I

tfact an& UbcotT papers.

NUMBER VI. THE

TIME-RELATIONS OF MENTAL PHENOMENA

BY PROF. JOSEPH JASTROW

fact an£> 3beore papers.

THE TIME-RELATIONS OF MENTAL PHENOMENA

BY

JOSEPH JASTROW,

Professor of Psychology at the University of Wisconsin.

NEW YORK :

N. D. C. HODGES, PUBLISHER

47 LAFAYETTE PLACE

1890

THE TIME-KELATIONS OF MENTAL PHENOMENA.

THE study of the time relations of mental phenomena is important from several points of view: it serves as an index of mental complexity, giving the sanction of objective demonstration to the results of subjective observation ; it indicates a mode of analysis of the simpler mental acts, as well as the relation of these laboratory products to the pro- cesses of daily life; it demonstrates the close inter-relation of psychological with physiological facts, an analysis of the former being indispensable to the right comprehension of the latter; it suggests means of lightening and shortening men- tal operations, and thus offers a mode of improving educa- tional methods; and it promises in various directions to deepen and widen our knowledge of those processes by the complication and elaboration of which our mental life is so wonderfully built up. It is only within very recent years that this department of research has been cultivated ; and it is natural that the results of different workers, involving variations in method and design, should show points of

2 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

difference. In spite of these it seems possible to present a systematic sketch of what has been don?, with due reference to the ultimate goal as well as to the many gaps still to be filled. It is with the object of furnishing such a general view that the following exposition has been attempted. Rate of Nervous Impulses.

While it follows, as a very natural consequence of the modern view of the relation between body and mind, that mental processes, however simple, should occupy time, it must be remembered that the very opposite opinion has been held by serious thinkers. It has been argued as a proof of the immateriality of thought that its operations were out of relation to time, and the expression "quick as thought" has come to indicate a maximum -of speed. It being estab- lished thr-t so comparatively simple a process as sensation involves the passage of an impulse along nerve-fibres, it is plain that the rate of travelling of this impulse sets a limit to the time of the entire process, as well as of all more com- plicated mental operations in which sensations are involved. The physiologist Johannes Muller, writing in 1844, despaired of our ever being able to measure the time of so excessively rapid and short a movement; but before the close of the same decade, Helmholtz measured the rate in the nerve of the frog, finding it to be about 86 feet per second. Though somewhat greater in man. 110 feet per second, this movement is ex- tremely slow compared with the velocity of light or even sound: indeed, it is only slightly faster than the fastest ex- press train.

Mi'iller writes: '" We shall probably never secure the means of ascertaining the speed of nerve activity, because we lack the comparison of enormous distances from which the speed of a movement, in this respect analogous to light, could be calculated;" and again: "The time in which a sensation proceeds from the periphery to the brain and the spinal cord, and is followed by a re-action at the periphery by means of muscular contractions, is infinitely small and immeasura-

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 3

ble." It is interesting to note how very crude were the con- ceptions of the older physiologists upon this point. Haller (1762) tells us of one who, following the view that the ner- vous impulse was a fluid, and its action analagous to that of the blood, fourd the " nerve tubes" of the heart to be 2,880 million times as narrow as the aorta, and concluded that the nervous impulse travelled proportionately faster than the blood, thus making its rate 57,600 million feet per second. Haller himself measured the maximum rapidity of short rhythmical movements, and (falsely), assuming that the im- pulse travelled to and from muscle and brain between each contraction, found an (accidentally not very erroneous) speed of 9,000 feet per second. The method introduced by Helmholtz, and improved by himself and others, consists in excising a muscle with a long stretch of nerve attached, and connecting the muscle with a lever, so that every con- traction of it is registered upon the quickly moving surface of a revolving drum or a swinging pendulum. By electrically stimulating the nerve first at a point near to and then at a point far off from the muscle, two curves are recorded, the latter of which is found to leave the base line a trifle after the former. A tuning-fork writes its vibrations beneath these records, and enables us to measure how much later the second contraction began, while the distance travelled in this time is that between the two points of stimula- tion on the nerve. It has been attempted to measure this rate in man by having the subject re-act once to a stimulus applied to the foot, and again to a stimulus at the hip, or some point nearer the spinal cord, and counting the differ- ence in time as due to the difference in length of nerve traversed. While the method is necessarily inaccurate, and other factors contribute to the difference in time, the majority of the determinations indicate a rate of between 30 and 40 metres (100 to 130 feet) per second. These determinations apply to sensory nerves: for the motor nerves of man, Helm- holtz has found, by a method closely similar to that employed upon the frog, a rate of 110 teet per second. The most in- fluential of the conditions affecting this rate is temperature: cold decreases and heat increases it. the extremes of varia- tion being 30 to 90 metres. Under normal conditions it seems fait- to regard the rate for both motor and sensory nerves of man as about 110 feet per second.

THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

Analysis of Re-actions.

A great variety of actions may be viewed as responses to stimuli. There is a flash of light, and we wink; a burning cinder falls upon the hand, and we draw it away; a bell rings, and the engineer starts his train, or the servant opens the door, or we go down to dinner; the clock strikes, and we stop work, or go to meet an appointment. Again, in such an occupation as copying, every letter or word seen acts as a stimulus, to which the written letter or word is the response; in piano playing, and the guidance of complicated machinery, we see more elaborate instances of similar pro- cesses. The printer distributing "pi." the post-office clerk sorting the mails, are illustrations of quick forms of re-action, in which the different letters of the alphabet or the different addresses of the mail matter act as the stimuli, and the plac- ing them in their appropriate places follows as the response. In many games, such as tennis or cricket, the various ways in which the ball is seen to come to the striker ai'e the stimuli, for each variation of which there is a precise and complex form of response in the mode of returning the ball. In military drill the various words of command are the stimuli, and the actions thus induced the responses; and such illustrations could be multiplied indefinitely. In all these actions the time-relations are more or less definite and im- portant, but a useful study of them presupposes a careful and systematic analysis of the processes therein involved. We recognize that certain of the above actions are more complicated than others, and we must inquire in what this complication consists. In the process as usually presented the nature of the re-action depends upon the nature of the stimulus, a variation in the one being concomitant with a variation in the other. The piano player, seeing a certain mark on the page, strikes a certain key on the key-board, but strikes a different key if this mark be differently placed ; the soldier varies his movement according to the word of

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 5

command, aud so on with most of the others. All such actions in volve at least three processes: (1) the recognition of the sense impression, (2) the performance of the appro- priate action, and (3) the association of the one with the other. The recognition involves the appreciation of the presence together with the appreciation of the nature of the sense-impression; and the movement involves the contrac- tion of muscles together with the initiation of the impulse. We obtain the simplest form of re-action by limiting the stimulus to a single definite one, and having one and the same response irrespective of the nature of the stimulus. The subject expects the stimulus the nature of which he knows, and is ready to signal, by a simple movement agreed upon in advance, merely that the impression has bsen re- ceived. This we shall speak of as a "simple re-action." It occurs whenever a certain sense-impression is agreed upon as a signal for the execution of a simple movement. Tlie lime-keeper pressing the spring of the stop-watch, or the racer starting off as soon as the pistol is fired or the word is given, are instances of simple re-actions. It should be noted that the simplicity of the act refers primarily to the subject's fore-knowledge of what is to occur; the nature of the sense-impression, as of the motion, is known in advance, the association between the two being in the main artificial. Inasmuch as the more elaborate mental processes involve those of the simple re-action, our first step must be to deter- mine its elements and their time-relations.

The Elements of a Simple Re action.

The several elements of a simple re-action have been variously analyzed by different observers, but all recognize the physiological and the specially psychological portions of the process. The physiological time-elements include, (a) the time for the sense-organ to respond to an impression, i.e., to overcome its inertia; (b) the time for the passage of the impulse inward along nerves (and spinal cord), with the

6 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

various delays whenever the impulse eaters or passes through ceils; (c) the return passage of the motor impulse from the brain to (spinal chord and) nerve and muscle; and (d) the time for the contraction of the muscle. The time thus left unaccounted for is that taken up by the psychological pro- cess, the transformation of the sensory into the motor im- pulse,— a process taking place in the brain, but as to the precise nature of which we have no definite information. The separate determination of each of the physiological fac- tors enables us to find approximately the duration of the central process As a sufficiently typical case we may accept the estimate of Cattell, that, in re-acting to a light by press- ing the key with the finger, the time needed by the impulse to travel from eye to brain and from brain to spinal cord and finger is about 507 ;* the latent time in the muscle, dur- ing which it overcomes its inertia, is judged from experi- ments upon the frog to be about 5(7 to 10(7; and experiment gives a value of 15(7 to 20(7 for stimulating the retina and initiating the impulse. As the entire re-action occupied about 150(7 we conclude that in this case the physiological and the psychological portions of the process occupy about equal times. One may obtain a fair notion of the rate of these processes by the following simple experiment. A score or so of persons form a chain by joining hands, and at a given signal a certain member of the group sharply presses the hand of Ids neighbor, who in turn imparts the pressure as quickly as possible to his neighbor, and so on until the impression has gone the rounds. An outsider keeps the time (which may be done with sufficient accuracy by count- ing the ticks of a watch, usually fifths of a second) from the moment of giving the signal to start to the moment of re- ceiving the signal from the last member of the group that the impression has been circulated. The entire time divided by the number of persons in the group (or better, by that

1 The sign <r indicates one one-thousandth of a second.

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 7

number plus two to include the re-actions at starting and stopping) gives an average simple re-action time, which, though long at first, is reduced after a lii/cle practice to a sixth or a seventh of a second. On this basis one may cal- culate that if a number of men, stretching out their arms and grasping one another's hands, were stationed in a straight line, it would take three minutes to send a message in the manner just described along a mile of this human telegraph.

(a) The inertia of sense-organs has been variously deter- mined. One method measures how closely impressions may follow one another without fusing. The time thus measured is the minimum time during which the sense-organ may he stimulated and recover sufficiently to receive a second stim- ulation. This process thus includes something more than the one we desire to measure, and may perhaps be regarded as furnishing a maximum time of the sensory inertia. Here again various circumstances influence the determinations, the chief ones being the sense-organ in question and the clearness and intensity of the impression. Sectors of black and white upon a disc revolving in daylight at the rate of about 25 times a second fuse into a uniform gray, making the inertia of the retina under these conditions about 40(7. In weak light (moonlight) the time lengthens to about lOOff. The same experiment has been made with sectors of different colors, with the disc stationary and the light reflected from a rotating mirror, with a vibrating point of light; and, while all these variations somewhat affect the result, the majority of the determinations indicate a fusion at 30 to 40 impressions a second, or a duration of S3ff to 25O". For sound, different observers have chosen different points for measurement. The slowest rate of impressions fusing into a musical sound has been fixed at between 30 and 40 per second ; but Helmholtz has shown that the interi'erence of sound-waves perceptible as beats does not escape detection when recurring as rapidly as 132 per second. For non-musical sounds, such as electric clicks, a still higher rate has been found. In touch we dis- tinguish differences of feeling when impressions are rapid enough to fuse but not rapid enough to fuse perfectly. The smoothness of a polished surface is not obtained until the impressions occur 480 to 640 times a second (Valentin). For taste and smell the period, though not accurately determined,

THE TIME-RELATIONS OP

is undoubtedly very long. Here the time needed to reach the somewhat concealed sense-organs is considerable, and the chemical processes involved are relatively slow in action. The influence of the mode of activity of the sense-organ upon its period of stimulation is further illustrated in the long inertia period of the probably chemical action of vision com- pared with the short period of the mechanical senses of hear- ing and touch. This view is also supported by the fact that the period for the retina is shortened if the eye be directly stimulated electrically. Another mode of experimenting consists in applying a stimulus for the minimum time during which it can be recognized. The time thus measured will be shorter than the other, for it tells us only how long is needed for initiating the process of recognition sufficiently to have it continue to completion (probably after the stimulus ceases). This is indeed a surprisingly short time. Cattell and San- ford independently found that a color or a letter could be recognized when visible for only from Iff to 5ff, while less recently Baxt recognized 6 to 7 letters when exposed for only 5<7. Others have calculated that the maximum effect of an impression is not reached until from 50 ff to 150(7, but these determinations seem to involve some mental process of recog- nition. Whether or not some such process of recognition is involved is not quite clear. Unless specially prevented, the recognition will take place on the basis of the after-image, a few thousandths of a second being sufficient to initiate the process. By following the impression by a strong flash of light, and thus nullifying the afterimage, Baxt found a longer time needed to recognize a more complicated impres- sion. Within 10(7 to 15(7, one letter : within 24(7, three letters ; within 34(7, four letters, could be recognized. This only partially excludes the effect of the after-image, so that per- haps the results with complicated impressions are minimum "recognition times," and those with simple impressions '' inertia times.'' Another method, that of Exner, is similar to the method of fusion. It consists in finding how closely two impressions, stimulating slightly different portions of the sense-organ, may follow one another and yet be recog- nized as successive. Optical impressions were so recognized when falling at an interval of 44(7 on two points of the retina near the centre .011 millimetres apart, a longer time being necessary if the points are away from the centre of the ret- ina, It seems probable that this process is more complicated

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 9

than the one we are attempting to study. While the data thus at our disposal do not allow us to fix accurately the time of sensory inertia, the estimate provisionally accepted in the text cannot be far from the truth, being rather over than under estimated. The methods of measuring the rate of nervous impulses (6) and (c) have already been described. The inertia of the muscle and the time of its contraction are determined upon the same apparatus by observing how much ;:fter the shock is given the curve leaves the base-line.

Reflex, Automatic, and Voluntary Re-actions. The term " re-action " as here used is not intended to in- clude all responses to stimuli. The above instanced forms of re actions present various grades of naturalness, utility, and habituation; that is, the association between motion and stimulus has by practice become more or less close and easy. Copying, for example, may become so entirely automatic that it runs on of itself without the need of renewed voli- tional effort. The actions recognized as reflex take place in spile of all volition. The re-actions here considered are limited to those requiring some degree of voluntary effort for their execution, though this may be almost indefinitely re- duced by practice. The reflex act takes very much less time for its execution than the voluntary: the time for winking has been determined by Exner to be something over 50(7. In other words, it takes about three times as long to signal by a voluntary closure of the eye-lid that an impression has been received as to perform the same act reflexly when the eye is threatened. The utility of this quick action for the protection of the eye is evident; and other useful re-ac- tions, such as those of flight and escape in timid animals, seem to be of a similar nature. The quick movements of defence when attacked, of regaining one's balance when slip- ping, are so immediately useful and so well inculcated in the organism as often to surprise us by their quickness. Most of these actions can also be performed voluntarily, but neither so well nor so quickly; it is therefore difficult to

10 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

subject them to experiment. As already indicated, in the oi'dinary re-action there is little naturalness in the connec- tion of stimulus and movement, the same type of movement being1 used for all. The experienced re-actor becomes accus- tomed to signal by the finger movement that the operation required of him has been accomplished, but hardly associ- ates this movement with any particular stimulus.

It is perhaps well to add that the great saving of time in actions that have become automatic (such as is seen in the experienced piano player or post-office clerk as compared with the beginner), is in great part due to the increased facility of doing several things at once and not serially, a factor that enters only in a small degree into the simple re- action. The processes we should be most interested in measuring are those most closely approaching the operations of daily thought, so that the inference from experiment to practice shall be as direct as possible. This, however, it is difficult to do, because every-day mental processes do not present the simplicity of conditions required by experiment. Accordingly the method has been to study the simplest re- actions, and then take into account the circumstances in which our usual mental operations differ from them.

Conditions Affecting Simple Re-action Times.

Referring to the accompanying tab'e for a general view of the time-relations of simple re-actions, we may pass at once to the topic of greatest interest, viz., the influences by which they are quickened or retarded. These maybe considered as (A) objective, or affecting the conditions of the experiment, and (B) subjective, affecting the attitude of the re-actor.

(A, 1) The Nature of the Impression. The distinctive characteristics of a simple re-action being in the attitude of the re-actor, it would seem that its time could be little af- fected by the nature of the impression. The motor signal- ling process is the same, the connection between the im.

BIENTAL PHENOMENA.

11

X^

HH HH

%K*

X X

(•

< k- K H

j

^*

H "*H

4 HH

g^

&*Baa ^

M

M

*— t >

1— 1 t-H >-<

?

-3

00

.g .

CO

o

c

8

CO _i

-g J

g

(S

H

Is-

v.

'sL

n

B.

—~A—

>

CD <

Pi

& &

;? ^

0

!-*»

B

o>

iperaturt

14

C^ ^

P

' *0

fature of

n

CD

ff |

0 M

o"

CO

o

CD_

"^ ^4 ^ 1— < >-H •— I "^ *< ^H ta^ I-H

^ ?

CD E

» -B" "o.

CO O> B CD

FT

S

•d

f?

P

d

i s

B Pi

.....

1

B.

1= Pi

. .

^

5

TO

Be

B 0

3

&

r*

r-* O

S! o

SB

•>

' "TO

a> ji

B """**

'1

•~-

O

&

m

B

0 tt

^ ftl

O W

S 1

a s

!

o

B to

terberg. ii

11

v_v_,

0 TO P P

m TO

0 0

i-h

' "B P

bserver.

i

0 o>"

<

<

<!

c

1

^

^

Ul

VI

'i O-- O OiS CO

to

O>

£

C^ -1 -1 CC 4-

^n . -1-JOO i-*

Ci CC O *>• 4- O

^; CT

S^g

1

1

8 minutes after taking 60 ccra. of rum.

gQ n .1 41 11 14

Normal.

Intensity of sound unknown. \ Attention directed to sensation. " " movement.

Intensity of sound known.

Preparatory signal irregularly varied with- lu 15 seconds.

Preparatory signal at regular intervals.

Ou the hand. Ou the foot. With preparato-y signal. Without " "

The intensity in terms of a common unit were as 7, 23, 123, 315, 1000, the two high- est intensities not being determluable.

Average of all parts of body.

Remarks.

GO

12 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

pression and movement is about equally artificial in all cases, so that the chief variability must be in the time needed for receiving the impression. For the different senses this time is different. Taking the general average of all the observations accessible to me, I find, for hearing, 1380"; for touch, 148(7; for sight, 185(7. This order is quite con- stant with the different observers, the long time of visual re-actions being referable to the long inertia period of that sense, as well as to the small perceptive area of the retina, necessitating a precise accommodation, a condition not always supplied in the above experiments. This view is strengthened by the shortening in the re-action time (by 36(7 for Exner, by 24(7 for v. Wittich) when the eye is stimu- lated electrically. In re-acting to a temperature sensation, care must be taken not to re-act to the sensation of contact with the skin. Where this has been done it has been found that the re-action to the sensations of temperature is longer than to contact, and I hat the re-action to heat is longer than to cold. Thus, Vintschgau and Steinach re-act to a pressure on various points of the head in 109(7, to a sensation of cold in 135(7, of heat in 146(7, similar values for various points of the hand being 121(7, 188(7, 209(7. The researches of Gold- scheider agree with these in the main, but make the differ- ence between the re action times to heat and to cold much greater. The senses of taste and smell clearly illustrate the effect of the kind of stimulation, for here the relative inac- cessibility of the sense organs and the slowly acting cLemi cal processes involved lead to a long re-action time. Though experimentation is difficult and uncertain in these senses, we may cite for smell the results of Moldenhauer on the odors of various oils, centring about 300(7 (oil of roses 273(7, cam- phor 321(7, musk 319(7, ether 255(7, etc.), and for taste, of Honigschmied, who re-acts to various tastes on the tip of the tongue in 182(7, though other subjects require about 300(7. On the back of the tongue the time is much longer, and it

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 13

varies for different tastes, being longest for bitter, shortest for salt, and about equal for sweet and sour. Within the same sense the re-action time will var}' according to the na- ture and place of the stimulus. The above cited differences for tastes and smells show this; and for different visual im- pressions, for different tones, for contact at different parts of the body, different results have been obtained, referable to slight variations in sensibility, length of nerve traversed, clearness of the impression, and the like. These minor dif- ferences are not easily established, but the following may be cited. Exner re-acts to an electric shock on the hand in 132(7, on the forehead in 137(7, on the foot in 175(7; v. Wit- tich re-acts to a point 011 the back of the finger in a longer time than to one on the front, 144(7 and 156(7, and regards the difference as due to a difference of sensibility. Hall and Kries clearly show that the re-action to a point looked at in indirect vision is longer than to one in direct vision, 195(7 and 235(7, and find further differences according as the point is above or below, inside or outside, the retinal centre. A high tone is re-acted to more quickly than a low one, and so on.

It is easier to demonstrate the influence of (2) the inten- sity of the stimulus. Within limits, intense stimuli affect sense-organs more quickly than weak ones, and, roughly speaking, an increase in the intensity of the stimulus is con- comitant with a decrease in the re-action time. According to Wuudt, the noise of a hammer falling respectively from heights of 1, 4, 8, and 16 millimetres was re-acted to in 217(7, 146(7, 132(7, and 135(7, and the sound of a ball falling from heights of 2, 5, 25, and 55 centimetres in 176(7, 161(7, 159(7, and 94(7 respectively. Exner varied the length and there- fore the brilliancy of an electric spark from 0.5 to 7 milli- metres and obtained a steadily decreasing re-action time of 158(7 to 123(7. More complete are the observations of Ber- ger and Cattell, who found that as the light increased from

14 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

7 to 23, to 123, to 315, to 1.000, and to two greater but not deterrniuable degrees of intensity (as compared with a small unit of light), the re-action *,imes fell (average of two ob- servers) from 210(5- to 184(7, to 174(7, to 1707, to 169(7, to 156(7, to 148(7. For sound, as the ball fell from heights of 60, 160, 300, and 560 millimetres the re-action times were 151 (7, 146(7, 1270", and 123 ff. For electrical touch excitations, re-actions to four grades of stimuli separated by equally perceptible differences were made (average of two observers) in 173(7, 159(7, 145(7, and 145(7. Wundt regards the differ- ence in re-action times of the different senses as in part

referable to differences in intensity, and, when re-acting to just perceptible intensities of sensation in various senses, finds about the same long time for each, 330(7.

3. The Mode of Re-action. The various movements by which we may signal that a sensation has been received may differ in the ease of their execution, in the length of nerve traversed, as well as in the naturalness of association with the impression. Such differences, however, seem to be small ; when once the movement is understood and antici- pated, the difference in the times of its execution is slight. Thus, Miinsterberg found, in testing the re-action of each of the five fingers, that while at first the thumb and little finger re-acted more slowly than the others, after some practice the times of all were substantially the same. Fere, however, has some results suggesting that the fingers making the strongest movements re-act in the shortest times. Very in- teresting, too, is the experiment of Ewald in which the stimulus, an electric shock, is given to the finger in the very key by which the re-action is signalled, the re-action consist- ing in the very natural movement of drawing the finger away. Under these circumstances he found a brief and constant time of 90(7. Both Vintschgau and Cattell have compared the time of re-acting by closing a key with the finger and by speaking a word, and find the vocal method

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 15

the longer by about 16 0" and 30(7 respectively. Differences in re-acting from the two sides of the body have been ob- served by some, the right side showing the shorter re-action, but this difference can hardly be considered as constant. Orchansky has shown in one case that the movements of inhibition take about the same time as those of excitation of a muscle, and it would be possible to study the relative ease of various movements by this method. A practical exam pie is furnished by the commands of military drill, the words, "carry," "present," etc., announcing the mode of re-action for the performance of which the following word, "arms," is the signal.

(B) We pass next to the more important subjective fac- tors, referring in the main to the expectation and the atten- tion. While nothing has been definitely said upon tins point, the implication has been that the subject tries his ut- most to re-act as quickly as possible, and that he knows the nature of the experiment. While the influences now to be discussed seem to be general in their effect, making the nervous system at one time a better and again a worse re- acting apparatus, they may, in certain respects, be subjected to a more definite analysis. We begin with (1) the subject's fore-knowledge of what is to take place. We may antici- pate the outcome of experimentation on this point by for- mulating the law that the more definite the fore-knowledge of the subject the quicker the re-action. Apparently there is a process that must be gone through with in each re action, and the better prepared the subject is for this, that is, the more of this process gone through with before the giving of the stimulus, the less of it falls within the measured inter- val. The precise nature of this process is a difficult and much discussed problem. It may be sufficient to note at present that the re action to a certain stimulus cannot but imply in some sense the distinction of that stimulus from the many others by which we are constantly surrounded. If

16 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

the subject be re-acting to a visual impression, he will prob ably not press the key should a noise occur in the room or something accidentally come in contact with his hand. To re-act to a visual impression thus implies the distinction of that from other impressions. It implies the identification of the expected with the existing impression. Just as we recognize an appearance in the heavens or under the micro- scope more readily when we know where and what to look for, or as we immediately recognize an almost forgotten ac- quaintance when expecting him, though at a chance mealing W3 might have passed him without recognition, so we re-act to an impression most quickly when it is most definitely ex- pected, with regard to its nature, its time, place of ap- pearance, and the like. This expectation may be more or less specific, and an interesting series of experiments consists in varying the fore-knowledge of the subject while still leav- ing it definite enough to call the result a simple re-action, (a) We may leave the precise time of the appearance of the stimulus undetermined. This may be done by experiment- ing with and without a preparatory .signal, preceding the stimulus by a regular interval. Wundt re-acted to the sound of a ball falling from a height of 25 centimetres in 76(7 with a preparatory signal, but in 253(7 if no such signal preceded ; to a ball falling five centimetres, in 175(7 in the first case, and 266(7 in the second. Marti us re-acts to the sound of a falling hammer in 127(7 when preceded at a regular interval by a signal, but in 178(7 without the signal. Dwelshauvers re-acts in 193(7 in the former case, in 236(7 in the latter (average of "sensory" and "motor" re-actions). The time between the signal and stimulus is here regular, and the most favora- ble time seems to be about two seconds. Lange found the time with an interval of two seconds less than with one of one or three seconds. Dwelshauvers varied the interval from a second and a half to three, and then to six seconds, and finds the shortest re-actions at a second and a half. Martius has

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 17

experimented with intervals from about one second to one- sixth of a second, and finds the one-second interval the most favorable. If the interval be irregularly varied within two seconds the effect is hardly noticeable, but if irregularly varied within fifteen seconds the time is increased (Cattell). With a normal re-action to sight of 1490" and to sound of 124(7, the re-action to sight with the interval varying within two seconds was 148(7; when varying within fifteen seconds, to sight 174(7, to sound 165(7 (average of two observers). Similarly Martius finds that re-actions with an irregular interval between signal and stimulus result in a time inter- mediate between that with a regular interval and that with- out a signal at all. (6) If the time and nature of the stimulus be known, but its intensity be varied, the time is increased. When re-acting to a uniform change between a feeble and a loud sound, the re-action time to the former was 127(7, to the latter, 116(7; but when these changes were made in an irregu- lar and unexpected manner, the times were lengthened to 208(7 and 19S<7.

In a similar manner the attention, which we have sup- posed hitherto to be focused upon the matter in hand with a maximum of effort, may be prevented from being ef- fectually directed to the making of the re-action by a variety of circumstances. Some of these we may group under the term (2) distraction. By a constant noise or other means we may be creating a stimulus to which the attention is in- voluntarily drawn, and thus withdrawn from the process of re-action. Wundt re-acted to a sound of mean intensity in 189(7, to a strong sound in 158(7, but when a disturbing sound was going on in the room these re-actions required 313(7 and 203(7. On the other hand, with Cattell, when in good practice, so that the re-action became almost automatic, the effect of a disturbing sound both upon sight and sound re-actions was insignificant, normal for sight 149(7, with disturbing noise 155(7; normal for sound 124(7, with dis-

18 THE TIME-RELATIONS OP

turbing noise 124(7. Dwelshauvers finds a longer re-action time when a minimum of attention is paid to the re-action. It is quite probable that what acts as a disturbance to one person hardly affects another. In some individuals the re- action time seems to be extremely sensitive to any mental disturbance. One of Obersteiner's subjects, with an average re-action time of about 100(7, requires 142(7 to re-act when music is heard, and another's re action time is lengthened by 100(7 when talking is going on in the room.

A more general and thorough form of distraction may be effected by imposing a task requiring distinct mental effort at the same time that the re-action is to take place. Thus Cattell attempted to add 17 consecutively to a series of num- bers, and found that re actions taken while this was going on were longer by 28(7 (average of two observers). All such effects seem to be much more marked when the re-action in question is new than when it has become familiar and partly automatic. The disturbance seems to act by delaying the association between stimulus and movement.

(3) We have now to notice a distinction which, though but recently brought to light (by N. Lange, 1888), is of fun- damental importance. A re-action may be made in two ways. In the one form of re-action the attention is directed to the expected impression: it is identified as the expected impression, and thereupon is initiated the impulse resulting in the re- acting movement. The several processes are per- formed serially, the attention being concentrated upon the sensory part of the process. In the other form of re-action the attention is directed to the movement: the impulse is ready, and is set off by the appearance of the signal almost automatically, the identification of the actual with the ex- pected impression being omitted. The first is spoken of as the "complete" or "sensory" mode of re-action ; the second, as the " shoi'tened "or " motor " form. In the experiments of Lange the simple sensory re-action time to a sound (aver-

MENTAL PHENOMENA. Ill

age of three persons) was 227(7, motor 123(7; to a visual im- pression (average of two persons), sensory 290(7, motor 113d; to a tactile impression (one person), sensory 213(7, motor 108(7.

These differences, however, seem to be rather extreme. Miinsterberg finds for sound, sensory 162(7, motor 120(7. Martius finds (average of various experiments) for a "sen- sory " re action to a sound 161(7, for a " motor" 141(7, but in two subjects not practised in re-acting 210<T and 111(7. Dwelshauvers finds a difference as great as between 279(7 and 137(7 for three subjects. It should be noted that this differ- ence in the attitude of the subject is not always easy to maintain, and that it is at times equally difficult to decide whether a re-action has been "sensory" or " motor." Un- doubtedly transitional modes of re-action occur in which the attention is not sharply focused on either stimulus or move- ment, but rather divided between the two; and it maybe that this is the most usual mode of re-action when the distinc- tion is not taken in to account. Both Martius and Dwelshauvers have recorded the subject's own opinion of the quickness of each re-action, and the state of his attention at the moment of re-acting. The estimate of the relative speed of re-action seems to be fairly accurate, and those re actions seem to be shortest in which the attention of the subject was sharply focused upon the matter in hand. A further characteristic of the motor form of re-action is that its average varia- tion is smaller, i.e., the process is more regular; and that false re-actions occur, either anticipations of stimulus or re-actions to some accidental disturbance. The distinc- tion is important as aiding in the explanation of individ- ual differences, as well as of the path of practice. The somewhat conflicting results obtained before this distinc- tion was taken into account might very well be due to the fact that the one observer re-acted in the one way, and the other in the other. Thus the re-action times of

20 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

Kries and Auerbach are motor; for they are brief, false re- actions occur, and it is noted that the simple re-actions fol- lowing re-actions involving distinctions were longer by 410" and Biff than before,— a change probably due to a return to a partially sensory mode of re-action. Again, there are doubtless transitional modes between the two, and there are reasons for believing that the path of practice is from the sensory to the motor form of re-action.

The influences that remain to be discussed may be consid- ered under the heads of "practice," "fatigue," 'individual differences," and "abnormal variations." (4) Practice. As just noticed, the effect of practice is intimately connected with the mode of re-action. It is noticed by almost all writers, but the extent to which it influences the time is very various. The observations make it probable that the effect of practice is most marked at first, and that when once the initial stages are over, the effect of continued practice is small. It is greatest in those persons whose time is longest at first, and seems most influential in acts that are complicated and lie somewhat beyond the realm of daily experience.

When the action is once thoroughly learned, an interval of disuse seems not to affect the time seriously. After not re-acting for three months, Cattell found no essential differ- ence in the time. On the other hand, with some there is a slight newness on beginning each day's work, making the first re-actions of a series rather long (Trautschoklt).

(5) A similar statement may be made of fatigue: it has greatest effect upon the complicated, less thoroughly learned processes, and varies with the individual and the mode of re action. With an automatic simple process its effect is very slow to appear (Cattell. It may enter at any stage of the process, sensory, motor, or central ; but the last seems to be the most serious. It appears as a difficulty in keeping one's attention upon the experiment, and thus lengthens the time, and especially the average variation of the experi-

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 21

mrnts. By fatigue is meant the fatigue brought about by the experimenting itself. The time is also affected by gen- eral fatigue preceding tbe experiment. Some individuals are extremely sensitive to influences of this kind.

(6) Individual Variations. The fact here to be investi- gated is the general one that different persons require differ- ent times for the performance of the same operations. The difficulty of drilling a company of men to act in concert, whether in military drill or otherwise, springs in part from this difference. It was from this point of view, too, that the time of mental processes was first studied. So long ago as 1795 Maskelyne, the astronomer i-oyal, discharged his as- sistant because the latter recorded the transit of a star across the wire of the telescope half a second or more later than he himself. Some twenty-five years later Bessel, another as- tronomer, had his attention called to the point, and upon in- vestigation established the fact that no two observers re- corded such ti-ansits at precisely the same time. The differ- ence in time between any two observers was usually expressed as an equation, and hence the term "personal equation," which, though strictly applicable only to the differences so found, has assumed a much wider meaning. The individual differences become greater as the process to be performed increases in complexity, and this explains in part why the personal equations as determined by the com- plicated eye and ear method were so large: with the simpler method of electrical record these d ifferences are much reduced . Besides the differences due to practice and the mode of re- action, there are a large number of minor sources of varia- tion, which as yet are not sufficiently understood to justify a correlation of quick or slow re-action times with definite individual qualities. We may, however, note (a) that the time is longer in children than in adults, as has been shown, amongst others, by Binet, who found that children from 3^ to 7 years re-acted in from 440(7 to 6600", when adults required

22 THE TIME-RELATIONS OP

but 140(7. In the very old the time is longer than in the prime of life. Under the influence of mental or physical fatigue, worry, or slight indisposition, the time has been in- creased. Obersteiner, Vintschgau, Goldscheider, and others, have incidentally observed these effects, showing an increase of 30i to 40(7. These variations are related to others, shad- ing over into the abnormal. Under this head may be con- sidered (7) the action of drugs and re-action times in the insane. Several of the earlier experimenters made a few observations concerning the effect of drugs. Exner found quite a marked lengthening of the time after drinking wine. Vintschgau and Dietl found that the effect of coffee was to decrease and of morphium to increase the time for a consid- erable period. The more elaborate researches of Kraepelin show that the effect of amyl, ether, and chloroform is a sudden lengthening of the re-action times, reaching a maxi- mum in a very few minutes, and followed by a rather long period of times slightly shorter than the normal. If a strong dose of the drug be used the lengthening is more considera- ble and the secondary shortening slighter. Thus Kraepelin, whose normal re-action was 183(7, after a strong inhalation of ether re-acted in 298(7, and in the period of shortening in 170(7; while with a light narcosis the maximum re-action was 223(7, and the shortened re-action 150(7. The effect of alcohol, however, is a brief period of shortened times fol- lowed by a long period of lengthened times. This is also found by Orchansky, who, with a normal re-action of 155(7, re-acts in 105(7 eight minutes after taking a dose of alcohol, and in 225(7 after thirty minutes. The observations of War- ren do not yield equally positive results, but do not conflict with those of Kraepelin. Changes in the extent of the aver- age variation have also been observed. On what psycho- logical factors these differences depend it is difficult to say, but the subjective feelings accompanying the lengthened times are a difficulty in keeping the attention upon the mat-

MENTAL PHENOMENA.

ter iu hand, and an unwillingness to exert one's self. The evidence afforded by the action of drugs upon these pro- cesses is important as indicating the dependence of the re-actions upon physiological conditions. A change of re- action times in insanity has been frequently observed, but the field for individual variation is here very large. It seems probable that in most forms of mental disease, and particularly in melancholia, there is a considerable length- ening of the re-action time, amounting in extreme cases to one half or three-quarters of a second. In the excited forms of disease, such as mania, a shortening has been observed. Obersteiner cites a case of general paralysis in the incipient stages of which the thne was 1660", in a more advanced stage 2810", in a most advanced stage 451<T. Stanley Hall has found a marked shortening of the time iu the hypnotic condition, but his result is not corroborated by others.

Methods of Experimentation.

The chief requisite in these experiments is an apparatus for accurately measuring small intervals of time. The ear- liest method, still in use, records the vibrations of a tuning- fork upon the quickly-moving smoked surface of a rotating drum, and beneath this the moment of giving the signal and making the response. If a fork making one hundred vibra- tions per second be used, whole hundredths can be directly counted and smaller fractions estimated. Wundt has con- structed a more accurate and specialized instrument in which a fork making five hundred vibrations per second is used. A very much simplified form of apparatus has been devised by Obersteiner, in which the slide holding the record is moved by hand, and the movement of re-action draws the fork off the record; and by Bowditch, in which the fork it- self carries the record, and the signal and re-action are indi- cated by a shifting of the writing point. In the astronomical records clock-work takes the place of a tuning fork. The objection to these methods is that they necessitate te.lious counting of curves. If the rate of the rotating-apparalus is very uniform and frequently tested, one may substitute

24 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

measuring- for counting-, but the most convenient apparatus for the purpose is the Hipp chronoscope. This instrument contains a fine clock-work, set iu motion by releasing a spring and running for about half a minute. The hands of the two dials, the one indicating tenths and the other thou- sandths of a second, do not move until drawn away from a set of cogs by the opening or closure of a magnetic circuit, and are stopped again in the same way. By making- the usual arrangement whereby the production of the stimulus sets the hands in motion and the re-acting movement brings them to a stand-still, we can read off directly the interval of the re-action time. Unless we can afford to sacrifice accu- racy for convenience, a means of controlling the chrono- scope is indispensable. This may be done by timing the fall of a ball from a given height and comparing it with the theo- retical time. In the apparatus for this purpose supplied with the chronoscope the ball is mechanically released, and the mode of making the circuit is equally defective, so that the error of the control apparatus is probably greater than that of the chronoscope. To obviate this difficulty I make use of a ball held in position by a magnet, and failing from any height up to seven feet, upon the arm of a well-balanced lever, thus securing an instantaneous release. By setting the magnet and ball at different distances we are also enabled to decide whether the error is absolute or relative. It is here necessary to break the current by which the ball falls, and to make the current by which the chronoscope starts at the same moment; this is effected by a key specially devised for the purpose. The chronoscope possesses a regulation for altering its rate when too slow or too fast, but I find it most convenient to make sparing use of this, and apply a correction for each day's determinations as found with the •'fall apparatus." Another form of control makes use of a falling hammer, the record being also made with a tuning- fork. A recent device of Ewald combines the two methods by mechanically counting the vibrations of a tuning-fork: a delicate armature is drawn to and released by a magnet with each vibration of the fork, moving the hand of a dial over one of its divisions as it does so. The fork is vibrating con- stantly, but the making of the signal sends the current into the u interruption-counter," while the re-acting movement again diverts the current away from it. It will record at

IUKNTAL PHEXOMFXA. 25

the rate of one hundred per second. Galton has constructed for ordinary uses a machine in which the signal is given by the release of a rod or pendulum, and the re-acting move- ment mechanically arrests the fall or swing, a scale of in- terval being determined for the apparatus empirically. San- ford has devised a simple but not expeditious chronoscope, in which the signal and the response separately set in mo- tion two pendulums of slightly different periods, the re-act- ing interval being calculated from the number of oscillations occurring before the two are in unison.

The methods of indicating the moment at which the signal appeared and the moment at which the re-acting movement was made are simple. When the record is writ- ten on a rotating surface, a point connected with a magnet, and writing a straight line beneath the vibrations of the fork, writes that line at a different level when the signal is given, and returns to the same level when the re-acting movement is made; or the tuning-fork itself may be made to write at a different level during the interval measured. The arrangement by which the level is changed on the rec- ord, or the hands are set in motion in the chronoscope at the same instant that the stimulus appears, is equally sim- ple. For sound, the noise of the key by which the circuit is made is generally sufficient, or other sound may be pro- duced by bodies falling upon various surfaces and thereby opening or closing a key. For sight, the impression to which a re-action is to bo made may be concealed behind a screen, and the drawing away of this screen at the same time makes or breaks an electric circuit. Frequently the re-actor sits in the dark, and the impression becomes visible only when an electric spark appears, or the spark itself may be the stimulus. For touch, temperature, and taste, a typi- cal device is that of Vintschgau, in which the end of a rod touches the sensitive surface, and the pressure so exerted makes a contact with a delicate metallic blade inserted in the same apparatus. For smell, the movement by which the odor is set free is similarly utilized. The re-acting movement is usually that of pressing an ordinary telegraphic key. Devices have been constructed by which movements of the foot, of the jaw, of the voice and lip, may be similarly noted. For more detailed descriptions consult the references under this head at the end.

»b THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

Having- thus considered the time-relations of a simple re- action, we may proceed, on the line of analysis there laid down, to the consideration of the more complex forms of re-action.

Adaptive Re-actions.

It has been noted that the prominent characteristic of a useful re-action is the adaptation of the response to the excitation by which it was called out. This adaptation involves a recognition of the stimulus, and its association with the movement in question. In this recognition we found it convenient to distinguish between the recognition of the presence and that of the nature of the stimulus ; but it may be questioned whether we can recognize the presence except by noting some point of the nature of the stimulus, and whether the noting of this point does not involve its distinction from others. If, in re-acting to a sound, I recognize that it is the stimulus to which I am to re-act, and press the key, does this mean that I know that the stimulus is not a visual or a tactile one, that it is not a higher or a lower, a louder or a feebler, sound ? Here, as still more in the analysis to follow, our experimental basis is defective.

Experiment has naturally followed the lines of conven- ience and ready analysis; and as there has been little har- mony in these analyses, and as the one here adopted differs somewhat from those adopted by other writers, it will be difficult to maintain the parallelism between theoretical discussion and the obtained results. If we understand by the simple re-action the mere signalling that a definite, pre designated, and expected stimulus is present, and by an "adaptive" re-action one in which the mode of response depends upon and varies with the nature of the stimulus, we may distinguish several stages of connection between the two. as shown in the schedule at the top of the following page.

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 27

I. A single stimulus with a single mode of re-action. II. Several stimuli with a single mode of re-act inn. (a) The subject foreknows the stimulus. (6) The subject does not foreknow the stimulus. III. A single stimulus icith several modes of re-action.

SIMPI.K UK-

IV. Several stimuli with several modes of re-action. ACTIONS.

(a) The subject foreknows the stimulus and al o he re-action.

(b) The subject foreknows the re- action, but not the stimulus

(O The subject foreknows neither stimulus ) ADAPTIVE RE.ACTION. nor re-action. (

Or, more simply, if the re-action is foreknown, the pro- cess is a simple re-action ; if not, it is an adaptive re-action. In addition, in the simple re-action the foreknowledge of the stimulus may be entirely definite, the stimulus always being the same, or there may be a known range of variation or an unknown range of variation ; while in the adaptive re-action the possibilities are limited to the latter t\vo.

I. has been fully considered. In IT. (a) we have a num- ber of different simple re-actions; but, instead of investigat- ing them in separate series, we have different kinds in one series: e.g.. a sound, a light, or a touch may appear, it being announced to the subject which it is to be; and he in each case re-acts by pressing the key. The impressions may be more homogeneous, as a series of colors; but in all cases the subject need not appreciate the nature of the stimulus, but simply that a stimulus has appeared. In II. (6) the subject knows the possible stimuli, but does not know which is to come next; otherwise the conditions are precisely the same as above. Wuiidt's experiment with the irregular change between two intensities of sound would belong here, and would indicate that this is an essential factor. In III. the several modes of re-action are necessarily known in advance. Instead of testing the different forms of re-actions in separate series, we have several in one series. For example : we re. act to a sound now with the thumb, then with the I'oivlinger, the subject always knowing in advance what he is to do. In

28 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

IV. (a) we are combining into one series different forms of simple re-actions, differing both in stimulus and form of re- action: but the complete reaction (e.g., red color to be re-acted to by middle finger) is announced beforehand. In IV. (6) the subject is told in advance how to re-act, but not what the stimulus is to be. However, in both this and the foregoing case he need not wait to recognize the nature of the stimulus, but re acts as soon as he detects its presence. All these are variations of simple re-action times. When we pass to IV. (c), we have a different, namely, an adaptive, re-action. The subject is not told any thing in advance ex- cept the association upon which he is to re- act: e.g., if a blue light, with the right hand ; if a red light, with the left hand ; and so on. The essential difference here is that the subject must first distinguish a certain feature of the nature of the stimulus, in this case the color; then call up the appropriate movement and perform it. A re-action of this kind, there- fore, involves a definite distinction of stimuli, and a choice of

movements.

Distinction and Choice.

The mental processes involved in an adaptive re-action, in addition to those involved in the simple re action, are thus a more specific recognition of the stimulus, and a choice between movements. By maintaining all other factors alike, the difference of time of the two modes of re-action measures the combined time of distinction and choice. The first determinations of this nature were made by Donders and his pupils (1865-68^. A simple re- action to a light, white or red, was made in 201(7 (average of five observers) ; but an adaptive re-action with the right hand for the one light, and the left hand for the other, in 355o-,_a difference of 154(7. Cattell makes a simple adap- tive re-action to two colors in 340(7, his simple re-action time being 146(7, or a difference of 194(7 (XL). Miinsterberg re- acts simply with any of the five fingers in 141(7, but re-acts

MENTAL 1'HKNOMEXA. 2!t

willi M definite finger (according as the numbers of the fin- gers "one," "two,"' "three," etc., are called) in 195(7 longer (XXIV.). Accepting these as values for the combined dis- tinction and choice time under simple conditions, our next step would naturally be to determine how much of the time is due to distinction, how much to choice. This is a diffi- cult step; for we cannot readily determine that a distinction has been made, except by indicating it in the mode of re- action, and we cannot execute a choice except upon the basis of some distinction. The most usual experiment by which it has been attempted to overcome this difficulty consists in re-acting to only a designated one of a group of stimuli, allow- ing all others to pass without re-action. To take a simple case, let red and blue be the possible stimuli: if red appears, re-act; if blue, do nothing. While this form of experiment is interesting and useful, the inferences from it are not as clear as could be wished. It may be termed the "incomplete adaptive re-action," or briefly the "incomplete re-action." It involves a distinction of the stimulus to be re acted to, from those not to be re-acted to, and a choice between motion and refraining from action. It seems probable that these processes are respectively easier than a distinction that cannot be anticipated and a choice between two movements; but it seems equally probable that the extent of these differ- ences will vary considerably under different circumstances. If the simple re- action is of the quick, motor form, and the incomplete re-action involves an additional distinction of the stimulus, as well as the choice between motion and rest, the additional time above the simple re-action would be long, and the difference between it and the adaptive re-action short. This is evidently the case with Cattell and Berger, who, with a simple re action of 146 ff and 150(7, perform the incomplete re-action in 306(7 and 277(7, the adaptive in 340(7 and 295(7 (IV. and XL). On the other hand, Dondrrs, with an evidently sensory mode of re-action, has a simple re-

30 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

action of 201(7, an incomplete of 237 (7, and an adaptive of 284(7. A second method attempts to deal with the difficulty by delaying the re-action until the precise nature of the stimulus has been appreciated, and regards the difference in time between this and the simple re action as ' he time needed for the distinction of the stimulus. There is nothing but the subjective guaranty that the moment of re-action is coinci- dent with the process of recognition, and we have no reason to regard this guaranty as valid. There may be a tendency to make the distinction on the basis of the after-image, and thus signal the appreciation of it too soon; or, again, an extreme desire not to re-act before the distinction is made may delay reaction to an unusual length. Friederich's investigations show for colors a simple re-action time of 175(T, and a "subjective distinction" time of 267(7 (XXXIX.); while Tigerstedt, and also Tischer, find only about half this difference for nearly the same re-action.. It seems wisest, under these circumstances, not to decide the relative shares of the distinction and choice in the adaptive re action, but to study the combined time as a whole, and the influences by which it is affected. We can thus utilize the results of all the methods for comparative purposes; and, in addition, we can vary the complexity of the distinction while leaving the choice the same (and to a more limited extent can vary the choice without the distinction), and thus can in many cases distinguish whether an increased complexity of an adaptive re action is to be referred to an increase in the difficulty of the choice or to an increase in the difficulty of the distinc- tion.

It is desirable to analyze more particularly the nature of the difference between the simple re-action and the "sub- jective," and between the simple and the incomplete. An essential point relates to the mode of re action, whether motor or sensory ; nor is it necessary that the same mode of re-action be followed in all cases. A few points here relevant are illustrated in Tischer's results upon nine subjects with sound

MKNTAL PHENOMENA 31

re-actions and distinctions. The average of the nine gives a distinction time of 159(T, and a simple time of I18o". Four of the subjects evidently make vise of the motor re-action, their simple time being 107(7, and their subjective distinction 116(7; i.e., the re-action takes place upon the appearance of the stimulus, its distinction taking place later. Berger and Cat- tell express the same difficulty, and for this reason discarded the method. Their simple re-action to weak liyht was 198(7, with distinction of intensity 208(7. Two of the subjects evidently 7-e-act according to the "sensory" method, their sim- ple re-action being 141(7, and the subjective distinction 246(7. That these are not individual differences is shown by the fact that the adaptive re-actions are about alike in all. Similarly with regard to the difference between the simple and the incomplete re action times. Dondeis, and those of Tischer's subjects who re-act by the "sensory" method, show a relatively small difference, though this is not true of Friede- rich's subjects. While Tischer's "motor" subjects show a difference of 159(7 between the simple and the incomplete, the " sensory " subjects show one of only 61(7. Again, when the re-action is " motor," the expectation is entirely directed to the stimulus upon which re-action is to follow, and the fact that other stimuli may appear hardly enters into the experiment. This seems to he the case with Kries and Auer- bach, who, with clearly "motor" re-actions, find a difference of 30-40(7 for (XXX.-XXXYJ.) a variety of incomplete re- actions. It may be added that the change from the simple to the incomplete form of re-action will often bring with it an at- tention to the sensory part of the process, and thus make the difference between it and the simple time long. This seems to be the case with Berger and Oattell, who. witli a simple re- action time of 147(7 and 150 >. have an incomplete re-action time of SOQ'J and 277o~. The difference between the incom- plete and the adaptive re-action seems to be uniformly small (many of the differences being not far from 40(7), though the individual variations are considerable. It is likely that the effects attributed to practice and fatigue may really be due to a change from the sensory to the motor form of re- action. Thus Kries and Auerbach mention that their incom- plete times were at first very long, but that they became very small, the reduction continuing long after the effect of pi tc- tice upon the simple re-action had ceased. Again, the i'a<-t

THE TIME-RELATIONS OP

ft^

I

^

^

-O

-H

4 S 1- S3

CO-

I2

CD--

1

a

33

a

^ 3 CD' a ^ •: s o

"o

CD

bO

c8

Is-

CD

lafill

2 &i>3 too- - -- - - -

A

S § 1 §^ 3

a -^ ho o c ^ ^r aj

2n P3 0^ P^

CD - - S" 1/2

>0 W

© 3 '^* ' m

C5 Ed ^^ **

CD 1

CM ^H 33 . O^2 CD 33

o-i i!

i— ' C-t OJ W CJ QI

CD •«->

*fl

a

HH

;; -

«

•emu UOUOB

CO ^O O £O CO 'O iO » "-O £O

§ S P°gSgPgg g

OO CM

cc

-9JJ editing

q:^ S gS^SSi^s

o ^- "^ * r ~' ~^ o co

M Tf TT •^•^t

OOO CO id QO OO

.^

«CN o< rora .. cororoco

c

0

CD

IK

s

CD

Ll

CD

4-1 - - CO

O

ta

33

0

:3

2 |

i

4>

^e"0'^

»

CD '

^5 ^^ --------

yj

•*

* 1

T* ^

l^J

in

l,|

o M © o3 Cd d

2 "a. - - -

CD 3

i; a n

^ - --------'33

1 - 1

o a

g- - -------

o

s

I-H

a --------go (3 0 •O O •< ^^

*' 1

| ; ; i ; ; ; ;

CO

-o

: : § :'a £^ d

1

^ S : a : 33 i : : :

S | : ^2 : : : : a

; : r Os

Nature of Distinc Between.

"3 K^ 0 ^ ;

"i"^ O O <O o ~ ** U

|a 1 E iS" gi

fees cS i. SB 2o

_- T3 * " "" ^ "

jjfl a CD oa'cDm

11 1

M « £3^ad3:^l

s i iigili | §

D U3 O a^;^; g'g O

>o s-i - - "2,- g o 5 M ® '3 ' cs" 5- 35 5

PH D^ ^^ ^5 ^ £H ^*

o Ca

s- 1-1 r

s

a s

d fc

-a 5 a>?=5^

b^ ^~J ij i^ kj f**- J^ ij p^ ^ j

i i s

MKNTAL PHENOMENA.

83!i |

1

|

M

A

M

«M

£

•? .£3 ^ &(

-~

•f.

/.'

cd

£ '

Cl -• - -•

•;;•- CD •§ ~T

;

^

'

A

CDHH

i— i

- i 8 _r -5

i

-~

b

IM

^o

13

o! * -

%

n

a -

u

Cv

a

j.,

j-,

a a ° § fe

S

i

0

f,

<*-<

aa

M §| *

g-d

5* - •£

® 1> X ^. "•'"^

. *

:•:

-

o5 5

5 ®

fO -t^ O >

•—i nj

«*H O 4J 3

l^fllUiy

i|

-S

g

£ a

=3 fe

ti«

O - - -

n M &JD ^

o> 9

GO -

^

a

0 ® tj) -^

cs

<d a a

*. H «8

o a a O

6 M

"Ss - ^co">' <D a

- - - <o

- - - -a

H

5

<B

3

it iO ifl

o

s*

w

«

c? w ww w

TfClQ^ <?* CC^O Ol

-reoooo

\ \

a

O5 Qj

""-1

03

•d

n

a

h- (

CB

eo tra 5n

|

S

ofc

m

COW TPOOO

•^ ^ co »o -^

JC

»OCDCDO ^ •^^'•^ GO t-X30CO i~> T— IT— tt— i GO

'-f. -J3330O

OO XJ3OCO

\ \

ID

tD t- CO

gs

<—

1

ilo*

T-«

t-^aDC^Oi I- £> I- O «-H

Tt i-«*-l WO?

?>

OXi-t~ CO -fXTt* (O OJ TO CO CD T-< i— i r^T rH ol

1-OS ?! X

OS 00 CO 30

c? -r in in

lO t

1O C

ft M CO

ti

a

' 3

« 2 n

_fl

^rt

S

(H

1 S =

a

:=

-

I

1 Auerbai i<

ii

H

: " ; : :

<D OQ

•S-31

"^

2 S g 2 |

!"*si rsi'i I

B 5 Is

i i i i

"CB.J

C3

orrespouc

S

^^v

_ Y— v

O

u

2

S

s

•—

&a

a

tn

a

s

a

•*

to

s -

Z

- - * ^ i

•:

iii- ^ -ii «

- i I 3

"g J

o

a

a

0

a

lO

ts.

c1;

ID

si

H

<n

4)

ID

>

ID

03

4-j

^

3,

j)

a

**

=

•* ~*

"

" - - - -

o

IV

ft

- - - -

5*

-a

•a

§

K

-

09

•d

d o

a

o

.

1-1

.

r

^

o

2"

0 : S

<n •£

o-fi S

•I : ° a . CD ^ ^ ^

a

3

p a £? -

St 3 te

- o

*•

03

** u "*

"5. o-^o

M 13 "

-i a oo

•a'S o

a

a!

a

aj m

a

a

^ in ^

Ht!

C5fi >H

o

oT.H af

~ % •? •_ oj y

i? i

o

£

3

!jii®i

SC 0 * iS -

a

2

^ S- - --- 03 SB 03

M 3 ~™ O

^ i : :

?

ga o - 1$ *

ID -Z X to i i O

ft /.

*

Direction o

Colors Distance of

Localize to

2 •o'^Z °

,_ d tx -p a a g a g H E-I -j? f- -Jo

•a a d cc

3 ^

^ CO S ® ft

3 S— g o g g p.® ft -S - - - TS

' ® fli C3 >•*

^§5.5 g J3

^ O r~" ^ V2 1>

i i " ;

88

HH t— 1 )— 1 ^ h- ( 1— i

M > >

x r; x

^ X

X

^

^

XXXIII

IIIAXXX

IIAXXX IAXXX AX XX AIXXX

XXXIX

J H- . i— 1 ^. J^,._— I_H

M y,

P5

34 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

that simple re-action times are long when following complex ones, or that subjective times are longer when following adaptive re-actions, seems to be not so much the effect of fatigue as of a continuance of a sensory mode of re-action. It should also be mentioned that Tigerstedt ingeniously proposes to measure the distinction time by taking the differ- ence between two incomplete re-actions, in one of which we re-act to a definite simple impression, and in the other to the impression requiring distinction (e.g., in one series I re-act to white, but not to a color; in the other, to a color, but not to white); and the difference in time will be needed for distinguishing a color from white. The general fact re mains, then, that while the combined distinction and choice times exhibit only such individual and other variations as seem explicable by the differences in the conditions of ex- periment (the adaptive re action times of eight of Tischer's nine subjects fall between 293 and 3205"), the estimates that have been attempted of the portions of the time due to dis- tinction and to choice separately, show such large variations as to force the conviction that the different experimenters were not measuring the same processes.

Conditions affecting Distinction and Choice. Bearing in mind that we are dealing with comparative re- sults only, and comparisons restricted mainly to the results of the same observer, obtained by the same method, we pro- ceed to investigate the conditions by which these processes involving distinction and choice are affected. It will be convenient to begin with the effect of (1) the number of dis- tinctions and of choices. The effect of the number of ob- jects among which distinction is to take place, upon the time needed to make the distinction, is best shown in the "incom- plete" and subjective methods, in which the range of dis- tinction may be varied without affecting that of choice. For example: Cattell makes an incomplete re-action to a certain color when either that or one other color may appear in 306o", when either that or any one of nine other colors may appear (IV and V.) in 3130". Friederich's subjects make a subjective distinction bet ween two colors in 267<J, between four

MENTAL IMIKNOMENA.

in 296<7 (XXXIX. and X I,.). Six of Tischer's subjects make a subjective distinction between two sounds of different inten- sity in 146(7 (simple re-action, 114 (7) ; between three sounds, in 1640"; four sounds, in 178(7; five sounds, in 194(7 (XLIV.- XLVII.). Other experiments cited in the table (p. 32) show the same slight increase of distinction time with the increase of the range of impressions, but complicated with other factors as well. With regard to the effect upon the choice time when the number of possible choices increases, we have the results of Merkel, who found for the simple re-action time of ten subjects to visual impressions 1883"; for an adaptive re- action between two impressions, 2760"; between three, 3300"; between four. 3940"; between five, 4450"; between six, 489(7; between seven, 526(7; between eight, 562(7; between nine, 581(7; and between ten, 588(7 (partially cited in XL VIII.- L1I.). The impressions were the numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, and I., II., III., IV., and V. The re-actions to movements of the ten fingers naturally associated with these impressions, and the naturalness of this association doubtlessly contributes to the small increase in time. Miinsterberg called these numbers and re-acted in the same way, finding for a choice between five movements 383(7. and between ten 478(7 (simple re-action being 162(7). Martins finds for the same re-actions 474(7 and 552(7 (average of three observers). It being established that but a small share of the increase is due to the distinction (Merkel has experimentally shown this for his subjects), we may conclude, that, with an increase in number, the difficulty of choice increases rr.ore rapidly than the difficulty of distinction. In addition, we have reason to believe that the increase would be still more marked in case the association between impression and motion is artificial. When this association reaches the maximum of natutalness, in naming objects, the increase with the number of impressions is slight Thus it may !><• calculated from Cattell's results that it takes him but a

36 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

100" longer to name 26 letters or short words than to name one of two, but QQff longer to name one of 26 than one of two pictures, and 163(7 longer to name one of ten than one of two colors; the action of naming being more closely re- lated to letters and words than to pictures and colors.

It is the ability to deal promptly and correctly with a large and varying number of impressions, disposing of each in its appropriate way, that we recognize as evidence of mental power, and it is this that experiment shows to be a factor of great influence upon the time of an adaptive re-action. It is the skill in disposing of so large a number of adaptive re-actions that we admire in the post-office clerk, and in many other exhibitions of manual dexterity. It is this that necessi- tates the division of labor, there being a limit to the number of adaptive re-actions that can be economically controlled. Again: the fact that a large number of distinctions does not complicate the process as much as a large number of choices, finds its analogue in the observation that our power of re- production falls below our powers of appreciation. This plays a part in the fact that we learn to understand a lan- guage long before we learn to speak it, and in many similar processes. The development of mental power reveals itself as an increasing facility in performing a large number of complicated adaptive re-actions; and here, too, the power of appreciating distinctions develops earlier than the power of choosing. This result was illustrated experimentally in a brief study of the re-action times of a ten-year-old child as compared with those of an adult. While the pure distinc- tion time rose from 58 ff to 250(7 as the impressions to be distinguished increased from two to five 'subjective method, with colors), as compared with 44(f and 78(7 for adults, for the adaptive re-action for two impressions the time was 120(7, for five impressions 603(7, as compared with 79(7 and 210 ff for adults.

We may conveniently introduce the general topic of the

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 37

effect of the nature of the distinction and the choice upon the time of its performance with ths consideration of a few points affecting th'e distinction alone. (2) The similarity of the impressions. The endowment of the various sense- organs varies considerably (e.g., the sense of musical pitch is finer than that of sound intensity) ; but, in the absence of a standard of comparison of sense-differences in disparate types of sensation, we can only illustrate the point in question by varying the difficulty of distinction within the same sense. Thus Kries and Auerbach find that it takes much longer to tell whether a sound is to the right or to the left, according as the two points at which the sound is produced are closer together. When they form an angle of 35°-120° with the centre of the face, the additional time (by the incomplete method) was 17 ff; when varied between 35° and 26°, the time was 78ff; when within 26° and 11°, it was 137(7. The ease of distinction is largely a function of practice. We readily seize the slight optical differences furnished by the different letters of a known language, but constantly con- fuse much greater sense differences with which we are less familiar. (3) The specific nature of the impression. Very many of the results cited in the table may be said to illus- trate the effect of a change in the nature of the distinction ; but it is difficult to show this, uncomplicated with other variations. The determinations of Kries and Auerbach (XXX.-XXXVIII.) show the result of distinctions of vari- ous kinds, though an analysis of the causes of these differ- ences is hardly practicable. It is quite clear that in re-act- ing by the incomplete method the re action is shorter when the stimulus is the stronger of t\vo intensities than when it is the weaker of the two (XXXVI and XXXVIII.). Berger has also shown that the intensity of the stimulus has some influence upon the distinction time beyond what would be due to the effect upon the simple re-action time therein con- tained. The difference between the corresponding simple

;!S THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

and the incomplete re-action to a bright light is 85tf; to a medium light, 119(J; to a weak light, 114(T; while similar differences for adaptive re-actions are 167<7, 179 ff, 1925"; the inference being that the intensity of the stimulus affects the distinction rather than the choice. Again (in the series VI. -X.), we find that Cattell recognized most quickly that an expected one of 26 pictures was present, then that one of 26 letters, next one of 28 short English words, next one of 26 short German words. The differences between the time for recognizing letters and short words is very slight com- pared to the increase in complexity of the impression, and thus shows the effect of practice in recognizing words as a whole. Furthermore, in the series of experiments (partly cited in XLT.-XLIIF.) in which one to six place numbers were recognized, while there is a concomitant increase in the number of possible impressions, it seems fair to refer the main increase in time to the increasing complexity of the impression. In passing from the recognition of one to two or of two to three place numbers, the increase in time is slight; but from there on, the increase itself increases with the increase of the number of numerals (53 ff, 147 ff, 322<r),— a fact probably related to the practice in grasping numbers in groups of threes. Another series (XXIV. -XXIX ) may be mentioned here, and is interesting as indicating that it is more difficult to tell to which of five categories (a city, a river, etc.) a word belongs than what part of speech it is; and this is in turn easier than to tell the sphere of activity of a noted man. It should be noted that the choice, the range of impressions, the connection between impression and movement, the method of re-action, are equivalent hi all three experiments; so that the difference is fairly referable to the distinction process involved. We may finally notice as here pertinent the observations of Vintschgau upon the distinguishability of different tastes. He found that by the incomplete method it took longest to re-act to bitter when

MENTAL PHENOMENA. :>>!)

the alternative \vas distilled water, next long to sweet, next to sour, and shortest to salt. Similarly, in adaptive re-ac- tions with the two hands to all possible combinations of .two of the four tastes, salt was most quickly re-acted to (384(7), sour next (397(7), sweet next (409(7), and bitter last (456(7).

(4) The Foreknowledge of the Subject. Within the re- striction that the foreknowledge of the subject shall be limited to the knowledge of the associative boud between stimulus and movement, there is room for variation. The simplest case would present but one stimulus re-acted to, and but one not re-acted to, or, in the adaptive re-action, but one stimulus for each mode of re-action. In all such cases (I., II., IV., XI., XXXVIII., may be cited as instances) the foreknowledge of the subject presents the maximum of definiteness. Any departure from these conditions brings with it an increase in the time of re action. Cattell finds but a very slight increase (5-7(7) in the incomplete re-action when the stimulus not re-acted fo, instead of being but a single one, is any one of ten colors, but finds a greater in- crease (15(7, difference of II. and III.) when the stimulus re-acted to, instead of being a single one, is one of ten colors, though the particular kind of color need not be recog- nized. Both the stimulus re-acted to and the one not re- acted to might be one of a larger or smaller, a more or less homogeneous group; but I am unable to find a rrcoid of such an experiment. The somewhat modified form of ex- periment adopted by Tigerstedt and Bergqvist shows a similar result. They re-acted to a light, when either the light or a one to three place number might appear, in 297<T, and to the number (including its recognition) in 318(7. If the number of digits of the numbers that may appear is foreknown, the time is considerably reduced; and when either the light or a foreknown letter might appear, the time for recognizing the light was still further shortened (190(7). The same scries <>f variations could be applied to adaptive reactions (i.e., one

THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

or more, or all, of the modes of re-action might be associated

with any member of a variable group of stimuli), but experi-

ments designed to show the effect of such variations are

lacking. Mention should be made, however, of the experi-

ments of Miinsterberg, in which he first re-acts witb the five

fingers to five categories, each limited to one term (XXIV.

and XXV.); then to five categories, each comprising three

terms (XXVI.); and then to five categories, each com-

prising a practically indefinite number of terms (XXVII.,

XXVIII., XXIX.); and finds an increase of time in making

these steps (Martius has repeated experiments XXV.,

XXVI., and XXVII., finding the times to be 551ef, 644ff,

and 804ff). Although other factors contribute to this in-

crease in time, part of it may be referred to the decreasing

definiteness of the foreknowledge of the subject. It may be

added, that the mechanism by which an increase in the

number of possible re-actions increases the re-action time

is allied to that by which a decrease in the foreknowledge of

the subject does so.

The effect of the mode of re-action upon the re-action time is the same here as in the simple re-action. Re-acting by the voice in the incomplete form of re-action has been found to be longer than re-acting by the finger; and when- ever the re-action takes the form of speaHng or naming, it takes some time to place the organs in position and speak the word. But a very special and important effect in adap- tive re-actions is that of (5) the association between move- ment and stimulus.

As the effect of a special or a general practice, certain modes of re-acting to certain types of stimuli have become natural, easy, and familiar, while in other cases (e.g., the re-acting by pressing a key, —a process learned only for the purposes of the experiment) the association is extremely artificial If we compare, in Miinsterberg's series, the ex- periment in which the five fingers re act to the numbers

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 41

"one," "two," "three,'1 "four," "five" (XXIV.), with that in which they re-act to the declensional forms of a Latin noun (XXV.), we recognize that the former is a more natu- ral association than the latter, and seem justified in at- tributing a good share of the increase in time to this differ- ence. Again: to re-act by naming is a process in which we have had considerable training, and it is quite evident that the time needed for naming one of 26 different impressions (XV.-XVJIL, and XX.) is much shorter than would be needed for re acting by 26 artificial and irregular movements of the hand. The difficulty in learning a foreign language, or a telegraphic code, or a shorthand system of writing, is largely the difficulty of forming associations between com- plex stimuli and movements; and the great decrease in time that is brought about when such associations have been mastered emphasizes the importance of the factor now under discussion, which, in turn, may be regarded as an expression of the effect of practice.

We may push the analysis a step farther. The process of naming is much more closely associated with a word or a letter than with a picture or a color; for the former are artificial symbols, becoming significant only when so interpreted, while the latter reveal their meaning directly without needing to be named or read. Accordingly, we find that it takes longer to name a color (6010") or a picture (545(7) than to name a letter (4240") or a word (409(7), though the recognition of a color or a picture is a quicker process than the recognition of a letter or a word (compare XV., XVII.. XIX., XX., and V., VI., VII., X ). Furthermore, if the time of naming or reading is thus mainly conditioned by the strength of association involved, we may in turn utilize this process as an index of familiarity with the nam- ing or reading, or, more briefly, with the language. Thus Cattell, an American, reads English words more quickly than German (XVII. and XVIIT. t, while with Berger, a

42 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

German, this relation is reversed. To name a picture in German occupies Cattell for 614(7; in English, 588 ff. It occupies Berger in German for 501(7; in English. 580(7. The inference is the same (though the absolute time is much shorter) if we read words in construction instead of isolated. By this method Cattell finds that he can read an English word in 138(7, a French in 167(7, a German in 250(7, an Italian in 327(7, a Latin in 434(7, and a Greek word in 484(7, this being the order of his familiarity with these languages. The particular nature of the association may be revealed in the study of these time-relations. Thus, while in all cases it takes longer to read words from right to left than from left to right, this difference is relatively least in the least familiar languages; i.e., in those in which the bond of asso- ciation between the words is least significant. For a like reason letters are read much more quickly from above down- wards (102(7) than from below upwards (264(7).

(6) The Overlapping of Mental Processes. We pass now to a point of critical importance in the application of results gained in the laboratory, to the mental operations of daily life. While in the former case we are performing a set task, isolated for purposes of investigation, in the lat- ter case (i.e., in such operations as reading, copying, play- ing upon instruments, and the like) we are performing a continuous, more or less extended, series of re-actions, bound together by bonds of common purpose and associations of habit. It is not a mere aggregate, but an organization of mental processes ; and this makes possible the performance of the several factors of the process in part at the same time. It leads to an "overlapping" of the mental elements. It is a proficiency in thus doing several things at once that consti- tutes much of the difference between the expert and the novice; and it is this "telescoping" process that seems to be the method by which complicated operations are at length performed in short times. It is for this reason that the time

MENTAL PHENOMENA. (:',

per word of reading 100 words is shorter than the time of reading a single word. Cattell reads a short word in 4090", a long one in 4510", but 100 such in 255(7 per word, and, if the words are in construction, in 125(T per word ; thus indicat- ing how much of the difference between ordinary reading, and reading single words, is due to the continuity of the experi- ment, how much to the association between the words. So, also, Cattell reads a single letter in 424<7, but 100 such in 224(7 (compare XVII., XV., with LIIL, LIV.). When the series is too long continued, fatigue sets in, and the time is again longer; it is longer for 500 than for 100 words and letters; and for colors and pictures there is no saving in naming 100 above naming a single color or picture.

A special study of this power of grasping several things at once was made by Cattell by having letters move along on the surface of a rotating drum, and varying the width of a slit in a screen through which they were read. When the slit just allowed one letter to be seen at a time, they could be read at the rate of one letter in 228(7; and as the slit was widened to admit two, three, four, five, and six letters at once, the rate increased to one letter in 200(7, 178 (7, 166 ff, 160(7, and 160<7. As it takes 424(7 to name a letter singly ("XV.), it would seem that the whole of a letter need not be seen at once to be recognized, an inference corroborated bv the fact, that, when the slit admils only one-tenth of a let- ter at a time, the letters can be read at 4000" per letter. The result also indicates that there is a limit to the power in question. M. Paulhan finds similar results in more complex operations. He multiplies numbers and recites a verse or two at the same time ; and the time needed for this is shorter than the sum of the times required to do each separately. In very simple cases the time of doing both together is not longer than the time for doing the more difficult of the two separately. The mind should accordingly not be likened to a point at which but a single object can impinge at our time, but

44 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

rather to a surface of variable extension. It should like- wise be noted that the performance of a complex and ex- tended mental task is not the same thing as the separate performance of the several elements into which that task may be analyzed.

Mtinsterberg has applied the distinction between the sensory and motor form of re-action to complicated adaptive re-actions, and regards it as there involving the overlap- ping of mental processes. The times cited in the table (XXIV.-XXIX.) in Munsterberg's experiments refer to sensory re-actions. In these the attention is directed to the word about to be uttered. It is recognized, and re- ferred to its group. The corresponding movement is then aroused and performed, the several processes being succes- sive in time. In the motor form the word is thought of as a "forefinger-moving" word; and the movement upon which the attention is kept fixed is expectantly kept ready to be set off at the slightest notice. The several processes thus play into one another, some perhaps entirely falling away. Both anticipatory movements and errors (moving the finger next to the correct one) are not infrequent. The motor times for the series XX IV. -XXIX. are 289, 355, 430, 432, 432, and 437 6; the differences between motor and sensory times, 94, 110, 258, 280, 461, 6850". Until these very important and striking results are better understood, it would be unwise to enter into a discussion of them. Martius has very recently repeated some of Munsterberg's results (XXLV.-XXVII.), and not only fails to corroborate them, but finds that the attention to the movement about to be made lengthens the time. He holds that the distinction between motor and sensory re-actions is applicable only to simple re-actions, and, while unable to explain Munsterberg's results, does not believe the difference there involved to be the same as that involved in simple re-actions. It remains for future research to shed light upon the problem.

(7) Practice and Fatigue. What was said under these headings of simple re-actions applies with equal force to complex ones. Various experimenters notice the decrease in time as the experiments proceed. They note that this

MENTAL PHENOMENA. C,

decrease is relatively greatest at first, and in those individu- als and processes whose time is relatively longest at the out- set; also that it soon reaches a limit, and, when once thor- oughly acquired, is not liable to be lost after a moderate degree of disuse; and that it at times seems to be confused with a transition from a sensory to a motor form of re-ac- tion. As illustrative of one or other of these points, it may be mentioned that Tischer finds as a rather typical case the decrease of a distinction time from 1600" in the first set to 95(7 in the second, and 860" in the third, all reduction ceas- ing on the average after 5.5 sets; that Trautscholdt, in re- actions consisting of repeating a word, finds times of 299, 273, and 258, and in another case of 205, 176, and 155 G, in three successive periods of fourteen days each; that Ber- ger and Cattell, beginning with some practice in experi- ments of this kind, find the time for incomplete re-actions reduced by 30 and 20(7 after four months' experimentation; and, finally, that the great decrease in the incomplete re- actions of Kries and Auerbach (from 64 and 117 to 21(7, from 153 and 109 to 36 ff, from 104 and 97 to 49 and 54(7, in various experiments) strongly suggests a radical change in the mode of re-action. Another aspect of the effect of practice appears in a study by Berger of the times required by the boys of the nine classes of a German Gymnasium, and of the class preparatory to the Gymnasium, to read 100 and 500 words in construction in German and in Latin at a maximum and at a normal rate. There is a constant de- crease in time as the boys advance in age. In Latin the several times per word were 262, 135, 100, 84, 79, 57, 54, 49, 48, 43(7 ; in German 72, 55, 43, 37, 39, 28, 27, 26, 25, 23(7; the great difference between the first two times in Latin being due to the fact that the boys who required 262(7 to read a Latin word had never learned Latin at all. That these differences are to be referred to specific practice rather than to general mental maturity, appears from a comparison of the above

40 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

times with the times required by those boys to name colors; viz., 135, 99, 119, 123, 100, 91, 112, 99, 86 ff.

The results regarding fatigue are not equally definite. Many mention the general fact of fatigue, and to avoid it perform but few experiments in a series. We have already seen that it takes relatively longer to read 500 letters, words, colors, pictures, than to read 100. On the other hand, Cat- tell, after a very long series of re-actions, found no serious or constant increase in the time, but seemed to feel the ef- fects of fatigue on the following day. Both practice and fatigue are subject to large individual variations. Oehrn has studied the minor variations of practice and fatigue in a session of two hours1 work, finding first a stage in which practice outweighs fatigue, and then a stage in which the reverse is true.

(8) Miscellaneous and Individual Variations. The complex re-actions, just as the simple ones are subject to the influences of distraction, vary under the action of drugs, in morbid conditions, and present large individual variations. These points, though frequently noticed incidentally, have not been subjected to special study, so that briefly citable and conclusive figures are lacking. Regarding the action of drugs, Kraepelin is inclined to believe that the distinction is, under their influence, almost always rendered more diffi- cult, being only slightly subject to the period of shortened times, while the choice factor very readily becomes shorter than the normal. Marie Walitzkaja finds that the complex re-action times in the insane differ more from the normal than do their simple times. __ An adaptive re-action for the two hands which for the normal required 351-406(7, required 707-9435" in cases of general paralysis, and 1085 ff in a case of mania. These should, however, be regarded as individ- ual rather than general results. The individual variations may be regarded as increasing with the complexity of the re-action. Men differ more from one another in the time

MENTAL PHKNOMKXA. 47

needed for doing difficult things than in the time needed for simple things. Systematic experimentation upon this point is lacking: but a suggestion of the truth may be obtained by calculating the average deviation from their mean, of Mer- kel's ten subjects in their simple re-action times, their sub- jective distinction times, and their adaptive re-action times; the result being 2.23 per cent, 3.35 per cent, and 6.79 per

cent.

Association Times.

While the effect of the association between stimulus and movement upon the time of the re-action has been already discussed, the process of association forms so important a. factor in our mental life, that it requires a more specialized and independent investigation.

(1) Questions ivith but a Single Ansiver. We may view an adaptive re-action under the aspect of a "question and answer;" the stimulus being equivalent to the question, 'What, with regard to certain points, is this impression?" and the answer, whether indicated by a name, or word, or movement, is given in the re-action. Our problem is to in- vestigate the time-relations of these questions and answers, as an index of the readiness of the association between the two. The processes intervening between the appreciation of the question and the formulation of the answer may vary greatly in complexity and character. A common character- istic of the re-actions hitherto regarded consisted in the fact that the material for forming the answer is simply and di- rectly supplied by the stimulus itself: it is in the main a verdict regarding the particular nature of sensation then present. The re-actions to which we now pass all include something more than this; and the formulation of the an- swer involves to a greater or less extent more complicat>-:l forms of mental activity, and depends more or less upon the past experiences, the special habits and tendencies of mind, of the individual.

48 THE TIME -RELATIONS OF

While the line of division between the direct appreciation and the indirect interpretation of a sense-impression cannot be rigidly drawn, and while it is no less difficult to decide what processes are involved in this interpretation and elabo- ration of the sense-impression, yet we may with sufficient precision mark out as the first class of associations (a) those in which a simple act of memory plays the chief role. Thus, when Cattell, instead of naming a picture in his own language (which he does in 545(7), names it in German (in 6940"), the difference in time is needed for calling to mind the German name, and measures the strength of this asso- ciation. Berger's acquaintance with English is less than CattelTs with German, and accordingly with him the differ- ence between naming a picture in the vernacular and in a foreign language is greater (477 ff and 649(7). The transla- tion of a short familiar word from English to German occu- pies Cattell 686(7; from German to English, but 5SO<J; the time for long and less familiar words being much longer. (We may obtain the portion of the time required for the act of translation alone by subtracting from this the time to see and name a word, 428(7.) Such operations as addition and multiplication, when confined to numbers of one place, can hardly be more than acts of memory. Cattell adds such numbers in 336(7; Berger, who is a mathematician, in 221 ff. The former multiplies them in 544^7; the latter, in 389(7. Vmtschgau's three subjects multiply such numbers (though under different conditions) in 233(7. More complicated types of "memory re-actions" have been performed by Cattell and by Miinsterberg. The former determined in separate series the time necessary, when given a city, to name the country in which it was situated (462(7); when given a month, to name the season to which it belongs (310(7), to name the fol- lowing month (389(7), to name the preceding month (832(7); given an author, to name the language in which he wrote (350(7) ; given an eminent man, to name his sphere of activity

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 49

(368(7). Miinsterberg constantly varied the type of question including suck as the above, the position of cities, the quali- ties of objects, the relations of men, and many others, find- ing an average time of 848(7 (average of two subjects). While many of these determinations are doubtless of more individual than general value, we may stop to note a few points that are presumably typical. The re-actions here grouped under one class vary considerably in difficulty, and a few instances may be cited to indicate the range of this variation. In giving a country in which a given city is situated, the shortest time is for Paris (278ff) ; the longest, for Geneva (4850"). In giving the language in which an au- thor wrote, Berger requires least time for Luther (227(7) and Goethe (265(7), most for Bacon (565(7); Cattell, least for Plato (224(7) and Shakspeare (258(7), most for Plautus (478(7). In giving the calling of an eminent man, the least time is required for poets (291(7), the longest for men of science (421(7). Miinsterberg mentions as quickly answered questions (400(7 to 600(7), "On what river is Cologne?" " In what season is June?" "In what continent is India?" as questions requiring a long time (1100(7 -1300(7), "Who is the author of Hamlet?" "What is the color of ice?" "Who was the teacher of Plato?" An influence which we have found of great significance hitherto is equally important here; viz., the foreknowledge of the subject of what is to occur. In Cattell's experiments the general question is vir- tually asked once for the entire series, the special terms be- ing given in each experiment, while in Miinsterberg's results the entire question changes with each observation; and this difference in the expectancy of the subject cannot but be an important factor in the longer times found by the latter. A somewhat different phase of this influence appears in the results of Vintschgau. In multiplying the numbers from 1X1 to 9X9, the smaller number was always announced first. Accordingly, when the first nine was announced, the

50 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

subject practically anticipated the result, and had the prod- uct ready; when eight was announced, he knew that it was one of two results; when seven, one of three; and so on. Accordingly we find these to be the shortest processes (9x9, only 160(5") but there is another factor at work counteract- ing this effect, viz., the familiarity of certain multiplications, making the products by one short, and those by four and five long.

(b) The next type of "question and answer11 will be one in which, in addition to the act of memory, a comparison, or a judgment, is involved. The result of the comparison, thougb not always the same for all individuals (and in this sense the question is not limited to a single answer), will probably always be the same in the same individual. The only experiment of Cattail's that seems properly to belong here is that in which the subject decided which was the greater of two eminent men (558(7). Munsterberg finds the average time for answering a miscellaneous group of such compari- sons 947(7, or 99(7 longer than the process without compari- son: comparisons rapidly made (600(7-800(7) being, "Which has the more agreeable odor, cloves or violets?'' "Who is greater, Virgil or Ovid?" "What is more beautiful, woods or mountain?" and difficult questions (1200(7-1500(7) being, "Which is healthier, swimming or dancing?" "Which do you like better, Goethe's drama or his lyric?" "Which is more difficult, physics or chemistry?" The comparison may be among more than two objects. Thus, in asking which is the finest of Goethe's dramas, the process of formulating the reply may include the calling to mind what the various dramas are, and a choice among them; not, of course, a con- siderate judgment, but the selection, under the necessity of an immediate answer, of one deciding motive. On the other hand, among the several possibilities, a certain one may, by habitual association or for other reasons, have become &o prominent that virtually no comparison ensues; and the

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 51

relatively slight excess in time of this type of association above the former ones (1049<7) suggests that this was often the case. To decide which is the pleasantest odor (rose), or which the most important German river (Rhine), required only between 6000" and 700(7; to decide which was the most difficult Greek author (Pindar), or your favorite French writer (Corneille), from 14000- to 1600(7.

Miinsterberg has ingeniously modified this form of experi- ment to show the influence of the foreknowledge or pre- paredness of the subject. He precedes the asking of the question by a dozen or so words of the category within which the comparison is to be made. Thus, ''Apples, pears, cherries, peaches, plums, grapes, strawberries, dates, figs, raisins: which do you like better, grapes or cherries?" Although the comparison cannot be begun until the last word is heard, still the subject has in a way anticipated the general nature of the question, as well as the scope of the comparison, and has reduced the time considerably (676(7, as compared with 947(7), certainly a striking result.

(2) Questions with More than a Single Answer. In the class of re-actions to which we now pass, the question ad- mits of several answers. The answer at one time may not be the same as at another time; and the determining factors in the particular character of the answer are the peculiar mental habits and tendencies of the individual. The question thus changes from a specific to a general one, the answer being any member of a more or less extended class answering to such and such a description. In some the choice may be somewhat limited. This is true of Cat- telFs experiments in which, given a country, we are to name a city in it (346(7); given a season, to name a month in it (435ff); given a language, to name an author writing in that language (519(?) ; or, given an author, to name any work of his (763(7). In all these cases we are apt to have in mind only a very few prominent instances under each head among

52 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

which individual preference is exercised. In the following series the classes are more general, and accordingly the scope for individual preference much larger: given a general term to name a particular instance under that term (537 ff) ; given a picture to name some detail of it (447 ff) ; given the word instead of the picture, to make a similar association (439(7) ; given the picture or the name to mention some prop- erty of it (372(7 and 337(7) ; given a quality to name an ob- ject to which it can be applied (351(7); given an intransitive verb to find an appropriate subject (527(7), or a transitive verb to find an appropriate object (379<J). Miinsterberg has a series including a miscellaneous collection of such re-ac- tions, and finds a time of 1036(7. Trautscholdt has investi- gated a similar series in which a specific instance of a gen- eral term had to be given, and finds a time of 1020(7 (average of three subjects), 155(7 of which must be deducted to get the pure association time.

Here, again, we may stop to consider a few generalizations which these results seem to sustain. The processes involved vary very considerably in the different experiments. Miin- sterberg cites as quick responses (450(7-600(7) the instancing of ' a German wine (Rudesheimer)," "of a number between ten and four (six),' "of a Greek poet (Homer);" as slow ones (1200(7-1500(7), "a beast of the desert (lion),1' " a French author (Voltaire)." Trautscholdt names " mast "as "a part of a ship" in 391(7, but requires 1899(7 to name "art" as ' an aesthetic activity of man." These differences should ap- pear in the average variations: that is, the average divergence of the re-action times from their mean. When the process is simple and constant, the average variation is small ; when the processes are complicated and variable, the average variation is large. While in simple re-actions it is often less than 10 per cent of the re-action time, it is not infrequently as high as 30 per cent in the re-actions just considered. It may have been noticed that in certain cases the process in (2) was

MENTAL PHENOMENA. 53

the reverse of that in (1). The one was a step from the whole to the part, the general to the special; while the other was from the part to the whole, the special to the general. In CattelTs case 'the former is the longer (433(7 and 374(7). In Trautscholdt's results the conclusion comes out more clearly, the pure association time of an association of part to whole is 608(7; of whole to part, 901<7; of special to general, 754(7; of general to special, 947(7. It is thus easier to refer an individual ohject or quality to its class than to give an instance of a general concept. A similar result (namely, that the bond of association between two concepts is not equally strong in both directions) is derived from observing that it takes longer to recall that May precedes June than that June follows May, longer to go back and find a subject for a verb than to go forward and find an object for it, longer when given a quality to find an object possessing that quality than to recall a quality for an object, and so on.

We may here also conveniently consider the overlapping of mental processes, which we have found takes place when- ever a series of simple processes, or a complex process in- volving many simple ones, is performed. The general truth that the time of a complex mental operation is less than the sum of the times needed for the performance of the separate factors into which the former may be resolved, will be again illustrated. Thus Mtinsterberg finds that it takes 103(7 to name a specific instance of a class (e.g., to name a German river), 992(7 to make a comparison, (e.g.. Which is more im- portant,— this river or that?) but only 1049(7 to decide both questions together (e.g.. Which is the most important German river ?) In this case we clearly recognize that the last pi'ocesses are not the sum of the preceding two, but that the category "most important German river" is already formed in the mind. The following comparisons are more illustrative. Instead of asking first, "Which is the most important German river ?" (1049(7,) and then, " Which lies

54 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

more westerly, -- Berlin, or the Rhine?1' (992(7,) we ask at once, "Which lies more westerly, -- Berlin, or the most important German river ? " and find the time 18550", or 176 ff less than the sum of the two foregoing processes. Similarly, if instead of asking first, "On what river is Cologne situated?" (848 ff,) and then, "Which is more westerly, the Rhine or Berlin ?" (992(7,) we ask at once, "Which is more westerly, Berlin, or the river on which Cologne is situated ? " we find a more remarkable saving of time (1314(7, or 526(7 less than the sum of the two questions). This time was still further reduced to 1149<T when the question was preceded by a list of a dozen cities.

(3) Unlimited Associations. When we pass to the re- action of naming as rapidly as possible any word whatever, that is suggested by a given word, we are drawing entirely upon the natural associative habits of the individual, and accordingly this method has been most useful in studying psychological habits and tendencies. Our present purpose, however, is only with the time-relations of this unrestricted association. This has been the type of association first and most frequently investigated, and it is customary to speak of the " pure association time " as the total time minus the time needed to repeat a word. Thus Miinsterberg repeats a word in 3820", and calls out a word in association with the given word in 896 ff. Trautscholdt, however, who experimented upon Wundt, Stanley Hall, and two other subjects, finds an average time of 1024(7, 727(7 of which is regarded as the pure association time. Galton and others have made esti- mates, by rougher methods, of the rapidity with which trains of ideas pass through the mind, and the result is a rate not differing much in either direction from one associa- tion per second. It will be recognized at once that this pro- cess will be very different in different individuals and with different words. Miinsterberg's shortest association was "gold-silver" (390(7); the longest, "sing-dance," "moun-

MENTAL PHENOMENA. -Vi

tain-level'' (1100(7-14000-). Trautscholdt also found " gold- silver " a very quick re-action (4020-), " storm-wind " (368(7), " duty-right" (415(7). Long re-actions were " God-fearing " (1132(7), "throne-king" (1437(7), " Karl- August" (1662(/). Some interesting inferences result from the consideration of the times of different types of these unrestricted associations Trautscholdt divides these into " word associations," or those suggested hy the word rather than by the thing; "outer associations," or those relating to the sense-qualities of the object; and "inner" or logical associations. The results were 1033;7, 1028(7, 989(7, though this order may be liable to individual differences. Cattell and Berger have also com- pared the re-action times to concrete nouns (374(7, pure asso- ciation time), to less concrete nouns (462(7), to abstract nouns (570(7), and to verbs (501(7), clearly showing that concrete terms are more readily suggestive than abstractions, and concrete objects more so than actions. Trautscholdt finds for associations to concrete nouns, 710(7; to actions, 837(7; to abstractions, 871(7.

Many of the influences to which we found simpler forms of re-action times open, are doubtless true of association times, but the great variability of the latter makes these diffi- cult to establish. The effect of practice is noticed by Traut- scholdt; and Cattell has shown that in students from thirteen to eighteen years of age a distinct shortening of the associa- tion time accompanies growth and education, while the students ranking higher in class have a somewhat shorter time than those standing low in class. Fatigue very readily enters, the accessible associations are easily exhausted, ;m<l the mind repeats itself very markedly. Changes under the action of drugs and in morbid mental states have been inci- dentally noticed, but still await systematic investigation.

The various processes, the times of which we have been studying, by no means exhaust the possibilities in this field. As our knowledge of mental operations becomes more per-

56 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF MENTAL PHENOMENA.

feet and more capable of experimental study, and as our power of analysis makes similar progress, the study of the time-relations of mental phenomena, already fertile in sug- gestions and results, will increase in interest and impor- tance.

BIBLIOGRAPHY.

(This bibliography, though intended to be fairly complete, is by no means exhaustive. It is furthermore Limited to the points discussed in the text, and the classification corresponds in the main with the order of topics in the text. Each article is cited in full under the topic to which it is more especially devoted, and referred to by number under other topics to which it contributes to a greater or less extent. While the general articles are fre- quently cited under the special topics, it will be well to consult them even when not so cited. Specially important articles have their numbers printed in bold type.)

A. GENERAL.

I. Expository.

I. WUNDT. Physiologische Psychologic, 3d ed., 1887, vol. ii. pp. 261-364. 2. SERGI. La Psychologic Physiologique. 1888, pp. 272-296.

3. BUCCOLA. La legge del tempo nei fenomeni del pensiero, 1883. 4. LADD. Elements of Physiological Psychology, 1887, pp. 468-497.

5. KRAEPELIN. BiolofjischesCentralblatt. vol. i. (several articles).

6. KRAEPELIX. Die Neueste Literatur auf dem Gebiete der psychischen

Zeitmessung, Idem, Hi. 53-63.

7. FRICKE. Ueber psychische Zeitmessung, Idem, viii. 673-690; ix. 234-256,

437-448, 467-469. 8. BIBOT. German Psychology of To-day (translation), 1886, pp. 250-287.

9. EXNER. Herrmann's Handbuch der Physiologic, ii. 2, part ii. chap. iv.

pp. 252-283.

ii. Experimental.

10. DONDERS. Die Schnellegkeit Psychischer Processe(DuBois-Reymond^

Archiv, 1868, pp. 657-681).

II. DE JAAGER. De physiologische Tigo bij psychische Processen, Thesis,

1865.

12. KRIES and AUERBACH. Die Zeitdauer einfachster psychische Vor-

gange (Du Bois-Reymond's Archiv, 1877, pp. 297-378).

13. CATTELL. Psychometrische Untersuchungen (Wundfs Studien, iii.

pp. 2, 3; also as thesis, 1886).

14. JASTROW. An Easy Method of Measuring the Time of Mental Processes (Science, Sept. 10, 1886).

B. SIMPLE RE-ACTIONS.

i. General.

15. EXNER. Experimentelle Untersuchungen der einfachsten psychischen

Processe (Pfliif/ci-'x Anitir, vii. 601-060, viii. 520-537, xi. in:! I :.'

57

58 THE TIME-RELATIONS OF

ii. Inertia of Sense-Organs.

16. CATTELL. The Inertia of the Eye and Brain (Brain, 1885).

17. PEEYER. Grenzen des Empfindungsvermogens, etc., 1868.

18. SANFORD. The Relative Legibility of the Small Letters (American

Journal of Psychology, i. pp. 402-436).

19 EUNKEL. Ueber die Abhangigkeit der Farbenempflndung von der Zeit (Pfluger"s Archiv, ix. pp. 197-220).

20. V. WITTICH. Bemerkungen zu Preyer's Abhandlung (Idem, ii. pp. 329-

350).

21. BAXT. Ueber die Zeit, welche nothig ist damit ein Gesichtseindruck

zum Bewusstsein kommt, etc. (Idem, iv. pp 325-336).

22. EXNER. Ueber die zu einer Gesichtswahrnehmung nothige Zeit (Wie-

ner Sitzungsberichte, 58, pp. 601-631). 47.

in. Be actions to Impressions of Sight. 10, 11, 13, 15, 29, 31, 48.

23. VINTSCHGAU and LUSTIG. Zeitmessende Beobachtungen iiber die

Wahrnehinung des sich entwickelnden positiven Nachbildes eines electrischen Funkens (Pfliiger's Archiv, xxxiii. pp. 494-512).

IV. Re-actions to Impressions of Sound. 10, 13, 15, 33, 45, 49.

v. Re-actions to Impressions of Touch.

24. VINTSCHGAU. Die physiologische Reactionszeit und der Ortsinn der

Haut (Pfluger's Archiv, xxii. pp. 87-110). 10, 11, 12, 15, 26, 27, 31, 32, 37.

v. (a) Temperature.

25. GOLDSCHEIDER. Du Bois-Reymond's Archiv, 1887. p. 469.

26. VINTSCHGAU and STEINACH. Zeitmessende Versuche iiber den Tem-

peratur- und Drucksinn (Pfliiger^s Archiv, xliii. pp. 152-195).

vi. Re-actions to Taste.

27. VINTSCHGAU and HONIGSCHMIED. Versuche iiber die Reactionszeit

einer Geschmacksempfindung (Pfl tiger's Archiv, x. pp. 1^18, xiv. pp. 529-592).

vn. 3e actions to Smell.

28. MOLDENHAUER. Ueber die einfache Reactionszeit einer Geruchsem-

pflndung (Wundfs Studien, i. pp. 606-614).

vni. Influence of Intensity of Stimulus.

29. BERGER. Ueber den Einfluss der Reizstiirke auf die Dauer einfacher psychischer Vorgange, etc. (WundVs Studien, iii. pp. 38-93).

30. CATTELL. Influence of the Intensity of the Stimulus on the Length of

the Re-action Time (Brain, 1886, pp. 512-516). 12, 15, 32, 49.

ix. Variation of Stimulus within the Same Sense.

31. HALL and KRIES. Ueber die Abhangigkeit der Reactionszeit, etc. (Du

Bois-Reymond's Archiv, 1879, supplement, pp. 1-10). 2, 10, 11. 12, 15, 20, 24, 25, 26, 27, 28. x. Mode of Re-actions; Analysis of Re-actions.

32. ORCHANSKY (reported by Gad). Du Bois-Reymnnd's Archiv, 1887, p.

369.

10, 13, 15, 24.

xi. Effect of Disturbance, Expectation, Practice, and Fatigue.

11, 12, 13, 34, 35, 49.

MENTAL PHENOMENA. oil

xii. Distinction betireen S'DI.SW// and Motor.

33. LANGE. Neue Experimeute Qber den Vorganjj der eiufarhm Reaction

auf Sinneseindriicke (Wundt's Studien, iv. pp. 479-511;.

34. MARTIUS. Die muskuliire Reaction und die Aufmerksamkeit

(Idem, vi. pp. 167-'-!17). 35. DWELSHAUVERS. Untersuchungen zur Mechanik der activen Auf

merksainkeit (Idem, pp. 217-249). 45.

xni. Individual Variations: Personal Equations.

36. SANFORD. Personal Equation (American Journal of Psycltolor/y, it. pp. 3-38. 271-298, 403-430. Consult bibliography there given for de- tailed references). 15,38.

xiv. Abnormal Variations.

37. DIETL and VINTSCHGAU. Das Verhalten dor pbysiologischen Reac-

tionszeit unter den Einfluss von Morphium, Caffee und Wein (Pfliiger's Archiv, xvi. pp. 316-4061.

38. OBERSTEINER. Experimental Researches on Attention (Brain, i. pp.

439-453).

39. OBERSTEINER. Ueber eine neue einfache Methode zur Bestimmung

des psychischen Leitungsfahigkeit des Gehirns Geisteskranker (Virchow's Archiv, lix. pp. 427^58).

40. KRAEPELIN. Ueber die Einwirkung einiger medicamentoser Stoffe auf die Dauer einfacher psychischer Vorgiinge (Wundt's Studien, i. pp. 417^62, 573-605).

41. WARREN. The Effect of Pure Alcohol on the Re- action Time, etc.

(Journal of Physiology, viii. No. 6, pp. 311-348). 15, 26, 32.

42. STANLEY HALL. Re-action Time in the Hypnotic State (Mind, viii.).

43. JAMES. Re-action Time in the Hypnotic Trance (Proceedings of the

American Society for Psychical Research, i. 3, pp. 246-248). xv. Appliances and Methods.

44. SANFORD. A Simple and Inexpensive Chronoscope (American Journal

of Psychology, iii. pp. 174-182). 1, 11, 13, 14, 39, 41.

C. ADAPTIVE RE-ACTIONS.

(Distinction and Choice.) i. General and Theoretical. 45. MUNSTERBERG. Beitrage zur Experimentellen Psychologic, i. pp. 64-

188. 1, 4,5,6,7,9. 10. I:.'. 13, 4!).

46. KRIES. Ueber Uuterseheidungszeiten (Vierteljahrsschrift fiir wissen-

schaftliche Philosophic, xi. pp. 1-23).

47. CATTELL. Ueber die Zeit der Erkeunung und Benennung von Schrift-

zeichen, Bildern, und Parbeu i M"ini</f .s Studien, ii. 4, pp. 635-650). . n. Effect of Number of Distinctions and of Choices.

48. TIGERSTEDT and BERGQVIST. Zur Kenntniss der Apperceptionsdauer

zusammengesetzter Gesichtsvorstellungen (Zeitschrift fiir Bio- logic. xix. pp. 5-44).

49. TISCHER. Ueber die Unterscheiduug von Schallstiirken (Wundr*

Studien, i. pp. 495-542). 50. MERKEL. Die zeitlichen Verhaltnisse der Willcusthatigkeit (Idem. ii.

PP. 73-127). 1, 10, 13, 14,34.

CO THE TIME-RELATIONS OF MENTAL PHENOMENA.

in. Specific Nature of Impression.

1, 4, 5, 6, 7, 9, 10, 11, 12, 13, 15, 27, 29, 30.

iv. Foreknowledge of Subject.

1, 13, 54.

v. Mode of Re-action: Association of Stimulus and Movement. 13, 34.

vi. Overlapping of Mental Processes: Sensory and Motor Re-actions. 13, 44, 35, 52.

51. PAULHAN. Revue Scientifique, 1887.

VII. Practice and Fatigue.

52. BERGER. Ueber den Einfluss der Uebung auf geistige Processe

(WundVs Studien, v. pp. 170-178). 1, 12, 13, 27, 50.

vni. Miscellaneous and Individual Variations. 1, 9, 13, 39, 40, 49, 50.

D. ASSOCIATION TIMES.

i. General.

53. CATTELL. Experiments on the Association ot Ideas (Mind, xii. pp.

68-74). 1, 4, 45. II. Questions limited to a Single Answer, involving Acts of Memory.

54. VINTSCHGAU. Die physiologische Zeit einer Kopfmultiplication vou

zwei einziffrigen Zahleii (Pliiger's Archiv, xxxvii. pp 187-202).

45, 53. in. Questions limited to a Single Answer, involving Comparison.

45, 53. iv. Questions admitting of Various Answers.

45, 53, 56.

v. Unrestricted Associations.

55. CATTELL and BRYANT. Mental Association investigated by Experiment

(Mind, xiv. pp. 230-250).

56. TRAUTSCHOLDT. Experimentelle Untersuchungen iiber die Associa- tion der Vorstellungen ( Wundfa Studien, i. pp. 213-250). 1, 14, 45. 57. GALTON. Inquiries into Human Faculty, pp. 182-203.

Fact and Theory Papers

THE SUPPRESSION OF CONSUMPTION.

By GODFREY W. HAMBLETON, M.D. 12°. 40c.

"The inestimable importance of the subject, the eminence of the author and the novelty of his work all combine to render the little treatise worthy of special consideration. . . . We heartily com- mend Dr. Hambleton's booklet and wish there were more such works."— Editorial, Boston Daily Adver- tiser.

THE SOCIETY AND THE "FAD."

By APPLETON MORGAN, Esq. 12°. 20 cents.

In this book Mr. Morgan, who is president of the New York Shakespeare Society, sets forth what he believes to be the true function of a Shakespeare Society, which in many respects he makes essen- tially scientific.

PROTOPLASM AND LIFE.

By C. F. Cox. 12°. 75 cents.

The author of this book was for some years presi- dent of the New York Microscopical Society, and in this volume he sets forth his views on the spontane- ous generation theory and its relation to the general theory of evolution, and on protoplasm a,nd the cell doctrine.

THE TORNADO.

By H. A. HAZEN, 12°. $1.

Professor Hazen is one of the prominent meteor- ologists connected with the United States Signal Office. In this work he reviews our present infor- mation as to tornadoes, severely criticising some of the opinions held in regard to them up to this time. No one has given a more careful study to these de- structive storms than has Professor Hazen, and his book will prove a decided contribution to the world's knowledge.

N. D. C. HODGES, 47 Lafayette PL, New York

Fact and Theory Papers

THE CHEROKEES IN PRE-COLUMBIAN TIMES

By CYRUS THOMAS. 12°. $1.

Dr. Thomas in this work will reverse the usual method of dealing with prehistoric subjects ; that is to say, he will commence with the earliest recorded history of the tribe as a basis and trace the chain back step by step by the light of the mounds, tradi- tions, and other evidence, as far as possible. He has already presented to the public some reasons for believing the Cherokees were mound-builders, but additional evidence bearing on the subject has been obtained. A more careful study of the Dela- ware tradition respecting the Tallegwi satisfies him that we have in the Bark Record (Walam Olurn) itself proof that they were Cherokees. He thinks the mounds enable us to trace back their line of migration even beyond their residence in Ohio to the western bank of the Mississippi. The object is therefore threefold: 1. An illustration of the re- verse method of dealing with prehistoric subjects ; 2. Incidental proof that some of the Indians were mound-builders ; 3. A study of a single tribe in the light of the mound testimony. This work will be an important contribution to the literature of the Co- lumbian discovery which will doubtless appear during the coming two years.

THE WINNIPEG COUNTRY;

OR,

ROUGHING IT WITH AN ECLIPSE PARTY.

BY A. KOt HESTER KEM,O\\ .

(S. H. SCUDDER.)

With thirty-two Illustrations and a Map. 12°. $1.50.

"The story is a piquant, good humored, entertain- ing narrative of a canoe voyage A neater, prettier book is seldom seen."— Literary World.

"This is a sprightly narrative of personal inci- dent. The book will be a pleasant reminder to many of rough experiences on a frontier which is rapidly receding."— Boston Transcript.

" The picture of our desolate North-western terri- tory twenty-five years ago, in contrast with its civilized aspect to-day, and the pleasant features of the writer's style, constitute the claims of bis little book to present attention.1'— The Dial.

N, B. C. HODGES, 47 Lafayette PL, New York.

SCIENCE.

I3ST 1S83_

A WEEKLY journal devoted to recording the progress of science and the arts. Among recent contributors may be named: A. Melville Bell, Joseph Jastrow, J. H. Raymond, M.D., G. Stan- ley Hall, R H. Thurston, H. T. Cresson, H. B. Bashore, H. E. Stockbridge, Lieut. Bradley A. Fiske, John T. Stoddard, Charles S. Minot, Jacques W. Redway, Nelson W. Perry, T. Berry Smith, Robert H. Lamborn, Gardiner G. Hubbard. Edgar Richards, H. A. Hazen, Cyrus Thomas, T. C. Chamberlin, A. E. Dolbear, W. M. Davis, L. W. Ledyard, John C Branner, A. T. Drum- mond, G. Brown Goode, Burt G. Wilder, Godfrey W. Hamble- ton, M.D.

Among the subjects discussed may be mentioned : The Sup- pression of Consumption, Cookery for the Poor, Marine Biological Laboratory, Movements in Young Children, The Phonograph in the Study of Indian Languages, Effigy Mounds, Lightning-Dis- charge, Sunspots and Tornadoes, Stanley's Explorations, Pho- netics, The Influence of Baking-Powder Residues on Digestion, Unconscious Bias in Walking, Jade, Clark University, The Influenza, Hallucinations in Alcoholism.

News is promptly given of all new books of importance not fiction.

-

$3.50 per Year ; $i, Trial Subscription for Four Months.

N. D. C. HODGES,

47 Lafayette P1<u*e, - New York.

I

i

.

.

i

.

I

. i .

.

I

' -

-

.

- -

.. 5

.

.

.

I * .

:

-

.

.

. -.

.

. . ..

.

.

.

I

:-,

.

••

'