\ STUDIA IN

THE LIBRARY

of VICTORIA UNIVERSITY

Toronto

-

_

THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

PRINTED BY MORRISON AND GIBB, FOR

T. & T. CLARK, LAW PUBLISHERS, EDINBURGH.

GLASGOW J. SMITH AND SON.

LONDON STEVENS AND SONS.

STEVENS AND HAYNES.

HAMILTON, ADAMS AND CO.

THE PHILOSOPHY OF LAW

3n (Exposition

OF THE

FUNDAMENTAL PRINCIPLES OF JURISPRUDENCE

A<J

THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT.

BY

IMMANUEL KANT.

Cranslatcto from tfjc German

BY W. HASTIE, B.D.

EDINBURGH: T. & T. CLARK, 38 GEORGE STREET.

1887.

6

next to a new History of Law, what we most require is a new Philosophy of Law. '—Sir HENRY SUMNER MAINE.

7, it> , 9$ 7

TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE.

KANT'S Science of Riykt 1 is a complete exposition of the Philosophy of Law, viewed as a rational investigation of the fundamental Principles of Jurisprudence. It was published in 1796,2 as the First Part of his Metaphysic of Morals,3 the promised sequel and completion of the Foundation for a Metaphysic of Morals? published in 1785. The importance and value of the great thinker's exposition of the Science of Eight, both as regards the fundamental Principles of his own Practical Philosophy and the general interest of the Philosophy of Law, were at once recognised. A second Edition, enlarged by an

1 Rechfcdehre.

- It appeared soon after Michaelmas 1796, but with the year 1797 on the title-page. This has given rise to some confusion regarding the date >f th«- fii>t Edition, which is now usually quoted as 1796-7. (Schubert, f rente, Bd. ix. viii., and /Hoijrafihie, p. 145.)

1 Dit- .M.-t.iphyMk .lor Siitm. Krst.-r Thril. Metaphysische Anl'.i iimn.li' il.-r K.-rhNlrhn-. Kniii^herL', 1797.

4 Grundlegung /in M. -tapliy.-ik d. r Sitt«-n. Translated by Willi«-h (1798), Semple (1836), and Abbott (1873).

VI

KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Appendix, containing Supplementary Explanations of the Principles of Right, appeared in 1798.1 The work has since then been several times reproduced by itself, as well as incorporated in all the complete editions of Kant's Works. It was immediately rendered into Latin by Born2 in 1798, and again by Konig 3 in 1800. It was translated into French by Professor Tissot in 1837,4 of which translation a second revised Edition has appeared. It was again translated into French by M. Barni, preceded by an elaborate analytical introduction, in 1853.5 With the exception of the Preface and Introductions,6 the work now appears translated into English for the first time.

Kant's Science of Eight was his last great work of an independent kind in the department of pure Philosophy,

1 These Supplementary Explanations were appended by Kant to th« First Part of the work, to which most of their detail more directly apply ; but they are more conveniently appended in this translation to the whole work, an arrangement which has also been adopted by the other Translators.

2 Initia Metaphysica Doctrinse Juris. Immanvelis Kantii Opera ad philosophiam criticam. Latine vertit Fredericus Gottlob Born. Volumen qnartum. Lipsiae, MDCCLXXXXVIII.

1 Elementa Metaphysica Juris Doctrinae. Latine vertit G. L. Konig. Amstel. 1800, 8. (Warnkonig and others erroneously refer it to Gotha.)

4 Priucipes Metaphysiques du Droit, par Emm. Kant, etc. Paris, 1837.

5 Elements Metaphysiques de la Doctrine du Droit, etc. Paris, 1853.

c The Preface and the Introductions (infra, pp. 1-58, 259-265) have been translated by Mr. Semple. See The Metaphyaic of Ethics by

TIIAXSLATOR'S PBWACE. vii

and with it he virtually brought his activity as a m of thought to a close.1 It fittingly crowned the rich practical period of his later philosophical teaching, and he shed into it the last effort of his energy of thought. Full of years and honours he was then deliberately engaged, in the calm of undisturbed and unwearied reflection, in gathering the finally matured fruit of all the meditation and learning of his life. His three immortal Critiques of the Pure Reason* (1781), the Practical Reason* (1788), and the Judgment* (1790), had unfolded all the theoretical Principles of his Critical Philosophy, and established his claim to be recognised as at once the most profound and the most original thinker of the modern world. And as the experience of life deepened around and within him, towards the sunset, his

Immanuel Kant, translated by J. W. Semple, Advocate. Fourth Ed. Edited with Introduction by Rev. Henry Calderwood, LL.D., Professor of Moral Philosophy, University of Edinburgh. Edin. : T. & T. Clark, 1886.— These are indispensable parts of the present work, but they have been translated entirely anew.

1 He ceased lecturing in 1797 ; and the only works of any importance published by himself subsequent to the Rechtslehre, were the Mtta physwche Aiifanfjwjrunde tier Tugendlehre in 1797, and Der Ktreit der Facidtaten and the Anthropoloyie in 1798. The Loyik was edited by Jiische in 1800 ; the Physische Geographic by Rink in 1802, and the Pddaf/orjik, also by Rink, in 1803, the year before Kant's death.

* Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Translated anew by Max Mailer (1881).

3 Kritik der praktischen Vernunft. Translated by Abbott.

1 Kritik der Urthcilskraft. Translated into French by M. Barai.

viii KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

interest had been more and more absorbed and concen trated in the Practical. For to him, as to all great and Comprehensive thinkers, Philosophy has only its beginning in the theoretical explanation of things ; its chief end is the rational organization and animation and guidance of the higher life in which all things culminate. Kant had carried with him through all his struggle and toil of thought, the cardinal faith in God, Freedom, and Immor tality, as an inalienable possession of Eeason, and he had beheld the human Personality transfigured and glorified in the Divine radiance of the primal Ideas. But he had further to contemplate the common life of Humanity in its varied ongoings and activities, rising with the innate right of mastery from the bosom of Nature and asserting its lordship in the arena of the mighty world that it incessantly struggles to appropriate and subdue to itself. In the natural chaos and conflict of the social life of man, as presented in the multitudinous ami ever-changing mass of the historic organism, he had also to search out the Principles of order and form, to vindicate the rationality of the ineradicable belief in human Causation, and to quicken anew the lively hope of a higher issue of History. The age of the i Revolution called and inspired him to his task. With keen vision he saw a new world suddenly born before him, as the blood-stained product of a motion long toiling in

TKANSI.ATUUS I'KKFACE. IX

tlie gloom, and all old things tlius passing away ; and h. knew that it was only the pure and the practical Reason, in that inmost union which constitutes the birthright of Freedom, that could regulate and harmonize the future order of this strongest offspring of time. And if it was not given to him to work out the whole cycle of the new rational ideas, he at least touched upon them all, and he has embodied the cardinal Principle of the System in his Science of Right as the philosophical ^ Magna Charta of the age of political Reason and the permanent foundation of all true Philosophy of Law.

Thus produced, Kant's Science of Right constituted an epoch in jural speculation, and it has commanded the homage of the greatest thinkers since. Fichte, with characteristic ardour and with eagle vision, threw his whole energy of soul into the rational problem of Right, and if not without a glance of scorn at the sober limita tions of the ' old Lectures ' of the aged professor, he yet acknowledges in his own more aerial flight the initial safety of this more practical guidance.1 In those early days of eager search and high aspiration, Hegel, stirred to the depths by Kant, and Fichte, and Schelling, wrote his profound and powerful essay on the Philosophy of

i Fichte's Nachgelassene Werke, 2 Bd. System der Rechtslehre (1804), 498, etc. (Bonn, 1834.) Fichte's Grundlage dcs Naturrechts (1796), hims.-lf pointeout, was published before Kant's Jtcchtalehre, butits principle* IN all «-s<uiti;illy Kantian. (Translated by Kroeger, Philadelphia, 1870.)

\ KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Right, laden with an Atlantean burden of thought and strained to intolerable rigidity and severity of form, but his own highest achievement only aimed at a completer integration of the Principles differentiated by Kant.1 It was impossible that the rational evangel of universal freedom and the seer-like vision of a world, hitherto groaning and travailing in pain but now struggling into the perfection of Eternal Peace and Good- will, should find a sympathetic response in Schopenhauer, notwith standing all his admiration of Kant ; but the racy cynicism of the great Pessimist rather subsides before him into mild lamentation than seeks the usual refuge from its own vacancy and despair in the wilful caustic of scorching invective and reproach.2 Schleiermacher, N the greatest theologian and moralist of the Century, early discerned the limitations of the & priori formalism, and supplemented it by the comprehensive conceptions of the primal dominion and the new order of creation, but he owed his critical and dialectical ethicality mainly to Kant.3 Krause, the leader of the latest and largest

1 Hegel's Werke, Bd. i. Philosophische Abhandlungen, iv. Ueber die Wi^enschaf (lichen Behandlungsarten des Naturrechts (1802-3) ; and the Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, oder Naturrecht und Staatsvrissenschaft im Grundrisse (1821). Werke, Bd. viii. (passim}. Dr. J. Hutchison Stirling's Lectures on the Philosophy of Law present a most incisive and suggestive introduction to Hegel's Philosophy of Right.

%J Die beiden Grundprobleme der Ethik (1841), pp. 118-9.

1 Grundlinien einer Kritik der bisherigen Sittenlehre (1803). Entmirf

TRANSLATOR'S PRKI xi

thought in this sphere at once intuitive, radical, and productive in his faculty, analytic, synthetic, and organic in his method, and real, ideal, and historic in his product caught again the archetypal perfectibility of the human reflection of the Divine, and the living conditions of the true progress of humanity. The dawn of the thought of the new age in Kant rises above the horizon to the* clear day, full-orbed and vital, in Krause.1 All the continental thinkers and schools of the century in this sphere of Jurisprudence, whatever be their distinctive characteristics or tendencies, have owned or manifested their obligations to the great master of the Critical Philosophy.

eines Systems der Sittenlehre, herausg. von A. Schweizer(1835). Grund- riss der philosophischen Ethik, von A. Twesten (1841). Die Lehre vom Staat, herausg. von Ch. A. Brandes (1845).

1 Grundlage des Naturrechts (1803). Abriss des Systems der Philo sophic dos Rechts oder des Naturrechts (1828). Krause is now univery sally recognised as the definite founder of the organic and positive school of Natural Right. His principles have been ably expounded by his two most faithful followers, Ahrens (Court de Droit Naturel , 7th ed. 1875) and Roder (Orundzuge des Naturrechts o. der Rechtsfiloaofie, 2 Auf. 1860). Professor J. S. del Rio of Madrid has vividly expounded and enthusiastically advocated Krause's system in Spanish. Professoj^I/oriiner of the Edin burgh University, while maintaining an independent and critical attitude towards the various Schools of Jurisprudence, is in close sympathy with the Principles of Krause (The Institutes of Law: a Treatise of the Prin ciple* of Jurisprudence as determined by Nature, 2nd ed. 1880, and The Institutes of the Law of Nations). He has clearly indicated his agreement with the Kantian School, so far as its principles go (Instlt. p. 336, n.).

Ml

KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

The influence of the Kantian Doctrine of Eight has thus been vitally operative in all the subsequent progress of jural and political science.1 Kant, here as in every other department of Philosophy, summed up the frag mentary and critical movement of the Eighteenth Century, and not only spoke its last word, but inaugu rated a method which was to guide and stimulate the highest thought of the future. With an unwonted blending of speculative insight and practical knowledge, an ideal universality of conception and a sure grasp of the reality of experience, his effort, in its inner depth, vitality, and concentration, contrasts almost strangely with the trivial formalities of the Leibnitzio-Wolffian nationalists on the one hand,2 and with the pedantic

1 This applies to the latest German discussions and doctrines. The following works may be referred to as the most important recent contribu tions, in addition to those mentioned above (such as Ahrens and Rbder, xi. n.) :— Trendelenburg, Naturrecht auf dem Grunde der Ethik, 2 Auf. 1868. Post, Das Naturgesetz des Rechts, 1867. W. Arnold, Cultur und Rechtsleben, 1865. Ulrici, Naturrecht, 1873. Zoepfl, Grundriss zu Vorlesungen iiber Rechtsphilosophie, 1878. Rudolph von Ihering, Der Zweck im Recht, i. 1877, ii. 1883. Professor Frohschammer of Munich has discussed the problem of Right in a thoughtful and suggestive way from the standpoint of his original and interesting System of Philosophy, in his new volume, Ueber die Organisation und Cultur der menschlichen Gesellschaft, Philosophische Untersuchungen iiber Recht und Staat, sociales Leben und Erziehung, 1885.

2 Leibnitz, Nova Methodus discendae docendseque Jurisprudent, 1767. Observationes de principio Juris. Codex Juris Gentium, 1693-1700.

Wolff, Jus Naturae Methodo Scientifica pertractatum, Lips. 8 Tomi.

TRANSLATOB'S PREFACE. xiii

inliousncss of the Empiricists of the School of Clrotius on tlie other.1 Thomasius and his School, the expound of the Doctrine of Right as an independent Science, y were the direct precursors of the formal method of Kant's System.2 Its firm and clear outline implies the substance of many an operose and now almost unread able tome ; and it is alive throughout with the quick, keen spirit of the modern world. Kant's unrivalled genius for distinct division and systematic form, found full and appropriate scope in this sphere of thought. He

1740-48. lustitutiones Juris Naturae et Gentium, Hahe, 1754. (In French by Luzac, Amsterdam, 1742, 4 vols.) Vernunftigc Gcdanken.

Vatel, Le Droit des Gens, Leyden, 1758. Edited by Royer-Collard, Paris, 1835. English translation by Chitty, 1834. [For the other works of this school, see Ahrens, i. 323-4, or Miller's Lecture*, p. 411.]

1 Grotius, De Jure Belli ac Pacis, lib. iii. 1625. Translated by Barbeyrae into French, 1724 ; and by "NVhewell into English, 1858.

Pufcndorf, Elementa Juris Universalis, 1660. De Jure Natura- et Gentium, 1672. [English translation by Kennett, 1729.]

Cumberland, De Legibus Natune Disquisitio Philosophica, London, 1672. Translated into English by Towers, Dublin, 1750.

Cocceji, Grotius illustratus, etc., 3 vols. 1744-7. [See Miller, 409.]

* Christian Thomasius (1655-1728) first clearly distinguished between the Doctrine of Right and Ethics, and laid the basis of the celebrated d^tinction of Perfect and Imperfect Obligations as differentiated by the i-l« -ini-nt of Constraint. See Professor Lorimer's excellent account of Thomasius and of Kant's relation to his System, Inst. qf Law, p. 288 ; and Uoder, i. 240. The principal works of this School are : Thomasius, Fumlimenta juris natura? et gentium ex sensu communi deducta, 1705. (Mihard, Delincatio juris naturalis, 1712. Gundlinpr, Jus Naturn' et gentium. Koehler, Exercitationes, 1728. Achenwall, Prolegomena Juris iiriturulis :md Jus Naturae, 1781.

xiv KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

had now all his technical art as an expounder of Philo- \ sophy in perfect control, and after the hot rush through the first great Critique he had learned to take his time. His exposition thus became simplified, systematized, and clarified throughout to utmost intelligibility. Here, too, the cardinal aim of his Method was to wed speculative thought and empirical fact, to harmonize the abstract universality of Eeason with the concrete particularities of Right, and to reconcile the free individuality of the citizen with the regulated organism of the State. And the least that can be said of his execution is, that he has rescued the essential principle of Eight from the debase ment of the antinomian naturalism and arbitrary politi- cality of Hobbes1 as well as from the extravagance of the lawless and destructive individualism of Rousseau,2 while conceding and even adopting what is substantially true in the antagonistic theories of these epochal thinkers ; and he has thereby given the birthright of Freedom again, full-reasoned and certiorated, as ' a possession for ever' to modern scientific thought. With widest and

1 Hobbes, De Give, 1642. Leviathan seu de civitate ecclesiastica et civili, 1651. On Hobbes generally, see Professor Croom Robertson's Monograph in 'Blackwood's Philosophical Classics.'

2 L'origine et les fondements de I'inegalite parnii les hommes, Dijon, 1751. Contrat social, 1762. Rousseau's writings were eagerly read by Kant, and greatly influenced him. On Rousseau generally, see John Morley's Rousseau, Lond. 1878.

TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE. \\

furthest vision, and with a wisdom incomparably superior to the reactionary excitement of the great English Orator,1 he looked calmly beyond ' the red fool-fury of the Seine ' and all the storm and stress of the time, to the sure realization of the one increasing purpose that runs through the ages. The burden of years chilled none of his sympathies nor dimmed any of his hopes for humanity ; nor did any pessimistic shadow or murmur becloud his strong poetic thought, or disturb ' the mystical lore ' of his eventide. And thus at the close of all his thinking, he made the Science of Eight the very corner-stone of the social building of the race, and the practical culmination of all Religion and all Philosophy. It is not meant that everything presented here by Kant is perfect or final. On the contrary, there is probably nothing at all in his whole System of Philo sophy whose predominant characteristics are criticism, v initiation, movement that could be intelligently so regarded ; and the admitted progress of subsequent theories of Right, as briefly indicated above, may be considered as conceding so much. It must be further admitted of Kant's Science of Right that it presents

1 Burke is assigned to the Historical School of Jurisprudence by Ahrens, who not inaptly designates him ' the Mirabeau of the anti- revolution ' (i. 58). See the Reflections on the French Revolution (1790). Stahl gives a high estimate of Burke as ' the purest representative of Conservatism.'

Xvi KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

everywhere abundant opening and even provocation for ' Metacriticism ' and historical anticriticism, which have certainly not been overlooked or neglected. But it is meant withal that the Philosophy of Jurisprudence has really flourished in the Nineteenth Century only where Kant's influence has been effective, and that the higher altitudes of jural science have only come into sight where he has been taken as a guide. The great critical thinker set the problem of Eight anew to the pure Speculative Reason, and thus accomplished an intellec tual transformation of juridical thought corresponding to the revolutionary enthusiasm of liberty in the practical sphere. It is only from this point of view that we can rightly appreciate or estimate his influence and signifi cance. The all-embracing problem of the modern meta morphosis of the institutions of Society in the free State, lies implicitly in his apprehension. And in spite of his negative aspect, which has sometimes entirely misled superficial students, his solution, although betimes tenta tive and hesitating, is in the main faithful to the highest ideal of humanity, being foundationed on the eternity of Eight and crowned by the universal security and peace of the gradually realized Freedom of mankind. As Kant saved the distracted and confused thought of his time from utter scepticism and despair, and set it again with renewed youth and enthusiasm on its way, so his spirit

TKANSLATOK'S m:: xvii

seems to be -ain upon n- in this our hour of

need, with fresh healing in his win^s. ( hir Jurists must thrrefore also join the ever increasing throng of contem porary thinkers in the now general return to Kant.1 Their principles are even more conspicuously at hazard than any others, and the whole method of their science, long dying of intellectual inanition and asphyxia, must seek the conditions of a complete renovation. It is only thus, too, that the practical Politician will find the guidance of real principle in this agitated and troubled age in which the foundations of Government as well as of Right are so daringly scrutinised and so manifestly imperilled,2 and in which he is driven by the inherent necessary

1 ' The very cry of the hour is, Ficlite and Schelling are dead, and Hegel, if not clotted nonsense, is unintelligible ; let us go back to Kant. See, v too, in other countries, what a difference the want of Kant has made.1 Dr. J. H. Stirling, Mind, No. xxxvi. ' Within the last ten years many voices have been heard, both in this country and in Germany, bidding us return to Kant, as to that which is alone sound and hopeful in Philo sophy ; that which unites the prudence of science with the highest speculative enterprise that is possible without idealistic extravagances.' Professor E. Caird, Journal of Speculative Philosophy, vol. xiv. 1, 126. 1 From Hegel, we must, I think, still return upon Kant, seeking fresh hope for Philosophy in a continued use of the critical method.' Professor Calderwood, Introduction to Kant's Mttaphynic of Ethic*, p. xix.

1 The Socialistic and Communistic Doctrines of Owen (1771-1858), Fourier (1777-1837), Saint-Simon (1760-1825), Louis Blanc, Proudhon, and Ciibet, * considered as aberrations in the development of Right,' an sk- tdied by Ahrens (i. § 12) with his characteristic discrimination and fid i ness. The principles of the contemporary English Socialism will be

xviii KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

implication of local politics to face the inevitable issue of world- wide complications and the universal problem of human solidarity. And thus only, as it now appears, will it be possible to find a Principle that will at once be true to the most liberal tendency of the time, and yet do justice to its most conservative necessities.

Of criticism and comment, blind adulation and unjust depreciation of Kant's system of Eight, there has been, as already hinted, abundance and even more than enough. Every philosophical Jurist has had to define more or less explicitly his attitude towards the Kantian standpoint. The original thinkers of the dogmatic Schools Fichte, Schelling,1 Hegel, and Krause,

found summed up in A Summary of the Principles of Socialism written for the Democratic Federation, by H. M. Hyndman and William Morris (1884). Compare also Hyndman's The Historical Basis of Socialism in England, and To-day and Justice, the organs of the Social Democracy.

1 Schclling's contributions to the Science of Right have hardly received the attention they deserve. The absorption of his thought in the Philosophy of Nature left him less free to devote himself to the Philosophy of History, but it is mainly to him that the idea of the systematic objectivity and the organic vitality of the State, in its latest forms, is due. Hegel and Krause have severally adopted and developed the two sides of this conception. Compare Schelling's Abhandiuny iiber das Naturrecht in Fichte and Niethammer's Journal, iv. and v. ; and his Vorlesungen ilber die Methode des akademischcn Ktudiums, p. 146, etc. See Stahl's excellent account of Schelling' s Doctrine, Philosophic, des Rechts, i. 403-14, and The Journal of Speculative Philosophy, vol. xiii. No. 3, vi., 'Schelling on History and Jurisprudence.'

TRANSLATOR'S PIIEFACK. xix

—have made it the starting-point of their special efforts, and have elaborated their own conceptions by positive or negative reference to it. The recent Theological School of Stahl and Baader, De Maistre and Bonald,1 represent ing the Protestant and Papal reaction from the modern autonomy of Reason, has yet left the Kantian principle unshaken, and has at the best only formulated its doctrine of a universal Divine order in more specific Christian terms. The Historical School of Hugo and Savigny2 and Puchta,3 which is also that of Bentham, Austin

1 Stahl and Baader represent the Neo-Schellingian standpoint in their philosophical doctrines.— F. J. Stahl, Die Philosophic des Rechts, 3 Bdc., 3 Auf. 1865 (an important and meritorious work).— Franz von Baader's Summtliche Werke, 16 Bde. 1851-60. (Cf. Franz Hoffmann's Beleuchtuny des Anrjri/s auf Baader in Thilo's Schrift : ' Die theologisikende Rechts- und Staatslehre,' 1861.)— Joseph de Maistre, Soirees de St. Petersburg, Paris, 1821. Memoires, etc., par A. Blanc, 1858.— L' Abbe de Bonald, Legislation primitive, 1821.

1 Hugo (1768-1844) is usually regarded as the founder, and Savigny (1778-1861) as the chief representative of the Historical School. Hugo, Lchrbuch des Naturrechts als finer Philosophic des positiven Rechte, 1799, 3 Auf. 1820. Frederich Carl von Savigny, Vom Benif unserer Ztit fiir Gexetzycbunri und Reclit8ici*aen*chaft , 1814 ; System des heutiyen Romischen Rechls, 1840. (See Guthrie's translation of Savigny, Treatise on the Conflict of Laws, with an excellent Preface. T. & T. Clark. )

8 The Historical School, as Ahrciis shows, must be carried back so as to include such thinkers as Cujas, the great French Jurist of the 16th century, who called the History of Right his ' hame9on d'or ; ' Mon- ti-s.juicu (1689-1755), whose well-known book, UEnpr'd des Lois (1748), ran through twenty-two editions in a few years ; and the Neapolitan Vico (1688-1744), the founder of the ' New Science ' of History. Vico is only im\v becoming properly appreciated. See Professor's Flint's able and

xx KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

and Buckle, Sir George C. Lewis and Sir Henry Simmer Maine, and Herbert Spencer, with all its apparent antagonism, has only so far supplemented the rational universality of Kant by the necessary counterpart of an historical Phenomenology of the rise and development of the positive legal institutions, as the natural evolution and verification in experience of the juridical conceptions.1 The conspicuous want of a criterion of Eight in the application of the mere his-

instructive ' Vico ' in Blackwood's Philosophical Classics. ' In his work, De universi juris uno principio et fine (1820), Vico divides the whole Science of Right into three parts : (1) the Philosophy of Right, (2) the History of Right, and (3) the Art of applying the Philosophy to facts. He distinguishes profoundly in Laws the spirit or will of the legislator (mens legis) and the reason of the law (ratio legis), which consists in the accordance of a law with historical facts and with the eternal principles of the True and Good ' (Ahrens). The contemporary Historical School does not yet occupy so philosophical a position.

1 Sir Henry Sumner Maine, the most eminent English representative of the Historical School, continues to regard ' the philosophy founded on the hypothesis of a state of nature ' as ' still the greatest antagonist of the Historical Method ' (Ancient Law, pp. 90, 91) ; but this is evidently said in disregard of the transformation of Rousseau's theory by Kant, and the contributions to the application of the Historical Method by Hegel and his school, in whose principle the historic evolution is an essential element. Sir H. S. Maine's own contributions cannot be too highly recommended for their thoroughness and suggestiveness. He has gathered much of his original and pregnant matter from direct acquaintance with India, where, as is the case with the forms of nature, the whole genesis and stratification of the forms of Society are presented livingly to view. (Ancient Law, 1861, 7th ed. 1880. Village Communities in the East and West, 4th ed. 1881. Early History of Institutions, 1874.)

TRANSLATORS I'KKFACE. XXI

Method to the manifold, contingent, and vari able institutions of human society, has been often signalized ; and the representatives of the School have been driven again, especially in their advocacy of political liberalism, upon the rational principles of Freedom.1

The Civil Jurists who have carried the unreasoning admiration of the Roman Law almost to the idolatry of its letter, and who are too apt to ignore the movement of two thousand years and all the aspirations of the modern Reason, could not be expected to be found in sympathy with the Rational Method of Kant. Their multiplied objections to the details of his exposition, from Schmitthenner 2 to the present day, are, however, founded upon an entire misapprehension of the purpose of his form. For while Kant rightly recognised the

1 Extremes meet in the moral indifference of the universal naturalism of the ultra-historical School and the abstract absolute rationalism of Spinoza. It was Grotius who first clearly distinguished between positive fact and rational idea in the sphere of Right, and thus originated thn movement of modern ' jural ' speculation. For evidence of the statement in the text, see Bentham's Work*, Buckle's History of Civilisation, Mill on Liberty, and especially Puchta's Encyclojxidie, introductory to hU CursuH der Intttitutionen, 6 Auf. 1865. The standpoint of the Historical School has been thoroughly reviewed by Stahl, i. 570-90 ; Ahrens, L 61-61 ; and Rbder, i. 266-279.

* ' Ueber den Charakter und die Aufgaben unserer Zeit in Beziehung auf und Staatswissenschaft,' Giess. 1832. Zwblf Biicher vom Staate, 1839. See Rosenkranz's Ge*cliichtt dtr KanCurlfn Philosophic, p. 268.

xxii KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Roman Law as the highest embodiment of the juridical Reason of the ancient world, and therefore expounded his own conceptions by constant reference to it, he clearly discerned its relativity and its limitations ; and he accordingly aims at unfolding everywhere through its categories the juridical idea in its ultimate purity. In Kant the juridical Idea first attains its essential self- realization and productivity, and his system of Private Right is at once freer and more concrete than the Systems of Hobbes and Rousseau, because it involves the ancient civil system, corrected and modernized by regard to its rational and universal principles. This consideration alone will meet a host of petty objections, and guard the student against expecting to find in this most philosophical exposition of the Principles of Right a mere elementary text-book of the Roman Law.1

In England, Kant's Science of Eight seems as yet to

f

1 This remark especially applies to the running fire of criticism in Von Kirchmann's recent Erlauterungen zu Kant's Metaphysilc der Sitten, 1882. It is a matter of regret that such criticisms cannot be here dealt with in detail. Kant has himself clearly indicated the position stated above, as at p. 54, infra.— The depth and subtlety of Kant's method, so far transcending the common modes of juridical thinking in England, are inseparable from the system, but he has himself given the sufficient reason for their appearance in it (infra, p. 116). Without entering in detail upon the point, the translator may remark with regard to one con spicuous, yet irremoveable blot, that he homologates the unanimous disapprobation of subsequent jurists, and would only refer to Dr. Hutchison Stirling's drastic castigation of it in his Lectures, p. 51. But

TKANSLATOK'S I-KK; xxiii

have been little studied, and it has certainly exerted but little influence on English Juridical Science. This has no doubt been mainly due to the traditional habit of the national mind, and the complete ascendancy during the present century of the Utilitarian School of Bentham.1 The criterion of Utility found a ready application to the more pressing interests of Political and Legal Reform, and thus responding to the practical legislative spirit of the time, its popular plausibilities completely obscured or superseded all higher rational speculation. By Austin the system was methodically applied to the positive determination of the juridical conceptions ; under aid of the resources of the German Historical School, with the result that Eight was made the mere 'creature' of positive law, and the whole Rational Method pretentiously con demned as irrational ' jargon.' In Austin * we have only

of this and other difficulties in so original and originative a work i-an only be said in the meantime :

' Sunt delicta tamen, quibus ignovisse velimus.'

And every reader and student should be ready to apply the Horatinn rule here too :

' Verum ubi plura nitent . . . non ego paucis

Offendar maculis, quas aut incuria fiulit

Aut humana parum cavit natura.'

1 Fragment on Government, 1776. Essay on Political Tactics, 1791. Principles of Morals and Legislation, 1780. Traite's de Legislation, 1802.

2 Province of Jurisprudence determined, or Philosophy of Positive Law, 1832. Lectures on Jurisprudence, edited by his Widow.

Austin (1790-1859) has been greatly overestimated as a Jurist by hi§

KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

' the positive outcome of Hobbes and Hume and Bentham. The later forms of this legal positivism have not been fruitful in scientific result, and the superficiality and infutility of the standpoint are becoming more and more apparent. Nor does the Utilitarian Principle,1 with all

friends and followers. The affectionate tributes of his widow may be borne with, but it is more extraordinary to find Professor Sheldon Amos characterizing him as ' the true founder of the Science of Law ' (S. Amos, The Science of Law, p. 4). Here is Austin's estimate of Kant's Science. of Right : ' A treatise darkened by a philosophy which, I own, is my aver sion, but abounding, I must needs admit, with traces of rare sagacity. He has seized a number of notions, complex and difficult in the extreme, with distinction and precision which are marvellous, considering the scantiness of his means. For of positive systems of law he had scarcely the slightest tincture ; and the knowledge of the principles of jurisprudence, which he borrowed from other writers, was drawn, for the most part, from the muddiest sources ; from books about the fustian which is styled the Law of Nature.' (Lecture*, iii. 157.) And here is his account of the German Jurists generally .- ' It is really lamentable that the instructive and admirable books which many of the German Jurists have certainly produced, should be rendered inaccessible, or extremely difficult of access, by the thick coat of obscuring jargon with which they have wantonly incrusted their necessarily difficult science ' (ii. 405). Comment on this is superfluous. In the same breath a more condemnatory judgment is dealt out even to Sir W. Blackstone. So long as such statements passed as philosophical criticism there was no possibility for a genuine Philosophy of Law in England. Austin, notwithstanding his English reputation, is entirely ignored by the German Jurists. He seems to have known only enough of German to consult the more popular productions of the Historical School. Dr. Hutchison Stirling has dealt with Austin's com monplace Hedonism in a severe way, and yet not too severely, in his Lectures on the Phllosoj)hy of Law (sub fin.}.

1 Utilitarianism has been the subject of, incessant discussion in England down to its latest systematic exposition in Sidgwick's Methods of Ethics.

TRANSLATOR'S PKEI xxv

its seeming justice and humanity, appear capable of longer satisfying the popular mind with its deepening Consciousness of Right, or of resolving the more funda mental political problems that are again coming into view. In this connection we may quote and apply the authority of Sir Henry Sumner Maine when he says : 1 'There is such widespread dissatisfaction with existing theories of jurisprudence, and so general a conviction that they do not really solve the questions they pretend to dispose of, as to justify the suspicion that some line of inquiry necessary to a perfect result has been in completely followed, or altogether omitted by their authors.' The present unsatisfactory condition of the Science of Plight in England if not in Scotland2 could not be better indicated.

On the Continent the system has also been carefully and ably reviewed by Th. JouflVoy (Court de droit natural, 1835), Ahrens (i. 48, but less fully in the later editions), I. II. Fichte (Die philoxophitchtn Lehren von Recht, ' und Sitte, 1850), De Wai (Prysverhandeling van het Natuurregt, 1833), and particularly by the Italian Jurists (Ruder, i. 108).

1 Ancient Law, p. 118.

2 Much more may be justly claimed for Scotland than for England since the middle of the last century in regard to the cultivation of the IMiilosophy of Right. The Scottish School of Philosophy started on this side from Orotius and Thomasius. Gershom Carmichael edited Pufendorf with praiseworthy notes. Hutchison discussed the doctrine of Right with fulness and care in his System of Moral Philosophy (1755). Hume, in consistency with the method of his Intellectual Philosophy, derationalized thr conceptions of Justice and Right, and resolved them into empirical products of public Utility (Treatise, on Human Natvre, 1739. E*say»,

XXVI KANTS PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

In these circumstances, no other alternative is left for us but a renewed and deepened appeal to the universal V principle of Iteason, as the essential condition of all true progress and certainty. And in the present dearth of philosophical origination and the presence of the un- assimilated products of well-nigh a century of thought, it seems as if the prosecution of this Method of all methods

1742). Reid, leading the realistic reaction, examined this side of Hume's speculation with his characteristic earnestness, and advanced by his practical principle of Common Sense to positions akin to those of Kant's Practical Reason (Active Powers, 1788, Essay V. c. iii. Of Systems of Natural Jurisprudence, and the following chapters on Hume's Utili tarianism). Henry Home, Lord Kames, prosecuted the same method with more juridical knowledge (Principles of Equity ; Historical Law Tracts, 1758 ; Sketches of the History of Man). The movement was carried on by Adam Ferguson (Principles of Moral and Political Science, 1792 ; Essay on the History of Civ'd Society, 1767), Dugald Stewart (see especially the account of the Grotian School in the Dissertation, 1815), and Dr. Thomas Brown (Lectures). Sir James Mackintosh wrote a Discourse on the Study of the Law of Nature and Nations, 1835. The cultivation of the Philosophy of Law has never been extinct in the Scottish Universities. Since the revival of the Chair of Public Law in the University of Edinburgh in 1862, Professor Lorimer has done much by his devotion and erudition to further the cultivation of the subject. (See the reference to his own works, supra, xi. n. ) One of his pupils, Mr. W. G. Miller, Lecturer on Public Law in the University of Glasgow, has published a series of excellent Lectures on the subject, displaying exten sive knowledge and critical acumen, with general regard to the Hegelian standpoint (Lectures on the Philosophy of Law, designed mainly as an introduction to the study of International Law, 1884). Professor Flint's important work on the Philosophy of History in France and Germany, and Professor Edward Caird's recent book on Comte's Social Philosophy, may also be referred to in this connection.

TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE. xxvii

an only now be fruitfully carried on by a return to K«nt and advance through his System. Enough has perhaps already been said to indicate the recognised importance of the Kantian standpoint, and even to point to the rich fields of thought and inquiry that open every where around it to the student. Into these fields it was the original intention of the translator to attempt to furnish some more definite guidance by illustrative comment and historical reference in detail, but this intention must be abandoned meanwhile, and all the more readily as it must be reckoned at the most but a duty of subordinate obligation and of secondary import ance. The Translation is therefore sent forth by itself in reliance upon its intelligibility as a faithful rendering of the original, and in the hope that it will prove at once a help to the Students and an auxiliary to the Masters of our present juridical science. "W. II.

EDINBURGH, Jamtary 1887.

BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE.

K.'II.KH remarks (i. 254) that by far the most of the later philosophical is on Natural Right ' nomen illis leyio! ' follow the system of Kant ami Fichtc, which is in the main identical in principle with that of Thomasius. It was impossible to refer to them in detail in these pre fatory remarks, but it may be useful to quote the following as the more

xxviii KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

important works on the subject from this standpoint since the appearance •if Kant's Rechtalchre :

A. Mellin, Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Rechte, 1796.

P. J. A. Feuerbach, Kritik des natiirlichen Rechts, 1796.

H. Stephani, Grundlinien der Rechtswissenschaft, 1797.

Ph. Schmutz, Erklarung der Rechte des Menschen u. des Burgers,

1798. Handbuch der Rechtsphilosophie, 1807. R. Gerstacker, Metaphysik des Rechts, 1802. L. Bendavid, Versuch eincr Rechtslehre, 1802. K. H. v. Gros, Lehrbuch des Naturrechts, 1802. 6 Ausg. 1841. Fries, Philosophische Rechtslehre u. Kritik aller positiven Gesetz

Gebung, 1803.

L. N. Jacob, Philosophische Rechtslehre, 2 A. 1802. K. S. Zacharia, Anfangsgriinde der Philosoph. Privatrechts, 1804. Philosophische Rechtslehre o. Naturrecht u. Staatslehre, 1819. Vierzig Bucher vom Staate, 1839-43. Chr. Weiss, Lehrbuch der Philosophic des Rechts, 1804. A. Bauer, Lehrbuch des Naturrechts, 1808. 3 Ausg. 1825. J. C. F. Meister, Lehrbuch des Naturrechts, 1809. Dresch, Systematische Entwickelung der Grundbegriffe u. Grundpriu- zipien des gesammten Privatrechts, Staatsrechts, und Volkerrechts 1810, 1822.

V. Zeiller, Naturrecht, 1813.

W. F. Krug, Dikiiologie oder philosophische Rechtslehre, 1817, 1830. Eschenmeyer, Normalrecht, 2 Thle. 1819. S. Beck, Lehrbuch des Naturrechts, 1820.

V. Droste-Hiilshoff, Lehrbuch des Naturrechts o. der Rechtsphilo sophie, 1823, 1831.

Pblitz, Natur- und Volkerrecht, Staats- und Staatenrecht, 1823, 1825. J. Haus, Elementa doctrinse philosophic sive juris naturalis. Gondavi 1824.

K. von Rotteck, Lehrbuch des Vernunftrechts und der Staatswissen-

schaft, 4 Bde. 1829-34, 1841. Ant. Virozsil, Epitome juris naturalis. Pesthini, 1839.

F. Fischer, Naturrecht und natiirliche Staatslehre, 1848.

G. Schilling, Lehrbuch des Naturrechts, 1859.

TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE. xxix

l!'->iJea these a considerable number of similar German works might referred to by Schaumann, Heydenreich, Klein, A. Thomas, Weiss, J. K. S.-hmid, T. M. Zacharia, Stbckhardt, E. Reinhold, Schnabel, Pfitzer, and others.

Of the French works, from the Kantian standpoint, may be quoted (Ahrens, i. 326) :—

M. Bussart, Elements de droit naturel prive*. Fribourg en Suisse, 1836. V. Belime, Philosophic du droit. Paris, 1844, 4 ed. 1881. In Italy, where the Philosophy of Law has been cultivated ' with great zeal and intelligence' (Ahrens, i. 327 ; Roder, Krit. Zeitschrift fur Rechte- tciss. xv. 1, 2, 3), the Kantian system has been ably discussed by Mancini, Mamiani, Rosmini, Poli, and others. Its chief representatives have been Baroli, Diritto naturale private e publico, 6 vol. Cremona, 1837. Tolomei, Corso elementare di diritto naturale, 2 ed. Padova, 1855. Soria di Crispan, Filosofia di diritto publico. (Philosophic du droit

public. Brux. 1853-4.) Transl. into French. Rosmini-Serbati, Filosofia del diritto, 1841. (In part Kantian.)

[Since writing the foregoing Preface there has come to hand the import ant work, ' La Vita del Diritto, nei suoi rapporti colla Vita Sociale : Studio comparative di Filosofia Giuridica. Per Giusseppe Carle, Pro- fessore ordinario di Filosofia de Diritto nella R. Universita di Torino.' Its comprehensive method and profound insight add to the already ample evidence of the ' great zeal and intelligence ' with which the Philosophy of Law is now being cultivated by the countrymen of Vico, the natural successors of Antistius Labeo, and Papinian. Professor Curie points out the relation of Kant not only to Rosmini, but also to Mamiani and others. Hit view of the importance and influence of the Kantian System is in accord with the brief indications ventured in these Prefatory hints. It is impossible to quote his exposition here, but attention may be directed to P. ii. L. i. Cap. ii. § 3, * Emmanuele Kant come iniziatore del metodo rationale nello studio del diritto naturale ; ' and L. ii. Cap. v. ' Ulteriore svolgimento,' etc. TK.]

CONTEXTS.

KANT'S METAPHYSICAL PRINCIPLES OF THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT.

PAor

I'l.i.i ATOUY EXPLANATIONS, ..... 3

PROLEGOMENA GENERAL IHTRODUCTION TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS.

vl. Relations of the Faculties of the Human Mind to the Moral

Laws, ....... 9

v II. The Idea and Necessity of a Metaphysic of Morals, . . If.

III. The Division of a Metaphysic of Morals, ... 20

GENERAL DIVISIONS OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS.

I. Division of the Metaphysic of Morals as a System of Duties

generally, . . . . . . .21

II. Division of the Metaphysic of Morals according to Relations

of Obligation, ...... 2f>

ylll. Division of the Metaphysic of Morals according to its Prin ciples and Method, ...... 27

yiV. General Preliminary Conceptions defined and explained, . 28

INTRODUCTION TO THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT.

GENERAL DEFINITIONS AND DIVISIONS.

A What the Science of Right is, . . . .4:?

-E. What is Right? ...... 44

> C. Universal Principle of Right, . . . 45

D. Ki^ht is conjoined with the Title to compel, ... 47

rict Right ; Compulsion, Freedom, Universal Laws, 47

i'plrmentary Remarks on Equivocal Right, . .60

I. Equity, •. f>0

II. Tin- Ri-ht

XXxil CONTEXTS.

DIVISION OF THE SCIENCE OF EIGHT.

PAGE

A. General Division of the Duties of Right, . . 54

B. Universal Division of Rights, .

I. Natural Right and Positive Right, . 55

II. Innate Right and Acquired Right, . 55 v There is only one Innate Right, the Birthright of

Freedom, . . 56

X C. Methodical Division of the Science of Right, ... 58

THE SCIENCE OF EIGHT. PART FIRST : PRIVATE RIGHT.

THE SYSTEM OF THOSE LAWS WHICH REQUIRE NO EXTERNAL PROMULGATION.

THE PRINCIPLES OF THE EXTERAL MINE AND THINE.

PRIVATE RIGHT.

CHAPTER FIRST. OF THE MODE OF HAVING ANYTHING EXTERNAL AS ONE'S OWN.

1. The Meaning of ' Mine ' in Right, .... 61

2. Juridical Postulate of the Practical Reason, ... 62

3. Possession and Ownership, . . . . .64

4. Exposition of the Conception of the External Mine and

Thine, . . . . . . .64

5. Definition of the Conception of the External Mine and

Thine, ....... 66

6. Deduction of the Conception of Juridical Possession of an

External Object, ...... 67

7. Application of the Principle of the possibility of an External

Mine and Thine to Objects of Experience, ... 72

8. To have anything External as one's own is only possible in a

Juridical or Civil State of Society, .... 76

9. An External Mine and Thine in the State of Nature only

provisory, . . . . . . .78

CHAPTER SECOND.

THE MODE OF ACQUIRING ANYTHING EXTERNAL. 10. The General Principle of External Acquisition, . , 81

CONTENTS. XXX111

FIRST SECTION : PRINCIPLES OF REAL RIGHT.

PAGE

11. What is a Real Right?

12. The First Acquisition of a Thing can only be that of the

Soil -7

13. Every part of the Soil may be originarily acquired, .

14. The Juridical Act of this original Acquisition is Occupancy, . 89

15. Peremptory and Provisory Acquisition, ... 90

16. Conception of a Primary Acquisition of the Soil, . . 94

17. Deduction of the Conception of original primary Acquisition, 95 Property, . . . . . . .98

SECOND SECTION : PRINCIPLES OF PERSONAL RIGHT.

13. Nature and Acquisition of Personal Right, . . .100

19. Acquisition by Contract, . . . . .101

20. What is acquired by Contract ? . . . .104

21. Acceptance and Delivery, ..... 105

THIRD SECTION : PRINCIPLES OF PERSONAL RIGHT THAT is REAL IN KIND.

22. Nature of Personal Right of a Real Kind, . . .108

23. What is acquired in the Household, . . . .109

RIGHTS OF THE FAMILY AS A DOMESTIC SOCIETY. TITLE FIRST : CONJUGAL RIGHT (Husband and Wife).

24. The Natural Basis of Marriage, . . . .109

25. The Rational Right of Marriage, . . . .110

26. Monogamy and Equality in Marriage, . . . Ill

27. Fulfilment of the Contract of Marriage, . . . 113

TITLE SECOND : PARENTAL RIGHT (Parent and Child).

28. The Relation of Parent and Child, . . . .114

29. The Rights of the Parent, . . . . .116

TITLE THIRD : HOUSEHOLD RIGHT (Master and Servant).

30. Relation and Right of the Master of a Household, . .118

XXXIV CONTEXTS.

SYSTEMATIC DIVISION OF ALL THE RIGHTS CAPABLE OF BEING ACQUIRED BY CONTRACT.

PAGE

81. Division of Contracts, .

Illustrations: I. What is Money ? . . 125

II. What is a Book? . 129

The Unauthorized Publishing of Books, . 130

Confusion of Personal Right and Real Right, . 131

EPISODICAL SECTION : THE IDEAL ACQUISITION OF EXTERNAL OBJECTS OF THE WILL.

32. The Nature and Modes of Ideal Acquisition, . . 132

33. I. Acquisition by Usucapion, . 133

34. II. Acquisition by Inheritance, .... 136

35. III. The Right of a good Name after Death, . . .138

CHAPTER THIRD.

ACQUISITION CONDITIONED BY THE SENTENCE OF A PUBLIC JUDICATORY.

36. How and what Acquisition is subjectively conditioned by

the Principle of a Public Court, . . . .141

37. I. The Contract of Donation, .... 143

38. II. The Contract of Loan, ..... 144

39. III. The Revindication of what has been Lost, . . 147

40. IV. Acquisition of Security by taking of an Oath, . . 151

TRANSITION FROM THE MINE AND THINE IN THE STATE OF NATURE

TO THE MINE AND THINE IN THE JURIDICAL STATE GENERALLY.

41. Public Justice as related to the Natural and the Civil State, . 155

42. The Postulate of Public Right, , . . . . 157

CONTENTS. XXXV

PART SECOND: PUBLIC RIGHT.

THE SYSTEM OF THOSE LAWS WHICH REQUIRE PUBLIC PROMULGATION.

THE PRINCIPLES OF RIGHT IN CIVIL SOCIETY.

PAUK

43. Definition and Division of Public Right, . . . 1G1

PUBLIC RIGHT.

I. RIGHT OF THE STATE AND CONSTITUTIONAL LAW.

44. Origin of the Civil Union and Public Right, . . .163

45. The Form of the State and its Three Powers, . . 16r>

46. The Legislative Power and the Members of the State, . 166

47. Dignities in the State and the Original Contract, . . 169

48. Mutual Relations and Characteristics of the Three Powers, . 170

49. Distinct Functions of the Three Powers. Autonomy of the

State, . . . . . 171

CONSTITUTIONAL AND JURIDICAL CONSEQUENCES ARISING FUOM THE NATURE OF THE CIVIL UNION.

A. Right of the Supreme Power. Treason ; Dethronement ;

Revolution ; Reform, ..... 174

B. Land Rights. Secular and Church Lands. Rights of

Taxation ; Finance ; Police ; Inspection, . . 182

C. Relief of the Poor. Foundling Hospitals. The Church, 186

D. The Right of assigning Offices and Dignities in the

State, 190

E. The Right of Punishing and of Pardoning, . . 194

50. Constitutional Relations of the Citizen to his Country and to

other Countries. Emigration ; Immigration ; Banish ment ; Exile, ...... 205

51. The Three Forms of the State. Autocracy ; Aristocracy ;

Democracy, ....... 206

52. Historical Origin and Changes. A Pure Republic. Repre

sentative Government, ..... 208

II. THE RIGHT OF NATIONS AND INTERNATIONAL LAW.

53. Nature and Division of the Right of Nations, . .213 f,4. The -Elements of the Right of Nations, . . .214

1 ;:.-{ht of going to War as related to the Subjects of the State, 215 lit of going to War in relation to Hostile States, . . 218

xx xvi CONTENTS.

57. Right during War, ... . '219

58. Right after War, ...... 221

f>9. The Rights of Peace, ...... 222

HO. Right as against an unjust Enemy, .... 223

61. Perpetual Peace and a Permanent Congress of Nations, . 224

III. THE UNIVERSAL RIGHT OF MANKIND.

62. Nature and Conditions of Cosmopolitical Right, . . 226 CONCLUSION, ....... 229

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PETNCIPLES OF EIGHT.

OCCASION AND OBJECT OF THESE SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS.

Objection as to the Faculty of Desire, .... 234

I. Logical Preparation for the preceding Conception of Right, 235 II. Justification of the Conception of a Personal Right of a

Real Kind, 237

III. Examples of Real-Personal Right, . . . .238

IV. Confusion of Real and Personal Right, . . . 241 V. Addition to the Explanation of the Conception of Penal

Right, ....... 243

VI. On the Right of Usucapion, .... 245

VII. On Inheritance and Succession, .... 247

VIII. The Right of the State in relation to Perpetual Founda tions for the benefit of the Subjects, . . . 249

A. Hospitals, ...... 250

B. Churches, ...... 251

C. The Orders in the State, .... 253

D. Primogeniture and Entail, .... 254 IX. Concluding Remarks on Public Right and Absolute Submis sion to the Sovereign Authority, .... 255

APOLOGIA.

Kant's Vindication of his Philosophical Style, . . . 259

THE METAPHYSICAL PRINCIPLES

OF

THE SCIENCE OF EIGHT

AS CONTAINED IN

THE METAPHYSK; OF MORALS.

BY

IMMANUEL KANT.

2Translatft» from tfjc (German.

PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS.

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS, as constituting the System of Practical Philosophy, was to follow the ' Critique of the Practical Reason,' as it now does. It falls into two parts: (1) THE METAPHYSICAL PRINCIPLES OF JURIS PRUDENCE AS THE SCIENCE OF EIGHT, and (2) THE META PHYSICAL PRINCIPLES OF ETHICS AS THE SCIENCE OF VIRTUE. The whole System forms a counterpart to the ' Metaphysical Principles of the Science of Nature/ which have been already discussed in a separate work (1786). The General Introduction to the ' Metaphysic of Morals ' bears mainly on its form in both the Divisions ; and the Definitions and Explanations it contains exhibit and, to some extent, illustrate the formal Principles of the whole System.

THE SCIENCE OF PtiGHT as a philosophical exposition of the fundamental Principles of Jurisprudence, thus forms the First Part of the Metaphysic of Morals. Taken here by itself apart from the special Principles of Ethics as the Science of Virtue which follows it it has to be

4 KANT'S PREFATORY EXPLANATIONS.

treated as a System of Principles that originate in Reason ; and, as such, it might be properly designated ' The Meta- physic of Right' But the conception of Right, purely rational in its origin though it be, is also applicable to cases presented in experience ; and, consequently, a Metaphysical System of Rights must take into considera tion the empirical variety and manifoldness of these cases in order that its Divisions may be complete. For com pleteness and comprehensiveness are essential and indis pensable to the formation of a rational system. But, on the other hand, it is impossible to obtain a complete survey of all the details of experience, and where it may be attempted to approach this, the empirical conceptions embracing those details cannot form integral elements of the system itself, but can only be introduced in subordinate observations, and mainly as furnishing examples illustrative of the General Principles. The only appropriate designa tion for the First Part of a Metaphysic of Morals, will, therefore, be THE METAPHYSICAL PRINCIPLES OF THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT. And, in regard to the practical appli cation to cases, it is manifest that only an approximation to systematic treatment is to be expected, and not the attainment of a System complete in itself. Hence the same method of exposition will be adopted here as was followed in the former work on ' The Metaphysical Prin ciples of the Science of Nature.' The Principles of Right which belong to the rational system will form the leading

M'S I'UEFATOllY EXPLANATIONS. 5

portions of the text, and details connected with Eights which refer to particular cases of experience, will be appended occasionally in subordinate remarks. In this way a distinction will be clearly made between what is a Metaphysical or rational Principle, and what refers to the empirical Practice of Plight

Towards the end of the work, I have treated several sections with less fulness of detail than might have been expected when they are compared with what precedes them. But this has been intentionally done, partly because it appears to me that the more general principles of the later subjects may be easily deduced from what has gone before; and, also, partly because the details of the Principles of Public Plight are at present subjected to so much discussion, and are besides so important in them selves, that they may well justify delay, for a time, of a final and decisive judgment regarding them.

PROLEGOMENA. GENERAL INTRODUCTION

TO

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS.

GENERAL INTRODUCTION TO THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS.

THE RELATION OF THE FACULTIES OF THE HUMAN MIND TO THE MORAL LAWS.

The Practical Faculty of Action. THE ACTIVE FACULTY OF THE HUMAN MIND, as the Faculty of Desire in its widest sense, is the Power which man has, through his mental representations, of becoming the cause of objects corre sponding to these representations. The capacity of a IJeing to act in conformity with his own representations,4' is what constitutes the Life of such a Being.

The Feeling of Pleasure or Pain. It is to be observed, first, that with Desire or Aversion there is always con nected PLEASURE or PAIN, the susceptibility for which is called FEELING. But the converse does not always hold. For there may be a Pleasure connected, not with the desire of an object, but with a mere mental represen tation, it being indifferent whether an object correspond ing to the representation exist or not And, second, the -ure or Pain connected with the object of desire not always precede the activity of Desire ; nor can it be regarded in every case as the cause, but it may .'•11 be the Effect of that activity. The capacity periencing Pleasure or Pain on the occasion of u

10 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

mental representation, is called ' Feeling,' because Plea sure and Pain contain only what is subjective in the relations of our mental activity. They do not involve any relation to an object that could possibly furnish a knowledge of it as such; they cannot even give us a knowledge of our own mental state. For even Sensa tions,1 considered apart from the qualities which attach to them on account of the modifications of the Subject, as, for instance, in reference to Eed, Sweet, and such like, are referred as constituent elements of knowledge to Objects, whereas Pleasure or Pain felt in connection with what is red or sweet, express absolutely nothing that is in the Object, but merely a relation to the Subject. And for the reason just stated, Pleasure and Pain con sidered in themselves cannot be more precisely defined. All that can be further done with regard to them is merely to point out what consequences they may have in certain relations, in order to make the knowledge of them available practically.

1 The Sensibility as the Faculty of Sense, may be defined by reference to the subjective Nature of our Representations generally. It is the Under standing that first refers the subjective Representations to an object ; it alone thinks anything by means of these Representations. Now, the subjec tive nature of our Representations might be of such a kind that they could be related to Objects so as to furnish knowledge of them, either in regard to their Form or Matter in the former relation by pure Perception, in the latter by Sensation proper. In this case the Sense-faculty, as the capacity for receiving objective Representations, would be properly called Sense-perception. But mere mental Representation from its subjective nature cannot, in fact, become a constituent of objective knowledge, because it contains merely the relation of the Representations to the Subject, and includes nothing that can be used for attaining a knowledge of the object. In this case, then, this receptivity of the Mind for sub jective representations is called FEELING. It includes the effect of the Representations, whether sensible or intellectual, upon the Subject ; and it belongs to the Sensibility, although the Representation itself may belong to the Understanding or the Reason.

THE MKTAPIIYSIC OF MORALS. 11

Practical Pleasure, Interest, Inclination. The Pleasure, which is necessarily connected with the activity of Desire, when the representation of the object desired affects the rapacity of Feeling, may be called Prcictical Pleasure. And this designation is applicable whether the Measure is the cause or the effect of the Desire. On the other hand, that Pleasure which is not necessarily connected with the Desire of an object, and which, therefore, is not a pleasure in the existence of the object, but is merely attached to a mental representation alone, may be called Inactive Complacency, or mere Contemplative Pleasure. The Feeling of this latter kind of Pleasure, is what is called Taste. Hence, in a System of Practical Philosophy, the Contemplative Pleasure of Taste will not be discussed as an essential constituent conception, but need only be referred to incidentally or episodically. But as regards Practical Pleasure^ it is otherwise. For the determina- t ion of the activity of the Faculty of Desire or Appe tency, which is necessarily preceded by this Pleasure as its cause, is what properly constitutes DESIRE inf the strict sense of the term. PfaBitual Desire, again, and the connection of Plea

sure with the activity of Desire, in so far as this

roiinection is judged by the Understanding to be

valid according to a general Rule holding good at

for the individual, is what is called Interest.

Hence, in such a case, the Practical^ Pleasure is an

est of the. Inclination of the individual. On

other hand, if the Pleasure can only follow a pre

ceding determination of the Faculty of Desire, it is an

Intellectual Pleasure, and the interest in the object must

II 1 a "rational Interest; for were the Interest

lous, and not based only upon pure Principles of

1 2 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Eeason, Sensation would necessarily be conjoined with the Pleasure, and would thus determine the activity of the Desire. Where an entirely pure Interest of Eeason must be assumed, it is not legitimate to introduce into it an Interest of Inclination surreptitiously. However, in order to conform so far with the common phraseology, we may allow the application of the term ' Inclination ' even to that which can only be the object of an ' Intel- J lectual ' Pleasure in the sense of a habitual Desire , arising from a pure Interest of Eeason. But such | Inclination would have to be viewed, not as the Cause, I but as the Effect of the rational Interest ; and we might call it the non- sensuous or RATIONAL INCLINATION (pro- pensio intellectualis). Further, Concupiscence is to be dis tinguished from the activity of Desire itself, as a stimulus or incitement to its determination. It is always a sen- vsuous state of the mind, which does not itself attain to the definiteness of an act of the Power of Desire.

The Will generally as Practical Reason. The activity of the Faculty of Desire may proceed in accordance with Conceptions ; and in so far as the Principle thus deter mining it to action is found in the mind, and not in its object, it constitutes a Power of acting or not acting according to liking. In so far as the activity is accom panied with the Consciousness of the Power of the action to produce the Object, it forms an act of Choice ; if this consciousness is not conjoined with it, the Activity is called a Wish. The Faculty of Desire, in so far as its inner Principle of determination as the ground ' of its liking or Predilection lies in the Eeason of the Subject, constitutes THE WILL. The Will is therefore the Faculty of active Desire or Appetency, viewed not so much in relation to the action which is the relation

THE METAI'HYSIC OF MORALS. 13

of the act of Choice as rather in relation to the Principle that determines the power of Choice to the action. It has, in itself, properly no special Principle of determina tion, but in so far as it may determine the voluntary act of Choice, it is THE PRACTICAL REASON ITSELF.

The Will as the Faculty of Practical Principles. _ Under the Will, taken generally, may be included the volitional act of Choice, and also the mere act of Wish, in so far as Reason may determine the Faculty of Desire in its activity. The act of Choice that can be determined by pure Reason, constitutes the act of Free-will. That act which is determinable only by Inclination as a sensuous impulse or stimulus would be irrational brute Choice (arbitrium brufatm). The human act of Choice, however, as human, is in fact affected by such impulses orV stimuli, but is not determined by them ; and it is, there- fore, not pure in itself when taken apart from the acquired habit of determination by Reason. But it may be determined to action by the pure Will. The Freedom of the act of volitional Choice, is its independence of being determined by sensuous impulses or stimuli. This forms the negative conception of the Free-will. The

/ ^jOoncepficrot freedom is given by the fact that tin- Will is the capability of Pure Reason to be practical of itself. But this is not possible otherwise than by the M .im of every action being subjected to the condition of being practicable as a universal Law. Applied as Purr Reason to the act of Choice, and considered aparl from its objects, it may be regarded as the Faculty of and, in this connection, it is the source of

.

Piif ticil Principles. Hencejt isjtp be viewed as a law-;4 giving Faculty. But as the material upon which to ' ruct a~Taw is not furnished to it, it can only make

14 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Vthe/orw of the Maxim of the act of Will, in so far as it is available as a universal Law, the supreme Law and I ; determining Principle of the Will. And as the Maxims, or Rules of human action derived from subjective causes, 'do not of themselves necessarily agree with those that ^are objective and universal, Eeason can only prescribe ithis supreme Law as an absolute Imperative of prohibi tion or command.

The Laws of Freedom as Moral, Juridical, and Ethical.— The Laws of Freedom, as distinguished from the Laws of Nature, are moral Laws. So far as they refer only to external actions and their lawfulness, they are called Juridical ; but if they also require that, as Laws, they £ shalT themselves be the determining Principles of our Q actions, -they are Ethical. The agreement of an action with Juridical Laws, is its Legality ; the agreement of / an action with Ethical Laws, is its Morality. The Free- a dom to which the former laws refer, can only be Freedom in external practice ; but the Freedom to which the / latter laws refer, is Freedom in the internal as^ well as the external exercise of the activity of the Will in so far as it is determined by Laws of Reason. So, in Theoretical Philosophy, it is said that only the objects of the external senses are in Space, but all the objects both of internal and external sense are in Time ; because the representations of both, as being representations, so far belong all to the internal sense. In like manner, whether Freedom is viewed in reference to the external or the internal action of the Will, its Laws, as pure practical Laws of Reason for the free activity of the Will generally, must at the same time be inner Prin ciples for its determination, although they may not always be considered in this relation.

THE METAPHYSIC OF MOKALS. 15

II.

THE IDEA AND NECESSITY OF A METAPHYSIC OF MORALS.

The Laws of Nature Rational and also Empirical. It has been shown in The Metaphysical Principles of the Science of Nature, that there must be Principles ft priori ^ for the Natural Science that has to deal with the objects i»i the external senses. And it was further shown that it is possible, and even necessary, to formulate a System of these Principles under the name of a ' Metaphysical Srjfuce of Nature/ as a preliminary to Experimental Physics regarded as Natural Science applied to particular objects of experience] But this latter Science, if care be taken to keep its generalizations free from error, may accept many propositions as universal on the evidence of »• \j.< -Hence, although if the term ' Universal ' be taken in its strict sense, these would necessarily have to be deduced by the Metaphysical Science from Principles a priori. Thus Newton accepted the principle of the K«(uality of Action and Reaction as established by ex- ^ perience, and yet he extended it as a universal Law

the whole of material Nature. The Chemists go even farther, grounding their most general Laws regard ing the combination and decomposition of the materials of bodies wholly upon experience ; and yet they trust so completely to the Universality and Necessity of those laws, that they have no anxiety as to any error being found in propositions founded upon experiments conducted in an ,>]•< hmoe with them.

Moral Laws a priori and Necessary. But it is other-

with Moral Laws. These, in contradistinction to Natural Laws, are only valid as Laws, in so far as they

1 6 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

can be rationally established & priori and comprehended as necessary. In fact, conceptions and judgments regard ing ourselves and our conduct have no moral significance, if they contain only what may be learned from experi ence ; and when any one is, so to speak, misled into making a Moral Principle out of anything derived from this latter source, he is already in danger of falling into the coarsest and most fatal errors.

If the Philosophy of Morals were nothing more than a Theory of Happiness (Eudwmonism), it would be absurd to search after Principles a priori as a foundation for it. For however plausible it may sound to say that lieason, even prior to experience, can comprehend by what means we may attain to a lasting enjoyment of the real pleasures of life, yet all that is taught on this subject a priori is either tautological, or is assumed wholly without foundation. It is only Experience that can show what will bring us enjoyment. The natural im pulses directed towards nourishment, the sexual instinct, or the tendency to rest and motion, as well as the higher desires of honour, the acquisition of knowledge, and such like, as developed with our natural capacities, are alone capable of showing in what those enjoyments are to be found. And, further, the knowledge thus acquired, is available for each individual merely in his own way ; and it is only thus he can learn the means by which he has to seek those enjoyments. All specious rationalizing <:> priori, in this connection, is nothing at bottom but carrying facts of Experience up to generalizations by induction (secundum principia yeneralia non univcrsalia) ; and the generality thus attained is still so limited that numberless exceptions must be allowed to every indi vidual in order that he may adapt the choice of his

THE METAPIIYSIC OF MORALS. 17

«• of life to his own particular inclinations and his rapacity for pleasure. And, after all, the individual

really to acquire his Prudence at the cost of his own suffering or that of his neighbours.

But it is quite otherwise with the Principles oft- Morality. They lay down Commands for every one without regard to his particular inclinations, and merely because and so far as he is free, and has a practical Reason. Instruction in the Laws of Morality is not drawn from observation of oneself or of our animal nature, nor from perception of the course of the world in regard to what happens, or how men act.1 But Reason commands howjve_ ought to act, even although no example of such action were to be found ; nor does Reason give any regard to the Advantage which mayi/ accrue to us by so acting, and which Experience could alone actually show. For, although Reason allows us to seek what is for our advantage^m" every possible way, and although, founding upon the evidence of Experience, it may further promise that greater advantages will probably follow on the average from the observance of her commands than from their transgression, especially if Prudence guides the conduct, yet the authority of her precepts as Commands does not rest on such considerations. They are used by

•>n only as Counsels, and by way of a counterpoise a - a i nst seductions lo ~an opposite course, when adjusting beforehand the equilibrium of a partial balance in the sphere of Practical Judgment, in order thereby to secure tin- decision of this Judgment, according to the due weight

>• a priori Principles of a pure Practical Reason.

1 This holds notwithstanding the fart that the term 'Morals,' in Latin and in German Sitten, signifies originally only Manners or Mode '

B

18 KAXT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

The Necessity of a Metaphysic of Morals. 'META PHYSICS' designates any System of Knowledge a priori that consists of pure Conceptions. Accordingly a Practical Philosophy not having Nature, but the Free dom of the Will for its object, will presuppose and require a Metaphysic of Morals. It is even a Duty to have such a Metaphysic ; and every man does, indeed, possess it in himself, although commonly but in an obscure way. For how could any one believe that he has a source of universal Law in himself, without Prin ciples a priori ? And just as in a Metaphysic of Nature there must be principles regulating the application of the universal supreme Principles of Nature to objects of Experience, so there cannot but be such principles in the Metaphysic of Morals; and we will often have to deal objectively with the particular nature of man as known only by Experience, in order to show in it the conse quences of these universal Moral Principles. But this mode of dealing with these Principles in their particular applications will in no way detract from their rational purity, or throw doubt on their a priori origin. In other words, this amounts to saying that a Metaphysic of Morals cannot be founded on Anthropology as the Empirical Science of Man, but may be applied to it.

Moral Anthropology. The counterpart of a Metaphysic of Morals, and the other member of the Division of Practical Philosophy, would be a Moral Anthropology, as the Empirical Science of the Moral Nature of Man. This Science would contain only the subjective conditions that hinder or favour the realization in practice of the universal moral Laws in human Nature, with the means of propagating, spreading, and strengthening the Moral Principles, as by the Education of the young and the

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 19

instruction of the people,— and all other such doctrines and precepts founded upon experience and indispensable in themselves, although they must neither precede the metaphysical investigation of the Principles of Reason, nor be mixed up with it. For, by doing so, there would be a great danger of laying down false, or at least very flexible Moral Laws, which would hold forth as unattain able what is not attained only because the Law has not bet -n comprehended and presented in its purity, in which also its strength consists. Or, otherwise, spurious and mixed motives might be adopted instead of what is dutiful and good in itself; and these would furnish no certain Moral Principles either for the guidance of the Judgment or for the discipline -of the heart in the pni.-tice of Duty. It is only by Pure Reason, therefore, that Duty can and must be prescribed.

Practical Philosophy in relation to Art. The higher Division of Philosophy, under which the Division just mentioned stands, is into Theoretical Philosophy and Pruetical Philosophy. Practical Philosophy is just Moral Philosophy in its widest sense, as has been explained ..here.1 All that is practicable and possible, accord ing to Natural Laws, is the special subject of the activity i , and its precepts and rules entirely depend on the ry of Nature. It is only what is practicable accord ing to Laws of Freedom that can have Principles in dependent of Theory, for there is no Theory in relation ty what passes beyond the determinations of Nature. Philosophy therefore cannot embrace under its practical ion a technical Theory, but only a morally practical Doctrine. But if the dexterity of the Will in acting according to Laws of Freedom, in contradistinction to

1 In the Critique of the Judgment (1790).

20 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Nature, were to be also called an Art, it would neces sarily indicate an Art which would make a System of Freedom possible like the System of Nature. This would truly be a Divine Art, if we were in a position by means of it to realize completely what Reason prescribes to us, and to put the Idea into practice.

III. THE DIVISION OF A METAPHYSIC OF MORALS.

Two Elements involved in all Legislation. All Legis lation, whether relating to internal or external action, and whether prescribed a priori by mere Eeason or laid down by the Will of another, involves two Elements : 1st, a LAW which represents the action that ought to happen as necessary objectively, thus making the action a Duty; 2nd, a MOTIVE which connects the principle determining the Will to this action with the Mental repre sentation of the Law subjectively, so that the Law makes Duty the motive of the Action. By the first element, the action is represented as a Duty, in accordance with the mere theoretical knowledge of the possibility of determining the activity of the Will by practical Rules. By the second element, the Obligation so to act, is connected in the Subject with a determining Principle of the Will as such.

Division of Duties into Juridical and Ethical. All Legislation, therefore, may be differentiated by reference to its Motive -principle.1 The Legislation which niako

1 This ground of Division will apply, although the action which it makes a duty may coincide with another action, that may be otherwise looked at from another point of view. For instance, Actions may in all cases be classified as external.

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 21

an Action a Duty, and this Duty at the same time a Motive, is ethical. That Legislation which does not include the Motive - principle in the Law, and conse- 4iu'iitly admits another Motive than the idea of Duty itself, is juridical. In respect of the latter, it is evident that the motives distinct from the idea of Duty, to which it may refer, must be drawn from the subjective (pathological) influences of Inclination and of Aversion, <lctcrmining the voluntary activity, and especially from the latter; because it is a Legislation which has to be compulsory, and not merely a mode of attracting or persuading. The agreement or non-agreement of an ad ion with the Law, without reference to its Motive, is its Legality; and that character of the action in whicli the idea of Duty arising from the Law, at the same time forms the Motive of the Action, is its Morality.

Duties specially in accord with a Juridical Legislation, can only be external Duties. For this mode of Legisla tion does not require that the idea of the Duty, which is internal, shall be of itself the determining Principle of the act of Will ; and as it requires a motive suitable to the nature of its laws, it can only connect what is external with the Law. Ethical Legislation, on the other hand, makes internal actions also Duties, but not to the exclusion of the external, for it embraces everything which is of the nature of Duty. And ,ju>t because ethical Legislation includes within its Law the internal motive of the action as contained in the idea of Duty, it involves a characteristic which cannot at all enter into the Legislation that is external. Hence, Ethical Legislation cannot as such be external, not even when proceeding from a Divine Will, although

22 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

it may receive Duties which rest on an external Legis lation as Duties, into the position of motives, within its own Legislation.

Jurisprudence and Ethics distinguished. From what has heen said, it is evident that all Duties, merely because they are duties, belong to Ethics ; and yet the Legislation upon which they are founded is not on that account in all cases contained in Ethics. On the con trary, the Law of many of them lies outside of Ethics. Thus Ethics commands that I must fulfil a promise entered into by Contract, although the other party might not be able to compel me to do so. It adopts the Law ' pacta sunt serranda,' and the Duty corresponding to it, from Jurisprudence or the Science of Right, by which they are established. It is not in Ethics, therefore, but

Jurisprudence, that the principle of the Legislation lies, that 'promises made and accepted must be kept.' Accordingly, Ethics specially teaches that if the Motive- principle of external compulsion which Juridical Legis lation connects with a Duty is even let go, the idea of Duty alone is sufficient of itself as a Motive. For were it not so, and were the Legislation itself not juridical, and consequently the Duty arising from it not specially a Duty of Right as distinguished from a Duty of Virtue, then Fidelity in the performance of acts, to whicrP'the individual may be bound by the terms of a Contract, would have to be classified with acts of Benevolence and the Obligation that underlies them, which cannot be correct. To keep one's promise is not properly a Duty of Virtue, but a Duty of Right ; and the performance of it can be enforced by external Compulsion. But to keep one's promise, even when no Compulsion can be applied to enforce it, is, at the same time; a virtuous

THE METAPIIYSIC OF MORALS. 23

action, and a proof of Virtue. Jurisprudence as the Scienceof Right, and Ethics as the "Science of Virtue, are therefore distinguished not so much by their different Duties, as rather by the difference of the Legislation which connects the one or the other kind of motive with their Laws.

EthicalJ.egislation is that which cannot be external, although the Duties it prescribes may be external as well as internal. Juridical Legislation is that which may also be external Thus it is an external duty to keep a promise entered into by Contract ; but the injunction to do this merely because it is a duty, without regard to any other motive, belongs exclusively to the internal Legislation. It does not belong thus to the ethical sphere as being a particular kind of duty or a particular mode of action to which we are bound, for it is an external duty in Ethics as well as in Juris prudence, but it is because the Legislation in thi* case referred to is internal, and cannot have an external Lawgiver, that the Obligation is reckoned as belonging to Ethics. For the same reason, the Duties of Benevo lence, although they are external Duties as Obligations to external actions, are, in like manner, reckoned as belonging to Ethics, because they can only be enjoined by Legislation that is internal. Ethics has no doubt its own peculiar Duties, such as those towards oneself, but it has also Duties in common with Jurisprudence, only not under the same mode of OlUyation. In short, the peculiarity of Ethical Legislation is to enjoin the performance of certain actions merely because they are! Duties, and to make the Principle of Duty itself what-/ ever be its source or occasion the sole sufficing motive of the activity of the Will. Thus, then, there are many

24 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

ethical Duties that are directly such; and the inner Legislation also makes the others— all and each of them indirectly Ethical.

The Deduction of the division of a System is the proof of its completeness as well as of its continuity, so that there may be a logical transition from the general conception divided to the members of the Division, and through the whole series of the sub divisions without any break or leap in the arrange ment (divisio per saltum). Such a Division is one of the most difficult conditions for the architect of a System to fulfil. There is even some doubt as to what is the highest Conception that is primarily divided into Right and Wrong (aut fas aut nefas). 1 1 is assuredly the conception of the activity of the yFree-will in general. In like manner, the expounders of Ontology start from 'Something' and 'Nothing' without perceiving that these are already members of a Division for which the highest divided conception is awanting, and which can be no other than that of ' Thing ' in general.

GENERAL DIVISIONS OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS.

I.

DIVISION OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS AS A SYSTEM OF DUTIES GENERALLY.

1. All Duties are either Duties of Right, that is, JURIDICAL DUTIES (Officia Juris}, or Duties of Virtue, that is, ETHICAL DUTIES (Officia Virtutis s. ethica). Juridical Duties are such as may be promulgated by external Legislation ; Ethical Duties are those for which

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 25

such legislation is not possible. The reason why the latter cannot be properly made the subject of external^ Legislation is because they relate to an End or final pur pose, which is itself, at the same time, embraced in these Duties, and which it is a Duty for the individual to have as such. But no external Legislation can cause any one to adopt a particular intention, or to propose to himself a certain purpose ; for this depends upon an internal condition or act of the mind itself. However, external actions conducive to such a mental condition may be commanded, without its being implied that the individual will of necessity make them an End to himself.

But why, then, it may be asked, is the Science of Morals or Moral Philosophy, commonly entitled— especially by Cicero the Science of Duty and not also the Science of Right, since Duties and Eights refer to each other ? The reason is this. We know our own Freedom from which all Moral Laws and consequently all Rights as well as all Duties arise 011ly through the Moral Imperative, which is an immediate injunction of Duty; whereas tne,. conception of Right as a ground of putting others* under Obligation has afterwards to be developed out of it.

2. In the Doctrine of Duty, Man may and ought to be represented in accordance with the nature of his faculty of Freedom, which is entirely supra-sensible. He is, therefore, to be represented purely according to his Humanity as a Personality independent of physical determinations (homo noumcnori), in distinction from the same person as a Man modified with these determina tions (homo phenomenon). Hence the conceptions of IJi-ht and End when referred to Duty, in view of this twofold quality, give the following Division:

26

KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

DIVISION OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS ACCORDING TO THE OBJECTIVE RELATION OF THE LAW TO DUTY I. THE RIGHT OF HUMANITY in our own Person

I. JURIDICAL) , °XESELF

DUTIES l

to

II. ETHICAL

OTHERS.

OTHERS.

(Juridical Duties towards Oneself).

II. THE RIGHT OF MANKIND in Others (Juridical Duties towards Others).

rill. THE END OF HUMANITY in our Person (Ethical Duties towards Oneself).

IV. THE END OF MANKIND in Others (Ethical Duties towards Others).

II.

DIVISION OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS ACCORDING TO

RELATIONS OF OBLIGATION.

As the Subjects between whom a relation of Ei«ht Duty is apprehended— whether it actually exist°or -admit of being conceived in various juridical itions to each other, another Division may be pro posed from this point of view, as follows :—

,»:::•' s:1";:;;;- T " '• '- "i"-"™- »~* , „„.

sasSs&S* A*" *•""'••'

be put under Obligation by them.

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 27

3. 4.

The juridical Relation of Man The juridical Relation of Man

to Beings who have only Duties to a Being who has only Rights

and no Rights. and no Duties (Goo).

VACAT. There is no such Re- VACAT. There is no such Re lation. For such Beings would lation in mere Philosophy, because be Men without juridical Person- such a Being is not an object of ality, as Slaves or Bondsmen. possible experience.

A real relation between Right and Duty is therefore found, in this scheme, only in No. 2. The reason why such is not likewise found in No. 4 is, because it would constitute a transcendent Duty, that is, one to which no corresponding subject can be given that is external and capable of imposing Obligation. Consequently the Rela tion from the theoretical point of view is here merely ideal ; that is, it is a Relation to an object of thought which we form for ourselves. But the conception of this , object is not entirely empty. On the contrary, it is a | fruitful conception in relation to ourselves and the maxims of our inner morality, and therefore in relation : to practice generally. And it is in this bearing, that all V the Duty involved and practicable for us in such a merely ideal relation lies.

III.

DIVISION OF THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS.

AS A SYSTEM OF DUTIES GENERALLY. According to the constituent Principles and the Method of the System.

I. PRINCIPLES,/ I.Duru.o'B.onT, },£ gggagp

( II. DUTIES OF VIRTUE, ETC. And so on, in cluding all that refers not only to the Materials, but also to the Architectonic Form of a scientific system of Morals, when the Meta physical investigation of the ele ments has completely traced out the Universal Principles consti tuting the whole.

II. METHOD,

28 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

IV.

GENERAL PKELIMINARY CONCEPTIONS DEFINED AND EXPLAINED.

(Philosophia practica universalis.)

Freedom. Tlie conception of FREEDOM is a conception of pure Eeason. It is therefore transcendent in so far as regards Theoretical Philosophy ; for it is a conception tor which no corresponding instance or example can be found or supplied in any possible experience. Accord ingly Freedom is not presented as an object of any theoretical knowledge that is possible for us. It is in no respect a constitutive, but only a regulative con ception ; and it can be accepted by the Speculative Reason as at most a merely negative Principle. In the practical sphere of Eeason, however, the reality of Freedom may be demonstrated by certain Practical Principles which, as Laws, prove a causality jof___the I'1'-'''1 Keuson in the process of di'tmnining the activity oitneWill, that is independent of all empirical and sensible conditions. And thus there is established the f fact of a pure Will existing in us as the source of all ; moral conceptions and laws.

Moral Laws and Categorical Imperatives. On this positive conception of Freedom in the practical relation certain unconditional practical Laws are founded, and they specially constitute MOBAL LAWS. In relation to us as human beings, with an activity of Will modified by sensible influences so as not to be conformable to the pure Will, but as often contrary to it, these Laws appear us IMPERATIVES commanding or prohibiting certain

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 2$

actions ; and as such they are CATEGORICAL or UNCON DITIONAL IMPERATIVES. Their categorical and uncon ditional character distinguishes them from the Technical Imperatives which express the prescriptions of Art, and which always command only conditionally. According to these Categorical Imperatives, certain actions arc allowed or disallwved as being morally possible or im possible ; and certain of them or their opposites are morally necessary and obligatory. Hence, in reference, to such actions, there arises the conception of a Duty whose observance or transgression is accompanied with a Pleasure or Pain of a peculiar kind, known as Moral reeling. We do not, however, take the Moral Feelings or Sentiments into account, in considering the practical Laws of Reason. For they do not form the foundation or principle of practical Laws of Reason, but only the sub jective Effects that arise in the mind on the occasion of our voluntary activity being determined by these Laws. And while they neither add to nor take from the objec tive validity or influence of the moral Laws in the judg ment of Reason, such Sentiments may vary according to the differences of the individuals who experience them.

The following Conceptions are common to Jurisprudence and Ethics as the two main Divisions of the Meta- physic of Morals.

Obligation. OIJLIGATION is the Necessity of a free Action when viewed in relation to a Categorical Impera tive of Reason.

An IMPERATIVE is a practical Rule by which an Action, otherwise contingent in itself, is made neces sary. It is distinguished from a practical Law, in

30 KAXT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

that such a Law, while likewise representing the Action as necessary, does not consider whether it is internally necessary as involved in the nature of the Agent say as a holy Being or is contingent to him, as in the case of Man as we find him ; for, where the first condition holds good, there is in fact no Impera tive. Hence an Imperative is a Eule which not only represents but makes a subjectively contingent action necessary ; and it, accordingly, represents the Subject as being (morally) necessitated to act in accordance with this Eule. A Categorical or Unconditional Imperative is one which does not represent the action in any way mediately through the conception of an End that is to be attained by it ; but it presents the action to the mind as objectively necessary by the mere representation of its form as an action, and thus makes it necessary. Such Imperatives cannot be put forward by any other practical Science than that which prescribes Obligations, and it is only the Science of Morals that does this. All other Imperatives are technical, and they are altogether conditional. The ground of the possibility of Categorical Imperatives, lies in the fact that they refer to no determination of the activity of the Will by which a purpose mi^ht be assigned to it, but solely to its FREEDOM.

The Allowable.— Every Action is ALLOWED (licitum)

which is not contrary to Obligation ; and this Freedom

eing limited by an opposing Imperative, constitutes

i Moral Eight as a warrant or title of action (facultas

inoralis). From this it is at once evident what actions

are DISALLOWED or illicit (illicita).

Duty. Duty is the designation of any Action to i any one is bound by an obligation. It is there- the subject-matter of all Obligation. Duty as the Action concerned, may be one and the same yet we may be bound to it in various ways

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 31

The Categorical Imperative, as expressing an Obli gation in respect to certain actions, is a morally practical Law. But because Obligation involves not merely practical Necessity expressed in a Law as such, but also actual Nccessitation, the Categorical Impera tive is a Law either of Command or Prohibition, according as the doing or not doing of an action is represented as a Duty. An Action which is neither commanded nor forbidden, is merely allowed, because there is no Law restricting Freedom, nor any Duty in respect of it. Such an Action is said to be morally indifferent (indifferens, adiaphoron, res mercc facultatis). It may be asked whether there are such morally in different actions ; and if there are, whether in addition to the preceptive and prohibitive Law (lex prceccptiva ct prohibitiva, lex mandati et vetiti), there is also required a Permissive Law (lex permissiva), in order that one may be free in such relations to act, or to forbear from acting, at his pleasure ? If it were so, the moral Plight in question would not, in all cases, refer to actions that are indifferent in themselves (adiaphora) ; for no special Law would be required to establish such a liight, considered according to Moral Laws.

Act ; Agent. An Action is called an ACT or moral Deed in So far as it is subject to Laws of Obligation, and consequently in so far as the Subject of it is regarded with reference to the Freedom of his choice in the exercise of his Will. The AGENT as the actor or doer of the deed is regarded as, through the act, the Autlwr of its effect ; and this effect, along with the action itself, may be imputed to him, if he previously knew the Law, in virtue of which an Obligation rested upon him.

Person ; Imputation. A PERSON is a Subject who is capable of having his actions imputed to him. Moral Personality is, therefore, nothing but the Freedom of a

r

32 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

rational Being under Moral Laws ; and it is to be dis tinguished from psychological Freedom as the mere faculty by which we become conscious of ourselves in different states of the Identity of our existence. Hence it follows that a Person is properly subject to no other Laws than those he lays down for himself, either alone or in conjunction with others.

Thing. A THING is what is incapable of being the

subject of Imputation. Every object of the free activity of the Will, which is itself void of freedom, is there fore called a Thing (res corporealis).

Right and Wrong. RIGHT or WRONG applies, as a general quality, to an Act (rectum aut minus rectum), in so far as it is in accordance with Duty or contrary to Duty (factum licitum aut illicitum), no matter what may be the subject or origin of the Duty itself. An act that is contrary to Duty is called a Transgression (reatus).

Fault; Crime. An unintentional Transgression of a Duty, which is, nevertheless, imputable to a Person, is called a mere FAULT (culpa). An intentional Transgres sion that is, an act accompanied with the consciousness that it is a Transgression constitutes a CRIME (dolus).

Just and Unjust. Whatever is juridically in accord ance with External Laws, is said to be JUST (Jus, iustum}\ and whatever is not juridically in accordance with external Laws, is UNJUST (unjustum).

Collision of Duties. A COLLISION OF DUTIES OR OBLI- <;ATIOXS (collisio officiorum s. obliyationum} would be the result of such a relation between them that the one would annul the other, in whole or in part. Duty and Obligation, however, are conceptions which express the objective practical Necessity of certain actions, and two opposite Rules cannot be objective and necessary at

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 33

the same time ; for if it is a Duty to act according to one of them, it is not only no Duty to act according to an opposite Rule, but to do so would even be contrary to Duty. Hence a Collision of Duties and Obligations is entirely inconceivable (obligationes non colliduntur). There may, however, be two grounds of Obligation (rationes obligandi), connected with an individual under a Rule prescribed for himself, and yet neither the one nor the other may be sufficient to constitute an actual Obligation (rationes obliyandi non obligantes) ; and in that case the one of them is not a Duty. If two such grounds of Obligation are actually in collision with each other, Practical Philosophy does not say that the stronger Obligation is to keep the upper hand (fortior olligatio vincit), but that the stronger ground of Obligation is to maintain its place (fortior obligandi ratio vincit).

Natural and Positive Laws. Obligatory Laws for which an external Legislation is possible, are called generally External Laws. Those External Laws, the obligatoriness of which can be recognised by Eeason a priori even without an external Legislation, are called NATURAL LAWS. Those Laws, again, which are not obligatory without actual External Legislation, are called POSITIVE LAWS. An External Legislation, containing 'pure Natural Laws, is therefore conceivable ; but in that case a previous Natural Law must be presupposed to establish the authority of the Lawgiver by the Eight to subject others to Obligation through his own act of Will.

Maxims. The Principle which makes a certain action

> a Duty, is a Practical Law. The Eule of the Agent or

Actor, which he forms as a Principle for himself on sub-

'ective grounds, is called his MAXIM. Hence, even when

c

34 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

the Law is one and invariable, the Maxims of the Agent may yet be very different.

The Categorical Imperative. The Categorical Impera tive only expresses generally what constitutes Obligation. It may be rendered by the following Formula : ' Act according to a Maxim which can be adopted at the same, time as a Universal Law.' Actions must therefore be considered, in the first place, according to their subjective Principle; but whether this principle is also valid objectively, can only be known by the criterion of the Categorical Imperative. For lieason brings the principle or maxim of any action to the test, by calling upon the Agent to think of himself in connection with it as at the same time laying down a Universal Law, and to consider whether his action is so qualified as to be fit for entering into such a Universal Legislation.

The simplicity of this Law, in comparison with the

great and manifold Consequences which may be drawn

(from it, as well as its commanding authority and

supremacy without the accompaniment of any visible

' motive or sanction, must certainly at first appear very

, surprising. And we may well wonder at the power of

our Keason to determine the activity of the Will by the

mere idea of the qualification of a Maxim for the

universality of a practical Law, especially when we are

taught thereby that this practical Moral Law first reveals

a property of the Will which the Speculative Eeason

would never have come upon either by Principles a priori,

or from any experience whatever; and even if it had

ascertained the fact, it could never have theoretically

stablished its possibility. This practical Law, however,

>t only discovers the fact of that property of the Will,

which is FREEDOM, but irrefutably establishes it. Hence

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 35

it will be less surprising to find that the Moral Laws are uudenionstralle, and yet apodictic, like the mathe- \ matical Postulates ; and that they, at the same time, / open up before us a whole field of practical knowledge,/ from which Reason, on its theoretical side, must find itself entirely excluded with its speculative idea of Free dom and all such ideas of the Supersensible generally.

The conformity of an Action to the Law of Duty constitutes its Legality ; the conformity of the Maxim of the Action with the Law constitutes its Morality. A Maxim is thus a subjective Principle of Action, which the individual makes a Rule for himself as to how in fact he will act.

On the other hand, the Principle of Duty is what Reason absolutely, and therefore objectively and univer sally, lays down in the form of a Command to the individual, as to how he ought to act.

The SUPREME PKINCIPLE of the Science of Morals accordingly is this : ' Act according to a Maxim which can likewise be valid as a Universal Law.' Every Maxim which is not qualified according to this condition, is contrary to Morality.

Laws arise from the Will, viewed generally as Practical Reason ; Maxims spring from the activity of the Will in the process of Choice. The latter in Man, is what constitutes free-will. The Will which refers to nothing else than mere Law, can neither be called free nor not free ; because it does not relate to actions immediately, but to the giving of a Law for the Maxim of actions; it is therefore the Practical Reason itself. Hence as a Faculty, it is absolutely necessary in itself, and is not subject to any external necessita- tion. It is, therefore, only the act of Choice in the voluntary process, that can be called free.

:>,G EAST'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

The Freedom of the act of Will, however, is not to be defined as a Liberty of Indifference (libertas indi/er- N entice), that is, as a capacity of choosing to act for or against the Law. The voluntary process, indeed, viewed as a phenomenal appearance, gives many examples of this choosing in experience ; and some have accordingly so defined the free-will. For Freedom, as it is first I made knowable by the Moral Law, is known only as A A /a negative Property in us, as constituted by the fact of (not being necessitated to act by sensible principles of determination. Regarded as a noumenal reality, how ever, in reference to Man as a pure rational Intelli gence, the act of the Will cannot be at all theoretically exhibited ; nor can it therefore be explained how this power can act necessitatingly in relation to the sensible activity in the process of Choice, or consequently in what the positive quality of Freedom consists. Only thus much we can see into and comprehend, that although Man, as a Being belonging to the world of Sense, exhibits as experience shows a capacity of choosing not only conformably to the Law but also contrary to it, his Freedom as a rational Being belong ing to tlie world of Intelligence cannot be defined by reference merely to sensible appearances. For sensible phenomena cannot make a supersensible object such as free-will is intelligible ; nor can Freedom ever be ^ placed in the mere fact that the rMional^iljJect can make a choice in conflict with his own Lawgiving Keason, although experience may prove that it happens often enough, notwithstanding our inability to conceive how it is possible. For it is one thing to admit a proposition as based on experience, and another thing to make it the defining Principle and the universal differentiating mark of the act of free will, in its distinction from the arUtrium brutum s. urvum; because the empirical proposition does not assert that any particular characteristic necessarily belongs to the conception in question, but this is

THE METAPHYSIC OF MORALS. 37

requisite in the process of Definition. Freedom in / relation to the internal Legislation of Reason, can * alone be properly called a Power ; the possibility oi diverging from the Law thus given, is an incapacity or want of Power. How then can the former be defined by the latter ? It could only be by a Defini tion which would add to the practical conception of the free-will, its exercise as shown by experience; but this would be a hybrid Definition which would exhibit the conception in a false light.

Law; Legislator. A morally practical LAW is a pro position which contains a Categorical Imperative or Command. He who commands by a Law (imperans) is the Lawgiver or LEGISLATOR. He is the Author of the Obligation that accompanies the Law, but he is not always the Author of the Law itself. In the latter case, the Law would be positive, contingent, and arbitrary. The Law which is imposed upon us & priori and uncon ditionally by our own Reason, may also be expressed as proceeding from the Will of a Supreme Lawgiver or the Divine Will. Such a Will as Supreme can conse-y) quently have only Rights and not Duties ; and it only indicates the idea of a moral Being whose Will is Law for all, without conceiving of Him as the Author of that Will.

Imputation ; Judgment ; Judge. IMPUTATION, in the moral sense, is the Judgment by which any one is declared to be the Author or free Cause of an action which is then regarded as his moral fact or deed, and is subjected to Law. When the Judgment likewise lays down the juridical consequences of the Deed, it is judicial or valid (imputatio judiciaria s. valida) ; otherwise it would be only adjudicative or declaratory (imputatio dijudicatoria). That Person individual or collective

38 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

who is invested with the Eight to impute actions judicially, is called a JUDGE or a Court (judex s. forum).

Merit and Demerit. When any one does, in conformity with Duty, more than he can be compelled to do by the Law, it is said to be meritorious (meritum). What is done only in exact conformity with the Law, is what is due (debitum). And when less is done than can be demanded to be done by the Law, the result is moral Demerit (demeritum) or Culpability.

Punishment ; Reward. The juridical Effect or Con sequence of a culpable act of Demerit is PUNISHMENT (poena) ; that of a meritorious act is REWARD (prcemium), assuming that this Eeward was promised in the Law and that it formed the motive of the action. The coinci dence or exact conformity of conduct to what is due, has no juridical effect. Benevolent REMUNEEATION (remune- ratio s. repensio benefica) has no place in juridical Rela tions.

The good or bad Consequences arising from the performance of an obligated action as also the Con sequences arising from failing to perform a meritori ous action cannot be imputed to the Agent (modus imputationis tollens).

The good Consequences of a meritorious action as also the bad Consequences of a wrongful action may be imputed to the Agent (modus imputationis poneus).

The degree of the Imputalility of Actions is to be reckoned according to the magnitude of the hin drances or obstacles which it has been necessary for them to overcome. The greater the natural hin drances in the sphere of sense, and the less the moral hindrance of Duty, so much the more is a good Deed imputed as meritorious. This may be seen by con sidering such examples as rescuing a man who is an entire stranger from great distress, and at very consider-

THE METAPHYSIC OF MOIIALS. 39

able sacrifice. Conversely, the less the natural hin drance, and the greater the hindrance on the ground of Duty, so much the more is a Transgression imputable as culpable. Hence the state of mind of the Agent or Doer of a deed makes a difference in imputing its consequences, according as he did it in passion or performed it with coolness and deliberation.

INTRODUCTION

ro

THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT.

INTRODUCTION TO THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT.

GENERAL DEFINITIONS AND DIVISIONS.

A.

What the Science of Right is.

THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT has for its object the Principles of all the Laws which it is possible to promulgate by external legislation. Where there is such a legislation, it becomes in actual application to it, a system of positive Right and Law ; and he who is versed in the knowledge of this System is called a Jurist or Jurisconsult (juris- consultus). A practical Jurisconsult (jurisperitus), or a professional Lawyer, is one who is skilled in the know ledge of positive external Laws, and who can apply them to cases that may occur in experience. Such practical knowledge of positive Right, and Law, may be regarded as belonging to Jurisprudence, (Jurisprudentia) in the original sense of the term. But the theoretical knowledge of Right and Law in Principle, as distinguished from positive Laws and empirical cases, belongs to the pure SCIENCE OF RIGHT (Jurisscientia). The Science of Right thus designates the philosophical and systematic knowledge of the Principles of Natural Right. And it is from this Science that the

44 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

immutable Principles of all positive Legislation must be derived by practical Jurists and Lawgivers.

B. What is Right ?

This question may be said to be about as embarrassing to the Jurist as the well-known question, 'What is Truth ? ' is to the Logician. It is all the more so, if, on reflection, he strives to avoid tautology in his reply, and recognise the fact that a reference to what holds true merely of the laws of some one country at a particular time, is not a solution of the general problem thus proposed. It is quite easy to state what may be right in particular cases (quid sit juris), as being what the laws of a certain place and of a certain time say or may have said; but it is much more difficult to determine whether what they have enacted is right in itself, and to lay down a universal Criterion by which Right and Wrong in general, and what is just and unjust, may be recognised. All this may remain entirely hidden even from the practical Jurist until he abandon his empirical principles for a time, and search in the pure Reason for the sources of such judgments, in order to lay a real foundation for actual positive Legislation. In this search his empirical Laws may, indeed, furnish him with excellent guidance ; but a merely empirical system that is void of rational principles is, like the wooden head in the fable of Ph^drus, fine enough in appearance, but unfortunately it wants brain.

1. The conception of RIGHT, as referring to a corre sponding Obligation which is the moral aspect of it, in the first place, has regard only to the external and practical

INTRODUCTION TO THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT. 45

relation of one Person to another, in so far as they can have influence upon each other, immediately or mediately, by their Actions as facts. 2. In the second place, the conception of Eight does not indicate the relation of the action of an individual to the wish or the mere desire of another, as in acts of benevolence or of unkinduess, but only the relation of his free action to the freedom of action of the other. 3. And, in the third place, in this reciprocal relation of voluntary actions, the conception of Bight does not take into consideration the matter of the act of Will in so far as the end which any one may have in view in willing it, is concerned. In other words, it is not asked in a question of Ilight whether any one on buying goods for his own business realizes a profit by the transaction or not ; but only the form of the trans action is taken into account, in considering the relation of the mutual acts of Will. Acts of Will or voluntary Choice are thus regarded only in so far as they are free, and as to whether the action of one can harmonize with the Freedom of another, according to a universal Law.

EIGHT, therefore, comprehends the whole of the con ditions under which the voluntary actions of any one Person can be harmonized in reality with the voluntary actions of every other Person, according to a universal Law of Freedom.

C.

Universal Principle of Right.

' Every Action is right which in itself, or in the maxim on which it proceeds, is such that it can co-exist along with the Freedom of the Will of each and all in action, according to a universal Law.'

46 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

If, then, my action or my condition generally can co-exist with the freedom of every other, according to a universal Law, any one does me a wrong who hinders me in the performance of this action, or in the maintenance of this condition. For such a hindrance or obstruction cannot co-exist with Freedom according to universal Laws.

It follows also that it cannot be demanded as a matter of Right," that this universal Principle of all maxims shall itself be adopted as my maxim, that is, that I shall make it the maxim of my actions. For any one may be free, although his Freedom is entirely indifferent to me, or even if I wished in my heart to infringe it, so long as I do not actually violate that freedom by my external action. Ethics, however, as distinguished from Jurisprudence, /imposes upon me the obligation to make the fulfilment of Right a maxim of my conduct.

The universal Law of Right may then be expressed, thus : ' Act externally in such a manner that the free exercise of thy Will may be able to co-exist with the Freedom of all others, according to a universal Law.' This is undoubtedly a Law which imposes obligation upon me; but it does not at all imply and still less command that I ought, merely on account of this obliga tion, to limit my freedom to these very conditions. Reason in this connection says only that it is restricted thus far by its Idea, and may be likewise thus limited in fact by others; and it lays this down as a Postulate which is not capable of further proof. As the object in view is not to teach Virtue, but to explain what Right is, thus far the Law of Right, as thus laid down, may not and should not be represented as a motive-principle of action.

INTRODUCTION TO THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT. 47

D.

Right is conjoined with the Title or Authority to compel.

The resistance which is opposed to any hindrance of an effect, is in reality a furtherance of this effect, and is in accordance with its accomplishment. Now, everything that is wrong is a hindrance of freedom, according to universal Laws ; and Compulsion or Constraint of any kind is a hindrance or resistance made to Freedom. Con sequently, if a certain exercise of Freedom is itself a hindrance of the Freedom that is according to universal Laws, it is wrong ; and the compulsion or constraint which is opposed to it is right, as being a hindering of a hindrance of Freedom, and as being in accord with the Freedom which exists in accordance with universal Laws. Hence, according to the logical principle of Contradiction, all Right is accompanied with an implied Title or warrant to bring compulsion to bear on any one who may violate, it in fact.

E.

Strict Right may be also represented as the possibility of a universal reciprocal Compulsion in harmony with the Freedom of all according to universal Laws.

This proposition means that Plight is not to be regarded as composed of two different elements Obligation accord ing to a Law, and a Title on the part of one who has bound another by his own free choice, to compel him to perform. But it imports that the conception of Right may be viewed as consisting immediately in the possi bility of a universal reciprocal Compulsion, in harmony with the Freedom of all. As Right in general lias for its

48 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

object only what is external in actions, Strict Eight, as that with which nothing ethical is intermingled, requires no other motives of action than those that are merely external ; for it is then pure Eight, and is unmixed with any prescriptions of Virtue. A strict Eight, then, in the exact sense of the term, is that which alone can be called wholly external. Now such Eight is founded, no doubt, upon the consciousness of the Obligation of every indi vidual according to the Law ; but if it is to be pure as such, it neither may nor should refer to this conscious- ness as a motive by which to determine the free act of the Will. For this purpose, however, it founds upon the principle of the possibility of an external Compulsion, such as may co-exist with the freedom of every one according to universal Laws. Accordingly, then, where it is said that a Creditor has a right to demand from a Debtor the payment of his debt, this does not mean merely that he can bring him to feel in his mind that Eeason obliges him to do this ; but it means that he can apply an external compulsion to force any such one so to pay, and that this compulsion is quite consistent with the Freedom of all, including the parties in question, according to a universal Law. Eight and the Title to compel, thus indicate the same thing.

The Law of Eight, as thus enunciated, is repre sented as a reciprocal Compulsion necessarily in accordance with the Freedom of every one, under the principle of a universal Freedom. It is thus, as it were, a representative Construction of the conception of Eight, by exhibiting it in a pure intuitive percep tion d priori, after the analogy of the possibility of the free motions of bodies under the physical Law of the Equality of Action and Reaction. Now, as in pure Mathematics, we cannot deduce the properties of

INTRODUCTION TO THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT. 49

its objects immediately from a mere abstract concep tion, but can only discover them by figurative con struction or representation of its conceptions; so it is in like manner with the Principle of Right. It is not so much the mere formal Conception of Right, but rather that of a universal and equal reciprocal Compulsion as harmonizing with it, and reduced under general laws, that makes representation of that conception possible. But just as those conceptions presented in Dynamics are founded upon a merely formal representation of pure Mathematics as presented in Geometry, Reason has taken care also to provide the Understanding as far as possible with intuitive presentations & priori in behoof of a Construction of the conception of Right. The Right in geometrical lines (rectum) is opposed as the Straight to that which is Curved, and to that which is Oblique. In the first opposition there is involved an inner quality of the lines of such a nature that there is only one straight or right Line possible between two given points. In the second case, again, the positions of two intersect ing or meeting Lines are of such a nature that there can likewise be only one line called the Perpendicular, which is not more inclined to the one side than the other, and it divides space on either side into two equal parts. After the manner of this analogy, the Science of Right aims at determining what every one shall have as his ovm with mathematical exactness ; but this is not to be expected in the ethical Science of Virtue, as it cannot but allow a certain latitude for exceptions. But without passing into the sphere of Ethics, there are two cases known as the equivocal Right of Equity and Necessity which claim a juri dical decision, yet for which no one can be found to give such a decision, and which, as regards their relation to Rights, belong, as it were, to the ' Inter- mundia ' of Epicurus. These we must at the outset take apart from the special exposition of the Science

50 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

of Right, to which we are now about to advance ; and we may consider them now by way of supplement to these introductory Explanations, in order that their uncertain conditions may not exert a disturbing influ ence on the fixed Principles of the proper doctrine of Eight.

F.

Supplementary Remarks on Equivocal Right.

(Jus aequivocum.)

With every Right, in the strict acceptation (jus stridum), there is conjoined a Right to compel. But it is possible to think of other Rights of a wider kind (jus latum) in which the Title to compel cannot be determined by any law. Now there are two real or supposed Rights of this kind EQUITY and THE RIGHT OF NECESSITY. The first alleges a Right that is without compulsion ; the second adopts a compulsion that is without Right. This equivocalness, however, can be easily shown to rest on the peculiar fact that there are cases of doubtful Right, for the decision of which no Judge can be appointed.

I. EQUITY.

EQUITY (/Equitas), regarded objectively, does not properly constitute a claim upon the moral Duty of benevolence or beneficence on the part of others; but whoever insists upon anything on the ground of Equity, founds upon his Eight to the same. In this case, how ever, the conditions are awanting that are requisite for the function of a Judge in order that he might determine vhat or what kind of satisfaction can be done to this claim. When one of the partners of a Mercantile Company,

INTRODUCTION TO THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT. 51

formed under the condition of Equal profits, has, how ever, done more than the other members, and in conse quence has also lost more, it is in accordance with Equity that he should demand from the Company more than merely an equal share of advantage with the rest. But, in relation to strict Right, if we think of a Judge con- / sidering his case, he can furnish no definite data to establish how much mdre belongs to him by the Con tract ; and in case of an action at law, such a demand would be rejected. A domestic servant, again, who might be paid his wages due to the end of his year of service in a coinage that became depreciated within that period, so that it would not be of the same value to him as it was when he entered on his engagement, cannot claim by Right to be kept from loss on account of the unequal value of the money if he receives the due amount of it. He can only make an appeal on the ground of Equity,— a dumb goddess who cannot claim a hearing of Right, because there was nothing bearing on this point in the Contract of Service, and a Judge cannot give a decree on the basis of vague or indefinite conditions. Hence it follows, that a COURT OF EQUITY for tha/ decision of disputed questions of Right, would involve a contradiction. It is only where his own proper Rights* are concerned, and in matters in which he can decide, that a Judge may or ought to give a hearing to Equity. Thus, if the Crown is supplicated to give an indemnity to certain persons for loss or injury sustained in its service, it may undertake the burden of doing so, although, according to strict Right, the claim might be rejected on the ground of the pretext that the parties in question undertook the performance of the service occasioning the loss, at their own risk.

52 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

The Dictum of Equity may be put thus : ' The strictest Right is the greatest Wrong ' (summum jus summa injuria). But this evil cannot be obviated by the forms of Right although it relates to a matter of Right ; for the grievance that it gives rise to can only / be put before a ' Court of Conscience ' (forum poll), whereas every question of Right must be taken before a CIVIL COURT (forum soli}.

II. THE KIGHT OF NECESSITY.

The so-called Right of Necessity (Jus iiccessitatis) is the supposed Right or Title, in case of the danger of losing my own life, to take away the life of another who has, in fact, done me no harm. It is evident that, viewed as a doctrine of Right, this must involve a con tradiction. For this is not the case of a ivrongful aggressor making an unjust assault upon my life, and whom I anticipate by depriving him of his own (jus inculpates tutda>) ; nor consequently is it a question merely of the recommendation of moderation which belongs to Ethics as the Doctrine of Virtue, and not to Jurispru dence as the Doctrine of Right. It is a question of the allowableness of using violence against one who has used none against me.

It is clear that the assertion of such a Right is not

to be understood objectively as being in accordance with

what a Law would prescribe, but merely subjectively, as

proceeding on the assumption of how a sentence would

3 pronounced by a Court in the case. There can, in

ict, be no Criminal Law assigning the penalty of deatli

a man who, when shipwrecked and struggling in extreme

danger for his life, and in order to save it, may thrust

INTRODUCTION TO THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT. 53

another from a plank on which he had saved himself. For the punishment threatened by the Law could not possibly have greater power than the fear of the loss of life in the case in question. Such a Penal Law would thus fail altogether to exercise its intended effect ; for the threat of an Evil which is still uncertain such as Death by a judicial sentence— could not overcome the fear of an Evil which is certain, as Drowning is in such circum stances. An act of violent self-preservation, then, ought , not to be considered as altogether beyond condemnation/ (inculpcibile) ; it is only to be adjudged as exempt from punishment (impunibilc). Yet this subjective condition of/ impunity, by a strange confusion of ideas, lias been) regarded by Jurists as equivalent to objective lawfulness.

The Dictum of the Kight of Necessity is put in these terms, ' Necessity has no Law ' (Neccssitas non habet legcvi). And yet there cannot be a necessity that could make what is wrong lawful.

It is apparent, then, that in judgments relating both to ' Equity ' and ' the Right of Necessity/ the Equivocations involved arise from an interchange of the objective andl/i7' v, subjective grounds that enter into the application of the) Principles of Eight, when viewed respectively by Keason

or by a Judicial Tribunal. What one may have gooc

grounds for recognising as Kight in itself, may not find \ confirmation in a Court of Justice ; and what he must consider to be wrong in itself, may obtain recognition in such a Court. And the reason of this is, that the con- ception of Eight is not taken in the two cases in one the same sense.

DIVISION OF THE SCIENCE OF EIGHT.

A.

GENERAL DIVISION OF THE DUTIES OF EIGHT. (Juridical Duties.)

In this Division we may very conveniently follow ULPIAN, if his three Formulae are taken in a general sense, which may not have been quite clearly in his mind, but which they are capable of being developed into or of receiving. They are the following >—

1. HONESTE VIVE. ' Live rightly.' Juridical Eecti- tude, or Honour (Honestas juridica), consists in maintaining one's own worth as a man in relation to others. This Duty may be rendered by the pro position, 'Do not make thyself a mere Means for the use of others, but be to them likewise an End ' This Duty will be explained in the next Formula as an Obligation arising out of the Eight of Humanity in our own Person (Lexjusti}.

, NEMINEM L*DE. Do Wrong to no one.' This * ormula may be rendered so as to mean, < Do no Wrong to any one, even if thou shouldst be under the necessity, m observing this Duty, to cease from all connection with others and to avoid all Society' (Lex juridica). J

SUUMCUIQUE TKIBUE. 'Assign to every one what ; his own.' This may be rendered, 'Enter if

-, "?? }Cann0t be avoided> into » Society with others ch every one may have secured to him what is -If this Formula were to be simply trans- Give every one his own; it would express an xsurdity for we cannot ^e any one what he already t is to have a definite meaning it must

INTRODUCTION TO THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT.

therefore run thus, ' Enter into a state in which every one can have what is his own secured against the action of every other ' (Lex justitice).

These three classical Formula?, at the same time, repre sent principles which suggest a Division of the System of Juridical Duties into Internal Duties, External Duties, and those Connecting Duties which contain the latter as deduced from the Principle of the former by sub- sumption.

B.

UNIVERSAL DIVISION OF RIGHTS.

I. Natural Right and Positive Right.

The System of Eights, viewed as a scientific System of Doctrines, is divided into NATURAL RIGHT and POSITIVE RIGHT. Natural Right rests upon pure rational Prin ciples a priori; Positive or Statutory Right is what proceeds from the Will of a Legislator.

II. Innate Right and Acquired Right.

The System of Rights may again be regarded in refer ence to the implied Powers of dealing morally with others as bound by Obligations, that is, as furnishing a legal Title of action in relation to them. Thus viewed, the System is divided into INNATE RIGHT and ACQUIRED RIGHT. Innate Right is that Right which belongs to every one by Nature, independent of all juridical acts of experience. ACQUIRED RIGHT is that Right which is founded upon such juridical acts.

Innate Right may also be called the ' Internal Mine and Thine ' (Mcum vel Tuum internum) ; for External Right must always be acquired.

56 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

\ There is only one Innate Right, the Birthright of Freedom.

FREEDOM is Independence of the compulsory Will of another ; and in so far as it can co-exist with the Free dom of all according to a universal Law, it is the one sole original, inborn Plight belonging to every man in virtue of his Humanity. There is, indeed, an innate EQUALITY belonging to every man which consists in his Kight to be independent of being bound by others to anything more than that to which he may also recipro cally bind them. It is, consequently, the inborn quality of every man in virtue of which he ought to be his own master by Eight (sui juris). There is, also, the natural I quality of JUSTNESS attributable to a man as naturally of unimpeachable Right (justi), because he has done no Wrong to any one prior to his own juridical actions. And° j further, there is also the innate Eight of COMMON ACTION on the part of every man so that he may do towards others what does not infringe their Rights or take away mything that is theirs unless they are willing to appro- such as merely to communicate thought to arrate anything, or to promise something whether truly honestly, or untruly and dishonestly (veriloquium siloquium), for it rests entirely upon these others 3ther they will believe or trust in it or not.1 But all ights or Titles are already included in the Prin-

a

INTRODUCTION TO THE SCIENCE OF RIGHT. 57

ciple of Innate FREEDOM, and are not really distinguished ^ from it, even as dividing members under a higher species of Right.

The reason why sjiichaJJiyision into separate Rights has been introduced into the System of Natural Right viewed as including all that is innate, was not without a purpose. Its__object was to enable proof to be more readily put forward in case of any controversy arising about an Acquired Right, and questions emerging either with reference to a fact that might be in doubt, or, if that were established, in reference to a Right under dis pute. For the party repudiating an obligation, and on whom the burden of proof (onus probandi) might be incumbent, could thus methodically refer to his Innate Right of Freedom as specified under various relations in detail, and could therefore found upon them equally as different Titles of Right.

In the relation of Innate Right, and consequently of the Internal ' Mine' and ' Thine,' there is therefore noW Rights, but only ONE RIGHT. And, accordingly, this highest Division of Rights into Innate and Acquired, which evidently consists of two members extremely unequal in their contents, is properly placed in the Introduction ; and the subdivisions of the Science of Right may be referred in detail to the External Mine and Thine.

is his (falxiloquium dolosum). This distinction of conceptions so closely allied is not without foundation ; because on the occasion of a simple statement of one's thoughts, it is always free for another to take them as he may ; and yet the resulting repute that such a one is a man whose word cannot be trusted, comes so close to the opprobrium of directly calling him a Liar, that the boundary-line separating what in such a case belongs to Jurisprudence and what is special to Ethics, can hardly be otherwise drawn.

58 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

C. METHODICAL DIVISION OF THE SCIENCE OF EIGHT.

The highest Division of the System of Natural Bight should not be as it is frequently put into' Natural Eight' and ' Social Eight,' but into NATURAL EIGHT and CIVIL EIGHT. The first constitutes PRIVATE EIGHT ; the second, PUBLIC EIGHT. For it is not the ' Social state ' but the ' Civil state ' that is opposed to the ' State of Nature ; ' for in the ' State of Nature ' there may well be Society of some kind, but there is no 'civil' Society, as an Institution securing the Mine and Thine by public laws. It is thus that Eight, viewed under reference to the state of Nature, is specially called Private Eight. The whole of the Principles of Eight will therefore fall to be expounded under the two subdivisions of PRIVATE EIGHT and PUBLIC EIGHT.

THE SCIENCE OF BIGHT

PART FIRST. PRIVATE RIGHT.

THE SYSTEM OF THOSE LAWS WHICH REQUIRE NO EXTERNAL PROMULGATION.

PRIVATE RIGHT.

THE PRINCIPLES OF THE EXTERNAL MINE AND THINE GENERALLY.

CHAPTEK FIKST.

OF THE MODE OF HAVING ANYTHING EXTERNAL AS ONE'S OWN.

1.

The meaning of ' Mine ' in Right. (Meum Juris.)

'ANYTHING is ' Mine ' ly Right, or is rightfully Mine, when I am so connected with it, that if any other Person should make use of it without my consent, he would do me ;i lesion or injury. The subjective condition of the use of anything, is Possession of it,

An external thing, however, as such could only be mine, if I may assume it to be possible that I can be wronged by the use which another might make of it when it is not actually in tny possession. Hence it would be a contradiction to have anything External as one's own, were not the conception of Possession capable of two different meanings, as sensible Possession that is perceivable by the senses, and 'rational Possession that is

02 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

perceivable only by the Intellect., By the former is to be understood a physical Possession, and by the latter, a purely juridical Possession of the same objectv

The description of an Object as ' external to me ' may signify either that it is merely 'different and distinct from me as a Subject,' or that it is also ' a thing placed outside of me, and to be found elsewhere in space or time.' Taken in the first sense, the term Possession signifies ' rational Possession ; ' and, in the second sense, it must mean ' Empirical Possession.' A rational or intelligible Possession, if such be possible, is Possession viewed apart from physical holding or detention (detentio).

2.

Juridical Postulate of the Practical Reason.

It is possible to have any external object of my Will as Mine. In other words, a Maxim to this effect were it to become law that any object on which the Will can be exerted must remain objectively in itself without an owner t as ' res nullius,' is contrary to the Principle of Right

For an object of any act of my Will, is something that it would be physically within my power to use. Now, suppose there were things that by right should absolutely not be in our power, or, in other words, that it would be wrong or inconsistent with the freedom of all, according to universal Law, to make use of them. On this suppo sition, Freedom would so far be depriving itself of the use of its voluntary activity, in thus putting usedble objects out of all possibility of use. In practical rela tions, this would be to annihilate them, by making them res nullius, notwithstanding the fact that acts of Will in

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 63

relation to such things would formally harmonize, in the actual use of them, with the external freedom of all according to universal Laws. Now the pure practical Reason lays down only formal Laws as Principles to regulate the exercise of the Will ; and therefore abstracts from the matter of the act of Will, as regards the other qualities of the object, which is considered only in so far as it is an object of the activity of the Will. Hence the practical Reason cannot contain, in reference to such an object, an absolute prohibition of its use, because this would involve a contradiction of external freedom with itself. An object of my free Will, however, is one which I have the physical capability of making some use of at will, since its use stands in my power (in potentia}. This is to be distinguished from having the object brought under my disposal (in potestatcm meam reductum), which supposes not a capability merely, but also a particular act of the free-will. But in order to consider something merely as an object of my Will as such, it is sufficient to be conscious that I have it in my power. It is there fore an assumption a priori of the practical Reason, to regard and treat every object within the range of my free exercise of Will as objectively a possible Mine or Thine.

This Postulate may be called ' a Permissive Law ' of the practical Reason, as giving us a special title which we could not evolve out of the mere conceptions of Right generally. And this Title constitutes the Right to impose upon all others an obligation, not otherwise laid upon them, to abstain from the use of certain objects of our free Choice, because we have already taken them into our possession. Reason wills that this shall be recognised as a valid Principle, and it does so as practical

64 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Ecason; and it is enabled by means of this Postulate d priori to enlarge its range of activity in practice.

3.

Possession and Ownership.

Any one who would assert the Eight to a thing as his, must be in possession of it as an object* Were he not its actual possessor or owner, he could not be wronged or injured by the use which another might make of it without his consent. For, should anything external to him, and in no way connected with him by Eight, affect this object, it could not affect himself as a Subject, nor do him any wrong, unless he stood in a relation of Ownership to it.

4.

Exposition of the Conception of the External Mine and Thine.

There can only be three external Objects of my Will in the activity of Choice :

(1) A Corporeal Thing external to me ;

(2) The Free-will of another in the performance of a particular act (prccstatio') ;

(3) The State of another in relation to myself.

These correspond to the categories of Substance, Caus ality, and Reciprocity; and they form the practical relations between me and external objects, according to the Laws of Freedom.

A. I can only call a corporeal thing or an object

in space ' mine/ when, even although not in physical

*ssion of it, I am able to assert that I am in

possession of it in another real non-physical sense.

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 65

Thus, I am not entitled to call an apple mine merely because I hold it in my hand or possess it physically ; but only when I am entitled to say, 'I possess it, although I have laid it out of my hand, and wherever it may lie.' In like manner, I am not entitled to say of the ground, on which I may have laid myself down, that therefore it is mine ; but only when I can rightly assert that it still remains in my possession, although I may have left the spot. For any one who, in the former appearances of empirical possession, might wrench the apple out of my hand, or drag me away from my resting-place, would, indeed, injure me in respect of the wrar ' Mine ' of Freedom, but not in respect of the external 'Mine,' unless I could assert that I was in the possession of the Object, even when not actually holding it physically. And if I could not do this, neither could I call the apple or the spot mine.

B. I cannot call the performance of something by the action of the Will of another 'Mine,' if I can only say ' it has come into my possession at the same time with a promise ' (pactum re initum) ; but only if I am able to assert ' I am in possession of the Will of the other, so as to determine him to the performance of a particular act, although the time for the performance of it has not yet come.' In the latter case, the promise belongs to the nature of things actually held as possessed, and as an ' active obligation ' I can reckon it mine ; and this holds good not only if I have the thing promised as in the first case already in my possession, but even although I do not yet possess it in fact. Hence, I must be able to regard myself in thought as independent of that empirical form of possession that is limited by the condition of time, and as being nevertheless in possession of the object.

C. I cannot call a Wife, a Child, a Domestic, or, generally, any other Person ' mine ' merely because I I

66 KAXT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

command them at present as belonging to my house hold, or because I have them under control, and in my power and possession. But I can call them mine, if, although they may have withdrawn them selves from my control and I do not therefore possess them empirically, I can still say ' I possess them by my mere Will, provided they exist anywhere in space or time ; and, consequently, my possession of them is purely juridical* They belong, in fact, to my posses sions, only when and so far as I can assert this as a matter of Plight.

5.

Definition of the conception of the external Mine and Thine. Definitions are nominal or real, A nominal Definition is sufficient merely to distinguish the object defined from all other objects, and it springs out of a complete and definite exposition of its conception. A real Definition further suffices for a Deduction of the conception defined, so as to furnish a knowledge of the reality of the object. —The nominal Definition of the external ' Mine ' would thus be: 'The external Mine is anything outside of myself, such that any hindrance of my use of it at will, would be doing me an injury or wrong as an infringement of that Freedom of mine which may coexist with the freedom of all others according to a universal Law.' The real Definition of this conception may be put thus : ' The external Mine is anything outside of myself, such that any prevention of my use of it would be a wrong, although I may not be in possession of it so as to be actually hold ing it as an object.'— I must be in some kind of posses sion of an external object, if the object is to be regarded as mine; for, otherwise, any one interfering with this object would not, in doing so, affect me; nor, conse quently, would he thereby do me any wrong. Hence,

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 67

according to § 4, a rational Possession (possessio nou- mcnon) must be assumed as possible, if there is to be rightly an external ' Mine and Thine.' Empirical Posses sion is thus only phenomenal possession or holding (detention) of the object in the sphere of sensible appearance (possessio phenomenon}, although the object which I possess is not regarded in this practical relation as itself a Phenomenon, according to the exposition of the Transcendental Analytic in the Critique of Pure Season but as a Thing in itself. For in the Critique of Pure Reason the interest of Reason turns upon the theoretical knowledge of the Nature of Things, and how far Reason can go in such knowledge. But here Reason has to deal with the practical determination of the action of the Will according to Laws of Freedom, whether the object is perceivable through the senses or merely think able by the pure Understanding. And Right, as under con sideration, is a pure practical conception of the Reason in relation to the exercise of the Will under Laws of Freedom. And, hence, it is not quite correct to speak of 'possessing' a Right to this or that object, but it should rather be said that an object is possessed in a purely juridical way ; for a Right is itself the rational possession of an Object, and to ' possess a possession,' would be an expression without meaning.

6.

Deduction of the conception of a purely juridical Possession of an External Object.

(Possessio noumenon.)

The question, 'How is an external Mine and Thine possible ? ' resolves itself into this other question, ' How

68 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

is a merely juridical or rational Possession possible ?' And this second question resolves itself again into a third, 'How is a synthetic proposition in Eight possible a priori ? '

All Propositions of Plight as juridical propositions- are Propositions a priori, for they are practical Laws of lieason (Dictamina rationis). But the juridical Pro position & priori respecting empirical Possession is analytical ; for it says nothing more than what follows by the principle of Contradiction, from the conception of sucli possession ; namely, that if I am the holder of a thing in the way of being physically connected with it, any one interfering with it without my consent as, for instance, in wrenching an apple out of my hand affects and detracts from my freedom as that which is internally Mine ; and consequently the maxim of his action is in direct contradiction to the Axiom of Plight. The pro position expressing the principle of an empirical rightful Possession, does not therefore go beyond the Plight of a Person in reference to himself.

On the other hand, the Proposition expressing the possibility of the Possession of a thing external to me, after abstraction of all the conditions of empirical posses sion in space and time consequently presenting the assumption of the possibility of a Possessio Noumenon goes beyond these limiting conditions ; and because this Proposition asserts a possession even without physical holding, as necessary to the conception of the external Mine and Thine, it is synthetical. And thus it becomes a problem for Keason to show how such a Proposition, extending its range beyond the conception of empirical possession, is possible ci priori.

In this manner, for instance, the act of taking possession of a particular portion of the soil, is a mode

THE PRINCIPLES OF PKIVATE EIGHT. 69

exercising the private free-will without being an act of usurpation. The possessor founds upon the innate Right of common possession of the surface of the earth, and upon the universal Will corresponding & priori to it, which allows a private Possession of the soil ; because what are mere things would be otherwise made in themselves and by a Law, into unappropriable objects. Thus a first appropriator acquires originally by primary possession a particular portion of the ground ; and by Eight (jure) he resists every other person who would hinder him in the private use of it, although while the ' state of Nature ' continues, this cannot be done by juridical means (<h jure), because a public Law does not yet exist.

And although a piece of ground should be regarded as free, or declared to be such, so as to be for the public use of all without distinction, yet it cannot be said that it is thus free by nature and originally so, prior to any juridical act. For there would be a real relation already incorporated in such a piece of ground by the very fact that the possession of it was denied to any particular individual ; and as this public freedom of the ground would be a prohibition of it to every particular individual, this presupposes a common possession of it which cannot take effect without a Contract. A piece of ground, how ever, which can only become publicly free by contract, must actually be in the possession of all those associated together, who mutually interdict or suspend each other, from any particular or private use of it.

This original Community of the soil and of the things upon it (communio fundi originaria), is an idea which has objective and practical Juridical reality, and is entirely different from the idea of a primitive community of things which is a fiction.

70 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

For the latter would have had to be founded as a form of Society, and must have taken its rise from a Contract by which all renounced the Eight of Private Possession, so that by uniting the property owned by each into a whole, it was thus transformed into a common possession. But had such an event taken place, History must have presented some evidence of it. To regard sucli a procedure as the original mode of taking possession, and to hold that the particular possessions of every individual may and ought to be grounded upon it, is evidently a contradiction.

Possession (possessio) is to be distinguished from habitation as mere residence (sedes) ; and the act of taking possession of the soil in the intention of acquiring it once for all, is also to be distinguished from settlement or domicile (incolatus), which is a continuous private Possession of a place that is dependent on the presence of the individual upon it. We have not here to deal with the question of domi ciliary settlement, as that is a secondary juridical act which may follow upon possession, or may not occur at all; for as such it could not involve an original possession, but only a secondary possession derived from the consent of others.

Simple physical Possession, or holding of the soil

involves already certain relations of Eight to the

thing, although it is certainly not sufficient to enable

.0 regard it as Mine. Eelative to others, so far

they know, it appears as a first possession in har-

>ny with the law of external freedom ; and, at the

is embraced in the universal original

possession which contains a priori the fundamental

iciple of the possibility of a private possession

isturb the first occupier or holder of a

portion of the soil in his use of it, is a lesion or

"g done to him. The first taking of Possession

has therefore a Title of Eight (titulm possession**)

favour, which is simply the principle of the

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 71

original common possession ; and the saying that 1 It is well for those who are in possession ' (beati possidentes), when one is not bound to authenticate his possession, is a principle of Natural Right that establishes the juridical act of taking possession, as a ground of acquisition upon which every first possessor may found.

It has been shown in the Critique of Pure Reason that in theoretical Principles a priori, an intuitional Perception a priori must be supplied in connection with any given conception ; and, consequently, were it a question of a purely theoretical Principle, some thing would have to be added to the conception of the possession of an object to make it real. But in respect of the practical Principle under considera tion, the procedure is just the converse of the theoretical process ; so that all the conditions of per ception which form the foundation of empirical possession must be abstracted or taken away in order to extend the range of the juridical Conception beyond the empirical sphere, and in order to be able to apply the Postulate, that every external object of the free activity of my Will, so far as I have it in my power, although not in the possession of it, may be reckoned as juridically Mine.

The possibility of such a possession, with conse quent Deduction of the conception of a non-empirical possession, is founded upon the juridical Postulate of the Practical Reason, that ' It is a juridical Duty so to act towards others that what is external and useable may come into the possession or become the property of some one.' And this Postulate is conjoined with the exposition of the Conception that what is exter nally one's own, is founded upon a possession, that is not physical The possibility of such a possession, thus conceived, cannot, however, be proved or com prehended in itself, because it is a rational concep tion for which no empirical perception can be

72 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

furnished ; but it follows as an immediate conse quence from the Postulate that has been enunciated. For, if it is necessary to act according to that juridical Principle, the rational or intelligible con dition of a purely juridical possession must also be possible. It need astonish no one, then, that the theoretical aspect of the Principles of the external Mine and Thine, is lost from view in the rational sphere of pure Intelligence, and presents no extension of Knowledge ; for the conception of Freedom upon which they rest does not admit of any theoretical Deduction of its possibility, and it can only be inferred from the practical Law of Eeason, called the Categorical Imperative, viewed as a fact.

7.

Application of the Principle of the Possibility of an external Mine and Thine to Objects of Experience.

The conception of a purely juridical Possession, is an empirical conception dependent on conditions of Space and Time, and yet it lias practical reality. As such it must be applicable to objects of experience, the knowledge of which is independent of the conditions Space and Time. The rational process by which the conception of Eight is brought into relation to such so as to constitute a possible external Mine and s as follows. The Conception of Eight, bein* contained merely in Eeason, cannot be immediately applied to objects of experience, so as to give the con- ception of an empirical Possession, but must be applied *ly to the mediating conception in the Under- 'Possession in general; so that, instead of ] lysical holding (Detcntio) as an empirical representation asion, the formal conception or thought of

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 73

abstracted from all conditions of Space and Time, is conceived by the mind, and only as implying that an object is in my power and at my disposal (in potcstate mea positum esse). In this relation, the term 'external' does not signify existence in anotlier place, than where I am, nor my resolution and acceptance at another time than the moment in which I have the ofler of a thing : it signifies only an object different from or other than myself. Now the practical Reason by its Law of Kight wills, that I shall think the Mine and Thine in application to objects, not according to sensible conditions, but apart from these and from the Possession they indicate ; because they refer to determinations of the activity of the Will that are in accordance with the Laws of Freedom. For it is only a conception of the, Understanding that can be brought under the rational Conception of Plight. I may therefore say that I possess a field, although it is in quite a different place from that on which I actually find myself. For the question here is not concerning an intellectual relation to the object, but I have the thing practically in my power and at my disposal, which is a conception of Possession realized by the Understanding and independent of relations of space ; and it is mine, because my Will in determining itself to any particular use of it, is not in conflict with the Law of external Freedom. Now it is just in abstraction from physical possession of the object of my free-will in the sphere of sense, that the Practical Reason wills that a rational possession of it shall be thought, according to intellectual conceptions which are not empirical, but contain & priori the conditions of rational possession. Hence it is in this fact, that we found the ground of the validity of such a rational conception of possession

74 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

(posscssio noumcnon) as the principle of a universally valid Legislation. For such a Legislation is implied and contained in the expression, ' This external object is mi tie' because an Obligation is thereby imposed upon all others in respect of it, who would otherwise not have been obliged to abstain from the use of this object.

The mode, then, of having something External to myself as Mine, consists in a specially juridical connection of the Will of the Subject with that object, independently of the empirical relations to it in Space and in Time, and in accordance with the conception of a rational possession. A particular spot on the earth is not externally Mine because I occupy it with my body ; for the question here discussed refers only to my external Freedom, and consequently it affects only the possession of myself, which is not a thing external to me, and therefore only involves an internal Eight. But if I continue to be in possession of the spot, although I have taken myself away from it and gone to another place, only under that condition is my external Eight concerned in connection with it. And to make the continuous possession of this spot by my person a condition of having it as mine, must either be to assert that it is not possible at all to have anything External as one's own, which is contrary to the Postulate in § 2, or to require, in order that this external Possession may be possible, that I shall be in two places at the same time. But this amounts to say ing that I must be in a place and also not in it, which is contradictory and absurd.

This position may be applied to the case in which I have accepted a promise ; for my Having and Possession in respect of what has been promised, become established on the ground of external Eight. This Eight is not to

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIG11T. 75

be annulled by the fact that the promiser having said at one time, ' This thing shall be yours/ again at a sub sequent time says, ' My will now is that the thing shall not be yours.' In such relations of rational Eight the conditions hold just the same as if the promiser had, without any interval of time between them, made the two declarations of his Will, ' This shall be yours,' and also ' This shall not be yours ; ' which manifestly contradicts itself.

The same thing holds, in like manner, of the Con ception of the juridical possession of a Person as belong ing to the ' Having ' of a subject, whether it be a Wife, a Child, or a Servant. The relations of Right involved in a household, and the reciprocal possession of all its members, are not annulled by the capability of separat ing from each other in space ; because it is by juridical relations that they are connected, and the external ' Mine ' and ' Thine,' as in the former cases, rests entirely upon the assumption of the possibility of a purely rational possession, without the accompaniment of physical detention or holding of the object.

Reason is forced to a Critique of its juridically Practical Function in special reference to the con ception of the external Mine and Thine, by the Antinomy of the propositions enunciated regarding the possibility of such a form of Possession. For these give rise to an inevitable Dialectic, in which a Thesis and an Antithesis set up equal claims to the validity of two conflicting Conditions. Reason is thus com pelled, in its practical function in relation to Right,-— as it was in its theoretical function, to make a dis tinction between Possession as a phenomenal appear ance presented to the senses, and that Possession which is rational and thinkable only by the Understanding.

70 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

THESIS.— The Thesis, in this case, is, l It is _ to have something external as mine, although I am not in possession of it.'

ANTITHESIS.— The Antithesis is, ' It is not possible to have anything external as mine, if I am not in possession of it.'

SOLUTION. The Solution is, 'Both Propositions are true ; ' the former when I mean empirical Posses sion (possessio phenomenon), the latter when I under stand by the same term, a purely rational Possession ( possessio noumenon).

But the possibility of a rational possession, and consequently of an external Mine and Thine, cannot be comprehended by direct insight, but must be deduced from the Practical Eeason. And in this relation it is specially noteworthy that the Practical Keason without intuitional perceptions, and even without requiring such an element a priori, can extend its range by the mere elimination of empirical con ditions, as justified by the law of Freedom, and can thus establish synthetical Propositions a priori. The proof of this in the practical connection, as will be shown afterwards, can be adduced in an analytical manner.

8.

To have anything External as one's own is only possible in a Juridical or Civil State of Society under the regulation of a public legislative Power.

If, by word or deed, I declare my Will that some external thing shall be mine, I make a declaration that every other person is obliged to abstain from the use of this object of my exercise of Will ; and this imposes an Obligation which no one would be under, without such a juridical act on my part. But the assumption of this

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 77

Act, at the same time involves the admission that I am obliged reciprocally to observe a similar abstention towards every other in respect of what is externally theirs ; for the Obligation in question arises from a universal Rule regulating the external juridical relations. Hence I am not obliged to let alone what another person declares to be externally his, unless every other person likewise secures me by a guarantee that he will act in relation to what is mine, upon the same Principle. This guar antee of reciprocal and mutual abstention from what belongs to others, does not require a special juridical act for its establishment, but is already involved in the Conception of an external Obligation of Eight, on account of the universality and consequently the reciprocity of the obligatoriness arising from a universal Rule. Now a single Will, in relation to an external and consequently contingent Possession, cannot serve as a compulsory Law for all, because that would be to do violence to the Freedom which is in accordance with universal Laws. Therefore it is only a Will that binds every one, and as such a common, collective, and authoritative Will, that can furnish a guarantee of security to all. But the state of men under a universal, external, and public- Legislation, conjoined with authority and power, is called the Civil state. There can therefore be an external Mine and Thine only in the Civil state of Society.

CONSEQUENCE. It follows, as a Corollary, that if it is juridically possible to have an external object as one's own, the individual Subject of possession must be allowed to compel or constrain every person, with whom a dispute; as to the Mine or Thine of such a possession may arise, to enter along with himself into the relations of a Civil Constitution.

78 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

9.

There may, however, be an external Mine and Thine found as a fact in the state of Nature, but it is only provisory.

Natural Eight in the state of a Civil Constitution, means the forms of Eight which may be deduced from Principles a priori as the conditions of such a Constitution. It is therefore not to be infringed by the statutory laws of such a Constitution ; and accordingly the juridical Principle remains in force, that, ' Whoever proceeds upon a Maxim by which it becomes impossible for me to have an object of the exercise of my Will as Mine, does me a lesion or injury.' For a Civil Constitution is only the juridical condition under which every one has what is his own merely secured to him, as distinguised from its being specially assigned and determined to him. All Guar antee, therefore, assumes that every one to whom a thing is secured, is already in possesion of it as his own. Hence, prior to the Civil Constitution or apart from it an external Mine and Thine must be assumed as possible, and along with it a Eight to compel every one with whom we could come into any kind of intercourse, to enter witli us into a constitution in which what is Mine or Thine can be secured. There may thus be a Possession in expectation or in preparation for such a state of security, as can only be established on the Law of the Common Will ; and as it is therefore in accord ance with the possibility of such a state, it constitutes a provisory or temporary juridical Possession ; whereas that Possession which is found in reality in the Civil state of Society will be a peremptory or guaranteed Pos-

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. (.)

session. Prior to entering into this state, for which he is naturally prepared, the individual rightfully resists those who will not adapt themselves to it, and who would disturb him in his provisory possession ; because if the Will of all except himself were imposing upon him an obligation to withdraw from a certain possession, it would still be only a one-sided or unilateral Will, and consequently it would have just as little legal Title which can be properly based only on the universalized Will to contest a claim of Eight ; as he would have to assert it. Yet he has the advantage on his side, of being in accord with the conditions requisite to the introduction and institution of a civil form of Society. In a word, the mode in which anything external may be held as one's own in the state of Nature, is just physical possession with a presumption of Right thus far in its favour, that by union of the Wills of all in a public Legislation, it will be made juridical ; and in this ex pectation it holds comparatively, as a kind of potential juridical Possession.

This Prerogative of Right, as arising from the fact of empirical possession, is in accordance with the Formula, ' It is well for those who are in possession ' (Beati possidentes). It does not consist in the fact that because the Possessor has the presumption of being a rightful man, it is unnecessary for him to bring forward proof that he possesses a certain thing rightfully, for this position applies only to a case of disputed Right. But it is because it accords with the Postulate of the Practical Reason, that every one is invested with the faculty of having as his own any external object upon which he has exerted his Will ; and, consequently, all actual possession is a state whose rightfulness is established upon that Postulate

KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

l»y an anterior act of Will. And such an act, if there be no prior possession of the same object by another opposed to it, does, therefore, provisionally justify and entitle me, according to the Law of external Freedom, to restrain any one who refuses to enter with me into a state of public legal Freedom, from all pretension to the use of such an object. For such a procedure is requisite, in conformity with the Postulate of Reason, in order to subject to my proper use a thing which would otherwise be practically annihilated, as°re«ards all proper use of it.

PRIVATE RIGHT

CHAPTER SECOND. THE MODE OF ACQUIRING ANYTHING EXTERNAL.

10.

The general Principle of External Acquisition.

I ACQUIRE a thing when 1 act (cfficio) so that it becomes mine. An external thing is originally mine, when it is mine even without the intervention of a juridical Act. An Acquisition is original and primary, when it is not derived from what another had already made his own.

There is nothing External that is as such originally mine ; but anything external may be originally acquired when it is an object that no other person has yet made his. A state in which the Mine and Thine are in common, cannot be conceived as having been at any time original. Such a state of things would have to he acquired by an external juridical Act, although there may be an original and common possession of an external ob ject. Even if we think hypothetically of a state in which the Mine and Thine would be originally in common as a ' Communio mci et tui originaria,' it would still have to be distinguished from a primeval communion (Com-

F

g2 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

munio primccva) with things in common, sometimes supposed to be founded in the first period of the relations of Eight among men, and which could not be regarded as based upon Principles like the former, but only upon History. Even under that condition the historic Communio, as a supposed primeval Community, would always have to be viewed as acquired and derivative (Communio derivative).

The Principle of external Acquisition, then, may be expressed thus: ''Whatever I bring under my power according to the Law of external Freedom, of which as an object of my free activity of Will I have the capability of making use according to the Postulate of the Practical Pteason, and which I will to become mine in conformity with the Idea of a possible united common Will, is mine.,'

"The practical Elements (Momenta attendenda) con stitutive of the process of original Acquisition are :

1. PREHENSION or Seizure of an object which belongs to no one ; for if it belonged already to some one the act would conflict with the Freedom of others that is according to universal Laws. This is the taking possession of an object of my free activity of Will in Space and Time ; the Possession, therefore, into which I thus put myself is sensible or physical possession (possessio phenomenon) ;

2/DECLARATiON of the possession of this object by formal designation and the act of my free-will in inter dicting every other person from using it as his ;

3. APPROPRIATION, as the act, in Idea, of an externally legislative common Will, by which all and each are obliged to respect and act in conformity with my act of Will.

The validity of the last element in the process of

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 83

Acquisition, as that on which the conclusion that ' the external object is mine ' rests, is what makes the pos session valid as a purely rational and juridical possession (possessio noumcnon). It is founded upon the fact that as all these Acts are juridical, they consequently proceed from the Practical Reason, and therefore in the question as to what is Right, abstraction may be made of the empirical conditions involved, and the conclusion ' the external object is mine ' thus becomes a correct infer ence from the external fact of sensible possession to the internal Right of rational Possession.

The original primary Acquisition of an external object of the action of the Will, is called OCCUPANCY. It can only take place in reference to Substances or Corporeal Things. Now when this Occupation of an external object does take place, the Act presupposes as a condition of such empirical possession, its Priority in time before the act of any other who may also be willing to enter upon occupation of it. Hence the legal maxim, 1 qui prior tempore, potior jure' Such Occupation as original or primary is, further, the effect only of a single or unilateral Will ; for were a bilateral or twofold Will requisite for it, it would be derived from a Contract of two or more persons with each other, and consequently it would be based upon what another or others had already made their own. It is not easy to see how such an act of free-will as this would be, could really form a foundation for every one having his own. However, the first Acquisition of a thing is on that account not quite exactly the same as the original Acquisition of it. For the Acquisition of a public juridical state by union of the Wills of all in a universal Legislation, would be such an original Acquisition, seeing that no other of the kind

84 KANT'S* PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

could precede it, and yet it would be derived from the particular Wills of all the individuals, and consequently become all-sided or omnilateral; for a properly primary Acquisition can only proceed from an individual or uni lateral Will.

DIVISION OF THE SUBJECT OF THE ACQUISITION OF TIIK

EXTERNAL MlNE AND TlIINE.

I. In respect of the MATTER or Object of Acquisition, I acquire either a Corporeal THING (Substance), or the PERFORMANCE of something by another (Causality), or this other as a PERSON in respect of his state, so far as I have a Eight to dispose of the same (in a relation of Reciprocity with him).

II. In respect of the FORM or Mode of Acquisition, it is either a HEAL EIGHT (jus reule), or a PERSONAL RIGHT (jus personak), or a REAL-PERSONAL RIGHT (>* realitcr personate), to the possession, although not to the use, of another Person as if he were a Thing.

III. In respect of the Ground of Right or THE TITLE (tilulus) of Acquisition which, properly, is not a par ticular member of the Division of Rights, but rather a constituent element of the mode of exercising them any tiling External is acquired by a certain free Exercise of Will that is either unilateral, as the act of a single Will (facto), or bilateral, as the act of two Wills (pacto), or omnilateral, as the act of all the Wills of a Community together

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 85

FIRST SECTION.

PRINCIPLES OF HEAL RIGHT.

11.

What is a Real Right ?

The usual Definition of Real Right, or ' Right in a Thing ' (jus reale, jus in re), is that 'it is a Right as against every possessor of it.' This is a correct Nominal Definition. But what is it that entitles me to claim an external object from any one who may appear as its possessor, and to compel him, per vindicationcm, to put me again, in place of himself, into possession of it ? Is this external juridical relation of my Will a kind of immediate relation to an external thing ? If so, whoever might think of his Right as referring not immediately to Persons but to Things, would have to represent it, although only in an obscure way, somewhat thus. A Right on one side has always a Duty corresponding to it on the other, so that an external thing, although away from the hands of its first Possessor, continues to be still connected with him by a continuing obligation ; and thus it refuses to fall under the claim of any other possessor, because it is already bound to another. In this way my Right, viewed as a kind of good Genius accompanying a thing and preserving it from all external attack, would refer an alien possessor always to me ! It is, however, absurd to think of an obligation of Persons towards Things, and conversely ; although it may be allowed in any particular case, to represent the

8G KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

juridical relation by a sensible image of this kind, and to express it in this way.

The Real Definition would run thus: THING is a Right to the Private Use of a Thing, of which I am in possession— original or derivative— in common with all others.' For this is the one condi tion under which it is alone possible that I can exclude every other possessor from the private use of the Thing (jus contra quemlilet hujus rci possessorem). For, except by presupposing such a common collective possession, it cannot be conceived how, when I am not in actual pos session of a thing, I could be injured or wronged by others who are in possession of it and use it. By an individual act of my own Will I cannot oblige any other person to abstain from the use of a thing in respect of which he would otherwise be under no obligation ; and, accordingly, such an Obligation can only arise from the collective Will of all united in a relation of common possession. Otherwise, I would have to think of a Right in a Thing, as if the Thing had an Obligation towards me, and as if the Right as against every Possessor of it had to be derived from this Obligation in the Thing, which is an absurd way of representing the subject.

Further, by the term ' Real Right ' (jus rcale) is meant not only the ' Right in a Thing ' (jus in re), but also the constitutive principle, of all the Laws which relate to the real Mine and Thine. It is, however, evident thatxa man entirely alone upon the earth could properly neither have nor acquire any external thing as his own ; because between him as a Person and all external Things as material objects, there could be no relations of Obligation^ There is therefore, literally,

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 87

no direct Right in a Thing, but only that Right is to be properly called ' real ' which belongs to any one as constituted against a Person, who is in common pos session of things with all others in the Civil state of Society.

12.

The First Acquisition of a Thing can only be that of the Soil.

By the Soil is understood all habitable Land. In relation to everything that is moveable upon it, it is to be regarded as a Substance, and the mode of the exist ence of the Moveables is viewed as an Inherence in it. And just as, in the theoretical acceptation, Accidents cannot exist apart from their Substances, so, in the practical relation, Moveables upon the Soil cannot be regarded as belonging to any one unless he is supposed to have been previously in juridical possession of the Soil so that it is thus considered to be his.

For, let it be supposed that the Soil belongs to no one. Then I would be entitled to remove every moveable thing found upon it from its place, even to total loss of it, in order to occupy that place, without infringing thereby on the freedom of any other ; there being, by the hypo thesis, no possessor of it at all. But everything that can be destroyed, such as a Tree, a House, and such lik<; as regards its matter at least is moveable ; and if we call a thing which cannot be moved without destruc tion of its form an immovedble, the Mine and Thine in it is not understood as applying to its substance, but to that which is adherent to it, and which does not essen tially constitute the thing itself.

KANT'S PHILOSOPHY or LAW.

13.

Every part of the Soil may be originarily acquired ; and the Principle of the possibility of such Acquisition is the original Community of the Soil generally.

The first Clause of this Proposition is founded upon the Postulate of the Practical Reason 2) ; the second is established by the following Proof.

All Men are originally and before any juridical act of Will in rightful possession of the Soil ; that is, they have a 1 light to be wherever Nature or Chance has placed them without their will. Possession (possessio), which is to be distinguished from residential settlement (secies) as a voluntary, acquired, and permanent possession, becomes common possession, on account of the connection with each other of all the places on the surface of the Earth as a globe. For, had the surface of the earth been an infinite plain, men could have been so dispersed upon it that they might not have come into any necessary communion with each other, and a state of social Community would b have been a necessary consequence of their existence upon the Earth.— Now that Possession proper to all men upon the earth which is prior to all their particular ichcal acts, constitutes an original possession in common mo possessions originaria). The conception of an original, common Possession of things is not rived from experience, nor is it dependent on condi- time, as is the case with the imaginary and indemonstrable fiction of a primeval Community of posses- | m actual history. Hence it is a practical conception son, involving in itself the only Principle according ich Men may use the place they happen to occupy

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 89

on the surface of the Earth, in accordance with Laws of Right.

14.

The juridical Act of this original Acquisition is Occupancy.

The Act of taking possession (appreliensio), as being at its beginning the physical appropriation of a corporeal thing in space (possession™ physiccc}, can accord with the Law of the external Freedom of all, under no other condition than that of its Priority in respect of Time. In this relation it must have the characteristic of a first net in the way of taking possession, as a free exercise of Will. The activity of Will, however, as determining that the thing in this case a definite separate place on the surface of the Earth shall be mine, being an act of Appropriation, cannot be otherwise in the case of original Acquisition than individual or unilateral (voluntas uni- lateralis s. propria). Now, OCCUPANCY is the Acqui sition of an external object by an individual act of Will., The original Acquisition of such an object as a limited portion of the Soil, can therefore only be accomplished by an act of Occupation.

The possibility of this mode of Acquisition cannot be intuitively apprehended by pure Ueason in any way, nor established by its Principles, but is an immediate conse quence from the Postulate of the Practical Reason. The Will as practical Reason, however, cannot justify ex ternal Acquisition otherwise than only in so far as it is itself included in an absolutely authoritative Will, with which it is united by implication ; or, in other words, only in so far as it is contained within a union of the Wills of all who come into practical relation with each

90 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

other. For an individual, unilateral Will and the same applies to a Dual or other particular Will cannot impose on all an Obligation which is contingent in itself. This requires an omnilateral or universal Will, which is not contingent, but a priori, and which is therefore necessarily united and legislative. Only in accordance with such a Principle can there be agreement of the active free-will of each individual with the freedom of all, and consequently Eights in general, or even the possibility of an external Mine and Thine.

15.

It is only within a Civil Constitution that anything can be acquired peremptorily, whereas in the State of Nature Acquisition can only be provisory.

A Civil Constitution is objectively necessary as a Duty, although subjectively its reality is contingent. Hence, there is connected with it a real natural Law of Eight, to which all external Acquisition is subjected.

The empirical Title of Acquisition has been shown to l>e constituted by the taking physical possession (Appre- hensio physica) as founded upon an original community of 1 light in all to the Soil. And because a possession in the phenomenal sphere of sense, can only be subordinated to that Possession which is in accordance with rational conceptions of right, there must correspond to this physical act of possession a rational mode of taking possession by elimination of all the empirical conditions in Space and Time. This rational form of possession establishes the proposition, that ' whatever I bring under my power in accordance with Laws of external Freedom, and will that it shall be mine, becomes mine.'

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 01

The rational Title of Acquisition can therefore only lie originally in the Idea of the Will of all united implicitly, or necessarily to be united, which is here tacitly assumed as an indispensable Condition (Conditio sine qua nori). For by a single Will there cannot be imposed upon others an obligation by which they would not have been otherwise bound. But the fact formed by Wills actually and universally united in a Legislation, constitutes the Civil state of Society. Hence, it is only in conformity with the idea of a Civil state of Society, or in reference to it and its realization, that anything External can be acquired. Before such a state is realized, and in anticipation of it, Acquisition, which would otherwise be derived, is consequently only provi sory. The Acquisition, which is peremptory, finds place only in the Civil state.

Nevertheless, such provisory Acquisition is real Acqui sition. For, according to the Postulate of the juridically Practical Reason, the possibility of Acquisition in whatever state men may happen to be living beside one another, and therefore in the State of Nature as well, is a Principle of Private Plight. And in accordance with this Principle, every one is justified or entitled to exercise that compul sion by which it alone becomes possible to pass out of the state of Nature, and to enter into that state of Civil Society which alone can make all Acquisition peremptory.

It is a question as to how far the right of taking possession of the Soil extends ? The answer is, So far as the capability of having it under one's power extends, that is, just as far as he who wills to appro priate it can defend it, as if the Soil were to say, ' If you cannot protect me, neither can you command me.' In this way the controversy about what con-

92 K AST'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

stitutes a free or closed Sea must be decided. Tims, within the range of a cannon-shot no one has a right to intrude on the coast of a country that already belongs to a certain State, in order to fish or gather amber on the shore, or such like. Further, the question is put, ' Is Cultivation of the Soil, by build ing, agriculture, drainage, etc., necessary in order to its Acquisition ? ' No. For, as these processes as forms of specification are only Accidents, they do not constitute objects of immediate possession, and can only belong to the Subject in so far as the substance of them has been already recognised as his. When it is a question of the first Acquisition of a thing, the cultivation or modification of it by labour forms nothing more than an external sign of the fact that it has been taken into possession, and this can be indi cated by many other signs that cost less trouble. Again, ' May any one be hindered in the Act of taking possession, so that neither one nor other of two Competitors shall acquire the Eight of Priority, and the Soil in consequence may remain for all time free as belonging to no one ? ' Not at all Such a hindrance cannot be allowed to take place, because the second of the two, in order to be enabled to do this, would himself have to be upon some neighbour ing Soil, where he also, in this manner, could be hindered from being, and such absolute Hindering would involve a Contradiction. It would, however, be quite consistent with the Eight of Occupation, in the case of a certain intervening piece of the Soil, to let it lie unused as a neutral ground for the separa tion of two neighbouring States ; but under such a condition, that ground would actually belong to them both in common, and would not be without an owner nullius), just because it would be used by both in order to form a separation between them.— Again lay one have a thing as his, on a Soil of which no one has appropriated any part as his own ? ' Yes. In

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 93

Mongolia, for example, any one may let lie whatever baggage he has, or bring back the horse that has run away from him into his possession as his own, because the whole Soil belongs to the people generally, and the use of it accordingly belongs to every individual. But that any one can have a moveable thing on the soil of another as his own, is only possible by Contract. Finally, there is the question : •' May one of two neighbouring Nations or Tribes resist another when attempting to impose upon them a certain mode of using a particular Soil ; as, for instance, a tribe of hunters making such an attempt in relation to a pastoral people, or the latter to agriculturists and such like ?' Certainly. For the mode in which such peoples or tribes may settle themselves upon the surface of the earth, provided they keep within their own boundaries, is a matter of mere pleasure and choice on their own part (res mercc facullatis).

As a further question, it may be asked : Whether, when neither Nature nor Chance, but merely our own AVill, brings us into the neighbourhood of a people that gives no promise of a prospect of entering into Civil Union with us, we are to be considered entitled in any case to proceed with force in the intention of founding such a Union, and bringing into a juridical state such men as the savage American Indians, the Hottentots, and the New Hollanders; Or and the case is not much better whether we may establish Colonies by deceptive purchase, and so become owners of their soil, and, in general, without regard to their first possession, make use at will of our superiority in relation to them ? Further, may it not be held that Nature herself, as abhorring a vacuum, seems to demand such a procedure, and that large regions in other Continents, that are now magnificently peopled, would otherwise have remained unpossessed by civil ised inhabitants, and might have for ever remained thus, so that the end of Creation would have so far

94 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

been frustrated ? It is almost unnecessary to answer ; for it is easy to see through all this flimsy veil of injustice, which just amounts to the Jesuitism of making a good End justify any Means. This mode of acquiring the Soil is, therefore, to be repudiated.

The Indefiniteness of external acquirable objects in respect of their Quantity, as well as their Quality, makes the problem of the sole primary external Acquisition of them one of the most difficult to solve. There must, however, be some one first Acquisition of an external object; for every Acquisition cannot lie derivative. Hence, the problem is not to be given up as insoluble, or in itself as impossible. If it is solved by reference to the Original Contract, unless this Contract is extended so as to include the whole human race, Acquisition under it would still remain but provisional.

16.

Exposition of the Conception of a Primary Acquisition of the Soil.

s

All men are originally in a common collective possession of the Soil of the whole Earth (Communio fundi origi- naria), and they have naturally each a Will to use it (Icxjusti). But on account of the opposition of the free / Will of one to that of the other in the sphere of action, which is inevitable by nature, all use of the soil would be prevented did not every will contain at the same time a Law for the regulation of the relation of all Wills m action, according to which a particular possession can be determined to every one upon the common soil. This the juridical Law (lex juridica). But the distributive Law of the Mine and Thine, as applicable to each indi- idual on the soil, according to the Axiom of external Freedom, cannot proceed otherwise than from a primarily

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 95

united Will ti priori which does not presuppose any juridical act as requisite for this union. This Law can only take form in the Civil State (lex justitice distribu tive?) ; as it is in this state alone that the united common Will determines what is right, what is rightful, and what is the constitution of Eight. In reference to this state, however, and prior to its establishment and in view of it, —it is provisorily a Duty for every one to proceed accord ing to the Law of external Acquisition; and accordingly it is a juridical procedure on the part of the Will to lay every one under Obligation to recognise the act of possessing and appropriating, although it be only unilaterally. Hence a provisory Acquisition of the Soil, with all its juridical consequences, is possible in the state of Nature.

Such an Acquisition, however, requires and also obtains the favour of a Permissive Law (Lex permissiva), in respect of the determination of the limits of juridi cally possible Possession. For it precedes the juridical state, and as merely introductory to it is not yet peremptory; and this favour does not extend farther than the date of the consent of the other co-operators in the establishment of the Civil State. But if they are opposed to entering into the Civil State, as long as this opposition lasts it carries all the effect of a guar anteed juridical Acquisition with it, because the advance from the state of nature to the Civil State is founded upon a Duty.

17.

Deduction of the Conception of the original Primary Acquisition.

We have found the Title of Acquisition in a universal original community of the Soil, under the conditions of

00 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

an external Acquisition in space ; and the Mode, of Acquisition is contained in the empirical fact of taking possession (Apprekensio), conjoined with the Will to have an external object as one's own. It is further necessary to unfold from the Principles of the pure juridically Practical Ueason involved in the conception, the juridical Acquisition proper of an object, that is, the external Mine and Thine that follows from the two previous conditions, as IJational Possession (possessio noumenon).

The juridical Conception of the external Mine and Thine, so far as it involves the category of Substance, cannot by ' that which is external to me ' mean merely 1 in a place other than that in which I am ; ' for it is a rational conception. As under the conceptions of the Reason only intellectual conceptions can be embraced, the expression in question can only signify ' something that is different and distinct from me ' according to the idea of a non-empirical Possession through, as it were, a con tinuous activity in taking possession of an external object; and it involves only the notion of ' having something in mi/ power,' which indicates the connection of an object with myself, as a subjective condition of the possibility of making use of it. This forms a purely intellectual conception of the Understanding. Now we can leave out or abstract from the sensible conditions of Posses sion, as relations of a Person to objects which have no obligation. This process of elimination just gives the rational relation of a Person to Persons ; ' and it is such that he can bind them all by an obligation in reference to the use of things through his act of Will, so far as it « conformable to the Axiom of Freedom, the Postulate ight, and the universal Legislation of the common Will conceived as united a priori. This is therefore tlu-

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 97

rational intelligible possession of things as by pure Right, although they are objects of sense.

It is evident that the first modification, limitation, or transformation generally of a portion of the Soil cannot of itself furnish a Title to its Acquisition, since possession of an Accident does not form a ground for legal possession of the Substance, liather, con versely, the inference as to the Mine and Thine must be drawn from ownership of the Substance according to the rule, ' Accessarium sequitur mum principalc.' Hence one who has spent labour on a piece of ground that was not already his own, has lost his effort and work to the former Owner. This position is so evident of itself, that the old opinion to the opposite effect, that is still spread far and wide, can hardly be ascribed to any other than the prevailing illusion which unconsciously leads to the Personification of things ; and, then, as if they could be bound under an obligation by the labour bestowed upon them to be at the service of the person who does the labour, to regard them as his by immediate Kight. Other wise it is probable that the natural question already discussed would not have been passed over with so light a tread, namely, 'How is a Kight in a thing possible ? ' For, Bight as against every possible possessor of a Thing, means only the claim of a particular Will to the use of an object so far as it may be included in the All-comprehending universal Will, and can be thought as in harmony with its law.

As regards bodies situated upon a piece of ground which is already mine, if they otherwise belong to no other Person, they belong to me without my requiring any particular juridical act for the purpose of this Acquisition ; they are mine not facto, but leyc. For they may be regarded as Accidents inhering in the Substance of the Soil, and they are thus mine jure rci rnrcc. To this Category also belongs everything

98 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

which is so connected with anything of mine, that it cannot be separated from what is mine without ilturiii" it substantially. Examples of this are Gildin° on an object, Mixture of a material belonging to me with other things, Alluvial deposit, or even Alteration of the adjoining bed of a stream or river m my favour so as to produce an increase of my land, etc. By the same principles the question must also be 'decided as to whether the acquirable Soil may extend farther than the existing land, so as even to include part of the bed of the Sea, with the Eight to fish on my own shores, to gather Amber and such like. So far as 1 have the mechanical capability from my own Site, as the place I occupy, to secure my Soil from the attack of others and, therefore, as far as Cannon can carry from the shore all is included in my possession, and the sea is thus far closed (mare daumm). But as there is no Site for Occupation upon the wide sea itself, possible possession cannot be extended so far, and the open sea is free (mare libernm). But in the case of men, or things that belong to them, becoming stranded on the Shore, since the fact is not voluntary, it cannot be regarded by the owner of the shore as giving him a Eight of Acquisition. For shipwreck is not an act of Will, nor is its result a lesion to him ; and things which may have come thus upon his Soil, as still belonging to some one, are not to be treated as being without an Owner or Res nullius. On the other hand, a Eiver, so far as possession of the bank reaches, may be originally acquired, like any other piece of ground, under the above restrictions, by one who is in possession of both its banks.

PROPERTY.

An external Object, which, in respect of its Substance, can be claimed by some one as his own, is called the

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 90

PROPERTY (dominium) of that Person to whom all the Eights in it as a thing belong, like the Accidents inhering in a Substance, and which, therefore, he as the Proprietor (dominus) can dispose of at will (jus disponendi de re sua). lint from this it follows at once, that such an object can only be a Corporeal Thing towards which there is no direct personal Obligation. Hence a man may be HIS OWN MASTER (sui juris) but not the Pro prietor of himself (sui dominus), so as to be able to dispose of himself at will, to say nothing of the possi bility of such a relation to other men ; because he is responsible to Humanity in his own person. This point, however, as belonging to the Eight of Humanity as such, rather than to that of individual men, would not be dis cussed at its proper place here, but is only mentioned incidentally for the better elucidation of what has just been said. It may be further observed that there may be two full Proprietors of one and the same thing, with out there being a Mine and Thine in common, but only in so far as they are common Possessors of what belongs only to one of them as Ms own. In such a case the whole Possession without the Use of the thing, belongs to one only of the Co-proprietors (condomini) ; while to the other belongs all the Use of the thing along with its Possession. The former as the direct Proprietor (dominus diredus), therefore, restricts the latter as the Proprietor in use (dominus utilis) to the condition of a certain con tinuous performance, with reference to the thing itself, without limiting him in the use of it.

100 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

SECOND SECTION.

I'lilXCIPLES OF PERSONAL IllGHT.

18.

Nature and Acquisition of Personal Eight, The possession of the active free-will of another person, as the power to determine it by my Will to a

ertain action, Wording to Laws of Freedom » a form of BWit relating to the external Mine and Thine, as dfected by the Causality of another. It is possible to £ several such Bight, in reference to the , «ne Person or to different persons. The Principle of the System of Laws, according to which I can be in such possession,

is that of Personal Hight, and there is only one

Principle. ,

The Acquisition of a Personal Eight can never be primary or arbitrary; for such a mode of acquiring it would not be in accordance with the Principle of the harmony of the freedom of my will with the freedom of every other, and it would therefore be wrong. -Nor can such a Eight be acquired by means of my unjust act of another (faoto injusti alterius), as being itself con trary to Eight/, for if such a wrong as it implies were perpetrated on me, and I could demand satisfaction from the other, in accordance with Eight, yet in such a case I would only be entitled to maintain undiminished what was mine, and not to acquire anything more than what I formerly had.

Acquisition by means of the action of another, to

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 101

which I determine his Will according to Laws of Right, is therefore always derived from what that other has as his own. This derivation, as a Juridical act, cannot be effected by a mere negative relinquiskmcnt or renunciation of what is his (per derelict ionem aut renunciationem) ; because such a negative Act would only amount to a cessation of his Right, and not to the acquirement of a 1 tight on the part of another. It is therefore only by positive TRANSFERENCE (translatio), or CONVEYANCE, that a Personal Right can be acquired ; and this is only possible by means of a common Will, through which objects come into the power of one or other, so that as one renounces a particular thing which he holds under the common Right, the same object when accepted by another, in consequence of a positive act of Will, becomes his. Such transference of the Property of one to another is termed its ALIENATION. The act of the united Wills of two Persons, by which what belonged to one passes to the other, constitutes CONTRACT.

19.

Acquisition by Contract.

In every CONTRACT there are four Juridical Acts of Will involved ; two of them being preparatory Acts, and two of them constitutive Acts. The two Preparatory Acts, as forms of treating in the Transaction, are OFFER (oblatio) and APPROVAL (approbatio) ; the two Constitu tive Acts, as the forms of concluding the transaction, are PROMISE ( promissum) and ACCEPTANCE (acceptatio). For an offer cannot constitute a Promise before it can be judged that the thing offered (oblatum) is something that is ayrceallc to the Party to whom it is offered, and this

102 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

much is shown by the first two declarations; but by them alone there is nothing as yet acquired.

Further, it is neither by the particular Will of the Promisor nor that of the Acceptor that the property of the former passes over to the latter. This is effected only by the combined or united Wills of both, and con sequently so far only as the Will of both is declared at the same time or simultaneously. Now, such simul- taneousness is impossible by empirical acts of declara tion, which can only follow each other in time, and are never actually simultaneous. For if I have promised, and another person is now merely willing to accept, during the interval before actual Acceptance, however short it may be, I may retract my offer, because I am thus far still free ; and, on the other side, the Acceptor, for the same reason, may likewise hold himself not to be bound, up till the moment of Acceptance, by his counter-declaration following upon the Promise. The external Formalities or Solemnities (solemnia) on the conclusion of a Contract, such as shaking hands or breaking a straw (stipula) laid hold of by two persons, and all the various modes of confirming the Declarations on either side, prove in fact the embarrassment of the contracting parties as to how and in what way they may represent Declarations, which are always successive, as existing simultaneously at the same moment ; and these forms fail to do this. They are, by their very nature, Acts necessarily following each other in time, so that when the one Act is, the other either is not yet or is no longer.

It is only the philosophical Transcendental Deduction of the Conception of Acquisition by Contract, that can remove all these difficulties. In a juridical external

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 1 03

relation, my taking possession of the free-will of another, as the cause that determined it to a certain Act, is con ceived at first empirically by means of the declaration and counter-declaration of the free-will of each of us in time, as the sensible conditions of taking possession ; and the two juridical Acts must necessarily be regarded as following one another in time. But because this relation, viewed as juridical, is purely Rational in itself, the Will as a law-giving faculty of Reason represents this possession as intelligible or rational (posscssio noumenon), in accordance with conceptions of Freedom and under abstraction of those empirical conditions. And now, the two Acts of Promise and Acceptance are not regarded as following one another in time, but, in the manner of a pactum re initum, as proceeding from a common Will, which is expressed by the term ' at the same time,' or 'simultaneous,' and the object promised (pro- missum) is represented, under elimination of empirical conditions, as acquired according to the Law of the pure Practical Reason.

That this is the true and only possible Deduction of the idea of Acquisition by Contract, is sufficiently attested by the laborious yet always futile striving of writers on Jurisprudence such as Moses Mendels sohn in his Jerusalem to adduce a proof of its rational possibility. The question is put thus : ' Why ought I to keep my Promise ? ' for it is assumed as understood by all that I ought to do so. It is, how ever, absolutely impossible to give any further proof of the Categorical Imperative implied ; just as it is impossible for the Geometrician to prove by rational Syllogisms that in order to construct a Triangle, I must take three Lines so far an Analytical Pro position of which three Lines any two together must

104 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

be greater than the tliird-a Synthetical Proposition, and like the former a priori. It is a Postulate o the Pure Reason that we ought to abstract from all sensible conditions of Space and Time in reference to the conception of Eight; and the theory of the pos sibility of such Abstraction from these conditions without taking away the reality of the Possession, just constitutes the Transcendental Deduction of the Conception of Acquisition by Contract. It is quite akin to what was presented under the last Title, as the Theory of Acquisition by Occupation of the external object.

20.

What is acquired by Contract ?

But what is that, designated as ' External,' which I acquire by Contract ? As it is only the Causality of the active Will of another, in respect of the Performance of something promised to me, I do not immediately acquire thereby an external Thing, but an Act of the Will in question, whereby a Thing is brought under my power so that I make it mine. By the Contract, there fore, I acquire the Promise of another, as distinguished from the Thing promised ; and yet something is thereby added to my Having and Possession. I have become the riclier in possession (locuplctior) by the Acquisition of an active Obligation that I can bring to bear upon the Freedom and Capability of another. This my Eight, however, is only a personal Plight, valid only to the effect of acting upon a particular physical Person and specially upon the Causality of his Will, so that he shall perform something for me. It is not a Real Right upon that Mural Person, which is identified with the Idea of the united Will of All viewed a priori, and through which

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 105

alone I can acquire a Eight valid against every Possessor of the Tkinfj. For, it is in this that all Eight in a T/tiny consists.

The Transfer or transmission of what is mine to another by Contract, takes place according to the Law of Continuity (Lex Continui). Possession of the object is not interrupted for a moment during this Act; for, otherwise, I would acquire an object in this state as a Thing that had no Possessor, and it would thus be acquired originally ; which is contrary to the idea of a Contract. This Continuity, however, im plies that it is not the particular Will of either the Promiser or the Acceptor, but their united Will in common, that transfers what is mine to another. And hence it is not accomplished in such a manner that the Promiser first relinquishes (derclinquit) his Pos session for the benefit of another, or renounces his Plight (renunciat), and thereupon the other at the same time enters upon it ; or conversely. The Trans fer (translatio) is therefore an Act in which the object belongs for a moment at the same time to both, just as in the parabolic path of a projectile the object on reaching its highest point may be regarded for a moment as at the same time both rising and falling, and as thus passing in fact from the ascending to the falling motion.

21.

Acceptance and Delivery.

A thing is not acquired in a case of Contract by the ACCEPTANCE (acceptatio) of the Promise, but only by the DELIVERY (traditio) of the object promised. For all Promise is relative to Performance ; and if what was promised is a Thing, the Performance cannot be exe cuted otherwise than by an act whereby the Acceptor

106 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

is put by the Promiser into possession of the Thing ; and this is Delivery. Before the Delivery and the Keception of the Thing, the Performance of the act required has not yet taken place ; the Thing has not yet passed from the one person to the other, and consequently has not been acquired by that other. Hence the Eight arising from a Contract, is only a Personal Right ; and it only becomes a Heal Right by Delivery.

A Contract upon which Delivery immediately follows (pactum re initum) excludes any interval of time between its conclusion and its execution ; and as such it requires no further particular act in the future by which one person may transfer to another what is his. But if there, is a time definite or indefinite- agreed upon between them for the Delivery, the question then arises, Whether the Thing has already before that time become the Acceptor's by the Con tract, so that his Right is a Right in the Thing ; or whether a further special Contract regarding the Delivery alone must be entered upon, so that the Rii*ht that is acquired by mere Acceptance is only a Personal Right, and thus it does not become a Right in the Thing until Delivery ? That the relation must be determined according to the latter alternative, will be clear from what follows.

Suppose I conclude a Contract about a Thing that I wish to acquire, such as a Horse, and that I take- it immediately into my Stable, or otherwise into my possession ; then it is mine (vi pacti re initi), and my Right is a Right in the Thing. But if I leave it in the hands of the Seller without arranging with him specially in whose physical possession or holding (detentio) this Tiling shall be before my taking pos session of it (apprehensio), and consequently before the actual change of possession, the Horse is not yet mine ; and the Right which 1 acquire is only a Right

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 107

against a particular Person namely, the Seller of the Horse to be put into possession of the object (posccndi traditionem) as the subjective condition of any use of it at my will. My Eight is thus only a Personal Itight to demand from the Seller the performance of his promise (prccstatio) to put me into possession of the thing. Now, if the Contract does not contain the condition of Delivery at the same time, as a pactum re initum, and consequently an interval of time in tervenes between the conclusion of the Contract and the taking possession of the object of acquisition, I cannot obtain possession of it during this interval otherwise than by exercising the particular juridical activity called a possessory Act (actum posse ssorium) which constitutes a special Contract. This Act con sists in my saying, ' I will send to fetch the horse/ to which the Seller has to agree. For it is not self- evident or universally reasonable, that any one will take a Tiling destined for the use of another into his charge at his own risk. On the contrary, a special Contract is necessary for this arrangement, according to which the Alienator of a thing continues to be its owner during a certain definite time, and must bear the risk of whatever may happen to it ; while the Acquirer can only be regarded by the Seller as the Owner, when he has delayed to enter into possession beyond the date at which he agreed to take delivery. Prior to the Possessory Act, therefore, all that is acquired by the Contract is only a Personal Uight ; and the Acceptor can acquire an external Thing only by Delivery.

10S KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

THIRD SECTION.

PRINCIPLES OF PERSONAL RIGHT THAT IS REAL IN KlND.

(Jus realiter personale.)

22.

Nature of Personal Right of a Real Kind.

Personal Right of a real kind is the Right to the possession of an external object AS A THING, and to the use of it AS A PERSON. The Mine and Thine embraced under this Right relate specially to the Family and Household ; and the relations involved are those of free beings in reciprocal real interaction with each other. Through their relations and influence as Persons upon one another, in accordance with the principle of external Freedom as the cause of it, they form a Society com posed as a whole of members standing in community with each other as Persons ; and this constitutes the HOUSEHOLD. The mode in which this social status is acquired by individuals, and the functions which prevail within it, proceed neither by arbitrary individual action (facto), nor by mere Contract (pacto), but by Law (lege). And this Law as being not only a Right, but also as con stituting Possession in reference to a Person, is a Right rising above all mere Real and Personal Right. It must, in fact, form the Right of Humanity in our own Person ; and, as such, it has as its consequence a natural Per missive Law, by the favour of which such Acquisition becomes possible to us.

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 109

23.

What is acquired in the Household?

The Acquisition that is founded upon this Law is, as regards its objects, threefold. The Man acquires a WIFE ; the Husband and Wife acquire CHILDREN, constituting a Family ; and the Family acquire DOMESTICS. All these objects, while acquirable, are inalienable ; and the Right of Possession in these objects is the most strictly 2lcrsoJlfl^ of all Rights.

THE RIGHTS OF THE FAMILY AS A DOMESTIC SOCIETY.

T I T L E FIRS T.

CONJUGAL RIGHT. (Husband and Wife.)

24. The Natural Basis of Marriage.

The domestic Relations are founded on Marriage, and Marriage is founded upon the natural Reciprocity or intercommunity (commercium) of the Sexes.1 This natural

1 Commercium nexua.lt est u*ux membrorum ft facn/fahtm texualiwn altering. This ' UBUX' is either natural, by winch human beings may reproduce their own kind, or unnatural, which, again, refers either to a person of the same sex or to an animal of another species than num. These transgressions of all Law, as ' crimina carnix contra ncUuram,' are even ' not to be named ;' and as wrongs against all Humanity in the Person they cannot be saved, by any limitation or exception whatever, from entire reprobation.

110 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

union of the sexes proceeds either according to the mere animal Nature (vaga libido, vcnus vulgivaga, fornicatio), or according to Law. The latter is MARRIAGE (matri- monium), which is the Union of two Persons of different sex for life -long reciprocal possession of their sexual faculties. The End of producing and educating children may be regarded as always the End of Nature in im planting mutual desire and inclination in the sexes ; but it is not necessary for the rightfulness of marriage that those who marry should set this before themselves as the End of their Union, otherwise the Marriage would be dissolved of itself when the production of children ceased.

And even assuming that enjoyment in the reciprocal use of the sexual endowments is an end of marriage, yet the Contract of Marriage is not on that account a matter of arbitrary will, but is a Contract necessary in its nature by the Law of Humanity. In other words, if a man and a woman have the will to enter on reciprocal enjoyment in accordance with their sexual nature, they must necessarily marry each other; and this necessity is in accordance with the juridical Laws of Pure Pieason.

25.

The Rational Right of Marriage.

For, this natural ' Commercium ' as a ' usus mem- Irorum scxnalium alterius ' is an enjoyment for which the one person is given up to the other. In this rela tion the human individual makes himself a ' res,' which is contrary to the Right of Humanity in his own Person. This, however, is only possible under the one condition,

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. Ill

that as the one Person is acquired by the other as a res, that same Person also equally acquires the other recipro cally, and thus regains and re-establishes the rational Personality. The Acquisition of a part of the human organism being, on account of its unity, at the same time the acquisition of the whole Person, it follows that the surrender and acceptation of, or by, one sex in relation to the other, is not only permissible under the condition of Marriage, but is further only really possible under that condition. But the Personal Eight thus acquired is at the same time, real in kind ; and this characteristic of it is established by the fact that if one of the married Persons run away or enter into the possession of another, the other is entitled, at any time, and incontestably, to bring such a one back to the former relation, as if that Person were a Thing.

26.

Monogamy and Equality in Marriage.

For the same reasons, the relation of the Married Persons to each other is a relation of EQUALITY as regards the mutual possession of their Persons, as well as of their Goods. Consequently Marriage is only truly realized in MONOGAMY; for in the relation of Polygamy the Person who is given away on the one side, gains only a part of the one to whom that Person is given up, and therefore becomes a mere res. But in respect of their Goods, they have severally the Plight to renounce the use of any part of them, although only by a special Contract.

From the Principle thus stated, it also follows that Concubinage is as little capable of being brought

1 2 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

under a Contract of Right, as the hiring of a person on any one occasion, in the way of a pactum forni- cationis. For, as regards such a Contract as this latter relation would imply, it must be admitted by all that any one who might enter into it could not be legally held to the fulfilment of their promise if they wished to resile from it. And as regards the former, a Contract of Concubinage would also fall as a padum tiLrpe; because as a Contract of the hire (locatio, condudio), of a part for the use of another, on account of the inseparable unity of the members of a Person, any one entering into such a Contract would be actually surrendering as a res to the arbi trary Will of another. Hence any party may annul a Contract like this if entered into with any other, at any time and at pleasure ; and that other would have no ground, in the circumstances, to complain of a lesion of his Eight. The same holds likewise of a morganatic or ' left-hand ' Marriage contracted in order to turn the inequality in the social status of the two parties to advantage in the way of establishing the social supremacy of the one over the other ; for, in fact, such a relation is not really different from Concubinage, according to the principles of Natural Eight, and therefore does not constitute a real Marriage. Hence the question may be raised as to whether it is not contrary to the Equality of married Persons when the Law says in any way of the Hus band in relation to the Wife, ' he shall be thy master,' so that he is represented as the one who commands, and she as the one who obeys. This, however, cannot be regarded as contrary to the natural Equality of a human pair, if such legal Supremacy is based only upon the natural superiority of the faculties of the Husband compared with the Wife, in the effectuation of the common interest of the household ; and if the Right to command, is based merely upon this fact. For this Plight may thus be deduced from the very

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 113

duty of Unity and Equality in relation to the End involved.

27.

Fulfilment of the Contract of Marriage.

The Contract of Marriage is completed only by con jugal cohabitation. A Contract of two Persons of different sex, with the secret understanding either to abstain from conjugal cohabitation or with the conscious ness on either side of incapacity for it, is a simulated Contract ; it does not constitute a marriage, and it may be dissolved by either of the parties at will. But if the incapacity only arises after marriage, the Eight of the Contract is not annulled or diminished by a contingency that cannot be legally blamed.

The Acquisition of a Spouse either as a Husband or as a Wife, is therefore not constituted facto that is, by Cohabitation without a preceding Contract ; nor even pacto by a mere Contract of Marriage, without subse quent Cohabitation ; but only lege, that is, as a juridical consequence of the obligation that is formed by two Persons entering into a sexual Union solely on the basis of a reciprocal Possession of each other, which Possession at the same time is only effected in reality by the reciprocal ' usus facultatum sexualium alterius.'

KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

RIGHTS OF THE FAMILY AS A DOMESTIC SOCIETY.

TITLE SECOND.

PARENTAL EIGHT.

(Parent and Child.)

28.

The Relation of Parent and Child.

From the Duty of Man towards himself that is, towards the Humanity in his own Person there thus arises a personal Eight on the part of the Members of the opposite sexes, as Persons, to acquire one another really and reciprocally by Marriage. In like manner, from the fact of Procreation in the union thus con stituted, there follows the Duty of preserving and rearing Children as the Products of this Union. Accordingly Children, as Persons, have, at the same time, an original congenital Eight distinguished from mere hereditary Eight to be reared by the care of their Parents till they are capable of maintaining themselves ; and this pro vision becomes immediately theirs by Law, without any particular juridical Act being required to determine it.

For what is thus produced is a Person, and it is impossible to think of a Being endowed with personal Freedom as produced merely by a physical process. And hence, in the practical relation, it is quite a correct and even a necessary Idea to regard the act of generation as a process by which a Person is brought without his

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 115

consent into the world, and placed in it by the respon sible free will of others. This Act, therefore, attaches an obligation to the Parents to make their Children as far as their power goes contented with the condition thus acquired. Hence Parents cannot regard their Child as, in a manner, a Thing of their own making, for a Being endowed with Freedom cannot be so regarded. Nor, consequently, have they a Right to destroy it as if it were their own property, or even to leave it to chance; because they have brought a Being into the world who becomes in fact a Citizen of the world, and they have placed that Being in a state which they cannot be left to treat with indifference, even according to the natural conceptions of Right.

We cannot even conceive how it is possible that GOD can create FREE Beings ; for it appears as if all their future actions, being predetermined by that first act, would be contained in the chain of natural necessity, and that, therefore, they could not be free. But as men we are free in fact, as is proved by the Categorical Imperative in the moral and practical relation as an authoritative decision of Reason ; yet reason cannot make the possibility of such a relation of Cause to Effect conceivable from the theoretical point of view, because they are both suprasensible. All that can be demanded of Reason under these conditions, would merely be to prove that there is no Contradiction involved in the conception of a CREATION OF FREE BEINGS ; and this may be done by showing that Contradiction only arises when, alon^ with the Category of Causality, the Conilition of Time is transferred to the relation of suprasensible Things. This condition, as implying that the cause of an effect must precede the effect as its reason, is inevitable in thinking the relation of objects of sense to one

116 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

another ; and if this conception of Causality were to have objective reality given to it in the theoretical bearing, it would also have to be referred to the suprasensible sphere. But the Contradiction vanishes when the pure Category, apart from any sensible conditions, is applied from the moral and practical point of view, and consequently as in a non-sensible relation to the conception of Creation.

The philosophical Jurist will not regard this in vestigation, when thus carried back even to the ultimate Principles of the Transcendental Philosophy, as an unnecessary subtlety in a Metaphysic of Morals, or as losing itself in aimless obscurity, when he takes into consideration the difficulty of the problem to be solved, and also the necessity of doing justice in this inquiry to the ultimate relations of the Principles of Right.

29.

The Rights of the Parent.

From the Duty thus indicated, there further neces sarily arises the Right of the Parents to THE MANAGE MENT AND TRAINING OF THE CHILD, so long as it is itself incapable of making proper use of its body as an Organism, and of its mind as an Understanding. This involves its nourishment and the care of its Education. This includes, in general, the function of forming and developing it practically, that it may be able in the future to maintain and advance itself, and also its moral Culture and Development, the guilt of neglecting it falling upon the Parents. All this training is to be con tinued till the Child reaches the period of Emancipation (emancipatio), as the age of practicable self-support. The Parents then virtually renounce the parental Right to command, as well as all claim to repayment for their

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 11?

previous care and trouble ; for which care and trouble, after the process of Education is complete, they can only appeal to the Children by way of any claim, on the ground of the Obligation of Gratitude as a Duty of Virtue.

From the fact of Personality in the Children, it further follows that they can never be regarded as the Property of the Parents, but only as belonging to them by way of being in their possession, like other things that are held apart from the possession of all others and that can be brought back even against the will of the Subjects. Hence the Eight of the Parents is not a purely Eeal Plight, and it is not alienable (jus personalissimum). But neither is it a merely Personal Right ; it is a Personal Eight of a real kind, that is, a Personal Eight that is constituted and exercised after the manner of a Eeal Eight.

It is therefore evident that the Title of a Personal lliyht of a Eeal Kind must necessarily be added, in the Science of Eight, to the Titles of Eeal Eight and Personal Eight, the Division of Eights into these two being not complete. For, if the Eight of the Parents to the Children were treated as if it were merely a Eeal Eight to a part of what belongs to their house, they could not found only upon the Duty of the Children to return to them in claiming them when they run away, but they would be then entitled to seize them and to impound them like things or runaway cattle.

118 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

EIGHTS OF THE FAMILY AS A DOMESTIC SOCIETY.

TITLE THIKD.

HOUSEHOLD EIGHT. (Master and Servant.)

30.

Relation and Eight of the Master of a Household.

The Children of the House, who, along with the Parents, constitute a Family, attain majority, and become MASTERS OF THEMSELVES (majorennes, sui juris), even without a Contract of release from their previous state of Dependence, by their actually attaining to the capability of self-maintenance. This attainment arises, on the one hand, as a state of natural Majority, with the advance of years in the general course of Nature ; and, on the other hand, it takes form, as a state in accordance with their own natural condition. They thus acquire the Eight of being their own Masters, without the interposition of any special juridical act, and therefore merely by Law (lege) ; and they owe their Parents nothing by way of legal debt for their Education, just as the parents, on their side, are now released from their Obligations to the Children in the same way. Parents and Children thus gain or regain their natural Freedom ; and the domestic society, which was necessary according to the Law of Eight, is Jthus naturally dissolved.

Uotli Parties, however, may resolve to continue the

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 119

Household, but under another mode of Obligation. It may assume the form of a relation between the Head of the House as its Master, and the other members as domestic Servants, male or female; and the connection between them in this new regulated domestic economy (societas herilis) may be determined by Contract. The Master of the House, actually or virtually, enters into Contract with the Children, now become major and masters of themselves ; or, if there be no Children in the Family, with other free Persons constituting the member ship of the Household ; and thus there is established a domestic relationship not founded on social equality, but such that one commands as Master, and another obeys as Servant (Imperantis et subjecti Domestic!).

The Domestics or Servants may then be regarded by the Master of the household, as thus far his. As regards the form or mode of his Possession of them, they belong to him as if by a Eeal Eight ; for if any of them run away, he is entitled to bring them again under his power by a unilateral act of his will. But as regards the matter of his Eight, or the use he is entitled to make of such persons as his Domestics, he is not entitled to con duct himself towards them as if he was their proprietor or owner (domimis servi) ; because they are only subjected to his power by Contract, and by a Contract under certain definite restrictions. For a Contract by which the one party renounced his whole freedom for the ad vantage of the other, ceasing thereby to be a person and consequently having no duty even to observe a Contract, is self -contradictory, and is therefore of itself null and void. The question as to the Eight of Property in relation to one who has lost his legal personality by a Crime, does not concern us here.

120 KAXT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

This Contract, then, of the Master of a Household with his Domestics, cannot be of such a nature that the use of them could ever rightly become an abuse of them ; and the judgment as to what constitutes use or abuse in such circumstances is not left merely to the Master, but is also competent to the Servants, who ought never to be held in bondage or bodily servitude as Slaves or Serfs. Such a Contract cannot, therefore, be concluded for life, but in all cases only for a definite period, within which one party may intimate to the other a termination of their connection. Children, however, including even the children of one who has become enslaved owing to a Crime, are always free. For every man is born free, because he has at birth as yet broken no Law ; and even the cost of his education till his maturity, cannot be reckoned as a debt which he is bound to pay. Even a Slave, if it were in his power, would be bound to educate his children without being entitled to count and reckon with them for the cost ; and in view of his own inca pacity for discharging this function, the Possessor of a Slave, therefore, enters upon the Obligation which he has rendered the Slave himself unable to fulfil.

Here, again, as under the first two Titles, it is clear that there is a Personal Eight of a Real kind, in the relation of the Master of a House to his Domestics. For he can legally demand them as belonging to what is externally his, from any other possessor of them ; and he is entitled to fetch them back to his house, even before the reasons that may have led them to run away, and their particular Right in the circum stances, have been judicially investigated. [See Sup plementary Explanations, I. u. m.]

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 121

SYSTEMATIC DIVISION

OF ALL THE RIGHTS CAPABLE OF BEING ACQUIRED BY CONTRACT.

31.

Division of Contracts. Juridical Conceptions of Money and A Book.

It is reasonable to demand that a metaphysical Science <>f Kight shall completely and definitely determine the members of a logical Division of its Conceptions & priori, and thus establish them in a genuine System. All empirical Division, on the other hand, is merely fragmen tary Partition, and it leaves us in uncertainty as to whether there may not be more members still required to complete the whole sphere of the divided Conception. A Division that is made according to a Principle & priori may be called, in contrast to all empirical Partitions, a dogmatic Division.

Every Contract, regarded in itself objectively, consists of two juridical Acts : the PROMISE and its ACCEPTANCE. Acquisition by the latter, unless it be a pactum re initum which requires Delivery, is not a part, but the juridically necessary Consequence of the Contract. Considered again subjectively, or as to whether the Acquisition, which ought to happen as a necessary Consequence according to Reason, will also follow, in fact, as a physical Conse quence, it is evident that I have no Security or Guarantee that this will happen by the mere Acceptance of a Pro mise. There is therefore something externally required

122 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

connected with the mode of the Contract, in reference to the certainty of Acquisition by it ; and this can only be some element completing and determining the Means necessary to the attainment of Acquisition as realizing the purpose of the Contract. And in his connection and behoof, three Persons are required to intervene the PKOMISER, the ACCEPTOR, and the CAUTIONER or Surety. The importance of the Cautioner is evident ; but by his intervention and his special Contract with the Promiser, the Acceptor gains nothing in respect of the Object, but the means of Compulsion that enable him to obtain what is his own.

According to these rational Principles of logical Divi sion, there are properly only three pure and simple Modes of Contract. There are, however, innumerable mixed and empirical Modes, adding statutory and conventional Forms to the Principles of the Mine and Thine that are in accordance with rational Laws. But they lie outside of the circle of the Metaphysical Science of Plight, whose Itational Modes of Contract can alone be indicated here.

All Contracts are founded upon a purpose of Acquisi tion, and are either

A. GRATUITOUS CONTRACTS, with unilateral Acquisi

tion; or

B. ONEROUS CONTRACTS, with reciprocal Acquisition; or

C. CAUTIONARY CONTRACTS, with no Acquisition,

lut only Guarantee of what has leen already acquired. These Contracts may be gratuitous on the one side, and yet, at the same time, onerous on the other.

A. THE GRATUITOUS CONTRACTS (pacta gratuita) are— 1. Depositation (depositum), involving the Preser vation of some valuable deposited in Trust.

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 123

2. Commodate (commodatum), a Loan of the use of

a Thing.

3. Donation (donatio), a free Gift.

B. THE ONEROUS CONTRACTS, are Contracts either of Permutation or of Hiring.

I. CONTRACTS OF PERMUTATION OR EECIPROCAL

EXCHANGE (permutatio late sic dicta) :

1. Barter, or strictly real Exchange (permutatio

stride sic dicta). Goods exchanged for Goods.

2. Purchase and Sale (emptio venditio). Goods

exchanged for Money.

3. Loan (mutuum). Loan of a fungible under

condition of its being returned in kind : Corn for Corn, or Money for Money.

II. CONTRACTS OF LETTING AND HIRING (locatio con-

ductio) :

1. Letting of a Thing on Hire to another person

who is to make use of it (locatio rei). If the Thing can only be restored in specie, it may be the subject of an Onerous Con tract combining the consideration of Interest with it (pactum usurarium).

2. Letting of Work on Hire (locatio opera1).

Consent to the use of my Powers by another for a certain Price (mcrces). The Worker under this Contract is a hired Servant (mercenarius).

3. Mandate (mandatum). The Contract of Man

date is an engagement to perform or execute a certain business in place and in name of another person. If the action is merely done in the place of another, but

124 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

not, at the same time, in his name, it is performance without Commission (fjcstio ncgotii) ; but if it is (rightfully) performed in name of the other, it constitutes Man date, which as a Contract of Procuration is an onerous Contract (mandatum onerosum).

C. THE CAUTIONAKY CONTRACTS (cautiones) are :

1. Pledge (pignus). Caution by a Moveable

deposited as security.

2. Suretyship (fidcjussio). Caution for the ful

filment of the promise of another. :>. Personal Security (prcestatio obsidis). Guar antee of Personal Performance.

This List of all the modes in which the property of one Person may be transferred or conveyed to another, includes conceptions of certain objects or Instruments required for such transference (translatio). These appear to be entirely empirical, and it may therefore seem questionable whether they are entitled to a place in a Metaphysical Science of Eight. For, in such a Science the Divisions must be made according to Principles a priori; and hence the matter of the juridical relation, which may be conventional, ought to be left out of account, and only its Form should be taken into consideration.

Such conceptions may be illustrated by taking the instance of Money, in contradistinction from all other exchangeable things as Wares and Merchandise ; or by the case of a Boole. And considering these as illustra tive examples in this connection, it will be shown that the conception of MONEY as the greatest and most usealle of all the Means of human intercommunication through Things, in the way of Purchase and Sale in commerce,

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 125

as well as that of Books as the greatest Means of carry ing on the interchange of Thought, resolve themselves into relations that are purely intellectual and rational. And hence it will be made evident that such Conceptions do not really detract from the purity of the given Scheme of pure Rational Contracts, by empirical admixture.

ILLUSTRATION OF RELATIONS OF CONTRACT BY THE CONCEPTIONS OF MONEY AND A BOOK.

I. What is Money ?

MONEY is a tiling which can only be made use of, by being alienated or exchanged. This is a good Nominal Definition, as given by Achenwall ; and it is sufficient to distinguish objects of the Will of this kind from all other objects. But it gives us no information regarding the rational possibility of such a thing as money is. Yet we see thus much by the Definition : (1) that the Alienation in this mode of human intercommunication and exchange is not viewed as a Gift, but is intended as a mode of reciprocal Acquisition by an Onerous Contract ; and (2) that it is regarded as a mere means of carrying on Commerce, universally adopted by the people, but having no value as such of itself, in contrast to other Things as mercantile Goods or Wares which have a particular value in relation to special wants existing among the people. It therefore represents all exchange able things.

A bushel of Corn has the greatest direct value as a means of satisfying human wants. Cattle may be fed by it ; and these again are subservient to our nourish ment and locomotion, and they even labour in our stead. Thus by means of corn men are multiplied and sup-

126 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

ported, who not only act again in reproducing such natural products, but also by other artificial products they can come to the relief of all our proper wants. Thus are men enabled to build dwellings, to prepare clothing, and to supply all the ingenious comforts and enjoyments which make up the products of industry. On the other hand, the value of Money is only indirect. It cannot be itself enjoyed, nor be used directly for enjoyment ; it is, however, a Means towards this, and of all outward things it is of the highest utility.

We may found a Real Definition of Money provi sionally upon these considerations. It may thus be defined as the universal means of carrying on the INDUSTRY of men in exchanging intercommunications with each other. Hence national Wealth, in so far as it can be acquired by means of Money, is properly only the sum of the Industry or applied Labour with which men pay each other, and which is represented by the Money in circulation among the people.

The Thing which is to be called Money must, there fore, have cost as much Industry to produce it, or even to put it into the hands of others, as may be equivalent to the Industry or Labour required for the acquisition of the Goods or Wares or Merchandise, as natural or artificial products, for which it is exchanged. For if it were easier to procure the material which is called Money than the goods that are required, there would be more Money in the market than goods to be sold ; and because the Seller would then have to expend more labour upon his goods than the Buyer on the equivalent, the Money coming in to him more rapidly, the Labour applied to the preparation of goods and Industry generally, with the industrial productivity which is the source of the

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 127

public Wealth, would at the same time dwindle and be cut down. Hence Bank Notes and Assignations are not to be regarded as Money although they may take its place by way of representing it for a time ; because it costs almost no Labour to prepare them, and their value is based merely upon the opinion prevailing as to the further continuance of the previous possibility of chang ing them into Ready Money. But on its being in any way found out that there is not Ready Money in suffi cient quantity for easy and safe conversion of such Notes or Assignations, the opinion gives way, and a fall in their value becomes inevitable. Thus the industrial Labour of those who work the Gold and Silver Mines in Peru and Mexico especially on account of the frequent failures in the application of fruitless efforts to discover new veins of these precious metals is probably even greater than what is expended in the manufacture of Goods in Europe. Hence such mining Labour, as un rewarded in the circumstances, would be abandoned of itself, and the countries mentioned would in consequence soon sink into poverty, did not the Industry of Europe, stimulated in turn by these very metals, proportionally expand at the same time so as constantly to keep up the zeal of the Miners in their work by the articles of luxury thereby ottered to them. It is thus that the concurrence of Industry with Industry, and of Labour with Labour, is always maintained.

But how is it possible that what at the beginning constituted only Goods or Wares, at length became Money ? This has happened wherever a Sovereign as a great and powerful consumer of a particular substance, which he at first used merely for the adornment and decoration of his servants and court, has enforced the

128 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

tribute of his subjects in this kind of material. Thus it may have been Gold, or Silver, or Copper, or a species of beautiful shells called Cowries, or even a sort of mat called Makutcs, as in Congo ; or Ingots of Iron, as in Senegal; or Negro Slaves, as on the Guinea Coast. When the Baler of the country demanded such things as im posts, those whose Labour had to be put in motion to procure them were also paid by means of them, accord ing to certain regulations of commerce then established, as in a Market or Exchange. As it appears to me, it is only thus that a particular species of goods came to be made a legal means of carrying on the industrial labour of the Subjects in their commerce with each other, and thereby forming the medium of the national Wealth. And thus it practically became MONEY.

The Rational Conception of Money, under which the empirical conception is embraced, is therefore that of a thing which, in the course of the public permutation or Exchange of possessions (pcrmutatio pullica), deter mines the Price of all the other things that form products or Goods under which term even the Sciences are included, in so far as they are not taught gratis to others. The quantity of it among a people constitutes their Wealth (opulentia). For Price (pretium) is the public judgment about the Value of a thing, in relation to the proportionate abundance of what forms the universal representative means in circulation for carrying on the reciprocal interchange of the products of Industry or Labour.1 The precious metals, when they are not merely

1 Hence where Commerce is extensive neither Gold nor Copper is specially used as Money, but only as constituting wares ; because there u too little of the first and too much of the second for them to be easily brought into circulation, so as at once to have the former in such small

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 129

-weighed but also stamped or provided with a sign indicating how much they are worth, form legal Money, and are called Coin.

According to Adam Smith, ' Money has become, in nil civilised nations, the universal instrument of Com merce, by the intervention of which Goods of all kinds are bought and sold or exchanged for one another.' This Definition expands the empirical conception of Money to the rational idea of it, by taking regard only to the implied form of the Reciprocal Performances in the Onerous Contracts, and thus abstracting from their matter. It is thus conformable to the conception of Eight in the Permutation and Exchange of the Mine and Thine generally (commutatio late sic dicta). The Definition, therefore, accords with the representation in the above Synopsis of a Dogmatic Division of Contracts a priori, and consequently with the Metaphysical Principle of Right in general.

II. What is a Book ?

A Book is a Writing which contains a Discourse addressed by some one to the Public, through visible signs of Speech. It is a matter of indifference to the present considerations whether it is written by a pen or imprinted by types, and on few or many pages. He who speaks to the Public in his own name, is the AUTHOR.

pieces as are necessary in payment for particular goods and not to have the latter in great quantity in case of the smallest acquisitions. Hence SILVER more or less alloyed with Copper is taken as the proper material of Money, and the Measure of the calculation of all Prices in the great commercial intercommunications of the world ; and the other Metals and still more non-metallic substances— can only take its place in the rase of a people of limited commerce.

I

130 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

He who addresses the writing to the Public in the name of the Author, is the PUBLISHER. When a Publisher does this with the permission or authority of the Author, the act is in accordance with Kight, and he is the right ful Publisher ; but if this is clone without such permis sion or authority, the act is contrary to Eight, and the Publisher is a counterfeiter or unlawful Publisher. The whole of a set of Copies of the original Document, is called an Edition.

The unauthorized Publishing of Books is contrary to the Principles of Right, and is rightly prohibited.

A Writing is not an immediate direct presentation of a conception, as is the case, for instance, with an Engrav ing that exhibits a Portrait, or a Bust or Caste by a Sculptor. It is a Discourse addressed in a particular form to the Public ; and the Author may be said to speak publicly by means of his Publisher. The Publisher, again, speaks by the aid of the Printer as his workman (operarius), yet not in his own name, for otherwise he would be the Author, but in the name of the Author ; and he is only entitled to do so in virtue of a MANDATE given him to that effect by the Author. Now the un authorized Printer and Publisher speaks by an assumed authority in his Publication ; in the name indeed of the Author, but without a Mandate to that effect (gerit se 'niandatarium absque mandato). Consequently such an unauthorized Publication is a wrong committed upon the authorized and only lawful Publisher, as it amounts to a pilfering of the Profits which the latter was entitled and able to draw from the use of his proper Plight (furtum usus). Unauthorized Printing and Publication of Books

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 131

is therefore forbidden as an act Counterfeit and Piracy on the ground of Eight.

There seems, however, to be an impression that there is a sort of common Right to print and publish Books ; but the slightest reflection must convince any one that this would be a great injustice. The reason of it is found simply in the fact that a Book, regarded from one point of view, is an external product of mechanical art (opus imclumicum), that can be imitated by any one who may be in rightful possession of a Copy ; and it is therefore his by a Real Riglit. But from another point of view, a Book is not merely an external Thing, but is a Discourse of the Publisher to the public, and he is only entitled to do this publicly under the Mandate of the Author (prce- statio operce) ; and this constitutes a Personal Right. The error underlying the impression referred to, therefore, arises from an interchange and confusion of these two kinds of Right in relation to Books.

Confusion of Personal Right and Real Right.

The confusion of Personal Right with Real Right may be likewise shown by reference to a difference of view in connection with another Contract, falling under the head of Contracts of Hiring (B. II. 1), namely, the Con tract of LEASE (jus incolatus). The question is raised as to whether a Proprietor when he lias sold a house or a piece of ground held on lease, before the expiry of the period of Lease, was bound to add the condition of the continuance of the Lease to the Contract of Purchase ; or whether it should be held that ' Purchase breaks Hire/ of course under reservation of a period of warning deter mined by the nature of the subject in use. In the

132 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

former view, a house or farm would be regarded as having a Burden lying upon it, constituting a Eeal Eight acquired in it by the Lessee; and this might well enough be carried out by a clause merely indorsing or ingrossing the Contract of Lease in the Deed of Sale. But as it would no longer then be a simple Lease, another Contract would properly be required to be conjoined, a matter which few Lessors would be disposed to grant. The proposition, then, that ' Purchase breaks Hire ' holds in principle ; for the full Eight in a Thing as a Property, overbears all Personal Eight which is inconsistent with it. But there remains a Eight of Action to the Lessee, on the ground of a Personal Eight for indemnification on account of any loss arising from breaking of the Contract. [See Supplementary Explanations, IV.]

EPISODICAL SECTION.

THE IDEAL ACQUISITION OF EXTERNAL OBJECTS OF THE WILL.

32.

The Nature and Modes of Ideal Acquisition.

I call that mode of Acquisition ideal which involves no Causality in time, and which is founded upon a mere Idea of pure reason. It is nevertheless actual, and not merely imaginary Acquisition ; and it is not called real only because the Act of Acquisition is not empirical. This character of the Act arises from the peculiarity that the Person acquiring, acquires from another who either is not yet, and who can only be regarded as a possible Being,

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 133

or who is just ceasing to be, or who no longer is. Hence such a mode of attaining to Possession is to be regarded as a mere practical Idea of Keason.

There are three Modes of Ideal Acquisition :

I. Acquisition by USUCAPION ; II. Acquisition by INHERITANCE or SUCCESSION;

III. Acquisition by UNDYING MKKIT (meritum im- inortalc), or the Claim by Right to a good name at Death.

These three Modes of Acquisition can, as a matter of fact, only have effect in a public juridical state of existence, but they are not founded merely upon the Civil Constitution or upon arbitrary Statutes ; they are already contained in 'priori in the conception of the state of Nature, and are thus necessarily conceivable prior to their empirical manifestation. The Laws regarding them in the Civil Constitution ought to be regulated by that rational Conception.

33.

I. Acquisition by Usucapion. (Acquisitio per Usucapionem.)

I may acquire the Property of another merely by Ion;/ possession and use of it (Usucapio). Such Property is not acquired, because I may legitimately presume that his Consent is given to this effect (per conscnsum prcc- mmptum) ; nor because I can assume that as he does not oppose my Acquisition of it, he has relinquished or aban doned it as his (rem derelictam). But I acquire it thus, because even if there were any one actually raising a claim to this Property as its true Owner, I may exclude him on the ground of my long Possession of it, ignore his previous existence, and proceed as if he existed

134 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

durin^ the time of my Possession as a mere abstraction, although I may have been subsequently apprized of his reality as well as of his claim. This Mode of Acquisi tion is not quite correctly designated Acquisition by Prescription (per proscription*™) ; for the exclusion of all other claimants is to be regarded as only the Conse quence of the Usucapion; and the process of Acquisition must have gone before the Right of Exclusion. The rational possibility of such a Mode of Acquisition, has now to be proved.

Any one who does not exercise a continuous possessory activity (actus possessorius) in relation to a Thing as his, is regarded with good Eight as one who does not at all exist as its Possessor. For he cannot complain of lesion so long as he does not qualify himself with a Title as its Possessor. And even if he should afterwards lay claim to the Thing when another has already taken possession of it, he only says he was once on a time Owner of it, but not that he is so still, or that his Possession has continued without interruption as a juridical fact. It can, therefore, only be by a juridical process of Posses sion, that has been maintained without interruption and is proveable by documentary fact, that any one can secure for himself what is his own after ceasing for a long time to make use of it.

For, suppose that the neglect to exercise this posses sory activity had not the effect of enabling another to found upon his hitherto lawful, undisputed and lona fid*' Possession, an irrefragable Eight to continue in its pos session so that he may regard the thing that is thus in his Possession as acquired by him. Then no Acquisition would ever become peremptory and secured, but all Acquisition would only be provisory and temporary. This

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 135

is evident on the ground that there are no historical Uecords available to carry the investigation of a Title back to the first Possessor and his act of Acquisition. The Presumption upon which Acquisition by Usucapion is founded is, therefore, not merely its conformity to llight as allowed and just, but also the presumption of its being Eight (prcesumtio juris ct de jure), and its being assumed to be in accordance with compulsory Laws (snppositio legalis). Any one who has neglected to embody his possessory Act in a documentary Title, has lost his Claim to the Eight of being Possessor for the time ; and the length of the period of his neglecting to do so which need not necessarily be particularly defined can be referred to only as establishing the certainty of this neglect. And it would contradict the Postulate of the Juridically Practical Reason to maintain that one hitherto unknown as a Possessor, and whose possessory activity has at least been interrupted, whether by or without fault of his own, could always at any time re- acquire a Property; for this would be to make all Ownership uncertain (Dominia rerum incerta facere).

But if he is a member of the Commonwealth or Civil Union, the State may maintain his Possession for him vicariously, although it may be interrupted as private Possession ; and in that case the actual Possessor will not be able to prove a Title of Acquisition even from a first occupation, nor to found upon a Title of Usucapion. But in the state of Nature Usucapion is universally a rightful ground of holding, not properly as a juridical mode of requiring a Thing, but as a ground for main taining oneself in possession of it where there are no Juridical Acts. A release from juridical claims is com monly also called Acquisition. The Prescriptive Title of

136 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

the older Possessor, therefore, belongs to the sphere of Natural Eight (est juris naturce). [See Supplementary Explanations, VI.]

34.

II. Acquisition by Inheritance. (Acquisitio hoereditatis.)

INHERITANCE is constituted by the transfer (translatw) of the Property or goods of one who is dying to a Survivor, through the consent of the Will of both. The Acquisition of the HEIR who takes the Estate (hceredis instituti) and the Ptelinquishment of the TESTATOR who leaves it, being the acts that constitute the Exchange of the Mine and Thine, take place in the same moment of time iTi articulo mortis and just when the Testator (.•eases to be. There is therefore no special Act of Transfer (translatw) in the empirical sense ; for that would involve two successive acts, by which the one would first divest himself of his Possession, and the other would thereupon enter into it. Inheritance as con stituted by a simultaneous double Act is, therefore, an ideal Mode of Acquisition. Inheritance is inconceivable in the State of Nature without a Testamentary Disposi tion (dispositio ultima wluntatis) ; and the question arises as to whether this mode of Acquisition is to be regarded as a Contract of Succession, or a unilateral Act instituting an Heir by a Will (testamentitm). The deter mination of this question depends on the further question, Whether and How, in the very same moment in which one individual ceases to be, there can be a transition of his Property to another Person. Hence the problem as to how a mode of Acquisition by Inheritance is possible,

THE PRINCIPLES OF PI5IVATE RIGHT. 137

must be investigated independently of the various possible forms in which it is practically carried out, and which can have place only in a Commonwealth.

' It is possible to acquire by being instituted or appointed Heir in a Testamentary Disposition.' For the Testator Cains promises and declares in his last Will to Titius, who knows nothing of this Promise, to transfer to him his Estate in case of death, but thus continuing as long as he lives sole Owner of it. Now by a mere unilateral act of Will, nothing can in fact be transmitted to another person, as in addition to the Promise of the one party there is required Acceptance (acceptatio) on the part of the other, and a simultaneous bilateral act of Will (voluntas simultanca) which, however, is here awant- ing. So long as Cains lives, Titius cannot expressly accept in order to enter on Acquisition, because Cains lias only promised in case of death ; otherwise the Property would be for a moment at least in common possession, which is not the Will of the Testator. How ever, Titius acquires tacitly a special Right to the Inheritance as a Real Right. This is constituted by the sole and exclusive Right to accept the Estate (jus in re jacente), which is therefore called at that point of time a hccreditas jaccns. Now as every man because he must always gain and never lose by it necessarily, although tacitly, accepts such a Right, and as Titius after the death of Cains is in this position, he may acquire the succession as Heir by Acceptance of the Promise. And the Estate is not in the meantime entirely without an Owner (res nullius), but is only in abeyance or vacant (vacua) ; because he has exclusively the Right of Choice as to whether he will actually make the Estate be queathed to him, his own or not.

138 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Hence Testaments are valid according to mere Natural Right (mnt juris naturce). This assertion, however, is to be understood in the sense that they are capable and worthy of being introduced and sanctioned in the Civil state, whenever it is instituted. For it is only the Common Will in the Civil state that maintains the possession of the Inheritance or Succession, while it hangs between Acceptance or Rejection and specially belongs to no particular individual. [See Supplementary Explanations, vn.]

35.

III. The continuing Right of a good Name after Death. (Bona fama Defuncti.)

It would be absurd to think that a dead Person could possess anything after his death, when he no longer exists in the eye of the Law, if the matter in question were a mere Thing. But a good Name is a congenital and external, although merely ideal possession, which attaches inseparably to the individual as a Person. Now we can and must abstract here from all consideration as to whether the Persons cease to be after death or still continue as such to exist ; because in considering their juridical relation to others, we regard Persons merely according to their humanity and as rational Beings (homo noumenon). Hence any attempt to bring the Pteputa- tion or good Name of a Person into evil and false repute after death, is always questionable, even although a well- founded charge may be allowed for to that extent the brocard ' De mortuis nil nisi bene' is wrong. Yet to spread charges against one who is absent and cannot defend himself, shows at least a want of magnanimity.

By a blameless life and a death that worthily ends it,

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 1 : ','.'

it is admitted that a man may acquire a (negatively) good reputation constituting something that is his own, even when he no longer exists in the world of sense as a visible Person (homo phenomenon'). It is further held that his Survivors and Successors whether relatives or strangers are entitled to defend his good Name as a matter of Kight, on the ground that unproved accusations subject them all to the danger of similar treatment after death. Now that a Man when dead can yet acquire such a Plight is a peculiar and, nevertheless, an undeni able manifestation in fact, of the ft priori law-giving lleason thus extending its Law of Command or Prohibi tion beyond the limits of the present life. If some one then spreads a charge regarding a dead person that would have dishonoured him when living, or even made him despicable, any one who can adduce a proof that this accusation is intentionally false and untrue, may publicly declare him who thus brings the dead person into ill repute to be a Calumniator, and affix dishonour to him in turn. This would not be allowable unless it were legitimate to assume that the dead person was injured by the accusation, although he is dead, and that a certain just satisfaction was done to him by an Apology, although he no longer sensibly exists. A Title to act the part of the Vindicator of the dead person does not require to be established ; for every one necessarily claims this of himself, not merely as a Duty of Virtue regarded ethically, but as a Plight belonging to him in virtue of his Humanity. Nor does the Vindicator require to show any special personal damage, accruing to him as a friend or relative, from a stain on the character of the Deceased, to justify him in proceeding to censure it. That such a form of ideal Acquisition, and even a

140 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Plight in an individual after death against survivors, is thus actually founded, cannot, therefore, be disputed, although the possibility of such a Right is not capable of logical Deduction.

There is no ground for drawing visionary inferences from what has just been stated, to the presentiment of a future life and invisible relations to departed souls. For the considerations connected with this Eight, turn on nothing more than the purely moral and juridical Relation which subsists among men even in the present life, as Rational Beings. Abstraction is, how ever, made from all that belongs physically to their existence in Space and Time ; that is, men are considered logically apart from these physical con comitants of their nature, not as to their state when actually deprived of them, but only in so far as being spirits they are in a condition that might realize the injury done them by Calumniators. Any one who may falsely say something against me a hundred years hence, injures me even now. For in the pure juridical Relation, which is entirely rational and suprasensible, abstraction is made from the physical conditions of Time, and the Calumniator is as culpable as if he had committed the offence in my lifetime ; only this will not be tried by a Criminal Process, but he will only be punished with that loss of honour he would have caused to another, and this is inflicted upon him by Public Opinion according to the Lex talionis. Even a Plagiarism from a dead Author, although it does not tarnish the honour of the Deceased, but only deprives him of a part of his property, is yet properly regarded as a lesion of his human Ei«ht.

PRIVATE RIGHT.

CHAPTER THIRD.

ACQUISITION CONDITIONED BY THE SENTENCE OF A PUBLIC JUDICATOKY.

36.

How and what Acquisition is subjectively conditioned by the Principle of a Public Court.

NATUKAL RIGHT, understood simply as that Right which is not statutory, and which is knowable purely h priori, by every man's Reason, will include Distributive Justice as well as Commutative Justice. It is manifest that the latter as constituting the Justice that is valid between Persons in their reciprocal relations of inter course with one another, must belong to Natural Right. But this holds also of Distributive Justice, in so far as it can be known a priori ; and Decisions or Sentences regarding it, must be regulated by the Law of Natural Right.

The Moral Person who presides in the sphere of Justice and administers it, is called the COURT of Justice, and as engaged in the process of official duty, the Judi- eatory ; the Sentence delivered in a case, is the Judgment

142 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

(judicium). All this is to be here viewed a priori, according to the rational Conditions of Right, without taking into consideration how such a Constitution is to be actually established or organized, for which particular Statutes, and consequently empirical Principles, are requisite.

The question, then, in this connection, is not merely ' What is right in itself? in the sense in which every man must determine it by the Judgment of Eeason ; but ' What is Right as applied to this case ? ' that is, what is right and just as viewed by a Court ? The rational and the judicial points of view, are therefore to be distinguished ; and there are four Cases in which the two forms of Judgment have a different and opposite issue. And yet they may coexist with each other, because they are delivered from two different, yet respectively true points of view: the one from regard to Private Right, the other from the Idea of Public Right. They are: I. THE CONTKACT OF DONATION (pactum dona- tionis), II. THE CONTRACT OF LOAN (commodatum), III. THE ACTION OF REAL REVINDICATION (vindicatio), and IV. GUARANTEE BY OATH (jur amentum).

It is a common error on the part of the Jurist to fall here into the fallacy of begging the question, by a tacit assumption (yitium subreptionis). This is done by assuming as objective and absolute the juridical Principle which a Public Court of Justice is entitled and even bound to adopt in its own behoof, and only from the subjective purpose of qualifying itself to decide and judge upon all the Rights pertaining to individuals. ^ It is therefore of no small importance to make this specific difference intelligible, and to draw attention to it.

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 143

37.

I. The Contract of Donation. (Pactum donationis.)

The Contract of Donation signifies the gratuitous alienation (gratis) of a Tiling or Eight that is Mine. It involves a relation between me as the Donor (donans), and another Person as the Donatory (donatarius), in accordance with the Principle of Private Eight, by which what is mine is transferred to the latter, on his accept ance of it, as a Gift (donum). However, it is not to be presumed that I have voluntarily bound myself thereby so as to be compelled to keep my Promise, and that I have thus given away my Freedom gratuitously, and, as it were, to that extent thrown myself away. Nemo mum jactare prxsumitur. But this is what would happen, under such circumstances, according to the principle of Right in the Civil state ; for in this sphere the Donatory can compel me, under certain conditions, to perform my Promise. If, then, the case comes before a Court, according to the conditions of Public Right, it must either be presumed that the Donor has consented to such Compulsion, or the Court would give no regard, in the Sentence, to the consideration as to whether he intended to reserve the Right to resile from his Promise or not ; but would only refer to what is certain, namely, the condition of the Promise and the Acceptance of the Donatory. Although the Promisor, therefore, thought as may easily be supposed that he could not be bound by his Promise in any case, if he ' rued ' it before it was actually carried out, yet the Court assumes that he ought expressly to have reserved this condition if such was his

144

mind ; and if he did not make such an express reserva tion, it will be held that he can be compelled to imple ment his Promise. And this Principle is assumed by the Court, because the administration of Justice would otherwise be endlessly impeded, or even made entirely impossible.

38.

II. The Contract of Loan. (Commodatum.)

In the Contract of Commodate-Loan (commodatum) I give some one the gratuitous use of something that is mine. If it is a Thing that is given on Loan, the con tracting Parties agree that the Borrower will restore the very same thing to the power of the Lender. But the Pieceiver of the Loan (commodatarius) cannot, at the same time, assume that the Owner of the Thing lent (commodam) will take upon himself all risk (casus) of any possible loss of it, or of its useful quality, that may arise from having given it into the possession of the Pteceiver. For it is not to be understood of itself, that the Owner, besides the use of the Thing, which he has granted to the lieceiver, and the detriment that is inseparable from such use, also gives a Guarantee or Wanandice against all damage that may arise from such use. On the contrary, a special Accessory Contract would have to be entered into for this purpose. The only question, then, that can be raised is this: Is it incumbent on the Lender or the Borrower to add expressly the condition of undertaking the risk that may accrue to the Thing lent ; or, if this "is not done, which of the Parties is to be presumed to have consented and <l to guarantee the property of the Lender, up to

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 145

restoration of the very same Thing or its equivalent ? Certainly not the Lender; because it cannot be pre sumed that he has gratuitously agreed to give more than the mere use of the Thing, so that he cannot be supposed to have also undertaken the risk of loss of his property. But this may be assumed on the side of the Borrower ; because he thereby undertakes and performs nothing more than what is implied in the Contract.

For example, I enter a house when overtaken by a shower of rain, and ask the Loan of a cloak. But through accidental contact with colouring matter, it becomes entirely spoiled while in my possession ; or on entering another house, I lay it aside and it is stolen. Under such circumstances, everybody would think it absurd for me to assert that I had no further concern with the cloak but to return it as it was, or, in the latter case, only to mention the fact of the theft ; and that, in any case, anything more required would be but an act of Courtesy in expressing sympathy with the Owner on account of his loss, seeing he can claim nothing on the ground of Right. It would be other wise, however, if on asking the use of an article, I discharged myself beforehand from all responsibility, in case of its coming to grief among my hands, on the ground of my being poor, and unable to compensate any incidental loss. No one could find such a condition superfluous or ludicrous, unless the Borrower were, in fact, known to be a well-to-do and well-disposed man ; because in such a case it would almost be an insult not to act on the presumption of generous compensation for any loss sustained.

Now by the very nature of this Contract, the possible K

146 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

damage (casus) which the Thing lent may undergo cannot be exactly determined in any Agreement. Com- modate is therefore an uncertain Contract (pactum inccrtum], because the consent can only be so far pre sumed. The Judgment, in any case, deciding upon whom the incidence of any loss must fall, cannot there fore be determined from the conditions of the Contract in itself, but only ly the Principle of the Court before which it comes, and which can only consider what is certain in the Contract ; and the only thing certain is always the fact as to the possession of the Thing as property. Hence the Judgment passed in the state of Nature, will be different from that given by a Court of Justice in the Civil state. The Judgment from the standpoint of Natural Eight will be determined by regard to the inner rational quality of the Thing, and will run thus : ' Loss arising from damage accruing to a Thing lent falls upon the Borrower ' (casum sentit com- modatarius) ; whereas the Sentence of a Court of Justice in the Civil state will run thus : ' The Loss falls upon the Lender' (casum sentit dominus). The latter Judg ment turns out differently from the former as the Sentence of the mere sound Eeason, because a Public Judge cannot found upon presumptions as to what either party may have thought ; and thus the one who has not obtained release from all loss in the Thing by a special Accessory Contract, must bear the loss. Hence the difference between the Judgment as the Court must deliver it, and the form in which each individual is entitled to hold it for himself by his private Eeason, is a matter of importance, and is not to be overlooked in the consideration of Juridical Judgments.

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 147

39.

III. The Revindication of what has been Lost. (Vindicatio.)

^ It is clear from what has been already said that ;i Thing of mine which continues to exist, remains mine although I may not be in continuous occupation of it ; and that it does not cease to be mine without a Juridical Act of dereliction or alienation. Further, it is evident that a Eight in this Thing (jus reale) belongs in consequence to me (jus personate), against every holder of it, and not merely against some Particular Person. But the question now arises as to whether this Right must be regarded by every other person as a continuous Eight of Property per se, if I have not in any way renounced it, although the Thing is in the possession of another.

A Thing may be lost (res amissa), and thus come into other hands in an honourable bond fide way as a sup posed ' Find ; ' or it may come to me by formal transfer on the part of one who is in possession of it, and who professes to be its Owner, although he is not so. Taking the latter case, the question arises, Whether, since I cannot acquire a Thing from one who is not its Owner (a non domino), I am excluded by the fact from all Eight in the Thing itself, and have merely a personal Eight against a wrongful Possessor ? This is manifestly so, if the Acquisition is judged purely according to its inner justifying grounds and viewed according to the State of Xature, and not according to the convenience of a Court of Justice.

For everything alienable must be capable of being acquired by any one. The Eightfulness of Acquisition",

148 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

however, rests entirely upon the form in accordance with which what is in possession of another, is transferred to me and accepted by me. In other words, rightful Acquisition depends upon the formality of the juridical act of commutation or interchange between the Possessor of the Thing and the Acquirer of it, without its being required to ask how the former came by it ; because this would itself be an injury, on the ground that Quilibet prccwmitur bonus. Now suppose it turned out that the said Possessor was not the real Owner, I cannot admit that the real Owner is entitled to hold me directly responsible, or so entitled with regard to any one who might be holding the Thing. For I have myself taken nothing away from him, when, for example, I bought his horse according to the Law (titulo empti venditi) when it was offered for sale in the public market. The Title of Acquisition is therefore unimpeachable on my side ; and as Buyer I am not bound, nor even have I the Eight, to investigate the Title of the Seller; for this process of investigation would have to go on in an ascending series ad infinitum. Hence on such grounds I ought to be regarded, in virtue of a regular and formal purchase, as not merely the putative, but the real Owner of the horse.

But against this position, there immediately start up the following juridical Principles. Any Acquisition derived from one who is not the Owner of the Thing in question, is null and void. I cannot derive from another anything more than what he himself rightfully has ; and although as regards the form of the Acquisition the modus acquirendi I may proceed in accordance with all the conditions of Eight when I deal in a stolen horse ex posed for sale in the market, yet a real Title warranting

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 149

the Acquisition was awanting ; for the horse was not really the property of the Seller in question. However I may be a bond fide Possessor of a Thing under such conditions, I am still only a putative Owner, and the real Owner has the Eight of Vindication against me (rem suam vindi- candi).

Now, it may be again asked, what is right and just in itself regarding the Acquisition of external things among men in their intercourse with one another viewed in the state of Nature according to the Principles of Com mutative Justice ? And it must be admitted in this connection, that whoever has a purpose of acquiring anything, must regard it as absolutely necessary to in vestigate whether the Thing which he wishes to acquire does not already belong to another person. For although he may carefully observe the formal conditions required for appropriating what may belong to the property of another, as in buying a horse according to the usual terms in a market, yet he can, at the most, acquire only a Personal Right in relation to a Thing (jus ad rem) so long as it is still unknown to him whether another than the Seller may not be the real Owner. Hence, if some other person were to come forward, and prove by documentary evidence a prior Right of property in the Thing, nothing would remain for the putative new Owner but the advantage which he has drawn as a bond fide Possessor of it up to that moment. Now it is frequently impossible to discover the absolutely first original Owner of a Thing in the series of putative Owners, who derive their Kights from one another. Hence no mere exchange of external things, however well it may agree with the formal conditions of Commutative Justice, can ever guarantee an absolutely certain Acquisition.

150 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Here, however, the juridically law-giving Reason comes in again with the Principle of Distributive Justice ; and it adopts as a criterion of the Rightfulness of Possession, not what it is in itself in reference to the Private Will of each individual in the state of Nature, but only the consideration of how it would be adjudged by a Court of Justice in a Civil state, constituted by the united Will of all. In this connection, fulfilment of the formal con ditions of Acquisition that in themselves only establish a Personal Plight, is postulated as sufficient; and they stand as an equivalent for the material conditions which properly establish the derivation of Property from a prior putative Owner, to the extent of making what is in itself only a Personal Eight, valid before a Court, as a Peal Right. Thus the horse which I bought when exposed for sale in the public market under conditions regulated by the Municipal Law, becomes my property if all the conditions of Purchase and Sale have been exactly observed in the transaction ; but always under the reservation that the real Owner continues to have the Right of a claim against the Seller, on the ground of his prior unalienated possession. My otherwise Personal Right is thus transmuted into a Real Right, according to which I may take and vindicate the object as mine wherever I may find it, without being responsible for the way in which the Seller had come into possession of it.

It is therefore only in behoof of the requirements of juridical decision in a Court (in favorem justitice distribu tives) that the Right in respect of a Thing is regarded, not as Personal, which it is in itself, but as Real, because it can thus be most easily and certainly adjudged ; and it

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 151

is thus accepted and dealt with according to a pure Principle & priori. Upon this Principle various Statutory Laws come to be founded which specially aim at laying down the conditions under which alone a mode of Acquisition shall be legitimate, so that the Judge may be able to assign every one his own as easily and certainly as possible. Thus, in the brocard, ' Purchase breaks Hire,' what by the nature of the subject is a Keal Right— namely the Hire is taken to hold as a merely Personal Right ; and, conversely, as in the case referred to above, what is in itself merely a Personal Right is held to be valid as a Real Right. And this is done only when the question arises as to the Principles by which a Court of Justice in the Civil state is to be guided, in order to proceed with all possible safety in delivering judgment on the Rights of individuals.

40.

IV. Acquisition of Security by the taking of an Oath. (Cautio juratoria.)

Only one ground can be assigned on which it could be held that men are bound in the juridical relation, to lelieve and to confess that there are Gods, or that there is a God. It is that they may be able to swear an Oath ; and that thus by the fear of an all-seeing Supreme Power, whose revenge they must solemnly invoke upon themselves in case their utterance should be false, they may be constrained to be truthful in statement and faithful in promising. It is not Morality but merely blind Superstition that is reckoned upon in this process ; for it is evident it implies that no certainty is to be expected from a mere solemn declaration in matters of

152 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Right before a Court, although the duty of truthfulness must have always appeared self-evident to all, in a matter which concerns the Holiest that can be among men namely, the Eight of Man. Hence recourse has been had to a motive founded on mere myths and fables as imaginary guarantees. Thus among the Rcjangs, a heathen people in Sumatra, it is the custom according to the testimony of Marsden to swear by the bones of their dead relatives, although they have no belief in a life after death. In like manner the negroes of Guinea swear by their Fetish, a bird's feather, which they impre cate under the belief that it will break their neck. And so in other cases. The belief underlying these oaths is that an invisible Power whether it has Understanding or not by its very nature possesses magical power that can be put into action by such invocations. Such a belief which is commonly called Religion, but which ought to be called Superstition is, however, indispens able for the administration of Justice ; because, without referring to it, a Court of Justice would not have adequate means to ascertain facts otherwise kept secret, and to determine rights. A Law making an Oath obli gatory, is therefore only given in behoof of the judicial Authority.

But then the question arises as to what the obligation could be founded upon, that would bind any one in a Court of Justice to accept the Oath of another person, as a right and valid proof of the truth of his statements which are to put an end to all dispute. In other words, What obliges me juridically to believe that another person when taking an Oath has any Religion at all, so that I should subordinate or entrust my Right to his Oath? And, on like grounds, conversely, Can I be

THE PRINCIPLES OF PRIVATE RIGHT. 153

bound at all to take an Oath ? It is evident that both these questions point to what is in itself morally wrong. But in relation to a Court of Justice and generally in the Civil state if it be assumed there are no other means of getting to the truth in certain cases than by an Oath, it must be adopted. In regard to Keligion, under the supposition that every one has it, it may be utilized as a necessary means (in cavxu necessitatis), in behoof of the legitimate procedure of a Court of Justice. The Court uses this form of spiritual compulsion (tortura spiritualis) as an available means, in conformity with the superstitious propensity of mankind, for the ascertain ment of what is concealed ; and therefore holds itself justified in so doing. The Legislative Power, however, is fundamentally wrong in assigning this authority to the Judicial Power, because even in the Civil state any compulsion with regard to the taking of Oaths is con trary to the inalienable Freedom of Man.

OFFICIAL OATHS, which are usually promissory, being taken on entering upon an Office to the effect that the individual has sincere intention to administer his functions dutifully, might well be changed into assertory Oaths, to be taken at the end of a year or more of actual administration, the official swearing to the faithfulness of his discharge of duty during that time. This would bring the Conscience more into action than the Promissory Oath, which always gives room for the internal pretext that, with the best intention, the difficulties that arose during the admini stration of the official function were not foreseen. And, further, violations of Duty, under the prospect of their being summed up by future Censors, would give rise to more anxiety as to censure than when they are merely represented, one after the other, and forgotten.

154 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

As regards an Oath taken concerning a matter of Belief (de crcdulitate}, it is evident that no such Oath can be demanded by a Court. 1. For, first, it con tains in itself a Contradiction. Such Belief, as intermediate between Opinion and Knowledge, is a thing on which one might venture to lay a wager but not to swear an Oath. 2. And, second, the Judge who imposes an Oath of Belief, in order to ascertain anything pertinent to his own purpose or even to the Common Good, commits a great offence against the Conscientiousness of the party taking such an oath. This he does in regard both to the levity of mind, which he thereby helps to engender, and to the stings of conscience which a man must feel who to-day regards a subject from a certain point of view, but who will very probably to-morrow find it quite improbable from another point of view. Any one, therefore, who is compelled to take such an Oath, is subjected to an injury.

TRANSITION FROM PRIVATE RIGHT TO PUBLIC RIGHT. 155

TRANSITION FROM THE MINE AND THINE IN THE STATE OF NATURE

TO THE MINE AND TlIINE IN THE JURIDICAL STATE GENERALLY.

41.

Public Justice as related to the Natural and the Civil state.

The Juridical state is that relation of men to one another which contains the conditions, under which it is alone possible for every one to obtain the Right that is his due. The formal Principle of the possibility of actually participating in such Right, viewed in accordance with the Idea of a universally legislative Will, is PUBLIC JUSTICE. Public Justice may be considered in relation either to the Possibility, or Actuality, or Necessity of the Possession of objects regarded as the matter of the activity of the Will according to laws. It may thus be divided into Protective Justice (justitia testatrix), Commutative Justice (justitia commutativa), and Distri butive Justice (justitia distributiva). In the first mode of Justice, the Law declares merely what Relation is inter nally right in respect of Form (lex justi) ; in the second, it declares what is likewise externally in accord with a Law in respect of the Object, and what Possession is rightful (lex juridica) ; and in the third, it declares what is right, and what is just, and to what extent, by the Judgment of a Court in any particular case coming under the <'iven Law. In this latter relation, the Public

156 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

€ourt is called the Justice of the Country ; and the ques tion whether there actually is or is not such an admini stration of Public Justice, may be regarded as the most important of all juridical interests.

The non-juridical state is that condition of Society in which there is no Distributive Justice. It is commonly called the Natural state (static natumlis), or the state of Nature. It is not the ' Social State,' as Achenwall puts it, for this may be in itself an artificial state (status artificialis), that is to be contradistinguished from the ' Natural ' state. The opposite of the state of Nature is the Civil state (status civilis) as the condition of a Society standing under a Distributive Justice. In the state of Nature there may even be juridical forms of Society such as Marriage, Parental Authority, the Household, and such like. For none of these, however, does any Law a priori lay it down as an incumbent obligation, ' Thou shalt enter into this state.' But it may be said of the Juridical state that 'all men who may even involun tarily come into Relations of Eight with one another, ouyht to enter into this state.'

The Natural or non - juridical Social state may be viewed as the sphere of PRIVATE RIGHT, and the Civil state may be specially regarded as the sphere of PUBLIC RIGHT. The latter state contains no more and no other Duties of men towards each other than what may be conceived in connection with the former state ; the Matter of Private Right is, in short, the very same in both. The Laws of the Civil state, therefore, only turn upon the juridical Form of the co-existence of men under a common Constitution ; and in this respect these Laws must necessarily be regarded and conceived as Public Laws.

TRANSITION FROM PRIVATE RIGHT TO PUBLIC RIGHT. 157

The Civil Union (Unio civilis) cannot, in the strict sense, be properly called a Society; for there is no sociality in common between the Kuler (imperans) and the Subject (subditus) under a Civil Constitution. They are not co-ordinated as Associates in a Society with each other, but the one is subordinated to the other. Those who may be co-ordinated with one another must consider themselves as mutually equal, in so far as they stand under common Laws. The Civil Union may therefore be regarded not so much as being, but rather as making a Society.

42.

The Postulate of Public Eight.

From the conditions of Private Right in the Natural state, there arises the Postulate of Public Eight. It may be thus expressed : ' In the relation of unavoidable co-existence with others, thou shalt pass from the state of Nature into a juridical Union constituted under the condition of a Distributive Justice.' The Principle of this Postulate may be unfolded analytically from the conception of Right in the external relation, contradis tinguished from mere Might as Violence.

No one is under obligation to abstain from interfering with the Possession of others, unless they give him a reciprocal guarantee for the observance of a similar absten tion from interference with his Possession. Nor does he require to wait for proof by experience of the need of this guarantee, in view of the antagonistic disposition of others. He is therefore under no obligation to wait till he acquires practical prudence at his own cost ; for he can perceive in himself evidence of the natural Incli nation of men to play the master over others, and to

158 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

disregard the claims of the Eight of others, when they feel themselves their superiors by Might or Fraud. And thus it is not necessary to wait for the melancholy experience of actual hostility ; the individual is from the first entitled to exercise a rightful compulsion towards those who already threaten him by their very nature. Quilibct prccsumitur malus, donee sccuritatem dedcrit oppositi.

So long as the intention to live and continue in this state of externally lawless Freedom prevails, men may be said to do no wrong or injustice at all to one another, even when they wage war against each other. For what seems competent as good for the one, is equally valid for the other, as if it were so by mutual agreement. Uti partcs de jure suo disponunt, ita jus est. But generally they must be considered as being in the highest state of Wrong, as being and willing to be in a condition which is not juridical ; and in which, therefore, no one can be secured against Violence, in the possession of his own.

The distinction between what is only formally and what is also materially wrong and unjust, finds fre quent application in the Science of Eight. An enemy who, on occupying a besieged fortress, instead of honourably fulfilling the conditions of a Capitulation, maltreats the garrison on marching out, or otherwise violates the agreement, cannot complain of injury or wrong if on another occasion the same treatment is inflicted upon themselves. But, in fact, all such actions fundamentally involve the commission of wrong and injustice, in the highest degree ; because they take all validity away from the conception of Eight, and give up everything, as it were by law itself, to savage Violence, and thus overthrow the Eights of Men generally.

THE SCIENCE OF EIGHT PART SECOND.

PUBLIC RIGHT.

THE SYSTEM OF THOSE LAWS WHICH REQUIRE PUBLIC PROMULGATION.

PUBLIC RIGHT.

THE PRINCIPLES OF RIGHT IN CIVIL SOCIETV.

43.

Definition and Division of Public Right.

PUBLIC RIGHT embraces the whole of the Laws that require to be universally promulgated in order to produce a juridical state of Society. It is therefore a System of those Laws that are requisite for a People as a multitude of men forming a Nation, or for a number of Nations, in their relations to eacli other. Men and Nations, on account of their mutual influence on one another, require a juridical Constitution uniting them under one Will, in order that they may participate in what is right. This relation of the Individuals of a Nation to each other, constitutes THE CIVIL UNION in the social state; and, viewed as a whole in relation to its constituent members, it forms THE POLITICAL STATE (Civitas).

1. The State, as constituted by the common interest of all to live in a juridical union, is called, in view of its form, the COMMONWEALTH or the REPUBLIC in the wider sense of the term (Res puUica latins sic dicta). The Principles of Eight in this sphere, thus constitute the first department of Public Eight as the EIGHT OF THE STATE (jus Civitatis) or National Eight. 2. The State, again, viewed in relation to other peoples, is call(d a

L

162 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Power (potentia), whence arises the idea of Potentates. Viewed in relation to the supposed hereditary unity of the people composing it, the State constitutes a Nation (gens). Under the general conception of Public Right, in addition to the Right of the individual State, there thus arises another department of Right, constituting the RIGHT OF NATIONS (jus gentium) or International Right.— 3. Further, as the surface of the earth is not unlimited in extent, but is circumscribed into a unity, National Right and International Right necessarily culminate in the idea of a UNIVERSAL RIGHT OF MANKIND, which may be called ' Cosmopolitical Right ' (jus cosmopoliticum). And National, International, and Cosmopolitical Right are so interconnected, that if any one of these three possible forms of the juridical Relation fails to embody the essential Principles that ought to regulate external freedom by law, the structure of Legislation reared by the others will also be undermined, and the whole System would at last fall to pieces.

PUBLIC RIGHT.

I.

PLIGHT OF THE STATE AND CONSTITUTIONAL LAW. (Jus Civitatis.)

44.

Origin of the Civil Union and Public Right.

IT is not from any Experience prior to the appearance of an external authoritative Legislation, that we learn of the maxim of natural violence among men, and their evil tendency to engage in war with each other. Nor is it assumed here that it is merely some particular historical condition or fact, that makes public legislative constraint necessary ; for however well - disposed or favourable to Kight men may be considered to be of themselves, the rational Idea of a state of Society not yet regulated by Kight, must be taken as our starting-point. This Idea implies that before a legal state of Society can be publicly established, individual Men, Nations and States can never be safe against violence from each other; and this is evident from the consideration that every one of his own Will naturally does what sctms yuod and rifjht in his man eyes, entirely independent of the opinion of others. Hence, unless the institution of Right

164 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

is to be renounced, the first thing incumbent on men is to accept the Principle that it is necessary to leave the state of Nature, in which every one follows his own inclinations, and to form a union of all those who cannot avoid coming into reciprocal communication, and thus subject themselves in common to the external restraint of public compulsory Laws. Men thus enter into a Civil Union, in which every one has it determined by Law what shall be recognised as his ; and this is secured to him by a competent external Power distinct from his own individuality. Such is the primary Obligation, on the part of all men, to enter into the relations of a Civil State of Society.

The natural condition of mankind need not, on this ground, be represented as a state of absolute Injustice, aw if there could have been no other relation originally among men but what was merely determined by force. But this natural condition must be regarded, if it ever existed, as a state of society that was void of regulation by Eight (status justitice vacuus), so that if a matter of Eight came to be in dispute (jus contr over sum), no com petent judge was found to give an authorized legal decision upon it. It is therefore reasonable that any one should constrain another by force, to pass from such a rion - juridical state of life and enter within the jurisdiction of a civil state of Society. For, although on the basis of the ideas of Eight held by individuals as such, external things may be acquired by Occupancy or Contract, yet such acquisition is only provisory so long as it has not yet obtained the sanction of a Public Law. Till this sanction is reached, the condition of possession is not determined by any public Distributive Justice, nor is it secured by any Power exercising Public Eight.

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 165

If men were not disposed to recognise any Acquisi tion at all as rightful even in a provisional way prior to entering into the Civil state, this state of Society would itself be impossible. For the Laws regarding the Mine and Thine in the state of Xature, contain formally the very same thing as they pre scribe in the Civil state, when it is viewed merely according to rational conceptions: only that in the forms of the Civil state the conditions are laid down under which the formal prescriptions of the state of Nature attain realization conformable to- Distributive Justice. Were there, then, not even 'provisionally, an external Meum and Tuum in the state of Nature, neither would there be any juridical Duties in relation to them ; and, consequently, there would be no obligation to pass out of that state into another.

45.

The Form of the State and its Three Powers.

A State (Civitas) is the union of a number of men under juridical Laws. These Laws, as such, are to be regarded as necessary a priori, that is, as following of themselves from the conceptions of external Right gener ally, and not as merely established by Statute. The FORM of the State is thus involved in the Idea of the State, viewed as it ought to be according to pure principles of Right; and this ideal Form furnishes the normal criterion of every real union that constitutes a Common wealth.

Every State contains in itself THREE TOWERS, the universal united Will of the People being thus personi fied in a political triad. These are the Legislative Power, the Executive Power, and the Jiuliciary Power. 1. The Legislative Power of the Sovereignty in the State, is

1G6 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

embodied in the person of the Lawgiver ; 2. the Executive Power is embodied in the person of the Ruler who administers the Law ; and 3. the Judiciary Power, em bodied in the person of the Judge, is the function of assigning every one what is his own, according to the Law (Potcstas Icyixlatoria, rcctoria et judiciaria). These three Powers may be compared to the three propositions in a practical Syllogism: the Major as the sumption laying down the universal Law of a Will, the Minor presenting the command applicable to an action according to the Law as the principle of the subsumption, and the Conclusion containing the Sentence or judgment of Right in the particular case under consideration.

46.

The Legislative Power and the Members of the State.

The Legislative Power, viewed in its rational Principle, can only belong to the united Will of the People. Tor, as all Right ought to proceed from this Power, it is necessary that its Laws should be unable to do wrong to any one whatever. Now, if any one individual determines anything in the State in contradistinction to another, it is always possible that he may perpetrate a wrong on that other ; but this is never possible when all determine and decree what is to be Law to themselves. ' Volenti non fit injuria.' Hence it is only the united and consenting Will of all the People in so far as Each of them determines the same thing about all, and All determine the same thing about each that ought to have the power of enacting Law in the State.

The Members of a Civil Society thus united for the purpose of Legislation, and thereby constituting a State,

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 167

are called its CITIZENS; and there are three juridical attributes that inseparably belong to them by Right. These are 1. Constitutional FREEDOM, as the Right of every Citizen to have to obey no other Law than that to which he has given his consent or approval ; 2. Civil EQUALITY, as the Right of the Citizen to recognise no one as a Superior among the people in relation to himself, except in so far as such a one is as subject to his moral power to impose obligations, as that other has power to impose obligations upon him ; and 3. Political INDEPENDENCE, as the Right to owe his existence and continuance in Society not to the arbitrary Will of another, but to his own Rights and Powers as a Member of the Commonwealth ; and, consequently, the possession of a Civil Personality, which cannot be represented by any other than himself.

The capability of Voting by possession of the Suffrage, properly constitutes the political qualifica tion of a Citizen as a Member of the State. But this, again, presupposes the Independence or Self-sufficiency of the individual Citizen among the people, as one who is not a mere incidental part of the Commonwealth, but a Member of it acting of his own Will in com munity with others. The last of the three qualities involved, necessarily constitutes the distinction be tween active and passive Citizenship ; although the latter conception appears to stand in contradiction to the definition of a Citizen as such. The following examples may serve to remove this difficulty. The Apprentice of a Merchant or Tradesman, a Servant who is not in the employ of the State, a Minor (naturalitcr vel civiliter), all Women, and, generally, every one who is compelled to maintain himself not according to his own industry, but as it is arranged by others (the State excepted), are without Civil Personality, and their existence is only, as it were,

168 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

incidentally included in the State. The Woodcutter whom I employ on my estate ; the Smith in India who carries his hammer, anvil, and bellows into the houses where he is engaged to work in iron, as dis tinguished from the European Carpenter or Smith, who can offer the independent products of his labour as wares for public sale ; the resident Tutor as dis tinguished from the Schoolmaster ; the Ploughman as distinguished from the Farmer and such like, illustrate the distinction in question. In all these cases, the former members of the contrast are distinguished from the latter by being mere subsidiaries of the Common wealth and not active independent Members of it, because they are of necessity commanded and pro tected by others, and consequently possess no political Self-sufficiency in themselves. Such Dependence on the Will of others and the consequent Inequality are, however, not inconsistent with the Freedom and Equality of the individuals as Men helping to con stitute the people. Much rather is it the case that it is only under such conditions, that a People can become a State and enter into a Civil Constitution. But all are not equally qualified to exercise the Right of the Suffrage under the Constitution, and to be full Citizens of the State, and not mere passive Subjects under its protection. For, although they are entitled to demand to be treated by all the other Citizens according to laws of natural Freedom and Equality, as passive parts of the State, it does not follow that they ought themselves to have the Plight to deal with the State as active Members of it, to reorganize it, or to take action by way of introducing certain laws. All they have a right in their circumstances to claim, may be no more than that whatever be the mode in which the positive laws are enacted, these laws must not be contrary to the natural Laws that demand the Free dom of all the people and the Equality that is con formable thereto; and it must therefore be made

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 1C9

possible for them to raise themselves from this passive condition in the State, to the condition of active Citizenship.

47.

Dignities in the State and the Original Contract.

All these three Powers in the State are DIGNITIES ; and as necessarily arising out of the Idea of the State and essen tial generally to the foundation of its Constitution, they are to be regarded as POLITICAL Dignities. They imply the relation between a universal SOVEREIGN as Head of the State which according to the laws of freedom can be none other than the People itself united into a Nation and the mass of the individuals of the Nation as SUBJECTS. The former member of the relation is the riding Power, whose function is to govern (imperans) ; the latter is the ruled Constituents of the State, whose function is to obey (sulditi).

The act by which a People is represented as consti tuting itself into a State, is termed THE ORIGINAL CONTRACT. This is properly only an outward mode of representing the idea by which the rightfulness of the process of organizing the Constitution, may be made conceivable. According to this representation, all and each of the people give up their external Freedom in order to receive it immediately again as Members of a Common wealth. The Commonwealth is the people viewed as united altogether into a State. And thus it is not to be said that the individual in the State has sacrificed a part of his inborn external Freedom for a particular purpose ; but he has abandoned his wild lawless Freedom wholly, in order to find all his proper Freedom again entire and

170 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

undiminished, but in the form of a regulated order of dependence, that is, in a Civil state regulated by laws of llight. This relation of Dependence thus arises out of his own regulative law-giving Will.

48.

Mutual Relations and Characteristics of the Three Powers.

The three Powers in the State, as regards their rela tions to each other, are, therefore (1) co-ordinate with one another as so many Moral Persons, and the one is thus the Complement of the other in the way of completing the Constitution of the State ; (2) they are likewise subordinate to one another, so that the one cannot at the same time usurp the function of the other by whose side it moves, each having its own Principle, and main taining its authority in a particular person, but under the condition of the Will of a Superior ; and, further, (3) by the union of both these relations, they assign distributively to every subject in the State his own Plights.

Considered as to their respective Dignity, the three Powers may be thus described. The Will of the Sovereign Legislator, in respect of what constitutes the external Mine and Thine, is to be regarded as irreprehcnsible ; the executive Function of the supreme Ruler is to be regarded as irresistible ; and the judicial Sentence of the Supreme Judge is to be regarded as irreversible, being beyond appeal.

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 171

49.

Distinct Functions of the Three Powers. Autonomy of the State.

1. The Executive Power belongs to the Governor or llegent of the State, whether it assumes the form of a Moral or Individual Person, as the King or Prince (rex, princcps). This Executive Authority, as the Supreme Agent of the State, appoints the Magistrates, and pre scribes the Rules to the people, in accordance with which individuals may acquire anything or maintain what is their own conformably to the Law, each case being brought under its application. Regarded as a Moral Person, this Executive Authority constitutes the Govern ment. The Orders issued by the Government to the People and the Magistrates as well as to the higher Ministerial Administrators of the State (gubcrnatio), are Rescripts or Decrees, and not Laws ; for they terminate in the decision of particular cases, and are given forth as unchangeable. A Government acting as an Executive, and at the same time laying down the Law as the Legislative Power, would be a Despotic Government, and would have to be contradistinguished from a patriotic Government. A patriotic Government, again, is to be distinguished from a paternal Government (regimen paternale) which is the most despotic Government of all, the Citizens being dealt with by it as mere children. A patriotic Government, however, is one in which the State, while dealing with the Subjects as if they were Members of a Family, still treats them likewise as Citizens, and according to Laws that recognise their independence, each individual possessing himself and not being dcpen-

172 K AST'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

(lent on the absolute Will of another beside him or above him.

2. The Legislative Authority ought not at the same time to be the Executive or Governor ; for the Governor, as Administrator, should stand under the authority of the Law, and is bound by it under the supreme control of the Legislator. The Legislative Authority may therefore deprive the Governor of his power, depose him, or reform his administration, but not punish him. This is the proper and only meaning of the common saying in England, ' The King as the Supreme Execu tive Power can do no wrong.' For any such applica tion of Punishment would necessarily be an act of that very Executive Power to which the supreme Eight to compel according to Law pertains, and which would itself be thus subjected to coercion ; which is self-contradictory.

3. Further, neither the Legislative Power nor the Executive Power ought to exercise the judicial Function, but only appoint Judges as Magistrates. It is the People who ought to judge themselves, through those of the Citizens who are elected by free Choice as their Repre sentatives for this purpose, and even specially for every process or cause. For the judicial Sentence is a special act of public Distributive Justice performed by a Judge or Court as a constitutional Administrator of the Law, to a Subject as one of the People. Such an act is not invested inherently with the power to determine and assign to any one what is his. Every individual among the people being merely passive in this relation to the Supreme Power, either the Executive or the Legislative Authority might do him wrong in their determinations in cases of dispute regarding the property of individuals. It would not be the people themselves who thus deter-

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 173

mined, or who pronounced the judgments of ' guilty ' or 'not guilty' regarding their fellow -citizens. For it is to the determination of this issue in a cause, that the Court has to apply the Law ; and it is by means of the Executive Authority, that the Judge holds power to assign to every one his own. Hence it is only the People that properly can judge in a cause although indirectly by representatives elected and deputed by themselves, as in a Jury. It would even be beneath the dignity of the Sovereign Head of the State to play the Judge ; for this would be to put himself into a position in which it would be possible to do Wrong, and thus to subject himself to the demand for an appeal to a still higher Power (a reye male wfonnato ad reycm meHu* infonnandum).

It is by the co-operation of these three Powers the Legislative, the Executive, and the Judicial that the State realizes its Autonomy. This Autonomy consists in its organizing, forming, and maintaining itself in accord ance with the Laws of Freedom. In their union the Welfare of the State is realized. Salus reipuUiccc suprcma lex. By this is not to be understood merely the indi vidual well-being and happiness of the Citizens of the State ; for as Rousseau asserts this End may perhaps be more agreeably and more desirably attained in the state of Nature, or even under a despotic Government. Hut the Welfare of the State as its own Highest Good, signifies that condition in which the greatest harmony is attained between its Constitution and the Principles of Right, a condition of the State which Reason by a Categorical Imperative makes it obligatory upon us to strive after.

174 K AST'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

CONSTITUTIONAL AND JUKIDICAL CONSEQUENCES ARISING FROM THE NATURE OF THE CIVIL UNION.

A. Right of the Supreme Power, Treason ; Dethronement ; Revolution; Reform.

The Origin of the Supreme Power is practically in scrutable by the People who are placed under its authority. In other words, the Subject need not reason too curiously in regard to its origin in the practical relation, as if the Right of the obedience due to it were to be doubted (jus contr over sum). For as the People, in order to be able to adjudicate with a title of Plight regarding the Supreme Power in the State, must be regarded as already united under one common legislative Will, it cannot judge otherwise than as the present Supreme Head of the State (summus imperans) wills. The question has been raised as to whether an actual Contract of Subjection (pactum subjectionis civilis) originally preceded the Civil Government as a fact ; or whether the Power arose first, and the Law only followed afterwards, or may have followed in this order. But such questions, as regards the People already actually living under the Civil Law, are either entirely aimless, or even fraught with subtle danger to the State. For, should the Subject, after having dug down to the ultimate origin of the State, rise in opposition to the present ruling Authority, he would expose himself as a Citizen, according to the Law and with full Eight, to be punished, destroyed, or outlawed. A Law which is so holy and inviolable that it is practically a crime even to cast doubt upon it, or to suspend its operation for a moment, is represented of itself as necessarily derived

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 175

from some Supreme, unblameable Lawgiver. And this is the meaning of the maxim, ' All Authority is from God ; ' which proposition does not express the historical foundation of the Civil Constitution, but an ideal Prin ciple of the Practical Pteason. It may be otherwise rendered thus, 'It is a Duty to obey the Law of the existing Legislative Power, be its origin what it may.'

Hence it follows, that the Supreme Power in the State has only Rights, and no (compulsory) Duties towards the Subject. Further, if the Ruler or Regent, as the organ of the Supreme Power, proceeds in violation of the Laws, as in imposing taxes, recruiting soldiers, and so on, contrary to the Law of Equality in the distribution of the political burdens, the Subject may oppose complaints and objections (gravamina) to this injustice, but not active resistance.

There cannot even be an Article contained in the political Constitution that would make it possible for a Power in the State, in case of the transgression of the Constitutional Laws by the Supreme Authority, to resist or even to restrict it in so doing. For, whoever would restrict the Supreme Power of the State must have more, or at least equal power as compared with the Power that is so restricted ; and if competent to com mand the subjects to resist, such a one would also have to be able to protect them, and if he is to be considered capable of judging what is right in every case, he may also publicly order Resistance. But such a one, and not the actual Authority, would then be the Supreme Power ; which is contradictory. The Supreme Sovereign Power, then, in proceeding by a Minister who is at the same time the Ruler of the State, consequently becomes despotic; and the expedient of giving the People to

176 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

imagine when they have properly only Legislative influence— that they act by their Deputies by way of limiting the Sovereign Authority, cannot so mask and disguise the actual Despotism of such a Government that it will not appear in the measures and means adopted by the Minister to carry out his function. The People, while represented by their Deputies in Parlia ment, under such conditions, may have in these war rantors of their Freedom and Plights, persons who are keenly interested on their own account and their families, and who look to such a Minister for the benefit of his influence in the Army, Navy, and Public Offices. And hence, instead of offering resistance to the undue pre tensions of the Government whose public declarations ought to carry a prior accord on the part of the people, which, however, cannot be allowed in peace, they are rather always ready to play into the hands of the Govern ment. Hence the so-called limited political Constitution, as a Constitution of the internal Rights of the State, is an unreality; and instead of being consistent with Plight, it is only a Principle of Expediency. And its aim is not so much to throw all possible obstacles in the way of a powerful violator of popular Plights by his arbitrary influence upon the Government, as rather to cloak it over under the illusion of a Eight of opposition conceded to the People.

Resistance on the part of the People to the Supreme Legislative Power of the State, is in no case legitimate ; for it is only by submission to the universal Legislative Will, that a condition of law and order is possible. Hence there is no Right of Sedition, and still less of Rebellion, belonging to the People. And least of all, when the Supreme Power is embodied in an individual

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 177

Monarch, is there any justification, under the pretext of his abuse of power, for seizing his Person or taking away his Life (monarchomachismus sub specie tyranni- cidii). The slightest attempt of this kind is lliyh Treason (proditio eminens); and a Traitor of this sort who aims at the overthrow of his country may be punished, as a political parricide, even with Death. It is the duty of the People to bear any abuse of the Supreme Power, even then though it should be con sidered to be unbearable. And the reason is, that any Resistance of the highest Legislative Authority can never but be contrary to the Law, and must even be regarded as tending to destroy the whole legal Constitu tion. In order to be entitled to offer such Resistance, a Public Law would be required to permit it. But the Supreme Legislation would by such a Law cease to be supreme, and the People as Subjects would be made sovereign over that to which they are subject ; which is a contradiction. And the contradiction becomes more apparent when the question is put : Who is to be the Judge in a controversy between the People and the Sovereign ? For the People and the Sovereign are to be constitutionally or juridically regarded as two different Moral Persons; but the question shows that the People would then have to be the Judge in their own cause. See Supplementary Explanations, ix.

The Dethronement of a Monarch may be also con ceived as a voluntary abdication of the Crown, and a resignation of his power into the hands of the People ; or it might be a deliberate surrender of these without any assault on the royal person, in order that the Monarch may be relegated into private life. But, however it happen, forcible compulsion of it, on the part of the People, cannot be justified

M

178 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

under the pretext of a ' Right of Necessity ' (cams neeessitatis) ; and least of all can the slightest Eight be shown for punishing the Sovereign on the ground of previous maladministration. For all that has been already done in the quality of a Sovereign, must be regarded as done outwardly by Right ; and, considered as the source of the Laws, the Sovereign himself can do no wrong. Of all the abominations in the overthrow of a State by Revolution, even the murder or assassination of the Monarch is not the worst. For that may be done by the People out of fear, lest if he is allowed to live, he may again acquire power and inflict punishment upon them ; and so it may be done, not as an act of punitive Justice, but merely from regard to self-preservation. It is the formal Execution of a Monarch that horrifies a soul filled with ideas of human right ; and this feeling occurs again and again as often as the mind realizes the scenes that terminated the fate of Charles I. or Louis XVI. Now how is this Feeling to be explained ? It is not a mere aesthetic feeling, arising from the working of the Imagination, nor from Sympathy, pro duced by fancying ourselves in the place of the sufferer. On the contrary, it is a moral feeling arising from the entire subversion of all our notions of Right. Regicide, in short, is regarded as a Crime which always remains such, and can never be expiated (crimen immortale, inexpiaUle) ; and it appears to resemble that Sin which the Theologians declare can neither be forgiven in this world nor in the next. The explanation of this phenomenon in the human mind appears to be furnished by the following reflec tions upon it ; and they even shed some light upon the Principles of Political Right.

Every Transgression of a Law only can and must be explained as arising from a Maxim of the trans gressor making such wrong-doing his rule of action ; lor were it not committed by him as a free Being, it

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 179

could not be imputed to him. But it is absolutely impossible to explain how any rational individual forms such a Maxim against the clear prohibition of the lawgiving Keason ; for it is only events which happen according to the mechanical laws of Nature that are capable of explanation. Now a transgressor or criminal may commit his wrong-doing either accord ing to the Maxim of a Rule supposed to be valid objectively and universally, or only as an Exception from the Rule by dispensing with its obligation for the occasion. In the latter case, he only diverges from the Law, although intentionally. He may, at the same time, abhor his own transgression, and without formally renouncing his obedience to the Law only wish to avoid it. In the former case, however, he rejects the authority of the Law itself, the validity of which, however, he cannot repudiate before his own Reason, even while he makes it his Rule to act against it. His Maxim is therefore not merely defective as being negatively contrary to the Law, but it is even positively illegal, as being diametrically contrary and in hostile opposition to it. So far as we can see into and understand the relation, it would appear as if it were impossible for men to commit wrongs and crimes of a wholly useless form of wicked ness, and yet the idea of such extreme perversity cannot be overlooked in a System of Moral Philo sophy.

There is thus a feeling of horror at the thought of the formal Execution of a Monarch by his People. And the reason of it is, that whereas an act of Assassi nation must be considered as only an exception from the Rule which has been constituted a Maxim, such an Execution must be regarded as a complete per version of the Principles that should regulate the relation between a Sovereign and his People. For it makes the People, who owe their constitutional exist ence to the Legislation that issued from the Sovereign,

180 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

to be the Kuler over him. Hence mere violence is thus elevated with bold brow, and as it were by principle, above the holiest Right ; and, appearing like an abyss to swallow up everything without recall, it seems like suicide committed by the State upon itself, and a crime that is capable of no atonement. There is therefore reason to assume that the consent that is accorded to such executions is not really based upon a supposed Principle of Eight, but only springs from fear of the vengeance that would be taken upon the People were the same Power to revive again in the State. And hence it may be held that the formalities accompany ing them, have only been put forward in order to give these deeds a look of Punishment from the accom paniment of a judicial process, such as could not go along with a mere Murder or Assassination. But such a cloaking of the deed entirely fails of its pur pose, because this pretension on the part of the People is even worse than Murder itself, as it implies a principle which would necessarily make the restora tion of a State, when once overthrown, an impossibility.

An alteration of the still defective Constitution of the State may sometimes be quite necessary. But all such changes ought only to proceed from the Sovereign Power in the way of Reform, and are not to be brought about by the people in the way of Revolution; and when they take place, they should only affect the Executive, and not the Legislative Power. A political Constitution which is so modified that the People by their Representatives in Parliament can legally resist the Executive Power and its representative Minister, is called a Limited Constitu tion. Yet even under such a Constitution there is no Right of active Resistance, as by an arbitrary combination of the People to coerce the Government into a certain active procedure ; for this would be to assume to perform

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 181

an act of the Executive itself. All that can rightly be allowed, is only a negative Resistance, amounting to an act of Refusal on the part of the People to concede all the demands which the Executive may deem it necessary to make in behoof of the political Administration. And if this Eight were never exercised, it would be a sure sign that the People were corrupted, their Representatives venal, the Supreme Head of the Government despotic, and his Ministers practically betrayers of the People.

Further, when on the success of a Revolution a new Constitution has been founded, the unlawfulness of its beginning and of its institution cannot release the Sub jects from the obligation of adapting themselves, as good Citizens, to the new order of things ; and they are not entitled to refuse honourably to obey the authority that has thus attained the power in the State. A dethroned Monarch, who has survived such a Revolution, is not to be called to account on the ground of his former admini stration ; and still less may he be punished for it, when withdrawing into the private life of a citizen he prefers his own quiet and the peace of the State to the un certainty of exile, with the intention of maintaining his claims for restoration at all hazards, and pushing these either by secret counter-revolution or by the assistance of other Powers. However, if he prefers to follow the latter course, his Rights remain, because the Rebellion that drove him from his position was inherently unjust. But the question then emerges as to whether other Powers have the Right to form themselves into an alliance in behalf of such a dethroned Monarcli merely in order not to leave the crime committed by the People unavenged, or to do away with it as a scandal to all the States ; and whether they are therefore justified and called upon to

1S2 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

restore by force to another State a formerly existing Constitution that has been removed by a Revolution. The discussion of this question, however, does not belong to this department of Public Eight, but to the following section, concerning the Eight of Nations.

B. Land Rights. Secular and Church Lands. Rights of Taxation; Finance; Police; Inspection.

Is the Sovereign, viewed as embodying the Legislative Power, to be regarded as the Supreme Proprietor of the Soil, or only as the Highest Euler of the People by the laws ? As the Soil is the supreme condition under whicli it is alone possible to have external things as one's own, its possible possession and use constitute the first acquir- able basis of external Eight. Hence it is that all such Eights must be derived from the Sovereign as Over-lord and Paramount Superior of the Soil, or, as it may be better put, as the Supreme Proprietor of the Land (Dominus territorii). The People, as forming the mass of the Subjects, belong to the Sovereign as a People ; not in the sense of his being their Proprietor in the way of Eeal Eight, but as their Supreme Commander or Chief in the way of Personal Eight. This Supreme Proprietor ship, however, is only an Idea of the Civil Constitution, objectified to represent, in accordance with juridical con ceptions, the necessary union of the private property of all the people under a public universal Possessor. The relation is so represented in order that it may form a basis for the determination of particular Eights in property. It does not proceed, therefore, upon the Principle of mere Aggregation, which advances empirically from the parts to the Whole, but from the necessary formal prin-

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC 1UGHT. 183

ciple of a Division of the Soil according to conceptions of Right. In accordance with this Principle, the Supreme Universal Proprietor cannot have any private property in any part of the Soil ; for otherwise he would make himself a private Person. Private property in the Soil belongs only to the People, taken distributively and not collectively ; from which condition, however, a nomadic people must be excepted as having no private property at all in the Soil. The Supreme Proprietor accordingly ought not to hold private Estates, either for private use or for the support of the Court. For, as it would depend upon liis own pleasure how far these should extend, the State would be in danger of seeing all property in the Land taken into the hands of the Government, and all the Subjects treated as bondsmen of the Soil (yleucc adscripti). As possessors only of what was the private property of another, they might thus be deprived of Jill freedom and regarded as Serfs or Slaves. Of the Supreme Proprietor of the Land, it may be said that he possesses nothing as his own, except himself ; for if he possessed things in the State alongside of others, dispute and litigation would be possible with these others regarding those things, and there would be no independent Judge to settle the cause. But it may be also said that he possesses everything ; for he has the Supreme Right of Sovereignty over the whole People, to whom all external things severally (divisini) belong ; and as such he assigns distributively to every one what is to be his.

Hence there cannot be any Corporation in the State, nor any Class or Order, that as Proprietors can transmit the Land for a sole exclusive use to the following genera tions for all time (ad infinitum\ according to certain fixed Statutes. The State may annul and abrogate all

184 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

such Statutes at any time, only under the condition of indemnifying survivors for their interests. The Order of Knights, constituting the nobility regarded as a mere rank or class of specially titled individuals, as well as the Order of the Clergy, called the Church, are both subject to this relation. They can never be entitled by any hereditary privileges with which they may be favoured, to acquire an absolute property in the soil transmissible to their successors. They can only acquire the use of such property for the time being. If Public Opinion has ceased, on account of other arrangements, to impel the State to protect itself from negligence in the national defence by appeal to the military honour of the knightly order, the Estates granted on that condition may be recalled. And, in like manner, the Church Lands or Spiritualities may be reclaimed by the State without scruple, if Public Opinion has ceased to impel the members of the State to maintain Masses for the Souls of the Dead, Prayers for the Living, and a multitude of Clergy, as means to protect themselves from eternal fire. But in both cases, the condition of indemnifying existing interests must be observed. Those who in this connec tion fall under the movement of Reform, are not entitled to complain that their property is taken from them ; for the foundation of their previous possession lay only in the Opinion of the People, and it can be valid only so long as this opinion lasts. As soon as this Public Opinion in favour of such institutions dies out, or is even extinguished in the judgment of those who have the greatest claim by their acknowledged merit to lead and represent it, the putative proprietorship in question must cease, as if by a public appeal made regarding it to the State (a rege male informato ad regem melius informandum).

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 185

On this primarily acquired Supreme Proprietorship in the Land, rests the Eight of the Sovereign, as universal Proprietor of the country, to assess the private proprietors of the Soil, and to demand Taxes, Excise, and Dues, or the performance of Service to the State such as may be required in War. But this is to be done so that it is actually the People that assess themselves, this being the only mode of proceeding according to Laws of Eight. This may be effected through the medium of the Body of Deputies who represent the People. It is also per missible, in circumstances in which the State is in imminent danger, to proceed by a forced Loan, as a Eight vested in the Sovereign, although this may be a divergence from the existing Law.

Upon this Principle is also founded the Eight of administering the National Economy, including the Finance and the Police. The Police has specially to care for the Public Safety, Convenience, and Decency. As regards the last of these, the feeling or negative taste for public Propriety, it is important that it be not deadened by such influences as Begging, disorderly Noises, offensive Smells, public Prostitution ( Venus vulyi- vaga), or other offences against the Moral Sense, as it greatly facilitates the Government in the task of regulat ing the life of the People by law.

For the preservation of the State there further belongs to it a Eight of Inspection (jus inspect ionis), which entitles the public Authority to see that no secret Society, political or religious, exists among the people that can exert a prejudicial influence upon the public Weal. Accordingly, when it is required by the Police, no such secret Society may refuse to lay open its constitution. But the visitation and search of private houses by the

186 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Police, can only be justified in a case of Necessity ; and in every particular instance, it must be authorized by a higher Authority.

C. Relief of the Poor. Foundling Hospitals. The Church.

The Sovereign, as undertaker of the duty of the People, has the Eight to tax them for purposes essenti ally connected with their own preservation. Such are, in particular, the Eelief of the Poor, Foundling Asylums, and Ecclesiastical Establishments, otherwise designated charitable or pious Foundations.

1. The People have in fact united themselves by their common Will into a Society, which has to be per petually maintained ; and for this purpose they have subjected themselves to the internal Power of the State, in order to preserve the members of this Society even when they are not able to support themselves. By the fundamental principle of the State, the Government is justified and entitled to compel those who are able, to furnish the means necessary to preserve those who are not themselves capable of providing for the most neces sary wants of Nature. For the existence of persons with property in the State, implies their submission under it for protection and the provision by the State of what is necessary for their existence; and accordingly the State founds a Eight upon an obligation on their part to contribute of their means for the preservation of their fellow-citizens. This may be carried out by taxing the Property or the commercial industry of the Citizens, or by establishing Funds and drawing interest from them, not for the wants of the State as such, which is rich, but

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC PJGIIT. 187

for those of the People. And this is not to be done merely by voluntary contributions, but by compulsory exactions as State-burdens, for we are here considering only the Riyht of the State in relation to the People. Among the voluntary modes of raising such contributions Lotteries ought not to be allowed, because they increase the number of those who are poor, and involve danger to the public property. It may be asked whether the Ilelief of the Poor ought to be administered out of current contributions, so that every age should maintain its own Poor ; or whether this were better done by means of permanent funds and charitable institutions, such as Widows' Homes, Hospitals, etc. ? And if the former method is the better, it may also be considered whether the means necessary are to be raised by a legal Assess ment rather than by Begging, which is generally nigh akin to robbing. The former method must in reality be regarded as the only one that is conformable to the Bight of the State, which cannot withdraw its connection from any one who has to live. For a legal current provision does not make the profession of poverty a means of gain for the indolent, as is to be feared is the case with pious Foundations when they grow with the number of the poor ; nor can it be charged with being an unjust or unrighteous burden imposed by the Government on the people.

2. The State has also a Eight to impose upon the People the duty of preserving Children exposed from want or shame, and who would otherwise perish ; for it cannot knowingly allow this increase of its power to be destroyed, however unwelcome in some respects it may be. But it is a difficult question to determine how this may most justly be carried out. It might be considered

188 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

whether it would not be right to exact contributions for this purpose from the unmarried persons of both sexes who are possessed of means, as being in part responsible for the evil ; and further, whether the end in view would be best carried out by Foundling Hospitals, or in what other way consistent with Eight. But this is a problem of which no solution has yet been offered that does not in some measure offend against Right or Morality.

3. The Church is here regarded as an Ecclesiastical Establishment merely, and as such it must be carefully distinguished from Eeligion, which as an internal mode of feeling lies wholly beyond the sphere of the action of the Civil Power. Viewed as an Institution for public Worship founded for the people, to whose opinion or conviction it owes its origin, the Church Establishment responds to a real want in the State. This is the need felt by the people to regard themselves as also Subjects of a Supreme Invisible Power to which they must pay homage, and which may often be brought into a very undesirable collision with the Civil Power. The State has therefore a Eight in this relation ; but it is not to be regarded as the Eight of Constitutional Legislation in the Church, so as to organize it as may seem most advan tageous for itself, or to prescribe and command its faith and ritual forms of worship (ritus) ; for all this must be left entirely to the teachers and rulers which the Church has chosen for itself. The function of the State in this con nection, only includes the negative Eight of regulating the influence of these public teachers upon the visible political Commonwealth, that it may not be prejudicial to the public peace and tranquillity. Consequently the State has to take measures, on occasion of any internal conflict in the Church, or on occasion of any collision of the

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 1 39

several Churches with each other, that Civil concord is not endangered ; and this Kight falls within the province of the Police. It is beneath tlie difjnity of the Supreme Power to interpose in determining what particular faith the Church shall profess, or to decree that a certain faith shall be unalterably held, and that the Church may not reform itself. For in doing so, the Supreme Power would be mixing itself up in a scholastic wrangle, on a footing of equality with its subjects ; the Monarch would be making himself a priest ; and the Churchmen might even reproach the Supreme Power with understanding nothing about matters of faith. Especially would this hold in respect of any prohibition of internal Reform in the Church ; for what the People as a whole cannot determine upon for themselves, cannot be determined for the People by the Legislator. But no People can ever rationally determine that they will never advance farther in their insight into matters of faith, or resolve that they will never reform the institutions of the Church ; because this would be opposed to the humanity in their own persons, and to their highest Eights. And therefore the Supreme Power cannot of itself resolve and decree in these matters for the People. As regards the cost of maintaining the Ecclesiastical Establishment, for similar reasons this must be derived not from the public funds of the State, but from the section of the People who profess the particular faith of the Church ; and thus only ought it to fall as a burden on the Community. See Supplementary Explanations, vin.

100 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

D. The Right of assigning Offices and Dignities in the State.

The Plight of the Supreme Authority in the State also includes :

1. The Distribution of Offices, as public and paid em ployments ;

2. The Conferring of Dignities, as unpaid distinctions of Rank, founded merely on honour, but establishing a gradation of higher and lower orders in the political scale; the latter, although free in themselves, being under obligation determined by the public law to obey the former so far as they are also entitled to command ;

3. Besides these relatively beneficent Rights, the Supreme Power in the State is also invested with the. Right of administering Punishment.

As regards Civil Offices, the question arises as to whether the Sovereign has the Right, after bestowing an office on an individual, to take it again away at his mere pleasure, without any crime having been committed by the holder of the office. I say, No. For what the united Will of the People would never resolve regarding their Civil Officers, cannot (constitutionally) be determined by the Sovereign regarding them. The People have to bear the cost incurred by the appointment of an Official, and undoubtedly it must be their Will that any one in Office should be completely competent for its duties. But such competency can only be acquired by a long preparation and training, and this process would necessarily occupy the time that would be required for acquiring the means

support by a different occupation. Arbitrary and

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 101

frequent changes would therefore, as a rule, have the effect of filling Offices with functionaries who have not acquired the skill required for their duties, and whose judgments had not attained maturity by practice. All this is contrary to the purpose of the State. And besides it is requisite in the interest of the People, that it should be possible for every individual to rise from a lower office to the higher offices, as these latter would otherwise fall into incompetent hands, and that competent officials generally should have some guarantee of life-long pro vision.

Civil Dignities include not only such as are connected with a public Office, but also those which make the possessors of them without any accompanying services to the State, members of a higher class or rank. The latter constitute the Nobility, whose members are distinguished from the common citizens who form the mass of the People. The rank of the Nobility is inherited by male descendants ; and these again communicate it to wives who are not nobly born. Female descendants of noble families, however, do not communicate their rank to husbands who are not of noble birth, but they descend themselves into the common civil status of the People. This being so, the question then emerges as to whether the Sovereign has the Eight to found a hereditary rank and class, intermediate between himself and the other Citizens ? The import of this question does not turn on whether it is conformable to the prudence of the Sovereign, from regard to his own and the People's interests, to have such an institution ; but whether it is in accordance with the Kight of the People that they should have a class of Persons above them, who, while being Subjects like themselves, are yet born as their Commanders, or at

102 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

least as privileged Superiors? The answer to this (question, as in previous instances, is to be derived from the Principle that ' what the People as constituting the whole mass of the Subjects could not determine regard ing themselves and their associated citizens, cannot be constitutionally determined by the Sovereign regarding the People.' Now a hereditary Nobility is a Hank which takes precedence of Merit and is hoped for without any good reason, a thing of the imagination without genuine reality. For if an Ancestor had merit, he could not transmit it to his posterity, but they must always acquire it for themselves. Nature has in fact not so arranged that the Talent and Will which give rise to merit in the State, are hereditary. And because it cannot be supposed of any individual that he will throw away his Freedom, it is impossible that the common Will of all the People should agree to such a groundless Prerogative, and hence the Sovereign cannot make it valid. It may happen, however, that such an anomaly as that of Subjects who would be more than Citizens, in the manner of born Officials or hereditary Professors, has slipped into the mechanism of the Government in olden times, as in the case of the Feudal System, which was almost entirely organized with reference to War. Under such circum stances, the State cannot deal otherwise with this error of a wrongly instituted Ptank in its midst, than by the remedy of a gradual extinction through hereditary posi tions being left unfilled as they fall vacant. The State has therefore the Plight provisorily to let a Dignity in Title continue, until the Public Opinion matures on the subject. And this will thus pass from the threefold division into Sovereign, Nobles, and People, to the two fold and only natural division into Sovereign and People.

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 193

No individual in the State can indeed be entirely without Dignity; for he has at least that of being a Citizen, except when he has lost his Civil Status by a Crime. As a Criminal he is still maintained in life, but he is made the mere instrument of the Will of another, whether it be the State or a particular Citizen. In the latter position, in which he could only be placed by a juridical judgment, he would practically become a Slave, and would belong as property (dominium) to another, who would be not merely his Master (herns) but his Owner (dominus). Such an Owner would be entitled to exchange or alienate him as a thing, to use him at will except for shameful purposes, and to dispose of his Powers, but not of his Life and Members. No one can bind himself to such a con dition of dependence, as he would thereby cease to be a Person, and it is only as a Person that he can make a Contract. It may, however, appear that one man may bind himself to another by a Contract of Hire, to dis charge a certain service that is permissible in its kind, but is left entirely undetermined as regards its measure or amount ; and that as receiving wages or board or protection in return, he thus becomes only a Servant subject to the Will of a Master (subditus) and not a Slave (scrvus). But this is an illusion. For if Masters are entitled to use the powers of such subjects at will, they may exhaust these powers, as has been done in the case of Negroes in the Sugar Islands, and they may thus reduce their servants to despair and death. But this would imply that they had actually given themselves away to their Masters as property ; which, in the case of persons is impossible. A Person can therefore only con tract to perform work that is defined both in quality and quantity, either as a Day-labourer or as a domiciled Subject.

N

194 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LA.W.

In the latter case he may enter into a Contract of Lease for the use of the land of a Superior, giving a definite rent or annual return for its utilization by himself, or he may contract for his service as a Labourer upon the land. But he does not thereby make himself a slave, or a bonds man, or a serf attached to the soil (glebce adscriptus), as he would thus divest himself of his personality ; he can only enter into a temporary or at most a heritable Lease. And even if by committing a Crime he has personally become subjected to another, this subject-condition does not become hereditary ; for he has only brought it upon himself by his own wrong-doing. Neither can one who has been begotten by a slave be claimed as property on the ground of the cost of his rearing, because such rearing is an absolute duty naturally incumbent upon parents ; and in case the parents be slaves, it devolves upon their masters or owners, who, in undertaking the possession of such subjects, have also made themselves responsible for the performance of their duties.

E. The Right of Punishing and of Pardoning.

I. THE EIGHT OF PUNISHING.

The Eight of administering Punishment, is the Eight of the Sovereign as the Supreme Power to inflict pain upon a Subject on account of a Crime committed by him. The Head of the State cannot therefore be punished ; but his supremacy may be withdrawn from him. Any Transgression of the public law which makes him who commits it incapable of being a Citizen, constitutes a Crime, either simply as a private Crime (crimen), or also as a public Crime (crimen publicum). Private crimes are

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 195

dealt with by a Civil Court ; Public Crimes by a Criminal Court. Embezzlement or peculation of money or goods entrusted in trade, Fraud in purchase or sale, if &done before the eyes of the party who suffers, are Private Crimes. On the other hand, Coining false money or forging Bills of Exchange, Theft, Robbery, etc., are Public Crimes, because the Commonwealth, and not merely some particular individual, is endangered thereby. Such Crimes may be divided into those of a base character (indolis aljectcc) and those of a violent character (indolis violcnticc).

Judicial or Juridical Punishment (pcena forensis) is to be distinguished from Natural Punishment (pcena naturalis), in which Crime as Vice punishes itself, and does not as such come within the cognizance of the Legislator. Juridical Punishment can never be admini stered merely as a means for promoting another Good either with regard to the Criminal himself or to Civil Society, but must in all cases be imposed only because the individual on whom it is inflicted has committed a Crime. For one man ought never to be dealt with merely as a means subservient to the purpose of another, nor be mixed up with the subjects of Real Right. Against such treatment his Inborn Personality has a Right to protect him, even although he may be condemned to lose his Civil Personality. He must first be found guilty and punishable, before there can be any thought of drawing from his Punishment any benefit for himself or his fellow- citizens. The Penal Law is a Categorical Imperative ; and woe to him who creeps through the serpent-windings of Utilitarianism to discover some advantage that may discharge him from the Justice of Punishment, or even from the due measure of it, according to the Pharisaic

196 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

maxim : ' It is better that one man should die than that the whole people should perish.' For if Justice and Kighteousness perish, human life would no longer have any value in the world. What, then, is to be said of such a proposal as to keep a Criminal alive who has been condemned to death, on his being given to under stand that if he agreed to certain dangerous experiments being performed upon him, he would be allowed to sur vive if he came happily through them ? It is argued that Physicians might thus obtain new information that would be of value to the Commonweal. But a Court of Justice would repudiate with scorn any proposal of this kind if made to it by the Medical Faculty; for Justice would cease to be Justice, if it were bartered away for any consideration whatever.

But what is the mode and measure of Punishment which Public Justice takes as its Principle and Standard ? It is just the Principle of Equality, by which the pointer of the Scale of Justice is made to incline no more to the one side than the other. It may be ren dered by saying that the undeserved evil which any one commits on another, is to be regarded as perpetrated on himself. Hence it may be said : ' If you slander another, you slander yourself ; if you steal from another, you steal from yourself ; if you strike another, you strike yourself ; if you kill another, you kill your self.' This is the Eight of EETALIATION (jus talionis) ; and properly understood, it is the only Principle which in regulating a Public Court, as distinguished from mere private judgment, can definitely assign both the quality and the quantity of a just penalty. All other standards are wavering and uncertain ; and on account of other considerations involved in them, they contain no prin-

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 197

ciple conformable to the sentence of pure and strict Justice. It may appear, however, that difference of social status would not admit the application of the Principle of Retaliation, which is that of ' Like witli Like.' But although the application may not in all cases be possible according to the letter, yet as regards the effect it may always be attained in practice, by due regard being given to the disposition and sentiment of the parties in the higher social sphere. Thus a pecuniary penalty on account of a verbal injury, may have no direct proportion to the injustice of slander ; for one who is wealthy may be able to indulge himself in this offence for his own gratification. Yet the attack com mitted on the honour of the party aggrieved may have its equivalent in the pain inflicted upon the pride of the aggressor, especially if he is condemned by the judgment of the Court, not only to retract and apologize, but to submit to some meaner ordeal, as kissing the hand of the injured person. In like manner, if a man of the highest rank has violently assaulted an innocent citizen of the lower orders, he may be condemned not only to apologize but to undergo a solitary and painful imprison ment, whereby, in addition to the discomfort endured, the vanity of the offender would be painfully affected, and the very shame of his position would constitute an adequate Retaliation after the principle of ' Like with Like.' But how then would we render the statement : ' If you steal from another, you steal from yourself ' ? In this way, that whoever steals anything makes the property of all insecure ; he therefore robs himself of all security in property, according to the Right of Retaliation. Such a one has nothing, and can acquire nothing, but he has the Will to live ; and this is only

198 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

possible by others supporting him. But as the State should not do this gratuitously, he must for this purpose yield his powers to the State to be used in penal labour ; and thus he falls for a time, or it may be for life, into a condition of slavery. But whoever has committed Murder, must die. There is, in this case, no juridical substitute or surrogate, that can be given or taken for the satisfaction of Justice. There is no Likeness or propor tion between Life, however painful, and Death ; and therefore there is no Equality between the crime of Murder and the retaliation of it but what is judicially accomplished by the execution of the Criminal. His death, however, must be kept free from all maltreatment that would make the humanity suffering in his Person loathsome or abominable. Even if a Civil Society resolved to dissolve itself with the consent of all its members— as might be supposed in the case of a People inhabiting an island resolving to separate and scatter themselves throughout the whole world— the last Mur derer lying in the prison ought to be executed before the resolution was carried out. This ought to be done in order that every one may realize the desert of his deeds, and that bloodguiltiness may not remain upon the people ; for otherwise they might all be regarded as participators in the murder as a public violation of Justice.

The Equalization of Punishment with Crime, is there fore only possible by the cognition of the Judge extending even to the penalty of Death, according to the Plight of retaliation. This is manifest from the fact that it is only thus that a Sentence can be pronounced over all criminals proportionate to their internal wicked- ness; as may be seen by considering the case when the

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 199

punishment of Death has to be inflicted, not on account of a murder, but on account of a political crime that can only be punished capitally. A hypothetical case, founded on history, will illustrate this. In the last Scottish Rebellion there were various participators in it such as Balmerino and others who believed that in taking part in the Rebellion they were only discharging their duty to the House of Stuart ; but there were also others who were animated only by private motives and interests. Now, suppose that the Judgment of the Supreme Court regarding them had been this : that every one should have liberty to choose between the punishment of Death or Penal Servitude for life. In view of such an alternative, I say that the Man of Honour would choose Death, and the Knave would choose servitude. This would be the effect of their human nature as it is ; for the honourable man values his Honour more highly than even Life itself, whereas a Knave regards a Life, although covered with shame, as better in his eyes than not to be.1 The former is, without gainsaying, less guilty than the other ; and they can only be proportionately punished by death being inflicted equally upon them both ; yet to the one it is a mild punishment when his nobler temperament is taken into account, whereas it is a hard punishment to the other in view of his baser temperament. But, on the other hand, were they all equally condemned to Penal Servitude for life, the honourable man would be too severely punished, while the other, on account of his baseness of nature, would be too mildly punished. In the judgment to be pronounced over a number of criminals united in such a conspiracy, the best Equalizer

1 ' Animam pneferrc i>iulori, Juvtn.

200 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

of Punishment and Crime in the form of public Justice is Death. And besides all this, it has never been heard of, that a Criminal condemned to death on account of a murder has complained that the Sentence inflicted on him more than was right and just ; and any one would treat him with scorn if he expressed himself to this effect against it. Otherwise it would be necessary to admit that although wrong and injustice are not done to the Criminal by the Law, yet the Legislative Power is not entitled to administer this mode of Punishment ; and if it did so, it would be in contradiction with itself.

However many they may be who have committed a murder, or have even commanded it, or acted as art and part in it, they ought all to suffer death ; for so Justice wills it, in accordance with the Idea of the juridical Power as founded on the universal Laws of Eeason. But the number of the Accomplices (corrci) in such a deed might happen to be so great that the State, in resolving to be without such criminals, would be in danger of soon also being deprived of subjects. But it will not thus dissolve itself, neither must it return to the much worse condition of Nature, in which there would be no external Justice. Nor, above all, should it deaden the sensibilities of the People by the spectacle of Justice being exhibited in the mere carnage of a slaughtering bench. In such circumstances the Sove reign must always be allowed to have it in his power to take the part of the Judge upon himself as a case of Necessity, and to deliver a Judgment which, instead of the penalty of death, shall assign some other punish ment to the Criminals, and thereby preserve a multitude of the People. The penalty of Deportation is relevant in this connection. Such a form of Judgment cannot

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 201

be carried out according to a public law, but only by an authoritative act of the royal Prerogative, and it may only be applied as an act of grace in individual cases.

Against these doctrines, the Marquis BECCARIA has given forth a different view. Moved by the compas sionate sentimentality of a humane feeling, he has asserted that all Capital Punishment is wrong in itself and unjust. He has put forward this view on the ground that the penalty of death could not be contained in the original Civil Contract ; for, in that case, every one of the People would have had to consent to lose his life if he murdered any of his fellow-citizens. But, it is argued, such a consent is impossible, because no one can thus dispose of his own life. All this is mere sophistry and perversion of Eight. No one undergoes Punishment because he has willed to be punished, but because he has willed a punishable Action ; for it is in fact no Punishment when any one experiences what he \vills, and it is impossible for any one to will to be punished. To say, ' I will to be punished, if I murder any one,' can mean nothing more than, ' I submit myself along with all the other citizens to the Laws ; ' and if there are any Criminals among the People, these Laws will include Penal Laws. The individual who, as a Co-legislator, enacts Penal Law, cannot possibly be the same Person who, as a Subject, is punished according to the Law ; for, qua Criminal, he cannot possibly be regarded as having a voice in the Legislation, the Legislator being rationally viewed as just and holy. If any one, then, enact a Penal Law against himself as a Criminal, it must he the pure juridically law -giving lleason (lioino noumcnon), which subjects him as one capable of crime, and consequently as another Person

202 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

(homo phenomenon), along with all the others in the Civil Union, to this Penal Law. In other words, it is not the People taken distributively, but the Tribunal of public Justice, as distinct from the Criminal, that prescribes Capital Punishment ; and it is not to be viewed as if the Social Contract contained the Promise of all the individuals to allow themselves to be punished, thus dis posing of themselves and their lives. For if the Eight to punish must be grounded upon a promise of the wrongdoer, whereby he is to be regarded as being willing to be punished, it ought also to be left to him to find himself deserving of the Punishment ; and the Criminal would thus be his own Judge. The chief error (irpwrov >/re{}8o?) of this sophistry consists in regarding the judgment of the Criminal himself, necessarily deter mined by his Reason, that he is under obligation to undergo the loss of his life, as a judgment that must be grounded on a resolution of his Will to take it away himself ; and thus the execution of the Eight in question is represented as united in one and the same person with the adjudication of the Eight.

There are, however, two crimes worthy of death, in respect of which it still remains doubtful whether the Legislature have the Eight to deal with them capitally. It is the sentiment of Honour that induces their per petration. The one originates in a regard for womanly Honour, the other in a regard for military Honour; and in both cases there is a genuine feeling of honour incumbent on the individuals as a Duty. The former is the Crime of MATERNAL INFANTICIDE (infanticidium maternale) ; the latter is the Crime of KILLING A FELLOW- SOLDIER in a Duel (Commilitonicidium). Now Legislation cannot take away the shame of an illegitimate birth, nor

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIp RIGHT. 203

wipe off the stain attaching from a suspicion of cowardice, to an officer who does not resist an act that would brintr

O

him into contempt, by an effort of his own that is superior to the fear of death. Hence it appears that in such circumstances, the individuals concerned are remitted to the State of Nature ; and their acts in both cases must be called Homicide, and not Murder, which involves evil intent (homicidium dolosum). In all instances the acts are undoubtedly punishable ; but they cannot be punished by the Supreme Power with death. An ille gitimate child comes into the world outside of the Law which properly regulates Marriage, and it is thus born beyond the pale or constitutional protection of the Law. Such a child is introduced, as it were, like prohibited goods, into the Commonwealth, and as it has no legal right to existence in this way, its destruction might also be ignored ; nor can the shame of the mother when her unmarried confinement is known, be removed by any legal ordinance. A subordinate Officer, again, on whom an insult is inflicted, sees himself compelled by the public opinion of his associates to obtain satisfaction ; and, as in the state of Nature, the punishment of the offender can only be effected by a Duel, in which his own life is ex posed to danger, and not by means of the Law in a Court of Justice. The Duel is therefore adopted as the means of ^demonstrating his courage as that characteristic upon winch the Honour of his profession essentially rests ; and this is done even if it should issue in the killing of his adversary. But as such a result takes place publicly and under consent of both parties, although it may be done unwillingly, it cannot properly be called Murder (homicidium dolosum). What then is the Eight in both cases as relating to Criminal Justice ? Penal Justice is

204 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

here in fact brought into great straits, having apparently either to declare the notion of Honour, which is certainly no mere fancy here, to be nothing in the eye of the Law, or to exempt the crime from its clue punishment ; and thus it would become either remiss or cruel. The knot thus tied is to be resolved in the following way. The Categorical Imperative of Penal Justice, that the killing of any person contrary to the Law must be punished with death, remains in force ; but the Legislation itself and the Civil Constitution generally, so long as they are still barbarous and incomplete, are at fault. And this is the reason why the subjective motive-principles of Honour among the People, do not coincide with the standards which are objectively conformable to another purpose ; so that the public Justice issuing from the State becomes Injustice relatively to that which is upheld among the People themselves. [See Supplementary Explanations, v.]

II. THE EIGHT OF PARDONING.

The RIGHT OF PARDONING (Jus aygratiandi), viewed in relation to the Criminal, is the Eight of mitigating or entirely remitting his Punishment. On the side of the Sovereign this is the most delicate of all Eights, as it may be exercised so as to set forth the splendour of his dignity, and yet so as to do a great wrong by it. It ought not to be exercised in application to the crimes of the subjects against each other ; for exemption from Punishment (impunitas criminis) would be the greatest wrong that could be done to them. It is only on occasion of some form of TREASON (crimen Icesce tnajes- fctis), as a lesion against himself, that the Sovereign should make use of this Eight. And it should not be

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 205

exercised even in this connection, if the safety of th« People would be endangered by remitting such Punish ment. This Right is the only one which properly deserves the name of a ' Plight of Majesty.'

50.

Juridical Relations of the Citizen to his Country and to other Countries. Emigration ; Immigration ; Banish ment; Exile.

The Land or Territory whose inhabitants in virtue of its political Constitution and without the necessary intervention of a special juridical act are, by birth, fellow-citizens of one and the same Commonwealth, is called their COUNTRY or Fatherland. A Foreign Country is one in which they would not possess this condition, but would be living abroad. If a Country abroad form part of the territory under the same Government as at home, it constitutes a Province, according to the Roman usage of the term. It does not constitute an incorporated portion of the Empire (imperil) so as to be the aboil t- of equal fellow-citizens, but is only a possession of the Government, like a lower House ; and it must therefore, honour the domain of the ruling State as the ' Mother Country ' (rcgio domino).

1. A Subject, even regarded as u Citizen, has the Right of Emifjration ; for the State cannot retain him as if he were its property. But he may only carry away with him his Moveables as distinguished from his fixed possessions. However, he is entitled to sell his immov able property, and take the value of it in money with him.

2. The Supreme Power as Master of the Country, has the Right to favour Imm it/ration, and the settlement of

206 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Strangers and Colonists. This will hold even although the natives of the Country may be unfavourably disposed to it, if their private property in the soil is not diminished or interfered with.

3. In the case of a Subject who has committed a Crime that renders all society of his fellow-citizens with him prejudicial to the State, the Supreme Power has also the Eight of inflicting Banishment to a Country abroad. By such Deportation, he does not acquire any share in the Eights of the Citizens of the territory to which he is banished.

4. The Supreme Power has also the Eight of imposing Exile generally (Jus exilii), by which a Citizen is sent abroad into the wide world as the ' Out-land.' * And because the Supreme Authority thus withdraws all legal protection from the Citizen, this amounts to making him an ' outlaw ' within the territory of his own country.

51.

The Three Forms of the State. Autocracy ; Aristocracy ; Democracy.

The three Powers in the State, involved in the con ception of a Public Government generally (res publica latins dicta), are only so many Eelations of the united Will of the People which emanates from the a priori Eeason ; and viewed as such it is the objective practical realization of the pure Idea of a Supreme Head of the State. This Supreme Head is the Sovereign ; but con ceived only as a Eepresentation of the whole People, the Idea still requires physical embodiment in a Person, who

1 In the old German language ' Elend,' which in its modern use means 'misery.'

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC 1IIGIIT. 207

may exhibit the Supreme Power of the State, and bring the idea actively to bear upon the popular Will. The relation of the Supreme Power to the People, is con ceivable in three different forms : Either Chic in the State rules over all ; or Some, united in a relation of Equality with each other, rule over all the others ; or All together rule over each and all individually, including themselves. The Form of the State is therefore either autocratic, or aristocratic, or democratic. The expression ' monarchic ' is not so suitable as ' autocratic ' for the conception here intended ; for a ' Monarch ' is one who has the hiyhcst power, an ' Autocrat ' is one who has all power, so that this latter is the Sovereign, whereas the former merely represents the Sovereignty.

It is evident that an Autocracy is the simplest form of Government in the State, being constituted by the rela tion of One, as King, to the People, so that there is one only who is the Lawgiver. An Aristocracy, as a form of Government, is, however, compounded of the union of two relations : that of the Nobles in relation to one another as the Lawgivers, thereby constituting the Sovereignty, and that of this Sovereign Power to the People. A ^Democracy, again, is the most complex of all the forms of the State, for it has to begin by uniting the will of all so as to form a People ; and then it has to appoint a Sovereign over this common LTnion, which Sovereign is no other than the United Will itself. The consideration of the ways in which these Forms are adulterated by the intrusion of violent and illegitimate usurpers of power, as in Oligarchy and OcJdocracy, as well as the discussion of the so-called mixed Constitutions, may be passed over here as not essential, and as leading into too much detail.

208 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

As regards the Administration of Eight in the State, it may be said that the simplest mode is also the best ; but as regards its bearing on Eight itself, it is also tlu; most dangerous for the People, in view of the Despotism to which simplicity of Administration so naturally gives rise. It is undoubtedly a rational maxim to aim at simpli fication in the machinery which is to unite the People under compulsory Laws, and this would be secured were all the People to be passive and to obey only one person over them ; but the method would not give Subjects who were also Citizens of the State. It is sometimes said that the People should be satisfied with the reflection that Monarchy, regarded as an Autocracy, is the best political Constitution, if the Monarch is good, that is, if he has the judgment as well as the Will to do right. But this is a mere evasion, and belongs to the common class of wise tautological phrases. It only amounts to saying that ' the best Constitution is that by which the supreme administrator of the State is made the best Euler ; ' that is, that the best Constitution is the best !

52.

Historical Origin and Changes. A Pure Republic. Representative Government.

It is vain to inquire into the historical Origin of the political Mechanism ; for it is no longer possible to dis cover historically the point of time at which Civil Society took its beginning. Savages do not draw up ;i documentary Eecord of their having submitted themselves to Law ; and it may be inferred from the nature of uncivilised men that they must have set out from a state of violence. To prosecute such an inquiry in the inten-

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 209

tion of finding a pretext for altering the existing Con stitution by violence, is no less than penal. For such a mode of alteration would amount to a Revolution, that could only be carried out by an Insurrection of the People, and not by constitutional modes of Legislation. But Insurrection against an already existing Constitution, is an overthrow of all civil and juridical relations, and of IJiglit generally ; and hence it is not a mere alteration of the Civil Constitution, but a dissolution of it. It would thus form a mode of transition to a better Con stitution by Palingenesis and not by mere Meta morphosis ; and it would require a new Social Contract, upon which the former Original Contract, as then annulled, would have no influence.

It must, however, be possible for the Sovereign to change the existing Constitution, if it is not actually consistent with the Idea of the Original Contract. In doing so it is essential to give existence to that form of Government which will properly constitute the People into a State. Such a change cannot be made by the State deliberately altering its Constitution from one of the three Forms to one of the other two. For example, political changes should not be carried out by the Aristocrats combining to subject themselves to an Auto cracy, or resolving to fuse all into a Democracy, or conversely; as if it depended on the arbitrary choice and liking of the Sovereign what Constitution he may impose on the People. For, even if as Sovereign he resolved to alter the Constitution into a Democracy, he might be doing Wrong to the People, because they might hold such a Constitution in abhorrence, and regard either of the other two as more suitable to them in the circumstances.

210 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

The Forms of the State are only the letter (littera) of the original Constitution in the Civil Union ; and they may therefore remain so long as they are considered, from ancient and long habit (and therefore only sub jectively), to be necessary to the machinery of the political Constitution. But the spirit of that original Contract (anima pacti originarii) contains and imposes the obliga tion on the constituting Power to make the mode of the Government conformable to its Idea ; and, if this cannot be effected at once, to change it gradually and con tinuously till it harmonize in its working with the only rightful Constitution, which is that of a Pure Republic. Thus the old empirical and statutory Forms, which serve only to effect the political subjection of the People, will be resolved into the original and rational Forms which alone take Freedom ns their principle, and even as the con dition of all compulsion and constraint. Compulsion is in fact requisite for the realization of a juridical Con stitution, according to the proper idea of the State ; and it will lead at last to the realization of that Idea, even according to the letter. This is the only enduring political Constitution, as in it the LAW is itself Sovereign, and is no longer attached to a particular person. This is the ultimate End of all Public Eight, and the state in which every citizen can have what is his own peremp torily assigned to him. But so long as the Form of the State has to be represented, according to the Letter, by many different Moral Persons invested with the Supreme Power, there can only be a provisory internal Eight, and not an absolutely juridical state of Civil Society.

Every true Eepublic is and can only be constituted by a Representative System of the People. Such a Eepre- scntative System is instituted in name of the People,

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 211

and is constituted by all the Citizens being united together, iii order, by means of their Deputies, to protect and secure their Eights. But as soon as a Supreme Head of the State in person be it as King, or Nobility, or the whole body of the People in a democratic Union be comes also representative, the United People then does not merely represent the Sovereignty, but they are them selves sovereign. It is in the People that the Supreme Power originally resides, and it is accordingly from this Power that all the Rights of individual Citizens as mere Subjects, and especially as Officials of the State, must be derived. When the Sovereignty of the People themselves is thus realized, the Republic is established ; and it is no longer necessary to give up the reins of Government into the hands of those by whom they have been hitherto held, especially as they might again destroy all the new Insti tutions by their arbitrary and absolute Will.

It was therefore a great error in judgment on the part of a powerful Ruler in our time, when he tried to extricate himself from the embarrassment arising from great public debts, by transferring this burden to the People, and leaving them to undertake and dis tribute them among themselves as they might best think fit. It thus became natural that the Legislative Power, not only in respect of the Taxation of the Subjects, but in respect of the Government, should come into the hands of the People. It was requisite that they should be able to prevent the incurring of new Debts by extravagance or war; arid in conse quence, the Supreme Power of the Monarch entirely disappeared, not by being merely suspended, but by passing over in fact to the People, to whose legislative Will the property of every Subject thus became sub jected. Nor can it be said that a tacit and yet obligatory promise must be assumed as having, under

212 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

such circumstances, been given by the National Assembly, not to constitute themselves into a Sove reignty, but only to administer the affairs of the Sovereign for the time, and after this was done to deliver the reins of the Government again into the Monarch's hands. Such a supposed contract would be null and void. The Right of the Supreme Legis lation in the Commonwealth is not an alienable Right, but is the most personal of all Rights. Who ever possesses it, can only dispose by the collective Will of the People, in respect of the People; he cannot dispose in respect of the Collective Will itself, which is the ultimate foundation of all public Con tracts. A Contract, by which the People would be bound to give back their authority again, would not be consistent with their position as a Legislative Power, and yet it would be made binding upon the People ; which, on the principle that ' No one can serve two Masters,' is a contradiction.

PUBLIC RIGHT.

II.

THE RIGHT OF NATIONS AND INTERNATIONAL LAW. (Jus Gentium.)

53.

Nature and Division of the Right of Nations.

The individuals, who make up a People, may be regarded as Natives of the Country sprung by natural descent from a Common Ancestry (congcniti), although this may not hold entirely true in detail. Again, they may be viewed according to the intellectual and juridical relation, as born of a common political Mother, the Republic, so that they constitute, as it were, a public Family or NATION (gens, natio) whose Members are all related to each other as Citizens of the State. As members of a State, they do not mix with those who live beside them in the state of Nature, considering such to be ignoble. Yet these savages, on account of the law less freedom they have chosen, regard themselves as superior to civilised peoples ; and they constitute tribes and even races, but not States. The public Right of States (jus publicum Civitatum) in their relations to one another, is what we have to consider under the designa tion of the ' Right of Nations.' Wherever a State, viewed

214 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

as a Moral Person, acts in relation to another existing in the condition of natural freedom, and consequently in a state of continual war, such Eight takes it rise.

The Eight of Nations in relation to the State of War may be divided into: 1. The Eight of going to War; 2. Eight during War ; and 3. Eight after War, the object of which is to constrain the nations mutually to pass from this state of war, and to found a common Con stitution establishing Perpetual Peace. The difference between the Eight of individual men or families as related to each other in the state of Nature, and the Eight of the Nations among themselves, consists in this, that in the Eight of Nations we have to consider not merely a relation of one State to another as a whole, but also the relation of the individual persons in one State to the individuals of another State, as well as to that State as a whole. This difference, however, between the Eight of Nations and the Eight of Individuals in the mere State of Nature, requires to be determined by elements which can easily be deduced from the con ception of the latter.

54.

Elements of the Right of Nations.

The elements of the Eight of Nations are as follow :

1. STATES, viewed as NATIONS, in their external

relations to one another like lawless savages are

naturally in a non-juridical condition ;

2. This natural condition is a STATE OF WAR in which the Eight of the stronger prevails ; and although it may not in fact be always found as a state of actual

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 215

war and incessant hostility, and although no real wrong is done to any one therein, yet the condition is wrong in itself in the highest degree, and the Nations which form States contiguous to each other are bound mutually to pass out of it ;

3. An ALLIANCE OF NATIONS, in accordance with the idea of an original Social Contract, is necessary to pro tect each other against external aggression and attack, but not involving interference with their several internal difficulties and disputes;

4. This mutual connection by Alliance must dispense with a distinct Sovereign Tower, such as is set up in the Civil Constitution ; it can only take the form of a FEDERATION, which as such may be revoked on any occasion, and must consequently be renewed from time to time.

This is therefore a Eight which comes in as an accessory (in subsidium) of another original Eight, in order to prevent the Nations from falling from Eight, and lapsing into the state of actual war with each other. It thus issues in the idea of a Fcedus Ampliidyonum.

55.

Right of Going to War as related to the Subjects of the State.

We have then to consider, in the first place, the original Eight of free States to go to War with each other as being still in a state of Nature, but as exercis ing this Eight in order to establish some condition of society approaching the juridical state. And, first of all, the question arises as to what Eight the State has in relation to its own Subjects, to use them in order to make

216 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

war against other States, to employ their property and even their lives for this purpose, or at least to expose them to hazard and danger ; and all this in such a way that it does not depend upon their own personal judgment whether they will march into the field of war or not, but the Supreme Command of the Sovereign claims to settle and dispose of them thus.

This Plight appears capable of being easily estab lished. It may be grounded upon the Eight which every one has to do with what is his own as he will. Whatever one has made substantially for himself, he holds as his incontestable property. The following, then, is such a deduction as a mere Jurist would put forward.

There are various natural Products in a country which, as regards the number and quantity in which they exist, must be considered as specially produced (artefacta) by the work of the State; for the country would not yield them to such extent were it not under the Con stitution of the State and its regular administrative Government, or if the inhabitants were still living in

the State of Nature. Sheep, cattle, domestic fowl, the

most useful of their kind, swine, and such like, would either be used up as necessary food or destroyed by beasts of prey in the district in which I live, so that they would entirely disappear, or be found in very scant supplies, were it not for the Government securing to the inhabitants their acquisitions and property. This holds likewise of the population itself, as we see in the case of the American deserts; and even were the greatest industry applied in those regions— which is not yet done— there might be but a scanty population. The inhabitants of any country would be but sparsely sown

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 217

here and there were it not for the protection of Govern ment ; because without it they could not spread them selves with their households upon a territory which was always in danger of being devastated by enemies or by wild beasts of prey ; and further, so great a multi tude of men as now live in any one country could not otherwise obtain sufficient means of support. Hence, as it can be said of vegetable growths, such as potatoes, as well as of domesticated animals, that because the abundance in which they are found is a product of human labour, they may be used, destroyed, and con sumed by man ; so it seems that it may be said of the Sovereign as the Supreme Power in the State, that he has the Right to lead his Subjects, as being for the most part productions of his own, to war, as if it were to the chase, and even to march them to the field of battle, as if it were on a pleasure excursion.

This principle of Right may be supposed to float dimly before the mind of the Monarch, and it certainly holds true at least of the lower animals which may become the property of man. But such a principle will not at all apply to men, especially when viewed as citizens who must be regarded as members of the State, with a share in the legislation, and not merely as means for others but as Ends in themselves. As such they must give their free consent, through their representa tives, not only to the carrying on of war generally, but to every separate declaration of war ; and it is only under this limiting condition that the State has a Right to demand their services in undertakings so full of danger.

We would therefore deduce this Right rather from the duty of the Sovereign to the people than conversely.

218 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

Under this relation the people must be regarded as having given their sanction ; and, having the Eight of voting, they may be considered, although thus passive in reference to themselves individually, to be active in so far as they represent the Sovereignty itself.

56.

Right of Going to War in relation to Hostile States.

Viewed as in the state of Nature, the Eight of Nations to go to War and to carry on hostilities is the legitimate way by which they prosecute their Eights by their own power when they regard themselves as injured; and this is done because in that state the method of a juridical Process, although the only one proper to settle such disputes, cannot be adopted.

The threatening of War is to be distinguished from the active injury of a first Aggression, which again is distinguished from the general outbreak of Hostilities. A threat or menace may be given by the active pre paration of Armaments, upon which a Eight of Preven tion (jus prccventionis) is founded on the other side, or merely by the formidable increase of the power of another State (potestas tremenda) by acquisition of Territory. Lesion of a less powerful country may be involved merely in the condition of a more powerful neighbour prior to any action at all; and in the State of Nature an attack under such circumstances would be warrantable. This international relation is the foundation of the Eight of Equilibrium, or of the ' balance of Power/ among all the States that are in active contiguity to each other.

The Right to go to War is constituted by any overt act of Injury. This includes any arbitrary Retaliation

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 219

or act of Reprisal (retorsio) as a satisfaction taken by one people for an offence committed by another, without any attempt being made to obtain reparation in a peace ful way. Such an act of retaliation would be similar in kind to an outbreak of hostilities without a previous Declaration of War. For if there is to be any Right at all during the state of war, something analogous to a Contract must be assumed, involving acceptance on the one side of the declaration on the other, and amounting to the fact that they both will to seek their Eight in this way.

57.

Right during War.

The determination of what constitutes Eight in War, is the most difficult problem of the Right of Nations and International Law. It is very difficult even to form a conception of such a Right, or to think of any Law in this lawless state without falling into a contradiction. Inter arma silent leges. It must then be just the right to carry on War according to such principles as render it always still possible to pass out of that natural con dition of the states in their external relations to each other, and to enter into a condition of Right.

No war of independent States against each other, can rightly be a war of Punishment (bellum punitivum). For punishment is only in place under the relation of a Superior (imperantis) to a Subject (subditum) ; and this is not the relation of the States to one another. Neither can an international war be ' a war of Extermination ' (bellum internicinum), nor even ' a war of Subjugation ' (bellum subfugatorium) ; for this would issue in the moral

220 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

extinction of a State by its people being either fused into one mass with the conquering State, or being reduced to slavery. Not that this necessary means of attaining to a condition of peace is itself contradictory to the right of a State ; but because the idea of the Eight of Nations includes merely the conception of an antagonism that is in accordance with principles of external freedom, in order that the State may maintain what is properly its own, but not that it may acquire a condition which, from the aggrandizement of its power, might become threatening to other States.

Defensive measures and means of all kinds are allow able to a State that is forced to war, except such as by their use would make the Subjects using them unfit to be citizens ; for the State would thus make itself unfit to be regarded as a person capable of participating in equal rights in the international relations according to the Eight of Nations. Among these forbidden means are to be reckoned the appointment of Subjects to act as spies, or engaging Subjects or even strangers to act as assassins, or poisoners (in which class might well be included the so-called sharpshooters who lurk in ambush for individuals), or even employing agents to spread false news. In a word, it is forbidden to use any such malig nant and perfidious means as would destroy the con fidence which would be requisite to establish a lasting peace thereafter.

It is permissible in war to impose exactions and con tributions upon a conquered enemy ; but it is not legitimate to plunder the people in the way of forcibly depriving individuals of their property. For this would be robbery, seeing it was not the conquered people but the State under whose government they were placed that

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. L' '1 1

carried on the war by means of them. All exactions should be raised by regular Requisition, and lieceipts ought to be given for them, in order that when peace is restored the burden imposed on the country or the province may be proportionately borne.

58. Right after War.

The Eight that follows after War, begins at the moment of the Treaty of Peace and refers to the con sequences of the war. The conqueror lays down the conditions under which he will agree with the conquered power to form the conclusion of Peace. Treaties are drawn up ; not indeed according to any Right that it pertains to him to protect, on account of an alleged lesion by his opponent, but as taking this question upon himself, he bases the right to decide it upon his own power. Hence the conqueror may not demand restitu tion of the cost of the war ; because he would then have to declare the war of his opponent to be unjust. And even although he should adopt such an argument, he is not entitled to apply it ; because he would have to declare the war to be punitive, and he would thus in turn inflict an injury. To this right belongs also the Exchange of Prisoners, which is to be carried out without ransom and without regard to equality of numbers.

Neither the conquered State nor its Subjects, lose their political liberty by conquest of the country, so as that the former should be degraded to a colony, or the latter to slaves ; for otherwise it would have been a penal war, which is contradictory in itself. A colony or a province is constituted by a people which has its own

KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

constitution, legislation, and territory, where persons be longing to another State are merely strangers, but which is nevertheless subject to the supreme executive power of another State. This other State is called the ' mother- country.' It is ruled as a daughter, but has at the same time its own form of government, as in a separate Parlia ment under the presidency of a Viceroy (civitas Uybrida). Such was Athens in relation to different islands ; and such is at present [1796] the relation of Great Britain to Ireland.

Still less can Slavery be deduced as a rightful institu tion, from the conquest of a people in war; for this would assume that the war was of a punitive nature. And least of all can a basis be found in war for a Jicreditary Slavery, which is absurd in itself, since guilt cannot be inherited from the criminality of another.

Further, that an Amnesty is involved in the conclusion of a Treaty of Peace, is already implied in the very idea of a Peace.

59.

The Rights of Peace. The Eights of Peace are :

1. The Eight to be in Peace when War is in the neighbourhood, or the Kight of Neutrality.

. The Kight to have Peace secured so that it may continue when it has been concluded, that is, the Kight of Guarantee.

. The Kight of the several States to enter int..

mutual Allmnce, so as to defend themselves in common

unst all external or even internal attacks. This Eight

of Federation, however, does not extend to the formation

B

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT.

of any League for external aggression or internal aggran dizement.

60.

Right as against an Unjust Enemy.

The Hight of a State against an unjust Enemy has no limits, at least in respect of quality as distinguished from quantity or degree. In other words, the injured State may use not, indeed, any means, but yet all those means that are permissible and in reasonable measure in so far as they are in its power, in order to assert its 1 tight to what is its own. But what then is an unjust enemy according to the conceptions of the liight of Nations, when, as holds generally of the state of Nature, every State is judge in its own cause ? It is one whose publicly expressed Will, whether in word or deed, betrays u maxim which, if it were taken as a universal rule, would make a state of Peace among the nations impos sible, and would necessarily perpetuate the state of Nature. Such is the violation of public Treaties, with regard to which it may be assumed that any such violation concerns all nations by threatening their free dom, and that they are thus summoned to unite against such a wrong, and to take away the power of committing it. But this does not include the liight to partition and appropriate the country, so as to make a State as it were disappear from the earth ; for this would be an injustice to the people of that State, who cannot lose their original Eight to unite into a Commonwealth, and to adopt such a new Constitution as by its nature would be unfavour able to the inclination for war.

Further, it may be said that the expression 'an unjust enemy in the state of Nature ' is pleonastic ; for the state

004 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

of Nature is itself a state of injustice. A just Enemy would be one to whom I would do wrong in offering resistance; but such a one would really not be my Enemy.

61.

Perpetual Peace and a Permanent Congress of Nations.

The natural state of Nations as well as of individual men is a state which it is a duty to pass out of, in order to enter into a legal state. Hence, before this transition occurs, all the Eight of Nations and all the external property of States acquirable or maintainable by war, are merely provisory ; and they can only become peremptory in a universal Union of States analogous to that by which a Nation becomes a State. It is thus only that a real state of Peace could be established. But with the too great extension of such a Union of States over vast regions any government of it, and conse quently the protection of its individual members, must at last become impossible ; and thus a multitude of such corporations would again bring round a state of war. Hence the Perpetual Peace, which is the ultimate end of all the Eight of Nations, becomes in fact an impractic able idea. The political principles, however, which aim at such an end, and which enjoin the formation of such unions among the States as may promote a continuous approximation to a Perpetual Peace, are not impractic able ; they are as practicable as this approximation itself, which is a practical problem involving a duty, and founded upon the Eight of individual men and States.

Such a Union of States, in order to maintain Peace, may be called a Permanent Congress of Nations ; and it

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 22

_ •_' .

is free to every neighbouring State to join in it. A union of this kind, so far at least as regards the for malities of the Right of Nations in respect of the preservation of peace, was presented in the first half of this century, in the Assembly of the States-General at the Hague. In this Assembly most of the European Courts, and even the smallest Republics, brought forward their complaints about the hostilities which were carried on by the one against the other. Thus the whole of Europe appeared like a single Federated State, accepted as Umpire by the several nations in their public differ ences. But in place of this agreement, the Right of Nations afterwards survived only in books; it dis appeared from the cabinets, or, after force had been already used, it was relegated in the form of theoretical deductions to the obscurity of Archives.

By such a Congress is here meant only a voluntary combination of different States that would be dissoluble at any time, and not such a union as is embodied in the United States of America, founded upon a political con stitution, and therefore indissoluble. It is only by a Congress of this kind that the idea of a Public Right of Nations can be established, and that the settlement of their differences by the mode of a civil process, and not by the barbarous means of war, can be realized.

PUBLIC RIGHT.

III.

THE UNIVERSAL EIGHT OF MANKIND. (Jus cosmopoliticum.)

62.

Nature and Conditions of Cosmopolitical Right.

THE rational idea of a universal, peaceful, if not yet

friendly, Union of all the Nations upon the earth that

may come into active relations with each other, is a

juridical Principle, as distinguished from philanthropic

or ethical principles. Nature has enclosed them

altogether within definite boundaries, in virtue of the

spherical form of their abode as a globus terraqucus ; and

the possession of the soil upon which an inhabitant of

the earth may live, can only be regarded as possession

of a part of a limited whole, and consequently as a

part to which every one has originally a Right. Hence

all nations originally hold a community of the soil, but

not & juridical community of possession (communio), nor

consequently of the use or proprietorship of the soil,

but only of a possible physical intercourse (commercium)

by means of it. In other words, they are placed in

such thoroughgoing relations of each to all the rest,

that they may claim to enter into intercourse with one

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 227

another, and they have a right to make an attempt in this direction, while a foreign nation would not be entitled to treat them on this account as enemies. This Eight, in so far as it relates to a possible Union of all Nations, in respect of certain laws universally regulating their intercourse with each other, may be called ' Cosmo- political Kight ' (jus cosmopoliticum}.

It may appear that seas put nations out of all com munion with each other. But this is not so ; for by means of commerce, seas form the happiest natural provision for their intercourse. And the more there are of neighbouring coast - lands, as in the case of the Mediterranean Sea, this intercourse becomes the more animated. And hence communications with such lands, especially where there are settlements upon them con nected with the mother countries giving occasion for such communications, bring it about that evil and violence committed in one place of our globe are felt in all. Such possible abuse cannot, however, annul the Right of man as a citizen of the world to attempt to enter into communion with all others, and for this pur pose to visit all the regions of the earth, although this does not constitute a right of settlement upon the terri tory of another people (jus incolatus), for which a special contract is required.

But the question is raised as to whether, in the case of newly discovered countries, a people may claim the right to settle (accolatus), and to occupy possessions in the neighbourhood of another people that has already settled in that region ; and to do this without their consent.

Such a Right is indubitable, if the new settlement takes place at such a distance from the seat of the

228 KANT S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

former, that neither would restrict or injure the other in the use of their territory. But in the case of nomadic peoples, or tribes of shepherds and hunters (such as the Hottentots, the Tungusi, and most of the American Indians), whose support is derived from wide desert tracts, such occupation should never take place by force, but only by contract ; and any such contract ought never to take advantage of the ignorance of the original dwellers in regard to the cession of their lands. Yet it is commonly alleged that such acts of violent appro priation may be justified as subserving the general good of the world. It appears as if sufficiently justifying grounds were furnished for them, partly by reference to the civilisation of barbarous peoples (as by a pretext of this kind even Busching tries to excuse the bloody introduction of the Christian religion into Germany), and partly by founding upon the necessity of purging one's own country from depraved criminals, and the hope of their improvement or that of their posterity, in another continent like New Holland. But all these alleged good purposes cannot wash out the stain of injustice in the means employed to attain them. It may be objected that had such scrupulousness about making a beginning in founding a legal State with force been always main tained, the whole earth would still have been in a state of lawlessness. But such an objection would as little annul the conditions of Eight in question as the pre text of the political revolutionaries, that when a con stitution has become degenerate, it belongs to the people to transform it by force. This would amount generally to being unjust once and for all, in order thereafter to found justice the more surely, and to make it flourish.

CONCLUSION.

IF one cannot prove that a thing is, he may try to prove that it is not. And if he succeeds in doing neither (as often occurs), he may still ask whether it is in his interest to accept one or other of the alternatives hypothetically, from the theoretical or the practical point of view. In other words, a hypothesis may be accepted either in order to explain a certain Phenomenon (as in Astronomy to account for the retrogression and station- ariness of the planets), or in order to attain a certain end, which again may be either pragmatic as belonging merely to the sphere of Art, or moral as involving a purpose which it is a duty to adopt as a maxim of action. Now it is evident that the assumption (suppo- xitio) of the practicability of such an End, though pre sented merely as a theoretical and problematical judgment, may be regarded as constituting a duty ; and hence it is so regarded in this case. For although there may be no positive obligation to believe in such an End, yet even if there were not the least theoretical probability of action being carried out in accordance with it, so long as its impossibility cannot be demonstrated, there still remains a duty incumbent upon us with regard to it.

Now, as a matter of fact, the morally practical Reason

230 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

utters within us its irrevocable Veto : ' There shall le no War.' So there ought to be no war, neither between me and you in the condition of Nature, nor between us as members of States which, although internally in a condition of law, are still externally in their relation to each other in a condition of lawlessness ; for this is not the way by which any one should prosecute his Eight. Hence the question no longer is as to whether Perpetual Peace is a real thing or not a real thing, or as to whether we may not be deceiving ourselves when we adopt the former alternative, but we must act on the supposition of its being real. We must work for what may perhaps not be realized, and establish that Constitution which yet seems best adapted to bring it about (mayhap Eepubli- canism in all States, together and separately). And thus we may put an end to the evil of wars, which have been the chief interest of the internal arrangements of all the States without exception. And although the realization of this purpose may always remain but a pious wish, yet we do certainly not deceive ourselves in adopting the maxim of action that will guide us in working incessantly for it ; for it is a duty to do this. To suppose that the moral Law within us is itself deceptive, would be sufficient to excite the horrible wish rather to be deprived of all Reason than to live under such deception, and even to see oneself, according to such principles, degraded like the lower animals to the level of the mechanical play of Nature.

It may be said that the universal and lasting establish ment of Peace constitutes not merely a part, but the whole final purpose and End of the Science of Eight as viewed within the limits of Reason. The state of Peace is the only condition of the Mine and Thine that is

THE PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC RIGHT. 231

secured and guaranteed by Laws in the relationship of men living in numbers contiguous to each other, and who are thus combined in a Constitution whose rule is derived not from the mere experience of those who have found it the best as a normal guide for others, but which must be taken by the Keason h priori from the ideal of a juridical Union of men under public laws generally. For all particular examples or instances, being able only to furnish illustration but not proof, are deceptive, and at all events require a Metaphysic to establish them by its necessary principles. And this is conceded indirectly even by those who turn Metaphysics into ridicule, when they say, as they often do, ' The best Constitution is that in which not Men but Laws exercise the power.' For what can be more metaphysically sublime in its own way than this very Idea of theirs, which according to their own assertion has, notwithstanding, the most objective reality ? This may be easily shown by reference to actual instances. And it is this very Idea which alone can be carried out practically, if it is not forced on in a revolutionary and sudden way by violent overthrow of the existing defective Constitution ; for this would produce for the time the momentary annihilation of the whole juridical state of Society. But if the idea is carried forward by gradual Reform, and in accordance with fixed Principles, it may lead by a continuous approximation to the highest political Good, and to Perpetual Peace.

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS

OF THE

PEINCIPLES OF EIGHT

[Written by Kant in 1797, and added to the Second Edition in 1798.1

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF THE PRINCIPLES OF RIGHT.

The Occasion for these Explanations was furnished mainly by a Review of this work that appeared in the Gottingen Journal, No. 28, of 18th February 1797. The Review displays insight, and with sympathetic appreciation it expresses ' the hope that this Ex position of Principles will prove a permanent gain for juridical Science.' It is here taken as a guide in the arrangement of some critical Remarks, and at the same time as suggesting some expansion of the system in certain points of detail.

Objection as to the Faculty of Desire.

In the very first words of the GENERAL INTRODUCTION the acute Reviewer stumbles on a Definition. He asks what is meant by 'the Faculty of Desire.' In the said Introduction it is defined as ' the Power which Man has, through his mental representations, of becoming the cause of objects corresponding to these representations.' To this Definition the objection is taken, ' that it amounts to nothing as soon as we abstract from the external con ditions of the effect or consequence of the act of Desire.' ' But the Faculty of Desire,' it is added, ' is something even to the Idealist, although there is no external world according to his view.' ANSWER : Is there not likewise

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 235

a violent and yet consciously ineffective form of Desire as a mere mental longing, which is expressed by such words as ' Would to God such a one were still alive ! ' Yet although this Desire is actless in the sense of not issuing in overt action, it is not effectless in the sense of having no consequence at all ; in short, if it does not produce a change on external things, it at least works powerfully upon the internal condition of the Subject, and even may superinduce a morbid condition of disease. A Desire, viewed as an active Striving (nisiis) to be a cause by means of one's own mental representations, even although the individual may perceive his incapacity to attain the desired effect, is still a mode of causality within his own internal experience. There is therefore a misunderstanding involved in the objection, that because the consciousness of one's Power in a case of Desire may be at the same time accompanied with a consciousness of the Want of Power in respect of the external world, the definition is therefore not applicable to the Idealist. But as the question only turns generally upon the rela tion of a Cause (the Representation) to an Effect (the Feeling), the Causality of the Representation in respect of its object whether it be external or internal must inevitably be included by thought in the conception of the Faculty of Desire.

I.

Logical Preparation for the Preceding Conception of Right.

If philosophical Jurists would rise to the Metaphysical Principles of the Science of Right, without which all their juridical Science will be merely statutory, they

236 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

must not be indifferent to securing completeness in the Division of their juridical conceptions. Apart from such internal completeness their science would not be a rational System, but only an Aggregate of accidental details. The topical arrangement of Principles as deter mined by the form of the System, must therefore be made complete ; that is to say, there must be a proper place assigned to each conception (locus communis) as determined by the synthetic form of the Division. And it would have to be afterwards made apparent that when any other conception were put in the place of the one thus assigned, it would be contradictory to itself and out of its own place.

Now Jurists have hitherto received only two formal commonplaces in their Systems, namely, the conceptions of Real Eight and of Personal Eight. But since there are other two conceptions possible even a priori by a mere formal combination of these two as members of a rational Division, giving the conception of a Personal Eight of a Eeal Kind, and that of a Eeal Eight of a Personal Kind, it is natural to ask whether these further conceptions, although viewed as only proble matical in themselves, should not likewise be incorporated in the scheme of a complete Division of the juridical System ? This in fact does not admit of doubt. The merely logical Division, indeed, as abstracting from the object of Knowledge, is always in the form of a Diclwtomy ; so that every Eight is either a Eeal or a not-Eeal Eight. But the metaphysical Division, here under consideration, may also be in the fourfold form of a Tdrachotomy ; for in addition to the two simple members of the Division, there are also two relations between them, as conditions of mutual limitation arising

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 237

from the one Eight entering into combination with the other ; and the possibility of this requires a special investigation. But the conception of a Real Eight of a Personal Kind falls out at once ; for the Right of a Thing as against a Person is inconceivable. It remains, therefore, only to consider, whether the converse of this relation is likewise inconceivable ; or whether the con ception of a Personal Right of a Real Kind is not only free from internal contradiction, but is even contained a priori in Reason and belongs as a necessary constituent to the conception of the external Mine and Thine in its completeness, in order that Persons may be viewed so far in the same way as Things ; not indeed to the extent of treating them in all respects alike, but by regard to the possession of them, and to proceeding with Persons in certain relations as if they were Things.

II

Justification of the Conception of a Personal Right of a Real Kind.

The Definition of a Personal Right of a Real Kind may be put shortly and appropriately thus : ' it is the Right which a man has to have another Person than himself as his.' I say intentionally a ' Person ; ' for one might have another man who had lost his civil per sonality and become enslaved as 7m ; but such a Real Right is not under consideration here.

Now we have to examine the question whether this conception described as ' a new phenomenon in the juristic sky ' is a stella mirdbilis in the sense of growing into a star of the first magnitude, unseen before but gradually vanishing again, yet perhaps destined to return,

238 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

or whether it is to be regarded as merely a shooting and falling star ! l

III. Examples of Real-Personal Right.

1. To have anything external as one's own, means to possess it rightfully ; and Possession is the condition of the possibility of using a thing. If this condition is regarded merely as physical, the possession is called detention or holding. But legal detention alone does not suffice to make an object mine, or to entitle me so to regard it. If, however, I am entitled, on any ground whatever, to press for the possession of an object which has escaped from my power or been taken from me, this conception of right is a sign in effect that I hold myself entitled to conduct myself towards it as being mine and in my rational possession, and so to use it as my object.

The ' Mine ' in this connection does not mean that it is constituted by ownership of the Person of another ; for a man cannot even be the owner of himself, and much less of another person. It means only the right of Usufruct (jus utendi fruendi) in immediate reference to this person, as if he were a thing, but without infring- 1 According to the Definition, I do not use the expression ' to have another Person as my Person,' but as ' mine ' (™ meum), as if the Person were viewed in this relation as a Thing. For I can say ' this is my father ' in indicating my natural relationship of connection with him, by which I merely state that I have a father. But I may not say ' I have him as mine ' in this relation. However, if I say 'my Wife,' this indicates a special juridical relation of a possessor to an object viewed as a thing, although in this case it is a person. But physical possession is the condition of the use of a thing as such (manipulatio) ; although in another relation the object must at the same time be treated as a Person.

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 239

ng on the right of his personality, even while using him is a means for my own ends.

These ends, however, as conditioning the rightfulness of such use, must necessarily be moral. A man may neither desire a wife in order to enjoy her as if she were a thing by the immediate pleasure in mere physical intercourse, nor may the wife surrender herself for this purpose ; for otherwise the rights of personality would be given up on both sides. In other words, it is only under the condition of a marriage having been previously concluded that there can be such a reciprocal surrender of the two persons into the possession of each other that they will not dehumanize themselves by making a corporeal use of each other.

When this condition is not respected, the carnal enjoyment referred to, is in principle, although not always in effect, on the level of cannibalism. There is merely a difference in the manner of the enjoyment between the exhaustion which may thus be produced and the consumption of bodies by the teeth and maw of the savage ; and in such reciprocal use of the sexes the one is really made a res fungibilis to the other. Hence a contract that would bind any one for sucli mere use would be an illegal contract (pactum turpe).

2. In like manner, a husband and wife cannot produce a child as their mutual offspring (res artificialis) without both coming under the obligation towards it and towards each other to maintain it as their child. This relation accordingly involves the acquisition of a human being as if it were a thing, but it holds only in form according to the idea of a merely Personal Eight of a real kind. The parents have a Right against any possessor of the child who may have taken it out of their power (jus in

240 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

re), and they have likewise a Right to compel the child to perform and obey all their commands in so far as they are not opposed to any law of freedom (jus ad rein) ; and hence they have also a Personal Eight over the child.

3. Finally, it', on attaining the age of majority, the duty of the parents in regard to the maintenance of their children ceases, they have still the Eight to use them as members of the house subjected to their authority, in order to maintain the household until they are released from parental control. This Eight of the parents follows from the natural limitation of the former Eight. Until the children attain maturity, they belong as members of the household to the family ; but thereafter they may belong to the domestics (famulatus) as servants of the household, and they can enter into this relation only by a contract whereby they are bound to the master of the house as his domestics. In like manner, a relation of master and servant may be formed outside of the family, in accordance with a personal right of a real kind on the part of the master ; and the domestics are acquired to the household by contract (famulatus domcsticus). Such a contract is not a mere letting and hiring of work (locatio conductio operce) ; but it further includes the giving of the person of the domestic into the possession of the master, as a letting and hiring of the person (locatio conductio personal). The latter relation is distinguished from the former in that the domestic enters the contract on the understanding that he will be available for everything that is allowable in respect of the well-being of the household, and is not merely engaged for a certain assigned and specified piece of work. On the other hand, an artisan or a day-

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 241

labourer who is hired for a specific piece of work- does not give himself into the possession of another,' nor is he therefore a member of his household. As the latter is not in the legal possession of his employer, who has bound him only to perform certain things, the employer, even though he should have him dwelling in his house (inquilmus), is not entitled to seize him as a thing (via facti), but must press for the performance of his engagement on the ground of personal right, by the legal means that are at his command (via juris).

So much, then, for the explanation and vindication of this new Title of Right in the Science of Natural Law, which may at first appear strange, but which has never theless been always tacitly in use.

IV.

Confusion of Real and Personal Right.

The proposition 'Purchase breaks Hire' 31, p. 131) has further been objected to as a heterodoxy in the doctrine of Natural Private Right. It certainly appears at first sight to be contrary to all the Rights of contract, that any one should intimate the termination of the lease' of a house to the present Lessee before the expiry of the period of occupation agreed upon ; and that the former can thus, as it appears, break his promise to the latter, if he only gives him the usual warning determined by the customary and legal practice. P>ut let it be supposed that it can be proved that the Lessee when he entered upon his contract of hire knew, or must have known, that the promise given to him by the Lessor or pro prietor was naturally (without needing to be expressly stated in the contract, and therefore tacitly) connected

KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

with the condition ' in so far as he should not sell his house within this time, or might have to renounce it on the occasion of an action on the part of his creditors.' On this supposition the Lessor does not break his promise, which is already conditioned in itself according to reason, and the Lessee does not suffer any infringement of his Eight by such an intimation being made to him before the period of lease has expired. For the Eight of the latter arising from the contract of hire, is a Personal Eight to what a certain person has to perform for another (jus ad rem) ; it is not a Eeal Right (jus in re) that holds against every possessor of the thing.

The Lessee might indeed secure himself in his lease and acquire a Eeal Eight in the house ; but he could do this only by having it engrossed by a reference to the house of the Lessor as attached to the soil. In this way he would provide against being dispossessed before the expiry of the time agreed upon, either by the intimation of the proprietor or by his natural death, or even by his civil death as a bankrupt. If he did not do this, because he would rather be free to conclude another lease on better conditions, or because the proprietor would not have such a burden (onus) upon his house, it is to be inferred that, in respect of the period of intimation, both parties were conscious of having made a tacit contract to dissolve their relation at any time, according to their convenience, subject, however, to the conditions determined by the municipal law. The confirmation of the Eight to break hire by purchase, may be further shown by certain juridical consequences that follow from such a naked contract of hire as is here under consideration. Thus the Heirs of the Lessee when he dies should not have the obligation imposed upon them to continue the hire,

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 243

because it is only an obligation as against a certain person and should cease with his death, although here again the legal period of intimation must be always kept in view. The right of the Lessee as sucli can thus only pass to his heirs by a special contract. Nor, for the same reason, is he entitled even during the life of both parties, to sublet to others what he has hired for himself, without express agreement to that effect.

V.

Addition to the Explanation of the Conceptions of Penal Right.

The mere idea of a political Constitution among men involves the conception of a punitive Justice as belonging to the supreme Power. The only question, then, is to consider whether the legislator may be indifferent to the modes of punishment, if they are only available as means for the removal of crime, regarded as a violation of the Security of property in the State ; or whether he must also have regard to respect for the Humanity in the person of the criminal, as related to the species ; and if this latter alternative holds, whether he is to be guided by pure principles of Right, taking the jus talionis as in form the only & priori idea and determining principle of Penal Right, rather than any generalization from experience as to the remedial measures most effective for his purpose. But if this is so, it will then be asked how he would proceed in the case of crimes which do not admit of the application of this Principle of Retaliation, as being either impossible in itself, or as in the circum stances involving the perpetration of a penal offence against Humanity generally. Such, in particular, are

944 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

the relations of rape, paederasty, and bestiality. The former two would have to be punished by castration (after the manner of the white or black eunuchs in a seraglio), and the last by expulsion for ever from civil society, because the individual has made himself un worthy of human relations. Per quod quis peccat per idem, punitur et idem. These crimes are called unnatural, because they are committed against all that is essential to Humanity. To punish them by arbitrary penalties, is literally opposed to the conception of a penal Justice. l>ut even then the criminal cannot complain that wrong is done to him, since his own evil deed draws the punish ment upon himself ; and he only experiences what is in accordance with the spirit, if not the letter, of the penal Law which he has broken in his relation to others.

Every punishment implies something that is rightly degrading to the feeling of honour of the party con demned. For it contains a mere one-sided compulsion. Thus his dignity as a citizen is suspended, at least in a particular instance, by his being subjected to an ex ternal obligation of duty, to which he may not oppose resistance on his side. Men of rank and wealth, when mulcted in a fine, feel the humiliation of being compelled to bend under the will of an inferior in position, more than the loss of the money. Punitive Justice (justitia punitiva), in which the ground of the penalty is moral (quia peceatum est), must be distinguished from punitive Expediency, the foundation of which is merely pragmatic (ne peccetur) as being grounded upon the experience of what operates most effectively to prevent crime. It has consequently an entirely distinct place (locus justi) in the topical arrangement of the juridical conceptions. It is neither the conception of what is conduciUe to a

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PKINCIl'LES. 245

certain effect (conducililis), nor even that of the pure Jloneslum, which must be properly .placed in Ethics.

VI.

On the Right of Usucapion.

Referring to § 33, p. 133, it is said that 'the Eight of Usucapion ought to be founded on natural right ; for if it were not assumed that an ideal acquisition, as it is here called, is established by bona fide possession, no acquisition would be ever peremptorily secured.'— But I assume a merely provisory acquisition in the state of nature; and, for this reason, insist upon the juridical necessity of the civil constitution. Further, it is said, ' I assert myself as lona fide possessor only against any one who cannot prove that he was lona fide possessor of the same thing before me, and who has not ceased by his own will to be such.' But the question here under consideration is not as to whether I can assert myself as owner of a thing although another should put in a claim as an earlier real owner of it, the cognizance of his existence as possessor and of his possessorship as owner having been absolutely impossible; which case occurs when such a one has given no publicly valid indication of his uninterrupted possession, whether owing to his own fault or not, as by Registration in public Records, or uncontested voting as owner of the property in civil Assemblies.

The question really under consideration is this : Who is the party that ought to prove his rightful Acquisition ? This obligation as an onus probandi cannot be imposed upon the actual Possessor, for he is in possession of the thing so far back as his authenticated history reaches.

246 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY or LAW.

The former alleged owner of it is, however, entirely sepa rated, according to juridical principles, from the series of successive possessors by an interval of time within which he gave no publicly valid indications of his ownership. This intromission or discontinuance of all public posses sory activity reduces him to an untitled claimant. But here, as in theology, the maxim holds that conservatio cst continua creatio. And although a claimant, hitherto unmanifested but now provided with discovered docu mentary evidence, should afterwards arise, the doubt again would come up with regard to him as to whether a still older claimant might not yet appear and found a claim upon even earlier possession. Mere length of time in possession effects nothing here in the way of finally acquiring a thing (acquirere per usucapionem). For it is absurd to suppose that what is wrong, by being long continued, would at last become right. The use of the thing, be it ever so long, thus presupposes a Eight in it ; whereas the latter cannot be founded upon the former. Hence Usucapion, viewed as acquisition of a thing merely by long use of it, is a contradictory conception. The prescription of claims, as a mode of securing possession (conservatio possessionis mece per prcescriptionem), is not less contradictory, although it is a different conception as regards the basis of appropriation. It is in fact a negative Principle ; and it takes the complete disuse of a Eight, even such as is necessary to manifest possessor- ship, as equivalent to a renunciation of the thing (dere- lictio). But such renunciation is a juridical act, and it implies the use of the Eight against another, in order to exclude him by any claim (per perscriptioncm) from acquiring the object ; which involves a contradiction. I acquire therefore without probation, and without any

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 247

juridical act ; I do not require to prove, but I acquire by the law (lege). What then do I acquire? The public release from all further claims ; that is, the legal security of my possession in virtue of the fact that I do not require to bring forward the proof of it, and may now found upon uninterrupted possession. And the fact that all Acquisition in the state of Nature is merely provisory, has no influence upon the question of Security in the Possession of what has been acquired, this con sideration necessarily taking precedence before the former.

VII.

On Inheritance and Succession.

As regards the ' Right of Inheritance,' the acuteness of the Reviewer has here failed him, and he has not reached the nerve of the proof of my position. I do not say 34, p. 136) that 'every man necessarily accepts every thing that is offered to him, when by such accept ance he can only gain and can lose nothing ; ' for there are no things of such a kind. But what I say is, that every one always in fact accepts the Right of the offer of the thing, at the moment in which it is offered, inevit ably and tacitly, but yet validly ; that is, when the circumstances are such that revocation of the offer is impossible, as at the moment of the Testator's death. For the Promiser cannot then recall the offer ; and the nominated Beneficiary, without the intervention of any juridical act, becomes at the moment the acceptor, not of the promised inheritance, but of the Right to accept it or decline it. At that moment he sees himself, on the opening of the Testament and before any acceptance of the inheritance, become possessed of more than he was

248 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

before; for he has acquired exclusively the Eight to accept, which constitutes an element of property. A Civil state is no doubt here presupposed, in order to make the thing in question the property of another person when its former owner is no more ; but this transmission of the possession from the hand of the dead (mort-main) does not alter the possibility of Acquisition according to the universal Principles of Natural Eight, although a Civil Constitution must be assumed in order to apply them to cases of actual experience. A thing which it is in my free choice to accept or to refuse unconditionally, is called a res jacens. If the owner of a tiling offers me gratuitously a thing of this kind, as, for instance, the furniture of a house out of which 1 am about to remove, or promises it shall be mine, so long as he does not recall his offer or promise, which is im possible if he dies when it is still valid, then I have exclusively a Eight to the acceptance of the thing offered (jus in re jacente) ; in other words, I alone can accept or refuse it, as I please. And this Eight, exclusively to have the choosing of the thing, I do not obtain by means of a special juridical act, as by a declaration that ' I will that this Eight shall belong to me;' but I obtain it without any special act on my part, and merely by the law (lege). I can therefore declare myself to this effect : ' I will that the thing shall not Mong to me ' (for the acceptance of it might bring me into trouble with others). But I cannot will to have exclusively the choice as to whether it shall or shall not belong to me ; for this Eight of accepting or of refusing it, I have immediately by virtue of the Offer itself, apart from any declaration of acceptance on my part. If I could refuse even to have the choice, I might choose not to choose ; which is a

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 1

contradiction. Now this right to choose passes at the moment of the death of the Testator to me ; but although instituted heir by his Will (institutio hcvrcdis), I do not yet, in fact, acquire any of the property of the Testator, but merely the juridical or rational possession of that property or part of it, and I can renounce it for the benefit of others. Hence this possession is not inter rupted for a moment, but the Succession, as in a con tinuous series, passes by acceptance from the dying Testator to the heir appointed by him ; and thus the proposition testamcnta sunt juris naturae is established beyond all dispute.

VIII.

The Right of the State in relation to Perpetual Foundations for the Benefit of the Subjects.

A FOUNDATION (Sanctio tcstainentaria leneficii pcrpetui) is a voluntary beneficent institution, confirmed by the State and applied for the benefit of certain of its members, so that it is established for all the period of their existence. It is called perpetual when the ordinance establishing it is connected with the Constitution of the State ; for the State must be regarded as instituted for all time. The beneficence of such a foundation applies tiither to the people generally, or to a class as a part of the people united by certain particular principles, or to a certain family and their descendants for ever. Hospitals present an example of the first kind of foundations ; Churches of the second ; the Orders in the State (spiritual and secular) of the third ; Primogeniture and Entail of the fourth.

Of these corporate institutions and their Rights of sue-

250 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

cession, it is said that they cannot be abolished ; because the Right has been made the property of the appointed heirs in virtue of a legacy, and to abrogate such a con stitution (corpus mysticum) would amount to taking from some one what was his.

A. Hospitals.

Such benevolent institutions as Hospitals and other Foundations for the poor, for invalids, and for the sick, when they have been founded by the property of the State, are certainly to be regarded as indissoluble. But if the spirit, rather than the mere letter, of the will of a private Testator is to form the ground of determination, it may be that circumstances will arise in the course of time such as would make the abolition of such founda tions advisable, at least in respect of their form. Thus it has been found that the poor and the sick may be better and more cheaply provided for by giving them the assistance of a certain sum of money proportionate to the wants of the time, and allowing them to board with relatives or friends, than by maintaining them in magnificent and costly institutions like Greenwich Hospital, or other similar institutions which are main tained at great expense and yet impose much restriction on personal liberty. Lunatic asylums, however, must be regarded as exceptions. In abolishing any such institutions in favour of other arrangements, the State cannot be said to be taking from the people the enjoy ment of a benefit to which they have a right as their own ; rather does it promote their interest by choosing wiser means for the maintenance of their rights and the advancement of their well-bein".

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 251

B. Churches.

A spiritual order, like that of the Koman Catholic Church, which does not propagate itself in direct descend ants, may, under the favour of the State, possess lands with subjects attached to them, and may constitute a spiritual corporation called the Church. To this corpora tion the laity may, for the salvation of their souls, bequeath or give lands which are to be the property of the Church. The Pioman Clergy have thus in fact acquired possessions which have been legally transmitted from one age to another, and which have been formally confirmed by I'apal Bulls. Now, can it be admitted that this relation of the clergy to the laity may be annulled by the supreme power of the secular State ; and would not this amount to taking violently from them what was their own, as has been attempted, for example, by the unbelievers of the French Kepublic ?

The question really to be determined here is whether the Church can belong to the State or the State to the Church, in the relation of property; for two supreme powers cannot be subordinated to one another without contradiction. It is clear that only the former consti tution (politico - hierarchical, according to which the property of the Church belongs to the State, can have proper existence ; for every Civil Constitution is of this viorld, because it is an earthly human power that can be incorporated with all its consequences and effects in experience. On the other hand, the believers whose Kingdom is in Heaven as the otJter world, in so far as a hierarchico-political constitution relating to this world is conceded to them, must submit themselves to the sufferings of the time, under the supreme power of the

>:>-2 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

men who act in the world. Hence the former Con stitution is only, in place.

lieligion, as manifested in the form of belief in the dogmas of the Church and the power of the Priests who form the aristocracy of such a constitution, even when it is monarchical and papal, ought not to be forced upon the people, nor taken from them by any political power. Neither should the citizen as is at present the case in Great Britain with the Irish Nation be excluded from the political services of the State, and the advantages thence arising, on account of a religion that may be different from that of the Court.

Now, it may be that certain devout and believing souls, in order to become participators of the grace which the Church promises to procure for believers even after their death, establish an institution for all time, in accordance with which, after their death, certain lands of theirs shall become the property of the Church. Further, the State may make itself to a certain extent, or entirely, the vassal of the Church, in order to obtain by the prayers, indulgences, and expiations administered by the clergy as the servants of the Church, participa tion in the boon promised in the other world. Lut such a Foundation, although presumably made for all time, is not really established as a perpetuity ; for the State may throw off any burden thus imposed upon it by the Church at will. For the Church itself is an institution established on faith, and if this faith be an illusion engendered by mere opinion, and if it disappear with the enlightenment of the people, the terrible power of the Clergy founded upon it also falls. The State will then, with full right, seize upon the presumed property of the Church, consisting of the land bestowed

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 2

upon it by legacies. However, the feudatories of the hitherto existing institution, iuay of their own right demand to be indemnified for their life interests.

In like manner, Foundations established for all time, in behoof of the poor as well as educational Institutions even supposing them to have a certain definite character impressed by the idea of their founder, cannot be held as founded for all time, so as to be a burden upon the land. The State must have the liberty to reconstitute them, in accordance with the wants of the time. No one may be surprised that it proves always more and more difficult to carry out such ideas, as for instance a provision that poor foundationers must make up for the inadequacy of the funds of their benevolent institution by singing as mendicants; for it is only natural that one who has founded a beneficent institution should feel a certain desire of glory in connection with it, and that he should be unwilling to have another altering his ideas, when he may have intended to immortalize himself by it. But this does not change the conditions of the thing itself, nor the right, and even the duty of the State, to modify any foundation when it becomes inconsistent with its own preservation and progress ; and hence no such institution can be regarded as unalterably founded for all time.

C. The Orders in the State.

The nobility of a country which is not under an. aristocratic but a monarchical Constitution, may well form an institution that is not only allowable for a certain time, but even necessary from circumstances, Hut it cannot be maintained that such a class may

254 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

established for all time, and that the Head of the State should not have the right entirely to abolish the privi leges of such a class ; nor, if this be done, can it be held that thereby what belonged to the Nobility as Subjects, by way of a hereditary possession, has been taken from . them. The Nobility, in fact, constitute a temporary corporation or guild, authorized by the State ; and it must adapt itself to the circumstances of the time, nor may it do violence to the universal right of man, how ever long that may have been suspended. For the rank of the nobleman in the State is not only dependent upon the Constitution itself, but is only an accident, with a merely contingent inherence in the Constitution. A nobleman can be regarded as having a place only in the Civil Constitution, but not as having his position grounded on the state of Nature. Hence, if the State alters its constitution, no one who thereby loses his title and rank would be justified in saying that what was his own had been taken from him ; because he could only call it his own under the condition of the continued duration of the previous form of the State. But the State has the right to alter its form, and even to change it into a pure Eepublic. The Orders in the State, and the privilege of wearing certain insignia distinctive of them, do not therefore establish any right of perpetual possession.

D. Primogeniture and Entail.

By the Foundation of Primogeniture and Entail is meant that arrangement by which a proprietor institutes a succession of inheritance, so that the next proprietor in the series shall always be the eldest born heir of the family, after the analogy of a hereditary monarchy in

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF PRINCIPLES. 255

the State. But such a Foundation must be regarded as always capable of being annulled with the consent of all the Agnates ; and it may not be held to be instituted as for all time, like a hereditary Kight attaching to the Soil. Nor, consequently, can it be said that the abroga tion of it is a violation of the Foundation and Will of the first ancestral Founder. On the contrary, the State lias here a Kight and even a duty, in connection with gradually emerging necessity for its own Reform, if it has been once extinguished, not to allow the resuscita tion of such a federative system of its subjects, as if they were viceroys or sub-kings, after the analogy of the ancient Satraps and Heads of Dynasties.

IX.

Concluding Remarks on Public Right and Absolute Submission to the Sovereign Authority.

\Vitli regard to the ideas presented under the Heading of PUBLIC RIGHT, the Reviewer says that ' the want of room does not permit him to express himself in detail.' But he makes the following remarks on one point : ' So far as we know, no other philosopher has recognised this most paradoxical of all paradoxes, that the mere idea of a Sovereign Tower should compel me to obey as my master any one who gives himself out to be my master, without asking who has given him the Right to com mand me? That a Sovereign Power and a Sovereign are to be recognised, and that the one or the other whose existence is not given in any way A priori is also to be regarded a priori as a master, are represented so as to be one and the same thing.' Now, while this view is admitted to be paradoxical, I hope when it is more

256 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

closely considered, it will not at least be convicted of heterodoxy. Rather, indeed, may it be hoped that this penetrating, thoughtful, and modestly censuring Critic may not grudge to make a second examination of this point, nor regret to have taken the whole discussion under his protection against the pretentious and shallow utterances of others. And this all the more, in view of his state ment that he ' regards these Metaphysical Principles of the Science of Right as a real gain for the Science.'

Now, it is asserted that obedience must be given to whoever is in possession of the supreme authoritative and legislative power over a people ; and this must be done so unconditionally by right, that it would even be penal to inquire publicly into the title of a power thus held, with the view of calling it in doubt, or opposing it in consequence of its being found defective. Accord ingly it is maintained, that ' Obey the authority which has power over you ' (in everything which is not opposed to morality), is a Categorical Imperative. This is the objectionable proposition which is called in question ; and it is not merely this principle which founds a right upon the fact of occupation as its condition, but it is even the very idea of a sovereignty over a people obliging me as belonging to it, to obey the presumptive right of its power, without previous inquiry 44), that appears to arouse the reason of the Reviewer.

Now every fact is an object which presents itself to the senses, whereas what can only be realized by pure Reason must be regarded as an idea for which no adequately corresponding object can be found in experi ence. Thus a perfect juridical Constitution among men is an ideal Thing in itself.

If then a people be united by laws under a sovereign

SUPPLEMENTARY EXPLANATIONS OF 1'KIXCIPLES. 257

power, it is conformable to the idea of its unity as such under a supreme authoritative will, when it is in fact so presented as an object of experience. But this holds only of its phenomenal manifestation. In other words, a juridical constitution so far exists in the general sense of the term ; and although it may be vitiated by great defects and coarse errors, and may be in need of important improvements, it is nevertheless absolutely unallowable and punishable to resist it. For if the people regarded themselves as entitled to oppose force to the Constitu tion, however defective it may be, and to resist the supreme authority, they would also suppose they had a right to substitute force for the supreme Legislation that establishes all rights. But this would result in a supreme will that would destroy itself.

The idea of a political Constitution in general, involves at the same time an absolute command of a practical Keason that judges according to conceptions of right, and is valid for every people; and as such it is holy and irresistible. And although the organization of a State were defective in itself, yet no subordinate power in the State is entitled to oppose active resist ance to its legislative Head. Any defects attaching to it ought to be gradually removed by reforms carried °out on itself ; for otherwise, according to the opposite maxim, that the subject may proceed according to his own private will, a good Constitution can only be realized by blind accident. The precept, ' Obey the authority that has power over you,' forbids investigating into how this power has been attained, at least with any view to undermining it. For the Power which already exists, and under which any one may be living, is already in possession of the power of Legislation; and one may,

258 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

indeed, rationalize about it, but not set himself up as an opposing lawgiver.

The will of the people is naturally un-unified, and consequently it is lawless ; and its unconditional sub jection under a sovereign Will, uniting all particular wills by one law, is a fact which can only originate in the institution of a supreme power, and thus is public Eight founded. Hence to allow a Eight of resistance to this sovereignty, and to limit its supreme power, is a contradiction ; for in that case it would not be the supreme legal power, if it might be resisted, nor could it primarily determine what shall be publicly right or not. This principle is involved a priori in the idea of a political Constitution generally as a conception of the practical Eeason. And although no example adequately corresponding to this principle can be found in experi ence, yet neither can any Constitution be in complete contradiction to it when it is taken as a standard or rule.

APOLOGIA.

KANT'S VINDICATION OF HIS PHILOSOPHICAL STYLE.

[IN THE PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION, 1796-97. J

KANT'S VINDICATION OF HIS PHILOSOPHICAL STYLE

THE reproach of obscurity, and even of a studied inde- tiniteness affecting the appearance of profound insight, has been frequently raised against my philosophical style of exposition. I do not know how I could better meet or remove this objection than by readily accepting the condition which Garve, a philosopher in the genuine sense of the term, has laid down as a duty incumbent upon every writer, and especially on philosophical authors. And for my part, I would only restrict his injunction by the condition, that it is to be followed only so far as the nature of the science which is to be improved or enlarged will allow.

Garve wisely and rightly demands, that every philo sophical doctrine must be capable of being presented in a popular form, if the expounder of it is to escape the sus picion of obscurity in his ideas ; that is, it must be capable of being conveyed in expressions that are universally in telligible. I readily admit this, with the exception only of the systematic Critique of the Faculty of Keason, and all that can only be determined and unfolded by it ; for all this relates to the distinction of the sensible in our knowledge from the supersensible, which is attainable Reason. This can never be made popular, nor can any

2C2 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

formal Metaphysic as such be popular; although their results may be made quite intelligible to the common reason, which is metaphysical without its being known to be so. In this sphere, popularity in expression is not to be thought of. We are here forced to use scholastic accuracy, even if it should have to bear the reproach of troublesomeness ; because it is only by such technical language that the precipitancy of reason can be arrested, and brought to understand itself in face of its dogmatic assertions.

But if pedants presume to address the public in technical phraseology from pulpits or in popular books, and in expressions that are only fitted for the Schools, the fault of this must not be laid as a burden upon the critical philosophers, any more than the folly of the mere wordmonger (logodcedalus) is to be imputed to the grammarian. The laugh should here only turn against the man and not against the science.

It may sound arrogant, egotistical, and, to those who have not yet renounced their old system, even derogatory, to assert ' that before the rise of the Critical Philosophy, there was not yet a philosophy at all.' Now, in order to be able to pronounce upon this seeming presumption, it is necessary to resolve the question as to whether there can really be more than one philosophy. There have, in fact, not only been various modes of philosophizing and of going back to the first principles of Reason in order to found a system upon them, with more or less success ; but there must be many attempts of this kind of which every one has its own merit at least for the present. However, as objectively considered there can only be one human Eeason, so there cannot be many Philosophies ; in other words, there is only one true System of Philo-

VINDICATION OF HIS PHILOSOPHICAL STYLE.

sophy founded upon principles, however variously and however contradictorily men may have philosophized over one and the same proposition. Thus the Moralist rightly says, there is only one virtue, and only one doctrine regarding it ; that is, one single system connects all the duties of virtue by one principle. The Chemist, in like manner, says there is only one chemistry, that which is expounded by Lavoisier. The Physician, in like manner, says there is only one principle, according to Brown, in the system of classifying Diseases. But because it is held that the new systems exclude all the others, it is not thereby meant to detract from the merit of the older Moralists, Chemists, and Physicians; for without their discoveries, and even their failures, we would not have attained to the unity of the true principle of a complete philosophy in a system. Accordingly, when any one announces a system of philosophy as a production of his own, this is equivalent to saying that ' before this Philo sophy there was properly no philosophy.' For should he admit that there had been another and a true philosophy, it would follow that there may be two true systems of philosophy regarding its proper objects ; which is a con tradiction. If, therefore, the Critical Philosophy gives itself forth as that System before which there had been properly no true philosophy at all, it does no more than has been done, will be done, and even must be done, by all who construct a Philosophy on a plan of their own.

Another objection has been made to my System which is of less general significance, and yet is not entirely without importance. It has been alleged that one of the essentially distinguishing elements of this Critical Philo sophy is not a growth of its own, but has been borrowed from some other philosophy, or even from an exposition

264 KANT'S PHILOSOPHY OF LAW.

of Mathematics. Such is the supposed discovery, which a Tubingen Reviewer thinks he has made, in regard to the Definition of Philosophy which the author of the Critique of tJie Pure Reason gives out as his own, and as a not insignificant product of his system, but which it is alleged had been given many years before by another writer, and almost in the same words.1 I leave it to any one to judge whether the words : ' intellectualis qucedam construct™' could have originated the thought of the pre sentation of a given conception in an intuitive perception h priori, by which Philosophy is at once entirely and definitely distinguished from Mathematics. I am certain that Hausen himself would have refused to recognise this as an explanation of his expression ; for the possibility of an intuitive perception h priori, and the recognition of Space as such an intuition and not the mere outward coexistence of the manifold objects of empirical per ception (as Wolf defines it), would have at once repelled him, on the ground that he would have felt himself thus entangled in wide philosophical investigations. The presentation, constructed, as it were, ly the Understanding, re ferred to by the acute Mathematician, meant nothing more than the (empirical) representation of a Line correspond ing to a conception, in making which representation attention is to be given merely to the Eule, and abstrac tion is to be made from the deviations from it that inevitably occur in actual execution, as may be easily perceived in the geometrical construction of Equalities. And least of all is there any importance to be laid

Porro de actual! constructione hie non quaeritur, cum ne possint quidem seusibiles figurae ad rigorem definitionum effingi ; sed requiritur cognitio eorum, quibus absolvitur formatio quse intellectualis quadam

tructio est. C. A. Hausen, Elem. Mathes. Pars I. p. 86 (1734)

VINDICATION OF HIS PHILOSOPHICAL STYLE.

upon the objection made regarding the spirit of this Philosophy, on the ground of the improper use of some of its terms by those who merely ape the system in words. The technical expressions employed in the Critique of the Pure Reason cannot well be replaced by others in current use, but it is another thing to employ them outside of the sphere of Philosophy in the public interchange of ideas. Such a usage of them deserves to be well castigated, as Nicolai has shown ; but he even shrinks from adopting the view that such technical terms are entirely dispensable in their own sphere, as if they were adopted merely to disguise a poverty of thought. However, the laugh may be much more easily turned upon the unpopular pedant than upon the uncritical ignoramus; for in truth the Metaphysician who sticks rigidly to his system without any concern about Criticism, may be reckoned as belonging to the latter class, although his ignorance is voluntary, because he will only not accept what does not belong to his own older school. But if, according to Shaftesbury's saying, it is no contemptible test of the truth of a predominantly practical doctrine, that it can endure Ridicule, then the Critical Philosophy must, in the course of time, also have its turn ; and it may yet laugh lest when it will be able to laugh last. This will be when the mere paper systems of those who for a long time have had the lead in words, crumble to pieces one after the other ; and it sees all their adherents scattering away, a fate which inevitably awaits them.

MORRISON AND GIBB, EDINBURGH, PRINTERS TO HER MAJESTY'S STATIONERY OFFICE.

T. and T. Clark's Publication*.

In crown 8vo, Fourth Edition, price 68.,

THE METAPHYS/C OF ETHICS.

BY IMMANUEL KANT.

TRANSLATED IJY J. \V. SEMPLE, ADVOCATE. EDITED BY REV. PROFESSOR HENRY CALDERWOOD, LL.D.

4 Mr. Sample's translation lias been accepted by scholar* as a real success.' —Contemporary Review.

LOTZE 8 MICROCOSMUS Just published, in Two Vols., 8vo (1450 pages), price 36».,

MICROCOSMUS:

CONCERNING MAN AND HIS RELATION TO THE WORLD. BY HERMANN LOTZE.

CoxTBNTs:-Book I. The Body. II. The Soul. III. Life. IV. Man. V. Mind. VI. The Microcosmic Order ; or. The Course of Human Lift-. VII. History. VIII. Progress. IX. The Unity of Things.

4 These are indeed two masterly volumes, vigorous in intellectual power and translated with rare ability. . . . This work will doubtless find a place on the shelves of all the foremost thinkers and students of modern times.'— Evangelical Magazine.

The English public have now before them the greatest philosophic work produced in Germany by the generation just past. The translation comes at an opportune time, for the circumstances of English thought just at the present moment are peculiarly those with which Lotze attempted to deal when he wrote his 44 Microcosraus " a quarter of a century ago. . . . Few philosophic books of the century are so attractive both in stylo and matter.'— Atlienccum.

4 The translation of Lotze's 44 Microcosmus " is the most important of recent events in our philosophical literature. . . . The discussion is carried on on the basis of an almost encyclopaedic knowledge, and with the profoundest and subtlest critical insight Wo know of no other work containing so much of speculative suggestion, of keen criticism, and of sober judgment on these topics.'— Andover Review.

T. and T. Clark's Publications.

Just published, in Two Vols., 8vo, price 21s.,

NATURE AND THE BIBLE:

LECTURES ON THE MOSAIC HISTORY OF CREATION IN ITS RELATION TO NATURAL SCIENCE.

BY DR. FR. H. REUSCH.

REVISED AND CORRECTED BY THE AUTHOR.

CranslatrtJ from tfjc JFourtfj lEDftion

BY KATHLEEN LYTTELTON.

'Other champions much more competent and learned than myself might have been placed in the field ; I will only name one of the most recent, Dr. Reusch, author of "Nature and .the Bible." '^-The Right Hon. W. E! GLADSTONE.

' We owe to Dr. Reusch, a Catholic theologian, one of the most valuable treatises on the relation of Religion and Natural Science that has appeared for many years. Its fine impartial tone, its absolute freedom from passion, its glow of sympathy with all sound science, and its liberality of religious views, are likely to surprise all readers who are unacquainted with the fact that, whatever may be the errors of the Romish Church, its more enlightened members are, as a rule, free from that idolatry of the letter of Scripture which is one of the most dangerous faults of ultra-Protestantism.' Literary World.

In One Volume, 8vo, Second Edition, price 12s.,

FINAL CAUSES.

BY PAUL JANET, Member of the Institute, Paris. TRANSLATED FROM THE FRENCH BY WILLIAM AFFLECK, B.D.

4 This very learned, accurate, and, within its prescribed limits, exhaustive work. ... The book as a whole abounds in matter of the highest interest and is a model of learning and judicious treatment.' Guardian.

'Illustrated and defended with an ability and learning which must command the reader's admiration.' Dublin Review.

'A great contribution to the literature of this subject. M. Janet has mastered the conditions of the problem, is at home in the literature of science and philosophy; ... in clearness, vigour, and depth it has been seldom equalled, and more seldom excelled, in philosophical literature.'— Spectator.

4 A wealth of scientific knowledge and a logical acumen which will win the admiration of every reader.'— Church Quarterly Review.

BY THE SAME AUTHOR. Just published, in demy 8vo, price 10s. 6d.,

THE THEORY OF MORALS.

TRANSLATED FROM THE LATEST FRENCH EDITION.

' As remarkable for the force and beauty of its form of expression as for its vast and varied learning, its philosophical acumen, and its uniform attitude of reverence toward religious and moral problems of the most transcendent interest to mankind.'— Library World.

'This book is really a valuable addition to the literature of the subject . Let the student of morals and religion read it for himself. It is pleasant reading, and the translation seems to us in every respect admirable'—

Q-

i_i c/.

CV

JAN 1 9 1983

I I

APR181984

UAN6

C?5

z <

= |NI

1 7

*>& TO «K * V %w 7Vt v » * 4 ' ^V^N^V>V|%V'^^NxVl?

XHy ^v>%%V/AAtvhV