examination of the reasoning by which he endeavours to establish these points. The reasoning by which the first point is aimed to be established, is the general reasoning respect- ins cause and effect. Volition is an effect, and must have a cause. Its cause is the motive lying in the correlation of mind and object. When several physical causes conflict with each other, we call that the strongest which prevails and pro- duces its appropriate effects, to the exclusion of the others. So also where there are several moral causes or motives conflicting with each other, we call that the strongest which prevails. Where a physical cause is not opposed by any other force, it of course produces its effect; and in this case we do not say the strongest cause produces the effect, because there is no compari- son. So also there are cases in which there is but one moral cause or motive present, when there being no comparison, we cannot affirm that the volition is determined by the strongest motive : the doing of something may be en- tirely agreeable, and the not doing of it may be utterly disagreeable : in this case the motive is only for the doing of it. But wherever the case contains a comparison of causes or of motives, it ]5 1^0 ( 0N8EQUENCE8 OF must be true that the effect which actually takes place, is produced by the strongest cause or mo- tive. This indeed is nothing more than a truism, or a mere postulate, as if we should say, — let a cause or motive producing effects be called the strongest. It may be represented, also, as a j)c- hiio principii, or reasoning in a circle, — since the proof that the will is determined by the strongest motive is no other than the fact that it is deter- mined. It may be stated thus : The will is deter- mined by the strongest motive. How do you know this ? Because it is determined. How does this prove it ? Because that which determines it must be the strongest.* * " The great argument that men are determined by the strong- est motives, is a mere equivocation, and what logicians call pe- titio principii. It is impossible even to produce any medium of proof that it is the strongest motive, except that it has prevailed. It is not the greatest in itself, nor docs it seem to be in all re- spects the strongest to the agent ; but you say it appears strong- est in the meantime. Why ? Because you arc determined by it. Alas! you promised to prove that I was determined by the ttrongest motive, and you have only shown that I had a motive when I acted. But what has determined you then ? Can any effect be without a cause? I answer — supposing my self-de- termining power to exist, it is as real a cause of its proper and distinguishing effect, as your moral necessity: so that the matter just conies to a stand, and is but one and the same thing on one side and o 1 the other.'' — (Withcrspoon's Lectures, lect. xiii.) edwards's system. 171 Edwards assumes, also, that motive is the cause of volition. This assumption he afterwards en- deavours indirectly to sustain, when he argues against a self-determining will. If the will do not cause its own volitions, then it must follow that motive is the cause. The argument against a self-determining will we are about to take up. 2. Tlie strongest motive is always the most agree- able. Edwards maintains that the motive which always prevails to cause volition, has this charac- teristic, — that it is the most agreeable or pleas- ant at the time, and that volition itself is nothing but the sense of the most agreeable. If there should be but one motive present to the mind, as in that case there would be no comparison, we presume he would only say that the will is deter- mined by the agreeable. But how are we to know whether the motive of every volition has this characteristic of agreea- bleness, or of most agreeableness, as the case may be ? We can know it only by consulting our con- sciousness. If, whenever we will, we find the sense of the most agreeable identified with the volition, and if we are conscious of no power of willing, save under this condition of willing what is most agreeable to us, then certainly there re- mains no farther question on this point. The de- 172 CONSBQl F.NCES OF termination of consciousness is final. Whether such be the determination of consciousness, we are hereafter to consider. Does I'M wards appeal to consciousness? He does, — but without formally announcing it. The following passage is an appeal to con- sciousness, and contains Edwards's whole thought on this subject : " There is scarcely a plainer and more universal dictate of the sense and experience of mankind, than that when men act voluntarily, and do what they please, then they do what suits them best, or what is most agreeable to them. To say that they do what jrfeases them, but yet what is not agreeable to them, is the same thing as to say, they do what they please, but do not act their pleasure ; and that is to say, that they do what they please, and yet do not what they please." (p. 25.) Motives differ widely, intrinsically consider- ed. Some are in accordance with reason and conscience ; some are opposed to reason and con- science. Some are wise ; some are foolish. Some are good ; some are bad. But whatever may be their intrinsic properties, they all have this cha- racteristic of agreeableness when they cause voli- tion ; and it is by this characteristic that their strength is measured. The appeal, however, which is made to sustain this, is made in a way to edwards's system. 173 beg the very point in question. Will not every one admit, that " when men act voluntarily and do what tlicy please, they do what suits them best, and what is most agreeable to them ?" Yes. Is it not a palpable contradiction, to say that men "do what pleases them," and yet do " what is not agreeable to them," according to the ordinary use of these words? Certainly. But the poiet in question is, whether men, act- ing voluntarily, always do what is pleasing to them : and this point Edwards assumes. He as- sumes it here, and he assumes it throughout his treatise. We have seen that, in his psychology, he identifies will and desire or the affections : — hence volition is the prevailing desire or affection, and the object which moves the desire must of course appear desirable, or agreeable, or pleas- ant ; for they have the same meaning. If men always will what they most desire, and desire what they will, then of course when they act vol- untarily, they do what they please ; and when they do what they please, they do what suits them best and is most agreeable to them. Edwards runs the changes of these words with great plausibility, and we must say deceives him- self as well as others. The great point, — wheth- er will and desire are one, — whether the volition 15* 1" 1 ( 0N8BQITBNCE8 OF is as the most agreeable, — lie takes up at the be- gioning as an unquestionable fact, and adheres to throughout as such ; but he never once attempts an analysis of consciousness in relation to it, ade- quate and satisfactory. His psychology is an as- sumption. 3. The will is necessarily determined. How does Edwards prove this? 1. On the general connexion of causes and effects. Causes necessarily produce effects, unless resisted and overcome by opposing forces ; but where several causes are acting in opposition, the strongest will necessarily prevail, and produce its appropriate effects. Now, Edwards affirms that the nature of the connexion between motives and volitions is the same with that of any other causes and effects. The difference is merely in the terms : and when he calls the necessity which characterizes the connexion of motive and volition " a moral neces- sity." he refers not to the connexion itself, but only to the terms connected. In this reasoning he plainly assumes tl.at the connexion betveen cause and effect in general, is a necessary con- nexion ; that is, all causation is necessary. A contingent, self-determining cause, in his system, is characterized as an absurdity. Hence he lays edwards's system. 175 himself open to all the consequences of a univer- sal and absolute necessity. 2. He also endeavours to prove the necessity of volition by a method of approximation, (p. 33.) He here grants, for the sake of the argument, that the will may oppose the strongest motive in a given case ; but then he contends that it is sup- posable that the strength of the motive may be increased beyond the strength of the will to resist, and that at this point, on the general law of cau- sation, the determination of the will must be con- sidered necessary. " Whatever power," he re- marks, " men may be supposed to have to sur- mount difficulties, yet that power is not infinite." If the power of the man is finite, that of the mo- tive may be supposed to be infinite : hence the resistance of the man must at last be necessarily overcome. This reasoning seems plausible at first ; but a little examination, I think, will show it to be fallacious. Edwards does not determine the strength of motives by inspecting their intrin- sic qualities, but only by observing their degrees of agrceableness. But agrecableness, by his own representation, is relative, — relative to the will or sensitivity. A motive of infinite strength would be a motive of infinite agrecableness, and could be known to be such only by an infinite sense of 176 CONSBQUBirCM Off KDWARDs's SYSTEM. agrecableness in the man. The same of course must hold true of any motive less than infinite : and universally, whatever be the degree of strength of the motive, there must be in the man an affec- tion of corresponding intensity. Now, if there be a power of resistance in the will to any mo- tive, which is tending strongly to determine it, this power of resistance, according to Edwards, must consist of a sense of agrecableness opposing the other motive, which is likewise a sense of agrecableness : and the question is simply, which shall predominate and become a sense of the most agreeable. It is plain that if the first be in- creased, the second may be supposed to be in- creased likewise ; if the first can become infinite, the second can become infinite likewise : and hence the power of resistance may be supposed always to meet the motive required to be resist- ed, and a point of necessary determination may never be reached. If Edwards should choose to throw us upon the strength of motives intrinsically considered, then the answer is ready. There are motives of infi- nite strength, thus considered, which men are continually resisting : for example, the motive which urges them to obey and love God, and seek the salvation of their souls. III. EXAMINATION OF THE ARGUMENTS AGAINST A SELF-DETERMINING WILL. III. AN EXAMINATION OF THE ARGUMENTS AGAINST A SELF-DETERMINING AND CONTINGENT WILL. Edwards's first and great argument against a self-determining will, is given in part II. sec. 1, of his work, and is as follows : The will,— or the soul, or man, by the faculty of willing, effects every thing within its power as a cause, by acts of choice. " The will determines which way the hands and feet shall move, by an act of choice ; and there is no other way of the will's determining, directing, or commanding any thing at all." Hence, if the will determines it- self, it does it by an act of choice ; " and if it has itself under its command, and determines itself in its own actions, it doubtless does it in the same way that it determines other things which are un- der its command.'' But if the will determines its 180 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST choice by its choice, then of course we have an infinite series of choices, or wc have a first choice which is not determined by a choice, — "which brings us directly to a contradiction ; for it sup- poses an act of the will preceding the first act in the whole train, directing and determining the rest ; or a free act of the will before the first free act of the will : or else we must come at last to an act of the will determining the consequent acts, wherein the will is not self-determined, and so is not a free act, in this notion of freedom." (p. 43.) This reasoning, and all that follows in the at- tempt to meet various evasions, as Edwards terms them, of the advocates of a self-determining will, depend mainly upon the assumption, that if the will determines itself, it must determine itself by an act of choice ; that is, inasmuch as those acts of the will, or of the soul, considered in its power of willing, or in its personal activity, by which ef- fects are produced out of the activity or will itself, are produced by acts of choice, for example, walking and talking, rising up and sitting down : therefore, if the soul, in the power of willing, cause volitions, it must cause them by volitions. The causative act by which the soul causes voli- tions, must itself be a volition. This assumption A SELF-DETERMINING WILL. 181 Edwards does not even attempt to sustain, but takes for granted that it is of unquestionable va- lidity. If the assumption be of unquestionable validity, then his position is impregnable ; for nothing can be more palpably absurd than the will determining volitions by volitions, in an inter- minable series. Before directly meeting the assumption, I re- mark, that if it be valid, it is fatal to all causal- ity. Will is simply cause ; volition is effect. 1 affirm that the will is the sole and adequate cause of volition. Edwards replies : if will is the cause of volition, then, to cause it, it must put forth a causative act; but the only act of will is volition itself: hence if it cause its own voli- tions, it must cause them by volitions. Now take any other cause : there must be some effect which according to the general views of men stands directly connected with it as its effect. The effect is called the phenomenon, or that by which the cause manifests itself. But how does the cause produce the phenomenon ? By a causative act: — but this causative act, ac- cording to Edwards's reasoning, must itself be an effect or phenomenon. Then this effect comes between the cause, and what was at first consid- ered the immediate effect : but the effect in question 16 182 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST must likewise be caused by a causative act ; and (his causative act, again, being' an effect, must have another causative ad before it ; and so on, ad infinitum. We have here then an infinite se- ries of causative acts — an absurdity of the same kind, with an infinite series of volitions. It follows from this, that there can be no cause whatever. An infinite series of causative acts, without any first, being, according to this reason- ing, the consequence of supposing a cause to cause its own acts, it must therefore follow, that a cause does not cause its own acts, but that they must be caused by some cause out of the cause. But the cause out of the cause which causes the cau- sative acts in question, must cause these causative acts in the other cause by a causative act of its 0Wn : — but the same difficulties occur in relation to the second cause as in relation to the first ; it cannot cause its own acts, and they must there- fore be caused out of itself by some other cause ; and so on, ad infinitum. We have here again the absurdity of an infinite series of causative acts ; and also, the absurdity of an infinite series of causes without a first cause. Otherwise, we must come to a first cause which causes its own acts, without an act of causation ; but this is impossi- ble, according to the reasoning of Edwards. As, therefore, there cannot be a cause causing its own A SELF-DETERMINING WILL. 183 acts, and inasmuch as the denial of this leads to the absurdities above mentioned, we are driven to the conclusion, that there is no cause whatever. Every cause must either cause its own acts, or its acts must be caused out of itself. Neither of these is possible ; therefore, there is no cause. Take the will itself as an illustration of this last consequence. The will is cause ; the volition, ef- fect. But the will does not cause its own voli- tion : the volition is caused by the motive. But the motive, as a cause, must put forth a causative act in the production of a volition. If the motive determine the will, then there must be an act of the motive to determine the will. To determine, to cause, is to do, is to act. But what determines the act of the motive determining the act of the will or volition ? If it determine its own act, or cause its own act, then it must do this by a pre- vious act, according to the principle of this reason- ing ; and this again by another previous act ; and so on, ad infinitum. Take any other cause, and the reasoning must be the same. It may be said in reply to the above, that voli- tion is an effect altogether peculiar. It implies selection or determination in one direction rather than in another, and therefore that in inquiring 184 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST after its cause, we inquire not merely after the energy which makes it existent, but also after the cause of its particular determination in one direc- tion rather than in another. " The question is not so much, how a spirit endowed with activity comes to act, as why it exerts such an act, and not an- other ; or why it acts with a particular determi- nation ? If activity of nature be the cause why a spirit (the soul of man, for instance) acts and does not lie still ; yet that alone is not the cause why its action is thus and thus limited, directed and determined." (p. 50.) Every phenomenon or effect is particular and limited. It must necessarily be one thing and not another, be in one place and not in another, have certain characteristics and not others ; and the cause which determines the phenomenon, may be supposed to determine likewise all its properties. The cause of a particular motion, for example, must, in producing the motion, give it likewise a particular direction. Volition must have an object ; something is willed or chosen ; particular determination and direction are therefore inseparable from every vo- lition, and the cause which really gives it a being, must necessarily give it character, and particular direction and determination. A SELF-DETERMINING WILL. 185 Selection is the attribute of the cause, and an- swers to particular determination and direction in the effect. As a phenomenon or effect cannot come to exist without a particular determination, so a cause cannot give existence to a phenomenon, or effect, without selection. There must neces- sarily be one object selected rather than another. Thus, if fire be thrown among various substances, it selects the combustibles, and produces pheno- mena accordingly. It selects and gives particu- lar determination. We cannot conceive of cause without selection, nor of effect without a particu- lar determination. But in what lies the selection ? In the nature of the cause in correlation with cer- tain objects. Fire is in correlation with certain objects, and consequently exhibits phenomena only with respect to them. In chemistry, under the title of affinities, we have wonderful exhibitions of selection and particular determination. Now mo- tive, according to Edwards, lies in the correlation of the nature of the will, or desire, with certain objects ; and volition is the effect of this correla- tion. The selection made by will, arising from its nature, is, on the principle of Edwards, like the selection made by any other cause : and the par- ticular determination or direction of the volition, in consequence of this, is like that which appears 16* 18G EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST in every other effect. In the case of will, what- ever effect is produced, is produced of necessity, by ;i pro-constitution and disposition of will and objects, just as in the case of any other cause. Prom this it appears sufficiently evident, that on Edwards's principles there is no such difference between volition and any other effect, as to shield his reasonings respecting a self-determining will, against the consequences above deduced from them. The distinction of final and efficient causes does not lie in his system. The motive is that which produces the sense of the most agreeable, and produces it necessarily, and often in opposi- tion to reason and conscience ; and this sense of the most agreeable is choice or volition. It be- longs to the opposite system to make this distinc- tion in all its clearness and force — where the efficient will is distinguished, both from the per- suasions and allurements of passion and desire, and from the laws of reason and conscience. Thus far my argument against Edwards's as- sumption,— that, to make the will the cause of its own volitions, is to make it cause its volitions by an act of volition, — has been indirect. If this indirect argument has been fairly and legitimately conducted, few probably will be disposed to deny that the assumption is overthrown by its conse- A. SELF-DETEKMINI3C WILL. 187 quences. In addition to the above, however, on a subject so important, a direct argument will not be deemed superfluous. Self-determining will means simply a will caus- ing its own volitions ; and consequently, particu- larly determining and directing them. Will, in relation to volition, is just what any cause is in relation to its effect. Will causing volitions, causes them just as any cause causes its effects. There is no intervention of anything between the cause and effect ; between will and volition. A cause producing its phenomena by phenomena, is a manifest absurdity. In making the will a self- determiner, we do not imply this absurdity. Ed- wards assumes that we do, and he assumes it as if it were unquestionable. The will, he first remarks, determines all our external actions by volitions, as the motions of the hands and feet. He next affirms, generally, that all which the will determines, it determines in this way ; and then concludes, that if it determines its own volitions, they must come under the general law, and be determined by volitions. The first position is admitted. The second, in- volving the last, he does not prove, and I deny that it is unquestionable. In the first place, it cannot legitimately be taken 188 EXAMINATION OK AKUUMKNTS AGAINST as following from the first. The relation of will to the sequents of its volitions, is not necessarily the same as its relation to its volitions. The se- quents of volitions are changes or modifications, in external nature, or in parts of the being external to the will ; but the volitions are modifications of the will itself. Now if the modification of exter- nal nature by the will can be effected only by that modification of itself called volition, how does it appear that this modification of itself, if effected by itself, must be effected by a previous modifica- tion of itself? We learn from experience, that volitions have sequents in external nature, or in parts of our being external to will ; but this expe- rience teaches us nothing respecting the produc- tion of volitions. The acts of the will are voli- tions, and all the acts of wills are volitions ; but this means nothing more than that all the acts of the will are acts of the will, for volition means only this — an act of the will. But has not the act of the will a cause? Yes, you have assigned the cause, in the very language just employed. It is the act of the will — the will is the cause. But how does the will cause its own acts ? I do not know, nor do I know how any cause exerts itself, in the production of its appropriate pheno- mena; I know merely the facts. The connexion A SELF-DETERMINING WILL. 189 between volition and its sequents, is just as won- derful and inexplicable, as the connexion between will and its volitions. How does volition raise the arm or move the foot ? How does fire burn, or the sun raise the tides ? And how does will cause volitions ? I know not ; but if I know that such are the facts, it is enough. Volitions must have a cause ; but, says Edwards, will cannot be the cause, since this would lead to the absurdity of causing volitions by volitions. But we cannot perceive that it leads to any such ab- surdity. It is not necessary for us to explain how a cause acts. If the will produce effects in external na- ture by its acts, it is impossible to connect wTith this as a sequence, established either by experi- ence or logic, that in being received as the cause of its own acts, it becomes such only by willing its own acts. It is clearly an assumption unsupport- ed, and incapable of being supported. Besides, in denying will to be the cause of its own acts, and in supplying another cause, namely, the motive, Edwards does not escape the very difficulty which he creates ; for I have already shown, that the same difficulty appertains to motive, and to every possible cause. Every cause produces effects by exertion or acting ; but what is the cause of its 190 EXAMINATION OF AKCI'.Mi:NTS AGAINST acting ? To suppose it the cause of its own acts, involves all the absurdities which Edwards attri- butes to Belf-de termination. But, Jn the second place! — let us look at the con- nexion of cause and phenomena a little more parti- cularly. What is cause ! It is that which is the ground of the possible, and actual existence of phenomena. How is cause known? By the phe- nomena. Is cause visible ? No : whatever is seen is phenomenal. We observe phenomena, and by the law of our intelligence we assign them to cause. But how do we conceive of cause as producing phenomena ? By a nisus, an effort, or energy. Is this nisus itsell a phenomenon? It is when it is observed, Is it always observed ? It is not. The nisus of gravitation we do not ob- serve ; we observe merely the facts of gravita- tion. The nisus of heat to consume we do not observe ; we observe merely the facts of combus- tion. Where then do we observe this nisus? Only in will. Really, volition is the nisus or ef- fort of that cause which we call will. I do not wish to anticipate subsequent investigations, but I am constrained here to ask every one to ex- amine his consciousness in relation to this point. When 1 wish to do anything I make an effort — a nisus to do it ; I make an effort to raise my arm, and I raise it. This effort is simply the vo- A SELF-DETEUMININO WILL. 191 lition. I make an effort to lift a weight with my hand, — this effort is simply the volition to lift it, — and immediately antecedent to this effort, I recog- nise only my will, or really only myself. This effort — this nisus — this volition — whatever we call it, — is in the will itself, and it becomes a phenomenon to us, because we are causes that know ourselves. Every ?iisus, or effort, or voli- tion, which we may make, is in our consciousness : causes, which are not self-conscious, of course do not reveal this nisus to themselves, and they can- not reveal it to us because it is in the very bosom of the cause itself. What we observe in relation to all^ causes — not ourselves, whether they be self-conscious or not, is not the nisus, but the se- quents of the nisus. Thus in men we do not ob- serve the volition or nisus in their wills, but the phenomena which form the sequents of the nisus. And in physical causes, we do not observe the nisus of these causes, but only the phenomena which form the sequents of this nisus. But when each one comes to himself, it is all different. He penetrates himself — knows himself. He is him- self the cause — he, himself, makes the nisus, and is conscious of it ; and this nisus to him becomes an effect — a phenomenon, the first phenomenon by which he reveals himself, but a phenomenon 193 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST by which lie reveals himself only to himself. It is by the sequents of this nisus, — the effects pro- duced in the external visible world, — that he re- veals himself to others. Sometimes the nisus or volition expends itself in the will, and gives no external phenomena. I may make an effort to raise my arm, but my arm may be bound or paralyzed, and consequently the effort is in vain, and is not known without. How energetic are the efforts made by the will during a fit of the night-mare ! we struggle to resist some dreadful force ; we strive to run away from dan- ger — but all in vain. It is possible for me to make an effort to re- move a mountain : I may place my hand against its side, and tug, and strive : the nisus or voli- tion is the most energetic that I can make, but, save the straining of my muscles, no external expression of the energy of my will is given ; I am resisted by a greater power than myself. The most original movement of every cause is, then, this nisus in the bosom of the cause itself, and in man, as a cause, the most original move- ment is this nisus likewise, which in him we call volition. To deny such a Jiisus would be to deny the activity, efficiency, and energy of cause. This nisus, by its very conception and definition, ad- A SELF-DETERMINING WILL. 193 admits of no antecedent, phenomenon, or move- ment : it is in the substance of the cause ; its first going forth to effects. A first movement or nisus of cause is just as necessary a conception as first cause itself. There is no conception to oppose to this, but that of every cause having its first movement determined by some other cause out of itself — a conception which runs back in endless retrogression without arriving at a first cause, and is, indeed, the annihilation of all cause. The assumption of Edwards, therefore, that if will determine its own volitions, it must deter- mine them by an act of volition, is unsupported alike by the facts of consciousness and a sound logic, — while all the absurdities of an infinite se- ries of causation of acts really fasten upon his own theory, and destroy it by the very weapons with which it assails the opposite system. In the third place, — Edwards virtually allows the self-determining power of will. Will he defines as the desire, the affections, or the sensibility. There is no personal activity out of the affections or sensitivity. Volition is as the most agreeable, and is itself the sense of the most agreeable. But what is the cause of volition ? He affirms that it cannot be will, assuming that to make will the cause of its own volitions, in- 17 194 EXAMINATION OF AUGVMKNTS AGAINST volvcs the absurdity of willing volitions or choos- iii" choices ; but at the same lime he affirms the cause to be the state of the affections or will, in correlation with the nature and circumstances of objects. .But all natural causes are in correlation with certain objects, — as, for example, heat is in correlation with combustibles ; that is, these nat- ural causes act only under the condition of meet- ing with objects so constituted as to be suscepti- ble of being acted upon by them. So, likewise, according to Edwards's representation, we may- say that the cause of volition is the nature and state of the affections or the will, acting under the condition of objects correlated to it. The sense of the most agreeable or choice cannot indeed be awakened, unless there be an object presented which shall appear the most agreeable ; but then its appearing most agreeable, and its awakening the sense of the most agreeable, depends not only upon " what appears in the object viewed, but also in the manner of the view, and the state and circumstances of the mind that views." (p. 22.) Now " the state and circumstances of the mind that viewrs, and the manner of its view," is simply the mind acting from its inherent nature and un- der its proper conditions, and is a representation which answers to every natural cause with which K SELF-DETERMINING WILL. 105 we are acquainted : the state of the mind, there- fore, implying of course its inherent nature, may with as much propriety be taken as the cause of volition, on Edwards's own principles, as the na- ture and state of heat may be taken as the cause of combustion : but by " the state of mind," Ed- wards means, evidently, the state of the will or the affections. It follows, therefore, that he makes the state of the will or the affections the cause of volition ; but as the state of the will or the affec- tions means nothing more in reference to will than the state of any other cause means in reference to that cause, — and as the state of a cause, imply- ing of course its inherent nature or constitution, means nothing more than its character and quali- ties considered as a cause, — therefore he virtu- ally and really makes will the cause of its own vo- litions, as much as any natural cause is the cause of its invariable scquents. Edwards, in contemplating and urging the ab- surdity of determining a volition by a volition, overlooked that, according to our most common and necessary conceptions of cause, the first movement or action of cause must be determined by the cause itself, and that to deny this, is in fact to deny cause. If cause have not within itself a nisus to produce phenomena, then wherein is it a 19G EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST cause ? He overlooked, too, that in assigning as the cause or motive of volition, the state of the will, he really gave the will a self-determining power, and granted the very point he laboured to overthrow . The point in dispute, therefore, between us and Edwards, is not, after all, the self-determining power of the will. If will be a cause, it will be self-determining ; for all cause is self-determining, or, in other words, is in its inherent nature active, and the ground of phenomena. But the real point in dispute is this : " Is the will necessarily determined, or not? • The inherent nature of cause may be so consti- tuted and fixed, that the nisus by which it deter- mines itself to produce phenomena,shalltake place according to invariable and necessary laws. This we believe to be true with respect to all physical causes. Heat, electricity, galvanism, magnetism, gravitation, mechanical forces in general, and the powers at work in chemical affinities, produce their phenomena according to fixed, and, with respect to the powers themselves, necessary laws. We do not conceive it possible for these powers to produce any other phenomena, under given cir- cumstances, than those which they actually pro- duce. When a burning coal is thrown into a A CONTINGENT WILL. 197 mass of dry gunpowder, an explosion must take place. Now, is it true likewise that the cause which we call will, must, under given circumstances, ne- cessarily produce such and such phenomena? Must its nisus, its self-determining energy, or its volition, follow a uniform and inevitable law? Edwards answers yes. Will is but the sensitivity, and the inherent nature of the will is fixed, so that its sense of the most agreeable, which is its most original nisus or its volition, follows certain neces- sary laws, — necessary in relation to itself. If we know the state of any particular will, and its cor- relation to every variety of object, we may know, with the utmost certainty, what its volition will be at a given time, and under given circumstance?. Moral necessity and physical necessity differ only in the terms, — not in the nature of the connexion between the terms. Volition is as necessary as any physical phenomenon. Now, if the will and the affections or sensitivity are one, then, as a mere psychological fact, we must grant that volition is necessary ; for nothing can be plainer than that the desires and affections necessarily follow the correlation of the sensitivity and its objects. But if we can distinguish in the consciousness, the will as a personal activity, from 17* 198 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST the sensitivity, — if we can distinguish volition from the strongest desire <>r the sense <>f the most agree- able,— then it will not follow, because the one is necessary, the other is necessary likewise, unless a necessary connexion between the two be also an observed fact of consciousness. This will be inquired into in another part of our undertaking. What we are now mainly concerned with, is Ed- wards's argument against the conception of a will not necessarily determined. This he calls a con- tingent determination of will. We adopt the word contingent ; it is important in marking a distinction. Edwards, in his argument against a contingent determination, mistakes and begs the question un- der discussion. 1. He mistakes the question. Contingency is treated of throughout as if identical with chance or no cause. " Any thing is said to be contingent, or to come to pass by chance or accident, in the original meaning of such words, when its connex- ion with its causes or antecedents, according to the established course of things, is not discerned ; and so is what we have no means of foreseeing. And especially is any thing said to be contingent or accidental, with regard to us, when it comes to pass without our foreknowledge, and beside vv or the nr 'UFIVERS A CONTINGENT WILL. \, C 199 our design and scope. But the word contingent is used abundantly in a very different sense ; not for that whose connexion with the series of things we cannot discern so as to foresee the event, but for something which has absolutely no previous ground or reason with which its existence has any fixed and certain connexion." (p. 31.) Thus, according to Edwards, not only is con- tingent used in the same sense as chance and ac- cident, in the ordinary and familiar acceptation of these words, but it is also gravely employed to represent certain phenomena, as without any ground, or reason, or cause of their existence ; and it is under this last point of view that he op- poses it as applied to the determination of the will. In part 2, sec. 3, he elaborately discusses the question — " whether any event whatsoever, and volition in particular, can come to pass with- out a cause of its existence ;" and in sec. 4, — - whether volition can arise without a cause, through the activity of the nature of the soul." If, in calling volitions contingent, — if, in repre- senting the determination of the will as contin- gent, we intended to represent a class of phe- nomena as existing without " any previous ground or reason with which their existence has a fixed and certain connexion," — as existing without any n(l r\ AMIN.YTION OF AUGUMBNTB AGAINST cause whatever, and then fore as existing by chancc, or as really self-existent, and therefore not demanding any previous ground for their ex- istence,— it seems to me that no elaborate argu- ment would be required to expose the absurdity of our position. That " every phenomenon must have a cause," is unquestionably one of those primitive truths which neither require nor admit of a demonstration, because they precede all de- monstration, and must be assumed as the basis of all demonstration. By a contingent will, I do not mean a will which is not a cause. By contingent volitions, I do not mean volitions which exist without a cause. By a contingent will, I mean a will which is not a necessitated will, but what I conceive only and truly to be a free will. By contingent volitions, I mean volitions belonging to a contingent or free will. I do not oppose contingency to cause, but to necessity. Let it be supposed that we have a clear idea of necessity, then whatever is not ne- cessary I call contingent. Now an argument against contingency of will on the assumption that we intend, under this title, to represent volitions as existing without a cause, is irrelevant, since we mean no such thing. But an argument attempting to prove that con- A CONTINGENT WILL. 201 tingcncy is identical with chance, or no cause, is a fair argument ; but then it must be remembered that such an argument really goes to prove that nothing but necessity is possible, — for we mean by contingency that which is opposed to ne- cessity. The argument must therefore turn upon these two points : First, is contingency a possible con- ception, or is it in itself contradictory and absurd ? This is the main question ; for if it be decided that contingency is a contradictory and absurd con- ception, then we are shut up to a universal and an absolute necessity, and no place remains for inquiry respecting a contingent will. But if it be decided to be a possible and rational conception, then the second point will be, to determine wheth- er the will be contingent or necessary. The first point is the only one which I shall dis- cuss in this place. The second properly belongs to the psychological investigations which are to follow. But I proceed to remark, 2. that Ed- wards, in his argument against a contingent will, really begs the question in dispute. In the first place, he represents the will as necessarily deter- mined. This is brought out in a direct and posi- tive argument contained in the first part of his treatise. Here necessity is made universal and 202 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST absolute. Then, in the second place, when he comes particularly to discuss contingency, he as- sumes that it means no cause, and that necessity is inseparable from the idea of cause. Now this is plainly a begging of the question, as well as a mistaking of it ; for when we are inquiring wheth- er there be any thing contingent, that is, any thing opposed to necessity, he begins his argument by affirming all cause to be necessary, and contin- gency as implying no cause. If all cause be ne- cessary, and contingency imply no cause, there is no occasion for inquiry after contingency ; for it is already settled that there can be no contin- gency. The very points we are after, as we have seen, are these two : whether contingency be pos- sible ; and whether there be any cause, for ex- ample, will, which is contingent. If Edwards has both mistaken and begged the question respecting a contingent will, as I think clearly appears, then of course he has logically determined nothing in relation to it. But whether this be so or not, we may proceed now to inquire whether contingency be a possible and rational conception, or whether it be contra- dictory and absurd. Necessity and contingency are then two ideas opposed to each other. They at least cannot A CONTINGENT WILL. 203 coexist in relation to the same subject. That which is necessary cannot be contingent at the same time, and vice versa. Whether contingency is a possible conception and has place in relation to any subject, remains to be determined. Let us seek a definition of these opposing ideas : we will begin with necessity, because that this idea is rational and admits of actual application is not questioned. The only point in question respecting it, is, whether it be universal, embra- cing all beings, causes, and events. What is necessity ? Edwards defines necessity under two points of view : — 1. Viewed in relation to will. 2. Viewed irrespective of will. The first, supposes that opposition of will is possible, but insufficient ; — for example : it is pos- sible for me to place myself in opposition to a rushing torrent, but my opposition is insufficient, and the progress of the torrent relatively to me is necessary. The second does not take will into considera- tion at all, and applies to subjects where opposi- tion of will is not supposable ; for example, log- ical necessity, a is b, and c is a, therefore c is b : mathematical necessity, 2 x 2=4. The centre of a circle is a point equally distant from 204 EXAMINATION OP AUUUMKNTS AGAINST every point in the circumference : metaphysical necessity, the existence of a first cause, of time, of space. Edwards comprehends this second kind of necessity under the general designation of meta- physical or philosophical. This second kind of necessity undoubtedly is absolute. It is impossi- ble to conceive of these subjects differently from what they are. We cannot conceive of no space ; no time ; or that 2X2 = 5, and so of the rest. Necessity under both points of view he distin- guishes into particular and general. Relative necessity, as particular, is a necessity relative to individual will ; as general, relative to all will. Metaphysical necessity, as particular, is a neces- sity irrespective of individual will ; as general, irrespective of all will. Relative necessity is relative to the will in the connexion between volition and its sequents. When a volition of individual will takes place, without the sequent aimed at, because a greater force is opposed to it, then the sequent of this greater force is necessary with a particular rela- tive necessity. When the greater force is great- er than all supposable will, then its sequents take place by a general relative necessity. It is plain however, that under all supposable will, the will A CONTINGENT WILL. 205 of God cannot be included, as there can be no greater force than a divine volition. Metaphysical necessity, when particular, ex- cludes the opposition of individual will. Under this Edwards brings the connexion of motive and volition. The opposition of will, he contends, is excluded from this connexion, because will can act only by volition, and motive is the cause of volition. Volition is necessary by a particular metaphysical necessity, because the will of the in- dividual cannot be opposed to it ; but not with a general metaphysical necessity, because other wills may be opposed to it. Metaphysical necessity, when general, excludes the opposition of all will — even of infinite will. That 2X2= 4 — that the centre of a circle is a point equally distant from every point in the cir- cumference— the existence of time and space — are all true and real, independently of all will. Will hath not constituted them, nor can will destroy them. It would imply a contradiction to suppose them different from what they are. According to Edwards, too, the divine volitions are necessary with a general metaphysical necessity, because, as these volitions are caused by motives, and infinite will, as well as finite will, must act by volitions, the opposition of infinite will itself is excluded in the production of infinite volitions. 18 200 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST Now what is the simple idea of necessity con- tained in these two points of view, with their two-fold distinction? Necessity is that which is ■nut which cannot possibly not />e, or be otherwise than it is, 1. An event necessary by a relative particular necessity, is an event which is and cannot possi- bly not be or be otherwise by the opposition of an individual will. 2. An event necessary by a relative general necessity, is an event which cannot possibly not be, or be otherwise by the opposition of all finite will. In these cases, opposition of will of course is supposable. 3. An event is necessary by a metaphysical particular necessity, when it is, and admits of no possible opposition from the individual will. 4. An event is necessary by a metaphysical general necessity, when it is, and cannot possibly admit of opposition even from infinite will. All this, however, in the last analysis on Ed- wards's system, becomes absolute necessity. The infinite will is necessarily determined by a meta- physical general necessity. All events are neces- sarily determined by the infinite will. Hence, all events are necessarily determined by a metaphys- ical general necessity. Particular and relative necessity are merely the absolute and general ne- A CONTINGENT WILL. 207 cessity viewed in the particular individual and relation: — the terms characterize only the man- ner of our view. The opposition of the particular will being predetermined by the infinite will, which comprehends all, is to the precise limit of its force absolutely necessary ; and the opposite force which overcomes the opposition of the particular will, produces its phenomena necessarily not only in reference to the particular will, but also in refer- ence to the infinite will which necessarily prede- termines it. Having thus settled the definition of necessity, and that too, on Edwards's own grounds, we are next to inquire, what is the opposite idea of con- tingency, and whether it has place as a rational idea ? Necessity is that which is, and which cannot possibly not be, or be otherwise than it is. Con- tingency then, as the opposite idea, must be tJiat which is, or may be, and which possibly might not be, or might be otherwise than it is. Now, contingency cannot have place with respect to anything which is independent of will ; — time and space; — mathematical and metaphysical truths, for example, that all right angles are equal, thai every phenomenon supposes a cause, cannot be contingent, for they are seen to be real and true '-ir ABOUMSHTfl AGAINST them. Is this a possible and rational conception ' It is indeed the conception of a cause different from all other causes ; and on this conception there arc but two kinds of causes. The physi- cal, which arc necessarily determined by the cor- relation of their nature with certain objects, and will, which is a pure activity not thus determin- ed, and therefore not necessitated, but contingent. Now I may take this as a rational conception, unless its palpable absurdity can be pointed out, cr it can be proved to involve some contradic- tion. Docs the objector allege, as a palpable absurd- ity, that there is, after all, nothing to account for the particular determination ? I answer that the particular determination is accounted for in the very quality or attribute of the cause. In the case of a physical cause, the particular determination is accounted for in the quality of the cause, which quality is to be necessarily correlated to the ob- ject. In the case of will, the particular determi- nation is accounted for in the quality of the cause, which quality is to have the power to make the particular determination without being necessarily correlated to the object. A physical cause is a cause fixed, determined, and necessitated. The will is a cause contingent and free. A physical A CONTINGKNT WILL. 223 cause is a cause instrumental of a first cause : — the will is first cause itself. The infinite will is the first cause inhabiting eternity, filling immensity, and unlimited in its energy. The human will is first cause appearing in time, confined to place, and finite in its energy ; but it is the same in kind, because made in the likeness of the infinite will ; as first cause it is self-moved, it makes its nisus of itself, and of itself it forbears to make it ; and within the sphere of its activity, and in relation to its objects, it has the power of selecting by a mere arbitrary act, any particular object. It is a cause, all whose acts, as well as any particular act, con- sidered as phenomena demanding a cause, are accounted for in itself alone. This does not make the created will independent of the uncreated. The very fact of its being a created will, settles its dependence. The power which created it, has likewise limited it, and could annihilate it. The power which created it, has ordained and fixed the instrumentalities by which volitions become productive of effects. The man may make the volition or nisiiS, to remove a mountain, but his arm fails to carry out the nisus. His volitions are produced freely of himself; they are unre- strained within the capacity of will given him, but he meets on every side those physical causes 834 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST which arc mightier than himself, and which, in- strumental of the divine will, make the created will aware of its feebleness and dependence. But although the will is au activity or cause thus contingent, arbitrary, free, and indifferent, it is an activity or cause united with sensitivity and rea- son ; and forming the unity of the soul. Will, rea- son, and, the sensitivity or the affections, consti- tute mind, or spirit, or soul. Although the will is arbitrary and contingent, yet it does not follow that it must act without regard to reason or feeling. I have yet to make my appeal to consciousness ; I am now only giving a scheme of psychology in order to prove the possibility of a contingent will, that we have nothing else to oppose to an abso- lute and universal necessity. According to this scheme, wre take the will as the executive of the soul or the doer. It is a doer having life and power in itself, not necessarily de- termined in any of its acts, but a power to do or not to do. Reason we take as the lawgiver. It is the " source and substance " of pure, immutable, eternal, and necessary truth. This teaches and commands the executive will what ought to be done. The sensitivity or the affections, or the desire, is the seat of enjoyment : it is the capacity A CONTINGENT WILL. 225 of pleasure and pain. Objects, in general, hold to the sensitivity the relation of the agreeable or the disagreeable, are in correlation with it ; and, according to the degree of this correlation, are the emotions and passions awakened. Next let the will be taken as the chief characte- ristic of personality, or more strictly, as the per- sonality itself. By the personality. I mean the me, or myself. The personality — the me — the will, a self-moving cause, directs itself by an act of attention to the reason, and receives the laws of its action. The perception of these laws is attended with the conviction of their rectitude and imperative obligation ; at the same time, there is the consciousness of power to obey or to disobey them. Again, let the will be supposed to direct itself in an act of attention to the pleasurable emotions connected with the presence of certain objects ; and the painful emotions connected with the presence of other objects ; and then the desire of pleasure, and the wish to avoid pain, become rules of action. There is here again the consciousness of power to resist or to comply with the solicita- tions of desire. The will may direct itself to those objects which yield pleasure, or may reject them, and direct itself towards those objects which yield only pain and disgust. 22G EXAMINATION OF AKOIMKNTS AC. VINST We may suppose again two conditions of the reason and sensitivity relatively to each other: a condition of agreement, and a condition of disa- greement. If the affections incline to those ob- jects which the reason approves, then we have the first condition. If the affections are repelled in dislike by those objects which reason approves, then we have the second condition. On the first condition, the will, in obeying reason, gratifies the sensitivity, and vice versa. On the second, in obeying the reason, it resists the sensitivity, and vice versa. Now if the will were always governed by the highest reason, without the possibility of resist- ance, it would be a necessitated will ; and if it were always governed by the strongest desire, without the possibility of resistance, it would be a necessitated will ; as much so as in the system of Edwards, where the strongest desire is identi- fied with volition. The only escape from necessity, therefore, is in the conception of a will as above defined — a conscious, self-moving power, which may obey reason in opposition to passion, or passion in op- position to reason, or obey both in their harmoni- ous union ; and lastly, which may act in the indif- ference of all, that is, act without reference either A CONTINGENT WILL. 227 to reason or passion. Now when the will obeys the laws of the reason, shall it be asked, what is the cause of the act of obedience ? The will is the cause of its own act ; a cause per se, a cause self-conscious and self-moving ; it obeys the rea- son by its own nisus. When the will obeys the strongest desire, shall we ask, what is the cause of the act of obedience ? Here again, the will is the cause of its own act. Are we called upon to ascend higher? We shall at last come to such a self-moving and contingent power, or we must re- sign all to an absolute necessity. Suppose, that when the will obeys the reason, we attempt to ex- plain it by saying, that obedience to the reason awakens the strongest desire, or the sense of the most agreeable ; we may then ask, why the will obeys the strongest desire ? and then we may at- tempt to explain this again by saying, that to obey the strongest desire seems most reasonable. We may evidently, with as much propriety, account for obedience to passion, by referring to reason ; as account for obedience to reason, by referring to passion. If the act of the will which goes in the direction of the reason, finds its cause in the sensitivity ; then the act of the will which goes in the direction of the sensitivity, may find its cause in the reason. But this is only moving in a circle, 228 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST and is no advance whatever. Why does the will obey the reason ? because it is must agreeable : but why does the will obe) because it is most agreeable '. because to obey the most agreeable ins most reasonable. Acts of the will may be conceived of as ana- logous to intuitive or first truths. First truths require no demonstration ; they admit of none ; they form the basis of all demonstration. Acts of the will are first movements of primary causes, and as such neither require nor admit of antecedent causes, to explain their action. Will is the source and basis of all other cause. It explains all other cause, but in itself admits of no explanation. It presents the primary and all-comprehending fact of power. In God, will is infinite, primary cause, and uncreated : in man, it is finite, primary cause, constituted by God's creative act, but not necessitated, for if necessi- tated it would not be will, it would not be power after the likeness of the divine power ; it would be mere physical or secondary cause, and com- prehended in the chain of natural antecedents and sequents. God's will explains creation as an existent fact; mairs will explains all his volitions. When we proceed to inquire after the characteristics of A CONTINGENT WILL. 229 creation, we bring in the idea of infinite wisdom and goodness. But when we inquire why God's will obeyed infinite wisdom and goodness, we must either represent his will as necessitated by infinite wisdom and goodness, and take with this all the consequences of an absolute necessity; or we must be content to stop short, with will itself as a first cause, not necessary, but contingent, which, explaining all effects, neither requires nor admits of any explanation itself. When we proceed to inquire after the charac- teristics of human volition, we bring in the idea of right and wrong ; we look at the relations of the reason and the sensitivity. But when we inquire xrlnj the will now obeys reason, and now passjon ; and why this passion, or that passion ; we must either represent the will as necessitated, and take all the consequences of a necessitated will, or we must stop short here likewise, with the will itself as a first cause, not necessary, but contingent', which, in explaining its own volitions, neither re- quires nor admits of any explanation itself, other than as a finite and dependent will it requires to be referred to the infinite will in order to account for the fact of its existence. Edwards, while he burdens the question of the will's determination with monstrous consequen- 20 230 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST ccs, relieves it of do one difficulty. He lays down, indeed, a uniform law of determination ; but there is a last inquiry which he doea not presume to an- swer. The determination of the will, or the voli- tion, is always as the most agreeable, and is the sense of the most agreeable. But while the will is granted to be one simple power or capacity, there arise from it an indefinite variety of voli- tions ; and volitions at one time directly opposed to volitions at another time. The question now arises, how this one simple capacity of volition comes to produce such various volitions ? It is said in reply, that whatever may be the volition, it is at the time the sense of the most agreeable : but that it is always the sense of the most agree- able, respects only its relation to the will itself; the volition, intrinsically considered, is at one time right, at another wrong; at one time ra- tional, at another foolish. The volition really va- ries, although, relatively to the will, it always puts on the characteristic of the most agreeable. The question therefore returns, how this simple capa- city determines such a variety of volitions, always however representing them to itself as the most agreeable ? There are three ways of answering this. First, we may suppose the state of the will or sensitivity to remain unchanged, and the dif- A CONTINGENT WILL. 231 ferent volitions to be effected by the different ar- rangements and conditions of the objects relatively to it. Secondly, we may suppose the arrangements and conditions of the objects to remain unchanged, and the different volitions to be effected by changes in the state of the sensitivity, or will, relatively to the objects. Or, thirdly, we may suppose both the state of the will, and the arrangements and conditions of the objects to be subject to changes, singly and mutually, and thus giving rise to the different volitions. But our questionings are not yet at an end. On the first supposition, the ques- tion comes up, how the different arrangements and conditions of the objects are brought about? On the second supposition, how the changes in the state of the sensitivity are effected ? On the third supposition, how the changes in both, singly and mutually, are effected ? If it could be said, that the sensitivity changes itself relatively to the objects, then we should ask again, why the sensi- tivity chooses at one time, as most agreeable to itself, that which is right and rational, and at an- other time, that which is wrong and foolish ? Or, if it could be said, that the objects have the power of changing their own arrangements and condi- tions, then also we must ask, why at one time the objects arrange themselves to make the right and 232 EXAMINATION OF AIUUMENTS AGAINST rational appear most agreeable, and at another time, the wrong and foolish? These last questions are the very questions which Edwards does not presume to answer. The motive by which he accounts for the existence of the volition, is formed of the correlation of the state of the will, and the nature and circumstances of the object. But when the correlation is such as to give the volition in the direction of the right and the rational, in opposition to the wrong and the foolish, — we ask why does the correlation give the volition in this direction. If it be said that the volition in this direction appears most agreeable, the answer is a mere repetition of the question ; for the question amounts simply to this: — why the correlation is such as to make the one agreeable rather than the other ? The voli- tion which is itself only the sense of the most agree- able, cannot be explained by affirming that it is always as the most agreeable. The point to be explained is, why the mind changes its state in relation to the objects ; or why the objects change their relations to the mind, so as to produce this sense of the most agreeable in one direction rather than in another ? The difficulty is precisely of the same nature which is supposed to exist in the case of a contingent will. The will noic goes in A CONTINGENT WILL. 233 the direction of reason, and now in the direction of passion, — but why ? We say, because as will, it has the power of thus varying its movement. The change is accounted for by merely referring to the will. According to Edwards, the correlation of will and its objects, now gives the sense of the most agreeable, or volition, in the direction of the rea- son ; and now in the direction of passion — but why .' — Why does the reason now appear most agreeable, — and now the indulgences of im- pure desire ? I choose this because it is most agreeable, says Edwards, which is equivalent to saying, — I have the sense of the most agreeable in reference to this, because it is most agreeable ; — but how do you know it is the most agreeable ? because I choose it, or have the sense of the most agreeable in reference to it. It is plain, therefore, that on Edwards's system, as well as on that op- posed to it, the particular direction of volition, and the constant changes of volition, must be referred simply to the cause of volition, without giving any other explanation of the different determinations of this cause, except referring them to the nature of the cause itself. It is possible, indeed, to refer the changes in the correlation to some cause which governs the correlation of the will anil its 20* 984 EXAMINATION OF AUGUMKNTS AGAINST objects ; but then t!ic question must arise in rela- tion to this cause, why it determines the correla- tion in one direction at one time, and in another direction at another time ? And this could be answered only by referring it to itself as having the capacity of these various determinations as a power to do or not to do, and a power to determine in a given direction, or in the opposite direction ; or by referring it to still another ante- cedent cause. Now let us suppose this last ante- cedent to be the infinite will : then the question would be, why the infinite will determines the sensitivity, or will of his creatures at one time to wisdom, and at another to folly ? And what an- swer could be given ? Shall it be said that it seems most agreeable to him ? But why docs it seem most agreeable to him ? Is it because the particular determination is the most reasonable, that it seems most agreeable ? But why does he determine always according to the most reason- able ? Is it because to determine according to the most reasonable, seems most agreeable ? Now, inasmuch as according to Edwards, the volition and the sense of the most agreeable are the same ; to say that God wills as he does will, because it is most agreeable to him, is to say that he wills because he wills ; and to sav that he wills as he A CONTINGENT WILL. 235 does will, because it seems most reasonable to him. amounts to the same thing, because he wills according to the most reasonable only because it is the most agreeable. To represent the volitions, or choices, either in the human or divine will, as determined by mo- tives, removes therefore no difficulty which is supposed to pertain to contingent self-determina- tion. Let us compare the two theories particularly, although at the hazard of some repetition. Contingent self-determination represents the will as a cause making its nisus or volitions of itself, and determining their direction of itself — now obeying reason, and now obeying passion. If it be asked why it determines in a particular direction? — if this particular direction in which it determines be that of the reason ? — then it may be said, that it determines in this direction because it is reasonable; — if this particular direction be that of passion, as opposed to reason, then it may be said that it determines in this direction, because it is pleasing. But if it be asked why the will goes in the direction of reason, rather than in that of passion, as opposed to reason ? — we cannot say that it is most reasonable to obey reason and not passion ; because the one is all reason, and the 23G EXAMINATION OF AROUKENTB A.OAIN8T oilier is all passion, and <>f course they cannot be compared under the reasonable ; and no more can they be compared under the pleasing, — when, by the pleasing, we understand, the gratification of desire, as opposed to reason. To obey reason because it is reasonable, is nothing more than the statement of the fact that the will does obey rea- son. To obey desire because it is desirable, is nothing more than the statement of the fact that the will does obey desire. The will goes in one direction rather than in another by an act of self- determination, which neither admits of, nor indeed requires any other explanation than this, that the will has power to do one or the other, and in the exercise of this power, it does one rather than the other. To this stands contrasted the system of Ed- wards ; and what is this system ? That the will is determined by the strongest motive; — and what is the strongest motive ? The greatest apparent good, or the most agreeable : — what constitutes the greatest apparent good, or the most agreeable ? The correlation of will or sensitivity and the ob- ject. But why does the correlation make one object appear more agreeable than another ; or make the same object at one time appear agree- able, at another time disagreeable ? Now this A CONTINGENT WILL. 237 question is equivalent to the question, — why does the will go in the direction of one object rather than of another ; or go in the direction of a given object at one time, and in opposition to it at an- other time ? For the will to determine itself to- ward an object in one system, answers to the will having the sense of the most agreeable towards an object in Edwards's system. If Edwards should attempt to give an answer without going beyond the motive, he could only say that the sensitivity has the power of being affected with the sense of the most agreeable or of the most disagreeable ; and that in the exercise of this pow- er it is affected with the one rather than with the other. He could not say that to obey reason appears more agreeable than to obey passion as opposed to reason, for the obedience of the will on his system, is nothing more than a sense of the most agreeable. Nor could he say it is more reasonable to obey reason, for reason cannot be compared with its opposite, under the idea of itself; and if he could say this, it amounts to no more than this, on his system, that it is most agree- able to obey the reasonable; — that is, the rea- sonable is obeyed only as the most agreeable : but obedience of will being nothing more than the sense of the most agreeable, to say it is obeyed "238 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST because most .agreeable, is merely to say that if awakens the sense of the most agreeable j that is, it is obej - j cd. To refer the motive to the divine determina- tion makes volition necessary to the man, and throws the difficulty in question, if it is to be con- sidered a difficulty, only farther back. If God's will determines in the direction of the reasonable because it is most agreeable, then we ask, why is it the most agreeable ? If the re- ply be, because it is most reasonable, then we are only moving in a circle ; but if the agreea- ble be taken as an ultimate fact, then inasmuch as to will is only to have the sense of the most agreeable, it follows that God has the sense of the most agreeable towards an object only because it is most agreeable to him, or awakens this sense in him; and thus the question why God wills in one direction rather than in another, or what is the cause of his determination, is not answered by Edwards, unless he says with us that the will in itself as a power to do or not to do, or to do one thing, or its opposite, is a sufficient explanation, and the only possible explanation ; — or unless he refers the divine will to an antecedent cause, and this again to another antecedent cause, in an end- less series — and thus introduce the two-fold er- A CONTINGENT WILL. 239 ror of an endless series, and an absolute neces- sity. All possible volitions, according to the scheme of psychology I have above given, must be either in the direction of the reason or of the sensitivity, cr in the indifferency of both. If the volition be in the direction of the reason, it takes the characteristics of rational, good, &c. If in the direction of the sensitivity, it takes its characteristic from the na- ture of the particular desire which it obeys : — it is generous, benevolent, kind, &c. — or it is ma- licious, envious, unkind, vicious, &c. What moves the will to go in the direction of the reason ? Nothing moves it ; it is a cause per se ; it goes in that direction because it has power to go in that direction. What moves the will to go in the di- rection of the sensitivity? Nothing moves it; it is a cause per se ; it goes in that direction be- cause it has power to go in that direction. There are in the intelligence or reason, as uni- ted with the will in the constitution of the mind, necessary convictions of the true, the just, the right. There are in the sensitivity, as united in the same constitution, necessary affections of tiie agreeable and the disagreeable in reference to various objects. The will as the power which by 240 i:\.\MINATION OF ABGUMEHTS AGAINST its nisus j)roduccs changes or phenomena, is con- scious of ability to go in either of these directions, or in opposition to both. Now when it makes its nisus or volition in reference to the true, the just, the good i should we attempt to explain this nisus by saying that the true, the just, the good, atl'eet the sensitivity agreeably, this would only amount to saying that the nisus is made towards the true, not as the true, but only as the agreea- ble ; and then we would introduce the law that the nisus is always made in the direction of the agreeable. But then again we might seek to ex- plain why the nisus is always made in the direc- tion of the agreeable. Is it of an antecedent ne- cessity ? Then wo have an absolute and univer- sal necessity. Is it because to go in the direction of the agreeable seems most rational ? Then it follows that the nisus is made towards the agree- able not as the agreeable, but only as the ration- al ; and then we would introduce the law that the nisus is always made in the direction of the ra- tional. But then again we might seek to explain why this nisus is always made in the direction of the rational. Is it of an antecedent necessity ? Then here likewise we have an absolute and uni- versal necessity. Is it because to go in the di- rection of the rational seems most agreeable ? A CONTINGENT WILL. 241 Then wc are winding back in a circle to our first position. How shall we escape from these difficulties ? Shall wre adopt the psychology of Edwards, and make the will and the sensitivity one ? Then as the volition is always the strongest affection of the agreeable, if the sensitivity be necessary, voli- tions are necessary, and we are plunged head- long again into an absolute and universal necessity. If the sensitivity be not necessary, then we have shown fully, above, that we have to account for its various determinations just as we are suppos- ed to be called upon to account for the various determinations of the will when considered as a power distinct from the sensitivity: — we are met with the questions, why does the sensitivity rep- resent this object as more agreeable than that object ? — or the same object as agreeable at one time, and disagreeable at another ? Or if these various determinations are resolved into an an- tecedent necessity comprehending them, then we go up to the antecedent cause in which this ne- cessity resides, and question it in like manner. But one thing remains, and that is to consider the will as primary cause, contingent in opposi- tion to being necessitated — a cause having in it- self the power of making these various volitions or 21 242 KWMIN.VTION OF \ K<- 1 MI'.NTS AGAINST ;iis us, and neither asking nor allowing of any ex- planation of its acts, or their particular direction, save its own peculiarity and energy as will. The question respecting the indifferency of will must now be considered. The term indifferency comes up in consequence of considering the will as distinct from the sensitivity. It is not desire or feeling — it is a power indifferent to the agrec- ableness or disagreeableness of objects. It is also a power distinct from the reason ; it is not conviction or belief — it is a power indif- ferent to the true and the right, to the false and the wrong, in the sense that it is not necessarily determined by conviction and belief, by the true and the right, or by the false and the wrong. The conception of will in its utmost simplicity is the conception of pure power, self-moving, and self-conscious — containing within itself the ground and the possibility of creation and of modification. In God it is infinite, eternal, uncreated power ; and every nisus in his will is really creative or modifying, according to its self-directed aim. In man it is constituted, dependent, limited, and ac- countable. Now in direct connexion with power, we have the conception of law or rule, or what power ought to do. This law or rule is revealed in the A CONTINGENT WILL. reason. In man as pure, and we conclude in God likewise, as the archetype of all spirit, there is given a sensitivity or a capacity to be affected agreeably by, and to be drawn towards the ob- jects approved and commanded by the reason. If this sensitivity does not move in harmony with the reason, it is corrupted. Now will is placed in a triunity with these two other powers. We can distinguish but not separate it from them. A will without reason would be a power without eyes, or light. A will without sensitivity would be a power stern and isolated; — just as a reason and sensitivity without will, would be without ef- ficiency, or capacity of giving real manifesta- tions. The completeness and perfection of each, lies in a union with all ; but then each in its proper movements is in some sense independent and free of the others. The convictions, beliefs, or per- ceptions of reason are not made, nor can they be unmade by the energy of the will. Nor has the will any direct command over the sensitivitv. And yet the will can excite and direct both the reason and the sensitivity, by calling up objects and occasions. The sensitivity does not govern the reason, and yet it supplies conditions which are necessary to its manifestations. 244 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AOAINST The reason does not govern the sensitivity, and yet the latter would have no definite perception, and of course its highest sensibilities would lie dormant without the reason. So also the reason and the sensitivity do not determine the acts of the will. The will has ef- ficiency, or creative and modifying power in it- self— self-moved, self-directed. But then without reason and sensitivity, the will would be without objects, without designs, without rules, — a solita- ry power, conscious of ability to do, but not know- ing what to do. It addition to the above, the will has this high and distinguishing peculiarity. That it alone is free — that it alone is opposed to necessity. Rea- son must perceive, must believe. Sensitivity must feel when its objects are presented ; but will, when the reason has given its light and uttered its commands, — and when the sensitivity has awakened all its passions and emotions, is not compelled to obey. It is as conscious of power not to do, as of power to do. It may be called a power arbitrary and contingent ; but this means only that it is a power which absolutely puts forth its own nisus, and is free. It follows from this, that the will can act irre- spective of both reason and sensitivity, if an ob- A CONTINGENT WILL. 245 ject of action, bearing no relation to reason or sensitivity, be possible. It is plain that an object bearing no such relation, must be very trifling. If a case in illustration could not be called up, it would not argue anything against the indifferency of will ; — it would only prove that all objects of action actually existing, bear some relation to reason and sensitivity. There is a case, how- ever, frequently called up, and much disputed, which deserves some attention, and which it ap- pears to me, offers the illustration required. Let it be required to select one of the squares of the chess-board. In selecting one of the squares, does the will act irrespective of reason and sen- sitivity, or not ? Those who hold that the will is necessarily determined, must make out some con- nexion between the act of selection, and the rea- son and sensitivity. It is affirmed that there is a general motive which determines the whole pro- cess, viz : the aim or desire to illustrate, if possi- ble, the question in dispute. The motive is, to prove that the will can act without a motive. I reply to this, that this is undoubtedly the mo- tive of bringing the chess-board before the eye, and in making all the preparations for a selection ; — but now the last question is, which square shall I select ? The illustration will have the same force 21* 846 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAIN- f whichever square is selected, and there is no motive that can be drawn cither from the reason or the sensitivity for taking one square in prefer- ence to the other: under the absence of all such motives, and affording each time the same at- tempt at illustration, I can vary the selection sixty-four times : in making this selection, there- fore, it appears to me, there is an entire indiffer- ency as to which, particular square is selected ; — there is no command of the reason directing to one square rather than another ; — there is no af- fection of the sensitivity towards one square ra- ther than another, as most agreeable — and yet the will does select one of the squares. It will be proper, in this place, to consider the following argument of Edwards against indiffer- ence of will : "Choice may be immediately after a state of indifference, but cannot co-exist with it: even the very beginning of it is not in a state of indifference. And,, therefore, if this be liberty, no act of the will, in any degree, is ever performed in a state of liberty, or in the time of liberty. Vo- lition and liberty are so far from agreeing to- gether, and being essential one to another, that they are contrary one to another, and one ex- cludes and destroys the other, as much as motion and rest, light and darkness, or life and deaths (p. 73.) A CONTINGENT WILL. 247 Edwards reasons according to his own psycho- logy: If the will and the sensitivity are one, the will cannot well be conceived of as in a state of indiffe- rence, and if it could be conceived of as in a state of indifference before it exercises volition, inasmuch as, according to his system again, volition is the sense of the most agreeable, the moment volition begins, indifference ceases; and hence, if liberty consist in indifference, liberty must cease when volition takes place, just as rest ceases with motion. But according to the system of psychology, which we adopt, and which I shall verify here- after, the will is not one with the sensitivity, but is clearly distinguishable from it: — the sen- sitivity is the capacity of feeling ; the will is the causality of the soul: — a movement of the sensi- tivity, under the quality of indifference, is self- contradictory; and a movement of the will being a mere nisus of cause, under the quality of any sense and feeling whatever, would be self-contra- dictory likewise; it would be confounding that which we had already distinguished. From Ed- wards's very definition of will it cannot be indiffe- rent ; from our very definition of will it cannot be otherwise than indifferent. When it deter- mines exclusively of both reason and sensitivity, it of course must retain, in the action, the indiffc- 248 i:\VMI\ATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST rencc which it possessed before the action ; but this is no less true when it determines in the di- rection cither of reason or sensitivity. When the determination is in the direction of the reason, there is an exercise of reason in connexion with the act, and all the interest of the reason is wakened up, but the will considered in its entire simplicity, knows only the nisus of power. When the determination is in the direction of the sensi- tivity, there is a play of emotions and passions, but the will again knows only the nisus of power which carries it in this direction. In the unity of the soul these powers are generally found acting together. It may be difficult to distinguish them, and this, in con- nexion with the constantly observed fact of the fixed correlation between physical causes and the masses which they operate upon, may lead to the conclusion that there is a fixed correlation like- wise between the will and its objects, regarding the will as the sensitivity ; or at least, that there is a fixed connexion between the will and the sensi- tivity, so that the former is invariably governed by the latter. We have already shown, that to identify sensitivity and will does not relieve us from the difficulties of a self-determined and con- tingent will, unless we plunge into absolute neces- A CONTINGENT WILL. 240 sity ; and that to make the sensitivity govern the will, is only transferring to the sensitivity the diffi- culties which we suppose, to encompass the will. In our psychological investigations it will appear how clearly distinguishable those powers are, and also how clearly independent and sovereign will is, inasmuch as it does actually determine at one time, in opposition to the most agreeable ; at an- other, in opposition to reason ; and at another, in opposition to both conjoined. In the unity of our being, however, we perceive that will is designed to obey the reason, and as subordinated to rea- son, to move within the delights of the sensitivi- ty; and we know that we are acting unreason- ably and senselessly when we act otherwise ; but yet unreasonably and senselessly do we often act. But when we do obey reason, although we characterize the act from its direction, will does not lose its simplicity and become reason ; and when we do obey the sensitivity, will does not be- come sensitivity — will is still simply cause, and its act the nisus of power: thought, and con- viction, and design, hold their place in the reason alone : emotion and passion their place in the sensitivity alone. 250 EXAMINATION OF AIUJUMJ'.NTS AGAINST ARGUMENT THE DIVINE PRESCIENCE. Edwards's argument against a contingent, self- determining will, drawn from the divine presci- ence, remains to be considered. The argument is introduced as follows : " That the acts of the wills of moral agents are not con- tingent events, in such a sense as to be without all necessity, appears by God's certain foreknow- ledge of such events." (sec. xi. p. 98.) Edwards devotes this section to " the evidence of God's certain foreknowledge of the volitions of moral agents." In the following section, (sec. xii. p. 114,) he proceeds formally with his argument. Before examining this argument, let us look at the consequences of his position. God foresees all volitions ; that he foresees them makes their existence necessary. If their existence were not necessary, he could not fore- see them ; or, to express it still more generally, foreknowledge extends to all events, and fore- knowledge proves the necessary existence of everything to which it extends. It follows from A CONTINGENT WILL. 251 this, that all events exist with an absolute neces- sity,— all physical phenomena, all volitions, and moral phenomena, whether good or evil, and all the divine volitions, for God cannot but foresee his own volitions. In no part of his work, does Edwards lay down more summarily and deci- dedly, the doctrine of absolute and universal ne- cessity. We have already, in part II. of this treatise, deduced the consequences of this doc- trine. If then we are placed upon the alternative of denying the divine prescience of volitions, or of acknowledging the doctrine of necessity, it would practically be most desirable and wisest to take the first part of the alternative. " If it could be demonstrated," remarks Dugald Stewart, (vol. 5. app. sec. viii.) u which in my opinion has not yet been done, that the prescience of the volitions of moral agents is incompatible with the free agen- cy of man, the logical inference would be, not in favour of the scheme of necessity, but that there are some events, the foreknowledge of which im- plies an impossibility. Shall we venture to affirm, that it exceeds the power of God to permit such a train of contingent events to take place, as his own foreknowledge shall not extend to ? Does not such a proposition detract from the omnipo- tence of God, in the same proportion in which it 252 EXAMINATION OF ASOBMBNTfl AGAINST aims to exalt his omniscience !" If the divine foreknowledge goes to establish the doctrine of necessity, there is nothing left that it is worth while to contend for; all mora] and theological interests vanish away. But let us examine the argument of Edwards. This argument consists of three parts ; we shall consider them in order. I. Edwards lays down, that a past event is ne- cessary, "having already made sure of existence;" but divine foreknowledge is such an event, and is therefore necessary. This is equivalent to the axiom, that whatever is, is. He next affirms, that whatever is " indissolubly connected with other things that are necessary, are themselves neces- sary ;" but events infallibly foreknown, have an indissoluble connexion with the foreknowledge. Hence, the volitions infallibly foreknown by God, have an indissoluble connexion with his foreknow- ledge, and are therefore necessary. The force of this reasoning turns upon the con- nexion between foreknowledge and the events foreknown. This connexion is affinned to be " indissoluble ;" that is, the foreknowledge is cer- tainly connected with the event. But this only amounts to the certainty of divine foreknowledge, and proves nothing as to the nature of the exist- A CONTINGENT WILL. 253 ence foreknown. We may certainly know a past or present event, but our knowledge of its exist- ence defines nothing as to the manner in wliich it came to exist. I look out of my window, and I see a man walking in a certain direction : I have a positive knowledge of this event, and it cannot but be that the man is walking ; but then my knowledge of his walking has no influence upon his walking, as cause or necessary antecedent ; and the question whether his walking be contin- gent or necessary is entirely distinct, and relates to the cause of walking. I looked out of my window yesterday, and saw a man walking ; and the knowledge of that event I now retain, so that it cannot but be that the man walked yesterday : but this again leaves the question respecting the mode of existence untouched : — Did the man walk of necessity, or was it a contingent event ? Now let me suppose myself endowed with the faculty of prescience, sufficiently to know the events of to-morrow ; then by this faculty I may see a man walking in the time called to-morrow, just as by the faculty of memory I see a man walking in the time called yesterday. The knowledge, whether it relate to past, present, or future, as a knowledge in relation to myself, is always a present know- ledge ; but the object known may stand in various 22 ^51 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST relations of time, place, &c. Now in relation to the future, no more than in relation to the past and present, does the act of knowledge on my part, explain anything in relation to the mode of \istcnce of the object of knowledge. Ed- wards remarks, (p. 121.) "All certain knowledge, whether it be foreknowledge, or after-knowledge, or concomitant knowledge, proves the thing known now to be necessary, by some means or other ; or proves that it is impossible that it should now be otherwise than true." Edwards does not distinguish between the cer- tainty of the mere fact of existence, and the ne- cessity by which anything comes to exist. Fore- knowledge, after-knowledge, and concomitant knowledge, — that is, the present knowledge of events, future, past, or present, — proves of course the reality of the events ; that they will be, have been, or are : or, more strictly speaking, the knowledge of an event, in any relation of time, is the affirmation of its existence in that relation ; but the knowledge of the event neither proves nor affirms the necessity of its existence. If the know- ledge of the event were the cause of the event, or if it genetically comprehended it in its own exist- ence, then, upon strict logical principles, the neces- sity affirmed of the knowledge would be affirmed of the event likewise. A CONTINGENT WILL. 255 That God foreknows all volitions is granted ; that as he foreknows them, they will be, is also granted ; his foreknowledge of them is the posi- tive affirmation of their reality in time future ; but by supposition, God's foreknowledge is not their cause, and does not generically comprehend them ; they are caused by wills acting in the fu- ture. Hence God's foreseeing how the wills act- ing in the time future, will put forth or determine their volitions, does not take away from these wills the contingency and freedom belonging to them, any more than our witnessing how wills act in the time present, takes away from them their contingency and freedom. God in his pre- science, is the spectator of the future, as really as we are the spectators of the present. Edwards's reasoning is a sort of puzzle, like that employed sometimes for exercising the stu- dent of logic in the detection of fallacies : for ex- ample, a man in a given place, must necessarily either stay in that place, or go away from that place ; therefore, whether he stays or goes away, he acts necessarily. Now it is necessary, in the nature of things, that a man as well as any other body should be in some place, but then it does not follow from this, that his determination, whether to stay or go, is a necessary determina- 856 i EXAMINATION or LBSUMENTfl &GAIN8T tion. His necessary condition as a body, is entire- ly distinct from the question respecting the ne- cessity or contingency of his volitions. And so also in respect of the divine foreknowledge : all human volitions as events occurring in time, arc subject to the necessary condition of being fore- known by that Being, "who inhabiteth eternity/* but this necessary condition of their existence neither proves nor disproves the necessity or the contingency of their particular causation. II. The second proposition in Edwards's argu- ment is, " No future event can be certainly fore- known, whose existence is contingent, and without all necessity." His reasoning in support of this is as follows: 1. "It is impossible for a thing to be certainly known to any intellect without cviderice." 2. A contingent future event is without evidence. 3. Therefore, a contingent future event is not a possible object of knowledge. I dispute both pre- mises: That which is known by evidence or proof is mediate knowledge, — that is, we know it through something which is immediate, standing between the faculty of knowledge and the object of knowledge in question. That which is known intuitively is known without proof, and this is im- vi< (Hate knowledge. In this way all axioms or first truths and all facts of the senses are known. A CONTINGENT WILL. 257 Indeed evidence itself implies immediate know- ledge, for the evidence by which anything is known is itself immediate knowledge. To a Being, there- fore, whose knowledge fills duration, future and past events may be as immediately known as pre- sent events. Indeed, can we conceive of God otherwise than immediately knowing all things? An Infinite and Eternal Intelligence cannot be thought of under relations of time and space, or as arriving at knowledge through media of proof or demonstration. So much for the first premise. The second is equally untenable : " A contingent future event is without evidence," We grant with Edwards that it is not self-evident, implying by that the evidence arising from " the necessity of its nature," as for example, 2x2=4. What is self-evident, as we have already shown, does not require any evidence or proof, but is knowrn im- mediately; and a future contingent event may be self-evident as a fact lying before the divine mind, rer.ching into futurity, although it cannot be self-evident from " the necessity of its nature." But Edwards affirms, that " neither is there any proof or evidence in anything else, or evidence of connexion with something else that is evident ; for this is also contrary to the supposition. It is supposed that there is now nothing existent with 22* 268 EXAMINATION OF AXOVMBNTi AGAINST which the future existence of the contingent event is connected. For such a connexion destroys its contingency and supposes necessity." (p. 116.) He illustrates his meaning by the following exam- ple : "Suppose that five thousand seven hundred and sixty years ago, there was no other being but the Divine Being, — and then this world, or some particular body or spirit, all at once starts out of no- thing into being, and takes on itself a particular na- ture and form — all in absolute contingence, — with- out any concern of God, or any other cause in the matter, — without any manner of ground or reason of its existence, — or any dependence upon, or connexion at all with anything foregoing ; — I say that if this be supposed, there was no evi- dence of that event beforehand. There was no evidence of it to be seen in the thing itself ; for the thing itself as yet was not; and there was no evidence of it to be seen in any thing else; for evidence in something else ; is connexion with some- thing else ; but such connexion is contrary to the supposition." (p. 11G.) The amount of this reasoning is this : That inas- much as a contingent event exists " without any concern of God, or any other cause in the mattt r, — without any manner of ground or reason of its existence, — or any dependence upon or connexion A CONTINGENT WILL. 259 with anything foregoing" — there is really no- thing by which it can be proved beforehand. If Edwards be right in this definition of a contingent event, viz.: that it is an event without any cause or ground of its existence, and " that there is no- thing now existent with which the future cxist- tence of the contingent event is connected," then this reasoning must be allowed to be conclusive. But I do not accede to the definition : Contingence 1 repeat again, is not opposed to cause but to ne- cessity. The world may have sprung into being by absolute contingence more than five thousand years ago, and yet have sprung into being at the com- mand of God himself, and its existence have been foreseen by him from all eternity. The contin- gence expresses only the freedom of the divine will, creating the world by sovereign choice, and at the moment of creation, conscious of power to withhold the creative visas, — creating in the light of his infinite wisdom, but from no compulsion or necessity of motive therein found. Under this view to foresee creation was nothing different from foreseeing his own volitions. The ground on which human volitions can be foreseen, is no less plain and reasonable. In the first place, future contingent volitions are never without a cause and sufficient ground of their ex- 2G0 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST istence, the individual will being always taken as the cause and sufficient ground of the individual volitions. God has therefore provided for the pos- sible existence of volitions other than his own, in the creation and constitution of finite free will. Now, in relation to him, it is not required to con- ceive <>f media by which all the particular voli- tions may be made known or proved to his mind, previous to their actual existence. Whatever he knows, he knows by direct and infinite intuition ; he cannot be dependent upon any media for his knowledge. It is enough, as I have already shown. to assign him prescience, in order to bring within his positive knowledge all future contingent voli- tions. He knows all the variety and the full ex- tent of the possible, and amid the possible he fore- sees the actual ; and he foresees not only that class of the actual which, as decreed and deter- mined by himself, is relatively necessary, but also that class of the actual which is to spring up under the characteristic of contingency. And herein, I would remark, lies the superiority of the divine prescience over human forecast, — in that the former penetrates the contingent as accurately as the necessary. With the latter it is far otherwise. Human forecast or calculation can foresee the motions of the planets, eclipses of A CONTINGENT WILL. 261 the sun and moon, and even the flight of the com- ets, because they are governed by necessary laws ; but the volitions of the human will form the sub- ject of only probable calculations. But if human volitions, as contingent, form the subject of probable calculations, there must be in opposition to Edwards something "that is evi- dent" and "now existent, with which the future existence of the contingent event is connected." There are three kinds of certainty. First, ab- solute certainty. This is the certainty which lies in necessary and eternal principles : e. g. 2 x 2=4 ; the existence of space ; every body must be in space ; every phenomenon must have a cause ; the being of God. Logical certainty, that is, the connexion be- tween premises and conclusion, is likewise abso- lute. Secondly. Physical certainty. This is the certainty which lies in the connexion between physical causes and their phenomena : e. g. grav- itation, heat, chemical affinities in general, me- chanical forces. The reason conceives of these causes as inhe- rently active and uniform ; and hence, wherever a physical cause exists, we expect its proper phe- nomena. 262 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST Now we do not call the operation of these cau- ses absolutely certain, because they depend ulti- mately upon will, — the will of God ; and we can conceive that the same will which ordained them, can change, suspend, or even annihilate them : they have no intrinsic necessity, — still, as causes given in time and space, we conceive of them generally as immutable. If in any case they be changed, or suspended, we are compelled to re- cognise the presence of that will which ordained them. Such change or suspension we call a mir- acle ; that is, a surprise, — a wonder, — because it is unlooked for. When, therefore, we affirm any thing to be physically certain, wre mean that it is certain in the immutability of a cause acting in time and space, and under a necessity relatively to the di- vine will ; but still not absolutely certain, because there is a possibility of a miracle. But when we affirm any thing to be absolutely certain, we mean that it is certain as comprehended in a principle which is unalterable in its very nature, and is therefore independent of will. Thirdly. Moral certainty, is the certainty which lies between the connexion of motive and will. By will we mean a self-conscious and in- telligent cause, or a cause in unity with intelli- A CO.NTLNGENT WILL. 2G3 gence. It is also, in the fullest sense, a cause per se ; that is, it contains within itself proper efficien- cy, and determines its own direction. By motives we mean the reasons according to which the will acts. In general, all activity proceeds according to rules, or laws, or reasons ; for they have the same meaning : but in mere material masses, the rule is not contemplated by the acting force, — it is contemplated only by the intelligence which ordained and conditioned the force. In spirit, on the contrary, the activity which we call will is self-conscious, and is connected with a perception of the reasons, or ends, or motives of action. These motives or ends of action are of two kinds. First, those found in the ideas of the practical reason, which decides what is fit and right. These are reasons of supreme authority. Secondly, those found in the understanding and sensitivity : e. g. the immediately useful and expedient, and the gratification of passion. These are right only when subordinate to the first. Now these reasons and motives are a light to the will, and serve to direct its activities ; and the human conscience, which is but the reason, has drawn up for the will explicit rules, suited to all circumstances and relations, which are called ethics, or the rules. U01 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST These rules the will is not compelled or neces- sitated to obey. In every volition it is conscious of a power to do or not to do ; but yet, as the will forms a unity with the intelligence, we take for granted that it will obey them, unless grounds for an opposite conclusion are apparent. But the only probable ground for a disobedience of these rules lies in a state of sinfulness, — a corruption of the sensitivity, — or a disposition to violate the harmony and fitness of the spiritual constitution. Hence moral certainty can exist only where the harmony of the spiritual being is preserved. For example : God and good angels. In God moral certainty is infinite. His dispositions are infi- nitely pure, and his will freely determines to do right ; it is not compelled or necessitated, for then his infinite meritoriousness would cease. Moral certainty is not absolute, because will being a pow- er to do or not to do, there is always a possibility, although there may be no probability, nay an in- finite improbability, that the will may disobey the laws of the reason. In the case of angels and good men, the moral certainty is such as to be attended with no ap- prehension of a dereliction. With respect to such men as Joseph, Daniel, Paul, Howard, and Wash- ington, we can calculate with a very high and sat- A CONTINGENT WILL. 265 isfactory moral certainty, of the manner in which they will act in any given circumstances involv- ing the influence of motives. We know they will obey truth, justice, and mercy, — that is, the first class of motives ; and the second only so far as they are authorized by the first. If the first class of motives are forsaken, then human conduct can be calculated only according to the influence of the second class. Human character, however, is mixed and vari- ously compounded. "We might make a scale of an indefinite number of degrees, from the highest point of moral excellence to the lowest point of moral degradation, and then our predictions of human conduct would vary with every degree. In any particular case where we are called up- on to reason from the connexion of motives with the will, it is evident we must determine the cha- racter of the individual as accurately as possible, in order to know the probable resultant of the op- posite moral forces which we are likely to find. We have remarked that moral certainty exists only where the harmony of the moral constitution is preserved. Here we know the right will be obeyed. It may be remarked in addition to this, however, that moral certainty may almost be said to exist in the case of the lowest moral degrada- 2:3 206 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST tion, where the right is altogether forsaken. Here the rule is, "whatever is most agreeable;" and the volition is indeed merged into the sense of the most agreeable. But in the intermediate state lies the wide held of probability. What is com- monly called the knowledge of human nature, and esteemed of most importance in the affairs of life is not the knowledge of human nature as it ought to be, but as it is in its vast variety of good and evil. We gain this knowledge from observation and history. What human nature ought to be, we learn from reason. On a subject of so much importance, and where it is so desirable to have clear and definite ideas, the rhetorical ungracefulncss of repetition is of lit- tle moment, when this repetition serves our great end. I shall be pardoned, therefore, in calling the attention of the reader to a point above sug- gested, namely, that the will is in a triunity with reason and sensitivity, and, in the constitution of our being, is designed to derive its rules and in- ducements of action from these. Acts which are in the direction of neither reason nor sensitivity, must be very trifling acts ; and therefore acts of this description, although possible, we may con- clude are very rare. In calculating, then, future acts of will, we may, like the mathematicians, drop A COXTINOIAT WILL. infinitesimal differences, and assume that all acts of the will are in the direction of reason or sensi- tivity, or of both in their harmony. Although the will is conscious of power to do, out of the direc- tion of both reason and sensitivity, still, in the tri- unity in which it exists, it submits itself to the general interests of the being, and consults the authority of conscience, or the enjoyments of pas- sion. Now every individual has acquired for himself habits and a character more or less fixed. He is known to have submitted himself from day to day, and in a great variety of transactions, to the laws of the conscience ; and hence we con- clude that he has formed for himself a fixed pur- pose of doing right. He has exhibited, too, on many occasions, noble, generous, and pure feel- ings ; and hence we conclude that his sensitivity harmonizes with conscience. Or he is known to have violated the laws of the conscience from day to day, and in a great variety of transactions : and hence we conclude that he has formed for himself a fixed purpose of doing wrong. He has exhibit- ed, too, on many occasions, low, selfish, and im- pure feelings ; and hence we conclude that his sensitivity is in collision with conscience. In both cases supposed, and in like manner in all supposable cases, there is plainly a basis on 2GS r.XAMIXATION OF AIM. DM i:\l- \(.\IN-[ which, in any given circumstances, we may fore- see and predict volitions. There is something "that is evident and now existent with which the future existence of the contingent event is con- nected." On the one hand these prediction crt no necessitating influence over the events themselves, for they are entirely disconnected with the causation of the events : and, on the other hand, the events need not be assumed as necessary in or- der to become the objects of probable calculations. If they were necessary, the calculations would no longer be merely probable : — they would, on the contrary, take the precision and certainty of the calculation of eclipses and other phenomena based upon necessary laws. But these calculations can aim only at moral certainty, because they are made according to the generally known and received determinations of will in a unity with reason and sensitivity ; but still a will which is known also to have the power to depart at any moment from the line of determination which it has established for itself. Thus the calculations which we make respecting the conduct of one man in given cir- cumstances, based on his known integrity, and the calculations which we make respecting anoth- er, based on his known dishonesty, may alike dis- appoint us, through the unexpected, though possi- A CONTINGENT WILL. 269 ble dereliction of the first, and the unexpected, though possible reformation of the latter. When we reason from moral effects to moral causes, or from moral causes to moral effects, we cannot regard the operation of causes as positive and uniform under the same law of necessity which appertains to physical causes, because in moral causality the free will is the efficient and last de- terminer. It is indeed true that we reason here with a high degree of probability, with a proba- bility sufficient to regulate wisely and harmoni- ously the affairs of society : but we cannot reason respecting human conduct, as we reason respect- ing the phenomena of the physical world, because it is possible for the human will to disappoint calcula- tions based upon the ordinary influence of motives : e. g. the motive does not hold the same relation to will which fire holds to combustible substance ; the fire must burn ; the will may or may not determine in view of motive. Hence the reason why, in common parlance, probable evidence has received the name of moral evidence : moral evidence be- ing generally probable, all probable evidence is called moral. The will differs from physical causes in being a cause per se, but although a cause per se, it has laws to direct its volitions. It may indeed violate 23* \!;<> EXAMINATION OS ARCFOHBNTfl AGAINST these laws and become a most arbitrary and in- constant law unto itself; but this violation of law and this arbitrary determination do not arise from it necessarily as a cause p< r « . but from an abuse of its liberty. As a cause in unity with the laws of the reason, we expect it to be uniform, and in its harmonious and perfect movements it is uniform. Physical causes are uniform because God has de- termined and fixed them according to laws derived from infinite wisdom. The human will may likewise be uniform by obeying the laws of conscience, but the departures may also be indefinitely numerous and various. To sum up these observations in general state- ments, we remark ; — First: The connexion on which we base pre- dictions of human volitions, is the connexion of will with reason and sensitivity in the unity of the mind or spirit. Secondly : By this connexion, the will is seen to be designed to be regulated by truth and right- eousness, and by feeling subordinated to these. Thirdly : In the purity of the soul, the will is thus regulated. Fourthly : This regulation, however, does not take place by the necessary governance which reason and sensitivity have over will, but by a A CONTINGENT WILL. 271 self-subjection of will to their rules and induce- ments : — this constitutes meritoriousness, — the opposite conduct constitutes ill desert. Fifthly : Our calculations must proceed accord- ing to the degree and fixedness of this self-subjec- tion to reason and right feeling ; or where this does not exist, according to the degree and fixed- ness of the habits of wrong doing, in a self- subjection to certain passions in opposition to reason. Sixthly : Our calculations will be more or less certain according to the extent and accuracy of our observations upon human conduct. Seventhly : Our calculations can never be at- tended with absolute certainty, because the will being contingent, has the power of disappointing calculations made upon the longest observed uni- formity. Eighthly : Our expectations respecting the de- terminations of Deity are attended with the high- est moral certainty. We say moral certainty, be- cause it is certainty not arising from necessity, and in that sense absolute ; but certainty arising from the free choice of an infinitely pure being. Thus, when God is affirmed to be immutable, and when it is affirmed to be impossible for him to lie, it cannot be meant that he has not the power to 272 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST change or to determine contrary to truth ; but that there is an infinite moral certainty arising from the perfection of his nature, that he never will depart from infinite wisdom and rectitude. To assign God any other immutability would be to deprive him of freedom. Ninthly : The divine foresight of human voli- tions need not be supposed to necessitate them, any more than human foresight, inasmuch as fore- seeing them, has no necessary connexion in any case with their causation. Again, if it does not appear essential to the divine foresight of volitions that they should be necessary. We have .seen that future contingent volitions may be calculated with a high degree of certainty even by men ; and now supposing that the divine being must proceed in the same way to calculate them through ?nedia, — the reach and accuracy of his calcula- tions must be in the proportion of his intelligence, and how far short of a certain and perfect know- ledge of all future contingent volitions can infinite intelligence be supposed to fall by such calcula- tions ? Tenthly : But we may not suppose that the infinite mind is compelled to resort to deduction, or to employ media for arriving at any particu- lar knowledge. In the attribute of prescience, IN VI 273 A CONTINGENT WILL. he is really present to all the possible and actual of the future. III. The third and last point of Edwards's ar- gument is as follows : "To suppose the future vo- litions of moral agents, not to be necessary events: or which is the same thing, events which it is not impossible but that they may not come to pass ; and yet to suppose that God certainly foreknows them, and knows all things, is to suppose God's knowledge to be inconsistent with itself. For to say that God certainly and without all conjec- ture, knows that a thing will infallibly be, which at the same time he knows to be so contingent, that it may possibly not be, is to suppose his knowledge inconsistent with itself; or that one thing he knows is utterly inconsistent with an- other thing he knows." (page 117.) The substance of this reasoning is this. That inasmuch as a contingent future event is uncer- tain from its very nature and definition, it cannot be called an object of certain knowledge, to any mind, not even to the divine mind, without a manifest contradiction. " It is the same as to say, he now knows a proposition to be of certain infallible truth, Which he knows to be of contin- gent uncertain truth.'' We have here again an error arising from not '-" 1 i:\.\MINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST making a proper distinction, which I have already pointed out, — the distinction between the cer- tainty of a future volition as a mere fact existent, and the manner in which that fact came to exist. The fact of volition comes to exist contingent- ly ; that is, by a power which in giving it exist- ence, is under no law of necessity, and at the moment of causation, is conscious of ability to withhold the causative nisus. Now all volitions which have already come to exist in this way, have both a certain and contingent existence. It is certain that they have come to exist, for that is a matter of observation ; but their existence is also contingent, because they came to exist, not by ne- cessity as a mathematical conclusion, but by a cause contingent and free, and which, although actually giving existence to these volitions, had the power to withhold them. Certainty and contingency are not opposed, and exclusive of each other in reference to what has already taken place. Are they opposed and exclusive of each other in reference to the future ? In the first place, we may reason on probable grounds. Contingent causes have already pro- duced volitions — hence they may produce voli- tions in the future. They have produced voli- A CONTINGENT WILL. 275 tions in obedience to laws of reason and sensitivi- ty— hence they may do so in the future. They have done this according to a uniformity self-im- posed, and long and habitually observed — hence this uniformity may be continued in the future. A future contingent event may therefore have a high degree of probability, and even a moral certainty. But to a being endowed with prescience, what prevents a positive and infallible knowledge of a future contingent event ? His mind extends to the actual in the future, as easily as to the actual in the past ; but the actual of the future is not only that which comes to pass by his own deter- mination and nisus, and therefore necessarily in its relation to himself as cause, but also that which comes to pass by the nisus of constituted wills, contingent and free, as powers to do or not to do. There is no opposition, as Edwards supposes, be- tween the infallible divine foreknowledge, and the contingency of the event; — the divine fore- knowledge is infallible from its own inherent per- fection ; and of course there can be no doubt but that the event foreseen will come to pass ; but then it is foreseen as an event coming to pass contingently, and not necessarily. The error we have just noted, appears again in 278 EXAMINATION <>r kROUMSNTfl AGAINST the corollary which Edwards immediately deduces from his third position. "From what has been observed," he remarks, "it is evident, that the ab- solute dt cr<" EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST tion between certainty and necessity. Necessity relates to truths and events considered in them- selves. Certainty relates to our apprehension or conviction of them. Hence necessity is not cer- tainty itself, but a ground of certainty. Absolute certainty relates only to truths or to being. First or intuitive truths, and logical conclusions drawn from them, are necessary with an absolute necessity. They do not admit of negative suppo- sitions, and are irrespective of will. The being of God, and time, and space, are necessary with an absolute necessity. Relative necessity relates to logical conclusions and events or phenomena. Logical conclusions are always necessary relatively to the premises, but cannot be absolutely necessary unless the premises from which they are derived, are abso- lutely necessary. All phenomena and events are necessary with only a relative necessity ; for in depending up- on causes, they all ultimately depend upon will. Considered therefore in themselves, they are contingent ; for the will which produced them, either immediately or by second or dependent causes, is not necessitated, but free and contin- gent— and therefore their non-existence is sup- posable. But they are necessary relatively to A CONTINGENT WILL. 281 will. The divine will, which gave birth to cre- ation, is infinite ; when therefore the nisus of this will was made, creation was the necessary result. The Deity is under no necessity of willing ; but when he does will, the effect is said necessarily to follow — meaning by this, that the nisus of the divine will is essential power, and that there is no other power that can prevent its taking effect. Created will is under no necessity of willing ; but when it does will or make its nisus, effects necessarily follow, according to the connexion es- tablished by the will of Deity, between the nisus of created will and surrounding objects. Where a nisus of created will is made, and effects do not follow, it arises from the necessarily greater force of a resisting power, established by Deity likewise ; so that whatever follows the nisus of created will, whether it be a phenomenon without, or the mere experience of a greater resisting force, it follows by a necessity relative to the divine will. When we come to consider will in relation to its own volitions, we have no more necessity, either absolute or relative ; we have contingency and absolute freedom. Now certainty we have affirmed to relate to our knowledge or conviction of truths and events. Necessity is one ground of certainty, both abso- 24* 282 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST lute and relative. We have a certain knowledge or conviction of that which we perceive to be ne- cessary id its own nature, or of which a negative is not supposable ; and this, as based upon an ab- solute necessity, may be called an absolute cer- tainty. The established connexion between causes and effects, is another ground of certainty. Causes are of two kinds ; first causes, or causes per sc, or contingent and free causes, or will ; and second or physical causes, which are necessary with a relative necessity. First causes are of two degrees, the infinite and the finite. Now we are certain, that whatever God wills, will take place. This may likewise be called an absolute certainty, because the connexion between divine volitions and effects is absolutely necessary. It is not supposable that God should will in vain, for that would contradict his admitted infinity. The connexion between the volitions of created will and effects, and the connexion between phys- ical causes and effects, supposing each of course to be in its proper relations and circumstances, is a connexion of relative necessity ; that is, relative to the divine will. Now the certainty of our know- ledge or conviction that an event will take place, A CONTINGENT WILL. 283 depending upon volition or upon a physical cause, is plainly different from the certain knowledge of a necessary truth, or the certain conviction that an event which infinite power wills, will take place. The will which established the connexion, may at any moment suspend or change the connexion. I believe that when I will to move my hand over this paper, it will move, supposing of course the continued healthiness of the limb ; but it is possi- ble for God so to alter the constitution of my being, that my will shall have no more connexion with my hands than it now has with the circula- tion of the blood. I believe also that if I throw this paper into the fire, it will burn; but it is pos- sible for God so to alter the constitution of this paper or of fire, that the paper will not burn ; and yet I have a certain belief that my hand will con- tinue to obey volition, and that paper will burn in the fire. This certainly is not an absolute cer- tainty, but a conditional certainty : events will thus continue to take place on condition the divine will does not change the condition of things. This conditional certainty is likewise called a physical certainty, because the events contemplated in- clude besides the phenomena of consciousness, which are not so commonly noticed, the events or phenomena of the physical world, or nature. 284 i:\AMI.\ATION Off ARGUMENTS AGAINST But we must next look at will itself in rela- tion to its volitions : Here all is contingency and freedom, — here is no necessity. Is there any ground of certain knowledge respecting future volitions? If will as a cause per Be, were isolated and in no relation whatever, there could not be any ground of any knowledge whatever, respecting future volitions. But will is not thus isolated. On the contrary, it forms a unity with the sensi- tivity and the reason. Reason reveals what ought to be done, on the basis of necessary and un- changeable truth. The sensitivity reveals what is most desirable or pleasurable, on the ground of personal experience. Now although it is granted that will can act without deriving a reason or in- ducement of action from the reason and the sen- sitivity, still the instances in which it does so act, are so rare and trifling, that they may be thrown out of the account. We may therefore safely assume as a general law, that the will determines according to reasons and inducements drawn from the reason and the sensitivity. This law is not by its very definition, and by the very nature of the subject to which it relates, a necessary law — but a law revealed in our consciousness as one to which the will, in the exercise of its freedom, A CONTINGENT WILL. 285 docs submit itself. In the harmony and perfec- tion of our being, the reason and the sensitivity perfectly accord. In obeying the one or the other, the will obeys both. With regard to per- fect beings, therefore, we can calculate with cer- tainty as to their volitions under any given cir- cumstances. Whatever is commanded by reason, whatever appears attractive to the pure sensitivi- ty, will be obeyed and followed. But what kind of certainty is this ? It is not absolute certainty, because it is supposable that the will which obeys may not obey, for it has power not to obey. Nor is it jrfiysical certainty, for it does not relate to a physical cause, nor to the connexion between volition and its effects, but to the connexion between will and its volitions. Nor again can we, strictly speaking, call it a con- ditional certainty ; because the will, as a power per se, is under no conditions as to the production of its volitions. To say that the volitions will be in accordance with the reason and pure sensitivi- ty, if the will continue to obey the reason and pure sensitivity, is merely saying that the volitions will be right if the willing power put forth right volitions. What kind of certainty is it, then ? I reply, it is a certainty altogether peculiar. — a certainty based upon the relative state of the rea- 286 j:\ami.\atio.\ of aim.i mi:m- AOAINB1 son and the sensitivity, and their unity with the will : and as the commands of reason in relation to conduct have received the name of moral * laws, simply because they have this relation, — and as the sensitivity, when harmonizing with the reason, is thence called morally pure, because at- tracting to the same conduct which the reason commands, — this certainty may fitly be called ?noral certainty. The name, however, does not mark degree. Does this certainty possess de- grees ? It does. With respect to the volitions of God, we have the highest degree of moral cer- tainty, — an infinite moral certainty. He, in- deed, in his infinite will, has the power of pro- ducing any volitions whatever ; but from his infi- nite excellency, consisting in the harmony of infi- nite reason with the divine affections of infinite benevolence, truth, and justice, we are certain that his volitions will always be right, good, and wise. Besides, he has assured us of his fixed de- termination to maintain justice, truth, and love : and he has given us this assurance as perfectly knowing himself in the whole eternity of his being. Let no one attempt to confound this perfect mor- al certainty with necessity, for the distinction is * Lat. moralis, from mos, — i. c. custom or ordinary conduct. A CONTINGENT WILL. 287 plain. If God's will were affirmed to be neces- sarily determined in the direction of truth, right- eousness, and love, it would be an affirmation re- specting the manner of the determination of the divine will: viz. — that the divine determination takes place, not in contingency and freedom, not with the power of making an opposite determina- tion, but in absolute necessity. But if it be affirm- ed that God's will, will certainly go in the direc- tion of truth, righteousness, and love, the affirma- tion respects our knowledge and conviction of the character of the divine volitions in the whole eternity of his being. We may indeed proceed to inquire after the grounds of this knowledge and conviction; and if the necessity of the divine determinations be the ground of this knowledge and conviction, it must be allowed that it is a suf- ficient ground. But will any man assume that necessity is the only ground of certain knowledge and conviction ? If necessity be universal, em- bracing all beings and events, then of course there is no place for this question, inasmuch as any other ground of knowledge than necessity is not sup- posable. But if, at least for the sake of the argu- ment, it be granted that there may be other grounds of knowledge than necessity, then I would ask whether the infinite excellence of the divine rea- 288 i:\AMIN-.YTION OF ARGIMINT- AGAINST son and sensitivity, in their perfect harmony, does afford to us aground for the most certain and sat- isfactory belief that the divine will will create and mould all being and order all events according to infinite wisdom and rectitude. In order to have full confidence that God will forever do right, must we know that his will is absolutely necessi- tated by his reason and his affections ? Can we not enjoy this confidence, while we allow him ab- solute freedom of choice ? Can we not believe that the Judge of all the Earth will do right, al- though in his free and omnipotent will he have the power to do wrong ? And especially may we not believe this, when, in his omniscience and his truth, he has declared that his purposes will for- ever be righteous, benevolent, and wise ? Does not the glory and excellency of God appear in this, — that while he hath unlimited power, he employs that power by his free choice, only to dispense justice, mercy, and grace ? And does not the excellency and meritoriousness of a crea- ture's faith appear in this, — that while God is known to be so mighty and so absolute, he is con- fided in as a being who will never violate any moral principle or affection ? Suppose God's will to be necessitated in its wise and good volitions, — the sun dispensing heat and light, and by A CONTINGENT WILL. 289 their agency unfolding and revealing the beauty of creation, seems as truly excellent and worthy of gratitude, — and the creature, exercising grati- tude towards God and confiding in him, holds no other relation to him than the sunflower to the sun — by a necessity of its nature, ever turning its face upwards to receive the influences which min- ister to its life and properties. The moral certainty attending the volitions of created perfect beings is the same in kind witii that attending the volitions of the Deity. It is a cer- tainty based upon the relative state of the reason and the sensitivity, and their unity with the will. Wherever the reason and the sensitivity are in harmony, there is moral certainty. I mean by this, that in calculating the character of future vo- litions in this case, we have not to calculate the relative energy of opposing principles : — all which is now existent is, in the constituted unity of the soul, naturally connected only with good volitions. But the degree of the moral certainty in created beings, when compared with that attending the volitions of Deity, is only in the proportion of the finite to the infinite. The confidence which we repose in the integrity of a good being, does not arise from the conviction that his volitions are necessitated, but from his known habit of obey- 25 990 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST ing truth and justice ; and our sense of his meri- toriousness does not arise from the impossibility of his doing wrong, but from his known determina- tion and habit of doing right while having the power of doing wrong, and while even under temptations of doing wrong. A certainty respecting volitions, if based upon the necessity of the volitions, would not differ from a physical certainty. But a moral certainty has this plain distinction, — that it is based upon the evidently pure dispositions and habits of the individual, without implying, however, any neces- sity of volitions. Moral certainty, then, is predicablc only of moral perfection, and predicablc in degrees ac- cording to the dignity and excellency of the being. But now let us suppose any disorder to take place in the sensitivity ; that is, let us suppose the sensitivity, to any degree, to grow into opposition to the reason, so that while the reason commands in one direction, the sensitivity gives the sense of the most agreeable in the opposite direction, — and then our calculations respecting future voli- tions must vary accordingly. Here moral cer- tainty exists no longer, because volitions are now to be calculated in connexion with opposing prin- A CONTINGENT WILL, 291 ciples : calculations now attain only to the proba- ble, and in different degrees. By the probable, we mean that which has not attained to certainty, but which nevertheless has grounds on which it claims to be believed. We call it probable or proveable, because it both has proof and is still under conditions of proof, that is. admits of still farther proof. That which is cer- tain, has all the proof of which the case admits. A mathematical proposition is certain on the ground of necessity, and admits of no higher proof than that which really demonstrates its truth. The divine volitions are certain on the ground of the divine perfections, and admit of no higher proof than what is found in the divine perfections. The volitions of a good created being are cer- tain on the ground of the purity of such a being, and admit of no higher proof than what is found in this purity. But when we come to a mixed being, that is, a being of reason, and of a sensitivity corrupted to- tally or in different degrees, then we have place not for certainty, but for probability. As our knowledge of the future volitions of such a being can only be gathered from something now exist- ent, this knowledge will depend upon our know- ledge of the present relative state of his reason 893 EXAMINATION OF AROUMKNTS AOAI.WT. and sensitivity ; but a perfect knowledge of this is in no case supposable, — so that, although our ac- tual knowledge of this being may be such as to afford us proof of what his volitions may be, yet, inasmuch as our knowledge of him may be increased indefinitely by close observation and study, so likewise will the proof be increased. According to the definition of probability above given, therefore, our knowledge of the future vo- litions of an imperfect being can only amount to probable knowledge. The direction of the probabilities will be deter- mined by the preponderance of the good or the bad in the mixed being supposed. If the sensi- tivity be totally corrupted, the probabilities will generally go in the direction of the corrupted sensitivity, because it is one observed general fact in relation to a state of corruption, that the enjoy- ments of passion are preferred to the duties en- joined by the conscience. But the state of the reason itself must be considered. If the reason be in a highly developed state, and the convic- tions of the right consequently clear and strong, there may be probabilities of volitions in opposition to passion which cannot exist where the reason is undeveloped and subject to the errors and preju- dices of custom and superstition. The difference A CONTINGENT WILL. 293 is that which is commonly known under the terms " enlightened and unenlightened conscience." Where the sensitivity is not totally corrupted, the direction of the probabilities must depend upon the degree of corruption and the degree to which the reason is developed or undeveloped. With a given state of the sensitivity and the rea- son, the direction of the probabilities will depend also very much upon the correlated, or upon the opposing objects and circumstances: — where the objects and circumstances agree with the state of the sensitivity and the reason, or to speak generally and collectively, with " the state of the mind," the probabilities will clearly be more easily determin- ed than where they are opposed to " the state of the mind." The law which Edwards lays down as the law of volition universally, viz : that M the volition is as the greatest apparent good :" understanding by the term "good," as he does, simply, that which strikes us M agreeably," is indeed a general rule, according to which the volitions of characters deeply depraved may be calculated. This law represents the individual as governed wholly by his passions, and this marks the worst form of character. It is a law which cannot extend to him who is struggling under the light of his rea- 25* 2'.H KXA.MINA.TION OF ARGVMT.NT- AGAINST son against passion, and consequently the proba- bilities in this last case must be calculated in a different way. But in relation to the former it is a sufficient rule. Probability, as well as certainty, respects only the kind and degree of our knowledge of any events, and not the causes by which those events are produced : whether these causes be necessary or contingent is another question. One great error in reasoning respecting the character of causes, in connexion with the calcu- lation of probabilities, is the assumption that uni- formity is the characteristic of necessary causes only. The reasoning maybe stated in the follow- ing syllogism : In order to calculate either with certainty or probability any events we must suppose a uniform law of causation ; but uniformity can exist only where there is a necessity of causation ; hence, our calculations suppose a necessity of causa- tion. This is another instance of applying to the will principles which were first obtained from the ob- servation of physical causes, and which really be- long to physical causes only. With respect to physical causes, it is true that uniformity appears to be a characteristic of necessary causes, simply A CONTINGENT WILL. 295 because physical causes are relatively necessary causes: — but with respect to the will, it is not true that uniformity appears to be a characteristic of necessary cause, because the will is not a ne- cecessary cause. That uniformity therefore, as in the case of physical causes, seems to become a characteristic of necessary cause, does not arise from the nature of the idea of cause, but from the nature of the particular subject, viz., physical cause. Uniformity in logical strictness, does not belong to cause at all, but to law or rule. Cause is simply efficiency or power : law or rule defines the direction, aims, and modes of power : cause explains the mere existence of phenomena: law explains their relations and characteristics : law is the thought and design of the reason. Now a cause may be so conditioned as to be incapable of acting except in obedience to law, and this is the case of all physical causes which act accord- ing to the law or design of infinite wisdom, and thus the uniformity which we are accustomed to attribute to these causes is not their own, but be- longs to the law under which they necessarily act. But will is a cause which is not so conditioned as to be incapable of acting except in obedience to law ; it can oppose itself to, and violate law. but still it is a cause in connexion with law, the law found 206 EXAMINATION Of AROl KBMTf AGAINST in the reason and sensitivity, which law of course has the characteristic of uniformity. The law of the reason and pure sensitivity is uniform — it is the law of right The law of a totally corrupted sensitivity is likewise a uniform law ; it is the law of passion ; a law to do whatever is most pleasing to the sensitivity; and every individual, whatever may be the degree of his corruption, forms for himself certain rules of conduct, and as the very idea of rule embraces uniformity, we expect in every individual more or less uniformity of con- duct. Uniformity of physical causation, is nothing but the design of the supreme reason developed in phenomena of nature. Uniformity of volitions is nothing but the design of reason and pure sensi- tivity, or of corrupted passion developed in human conduct. The uniformity thus not being the cha- racteristic of cause as such, cannot be the charac- teristic of necessary cause. The uniformity of causation, therefore, argues nothing respecting the nature of the cause ; it may be a necessary cause or it may not. There is no difficulty at all in con- ceiving of uniformity in a free contingent will, because this will is related to uniform rules, which in the unity of the being we expect to be obeyed but which we also know do not necessitate obe- dience. In physical causes we have the uniform- A CONTINGENT WILL. 297 ity of necessitated causes. In will we have the uniformity of a free intelligent cause. We can conceive of perfect freedom and yet of perfect order, because the free will can submit itself to the light of the reason. Indeed, all the order and harmony of creation, although springing from the idea of the reason, has been constituted by the power of the infinite free will. It is an order and harmony not necessitated but chosen by a power determining itself. It is altogether an as- sumption incapable of being supported that free- dom is identified with disorder. Of the words, Foreknowledge and Prescience. These wrords are metaphorical : fore and pre do not qualify knowledge and science in relation to the mind which has the knowledge or science ; but the time in which the knowledge takes place in relation to the time in which the object of knowledge is found. The metaphor consists in giving the attribute of the time of knowledge, con- sidered relatively to the time of the object of knowledge, to the act of knowledge itself. Ban- ishing metaphor for the sake of attaining greater perspicuity, let us say, First: All acts of knowing are present acts of 298 EXAMINATION OF ARGUMENTS AGAINST knowing, — there is no fore knowledge and no after knowledge. Secondly: The objects of knowledge may be in no relation to time and space whatever, e. g. pure abstract and necessary truth, as 2 x 2 = 4 ; and the being of God. Or the objects of know- ledge may be in relations of time and space, e. g. all physical phenomena. Now these relations of time and space are va- rious ; — the object of knowledge may be in time past, or time present, or time future; and it may be in a place near, or in a place distant. And the faculty of knowledge may be of a capacity to know the object in all these relations under cer- tain limitations, or under no limitations. The faculty of knowledge as knowing objects in all re- lations of time and space, under certain limitations, is the faculty as given in man. We know objects in time present, and past, and future; and we know objects both near and distant ; but then our knowledge does not extend to all events in any of these relations, or in any of these relations to their utmost limit. The faculty of knowledge as knowing objects in all relations of time and space, under no limita- tions, is the faculty under its divine and infinite form. Under this form it comprehends the present A CONTINGENT WILL. 290 perfectly, and the past and the future no less than the present — and it reaches through all space. God's knowledge is an eternal now — an omnipresent here ; that is, all that is possible and actual in eternity and space, is now perfectly known to him. Indeed God's knowledge ought not to be spoken of in relation to time and space; it is infinite and absolute knowledge, from eternity to eternity the same ; it is unchangeable, because it is perfect; it can neither be increased nor di- minished. We have shown before that the perfection of the knowledge does not settle the mode of causa- tion : that which comes to pass by necessity, and that which comes to pass contingently, are alike known to God. CONCLUSION. I here finish my review of Edwards's System, and his arguments against the opposite system. I hope I have not thought or written in vain. The review I have aimed to conduct fairly and hon- ourably, and in supreme reverence of truth. As to style, I have laboured only for perspicuity, and where a homely expression has best answered this end, I have not hesitated to adopt it- The 300 < «>\< LU8ION. nice graces of rhetoric, as popularly understood, cannot be attended to in severe reasoning. To amble on a flowery surface with fancy, when we aiv mining in the depths of reason, is manifestly impossible. The great man with whose work I have been engaged, I honour and admire for his intellec- tual might, and love and venerate for a purity and elevation of spirit, which places him among the most sainted names of the Christian church. But have I done wrong not to be seduced by his genius, nor won and commanded by his piety to the belief of his philosophy? I have not done wrong if that be a false philosophy. When he leads me to the cross, and speaks tome of salvation, I hear in mute attention — and one of the old preachers of the martyr age seems to have re-appeared. But when we take a walk in the academian grove, I view him in a different character, and here his voice does not sound to me so sweet as Plato's. The first part of my undertaking is accomplish- ed. When I again trouble the public with my lu- cubrations, I shall appear not as a reviewer, but in an original work, which in its turn must become the subject of philosophical criticism. ■»' /. Ill III I CD3S31b7M3 RETURN TO the circulation desk of any University of California Library or to the HERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY University of California 'ichmond Field Station, Bldg. 400 1301 South 46th Street Richmond, CA 94804-4698 MAY BE RECALLED AFTER 7 DAYS "•e your library materials, you may - to due date at (510) 642-6233 BELOW ■ \i. ULIAfXLLLI HI II I I III II C Q 3 5 3 1 b ? M 3 RETURN TO the circulation desk of any University of California Library or to the NORTHERN REGIONAL LIBRARY FACILITY University of California Richmond Field Station, Bldg. 400 1301 South 46th Street Richmond, CA 94804-4698 ALL BOOKS MAY BE RECALLED AFTER 7 DAYS To renew or recharge your library materials, you may contact NRLF 4 days prior to due date at (510) 642-6233 DUE AS STAMPED BELOW JUN G 6 2008 DD20 12M 7-06 m WV