Skip to main content

Full text of "A treatise on the Augustinian doctrine of predestination"

See other formats


A     TREATISE 


THE    AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE 


PREDESTINATION. 


BY     J.     B.      M  0  Z  L  E  Y,     B.  D. 

FELLOW  OF  MAGDALEN  COLLEGE,  OXFORD. 


LONDON: 

JOHN  MURRAY,  ALBEMARLE  STREET. 
1855. 


LONDON : 

A.  and  O.  A.  SPOTTISWOOOR, 
New-Jtreet-Square. 


CONTENTS. 


CHAPTER  I. 

Page 
Statement  of  the  Argument  for  Predestination         -  1 


CHAPTER  II. 

Examination  of  the  Argument  for  Predestination    -  -17 

CHAPTER  III. 

The. Pelagian  Controversy  -  -  -50 

CHAPTER  IV. 

Different  Interpretations  of  Original  Sin  \  -  -     107 

CHAPTER  V. 

Augustinian  Doctrine  of  Predestination       -  -  -     134 


CHAPTER  VI. 

Augustinian  Doctrine  of  (draco  )     -  -  -     157 


CHAPTER  VII. 
Augustinian  Doctrine  of  Final  Perseverance  }  -     191 


iv  CONTENTS. 

CHAPTER  VIII. 

Page 

Augustinian  Doctrine  of  Freewill  -  209 

CHAPTER  IX. 

Scholastic  Theory  of  Necessity       -  -     250 

CHAPTER  X. 

Scholastic  Doctrine  of  Predestination  -     278 

CHAPTER  XI. 

Conclusion  -  -  -  -     314 


NOTES -  -     343 


THE 

AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE 

OF 

PREDESTINATION, 


CHAPTER  I. 

STATEMENT   OP   THE   ARGUMENT   FOR   PREDESTINATION. 

THE  design  of  this  treatise  is  to  give  an  account  of  S. 
Augustine's  doctrine  of  Predestination,  together  with  such 
comments  as  may  be  necessary  for  a  due  examination  of,  and 
judgment  upon,  it.  Before  entering,  however,  on  S.  Augus- 
tine's statements,  some  general  description  of  the  doctrine 
itself,  its  grounds,  and  its  defences,  will  be  necessary :  and 
these  will  require  special  consideration,  with  a  view  to 
ascertaining  their  soundness  and  validity.  This  introduc- 
tory matter  will  occupy  the  following  chapter,  in  addition  to 
the  present  one,  in  which  I  shall  endeavour  to  give  a  general 
description  of  the  doctrine. 

A  distinction  must,  in  the  first  instance,  be  drawn  between 
the  predestinarian  and  the  necessitarian  or  fatalist.  The  pre- 
destinarian  and  the  fatalist  agree,  indeed,  in  the  facts  of  the 
case,  and  equally  represent  mankind  as  acting  necessarily, 
whether  for  good  or  evil,  in  distinction  to  acting  by  an  origi- 
nal motion  of  the  will.  But  the  fatalist  goes  to  philosophy 
for  the  reason  of  this  state  of  things,  the  predestinarian  to 
a  truth  of  revelation ;  the  former  argues  from  the  nature  of 
things,  the  latter  from  a  particular  fact  of  which  he  has  been 

B 


THE   ARGUMENT 


[CHAP.  I. 


informed  by  competent  authority.  The  fatalist  takes  the 
general  ground  that  every  event  must  have  a  cause  ;  and  ap- 
plying it  to  the  case  of  human  actions,  argues  that  just  as  the 
action  must  have  a  cause,  so  that  cause,  even  if  we  say  it  is  the 
will's  own  choice,  must  have  itself  a  cause ;  this  further  cause 
another  cause.  Being  thus  provided  with  an  unlimited  series 
of  causes  in  the  case  of  every  human  action,  while  the  past 
existence  of  the  agent  is  limited,  he  extends  this  series  back- 
wards till  it  reaches  a  point  at  which  it  goes  outside  of  the 
agent ;  who  is  consequently  proved  to  have  acted  ultimately 
from  causes  over  which  he  had  no  control. 

There  is  another  kind  of  necessitarianism,  again,  which 
takes  for  its  basis,  instead  of  a  physical  assumption,  like  the 
one  just  mentioned,  a  religious  one  —  the  attribute  of  the 
Divine  power ;  and  argues  downwards  from  the  First  Cause, 
instead  of  backwards  from  human  action.  To  the  meta- 
physician who  believes  in  a  Creator  or  First  Cause,  and  who 
contemplates  man  in  relation  to  that  Being,  one  great  and  pri- 
mary difficulty  presents  itself  in  the  question  how  a  being 
can  be  a  creature,  and  yet  have  freewill,  and  be  a  spring  of 
action  to  himself,  a  self- moving  being.  Our  very  notion  of 
cause  and  effect  is  of  the  cause  as  active,  the  effect  as  passive  ; 
and,  therefore,  if  man  is  an  effect,  how  is  he  an  active  being  ? 
A  tool  or  instrument  that  we  make,  issues  inert  out  of  our 
hands,  and  only  capable  of  that  motion  which  the  maker  of 
it  gives  it.  To  make  a  machine  is  to  cause  the  whole  series 
of  motions  which  it  performs.  Our  idea  of  creation  is  thus  at 
variance  with  the  idea  of  free  agency  in  the  thing  made.  Man 
as  a  self-moving  being  and  the  originator  of  his  own  acts,  is  a 
first  cause  in  nature  ;  but  how  can  we  acknowledge  a  second 
first  cause  —  a  first  cause  which  is  an  effect,  a  created  origi- 
nality ?  l 

Of  course  the  fact  of  moral  evil  is  at  once  an  answer 


1  If  man  be  a  self-determining  agent, 
will  it  not  necessarily  follow,  that  there 
are  as  many  First  Causes  (».  e.  in  other 
words,  as  many  Gods)  as  there  are 


men  in  the  world  ?  —  Toplady,  vol.  vi. 
p.  31.  If  I  am  an  independent  animal, 
I  am  also  necessarily  self-existent.  —  p. 
45. 


CHAP.  I.] 


FOR   PREDESTINATION. 


to  this  line  of  argument ;  so  far,  at  any  rate,  as  to  disprove 
the  cogency  and  decisiveness  of  it.  For  unless  we  make 
God  the  author  of  evil,  moral  evil  must  be  referred  to 
some  original  source  other  than  God;  in  which  case 
the  attribute  of  the  Divine  omnipotence  is  seen  to  meet 
in  the  first  instance  with  something  counter  to  it ;  and  so 
cannot  be  argued  upon  as  if  it  were  the  whole  of  the  truth  in 
the  question  under  consideration  But  so  far  as  we  attend 
to  this  attribute  exclusively,  as  is  the  fault  with  some 
schools,  this  is  the  natural  argument  from  it. 

The  necessitarian  thus  believes  freewill  not  only  to  be 
false,  but  to  be  impossible.  On  the  other  hand,  the  pre- 
destinarian  cannot  believe  it  to  be  impossible,  because  he 
admits,  on  the  authority  of  Scripture,  that  the  first  man 
Adam,  in  the  state  in  which  he  was  created,  had  it.1  He 
only  believes  that  man  has  since  the  fall  been  deprived 
of  it,  and  regards  it  as  an  historical  fact,  not  an  existing 
one.  He  is  thus  excluded,  on  this  question,  from  the 
ground  of  philosophy,  from  the  perfect  and  consistent  theory 
of  the  fatalist,  and  draws  his  conclusion  from  the  revealed 
doctrine  of  the  fall. 

But  though  predestinarians,  as  such,  draw  their  conclusion 
from  the  particular  sin  of  Adam,  such  a  ground  is  so  unsa- 
tisfactory to  a  philosophical  mind,  that  few  have,  in  fact, 
confined  themselves  to  it.  Some  have  dispensed  with  it 
altogether,  and  adopted  the  philosophy  either  of  causes2, 


1  Augustine  endows  Adam  With  free- 
will :  « Potuit  non  peccare  primus 
homo,  potuit  non  mori,  potuit  bonum 
non  deserere.  Nunquid  dicturi  sumus 
non  potuit  peccare  qui  tale  habebat  li- 
berum  arbitrium." — De.  Corr.  et  Grat. 
c.  12.  "Homo  male  utens  libero  ar- 
bitrio  et  se  perdidit  et  ipsum."  Ench. 
c.  30.  Lombard  (L.  2.  Distinct  24.  1.), 
Gotteschalus  (Usher,  p.  29.),  and 
Calvin,  follow  Augustine  :  "  In  his 
praeclaris  dotibus  excelluit  prima  ho- 
minis  conditio.  ...  In  hac  integri- 
tate  libero  arbitrio  pollebat  homo."  — 


Instit.  1.  1.  c.  15.  Though  the  latter 
afterwards  calls  the  notion  of  Adam's 
freewill  "frigidum  commentum,"  and 
asks  why  he  should  not  have  been  the 
subject  of  a  decree,  as  his  posterity 
were  :  "  Atqui  predestinatio  velint, 
nolint,  in  posteris  se  profert.  Neque 
enim  factum  est  naturaliter  ut  a  salute 
exciderent  omnes  unius  parentis  culpa. 
Quid  eos  prohibet  fateri  de  uno  homine 
quod  inviti  de  toto  humano  genere 
concedunt.r—  Instit.  1.  3.  c.  23. 

2  Edwards,  On  the  Freedom  of  the 
Will. 


B   2 


THE    ARGUMENT 


[CHAP.  I. 


or  of  the  Divine  power  :  the  latter  being  the  ground  of  the 
supralapsarian,  who  asks  how  such  a  universal  effect  could 
follow  from  a  particular  sin,  except  by  the  will  of  God 
ordaining  it  so,  and  so  pushes  back  the  ground  of  fact  imme- 
diately to  one  of  philosophical  principle.1  Others  have  not 
without  detriment  to  their  consistency  as  reasoners  mixed 
the  two  grounds.  The  ground  which  S.  Augustine  adopted 
and  which  the  Jansenists  revived,  was  in  the  main  that 
of  Scripture,  though  the  former  joined  to  it  occasionally 
that  of  philosophy l :  the  medieval  predestinarians  took 
in  the  main  the  ground  of  philosophy,  mixing  with  it 
occasionally  that  of  Scripture.  The  theory  of  necessity 
last  described,  was  adopted  under  the  name  of  ee  the  physical, 
predetermination  of  the  will "  by  this  medieval  school 2, 
who  maintained  that  there  could  be  but  one  true  cause 
of  every  event,  all  other  causes  being  secondary  and  inter- 
mediate ;  and  applying  it  to  the  case  of  human  actions,  ex- 
plained that  though  they  had  a  "  voluntary  cause,"  or  a  cause 
in  the  human  will,  this  was  only  secondary  and  intermediate 
between  the  agent  and  the  first  cause;  protecting  this 
position  from  the  consequence  which  it  apparently  in- 
volved in  the  case  of  evil  actions,  that  God  was  the  author 
of  evil,  by  distinctions  which  it  is  not  necessary  here  to 
state;  yet  the  same  writers  referred  to  the  fact  of  the 
fall  as  the  ground  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination.3 
Predestinarian  preachers,  again,  guided  half  by  sentiment 


1  NOTE  L 

At  qui  omnium  connexionem  rerum- 
que  causarum  qua  fit  omne  quod  fit, 
fati  nomine  appellant ;  non  multum  cum 
iis  de  verbi  controversia  certandum 
atque  laborandum  est,  quandoquidem 
ipsam  causarum  ordinem  et  quandam 
connexionem,  summi  Dei  tribuunt  vo- 
luntati.— De  Civit.  Dei,  1.  5.  c.  8. 

2  Jansen   draws  the   distinction  be- 
tween the  theory  of  the  "  predeternii- 
natio  physica  "  of  the  will  «'  ex  philoso- 
phia  profecta,"  and  which  "  defenditur 
a  sectatoribus  sancti  Thomae,"  and  the 


predestinarian  doctrine  of  efficacious 
grace,  which  rests  upon  original  sin. 
"  Predeterminatio  physica  necessaria 
statuitur  omnibus  agentibus  ex  vi  causae 
secundse  quae  essentialiter  tarn  in  operari 
quam  in  esse  suo  subordinatur  primae,  a 
qua  ad  agendum  praemoveri  debet ; 
Christi  adjutorium  nequaquam  sed  laesae 
voluntati  propter  solum  vulnus  necessa- 
rium  est. —  De  Grat.  Christi  Salvatoris, 
1.  8.  c.  1,  2. 

3  Ratio    reprobationis   est    originale 
peccatum.     Aquinas,  vol.  viii.  p.  330. 


CHAP.  I.]  FOtt    PREDESTINATION.  5 

and  half  by  theory,  are  accustomed,  though  using  the 
scriptural  ground  as  their  basis  on  this  question,  to 
speak  of  the  doctrine  of  freewill  as  an  insult  to  the 
Divine  Power,  which  is  to  mix  the  two  grounds ;  for 
while  the  scriptural  ground  is  one  of  fact,  the  argument 
of  the  Divine  power  is  an  abstract  argument. 

Assuming,  however,  the  doctrine  of  the  fall  or  original 
sin  as  the  proper  ground  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination, 
how,  it  will  be  asked,  is  the  one  doctrine  the  reason  and 
basis  of  the  other  ?  In  the  following  way. 

The  doctrine  of  original  sin  represents  the  whole  human 
race  as  in  a  state  of  moral  ruin  in  consequence  of  the  trans- 
gression of  the  first  man,  incapable  of  doing  anything  pleasing 
and  acceptable  to  God,  or  performing  any  really  good  act 1 ; 
that  is  to  say,  it  represents  the  human  race  as  without 
freewill.  And  such  being  the  condition  of  man,  the  Divine 
mercy  determines  on  his  rescue  out  of  it,  on  raising  him 
from  a  state  of  ruin  to  a  state  of  salvation.  But  how 
can  the  rescue  of  a  ruined  and  powerless  being  be  effected 
except  by  an  absolute  act  of  power  on  the  part  of  the 
Deliverer  ?  The  subject  of  this  rescue  is  supposed  to 
be  unable  to  do  anything  for  himself;  and  therefore,  if  he  is 
saved  at  all,  he  must  be  saved  without  any  waiting  for 
or  depending  upon  his  own  individual  agency.2  It  may 
perhaps  be  replied  that,  as  God  endowed  man  with  free- 
will, or  the  power  to  act  aright,  as  distinguished  from 
a  necessary  virtue,  at  the  creation ;  so  when  he  raises  him 
out  of  this  state  of  ruin  and  slavery  of  the  will,  he  may  endow 
him  again  with  freewill  only,  leaving  the  use  which  he 


1  We  have  no  power  to  do  good  works 
pleasant  and  acceptable  to  God,  without 
the  grace  of  God  by  Christ  preventing 
us.  —  Art.  x.     Works  done  before    the 
grace  of  Christ  are  not  pleasant  to  God, 
.  .  .    rather  we  doubt  not   but   they 
have  the  nature  of  sin.— Art.  xiii. 

2  So  totally  are  we  fallen  by  nature, 


towards  our  own  recovery.  Hence  it 
was  God's  own  arm  which  brought  salva- 
tion  Conversion  is  a  new  birth, 

and  resurrection  a  new  creation.  What 
infant  ever  begat  itself?  What  in- 
animate carcase  ever  quickened  and 
raised  itself?  What  creature  ever 
created  itself?  —  Toplady,  vol.  iiL  p. 


that   we   cannot   contribute    anything    j    363. 

B    3 


6  THE   ARGUMENT  [CHAP.  I. 

may  make  of  it  to  himself,  as  before.  It  may 
be  said  that  this  would  be  a  true  act  of  grace  or  favour 
on  the  part  of  God,  and  therefore  that  we  need  not 
suppose  that  in  the  act  of  delivering  man  out  of  the 
wretched  and  impotent  state  in  which  he  is  by  nature, 
God  does  anything  more  than  this.  But  though  such  a 
mode  of  acting  on  God's  part  does  not  involve  any  positive 
contradiction,  it  must  be  allowed  to  be  at  variance  with  our 
reasonable  notions  of  the  Divine  dealings ;  for  what  is  this 
but  to  institute  the  first  dispensation  over  again,  and  repeat 
a  trial  which  has  been  undergone  once,  and  had  its  issue  ? 
Suppose  a  man  carried  away  by  a  torrent,  to  master  which 
he  had  proved  himself  unequal,  would  it  be  a  reasonable 
or  consistent  act  to  take  him  out  only  to  recruit  his  strength 
for  a  second  resistance  to  it  ?  So,  after  man  in  the  exercise 
of  freewill  has  fallen  and  lost  freewill,  is  it  not  a  mockery 
to  save  him  by  giving  him  freewill  again?  What  will 
he  do  with  the  gift,  but  fall  again  ?  On  such  a  mode  of 
Divine  dealing,  the  fall  may  be  repeated  indefinitely,  and 
the  Divine  purposes  for  the  salvation  of  man  may  remain 
in  perpetual  suspense,  and  never  attain  completion. 

The  principle,  then,  being  acknowledged  that  God  does 
not  repeat  His  dispensations,  it  follows  that  a  second  dispen- 
sation cannot  be  the  first  one  a  second  time  instituted,  but 
must  be  a  different  one  in  itself;  divided  substantially  from 
the  old  one  in  the  nature,  character,  and  effect  of  the  aid 
which  it  supplies  to  man  for  attaining  salvation.  A  dis- 
pensation which  left  the  salvation  of  man  dependent  on  his 
will,  was  highly  suitable  as  a  first  one ;  suitable  alike  to  the 
justice  of  the  Creator  and  the  powers  of  the  untried  creature, 
and  such  as  we  should  naturally  expect  at  the  beginning  of 
things:  but  such  having  been  the  nature  of  the  first,  the 
second  must,  for  that  very  reason,  be  a  dispensation  of  a  dif- 
ferent kind,  effecting  its  design  not  by  a  conditional,  but 
by  an  absolute  saving  act. 

And  independently  of  all  reasoning,  the  fact  is  plain  from 


CHAP.  I.]  FOB   PREDESTINATION.  7 

Scripture  that  the  new  dispensation  differs  substantially 
from  the  old  in  the  nature  of  the  aid  which  it  supplies  to  man 
for  attaining  salvation.  God  is  not  represented  in  Scripture 
as  repeating  his  dispensations,  but  as  altering  them  according 
to  the  wants  of  man.  The  Gospel  aid  to  salvation,  then,  is, 
in  accordance  with  the  fundamental  difference  in  man's  own 
state,  fundamentally  different  from  that  which  man  had  before 
the  fall ;  and  if  fundamentally  different,  different  in  the  way 
which  has  been  just  mentioned.  For  whatever  peculiari- 
ties of  the  second  dispensation  may  be  appealed  to,  if  the 
grace  of  it  depends  on  the  human  will  for  its  use  and  im- 
provement, it  is  fundamentally  a  dispensation  of  freewill  like 
the  first  one. 

The  Divine  act,  then,  in  the  salvation  of  man  being,  as  the 
result  of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  an  absolute  one,  effecting 
its  purpose  with  infallible  certainty,  the  rest  of  the  doctrine 
of  predestination  follows  upon  ordinary  Christian  grounds. 
It  is  confessed  by  all  that,  whatever  God  does,  He  determines 
or  decrees  to  do  from  all  eternity ;  for  no  one  who  believes 
properly  in  a  God  at  all,  can  suppose  that  He  does  anything 
on  a  sudden,  and  which  He  has  not  thought  of  before.  There 
is,  therefore,  a  Divine  decree  from  all  eternity  to  confer  this 
certain  salvation  upon  those  on  whom  it  is  conferred.  And, 
again,  it  is  universally  admitted  that  only  a  portion  of 
mankind  are  saved.  But  these  two  admissions  complete  the 
doctrine  of  predestination  which  is,  that  God  has  decreed 
from  all  eternity  to  save  by  His  absolute  and  sovereign  power 
a  select  portion  of  mankind,  leaving  the  rest  in  their  previous 
state  of  ruin. 

The  doctrine  of  predestination  being  thus  reduced,  as  its 
essence  or  distinctive  part,  to  an  absolute  saving  act  on  the 
part  of  God  of  which  man  is  the  subject,  we  have  next  to 
consider  the  particular  nature  and  character  of  this  act.  The 
doctrine  of  predestination,  then,  while  it  represents  God  as 
deciding  arbitrarily  whom  He  saves,  and  whom  He  leaves  for 
punishment,  does  not  by  any  means  alter  the  conditions  on 

B    4 


THE   AKGUMENT 


[CHAP.  I. 


which  these  respective  ends  are  awarded.  His  government 
still  continues  moral  —  pledged  to  the  reward  of  virtue  and 
punishment  of  vice.  It  follows  that  in  ordaining  those  whom 
He  does  ordain  to  eternal  life,  God  decrees  also  that  they 
should  possess  the  qualifications  necessary  for  that  state  — 
those  of  virtue  and  piety.1  And  if  God  decrees  that 
particular  persons  shall  be  virtuous  and  pious  men,  He  ne- 
cessarily resolves  to  bestow  some  grace  upon  them  which  will 
control  their  wills  and  insure  this  result.  There  are  two 
main  kinds  of  grace  laid  down  in  the  schemes  of  divines, 
one,  assisting  grace,  which  depends  on  an  original  act  of  the 
human  will  for  its  use  and  cultivation,  and  which  was  therefore 
conferred  on  man  at  his  creation  when  the  power  of  his  will 
had  not  been  as  yet  tried  ;  the  other,  effective  or  irresistible 
grace,  given  when  that  will  has  been  tried  and  failed,  and 
must  have  its  want  of  internal  strength  supplied  by  con- 
trol from  without.  The  Divine  saving  act  is  the  bestowal  of 
this  irresistible  grace.  The  subject  of  the  Divine  predesti- 
nation is  rescued  by  an  act  of  absolute  power  from  the 
dominion  of  sin,  dragged  from  it,  as  it  were,  by  force,  con- 
verted, filled  with  the  love  of  God  and  his  neighbour,  and 
qualified  infallibly  for  a  state  of  ultimate  reward. 

Here,  then,  it  must  be  observed,  is  the  real  essence  and 
substance  of  the  doctrine  of  Predestination,  Predestinarians 
do  not  differ  from  their  opponents  in  the  idea  of  eternal 
Divine  decrees,  which,  though  popularly  connected  with  this 
system  more  than  with  others,  belongs  in  truth  to  all  theolo- 
gical systems  alike.  For  the  believer  in  freewill,  who  only 
admits  an  assisting  grace  of  God,  and  not  a  controlling  one, 
must  still  believe  that  God  determined  to  give  that  assisting 
grace,  in  whatsoever  instances  he  does  give  it,  from  all  eternity. 
Nor  do  they  differ  from  their  opponents  in  the  ground  or 


1  They  who  are  predestinated  to  life 
are  likewise  predestinated  to  all  those 
means  which  are  indispensably  necessary 
in  order  to  their  meetness,  entrance 
upon,  and  enjoyment  of  that  life,  such 


as  repentance,  faith,  sanctification,  and 
perseverance  unto  the  end. — Toplady, 
vol.  v.  p.  251.  Jackson  mistakes  the 
preflestinarian  position  on  this  head. — 
NOTE  II. 


CHAP.  I.] 


FOE   PREDESTINATION. 


9 


reason  of  God's  final  judgment  and  dispensing  of  reward  and 
punishment l ;  for  this  takes  place  in  both  schemes  wholly 
upon  the  moral  ground  of  the  individual's  good  or  bad  cha- 
racter. But  the  difference  between  the  predestinarians  and 
their  opponents  is  as  to  that  act  which  is  the  subject  matter  of 
the  Divine  decree,  and  as  to  the  mode  in  which  this  differ- 
ence of  moral  character  is  produced  ;  that  is  to  say,  the  two 
schools  differ  as  to  the  nature,  quality,  and  power  of  Divine 
grace  under  the  Gospel;  one  school  maintaining  that  that 
grace  is  only  assisting  grace,  depending  on  the  human  will 
for  its  use  and  improvement ;  the  other,  that  it  is  irresistible 
grace.  To  the  former  school  belong  those  who  hold  one  in- 
terpretation of  the  doctrine  of  baptismal  regeneration ;  who 
maintain  the  sacrament  of  baptism  to  be  the  medium  by  which 
the  power  of  living  a  holy  life  is  imparted  to  the  previously 
corrupt  and  impotent  soul ;  which  power,  however,  may  be 
used  or  neglected  according  to  the  individual's  own  choice. 

The  mode  in  which  the  doctrine  of  predestination  is  ex- 
tracted from  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  being  thus  shown, 
it  may  be  added  that,  by  thus  reducing  as  we  have  done  the 
former  doctrine  to  its  pith  and  substance,  we  evidently  much 
widen  the  Scripture  argument  for  it,  extending  it  at  once 
from  those  few  and  scattered  passages  where  the  word  itself 
occurs,  to  a  whole  field  of  language.  The  whole  Scripture 
doctrine  of  grace  is  now  appealed  to  as  being  in  substance 
the  doctrine  of  predestination,  because  there,  is  only  the 
Divine  foreknowledge  to  be  added  to  it,  in  order  to  make  it 
such.  Scripture  distinguishes  in  the  most  marked  way  be- 
tween two  covenants.  The  first  was  that  under  which  man- 
kind was  created,  and  which  ended  at  the  fall.  Its  language 
was — This  do,  and  thou  shalt  live.  It  endowed  man  with 
freewill,  or  the  power  to  obey  the  Divine  law,  and  in  return 
claimed  the  due  use  of  this  power  from  him,  the  proper  exer- 


1  Vita  scterna  .  .  .  gratia  nuncu- 
patur  non  ob  aliud  nisi  quod  gratis 
datur,  nee  ideo  quia  non  meritis  datur 


.  .  .  Justitia)  quidem  stipendium  est, 
sed  tibi  gratia  est,  cui  gratia  est  et  ipsa 
justitia.  — Aug.  Ep.  194.  n.  19.  21. 


10 


THE   ARGUMENT 


[CHAP.  I. 


tion  of  that  freewill.  The  burden  of  obedience,  the  attain- 
ment of  salvation,  was  thrown  upon  the  man  himself.  And 
of  this  covenant  the  Mosaic  law  was  a  kind  of  re-enactment ; 
not  that  the  law  was  really  a  continuation  of  it,  but  it  was  so 
by  a  supposition,  or  as  it  may  be  called  an  instructive  fiction, 
maintained  for  the  purpose  of  exhibiting  and  proving  the 
consequences  of  the  fall.  Man  was  addressed  under  the 
Mosaic  law,  as  if  he  had  the  full  power  to  love  and  obey  God, 
and  the  issue  of  the  attempt  showed  his  inability ;  he  was 
addressed  as  if  he  was  strong,  and  the  event  proved  his 
weakness.  This  was  the  covenant  of  works.  The  covenant 
of  grace  was  opposed  to  it.  But  how  could  it  be  op- 
posed to  it,  if  under  that  covenant  the  salvation  of  man 
still  continued,  as  before,  dependent  on  his  freewill?  If 
it  be  said  that  there  was  the  addition  of  grace  under  the 
second  covenant,  given  besides  and  for  the  support  of 
freewill,  and  that  this  addition  makes  the  distinction  between 
the  two  covenants,  the  reply  is  obvious,  that  whatever  ad- 
dition of  grace  there  may  be  under  the  second,  no  substantial 
difference  is  made  out  so  long  as  the  use  of  this  grace 
remains  dependent  on  the  will.  The  burden  of  obedience  is 
still  thrown  on  the  man  himself  in  the  first  instance,  and  his 
salvation  depends  on  an  original  act  of  choice,  as  it  did  under 
the  first.  Moreover,  it  has  been  always  held  that  man  had 
grace  in  addition  to  freewill,  even  under  the  first  covenant.1 


1  Bull  «  On  the  State  of  Man  before 
the  Fall,"  gives  this  as  the  doctrine  of 
all  the  early  Fathers, 

Nam  et  tune  (cum  natura  erat  Integra 
et  sana)  esset  adjutorium  Dei  et  tan- 
quam  lumen  sanis  oculis  quo  adjuti 
videant,  se  prceberet  volentibus. — Aug. 
De  Natura  et  Gratia,  c.  48. 

Quod  fuerit  conditus  in  gratia  vide- 
tur  requirere  ipsa  rectitude  primi  status 
in  qua  Deus  homines  fecit — Aquinas 
Summ.  Theol.  Prima  Q.  95.  Art.  1.  See 
NOTE  III. 

Hoc  autem  (the  need  of  grace), 
nedum  est  verum  propter  depressionem 
liberi  arbitrii  per  peccatum,  verum  etiam 
propter  gravedinem  liberi  arbitrii  natu- 


ralem'qua  ad  principaliter  diligendum  se 
alligatur. — Bradwardine,  p.  371. 

Homini  in  creatione,  sicut  de  angelis 
diximus,  datum  est  per  gratiam  auxi- 
lium  ....  Non  talis  natura  facta  est 
ut  sine  Divino  auxilio  posset  manere  si 
vellet." — Lombard,  L.  2.  Dis.  24. 

Jackson  objects  to  a  supernatural 
original  righteousness,  on  the  ground 
that  nature  would  not  be  corrupt  by 
the  loss  of  it.  "  If  the  righteousness  of 
the  first  man  did  consist  in  a  grace 
supernatural,  or  in  any  quality  addi- 
tional to  his  constitution,  as  he  was  the 
work  of  God,  this  grace  or  quality 
might  have  been,  or  rather  was,  lost, 
without  any  real  wound  unto  our  na- 
ture."— Works,  vol.  ix.  p.  6. 


CHAP.  I.] 


FOR   PREDESTINATION. 


11 


Then  in  what  are  the  two  opposed,  except  in  the  nature, 
quality,  and  power  of  that  grace  which  they  respectively 
confer,  that  in  the  one  grace  was,  and  in  the  other  is  not, 
dependent  on  any  original  motion  of  the  will  for  its  effect  ? 
The  grace  of  the  gospel  isues  in  being  an  effective  and  irre- 
sistible grace,  converting  the  will  itself,  and  forming  the  holy 
character  in  the  man  by  a  process  of  absolute  creation  ;  accord- 
ing to  such  texts  as  the  following ;  "  We  are  his  workman- 
ship, created  in  Jesus  Christ  unto  good  works,  which  God 
hath  before  ordained  that  we  should  walk  in  them  1 ;  "  "  It  is 
God  that  worketh  in  us  both  to  will  and  to  do  of  his  good 
pleasure  2 ;  "  "  According  as  God  hath  dealt  to  every  man 
the  measure  of  faith  3  ;  "  "  Who  maketh  thee  to  differ  from 
another?  and  what  hast  thou  which  thou  hast  not  received?"4 
"  No  man  can  come  to  me,  except  the  Father  which  hath 
sent  me,  draw  him  5 ; "  "  Who  hath  saved  us,  and  called  us 
with  an  holy  calling,  not  according  to  our  works  but  accord- 
ing to  his  own  purpose  and  grace,  which  was  given  to  us 
in  Jesus  Christ  before  the  world  began  6;  "  "  By  grace,  ye  are 
saved  through  faith ;  and  that  not  of  yourselves,  it  is  the  gift 


of  God 


7  .  » 


By  the  grace  of  God  I  am  what  I  am 8 ;  "  "Of 


him  are  ye  in  Jesus  Christ,  who  of  God  is  made  unto  us 
wisdom,  and  righteousness,  and  sanctification,  and  redemp- 
tion 9 ;  "  "  If  any  man  be  in  Christ,  he  is  a  new  creature  10 ;  " 
"And  I  will  give  them  one  heart,  and  I  will  put  a  new 
spirit  within  you ;  and  I  will  take  away  the  stony  heart  out  of 
their  flesh,  and  will  give  them  a  heart  of  flesh."  n  The 
ground  of  Scripture  for  the  doctrine  of  predestination  thus 
becomes  a  large  and  general  one,  consisting  of  a  certain 
pervading  language,  instead  of  being  confined  to  a  few  texts 
in  which  the  word  itself  is  mentioned,  and  which  are  po- 
pularly regarded  as  its  ground  ;  and  the  doctrine  appears  to 


1  Eph.  ii.  10. 

2  Phil.  ii.  13. 

3  Rom.  xii.  3. 


4  1  Cor.  iv.  7. 

5  John  vi.  44. 

6  2  Tim.  i.  9. 


7  Eph.  ii.  8,  9. 

8  1  Cor.  xv.  10. 

9  1  Cor.  i.  30. 


10  2  Cor.  v.  1 7. 
"Ezek.  xi.  19- 


12  THE   ARGUMENT  [CHAP.  I. 

be  no  more  than  the  gospel  doctrine  of  grace,  wth  the  addi- 
tion of  the  Divine  foreknowledge. 

From  the  basis  and  structure  of  the  doctrine  of  predesti- 
nation, I  now  come  to  its  defences.  An  arbitrary  decree 
ordaining  from  all  eternity,  and  antecedently  to  any  dif- 
ference of  desert,  some  of  the  human  race  to  eternal  life, 
and  others  to  eternal  punishment,  is  in  direct  opposition 
to  our  natural  idea  of  justice,  and  plainly  requires  a  defence. 
And  the  defence  given  for  it  rests  on  the  same  article  of  belief 
out  of  which  the  structure  of  the  doctrine  arose — the  article, 
viz.,  of  original  sin. 

It  is  true,  then,  predestinarians  say,  that  we  do  maintain 
an  arbitrary  decree,  ordaining,  antecedently  to  any  difference 
of  desert,  the  eternal  salvation  of  some  and  punishment  of 
others  of  the  human  race :  but  remember  in  what  state  this 
decree  finds  the  human  race.  It  finds  the  whole  of  the 
human  race  deserving  of  eternal  punishment.  This  decree, 
then,  does  indeed  confer  gratuitous  and  undeserved  happiness 
upon  one  portion  of  mankind ;  and  to  that  nobody  will  have 
any  objection;  for  it  would  indeed  be  a  rigorous  justice 
which  objected  to  an  excess  of  Divine  love  and  bounty  :  but 
it  does  not  do  that  which  alone  could  be  made  matter  of 
accusation  against  it,  inflict  gratuitous  and  undeserved  misery 
upon  the  other.  It  simply  allows  the  evil  which  it  already 
finds  in  them  to  go  on  and  produce  its  natural  fruits.  Had 
this  decree,  indeed,  to  do  with  mankind  simply  as  mankind, 
it  could  not  without  injustice  devote  any  portion  of  them 
arbitrarily  to  eternal  punishment :  for  man  has  not,  as  man, 
any  guilt  at  all,  and  some  guilt  is  required  to  make  his 
punishment  just.  But  this  decree  has  not  to  do  with 
human  nature  simply,  but  with  human  nature  under  certain 
circumstances.  Mankind  are  brought  into  a  particular 
position  before  it  deals  with  them.  That  position  is  the 
position  of  guilt  in  which  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  places 
them.  Viewed  through  the  medium  of  that  doctrine,  the 


CHAP.  I.] 


FOR    PREDESTINATION. 


13 


whole  human  race  lies  before  us,  prior  to  the  action  of  this 
decree  upon  them,  one  mass  of  perdition.  This  decree  only 
allows  a  portion  to  remain  such.  Viewed  through  that  me- 
dium, all  are  under  one  sentence  of  condemnation :  this  decree 
only  executes  this  sentence  upon  some.  But  if  it  would  be 
just  to  punish  the  whole,  it  cannot  be  unjust  to  punish  a 
part.  If  two  men  owe  us  debts,  we  may  certainly  sue  one. 
If  all  antecedently  deserve  eternal  punishment,  it  cannot  be 
unjust  that  some  should  be  antecedently  consigned  to  it. 
Or  would  we  fall  into  the  singular  contradiction  of  saying 
that  a  sentence  is  just,  and  yet  all  execution  of  it  whatever 
unjust? 

The  question  of  justice,  then,  is  already  settled,  when 
man  first  comes  under  this  decree ;  and  the  question  which 
is  settled  by  it  is  not  one  of  justice  at  all,  but  one  of  Divine 
arrangement  simply.  The  same  human  mass  which,  if 
innocent,  would  have  been  the  subject  of  God's  justice, 
becomes,  when  guilty,  the  subject  of  His  will  solely.  His 
absolute  sovereignty  now  comes  in,  and  He  hath  mercy  upon 
whom  He  will  have  mercy,  and  whom  He  will  he  hardeneth. 
"  Hath  not  the  potter  power  over  the  same  lump  to  make 
one  vessel  to  honour,  and  another  to  dishonour  ?  "  Are  we 
to  complain  of  God's  justice  in  some  cases,  because  He  shows 
mercy  in  others?  To  do  so  would  be  for  the  creature  to 
dictate  to  the  Creator.  Man,  guilty,  has  lost  his  rights,  and 
falls  under  the  jurisdiction  of  God's  absolute  and  sovereign 
will,  with  which  remonstrance  is  ridiculous.1 


1  Hie  si  dixerimus  quanto  melius 
ambo  liberarentur ;  nihil  nobis  conve- 
nientius  dicetur  quam,  O  homo,  tu  quis 
es  qui  respondeas  Deo  ?  Novit  quippe 
ille  quid  agat,  et  quantus  numerus  esse 
debeat  primitus  omnium  hominum, 
deinde  sanctorum,  sicut  siderum,  sicut 
angelorura,  atque,  ut  de  terrenis  lo- 
quamur,  sicut  pecorum,  piscium,  vola- 
tilium,  sicut  arborum  et  herbarum, 
sicut  denique  foliorum  et  capillorum 
nostrorum.  Nam  nos  huraana  cogita- 


tione  adhuc  possumus  dicere,  quo- 
niam  bona  sunt  cuncta  ista  quae  fecit, 
quanto  melius  ilia  duplicasset,  et  mul- 
tiplicasset,  ut  multo  essent  plura  quam 
sunt ;  si  enim  ea  non  caperet  mundus 
nunquid  uon  posset  etiam  ipsum  facere 
quantum  vellet  ampliorem  ?  Et  tamen 
quantumcunque  faceret  vel  ilia  plura, 
vel  istum  capaciorem  et  majorem,  nihil- 
ominus  eadem  de  multiplicandis  illis 
dici  possent,  et  nullus  esset  immoderatus 
|  modus. — Aug.  Ep.  186.  n.  22. 


14  THE   ARGUMENT  [CHAP.  I. 

Such  is  the  defence  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination  on 
the  score  of  justice.  Absolutely,  or  apart  from  any  previous 
supposition,  it  is  admitted  to  be  unjust ;  but  the  defence  is 
that  it  must  not  be  considered  absolutely,  but  in  its  real  and 
intrinsic  relation  to  another  doctrine,  which  in  theological 
order  precedes  it.  If  you  think  the  doctrine  unjust,  it  is 
said,  it  is  only  because  you  do  not  realise  what  the  doctrine 
of  original  sin  is,  and  what  it  commits  you  to.  You  go  on 
really,  and  in  your  heart  thinking  the  human  mass  innocent 
before  actual  sin,  and  therefore  you  are  scandalised  at  the 
antecedent  consignment  of  any  part  of  it  to  punishment. 
But  suppose  it  really  guilty,  as  your  creed  represents  it,  and 
you  will  not  be  scandalized  at  it.  Fix  upon  your  mind  the 
existence  of  real  ill-desert  antecedent  to  actual  sin,  and 
condemnation  will  appear  just  and  natural.  The  first  step 
mastered,  the  second  has  no  difficulty  in  it. 

The  doctrine  of  predestination  itself,  and  its  defence 
on  the  score  of  justice,  thus  rest  upon  the  one  doctrine  of 
original  sin.  There  is  another  objection,  however,  made  to 
it,  which  is  met  in  another  way ;  for  this  doctrine,  it  is  ob- 
jected, contradicts  our  experience  and  consciousness,  de- 
scribing us  as  acting  from  an  irresistible  influence,  either 
for  good  or  evil;  whereas  we  are  conscious  of  will  and 
choice,  and  feel  that  we  are  not  forced  to  act  in  one  way 
or  another.  But  it  is  replied  that  this  objection  proceeds 
from  a  misapprehension  as  to  the  nature  of  this  irresist- 
ible influence.  .  The  terms  irresistible,  necessary,  and  other 
like  terms,  imply,  indeed,  in  their  common  use  an  inclina- 
tion of  the  will  which  is  opposed,  and  express  a  certain 
overwhelming  power  exerted  upon  the  man,  in  consequence 
of  which  he  is  obliged  to  act  against  this  inclination.  But 
in  the  present  instance  these  terms  are,  in  defect  of  proper 
language  for  the  purpose,  used  incorrectly,  and  express  a 
power  which  inclines  the  will  itself,  in  the  first  place, 
and  does  not  suppose  an  inclination  already  formed  which  it 
contradicts.  Between  our  experience  and  consciousness, 


CHAP.  I.]  FOR   PREDESTINATION.  15 

then,  and  the  exertion  of  such  a  power  as  this  upon  our  wills, 
there  is  no  opposition.  Our  consciousness  is  only  concerned 
with  the  inclination  of  the  will  itself,  beyond  which  we  can- 
not by  any  stretch  of  thought  or  internal  scrutiny  advance, 
being  obliged  to  stay  at  the  simple  point  of  our  will,  pur- 
pose, inclinations  as  existing  in  us.  But  the  inclination 
itself  of  the  will  is  the  same,  however  it  may  have  been  ori- 
ginated ;  no  difference  therefore  respecting  its  origin  touches 
the  subject  matter  of  our  consciousness.  This  question  affects 
the  cause,  our  consciousness  is  concerned  only  with  the  fact ; 
these  two,  therefore,  can  never  come  into  collision.  And 
though  in  popular  language  such  a  grace  would  be  spoken  of 
as  obliging  a  man  to  act  in  a  particular  way,  as  if  it  obliged 
him  so  to  act  whether  he  willed  or  not,  operating  as  phy- 
sical force  does,  independent  of  the  will  of  the  agent 
altogether ;  such  a  description  of  it  is  incorrect,  and  misses 
the  fundamental  distinction  in  the  case.  The  agent  is  not 
caused  by  it  to  act  in  spite  of  his  will,  but  caused  to  will. 

This  general  description  of  the  structure  and  defence  of 
the  doctrine  of  predestination  will  perhaps  be  sufficient  as 
an  introduction  to  the  present  treatise.  Nakedly  stated,  the 
doctrine  is  simply  paradoxical,  and  those  who  are  acquainted 
with  no  more  than  the  mere  statement  of  it,  are  apt  to  feel 
surprise  and  perplexity  how  it  could  have  been  maintained  by 
the  pious  and  thoughtful  minds  that  have  maintained  it.  But  it 
must  be  admitted  that  its  paradoxical  character  is  diminished, 
when  we  come  to  examine  its  grounds  and  construction.  It 
happens  in  this  case,  as  it  does  in  many  others,  that  the 
surprise  which  the  conclusion  produced  is  lessened  by  an 
acquaintance  with  the  premisses,  the  steps  by  which  it  was 
arrived  at. 

Simplicity  of  system  is  a  great  object  with  one  class  of 
minds.  The  attribute  of  Divine  power  has  also  in  many 
religious  minds  the  position  not  only  of  important,  but 
favourite  truth.  It  is  evident  how  acceptable  on  both  these 
grounds  must  be  a  system  which  contrives  in  harmony  with 


16  THE  ARGUMENT   FOR   PREDESTINATION.        [CHAP.  I. 

the  facts  of  experience  and  the  rule  of  justice,  to  secure  the 
one  great  idea  of  the  whole  spiritual  action  of  the  human  race 
being  the  pure  creation  of  Almighty  will.  They  are  attracted 
by  a  conclusion  which  gives  so  signal  a  rebuke  to  human 
pride,  and  witness  to  Divine  mercy,  and  embrace  a  doctrine 
which  alone  appears  fully  to  set  forth  that  man  is  nothing 
and  God  all  in  all. 


CHAP.  II.]         EXAMINATION    OF    THE    ARGUMENT.  17 


CHAP.  II. 

EXAMINATION  OF   THE   ARGUMENT   FOR  PREDESTINATION. 

WHEN  particular  truths  of  philosophy  or  religion  are  used  as 
grounds  to  support  conclusions  which  are  repugnant  to 
natural  reason,  there  are  two  things  for  us  to  do.  First,  we 
have  to  examine  if  the  reasoning  upon  these  truths  is  correct, 
and  if  they  really  contain  the  conclusions  which  have  been 
drawn  from  them ;  and,  secondly,  if  this  should  be  the  case, 
we  have  to  examine  the  nature  of  these  truths,  and  the  sense 
or  manner  in  which  we  hold  them ;  for  if  the  truths  them- 
selves cannot  be  questioned,  and  yet  the  logical  conclusions 
from  them  are  untenable,  there  only  remains  for  extricating 
ourselves  from  the  difficulty,  the  consideration  that  these 
truths  must  have  been  held  in  some  sense  or  manner  which 
was  improper ;  which  impropriety  in  the  manner  of  holding 
them  has  been  the  reason  why,  however  certain  themselves, 
they  have  led  to  such  untenable  results. 

Let  us  take  the  case  of  philosophical  predestination  in  the 
first  place,  or  of  predestination  as  resting  on  philosophical 
grounds,  or  what  is  ordinarily  called  necessitarianism  or 
fatalism ;  and  let  us  examine  the  nature  of  these  grounds. 
It  will  be  evident  to  any  one  at  all  conversant  with  philo- 
sophy, and  who  will  summon  to  his  mind  a  few  instances  of 
the  different  kinds  of  truths  to  which  it  calls  our  attention, 
and  which  it  assumes  and  uses  in  its  arguments  and  specula- 
tions, that  there  are  two  very  different  kinds  of  truths  upon 
which  philosophy  proceeds  —  one,  of  which  the  conception  is 
distinct  and  absolute ;  the  other,  of  which  the  conception  is 
indistinct,  and  only  incipient  or  in  tendency.  Of  ordinary 
facts,  such  as  meet  the  senses  —  of  the  facts  of  our  internal 
consciousness,  our  own  feelings  and  sensations,  bodily  and 

c 


18  EXAMINATION   OF   THE  [CHAP.  II. 

mental,  we  have  distinct  conceptions,  so  far  at  least,  that 
these  are  complete  and  absolute  truths  embraced  by  our 
minds.  On  the  other  hand,  there  are  various  truths  which 
we  partly  conceive  and  partly  fail  in  conceiving;  the  con- 
ception, when  it  has  begun,  does  not  advance  or  come  to  a 
natural  termination,  but  remains  a  certain  tendency  of 
thought  only.  Such  are  the  ideas  of  substance,  of  cause,  of 
infinity,  and  others  which  we  cannot  grasp  or  subject  to  our 
minds,  and  which,  when  we  follow  them  up,  involve  us  in 
the  utmost  perplexity,  and  carry  us  into  great  apparent  con- 
tradictions. These,  as  entertained  by  our  minds,  are  incipient 
truths,  not  final  or  absolute  ones*  In  following  or  trying  to 
follow  them,  we  feel  that  we  are  in  a  certain  right  way,  that 
we  are  going  in  a  certain  true  direction  of  thought ;  but  we 
attain  no  goal,  and  arrive  at  no  positive  apprehension. 

In  contemplating  material  objects,  I  encounter  a  number 
of  impressions,  such  as  hardness,  softness,  smoothness,  rough- 
ness, colour,  which  are  only  qualities ;  but  I  cannot  rest  in 
them,  but  push  on  to  some  substance  to  which  they  belong, 
and  from  which  it  is  absurd  to  imagine  them  apart.  But  I 
cannot  form  the  least  idea  of  what  substance  is.  I  find 
myself  only  going  in  the  direction  of  something  which  I 
cannot  reach,  which  mocks  all  pursuit,  and  eludes  all  grasp ; 
I  have  only  a  sort  of  idea  of  a  confused  something  lying 
underneath  all  the  sensible  qualities  of  matter — that  is  to  say, 
beyond  and  outside  of  all  my  real  perceptions.  And  I  am 
just  as  incapable  of  forming  any  idea  of  a  spiritual  substance 
or  myself,  though  I  am  said  to  be  conscious  of  it ;  for  this 
plain  reason,  that  it  is  in  its  very  nature  anterior  to  all  my 
ideas. 

Again,  I  have  the  idea  of  force  or  power,  or,  what  is  the 
same  thing,  of  cause.  After  contemplating  any  event  in 
life  or  nature  I  find  myself  going  in  thought  beyond  it,  to 
consider  how  it  came  to  pass ;  and  this  thought  in  me, 
once  set  going,  tends,  by  some  instinctive  law,  some  con- 
stitutional motion  inherent  in  it,  in  the  direction  of  a  cause 


CHAP.  II.]          AllGUMENT   FOR   PREDESTINATION.  19 

of   that   event ;   something    not   merely   antecedent  to  it, 
but  which  stands  in  such  a  relation  to  it,  as  that,  in  con- 
sequence of  it,  that  event  or  thing  exists.     The  intellect 
pushes  on  to  this  ultimate  resting  place,  and  satisfaction  of 
its  own  indigenous  want  and  desire.     But  while  the  move- 
ment towards  a  cause,  or  some  kind  of  idea  of  one,  is  part  of 
our  rational  nature,  I  find,  on  reflection,  that  I  can  form  no 
distinct  conception  whatever  of  what  a  cause  is.     What  is 
that  of  which  existence  is  the  necessary  fruit  and  result? 
We  can  form  no  idea  of  what  goes  on  previous  to,  and  with 
infallible  cogency  and  force  for,  producing  existence.  All  this 
preliminary  agency   is   so  entirely  hid   from   us,    and   our 
faculties  so  completely  stop  short  of  it,  that  it  seems  almost 
like  an  absurdity  to  us,  that  there  should  be  anything  of 
the  kind.     The  order  of  nature  puts  before  us  an  endless 
succession  of  antecedents  and  consequents,  but  in  no  one 
instance  can  we  see  any  necessary  connection  between  the 
antecedent  and  its  consequent.     The  relation  between  the 
so-called  cause   and   effect — the   circumstance  in   a   cause 
which  makes  it  a  cause,  is  wholly  removed  from  my  view. 
I  see  that  fire  melts  metals  and  hardens  clay,  but  I  do  not 
see  why  it  does  either;  and  prior  to  experience,  I  should 
have  thought  it  as  likely  that  these  effects  would  have  been 
reversed.      The    motion    which    one    ball    set    in    motion 
communicates  to  another,  might  or  might  not  have  taken 
place  prior  to  experience.     I  see  nothing  in  the  first  motion 
to  produce  the  second,  and  can  conceive  no  motion  upon  im- 
pact with  as  little  contradiction  as  motion.     Again,  I  look 
into  myself,  and  observe  my  own  motions,  actions,  thoughts. 
I  find  that  by  a  certain  exertion  of  the  will,  I  can  move  my 
limbs,  raise  ideas,  excite  or  suppress  affections  and  emotions ; 
but  the  nature  of  that  power  by  which  the  will  does  this,  is 
absolutely  hidden  from  me.     When  I  exert  all  my  force  to 
lift  some  weight  or  remove  some  barrier,  I  may  seem  at  first 
to  myself  to  have  an  inward  perception  of  that  force,  and 
the  manner  in  which  it  operates ;  but  on  examination,  I  find 

c  2 


20 


EXAMINATION   OF   THE 


[CHAP.  II. 


that  I  have  only  the  idea  of  a  motion  of  the  will,  and  of  a 
strain  of  the  muscles  which  succeeds,  not  of  any  connection 
between  the  two.1  I  have  looked  around  and  within  me 
then,  and  I  do  not  see  a  cause  anywhere.  My  reason,  as 
surely  as  it  leads  me  up  to  the  truth,  that  there  is  a  cause  of 
things,  stops  at  that  point,  and  leaves  me  in  utter  perplexity 
and  amazement  as  to  what  a  cause  is.  It  is  a  wonder,  a 
mystery,  an  incomprehensible  truth.  My  reason  forces  me 
towards  the  idea  of  something,  of  which  I  can  give  no  more 
account  to  myself  than  I  can  of  the  most  inexplicable  article 
in  a  creed.  What  can  be  more  astonishing  than  a  power  by 
which  anything  in  nature  is.  Do  all  the  mysteries  of 
revelation — do  even  the  wildest  dreams  of  superstition 
exceed  it  ?  What  is  it  that  prevents  my  reason  from  reject- 
ing such  an  idea  ?  Simply,  that  my  reason  gives  it  me — 
gives  it  me,  though  in  that  incipient  and  incomplete  state 
from  which  this  perplexity  ensues. 

Again,  the  idea  of  infinity  is  part  of  our  rational  nature. 
Particular  times,  spaces,  and  numbers,  end ;  but  we  cannot 
possibly  think  of  time,  space,  and  number  in  general  as 
ending.  Any  particular  number  is  suggestive  of  further 
number.  In  two  or  three  straight  strokes  I  see  a  necessary 
capacity  of  multiplication,  two,  three,  or  any  number  of 
times  ad  infinitum.  I  imagine  myself  at  the  top  of  a  high 
mountain,  with  the  largest  conceivable  view  all  around  me. 
I  might  know  by  geography  that  there  are  countries  which 


1  It  may  be  pretended  that  the  re- 
sistance which  we  meet  with  in  bodies, 
obliging  us  frequently  to  exert  all  our 
force,  and  call  up  all  our  power,  thus 
gives  us  the  idea  of  force  and  power. 
It  is  this  nisus  or  strong  endeavour  of 
which  we  are  conscious,  that  is  the 
original  impression  from  which  this 
idea  is  copied.  But,  tirst,  we  attribute 
power  to  a  vast  number  of  objects, 
where  we  can  never  suppose  this  resist- 
ance or  force  to  take  place ;  to  the 
Supreme  Being,  who  never  meets 
with  any  resistance  ;  to  the  mind  in  its 


command  over  ideas  and  limbs.  .  .  . 
Secondly,  this  sentiment  of  an  endea- 
vour to  overcome  resistance  has  no 
known  connection  with  any  event ; 
what  follows  it,  we  know  by  experience, 
but  would  not  know  it  a  priori.  It 
must,  however,  be  confessed  that  the 
animal  nisus  which  we  experience, 
though  it  can  afford  no  accurate  or 
precise  idea  of  power,  enters  very  much 
into  that  vulgar  inaccurate  idea  which 
is  formed  of  it. — Hume,  "  Enquiry  con- 
cerning the  Human  Understanding," 
sect  7. 


CHAP.  II.]         ARGUMENT   FOR   PREDESTINATION.  21 

lie  beyond  it  on  all  sides,  but  I  do  not  wait  for  that 
information.  There  is  something  in  me  by  which  I  know 
antecedently,  that  the  space  is  going  on  all  the  same  as 
space,  however  differently  it  may  be  occupied,  beyond  my 
sight  as  within  it.  Having  raised  in  my  mind  the  largest 
picture  of  space  I  can,  so  that  if  I  try  to  increase,  I 
simply  repeat  it,  I  have  still  a  sense  of  limitation.  There 
is  at  the  furthest  line  of  the  horizon  an  excess  which  baffles 
me,  which  is  not  included  in  the  imagined  space,  or  it  would 
not  be  an  excess,  and  which  yet  belongs  and  is  attached  to 
it  and  cannot  be  removed ;  an  incipient  beyond  which  must 
be  endless,  for  the  very  reason  that  it  begins ;  because  this 
indefinable  excess,  for  the  very  reason  that  it  exists  itself, 
must  be  succeeded  by  the  like.  It  is  the  same  with 
respect  to  time.  Time,  space,  and  number,  then,  do  not 
end,  but  go  on  at  the  very  last ;  that  is  the  very  latest  per- 
ception we  have  of  them,  the  last  intelligence  as  it  were ; 
they  are  ultimately  going  further.  They  go  onward,  not 
only  to  the  end  (which  particular  portions  of  them  do), 
but  at  theend—z.e.  their  utmost  defined  extent  in  our  ima- 
gination; for  their  very  nature  is  progressive;  they  are 
essentially  irrepressible,  uncontrollable,  ever-growing,  without 
capacity  for  standing  still  and  subject  to  the  absolute  neces- 
sity of  being  continually  greater  and  greater. 

But  while  we  find  in  our  minds  the  idea  of  infinity,  we 
have  no  idea  of  what  infinity  is.  I  mean  that  we  have  no 
idea  of  an  actual  infinite  quantity  of  anything.  We  ap- 
prehend so  much  of  extent  or  number  as  we  can  measure 
or  count,  and  can  go  on  adding ;  but  wherever  we  stop,  we 
are  on  the  margin  of  an  infinite  remainder,  which  is  not 
apprehended  by  us.  Imagine  a  large  crowd  increasing  in 
all  directions  without  end ;  it  is  obvious  that  such  number  is 
unintelligible  to  us ;  as  much  so  as  any  mysterious  article  in 
a  creed.  Some  idea  of  infinity  we  have  no  doubt,  otherwise 
we  should  not  be  able  to  think  or  speak  of  it  at  all ;  and  that 
seems  to  be  more  than  a  negative  idea,  as  it  has  been 

c  3 


22 


EXAMINATION   OF    THE 


[CHAP.  II. 


asserted  to  be ;  for  it  is  the  idea  of  a  progress,  or  going 
further,  which  is  not  negative,  but  positive;  but  it  is  no 
mental  image  or  reflection  of  actual  infinity.1 

We  find  then  a  certain  class  of  truths  in  philosophy  of 
which  we  have  only  a  half  conception ;  truths  which,  as 
entertained  by  us,  are  only  truths  in  tendency,  not  absolute, 
not  complete.  We  are  conscious  of  the  germs  of  various 
ideas  which  we  cannot  open  out,  or  realise  as  whole  or  con- 
sistent ones.  We  feel  ourselves  reaching  after  what  we 
cannot  grasp,  and  moving  onward  in  thought  toward  some- 
thing we  cannot  overtake.  I  move  in  the  direction  of  a 
substance  and  a  cause  in  nature  which  I  cannot  find :  my 
thought  reaches  after  infinity,  but  the  effort  is  abortive,  and 
the  idea  remains  for  ever  only  beginning.  I  encounter 
mysterious  truths  in  philosophy  before  I  come  to  them  in 
religion,  natural  or  revealed.  My  reason  itself  introduces 
me  to  them.  Were  I  without  the  faculty  of  reason,  I 
should  not  have  these  ideas  at  all,  or  derive  therefore  any 
perplexity  from  them.  I  should  want  no  substance  under- 
neath my  impressions ;  I  should  have  no  sense  of  an  excess 
beyond  the  range  of  my  eye  :  but  reason  creates  these 
movements  in  my  mind,  and  so  introduces  me  to  indistinct 
and  mysterious  truths  within  her  own  sphere. 

And  this,  it  may  be  remarked,  is  an  answer  to  those  who  ob- 
ject to  such  truths  in  religion,  and  reject  or  put  aside  certain  doc- 
trines on  the  ground  that  they  relate  to  subject-matter  of  which 
we  can  form  no  conception,  and  which,  therefore,  it  is  argued,  we 
cannot  entertain  in  our  minds  at  all ;  cannot  make  the  subject  of 
thought,  or  therefore  of  belief.  It  is  wrong  to  say  that  we  are 
wholly  unable  to  entertain  truths  of  which  we  have  no  distinct 


1  It  is  an  oblique  proof  of  the  mys- 
teriousness  of  infinite  number,  that  it 
can  be  neither  odd  nor  even.  "  Nous 
connaissons  qu'il  y  a  un  infini,  et  ig- 
norons  sa  nature,  comme  nous  savons 
•ju'il  est  faux  que  les  nombres  soient 
nuis ;  done  il  est  vrai  qu'il  y  a  un  infini 
en  nombre,  mais  nous  ne  savons  ce 


qu'il  est.  II  est  faux  qu'il  soit  pair,  il 
est  faux  qu'il  soit  impair ;  car  en  ajou- 
tant  1'unite,  il  ne  change  point  de 
nature :  cependant  c'est  un  nombre, 
et  tout  nombre  est  pair  •  ou  impair ;  il 
est  vrai  que  celas'entendde  tous  nombres 
nnis. — Pascal  (ed.  Faugere),  vol.  ii. 
p.  164. 


CHAP.  II.]          ARGUMENT    FOR    PREDESTINATION.  23 

idea ;  and  those  who  suppose  so  have  an  incorrect  and  defective 
notion  of  the  constitution  of  the  human  mind.  The  human 
mind  is  so  constituted  as  to  have  relations  to  truth  without 
the  medium  of  distinct  ideas  and  conceptions.  The  con- 
stitution of  our  minds  makes  this  mixed  state  of  ignorance 
and  knowledge  possible  to  us.  Were  the  alternative  of  pure 
ignorance  or  pure  knowledge  necessary,  it  is  evident  that,  as 
soon  as  we  turned  from  sensible  objects  and  mathematics, 
we  should  be  in  a  state  of  absolute  ignorance  and  unmixed 
darkness ;  we  should  not  only  be  ignorant  of  the  nature  of 
many  other  truths,  but  should  have  no  sort  of  idea  what 
those  truths  were  of  which  we  were  ignorant;  we  should 
be  unable  to  think  of  or  discuss  them  on  that  account,  or  even 
to  name  them.  We  should  be  cut  off  wholly  from  meta- 
physics, and  all  that  higher  thought  and  philosophy  which 
have  occupied  the  human  mind  in  all  ages.  But  this  alter- 
native is  not  necessary. l 

With  the  general  admission,  then,  of  this  class  of  truths  in 
philosophy,  we  come  to  the  grounds  upon  which  philosophical 
predestination  or  fatalism  is  raised.  We  find  these  to  be 
mainly  two — first,  the  maxim  that  every  event  must  have  a 
cause,  and,  secondly,  the  idea  of  the  Divine  Power  ;  the  first 
being  a  physical,  the  second  a  religious  assumption,  but  both 
alike  forming  premises  from  which  a  schenie  of  absolute  ne- 
cessity in  human  actions  is  logically  inferred. 

To  take  first,  then,  the  maxim  that  every  event  must 
have  a  cause.  This  is  a  maxim  undoubtedly  that  approves 
itself  to  our  understanding.  If  we  see  a  body  which  has 
hitherto  been  at  rest,  start  out  of  this  state  of  rest  and 
begin  to  move,  we  naturally  and  necessarily  suppose  that 
there  must  be  some  cause  or  reason  of  this  new  mode  of  ex- 


1  "  Nous  sommes  surun  milieu  vaste, 
toujours  incertains,  et  flottants  entre 
1'ignorance  et  la  connaissance ;  et,  si 
nous  pensons  aller  plus  avant,  notre 


il  se  derobe,  et  fuit  d'une  fuite  eterneUe: 
rien  ne  peut  1'arreter."— Pascal.  Locke 
and  Hume  both  substantially  admit  the 
class  of  indistinct  ideas. — NOT*  IV. 


object  branle,  et  eehappe  a  nos  prises  ; 

c    4 


24  EXAMINATION   OF    THE  [CHAP.  II. 

istence.  And  this  applies  to  moral  events  or  actions  as  well 
as  to  events  physical.  Every  action  which  is  performed  is 
undoubtedly  a  new  event  in  nature,  and  as  such  there  must 
have  been  some  cause  to  produce  it.  Moreover,  on  the  same 
principle  that  the  action  itself  must  have  a  cause,  that  cause 
must  have  another  cause,  and  so  on,  till  we  come  to  some 
cause  outside  of  and  beyond  the  agent  himself.  The 
maxim,  then,  that  there  must  be  a  cause  of  every  event  once 
granted,  the  conclusion  of  a  necessity  in  human  actions 
inevitably  follows. 

But  though  the  maxim  that  every  event  must  have  a 
cause  is  undoubtedly  true,  what  kind  of  a  truth  is  it  ?  Is  it  a 
truth  absolute  and  complete,  like  a  fact  of  sensation  or  re- 
flection ;  or  is  it  a  truth  indistinct,  incipient,  and  in  tendency 
only,  like  one  of  those  ideas  which  have  just  been  discussed  ? 
It  is  a  truth  of  the  latter  kind,  for  this  simple  reason,  that 
there  is  a  contrary  truth  to  it.  When  we  look  into  our 
minds,  and  examine  the  nature  and  characteristics  of  action, 
we  find  that  we  have  a  certain  natural  and  irresistible  im- 
pression or  sense  of  our  originality  as  agents.  We  feel  before- 
hand that  we  can  do  a  thing  or  not  as  we  please,  and  when 
we  have  taken  either  course,  we  feel  afterwards  that  we  could 
have  taken  the  other,  and  experience  satisfaction  or  regret, 
as  may  be,  on  that  particular  account.  That  our  actions  are 
original  in  us,  is  the  ground  upon  which  arise  peculiar 
pleasures  and  pains  of  conscience,  which  are  known  and  fami- 
liar to  us.  Could  we  really  think  that  they  were  not,  we  should 
be  without  these  particular  feelings ;  we  should  not  have 
a  certain  class  of  sensations  which  we  know  we  have.  We 
have,  then,  a  certain  sense  or  perception  of  our  originality  as 
agents,  that  an  action  is  original  in  us,  or  has  no  cause. 

This  originality  in  human  actions  is,  for  want  of  better 
language,  sometimes  expressed  by  what  is  called  the  self- 
determination  of  the  will ;  and  from  this  mode  of  expressing  it 
persons  have  endeavoured  to  extract  a  reductio  adabsurdum  of 
the  truth  itself.  For  it  has  been  said,  "If  will  determines 


CHAP.  II.]          APwGUMENT    FOB   PREDESTINATION. 


25 


will,  then  choice  orders  and  determines  choice,  and  acts  of 
choice  are  subject  to  the  decision  and  follow  the  conduct  of 
other  acts  of  choice ; "  in  which  case  every  act  whatever  of 
the  will  must  be  preceded  by  a  former  act,  and  there  must 
therefore  be  an  act  of  the  will  before  the  first  act  of  the  will.1 
But  in  the  first  place  it  is  evident  this  is  at  the  best  an 
argument  drawn  from  a  particular  mode  of  expressing  a 
truth,  and  taking  advantage  of  the  inherent  defects  of  lan- 
guage ;  and  in  the  next  place  that  it  does  not  do  justice  even 
to  the  language ;  for  however  inconceivable  self-motion  strictly 
speaking  may  be,  what  we  mean  and,  so  far  as  we  can,  express 
by  it,  is  one  indivisible  motion,  not  a  relation  of  one  motion 
to  another,  of  something  moving  to  something  being  moved, 
as  is  supposed  in  this  argument,  and  is  necessary  to  the  force 
of  it.  The  real  question,  however,  at  issue  is,  in  whatever 
way  we  may  express  it,  have  we  or  have  we  not  a  certain 
sense  of  originality  in  our  acts;  that  we  are  springs  of  motion 
to  ourselves ;  that  however  particular  motives  and  impulses 
from  without  may  operate  on  us,  there  is  a  certain  ulti- 
mate .decision,  which  we  can  make  either  way,  and  which 
therefore  when  made,  in  one  way  or  the  other,  is  original. 
If  we  have,  we  have  a  certain  sense  or  perception  of  action 
as  being  something  uncaused,  i.e.  having  nothing  anterior 
to  it,  which  necessarily  produces  it — a  sense  or  perception 
which  goes  counter  to  the  other,  which  was  also  admitted  to 
exist  in  us,  of  the  necessity  of  a  cause  for  all  events,  actions 
included.  Regarding  actions  in  their  general  character  as 
events,  we  say  they  must  have  a  cause ;  but  in  their  spe- 
cial character  as  actions,  we  refuse  them  one :  our  whole 


1  Edwards  "  On  the  Freedom  of  the 
Will,"  part  2.  sect.  1.  Aquinas  in 
arguing  for  the  necessity  of  an  external- 
source  of  motion  to  the  will  (moveri  ab 
aliquo  exterior!  prlncipio)  reasons  in 
the  same  way.  "  Manifestum  est  quod 
voluntas  incipit  velle  aliquid  cum  hoc 
prius  non  vellet.  Necesse  est  ergo 
quod  ab  aliquo  moveatur  ad  volendum. 


.  .  .  Et  si  quidam  ipsa  moverat  se- 
ipsam  ad  volendum  oportuisset,  quod 
mediante  consilio  hoc  ageret  ex  aliqu& 
voluntatepraesupposita.  Hoc  autem  est 
procedere  in  infinitum.  Unde  necesse 
est  ponere  quod  in  primum  motum 
voluntatis  voluntas  prodeat  ex  instinctu 
alicujus  exterioris  moventis." —  Sum. 
Theol.  p.  2.  q.  9.  art  4._ 


26  EXAMINATION   OF   THE  [CHAP.  II. 

internal  feeling  and  consciousness  being  opposed  to  it. 
Here  then  are  two  contradictory  instincts  or  perceptions 
of  our  reason,  which  we  must  make  the  best  of,  and  arrive  at 
what  measure  of  truth  a  mixed  conclusion  gives.  We  cer- 
tainly have  both  these  perceptions,  and  one  must  not  be 
made  to  give  way  to  the  other.  However  reason  may 
declare  for  the  originality  of  our  acts,  it  says  also  that  every 
event  must  have  a  cause  ;  again,  however  it  may  declare  for 
a  cause  of  every  event,  it  says  that  our  acts  are  original. 

Metaphysicians  on  both  sides  appear  to  have  undervalued 
the  one  or  the  other  of  these  rational  instincts  or  perceptions, 
according  to  their  bias ;  the  advocates  of  freewill  thinking 
slightly  of  the  general  instinct  for  a  cause,  the  advocates 
of  necessity  thinking  slightly  of  our  perception,  as  agents,  of 
originality.  The  former  have  simply  dwelt  on  our  inward 
consciousness  of  power  of  choice,  dismissing  the  principle  of 
causes,  as  if,  however  it  applied  to  other  events,  it  did  not 
apply  to  actions,  being  excluded  from  this  ground  ipso  facto 
by  this  sense  of  the  originality  of  our  actions.  But  if  the 
necessity  of  a  cause  of  events  is  true  at  all,  it  must  apply  to 
actions  as  well  as  to  other  events;  and  to  suppose  that  it  is 
ipso  facto  deprived  of  this  application  by  this  special  sense  of 
originality  in  the  case  of  actions,  is  to  assume  that  we  cannot 
have  two  contradictory  ideas ;  which,  according  to  what 
I  endeavoured  to  show  in  this  chapter,  is  a  false  assump- 
tion, and  not  true  of  us  in  the  present  imperfect  state  of  our 
capacities,  in  which  we  may  have,  and  have,  imperfect  op- 
posing perceptions ;  though  it  is  of  course  absurd  to  suppose 
that  this  can  be  the  case  except  in  a  very  imperfect  state  of 
being,  or  that  there  can  be  absolute  and  perfect  perceptions  in 
opposition  to  each  other.  The  latter,  on  the  other  hand, 
have  regarded  the  principle  of  causation  as  the  only  pre- 
miss worth  taking  into  account  on  this  question,  and  have 
dismissed  the  sense  of  originality,  as  if  it  were  a  mere  con- 
fused and  blind  sentiment,  which,  when  examined,  really 
spoke  to  nothing,  and  was  found  to  issue  in  a  mere  cloud,  or 


CHAP.  II.]          ARGUMENT    FOR   PREDESTINATION.  27 

evaporate  altogether.  They  have  voted  the  one  idea  to  be 
solid  and  philosophical,  the  other,  to  be  empty  and  delusive. 
But  I  cannot  see  how  they  are  justified  in  thus  setting  up 
one  of  these  ideas  to  the  exclusion  of  the  other.  Express 
the  idea  of  causation  as  you  will,  whether  as  the  perception 
of  an  abstract  truth  that  there  must  be  a  cause  of  all  events, 
or  simply  as  the  observation  of  the  fact,  that  all  events  are 
connected  with  certain  antecedents  as  the  condition  of  their 
taking  place l  —  what  is  it,  after  all,  but  a  truth  so  far  as  it 
goes,  and  so  far  as  we  perceive  or  observe  it  to  be  such? 
The  reason  desiderates  a  cause  of  anything  that  takes  place, 
says  one  philosopher,  putting  it  as  the  perception  of  an 
abstract  truth ;  but  this  necessity  is  not  to  be  acknowledged 
in  any  more  unlimited  sense,  than  that  in  which  it  is 
perceived.  In  the  case  of  events  in  nature,  the  axiom 
reigns  supreme,  and  is  not  interfered  with;  but  when  we 
come  to  moral  events  or  actions,  it  is  there  met  by  an  innate 
perception — viz.  that  of  originality  which  is  just  as  rational 
as  the  other.  Another  philosopher  says  that  we  observe 
causation  as  a  fact.  We  do ;  but  though  we  observe  it  in 
nature,  we  do  not  certainly  observe  it  in  will ;  and  observa- 
tion can  only  speak  to  those  cases  to  which  it  extends.  The 
consideration  of  ourselves  as  agents  presents  another  truth 
to  us — viz.  that  of  originality  in  our  acts;  and  this  instinct 
or  perception  must  be  taken  into  account  as  a  philosophical 
premiss.  How  should  we  have  the  idea  of  the  will  as  being 
self-moving  and  self-determining  at  all  in  the  way  in  which 
we  have  it,  unless  there  were  truth  in  the  idea  ?  For  nature 
does  not  deceive  us  and  tell  us  falsehoods,  however  it  may 
tell  us  imperfect  truths.  And  though  it  may  be  said  that 
all  that  we  mean  by  the  will's  self-determination,  is  that  we 
act  with  will  as  distinct  from  compulsion,  however  that 
will  may  have  been  caused ;  this  is  not  true  upon  any  na- 
tural test;  for,  put  this  distinction  before  any  plain  man, 


1  The  former  is  Edwarda's,  the  latter  Mr.  Mill's  position.     NOTE  V. 


28  EXAMINATION   OF    THE  [CHAP.  II. 

and  he  will  feel  it  as  an  interference  in  some  way  with  his 
natural  consciousness,  and  will  reject  the  idea  of  an  externally- 
caused  will,  as  not  properly  answering  to  his  instinct  on  this 
subject.  And  if  it  be  argued  that  we  cannot  have  this  sense 
of  originality  or  self-determination  in  the  will,  because  all  that 
we  are  actually  conscious  of  is  our  will  itself,  the  fact  that 
we  decide  in  one  way  or  another,  and  not  the  cause  of  it, 
whether  in  ourselves  or  beyond  vis ;  it  is  sufficient  to  say 
that  this  sense  or  perception  of  originality  is  not  professed 
to  be  absolute  or  complete,  but  that  it  is  still  a  sense  or 
perception  of  a  certain  kind.  There  is  a  plain  instinct  in  us, 
a  perception  of  a  truth,  in  this  direction ;  and  that  being 
the  case,  to  say  that  it  is  not  apprehension  and  does  not 
arrive  at  a  positive  conclusion  or  point,  is  to  say  no  more 
than  may  be  said  of  many  other  great  ideas  of  our  in- 
telligent nature,  such  as  that  of  substance,  cause,  infinity. 

There  being  these  two  counter  ideas,  then,  with  respect  to 
the  necessity  of  a  cause ;  as  on  the  one  hand  we  demand  a  cause, 
and  on  the  other  reject  it ;  neither  of  these  can  be  truths 
absolute  and  complete  ;  and,  therefore,  neither  of  them  a 
basis  for  an  absolute  and  complete  theory  or  doctrine  to  be 
raised  upon  it.  So  far  as  the  maxim  that  there  must  be  a 
cause  of  every  event  is  true,  so  far  it  is  a  premiss  for  a 
scheme  of  fatalism.  But  it  is  not  true  absolutely,  and  thus 
no  absolute  system  of  this  kind  can  be  founded  upon  it. 
Did  the  fatalist  limit  himself  to  a  conditional  incomplete 
conclusion,  i.  e. — for  this  would  be  all  that  it  would  come  to 
in  such  a  case  —  to  a  mystery  on  this  subject,  no  one  could 
object.  But  if  he  raises  a  definite  scheme,  his  conclusion 
exceeds  his  premiss. 

The  same  may  be  said  of  any  absolute  doctrine  of  Pre- 
destination drawn  from  the  attribute  of  the  Divine  Power, 
or  the  idea  of  God  as  the  cause  of  all  things,  There  is  an 
insurmountable  contradiction  between  this  idea  and  that  of 
freewill  in  the  creature ;  for  we  cannot  conceive  how  that 
which  is  caused  can  itself  be  a  first  cause,  or  a  spring  of 


CHAP.  II.]          ARGUMENT    FOR    PREDESTINATION.  29 

motion  to  itself.  And  therefore  the  idea  of  Divine  Power 
leads  to  predestination  as  its  result.  But  what  is  this  truth 
of  the  Divine  Power  or  Omnipotence,  as  we  apprehend  it  ? 
Does  it  belong  to  the  class  of  full  and  distinct,  or  of  incomplete 
truths?  Certainly  to  the  latter,  for  there  appears  at  once 
a  counter  truth  to  it,  in  the  existence  of  moral  evil  which 
must  be  referred  to  some  cause  other  than  God,  as  well  as 
in  that  sense  of  our  own  originality  to  which  I  have  just 
alluded.  The  Divine  Omnipotence,  then,  is  a  truth  which 
we  do  not  understand — mysterious,  imperfect  truth;  and, 
therefore,  cannot  be  used  by  the  predestinarian  as  the  pre- 
miss of  an  absolute  doctrine,  but  only  as  that  of  an  indefinite 
or  conditional  one. 

The  two  ideas  of  the  Divine  Power  and  freewill  are,  in 
short,  two  great  tendencies  of  thought  inherent  in  our  minds, 
which  contradict  each  other,  and  can  never  be  united  or 
brought  to  a  common  goal ;  and  which,  therefore,  inasmuch 
as  the  essential  condition  of  absolute  truth  is  consistency 
with  other  truth,  can  never,  in  the  present  state  of  our 
faculties,  become  absolute  truths,  but  must  remain  for  ever 
contradictory  tendencies  of  thought,  going  on  side  by  side 
till  they  are  lost  sight  of  and  disappear  in  the  haze  of  our 
conceptions,  like  two  parallel  straight  lines  which  go  on  to 
infinity  without  meeting.  While  they  are  sufficiently  clear 
then,  for  purposes  of  practical  religion  (for  we  cannot  doubt 
that  they  are  truths  so  far  as  and  in  that  mode  in  which  we 
apprehend  them),  these  are  truths  upon  which  we  cannot 
raise  definite  and  absolute  systems.  All  that  we  build  upon 
either  of  them  must  partake  of  the  imperfect  nature  of  the 
premiss  which  supports  it,  and  be  held  under  a  reserve  of 
consistency  with  a  counter  conclusion  from  the  opposite 
truth.  And  as  I  may  have  occasion  hereafter  to  use  it,  I 
may  as  well  say  here  that  this  is  what  I  mean  by  the  dis- 
tinction between  absolute  truths,  and  truths  which  are 
truths  and  yet  not  absolute  ones — viz.,  that  the  one  are  of 
that  kind  which  is  distinct  and  consistent  with  other  truth ; 


30 


EXAMINATION   OF    THE 


[CHAP.  II. 


the  other  of  the  kind  which  is  indistinct,  and  especially 
such  truth  as  has  other  truth  opposed  to  it,  and  which  is 
therefore  obviously  but  half-truth. 

I  will  add  as  a  natural  corollary  from  this  relation  of  these 
two  ideas,  that  that  alone  is  a  genuine  doctrine  of  freewill 
which  maintains  such  a  freewill  in  man  as  is  inconsistent 
with  our  idea  of  the  Divine  Ppwer.  There  is  a  kind  of 
freewill  which  is  consistent  with  this  idea.  All  men, 
whatever  be  their  theory  of  the  motive  principle  of, 
admit  the  fact  of,  the  human  will;  that  we  act  willingly 
and  not  like  inanimate  machines  ;  nor  does  the  necessitarian 
deny  that  the  human  will  is  will,  and  as  far  as  sensation  goes, 
free,  though  he  represents  it  as  ultimately  moved  from 
without.  Here,  then,  is  a  sort  of  freewill  which  is  consistent 
with  the  idea  of  the  Divine  Power.  But  this,  as  was  above 
explained,  is  not  such  a  freewill  as  meets  the  demands 
of  natural  consciousness,  which  is  satisfied  with  nothing 
short  of  a  characteristic  of  will,  which  comes  into  collision 
with  our  idea  of  the  Divine  Power — viz.  originality. 

Again,  the  objection  against  the  doctrine  of  freewill, 
that  it  would  remove  human  actions  from  the  Divine 
Providence1,  and  so  reduce  this  whole  moral  scheme  of 
things  to  chance,  has  an  immediate  answer  in  the  very 
nature  of  the  truth  as  here  described.  Undoubtedly  there 
is  a  contradiction  in  supposing  that  events  really  contingent 
can  be  foreseen,  made  the  subjects  of  previous  arrangement, 
and  come  into  a  scheme  of  Providence ;  and  though  this 


1  If  the  will  of  man  be  free  with  a 
liberty  ad  utrumlibet,  and  if  his  actions 
be  the  offspring  of  his  will,  such  of  his 
actions  which  are  not  yet  wrought,  must 
be  both  radically  and  eventually  uncer- 
tain. It  is  therefore  a  chance  whether 
they  are  performed  or  no.  ...  So  that 
any  assertor  of  self-determination  is  in 
fact,  whether  he  mean  it  or  no,  a  wor- 
shipper of  the  heathen  lady  named 
Fortune,  and  an  ideal  deposer  of  Provi- 


dence from  its  throne.  —  Toplady,  vol. 
vi.  p.  90. 

If  it  be  said  that  volitions  are  events 
that  come  to  pass  without  any  deter- 
mining cause,  that  is  most  palpably 
inconsistent  with  all  use  of  laws  and 
precepts;  for  nothing  is  more  plain 
than  that  laws  can  be  of  no  use  to 
direct  and  regulate  perfect  accident. — 
Edwards  "On  Freedom  of  the  Will," 
part  3.  sect.  4. 


CHAP.  II.]          ARGUMENT    FOR   PREDESTINATION. 


31 


is  sometimes  met  by  the  answer  that  the  Divine  foresight 
is  the  sight  of  the  events  as  such,  and  not  in  their  causes 
only,  and  that  therefore  contingent  events  can  be  foreseen 
by  God  as  being  events,  which  however  future  to  us, 
are  present  to  His  eternal  eye;  it  must  be  owned  that 
such  a  foresight  as  this  is  a  contradiction  to  our  reason1, 
and  that  therefore  an  answer  which  appeals  to  it,  to  solve 
the  contradiction  of  freewill  to  Providence,  only  gets  rid 
of  one  contradiction  by  another.  Allowing,  however,  the 
contradiction  between  Providence  and  freewill  to  remain, 
what  comes  in  the  way  of  argument  from  it  ?  All  imper- 
fect truths  run  into  contradictions  when  they  are*  pursued. 
Thus,  a  great  philosopher  has  extracted  the  greatest  ab- 
surdities out  of  the  idea  of  material  substance ;  and  the 
idea  of  infinity  is  met  by  the  objection  that  all  number 
must  be  either  odd  or  even.  In  the  same  way  freewill, 
when  pursued,  runs  into  a  contradiction  to  Providence, 
but  this  does  not  show  that  it  is  false,  but  only  that  it  is 
imperfect  truth. 

The  same  mode  of  treatment  applies  to  the  great  prin- 
ciple of  religion  (substantially  the  same  with  that  of  the 
Divine  Power)  that  God  is  the  Author  of  all  good,  if  used 
as  a  basis  of  an  absolute  doctrine  of  predestination.  Un- 
doubtedly from  this  principle  the  doctrine  of  irresistible 
grace  follows;  for  according  to  it  man  derives  all  his 
goodness  from  a  source  beyond  himself;  and  with  this 
doctrine  of  grace,  predestination.  But  what  kind  of  a  truth 
is  this  principle  that  God  is  the  Author  of  all  good?  an 
absolute  or  an  imperfect  truth  ?  Plainly  the  latter.  There 
is,  indeed,  a  principle  of  humility  in  our  nature,  whether 
belonging  to  us  as  fallen  creatures,  or  necessary  to  the 


1  That  no  future  event  can  be  certainly 
foreknown  whose  existence  is  con- 
tingent, and  without  all  necessity,  may 
he  proved  thus  :  it  is  impossible  for  a 
thing  to  be  certainly  known  to  any  in- 
tellect without  evidence  .  .  .  But  no 
understanding,  created  or  uncreated,  can 


see  evidence  where  there  is  none  .  .  . 
But  if  there  be  "a  future  event  whose 
existence  is  contingent  without  all  ne- 
cessity, the  future  existence  of  the 
event  Is  absolutely  without  evidence. — 
Edwards,  "  On  Freedom  of  Will,"  part  2. 
sect  12. 


32  EXAMINATION   OF    THE  [CHAP.  II. 

very  relation  of  dependence  implied  in  created  being,  which 
leads  us  to  disown  any  source  of  good  within  ourselves. 
The  enlightened  moral  being  has  an  instinctive  dread  of 
appropriating  any  good  that  he  may  see  in  himself  to 
himself.  This  is  a  great  fact  in  human  nature.  Our  hearts 
bear  witness  to  it.  We  shrink  from  the  claim  of  originating 
good.  If  the  thought  rises  up  in  our  minds,  we  put  it 
down,  and  are  afraid  of  entertaining  it.  As  soon  as  we 
have  done  a  good  action,  we  put  it  away  from  us ;  we  try 
not  to  think  of  it.  Thus  praise  is  a  mixture  of  pleasure  and 
pain :  the  first  motion  in  our  minds  of  pure  pleasure  is  im- 
mediately checked  by  fear :  we  are  afraid  of  the  conscious- 
ness of  being  praised,  and  wish  to  cast  it  out  of  our  minds. 
The  general  manners  of  society,  the  disclaiming  of  merit 
which  always  takes  place  as  a  matter  of  form,  the  readiness 
to  give  place  to  others,  bear  witness  to  a  great  principle 
of  humility  in  human  nature,  by  which  it  is  ever  ejecting 
the  source  of  good  from  itself,  and  falling  back  on  some 
source  external  and  unknown.  The  act  of  prayer  is  a 
witness  to  the  same  principle  ;  for  we  pray  to  God  for  moral 
and  spiritual  goodness,  for  conversion  and  renewal  both 
for  ourselves  and  others.  Our  very  moral  nature  thus 
takes  us  out  of  ourselves  to  God,  referring  us  to  Him  as 
the  sole  and  meritorious  cause  of  all  moral  action ;  while 
it  takes  upon  itself  the  responsibility  of  sin.  This  consti- 
tutional humility,  this  fixed  tendency  of  our  minds  to  an 
external  source  of  good,  expressed  in  the  formal  language 
of  theology,  becomes  the  doctrine  of  irresistible  grace,  from 
which  that  of  predestination  immediately  follows.  But  is 
there  not  a  counter  principle  to  this  co-existing  with  it  in 
our  nature,  a  principle  of  self-appreciation  and  self-respect, 
whereby  we  are  able  to  contemplate  ourselves  as  original 
agents  in  good  actions  ? 

Let  us  turn  now  from  philosophical  to  theological  predes- 
tination, or  to  the  doctrine  of  predestination  as  resting  on 
scriptural  grounds.  It  must,  I  think,  be  admitted,  accord- 
ing to  the  argument  stated  in  the  last  chapter,  that  the  pre- 


CHAP.  II.]        ARGUMENT   FOR  PREDESTINATION.  33 

destinarian  draws  his  conclusion  naturally  from  the  doctrine 
of  original  sin :  while  at  the  same  time,  *  that  conclusion 
must  be  allowed  to  be  repugnant  to  natural  reason  and  justice. 
For  there  is  no  man  of  ordinary  moral  perception,  who, 
on  being  told  of  a  certain  doctrine  which  represented  God 
as  ordaining  one  man  to  eternal  life,  and  ordaining  another  to 
eternal  punishment,  before  either  had  done  a  single  act  or 
was  born,  would  not  immediately  say  that  God  was  repre- 
sented as  acting  unjustly.  There  remains,  however,  for  ex- 
tricating us  from  this  dilemma  an  examination  of  the  sense 
and  manner  in  which  the  church  imposes,  and  in  which  we 
hold,  the  doctrine  of  original  sin. 

From  the  doctrine  of  the  fall,  then,  which  represents  man 
as  morally  impotent,  unable  by  nature  to  do  any  good 
thing,  a  lost  and  ruined  being,  the  conclusion  is  undoubtedly 
a,  legitimate  one,  that  if  he  is  to  be  restored,  he  must  be 
restored  by  some  power  quite  independent  of  and  external 
to  him,  or  by  that  act  of  grace  which  divines  call  irresistible. 
But  to  what  kind  of  truth  does  the  doctrine  of  the  fall 
belong  ?  It  is  evident  on  the  mere  statement  of  it,  that  it  ia 
not  a  truth  which  we  hold  in  the  same  manner  in  which  we 
do  the  ordinary  truths  of  reason  and  experience,  Because 
it  is  met  immediately  by  a  counter  truth.  Mankind  has  a 
sense  of  moral  power,  of  being  able  to  do  good  actions  and 
avoid  wrong  ones,  which,  so  far  as  it  goes,  contradicts  the 
doctrine  of  the  fall.  For  so  far  as  it  is  true  that  we  can 
do  what  we  ought  to  do,  our  nature  is  not  fallen ;  it  is  equal 
to  the  task  imposed  upon  it;  and  it  is  our  own  personal 
fault,  and  not  our  nature's,  if  it  is  not  done.  The  conclusion, 
then,  of  the  necessity  of  an  irresistible  grace  to  produce  a 
good  life,  has  in  the  doctrine  of  the  fall  not  a  complete,  but 
an  imperfect  premiss,  and  must  follow  the  conditions  of  that 
premiss.  The  doctrine  of  the  fall  is  held  under  a  reserve 
on  the  side  of  the  contrary  truth ;  the  doctrine  of  irresisti- 
ble grace  then,  must  be  held  under  the  same  reserve.  So 
far  as  man  is  fallen,  he  wants  this  grace ;  but  so  far  as  he  is 

D 


34  EXAMINATION  OF   THE  [CHAP.  II. 

not  fallen,  he  does  not  want  it.  One  inference,  then,  from  one 
part  of  the  whole  premiss  lies  under  the  liability  to  be  con- 
tradicted by  another  from  another  part ;  and  the  legitimate 
issue  is  no  whole  or  perfect  conclusion,  but  only  a  con- 
ditional and  imperfect  one. 

The  predestinarian,  however,  neglects  this  distinction,  and 
upon  an  imperfect  basis  raises  a  definite  and  complete  doc- 
trine. Or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  he  does  not  see  that 
the  basis  is  imperfect.  He  does  not  consent  to  holding  the 
doctrine  of  the  fall  with  this  reserve,  but  imagines  he  has  in 
this  doctrine  a  complete  truth ;  and  he  proceeds  to  use  it  as 
he  would  any  ordinary  premiss  of  reason  or  experience,  and 
founds  a  perfect  argumentative  structure  upon  it. 

Thus  much  for  the  structure  of  the  doctrine  of  predesti- 
nation, as  raised  on  the  basis  of  original  sin.  And  the  same 
answer  may  be  made  to  the  defence  of  the  justice  of  the 
doctrine  on  the  same  ground ;  to  the  argument  that,  inas- 
much as  all  mankind  deserve  eternal  punishment  antece- 
dently to  actual  sin,  it  cannot  be  unjust  to  consign  a  portion 
of  them  antecedently  to  it. 

Undoubtedly  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  represents  the 
whole  human  race  as  subject  to  the  extreme  severity  of 
Divine  wrath  in  consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam.  It  has 
two  ways  or  forms  in  which  it  represents  this.  The  doctrine 
is  sometimes  so  expressed  as  to  represent  mankind  as  being 
actually  parties  to  the  sin  committed  by  Adam,  and  so  con- 
demned, on  a  principle  of  natural  justice,  for  a  sin  which  is 
their  own.  All  men  are  said  to  have  sinned  in  Adam,  and 
Adam,  or  the  old  man,  is  spoken  of  as  the  root  or  principle  of 
evil  in  every  human  being.  Sometimes  it  is  so  expressed  as 
to  represent  mankind  as  punished,  on  a  principle  of  vicarious 
desert,  for  the  sin  of  their  first  parent,  regarded  as  another 
person  from  themselves.1  But  whichever  of  these  two  modes 


1  Quanto   magis   prohiberi    [a  bap-    I    natus  nihil  peccavit,  nisi  quod  secundum 
tismo]  non  debet  [infans]   qui  recens    |    Adam  carnaliter  natus  contagium  mortis 


CHAP.  II.]        ARGUMENT    FOR   PREDESTINATION.  35 

of  stating  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  is  adopted,  it  is  evident 
that  in  dealing  with  it,  we  are  dealing  with  a  mystery,  not 
with  an  ordinary  truth  of  reason  and  nature.  If  we  adopt 
the  former  mode,  it  is  contradictory  to  common  reason,  ac- 
cording to  which  one  man  cannot  be  thus 'the  same  with 
another,  and  commit  a  sin  before  he  is  born.  If  we  adopt 
the  latter,  it  is  contradictory  to  our  sense  of  justice,  ac- 
cording to  which  one  man  ought  not  to  be  punished  for 
another  man's  sin  Under  either  form,  then,  we  are  dealing 
with  a  mystery,  and  that  which  is  described  in  this  doctrine 
as  having  taken  place  with  respect  to  mankind,  has  taken 
place  mysteriously,  not  after  the  manner  of  common  matter 
of  fact. 

And  this  distinction,  it  must  be  observed,  is  necessary  not 
only  to  guard  what  we  build  upon  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin,  but  for  the  defence  of  the  doctrine  itself.  This  doctrine 
is  sometimes  called  an  unjust  one,  and  this  charge  of 
injustice  is  sometimes  met  by  an  attempt  to  reduce  and 
qualify  the  statement  itself  of  the  doctrine ;  as  if  it  attri- 
buted only  negative  consequences  to  the  sin  of  Adam — a  loss 
of  perfection,  a  withdrawal  of  some  supernatural  aids.  But 
such  a  qualification  of  the  doctrine  is  contrary  to  the  plain 
language  of  Scripture,  as  well  as  that  of  catholic  writers. 
The  proper  defence  of  the  doctrine  is  not  a  limitation  of  its 
statements,  but  a  distinction  as  to  the  sense  in  which  these 
statements  are  to  be  held.  When  this  distinction  has  been 
drawn,  objectors  may  exhibit  as  forcibly  and  vividly  as  they 
will  the  paradoxical  nature  of  these  statements ;  they  gain 
nothing  by  doing  so.  We  may  be  asked  how  it  is  possible 
that  God  should  be  angry  with  innocent  infants,  should 
condemn  persons  before  they  are  born  to  the  torments  of 


antiquse  prima  nativitate  contraxit,  qui 
ad  reraissam  peccatorum  accipiendam 
hoc  ipso  facilius  accedit,  quod  illi  re- 
mittuntur  -non  propria  sed  aliena  pec- 
cata  (Cyprian,  Ep.  ad  Fidum,  64.  ed. 


Oxon.)  The  more  common  and  re- 
cognised mode  however  of  expressing  the 
doctrine  is  that  which  represents  man- 
kind as  having  sinned  in  Adam,  and 
having  been  parties  in  the  act. — NOTE  VI. 


D   2 


36 


EXAMINATION   OF   THE 


[CHAP.  II. 


hell,  and  other  like  questions;  but  with  the  aid  of  this 
distinction  it  is  easy  to  see  that  such  objections  suppose  an 
entirely  different  mode  of  holding  such  statements,  from  that 
which  every  reasonable  believer  adopts.  We  are  not  to 
measure  these  mysterious  consequences  of  the  sin  of  Adam 
by  human  analogies,  as  if  the  act  of  God  in  visiting  the  sin  of 
Adam  upon  all  mankind,  were  like  the  act  of  a  human 
monarch  who  punished  a  whole  family  or  nation  for  the 
crime  of  one  man.  They  are  of  the  order  of  mysterious 
truths,  and  represent  modes  of  Divine  dealing  which  are 
beyond  the  sphere  of  our  reason.1 

Upon  the  premiss,  then,  contained  in  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin,  that  all  mankind  deserve  eternal  punishment  antecedently 
to  actual  sin,  it  is  correctly  argued  that  it  cannot  be  unjust 
to  consign  a  portion  antecedently  to  it.  But  it  must  be 
remembered  what  kind  of  a  premiss  this  is.  If  it  is  a  truth 
of  revelation  that  all  men  deserve  eternal  punishment  in 
consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam,  it  is  a  truth  of  our  moral 
nature  equally  certain,  that  no  man  deserves  punishment 
except  for  his  own  personal  sin.  And  the  one  is  declared 
in  revelation  itself  as  plainly  as  the  other;  for  it  is  said, 
"  The  soul  that  sinneth,  it  shall  die :  the  son  shall  not  bear 
the  iniquity  of  the  father,  neither  shall  the  father  bear  the 
iniquity  of  the  son  ;  the  righteousness  of  the  righteous  shall 
be  upon  him,  and  the  wickedness  of  the  wicked  shall  be  upon 
him."2  It  is  a  truth,  then,  of  reason  and  Scripture  alike 
that  no  man  is  responsible  for  another's  sin:  and  so  far  as 


1  Le  peche"  originel  est  folie  devant 
les  homines  ;  mais  on  le  donne  pour 
tel.  Vous  ne  me  devez  done  pas  re- 
proclier  le  defaut  de  raison  en  cette 
doctrine,  puisque  je  le  donne  pour  etre 
sans  raison.  Mais  cette  folie  est  plus 
sage  que  toute  la  sagesse  des  hommes  ; 
sapientius  est  hominibus .  Car,  sans  cela, 
que  dira-t-on  qu'est  I'homme  ?  Tout 
son  ef-at  depend  de  ce  point  imper- 
ceptible. Et  comment  s'en  fut-il  ape^u 
par  sa  raison,  puisque  c'est  une  chose 
au-dessus  de  sa  raison  ;  et  que  sa  raison, 
bien  loin  de  I'inventer  par  ses  voies,  s'en 


eloigne  quand  on  le  lui  presente. — Pas- 
cal (ed.  Faugeres),  v.  ii.  p.  106. 

Nous  ne  concevons  ni  1'etat  glorieux 
d'Adam,  ni  la  nature  de  son  peche,  ni 
la  transmission  qui  s'en  est  faite  en 
nous.  Ce  sont  choses  qui  se  sont  passees 
dans  1'etat  d'une  nature  toute  differente 
de  la  n6tre,  et  qui  passent  notre  capa- 
cite  presente. —  p.  369.  ' 

Jeremy  Taylor  loses  sight  of  this 
principle  of  interpretation  in  his  argu- 
ment on  Original  Sin. — NOTE  VII. 

2  Ezek.  xviii.  '20. : 


CHAP.  II.]         ARGUMENT  FOR   PREDESTINATION.  37 

this  is  true  at  all,  it  is  universally  true1,  applying  as 
much  to  the  case  of  Adam's  sin,  as  to  that  of  any  other 
man.  For  though  God  suspends  the  operation  of  general 
laws  on  occasions,  such  laws  are  only  modes  of  proceed- 
ing in  the  physical  world.  Moral  truths  do  not  admit  of 
exceptions.  The  premiss,  then,  on  which  we  proceed 
in  this  question  is  a  divided  one;  and  if  the  predestin- 
arian  from  one  part  of  it  concludes  the  justice  of  his  doc- 
trine, his  opponent  can,  from  the  other,  conclude  the  con- 
trary. If  the  mystery  of  our  responsibility  for  the  sin  of 
Adam  justifies  his  scheme,  the  truth  of  our  exclusive  respon- 
sibility for  our  own  sins  condemns  it. 

Both  in  structure  and  defences,  then,  the  doctrine  of 
predestination  rests  on  an  imperfect  premiss,  and  can  only 
be  held  as  imperfect  truth ;  for  we  cannot  build  more  upon 
a  basis  than  it  can  bear,  and  from  what  is  conditional  and 
incomplete  extract  what  is  absolute  and  determinate.  But 
the  predestinarian  holds  the  premiss  itself  as  complete  and 
perfect,  overlooking  the  contrary  one  to  which  it  is  opposed ; 
and  therefore  raises  upon  it  a  complete  and  determinate 
doctrine.  He  does  not  consider,  in  the  first  instance,  that 
the  fall  of  man  is,  however  clearly  revealed  to  us,  but 
one  side  of  the  whole  truth  as  regards  human  nature ;  that 
it  is  mysterious,  as  distinguished  from  intelligible  truth. 
He  should  revise  the  whole  sense  and  manner  in  which  he 
holds  this  doctrine. 


1  Jeremy  Taylor's  argument  is  sound 
so  far  as  he  insists  that  the  case  of 
original  sin  should  not  be  treated  as  an 
exception  to  God's  ordinary  justice. 
"  When  your  lordship  had  said  that 
*  my  arguments  for  the  vindication  of 
God's  goodness  and  justice  are  sound 
and  holy,'  your  hand  run  over  it  again, 
and  added  '  as  abstracted  from  the  case 
of  original  sin.'  But  why  should  this 
be  abstracted  from  all  the  whole  eco- 
nomy of  God,  from  all  His  other  dis- 
pensations ?  Is  it  in  all  cases  of  the 
world  unjust  for  God  to  impart  our 


father's  sins  to  us,  unto  eternal  dam- 
nation ;  and  is  it  otherwise  in  this 
only  ?  " — Vol.  ix.  p.  383. 

It  is  evidently  wrong  to  treat  the 
case  of  original  sin  as  an  exception,  in 
one  particular  instance,  to  God's  ordinary 
justice ;  for  there  can  be  no  justifiable 
exception  to  the  rule  of  justice.  All 
God's  acts  must  be  just.  It  must  be 
treated  as  a  mystery,  something  un- 
known, and  against  which,  on  that 
account,  we  can  bring  no  charge  of 
injustice.  For  before  we  can  call  an  act 
unjust,  we  must  know  what  the  act  is. 


D   3 


38  EXAMINATION   OF    THE  [CHAP.  II. 

To  turn  from  reasoning  to  Scripture.  Predestination 
comes  before  us  in  Scripture  under  two  aspects,  as  a  truth 
or  doctrine,  and  as  a  feeling,  and  under  both  the  conclusion 
is  of  that  indeterminate  character  which  has  been  described 
here  as  its  proper  and  legitimate  one. 

1.  The  general  conclusion  of  Scripture  on  this  question, 
considered  as  a  question  of  abstract  truth,  is  indeterminate. 
There  exists  undoubtedly  in  Scripture,  as  was  observed  in 
the  last  chapter,  a  large  body  of  language  in  which  man  is 
spoken  of  as  a  lost  and  ruined  creature,  and  impotent  by 
nature  for  good.     And  in  this  state  he  is  pronounced  to  be 
saved  by  an  act  of  Divine  grace  alone.     And  this  language, 
as  has  been  explained,  is  substantially  the  assertion  of  pre- 
destination ;  because  we  have  only  to  add  to  it  the  acknow- 
ledged truth  of  God's  eternal  predetermination  of  all  His 
acts,  in  order  to  make  it  such.     And  in  addition  to  this 
general  body  of  language,  particular  passages  (such,  especially, 
as  the  eighth  and  ninth  chapters  of  the  Epistle  to  the  Romans) 
assert  the  express  doctrine  of  predestination  in  such  a  way 
that  we  cannot  escape  from  their  force  except  by  a  subtle 
and  evasive  mode  of  explanation,  which  would  endanger  the 
meaning  of  all  Scripture.    The  terms  elect  and  predestinated 
in  Scripture  mean,  according  to  their  natural  interpretation, 
persons  who  have  been  chosen  by  God  from  all  eternity  to 
be  called,  justified,  or  made  righteous,  and  finally  glorified.1 
But  Scripture  is  two-sided  on  this  great  question.     If  one 
set  of  passages,  taken  in  their  natural  meaning,  conveys  the 
doctrine   of  predestination,   another   conveys    the    reverse. 
The  Bible,  in  speaking  of  mankind,  and  addressing  them  on 
their  duties  and  responsibilities,  certainly  speaks  as  if  all  had 
the  power  to  do  their  duty  or  not,  when  laid  before  them ; 
nor  would  any  plain  man  receive  any  other  impression  from 
this  language,  than  that  the  moral  being  had  freewill,  and 
could  determine  his  own  acts  one  way  or  another.     So  that, 
sometimes  speaking  one  way,  and  sometimes  another,  Scrip - 


NOTK    VIII. 


CHAP.  II.]  ARGUMENT   FOR   PREDESTINATION.  39 

ture,  as  a  whole,  makes  no  assertion,  or  has  no  determinate 
doctrine  on  this  subject. 

To  some  persons,  perhaps,  such  an  estimate  of  the  general 
issue  of  Scripture  language  on  this  subject,  may  seem  de- 
rogatory to  Holy  Scripture ;  because  it  appears,  at  first 
sight,  to  be  casting  blame  upon  language,  to  say  that  it  is 
self-contradictory ;  the  form  of  such  an  assertion  suggesting 
that  the  expression  of  something  definite  was  aimed  at,  but 
that  the  language  fell  short  of  its  aim.  But  it  will  not,  upon 
consideration,  be  found  that  any  such  consequence  attaches 
to  this  estimate  of  Scripture  language.  For  though  Scrip- 
ture is  certainly  said  not  to  be  consistent,  and,  therefore,  not 
to  give  support  to  a  determinate  doctrine  of  predestination, 
it  is  not  said  that  the  expression  of  any  determinate  doctrine 
was  designed.  And,  therefore,  the  assertion  made  is  not 
that  Scripture  has  fallen  phort  of  an  object  which  it  aimed 
at ;  rather,  it  is  quite  consistent  with  Scripture  having  most 
completely  and  successfully  attained  its  object. 

Were  the  nature  of  all  truth  such  as  that  it  could  be 
expressed  —  that  is,  put  into  statement  or  proposition,  to  the 
effect  that  such  is  or  is  not  the  case,  explicitness  and  con- 
sistency would  be  always  requisite  for  language;  because 
real  expression  is  necessarily  explicit  and  consistent  with 
itself.  All  intelligible  truths  —  matters  of  fact,  for  example  — 
are  capable  of  expression ;  and  therefore,  in  the  case  of  such 
truths,  explicit  statement  is  necessary,  and  contradiction  is 
ruinous.  But  it  is  not  the  case  that  all  truth  can  be 
expressed.  Some  truths  of  revealed  religion  cannot  be 
stated  without  contradiction  to  other  truths,  of  which  reason 
or  the  same  revelation  informs  us,  and,  therefore,  cannot  be 
stated  positively  and  absolutely  without  becoming,  in  the 
very  act  of  statement,  false. 

The  truth  of  absolute  predestination  cannot  be  stated 
without  contradiction  to  the  Divine  justice  and  man's  free 
agency.  It  belongs,  then,  to  that  class  of  truths  which  does 
not  admit  of  statement.  It  is  an  imperfect  truth  —  that  is,  a 

»  4 


40  EXAMINATION   OF   THE  [CHAP.  II. 

truth  imperfectly  apprehended  by  us.  There  is  a  tendency, 
as  has  been  said,  to  a  truth  on  this  subject,  but  this  tendency 
never  becomes  a  conclusion :  and  an  idea  which  is  true,  as 
far  as  it  does  advance,  never  does  advance  to  any  natural  limit. 
The  intellect  stops  short  and  rests  in  suspense,  not  seeing  its 
way,  and  the  line  of  thought,  though  it  may  admit  of  such  a 
completion  as  will  make  it  a  truth,  is  not  a  truth  yet,  and 
cannot  be  made  a  proposition. 

But  with  respect  to  this  kind  of  truth  which  is  only  in 
tendency,  and  does  not  admit  of  statement,  if  anything  is  to 
be  said  at  all,  such  contradictory  or  double  language  only  can 
be  employed  as  Scripture  does  employ  on  the  subject  of 
predestination.  Consistent  language  would  do  more  than, 
indeed  the  very  reverse  of  what  was  wanted,  inasmuch  as 
it  would  state  positively.  Inconsistency  could  certainly 
be  avoided  by  saying  nothing  at  all,  but  that  mode  of 
avoiding  inconsistency  could  not  be  adopted  here,  because 
there  is  a  defective  and  incomplete  truth  to  be  expressed  in 
some  such  way  as  is  practicable.  Something,  therefore,  is  to 
be  said.  But  to  say  something,  and  yet  on  the  whole  to 
make  no  positive  statement,  to  express  suitably  such  indeter- 
minate truth,  what  is  to  be  done  but  first  to  assert  the  truth 
and  then  by  counter-statement  to  bring  round  indefiniteness 
again ;  thus  carrying  thought  a  certain  way  without  bringing 
it  to  any  goal,  and  giving  an  inclination  and  a  direction  to 
ideas  without  fixing  them. 

2.  Predestination  comes  before  us  in  Scripture  as  a 
feeling  or  impression  upon  the  mind  of  the  individual. 
All  conscious  power,  strength,  energy,  when  combined  with 
a  particular  aim,  tend  to  create  the  sense  of  a  destiny  — 
an  effect  with  which  we  are  familiar  in  the  case  of  many 
remarkable  persons.  A  man  who  feels  in  himself  the 
presence  of  great  faculties  which  he  applies  to  the  attain- 
ment of  some  great  object,  not  unnaturally  interprets  the 
very  greatness  of  these  faculties  as  a  providential  call  to 
such  an  application  of  them,  and  a  pledge  and  earnest  of  a 


CHAP.  II.]  ARGUMENT   FOE    PREDESTINATION.  41 

successful  issue.  Thus,  in  proportion  to  the  very  strength  and 
energy  of  his  own  will,  he  regards  himself  as  but  a  messenger 
from,  an  instrument  of,  a  Higher  Power;  he  sees  in  himself 
but  a  derived  agency,  an  impulse  from  without.  It  seems 
necessary  that  he  should  refer  those  extraordinary  forces, 
which  he  feels  working  within  him,  to  some  source  beyond 
the  confines  of  his  own  narrow  existence,  and  connect 
them  with  the  action  of  the  invisible  Supreme  Power 
in  the  universe.  He  is  in  a  sense,  in  which  other  persons 
are  not,  a  mystery  to  himself;  and  to  account  for  so  much 
power  in  so  small  and  frail  a  being,  he  refers  it  to  the  unknown 
world  in  which  reside  the  causes  of  all  the  great  operations 
of  nature.  This  is  the  way  in  which  he  expresses  his  own 
sense  and  consciousness  of  remarkable  powers;  he  would 
have  regarded  an  ordinary  amount  of  power  as  his  own, 
but  because  he  has  so  much  more,  he  alienates  it,  and 
transfers  it  to  a  source  beyond  himself.  Thus  heroes  and 
conquerors  in  heathen  times  have  sometimes  even  imagined 
themselves  to  be  emanations  from  the  Deity.  But  a  common 
result  has  been  the  idea  of  a  destiny,  which  they  have  had 
to  fulfil.  And  this  idea  of  a  destiny  once  embraced,  as  it  is 
the  natural  effect  of  the  sense  of  power,  so  in  its  turn  adds 
greatly  to  it.  The  person  as  soon  as  he  regards  himself  as  pre- 
destined to  achieve  some  great  object,  acts  with  so  much 
greater  force  and  constancy  for  the  attainment  of  it ;  he  is 
not  divided  by  doubts,  or  weakened  by  scruples  or  fears ;  he 
believes  fully  that  he  shall  succeed,  and  that  belief  is  the 
greatest  assistance  to  success.  The  idea  of  a  destiny  in  a 
considerable  degree  fulfils  itself. 

The  idea  of  destiny  then,  naturally  arising  out  of  a  sense 
of  power,  it  must  be  observed  that  this  is  true  of  the  moral 
and  spiritual,  as  well  as  of  the  natural  man,  and  applies  to 
religious  aims  and  purposes,  as  well  as  to  those  connected 
with  human  glory.  A  strong  will  in  moral  things,  a 
determination  to  resist  the  tendencies  of  corrupt  nature,  a 
sustained  aim  at  the  perfect  life  —  this  whole  disposition  of 


42  EXAMINATION  OF   THE  [CHAP.  II. 

mind  does,  if  recognised  and  contemplated  in  himself  by  the 
possessor,  in  proportion  to  its  extent  create  a  sense  of  a 
spiritual  destiny ;  and  the  Christian  in  his  own  sphere,  as  the 
great  man  of  the  world  in  his,  feels  himself  marked  out  for  a  par- 
ticular work  and  the  final  reward  which  is  to  follow  it.  Accor- 
ding to  his  calculation  of  his  resources  is  his  conviction  that  he 
shall  attain  his  object ;  and  from  the  calculation  that  he  will, 
the  sense  that  he  is  destined  to,  succeed  almost  immediately 
arises.  Not  that  this  result  need  take  place  in  all  Christian 
minds,  for  there  are  differences  of  natural  character  as  well 
as  of  moral  power  which  would  affect  it.  Some  minds  are 
constitutionally  more  self-contemplative  than  others,  and  have 
before  them  their  own  condition  and  prospects,  while  others 
pursue  the  same  actual  course  with  less  of  reflection  upon  them- 
selves as  agents.  So  far,  however,  as  a  man  thinks  definitely 
of  himself  and  of  his  own  spiritual  strength,  and  so  far  as 
the  result  of  the  inspection  is  satisfactory,  this  will  be  the 
result.  He  perceives  in  himself  now  that  which  must 
ultimately  overcome,  and  looks  forward  to  the  issue  as  to 
the  working  out  of  a  problem,  the  natural  fruit  of  moral 
resources  already  in  his  possession.  Nor  need  this  result  be 
confined  to  remarkable  and  eminent  Christians.  Whatever 
be  the  degree  and  standard  of  goodness  before  the  mind,  so 
far  as  a  man  definitely  recognises  in  himself  the  capacity  for 
attaining  it,  so  far  he  will  have  the  sense  of  being  marked 
out  for  its  attainment. 

And  it  is  evident  that  one  whole  side  of  Scripture  en- 
courages Christians  in  this  idea.  In  the  first  place,  without 
imposing  as  necessary,  Scripture  plainly  sanctions  and  en- 
courages that  character  of  mind  which  is  self-contemplative, 
or  involves  reflection  upon  self,  our  own  spiritual  state  and 
capacities.  The  more  childlike  temper  has  doubtless  its  own 
praise  ;  but  the  other  is  also  set  forth  in  Scripture  as  a 
temper  eminently  becoming  a  Christian.  Indeed,  placed  as 
we  are  here,  with  an  unknown  future  before  us,  of  good  or 
evil,  and  possessed  by  nature  of  the  strongest  self-love  and 


CHAP.  IT.]  ARGUMENT   FOB   PREDESTINATION.  43 

desire  for  our  own  ultimate  good,  is  it  to  be  said  for  a 
moment,  that  we"  ought  not  to  think  of  ourselves,  our  pro- 
pects,  the  object  of  our  existence,  and  our  amount  of  re- 
sources, the  degree  of  our  strength  and  ability  to  achieve  it  ? 
Certainly,  such  a  consideration  is  highly  befitting  our  state, 
and  suitable  to  a  Christian  man.  And  accordingly  the  New, 
as  distinguished  from  the  Old  Testament,  appears  specially 
to  encourage  this  peculiar  tone  of  mind,  and  to  direct  men 
more  to  reflection  upon  themselves ;  it  recommends  a  grave 
foresight,  a  prudential  regard  to  our  own  ultimate  hap- 
piness; it  promotes  a  deep  moral  self-interestedness  and 
spirit  of  calculation.  The  eye  of  the  soul  is  turned  inward 
upon  itself  to  think  of  its  own  value,  and  estimate  its  own 
capacities,  and  prospects.  "  Which  of  you  intending  to  build 
a  tower,  sitteth  not  down  first  and  counteth  the  cost, 
whether  he  have  sufficient  to  finish  it  ?  Or  what  king  going 
to  war  with  another  king,  sitteth  not  down  first  and  con- 
sulteth  whether  he  be  able  with  ten  thousand  to  meet  him 
that  cometh  against  him,  with  twenty  thousand."  1  But  if 
a  man  makes  the  estimate  which  is  here  recommended  to 
him,  and  if  he  conscientiously  finds  it  a  favourable  one  —  i.  e. 
if  he  feels  himself  possessed  of  strong  moral  purpose  and  will, 
what  is  to  prevent  him  from  thinking  that  he  is  destined  to 
the  end,  with  a  view  to  which  the  estimate  is  made  ?  that  he 
is  marked  out  by  Providence  to  build  this  tower  and 
conquer  this  foe  ?  History  and  experience  show,  that  the 
human  mind  is  so  constituted  as  to  receive  this  impression. 

Accordingly,  Christians  are  addressed  in  the  New  Testa- 
ment upon  this  supposition.  It  is  one  of  the  first  lessons 
which  the  Gospel  teaches  us,  that  the  ends  which  earthly 
greatness  proposes  to  itself,  are  but  shadows  of  those  to  which 
Christians  are  called ;  that  the  conquest  of  sin  is  the  true 
glory  of  man,  and  the  heavenly  his  true  crown.  The  Chris- 
tian, therefore,  is  addressed  as  one  predestined  to  eternal 


Luke  xiv.  28.  31. 


44  EXAMINATION   OF   THE  [CHAP.  II. 

glory.  He  is  encouraged  to  regard  himself  as  a  favourite  of 
Heaven,  singled  out  from  the  world,  and  stamped  from  the 
very  commencement  of  his  course  with  the  token  of  future 
triumph.  The  resolution  to  obtain  the  spiritual  crown  is 
supposed  to  impart  to  him  the  same  sense  of  a  destiny,  that 
the  consciousness  of  a  commanding  mind  imparts  to  the  man 
of  the  world ;  and  the  life  eternal  is  represented  as  an  end 
assured  to  the  individual  before  the  foundation  of  the  world. 
His  life  in  this  world  is  described  as  a  passage,  laborious  and 
painful  indeed,  but  still  conducting  him  by  a  sure  succession 
of  steps  to  this  end.  It  obstructs  and  postpones  rather  than 
involves  any  real  hazard  to  his  spiritual  prospects ;  the  goal 
is  pledged,  and  he  has  only  to  go  forward  till  he  reaches  it, 
putting  aside  the  hindrances  as  they  arise.  Life  is  to  him  a 
purgatorial  rather  than  a  trial-state,  purifying  him  by  afflic- 
tion, and  exercising  him  by  conflicts,  through  all  which,  how- 
ever, he  passes  steadily  onward  with  the  seal  of  God  upon  him, 
marking  him  infallibly  from  the  very  beginning  as  His  own. 
Nor  is  this  position  confined  to  a  few  eminent  saints,  but 
supposed  to  be  the  position  of  all  Christians,  who,  whatever 
be  the  differences  among  themselves,  are  all  saints  in  com- 
parison with  the  world  around  them.  This  is  the  natural 
construction  of  the  language  of  S.  Paul ;  and  as  this  idea  of 
&  destiny  is  the  result  of,  so  in  its  turn  it  strengthens,  the 
moral  energies  of  the  Christian.  The  conviction  that  he  is 
marked  out  for  a  heavenly  crown,  elevates  and  inspires  him 
in  the  pursuit  of  it. 

This  is  "  the  godly  consideration  of  predestination,"  re- 
commended in  the  seventeenth  article  of  our  church.  The 
sense  of  predestination  which  the  New  Testament  en- 
courages is  connected  with  strength  of  moral  principle  in  the 
individual ;  the  Christian  being  supposed  always  to  be 
devoted  to  his  calling,  so  much  so  that  he  is  even  by  antici- 
pation addressed  as  if  he  were  dead  to  carnal  desires,  and  in 
the  enjoyment  of  the  new  and  heavenly  life.  But  no  idea 
can  be  more  opposed  to  Scripture,  or  more  unwarrantable, 


CHAP.  IL  ]  ARGUMENT   FOR   PREDESTINATION.  45 

than  any  idea  of  predestination  separated  from  this  con- 
sciousness, and  not  arising  upon  this  foundation';  the  notion 
of  the  individual  that,  on  the  simple  condition  which  he 
cannot  violate,  that  of  being  the  particular  person  which  he 
is,  he  is  certain  of  salvation.  It  is  not  to  the  person  simply 
as  such,  but  to  the  person  as  good  and  holy,  that  eternal  life 
is  ordained.  Does  a  man  do  his  duty  to  God  and  his  neigh- 
bour ?  Is  he  honest,  just,  charitable,  pure  ?  If  he  is,  and 
if  he  is  conscious  of  the  power  to  continue  so,  so  far  as  he 
can  depend  on  this  consciousness,  so  far  he  may  reasonably 
believe  himself  to  be  predestined  to  future  happiness.  But 
to  suppose  that  a  man  may  think  himself  predestined,  not  as 
being  good,  but  as  being,  whether  good  or  bad,  himself,  is  a 
delusion  of  the  devil,  and  the  gross  fallacy  of  corrupt  sects, 
that  have  lost  sight,  first  of  duty;  and  next  of  reason,  and 
have  forgotten  that  the  government  of  the  world  is  moral. 
The  doctrine  of  predestination  is  thus,  in  effect,  a  profitable  or 
a  mischievous  doctrine,  according  to  the  moral  condition  of 
those  who  receive  and  use  it.  It  binds  and  cements  some 
minds,  it  relaxes  and  corrupts  others.  It  gives  an  energy  to 
some,  a  new  force  of  will,  bringing  out  and  strengthening  high 
aims  ;  it  furnishes  an  excuse  to  others,  already  disinclined  to 
moral  efforts,  to  abandon  them,  and  follow  their  own  worldly 
will  and  pleasure. 

The  above  remarks  will  supply  a  ground  for  judging  of  the 
doctrine  of  assurance ;  assurance  being  nothing  else  but  the 
sense  of  predestination  here  spoken  of.  It  is  evident,  in  the 
first  place,  that  assurance  ought  not  to  be  demanded  as  a  state 
of  mind  necessary  for  a  Christian ;  for  it  can  only  arise  legi- 
timately upon  a  knowledge  of  our  own  moral  resources  and 
strength ;  and  there  is  nothing  to  compel  a  Christian  to  have 
this  knowledge.  He  may  innocently  be  without  it.  He 
may  do  his  duty  without  reflecting  upon  himself  as  an  agent 
at  all;  and  if  he  does  think  of  himself,  he  may  inno- 
cently make  an  erroneous  estimate  of  his  own  strength. 
It  sometimes  happens  that  at  the  time  of  trial  a  man  finds 
that  he  has  more  strength  than  he  counted  upon,  and  is  sur~ 


46  EXAMINATION  OP   THE  [CHAP.  II. 

prised  at  his  own  easy  victory.  Nor  should  it  be  forgotten 
that  the  principle  of  humility  in  man  is  one  which  tends  to 
an  Tinder-estimate  of  his  own  power  and  resources ;  and 
though  to  carry  it  to  this  extent  is  not  perfection  in  respect 
of  truth  and  knowledge,  yet  our  moral  nature  is  so  fine  and 
intricate,  that  it  must  be  owned  that,  in  the  case  of  many 
minds,  there  is  a  sort  of  perfection  in  this  very  imperfection ; 
and  one  would  not  wish  them  to  estimate  themselves  cor- 
rectly ;  if  they  did,  we  should  feel  the  absence  of  something, 
and  a  certain  indefinable  grace  which  attached  to  them 
would  be  missed.  This  is  one  of  those  results  which  flow 
from  the  variety  which  marks  the  Divine  creation  and  con- 
stitution of  the  world,  whether  physical  or  moral.  Some 
characters  are  designed  to  raise  our  affections  on  one  plan, 
others  on  another ;  some  are  formed  to  inspire  what  is  com- 
monly called  love,  others  respect,  principally  ;  both  being  only 
different  forms  of  the  scriptural  principle  of  love.  These 
are  diversities  of  His  instituting  who  is  Himself  incompre- 
hensible, and  who  has  made  man  a  type  in  some  measure  of 
Himself;  with  a  moral  nature  which  cannot  be  reduced  to  one 
criterion  of  right,  but  which  attains  perfection  in  different 
forms,  and  satisfies  our  moral  sense,  under  modes  which  we 
cannot  analyse,  but  to  which  that  moral  sense  responds. 
For  human  goodness  is  not  a  simple  thing,  but  a  complex ; 
nor  is  it  a  measurable,  but  an  indefinable  thing ;  attaining 
its  perfection  often  by  seeming  excesses,  incorrectnesses 
in  the  latter,  and  faults  transmuted  by  the  medium  of  the 
general  character  into  virtues.  The  stronger  mind  confides 
in,  the  more  amiable  one,  distrusts  itself.  Both  are  good 
according  to  their  respective  standards,  and  therefore,  on  a 
principle  of  variety,  such  difference  is  desirable.  It  is 
desirable  also,  on  another  ground  —  viz.  that  different  instru- 
ments are  wanted  by  Providence  to  execute  its  designs  in  the 
world.  Large  and  difficult  objects  can  only  be  achieved^by 
men  who  have  confidence  in  themselves,  and  will  not  allow 
obstacles  to  discourage  them ;  and  a  sense  of  destiny  helps 
these  men.  The  tie,  on  the  other  hand,  of  mutual  confidence, 


CHAP.  II.]  ARGUMENT   FOE   PREDESTINATION. 


47 


is  aided  by  self-distrust.  Did  none  confide  in  themselves, 
there  would  be  none  to  command ;  but  those  who  do  so,  are 
at  the  same  time  constitutionally  slow  to  obey. 

Accordingly  the  doctrine  of  assurance  does  not  necessarily 
go  along  with  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  because  it 
does  not  follow  that  if  a  particular  person  is  predestined 
to  eternal  life  that  therefore  he  should  have  the  inward 
sense  or  feeling  that  he  is.  The  Divine  decree  may  be 
conducting  him  by  sure  steps  all  his  life  through  to  final 
glory,  and  he  may  not  be  aware  of  it ;  for  the  only  con- 
dition necessary  to  being  one  of  the  elect,  is  goodness ; 
and  a  good  man  may  act  without  contemplating  himself 
at  all,  or,  if  he  does,  he  may  distrust  himself.  Predestin- 
arians  accordingly,  both  Augustine  and  his  school,  and 
modern  ones,  have  disowned  the  doctrine  of  assurance, 
so  far  as  it  is  maintained  in  it  that  assurance  is  necessary  for 
a  Christian.1 

Secondly,  assurance  separated  from  a  good  life,  and  the 
consciousness  of  resolution  to  persevere  in  it,  is  unreasonable 


1  As  to  what  follows  in  your  letter, 
concerning  a  person's  believing  himself 
to  be  in  a  good  state,  and  its  being  pro- 
perly of  the  nature  of  faith  ;  in  this 
there  seems  to  be  some  real  difference 
between  us.  But  perhaps  there  would 
be  none,  if  distinctness  were  well  ob- 
served in  the  use  of  words.  If  by  a  man's 
believing  that,  he  is  in  a  good  estate, 
be  meant  no  more  that  his  believing 
that  he  does  believe  in  Christ,  love  God, 
&c. ;  I  think  there  is  nothing  of  the 
nature  of  faith  in  it ;  because  knowing 
or  believing  it  depends  on  our  imme- 
diate sensation  or  consciousness,  and  not 
on  Divine  testimony.  True  believers 
in  the  hope  they  entertain  of  salvation, 
make  use  of  the  following  syllogism, 
whosoever  believes  shall  be  saved.  I  be- 
lieve, therefore,  8fc.  Assenting  to  the 
major  proposition  is  properly  of  the  na- 
ture of  faith,  because  the  ground  of  my 
assent  to  that  is  Divine  testimony,  but 
my  assent  to  the  minor  proposition,  I 
humbly  conceive,  is  not  of  the  nature 
of  faith,  because  that  is  not  grounded  on 


Divine  testimony,  but  on  my  own  con- 
sciousness. The  testimony  that  is  the 
proper  ground  of  faith  is  in  the  word 
of  God,  Rom.  x.  17., "Faith  cometh  of 
hearing,  and  hearing  of  the  word  of  God." 
There  is  such  a  testimony  given  in  the 
word  of  God,  as  that  "  he  that  believeth 
shall  be  saved."  But  there  is  no  such 
testimony  in  the  word  of  God,  as  that 
such  an  individual  person,  in  such  a 
town  in  Scotland  or  in  New  England, 
believes.  There  is  such  a  proposition 
in  Scripture,  as  that  Christ  loves  those 
that  love  Him,  and  therefore  this 
every  one  is  bound  to  believe  or  affirm. 
Believing  thus  on  Divine  testimony  is 
properly  of  the  nature  of  faith,  and  for 
any  one  to  doubt  of  it,  is  properly  of 
the  heinous  sin  of  unbelief.  But  there 
is  no  such  proposition  in  the  Scripture, 
nor  is  it  any  part  of  the  gospel  of  Christ, 
that  such  an  individual  person  in 
Northampton  loves  Christ. — Edwards, 
"  On  the  Religious  Affections,"  Letter  2. 
to  Mr.  Gillespie. 


48  EXAMINATION   OF   THE  [CHAP.  II. 

and  wicked..  Thirdly,  assurance  united  with  both  of  these 
and  arising  upon  this  foundation,  is  legitimate. 

The  sense  or  feeling,  then,  of  predestination  is,  as  has  been 
shown,  both  sanctioned  and  encouraged  in  the  New  Testa- 
ment. But  while  this  is  plain,  it  is  also  obvious  that 
this  is  only  one  side  of  the  language  of  the  New  Testament. 
There  is  another  according  to  which  all  Christians,  what- 
ever be  their  holiness,  are  represented  and  addressed  as 
uncertain,  and  feeling  themselves  uncertain,  of  final  salva- 
tion. They  are  exhorted  to  "  work  out  their  own  salvation 
with  fear  and  trembling l " ;  to  "  give  diligence  to  make 
their  calling  and  election  sure 2 " :  and  S.  Paul  himself 
the  great  preacher  of  predestination,  who,  if  any,  had  the 
right  to  feel  himself  ordained  to  eternal  life,  and  who  said 
that  there  "  was  laid  up  for  him  a  crown  of  righteousness  3," 
also  tells  us  of  his  careful  self-discipline,  "lest  that  by 
any  means  when  he  had  preached  to  others,  he  himself 
should  be  a  cast-a-way." 4  Indeed  to  any  one  who  will 
fairly  examine  the  nature  of  this  feeling  of  destiny  which 
we  have  been  considering,  and  how  far  and  in  what  mode 
it  is  entertained,  when  it  is  entertained  rationally,  it  will 
be  evident  that  it  is  not  by  any  means  an  absolute  or 
literal  certainty  of  mind.  It  is  not  like  the  perception  of 
an  intellectual  truth.  It  is  only  a  strong  impression,  which 
however  genuine  or  rational,  and,  as  we  may  say,  authorized, 
issues,  when  we  try  to  follow  it,  in  obscurity,  and  vanishes 
in  the  haze  which  bounds  our  mental  view,  before  the 
reason  can  overtake  it.  Were  any  of  those  remarkable 
men  who  have  had  it,  asked  about  this  feeling  of  theirs, 
they  would  confess  it  was  in  them  no  absolute  perception 
but  an  impression  which  was  consistent  with  a  counter 
feeling  of  doubt,  and  was  accompanied  by  this  latent  and 
suppressed  opposite  in  their  case. 

Whether   regarded,   then,   as   a   doctrine,   or   a   feeling, 


Phil.  ii.  12.  2  2  Peter,  i,  10.    j    8  2  Tim.  iv.  8.        «  1  Cor.  ix.  27. 


CHAP.  It.]          ARGUMENT   FOR   PREDESTINATION.  49 

predestination  is  not  in  Scripture  an  absolute,  but  an 
indefinite  truth.  Scripture  has  as  a  whole  no  consistent 
scheme,  and  makes  no  positive  assertion;  it  only  declares, 
and  bids  its  readers  acknowledge,  a  mystery  on  this 
subject.  It  sets  forth  alike  the  Divine  Power,  and  man's 
freewill,  and  teaches  in  that  way  in  which  alone  it  can 
be  taught,  the  whole,  and  not  a  part  alone  of  truth. 


50 


CHAP.  III. 

THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 

FROM  a  general  introductory  statement  and  examination  of 
the  argument  of  predestination,  I  turn  now  to  the  history 
and  formation  of  this  doctrine  as  exhibited  in  S.  Augustine's 
writings.  And  as  the  Augustinian  scheme  of  predestination 
rests  upon  the  basis  of  original  sin,  the  inquiry  will  suitably 
commence  with  an  account  of  the  latter  doctrine.  I  shall 
therefore  devote  the  present  chapter  to  a  general  sketch  of 
the  Pelagian  controversy : —  First,  the  mode  in  which  it 
arose  ;  secondly,  the  main  arguments  involved  in  it ;  and, 
thirdly,  its  .bearing  upon  the  leading  doctrines  of  Christianity. 
Antagonist  systems  moreover  throw  light  upon  each  other, 
and  an  inquiry  into  the  doctrines  of  S.  Augustine  will  be 
aided  by  a  previous  account  of  the  system  of  Pelagianism* 

I.  It  may  seem  at  first  sight  unnecessary  to  inquire  into 
the  mode  in  which  the  Pelagian  controversy  arose,  because 
it  appears  enough  to  say  that  one  side  maintained,  and  an- 
other denied,  the  fall  of  man.  But  the  doctrine  of  the  fall 
though  substantially,  did  not  expressly  or  by  name,  form 
the  original  subject  of  dispute,  but  was  led  up  to  by  a  pre- 
vious question. 

It  has  been  disputed  whether  the  Augustinian  system 
was  a  reaction  from  the  Pelagian,  or  the  Pelagian  from 
the  Augustinian.  Historical  evidence  favours  the  latter 
assertion.1  But  the  dispute,  whichever  way  decided,  is  not 
an  important  one.  The  controversy  between  these  two  was 


NOTE  IX. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  51 

contained  in  an  elementary  statement  of  Christian  doctrine, 
which,  as  soon  as  it  came  to  be  examined  intellectually, 
was  certain  to  disclose  it.  The  language  by  which  the 
Christian  church  has  always  expressed  the  truths  of  man's  free- 
will and  Divine  grace  has  been,  that  the  one  could  do  no  good 
thing  without  the  aid  of  the  other,  nihil  bonum  sine  gratia. 
This  formula  satisfied  the  simplicity  of  the  primitive  church 
as  it  has  satisfied  the  uncontroversial  faith  of  all  ages ;  and  no 
desire  was  felt  for  further  expression  and  a  more  exact 
truth.  But  it  is  evident  that  this  state  of  theology  on  this 
subject  could  not  last  longer  than  the  reign  of  a  simpler 
faith.  When  minds  began  to  reason  upon  this  formula  and 
analyse  it  logically,  it  lost  its  finality,  and  the  combination  of 
grace  and  freewill  divided  into  two  great  doctrines  of  an  ab- 
solute power  of  freewill  and  an  absolute  power  of  grace. 

For  was  the  grace  here  asserted  to  be  necessary  for  doing 
any  good  thing,  a  grace  which  assisted  only  the  human  will 
or  one  which  controlled  it  ?  If  it  was  the  former,  it  de- 
pended on  some  action  of  the  human  will  for  being  accepted 
and  used,  which  action  therefore  could  not  be  said 
without  contradiction  to  be  dependent  upon  it.  Assisting 
grace,  then,  must  be  used  by  an  unassisted  will,  and  there 
must  be  some  motion  of  the  human  will  for  good  to  which 
Divine  grace  did  not  contribute,  but  which  was  original  and 
independent  in  the  person  who  accepted  and  availed  himself  of 
that  grace.  Take  two  men  who  have  both  equal  grace 
given  to  them,  but  of  whom  one  avails  himself  of  this  grace, 
while  the  other  does  not.  The  difference  between  these 
two  is  not  by  the  very  supposition,  a  difference  of  grace ;  it 
is  therefore  a  difference  of  original  will  only  ;  and  in  one 
there  has  been  a  self-sprung,  independent  act  for  good,  which 
there  has  not  been  in  the  other.  But  how  great,  how 
eventful  a  function  thus  attached  to  the  unassisted  human 
will  ?  It  decided  the  life  and  conduct  of  the  man,  and  con- 
sequently his  ultimate  lot,  for  happiness  or  misery.  That 
difference  between  one  man  and  another  in  consequence  of 

E    2 


52 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


which  one  becomes  a  child  of  Grod  and  daily  grows  in  virtue 
and  holiness,  and  the  other  becomes  a  servant  of  sin,  is  no 
difference  into  which  grace  even  enters,  but  one  of  natural 
will  only.  Indeed,  was  not  the  unassisted  human  will, 
according  to  this  doctrine,  more  than  a  real  agent,  the  chief 
agent  in  the  work  of  virtue  and  piety  ?  For  the  general 
sense  of  mankind  has,  in  the  case  of  any  joint  agency, 
assigned  the  part  of  chief  agent  to  the  one  that  uses  and 
turns  to  account  the  action  of  the  other.  If  one  man 
furnishes  another  with  the  means  and  resources  for  any 
undertaking,  and  the  other  applies  them  to  it,  both  indeed 
contribute  action ;  but  the  latter  is  the  chief  contributor,  and 
would,  in  ordinary  language,  be  called  the  doer  of  the  work. 
Thus  to  the  act  of  learning  a  teacher  and  a  learner  both  con- 
tribute, the  one  by  giving  information,  the  other  by  appre- 
hending it ;  but  the  act  of  learning  is  the  learner's  rather 
than  the  teacher's  act.  Apply  this  distinction  to  the  case 
of  the  human  will  using  the  assistance  of  Divine  grace  for 
the  work  of  a  holy  life.  While  the  giver  and  the  user  of 
that  assistance  are  both  agents  in  that  work,  the  user  is  the 
principal  one.1  In  cases  where  the  use  of  means,  if  supplied, 
takes  place  easily  and  as  a  matter  of  course,  the  result  may 
be  properly  referred  to  the  supplier  rather  than  the  user  of 
them.  But  the  act  of  the  will  in  using  grace  is  no  easy 
or  matter-of-course  one,  but  involves  much  effort  and  self- 
denial. 

The  combination  of  grace  with  freewill  thus  issued  in  the 
assertion  of  an  independent  freewill  on  the  one  hand,  while 
this  logical  result  was  avoided  on  the  other,  only  by  a 
recourse  to  the  opposite  extreme.  It  was  seen  that  an 
assisting  grace  could  only  be  protected  by  making  it  sorne- 


1  «'  Nam  quando  ad  eundem  actum 
liberum  concurrunt  plura  sine  quibus 
libertas  agendi  in  actum  suum  exire- 
non  potest,  non  illi  causae  tribui  debet 
exercitiumactusautvoluntatis,  sine  qua 


non  potest  fieri,  sed  illi  quae  nutu  suo 
totam  machinam  ad  motum  impellit, 
aut  otiosam  esse  sinit." — Jansen,  De 
Grat.  Christi,  p.  935. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  53 

thing  more  than  assisting,  and  that  the  will  must  have  the 
credit  of  the  unassisted  acceptance  and  use  of  it,  unless  it  were 
controlled  by  it.  The  original  formula,  therefore,  issued  on 
this  side  in  the  doctrine  of  a  controlling  and  irresistible 
grace ;  and  upon  these  two  interpretations  of  the  primitive 
doctrine  rose,  with  their  respective  accompaniments  and  con- 
sequences, the  Pelagian  and  Augustinian  systems. 

Pelagianism  then  started  with  the  position,  that,  however 
necessary  Divine  assistance  might  be  for  a  good  work  as  a 
whole,  there  was  at  the  bottom  a  good  act  or  movement, 
which  the  human  will  was  able  to  and  must  perform  without 
Divine  assistance.  And  this  position  supplies  the  clue  to  the 
solution  of  the  Pelagian's  apparently  contradictory  language 
about  grace.  The  Pelagian  asserts  the  ability  of  nature  at 
one  time;  he  asserts  the  necessity  of  grace  at  another.1  Now 
his  opponent  explained  this  apparent  inconsistency,  by  saying 
that  by  grace  he  meant  nature ;  that  he  used  the  word  dis- 
honestly in  a  sense  of  his  own,  and  only  included  in  it  the 
natural  will  and  endowments  of  man,  which,  as  being  Divine 
gifts,  he  chose  to  call  grace.2  And,  in  the  same  way,,  he  was 
charged  with  meaning  by  grace  only  the  outward  means  of 
instruction  and  edification,  which  God  had  given  to  man  in 
the  Bible  and  elsewhere,  as  distinct  from  any  inward  Divine 
influence.  This  is  the  explanation  of  the  Pelagian  grace,  as 
Lex  et  Natura,  which  we  meet  so  often  in  S.  Augustine. 
But  with  all  deference  to  so  great  a  name,  I  cannot  think 
that  this  adverse  explanation  is  altogether  justified  by  the 
language  of  the  Pelagians  themselves.  A  verbal  confusion 
of  nature  with  grace  is  undoubtedly  to  be  found  there ;  nor 
is  such  a  confusion  in  itself  unpardonable.  In  one  sense 


1  Anathemo  qui  vel  sentit  vel  dicit 
gratiam  Dei  non  solum  per  singulas 
boras,  aut  per  singula  momenta,  sed 
etiam  per  singulos  actus  nostros  non 
esse  necessarian!. — Pelagiusap.  Aug.  De 
Grat.  Christi,  n.  2.  He  repeats  the 


n.  5.29.  33.;  Contra  Duas.  Ep.l.  4.n.l3. 
On  the  other  hand  he  says,  Posse  in 
natura,  velle  in  arbitrio,  esse  in  effectu 
locamus.— De  Grat.  Christi,  n.  5. 

2  De  Natura  et  Gratia,  n.    12.  59.; 
De  Grat.  Christi,  n.  3. 


same  statement  often. — De  Grat.  Christi, 

E   3 


54 


THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 


[CnAr.  III. 


nature  is  grace ;  freewill  itself,  and  all  the  faculties  and  affec- 
tions of  our  nature  being  the  gifts  of  God;  while,  on  the 
other  hand,  grace  may  not  erroneously  be  called  nature,  in- 
asmuch as  when  received,  it  becomes  a  power  which  we  have, 
and  which  belongs  to  us ;  especially  acting,  as  it  does,  too, 
through  the  medium  of  our  natural  faculties,  our  conscience, 
and  good  affections.  And  in  this  sense  of  nature,  the 
Pelagians  asserted  that  nature  was  able  to  fulfil  the  law — 
Posse  in  naturd1 — a  statement,  which  so  understood,  is  no 
more  than  a  truism ;  nature  comprehending,  in  this  sense  of 
the  word,  all  the  moral  power,  from  whatever  quarter,  of 
which  a  man  is  possessed,  grace  included.  Again,  the 
Pelagian,  in  his  explanations  of  grace  and  its  operations, 
certainly  dwells  most  commonly  on  the  outward  helps 
which  revelation  and  Providence  afford  to  man  in  the  path  of 
obedience.  But  while  he  is  so  far  open  to  the  charge  of  his 
opponent,  it  does  not  appear  that  he  limits  the  idea  of  grace, 
either  to  nature  in  the  sense  of  the  powers  with  which  man 
was  originally  endowed  at  his  creation,  or  to  the  outward 
helps  of  the  Divine  law.  On  the  contrary,  he  includes  in 
it  those  internal  Divine  impulses  and  spiritual  assistances 
commonly  denoted  by  the  word.2  This  is  the  natural  inter- 
pretation of  his  language;  nor  is  there  anything  in  his 
argument,  as  a  controversialist,  to  require  the  exclusion  of 
such  grace.  The  Pelagian  maintained  the  power  of  the 
human  will  *  but  if  he  admitted  the  need  of  the  Divine  assist- 
ance at  all  to  it,  as  he  did  in  the  shape  of  the  created  affec- 
tions, and  general  endowments  of  our  nature,  there  was  no 
reason  why  he  should  limit  such  assistance  to  that  creative 


1  To  the  objection  of  the  Catholic, 
"  Potest  quidem  esse,  sed  per  gratiam 
Dei,"  Pelagius  replies,  "Ego  ne  ab- 
nuo  qui  rem  confitendo,  confitear  ne- 
cesse  est  et  per  quod  res  effici  potest ; 
an  tu  qui  rem  negando,  et  quicquid  illud 
est,  per  quod  res  efficitur  procul  dubio 
negas  .  .  .  Sive  per  gratiam,  sive  per 
adjutorium,  sive  per  misericordiam,  et 


quicquid  illud  est  per  quod  esse  homo 
sine  peccato  potest,  confitetur,  quisquis 
rem  ipsam  confitetur." —  De  Natura  et 
Gratia,  n.  11. 

8  "  Sanctificando,  coercendo,  provo- 
cando,  illuminando. " — Op.  Imp.  1.  3. 
c.  106.  "Dum  nos  multiformi  et 
ineffabili  dono  gratia;  ccelestis  illu- 
minat." — De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  7. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY?.  55 

one.  The  distinction  of  prior  and  posterior,  grace  creative 
and  grace  assisting  the  creature  already  made,  was  of  no  im- 
portance in  this  respect.  There  was  no  difference,  again,  in 
principle  between  inward  and  outward  grace ;  and  any  one 
who  acknowledged  Divine  assistance,  by  means  of  instruc- 
tion, warning,  and  exhortation  addressed  to  us  from  without, 
would  have  no  difficulty  in  acknowledging  it  in  the  shape 
of  spiritual  incitement  and  illumination  carried  on  within. 
The  clue,  then,  to  the  solution  of  the  Pelagian's  apparently 
contradictory  language  respecting  grace,  is  rather  to  be 
found  in  the  logical  necessity  there  was  for  an  unassisted  act 
of  the  human  will,  in  accepting  and  using  Divine  assistance. 
Admitting  Divine  grace  to  be  wanted,  but  regarding  the  use 
of  it  as  independent  of  grace,  claiming  some  real  power  for 
unassisted  nature,  though  not  all,  he  was  led  into  a  double  and 
inconsistent  language,  which  sometimes  asserted  the  necessity 
of  grace,  and  sometimes  the  ability  of  nature  alone. 

Indeed,  it  is  clear  from  the  argument  of  the  book  De 
Gratia  Christi,  that,  whatever  objection  Augustine  may 
raise  to  the  pelagian  doctrine  of  grace,  on  the  ground  that 
grace  in  it  only  means  Lex  et  Natura,  his  main  objection  to 
that  doctrine  is,  not  that  it  maintains  an  external  grace  as 
distinguished  from  an  internal,  or  a  grace  creative  as  dis- 
tinguished from  additional  to  created  nature,  but  that  it 
maintains  a  grace  which  depends  entirely  on  an  independent 
act  of  the  will  for  its  acceptance  and  use,  as  distinguished 
from  a  grace  which  supplies  that  act  and  secures  its  own  use. 
Pelagius  defines  what  the  function  of  grace  in  his  idea  is, 
and  he  confines  it  to  that  of  assisting  the  power  of  the 
natural  will — possibilitatem  adjuvat1 ;  the  phrase  supposes 


1  "  Nos  sic  tria  ista  distinguimus,  et 
certum  velut  in  ordinem  digesta  parti- 
raur.  Primo  loco  posse  statuimus,  secun- 
do  velle,  tertio  esse.  Posse  in  natura, 
velle  in  arbitrio,  esse  in  effectu  locamus. 
Primum  illud,  id  est,  posse,  ad  Deum 
proprie  pertmet,  qui  illud  creaturae  sute 


contulit:  duo  vero  reliqua,  hoc  est, 
velle  et  esse  ad  hominem  referenda  sunt, 
quia  de  arbitrii  fonte  descendunt.  Ergo 
in  voluntate  et  in  opere  bono  laus  ho- 
minis  est ;  imo  et  hominis  et  Dei,  qui 
ipsius  voluntatis  et  operis  possibilitatem 
dedit,  quique  ipsam  possibilitatem  gra- 


E    4 


56 


THE   PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


a  foundation  of  independent  power  in  the  will,  to  which 
grace  is  an  addition.  Augustine,  on  the  other  hand,  says  it 
is  more  than  this,  and  condemns  this  definition  as  insufficient 
and  insulting  to  the  Divine  Power.  This  is  the  question, 
then,  to  which  the  whole  argument  is  substantially  reduced, 
and  on  which  the  whole  book  hinges;  and  it  is  one  con- 
cerned, not  with  the  circumstances,  so  to  speak,  of  grace,  as 
the  other  distinctions  were,  but  with  its  substantial  nature, 
its  relation  to  the  human  will ;  whether  that  relation  is  one 
of  dependence  upon  the  will  for  its  use,  or  not.1  This  is  the 
ultimate  difference  between  the  two ;  and  it  must  be  seen, 
that  it  does  make  all  the  difference  in  the  nature  and  quality 
of  Divine  grace. 

The  charge  against  the  Pelagian  that  he  held  human 
merit  always  to  precede  grace,  appears  to  be  alike  without 
satisfactory  foundation.  He  disowned  the  position  himself2, 
nor  was  it  necessary  for  his  argument.  Grace  is,  indeed, 
sometimes  taken  in  a  final  sense,  for  the  designed  effect  of 
assisting  grace;  and  stands  for  an  ultimate  spiritual  habit, 
as  when  we  speak  of  the  graces  of  the  Christian  character, 
the  grace  of  charity,  and  the  like ;  and  in  that  sense,  if  the 


tiae  suse  adjuvat  semper  auxilio." — Pe- 
lagius  de  Lib.  Arb.  apud  Aug.  de 
Grat.  Christi,  n.  5. 

Thus  Julian :  "  Adsunt  tamen  ad- 
jutoria  gratis  Dei  quae  in  parte  virtutis 
nunquam  destituunt  voluntatera  :  cu- 
jus  licet  innumerae  species,  tali  tamen 
semper  moderatione  adhibentur,  ut 
nunquam  liberum  arbitrium  locopellant, 
sed  prjEbeant  adminicula,  quamdiu  eis 
voluerit  inniti ;  cum  tamen  non  oppri- 
mant  reluctantem  animum." — Op.  Imp. 
1.  iii.  c.  114. 

1  Bradwardine  and  Jansen  thus  under- 
stand the  Pelagian  doctrine  of  grace: 
"  Non  enim  existimandum  est  solam 
legem  atque  doctrinam  esse  possibili- 
tis  adjutorium.  .  .  .  Pelagiani  motus 
indeliberatos  bonos  sub  gratia  complexi 
sunt :  Nam  sive  motus  illos  a  Deo  con- 
ditos  inseri,  sive  mente  per  istam  gra- 
am  pulsata,  ulterius  naturaliter  a  corde 


proficisci  decernerent,  eorum  causam 
Deum  adjuvantem  esse  sentiebant." 
Jansen,  De  Grat.  Christi.  p.  127.  NOTE 
X. 

2  "  Ostendit  quomodo  resistere  debea- 
mus  Diabolo,siutiquesubditisimus  Deo, 
ejusque  faciendo  voluntatem  divinam 
mereamur  gratiam." — Pelagiusap.  Aug. 
De  Gratia  Christi,  c.  22.  Augustine 
argues  incorrectly  from  this  passage  that 
Pelagius  holds  that  merit  must  precede 
grace  ;  whereas  he  only  says  it  may,  — 
that,  grace  may  be  obtained  by  merit,  or 
good  works.  On  the  other  hand  Pela- 
gius at  the  Synod  of  Diospolis  "  dam- 
navit  eos  qui  decent  gratiam  Dei 
secundum  merita  noslra  dari."  —  De 
Grat.  Christi,  c.  3.,  and  Ben.  Ed.  pre- 
face, c.  10.  — Nor  is  there  anything  in 
the  Pelagian  statements  to  show  that 
assisting  grace  was  considered  to  wait 
till  human  merit  earned  it. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 


57 


human  will  is  to  have  any  share  in  the  matter,  grace  must 
be  the  consequence  in  part  of  human  merit.  As  the  crown 
of  human  efforts,  it  supposes  such  efforts  having  been  made. 
But  it  would  be  absurd  to  maintain  that  grace,  in  the  sense 
of  assisting  grace,  requires  a  previous  effort  of  the  human 
will  for  obtaining  it,  and  that  the  individual  must  show 
goodness  before  he  receives  the  Divine  assistance  to  be  good. 
All  Christians  allow  that  such  grace  is  given  to  sinners  in 
the  very  depth  of  their  sin,  and  in  order  to  draw  them  away 
from  it :  nor  does  the  admission  at  all  affect  the  Pelagian 
position  of  the  independent  power  of  the  will ;  for  this  would 
be  exerted  in  the  acceptance  and  use  of  such  grace.  I  will 
add  that  this  distinction  between  the  grace  which  crowns 
and  that  which  stimulates  the  efforts  of  the  will  explains  the 
apparently  contradictory  language  used  by  divines  to  explain 
the  combination  of  freewill  with  grace  ;  sometimes  the  com- 
mencement of  the  spiritual  life  being  attributed  to  the  human 
will  and  its  completion  to  grace,  and  sometimes  its  completion 
being  attributed  to  the  human  will  and  its  commencement  to 
grace.  Under  both  modes  of  speaking,  the  power  of  the 
human  will  is  secured :  but  under  the  one  the  will  uses  an 
assisting,  under  the  other  it  earns  a  crowning  grace.1 

Thus  apparently  sound  and  forced  upon  reason  by  the 
necessity  of  the  case,  this  position  of  an  ultimate  unassisted 
strength  in  the  natural  will,  was,  nevertheless,  the  root  of 
all  the  errors,  the  extravagances,  and  the  impieties  of  Pela- 
gianism.  It  was  a  position  logically  true,  indeed,  and  such 


1  The  general  language  of  the  Pelagians 
allows  an  initiative  grace  (provocans, 
excitans),  and  maintains  a  crowning 
will:|  "Quod  possumus  bonum  facere 
ill  i  us  est  qui  hoc  posse  donavit;  quod 
vero  bene  agimus  nostrum  est." — De 
Grat.  Christi,  c.  4.  The  Semipelagians 
speak  of  an  initiative  will  and  a  crowning 
grace  :  "  Priorem  volunt  obedientiam 
esse  quam  gratiam,  ut  initium  salutis 
ex  eo  qui  salvatur,  non  ex  eo  credendutn 
sit  stare  qui  salvat,  et  voluntas  hominis 


divinae  gratiae  sibi  pariat  opem." — Ep. 
Prosperi.  inter  Aug.  Ep.  225.  "  Quod 
enim  dicitur.  Crede  et  salvus  eris ; 
unum  horum  exigi  asserunt,  aliud 
offerri ;  ut  propter  id  quod  exigitur  si 
redditum  fuerit,  id  quod  offertur 
deinceps  tribuatur." — Ep.  Hilarii.  apud 
Aug.  Ep.  226.  Julian  the  Pelagian, 
speaks  of  a  certain  state  of  perfection  as 
a  crowning  grace  :  "  ut  hoc  ipsum  non 
peccare  premium  censeamus." — Op. 
Imp.  Contra  Jul.  1.  2.  c.  166. 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


as  could  not  be  denied  without  admitting  the  alternative  of 
irresistible  grace  or  necessitarianism.  Nor  had  it  been 
maintained  with  due  modesty  and  reserve.,  as  being  one  side 
of  the  whole  mysterious  truth  relating  to  human  action, 
would  it  have  been  otherwise  than  orthodox.  But  to  main- 
tain absolutely  and  definitely  an  ultimate  power  in  the 
human  will  to  move  aright  independently  of  God,  was  a 
position  untrue,  and  shocking  to  natural  piety ;  a  separation 
of  the  creature  from  the  Creator,  which  was  opposed  to  the 
very  foundation  of  religion.  And  to  proceed  to  argue  upon 
such  a  truth,  and  develop  it,  as  if  it  were  a  complete  and 
ascertained  premiss,  upon  which  a  system  could  be  erected, 
was  to  mistake  its  nature,  and  to  run  at  once  into  obliquity 
and  error.  But  this  was  what  the  Pelagians  did.1  For  from 
this  position  the  conclusion  was  immediately  drawn  that 
every  man  had  the  power  of  fulfilling  the  whole  law.  The 
will  was  able  to  make  use  of  grace ;  but  every  man,  as  the 
Divine  justice  required,  had  sufficient  grace  given  him. 
For  confining  sometimes,  as  a  matter  of  language,  the  term 
grace  to  such  higher  grace,  or  grace  par-excellence)  as  was 
given  under  the  gospel,  —  such  grace  as  facilitated  goodness 
rather  than  was  necessary  for  it 2 ;  the  Pelagians  held  really 
that  every  one  had  in  the  sense  of  natural  or  other  endow- 
ments, providential  aids,  spiritual  impulses,  sufficient  Divine 
assistance  or  grace  to  enable  him  to  do  his  duty.  Every 
man,  therefore,  having  sufficient  grace,  and  the  absolute 
power  to  use  it,  had  the  power  to  fulfil  the  whole  law. 


1 "  Quodpossumus  omnebonumfacere, 
dicere,  cogitare,  illius  est  qui  hoc  posse 
donavit :  quod  vero  bene  vel  agimus,  vel 
loquimur,  vel  cogitamus  nostrum  est,  quia 
haec  omnia  vertere  in  malum  possumus." 
—  Pelagius,  ap.  Aug.  De  Gratia  Christi, 
n.  5. 

2  "  In  omnibus  est  liberum  arbitrium, 
aequaliter  per  naturam,  sed  in  solis 
Christianis  juvatur  a  gratia." — Letter 
of  Pelagius  to  Innocent,  ap.  Aug. 
de  Gratia  Christi,  n.  33. 

"Ideo  Dei  gratiam  hominibus  dari 


utquod  facere  per  liberum  jubentur  arbi- 
trium facilius  possint  implere  per  gra- 
tiam."—  Pelagius  de  Lib.  Arb.  ap.  Aug. 
Epist  186.  n.  35. 

"  Sed  formidantes  multitudinem 
Christianam,  Pelagianum  verbum  sup- 
ponitis,  et  quaerentibus  a  nobis,  quare 
mortuus  sit  Christus,  si  natura  vel 
lex  efficit  justos ;  respondetis  ut  hoc 
ipsum  facilius  fleret,  quasi  posset,  quam- 
vis  difficilius  fieri  tamen,  sive  per 
naturam  sive  per  legem." — Op.  Imp. 
Contra  Jul.  1.  2.  c.  198. 


CHAP.  III.] 


THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 


59 


The  doctrine  of  the  perfectibility  of  man  in  this  life  was 
held,  indeed,  by  the  opponents  of  Pelagius,  as  well  as  by 
himself,  but  upon  a  totally  different  ground  from  that  on 
which  he  based  it.  Augustine  maintained  that  no  limits 
were  to  be  put  to  the  power  of  Divine  grace ;  but  that  it 
might  please  God  in  a  particular  instance  so  to  control 
and  direct  all  the  motions  of  a  human  will,  that  the  person 
might  even  in  this  life  become  perfect.1  The  admission, 
however,  is  made  with  much  hesitation ;  he  confesses  such 
a  case  would  be  a  miracle,  as  being  contrary  to  all  the 
established  laws  of  the  operation  of  grace ;  and,  what  is 
most  important,  he  rests  the  possibility  of  it  solely  upon  the 
ground  of  grace,  or  the  Divine  power.  Pelagius,  on  the 
other  hand,  naturalised  this  perfectibility,  making  it  part  of 
the  constitution  of  man,  and  drawing  it  from  the  essential 
power  of  the  human  will.2  However  rare,  therefore,  its 
attainment  might  be,  perfection,  upon  his  system,  was  attain- 
able by  every  one :  indeed  some  he  asserted  had  actually 
attained  it ;  an  assertion  from  which  S.  Augustine  shrank. 
The  possibility  admitted  in  theory,  his  practical  belief  with- 
drew the  admission,  and  bound  man,  as  long  as  he  remains 
in  this  mortal  state  to  sin,  obliged  to  cry  with  the  Apostle 
"who  shall  deliver  me  from  this  death,"  and  by  the  simple 
profession  of  "  having  no  sin"  infallibly  convicted  of  falsehood 
and  pride. 


1  NOTE  XI. 

2  "  Ante    omnia    interrogandus    est 
qui  negat  hominem  sine  peccato   esse 
posse,    quid  sit  quodcunque  peccatum, 
quod  vitari  potest,  an  quod  vitari  non 
potest.     Si  quod  vitari  non  potest,  pec- 
catum non  est;  si  quod  vitari  potest, 
potest   homo   sine    peccato   esse    quod 
vitari  potest.  .  .  .  Iterum  quaerendum 
est  peccatum  voluntatis  an  necessitatis 
est.     Si  necessitatis  est,  peccatum  non 
est ;  si  voluntatis  est,  vitari  potest.  .  .   . 
Iterum  quaerendum  est,  utruinne  debeat 
homo  sine  peccato  esse.     Procul  dubio 
debet.     Si  debct,  potest;  si  non  potest, 


ergo  nee  debet ;  et  si  nee  debet  homo 
esse  sine  peccato,  debet  ergo  cum  pec- 
cato esse;  et  jam  peccatum  non  erit,  si 
illud  debere  constiterit.  Aut  si  hoc 
etiam  dici  absurdum  est,  confiteri 
necesse  est  debere  hominem  sine  peccato 
esse,  et  constat  eum  non  aliud  debere 
quam  potest.  .  .  .  Iterum  quaerendum 
est  quomodo  non  potest  homo  sine 
peccato  esse,  voluntate  an  natura.  Si 
natura,  peccatum  non  est ;  si  voluntate, 
perfacile  potest  voluntas  voluntate  mu- 
tari." — Pelagius  ap.  Aug.De  Perfectione 
Justitia,  c.  2,  3.  6. 


40  THE  PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.          [CHAP.  III. 

The  original  position  respecting  the  will  thus  led  im- 
mediately to  the  other  great  question :  and  we  find  our- 
selves thrown  at  once  on  the  great  subject  of  the  Pelagian 
controversy.  Such  a  doctrine  of  the  power  of  the  human 
will  was  evidently  opposed  to  the  doctrine  of  the  fall : 
for  such  a  will  was  evidently  not  a  corrupt,  but  a  sound 
will,  inasmuch  as  it  could  perform  its  proper  function. 
It  may  be  doubtful,  therefore,  whether  Pelagius  in  the 
first  instance  meant  to  attack  the  catholic  doctrine  of  the 
fall ;  he  certainly  showed  reluctance  to  come  into  express 
collision  with  it,  and  resisted  the  logical  strain  upon  him : 
his  attitude  was  at  the  first  a  defensive  ratherthan  ag- 
gressive one,  as  if,  provided  the  church  would  let  him 
hold  what  he  considered  to  be  the  plain  facts  of  human 
nature,  he  did  not  wish  to  interfere  with  any  received 
doctrine :  and  his  answers  at  the  Synod  of  Diospolis l 
are  perhaps  too  summarily  attributed  to  duplicity  rather 
than  a  real  indisposition  to  advance  beyond  his  original 
statements,  though  his  disciple  Celestius  had  been  bolder. 
But  the  assertion  of  such  a  freewill  as  Pelagius  asserted 
was  in  itself  a  denial  of  the  fall,  and  therefore  necessarily 
carried  him,  whatever  his  direct  intention  at  first  was, 
to  the  express  denial  of  that  doctrine.  And  thus  the 
question  assumed  that  shape  in  which  it  has  come  down 
to  us  in  the  Pelagian  controversy. 

II.  With  this  introduction,  then,  I  come  to  my  second 
head,  and  shall  endeavour  to  state  in  succession,  and  with 
such  explanation  as  may  be  necessary,  the  main  posi- 
tions and  arguments  involved  in  that  controversy ;  and 
which  may  be  conveniently  placed  under  three  general 
heads — the  power  of  the  will,  the  nature  of  virtue  and 
vice,  and  the  Divine  justice. 

1.  The   first   and   most   obvious    argument    against    the 


1  Benedictine  Editor's  preface  to  Augustine's  Antipelagian  Treatises,  c.  x. 


CHAP.  IIT.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 


61 


doctrine  of  the  corruption  of  human  nature,  was  contained 
in  that  power  of  the  will  which  has  been  just  now  described. 
Here  nature  seemed  to  bear  testimony  to  its  own  com- 
petency, and  the  doctrine  of  its  corruption  to  be  contra- 
dicted by  a  plain  fact ;  for  we  are  conscious  of  freewill, 
power  of  choice.,  and  self-determination.  The  Pelagians 
appealed  to  these  instinctive  convictions,  and  pointed  out 
their  contrariety  to  the  doctrine  of  a  captive  and  corrupted 
nature.  Nor  was  their  argument  unsound  had  they  been 
content  to  direct  it  against  an  absolute  doctrine  of  human 
corruption  and  captivity.  But  they  pressed  it  too  far  and  lay 
more  weight  upon  it  than  it  could  bear.  They  fancied  them- 
selves in  possession  of  the  whole  ground  because  they  had  this 
sense  of  freedom  on  their  side.  But  S.  Augustine  could  ap- 
peal, on  the  other  side,  to  a  representation  of  human  nature, 
which  carried  with  it  its  own  evidence,  and  met  a  response  in 
the  human  heart — "To  will  is  present  with  me,  but  how 
to  perform  that  which  is  good  I  find  not.  For  the  good 
that  I  would  I  do  not,  but  the  evil  which  I  would  not 
that  I  do.  ...  I  see  a  law  in  my  members,  warring  against 
the  law  of  my  mind,  and  bringing  me  into  captivity  to  the 
law  of  sin."  l  The  sense  of  freedom  is  a  true  part  of  human 


1  "In  medium  procedit  homo  ille  qui 
clamat,  '  Non  quod  volo  facio  bonum, 
sed  quod  nolo*  malum  hoc  ago.' " — 
Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c!  18.  "Qui  per  legem 
quam  vidit  in  membris  suis  repug- 
nantem  legi  mentis  suae  et  captivantem 
se  sub  lege  peccati,  clamat,  '  Non  quod 
volo,'  &c.  Si  habet  liberum  arbitrium, 
quare  non  facit  bonum  quod  vult  ?  " — 
L.  3.  c.  1 1 2.  Augustine,  assuming  this 
captivity  as  an  evident  fact,  proves  ori- 
ginal sin  from  it :  "  Nam  si  peccatum 
non  pertransisset,  non  omnis  homo  cum 
lege  peccati  quse  in  membris  est  nas- 
ceretur." — L.  2.  c.  63.  "  Homo  qui  non 
cogitas  ubi  sis,  et  in  diebus  malis  tan- 
quam  in  bonis  coecus  extolleris ;  quando 
erat  liberum  arbitrium,  nondum  homo 
vanitati  similis  factus  erat." — L.  3.  c. 
110.  "  Qui  dicit,  '  Quod  nolo  malum, 
hoc  ago,'  responde  utrum  necessitatem 


non  habeat." — L.  5.  c.  50.  "Non  ei 
possibilitatis  inanitas,  sed  necessitatis 
inerat  plenitudo."  —  L.  5.  c.  59. 

The  Pelagians  interpreted  this 
text  as  referring  to  the  force  of  custom, 
"  Ille  enim  in  membris  legem  consue- 
tudinem  malam  vocabat,  quae  ab  eruditis 
etiam  seculi  dici  solet  secunda  natura." 
—  Op.  Imp.l.  1.  c.69.  An  interpretation 
which  Augustine  turned  against  them, 
as  committing  them  to  the  admission 
that  sin  might  be  necessary,  and  yet 
real  sin,  and  so  to  the  principle  of  ori- 
ginal sin.  "  Nam  et  ille  qui  dicit, « Non 
quod  volo,  ago,'  certe  secundum  vos 
necessitate  consuetudinis  premitur : 
hanc  autem  necessitatem,  ne  liberum 
auferatis  arbitrium,  eum  sibi  voluntate 
fecisse  contenditis,  et  tale  aliquid  in 
natura  humana  factum  esse  non  cre- 
ditis."— L.  4.c.  103.;  alsol.  I.e.  105.;  1. 


62 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


nature ;  but  there  is  also,  on  the  other  side,  a  sense  of  cap- 
tivity: and  as  Pelagius  appealed  to  one  side  of  our  conscious- 
ness, Augustine  appealed  to  the  other. 

The  conscience  of  every  enlightened  man,  as  all  confess, 
bears  witness  to  the  presence  of  sin.  But — more  than  this 
—  the  enlightened  conscience  bears  witness  to  a  certain 
impossibility  of  avoiding  sin  altogether.  It  is  true  we 
are  conscious  of  freewill,  and  feel  we  have  the  power  of 
doing  right  and  abstaining  from  wrong  on  each  occasion. 
Nay,  the  very  sense  of  sin  depends  upon  this  sense  of 
the  power  to  avoid  it ;  for  we  do  not  feel  responsible 
for  what  we  cannot  help.  But  with  this  sense  of  freedom 
there  is  also  a  certain  sense  of  necessity  —  a  perception 
that  sin  is  not  wholly  avoidable  in  this  present  state  of 
our  nature.  We  cannot  imagine  an  enlightened  conscience 
in  which  there  would  not  be  this  inward  sense  :  no  good  man 
could  ever  possibly  think  that  he  could  be  without  serious  sin 
in  this  world.  This  sense  of  a  law  working  for  evil  in  our  na- 
ture is  a  consequence  and  a  part  of  goodness ;  and  conscience 
witnesses  to  opposite  perceptions  which  it  cannot  harmonise. 
Experience,  indeed,  shows  the  great  improbability  of  perfec- 
tion in  this  life,  but  the  enlightened  conscience  speaks  to  its 
impossibility,  because  it  sees  a  law  of  our  present  nature 
to  which  it  is  opposed.  Experience  shows  that  men  never 
have  been  perfect,  but  not  that  they  could  not  be :  but  the 
enlightened  conscience  would,  upon  the  mere  hearing  of  some 
or  other  human  being  who  was  perfect,  justify  the  setting 
down  the  assertion  as  in  itself  absurd  and  incredible ;  con- 
taining, according  to  the  scriptural  criterion,  its  own  re- 
futation, se  If  we  say  we  have  no  sin,  we  deceive  ourselves, 
and  the  truth  is  not  in  us."  But  what  is  this  but  a  sense 
of  necessity  on  the  side  of  evil ;  for  if  it  is  simply  absurd 


4.  c.  91.  "  The  body  of  this  death  was 
interpreted  of  the  guilt  of  past  sin." 
"  Quis  me  liberavit  a  reatu  peccatorum 


meorum     quse    commisi,    cum    vitari 
potuissent." — Op.  Imp,  1.  1.  c.  67. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  63 

that  the  state  of  man  in   this  life  should  not  be  sinful, 
it  must  be  necessary  that  it  should  be. 

From  this  sense  of  freedom  on  the  one  side,  and  of  captivity 
on  the  other,  proceeds  that  mixture  and  opposition  in  our 
nature,  that  whole  ambiguous  state  of  mind  of  which  man  is 
so  deeply  conscious  in  moral  action ;  that  subtle  discord  in  the 
will ;  that  union  of  strength  and  weakness.  Take  the  case  of 
any  action  above  the  standard  of  ordinary  practice  that  a 
man  may  propose  to  himself  to  do ;  with  what  a  mixture  of 
feelings  does  he  approach  it  ?  He  feels,  on  the  one  hand, 
that  he  is  certainly  able  to  do  it,  and  can  exert  a  force  over 
himself  sufficient  for  the  purpose;  and  he  prepares  for  the 
turning  point  of  a  resolve  under  this  impression.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  level  of  ordinary  practice  pulls  him  down, 
and  the  weight  of  habit  rests  upon  him.  Nature  falls  back, 
the  will  is  unnerved,  and  invincible  repugnance  and  disin- 
clination contradict  his  natural  sensations  of  moral  power. 
He  doubts  the  sincerity  of  these  sensations,  as  if,  however 
innate,  they  were  specious  and  deceptive.  Can  he,  then, 
really  do  the  good  act  ?  Has  he  freewill  or  not  ?  He  alter- 
nates between  both  impressions,  unable  to  deny  his  freedom, 
yet  apparently  unable  to  use  it,  feeling  no  constraint,  yet 
inferring  from  the  difficulties  of  the  case  some  unfelt  one, 
existing  too  deep  in  nature  for  actual  apprehension,  and  only 
showing  itself  in  its  effects.  Such  is  the  inward  struggle  of 
the  imperfect  moral  agent  described  by  St.  Paul. 

Take,  again,  the  known  power  of  custom  over  the  will.  A 
man  under  the  most  inveterate  bad  habit,  has  on  every  suc- 
cessive occasion  the  feeling  of  a  power  to  do  the  action  op- 
posed to  it.  However  long  and  uniformly  he  may  have  acted 
on  the  side  of  his  habit,  the  very  next  time  he  has  to  act  he 
appears  to  himself  to  be  able — though  it  be  no  more  than 
naked,  bare,  ability — still  able,  I  say,  to  do  what  he  has 
never  yet  done.  But  it  Ts  evident  that  such  an  idea  of 
power  is  not  to  be  taken  as  a  certain  exponent  of  the  fact. 
There  is  an  idea  of  power,  indeed,  which  represents  faithfully 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


the  reality,  a  conscious  strength  of  purpose,  which  is  ge- 
nerally the  result  of  moral  preparation.  But  this  is  alto- 
gether a  distinct  sort  of  conviction  from  that  mere  sense  of 
bare  ability  to  do  a  thing  which  is  now  referred  to. 

The  sense  of  freedom  then  in  our  nature,  with  whatever 
force  and  vividness  it  may  appeal  to  us,  is  not  to  be  relied 
upon  absolutely,  as  if  it  represented  our  whole  state.  A 
larger  insight  into  ourselves,  a  general  survey  of  facts,  mo- 
difies the  result  of  the  impression,  and  does  not  sanction  the 
profession  of  absolute  power.  But  the  Pelagian  relied  upon 
this  sense  of  bare  ability,  as  if  it  were  an  infallible  footing 
for  the  most  complete  conclusion,  and  betrayed  that  want  of 
due  and  circumspect  distrust  which  never  forsakes  the  true 
philosophical  mind,  that  knows  how  nature  abounds  in  pit- 
falls to  catch  the  unwary;  and,  however  considerate  of,  is 
ever  jealous  of,  appearances.  He  trusted  with  blind  con- 
fidence a  single  impression  and  instinct,  so  blindly  indeed, 
as  to  put  aside  the  plainest  facts,  when  they  interfered 
with  it. 

For  nothing  can  show  more  strongly  the  reckless  and 
hasty  faith,  which  the  Pelagians  reposed  in  this  one  impres- 
sion, than  that  they  supported  it  against  the  most  palpable 
facts  connected  with  nature  and  habit ;  arguing,  that  sin  not 
being  a  substance,  but  only  an  act  which  took  place  and 
was  then  over,  could  not  by  any  amount  of  repetition  affect 
this  power  and  impair  freewill l ;  but  that  a  man  after  any 
amount  and  duration  of  sin,  had  as  much  freewill  as  ever. 


1  "Liberum  arbitrium  et  post  pec- 
cata"  tarn  plenum  est  quam  fuit  ante 
peccata." —  Julian  ap.  Op.  Imp.  1.  I.e. 
91.  "  Nos  dicimus  peccato  hominis  non 
naturae  statum  mutari  sed  merit!  qua- 
litatem,  id  est  et  in  peccato  bane  esse 
liberi  arbitrii  naturam,  per  quam  potest 
a  peccato  desinere,  quae  fuit  in  eo  ut 
posset  a  justitia  deviare." — c.  96. 
"  Primo  de  eo  disputandum  est  quod 
per  peccatum  debilitata  dicitur  et  im- 
mutata  natura.  Unde  ante  omnia  quae- 


rendum  puto  quid  sit  peccatum,  sub- 
stantia  aliqua,  an  omnino  substantia 
carens  nomen,  quo  non  res,  non  exis- 
tentia,  non  corpus  aliquid,  sed  perperam 
facti  actus  exprimitur.  Credo  ita  est. 
Et  si  ita  est  quomodo  potuit  humanam 
debilitare  vel  mutare  naturam  quod 
substantia  caret." — Pelagius  ap.  Aug. 
De  Nat.  et  Grat.  n.  21.  "  Materiam 
peccati  esse  vindictam,  si  ad  hoc  pec- 
cator  infirmatus  est  ut  plura  peccaret." 
—  n.  24. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY.  65 

The  reason  was  that,  as  I  have  just  stated,  the  sense  of  bare 
ability  continues  in  spite  of  any  length  of  habit ;  on  which 
sense  the  Pelagian  absolutely  relied.  But  this  was  not  a 
reasonable,  but  a  fanatical 1  doctrine  of  freewill ;  a  gross 
delusion,  belonging  to  that  class  and  rank  of  absurd  ideas 
upon  which  corrupt  and  fantastic  sects  arise ;  forsaking  the 
broad,  inclusive  ground  of  truth  for  some  narrow  conceit, 
some  one  notion  to  which  everything  gives  way,  and  which, 
losing  by  such  exclusiveness  all  its  original  share  of  truth, 
becomes  a  shadow  and  a  lie.  This  was  a  departure  from  the 
first  principles  of  morals,  as  attaching  no  consequences 
within  the  soul  itself  to  moral  evil,  which  is  thus  repre- 
sented as  passing  off,  and  leaving  no  trace  behind.  The 
moral  being  incurred,  indeed,  the  external  consequence  of 
liability  to  punishment,  but  was  not  in  himself  impaired  by 
sin;  remaining  the  same  as  before.  But  it  is  the  internal 
consequences  of  sin,  which  fasten  the  idea  of  sin,  as  being 
such,  upon  us,  and  make  us  regard  it  as  the  real  evil  it  is. 
Take  away  these  consequences,  and  sin  is  little  more  than  a 
shadow  which  just  rests  a  moment  on  the  soul,  and  is  then 
gone.  It  ceases  to  be  a  serious  thing,  it  ceases  to  be  sin ; 
its  very  substance  is  that  part  of  it  which  survives  the 
act,  and  its  continuance  is  its  existence.  The  Pelagian, 
then,  secures  his  unqualified  freewill  at  the  cost  of  the  very 
rudiments  of  morals ;  his  theory  would  injure  the  moral  tone 
of  any  mind  that  received  it,  and  its  natural  effect,  if  it 
spread,  would  be  a  relaxation  of  the  religious  standard,  and  a 
lowering  of  the  sense  of  sin  in  the  world ;  showing  how  im- 
possible it  is  to  carry  one  truth  to  an  excess  without  impair- 


1  It  was  perhaps  an  ironical  charge 
against  the  Pelagians  that  they  held 
"  etiam  parvulos  propria  per  liberum 

arbitrium  habere  peccata Ecce 

inquiunt,  Esau  et  Jacob  intra  viscera 
materna  luctantur,  et,  dum  nascun- 
tur,  alter  supplantatur  ab  altero,  atque 
in  pede  praecedentis  manu  consequents 


et  tenentis  inventa,  perseverans  quo- 
dammodo  lucta  convincitur.  Quomodo 
ergo  in  infantibus  haec  agentibus,  nul- 
lum  est  vel  ad  bonum  vel  ad  malum 
propriae  voluntatis  arbitrium,  unde 
proemia  sive  supplicia  meritis  praeceden- 
tibus  subsequantur."— Ep.  186.  n.  13. 


66 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTBOVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


ing  another.  Those  who  will  not  allow  the  will  to  be  the  less 
free  for  any  amount  of  sin  must  accept  the  alternative,  that 
sin  has  very  little  effect,' —  with  its  natural  corollary,  that  that 
which  has  so  slight  an  effect  cannot  be  a  very  serious  matter 
itself.  And  thus  an  unlimited  freewill  can  only  be  main- 
tained by  abandoning  the  sanctity  of  moral  principle. 

2.  The  argument  respecting  .the  will  was  succeeded,  in 
the  Pelagian  controversy,  by  the  argument  respecting  the 
nature  of  virtue  and  vice.  How  could  there  be  such  a 
thing  as  hereditary  sin  ?  sin  transmitted  from  father  to 
son,  and  succeeded  to  by  birth  ?  How  were  moral  disposi- 
tions involved  in  the  operations  of  nature  ?  l  This  appeal  to 
reason  was  properly  answered  by  an  appeal  to  mystery — 
an  answer,  however,  which  was  needlessly  perplexed  by  too 
minute  attempts  to  define  the  mode  of  the  transmission  of 
sin  ?  2  The  explanation  of  a  mystery  cannot  really  advance 
beyond  the  statement  of  it,  but  the  too  subtle  explainer 
forgets  his  own  original  admission  and  the  inherent  limits 
of  his  task,  and  imagines  himself  solving  what  is  inex- 
plicable. 

But  the  question  of  transmitted  or  hereditary  sin  gave 
place  to  the  larger  question  of  necessary  sin.  Sin  was  re- 
presented, in  the  doctrine  of  the  fall,  as  attaching  to  human 
nature,  i.e.  as  necessary.  But  was  not  this  opposed  to  the 
self-evident  truth,  that  sin  must  be  voluntary  ?  3  To  deserve 


1  "  Amentissimum  est  arbitrii  nego- 
tium  seminibus  immixtum  putare," — 
Julian,  Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  9.  "  Injustum 
est  ut  reatus  per  semina  traderetur." — 
L.  3.  c.  11.  "  Habuerunt  ergo  parvuli 
voluntatem  non  sol  urn  antequam  nas- 
cerentur,  verum  etiam  antequam  proavi 
eorum  generarentur ;  et  usi  sunt  elec- 
tionis  arbitrio,  priusquam  substantise 
eorum  semina  conderentur.  Curitaque 
metuis  dicere,  in  eis  tempore  concep- 
tuum  eorum  esse  liberam  voluntatem, 
qua  peccatum  non  trahant  naturaliter 
sed  sponte  committant ;  si  credis  eos 
hodie  conceptos  ante  tot  secula  habuisse 


sensum,  judicium,  efficientiam   volun- 
tatis."— L.  4.  104. 

2  Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  22. ;  1.  2.  c.  123.  ; 
1.  4.  c.  90—104.,  1.  6.  ;  c.  9—23.     An 
elaborate  attempt  at  an  explanation  of 
this  difficulty,  by  the  analogy  of  bodies, 
quae  afficiendo  transeunt,  non  emigrando 
(1.  5.  Contra  Jul.  Pel.  n.  51.),  concludes 
thus  ;   "  Sic  et  vitia  cum  sint  in  sub- 
jecto  ex  parentibus  tamen  in  fllios,  non 
quasi  transmigratione  de  suo  subjecto  in 
subjectum    alterum,   sed   affectione   et 
contagione  pertranseunt." 

3  "  Naturale   nullum    esse  peccatum 
potest." — «  Si  est  naturale  peccatum  non 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 


67 


properly  praise  or  blame,  must  not  a  man  be  a  free  agent? 
and  was  he  a  free  agent  if  he  could  not  act  otherwise 
than  as  he  did?  The  Pelagian  thus  adopted,  as  a  plain 
raaxim  of  reason,  and  a  fundamental  truth  of  morals,  the 
position  that  virtue  and  vice  derived  their  essential  charac- 
teristics from  the  power  of  the  individual  beforehand  to 
choose  the  one  or  the  other ;  possibilitas  utriusque  partis  ; 
that  an  act  of  the  will,  to  be  good  or  bad,  must  be  a 
decision  out  of  a  neutral  or  undecided  state.1  The  Pelagian 
controversy  thus  took  up  the  question  of  the  conditions  of 
virtue  and  vice;  whether  virtue  or  vice  were  consistent 
with  necessity  or  repugnant  to  it,  whether  they  involved 
in  their  own  nature  the  trial  of  the  will  or  not. 

The  Pelagian,  then,  as  the  above  statement  shows,  expressed 
himself  unguardedly  on  this  question,  and  exposed  himself 
immediately  to  the  irresistible  answer  of  S.  Augustine,  that, 
on  the  ground  he  adopted,  he  must  be  prepared  to  deny  all 
goodness  to  the  angels  in  heaven,  to  the  saints  in  glory2, 
and  even  to  God  Himself.  The  impossibility  of  sinning 
belonged  to  the  Divine  Being  as  His  nature,  and  to  the 
saints  and  angels  as  a  privilege  and  reward;  and  there- 
fore were  contingency,  or  the  absence  of  necessity,  essential 
to  goodness,  neither  God,  nor  the  angels,  nor  the  saints 
would  be  good. 

Thus  easily  and  summarily  refuted,  however,  his  argu- 
ment involved  a  mixture  of  truth  and  error.  So  much  must 
be  conceded  to  the  Pelagian,  that  the  trial  of  the  will  is  the 
necessary  condition  of  the  highest  kind  of  virtue  that  comes 


est  voluntarium." — "  Voluntas  neces- 
sitati  non  potest  admoveri." — "  Non 
potest  velle  antequam  potuerit  et  nolle." 
—  "  Suum  non  est  si  necessarium  est." 
1  Julian :  "  Inculco  liberum  arbitrium 
nee  ob  aliud  datum  esse,  nee  intelligi  in 
alio  posse,  quam  ut  nee  ad  justitiam,  nee 
ad  iniquitatem,  captiva  aliquis  volun- 
tate  rapiatur."  Augustine  :  "  Libra  tua 
quam  conaris  ex  utraque  parte  per 
a-'qualia  momenta  suspendere,  ut  volun- 


tas  quantum  sit  ad  malum,  tantum 
etiam  sit  ad  bonum  libera." — Op.  Imp. 
1.  3.  c.  112.  117.  "  Sic  deflnis  liberam 
voluntatem,  ut  nisi  utrumque,  id  est, 
et  bene  et  male  agere  po^sit,  libera  esse 
non  possit." — L.  3.  c.  120. 

2  "  Accedere  nobis  debet  virtus  major 
in  proemio,  ut  malam  voluntatem  sic 
non  haberemus,  ut  nee  habere  possemus. 
O  desideranda  necessitas  !  " — Op.  Imp. 
1.  5.  c.  61. 


F    2 


68  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

within  our  cognisance  and  experience.  Of  the  Divine  Nature, 
as  being  beyond  our  comprehension,  we  cannot  speak,  though 
we  know  that  it  must  be  infinitely  good,  while  it  must  also 
be  without  trial.  But  the  assertion  is  true  of  the  moral  creature 
in  this  present  state.  For  whatever  may  be  the  sweetness  of 
the  good  affections, —  even  though  we  could  imagine  them 
from  the  first  in  full  possession  of  the  mind,  and  so  powerfully 
moving  it,  that  it  felt  no  inclination  to  act  otherwise  than  as 
they  dictated ;  even  though  we  could  imagine  such  an  unin- 
terrupted flow  of  virtue  from  a  source  of  feeling, —  such  a 
result  could  not  bear  a  comparison  with  the  victory  of  the 
will.  The  good  affections  are  aids  and  supports  to  goodness; 
aids  and  supports  indeed  not  casual  or  adventitious,  but 
permanent,  and  belonging  to  our  nature ;  yet  having  the 
effect  of  saving  pain  and  effort.  But  in  trial  we  have 
to  act  without  this  aid.  For  though  even  the  will  itself 
cannot  be  said  to  act  without  affection,  inasmuch  as  some 
love  of  what  is  good  appears  to  enter  as  an  ingredient  into 
any  decision  in  favour  of  it,  we  are  properly  said  to  act 
from  the  will  as  distinct  from  the  affections,  in  the  case  of 
trial ;  such  trial  being  in  truth  caused  by  the  balance 
of  the  affections  being  on  the  side  of  evil.  Trial,  there- 
fore, throws  the  man  upon  himself  in  a  deep  and  peculiar 
sense.  He  is  reduced  to  the  narrowest  condition,  and 
with  all  the  excesses  of  a  bountifully  constituted  nature  cut 
off,  sustains  from  ultimate  conscience  and  the  bare  substance 
of  the  soul,  the  fight  with  evil.  But  such  a  combat  tests  and 
elicits  an  inner  strength  which  no  dominion  of  the  good 
affections,  however  continuous,  could  do.  The  greater  the 
desertion  of  the  moral  being,  and  his  deprivation  of  aids,  the 
deeper  appears  his  fidelity  ;  the  triumph  is  greater  in  pro- 
portion to  the  scantiness  of  the  means  with  which  it  is  gained ; 
and  in  this  adoption  of,  this  cleaving  to,  barren  good,  is  a 
depth  of  affection,  a  root  of  love,  contrasted  with  which,  all 
the  richness  of  the  untried  affections  is  a  poor  and  feeble 
offering  to  God. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN  CONTROVERSY.  69 

But  though  trial  is  the  necessary  condition  of  the  highest 
kind  of  goodness  in  this  life,  it  is  not  the  necessary  condition 
of  all  goodness.  It  is  evident  that  we  recognise  and  feel 
toward,  as  goodness,  certain  moral  states  and  dispositions 
which  have  not  been  the  result  of  tiial,  but  are  altogether 
natural.  We  may  see  this  in  a  very  low  degree  even  in  the 
case  of  animals  of  the  gentler,  more  generous,  and  confiding 
character  who  engage  our  affections  in  consequence,  and 
towards  whom  we  instinctively  feel  as  possessing  a  kind  of 
goodness.  But  the  good  natural  dispositions  of  moral  beings 
deserve  a  serious  consideration.1  For  though  it  may  be 
doubted  whether  these  dispositions  are  ever  sustained  en- 
tirely without  trial  of  the  will,  and  though  we  may  not  be 
able  to  tell  in  a  particular  case,  whether  what  appears  to  be 
the  man's  natural  disposition  has  not  been  formed  in  part 
by  early  trial  and  past  moral  acts,  still  the  general  sense  of 
mankind  acknowledges  what  are  called  good  natural  dispo- 
sitions ;  that  some  persons  have  by  nature  a  good  bias  in  one 
or  other  direction,  are  amiable,  courageous,  truthful,  humble 
naturally,  or  have  a  certain  general  happy  conformation; 
that  they  have,  that  is,  by  nature,  not  only  the  power  to  act 
in  a  certain  way,  but  the  disposition  so  to  act  already  formed 
within  them ;  a  habit  implanted,  or,  as  the  schoolmen  say, 
infused,  in  distinction  to  being  acquired  by  acts.  But  it 
would  be  absurd  to  say  that  such  dispositions  as  these  were 
not  virtues,  and  that  such  natural  goodness  was  not  real 
goodness.  We  feel  towards  persons  who  possess  such 
dispositions  as  persons  of  a  particular  character,  which 
character  is  good ;  nor  do  we  do  this  on  even  the  imaginary 
supposition  that  they  have  acquired  it  for  themselves,  the 
existing  moral  state  being  the  thing  we  attend  to  independent 
of  any  source  from  which  it  may  have  sprung.  The  system 


1  "  Cur  non  annuimus  esse  quosdam 
natura  misericordes,  si  natura  quosdam 
non  negamus  excordes?  Sunt  cnim 


nonnulla  congenita,  quse  in  atate  qua 
usus  incipit  esse  rationis,  sicut  ipsa  ratio, 
incipiunt  apparere." — Op.Imp.  1.4.  c.  1 29. 


F   3 


70  THE    PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

of  trial  and  probation  under  which  we  are  placed  is  thus  to 
some  extent  a  modified  one ;  not  throwing  us  wholly  upon 
ourselves,  to  work  our  way  up  to  the  virtuous  character  by 
the  power  of  the  mere  will,  but  more  or  less,  and  in  portions, 
endowing  us  with  it,  and  producing  in  us  to  begin  with  the 
ultimate  forms  of  moral  being. 

And  it  is  proper,  as  a  further  answer  to  the  Pelagian 
confined  idea  of  virtue  to  add,  that  no  exact  limit  is,  to  the 
eye  of  reason  apparent,  to  the  operation  of  such  a  power  of 
infusing  virtue  into  the  human  soul.  It  would  undoubtedly 
be  something  like  a  contradiction  to  suppose  that  the  dis- 
tinctive effect  of  trial  could  be  obtained  without  trial  as  the 
cause,  and  it  must  be  granted  that  there  must  be  some 
ultimate  difference  in  favour  of  that  virtue  which  is,  over 
that  which  is  not,  the  effect  of  trial.  But  there  is  no  other 
apparent  goal  to  an  untried  virtue.  We  know  that  a  certain 
excitement  of  the  feelings  produces  a  pleasure  in  virtue,  and 
that  particular  circumstances,  junctures,  appeals  from  without, 
act  with  an  exciting  power  upon  the  feelings,  kindling  zeal, 
enthusiasm,  and  love.  But  this  being  the  case,  it  is  im- 
possible to  say  to  what  extent  this  system  of  impulse  and 
excitement  existing  in  our  constitution  might  be  carried ; 
what  duration  these  conditions  of  mind  are  in  themselves 
capable  of,  and  whether  they  might  not  be  made,  by  Divine 
power  applying  a  fit  machinery  and  succession  of  exciting 
causes,  permanent.  We  only  know  that  such  a  system 
would  not  serve  that  particular  end  for  which  the  present 
system  of  trial  is  designed. 

But  the  Pelagian  was  further  wrong.  As  trial  is  not  the 
necessary  condition  of  all  goodness,  so  it  is  not  the  necessary 
condition  of  the  highest  kind  of  goodness  always.  The  system 
of  probation  points  according  to  the  reason  of  the  case,  to 
its  own  termination.  It  is  designed  for  an  end ;  but  the  end, 
when  attained,  implies  the  cessation  of  the  means.  There  is 
a  plain  incongruity  in  the  perfected  being  remaining  still  de- 
pendent on  a  contingent  will,  and  exposed  to  moral  risk;  i.  e. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  71 

being  for  ever  on  his  trial.  A  time  must  come,  then,  when 
this  will  cease,  when  there  will  be  no  more  deciding  between 
good  and  evil,  when  that  power  of  choice  which  makes  our 
virtue  here  will  be  over,  and  the  goodness  of  the  moral 
creature  will  be  necessary  goodness,  from  which  he  will  not 
be  able  to  depart  for  evermore. 

And  this  consideration  is  much  confirmed  by  another. 
The  trial  of  the  will  is  undoubtedly  the  condition  here  of 
the  highest  kind  of  virtue ;  but  it  must  be  admitted  at  the 
same  time  that  it  produces  this  virtue  in  an  incipient  and 
elementary  stage.  A  distinction  must  be  made  between 
trial  itself  and  its  effects.  The  undergoing  of  trial  is  the 
intensest  moral  act  we  know  of;  but  when  we  leave  the 
primary  stage  of  resistance  made,  strength  manifested, 
and  difficulty  overcome,  and  look  for  the  results,  we  are 
disappointed.  Virtue,  which  is  the  result  of  this  process, 
and  arises  wholly  from  effort  or  self-discipline,  is  deficient 
in  its  crowning  characteristic — its  grace,  or  what  moralists 
call  its  beauty.  It  betrays  effort,  conscious  aim  and 
design ;  is  practised  with  too  much  apparent  system  and 
method ;  it  wants  ease  and  naturalness ;  and  is  more  or 
less  hard,  formal,  and  artificial,  and  to  a  spectator  unat- 
tractive, which  it  is  not  its  proper  nature  to  be.  Thus, 
take  a  person  of  an  ambitious  and  assuming  habit  of  mind 
originally,  who  has  come  to  the  resolution  to  cultivate 
humility  ;  how  little  progress  does  he  appear  to  make  in  the 
task  compared  with  the  sincerity  of  his  intentions.  Whatever 
acts  he  may  do  in  conformity  with  his  design,  and  however 
he  may  succeed  in  imposing  on  himself  a  certain  general  line 
of  behaviour,  something  is  wanting  to  animate  it ;  the  vital 
spirit  keeps  aloof,  and  some  envious  influence  from  original 
temper  still  works  below  to  mar  the  growth  of  discipline. 
Compare  this  acquired  virtue  with  the  natural  virtue  of 
humility  as  seen  in  any  one  of  a  gentle  and  humble  dis- 
position by  nature,  how  imperfect,  how  abortive,  does 
the  result  of  human  effort  appear  by  the  side  of  the  Divine 

F    4 


72  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

gift?  Were  present  effects  alone  to  be  considered,  it  were 
better  to  be  simply  shone  upon  by  the  creative  grace  of 
God,  and  without  labour  of  our  own  to  receive  straight 
from  His  hands  an  unearned  virtue.  And  this  poverty  in 
acquired  virtues  arises  from  the  very  fact  that  they  are 
acquired,  from  the  very  manner  of  their  growth  and  forma- 
tion. It  is  essential  to  perfect  virtue  that  it  should  be 
truly  natural  and  part  of  ourselves ;  and  self-discipline, 
care,  and  Culture,  much  as  they  can  do,  cannot  make  a  nature. 
For  though  custom  is  called  a  second  nature  to  express 
its  great  power,  it  only  in  truth  renders  natural  or  easy  to 
us  the  original  act  which  it  adopts.  And  therefore  if  this 
act  is  one  of  self-control,  or  resistance  to  evil,  it  only 
renders  resistance  to  evil  easy,  not  goodness  itself  natural. 
Custom,  in  short,  improves  a  character  upon  its  old  basis, 
but  does  not  give  a  new  one,  or  make  a  man  what  Scripture 
calls  a  new  creature.  Nor,  in  fact,  do  we  see  it  perform 
even  this  inferior  function  perfectly.  For  it  must  be  asked, 
with  all  the  correcting  force  of  custom,  where  do  we  see 
in  the  world  what  may,  in  a  thorough  sense,  be  called 
renovation  of  character  ?  Nor  do  I  mean  an  eradication 
wholly  of  wrong  tendencies,  but  even  a  complete  and  suc- 
cessful suppression  of  them  existing.  A  serious  fault  ori- 
ginally attaching  to  a  character  assumes  in  some  persons 
subtler  forms  and  a  more  discreet  and  politic  bearing,  and 
is  finely  trained  and  educated  rather  than  really  resisted. 
In  others  it  meets  a  resistance ;  but  where  is  it  suppressed, 
so  that,  after  a  life  of  self -improvement,  we  do  not  see  it  ? 
The  possibility  of  true  moral  renovation  is  a  truth  of 
faith  rather  than  of  experience. 

But  such  being  the  defects  inherent  in  the  system  of 
trial,  if  virtue  is  ever  to  be  perfect  and  what  it  ought  to 
be,  it  must  be  removed  from  this  basis  altogether.  It  must 
in  a  future  state  become  in  a  way  indigenous  in  us.  It 
must  become  a  nature,  an  inspiration,  a  gift ;  be  cut  away 
completely  from  the  ground  of  effort ;  and  be  like  what 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  73 

we  call  natural  goodness  here,  though  with  this  important 
difference,  that  it  will  have  been  produced  by  trial.  That 
is,  to  become  what  it  ought  to  be,  it  must  become  necessary. 

The  highest  and  the  perfect  state  of  the  will,  then,  is  a 
state  of  necessity ;  and  the  power  of  choice,  so  far  from  being 
essential  to  a  true  and  genuine  will,  is  its  weakness  and  defect. 
"What  can  be  a  greater  sign  of  an  imperfect  and  immature 
state  of  the  will  than  that,  with  good  and  evil  before  it,  it 
should  be  in  suspense  which  to  do  ?  That  it  should  take  the 
worse  alternative  is  its  prostration ;  but  that  it  should  be  even 
undetermined  is  weakness.  Even  with  the  good  action  done, 
does  not  a  great  sense  of  imperfection  attend  the  thought 
that  it  was  but  an  instant  ago  uncertain  whether  it  would 
be  done  or  not  ?  And,  as  we  dwell  in  recollection  on  the 
state  of  our  will  previous  to  its  decision,  in  that  interval  of 
suspense  in  which  we  might  have  acted  in  one  way  or 
another,  does  not  so  unsteady  and  indeterminate  a  source  of 
action  interfere  even  with  the  comfort  of  certainty  which  is 
derived  from  the  action  as  being  done  ?  Is  not  the  circum- 
stance that  it  was  but  just  now  uncertain  whether  it  would 
be  done  or  not  a  surviving  reflection  upon  the  agent  ?  Was 
it  a  sort  of  luck  that  he  did  it  ?  And  would  he  do  it  again  if 
tried  again  ? 

We  have  indeed  at  first  an  idea  that  the  power  of  choice  is 
that  which  ennobles  and  dignifies  the  will,  and  that  the  will 
would  be  an  imperfect  one  without  it :  but  this  arises  from  a 
misconception.  The  power  of  choosing  good  or  evil  is  indeed 
that  which  ennobles  the  will  of  man  as  compared  with  the 
lower  wills  of  the  brute  creation  ;  but  it  is  not  therefore  the 
perfection  of  man's  will.  If  we  imagine  it  to  be  so,  we 
appear  to  attach  this  value  to  it,  for  this  reason,  viz.,  because 
a  power  in  the  will  of  determining  itself  either  way  is  power, 
and  we  suppose  power  to  be  an  advantage.  But  power  is  not 
itself  an  advantage.  In  our  ordinary  mode  of  speaking, 
indeed,  we  regard  it  as  such ;  because  we  ordinarily  associate 
power  with  an  advantageous  subject-matter,  or  think  of  it  as 


74  THE   PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

the  power  to  do  things  which  are  advantageous  to  ourselves. 
But  power  in  itself  is  neither  an  advantage  nor  the  contrary, 
but  depends  entirely  on  its  object,  or  that  which  it  has  the 
power  to  do,  for  being  the  one  or  the  other.  The  power  to 
do  that  which  is  injurious  to  oneself  is  a  disadvantage,  inas- 
much as  it  involves  the  chance  of  injury  ;  and  the  power  to 
do  evil  is  the  power  to  injure  oneself.  Such  power  has  no 
more  an  advantage  as  power  than  it  has  as  liability.  It  is 
true  that,  when  the  subject-matter  of  power  is  good,  then  the 
power  to  accomplish  it  has  an  excellence  as  power ;  that  is  to 
say,  it  is  an  additional  advantage  that  the  good  which  happens 
to  us  is  from  ourselves,  and  not  from  an  external  source. 
And  on  this  ground  the  attribute  of  power  as  belonging  to 
the  Supreme  Being  is  an  excellent  attribute :  it  being  an 
excellence  that  the  good  which  He  enjoys  comes  from  Himself, 
and  not  from  any  other  source. 

The  actions,  again,  which  the  good  will  perform  in  a  future 
state  of  necessity  will  not  be  the  less  good  on  that  account, 
and  because  they  do  not  proceed  from  a  power  of  choice.  It 
is  true  that  in  one  sense  a  good  act  which  proceeds  from  the 
exercise  of  a  power  of  choice  is  more  meritorious  than  one 
which  proceeds  from  a  will  acting  necessarily  right.  If  we 
measure  the  merit  of  an  action  by  the  degree  in  which  it 
is  in  advance  of  the  general  condition  of  the  agent,  then  un- 
doubtedly an  action  which  proceeds  from  a  will  determined 
necessarily  to  good  has  no  merit,  because  it  is  simply  on  a 
level  with,  and  not  at  all  in  advance  of  such  a  will.  On  the 
other  hand,  an  action  which  proceeds  from  a  will  which  has 
to  exert  a  power  of  choice  in  order  to  compass  it,  has  merit, 
because  it  is  in  advance  of  such  a  will ;  inasmuch  as  the 
certainty  of  an  action  done  is  an  advance  upon  the  mere 
power  of  doing  it.  But  it  is  evident  that  that  which  is  here 
spoken  of  is  not  the  positive  merit  of  an  action,  but  only  a 
relative  one ;  its  merit  as  compared  with  the  condition  and 
ability  of  the  agent.  A  will  which  acts  of  necessity  for 
good  is  the  very  strongest  will  on  the  side  of  good ;  and 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 


75 


therefore,  compared  with  the  ability  of  this  agent,  a  good  act 
is  a  little  result.  A  will  which  has  to  exert  a  power  of  choice, 
and  use  struggle  and  effort,  is  a  weaker  will ;  and  therefore 
a  good  action,  as  compared  with  the  ability  of  this  agent,  is  a 
greater  result.  The  superior  merit,  then,  of  a  good  act,  in  this 
case,  is  arrived  at  by  comparing  it  with  the  weakness  of  the 
agent ;  in  the  same  way  that  the  merit  of  a  work  of  art  is 
sometimes  arrived  at  by  comparing  it  with  the  inferiority  of 
the  instrument  by  which  it  was  executed.  It  is  a  merit, 
therefore,  which  tells  against  the  perfection  of  the  will,  and 
not  in  its  favour.  The  act,  as  such,  if  we  can  separate  the 
act  from  the  will,  is  more  meritorious ;  but  that  very  superior 
merit  of  the  act  is  gained  at  the.  cost  of  the  will,  from  which 
it  proceeds.  The  act  is  better  because  the  agent  is  worse. 

What  has  been  said  of  natural  or  necessary  goodness  may 
be  said  of  natural  or  necessary  evil.  Amid  the  obscurity 
which  attaches  to  this  class  of  questions,  something  to  which 
mankind  had  borne  large  testimony  would  be  relinquished 
in  denying  the  existence  of  bad  natural  dispositions.  And 
the  system  of  trial  points  as  much  to  a  necessary  evil  state 
as  it  does  to  a  necessary  good  one  as  its  termination.  It 
must  be  added,  that  the  law  of  custom  unhappily  produces 
much  nearer  approaches  in  this  life  to  a  necessary  state  in  evil 
than  it  does  to  the  same  in  good ;  furnishing  a  proof  of  the 
compatibleness  of  a  necessary  with  a  culpable  or  sinful  state, 
to  which  Augustine  often  appeals  in  defending  the  doctrine 
of  original  sin  against  the  Pelagian  objection  on  that  head.1 


1  "  Consuetude  fructus  est  voluntatis, 
quoniam  ex  voluntate  gignitur,  quae 
tamen  id  quod  agit,  negat  se  agere 
voluntate." — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  103. 
The  admission  of  Julian,  "  Evenire 
hominibus  affectionalem  qualitatem, 
atque  ita  inhaerescere,  u't  aut  magnis 
molitionibus,  aut  nullis  separetur  om- 
nino,"  and  the  Pelagian  interpreta- 
tion of  the  text  Quod  nolo  malum  hoc 
ago,  on  the  ground  of  custom,  were 
thus  turned  to  the  account  of  original 
*in.  "  Ac  per  hoc  etiam  secundum  vos 
peccandi  necessitas  unde  abstinere  li- 
berum  non  est,  illius  peccati  pcena  fuit, 


a  quo  abstinere  liberum  fuit." — L.  1.  c. 
105.  "  'Dicis  quod  contrarium  sit  neces- 
sitas  et  voluntas,  ita  ut  se  mutua  impug- 
natione  consumant ; '  inde  nos  arguens 
quod  «  alterum  alterius  subdamus  effec- 
tui,  dicentes  necessitatem  de  fructibus 
voluntatis  exortam,'  cum  videas  neces- 
sitatem consuetudinis  fructum  esse  ma- 
nifestissimum  voluntatis.  Nonne  quod 
tibi  impossibile  visum  est,  '  sua  se 
voluntas  multiplication  delevit,  et  sta- 
tum  proprium  operata  mutavit,'  quse 
multiplicata  necessitatem  ronsuctudinis 
fecit." — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  103. 


76  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

The  rational  doctrine,  then,  of  voluntariness,  i.e.  how  far 
the  trial  of  the  will  is  involved  in  the  nature  of  virtue  and 
vice  is  a  modified  one.  Freewill  and  necessity  have  both 
their  place  in  it,  nor  does  it  oppose  the  necessary  to  the 
voluntary.  But  the  Pelagian  adopted  an  extreme  and  un- 
qualified doctrine  on  this  head;  throwing  everything  upon 
the  direct  choice  or  exertion  of  the  will,  and  separating 
absolutely  the  necessary  from  the  voluntary.  Virtue,  in  the 
heavenly  state,  then,  could  be  no  virtue  in  his  eyes,  be- 
cause it  had  ceased  to  require  effort  and  choice.  He  allowed, 
so  far  as  his  language  went,  no  room  for  an  ultimate  and 
perfect  state,  and  established  an  eternal  restless  contingency 
in  the  moral  world.  Not,  however,  to  fasten  this  extreme 
meaning  upon  his  language,  which  was  perhaps  hardly 
intended,  inasmuch  as  the  Pelagian  nowhere  denies  the 
received  doctrine  of  a  future  state ;  and  understanding  him 
only  to  mean  that  a  man  could  not  be  good  or  bad  in  this 
life  except  by  his  own  individual  choice,  his  position  is  still 
a  narrow  and  one-sided  one.  The  general  sense  of  mankind 
is  certainly  on  the  side  of  there  being  good  and  bad  natural 
dispositions,  and  we  attach  the  idea  of  goodness  to  generous* 
excitements  and  emotions,  which  do  not  arise  from  any  effort 
of  the  will  but  spontaneously.  The  Christian  doctrine  of 
grace  which  makes  goodness  a  divine  gift  or  inspiration 
is  thus  fully  in  accordance  with  the  instincts  of  our  nature, 
while  the  Pelagian  doctrine,  which  reduces  all  virtue  to 
effort  and  discipline,  is  felt  as  a  confinement  and  an  artificial 
limit  in  morals. 

There  are,  however,  two  distinct  questions  properly  in- 
volved in  this  subject;  one,  whether  the  trial  of  the  will 
is,  as  opposed  to  implanted  dispositions,  essential  to  the 
nature  of  virtue  or  vice ;  the  other  relating  to  the  determi- 
nation of  the  will  on  its  trial, — whether  its  self-determination 
is  necessary  to  the  nature  of  virtue  and  vice  as  distinct  to 
its  determination  from  without.  The  Pelagian  thought  it 
essential  that,  for  this  purpose,  the  will  should  determine 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 


77 


itself,  that  virtue  and  vice,  in  order  to  be  such,  must  be 
of  our  own  originating.  S.  Augustine  maintained  a  goodness 
and  a  sinfulness  to  which  the  will  was  determined  from 
without.  Both  these  positions  are  true,  if  held  together,  and 
both  false  if  held  apart. 

3.  To  the  questions  of  the  power  of  the  will,  and  the 
nature  of  virtue  and  vice,  succeeded  the  question  of  the 
Divine  justice. 

The  doctrine  of  original  sin  described  all  mankind  as 
punished  for  the  sin  of  Adam,  deriving  a  positive  sinful- 
ness,  and  even  a  necessity  to  sin,  a  slavery,  and  a  captivity 
from  it.  But  how  was  it  consistent  with  justice  that  one  man 
should  be  punished  for  the  sin  of  another ;  that  mankind 
should  be  created  guilty,  and  derive  from  one  particular  act 
committed  before  they  were  born  a  positive  necessity  to  sin  ? l 
The  objection  of  the  Pelagian  was  met  in  two  ways;  first,  by 
an  appeal  to  mystery ;  and,  secondly,  by  an  appeal  to  facts. 

1.  The  objection  that  it  was  contrary  to  the  Divine  justice 
to  punish  one  man  for  the  sin  of  another  was  met  by  an 
appeal  to  mystery,  and  the  answer  that  the  Divine  justice 
was  incomprehensible.  And  this  was  a  sound  and  proper 
answer,  but  the  form  in  which  it  was  put  was  not  wholly 
faultless. 

For  it  is  one  thing  to  say  that  the  Divine  justice  is  incom- 
prehensible, and  another  thing  to  say  that  the  Divine  justice 
is  different  from  human  justice ;  or  that  we  are  to  have  a 
different  idea  altogether  of  justice  as  a  human  and  as  a 
Divine  characteristic.  In  saying  that  the  Divine  justice  is 
incomprehensible  we  make  no  assertion  about  it  at  all,  and 
therefore  do  not  establish  any  contradiction  between  it  and 
our  natural  ideas  of  justice.  Having  conceived  of  it,  so  far 


1  "  Ais  credere  te  quidem  conditorem 
Deura,  sed  malorum  hominum  .... 
et  Dei  sanctitati  informationem  sceleris 
appulisti.  Great  igitur  malum  Deus  et 
puniuntur  innocentes  propter  quod  fecit 
Deus;  et  imputat  hominibus  crimen 


manuum  suarum  Deus;  et  quod  per- 
suasit  diabolus  tenuiter,  solerter  et  per 
severanter  fingit  et  protegit  et  format 
Deus.  Et  fructum  ab  homine  bonitatis 
reposcit,  cui  malum  ingenuit  Deus." — 
Julian,  ap.  Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  1 24.  et  seq. 


78 


THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 


[CHAP.  III. 


as  we  conceived  of  it  at  all,  as  the  ordinary  natural  quality 
so  called,  we  only  cease  at  a  certain  point  to  form  any  con- 
ception about  it.  But  to  say  that  the  Divine  justice  is 
different  from  human  is  to  confuse  our  moral  notions  alto- 
gether. Pressed  by  the  Pelagian  with  the  strong  testimo- 
nies in  Scripture  to  the  rule  of  natural  justice,  that  no  man 
should  be  punished  except  for  .his  own  sins,  S.  Augus- 
tine properly  appealed  to  another  set  of  texts  which  repre- 
sented God  as  visiting  the  sins  of  the  fathers  upon  the 
children1,  and  showed  that  Scripture  asserted  an  incom- 
prehensible as  well  as  a  natural  justice.  But  he  further 
proceeded  to  explain  away  these  assertions  of  the  rule  of  na- 
tural justice  itself,  as  intended  to  apply  to  human,  not  to  the 
Divine  conduct.  The  rule  laid  down  in  Deuteronomy,  that 
the  "  fathers  shall  not  be  put  to  death  for  the  children, 
neither  the  children  for  the  fathers,  but  every  man  for  his 
own  sin  2,"  was  interpreted  as  applying  to  human  judges  only, 
not  to  God,  who  was  altogether  free  from  such  an  obligation.3 
And  the  natural  rejoinder  of  the  Pelagian,  that  God  was 
not  less  just  than  He  wanted  man  to  be,  was  overruled  by 
the  argument,  that  God  did  many  things  which  it  would  be 
wrong  for  man  to  do.4  But  such  an  argument  was  fallacious. 
The  Being  who  gave  life  has  a  right  to  take  it  away, 


1  Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  30. 

2  Deut.  xxiv.  16. 

3  Augustine  :    "  Aliter  mandavit  ho- 
mini,  aliter  judicavit  ipse." — Op.  Imp. 
1.  3.  c.  33.     Julian  :  "  Si  qua?  sunt  justa 
a  nobis  fieri  velit,   et   ipse  faciat  quod 
injustum  est :  justiores  nos,  quam  ipse 
est,   cupit   videri ;  imo   non   justiores, 
sed  nos  aequos,  et  se  iniquum." — Julian, 
ap.  Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  24. 

4  "  Hoc  quidem  pracceptum  dedit  ho- 
minibus  judicantibus,  ne  pater  pro  filio, 
vel  fill  us  pro  patre  more  ret  ur.     Caete- 
rum  judicia  sua  Deus  non  alligavit  hac 
lege." — Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.12.     "  Non  est 
leg  is  sua?  praevaricator  Deus  quando  aliud 
facit  Deus  ut  Deus,  aliud  imperat  homini 
ut  homini  ?" — c.  23.     "  Facit  enim  Deus 


aliquando  contra  quse  facienda  mandavit. 
Nee  opus  est  ut  multa  commcmorem. 
Mandavit  homini  Scriptura  die-ens  '  non 
telaudet  os  tuum '  (Prov.  xxvii.  2.),  nee 
tamen  dicendus  est  arrogans  aut  super- 
bus,  cum  se  innumerabiliter  laudare  non 
desinit." — c.  22.  "Hoc  judicium  Deus 
hominum  voluit  esse  non  suum,  qui 
dixit,  Reddam  peccata  patrum  in  filios. 
(Deut.  v.  9.)  Quod  etiam  per  homi- 
nem  fecit,  quando  per  Jesum  Nave  non 
solum  Achan,  sed  etiam  filios  ejus  occi- 
dit ;  vel  per  eundem,  filios  Canaanorum 
etiam  parvulos  damnavit." — c.  30, 
"  Quis  enim  homo  Justus  si  nit  perpe- 
trari  scelus  quod  habet  in  potestate  non 
sinere  ?  Et  tamen  sinit  haec  Deus." 
—  c.  24. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 


79 


and  the  supremely  good  Being  has  a  right  to  praise  Him- 
self; but  the  difference  in  the  rightfulness  of  such  acts  in 
the  case  of  God  and  man  is  not  any  difference  of  the 
moral  law  by  which  God  and  the  creature  act,  but  a  dif- 
ference in  their  respective  positions,  which  justifies  these 
acts  in  God,  and  not  in  the  creature.  Indeed,  the  chapter 
in  Ezekiel  applies  the  rule  of  natural  justice  directly  to 
the  Divine  conduct,  and  represents  God  as  asserting  of 
Himself,  that  He  punishes  no  man  except  for  his  own  sins, 
and  so  gives  no  ground  whatever  for  such  a  distinction. 
But  this  declaration  was  not  allowed  its  obvious  interpreta- 
tion, as  stating  a  universal  law  of  the  Divine  dealings, 
but  only  a  special  prophetical  one,  as  alluding  to  the  Divine 
mercy  under  the  Gospel  dispensation  and  the  covenant  of 
grace1,  under  which  the  effect  of  original  sin,  the  punishment 
of  mankind  for  the  sin  of  their  first  parent,  was  removed. 

But  the  punishment  which  all  mankind  suffered  for  the 
sin  of  Adam  was  punishment  of  a  peculiar  kind ;  because  it 
was  not  only  pain  but  sin,  and  not  only  sin  but  captivity 
to  sin  and  inability  to  do  any  good  thing.  This  worst  and 
strongest  penalty,  then,  attaching  to  the  sin  of  Adam,  was  de- 
fended by  an  appeal  to  a  remarkable  law  of  God's  judicial 
administration,  discernible  in  his  natural  providence,  and 
specially  attested  by  Scripture ;  the  rule,  viz.  of  punishing 
sin  by  further  sin,  peccatum  pcena  peccati,  —  a  rule  which, 
in  the  present  instance,  only  received  a  mysterious  applica- 
tion, as  being  extended  to  the  case  of  a  mysterious  and  incom- 
prehensible sin. 

S.  Augustine  argued,  then,  that  original  sin  was  real  sin  in 


1  "  Haec  per  Ezechielem  prophetam 
promissio  est  novi  Testamenti,  quam 
non  intelligis,  ubi  Deus  regenerates  a 
generatis  si  jam  in  majoribus  aetatibus 
sunt,  secundum  propria  facta  discernit. " 
— Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  38.  "  '  Si  dicetur  am- 
plius  parabola ' :  .  .  .  non  arguit  quia 
diccbcttur,  sed  permittit  ubi  non  dicatur 


.  .  .  .  '  Non  dicetur  in  Israel '  recte 
diceres,  si  veros  Israelitas  regeneratos 
videres  in  quibus  hoc  non  dicetur." — 
c.  39.  41.  Jeremiah  xxxi.  21 — 32.  is 
adduced  to  confirm  this  interpretation. 
"  In  diebus  Hits  non  dicent  ultra.  Patres 
comederunt,"  &c. —  c.  84.  See  Contra, 
Jul.  Pel.  1.  6.  n.  82. 


80 


THE   PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


the  being  in  whom  it  resided ;  and  being  such,  was  justly 
punishable  by  the  abandonment  of  the  person  guilty  of  it,  to 
sin ;  that  the  natural  man,  therefore,  could  not  plead  his  want 
of  moral  power  as  any  excuse  for  his  sins,  any  more  than  a 
man  in  common  life,  who  had  contracted  a  bad  habit,  could 
plead  the  dominion  of  that  habit  as  such  an  excuse.  That 
bad  habit  might  be  so  strong  that  he  could  not  help  com- 
mitting the  sins  to  which  it  inclined  him;  but  he  was  responsible 
for  those  sins,  in  that  he  was  responsible  for  their  cause.  In 
like  manner,  man  was  responsible  for  the  sins  which  in  the 
state  of  original  sin  he  could  not  avoid,  in  that  he  was 
responsible  for  original  sin  itself.1 

Two  difficulties,  however,  presented  themselves  to  the 
application  of  such  a  law  to  the  case  of  original  sin.  In 
the  first  place,  though  it  is  true  that  all  sin,  so  far  as  it 
is  indulged,  predisposes  the  mind  to  further  sin,  or  creates 
a  sinful  habit,  this  effect  is  in  proportion  to  the  amount 
of  such  indulgence;  and  it  is  only  extreme  indulgence 
that  produces  an  uncontrollable  habit,  or  a  loss  of  freewill : 
whereas  the  sin  of  our  first  parents,  to  which  this  extreme 
effect  was  attached,  was  but  a  single  sin,  and  not  appar- 
ently a  heinous  one.  But  the  sin  of  our  first  parents,  it 
was  replied,  was  neither  a  single  nor  a  light  one.  The 
outward  act  was  but  the  consummation  of  a  course  of  inward 
sin,  self-pleasing,  pride,  and  departure  from  God.  And,  even 
were  its  subject-matter  light,  the  sin  itself  was  disobedience  ; 
the  more  wanton,  that  there  was  no  strength  of  passion  as 
yet  in  man's  nature  to  excuse  it.  Who  would  measure  the 


1  "  Sed  vos  isla  peccata  ex  illis  venire 
peccatis  quae  nulla  necessitate  commissa 
sunt,  in  illo  saltern  conceditis,  qui  dicit, 
*  Quod  nolo  malum  hoc  a</o.'  Qui  enim, 
ut  istara  patiatur  necessitatem,  non 
nisi  peccandi  consuetudine  premitur, 
procul  dubio  priusquam  peccaret,  non- 
dum  necessitate  consuetudinis  pre- 
mebatur.  Ac  per  hoc,  etiam  secundum 
vos,  peccandi  necessitas  unde  abstinere 


liberum  non  est,  illius  peccati  poena  fuit 
a  quo  abstinere  liberum  fuit,  quando 
nullum  pondus  necessitatis  urge  bat. 
Cur  ergo  non  creditis  tantum  saltern 
valuisse  illud  primi  hominis  ineffa- 
biliter  grande  peccatum,  ut  eo  vitia- 
retur  humana  natura  universa,  quan- 
tum valet  nunc  in  homine  uno  secunda 
natura?" — Op.  Imp.  1.  i.  c.  105. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 


81 


greatness  of  a  first  sin  as  being  the  first,  a  departure 
from  created  rectitude,  the  primary  act  of  the  will  for  evil, 
to  which  no  previous  evil  predisposed  ?  But  the  subject- 
matter  was  only  externally  light,  not  really,  being  not  a  mere 
fruit  of  a  tree,  but  good  out  of  their  existing  state  of 
union  with  God,  which  was  grasped  at;  showing  a  greediness 
for  which  God  did  not  suffice ;  and  that  alien  good  being, 
moreover,  the  presumptuous  position  of  being  gods  them- 
selves —  a  pride  which  was  the  very  counterpart  of  our  Lord's 
humility,  who  emptied  Himself  of  a  Divinity  which  was 
His  right,  while  they  grasped  at  a  divinity  to  which  they 
had  none.1 

But,  however  serious  the  sin  of  our  first  parents  might 
be,  a  much  greater  difficulty  presented  itself  in  the  question 
how  individuals  could  be  responsible  for  a  sin  to  which 
they  were  not  themselves  personally  parties.  But  this 
difficulty  was  overruled  by  an  appeal  to  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin  itself,  which  rested  upon  Scripture,  and  the 
very  foundation  of  which  was,  that  all  men  had  in  some 
sense  .sinned  in  Adam.  This  was,  indeed  a  mystery,  and 
beyond  our  comprehension,  but  faith  accepted  it  as  true ; 
and  if  true,  the  basis  which  this  argument  required  was  sup- 
plied to  it.  Such  an  explanation  was  only  the  application 
to  a  mysterious  subject-matter  of  a  law,  which  we  recognise 
as  just  in  that  sphere  of  providence  which  comes  under 
our  knowledge.  We  see  the  justice  of  the  law  that  sin 


1  "  In  occulto  autcm  mail  esse 
coeperunt,  ut  in  apertam  inobedientiam 
laberentur." — De  Civit.  Dei,  1.  xiv.  c. 
13.  et  seq.  "  Quantum  malum  sola 
inobedientia." — De  Gen.  ad  literara, 
1.  8.  c.  13.  "  Noluit  homo  inter  de- 
licias  paradisi  servare  justitiam." — De 
Pecc.  Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  2.  n.  55. 
«'  Quid  avarius  illo  cui  Deus  sufficere 
non  potuit."  — In  Ep.  Joannis  ad  Ear- 
thos,  Tr.  8.  n.  6.  "  Rapere  voluerunt 
divinitatem,  perdiderunt  felicitatem." — 
In  Tr.  68.  n.  9.  "  Tanto  gravius  pec- 


cavit  quanto  ibi  major  non  peccandi 
facilitas  erat,  ubi  vitiata  natura  non- 
dum  erat." — Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  189. 
"  Tanta  impietate  peccavit  quantam 
nos  metiri  atque  aestimare  non  pos- 
sumus." — Ibid.  1.  3.  c  65.  "Illius 
natura  quanto  magis  sublimiter  stabat, 
tanto  magis  graviter  occidit.  .  .  .  Pec- 
catum  quanto  incredibilius,  tanto  dam- 
nabilius." — Ibid.  1.  6.  c.  22.  See  Bull 
on  the  State  of  Man  before  the  Fall, 
vol.  ii.  (Oxford  ed.)  p.  64. 


82 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


hardens  the  heart,  as  applied  to  the  case  of  actual  sin, 
because  we  know  the  sin ;  we  see  a  justice  in  such  sin, 
long  indulged,  leading  to  actual  slavery  and  loss  of  freewill : 
but  the  justice  of  this  law  as  applied  to  the  case  of  original 
sin  was  a  mysterious  and  incomprehensible  justice,  that 
which  is  its  subject-matter  being  a  mysterious  and  incom- 
prehensible sin. 

When  S.  Augustine,  however,  left  the  ground  of  mystery 
for  that  of  reasoning,  he  adopted  doubtful  positions.  The 
appeal  to  the  Divine  foreknowledge  of  man's  evil  lives, 
in  spite  of  which  He  creates  them,  as  a  defence  of  a  crea- 
tion under  a  necessity  to  evil,  was  plausible l ;  but  there  is 
plainly  a  difference  between  exposing  men  to  the  risk,  and 
subjecting  them  to  the  certainty  of  moral  evil,  and  that 
evil  in  some  cases  eternal.  The  issue  being  alike  foreseen 
in  both  cases ;  in  the  one  the  sinner  has  had  the  opportunity 
of  a  better  issue  given  him,  and  has  therefore  only  himself 
to  blame  for  the  worse  one;  in  the  other  he  has  had  no 
such  opportunity.  The  appeal  to  God's  natural  providence 
and  his  support  and  nourishment  of  evil  men  in  the  world 


1  "  Ut  quid  creat  quos  impios  futures 
et  damnandos  esse  prsescivit."  —  Op. 
Imp.  1.  1.  c.  48.,  vid.  119.  121.;  1.  5. 
c.  13. 

The  argument,  however,  with  a 
modification,  may  claim  the  more  re- 
cent authority  of  Archbp.  Whately, 
who  says  :  "  We  should  be  very 
cautious  how  we  employ  such  weapons 
as  may  recoil  upon  ourselves  .  .  .  Why 
the  Almighty  does  not  cause  to  die  in 
the  cradle  every  infant  whose  future 
wickedness  and  misery,  if  suffered  to 
grow  up,  He  foresees,  is  what  no  system 
of  religion,  natural  or  revealed,  will 
enable  us  satisfactorily  to  account  for." 
— Essays  on  S.  Paul,  p.  88.  But  is 
there  not  some  confusion  of  thought 
in  this  argument?  As  stated  by  S. 
Augustine,  it  is  in  form  absurd.  For 
the  difficulty  in  the  constitution  of 
things  which  he  sets  against  that  of 
reprobation,  or  creating  a  being  to  be 


eternally  miserable,  is  this,  that  God 
foresees  men's  evil  lives  and  their  judi- 
cial result,  and  yet  creates  them.  But 
if  God  foresees  men's  evil  lives,  He  by 
the  hypothesis  creates  them,  and  it 
would  be  a  contradiction  that  He  should 
not.  Facts  cannot  first  be  foreseen, 
and  then  because  they  are  foreseen  be 
prevented.  Archbp.  Whately,  however, 
relieves  the  argument  from  this  ab- 
surdity, by  making  foresight  to  be  the 
foresight  "  of  men's  future  wickedness 
and  misery  if  suffered  to  grow  up. "  But 
what  can  be  meant  by  the  foresight  of 
events  which,  by  the  very  supposition, 
may  not  take  place  ?  This  alleged 
difficulty,  then,  in  the  constitution  of 
things,  cannot  be  stated  without  a  great 
absurdity  and  contradiction;  whereas 
the  difficulty  of  God  creating  a  being 
to  be  eternally  miserable  is  as  plain 
and  simple  a  one  as  can  be  conceived. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  83 

as  an  analogous  case  to  the  creation  of  men  as  evil,  was  still 
more  incorrect.1 

2.  The  objection  to  the  punishment  of  mankind  for  the 
sin  of  Adam,  on  the  score  of  the  Divine  justice,  was  an- 
swered by  an  appeal  to  facts ;  an  appeal  which  divided  into 
two  great  heads — the  fact  of  sin,  and  the  fact  of  pain. 

First,  how  were  we  to  account  for  the  fact  of  sin,  as 
it  met  us  in  the  world — the  universal  depravation  and  cor- 
ruption of  mankind  ?  could  we  account  for  this  by  chance, 
or  the  contingent  action  of  each  man's  freewill  ?  Or  did  it 
not  at  once  point  to  some  law  in  our  nature,  on  the  same 
principle  on  which,  in  the  physical  world  and  common  life, 
whenever  we  see  a  uniform  set  of  phenomena,  we  refer  them 
to  some  law  ? 

The  argument,  however,  for  original  sin  derived  from 
the  prevalence  of  actual  sin  in  the  world,  though  un- 
doubtedly sound  and  unanswerable,  requires  some  caution 
and  discrimination  in  the  use  of  it.  And  in  the  first  place 
it  must  be  observed  that,  when  we  examine  this  argument, 
we  find,  that  upon  a  nearer  view  it  divides  into  two  distinct 
arguments,  depending  upon  two  different  kinds  of  reasoning. 
One  is  the  argument  simply  of  cause  and  effect.  On  the 
principle  that  every  event  must  have  a  cause,  actual  sin 
must  have  a  cause  anterior  to  itself,  from  which  it  proceeds : 
and  for  the  same  reason  that  this  cause  is  wanted  itself, 
another  cause  is  wanted  for  it,  and  so  another  and  another 
in  succession,  till  we  arrive  at  some  origin  or  first  cause 
of  sin.  But  this  origin  of  sin  cannot  be  in  the  Divine 
will,  it  must  therefore  be  in  the  human ;  which  ultimate  and* 
original  evil  in  the  will  is  what  is  signified  by  original  sin. 

This   argument,  then,    for   original  sin,  does  not  at  all 


1  "  Sic  creat  malos  quomodo  pascit  et 
nutrit  malos." — De  Nupt.  et  Cone.  1.  2. 
n.  32,  33.  Julian :  "  Quod  pascit  Deus 
etiam  peccatores,  benignusque  est  super 
ingratos  et  malos  pietatis  est  ejus  tes- 

O    2 


timonium  non  malignitatis.  .  .  .  Vide 
ergo  quam  nescias  quid  loqueris,  qui  de 
exemplo  misericordise  voluisti  crudeli- 
tatem  probare," — Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  64. 


84 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVEKSY.  [CHAP.  Til. 


depend  on  the  amount  of  actual  sin  in  the  world,  but  would 
be  just  as  valid  on  the  supposition  of  one  sin,  as  on  that  of 
universal ;  original  sin  itself  following  from  the  simple  fact 
of  actual,  though  its  universality  depends  on  the  universality 
of  actual.  And  the  validity  of  this  argument  depends  on 
the  validity  of  the  general  argument  of  cause  and  effect,  or 
upon  the  truth  of  the  axiom,  that  every  event  must  have 
a  cause, — an  axiom  which  I  discussed  in  the  last  chapter, 
when  I  defined  the  degree  and  measure  of  truth  which 
belonged  to  it.  It  will  be  enough  to  say  here  of  this  rationale 
of  original  sin,  that  it  is  a  wholly  philosophical,  as  dis- 
tinguished from  a  scriptural  one;  because,  in  representing 
original  sin  as  anterior  to  all  actual  sin,  it  represents  it  as 
anterior  to  the  sin  of  Adam,  and  as  much  the  condition  of 
man  at  his  first  creation  as  it  ever  was  afterwards.1 

The  other  and  the  more  common  argument,  is  the  argu- 
ment of  probability, — that  it  is  contrary  to  the  doctrine  of 
chances,  that  every  one  of  those  innumerable  millions  that 
have  lived  in  the  world  should  have  been  a  sinner,  if  such 
sin  had  depended  on  the  mere  contingency  of  every  individual's 
freewill ;  such  a  universal  fact  evidently  proving  the  exist- 
ence of  some  law  of  sin  in  our  nature.  But  the  correctness 
of  this  argument  for  original  sin  depends  on  the  sense  in 
which  we  understand  sin  in  the  preliminary  statement,  that 
every  one  of  the  human  race  has  been,  and  is,  a  sinner. 

If  by  sin  is  meant  here  the  absence  of  perfection  only  — 
that  every  man  that  has  ever  lived  has  done  something 
wrong  in  the  course  of  his  life,  there  appears  to  be  nothing, 
even  in  a  universal  faultiness  of  the  human  race,  in  such  a 
sense,  more  than  may  be  accounted  for  on  the  principle  of 
each  man's  contingent  will,  or  that  requires  the  operation 
of  a  law.  For,  considering  the  length  of  human  life,  the 


1  Mr.  Coleridge,  in  his  "Aids  to 
Reflection,"  adopts  this  rationale  of 
original  sin,  and  discusses  it  with 


his    usual   mixture   of    obscurity   and 
power.      See  NOTE  XII. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  85 

constant  succession  of  temptations  in  it,  and  their  variety, 
the  multiplicity  of  relations  in  which  a  man  stands  to  others, 
all  of  which  have  to  be  fulfilled  in  order  to  constitute  him 
faultless,  is  there  anything  very  remarkable  in  the  coin- 
cidence that  every  man  should,  on  some  occasion  or  other  in 
his  life,  have  diverged  from  the  strict  duty  ?  If,  on  the  one 
hand,  it  may  be  said,  that  out  of  so  great  a  number  of 
individuals  as  there  have  been  in  the  world  some  few 
perfect  men  might  have  been  calculated  upon ;  on  the  other 
hand,  it  may  be  said  that,  with  so  vast  a  number  of  trials,  we 
could  not  calculate  any  one's  universal  success  under  them. 
The  chances  in  favour  of  cases  of  perfection  which  the 
number  of  individuals  in  the  world  presents,  are  met  by  the 
chances  against  it,  contained  in  the  number  of  trials  in  the 
life  of  each  individual. 

But  if  by  sin  we  understand  not  only  a  loss  of  perfection, 
but  positive  depravity,  certainly  the  general  fact  of  sin  in 
this  sense  cannot  be  accounted  for  on  the  mere  principle  of 
contingency.  Supposing  ourselves  calculating  beforehand 
the  result  of  the  action  of  freewill  in  the  human  race,  we 
should  have  no  more  right  to  calculate  on  general  depravity 
and  wickedness  as  the  result,  than  on  general  piety  and 
virtue.  Undoubtedly  there  is  this  important  distinction 
between  vice  and  virtue,  that  vice  is  pleasant,  and  virtue 
painful  at  the  time ;  and  it  may  be  thought  perhaps  that,  in 
making  any  calculations  beforehand  as  to  the  conduct  of 
mankind,  we  should  be  justified  in  expecting  that  the 
generality  would  do  what  was  easiest  at  the  time.  But  if 
any  one  will  examine  the  real  ground  on  which  he  forms  this 
expectation,  he  will  find  that  he  forms  it  upon  the  experience 
of  the  result,  and  not  upon  any  ground  of  antecedent  cal- 
culation. He  sees  that  this  is  the  general  way  in  which 
mankind  act,  and,  therefore,  he  imagines  himself  expecting 
it  beforehand.  But  it  is  evident  that,  in  calculating  the 
conduct  of  mankind  beforehand,  we  should  have  no  more 
right  to  calculate  on  a  general  preference  of  present  to  future 

G   3 


86  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

interests,  than  on  a  general  contrary  preference.  The  choice 
that  freewill  would  make  in  the  matter  would  be  as  probable 
one  way  as  another. 

Understanding  sin,  then,  in  the  sense  of  depravity  and 
wickedness,  the  general  fact  of  human  sinfulness  in  this 
sense  certainly  requires  some  law  of  sin  in  our  nature  as  its 
explanation ;  such  a  law  as  is  asserted  in  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin.  But  while  such  a  fact  must  be  allowed  as  a 
proof  of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  it  must  at  the  same 
time  be  remembered,  that  the  assertion  of  general  depravity 
and  wickedness  is  a  very  grave  assertion  to  make  respecting 
the  human  race.  It  is  an  assertion,  however,  which  rests  on 
a  ground  of  actual  observation  and  experience,  confirmed  by 
the  authority  of  Scripture,  and  is  true  in  two  different  ways. 

First,  every  man  is  depraved  in  the  sense  of  having  vile, 
selfish,  and  proud  desires,  which  have  a  certain  power  over 
him,  and  occupy  and  fill  his  mind  with  sufficient  strength 
and  frequency  to  constitute  a  depraved  condition  of  mind. 
A  certain  tendency  to  evil  is  indeed  no  more  than  what  is 
necessary  to  constitute  a  state  of  trial,  and  does  not  show 
depravity  or  corruption  in  the  moral  being.  But  it  is 
evident  that  evil  desire,  in  the  degree  in  which  it  exists  in 
human  nature,  is  more  than  such  a  tendency  as  this,  and  is 
in  itself  a  disease;  inasmuch  as  men  feel  it  as  something 
sinful  in  itself,  independent  of  its  gratification.  Test  even 
the  best  of  men,  with  this  strength  of  evil  desire  residing  in 
him,  by  a  perfect  standard,  and  it  must  be  seen  that  he  is  a 
corrupt  being,  whom  we  can  only  think  of  at  all  as  good  by 
a  kind  of  anticipation,  regarding  this  as  a  transient  condition 
of  mind,  of  which  he  is  one  day  to  be  relieved.  In  the  sense, 
then,  of  having  concupiscence,  which  hath  of  itself  the  nature 
of  sin,  all  mankind  are  depraved. 

Secondly,  the  generality  of  mankind  are  depraved  in  the 
sense  of  actual  bad  life  and  conduct ;  as  the  former  was  a  fact 
of  inward  experience,  this  latter  being  a  fact  of  observation. 
The  wickedness  of  the  generality  of  mankind  was  acknow- 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN  CONTKOVERSY. 


87 


ledged  even  by  the  heathen,  and  has  been  generally  admitted. 
It  is  proved,  therefore,  in  the  only  way  in  which  a  general 
fact  admits  of  being  proved,  viz.  by  large  general  and  con- 
sentient observation;  observation,  moreover,  which,  when  once 
made,  keeps  its  ground,  and  meets  with  comparatively  little 
contradiction.  It  is,  moreover,  strongly  asserted  in  Scripture, 
which  refers  to  it,  however,  as  a  known  and  ascertained  fact, 
rather  than  professes  to  reveal  it  in  the  first  instance.  Such 
being  the  case,  it  is  evident,  even  supposing  particular 
persons  should  say  that  their  own  observation  had  been  other- 
wise, that  their  individual  testimony  is  no  counterbalance  to 
the  general  observation  of  mankind.  And  though  the  reluc- 
tance of  all  persons  to  form  judgments  upon  their  relations, 
friends,  and  acquaintances  may  be  appealed  to,  as  counter- 
evidence  on  this  subject,  it  should  be  remembered  that  a 
judgment  of  charity  does  not  supersede  that  of  observation. 

Secondly,  the  defence  of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  on 
the  ground  of  fact,  from  the  objection  urged  on  the  score  of 
the  Divine  justice,  appealed  straight  to  the  great  fact  of  pain 
and  misery  in  the  world.  How  was  this  to  be  accounted  for? 
It  could  not  be  accounted  for  on  the  ground  of  men's  actual 
sins,  because  it  was  evidently  a  part  of  the  present  con- 
stitution of  nature,  and  in  the  case  of  infants  preceded 
actual  sin.  Anyhow,  then,  we  were  in  a  difficulty  with 
respect  to  the  Divine  justice  ;  for  if  we  gave  up  the  doctrine 
of  original  sin,  there  was  nothing  to  account  for  this  fact, 
and  the  charge  of  injustice  could  be  brought  against  God 
for  an  undeserved  infliction  of  pain. 1 


1  S.  Augustine,  in  Op.  Imp.  1.  1. 
c.  92.,  1.  2.  c.  89.  104.  116.  124.  139. 
144.,  1.  3.  c.  7.  48.  89.  95.  154.  198., 
1.  5.  c.  1.,  1.  6.  c.  7.  9.,  and  passim, 
refers  to  the  general  fact  of  human 
misery  as  a  proof  of  original  sin: 
"  Teste  ipsa  generis  humani  miseria 
peccatum  originale  monstratur."  —  L.  3. 
c.  89.  "  Constat  mala  hujus  vitse,  qui- 
bus  plenus  est  mundus  Manichaeos  cum 
Catholicis  confiteri :  sed  unde  sint  hsec 


non  utrosque  idem  dicere :  quod  ea 
Manichaei  tribuunt  alienae  naturae 
malse,  Catholici  vero  et  bonae  et  nostrae  ; 
sed  peccato  vitiatae,  meritoque  punitae." 
— L.  6.  c.  14.  "  Si  parvuli  sine  ullius 
peccati  merito  premuntur  gravi  jugo, 
iniquus  est  Deus." — L.  2.  c.  124.  "  Si 
ergo  nullum  esset  in  parvulis  ex  origine 
meritum  malum,  quicquid  mali  pati- 
untur  esset  injustum." — L.  3.  c.  204. 


G    4 


83 


THE    PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


The    argument,    however,    which   infers  sin    from   pain, 
should  be  used  with  caution  ;  we  do  not  know  enough  of  the 
whole  scheme   of  things   to  decide   whether,  distinct  from 
judicial  grounds,  pain  may  not  be  necessary  simply  as  a  pre- 
paration and  training  for  a  higher  state  of  existence.     That 
kind  of  pain  which  is  involved  in  effort  and  the  overcoming  of 
difficulty  we  do  not  naturally  regard  as  at  all  of  necessity  ju- 
dicial ;  and  S.  Augustine  exceeds  the  limits  of  a  common  sense 
judgment,  when  he  appeals  to  the  slow  and  gradual  growth 
of  the  understanding  in  man,  the  imbecility  of  infancy,  and 
the  difficulties  which  accompany  the  progress  of  education,  as 
evidences  of  the  Divine  wrath.1     But  pain  of  the  positive 
and  acute  kind  certainly  suggests  a  judicial  source;  nor  can 
we  reflect  on  the  dreadful  forms  of  misery  and  the  diseases, 
bodily  and  mental,  which  attach  to  human  nature,  without 
being  led  instinctively  to  the  idea  of  some  moral  evil  residing 
in  that  nature.     It  admits  perhaps  of  a  doubt,  whether  the 
overwhelming  nature  of  present  pain,  whether  as  a  sight  or 
feeling,  does  not  disorder  us  as  judges  on  such  a  question ; 
nor  can  we  say  for  certain  that,  supposing  ourselves  to  be 
looking  back  from  the  immense  distance  of  a  happy  eternity 
upon  the  pains  of  this  mortal  life,  the  greatest  amount  of  these 
might  not  appear  so  small  in  comparison  with  the  happiness 
which  had  succeeded  them2,  that  they  might  be  regarded, 
then,  as  a  simple  preparation  for  and  introduction  to  futurity, 
and   accounted  for  on  that  ground,  superseding  the  judicial 


1  "  Sedilli  parvuli  nee  flerent  in  para- 
diso,  nee  muti  essent,  nee  aliquando 
uti  ratione  non  possent,  nee  morbis 
affligerentur,  nee  a  bestiis  Isederentur 
....  nee  surgentes  in  pueritiam 
domarentur  verberibus,  aut  erudirentur 
laboribus."—Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  198. 
"  Omnibus  cogenita  est  quaedam  tarditas 
mentis,  qua  et  hi  qui  appellantur 
ingeniosi,  non  sine  aliqua  laboris 
serumna,  vel  quascunque  artes,  vel  eas 
etiam  quas  liberates  nuncupant  diseunt 
....  Si  in  paradise  aliquid  dis- 


ceretur,  quod  illi  vitae  esset  utile  seire, 
sine  ullo  labore  aut.  dolore  id  asse- 
queretur  beata  natura,  vel  Deo  docente 
vet  seipsa.  Unde  quis  non  intelligat 
in  hac  vita  etiam  tormenta  discentium 
ad  miserias  hujus  saeculi,  quod  ex  uno 
in  condemnationem  propagatum  est, 
pertinere."  —  L.  6.  c.  9. 

2  "  'Eo-Acoi/  yap  virb  xa-pparcw 

Ilfjjua  dvdffKet  iraXiyKOTov  8a/j.a(rdtv 
po'ipa  ire/jurr) 


PINDAR.  Olymp.  2. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    PEL AG IAIN    CONTROVERSY.  89 

one.  The  common  spectacle  of  human  misery,  however,  has, 
in  fact,  impressed  the  religious  portion  of  the  world  in  all 
ages,  Christian  or  pagan,  in  the  latter  way ;  and  the  genera* 
feeling  of  mankind  has  connected  it  with  some  deep  though 
undefined  root  of  sin  in  the  human  race. 

Thus  maintained  and  defended  on  the  several  grounds  of 
the  power  of  the  will,  the  nature  of  virtue  and  vice,  and  the 
Divine  justice,  the  Catholic  doctrine  of  original  sin  adopted, 
as  an  account  of  the  existence  of  evil,  a  middle  ground 
between  two  extreme  theories  on  either  side,  which  pre- 
vailed in  the  world.  According  to  the  Manichean  theory, 
evil  was  an  original  substance  in  nature,  coeval  with  the 
Divine.  It  was  therefore  an  ineradicable,  unconquerable 
thing ;  for  though  some  triumph  over  the  Gentes  tenebrarum 
was  talked  of,  a  part  of  the  Divine  nature  was  irrevocably 
polluted  in  the  contest.  The  practical  meaning  of  this  theory 
was,  that  the  world  was  a  mixture;  that  good  and  evil  had  gone 
on  together  in  it  from  all  eternity,  and  would  to  all  eternity 
continue  to  do  so ;  that  things  were  what  they  were,  and  that 
there  was  no  altering  them ;  — much  the  view  taken  by  practical 
worldly  men,  who  cannot  persuade  themselves  to  believe  that 
there  is  such  a  thing  as  pure  good,  the  whole  of  experience  going 
so  much  against  it,  and  therefore  virtually  disbelieve  in  Him 
who  is  absolute  goodness.  The  other  extreme  theory  was 
the  Pelagian,  which  accounted  for  the  universal  corruption 
of  the  world  simply  upon  the  ground  of  each  individual's 
will ;  and  the  practical  tendency  of  the  Pelagian,  as  of 
the  Manichean  theory,  was  to  carelessness  and  indifference ; 
attributing  too  slight  a  power  to  sin  over  the  liberty  of  the 
will,  and  so  lowering  our  idea  of  the  nature  of  sin;  as  the 
other  gave  it  too  much,  and  so  abandoned  us  to  it.  Between 
these  two  theories  the  Church  has  taken  the  middle  line, 
denying  evil  to  be  original  in  the  universe,  but  asserting  it 
to  be  original  in  our  present  nature  ;  giving  it  a  voluntary 
beginning  but  a  necessary  continuance,  and  a  descent,  when 
once  begun,  by  a  natural  law.  This  mixture  and  balance 


90 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


of  voluntariness  and  necessity  makes  up  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin ;  and  the  practical  impression  it  leaves,  is  that 
of  the  deep  and  awful  nature,  but  not  the  dominance  of  sin. 
And  thus  S.  Augustine  was  enabled,  in  answer  to  the 
Pelagian  charge  of  Manicheanism,  to  appeal  to  his  doctrine 
as  a  safeguard  against  that  system.  The  facts  of  the  world 
drove  the  Manichean  into  blasphemy  and  a  denial  of  the 
Divine  omnipotence ;  but  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  ac- 
counted for  these  facts  in  a  way  which  saved  at  once  the 
Divine  justice  and  the  Divine  power.  It  attributed  evil, 
moral  and  physical,  to  the  wilful  act  of  man ;  thus  separating 
it  from  the  essence  of  his  nature,  and  dislodging  it  as  a 
substance  in  the  universe,  while  it  accounted  judicially  for 
the  pains  of  this  present  life.1 

III.  The  main  arguments  of  Pelagianism  being  stated2,  it 
remains  to  notice  the  bearing  of  this  system  upon  the  Ca- 
tholic doctrines  of  the  Original  State  of  man,  the  Incarnation, 
and  the  Atonement. 

1.  Scripture  represents  the  original  state  of  man  as  one  of 
innocence  and  goodness,  and  as  blessed  with  a  corresponding 
happiness.  He  conies  from  the  hands  of  his  Maker  an  up- 
right being,  and  he  is  placed  in  the  garden  of  Eden,  where 
he  is  surrounded  with  all  that  can  please  the  senses  and 
satisfy  the  mind  of  a  creature  thus  constituted.  And  reve- 
lation is  here  confirmed  by  general  tradition.  The  legend  of 
the  golden  age  goes  back  to  a  primitive  state  of  our  nature, 
in  which  it  was  both  good  and  happy. 

Such  an  original  moral  disposition  of  man  again  involves 
a  certain  measure  of  stability  and  strength  in  the  formation 
of  it ;  such  a  character  implies  a  certain  degree  of  depth,  with 
which  it  is  stamped  upon  human  nature.  It  may  be  said 


1  Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  170—177.  186.; 
1.  4.  c.  2. ;  1.  5.  c.  30.  56. ;  1.  6.  c.  7.  9. 

*  For  the  mode  in  which  the  Pelagian 


interpreted  the  texts  of  Scripture 
bearing  on  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin,  see  NOTE  XIII. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 


91 


that  a  being  is  good  till  he  has  sinned  ;  and  that,  consequently, 
if  he  is  endowed  simply  with  freewill  at  his  creation,  he  is 
created  a  good  being.  But  it  may  be  doubted  whether  free- 
will of  itself,  and  prior  to  its  determination  to  good,  caa  be 
called  goodness l :  at  any  rate,  the  possession  of  it  alone  affords 
no  reason  for  a  state  of  goodness  lasting  beyond  the  first  mo- 
ment of  creation  ;  and  therefore  we  are  evidently  intended  to 
regard  man's  original  state  of  uprightness  as  something  more 
than  the  mere  state  of  freewill.  Man's  uprightness,  however, 
being  this  farther  state,  whatever  we  may  call  it ;  the  support 
and  continuance  of  this  state  depended  upon  freewill  in  a 
being  not  yet  perfected  but  on  his  trial.  It  thus  became  an 
object  of  attention  in  Catholic  theology  to  define,  under  this 
balance  of  considerations,  with  as  much  accuracy  as  the 
subject  admitted  of,  what  was  the  condition  of  Adam  before 
the  fall,  in  respect  of  goodness  on  the  one  side,  and  liability 
to  sin  on  the  other. 

On  the  one  hand,  then,  it  was  determined  that  Adam  could 
not  have  concupiscence  or  lust,  i.  e.  the  direct  inclination  to 
evil ;  that  positive  appetite  and  craving  for  corrupt  pleasure 
which  is  now  the  incentive  to  sin  in  our  nature;  for  this 
would  be  to  make  no  difference  between  man  unfallen  and 
fallen.  There  was  no  positive  contrariety  as  yet  between  the 
flesh  and  the  spirit ;  and  the  inward  struggle,  which  is  now  the 
normal  condition  of  man,  was  alien  to  a  nature  made  harmo- 
nious and  at  peace  with  itself.2  On  the  other  hand,  Adam 
must  have  had  a  tendency  of  some  kind  toward  evil,  in  order 
to  be  in  a  state  of  trial  at  all.3  There  remained,  then,  the 
conclusion,  of  an  indirect  or  distant  tendency  to  evil  in 
Adam.  A  regular  and  formed  virtuous  habit  of  mind,  or, 


1  An  rectus  erat  non  habens  volun- 
tatem  bonam  sed   ejus  possibilitatem  ? 
—Op.  Imp.  5.  57.      See  NOTE  XIV. 

2  "Hsec  discordia  carnis  et  spiritus 
in  paradiso,  si  nemo  peccasset,  absit  ut 
csse  potuerit."— Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  37. 

8  "  Quasi  non  potuerit  Deus  hominem 


facere  voluntatis  bonae,  in  qua  cum 
tamen  permanere  non  cogeret  sed  in  ejus 
esset  arbitrio  sive  in  ea  semper  esse 
vellet,  sive  non  semper,  sed  ex  ilia  se 
in  malam  nullo  cogente  mutaret,  sicut 
et  factum  est." — Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.61. 


92 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 


[CHAP.  III. 


as  S.  Augus  ine  calls  it,  a  good  will,  implanted  in  him  to 
begin  with  by  God,  intervened  between  him  and  sin,  and 
stood  as  a  barrier  against  any  strong  and  disturbing  force 
of  temptation.  Suppose  a  tendency  to  evil  in  man,  with 
simply  freewill  to  resist  it,  and  that  tendency  is  at  once  a 
strong  power  and  force  in  his  nature ;  but  suppose,  together 
with  that  tendency  to  evil,  and  coeyal  with  it,  a  formed  and 
set  habit  and  disposition  of  the  whole  soul  to  good  —  suppose, 
in  short  (allowing  for  necessary  distinctions),  a  character 
equal  to  a  virtuous  character  which  it  has  taken  time  and 
effort  to  acquire,  existing  in  man  as  the  gift  of  God,  at  the 
moment  of  his  creation1,  and  it  is  at  once  evident  that  the 
evil  tendency  in  his  nature  is  at  a  very  great  disadvantage ; 
because  it  starts  with  a  loss  of  position,  and  opposes  an  ante- 
dated strength,  a  created  precedence,  and  an  implanted  growth 
of  goodness.  Evil  thus  begins  its  course  under  a  righteous 
oppression,  which  confines  its  movements  and  keeps  it  at  a 
distance  from  the  centre  of  human  life  and  feeling ;  its  in- 
vitations are  faintly  heard  from  the  extremities  of  nature,  a 
solid  intervening  formation  of  good  intercepting  them  before 
they  arrive  at  a  forcible  and  exciting  stage ;  and  sin,  yet  un- 
known to  conscience,  accompanies  human  nature,  like  a  dream, 
with  languid  and  remote  temptations,  while  good  occupies  the 
active  and  waking  man.  Such  a  state  may  be  partially  under- 
stood from  the  ordinary  case  of  any  one  who  has  acquired  vir- 
tuous habits  of  any  kind.  These  habits  do  not  exclude  a  man 
from  trial,  for,  however  firmly  rooted,  they  have  still  to 
be  sustained  by  the  effort  of  the  will.  Still,  in  the  case  of 
confirmed  virtuous  habits,  this  effort  is  an  easy  and  uncon- 
scious one,  not  anxious  or  laborious  ;  the  person,  though  not 
out  of  the  reach  of  evil,  is  separated  at  a  considerable  in- 
terval from  it,  and,  under  the  safeguard  of  his  habit,  a  serene 
precaution  has  to  defend  him  from  distant  danger,  rather  than 


1  «'  Ilia  itaque  perfectio  naturae  quam 
non  dabant  anni  sed  sola  manus  Dei, 
non  potuit  nisi  habere  voluntatem 


aliquam,    eamque   non   raalam." — Op. 
Imp.  1.  5.  c.  61. 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 


93 


positive  fear  from  a  near  and  immediate  one.  In  the  same 
way,  only  more  perfectly  than  in  any  case  of  habit  of  which 
we  have  experience,  the  first  man  was  protected  from  sin 
by  an  implanted  holy  disposition  of  mind,  and  habitual  in- 
clination to  good  imparted  to  him  at  his  creation.  His  trial 
lay  in  having  to  sustain  a  divinely  bestowed  defence  against 
sin,  rather  than  engage  in  direct  conflict  with  it;  and  a 
tranquil  precaution,  not  inconsistent  with  the  happiness 
of  paradise,  against  a  remote  issue  on  the  side  of  evil,  had 
it  been  adequately  maintained,  would  have  effectually  pre- 
served him.1  He  had  by  his  created  disposition  a  pleasure 
in  goodness;  and  that  pleasure  naturally  preserved  him  in 
obedience  without  the  need  of  express  effort.  But  though 
thus  held  to  obedience  by  the  persuasive  tie  of  an  ade- 
quate pleasure  and  delight,  man  was  not  without  an  inde- 
finite principle  of  desire  in  his  nature,  which  tended  to  pass 
beyond  the  bounds  of  present  happiness  in  quest  of  more, 
Thus,  in  common  life,  persons  happy  after  a  human  measure 
in  their  present  situation  and  resources,  still  carry  about 
with  them  a  general  sense  of  a  capacity  for  greater  happiness, 
which  is  without  much  difficulty  kept  under  and  controlled, 
by  the  mind  simply  sustaining  a  proper  estimate  of  the 
resources  in  its  possession  and  applying  a  just  attention  to 
the  enjoyment  of. them;  but  which  may  be  allowed  to 
expand  unduly,  till  it  impels  the  man  to  a  trial  of  new  and 
dangerous  sources  of  pleasure.  Happy  within  the  limits  of 
obedience,  Adam  was  still  not  out  of  the  reach  of  a  remote 
class  of  invitations  to  advance  beyond  the  precincts  of  a 
sacred  sufficiency  and  make  trial  of  the  unknown.  But  the 
happiness  with  which  God  had  connected  his  duty  could 
have  easily,  with  the  aid  of  an  unpainful  caution  of  his  own, 
mastered  the  temptation.2  Thus,  in  some  calm  interval, 


1  "  Pcenae  illius  devitandae  quae  fuerat 
secuturapeccatum,tranquillaeratcautio, 
non  turbulenta  formido." — Op.  Imp.  1. 
6.c.  14. 

2  "  Boiife  igitur  voluntatis  factus  est 


homo,  paratus  ad  obediendum  Deo,  et 
prseceptum  obedienter  accipicns,  quod 
sine  ulla  quamdiu  vellet  difficultate 
servaret."— Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  61. 


94  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

produced  by  sight  or  sound,  or  by  some  cheering  or  tran- 
quillising  news,  or  arising  in  the  mind  he  knows  not  how, 
a  man  enjoys,  amid  the  business,  anxiety,  and  turmoil  of 
the  world,  a  brief  repose  and  happiness  within ;  which  does 
not,  however,  while  it  removes  to  the  distant  horizon  for 
the  time  the  evils  and  the  pains  of  life,  altogether  put 
them  out  of  sight.  Behind  him  are. the  sorrows  and  misfor- 
tunes of  the  past,  before  him  those  of  the  future.  He  is  not 
unconscious  of  either ;  but  they  yield  to  the  reign  of  the  pre- 
sent hour,  which  disables  and  unsubstantiates,  though  it  does 
not  suppress  them.  The  fulness  of  present  peace  occupies 
the  mind,  excluding  the  power  of  realising  anything  which 
is  not  in  harmony  with  it;  and  evil  is  only  seen  as  a  distant 
shadow,  hovering  on  the  outside  of  things,  a  feeble  and  inert 
phantom  belonging  to  another  world  than  our  own,  which 
cannot  come  near  enough  to  hurt,  or  penetrate  within  the 
sphere  of  solid  things.  So,  from  some  inland  scene  is  heard 
the  distant  roar  of  the  sea,  or  from  some  quiet  country  spot 
the  noise  of  the  neighbouring  city;  the  sounds  are  heard, 
but  they  affect  the  mind  altogether  differently  than  if  they 
were  near.  They  do  not  overwhelm  or  distract,  but  rather 
mingle  with  the  serenity  of  the  scene  before  us. 

This  implanted  rectitude  or  good  habit  it  was  which  made 
the  first  sin  of  man  so  heinous,  and  caused  that  distinction 
between  it  and  all  the  other  sins  which  have  been  com- 
mitted in  the  world.  For  the  first  sin  was  the  only  sin  which 
was  committed  against  and  in  spite  of  a  settled  bias  of  nature 
toward  good ;  all  the  sins  which  have  been  committed  since 
have  been  committed  in  accordance  with  a  natural  bias 
toward  evil.  There  was  therefore  a  perversity  in  the  first 
sin  altogether  peculiar  to  it,  and  such  as  made  it  a  sin  sui 
generis.  S.  Augustine  is  accordingly  exact  in  distinguishing 
the  motive  to  the  first  sin  as  being  a  depraved  will  as 
contrasted  with  concupiscence  or  lust ;  by  a  depraved  will 
meaning  a  perverse  opposition  to  the  good  will  established 
in  the  first  man,  a  voluntary  abandonment  of  the  high  ground 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 


95 


on  which  he  stood  by  nature,  a  violation  of  his  own  created 
inclination  to  good.1  A  kind  of  horror  attaches  to  the  falls 
of  saints,  when  those  who  have  maintained  a  high  and  con- 
sistent course  of  holiness  commit  some  deep  sin.  Such  sins 
are  like  unaccountable  convulsions  in  nature,  and  our  moral 
instincts  immediately  draw  a  distinction  between  them  and 
common  sins.  The  peculiarity,  however,  of  the  sin  of  Adam, 
exceeded  that  of  any  sin  of  fallen  man,  in  that  it  was  the 
sin  of  man  unfallen. 

It  may  be  added,  that  such  an  inspired  good  habit  or 
disposition  of  man  as  first  created  is  part  of  the  tradition  of 
the  golden  age.  A  certain  disposition  is  described  in  that 
legend  as  being  that  of  the  whole  human  race  at  the  com- 
mencement of  its  existence  —  an  original  moral  formation, 
like  the  creation  of  the  race  itself, —  and  it  is  described 
as  continuing  some  time;  —  a  disposition  involving  general 
goodness  and  uprightness,  love,  gentleness,  serenity,  content. 
So  suitable  has  it  seemed  even  to  the  unenlightened  human 
mind  that  the  morning  of  a  world  of  moral  beings  should  arise 
in  light,  and  purity, — that  the  creation  fresh  from  the  Divine 
hands  should  shine  with  the  reflexion  of  the  Divine  goodness, 
and  bear  the  stamp  of  a  proximity  to  God, — that  the  will  of 
man  as  first  created  should  not  be  neutral  or  indeterminate, 
but  disposed  to  good.  Nor  have  the  definitions  of  Catholic 
theology,  however  elaborate  and  subtle  in  form,  diverged  in 
substance  from  the  ground  of  general  tradition  and  natural 
ideas. 

Scripture  and  common  tradition  thus  assert  a  paradisal  life 
as  the  original  state  of  man.  But  the  Pelagian,  in  denying 
the  fall,  rejected  Paradise ;  as  he  would  not  admit  original  sin, 
he  could  fall  back  on  no  antecedent  state  of  innocence.  He 


1  "Prsecessit  mala  voluntas,  et  se- 
cuta  est  mala  concupiscentia  .... 
Voluntas  cupiditatem,  non  cupiditas 
voluntatem  duxit."  —  Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c. 
71.  "Voluntatem  ejus  prius  fuisse 


vitiatam  venenosa  persuasione  serpentis, 
ut  oriretur  cupiditas  quae  sequeretur 
potius  voluntatem  quam  resisteret 
voluntati."— Ibid.  1.  6.  c.  14. 


96 


THE   PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 


[CHAP.  III. 


robbed  human  nature  of  the  glory,  the  freshness,  and  the 
beauty  of  its  first  creation,  reduced  the  primitive  to  the 
level  of  all  that  succeeded  it,  and  fixed  the  present  facts  of 
the  world  as  the  standard  of  our  nature.  He  made  this  ex- 
isting state  of  sin  and  pain  coeval  with  the  commencement 
of  things ;  and  S.  Augustine  taunted  his  opponents  with  the 
(c  Pelagian  Paradise."  l  Human  nature  in  the  midst  of  trials 
looks  back  with  consolation  to  the  paradisal  state  as  a 
sign  that  pain  is  the  accident  and  happiness  the  law  of 
our  being ;  and  were  the  rest  of  the  Old  Testament  silent, 
a  future  state  was  still  preached  to  the  Jew  in  the  first 
chapter  of  Genesis ;  but  the  Pelagian  cut  off  both  the  retro- 
spect and  the  pledge.  The  paradisal  age  was  to  him  nothing 
more  than  the  first  age  of  the  world,  when  science,  art, 
and  the  refinements  of  life  had  not  yet  arisen,  and  man  was 
simpler  than  he  was  afterwards,  only  because  he  was  more 
rude.  He  took  the  same  view  of  it  that  a  human  philo- 
sopher would  take  who  pictures  to  himself  the  primitive 
state  of  man  simply  as  a  state  anterior  to  civilisation2,  and 
contrasts  it  with  the  law,  system,  and  social  growth  of  a  more 
advanced  age. 

And,  together  with  the  paradisal  life  in  general,  the 
created  goodness  of  the  first  man  fell  to  the  ground.  The 
idea  of  created  virtue  jarred  with  the  Pelagian  theory  of 
freewill,  according  to  which  virtue  was  no  virtue  at  all, 
unless  a  man  acquired  it  for  himself.  An  original  gift 
of  righteousness  was  thus  dismissed  as  a  contradiction,  and 
Adam  at  his  creation  was  considered  to  be  in  the  same 


1  "  Naturam  humanam  a  Deo  bono 
conditam  bonatn  magno  inobedientiae 
peccato  fuisse  vitiatam,  Catholica  fides 
dicit,  Sed  vos  qui  hoc  negatis,  quaeso, 
paulisper  Pavadisum  cogitate.  Placetne 
vobis  ut  ponamus  .  .  .  innumerabiles 
morbos,  orbitates,  luctus,  etc.  Certe  si 
tails  paradisus  pingeretur  nullus  diceret 
esse  paradisum,  nee  si  supra  legisset  hoc 
nomen  conscriptum :  nee  diceret  errasse 
pictorem,  sed  plane  agnosceret  irriso- 


rem.  Veruntamen  eorura  qui  nos  no- 
verunt,  nemo  miraretur,  si  adderetur 
nomen  vestrum  ad  titulum,  et  scribere- 
tur  Paradisus  Pelagianorum." — Op. 
Imp.  1.  3.  c.  1 54.  Fide  1.  3.  c.  95.  147. ; 
1.  6.  c.  25.  27,  28. 

2  "  Homines  fuisse  primitus  nudos, 
quia  ad  solertise  humanse  operam  ut  se 
tegerent  pertinebat,  quae  nondum  in  illis 
fuit."— Contra.  Jul.  Pel.l.  4.  n.  81. 


CHAP.  III.] 


THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 


97 


condition    as  every  other  man  that  has  been  born,  and  to 
have  had  the  same  struggle  of  the  flesh  and  spirit.1 

2.  The  Pelagian  doctrine  had  an  important  bearing  on 
the  doctrine  of  the  Incarnation,  in  regard  to  the  manner  in 
which  our  Lord  was,  according"  to  that  economy,  subject  to 
temptation  and  trial,  and  exposed  to  the  approaches  of  sin. 
Scripture  says  that  our  Lord  was  in  all  points  tempted  like  as 
we  are.  But  the  Church  has  not  considered  it  consistent  with 
piety  to  interpret  this  text  to  mean  that  our  Lord  had  the 
same  direct  propension  to  sin  that  we  have,  or  that  which  is 
called  by  divines  concupiscence.2  Such  direct  appetite  for 
what  is  sinful  is  the  characteristic  of  our  fallen  and  corrupt 
nature ;  and  our  Lord  did  not  assume  a  corrupt,  but  a 
sound  humanity.  Indeed,  concupiscence,  even  prior  to  and 
independent  of  its  gratification,  has  of  itself  the  nature  of 
sin  3 ;  and,  therefore,  could  not  belong  to  a  perfect  Being. 
Our  Lord  had  all  the  passions  and  affections  that  legiti- 
mately belong  to  man ;  which  passions  and  affections, 
tending  as  they  do  in  their  own  nature  to  become  inordi- 
nate, constituted  of  themselves  a  state  of  trial;  but  the 
Church  has  regarded  our  Lord's  trial  in  the  flesh  as  consisting 
in  preserving  ordinate  affections  from  becoming  inordinate, 
rather  than  in  restraining  desire  proximate  to  sin  from 
gratification.  So  mysterious  a  subject  precludes  all  ex- 
actness of  definition ;  yet  the  Church  expressed  a  substantial 


1  "Quod  miserrimum  bellum  introdu- 
cere  conaris  in  illius  beatissimae  pacis  et 
libertatis  locum." — Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  8. 
"  Nos  autem  dicimus  tarn  beatum  fuisse 
ilium  hominem  ante  peccatum,  tamque 
liberae  voluntatis,  ut  Dei  praeceptum 
magnis  viribus  mentis  observans,  resis- 
tentem  sibi  carnem  nullo  certamine  pa- 
teretur,  nee  aliquid  omnino  ex  aliqua 
cupiditate  sentiret,  quod  nollet."— L.  6. 
c.  14.  "  Addo  ad  bonitatem  conditionis 
Ada;  quod  in  eo  caro  ad  versus  spiritum 
nonconcupiscebatante  peccatum:  tu au- 
tem quitalem  dicis  carnis  concupiscen- 
tiam  qualis  nunc  est,  in  paradise  futuram 


esse,  si  nemo  peccasset,  talemque  in 
illo  fuisse  et  priusquam  peccaret ;  addis 
ejus  condition!  et  istam  miseriam  per 
carnis  spiritusque  discordiam."  —  C. 
16. 

2  "  Christus  ergo  nulla  illicita  con- 
cupivit,  quia  discordiam  carnis  etspiritus, 
quse  in  hominis  naturam  ex  prsevarica- 
tione  primi  hominis   vertit,  prorsus  ille 
non  habuit,  qui  de  Spiritu  et    Virgine 
non   per    concupiscentiam    carnis    est 
natus." — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  57. 

3  Malum  esse   quamvis   mente   non 
consentiente,  vel  carne  tamen  talia  con- 
cupiscere. — Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  59. 


98 


THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 


truth  of  morals,  as  well  as  one  of  faith  and  piety,  when  she 
guarded  the  person  of  our  Lord  from  the  too  near  approaches 
of  sin.  Desire  discloses,  on  a  nearer  examination,  different 
moral  complexions,  ar.d  at  a  certain  stage  is  seen  to  be  no 
longer  a  neutral  thing.  Our  Lord,  therefore,  had  not  the 
whole  of  desire  assigned  to  Him,  but  only  that  earlier  stage 
of  it  which  is  consistent  with  a  sound  nature ;  and,  together 
with  a  true  trial,  a  true  sinlessness  was  provided  for. 

But  S.  Augustine  had  to  contest  this  whole  question  with 
the  Pelagian  in  the  instance  of  our  Lord,  as  he  had  con- 
tested it  before  in  the  instance  of  Adam.  The  Pelagian 
who  attached  concupiscence  to  man  in  Paradise,  saw  no 
reason  against  attaching  it  to  the  humanity  assumed  by 
our  Lord.  Intent  on  effort  exclusively  as  the  test  of  good- 
ness, he  argued  that  it  was  this  very  strength  of  desire 
which  constituted  the  force  of  trial ;  and  that,  therefore,  the 
great  merit  of  our  Lord's  obedience  was  destroyed  by  sup- 
posing Him  to  have  been  without  it.1  Moreover,  He  was 
our  Model,  as  having  been  subjected  to  the  same  trials;  but 
if  His  desires  were  weaker  than  ours,  His  temptation  had 
been  less,  and  the  force  of  His  example  was  less  with  it.2 
But,  it  was  replied,  that  a  state  of  mind  which  kept  off  the 
approach  of  sin  was  a  higher  one  than  that  which  resisted 
it  near;  that  the  merit  of  our  Lord's  obedience  was  the 
perfect  one  of  a  triumphantly  sustained  distance  from  evil 3 ; 


1  Julian :  « Non  qui  virtute  judicii 
delicta  vitasset ;  sed  qui  felicitate  rarnis 
a  nostris  sensibus  sequestratae,  cupi- 
ditatem  vitiorum  sen  tire  nequivisset." 
Augustine  objects  to  this  mode  of  stating 
the  Catholic  position.  "  Sensisset  enim 
si  habuisset ;  non  enim  sensus  ei  defuit 
quo  earn  sentiret,  sed  voluntas  adfuit 
qua  non  haberet." — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c. 
48.  And  he  observes  that  if,  according 
to  Julian's  argument,  the  merit  of  virtue 
lay  in  conquest,  it  would  follow  that 
where  the  virtue  was  greatest,  the  pas- 
sions must  be  strongest ;  which  would 
lead  to  a  blasphemous  conclusion  in  the 


case  of  our  Lord.  "  Ecce  quod  Christo 
conaris  importare  insane.  .  .  Tan  to 
quippe  in  eo  continentia  spiritus  major 
est,  quanto  majorem  carnis  concupis- 
centiam  coerceret." — C.  52. 

2  "  Nunquam  commemorationem  fe- 
cisset  exempli :  quern  enim  hominibus 
ostenderet  imitandum,  si  ilium  externa? 
carnis  natura  discrevisset.  .  .  Quanto 
ei  rectius  diceret  aegritudo  peccantium 
et  securitas  coactorum  ;  « cum  valemus 
omnes  recta  consilia  preebemus  aegrotis ; 
tu  si  sic  esses,  aliter  longe  longeque 
sentires.'" — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  86,  87. 

8  "  Dicimus  eum  perfectione  carnis, 


CHAP.  III.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY. 


99 


and  that  the  force  of  example  did  not  depend  on  the  identity 
of  trial,  but  on  the  goodness  of  the  example  itself,  as  was 
evident  from  the  injunction  in  Scripture  to  imitate  God.1 
It  must,  indeed,  be  remarked,  on  this  reply,  that  Scripture 
rests  the  force  of  our  Lord's  example  expressly  on  the  ground 
that  His  trial  was  like  our  own.  The  Pelagian,  therefore, 
was  right  in  insisting  on  this  similarity.  But  he  proceeded 
to  argue  from  it  upon  the  principles  of  ordinary  logic,  and 
his  conclusion  degraded  our  Lord's  humanity,  and  endan- 
gered that  balance  of  truths  on  which  the  doctrine  of  the 
Incarnation  rested.  The  doctrine  of  our  Lord's  Divinity 
modifies  the  truths  connected  with  His  humanity  in  this  way, 
that  He  who  was  both  God  and  man  cannot  be  thought  of 
even  as  man  exactly  the  same  as  if  He  were  not  God.  And 
the  truth  of  our  Lord's  trial  and  temptation,  among  others, 
is  in  this  sense  a  modified  one.  To  carry  out,  therefore,  the 
conception  of  a  human  trial  to  the  full  in  the  instance  of 
our  Lord,  without  respect  to  other  truth,  was  to  trench  on 
his  Divinity.  To  the  idea  of  trial,  and  of  example  on  the 
ground  of  trial,  pursued  exclusively,  the  next  idea  is  that  of 
peccability,  and  the  next  that  of  simple  manhood.  It  was 
consistent  with  such  tendencies  in  Pelagianism  that  our 
Lord  did  not  stand  forth  as  the  one  sole  example  of  perfect 


et  non  per  carnis  concupiscentiam  pro- 
creata  carne,  cupiditatem  non  habuisse 
vitiorum.  .  .  Illius  virtus%aec  erat  earn 
non  habere ;  nostra  virtus  est  ei  non 
consentire." — Op.  Imp.  1.4.  c.  48.  "  Sic 
ijritur  Christus  abstinuit  a  peccato,  ut 
abstineret  etiam  ab  omni  cupiditate  pec- 
cati :  non  ut  ei  existent!  resisteret,  sed  ut 
ilia  mmquam  prorsus  existeret." — C.  58. 

1  "  Ncque  negare  debemus  ejus  excel- 
k'ntiam,  neque  propter  hanc  excellentiam 
nos  excusare,  ut  non  eum  pro  modo 
nostrostudeamusimitari." — Op.  Imp.  1. 
4.  c.  89. 

"Quid  enim,  homo  multum  loquens 
et  parum  sapiens,  si  dicerent  homines 
Christo,  Quare  nobis  jubetur  ut  imite- 
mur  te  ?  Nunquid  nos  de  Spiritu  Sancto 


et  Virgine  Maria  nati  sumus  ?  Postremo 
nun  quid  tanta  nobis  esse  virtus  potest 
quanta  tibi  est,  qui  ita  homo  es,  ut  etiam 
Deus  sis  ?  Ideone  non  debuit  sic  nasci 
ut  hominibus  eum  nolentibus  imitari  talis 
excusatio  daretur  ?  Sicut  nobis  ipse 
Patrem  proposuit  imitandum,  qui  certe 

homo  fuit Nee   dicunt   ei,  Tu 

propterea  hoc  potes  quia  Deus  es.  .  .  . 
Non  itaque  ideo  debuit  natus  de  Spiritu 
Sancto  et  Virgine  Maria  habere  concu- 
piscentiam, qua  cuperet  mala,  etsi  ei 
resistendo  non  faceret,  ne  dicerent  ei 
homines,  Habetoprius  cupiditates  malas, 
et  eas  vince,  si  potes,  ut  te  imitari  nos- 
tras  vincendo  possimus." — Op.  Imp.  1. 
4.  c.  87. 


100  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

obedience  in  that  system ;  but  only  one,  though  the  principal 
one,  of  a  succession  of  perfect  men  that  had  appeared  in  the 
world — extending  from  Abel  and  Enoch  to  Simeon  and 
Joseph,  the  husband  of  Mary.1  An  extreme  idea  of  freewill 
and  human  perfectibility  was  in  truth  inconsistent  with  a 
sound  doctrine  of  the  Incarnation,  not  admitting  of  such  a 
singularity  in  our  Lord's  life  and  -character  as  that  doctrine 
involved. 

The  Pelagian,  indeed,  in  retaliation  for  the  charge  of 
degrading  our  Lord's  humanity,  charged  his  opponents  with 
unsubstantiating  it,  and  threw  back  upon  them  the  name 
of  Apollinarists,  as,  with  a  difference  of  temptation,  not  as- 
signing to  our  Lord  the  same  humanity  which  other  men 
have,  and  so  denying  His  true  assumption  of  our  nature. 
But  it  was  replied  that  our  Lord  took  on  Him  the  nature, 
but  not  the  sin  of  man.  He  even  charged  his  opponents 
with  Manicheanism,  as  denying  that  Christ  had  assumed  our 
flesh;  but  the  same  answer  was  made,  that  the  flesh  was 
assumed,  but  not  the  corruption.  He  discovered,  again,  in 
the  Catholic  representation  of  our  Lord's  trial  in  the  flesh,  a 
combination  of  both  heresies  modified — a  semi-Apollinarism 
in  a  soul  imperfectly  connected  with  the  flesh,  a  semi-Mani- 
cheanism  in  a  flesh  imperfectly  connected  with  the  soul 
of  our  Lord.  But  it  was  replied,  as  before,  that  the  soul  of 
Christ  had  perfect  connection  with  the  flesh,  but  not  with  its 
corruption.2 


1  De  Natura  et  Gratia,  n.  42. 
"Incarnatio  Christ!  justitiae  fuit  forma 

lion  prima  sed  maxima,  quia  et  ante- 
quam  Verbum  caro  fieret,  et  in  Prophetis 
et  in  multis  aliis  sanctis  fulsere  virtu- 
tes."  —  Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  188. 

2  Julian :  "  Hie  igitur  ut  adsit  toto 
anhno  lector   admoneo :    videbit   enim 
Apollinaristarum    haeresim,    sed    earn 
Manicbaei    per  te  adjectione   reparari. 
Apollinaris  primo  talem  incarnationem, 
Christi  induxisse  fertur,ut  diceret  solum 
corpus  dehumana  substantia  assumptum 
videri,   pro   anima  vero   ipsam   fuisse 
deitatem.       Quod    posteaquam     crepit 


tarn  rationis  quam  evangelii  attestatione 
convelli  .  ,  excogitavit  aliud  unde  ejus 
haere.sis,  quee  perdurat  hactenus,  nasce- 
retur ;  et  dixit  animam  quidem  huma- 
nam  in  Christo  fuisse  sed  sensus  in  eo 
corporis  non  fuisse,  atque  impassibilem 
eum  pronuntiavit  universis  extitisse 
peccatis." — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  47. 

"  Certe  hanc  vim  in  disputando 
Apostolus  non  haberet  si  secundum 
Manichaeos  et  eorum  discipulos  Traduci- 
anos,  carnem  Christi  a  naturae  nostrae 
communione  distingueret." — Op.  Imp. 
1.  6.  c.  33. 

Augustine,    in    reply,    distinguishes 


CHAP.  HI.]  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  101 

3.  Pelagianism  was  fundamentally  opposed  to  the  doctrine 
of  the  atonement ;  for  no  atonement  was  wanted  if  there  had 
been  no  fall.  And  this  was  the  chief  obstacle  between  the 
Pelagian  and  a  sound  doctrine  of  the  Incarnation.  The 
design  of  the  Incarnation  was  to  remedy  the  effects  of  the 
fall;  apart  from  which  object,  it  could  only  be  held  as  an 
isolated  fact,  and,  without  place  or  significancy,  had  no  root 
in  the  system. 

The  Pelagian,  however,  in  superseding  the  atonement 
fundamentally,  retained  some  scattered  fragments  of  the 
doctrine.  The  relation  of  Christ,  as  Redeemer,  to  the  whole 
race  of  man,  was  abandoned  in  that  doctrine  of  freewill 
which  represented  all  men  as  able  to  fulfil,  and  some  as 
having  fulfilled,  the  whole  law,  without  any  other  aids  than 
such  as  were  attached  to  the  system  of  nature.  This  position 
was  a  contradiction  to  a  universal  atonement.  But  though 
the  Pelagians  did  not  regard  the  assisting  grace,  which 
that  event  procured,  as  necessary  for  everybody,  or  the  par- 
doning grace  as  wanted  by  all,  they  attached  an  advantage 
and  benefit  to  the  one,  and  maintained  a  general  need 
of  the  other.  The  grace  of  which  Christ  was  the  source 
rendered  the  fulfilment  of  the  law,  though  possible  without 
it,  easier,  and  was  a  valuable,  though  not  a  necessary  assist- 
ance ;  while  the  great  mass  of  mankind  stood  in  need  of  the 
atonement  for  the  pardon  of  actual,  though  not  of  original 
sin.  But  the  force  of  the  Christian  atonement  lies  in  its 
interest  to  mankind  as  one  corporate  whole,  and  that  interest 
being  one  of  absolute  need.  To  deny  the  universal  necessity 
of  the  atonement,  therefore,  was  to  give  up  the  doctrine. 
As  advantageous  to  any,  essential  to  some,  the  grace  of 


between  the  Apollinarist  statement, 
Christum  non  habuisse  corporis  sensus, 
and  his  own,  that  those  senses  non  con- 
tra Spiritum  concupisse  (1.  4.  c.  47.);  and 
as  against  the  Manicheans,  he  says, 
"Manicheei  non  sunt,  qui  camera  Christ! 
a  naturae  nostrae  communione  distingu- 


unt,  sed  qui  nullam  carnem  Christum 
habuisse  contendunt.  .  .  .  Dimitteillos 
.  .  .  quia  nobiscum  carnem  Christi  etsi 
dissimiliter  confiteris.  Nee  nos  enim 
earn  a  naturae  atque  substantiae  carnis 
nostrae,  sed  a  vitii  communione  distin- 
guimus."—  Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  33. 


H  3 


102  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

Christ  was  a  Pelagian  fiction,  accommodated  to  a  theory 
opposed  to  it,  and  maintained  as  a  feeble  show  of  orthodoxy. 
The  separation  of  renovating  from  pardoning  grace,  again, 
was  a  blow  at  the  integrity  of  Gospel  grace.  Pardoning 
grace  was  necessary  for  any  one  who  had  sinned,  because 
the  sin  was  a  past  fact  which  could  not  be  undone ;  but  the 
renovating  or  assisting  grace  of  Christ  was  not  necessary, 
however  advantageous  to  him,  because  the  future  sin  could 
be  avoided  by  nature  alone.  These  two  graces  go  together 
in  the  Divine  scheme,  and  belong  to  the  same  act  of  the 
Divine  mercy. 

Out  of  one  extreme  statement  at  the  commencement, 
Pelagianism  thus  expanded  into  a  large  body  of  thought,  in- 
complete indeed,  but  having  one  general  stamp,  and  develop- 
ing more  and  more,  as  it  came  out,  the  original  difference 
from  Catholic  truth ;  passing  from  the  human  will  to  higher 
mysteries,  and  upon  the  basis  of  exalted  nature  threatening 
the  truth  of  the  Incarnation. 

The  philosophical  fault  of  Pelagianism  was,  that  it  went 
upon  ideas  without  considering  facts,-r-  in  the  case  both  of 
freewill  and  the  Divine  justice.  The  abstract  idea  of  free- 
will is  that  of  a  power  to  do  anything  that  it  is  physically 
possible  for  us  to  do.  As  man  had  freewill,  then,  the  Pelagian 
argued  that  he  had  this  power ;  and  that  any  man,  therefore, 
could  fulfil  the  whole  law  and  be  perfect.  But  what  we 
have  to  consider  in  this  question,  is  not  what  is  the  abstract 
idea  of  freewill,  but  what  is  the  freewill  which  we  really  and 
actually  have.  This  actual  freewill,  we  find,  is  not  a  simple 
but  a  complex  thing ;  exhibiting  oppositions  and  incon- 
sistencies ;  appearing  on  the  one  side  to  be  a  power  of  doing 
anything  to  which  there  is  no  physical  hindrance,  on  the 
other  side  to  be  a  restricted  faculty.  It  is  that  will  which 
S.  Paul  describes,  when,  appealing  to  the  facts  of  human 
nature  (the  account  of  which,  as  referred  to  the  sin  of  Adam, 
is  a  matter  of  faith,  but  which  are  themselves  matters  of 
'experience),  he  describes  a  state  of  divided  consciousness,  and 


CHAP.  III.]  THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY.  103 

a  sense  of  power  and  weakness.  But  the  Pelagian  did  not 
possess  himself  properly  of  the  facts  of  human  nature,  and, 
committing  the  same  fault  in  morals  that  the  mediaeval 
philosophers  did  in  science,  he  argued  upon  an  abstract  idea, 
instead  of  examining  what  the  faculty,  as  we  experience  it, 
really  is;  and  an  absolute  freewill,  which  was  a  simple 
conception  of  the  mind,  displaced  the  incomprehensible 
actual  will,  the  enigma  of  human  nature,  the  mystery  of  fact. 

The  Pelagian's  argument  respecting  the  Divine  justice 
proceeded  in  the  same  way  upon  an  idea  without  considering 
facts.  It  was  founded  indeed  upon  the  true  natural  idea  of  jus- 
tice in  our  minds ;  and  so  far  no  fault  is  to  be  found  with  it. 
Nor  was  this  a  mere  abstract  idea.  But  he  did  not  take  into 
consideration  with  it  the  facts  of  the  existing  constitution 
of  things.  We  find  a  severe  law  of  suffering  in  operation 
in  this  world  previous  to  the  existence  of  the  individual ; 
which  law,  therefore,  can  hardly  be  said  to  be,  in  a  compre- 
hensible sense,  a  just  one.  Our  moral  nature,  then,  and  the 
existing  constitution  of  things,  being  at  variance  on  the  ques- 
tion of  the  Divine  justice,  we  arrive  at  the  conclusion  that  the 
Divine  justice  is  incomprehensible.  But  the  Pelagian  attended 
simply  to  the  idea  of  justice  in  his  own  mind,  and  ignored 
the  facts  on  the  other  side.  The  doctrine  of  original  sin, 
then,  which  is  in  truth  nothing  but  an  account,  though  a 
revealed  one,  of  these  facts,  was  not  wanted  by  him.  He 
did  not  attend  to  the  difficulty,  and  therefore  wanted  no 
solution.  This  doctrine  was  therefore,  in  his  eyes,  a  mere 
gratuitous  theory,  which  needlessly  and  wantonly  contradicted 
the  truth  of  the  Divine  justice. 

But  the  primary  fault  of  Pelagianism  was  the  sin  against 
piety  contained  in  its  fundamental  assertion,  as  explained  at 
the  commencement  of  this  chapter,  of  an  ultimate  movement 
of  the  natural  will  to  good,  unassisted  by  God.  However 
logical  a  result  of  the  admission  of  the  freedom  of  the  will, 
the  absolute  assertion  of  this  position  was  false,  because  its 
premiss  was  an  imperfect  one ;  and  it  was  contrary  to  piety, 

H    4 


104  THE   PELAGIAN   CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

the  religious  mind  feeling  an  insurmountable  check  and 
prohibition  against  calling  any  good  movement  purely  its 
own,  and  appropriating  it  to  the  exclusion  of  God.  But 
the  Pelagian  ventured  on  this  act  of  appropriation. 

Raised  upon  a  basis  thus  philosophically  and  religiously 
at  fault,  Pelagianism  was  first  an  artificial  system,  and  next 
of  a  low  moral  tendency. 

It  wanted  reality,  and  was  artificial  in  assigning  to  man 
•what  was  opposed  to  his  consciousness  and  to  what  he 
felt  to  be  the  truth  about  himself.  The  absolute  power 
of  man  to  act  without  sin  and  be  morally  perfect  was 
evidently  a  fiction,  based  on  an  abstract  idea  and  not  on 
the  experienced  faculty  of  freewill.  And  when  he  fol- 
lowed with  a  list  of  men  who  had  actually  been  perfect 
moral  beings,  Abel,  Enoch,  Melchisedek,  and  others,  he 
simply  trifled ;  and  showed  how  fantastic,  absurd,  and  un- 
substantial his  position  was.  Human  nature  is  too  seriously 
alive  to  the  law  of  sin  under  which  it  at  present  acts, 
not  to  feel  the  mockery  of  such  assertions. 

The  system,  again,  had  a  low  moral  tendency.  First, 
it  dulled  the  sense  of  sin.  Prior  to  and  independent  of 
action  there  exists  a  state  of  desire  which  the  refined  con- 
science mourns  over  ;  but  which  is  part  of  the  existing  nature 
as  distinguished  from  being  the  choice  of  the  man.  Hence 
the  true  sense  in  which  the  saints  have  ever  grieved,  not 
only  over  their  acts,  but  over  their  nature:  for,  however 
incomprehensible,  they  have  felt  something  to  be  sinful 
within  them  which  was  yet  coeval  with  them.  But  the 
Pelagian,  not  admitting  any  sin  but  that  of  direct  choice, 
would  not  see  in  concupiscence  anything  but  a  legitimate 
desire,  which  might  be  abused,  but  was  in  itself  innocent. 
In  disallowing  the  mystery  of  evil  he  thus  impaired  his 
perception  of  it;  he  only  saw  nature  in  that  to  which 
the  acute  conscience  attached  sin l ;  and  gave  himself  credit 


1  "  Naturalem  esse  omnium  sensuum    I   cemus  .  .  .   Concupiscentia  cum  intra 
voluptatem,  testimonio  universitatis  do-    |  limitem  concessorum  tenetur  affectio  na- 


CHAP.  III.] 


THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 


105 


for  a  sound  and  practical  standard  of  morals,  as  opposed  to 
a  morbid  and  too  sensitive  one.  The  doctrine  of  per- 
fectibility encouraged  the  same  tendency  in  the  system, 
demanding  a  lower  moral  standard  for  its  verification. 

And  the  same  narrowness  of  moral  basis  which  dulled 
the  sense  of  sin,  depressed  the  standard  of  virtue.  The 
Pelagian  denied  virtue  as  an  inspiration  and  gift  of  God, 
confining  his  idea  of  it  entirely  to  human  effort  and  direct 
choice.  But  the  former  conception  of  the  source  of  virtue 
was  necessary  to  a  high  standard  of  virtue  itself.  If  we  are 
to  rely  on  what  general  feeling  and  practical  experience  say 
on  this  subject,  virtue  needs  for  its  own  support  the  reli- 
gious rationale,  i.  e.  the  idea  of  itself  as  something  imparted. 
There  must  be  that  image  and  representation  of  it  in  men's 
minds  which  presents  it  less  as  a  human  work  than  as  an 
impulse  from  above,  possessing  itself  of  the  man  he  knows 
not  how;  a  holy  passion,  and  a  spark  kindled  from  the 
heavenly  fire.  It  is  this  conception  of  it  as  an  inspiration  that 
has  excited  the  sacred  ambition  of  the  human  mind,  which 
longs  for  union  with  God,  or  a  participation  of  the  Divine 
life,  and  sees  in  this  inspiration  this  union.  Virtue  has  thus 
risen  from  a  social  and  civil  to  a  sublime  and  intrinsic 
standard,  and  presented  itself  as  that  which  raised  man  above 
the  world,  and  not  simply  moulded  and  trained  him  for  it. 
This  conception  has  accordingly  approved  itself  to  the  great 
poets  of  the  world,  who  have  in  their  ideal  of  man  greatly 


turalis  et  innocuus    est." — Op.  Imp.  1. 
1.  c.  71. 

The  particular  difficulty  attaching  to 
concupiscence  as  sin,  and  yet  unavoidable, 
Julian  exposes  with  logical  acuteness, 
which  does  not,  however,  still  answer  the 
real  argument  upon  which  this  sort  of 
sin  rests,  which  is  that  of  inward 
feeling  and  conscience.  "  Quod  vero 
posuisti,  legem  quidem  peccati  esse  in 
membris  nostris,  sed  tune  habere  pecca- 
tum  quando  consentimus ;  tune  vero 
solum  proelium  suscitare  quando  non 


consentimus,  et  indicere  miseriam  pace 
turbata;  quis  non  prudens  pugnare 
perspiciat  ?  Nam  si  lex  peccati,  id  est, 
peccatum,  et  necessitas  peccati  membris 
est  inserta  naturaliter,  quid  prodest  non 
ei  praebere  consensum,  cum  propter  hoc 
ipsum  quod  est,  necesse  sit  subire  suppli- 
cium  ?  Aut  si  est  lex  quidem  peccati, 
sed  quando  ei  non  consentio  non  pecco, 
inestimabilis  potentia  voluntatis  huma- 
nae,  quae  (si  dici  permittat  absurditas) 
cogit  ipsum  non  peccare  peccatum." 
— Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  71. 


106  THE    PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY.  [CHAP.  III. 

leaned  to  the  inspired  kind  of  virtue.  So  congenial  to  the 
better  instincts  even  of  the  unenlightened  human  mind  is  the 
Christian  doctrine  of  grace,  while,  disconnected  with  this 
ennobling  conception,  morality  has  sunk  down  to  a  political 
and  secular  level.  Nor  is  there  any  justice  surer  than  that 
by  which  the  self-sufficient  will  is  punished  by  the  exposure 
of  its  own  feebleness,  and  rejected  grace  avenged  in  a  barren 
and  impoverished  form  of  virtue.  Those  schools  that  have 
seen  in  the  doctrine  of  grace  only  an  unsound  enthusiasm, 
and  have  aimed  at  fortifying  the  ground  of  morals  by  re- 
leasing it  from  this  connection,  have  not  improved  their 
moral  standard,  but  greatly  lowered  and  relaxed  it.  With 
a  dulled  sense  of  sin,  a  depressed  standard  of  virtue,  Pe- 
lagianism  thus  tended  to  the  moral  tone  of  Socinianism, 
and  the  religion  which  denies  the  Incarnation.  The  as- 
ceticism of  its  first  promulgators  and  disciples  could  not 
neutralise  the  tendencies  of  a  system  opposed  to  mystery 
and  to  grace,  and  therefore  hostile  at  once  to  the  doctrinal 
and  the  moral  standard  of  Christianity. 

The  triumphant  overthrow  of  such  a  school  was  the  service 
which  S.  Augustine  performed  to  the  Church,  and  for  which, 
under  God,  we  still  owe  him  gratitude.  With  all  the  excess 
to  which  he  pushed  the  truth  which  he  defended,  he  de- 
fended a  vital  truth,  without  which  Christianity  must  have 
sunk  to  an  inferior  religion,  against  a  strong  and  formidable 
attack.  He  sustained  that  idea  of  virtue  as  an  inspiration 
to  which  the  lofty  thought  of  even  heathen  times  ever  clung, 
which  the  Gospel  formally  expressed  in  the  doctrine  of 
grace,  and  which  is  necessary  to  uphold  the  attributes  of  God 
and  the  moral  standard  of  man. 


107 


CHAP.   IV. 

DIFFERENT   INTERPRETATIONS   OF    ORIGINAL   SIN. 

THE  doctrine  of  the  fall  of  man  has  been  always  held  as  a 
fundamental  doctrine  in  the  Church ;  and  all  Catholic  writers 
have  witnessed  to  the  truth,  that  the  first  man  came  from 
the  hands  of  God  an  upright  creature,  that  he  fell  from 
that  uprightness  by  voluntary  transgression,  and  that  he 
involved  in  his  fall  the  whole  of  his  posterity.  But  the 
different  ways  in  which  this  doctrine  has  been  held  involve 
a  discussion  of  some  length  and  difficulty,  to  which  I  shall 
devote  this  chapter. 

The  language  in  which  the  primitive  Church  expresses  this 
doctrine  distinctly  asserts  two  things.  The  early  fathers,  in 
the  first  place,  clearly  held,  that  the  sin  of  Adam  did  not 
stop  with  itself ;  they  speak  of  the  race  and  not  of  the  indi- 
vidual only,  with  reference  to  it ;  and  the  universal  terms  of 
"  man,"  "  mankind,"  "  the  soul,"  leave  no  doubt  as  to  their 
belief  that  human  nature  was  in  some  way  or  other  affected 
by  that  sin.1  Secondly,  when  we  examine  what  this  uni- 
versal consequence  was,  we  find  that  it  is  called  apostacy, 
captivity,  corruption  and  death.2  These  are  metaphorical 


1  Justin    Martyr  :    Tb    y4vos     ruv 
avQpanrcw  6  airb  TOV  'ASct/i  inrb  QO.VO.TOV 


r\avi]v   Triv   TOV  o<pios 
—  Dial  cum  Try  ph.  c.  88. 

Irenseus  :  Ilominem  (the  race)  absor- 
ber! magno  ceto.  —  Adv.  Hoer.3.  22. 

Tatian  :  Trrepoxris  yap  rrjs  tyv^s  rb 
irvtvfj.0.  T~b  rcAetoj/,  (Jirep  awopptyaffa,  5ta 
TTjV  a/JLapTiav  C'TTTTJ  Sxnrep  vtovabs,  KOI 
Xa/xaiTrcT^s  tyevero.  —  Ad.  Graec.  c.  20. 

Athanasius  :  'H  tyvxh  aitoaraoa  rijs 
irpbs  TO  /coAa  Qwpias.  —  Contra  Gentes,4. 

Basil  :  'EKOKudi)  r)  ^vxh  itapaTpaireiaa 
TOV  Kara  <pv<nv.  —  Horn.  Deus  non  Auc- 
tor  Mali.  s.  6. 


Of  the  same  generic  sort  are  the  ex- 
pressions, 7)  irpdanr)  yevecris  (Justin.  Apol. 
1.  61.),  TJ  TraAoto  yweffis  (Tatian,  contra 
Grac.  c.  11.). 

*  Dominabatur  nobis  apostasia. — Ire- 
nacus,  Adv.  Hcer.  5,  1. 

Quos  in  eadem  captivitate  (Adam) 
generavit. —  3. 34. 

Per  priorem  generationem  mortem 
hsereditavimus. — 5.  1. 

Vitium  originis.  Naturae  corruptio. — 
Tertullian,  DeAnima,  c.  41. 

Nativitatis  sordes — Origen,  Horn.  14. 
in.  Luc. 


108  DIFFERENT   INTERPRETATIONS  [CHAP.  IV. 

expressions,  indeed,  and  convey  no  precise  and  accurate  mean- 
ing, but  they  plainly  signify  something  more  than  a  privation 
of  higher  good,  and  something  more  than  a  mere  tendency  to 
positive  evil.  This  tendency  existed  before  the  fall,  and  no 
mere  increase  of  it  could  have  brought  it  up  to  the  natural 
meaning  of  these  terms ;  which  must  therefore  be  taken  to 
signify  positive  moral  evil,  and  to  indicate,  as  the  doctrine  of 
the  early  fathers,  the  positive  sinfulness  of  the  whole  human 
race  in  consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam,  that  is  to  say,  the 
doctrine  of  original  sin. 

But  as  Scripture  reveals  this  consequence  of  the  sin  of 
Adam,  so  natural  reason  certifies,  on  the  other  hand,  that 
nobody  can  sin  but  by  his  own  personal  act,  and  that  one 
man's  guilt  cannot  be  transferred  to  another.  This  truth 
of  natural  reason  mingled  intimately  in  the  statements  of 
the  early  fathers  with  the  truth  of  revelation ;  so  intimately 
indeed,  that  often  no  definite  meaning  can  be  extracted  from 
them.  Two  opposite  truths  are  expressed  together,  and  side 
by  side.1  The  consequence  is,  that  persons  accustomed  to 
the  later  theological  statements  of  this  doctrine  have  been 
often  dissatisfied,  when  they  have  gone  to  examine  the  earlier 
one,  and  have  set  down  the  writers  as  not  full  believers  in 
it.  But  the  truth  is,  such  mixed  and  double  statements 
more  faithfully  express  the  truth  than  single-sided  ones 
drawn  out  in  either  direction  would,  because  they  express 
the  whole  truth,  and  not  a  part  of  it.  What  appears  to  be 
ambiguity  is  comprehensiveness,  and  is  a  merit  and  perfec- 
tion, and  not  a  defect.  Nor,  on  the  same  grounds  on  which 
the  early  fathers  are  charged  with  a  disbelief  in  this  doctrine, 
could  Scripture  itself  be  acquitted. 

But  it  was  not  in  accordance  with  the  nature  of  the 
human  mind  to  allow  these  great  truths  respecting  the  moral 
condition  of  man  to  go  on  thus  mixed  and  united.  Theo- 
logy began  soon  to  draw  out  each  separately ;  and  this 


1  NOTE  XV. 


CHAP.  IV.]  OP   ORIGINAL   SIN.  109 

mixture  parted  into  two  great  doctrinal  views  or  schemes,  of 
which  the  earlier  took  the  side  of  the  natural  truth,  the 
later  of  the  revealed.  The  earlier  fathers,  without  nega- 
tiving their  witness  to  the  true  doctrine  of  original  sin  as  ex- 
pressed in  Scripture,  and  handed  down  in  the  Church,  wrote 
as  theologians  with  a  strong  bias  in  favour  of  the  natural 
truth ;  and  gave  it,  in  their  scheme  of  philosophy  and  doc- 
trine, a  disproportionate  expansion.  Instead  of  leaving  the 
truth  of  revelation  in  its  original  mystery  and  contradiction 
to  human  reason,  as  individual  thinkers  they  modified  and 
limited  it,  so  as  to  be  consistent  with  reason  ;  while  a  later 
school  went  to  the  other  extreme,  and  developed  the  revealed 
truth  at  the  expense  of  the  natural. 

But  an  account  of  the  doctrine  of  the  fall  will  require  as 
an  introduction  some  account  of  the  state  from  which  this 
was  a  fall,  i.e.  of  man's  original  righteousness. 

The  original  righteousness  of  man,  then,  is  universally 
described  in  ancient  writers  as  partly  natural,  partly  super- 
natural. It  was  natural  in  this  respect,  that  it  proceeded  from 
the  exercise  of  a  natural  freewill  and  power  of  choice.  It 
was  supernatural  in  this  respect,  that  certain  supernatural 
gifts,  in  addition  to  freewill,  were  required  for  it.  These 
gifts  could  not  produce  righteousness  unless  his  natural  will 
first  consented  to  use  them;  nor  could  his  will,  however 
sound,  without  the  inspiring  assistance  of  these  gifts;  and 
grace  was  necessary  for  the  righteousness  of  man  upright  as 
well  as  of  man  fallen. 

Such  a  doctrine,  however,  requires  some  explanation  with 
respect  to  two  points.  First,  how  could  it  be  maintained 
with  a  consistent  meaning  that  supernatural  assistance  was 
necessary  towards  fulfilling  the  Divine  precepts,  if  man  had 
naturally  freewill?  For  we  mean  by  freewill,  it  may  be 
said,  the  power,  supposing  the  opportunity,  of  doing  or  ab- 
staining from  any  actions  whatever;  and  therefore,  whatever 
impulse  and  facility  might  be  given  to  right  action  by 


110          DIFFERENT  INTERPRETATIONS     [CHAP.  IV. 

supernatural  assistance,  the  power  to  act  would  not  depend 
upon  it.  But  to  this  objection  it  may  be  replied  that, 
however  we  may  define  freewill  in  words  as  such  a  power, 
we  do  not  mean  that  it  is  such  a  power  abstracted  from 
all  stimulus  or  motive  supplied  to  our  nature  from  other 
quarters.  Thus,  in  the  sphere  of  common  life,  a  man  with 
freewill  has  the  power  to  do  his  duty  to  his  parents,  rela- 
tions, and  friends;  but  he  has  not  this  power  independently 
of  certain  affections  implanted  in  his  nature  over  and  above 
his  will.  Such  questions  as  these  cannot  be  treated  satis- 
factorily, on  account  of  the  great  defects  and  obscurity  both 
in  our  conceptions  of  our  own  nature  and  the  language  in 
which  we  express  them.  But,  upon  the  most  correct  idea  we 
can  form  of  what  the  will  is,  and  what  the  affections  are,  it 
would  seem  that  neither  of  them  could,  without  the  other, 
enable  us  to  fulfil  our  duties  in  common  life.  The  benevolent 
affections  incline  us  indeed  to  benevolent  acts  ;  but,  unless 
supported  by  the  will,  they  yield  to  selfish  considerations, 
and  produce  no  fruits.  The  will,  in  like  manner,  does  not 
enable  us  to  perform  laborious  services  in  our  neighbour's 
behalf  without  the  stimulus  of  the  affections.  Nor,  did 
it  even  enable  us  to  perform  the  external  acts,  could  it 
therefore  enable  us  to  perform  our  whole  duty;  such  duty 
involving  something  of  love  and  affection  in  the  very  perfor- 
mance of  it. 

There  is,  then,  something  defective  in  the  will  as  a  source 
of  action  ;  and  this  defect  existed  in  the  will  of  the  first  man, 
however  sound  and  perfect  that  will  might  be ;  because  it 
is  a  defect  inherent  in  the  will  itself,  and  not  attaching  to 
it  as  a  weak  and  corrupted  will  only.  As,  therefore,  for 
fulfilling  the  relations  of  common  life  we  require  the  help  of 
certain  natural  gifts,  such  as  the  natural  affections  plainly  are, 
being  received  from  God  at  our  creation;  in  the  same  way 
the  first  man,  to  enable  him  to  perform  the  spiritual  relations 
assigned  to  him,  required  the  aid  of  certain  gifts  supernatural, 
or  such  gifts  as  come  under  the  head  of  grace. 


CHAP.  IV.]  OF   ORIGINAL    SIN.  Ill 

But,  in  the  second  place,  granting  that  these  gifts  were  ne- 
cessary for  the  first  man,  it  may  still  be  asked,  why  call  them 
supernatural?  They  were  not  supernatural  as  being  Divine 
gifts ;  for  in  that  case  our  natural  affections  would  be  super- 
natural gifts.  Nor  were  they  supernatural  as  being  additions 
to  his  created  state;  though,  had  they  been,  they  would  not 
have  been  supernatural,  because  they  were  thus  additional. 
Is  not  this,  then,  it  may  be  asked,  an  arbitrary  distinction? 
How  can  the  nature  of  a  man  be  defined  but  as  that  assem- 
blage of  faculties  and  affections,  higher  or  lower,  with  which 
God  endows  him  ?  and  how  can  we  therefore,  out  of  this  whole 
assemblage,  single  out  some  as  natural,  others  as  super- 
natural ? 

In  answer  to  this  objection,  it  may  be  enough  to  say,  that 
when  the  fathers  speak  of  these  gifts  as  supernatural,  they 
do  not  seem  to  mean  that  they  were  above  human  nature 
itself,  that  nature  being  whatever  it  might  please  God  by 
His  various,  gifts  to  make  it,  but  above  human  nature  as 
adapted  to  that  order  of  things  in  which  it  is  at  present 
placed ---this  visible  order  of  things  or  the  world.  A  world 
is  below  or  on  a  level  with  any  set  of  affections,  according  as 
it  manifests  or  does  not  manifest  the  final  objects  of  them. 
The  world  in  which  we  are  manifests  or  presents  to  our  sight 
the  final  object  of  the  social  affections,  viz.  man ;  this  world, 
therefore,  is  not  below,  but  on  a  level  with  the  social  affec- 
tions. But  the  final  object  of  the  spiritual  affections  is  not 
man  but  God  ;  and  this  world,  though  it  proves  to  the  un- 
derstanding the  existence  of,  does  not  manifest  or  present  to 
our  sight,  God.  This  world  is,  therefore,  below  the  spiritual 
affections;  i.  e.  the  spiritual  affections  are  above  this  world. 
The  heavenly  world  cannot  be  carried  on  without  these ; 
for  in  heaven  is  what  divines  call  the  Visio  Dei,  the  sight  of 
God ;  and  therefore  the  supreme  visible  Inhabitant  of  that 
world,  and  omnipresent  as  He  is  supreme,  would  want  atten- 
tion and  regard  without  them.  But,  though  absolutely  need- 
ing the  social  affections  for  its  maintenance,  this  world  can  be 


112 


DIFFERENT   INTERPRETATIONS  [CHAP.  IV. 


carried  on  and  its  affairs  conducted  without  the  aid  of  the 
spiritual ;  which,  as  being  more  than  necessary  for  its  main- 
tenance, are  therefore  above  it;  that  is  to  say,  are  above 
nature,  or  supernatural.1 

Such  being  the  composition  of  man's  original  righteousness, 
the  earlier  fathers  held  that  the  fall  deprived  him  of  these 
supernatural  gifts,  but  left  him  a  fundamentally  sound  nature, 
while  Augustine  maintained,  together  with  the  loss  of  these 
supernatural  gifts,  an  entire  corruption  of  his  nature  as  the 
consequence  of  the  fall. 

To  account  for  the  rise  of  a  particular  school  of  thought  is 
a  superfluous  task,  when  all  that  we  are  concerned  with  is 
the  school  itself;  and  a  task  often  more  perplexing  than 
useful.  Some  reasons,  however,  are  perhaps  discernible  in  the 
circumstances  of  the  early  Church  for  the  supremacy  of  a 
milder  interpretation  of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin.  The 
writers  of  that  age  were,  in  the  first  place,  more  imbued  with 
gentile  thought  than  those  of  a  later  era ;  and  the  Church,  on 
its  first  entrance  into  the  world,  was  both  more  dependent 
on  and  less  suspicious  of  the  world's  philosophers.  It  was 
more  dependent  on  them,  because  it  was  as  yet  without  an 
established  literature  of  its  own ;  it  was  less  suspicious  of 
them,  because  it  did  not  stand  in  so  strong  an  antagonistic 
relation  to  the  world  without,  as  it  subsequently  did  when 
that  world  had  been  longer  tried,  and  had  shown — that  por- 
tion of  it  which  remained  without  —  greater  obstinacy  in 
rejecting  the  Gospel.  Earlier  Christianity  regarded  the 
gentile  world  more  as  a  field  of  promise ;  and  saw  in  it  the 


1  Man  may  be  considered  in  a  double 
order  or  relation.  1.  In  relation  to  the 
natural,  animal,  or  earthly  life.  And 
so  he  is  a  perfect  man  that  hath  only  a 
reasonable  soul  and  a  body  adapted 
thereunto  ;  for  the  powers  and  faculties 
of  these  are  sufficient  to  the  exercise  of 
the  functions  and  operations  belonging 
to  such  a  life.  But,  2.  Man  may  be 
considered  in  order  to  a  supernatural 
end,  and  as  designed  to  a  spiritual  and 


celestial  life ;  and  of  this  life  the  Spirit 
of  God  is  the  principle ;  for  man's 
natural  powers  and  faculties,  even  as 
they  were  before  the  fall,  entire,  were 
not  sufficient  of  themselves  to  reach 
such  a  supernatural  end,  but  needed  the 
power  of  the  Divine  Spirit  to  strengthen, 
elevate,  and  raise  them  thereunto. — 
Bull,  "  On  the  State  of  Man  before  the 
Fall,"  vol.  ii.  p.  87. 


CHAP.  IV.]  OF   ORIGINAL   SIN.  113 

future  harvest  rather  than  the  present  foe.  Nor  is  it  to  be 
forgotten,  that  the  principal  writers  of  that  age  themselves, 
Justin  Martyr,  Clement  of  Alexandria,  and  others,  came 
from  the  ranks  of  gentile  philosophy,  and  retained  in  their 
conversion  the  intellectual  tastes  of  their  former  life.  The 
early  Church  thus  adopted  a  friendly  tone  toward  gentile 
philosophy,  and  acknowledged  sympathies  with  it.  But  such 
sympathies  could  not  but  raise  the  estimate  of  the  natural 
state  of  man ;  for  they  were  themselves  a  tribute  of  respect  to 
the  fruits  of  human  thought  and  feeling  in  that  state. 

Another  reason  for  the  milder  interpretation  of  original  sin 
in  the  early  Church  was  the  great  prominence  then  given  to 
the  doctrine  of  the  Logos,  i.  e.  to  the  contemplation  of  our 
Lord  as  the  wisdom  or  reason  of  the  Father,  and  as  such  the 
source  of  wisdom  and  enlightenment  to  the  human  mind  ;  — 
the  aspect  in  which  He  is  set  forth  in  the  opening  of  St. 
John's  gospel.  The  early  fathers,  partly  from  a  peculiar  sym- 
pathy with  it  as  philosophers,  —  partly  from  an  acquaintance 
with  the  Platonic  doctrine  of  a  Logos,  which  bore  some  re- 
semblance to  and  appeared  to  be  a  heathen  anticipation  of 
the  true  one,  —  and  partly  to  fortify  a  controversial  position 
against  the  Gnostics,  whose  boast  of  a  peculiar  inward  illumi- 
nation imparted  by  their  philosophy  was  thus  met  on  its  own 
ground,  gave  a  conspicuous  place  to  this  character  of  our 
Lord.  The  result  was,  without  any  intention  on  their  part, 
some  loss  of  pre-eminence  to  our  Lord's  office  of  Victim  and 
Expiator.  The  doctrine  of  the  Logos  divided  a  theological 
attention,  which  was  afterward  given  more  wholly  to  the 
doctrine  of  the  atonement.  And  this  position  of  the  atone- 
ment would  naturally  affect  the  position  of  the  doctrine  of  ori- 
ginal sin. 

But,  whatever  were  the  reasons,  an  earlier  school  repre- 
sented man's  nature  as  continuing  fundamentally  sound  after 
the  fall,  and  laid  down,  as  the  consequence  of  that  event,  a 
state  of  defect  and  loss  of  perfection  as  distinguished  from 
a  state  of  positive  corruption.  Man  was  deprived  of  impulses 


114 


DIFFERENT  INTERPRETATIONS     [CHAP.  IV. 


which  elevated  his  moral  nature ;  but  still  that  moral  nature 
remained  entire  and  able  to  produce  fruits  pleasing  in  their 
measure  to  God.  And  though  it  was  admitted  that  all 
mankind  were,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  positive  sinners,  such 
positive  sin  was  not  regarded  as  the  necessary  consequence  of 
original,  but  referred  to  the  freewill  of  each  individual,  who 
could  have  avoided  it,  had  he  chosen  1 ;  all  that  original  sin 
had  entailed  as  of  necessity  and  beyond  the  power  of  man  to 
avoid,  being  a  state  of  defect.2 

Such  an  estimate  of  the  effects  of  the  fall,  as  it  was  partly 
produced  by,  in  its  turn  produced,  a  more  favourable  view 
of  the  moral  condition  of  that  large  proportion  of  mankind 
which  had  been  in  no  way  relieved  from  them, — the  heathen 
world.  It  may  be  considered  doubtful  to  what  precise 
extent  S.  Clement  of  Alexandria,  the  earlier  schools'  great 
exponent  on  this  question,  represents  the  sentiments  of  the 
actual  early  Church  at  large  upon  it.  He  acknowledges  in 
his  writings  the  existence,  and  answers  the  objections,  of  a 
part  of  the  Church  that  did  not  agree  with  him.3  But  it  is 
difficult  to  judge  of  the  size  or  importance  of  this  part ;  and 
a  great  writer  is  in  later  ages  legitimately  supposed,  in  the 
absence  of  express  evidence  to  the  contrary,  and  if  tradition 
has  attached  authority  to  his  name,  to  represent  the  mind  of 
his  age. 


av&aiperov  TTJS  ai/0pa>7rti/r?s 
avT££ovcri6v  — rb  avdaiperov 
a8ov\(ioToi>  Trpbs  e/cA<>7V  jSt'ou  —  ctfpfffis 
jueTa/3oA.7/s  atria  —  irpoaipeffis  €\€vQepa 
— rb  €<£>'  fiiMV — afy'  eavrov  €\6/j.evos 
T&  ayaQov  —  avroKpar-fis.  These  ex- 
pressions occurring  in  the  early  fathers 
(Justin  Martyr,  Irenaeus,  Clement  of 
Alexandria,  Athenagoras,  Tatian,  Cyril) 
are  applied  to  man  fallen  as  well  as  un- 
fallen.  "All  the  Greek  fathers,"  says 
Hagenbach,  "-maintain  the  avrej-oixnov  of 
the  human  soul."  The  early  westerns  are 
no  less  explicit :  Homo  vero  rationabiHs 
et  secundum  hoc  similis  Deo,  liber  in 
arbitrio  factus  et  suse  potestatis,  ipse  sibi 
causa' est,  ut  aliquando  quidem  frumen- 
tum,  aliquando  autem  palea  fiat. — Ire- 
na?us,  1.  4.  c.  9.  Id  quod  erat  semper 


liberum  in  homine  et  sua*  potestatis — C. 
29.  I  give  below  Tertullian's  elaborate 
statement  of  man's  freewill.  No  dis- 
tinction, as  regards  the  will,  appears  to 
have  been  made  between  man  fallen 
and  unfallen,  but  man  as  such  is  spoken 
of  as  having  it. 

2  Bull,  "  On  the  State  of  Man  before 
the    Fall,"   describes   the   loss   of  the 
supernatural  gifts  as  the  consequence 
which   the   early    fathers   annexed   to 
the  fall. 

3  Ot   iroAAot    8e,    KaOaTTfp    ot    TrcuSes 
ra  /ji.opfj.o\vKia  ovrcas  SeSfatrt  TTJZ/  'E\\r)- 
K^V  QiXoffofyiav,  (pogoj'/wej'Oi  JUT?  aTraydyr) 
avrovs. — Potter's    ed.    v.    ii.    p.     780. 
Nal  <pa<r\v  yeypdtydai,  Trdvres  ol  irpb  rrjs 
•jrapovcias  TOV  Kvpiov,    K\fTrrai  flat   Kal 
\9j(rraf. — Vol.  i.  p    366. 


CHAP.  IV.] 


OF    ORIGINAL    SIN. 


115 


Clement  of  Alexandria,  then,  on  this  subject,  takes  what 
may  be  called  the  natural  view  of  the  facts  which  meet  his 
eye.  He  acknowledges  the  noble  affections,  the  moral 
virtues,  even  the  religious  acts,  of  the  heathen  as  real  and 
genuine,  only  as  not  reaching  so  high  a  standard  as  those  of 
the  Christian.  The  authority  of  Scripture  is  claimed,  and 
the  Apostle  is  cited  as  saying  that  "  the  uncircumcision  kept 
the  righteousness  of  the  law." l  There  was  a  first  purifi- 
cation of  the  soul,  which  resulted  in  abstaining  from  evil ; 
a  second,  which  advanced  to  positive  goodness.2  Attention 
is  drawn  to  the  moral  lessons  of  heathen  poets,  to  the  labours 
of  lawgivers3,  to  the  ascetic  fruits  of  the  Buddhist  and 
Brahman  religions  4,  to  the  worship  which  Athens  ignorantly 
paid  to  the  true  God. 

But  the  philosophy  of  the  heathen,  as  the  highest  effort  of 
their  moral  as  well  as  intellectual  faculties,  their  discipline 
of  life  and  school  of  perfection  as  well  as  guide  to  truth, 
was  the  great  fact  which  influenced  Clement  on  this  ques- 
tion, and  which  elicited  his  greatest  admissions,  both  as  to 
the  reality  and  the  source  of  heathen  goodness.  Heathen 
philosophy,  then,  was,  in  his  view,  a  reaching  forward  to 
Divine  truth  and  a  reflection  of  it.  It  only  taught  indeed, 
comprehensible  and  not  mysterious  truth ;  but  the  one  pre- 
pared the  way  for  the  other.  Heathen  philosophy  was  the 
forerunner  of  the  Gospel 5,  and,  as  being  so  excellent  a  thing, 


1  Strom.  1.  1.  c.  19. 

2  Strom.  1.  6.  c.  7. 

9  Strom.  1.  1.  c.   14,  15. 

4  'IvSuv  re  oi  rv^vofrocpiffral,  &\\oi  re 
<f>i\oa6(f>oi  j8ap)3apoi.  AITTOJ/  Se  rovroav 
rb  yevos,  ol  /j.ev  'Sap/j.dvou  avriav,  ol  8e 
BpaX^dvai  Ka\ovfj.evor  Kal  ru>v  2ap/xa- 
vSav  ol  *A\\6§iot  Trpo<ra.yopev6/Ji.ei>oi,  oftre 
irfafis  oiKovmv,  otire  trreyas  K~ypv(Tiv, 
8eV8pa>i>  5s 

aKpofipva  (Tirovvrai,  Kal  vftwp 
irivovffiv,  oo  •ydjuov,  ou  iraiooiroiav  Iffaat 
&<riTep   ol   vvv  'EyKparr)ral  Ka\ou^evoi. 
'Eurl  8t  rwv  'lySajj/  of  rots  E6vrra  TTCI- 
81' 


ffe/j.v6rr)Tos  els  ®ebv  reti/^'fiKcun. — Strom. 
1.  1.  c.  15. 

5  'Opeyerai  rrjs  &€tas  eTnffT'hfj.ris>  ov8e- 
Trca  8e  ruyxdvet. —  Strom.  1.  6.  c.  7. 
The  true  Gnostic  or  Christian  alone 
attained  this  knowledge  :  'O  yvwariKos 
8e  eK€?i/os,  rb.  SoKovvra  ctKaT(£Ar)7rra  elvai 
rois  &\\ois,  atirbs  Ka.ra\a/j.Sdi>ei'  TTUT- 
T€i;cros  ort  ovSev  aKard\r)irTOV  r§  vlai 
rov  deov. — L.  6.  c.  8.  But  the  heathen 
philosophy  supplied  the  elements  of  the 
Divine  :  Atb  Kal  ffroixe^rar-fi  rls  e<rnv 
T)  p.epiK^  of'TTj  (pt\o(To<p'ia  TTJJ  re\fias 
ovrus  *irurr-fifj.r)S  tireKeiva  K6ap.ov  irtpl 
rA  vo-rjTCi,  HO.}  fri  rovrcavra  irvevuariKw- 


I    2 


116 


DIFFERENT   INTERPRETATIONS  [CHAP.  IV. 


it  could  have  no  other  source  than  a  Divine  one.  Philo- 
sophy was  the  great  gift  of  God  to  the  gentile  world ;  and 
the  less  perfect  law  and  the  more  perfect  law  came  both 
from  the  same  Fountain  Head.1  And  though  some  called  its 
truths  stolen  ones,  or  attributed  them  to  the  devil,  or  to  nature 
as  their  teacher ;  still  philosophy,  if  it  had  stolen  its  truths, 
had  them  ;  the  devil,  if  he  taught  them,  had  taught  the  truth  ; 
and  there  was  but  one  Author  of  nature,  z.  e.  God.2 

But  gentile  philosophy  is  not  only  referred  to  Divine 
inspiration  generally  as  its  source,  but  specially  to  our  Lord 
as  the  Logos ;  being  a  fragment  of  that  truth  which  after- 
wards issued  from  the  Incarnate  Word  as  an  harmonious 
whole.3  The  estimate  of  the  heathen  world  thus  gained 
another  important  step ;  and  natural  goodness,  once  admitted 
to  belong  to  it,  did  not  rest  simply  such,  but  rose  above 


repot  avaffrpe(poiJi.ftn)S.  —  c.  8.  Tlpoita- 
raffKevdfei  rfyv  68bv  rrj  fiaffiXiKGirdrri 
8t8a<r/caAia.  —  L.  I.e.  16.  '  A\\a  o~v\ha/j.- 
€dverai  ye  rip  \oyiK(os  eTrtxeipeu/  eef- 
7rou5a/c<fn  avQaTrreffdai  yvuxreus.  —  c.20. 
Kairoi  eV  TToAAoTs  ret.  eoiKora  eirix^ipei 
Kal  TriOavcverat  <pi\oo~o<pia  •  aAAa  ras 
alpefffis  cTTippaTrifei.  —  c,  19.  Kal  icar' 
€fi(paffi,v  Se  Kal  8id<j>ao~iv  ot  ctKpiS&s  irapa 
"EAArjtrt  <pi\oyofyT]ffavres  5iop<ao~i  rbv 
&e6v.  —  C.  1  9.  IlauAos  eV  rais  eirio'roXdis 


verai  aroi- 


crroi- 

drrjv  riva  oixrav,  Kal 
rrjs  aX-nOeias.  —  Strom.  1.  6.  c.  8. 

1  &CLUV  Swpeay  "EAArjcri 
—  Strom.  1.  1.  c.  2.  'Aywybv  Se  rb  4pa- 
ffrbv  Trpbs  r)]v  kavrov  &f(i>piav,  iravrbs 
rov  oKov  eaurbv  rfj  TTJS  yvcaffeoos  aydtrr) 
fTriSۤ\f]Koros  rfj  6ecapi(f.  Aib  Kal  ras 
GPTO\as  as  eScowey,  rds  re  irporepas  rds 
re  Sevrepas  €K  fuas  apvrr6p.evos  TTT^TJS 
6  Kvpios.  K.  r.  A.  —  L.  7.  c.  2. 

"Ean  yap  r§  ovri  <pi\o(ro(f>ia  /jLeyicrrov 
KT^O,  Kal  rifjudirarov  ®f(p.  —  Justin 
Martyr,  Dial,  c,  2.  Though  in  the 
Cohortatio  ad  Grcecos,  he  disparages 
Pagan  philosophy,  while  he  acknow- 
ledges its  possession  of  some  truths, 
such  as  the  unity  of  the  Deity  as 
taught  by  Plato  ;  which,  as  well  as  his 
doctrine  of  ideas,  however,  he  con- 


siders him  te  have  got  from  the  Scrip- 
tures, which  he  saw  in  Egypt ;  the 
latter  from  the  mention  of  the  pattern 

shown  to  Moses  on  the  mount Ad. 

Graec.  c.  21.  et  seq. 

Ea  quidem  quae  ad  sapientes  seculi  de 
veritatis  scientia  pervenerunt,  Deo  re- 
velante  pervenerunt :  sed  dum  aut  vanee 
gloriae  student,  aut  adulantur  erroribus 
vetustis,  aut  metu  principum  refrenan- 
tur,  damnationis  suae  ipsi  judices  fiunt. 
— Origen,  in  Rom.  i.  18.,  vol.  4.  p.  471. 

2  Ou  roivvv  fyevbysrj  <pi\oao<pia,  K.Q.V  6 
/cAeTTTTjs,  Kal  6  \tyevcrrr]S  Kara  /j.eraax'nV-0-- 
rifffjLbvevepyeiasra  aATjflr/  \eyrj. — Strom. 
1.  6.  c.  8.      'O  /cAfTTTTjs  'oirep  ixpeXo/uievos 
eX^t  aATjflcos   exet,    KUV  xPvff'iov   V,   K&v 
apyvpos,  kav  \6yos,  Kav  ti6y/*a. — Strom. 
1.    1.   c.  20.      Et5   Se   (6     5ta§oAos),   cos 
ayye\os   (pcarbs  irpo^rjTevei,  aAr)9rj   apa 
fpet. — L.  6.  c.  8.     EJfr'  a§  (pvaiK^v  ev- 
voiav  fcrx^KevaL  rovs  vEAA7ji/as  \eyoi,  rbv 
rrjs  (pvveus  St]fji.iovpybv  eVa  yiV(a<rKOfj.ev. 
— L.  1.  c.  19. 

3  O&TWS   olv   '-f)    re   &dp§apos,     %    re 
'E\\^viK^  </>iAo<ro<J>ia  rty  d'iSiav  a.\T]QGtav 
ffirapayfj.6v  riva,   ov  rrjs  Aiovvcrov  fj.v6o- 
\oyias,  rys  5e  rov  A6yov  rov  ovros  del 
©eoAo7i'as  ireiroirfraf  6  Se  TO    S/TjpTj^ueVa 
ffvvQels    avQis,   Kal   ei/OTrotTjo'ay,    re\eiov 
rbv  \6yov  aKivSvvus  ev  "crff  on  Kar6- 

iv  a\T)9fiav. — Strom.  1.  I.e.  13. 


CHAP.  IV.] 


OF    ORIGINAL    SIN. 


117 


nature,  and  claimed  affinity  with  grace.  The  dispensation 
of  Paganism,  so  far  as  it  contained  truth,  was  but  a  lower 
part  of  one  large  dispensation,  which  our  Lord,  as  the  Divine 
Reason,  had  instituted  and  carried  on  for  the  enlightenment 
of  the  human  race,  and  of  which  the  Gospel  was  the  con- 
summation ;  heathens  and  Christians  were,  though  in  a  dif- 
ferent measure,  still  alike  partakers  of  that  one  "  Light  that 
lighteth  every  man  that  cometh  into  the  world ;  "  and  all 
mankind,  as  brought  into  union  and  fellowship  by  that 
common  participation,  formed  one  religious  society  and  com- 
munion—  one  Church.1 

The  interpretation  of  original  sin,  again,  as  a  privation 
of  higher  good  rather  than  a  positive  state  of  sin,  affected 
the  punishment  which  was  assigned  to  it.  The  penalty  of 
the  fall  was  exclusion  from  Paradise,  and  with  it  exclusion 
from  that  state  of  blessedness  for  which  the  life  in  Paradise 
was  a  preparation.2  Had  man  kept  the  commandment 
given  to  him,  he  would  have  been  allowed  to  continue  in 
a  state  of  earthly  felicity  till  his  obedience  had  been  tried ; 
he  would  then  have  migrated  by  no  process  repugnant 
to  nature,  but  by  an  easy  and  painless  one,  provided  by 
God  for  this  purpose,  from  an  earthly  to  a  heavenly  Paradise. 


oAA' 

•  «ol 


1  Udvres  avrov  ol  avOpoyiroi 
ol  fj.fv  /car'  tiriyvwffiv,  ol  8e 
oi  p\v  us  <t>i\oi,  ol  Se  us 
ol  5£  us  air\us  oute'rat  •  b  8i8a<r/caAos 
ovros  6  ira&evuv  /j.v<TTiipiois  ptv  TOP 
yvuffTiKbv,  4\-jri(ri  8e  ayadais  TOJ/TTIO-TOC, 
Kal  TratSeia  -ry  firavopBuriKy  Si'  aladr)- 
TIKTJS  evepysias  rbv  o~K\i]poKdp8iov.  .  .  . 
ovr6s  4(TTiv  6  8i8oi»s  Kal  ro7s  "E\\r)<rt  T  V 
<piXoao<piav,  8ta  ruv  vTrepSfeo-repuv  ayye- 
\uv.  .  .  .  "Hroi  yap  ov  <ppovTi£et  iravrvtv 
avdptoiruv  o  Kvpios  '  Kal  TOVTO,  rj  T$  ^ 
Suj/ao-001  iraQoi  av  '  o-rrep  ov  Qfp.n6v  ' 
affQfvetas  yap  ff^f"iov  %  T$  ^  fiov- 
\eadai  Svvd/Jievos,  O&K  ayaQbv  5%  TO 
irdQos.  .  .  .  ^  Kr)8fTai  TWV  (Tvfj.irdvruv  • 
'6irep  Kal  KadrjKei  T^J  Kupiu  irdvruv  ytvo- 
l*.sv(p'  (rarr^p  yap  iffTiv  •  ovx^  T&v  (ifis, 
TUV  8'  of}  —  Strom.  1.  7.  c.  2. 

'ils    olv    (rvyKiyfirai   Ka\ 


\i6ov 

•jrvev/j.ari,  8tA  iro\\uv  *rS>v  fft^i\pS>v  e'/cret- 
KTvhtui',  ovrca  Kal  T$  a.yt<p 
f\K6/j.evoi,  ol  fjLfV  frdperoi, 
oiKetovvrai  rrj  irpurr)  (Ji6vri,  e^e^s  8' 
&*.\oi  Aie'xpt  T^S  T€A.et»ratas. — L.  7.  c.  2. 

Athanasius  (De  Incarn.  c.  12.)  ap- 
pears to  speak  of  the  heathen  as  in  a 
certain  sense  under  the  same  dispen- 
sation as  the  Jews ;  as  having  the  power 
Trarpbs  \6yov  yv&vai  from  the  works 
of  nature  ;  the  prophets  sent  by  God 
to  the  Jews  having  been  sent  for 
their  sake  as  well. 

2  Tatian,  Ad  Graec.  c.  20.  ^upurOf- 
ffav  ol  TrpuToir\ao~Tai  airb  rrjs  yijs  peis, 
a\\'  oijK  £K  ravrrfs,  Kpftrrovos  ot  rfjs 
fvravQa  5iaKofffjL-f]<rfus.  See  Bull,  On 
the  State  o  f  Man  before  the  Fall,  p. 
67. 


I   3 


DIFFERENT    INTERPRETATIONS  [CHAP.  IV. 

His  disobedience  excluded  him  from  both  these  states. 
But  both  the  earthly  Paradise  and  the  heavenly  one  were 
states  of  higher  good :  one  of  lower  good  was  still  left  open 
to  him,  as  the  reward  of  such  virtue  as  he  was  still  capable 
of  reaching. 

The  distinction  between  the  natural  and  supernatural  life, 
it  is  to  be  remembered,  is  a  distinction  between  the  two  states 
themselves,  and  not  between  the  dates  of  them,  whether 
now  or  in  futurity.  It  is  one  drawn  from  their  respective 
inherent  characteristics,  which  are  not  affected  by  the 
order  of  time.  Christian  association  indeed  identifies  the  super- 
natural with  future  life,  the  natural  with  present ;  because 
the  future  life  at  which,  as  Christians,  we  aim  is  a  super- 
natural one :  but  the  two  ideas  are  not  identical.  The 
future  eternal  world  of  the  Pagan,  the  Mahometan,  and 
the  savage  is  a  natural  order  of  things,  and  even  an  inferior 
one  of  that  rank.  A  much  higher  and  more  moral  eternity 
may  be  conceived,  which  would  still  be,  according  to  the 
distinction  which  has  been  laid  down  on  this  subject  *,  a 
natural  one.  Such  an  eternity  was,  according  to  early 
theology,  open  to  man  in  a  state  of  original  sin,  though 
shut  out  from  a  supernatural  or  heavenly  one ;  — the  penalty 
of  which  sin  was  therefore,  as  regards  a  future  life,  made 
a  privation  only,  and  not  a  positive  punishment.  As  re- 
gards the  present  life,  the  exchange  of  pain,  labour,  and 
sorrow  for  the  happiness  of  Paradise  was  indeed  in  itself 
positive  punishment.  But  if  transient  pain  leads  to  an  eter- 
nity of  happiness,  even  of  the  natural  kind,  the  existence 
of  the  creature  is  on  the  whole  a  good  to  him  not  an  evil. 
And  therefore,  however  it  may  have  pleased  God  to  lighten 
the  state  of  trial  in  the  first  instance,  and  even  to  make 
it  painless  and  happy,  a  painful  trial  is,  as  the  means  to 
so  valuable  an  end,  not  otherwise  than  a  good. 

The   assignment   of  such   a   punishment    to  original   sin 

1  P.  in. 


CHAP.  IV.]  OF    ORIGINAL    SIN.  119 

was  in  substance  the  doctrine  of  a  middle  state ;  and  early 
theology  may  be  considered  as  having  pointed  to  such  a 
state  as  the  final  condition  of  the  heathen  and  unbaptized. 
In  saying  this,  however,  I  give  what  theology  before  the 
time  of  S.  Augustine  upon  this  subject  as  a  whole  comes 
to,  rather  than  any  definite  doctrine  that  was  held.  If  we 
examine  the  particulars  of  the  early  Church's  view,  or  what 
was  said  at  different  successive  times  on  this  subject,  these 
will  appear  mainly  under  the  three  following  heads  :  — 

I.  The  statements  of  the  three  first  centuries  bearing 
on  the  question  are  principally  confined  to  a  general  ac- 
knowledgment of  real  goodness  existing  among  the  heathen  ; 
such  an  acknowledgment  as  immediately  suggests  future 
reward  as  the  necessary  result,  under  God's  moral  govern- 
ment, of  such  goodness  ;  but  without  any  reference,  express 
or  implicit,  to  such  a  result.  These  statements,  however, 
assume  occasionally  a  greater  significance  in  this  direction, 
and  appear  to  include  without  expressly  mentioning,  a 
future  state  of  reward.  The  Logos  or  Son  of  God  is, 
according  to  Clement,  not  only  the  Teacher  and  Light  of  all 
mankind  in  different  degrees,  but  the  Saviour  of  all ;  dis- 
pensing His  bounty,  in  proportion  to  their  fitness  for  it ; 
to  the  Greeks  and  barbarians  a  lesser,  to  the  faithful  and 
elect  a  greater  share;  to  all,  according  to  the  measure 
in  which  He  has  dispensed  His  gifts,  and  the  use  made 
of  them,  awarding  a  higher  or  a  lower  rank  in  the  uni- 
verse.1 And  an  express  allusion  to  a  future  life  is  made 
in  the  application  to  the  heathen  of  the  passage  in  Hermas 
relating  to  the  salvation  of  just  men  before  the  law,  bestowed 
by  means  of  a  baptism  after  death.2  But  while  a  pro- 
portionate eternal  reward,  in  the  case  of  the  heathen,  is 
pointed  to,  no  positive  line  is  as  yet  drawn  between  the 


1   B€\TIOJ><X  o7roAo/igc£i>€ii>  Iv  rif  iravrl    j         *  'fls  "A§f\,  us  Nwe,  us  ('•  TIS  Urtpos 
Ta|t».  —  Strom.  1.  7.  c.  2.  !    SIXMOS. — Strom.  1.  2.  c.  9. 


I    4 


120 


DIFFERENT    INTERPRETATIONS  [CHAP.  IV. 


heathen  and  the  Christian  states  in  eternity.  One  state 
with  different  ranks  in  it  is  rather  suggested,  and  all  good 
men  considered  Christians  in  their  degree  are  admitted  to 
one  common,  though  variously  arranged,  kingdom  of  heaven.1 

II.  But,  secondly,  the  concession  to  the  heathen  of  some 
state  of  happiness  after  death  not  being  abandoned,  we  find,  in 
course  of  time,  the  opinion  established  in  the  Church,  that 
original  sin  did  exclude  from  that  place  of  supernatural 
happiness  which  was  called  the  kingdom  of  God,  or  the 
kingdom  of  heaven.  Origen,  while  he  pointedly  claims  for 
heathen  goodness  some  eternal  reward,  and  so  applies  the 
text  "  Glory,  honour,  and  peace  to  every  man  that  worketh 
good,  to  the  Jew  first,  and  also  to  the  Gentile,"  at  the  same 
time  excludes  the  heathen,  as  being  still  under  original  tdn, 
from  the  kingdom  of  heaven.2  The  Pelagians,  with  a  doctrine 
which  did  not  support,  or  rather  opposed  such  a  conclusion,  de- 
ferred-to  an  established  distinction,  and  excluded  the  unbap- 
tized,  whom  the  Church  at  large  regarded  as  under  the  guilt 
of  original  sin,  though  they  themselves  acknowledged  no  such 
sin  in  the  first  instance  from  which  such  guilt  could  arise, 
from  this  state  of  happiness.  The  text,  "  Except  a  man  be 
born  of  water  and  of  the  Spirit,  he  cannot  enter  into  the 
Kingdom  of  God,"  was,  indeed,  considered  to  settle  this 
question,  and  that  in  two  ways :  first,  as  deciding  that  no 
one  in  a  state  of  nature  could  enter  into  the  kingdom  of 
God;  secondly,  as  deciding  that  the  only  means  by  which 
the  penalty  of  nature  was  removed  was  the  rite  of  baptism. 


.  .  .  \6yov  OVT&,  ov 
irav  yevos  avdpuircw  jueretrxc '  Kal  ot 
e  \6yov  puaffavTss  \piaT iavoi  eiffi, 
aBeot  fvofjLi<r6ri<Tav  •  olos  eV  "EAATjcrt 
Sco/cpcfo-Tj?  Kal  'Hpa/cAetTOS,  KOI  oi 
afaois  '  fv  jSapgapots  8e  'AGpaa/J. 
Kal  'Avavlas,  Kal  'Afapias,  Kal  Mt<ra$jA, 
Kal  'HAtay,  Kal  #AAoi  TroA^of. — Justin, 
Apol.  1.  46.,  Ben.  ed. 

2  "Quod  (Rom.  ii.   10.)  de  Judacis 
«t    Gcntibus   dicit,   utrisque    nondum 


credentibus.  Potest  enim  fieri  .  . 
ut  Gracus,  i.  e.  Gentilis  justitiam  teneat. 
.  .  .  Iste  licet  alienus  a  vita  videatur 
seterna,  quia  non  credit  in  Christo,  et 
intrare  non  possit  in  regnum  coelorum, 
quia  renatus  non  est  ex  aqua  et  Spiritu, 
videtur  tamen  quod  per  hsec  qua; 
dicuntur  ab  Apostolo,  bonorum  operura 
gloriam,  et  honorem,  et  pacem  perdere 
penitus  non  possit." — In  Rom.  ii.  10., 
vol.  iv.  p.  484. 


CHAP.  IV.] 


OF   ORIGINAL    SIN. 


121 


An  exception  was  made  in  favour  of  those  who  died  accident- 
ally, before  partaking  of  this  sacrament,  having  shown  faith 
and  repentance ;  and  especially  in  favour  of  martyrs.  But  no 
supposition  of  a  subsequent  extraordinary  Divine  mercy,  and 
extraordinary  means,  was  allowed  in  favour  of  the  rest,  who 
were  all,  heathen  and  unbaptized  infants  alike,  considered  as 
cut  off  for  ever  from  the  remission  of  original  sin,  and  so  as 
excluded  eternally  from  the  kingdom  of  heaven.1 

III.  A  state  of  happiness  after  death,  which  is  not  the 
highest  state,  is  by  implication  a  middle  state.  But,  thirdly,  a 
definite  idea  of  a  middle  state  subsequently  grew  up.  Two 
distinguished  fathers  of  the  Eastern  Church,  Gregory 
Nazianzen,  and  Gregory  of  Nyssa,  leaned  to  it2;  and  the 
Pelagians  seem  to  have  held  it  unchallenged  till  Augustine 
—  who  himself,  in  his  earlier  theological  life,  inclined  to 
it  —  rebuked  them.  But  this  state  was  introduced  only 
to  meet  the  case  of  infants,  not  of  heathens ;  though  on 
the  same  principle  in  which  the  former  were  admissible 
into  it,  the  latter  were  also ;  for  those  who  have  made  the 
most  of  inferior  opportunities  are  in  no  worse  case  than 
those  who  have  had  none.  But  the  early  Church  stopped 
short  of  any  large  application  of  the  doctrine  of  a  middle 
state ;  checked  by  the  absence  of  any  allusion  to  it  in 
Scripture,  and  reluctant  to  give  substance,  shape,  and 
expansion  to  an  idea  in  which  Christians  had  no  practical 
concern,  for  the  aim  assigned  to  them  was  no  middle  one,  but 
the  highest. 

But  while  we  have  before  us  as  the  view  on  the  whole  of 
the  early  Church  before  Augustine's  time,  with  respect  to  the 


1  Augustine  appeals  to  this  estab- 
lished opinion  in  the  case  of  infants  in 
his  controversy  with  Vincentius  Victor: 
— •'  Never  believe,  or  say,  or  teach  that 
infants  dying  before  they  are  baptized 
can  attain  to  the  remission  of  original 
sin,  if  you  wish  to  be  a  Catholic— «  vis 
esse  Catholicus.  (De  Anima,  1.  3.  c. 


ix. )  This  is  opposed  to  the  most  fund- 
ament al  Catholic  faith — contra  Catho- 
licam  fundatissimam  fidem."  —  De 
Anima,  1.  2.  c.  xii.  See  Wall  on  In- 
fant Baptism,  part  1.  c.  15.;  part  2. 
c.  6. 

2  NOTE.  XVI. 


122  DIFFERENT    INTERPRETATIONS  [CHAP.  IV. 

virtuous  heathen  and  unbaptized  infants,  partly  implied  and 
partly  expressed,  a  middle  state,  it  is  indifferent  to  the 
question  before  us  whether  this  state  was  a  distinct  one  or 
only  a  lower  rank  of  one  and  the  same  heavenly  state ;  the 
only  point  important  to  observe  being,  that  the  penalty  of 
original  sin  was  a  privation,  not  a  positive  evil. 

The  doctrine  of  original  sin,  thus  explained  and  modified, 
was  not  inconsistent  with  natural  reason  and  justice.  It  did 
not  contradict  the  truth  of  common  sense,  that  one  man  is 
not  responsible  for  another  man's  acts,  because  it  did  not 
attach  any  such  judicial  consequences  to  the  sin  of  Adam,  as 
required  such  a  responsibility  to  justify  them.  The  penalty 
of  original  sin  was  a  particular  state  and  condition  of  the 
human  race,  which  would  not  have  been  unjustly  ordained, 
had  there  been  no  original  sin  at  all.  The  infliction  of  posi- 
tive evil  and  pain  as  a  punishment  is  wholly  contrary,  indeed, 
to  natural  justice,  except  on  the  ground  of  personal  guilt; 
but  every  one  must  admit,  that  the  Author  of  nature  has 
a  perfect  right  to  allot  different  degrees  of  good  to  His 
creatures,  according  to  His  sovereign  will  and  pleasure ;  and 
that  He  is  not  bound  in  justice  to  give  either  the  highest 
moral  capacities,  or  their  accompaniment,  the  highest  capa- 
cities for  happiness  to  all,  because  He  is  able  to  bestow  these 
when  it  pleases  Him.  We  see,  in  the  order  of  nature,  and  in 
the  constitution  of  the  world  around  us,  the  greatest  variety 
on  this  head ;  and  on  the  same  principle  on  which  God  has 
created  different  kinds  of  beings  He  may  also  create  the 
same  kind  with  higher  or  lower  faculties.  A  lower  capacity, 
then,  for  virtue  and  happiness  in  the  human  race,  was  no  in- 
justice as  a  consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam ;  because  it  was 
no  injustice  had  it  been  no  consequence  of  anything,  but 
been  assigned  to  man  originally  at  his  creation,  as  that 
measure  of  good  which  it  pleased  God  to  appoint  for  him. 
For,  though  the  fall  was  the  occasion  and  cause  of  this 
measure  being  assigned,  it  is  not  unjust  to  do  that  for  a 
particular  reason  which  you  have  a  right  to  do  without 


CHAP.  IV.]  OF   ORIGINAL   SIN.  123 

a  reason;  the  agreement  of  the  act  itself  with  justice  being 
supposed,  no  great  importance,  at  any  rate,  will  attach  to 
such  a  further  question.  Nor  is  temporary  pain,  again,  an 
injustice,  if  it  is  designed  to  lead  to  ultimate  happiness;  but 
might  have  been  justly  imposed  by  God  on  mankind  at  the 
creation,  and  independently  of  the  sin  of  Adam,  for  that  end. 

From  such  a  limited  and  modified  doctrine  of  original  sin 
let  us  turn  to  the  doctrine  of  a  later  school. 

The  Western  Church  has,  as  a  whole,  entered  more  deeply 
into  the  mysteries  of  the  inner  man  than  the  Eastern  has, 
into  that  mixed  sense  of  spiritual  weakness  and  desire,  of  a 
void  which  no  efforts  can  fill,  and  of  a  struggle  endless  upon 
all  natural  principles.  This  disposition  has  characterised  her 
great  schools  ;  has  largely  hinged  her  great  conflicts  and  di- 
visions ;  the  portions  which  the  Reformation  separated  from 
the  main  body  have  retained  it ;  the  Koman  and  Protest- 
ant churches  meet  in  it ;  and  the  West  has  been  the  pro- 
vidential exponent  of  the  doctrine  of  S.  Paul.  Tertullian 
first  set  the  example  of  strength  and  copiousness  in  laying 
down  the  nature  and  effects  of  original  siu ;  he  was  fol- 
lowed by  Cyprian  and  Ambrose.  But  language  did  not 
as  yet  advance  out  of  the  metaphorical  stage;  and  apo- 
stacy,  captivity,  death,  in  a  word,  the  corruption  of  human 
nature,  was  all  that  was  yet  asserted.  But  language  could 
not  ultimately  rest  in  a  stage  in  which,  however  strong  and 
significant,  it  did  not  state  what  definite  thing  had  happened 
to  human  nature  in  consequence  of  the  fall,  and  just  stopped 
short  of  expressing  what,  upon  a  real  examination,  it  meant. 
If  a  man  is  able  to  do  a  right  action,  and  does  a  wrong  one, 
he  is  personally  guilty  indeed,  but  it  cannot  be  said  that  his 
nature  is  corrupt.  The  passions  and  affections  may  be  in- 
conveniently strong,  and  so  the  nature  be  at  a  disadvantage ; 
but  no  mere  strength  of  the  passions  and  affections  shows 
the  nature  corrupt  so  long  as  the  will  retains  its  power.  On 
the  contrary,  the  nature  is  proved  to  be  fundamentally  sound, 
by  the  very  fact  of  its  being  equal  to  the  performance  of  the 


124 


DIFFERENT    INTERPRETATIONS 


[CHAP.  IV. 


right  act.  The  test  of  a  sound  or  corrupt  nature,  then,  is  an 
able  or  an  impotent  will;  and  if  a  corruption  of  nature 
means  anything  at  all,  it  means  the  loss  of  freewill.  This  was 
the  legitimate  advance  which  was  wanted  to  complete  the 
expression  of  the  doctrine  ;  and  this  complement  it  was  left  to 
S.  Augustine  to  give. 

S.  Augustine's  position  respecting  freewill  had  its  com- 
mencement at  a  date  in  the  history  of  man  earlier  than  the 
corruption  of  his  nature,  viz.  at  his  creation.  Philosophy 
raises  an  insuperable  difficulty  to  the  freedom  of  any  created 
will ;  for  freedom  of  the  will  implies  an  original  source  of 
action  in  the  being  who  has  it,  original  not  relatively  only, 
in  the  way  in  which  any  cause,  however  secondary,  is  original 
as  compared  with  its  effect,  but  absolutely ;  and  to  be  an  ori- 
ginal cause  of  anything  is  contrary  to  the  very  essence  of  a 
being  who  is  not  original.  Tertullian  had  a  distinct  philo- 
sophical conception  of  this  difficulty,  and  met  it  by  the  only 
answer  open  to  a  believer  in  freewill ;  an  assertion  of  the 
truth  together  with  an  acknowledgment  of  the  difficulty. 
Originality  is  the  highest  form  of  being ;  and  everything 
which  does  not  move  itself,  whatever  be  its  grandeur  or  sub- 
limity as  a  spectacle,  is  intrinsically  despicable,  in  comparison 
with  that  which  does.  The  Divine  Power,  then,  resolving 
upon  its  own  highest  exertion,  chose  originality  itself  as  a 
subject  of  creation,  and  made  a  being  which,  when  made,  was 
in  its  turn  truly  creative,  the  author  and  cause  of  its  own 
motions  and  acts.  And  whereas  the  creature  would,  as  such, 
have  possessed  nothing  of  his  own,  God  by  an  incomprehen- 
sible act  of  liberality,  alienated  good  from  Himself  in  order 
that  the  creature  might  be  the  true  proprietor  of  it,  and  ex- 
hibit a  goodness  of  which  His  own  will  was  the  sole  cause.1 


1  "  Sola  nunc  bonitas  deputetur, 
quae  tantum  homini  largita  sit,  id  est 
arbitrii  libertatem.  .  .  .  Nam  bonus 
natura  Deus  solus.  .  .  .  Homo  autem 
qui  totus  ex  institutione  est,  habens 


initium,  cum  initio  sortitus  est  formam 
qua  esset,  atque  ita  non  natura  in 
bonum  dispositus  est,  sed  institutione; 
non  suum  habens  bonus  esse  sed  in- 
stitutione. .  .  .  Ut  ergo  bonum  jam 


CHAP.  IV.] 


OF    ORIGINAL    SIN. 


125 


And  this  redounded  ultimately  to  God's  glory,  for  the 
worthiest  and  noblest  creature  must  know  Him  best.  Tertul- 
lian,  then,  distinctly  and  philosophically  recognised  a  created 
will  which  was  yet  an  original  cause  in  nature.  But  S. 
Augustine,  while,  on  the  ground  of  Scripture,  he  assigned 
freewill  to  man  before  the  fall,  never  recognised  philosophi- 
cally an  original  source  of  good  in  the  creature.  As  a 
philosopher  he  argued  wholly  upon  the  Divine  attribute  of 
power,  or  the  operation  of  a  First  Cause,  to  which  he  simply 
referred  and  subordinated  all  motion  in  the  universe  ;  and 
laid  down  in  his  dicta  on  this  subject  the  foundation  of  scho- 
lastic necessitarianism.1 

Thus  philosophically  predisposed,  the  mind  of  S.  Augus- 
tine took  up  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  as  handed  down  by 
the  voice  of  the  Church  and  by  a  succession  of  writers,  and 
brought  the  whole  mass  of  language  which  three  centuries 
had  produced,  and  which  up  to  his  time  had  advanced  in 
copiousness  and  illustration,  rather  than  in  strength  of  mean- 
ing, to  a  point.  He  explained  the  corruption  of  human  nature 
to  mean  the  loss  of  freewill;  and  this  statement  was  the 
fundamental  barrier  which  divided  the  later  from  the  earlier 
scheme  and  rationale  of  original  sin.  The  will,  according  to 
the  earlier  school,  was  not  substantially  affected  by  the  fall. 
Its  circumstances,  its  means  and  appliances,  were  altered,  not 
itself ;  and  endowed  with  spiritual  aids  in  Paradise ;  deprived 
of  them  at  the  fall ;  re-endowed  with  them  under  the  Gospel, 
it  retained  throughout  these  alterations  one  and  the  same 
unchanged  essential  power,  in  that  power  of  choice  whereby 
it  was,  in  every  successive  state  of  higher  or  lower  means, 
able  to  use  and  avail  itself  of  whatever  means  it  had.  But 
in  Augustine's  scheme  the  will  itself  was  disabled  at  the 


suum  haberet  homo,  emancipatum  sibi 
a  Deo,  et  fieret  proprietas  jam  boni  in 
homine  et  quodammodo  natura,  de  in- 
stitutione  ascripta  est  illi  quasi  libripens 


emancipati  a  Deo  boni,  libertas  et  po- 
testas  avbitrii,  quae  efficeret  bonum  ut 
proprium." — Adv.  Marc.  1.  2   c.  0. 
1  See  p.  4. 


126  DIFFERENT    INTERPRETATIONS  [CHAP.  IV. 

fall,  and  not  only  certain  impulses  to  it  withdrawn,  its  power 
of  choice  was  gone,  and  man  was  unable  not  only  to  rise 
above  a  defective  goodness,  but  to  avoid  positive  sin.  He 
was  thenceforth,  prior  to  the  operation  of  grace,  in  a  state  of 
necessity  on  the  side  of  evil,  a  slave  to  the  devil  and  to  his 
own  inordinate  lusts. 

Such  a  difference  in  the  explanation  of  original  sin  neces- 
sarily produced  a  corresponding  difference  in  the  estimation 
of  heathen  morals.  Augustine  and  Clement  both  regard  the 
heathen  character  as  faulty ;  but  there  are  two  distinct  types 
of  a  faulty  character.  It  is  a  rule  in  morals,  that  the  mo- 
rality of  the  man  must  precede  the  morality  of  the  action, 
that  some  general  condition  must  be  fulfilled  in  the  agent's 
character  before  any  particular  act  can  be  pronounced  good 
in  him ;  this  morality  of  the  man,  the  fulfilment  of  this 
general  condition,  is  the  foundation.  One  type,  then,  of  a 
faulty  character,  is  that  of  a  character  good  at  the  foundation, 
and  only  failing  in  degree ;  another  is  that  of  a  character  bad 
at  the  foundation.  The  fruits  of  the  former  are  solid,  as  far 
as  they  go  ;  but  the  apparently  good  fruits  of  a  fundamentally 
corrupt  character  are  hollow,  and  are  not  real  virtues.  Such 
a  character  may  display,  for  example,  affection  to  individuals, 
generosity  upon  occasions,  or  courage,  or  industry  ;  but  upon 
such  a  foundation  these  are  not  virtues.  This  is  the  distinc- 
tion between  the  faultiness  which  Clement  and  the  faultiness 
which  Augustine  attributes  to  heathen  morality.  Clement 
allows  the  foundation  to  exist  — this  general  condition  to  be 
fulfilled  in  a  degree — in  the  heathen,  because  he  considers 
nature  able  in  a  degree  to  supply  it ;  he  therefore  regards 
heathen  morality  as  real  and  solid,  as  far  as  it  goes,  though 
imperfect.  But  Augustine  does  not  admit  the  power  of 
nature  to  supply  such  a  foundation  in  any  degree  whatever ; 
for  constituting  which  he  requires  a  certain  state  of  mind, 
which  he  considers  to  be  only  possible  under  grace,  viz. 
faith,  so  interpreting  the  texts,  "  Without  faith  it  is  impossi- 


CHAP.  IV.] 


OF    ORIGINAL    SIN. 


127 


ble  to  please  God,"  and  "  whatsoever  is  not  of  faith  is  sin." l 
He  therefore  regards  heathen  morality  as  bad  at  the  founda- 
tion, and  therefore  as  a  hollow,  false,  and  only  seeming  mo- 
rality itself.  Nor  does  he  admit  the  existence  of  a  good 
heathen,  though  he  admits  that  the  heathen  did  actions 
which  in  Christians  would  be  good  ones.2  And  though  he 
allows  that  the  Divine  image  in  which  man  was  created  did 
not  wholly  disappear  at  the  fall,  a  remainder  (to  preserve 
man's  identity  in  the  two  states)  of  a  rational  nature  is 
alone  admitted.  He  extends  this  view  to  heathen  philosophy. 
Acknowledging  in  some  systems  a  greater  likeness  to  Christian 
truth  than  in  others,  he  speaks  of  heathen  philosophy  as  a 
whole  with  coldness,  distrust,  and  hostility,  warning  the 
Christian  against  it.  He  looks  on  the  truth  it  promulgates  as 
external  to  Christian  truth  and  not  mingling  with  it,  and 
sees  a  barrier  between  the  two  where  the  earlier  fathers  only 
saw  a  gradual  ascent.3 


1  "  Sed  absit   ut  sit  in  aliquo  vera 
virtus,  nisi  fuerit  Justus.     Absit  autem 
ut  sit  Justus  vere,  nisi  vivat  ex  fide: 
'Justus    enim    ex    fide   vivit.'      Quis 
porro  eorum  qui  se  Christianos  haberi 
volunt,  nisi  soli  Pelagiani,  aut  in  ipsis 
etiam    forte   tu    solus,  justum   dixerit 
infidelem,     justum     dixerit     impium, 
justum    dixerit   diabolo    mancipatum? 
Sit  licet  ille  Fabricius,  sit  licet  Fabius, 
sit  licet  Scipio,  sit  licet  Regulus,  quorum 
me    nominibus,    tanquam   in   antiqua 
Curia  Romana  loqueremur,  putasti  esse 
terrendum."— Contra  Julianum,Pelag.l. 
4.  n.  17. ;  see,  too,  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  3. 
n.  14.  23. 

2  "  Hi  qui  naturaliter  quae  legis  sunt 
faciunt,  nondum  sunt  habendi  in  nu- 
mero    eorum    quos    Christi    justificat 
gratia;  sed  in   eorum   potius   quorum 
etiam  impiorum  nee  Deum  verum  ve- 
raciter    justeque    colentium,    quaedam 
tamen  facta  vel  legimus  vel  novimus 
vel   audimus,  quse   secundum  justitia? 
regulam    non    solum   vituperare    non 
possumus,  verum  etiam  merito  recteque 
lauclamus" :   quanquam    si    discutiantur 
quo   fine    fiant,    vix   inveniuntur  qua? 


justitias  debitam  laudem  defensionemvc 
mereantur." —  De  Spirit  et  Lit.  1.  1.  n. 
48. 

3  Eosque  (Platonists,  Pythagoreans, 
&c. )  nobis  propinquiores  fatemur. — 
De  Civit.  Dei,  1.  8.  c.  9. 

"  Cavet  (Cbristianus)  eos  qui  se- 
cundum elementa  hujus  mundi  philo- 
sophantur,  non  secundum  Deum,  a  quo 
ipse  factus  est  mundus.  Admonetur 
enim  praecepto  Apostolico  :  '  Cavete  ne 
quis  vos  decipiat,'  "  &c.  (Col.  ii.  8.) — De 
Civit.  Dei,  1.  8.  c.  10. 

It  is  worthy  of  remark,  that  while 
Clement  sees  in  the  "  rudiments  of  the 
world  "  which  S.  Paul  speaks  of,  the 
objects  of  intellectual  apprehension,  as 
distinct  from  but  subsidiary  to  those 
of  faith  (Strom.  1.  6.  c.  8.),  Augustine 
sees  in  them  carnal  and  corrupt  ideas 
only.  The  latto.r  interpretation  agrees 
more  with  the  text,  in  which,  however, 
S.  Paul  is  speaking  only  of  a  certain 
portion  of  heathen  philosophy,  not  the 
whole  of  it:  but  the  difference  in  the 
interpretation  of  the  Apostle  shows  the 
different  feeling  of  the  two  writers  on 
this  subject. 


128          DIFFERENT  INTERPRETATIONS     [CHAP.  IV. 

But,  though  no  goodness  in  the  heathen  is  admitted,  he 
allows  different  degrees  in  evil,  and  that  some  men  in  a  state 
of  nature  have  been  less  sinful  than  others,  such  as  Socrates 
and  Fabricius ;  but  it  is  difficult  to  say  whether  he  allows,  in 
this  admission,  any  relaxation  in  the  servitude  of  the  natural 
will,  any  kind  or  degree  of  liberty  of  choice  as  still  left  in  it,  or 
whether  he  only  means  that  the  evil  passions  are  less  strong 
in  some  natural  constitutions  than  in  others.  Indeed,  if  it  be 
asked  to  what  extent  Augustine's  law  of  peccatum  p&na  peccati 
operated, — whether  that  relation  of  necessary  effect  in  which 
actual  sin  stood  to  original  applied  to  all  the  actual  sin  of 
man  in  a  state  of  nature, —  whether  the  want  of  power  to  avoid 
sin  involved  in  original  sin  was  a  want  of  power  to  avoid  every 
excess  of  sin  which,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  had  been  committed  in 
the  world, —  and  so  whether  the  whole  of  that  mass  of  depra- 
vity and  crime  which  the  history  of  mankind  presented  went 
back,  according  to  his  doctrine,  to  original  sin,  as  the  neces- 
sary development  of  that  one  seed, — it  must  be  replied,  that 
his  language  varies  on  this  subject.  He  sometimes  represents 
the  whole  of  this  mass  of  actual  sin  as  the  necessary  effect  of 
original,  and  accounts  for  the  different  degrees  in  it  by  sup- 
posing different  degrees  of  original  sin ;  that  is  to  say,  by 
supposing,  the  impotence  of  the  will  remaining  the  same  in 
all,  different  degrees  of  strength  in  the  evil  passions  and 
inclinations.  Sometimes  he  only  represents  a  part  of  it  as 
such,  and  the  rest  as  added  by  the  man  himself.1  But  the 
language  in  which  this  modification  of  the  effect  of  original 
sin  is  expressed  is  obscure  and  uncertain ;  nor  is  it  easy  to 
see  whether  those  additions  are  only  additions,  as  effects  are 
additions  to  a  cause,  or  whether  they  are  additions  man  him- 
self has  made  in  the  use  of  a  lower  kind  of  freewill  still  left 
in  his  nature.  Thus  much  is  certain,  however,  that  such  a 
liberty  of  choice,  if  it  is  allowed  by  Augustine,  is  not  the 


1  NOTE  XVII. 


CHAP.  IV.]  OF   ORIGINAL    SIN.  129 

liberty  to  choose  good,  but  only  lesser  evil,  and  therefore  is  not 
properly  freewill ;  though  whether  a  will  which  can  do  the 
one  and  not  the  other  is  a  tenable  conception,  is  a  question 
into  which  we  need  not  enter. 

Original  sin  was  thus  represented,  in  its  nature  and  effects, 
by  Augustine,  as  positive  sin,  and  not  as,  according  to  the 
earlier  interpretation,  a  loss  of  higher  goodness  only;  and 
this  difference  was  followed  by  a  corresponding  difference  in 
the  punishment  attached  to  it.  S.  Augustine  held  a  state  of 
positive,  evil  and  pain,  and  not  a  privation  of  higher  happi- 
ness only,  as  the  punishment  of  original  sin.  Inclined,  at  an 
earlier  stage  of  his  theological  life,  to  the  position  of  a  middle 
state  for  unbaptized  infants,  as  a  convenient  solution  of  a 
difficulty,  a  stronger  subsequent  view  of  the  guilt  of  original 
sin  rejected  it ;  and  in  the  controversy  with  the  Pelagians 
he  not  only  attacked  that  position,  but  made  an  argumenta- 
tive use  of  the  contrary  one  as  proved  from  Scripture.  The 
Pelagians  adopted  the  position  of  a  middle  state  as  fitting  in 
with  their  own  scheme,  which  they  had  constructed  upon  a 
mixed  ground  of  their  own  peculiar  doctrine,  and  of  deference 
to  the  general  belief  of  the  Church.  Denying  original  sin 
altogether,  they  could  not  admit  any  positive  punishment  as 
due  to  unbaptized  infants,  much  less  a  punishment  in  hell ; 
while  deference  to  general  belief  prevented  the  assignment 
of  heaven.  A  middle  place,  therefore,  between  heaven  and 
hell,  exactly  served  their  purpose ;  neither  punishing  the  in- 
nocent being  nor  exalting  the  unbaptized  one.  But  Augustine 
attacked  this  position  energetically  as  one  which  in  effect 
abolished  original  sin  itself;  arguing  forcibly,  that  only  two 
places  were  mentioned  in  Scripture,  heaven  and  hell,  and  that, 
therefore,  a  third  place,  which  was  neither  the  one  nor  the 
other,  was  an  unauthorised  invention  of  man.  He  then  used 
the  scriptural  position  of  only  two  places  as  a  positive  argu- 
ment in  support  of  his  doctrine  of  original  sin.  For  if  there 
were  only  two  places,  and  those  guilty  of  original  sin  were 
excluded  by  the  general  belief  of  the  Church  from  heaven, 

K 


130 


DIFFERENT   INTERPRETATIONS  [CHAP.  IV. 


hell   only   remained   for   them;   and   a   punishment   in  hell 
necessarily  implied  a  positive  original  guilt  to  deserve  it.1 

The  position  of  a  middle  state  then  rejected,  Augustine 
assigned  a  punishment  in  hell  to  original  sin,  and,  allowing 
differences  in  degree,  still  left  some  degree  or  other  of  that 
punishment  necessary  for  that  sin.  The  heathen  who  had 
not  sinned  against  the  light  had  a  milder  punishment  in  hell 
than  those  who  had;  but  ignorance  was  only  allowed  to 
procure  a  mitigation  of  it,  not  a  release  from  it.  Those  who 
knew  our  Lord's  will  and  did  it  not,  were  beaten  with  many 
stripes ;  those  who  knew  it  not  and  did  it  not,  with  few 
stripes.2  With  respect  to  unbaptized  infants,  his  language 
varies  in  strength.  The  severest  consigns  them  to  the  flames 
of  hell ;  the  most  lenient  to  such  a  punishment  as  left 
existence  under  it  better  than  deprivation  of  being; — a  li- 
mitation which  might  appear  to  leave  no  room  for  positive 
punishment  at  all,  as  it  might  be  said  that  it  would  be  better 
not  to  exist  than  to  exist  eternally  in  any  degree  of  pain ; 
but  such  refinements  are  hardly  worth  pursuing.  A  middle 
language  consigns  them  to  the  mildest  punishment  which 


1  "  Istam  nescio  quam   medietatem 
quam   conantur  quidam   parvulis  non 
baptizatis  tribuere. " — De  Pecc.  Merit,  et 
Rern.  1,  28.     "An   tandem  aliquando 
extra  regnum  Dei  infelices  futures  fate- 
mini    parvulos   non   renatos?      Dicite 
ergo  hujus  infelicitatis  meritum,   ver- 
bosi  et  contentiosi,  qui  negatis  originale 
peccatum." — Op.  Imp.    2.  113.     "  Qui 
velut  defensione  justitiae  Dei  niteris,  ut 
evertas   quod  de  parvulorum   non   re- 
generatorum    damnatione    tota    sentit 
ecclesia,    nunquam   dicturus   es    grave 
jugum  super  parvulos  unde  sit  justum, 
si  non  trahant  originale  peccatum." — 
2.  117.     See  NOTE  XVIII. 

2  "  Sed  et  ilia  ignorant ia  quae  non 
est  eorum  qui  scire  nolunt,  sed  eorum 
qui  tanquam  simpliciter  nesciunt,  ne- 
minem  sic  excusat  ut  sempiterno  igne 
non  ardeat,  si  propterea  non  credidit, 
quia  non  audivit  omninoquod  crederet; 
sed    fortasse   ut    mitius    ardeat.     Non 


enim  sine  causa  dictum  est  'Effunde 
iram  tuam  in  gentes  quae  te  non  nove- 
runt;'  et  illud  quod  ait  Apostolus, 
'  Cum  venerit  in  flamma  ignis  dare  vin- 
dictam  in  eos  qui  ignorant  Deum.'" — 
De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.,  c.  iii. 

"  Sicut  enim  non  impediunt  a  vita 
eterna  justum  quaedam  peccata  venialia 
sine  quibus  haec  vita  non  ducitur:  sic 
ad  salutem  aeternam  nihil  prosunt  impio 
aliqua  bona  opera,  sine  quibus  diffi- 
cillime  vita  cujuslibet  pessimi  hominis 
invenitur.  Veruntamen  sicut  in  regno 
Dei  velut  Stella  ab  stella  in  gloria 
different  sancti;  sic  et  in  damnatione 
poenae  sempiternae  tolerabilius  erit 
Sodomae  quam  alteri  civitati :  et  erunt 
quidam  duplo  amplius  quibusdam 
gehennse  filii:  ita  nee  illud  in  judicio 
Dei  vacabit,  quod  in  ipsa  impietate 
damnabili  magis  alius  alio  minusve 
peccaverit." — De  Spirit,  et  Lit.  1.  1. 
c.  28. 


CHAP.  IV.]  OF   ORIGINAL   SIN.  131 

there  is  in  hell.     On  the  whole,  some  true  punishment  in  hell 
is  assigned  to  unbaptized  infants.1 

This  whole  doctrine  of  original  sin,  its  effects  and  its 
punishment,  we  must  observe,  is  but  the  legitimate  drawing 
out,  in  statement  and  consequence,  of  the  true  and  scriptural 
doctrine  of  original  sin.  The  corruption  of  human  nature 
followed  deservedly,  according  to  that  doctrine,  upon  the  sin 
of  Adam.  But  the  corruption  of  human  nature  can  only  be 
adequately  defined  as  the  loss  of  freewill  or  necessary  sinful- 
ness;  and  sin  deserves  eternal  punishment,  and  deserving  it, 
will,  according  to  the  Divine  justice,  infallibly  obtain  it,  unless 
it  is  forgiven.  The  consignment,  therefore,  of  heathens  and 
unbaptized  infants  to  the  punishment  of  hell,  extreme  result 
as  it  was,  was  but  the  result  of  the  true  doctrine  ;  because,  in 
the  absence  of  the  only  authorised  sign  of  Divine  forgiveness, 
these  lay  under  the  full  guilt  of  a  sin  which  deserved  such 
punishment.  There  was  no  authority,  indeed,  for  the  positive 
assertion  of  the  fact  of  such  punishment;  for  the  fact  implies 
that  no  forgiveness  by  any  other  means  has  been  obtained, 
and  nobody  can  know  whether  God  may  not  choose  to 
employ  other  means  to  this  end  besides  those  of  which  He 
has  informed  us;  and  if  an  exception  to  the  necessity  of 
baptism  is  allowed  in  certain  cases,  it  can  not  be  arbitra- 
rily limited;  nor  does  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  itself  at 
all  restrict  the  means  by  which  its  guilt  may  be  removed. 
In  asserting  the  fact,  then,  Augustine  plainly  exceeded  the 
premiss  which  the  true  doctrine  supplied ;  but,  so  far  as  he 
left  all,  who  lay  under  the  guilt  of  original  sin,  under 
desert  of  eternal  punishment,  he  no  more  than  drew  out 
the  true  scriptural  and  Catholic  doctrine.  But,  while  he 
interpreted  the  revealed  doctrine  on  the  whole  legitimately 
and  faithfully,  he  failed  in  not  seeing  or  not  allowing  a 
place  to  the  counter-truth  of  natural  reason.  As  Scripture 
declares  the  nature  of  every  man  to  be  corrupt  in  con- 


1  NOTE  XVIIL 

K     2 


132  DIFFERENT   INTERPRETATIONS  [CHAP.  IV. 

sequence  of  Adam's  sin,  and  from  that  corruption  sinfulness 
necessarily  follows,  and  from  that  sinfulness  desert  of  eternal 
punishment, — so  Scripture  and  reason  alike  declare,  that  one 
man  is  not  responsible  for  another  man's  sin  ;  and  from  that 
position  it  follows  that  the  posterity  of  Adam  are  not  as 
such  sinful ;  and  from  that,  that  they  do  not  as  such  deserve 
eternal  punishment.  It  was  wrong,  then,  to  draw  out  a 
string  of  consequences  from  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  and 
state  them  as  absolute  truths,  when  they  were  contradicted 
at  every  step  by  a  set  of  parallel  consequences  from  another 
truth,  which  was  equally  certain,  and  to  which  Scripture 
itself  bore  equal  testimony.  It  was  quite  true  that  the 
doctrine  of  original  sin,  did  it  stand  alone,  withdrew  from  the 
heathen  the  whole  foundation  of  virtue,  and  so  represented 
a  good  heathen  as  impossible.  But  this  was  only  one  aspect 
of  his  state ;  there  was  also  another,  in  which  he  came  before 
us  as  capable  of  virtue ;  and,  under  the  check  of  a  mystery,  the 
plain  and  natural  facts  of  the  case  might  be  acknowledged. 
And  the  same  may  be  said,  with  respect  to  the  heathen,  on  the 
question  of  future  punishment.  These  were  truths,  then,  to  be 
held  with  a  special  understanding  in  accordance  with  the  par- 
tial premiss  from  which  they  were  derived ;  they  were  not  to 
be  stated  as  absolute  truths,  such  as  are  drawn  from  ascer- 
tained data,  like  the  truths  of  natural  philosophy.  It  was 
incorrect  to  deduce  conclusions  of  the  same  certainty  from  an 
incomprehensible  relationship,  which  would  be  drawn  from 
ordinary  and  known  ones,  and  to  argue  in  the  same  way  from 
a  mysterious  Divine  wrath,  as  if  it  were  the  same  affection 
with  which  we  are  cognisant  in  ourselves  and  in  common  life. 
The  doctrine  of  original  sin  ought  not  to  be  understated  or 
curtailed  because  it  leads  to  extreme  conclusions  on  one  side 
of  truth ;  and  Augustine,  who  is  not  deterred  by  such  results 
from  the  full  statement  of  it,  is,  so  far,  a  more  faithful  in- 
terpreter of  it  than  an  earlier  school.  But  those  who  draw 
out  this  doctrine  to  the  full,  and  do  not  balance  it  by  other 
truths,  give  it  force  at  the  expense  of  tenableness  and  justice. 


CHAP.  IV.]  OF   ORIGINAL   SIN.  133 

From  the  Augustinian  statements  relating  to  original  sin 
two  inferences  remain  to  be  drawn.  First,  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin  itself  was  a  sufficient  premiss  for  a  doctrine  of 
predestination.  The  latter  consigns  a  certain  portion  of 
mankind,  antecedently  to  actual  sin,  to  eternal  punishment ; 
but  if  antecedently  they  deserve  such  punishment,  the  con- 
signment to  it  is  a  natural  consequence  of  such  desert,  and 
is  no  injustice.  But,  secondly,  Augustine  says  more  than 
that  persons  under  the  guilt  of  original  sin  deserve  eternal 
punishment ;  for  he  asserts  that  they  are  punished  eternally. 
But  such  actual  punishment  is  more  than  a  premiss  for,  for 
it  is  itself  an  instance  of  predestination.  It  evidently  does 
not  depend  on  a  man's  conduct  in  what  part  of  the  world 
he  is  born,  whether  in  a  Christian  part  or  a  heathen ;  or 
in  what  state  as  an  infant  he  dies,  whether  with  baptism  or 
without  it.  These  are  arrangements  of  God's  providence 
entirely.  If  such  arrangements,  then,  involve  eternal 
punishment,  the  Divine  will  consigns  to  such  punishment 
antecedently  to  all  action — which  is  the  doctrine  of  predes- 
tination. A  true  predestination,  then,  is  seen  in  full  operation 
in  his  theology,  before  we  come  to  the  specific  doctrine ;  and 
we  have  substantially  at  an  earlier  stage  all  that  can  be  main- 
tained at  a  later. 


134 


CHAP.  V. 


AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE   OF   PREDESTINATION. 

FROM  S.  Augustine's  doctrine  of  original  sin,  I  proceed 
to  his  statements  on  the  subject  of  predestination.  S. 
Augustine,  then,  held  the  existence  of  an  eternal  Divine 
decree,  separating,  antecedently  to  any  difference  of  desert, 
one  portion  of  the  human  race  from  another;  and  ordaining 
one  to  everlasting  life  and  the  other  to  everlasting  misery. 
This  doctrine  occurs  frequently  in  many  of  his  treatises ; 
wholly  pervades  some,  and  forms  the  basis  of  his  whole 
teaching  in  the  latter  portion  of  his  theological  life,  It 
will  be  impossible,  therefore,  by  one  or  two  extracts  to  re- 
present duly  the  position  which  this  doctrine  has  in  his 
writings;  but  the  following  may  be  taken  as  samples  of 
a  general  language  on  this  subject.1 

"  Whoever,  therefore,  are  separated  by  Divine  grace  from 


1  The  dates  of  the  four  following 
extracts  are, — of  the  first  A.T>.  426,  of 
the  second,  A.D.  428,  of  the  third,  A.D. 
421,  of  the  fourth,  A.D.  417.  But  the 
Liber  ad  Simplicianum,  written  A.  D. 
394,  contains  substantially  the  same 
doctrine,  though  being  written  just  as 
he  was  crossing  the  boundary  line,  and 
passing  from  one  system  to  another,  it 
winds  about  so  and  alternates  and  os- 
cillates so  long  between  one  conclusion 
and  another,  that  it  is  with  some  diffi- 
culty that  we  ascertain  what  his  real 
conclusion  is.  He  ends,  however,  in 
adopting  the  strong  interpretation  of 
S.  Paul :  and  his  argument,  which  is  to 
reconcile  the  text,  "  Many  are  called 
but  few  chosen,"  with  an  effectual 
call  —  effectrix  vocatio  —  runs  thus : 
Is  it  that  they  are  called  and  that  the 
call  is  not  effectual,  because  they  do 
not  will  to  obey  it?  This  does  not 


agree  with  the  text,  "  Not  of  him  that 
willeth,"  &c. ;  for  the  contrary,  not 
of  God  that  giveth  mercy,  but  of  him 
that  willeth,  would  then  be  true  as 
well.  Is  it,  then,  because  God  calls 
some  in  a  way  which  He  knows  will 
be  effectual,  and  gives  this  call  to  some 
and  not  to  others?  So  that  of  the 
latter  it  might  be  said,  pofsent  olio  modo 
vocati  accommodate  fidei  voluntatem  ? 
He  decides  in  favour  of  this  interpre- 
tation, on  the  ground  that  it  agrees 
with  the  text,  "Not  of  him  that 
willeth,"  &c. ;  while  the  contrary  cannot 
be  said  of  it,  because  the  effectual  call 
thus  defined  depends  not  on  man's 
will  but  on  God's,  who  would  have 
given  it  to  others  besides  those  to 
whom  He  has  given  it,  if  He  had  pleased. 
Q'da  si  vellet  etiam  ipsorum  misereri, 
posset  ita  vocare,  quomodo  eis  aptum 
esset. 


CIIAP.   V.]  DOCTRINE    OF    PREDESTINATION.  135 

that  original  damnation,  we  doubt  not  but  that  there  is  pro- 
cured for  them  the  hearing  of  the  Gospel,  that  when  they 
hear  they  believe,  and  that  in  that  faith  which  worketh  by 
love  they  continue  unto  the  end;  that  even  if  they  go  astray 
they  are  corrected,  and,  being  corrected,  grow  better ;  or  that 
if  they  are  not  corrected  by  man,  they  still  return  into  the 
path  they  left,  some  being  taken  away  from  the  dangers  of 
this  life  by  a  speedy  death.  All  these  things  in  them  He 
worketh  whose  handiwork  they  are,  and  who  made  them 
vessels  of  mercy;  He  who  chose  them  in  His  Son  before  the 
foundation  of  the  world  according  to  the  election  of  grace  ; 
'and  if  of  grace,  then  no  more  of  works,  otherwise  grace  is 
no  more  grace,'  Of  such  the  Apostle  saith,  'We  know  that 
all  things  work  together  for  good  to  them  that  love  God,  who 
are  called  according  to  His  purpose.'  Of  them  none  perish 
because  all  are  elect;  and  they  are  elect  because  they  are 
called  according  to  the  purpose ;  and  that  purpose  not  their 
own,  but  God's;  of  which  he  elsewhere  saith,  '  That  the  pur- 
pose of  God  according  to  election  might  stand,  not  of  works 

but  of  Him  that  calleth.' If  any  of  these  perish,  God 

is  deceived,  but  none  doth  perish,  for  God  is  not  deceived.  If 
any  of  these  perish,  God  is  overcome  by  man's  corruption : 
but  none  doth  perish,  for  God  is  conquered  by  nothing.  They 
are  chosen  to  reign  with  Christ,  not  as  Judas  was  chosen,  of 
whom  our  Lord  said,  'Have  I  not  chosen  you  twelve,  and 
one  of  you  is  a  devil,'  but  chosen  in  mercy  as  He  was  in 
judgment,  chosen  to  obtain  the  kingdom  as  He  was  to  spill 

his  own   blood These  it   is    who    are   signified   to 

Timothy,  where,  after  saying  that  Hymenaeus  and  Philetus 
were  subverting  the  faith  of  some,  the  Apostle  adds, 
'Nevertheless,  the  foundation  of  God  standeth  sure,  having 

this  seal,  the  Lord  knoweth  them   that  are  His.' 

Their  faith,  which  worketh  by  love,  either  never  faileth, 
or,  if  it  does,  is  repaired  before  life  is  ended;  and,  all  inter- 
vening iniquity  blotted  out,  perseverance  unto  the  end  is 
imputed  to  them.  But  those  who  are  not  about  to  persevere 

E.    4 

\ 


136 


AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  V. 


are  not,  even  at  the  time  when  they  live  piously,  to  be 
reckoned  among  that  number ;  because  they  are  not 
separated  from  that  mass  of  perdition  by  the  Divine  fore- 
knowledge and  predestination;  and  therefore  are  not  called 
according  to  His  purpose,  and  therefore  not  chosen." — De 
Correptione  et  Gratia,  c.  vii. 

Again:  "Such  is  the  predestination  of  the  saints,  the  fore- 
knowledge that  is,  and  preparation  of  the  Divine  acts  of  grace, 
by  which  every  one  is  infallibly  saved  who  is  saved.  But  for 
the  rest,  where  are  they  but  in  that  mass  of  perdition  where 
the  Divine  justice  most  justly  leaves  them?  Where  the 
Tyrians  are,  and  the  Sidoiiians  are,  who  would  have  been 
able  to  believe  if  they  had  seen  the  miracles  of  Christ ;  but 
who,  inasmuch  as  faith  was  not  destined  for  them,  were 
denied  the  means  of  faith  as  well.  Whence  it  is  evident 
that  some  have  a  Divine  gift  of  intelligence  implanted  in 
their  natures,  designed  for  exciting  them  to  faith,  provided 
they  see  or  hear  preaching  or  miracles  which  appeal  to  that 
gift;  and  yet  being,  according  to  some  deeper  judgment  of 
Grod,  not  included  within  the  predestination  of  grace,  and 
separated  from  the  jnass  of  perdition  by  it,  have  not  those 
Divine  words  and  those  Divine  acts  brought  before  them, 
and  so  are  not  enabled  to  believe.1  The  Jews  who  would  not 
believe  our  Lord's  miracles  were  left  in  the  mass  of  per- 
dition, and  why  ?  The  Evangelist  tells  us.  (  That  the  saying 
of  Esaias  the  prophet  might  be  fulfilled  which  he  spake,  Lord, 
who  hath  believed  our  report,  and  to  whom  hath  the  arm  of 
the  Lord  been  revealed  ?  Therefore  they  could  not  believe, 
because  that  Esaias  said  again,  He  hath  blinded  their  eyes 
and  hardened  their  hearts,  that  they  should  not  see  with  their 


1  Ex  quo  apparet  habere  quosdam  in 
ipso  ingenio  divinum  naturaliter  munus 
intelligentia?,  quo  moveantur  ad  fidem, 
si  congrua  suis  mentibus  vel  audiant 
verba,  vel  signa  conspiciant :  et  tamen 
si  Dei  altiore  judicio,  a  perditionis 
massa  non  sunt  gratiae  praedestination* 


discreti,  nee  ipsa  eis  adhibentur  vel 
dicta  divina  vel  facta,  per  quse  possent 
credere,  si  audirent  utique  talia  vel  vide- 
rent.  In  eadem  perditiouis  massa 
relicti  sunt  etiam  Judsei  qui  non  potu- 
erunt  credere  factis  in  conspectu  suo 
tam  magnis  clarisque  virtutibus. 


CHAP.  V.] 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


137 


eyes  and  understand  with  their  hearts,  and  be  converted,  and 
I  should  heal  them.'  But  the  hearts  of  the  Tyrians  and 
Sidonians  were  not  thus  hardened,  for  they  would  have  be- 
lieved if  they  had  seen  such  miracles.  That  they  were  able 
to  believe,  however,  was  of  no  service  to  them,  when  they 
were  not  predestinated  by  Him  whose  judgments  are  un- 
searchable and  His  ways  past  finding  out;  any  more  than 
their  not  being  able  to  believe  would  have  been  of  disservice 
to  them  if  they  had  been  thus  predestinated  by  God  to  the 
illumination  of  their  blindness  and  the  taking  away  of  their 
heart  of  stone.1  With  respect  to  the  Tyrians  and  Sidonians, 
indeed,  there  may  be  possibly  some  other  interpretation  of  the 
passage;  but  that  no  one  comes  to  Christ  except  it  be  given 
him,  and  that  this  is  given  only  to  those  who  are  elected  in 
Him  before  the  foundation  of  the  world,  this  must  beyond 
all  question  be  admitted  by  every  one  whose  heart  is  not 
deaf  to,  while  his  ear  hears,  the  Divine  oracles."  — De  Dono 
Per  sever  antice,  c.  xiv. 

Again :  "  The  Lord  knows  those  that  are  His.  All  things 
work  together  for  good  for  those  alone  who  are  called  accord- 
ing to  His  purpose ;  the  called  according  to  His  purpose,  not 
the  called  simply,  not  the  many  called,  but  the  few  chosen. 
For  whom  He  did  foreknow  He  also  did  predestinate  to 
be  conformed  to  the  image  of  His  Son,  that  he  might  be 
the  firstborn  among  many  brethren;  and  whom  He  did 
predestinate  them  also  He  called;  and  whom  He  called 
them  also  He  justified ;  and  whom  He  justified  them 
He  also  glorified.  All  things  work  together  for  good 
to  those  who  were  chosen  before  the  foundation  of  the 
world  by  Him  who  calleth  those  things  which  be  not  as 
though  they  were ;  to  the  elect  according  to  the  election  of 
grace,  who  were  chosen  before  the  foundation  of  the  world 


1  Sod  nee  tills  profuit  quod  poterant 
credere,  quiu  praedestinati  non  sunt  ab 
eo  cujus  inscrutab'.lia  sunt  judicia,  et 
invcstigabilcs  viae;  ncc  istis  obfuisset 


quod  non  poterant  credere,  si  ita  prae- 
destinati essent,  ut  eos  CECCOS  Deus 
illuminaret,  et  induratis  cor  lapideum 
vellet  auferre. 


138  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  V. 

freely  and  not  on  account  of  any  good  works  fore- 
seen. Within  that  number  of  the  elect  and  the  predes- 
tinated, even  those  who  have  led  the  worst  lives  are  by 
the  goodness  of  God  led  to  repentance  ...  Of  these  our 
Lord  spoke  when  He  said,  '  This  is  the  Father's  will  which 
hath  sent  me,  that  of  all  He  hath  given  I  should  lose 
nothing.'  But  the  rest  of  mankind  who  are  not  of  this 
number,  but  who,  out  of  the  same  lump  of  which  they  are, 
are  made  vessels  of  wrath,  are  brought  into  the  world  for  the 
advantage  of  the  elect.  God  does  not  create  any  of  them 
indeed  without  a  purpose.  He  knows  what  good  to  work 
out  of  them :  He  works  good  in  the  very  fact  of  creating 
them  human  beings,  and  carrying  on  by  means  of  them 
this  visible  system  of  things.1  But  none  of  them  does  He 
lead  to  a  wholesome  and  spiritual  repentance.  All  indeed 
do,  as  far  as  themselves  are  concerned,  out  of  the  same 
original  mass  of  perdition  treasure  up  unto  themselves 
after  their  hardness  and  impenitent  heart,  wrath  against 
the  day  of  wrath ;  but  out  of  that  mass  God  leads  some 
in  mercy  to  repentance,  and  others  in  judgment  does  not 
lead." —  Contra  Julianum  Pelag.  1.  v.  n.  14. 

Again:  "There  is  a  certain  defined  number  of  saints 
in  God's  foreknowledge  (Dei  prascientia  definitus  numerus 
sanctorum)  who  love  God  because  God  hath  given  them 
His  Holy  Spirit  shed  abroad  in  their  hearts,  and  to  whom 
all  things  work  together  for  good ;  who  are  called  according 

to  His  purpose There  are  others,  too,   called,  but 

not  chosen;  and,  therefore,  not  called  according  to  His 
purpose.  The  former  are  the  children  of  promise,  the 
elect,  who  are  saved  according  to  the  election  of  grace, 
as  it  is  written,  f  But  if  of  grace,  then  no  more  of  works, 


1  Caeteri  autem  mortales  qui  ex  isto  |    operetur   ignorat ;    cum    et    hoc  ipso 

numero  non  sunt,  et  ex  eadem  quidera  bonum  operetur,  quod  in  eis  humanam 

ex  qua  et  isti,  sed  vasa  irae  facta  sunt,  creat  naturam,  et  ex  eis  ordinem  prse- 

ad  utilitatem  nascuntur  istorum.     Non  sentis   saeculi    exornat     Istorum    ne- 

enim  quenquam  eorum  Deus  temere  ac  minem  adducit  ad  paenitentiam  salu- 

fortuito  creat,  aut   quid .  de  illis   boni  I    brem  et  spiritualem. 


CHAP.  V.J 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


139 


otherwise  grace  is  no  more  grace.'  These  are  the  vessels 
of  mercy,  in  whom  God  even  by  means  of  the  vessels  of 
wrath  makes  known  the  riches  of  His  glory  ....  But 
the  rest  of  mankind — who  do  not  pertain  to  this  society, 
but  whose  soul  and  body,  nevertheless,  God  hath  made, 
together  with  whatever  also  belongs  to  their  nature  apart 
from  its  corruption  —  are  created  by  a  fore-knowing  God 
on  this  account,  that  by  them  He  may  show  how  little 
the  freewill  of  fallen  man  can  do  without  His  grace  ;  and 
that  by  their  just  and  due  punishment  the  vessels  of  mercy, 
who  are  separated  from  the  original  mass  not  by  their 
own  works,  but  by  the  free  grace  of  God,  may  know  how 
great  a  gift  has  been  bestowed  upon  them,  that  every  mouth 
may  be  stopped,  and  that  he  that  glorieth  may  glory  in  the 
Lord."  1— Epist.  186.  c.  vii. 

The  general  conclusion  to  which  these  passages  point, 
is  that  S,  Augustine  held  the  predestinarian  doctrine;  viz. 
that  God  by  an  eternal  decree  prior  to  any  difference  of 
desert,  separated  one  portion  of  mankind  from  another,  ordain- 
ing one  to  eternal  life  and  the  other  to  eternal  punish- 
ment.2 But  it  will  be  proper  to  enter  into  some  distinctions 
which  are  drawn  on  this  subject  in  order  to  separate  S. 
Augustine's  doctrine  from  another  and  a  different  doctrine 
of  predestination. 

A  certain  limited  and  qualified  doctrine  of  predestination 
is  held  by  some  schools  of  divines  opposed  to  the  predestin- 
arians,  who  maintain  the  doctrine  to  be  a  sound  and  scrip- 
tural one;  but  maintain  the  predestination  to  be  first  to  priv- 
ileges and  means  of  grace,  not  to  final  happiness ;  or,  secondly, 
if  to  final  happiness,  to  be  a  predestination  in  consequence  of 
foreseen  virtue  and  holiness  in  the  individuals  predestinated. 


1  Ut  in  his  ostenderet  liberum  arbi- 
trium  sine  sua  gratia  quid  valerct ;  ut 
in  eorum  justis  et  debitis  pcenis  vasa 
misericordiae,  quae  non  suorum  meritis, 
sed  gratuita  Dei  gratia  sunt  ab  ilia  con- 


crctione   discreta,    quid   sibi    collatum 
esset  addiscerent. 

2  See  Hooker's  Statements  of  S.  Au- 
gustine's Doctrine.     NOTE  XIX. 


140  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  V. 

A  third  modification,  which  rests  upon  a  distinction  between 
individuals  and  the  body,  and  allowing  predestination  to  be 
to  final  glory,  applies  it  to  the  Church  as  a  whole,  and  not  to 
individuals,  is  evidently  only  the  second  in  another  form.  For, 
as  no  one  can  mean  to  say  that  the  whole  of  the  visible  Church 
is  predestinated  to  eternal  glory,  by  the  Church  as  a  body 
must  be  meant  the  truly  virtupus  and  pious  members  of  the 
Church  whom  God  predestinates  to  glory  in  consequence  of 
foreseeing  this  piety  and  virtue  in  them.  Now,  had  S.  Augus- 
tine only  held  predestination  in  this  sense,  that  God  determined 
from  all  eternity  to  admit  a  certain  portion  of  mankind  to  cer- 
tain religious  privileges  and  to  reward  the  pious  and  vir- 
tuous with  eternal  glory,  he  would  only  have  held  what  no 
Christian,  or  even  believer  in  natural  religion  can  deny. 
It  is  evident  that  God  has  admitted  a  certain  portion  of 
mankind  to  certain  religious  privileges  to  which  He  has  not 
admitted  others ;  and,  as  He  has  done  this,  it  is  certain  that 
He  has  eternally  decreed  to  do  it.  And  it  is  certain  that 
God  will  finally  reward  men  according  to  their  works; 
and,  as  this  will  be  His  act,  and  this  the  reason  of  it, 
it  is  certain  He  has  eternally  decreed  the  one  and  foreseen 
the  other.  Such  a  doctrine  of  predestination  as  this,  then, 
is  no  more  than  what  everybody  must  hold.  But  the 
passages  which  have  been  quoted  contain  very  clearly  a 
different  doctrine  of  predestination  from  this.  And  this 
difference  will  appear  the  more  decisively,  the  more  we 
enter  into  the  particulars  of  S.  Augustine's  view. 

In  the  first  place,  we  find  S.  Augustine  always  speaking 
of  predestination  as  a  mystery,  a  dark  and  perplexing  doc- 
trine, contradictory  to  our  natural  ideas  of  the  Divine 
justice,  and  requiring  the  profoundest  submission  of  human 
reason  in  order  to  its  acceptance.  For  example,  he  says,  in 
the  text  (John  vi.  45.) :  "  Every  one  that  hath  heard  and 
hath  learned  of  the  Father  cometh  unto  me." 

ff  Very  far  removed  from  our  fleshly  senses  is  that  school  in 
which  God  is  heard  and  teaches — valde  remota  cst  a  scnsilus 


CHAP.  V.] 


OF   PREDESTINATION. 


141 


carnis  hcec  schola  in  qua  Pater  auditur  et  docet.  We  see  many 
come  to  the  Son,  because  we  see  many  believe  in  Christ :  but 
where  and  how  they  heard  and  learned  this  of  the  Father 
we  see  not.  Too  secret  is  that  grace ;  but  that  it  is  grace 
who  can  doubt  ?  This  grace  thus  secretly  imparted  is  re- 
jected by  no  heart,  however  hard.1  Indeed,  it  is  given  for  that 
purpose,  'viz.  that  this  hardness  of  heart  may  be  removed. 
When  the  Father  is  heard,  and  teaches  the  man  within  to 
come  to  the  Son,  He  takes  away  the  stony  heart  and  gives  the 
heart  of  flesh,  thus  making  sons  of  promise  and  vessels  of 
mercy  prepared  for  glory.  But  why  does  He  not  teach  all 
to  come  to  Christ?  Because  those  whom  He  teaches  He 
teaches  in  mercy,  and  those  whom  He  teaches  not  He  teaches 
not  in  judgment.  *  For  He  hath  mercy  on  whom  He  will 

have  mercy,  and  whom  He  will  He  hardeneth.' 

And  to  him  who  objects  why  doth  He  yet  complain, 
for  who  hath  resisted  His  will  ?  the  Apostle  answers,  not  by 
denying  the  objection,  but  urging  submission  under  it :  O 
man,  who  art  thou  that  repliest  against  God  ?  "  2 

Again :  "  Why,  when  both  alike  hear,  and,  supposing  a 
miracle,  both  alike  see,  one  believes  and  another  does  not 
believe,  lies  in  the  abyss  of  the  riches  of  the  wisdom  and 
knowledge  of  God,  whose  judgments  are  unsearchable,  and 
who,  without  iniquity,  has  mercy  upon  whom  He  will  have 
mercy,  and  whom  He  will,  hardeneth.  For  His  decrees  are 
not  unjust,  because  they  are  incomprehensible."3 

Again  :  "  It  displeases  him  (the  objector  in  Rom.  c.  ix.) 
that  God  complains  of  sinners  whom,  as  it  appears  to  him, 
He  hardens.  But  God  does  not  harden  sinners  by  obliging 
them  to  sin,  but  by  withholding  grace,  such  grace  being 
withheld  from  those  from  whom  it  is  withheld,  according 


1  Niinium  gratia  ista  secreta  est, 
gratiam  vero  esse  quis  ambigat  ?  Haec 
itaque  gratia,  qua;  occulte  humanis 


cordibus   divina  largitate  tribuitur,   a 
nullo  duro  cordc  respuitur. 

2  De  Pra?d.  Sanct.  c.  viii. 

3  Epist.  194.  c.  iii. 


142  AUGUST JNI AN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  V. 

to  an  occult  justice,  infinitely  removed  from  human  percep- 
tions."1 

Again :  te  Why  He  wills  to  convert  some,  and  to  punish 
others  for  being  unconverted  (quare  illos  velit  convertere, 
illos  vero  pro  aversions  punire),  let  none  presume  to  ask  as 

if  to  blame  God for  the  law  of  His  secret  justice 

rests  with  Him  alone  (consilium  occultioris  justifies  penes 
ipsum  esf)"  2 

S.  Augustine,  then,  regarded  predestination  as  a  perplex- 
ing mystery, — a  doctrine  which  disagreed  with  our  natural 
ideas  of  God's  justice,  and  which  could  only  be  defended  by 
a  reference  to  His  inscrutable  and  sovereign  will. 

I  will  single  out  the  term  "hidden  justice — occnltajustitia" 
as  expressing  in  a  summary  and  convenient  form  this  charac- 
teristic of  the  doctrine  held  by  him.  S.  Augustine  asserts, 
as  every  one  who  believes  in  the  existence  of  a  God  must 
do,  that  God  is  just,  and  therefore  that  the  decree  of  pre- 
destination and  reprobation  which  He  has  from  all  eternity 
made  is  just ;  but  he  adds,  that  this  justice  is  of  a  nature  not 
addressed  to  our  natural  faculties  and  perceptions,  or  dis- 
cernible by  them.  Natural  justice  —  the  rule  of  rewarding 
and  punishing  according  to  desert  — is  justice,  and  is  also  a 
justice  cognisable  by  our  natural  faculties ;  predestinating 
justice  is  as  real  justice  as  natural,  but  is  not  thus  cognisable. 
The  one  is  justice  and  also  apparent  justice ;  the  other  is 
justice,  but  not  apparent  justice  —  i.  e.  apparent  ^justice. 

But  such  language  as  this  is  very  inapplicable  to  a  doc- 
trine of  predestination,  which  is  no  more  than  the  assertion 
that  God  has  determined  from  all  eternity  to  admit  some 
portions  of  mankind  and  not  others  to  certain  privileges  and 
means  of  grace ;  or,  that  God  has  determined  to  reward  or 
punish  those  respectively  who  He  sees  will  be  virtuous  or 
vicious.  There  is  nothing  mysterious  in  the  doctrine  of  pre- 


1  De  Div.  Qusest.  ad  Simplic.   1.  i.    I        *  De.  Pecc.    Merit,  et  Rem.  1.  2.  c. 
Q.  2.  n.  16.  |    xviii. 


CHAP.  V.]  OF   PREDESTINATION.  143 

destination  as  thug  explained,  nothing  from  which  natural 
feeling  or  reason  shrinks,  nothing  which  requires  any  deep 
submission  of  the  intellect  to  accept.  That  God  should 
reward  the  virtuous  and  punish  the  wicked  is  the  simple 
rule  of  justice,  and  that  He  should  give  privileges  to  some 
which  He  does  not  give  to  others,  is  no  injustice. 

It  may  be  said,  indeed,  that  the  admission  of  one  portion 
of  mankind  to  peculiar  religious  privileges  and  advantages 
not  enjoyed  by  the  rest  is  a  mystery  ;  that  there  is  something 
inexplicable  in  that  great  inequality  of  God's  administration 
in  this  respect  which  we  see  in  the  world,  especially  the  re- 
markable one  of  one  part  of  the  world  only  having  been 
admitted  into  the  Christian  Church,  while  far  the  larger 
part  has  been  left  in  pagan  darkness  and  ignorance :  but  it 
cannot  be  said,  that  this  is  a  mystery  in  the  sense  of  being  a 
scandal  or  offence  to  our  reason.  It  is  a  mystery,  in  the  first 
place,  as  being  a  fact  which  we  are  obliged  to  refer  simply 
to  the  Divine  will  and  pleasure ;  but  in  this  sense  many  of 
the  commonest  events  which  take  place  in  the  world  are 
mysteries.  It  is  one  thing  to  be  uninformed,  and  another  to 
be  scandalised  ;  one  thing  not  to  have  curiosity  satisfied,  and 
another  to  have  reason  perplexed.  It  is  a  mystery  also  in  a 
sense  somewhat  stronger  than  this ;  for,  without  imposing  as 
obligatory,  our  moral  nature  yet  favours  the  rule  of  equal 
dealing,  and  its  bias  is  in  that  direction  ;  so  that  exceptions 
to  it  are  not  in  themselves  acceptable  to  us.  But  neither  in 
this  sense  is  it  a  difficulty  or  scandal ;  being  only  the  violation 
of  a  rule  which  is  not  obligatory.  Indeed,  this  bias  of  our 
minds  is  one  which  easily  submits,  on  the  first  due  considera- 
tion, that  there  may  be  good  reasons  for  the  inequality  we 
see  in  the  Divine  dispensing  of  religious  privileges.  And, 
on  the  whole,  provided  the  great  rule  of  justice  be  kept 
to,  that  men  are  rewarded  and  punished  according  to  their 
use  of  the  means  given  them,  the  general  sense  of  mankind 
allows  the  Almighty  the  right  to  apportion  the  means  them- 
selves as  He  thinks  fit,  and  give  some  higher,  and  some  lower, 


144 


AUCUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  V. 


without  making  any  difficulty  of  the  matter.  Particular 
persons,  indeed,  have  embraced  so  rigid  and  importunate  an 
idea  of  justice,  that  they  have  not  been  able  so  to  satisfy  them- 
selves, but  have  insisted  on  an  absolute  equality  of  spiritual 
condition  for  all.  And  truly  the  idea  of  justice,  like  other 
ideas,  may  be  unduly  nourished;  and  persons,  by  brooding 
narrowly  upon  it,  may  get  themselves  to  regard  many  things 
as  grievances,  both  in  human  society  and  the  system  of  Provi- 
dence, which  they  would  not  otherwise  have  done.  But  such 
an  idea  of  justice  is  not  supported  by  the  general  feeling  of 
mankind,  which  has  adopted  a  larger  and  more  liberal  one. 

Inequality,  then,  in  the  dispensing  of  religious  privileges, 
is  not  a  difficulty  to  reason  or  contrary  to  justice  ;  but  S. 
Augustine  speaks  of  predestination  as  a  difficulty,  and  contrary 
to  our  instinctive  ideas  of  justice ;  and  therefore  must  have 
included  something  more  than  this  kind  of  inequality  in  his 
idea  of  what  predestination  was. 

Indeed,  the  very  circumstances  of  the  argument  which  S. 
Augustine  is  carrying  on,  if  any  one  will  consider  them,  will 
be  found  to  involve  something  more  than  this  as  his  meaning 
of  predestination  ;  for,  had  he  meant  no  more  than  this,  there 
would  have  been  no  occasion  for  this  defence  of  the  doctrine 
at  all,  In  arguing  with  an  infidel  he  might  have  had  to 
answer  the  objection  of  these  inequalities  in  the  Divine  dis- 
pensation ;  but  he  is  defending  the  doctrine  of  predestination 
not  against  an  infidel,  but  against  a  Christian  objector — i.  e. 
an  objector  who  at  the  very  outset  admits  such  inequalities, 
and  therefore  would  not  object  to,  or  c;ill  out  a  defence  of 
that  doctrine,  on  that  ground.  Indeed,  S.  Augustine's  oppo- 
nent is  not  only  a  Christian,  but  sometimes  even  a  Catholic 
Christian,  he  having  to  defend  this  doctrine  not  only  against 
Pelagians  but  against  opponents  within  the  Church.1  But  it 


1  The  Church  of  Marseilles,  which, 
through  Prosper  and  Hilary,  protested 
against  the  doctrine  of  the  book  De 


Correptione  et  Gratia,  and  were  an- 
swered by  the  book  De  Prcedestinatione 
Sanctorum. 


CHAP.  V.]  OF    PREDESTINATION.  145 

is  absurd  to  suppose  such  an  opponent  taking,  against  a 
particular  doctrine,  a  ground  only  suitable  to  an  infidel 
arguing  against  revelation  altogether,  just  as  it  would  be 
absurd,  on  the  other  hand,  to  suppose  S.  Augustine  not 
giving  the  ready  and  obvious  answer  to  such  an  objection  if 
brought.  He  answers  his  opponent  by  referring  him  to  God's 
secret  and  inscrutable  will ;  but  had  mere  inequality  been  his 
opponent's  ground  of  objection,  he  would  have  answered  him 
much  more  decisively  by  referring  him  to  the  broad  and 
evident  fact  of  the  inequality  in  the  Divine  dispensing  of 
means  of  grace  involved  in  the  very  existence  of  Christianity, 
not  to  say  in  the  very  order  of  God's  natural  providence. 

But  the  general  admission  of  mystery,  darkness,  and 
apparent  contrariety  to  justice  which  S.  Augustine  makes 
with  respect  to  predestination,  is  only  a  preliminary,  however 
decisive  an  answer,  to  such  an  interpretation  of  his  doctrine 
as  would  reduce  it  to  the  qualified  doctrine  of  predestination 
above  referred  to.  The  qualified  doctrine  drew  distinctions, 
according  as  it  wanted  them,  between  individuals  and  the 
body  as  the  subjects  of  predestination,  between  the  means  of 
grace  and  final  happiness  as  the  gift  in  it,  and  between 
foreseen  merits  and  arbitrary  choice  as  the  reason  and 
ground  of  it.  But  none  of  these  distinctions  appear  in  the 
Augustinian  statements  of  the  doctrine,  which  quite  plainly 
and  simultaneously  assign  to  predestination  individuals  as  its 
subjects,  final  glory  as  its  gift,  and  a  sovereign  and  inscrutable 
choice  on  the  part  of  God,  as  distinguished  from  foreseen 
merits  in  the  predestinated  person,  as  its  reason  and  ground. 

He  applies,  in  the  first  place,  predestination  to  individuals, 
speaking  of  the  subjects  of  it  as  "  these"  and  "  those  "  (illi, 
isti\  and  "  many  "  (multi,  plurimi).  The  question  put  by  the 
objector  to  the  doctrine,  and  met  by  him  with  the  answer 
of  God's  inscrutable  will,  is,  "  Why  God  liberates  this  man 
rather  than  that —  cur  istum  potius  quam  ilium  liberet"  l 


1  Pracd.  Sanct.  c.  viii. 
L, 


146  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  V. 

And  the  predestinated  are  considered  as  amounting  to  a 
certain  definite  number  of  persons.  "  I  speak,"  he  says,  "  of 
those  who  are  predestinated  to  the  kingdom  of  God,  of 
whom  the  number  is  so  certain  that  no  one  can  be  added  to 
them  or  taken  from  them. "  l 

It  is  evident,  in  the  next  place,  that  S.  Augustine  is 
speaking  of  the  predestination  of  these  individuals  to  final 
glory,  and  not  to  means  of  grace  only  ;  asserting,  as  he  does, 
that  by  predestination  "  every  one  is  infallibly  saved  who 
is  saved  —  certissime  liberantur  quicumque  liberantur?  and 
that  "of  the  elect  none  perish2,"  and  everywhere  speaking 
of  predestination  as  predestination  to  eternal  life. 

It  is  equally  evident  that  he  does  not  mean  that  these 
individuals  are  predestinated  to  eternal  life  on  account  of 
foreseen  goodness  in  them.  This  was  the  ground  on  which 
predestination  was  placed  by  some  maintainers  of  a  quali- 
fied doctrine  on  this  subject  in  S.  Augustine's  time ;  but  it 
met  not  with  his  agreement  but  strong  condemnation ;  and 
those  who  held  it  are  argued  with  as  opponents  not  so 
far  gone  as  the  Pelagians,  but  still  labouring  under  formid- 
able error.  The  distinction  of  foreseen  merits  was  a 
regular  and  known  distinction  in  the  controversy  on  this 
question  at  that  day,  and  was  thus  disposed  of.  Thus,  com- 
menting on  the  text,  "  Ye  have  not  chosen  Me,  but  I  have 
chosen  you  "  (John  xv.  16.),  he  says,  "  This,  then,  is  the  im- 
moveable  truth  of  predestination.  The  Apostle  says,  (  He 
hath  elected  us  in  Him  before  the  foundation  of  the  world.' 
If  this  is  interpreted,  then,  to  mean  that  God  elects  men 
because  He  foresees  they  will  believe,  and  not  because  He 
is  about  to  make  them  believing,  against  such  a  fore- 
knowledge as  this  the  Son  speaks,  saying,  '  Ye  have  not 
chosen  Me,  but  I  have  chosen  you,'  for  upon  this  interpre- 
tation God  would  rather  have  foreseen  that  they  would 
choose  Him,  and  so  deserve  to  be  chosen  by  Him.  They  are 


1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xiii.  I  2  pe  j)ono  pers  c 


CHAP.  V.]  OF   PREDESTINATION.  147 

chosen  therefore  before  the  foundation  of  the  world  by  that 
predestination  by  which  God  foresees  his  own  future  work ; 
and  they  are  chosen  out  of  the  world  by  that  calling  by 
which  God  fulfils  what  He  predestines."  l 

Again,  on  the  text  (Eph.  i.  4.)  "According  as  He  hath 
chosen  us  in  Him  before  the  foundation  of  the  world,  that 
we  should  be  holy  and  without  blame  before  Him  in  love." 
"  f  He  foreknew,'  says  the  Pelagian,  s  who  were  about  to  be 
holy  and  without  blame  by  the  exercise  of  their  freewill, 
and  therefore  chose  them  before  the  foundation  of  the 
world  in  His  foreknowledge,  because  He  foreknew  that 
they  would  be  such.'  But  the  Apostle  says,  'Chose  not 
because  we  were,  but  that  we  might  be  holy  and  without 
blame.'  They  were  to  be  such,  then,  because  He  elected 
them  and  predestinated  them  to  be  such  by  His  grace."  2 

The  text,  again  (Rom.  ix.  11.),  respecting  Jacob  and  Esau, 
"For  the  children  being  not  yet  born,  neither  having  done 
any  good  or  evil,  that  the  purpose  of  God  according  to 
election  might  stand,  not  of  works  but  of  Him  that  calleth," 
is  strongly  insisted  upon  as  obviously,  and  at  first  sight 
disproving  the  conditional  ground  attributed  by  some  to 
predestination;  and  the  explanation  by  which  this  natural 
inference  from  the  passage  is  met,  viz.  —  that  the  election 
of  Jacob  in  preference  to  Esau,  though  not  caused  by  any 
difference  of  conduct  between  them  at  the  time,  inasmuch  as 
they  were  not  yet  born,  was  yet  caused  by  the  difference 
which  was  to  be  and  which  God  foresaw,  is  rejected,  as 
depending  on  a  distinction  wholly  irrelevant;  it  making 
no  difference  to  works  as  a  cause  of  election,  whether  they 
operate  thus  as  present  or  as  foreseen  works.  "Jacob  was 
not  loved  because  he  was  of  such  a  character,  or  because  he 


1  De  Trad.  Sanct.  c.  xvii.— Quod 
profecto  si  propterea  dictum  est  quia 
prcEscivit  Deus  creditnros  esse  .... 
Electi  sunt  autem  ante  mundi  consti- 
tutionem  ea  praedestinationein  qua  Deus 

L    2 


sua  futura  facta  praescivit :  electi  sunt 
autem  de   mundo   ea    vocatione,    qua 
Deus  id,  quod  prasdestinavit,  implevit. 
2  De  Pra?d.  Sanct.  c.  xviii. 


148  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  V. 

was  to  be;  but  he  was  made  of  such  a  character  because 
he  was  loved —  non  ideo  quia  tails  erat}  vel  talis  futurus 
erat  dilectum,  sed  talem,  quia  dilectus  est,  factum.  The 
Apostle  does  not  lie.  Jacob  was  not  loved  on  account  of 
works,  for  if  of  works,  then  no  more  of  grace  ;  but  he  was 
loved  on  account  of  grace,  which  grace  made  him  to  abound 
in  works."1 — Uf  It  is  not  of -him  that  willeth,  or  of  him 
that  runneth,  but  of  God  that  showeth  mercy  ? '  God 
had  not  mercy  on  Jacob,  therefore,  because  Jacob  willed 
and  ran;  but  Jacob  willed  and  ran  because  God  had  mercy. 
For  the  will  is  prepared  by  the  Lord."  2 — "  '  Jacob  have  I 
loved,  but  Esau  have  I  hated.'  The  Apostle  speaks  of  an 
election,  where  God  does  not  find  something  done  by  another 
for  Him  to  choose,  but  something  to  choose  which  He  Himself 
does  —  '  ubi  Deus  non  ab  alto  factum  quod  eligat  invenit,  sed 
quod  inveniat  ipsefacitS  As  he  says  of  the  remnant  of  Israel, 
f  There  is  a  remnant  according  to  the  election  of  grace;  and 
if  by  grace,  then  is  it  no  more  of  works,  otherwise  grace  is 
no  more  grace.' 3  Wherefore  ye  are  foolish  who,  when  the 
truth  says,  *  Not  of  works,  but  of  Him  that  calleth,'  say,  on 
account  of  future  works  which  God  foresaw  that  Jacob 
would  do,  and  therefore  loved  him;  contradicting  the 
Apostle's  own  words.  As  if  the  Apostle  would  not  have 
said,  not  on  account  of  present,  but  of  future  works,  if  he 
had  meant  this — (  quasi  non  posset  dicere,  non  ex  prasentibus 
sed  ex  futuris  operibus.'*  "  4 

The  ground  of  foreseen  merits  is  thus  expressly  rejected 
by  S.  Augustine  as  the  ground  of  predestination,  which  is  re- 
ferred, instead,  to  an  absolute  and  inscrutable  Divine  choice. 
Though  one  distinction  must  be  here  made.  The  most  rigid 
predestinarian  must  in  one  sense  allow  that  God  predesti- 
nates the  elect  to  eternal  life  in  consequence  of  goodness  fore- 
seen in  them.  For,  however  absolutely  God  may  predestinate 


1  Op.  Imp.,  Contra  Jul.  1.  1.  c.  133.    I        3  Rom.  xi.  5,  6. 

2  Ibid.  c.  141.  4  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  Tel.  1.  2.  n.  15. 


CHAP.  V.]  OF   PREDESTINATION.  149 

particular  persons  to  eternal  life  in  the  sense  of  certainty, 
He  plainly  does  not  do  it  absolutely  in  the  sense  of  re- 
quiring no  qualifications.  His  predetermination,  then,  to 
give  them  eternal  life  must  suppose  the  foresight  of  these 
qualifications  for  it  in  them,  though  it  is  the  foresight  of 
qualifications  which  He  Himself  has  determined  to  give  them 
by  the  operation  of  efficacious  grace.  "  God  foresees  His  own 
future  work."  He  has  decreed  from  all  eternity  to  make,  and 
therefore  foresees  that  He  will  make,  Jacob  of  such  a  cha- 
racter. But  this  is  predestination  in  consequence  of  foreseen 
goodness,  in  quite  a  different  sense  from  that  which  is 
intended  in  the  modification  of  the  doctrine  above  referred 
to.  The  effect  of  that  modification  is  to  make  the  whole  of 
predestination  conditional,  —  God  predestinating  persons  to 
eternal  life  in  consequence  of  something  which  by  virtue  of 
the  Divine  attribute  of  foreknowledge  He  certainly  fore- 
sees, but  which  is  in  itself  contingent,  depending  on  the 
will  and  efforts  of  the  persons  themselves.  But  of  the  dis- 
tinction now  spoken  of  this  is  not  the  effect.  For  though, 
according  to  it,  God  predestinates  the  elect  to  their  final 
reward  relatively  to  their  qualifications  for  it,  He  predesti- 
nates them  absolutely  to  those  qualifications ;  so  that,  though 
one  part  of  predestination  is  dependent  upon  another,  the 
whole  is  unconditional.1 

It  is  indeed  observable  that,  when  S.  Augustine  is  charged 
by  the  Pelagians  with  fatalism,  he  does  not  disown  the 
certainty  and  necessity,  but  only  the  popular  superstitions 
and  impieties  of  that  system.  He  rejects  the  appeal  to 
the  stars  as  absurd,  and  distinguishes  between  the  operation 
of  fate  which  is  for  good  and  evil  alike,  and  that  of 
Divine  grace  which  is  for  good  only  ;  sin  and  its  punishment 


1  "  Effectum  prsedestinationis  con- 
siderare  possumus  duplicitcr:  unomodo 
in  particular!,  et  sic  nihil  prohibet 
aliquem  effectum  praedestinationis  esse 
causum  altcrius.  .  .  .  Alio  modo  in 


communi ;  et  sic  impossibile  est  quod 
totus  praidestinationis  effectus  in  com- 
muni habeut  aliquam  causam  ex  parte 
nostra." — Sum.  Theol.  P,  1.  Quaest. 
23.  Art.  5. 


L    3 


150 


AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  V. 


being  referable  wholly  to  man.  But  lie  does  not  disown 
a  Divine  predestination,  upon  which  the  future  happiness 
and  misery  of  mankind  depend.1 

Such  being  S.  Augustine's  doctrine  of  predestination, 
the  ground  on  which  the  justice  of  such  a  doctrine  is 
defended  has  already  appeared  in  so  many  of  the  extracts 
given,  that  it  is  hardly  necessary  to  recur  to  it.  Had 
mankind  continued  in  the  state  in  which  they  were  ori- 
ginally created,  the  consignment  of  any  portion  of  them 
antecedently  to  all  action  to  eternal  punishment,  would 
have  been  unjust.  But  all  mankind  having  fallen  from 
that  state  by  their  sin  in  Adam,  and  become  one  guilty 
mass,  eternal  punishment  is  antecedently  due  to  all;  and 
therefore  none  have  any  right  to  complain  if  they  are 
consigned,  antecedently  to  it;  while  those  who  are  spared 
should  thank  God's  gratuitous  mercy. 

To  this  mass  of  perdition,  this  apostate  root,  we  are  referred 
for  the  defence  of  the  justice  of  predestination.  "  Those  who 
are  not  freed  by  grace,  whether  they  have  not  had  the  oppor- 
tunity of  hearing,  or  whether  they  have  heard  and  refused  to 
obey,  or  whether  they  have  not  lived  to  be  old  enough  to  hear, 
but  died  before  receiving  the  washing  of  regeneration  to 
save  them,  are  all  justly  condemned ;  inasmuch  as  they  are 
none  of  them  without  sin,  original  or  actual.  For  all  have 
sinned,  either  in  Adam  or  in  themselves,  and  come  short  of  the 
glory  of  God.  The  whole  mass,  therefore,  deserves  punish- 
ment ;  and  were  this  punishment  inflicted  upon  all,  it  would 
be  inflicted  beyond  all  doubt  justly." 2 — "  It  is  unjust,  say  they, 
that  when  both  are  in  one  and  the  same  evil  case,  this  man 
should  be  liberated  and  that  man  punished.  But  it  were 
just  that  both  should  be  punished.  Who  can  deny  this  ?  Let 


1  "  Fatum  qui  affirmant  de  siderum 
positione,  ad  tempus  quo  concipitur 
quisque  vel  nascitur,  actus  et  eventa 
pendere  contendunt:  Dei  vero  gratia 
omnia  sidera  progreditur.  .  .  .  Deinde 


fati     assertores     ct     bona      et     mala 
hominum     fato     tribuunt."  —  Contra 
Duas,  Ep.  1.  2.  n.  12. 
2  De  Nat.  et  Grat.  c.  iv. 


CHAP.  V.]  OF   PREDESTINATION.  151 

us  give  thanks,  then,  to  the  Saviour,  for  that  He  does  not 
repay  to  us  what,  by  the  damnation  of  others  like  us,  we 
know  to  be  our  due.  Were  every  man  liberated,  it  would 
not  be  seen  what  sin  deserved ;  were  no  man,  what  grace 
could  bestow  ....  But  the  whole  lump  deserving  condemna- 
tion, justice  repays  the  due  shame,  grace  bestows  the  un- 
merited honour."  l  — "  Forasmuch  as  that  one  man  in  whom 
all  have  sinned  is  also  in  each  individual  punished." 2— 
"  Grace  alone  separates  the  redeemed  from  the  lost,  alone 
divides  those  whom  a  common  original  sin  formed  into 
one  mass  of  perdition  .  .  .  The  whole  human  mass  was 
so  justly  condemned  in  the  apostate  root,  that,  were  none 
rescued  from  that  damnation,  none  could  blame  God's  justice. 
Those  who  are  rescued  are  rescued  gratuitously  ;  those  who 
are  not,  only  show  what  the  whole  lump  deserved,  even  the 
rescued  themselves,  had  not  undeserved  mercy  succoured 
them."3 — "Divine  Scripture  calleth  those  in  excusable  whom 
it  convicts  of  sinning  knowingly.  But  neither  does  the  just 
judgment  of  God  spare  them  who  have  not  heard  :  *  for  as 
many  as  have  sinned  without  law  shall  also  perish  without 
law.'  And  however  they  may  appear  to  excuse  themselves, 
He  admits  not  this  excuse  who  knows  that  He  at  first 
made  man  upright,  and  gave  him  the  commandment  to 
obey ;  and  that  sin  has  not  passed  to  his  posterity  but  by 
his  misuse  of  freewill.  Men  are  not  condemned  without 
having  sinned,  inasmuch  as  sin  hath  passed  to  all  from 
one,  in  whom,  previous  to  their  separate  individual  sins, 
all  have  sinned  in  common.  And  on  this  account  every 
sinner  is  inexcusable,  either  by  the  guilt  of  his  origin  or 
the  addition  of  his  own  will,  whether  he  knows  or  whether 
he  is  ignorant ;  for  ignorance  itself  is  sin  beyond  question 
in  those  who  are  unwilling  to  learn,  and  in  those  who  are 
not  able  is  the  punishment  of  sin.  So  that  of  both  the 
excuse  is  unjust,  the  damnation  just What  did 


Ep.  194.  c.  2.  |          2  Ep.  186.  c.  4.         |      8  Enchiridion,  c.  99. 

L   4 


152 


AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  V. 


He  love  in  Jacob  but  the  freegift  of  His  own  mercy,  what 
did  He  hate  in  Esau  but  original  sin  ?  "  l 

One  peculiar  argument  for  predestination  drawn  from  the 
Incarnation  should  be  added  to  the  general  body  of  state- 
ment which  we  meet  with  in  St.  Augustine  on  this  subject  — 
an  argument  which  is  remarkable  as  showing  how  intimately 
the  doctrine  of  predestination  is  connected  with  the  funda- 
mental truths  of  Christianity.  Original  sin  is  its  main 
basis;  but  an  oblique  proof  of  it  is  here  drawn  from  the 
assumption  of  the  Man  Jesus  into  unity  of  person  with  God.2 

"The  most  eminent  instance  of  predestination  and  grace 
is  the  Saviour  Himself,  the  Mediator  of  God  and  man, 
the  Man  Christ  Jesus  ;  for  by  what  preceding  merits  of 
of  its  own,  either  of  works  or  faith,  did  that  human  nature 
which  was  in  Him  earn  this  ?  Answer :  How  did  the 
Man  Jesus  merit  to  be,  as  assumed  into  unity  of  person 
with  the  co-eternal  Word,  the  only  begotten  Son  of  God  ? 
What  good  in  him  preceded  ?  What  did  he  do,  believe, 
ask,  antecedently,  that  he  should  attain  to  this  ineffable 
dignity  ?  Was  not  this  Man,  by  virtue  of  his  assumption 
by  the  Word,  from  the  first  moment  that  he  was  Man,  the 
Son  of  God?  Was  it  not  as  the  only  Son  of  God  that 
that  woman  full  of  grace  conceived  him  ?  Was  he  not  born 
the  only  Son  of  God  of  the  Holy  Ghost  and  the  Virgin  Mary 
by  a  singular  dispensation?  Was  there  any  fear  then, 
that,  on  coming  to  mature  age,  that  Man  should  sin  in  the 
exercise  of  freewill  ?  Or,  had  he  not  freewill  on  that 
account ;  nay,  a  will  on  that  very  account,  and  because  He 
could  not  serve  sin,  all  the  more  free?  All  these  singular 
and  wonderful  privileges  human  nature  in  him  received, 
without  any  preceding  merits  of  its  own  ?  And  will  any 
man  dare  to  say  to  God,  *  Why  was  not  I  so  privileged? 


1  Ep.  194.  c.  6.  8. 

2  Edwards,  in    his   book   "  On   the 
Freedom  of  the   Will,"  uses  the  same 
argument  in  the  chapter  on  "  the  acts 


of  the  will  of  the  human  soul  of  Jesus 
Christ,  necessarily  holy,  yet  truly  vir- 
tuous, praiseworthy,  rewardable,"  &c. 


CHAP.  V.]  OF    PREDESTINATION.  153 

.  .  .  Why,  when  nature  is  common,  is  grace  so  different  ? 
Why  is  there  respecting  of  persons  with  God?'  What 
I  will  not  say,  Christian,  but  sane  man  would  say  this." 
From  the  case  of  Him,  then,  who  is  our  Head,  we  may 
understand  the  operation  of  grace  ;  how  from  the  Head  it 
diffuses  itself,  according  to  the  measure  of  each,  through 
all  the  members.  By  what  grace  that  Man  was  made 
from  the  beginning  Christ,  by  that  grace  is  every  man 
who  is  such  made  from  the  beginning  of  his  faith  a 
Christian :  reborn  of  the  spirit  of  which  he  was  born ; 
forgiven  his  sins  by  the  same  Spirit  by  whom  he  was 
made  to  have  none.  This  is  the  predestination  of  saints, 
which  shone  chiefly  in  him  who  is  the  Saint  of  saints. 
In  so  far  as  he  was  Man,  the  Lord  of  glory  was  Himself 
predestinated  —  predestinated  to  be  the  Son  of  God  .... 
Jesus  was  predestinated  to  be  of  the  seed  of  David  accord- 
ing to  the  flesh,  and  according  to  the  Spirit  of  holiness 

the  Son  of  God  with  power As,  then,  that 

one  Man  was  predestinated  to  be  our  Head,  so  are  we 
many  predestinated  to  be  his  members.  Let  human  merits, 
which  perished  in  Adam,  be  silent,  and  let  grace  reign. 
Whoever  finds  in  our  Head  preceding  merits  to  cause  his 
singular  generation,  may  find  in  his  members  the  same 
to  cause  their  regeneration.  But  as  that  generation  was 
not  a  reward,  but  a  freegift  to  Christ,  so  is  our  regeneration 
no  reward  but  a  freegift  to  us  ...  He  makes  us  believe 
in  Christ,  who  made  him  that  Christ  in  whom  we  believe.1 
Again:  "God  therefore  took  the  nature  of  man,  i.e.  the 
rational  soul  and  flejsh  of  the  Man  Christ,  by  a  singularly  won- 
derful and  wonderfully  singular  adoption;  so  that,  without 
any  preceding  merits,  that  Man  was  from  the  beginning  of 
his  human  life  the  Son  of  God,  even  as  he  was  one  Person 
with  the  Word,  which  is  without  beginning.  For  no  one 
is  so  blindly  ignorant  as  to  dare  to  say  that,  born  of  the 


1  De  Pra:d.  Sanct.  c.  xv.     See  De  Dono  Perseverantiae,  c.  xxiv,  Op.  Imp.  1.  1. 
c.  138. 


154  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  V. 

Holy  Spirit  and  the  Virgin  Mary,  the  Son  of  Man,  he 
obtained,  by  the  merit  of  a  sinless  life  and  the  good  use 
of  freewill,  the  Divine  Sonship ;  —  to  say  this  in  the  face 
of  the  text :  (  The  Word  was  made  flesh.'  For  where 
did  this  take  place  but  in  the  Virgin's  womb,  where  the 

Man  Christ  began  to  be? That  gratuitous 

nativity  joined  in  unity  of  person  man  with  God,  the  flesh 
with  the  Word.  Good  works  then  followed  that  nativity, 
and  did  not  merit  it.  There  was  no  risk,  when  human 
nature  was  thus  ineffably  taken  into  unity  of  Person  by  the 
Word  of  G  od,  that  it  should  sin  in  the  exercise  of  freewill : 
—  that  nature  being  so  assumed  by  God  that  it  admitted 
of  no  evil  motion  of  the  will.  As,  therefore,  this  Mediator 
was,  by  reason  of  his  assumption,  never  evil  but  always 
good ;  so  those  whom  God  redeems  by  his  blood  are  made 
by  him  eternally  good  out  of  evil."  l 

This  is  an  argument,  however,  for  predestination  which 
admits  of  much  the  same  answer  which  was  given  to  the 
argument  drawn  from  original  sin.  The  sinless  life  of  the 
Man  Jesus  was  undoubtedly  an  infallible  consequence  of 
the  Incarnation ;  for  He  could  not  be  one  with  God  and 
be  capable  of  sinning.  His  goodness  was  therefore  a  ne- 
cessary goodness;  and  one  Man,  in  being  predestin- 
ated from  all  eternity  to  a  union  with  God,  was  pre- 
destinated to  a  perfect  holiness.  The  Incarnation  is  thus 
a  premiss  for  a  doctrine  of  predestination.  But  it  should 
be  remembered  what  kind  of  premiss  this  is,  that  it  is  not 
a  truth  of  nature  or  reason  which  we  comprehend,  but 
a  mysterious  and  incomprehensible  truth ;  and  therefore 
that  the  inference  drawn  from  it  is  alike  a  mystery  and  not 
an  ascertained  and  complete  truth,  like  a  logical  consequence 
from  a  known  premiss. 

The  conclusion,  then,  to  which  S.  Augustine's  general 
statements,  given  at  the  commencement  of  this  chapter, 
of  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  naturally  led,  has  only 


De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xi. 


CHAP.  V.] 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


155 


obtained  confirmation  and  accuracy  from  further  examina- 
tion and  the  subsequent  particulars  into  which  we  have 
entered.  The  characteristic  of  S.  Augustine's  doctrine, 
compared  with  the  scriptural  one  is,  that  it  is  a  definite 
and  absolute  doctrine.  Scripture,  as  a  whole,  as  has  been 
said  *,  only  informs  us  of  a  mystery  on  the  subject ;  that 
is  to  say,  while  it  informs  us  that  there  is  a  truth  on  the 
subject,  it  makes  no  consistent  statement  of  it,  but  asserts 
contrary  truths,  counterbalancing  those  passages  which  con- 
vey the  predestinarian  doctrine  by  passages  as  plain  the  other 
way ;  but  S.  Augustine  makes  predestinarian  statements  and 
does  not  balance  them  by  contrary  ones.  Rather  he  endea- 
vours to  explain  away  those  contrary  statements  in  Scripture. 
Thus  he  evades  the  natural  force  of  the  text  that  "  God 
would  have  all  men  to  be  saved,"  by  supposing  that  it  only 
means  that  no  man  is  saved  except  through  the  will  of  God  2 ; 
or  that  "  all "  means  not  all  men,  but  some  out  of  ail  classes 
and  ranks  of  men :  on  the  same  rule  on  which  we  understand 
the  phrase  "  ye  tithe  all  herb 3,"  as  meaning  not  that  the 
Pharisees  gave  literally  a  tenth  of  all  the  herbs  in  the  world, 
but  only  of  all  kinds  of  herbs.4 


1  Chapter  II. 

'•Enchiridion,  c.  ciii. ;  Contra  Jul. 
Pelag.  1.  4.  c.  viii.;  Ep.  217.  c.  vi. 

*  Luke  ii.  42. 

4  "  Neque  enim  Pharisaci  omnia 
olera  decimabant.  .  .  .  Ita  et  illic 
omnes  homines,  omne  hominum  genus 
intelligere  possumus." —  Enchiridion, 
c.  ciii. 

The  text  that  God  is  no  respecter 
of  persons  is,  in  its  general  spirit,  a 
counter  text  to  the  predestinarian 
ones.  But  its  opposition  is  not  exact, 
because  it  supposes  a  difference  of  rank, 
or  other  advantages,  in  the  individuals, 
•which  is  not  respected  ;  whereas  pre- 
destination applies  to  those  between 
whom  there  is  no  difference,  all  de- 
serving condemnation.  Upon  this 
ground  S.  Augustine  rejects  his  oppo- 
nent's application  of  this  text  altogether 
as  incorrect  ;  "  Nee  ulla  est  acceptio 


personarum,  in  duobus  debitoribus 
sequaliter  reis,  si  alteri  dimittitur 
alteri  exigitur,  quod  pariter  ab  utroque 
debetur." — Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  2.  c.  7. 
"  Cur  ergo  in  regnum  coelorum,  non 
accepto  regenerationis  lavacro,  parvulus 
nullus  intrabit?  Nunquidnam  ipse 
sibi  parentes  infideles  vel  negligentes, 
de  quibus  nasceretur  elegit?  Quid 
dicam  de  inopinatis  et  repentinis  innu- 
merabilibus  mortibus,  quibus  sa?pe  etiam 
religiosorum  Christianorum  praesumun- 
tur,  et  baptismo  prseripiuntur  infantes ; 
cum  e  contrario  sacrilegorum  et  inimi- 
corum  Christi  aliquo  modo  in  Chris- 
tianorum manus  venientes,  ex  hac  vita 
non  sine  sacramento  regenerationis 
emigrent.  .  .  .  Ista  cogitent,  ista  con- 
siderent,  hie  audeant  dicere  Deum 
vel  acceptorem  in  sua  gratia  personarum, 
vel  remuneratorem  meritorum." — Ep. 
194.  n.  32. 


156  DOCTRINE   OF   PREDESTINATION.  [CHAP.  V. 

S.  Augustine  then  takes  that  further  step  which  Scrip- 
ture avoids  taking,  and  asserts  a  determinate  doctrine  of 
predestination.  He  erects  those  passages  of  Scripture  which 
are  suggestive  of  predestination  into  a  system,  explaining 
away  the  opposite  ones ;  and  converts  the  obscurity  and  in- 
consistency of  Scripture  language  into  that  clearness  and 
consistency  by  which  a  definite  -truth  is  stated.  His  was 
the  error  of  those  who  follow  without  due  consideration  that 
strong  first  impression  which  the  human  mind  entertains, 
that  there  must  be  some  definite  truth  to  be  arrived  at  on  the 
question  under  consideration,  whatever  it  may  be ;  and  who 
therefore  imagine  that  they  cannot  but  be  doing  service, 
if  they  only  add  to  what  is  defective  enough  to  make  it 
complete,  or  take  away  from  what  is  ambiguous  enough  to 
make  it  decisive.  Assuming  arrival  at  some  determinate 
truth  necessary,  he  gave  an  exclusive  development  to  those 
parts  of  Scripture  which  he  had  previously  fixed  on  as  con- 
taining, in  distinction  to  any  apparently  opposite  ones,  its 
real  meaning.  But  the  assumption  itself  was  gratuitous. 
There  is  no  reason  why  Scripture  should  not  designedly 
limit  itself,  and  stop  short  of  expressing  definite  truth ; 
though  whether  it  does  so  or  not  is  a  question  of  fact.  If 
Revelation  as  a  whole  does  not  state  a  truth  of  predesti- 
nation, that  stopping  short  is  as  much  a  designed  stopping 
short,  as  a  statement  would  have  been  a  designed  statement. 
Nor  are  we  to  be  discontented  with  the  former  issue,  when 
the  comparison  of  one  part  of  God's  word  with  another 
fairly  leads  to  it ;  to  suppose  that  an  indeterminate  con- 
clusion must  be  a  wrong  one,  and  to  proceed  to  obtain  by 
forced  interpretation  what  we  had  failed  to  do  by  natural. 
If  Revelation  as  a  whole  does  not  speak  explicitly,  Reve- 
lation did  not  intend  to  do  so  :  and  to  impose  a  definite 
truth  upon  it,  when  it  designedly  stops  short  of  one,  is  as 
real  an  error  of  interpretation  as  to  deny  a  truth  which  it 
expresses. 


157 


CHAP.  VI. 

AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE. 

THE  doctrine  of  absolute  predestination  implies  the  doctrine 
of  efficacious  or  irresistible  grace,  for  the  end  implies  the 
means ;  and  therefore,  if  eternal  life  is  ensured,  the  ne- 
cessary qualifications  for  that  life,  which  are  holiness  and 
virtue,  must  be  earned  also.  But  these  can  only  be  ensured 
by  such  a  Divine  influence  as  does  not  depend  for  its  effect 
on  the  contingency  of  man's  will ;  z.  e.  by  what  divines 
call  irresistible  or  efficacious  grace  —  a  grace  which  S.  Au- 
gustine accordingly  maintains. 

The  language  which  the  Church  has  always  used  for 
expressing  the  relation  in  which  grace  stands  to  the  human 
will  has  been  that  grace  assists  the  will;  and  such  a  term 
implies  in  its  natural  meaning  an  original  power  in  ourselves, 
to  which  this  assistance  was  given,  and  by  which  it  must 
be  used — an  assistance,  in  short,  which  is  no  more  than 
assistance.  S.  Augustine,  however,  in  adopting  the  au- 
thorised expression,  and  speaking  of  grace  as  assistance,  is 
obliged  by  his  system  to  use  the  term  in  a  meaning  exceeding 
this  natural  and  obvious  one,  viz., —  not  as  assistance,  but 
as  control ;  —  though  he  arrives  at  his  definition  of  such  a 
controlling  grace  only  gradually,  after  long  familiarity  with 
the  subject,  and  when  controversy  has  strengthened  and 
sharpened  his  ideas. 

S.  Augustine  early  in  his  theological  life  commits  himself 
to  an  idea  of  the  Divine  Power  as  being  a  power  of  creating 
perfect  goodness  in  the  creature,  and  defends  in  his  book 
De  Libero  Arbitrio,  written  against  the  Manicheans, 
the  act  of  God  in  not  creating  man  thus  perfect  at  once, 


158 


AUGUSTINIAN 


[CHAP.  VI 


but  only  with  the  power  of  becoming  so ;  arguing  that 
God  dispensed  different  kinds  of  advantages 1  according 
to  His  own  sovereign  will,  and  that  a  lesser  good  is  not 
to  be  undervalued  because  it  is  not  a  higher  one.  The 
passage,  however,  expressing  as  it  does  the  fitness  of  loth 
kinds  of  goods  to  be  Divine  gifts,  he  appeals  to  in  his 
f<  Retractations  "  to  prove  how,  even  in  an  early  work,  and 
before  his  mind  had  expanded  on  the  subject  of  grace,  he 
had  laid  down  the  principles  of  his  subsequent  teaching.2 

The  first  regular  attempt,  however,  at  a  definition  of  the 
characteristic  power  of  Gospel  grace,  occurs  in  the  treatise 
"  De  Gratia  Christi"  in  which  he  calls  it  "  the  assistance 
of  will  and  action — adjutorium  voluntatis  et  actioni*.***  It 
will  of  course  be  evident  at  first  sight  that  this  definition 
does  not  of  itself  describe  an  irresistible  grace,  but  would 
apply  to  a  simply  assisting  one  as  well.  But,  considered  in 
connexion  with  the  context,  and  taken  in  the  meaning  which 
its  opposition  to  another  definition  of  grace  fastens  upon 
it,  it  will  be  found  to  imply  the  former.  It  was  asserted 
by  the  Pelagians  that,  inasmuch  as  the  power  of  willing 
and  acting  in  one  way  or  another  (jpossibilitas  utriusque 
partis)  was  inseparable  from  human  nature,  human  nature 
had  of  itself  the  power  to  will  and  act  aright ;  but  that  this 
power  needed  to  be  assisted  by  grace  (ut  possibilitas  semper 
gratis  adjuvetur  auxiUo)*  To  this  Augustine  replied,  that 
not  only  the  power  to  will  and  act  was  assisted  by  grace, 
but  that  will  and  action  itself  were;  and  therefore  to  the 
Pelagian  definition  of  grace,  as  the  "  assistance  of  power " 
(adjutorium  possibilitatis),  he  opposed  his  own,  "  the  assist- 
ance of  will  and  action  "  (adjutorium  voluntatis  et  actionis). 
Now,  by  assisting  will  and  action  we  should  naturally  and 


1  "  Bona  quibus  male  uti  malus 
potest,  et  quorum  esse  usus  non  potest 
malus ;  "  the  one  being  freewill  or  the 
power  of  being  good,  the  other  goodness 
itself.— De  Lib.  Arb.  1.  2.  c.  17.,  et  seq.: 
De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  2.  c.  18. 


3  Retract.  1.  1.  c.  9. 

3  I  give  the  Jansenist  turn  to  the 
phrase  gratia  qua  adjuvat  voluntatem  et 
actionem. 

4  De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  iii. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  159 

ordinarily  understand  assisting  the  power  to  will  and  act, 
taking  the  words  will  and  action  loosely  to  signify  the 
faculties;  for  acts  themselves  are  not  susceptible  of  assist- 
ance, being  already  done.  Nor,  therefore,  should  we  na- 
turally see  any  difference  at  all  of  meaning  in  these  two 
expressions,  assistance  of  power  and  assistance  of  action. 
But  if  this  ordinary  meaning  is  disclaimed  for  the  expression 
assistance  of  action,  and,  instead  of  being  identified  with,  the 
latter  is  contrasted  to,  the  assistance  of  the  power  to  will 
and  act,  it  must  follow  that  by  assistance  of  action  a  grace 
of  a  stronger  kind  is  meant  than  that  which  assists  the 
power  to  act ;  and  what  can  that  grace  be  but  one  which 
causes  action  itself, —  i.e.  irresistible  grace? 

Indeed,  this  absolute  sense  is  fastened  on  the  word 
adjutorium  in  this,  Augustine's,  definition  of  grace,  by  the 
mode  in  which  the  same  word  is  used  in  the  rival  and 
opposing  definition.  For  the  word  carries  to  the  phrase 
adjutorium  voluntatis  et  actionis  the  same  meaning  that 
it  bore  in  the  phrase  adjutorium  possibilitatis  (for  the 
two  sides  differ  not  about  the  meaning  of  assistance,  but 
about  what  is  assisted).  But  in  the  latter  phrase  it  bears 
the  sense  of  causing  as  well  as  of  assisting ;  for  the  Pe- 
lagians said  this  power  (jpossibilitas)  was  given  by  God  in 
the  first  instance  as  well  as  assisted  when  had.  The  word 
therefore  bears  the  same  sense  in  the  phrase  "  adjutorium 
voluntatis  et  actionis"  and  implies  the  gift  or  causation 
of  will  and  action,  and  not  only  the  assistance  of  it. 

But  the  meaning  of  this  definition  of  grace,  which  is 
evident  hitherto  with  some  difficulty,  and  only  by  a  close  and 
exact  process  of  comparison,  is  abundantly  clear  and  mani- 
fest when  we  come  to  S.  Augustine's  own  explanation 
and  exposition  of  it.  He  says :  "  Pelagius  in  his  first  bcok 
on  Freewill  thus  speaks :  '  We  have,'  he  says,  (  a  power  of 
taking  either  side — possibilitatem  utriusque  partis  — im- 
planted in  us  by  God,  as  a  fruitful  and  productive  root, 
to  produce  and  bring  forth  according  to  men's  different 


160  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

wills ;  and  either  shine  with  the  flower  of  virtue,  or  bristle 
with  the  thorns  of  vice,  according  to  the  choice  of  the 
cultivator.'  In  which  passage,  not  perceiving  what  he 
says,  he  establishes  one  and  the  same  root  of  good  and  evil 
men,  against  evangelical  truth  and  apostolical  teaching. 
For  our  Lord  says,  that  a  good  tree  cannot  bring  forth 
evil  fruit,  nor  an  evil  tree  good  fruit.  And  the  Apostle 
Paul,  when  he  says  that  cupidity  is  the  root  of  all  evil, 
intimates  also  that  love  is  the  root  of  all  good.  If,  therefore, 
the  two  trees  good  and  evil  are  two  men  good  and  evil,  what 
is  the  good  man  but  the  man  of  a  good  will ;  that  is,  the  tree 
of  a  good  root  ?  And  what  is  the  evil  man,  but  the  man  of 
an  evil  will ;  that  is,  the  tree  of  an  evil  root  ?  And  the 
fruits  of  these  two  trees  are  acts,  words,  thoughts ;  which 
if  good  proceed  from  a  good  will,  and  if  evil  from  an  evil 

will It  is  not  true,  then,  as  Pelagius  says,  that 

there  is  one  and  the  same  root  of  good  and  evil  men ; 
for  there  is  one  root  of  good  men,  viz.  love ;  and  another 
root  of  evil  men,  viz.  cupidity:  although  it  is  true  that  that 
power  is  capable  of  both  roots  —  ilia  possibilitas  utriusque 
radicis  est  capax — because  a  man  is  able  not  only  to  have  love 
but  also  to  have  cupidity."  * 

He  proceeds  to  say  that  love,  which  is  the  root  of  good 
actions,  is  a  free  gift  of  God,  and  not  given  according  to  our 
merits. 

Now  this  passage  evidently  contains  a  different  doctrine, 
as  to  the  source  of  our  actions,  from  the  doctrine  of  freewill. 
The  doctrine  of  freewill  is  that  we  do  possess  a  power 
of  taking  both  sides,  and  act  well  or  ill  according  as  we 
use  it;  that  therefore  good  and  evil  acts  may  both  arise 
out  of  one  root  or  one  and  the  same  moral  condition  of 
the  agent.  But  Augustine  denies  the  residence  in  man  of 
a  power  to  act  either  way,  on  the  logical  or  speculative 
ground  of  the  absurdity  of  supposing,  that  both  virtue  and 


1  De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  xviii. 


CHAP.  VI.]         DOCTRINE  OF  GRACE.  161 

vice  can  come  out  of  the  same  moral  condition  of  the  agent, 
as  this  neutral  state  of  power  would  be ;  and  maintains  that 
human  actions  proceed  either  out  of  a  moral  condition  which 
necessarily  produces  right  action,  or  out  of  a  moral  condition 
which  necessarily  produces  wrong.  He  denies  therefore  the 
doctrine  of  freewill.  He  admits,  indeed,  that  man  is  capable 
of  either  moral  condition,  —  or,  to  use  his  own  language, 
capable  of  either  root ;  but  this  is  not  the  doctrine  of  free- 
will, which  is,  that  the  same  moral  condition,  or  the  same  root, 
is  capable  of  either  fruit.  The  former  is  only  the  admission 
of  the  obvious  fact,  that  man  has  a  capacity,  in  the  first 
instance,  both  for  good  and  evil ;  an  admission  which  is  quite 
consistent  with  the  subsequent  necessity  of  either  in  him; 
just  as  a  material  is  capable,  in  the  first  instance,  of  any  one 
out  of  many  different  forms ;  but  when  it  has  once  received 
a  particular  form,  is  necessarily  of  that  form  which  it  has 
received. 

The  whole  of  the  book,  however,  De  Gratia  Christi, 
is  one  comment  on  the  adjutorium  voluntatis  et  actionis,  as 
involving  the  sense  of  irresistible  grace,  as  the  following 
passage  on  illuminating  grace  will  exemplify :  "  Our  Lord 
saith,  'Every  man  that  hath  heard  and  hath  learned  of  the 
Father,  cometh  unto  Me.'  Whosoever  therefore  doth  not 
come,  of  him  it  is  not  right  to  say,  'He  hath  heard  and 
learned,  indeed,  that  he  should  come,  but  he  does  not  will  to 
do  what  he  has  learned.'  That  is  not  rightly  said,  if  we 
speak  of  that  mode  of  teaching  which  God  employs  through 
grace.  For  if,  as  the  truth  saith,  'Every  man  that  hath 
learned,  cometh,'  if  any  man  hath  not  come,  neither  hath  he 
learned.  It  is  true,  indeed,  a  man  comes  or  does  not  come, 
according  to  the  choice  of  his  will.  But  this  choice  is  alone  if 
he  does  not  come;  it  cannot  but  be  assisted  if  he  does  come; 
and  so  assisted  as  that  he  not  only  knows  what  he  should  do, 
but  also  does  what  he  knows.  Wherefore,  when  God  teaches 
not  by  the  letter  of  the  law,  but  by  the  grace  of  the  spirit,  He 
so  teaches  as  that  what  a  man  learns  he  not  only  perceives  by 

M 


162  AUGUSTINIAN  [CuAr.  VT. 

knowing  it,  but  also  pursues  by  willing  it,  and  accomplishes  by 
doing  it.  By  that  Divine  mode  of  teaching  will  itself  and  action 
itself,  not  only  the  natural  power  of  willing  and  acting,  are 
assisted.  For,  were  our  power  alone  assisted  by  this  grace, 
our  Lord  would  have  said,  ( Every  man  that  hath  heard  or 
hath  learned  of  the  Father  is  able  to  come  to  Me.'  But  He 
has  not  said  this,  but  *  Every  man  that  hath  heard  and  hath 
learned  of  the  Father  cometh  unto  Me.'  ....  Every  man 
that  hath  learned  of  the  Father  is  not  only  able  to  come, 
but  comes ;  wherein  not  only  the  proficiency  of  the  power, 
but  the  affection  of  the  will,  and  the  effect  of  action  is  in- 
cluded." ! 

The  grace,  then,  to  which  Augustine  gives  the  name  or 
description  of  "  adjutorium  voluntatis  et  actionis"  we  find,  on 
examining  his  own  account  and  explanation  of  it,  to  be  en- 
dowed with  the  effect  of  action ;  to  be  a  grace,  not  only 
given  in  order  that  such  and  such  actions  may  be  done,  but 
also  causing  those  actions  to  be  done  in  fact. 

But  such  a  phrase  as  "  adjutorium  volunfatis  et  actionis  " 
is  obviously  a  very  imperfect  and  awkward  description  of 
irresistible  grace  ;  being,  in  fact,  not  of  itself  any  description 
of  it  at  all,  but  depending  entirely  on  the  definition  to  which 
it  is  opposed  and  on  the  context  generally,  for  its  meaning. 
Indeed,  hitherto,  Augustine  appears  rather  feeling  his  way 
toward  some  clear  and  exact  definition  of  the  grace  for 
which  he  is  arguing,  than  really  defining  it.  His  language 
as  a  whole  has  one  evident  meaning ;  but  it  is  only  as  a 
whole  that  it  has :  it  effects  its  object  by  large,  varied,  and 
diffuse  statement  and  explanation  ;  but  in  aiming  at  point 
it  altogether  fails,  and  cannot  concentrate  itself  in  definition. 
As  his  doctrine  of  grace,  however,  obtains  a  more  familiar 
hold  of  his  mind,  and  perpetual  controversy  multiplies 
thought  and  language  about  it,  and  the  subject  by  being 
turned  over  repeatedly  is  seen  in  every  aspect,  his  ideas 


De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  xiv. 


CHAP.  VI.]         DOCTRINE  OF  GRACE.  163 

become  more  exact  and  his  choice  of  terms  greater ;  and 
out  of  the  accumulation  of  statements  he  is  at  last  able 
to  fix  on  one  to  serve  as  a  complete  definition  of  this  grace. 

In  the  book  (f  De  Correptione  et  Gratia"  he  draws  a  clear 
distinction  between  two  different  kinds  of  grace,  which  he 
calls   respectively    "  an    assistance   without   which   a  thing 
cannot  be  done,"  and  "  an   assistance  by  which  a  thing  is 
done  "  (adjutorium  sine  quo  aliquid  non  fit,>  and  adjutorium 
quo  aliquid  Jit).     He  first  draws  a  strong  distinction  between 
the  wants  of  man  before  and  man  after  the  fall,  and  then 
gives  this  as  the  corresponding  distinction  in  the  nature  of 
the   grace   by  which  these   respective  wants  are  supplied. 
Man  even  before  the  fall,  upright  and  perfect  being  as  he 
was,  and  possessed  of  freewill,  stood  in  need  of  grace  to 
enable  him.  to  act  aright ;    nor   could  he  do  anything   ac- 
ceptable to  God  by  his  own  natural  strength.     But  as  an 
upright  being  and  possessed  of  freewill  he  only  stood  in 
need   of  assisting   grace,  he    was   strong   enough   to   have 
the  ultimate  choice  of  good    and  evil   thrown  upon  him, 
and  only  wanted  grace  to  advance  and  aid  the  choice  when 
made.    So  great  a  burden  might  be  placed  upon  him,  because 
he  was  able  to  bear  it,  and  was  no   penalty,  but  the  sign  of 
strength  and  perfection.     To  man,  then,  before  the  fall  "an 
assistance  without  which  a  thing  is  not  done  "  was  given  ; 
that  is  to  say,  an  assistance  which  he  could  not  do  without, 
but   which  did  not   effect   anything   unless   he    added   the 
exercise  of  his  own  original  choice  to  it,  —  that  which  is 
commonly  called  assisting  grace.     But  at  the  fall  this  whole 
state  of  things  ceased.     The  fall  deprived  man  of  freewill,  and 
inclined  his  nature  irresistibly  to  evil.     In  this  state  he  was 
too  weak  to  bear  the  ultimate  choice  of  good  and  evil  being 
thrown  upon  him,  and  must  perish  if  it  was.     The  grace, 
therefore,  which  is  given  to  man  after  the  fall  is  not  the 
assistance  "without  which  a  thing  is  not  done,"  but  that 
"  with  which  a  thing  is  done ;  "  that  is  to  say,  an  assistance, 
upon  which  being  given,  the  effect  of  a  renewed  heart  and 

M    2 


164  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

renewed  will  follows  certainly.  A  grace  is  now  given  him 
suited  to  an  entirely  impotent  nature,  wholly  controlling 
choice  and  action,  and  leading  irresistibly  to  good. 

Augustine  explains  at  length  the  difference  between 
these  two  kinds  of  grace,  and  the  reason  for  it :  "  Adam 
was  in  the  midst  of  good  which  he  had  received  from  the 
goodness  of  his  Creator ;  but  the  saints  in  this  life  are  in 
the  midst  of  evil,  out  of  which  they  cry  aloud  to  God, 
*  Deliver  us  from  evil.'  He  amidst  that  good  needed  not  the 
death  of  Christ;  them  from  guilt,  hereditary  and  personal, 
the  blood  of  that  Lamb  absolveth.  He  had  not  need  of 
that  assistance  which  they  implore,  saying,  ( I  see  another 
law  in  my  members  warring  against  the  law  of  my  mind, 
and  bringing  me  into  captivity  to  the  law  of  sin  which  is 
my  members.'  In  them  the  flesh  lusteth  against  the  spirit, 
and  the  spirit  against  the  flesh ;  and  in  this  struggle,  labouring 
and  endangered,  they  ask  for  strength  through  Christ's  grace 
to  fight  and  conquer.  He,  tried  and  harassed  by  no  such 
conflict,  enjoyed  in  that  place  of  bliss  internal  peace."  l  .  .  . 

"  The  first  man,  therefore,  had  an  assistance,  which  he 
could  desert  if  he  willed,  and  in  which  he  would  abide  if  he 
willed  ;  not  one  by  which  he  was  made  to  will.  This  is 
the  first  grace  which  was  given  to  the  first  Adam :  but  a 
stronger  than  this  is  given  in  the  second  Adam.  For  the 
first  is  a  grace  of  which  the  effect  is,  that  a  man  may  have 
righteousness  if  he  wills :  the  second  is  a  more  powerful 
one,  of  which  the  effect  is,  that  he  wills,  and  wills  so  strongly 
and  loves  so  ardently,  that  the  will  of  the  flesh  is  conquered 
by  the  contrary  will  of  the  spirit.  Nor  was  that  a  small 
assistance  by  which  the  power  of  a  concurrent  freewill  was 
acknowledged ;  being  so  great,  as  that  he  could  not  remain 
in  good  without  it,  though  if  he  willed  he  could  desert  it. 
But  this  is  so  much  the  greater,  as  that  it  is  not  enough 
to  say  that  lost  freewill  is  repaired  by  it,  not  enough  to  say 


De  Corr.  et  Grat.  n.  29. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTKINE   OF   GRACE.  165 

that  a  man  cannot  attain  to  or  abide  in  good  without  it, 
but  with  it  can  if  he  will ;  except  we  add  also,  that  it  makes 
him  to  will"  1 

"  For  we  must  distinguish  between  one  kind  of  assistance 
and  another.  There  is  one  assistance,  without  which  some- 
thing is  not  done,  and  another  by  which  something  is  done. 
For  example,  food  is  a  thing  without  which  we  cannot  live ; 
but  we  have  it  and  die.  And  therefore  food  is  an  assistance 
without  which  it  is  not  effected,  not  an  assistance  by  which 
it  is  effected,  that  we  live.  On  the  other  hand,  if  happi- 
ness be  given  to  a  man,  he  is  forthwith  happy.  Happiness, 
therefore,  is  an  assistance  by  which  something  is,  not  an 
assistance  without  which  something  is  not,  effected.  The 
first  man  received  the  gift  of  being  able  not  to  sin,  able  not 
to  die,  able  not  to  desert  good:  that  assistance  of  perse- 
verance was  given  him  without  which  he  could  not  be,  not 
an  assistance  by  which  he  was  persevering.  On  the  other 
hand,  to  the  saints,  who  by  grace  are  predestinated  to  the 
kingdom  of  God,  not  such  an  assistance  of  perseverance  as 
this  is  given,  but  such  an  assistance  as  that  perseverance 
itself  is  given  —  tale  ut  eis  perseverantia  ipsa  donetur;  not  only 
a  gift  of  perseverance,  without  which  they  cannot  be,  but 
a  gift  by  which  they  cannot  but  be  persevering — non  solum 
ut  sine  isto  dono  perseverantes  esse  non  possint,  verum  etiam 
ut  per  hoc  donum  non  nisi  perseverantes  sint.2  .  .  . 

"  In  truth,  a  greater  freedom,  and  one  fortified  and  con- 
firmed by  the  gift  of  perseverance,  is  necessary  against  so 
many  and  so  great  temptations,  such  as  there  were  not  in 
Paradise;  that,  with  all  its  affections,  terrors,  errors,  the 
world  be  conquered.  This  the  martyrdom  of  the  saints 
has  shown.  For  Adam,  yielding  to  no  terror,  but  rather 
using  his  freewill  against  the  command  of  a  terrible  God, 
stood  not  firm  in  so  great  felicity,  and  so  great  facility  of 
avoiding  sin  :  but  they,  against  a  world  not  terrible  only 


1  De  Corr.  et.  Grat.  n.  31.  |          2  De  Corn  et  Grat  n.  34. 

M   3 


166 


AUGUSTINIAN 


[CHAP.  VI. 


but  raging,  stood  firm  in  the  faith:  though  he  saw  those 
present  advantages  which  he  was  about  to  leave,  and  they 
saw  not  the  future  ones  which  they  were  about  to  gain. 
Whence  this,  but  by  His  gift  from  whom  they  obtained 
mercy  that  they  might  be  faithful.1  .... 

"  Perseverance,  then,  was  not  given  to  Adam  as  a  Divine 
gift,  but  the  choice  of  persevering  or  not  was  left  to  himself, 
because  his  will,  created  as  it  was  without  sin  and  without 
concupiscence,  was  furnished  with  such  strength,  that  it  was 
worthy  of  such  a  choice  being  committed  to  it;  so  great 
goodness  and  facility  of  living  well  was  his.  But  now,  after 
that  great  freedom  has  been  lost  by  sin,  it  remains  that 

human   infirmity  be   assisted  with   greater   gifts.2 

God  not  wishing  His  saints  to  glory  in  their  own  strength, 
but  in  Him,  gives  them  more  than  that  assistance  which  He 
gave  to  the  first  man ;  for  inasmuch  as  they  will  not  persevere 
except  they  both  can  and  will,  He  gives  them  by  an  act  of 
free  grace  the  power  and  the  will  both.  For  if  their  own 
will  were  left  in  such  a  way  as  that  if  they  willed  they 
would  persevere,  without  it  being  provided  that  they  should 
will,  their  will  must  succumb  amid  so  many  infirmities, 
and  persevere  they  could  not.  Therefore  such  a  succour  is 
afforded  to  the  infirmity  of  their  will  as  that  by  Divine  grace 
action  takes  place,  without  it  being  possible  to  fall  away  or 
be  overcome.3  Thus,  weak  though  it  is,  this  will  fails  not 
and  is  not  conquered.  The  feeble  will  of  man,  through  the 
Divine  strength,  perseveres  in  a  yet  imperfect  goodness, 
when  the  strong  and  sound  will  of  the  first  man  did  not  in 
its  more  perfect.  The  strength  of  freewill  failed,  because, 
though  that  assistance  of  God  without  which  a  man  cannot, 
if  he  wills,  persevere,  was  not  wanting ;  such  assistance  as 
that  by  which  God  works  in  a  man  to  will,  was.  God  left  it 


1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  n.  35. 

2  Ibid.  n.  36. 

8  "  Ut  divina  gratia  indeclinabiliter 


et  insuperabiliter  ageretur."  The  ac- 
knowledged MS.  reading,  though  some 
editions  have  "  inseparabiliter." 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  167 

to  the  strong  man  to  do,  if  he  willed  ;  to  the  weak  He  has  re- 
served, as  a  gift  from  Himself,  to  will  unconquerably  what  is 
good  and  unconquerably  persevere  in  it."  l 

Such  is  the  distinction  between  the  two  kinds  of  grace 
by  which  the  spiritual  wants  of  man  before  the  fall  and 
after  are  respectively  supplied, —  the  grace  of  the  paradisal, 
and  the  grace  of  the  gospel  dispensation.  Under  the  former 
dispensation  grace  was  weak,  because  nature  was  strong  -9 
under  the  latter,  grace  is  absolute,  because  nature  is  im- 
potent. Human  nature  is  too  corrupt  and  weak  now  to 
have  anything  left  to  itself  to  do ;  and  it  must  be  treated  as 
such,  and  be  taken  in  hand  with  the  understanding  that 
everything  must  be  done  for  it.  It  is  past  all  but  the 
strongest  remedy,  a  self-acting  one.  The  distinction  rests 
upon  the  doctrine  of  the  fall  of  man  and  the  change  it  in- 
troduced into  his  nature.  The  doctrine  of  the  fall  of  man 
asserts  an  essential  change  in  the  powers  of  his  moral  nature 
to  have  followed  from  that  event,  in  consequence  of  which 
he  cannot  will  or  do  anything  aright  now  of  his  own  natural 
strength.  But  if  man  in  a  natural  state  has  not  the  power 
to  will  aright,  he  has  not,  Augustine  says,  freewill.  Ac- 
cordingly it  is  assumed  in  this  argument  that  this  is  the 
difference  between  man  before,  and  man  after  the  fall;  that 
before  he  had  a  will  which  exerted  a  power  of  its  own2,  and 
after  has  not ;  and  Augustine  comes  to  the  question  of 
the  nature  of  Christian  grace,  with  the  understanding  that 
grace  has  now  to  deal  with  a  being  who  has  not  freewill. 
But  what  kind  of  grace,  he  then  naturally  argues,  is  to 
restore  and  reclaim  such  a  being,  to  raise  him  to  spiritual 
life,  and  make  him  persevere  in  it,  but  an  over-mastering 
and  controlling  grace?  Less  power  in  the  grace  would 
suffice  if  there  were  some  in  the  being;  for  if  there  is  any 
power  in  nature,  the  complement  of  it  only  is  needed  from 


1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  n.  38.  I        2  Potentia  libcri  arbitrii.  -  De  Corr. 

et  Grat.  c.  xi. 


M   4 


168  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

grace;  but  if  there  is  none,  grace  must  supply  the  whole. 
Had  man  freewill,  grace,  to  be  suited  to  his  condition,  must 
recognise  it,  leave  it  to  act,  and  suspend  its  own  effect  upon 
its  action.  But  when  man  has  freewill  no  longer,  to  leave 
the  effect  of  grace  dependent  upon  his  freewill  is  a  mockery. 
If  he  is  to  be  reclaimed  at  all,  he  must  then  be  reclaimed 
by  an  absolute  act  of  power,  and  "grace  must  either  do  every- 
thing for  him  or  do  nothing. 

Here  there  is  a  clear  and  express  definition  of  irresistible 
or  efficacious  grace, —  the  assistance  with  which  a  thing  is  done 
— adjutorium  quo  aliquidjit,  —  as  distinguished  from  assisting 
grace  —  adjutorium  sine  quo  ali quid  non  fit  i  or,  as  abbreviated 
by  the  Jansenist  divines,  the  adjutorium  quo,  as  distinguished 
from  the  adjutorium  sine  quo  non.  According  to  this  de- 
finition, if  the  grace  defined  is  given,  the  effect  takes  place — 
aliquid  fit ;  the  renewal  and  conversion  of  the  man  follows 
in  fact.  By  this  definition,  then,  the  effect  is  made  the  test, 
whether  the  grace  is  given  or  not ;  and  a  grace,  of  which 
the  bestowal  is  thus  tested,  is  by  the  very  terms  an  irre- 
sistible and  efficacious  one. 

But,  while  preceding  statements  are  at  last  embodied  in 
a  definition,  the  definition  does  no  more  than  embody  and  give 
point  to  them ;  for  a  grace,  of  the  bestowal  of  which  the 
effect  is  the  test,  has  been  described  all  along.  "  If  every 
man  that  hath  learned  cometh  unto  Christ,  if  any  man  hath 
not  come,  neither  hath  he  learned."1 — "If  every  one  that 
hath  heard  and  learned  of  the  Father  cometh,  whoever  hath  not 
come  hath  not  heard  or  learned  of  the  Father.  For  if  he  had 
heard  or  learned,  he  would  have  come.  For  there  is  no  one 
that  hath  heard  or  learned,  and  cometh  not ;  but  every  one, 
as  saith  the  truth,  that  hath  heard  and  learned  of  the  Father 
cometh."2  Here  the  test  of  grace,  whether  it  is  given  or  not, 
is  the  effect.  If  a  man  is  admitted  to  hearing  and  learning, 
i.e.  to  illuminating  grace,  the  effect  of  a  new  life  or  coming 


De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  xiv.  |  2  De  Prod.  c.  viii. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  169 

to  Christ  follows :  if  this  effect  does  not  follow,  he  has  not 
been  admitted  to  this  grace.  We  do  indeed  sometimes  use 
the  words  hearing  and  learning  in  the  sense  of  a  man's 
own  act  of  attending  to  what  is  told  him,  and  profiting 
by  what  is  taught  him ;  and  in  this  sense  the  words  would 
express  here,  not  the  enlightening  grace  of  God,  but  a  man's 
own  use  of  that  grace ;  and  therefore  not  the  giving  of  a 
grace,  but  a  man's  own  use  of  it,  would  be  the  thing  tested 
here  by  the  effect.  But  the  obvious  sense  of  this  passage, 
and  the  whole  nature  of  the  discussion,  to  which  it  belongs, 
exclude  such  a  meaning  of  the  words  hearing  and  learning 
here,  which  mean  the  fact  of  being  told  and  being  taught,  or 
the  act  of  another  telling  or  teaching.  A  certain  teaching 
of  God,  then1,  that  is  to  say,  a  grace,  is  the  thing  of  which 
the  bestowal  is  in  these  passages  tested  by  the  effect;  and  to 
this  purpose  Augustine  criticises  the  common  saying,  that 
"  God's  mercy  to  us  is  in  vain  if  we  do  not  will,"  remarking, 
"  I  do  not  know  how  this  can  be  said,  for  if  God  has  mercy 
we  also  will  —  si  Deus  miseretur  etiam  volumus :  God  has 
mercy  on  no  man  in  vain — nullius  Deus  frustra  miseretur"  2 
This  is  to  adopt  the  test  of  the  effect.  The  saying  "  Agis  si 
acjaris — thou  actest  if  thou  art  acted  on3"  does  the  same, 
its  force  lying  in  the  contrast  and  inseparableness  at  the 
same  time  of  an  influence  on  the  man  and  an  act  of  him. 
The  saying  "  Grace  gives  merits,  when  it  is  given  itself  — 
gratia  dat  merita  cum  donatur  4,"  the  term  merit  meaning  in 
Augustine's  use  of  it  right  action,  does  the  same.  Again, 
"  Grace  is  given,  that  the  faults  both  of  nature  and  will  may 
be  conquered ;  for  that  which  is  impossible  with  man  is  easy 
to  God.  But  those  to  whom  the  grace  of  God  is  not  given 
become  sinners,  unrighteous  men.  Though  these  too  live 
for  the  advantage  of  the  children  of  mercy,  that  the  sight  of 


1  Iste  docendi  modus  quo  per  gratiam 
docet  Dens. 

2  De  Div.  Quaest.ad  Simp.  1. 1 .  n.  1 2, 1 3. 


3  Serm.  128.  c.  7. 

*  Ep.  ad  Vitalem,  217.  n.  5. 


170 


AUGUSTINIAN 


[CHAP.  VI. 


them  may  subdue  their  pride ;  reminding  them  that  what 
has  been  given  to  them  is  God's  free  gift,  and  not  of  their 
own  deserving."  1  The  test  of  the  effect  is  clearly  adopted 
here;  the  conquest  of  sin  and  continuance  in  it  being  re- 
spectively attached  to  the  bestowal  of  grace  and  the  with- 
holding of  it.2 

A  general  body  of  language  to  the  same  effect  must  be 
noticed,  in  which  a  holy  disposition  and  conduct  is  put  for- 
ward as  a  Divine  gift  and  a  Divine  creation.  It  is  certain 
from  revelation,  that  God  is  the  Giver  of  every  good  thing ; 
and  this  truth  is  applied  absolutely  by  Augustine  to  the  sub- 
ject of  human  action,  which,  when  good,  is  described  as  being 
a  Divine  gift.  Conversion  is  a  Divine  gift — donum  Dei 
etiam  ipsa  ad  Deum  nostra  conversio 3 :  so  is  obedience  — 
donum  obedientice  ;  a  good  life — bene  vivere  donum  divinum  ; 
merit  or  deserving  action  —  Dei  dona  sunt,  et  Dei  gratia 
conferuntur  universa  merita  justorum 4  ;  perseverance  — 
donum  Dei  per  sever  antia  5  ;  faith  in  its  beginning — <{  gratuito 
munere  nobis  datur 6 ;  "  even  the  very  beginning,  "  when 
men  begin  to  have  faith  which  they  had  not — incipiunt 
habere  fidem  quam  non  habebant 7 ;  "  faith  in  its  increase  — 
augmentum,  incrementum,  supplementumjidei^  donum  Dei.8 

Again,  it  is  certain  from  revelation  that  God  is  the  Creator 
of  every  thing  visible  and  invisible :  and  this  truth  is  also 
applied  absolutely  by  Augustine  to  the  subject  of  human 
action ;  which,  when  good,  is  described  as  being  a  Divine  crea- 
tion, And  if  a  reason  is  asked  for  this  limitation,  inasmuch  as, 


1  Op.  Imp.,  Contra  Jul.  1.  iv.  c.  129. 

2  "  Nulla  omnino  medicinalis  Cbristi 
gratia    effectu    suo   caret;  sed    omnis 
efficit  ut  voluntas  velit,  et  aliquid  ope- 
retur.  t  .  .  Primo    igitur   hoc   probat, 
quod  apud   Augustinum  gratia  et  opus 
bonum  ita  reciprocentur,  ut  quemad- 
modum   ex  gratia  data  mox  effectum 
operis    consecutum    inferre   solet;  ita 
vice   versa,  ex  defectu  operis  gratiam 
non    esse    datam.      Quo    ratiocinandi 
mcdo  indicatur  gratiam  tanquum  cau- 


sam,  et  operationem  voluntatis  bonam 
velut  effectum,  esse,  ut  philosopbl  lo- 
quuntur,  convertibles,  et  a  se  mutuo 
inseparabiles."  —  Jansen,  De  Gratia 
Christi  Salvatoris,  1.  2.  c.  25. 

De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb,  c.  v. 

De  Dono  Pers.  c.  ii, 

De  Dono  Pers.  c.  i. 

Ep.  194.  n.  12. 

Ep.  217.  n.  29. 

De  Prad.  c.  ii.1 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  171 

according  to  the  argument,  God  would  be  the  Creator 
of  all  action,  good  as  well  as  bad,  the  answer  is  ready, 
that  bad  action,  or  sin,  is  not  a  thing ,  but  only  a  negation. 
Sin  is  "  nothing,"  according  to  Augustine.  The  faculties  of 
mind  and  body  which  are  used  in  a  sinful  action,  are  indeed 
things,  and  are  the  creatures  of  God;  but  the  sin  itself 
is  not  a  thing,  and  is  consequently  not  a  creature.  God 
is  indeed  the  Author  of  all  that  is,  of  every  substance ;  but 
sin  is  not  a  substance,  and  is  not.  It  is  a  declination  from 
substance  and  from  being,  and  not  a  part  of  it :  true  being 
and  true  substance  being  necessarily  good,  and  "is  good," 
and  "  is  "  being  convertible  propositions.  It  is  unnecessary 
to  enter  at  large  here  into  this  distinction.  It  is  obvious 
that  some  explanation  or  other  is  wanted  in  order  to  prevent 
the  conclusion  that  God  is  the  Author  of  evil ;  and  it  is 
enough  to  say  that  this  difficulty  is  seen  and  is  in  some 
way  disposed  of. 

This  idea  of  human  virtue  and  piety,  as  a  Divine  crea- 
tion, is  indeed,  in  itself,  a  scriptural  one ;  a  point  which 
deserves  consideration.  The  attribute  of  God  as  Creator, 
in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word,  is  a  truth  almost  peculiar 
to  the  Bible;  for  though  this  truth  may  be  considered  a 
part  of  natural  religion,  it  has  not  practically  been  brought 
out  under  that  dispensation;  the  more  general  notion 
having  been,  that  God  was  the  Former  of  the  world,  and 
put  it  into  shape,  but  was  not  the  Maker  of  its  substance. 
The  human  mind  appears  to  have  had  great  difficulty  in 
reaching  the  idea  of  positive  causation  of  existence,  making 
substance  out  of  nothing ;  such  a  power  appearing  even  to 
those  who  entertained  a  system  of  religion,  and  admitted 
the  existence  of  a  Deity  and  our  duties  to  Him,  incredible, 
fictitious,  and  monstrous.  A  material  was  accordingly 
provided  for  the  great  Architect,  ready  at  hand  for  Him 
to  work  upon  and  put  into  shape;  and  matter  was  made 
a  co-eternal  substance  with  the  Deity.  The  timidity 
or  fastidiousness  of  philosophy  thus  weakened  essentially 


172  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

the  great  idea  of  God's  omnipotence;  but  the  Bible 
sustains  it  in  a  remarkable  way  upon  this  head.  Exem- 
plifying the  rule,  that  "  the  foolishness  of  God  is  wiser 
than  men,  and  the  weakness  of  God  is  stronger  than  men," 
Scripture  puts  forward  prominently,  and  as  a  fundamental 
truth,  that  very  idea  which  appeared  thus  monstrous  and 
untenable  to  the  philosopher,  •  viz.  that  God  is  the  true 
Creator  of  the  world,  and  made  substance  out  of  nothing. 

This  difference  between  the  Bible  and  ancient  philosophy 
is  specially  important  as  regards  one  division  of  the  crea- 
tion, viz.  the  world  invisible.  Philosophy  did  riot  speak 
of  the  intelligent  soul  as  being  a  created  substance,  but 
rather  as  being  an  emanation  of  the  Divine  mind ;  thus 
making  it  part  of  the  Deity  Himself,  and  forestalling  the 
peculiar  subjection  which  it  derives  from  creation.  But 
the  Bible  teaches  that  the  intelligent  soul  is  a  created  sub- 
stance, as  truly  as  matter  is.  The  subjection  which  belongs 
to  the  creature  thus  attaches  to  the  soul  in  the  system  of  the 
Bible  ;  the  susceptibility  to  and  need  of  influence  ;  the  capa- 
city for  being  moulded  and  controlled  by  that  Being  by  whom 
it  was  originally  made,  and  dependence  upon  this  moulding 
and  controlling  Power.  The  Divine  power  in  Scripture  thus 
extends  from  the  first  act  of  creating  the  substance  of  the 
soul  to  the  kindred  one  of  creating  it  morally ;  of  forming 
and  fashioning  the  inner  man,  inspiring  holy  acts,  im- 
parting holy  dispositions,  and  confirming  and  sustaining 
them  afterwards.  This  absolute  dominion  over  men  and 
irresistible  power  over  their  hearts  is  illustrated  by  the 
similitude  of  a  potter,  who  makes  what  he  pleases  of 
his  clay ;  now  forming  it  and  then  breaking  it,  now 
preserving  it  and  then  rejecting  it.1  The  New  Testament 
both  interprets  and  sustains  the  language  of  the  old; 
appealing  to  this  similitude  and  describing  renewed 


1  Isaiah,  xxix.  16.;  xlv.  9.;  Ixiv.  8.;  Jeremiah  xviii.  6. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  173 

hearts  as  a  Divine  creation.  "  Shall  the  thing  formed 
say  to  Him  that  formed  it,  why  hast  Thou  made  me  thus  ?  "  l 
"  If  any  man  be  in  Christ,  he  is  a  new  creature." 2  "  In 
Christ  Jesus  neither  circumcision  availeth  anything,  nor 
uncircumcision,  but  a  new  creature."  3  "  We  are  His  work- 
manship, created  in  Christ  Jesus  unto  good  works,  which 
God  hath  before  ordained,  that  we  should  walk  in  them."  4 

This  language,  however,  receives  in  Scripture  a  limita- 
tion of  meaning  from  the  general  doctrine  of  man's  free- 
will which  Scripture  inculcates.  But  Augustine  uses  this 
language  absolutely,  and  adds  to  its  strength  and  de- 
finiteness.  Thus,  God  "  makes  men  good  in  order  that  they 
may  do  good  acts  —  ipse  ergo  illos  bonos  facit  ut  lona 
faciant."  5  God  ct  makes  faith  — fidem  gentium  facit."  6  (<  He 
makes  men  believers — facit  credentes"  7  God  "  makes  men 
to  persevere  in  good."  8  "  God  calls  whom  He  vouchsafes 
to  call,  and  makes  whom  He  will  religious  —  Deus  quos 
dignatur  vocat,  et  quern  vult  religiosum  facit :  "  a  saying  of 
S.  Cyprian's,  often  quoted,  on  which  he  affixes  a  literal 
meaning.  "  Man  never  does  good  things  which  God  does 
not  make  him  do. —  qua  non  facit  Deus  ut  faciat  homo."9 
"  The  Holy  Spirit  not  only  assists  good  minds,  but  makes 
them  good  —  non  solum  mentes  bonas  adjuvat,  verum  etiam 
bonas  eas facit"  10  "  There  is  a  creation,  not  that  by  which 
we  were  made  men,  but  that  of  which  a  man  already 
created  spoke,  <  create  a  clean  heart  in  me  ; '  and'that  of  which 
speaks  the  Apostle,  '  If  any  man  be  in  Christ,  he  is  a  new 
creature.'  We  are  therefore  fashioned  and  created  in  good 
works,  which  we  have  not  ourselves  prepared,  but  God, 
that  we  should  walk  in  them."  n 

Nor  is  this  language  used  by  S.  Augustine  in  a  qualified 


Rom.  ix.  20. 

'2  Cor.  v.  1 7. 

Gal.  vi.  15. 

Eph.  ii.  10. 

De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xii. 

De  Pra?d.  c.  ii. 


De  Freed,  c.  xvii. 


8  De  Corr.  et  Graf.  c.  xii. 

9  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  2.  c.  xxi. 

10  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  4.  c.  vii. 

11  De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.  c.  8. 


174  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

sense,  simply  to  express  vividly  the  power  of  God's  assisting 
grace,  as  if  giving  and  creating  were  meant  by  Him  to  be 
conditional  upon,  and  supplemental  to,  a  certain  exertion  of 
man's  own  freewill,  understood  though  not  expressed ;  for 
he  distinctly  disclaims  this  qualification,  making  a  differ- 
ence in  this  very  respect  between  the  gift  of  obedience  or 
holiness  and  the  ultimate  gift  of  eternal  life.  Eternal  life 
is  the  gift  of  God,  but  it  is  given  according  to  merit;  that 
is,  it  is  a  gift  upon  certain  cond  itions,  viz.  the  conditions  of 
obedience  and  holiness  in  the  persons  to  whom  it  is  awarded. 
But  the  conditions  themselves  of  obedience  and  holiness  are 
not  given  according  to  merit,  but  are  gifts  unconditional  and 
gratuitous.  The  gift  of  eternal  life  is  a  reward,  and  not  a  gift 
only ;  but  that  for  which  it  is  a  reward  is  not  itself  a  reward, 
or  given  upon  condition  of  endeavours  and  exercise  of  will 
by  the  man  himself,  but  is  a  free  gift — dona  sua  coronal 
Dens,  non  merita  tua  l —  God  crowns  His  gifts  and  not  thy 
merits.  "  Eternal  life  is  the  recompense  of  preceding 
merits;  but  those  merits  of  which  it  is  the  recompense 
are  not  prepared  through  our  own  sufficiency,  but  are 
made  in  us  by  grace ;  it  is  given  to  merits,  but  the  merits 
to  which  it  is  given  are  themselves  given  —  data  sunt  et 
ipsa  merita  quibus  datur."2  God  at  the  last  judgment  has 
respect  to  His  own  gifts  in  those  who  appear  before  Him, 
not  distributing  eternal  life  to  this  person  or  that,  according 
to  His  own  sovereign  will  and  pleasure  only,  but  according 
to  a  rule ;  that  is  to  say,  according  as  persons  show  the 
possession  of  certain  previous  gifts  of  His  own  to  them : 
but  those  gifts  themselves  are  not  to  be  divested  of  their 
proper  character  of  gifts  because  a  reward  is  based  upon 
them,  —  the  second  gift  is  indeed  upon  the  basis  of 
the  first,  but  the  first  gift  is  upon  no  basis  at  all  but 
the  Divine  will  and  pleasure.  Here,  then,  is  a  contrast 
which  establishes  the  sense  of  the  term  gift  as  used  of  the 


1  See  Note,  p.  9.  2  Ep.  134.  n.  19. 


CHAP.  VI.] 


DOCTRINE   OF    GRACE. 


175 


qualifications  for  eternal  life,  as  the  more  simple  and  natural 
one  of  a  gift  absolute,  for  so  used  it  is  opposed  to  the  gift 
conditional. 

Thus  he  handles  the  text  "  Turn  unto  me,  and  I  will 
turn  unto  you  l ;  "  a  text  of  which  the  natural  meaning  is,  that 
if  man  does  his  part  according  to  the  power  of  free  agency 
which  he  possesses,  God  will  do  His  in  the  way  of  pardon 
and  reward.  "  They,  the  Pelagians,  gather  from  this 
text,  that  the  grace  wherewith  God  turns  to  us  is  given 
as  a  reward  for  our  own  turning  of  ourselves  to  God ;  not 
considering  that  unless  this  very  conversion  to  God  were 
the  gift  of  God,  it  would  not  have  been  said,  'Turn  us, 
Thou  God  of  Hosts  V  and  '  wilt  Thou  not  turn  again  and 
quicken  us,'  and  'Turn  us  then,  0  God  our  Saviour3/ 
and  the  like.  What  else  is  coming  to  Christ  but  turning 
to  Him  by  faith  ?  and  yet  He  saith,  e  No  man  can  come 
unto  Me  except  it  were  given  him  of  my  Father.'  4  All 
that  this  passage  asserts  is,  that  obedience  is  a  gift  of 
God  as  well  as  salvation.  But  obedience  is  next  made  a 
gift  of  God  in  distinction  to  salvation.  "  When  the  Pela- 
gians say,  that  that  grace  which,  is  given  at  the  end — i.e. 
eternal  life,  is  awarded  according  to  preceding  merits, — I 
reply,  true,  if  they  understand  these  merits  themselves 
to  be  gifts  of  God." 5  "  But  how  could  the  just  Judge 
award  the  crown,  if  the  merciful  Father  had  not  given 
the  grace  ?  How  could  there  be  the  crown  of  righteousness, 
if  the  righteousness  by  grace  had  not  preceded  ?  How 
could  this  final  reward  be  given  to  merit,  if  the  merit 
itself  had  not  been  given  as  a  free  gift  ? " 6  Here  the 
qualified  sense  of  gift,  viz.  as  a  gift  according  to  merit 


Zech.  i.  3. 

Ps.  Ixxx.  7. 

Ps.  Ixxxv.  4.  6. 

John  vi.  65. ;  De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Art. 

Ibid.  c.  vi. 

Again  :   "  Itaque,  charissimi,  si  vita 
bona  nostra  nihil  aliucl  cst  quam  Dei 


gratia,  sine  dubio  et  vita  aeterna  qusc 
bonse  vita*  redditur,  Dei  gratia  est :  et 
ipsa  enim  gratis  datur,  quia  gratis  data 
est  ilia  cui  datur.  Sed  ilia  cui  datur 
tantummodo  gratia  est:  haec  autem 
qua;  illi  datur,  quoniam  proemium  ejus 
est,  gratia  est  pro  gratia,  tanquara 
merces  pro  justitia." — C.  viii. 


176 


AUGUSTINIAN 


[CHAP.  VI. 


or  upon  the  fulfilment  of  certain  conditions,  is  allowed  of 
the  ultimate  gift  of  eternal  life,  only  on  the  understanding 
that  it  is  denied  of  the  preparatory  gift  of  the  righteousness 
which  qualifies  for  it.  The  crown  of  righteousness  is  a 
reward,  but  the  righteousness  itself  is  not  a  reward;  i.e. 
anything  given  in  consideration  of  preceding  endeavours 
of  man's  own  will.  And  the  gift  of  obedience  is  described 
as  a  gift  residing  in  the  individual  previous  to  action  of 
his  own  ;  for  Augustine  lays  it  down  as  the  object  of  the 
institution  of  preaching,  that  those  who  have  this  gift 
may  be  instructed  as  to  the  application  of  it — "  ut  qui 
haberent  donum  obedientia,  quibus  jussis  obediendum  esset 
audirent"  l 

There  is  another  evidence  of  the  sense  in  which 
Augustine  uses  the  term  gift,  as  applied  to  a  holy  life 
and  conduct,  in  an  argument  in  constant  use  with  him, 
drawn  from  the  fact  of  prayer.  We  pray,  he  says,  not  only 
for  external  good  things,  but  for  spiritual  dispositions  and 
habits ;  for  virtue,  holiness,  obedience,  both  for  ourselves 
and  others.  But  a  request  implies  that  we  suppose  the 
thing  asked  for  to  be  in  the  gift  of  him  from  whom  we 
ask  it,  and  that  he  is  able  to  bestow  it  or  not,  according 
to  his  will  and  pleasure,  otherwise  there  is  no  reason  to 
account  for  our  asking.  If  we  ask  God  for  holiness  then, 
and  obedience,  it  follows  that  we  suppose  holiness  and 
obedience  to  be  properly  in  His  gift.2  "  If  God  so  prepared 
and  worked  a  good  will  in  a  man  as  only  to  apply  His  law 
and  teaching  to  his  freewill,  and  did  not  by  a  deep  and 


1  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  xix. 

2  "  Frequentationibus  autem  oratio- 
num   simpliciter   apparebat  Dei  gratia 
quid  valeret :   non  enim  poscerentur  de 
Deo   quas   praecipit  fieri,    nisi   ab    illo 
donarentur,    ut   fierent."  —  De   Prasd. 
Sanct.  c.  xiv. 

"  Si  alia  documenta  non  essent,  do- 
minica  oratio  nobis  ad  causam  gratia? 
quam  dcfendimus  sola  sufficerct.  Si- 


quidem  ut  non  discedamus  a  Deo  non 
ostendit  dandum  esse  nisi  a  Deo,  cum 
poscendum  ostendit  a  Deo.  Qui  enim 
non  infertur  in  tentationem  non  disce- 
dit  a  Deo." 

"  Ecclesia  orat  ut  increduli  credant. 
Deus  ergo  convertit  ad  fidem.  Orat  ut 
credentes  perseverent :  Deus  ergo  dat 
perseverantiam  in  finem." — De  Dono 
Pers.  c.  vii. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE  OF   GRACE.  177 

occult  vocation  so  act  upon  his  mind,  that  he  complied 
with  that  law  and  teaching,  beyond  a  doubt  it  would  be 
enough  to  expound  and  preach  to  that  man,  and  there 
would  be  no  necessity  to  pray  that  God  would  convert  him 
or  give  him  perseverance  when  converted.  If  these  things 
are  to  be  prayed  for  then,  and  you  cannot  deny  that  they 
are  to  be,  what  remains,  but  that  you  confess  that  these 
things  are  gifts  ?  for  you  must  ask  God  for  what  He 
gives." l 

It  is  evident  that  this  argument  defines  an  absolute  gift  of 
holiness  and  obedience,  for  the  force  of  the  argument  lies  in 
pushing  the  act  of  prayer  to  its  extreme  consequences ;  and 
this  is  the  logical  consequence  of  prayer,  as  a  request  for 
holiness  and  obedience  from  God.  It  is  undoubtedly  of  the 
very  nature  of  prayer  to  suppose  the  subject  of  its  request  to 
be  simply  in  God's  gift ;  so  far  as  a  thing  is  not  in  God's 
power  to  give,  so  far  it  is  not  the  subject  of  prayer.  If  the 
act  of  prayer,  then,  in  the  case  of  asking  for  goodness  from 
God,  is  to  be  pushed  to  its  logical  consequences,  it  must 
follow  from  it  that  goodness  is  God's  absolute  gift.  Upon 
the  doctrine  of  freewill,  when  the  act  of  prayer  extends  to 
such  requests  as  these,  it  is  understood  in  such  a  sense  as  to 
forestall  this  consequence  of  it;  but  Augustine  embraces 
himself,  and  presses  upon  others  the  extreme  consequences 
of  prayer. 

He  adds  that  which  is  necessary  to  make  this  view  a  con- 
sistent one,  that  prayer  itself  also  is  the  gift  of  God;  for 
it  would  be  evidently  inconsistent  to  make  other  spiritual 
habits  the  gift  of  God,  if  that  habit  which  was  a  means  to 
those  was  not  a  gift  of  God  too.2 

Another  convincing  proof  of  the  sense  in  which  Au- 
gustine uses  the  terms  gift  and  creation,  as  applied  to  a 
holy  life,  is  his  express  connection  of  this  gift  with  pre- 


1  Ep.  217.  ad  Vitalem.  n.  5.    |      2  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  xxiii. ;  Ep.  194.  c.  iv. 

N 


178  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

destination,  and  the  referring  of  it  to  God's  secret  and 
mysterious  will.  Had  he  simply  meant  by  these  terms  that 
God  crowned  man's  own  endeavours,  and  gave  the  increase 
if  man  make  a  beginning,  such  a  doctrine  would  have 
approved  itself  naturally  to  our  sense  of  justice,  and  would 
not  have  needed  any  reference  to  mystery  for  its  defence. 
But  Augustine  bases  this  gift  of  holiness  and  obedience  upon 
mystery.  "  Deaf  as  thou  art,  hear  the  apostle  thanking  God 
that  they  have  obeyed  the  doctrine  from  the  heart;  not 
that  they  have  heard  the  doctrine  preached,  but  that  they 
have  obeyed  it.  For  all  have  not  obeyed  the  Gospel,  but 
those  to  whom  it  is  given  to  obey ;  just  as  to  know  the 
mysteries  of  the  kingdom  of  God  is  given  to  some,  but  to 
others  is  not  given."  l  .  .  .  . 

Again :  "As  begun  and  as  perfected,  faith  is  alike  the 
gift  of  God ;  and  that  this  gift  is  given  to  some  and  not 
to  others  cannot  be  doubted  without  opposing  the  plainest 
declarations  of  Scripture.  Nor  should  this  disturb  any 
believer  who  knows  that  from  one  man  all  went  into  justest 
condemnation ;  so  that,  were  none  rescued,  God  could  not 
be  blamed,  the  real  deserts  even  of  those  who  are  rescued 
being  the  same  with  those  of  the  damned.  It  belongs  to 
God's  unsearchable  judgments,  and  His  ways  past  finding  out, 
why  He  rescues  one  man  and  not  another.  O  man,  who  art 
thou  that  repliest  against  God?  Bow  to  the  rebuke,  rather 
than  speak  as  if  thou  knowest  that  which  God  who  wills 
nothing  unjust  has  yet  willed  to  be  secret."  2  Again :  "  God 
converts  to  faith.  God  gives  perseverance.  God  fore- 
knew that  He  would  do  this.  This  is  the  predestination  of 
the  saints  whom  He  elected  in  Christ  before  the  founda- 
tion of  the  world,  that  they  should  be  holy  and  with- 
out blame  before  Him  in  love,  having  predestinated  us 
unto  the  adoption  of  children  by  Christ  Jesus  to  Himself, 


Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  230.  |  2  De  Praed.  c.  viii. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  179 

according  to  the  good  pleasure  of  His  will ;  in  whom  we 
have  obtained  an  inheritance,  being  predestinated  according 
to  the  purpose  of  Him  who  worketh  all  things  after  the 

counsel  of  His  own  will But  why  is  not  the  grace 

of  God  given  according  to  merit  ?  I  reply,  because  God  is 
merciful.  And  why  is  He  not  merciful  to  all  ?  I  reply, 
because  He  is  just.  His  justice  on  some  shows  how  freely 
His  grace  is  given  to  others.  Let  us  not  then  be  ungrate* 
ful,  because  according  to  the  pleasure  of  His  will,  and  the 
praise  of  His  glory,  the  merciful  God  frees  so  many  from 
a  just  perdition  when  He  would  not  be  unjust  if  He 
freed  nobody.  From  one  man  have  all  gone,  not  into  any 
unjust  condemnation,  but  a  just  one.  Whoever  is  freed 
then,  let  him  love  the  grace ;  whoever  is  not  freed,  let  him 
acknowledge  the  justice.  God's  goodness  is  seen  in  remitting, 
His  equity  in  exacting,  His  injustice  in  nothing."  l  Again  on 
the  text  "  It  is  He  that  made  us  and  not  we  ourselves." 
"  He  therefore  makes  sheep  — facit  oves.  .  .Why  dost  thou 
cast  freewill  in  my  teeth,  which  will  not  free  for  righteous- 
ness except  thou  be  a  sheep  ?  He  it  is  who  makes  men  sheep, 
who  frees  human  wills  for  works  of  piety.  But  why,  when 
there  is  with  Him  no  respect  of  persons,  He  makes  some  men 
sheep,  and  not  others,  is,  according  to  the  Apostle,  a  question 
more  curious  than  becoming.  O  man!  who  art  thou  that 
repliest  against  God  ?  Shall  the  thing  formed  say  to  Him 
that  formed  it,  why  hast  Thou  made  me  thus  ?  This  ques- 
tion belongs  to  that  abyss  from  which  the  Apostle  shrank 
with  dread,  exclaiming,  « O  the  depth  of  the  riches  both 
of  the  wisdom  and  knowledge  of  God ! '  .  .  .  Why  this 
man  receives,  and  that  man  does  not  receive,  when  neither 
deserves  to  receive,  measuring  thy  strength,  examine  not; 
enough  that  we  know  that  there  is  no  iniquity  with  God.  .  . 
The  vessels  of  mercy  understand  how  entirely  in  their  own 


1  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  vii.  viii. 
N    2 


180  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

case  mercy  is  gratuitous,  when  those,  with  whom  they  share 
one  common  lump  of  perdition,  receive  their  just  punish- 
ment."1 

In  these  passages  the  gift  of  obedience,  the  gift  of  faith, 
the  gift  of  perseverance,  the  creation  of  the  holy  and  good 
man,  or  sheep  as  he  is  called,  are  treated  as  the  effects  of 
the  Divine  predestination,  and  are  accounted  for  on  a  mys- 
terious principle.  It  is,  therefore,  a  proper  gift  and  creation 
of  which  he  is  speaking,  and  not  a  mere  crowning  of  human 
endeavours  after  holiness,  for  which  such  an  account  would 
be  both  superfluous  and  unsuitable.  For  there  could  be  no 
occasion  to  go  to  mystery  for  the  explanation  of  a  proceeding 
of  which  so  very  natural  and  intelligible  account  could  be 
given,  as  of  God's  giving  the  advancing  and  perfecting  grace 
in  proportion  as  man  exerts  his  own  faculties  and  will. 

To  sum  up  briefly,  then,  the  evidences,  as  far  as  we  have 
gone,  of  the  Augustinian  doctrine  of  grace;  there  is  first 
an  express  definition  of  the  nature  of  grace,  under  the 
Gospel  dispensation,  arrived  at  after  much  thought  and 
effort,  and  much  handling  and  discussing  of  the  subject ;  a 
definition  according  to  which  the  grace  of  the  Gospel  is  an 
assistance  productive  of  that  effect  upon  man's  life  and 
conduct  for  which  it  is  given  —  adjutorium  cum  quo  fit. 
And  this  definition  is  sustained  by  a  general  body  of  lan- 
guage describing  goodness  and  holiness  as  a  Divine  gift 
and  a  Divine  creation,  not  in  a  secondary  and  qualified 
but  a  natural  and  proper  sense  of  the  terms,  as  shown  by 
the  caution  annexed,  that  this  gift  is  not  given  according  to 
merit — L  e.  according  to  any  conditions  which  man  himself 
previously  fulfils ;  by  the  argument  from  prayer,  and  by  the 
express  referring  of  this  gift  and  this  creation  to  the  mystery 
of  the  Divine  predestination.  But  a  grace  which  is  always 
productive  of  the  effect  upon  life  and  conduct  for  which 


1  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  Pel.  1.  4.  c.  6. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  181 

it  is  given  —  a  grace  which  gives  and  creates  goodness  ab- 
solutely is  an  effective  or  irresistible  grace. 

This  rationale  is,  then,  confirmed  by  examples  from  Scrip- 
ture. "  I  wish,"  says  S.  Augustine  to  the  Pelagian  who 
accounted  for  change  of  heart  from  bad  to  good  by  self- 
discipline  and  self-mortification  on  the  part  of  man,  which 
Divine  grace  seconded,  "  I  wish  you  would  tell  me  whether 
that  Assyrian  king  whose  bed  the  holy  Esther  abhorred, 
when  he  sat  on  the  throne  of  his  kingdom,  clad  in  glorious 
apparel,  and  covered  with  gold  and  precious  stones,  and  was 
very  dreadful,  and  looked  at  her  with  a  countenance  inflamed 
with  indignation,  so  that  the  queen  fainted  with  fear, — 
whether  that  king  had  already  f  run  to  the  Lord,  and  desired 
to  be  led  by  Him,  and  suspended  his  will  upon  His  will,  and 
by  cleaving  constantly  to  Him  had  been  made  one  spirit 
with  Him '  (he  quotes  the  Pelagian  statement),  ( by  the  power 
of  his  freewill ;  whether  he  had  given  himself  up  to  God,  and 
mortified  all  his  will,  and  put  his  heart  in  God's  hand.'  It 
would  be  madness  to  think  so  ;  and  yet  God  converted  him, 
and  changed  his  fury  to  mildness.  But  who  does  not  see 
that  it  is  a  much  greater  thing  to  convert  an  opposite  indig- 
nation into  mildness,  than  to  convert  a  heart  pre-occupied 
with  neither  the  one  nor  the  other  affection,  but  midway 
between  the  two?  Read  then,  and  understand,  behold  and 
confess,  that  not  by  law  and  teaching  from  without,  but  by  a 
marvellous  and  ineffable  power  within,  God  produces  in  the 
hearts  of  men,  not  only  true  revelations>  but  also  good 
wills."1 

The  particular  conclusion  from  this  passage  is,  that,  in  the 
change  from  a  bad  to  a  good  state  of  mind  in  the  case  of 
Ahasuerus,  Divine  grace  could  not  have  waited  for  any 
motive  of  the  will ;  his  will  having  been  up  to  the  very 
instant  of  that  effect  taking  place  violently  opposed  to  such 


1  DC  Gratia  Christi,  n.  25. 
N   3 


182  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

a  change ;  the  general  one  is,  that  if  grace  alone  turned  the 
raging  and  hostile  will  of  that  monarch,  it  can  certainly  do 
the  same  with  other  wills  in  a  more  neutral  state. 

The  conversion  of  S.  Paul  is  appealed  to  as  another  in- 
stance of  the  operation  of  such  a  grace.  "  I  pardon  you," 
he  says  to  his  Pelagian  opponent  Julian,  "  that  on  a  very 
deep  matter  you  are  mistaken,  as  a  man  may  be — ignoscendum 
est  quia  in  re  in  multum  abditd,  ut  homo  fallens.  God  for- 
bid that  the  intention  of  the  omnipotent  and  all-foreseeing 
One  should  be  frustrated  by  man.  Little  do  they  think 
about,  or  small  power  have  they  of  thinking  out  a  weighty 
matter,  who  suppose  that  God  omnipotent  wills  anything, 

and  through  weak  man's  resistance  cannot  do  it If,  as 

you  say,  men  are  not  recalled  by  any  necessity  from  their 
own  evil  intentions,  how  was  the  Apostle  Paul,  yet  Saul, 
breathing  slaughter  and  thirsting  for  blood,  recalled  from 
his  most  wicked  intention  by  the  stroke  of  blindness  and 
the  terrible  voice  from  heaven,  and  from  the  prostrate  per- 
secutor, raised  to  be  a  preacher  and  the  most  laborious  one 
of  all?  Acknowledge  the  work  of  grace.  But  God  calls 
one  man  in  this  way,  and  another  in  that,  whomever  He 
prefers  to  call,  and  the  wind  bloweth  where  it  listeth."  * 
That  is,  acknowledge  the  work  of  God,  not  only  in  this 
particular  instance,  but  in  all  cases  of  conversion  from  a 
wicked  to  a  holy  life.  The  operation  of  a  grace  absolutely 
determining  the  will  of  man  comes,  as  it  were,  visibly  before 
us,  as  in  the  case  of  S.  Paul.  But  God  calls  one  man  in  this 
way,  and  another  in  that  —  alium  sic,  alium  autem  sic.  Be- 
cause He  does  not  call  all  those  whom  He  calls  in  the  same 
striking  and  visible  manner  in  which  He  called  S.  Paul, 
do  not  infer  any  difference  of  principle  upon  which  His  calls 
are  conducted ;  for  the  laws  of  God's  spiritual  dealings  are 
uniform,  and  He  makes  one  saint  in  the  same  way  funda- 


1  Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  93. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTEINE   OF   GRACE.  183 

mentally  in  which  He  makes  another.  In  the  gentlest  and 
most  gradual  conversions,  then,  acknowledge  the  operation  of 
the  same  power  which  operates  in  that  of  S.  Paul. 

S.  Peter  is  brought  forward  as  another  instance  of  the 
operation  of  such  a  grace  upon  the  will ;  or  of  grace  alone  and 
by  itself  determining  it  or  causing  the  particular  will  of  the 
man  to  be  the  will  which  it  is.  "  What  will  you  oppose  to 
the  text  '  I  have  prayed  for  thee,  Peter,  that  thy  faith  fail 
not  ? ' 1  Will  you  dare  to  say,  that  even  the  prayer  of 
Christ  could  not  have  procured  indefectible  faith  for  Peter, 
had  Peter  wished  that  it  should  fail ;  that  is,  had  been  unwill- 
ing to  persevere  ?  As  if  Peter  could  possibly  will  anything 
else  but  what  Christ  had  prayed  that  he  should  will !  True, 
indeed,  Peter's  faith  would  have  failed,  if  Peter's  will  to  be 
faithful  had  failed.  But  the  will  is  prepared  by  the  Lord, 
and  therefore  Christ's  prayer  for  him  could  not  be  ineffec- 
tual." 2  This  passage  is  clear.  Peter's  faith  would  have 
failed  if  Peter's  will  had ;  but  Peter's  will  would  not  be  any- 
thing else  but  what  God  had  determined  it  to  be,  and  God 
had  determined  that  it  should  be  faithful. 

It  remains  now  to  inquire  whether  anything  is  said  of 
the  nature  or  quality  of  this  grace  in  itself — itself,  I  mean, 
as  distinguished  from  its  effects,  by  which  alone  it  has 
hitherto  been  described.  And  to  this  question  the  answer 
is,  that  Augustine  identifies  this  grace  with  the  disposition 
of  love. 

Christian  love  is  a  general  affection  toward  God  and 
man,  productive  of  all  the  virtues  and  the  whole  of  obedience. 
"  Love  is  the  fulfilling  of  the  law." 3  "  If  we  love  one  another, 
God  dvvelleth  in  us  and  His  love  is  perfected  in  us."4  But 
this  love  is,  according  to  the  doctrine  of  freewill,  a  result, 
an  ultimate  habit,  gained  by  the  endeavours  of  the  man 
himself  assisted  by  Divine  grace.  But  in  the  system  of 


1  Luke,  xxii.  32.  «  Rom.  xiii.  10. 

2  De  Corr.  et  Grat,  c.  viii.  «  1  John,  iv.  12. 


N    4 


184  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI- 

Augustine  it  appears  as  a  primary  disposition  imparted 
to  the  soul  by  an  act  of  free  grace ;  not  the  reward  and 
effect  of,  but  a  gift  preceding  and  producing,  a  good  course 
of  life.  That  which  is  the  infallible  root  of  general  obedience 
is  implanted  in  the  man  at  the  outset.  The  grace  of  love 
is  infused  into  his  heart.  In  consequence  of  the  indwelling 
of  this  gift,  he  cannot  but  take  pleasure  in  God's  law, 
obeying  it  not  out  of  servile  fear  and  in  the  spirit  of 
bondage,  but  in  the  freedom  of  a  renewed  and  converted 
inclination.  The  gift  of  love  makes  that  sweet  to  him 
which  before  was  difficult,  nay  impossible.  Not  that  those 
who  have  the  gift  enjoy  the  full  virtue  of  it  all  at  once, 
and  immediately  find  a  holy  life  pleasant  to  them  ;  but  in 
proportion  as  the  virtue  of  it  comes  out,  they  do  find  this 
result ;  and  the  gift  ultimately,  by  means  of  this  power  in- 
herent in  it  of  accommodating  the  human  will  to  the  Divine, 
inclination  to  law,  does  produce  a  saving  and  acceptable 
obedience. 

Thus,  in  a  passage  which  has  been  quoted,  Augustine  lays 
down  one  root  of  good  men,  viz.  love,  and  another  root  of 
evil  men,  viz.  cupidity ;  adding,  "  The  virtue  of  love  is  from 
God,  and  not  from  ourselves,  for  Scripture  says,  cLove  is 
God,  and  every  one  that  loveth  is  born  of  God  and  knoweth 
God ; '  and  '  Whosoever  is  born  of  God  doth  not  commit  sin,' 
and  that  because  ( he  cannot  sin.'  Nor  have  our  preceding 
merits  caused  this  love  to  be  given  us ;  for  what  good  merits 
were  we  able  to  have  at  the  time  when  we  did  not  love 
God?  That  we  might  have  that  love,  we  were  loved 
before  we  had  it ;  as  the  Apostle  John  saitb,  '  Not  that 
we  loved  God,  but  that  He  loved  us,'  and,  '  We  love  Him 
because  He  first  loved  us.'  For  what  good  could  we  do 
if  we  did  not  love,  or,  how  can  we  not  do  good  if  we  do 
love?1'1 

Here  love,  which   is   described   as   a  necessary   root   of 


De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  xxi.  et  seq. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  185 

good  action,  or  involving  a  good  life  in  the  individual  who 
has  it,  is  also  made  an  original  and  primary  gift  of  God 
to  man.  "  Who  hath  it  in  his  power  to  secure,  either  that 
something  delighting  should  come  across  him,  or  that  it 
should  delight  him  when  it  does  ?  When  a  holy  life  delights 
us  then,  this  delight  is  inspired  and  given  by  the  grace  of 
God,  and  not  gained  by  our  own  will,  or  endeavours,  or 
works  ;  this  very  will,  these  very  endeavours,  and  these  very 
works,  being  His  gifts. " l 

Again :  "  When  we  ask  assistance   from    Him   to   work 
righteousness,  what  ask  we  but  that  He  should  open  what 

was  hid,    and  make  sweet  what  was  unpleasant? 

There  precedes  in  the  will  of  man  a  certain  appetite  for  its 
own  power,  so  that  it  becomes  disobedient  through  pride. 
Were  this  appetite  away,  nothing  would  be  difficult,  and  man, 
as  he  now  seeks  his  own  will,  would  quite  as  easily  not  have 
sought  it.  But  there  has  come  upon  him,  as  a  just  punish- 
ment, such  a  corruption  of  nature,  that  it  is  now  disagreeable 
to  him  to  obey  the  Divine  law.  And  unless  this  corruption 
is  overcome  by  assisting  grace,  no  one  is  converted  to 
obedience :  unless  healed  by  the  operation  of  grace,  no  one 
enjoys  the  peace  of  obedience.  But  by  whose  grace  is  he 
conquered  and  healed,  but  by  His  to  whom  it  is  said,  '  Turn 
us,  then,  O  God  our  Saviour,  and  let  Thine  anger  cease  from 
us?'  which,  if  He  does  to  any,  He  does  to  them  in  mercy ; 
while  to  those  to  whom  He  does  it  not  He  does  it  not  in 
judgment.  And  who  shall  say  to  Him  (whose  mercy  and 
judgment  all  pious  minds  celebrate),  what  doest  Thou? 
Wherefore  even  His  saints  and  faithful  servants  He  heals 
slowly  in  some  faults,  so  that  good  delights  them  less  than  is 
sufficient  for  fulfilling  the  whole  law ;  in  order  that,  tried  by 
the  perfect  rule  of  His  truth,  no  flesh  may  be  justified  in 
His  sight.  Nor  is  such  imperfection  intended  for  our  con- 


De  Div.  Quaest.  ad  Simpl.  1.  1.  n.  21. 


186  AUGUSTINIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

demnation,  but  only  our  humbling,  and  to  remind  us  of  our 
dependence  on  this  same  grace ;  lest,  attaining  facility  in 
everything,  we  think  that  our  own  which  is  His.  .  .  .  Let 
us  be  wise,  and  understand  that  God  sometimes  does  not 
give  even  to  his  saints,  with  respect  to  any  work,  either 
a  certain  knowledge,  or  a  victorious  delight  —  victricem  delec- 
tationem — in  order  that  they  may  know  that  not  from 
themselves  but  from  Him  is  that  light  by  which  their  dark- 
ness is  illuminated,  and  that  sweetness  by  which  their  land 
yields  her  fruit." l 

Love,  which  he  calls  delight  and  sweetness,  is  de- 
scribed in  this  passage  as  a  "  conquering  "  or  irresistible 
grace ;  upon  the  bestowal  of  which  certain  effects  of  life 
and  conduct  follow  naturally,  though  not  always  in  a  full 
measure,  but  only  in  proportion  to  the  amount  imparted 
of  the  gift  itself.  And  being  such  a  gift,  it  is  described 
as  a  free  gift ;  not  half  given  by  God,  half  attained  by 
man,  or  given  in  proportion  to  our  natural  striving  after 
it.  For  why  it  is  given  to  one  more  than  another  he 
treats  as  a  mystery,  or  a  question  belonging  to  the  secret 
counsels  of  God ;  whereas,  on  the  latter  supposition  there 
would  have  been  no  difficulty  to  account  for.  Moreover, 
the  gift  is  described  throughout  as  preceding  and  producing 
action,  and  not  following  it. 

Again :  "  The  appetite  for  good  is  from  God ;  the  most 
high,  unchangeable  good ;  which  appetite  is  love,  of  which 
John  saith,  'Love  is  of  God.'  Not  that  its  beginning 
is  of  us,  and  its  perfecting  of  God,  but  that  the  whole  of 
love  is  from  God.  Fof  God  avert  such  madness  as  to  make 
ourselves  prior  in  His  gifts  and  Him  posterior ;  seeing,  it 
is  said,  '  Thou  preventest  him  with  the  blessings  of  sweet- 
ness.' For  what  can  be  meant  here  but  that  appetite  for 
good  of  which  we  speak.  For  good  begins  to  be  desired 


1  De  Pecc.  Mer.  et  Rem.  1.  2.  c.  xix. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  187 

as  soon  as  it  begins  to  be  sweet.  But  when  good  is  done 
through  fear  of  punishment,  and  not  through  love,  good  is 
not  done  well.  It  is  done  in  the  act,  but  not  in  the  heart, 
when  a  man  would  not  do  it  if  he  could  refuse  with  im- 
punity. The  blessing  of  sweetness  is  therefore  given  as 
a  grace  whereby  that  which  is  commanded  delights  us,  and 
is  desired  and  loved." l  Again :  (e  If  grace  co-operates  with 
a  previously  existing  good  will,  and  does  not  prevent  and 
produce  that  will,  how  is  it  truly  said  that  '  God  worketh 
in  us  to  will,'  and  that  the  will  is  prepared  by  the  Lord 
and  that  (  Love  is  of  God,'  love  which  alone  wills  beatific 
good  ?  " 2  Again :  "  When  the  love  of  God  is  shed  abroad 
in  our  hearts,  not  that  love  is  meant  with  which  He  loves 
us,  but  that  love  by  which  He  makes  us  lovers  of  Him ; 
as  the  righteousness  of  God  is  that  by  which  He  makes 
us  righteous  of  free  grace,  and  the  salvation  of  God  that 
by  which  He  saves  us,  and  the  faith  of  Jesus  Christ 
that  by  which  He  makes  us  believers."3  Again:  "God 
alone  gives  love ;  for  '  love  is  of  God.'  This  you  will  not 
reckon  among  your  assistances  of  grace,  lest  you  should 
concede  the  truth,  that  the  very  act  of  obedience  is  of 
that  grace." 4  Again :  •*  Thou  mentionest  many  things  by 
which  God  assists  us,  viz.  by  commanding,  blessing,  sancti- 
fying, coercing,  exciting,  illuminating;  and  then  mentionest 
not,  by  giving  love  ;  whereas  John  saith  « Love  is  of  God,' 
and  adds,  'Behold  what  manner  of  love  the  Father  hath 
bestowed  on  us,  that  we  should  be  called  the  sons  of  God.' "  5 
Again :  "  If  among  the  kinds  of  grace  you  refer  to  you 
would  place  love,  which  the  Scriptures  most  plainly  declare 
to  be  not  from  ourselves  but  from  God,  and  to  be  a  gift  of 
God  to  His  own  sons,  that  love  without  which  no  one  lives 
piously,  and  with  which  a  man  cannot  but  live  piously  ;  with- 


1  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  2.  c.  viii. 

2  Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  95. 

«  De  Spirit  et  Lit.  c.  xxxii. 


4  Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  114. 
8  Ibid.  1.  3.  c.  106. 


188  AUGUSTOIAN  [CHAP.  VI. 

out  which  no  one  has  a  good  will,  and  with  which  a  man 
cannot  but  have  a  good  will,  you  would  then  define  a  true 
freewill,  and  not  inflate  a  false  one."  l 

Throughout  these  passages  the  gift  of  love  is  described 
as  a  disposition  of  mind  necessarily  productive  of  holy 
action,  and  at  the  same  time  it  is  described  as  the  gift 
of  God  without  any  qualification,  of  the  simple  and  natural 
sense  of  that  term.  f  And,  lastly,  this  gift  is  identified  ex- 
pressly with  efficacious  or  irresistible  grace,  as  that  grace  was 
formally  defined  above ;  it  being  described  as  a  gift fe  with 
which  a  man  cannot  but  live  piously  —  cum  qua  nemo  nisi  pie 
vivit"  which  is  a  repetition  of  the  language  above — "  ad~ 
jutorium  cum  quo  aliquid  fit ;  donum  per  quod  non  nisi  per- 
severantes  sunt."  2 

Having  thus  shown,  what  it  was  the  object  of  this 
chapter  to  show,  that  Augustine  held  the  doctrine  of 
efficacious  or  irresistible  grace,  I  shall  conclude  with  two 
observations. 

It  is  evident,  then,  in  the  first  place,  that  this  doc- 
trine is  no  more  than  a  supplemental  one  to  the  doctrine 
of  predestination  described  in  the  preceding  chapter.  If 
there  be  a  Divine  decree  predestinating  from  all  eternity 
antecedently  to  any  acts  of  their  own  certain  individuals 
of  the  human  race  to  everlasting  life,  there  must  be  an 
instrument  for  putting  this  decree  into  effect.  The  grace 
of  which  the  discussion  has  occupied  this  chapter  is  this 
instrument.  It  imparts  absolutely  to  the  predestinated 
persons  those  acts  and  dispositions  which  are  the  conditions 
of  this  final  reward.  The  Divine  decree,  in  ensuring  this 
end  to  certain  persons,  ensures  them  the  means  to  it ;  but 
piety  and  virtue  are  the  necessary  means  for  attaining 
this  end;  this  decree  therefore  necessarily  involves,  as  its 
supplement,  a  grace  which  ensures  the  possession  of  piety 
and  virtue, 

V  Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  122.  |  2  Pp.  163.  165. 


CHAP.  VI.]  DOCTRINE   OF   GRACE.  189 

In  the  next  place  I  will  guard  the  reader  against  a 
mistake  which  is  not  unlikely  to  arise  with  respect  to 
this  doctrine.  For  it  may  be  asked  whether  the  assertion 
of  an  efficacious  or  irresistible  grace  involves  more  than 
maintaining  that  there  is  such  a  grace  which  God  chooses 
to  give  to  certain  select  and  privileged  persons,  without 
maintaining  that  it  is  the  only  grace  by  which  holiness 
and  salvation  can  be  obtained  ?  Whether  it  cannot  be 
held  that  God  gives  an  irresistible  grace  to  some,  and  also 
gives  a  sufficient  grace  to  the  rest?  Whether  the  higher 
gift  to  a  select  number,  which  ensures  holiness,  is  not  com- 
patible with  the  lower  one  to  the  rest,  which  gives  them 
the  power  to  attain  it  ? 

But,  indeed,  if  we  consider  the  matter,  such  a  question 
as  this  will  be  seen  to  proceed  from  a  confusion  of  thought 
on  this  subject.     For  upon  what  ground  does  any  one  hold 
that  there  is  this  irresistible  grace,  except  on  the  ground 
that  human  nature  needs  it,  and  cannot  do  without  it  ?  but 
if  human  nature  cannot  do  without  it,  nothing  short  of  it 
is  sufficient.     This  is  the  ground  on  which  Augustine  raises 
the  doctrine,  and  on  which  all  who  do  maintain  it  do  maintain 
it.     Indeed,  on  what  other  ground  can  it  be  seriously  main- 
tained ?     For  whether  or  not  it  might  attach  as  a  superfluity 
to  a  nature  able  to  do  without  it,  its  existence  could  not 
be  other  than  a  mere  conjecture  in  such  a  case.     For  as- 
serting its  existence  there  must  be  an  adequate  reason  given  ; 
and  what  adequate   reason  can   be  pretended,  except  that 
which  is  given,  viz.  that  it  is  necessary  ?     Were  this  grace, 
then,   maintained  as  a  superfluity,  there  might  consistently 
be  maintained  together  with  it  another  grace  short  of  it,  and 
only  sufficient ;  but  it  is  maintained  as  remedial  to  a  fatal 
disease,  as  supplemental  to  an  absolute  want.     The  first  dis- 
pensation did  not  provide  it  because  man  could  do  without 
it ;  the  second  provides  it  because  he  cannot.     If  an  irre- 
sistible grace  then  is  maintained  at  all,  it  cannot  be  main- 
tained as  a  grace  along  with  the  other  or  merely  assisting 


190 


DOCTRINE  OF   GRACE. 


[CHAP.  VI. 


one,  but  must  be  maintained  as  the  grace  of  the  Gospel 
dispensation,  —  the  grace  by  the  operation  of  which  all  the 
goodness  and  holiness  there  is  in  men  arises.  To  endeavour, 
then,  to  combine  it  in  one  system  with  the  other  would  be  to 
treat  it  apart  from  and  in  opposition  to  the  very  ground 
on  which  we  suppose  it  to  exist.  The  doctrine  of  an 
absolute  predestination  cannot  combine  with  any  other 
account  of  the  origin  of  human  goodness ;  it  must  either  be 
denied  altogether,  or  applied  to  the  whole.  An  antecedent 
moral  inability  in  the  whole  human  mass  is  the  very  occa- 
sion of  that  decree,  which  is  made  for  no  other  reason  than 
to  provide  a  remedy  for  it.  It  follows,  that  while  those 
who  are  affected  by  its  remedial  provisions  are  endowed 
with  that  certainty  of  attaining  to  holiness  which  they 
impart ;  those  whom  the  decree  does  not  affect  remain  in 
their  original  inability ;  and  therefore,  that,  besides  those 
who  have  an  irresistible  grace,  there  are  none  who  have 
sufficient.1 


1  Bishop  Overall  appears  to  have  fallen 
into  the  error  of  endeavouring  to  com- 
bine  irresistible  grace  to  some  with  suf- 
ficient grace  to  all :  "  These  two  things 
agree  very  well  together,  that  God,  in 
the  first  place,  proposed  salvation  in 
Christ  to  all,  if  they  believed,  and  com- 
mon and  sufficient  grace  in  the  means 
divinely  ordained,  if  men  were  not 
wanting  to  the  Word  of  God  and  to  the 
Holy  Spirit :  then,  secondly,  that  He 
might  help  human  infirmity,  and  that 


the  salvation  of  men  might  be  more 
certain,  that  He  thought  good  to  add  a 
special  grace,  more  efficacious  and 
abundant,  to  be  communicated  to  whom 
He  pleased,  by  which  they  might  not 
only  be  able  to  believe  and  obey,  if  so 
inclined,  but  also  actually  be  inclined, 
believe,  obey,  and  persevere." — Overall 
on  the  Quinquarticular  Controversy, 
quoted  by  Mr.  Goode,  "  Effects  of 
Infant  Baptism,"  p.  129. 


191 


CHAP.  VII. 

AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE    OF    FINAL   PERSEVERANCE. 

IN  the  preceding  chapter  it  has  been  shown  that  the  grace 
of  the  Gospel  dispensation  is,  according  to  the  doctrine 
of  S.  Augustine,  an  efficacious  and  irresistible  one.  But 
the  question  still  remains  in  what  measure  this  grace  is 
given,  how  much  of  it  is  required  for  accomplishing  the 
object  for  which  it  is  designed,  viz.  the  individual's  salvation. 
Must  it  be  given  to  him  in  perfect  fulness,  i.e.  every 
moment  and  act  of  his  life  without  exception  ?  Or  is  a  less 
measure  of  it  sufficient  ?  and  if  so,  what  is  that  measure  ? 

The  answer  to  this  question  is,  that  the  measure  of  this 
grace  which  is  required  for  salvation  is  the  same  as  the 
measure,  whatever  it  may  be,  of  goodness  and  holiness  which 
is  required.  As  this  grace  is  the  efficacious  cause  of  good- 
ness, exactly  as  much  is  wanted  of  the  cause  as  is  wanted 
of  the  effect.  And  to  ask  this  question  is  exactly  the  same 
as  to  ask,  how  much  goodness  is  required  for  salvation. 

If  the  question,  then,  be  asked,  how  much  goodness  is 
required  for  salvation?  while  it  is  plain  that  no  definite 
amount  can  be  fixed  upon  in  answer,  a  certain  indefinite  one 
can  be.  Disobedience  and  sin  for  an  indefinite  portion  of 
life  are  not  incompatible  with  it;  but  a  man  must  on  the 
whole  have  manifested  a  good  character.  And  if  it  be  asked, 
further,  what  constitutes  such  a  manifestation,  and  what  is 
the  test  of  goodness  on  the  whole  ?  the  answer  is,  the  end 
of  life — that  which  the  man  is  at  the  close  of  the  state  of 
probation  in  which  he  has  been  placed. 

The  amount  of  efficacious  grace,  then,  which  is  required 
in  order  to  salvation,  is  that  which  produces  this  final  state 
of  goodness,  i.e.  the  grace  of  final  perseverance.  And 


192  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VII. 

therefore  I  shall  endeavour,  in  this  chapter,  to  explain  the 
doctrine  of  final  perseverance ;  first  as  a  test,  and  secondly 
as  a  grace. 

I.  It  will  be  evident,  on  slight  consideration,  that  the  doc- 
trine of  final  perseverance,  so  far  as  that  doctrine  is  simply 
the  adoption  of  a  particular  test  of  an  acceptable  and  saving 
obedience,  is  no  predestinarian  one,  but  simply  one  of 
morals  and  religion.  Some  test  is  wanted  of  what  con- 
stitutes in  the  individual  goodness  on  the  whole  ;  and  this 
doctrine  supplies  a  test,  viz.  the  character  of  the  individual 
at  the  end  of  life.  The  doctrine  does  not,  indeed,  in  form 
adopt  the  end  of  life,  but  continuance  up  to  the  end,  as 
this  test.  But  it  is  evident  that  in  continuance  up  to  the 
end,  nothing  is  ruled  as  to  when  that  course  of  goodness 
which  is  to  be  thus  continued  is  to  begin.  The  literal  and 
absolute  end  of  life  is,  indeed,  excluded  as  such  a  point  of 
commencement ;  for  there  cannot  be  continuance  up  to  the 
end  if  the  end  takes  place  immediately.  But,  interpreting 
the  end  of  life  liberally,  it  is  left  open  in  this  test  whether 
such  goodness  commences  at  the  beginning  of  life,  or  at 
the  middle,  or  at  the  end.  And  though  an  obedience 
which  continues  up  to  the  end  is  doubtless  more  valuable 
if  it  commenced  at  the  beginning  of  life  than  if  it  com- 
menced at  the  middle,  and  if  it  commenced  at  the  middle 
of  life  than  if  it  commenced  at  the  end,  still  so  long  as  it 
begins  in*  sufficient  time  to  be  a  fair  and  substantial  con- 
tinuance in  goodness,  it  fulfils  the  requirements  of  the  test. 

The  principle,  then,  on  which  such  a  test  goes,  and  on 
which  it  recommends  itself  to  adoption,  is  the  obvious  and 
natural  one,  embodied  in  the  old  maxim  reAo?  cpa,  look 
to  the  end,  the  principle,  that  the  end  determines  the 
character  of  the  whole  to  which  it  belongs.  This  rule 
applied  to  the  case  of  man's  moral  character  leads  us  to 
decide,  that  if  he  ends  virtuously  he  is  on  the  whole  a  good 
man ;  or,  on  the  other  hand,  that  if  he  ends  immorally,  he  is 


CHAP.  VII.]  OF    FINAL    PERSEVERANCE.  193 

on  the  whole  a  bad  man.  Solon,  indeed,  applied  this  rule 
to  determine  the  question,  not  of  a  man's  moral  character, 
but  of  his  happiness  in  life ;  and  here  it  does  not  literally 
apply.  For  it  cannot  be  said  to  be  true,  that  the  happiness 
of  a  man's  life  does  depend  on  the  happiness  or  misery  of 
its  end  ;  because  happiness  being  a  thing  of  present  sensa- 
tion, if  the  sensation  has  been,  there  has  been  happiness. 
The  fact  has  already  taken  place,  then,  before  the  end 
comes ;  and  whatever  that  end  may  be,  it  cannot  cause  what 
has  taken  place  not  to  have.  A  man  therefore  who  has 
had  uninterrupted  happiness  up  to  the  end  of  his  life,  but 
has  then  fallen  into  misfortune,  has  undoubtedly  had  more 
happiness  than  one  who  has  been  miserable  up  to  the  end 
of  his  life,  but  has  then  become  prosperous.  Solon's  asser- 
tion applies  properly  not  to  the  state  and  condition  of  the 
persons  themselves,  but  to  their  position  in  the  minds  of 
the  survivors ;  for  we  naturally  think  of  a  man  afterwards 
as  we  last  knew  him.  However  prosperous,  therefore,  a 
man  has  been  up  to  the  end,  if  at  the  end  he  falls,  then, 
inasmuch  as  that  is  the  last  we  saw  of  him,  and  he  dis- 
appeared from  that  time,  and  was  no  more  seen,  we  carry  his 
image  in  our  minds  connected  with  this  fall  and  adversity. 
If  the  melancholy  association  is  the  last  in  order,  it  cannot 
be  corrected,  but  is  fixed  and  unchanging  ;  and  the  same  is 
true  of  the  contrary  one.  It  was  a  natural  law  of  associa- 
tion, then,  which  the  philosopher  observed,  of  which  this 
was  the  result.  When  he  said  that  a  man's  happiness  in 
life  was  decided  by  its  end,  that  end  was  imagined  as  still 
going  on ;  it  was  not  the  real  termination  of  life  but  an 
ideal  continuation  of  it,  and,  as  being  ideal,  unending,  for 
we  can  always  summon  the  idea.  The  two  young  men 
who,  after  their  work  of  piety  in  drawing  their  sacred 
mother  to  the  temple,  fell  asleep  in  the  holy  precincts  and 
died,  enjoy  an  eternal  rest  in  our  minds.  Their  sweet  and 
blissful  repose  still  in  idea  goes  on.  And  so  the  other  who 
died  in  victory  fighting  for  his  country  enjoys  an  eternal 

o 


194  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VII. 

transport  in  our  minds.  The  image  of  repose,  and  the 
image  of  glory  stay  for  ever.  Such  an  ideal  end  of  life,  were 
it  real,  would  indeed  be  the  test  of  a  man's  happiness  in 
life ;  because  the  eternal  continuation  of  a  life  is  the  greater 
portion  of  it,  and  the  happiness  of  the  greater  portion  is 
the  happiness  of  the  life  as  a  whole.  But  the  literal  end  of 
life  is  no  such  test. 

But  a  test  which  is  deceptive  as  applied  to  the  estimation 
of  a  man's  happiness  is  true  as  applied  to  the  estimation  of 
his  goodness.  For  there  is  a  peculiarity  in  the  composition 
or  organisation  of  moral  character  which  makes  it  apply. 
It  might  appear,  indeed,  at  first  sight,  that  as  happiness  is 
present  sensation,  so  goodness  is  present  action ;  and  there- 
fore, that  if  any  portion,  large  or  small,  of  a  man's  life  has 
been  conducted  well,  there  has  been  so  much  goodness 
which  cannot  be  reversed,  whatever  state  of  sin  may  succeed 
it.  But  this  is  not  a  true  statement  of  the  case.  Present 
action  is  certainly  present  goodness,  goodness  for  the  time ; 
but  goodness  for  the  time  is  not  goodness  absolutely. 
Moral  character  is  subject  to  this  law,  that  change  in  it 
affects  not  only  the  individual's  present  life,  but  his  relation 
to  his  former,  disconnecting  him  with  it.  The  change  from 
bad  to  good  conduct  disconnects  him  with  the  bad  ;  the  change 
from  good  to  bad  disconnects  him  with  the  good.  Good  after 
bad  and  bad  after  good,  exert  each  a  rejective  power  over 
the  past,  to  his  loss  and  to  his  relief  respectively.  For  a 
man  cannot  turn  from  bad  to  good  conduct  sincerely  and 
heartily  without  such  a  sense  of  aversion,  grief,  and  disgust 
for  his  former  life  as  amounts  to  a  putting  it  away  from  him, 
a  severance  of  it  from  his  proper  self;  and  in  like  manner 
he  cannot  turn  from  a  good  behaviour  to  a  bad  entirely, 
without  such  an  indifference  to  or  contempt  of  virtue  as 
amounts  to  a  disowning  and  rejection  even  of  his  own. 
Thus  he  loses  his  property  in  one  set  of  actions  as  he  turns 
to  another.  The  actions,  indeed,  that  he  has  performed 
remain  for  ever  his  in  the  sense  that  he  is  the  person  that 


CHAP.  VII.]  OF   FINAL   PERSEVERANCE.  195 

performed  then) ;  but  they  cease  to  be  his  in  the  sense  that 
they  affect  his  character.  From  this  law,  then,  it  follows 
necessarily,  that  the  character  of  the  man  is  the  character 
which  he  has  at  last,  inasmuch  as  he  has  no  other  but  that, 
being  dispossessed,  by  the  fact  of  having  it,  of  any  different  one 
which  he  may  have  had  before.  The  question  of  property 
in  acts  is  the  whole  of  the  question  of  the  goodness  or  bad- 
ness of  the  man ;  for  how  can  his  previous  actions,  good  or 
bad,  affect  him,  except  they  belong  to  him  ?  This  law,  then, 
determines  the  question  of  property  in  acts,  and  it  determines 
it  by  the  fact  of  what  come  latest.  The  man's  previous 
virtue  or  vice  for  the  time  are  not  his  absolutely,  unless  they 
are  his  then ;  they  wait  in  suspense  for  that  final  appro- 
priation. The  question  of  property  in  the  case  of  happiness 
or  pleasure  is  perfectly  simple ;  for  happiness  being  only 
a  present  sensation,  can  only  belong  to  the  present  possessor, 
but  goodness  is  more  than  present  action,  and  therefore 
wants  another  proprietor  besides  the  present  agent. 

Indeed,  one  view  which  is  held  of  change  of  character  in 
persons  rejects  the  idea  of  real  or  substantial  change  in  them 
altogether,  arid,  whatever  they  become  at  last,  regards  them 
as  having  been  really  of  that  character  from  the  first. 
According  to  this  view,  change  is  interpretative  simply  and 
not  actual,  as  regards  the  man's  substantial  temper;  it  only 
shows  that  his  former  character  was  superficial,  and  that  he 
had  at  the  time  another  underneath  it,  which  was  really 
his  character,  in  spite  of  appearances.  Thus  the  end  in- 
terprets the  whole  of  life  from  its  beginning,  and  we  wait 
in  suspense  till  it  arrives,  in  order  to  ascertain  not  what 
a  man  will  on  the  whole  turn  out,  but  what  he  has  been  all 
along.  This  view  rests  for  its  ground  upon  a  certain  pre- 
sumed necessity  for  a  unity  of  the  moral  being.  It  appears 
to  be  dividing  one  person  into  two,  to  say  that  he  was  once 
a  good  man,  and  is  now  a  bad  man;  and  the  division  of 
his  moral  unity  is  considered  to  be  as  much  a  contradiction 
as  the  division  of  his  personal.  The  popular  aspect,  then, 

o  2 


196  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTKINE  [CHAP.  VII. 

of  change  of  character,  as  an  actual  change  or  division  of 
it,  is  used  as  a  convenience,  just  as  a  metaphor  might  be 
used  which  expressed  a  truth  with  practical  correctness  and 
perhaps  even  greater  vigour  than  a  literal  statement  would, 
while  another  and  a  deeper  view  is  really  taken  of  such 
change. 

And  this  explanation  of  change  of  character  is  undoubtedly 
a  natural  and  true  one,  properly  understood,  and  with  a 
certain  limitation.  A  man  who  changes  his  character 
cannot  indeed  be  said  to  have  had  his  later  character  before 
in  the  same  sense  in  which  he  has  it  after,  nor  can  such  a 
meaning  be  intended;  at  the  same  time  he  must  have  had 
this  character  before  in  the  sense  of  having  its  seed  or  root, 
— that  out  of  which  it  grew.  For  it  is  contrary  to  experi- 
ence and  common  sense  to  suppose  that  a  change  of  character 
can  take  place  all  at  once,  without  previous  preparation  and 
growth;  nor  can  there  be  any  doubt  that  men  have  even 
the  sure  root  of  alteration  in  them  a  longer  or  shorter  time 
before  they  actually  alter  —  i.  e.  the  altered  character  itself, 
before  it  comes  out  and  manifests  itself;  the  substance  having 
existed  in  the  shape  of  secret  habits  of  mind,  of  which  the 
formation  may  date  very  far  back.  But  if  the  idea  of  moral 
unity  is  pushed  further  back  than  this,  and  the  root  which 
contains  the  man's  subsequent  character  be  made  coeval 
with  the  man,  this  cannot  be  done  without  intrenching  upon 
freewill ;  and  therefore  such  a  supposition,  though  it  may  be 
entertained  as  an  approach  to  some  truth  on  this  subject  with 
which  we  are  unacquainted,  cannot  be  entertained  absolutely. 
I  will  add,  that  we  find  in  Scripture  both  aspects  of  change  of 
character  ;  the  popular  aspect  of  it  as  real  change,  and  the  eso- 
teric as  only  external.  The  prophet  Ezekiel  uses  the  former 
when  he  says,  "  If  the  wicked  will  turn  from  all  his  sins 
that  he  hath  committed  and  keep  all  My  statutes,  and  do 
that  which  is  lawful  and  right,  he  shall  surely  live,  he  shall 
not  die.  All  his  transgressions  that  he  hath  committed  they 
shall  not  be  mentioned  unto  him :  in  his  righteousness  that 


CHAP.  VII.]  OF   FINAL    PEKSEVERANCE.  197 

he  hath  done  he  shall  live.  But  when  a  righteous  man 
turneth  away  from  his  righteousness,  and  committeth  ini- 
quity, and  doeth  according  to  all  the  abominations  that  the 
wicked  doeth,  shall  he  live  ?  All  his  righteousness  that  he 
hath  done  shall  not  be  mentioned:  in  his  trespass  that  he 
hath  trespassed,  and  in  his  sin  that  he  hath  sinned,  in  them 
shall  he  die.  "*  St.  John  uses  the  latter  when  he  says, 
"They  went  out  from  us,  but  they  were  not  of  us;  for  if 
they  had  been  of  us  they  would  no  doubt  have  continued 
with  us ;  but  they  went  out  that  they  might  be  made  mani- 
fest that  they  were  not  all  of  us. "  2 

The  doctrine  of  final  perseverance,  then,  so  far  as  it  is 
the  adoption  of  a  test  of  saving  goodness,  is  only  the  doctrine 
of  trial  and  probation  explained.  The  doctrine  of  trial  and 
probation  is,  that  we  are  placed  in  this  world  in  order  to  prove 
by  our  actions  whether  we  are  worthy  of  reward  or  punish- 
ment in  an  eternal  world  to  come.  The  doctrine  of  final 
perseverance  is,  that  those  actions  are  not  estimated  simply 
with  regard  to  quantity,  but  also  with  regard  to  order ;  that 
what. constitutes  a  good  or  bad  life  is  not  the  mere  aggregate 
of  them,  in  which  case  it  would  not  signify  whether  they 
came  at  the  beginning  or  end  of  life,  for  so  long  as  there 
was  enough  of  them  to  satisfy  the  Judge,  it  would  be  indif- 
ferent how  the  number  was  made  up ;  but  their  succession, 
whether  prior  or  posterior  in  life :  in  other  words,  not  the 
acts  themselves,  but  their  relation  to  the  man,  whether  they 
are  appropriated  by  him  or  not ;  for  this  is  what  their 
order  of  prior  or  posterior  tests. 

And  as  the  doctrine  of  final  perseverance  as  a  test  is 
only  the  doctrine  of  trial  and  probation  explained;  so  the 
objections  to  it  on  the  ground  of  justice  are  only  of  the  kind 
which  attaches  to  the  general  doctrine  of  trial  and  probation. 
The  doctrine  indeed  that  the  whole  period  of  trial  must  be 


Ezekicl,  xviii.  21,  22,  24.       |  2  1  John,  ii.  19. 

o  3 


198  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VII. 

judged  by  its  termination,  prominently  suggests  the  question, 
in  the  case  of  a  bad  termination  of  it,  Why  is  this  period 
terminated  now  ?  As  the  end  makes  all  the  difference,  why 
could  not  that  end  have  been  postponed?  Why  could  not 
the  period  have  been  extended  to  sufficient  length  to  give 
room  for  another,  and  so,  by  a  small  addition  to  its  duration, 
the  whole  of  its  effects  have  been  removed  ?  But  it  is  evident 
that  this  objection  applies  to  the  end  of  all  trial  whatever, 
and  upon  whatever  rule  proceeding,  whether  that  of  the 
order  of  actions  or  of  the  aggregate  simply.  In  either  case 
a  longer  period  might,  as  far  as  we  see,  have  produced  a 
different  issue  from  that  of  a  shorter  one.  The  whole  doc- 
trine of  trial  and  probation  is  indeed  incomprehensible  to 
us ;  for,  whereas  probation  must  in  the  nature  of  the  case  be 
limited,  we  cannot  understand  how  a  limitation  of  it  can  be 
so  arranged  as  to  be  perfectly  just  and  equitable ;  how  it  is 
that  a  person  at  a  particular  time  is  completely  tried  and 
proved:  notwithstanding  which  difficulty,  the  doctrine  of 
trial  and  probation  is  a  doctrine  both  of  revelation  and  natural 
religion. 

The  test  of  final  perseverance  does  indeed,  in  some  of  its 
applications,  appear  to  be  open,  not  only  to  this  objection, 
which  applies  to  all  limited  probation,  that  we  do  not  see 
its  justice,  but  to  a  positive  charge  of  injustice.  For  in  the 
case  of  a  person  who  has  lived  uprightly  and  religiously  up 
to  the  end  of  life,  but  has  then  yielded  to  some  temptation 
and  fallen  into  sin,  it  does  appear  unjust  that  the  end 
should  undo  the  whole  of  the  life  previous,  and  deprive  him 
of  any  advantage  from  it ;  and  the  rule  of  final  perseverance 
seems  at  first  to  impose  such  a  result.  But  this  will  be 
found,  upon  consideration,  not  to  be  the  case.  The  rule  of 
final  perseverance  is  the  rule,  that  a  man  must  be  judged 
according  to  his  final  character ;  but  what  in  a  particular 
case  is  the  final  character  it  does  not  and  cannot  determine. 
Some  rules  indeed  are  of  such  a  kind  that  they  appear  when 
laid  down  to  decide  their  own  application ;  and  the  rule 


CHAP.  VII.]  OF   FINAL   PERSEVERANCE.  199 

which  identifies  a  man's  character,  good  or  bad,  with  his 
final  one,  will  appear,  unless  we  are  on  our  guard,  to  decide 
the  particular  fact  of  his  final  character,  its  goodness  or 
badness ;  the  change  which  is  presented  to  observation  in  the 
particular  case  appearing  to  be,  without  any  further  reflec- 
tion, the  change  which  is  supposed  in  the  rule.  But  it  is 
evident  that  we  should  be  deceived  here  by  an  apparent 
connection  between  two  things  which  are  really  separate. 
No  rule  can  possibly  decide  its  own  application  ;  it  supposes 
the  case  to  which  it  applies  and  does  not  discover  or  select 
it.  On  the  question,  whether  such  and  such  a  case  is  one 
of  change  of  character,  we  must  take  the  best  evidence 
which  our  own  experience  and  observation  can  apply,  as  we 
would  on  any  other  question  of  fact.  In  the  case  of  a  man 
who  at  the  end  of  a  life  of  steady  virtue  falls  into  sin,  we 
ought  certainly  to  be  slow  to  believe  that  such  sin  is  a  real 
change  of  character.  His  previous  good  life,  though  of  no 
avail  as  a  counterbalance,  supposing  a  real  change  from  it, 
is  yet  legitimate  evidence  on  the  question  whether  there  is 
such  change;  and  evidence,  as  far  as  it  goes,  against  it.  For 
there  is  a  difficulty  in  supposing  that  one  who  had  evinced 
such  steadiness  and  constancy  should  fall  away  really,  how- 
ever he  might  appear  to  do  so ;  and  both  reason  and  charity 
direct  us  to  a  favourable  supposition,  except  something  very 
peculiar  in  the  case  prevents  it.1 

The  rule  of  final  perseverance,  then,  as  a  test,  is  not  itself 
unjust;  but  whether  it  is  unjust  or  not  in  its  application 
depends  upon  our  discrimination  and  charity  in  applying  it. 
This  rule  is  not  intended  to  over-ride  our  natural  ideas  of 
justice,  as  if  because  we  admitted  it,  we  allowed  a  self- 
applying  power  to  it,  to  which  those  ideas  must  succumb ; 
but  those  ideas  of  justice  must  be  our  guide  in  applying 


1  The  following  is  not  a  cautious 
statement  of  S.  Augustine's,  though  it 
admits  of  explanation  :  Potius  hanc 
perseverantiam  habuit  unius  anni  fidelis 
et  quantum  infra  cogitan  potcst,  si  donee 

O    4 


moreretur  fideliter  vixit,  quam  multo- 
rum  annorum,  si  exiguum  temporis 
ante  mortem  a  fidei  stabilitate  defecit — - 
De  Dono  Perseverantiae.  c.  1. 


200  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIL 

the  rule.  We  must  apply  it  then  in  the  particular  case, 
according  to  the  evidence  ;  and  remember  that,  after  all,  we 
cannot  apply  it  with  certainty,  because  God  only  knows 
the  final  state  of  man's  heart.  There  cannot  in  that  case  be 
any  unjust  application  of  the  rule,  because  its  application 
will  be  suspended  altogether.  Indeed  this  rule,  when  we 
go  to  the  bottom  of  it,  issues  after,  all  in  being  substantially 
no  more  than  the  rule  that  a  man  must  be  judged  according 
to  his  character ;  for  by  a  man's  character  we  mean  his  final 
character,  and  no  character  previous  to  it.  The  rule  then 
is  certain,  because  it  is  no  more  than  the  rule,  that  the  good 
are  rewarded  and  the  bad  punished  ;  but  it  cannot  be  applied 
to  the  individual  with  certainty,  because  we  do  not  know 
who  are  the  bad,  and  who  are  the  good. 

II.  Final  perseverance  has  thus  far  been  treated  of  as  a  test, 
in  which  sense  the  doctrine  is  no  predestinarian  one,  but 
only  one  of  ordinary  religion  and  morality.  But  it  remains 
to  see  what  produces,  in  the  Augustinian  system,  this 
saving  obedience  of  which  final  perseverance  is  the  test,  that 
is,  to  consider  final  perseverance  as  a  grace. 

Final  perse verance>  then,  is  maintained  by  S.  Augustine 
to  be  the  free  gift  of  God ;  that  is  to  say,  not  a  gift 
bestowed  in  consideration  of  the  man's  previous  acts,  or  as 
an  assistance  to  his  own  efforts,  but  an  absolute  gift  bestowed 
upon  certain  individuals  of  the  human  race,  in  accordance 
with  an  eternal  Divine  decree  which  has  predestinated  them 
to  the  privilege  of  it.  This  is  quite  evident  from  the  pre- 
vious chapter,  and  requires  strictly  no  further  proof.  For 
there  is  no  necessity,  after  it  has  been  shown  that  all  good- 
ness under  the  Christian  dispensation  is  on  the  Augustinian 
doctrine  a  free  and  absolute  Divine  gift,  to  show  that  a  par- 
ticular measure  and  degree  of  it  is  upon  the  same  doctrine 
such  a  gift ;  and  final  perseverance  is,  as  I  have  shown,  only 
a  particular  measure  and  degree  of  goodness ;  such  a  one, 
viz.,  as  avails  for  the  man's  salvation.  What  is  said  of  the 


CHAP.  VII.]  OF   FINAL   PERSEVERANCE.  201 

whole  is  of  course  said  of  the  part.  Nevertheless,  the  grace 
of  final  perseverance  occupies  so  prominent  a  place  in  the 
Augustinian  system,  that  it  appears  proper  to  explain  the 
position  of  this  grace  in  particular,  and  to  show  that  what 
is  said  of  grace  in  general  is  said  of  this  measure  of  it. 

In  the  first  place,  then,  S.  Augustine  says  generally  that 

final  perseverance  is  a  gift.     "  Will  any  one  dare  to  assert 

that  final  perseverance  is  not  the  gift  of  God  ?  .  .  .  .  We 

cannot  deny  that  final  perseverance  is  a  great  gift  of  God, 

coming  down  from  Him  of  whom  it  is  written,  '  Every  good 

gift  and  every  perfect  gift  is  from  above,  and  cometh  down 

from  the  Father  of  lights.' " 1     "  Perseverance  is  the  gift  of 

God,  by  virtue  of  which  a  man  perseveres  in  Christ  unto  the 

end."  2     "  We  pray  that  the  unbelieving  may  believe :  faith, 

therefore,  is  the  gift  of  God.     We  pray  that  the  believing 

may   persevere :  final  perseverance,  therefore,  is  the  gift  of 

God."  3     "  Why  is  perseverance  asked  of  God,  if  it  is  not 

given  by  God?     It  is  mocking  Him  to  ask  Him  for  what 

you  know  He  does  not  give,  for  what  you  can  give  yourself. 

We  pray  '  Hallowed  be  Thy  name :  '  that  is  to  say,  we  pray 

that,  having  been  sanctified  in  baptism,  we  may  persevere  in 

that  beginning.     We  pray,  therefore,   for  perseverance  in 

sanctification.  ...  If  we  receive  that  perseverance,  then,  we 

receive  it  as  the  gift  of  God,  that  great  gift  by  which  His 

other  gifts  are  preserved."4  —  "He  makes  men  to  persevere 

in  good  who  makes  men  good.     He  gives  perseverance  who 

makes  men  stand.     The  first  man  did  not  receive  this  gift  of 

God,  perseverance."  5 

Final  perseverance,  then,  is,  according  to  S.  Augustine,  a 
Divine  gift.  And  that  he  uses  the  word  gift  here  in  its 
natural  sense  as  a  free  gift,  not  a  conditional  one,  depending 
on  man's  own  disposition  and  conduct,  is  evident  from  the 
following  considerations. 


1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  vi. 
*  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  i. 
3  Ibid.  c.  iii. 


4  De  Dono  Pers.  <•.  ii. 

5  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xii. 


202  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VII. 

First,  he  makes  final  perseverance  a  gift  in  the  same  sense 
in  which  the  end  of  life  is  a  gift:  but  the  end  of  life  is  un- 
doubtedly an  absolute  gift  of  God ;  gift,  I  say,  because  we 
are  supposing  a  case  here  in  which  it  is  advantageous  to  the 
person,  and  not  the  opposite, —  it  is  entirely  an  arrangement 
of  Providence  when  death  takes  place. 

S.  Augustine  urges  strongly  that  in  certain  cases,  the  end 
of  life,  that  is  to  say,  the  circumstance  of  the  end  of  life 
taking  place  at  the  time  it  does,  makes  final  perseverance. 
He  takes  the  case  of  persons  who  die  young,  or  when  their 
characters  are  unformed,  but  die  while  their  minds  are  as  yet 
innocent  and  uncorrupted.  Such  persons,  he  says,  attain 
final  perseverance,  because  they  do  as  a  fact  continue  in 
goodness  up  to  the  end ;  but  their  final  perseverance  is  evi- 
dently made  by  the  occurrence  of  the  end  while  they  are  in 
a  good  state  of  mind,  not  by  their  own  stability  and  con- 
stancy. That  it  is  not  any  stability  of  principle  in  the 
person  which  constitutes  in  such  cases  final  perseverance  is 
plain,  he  argues,  because  final  perseverance  takes  place,  even 
where  no  principle  of  stability  exists,  but  the  very  reverse  ; 
because  it  takes  place  even  in  cases  where  the  person,  had  he 
lived,  would  have  lapsed :  and  he  quotes  for  this  assertion 
the  text  from  the  Book  of  Wisdom,  "  Speedily  was  he  taken 
away,  lest  that  wickedness  should  alter  his  understanding, 
or  deceit  beguile  his  soul."  Here,  he  observes,  is  manifestly 
a  case  in  which  the  person's  lapse,  had  he  lived  longer,  was 
foreseen,  and  yet  final  perseverance  takes  place ;  in  which, 
therefore,  it  is  manifest  that  final  perseverance  takes  place 
not  by  the  stability  of  the  man,  but  by  the  act  of  God  in 
putting  an  end  to  his  life  at  the  time  He  does,  which  is  pur- 
posely fixed  so  as  to  prevent  a  lapse.  And  if  the  want  of 
authority  in  the  Book  of  Wisdom,  as  not  being  part  of  the 
sacred  book,  is  alleged,  he  replies  that  he  can  do  without  the 
text;  because  even  were  the  certainty  of  a  lapse  lost  to  his 
argument,  all  that  his  argument  really  wants  is  the  danger 


CHAP.  VII.]  OF   FINAL   PERSEVEEANCE.  203 

of  one  l ;  for  that,  if  there  is  the  danger  of  a  lapse,  it  cannot 
be  the  man's  stability  which  constitutes  his  final  perseverance, 
but  the  act  of  God  in  forestalling  his  trial.  What  makes 
final  perseverance  in  such  cases  then,  is,  he  concludes,  the 
Divine  location  of  the  end  of  life.  And  thence  he  argues 
immediately  that  in  such  cases  final  perseverance  itself  is  a 
Divine  gift.  <f  Consider  how  contradictory  it  is  to  deny  that 
perseverance  up  to  the  end  of  this  life  is  the  gift  of  God, 
•when  He  undoubtedly  gives  the  end  of  life  whenever  He 
pleases ;  and  the  giving  of  the  end  of  life  before  an  impend- 
ing lapse  makes  final  perseverance."  2  "  How  is  not  per- 
severance unto  the  end  of  God's  grace,  when  the  end  itself  of 
life  is  in  God's  power,  and  God  can  confer  this  benefit  even 
on  one  who  is  not  about  to  persevere  ?  "  3 

Having  proved  one  kind  of  final  perseverance  by  this  argu- 
ment to  be  a  Divine  gift,  he  then  infers  that  all  final  perse- 
verance whatever  is  the  same.  There  may  be  a  wide  interval 
between  the  final  perseverance  of  one  who  is  snatched  from 
impending  trial  by  some  sudden  illness  or  accident,  and  that 
of  one  who  has  been  reserved  for  trial  and  has  sustained  it 
without  falling  ;  but  if  the  one  kind  is  the  gift  of  God,  the 
other  is  too.  "  He  who  took  away  the  righteous  man  by  an 
early  death,  lest  wickedness  should  alter  his  understanding, 
preserves  the  righteous  man  for  the  length  of  a  long  life, 
that  wickedness  does  not  alter  his  understanding." 4  "  Per- 
severance amid  hindrances  and  persecutions  is  the  more  dif- 
ficult ;  the  other  is  the  easier :  but  He  to  whom  nothing  is 
difficult  can  easily  give  both."  5 

The  substance  of  this  argument  is,  that  the  power  of  re  • 
sisting  temptation  is  as  much  a  gift  of  God  as  the  removal 
from  temptation.  Death  can  only  be  effective  of  final  per- 
severance as  being  a  removal  for  ever  from  temptation. 


1  De  Pra?d.  c.  xiv. 

3  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  xvii, 

8  Ep.  217.  c.  vi. 


4  De  Prad.  c.  xiv.  (980.) 
6  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  2. 


204  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIL 

And  therefore  to  say  that  perseverance,  which  consists  in 
sustaining  temptation,  is  as  much  a  gift  of  God  as  that  which 
is  caused  by  the  occurrence  of  death,  is  only  to  say,  that  the 
power  of  sustaining  temptation  is  as  much  a  gift  of  God 
as  the  removal  from  temptation.  And  so  the  argument  is 
sometimes  put  by  S.  Augustine,  the  substance  being  given 
apart  from  this  particular  form  of  it,  which  alludes  to  the  end 
of  life.  "  God  is  able  to  convert  the  averse  and  adverse  wills 
of  men  to  His  faith,  and  work  in  their  hearts  a  sustaining 
of  all  adversities  and  an  overcoming  of  all  temptation ;  inas- 
much as  He  is  able  not  to  permit  them  to  be  tempted  at  all 
above  that  they  are  able:"  the  resistance  to  temptation  is 
pronounced  to  be  in  the  power  of  God  to  give,  because  the 
protection  from  temptation  is  in  His  power.1 

Such  an  argument  is,  indeed,  more  ingenious  than  sound  ; 
for  it  does  not  follow  that  because  God  spares  some  persons 
on  particular  occasions  the  exercise  of  a  certain  power  of 
choice  and  original  agency  inherent  in  their  nature,  that 
therefore  such  a  power  does  not  exist,  and  would  not  have 
been  called  into  action  by  another  arrangement  of  Pro- 
vidence. But  the  argument  itself,  which  is  all  that  we  are 
concerned  with  here,  certainly  shows  the  sense  in  which 
S.  Augustine  uses  the  term  "  gift "  of  final  perseverance. 
For  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  removal  from  temptation  is 
an  absolute  and  free  gift  of  God ;  it  being  entirely  an  arrange- 
ment of  His  providence  what  temptations  we  encounter  in 
the  course  of  our  life,  and  what  we  do  not.  If  perseverance, 
therefore,  in  spite  of  temptation,  is  as  much  a  gift  of  God 
as  the  removal  from  temptation,  it  is  a  gift  simple  and  ab- 
solute. And  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  the  occurrence  of 
the  end  of  life  at  a  particular  time  is  an  arrangement  solely 
of  God's  providence.  If  all  perseverance,  then,  is  alike  the 
gift  of  God,  while  one  kind  of  it  is  said  to  be  constituted 


1  De  Dono  Ters.  c.  ix. 


CHAP.  VII.]  OF   FINAL   PERSEVERANCE.  205 

by  the  occurrence  of  the  end  of  life  at  a  particular  time, 
all  perseverance  is  a  gift  of  God  simple  and  absolute. 

Again,  he  places  the  gift  of  perseverance  on  the  same 
ground  as  the  gift  of  baptism,  with  respect  to  the  principle 
or  law  upon  which  it  is  bestowed.  Some  persons,  he 
observes,  have  baptism  given  to  them,  and  others  have 
not ;  and  in  like  manner  some  have  the  gift  of  perseverance 
given  to  them,  and  others  have  not.1  Now,  it  is  obvious 
that  the  gift  of  baptism  is  a  free  gift,  the  bestowal  of  which 
depends  solely  on  God's  will  and  pleasure,  who  gives  it  to 
whom  He  pleases  and  from  whom  He  pleases  withholds  it. 
Thus  the  population  of  Europe  is  baptized,  the  popula- 
tion of  Asia  is  not ;  evidently  not  because  the  inhabitants 
of  Europe  have  done  anything  to  deserve  it  which  the 
inhabitants  of  Asia  have  not  done,  but  simply  owing  to 
an  arrangement  of  Providence.  We  see  with  our  eyes  that 
a  man's  baptism  results  from  causes  wholly  irrespective  of 
his  own  conduct,  such  as  the  part  of  the  world  he  was  born 
in,  in  what  communion,  from  what  parents.  There  can  be 
no  more  genuine  instance,  then,  of  a  free  gift  than  baptism  ; 
and,  therefore,  if  final  perseverance  is  a  gift  in  the  same 
way  in  which  baptism  is,  final  perseverance  is  a  free  gift. 

It  remains  to  add,  that  the  notes  of  genuineness  which 
were  observed  in  the  last  chapter  to  attach  to  the  word 
"  gift,"  as  used  by  S.  Augustine,  of  grace  in  general,  attach 
to  the  word  equally  as  used  by  him  of  this  particular 
measure  of  grace,  final  perseverance.  These  notes  were 
contained  in  the  caution  that  grace  was  not  given  according 
to  merit;  in  the  argument  from  prayer;  and  in  the  entire 
reference  of  the  matter  to  a  ground  of  mystery,  the  bestowal 
or  withholding  of  grace  being  attributed  wholly  to  God's 
secret  counsels  and  sovereign  will.  All  this  is  applied  in  par- 
ticular by  S.  Augustine  to  the  grace  of  final  perseverance.  It 


1  De  Dono  Pers.  cc.  ix.  x. ;  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  viii. 


206  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VII. 

is  not  given  according  to  merit ;  it  is  given  in  the  same  sense 
in  which  other  gifts  which  the  act  of  prayer  assigns  to  God's 
absolute  bounty  are  given ;  and  the  reason  why  it  is  given 
to  one  man  and  not  to  another  is  altogether  a  mysterious 
and  incomprehensible  one,  belonging  to  the  secret  counsels 
of  God.  A  considerable  part  of  the  books  "  De  Dono  Per- 
severantia  l  "  and  "  De  Correptione.  et  Gratia 2 "  is  devoted 
to  proving  that  the  gift  of  final  perseverance  is  not  given 
according  to  merit ;  that  is  to  say,  in  consideration  of  any 
previous  acts  or  efforts  of  the  man  himself.  And  the  whole 
of  the  beginning  of  the  former  book  is  occupied  with  proving 
that  final  perseverance  must  be  God's  gift,  inasmuch  as  we 
ask  God  for  it,  both  in  our  own  behalf  and  that  of  others, 
and  what  we  ask  God  for  we  necessarily  confess  to  be  in  His 
power  to  give  or  to  withhold. 

With  respect  to  the  law  upon  which  the  gift  of  perseve- 
rance is  given  to  one  man  and  not  to  another,  he  says,  "  If 
any  one  asks  me  why  God  does  not  give  perseverance  to 
those  who  by  His  grace  lead  a  Christian  life  and  have  love,  I 
reply,  that  I  do  not  know,  I  recognise  my  measure  in  that 
text,  *  O  man,  who  art  thou  that  repliest  against  God  ?  O 
the  depth  of  the  riches  both  of  the  wisdom  and  knowledge 
of  God !  How  unsearchable  are  His  judgments,  and  His 
ways  past  finding  out.'  So  far  as  He  deigns  to  reveal  His 
judgments,  let  us  be  thankful ;  so  far  as  He  hides  them, 
let  us  not  murmur.  Say  you,  who  oppose  yourself  to  Divine 
grace,  you  are  a  Christian,  a  Catholic,  and  boast  of  being 
one,  do  you  admit  or  deny  that  final  perseverance  is  the  gift 
of  God  ?  If  you  allow  it  to  be,  then  you  and  I  are  alike 
ignorant  why  one  receives  it,  and  another  does  not ;  then  you 
and  I  are  alike  unable  to  penetrate  the  unsearchable  judg- 
ments of  God." 3  Again :  "  Of  two  children,  why  one  is 


1  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  viii.  et  seq. 
3  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xii. 


3  DC  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  viii. 


CHAP.  VII.]  OF    FINAL   PERSEVERANCE.  207 

taken  and  the  other  left  (i.  e.  baptized  and  not  baptized),  of 
two  adults,  why  one  is  so  called,  that  he  follows  the  caller, 
and  the  other  either  not  called  at  all  or  not  so  called,  belongs 
to  the  inscrutable  judgments  of  God.     Of  two  pious  men, 
why  final  perseverance  is  given  to  one  and  not  to  the  other, 
belongs  to  His  still  more  inscrutable  judgments."  1     Again  : 
"  It  is  evident  that  both  the  grace  of  the  beginning  and  the 
grace  of  persevering  to  the  end  is  not  given  according  to  our 
merits,  but  according  to  a  most  secret,  most  just,  most  wise, 
most  beneficent  will ;  inasmuch  as  whom  He  hath  predesti- 
nated those  He  hath  also  called  with  that  call  of  which  it  is 
said,  '  The  gifts  and  calling  of  God  are  without  repentance.'  "2 
Again :  "  Wonderful  indeed,  very  wonderful,  that  to  some  of 
His  own  sons,  whom  He  has  regenerated  and  to  whom  He 
has  given  faith,  hope,  and  charity,  God  does  not  give  perse- 
verance !  that  He  who  oftentimes  pardons  and  adopts  the 
stranger's   (unbeliever's)   son,  should  withhold   such  a  gift 
from  His  own  !     Who  but  must  wonder,  be  astonished,  and 
amazed  at  this  ! "  3     Again :  "  I  am  speaking  of  those  who 
have  not  the  gift  of  perseverance,  but  have  turned  from  good 
to  evil,  and  die  in  that  declination ;  let  them  (his  opponents) 
tell  me  why  God  did  not  take  such  persons  out  of  this  world 
while  they  were  yet  unchanged  ?     Was  it  because  He  could 
not  ?  or  was  it  because  He  foresaw  not  their  future  wicked- 
ness?   .They  cannot  assert  either  of  these  without  perversity 
and  madness.     Then  why  did  He  do  so  ?     Let  them  answer 
this  question  before  they  deride  me,  when  I  exclaim, f  How  un- 
searchable are  His  judgments,  and  His  ways  past  finding  out ! 
Either  God  gives  that  gift  to  whom  He  will,  or  Scripture 
lies.  .  .  .  Let  them  confess  this  truth  at  once,  and  why  God 
gives  that  gift   to   one   and   not   to   another, —  condescend 
without  a  murmur  to  be  ignorant  with  me." 4 


1  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  ix.  3  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c,  viii. 

2  Ibid.  c.  xiii.  4  Ibid.  c.  viii. 


208  DOCTRINE   OF    FINAL   PERSEVERANCE.       [CHAP.  VII. 

Final  perseverance,  then,  is,  upon  the  Augustinian  doctrine, 
the  true  and  absolute  gift  of  God  to  certain  members  of  the 
human  race  ;  to  whom,  according  to  an  eternal  decree,  He  has 
determined  to  give  it :  and  it  has  that  prominent  place  which 
it  has  in  the  predestinarian  scheme,  because  it  is  that  measure 
of  Divine  grace  which  is-  sufficient  for  salvation.  The  pre- 
destinarian doctrine  is  that  certain  persons  are  predestined 
by  God  from  all  eternity  to  be  saved ;  but  God  only  saves 
the  righteous,  and  not  the  wicked.  It  must  therefore  be 
provided,  in  accordance  with  this  doctrine,  that  those  persons 
shall  exhibit  as  much  goodness  of  life  as  is  necessary  for  the 
end  to  which  they  are  ordained  ;  and  final  perseverance  is  this 
measure  of  goodness.  The  gift  of  final  perseverance,  then, 
is  the  great  gift  which  puts  into  execution  God's  eternal 
decree  with  respect  to  the  whole  body  of  the  elect.  He 
may  predestine  some  to  a  higher  and  others  to  a  lower  place, 
but  He  predestines  all  the  elect  to  a  place  in  the  kingdom  of 
heaven  ;  and  therefore,  while  He  provides  that  some  shall  ex- 
hibit higher  and  other  lower  degrees  of  sanctity  and  goodness, 
He  provides  that  all  shall  exhibit  enough  for  admission ; 
which  sufficiency  is  final  perseverance. 


20<J 


CHAP.   VIII. 

AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE   OP    FREEWILL. 

THE  preceding  chapters  have  exhibited  a  full  and  sys- 
tematic scheme  of  predestinarian  doctrine,  as  held  by  S. 
Augustine,  who  asserts  in  the  first  place  an  eternal  Divine 
decree,  whereby  one  part  of  mankind  has  been,  anteced- 
ently to  any  moral  difference  between  the  two,  separated 
from  the  other,  and  the  one  ordained  to  eternal  life,  and 
the  other  to  eternal  punishment l ;  and  next  supplies  a  grace 
for  putting  it  into  effect.2  But  while  he  lays  down  this 
doctrine  of  predestination  and  irresistible  grace,  S.  A.ugus- 
tine  at  the  same  time  acknowledges  the  existence  of  freewill 
in  man — liberum  arbitrium;  an  admission,  which,  understood 
in  its  popular  sense,  would  have  been  a  counterbalance  to 
all  the  rest  of  his  scheme.  The  question,  however,  imme- 
diately arises,  what  he  means  by  freewill;  whether  he  uses 
the  word  in  the  sense  which  the  ordinary  doctrine  of  free- 
will requires,  or  in  another  and  a  different  sense.  Persons 
are  apt  indeed  to  suppose,  as  soon  as  ever  they  hear  the 
word  freewill,  that  the  word  must  involve  all  that  those 
who  hold  the  regular  doctrine  of  freewill  mean  by  it.  It 
remains,  however,  to  see  whether  this  is  the  case  in  S. 
Augustine's  use  of  the  word. 

The  doctrine  of  freewill  consists  of  two  parts ;  one  of 
which  has  respect  to  the  existence  of  the  will,  and  the 
other  to  the  mode  in  which  it  is  moved  and  determined. 
That  part  which  respects  the  existence  of  the  will,  the  doc- 
trine of  freewill,  and  the  contrary  doctrine,  hold  in  common. 
No  person  in  his  senses  can  deny  the  fact  of  the  will,  that 


Chap,  V.  j  2  Chaps>  vi.  and  VII. 


210  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

we  will  to  do  this,  that,  and  the  other  thing,  that  we  act 
with  intention,  design,  deliberation.  We  are  directly  con- 
scious of  all  this.  No  predestinarian,  therefore,  however  rigid, 
denies  it;  and  the  whole  set  of  sensations  which  are  con- 
nected with  willing,  or  the  whole  fact  of  the  will,  in  its 
minutest  and  most  subtle  particulars,  is  the  common  ground 
both  of  him  and  his  opponent.  But  the  fact  of  the  will 
admitted,  the  further  question  remains,  how  this  will  is 
determined ;  that  is,  caused  to  decide  on  one  side  or  another, 
and  choose  this  or  that  act.  The  doctrine  of  freewill  is 
that  the  cause  of  this  decision  is  the  will  itself,  and  that  the 
will  has  a  power  of  self-determination  inherent  in  it.  This 
appears  to  the  maintainers  of  this  doctrine  the  natural 
inference  from  that  whole  fact  of  willing,  of  which  they  are 
conscious,  so  that  they  could  not  draw  any  other  without 
seeming  to  themselves  to  contradict  plain  reason.  Nobody 
can  assert  indeed  that  he  is  conscious  distinctly,  and  after 
the  mode  of  clear  perception,  of  a  power  of  determining 
his  own  will,  for  all  that  he  is  distinctly  conscious  of  is  his 
will  itself.  Nevertheless,  the  will  as  we  feel  and  experience 
it,  acting  with  struggle,  effort,  resolution,  summoning  up  of 
force,  and  deliberate  choice  of  alternatives,  has  so  much  the 
appearance  of  being  self-determining  and  original,  that  when 
the  notion  is  suggested  that  it  is  not,  such  a  notion  is  felt  to 
be  contrary  to  an  idea  which  we  naturally  and  instinctively 
have  respecting  our  will,  its  originality  appearing  to  be  im- 
plied in  this  kind  of  motion  and  operation.  Nor  is  this 
self-determining  power  of  the  will  interfered  with  by  the 
doctrine  of  assisting  grace,  which  is  so  formed  as  to  admit 
the  human  will  as  an  original  agent,  co-operating  with 
grace.  The  doctrine  of  freewill,  then,  is  that  the  will  is 
determined  by  itself,  or  is  an  original  agent,  as  distinguished 
from  the  assertion  simply  of  a  will  in  man,  which  latter  it 
holds  in  common  with  the  rival  and  opposite  doctrine  re- 
specting the  will. 

The  validity  indeed  of  this  whole  distinction  between  the 


CHAP.  VIII]  OF    FREEWILL.  211 

will  itself  and  the  will  as  self-determining,  i.  e.  the  existence 
of  this  self-determining  power  in  the  will  over  and  above 
the  fact  of  willing,  is  denied  by  the  school  of  metaphysi- 
cians, who  take  against  the  common  doctrine  of  freewill  and 
favour  that  of  necessity.  They  maintain  freewill  to  consist 
in  the  simple  fact  of  will ;  that  we  act  willingly  and  without 
constraint ;  and  they  deny  that  we  can  go  any  further  than 
this,  or  see  anything  whatever  more  than  this  fact,  however 
far  we  may  try  to  look.  They  say  that  in  this  consists  the 
whole  of  freewill,  that  this  is  all  we  mean  or  can  mean  by 
it ;  and  that  if  we  try  to  go  any  deeper^  we  involve  our- 
selves in  confusion  and  absurdity.  This  position  is  among 
others  maintained  by  Locke,  whose  great  fairness  of  mind 
and  anxiety  to  represent  faithfully  and  exactly  the  truth 
respecting  the  human  mind  and  its  constitution  entitle  his 
opinions  on  this  subject  to  much  consideration,  because  he  does 
not  appear  to  have  started  with  any  bias  one  way  or  another 
on  the  examination  of  the  question,  but  to  have  decided 
according  to  what  he  thought  the  plain  facts  of  the  case.  I 
cannot  but  think,  however,  that  his  love  of  exact  truth 
and  the  test  of  actual  perception  and  apprehension  which 
his  philosophy  applies,  have  been  carried  too  far  in  this  in- 
stance, and  led  him  into  a  mistake.  For  this  test  cannot 
be  applied  with  absolute  strictness  in  all  cases,  as  I  have 
often  said  ;  there  being  truths  of  reason,  which  do  not  admit 
of  it,  truths  in  their  very  nature  indeterminate  and  indistinct ; 
to  which  class  belongs  the  truth  now  in  question,  that  of  the 
self-determining  power  of  the  will. 

Locke's  elaborate  argument  on  this  subject  divides  itself 
into  two  questions ;  one  whether  the  will  is  free,  the  other 
whether  the  man  or  the  agent  is  free  to  will. 

The  first  question  is  not  really  the  question  at  issue  be- 
tween the  two  sides ;  for  what  those  who  maintain  the  self- 
determining  power  of  the  will  mean  by  the  will  being  free, 
is,  that  the  agent  is  free  to  will :  nor  does  their  position  at 
all  necessarily  involve  the  particular  expression, —  freedom 

p  2 


212  AUGU8TINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAF.  VIII. 

of  the  will,  which  Locke  first  impugns  in  his  argument, 
though  they  use  it  as  a  convenient  mode  of  stating  the 
real  truth  for  which  they  contend.  Locke,  however,  first 
examines  this  expression,  and  starts  the  question  in  this 
particular  form,  whether  the  will  is  free ;  and  he  decides 
against  its  freedom  on  the  ground  that  freedom  is  a  power 
and  the  will  a  power,  and  that  a  -power  cannot  be  predicated 
of  a  power,  power  being  the  attribute  of  an  agent.  Free- 
dom, he  says,  is  the  power  to  act  as  we  will.  "  So  far  as 
a  man  has  power  to  think  or  not  to  think,  to  move  or 
not  to  move,  according  to  the  preference  or  direction  of 

his  own    mind,    so  far  is  a   man  free The  idea  of 

liberty  is  the  idea  of  a  power  in  any  agent  to  do  or  forbear 
any  particular  action,  according  to  the  determination  or 
thought  of  his  mind."  1  Freedom,  then,  being  the  power  to 
act  as  we  will,  assert  this  power  of  the  will,  he  says,  and  what 
does  it  become  ?  —  the  power  of  the  will  to  act  as  it  wills ;  i.  e. 
for  this  is  the  only  act  the  will  can  do,  the  power  of  the  will 
to  will  as  it  wills.  But  this  is  a  power  which  is  contained 
in  the  very  act  of  willing,  and  does  not  go  at  all  beyond  the 
mere  fact  of  will.  So  that,  he  argues,  when  we  would 
attribute  this  power — i.  e.  freedom — to  the  will,  we  find  im- 
mediately that  we  are  making  no  assertion  beyond  that  of  the 
will  itself,  not  advancing  a  step  farther,  but  going  on  like 
a  rocking  horse  upon  the  same  ground.  Though  in  a  certain 
incorrect  way  he  allows  this  freedom  to  be  asserted  of  the 
will,  because  its  exertion  is  thus  ipso  facto  freedom.  <f  If 
freedom  can  with  any  propriety  of  speech  be  applied  to 
power,  it  may  be  attributed  to  the  power  that  is  in  man 
to  produce  or  forbear  producing,  by  choice  or  preference, 
which  is  that  which  denominates  him  free,  and  is  freedom 
itself.  But  if  any  one  should  ask  whether  freedom  were 
free,  he  would  be  suspected  not  to  understand  well  what 
he  said ;  and  he  should  be  thought  to  deserve  Midas'  ears, 


Essay,  book  2.  c.  21. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  OF    FREEWILL.  213 

who,  knowing  that  rich  was  a  denomination  for  the  posses- 
sion of  riches,  should  demand  whether  riches  themselves 
were  rich."  l 

But  the  question  Whether  the  will  is  free  being  thus 
decided,  the  next  follows,  whether  the  man  is  free  to  will ; 
which  is,  as  has  been  just  said,  the  real  question  at  issue 
between  the  two  sides.  On  this  question,  then,  he  first  de- 
cides — and  no  one  will  oppose  him,- — that  the  man  is  not  free 
in  the  case  of  any  proposed  action,  generally  and  altogether 
in  respect  of  willing ;  but  that  he  must  will  one  thing  or 
another,  either  doing  the  act  or  abstaining  from  it.  "  Will- 
ing or  volition  being  an  action,  and  fteedom  consisting  in  a 
power  of  acting  or  not  acting,  a  man  in  respect  of  willing 
or  the  act  of  volition,  when  an  action  in  his  power  is  once 
proposed  to  his  thoughts  as  presently  to  be  done,  cannot 
be  free.  The  reason  whereof  is  very  manifest ;  for  it  being 
unavoidable  that  the  action  depending  on  his  will  should 
exist  or  not  exist,  and  its  existence  or  not  existence  follow- 
ing perfectly  the  determination  and  preference  of  his  will, 
he  cannot  avoid  willing  the  existence  or  not  existence  of 
that  action ;  it  is  absolutely  necessary  that  he  will  the  one 
or  the  other This,  then,  is  evident,  that  in  all  pro- 
posals of  present  action,  a  man  is  not  at  liberty  to  will  or 
not  to  will,  because  he  cannot  forbear  willing." 

It  being  decided,  then,  that  the  man  must  will  one  way  or 
another  — i.  e.  is  not  free  to  will  neither  way, — Locke  comes 
at  last  to  the  question,  which  is  the  only  real  one  between  the 
two  sides,  and  upon  which  the  whole  controversy  turns  —  Is 
he  free  to  will  either  way  ?  And  he  settles  it  thus  summarily. 
"  Since,  then,  it  is  plain  that  in  most  cases  a  man  is  not  at 
liberty,  whether  he  will  or  no,  the  next  thing  demanded  is, 
Whether  a  man  le  at  liberty  to  will  which  of  the  tiuo  he  pleases? 
This  question  carries  the  absurdity  of  it  so  manifestly  in 


Essay,  book  2.  c.  21. 
P  3 


214  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

itself,  that  one  might  thereby  be  sufficiently  convinced  that 
liberty  concerns  not  the  will.  For  to  ask  whether  a  man 
be  at  liberty  to  will  either  motion  or  rest,  speaking  or  silence, 
which  he  pleases,  is  to  ask  whether  a  man  can  will  what  he 
wills,  or  be  pleased  with  what  he  is  pleased  with.  A  ques- 
tion which,  I  think,  needs  no  answer ;  and  they  who  can 
make  a  question  of  it,  must  suppose  one  will  to  determine 
the  acts  of  another,  and  another  to  determine  that,  and  so  on 
in  infinitnm? 

Upon  this  ground  it  is  decided  that  the  man  or  agent  does 
not  determine  his  own  will.  But  is  not  this  an  argument 
which  simply  takes  advantage  of  the  difficulties  of  language, 
with  which  questions  like  these  are  beset  ?  The  position  that 
the  man  determines  his  own  will  is  stated  in  a  form  in  which 
it  becomes  absurd,  and  then  the  charge  of  absurdity  is 
brought  against  the  position  itself.  It  is  described  as  the  as- 
sertion, that  "  the  man  is  at  liberty  to  ivill  which  of  the  two  he 
.pleases?  or  wills.  And  certainly  in  this  form  the  position 
is  absurd ;  for  it  assumes  the  previous  existence  of  a  particular 
decision  of  the  will,  as  the  condition  of  the  power  or  liberty 
of  the  man  to  make  it.  But  though  in  loose  speech  the  self- 
determining  power  of  the  will  may  sometimes  be  expressed 
in  this  way,  the  truth  really  intended  and  meant  does  not 
depend  on  such  an  expression  of  it.  The  truth  which  is 
meant,  is  not  the  man's  power  to  will  as  he  wills  or  pleases, 
but  simply  his  power  to  will ;  that  his  will  rises  ultimately 
and  originally  from  himself  as  the  agent  or  possessor  of  the 
will :  in  other  words,  that  that  whole  affair  of  the  man 
Billing  is  an  original  event. 

The  question  of  such  a  self-determining  power  in  the 
will  may  be  called  "  an  unreasonable,  because  unintelligible 
question  1  ;  "  and  the  other  ground  be  preferred,  as  simpler 
,and  more  common  sense  and  straightforward,  that  will  is  will, 
and  that  that  is  all  that  can  be  said  about  it.  But  if  truths 


1  Essay,  book  2.  c.  21.  s.  14. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  OF   FREEWILL.  215 

are  to  be  rejected  because  they  are  indistinct,  indefinite,  and 
incapable  of  consistent   statement,  we    must  reject   a  large 
class  of  most   important   truths   belonging  to  our  rational 
nature.1     This  self-determining  power  in  the  will  cannot  be 
stated  accurately,  nor  can  it  be  apprehended  accurately  ;  but 
have  we  not  a  perception  in  this  direction  ?     Is  there  not  a 
rational  instinct  which  speaks  to  our  originality  as  agents, 
as  there  is  a  rational  instinct  which  tells  us  of  substance, 
of  cause,  of  infinity  ?     And  does  not  this  instinct  or  per- 
ception see  a  certain  way,  so  that  we  have  some  sort  of  idea 
of  the  thing  in  our  minds  ?     Locke's  rejection  of  this  power 
in  the  will  on  such  a  ground  appears  to  be  inconsistent  with 
his  admission  of  the  class  of  indistinct  ideas?2     For  if  we 
admit  such  a  kind  and  order  of  truths,  are  we  arbitrarily  to 
exclude  such  a  truth  as  this  from  the  benefit  of  it  —  a  truth 
which  is  felt  and  asserted  by  the  great  mass  of  mankind  ? 
But  this  is  the  line  which  Locke  takes  on  this  question.     He 
sees  there  is  no  distinct  idea  of  originality  or  self-determina- 
tion in  the  human  mind ;  and  he  does  not  allow  such  an  idea 
a  place  as  an  indistinct  one.     He  thus  rests  ultimately  in 
the  simple  fact  of  will,  as  the  whole  of  the  truth  of  the  free- 
dom of  the  will.  "  For  how  can  we  think  any  one  freer,  than 
to  have  the  power  to  do  what  he  will  ?......  We  can 

scarce  tell  how  to  imagine  any  being  freer  than  to  be  able  to 
do  what  he  wills."  3 

It  must  be  added,  that  important  results  in  theology  follow 
the  decision  of  this  question  respecting  the  will,  one  way  or 
another.  On  the  supposition  of  a  self- determining  power  in 
the  will,  and  so  far  as  it  is  a  true  one,  the  Divine  justice  is 
freed  from  all  substantial  difficulty ;  for  moral  evil  is  brought 
instantly  home  to  the  individual,  who  is  made  responsible 
for  it,  and  so  justly  subject  to  punishment.  But  deny  this 
power,  and  suppose  the  will  to  be  moved  from  without,  and 


1  See  Chap.  II.  I  »  Essay,  book  2.  c.  21.  s.  21. 

2  NOT*  IV. 


P    4 


216  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

the  Divine  justice  is  immediately  challenged,  and  we  are 
involved  in  whatever  difficulty  accompanies  the  depravation 
of  moral  beings  from  a  source  external  to  themselves,  and 
their  punishment  when  their  depravation  has  proceeded  from 
such  a  source.  I  am  speaking  of  the  latter  doctrine  as  held 
definitely  or  exclusively.  It  may  be  said,  indeed,  that  the 
will  which  is  thus  moved  from  without  is  still  will,  the  will 
of  the  individual, —  that  it  has  all  the  properties  which  we  can 
distinctly  conceive  of  will ;  but  these  characteristics  of  will 
will  not  prevent  the  difficulties  which  arise  from  this  theory 
of  its  motion  or  determination.  And  this  perhaps  is  worth 
the  consideration  of  those  who  not  so  much  deny  the  self- 
determining  power  of  the  will,  as  set  the  question  aside  as 
unimportant ;  as  if  the  acknowledgment  of  will  as  a  fact 
were  the  only  thing  of  real  importance.  Of  course,  if  this 
is  so,  it  is  impossible  to  be  in  the  wrong  on  this  subject ;  for 
nobody  in  his  senses  can  deny  the  fact  of  the  will.  But  the 
further  question  of  its  determination  cannot  be  said  to  be 
unimportant,  both  in  itself,  and  as  involving  these  theo- 
logical results.  It  makes  a  difference  in  what  way  we 
decide  it. 

A  distinguished  writer  of  the  present  day,  Archbishop 
Whately,  adopts  this  line :  "  Let,  then,  necessarians  of  all 
descriptions  but  step  forth  into  light,  and  explain  their  own 
meaning ;  and  we  shall  find  that  their  positions  are  either 
obviously  untenable,  or  else  perfectly  harmless  and  nearly 
insignificant.  If  in  saying  that  all  things  are  fixed  and  ne- 
cessary, they  mean  that  there  is  no  such  thing  as  voluntary 
action,  we  may  appeal  from  the  verbal  quibbles  which  alone 
afford  a  seeming  support  to  such  a  doctrine  to  universal  con- 
sciousness ;  which  will  authorise  even  those  who  have  never 
entered  into  such  speculations  as  the  foregoing,  to  decide  on 
the  falsity  of  the  conclusion,  though  they  are  perplexed  with 
the  subtle  fallacies  of  the  argument.  But  if  nothing  more 
be  meant  than  that  every  event  depends  on  causes  adequate  to 
produce  it,  that  nothing  is  in  itself  contingent,  accidental.,  or 


CHAP.  VIII.]  OF   FREEWILL.  217 

uncertain^  but  is  called  so  only  with  reference  to  a  person 
who  does  not  know  all  the  circumstances  on  which  it  depends, 
—  and  that  it  is  absurd  to  say  anything  could  have  happened 
otherwise  than  it  did,  supposing  all  the  circumstances  connected 
with  it  to  remain  the  samei  —  then  the  doctrine  is  undeniably 
true,  but  perfectly  harmless,  not  at  all  encroaching  on  free 
agency  and  responsibility,  and  amounting  in  fact  to  little 
more  than  an  expansion  of  the  axiom,  that  it  is  impossible  for 
the  same  thing  to  be  and  not  to  be."  1 

Archbishop  Whately  in  this  passage  more  than  tolerates 
necessitarianism,  because  he  adopts  it.  He  asserts  that 
"  nothing  is  in  itself  contingent,  accidental,  uncertain,"  and 
that,  supposing  all  the  circumstances  connected  with  it  to 
remain  the  same,  f<  it  is  absurd  to  say  anything  could  have 
happened  otherwise  than  as  it  did."  This  is  the  doctrine  of  ne- 
cessity. Suppose  two  men  under  exactly  the  same  circum- 
stances as  regards  a  particular  temptation  to  which  they  are 
subjected  —  the  same  even  to  the  minutest  particulars.  Let 
the  circumstances  which  are  thus  identical  be  not  external 
only,  but  internal  ones.  Let  them  have  the  same  amount  of 
inward  bias  or  inclination,  and  let  this  inclination  be  acted 
upon  from  without  by  a  whole,  complex,  manifold  and  intri- 
cate machinery  of  invitations  and  allurements,  precisely  the 
same  in  both  casee.  Let  every  thing,  in  short,  which  is  pro- 
perly circumstantial — i.  e.  is  not  the  very  act  of  the  will  itself 
-  be  by  supposition  the  same  in  both  cases.  .  Now,  the  doc- 
trine of  freewill  is,  that  these  two  agents  may,  under  this 
entire  and  absolute  identity  of  circumstances,  act  differently  ; 
the  doctrine  of  necessity  is  that  they  must  act  the  same. 
According  to  the  doctrine  of  freewill  there  is  an  ultimate 
power  of  choice  in  the  human  will,  which,  however  strongly 
it  may  be  drawn,  or  tempted,  or  attracted  to  decide  one  way 
or  another  by  external  appeals  or  motives,  is  not  ruled  and 


:  Appendix  to  Archbp.  King,  On  Predestination,  p.  99. 


218  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTPaNE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

decided  by  such  motives,  but  by  the  will  itself  only.  This  is 
the  self-determining  power  of  the  will,  the  assertion  of  which 
is  the  characteristic  of  that  doctrine.  Under  this  identity  of 
circumstances,  an  original  act  or  motion  of  the  will  is  said  to 
take  place,  which  may  be  different  in  the  two  persons,  and  be 
the  one  single  difference  in  the  whole  of  the  two  cases.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  necessitarian  maintains  that  where  the 
circumstances,  external  and  internal,  are  really  and  completely 
alike,  there  is  not  room  for  this  further  difference ;  but  that 
the  issue  will  be  the  same  in  both  cases,  and  both  will 
act  alike.  Archbishop  Whately's  position,  that  "  supposing 
all  the  circumstances  connected  with  it  to  remain  the  same,  it 
is  absurd  to  say  anything  could  have  happened  otherwise  than 
as  it  did,"  is  identical  with  this  necessitarian  one.  He  adds, 
that  this  assertion  that  the  event  must  always  be  the  same 
under  the  same  circumstances,  is  <(  little  more  than  an  ex- 
pansion of  the  position  that  it  is  impossible  for  the  same 
thing  to  be  and  not  to  be."  Of  course,  supposing  it  true 
that  the  whole  of  the  circumstances  of  an  act  or  event 
amount  to  and  really  are  and  constitute  that  act  or  event 
itself,  it  immediately  follows,  that  to  say  that  under  the 
same  circumstances  the  same  event  will  take  place,  is  an  iden- 
tical assertion.  But  that  the  assertion  should  be  thus  identical 
supposes  that  circumstances  do  constitute  the  act  or  event ;  i.e. 
it  sets  aside  and  ignores  an  original  motion  of  the  will  under 
the  circumstances,  as  if  it  had  no  place  in  the  question,  and 
there  were  no  such  thing :  which  is  the  necessitarian  assump- 
tion. The  Archbishop  slightly  qualifies  his  remark  indeed, 
and  only  calls  the  two  assertions  nearly  identical :  the  asser- 
tion that  the  same  event  must  take  place  under  the  same  cir- 
cumstances "  amounts  to  little  more  than  an  expansion  of  the 
axiom  that  it  is  impossible  for  the  same  thing  to  be  and  not 
to  be."  But  surely  the  two  assertions  must  be  either  abso- 
lutely and  completely  identical,  or  not  at  all.  For  if  it  is  not 
true,  wholly  and  entirely,  that  identity  of  circumstances  is  the 
identity  of  the  act,  what  is  the  reason  of  this  defect  of  truth  ? 


CHAP.  VIII. ] 


OF   FREEWILL. 


219 


It  is  —  for  there  can  be  no  other, —  that  there  is  an  original 
motion  of  the  will,  which  may  be  different  in  spite  of  the 
circumstances  being  the  same.  But  if  there  is  an  original 
motion  of  the  will  in  the  case,  then  the  whole  position  that 
the  same  circumstances  will  produce  the  same  event  or  act 
falls  at  once  to  the  ground  ;  another  principle  comes  in,  which 
altogether  upsets  the  necessary  force  of  circumstances,  and 
produces  the  widest  possible  differences  of  acts  under  circum- 
stances exactly  the  same.1 

The  writer,  indeed,  appears  to  think  that  the  admission 
of  the  fact  of  the  will,  or  "  voluntary  action,"  is  itself  a  safe- 
guard against  necessitarianism ;  and  that  necessitarians  have 
to  be  driven  by  argument  into  the  acknowledgment  of  this 
fact ;  the  admission  of  which,  when  they  are  forced  to  see  and 
confess  it,  makes  them  virtually  cease  to  be  such.  But  all 
necessitarians  acknowledge  in  limine,  and  without  any  dif- 


1  A  position  maintained  in  another 
passage  in  Archbp.  Whately's  Essay, 
is  in .  tendency  and  language,  necessi- 
tarian, though  it  admits  of  an  expla- 
nation. "  But  some  may  say,  have  I 
the  power  of  choosing  among  several 
motives  at  once  present  to  my  mind  ? 
or  must  I  obey  the  strongest?  for  if  so, 
how  can  I  enjoy  freewill  ?  Here,  again, 
Is  an  entanglement  in  ambiguous  words: 
*  must '  and  '  obey  '  and  '  strongest ' 
suggest  the  idea  (which  belongs  to 
them  in  their  primary  sense)  of  com- 
pulsion, and  of  one  person  submitting 
to  another ;  whereas  here  they  are  only 
used  figuratively,  the  terms  '  weak  ' 
and  'strong,'  when  applied  to  motives, 
denoting  nothing  but  their  greater  or 
less  tendency  to  prevail  (that  is,  to 
operate  and  take  effect}  in  practice  ;  so 
th'.it  to  say  <  the  stronger  motive  pre- 
vails' is  only  another  form  of  saying 
that  '  that  which  p.-evails  prevails  ! '  " 
—  P.  95.  Now,  when  persons  talk  of 
the  stronger  motive  prevailing,  they 
sometimes  make  the  assertion  in  a 
sense  involving  an  original  act  of  the 
.  will  Itself.  A  man  is  drawn  by  some 
strong  temptation  towards  a  had  act, 
while  conscience  dissuades:  the  bad 


motive  is  at  the  first  much  the  stronger 
of  the  two;  he  feels  the  former  as 
almost  overwhelming,  while  the  latter 
is  but  feebly  felt:  but  his  will  now 
comes  in  and  deliberately  increases  and 
strengthens  the  conscientious  motive, 
calling  up  every  consideration  of  pre- 
sent or  future  interest  to  outweigh  the 
other,  and  putting  the  advantages  of 
the  right  side  as  vividly  before  the 
mind  as  possible.  Thus  in  time  what 
was  the  more  feebly  felt  becomes  the 
more  strongly  felt  motive ;  and  the  man 
acts  on  the  right  side.  In  this  sense, 
then,  there  is  no  doctrine  of  necessity 
involved  in  the  position  that  a  man 
must  act  upon  the  strongest  motive. 
For  in  every  act  of  choice  between 
good  and  evil,  the  will  either  docs  or 
does  not  create  this  good  stronger 
motive ;  in  either  case  it  is  the  man's 
will  acting  well  or  ill,  and  not  the 
power  of  externally  caused  motives, 
which  produces  the  result.  But  under- 
standing by  the  term  motive  something 
simply  acting  from  without  upon  the 
mind,  to  say  that  the  stronger  motive 
must  prevail,  is  to  say  that  the  in- 
dividual's act  is  decided  by  causes  out- 
side of  himself. 


220  AUGUSTINIAK   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

ficulty,  the  fact  of  the  will :  indeed,  every  one  of  sound  mind 
must. 

I  will  not,  however,  understand  Archbishop  Whately  in 
this  passage  as  more  than  neutral ;  tolerating  the  necessitarian, 
and  treating  the  question  between  him  and  his  opponent,  pro- 
vided the  fact  of  the  will  is  admitted,  as  one  of  no  importance. 
But  perhaps  even  this  assertion  should  be  modified.  It  is 
true,  indeed,  that,  so  long  as  men  acknowledge  a  will,  re- 
sponsibility, and  moral  obligations,  there  is  nothing  in  neces- 
sitarianism to  interfere  with  practical  religion.  But  still  the 
theory  has  important  consequences  in  theology,  and  largely 
affects  our  idea  of  the  Divine  dealings,  which  it  represents 
under  an  aspect  repulsive  to  our  natural  feeling  and  sense  of 
justice.  And  though  a  mystery  must  be  acknowledged  on 
this  subject,  it  is  a  different  thing  to  hold  the  predestinarian 
doctrine,  as  the  Church  at  large  does,  as  a  mystery  and  with 
a  reserve,  and  to  hold  it  as  a  definite  and  complete  doctrine. 

The  language  of  S.  Augustine  respecting  the  will  may  be 
put  under  two  heads;  under  the  first  of  which  it  does  not 
come  up  to  the  received  doctrine  of  freewill,  and  under  the 
second  is  opposed  to  it. 

I.  First,  freewill,  as  maintained  by  S.  Augustine,  does 
not  mean  so  much  as  the  freewill  above  described,  or  a  self- 
determining  will;  but  only  a  will;  his  language  not  advancing 
beyond  that  point  up  to  which  the  doctrine  of  freewill  and 
the  opposite  doctrine  agree. 

In  examining  the  language  of  Augustine  on  this  subject 
we  must  take  care  to  distinguish  between  what  he  says  of 
the  freewill  of  man  in  his  former  perfect,  and  that  of  man 
in  his  present  corrupt  state.  In  the  book  De  Libero  Ar- 
bitrio,  a  freewill  is  indeed  described  which  comes  up  to  the 
above  definition  of  it  as  original  and  self-determining.  The 
Manichean  there,  not  content  with  the  fact  of  the  human 
will  as  accounting  for  moral  evil  in  the  world,  demands  the 
cause  of  that  will;  and  Augustine  replies:  "  The  will  being 


CJJAP.  VIII.] 


OF    FREEWILL. 


221 


the  cause  of  sin,  you  ask  the  cause  of  the  will :  should  I 
discover  it,  will  you  not  ask  then  the  cause  of  that  cause ;  and 
what  limit  of  inquiry  can  there  be,  if  you  will  go  deeper 
than  the  very  root  ?  .  .  .  What  cause  of  will  can  there  be 
before  will  ?  For  either  this  cause  is  will,  and  we  are  no 
nearer  the  root  than  we  were  before  ;  or  it  is  not  will,  and  in 
that  case  there  is  no  sin."  ]  Here  a  will  is  described  which 
is  truly  an  original  agent  in  nature,  having  no  cause  but 
itself.  But  the  will  thus  described  is  the  will  of  man  in  his 
created,  not  in  his  fallen  state.2  In  some  passages,  again, 
quoted  in  a  former  chapter,  a  will  was  described  which  was 
self-determining  and  original ;  for  it  was  said  that  the  first  man 
"  had  such  an  assistance  given  him  as  he  could  use  if  he 
willed,  and  neglect  if  he  willed ;  not  one  by  which  it  was 
caused  that  he  did  will." 3  His  wil!3  therefore,  had  no 
cause  beyond  itself,  or  was  self- caused,  that  is  to  say,  self- 
determined  and  original :  but  this,  he  expressly  says,  was  the 
will  of  the  first  man  in  his  state  of  integrity,  and  not  of  man 
as  now  existing. 

When  Augustine  comes  to  describe  the  will  of  man  as  now 
existing,  he  describes  it  simply  by  the  fact  of  will  or  willing. 
There  are  various  passages  in  his  works,  especially  a  passage 
in  the  book  De  Libero  Arbitrio,  another  in  the  book  De  Spi- 
ritu  et  Literd,  and  another  in  his  Retractations  explanatory  of 
a  passage  in  the  book  De  Diversis  Qucestionibus  ad  Simpli- 
cianum,  in  which  it  is  defined  with  much  minuteness  and 
labour  what  the  freedom  of  the  will  is,  and  in  what  it  consists; 
and  this  definition  terminates  in  the  fact  of  a  will.  First, 
freedom  itself  is  defined ;  and  it  is  said  to  consist  in  power. 
We  are  free  when  it  is  in  our  power  to  do  a  thing.  But 
what  is  power?  for  it  becomes  necessary  now  to  say  what 
power  is,  if  there  is  anything  to  be  said  about  it.  He  pro- 
ceeds accordingly  to  define  next  what  is  meant  by  its  being 


1  L.  3.  c.  xvii. 

2  Cum   autem    de   libera   voluntate 
faciendi  loquimur,  de  ilia  scilicet  in  qua 


homo    factus   est   loquimur.  —  L.    3. 
c.  18. 

8  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xi. 


222 


AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  VIII. 


in  our  power  to  do  a  thing;  and  this  he  defines  by  saying 
that  it  is  our  having  the  power  to  do  it  if  we  will.  "  What 
need  for  further  question  ?  we  call  that  power  where  to  the 
will  is  joined  the  ability  to  do.  That  is  in  a  man's  power  which 
he  does  if  he  wills,  does  not  do  if  he  does  not  will — quod  si 
vult  facit)  si  non  vult  nonfacit."  l  Freedom  being  thus  defined, 
it  only  remains  to  apply  this  definition  of  freedom  to  the  will, 
which  is  a  simple  and  easy  process.  Freedom  is  a  power  to 
do  a  thing  if  we  wilL  Freedom  of  the  will,  therefore,  is  the 
power  to  will  if  we  will — a  power,  he  adds,  which  unques- 
tionably every  man  possesses ;  for  if  we  will,  we  are  neces- 
sarily not  only  able  to  will,  but  do  will :  there  is  the  act  itself 
of  willing,  and  therefore  certainly  the  power  for  it.2  "  It 
must  be  that  when  we  will,  we  will  with  freewill  —  necesse 
est  ut  cum  volumus,  libero  velimus  arbitrio"  3 

The  definition  of  freewill  thus  stops  at  the  fact  of  will 
as  the  ultimate  truth  beyond  which  nothing  can  be  said ; 
the  basis  of  this  definition  of  will  being  a  particular  defini- 
tion of  power.  The  question  of  freedom  is  first  correctly 
stated  as  being  a  question  of  power — what  it  is  which 
constitutes  the  power  to  act  in  this  or  that  way ;  and  the 
constitution  of  power  is  decided  by  making  the  will  a 
necessary  element  in  it.  A  distinction  is  acknowledged, 
indeed,  between  power  and  will;  but  a  man  is  still  not 
allowed  to  have  the  whole  power  to  do  a  thing  unless  he 
has  the  will  also — ut  potestate  aliquid  Jiat  voluntas  aderit  ; 
"  in  order  that  anything  may  be  done  by  power,  there  must 
be  the  will ; "  and  will  is  a  condition  of  power  and  a  true 
ingredient  in  its  composition.  Freedom  is  thus  first 
defined  by  power,  and  power  is  then  conditionated  upon 


1  "  Quid  igitur  ultra  quaerimus : 
quandoquidem  hanc  dicimus  potes- 
tatem,  ubi  voluntati  adjacet  facultas 
faciendi?  Unde  hoc  quisque  in  potes- 
tate habere  dicitur,  quod  si  vult  facit, 
Bi  non  vult,  non  facit." —  De  Spir.  ct 
Lit.  c.  xxxi. 


2  Nihil  tarn  in  nostra  potestate 
quam  ipsa  voluntas  est.  Ea  enim 
prorsus  nullo  intervallo  mox  ut  vo- 
lumus  praesto  est.  — De  Lib.  Arb.  1.  3. 
c.  3, 

8  De  Civit.  Dei.  1.  5.  c.  10. 


CHAP.  VIII.  j 


OF    FREEWILL. 


223 


will,  and  there  the  definition  stops  *,  leaving  the  ultimate 
test  of  freewill,  and,  as  all  that  is  meant  by  it,  simple  will. 
We  have  freewill  or  the  power  to  will  if  we  will. 

It  will  be  seen  that  this  definition  of  freewill  exactly 
coincides  with  Locke's,  quoted  above.  Both  writers  define 
freedom  to  be  the  power  of  doing  what  we  will;  Augus- 
tine's ubi  voluntati  adjacet  facultas  faciendi  just  tallying  with 
Locke's  "  How  can  we  think  any  one  freer  than  to  have 
the  power  to  do  what  he  will  ?  "  Both  writers,  applying  this 
freedom  to  the  will,  immediately  discover  the  freedom 
of  the  will  to  consist  in  willing  as  it  wills:  Augustine 
saying,  "  Nildl  tarn  in  nostra  potestate  quam  ipsa  voluntas  est ; 
ea  enim  prorsus  nullo  intervallo  mox  ut  volumus  prcesto  est :  " 
Locke  stating  freewill  as  "  the  man's  liberty  to  will  which 
of  the  two  things  lie  pleases"  and  challenging  any  one  to  ask 
"  whether  freedom  itself  were  free." 

Augustine  meets  the  difficulty  raised  against  the  freedom 
of  the  will  from  the  Divine  foreknowledge  with  the  same 
answer ;  viz.  that  as  a  matter  of  fact  we  have  will,  and  that 
will  is  as  such  free.  "  Whatever  may  be  the  tortuous  wrang- 
lings  and  disputes  of  philosophers,  we,  as  we  acknowledge 
one  supreme  and  true  God,  so  acknowledge  His  supreme  will, 
power,  and  foreknowledge.  Nor  do  we  fear  on  that  account 
that  we  do  not  do  with  our  will  what  we  do  with  our  will  — 
nee  timemus  ne  ideo  non  voluntate  faciamus,  quod  voluntate 

facimus We  say  both  that  God  knows  all  things 

before  they  take  place,  and  that  we  act  with  our  will, 
inasmuch  as  we  feel  and  know  we  do  not  act  except  with 
our  will."'2 

This,  however,  being  S.  Augustine's  definition  of  freewill, 
it  must  be  admitted  that  a  considerable  body  of  language, 


1  A  dictum  of  S.  Anselm's,  expresses 
the  principle  of  it  scientifically—  In 
libero  arbitrio  posse  non  prcecedit  sed 
sequitur  voluntatem.  The  will  is  the 


original  supposition,  on  which  the  defi- 
nition of  power  is  raised. 
*  De  Civ.  Dei,  1.  5.  c.  9. 


224 


AUGUST1NIAN    DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  VIIL 


especially  his  language  at  the  commencement  of  the  book 
De  Gratia  et  Libero  Arbitrio,  and  in  the  two  Epistles l 
relating  to  the  occasion  on  which  that  book  was  written, 
appears  at  first  sight  to  advance  upon  this  definition,  and 
to  imply  an  original  and  self-determining  power  in  the  will. 
He  argues  for  freewill  as  a  doctrine  of  Scripture,  and  uses 
the  common  arguments  which  tlie  main  tamers  of  the  ordi- 
nary doctrine  of  freewill  use ;  viz.  that  Scripture  employs 
commands,  promises,  and  threats,  and  speaks  to  men  as  if 
they  had  freewill.  Such  an  argument  proves  that  he — 
i.e.  Scripture  as  interpreted  by  him — acknowledges  a  will 
in  man  which  is  truly  and  properly  the  subject  of  com- 
mands, promises,  and  threats ;  and  can  such  a  will,  it  may 
be  asked,  be  anything  but  a  self-determining  one?  Does 
not  such  a  mode  of  addressing  man  suppose  an  original 
power  of  choice  in  him  ?  But  though  this  w^ould  be  sound 
and  correct  as  a  popular  inference  from  such  language, 
it  is  not  as  a  logical  one.  Logically  all  that  can  be 
inferred  from  the  use  of  commands  and  threats  in  the  Divine 
dealings  with  man  is,  that  man  has  a  capacity  for  choosing, 
obeying,  and  acting  upon  motives  2 ;  but  these  are  operations 
of  the  will,  and  are  wholly  performed,  if  there  is  only  a  will 
to  perform  them,  without  going  into  the  question  what 
decides  that  will.  If  man  has  a  will,  which  will  is  intended 
to  act  in  the  particular  way  of  choice  and  obedience,  he 


1  Ep.  214,  215. 

*  Non  eodem  modo  se  habent  Deus  et 
homo  ad  reddendum  prsemium.  Homo 
namque  sicut  Rex  publico  edicto  pro- 
mulgat,  monetque  ipse  indiflferens  et 
indeterminatus  in  voluntate  sua  circa 
sibi  subjectos.  .  .  .  Non  sic  autem 
Deus.  Semper  aeque  determinate  vult. 
Per  meritum  innotescit  hominibus, 
daemonibus,  et  forsitan  Angelis,  quale 
premium  quis  habebit.  .  .  .  Cum 
dicitur,  Deus  vult  istum  propter  merita 
pnemiarc,  hoc  est,  Deus  vult  istum 


prsemiare  propter  merita  final iter  or- 
dinanda,  i.e.  vult  quod  tails  sit  finis 
talium  meritorum  secundum  ordinem 
ab  ipso  talibus  preestitutum,  ita  quod 
merita  nullo  modo  antecedenter,  cau- 
saliter,  a  priori,  monent,  determinant, 
vel  actuant  voluntatem  divinam  ad 
pramia  reddenda.  .  .  .  Deus  primo 
vult  homini  premium  et  gloriam  tan- 
quam  finem,  et  ideo  vult  sibi  et  facit 
merita  congrua." —  Bradwardine,  p. 
150.  et  seq. 


CHAP.  VIII.  ]  OF   FREEWILL.  225 

must  be  addressed  in  a  manner  suitable  to  such  a  design ; 
he  must  be  commanded,  in  order  that  he  may  obey,  and  he 
must  have  the  alternative  placed  before  him  in  order  that  He 
choose.  But  such  a  mode  of  addressing  him  does  not  neces- 
sarily prove  any  more  than  that  he  is  possessed  of  a  will  to 
which  those  operations  belong.  While,  therefore,  in  the  case 
of  Scripture  we  are  justified  in  taking  such  language  to  imply 
an  original  and  self-determining  \vill  in  man,  because  Scripture 
is  addressed  to  the  popular  understanding,  and  this  is  the 
popular  inference  to  draw  from  such  language;  in  the  case 
of  a  philosophical  writer  like  Augustine, — who  treats  of 
the  human  will  and  the  questions  belonging  to  it  in  a 
scientific  and  subtle  way,  and  from  whose  language  therefore 
we  are  not  justified  in  inferring  more  than  it  logically 
contains, —  we  cannot  take  it  as  implying  more  than  the 
existence  of  a  will  in  a  man. 

Indeed,  the  fact  of  a  will  is  all  the  conclusion  which 
he  himself  arrives  at  by  this  argument,  and  all  that  he 
presses  upon  his  readers. *  "  These  commands  would  not 
be  given  unless  man  had  a  will  truly  belonging  to  him 
with  which  to  obey  them  —  nisi  homo  haberet  propriam 
voluntatem,  qua  divinis  prceceptis  obediret" —  "  To  the  man 
who  says  I  cannot  do  what  is  commanded,  because  he  is 
conquered  by  concupiscence,  the  Apostle  says,  f  Will  not 
to  be  overcome  of  evil,  but  overcome  evil  with  good ; ' 
'  will  not  to  be  overcome  —  noli  vinci  implying  certainly 
a  choice  of  his  will;  for  to  will  and  not  to  will  is  of  the 
individual's  will — arbitrium  voluntatis  ejus  sine  dubio  conveni- 
tur,  velle  enim  et  nolle  propria  voluntatis  est" — "  Freewill 
is  sufficiently  proved  by  Scripture  saying,  will  not  this, 
and  will  not  that,  and  demanding  an  act  of  the  will  in 
doing  or  not  doing  anything.  Let  no  one  then  blame  God 
in  his  heart,  but  impute  it  to  himself  when  he  sins. 
Nor,  when  he  does  anything  according  to  God's  will,  let 


1  De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.  c.  ii.  et  seq. 
Q 


226  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

him  alienate  it  from  his  own.  For  when  he  does  it 
willingly,  then  it  is  a  good  work,  then  a  reward  attaches 
to  it  —  quando  volens  facit  tune  dicendum  est  opus  bonum" 
Again  on  the  text  ((  All  men  cannot  receive  this  saying,  save 
they  to  whom  it  is  given  ;  "  he  says,  "  Those  to  whom  it  is 
not  given  either  will  not  or  do  not  what  they  will :  those  to 
whom  it  is  given  so  will  that  they  do  what  they  will. 
That  which  is  not  received*  by  all,  but  is  received  by  some, 
is  both  the  gift  of  God  and  also  is  freewill — et  Dei  donum 
est)  et  liberum  arbitrium*  That  is  to  say,  it  is  freewill 
in  him,  because,  from  whatever  source  it  comes,  when  he 
has  it,  it  is  his  own  will.  These  explanations  all  appeal  to 
the  fact  of  a  will  in  man,  as  being  sufficient  to  constitute 
a  free  agent,  and  a  proper  subject  of  promises  or  threats, 
of  reward  or  punishment.  Indeed,  what  these  arguments 
are  designed  to  remove  is  not  any  part  of  the  predestinarian 
doctrine,  but  only  a  false  practical  inference  from  it;  for 
the  occasion  on  which  this  treatise  was  written  was,  that 
certain  persons  had  begun  to  argue,  that  if  that  doctrine  was 
true,  it  did  not  signify  what  kind  of  lives  men  led,  because 
they  were  not  responsible  for  them.  Augustine  corrects  this 
inference  by  reminding  them,  that  the  predestinarian  doctrine 
did  not  exclude  a  will  in  man ;  and  that  if  he  had  a  will,  that 
made  him  responsible. 

Augustine's  doctrine  of  freewill,  then,  does  not  come  up 
to  that  which  is  ordinarily  understood  as  that  doctrine ;  not 
advancing  beyond  that  point  up  to  which  the  doctrine  of 
freewill  and  the  opposite  doctrine  agree.  He  acknow- 
ledges a  will  in  man,  that  which  makes  him  act  willingly, 
as  distinguished  from  acting  by  compulsion  and  constraint ; 
but  this  is  saying  nothing  as  to  how  that  will  is  determined. 

II.  But,  in  the  second  place,  we  come  to  the  question  of 
the  determination  of  this  will,  and  under  this  head  Augus- 
tine's language  is  not  only  less  than,  but  is  opposed  to,  the 
common  doctrine  of  freewill. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  OF  FREEWILL.  227 

The  doctrine  of  freewill  is,  as  has  been  stated,  that  the 
will  has  a  self-determining  power,  which  produces  right  acts 
or  wrong,  according  as  it  is  exercised.  On  the  other  hand, 
the  opponents  of  the  doctrine  of  freewill  object  that  this 
is  an  absurd  and  self-contradictory  cause  to  assign  to  human 
actions  ;  for  that,  if  the  power  of  acting  one  way  or  another 
be  the  cause  of  the  distinction  in  human  actions,  —  z.  e.  of  the 
good  or  bad  act  which  really  ensues, — the  same  cause,  can 
produce  opposite  effects.  The  objection  proceeds  on  the 
assumption  that  human  actions  must  have  a  cause;  which 
granted,  it  follows  of  course  that  such  a  cause  cannot  be  a 
neutral  or  flexible  thing,  as  this  freewill  or  power  of  choice 
is  described  to  be. 

Now,  there  is  a  passage,  which  I  have  already  quoted  *, 
in  which  the  doctrine  of  freewill,  as  thus  stated,  comes  under 
the  notice  of  Augustine.  The  doctrine  is  stated  in  this 
passage  thus:  that  "  We  have  a  power  of  taking  either  side  — 
possibilitas  utriusque  partis, — implanted  in  us  by  God,  as  a 
fruitful  and  productive  root,  to  produce  and  bring  forth 
according  to  men's  different  wills,  and  either  shine  with  the 
flower  of  virtue,  or  bristle  with  the  thorns  of  vice,  according 
to  the  choice  of  the  cultivator."  This  is  a  plain  statement 
of  the  ordinary  doctrine  of  freewill.  There  is  a  power  of 
taking  either  side  inherent  in  our  nature;  that  power  deter- 
mines our  wills,  and  according  as  our  wills  are  determined 
we  do  good  or  bad  actions.  To  this  doctrine,  then,  thus 
stated,  Augustine  objects  on  the  same  ground  as  that  which 
has  been  just  mentioned,  viz.,  that  it  gives  an  absurd  and 
self-contradictory  cause  to  human  actions.  Such  a  doctrine 
he  says,  "  establishes  one  and  the  same  root  of  the  good  and 
the  bad, —  unam  eandemque  radicem  constitute  bonorum  et 
malorum."  That  is,  he  says,  it  maintains  one  and  the  same 
ultimate  or  original  condition  of  the  man,  out  of  which  the 


1  De  Gratia  Christi,  c.~  18. 
Q  2 


228 


AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  VIII. 


opposite  lives  and  actions  of  the  two  issue  ;  to  maintain  which 
is  to  give  the  same  cause  to  opposite  effects.  Augustine's  argu- 
ment proceeds  on  the  supposition  of  the  necessity  of  a  cause 
for  human  actions,  and  is  substantially  the  same  argument 
with  that  used  by  Edwards,  that  "an  act  of  the  will  cannot 
directly  and  immediately  arise  out  of  a  state  of  indifference ;  " 
because  the  act  implies  "  an  antecedent  choice,"  which  choice 
cannot  be  simultaneous  with  indifference  *; —  the  assumption 
in  this  latter  argument  being  that  actions  must  have  a 
cause  out  of  which  they  spring;  which  cause  can  only  be 
calculated  to  produce  one  effect,  and  not  either  one  or 
the  other  of  two  effects.  The  advocates  of  freewill,  on  the 
other  hand,  do  not  admit  this  assumption,  and  so  answer 
the  argument  which  is  raised  upon  it.  They  allow  that 
this  power  of  choice  is  no  cause  of  the  determination  of  the 
will,  nor  do  they  profess  it  to  be  such ;  but  they  maintain 
that  for  a  determination  of  the  will  one  way  or  another,  it  is 
not  necessary  to  assign  a  cause,  such  determination  being 
an  original  motion  of  the  will.  It  must  be  added,  however, 
that  in  using  such  an  argument  as  this,  Augustine  is 
inconsistent,  for  he  admits  in  the  case  of  the  first  man  this 
power,  this  freewill  in  the  complete  sense,  this  power  of 
either  side;  appealing  to  it,  as  throwing  the  responsibility 
of  sin  upon  him,  and  removing  it  from  God;  after  which 
admission,  he  is  properly  precluded  from  arguing  upon 
abstract  grounds  against  such  a  power. 

The  power  of  choice,  as  the  account  of  the  evil  and 
good  actions  and  lives  of  men,  being  thus  set  aside,  S. 
Augustine  proceeds  to  lay  down  a  rationale  of  two  different 


1  "  If  the  act  springs  immediately  out 
of  a  state  of  indifference,  then  it  does 
not  arise  from  antecedent  choice  or  pre- 
ference. But  if  the  act  arises  directly 
out  of  a  state  of  indifference,  without 
any  intervening  choice  to  determine  it, 
then  the  act  not  being  determined  by 
choice  is  not  determined  by  the  will." 
.  .  An  antecedent  choice,  then,  he  says, 
must  be  granted.  But  if  it  is,  "  if  the 


soul,  \vhile  it  yet  remains  in  a  state 
of  perfect  indifference,  chooses  to  put 
itself  out  of  that  state  and  to  turn 
itself  one  way,  then  the  soul  is  already 
come  to  a  choice,  and  chooses  that  way, 
And  so  the  soul  is  in  a  state  of  choice, 
and  in  a  state  of  equilibrium,  both  at 
the  same  time." — On  the  Freedom  of 
the  Will,  part  ii.  sect.  7. 


CHAP.  VIII.] 


OF   FREEWILL. 


229 


roots  or  causes  for  the  two.  "  Our  Lord  says,  that  a  good 
tree  cannot  bring  forth  evil  fruit,  nor  an  evil  tree  good 
fruit.  And  the  Apostle  Paul,  when  he  says  that  cupidity 
is  the  root  of  all  evil,  intimates  also  that  love  is  the  root  of 
all  good.  If  therefore  the  two  trees  good  and  evil  are  two 
men  good  and  evil,  what  is  the  good  man  but  the  man  of 
good  will ;  that  is,  the  tree  of  good  fruit  ?  And  what  is 
the  evil  man  but  the  man  of  an  evil  will;  that  is,  the 
tree  of  an  evil  root?  And  the  fruits  of  these  two  trees 
are  acts,  words,  thoughts,  which  if  good  proceed  from 
a  good  will,  and  if  evil  from  an  evil  will.  And  man 
makes  a  good  tree  when  he  receives  the  grace  of  God. 
For  he  does  not  make  himself  good  out  of  evil  by  him- 
self; but  of  Him,  and  through  Him,  and  in  Him  who  is 

good And  he  makes  an  evil   tree,  when  he  makes 

himself  evil,  when  he  departs  from  immutable  good;  for 
the  origin  of  an  evil  will  is  that  departure." l  In  this 
passage  the  lives  and  actions  of  the  good  and  evil  man  are 
referred  in  the  first  place  to  two  immediate  or  proximate 
roots,  and  then  to  two  ultimate  or  original  ones.  The 
proximate  roots  of  the  two  respectively  are  a  good  and  evil 
will,  which  he  calls  also  love  and  cupidity.  The  original 
roots,  or  those  from  which  this  good  and  evil  will  themselves 
spring,  are  grace  and  sin.  "  Man  makes  a  good  tree  or  root, 


1  Habemus  autem,  inquit,  possi- 
bilitatem  utriusque  partis  a  Deo  insitam, 
velut  quandam,  ut  ita  dicam,  radicem 
fructiferam  atque  fecundam  qua  ex 
voluntate  hominis  diversa  gignat  et 
pariat,  et  quse  possit  ad  proprli  cultoris 
arbitrium,  vel  nitere  flore  virtutum, 
vel  sentibus  horrere  vitiorum.  Ubi  non 
intuens  quod  loquatur,  unam  eandemque 
radicem  constituit  bonorum  et  malorum, 
contra  evangelicam  veritatem  doctri- 
namque  apostolicam.  Nam  et  Dominus 
nee  arborem  bonam  dicit  posse  facere 
fructus  malos,  nee  malam  bonos ;  et 
Apostolus  Paul  us  cum  dicit  radicem 
malorum  omnium  esse  cupiditatem, 
admonet  utique  intelligi  radieem  bono- 
rum omnium  charitatem.  Unde  si 


duae  arbores  bona  et  mala  sunt,  duo 
homines,  bonus  et  malus,  quid  est 
bonus  homo,  nisi  voluntatis  bonae,  hoc 
est  arbor  radicis  bonas?  et  quid  est 
homo  malus,  nisi  voluntatis  malae, 
haac  est  arbor  radicis  malae?  Fructutf 
autem  harum  radicum  atque  arbo- 
rum  facta  sunt,  dicta  sunt,  cogitata 
sunt,  quaa  bona  de  bona  voluntate 
procedunt,  et  mala  de  mala.  Facit 
autem  homo  arborem  bonam,  quando 
Dei  accipit  gratiam.  Non  autem  se 
ex  malo  bonum  per  seipsum  facit,  sed 
in  illo  et  per  ilium,  et  in  illo  qui 
semper  est  bonus.  .  .  .  Malam  vero 
arborem  facit  quando  seipsum  malum 
facit,  quando  a  bono  immutabili  deficit, 
—  De  Gratia  Cnristi,  c.  18,  19. 


Q   3 


230  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

[tree  and  root  being  synonymous  here]  when  he  receives  the 
grace  of  God  ;  for  he  does  not  make  himself  good  by  himself, 
but  of  Him :  "  that  is,  his  own  preparation  of  his  will,  by 
which  he  makes  it  a  good  will,  is  itself  derived  from  grace ; 
man  is  the  immediate,  but  grace  the  original  agent.  On  the 
other  hand,  "  Man  makes  an  evil  tree  or  root  when  he  makes 
himself  evil,  and  departs  from  immutable  good,"  as  he  did 
by  his  transgression  in  Paradise,  for  so  the  general  doctrine 
of  Augustine  interprets  this  allusion.  A  rationale  of  two 
different  roots  or  causes  of  the  lives  of  good  and  evil  men 
is  thus  laid  down,  in  the  place  of  one  and  the  same  moral 
condition  out  of  which  they  are  supposed  to  arise  on  the 
doctrine  of  freewill. 

The  same  argument  is  repeated  in  a  passage  from  the 
book  De  Peccatorum  Mentis  et  Remissions:  "It  is  strange 
if  the  will  can  stand  at  a  certain  point  midway,  so  as  to  be 
neither  good  nor  bad  —  voluntas  mirum  si  potest  in  media 
quodam  ita  consistere,  ut  nee  bona  nee  mala  sit.  For  either 
we  love  righteousness,  and  it  is  good,  or  we  do  not  love 
righteousness,  and  it  is  bad ;  the  bad  will  not  coming  from 
God,  the  good  one  coming  from  God,  and  being  the  gift 
whereby  we  are  justified  ...  a  gift  which  to  whomsoever 
God  gives  it,  He  gives  in  His  mercy,  and  from  whomsoever 
He  withholds  it,  He  withholds  it  in  His  judgment  .  .  . 
for  the  law  of  His  secret  justice  rests  with  Him  alone."  * 
The  writer  here  refuses  to  comprehend  a  neutral,  and  simply 
determinable  will,  arid,  setting  aside  such  a  rationale  of  human 
conduct,  lays  down  two  separate  wills,  good  and  bad,  which 
have  each  possession  of  the  agent  prior  to  all  action. 

These  two  distinct  wills,  or  roots  or  causes  of  human 
action,  then,  are,  as  has  already  appeared,  and  as  the  whole 
doctrine  of  Augustine  shows,  original  sin  and  grace. 

I.  The  will  of  fallen  man  is  determined  to  evil  by  a  cause 


De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Rem.  1.  2.  c   18. 


CHAP.  VIII.] 


OF    FREEWILL. 


231 


out  of  and  beyond  the  personal  will  or  the  will  of  the  indi- 
vidual ;  i.  e.  by  the  transgression  of  the  first  man,  or  original 
sin ;  which  captive  will,  however,  is,  notwithstanding,  freewill, 
for  the  following  reasons. 

In  the  first  place,  Augustine  defends  its  freedom  upon 
the  simple  ground  which  has  been  maintained.  In  reply 
to  the  Pelagian,  who  presses  him  continually  with  the  con- 
sequences of  his  doctrine,  and  asks  how  a  being,  who  is  lite- 
rally unable  to  turn  to  good  from  the  moment  of  his  birth, 
can  be  treated  as  a  free  agent  and  responsible  for  his  acts, 
he  answers  simply  that  he  is  so,  inasmuch  as  he  has  a  will. 
He  does  what  he  does  with  his  will,  and  not  against  it.  No 
force  has  compelled  him  to  act  contrary  to  his  inclination,  but 
he  has  acted  according  to  his  inclination.  He  has  therefore 
acted  as  a  free  agent,  and  he  is  responsible  for  his  acts. 
What  more  is  wanted  for  responsibility  than  that  a  man  has 
acted  willingly,  and  without  constraint  ?  "  Why  perplex  a  very 
plain  subject.  He  is  free  for  evil  (i.  e.  a  free  agent  in  doing 
evil)  who  acts  with  an  evil  will.  He  is  free  for  good  (i.  e.  a 
free  agent  in  doing  good)  who  acts  with  a  good  will."1 — 
"  Men  are  not  forced  by  the  necessity  of  the  flesh  into  sin,  as 
if  they  were  unwilling  (quasi  inviti)  ;  but  if  they  are  of  an  age 
to  use  their  own  choice,  they  are  both  retained  in  sin  by  their 
will,  and  precipitated  from  one  sin  to  another  by  their  will. 
For  he  who  persuades  and  deceives  them  does  not  work 
anything  in  them,  but  that  they  sin  with  their  will."  3  —  "  The 
will  is  that  with  which  we  sin,  and  with  which  we  live  well 


1  Quid   aperta  implicas    loquacitate 
perplexa?     Ad  malum    liber   est,    qui 
voluntate  agit  mala  :  ad  bonum  autem 
liber   est  qui  voluntate  agit  bona.  — 
Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  120. 

2  "  Non    itaque,   sicut    dicunt     nos 
quidem  dicere,    et  iste   audet   insuper 
scribere,  'omnes    in   peccatum,    velut 
inviti,  carnis  suzc  necessitate  coguntur  : ' 
sed,  si  jam  in  ea  astate  sunt  ut  propviae 
mentis  utantur  arbitrio,  et  in  peccato 


sua  voluntate  retinentur,  et  a  peccato 
in  peccatum  sua  voluntate  pra?cipitantur. 
Neque  enim  agit  in  eis  qui  suadet  et 
decipit,  nisi  ut  peccatum  voluntate 
committant." — Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  I. 
c.  3. 

"Liberum  arbitrium  usque  adeo  in 
peccatore  non  periit,ut  per  illud  peccent, 
maxime  omnes  qui  cum  delectatione 
peccant."— Ibid.  1.  1.  c.  2. 


232 


AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE 


[CuAr.  VIII. 


—  voluntas  est  qua  et  peccatur  et  recte  vivitur."  1  It  is  enough 
for  freedom,  according  to  these  statements,  if  we  sin  by  or 
with  the  consent  of  our  will. 

Another  answer  to  this  difficulty  is  more  subtle  and  intricate. 
The  sin  of  our  nature  is  voluntary,  and  men  are  responsible 
for  it,  because  this  sin  proceeds  from  a  self-determining 
human  will  in  the  first  instance ;  the  sin  of  the  first  man  or 
the  original  sin  having  been  committed  when  man  had  a 
self-determining  will.  The  root  or  origin,  therefore,  of  sin  is 
entirely  free,  and  it  must  be  judged  by  its  root  or  origin. 
Subsequently,  indeed,  to  its  origin,  sin  becomes  not  free  in 
this  sense,  but  necessary,  and  our  nature  is  captive  to  it :  but 
this  does  not  undo  the  freedom,  of  its  origin.  "  Sin  cannot 
be  without  the  will,  in  the  same  way  in  which  we  say  that  the 
fruit  cannot  be  without  the  root.  .  .  .  Without  the  will  of  him 
(Adam)  from  whom  is  the  origin  of  all  that  live,  the  original 
sin  was  not  committed.  But  the  contagion  of  it  could  pass  to 
others  without  the  will.  It  must  exist  with  the  will,  in  order 
that  it  might  pass  to  others  without  the  will,  as  a  tree  must 
have  a  root  below,  in  order  that  it  may  be  above  without  a 
root.  .  .  .  Sin  is  both  with  the  will  and  without  the  will  :  it 
is  with  the  will  in  so  far  as  it  must  begin  to  be  with  it ;  it  is 
without  the  will  in  so  far  as  it  remains  without  it."  2  When  it 
is  said  in  this  passage  that  sin  remains  without  the  will,  it  is 
not  of  course  meant  that  it  remains  apart  from  all  will  what- 
ever, for  some  kind  of  will  must  go  along  with  a  sinful  act  to 
make  it  the  man's  act ;  but  will  is  here  used  in  the  highest 
sense  as  a  self-determining  will,  such  a  will  as  the  first  man 
in  his  perfect  state  had.  The  meaning  of  this  passage,  then, 
is  this:  that  sin  began  in  a  self-determining  will;  and  that, 


1  Retract.  1.  1.  c.  9. 

2  Ego  sic  dixi  peccatum  sine  volun- 
tate  esse  non  posse,  quomodo  dicimus 
poma  vel  frumenta  sine  radicibus  esse 
non    posse.  .  .   .  Sine   voluntate    esse 
non  posset,  ut  e«set  quod  in  alios  sine 
voluntate    transiret ;    sicut    frumenta 
sine    radicibus  esse   non    possent,    ut 


essent  quae  in  alia  loca  transire  sine 
radicibus  possent.  .  .  .  Sine  voluntate 
non  potest  esse,  nam  sine  voluntate  non 
potest  existere  ut  sit;  sine  autem  vo- 
luntate potest  esse,  quia  sine  voluntate 
potest  manere  quod  existit. —  Op.  Imp, 
1.  4.  cc.  97.  99. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  OF    FREEWILL.  233 

therefore,  though  when  once  existing,  it  remains  in  the  human 
race  without  such  a  will,  it  ever  carries  about  with  it  the 
freedom  and  responsibility  of  its  commencement.  The  human 
will  is  viewed  as  one  stream  of  will,  so  to  call  it,  flowing 
first  from  a  fountain  head  in  the  will  of  the  first  man,  as 
he  came  from  the  hands  of  his  Creator,  undergoing  a  change 
of  its  powers  and  condition  at  the  fall,  and  with  that  internal 
change  passing  into  all  the  individual  members  of  the  human 
race,  as  they  are  successively  born.  At  its  fountain  head 
this  will  is  self-determining  and  free  in  the  complete  sense ; 
but  at  the  fall  it  loses  this  freedom,  and  receives  into  itself 
an  inclination  to  evil,  which  operates  necessarily.  Thus 
biassed,  it  passes  into  the  successive  generations  of  individual 
men,  as  they  are  born,  constituting  them  sinful  beings, 
and  issuing  in  sinful  desires  and  acts.  If  mankind  complain, 
then,  of  this  captive  condition,  and  ask  why,  when  their  will 
acts  under  a  necessity  they  are  treated  as  free  and  responsible 
beings  subject  to  punishment  for  their  acts,  they  are  told 
that  their  will  was  originally  free  and  self- determining  ;  that 
it  only  lost  that  power  by  its  own  fault ;  and  that  a  loss 
which  it  has  brought  upon  itself  does  not  give  it  immunity. 
An  analogy  is  instituted  between  the  effect  of  original  sin 
upon  the  will,  and  the  effect  of  habit  or  custom.  The  will 
of  the  man  who  is  born  under  the  influence  of  original  sin 
is  treated  as  identical  with  the  will  which  committed  that  sin  ; 
just  as  the  will  of  an  individual  who  is  under  the  force  of  a  bad 
habit  is  identical  with  the  will  which  contracted  that  habit. 
And  this  view  accounts  for  an  apparent  contradiction  which 
we  meet  with  in  Augustine,  in  speaking  of  the  will.  He 
talks  of  will  as  being  essentially  original  and  the  cause 
of  itself,  or  self-determining ;  being  this,  as  being  will 1 ; 
and  he  also  speaks  of  will  as  if  the  fact  of  a  will,  whatever 
were  its  cause,  made  a  true  and  genuine  will.  He  is  first 
spenking  of  will  as  a  whole,  and  secondly  of  will  in  a  parti- 


P.  221. 


234  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

cular  stage.  Will  as  a  whole  must  be  original  and  self-deter- 
mining ;  that  is,  there  must  have  been  a  time  in  the  history 
of  the  will  when  it  was  so :  otherwise  we  make  sin  simply 
necessary  in  the  world,  and  fasten  its  authorship  on  the 
Deity.  But  will  in  a  particular  stage  or  condition  may  be 
the  conscious  fact  of  willing,  and  no  more,  acting  really  under 
a  necessity.  Such  an  explanation,  however,  is  wholly 
mystical. 

II.  The  will  of  man  is  determined  to  good  by  grace,  and 
yet  it  is  freewill ;  just  as  his  will,  when  so  determined  by  ori- 
ginal sin  to  evil,  was  free :  because  it  is  true  will ;  because  the 
man  acts  willingly  and  without  constraint.  "  The  human 
will  is  not  taken  away,  but  is  changed  from  evil  to  good  by 
grace  —  voluntas  humana  non  tollitur,  sed  ex  mala  mutatur  in 
bonam"  *  —  "  Freewill  is  one  of  the  gifts  of  God ;  not  only 
itself  but  the  goodness  of  it  —  non  tantum  ut  sit  sed  etiam  ut 
bonum  sit" 2  —  "It  is  certain  that  when  we  will,  we  will ;  but 
it  is  He  who  makes  us  to  will  —  cerium  est  nos  velle  cum  volu- 
mus,  sed  illefacit  ut  velimus  bonum.  It  is  certain  that  when  we 
do  we  do  ;  but  He  makes  us  to  do,  by  giving  the  most  effective 
strength  to  the  will —  cerium  est  nos  facer e  cumfacimus,  sed 
ille  facit  utfaciamus,  prcebendo  vires  efficacissimas  voluntati."3 — 
"  Some  will  to  believe,  others  do  not ;  because  the  will  of  some 
is  prepared  by  God,  the  will  of  others  is  not  —  aliis  prapara- 
tur  aliis  non  prceparatur  voluntas  a  Domino.  .  .  .  Mercy  and 
justice  have  been  respectively  exerted  in  the  very  wills  of  men 
—  misericordia  et  judicium  in  ipsis  voluntatibus  facia  sunt." 4 
That  is  to  say,  the  will  is  moved  and  determined  by  Divine 
grace,  but  it  is  still  will,  and  freewill. 

A  higher  sense,  however,  than  that  of  freedom  from 
constraint  and  force,  or  simple  willingness,  though  at  the 
same  time  including  this  latter  sense,  is  sometimes  given 


i  De  Gratia  et  Lib.  Arb.  n.  41.  I        8  De  Gratia  et  Lib.  Arb.  n.  32. 

9  De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Rem.  1.  2.  c.  6.    |       *  De  Praed.  Sanct.  c.  6. 


CHAP.  VIII.  ] 


OF   FREEWILL, 


235 


to  the  term  freewill ;  viz.,  that  of  freedom  from  the  yoke 
and  bondage  of  sin,  the  dominion  of  evil  inclinations  and 
passions.  The  term  freedom  is  raised  from  its  neutrality  and 
appropriated  to  a  good  condition  of  the  will ;  such  condition 
being  still,  however,  not  freedom  in  the  sense  of  power 
of  choice,  but  a  state  of  servitude  to  good, —  the  contradictory 
of  servitude  to  evil. 

S.  Paul  speaks  of  two  bondages,  a  bondage  to  righteous- 
ness and  a  bondage  to  sin ;  and  of  two  freedoms,  a  freedom 
from  righteousness  and  a  freedom  from  sin.  And  S.  Au- 
gustine, following  him,  says :  "  The  will  is  always  free  in  us, 
but  not  always  good ;  for  either  it  is  free  from  righteousness, 
and  under  bondage  to  sin,  or  it  is  free  from  sin,  and  under  bond- 
age to  righteousness."1  Here  the  term  free  is  evidently  used 
not  in  the  sense  of  free  for  evil  or  good,  i.  e.  with  the  power 
of  doing  either ;  but  as  meaning  free  from  evil,  and  free 
from  good.  There  is  a  state  of  mind  in  which  the  good 
principle  is  dominant  and  supreme,  and  the  man  in  entire 
subjection  to  it  or  under  its  yoke  ;  a  state  of  mind  in 
which  the  will  has  reached  such  a  point  of  strength  on 
the  good  side,  as  that  the  man  could  not  act  against  it, 
without  such  a  violence  as  it  would  be  absurd  to  suppose 
him  committing  toward  himself.  There  is  a  state  of  mind  also 
in  which  evil  has  this  dominance  and  supremacy.  Freewill 
is  here  understood  as  will,  which  is  either  free  from  this  yoke 
of  good,  or  free  from  this  yoke  of  evil.  In  this  sense  of  the 
word  free,  then,  the  freedom  of  the  will  is  inconsistent  with 
a  power  of  choice ;  for,  according  to  this  use  of  the  term,  a 
freewill,  so  far  from  having  ability  to  do  evil  or  good,  has  its 
very  name,  because  it  is  either  not  able  to  do  evil  on  the  one 


1  "  Semper  est  in  nobis  voluntas 
libera,  sed  non  semper  est  bona.  Aut 
enim  a  justitia  libera  est,  quando  servit 
peccato,  et  tune  est  mala :  aut  a  peccato 
libera  est,  quando  servit  justitiae,  et  tune 
est  bona.  Gratia  vero  Dei  semper  est 
bona,  et  per  hanc  fit  ut  sit  homo  bonze 
voluntatis,  qui  prius  fuit  voluntatis 
make."—  De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.  n.  31. 


"  Liberum  arbitriura  et  ad  malum  et 
ad  bonum  faciendum  confitendum  est 
nos  habere :  sed  in  malo  faciendo  liber 
est  quisque  justitiae  servusque  peccati; 
in  bono  autem  liber  est  nullus,  nisi 
fuerit  liberatus  ab  illo." — De  Corr.  et 
Grat.  n.  2. 


236  AUGUSTIXIAN   DOCTRINE  [CiiAr.  VIII. 

hand,  or  not  able  to  do  good  on  the  other.  It  is  not  a 
will  which  has  yet  to  make  its  choice,  but  which  is  already 
determined,  and  is  an  acting  will  on  one  side  or  the  other. 
Nor  has  such  a  freewill  arisen  in  the  first  instance  by  a 
power  of  choice,  because  such  a  freewill  there  has  always 
been  on  the  evil  side  or  the  good ;  "  the  will  is  always 
free  in  us,"  z.  e.  is  always  in  one  of  these  states  of  freedom 
or  the  other.  Were  the  change  from  the  bondage  of  evil, 
of  which  Augustine  speaks,  a  change  from  this  bondage 
to  evil  to  a  power  of  choosing  evil  or  good  (and  this 
is  what  on  the  common  doctrine  of  freewill  is  understood 
by  the  freedom  of  grace  as  distinguished  from  the  bondage 
of  nature),  a  power  of  choice  in  the  will  would  then  come 
in.  But  this  change  is  simply  an  exchange  of  one  bondage 
for  another, —  a  bondage  to  good  for  a  bondage  to  evil ;  and, 
therefore,  there  is  no  room  for  the  introduction  of  this  power. 

A  state  of  bondage  to  righteousness,  then,  or  a  state 
in  which  the  will  is  necessarily  good,  is,  according  to  this 
scheme,  a  state  of  freewill;  only  as  yet  it  has  that  name 
in  common  with  the  corresponding  state  on  the  side  of  evil. 
S.  Paul  uses  the  terms  bondage  and  freedom,  instead 
of  in  a  respectively  favourable  and  unfavourable  sense,  in 
a  neutral  one ;  and  S.  Augustine  follows  him.  But  the 
application  of  the  term  is  afterwards  restricted  and  appro- 
priated to  the  good  side ;  and  the  good  state  of  the  will 
is  called  the  freedom,  in  contrast  with  the  other,  which  is 
called  the  slavery  of  the  will.1 

It  appears  then,  upon  a  general  examination  of  the  language 
of  Augustine  respecting  freewill,  first,  that  it  does  not  come 
up  to  that  which  we  call  the  doctrine  of  freewill,  not  going 
beyond  that  simple  acknowledgment  of  a  will  in  which 
that  doctrine  and  its  opposite  agree  ;  and,  secondly,  that 
it  is  opposed  to  that  doctrine,  his  language  being  that 


1  "  Intantum    libera   est   (voluntas)  in  quantum    liberata   est    (a  dominant? 
cupiditate)."— Retract.  1.  1.  c.  15. 


CH..P.  VIII.]  OF    FKEEWILL.  237 

the  will  has,  notwithstanding  its  freedom,  no  self-deter- 
mining power,  but  is  determined  to  evil  and  to  good 
respectively  by  original  sin  and  by  grace. 

It  is  true,  indeed,  that  language  of  an  apparently 
opposite  kind  to  this  is  to  be  found  occasionally  in  S. 
Augustine;  but  when  such  language  is  examined,  it  will 
be  found  to  be  only  verbally"  opposite  to,  and  really  in 
harmony  with,  the  doctrine  which  has  been  exhibited. 
S.  Augustine  uniformly  indeed  holds  a  co-operation  of 
the  human  will  with  Divine  grace,  and  co-operation  seems 
to  imply  two  original  agencies  meeting  and  uniting  in 
the  same  work;  but  on  examination  we  find  that  the  term, 
in  S.  Augustine's  use  of  it,  does  not  imply  this.  The 
co-operation  of  the  human  will  with  Divine  grace  only 
commences,  according  to  S.  Augustine,  after  the  human 
will  has  undergone  that  whole  process  which  has  been 
just  described ;  that  is  to  say,  after  it  has  been  moved  by 
the  sole  action  of  Divine  grace  into  a  state  of  efficiency. 
u  He  works  in  us  that  we  will,  and  that  is  the  beginning, 
He  co-operates  with  us  when  we  will,  and  that  is  the 
perfecting,  of  the  work.  Being  confident  of  this  very 
thing,  says  the  Apostle,  that  He  which  hath  begun  a  good 
work  in  you  will  perfect  it  until  the  day  of  Jesus  Christ. 
That  we  will,  therefore  He  works  in  us  without  us;  and 
when  we  will,  and  so  will  that  we  do,  He  co-operates  with 
us — ut  ergo  velimus  sine  nobis  operatur,  cum  autem  volumus 
et  sic  volumus  ut  faciamus,  nobiscum  operatur.  And  we 
can  do  no  good  works  of  piety  without  Him  first  operat- 
ing that  we  will,  and  then  co-operating  with  us  when  we 
will.  Of  God  operating  that  we  will  it  is  said,  '  It  is  God 
that  worketh  in  us  to  will.'  Of  God  co-operating  with 
us  when  we  will,  and  so  will  that  we  do,  it  is  said,  '  We 
know  that  all  things  work  together  for  good  to  them  that  love 
God.'"  *  The  condition  of  the  human  will  is  here  divided 


1  De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.  c.  xvii. 


238  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CIIAP.  VIII. 

into  two  stages,  in  the  former  of  which  God  simply  operates 
upon  it,  in  the  latter  co-operates  with  it.  The  former  stage 
lasts  till  the  will  is  effective,  till  we  will  and  so  will  that 
we  do :  that  point  attained  the  latter  stage  commences,  and 
God  co-operates  with  this  will,  and  this  will  co-operates 
with  Him.  It  is  evident  from  the  very  terms  of  this 
division  what  the  nature  of  this,  co-operating  human  will 
is ;  that  it  is  not  an  original  agent,  but  a  will  that  has 
been  made  to  be  what  it  is  by  grace  wholly.  That  such 
a  will  co-operates  with  grace  is  no  more  than  to  say,  that 
grace  co-operates  with  grace ;  for  that  which  the  pure 
effect  does,  the  cause  does  really  and  properly.  Grace  is 
the  original,  the  will  is  only  an  instrumental  co-operator. 
The  dictum  "  Gratia  ipsa  meretur  augeri,  ut  aucta  mereatur 
perfici"  expresses  the  same  doctrine,  making  the  simple 
bestowal  of  grace  the  reason  of  its  further  bestowal,  so  that 
grace  is  its  own  augmenter,  and  increases  upon  an  internal 
law  of  growth. 

It  is  such  a  mode  of  co-operation  as  this  which  the  follow- 
ing passage  describes  :  "  It  is  plain  that  human  righteousness, 
although  it  is  not  done  without  the  human  will,  is  to  be  at- 
tributed to  the  operation  of  the  Divine,  which  is  the  reason 
we  cannot  deny  that  the  perfection  of  that  righteousness  is 
possible  even  in  this  life ;  because  all  things  are  possible  to 
God,  both  what  He  does  when  His  own  will  solely  operates, 
and  what  He  does  when  the  wills  of  His  creatures  operate 
with  Him  —  sive  quce  facit  sola  sua  voluntate,  sive  qua  co- 
operantibus  creaturcB  sua  voluntatibus,  a  se  fieri  posse  con- 
stituit? l  Here  is  a  co-operation  mentioned  of  the  human  will 
with  the  Divine,  but  it  is  a  co-operation  subordinated  to  an 
absolute  power  in  the  Divine  will.  Whatever  therefore  such 
co-operation  in  the  human  will  involves,  it  does  not  involve 
any  dependence  of  the  issue  upon  it,  inasmuch  as  such  issue 


1  De  Lit.  et  Spirit,  c.  5. 


CHAP.  VIII. ]  OF  FREEWILL.  239 

is  secured  by  the  absolute  power  of  the  Divine  will  to  pro- 
duce it.  The  power  is  on  one  side,  the  co-operation  on 
another ;  co-operation  abstracted  from  power  is  instrumental 
co-operation. 

The  same  mode  of  co-operation  is  described  in  the  follow- 
ing extract :  "  When  God  wills  the  salvation  of  a  man,  no 
will  of  man  resists  Him,  For  to  will  or  not  to  will  is  in  the 
power  of  the  willing  or  unwilling  man  in  such  sense  only 
that  it  does  not  impede  the  Divine  will  or  frustrate  the  Di- 
vine power — sic  enim  velle  seu  nolle  in  volentis  aut  nolentis 
est  potestate,  ut  Divinam  voluntatem  non  impediaty  nee  super 
et  potestatem"1  Here  it  is  said  that  in  a  particular  sense 
a  man's  will  is  in  his  own  power,  and  were  the  sense  in 
which  this  were  allowed  a  free  and  natural  one,  nothing 
more  would  be  wanted  for  a  testimony  on  the  side  of  freewill. 
But  we  see  at  once  that  it  is  anything  but  a  free  and  natural 
sense  in  which  this  power  is  conceded ;  for  it  is  conceded 
under  the  salvo,  that  this  power  does  not  interfere  with  the 
natural  operation  of  another  power,  which  other  power  is 
absolute.  But  what  is  power  which  is  itself  the  subject  of 
absolute  power  ?  Had  S.  Augustine  wished  to  admit  a  real 
power  in  the  human  will,  there  are  many  plain  and  simple 
modes  in  which  he  might  have  done  it,  as  a  common  language 
in  theology,  both  ancient  and  modern,  on  this  subject  shows. 
But  he  only  admits  a  power  which  is  negatived  by  an  entire 
subordination  to  another  power ;  and  a  will  with  such  a 
negatived  power  over  itself  is  not  an  original  but  an  instru- 
mental co-operator  with  the  Divine  will. 

One  passage,  however,  has  attracted  remarkable  attention, 
in  consequence  of  one  particular  phrase,  contained  in  it, 
appearing  at  first  to  involve  very  decidedly  the  position 
of  a  self-determining  will :  "  If  it  be  said  that  we  must 
beware  of  interpreting  the  text,  '  What  hast  thou  which 


Be  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xiv. 


240 


AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTKINE 


[CHAP.   VIII. 


thou  Least  not  received  ? '  of  the  believing  will,  and  asserting, 
because  this  proceeds  from  a  freewill  which  was  a  Divine 
gift  at  our  creation,  that  therefore  it  is  itself  &  Divine  gift, 
lest  we  attribute  to  God  the  authorship  of  sin  as  well ; — I  say, 
that  a  believing  will  is  net  to  be  attributed  to  God  solely 
because  it  proceeds  from  freewill,  but  because  it  depends  upon 
the  Divine  persuasion,  either  external  or  internal ;  though  it 
belongs  to  the  individual's  will  to  agree  with  or  dissent  from  this 
persuasion.  God's  mercy  always  anticipates  us,  and  He  works 
in  man  the  will  to  believe;  but  to  assent  to  or  dissent  from 
the  Divine  will  belongs  to  the  individual  will.  Nor  does  this 
at  all  contradict  the  text,  (  What  hast  thou  which  thou  hast 
not  received?'  but  rather  confirms  it.  The  soul  cannot 
receive  these  gifts  without  consenting;  because,  what  it 
has  and  what  it  receives  is  from  God:  to  have  and  re- 
ceive belongs  to  a  possessor  and  receiver."  He  then  de- 
cides why  this  Divine  persuasion,  to  which  this  assent  of 
the  will  is  necessary,  is  effectual  with  some,  and  not  with 
others,  and  decides  it  by  a  reference  to  the  inscrutable  will 
of  God.1 

We  have,  then,  in  this  passage  the  expression,  "  assentire 


1  "  Si  autem  respondetur,  cavendum 
esse  ne  quisquam  Deo  tribuendum  putet 
peccatum,  quod  admittitur  per  liberum 
arbitrium,  -si  in  eo  quod  dicitur,  '  Quid 
habes  quod  non  accepisti?'  propterea 
etiam  voluntas  qua  credimus  dono  Dei 
tribuitur,  quia  de  libero  existit  arbitrio, 
quod  cum  crearemur  accepimus;  at- 
tendat  et  videat,  non  ideo,  quia  ex 
libero  arbitrio  est,  quod  nobis  naruraliter 
concreatum  est;  verum  etiam  quod 
visorum  suasionibus  agit  Deus,  ut 
velimus  et  ut  credamus,  sive  extrin- 
secus,  per  evangelicas  exhortationes  .  . 
sive  intrinsecus,  ubi  nemo  habet  in 
potestate  quid  ei  veniat  in  mentem, 
sed  consentire  vel  dissentire  proprice 
voluntatis  est.  His  ergo  modis  quando 
Deus  agit  cum  anima  rational!,  u".  ei 
credat  (neque  enim  credere  potest 
quodlibet  libero  arbitrio  si  nulla  sit 
suasio  vel  vocatio  cui  credat)  profecto 


et  ipsum  velle  credere  Deus  operatur  in 
homine,  et  in  omnibus  misericordia 
ejus  praevemt  nos :  consentire  autem 
vocationi  Dei,  vel  ab  ea  dissentire,  sicut 
dixi,  proprice  voluntatis  est.  Quse  res 
non  solum  non  infirmat  quod  dictum 
est,  '  Quid  habes  quod  non  accepisti  ?  ' 
verum  etiam  confirmat.  Accipcre 
quidem  et  habere  anima  non  potest 
dona,  de  quibus  hoc  audit,  nisi  con- 
sentiendo:  ac  per  hoc  quid  habeat  et 
quid  accipiat,  Dei  est ;  accipere  autem 
et  habere,  accipientis  et  habentis  est. 
Jam  si  ad  illam  profunditatem  scru- 
tandam  quisquam  nos  coarctet,  cur  illi 
ita  suadeatur  ut  persuadeatur,  illi  autem 
non  ita:  duo  sola  occurrunt  interim 
quas  respondere  mihi  placeat  '  O  altitude 
divitiarum'  et  '  Numquid  iniquitas  apud 
Deum?"'  —  De  Spiritu  et  Litera,  1.  1. 
n.  60. 


CHAP.  VIII. ]  OF   FREEWILL.  241 

vel  dissentire  propricB  voluntatis  est ;"  and  this  expression  seems 
at  first  sight  to  involve  a  self-determining  will.  But  it  will 
be  seen,  that  in  the  course  of  the  statement  it  receives  a 
different  explanation.  In  this  passage  S.  Augustine  is  dis- 
cussing the  question,  whether  the  will  to  believe  is  given  by 
God ;  and  he  answers,  first,  that  it  is  given  *by  God  because 
it  arises  out  of  that  freewill  which  was  given  to  man  at 
his  creation.  But  then  he  remarks,  that  this  answer  is  not 
enough,  because  sin  also  arises  out  of  freewill,  and  sin  is  not 
the  gift  of  God.  What  is  the  difference,  then,  he  asks,  in  the 
mode  in  which  they  respectively  arise,  which  makes  one  the 
gift  of  God,  and  the  other  not  ?  He  decides  that  this  differ- 
ence lies  in  a  certain  calling  or  persuading  on  the  part  of  God, 
which  is  necessary  in  order  to  produce  the  believing  will  — 
neque  enim  credere  potest  quodlibet  libero  arbitrio,  si  nulla  sit 
suasio  vel  vocatio  cui  credat.  And  to  this  calling  and  per- 
suasion the  natural  will  has  to  consent,  in  order  for  it  to  be 
effectual;  for  that  "assenting  or  dissenting  belongs  to  the 
natural  will — consentire  vocationi  Dei  vel  ab  ea  dissentire 
proprics  voluntatis  est"  The  believing  will,  then,  is  a  Di- 
vine gift,  inasmuch  as  it  is  the  result  of  a  Divine  calling 
with  which  the  human  will  agrees.  But  then  the  ques- 
tion immediately  arises,  whether  this  is  not  a  compromise 
which  really  gives  up  the  whole  point,  and  makes  the  be- 
lieving will  not  a  gift  which  man  receives  simply,  but 
something  which  he  acquires  by  an  act  of  his  own.  And 
to  that  he  replies,  that  it  is  not,  because  consent  is  only  the 
necessary  mode  in  which  the  will  receives  a  gift:  consent 
being,  in  fact,  nothing  but  the  act  itself  of  receiving  ;  so  that 
to  say  that  the  will  must  consent  in  order  to  receive,  is 
nothing  more  than  to  say  that  the  will  must  receive  when 
it  receives  —  accipere  et  habere  utique  accipientis  et  habentis 
est.  The  believing  will  thus  comes  out,  after  due  ex- 
planation, a  simple  gift,  to  which  the  only  consent  is  one 
which  is  involved  in  the  mere  fact  of  it  being  given;  viz. 
reception  and  possession.  And,  lastly,  why  one  man  has 

R 


242 


AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  VIII. 


this  gift,  and  another  not,  is  explained  by  a  simple  appeal  to 
mystery. 

Any  one  who  carefully  examines  this  passage  will  see  that 
the  explanation,  here  given  of  it,  is  the  only  one  by  which 
a  consistent  meaning  is  secured  for  it  throughout.  A  phrase 
apparently  owning  an  original  power  in  the  human  will  to 
accept  or  reject  the  Divine  operation  upon  it,  is  admitted ; 
but  as  soon  as  it  has  been  admitted  it  is  explained  in  a  par- 
ticular way,  and  reduced  into  entire  harmony  with  a  theory 
of  omnipotent  grace,  resting  upon  a  basis  of  mystery.1 

To  sum  up  in  one  distinction  the  general  argument  of  this 
chapter,  the  Augustinian  doctrine  of  freewill  may  be  said  in 
a  word  to  describe  the  nature  of  freewill  as  being  a  mode  of 
action,  not  a  source  of  action  —  taking  source  in  its  proper 
sense  as  an  original  source.  The  mode  of  human  action  is 
free.  We  act  willingly  and  without  compulsion  whenever 
we  truly  act  at  all ;  for  action  forced  upon  us  is  not  our 
own,  but  another's,  and  to  act  willingly  is  to  act  freely.  We 
act  with  deliberation,  choice,  preference,  on  certain  principles, 
and  to  certain  ends.  But  it  does  not  follow,  it  is  argued, 
that  our  mode  of  action  decides  anything  as  to  the  source  of 
action :  we  act  as  we  will;  but  the  question  still  remains  how 


1  Jansen  (De  Gratia  Christi,  pp.  220. 
225.  908.  936.  955.  980.  989.)  pro- 
perly explains  various  passages  of 
Augustine  from  which  the  Jesuits 
Bellarmine,  Suarez,  Molina,  Lessius  and 
others  had  extracted  a  freewill  meaning, 
as  applying  to  the  will  of  man  as 
created,  or  simply  to  will  as  such.  But 
while  such  explanation  is  sometimes 
required  on  his  own  side,  nothing  can 
be  more  far-fetched  and  artificial  than 
the  Jesuit  interpretations  of  the  great 
pervading  dicta"  and  fundamental  posi- 
tions of  Augustine  ;  if  interpretations 
deserve  that  name  which  are  obvious 
and  barefaced  contradictions  to,  rather 
than  explanations  of,  S.  Augustine's 
meaning ;  as  Lessius'  interpretation  of 
the  Augustinian  predestination  as  con- 
ditional and  incomplete  (pp.  955.  981.) 


his  view  of  Augustinian  election  as 
ex  prcevisis  operibus  (p.  989.):  and 
his  and  Molina's  explanation  of  gratia 
ejficax,  as  efficacious  si  voluntas  cum  ea 
co-operari  velit  (p.  936.),  omitting  the 
whole  consideration  that  this  consent 
of  the  will  is  itself,  according  to  Au- 
gustine the  effect  of  grace.  Having 
excluded  Augustinianism  from  the  pale 
of  tolerated  opinion,  the  Church  of 
Rome  is  obliged  to  prove  that  S.  Au- 
gustine was  not  Augustinian.  But 
the  plain  language  of  S.  Augustine 
refutes  such  interpreters,  and  forces 
one  of  two  alternatives  upon  them, 
either  that  they  tolerate  his  doctrines, 
and  so  keep  him  in  communion  with 
their  Church,  or  anathematise  his 
doctrines,  and  confess  that  S.  Augustine 
does  not  belong  to  their  communion. 


CHAP,  VIII.]  OF   FREEWILL.  243 

we  come  to  will.  Underneath  all  our  sensations  of  original 
agency,  it  is  maintained,  a  deeper  cause  operates,  and 
that  which  is  not  the  will  produces  the  movements  and  acts 
of  the  will.  "  Men  are  acted  upon,  that  they  may  act,  not 
that  they  may  not  act  —  aguntur  ut  agant  non  ut  ipsi  nihil 
agant"  A  translation  cannot  give  the  point  of  the  original, 
which  is  literally  that  "  men  are  acted  that  they  may  act ;  " 
the  passive  and  the  active  of  the  same  verb  being  used 
to  express  the  more  pointedly  the  entire  sequency  of  an 
effect  from  a  cause.  Men  act  —  agunt,  that  is  the  effect ;  they 
are  acted  upon  —  aguntur,  that  is  the  cause  which  accounts 
for  the  whole  of  the  effect.  The  whole  cause,  then,  of  human 
acts  is  beyond  the  agent  himself.  But  the  agent  is  not 
nevertheless  inert,  because  he  is  not  a  cause  ;  on  the  contrary, 
he  is  an  agent,  he  acts.  He  is  not  caused  to  do  nothing ; 
caused  to  be  idle,  passive,  motionless;  an  actor  is  the, very 
thing  he  is  caused  to  be.  That  is  to  say,  his  mode  of  acting, 
which  is  wholly  free,  coexists  with  a  source  of  action  which 
is  external. —  "  When  we  will  we  will,  but  He  makes  us  to 
will  — •  cerium  est  nos  velle  cum  volumus,  sed  illefacit  ut  velimus 
bonum."  An  objector  is  supposed  to  say  that  he  must  be  the 
cause  of  his  own  acts  because  he  wills  them.  But  he  is  told 
that  his  mode  of  action,  which  is  free,  decides  nothing  as  to 
its  source.  That  a  man  should  be  "  forced  to  will  —  cogatur 
velle"  would  be  a  contradiction  ;  for,  "  if  he  is  forced,  he  does 
not  will,  he  cannot  will  unwillingly  —  cum  enim  cogitur  non 
vult,  et  quid  absurdim  quam  ut  dicatur  nolens  velle"  l  But  there 
is  no  contradiction  in  his  being  made  to  will,  because  the  will 
cannot  resist  before  it  exists,  and  therefore  cannot  be  opposed 
to  its  own  formation.  It  is  the  same  distinction  of  mode  and 
source.  "  You  do  not  understand,"  Augustine  tells  the  Pela- 
gian who  brings  against  him  the  text  2  Tim.  ii.  21. :  "If  a  man, 
therefore,  purge  himself"  &c.,  as  proving  man  to  be  the  proper 
source  of  his  own  acts,  "you  do  not  understand  that  both  as- 


1  Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  134. 
R    2 


244 


AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  VIII, 


sertions  are  true,  that  the  vessels  of  glory  prepare  themselves, 
and  that  God  prepares  them.  For  God  makes  that  man  does 
—  utfaciat  homofacit  Deus."  —  (i  What  can  be  more  absurd 
than  your  idea  that  because  the  motives  of  the  will  are  un- 
forced, we  are  not  to  inquire  whence  they  are,  as  if  a  cause 
were  contradictory  to  their  freedom,  as  forcing  them  to  be  ? 
Is  a  man  forced  to  exist,  because  he  has  an  origin?  Before 
he  existed,  was  there  anything  to  be  forced  ?  The  will  has 
an  origin,  and  yet  is  not  forced  to  be ;  and  if  this  origin  is 
not  to  be  sought  for,  the  reason  is  not  that  it  should  not  be, 
but  that  it  need  not, —  that  it  is  too  manifest.  The  will  is 
from  him  whose  the  will  is ;  the  angel's  will  from  the  angel, 
the  man's  from  the  man,  God's  from  God.  God,  in  working 
a  good  will  in  man,  causes  a  good  will  to  arise  in  him  whose 
the  will  is — agit  ut  oriatur  ab  illo  bona  voluntas  cujus  est  volun- 
tas ;  just  as  He  causes  man  to  spring  from  man."  l  No  lan- 
guage could  indicate  more  fully  the  nature  of  the  will,  as  an 
active, living,  willing  will,  internal  and  truly  our  own,  than  this 
which  goes  even  the  length  of  claiming  an  originality  of  the 
will  within,  and  making  it  arise  out  of  ourselves.  But,  on  the 
other  hand,  this  very  originality  of  the  will  is  not  original ; 
this  very  source  within  us  is  derived  from  a  source  without  us. 
This  rise  of  the  will  out  of  ourselves  is  no  more  opposed  to 
its  true  causation  by  Divine  grace,  than  the  birth  of  man  from 
man  is  opposed  to  man's  creation  by  Divine  power.  The  will 
is  a  middle  cause  between  God  and  the  act,  as  man  is  a  middle 


1  Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  101. 

Quid  autem  vanius  definitionibus 
tuis,  qui  propterea  putas  non  esse  quae- 
rendum  unde  sit  voluntas,  quia  motus 
est  animi  cogente  nullo?  Si  enim 
dicatur,  ut  putas,  unde  sit;  non  erit 
verum  quod  dictum  est,  cogente  nullo : 
quia  illud  unde  est  earn  cogit  esse;  et 
ideo  non  est  alicunde,  ne  cogatur  esse. 
O  stultitiam  singularem !  Non  est 
ergo  alicunde  ipse  homo,  qui  non  est 
coactus  esse,  quia  non  erat  qui  cogeretur 
antequam  esset.  Prorsus  et  alicunde 
est  voluntas,  et  esse  non  cogitur ;  et  si 


ejus  origo  quaerenda  non  est,  non  ideo 
quaerenda  non  est  quod  voluntas  ali- 
cunde non  sit,  sed  quia  manifestum  est 
unde  sit.  Ab  illo  est  enim  voluntas 
cujus  est  voluntas ;  ab  angelo  scilicet 
voluntas  angeli,  ab  homine  hominis,  a 
Deo  Dei,  et  si  operatur  Deus  in  homine 
voluntatem  bonam,  id  utique  agit,  ut 
oriatur  ab  illo  bona  voluntas,  cujus  est 
voluntas  ;  sicut  agit  ut  homo  oriatur 
ab  homine  ;  non  enim  quia  Deus  creat 
hominem,  ideo  non  homo  ex  homine 
nascitur.  —  Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  42. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  OF   FREEWILL.  245 

cause  between  God  and  the  human  birth.  It  is  a  cause,  but 
that  very  cause  is  caused ;  i.  e.  the  will  is  an  absolutely  free 
mode  of  action,  but  not  a  true  original  source  of  action.  Such 
a  doctrine  is  not  fairly  open  to  the  charge  commonly  brought 
against  it,  that  it  converts  man  into  a  machine,  and  degrades 
him  to  the  level  of  matter ;  for  it  does  not  do  so.  A  machine 
has  no  will ;  but  this  doctrine  expressly  admits  in  man  a  will. 
But  it  allows  a  will  as  a  mediate,  and  not  a  first  cause,  of 
action. 

The  Augustinian  doctrine  of  freewill  having  been  thus 
stated,  it  only  remains  to  point  out  wherein  lies  its  pecu- 
liarity, in  what  the  true  difference  between  it  and  the 
ordinary  doctrine  of  freewill  consists. 

The  first  characteristic,  then,  that  we  observe  in  the  doc- 
trine which  we  have  been  considering,  is,  that  it  combines 
freewill  with  necessity.  The  terms  themselves  necessity 
and  necessary  are  not  indeed  in  constant  use  in  Augustine 
though  he  does  use  them;  maintaining  man  in  a  state  of 
nature  to  be  under  "  a  necessity  to  sin  — peccati  necessitas  V 
and  under  grace  to  be  recalled  by  necessity  to  a  spiritual 
life  —  necessitate  revocari.2  Not  selecting  them  for  his  own 
use, —  conveying  as  they  do  to  ordinary  minds  the  idea 
of  force,  —  when  challenged  by  his  Pelagian  opponent  to 
admit  them,  he  does  not  refuse;  only  securing  a  distinc- 
tion between  a  co-active  and  a  creative  necessity.  But 
though  the  word  itself  is  not  in  constant  use,  other  words 
which  signify  the  same  thing  are;  and  therefore  this  doc- 
trine may  be  called,  in  the  first  place,  a  combination  of 
freewill  with  necessity. 


1  Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  61. 

2  Op.  Imp.  1. 1.  c,  93.     "  Necessitatis 
inerat  plenitude." — L.  5.  c.  59.     "  At- 
tende  eum  qui  dicit,  Quod  nolo  malum 
hoc  ago,  et  responde  utrum  necessitatem 
non  habeat." — L.   5.  c.    50.     "  Quia 
vero  peccavit  voluntas  secuta  est  pec- 


cantem  peccatum  habendi  dura  ne- 
cessitas, donee  tota  sanetur  infirmitas, 
.  .  .  ita  ut  sit  etiam  bene  vivendi,  et 
nunquam  peccandi  voluntaria  felixque 
necessitas." — De  Perfectione  Justitiae, 
c.  4. 


246  AUGUSTINIAN   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

The  peculiarity,  however,  of  the  Augustinian  doctrine 
does  not  lie  in  this  combination ;  for  the  combination  itself 
is  not,  when  we  examine  the  matter,  open  to  any  substantial 
objection.  "We  are  apt  indeed  at  first  to  think,  that  no  will 
can  be  in  any  sense  free  that  acts  necessarily ;  but  a  little 
reflection  will  show  us  that  this  is  a  first  thought  resulting 
from  not  properly  knowing  our  own  admissions  on  this  subject. 
We  attribute  to  the  Supreme  Being,  the  angels,  and  saints 
in  their  state  of  reward,  a  necessity  on  the  side  of  goodness ; 
but  we  attribute  to  God,  the  angels,  and  the  saints  the  oper- 
ation of  a  genuine  will.  We  attribute  to  the  evil  spirits  and 
the  wicked,  in  their  state  of  punishment,  a  necessity  on  the 
side  of  evil,  and  together  with  it  the  same  genuine  will. 
Necessity  indeed  only  operates  in  matter  in  this  lower 
world;  inevitable  growth,  inevitable  decay,  organisation, 
and  disorganisation,  are  only  seen  in  the  animal,  vegetable, 
and  mineral  bodies ;  but  in  the  eternal  world,  the  intelli- 
gent substance  acts  necessarily,  and  that  which  moves  with 
certainty  in  the  direction  of  good  or  evil  is  will.  The 
Supreme  Will  being  essentially  good,  cannot  contradict  itself; 
the  will  of  the  wicked  cannot  agree  with,  the  will  of  the 
righteous  cannot  recede  from,  the  Will  Supreme.  Indeed, 
we  are  conversant  with  certain  approaches  to  necessity  in 
human  conduct  in  this  life.  It  is  the  essential  characteristic 
of  habit,  that  it  makes  acts  to  be  performed  by  us  as  a 
matter  of  course,  implants  a  kind  of  law  in  our  minds,  by 
which  we  act  in  this  or  that  way ;  and  therefore  habit  is 
called  a  second  nature.  But  we  do  not  consider  that  men 
who  have  formed  habits,  virtuous  or  the  contrary,  do  not  act 
with  freewill. 

Nor,  again,  does  the  peculiarity  of  S.  Augustine's  doctrine, 
as  it  does  not  lie  in  the  combination  of  freewill  with  ne- 
cessity, lie  either  in  the  source  which  he  assigns  to  such 
necessity,  which  is  one  external  to  the  agent.  The  doctrine 
of  an  eternal  state  of  reward  and  punishment,  which  all 
Christians  admit,  asserts  the  transference  of  human  wills 


CHAP.  VIII.]  OF   FREEWILL.  247 

into  a  state  of  necessity,  both  for  evil  and  good,  by  an  act 
of  Almighty  Power ;  that  the  wills  of  wicked  men  are,  on 
their  departure  from  this  life,  put  by  this  act  into  a  state  in 
which  they  are  beyond  recovery  ;  those  of  the  good  into  a 
state  in  which  they  are  beyond  lapse.  The  power  of  choice 
being,  according  to  the  doctrine  of  freewill,  retained  by  man 
so  long  as  he  remains  in  this  world  ;  its  determination,  on  his 
departure  to  another,  is  caused  not  by  an  act  of  his  own, 
but  by  a  Divine  act  of  judgment  or  of  reward,  as  it  may  be. 
Thus  all  God's  moral  creatures  pass,  at  a  particular  stage 
of  their  being,  by  an  act  of  Divine  Power,  from  a  state  in 
which  their  wills  are  indeterminate  and  may  choose  either 
good  or  evil,  to  a  state  in  which  they  necessarily  choose  one 
or  the  other.  While  there  is  life  there  is  hope,  and  there 
is  fear.  The  most  inveterate  habits  of  vice  still  leave  a 
power  of  self-recovery  in  the  man  if  he  will  but  exert  it ; 
the  most  confirmed  habits  of  virtue  still  leave  the  liability 
to  a  fall.  The  resources  for  a  struggle  between  good  and 
evil  remain  up  to  the  time  of  departure  from  life,  when 
a  change  takes  place  which  no  thought  can  reach,  and  by 
a  Divine  act  the  will,  remaining  the  same  in  substance,  is 
changed  fundamentally  in  condition,  and  put  out  of  a  state 
of  suspense  and,  in  ordinary  language,  freedom,  into  one  of 
necessity. 

But  the  combination  of  necessity,  and  that  a  necessity 
communicated  to  the  will  from  without,  with  freewill,  being 
admitted  on  both  sides,  the  peculiarity  of  Augustine's  doc- 
trine lies  in  the  application  of  this  principle ;  in  the  reason, 
the  time,  and  the  manner  he  assigns  to  its  operation.  That 
state  of  the  will  to  which  an  original  power  of  choice  attaches 
is  upon  the  doctrine  of  freewill  identical  with  a  state  of 
trial ;  and  this  consideration  gives  us  the  reason  and  time  of 
the  introduction  of  necessity,  as  well  as  the  manner  of  its 
operation  according  to  the  doctrine  of  freewill.  The  ground 
of  its  introduction  is  final  reward  and  punishment ;  the  time 
of  its  introduction  is  after  a  state  of  trial ;  and  the  manner  of 

R    4 


248  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  VIII. 

its  operation  consists  in  the  absence  of  struggle,  effort,  or 
interruption  ;  in  the  entire,  continuous,  and  natural  yielding 
of  the  will  to  the  impulses  of  good  or  evil.  The  strife  is 
over  in  the  inind  of  man ;  and  the  will,  finally  rooted,  goes  on 
producing  good  or  evil  acts  and  motions  with  the  ease  and 
uniformity  of  physical  law.  But  in  S.  Augustine's  applica- 
tion of  the  principle,  the  reason,  and  time  of  its  introduction, 
and  mode  of  operation,  are  all  different.  Necessity  is  not  the 
reward  or  punishment  of  a  previous  exercise  of  liberty  of 
choice,  but  the  effect  of  original  sin  on  the  one  hand,  and  an 
eternal  Divine  decree  of  mercy  on  the  other.  And  with  the 
difference  of  reason  for,  the  time  of  its  introduction  is  also 
different.  It  does  not  succeed  and  come  after  a  state  of 
trial,  but  is  simultaneous  with  it,  and  is  in  full  operation  in 
this  life,  instead  of  being  reserved  for  the  next.  And  the 
manner  of  its  operation  is  for  the  same  reason  different, 
exhibiting  the  struggle,  the  variableness,  and  interruption 
incident  to  this  present  state  of  existence.  The  difference 
between  the  trial,  effort,  and  alternation  of  the  present,  and 
the  peace  and  serenity  of  the  future  life,  which  is  upon  the 
doctrine  of  freewill  a  difference  between  a  state  of  liberty 
and  a  state  of  necessity,  is,  according  to  the  predestinarian, 
only  a  difference  between  two  modes  of  operation  on  the 
part  of  the  same  necessity.  That  grace  from  which  good 
action  necessarily  follows  is  not  given  with  uniformity  in 
this  life,  sometimes  being  given  and  sometimes  not,  to  the 
same  individual ;  whereas,  in  the  eternal  world  it  is  either 
given  wholly  or  taken  away  wholly,  always  given  or  never ; 
so  that  there  the  determination  of  the  will  is  constant  for 
good  or  for  evil.  Its  mode  of  operation,  then,  in  this  life  is 
variable,  in  the  next  uniform;  here,  with  pain  and  effort  to 
the  man,  with  trouble  and  anxiety,  the  feeling  of  uncertainty, 
and  other  feelings  exactly  like  what  we  should  have,  sup- 
posing our  wills  were  free  and  our  acts  contingent;  there 
with  ease,  security,  and  bliss;  here  preparatory,  there  final; 
here  after  the  mode  of  trial,  there  after  the  mode  of  reward. 


CHAP.  VIII.]  OF   FREEWILL.  249 

Such  a  difference  between  two  doctrines  of  necessity,  it 
will  be  seen,  involves  all  the  difference  between  a  doctrine  of 
necessity  and  a  doctrine  of  freewill.  The  former  gives  to 
freewill  that  period  which  is  the  turning  part  of  man's 
existence,  this  life ;  to  necessity  only  that  future  state  which 
is  here  decided.  The  latter  gives  to  necessity  both  the 
future  state  itself  and  the  decision  of  it. 


250 


CHAP.  IX. 

SCHOLASTIC   THEORY  OF   NECESSITY. 

THE  teaching  of  S.  Augustine  had  that  result  which 
naturally  follows  from  the  keen  perception  and  mastery  of  a 
particular  truth  by  a  vigorous,  powerful,  and  fertile  mind ; 
endowed  with  an  inexhaustible  command  and  perfect  manage- 
ment of  language,  which  seconded  and  acted  as  the  simple 
instrument  of  the  highest  religious  ardour  and  enthusiasm. 
Copious  and  exuberant,  and  concise  and  pointed,  at  the 
same  time ;  bold,  ingenious,  and  brilliant,  yet  always  earnest 
and  natural,  he  did  not  write  so  much  in  vain.  As  the  pro- 
duction of  a  single  mind,  the  quantity  of  the  writing  had  a 
unity,  force,  and  wholeness  which  told  with  surprising  effect 
upon  the  Church.  The  large  aggregate  of  thought  and  state- 
ment came  in  one  effective  mass  and  body.  One  such  writer 
is  in  himself  a  whole  age,  and  more  than  an  age  of  authorship ; 
a  complete  school,  and  more  than  a  school  of  divinity.  He  had, 
moreover,  the  advantage  of  an  undoubted  and  solid  ground 
of  Scripture ;  an  advantage  which  his  deep  and  full  know- 
ledge of  the  sacred  text,  and  wonderful  skill  and  readiness  in 
the  application  of  it,  enabled  him  to  use  with  the  greatest 
effect.  He  erected  on  this  ground,  indeed,  more  than  it 
could  legitimately  bear,  and  was  a  one-sided  interpreter. 
Still  he  brought  out  a  side  of  Scripture  which  had  as  yet 
been  much  in  the  shade,  and  called  attention  to  deep  truths 
which  had  comparatively  escaped  notice  in  the  Church.  He 
brought  to  light  the  full  meaning  of  S.  Paul,  and  did  that 
which  the  true  interpreter  does  for  his  teacher  and  master, — 
fastened  the  great  doctrine  of  the  Apostle,  in  its  full  and 
complete  sense,  upon  the  Church. 

Such  an  exposition  had  as  great  and  as  permanent  success 


CHAP.  IX.] 


THEORY   OF    NECESSITY. 


251 


as  could  have  been  anticipated.  The  doctrine  of  S.  Au- 
gustine reigned  in  the  mediaeval  Church,  and  moulded  its 
authoritative  teaching,  till  the  Reformation  produced  a 
reaction ;  and  the  Roman  Church,  apprehensive  of  the 
countenance  which  it  gave  to  some  prominent  doctrines  of 
the  Reformers,  and  repelled  by  the  use — sometimes  unfair 
and  fanatical — made  of  it,  fell  back  upon  a  strong  doctrine 
of  freewill.  The  Thomists  took  an  important  part,  indeed, 
in  the  Council  of  Trent,  and  had  sufficient  influence  to 
guard  its  decrees  from  any  turn  unfavourable  to  themselves. 
But  they  ceased  after  the  Reformation  to  be  a  prominent 
and  ruling  school,  and  gave  place  to  the  Jesuits,  who,  as  the 
antagonists  by  position  and  calling  of  the  Reformation, 
formed  their  theology  in  express  opposition  to  it,  and 
abandoned  the  Augustinian  ground.  The  Jansenists  at- 
tempted a  revival  of  it,  to  which  their  enthusiasm  and 
devotion  gave  a  temporary  success,  sufficient  to  alarm  the 
dominant  school :  but  authority  finally  suppressed  it,  and 
ejected  them,  and  practically  with  them  the  Augustinian 
doctrine,  from  the  Roman  Church. 

The  mediaeval  Augustinian  school  presents  us  with  the 
names  of  Peter  Lombard,  S.  Bernard,  S.  Anselm,  Thomas 
Aquinas,  Bradwardine  19  and  others.2  Among  these  Lombard 
and  Aquinas  occupy  the  first  place  as  formal  and  systematic 
theologians.  The  former  of  these,  however,  is  more  of  a 
compiler  and  collector  of  extracts  and  references,  than  an 
exponent  and  a  constructor.  His  collection  of  statements, 
indeed,  arranged  on  a  plan,  and  extending  over  a  large 


1  I  cannot  wholly  understand,  except 
as  unfavourably  characteristic  of  that 
age,  the  great  mediaeval  reputation  of 
Bradwardine,  called  the  "profound 
doctor."  A  dull  monotony  character- 
ises his  speculations,  which  are  all  spun 
out  of  the  idea  of  the  Divine  Power,  or 
of  God  as  the  Universal  Cause  ;  but  spun 
into  airy  subtleties,  which  want  the  sub- 
stance of  solid  thought  and  argument, 


and  are  more  like  the  shadows  and 
ghosts  of  reasonings  than  the  realities. 
2  The  predestinarian  controversy  in 
the  Gallican  Church,  which  arose  out 
of  the  statements  of  Gotteschalcus,  in 
the  ninth  century,  does  not  offer  much 
valuable  material  to  the  theological 
student.  I  give  the  principal  points  of 
it  in  NOTE  XX. 


252  SCHOLASTIC   THEORY  [CHAP.  IX. 

ground,  is  in  itself  an  exposition,  and  an  able  one ;  and  it 
formed  the  great  text  book  of  the  Church  for  centuries. 
But   it   is   not   an  argumentative   exposition :  it  does   not 
expand   and    develope   by   statement   and   reasoning   theo- 
logical ideas.     Aquinas,  however,  supplies  the  deficiencies 
of  Lombard,   and  taking  up  the  scheme   and  ground-plan 
which  the  older  commentator  furnishes,  applies  the  argu- 
mentative and  philosophical  talent  to  it,  and  fills  it  out  with 
thought ;  enriching  it  at  the  same  time  with  large  additions 
from   the   stores   of  heathen   philosophy.     Aquinas   is   ac- 
cordingly  the    great    representative   of   mediaeval   Augus- 
tinianism — I   might   say,  of  mediaeval  theology.     He  re- 
flects the  mind — he   embodies   the    ideas   and   sentiments 
of  the  mediaeval  Church.     In  him,  as  in  a  mirror,  we  see 
the  great  assumptions,  the  ruling  arguments  of  the  theo- 
logical world ;  the  mode  of  inference  which  was  considered 
legitimate ;  the  way  of  solving  difficulties  which  was  thought 
satisfactory.     In  his  large  and  capacious  mind  we  see  the 
collective  theological  thought  and  philosophy  of  the  middle 
ages.     He  fails,  indeed,  in  a  power  which  it  was  reserved 
for  a  modern  age  to  call  forth  from  the  human   mind — 
the   analytical  one.     He  does   not   turn  his  mind  inward 
upon  itself  to   examine   its  own  thoughts  and  ideas,  and 
compare  received  and  current  truths  with  the  original  type 
from   which   they  are  copied.     In   this  sense  he  does  not 
apprehend   and  realise   truths;  because   he   does   not   put 
his  mind  into  that  attitude  in  which  it  has  alone  the  power 
of  seeing  its  own  processes,  ideas,  and  modes  of  entertaining 
truth — the  attitude  of  reflection  and  turning  inward  of  the 
mind  upon  itself.     No  one  can  see  a  thing  but  by  looking 
at  it ;  the  mediaeval  mind  did  not  look  within,  or  examine 
itself:  it   could  not,   therefore,   see   itself  —  i.e.   get   such 
knowledge  as  has  been  since  proved  to  be  attainable  of  its 
own  operations  and  ideas.     It  was  left  for  a  later  age  to  call 
attention  to  this  world  of  internal  discovery,  and  force  the 
human   mind  back  upon  itself;  changing  that  progressive 


CHAP.  IX.]  OP  NECESSITY.  253 

habit,  in  which  it  had  so  long  exclusively  indulged,  of 
following  up  and  arguing  interminably  upon  truths,  into 
the  stationary  one  of  examining  the  truths  themselves. 
Aquinas  accepts  the  received  statements  and  positions,  and 
expands  them  with  argumentative  subtlety  and  power. 
And  the  vast  amount  of  statements  and  positions  which 
his  mind  includes  and  thus  expands  and  treats  argumen- 
tatively  is  surprising;  showing  a  truly  enormous  grasp 
and  capacity,  somewhat  analogous  to  that  of  a  great 
statesman,  who,  without  penetrating  far  below  or  aiming 
at  a  deeper  understanding  of  the  particular  subjects  and 
questions  presented  to  his  consideration  than  he  practically 
wants,  embraces  an  immense  quantity  of  such  particulars; 
all  of  which  he  treats  argumentatively  and  is  ready  to 
discuss,  and  come  to  a  conclusion  and  decision  upon  them. 
The  argumentative  edifice,  however,  of  Aquinas,  for  want 
of  this  later  and  inward  attitude  of  mind,  shows  deep 
deficiencies ;  and  especially  that  great  vice  of  the  scholastic 
intellect  —  distinguishing  without  a  difference  ;  a  fault 
which  arises  from  accepting  the  superficial  meaning  of 
statements,  or  the  words  themselves,  without  going  into 
their  real  meaning,  which  would  often  show  that  different 
words  really  meant  the  same  thing. 

Taking  Aquinas,  therefore,  as  the  representative  of 
mediaeval  Augustinianism,  I  shall  endeavour  in  this  and 
the  following  chapter  to  give  an  account  of  his  system  so 
far  as  it  touches  on  the  particular  subject  of  the  present 
treatise.  The  examination  will  disclose  some  forms  of 
thought  and  modes  of  arguing  with  which  a  modern  mind  will 
not  sympathise,  but  to  which  it  will  rather  appeal  as  showing 
how  differently  the  intellect  of  man  reasons  in  different 
ages,  and  how  the  received  thought  of  one  period  becomes 
quaint  and  obsolete  in  another.  The  system,  however,  will 
be  found  as  a  whole  to  rest  upon  some  broad  and  common 
assumptions,  which  have  always  formed,  and  always  will 
form,  an  important  portion  of  the  basis  of  human  opinion. 


254 


SCHOLASTIC    THEOEY 


[CHAP.  IX. 


The  doctrine  of  predestination,  then,  in  the  system  of 
Aquinas,  rests  mainly  on  philosophy,  and  rises  upon  the 
idea  of  the  Divine  Power.  This  fundamental  position 
was  laid  down,  this  religious  axiom  stated  with  jealous 
exactness  and  the  most  scientific  strength  of  language, 
and  the  rest  was  deduced  by  way  of  logical  consequence 
from  it.  God  was  the  First  Great  Cause:  His  will  the 
source  of  all  things,  the  spring  of  all  motions,  all  events : 
it  could  not  be  frustrated,  it  must  always  be  fulfilled : 
se  God  hath  done  whatsoever  He  would  —  omnia  quacun- 
que  voluit  fecit,  in  ccelo  et  in  terra"  This  was  contained  in 
the  very  idea  of  Omnipotence ;  for  no  agency  can  be  impeded 
but  by  stronger  agency,  and  none  can  be  stronger  than 
Omnipotence :  it  was  contained  in  the  very  idea  of  the 
Divine  Felicity ;  for  no  one  can  be  perfectly  happy  whose 
will  is  not  fulfilled,  and  the  Supreme  Being  is  perfectly 
happy.1  Though  the  Divine  Will,  then,  acted  by  mediate 
and  secondary  causes,  both  in  the  physical  and  moral  world, 
these  causes  were  no  more  than  mediate  ones,  and  fell  back 
upon  the  First  Great  Cause,  from  which  they  derived  all 
their  efficacy.  Nor,  because  a  secondary  cause  failed  of  its 
effect,  was  there,  therefore,  any  failure  of  the  power  of  the 
First  Cause.  One  particular  cause  was  impeded  in  its  opera- 
tion by  another;  the  action  of  fire  by  that  of  water,  the 
digestive  functions  of  the  stomach  by  the  coarseness  of  the 
food  :  but  the  qualities  of  the  water  and  the  food  were 


1  "  Voluntas  Dei  causa  est  omnium 
quae  naturaliter  fiunt,  vel  facta  sive 
futura  sunt,  ....  prima  et  summa 
causa  omnium  specierum  et  motionum." 
— Lombard.  1. 1. 'Distinct.  45.  "  Cassari 
non  potest,  quia  ilia  voluntate  fecit 
quaecunque  voluit,  in  ccelo  et  in  terra, 
cui,  teste  Apostolo,  nihil  resistit." — 
Distinct.  46.  "Nulla  causa  impeditur 
nisi  ab  aliquo  fortiori  agente,  sed  nihil 
est  fortius  Divina  voluntate.  .  .  .  Prse- 
terea,  diminutio  gaudii  si  voluntas  non 
impleatur,  sed  Deus  felicissimus." — 
Aquinas,  in  Lombard.  Distinct.  47. 


"  Causalitas  autem  Dei  qui  est  primum 
agens,  se  extendit  usque  ad  omnia  entia, 
non  solum  quantum  ad  principia  spe- 
ciei,  sed  etiam  quantum  ad  individua 
principia."  —  Summa  Theologica,  P.  1. 
Queest.  22.  Art.  2. 

"  In  hujusmodi  autem  causis  non 
est  infiriitus  processus,  est  ergo  aliqua 
omnium  una  prima  qua?  est  Deus." — 
Bradwardine,  p.  190.  "  Omne  movens 
posterius  est  instrumentum  primi  mo- 
ventis,  alias  enim  non  est  posterius  na- 
turaliter eo,  sed  prius  vel  etiam  coae- 
quum," — p.  173. 


CHAP.  IX.] 


OF   NECESSITY. 


255 


also  particular  causes,  acting  under  the  Universal  Cause  as 
much  as  those  which  they  impeded.  Thus  what  seemed  to 
recede  from  the  Divine  Will  according  to  one  order,  returned 
to  it  under  another ;  and  the  failure  of  the  particular  cause 
was  the  success  of  the  universal.1 

To  the  position  that  the  Divine  Will  was  the  cause  of 
things  that  were,  succeeded  the  further  one,  that  it  could 
have  caused  every  thing  that  was,  without  a  contradiction 
in  terms,  possible?  And  stated  thus  indefinitely,  this  posi- 
tion also  was  only  a  legitimate  expansion  of  the  idea  of  the 
Divine  Power.  We  evidently  cannot  restrict  the  Divine 
Power  to  the  simple  causation  of  the  existing  world,  with- 
out reducing  it  to  a  cause  acting  itself  under  a  necessity,  or 
to  a  kind  of  fate.  If  we  liberate  the  First  Cause,  however, 
from  this  tie,  and  suppose  it  to  act  freely,  causing  some 
effects  and  not  others,  according  to  its  own  sovereign  will 
and  pleasure,  we  cannot  state  its  Power  less  narrowly  than 
as  a  Power  of  causing  anything  which  is,  in  the  nature  of 
things,  possible.  But  while  the  scholastic  position  was  in 
itself  legitimate,  it  was  carried  out  unsoundly  and  hastily. 
Its  maintainers  advanced  beyond  the  indefinite  ground 
that  God  could  cause  every  thing  that  was  possible,  to 
state  what  was  possible ;  and  they  determined  that  the 
Supreme  Being  could,  had  it  pleased  Him,  have  made 
the  whole  universe  more  perfect  than  it  was,  both  by 


1  "  Quod  si  aliqua  causa  particularis 
deficiat  a  suo  effectu,  hoc  est  propter 
aliquam  aliam  causam  particularem 
immediantem,  quse  continetur  sub  or- 
dine  causse  universalis.  Unde  effectus 
ordinem  causae  universalis  nullo  modo 
potest  exire." — Sum.  Theol.  P.  1.  Q. 
19.  Art.  6.  "  Sicut  lignum  impeditur 
a  combustione  per  actionem  aquaa." — 
Q,  22.  Art.  2.  "  Sicut  indigestio  con- 
tingit  praeter  ordinem  virtutis  nutritivae 
ex  aliquo  impedimento,  puta  ex  gros- 
sitie  cibi,  quam  necesse  est  reducere  in 
aliam  causam,  et  sic  usque  ad  causam 
primam  universalem.  Cum  igitur  Deus 


sit  prima  causa  universalis  non  unius 
generis  tantum,  sed  universaliter  totius 
ends,  impossibile  est  quod  aliquid  con- 
tingat  prapter  ordinem  divinse  guberna- 
tionis  ;  sed  ex  hoc  ipso  quod  aliquid  ex 
una  parte  videtur  exire  ab  ordine  Di- 
vinse providentiae,  quo  consideratur  se- 
cundum  aliquam  particularem  causam, 
necesse  est  quod  in  eundem  ordinem 
relabatur  secundum  aliam  causam." — 
Sum.  Theol.  P.  1.  Q.  103.  Art.  7. 

2  Cum  Deus  omnia  posse  dicitur, 
nihil  rectius  intelligitur  quam  quod 
possit  omnia  possibilia.  —  Sum.  Theol. 
P.  1.  Q.  25.  Art.  3. 


256 


SCHOLASTIC    THEORY 


[CHAP.  IX. 


adding  to  its  parts  and  species,  and  by  making  the  existing 
ones  better,  and  not  only  better  but  faultless.  The  universe 
was  finite,  and  what  was  finite  could  be  added  to ;  and  the 
scale  which  ascended^  from  this  created  world  to  infinity 
had  numberless  places  unoccupied,  which  the  Creator  could 
have  filled  up,  and  successive  types  of  being  which  He 
could  have  embodied  and  expressed,  had  He  so  willed, 
and  so  increased  the  ranks  and  orders  of  the  existing  uni- 
verse. The  existing  species,  too,  could  have  been  made 
better,  and  even  without  fault,  for  God  could,  had  it  pleased 
Him,  have  created  a  universe  in  which  there  was  no  evil ; 
and  man  himself  could  have  been  made  so  that  he  neither 
could  nor  would  even  wish  to  sin.1 

The  fundamental  idea  of  the  Divine  power  thus  laid  down 
was  applied  strictly  to  the  motions  of  the  human  will,  or  to 
human  actions.  God  was  the  cause  of  all  the  motions  of  the 
human  will,  but  He  caused  them  by  means  of  the  will  itself, 
as  a  mediate  and  secondary  cause.  The  great  scheme  of 
Divine  Providence  contained  two  great  classes  of  secondary 
causes 2,  one  necessary,  the  other  contingent.  The  course  of 
nature  was  conducted  by  means  of  necessary  causes,  or 


1  "Potest  Deus  meliorem  rem  facere, 
sive  etiam  rerum  universitatem,  quam 
fecit."— Lombard,  L.  1.  Dist.  44.  "  Se- 
cundum  philosophum  albius  est  quod 
est  nigro  impermistius :  ergo  etiam 
melius  est  quod  est  impermistius  malo : 
sed  Deus  potuit  facere  universum  in  quo 
nib.il  mali  esset.  .  .  .  Quantum  ad 
partes  ipsas  potest  intelligi  universum 
fieri  melius.  Sive  per  additionem  plu- 
rium  partium,  ut  scilicet  crearentur 
multse  alias  species,  et  implerentur 
multi  gradus  bonitatis  qui  possunt  esse, 
cum  etiam  inter  summam  creaturam  et 
Deum  infinita  distantia  sit ;  et  sic  Deus 
melius  universum  facere  potuisset  .  . 
Vel  potest  intelligi  fieri  melius  quasi 
intensive,  quasi  mutatis  omnibus  par- 
tibus  ejus  in  melius  .  .  .  et  sic  etiam 
esset  (melioratio)  Deo  possibilis." — 
Aquinas,  in  Lomb.  L.  1.  Dist.  44. 


"  Utrum  Deus  potuerit  facere  hu- 
manitatem  Christi  meliorem  quam  fit." 
—  "  Quamvis  humana  natura  sit  Divi- 
nitati  unita  in  persona,  tamen  naturee 
remanent  distantes  infinitum,  et  ex 
hoc  potest  esse  aliquid  melius  humana 
natura  in  Christo." — Aquinas,  in  Lomb. 
Dist.  44.  Art.  3. 

"  Talem  potuit  Deus  hominem  fecisse 
qui  nee  peccare  posset  nee  vellet ;  et 
si  talem  fecisset  quis  dubitet  eum  melio- 
rem fecisse." — Aug.  sup.  Gen.  ad  Lit. 
xi.  7.  Quoted  by  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  44. 

2  Causae  mediae — proximae  —  secun- 
dae.  —  "  Omnium  qua?  sunt  causa  est 
Dei  voluntas  .  .  .  mediantibus  aliis 
causis,  ut  sic  etiam  causandi  dignitas 
creaturis  communicaretur." — Aquinas, 
in  Lomb.  Dist.  45. 


CHAP.  IX.] 


OF    NECESSITY. 


257 


causes  acting  necessarily  ;  which  class,  again,  had  two  different 
operations  and  effects,  according  to  the  difference  of  the 
natures  to  which  it  was  applied.  In  fixed  and  permanent 
natures,  the  operation  of  necessary  causes  was  unfailing,  and 
they  could  not  by  possibility  fall  short  of  their  effects  ;  such 
was  the  operation  of  fixed  and  unalterable  law  in  the  motions 
of  the  heavenly  bodies,  presenting  to  us  an  instance  of  a 
world  which  was  without  change,  and  of  which  it  was  said, 
that  above  the  sphere  of  the  moon  was  no  evil.  In  generable 
and  corruptible  natures  they  had  a  failing  operation,  and  al- 
ternately attained  and  fell  short  of  their  effects :  the  Univer- 
sal Cause,  however,  being  alike  effective  in  either  case,  and 
good  alike  the  result ;  for  the  corruption  of  one  thing  was  the 
generation  of  another.1  The  second  class  of  causes  was  con- 
tingent or  voluntary,  operating  in  those  creatures  which  had 
in  addition  to  nature  the  principle  of  will.  The  effects,  then, 
which  took  place  in  the  world  took  place  necessarily,  or  con- 
tingently, according  to  the  character  of  those  mediate  and 
secondary  causes  which  were  respectively  in  operation  ;  but 
in  either  case  these  causes  were  but  mediate,  and  fell  back 
upon  the  First  Great  Cause,  from  which  they  derived  all 
their  virtue  as  secondary  ones.  The  Supreme  Being  fitted 
like  causes  to  like  effects,  necessary  to  necessary,  contingent 
to  contingent 2 ;  but  His  will  it  was  which  gave  to  these 


1  In  his  autem  qui  consequuntur  finem 
per  principium  quod  est  natura  in- 
venitur  quidam  gradus,  eo  quod  quarun- 
dam  rerun  natura  impediri  non  potest 
a  consecutione  effectus  sui,  et  iste  est 
gradus  altior  sicut  est  in  corporibus  cae- 
lestibus.  Unde  in  his  nihil  contingit 
non  intentum  a  Deo  ex  defectu  ipsorum; 
et  propter  hoc  Avicenna  dicit  quod  supra 
orbem  lunae  non  est  malum.  Alius 
autem  gradus  naturae  est  quae  impediri 
potest  et  defi cere,  sicut  natura  generabi- 
lium  et  corruptibilium  ;  et  quamvis  ista 
natura  sit  inferior  in  bonitate,  tamen 
bona  est— Aquinas,  in  Lomb.  1.  1. 
Dist.  39. 


8  "  Quibusdam  effectibus  praaparavit 
causas  necessarias  ut  necessario  eveni- 
rent;  quibusdam  vero  causas  contin- 
gentes,  ut  evenirent  contingenter,  se- 
cundum  conditionem  proximarum  cau- 
sarum." — Sum.  Theol.  P.  1.  Q.  23. 
Art.  4. 

"  Ita  omnia  movet  secundum  eorum 
conditionem  ;  ita  quod  ex  causis  neces- 
sariis  per  motionem  divinam  sequuntur 
effectus  ex  necessitate ;  ex  causis  autem 
contingentibus  sequuntur  effectus  con- 
tingentes." — lma  2a»a  Q.  49.  Art.  4. 

"  Effectus  consequitur  conditionem 
causae  suae  proximo."  —  Aquinas,  in 
Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  39. 


258 


SCHOLASTIC   THEORY 


[CHAP.  IX, 


causes  their  respective  natures,  and  made  one  necessary  and 
the  other  contingent.1  He  moved  matter,  and  He  moved 
will  by  causes  alike  of  His  own  arbitrary  and  sovereign 
creation.  He  produced  the  motions  of  the  physical  world 
by  necessary,  the  motions  of  the  human  will  by  voluntary 
causes ;  but  these  voluntary  causes  were  set  in  motion  by 
Himself;  God  was  the  cause  ojf  the  will.2  The  aims,  the 
designs,  the  deliberations,  and  the  acts  of  man  were  sub- 
jected to  the  Divine  Will,  as  being  derived  ultimately  from 
it ;  and  man's  providence  was  contained  under  the  Divine,  as 
the  particular  cause  under  the  universal.3 

Such  was  the  logical  consequence  of  the  idea  of  the 
Divine  power,  as  regards  the  human  will.  Under  the  notion 
of  the  will,  as  a  mediate  cause,  the  Augustinian  schoolmen 
left  out  no  function,  action,  or  characteristic  of  will  of  which 
the  human  soul  is  conscious.  They  acknowledged  every  in- 
ternal act  and  sensation  which  belongs  to  us  as  having  and 
exercising  will ;  that  which  every  reasonable  man  who  does 
not  deny  the  plainest  facts  must  admit.;  .-They  brought  all 
these  characteristics  to  a  point,  and  expressed  them  in 
one  term  —  self-motion.  The  will  moved  itself,  was  the 
cause  of  its  own  motion,  the  mistress  of  its  own  acts;  it  was 
in  its  power  to  will  or  not  to  will.  Man  moved  himself 
to  action  by  his  freewill.  But  this  self-motion  was  only 
admitted  as  an  internal  impression,  and  was  not  allowed  to 
counteract  or  modify  the  dominant  position  of  one  absolute 


1  Dicendum  est  quod  hoc  contingit 
propter  efficaciamDivinaevoluntatis.  .  . 
Vult  enim  quaedam  Deus  necessario, 
quaedam  contingenter,  ut  sit  ordo  in 
rebus  ad  complementum  universi.  Et 
ideo  quibusdam  effectibus  aptavit  causas 
necessarias,  ex  quibus  effectus  ex  ne- 
cessitate proveniant;  quibusdam  autem 
causas  defectibiles,  ex  quibus  effectus 
contingenter  proveniant.  Non  igitur 
propterea  effectus  voliti  a  Deo  eveniunt 
rontingenter,  quia  causa?  proximas  sunt 
contingentes  ;  sed  propterea  quia  Deus 


voluit  eos  contingenter  evenire,  contin- 
gentes causas  ad  eos  praeparavit.  —  Sum. 
Theol.  lma  Q.  19.  Art.  8. 

2  "  Voluntatis  causa  nihil  aliud  esse 
potest  quam  Deus." — Sum.   Theol.  lro" 
2dae   Q.  10.  Art.  6.     "Deus  est   causa 
prima  movens   et    naturales  causas  et 
voluntarias." —  lm»  Q.  83.  Art.  1. 

3  « Providentia   hominis   continetur 
sub  provident  ia  Dei  sicut  particularis 
causa    sub   causa   universali." —  Sum. 
Theol.  lm»  Q.  23.  Art.  2. 


CHAP.  IX.] 


OF    NECESSITY. 


259 


causality.  The* will  was  a  principle  of  motion  to  itself;  but 
it  was  not,  therefore,  ihejirst  principle  of  such  motion, —  it  did 
not  follow  that  this  principle  of  motion  was  not  itself  set  in 
motion  by  something  else.  The  will  was  the  internal  prin- 
ciple of  its  own  motion ;  but  this  self-determining  power  moved 
the  will  as  causa  proximo,  not  as  causa  prima  ;  the  internal 
principle  was  only  a  secondary  one,  succeeding  to  a  first  prin- 
ciple, which  was  external  to  the  will.  The  will,  though  it 
moved  itself,  was  moved  ab  alio  to  this  motion.  Nor  was  the 
true  and  genuine  voluntariness  of  its  motions  at  all  affected 
by  their  source  being  external.  For  the  Supreme  Mover  did 
not,  by  setting  natural  causes  in  motion,  hinder  the  acts 
in  which  such  causes  issued  from  being  natural ;  no  more, 
when  He  set  in  motion  the  voluntary  causes,  did  He  hinder 
the  acts  in  which  they  issued  from  being  voluntary.  Rather 
He  Himself  caused  in  these  acts  their  voluntariness,  and 
their  naturalness  respectively,  working  in  each  nature  accord- 
ing to  its  peculiarity  —  in  unoquoque  operans  secundum  ejus 
proprietatem.1 

And  this  consideration  supplied  the  answer  to  the  question 
how  our  wills  could  be  moved  from  without,  and  yet  feel 
no  force,  no  constraint,  but  all  its  motions  go  on  exactly  as 
if  they  originated  in  ourselves.  There  were  two  kinds  of 


1  "  Voluntas  domina  est  sui  actus,  et 
in  ipsa  est  velle  et  non  velle  ;  quod  non 
esset  si  non  haberet  in  potestate  movere 
seipsam  ad  volendum." —  lm»  2dM  Q. 
9.  Art.  3. 

"Liberum  arbitrium  est  causa  sui 
motus:  quia  homo  per  liberum  arbi- 
trium seipsum  movet  ad  agendum. 
Non  tamen  hoc  est  necessitate  libertatis 
quod  sit  prima  eausa  sui  id  quod  liberum 
est ;  sicut  nee  ad  hoc  quod  aliquid  sit 
causa  alterius,  requiritur  quod  sit 
prima  causa  ejus.  Deus  igitur  est 
prima  causa  movens  et  naturales  causas 
et  voluntarias.  Et  sicut  naturalibus 
causis,  movendo  eas,  non  aufert  quin 
actus  earum  sint  naturales,  ita  movendo 
causas  voluntarias,  non  aufert  quin 


actiones  earum  sint  voluntarise,  sed 
potius  hoc  in  eis  facit ;  operatur  enim 
in  unoquoque  secundum  ejus  proprie- 
tatem."—  Sum.  Theol.  lma  Q.  83. 
Art.  1. 

"  De  ratione  voluntarii  est  quod 
principium  ejus  sit  intra ;  sed  non  oport- 
et  quod  hoc  principium  intrinsecum 
sit  primum  principium  non  motum  ab 
alio.  Unde  motus  voluntarius,  etsi  ha- 
bp.at  principium  proximum  intrinsecum, 
tamen  principium  primum  est  ab  extra  ; 
sicut  et  primum  principium  motus  na- 
turalis  est  ab  extra,  quod  scilicet  movet 
naturam." —  lma  2dae  Q.  9.  Art.  3. 

"  Ipse  actus  liberi  arbitrii  reducitur 
in  Deum  sicut  in  causam." —  lma  Q. 
23.  Art.  2. 


s   2 


260 


SCHOLASTIC   THEORY 


[CHAP.  IX. 


necessity,  the  necessity  of  force,  and  the  necessity  of  nature 
or  inclination.  The  necessity  of  force  was  vi  termini  opposed 
to  inclination,  and  if  it  prevailed,  prevailed  in  spite  of  it, 
and  was  attended  with  the  sensation  to  the  man  of  being 
forced  or  obliged  to  do  a  thing.  But  the  necessity  of  in- 
clination, or  that  which  made  the  inclination  to  be  what  it 
was,  could  only  be  felt  as  inclination,  not  as  force.  For  the 
inclination  itself  was  to  begin  with  that  which  such  necessity 
had  made  it  to  be ;  it  could  have  felt  nothing  contrary  to  it, 
nothing  violating  it,  in  that  which  was  not  its  combatant,  or 
its  coercer,  but  its  cause.1 

Now  it  is  evident  that  such  a  scheme  as  this  is  necessi- 
tarian, and  is  inconsistent  with  the  ordinary  doctrine  of 
freewill ;  because  freewill  is  here  not  truly  self-moving,  and 
an  original  spring  of  action.  It  is  not  a  first  cause,  but  a 
second  cause,  subordinated  to  another  above  it,  which  sets  it 
in  motion.  But  the  will,  as  a  link  in  a  chain  of  causes  and 
effects,  is  not  freewill,  in  the  common  and  true  understanding 
of  that  term,  according  to  which  it  means  an  original  source 
of  action.  Freewill  is  here  reconciled  and  made  consistent 
with  the  Divine  Power ;  brought  into  the  same  scheme  and 
theory.  But  it  is  of  itself  a  sufficient  test  that  a  system  is 
necessitarian,  that  it  maintains  the  Divine  Power  in  harmony 
with  freewill.  The  will  as  an  original  spring  of  action  is 
irreconcilable  with  the  Divine  Power,  a  second  first  cause  in 
nature  being  inconsistent  with  there  being  only  one  First 
Cause.  To  reconcile  freewill,  then,  with  the  Divine  Power 
is  to  destroy  it ;  because  such  a  reconciliation  can  only  be 
effected  by  subordinating  one  to  the  other,  in  the  way  just 
described,  as  second  cause  to  first  cause,  and  so  depriving 


1  "Haec  igitur  coactionis  necessitas 
omnino  repugnat  voluntati.  Nam  hoc 
dicimus  esse  violentum  quod  est  contra 
inclinationem  rei.  Ipse  autem  motus 
voluntatis  est  inclinatio  qusedam  in 
aliquid  :  et  ideo,  sicut  dicitur  aliquid 
naturale,  quia  est  secundum  inclinatio- 
nem naturae  ;  ita  dicitur  aliquid  volun- 


tarium,  quia  est  secundum  inclinationem 
voluntatis.  Sicut  ergo  impossibile  est 
quod  aliquid  simul  sit  violentum  et 
naturale ;  ita  impossibile  est  quod  aliquid 
simpliciter  sit  coactum,  sive  violentum, 
et  voluntarium.  Necessitas  autem  na- 
turalis  non  repugnat  voluntati." —  1™» 
Q.  82.  A.  4. 


CHAP.  IX.]  OP   NECESSITY.  261 

the  will  of  that  which  constitutes  its  freedom,  in  the  common 
acceptation  of  the  word,  viz.  its  originality.  Freewill  to 
be  true  freewill  must  be  inconsistent  with  the  other  great 
truth  ;  it  must  be  held  as  something  existing  side  by  side  with 
the  Divine  Attribute,  but  never  uniting  to  our  understanding 
with  it.  This  inconsistency,  this  absence  of  relation,  is  the 
only  security  for  its  genuineness ;  the  removal  of  which  is, 
therefore,  fatal  to  it.  When,  in  the  place  of  philosophical 
disagreement,  we  have  philosophical  unity,  one  consistent 
scheme  and  theory,  one  connection  of  part  with  part,  one 
harmony  of  cause  with  cause,  we  have,  in  the  place  of  two 
truths,  one  truth,  and  the  Divine  Power  is  maintained,  but 
freewill  is  abandoned. 

Such  a  compact  and  harmonious  theory,  however,  en- 
countered in  limine  one  great  difficulty.  Upon  the  idea 
of  the  Divine  Power,  thus  singly  and  determinately  carried 
out,  and  made  the  exclusive  rationale  of  all  the  facts  in 
the  universe,  how  were  we  to  account  for  the  origin  of 
evil  ?  The  existence  of  evil  was  a  plain  fact,  Was  God  the 
cause  of  it  ?  That  could  not  be  ;  for  God  could  not  possibly 
will  evil.  Did  it  exist  in  spite  of  Him,  and  against  His 
will  ?  That  could  not  be ;  for  God  could  not  possibly  be 
deficient  in  power.  Then  how  was  its  existence  to  be  ac- 
counted for  ? 

Now,  evil  is  sometimes  understood  in  a  negative  rather 
than  in  a  positive  sense, — in  the  sense  of  a  defect  and  falling 
short,  of  lesser  as  contrasted  with  greater  good ;  and  in  this 
sense  it  was  not  difficult  to  account  for  the  existence  of 
evil  in  the  universe.  For  if  we  considered  it  inconsistent 
with  the  justice  and  benevolence  of  God,  that  He  should 
not  make  everything  the  very  best,  where  were  we  to  stop 
in  our  demand?  We  could  not  pause  till  we  reached  in 
our  wishes  the  very  highest  point  of  all,  and  arrived  at  the 
Uncreated  Perfection  itself.  Wherever  we  stopped  below 
this  culminating  point,  the  same  charge  could  be  urged  as 
now,  that  things  were  not  made  so  good  as  they  could 

s  s 


262 


SCHOLASTIC   THEORY 


[CHAP.  IX. 


be  made.  But  a  desire  that  tended  straight  to  the  con- 
fusion of  the  distinction  between  the  creature  and  God, 
and  could  not  be  satisfied  but  by  a  contradiction,  was 
absurd ;  and  a  charge  which  would  always  be  made,  whatever 
the  Creator  might  do,  was  untenable.  The  possibility,  then, 
of  things  being  made  better  argued  no  envy  in  God  who 
made  them  worse,  and  the  existence  of  evil,  in  the  sense 
of  lesser  good,  was  no  real  difficulty  at  all.1 

But  evil  existed  in  the  world,  not  only  in  the  sense  of 
lesser  good,  but  in  that  of  positive  evil;  and  this  was  a 
more  difficult  fact  to  account  for.  The  explanations  of 
this  fundamental  difficulty,  then,  by  the  Augustiriian  school- 
men may  be  placed  under  two  heads:  under  the  first 
of  which  the  explanation  is  almost  purely  verbal,  and  can 
hardly  be  said  to  come  into  contact  even  with  the  real 
difficulty;  while  under  the  second  the  difficulty  is  really 
confronted,  and  an  effort  of  a  philosophical  kind  made  to 
solve  it. 


I.  The  first  of  these  verbal  explanations  which  I  will 
instance,  and  which  is  a  rather  extreme  specimen  of  its 
class,  is  an  attempt  to  pare  down  by  simple  artifices  of 
language  the  opposition  of  the  Divine  Will  to  evil,  till 
it  reaches  a  point  at  which  it  substantially  ceases,  and 
becomes  a  manageable  truth  to  the  metaphysician.  It  is 
evident  that,  so  Ipng  as  the  opposition  of  the  Divine  Will 
to  evil  remains  decided  and  absolute,  there  being  this  evil 
as  a  plain  fact  in  the  world,  such  opposition  affects  the 
attribute  of  the  Divine  Power;  because  if  God  does  not 
will  evil,  it  would  appear  that  evil  takes  place  only  because 


1  Cuilibet  finite  possibilis  est  ad- 
ditio;  sed  cujuslibet  creaturae  bonitas 
finita  est.  Ergo  potest  sibi  fieri  additio, 
sed  creatura  nunquam  potest  attingere 
ad  aequalitatem  Dei.  Nee  alia  mensura 
divinae  bonitatis  sibi  debetur  quam  se- 


cundurn  determinationem  divinae  vo- 
luntatis,  et  ideo  nulla  invidia  in  Deo 
resultat,  si  rem  meliorem  facere  potuit 
quam  fecerit.  —  Aquinas,  in  Lomb, 
Dist.  43.  Q.  1.  A.  1. 


CHAP.  IX.] 


OF    NECESSITY-. 


263 


He  has  not  the  power  to  prevent  it.  The  aim,  therefore, 
was  to  reduce  by  niceties  of  expression  this  opposition  of 
the  Divine  Will,  until  that  will  ceased  to  disagree  with  evil, 
and,  as  a  consequence,  its  frustration  ceased ;  and  with  it  the 
danger  to  the  attribute  of  Power.  A  distinction  was  accord- 
ingly drawn  between  "  God  not  willing  evil — mala  velle  "  and 
God  not  willing  that  evil  should  take  place — velle  mala  non 
fieri;  and,  allowing  that  God  did  not  will  evil,  it  was 
determined  that  He  did  will  that  evil  should  take  place. 
Again,  those  who  objected  to  this  position  as  being  opposed 
to  the  goodness  of  the  Divine  Will,  made  a  distinction 
between  "  God  not  willing  that  evil  should  take  place  "  and 
"  God  willing  that  evil  should  not  take  place  ;  "  accepting  the 
former,  but  rejecting  the  latter  formula,  the  difference  being 
in  the  situation  of  the  negative  adverb  in  the  two  state- 
ments ;  which  in  the  one  is  next  to  "  willing,"  in  the  other 
to  "  taking  place ; "  and  these  denied  accordingly  -  that 
"God  willed  that  evil  should  not  take  place."1  Here, 
then,  are  two  modifications  of  the  opposition  of  the  Divine 
will  to  evil,  one  professing  to  be  an  improvement  on  the 


1  Alii  dicunt  quod  Dens  vult  mala 
ease  vel  fieri,  non  tamen  vult  mala.  Alii 
vero  quod  nee  vult  mala  esse  nee  fieri. 
In  hoc  tamen  conveniunt  et  hi  et  illi 
quod  utrique  fatentur  Deum  mala  non 
velle.  Utrique  vero  rationibus  et  auctori- 
tatibus  utuntur  ad  muniendam  suam  as- 
sertionem.  Qui  enim  dicunt  Deum  mala 
velle  esse  vel  fieri  suam  his  modis  mu- 
niunt  intentionem.  Si  enim,  inquiunt, 
mala  non  esse  vel  non  fieri  vellet,  nullo 
niodo  essent  vel  fierent,  quia  si  vult  ea 
non  esse  vel  non  fieri,  et  non  potest  id 
efficere,  scilicet  ut  non  sint  vel  non 
fiant,  voluntati  ejus  et  potentiae  aliquid 
resistit,  et  non  est  omnipotens,  quia 
non  potest  quod  vult,  sed  impotens 
est  sicut  et  nos  sumus,  qui  quod  vo- 
lumus  quandoque  non  possumus.  Sed 
quia  omnipotens  est  et  in  nullo  im- 
potens, certum  est  non  posse  fieri 
mala  vel  esse  nisi  eo  volente.  Quo- 
modo  enim  invito  eo  et  nolente  posset  ab 


aliquo  malum  fieri,  cum  scriptum  est, 
Rom.  9.,  voluntati  ejus  quis  resistit? 
Supra  etiam  dixit  Augustinus  quia  ne- 
cesse  est  fieri  si  voluerit.  Sed  vult 
mala  fieri  aut  non  fieri  Si  vult  non 
fieri  non  fiunt ;  fiunt  autem,  vult  ergo 
fieri. 

Illi  vero  qui  dicunt  Dei  voluntate 
mala  non  fieri  vel  non  esse,  inductio- 
nibus  praemissis  ita  respondent,  dicentes 
Deum  nee  velle  mala  fieri,  nee  velle  non 
fieri,  vel  nolle  fieri,  sed  tantum  non  velle 
fieri.  Si  enim  vellet  ea  fieri  vel  esse, 
faceret  utique  ea  fieri  vel  esse,  et  ita 
esset  auctor  malorum.  .  .  .  Item  si 
nollet  mala  fieri,  vel  vellet  non  fieri, 
et  tamen  fierent,  omnipotens  non  esset. 
....  Ideoque  non  concedunt  Deum 
velle  mala  fieri  ne  malorum  auctor  in- 
telligatur,  nee  concedunt  eum  velle  mala 
non  fieri,  ne  impotens  esse  videatur,  sed 
tantum  dicunt  eum  non  velle  mala  fieri. 
—Lombard,  1.  1 .  Dist.  46. 


8   4 


264 


SCHOLASTIC    THEORY 


[CHAP.  IX. 


other.  But  it  is  obvious  that  such  modifications  are  no 
more  than  plays  of  words,  and  can  lead  to  no  result ;  because 
in  proportion  as  these  statements  reduce  the  opposition  of 
the  Divine  Will  to  evil,  they  cease  to  be,  in  their  natural 
meaning,  true ;  while  in  proportion  as  an  artificial  inter- 
pretation relieves  them  of  falsehood,  it  divests  them  also 
of  use  for  the  purpose  for  which  they  are  wanted.  They 
either  deny  a  characteristic  of  the  Divine  Will,  and  in 
that  case  they  are  false ;  or  they  admit  it,  and  in  that  case 
they  fail  of  their  object  of  relieving  the  attribute  of  the 
Divine  Power. 

Again,  a  distinction  was  made  between  the  Divine  Will 
and  the  signs  of  it,  —  voluntas  and  signa  voluntatis  ;  between 
the  will  itself  of  God,  and  those  outward  expressions  of  it 
which  were  given  in  accommodation  to  our  understandings 
and  for  the  practical  purposes  of  life  and  conduct, —  precept, 
prohibition,  permission,  and  the  like  — pr&ceptio,  prohibit™, 
permissio  ;  between  a  real  and  a  metaphorical  will  of  God, — 
the  one  being  called  voluntas  beneplaciti,  the  other  voluntas 
signi.1  And  the  object  of  this  distinction  is  the  same  with 


1  "  Aliquando  vero  secundum  quandam 
figuram  dicendi  voluntas  Dei  vocatur, 
quod  secundum  proprietatem  non  est 
voluntas  ejus:  ut  praeceptio,  prohibitio, 
consilium,  ideoque  pluraliter  aliquando 
Scriptura  voluntates  Dei  pronuntiat. 
Unde  Propheta  psalm  1 1 0.  Magna  opera 
Domini,  exqnisita  in  omnes  voluntates 
ejus,  cum  ron  s;t  nisi  una  voluntas  Dei 
quae  ipse  est.  .  .  .  Ideo  autem  praeceptio 
et  prohibitio  atque  consilium,  cum  sint 
tria,  dicitur  tamen  unumquodque  eo- 
rum  Dei  voluntas,  quia  ista  sunt  signa 
divinae  voluntatis:  quemadmodum  et 
signa  irse  dicuntur  ira,  et  dilectionis 
signa  dllectio  appellantur ;  et  dicitur 
iratus  Deus,  et  tamen  non  est  ira  in  eo 
aliqua,  sed  signa  tantum  quae  foris  fiunt, 
quibus  iratus  ostenditur,  ira  ipsius  no- 
minantur.  Et  est  figura  dicendi,  se- 
cundum quam  non  est  falsum  qucd 
dicitur,  sed  verum  quod  dicitur  sub 
tropi  nubilo  obumbratur.  Et  secundum 


hos  tropos  diverse  voluntates  Dei  di- 
cuntur, quia  diversa  sunt  ilia  quae  per 
tropum  voluntas  Dei  dicuntur." 

"  Magna  est  adhibenda  discretio  in 
cognitione  Divinse  voluntatis,  quia  et 
beneplacitum  Dei  est  voluntas  ejus,  et 
signum  beneplaciti  ejus  dicitur  voluntas 
ejus.  Sed  beneplacitum  ejus  aeternum 
est,  signum  vero  beneplaciti  ejus  non." 
—  Lombard,  1.  1.  Dist.  45. 

"  Voluntas  Dei  distinguitur  in  volun- 
tatem  beneplaciti  et  voluntatem  signi. 
.  .  De  Deo  quaedam  dicuntur  proprie, 
quaedam  metaphorice.  Ea  quae  proprie 
de  ipso  dicuntur,  vere  in  eo  sunt ;  sed 
ea,  quae  metaphorice  dicuntur  de  eo,  per 
similitudinem  proportionabilitatis  ad 
effectum  aliquem,  sicut  dicitur  ignis 
Deutero.  4.,  eo  quod  sicut  ignis  se  habet 
ad  consumptionem  contrarii,  ita  Deus 
ad  consumendam  nequitiam.  .  .  Deus 
potest  did  aliquid  velle  dupliciter ;  vel 
proprie,  et  sic  dicitur  velle  Ulud,  cujus 


CHAP.  IX.] 


OP   NECESSITY. 


265 


that  of  the  preceding  ones ;  viz.  to  enable  the  theologian 
to  refer  to  a  Divine  Will,  which  was  in  some  way  not 
opposed  to  evil,  and  with  which,  therefore,  evil  could  co- 
exist without  risk  to  the  attribute  of  the  Divine  Power. 
That  will  of  God  which  came  into  contact  with  our  under- 
standings, which  commanded  and  which  prohibited,  was 
opposed  to  evil ;  and  this  will  could  be  violated,  neglected, 
and  trodden  under  foot  by  the  passion  and  the  pride  of  man. 
But  that  secret  and  ulterior  will  which  lay  behind  this 
external  and  expressed  one,  was  not  opposed  to  any,  but 
harmonised  with  all  facts ;  and  evil  was  no  rebel  against  it, 
but  its  subject ;  nothing  impeded,  then,  but  everything  in 
heaven  and  earth  fulfilled  this  eternal,  incomprehensible  Will, 
which  was  of  the  essence  of  God,  and  which  was  God. 

Now,  this  distinction  is  drawn  with  greater  breadth,  bold- 
ness, and  strength  than  the  preceding  ones ;  but  it  is  open 
to  the  same  answer,  viz.  that  so  far  as  it  denies  the  disagree- 
ment of  the  Divine  Will  with  evil  it  is  false,  so  far  as  it 
admits  it  it  is  useless  for  its  purpose.  This  position  of  a  real 
will  of  God  which  is  different  from  His  expressed  will  may  be 
interpreted  in  two  ways.  It  may  be  understood  as  meaning 
that  the  real  will  of  God  is  in  true  and  actual  harmony  with 
evil,  the  expressed  being  only  an  outside  show,  which  is 
useful  in  some  way  for  the  Divine  government  of  mankind 
in  this  present  state,  and  the  maintenance  of  this  existing 
system.  And  a  theory  like  this  has  been  put  forward  in 
modern  times,  representing  the  Divine  Will,  as  expressed  in 
the  distinction  of  good  and  evil,  as  a  mere  mask,  concealing 
a  deeper  truth  behind  it ;  a  truth  of  pure  fact,  in  which  good 
and  evil  meet  and  are  united,  and  each  is  good.  The  com- 
mands and  prohibitions,  the  promises  and  the  terrors  of 
the  moral  law,  are  according  to  such  a  theory  but  a  dis- 


voluntas  vere  in  eo  est,  et  h<ec  est  volun- 
tas  be.neplaciti.  Dicitur  etiam  aliquid 
velle  metaphorice,  eo  quod  ad  modum 
volentis  se  habet,  in  quantum  prcecipit, 
vel  consulit,  vel  aliquid  hujusmodi  facit. 


Unde  ea,  in  quibus  attenditur  similitudo 
istius  rei  ad  voluntatem  Dei,  voluntates 
ejus  metaphorice  dicuntur,  et  quia  talia 
sunt  effectus,  dicuntur  signa. " — Aquinas, 
in  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  45.  A.  4. 


266 


SCHOLASTIC   THEORY 


[CHAP.  IX. 


play,  which  deludes  the  mass,  but  is  penetrated  by  the 
philosopher.  And  understood  in  such  a  way  this  position 
does  indeed  get  rid  most  effectually  of  the  difficulty  of 
the  existence  of  evil  as  being  against  the  will  of  God, 
and  so  a  sign  against  His  Power,  But  then,  understood 
in  such  a  way,  this  position  is  false  and  impious.  We 
cannot  suppose  any  difference  between  the  real  and  the 
expressed  will  of  God1,  without  destroying  the  basis  of 
all  morals  and  religion.  But  if  this  position  does  not  mean 
this,  as  in  the  minds  of  those  who  maintained  it  it  did  not, 
it  is  not  available  for  the  object  for  which  it  is  designed. 
For  all  it  means  to  assert  in  that  case  is  the  incompre- 
hensibility of  the  Divine  Will,  and  that  there  is  some 
mysterious  sense  in  which  everything  which  takes  place 
agrees  with  this  will ;  but  this  is  not  to  explain  the  difficulty 
of  the  co-existence  of  evil  with  that  will,  but  only  to  state  it, 
A  distinction,  again,  was  drawn  between  an  antecedent 
will  of  God — voluntas  antecedens,  and  a  posterior  will  — 
voluntas  consequens ;  the  former  of  which  willed  a  thing 
absolutely — simpliciter,  the  latter  conditionally — secundum 
quid2 ;  and  the  former  of  which  was  opposed  to  evil,  the 
latter  not.  Thus  God  willed  the  salvation  of  all  men  on 
the  one  hand  absolutely ;  and  that  will,  which  was  opposed 
to  all  evil,  to  sin  and  punishment  alike,  could  be  frustrated 


1  "  Et  si  ilia  dicantur  Dei  voluntas, 
ideo  quia  signa  sunt  Divinae  voluntatis, 
non   est   tamen    iutelligendum    Deum 
omne  illud   fieri  velle  quod  cuicunque 
praecipit,  vel  non  fieri  quod  prohibuit. 
Praecepit  enim  Abrahae  immolare  filium, 
nee  tamen  voluit ;  nee  ideo  prascepit  ut 
id   fieret,   sed   ut   Abrahae   probaretur 
fides ;  et  in  evangelic  praecepit  sanato 
lie  cui  diceret ;  ille  autem  praedicavit 
ubique,    intelligens    Deum    non    ideo 
prohibuisse,    quin    vellet    opus    suum 
praedicari,  sed  ut  daret  formarn  homini, 
laudem  humanam  declinandi." — Lomb. 
1.  1.  Dist.  45. 

2  «  Voluntas  Dei  duplex,  antecedens 
et    consequens  .  .  .  propter    diversas 


conditiones  ipsius  voliti.  Si  in  homine 
tantum  natura  ipsius  consideretur, 
sequaliter  bonum  est  omnem  hominem 
salvari,  et  hoc  Deus  vult,  et  heec  est 
voluntas  antecedent.  .  .  .  Consideratis 
autem  circumstantii?,  non  vult  omnem 
.  .  .  non  volentem  et  resistentem." — 
Aquinas,  in  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  46.  Q.  1. 
A.  1. 

«'  Quicquid  vult  Deus  voluntate  con- 
sequent! totum  fit,  non  autem  quicquid 
vult  voluntate  antecedent! ;  quia  hoc 
non  simpliciter  vult,  sed  secundum  quid 
tantum  ;  nee  ista  imperfectio  est  ex 
parte  voluntatis,  sed  ex  conditione 
voliti."— In  Lomb.  Dist.  47.  Q.  1. 
A.  1. 


CHAP.  IX.]  OF    NECESSITY.  267 

—  imperfectio  antecedentis  voluntatis.  But,  on  the  other 
hand,  He  willed  this  salvation  conditionally — i.e.  on  the 
supposition  that  men  were  good;  and  this  will,  which  was 
not  opposed  to  the  evil  of  punishment  if  men  were  bad,  could 
not  be  frustrated,  being  as  much  fulfilled  in  the  damnation 
of  men  as  in  their  salvation.  This  distinction,  then,  had  the 
same  aim  as  the  former;  viz.  to  establish  a  Divine  Will  which 
was  not  opposed  to  evil,  and  which  therefore  the  existence 
of  evil  did  not  frustrate,  and  so  interfere  with  the  Divine 
Power.  But  while  the  difficulty  which  this  distinction 
professes  to  meet  is  in  the  case  of  the  will  antecedent  simply 
confessed  instead  of  solved,  it  is  only  evaded  instead  of  solved 
in  the  case  of  the  will  consequent.  God  wills  the  salvation 
of  men  on  the  condition  that  they  are  good;  which  will,  if 
they  are  bad,  is  not  opposed  to  the  evil  of  their  punishment. 
The  evil  of  punishment,  then,  is  here  accounted  for  and  made 
to  agree  with  the  Divine  Power,  because  made  to  agree  with 
the  Divine  Will :  but  what  account  is  given  of  the  evil  of  that 
sin  which  is  the  reason  of  punishment  ?  This  evil  is  passed 
over  altogether.  Yet  it  is  a  plain  evil  which  takes  place 
in  the  universe,  and  we  must  either  say  that  the  will  of 
God  is  opposed  to  it  or  not ;  the  former  alternative  being  appa- 
rently inconsistent  with  the  Divine  Power,  the  latter  with 
the  Divine  Goodness.  The  difficulty  put  off  at  one  stage  thus 
meets  us  at  another ;  and  an  evil  remains  which  we  cannot 
without  impiety  assert  not  to  be  opposed  to  the  Divine 
Will,  and  the  existence  of  which  therefore  is  inconsistent 
apparently  with  the  Divine  Power. 

II.  To  these  verbal  explanations,  however,  there  succeeded 
two  which  were  attempts  at  real  explanation.  One  of  these 
was  the  argument  of  variety,  which  was  put  in  two  forms ; 
under  the  first  of  which,  however,  it  did  not  satisfy  its  own 
employers,  who  used  it  with  evident  misgivings,  though  they 
would  not  deprive  themselves  of  its  aid  altogether.  Should 
there  not  be  evil  in  the  world,  that  the  contrast  may  heighten 


268 


SCHOLASTIC    THEORY 


[CHAP.  IX. 


the  good  and  set  it  off  to  better  advantage  ?  Would  the  good 
be  appreciated  as  it  should  be,  and  its  real  nature  come  to 
light ,  but  for  this  evil  ?  And  in  this  way  is  not  evil  of  the 
perfection  of  the  universe  —  de  perfections  universi  ?  The  solu- 
tion was  a  tempting  one ;  but  it  was  resisted,  on  the  ground 
that  the  loss  which  evil  caused  was  greater  than  the  com- 
pensation it  gave  for  it ;  inasmuch  as  it  took  away  absolute 
good,  and  only  gave  comparative.1  The  solid  justice  of 
this  reply  embraces  within  a  short  compass  all  the  points  of 
the  case.  Variety  is  a  sound  explanation  indeed  of  a  certain 
class  of  evils.  The  decay  and  corruption  of  the  vegetable 
world  set  off  by  contrast  the  birth  and  growth ;  summer 
is  all  the  more  agreeable  for  winter ;  the  decay  of  autumn 
heightens  the  freshness  of  the  spring.  And  on  the  same 
law  rest  is  all  the  more  pleasant  after  fatigue,  food  after 
hunger ;  and  much  even  of  the  higher  and  more  intellectual 
kind  of  pleasure  is  relished  the  more  for  the  void  and  dul- 
ness  alternating  with  it.  But  this  is  only  by  a  law  of  our 
nature  in  present  operation,  in  consequence  of  which  change 
is  necessary  for  us,  though  at  the  cost  of  pain.  Such  a 
law  is  acknowledged  to  be  a  sign  of  great  imperfection. 
And,  what  is  more  to  the  purpose,  all  these  are  cases  in 
which  ourselves  alone  and  our  own  enjoyment  are  concerned. 
To  inanimate  nature  it  is  all  the  same  whether  it  decays 
or  endures,  lives  or  dies ;  and  therefore  we  need  not  take 
its  part  in  the  matter  into  account.  But  when  we  come 
to  moral  evil  the  case  is  very  different.  It  is  true  the 
law  of  comparison  or  contrast  operates  even  here,  and 
we  are  pleased  with  the  virtue  which  meets  us  in  the 


1  "  Illud  sine  quo  universum  raelius 
esset  non  confert  ad  perfectionem  uni- 
versi :  sed  si  malura  non  esset  universum 
melius  esset,  quia  malum  plus  tollit  uni 
quam  addit  alteri,  quia  eicujusest  tollit 
bonitatem  absolutam,  alteri  autera  addit 
bonitatera  comparationis." —  In  Lomb. 
1.  1.  Dist.  46.  Q.  1.  A.  3. 

Yet  Aquinas  reverts  to  this  rationale 


of  the  existence  of  evil  with  approval : 
"  Dicendum  quod  ex  ipsa  bonitate  Di- 
vina  ratio  sumi  potest  prsedestinationis 
aliquorum  et  reprobationis  aliquorum. 
...  Ad  completionem  enim  universi 
requiruntur  diversi  gradus  rerum,  qua- 
rum  quaedam  altum  et  quaedam  in- 
nmum  locum  teneant  in  universe." — 
Sum.  Theol.  lm*  Q.  23.  A.  5. 


CHAP.  IX.] 


OF   NECESSITY. 


269 


world,  all  the  more  for  the  evil  which  we  see  in  it. 
Indeed,  the  nature  or  quality  of  goodness  —  the  light  that 
issues  from  a  good  character,  is  so  completely  seen  in  the 
sense  and  degree  in  which  we  do  see  it,  by  means  of  this 
assistance — i.  e.  by  the  contrast  between  this  goodness  and  a 
background  of  average  and  indifferent  character,  formed  as 
an  image  in  our  mind  from  the  experience  of  human  life,  — 
that  it  is  difficult  to  contemplate  without  some  surprise 
and  awe  the  signal  and  noble  use  which  the  wickedness  of 
the  world  answers ;  inasmuch  as  for  anything  we  see  to  the 
contrary,  in  the  present  state  of  our  capacities,  in  which 
contrast  seems  to  be  so  essential  to  true  perception,  virtue 
could  not  be  appreciated  as  it  is  without  this  contrast,  or  be 
the  bright  light  which  it  is  without  this  dark  background. 
The  light  shineth  in  darkness.  But  though  moral  evil  answers 
this  high  purpose  in  the  world,  is  it  a  sufficient  account 
of  its  existence  that  it  does  so  ?  Is  it  just  that  one  man 
should  be  wicked  in  order  that  the  virtue  of  another  may 
be  set  off?  The  spectator  may  derive  benefit  from  the 
contrast,  but  there  is  another  whose  interests  are  quite  as 
important  as  his. 

And  the  same  may  be  said  of  the  use  of  which  the  moral 
evil  in  the  world  is,  for  the  trial,  purification,  and  confirm- 
ation of  the  good.  The  wickedness  of  the  bad  portion  of 
mankind  is  indeed  one  of  the  principal  means  by  which  the 
good  portion  is  educated  and  disciplined;  the  pride  and 
tyranny  of  one  man  serve  to  produce  the  virtue  of  patience  in 
another ;  the  wrongs  of  the  world  subdue  and  temper,  its  cor- 
ruptions and  temptations  fortify,  those  minds  that  are  disposed 
to  make  this  use  of  them.  But  though  the  schoolman  appeals 
to  this  effect  of  moral  evil  as  a  justification  of  its  existence,1 


1  "  Si  enim  omnia  mala  impediren- 
tur,  multa  bona  deessent  universe  ;  non 
enim  esset  vita  leonis,  si  non  esset 
occisio  animalium  ;  nee  esset  patientia 
martyrum  si  non  esset  persecutio  tyran- 
norum." — Sum.Theol.  lm«  Q.  22.  A.  2. 


"  Multa  bona  tollerentur,  si  Deus 
nullum  malum  permitteret  esse;  non 
enim  generaretur  ignis  nisi  corrumpe- 
retur  aer ;  neque  conservaretur  vita 
leonis,  nisi  occideretur  asinus."—  Q.  48. 
A.  2. 


270  SCHOLASTIC   THEORY  [CHAP.  IX. 

such  an  argument  admits  of  the  obvious  answer,  that  it  is  not 
just  that  one  man  should  be  wicked  in  order  that  another 
should  be  good. 

The  argument  of  variety,  however,  was  put  in  another  form, 
and  another  explanation  extracted  from  it.  The  principle 
of  variety  demanded  that  there  should  be  different  natures  in 
the  universe ;  and  that,  besides  such  natures  as  were  subject 
to  necessary  laws,  there  should  be  other  nobler  ones  possess- 
ing will.  But  this  conceded,  moral  evil,  it  was  said,  followed. 
For  such  natures  as  the  latter  must,  as  the  very  condition  of 
this  higher  good,  have  the  power  of  going  wrong  and  reced- 
ing from  the  end  designed  for  them ;  and,  with  the  power  to 
do  so,  the  fact  would  in  some  instances  take  place.1  Now,  this 
is  a  substantially  different  argument  from  the  former,  and  is 
perhaps  the  nearest  approach  we  can  make  to  an  account  of 
the  existence  of  moral  evil  in  the  world.  But  it  is  in  truth 
no  explanation ;  for  is  this  will  of  the  creature  to  which 
evil  is  referred  an  original  cause  or  only  a  secondary  one  ? 
If  the  former,  this  argument  only  explains  one  difficulty  by 
another  as  great,  the  existence  of  evil  by  the  existence  of 
an  original  cause  in  nature  besides  God.  If  the  latter, 
the  existence  of  moral  evil  falls  back,  as  before,  upon  the 
First  Cause ;  the  human  will  in  that  case  being  no  such  bar- 
rier intervening  between  moral  evil  and  God,  as  is  wanted 
for  the  present  purpose. 

But  the  principal  explanation  which  was  given  of  this 
difficulty,  and  that  in  which  Aquinas  appears  finally  to 
repose,  was  borrowed  from  his  master.  Every  reader  of  S. 
Augustine  is  familiar  with  a  certain  view  of  the  nature  of 


"  Sed  in  nobilioribus  creaturis  in-    I    providentiam    tolleretur   sibi    conditio 


venitur  aliud  principium  prater  natu- 
ram,  quod  est  voluntas,  quod  quanto 
"vicinius  est  Deo,  tanto  a  necessitate  na- 
turalium  causarura  magis  est  Hberum. 
.  .  .  Et  ideo  taliter  a  Deo  instituta  est  ut 
deficere  posset.  ...  Si  autem  inevita- 
biliter  in  finem  tenderet  per  divinam 


suae   naturae."  —  In  Lomb.  1.  1.   Dist. 
39.  Q.  2.  A.  2. 

"  Perfectio  Universi  requirit  ut  sint 
quaedam  quac  a  bonitate  deficere  possint: 
ad  quod  sequitur  ea  interdiim  deficere" 
— Sum.  Theol.  lma  Q.  48.  A.  2. 


CHAP.  IX.] 


OP   NECESSITY. 


271 


evil,  to  which  he  constantly  recurs,  and  which  he  seems  to 
cherish  in  his  mind  as  a  great  moral  discovery,  a  fundamental 
set-off  and  answer  to  the  great  difficulty  of  the  existence  of 
evil,  and  the  true  and  perfect  mode  of  extricating  the  Divine 
attribute  of  Power  from  the  responsibility  of  permitting  it, 
— the  position,  viz.  that  evil  is  nothing — nihiL  God  was 
the  source;  and  as  being  the  source  of,  included  and  com- 
prised, all  existence.  Evil  was  a  departure  from  God. 
Evil,  therefore,  was  a  departure  from  existence.  External 
to  God,  it  was  outside  of  all  being  and  substance ;  L  e. 
was  no-being  or  nothing. 

Aquinas  adopts  this  position,  and  improves  upon  it  in 
his  usual  way.  Evil  was  nothing  in  another  sense  besides 
that  of. pure  negation,  which  is  the  common  meaning  of 
nothing,  viz.  that  of  privation.  Every  nature  aimed  at 
good  as  its  perfection  or  true  existence ;  evil  was  a  depriva- 
tion of  this  good  or  true  existence.  In  the  case  of  evil,  then, 
there  was  something  in  our  idea  antecedent  to  it,  of  which 
it  was  a  loss  or  absence.  That  which  every  nature  truly  and 
properly  was,  was  in  scholastic  language  its  form;  whence 
the  formal  cause  of  a  thing  is  that  which  makes  a  thing 
to  be  what  it  is.  Evil  was  a  privation  of  form.  There  was 
an  end,  and  there  was  an  action  proper  to  every  thing  in  the 
universe ;  evil  was  inordination  to  the  end,  a  defect  of  action.1 
The  evil  proper  to  the  nature  of  fire  was  cold;  the  evil  proper 
to  the  nature  of  water  was  drought.  Thus  while,  in  the  col- 
lision of  different  natures  in  the  universe,  the  defect  of  one 
was  the  growth  of  another,  the  evil  to  each  nature  was  the 


1  "  Causam  formalem  nullam  habet, 
sed  est  magis  privatio  forma  :  et  simi- 
liter  nee  causam  finalem,  sed  magis  est 
privatio  ordinis  ad  jinem." — Sum. 
Theol.  lm»  Q.  49.  A.  1. 

"  Malum  quod  in  defectu  actionis 
consistit,  semper  causatur  ex  defectu 
agentis." —  A.  2. 

Cum  omnis  natura  appetat  suum  esse 


et  suam  profectionem,  necesse  est  dicere 
quod  et  perfectio  cujuscunque  naturae 
rationem  habeat  bonitatis.  Unde  non 
potest  esse  quod  malum  signiflcet  quod- 
dam  esse,  aut  quandam  formam,  seu 
naturam.  Relinquitur  ergo  quod  no- 
mine mali  significetur  quaedam  absentia 
boni.—  lm»Q.48.  A.  1. 


272 


SCHOLASTIC   THEORY 


[CHAP.  IX. 


defect  of  that  nature.1  Everything,  so  far  as  it  ivas,  was 
good  —  omne  ens  in  quantum  hujusmodi  bonum ;  and  evil 
was  no-thing  —  non-ens,  and  no  part  of  the  universe.2 

And  that  which  was  true  of  evil  in  general,  was  true 
in  particular  of  moral  evil.  The  act  of  sin  was  defined 
as  an  act  contrary  to  the  end  for  which  the  moral  creature 
is  designed,  or,  as  is  expressed  in-  modern  language,  to  the 
constitution  of  man — actus  inordinatus ;  which  consisted, 
however,  of  two  separate  and  distinct  parts.  The  act — 
actus  peccati,  was  simply  the  material,  bodily  or  mental, 
employed  in  the  sin,  whether  outward  motion,  or  inward 
passion,  fueling,  desire;  and  this  was  real  substance  and 
part  of  the  universe  of  God.  A  man  who  committed,  for 
example,  an  act  of  intemperance  or  anger,  sinned  with  and 
by  the  natural  sensation  of  hunger  or  thirst,  or  the  natural 
passion  of  resentment,  as  the  internal  material  of  his  sin ; 
he  sinned  with  the  motion  of  his  mouth  by  which  he  eat 
or  drank,  or  with  a  motion  of  his  arm  by  which  he  struck 
a  blow,  as  its  external  material.  All  these  motions,  then, 
considered  simply  as  such,  whether  within  or  without,  were 
substantial ;  and  the  act  of  sin,  as  such,  existed.  But  the 
inordinateness  of  the  act,  or  the  sin  of  it — the  error  in 
the  use  and  application  of  these  natural  passions,  these 
bodily  organs,  was  no  thing?  As  evil  in  the  case  of  fire 
was  a  defect  of  the  natural  action  of  fire,  so  evil  in  the 
case  of  the  will  was  a  defect  of  the  natural  action  of  the 
will. 

This   position,   then,   was    applied    as    the   key   to   the 


1  "  Corruptio   aeris   et  aquae  est  ex 
perfectione  ignis.    ...     Si    sit   de- 
fectus  in   effectu    proprio   ignis,    puta 
quod    deficiat    a  calefaciendo,  hoc    est 
propter  defectum  actionis,  sed  hoc  ipsum 
quod  est  esse  deficiens,  accidit  bono  cui 
per   se   competit  agere." — lma  Q.   49. 
A.  1. 

2  Nihil  potest  esse  per  suam  essentiam 
malurn. — lma  Q.  49.  A,  3.  Malum  non 


est  pars  universi  quia  neque  habet  na- 
turam  substantial  neque  accidentis,  sed 
privationis  tantuin. — In  Lorn.  1.  1. 
Dist.  46.  Q.  1.  A.  3. 

8  "  Peccatum  est  actus  inordinatus. 
Ex  parte  igitur  actus  potest  habere  cau- 
sam, ex  parte  autem  inordinationis  ha- 
bet causam  eo  modo  quo  negatio  vel 
privatio  potest  habere  causam." — lma 
2dac  Q.  75.  A.  1. 


CHAP.  IX.]  OF   NECESSITY.  273 

solution  of  the  great  difficulty  of  the  existence  of  evil.  The 
difficulty  of  the  existence  of  evil  respected  its  cause,  how 
evil  had  an  existence  at  all,  when  the  Universal  Cause  or 
cause  of  everything,  could  not  have  given  it.  It  was  a 
direct  answer,  then,  to  this  difficulty,  to  say  that  it  was 
a  mistake  to  begin  with,  to  suppose  that  evil  had  existence. 
This  original  mistake  removed,  all  was  clear ;  for  that 
which  had  no  existence  needed  no  cause1,  and  that  which 
needed  no  cause  could  dispense  with  the  Universal  Cause. 
A  universal  cause  was  necessary ;  but  this  inconvenience 
attended  it,  viz.  that  it  was  universal,  and  thus  contracted 
responsibilities  from  which  it  had  rather  be  relieved.  This 
rationale  exactly  relieved  it  of  its  inconvenient  charge. 
Evil  was  regarded  in  an  aspect  in  which  it  ceased  to  belong 
to  the  domain  even  of  a  universal  cause.  The  fact  or 
phenomenon  of  evil,  emptied  of  true  or  logical  essence,  had 
no  place  in  the  nature  of  things ;  seen  everywhere,  it  ex- 
isted nowhere,  a  universal  nothing  attending  on  substance 
as  a  shadow,  but  no  occupant  of  room,  and  without  insertion 
in  the  system.  This  unsubstantial  presence,  this  inane  in 
the  midst  of  things,  escaped  as  such  the  action  of  the  First 
Cause ;  unsusceptible,  as  a  pure  negative,  of  connection 
or  relation,  it  was  in  its  very  nature  a  breaking  of  from 
the  chain  of  causes  and  effects  in  nature,  and  not  a  link 
of  it.2  Had  evil  a  cause,  indeed,  it  could  have  but  one, 
viz.  God ;  but  nothing  had  no  cause,  and  was,  therefore, 
wholly  independent  of  the  Universal  Cause. 

Such  an  explanation  as  this,  however,  it  is  hardly 
necessary  to  say,  is  no  real  explanation  of  the  difficulty. 
It  is  undoubtedly  the  first  truth  of  religion  that  true  being 
and  good  are  identical.  The  same  argument,  which  proves 


1  Malum   causam  formalem  nullam 
habet.— lm»  Q.  49.  A.  1. 

2  "  Effectus  causa?  mediae  secundum 
quod  exit  ordinem  causa    primze  non 


reducitur  in  causam    primam 

Defectus  a  libero  arbitrio  non  reducitur 
in  Deum  sicut  in  causam. ' —  lm' 
2dac  Q.  79.  A  1. 


274  SCHOLASTIC    THEOKY  [CHAP.  IX. 

a  First  Cause  at  all,  proves  His  goodness ;  and  if  Being  in 
the  Cause  must  be  good,  being  in  the  effect  must  be  good 
too;  for  the  effect  must  follow  the  nature  of  the  cause. 
Nor  can  we  avoid  this  conclusion  but  by  a  scheme  of 
dualism,  which  allows  an  evil  first  cause  of  being ;  and, 
therefore,  evil  being  as  its  effect.  So  far  the  above  rationale 
is  true,  and  is  the  proper  contrary  to  dualism.  But  this 
first  truth  of  sound  religion  is,  when  examined,  no  explana- 
tion of  the  mystery  of  the  existence  of  evil,  but  only 
another  mode  of  stating  it.  We  rightly  say  that  true  being 
is  identical  with  good ;  but  how  comes  there  to  be  being 
which  is  not  true  being  ?  On  the  religious  ground,  and  as 
believers  in  a  God,  we  say,  that  evil  cannot  be  an  existing 
thing  ;  because  God  is  the  Author  of  every  thing,  and  yet  not 
the  author  of  evil.  But  plain  common  sense  tells  us  clearly 
enough  that  evil  exists,  and  exists  just  as  really  as  good. 
A  man  commits  some  act  of  violence  under  the  influence 
of  strong  passion,  malignant  hatred,  revenge,  cupidity ;  his 
state  of  mind  is  as  intense  as  possible ;  there  is  the  fullest 
determination  and  absorption  in  the  act.  Is  not  this 
something  —  something  going  on  and  taking  place  in  his 
mind?  We  may  distinguish,  indeed,  between  the  animus 
and  the  material  of  the  act,  or,  in  the  scholastic  language, 
between  the  act  and  the  sin;  but  this  distinction  applies 
as  much  to  good  acts  as  to  bad.  The  virtue  of  a  good  act 
is  something  quite  distinct  from  the  feelings  and  faculties 
of  mind  and  body  employed  in  it,  of  which  it  is  the  direction. 
If  virtue,  then,  is  something,  is  not  vice  something  too  ? 

The  real  source  of  these  argumentative  struggles  and  vain 
solutions  was  the  original  position  respecting  the  Divine 
Power,  which,  however  true,  was  laid  down  without  that 
reserve  which  is  necessary  for  this  kind  of  truth.  It  is 
evident  that  the  Divine  Power  is  incomprehensible  to  us,  and 
that  therefore  we  cannot  proceed  upon  it,  as  if  it  were  a 
known  premiss,  and  argue  upon  the  vague  abstract  idea  of 
omnipotence  in  our  minds  as  if  it  were  the  real  truth  on  this 


CHAP.  IX.] 


OF    NECESSITY. 


275 


subject.  Aquinas  himself  defines  the  Divine  Power  at  the 
outset  with  a  reserve  :  it  was  the  power  of  doing  any  thing 
which  was  possible  —  omnia  possibilia  ;  and  the  principle  he 
lays  down  with  respect  to  the  sense  in  which  the  Divine 
attributes  are  to  be  understood  is  philosophical ;  viz.  that 
they  are  to  be  understood  neither  -as  wholly  the  same  with 
(univoce),  or  wholly  different  from,  the  corresponding  attri- 
butes in  man  (cequivoce),  but  as  analogous  to  them  —  analogice.1 
The  univocal  sense  confounded  God  with  the  creature ;  the 
equivocal  hid  God  from  the  creature,  removing  and  alien- 
ating Him  altogether  as  an  object  of  human  thought ;  the 
analogical  allowed  an  idea  of  God,  which  was  true  as  far  as 
it  went,  but  imperfect.  But  though  the  human  mind,  under 
scholasticism,  saw,  as  it  always  must  do  whenever  sane,  its 
own  ignorance,  it  did  not  see  it  so  clearly  or  scientifically  as 
it  has  done  subsequently,  when  a  later  philosophy  has  thrown 
it  back  upon  itself,  and  forced  it  to  examine  its  own  ideas,  how 
far  they  go,  and  where  they  stop  short.  The  mediaeval  mind 
forgot,  then,  in  the  conduct  of  the  argument,  the  principle  it 
had  laid  down  at  its  commencement ;  and,  just  as  a  boy  in 
learning  a  problem  of  Euclid  sees  some  critical  point  of  the 
demonstration,  but  does  not  see  it  sufficiently  clearly,  or  master 
it  enough  to  carry  it  with  him  throughout  the  proof,  the 
schoolman  first  saw  that  he  was  ignorant,  and  then  argued  as 
if  he  knew.  Thus,  notwithstanding  the  preliminary  reserve 
in  the  definition  of  the  Divine  Power,  the  vague  abstract  idea 
of  omnipotence  prevailed  as  if  it  were  a  known  premiss  in  the 


1  "  Tribus  modis  contingit  aliquid 
aliquibus  commune  esse,  vel  univoce, 
vel  aequivoce,  vel  analogice.  Univoce 
non  potest  aliquid  de  Deo  et  de  creatura 
dici  .  .  .  et  ideo  quidam  dicunt  quod 
quicquid  de  Deo  et  creatura  dicitur,  per 
puram  aequivocationem  dicitur.  Sed 
hoc  etiam  non  potest  esse  quia  in  his 
quae  sunt  pure  aequivoca  ex  uno  non 
agnoscitur  alterum,  ut  quando  idem 


nomen  duobus  hominibus  conveuit. 
Cum  igitur  per  scientiam  nostram 
deveniatur  in  cognitionem  Divinse  sci- 
entiae,  non  potest  esse  quod  sit  omnino 
aequivocum.  Et  ideo  dicendum  quod 
scientia  analogice  dicitur  de  Deo  et 
creatura :  et  similiter  omnia  hujus- 
modi." — Aquinas,  in  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist. 
35.  Q.  1.  A.  4. 


T    2 


276  SCHOLASTIC   THEORY  [CHAP.  IX. 

argument,  entailing  these  struggles  with  the  fact  of  evil  as 
the  consequences  of  it ;  for  with  absolute  power  in  God  to 
prevent  it,  how  could  evil  exist  ?  Hence  these  vain  efforts  of 
reason,  these  blind  explanations  ;  for  it  was  necessary  to  recon- 
cile a  known  premiss  with  facts.  As  an  unknown  premiss, 
the  Divine  Power  is  in  no  contradiction  to  the  fact  of  evil,  for 
we  must  know  what  a  truth  is  before  we  see  a  contradiction 
in  it  to  another  truth ;  and  with  no  contradiction,  no  solution 
would  have  been  wanted.  But  the  schoolman  vaguely 
fancied  that  he  knew  his  premiss,  and  therefore  involved 
himself  in  these  elaborate  and  futile  explanations.  We  may 
admire  indeed  an  obstinate  intellectual  energy,  which  strug- 
gles against  insuperable  difficulties,  and  tries  to  beat  down 
by  force  what  it  cannot  disentangle,  and  lay  down  a  path 
which  must  be  stopped  at  last.  We  admire  his  resolution, 
as  we  would  that  of  some  strong  animal  caught  in  a  net,  the 
thin  meshes  of  which  it  would  burst  any  moment  with  the 
least  part  of  that  blind  force  which  it  exerts,  were  it  not 
that  their  multiplicity  and  intricacy  baffle  it.  But  the  resig- 
nation of  the  philosopher  is  to  be  admired  more,  who  has  one 
great  difficulty  at  starting,  and  a  tranquil  path  after  it,  who 
sees  to  begin  with  the  inexplicableness  of  things,  and  is 
saved  by  the  admission  from  the  trouble  of  subsequent  solu- 
tion. The  clear  perception  by  the  mind  of  its  own  ignor- 
ance is  the  secret  of  all  true  success  in  philosophy ;  while 
explanations  which  assume  that  the  constitution  of  things 
can  really  be  explained,  can  only  be  a  fruitless  waste  of 
strength.  The  fault  of  the  schoolman  throughout  this  whole 
argument  is,  that  he  vaguely  imagines,  that  he  really  can 
explain  the  origin  of  evil ;  that  he  sets  out  with  that  aim  ; 
that  he  really  fancies  himself  in  a  line  of  discovery  while 
he  argues,  and  thinks  that  he  has  in  his  conclusion  some- 
thing of  the  nature  of  a  true  solution.  He  does  not  actually 
profess  so  much,  but  his  general  argument  betrays  the  latent 
assumption  in  his  mind.  His  fault  then  was  a  want  of  a 
clear  and  acute  perception  of  his  own  ignorance;  such  a  per- 


CHAP.  IX.]  OF   NECESSITY.  277 

ception  as  the  mind  acquires  by  the  long-sustained  stationary 
attitude  of  reflexion  upon  itself.  There  must  be  a  pause,  a 
cessation  from  active  speculation  and  inference,  from  argu- 
ment, from  words,  while  the  reason  looks  within,  and  observes 
itself.  The  passive  attitude  required  for  this  simple  act  of 
sight,  more  difficult  really  than  all  active  arguing,  requires 
a  lull  and  a  calm,  an  interruption  of  the  busy  operations  of 
the  mind,  a  voluntary  suspension  of  the  motion  of  that  whole 
machinery  of  active  thought,  which  is  generally  going  on  in 
intellectual  minds,  and  constitutes  their  normal  state.  But 
the  schoolman  was  always  busy,  always  arguing,  always  in 
the  thick  of  words,  always  constructing  upon  assumption,  and 
pushing  on  to  conclusion  after  conclusion.  He  could  not  afford 
the  time  to  stop  to  examine  fairly  a  single  assumption  on 
which  he  went.  He  had  not  the  patience  to  pause,  and  look 
within.  He  had  other  work  always  to  do,  as  he  thought  more 
important.  A  passive  attitude  was  intolerable  to  a  mind 
accustomed  exclusively  to  busy  construction;  and  thought 
internal  and  without  words  to  one,  to  whom  words  were  the 
great  machinery  by  which  he  thought.  Put  him  to  such  a 
task,  and  he  would  feel  like  a  workman  without  his  accus- 
tomed tools,  or  like  a  man  of  practical  talent  and  energy 
shut  up  in  a  dark  room  and  told  to  think.  The  consequence 
was,  that  it  was  a  chance  whether  his  assumptions  were  true 
or  false.  When  he  thought  as  a  man  and  with  mankind  at 
large,  they  were  right ;  when  he  thought  as  a  philosopher 
they  were  too  often  mistaken,  extreme  and  unqualified  when 
they  should  have  been  limited,  and  absolute  when  they 
should  have  been  with  a  condition  and  reserve. 


T    3 


278 


CHAP.  X, 

SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE   OP   PREDESTINATION. 

THE  last  chapter  explained  the  scholastic  theory  of  the 
physical  predetermination  of  the  will,  or  the  subordination  of 
the  will  to  the  universal  cause — a  philosophical  doctrine  of 
necessity.  To  this  theory  succeeded  the  proper  or  Augus- 
tiiiian  doctrine  of  predestination,  which  went  upon  the  basis 
of  original  sin.  All  mankind  being  previously  in  a  state  of 
ruin  owing  to  original  sin,  God  chose  to  exercise  His  mercy 
upon  some  of  this  whole  mass,  His  judgment  upon  others ; 
to  bring  some  to  glory,  and  others  to  punishment.  Nor  was 
this  Divine  determination  in  favour  of  one,  and  against  the 
other  portion  of  the  human  race  to  be  attributed  to  any 
foreseen  difference  of  character  between  the  two :  this  dif- 
ference of  character  being  the  effect  of  that  determination, 
instead  of  the  determination  the  effect  of  that  difference. 
On  the  principle  that  the  end  includes  the  means,  the  predes- 
tination of  the  individual  to  eternal  life  included  in  it  the 
bestowal  of  all  those  qualifications  of  virtue  and  piety  which 
were  necessary  for  his  admission  to  that  final  state.  These 
qualifications  were  therefore  the  effect,  and  not  the  cause  of 
predestination,  for  which  no  cause  was  to  be  assigned  but 
God's  sovereign  will  and  pleasure.1  Nor  had  the  creature 


1  Praescientia  meritor  um  non  est  causa 
vel  ratio  praedestinationis.  .  .  .  Mani- 
festum  est  quod  id  quod  est  gratise  est 
praedestinationis  eflfectus ;  et  hoc  non 
potest  poni  ut  ratio  praedestinationis, 
cum  hoc  sub  predestination e  conclu- 
datur.  Si  igitur  aliquid  aliud  ex  parte 


est  autem  distinctum  quod  est  ex  libero 
arbitrio  et  ex  praedestinatione,  sicut 
nee  est  distinctum  quod  est  ex  causa 
secunda  et  causa  prima. — lma  Q.  23. 
A.  5. 

Electio  Dei  qua  unum  eligit  et  alium 
reprobat    rationabilis   est,   nee    tamen 


nostra  sit  ratio  prsedestinationis,  hoc  est    j    oportet  quod  ratio  electionis  sit  meri- 
prseter  effectum  praedestinationis,     Non    |   turn ;  sed   in   ipsa   electione  ratio  est 


CHAP.  X.}  DOCTRINE    OF    PREDESTINATION. 


279 


any  ground  of  complaint  against  this  Divine  arrangement. 
For  all  deserved  eternal  punishment;  and  therefore  those  upon 
whom  the  punishment  was  inflicted  only  got  their  deserts, 
while  those  who  were  spared  received  a  favour  to  which  they 
had  in  justice  no  right,  and  were  indebted  to  a  gratuitous 
act  of  mercy,  and  an  excess  of  the  Divine  goodness.1 

The  doctrine  of  necessity,  however,  explained  in  the  last 
chapter,  and  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  are  in  sub- 
stance the  same  doctrine,  and  only  differ  in  their  ground, 
which  is  in  one  a  ground  of  philosophy,  in  the  other 
one  of  Scripture.  The  schoolmen  attached  indeed  to  these 
two  doctrines  different  functions  and  operations  of  the 
Divine  Power.  Under  the  one,  God  acted  as  universal 
mover ;  under  the  other  as  special  mover ;  under  the  one  He 
exerted  a  natural  power,  under  the  other  a  spiritual  or 
grace ;  under  the  one  He  moved  men  to  a  good  proportionate 
to  their  nature,  under  the  other  to  a  good  exceeding  the 
proportions  of  nature 2 ;  under  the  one  He  supported  the 
natural  goodness  of  man  unfallen,  under  the  other  He  healed 
man  fallen.  And  in  all  acts  in  which  the  special  power 
operated,  the  general  power  operated  too :  so  that  God  acted 


divina  bonitas:  ratio  autem  reproba- 
tionis  est  originate  peccatum. — Aquinas, 
rol.  8.  p.  330. 

1  Voluit  Deus  in  hominibus,  quantum 
ad  aliquos  quos  prsedcstinat,  suam  re- 
praesentare  bonitatem  per  modum  mi- 
sericordiae  parcendo,  et  quantum  ad 
aliquos  quos  reprobat,  per  modum  jus- 
titisepuriiendo.  .  .  Neque  tamen  propter 
hoc  est  iniquitas  apud  Deum,  si  in- 
icqualia  non  inaequalibus  prrcparat.  Hoc 
enim  esset  contra  justitiae  rationem,  si 
praedestinationis  effectus  ex  debito  red- 
deretur,  et  non  daretur  ex  gratia. 
In  his  enim  quae  ex  gratia  dantur, 
potest  aliquis  pro  libitu  suo  dare  cui 
vult  plus  vel  minus,  dummodo  nulli 
subtrahat  debitum,  absque  praejudicio 
justitisc.  Et  hoc  est  quod  dicit  pater- 
familias. Matt  20.  1 5.  "  Tolle  quod 


tuum  est  et  vade ;  an  non  licet  mini 
quod  volo  facere?" — lm»  Q.  23.  A.  5. 

2  Deus  movet  voluntatem  hominis  si- 
cut  TJniversalis  motor  ad  universale  ob- 
jectum  voluntatis,  quod  est  bonum  ;  et 
sine  hac  universal!  motione  homo  non 
potest  aliquid  velle.  .  .  .  Sed  tamen 
interdumspecialiterDeus  movet  aliquos 
ad  aliquid  determinate  volendum,  quod 
est  bonum,  sicut  in  his  quos  movet  per 
gratiam."— S,  T.  lm»  2d»e  Q.  10.  A.  6. 

Est  duplex  hominis  beatitude  ;  una 
quidem  proportionata  humanee  naturae, 
ad  quam  scilicet  homo  pervenire  potest 
per  principia  suae  naturae  :  alia  autem 
est  beatitudo  naturam  hominis  exce- 
dens,  ad  quam  homo  sola  divina  virtute 
pervenire  potest  secundum  quandam 
Divinitatis  participationem." —  lma  2d"e 
Q.  62.  A.  1 . 


T    4 


280 


SCHOLASTIC    DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X. 


in  both  capacities,  in  the  case  of  the  same  act.1  But 
thus  described  as  two  separate  and  distinct  actions,  the  uni- 
versal and  special  action  were  really  only  the  same  action, 
in  a  higher  and  lower  degree,  of  the  Divine  motive  Power 
over  the  human  will. 

Thus  clearly  and  strongly  laid  down,  however,  the  doctrine 
of  Aquinas  and  the  Augustinian  schoolmen  on  the  subject  of 
predestination  has  been  mistaken  in  a  well-known  treatise, 
which  professes  to  give  a  resume  of  the  opinions  of  the 
schools  on  this  subject.  Archbishop  Laurence  asserts  the 
predestination  maintained  by  the  schoolmen  to  be,  a  predesti- 
nation in  consequence  of  foreseen  good  works  in  the  indivi- 
dual. "  Almighty  God  before  the  foundations  of  the  world 
were  laid,  surveying  in  His  comprehensive  idea,  or,  as  they 
phrased  it,  in  His  prescience  of  simple  intelligence,  the  possi- 
bilities of  all  things,  before  He  determined  their  actual  exis- 
tence, foresaw,  if  mankind  were  created,  although  He  willed 
the  salvation  of  all,  and  was  inclined  to  all  indifferently,  yet 
that  some  would  deserve  eternal  happiness,  and  others  eternal 
misery;  and  that,  therefore,  He  approved  and  elected  the 
former,  but  disapproved  or  reprobated  the  latter.  Thus 
grounding  election  upon  foreknowledge,  they  contemplated  it 
not  as  an  arbitrary  principle,  separating  one  individual  from 
another,  under  the  influence  of  a  blind  chance,  or  an  irra- 
tional caprice ;  but  on  the  contrary,  as  a  wise  and  just  one, 
which  presupposes  a  diversity  of  nature  between  those  who  are 
accepted,  and  those  who  are  rejected.  Persuaded  that  God  is 
the  fountain  of  all  good,  that  from  His  Divine  preordination 
freely  flows  the  stream  of  grace,  which  refreshes  and  invigo- 
rates the  soul,  they  believed  that  He  has  regulated  His  pre- 


1  Homo  in  statu  naturae  integras 
potest  operari  virtute  suae  naturae  bonum 
quod  est  sibi  connaturale,  absque  super- 
additione  gratuiti  doni,  licet  non  absque 
auxilio  Dei  moventis. — lm"2dae  Q,  109. 
A.  3. 


Secundum  utrumque  statum  natura 
humana  indiget  Divino  auxilio,  ad  faci- 
endum etvolendum  quodcunque  bonum, 
sicut  primo  movente.  Virtute  gratuita 
superaddita  indiget  ad  bonum  super- 
naturale.— Ibid.  A.  2. 


CHAP.  X.]  OF   PREDESTINATION.  281 

determination  by  the  quality  of  the  soil  through  which  His 
grace  passes,  and  the  effects  which  in  any  case  it  produces, 
not  restricting  His  favours,  but  distributing  them  with  an 
impartial  hand;  equally  disposed  toward  all  men,  but,  be- 
cause all  are  not  equally  disposed  toward  Him,  distinguish- 
ing only  such  as  prove  deserving  of  His  bounty  .... 
They  considered  the  dignity  of  the  individual  as  the  merito- 
rious basis  of  predestination ."  1 

The  first  remark  that  this  passage  suggests,  is  that  the 
writer  confuses  sill  the  schoolmen  together,  and  attributes  one 
common  opinion  to  them  on  this  subject ;  whereas  there  were 
different  schools  amongst  them,  as  among  modern  thinkers, 
some  taking  the  predestinarian  side,  and  others  that  of  free- 
will ;  though  the  great  names  are  chiefly  on  the  former  side. 
The  writer,  however,  treats  them  all  as  one  school,  and  con- 
siders the  predestination  taught  by  the  Augustinian  Aquinas 
to  be  of  the  kind  which  he  here  describes ;  z.  e.  a  predesti- 
nation on  the  ground  of  foreseen  good  life.  Of  course  if  this 
is  so,  this  is  all  the  difference  between  predestinarianism  and 
the  doctrine  of  freewill.  But  I  cannot  understand  how  he 
can  put  this  interpretation  upon  the  doctrine  of  Aquinas, 
when  the  latter  plainly  and  expressly  asserts  the  contrary ; 
viz.,  that  foreseen  merits  are  not  the  cause  of  predestination, 
— prascientia  meritorum  non  est  causa  velratiopredestinationis, 
but  predestination  the  cause  of  these  foreseen  merits ;  these 
merits  being  the  effect  of  grace,  and  grace  the  effect  of  pre- 
destination ;  —  id  quod  est  gratice  est  prcedestinationis  effectus. 
Archbishop  Laurence  appears  to  have  been  misled  by  two 
classes  of  expressions  in  Aquinas,  one  relating  to  contingency, 
the  other,  to  human  blame  and  responsibility. 

He  refers  in  support  of  this  interpretation  of  the  doctrine 
of  Aquinas,  to  the  latter's  assertion  of  contingency.  "  The 
mistakes  upon  this  subject  of  those  who  have  but  partially 


1  Laurence's  Bainpton  Lectures,  pp,  148.  152. 


282  SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  X. 

consulted  the  speculations  of  the  schools  (he  is  speaking  of 
those  who  have  interpreted  these  speculations  in  a  predesti- 
narian  sense)  seem  to  have  arisen  from  the  want  of  properly 
comprehending  what  was  meant  by  the  effect  of  predestina- 
tion, an  effect  always  supposed  to  be  contingent ;  the  opera- 
tions of  freewill,  whether  with  or  without  grace,  being 
considered  only  as  foreknown,  and  not  necessarily  predeter- 
mined." *  And  he  quotes  a  passage  relating  to  contingent 
causes,  as  distinguished  from  necessary  ones  — (f  Although 
all  things  are  subject  matter  of  Providence,  all  things  do 
not  take  place  necessarily,  but  according  to  the  condition 
of  their  proximate  causes, — secundum  conditionem  causarum 
proximarum  2,"  which  are  in  some  cases  not  necessary  but 
contingent  causes.  Archbishop  Laurence  understands  this 
assertion  of  contingency  as  a  denial  of  the  doctrine  of 
necessity,  and  an  assertion  of  the  received  doctrine  of 
freewill.  But  the  system  of  Aquinas,  as  explained  in  the 
last  chapter,  does  not  verify  such  an  inference  from  his 
use  of  the  term  contingent.  Aquinas  divides  proximate 
or  mediate  or  secondary  causes  into  two  classes,  necessary 
and  contingent ;  but  the  contingent  causes  are  still  mediate 
causes  only,  not  original  ones.  They  are  as  in  complete 
subordination  to  the  first  cause,  as  necessary  causes  are ; 
only  differing  from  the  latter  in  their  manner  of  operation, 
which  is  variable  and  irregular,  instead  of  fixed  and  uniform. 
And  the  human  will,  as  a  contingent  cause,  is  no  more 
than  a  mediate  one.  God  is  cause  of  the  will  —  ipse  actus 
liberi  arbitrii  reducitur  in  Deum  sicut  in  causam.  Contin- 
gency then  in  acts  is  not,  according  to  the  doctrine  of 
Aquinas,  opposed  to  their  ultimate  causation  from  without ; 
which  is  the  doctrine  of  necessity :  contingency  is  a  certain 
mode  in  which  things  take  place;  and  volition  is  such  a 


Bampton  Lectures,  p.  152.  i        3  Aquinas  in  Lomb.    1.  1.  Disk  40. 

!    Q.  3.  A.  1.;  Bampton  Lectures,  p.  354. 


CHAP.  X.]  OF    PREDESTINATION.  283 

mode  in  the  case  of  actions ;  but  volition  is  a  mode,  and  not 
the  cause,  in  the  sense  of  original  cause,  of  them. 

There  is  another  set  of  expressions  in  the  Augustinian 
schoolmen  relating  to  human  blame  and  responsibility,  to 
which  Archbishop  Laurence  refers.  "  To  the  inquiry  why 
some  are  unendowed  with  grace,  their  answer  was,  because 
some  are  not  willing  to  receive  it,  and  not  because  God  is 
unwilling  to  give  it ;  He,  they  said,  offers  His  light  to  all : 
He  is  absent  from  none,  but  man  absents  himself  from  the 
present  Deity,  like  one  who  shuts  his  eyes  against  the  noon- 
day blaze."  l  The  language  he  refers  to  is  that  of  Aquinas, 
whom  again  he  quotes  as  saying  that  there  are  two  reasons 
why  grace,  where  it  is  withheld,  is  withheld ;  one  because 
the  man  is  not  willing  to  receive  it,  the  other  because  God 
does  not  will  to  give  it ;  of  which  two  the  latter  is  posterior 
in  order  to  the  former  —  tails  est  ordo  ut  secundum  non  sit  nisi 
ex  suppositione  primi.2  Understanding  the  want  of  desire 
for  grace,  referred  to  here,  to  be  the  opposition  of  the 
individual's  free  and  self-determining  will,  he  takes  these 
expressions  as  involving  the  common  doctrine  of  freewill, 
that  God  offers  His  grace  to  all,  while  man  rejects  or  accepts 
it  according  to  his  own  choice.  But  the  fault  in  the  human 
agent  here  referred  to  is  not  one  to  be  confounded  with  the 
fault  of  individual  choice :  it  is  the  original  fault  of  the 
whole  race.  All  mankind  are  to  begin  with,  according  to 
the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  disinclined  to  grace,  and,  so  far 
as  themselves  are  concerned,  reject  it.  Aquinas  then  can 
assert  that  the  reason  why  grace  is  withheld  is  man's  own 
fault,  without  committing  himself  in  saying  so  to  the 
common  doctrine  of  freewill.  It  is  the  old  position  which 
meets  us  in  S.  Augustine.  The  will  of  man  is  naturally 
a  corrupt  and  faulty  will,  but  it  is  so  at  the  same  time 
necessarily,  and  as  the  effect  of  original  sin.  Eesponsibility 


1  Bampton  Lectures,  p.  151.  2  Aquinas  in  Lomb.  1.  1.    Dist.  40. 

Q.  4.  A.  2. 


284 


SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X. 


attaches  to  it  as  being  will;  the  voluntary  agent  is  as  such 
susceptible  of  praise  or  blame  —  ut  ei  imputetur  aliquid  ad 
culpam  vel  ad  meritum  l ; —  and  legitimately  comes  under  a 
dispensation  of  rewards  and  punishments.  Such  is  the  sense 
in  which  man's  fault  is  said  by  Aquinas  to  be  the  first  cause 
why  grace,  where  it  is  withheld,  is  withheld.  It  is  the  faulty 
will  of  the  race,  not  the  mere  choice  of  the  person,  which  is 
this  cause ;  which  faultiness  is  therefore  consistent  with  ne- 
cessity, and  not  opposed  to  it.  It  is  a  further  test  of  such  a 
sense,  that  the  will  thus  represented  as  the  original  barrier 
against  grace,  is  next  represented  as  wholly  able  to  be  changed 
and  made  a  different  will,  by  grace.  "  God  is  able  when,  where, 
and  in  whomever  He  pleases,  to  convert  men's  evil  wills  from 
evil  to  good."  2  It  follows  that  when  man's  will  is  changed 
from  evil  to  good,  it  is  by  His  irresistible  power;  and 
therefore  that  the  admission  into  a  state  of  grace  takes  place, 
according  to  this  system,  on  a  ground  quite  different  from 
that  on  which  Archbishop  Laurence  considers  it  to  do,  upon 
his  too  hasty  and  superficial  interpretation  of  the  scholastic 
language.  Indeed,  if  none  are  to  be  considered  necessi- 
tarians who  make  man  a  responsible  being,  and  lay  his 
sins  and  their  consequences  at  his  own  door,  there  cannot 
be  a  Christian  necessitarian ;  for  we  must  either  do  this, 
or  charge  God  with  them — which  latter  no  Christian  can  do. 
The  most  rigid  predestinarian  writers  impose  this  responsi- 
bility upon  man.3 


1  S.  T.  1™  Q.  22.  A.  2. 

8  "  Quis  tarn  impie  desipiat,  ut  dicat 
Deum  malas  hominum  voluntates  quas 
voluerit,  et  quando  voluerit  et  ubi 
voluerit  in  bonum  non  posse  conver- 
tere." — Augustine,  quoted  by  Lombard, 
1.  1.  Dist.  47.  Neque  ideo  prsecepit 
omnibus  bona,  quia  vellet  ab  omnibus 
bona  fieri,  si  enim  vellet  utiqtie  fierent. " 
—Ibid. 

3  Arcbbp.  Laurence's  use  of  the  fol- 
lowing statement  in  Aquinas  (B.  L.  p. 
151.)  shows  the  same  want  of  insight  into 


his  system,  and  the  same  contented 
resting  on  the  apparent  meaning  of 
particular  language,  without  any  con- 
sciousness of  a  different  interpretation, 
which  in  a  vast  and  intricate  theolo- 
gical fabric  might  be  reflected  from 
other  quarters  upon  it.  "  Dicendum 
quod  electio  divina  non  praeexigit  diver- 
sitatem  gratiac,  quia  haec  electionem 
consequitur ;  sed  praeexigit  diversitatem 
naturae  in  divina  cognitione,  et  facit 
diversitatem  gratiac,  sicut  dispositio 
diversitatem  naturae  facit." — In  Lomb. 


CHAP.  X.] 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


285 


To  the  doctrine  of  predestination  thus  laid  down  by 
Aquinas  succeeded  a  corresponding  doctrine  of  grace. 
If  eternal  happiness  is  ensured  to  the  individual  by  a  Divine 
decree,  the  means  to  it,  i.e.  a  good  life,  must  be  ensured  also ; 
and  this  can  only  be  ensured  by  the  operation  of  a  Divine 
grace  or  influence  upon  him,  the  effect  of  which  is  not  depen- 
dent on  his  own  will,  but  is  necessary.  Aquinas  accordingly 
proceeds  to  lay  down  the  doctrine  of  effective  or  irresistible 
grace. 

And  first  it  must  be  observed  that,  without  appending  the 


1.  1.  Dist.  41.  Q.  1.  A.  2.  He  infers 
from  this  that  election  is  asserted 
by  Aquinas  to  be  on  the  ground  of 
foreseen  merits  in  the  individual,  —  a 
diversitas  natures  in  the  good  man 
from  that  of  the  bad  man.  But  this 
very  statement  says  that  this  diversitas 
naturae  is  the  effect  of  a  divine  arrange- 
ment or  disposing  —  dispositio  diversi- 
tatem  nature  facit.  And  when  we  turn 
to  the  part  of  Aquinas'  system  which 
relates  to  grace,  we  find  that  a  certain 
Divine  preparation  of  the  man,  while 
in  a  state  of  nature  and  previous  to  a 
state  of  grace,  is  necessary  as  a  pre- 
paration for  grace — proeparatio  volun- 
tat'is  humanas  ad  consequendum  ipsum 
gratia  habitualis  donum  —  auxilium 
gratuitum  Dei  interius  animam  mo- 
ventis.—  lma  2dae  Q.  109.  A.  6.  Gratise 
causa  non  potest  esse  actus  humanus 
per  modum  meriti,  sed  diapositio  natu- 
ralis  quacdam  in  quantum  per  actus 
prasparamur  ad  gratia)  susceptionem. — 
Aquinas,  vol.  viii.  De  Prsed.  This  is, 
then,  the  dispositio  naturae  here  referred 
to,  which  is  a  Divine  moulding  of  the 
natural  man  to  fit  him  for  grace.  The 
statement,  again,  on  which  Archbp. 
Laurence  relies  —  Dicendum  quod 
quamvis  Deus,  quantum  in  se  est, 
sequaliter  se  habeat  ad  omnes,  non 
tamen  sequaliter  se  habeant  omnes 
ad  ipsum,  et  ideo  non  ajqualiter  om- 
nibus gratia  praeparatur  (in  Lomb.  1.  i. 
Dist.  40.  Q.  2.  A,  2.) — cannot  be  reposed 
in  against  a  whole  interpretative  force 
of  the  system  explaining  it  the  other 
way.  In  the  first  stage  of  original  sin 
all  men  do  cequaliter  se  habentad  Deum  : 
but  God  lifts  some  out  of  this  state, 
and  others  not,  previously,  as  we  have 
just  seen,  to  conferring  actual  grace  upon 


them.  In  this  intermediate  stage,  then, 
all  men  do  not  osqualiter  se  habent  ad 
Deum,  but  some  are  and  some  are  not  in 
a  preparatory  state  for  grace:  but  this 
difference  is  the  result  of  the  Divine  will. 

Archbp.  Laurence  relies  on  Calvin's 
dissatisfaction  with  Aquinas,  but  the 
instance  to  which  he  refers  is  no  case 
of  substantial  disagreement  between 
the  two,  but  only  of  a  difference  be- 
tween a  more  subtle  and  a  broader 
mode  of  statement.  Calvin  censures 
the  refinement  or  quibble  —  argutia,  of 
Aquinas  in  saying  that  foreseen  human 
merit,  though  not  the  cause  of  predes- 
tination on  God's  part,  may  be  called 
the  cause  of  it  in  a  certain  way — quo- 
dammodo — on  man's  part ;  because  God, 
having  predestinated  men  to  goodness, 
predestinates  them  to  glory  because 
they  are  good.  Such  a  statement  makes 
no  difference  in  the  doctrine  of  predes- 
tination as  a  whole ;  because  though 
one  part  of  it  is  regarded  as  de- 
pendent on  another,  the  whole  is  made 
to  depend  on  the  Divine  will  solely. 
But  Calvin  dislikes  the  subtlety  as  in- 
terfering with  the  breadth  of  the  doc- 
trine :  "  Ac  ne  illam  quidem  Thomse 
argutiam  moramur,  prsescientiam  meri- 
torum  non  ex  parte  quidem  actus  prse- 
destinatis  esse  praedestinationis  causam; 
ex  parte  autem  nostra,  quodammodo  sic 
vocari  posse,  nempe  secundum  particu- 
larem  praedestinationis  aestimationem  ;ut 
quum  dicitur  Deus  prsedestinare  homini 
gloriam  ex  meritis,  quia  gratiam  ei  lar- 
giri  decrevit  qua  gloriam  mereatur." — 
Instit.  1.  3.  c.  22.  s.  9. 

Between  the  Augustinian  and  Thomist 
doctrine  of  predestination,  and  that  of 
Calvin,  I  can  see  no  substantial  differ- 
ence. NOTE  XXI. 


286 


SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X. 


term  efficacious,  the  use  of  which  was  introduced  by  the  later 
Thomists,  grace  of  itself  bears  in  Aquinas  the  sense  of 
efficaciousj  i.  e.  means  something,  which  simply  by  the  fact 
of  its  being  given  us  by  God,  and  of  the  man  himself  having 
it,  has  the  effect  of  making  the  man  good  and  acceptable 
to  God.  The  leaning  to  the  side  of  freewill  which  has 
marked  church  authority  for  the'  last  three  centuries,  has 
impressed  for  the  most  part  upon  the  term  grace  the  sense 
of  assisting  grace ;  i.  e.  a  Divine  influence  which  excites, 
prompts,  suggests,  and  encourages,  but  which  depends  on 
the  human  will  for  its  proper  and  intended  effect,  and  does 
not  issue  in  any  good  act  or  good  and  acceptable  state  of 
mind,  unless  the  will  has  by  an  original  movement  of  its  own 
converted  it  to  use.  And  this  is  perhaps  the  sense  in  which 
grace  is  more  generally  and  popularly  understood  at  the 
present  day.  But  the  Augustinian  schoolmen,  following 
their  master,  do  not  mean  by  grace  such  an  influence  as  this, 
but  a  different  one ;  one  which,  when  received,  produces  of 
itself  its  designed  effect — an  acceptable  and  justifying  state 
of  the  soul.  They  divide  grace  into  two  great  kinds,  one 
which  is  designed  for  the  good  of  the  individual,  and  makes 
him  acceptable  to  God,  —  gratia  gratum  faciens  ;  the  other, 
which  is  not  the  grace  of  acceptableness,  but  only  some  gift 
or  power  with  which  the  individual  is  endowed  for  the 
benefit  of  the  church,  — gratia  gratis  data.1  The  former  grace 
becomes  when  imparted  a  quality  of  the  soul,  a  certain 


1  Duplex  est  gratia,  una  quidam  per 
quam  ipse  homo  Deo  conjungitur,  quae 
vocatur  gratia  gratum  faciens  ;  alia  vero 
per  quam  unus  homo  cooperatur  alter! 
ad  hoc  quod  ad  Deum  reducatur ;  hujus- 
modi  autem  donum  vocatur  gratia 
gratis  data;  quia  supra  facultatem  na- 
turae, et  supra  meritum  personae  homini 
conceditur.  Sed  quia  non  datur  ad  hoc 
ut  homo  ipse  per  earn  justificetur,  sed 
potius  ut  ad  justificationem  alterius  co- 
operetur,  ideo  non  vocatur  gratum 
faciens.  Et  de  hac  dicit  Apostolus  1. 
ad  Cor.  12.  7.  Unicuique  datur  ma- 
nifestatio  spiritus  ad  utilitatem,  scilicet, 
aliorum. 


Gratia  autem  gratum  faciens  ordinat 
hominem  immediate  ad  conjunction  em 
ultimi  tinis  ;  gratiae  autem  gratis  data? 
ordinant  hominem  ad  qua&dam  prsepa- 
ratoria  finis  ultimi,  sicut  per  prophetiam 
et  miracula.  Et  ideo  gratia  gratum 
faciens  est  multoexcellentior  quam  gratia 
gratis  data. — lm»  2dae  Q.  iii.  A.  1.  5. 

Gratia  habitus  gratus  a  Deo —  causa 
efficiens  meriti.  .  .  .  Virtutes  theolo- 
gicae  et  supernaturales,  non  sunt  minus 
efficaces  similium  actuum  quam  vir- 
tutes  morales. — Bradwardine,  p.  364. 
et  seq. 


CHAP.  X.] 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


287 


graciousness  and  goodness  belonging  to  it,  as  beauty  belongs 
to  the  body  —  nitor  animce.1 

The  question  then  is  how  this  grace  is  obtained  in  the 
first  place,  and  how  in  the  next  place  it  is  sustained  and 
preserved.  Is  it  obtained  by  any  merit  of  the  individual  in 
the  first  place,  i.  e.  is  it  the  reward  of  any  original  exertion 
of  the  will  ?  Or,  if  not  obtained  in  this  way,  is  it  preserved 
in  this  way,  i.  e.  by  the  freewill  of  the  individual  sustaining 
and  guarding  it  ?  In  either  of  these  cases  such  a  grace  as 
this  involves  no  doctrine  of  efficacious  and  irresistible  grace ; 
because  in  the  former  case  it  is  a  state  of  the  mind  which  the 
will  has  in  part  earned ;  in  the  latter  it  is  one,  which,  though 
the  individual  is  endowed  with  it,  by  an  act  of  God,  as 
Adam  according  to  the  authorized  doctrine  was  with  a  cer- 
tain good  disposition  at  his  creation ;  the  individual  has  to 
maintain,  as  Adam  had,  by  his  own  freewill.  But  if  this 
grace  is  neither  obtained  nor  preserved  by  the  freewill  of  the 
individual,  but  is  given  in  the  first  instance  as  a  free  gift  of 
God,  and  sustained  afterwards  by  the  supporting  power  of 
God,  exerted  gratuitously  and  arbitrarily ;  it  then  involves 
the  doctrine  of  efficacious  grace;  for  there  is  no  room  at 
either  end  for  any  original  motion  of  the  will,  upon  which 
the  possession  of  such  grace  depends. 

But  the  latter  is,  according  to  the  Thomist  doctrine,  the 
mode  in  which  this  grace  is  obtained  and  preserved.  First, 
the  primary  possession  of  this  grace  is  not  owing,  in  whole 
or  in  part,  to  any  merit  or  original  act  of  will  in  the  indivi- 
dual. It  was  laid  down  that  to  a  man  who  prepared*  himself 
as  much  as  possible  for  grace,  grace  was  still  not  necessarily 
given ;  — non  necessario  data  se  prceparanti  ad  gratiam  et 
facienti  quod  in  se  est?  But  if  a  man's  best  possible  prepa- 


1  Gratia  est  nitor  animse  sanctum 
concilians  amorem. — lms  2a"e  Q.  110. 
A.  2. 

8  Homo  comparatur  ad  Deum  sicut 
lutum  ad  flgulum,  secundum  illud 
Jer.  18.  6.  Sicut  lutum  in  manu  figuli 


sic  vos  in  matin  mea.  Sed  lutum  non 
ex  necessitate  accipit  formam  a  figulo, 
quantumcunque  sit  praeparatum.  Ergo 
neque  homo  recipit  ex  necessitate  prra- 
tiam  a  Deo,  quantumcunque  se  prze- 
paret. —  lma  2dae  Q.  1 12.  A.  3. 


288 


SCHOLASTIC    DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X. 


ration  of  himself  for  it  was  no  claim  in  the  eye  of  God  to  it, 
the  bestowal  of  it  evidently  did  not  depend  upon  any  thing 
in  a  man  himself,  but  proceeded  upon  a  different  law.  And 
when  we  are  let  into  the  real  meaning  of  this  position,  the 
same  conclusion  is  still  more  clear.  For  when  this  position 
comes  to  be  explained,  as  it  is  further  on  in  the  argument,  it 
turns  out  to  be  only  another  form  of  the  position  that  nobody 
can  prepare  himself,  either  in  whole  or  in  part,  for  grace,  i.  e. 
have  any  original  share  in  this  work.  The  preparation  of  the 
human  heart  for  the  reception  of  grace  was  a  Divine  work, 
in  which  God  was  the  mover,  and  the  human  will  the  thing 
moved. 

The  distinction  indeed  of  operating  and  co-operating  grace, 
gratia  operans  et  cooperans,  appears  at  first  sight  to  imply 
an  original  act  of  the  will,  with  which  Divine  grace  co-ope- 
rates, and  which  is  co-ordinate  with  that  grace.  But  as 
explained,  it  carries  no  such  meaning  with  it,  and  issues  in  a 
verbal  subtlety.  Two  acts  are  attributed  to  the  will,  one  in- 
terior, the  other  exterior,  the  one  being  the  substance  of  the 
act,  the  other  its  manifestation ;  the  one  the  real  moral  act 
itself,  the  other  that  act  as  expressed  in  outward  form.  Of 
these  two  acts  then,  the  former  is  attributed  to  Divine  grace 
alone, — gratia  operans,  the  human  will  not  co-operating  with 
it,  but  being  simply  moved  by  it.  The  latter  is  allowed  to 
co-operate  with  Divine  grace.  But  this  is  no  independent 
but  a  wholly  moved  and  dictated  co-operation.  The  will 
having  being  wholly  moved  to  action  by  grace,  that  action 
is  then  called  a  co-operation  with  grace.1 


1  "  In  illo  effectu  in  quo  mens  nostra 
et  movet  et  movetur,  operatic  non  solum 
attribuitur  Deo  sed  etiam  animae;  et 
secundum  hoc  dicitur  gratia  cooperans. 
Est  autem  in  nobis  duplex  actus  ;  primus 
quidem  interior  voluntatis ;  et  quantum 
ad  istum  actum  voluntas  se  habct  ut 
mota  ;  Deus  autem  ut  movens  ;  et  prae- 
sertim  cum  voluntas  incipit  bonum 


velle,  qua?  prius  malum  volebat ;  et  ideo 
secundum  quod  Deus  movet  humanavn 
mentem  ad  hunc  actum,  dicitur  gratia 
operans.  Alius  autem  est  actus  exterior, 
qui  cum  a  voluntate  imperetur,  consequens 
est  quod  ad  hunc  actum  operatlo  attri- 
buatur  voluntati.  Et  .  .  .  respectu  hu- 
jusmodi  actus  dicitur  gratia  cooperans." 
—  lm»  2d«  Q.  iii.  A.  2. 


CHAP.  X.] 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


289 


The  bestowal  of  justifying  grace,  then,  does  not,  in  the 
system  of  Aquinas,  depend  in  the  first  instance  upon  any 
act  of  man's  will;  nor  does  its  continuance  depend  on  it 
either.  The  continuance  of  this  grace  depends  on  the  gift 
of  perseverance,  which  is  a  gratuitous  gift  of  God,  given  to 
whom,  and  withheld  from  whom  He  will l ;  and  to  which  no 
life  and  conduct  of  man  can  afford  any  claim.  Suppose  a 
person  in  a  good  present  state  of  mind,  leading  a  good  life, 
and  therefore,  for  the  time  being,  in  a  state  of  acceptance  ; 
the  question  is,  upon  what  law  does  this  state  of  things  last  ? 
Does  its  permanence  depend  on  the  individual's  own  original 
will,  which  performing  its  part  in  the  guard  and  maintenance 
of  this  state,  God  performs  His,  and  supplies  the  complement? 
Not,  according  to  Aquinas.  The  continuance  of  this  state 
of  things  is,  from  moment  to  moment,  a  gratuitous  act  of 
God's  sustaining  power,  who  keeps  up  this  moral  and  spiri- 
tual fabric,  as  He  does  that  of  the  material  world,  so  long  as 
it  suits  His  sovereign  pleasure,  and  no  longer.  The  creature 
cannot  conditionate  this  Will  Supreme,  or  impose  any  obliga- 
tion in  justice  upon  it,  in  this  matter.  Thus,  guarded  at  both 
ends  from  dependence  on  the  human  will,  given  as  the  free  gift 
of  God  in  the  first  instance,  and  sustained  by  His  absolute 
power  afterwards,  justifying  grace — gratia  gratum  faciem, 
was  effective  or  irresistible  grace. 

So  far,  however,  the  Thomist  doctrine  of  grace  was  only 
the  Augustinian  doctrine,  which  was  a  perfectly  simple  one, 


1  "  Homo  etiam  in  gratia  constitutus 
indiget  ut  ei  perseverantia  a  Deo  detur. 
.  .  .  Postquam  aliquis  est  justificatus 
per  gratiam,  necesse  habet  a  Deopetere 
perse verantiae  donum  ;  ut  scilicet  cus- 
todiatur  a  malo  usque  ad  finem  vitae. 
Multis  enim  datur  gratia  quibus  non 
datur  perse verare  in  gratia." —  lmft  2d»e 
Q.  110.  A.  10. 

"Omne  quod  quis  meretur  a  Deo  con- 
sequitur,  nisi  impediatur  per  peccatum. 
Sed  multi  habent  opera  meritoria,  qui 
non  consequuntur  perseverantiam  j  nee 


potest  dici  quod  hoc  fiat  propter  impedi- 
mentum  peccati,  quia  hoc  ipsura  quod 
est  peccare,  opponitur  perseverantiae ; 
ita  quod  si  aliquis  perseverantiam  me- 
reretur,  Deus  non  permitteret  ilium 
cadere  in  peccatum.  Non  igitur  per- 
severantia cadit  sub  merito.  .  .  .  Per- 
severantia vise  non  cadit  sub  merito, 
quia  dependet  solum  ex  motione  divina, 
quae  est  principium  omnis  meriti.  Sed 
Deus  gratis  perseverantice  bonum  lar- 
gitur  cuicunque  illud  largitur." — lm* 
2'3»e  Q.  114.  A.  9. 


U 


290 


SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X. 


regarding  the  operation  of  grace  as  the  action  on  each  suc- 
cessive occasion  of  Divine  power;  upon  which  action  the 
effect  of  goodness  in  the  soul  followed,  and  upon  its  cessation 
or  interruption  ceased.  But  the  schoolmen  added  to  this 
doctrine  a  distinction,  which,  though  founded  in  reason  and 
nature,  ended,  in  their  hands,  in  greatly  burdening  and  per- 
plexing it.  Aristotle  had  laid  down  the  very  natural  position, 
that  what  constituted  a  man  good,  was  not  the  good  act  on 
the  particular  occasion,  but  a  habit  of  mind :  this  habit  was 
productive,  indeed,  of  acts,  and  defined  as  such ;  but  still  it 
was  from  having  this  source  of  acts  in  his  mind,  that  a  man 
was  good,  rather  than  from  the  acts  considered  in  themselves. 
As  grace  was  concerned,  then,  with  the  production  of 
goodness,  the  schoolmen,  incorporating  the  Aristotelian  doc- 
trine of  habits  with  the  doctrine  of  grace,  maintained  that 
God  imparted  goodness  in  the  shape  of  habit ;  and  the  result 
was,  the  distinction  between  habitual  and  actual  grace — 
gratia  habitualis  et  actualis1 ; — a  distinction  which,  in  their 
mode  of  carrying  it  out,  produced  such  a  labyrinth  of  com- 
partments and  network  of  verbal  subtleties,  that  it  requires 
some  patience  in  a  reader  to  extricate  any  meaning  at  all 
from  such  confusion,  or  arrive  at  the  substance  and  kernel 
of  the  system,  amidst  such  obstructions. 

Aquinas  then  commences  with  laying  down,  in  general 
terms,  the  doctrine  of  infused  habits, —  a  doctrine  which,  as  I 
have  explained  in  a  preceding  chapter,  is  in  itself  a  natural 


1  "  Homo  ad  recte  vivendum  duplici- 
tur  auxilio  Dei  indiget :  uno  quidern 
modo  quantum  ad  aliquod  habituale  do- 
num,  per  quod  natura  humana  corrupta 
sanetur,  et  etiam  sanata  elevetur  ad 
operanda  opera  meritoria  vitsc  aeternas, 
quae  excedunt  proportionem  naturae : 
alio  modo  indiget  homo  auxilio  gratiae, 
ut  a  Deo  moveatur  ad  agendum  .  .  .  et 
hoc  propter  duo ;  primo  quidem  ra- 
tione  generali,  propter  hoc  quod  nulla 
res  creata  potest  in  quemcunque  actum 
prodire,  nisi  virtute  motionis  divinae  : 


secundo  ratione  speciali  propter  condi- 
tionem  status  humanae  naturae ;  quae 
quidem  licet  per  gratiam  sanetur  quan- 
tum ad  mentem,  remanet  tamen  in  eo 
corruptio  et  infectio  quantum  ad  car- 
nem  .  .  .  et  ideo  necesse  est  nobis  ut 
a  Deo  dirigamur  et  protegamur,  quia 
omnia  movet  et  omnia  potest.  .  .  .  Do- 
num  habitualis  gratia  non  ad  hoc  datur 
nobis  ut  per  ipsum  non  indige.amus 
ulterius  divino  auxilio." — lma  2d*e  Q. 
110.  A.  9. 


CHAP.  X.] 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


291 


one,  and  agreeable  to  our  experience.  He  asserts  in  the 
first  place,  that  there  are  such  things  as  natural  habits  l}  or 
dispositions,  moral  and  intellectual,  which  are  born  with 
men ;  though  he  artificially  limits  the  former  to  such  as  are 
evidently  connected  with  the  bodily  temperament,  such  as 
temperance.  And  upon  this  foundation  of  natural  truth,  he 
proceeds  to  erect  another,  and  a  more  important  class  of  in- 
fused habits,  connected  with  grace. 

Besides  habits  infused  by  nature,  then,  there  were  habits 
"  infused  by  God ;  "  which  differed  from  the  natural  virtues 
in  this,  that  they  were  designed  for  the  spiritual  good  of  man, 
as  the  former  were  for  his  temporal  and  worldly.  These 
were  certain  imparted  holy  dispositions,  or  spiritual  virtues, 
produced  in  the  soul  without  any  efforts  of  its  own  —  quas 
Deus  in  nobis  sine  nobis  operatur.2  First  in  order,  came  the 
Theological  virtues, —  Faith,  Hope,  and  Charity.  Then  came 
the  gifts  —  Dona  ;  which  were  seven  in  number, —  Wisdom, 
Understanding,  Knowledge,  Counsel,  Piety,  Fortitude,  and 
Fear.  But,  besides  these,  were  also  infused  moral  virtues  — 
virtutes  morales  infusce ;  which  were  the  same  in  matter  with 
natural  or  acquired  virtues,  but  differed  in  the  end  or  motive, 
which  was  a  spiritual  one,  while  thd!t  of  the  former  was  na- 
tural. The  acquired,  and  the  infused,  virtue  of  temperance, 
for  example,  were  both  expressed  by  the  same  acts ; 


1  "  Sunt  in  hominibus  aliqui  habitus 
naturales,   ...  In    appetitivis    autem 
potentiis  non  est  aliquis  habitus  natu- 
ralis  secundum  inchoationetn  ex  parte 
ipsius  animae.  .  .  .  Sed  ex  parte  cor- 
poris  .   .  .  sunt  enim  quidam  dispositi 
ex  propria  corporis  complexione  ad  cas- 
titatem    vel    mansuetudinem,   vel    ad 
aliquid  hujusmodi." — lmft  2d»e   Q.    51. 
A.  1. 

2  "  Habitus  homini  a  Deo  infundun- 
tur.  .  .  .  Ratio  cst  quia  aliqui  habitus 
sunt  quibus  homo  bene  disponitur  ad 
finem  excedentem  facultatem  humanae 
naturae,  .   .  .  et  quia  habitus   oportet 
esse   proportionatos  ei   ad  quod   homo 
disponitur  secundum  ipsos,  ideo  necesse 


est  quod  etiam  habitus  ad  hujusmodi 
finem  disponentes,  excedant  facultatem 
humanas  natura?.  Unde  tales  habitus 
nunquam  possunt  homini  inesse,  nisi  ex 
infusione  divina." — Though  God  is  also 
able  to  infuse  common  habits,  such  as 
are'ordinarily  acquired  by  acts. — "  Deus 
potest  producere  effectus  causarum  se- 
cundarum  absque  ipsis  causis  secundis. 
.  .  .  Sicut  igitur  quandoque  ad  osten- 
sionem  sua?  virtutis  producit  sanitatem 
absque  causa  natnrali ;  quse  tamen  per 
naturam  posset  causari ;  ita  etiam  quan- 
doque infundit  homini  illos  habitus  qui 
naturali  virtute  possunt  causari." —  lm» 
2dae  Q.  52.  A,  4. 


U    2 


292  SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  X. 

but  the  one  aimed  at  bodily  health,  or  an  undisturbed  exer- 
tion of  the  intellectual  faculties,  the  other  at  spiritual 
discipline. 

Now,  so  far  as  the  schoolman  in  this  scheme  simply  asserts 
that  God  can,  and  often  does,  implant  holy  dispositions  and 
habits  in  human  souls,  without  previous  discipline  and 
training  on  their  part ;  or  maintains  the  principle  of  infused 
habits,  as  distinguished  from  habits  acquired  by  acts,  his 
position  is  a  natural  one,  and  agrees  with  our  experience,  as 
well  as  with  the  doctrine  of  the  early  Church.  We  mean  by 
a  habit,  a  certain  bias  or  proneness  to  act  in  a  particular  di- 
rection ;  and  this  bias  or  proneness  is  obtained  in  one  way 
by  successive  acts.  But  it  would  be  untrue,  and  contrary  to 
the  plainest  facts  of  nature,  to  suppose  that  this  is  the  only  way 
in  which  such  a  bias  of  the  mind  is  ever  obtained.  God  evi- 
dently imparts  it  to  men,  at  birth,  in  different  moral  directions ; 
for  we  see  them  born  with  particular  dispositions  and  charac 
ters.  And  as  He  imparts  it  at  birth,  He  appears  also  sometimes 
to  impart  it  on  subsequent  occasions,  by  powerful  impulses, 
communicated  to  the  souls  of  man,  either  internally,  or  by  the 
machinery  of  his  outward  providence;  by  sudden  junctures, 
emergencies,  in  private  or  public  life.  We  see  great  changes 
produced  in  men's  characters  by  these  exciting  causes,  and 
their  minds  put,  by  the  force  of  events,  into  particular  states 
and  tempers,  which  they  retain  afterwards.  That  is  to  say, 
habits  are  sometimes  imparted  to  men  at  once,  and  from 
without,  in  distinction  to  being  the  result  of  successive  acts. 
The  doctrine  of  Conversion,  is  the  application  of  this  truth  to 
the  department  of  religion :  what  this  doctrine  asserts  being, 
that  God,  by  particular  impulses,  either  wholly  internal  or 
connected  with  outward  events,  imparts  at  once  a  religious 
disposition  or  habit  to  the  mind  ;  so  that,  from  being  careless 
and  indifferent,  it  immediately  becomes  serious ;  which  is  un- 
doubtedly sometimes  the  case.  So  far,  then,  as  the  schoolman 
simply  maintains  in  this  scheme  the  position  of  infused 
habits,  or  that  habits  need  not  necessarily  be  obtained  by  acts, 
he  maintains  a  true  and  natural  doctrine.  And  this  was  an 


CHAP.  X.]  OF    PREDESTINATION.  293 

important  modification  of  the  Aristotelian  doctrine,  which 
rested  too  exclusively  upon  acts  as  the  cause  of  habits.  So 
acute  an  observer,  indeed,  of  facts,  as  that  great  philo- 
sopher was,  could  not  but  see  himself  that  this  cause  did 
not  apply  in  all  cases ;  —  and  the  observation  extracted 
from  him  a  partial  modification  of  his  own  system,  in 
the  shape  of  the  admission  of  natural  virtue  —  fyvaiia)  dpsr?). 
But  the  addition  of  infusion,  as  a  formal  and  regular  cause, 
in  the  case  of  habits,  was  a  substantial  modification  of  the 
Aristotelian  doctrine.  It  was,  however,  a  modification,  which 
naturally  followed  from  Christianity.  The  idea  of  the  Divine 
power,  which  was  not  fully  embraced  by  the  Pagan  philoso- 
pher, was  brought  out  by  the  true  religion,  and  applied  to  the 
moral,  as  well  as  to  the  physical  world,  to  the  department  of 
will,  as  well  as  that  of  matter.  In  other  words,  it  taught  a 
doctrine,  which  the  pagan  philosopher  did  not  hold,  that  of 
Divine  Grace ;  which  immediately  became  a  fresh  element  in 
the  argument,  and  supplied  a  new  cause  for  the  formation  of 
the  habit. 

But,  while  the  scheme  thus  rested  upon  a  basis  of  nature 
and  truth,  two  great  causes  of  confusion  were  at  work  in  it. 
One  was  an  unreal  or  artificial  distinction  in  the  subject 
matter  of  acquired  and  infused  habits.  It  will  be  evident 
to  any  one,  on  reflection,  that  the  distinction  between  these 
two  kinds  of  habits,  is  a  distinction  simply  in  the  mode  in 
which  they  are  formed,  and  not  at  all  in  the  nature  or  matter 
of  the  habits  themselves ;  the  same  state  and  disposition  of 
mind  being  formed  in  the  one  case  by  time,  custom,  successive 
acts,  and  in  the  other  by  Divine  power  producing  it,  without 
the  aid  of  these  previous  steps.  All  habits,  as  such,  then,  what- 
ever be  their  subject  matter,  or  rank,  come  alike  under  both 
these  modes  of  formation :  an  ordinary  moral  habit,  such  as 
honesty  or  temperance,  is  as  much  a  subject  of  infusion  as  a 
spiritual  one,  such  as  faith  or  charity ;  and  a  spiritual  habit, 
such  as  faith  or  charity,  is  as  much  a  subject  of  acquisition, 
as  a  common  moral  one  of  temperance  or  honesty.  Infusion 

u  3 


294 


SCHOLASTIC    DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X. 


and  acquisition  apply  alike  to  both.  A  habit  of  faith  is 
acquired  by  acts  of  faith,  and  a  habit  of  love  by  acts  of  love ; 
and  the  natural  or  Aristotelian  law  of  the  formation  of 
habits,  is  as  true  of  spiritual  as  of  common  moral  habits. 
Again,  the  commonest  moral  dispositions  are  as  capable,  as 
spiritual  ones,  of  being  imparted  in  the  other  way,  i.  e.  with- 
out previous  acts;  and  we  see  them  so  imparted  often  at 
birth.  But  Aquinas  artificially  appropriates  infusion  to 
spiritual  virtues,  acquisition  to  moral  ones  1 ;  as  if  the  former 
were  never  acquired  by  acts,  and  the  latter  never  but  by 
them.  It  depends  on  the  dispensation  under  which  a  person 
is  individually  placed,  in  what  way  he  obtains  either  spiritual 
or  moral  habits ;  whether  both  are  the  simple  growth  of 
time  and  acts  in  him,  or  whether  he  obtains  both  in  the 
more  immediate  way:  though  we  must  not  so  divide  the 
two  modes  of  formation  of  character,  as  to  forget  that  both 
may  go  on  together  in  the  same  person,  and  that  mankind 
are  all  more  or  less  under  both  systems. 

Another  cause  of  confusion  was  the  technical  and  quaint 
division  of  these  habits,  followed  by  the  artificial  subordi- 
nation of  one  division  to  another,  the  attempt  being  to  con- 
struct them  into  one  harmonious  machinery  for  the  building 
up  of  the  human  soul,  —  one  set,  at  the  point  where  its  power 
failed,  being  taken  up,  and  its  action  carried  on  by  another. 
The  theological  virtues,  Faith,  Hope,  and  Charity,  were 
infused  habits.  But  though,  their  infusion  into  a  particular 
soul  being  supposed,  these  were  true  habits  or  dispositions 
of  that  soul;  they  were  passive  and  inert,  not  producing 
acts  until  they  were  moved  from  another  quarter  to  do  so. 
They  were  habits  indeed,  but  elementary  ones,  imperfectly 
possessed,  and  rather  of  the  nature  of  principles  or  faculties 
— principia  super  natur  alia  ^  corresponding  to  the  natural 
faculties  of  man — principia  naturalia.2  While  the  natural 


1  He  admits  natural  moral  virtue  in 
limited  way,  p.  291. 

2  Et  quia  hujusmodi  beatitude  pro- 


portionem  humanae  naturae  excedit, 
principia  naturalia  hominis  non  suffi- 
ciunt  ad  ordinandum  hominem  in  bea- 


CHAP.  X.] 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


295 


will  of  man,  then,  could  put  the  natural  principles  into 
action,  because  these  were  possessed  perfectly,  it  could  not, 
of  itself,  put  into  action  the  supernatural  principles.  To  put 
these  into  action  another  spiritual  force  was  necessary.1  To 
the  theological  virtues,  therefore,  succeeded  the  Dona.  Now 
it  is  true  that  a  habit  does  not  move  itself  to  action,  but 
requires  to  be  put  in  motion  by  a  particular  act  of  freewill, 
on  one  theory,  by  a  particular  act  of  grace,  on  another. 
But  the  Dona  were  themselves  only  imparted  habits.  Here, 
then,  was  one  set  of  habits,  which  was  necessary  to  put  in 
motion  another.  And  as  the  Dona  succeeded  the  theological 
virtues,  the  "  infused  moral  virtues "  succeeded  the  Dona ; 
being  those  final  and  settled  spiritual  habits  to  which  the 
supernatural  principles  in  man,  i.  e.  the  theological  virtues, 
tended ;  as  the  acquired  habits  were  the  completion  of  his 
natural  principles.2  Yet  this  accumulation  of  habits,  rising 
one  above  another  in  formal  scale,  this  whole  complex  ma- 
chinery, did  not  complete  the  moral  being,  who  seemed  always 
approaching  the  terminus  of  action,  and  never  attaining  it. 

For,  secondly,  habitual  grace,  with  all  this  multiplicity 
of  internal  construction,  could  still  not  put  itself  in  action. 
It  was  still  no  more  than  a  habit  of  the  mind,  imparted  by 


tudinem  praedictam ;  unde  oportet  quod 
superaddantur  homini  divinitus  aliqua 
principia,  per  quae  ita  ordinetur  ad 
beatitudinem  supernaturalem,  sicut  per 
principia  naturalia  ordinatur  ad  finem 
connaturalem  :  et  hujusmodi  principia 
dicuntur  virtutes  theologicce ;  turn  quia 
habent  Deum  pro  objecto,  turn  quia  a 
solo  Deo  nobis  infunduntur. — lma  2dae 
Q.  62.  A.  1. 

1  Manifestum  est  quod  virtutes  hu- 
manae  proficiunt  hominem,  secundum 
quod  homo  natus  est  moveri  per  ra- 
tionem.  Oportet  igitur  inesse  homini 
altiores  perfectiones,  secundum  quas 
sit  dispositus  ad  hoc  quod  divinitus 
moveatur ;  et  istce  perfectiones  vocantur 
dona.—l™  2d»8  Q.  68.  A.  1.  The 
Theological  virtues  are  imperfect  agents 
and  cannot  move  without  the  Dona. — 


Prima  (naturalis)  virtus  habetur  ab 
homine  quasi  plena  possessio  :  secunda 
autem  (theologica)  habetur  quasi  im- 
perfecta.  Sed  id  quod  imperfecte  habet 
naturam  aliquam  non  habet  per  se  ope- 
rari,  nisi  ab  altero  moveatur.  ...  Ad 
finem  ultimum  naturalem  ad  quam  ratio 
movet,  secundum  quod  est  imperfecte 
formata  per  theologicas  virtutes,  non 
sufficit  ipsa  motio  rationis,  nisi  desuper 
adsit  instinctus  Spiritus  Sancti — A.  2. 
2  Loco  naturalium  principiorum  con- 
feruntur  nobis  a  Deo  virtutes  theolo- 
gicae.  .  .  .  Unde  oportet  quod  his  etiam 
virtutibus  theologicis  proportionaliter 
respondeant  alii  habitus  divinitus-.causati 
in  nobis,  qui  sic  se  habent  ad  virtutes 
theologicas,  sicut  se  habent  virtutes 
morales  ad  principia  naturalia  virtutum. 
—  lma  2dae  Q.  63.  A.  3. 


u   4 


296 


SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X. 


God :  and  no  habit,  as  has  been  just  said,  can  put  itself  in 
action ;  for  a  man  does  not  necessarily  do  a  thing,  in  fact, 
because  he  has  a  certain  disposition  to  do  it.  It  became 
then  a  vital  question,  what  it  was  which  put  habitual  grace 
into  action.  Was  it  the  freewill  of  man  ?  If  it  was,  then 
the  human  will  had  an  original  and  independent  act  assigned 
to  it ;  a  position  which  was  contrary  to  this  whole  scholastic 
doctrine  of  grace.  It  was  not  freewill,  then,  but  another 
and  a  further  grace,  which  set  in  motion  habitual,  viz. 
grace  actual  —  gratia  actualis.1  This  was  the  completion 
of  the  system,  the  key-stone  of  the  arch.  Habitual  grace 
could  be  admitted  without  any  serious  drawback  from  the 
power  of  the  natural  will ;  for  God  might  impart  a  certain 
disposition,  or  continuous  impulse ;  while  it  depended  wholly 
on  the  independent  motion  of  the  will,  whether  the  man 
acted  upon  it  or  not.  The  turning  and  distinctive  assertion 
in  the  system,  then,  was  the  assertion  of  actual  grace,  as 
that  which  moved  habitual :  and  to  this  cardinal  position 
the  Thomists,  and  their  successors  the  Jansenists,  directed 
their  most  zealous  and  anxious  attention,  repelling  all 
interference  with  it  as  a  subversion  of  the  whole  Gospel 
doctrine  of  grace.  The  admission  of  habitual  grace  set 
aside  as  one  which  the  Semi-Pelagian  or  even  the  Pelagian 
could  make,  without  danger  in  principle  to  his  theory  ; 
grace  actual  was  defended  as  the  central  fort  of  Christian 
truth  in  this  department.2 


1  See  p.  290. 

2  Non    est  habitus  qui  faelt  facere, 
says    Jansen.       No    habit,    he    urges, 
is  the   cause  of  action,  but  liberum  ar- 
bitrium  at  the  time. — De  Gratia  Christi, 
pp.  186.  996.     Nee  est  lux  vel  habitus 
quae  velle  vel  non  velle,  videre  vel  non 
videre   faciunt,    sed   tantummodo   sine 
guibus  actus   volendi   vel   videndi   non 
fit.  —  p.  '935.      And  this  motion   of 

liberum  arbitrium  at  the  time,  is  pro- 
duced by  grace  at  the  time — gratia 
specialis,  actualis —  adjutorium  gratise 


actualis  quod  tune  datur,  quando  actu 
volumus  et  operamur.  .  .  .  inspirans 
etiam  habitualiter  justis  velle  et  operari. 
—  pp.  151.  153.  He  adds:  Tota  dis- 
putatio  cum  Pelagio  de  justorum,  hoc 
est,  habitualem  gratiam  jam  habentium 
fervuit.  .  .  Non  ita  deliravit  Pelagius, 
ut  existimaret  justitiam  habitualem,  ad 
opera  justa  suo  modo  non  adjuvare. — 
p.  1 53.  "  Actualis  gratia  "  thus  gives 
the.  "  completum  posse,"  which  is  "  per 
liberum  arbitrium  remotior,  per  fidem 
propinquior,  per  charitatem  multo  pro- 


CHAP.  X.] 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


297 


As  then  in  the  simpler  and  Augustinian,  so  in  the  com- 
plex and  Aristotelian  statement  of  the  doctrine  of  grace, 
in  which  the  distinction  of  habitual  and  actual  is  intro- 
duced, Aquinas  maintains,  we  see,  an  irresistible  or  effective 
grace.  Habitual  grace  is  guarded  carefully  at  both  ends 
from  dependence  on  the  human  will.  It  was  alike  imparted 
and  applied  by  an  act  of  Divine  Power.  Had  the  spiritual 
habit  been  either  obtained  in  the  first  instance  by  an  act 
of  the  will,  or,  when  imparted  as  a  free  gift,  depended  for 
its  use  on  the  will,  a  place  for  freewill  would  have  been 
allowed.  But  if  freewill  comes  in  neither  at  the  beginning 
nor  at  the  end,  neither  as  obtaining  the  habit  in  the  first 
instance  nor  as  using  it  in  the  next,  or  causing  it  to  ter- 
minate in  act,  one  operation  of  an  irresistible  Divine  influ- 
ence is  maintained  throughout. 

The  Summa  Theologica  thus  lays  down  a  doctrine  of 
absolute  predestination,  with  its  complemental  doctrine  of 
irresistible  grace  —  that  the  whole  world,  being  by  original 
sin  one  mass  of  perdition,  it  pleased  God  of  His  sovereign 
mercy  to  rescue  some  and  to  leave  others  where  they  were  ; 
to  raise  some  to  glory,  giving  them  such  grace  as  necessarily 
qualified  them  for  it,  and  abandon  the  rest,  from  whom 
He  withheld  such  grace,  to  eternal  punishment.  But  this 
formal  scheme  laid  down,  the  attentive  reader  of  Aquinas 
will  next  observe  a  certain  general  leaning  and  bias  towards 
a  modifying  interpretation  of  it.  Having  constructed  a 


pinquior,  per  actualem  gratiam,"  really 
had.  — p.  338.  This  position  is  main- 
tained as  the  only  one  which  cuts  off 
the  ground  of  merit  from  man.  Did 
he  use  habitual  grace  by  his  own  power 
of  choice,  he  would  have  the  merit  of 
his  own  use  of  this  grace  (p.  186.); 
but  if  this  grace  is  put  in  action  by 
another  grace,  no  ground  of  merit  in 
the  man  himself  remains.  And  a  dis- 
tinction is  drawn  in  this  respect  be- 
tween fallen  man  and  the  angels. — 
llinc  nascebatur  ut  neque  volitioncs 


neque  actiones  angelorum  essent  spe- 
cialia  Dei  dona,  hoc  est,  non  eis  Deus 
special!  donatione  seu  gratia  largiretur. 
Tantummodo  enim  donabat  ea  in 
radice,  quatenuseis  adjutoriumquoddam 
gratia;  tribuebat,  sine  quo  .  .  .  non 
poterant :  sed  ipsum  velle,  agere,  et 
perseverare,  non  eis  dabat  adjutorium 
gratise,  sed  propria  voluntas  .  .  .  Tune 
igitur  velle  et  agere  bonum  non  erat 
speciale  Dei  donum,  sed  tantum  gene- 
rale. — pp.  935,  936. 


298 


SCHOLASTIC    DOCTIilNE 


[CHAP.  X. 


system  on  the  strict  Augustinian  basis,  the  mind  of  the 
great  schoolman  appears  to  have  shrunk  from  the  extreme 
results  which  it  involved ;  and  without  committing  himself 
to  any  substantial  difference  from  his  master,  he  yet  uses 
modes  of  speaking  suggestive  of  another  view  of  the  question 
than  that  which  he  had  borrowed  from  him ;  and  a  phrase- 
ology, which  is  not  casual,  but  set  and  constant,  insinuates 
a  relaxation  of  the  Augustinian  doctrine. 

And  first  I  will  make  the  preliminary  remark,  that  a 
difference  is  to  be  observed  in  the  general  tone  of  these 
two  great  theological  minds,  tending  more  or  less  to  affect 
their  respective  views  on  this  subject.  Aquinas  is  more  pf 
a  philosopher  than  his  master,  and  has  greater  sympathies 
with  the  human  mind  as  such,  with  the  natural  intellect, 
reason,  and  moral  ideas  of  mankind.  His  vast  acquaintance 
with  heathen  philosophy  opens  his  mind  to  the  valuable  gifts 
even  of  unenlightened  man,  his  deep  reflections  upon  him- 
self, his  knowledge  of  God, — true  as  far  as  it  goes,  —  and  his 
advancement  in  virtue,  under  the  guidance  of  reason  and 
conscience.  Nor  is  the  deference  which  he  shows  to  heathen 
authority,  in  philosophical  and  moral  questions,  altogether 
consistent  with  the  position  which  his  formal  theology,  as  an 
Augustinian,  assigned  to  unconverted  human  nature,  which 
it  represented  as  in  the  depths  of  sin,  and  unable  to  do  or  to 
think  anything  good.  The  perplexity,  again,  with  respect  to 
the  existence  of  evil,  appears  in  a  deeper  and  more  sensitive 
form  in  the  mind  of  Aquinas  than  it  does  in  that  of  his 
master.  Augustine  sees  as  a  theologian  an  inexplicable 
mystery ;  but  Aquinas  shows  more  of  that  human  sentiment, 
with  respect  to  the  great  fact  of  evil  in  the  world  l,  which 


1  Bradwardine    has    less  scruple 

Ecce  triplex  bonum  ex  reprobis :  utilitas 
electorum,  bonum  naturae,  seculique 
ornatus.  Ponatur  quoque  secundum 
pium  zelum  multorum,  licet  non  se- 
cundum scientiam,  quod  totus  infernus 


cum  omnibus  suis  domesticis  reprobatis 
tollereturde  medio,  essetque  coelumtan- 
tummodo  cum  civibus  suis  sanctis  :  tune 
seculum  esset  multum  perfectum,  et  si 
Deus  sic  fecisset  multum  bene  fecisset. 
Nunc  autem  tanto  perfectius  et  tanto 


CHAP.  X.I 


OF    PREDESTINATION. 


299 


has  rested  upon  so  many  of  the  deep  and  philosophical  minds 
of  different  ages,  and  especially  of  modern  times,  disquieting 
some,  and  sobering  and  subduing  others.  His  perception 
not  dulled  by  the  commonness  and  constancy  of  the  fact, 
as  inferior  ones  are,  but  ever  retaining  something  of  a  first 
surprise,  acknowledges,  as  the  eye  of  a  naturalist  would 
some  remarkable  law  in  his  department,  the  prevalence 
of  moral  evil  in  this  lower  world  —  bonum  videtur  esse  ut 
in  paudoribus  ; —  a  fact  which,  as  he  cannot  explain,  he 
endeavours  to  outweigh,  conjecturing  some  compensation  for 
it  in  other  parts  of  the  universe,  and  isolating  this  sublunary 
world  as  one  exception  to  a  universal  law.  This  sphere  of 
natural  evil,  of  generation  and  corruption,  was  small  in  com- 
parison with  the  world  of  heavenly  bodies,  whose  existence 
was  eternal  and  fixed.  This  sphere  of  moral  evil  in  the 
majority  was  small,  again,  in  comparison  with  the  angelic 
world,  where  a  different  law  was  in  operation ;  and  the  angels 
who  stood  were  much  more  in  number  than  those  who  fell, 
and,  perhaps,  even  than  the  whole  number  of  the  condemned, 
both  men  and  demons — et  forte  etiam  multo  plures  quam 
omnes  damnandi  dcemones  et  homines.1  Such  a  line  of  thought 
had  a  bearing  upon  the  present  question,  and  tended  to  affect 
his  view  upon  it ;  because  an  attempt  to  reduce  the  amount 
of  evil  in  the  universe  at  large  disposed  to  reducing,  as  far 
as  might  be,  the  alarming  estimate  of  it  in  this  world. 

The  distinction,  then,  involved  in  Augustinian  predesti- 
nation and  reprobation,  being  a  distinction  between  positive 
good  and  positive  evil,  goodness  and  wickedness,  and  their 


melius  fecit  Deus,  quantum  perfectionis 
et  bonitatis  continent  in  se  illce  nobiles 
creatures  damnatee,  quantum  etiam 
resplendentiae  et  apparentise  purioris 
ilia  •comparatio  veluti  contrarietatis 
extremae  confert  justis,  tanquam  scin- 
tillas fulgentibus,  et  ut  stellae.  Quis 
enim  vel  cujus  ratio  prohibuisset  Do- 
minum  ab  initio,  si  fuisset  placitum 
coram  eo,  creasse  codum  plenum  electis 


in  gloria,  et  infernum  plenum  reprobis 
in  pcena,  ut  hoc  illi  comparate  apparu- 
isset  gloriosius  et  fuisset?  Non  de- 
erunt  tamen  qui  hos  humano  misere- 
rentur  afFectu,  et  pia  compassione 
contenderent  sic  facere  non  debere. — 
p.  355. 

1  In  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  39.  Q.  2.  A. 
2. 


300 


SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X 


consequences,  eternal  happiness  and  eternal  misery,  to  two 
portions  of  the  world  respectively ;  there  is  a  tendency  in 
the  language  of  Aquinas  to  reduce  this  distinction  to  a  dis- 
tinction between  higher  and  lower  good.  Two  kinds  of 
happiness  are  laid  down  in  his  system,  "  one  of  which  is  pro- 
portioned to  human  nature,  and  to  which  a  man  can  arrive 
by  this  principle  of  his  own  nature ;  the  other  exceeding 
human  nature,  and  to  which  a  man  can  arrive  only  by  Divine 
virtue  and  by  a  participation  of  the  Divinity,  according  to 
the  text  in  S.  Peter,  that  we  are  by  Christ  made  partakers  of 
the  Divine  Nature."  l  Here,  then,  are  two  kinds  of  happi- 
ness, and  two  kinds  of  virtues,  which  respectively  qualify  for 
them.  There  is  one  class  of  virtues,  which  fits  a  man  for  his 
place  in  the  order  of  nature,  and  makes  him  a  worthy  member 
of  the  world  of  God's  natural  providence — secundum  guas  homo 
se  bene  habet  in  or  dine  ad  res  humanas  ;  another  class,  which 
fits  a  man  for  a  place  in  a  supernatural  order  of  things  and  a 
heavenly  citizenship — ad  hoc  quod  sint  cives  sanctorum  et  domes- 
tici  Dei?  Expressed  with  scholastic  formality,  here  is  a  very 
obvious  distinction,  and  one  which  we  cannot  avoid  observing 
in  the  world  around  us,  —  one  which  is  recognised  in  the 
common  language  and  writings  of  Christians.  We  see  as  a 
plain  fact,  that  there  is  a  kind  of  goodness,  which,  as  dis- 
tinguished from  another  kind,  must  be  pronounced  to  belong 
to  this  world,  — that  men  may  be  honest,  conscientious,  and 
high  principled  in  their  worldly  callings,  still  having  their 
view  confined  to  this  world.  It  is  a  virtuous  mould  and 
character  of  mind,  —  that  of  a  man  who  recognises  the  world 
as  a  true  sphere  of  moral  action,  desires  to  be  on  the  right 
side,  and  cultivates  with  that  view  various  moral  qualities ; 


1  Est  autem  duplex  hominis  beati- 
tude ;  una  quidem  proportionata 
humanae  naturae,  ad  quam  scilicet  homo 
pervenire  potest  per  principia  suae  na- 
turae. Alia  autem  beatitude  naturam 
hominis  excedens,  ad  quam  homo  sola 
divina  virtute  pervenire  potest  secun- 


dum quandam  Divinitatis  participa- 
tionem ;  secundum  quod  dicitur 
(2  Pet.  i.)  quod  per  Christum  facti 
sum  us  consortes  divines  natures. — lm* 
2dM  Q.  62.  A.  1. 

2    lm»  2d»e  Q.   63<   A,   4. 


CHAP.  X.] 


OF   PREDESTINATION. 


301 


who,  therefore,  so  far  as  the  spiritual  principle  is  involved 
in  any  bond  fide  and  honest  distinction  of  good  and  evil, 
acknowledges  a  spiritual  law  in  his  own  nature  and  the  con- 
stitution of  things,  to  which  he  defers,  and  on  which  he 
frames  his  life  and  conduct ;  but  who  lowers  this  law  by  his 
narrow  and  confined  application  of  it  to  present  things  and 
visible  relations.  This,  then,  is  what  Christian  moralists  call 
the  virtue  of  the  natural  man;  and  its  defect  is  in  the 
principle  of  faith,  which,  by  opening  another  world  for  them, 
and  so  enlarging  their  scope  and  field,  would  have  given  a 
spring  and  impulse  to  these  moral  perceptions,  quickening  and 
strengthening  them ;  whereas  they  are  now  kept  down  to  a 
particular  level.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  an  essential  part 
of  Christian  doctrine,  that  there  is  a  temper  of  mind  so  far  in 
advance  of  this  natural  morality,  as  to  seem  to  differ  from  it 
in  kind ;  in  the  sense  in  which  everything  seems  at  its  per- 
fection and  final  point,  to  be  a  different  thing  from  what  it 
was  before,  as  a  lens  burns  at  its  centre  only.  This  is  the 
supernatural  temper  of  charity.1 

From  morals  the  distinction  of  natural  and  supernatural 
is  then  extended  by  Aquinas  to  religion.  It  was  obvious 
that  the  natural  man  had  not  only  moral  virtue  of  some 
kind,  but  religion  as  well.  For,  independent  of  the  religious 
men  which  Paganism  had  produced,  what  is  the  obedience 
which  the  natural  man,  in  his  moral  course  of  life,  pays 
to  his  own  conscience,  but  an  obedience  to  God,  whom  he 
virtually  recognises  as  speaking  to  him  by  that  internal 


1  La  distance  infinie  des  corps  aux 
esprits  figure  la  distance  infiniment  plus 
infinie  des  esprits  a  la  charite  ;  car  elle 
est  surnaturelle. 

Tous  les  corps,  le  firmament,  les 
etoiles,  la  terre  et  les  royaumes  ne 
valent  pas  le  moindre  des  esprits ;  car 
il  connait  tout  cela,  et  soi-meme  ;  et 
le  corps,  rien.  Et  tous  les  corps,  et 
tons  les  esprits  ensemble,  et  toutes  leurs 
productions,  ne  valent  pas  le  moindre 


mouvement   de   charite ;    car   elle   est 
d'un  ordre  infiniment  plus  eleve'. 

De  tous  les  corps  ensemble  on  ne 
saurait  tirer  la  moindre  pensee:  cela 
est  impossible,  et  d'un  autre  ordre. 
Tous  les  corps  et  les  esprits  ensemble 
ne  sauraient  produire  un  mouvement 
de  vraie  charite :  cela  est  impossible, 
et  d'un  autre  ordre  tout  surnaturel. — 
Pascal. 


302  SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  X. 

voice  ?  And  as  he  will  obey  that  conscience,  even  at  the 
cost  of  his  worldly  interests,  suffering  the  greatest  incon- 
veniences rather  than  offend  against  probity  and  honesty, 
it  is  plain  that  in  some  sense  he  prefers  the  Divine*  appro- 
bation to  everything  else.  It  was  accordingly  laid  down 
that  the  natural  man  was  able  to  love  God  above  all  things 
— homo  potest  diligere  Deum  super  omnia  ex  solis  naturalibus 
sine  gratia.  But  the  distinction  was  then  applied  that  he 
loved  God  naturally,  not  supernaturally,  "  as  the  source 
and  end  of  natural  good ;  whereas  charity  loved  Him  as 
the  centre  of  spiritual  good  or  happiness.  Charity  had, 
moreover,  a  positive  communion  with  God,  which  nature  had 
not ;  of  which  communion  a  certain  promptitude  and  delight 
were  the  results,  which  did  not  belong  to  the  natural  love  of 
God."1 

These  two  kinds  of  goodness,  then,  natural  and  super- 
natural, had  their  respective  sources  assigned  to  them, 
and  the  cause  or  motive  power  was  pronounced,  by  an 
abbreviation,  in  the  one  case  to  be  reason,  in  the  other  God 
— Ratio  et  Deus  2 :  the  Divine  Power,  however,  operating 
alike  in  both  cases  as  true  and  original  Cause.  The  Divine 
Power,  acting  simply  as  the  First  or  Universal  Cause  in 
nature,  moved  the  freewill  of  man  to  natural  virtue  ;  acting 
in  a  special  way  or  by  grace,  it  moved  the  same  freewill 
to  supernatural  virtue.3  ff  All  things,"  says  Aquinas,  "  are 
subject  to  Providence,  and  it  pertains  to  Providence  to 
ordain  all  things  to  their  end.  But  the  end  to  which  created 
things  are  ordained  by  God  is  twofold.  One  is  the  end 
which  exceeds  the  proportion  and  faculty  of  created  nature  ; 


1  "  Charitas  diligit  Deum  super  om- 
nia eminentius  quam  natura.  Natura 
enim  diligit  Deum  super  omnia,  prout 
est  principium  et  finis  naturalis  boni ; 
charitas  autem,  secundum  quod  est 
objectum  beatitudinis,  et  secundum 
quod  homo  habet  quandam  societatem 


spiritualem  cum  Deo.  Addit  etiam 
charitas  super  naturalem*  dilectionsm 
Dei,  promptitudinem  quandam  et  delec- 
tationem."— lma  2daa  Q.  109.  A.  3. 

2  lmft  2<3ac  Q.   68.   A.    1. 

3  lma  2d»e  Q.   1Q.   A.  6. 


CHAP.  X.] 


OF    PKEDESTINATION. 


303 


that  is  say,  the  life  eternal,  which  consists  in  the  Divine 
vision, — which  vision  is  above  the  nature  of  every  creature. 
Another  is  the  end  proportioned  to  created  nature,  and 
which  that  nature  can  attain  by  the  virtue  of  that  nature. 
Now,  that  which  cannot  arrive  at  a  point  by  its  own  virtue 
must  be  transmitted  thither  by  another,  as  an  arrow  is  sent 
by  an  archer  at  a  mark.  Wherefore,  properly  speaking,  the 
rational  creature,  which  is  capable  of  life  eternal,  is  con- 
ducted up  to  it,  or  transmitted  to  it  by  God.  Of  which 
transmission  the  reason  pre-exists  in  the  mind  of  God,  even 
as  there  exists  generally  the  reason  of  the  ordination  of  all 
things  whatever  to  the  end.  But  the  reason  of  anything  being 
done  is  a  certain  pre-existence  in  the  mind  of  the  doer  of 
the  thing  itself  to  be  done  ;  whence  the  reason  of  the  trans- 
mission of  the  rational  creature  to  life  eternal  is  called 
predestination  —  nam  destinare  est  mittere? l  While  the 
cause,  then,  of  natural  virtue  is  the  Divine  Power  acting 
in  its  ordinary  function,  as  predetermining  universally  the 
created  wills  of  men,  the  cause  of  supernatural  virtue  in  man  is 
the  Divine  Power  acting  in  predestination,  or  in  the  execu- 
tion of  a  certain  special  decree.  "  The  virtue  which  qualifies 
man  for  good  as  defined  by  the  Divine  Law,  in  distinction 
to  reason,  cannot  be  caused  by  human  acts  of  which  the 
principle  is  reason,  but  is  caused  in  us  by  the  Divine  opera- 
tion alone." '  And  this  Divine  operation  is  carried  on  by 
means  of  that  machinery  of  infused  supernatural  virtues 


1  "  Ad  illud  autem,  ad  quod  noil  po- 
test  aliquid  virtute  suae  naturae  perve- 
nire,  oportet  quod  ab  alio  transmittatur, 
sicut  sagitta  a  sagittante  mittitur  ad 
signum.  Unde  proprie  loquendo,  ra- 
tionalis  creatura,  quae  est  capax  vitae 
aeternae  perducitur  in  ipsam  quasi  a  Deo 
transtnissa.  Cu,]us  quidem  transmissionis 
ratio  in  Deo  praeexistir,  sicut  et  in  eo 
est  ratio  ordinis  omnium  in  finem. 
Ratio  autem  alicujus  fiendi  existens  est 
queedam  praeexistentia  rei  fiendae  in  eo. 


Unde  ratio  prsedicta transmissionis  crea- 
turae  rationalis  in  finem  vitae  aeternae 
pradestinatio  nominatur  ;  nam  desti- 
nare est  mittere." —  lma  Q.  23.  A.  1. 

2  "  Virtus  vero  ordinans  hominem  ad 
bonum  secundum  quod  modificatur  per 
legem  divinam,  et  non  per  rationem 
humanam,  non  potest  causari  per  actus 
humanos  quorum  principium  est  ratio; 
sed  causatur  solum  in  nobis  per  ope- 
rationem  divinam." — Im*  2dae  Q.  63. 
A.  2. 


304  SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  X. 

above  described.  For  "as  God  provides  for  His  natural 
creatures  in  such  wise,  that  He  not  only  moves  them  to 
natural  acts,  but  even  endows  them  with  certain  forms 
and  virtues  to  act  as  principles  of  action  and  to  be  in 
themselves  dispositions  to  such  action ;  so  into  those  whom 
He  moves  to  attain  eternal  and  supernatural  good  He  in- 
fuses certain  supernatural  forms  or  qualities,  by  which  they 
are  sweetly  and  promptly  disposed  to  attain  that  good."  l 
Supernatural  virtue  is  thus  an  extraordinary,  natural  an 
ordinary,  gift ;  the  one  an  inspiration,  the  other  a  provi- 
dential endowment. 

But  while  these  two  kinds  of  virtue,  and  the  ends  to  which 
they  respectively  tend,  diifer  in  the  quality  of  good  which 
belongs  to  them,  both  have,  according  to  this  language,  some ; 
and  the  difference  between  these  two  states  is  one  of  higher 
and  lower  good,  and  not  one  of  good  and  evil.  As  a  disci- 
ple of  S.  Augustine,  indeed,  Aquinas  is  obliged  formally  to 
preserve  the  distinction  between  the  natural  and  spiritual 
man  as  one  of  positive  good  and  positive  evil,  and  to  use  the 
terms  predestination  and  reprobation  as  involving  this 
difference ;  to  represent  inclusion  within  the  Divine  decree  as 
salvation,  exclusion  from  it  as  damnation.  The  pure  Augus- 
tinian  doctrine  admitted  of  no  medium  between  these  two 
results ;  which  it  defends  on  the  ground  of  an  original  guilt 
in  the  human  race,  which  meets  with  its  due  punishment  in  one 
of  these,  with  a  gratuitous  pardon  in  the  other.  Aquinas, 
then,  formally  adopts  the  Augustinian  scheme,  with  the  esta- 
blished defences.  But  a  careful  observation  of  his  language 
will  detect  a  contest  between  two  different  rationales  in  his 
mind  ;  the  Clementine  view  of  human  nature  struggling  with 


1  "  Creaturis  autem  naturalibus  sic 
providet  ut  non  solum  moveat  eas  ad 
actus  naturales,  sed  etiam  largitur  eis 
formas  et  virtutes  quasdam  quae  sunt 
principia  actuum.  .  .  Multo  igitur 
magis  illos  quos  movet  ad  consequen- 


dum  bonum  supernaturale  aeternum  in- 
fundit  aliquas  formas,  seu  qualitates  sn~ 
pernaturales,  secundum  quas  suaviter  et 
prompte  ab  ipso  moveantur  ad  bonum 
aeternum  consequendum." — lma  2dae  Q. 
110.  A,  2. 


CHAP.  X.J  OF   PREDESTINATION.  305 

the  Augustinian.  Reprobation,  maintained  on  one  side  in  full 
severity,  is  softened  down  on  another,  and  identified  with  a 
lower  step  in  the  scale  of  being ;  and  the  rigid  Augustinian 
line  of  defence  for  the  doctrine  mixes  with  another,  which 
implies  a  reduced  doctrine  to  be  defended.  We  are  referred, 
together  with  an  original  guilt  in  human  nature,  to  a  prin- 
ciple of  variety  in  the  constitution  of  things,  which  requires 
that  there  should  be  higher  and  lower  places  in  the  universe, 
down  even  to  some  lowest  place  of  all,  which  must  be  occu- 
pied. ((  As  created  things,"  he  says,  "  cannot  attain  to  the 
Divine  simplicity,  it  is  necessary  that  the  Divine  goodness, 
which  is  in  itself  one  and  simple,  should  be  represented 
multiformly  in  them ;  and  the  completeness  of  the  universe 
requires  a  difference  of  grades,  some  high  and  others  low  in  it. 
And  on  this  account  God  permits  evils  to  take  place,  lest 
good  should  be  obstructed  by  its  own  abundance,  and  to  pre- 
serve this  multiformity  of  grades  in  the  universe.  And  He 
deals  with  the  human  race  as  He  does  with  the  universe,— 
He  represents  His  goodness  with  that  variety  which  is  ne- 
cessary to  such  representation,  in  the  shape  of  mercy  to  those 
whom  He  spares,  of  punishment  to  those  whom  He  reprobates. 
.  .  .  .  e  God  willing  to  show  His  wrath,  and  to  make  His 
power  known,  endured  (z.  e.  permitted)  with  much  long- 
suffering  the  vessels  of  wrath  fitted  to  destruction,  that  He 
might  make  known  the  riches  of  His  glory  on  the  vessels  of 
mercy,  which  He  had  afore  prepared  for  glory  ; '  and  « in  a 
great  house  there  are  not  only  vessels  of  gold  and  silver,  but 
also  of  wood  and  earth,  and  some  to  honour  and  some  to  dis- 
honour.' But  why  He  has  elected  these,  and  reprobated 
those,  there  is  no  reason  but  the  Divine  Will,  as  Augustine 
saith,  '  Why  He  draws  this  man,  and  not  that,  do  not  to  in- 
quire, if  thou  wouldest  not  err.'  Just  as  in  natural  things,  a 
reason  can  be  assigned,  why  out  of  uniform  elemental  matter 
one  part  is  put  under  the  form  of  fire,  and  another  under  the 
form  of  earth,  and  so  on ;  but  why  this  or  that  part  of  matter  is 
chosen  for  this  or  that  form  none  can  be,  except  the  arbitrary 

x 


306 


SCHOLASTIC    DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X. 


will  of  the  Creator  :  and  as  in  the  case  of  a  building  there  is  a 
reason  why  some  stones  or  other  should  be  put  in  particular 
places,  but  why  these  or  those  stones  are  selected  to  be  put 
in  the  places,  none  —  except  the  arbitrary  will  of  the  builder."1 
Two  interpretations  evidently  divide  this  explanation  and  de- 
fence of  reprobation,  one  a  severer,  the  other  a  milder  one.  It 
is  spoken  of  as  positive  evil,  punishment  on  sin  —  vindictajus- 
titice;  and  it  is  spoken  of  as  lower  good,  for  it  is  represented 
as  a  lower  grade  in  the  scale  of  being  —  infimus  locus  in  uni- 
verso.  But,  according  to  Aquinas,  evil  is  no  part  of  the 
universe,  of  which,  however  varied  and  graduated  that  good 
may  be,  the  whole  is  good ;  so  that  a  lower,  or  the  lowest 
place  in  it  is  a  place  of  good  and  not  of  evil.  And  according 
as  reprobation  is  regarded  in  one  light  or  the  other,  the 
appeal  in  defence  of  it  is  made  either  to  original  sin  or  the 
principle  of  variety  in  nature. 

The  religious  philosophy  of  Aquinas,  then,  of  which  these 
are  the  hints,  tends  simply  to  two  different  moral  creations, 
a  higher  and  a  lower  one.  The  natural  man  is  created  and 
has  the  advantages  of  his  creation;  the  spiritual  man  is 
created  and  has  the  advantages  of  his :  and  predestination 
marks  for  a  special  glory,  and  a  higher  place  in  the  universe ; 
but  exclusion  from  it  does  not  involve  positive  evil  or  misery. 
But  it  is  remarkable  that,  while  he  systematically  hints  at 
such  a  conclusion  as  this,  in  one  peculiar  remote  and  isolated 
case  alone  does  he  apply  it — a  case  outside  of  the  general 
mass  of  moral  beings  which  it  so  deeply  affects,  and  to  which 
the  substantial  interest  of  any  application  of  it  attaches  —  the 
case  of  infants  dying  unbaptized  or  in  original  sin.  Yet  the 
elaborate  and  minute  care  with  which  he  examines  this  par- 


1  "  Sicut  in  rebus  naturalibus  potest 
assignari  ratio,  cum  prima  materia  tota 
sit  in  se  uniformis,  quare  una  pars  ejus 
est  sub  forma  ignis,  et  alia  sub  forma 
terrae  a  Deo  in  principio  condita,  ut  sic 
sit  divcrsitas  specierum  in  rebus  natu- 
ralibus ;  sed  quare  hsec  pars  materite 


est  sub  ista  forma,  et  ilia  sub  alia,  de- 
pendet  ex  simplici  divina  voluntate ; 
sicut  ex  simplici  voluntate  artificis  de- 
pendet  quod  ille  lapis  est  in  ista  parte 
parietis,  et  ille  in  alia,  quamvis  ratio 
artis  habeat  quod  aliqui  sint  in  liac,  et 
aliqui  sint  in  ilia." — lm»  Q.  23.  A.  5. 


CHAP.  X.J  OF   PREDESTINATION.  307 

ticular  case,  with  a  view  to  relieving  it  of  the  pressure  which 
the  Augustinian  doctrine,  in  its  natural  meaning,  left  upon 
it,  is  deserving  of  attention ;  as  showing  the  strength  and 
firmness  of  the  basis,  which,  however  little  built  upon,  was 
formed  in  the  mind  of  the  writer  for  a  general  decision  on 
this  subject. 

Infants  dying,  then,  in  original  sin.  necessarily  came,  ac- 
cording to  the  pure  Augustinian  doctrine,  under  the  Divine 
wrath  which  was  due  to  that  sin.     Being  by  nature  repro- 
bates, and  not  being  included  within  the  remedial  decree  of 
predestination,  they  were,  in  common  with  all  the  rest  of 
mankind  who  were  born  under  this  curse  and  were  not  re- 
lieved by  this  decree,  subject  to  the   sentence   of  eternal 
punishment ;  which  sentence  was  executed  upon  them.  How- 
ever repugnant,  then,  to  natural  reason  and  natural  feeling, 
the   Augustinian  schoolman  could  not  expressly  contradict 
this   position ;    but   what  he  could  not  contradict  he  could 
explain.     Augustine  had  laid  down  that  the  punishment  of 
such  children  was  the  mildest  of  all  punishments  in  hell — om- 
nium esse  mitissimam.    Taking  this  as  the  authorised  definition 
of  the  punishment  of  unbaptized  infants,  he  proceeded  to  raise 
a  structure  of  explanation  upon  it.    First,  was  the  punishment 
of  such  infants  sensible  punishment — sensibilis  pce?ia?     No; 
because  then  it  would  not  be  mitissima,  the  mildest  of  all. 
Moreover,  sensible  pain  is  a  personal  thing — personcsproprium, 
and  therefore  inappropriate  to  a  kind  of  sin  which  is  not  per- 
sonal.    Nor  could  any  argument  be  drawn  from  the  fact,  that 
children  suffered  pain  in  this  world ;  because  this  world  was  not 
under  the  strict  law  of  justice,  as  the  next  was.     Nor  did  this 
immunity  from  pain  imply  in  their  case  any  invasion  of  the 
special  privilege  of  the  saints ;  for  they  enjoyed  no  internal 
impassibility,  but  only  a   freedom  from  external  causes  of 
suffering.     Did  the  punishment  of  such  infants,  again,  involve 
affliction    of  soul — animce    afflictionem    spiritualem?       No; 
for  such  affliction  must  arise  either  on  account  of  their  sin, 
or  of  their  punishment — de  culpa  or  de  pcena.       But  if  it 

x  2 


308 


SCHOLASTIC    DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X, 


arose  on  account  of  their  sin,  it  would  involve  despair  and 
the  worm  of  conscience;  in  which  case  their  punishment 
would  not  be  the  mildest  one,  and  would  therefore  be  op- 
posed to  the  original  supposition.  If  it  arose  on  account  of 
their  punishment,  it  would  involve  an  opposition  in  their 
will  to  the  will  of  God;  in  which  case,  their  will  would 
actually  be  deformed — actualiter  deformis  ;  which  would  imply 
actual  sin,  and  so  be  contrary  to  the  original  supposition. 

The  punishment  of  such  children,  then,  not  being  pain 
either  of  body  or  mind,  what  is  it?  Aquinas  answers,  it  is 
the  want  of  the  Divine  Vision,  or  exclusion  from  the  sight 
of  God — carentia  Divince  visionis,  qua  est  propria  et  sola 
pcena  originalis  peccati  post  mortem  ;  which  he  proves  by  the 
following  argument. 

Original  sin,  he  says,  is  not  the  corruption  of  natural  good, 
but  the  subtraction  of  supernatural ;  its  final  punishment 
therefore  must  correspond,  and  be  the  exclusion,  not  from 
that  end  to  which  the  natural,  but  from  that  end  only 
to  which  the  supernatural  faculties  tend.  But  the  end  of 
the  supernatural  faculties  is  the  Divine  Vision.  It  is  the 
want,  then,  of  this  vision  which  is  the  punishment  of  original 
sin ;  not  the  want  of  any  good  which  properly  belongs  to 
nature.  "  In  the  other  perfections  and  goods  to  which  nature 
tends  upon  her  own  principles,  those  condemned  for  original 
sin  will  sustain  no  detriment."  * 

The  want  of  the  Divine  Vision,  however,  being  thus  laid 
clown  as  the  punishment  of  unbaptized  infants,  an  argumen- 
tal  obstacle  arose  from  the  quarter  of  the  original  definition. 
For,  according  to  Chrysostom,  the  exclusion  from  the  sight  of 
God  is  the  severest  part  of  the  punishment  of  the  damned ; 
at  any  rate  the  want  of  that  which  we  wish  to  have  cannot 
be  without  affliction,  and  unbaptized  infants  wish  to  have 
the  sight  of  God — pueri  vellent  Divinam  visionem  habere  ; 


1  "In  aliis  autem  perfectionibus  et 
bonitatibus  quac  naturam  humanam 
consequuntur  ex  suis  principiis,  nullum 


detrimentum  sustinebunt  pro  peccato 
original!  damnati."  —  In  Lonib.  1.  2, 
Dist.  33.  Q.  2.  A.  1. 


CHAP.  X.]  OF    PREDESTINATION.  309 

otherwise  their  wills  would  be  actually  perverse.  It  would 
therefore  appear,  that  this  want  or  loss  would  be  affliction  to 
them;  and  therefore,  that,  if  this  were  their  punishment, 
their  punishment  would  not  be  the  mildest  of  all  —  mitis- 
sima.  Nor,  adds  Aquinas,  is  it  any  answer  to  this  ob- 
jection to  say,  that  this  exclusion  does  not  arise  from  their 
own  personal  fault ;  for  immunity  from  blame  does  not 
diminish,  but  increase  the  pain  of  punishment :  or,  again, 
correct  to  say,  that  they  are  happy  because  they  do  not  know 
what  they  have  lost ;  for  the  soul  freed  from  the  burden  of 
the  body  must  know  whatever  reason  can  discover — et 
etiam  multo  plura. 

The  general  solution,  then,  of  this  difficulty,  is,  that  it  is 
no  pain  to  any  one  of  well-ordered  mind  not  to  have  that  to 
which  his  nature  is  in  no  way  proportioned,  provided  the 
want  is  not  owing  to  any  personal  fault  of  his  own.  A  nian 
regrets  the  disappointment  of  some  natural  want,  even 
though  he  is  not  to  blame  for  it ;  and  the  exclusion  from  a 
good  exceeding  nature,  if  he  is.  But  the  combination  of 
blanielessness  in  himself  and  excess  in  the  good  protects  him. 
Such  a  case  comes  under  the  rule  of  Seneca,  that  perturbation 
does  not  fall  on  the  wise  man  for  that  which  is  unavoidable; 
and  children  dying  under  original  sin  alone  are  wise  —  sed 
in  pueris  recta  est  ratio  nullo  actuali  peccato  obliquata.  They 
will  therefore  feel  no  more  pain  under  the  want  which 
attaches  to  their  condition,  than  a  reasonable  man  does 
because  he  cannot  fly  like  a  bird,  or  because  he  is  not  a  king 
or  an  emperor.  Rather  they  will  rejoice  in  their  share  of 
the  Divine  bounty,  and  in  the  natural  perfections  they  will 
have  attained.1 


1  Sicut  nullus  sapiens  homo  affligitur 
de  hoc  quod  non  potest  volare  sicut 
avis,  vel  quia  non  est  rex  vel  imperator; 
cum  sibi  non  sit  debitum.  .  .  .  Si  ab 
hoc  deficiant  (qui  liberum  arbitrium 
habent),  maximus  crit  dolor  eis  quia 
amittunt  illud  quod  suum  esse  possibile 


fuit.  Pueri  autem  nunquam  fuerunt 
proportionati  ad  hoc,  quod  vitam  aeter- 
nam  haberent,  quae  nee  eis  debebatur  ex 
principiis  naturae,  nee  actus  proprios 
habere  potuerunt :  et  ideo  nihil  omnino 
dolebunt  de  carentia  divine  visionis: 
immo  magis  gaudebunt  de  hoc  quod 


x   3 


310 


SCHOLASTIC    DOCTRINE 


[CHAP.  X. 


It  will  be  seen  that  the  whole  of  this  elaborate  position 
rests  upon  a  particular  interpretation  of  original  sin  ;  viz., 
as  a  privation  or  loss  of  perfection,  and  not  a  positive  evil. 
Having  constructed  his  system  on  the  strict  Augustinian 
sense  of  original  sin,  Aquinas  falls  back  on  the  Clementine 
when  he  comes  to  an  individual  case ;  and  avails  himself  of 
the  milder  theology  of  the  early  fathers.  Such  a  position, 
however,  when  once  laid  down  in  the  case  of  infants  dying 
under  original  sin,  evidently  cannot  stop  short  of  a  much 
wider  application.  Man  is  the  same,  as  regards  his  nature, 
whether  he  dies  as  an  infant  or  grows  up  to  maturity ;  and 
therefore  the  whole  condition  of  the  natural  man,  whether 
heathen  or  professedly  Christian,  is  involved  in  this  conclusion, 
and  may  demand  admission  to  the  benefit  of  that  explanation 
which  the  particular  case  of  infants  has  evoked.  The  life 
which  is  conducted  upon  principles  of  honesty,  justice,  and 
reason,  though  it  be  not  upon  that  of  Christian  faith, —  the 
morality  of  the  conscientious  man  of  the  world, — in  a  word, 
the  well  ordered  natural  life,  though  below  the  spiritual, 
may  claim  not  to  be  condemned.  And  while  the  formal 
theology  of  the  Augustinian  allows  no  interval  between 
the  child  of  God  and  the  child  of  the  devil,  the  faithful 
and  the  unbelieving,  the  spiritual  and  the  carnal  man,  and 
their  respective  ends,  eternal  happiness  and  eternal  misery ; 
a  modification  of  the  meaning  of  a  term,  in  one  par- 
ticular case,  undermines  in  principle  this  whole  division; 
punishment  reduced  from  its  positive  to  a  merely  negative 


participabunt  multum  de  divina  boni- 
tate,  et  perfectionibus  naturalibus. — 
In  Lomb.  A.  2. 

The  question  came  up  in  the  disputes 
at  the  Council  of  Trent,  in  which  the 
majority  appear  to  have  favoured  the 
position  of  Aquinas ;  but  not  without 
distinctions  ;  "  For  the  Dominicans 
said  that  the  children  dead  without 
baptism  before  the  use  of  reason 
remain  after  the  resurrection  in  a  limbo 


and  darkness  under  the  earth,  but 
without  fire;  the  Franciscans  say  they 
are  to  remain  upon  the  earth,  and  in 
light.  Some  affirmed  also,  .that  they 
should  be  philosophers,  busying  them- 
selves in  natural  things,  not  without 
that  greatest  pleasure  which  happeneth 
when  curiosity  is  satisfied  by  invention." 
— Paul's  History  of  the  Council  of 
Trent. 


CHAP.  X.]  OF    PREDESTINATION.  311 

and  privative  sense,  becomes  another  word  for  a  lower 
reward,  and  admits  to  a  valuable  and  a  substantial,  though 
not  the  highest,  happiness,  both  in  this  life  and  the  next, 
that  not  inconsiderable  portion  of  mankind  who  are  moral 
without  being  spiritual,  well  disposed  without  faith,  and 
reasonable  without  illumination. 

It  may  be  added,  that  the  difficulty  involved  in  these 
considerations  is  one  which  meets  us  on  either  theory,  that  of 
necessity  or  of  freewill.  The  necessitarianism  indeed  of  Aqui- 
nas marks  the  natural  and  the  spiritual  life  alike  as  creations 
of  God ;  but  however  we  may  account  for  them,  the  natural 
life  and  the  spiritual  life,  in  the  sense  in  which  they  have 
been  spoken  of,  exist  as  facts  in  the  world ;  and  we  see  these 
two  moral  classes  and  types  around  us.  Scripture  speaks 
indeed,  speaks  only  of  a  way  which  leadeth  to  life,  and  a 
way  which  leadeth  to  salvation ;  and  separates  the  few  who 
attain  to  eternal  glory  from  a  wicked  world.  But  it  must 
be  confessed  that,  when  we  look  at  the  world  around  us,  the 
application  of  the  truth  of  Scripture  is  not  free  from  diffi- 
culty, and  that  it  depends  much  on  the  frame  of  mind  which 
we  assume,  and  the  point  of  view  which  we  adopt,  whether 
society  at  large  most  aptly  confirms  the  scriptural  position, 
or  apparently  contradicts  it.  In  one  aspect  all  is  mixture 
and  balance  in  the  world  of  moral  life  around  us, — a  nicely 
graduated  scale  of  human  character,  division  gliding  into 
division,  and  shade  deepening  or  softening  into  shade. 
Men  are  such  combinations  of  good  and  evil,  that  we  hardly 
know  where  to  place  them ;  and  a  large  portion  of  the  world 
seems  to  occupy  a  middle  place,  in  opposition  to  the  twofold 
destination  of  mankind  in  Scripture  to  glory  on  the  one 
hand,  and  misery  on  the  other.  The  idea  of  a  middle  state 
luis  thus  always  recommended  itself  more  or  less  as  a  con- 
jecture to  human  thought;  and  a  tendency  to  this  doctrine, 
even  where  not  formally  expressed,  is  observable  in  all 
ages  of  the  Church  ;  nor,  so  long  as  the  facts  of  the  world 
around  us  remain  the  same,  will  it  be  otherwise.  In  another 

x    4 


312  SCHOLASTIC   DOCTRINE  [CHAP.  X. 

aspect  the  world  presents  itself  to  our  minds  in  harmony 
with  the  scriptural  division,  as  consisting  of  the  good  few 
and  the  wicked  and  depraved  mass ;  vice,  selfishness,  and 
corruption  appearing  tike  general  rule,  to  which  the  disin- 
terestedness or  genuine  goodness  of  a  select  number  is  the 
exception.  The  wickedness  of  the  world  is  thus  a  recognised 
maxim  in  the  world  itself;  and  is  one  of  the  deepest 
sentiments  of  the  human  mind,  whose  universal  judgment 
one  wise  man  of  even  heathen  times  expressed  in  the  great 
proverb. 

In  this  state  of  the  case  it  is  needless  to  add,  that  the 
plain  statements  of  Scripture  on  this  subject  are  to  be  im- 
plicitly received,  as  containing  certain  and  important  truth. 
One  great  division  of  mankind  is  seen  there,  that  of  good  and 
bad;  one  great  distinction  of  eternal  lot,  that  of  heaven 
and  hell.     It  remains  that  those  who  have  received  this  re- 
velation should  act  accordingly,  and,  instead  of  forming  con- 
jectures about  a  middle  state,  live  as  for  the  highest.     Those 
who  accept  a  revelation  generally  are  bound  in  consistency 
to  accept  its  plain  assertions  in  particulars;  nor  does  this 
obligation  cease  because  difficulties  may  follow.     Those  who 
accept  a  revelation  accept  in  doing  so  a  limitation  to  the 
rights  of  human  reason.     There  are  great  and  important  dif- 
ferences in  the  Christian  world  as  to  the  point  at  which  such 
limitation  comes  in ;   but  whether  traditional  interpretation 
of  Scripture,  or  a  present  infallible  one,  or  the  letter  of  the 
Bible  itself  is  the  check,  a  check  to  private  judgment  is  implied 
in  the  very  fact  of  a  revelation,  and  is  the  common  admission 
of  all  who  accept  that  revelation;  who  so  far — and  a  very 
important  and  vital  measure  of  agreement  it  is  —  agree  with 
each  other.  But  when  men  have  accepted  the  check  in  general, 
they  must  submit  to  it  in  the  particular   case.     There  is 
no  obligation  indeed   on  any  one  to  think  any  individual 
either  better  or  worse    than  his  observation  or  knowledge 
of  his  character  warrants ;  rather  he  is  bound  not  to  do  so : 
nor,  because    general   statements    are    made   in    Scripture 


CHAP.  X.]  OP   PREDESTINATION.  313 

are  we  bound  to  apply  them,  and  bring  particular  persons 
under  one  head  or  another.  An  impenetrable  veil  hides 
the  heart  of  one  man  from  another,  and  we  see  the  mani- 
festation, but  not  the  substance,  of^the  moral  creature.  In 
the  application,  then,  of  the  scriptural  assertion  all  is  mystery 
and  uncertainty;  but  the  statement  itself  is  clear  and  distinct ; 
and  while  that  dispensation  of  ignorance  under  which  we 
are  placed,  in  mercy  as  well  as  discipline,  relieves  us  from 
the  difficulties  of  the  individual  case,  the  general  truth  is 
calculated  to  produce  the  most  salutary  effect  upon  us. 


314 


CHAP.  XL 

CONCLUSION. 

IT  were  to  be  wished  that  that  active  penetration  and  close 
and  acute  attention  which  mankind  have  applied  to  so  many 
subjects  of  knowledge,  and  so  successfully,  had  been  applied, 
in  somewhat  greater  proportion  than  it  has  been,  to  the  due 
apprehension  of  that  very  important  article  of  knowledge,  their 
own  ignorance.  Not  that  all  men  have  not  acknowledged, 
and  in  some  sense  perceived,  this  truth.  How,  indeed,  could 
they  avoid  doing  so  ?  But  over  and  above  this  general  and 
vague  confession  of  ignorance,  it  might  have  been  expected, 
perhaps,  that  more  would  have  attained,  than  appear  to  have 
done,  to  something  like  an  accurate  or  philosophical  per- 
ception of  it;  such  as  arises  from  the  mind's  contemplation 
and  examination  of  itself,  and  its  own  perceptions ;  a 
scrutiny  into  its  own  insight  into  truth,  and  a  com- 
parison of  the  different  modes  in  which  it  perceives  and 
entertains  truth ;  which  modes  or  kinds  of  perception  widely 
differ,  and  being  with  respect  to  some  truths,  distinct, 
complete,  and  absolute,  are  with  respect  to  others  dim, 
confused,  and  imperfect.  To  judge  from  the  way  in  which 
people  in  general  express  themselves  on  this  subject  of  human 
ignorance,  they  have  no  very  accurate  perception  of  it; 
seldom  going  out  of  certain  commonplace  phrases  and  forms 
of  speech,  —  forms  of  speech,  indeed,  which  mean  much  when 
used  by  those  who  see  their  true  meaning,  but  mean  much 
less,  though  still  perhaps  something,  when  used  vaguely 
and  without  attention,  and  because  the  whole  thing  is  taken 
for  granted  immediately,  and  then  dismissed  from  the  mind. 
This  general  admission  and  confession  of  the  fact,  is  all  that 
the  mass  of  men  appear  to  attain  to  on  this  important 


CHAP.  XI.]  CONCLUSION.  315 

question;  and  doubtless  it  is,  as  far  as  it  goes,  a  useful  and 
serviceable  conclusion  of  the  mind — especially  in  the  case  of 
devout  persons,  whose  piety  compensates  for  the  want  of 
clearness  in  their  ideas,  and  sustains  in  them  a  perpetual 
practical  perception  of  this  truth,  together  with  its  natural 
fruits  of  humility,  sobriety,  and  resignation. 

But  though  it  is  undoubtedly  a  matter  of  regret  that  more 
should  not  have  attained,  than  appear  to  have  done,  to  some- 
thing like  an  accurate  and  philosophical  perception  of  their 
own  ignorance ;  the  explanation  of  this  fact  is  contained  in 
the  very  statement  of  it,  as  just  given.     For  this  deeper  per- 
ception cannot  be  gained,  but  by  those  minds  that  have  gone 
through  something  of  that  process  of  thought,  which  has  been 
just  referred  to.     Men  must  have  reflected  upon  themselves, 
and  examined  to  a  certain  extent  the  constitution  of  their  own 
minds,  their  perceptions,  or  modes  of  entertaining  truth,  in 
order  to  have  gained  it.     But  this  internal  department  is  not 
one  in  which  any  large  proportion  of  men  take  much  interest ; 
and  a  taste  for  this  kind  of  inspection  is  perhaps  rarer  than 
any  other, — I  mean  as  a  taste  seriously  and  regularly  adopted, 
and  made  a  work  of.    Many  indeed  start  with  something  like 
a  general  taste  or  a  fancy  for  metaphysics,  which  they  indulge 
so  long  as  it  gives  them  little  trouble,  and  merely  ministers  to 
pleasing  vague  sensations  of  depth,  and  love  of  the  unknown 
and  indefinite ;  affording  a  domain  for  dreamy  and  vaporous 
evolutions  of  thought,  cloudy  connections,  and  fictitious  ascents 
of  the  intellect,  —  reasonings  somewhat  akin  to  what  people 
carry  on  in  sleep,  and  pursued  as  a  mere  diversion  and  vent 
to,  rather  than  an  exercise  of,  the  mind.     But  the  taste  is 
given  up  as  soon  as  they  have  to  examine  facts,  to  fasten 
their  ideas  upon  real  things,  —  real  truths  within  the  actual 
mind, —  for    the    purpose  of  apprehension  and  knowledge. 
This  internal  field  of  examination,  I  say,  is  not  to  the  taste 
of  any   large  proportion  of  minds;   because    it    requires  a 
more  patient  sort  of  attention,  a  more  enduring  and  passive 
attitude  of  the  whole  mind,  than  is  ordinarily  congenial  to 


316  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XT 

the  human  temper.     The   act  necessary  here  is  an  act  of 
simple  internal  observation,  which,  while  it  is  a  very  difficult 
one  in   this  particular  department,  owing  to  the  obscurity 
and  subtlety  of  its   subject  matter,  is   at  the  same  time  a 
quiet  one;    for  quiet  is  essential  to    secure   correctness  of 
observation  in  metaphysics  as  in   nature.      But   this  com- 
bination is  a  distasteful  one  to. most  minds.     In  life,  prac- 
tical or  intellectual,  the  general  compensation  for  difficulty 
is   the  pleasure  of  action;  for   passiveness,  that  of  repose. 
The    energetic    man    delights  in  obstacles  which   summon 
forth  all  his  powers  and  put  them  into  active  operation ; 
the  labour  is  forgotten  in  the  satisfaction  of  exertion,  and 
the  legitimate  play  and  excitement  of  the  whole   system 
carry  off  the  task,  and  convert   it  into  a  pleasure.       The 
natural  activity  of  the  human  mind,  again,  so  opposed  to  the 
passive  attitude  ordinarily,  puts  up  with  it  at  certain  intervals, 
for  the  sake  of  rest,  and  enjoys  it.     But  difficulty  with  pas- 
siveness, is  uncongenial.     We  want  always,  when  we  are  at 
work,  to  feel  ourselves  in  progress,  in  action,  advancing  step 
after  step ;  and  the  attitude  of  standing  still  in  thought,  though 
it  be  for  an  important  result,  though  it  be  consciously  only 
a  waiting  in  readiness  to  catch  some  idea  when  it  may  turn 
up,  is,  for  the  time  that  it  is  such  a  waiting,  and  previous  to 
its  reward,  a  painful  void  and  hollowness  of  the  mind.     But 
such  is  the  attitude  which   is  required  for   true  analytical 
thought,    or    the    mind's    examination   of  itself.     For   the 
ideas  which  are  the  contents  of  that  inward  world,  wandering 
in  and  out  of  darkness,  emerging  for  an  instant  and  then  lost 
again,  and  carried  about  to  and  fro  in  the  vast  obscure,  are 
too  subtle  and  elusive  to  be  subject  matter  of  regular  and 
active  pursuit ;  but  must  be  waited  and  watched  for,  with 
strength  suspended  and  sustained  in  readiness  to  catch  and 
fasten  on  them  when  they  come  within  reach  ;  but  the  exer- 
tion being  that  of  suspended  and  sustained,  rather  than  of 
active  and  employed,  strength.     And  if  this  line  of  thought 
in  general  is  opposed  to  the  tastes  of  the  mass,  so  that  even 


CHAP.  XI.]  CONCLUSION.  317 

a  moderate  degree  of  application  to  it  is  too  much  for 
them,  and  even  that  lower  insight  into  this  department  of 
truth,  which  minds  of  average  ability  may  gain,  is  a  part  of 
knowledge  into  which  they  are  not  admitted, — by  what  a 
wide  and  immeasurable  interval  are  they  separated  from  the 
great  analytical  minds  which  have  appeared  in  the  world, 
who,  with  unwearied  patience  and  keen  exertion  of  the  intel- 
lectual eye,  have  caught  sharp  glimpses  of  the  great  ideas  and 
processes  of  the  human  reason, — quick  and  momentary  sights, 
which,  impressed  by  their  vividness  upon  the  memory,  and 
thence  transferred  to  paper,  have  enabled  them  in  a  certain 
sense  to  bring  the  human  mind  to  light,  to  mark  its  main 
outlines,  and  distinguish  its  different  perceptions  or  ideas  ;  by 
which  genuine  and  authentic  originals  they  have  then  tested 
current  popular  and  second-hand  truths. 

This,  then,  is  the  reason  why  more  have  not  attained  than 
have  to  an  accurate  perception  of  their  own  ignorance  as 
human  creatures.  For  this  correcter  and  truer  perception 
of  ignorance  is  the  correlative  of  a  correcter  and  truer 
knowledge.  Of  the  human  mind  there  is  a  luminous  and 
there  is  a  dark  side.  The  luminous  side  is  that  on  which 
it  clearly  perceives  and  apprehends  truths,  either  by  simple 
apprehension,  or  by  demonstrative  reasoning :  the  dark  side 
is  that  on  which  it  does  not  perceive  in  either  of  these  two 
ways ;  but  either  does  not  see  at  all,  and  has  a  blank  before 
it,  or  has  only  an  incipient  and  indistinct  sight,  not  amount- 
ing to  perception  or  apprehension.1  In  proportion,  then, 
to  the  acuteness  with  which  the  mind  perceives  truth,  either 
by  apprehension  or  by  demonstration,  on  its  luminous  side, 
in  that  proportion  it  sees  the  defect  of  perception  on  its 
dark  side.  The  clearness  of  knowledge,  where  it  is  had, 
reveals  and  exposes  by  the  contrast  its  absence,  where  it 
is  not  had ;  and  the  transition  from  light  heightens  the 


See  Chapter  II. 


318  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XT. 

obscurity.  Each  successive  step  of  demonstrative  reasoning, 
by  which  a  problem  in  mathematics  is  proved,  from  the 
first  up  to  the  conclusion,  is  accomplished  by  means  of  a 
certain  light  contained  within  it — an  overpowering  light, 
to  which  the  mind  succumbs,  unable  to  resist  its  penetrating 
force,  but  pierced  through  by  it,  as  by  lightning.  Even 
that  elementary  and  primary  piece  of  demonstrative  rea- 
soning which  is  called  an  axiom, — that  first  inference  or 
extraction  of  one  truth  from  another,  which,  in  the  depart- 
ment of  demonstration,  we  are  called  upon  to  make, — is 
accomplished  by  means  of  such  a  vivid  and  penetrating  light 
contained  within  it ;  so  that  the  perception  of  the  simplest 
axiom,  where  such  perception  is  a  true  and  not  a  formal 
one,  is,  by  reason  of  this  perfection  of  light  in  it,  an  illumina- 
tion for  the  time  of  the  whole  intellect,  and  may  be  regarded 
as  a  kind  of  natural  inspiration,  answering  to  passion  or 
emotion  in  moral  life.  In  proportion,  then,  to  the  keenness 
with  which  this  process  goes  on,  is  the  reaction  from  it ; 
after  the  clearness  of  sight  the  change  is  all  the  greater 
to  its  dimness  and  indistinctness ;  and  the  reason  turning, 
while  full  of  penetrating  light  from  one  side,  upon  the 
darkness  of  the  other,  receives,  as  it  were,  a  shock,  by  the 
violence  of  the  contrast.  The  difference  between  seeing 
truth  and  not  seeing  it,  between  knowledge  and  ignorance, 
is  felt  in  a  degree  and  manner  in  which  those  who  have 
not  attained  such  sight  or  knowledge,  cannot  feel  it. 
The  analytical  class  of  intellects  that,  not  satisfied  with 
the  vague  first- sight  impressions  and  notions  of  things, 
follow  them  up  to  that  ultimate  point  at  which  they  are 
plainly  seen  to  be  either  true  or  false,—  that  draw  the 
contents  of  the  mind  from  their  obscurity  to  the  test  of 
an  actual  examination, —  that  see  clearly  the  truth  they 
do  see,  whether  as  simply  apprehended,  or  as  extracted  from 
other  truth; — these  minds,  in  proportion  to  the  keenness 
with  which  they  are  conscious  of  perceiving  truth,  when 
they  do  perceive  it,  know  that  they  have  got  hold  of  it,  and 


CHAP.  XI.]  CONCLUSION.  319 

that  no  power  can  wrest  it  from  them, — in  proportion,  i.e.  to 
the  measure  in  which,  in  the  department  of  knowledge, 
they  are  filled  with  the  light  of  clear  apprehension  or 
demonstrative  reasoning, —  see  the  distinction  between  this 
mode  of  perception  and  that  which  awaits  them  when 
they  leave  the  scientific  ground,  and  turn  from  the  truths 
of  knowledge  to  those  of  faith  and  of  religion.  They  see, 
in  consequence  of  their  appreciation  of  final  truth,  so  much 
the  more  clearly  the  defect  of  that  which  is  not  final ; 
and  that  which  has  come  to  a  point  contrasts  the  more 
strongly,  with  that  which  comes  to  none,  but  which 
vanishes  and  is  gone  before  it  reaches  a  conclusion;  ever 
beginning,  ever  tending  to  some  goal,  but  never  attaining 
it ;  stopping  short,  as  it  does,  at  its  very  starting,  and, 
in  the  very  act  of  progress,  absorbed  in  the  atmosphere 
of  obscurity,  which  limits  our  mental  view.  Then,  under 
the  influence  of  such  a  contrast,  it  is,  that,  the  reason  pauses, 
stops  to  consider,  to  reflect,  and  then  says  to  itself — this  is 
ignorance. 

And  these  considerations,  while  they  serve  to  explain 
why  more  have  not  attained  to  an  accurate  knowledge  of 
their  own  ignorance,  as  human  creatures,  than  appear  to 
have  done,  serve,  also,  to  temper  our  regret  at  such  a 
deficiency  ;  for  it  must  be  seen,  on  the  bare  description  of 
such  a  deep  and  peculiar  perception  of  ignorance  as  I  am 
now  referring  to,  that  it  is  a  state  of  mind  not  unattended  by 
danger.  No  perception  of  ignorance,  indeed,  however  strong, 
can  be  charged  with  an}  legitimate  tendency  to  produce 
unbelief;  for  it  does  not  follow  that,  because  we  see  some 
truths  clearly  and  others  obscurely,  some  finally  and  others  in- 
completely and  but  in  commencement,  that  therefore  we  may 
not  hold  these  latter  truths  so  far,  however  little  way  that 
may  be,  as  we  do  perceive  them,  and  accept  and  use  them  in 
that  sense  and  manner  in  which  we  find  our  minds  able  to 
entertain  them.  And  thus  the  truths  of  natural  and  revealed 
religion,  incomprehensible  as  they  are,  are  proper  subject 


320  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XI. 

matter  of  belief.  Our  minds  are  constituted  in  such  a  way, 
as  that  we  can  entertain  this  class  of  truths,  which  are  not 
subject  matter  of  knowledge,  and  yet  fall  under  some  indis- 
tinct sort  of  perception,  which  we  feel  properly  to  belong  to 
us.  To  reject  them,  then,  because  they  are  seen  imperfectly 
and  obscurely,  and  because  we  have  the  light  of  clear  ap- 
prehension and  demonstration  in  one  department,  to  claim 
it,  and  be  content  with  nothing  else  in  another,  would  be 
simply  unreasonable.  The  deeper  sense  of  ignorance,  then, 
has  no  legitimate  tendency  to  lessen  belief  in  the  truths 
of  natural  and  revealed  religion:  more  than  this,  it  has 
legitimately  even  a  direct  tendency  to  strengthen  it ;  because 
the  sense  of  ignorance  tends  properly  to  produce  humility, 
to  subdue,  chasten,  and  temper  the  mind.  The  natural 
result  of  seeing  how  poor  and  imperfect  creatures  we  are, 
and  how  small  and  limited  our  capacities,  is  to  lower  our 
idea  of  ourselves,  and  so  to  put  us  into  a  frame,  in  which  we 
are  the  more  ready  to  accept  and  use  whatever  measure  and 
kind  of  truth  we  may  possess  in  this  department.  But  it 
must  also,  on  the  other  side,  be  admitted,  that  there  is  a 
natural  tendency,  in  such  a  strong  contrast  as  that  which  has 
been  described,  to  overwhelm  that  class  of  truths  which  has 
the  disadvantage  in  it ;  and  that  minds  which  turn,  full  of 
the  clear  light  of  apprehension  and  reasoning,  upon  the 
obscurity  of  the  truths  of  faith,  will  be  apt  to  suppose  that 
they  see  nothing  because  they  do  not  see  clearly,  and  that 
they  have  a  simple  blank  before  them.  And  the  natural 
impatience  of  the  human  temper  will  much  aid  such  a  con- 
clusion ;  for  men  are  apt  to  see  everything  in  extremes,  and 
when  they  have  less  than  what  they  want,  are  instantly 
inclined  to  think  that  they  have  nothing.  In  this  temper, 
then,  men  set  down  the  ideas  belonging  to  religion,  as  not 
only  indistinct,  but  as  no  ideas  at  all,  but  mere  void ;  and 
urge  that  persons  are  under  a  mistake  in  supposing  that  they 
have  anything  really  in  their  minds  when  they  profess  to 
entertain  these  truths, —  not  having,  as  it  is  asserted,  any 


CHAP.  XL]  CONCLUSION.  321 

idea  of  them.  In  this  way,  then,  the  deeper  perception  of 
ignorance  tends  to  lessen  belief  in  the  truths  of  religion; 
inclining  persons  to  set  them  aside  altogether  as  truths  from 
which  our  understandings  are  entirely  separated  by  an  im- 
passable barrier,  and  with  which,  therefore,  as  lying  wholly 
outside  of  us,  we  have  no  concern.1 

Such  being,  then,  the  two  arguments  from  human  ignorance, 
the  two  modes  of  using  and  applying  the  fact,  the  question 
is,  supposing  the  mass  of  men  had  that  distinct  and  clear 
perception  of  their  ignorance  which  analytical  minds  acquire, 
how  would  they  use  it  ?  would  they  use  it  for  the  purpose 
of  deepening  their  humility,  chastising  their  curiosity,  sub- 
duing their  impatience  ?  would  they  frame  themselves  upon 
a  pattern  of  intellectual  submission  and  be  grateful  for  such 
a  measure  of  insight  into  religious  truths  as  God  had  given 
them  ?  or  would  they  use  and  apply  it  in  the  other  way,  and, 
struck  simply  by  the  force  of  the  contrast  between  their 
knowledge  in  one  department  and  their  ignorance  in  another, 
draw  from  it  the  impatient  inference,  that  because  they  did 
not  see  these  truths  clearly,  they  did  not  see  them  at  all, 
and  were  rationally  disconnected  with  them  ?  It  is  to 
be  feared  that  the  natural  impatience  of  the  human  mind 
would,  in  the  majority  of  instances,  lean  to  the  latter  infer- 
ence. It  is  indeed  true,  and  it  is  a  cheering  and  consolatory 
fact,  that  we  see  a  broad  division  among  the  great  analytical 
minds  on  this  head ;  and  that  while  some  have  drawn  the 
argument  for  unbelief  from  the  fact  of  human  ignorance, 
others  have  drawn  from  it  the  argument  for  faith ;  that  to 
Hume  and  Hobbes  on  the  one  side  we  may  oppose  Butler  and 
Pascal  on  the  other.  But  could  we  expect  that  the  gene- 
rality of  men  would  exert  that  intellectual  self-discipline 
which  these  devout  and  reverential  minds  did?  Would 
not  natural  impatience  rather  prevail,  and  the  more  imme- 


1  This  appears  to  have  been  Hume's  state  of  mind  with  respect  to  religious 
truths. 


322  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XT. 

diate  and  obvious  effect  of  a  contrast  be  yielded  to  ?  And 
if  so,  are  not  the  generality  of  men  spared  a  severe  trial, 
with  probably  an  unfavourable  issue,  in  not  having  in  the 
first  instance  this  deeper  sense  of  ignorance  at  all  ?  Is  not 
their  ignorance  veiled  in  mercy  from  them  by  a  kind  Pro- 
vidence ;  so  that,  with  respect  to  these  truths,  they  go  on  for 
their  whole  lives,  thinking  they  know  a  great  deal  more  than 
they  do?  Nor  does  this  apply  to  the  uninstructed  and 
uncultivated  part  of  mankind  only,  but  perhaps  even  more 
strongly  to  the  learned  and  controversial  class.  For,  cer- 
tainly, to  hear  the  way  in  which  some  of  this  class  argue, 
and  draw  inferences  from  the  incomprehensible  truths  of 
revelation,  carrying  them,  as  they  say,  into  their  consequences 
and  logical  results,  upon  which,  however  remote  and  far- 
fetched, they  yet  insist,  as  if  they  were  of  the  very  substance 
of  the  primary  truth  itself; — to  judge,  I  say,  from  the  long 
and  fine  trains  of  inferences  drawn  by  some  theologians  from 
mysterious  doctrines, — endless  distinctions  spun  one  out  of 
the  other  in  succession,  and  issuing  in  subtleties  which  baffle 
all  comprehension,  and  are,  in  short,  mere  words  and  nothing 
more,  but  for  which,  so  long  as  at  each  successive  step  there 
has  been  an  inference  (or  something  which  to  the  contro- 
versially wound-up  intellect  or  fancy  at  the  time  appeared 
such), — these  persons  claim  the  most  absolute  deference;  as 
if  some  subtlest  conception  of  the  argumentative  brain,  some 
needle's  point  so  inconceivably  minute,  that  not  one  man  in 
ten  thousand  could  even  see  it  once  if  he  tried  for  his  whole 
life,  were  of  the  very  foundation  of  the  faith ; — :  to  judge,  I  say, 
from  such  a  mode  of  arguing  from  religious  truths,  one 
cannot  avoid  two  reflections ;  one,  that  such  persons  do  not 
know  their  own  ignorance;  the  other,  that  it  is  probably 
a  mercy  to  them  that  they  do  not.  They  do  not  know  their 
own  ignorance  with  respect  to  these  truths ;  for  if  they 
did,  they  would  see  that  such  incomprehensible  truths  were 
not  known  premisses,  and  could  not  be  argued  upon  as  such, 
or  made  foundation  of  unlimited  inference  :  and  that  they  do 


CHAP.  XI.]  CONCLUSION.  323 

not  know  it  is  probably  a  mercy  to  them ;  for  the  very  same 
hasty  and  audacious  temper  of  the  intellect  which  leads  them 
to  build  so  much  upon  assumptions,  the  nature  of  which  they 
have  never  examined,  would,  had  they  examined  it,  and  so  ar- 
rived at  a  real  perception  of  their  unknown  nature,  have  in- 
clined them  to  reject  such  truths.  Thus,  in  compassion  to 
the  infirmity  of  man,  a  merciful  Providence  hides  his  igno- 
rance from  him ;  and  by  a  kind  deceit,  such  as  parents  use  to 
their  children,  allows  him  to  suppose  that  he  knows  what 
he  does  not  know.  He  is  thus  saved  from  unbelief,  and  only 
falls  into  a  well-meaning,  though  foolish  and  presumptuous, 
dogmatism. 

And  now,  to  bring  these  remarks  to  bear  on  the  subject 
of  this  treatise,  the  question  of  Divine  grace  is  a  question 
of  Divine  Power.  Grace  is  power.  That  power  whereby 
God  works  in  nature  is  called  power.  That  power  whereby 
He  works  in  the  wills  of  His  reasonable  creatures  is  called 


With  respect,  then,  to  the  attribute  of  the  Divine  Power, 
S.  Augustine  and  his  school  took  up,  in  the  first  instance,  a 
hasty  and  ill-considered  position,  which,  once  adopted,  com- 
mitted them  to  extreme  and  repulsive  results.  And  the 
reason  of  their  adopting  such  a  position  was,  that  they  were 
insufficiently  acquainted  with  the  limits  of  human  reason. 
For  it  must  be  evident  to  any  person  of  reflection,  that  a 
want  of  discernment  on  this  subject  is  not  only  an  error  in 
itself,  but  can  hardly  fail  to  be  the  source  of  other  errors ; 
because  persons  who  entertain  a  certain  idea  with  respect  to 
their  knowledge,  naturally  proceed  to  act  upon  it  and  to 
make  assertions ;  and  it  must  be  a  chance  whether  assertions 
made  under  such  circumstances  are  correct.  I  would  not  be 
understood,  however,  to  cast  any  blame  upon  these  writers. 
The  limits  of  human  reason  are  not  easy  to  discern.  It  is 
not  easy,  as  I  have  said,  to  judge  our  own  pretensions,  and 
distinguish  between  one  part  and  another  of  that  whole  body 
of  ideas  and  assumptions  which  we  find  within  our  minds. 

Y    2 


324  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XT. 

Some  philosophers  have  settled  the  question  summarily,  by 
saying  that  we  know  nothing;  others  have  extended  the 
range  of  human  knowledge  indefinitely,  and  given  it  a  right 
to  decide  upon  the  possibilities  of  things,  and  to  judge  the 
scheme  of  Providence.  To  draw  the  mean  between  these  two 
extremes  is  the  work  of  an  acute  and  original  judgment,  and 
requires  a  peculiar  constitution  of  mind.  The  tendency  of 
even  deep  and  able  minds  generally  is  so  immediately  to  fas- 
ten on  any  assumption,  especially  any  one  relating  to  divine 
things,  which  appears  at  first  sight  a  natural  one  to  them, 
that  their  very  power  becomes  a  snare,  and  before  they  have 
reflected  upon  an  idea  they  are  committed  to  it ;  so  that  to 
return  to  the  preliminary  question  of  its  truth  would  be  in 
the  highest  degree  difficult  to  them,  as  being  so  offensive  to 
an  already  formed  bias.  Indeed,  some  minds  of  great  pre- 
tensions appear  to  labour  under  a  moral  inability  in  this 
respect;  their  intellect,  strong  in  pursuing  an  idea,  is  so 
utterly  unable  to  stop  itself  for  the  purpose  of  judgment, 
that  in  reference  to  that  particular  function  it  may  be  said 
to  have  almost  the  imperfection  of  a  mere  instinct,  rather 
than  to  operate  as  the  true  faculty  of  reason*  This  mixture 
of  singular  weakness  with  singular  power  it  is  which  makes 
the  task  of  estimating  authorities  so  difficult;  opinions  of 
the  greatest  value  on  details  and  collateral  points  being 
sometimes  of  the  very  least  on  fundamental  questions,  or 
those  concerned  with  the  soundness  or  unsoundness  of  original 
assumptions.  Yet  assumptions  and  particular  dicta,  laid  down 
in  the  first  instance  by  minds  of  this  latter  class,  have  had 
great  weight  and  a  long  reign  in  the  world ;  one  writer  taking 
them  up  after  another ;  till  some  person  of  original  powers 
of  judgment  has  risen  up  who,  on  comparing  an  assertion 
carefully  with  his  own  knowledge,  has  discovered  a  want  of 
connection  between  the  two.  He  has  not  seen  such  truth 
included  within  that  field  of  apprehended  truth,  set  out  and 
divided  from  that  of  conjecture,  in  his  mind;  and  this 
negative  discovery  once  made,  has,  like  other  discoveries, 
approved  itself  to  the  world,  people  seeing  it  when  it  was 


CHAP.  XI.]  CONCLUSION.  325 

pointed  out  to  them.  Such  a  judgment  passed  upon  any 
important  set  of  assumptions  is  a  discovery  in  philosophy ; 
and  in  this  respect  modern  philosophy  has  improved  much 
upon  the  ancient.  It  has  given  us  an  acquaintance  with  the 
limits  of  human  reason  which  we  had  not  before,  and  has 
enabled  us  to  distinguish  more  accurately  what  we  know 
from  what  we  do  not  know,  what  we  can  say  from  what  we 
cannot,  on  some  important  questions ;  it  has  tested  the 
correctness  of  many  important  assumptions :  but  it  does  not 
follow  that  those  are  particularly  to  blame  who  wrote  before 
such  improvement  in  the  acquaintance  with  the  limits  of 
human  reason  took  place. 

On  this  definite  basis,  then,  and  with  the  great  disadvantage 
of  a  less  accurate  knowledge  of  the  limits  of  human  reason 
than  has  been  attained  in  more  recent  times,  S.  Augustine 
and  his  school  proceeded  to  the  general  question  of  the  Divine 
Omnipotence.  And  they  commenced  with  an  assumption, 
which  no  modern  philosopher  would  allow,  that  the  Divine 
Power  must  be  an  absolutely  unlimited  thing.  That  the 
Divine  Power  is  not  liable  to  any  foreign  control  is  a 
principle  which  every  one  must  admit  who  believes  properly 
in  a  Deity ;  but  that  there  is  no  intrinsic  limit  to  it  in  the 
possibilities  of  things  would  not  be  admitted,  in  the  present 
state  of  philosophy,  in  which  this  whole  subject  is  properly 
understood  to  be  out  of  the  range  of  human  reason.  The 
Divine  Omnipotence  must  be  admitted  practically  and  in 
every  sense  which  can  be  wanted  for  the  purpose  of  religion ; 
but  we  have  not  faculties  for  speculation  upon  its  real  nature. 
These  writers,  however,  insisted  on  an  unlimited  omnipotence, 
arguing  logically  upon  the  simple  word  or  abstract  idea,  that 
if  omnipotence  was  limited,  it  was  not  omnipotence.  And 
upon  this  assumption  they  went  on  to  assert  that  God  could, 
had  He  pleased,  have  created  a  better  universe  than  He  has ; 
a  universe  without  evil  and  without  sin ;  and  that,  sin 
existing  in  the  world,  He  could  by  His  simple  power  have 
removed  it,  and  have  changed  the  wills  of  all  wicked  men 

Y    3 


326  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XI. 

from  evil  to  good.  Upon  such  an  idea  of  the  Divine  Power, 
these  writers  were  indeed  somewhat  perplexed  for  an 
answer  to  the  objection  which  naturally  arose  to  the  Divine 
Goodness.  A  limit  supposed  to  the  possibilities  of  things 
is  indeed  an  impregnable  defence  to  the  theologian  on  this 
question ;  for  no  one  can  be  blamed  for  not  doing  that  which 
is  impossible.  But  if  this  limit  is  not  allowed,  and  if  God 
could  have  created  a  universe  with  all  the  advantages  of  the 
present  one  and  none  of  its  evils,  and  if,  when  moral  evil 
had  begun,  He  could  have  removed  it ;  it  is  certainly  very 
difficult  to  answer  the  question  why  He  did  not ;  for  we 
necessarily  attribute  consummate  benevolence  to  the  Deity. 
The  explanation  of  such  a  difficulty  on  the  principle  of  variety, 
that  evil  and  good  together,  with  their  respective  reward  and 
punishment,  redound  to  the  glory  of  God  more  than  good 
alone  of  itself  would  do,  is  futile  and  puerile.  Variety  is 
cceteris  paribus  an  advantage ;  and  we  praise  God's  natural 
creation,  not  only  because  it  is  good,  but  because  that  good 
is  various.  Nor  would  it  be  reasonable  to  object  to  different 
degrees  of  good  in  the  created  universe ;  to  complain  because 
the  earth  was  not  as  beautiful  all  over  as  it  is  at  its  most 
beautiful  part,  or  because  all  the  birds  of  the  air  have  not  the 
colours  of  the  tropical  birds;  or  even,  in  moral  life,  because 
all  have  not  the  same  moral  capabilities  or  power  of  attaining 
the  same  goodness.  But  when  it  comes  to  a  comparison, 
not  of  like  good  with  varied,  or  of  higher  good  with  lower, 
but  of  good  with  evil,  the  case  is  very  different. 

Upon  this  abstract  idea,  then,  of  the  Divine  Power,  as  an 
unlimited  power,  rose  up  the  Augustinian  doctrine  of  Pre- 
destination and  grace ;  while  upon  the  abstract  idea  of  free- 
will, as  an  unlimited  faculty,  rose  up  the  Pelagian  theory. 
Had  men  perceived,  indeed,  more  clearly  and  really  than  they 
have  done,  their  ignorance  as  human  creatures,  and  the  rela- 
tion in  which  the  human  reason  stands  to  the  great  truths 
involved  in  this  question,  they  might  have  saved  themselves 
the  trouble  of  this  whole  controversy.  They  would  have 


CHAP.  XI.]  CONCLUSION.  327 

seen  that  this  question  cannot  be  determined  absolutely,  one 
way  or  another ;  that  it  lies  between  two  great  contradictory 
truths,  neither  of  which  can  be  set  aside,  or  made  to  give 
way  to  the  other ;  two  opposing  tendencies  of  thought,  inherent 
in  the  human  mind,  which  go  on  side  by  side,  and  are  able 
to  be  held  and  maintained  together,  although  thus  opposite  to 
each  other,  because  they  are  only  incipient,  and  not  final  and 
complete  truths ;  —  the  great  truths,  I  mean,  of  the  Divine 
Power  on  the  one  side,  and  man's  freewill,  or  his  originality 
as  an  agent,  on  the  other.     And  this  is,  in  fact,  the  mode  in 
which  this  question  is  settled  by  the  practical  common  sense 
of  mankind.     For  what  do  the  common  phrases  employed  in 
ordinary  conversation  and  writing  upon  this  question  —  the 
popular  and  received  modes  of  deciding  it,  whenever  it  in- 
cidentally turns  up  —  amount  to  but  this  solution  ?     Such 
phrases,  I  mean,  as  that  we  must  hold  man's  freewill  together 
with  God's  foreknowledge  and  predestination,  although  we  do 
not  see  how  they  agree;  and  other  like  formulas  ?  Such  forms  of 
language  for  deciding  the  question  evidently  proceed  upon  the 
acknowledgment  of  two  contradictory  truths  on  this  subject, 
which  can  not  be  reconciled,  but  must  be  held  together  in  in- 
consistency.    They  imply  that  the  doctrine  of  predestination 
and  the  doctrine  of  freewill  are  both  true,  and  that  one  who 
would  hold  the  truth  must  hold  both.  The  plain  natural  reason 
of  mankind  is  thus  always  large  and  comprehensive;  not  afraid 
of  inconsistency,  but  admitting  all  truth  which  presents  itself 
to  its  notice.     It  is  only  when  minds  begin  to  philosophise 
that  they  grow  narrow, —  that  there  begins  to  be  felt  the 
appeal  to  consistency,  and  with  it  the  temptation  to  exclude 
truths.     Then  begins  the  pride  of  argument,  the  ingenuity 
of  construction,  the  "  carrying  out "  of  ideas  and  principles 
into  successive  consequences ;  which,  as  they  become  more 
and  more  remote,  and  leave  the  original  truth  at  a  distance, 
also  carry  the  mind  of  the  reasoner  himself  away  from  the 
first  and  natural  aspect  of  that  truth,  as  imperfect  and  partial, 
to  an  artificial  aspect  of  it  as  whole  and  exclusive.  While  the 

Y    4 


328  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XI. 

judgment,  however,  of  man's  plain  and  natural  reason  on  this 
question  is  a  comprehensive  one,  men  have,  on  this  as  on 
other  subjects,  left  the  ground  of  plain  and  simple  reason  for 
argument  and  philosophy ;  and  in  this  stage  of  things  they 
have  adopted  man's  freewill  or  the  Divine  Power  as  favourite 
and  exclusive  truths,  and  have  erected  systems  upon  them. 
The  Pelagian  and  Augustinian  systems  are  thus  both  at 
fault,  as  arising  upon  narrow,  partial,  and  exclusive  bases. 
But  while  both  systems  are  at  fault,  they  are  at  fault  in  very 
different  degrees  and  manners ;  and  while  the  Augustinian 
is  only  guilty  of  an  excess  in  carrying  out  certain  religious 
ideas,  the  Pelagian  offends  against  the  first  principles  of  re- 
ligion, and  places  itself  outside  of  the  great  religious  ideas 
and  instincts  of  the  human  race. 

I.  The  predestinarian  is  at  fault  in  assuming  either  the 
Divine  Power,  or  original  sin,  as  singly  and  of  itself  a  legiti- 
mate basis  of  a  system, — in  not  allowing  side  by  side  with  these 
premisses  a  counter  premiss  of  freewill  and  original  power 
of  choice.  While  he  properly  regards  the  created  will  as 
an  effect,  he  is  wrong  in  not  also  regarding  it  as  a  first 
cause  in  nature.  But  while  this  is  a  decided  error,  and  an 
error  which  has  dangerous  moral  tendencies  when  adopted 
by  undisciplined  minds,  it  is  not  in  itself  an  offence  against 
morals  or  piety.  The  predestinarian,  while  he  insists  on 
the  will's  determination  from  without,  still  allows  a  will ; 
he  does  not  regard  man  as  an  inanimate  machine,  but  as  a 
living,  willing,  and  choosing  creature.  And  as  he  admits  a 
will,  he  assigns  in  every  respect  the  same  moral  nature  to 
man  that  his  opponent  does ;  he  imposes  the  same  moral 
obligations,  the  same  duty  to  God  and  our  neighbours ;  he 
inculcates  the  same  affections,  he  maintains  exactly  the 
same  standard  in  morals  and  religion  that  his  opponent 
maintains.  It  is  true  his  theory,  as  taken  up  by  the  careless 
unthinking  mass,  tends  to  immorality  ;  for  the  mass  will 
not  see  distinctions,  and  confound  the  predestination  of  the 


CHAP.  XI.]  CONCLUSION.  329 

individual,  as  holy  and  virtuous,  with  the  predestination  of 
the  individual  as  such,  to  eternal  life ;  and  because  the  end 
is  assured,  suppose  it  to  be  assured  without  the  necessary 
means  and  qualifications  for  it.     And  such  a  practical  ten- 
dency in  the  doctrine,  however  justly  it  may  be  charged  to 
a  misapprehension  and  mistake  in  some   who   adopt   it,   is 
still  a  reflexion  upon  the  doctrine  itself;  showing  how  truth 
cannot  be  tampered  with  without  bad  practical  effects ;  and 
that  exclusive  and  one-sided  theories  are  a  stumbling  block 
to   ordinary   minds,   tending   to    confuse  their    reason   and 
moral  perceptions.     Still,  regarding  the  error  of  the  predes- 
tinarian    apart    from    those    consequences    which  it   tends 
practically  to  produce  in  the  minds  of  the  vulgar,  but  which 
are  not  legitimately  deducible  from  it,  it  cannot  perhaps  be 
called  much  more  than  a  metaphysical  mistake, — an  over- 
looking of  a  truth  in  human  nature ;  a  truth  indistinctly 
perceived  indeed,  but  still  perceived  in  that  sense  and  mode 
in  which  many  other  recognised  truths  are  perceived.     The 
predestinarian    passes  over   the   incomplete   perception    we 
have  of  our  originality  as  agents,  because  his  mind  is  preoc- 
cupied with  a  rival  truth.     But  this  cannot  in  itself  be  called 
an  offence  against  piety :  rather  it  is  occasioned  by  a  well- 
intended  though  excessive  regard  to  a  great  maxim  of  piety. 
He  is  unreasonably  jealous  for  the  Divine   Attribute,  and 
afraid  that  any  original  power  assigned  to  man  will  endanger 
the  Divine.     He  thus  allows  the  will  of  man  no  original 
part  in  good  action,  but  throws  all  goodness  back  upon  the 
Deity,  as  the  sole  Source  and  Creator  of  it,    forming  and 
fashioning  the  human  soul  as  the  potter  moulds  the  clay.     It 
may  be  said,  indeed,  that  his  doctrine,  in  attributing  injustice 
to  the  Deity,  is  inconsistent  with  piety :  but  he  does  not  at- 
tribute injustice  to  the  Deity ;  but  only  a  mode  of  acting, 
which,  as  conceived  and  understood  by  us,  is  unjust ;  or  which 
we  cannot  explain  in  consistency  with  justice. 

II.  Pelagianism,  on   the  other  hand,   offends  against  the 


330  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XI. 

first  principles  of  piety,  and  opposes  the  great  religious 
instincts  and  ideas  of  mankind.  It  first  tampers  with  the 
sense  of  sin.  The  sense  of  sin  as  actually  entertained  by 
the  human  mind ;  that  sense  of  it  which  we  perceive,  observe, 
and  are  conscious  of,  as  a  great  religious  fact  —  a  part  of 
our  moral  nature  whenever  sufficiently  enlightened  —  is 
not  a  simple,  but  a  mysterious  and  a  complex  sense ;  not 
confined  to  positive  action,  as  the  occasion  of  it,  but  going 
further  back  and  attaching  itself  to  desire;  nor  attaching 
itself  to  desire  only  as  the  effect  of  free  choice,  but  to 
desire  as  in  some  sense  necessary  in  us,  belonging  to  our 
present  condition  as  human  beings,  and  such  as  we  cannot 
imagine  ourselves,  in  our  present  state,  in  some  degree  or  other 
not  having.  Mankind  know  and  feel  that  sin  is  necessary 
in  this  world,  and  cannot  be  avoided ;  yet  simultaneously 
with  this  sense  of  its  necessity  they  mourn  over  it,  and 
feel  themselves  blameworthy.  A  sense  of  such  a  peculiar 
kind  as  this,  of  moral  evil,  is  indeed  mysterious  and  in- 
comprehensible, but  it  is  a  fact ;  it  is  a  part  of  a  whole  nature 
which  cannot  be  explained,  made  up  as  it  is  of  apparent 
inconsistencies  and  contradictions.  But  the  Pelagian  would 
only  allow  so  much  of  this  whole  sense  of  sin  in  human 
nature  as  he  could  rationally  and  intelligibly  account  for: 
he  could  understand  voluntary  but  not  necessary  sin,  how 
man's  acts,  but  not  how  his  nature  should  humble  him.  He 
therefore  rejected  the  doctrine  of  original  sin.  And  as  he  tam- 
pered with  the  sense  of  moral  evil,  so  he  rejected  the  sense  of 
moral  weakness.  He  could  not  understand  that  discord  and 
opposition  in  the  will  which  the  Apostle  expresses  in  the  text, 
"  To  will  is  present  with  me,  but  how  to  perform  that  which  is 
good  I  know  not ;  for  the  good  that  I  would  I  do  not,  but  the 
evil  which  I  would  not  that  I  do;"  and  he  therefore  thrust  it 
aside  for  a  mere  abstract  conception  of  freewill,  pronounced 
man  to  have  a  power  of  doing  anything  to  which  there 
was  no  physical  hindrance,  and  placed  an  absolute  origin 
and  source  of  good  in  human  nature.  The  principle  of 


CHAP.  XI.]  CONCLUSION.  331 

humility  in  human  nature  which  leads  it  to  eject  the 
source  of  good  from  itself,  and  place  it  wholly  in  God, 
was  thus  disowned ;  and  with  it  the  earnest  craving  of 
human  nature  for  an  atonement  for  sin :  for  if  mankind 
had  the  power  to  avoid  sin,  and  if  some,  as  he  maintained, 
had  actually  lived  without  it,  mankind  did  not  in  their 
corporate  capacity  want  a  Saviour;  and  the  sense  of  this 
vital  need  did  not  belong  to  human  nature. 

And  in  disowning  these  doctrines  the  Pelagian  at  the 
same  time  opposed  himself  to  facts.  The  doctrine  of  the 
Fall,  the  doctrine  of  Grace,  and  the  doctrine  of  the  Atone- 
ment are  grounded  in  the  instincts  of  mankind.  It  is  true 
we  receive  these  truths  by  revelation,  and  should  not  other- 
wise have  possessed  them  in  anything  like  the  fulness  in 
which  we  do.  But  when  revealed  they  are  seen  to  lie  deep 
in  the  human  conscience.  The  doctrine  of  original  sin 
lies  deep  in  the  human  heart,  which  has  never  truly  and 
earnestly  perceived  its  guilt  at  all,  without  coupling  with  it 
the  idea  of  a  mysterious  alloy  and  taint  antecedent  to  action, 
and  coeval  with  its  own  life.  And  in  like  manner  man  has 
in  all  ages  craved  an  atonement  for  sin;  he  has  always 
ejected  the  source  of  good  from  himself,  and  referred  it 
to  God.  These  are  religious  feelings  and  instincts  belonging 
to  human  nature,  and  which  can  never  be  eradicated  so  long 
as  that  nature  remains  itself.  The  Pelagian,  then,  in  rejecting 
these  doctrines,  opposed  himself  to  facts ;  he  separated  him- 
self from  that  whole  actual  body  of  sentiment,  instinct,  and 
feeling  which  constitutes  the  religious  life  of  mankind,  and 
placed  himself  outside  of  human  nature.  •  A  true  system  of 
religion  must  represent  these  facts;  these  large,  these  deep, 
these  powerful,  these  penetrating,  and  marvellous  instincts: 
and  it  is  the  glory  of  Catholic  Christianity  that  it  does  this, 
that  it  expounds  faithfully  the  creed  of  the  human  heart,  that 
nothing  in  human  nature  is  left  unrepresented  in  it;  but 
that  in  its  vast  and  intricate  fabric  of  doctrine  is  reflected, 
as  in  a  mirror,  every  vague  perception  of  our  nature,  every 


332  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XI. 

inexplicable  fear  and  desire,  grief  and  joy;  every  internal 
discord,  unfinished  thought,  beginning  of  unknown  truth ;  all 
that  in  the  religious  conscience,  will,  and  affections  can  or  can- 
not be  understood.  But  the  Pelagian  discarded  the  religion 
of  human  nature  and  of  fact,  for  an  idea  of  his  own  mind ; 
because  his  own  idea  was  simple  and  intelligible,  and  the 
religion  of  human  nature  was  mysterious  and  complex ;  as 
if,  when  facts  were  mysterious,  it  were  anything  in  favour 
of  the  truth  of  a  religion  that  it  was  not.  Rather  as  if 
such  an  absence  of  mystery  did  not  prove  that  the  system 
was  a  fiction  and  a  fancy ;  the  artificial  production  of  human 
thought,  instead  of  a  true  revelation  from  the  Author  of 
nature,  who  makes  all  things  double  one  of  another,  and 
who  adapts  His  revelations  to  that  human  nature  which 
He  has  made.  Nature  and  revelation,  as  having  the  same 
source,  are  both  expressions  of  the  same  truth,  and  must 
correspond  with  each  other.  If  a  religion  is  true,  then, 
it  must  harmonise  with  that  whole  complex  and  intricate 
body  of  feelings  and  ideas,  of  which  human  nature  is  really 
and  actually  composed.  The  Pelagian,  then,  or — to  take 
the  stronger  instance  —  the  Socinian,  may  appeal  to  the 
simplicity  and  plainness  of  his  system,  that  it  contains  no  ob- 
scure and  incomplete,  no  discordant  and  irreconcilable  ideas  ; 
but  if  he  does,  he  boasts  of  a  religion  which  is  self-convicted 
of  falsehood  and  delusion,  and  is  proved  on  its  own  showing 
to  be  a  dream.  Such  a  religion  may  satisfy  a  mind  that 
has  thought  out  a  belief  for  itself,  and  has  allowed  a  parti- 
cular line  of  thought  to  lead  it  out  of  the  great  circle  of 
human  feelings  and  instincts,  but  it  cannot  satisfy  the 
natural  wants  of  the  human  heart ;  it  may  please  and  amuse 
in  comfort  and  tranquillity,  but  it  will  not  support  in 
distress;  it  may  be  argued  for,  but  it  cannot  be  loved; 
and  it  may  be  the  creed  of  a  philosopher,  but  it  is  not  the 
religion  of  man. 

In  this  state  of  the  case  the  Church  has  made  a  wise 


CHAP.  XL]  CONCLUSION.  333 

and  just  distinction,  in  its  treatment  of  the  respective 
errors  of  the  Pelagian  and  the  predestinarian ;  and  while  it 
has  cast  Pelagianism  out  of  its  communion,  as  a  system 
fundamentally  opposed  to  Christian  belief,  it  has  tole- 
rated predestinarianism ;  regarding  it  as  a  system  which 
only  carries  some  religious  ideas  to  an  excess,  and  does  not 
err  in  principle,  or  offend  against  piety  or  morals.  The 
seventeenth  article  of  our  Church  has  accordingly  allowed  a 
place  for  a  predestinarian  school  among  ourselves ;  and  such 
a  school  has  long  existed,  and  still  exists  among  us.  This 
article  indeed  admits  of  two  interpretations,  and  may  be  held 
and  subscribed  to  in  two  ways,  one  suiting  the  believer  in 
freewill,  the  other  the  predestinarian.  It  may  be  held  as 
containing  one  side  of  the  whole  truth  respecting  grace 
and  freewill — the  side,  viz.  of  grace  or  the  Divine  Power ; 
but  not  at  all  as  interfering  with  any  one's  belief  in  a  counter 
truth  of  man's  freewill  and  originality  as  an  agent.  And  in 
this  sense  it  only  excludes  a  Pelagian,  and  not  such  as  are 
content  to  hold  a  mystery  on  this  subject,  and  maintain  the 
Divine  Power  in  conjunction  with  man's  freewill.  Or,  again, 
this  article  may  be  held  as  containing  a  complete  and  whole 
truth;  i.  e.  in  a  definitely  predestinarian  sense.  But  as  it 
would  be  unfair  in  the  predestinarian  to  prohibit  the  qua- 
lified, so  it  would  be  unfair  in  the  advocate  of  freewill  not 
to  allow  the  extreme  mode  of  holding  this  article,  or  to 
disallow  it  as  permitting  and  giving  room  for  a  pure  pre- 
destinarian school  within  our  Church.  This  wise  and  just 
liberty  has  indeed  at  times  offended  those  whom  the  excesses 
of  this  school  have  roused  to  hostility,  or  whom  insufficient 
reflection  and  the  philosophical  bias  of  the  day  have  made 
too  exclusive  and  dogmatic  in  their  opinions  concerning 
freewill ;  and  at  the  close  of  the  last  century  a  proposal  was 
made  by  a  Divine  who  became  afterwards  a  distinguished 
prelate  of  our  Church,  to  ecclesiastical  authority,  that 
the  terms  of  the  seventeenth  article  should  be  altered  and 


334 


CONCLUSION. 


[CHAP.  XI. 


so  framed  as  to  give  no  further  licence  to  predestinarianism.1 
But  a  wise  caution,  if  not  a  profound  theology,  in  the  rulers 
of  the  Church  at  that  time  rejected  it.  And  this  liberty 
still  remains  a  great  advantage  to  the  Church,  and  a  signal 
proof  at  once  of  judgment  and  discretion,  and  of  a  correct 
and  enlarged  theology.  It  would  indeed  have  been  a  fatal 
mistake  to  have  excluded  from  our  pale  an  aspect  of  Christian 
truth, which  simply  erred  in  a  pardonable  obliquity,  such  as 
is  incident  to  minds  of  the  highest  order,  to  the  strongest 
intellect,  to  the  deepest  devotion.  Such  an  exclusion  would 
have  shown  also  great  ignorance  of  antiquity  and  the  his- 
tory of  Christian  doctrine ;  for,  without  attaching^  more  than 
undue  importance  to  a  single  name,  it  will  be  allowed  perhaps 
that  what  S.Augustine  held  is  at  any  rate  a  tolerable  opinion, 
and  no  sufficient  ground  for  separation  either  from  the  commu- 
nion or  the  ministry  of  the  Church.  He  is,  however,  only  the 
first  of  a  succession  of  authorities  that  from  his  own  age  to  the 
present  have  maintained  and  taught  predestinarianism  within 
the  Church.  Such  a  proposal  with  respect  to  the  seventeenth 
article,  from  the  person  who  made  it,  only  shows  how  apt 


1  About  this  time  a  circumstance 
occurred,  which  then  excited  con- 
siderable interest,  and  in  which  the 
part  that  Dr.  Porteous  took  has  been 
much  misinterpreted  and  misunder- 
stood. The  following  statement  in 
his  own  words  will  place  the  fact  in  its 
true  point  of  view :  "  At  the  close  of 
the  year  1772,  and  the  beginning  of 
the  next,  an  attempt  was  made  by 
myself,  and  a  few  other  clergymen, 
among  whom  were  Mr.  Francis  Wol- 
laston,  Dr.  Percy,  now  Bishop  of  Dro- 
more,  and  Dr.  Torke,  now  Bishop  of 
Ely,  to  induce  the  bishops  to  promote 
a  review  of  the  Liturgy  and  Articles  ; 
in  order  to  amend  in  both,  but  parti- 
cularly in  the  latter,  those  parts  which 
all  reasonable  persons  agreed  stood  in  need 
of  amendment.  This  plan  was  meant 
to  strengthen  and  confirm  the  eccle- 
siastical establishment ;  to  repel  the 
attacks  which  were  at  that  time  con- 
tinually made  upon  it  by  its  avowed 
enemies ;  to  render  the  1 7th  Article 


on  Predestination  and  Election  more 
clear  and  perspicuous,  and  less  liable 
to  be  wrested  by  our  adversaries  to 
a  Calvinistic  sense,  which  has  been 

so   unjustly  affixed   to   it On 

these  grounds  we  applied  in  a  private 
and  respectful  manner  to  Archbishop 
Cornwallis,  requesting  him  to  signify  our 
wishes  (which  we  conceived  to  be  the 
wishes  of  a  very  large  proportion,  both 
of  the  clergy  and  laity)  to  the  rest  of 
the  bishops,  that  everything  might  be 
done  which  could  be  prudently  and 
safely  done,  to  promote  these  important 
and  salutary  purposes." 

"  The  answer  given  by  the  Arch- 
bishop, February  11.  1773,  was  in  these 
words  :  '  I  have  consulted  severally  my 
brethren  the  bishops,  and  it  is  the 
opinion  of  the  Bench  in  general,  that 
nothing  can  in  prudence  be  done  in 
the  matter  which  has  been  submitted 
to  our  consideration.' " — Works  of  Bishop 
Porteous,  vol.  i.  p.  38. 


CHAP.  XL]  CONCLUSION.  335 

minds  are  to  be  confined  to  the  prevailing  notions  of  their  day, 
and  to  suppose  that  there  is  no  room  for  any  other  truth  than 
what  happens  to  have  been  familiar  to  themselves.  And  it 
should  operate  as  a  warning  against  similar  attempts,  showing, 
as  it  does,  what  great  mistakes  may  be  made  when  we  trust 
too  confidently  one  apparent  truth  ;  forgetting  how  much  it 
might  be  modified,  were  we  in  possession  of  the  whole  system 
to  which  it  belongs ;  and  how  easily  we  may  be  ignorant  and 
uninformed  upon  those  further  points  upon  which  this  modi- 
fication would  follow. 

The  formularies  of  our  own  Church,  following  Catholic 
precedent,  accordingly  allow  predestinarianism ;  and  this  is 
the  decision  of  common  sense  and  common  reason  on  this 
subject.  For,  so  long  as  a  man  thinks  nothing  which  is  in- 
consistent with  piety,  what  great  difference  can  it  make, 
provided  his  actions  are  good,  on  what  particular  rationale 
of  causation  he  supposes  them  to  be  done?  whether v  he 
thinks  them  done  wholly  by  Divine  grace,  or  partly  by 
an  original  motion  of  his  own  will  coinciding  with  grace  ? 
The  latter  is  the  more  large  and  reasonable  view;  but 
whichever  of  the  two  opinions  he  adopts,  if  he  only  does  his 
duty,  that  is  the  great  thing.  The  object  for  which  this 
present  life  is  given  us,  is  not  philosophy  and  reasoning, 
and  the  arrival  at  speculative  truth  respecting  even  our 
own  wills,  and  how  they  are  moved ;  but  it  is  self-discipline 
and  moral  action,  growth  in  piety  and  virtue.  So  long  as 
this  practical  object  is  attained,  mistakes  of  mere  speculation 
may  well  be  passed  over.  Those  who  give  these  mistakes 
a  practical  direction,  indeed,  and  from  thinking  erroneously 
proceed  to  act  viciously,  are  responsible  for  such  an  appli- 
cation of  a  speculative  tenet;  but  those  who  do  not  so 
apply  it,  are  not  so  responsible.  Numbers  of  pious  and 
earnest  Christians  who  have  laboured  for  the  welfare  and 
salvation  of  their  brethren,  enduring  thankfully  fatigue  and 
pain,  and  despising  the  riches  and  honours  of  the  world, 
have  thought  that  they  did  all  this  by  an  irresistible  Divine 


336  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XT. 

influence  in  consequence  of  which  they  could  not  act  other- 
wise than  they  did.  And  what  if  they  did  think  so  ?  They 
took  a  one-sided  view ;  but  if  we  wait  till  men  are  per- 
fectly fair,  clear,  and  large  in  their  judgment  before  we  ac- 
knowledge them  as  brethren,  in  the  case  of  the  great 
majority  of  mankind  we  may  wait  for  ever. 

Such  is  the  imperfection  even  of  the  human  mind, 
that,  under  Providence,  a  certain  narrowness  of  judgment 
often  works  for  good,  and  seems  to  favour  practical  energy 
and  zeal.  How  universal  is  that  disposition  in  men  of 
religious  ardour,  enthusiasm,  and  activity,  to  over-value 
some  one  or  two  particular  tenets,  which  are  either  true, 
or  which  they  suppose  to  be  true ;  appearing  to  think 
almost  more  about  them  than  they  do  about  the  whole  of 
the  rest  of  their  religious  creed,  containing  all  the  broad 
and  fundamental  truths  of  the  religion  they  profess  I  How 
do  they  cherish  and  foster  this  tendency  in  their  minds,  as 
if  it  were  the  most  sacred  and  highest  characteristic  of  their 
religious  life!  How  do  they  idolise  these  special  tenets, 
as  if  to  part  with  them  were  to  bid  farewell  altogether  to 
piety  and  religion  I  And  doubtless  in  their  particular  case 
this  even  might  be  the  result.  For  if  minds  have  accustomed 
themselves  to  cling  with  this  exclusive  force  to  particular 
points,  and  identify  religion  as  a  whole  with  them,  who 
can  tell  the  effect  of  the  revulsion  which  would  take  place, 
could  they  be  brought  to  doubt  the  truth  of  these  ?  For 
men  go  from  one  extreme  to  another,  and  from  reposing 
the  most  absolute  faith  upon  articles  resting  on  small 
evidence,  rush  into  disbelief  of  those  which  rest  upon  the 
strongest.  And  if  so,  who  would  in  all  cases  wish  to  try 
the  experiment  of  a  change  ?  Who  but  a  philosopher  with- 
out knowledge  of  mankind  would,  for  the  chance  of  a  possible 
advantage,  endeavour  in  all  cases  to  disturb  even  a  cherished 
error  of  the  minor  and  pardonable  class  ?  As  if  minor 
errors  were  not  sometimes  even  a  safeguard  against  greater 
ones ;  and  as  if  an  obstinate  propensity  of  the  human  mind, 


CHAP.  XL]  CONCLUSION.  337 

checked  in  one  direction,  would  not  run  out  in  another ;  like 
a  stream  which,  if  you  dam  it  up  in  one  part,  breaks  its 
bank  elsewhere,  and  perhaps  floods  a  whole  district.  Nor 
is  this  propensity  to  over-estimate  particular  truths  or  sup- 
posed truths  confined  to  any  one  communion :  the  Roman 
Catholic  and  the  Protestant  shows  it  alike ;  most  sects  and 
divisions  of  the  Christian  world  have  their  favourite  tenets, 
which  individuals  identify  with  religion  as  a  whole,  and 
associate  intimately  and  fundamentally  with  their  whole 
Christian  prospects,  as  if  their  spiritual  life  and  sanctification 
were  essentially  bound  up  with  them.  They  seem  to  see 
in  such  special  tenets  the  source  of  all  their  strength,  their 
stay,  encouragement,  and  consolation. 

The  history  of  the  human  mind,  I  say,  shows  this  great 
imperfection  in  it,  that  it  is  so  much  more  able  to  appreciate 
smaller  and  particular  truths,  real  or  supposed,  than  larger 
and  fundamental  ones.  There  is  in  the  first  place  an  ad- 
vantage in  this  respect,  belonging  to  the  former,  in  the  very 
circumstance  that  they  are  smaller;  they  are  more  easily 
grasped,  and  the  whole  heart  embraces  them,  and  winds  itself 
about  them  more  completely.  There  is  in  the  next  place  the 
stimulus  of  rivalry  and  contradiction,  which  surrounds  a  pecu- 
liar and  distinctive,  and  as  such,  an  opposed  tenet,  with  a  halo 
of  its  own,  and  invests  it  with  an  interest  which  does  not  attach 
to  undisputed  truths.  The  broad  doctrines  of  revelation  are 
defective  in  this  appeal  to  our  interest,  because  they  are  so 
broad ;  and  truths  which  all  hold  are  thought  little  of  com- 
paratively, because  all  hold  them.  What  merit  is  there  in 
believing  what  everybody  else  believes  ?  We  are  thrown  in 
the  case  of  such  truths  upon  the  intrinsic  gravity  and  import- 
ance of  the  truths  themselves,  to  the  exclusion  of  that  ad- 
ventitious interest  which  accrues  from  the  really  irrelevant 
and  impertinent  consideration  of  who  hold  them,  —  that  we 
maintain  and  accept  them  in  distinction  to  others  who  do 
not.  Men  thus  glory  in  a  privilege  while  they  pass  over 
coldly  and  slightingly  a  common  benefit.  In  the  case  of  the 


338  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XI. 

distinctive  tenet  they  feel  themselves  champions;  the  be- 
frienders  of  truth,  and  not  its  disciples  only;  its  patrons, 
rather  than  its  sons.     Stripped  of  this  foreign,  and  thrown 
back  on  its  own  intrinsic  interest,  truth  is  apt  to  be  a  some- 
what cold  and  insipid  thing  to  the  majority  of  men — at  least 
in  their  average  state  of  mind ;  though  sickness  or  adversity 
will  sometimes  reveal  to  them  this,  true,  this  solid,  this  really 
sublime   and  native  interest  belonging  to   it.     Ordinarily, 
they  are  too  apt  to  be  little  interested  in  it,  unless  supported 
by  some  external  aid  of  this  kind.     There  is  again  another 
and  a  better  reason  than  either  of  those  which  have  been 
given  for  the  disproportionate  estimate  of  particular  tenets ; 
viz.  that  they  really  suit,  assist,  and  support  particular  men- 
tal, as  strong  medicines  do  particular  bodily,  constitutions. 
But  whatever  be  the  reasons  for  this  disposition,  all  sects 
and  communions  more  or  less  exhibit  it;    and  men,  and 
serious  and  earnest  men,  come  forward  and  tell  us,  that  they 
could  not  conduct  their  spiritual  progress  without  the  aid  of 
one  or  other  special  tenet,  which  they  assert,  and  really 
imagine  to  be,  the  spring  of  their  energies,  and  the  main- 
stay of  their  hopes.    And  among  the  rest,  the  predestinarian 
comes  forward  and  says  this.     He  says  that  he  could  not,  as 
a  spiritual  being,  go  on  without  this  doctrine ;  that  he  finds 
it  essential  to  him ;  that  without  it  the  universe  would  be  a 
chaos,  and  the  Divine  dispensations  a  delusion;   that  he 
reposes  in  it  as  the  only  true  mode  of  asserting  the  Divine 
Love  and  Power ;  and,  therefore,  his  only  support  in  this  life, 
his   only    security  for  a  better  life  to  come.     He  says  all 
this;  he  says  it  from  his  heart;  he  feels  it;  he  believes  it. 
Then  what  are  we  to  say  ?     What,  but  that,  however  such  a 
result  may  be  owing  to  an  imperfection  in  his  mind,  this 
doctrine   is    certainly   to   him,    under   this   imperfection,    a 
strength    and   a   consolation ;    and   that   an   error   and   an 
obliquity  is  overruled  by  Providence  for  good  ?  l 


1  "  As  the  workings  of  the  heart  of   I    general  the  same  in  all   who  are  the 
man,  and  of  the  Spirit  of  God,  are  in    I    subjects  of  grace,  I  hope  most  of  these 


CHAP.  XI.] 


CONCLUSION. 


339 


Whether  the  time,  indeed,  will  ever  come  when  men  in 
general  will  see  that  on  this  and  some  other  questions  truth 
is  twofold,  and  is  not  confined  to  either  side  singly,  —  that  our 
perceptions  are  indistinct  and  contradictory,  and  therefore, 
do  not  justify  any  one  definite  position,  —  remains  to  be  seen. 
Philosophers  have  from  time  to  time  prophesied  a  day,  when 
a  better  understanding  would  commence  of  man  with  himself, 
and  of  man  with  man.  They  have  risen  up  from  the  survey 
of  the  past  with  the  idea  that  it  is  impossible  that  mankind 
can  go  on  for  ever  repeating  the  same  mistakes ;  that  they 
must  one  day  see  the  limits  of  human  reason,  distinguish 
what  they  know  from  what  they  do  not  know,  and  draw  the 
necessary  conclusion,  that  on  some  questions  they  cannot 
insist  on  any  one  absolute  truth,  and  condemn  each  other 
accordingly.  But  the  vision  does  not  approach  at  present 
any  very  clear  fulfilment.  The  limits  of  human  reason  are 
perhaps  better  understood  in  the  world  now  than  they  ever 
were  before ;  and  such  a  knowledge  has  evidently  an  effect 
upon  controversy,  to  a  certain  extent  modifying  and  chasten- 
ing it.  Those  who  remind  men  of  their  ignorance  use  an 
argument  which,  however  it  may  fall  short  of  striking  with 


hymns,  being  the  fruit  and  expression 
of  my  own  experience,  will  coincide 
with  the  views  of  real  Christians  of 
all  denominations.  But  I  cannot  ex- 
pect that  every  sentiment  I  have  ad- 
vanced will  be  universally  approved. 
However,  I  am  not  conscious  of  having 
written  a  single  line  with  an  inten- 
tion either  to  flatter  or  offend  any 
party  or  person  upon  earth.  I  have 
simply  declared  my  own  views  and 
feelings.  .  .  .  I  am  a  friend  of  peace ; 
and  being  deeply  convinced  that  no 
one  can  profitably  understand  the  great 
truths  and  doctrines  of  the  Gospel  any 
further  than  he  is  taught  by  God,  I 
have  not  a  wish  to  obtrude  my  own 
tenets  upon  others  in  a  way  of  con- 
troversy ;  yet  I  do  not  think  myself 
bound  to  conceal  them.  Many  gracious 
persons  (for  many  such  I  am  persuaded 
there  are)  who  differ  from  me  more  or 


less  in  those  points  which  are  called 
Calvinistic,  appear  desirous  that  the 
Calvinists  should  for  their  sakes,  studi- 
ously avoid  every  expression  which  they 
cannot  approve.  Yet  few  of  them,  I 
believe,  impose  a  like  restraint  upon 
themselves,  but  think  the  importance  of 
what  they  deem  to  be  truth  justifies  them 
in  speaking  their  sentiments  plainly  and 
strongly.  May  I  not  plead  for  an  equal 
liberty  ?  The  views  I  have  received  of 
the  doctrines  of  grace  are  essential  to 
my  peace :  I  could  not  live  comfortably 
a  day  or  an  hour  without  them.  I 
likewise  believe,  yea,  as  far  as  my  poor 
attainments  warrant  me  to  speak,  I 
know  them  to  be  friendly  to  holiness, 
and  to  have  a  direct  influence  in  pro- 
ducing and  maintaining  a  Gospel  con- 
versation ;  and  therefore  I  must  not 
be  ashamed  of  them." — Newton's  Pre- 
face to  the  Olney  Hymns. 


Z    2 


340  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XI. 

its  full  philosophical  strength,  and  producing  its  due  effect, 
appeals  to  an  undeniable  truth,  before  which  all  human  souls 
must  bow.  And  the  most  ardent  minds,  in  the  very  heat  of 
controversy,  have  an  indistinct  suspicion  that  a  strong  ground 
has  been  established  in  this  quarter.  On  the  other  hand,  this 
knowledge  of  the  limits  of  human  reason  is  not,  and  perhaps 
never  will  be,  for  reasons  which  I- have  given,  very  acute  or 
accurate  in  the  minds  of  the  mass ;  while  the  tendency  to 
one-sided  views  and  to  hasty  assumption  is  strong,  and  is 
aided  by  passion  and  self-love,  as  well  as  by  better  feeling  mis- 
applied. On  the  whole,  therefore,  while  improved  philosophy 
has  perhaps  entirely  destroyed  some  great  false  assumptions 
which  have  reigned  in  the  world,  so  that  these  will  never  rise 
up  again,  it  cannot  subdue  the  temper  and  spirit  which  makes 
such  assumptions.  It  is  able  occasionally  to  check  and  qualify, 
but  it  cannot  be  expected  that  it  will  ever  habitually  regulate, 
theological  thought  and  controversy.  It  will  from  time  to 
time  step  in  as  a  monitor,  and  take  advantage  of  a  pause  and 
quiet  interval  to  impress  its  lesson  upon  mankind,  to  bring 
them  back  to  reflection  when  they  have  been  carried  too  far, 
and  convert  for  the  time  a  sense  of  error  into  a  more  cautious 
view  of  truth ;  but  it  will  never  perhaps  do  more  than  this. 
Unable  to  balance  and  settle,  it  will  give  a  useful  oscillation 
to  the  human  mind,  an  alternation  of  enthusiasm  and  judg- 
ment, of  excitement  and  repose. 

In  the  meantime  it  only  remains  that  those  who  differ  from 
each  other  on  points  which  can  never  be  settled  absolutely,  in 
the  present  state  of  our  .capacities,  should  remember  that  they 
may  differ,  not  in  holding  truth  and  error,  but  only  in  holding 
different  sides  of  the  same  truth.  And  with  this  reflection 
I  will  conclude  the  present  treatise.  After  long  considera- 
tion of  the  subject,  I  must  profess  myself  unable  to  see  on 
what  strictly  argumentative  ground  the  two  great  parties  in 
the  English  Church  can,  on  the  question  which  has  occupied 
this  treatise  — viz.  the  operation  of  Divine  grace,  and  on  other 
questions  connected  with  it  —  imagine  themselves  to  be  so 


CHAP.  XI.]  CONCLUSION.  341 

fundamentally  opposed  to  each  other.  All  differences  of 
opinion,  indeed,  even  those  which  are  obviously  of  a 
secondary  and  not  a  fundamental  kind,  tend  to  create  division 
and  separation ;  for  all  difference  in  its  degree  is  apt  to  be  a 
sign  of  some  general  difference  of  mental  mould  and  religious 
temper,  and  men  naturally  consort  together  according  to  their 
general  sympathies  and  turn  of  mind :  and  for  men  to  consort 
with  some  as  distinct  from  others,  is  in  itself  a  sort  of  division 
in  the  body ;  a  division,  too,  which,  when  once  begun,  is  apt 
to  deepen.  Such  an  existence  of  preference  is  suggestive  of 
positive  controversy ;  and  men  once  brought  together  upon 
such  an  understanding,  and  formed  into  groups  by  special 
sympathies,  are  liable  to  become  by  this  very  position  anta- 
gonistic parties,  schools,  and  sides.  Yet  the  differences  of 
opinion  in  our  Church,  on  the  question  of  grace,  and  on 
some  further  questions  connected  with  it,  do  not  appear  to 
be  sufficient  to  justify  either  party  in  supposing  that  if  dif- 
fers from  the  other  fundamentally,  or  so  as  to  interfere  with 
Christian  fellowship.  If  the  question  of  grace  is  one  which, 
depending  on  irreconcilable  but  equally  true  tendencies  of 
thought  in  man,  cannot  be  settled  absolutely  either  way,  it 
seems  to  follow  that  a  difference  upon  it  should  not  occasion 
a  distance  or  separation.  And  this  remark  will  apply  to  such 
further  and  more  particular  questions  as  are  connected  with 
this  general  question,  and  are  necessarily  affected  by  the  view 
we  take  upon,  and  the  mode  in  which  we  decide  the  general 
question.  Such,  for  example,  is  the  doctrine  of  baptismal 
regeneration.  A  slight  consideration  will  be  enough  to  show 
how  intimately  this  doctrine  is  connected  with  the  general 
doctrine  of  grace ;  and  that  one  who  holds  an  extreme,  and 
one  who  holds  a  modified  doctrine  of  grace  in  general, 
cannot  hold  the  doctrine  of  baptismal  regeneration  in  the 
same  sense.  If  a  latitude  of  opinion,  then,  may  be  allowed 
on  the  general  question,  it  seems  to  follow  that  an  equal  lati- 
tude may  be  allowed  on  this  further  and  more  particular  one ; 
and  that  if  an  extreme  predestinarian,  and  a  maintainer  of 

z  3 


342  CONCLUSION.  [CHAP.  XI. 

freewill  can  maintain  and  teach  their  respective  doctrines 
within  the  same  communion,  they  need  not  exclude  each 
other  when  they  come  to  give  to  their  respective  doctrines 
their  necessary  and  legitimate  application  in  a  particular  case. 
I  cannot,  therefore,  but  think,  that  further  reflection  will,  on 
this  and  other  questions,  modify  the  opposition  of  the  two 
parties  in  our  Church  to  each  other,  and  show  that  their  dis- 
agreement is  not  so  great  as  in  the  heat  of  controversy  they 
supposed  it  to  be.  Differences  of  opinion  there  will  always  be 
in  every  religious  communion,  so  long  as  the  human  mind  is 
as  variously  constituted  as  it  is,  and  so  long  as  proper  liberty 
is  allowed  it  to  express  and  unfold  this  variety.  But  it  depends 
on  the  discretion  and  temper  of  religious  men  to  what 
extent  they  wJll  allow  these  differences  to  carry  them ; 
whether  they  will  retain  them  upon  a  common  basis  of 
Christian  communion  and  fellowship,  or  raise  them  into  an 
occasion  of  separation  and  mutual  exclusion. 


NOTES. 


NOTE  I.  p.  4. 

TOPLADY  says,  "  If  God  had  not  willed  the  fall,  He  could 
and  no  doubt  would  have  prevented  it ;  but  He  did  not  pre- 
vent it,  ergo  He  willed  it ;  and  if  He  willed  it,  He  certainly 
decreed  it."  —  Vol.  v.  p.  242.  This  is  a  philosophical  argu- 
ment proceeding  upon  the  attribute  of  the  Divine  Power ; 
as  is  the  following  appeal  to  our  intellectual  consistency  as 
believers  in  a  God :  "  He  alone  is  entitled  to  the  name  of 
true  God  who  governs  all  things,  and  without  whose  will 
(either  efficient  or  permissive)  nothing  is  or  can  be  done. 
And  such  is  the  God  of  the  Scriptures,  against  whose  will 
not  a  sparrow  can  die,  nor  a  hair  fall  from  our  heads.  Now, 
what  is  predestination  but  the  determining  will  of  God  ?  I 
defy  the  subtlest  Semi-Pelagian  in  the  world  to  form  or 
convey  a  just  and  worthy  notion  of  the  Supreme  Being 
without  admitting  Him  to  be  the  Great  Cause  of  all  causes ; 
also  Himself  dependent  on  none ;  who  willed  from  eternity 
how  He  should  act  in  time,  and  settled  a  regular,  determinate 
scheme  of  what  He  would  do  and  permit  to  be  done,  from 
the  beginning  to  the  consummation  of  the  world.  A  con- 
trary view  of  the  Deity  is  as  inconsistent  with  reason  itself, 
and  with  the  very  religion  of  nature,  as  it  is  with  the  de- 
cisions of  revelation Without  predestination  to  plan, 

and  without  Providence  to  put  that  plan  in  execution,  what 
becomes  of  God's  omnipotence  ?  It  vanishes  into  air ;  it 
becomes  a  mere  nonentity.  For  what  sort  of  Omnipotence 
is  that  which  is  baffled  or  defeated  by  the  very  creatures  it 
has  made." — Toplady,  vol.  v.  p.  293. 

z  4 


344  NOTE   It. 


NOTE  II.  p.  8. 

JACKSON  quotes  a  predestinarian  statement,  "  That  God's 
irresistible  decree  for  the  absolute  election  of  some,  and  the 
absolute  reprobation  of  others,  is  immediately  terminated  to 
the  individual  natures,  substances,  or  entities  of  men,  with- 
out any  logical  respect  or  reference  to  their  qualifications  ;  " 
a  position  to  which  he  attaches  the  following  consequences : 
"  This  principle  being  once  granted,  what  breach  of  God's 
moral  law  is  there  whereon  men  will  not  boldly  adventure, 
either  through  desperation  or  presumption,  either  openly  or 
secretly?  For  seeing  God's  will,  which  in  their  divinity 
is  the  only  cause  why  the  one  sort  are  designated  to  death, 
the  other  to  life,  is  most  immutable  and  most  irresistible, — 
and  seeing  the  individual  entities  or  natures  of  men,  unto 
which  this  irresistible  decree  is  respectively  terminated,  are 
immutable, — let  the  one  sort  do  what  they  can,  pray  for 
themselves,  and  beseech  others  to  pray  for  them,  they  shall 
be  damned  because  their  entities  or  individual  substances  are 
unalterable :  let  the  other  sort  live  as  they  list,  they  shall 
be  saved,  because  no  corruption  of  manners,  no  change  of 
morality  finds  any  mutability  or  change  in  their  individual 
natures  or  entities,  unto  which  God's  immutable  decree  is 
immediately  terminated.  Whatsoever  becomes  of  good  life 
or  good  manners,  so  the  individual  nature  or  entity  fail  not, 
or  be  not  annihilated,  salvation  is  tied  unto  it  by  a  necessity 
more  indissoluble  than  any  chains  of  adamant." — Vol.  ix. 
p.  370. 

This  is  perhaps  a  misinterpretation  of  the  predestinarian 
statement  quoted.  The  Divine  decree,  it  is  true,  is,  ac- 
cording to  that  statement,  w  terminated  to  the  entities  of  men," 
and  has  (s  no  respect  to  their  qualifications,"  as  the  cause  or 
reason  of  such  decree  ;  but  it  may  still  have  respect  to  such 
qualifications  as  the  effects  of  such  decree.  But,  whatever 
may  be  said  of  this  particular  statement,  such  an  interpreta- 
tion of  it,  if  meant  for  a  representation  of  the  doctrine  of 
predestination,  is  very  incorrect. 


NOTE   III.  345 


NOTE  III.  p.  10. 

AQUINAS  argues  for  the  righteousness  of  Adam  before  the 
fall  as  supernatural,  or  the  effect  of  grace,  on  this  ground : 
"  Manifestum  est  quod  ilia  subjectio  corporis  ad  animam,  et 
inferiorum  virium  ad  ration  em,  non  erat  naturalis ;  alioquin 
post  peccatum  mansisset,  cum  etiam  in  daemonibus  data 
naturalia  post  peccatum  permanserint." — Sum.  Theol  lma 
Q.  95.  Art.  1. 

This  necessity  of  grace,  however,  before  the  fall  is 
explained  by  Aquinas  with  various  distinctions,  the  substance 
of  which  is,  that  grace  is  wanted  for  supernatural  virtue  only 
by  man  in  his  upright  state,  but  for  natural  as  well  in  his 
corrupt ;  while  the  assistance  of  God  as  Prime  Mover,  which 
he  distinguishes  from  grace,  is  necessary  for  all  acts  in  Iboth 
states.  "Homo in  statu naturae integrae  potest  operari  virtute 
suae  naturae  bonum  quod  est  sibi  connaturale  absque  super- 
additione  gratuiti  doni,  licet  non  absque  auxilio  Dei  moventis." 
—  lma  2dae  Q.  109.  Art.  3. 

"  Secundum  utrumque  statum  (corruptum  et  integrum) 
natura  humana  indiget  Divino  auxilio  ad  faciendum  vel 
volendum  quodcunque  bonum,  sicut  primo  movente.  Sed  in 
statu  naturae  integrae  poterat  homo  per  sua  naturalia  velle  et 
operari  bonum  suae  naturae  proportionatum,  quale  est  bonum 
virtutis  acquisitae ;  non  autem  bonum  superexcedens,  quale  est 
bonum  virtutis  infusae.  Sed  in  statu  naturae  corruptae  etiam 
deficit  homo  ab  hoc  quod  secundum  suarn  naturam  potest,  ut 
non  possit  totum  hujusmodi  bonum  implere  per  sua  naturalia. 
Quia  tamen  natura  humana  per  peccatum  non  est  totaliter 
corruptum,  potest  quidem  etiam  in  statu  naturae  corruptae 
per  virtutem  suae  naturae  aliquod  bonum  particulare  agere, 
sicut  aedificare  domos,"  &c. 

"  Virtute  gratuita  superaddita  virtuti  naturae  indiget  homo 
in  statu  naturae  integrae  quantum  ad  unum,  scilicet  ad  operan- 
dum  et  volendum  bonum  supernaturale ;  sed  in  statu  naturae 


346  NOTE   IV. 

corrupts  quantum  ad  duo  soil,  ut  sanetur,  et  ulterius  ut 
bonum  supernaturale  virtutis  operetur." — lma  2dae  Q.  109. 
Art.  2. 


NOTE  IV.  p.  23. 

LOCKE'S  theory  that  facts,  of  sense  or  reflexion,  are  the  sole 
source  of  our  ideas,  places  him  in  a  difficulty  with  respect  to 
this  indistinct  class  of  ideas.  He  is  committed  to  the  necessity 
of  deriving  them  from  this  source,  and  tries  in  a  roundabout 
way  to  extract  them  from  it.  "  They  are  ultimately  grounded 
on  and  derived  from  ideas  which  come  in  by  sensation  or 
reflexion,  and  so  may  be  said  to  come  in  by  sensation  or 
reflexion.". —  First  Letter  to  Bishop  of  Worcester.  But 
though  he  is  in  a  difficulty  as  to  their  origin,  and  cannot 
combine  them  with  his  theory,  he  acknowledges  as  a  fact  this 
class  of  indistinct  ideas.  Thus  the  idea  of  substance  C(  is  the 
obscure  and  indistinct  vague  idea  of  something  which  has  the 
relation  of  support  or  substratum  to  modes  or  accidents."  — 
Ibid.  "  The  idea  of  substance  is  but  a  supposed  I  know  not 
what  to  support  those  ideas  we  call  accidents.  We  talk  like 
children  who,  being  questioned  what  such  a  thing  is  which 
they  know  not,  readily  give  this  satisfactory  answer,  that  it  is 
something."  —  Essay,  b.  ii.  c.  23.  "  The  being  of  substance 
would  not  be  at  all  shaken  by  my  saying  we  had  but  an  ob- 
scure imperfect  idea  of  it ;  or  indeed  if  I  should  say  we  had 
no  idea  of  substance  at  all.  For  a  great  many  things  may 
be,  and  are  granted  to  have  being,  and  to  be  in  nature,  of 
which  we  have  no  ideas.  For  example,  it  cannot  be  doubted 
but  there  are  distinct  species  of  separate  spirits  of  which  yet 
we  have  no  distinct  ideas  at  all."  And  as  he  acknowledges 
an  idea  of  substance  which  is  yet  no  true  or  adequate  idea,  so 
he  does  of  infinity.  "  The  addition  of  finite  things  suggests 
the  idea  of  infinite  by  a  power  we  find  of  still  increasing  the 
same.  But  in  endeavouring  to  make  it  infinite,  it  being 
always  enlarging,  always  advancing,  the  idea  is  still  imperfect 
and  incomplete." — Essay,  b.  ii.  c.  17. 

Though  Stillingfleet  then  presses  him  hard  upon  the  origin 


NOTE   IT.  347 

of  such  ideas,  it  is  evident  that  with  respect  to  the  nature  of 
the  ideas  themselves  Locke  has  greatly  the  advantage  in  the 
argument ;  that  his  opponent  claims  a  distinctness  for  them 
which  mental  analysis  rejects,  and  in  his  alarm,  as  if  the 
foundations  of  truth  were  shaken  when  these  great  ideas  were 
discovered  to  be  incomplete  and  obscure,  shows  a  radical 
misapprehension  as  to  the  nature  of  the  fundamental  truths, 
on  which  much  of  philosophy  and  the  whole  of  religion  rests. 
No  error  can  be  greater  than  that  of  supposing  that,  when 
ideas  are  obscure,  they  are  not  rational  ones,  and  then  to  add, 
as  Stillingfleet  does,  "  if  we  cannot  come  at  the  rational  idea  " 
of  a  thing,  "  we  can  have  no  principle  of  certainty  to  go  upon." 
Religion  rests  upon  a  set  of  truths  which  exactly  miss  the 
condition  of  rational  truth  here  laid  down.  To  disprove 
this  condition,  then,  to  lay  down  the  consistency  of  a  rational 
character  with  an  obscure  and  indistinct  one  in  ideas,  is  not 
to  overthrow  religion,  but  support  it  on  the  most  essential  head. 
So  surely  do  we  find  that  no  discoveries  in  philosophy,  meta- 
physical or  natural,  really  turns  out  to  the  injury  of  the  faith. 
Hume,  as  Locke,  acknowledges  virtually  this  class  of  in- 
distinct ideas,  though  not  definitely  and  as  a  class.  Thus, 
while  showing  with  such  extreme  acuteness  that  we  have  no 
idea  of  a  cause,  he  allows  the  thing ;  asserting  strongly  the 
necessity  of  attributing  the  existence  of  the  world  to  a  cause. 
"  When  our  contemplation  is  so  far  enlarged  as  to  contem- 
plate the  first  rise  of  this  visible  system,  we  must  adopt  with 
the  strongest  conviction  the  idea  of  some  intelligent  cause." 
— Natural  History  of  Religion,  sect.  xv.  But  we  could  not 
lay  it  down  that  a  cause  was  necessary  unless  we  had  some 
idea  of  one.  What  is  this  then  but  to  say,  that  we  have  some 
idea,  but  not  a  true  one,  of  a  cause, — an  obscure,  incipient  idea. 
The  very  acuteness  with  which  the  philosopher  has  proved 
that  we  have  "  no  idea  "  of  a  cause  thus  turns  to  the  establish- 
ing of  this  kind  of  truth  that  I  am  speaking  of,  obscure,  in- 
cipient, or  mysterious  truth.  Hume  acknowledges  too  the  ex- 
istence of  "  a  vulgar,  inaccurate  idea  of  power." — Enquiry 
concerning  the  Human  Understanding,  sect.  vii.  But  what 
is  this  vulgar,  inaccurate  idea,  but  an  idea  which  all  man- 
kind have,  an  instinct,  or  indistinct  perception  ? 


348  NOTE   V. 


NOTE  V.  p.  27. 

MR.  MILL'S  argument  in  favour  of  the  doctrine  of  necessity 
consists  of  two  parts :  one  the  proof  of  the  doctrine ;  the 
other  an  answer  to  an  objection  to  it. 

His  proof  of  the  doctrine  is  an  inductive  one.  What  do 
we  mean  by  necessity,  he  asks,  but  causation ;  that,  the  an- 
tecedents supposed,  a  certain  consequent  will  follow  ?  Now, 
we  observe,  he  says,  this  law  of  causation  in  every  other  de- 
partment :  we  must  therefore  suppose  it  to  exist  in  the  de- 
partment of  the  human  will.  For  the  proof  of  the  existence 
of  this  law  in  other  departments  he  refers  us  to  facts,  and 
simply  appeals  to  observation.  "  Between  the  phenomena 
which  exist  at  any  instant,  and  the  phenomena  which  exist 
at  the  succeeding  instant,  there  is  an  invariable  order  of 
succession  ...  To  certain  facts  certain  facts  always  do,  and, 
as  we  believe,  will  continue  to,  succeed.  The  invariable 
antecedent  is  termed  the  cause;  the  invariable  consequent 
the  effect.  And  the  universality  of  the  law  consists  in  this, 
that  every  consequent  is  connected  in  this  manner  with  some 
particular  antecedent  or  set  of  antecedents.  Let  the  fact  be 
what  it  may,  if  it  has  begun  to  exist  it  was  preceded  by  some 
fact  or  facts  with  which  it  is  invariably  connected.  For  every 
event  there  exists  some  combination  of  object  or  events,  some 
given  concurrence  of  circumstances,  positive  and  negative, 
the  occurrence  of  which  is  always  followed  by  the  pheno- 
menon. We  may  not  have  found  out  what  this  concurrence 
of  circumstances  may  be ;  but  we  never  doubt  that  there  is 
such  a  one,  and  that  it  never  occurs  without  having  the  phe- 
nomenon in  question  as  its  effect  or  consequence.  On  the 
universality  of  this  truth  depends  the  possibility  of  reducing 
the  inductive  process  to  rules." — Vol.  i.  p.  338. 

Here  is  an  appeal  to  our  observation  for  a  proof  of  the  law 
of  causation.  Mr.  Mill  does  not  go  to  any  a  priori  ground 
on  this  question,  or  avail  himself  of  the  maxim  that  every 
event  must  have  a  cause.  He  does  not  appeal  to  any  in- 
stinct of  reason  antecedently  demanding  a  cause  for  every 


NOTE  V.  349 

event ;  nor  does  he  attach  to  the  term  cause  any  sense  of 
necessary  and  inherent  efficiency  and  productiveness  in  re- 
lation to  its  effect  — ( '  any  such  mysterious  compulsion  now 
supposed,  by  the  best  philosophical  authorities,  to  be  exer- 
cised by  the  cause  over  its  effect." — Vol.  ii.  p.  407.  By 
cause  and  effect  he  simply  means  antecedent  and  consequent ; 
and  he  appeals  to  our  simple  observation  for  the  proof  of  the 
existence  of  this  order  and  succession  in  things  around  us. 

Now,  it  would  be  obviously  begging  the  question  to  assert 
that  we  observe  this  uniform  order  and  succession  in  the  events 
in  which  the  human  will  takes  part ;  this  would  be  asserting 
to  begin  with  what  has  to  be  proved — viz.  that  this  law  of 
causation  exists  in  the  department  of  the  human  will;  be- 
sides, that  it  would  be  asserting  our  observation  of  something 
which  we  evidently  do  not  observe.  For  whatever  uni- 
formity we  may  observe  in  the  conduct  of  mankind  as  a  mass, 
however  like  one  generation  of  men  may  be  to  another,  and 
a  preceding  age  of  the  world  to  a  succeeding  one,  in  general 
moral  features  and  the  principles  on  which  the  race  is  go- 
verned and  acts,  we  evidently  do  not  observe  this  uniformity 
in  the  case  of  individuals.  And  it  is  the  case  of  the  indi- 
vidual which  tries  the  theory  of  necessity  or  causation  as 
applying  to  the  human  will.  Upon  the  ordinary  doctrine  of 
chances  there  will  be  much  the  same  amount  of  virtue  and 
vice  in  one  generation  that  there  is  in  others,  and  the  same 
general  exhibition  of  character  will  take  place.  The  doc- 
trine of  necessity  requires  that  the  individual  will  act  in  the 
same  way  under  the  same  circumstances.  And  this  latter 
fact  we  certainly  do  not  observe.  Mr  Mill,  then,  in  appeal- 
ing to  our  observation  for  a  proof  of  the  law  of  causation, 
must  mean  to  exclude  from  the  events  in  which  this  is  ob- 
served those  in  which  the  human  will  takes  part ;  i.  e.  to 
appeal  to  our  observation  of  material  nature  only.  And 
therefore  his  argument,  when  he  comes  to  assert  this  law  as 
prevailing  in  the  department  of  will,  is  one  of  induction, — 
the  common  argument  from  the  known  to  the  unknown. 
We  know,  he  says,  that  this  is  the  law  upon  which  one 
large  class  of  events  takes  place ;  we  must  therefore  suppose 
it  to  be  the  law  upon  which  another  class  of  events,  with  re- 


350  NOTE    V. 

spect  to  which  we  have  not  this  knowledge,  takes  place  ;  we 
observe  this  law  in  the  physical  world,  we  must  therefore 
presume  that  it  prevails  in  the  moral  as  well. 

Of  such  an  argument  as  this,  then,  it  will,  perhaps,  be 
enough  to  remark,  that  it  appears  to  be  nothing  more  than  a 
presumption  at  the  best.  One  class  of  events  takes  place 
according  to  a  certain  law  ;  therefore  another  does.  Is  this 
a  proof  to  satisfy  any  reasonable  m'ind  ?  Such  an  induction 
is,  on  the  first  showing,  in  the  highest  degree  weak  and  con- 
jectural. But  when  we  compare  matter  and  will,  and  dis- 
tinguish the  entirely  different  impressions  which  we  have 
with  respect  to  our  actions,  and  events  in  nature,  the  in- 
duction breaks  down  still  more.  Why  should  we  suppose 
that  events  so  totally  different  in  all  their  characteristics,  as 
those  which  take  place  in  matter  and  will,  should  take  place  on 
the  same  law;  and  presume  that,  because  causation  or  necessity 
rules  in  the  physical  world,  it  therefore  does  in  the  moral  ? 

But  while  I  interpret  Mr.  Mill's  argument  as  an  inductive 
one  —  which  indeed  appears  to  be  the  only  kind  of  argument 
which  observation  enables  him  to  use, — I  must  at  the  same 
time  allow  that  Mr.  Mill  in  other  passages  does  not  appear  al- 
together to  interpret  his  own  argument  in  this  way  ;  and  that 
he  seems  to  imagine  that  he  has  more  than  an  inductive,  i.  e. 
presumptive,  argument — viz.  one  of  actual  consciousness  and 
experience  in  his  favour,  on  this  question.  "  Correctly  con- 
ceived," he  says,  "  the  doctrine  called  Philosophical  Necessity 
is  simply  this :  that,  given  the  motives  which  are  present  to 
an  individual  mind,  and  given  likewise  the  character  and 
disposition  of  the  individual,  the  manner  in  which  he  will  act 
may  be  unerringly  inferred;  that  if  we  know  the  person 
thoroughly,  and  know  all  the  inducements  which  are  acting 
upon  him,  we  could  foretell  his  conduct  with  as  much  cer- 
tainty as  we  can  predict  any  physical  event.  This  proposi- 
tion I  take  to  be  a  mere  interpretation  of  universal  experience) 
a  statement  in  words  of  what  every  one  is  internally  convinced 
of.  No  one  who  believed  that  he  knew  thoroughly  the  cir- 
cumstances of  any  case,  and  the  characters  of  the  different 
persons  concerned,  would  hesitate  to  foretell  how  all  of  them 
would  act.  Whatever  degree  of  doubt  he  may  feel  arises 


NOTE   V.  351 

from  the  uncertainty  whether  he  really  knows  the  circum- 
stances or  the  character  of  some  one  or  other  of  the  persons 
with  the  degree  of  accuracy  required;  but  by  no  means 
from  thinking,  that  if  he  did  know  these  things,  there  would 
be  any  uncertainty  what  the  conduct  would  be.  Nor  does 
this  full  assurance  conflict  in  the  smallest  degree  with  what 
is  called  our  feeling  of  freedom." — Vol.  ii.  p.  406. 

I  quote  this  passage  not  for  the  statement  it  contains  of 
the  doctrine  of  necessity  so  much  as  to  call  attention  to  the 
ground  of  that  statement,  — the  nature  of  the  argument  or 
evidence  on  which  the  writer  appears  to  suppose  that  doctrine 
of  necessity  rests.  "  This  proposition,"  he  says,  "  I  take  to 
be  a  mere  interpretation  of  universal  experience,  a  statement 
in  words  of  what  every  one  is  internally  convinced  of;  "  the 
proposition,  viz.  that  the  inducements  internal  and  external 
to  action  supposed,  the  action  of  an  individual  may  be  pre- 
dicted with  as  much  certainty  as  we  can  predict  any  physical 
event.  Mr.  Mill  then  appeals  to  actual  experience,  and  to 
internal  conviction  or  consciousness,  as  the  evidence  of  the 
doctrine  of  necessity.  Now,  if  Mr.  Mill  were  content  to 
mean  by  this  experience  and  internal  conviction  of  necessity 
to  which  he  appeals,  such  an  indistinct  or  half-perception  of 
a  truth  in  this  direction  as  is  consistent  with  the  same  kind 
of  perception  of  the  contrary  truth  of  our  originality  as  agents, 
I  would  agree  with  him  ;  and  I  have  in  this  chapter  accepted 
the  necessitarian  maxim,  that  every  event  must  have  a  cause, 
as  supplying  one  side  of  the  truth  on  this  question.  But 
it  is  evident  that  Mr.  Mill  means  something  more  than 
this ;  his  argument,  as  an  advocate  of  necessity  against 
originality,  requires  a  full  and  distinct  experience  and  con- 
viction on  the  side  of  necessity,  not  a  divided  one.  More- 
over, the  ground  on  which  he  has  placed  the  whole  doctrine 
of  necessity  or  causation  is  a  ground  of  observation  —  that  we 
see  things,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  taking  place  in  a  certain  order 
and  succession.  When  he  appeals,  then,  to  an  internal  expe- 
rience and  conviction  on  the  side  of  necessity,  his  argument 
requires  him  to  appeal  to  such  a  full  internal  conviction  as  is 
grounded  on  observation.  But  can  Mr.  Mill  really  mean  to 
assert  that  we  observe  a  law  of  causation  in  operation  in  our 


352  NOTE   V. 

actions,  as  we  do  in  the  events  of  the  physical  world?  Such  an 
assertion  would  be  plainly  untrue,  and  he  himself  would  be  the 
first  to  disown  it ;  for  he  explains  how  it  is  that  we  cannot 
observe  such  a  law  in  the  case  of  human  actions,  as  we  do  in 
nature  ;  viz.  that  we  have  not  the  full  antecedents  before  us 
in  the  former  case  as  we  have  in  the  latter ;  that  we  do  not 
know  all  the  inducements,  internal  and  external,  operating  in 
a  man,  and,  therefore,  cannot  predict  with  accuracy  what  his 
action  will  be.  But  then  what  becomes  of  that  experience 
and  internal  conviction  to  which  he  appeals  on  this  question  ? 
If  we  are  not  able  to  make  the  observation  that  we  act  by  a 
law  of  causation,  how  can  we  have  the  experience  and  the  in- 
ternal conviction  that  we  do  ?  What  sort  of  conviction,  on  his 
own  showing,  must  that  be,  which  has  positively  no  observa- 
tion to  rest  upon  ? 

The  state  of  the  case,  then,  appears  to  be  this :  Mr.  Mill  be- 
gins with  an  inductive  or  presumptive  argument  on  this  ques- 
tion, which,  as  he  proceeds  and  advances  in  his  explanation  of 
it,  becomes  insensibly  from  an  inductive  argument,  an  appeal 
to  "  internal  conviction,"  or  consciousness.  And  instead  of 
saying,  the  law  of  causation  exists  in  the  case  of  physical 
events,  therefore  we  may  presume  it  does  in  the  case  of  moral 
ones  or  actions, — he  says  at  once  we  see,  we  know,  we  are  in- 
ternally convinced,  we  have  actual  experience,  that  our  actions 
take  place  upon  this  law. 

Having  established,  however,  whether  by  induction  or  ex- 
perience or  internal  conviction,  necessity  or  the  law  of  causa- 
tion, as  the  law  upon  which  the  acts  of  the  human  will  proceed, 
Mr.  Mill  has  to  meet  an  objection  to  such  a  position  which 
naturally  and  immediately  arises  from  our  consciousness  of 
freedom  as  agents.  "  To  the  universality  which  mankind  are 
agreed  in  ascribing  to  the  law  of  causation  there  is  one  claim 
of  exception,  one  disputed  case,  that  of  the  human  will ;  the 
determinations  of  which  a  large  class  of  metaphysicians  are 
not  willing  to  regard  as  following  the  causes  called  motives, 
according  to  as  strict  laws  as  those  which  they  suppose  to 
exist  in  the  world  of  mere  matter.  This  controverted  point 
will  undergo  a  special  examination  when  we  come  to  treat 
particularly  of  the  logic  of  the  moral  sciences.  In  the  mean- 


NOTE   V.  353 

time  I  may  remark  that  metaphysicians,  who,  it  must  be 
observed,  ground  the  main  part  of  their  objection  on  the 
supposed  repugnance  of  the  doctrine  in  question  to  our 
consciousness,  seem  to  me  to  mistake  the  fact  which  con- 
sciousness testifies  against.  What  is  really  in  contradiction 
to  consciousness,  they  would,  I  think,  on  strict  self-examina- 
tion, find  to  be  the  application  to  human  actions  and  voli- 
tions of  the  ideas  involved  in  the  common  use  of  the  term 
necessity,  which  I  agree  with  them  in  objecting  to.  But  if 
they  would  consider  that  by  saying  that  a  person's  actions 
necessarily  follow  from  his  character,  all  that  is  really  meant 
(for  no  more  is  meant  in  any  case  whatever  of  causation)  is 
that  he  invariably  does  act  in  conformity  to  his  character, 
and  that  any  one  who  thoroughly  knew  his  character  could 
certainly  predict  how  he  would  act  in  any  supposable  case, 
they  probably  would  not  find  this  doctrine  either  contrary 
to  their  experience  or  revolting  to  their  feelings."  —  Vol.  i. 
p.  358. 

I  will  stop,  in  the  first  place,  to  ask,  what  is  meant  by  the 
word  "  character,"  in  the  assertion  that  "  a  person's  actions 
necessarily  follow  from  his  ( character  ?' ;  If  the  term 
character  here  includes  a  man's  whole  conduct  and  action, 
this  assertion  amounts  to  nothing.  If  the  term  means  simply 
a  certain  general  disposition  and  bias  of  mind,  then  the 
assertion  is  without  proof;  the  assertion,  I  mean,  that  from 
this  general  disposition  a  particular  act  will  follow.  The 
main  object  of  this  passage,  however,  is  to  meet  the  ob- 
jection to  the  doctrine  of  necessity  proceeding  from  our 
consciousness  of  freedom  as  agents  ;  an  objection  which 
Mr.  Mill  meets  with  a  distinction  between  necessity  in  the 
sense  of  causation,  and  necessity  in  the  "common  use  of 
the  term,"  viz.  as  coaction  or  force ;  necessity  in  the  former 
sense  not  being  opposed  to  our  consciousness.  The  same 
answer  is  contained  in  the  following  passage :  f(  The  meta- 
physical theory  of  freewill  as  held  by  philosophers  (for 
the  practical  feeling  of  it,  common  in  a  greater  or  less 
degree  to  all  mankind,  is  in  no  way  inconsistent  with  the 
contrary  theory)  was  invented  because  the  supposed  alter- 
native of  admitting  human  actions  to  be  necessary  was 

A   A 


354  NOTE   V. 

deemed  inconsistent  with  every  one's  instinctive  conscious- 
ness, as  well  as  humiliating  to  the  pride  and  degrading  to  the 
moral  nature  of  man.  Nor  do  I  deny  that  the  doctrine,  as 
sometimes  held,  is  open  to  these  imputations ;  for  the  mis- 
apprehension in  which  I  shall  be  able  to  show  that  they 
originate,  unfortunately  is  not  confined  to  the  opponents  of 
the  doctrine,  but  participated  in  by  many,  perhaps  we  might 
say  by  most,  of  its  supporters." — Vol.  ii.  p.  405. 

Now,  it  must  be  admitted  that  the  doctrine  of  necessity  is 
not  opposed  to  any  express  and  distinct  consciousness  on  our 
part,  for  all  that  we  are  distinctly  anxious  of  is  our  willing 
itself;  we  have  no  positive  apprehension  or  perception  of  any 
thing  beyond  that  fact,  i.  e.  of  the  source  of  such  willing, 
whether  this  is  in  ourselves,  or  beyond  and  outside  of  us. 
But  though  we  have  no  distinct  apprehension  of  our  own  ori- 
ginality as  agents,  is  there  not  an  instinctive  perception  in 
that  direction  9  Does  not  the  whole  manner  in  which  we  find 
ourselves,  willing  and  choosing,  debating  between  conflicting 
lines  of  action,  and  then  deciding  on  one  or  other  of  them, 
lead  us  towards  an  idea  of  our  own  originality  as  agents,  and 
produce  that  impression  upon  us  ?  Would  not  any  person, 
holding  to  his  natural  impression  on  this  head,  be  disappointed 
by  any  explanation  of  these  characteristics  of  human  action, 
which  accounted  for  them  on  any  rationale  short  of  originality  ? 
Would  he  not  feel  that  there  was  something  passed  over,  not 
duly  acknowledged,  and  recognised,  in  any  rationale  which 
stopped  short  of  this  ?  You  might  explain  to  him  that  his 
will  being  caused  from  without  did  not  imply  any  force  or 
coaction,  but  that  he  might  have  all  the  sensations  of  voluntary 
agency  while  he  was  still  really  acting  from  causes  ultimately 
beyond  his  own  control ;  but  such  an  explanation  would  not 
satisfy  him.  The  feeling  he  has  that  he  can  decide  either 
way  in  the  case  of  any  proposed  action,  and  the  regret  or 
pleasure  that  he  feels  afterwards,  according  to  the  use  which 
he  has  made  of  this  apparent  power,  will  make  him  think 
himself  an  original  agent,  and  he  will  be  dissatisfied  with  any 
rationale  of  his  action  which  stops  short  of  this. 

Mr.  Mill  is  indeed  sufficiently  aware  of  the  strength  of  this 
natural  conviction  of  originality  in  the  human  mind,  to  be  in- 


NOTE    V.  355 

duced  to  meet  and  satisfy  its  demands  as  far  as  he  can  in  con- 
sistency with  his  theory ;  but  he  cannot,  because  his  theory 
prevents  him,  really  satisfy  them.  He  admits,  however,  for 
the  purpose  of  satisfying  this  claim,  that  a  man  can  in  a  certain 
sense  form  his  own  character,  and  is  an  agent  acting  upon 
himself,  and  he  draws  a  distinction  on  this  head  between  the 
necessarian  and  the  fatalist ;  the  former  of  whom,  according 
to  him,  allows,  in  keeping  with  true  philosophy,  this  agency 
upon  self,  which  the  latter,  carried  away  by  the  fallacy  that 
the  certainty  of  the  end  supersedes  the  necessity  of  the  means 
or  subordinate  agencies,  denies  it.  "  A  fatalist  believes,  or 
half  believes  (for  nobody  is  a  consistent  fatalist),  not  only  that 
whatever  is  about  to  happen  will  be  an  infallible  result  of  the 
causes  which  produce  it  (which  is  the  true  necessarian  doctrine), 
but,  moreover,  that  there  is  no  use  struggling  against  it;  that 
it  will  happen  however  we  may  strive  to  prevent  it.  Now, 
a  necessarian  believing  that  our  actions  follow  from  our  cha- 
racters, and  that  our  characters  follow  from  our  organisation, 
our  education,  and  our  circumstances,  is  apt  to  be,  with  more 
or  less  of  consciousness  on  his  part,  a  fatalist  as  to  his  actions, 
and  to  believe  that  his  nature  is  such,  or  that  his  education 
and  circumstances  have  so  moulded  his  character,  that  nothing 
can  now  prevent  him  from  feeling  and  acting  in  a  particular 
way,  or  at  least  that  no  effort  of  his  own  can  hinder  it.  In 
the  words  of  the  sect  (Owenite)  which  in  our  own  day  has 
most  perniciously  inculcated  and  most  perversely  misunder- 
stood this  great  doctrine,  his  character  is  formed  for  him, 
and  not  by  him ;  therefore  his  wishing  that  it  had  been  formed 
differently  is  of  no  use,  he  has  no  power  to  alter  it.  But 
this  is  a  grand  error.  He  has  to  a  certain  extent  a  power  to 
alter  his  character.  Its  being  in  the  ultimate  resort  formed  for 
him  is  not  inconsistent  with  its  being  in  part  formed  by  him  as 
one  of  the  intermediate  agents.  His  character  is  formed  by  his 
circumstances  (including  among  these  his  particular  organisa- 
tion); but  his  own  desire  to  mould  it  in  a  particular  way  is  one 
of  those  circumstances,  and  by  no  means  one  of  the  least  in- 
fluential. We  cannot,  indeed,  directly  will  to  be  different 
from  what  we  are ;  but  neither  did  those  who  are  supposed 
to  have  formed  our  characters  directly  will  that  we  should 

A  A   2 


356  NOTE    V. 

be  what  we  are. .  .  .  We  are  exactly  as  capable  of  making  our 
own  character,  if  we  will,  as  others  are  of  making  it  for  us."  — 
Vol.  ii.  p.  410. 

Here  is  an  attempt,  then,  to  represent  the  necessarian  system 
in  such  an  aspect,  as  to  reconcile  it  with  all  those  sensations 
of  power  over  ourselves  and  over  our  conduct,  which  are  part 
of  our  internal  experience.  But  the  attempt  fails,  because 
it  will  not  go  the  proper  length  of  acknowledging  such  power 
as  an  original  one.  A  man  "  has,  to  a  certain  extent,  a  power 
to  alter  his  own  character."  To  what  extent,  or  in  what 
sense  ?  While  it  is  "  in  the  ultimate  resort  formed  for  him, 
it  is  formed  by  him  as  one  of  the  intermediate  agents"  But 
does  this  concession  of  an  intermediate  agency  satisfy  the 
demands  of  natural  feeling  and  instinct  on  this  head  ?  Would 
any  person  naturally  regard  that  power  of  choice,  of  which 
he  is  conscious,  as  a  power  which  he  exerts  in  obedience  and 
subordination  to  some  deeper  cause  working  underneath  it, 
and  obliging  it  to  be  exerted  in  a  particular  way  ?  Would 
not  a  certain  instinctive  view  he  takes  of  this  agency  in  him 
be  contradicted  by  this  view  of  it  as  intermediate  agency, 
only  apparently  original,  and  really  produced  by  a  cause  be- 
yond itself?  Would  not  his  internal  sensations  appear  upon 
such  a  view  to  him  a  spurious  outside,  a  kind  of  semblance 
and  sham,  pretending  something  which  was  not  really  true, 
and  deluding  him  into  thinking  that  he  was  an  original  agent 
when  he  really  was  not  ? 

While,  then,  I  fully  admit,  in  addition  to  these  ideas  and 
sensations  of  originality  and  free  agency,  other  ideas  counter 
to  them  —  another  side  of  the  human  mind  to  which  philoso- 
phy and  theology  have  alike  legitimately  appealed,  and  with- 
out which  neither  necessarianism  nor  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin  would  have  arisen, — I  cannot  think  that  Mr.  Mill  does 
justice  to  these  ideas  —  these  true  perceptions,  it  appears  to 
me,  as  far  as  they  go — of  our  originality  as  agents. 

Hume's  argument  on  Liberty  and  Necessity  is  a  very 
summary  one.  He  does  not,  as  Mr.  Mill,  in  the  first  instance, 
appears  to  do,  from  the  observed  fact  of  causation  or  necessity 
in  the  physical  world,  presume  the  same  thing  in  the  moral ; 
he  boldly  appeals  at  once  to  what  he  considers  to  be  an  ob- 


NOTE   V.  357 

vious  and  plain  fact  of  observation.  He  considers  necessity, 
or  the  law  of  antecedent  and  consequent,  to  be  as  plain  and 
obvious  in  the  case  of  human  actions  as  it  is  in  the  events  of 
material  nature.  "  Our  idea,"  he  says,  "  of  necessity  or  cau- 
sation arises  entirely  from  the  uniformity  observable  in  the 
operations  of  nature.  Where  similar  objects  are  constantly 
conjoined  together,  and  the  mind  is  determined  by  custom  to 
infer  the  one  from  the  appearance  of  the  other,  these  two 
circumstances  form  the  whole  of  that  necessity  which  we 
ascribe  to  matter.  Beyond  the  constant  conjunction  of  similar 
objects,  and  the  consequent  inference  from  one  to  the  other, 
we  have  no  idea  of  any  necessity  of  connexion.  If  it  appear, 
therefore,  that  all  mankind  have  ever  allowed,  without  any 
doubt  or  hesitation,  that  these  two  circumstances  take  place 
in  the  voluntary  actions  of  men,  and  in  the  operations  of  mind, 
it  must  follow  that  all  mankind  have  ever  agreed  in  the 
doctrine  of  necessity,  and  that  they  have  hitherto  disputed 
merely  for  not  understanding  one  another." 

"  As  to  the  first  circumstance,  the  constant  and  regular 
conjunction  of  similar  events,  we  may  perfectly  satisfy  our- 
selves by  the  following  considerations.  It  is  universally  ac- 
knowledged that  there  is  a  great  uniformity  among  the  ac- 
tions of  men,  in  all  nations  and  ages,  and  that  human  nature 
remains  still  the  same  in  its  principles  and  operations.  The 
same  motives  always  produce  the  same  actions ;  the  same 
events  follow  the  same  causes.  Ambition,  avarice,  self-love, 
vanity,  friendship,  generosity,  public  spirit ;  these  passions, 
mixed  in  various  degrees,  and  distributed  throughout  society, 
have  been  from  the  beginning  of  the  world,  and  still  are,  the 
sources  of  all  the  actions  and  enterprises  which  have  ever 
been  observed  among  mankind.  Would  you  know  the  senti- 
ments, inclinations,  and  course  of  life  of  the  Greeks  and 
Romans,  study  well  the  temper  and  actions  of  the  French 
and  English.  You  cannot  be  much  mistaken  in  transferring 
to  the  former  most  of  the  observations  you  have  made  with 
regard  to  the  latter.  Mankind  are  so  much  the  same,  in  all 
times  and  places,  that  history  informs  us  of  nothing  new  or 
strange  in  this  particular.  Its  chief  use  is  only  to  discover 
the  constant  and  universal  principles  of  human  nature,  by 

A   A   3 


358  NOTE   V. 

showing  man  in  all  varieties  of  circumstances  and  situations, 
and  furnishing  us  with  materials  from  which  we  may  form 
our  observations,  and  become  acquainted  with  the  regular 
springs  of  human  action  and  behaviour.  These  records  of 
war,  intrigues,  factions,  and  revolutions  are  so  many  collec- 
tions of  experiments  by  which  the  politician  or  moral  philoso- 
pher fixes  the  principles  of  his  science,  in  the  same  manner  as 
the  physician  or  natural  philosopher  becomes  acquainted  with 
the  nature  of  plants,  minerals,  and  other  external  objects  by 
the  experiments  which  he  forms  concerning  them.  Nor  are 
the  earth,  water,  and  other  elements  examined  by  Aristotle 
and  Hippocrates  more  like  to  those  which  at  present  lie  under 
our  observation,  than  the  men  described  by  Polybius  or 
Tacitus  are  to  those  who  now  govern  the  world."  —  Section 
viii.  On  Liberty  and  Necessity,  v.  iv.  p.  98. 

No  argument  on  the  side  of  necessity  in  human  actions  can 
be  simpler  than  this ;  and  if  there  is  any  weight  in  it,  the 
question  is  decided  beyond  controversy ;  for  it  is  simply  an 
appeal  to  our  observation  that  such  is  the  case,  an  assertion 
that  necessity  is  as  visible  in  human  actions  as  it  is  in  the 
events  of  nature.  But  any  reader  of  common  intelligence 
must  see  at  once  a  fundamental  error  underlying  this  whole 
argument,  which  entirely  deprives  it  of  force.  The  uni- 
formity which  the  writer  observes  in  human  life  and  conduct 
applies  to  mankind  as  a  whole ;  while  the  principle  of  ne- 
cessity can  only  be  properly  tested  by  the  conduct  of  men  as 
individuals.  On  the  common  doctrine  of  chances,  mankind 
as  a  whole  will  be  much  the  same  in  one  generation  and  age 
of  the  world  that  it  is  in  another ;  i.  e.  there  will  be  the  same 
proportion  of  good  to  bad  men,  the  same  relative  amount  of 
selfish  and  disinterested,  generous  and  mean,  courageous  and 
cowardly,  independent  and  servile  characters.  But  the  doc- 
trine of  necessity  is  concerned  with  the  individual  cases  which 
compose  this  general  average  of  human  character;  and  the 
question  upon  which  that  doctrine  turns  is,  whether  indivi- 
duals with  the  same  antecedents — i.  e.  the  same  inducements, 
external  and  internal,  to  particular  conduct — have  uniformly 
acted  in  the  same  way.  The  sum  total  may  be  the  same,  but 
the  question  of  necessity  is  concerned  with  the  units  which 


NOTE   VI.  359 

compose  that  sum.  Have  the  individuals  who  have  been  bad 
and  good,  selfish  and  disinterested,  been  so  in  conjunction 
with  different  respective  sets  of  antecedents ;  i.  e.  different  cir- 
cumstances, education  and  natural  temperament  ?  Or,  have 
not  persons  under  apparently  the  same  circumstances,  edu- 
cation, and  natural  temperament,  turned  out  very  differently  ? 
The  latter  is  certainly  the  more  natural  observation  of  the 
two.  But  if  we  are  forbidden  to  make  it,  and  reminded  that 
we  do  not  know  all  the  antecedents,  circumstances,  and  mo- 
tives, internal  and  external,  to  conduct,  in  the  case  of  indivi- 
duals ;  then  at  any  rate  nobody  can  pretend  to  have  made 
the  contrary  observation,  or  profess  to  have  noted  a  uniform 
conjunction  of  antecedents  and  consequents  in  the  case  of 
human  action.  And  with  the  absence  of  this  observation  the 
whole  of  this  argument  falls  to  the  ground. 


NOTE  VI.  p.  35. 

FUIT  Adam  et  in  illo  fuimus  omnes. — Ambrose,  Lib.  7.  in 
Luc.c.  15,  24.  n.  234.  In  lumbis  Adam  fuimus. — Aug.  Op. 
Imp.  1.  1.  c.  48.  Unusquisque  homo  cum  primo  nascitur. 

—  De  Gen.  Contr.  Man.  1.  1.  c.  23.     Sic  autem  aliena  sunt 
originalia  peccata  propter  nullum  in  eis  nosto  voluntatis  arbi- 
trium,  ut  tamen  propter  originis  contagium  esse  inveniantur 
ut  nostra. —  Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  57. 

Inobedientia  quidem  unius  hominis  non  absurde  utique 
delictum  dicitur  alienum,  quia  nondum  nati  nondum  egeramus 
aliquid  proprium,  sive  bonum  sive  malum :  sed  quia  in  illo  qui 
hoc  fecit,  quando  id  agit,  omnes  eramus  .  .  .  hoc  delictum 
alienum  obnoxia  successione  fit  nostrum. —  Op.  Imp.  1.  2. 
c.  163. 

Ipsos  quoque  hoc  in  parente  fecisse,  quoniam  quando  ipse 
fecit,  in  illo  fuerunt,  ac  sic  ipsi  atque  ille  adhuc  unus  fuerunt. 

—  Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  177. 

Disce,  si  potes,  quemadmodum  peccata  originalia,  et 
aliena  intelligantur  et  nostra ;  non  eadem  causa  aliena  qua 
nostra :  aliena  enim,  quia  non  ea  in  sua  vita  quisque  coin- 

A   A    4 


360  NOTE   VI. 

misit,  nostra  vero  quia  fecit  Adam,  etin  illo  fuimus  omnes. — 
Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  25. 

Malum  est  de  peccato  veniens  originis  vitium,  cum  quo 
nascitur  homo  .  .  .  cujus  mail  reatus  non  innocentibus,  ut 
dicis,  sed  reis  imputatur.  .  .  .  Sic  enim  fuerunt  ornnes  ratione 
seminis  in  lumbis  Adam,  quando  damnatus  est,  et  ideo  sine 
illis  damnatus  non  est ;  quemadmodum  fuerunt  Israelite  in 
lumbis  Abraha3  quando  decimatus  est,  et  ideo  sine  illis 
decimatus  non  est —  Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  12. 

Per  unius  illius  voluntatem  malam  omnes  in  eo  peccaverunt, 
quando  omnes  ille  unus  fuerunt. — De  Nupt.  et  Cone.  1.  2.n.  15. 

S.  Anselm  regards  that  corruption  of  nature  which  is  in 
the  infant  at  its  birth  as  sin  then  and  at  the  time  in  the  in- 
fant— cum  debito  satisfaciendi ;  so  that  it  is  his  own  sin  and 
not  another's  for  which  he  is  responsible  in  his  responsibility 
for  original  sin  (De  Pec.  Orig.  c,  2.) ;  a  position  to  which  he 
proceeds  to  give  further,  and  very  strong  and  exact  expres- 
sion: (t  Originale  peccatum  esse  injustitiam  dubitari  non 
debet.  Nam  si  omne  peccatum  injustitia,  et  originale  pec- 
catum utique  est  et  injustitia.  Sed  si  dicit  aliquis :  non 
est  omne  peccatum  injustitia,  dicat  posse  simul  in  aliquo 
et  esse  peccatum,  et  nullam  esse  injustitiam :  quod  videtur 
incredibile.  Si  vero  dicitur  originale  peccatum  non  esse 
absolute  dicendum  peccatum,  sed  cum  additamento,  originale 
peccatum,  sicut  pictus  homo  non  vere  homo  est,  sed  vere  est 
pictus  homo,  profecto  sequitur  quia  infans  qui  nullum  habet 
peccatum  nisi  originale  mundus  est  a  peccato.  .  .  .  Qtiare 
omne  peccatum  est  injustitia,  et  originale  peccatum  est  abso- 
lute peccatum." — C.  3. 

Aquinas  is  against  the  imputation  of  another's  act  for  the 
purpose  of  guilt,  though  he  allows  it  for  that  of  satisfaction  : 
u  Dicendum  quod  si  loquamur  de  pcena  satisfactoria,  quae 
voluntarie  assumitur,  contingit  quod  cum  unus  portet  poenam 
alterius,  in  quantum  sunt  quodammodo  unum.  Si  autem 
loquimur  de  poena  pro  peccato  inflicta,  in  quantum  habet 
rationem  poenae,  sic  solum  unusquisque  pro  peccato  suo 
punitur,  quia  actus  peccati  aliquid  personale  est."  —  Sum. 
Theol  lma  2dae  Q.  87.  Art.  8. 

The  disputes  at  the  Council  of  Trent  on  the  subject  of 
original  sin  touched  more  on  the  extent  of  the  effects  of  it 


NOTE   VII.  361 

than  on  the  rationale  of  its  transmission.  But  the  view  of 
imputation  was  maintained  by  Catarinus  against  the  Domi- 
nicans, who  followed  the  Augustinian  idea  of  original  sin  as 
real  sin  in  the  individual.  "  He  oppugned  the  transmission 
of  sin  by  means  of  the  seed  and  generation ;  saying  that,  as, 
if  Adam  had  not  sinned,  righteousness  would  have  been 
infused  not  by  virtue  of  the  generation,  but  only  by  the 
will  of  God,  so  it  is  fit  to  find  another  means  to  transfuse 
sin  .  .  .  The  action  of  Adam  is  actual  sin  in  him,  arid  imputed 
to  others  is  original;  because  when  he  sinned  all  men  did 
(i.  e.  by  imputation)  sin  with  him.  Catarinus  grounded 
himself  principally,  for  that  a  true  and  proper  sin  must  be  a 
voluntary  act,  and  no  other  thing  can  be  voluntary  but  the 
transgression  of  Adam  imputed  unto  all  ....  The  opinion  of 
Catarinus  was  expressed  by  a  political  conceit  of  a  bargain 
made  by  one  for  his  posterity,  which,  being  transgressed, 
they  are  all  undoubtedly  bound." — PauTs  History  of  Council 
of  Trent  (Brent),  pp.  165.  168. 


NOTE  VII.  p.  36. 

JEREMY  TAYLOR'S  argument  on  original  sin  is  directed 
throughout  against  the  received  and  Catholic  interpretation 
of  that  sin,  as  involving  desert  of  eternal  punishment,  which 
he  rejects  as  being  opposed  to  our  natural  idea  of  justice. 
"  Was  it  just  in  God  to  damn  all  mankind  to  the  eternal 
pains  of  hell  for  Adam's  sin  committed  before  they  had  any 
being,  or  could  consent  to  it  or  know  of  it  ?  If  it  could  be 
just,  then  anything  in  the  world  can  be  just ;  and  it  is  no 
matter  who  is  innocent,  or  who  is  criminal,  directly  or  by 
choice,  since  they  may  turn  devils  in  their  mother's  bellies ; 
and  it  matters  not  whether  there  be  any  laws  or  no,  since 
it  is  all  one  that  there  be  no  laws,  and  that  we  do  not  know 
whether  there  be  or  no ;  and  it  matters  not  whether  there  be 
any  judicial  proofs,  for  we  may  as  well  be  damned  without 
judgment,  as  be  guilty  without  action." — Vol.  ix.  p.  332. 
"  And  truly,  my  Lord,  to  say  that  for  Adam's  sin  it  is  just 
in  God  to  condemn  infants  to  the  eternal  flames  of  hell,  and 


362  NOTE   VII. 

to  say  that  concupiscence  or  natural  inclinations  before  they 
pass  into  any  act  would  bring  eternal  condemnation  from 
God's  presence  into  the  eternal  portion  of  devils,  are  two 
such  horrid  propositions,  that  if  any  church  in  the  world 
should  expressly  affirm  them,  I,  for  my  part,  should  think  it 
unlawful  to  communicate  with  her  in  the  defence  or  profes- 
sion of  either,  and  to  think  it  would  be  the  greatest  tempta- 
tion in  the  world  to  make  men  not  to  love  God,  of  whom  men 
so  easily  speak  such  horrid  things." — p.  373.  "Is  hell  so  easy 
a  pain,  or  are  the  souls  of  children  of  so  cheap,  so  contempti- 
ble a  price,  that  God  should  so  easily  throw  them  into  hell  ? 
God's  goodness,  which  pardons  many  sins  that  we  could  avoid, 
will  not  so  easily  throw  them  into  hell  for  what  they  could 
not  avoid." — p.  14.  "To  condemn  infants  to  hell  for  the 
fault  of  another,  is  to  deal  worse  with  them  than  God  did  to 
the  very  devils,  who  did  not  perish  but  by  an  act  of  their  own 
most  perfect  choice.  This,  besides  the  formality  of  injustice 
or  cruelty,  does  add  and  suppose  a  circumstance  of  a  strange, 
ungentle  contrivance.  For,  because  it  cannot  be  supposed 
that  God  should  damn  infants  or  innocents  without  cause,  it 
finds  out  this  way,  that  God,  to  bring  His  purposes  to  pass, 
should  create  a  guilt  for  them,  or  bring  them  into  an  inevita- 
ble condition  of  being  guilty  by  a  way  of  His  own  inventing. 
For,  if  He  did  not  make  such  an  agreement  with  Adam,  He 
beforehand  knew  that  Adam  would  forfeit  all,  and  therefore 
that  unavoidably  all  his  posterity  would  be  surprised.  This 
is  to  make  pretences,  and  to  invent  justifications  and  reasons 
of  His  proceedings,  which  are  indeed  all  one  as  if  they  were 
not." — p.  16.  "Abraham  was  confident  with  God,  'Wilt 
Thou  slay  the  righteous  with  the  wicked  ?  shall  not  the  Judge 
of  all  the  earth  do  right  ? '  And  if  it  be  unrighteous  to  slay 
the  righteous  with  the  wicked,  it  is  also  unjust  to  slay  the 
righteous  for  the  wicked.  '  Ferretne  ulla  dvitas  laborem 
istiusmodi  legis,  ut  condemnetur  JiUus  aut  nepos,  si  pater  aut 
avus  deliquissent ;  —  It  were  an  intolerable  law,  and  no  com- 
munity would  be  governed  by  it,  that  the  father  or  grand- 
father should  sin,  and  the  son  or  nephew  should  be  pu- 
nished.'"—p.  39. 

No  one  can,  of  course,  deny  the  force  of  these  arguments, 


NOTE   VII.  363 

resting,  as  they  do,  upon  the  simple  maxim  of  common  sense 
and  common  justice,  that  no  man  is  responsible  for  another's 
sins.  The  mistake  in  Jeremy  Taylor's  mind  lies  in  his  con- 
ception of  the  doctrine  which  he  is  attacking.  He  supposes 
the  doctrine  of  original  sin  to  assert  mankind's  desert  of  eternal 
punishment  for  Adam's  sin,  in  an  ordinary  and  matter-of-fact 
sense;  and  he  treats  all  the  consequences  of  this  doctrine — the 
Divine  anger  with  infants  and  the  like  —  as  if  they  took  place 
in  the  literal  sense  in  which  they  would  take  place,  supposing 
a  present  visible  execution  of  this  sentence,  in  this  present 
and  visible  state  of  things.  But  the  doctrine  of  original  sin 
professes  to  be  concerned  with  a  mystery,  not  with  a  matter 
of  fact,  and  to  be  an  incomprehensible,  and  not  an  intelligible 
truth.  For  all  this  vivid  picture,  then,  of  injustice,  and 
monstrous  cruelty  which  Jeremy  Taylor  raises  as  a  represen- 
tation of  this  doctrine,  there  is  no  warrant ;  because  the 
doctrine  does  not  profess  to  assert  anything  whatever  that 
we  can  understand.  He  argues  as  if  human  analogies  gave 
us  a  sufficient  and  true  idea  of  the  truth  asserted  in  this 
doctrine,  whereas  the  doctrine  takes  us  out  of  all  human 
analogies.  His  whole  argument  thus  beats  the  air,  and  he 
refutes  what  no  sound-minded  and  reasonable  person  asserts. 

His  argument  against  the  assertion  of  the  impotence  and 
slavery  of  the  will,  involved  in  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  is 
open  to  the  same  remark  ;  i.  e.  that  he  takes  it  as  an  absolute 
assertion,  whereas  it  is  only  maintained  in  this  doctrine  as  one 
side  of  a  whole  truth  on  this  subject,  which  is  beyond  our 
knowledge.  "  To  deny  to  the  will  of  man  powers  of  choice 
and  election,  or  the  use  of  it  in  the  actions  of  our  life,  de- 
stroys the  immortality  of  the  soul.  Human  nature  is  in  danger 
to  be  lost  if  it  diverts  to  that  which  is  against  nature  !  For 
if  it  be  immortal  it  can  never  die  in  its  noblest  faculty.  But 
if  the  will  be  destroyed,  that  is,  disabled  from  choosing  (which 
is  all  the  work  the  will  hath  to  do),  then  it  is  dead.  For  to 
live  and  to  be  able  to  operate  in  philosophy  are  all  one.  If 
the  will,  therefore,  cannot  operate,  how  is  it  immortal?  And 
we  may  as  well  suppose  an  understanding  that  can  never 
understand,  and  passions  that  can  never  desire  or  refuse,  and 
a  memory  that  can  never  remember,  as  a  will  that  cannot 


364  NOTE   VII. 

choose." — Vol.  ix.  p.  47.  "  When  it  is  affirmed  in  the  writings 
of  some  doctors  that  the  will  of  man  is  depraved,  men 
presently  suppose  that  depravation  is  a  natural  or  physical 
effect,  and  means  a  diminution  of  power,  whereas  it  signifies 
nothing  but  a  being  in  love  with,  or  having  chosen  an  evil 
object,  and  not  an  impossibility  or  weakness  to  the  contrary, 
but  only  because  it  will  not ;  for  the  power  of  the  will  cannot 
be  lessened  by  any  act  of  the  same  faculty,  for  the  act  is  not 
contrary  to  the  faculty,  and  therefore  can  do  nothing  towards 
its  destruction.  As  a  consequent  of  this  I  infer  that  there 
is  no  natural  necessity  of  sinning,  —  that  there  is  no  sinful 
action  to  which  naturally  we  are  determined;  but  it  is  our 
own  choice  that  we  sin." — p.  88. 

This  is  the  Pelagian  argument  for  freewill  which  we  meet 
with  in  S.  Augustine ;  and  it  has  the  one-sidedness  of  that 
argument.  Nobody,  of  course,  can  deny  what  is  asserted 
here,  if  considered  as  one  side  of  the  truth ;  it  is  true  that  the 
will  must  have  the  power  of  choosing  ;  that  we  are  conscious 
of  this  power;  that  there  is  "  no  natural  necessity  for  sinning ; " 
that  "there  is  no  sinful  action  to  which  we  are  naturally  de- 
termined." All  this  enters  into  our  meaning  of  the  term 
will,  and  our  consciousness  of  its  operations.  But  there  is 
another  side  of  the  whole  truth  respecting  the  will  to  which 
S.  Augustine  appeals  :  "  To  will  is  present  with  me,  but 
how  to  perform  that  which  is  good  I  know  not.  For  the 
good  that  I  would  I  do  not,  but  the  evil  that  I  would  not 
that  I  do."  Jeremy  Taylor  appeals,  as  the  Pelagians  did, 
to  a  certain  sense  of  bare  ability  to  do  right  which  we  retain 
under  all  circumstances  and  states  of  mind,  as  if  it  were  the 
whole  truth  on  this  subject ;  he  relies  absolutely  upon  it.  He 
goes  even  to  the  length  to  which  the  Pelagians  went,  of 
saying  "  that  the  power  of  the  will  cannot  be  lessened  by 
any  act  of  the  same  faculty,"  so  that  however  long  a  man 
may  continue  in  a  course  of  sin,  and  however  inveterate  the 
habit  he  may  contract,  he  has  still  as  much  freewill  as  ever, 
and  on  the  very  next  occasion  of  acting  is  as  able  to  act 
aright  as  ever.  But  this  is  evidently,  and  on  principles  of 
common  sense,  untrue.  Jeremy  Taylor  sees  only  that  side 
of  the  human  will  which  favours  his  own  argument ;  he  sees 


NOTE   VII.  365 

in  it  a  simple  unity,  a  pure  undivided  faculty,  a  power  of 
doing  anything  to  which  there  is  no  physical  hindrance ;  but 
the  will  is  a  mixed  and  complex  thing,  exhibiting  oppositions 
and  incongruities.  He  proceeds  upon  an  abstract  idea  of  free- 
will  —  "there  cannot  be  a  will  that  cannot  choose;"  but  the 
question  is,  what  is  the  actual  and  real  will  of  which  we  find 
ourselves  possessed  ? 

Taylor  sees  in  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  according  to  the 
received  strict  interpretation  of  it,  a  basis  of  the  doctrine  of 
predestination  (p.  319.),  and  argues  against  them  as  virtually 
one  and  the  same  doctrine ;  in  doing  which  he  is  right.  But  if 
the  ground  is  only  true  in  a  mysterious  sense,  that  which  is 
raised  upon  it  is  only  true  in  the  same  sense,  and  is  so  deprived 
of  its  definiteness,  and  consequently  of  its  harshness ;  for  a 
doctrine  to  be  harsh  must  positively  state  something.  As  a 
mystery  it  disowns  such  a  charge. 

The  received  interpretation  of  original  sin  being  thus  re- 
jected, Jeremy  Taylor  substitutes  for  it  the  more  lenient  in- 
terpretation put  forward  by  the  early  fathers  of  this  sin,  as 
a  deprivation,  viz.  of  certain  higher  and  supernatural  gifts 
conferred  upon  man  at  his  creation ;  an  absence  of  perfec- 
tion, as  distinguished  from  a  positive  state  of  sin.  "  This  sin 
brought  upon  Adam  all  that  God  threatened  —  but  no  more. 
A  certainty  of  dying,  together  with  the  proper  effects  and 
affections  of  mortality,  were  inflicted  on  him,  and  he  was  re- 
duced to  the  condition  of  his  own  nature,  and  then  begat  sons 
and  daughters  in  his  own  likeness,  that  is,  in  the  proper 
temper  and  constitution  of  mortal  men.  For  as  God  was  not 
bound  to  give  what  He  never  promised  —  viz.,  an  immortal 
duration  and  abode  in  this  life,  —  so  neither  does  it  appear,  in 
that  angry  intercourse  that  God  had  with  Adam,  that  he  took 
from  him  or  us  any  of  our  natural  perfections,  but  his  graces 
only.  Man  being  left  in  this  state  of  pure  naturals,  could  not 
by  his  own  strength  arrive  to  a  supernatural  end,  which  was 
typified  in  his  being  cast  out  of  Paradise,  and  the  guarding 
of  it  with  the  flaming  sword  of  a  cherub.  For  eternal  life 
being  an  end  above  our  natural  proportions,  cannot  be  acquired 
by  any  natural  means." — Vol.  ix.  p.  1.  "God  gives  his  gifts 
as  He  pleases,  and  is  unjust  to  no  man  by  giving  or  not  giving 


366  NOTE   VII. 

any  certain  proportion  of  good  things ;  and  supposing  this 
loss  was  brought  first  upon  Adam,  and  so  descended  upon  us, 
yet  we  have  no  cause  to  complain,  for  we  lost  nothing  that 
was  ours." — p.  56. 

When  he  comes,  however,  to  reconcile  this  modification  of 
the  doctrine  of  original  sin  with  Scripture,  and  to  prove  "  that 
in  Scripture  there  is  no  signification  of  any  corruption  or  de- 
pravation of  our  souls  by  Adam's  sin,"  he  has  to  explain 
away  texts.  The  text  Rom.  v.  18.  "By  the  offence  of  one 
judgment  came  upon  all  men  to  condemnation,"  asserts  the 
condemnation,  Ka-raKpi^a^  of  all  mankind  as  the  consequence 
of  the  sin  of  Adam.  Taylor  explains  ((  damnation  "  first  as 
pos?ia  damni,  a  loss  of  a  higher  state ;  and,  secondly,  of 
temporal  death — which  was  {i  the  iv/wle  event,  for  it  names  no 
other, — according  to  that  saying  of  S.  Paul,  *  In  Adam  we  all 
die.' "  But  this  is  an  artificial  explanation  of  Scripture.  It 
is  true,  as  he  observes,  that  "  the  KaraKpipa  passed  upon  all 
men,  E(J>  &>  TTCLVTSS  rj/maprov  "  (p.  380.) ;  but  this  can  only  show 
that  the  natural  truth  is  maintained  in  Scripture  together 
with  the  mysterious  one,  not  that  the  mysterious  one  is  not 
maintained.  So  of  the  text  ft  Death  passed  upon  all  men  ;  for 
that  all  have  sinned,"  he  says,  "  all  men,  that  is,  the  gene- 
rality of  mankind,  all  that  lived  till  they  could  sin  ;  the  others 
that  died  before,  died  in  their  nature,  not  in  their  sin." — 
p.  381.  He  owns,  however,  at  last,  that  the  language  of 
Scripture  is  against  him,  by  falling  back  upon  the  ground  of 
justice  as  overruling  the  natural  meaning  of  such  language. 
"How  can  it  be  just  that  the  'condemnation'  should  pass 
upon  us  for  Adam's  sin?  " — p.  380. 

So  upon  the  text  "  Behold  I  was  shapen  in  wickedness, 
and  in  sin  hath  my  mother  conceived  me,"  he  says,  "  I 
answer,  that  the  words  are  a  Hebraism,  and  signify  nothing 
but  an  aggrandation  of  his  sinfulness,  and  are  intended  for  a 
high  expression,  meaning  that  e  I  am  wholly  and  entirely 
wicked.'  For  the  verification  of  which  exposition  there  are 
divers  parallel  places  in  the  Holy  Scriptures :  '  Thou  wast 
my  hope,  when  I  hanged  yet  upon  my  mother's  breast ; '  and 
(  The  ungodly  as  soon  as  they  be  born,  they  go  astray  and 
speak  lies,'  which,  because  it  cannot  be  true  in  the  letter, 


NOTE    VII.  367 

must  be  an  idiotism  or  propriety  of  phrase,  apt  to  explicate 
the  other,  and  signify  only  a  ready,  a  prompt,  a  great,  and 
universal  wickedness.  The  like  to  this  is  that  saying  of  the 
Pharisees,  (  Thou  wert  altogether  born  in  sin,  and  dost  thou 
teach  us?';  which  phrase  and  manner  of  speaking  being 
plainly  a  reproach  of  the  poor  blind  man  and  a  disparage- 
ment of  him,  did  mean  only  to  call  him  a  very  wicked 
person,  not  that  he  had  derived  his  sin  originally  and  from 
his  birth." — p.  27.  But  even  were  the  text  <(  In  sin  hath 
my  mother  conceived  me,"  only  a  phrase  to  express  the  depth 
and  strength  of  sin  in  the  character  of  the  person  using  it, 
why  should  that  depth  and  strength  of  sin  be  expressed  in 
that  form  ?  Why  does  David,  on  the  first  deep  perception 
of  his  own  guilt,  and  the  hold  wrhich  sin  has  had  over  him, 
go  back  to  his  birth?  Is  it  not  because  he  cannot  see  how 
he  can  stop  short  of  it  ?  The  more  he  considers  the  sinful- 
ness  of  his  character  the  more  rooted  it  seems,  and  the 
further  it  appears  to  go  back,  till  at  last  he  cannot  but  «ay, 
that  it  is  actually  coeval  with  his  existence.  The  phrase, 
then,  though  it  may  not  be  a  dogmatic  assertion  of  original 
sin,  is  an  assertion  of  a  certain  depth  and  radical  position  of 
sin  in  the  human  soul ;  upon  which,  when  realised,  the  doc- 
trine of  original  sin  naturally  arises.  Such  phrases  as  this, 
and  the  others  in  Scripture  referred  to  by  Taylor,  show  that 
there  was  a  truth  felt  respecting  sin,  which  was  expressed  in 
this  form  as  the  most  appropriate  one  for  it,  and  that  when- 
ever men  perceived  the  strength  of  the  hold  which  sin  had 
had  upon  them,  they  went  to  the  idea  of  its  originality,  as 
an  idea  nothing  short  of  which  would  do  justice  to  that  truth 
which  they  felt  respecting  sin,  and  which  the  fuller  consci- 
ousness of  their  own  sins  had  revealed  to  them. 

So  on  the  text  "  By  nature  we  were  children  of  wrath," 
Taylor  remarks:  "True,  we  were  so  when  we  were  dead 
in  sins,  and  before  we  were  quickened  by  the  Spirit  of  life 
and  grace.  We  were  so ;  now  we  are  not.  We  were  so  by 
our  own  unworthiness  and  filthy  conversation  ;  now  we  being 
regenerated  by  the  Spirit  of  holiness,  we  are  heirs  unto 
God,  and  no  longer  heirs  of  wrath.  This,  therefore,  as 
appears  by  the  discourse  of  S.  Paul,  relates  not  to  our  ori- 


368  NOTE   VII. 

ginal  sin,  but  to  the  actual ;  and  of  this  sense  of  the  word 
( nature,'  in  the  matter  of  sinning,  we  have  Justin  Martyr, 
or  whoever  is  the  author  of  the  questions  and  answers  Ad 
Orthodoxos,  to  be  witness.  For  answering  those  words  of 
Scripture,  6  There  is  not  any  one  clean  who  is  born  of  a 
woman/  and  there  is  none  begotten  who  hath  not  committed 
sin ;  he  says,  their  meaning  cannot  extend  to  Christ,  for  He 
was  not  c  7r£<f>vfcc0$  afjLdpTdvsw — born  to  sin;'  but  he  is  '  na- 
tura  ad  peccandum  natus  —  TTS^VKW^  a^apravsiv^  who,  by  the 
choice  of  his  own  will,  is  author  to  himself  to  do  what  he  list, 
whether  it  be  good  or  evil,  6  Kara  rrjv  av9aipsrov  Trpoaipsaw 
dycov savrov  sis  TO TrparrsiV  a  ftovXsrai,  sirs  ayaOd  SITS  (j>av\a" 
— p.  29.  One  who  can  sin,  then,  is  born  to  sin,  in  Taylor's 
sense  of  the  phrase ;  a  man  being  born  to  sin  means  that  he 
can  sin,  and  no  more.  But  such  a  meaning  is  inconsistent 
with  his  own  previous  meaning  of  the  similar  phrase,  "  By 
nature  children  of  wrath,"  which  he  understands  to  mean 
great  and  habitual  actual  sin,  or  a  bad  and  corrupt  course  of 
life ;  for  the  power  to  sin  and  the  fact  of  sin  are  not  the  same 
thing.  Either  meaning,  however  plainly,  falls  short  of  the 
Apostle's.  Why  should  S.  Paul  say  "  by  nature"  if  actual 
sin  was  all  that  he  meant  ?  The  term  evidently  introduces 
another  idea  beyond  and  in  addition  to  an  actual  bad  course 
of  life. 

The  modification  which  Taylor  has  hitherto  proposed  of 
the  doctrine  of  original  sin  has  been  rather  concerned  with 
its  effects  than  with  itself.  The  particular  view  of  the  sin 
itself  which  he  proposes  to  substitute  for  the  received  one  is, 
that  it  is  imputed  sin,  as  distinguished  from  real  sin  in  us. 
He  objects  to  the  idea  of  our  being  parties  to  Adam's  sin  as 
absurd ;  but  has  no  objection  to  a  certain  imputation  of  that 
sin,  considered  to  be  his  and  his  only,  to  us.  "  Indeed,  my 
Lord,  that  I  may  speak  freely  in  this  great  question  :  when 
one  man  hath  sinned,  his  descendants  and  relations  cannot 
possibly  by  him,  or  for  him,  or  in  him  be  made  sinners  really 
and  properly.  For  in  sin  there  are  but  two  things  imagina- 
ble, the  irregular  action  and  the  guilt  or  obligation  to  punish- 
ment. Now,  we  cannot  be  said  in  any  sense  to  have  done  the 
action  which  another  did,  and  not  we ;  the  action  is  as  indi- 


NOTE    VII.  369 

vidual  as  the  person  ;  and  Titius  may  as  well  be  Caius,  and 
the  son  be  his  own  father,  as  he  can  be  said  to  have  done  the 
father's  action  ;  and  therefore  we  cannot  possibly  be  guilty  for 
it,  for  guilt  is  an  obligation  to  punishment  for  having  done  it ; 
the  action  and  the  guilt  are  relatives,  —  one  cannot  be  done 
without  the  other,  —  something  must  be  done  inwardly  or 
outwardly,  or  there  can  be  no  guilt.  But  then  for  the  evil 
of  punishment,  that  may  pass  further  than  the  action.  If  it 
passes  upon  the  innocent  it  is  not  a  punishment  to  them,  but 
an  evil  inflicted  in  right  of  dominion ;  but  yet  by  reason  of 
the  relation  of  the  afflicted  to  him  that  hath  sinned,  to  him  it 
is  a  punishment.  But  if  it  passes  upon  others  that  are  not 
innocent,  then  it  is  a  punishment  to  both ;  to  the  first  prin- 
cipally ;  to  the  descendants  or  relatives  for  the  other's  sake, 
his  sin  being  imputed  so  far." — p.  379.  "  There  is  no  neces- 
sity to  affirm  that  we  are  sinners  in  Adam  any  more  than  by 
imputation." — p.  378. 

Taylor  considers  this  view  of  imputation  as  a  middle  one 
between  the  received  and  the  Pelagian  view  of  original  sin. 
"  I  do  not  approve  of  that  gloss  of  the  Pelagians  that  in 
Adam  we  are  made  sinners  by  imitation,  and  much  less  of 
that  which  affirms  that  we  are  made  so  properly  and  formally. 
But  made  sinners  signifies  used  like  sinners,  so  as  justified 
signifies  treated  like  just  persons ;  in  which  interpretation  I 
follow  S.  Paul,  not  the  Pelagians."— p.  383. 

But  what  is  gained  toward  reconciling  the  doctrine  of  ori- 
ginal sin  with  our  natural  ideas,  by  substituting  the  imputa- 
tion of  Adam's  sin  for  sin  in  Adam  ?  If  it  is  contrary  to  reason 
that  a  man  should  be  a  party  to  sin  committed  before  he  was 
born,  it  is  contrary  to  justice  that  a  sin  in  which  he  was  no 
partaker  should  be  imputed  to  him,  and  that  he  should  be 
punished  for  it.  It  is  true,  he  says,  "If  the  evil  of  punish- 
ment passes  upon  the  innocent,  it  is  not  a  punishment  to 
them,  but  an  evil  inflicted  by  right  of  dominion,  and  there- 
fore Kabbi  Simeon  Barsema  said  well,  that  'When  God 
visits  the  vices  of  the  fathers  upon  the  children— -jure  Dominii, 
non  poence  utitur — He  uses  the  right  of  empire  not  of  justice.' " 
The  result  of  this  distinction  is,  that  God,  in  cases  of  punish- 
ment for  imputed  sin,  inflicts  no  more  evil  than  He  has  a  right 
to  inflict  where  there  is  no  sin  in  the  case.  But  if  on  such  a 

B  B 


370  NOTE   VII. 

ground  the  imputation  of  sin  is  reconciled  with  our  idea  of 
justice,  what  becomes  of  the  idea  itself  of  imputation  f  There 
is  evidently  no  real  imputation  of,  no  punishment/or,  another's 
sin,  and  therefore  this  whole  mode  of  representing  original 
sin  falls  to  the  ground.  Taylor  says,  "  By  reason  of  the  rela- 
tion of  the  afflicted  to  him  that  sinned,  to  him  it  is  a  punish- 
ment." Why  so?  Whether  a  certain  evil  is  a  punishment 
depends  on  the  ground  on  which  it  is  inflicted.  If  it  is  in- 
flicted on  the  ground  of  guilt,  actual  or  imputed,  it  is  punish- 
ment; if  it  is  inflicted  simply  jure  Dominii,  on  the  ground  of 
that  right  which  the  Maker  of  the  world  has  over  the  lives 
and  fortunes  of  His  creatures,  it  is  not  punishment,  but  Pro- 
vidence. But  Taylor  is  still  unwilling  to  abandon  the  idea 
of  punishment,  and  he  suggests  a,  form  of  punishment  which, 
he  thinks,  is  not  liable  to  any  charge  of  injustice.  "In 
Adam  we  are  made  sinners,  that  is,  treated  ill  or  afflicted, 
though  ourselves  be  innocent  of  that  sin,  which  was  the  occa- 
sion of  our  being  used  so  severely  for  other  sins,  of  which  we 
were  not  innocent"  —  p.  4.  God  inflicts  pain  upon  us, 
then ;  which  pain  is  punishment,  because  such  pain  is  greater 
than  it  would  have  been  but  for  Adam's  sin ;  we  are  not 
punished  for  Adam's  sin,  but  we  are,  in  consequence  of 
Adam's  sin,  punished  worse  for  our  own  sins.  But  the 
difficulty  of  punishment  is  not  at  all  lessened  by  this 
artifice  of  attaching  the  punishment  to  our  own  actual 
sins  in  the  first  place,  and  only  charging  upon  Adam's  sin 
the  increase  of  this  punishment.  Increase  of  punishment  is 
fresh  punishment.  Taylor  thus  oscillates  between  acknow- 
ledging and  disowning  punishment  for  Adam's  sin.  He  dis- 
owns it  as  inconsistent  with  justice ;  he  acknowledges  it 
because  he  cannot  wholly  deny  that  something  very  like  it  is 
maintained  in  Scripture,  and  he  shrinks  from  wholly  giving 
up  the  received  doctrine.  He  thus  constructs  a  kind  of  in- 
direct vicarious  punishment,  which  is  inflicted  for  our  own  per- 
sonal sins,  but  inflicted  more  severely  on  account  of  Adam's  sin. 
Jeremy  Taylor  falls  into  all  these  forced  and  inconsistent 
modes  of  explanation,  in  consequence  of  the  fundamental 
misapprehension  with  which  he  starts  as  to  the  sense  and 
mode  in  which  the  truth  of  original  sin  is  held.  Had  he 
perceived  properly  that  it  was  and  professed  to  be  a  myste- 


NOTE    VIII.  371 

rious  as  distinguished  from  an  intelligible  truth,  he  would 
have  seen  that  all  these  charges  of  injustice  against  the  doc- 
trine were  erroneous,  and  these  consequent  attempts  at  a 
modification  of  it  superfluous  and  unnecessary.  The  profes- 
sion of  a  mystery  disarms  the  opposition  of  reason ;  for  what 
has  reason  to  object  to  in  that  which  it  does  not  understand? 
What  has  reason  before  it  in  such  a  case  ?  One  who  holds 
the  doctrine  in  this  sense  can  hold  it  in  its  greatest  strict- 
ness, without  the  slightest  collision  with  reason  or  justice, 
and  is  spared  this  vain  struggle  with  Scripture. 


NOTE  VIII.  p.  38. 

THE  doctrine  of  predestination  in  Scripture  is  not  uncom- 
monly interpreted  in  such  a  way  as  to  represent  that  doctrine, 
not  as  opposed  to  any  counter  truth  of  freewill,  but  as  itself 
harmonising  and  coinciding  with  it.  Predestination  and 
election  are  interpreted  to  mean  predestination  and  election  to 
privileges  or  means  of  grace,  which  depend  on  freewill  for 
their  cultivation.  But  this  is  certainly  not  the  natural  sense 
of  the  words  in  Scripture.  In  the  text  Matt.  xx.  16., 
"  Many  are  called  but  few  chosen,"  or  elect;  "elect"  evi- 
dently means  elect  to  eternal  life  itself,  and  not  merely  to 
the  opportunity  of  attaining  it.  The  same  may  be  said  of 
Matt.  xxiv.  22.:  "For  the  elect's  sake  those  days  shall 
be  shortened,''  the  elect  being  evidently  here  the  saints,  the 
good,  those  who  will  be  saved,  not  those  who  have  merely 
been  admitted  into  the  Christian  Church  and  the  means 
of  obtaining  salvation,  many  of  whom  being  wicked  men  and 
enemies  of  God,  God  would  not  "for  their  sakes"  perform 
this  special  act  of  mercy.  On  Acts  xiii.  48.,  "  As  many  as 
were  ordained  to  eternal  life  believed,"  the  remark  is  obvious 
that  that  to  which  men  are  said  to  be  "  ordained"  (which 
is  the  same  as  elect  or  predestinated)  is  expressly  "eternal 
life."  In  Eph.  i.  4.,  "  According  as  He  hath  chosen  us  in 
Him,  before  the  foundation  of  the  world,  that  we  should  be 
holy,"  the  election  is  not  to  the  power  but  to  the  fact  of  holi- 
ness. And  the  next  verse  sustains  this  obvious  sense : 

B   B   2 


372  NOTE   VIII. 

"  Having  predestinated  us  unto  the  adoption  of  children  by 
Jesus  Christ  to  Himself,"  adoption  always  implying  in  the 
epistles  sanctity.  So  2  Tim.  i.  9. :  "  Who  hath  saved  us 
and  called  us  with  an  holy  calling,  not  according  to  our 
works,  but  according  to  His  own  purpose  and  grace  which 
was  given  us  in  Christ  before  the  world  began,"  obviously 
speaks  of  actual  holiness  and  actual  salvation,  not  the  mere 
opportunity  of  them,  as  the  effect  of  predestination.  And 
generally  it  is  evident  that  the  terms  elect,  predestinated, 
adopted,  justified,  saints,  all  refer  to  the  same  state  and  the 
same  class;  and  that  plainly  the  state  and  the  class  of  ac- 
tually holy  men  who  will  certainly  be  saved,  as  the  neces- 
sary consequence  and  reward  of  such  holiness. 

The  8th  and  9th  chapters,  however,  of  the  Epistle  to 
the  Romans,  furnish  the  most  powerful,  and  because  the 
most  powerful  the  most  controverted,  evidence  for  the  mean- 
ing of  predestination  as  being  predestination  to  eternal  life 
itself,  and  not  merely  certain  means  of  grace  enabling  men 
to  obtain  it.  In  the  8th  is  the  passage :  "  We  know  that 
all  things  work  together  for  good  to  them  that  love  God, 
to  them  who  are  the  called  according  to  His  purpose.  For 
whom  He  did  foreknow  (know  before  as  His  own  with  deter- 
mination to  be  for  ever  merciful  unto  them — Hooker,  Ap- 
pendix to  bk.  v.  vol.  ii.  p.  751.)  He  also  predestinated  to  be 
conformed  to  the  image  of  His  Son,  that  He  might  be  the  first 
born  among  many  brethren.  Moreover,  whom  He  did  pre- 
destinate, them  He  also  called,  and  whom  He  called,  them  He 
also  justified,  and  whom  He  justified  them  He  also  glorified." 
Here  it  is  expressly  said  that  those  who  are  predestinated 
are  predestinated,  not  to  the  opportunity  of  conformation  to 
the  image  of  Christ,  but  to  that  conformation  itself,  to  actual 
justification,  and  to  actual  glory  in  the  world  to  come. 

The  9th  chapter- has  the  passage:  "  For  the  children 
being  not  yet  born,  neither  having  done  any  good  or  evil, 
that  the  purpose  of  God  according  to  election  might  stand, 
not  of  works,  but  of  Him  that  calleth,  it  was  said  unto  her, 
the  elder  shall  serve  the  younger.  As  it  is  written,  Jacob 
have  I  loved,  but  Esau  have  I  hated.  What  shall  we  say 
then?  Is  there  unrighteousness  with  God?  God  forbid. 


NOTE    VIII.  373 

For  He  saith  to  Moses,  I  will  have  mercy  on  whom  I  will 
have  mercy,  and  I  will  have  compassion  on  whom  I  will 
have  compassion.  So  then  it  is  not  of  him  that  willeth, 
nor  of  him  that  runneth  -,  but  of  God  that  sheweth  mercy. 
For  the  Scripture  saith  unto  Pharaoh,  even  for  this  same 
purpose  have  I  raised  thee  up,  that  I  might  show  My 
power  in  thee,  and  that  My  name  might  be  declared 
throughout  all  the  earth.  Therefore  hath  He  mercy  on  whom 
He  will  have  mercy,  and  whom  He  will  He  hardeneth. 
Thou  wilt  say  then  unto  me,  Why  doth  He  yet  find  fault? 
for  who  hath  resisted  His  will  ?  Nay,  but,  O  man,  who  art 
thou  that  repliest  against  God  ?  Shall  the  thing  formed  say 
unto  him  that  formed  it,  Why  hast  thou  made  me  thus? 
Hath  not  the  potter  power  over  the  clay,  of  the  same  lump  to 
make  one  vessel  unto  honour,  and  another  unto  dishonour? 
What  if  God,  willing  to  shew  His  wrath,  and  to  make  His 
power  known,  endured  with  much  long-suffering  the  ves- 
sels of  wrath  fitted  to  destruction.  And  that  He  might  make 
known  the  riches  of  His  glory  on  the  vessels  of  mercy,  which 
He  had  afore  prepared  unto  glory." 

Here  it  is  expressly  said  that  some  persons  are  from  all 
eternity  objects  respectively  of  the  Divine  love  and  the  Divine 
wrath,  which  love  and  which  wrath  involve  respectively 
eternal  "glory,"  and  " destruction "  (v.  22,  23.).  All  the 
attempts  to  explain  this  passage  as  meaning  only  that  some 
persons  are  predestined  to  higher  and  others  to  lower  means 
of  grace,  appear  to  violate  its  plain  and  natural  meaning.  It 
is  not  indeed  necessary  to  suppose  that  the  contrast  between 
Jacob  and  Esau,  as  individual  men,  is  that  of  one  finally 
saved  to  another  finally  condemned ;  but  it  is  no  less  clear 
that  the  Apostle  uses  them  as  types  of  these  two  respective 
classes,  and  that  the  argument  of  the  passage  has  reference  to 
man's  eternal  end,  good  or  bad;  for  "glory"  and  "destruc- 
tion" cannot  mean  only  higher  and  lower  spiritual  advan- 
tages. 

Archbishop  Whately  indeed  raises  an  ingenious  objection 
to  the  predestinarian  interpretation  of  the  image  of  the 
potter  and  the  clay,  and  remarks,  "We  are  in  His  hands, 
say  these  predestinaritins,  as  clay  in  the  potters',  '  who  hath 

B  B  a 


374  NOTE    VIII. 

power  of  the  same  lump  to  make  one  vessel  to  honour  and 
another  to  dishonour/  not  observing  in  their  party  eagerness 
to  seize  an  easy  apparent  confirmation  of  their  system,  that 
this  similitude,  as  far  as  it  goes,  rather  makes  against  them, 
since  the  potter  never  makes  any  vessel  for  the  express  pur- 
pose of  being  broken  and  destroyed.  This  comparison  ac- 
cordingly agrees  much  better  with  the  view  here  taken.  The 
potter  according  to  his  arbitrary  choice  makes  of  the  same 
lump  one  vessel  to  honour  and  another  to  dishonour — i.  e. 
some  to  nobler  and  others  to  meaner  uses,  but  all  to  some  use; 
none  with  a  design  that  it  should  be  cast  away  and  dashed 
in  pieces.  Even  so  the  Almighty,  of  His  own  arbitrary  choice, 
causes  some  to  be  born  to  wealth  or  rank,  others  to  poverty 
or  obscurity,  some  in  a  heathen,  and  others  in  a  Christian 
country ;  the  advantages  and  privileges  bestowed  on  each 
are  various." — Essay  3,  On  Election.  But  to  extract  thus  an 
argument  from  the  general  nature  of  an  image  used  in  Scrip- 
ture is  to  forget  that  Scripture,  in  making  use  of  images, 
only  adopts  them  in  such  respects  as  it  uses  them,  such 
respects  as  answer  the  particular  purpose  in  hand ;  it  does 
not  necessarily  adopt  the  whole  image.  What  we  have  to 
do  with,  then,  is  not  the  image  itself,  but  the  image  as  used 
ly  Scripture.  Now,  it  is  true  that  a  potter  never  makes 
a  vessel  for  destruction ;  but  some  vessels  are  certainly  in 
this  passage  spoken  of  as  "  fitted  to  destruction,"  others  as 
"  prepared  unto  glory  ;  "  of  which  destruction  and  glory  the 
cause  is  plainly  put  further  back  than  their  own  personal 
conduct, — viz.  in  a  certain  Divine  love  and  wrath,  before 
either  side  had  done  any  actual  good  or  evil, — u  The  children 
being  not  yet  born,  neither  having  done  any  good  or  evil,  it 
is  written,  Jacob  have  I  loved,  but  Esau  have  I  hated." 
And  were  a  predestination  to  privileges  all  that  was  meant 
by  the  passage — that  some  are  born  to  wealth  or  rank,  others 
to  poverty  or  obscurity,  some  in  a  heathen  and  others  in  a 
Christian  country,  what  ground  would  there  be  for  raising 
the  objection  ?  "  Thou  wilt  say  then  unto  me,  Why  doth  He 
yet  find  fault,  for  who  hath  resisted  His  will  ?"  It  is  evi- 
dent that  this  is  a  complaint  against  the  Divine  justice,  or  an 
objection  to  the  Apostle's  doctrine  just  before  laid  down,  on 
the  ground  that  it  contradicts  that  Divine  attribute.  But 


NOTE   VIII.  375 

how  could  a  mere  inequality  in  the  dispensing  of  religious 
privileges  provoke  such  a  charge,  except  from  a  positive  in- 
fidel ?  Inequality  is  a  plain  fact  of  God's  visible  providence, 
and  could  never  support  a  charge  of  injustice,  except  the 
objector  were  willing  to  go  the  further  step  of  denying  a 
Divine  creation  and  providence  altogether  on  account  of  this 
fact.  The  objector  here  plainly  means  to  say  this :  How 
can  it  be  just  that  a  man  should  be  the  object  of  Divine 
wrath  before  he  has  done  anything  to  deserve  it?  That  he 
should  be  incapacitated  for  obtaining  the  qualifications  neces- 
sary for  eternal  life,  and  then  blamed  because  he  has  not  got 
them  ?  "  Why  doth  he  find  fault,  for  who  hath  resisted 
His  will  ?"  Why  does  God  condemn  the  sinner,  when  Hia 
own  arbitrary  will  has  incapacitated  him  for  being  anything 
else  but  a  sinner? 

At  the  same  time  I  am  ready  to  admit,  that  there  is  ground 
for  saying  that  a  milder  sense  of  reprobation  does  come  in,  in 
this  passage,  along  with  the  stronger  one;  and  that  language 
is  used  expressive  rather  of  the  modified  rather  than  of  the 
extreme  doctrine  of  predestination.  It  is  at  any  rate  doubt- 
ful whether  "  honour "  and  "  dishonour "  do  not  mean 
higher  and  inferior  good  rather  then  positive  good  and  evil. 
The  use  of  the  words  in  2  Tim.  ii.  20. — "  In  a  great  house 
there  are  not  only  vessels  of  gold  and  silver,  but  also  of  wood 
and  earth,  and  some  to  honour  and  some  to  dishonour" — would 
seem  to  attach  the  former  meaning  to  them.  And  if  so,  so 
far  as  this  language  goes,  the  Apostle  expresses  a  modified 
doctrine  of  predestination  rather  than  an  extreme  one,  or 
predestination  to  unequal  advantages,  rather  than  to  positive 
good  and  evil.  But  whether  this  is  so  or  not,  such  a  sense 
of  predestination  only  obtains  so  far  as  the  language  which  ex- 
presses it  goes.  The  stronger  sense  of  predestination,  as  predes- 
tination to  positive  good  and  evil,  is  the  main  and  pervading 
one  in  the  passage ;  and  this  sense  must  not  be  lost  sight  of 
because  there  may  be  a  milder  sense  too  in  which  the  doctrine 
is  asserted.  It  is  characteristic  of  S.  Paul  to  slide  from 
one  meaning  to  another ;  and  just  as  a  counter  doctrine  al- 
together to  that  of  predestination  is  put  forth  in  other  pas- 
sages of  Scripture,  so  the  same  passage  may  be  more  or  less 

B   B    4 


376  NOTE    VIII. 

contradictory,  and  contain  its  own  balance.  But  if  the 
milder  meaning  of  predestination  is  there,  it  must  not  be 
thought  that  the  stronger  meaning  is  therefore  not  there  too ; 
or  supposed  that  all  that  this  passage  means  is  a  predesti- 
nation to  unequal  privileges  and  advantages. 

There  is  another  mode  of  interpreting  predestination  in 
Scripture,  so  as  to  make  the  doctrine  agree  with  the  truth 
of  freewill;  viz.  that  of  allowing  predestination  to  be  to 
eternal  salvation  itself,  but  with  the  qualification  that  it  is 
caused  by  the  Divine  foresight  of  the  future  good  life  of  the 
individual.  But  this  qualification  is  opposed  to  the  plain 
meaning  of  those  passages  of  Scripture  in  which  this  doc- 
trine is  set  forth.  These  passages  obviously  represent  pre- 
destination as  a  predestination  of  the  individual  to  a  good  life, 
as  well  as  to  the  reward  of  one,  to  the  means  as  well  as  to  the 
end ;  thus  making  a  good  life  the  effect  of  predestination,  and 
not  the  cause  or  reason  of  it.  "  He  hath  chosen  us  before 
the  foundation  of  the  world  that  we  should  be  holy  "  .  .  .  . 
"  predestinated  us  to  be  conformed  to  the  image  of  His  Son." 
But  the  ninth  chapter  of  Romans,  just  quoted,  supplies 
the  most  decisive  answer  to  this  qualification  of  the  doctrine 
of  predestination;  it  being  expressly  said  there  that  the 
purpose  of  God  according  to  election  is  antecedent  to  any  dif- 
ferences of  life  and  conduct  between  one  man  and  another ; 
that  it  is  formed  while  the  children  are  yet  unborn,  and  have 
done  neither  good  nor  evil ;  that  it  is  not  of  works,  but  of 
Him  that  calleth ;  and  that  it  is  not  of  him  that  willeth  or 
of  him  that  runneth,  but  of  God  that  showeth  mercy ;  that  it 
is  clay  of  the  same  lump  of  which  some  vessels  are  made  to 
honour,  and  others  to  dishonour. 

Jackson,  among  other  commentators,  interprets  the  pre- 
destination maintained  in  this  passage  in  this  way,  viz.  as 
predestination  in  consequence  of  foreseen  good  works.  But 
in  thus  interpreting  it  he  endeavours  at  the  same  time  by  an 
argument  more  ingenious  than  substantial,  to  explain  his 
own  interpretation  as  not  being  such  an  interpretation  as 
this ;  and  tries  to  show  that  he  does  not  base  predestination 
upon  foreseen  good  works.  He  says,  predestination  is  in 
consequence  not  of  any  foreseen  works  of  the  law,  but  the 


NOTE   VIII.  377 

foreseen  work  of  faith ;  which  work  of  faith  being  a  re- 
nunciation of  the  works  of  the  law  cannot  itself  be  called  a 
work.  He  interprets  the  Apostle's  assertion  that  election  is 
not  in  consequence  of  any  "  willing  or  running"  of  the 
man  himself,  in  this  way,  viz.  that  this  expression  applies  to 
works  of  the  Jewish  law  only,  and  not  to  works  of  faith ;  to 
the  self-willed  and  self-dependent  kind  of  good  works,  which 
are  not  really  good  as  not  proceeding  from  a  spiritual  state 
of  mind;  not  to  the  true  spiritual  temper.  The  work  of 
faith,  he  says,  is  {f  an  opus  quo  renunciamus,  the  formal  act 
by  which  all  works  must  be  renounced,"  and  so  not  properly 
a  work:  "jidesjustificat  non  qua  opus  sed  relative  —  is  essen- 
tially included  in  the  act  of  justification ;  not  included  in  the 
universality  of  works,  which  are  excluded  from  justification." 
And  the  "  fallacy "  of  calling  such  an  act  a  work  he  ex- 
presses thus :  "  If  such  divines  as  urge  it  most  should  come 
into  our  per-vices  and  apply  it  to  matters  there  discussed, 
thus — 

"  Omne  visibile  est  coloratum  : 
Omnis  color  est  visibilis  :  ergo 
Omnis  color  est  coloratus, — 

I  hope  a  meaner  artist  than  this  nursery  (God  be  praised !) 
hath  any,  would  quickly  cut  oif  their  progress  with  a  dis- 
tinction of  visibile  ut  quod,  et  visibile  ut  quo,  and  show  that 
the  major,  though  universally  true  of  every  subject  or  body 
that  may  be  seen,  did  not  nor  could  not  comprehend  colour 
by  which  they  are  made  visible,  and  by  whose  formal  act 
they  are  denominated  colorata.  The  fallacy  of  the  former 
objection  drawn  into  mood  and  figure  is  the  same,  but  more 
apparent. 

"  Every  will  or  work  of  man  must  be  utterly  renounced 
from  the  act  of  justification  or  conversion : 

"  But  to  deny  ourselves  and  renounce  all  works  is  a  work  : 

"  Ergo,  This  work  must  be  excluded  from  the  suit  of  mercy, 
as  no  way  available." — Vol.  ix.  p.  442. 

But  such  a  distinction  as  this  applied  to  works  as  a  ground 
of  the  Divine  election  is  inadmissible.  The  work  of  faith  is  a 
work ;  not  in  such  "an  ambiguous  sense  as  that  in  which  colour 


378  NOTE   VIII. 

is  a  visible  thing,  but  substantially  and  correctly.  It  is  a 
humble,  self-renouncing  act.  It  is  the  fundamental  act  of  the 
Christian  life.  If  election,  then,  is  in  consequence  of  this  fore- 
seen work  of  faith,  it  is  in  consequence  of  good  works,  which 
it  is  plainly  said  by  S.  Paul  not  to  be. 

Jackson  borrows  his  explanation  from  Origen,  who  implies 
the  same  distinction  between  "  carnal  works "  and  other 
works,  as  the  ground  of  Jacob's  election.  "  Quod  si  vel 
Isaac  vel  Jacob  pro  his  meritis  electi  fuissent  a  Deo  qua  in 
carne  positi  acquisierant,  et  per  opera  carnis  justificari  meru- 
issent,  posset  utique  meriti  eorum  gratia  ad  posteritatem  car- 
nis quoque  pertinere.  Nunc  vero  cum  electio  eorum  non  ex 
operibus  facta  sit,  sed  ex  proposito  Dei,  et  ex  vocantis  arbi- 
trio,  promiSsionum  gratia  non  in  filiis  carnis  impletur,  sed  in 
filiis  Dei."  —  In  Rom.  ix.  1 1.  vol.  iv.  p.  613.  Thus  Jackson  : 
"  Had  not  this  purpose  of  God  been  revealed  before  the 
children  had  been  born,  Jacob's  posterity  would  have  boasted 
that  either  their  father  Jacob  or  his  mother  Rebecca  had 
better  observed  those  rites  and  customs  wherein  they  placed 
righteousness  than  Isaac  or  Esau  had  done ;  and  that  God 
upon  these  motives  had  bestowed  the  birthright  or  blessing 
upon  Jacob  before  Esau." — Vol.  ix.  p.  436.  There  is  con- 
siderable confusion  here,  and  Origen  seems  to  slide  from  works 
not  carnal  to  no  works  at  all  as  the  ground  of  election ; 
though  the  former  idea  in  the  main  prevails.  Origen's  main 
view  of  the  ground  of  election  is  foreseen  good  character.  — 
Vol.  iv.  p.  616. 

Jackson  explains  the  similitude  of  the  potter  and  the  clay 
on  the  same  principle :  "  That  it  was  marred  in  the  first 
making  was  the  fault  of  the  clay."  —  Vol.  ix.  p.  462.  But  is 
this  said  in  Scripture  ?  On  the  contrary,  it  is  said  that  all  the 
clay  was  of  the  same  lump,  and  therefore  the  difference  of  the 
Divine  design  did  not  arise  from  any  difference  in  the  clay. 
Origen  makes  in  the  same  way  a  difference  in  the  clay,  though 
the  very  phrase  eadem  massa,  which  he  accepts,  as  he  is 
obliged  to  do,  from  the  Apostle,  refutes  it.  "  Videns  Deus  pu- 
ritatein  ejus,  et  potestatem  habens  ex  eadem  massa  facere 
aliud  vas  ad  honorem  aliud  ad  contumeliam,  Jacob  quidem 
qui  emundaverat  seipsum  fecit  vas  ad  honorem  ;  Esau  vero 


NOTE    VIII.  379 

cujus  animam  non  ita  pur  am  nee  ita  simplicem  videbat,  ex  ea- 
dem  massa  fecit  ad  contumeliam." — In  Eom.  ix.  vol.  iv.  p.  616. 

With  the  explanation  of  foreseen  goodness,  however,  as  the 
ground  of  election,  Jackson  couples  the  other  mode  of  recon- 
ciling the  passage  with  freewill ;  viz.  that  of  election  to  means 
and  opportunities.  "  The  Apostle  imagineth  such  a  potter 
as  the  wise  man  did,  that  knows  a  reason  why  he  makes  one 
vessel  of  this  fashion,  another  of  that,  why  he  appoints  this 
to  a  base  use,  that  to  a  better." — P.  462. 

Hooker's  explanation  of  the  passage  (given  in  a  recently  dis- 
covered and  edited  writing,  made  an  appendix  to  Ecclesiastical 
Polity,  bk.  v.)  makes,  like  Origen's  and  Jackson's,  a  difference 
in  the  clay,  though  he  will  not  at  the  same  time  allow  that  the 
Divine  Justice  requires  this  reason  for  its  own  defence.  "  Sup- 
pose (which  is  yet  false)  that  there  were  nothing  in  it,  but  only  so 
God  will  have  it, — suppose  God  did  harden  and  soften,  choose 
and  cast  off,  make  honourable  and  detestable,  whom  Himself 
will,  and  that  without  any  cause  moving  Him  one  way  or 
other, — are  we  not  all  in  His  hands  as  clay?  If  thus  God  did 
deal,  what  injury  were  it  ?  How  much  less  now,  when  they  on 
whom  His  severity  worketh  are  not  found  like  the  clay  with- 
out form,  as  apt  to  receive  the  best  shape  as  any  other,  but 
are  in  themselves  and  by  their  own  disposition  fashioned  for 
destruction  and  for  wrath."  —  Keble's  Ed.  vol.  ii.  p.  748. 
Now,  of  this  explanation  the  first  part  undoubtedly  adheres 
to  the  natural  meaning  of  the  passage  in  S.  Paul  more 
faithfully  than  the  latter,  which  diverges  from  it ;  mankind 
being  plainly  represented  by  S.  Paul  as  being  like  clay  of 
the  same  lump,  previous  to  election,  and  any  difference  of 
disposition  in  them,  in  this  previous  state,  so  far  from  being 
asserted,  being  expressly  denied.  Indeed,  as  Jansen  says,  if 
S.  Paul  meant  foreseen  goodness  as  the  ground  of  election,  he 
would  not  have  silenced  the  complainer  by  a  reference  to 
God's  inscrutable  will,  but  would  have  given  this  simple 
and  intelligible  answer  to  his  objection.  But  non  isto  nititur 
car  dine. — De  Grat.  Christi,  p.  347. 

On  the  whole,  that  which  is  commonly  called  the  Calvin- 
istic  sense,  appears  to  be  the  natural  sense  of  these  passages 
of  Scripture  ;  and  the  Calvinistic  use  of  them  should  be  met, 


380  NOTE    IX. 

not  by  denying  this  sense,  and  explaining  away  the  natural 
meaning  of  the  language,  but  by  opposing  to  them  other 
passages  of  Scripture  which  speak  equally  plainly  of  man's 
freewill.  I  may  add,  that  perhaps  more  has  been  made  by 
many  of  the  text  in  S.  James  than  it  will  exactly  bear,  and 
that,  though  proving  difficulty,  this  text  does  not  prove  so  much 
difficulty  in  those  parts  of  S.  Paul's  Epistles  as  many  would 
maintain.  These  epistles  were  certainly  addressed  to  the 
whole  Church,  and  were  meant  to  be  understood  by  men 
of  average  intelligence  who  applied  their  attention  properly. 
Their  predestinarian  meaning  in  parts  is,  on  the  whole,  clear 
and  decided ;  and  the  reason  why  their  meaning  is  thought 
by  many  to  be  so  very  obscure  and  difficult  to  get  at,  is  that 
they  will  not  acknowledge  this  predestinarian  meaning  to  be 
the  true  one.  These  interpreters  create  difficulties  for  them- 
selves by  rejecting  the  natural  meaning  of  passages,  and  then 
lay  the  difficulty  on  the  passages. 


NOTE  IX.  p.  50. 

THE  first  work  of  Pelagius  referred  to  in  the  controversy, 
is  his  letter  to  Paulinus,  which  appears  to  have  been  written 
about  A.  D.  405,  during  his  stay  at  Koine.  —  Benedictine 
Editor's  Preface,  c.  1.  But  Augustine's  doctrinal  bias  had 
clearly  asserted  itself  some  years  before,  in  the  book  De 
JDiversis  Quastionibus  ad  Simplicianum,  which  came  out 
A.  D.  397 ;  and  had  evidently  commenced  as  early  as  the 
book  De  Libero  Arbitrio,  which  he  began  to  write  A.  D. 
388.  In  his  Retractations  (1.  1.  c.  9.)  he  refers  to  this  early 
treatise,  with  which  the  Pelagians  taunted  him  as  contradict- 
ing his  later  ones  on  the  subject  of  freewill,  and  shows  that, 
though  not  consistently  brought  out,  the  germ  of  his  ultimate 
system  was  to  be  found  in  parts  of  that  treatise.  He  refers 
particularly  to  the  scheme  of  the  two  kinds  of  Divine  gifts 
laid  down  in  1.  2.  cc.  18,  19. ;  according  to  which  both  those 
which  did  and  those  which  did  not  admit  of  a  bad  use  (vir- 
tutes  and  potentice)  were  alike  gifts  of  God.  The  explana- 
tion which  he  gives  in  the  Retractations  of  some  of  the  state- 


NOTE    X.  381 

ments  favourable  to  freewill  in  the  other  treatise  may  be 
far-fetched ;  but  such  a  view  as  this  is  evidently  agreeable 
to  his  later  doctrine.  Nor  is  Augustine  at  all  a  pertinacious 
interpreter  of  his  early  writings  in  the  sense  of  his  later 
ones.  Consistency  has  less  charm  for  him  than  develop- 
ment as  a  writer  and  thinker ;  and  he  dwells  on  the  changes 
he  has  gone  through  with  the  satisfaction  of  one  who  believes 
his  later  notions  to  be  a  great  improvement  in  depth  and 
acuteness  upon  his  earlier  ones. 

To  these  two  earlier  treatises  may  be  added  the  Confes- 
sions, written  A.  D.  400.  A  celebrated  dictum  in  this  book— 
da  quodjubes,  etjube  quod  vis  —  was  the  first  apparent  stimu- 
lus to  the  speculations  of  Pelagius,  whom  it  greatly  irritated. 
*'  Pelagius  ferre  non  potuit,  et  contradicens  aliquanto  com- 
motius,  pene  cum  illo  qui  ilia  commemoraverat  litigavit." — 
De  Dono  Perseverantice,  n.  53.  Neander  says  :  "  Since  Augus- 
tine had  completed  his  doctrinal  system  on  this  particular  side 
more  than  ten  years  before  the  opinions  of  Pelagius  excited 
any  public  controversy,  it  is  clear  that  opposition  to  Pelagius 
could  not  have  influenced  him  in  forming  it.  With  more 
propriety  may  it  be  said  that  opposition  to  such  doctrines  as 
those  of  Augustine,  or  to  the  practical  consequences  which, 
through  misconstruction  or  abuse,  were  derived  from  such 
doctrines,  had  no  small  share  in  leading  Pelagius  to  form  such 
a  system  as  he  did." —  Church  History,  vol.  iv.  p.  312. 


NOTE  X.  p.  56. 

SUNT  alii  [Pelagiani]  tarn  validis  testimoniis  non  audentes 
resistere ;  ideoque  dant  Deo  primitias  extrinsecas  gratiae  et 
fidei,  ac  bonorum  similium,  sed  hominibus  gratiam  ipsam  et 
fidem  cum  caeteris  bonis  hujusmodi.  Dicunt  enim  Deum 
semper  praevenire  pulsando,  et  excitando  ad  gratiam,  fidem,  et 
ad  bona  similia,  et  hominem  subsequi  aperiendo  et  consen- 
tiendo,  et  hoc  ex  propriis  viribus  per  seipsum,  juxta  illud 
Apoc.  3. :  "  Ecce  sto  ad  ostium,  et  pulso :  si  quis  audierit 
vocem  meam,  et  aperuerit  mihi  januam,  introibo  ad  ilium,  et 
crenabo  cum  illo,  et  ipse  mecum."  Hi  autem  faciunt  Deum 


332  NOTE    X. 


gratise  publicum  venditorem,  hominesque  emptores. 
Dicunt  enim  eum  sicut  mercatorem  pauperculum  clamare,  et 
pulsare  ad  januas,  et  ad  ostia  singulorum  ;  aperient!  vero 
pro  sua  apertione  gratiam  suain  dare,  quod  tamen  verius 
commutare,  seu  vendere  diceretur.  Faciunt  quoque  Deum 
scriptorem  pauperculum  et  conductitium  suam  operam  pub- 
licantem,  et  pro  pretio  parvulo,  pro  apertione  et  coena,  ape- 
rientium  nomina  in  libro  vitas  scribentem  ;  sicque  gratia  ex 
prsecedentibus  operibus  nostris  erit.  .  .  .  Homo  non  potest 
aperire  nee  consentire  in  talibus  ex  seipso,  sed  voluntate 
Divina,  quod  et  probant  auctoritates  superius  allegatae.  Nemo 
potest  venire  ad  me,  nisi  Pater  meus  traxerit  ilium.  Secun- 
dum  istos  tamen  homo  licet  pulsatus  a  deo,  non  habens  adhuc 
patrem,  aperiendo  pulsanti,  verius  traheret  ad  se  Patrem.  .  .  . 
Et  licet  sic  pulsat  nihil  dat  nobis,  sed  nos  aperientes  damus 
sibi  consensum,  contra  illud  Apostoli,  Quis  prior  dedit  illi,  et 
retribuetur  ei  ?  Itane  haec  positio  tribuit  nobis  quod  melius 
est  et  majus3  Deo  vero  quod  deterius  est  et  minus  :  quis 
enim  dubitaverit  aperire  melius  et  utilius  nobis  esse  quam 
pulsare,  cum  pulsare  sine  apertione,  non  prosit  sed  obsit.  — 
JBradicardine,  De  Causa  Dei,  1.  I.e.  38. 

Sentiebant  ergo  Pelagiani  uno  omnes  consensu,  tantas 
esse  vires  in  naturali  libertate,  bonique  et  mali  possibilitate 
constitutas,  ut  quaecunque  tandem  a  rebus  sive  extrinsecus 
irruentibus,  sive  intrinsecus  se  commoventibus,  vel  cogita- 
tiones  phantasiaaque  moverentur  vel  animi  desideria  motusque 
cierentur,  quicquid  tandem  sive  homines,  sive  Angeli,  sive 
Da3mones,  adeoque  Spiritus  ipse  sanctus  suaderet,  et  suggereret, 
quicunque  vel  pietatis  vel  iniquitatis  motus  inciderent,  qui- 
buscunque  passionum  bonarum  auris  animus  propelleretur, 
vel  malarum  fluctibus  procellisque  turbaretur,  nihil  de  suo 
imperii  principatu  domina  ilia  libertas  amitteret  ;  sed  plenis- 
sima  discernendi  potestate  penes  vim  rationis  ac  voluntatis 
permanente,  sola  fieret  ad  malum  bonumque  snasio  ac  provoca- 
tio  ;  nutus  vero  probandi  vel  improbandi,  utendi  et  repellendi, 
in  ilia  naturalis  indifferentiae  libertate  ac  naturali  possibilitate 
persist  eret.  —  Jansen,  De  Hcer.  Pel.  1.  2.  c.  3. 

Nihil  verius  de  tali  possibilitate  divino  adjutorio  munita 
dici  potuit,  quam  id  quod  Pelagius  dixit  :  "  Quod  possumus 


NOTE   X.  383 

omne  bonum  facere,  dicere,  cogitare,  illius  est  qui  hoc  posse 
donavit,  qui  hoc  posse  adjuvat :  quod  vero  bene  vel  agimus  vel 
loquimur  vel  cogitamus  nostrum  est  quia  base  omnia  vertere 
in  malum  possuraus."  Quibus  verbis  adjutorium  possibilitatis 
explicuit.  Vigilantissime  quippe  et  perspicacissime  vidit 
(quod  ego  saepius  supra  modum  admiratus  sum  Scholasticos 
eruditissimos  acutissimosque  viros  non  agnoscere)  quod  sicut 
usus  cujuslibet  facultatis  sive  oculi  externoruinque  sensuum, 
sive  facultatis  progressive,  sive  intellectus,  sive  voluntatis, 
noster  est,  hoc  est,  ad  nostrae  voluntatis  indifferentem  flexum 
et  nutum  referri  debet,  non  ad  Deum,  quatenus  solam  facul- 
tatem  dedit;  ita  quoque  cujuslibet  adjutorii  concursus,  sive 
naturalis  sive  gratuiti,  etiamsi  esset  tantas  praestantiae  adju- 
torium quantam  vel  angelica  cogitatio  comminisci  posset,  imo 
etiamsi  esset  vel  ipsa  essentia  Dei  per  modum  speciei  ad  sui 
visionem,  vel  per  modum  gratiaD  ad  sui  amorem  concurrentis, 
similiter  prorsus  noster  sit:  si  videlicet  sic  solam  possibilitatem 
adjuvet,  et  usus  ejus  et  non  usus  in  libero  relinquatur  arbitrio. 
—Jansen>  De  Gratia  Christi,  1.  2.  c.  9. 

Hanc  ergo  mentem  Pelagianorum  cum  prospectam 
haberet  Augustinus,  quod  quicquid  motuum  vel  Deus  vel 
Diabolus  in  voluntate  suscitaret,  isti  dominativae  voluntatis 
potestati  subderent,  non  fuit  sollicitus  utrum  gratiam  legis 
atque  doctrinae,  sive  revelationem  sapiential,  sive  exemplum 
Christi,  sive  remissionem  peccatorum,  sive  habitus  bonos,  sive 
succensiones  ac  desideria  voluntatis  assererent ;  sed  generalis- 
sime  prophanum  eorum  dogma  quo  solum  possibilitatem 
adjuvari  gratia  censebant,  ubicunque  vel  qualemcunque  ponerent 
gratiam,  velut  exploratum  errorem  Scripturisque  contrarium 
jugulat.  .  .  .  Quamvis  enim  in  gratiam  legis  plerumque  magis 
propendere  videretur,  non  satis  tamen  certum  erat  Augustino 
quam  gratiam  tarn  vario  magnificorum  verborum  strepitu  Pela- 
gius  tune  defenderet,  cum  nunc  legem,  nunc  doctrinam,  nunc 
sapientiae  revelationem,  nunc  exemplum  Christi,  nunc  peccati 
remissionem,  nunc  voluntatum  succensionem,  nunc  desideria  a 
Deo  suscitata  celcbraret.  Fatetur  hanc  suam  incertitudinem 
passim  toto  libro  Augustinus.  .  .  .  Itaque  ut  omnis  erroribus 
istis  latebra  clauderetur,  sub  qualibet,  et  qualilibet,  et  ubi- 
cumque  constituta  gratia  sua  in  eos  tela  dirigit.  .  .  .  Nirnirum 


384  NOTE   XI. 

quia  utrobique  Augustinus  quamlibet,  qualemlibet,  ubilibet 
constitutam  gratiam  quisque  tueatur,  si  solam  possibilitatem 
voluntatis  et  actionis  adjuvet,  eum  sanae  et  Apostolicas  et 
Evangelicae  doctrinae  violatae  reum  facit. — Jansen,  De  Gratia 
Christi,  1.  2.  c.  10. 


NOTE  XL  p.  59. 

AUGUSTINE'S  view  on  this  subject  is  comprehended  under 
the  following  heads  :  — 

1.  No  one  of  the  human  race  can  be  without  sin  abso- 
lutely or  from  the  first,  all  being  born  in  sin.     "  Qui  omnino 
nullum  pecatum  habuerit,  habiturusve  sit,  prorsus  nisi  unum 
Mediatorem   Dei  et  hominum  Jesum  Christum,  nullum  vel 
esse  vel  fuisse  vel  futurum  esse  certissimum  est." — De  Pecc. 
Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  2.  n.  34.     "  Non  legitur  sine  peccato  esse 
nisi  Filius  hominis." — De  Perfect.  Just.  n.  29.      See  too  De 
Pecc.  Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  1.  n.  56,  57. 

2.  Though  all  men  are  in  sin  to  begin  with,  there  is  the 
possibility  of  attaining  to  a  sinless  state  in  this  life  ;  but  this 
possibility  is  through  the  Divine  grace  or  power,  and  by  a 
miraculous  exertion  of  that  power.     "  Et  ideo  ejus  perfec- 
tionem  etiam  in  hac  vita  esse  possibilem,  negare  non  possu- 
mus,  quia  omnia  possibilia  sunt  Deo,  sive  quae  facit  sola  sua 
voluntate,  sive  qua?  cooperantibus  creaturas  suaa  voluntatibus 
a  se  fieri  posse  constituit.    Ac  per  hoc  quicquid  eorum  non 
facit,  sine  exemplo  est   quidem  in  ejus  operibus  factis ;  sed 
apud  Deum  et  in  ejus  virtute  habet  causam  qua  fieri  possit, 
et  in  ejus  sapientia  quare  non  factum  sit." — De  Spiritu  et 
Litera,n.  7.  "  Ecce  quemadmodum  sine  exemplo  est  in  homi- 
nibus  perfecta  justitia,  et  tamen  impossibilis  non  est.     Fieret 
enim  si  tanta  voluntas  adhiberetur  quanta  sufficit  tantae  rei. 
Esset  autem  tanta,  si  et  nihil  eorum  quas  pertinent  ad  justi- 
tiam  nos  lateret,  et  ea  sic  delectarent  animum,  ut  quicquid 
aliud  voluptatis  dolorisve  impedit,  delectatio  ilia  superaret : 
quod  ut  non  sit,  non  ad  impossibilitatem,  sed  ad  judicium  Dei 
pertinet." —  Ibid.  n.  63.     (<  Sed  inveniant  isti,  si  possunt,  ali- 


NOTE   XI.  385 

quern  sub  onere  corruptions  hujus  viventem,  cul  jam  non 

habeat  Deus  quod  ignoscat Sane  quemquam  talem,  si 

testimonia  ilia  divina  competenter  accipiant,  prorsus  invenire 
non  possunt ;  nullo  modo  tamen  dicendura,  Deo  deesse  pos- 
sibilitatem,  qua  voluntas  sic  adjuvetur  humana,  ut  non  solum 
justitia  ista  quae  ex  fide  est,  omni  ex  parte  modo  perficiatur  in 
homine,  verum  etiam  ilia  secundum  quam  postea  in  aeternum 
in  Jpsa  ejus  contemplatione  vivendum  est.  Quandoquidem, 
si  nunc  velit  in  quoquam  etiam  hoc  corruptibili  induere  in- 
corruptionem,  atque  hie  inter  homines  morituros  eum  jubere 
vivere  minime  moriturum,  ut  tota  penitus  vetustate  con- 
sumpta  nulla  lex  in  membris  ejus  repugnet  legi  mentis, 
Deumque  ubique  praesentem  ita  cognoscat,  sicut  sancti  postea 
cognituri  sunt ;  quis  demum  audeat  affirmare,  non  posse  ? 
Sed  quare  non  faciat  quajrunt  homines,  nee  qui  quasrunt  se 
attendunt  esse  homines."  —  Ibid.  n.  66. 

3.  While  he  thus  admits  the  possibility,  he  denies  the  fact 
that  any  man  has  attained  to  a  sinless  state  in  this  life :  '^Si 
autem  quaeratur  utrum  sit,  esse  non  credo.  Magis  enim  credo 
Scripturae  dicenti.  Ne  intres  in  judicium,"  &c. — De  Pecc. 
Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  2.  n.  8.  "  Hie  fortasse  respondeas,  ista 
quae  commemoravi  facta  non  esse  et  fieri  potuisse,  opera  esse 
divina ;  ut  autem  sit  homo  sine  peccato,  ad  opus  ipsius  ho- 
minis  pertinere,  idque  opus  esse  optimum,  quo  fiat  plena  et 
pcrfecta  et  ex  omni  parte  absoluta  justitia :  et  ideo  non  esse 
credendum,  neminem  vel  fuisse,  vel  esse,  vel  fore  in  hac  vita 
qui  hoc  opus  impleverit,  si  ab  homine  impleri  potest.  Sed 
cogitare  debes  quamvis  ad  homines  id  agere  pertineat,  hoc  quo- 
que  munus  esse  divinum,  atque  ideo  non  dubitare  opus  esse 
divinum." — De  Spir.  et  Lit.  n.  2.  "  Si  omnes  illos  sanctos 
et  sanctas,  cum  hie  vixerunt,  congregare  possemus,  et  interro- 
gare  utrum  essent  sine  peccato,  quid  fuisse  responsuros  puta- 
mus?  Utrum  hoc  quod  iste  dicit,  an  quod  Joannes  Apostolus. 
Rogo  vos,  quantalibet  fuerit  in  hoc  corpore  excellentia  sancti* 
tatis,  si  hoc  interrogari  potuissent,  nonne  una  voce  clamassent, 
*  Si  diximus  quia  peccatum  non  habemus  nos  ipsos  decipirnus, 
et  veritas  in  nobis  non  est. '  An  illud  humilius  responderent 
fortasse  quam  verius  ?  Sed  huic  jam  placet,  et  recte  placet, 

c  c 


386  NOTE    XI. 

'  laudem  humilitatis  in  parte  non  ponere  falsitatis.'  Itaque  hoc 
si  verum  dicerent,  haberent  peccatum,  quod,  humiliter  quia 
faterentur  veritas  in  eis  esset :  si  autem  hoc  mentirentur, 
nihilominus  haberent  peccatum,  quia  veritas  in  eis  non 
esset."  —  De  Nat.  et  Grat.  n.  42.  He  reserves,  however,  the 
liberty  to  except  the  Virgin  Mary  from  this  general  asser- 
tion :  "  De  qua,  propter  honorem  Domini,  nullam  prorsus, 
cum  de  peccatis  agitur,  haberi  vol'o  quaestionem." 

4.  To  assert  that  there  have  been  persons  in  this  life  who 
have  attained  to  the   sinless  state,  though  an   error,  is   an 
error  as  to  a  fact  rather  than  a  doctrine,  and  a  venial  one. 
"  Quinetiam  si  nemo  est  aut  fuit,  aut  erit,  quod  magis  credo, 
tali  puritate  perfectus;  et  tamen  esse  aut  fuisse  aut  fore  de- 

enditur  et  putatur,  non  multum  erratur,  nee  perniciose  cum 
quadam  quisque  benevolentia  fallitur:  si  tamen  qui  hoc 
putat  seipsum  talem  esse  non  putet,  nisi  revera  ac  liquido 
talem  se  esse  perspexerit." — De  Spir.  et  Lit.  n.  3.  "  Utrum 
in  hoc  seculo  fuerit,  vel  sit,  vel  possit  esse  aliquis  ita  juste 
vivens,  ut  nullum  habeat  omnino  peccatum,  potest  esse  ali- 
qua  qusestio  inter  veros  piosque  Christianos,  Posse  tamen 
esse  certe  post  hanc  vitam  quisquis  ambigit  desipit  Sed 
ego  nee  de  ista  vita  volo  contendere.  Quanquam  enim  mihi 
non  videatur  aliter  intelligendum  quod  scriptum  est,  (  Non 
justificabitur  in  conspectu  tuo  omnis  vivens,'  et  siqua  similia  : 
utinam  tamen  possit  ostendi  haec  testimonia  melius  aliter  intel- 
ligi." — De  Nat.  et  Grat.  n.  70. 

5.  Augustine  thinks  that  the  subjection  of  mankind  to  the 
law  of  sin  works  mysteriously  in  the  Divine  scheme  for  good. 
"  Idcirco  etiam  sanctos  et  fideles  suos  in  aliquibus  vitiis  tardius 
sanat,  ut  in  his  eos  minus,  quam  implenda3  ex  omni  parte  justi- 
tia3  sufficit,  delectet  bonum. . . .  Nee  in  eo  ipso  vult  nos  damna- 
biles  esse  sed  humiles." —  De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  2.  n.  33. 
This  very  imperfection  is  in  a  sense,  he  thinks,  as  leading  to 
humility,  part  of  the  perfection  of  human  virtue.     "  Ex  hoc 
factuui  est,  virtutem  quae  nunc  est  in  homine  justo,  perfectam 
hactenus  nominari,  ut  ad  ejus  perfectionem  pertineat  etiam 
ipsius  imperfectionis  et  in  veritate  cognitio,  et  in  humilitate 
confessio.     Tune  enim  est  secundum  hanc  infmmtatem  pro 


NOTE   XI  I.  387 

suo  modulo  perfecta  ista  parva  justitia,  quando  etiam  quid 
sibi  desit  intelligit.  Ideoque  Apostolus  et  imperfectum  et 
perfectum  se  dicit." —  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  3.  n.  19.  "De- 
serit  aliquando  Deus  ut  discas  superbus  non  esse.  Quidam 
traduntur  Satanre  ut  discant  non  blasphemare." — De  Nat.  et 
Grat.  n.  32.  Pelngius  ridicules  the  idea  that  peccatis  peccata 
curantur. 


NOTE  XII.  p.  84. 

MR.  COLERIDGE,  in  his  Aids  to  Reflection,  p.  272.,  strongly 
objects  to  the  received  doctrine  of  original  sin,  as  involving 
the  injustice  of  punishing  one  man  on  account  of  the  sin  of 
another;  in  the  place  of  which,  he  substitutes  (p.  278.)  a  ra- 
tionale of  original  sin,  in  which  he  rests  that  doctrine,  upon 
the  principle  of  cause  and  effect ;  asserting  that  all  evil  action 
implies  an  evil  in  the  will  as  the  cause  of  it,  which  anterior 
evil,  when  pushed  backward  and  backward  indefinitely,  be- 
comes original  evil  in  the  will,  or  original  sin.  "  Whatever 
resists  and,  as  a  positive  power,  opposes  this  (the  moral  law) 
in  the  will,  is  evil.  But  an  evil  in  the  will  is  an  evil  will; 
and  as  all  moral  evil  is  of  the  will,  this  evil  will  must  have 
its  source  in  the  will.  And  thus  we  might  go  back  from  act 
to  act,  from  evil  to  evil,  ad  injinitum,  without  advancing  a 
step."  This  anterior  evil  in  the  will,  then,  regarded  as  mys- 
terious, independent  of  time  and  intelligible  succession,  is,  he 
argues,  original  sin.  "  Let  the  evil  be  supposed  such  as  to 
imply  the  impossibility  of  an  individual  referring  it  to  any 
particular  time  at  which  it  might  be  conceived  to  have 
commenced,  or  to  any  period  of  his  existence  at  which  it  was 
not  existing.  Let  it  be  supposed,  in  short,  that  the  subject 
stands  in  no  relation  whatever  to  time,  can  neither  be  called 
in  time  or  out  of  time,  but  that  all  relations  to  time  are  as 
alien  and  heterogeneous  in  this  question  as  the  relations  and 
attributes  of  space  (north  or  south,  round  or  square,  thick  or 
thin)  are  to  our  affections  and  moral  feelings.  Let  the  reader 

c  c  2 


388  NOTE  xi  r. 

suppose  this,,  and  he  will  have  before  him  the  precise  import 
of  the  scriptural  doctrine  of  original  sin." 

It  is  evident  that,  according  to  this  rationale,  Adam  as  first 
created  had  original  sin,  and  had  a  corrupt  nature  as  truly 
as  any  of  his  posterity.  For  the  first  sinful  act  of  man  is  as 
open  as  any  other  to  this  reasoning  from  effect  to  cause,  from 
an  evil  act  to  an  evil  will,  and  from  an  evil  will  to  a  source 
of  evil  in  the  will  or  original  sin :  so  that  Adam's  sin  in 
Paradise  was  the  effect  of  original  sin  in  him,  or  a  corrupt 
nature,  only  differing  from  other  sins  in  being  the  first  effect. 
"  The  corruption  of  my  will  may  very  warrantably  be  spoken 
of  as  a  consequence  of  Adam's  fall,  even  as  my  birth  of 
Adam's  existence ;  as  a  consequence,  a  link  in  the  historic 
chain  of  instances,  ichereof  Adam  was  the  first.  But  that  it 
is  on  account  of  Adam,  or  that  this  evil  principle  was  a 
priori  inserted  or  infused  into  my  will  by  the  will  of  another 
—  which  is  indeed  a  contradiction  in  terms,  my  will  in  such 
a  case  being  no  will,  —  this  is  nowhere  asserted  in  Scripture 
explicitly  or  by  implication.  It  belongs  to  the  very  essence 
of  the  doctrine,  that  in  respect  of  original  sin  every  man  is 
the  adequate  representative  of  all  men.  What  wonder,  then, 
that  where  no  outward  ground  of  preference  existed,  the 
choice  should  be  determined  by  outward  relation,  and  that 
the  first  in  time  should  be  taken  as  the  diagram?" — p.  283. 

Such  being  the  rationale  of  original  sin  substituted  by 
Mr.  Coleridge  for  the  received  doctrine  of  original  sin  as 
the  consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam,  which  he  rejects  on  the 
ground  of  its  opposition  to  reason,  my  remark  is  this — that 
I  cannot  think  it  philosophical  in  any  writer  to  overthrow  a 
whole  received  language,  processing  to  express  an  incompre- 
hensible mystery,  on  such  a  ground.  Contradictory  language, 
or  language  opposed  to  reason,  is  the  only  one  in  which  mys- 
teries and  incomprehensible  truths  can  be  expressed ;  if  they 
could  be  expressed  in  consistent  language,  they  would  not 
be  mysteries.  Moreover,  the  writer  professes  that  he  can 
only  substitute  other  inconsistent  language  for  that  which 
he  rejects.  Mr.  Coleridge  admits  the  absolute  inconsist- 
ency of  an  original  evil  in  the  will  with  the  will's  self- 
determination  ;  yet,  because  he  thinks  both  of  these  to  be 


NOTE   XII.  389 

truths,  he  adopts  a  language  which  contains  them  both,  as 
the  only  mode  of  expressing  "  an  acknowledged  mystery, 
and  one  which,  by  the  nature  of  the  subject,  must  ever 
remain  such." — p.  277.  What  is  the  improvement,  then,  in 
consistency,  in  his  langunge  upon  the  received  language? 
While,  on  the  other  hand,  the  received  language,  by  attribut- 
ing the  fall  to  an  act  of  freewill  only,  which  no  evil  in  the 
will  preceded,  expresses  an  important  truth  that  sin  is  not 
fundamental  in,  but  only  accidental  to  human  nature;  a 
truth  which  Mr.  Coleridge's  language  of  original  evil  in  the 
will,  so  far  from  expressing,  rather  contradicts. 

The  same  remark  may  be  made  on  Mr.  Coleridge's  objec- 
tion to  the  received  doctrine  of  the  atonement  as  a  satisfac- 
tion for  sin  ;  which  he  rejects  on  the  same  ground  as  he  does 
the  received  doctrine  of  original  sin,  viz.,  its  opposition  to 
our  natural  idea  of  justice.  "Let  us  suppose,  with  certain 
divines,  that  the  varied  expressions  of  S.  Paul  are  to  be 
literally  interpreted :  ex.  gr.  that  sin  is,  or  involves,  an  in- 
finite debt  (in  the  proper  and  law-court  sense  of  the  word 
debt), — a  debt  owing  by  us  to  the  vindictive  justice  of  God 
the  Father,  which  can  only  be  liquidated  by  the  everlasting 
misery  of  Adam  and  all  his  posterity,  or  by  a  sum  of  suffer- 
ing equal  to  this.  Likewise,  that  God  the  Father,  by  His 
absolute  decree,  or  (as  some  divines  teach)  through  the  ne- 
cessity of  His  unchangeable  justice,  had  determined  to  exact 
the  full  sum,  which  must  therefore  be  paid  either  by  ourselves 
or  by  some  other  in  our  own  name  and  behalf.  But,  besides 
the  debt  which  all  mankind  contracted,  in  and  through  Adam, 
as  a  homo  publicus,  even  as  a  nation  is  bound  by  the  acts  of 
its  head  or  its  plenipotentiary,  every  man  (say  these  divines)  is 
an  insolvent  debtor  on  his  own  score.  In  this  fearful  predi- 
cament the  Son  of  God  took  compassion  on  mankind,  and 
resolved  to  pay  the  debt  for  us,  and  to  satisfy  the  Divine 
justice  by  a  perfect  equivalent 

"Now,  as  your  whole  theory  is  grounded  on  a  notion  of 
justice)  I  ask  you,  Is  this  justice  a  moral  attribute  ?  But 
morality  commences  with,  and  begins  in  the  sacred  distinction 
between  thing  and  person :  on  this  distinction  all  law  human 
and  divine  is  grounded  ;  consequently,  the  law  of  justice.  If 

c  c  3 


390  NOTE   XII. 

you  attach  any  meaning  to  the  term  justice,  as  applied  to 
God,  it  must  be  the  same  to  which  you  refer  when  you 
affirm  or  deny  it  of  any  other  personal  agent  —  save  only, 
that  in  its  attribution  to  God  you  speak  of  it  as  unmixed  and 
perfect.  For  if  not,  what  do  you  mean?  And  why  do  you 
call  it  by  the  same  name?  I  may,  therefore,  with  all  right 
and  reason,  put  the  case  as  between  man  and  man.  For 
should  it  be  found  irreconcilable  with  the  justice,  which  the 
light  of  reason,  made  laic  in  the  conscience,  dictates  to  man, 
how  much  more  must  it  be  incongruous  with  the  all-perfect 
justice  of  God !  .  .  .  . 

"  A  sum  of  1000Z.  is  owing  from  James  to  Peter,  for  which 
James  has  given  a  bond.  He  is  insolvent,  and  the  bond  is 
on  the  point  of  being  put  in  suit  against  him,  to  James's 
utter  ruin.  At  this  moment  Matthew  steps  in,  pays  Peter 
the  thousand  pounds  and  discharges  the  bond.  In  this  case, 
no  man  would  hesitate  to  admit,  that  a  complete  satisfaction 
had  been  made  to  Peter.  Matthew's  1000/.  is  a  perfect 
equivalent  for  the  sum  which  James  was  bound  to  have  paid, 
and  which  Peter  had  lent.  It  is  the  same  thing:  and  this  is 
altogether  a  question  of  things.  Now,  instead  of  James's 
being  indebted  to  Peter  for  a  sum  of  money,  which  (he  hav- 
ing become  insolvent)  Matthew  pays  for  him,  we  will  put  the 
case,  that  James  had  been  guilty  of  the  basest  and  most 
hard-hearted  ingratitude  to  a  most  worthy  and  affectionate 
mother,  who  had  not  only  performed  all  the  duties  and  tender 
offices  of  a  mother,  but  whose  whole  heart  was  bound  up  in 
this  her  only  child  —  who  had  foregone  all  the  pleasures  and 
amusements  of  life  in  watching  over  his  sickly  childhood,  had 
sacrificed  her  health  and  the  far  greater  part  of  her  resources 
to  rescue  him  from  the  consequences  of  his  follies  and  ex- 
cesses during  his  youth  and  early  manhood,  and  to  procure 
for  him  the  means  of  his  present  rank  and  affluence — all 
which  he  had  repaid  by  neglect,  desertion,  and  open  pro- 
fligacy. Here  the  mother  stands  in  the  relation  of  the  credi- 
tor :  and  here  too  we  will  suppose  the  same  generous  friend 
to  interfere,  and  to  perform  with  the  greatest  tenderness 
and  constancy  all  those  duties  of  a  grateful  and  affectionate 
son,  which  James  ought  to  have  performed.  Will  this 


NOTE   XII.  391 

satisfy  the  mother's  claims  on  James,  or  entitle  him  to  her 
esteem,  approbation,  and  blessing  ?  Or  what  if  Matthew, 
vicarious  son,  should  at  length  address  her  in  words  to  this 
purpose :  '  Now,  I  trust,  you  are  appeased,  and  will  be 
henceforward  reconciled  to  James.  I  have  satisfied  all  your 
claims  on  him.  I  have  paid  his  debt  in  full :  and  you  are 
too  just  to  require  the  same  debt  to  be  paid  twice  over. 
You  will  therefore  regard  him  with  the  same  complacency, 
and  receive  him  into  your  presence  with  the  same  love,  as  if 
there  had  been  no  difference  between  him  and  you.  For  I 
have  made  it  up.1  What  other  reply  could  the  swelling  heart 
of  the  mother  dictate  than  this  ?  (  0  misery  !  and  is  it  possi- 
ble that  you  are  in  league  with  my  unnatural  child  to  insult 
me?  Must  not  the  very  necessity  of  your  abandonment  of 
your  proper  sphere  form  an  additional  evidence  of  his  guilt  ? 
Must  not  the  sense  of  your  goodness  teach  me  more  fully  to 
comprehend,  more  vividly  to  feel  the  evil  in  him?  Must  not 
the  contrast  of  your  merits  magnify  his  demerit  in  *  his 
mother's  eye,  and  at  once  recall  and  embitter  the  conviction 
of  the  canker-worm  in  his  soul  ? ' 

"  If  indeed  by  the  force  of  Matthew's  example,  by  persuasion, 
or  by  additional  and  more  mysterious  influences,  or  by  an 
inward  co-agency,  compatible  with  the  existence  of  a  per- 
sonal will,  James  should  be  led  to  repent ;  if  through  admi- 
ration and  love  of  this  great  goodness  gradually  assimilating 
his  mind  to  the  mind  of  his  benefactor,  he  should  in  his  own 
person  become  a  grateful  and  dutiful  child  —  then  doubtless 
the  mother  would  be  wholly  satisfied  !  But  then  the  case  is 
no  longer  a  question  of  things,  or  a  matter  of  debt  payable  by 
another."— Aids  to  Reflection,  p.  322. 

But  is  not  Mr.  Coleridge  fighting  the  air,  when  he  objects, 
on  these  grounds,  to  the  received  doctrine  of  the  atonement 
as  a  satisfaction  for  sin  ?  It  is  quite  true  that  such  a  doc- 
trine is  opposed  to  our  natural  idea  of  justice,  as  well  as  to 
the  truth  of  common  reason,  that  one  person  cannot  be  a  sub- 
stitute for  another  in  moral  action.  But  who  does  not 
acknowledge  this  contrariety  ?  Does  not  the  most  devout 
believer  profess  to  hold  this  doctrine  as  a  mystery,  and  not  as 
a  truth  of  reason,  or  an  intelligible  truth  ?  And  if  he  holds 

c  c  4 


392       •  NOTE   XIII. 

it  as  such,  how  can  he  be  charged  with  holding  anything 
unreasonable  ?  How  can  an  assertion  be  called  contrary  to 
reason,  when  we  do  not  know  what  its  meaning,  i.  e.  the  thing 
asserted  in  it,  is  ?  And  how,  therefore,  can  the  maintaining  of 
such  an  unknown  truth  be  unreasonable?  The  Christian 
only  believes  that  there  is  a  truth  connected  with  this  subject, 
which  in  the  present  state  of  his  capacities  he  cannot  un- 
derstand, but  which,  on  the  principle  of  accommodation,  is 
expressed  in  revelation  in  this  form,  as  that  mode  of  ex- 
pressing it  which  is  practically  nearest  to  the  truth. 


NOTE  XIII.  p.  90. 

THE  connexion  of  this  present  state  of  sin  and  suffering  with 
some  great  original  transgression  was  too  deeply  laid  down  in 
Scripture  to  offer  an  easy  explanation  to  the  Pelagians.  One 
main  solution,  however,  of  such  passages  was  given;  viz, 
that  they  referred  to  a  connection  not  of  descent,  but  example, 
that  the  sin  of  Adam  was  fatal  as  an  imitated,  not  as  a  trans- 
mitted sin.  But  such  an  interpretation  obviously  fell  short  of 
the  meaning  of  Scripture,  nor  was  it  improved  by  the  details 
of  the  application.  The  Pelagian  comment  on  the  great  passage 
in  the  Epistle  to  the  Romans,  that  "  by  one  man  sin  entered 
into  the  world,  and  death  by  sin ;  and  so  death  passed  upon 
all  men,  for  that  all  have  sinned,"  opposed  to  the  received 
doctrine  of  transmitted  sin  ;  first,  the  expression  "one  man," 
which  sufficed,  it  was  said,  for  the  view  of  example,  whereas 
both,  the  man  and  the  woman  were  necessary  for  transmission1 ; 
secondly,  the  distinction  that  "death  passed  upon  all  men,'' 
not  sin  ;  and,  thirdly,  the  ground  of  actual  sin,  as  distinguished 
from  original,  "  for  that  all  have  sinned."  But  the  first  of 
these  objections  was  futile;  the  second  was  overruled  by  other 
texts  of  Scripture  which  made  death  the  consequence  of  sin  ; 


1  Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  47.  64. ;  1.  3.  c.  85. 


NOTE    XIII.  393 

and  the  third  can  only  at  most  be  allowed  a  balancing,  not  a 
disproving  weight.  The  Pelagian  was,  indeed,  the  better 
construer  of  the  Greek  words,  which  our  translation  with 
him  renders  into  "  for  that,"  and  not  with  S.  Augustine  into 
"in  whom."1  But  though  this  particular  clause,  thus  trans- 
lated, refers  to  a  ground  of  actual  sin,  not  of  original,  or 
sin  "in  Adam,"  as  S.  Augustine  understood  it;  the  reference 
to  actual  sin  does  not  destroy  the  previous  reference  to 
original,  at  the  beginning  of  the  verse.  The  previous  asser- 
tion is  plain  and  decisive,  that  "  by  one  man  sin  entered  into 
the  world ; "  though  the  mystery  of  original  sin  must  still  be 
held  together  with  the  truth  of  nature  that  God  only  punishes 
men  "  for  that"  they  themselves  "have  sinned." 

It  was  equally  vain  in  a  comment  on  the  text  that 
"  the  judgment  was  from  one  offence  to  condemnation,  but 
the  free  gift  was  of  many  offences  unto  justification,"  to 
attempt  to  negative  the  unity  of  the  sin  mentioned  in  the 
preceding  clause  by  the  plurality  in  the  next ;  and  to  argue, 
that  if  one  sin  had  been  the  source  of  the  general  sinfulness  of 
mankind,  it  would  have  been  written  "  from  one  offence,"  not 
"from  many  offences  unto  justification."2  The  unity  of  the 
source  is  not  inconsistent  with  plurality  in  the  proceeds  from 
it.  To  interpret  "many "again  to  mean  many  offences  of 
one  and  the  same  person  was  gratuitous3,  though  convenient 
for  a  coveted  inference,  that  the  state  out  of  which  a  man  was 
raised  at  justification  was  contemplated  here  only  as  a  state  of 
personal,  not  of  original  sin. 

No  candid  interpreter,  again,  of  the  text,  "  As  by  the 
offence  of  one  judgment  came  upon  all  men  to  condemnation ; 
even  so  by  the  righteousness  of  One  the  free  gift  came  upon 
all  men  unto  justification  of  life,"  would  allow  its  obvious 
force  to  be  negatived  by  the  remark  that,  as  all  mankind  do 
not  attain  to  justification,  the  universality  ascribed  to  the 
effect  of  Adam's  sin  in  the  first  clause  is  destroyed  by  the 
necessarily  limited  sense  of  universality,  as  applied  to  justifi- 


Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  63.  *  "  Doce    parvulos   multis   obnoxios 

Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  105.  I    esse  criminibus." — Op.  Imp.  1.  2.c.  114. 


394 


NOTE    XIII. 


cation,  in  the  next. l  Where  the  weight  of  Scripture  goes 
plainly  in  one  direction,  these  minute  verbal  criticisms  on 
dependent  and  subordinate  clauses,  ought  not  to  be  allowed 
to  interfere  with  it. 

From  the  passage  in  the  Epistle  to  the  Romans  the 
Pelagian  passed  to  that  in  the  First  Epistle  to  the  Corinthians, 
*  As  in  Adam  all  die,  even  so  in  Christ  shall  all  be  made 
alive"  (1  Cor.  xv.  22.);  and  his  interpretation  was  the 
same,  that  whether  death  was  understood  here  of  natural 
or  of  moral  death,  i.  e.  sin,  Adam  was  only  put  forth  as  the 
sample,  not  as  the  root  of  it;  an  interpretation  which  he 
confirmed  by  a  reference  to  the  succeeding  text,  "As  we 
have  borne  the  image  of  the  earthly  we  shall  also  bear  the 
image  of  the  heavenly  ; "  as  if  this  explained  the  preceding 
one  in  the  sense  of  an  actual  imitation  of  Adam,  not  of  any 
transmitted  guilt  or  penalty  from  him.  2 

The  curse,  at  the  commencement  of  the  book  of  Genesis, 
received  a  double  explanation ;  first,  as  imposing  no  new 
suffering  on  man ;  and,  secondly,  as  imposing  it,  if  it  did  im- 
pose it,  only  for  the  warning,  and  not  for  the  punishment  of 
posterity.3  The  Pelagian  observed  that  sorrows  were  "  mul- 
tiplied" on  the  woman,  as  if  they  had  existed  before4;  and 
that  Adam,  again,  on  whom  the  curse  imposed  labour,  had 
laboured  before  in  the  Garden  of  Eden  5 ;  and  that  as  a  matter 
of  fact  labour  was  not  the  universal  penalty,  because  it  was 
not  the  universal  lot  of  man.  The  sentence  of  death  was 
even  more  boldly  dealt  with ;  and  when  the  Pelagian  had  in- 
ferred from  the  text,  "  For  dust  thou  art,  and  unto  dust  shalt 
thou  return,"  that  this  event  rested  upon  a  physical  ground 
anterior  to  man's  transgression,  he  proceeded  to  observe  that 


1  "  Si  Christus  salvarit  universes, 
Adam  quoque  universis  nocuisse  finga- 
tur." — Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  136.  Augus- 
tine answers,  "  Qui  propterea  omnes 
liberate  dictus  est  etiam  ipse,  quoniam 
non  liberal  quenquam  nisi  ipse." — Ibid. 

3  "  Sicut  omnes,  i.  e.  -multi  Adae 
imitatione  moriuntur,  ita  omnes,  i.  e. 
multi  Christi  imitatione  salvantur." — 
Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  31. 


3  "  Ut  commemoratione  primi  peccati, 
afflictio  succedanea  his,  quos  reos  non 
fecerat,  imitationis    malae  indicet  cau- 
tionem." — Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  27. 

4  Augustine  :   "  Multiplicabo,  multas 
eas  esse  faciam.     Poterat    multiplicare 
quae  non  erant." — Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  26. 

5  "  Quid  ei  novum   accidisse  credi- 
mus,  si  sentiret  sudorem." — Op   Imp. 
1.  6.  c.  27. 


NOTE    XIV.  395 

the  announcement  of  it  at  that  time  was  not  intended  as  a 
severe,  but  as  a  consolatory  one,  —  a  promise  of  relief  from 
the  trials  and  pains  of  life. l  But  S.  Augustine  appealed  to  the 
evident  meaning  of  the  curse  as  a  judicial  sentence,  inflicting 
a  punishment  in  consequence  of  man's  sin  which  did  not 
exist  before  it2;  he  appealed  to  a  larger  sense  of  labour  than 
the  narrow  one  of  his  opponent3;  and  he  showed  to  the 
Pelagian  the  unavoidable  inference  from  his  explanation  of 
the  sentence  of  death,  that  man  was  wiser  after  his  transgres- 
sion than  he  was  before  it.  For  if  death  awaited  him  before 
his  sin,  as  the  lot  of  nature,  the  only  difference  which  the 
curse,  in  announcing  the  event  to  him,  made  was,  that  it  gave 
him  the  knowledge  of  it." 4 


NOTE  XIV.  p.  91. 

JULIAN  the  Pelagian  interprets  Adam  being  created  good  as 
meaning  merely  that  he  was  created  with  freewill,  or  the 
power  to  do  good ;  Augustine  interprets  it  as  meaning  that 
Adam  was  created  with  a  good  disposition  or  formed  habit, 
and  rejects  the  Pelagian  meaning  as  a  false  one,  for  the  plain 
reason  that  to  be  able  to  be  good  is  not  the  same  as  to  be 
good ;  whereas,  Adam  was  made  good.  He  admits,  indeed, 
that  in  a  certain  sense,  a  nature  which  is  able  not  to  sin  is  a 
good  nature :  "  Bonum  conditum  Adam  non  ego  tantum  nee 
tu,  sed  ambo  dicimus.  Ambo  enim  dicimus  bonam  esse  na- 
turam  qua?  possit  non  peccare." —  Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  16.  But 
this  sense  is  put  aside  as  insufficient.  "  Quid  est  ergo  quod 
nunc  dicis ;  f  Bonus  Deus  bonum  fecit  hominem,'  si  nee  bo- 
nus  nee  mains  est,  habendo  liberum  arbitrium  quod  in  eo  Deus 
fecit  ?  .  .  .  .  Et  quomodo  verum  est,  f  Fecit  Deus  hominem 
rectum?  —  Eccl.  vii.  29.  An  rectus  erat  non  habens  volun- 


\ 

2    u 


Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  27. 


Imo,  inquis  et  damnatus  est,  et 
nihil  ei  accidit  novi.  Hie  risum  tenere 
difficile  est."— -L.  6.  c.  27. 


3  L.  2.  c.  28. 

4  L.  6.  c.  27. 


396  NOTE   XIV. 

totem  bonctm,  sed  ejus  possibilitatem  ?  Ergo  et  pravus  erat 
non  habens  voluntatem  pravam,  sed  ejus  possibilitatem.  .  .  . 
Ita  fit,  ut  per  tuam  mirabilem  sapientiam,  nee  Deus  fecerit 
rectum  hominem ;  sed  qui  rectus  posset  esse  si  vellet"-  -L.  5. 
c.  57. 

Adam  being  created  good,  then,  meant  that  he  was  created 
with  a  positive  goodness,  or  a  good  habit  of  mind.  Such  a  habit 
S.  Augustine  expresses  by  the  term  bona  voluntas,  voluntas 
meaning  an  established  bias  or  inclination,  or  what  we  call 
character.  "  Sed,  inquis,  f  Ideo  potuit  oriri  voluntas  mala, 
ut  oriri  posset  et  bona.'  Quasi  non  cum  bona  voluntate  fac- 
tus  sit  vel  angelus  vel  homo.  Factus  est  rectus,  sicut  dixit 
Scriptura.  —  Eccl.  vii.  29.  Non  ergo  quaeritur  unde  in  illo 
potuerit  oriri  bona  voluntas,  cum  qua  factus  est ;  sed  unde 
mala  cum  qua  factus  non  est.  Et  tu  dicis,  non  attendens 
quid  dicas  '  Ideo  potuit  oriri  voluntas  mala,  ut  oriri  posset 
et  bona : '  et  hoc  putas  ad  naturam  liberi  arbitrii  pertinere, 
ut  possit  utrumque  et  peccare  scilicet  et  non  peccare ;  et  in 
hoc  existimas  hominem  factum  ad  imaginem  Dei,  cum  Deus 
ipse  non  possit  utrumque." — L.  5.  c.  38.  "  Quis  enim  ferat, 
si  dicatur  talis  factus,  quales  nascuntur  infantes  ?  Ilia  ita- 
que  perfectio  naturae  quam  non  dabant  anni,  sed  sola  manus 
Dei,  non  potuit  nisi  habere  voluntatem  aliquam,  eamque  non 
malam.  Bona3  igitur  voluntatis  factus  est  homo  .  .  .  neque 
enim  nisi  recta  volens  rectus  est  quisquam" — L.  5.  c.  61. 

Julian  objects  to  this  implanted  voluntas  on  the  freewill 
ground,  pronouncing  it  absurd  that  a  man  can  be  made  good ; 
on  the  ground  that  goodness  implied,  in  its  very  nature,  choice 
and  exertion  of  the  will.  "Estnaturahumanabonum  opus  Dei  : 
est  libertas  arbitrii,  id  est,  possibilitas  vel  delinquendi  vel  recte 
faciendi,  bonum  aeque  opus  Dei.  Utrumque  hoc  homini  de 
necessario  venit.  Sed  voluntas  in  his  exoritur  non  de  his. 
Capacia  voluntatis  sunt  quippe,  non  plena." —  Op.  Imp.  1.  5. 
c.  56.  "  Est  ergo  ista  possibilitas,  quae  nomine  libertatis  os- 
tenditur,  ita  a  sapient! ssimo  constituta  Deo,  ut  sine  ipsa  non 
sit,  quod  per  ipsarn  esse  non  cogitur."- -  c.  57.  Augustine 
replies  :  "  Ut  video,  nee  bonam  voluntatem  vis  tribuere  na- 
turae, quando  est  homo  primitus  conditus :  quasi  non  potue- 
rit Deus  hominem  facere  voluntatis  bonaa." — c.  61. 


NOTE   XIV.  397 

Augustine's  lona  voluntas  only  seems  to  express  in  a  dif- 
ferent form  the  traditional  view  of  the  Church  from  the  first, 
as  contained  in  the  writings  of  the  earlier  fathers.  Bishop 
Bull,  in  his  discourse  on  the  State  of  Man  before  the  Fall, 
quotes  their  principal  statements  on  the  subject.  They  all 
take  for  their  basis  the  scriptural  truth,  that  Adam  was  made 
in  the  image  of  God ;  and  they  commonly  interpret  this  to 
mean  that  the  soul  of  Adam  had  a  certain  indwelling  of  the 
Holy  Spirit  in  it.  Tatian,  the  pupil  of  Justin  Martyr,  speaks 
of  "  the  familiarity  and  friendship  "  of  the  Spirit  with  Adam 
in  his  created  state :  rijs  avv  avra>  Statr^y  —  iov  Trvsv/jLaros 
rov  SvvaTtoTEpov,  whom  he  also  calls  77  Aoyov  ^vvajjas. — Contra 
Grcecos,  c.  7.  Irenaeus  says  :  (<  Spiritus  commixtus  animae 
unitur  plasmati"  (1.  5.  c.  6.);  and  also  speaks  of  the  robe  of 
sanctity  which  Adam  had  from  the  Spirit :  "  quam  habuit  a 
Spiritu  sanctitatis  stolam." — L.  3.  c.  23.  Tertullian  speaks 
of  the  Spirit  of  God  which  Adam  received  by  inspiration : 
"  Spiritum  quern  tune  de  afflatu  ejus  acceperat." — De  Bap- 
tismo,  c.  5.  Clemens  Alexandrinus  speaks  of"  the  characteris- 
tical  propriety  of  the  Holy  Spirit  superadded"  to  the  nature 
of  Adam  :  7rpoa<yiv6fjisvov  dylov  Trvsvfjbaros  f)(apaicTripicniKov 
t'Stcoyita. — Strom.  1  6.  c.  16.  Athanasius  speaks  of  God  impart- 
ing to  our  first  parents  the  power  of  His  own  Word:  /AsraSovs 
avrols  KOI  TTJS  rov  I&LOV  A6<yov  ^vvdfjisws. — De  Incar.  Verb.  torn, 
i.  c.  3.  Basil  speaks  of  the  "  assession  of  God,  and  conjunction 
with  him  (Adam)  by  love —  17  Trpoo-sBpsta  rov  6sov}  /cal  rj  Sia  rrjs 
ajaTrrjs  (rvvdfaia." — Howil.  quod  non  Deus  est  Auctor  Peccat. 
Cyril  speaks  of  "  that  Spirit  which  formed  him  (Adam)  after 
the  Divine  image,  and  was,  as  a  seal,  secretly  impressed  on  his 
soul  —  TO  Trpos  Osiav  siKova  Sia/jLOpfovv  avrb,  /cal  G-^^avrpov 
SLK^V  aTropprjTWs  svreBsLfjbevov^  - —  7.  Dialog,  de  Trin.  This 
familiar  abode  of  the  Spirit  in  the  first  man,  and  the  cha- 
racter and  seal  stamped  by  the  Spirit  upon  him,  evidently 
imply  a  certain  disposition  of  mind  or  holy  habit  which  was 
formed  in  him,  as  Cyprian  (De  Bono  Patientice)  actually  ex- 
presses it,  interpreting  the  Divine  image  as  involving  virtues 
—  virtutes. 


398  NOTE   XV. 


NOTE  XV.  p.  108. 

THUS  Justin  Martyr  Fays  of  the  human  race :  o  dirb  TOV  ' 
VTTO  OdvaTOv  KOI  ir\dv7]v  TTJV  TOV  ofaws  STCSTCTMKZI,  irapd  rrjv 
ISiav  alriav  s/cdaTov  avrcov  Trovypsvcra/jLEvov. — Dial,  cum  Tryph. 
c.  88.  Trapa  here  signifying  not  besides  (pr&ter)  but  by  rea- 
son of  sua  propria  cujusque  culpa,  the  latter  half  of  this  sen- 
tence gives  the  natural  truth — viz.,  that  the  individual  sins  by 
the  exercise  of  his  own  freewill;  as  the  former  gives  the 
revealed,  that  the  individual  sins  in  consequence  of  the  sin- 
fulness  of  the  race.  One  sentence  of  Tatian's  joins  the  two 
in  the  same  way :  ffiOi  TQ>  dsa)  rrjv  ira\aidv  ysvscriv  Trapatrov- 
IJLSVOS.  OVK  sysvo/AsOa  Trpo?  TO  aTrod^a/csiv,  airoQvr](JKO^v  Ss  SI 
savTovs. —  Contra  Grcec.  c.  1 1.  The  "  old  birth"  is  the  myste- 
rious, the  "  SI  SCLVTOVS"  the  obvious  and  conscious  cause  of  sin. 
So  far  the  fathers  only  follow  the  precedent  of  Scripture, 
which  put*  the  two  grounds  together,  as  in  Eom.  v.  12., 
<c  As  by  one  man  sin  entered  into  the  world  and  death  by 
sin  ;  and  so  death  passed  upon  all  men,  for  that  all  have 
sinned  ; "  death  being  referred  in  the  first  part  of  the  sentence 
to  the  sin  of  Adam,  in  the  last  to  each  man's  actual  sins. 
Again,  several  fathers  speak  of  infants  as  innocent  beings : 
"  Quid  festinat  innocens  aetas  ad  remissionem  peccatorum." — 
Tertullian,  De  Bapt.  c.  18.  "  *E\66vT£s  sisTovSs  TOV  Koa^ov 
avafidpTijToi." —  Cyril  of  Jerusalem,  Cat.  iv.  13.  "  To  aTrsi- 
pofcaicov  vrjTriov  .  .  prj  SSOJJLSVOV  TTJS  s/c  TOV  /ca6ap0f)vai  vytSLas, 
OTL  fj,r)Ss  Trjv  dpfflv  Trjv  voaov  Trj  ^v^(fj  TrapsSs^aTO.  .  .  TO  /JLIJTS 
ev  dydOq),  fj,r)TS  h  KCLKW  £vpi(TKo^svov^ —  Gregory  Nyss.  (De  iis 
qui  praemature  abripiuntur).  But  Hagenbach  is  precipitate 
in  concluding  from  the  passage  in  Cyril,  that  "  Cyril  of 
Jerusalem  assumed  that  men  are  born  in  a  state  of  inno- 
cence" (History  of  Doctrines,  v.  i.  p.  315.);  i.  e.  if  he  means 
by  this  that  Cyril  denied  original  sin.  It  is  a  truth  of  rea- 
son and  nature,  that  infants  are  innocent  beings,  which  may 
be  asserted,  as  it  must  be  by  every  rational  person,  without 
prejudice  to  the  mysterious  truth  of  their  guilt  as  descendants 


NOTE    XV.  399 

of  Adam.  Tertullian,  who  asserts  it,  is  at  the  same  time 
acknowledged  as  one  of  those  fathers  who  have  most  strongly 
asserted  the  doctrine  of  original  sin ;  and  Scripture  itself 
asserts  both,  saying  of  children,  that  "  of  such  is  the  kingdom 
of  heaven,"  while  at  the  same  time  it  declares,  that  "  in  Adam 
all  die."  Chrysostom  again  denies  that  one  man  can  be  re- 
sponsible for  another  man's  sin :  TO  /JLSV  <yap  srspov  &t'  srspov 
Ko\d£eo-dai  ov  a(j>&6opa  SOKSI  \6yov  s^eiv.  —  Horn.  X.  in  Rom. 
But  this  is  a  simple  truth  of  reason  which  nobody  can  deny, 
and  the  assertion  of  it  is  quite  consistent  with  holding  the 
mystery  of  our  guilt  in  Adam.  All  the  early  fathers,  more- 
over, assert  strongly  the  freewill  of  even  fallen  man,  his 
TrpoaLpscris  s\svOspa,  avTs^oixriov.  But  this  runs  side  by  side 
with  their  assertion  of  his  "  captivity"  and  (f  corruption,"  as 
another  part  of  the  whole  truth. 

The  case  of  Clement  of  Alexandria  is  perhaps  peculiar, 
though  too  much  should  not  made  of  particular  expressions, 
like  the  ones  just  quoted,  found  in  him.  In  combating, 
indeed,  the  Gnostic  doctrine  of  our  evil  nature,  he  uses 
arguments  which  would  equally  tell  against  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin.  He  denies  that  any  one  can  be  evil  but  by  his 
own  personal  act :  \8y4raMTav  r^^lv  TTOV  siropvsvasv  TO 

TTafStOV,  TJ  7TO)9  V7TO  TTjV  TOV    'A&tyt    VTrOTTETTTCOKSV  dpdv  TO 

svspyrjcrav, —  Strom.  1.  3.  c.  16.  He  describes,  again,  sin 
after  the  fall,  as  if  it  were  only  a  repetition,  and  not  an  effect 
of  sin  at  the  fall :  sis  yap  6  airaT^v  dvwOsv  JJLSV  TTJV  Euaz>,  vvv 
£e  rjSrj  KOL  TOVS  a\\ovs  avdpaiTrovs  sis  ddvaTOV  virocfrepcov. — 
Ad  Gentes,  vol.  1.  p.  7.  But  Hagenbach  is  precipitate  in 
concluding  that  Clement  "  rejects  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin,  properly  so  called,"  simply  on  the  strength  of  such  pas- 
sages as  these. — History  of  Doctrine,  v.  1.  p.  173.  Augus- 
tine himself  has  a  similar  passage  exactly  to  the  one  just 
quoted:  "Etiam  nunc  in  unoquoque  nostrum  nihil  aliud 
agitur,  cum  ad  peccatum  quisque  delabitur,  quam  tune  actum 
est  in  illis  tribus,  serpente,  muliere,  et  viro.  —  De  Genesi 
contra  Man.  1.  2.  c.  14.  Such  expressions  are  no  more  than 
what  common  sense  justifies  and  obliges,  and  are  quite 
consistent  with  belief  in  the  other  truth.  But  Clement, 
though  he  asserts  sin  to  be  "  natural,"  TO  <ydp 


400  NOTE    XVI. 


S/UL^VTOJ/  KOI  Koivbv^Pced.  1.  3.  c.  12),  (his  language,  how- 
ever, seeming  to  express  here  universal  rather  than  original 
sin),  certainly  seems  to  explain  away  the  passage  in  the  Psalms, 
"  in  sin  hath  my  mother  conceived  me,"  interpreting  it  to  refer 
to  sinful  custom  or  habit,  not  to  sinful  nature  (Strom.  1.  3. 
c.  16.),  though  at  the  same  time  it  must  be  remarked,  that  he 
is  relieving  the  passage  of  a  Gnostic  meaning,  according  to 
which  sin  was  inherent  in  natural  generation  as  such,  and 
not  opposing  the  Catholic.  Jeremy  Taylor  gives  a  somewhat 
similar  explanation  with  less  excuse.  "  The  words  are  a 
Hebraism,  and  signify  nothing  but  an  aggrandation  of  his 
sinfulness,  and  are  intended  for  a  high  expression,  meaning 
that  "  I  am  wholly  and  entirely  wicked."  —  Vol.  ix.  p.  27. 
On  the  whole,  though  Clement,  in  common  with  all  the  early 
fathers,  is  a  lenient  interpreter  of  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin,  and  though  such  passages  as  these  have  not  such  coun- 
terbalancing ones  in  his  writings  as  they  have  in  those  of 
other  fathers,  these  passages  are  no  test  of  his  belief  on  the 
subject. 


NOTE  XVI.  p.  121. 

Tous-  Se  (unbaptized  infants,  or  those  who  by  accident  died 
without  baptism)  /n^rs  &o%ao-0r}cr£cr0ai,,  IMJTS  /coXacrOtjasaOai, 
Trspl  rov  bifcalov  /cpirov,  ws  da(f)pajL(7Tovs  /jisv  airovrjpovs  $e, 
d\\a  TraObvras  jJuaXkov  rrjv  tfl/jblav  f)  Spdaavras.  ov  jap  00-71$ 
ov  KO\do~£(t)S  a^ios  ijSrj  /cal  TifATJs '  cbaTrsp  OGTIS  ov  Tijmfjs  ij$r]  /cal 
Ko\do-£dJ9. —  Gregory  Naz.  Orat.  40.  v.  i.  p.  653.  Gregory 
of  Nyssa  formally  discusses  the  question  of  the  future  condi- 
tion of  those  who  die  as  infants,  without  reference  to  their 
being  or  not  baptized  .(v.  ii.  p.  749)  ;  which,  in  distinction  to 
the  ground  taken  by  some,  that  they  do  not  deserve  so  much 
happiness  as  the  mature  good,  he  maintains  to  turn,  not  so 
much  upon  any  difference  of  claim,  as  of  natural  aptitude 
and  capacity  for  happiness.  Ov/c  E<TTW  slTrelv  icvpiws  dvriBo- 
auv  TWV  sv  ffefficoKOTCov  <ysvscr6ai  rrjv  rfjs  farjs  fjiSTOvaiav  Kal 

TO  £/J,7Ta\l,V.  'A\V  OjJLOiOV  SffTl  TO)  Kara  TOVS  6(f)Oa\fJiOVf 


NOTE    XVI.  401 

TO  \syofjisvov.  Qvos  jap  T&>  /cs/cadapfjusvp  ras  otysis 
£7ra6\6v  TL  fyajJLSv  elvai  KOI  Trpzcrftslov  rr)V  TCOV  6pdra)v  /cara- 
vdr](Tiv,  rj  T(j>  VOCTOVVTL  TO  Ejji7ra\ti>  /caraSiKrjv  nva  TO  fjur]  /ASTE- 
^siv  TTjf  opan/cfjs  evspygfas'  'AAA,'  o)s  dvayKalws  STrsrai,  TCO 
Kara  fyvaiv  8ia/C£i/j,sv(t)  TO  jSXsTrsiv,  TU>  rs  diro  irdOovs  Trapsvg- 
^dsvri  TTfs  (f)vasa)9,  TO  yu-^  Evspyslv  Tr)V  opacriv  '  rbv  avrov  TOTTOV 
Kal  f)  fjua/capia  for)  av/ji^urjs  sari,  /cat  OiKsla  rols  KSKaOapfMsvo^ 
ra  777?  'tyvxfjs  aladrjrrjpia.  Upon  this  principle  he  proceeds 
to  argue  that  the  happiness  of  infants  in  a  future  state  will 
be  in  proportion  to  their  capacity  for  it,  which  will  be  lower 
than  that  of  those  who  have  lived  virtuously  as  mature  men ; 
that  it  will  be  analogous  to  their  happiness  in  this  life,  which  is 
of  the  simpler  and  unconscious  kind.  ^aOdirsp  yap  0rj\fj  Kal 
rydXaKTi  YJ  TTpcarr)  TMV  VTJTTICOV  r)\iKia  TiOuvovjjbsvri  s/crpstpsrat ' 
slra  SLaSs^srai  Tavrrjv  Kard\\,rf\os  srspa  TO> 

TpO(j)r),  olfCELCOS    TS    KOL    STTLTrjBsLWS    TTpOS    TO    Tp£(j)6/J,SVOV 

fo>p   av  sjrl  TO     T£\£iov  (f)0da-r) '  OVTOJS  ol/jbat,   Kal  rrjv 
Sid  TWV  dsl  tear*  d\\i]\a)v  rd^st,  nvl  Kal  aKoXovQia 
rrj?  Kara  §\)<Jiv  for)?,  &$  XWP£^  Ka^  ^>vvaTai  rwv  sv 

Tr)Ti,7rpoK£i,jj,sva)i>  KaTa\a/j,{3dvovo-a fH  Ss  aysvcrros  rrjy 

dpsrrjs  ^f%^,  T0)v  IJLSV  EK  Tro^ptay  KaK&v,  are  fj,rjrs  rrjv 
rfj  rfjs  KaKias  vbo-w,  Stapsvsi,  dp,£TO%os  rrjs 
ii]V  ©eoO  yvwcrt'v  TS  Kal  /jusrovcrlav  TOOTOVTOV 
irapd  Trjv  7rpu)Tr)v}ocrov  ^a)psi  TO  Tpsfyofjuevov. — Augustine  main- 
tained a  middle  state,  in  his  earlier  theological  life. — Dicunt 
enim:  quid  opus  est  ut  nasceretur  qui  antequam  iniret  ullum 
vitae  meritum  excessit  e  vita?  Aut  qualis  in  futuro  judicio 
deputabitur,  cui  neque  inter  justos  locus  est,  quoniam  nihil 
recte  fecit ;  neque  inter  malos,  quoniam  nihil  peccavit  ?  Qui- 
bus  respondetur  :  ad  universitatis  complexum,  et  totius  crea- 
turse  vel  per  locos  vel  per  tempora  ordinatissimam  con- 
nexionem,  non  posse  superfluo  creari  qualemcunque  hominem, 
ubi  folium  arboris  nullum  superfluum  creatur;  sed  sane  su* 
perfluo  quae.ri  de  meritis  ejus  qui  nihil  meruerit.  Non  enim 
metuendum  est  ne  vita  esse  potuerit  media  quaedam  inter 
recte  factura  atque  peccatum,  et  sententia  judicis  media  esse 
non  possit  inter  pnemium  et  supplicium.  —  De  Lib.  Arb. 
1.  3.  c.  23. 

D  D 


402  KOTE    XVII. 


NOTE  XVII.  p.  128. 

IN  the  first  of  the  following  passages  all  wickedness,  in  the 
second  extreme  wickedness,  is  referred  to  original  sin ;  in  the 
third,  different  degrees  admitted  in  evil,  are  accounted  for  by 
different  degrees  of  original  sin;  in  the  fourth  and  fifth  these 
decrees  in  evil  appear  as  the  additions  of  the  individual  to 
original  sin,  though  in  what  precise  sense  they  leave  uncertain. 
(1.)  "  Ad  iram  quippe  Dei  [in  consequence  of  original  sin] 
pertinet  justam,    quicquid  caeca  et  indomita   concupiscentia 
faciunt  libenter  mali." — Enchiridion,  c.  27.     (2.)  "  Omnes 
ex  eadem  niassa  perditionis  et  damnationis   secundum  duri- 
tiem  cordis  sui   et    cor  impenitens,   quantum  ad  ipsos  per- 
tinet,  thesaurizant  sibi  iram   in   die  iraj,   quo  redditur  uni- 
cuique  secundum  opera  sua." — Contra  Julianum  Pelayiamim, 
1.  5.  c,  4.     (3.)  "  Veruntamen   taciturn  non    est  quod   erat 
eorum  malitia  naturalis ;  quae  quidem  omnium  hominum,  sed 
in  aliis  minor,  in  aliis  major  est :  sicut  corpora  corruptibilia 
sunt  omnium,  sed  alias  animas  minus,  alias  plus  gravant,  pro 
diversitate  judiciorum  Dei,  occultorum  quidem,  sed  sine  ulla 
dubitationejustoruni." — Opus  Imp.  Contra  Julianum  s\  A.  C.12S. 
(4.)  "  Hi  ergo  qui  non  pertinent  ad  istum  certissirnum  et  fe- 
licissimum  numerum  pro  mentis  justissime  judicantur.     Aut 
enim  jacent  sub  peccato,  quod  originaliter  generatim  traxerunt, 
et  cum  illo  haereditario  debito  hinc  exeunt,  quod  non  est  rege- 
neratione  dimissum ;  aut  per  liberum  arbitrium  alia  insuper 
addiderunt ;  arbitrium,  inquam,  liberum  sed  non  liberatum ; 
liberum  justitia3,  peccati  autem  servum,  quo  volvuntur  per 
diversas  noxias  cupiditates,  alii  magis,  alii  minus ;  sed  omnea 
mali."— De  Correptione  et   Gratia,  c.  13.     (5.)  "  Si  autem 
male  vivunt  de  suo  male  vivunt,  vel  quod  originaliter  traxe- 
runt, vel  quod  insuper  addiderunt.     Sed   si  vasa  sunt  iraj, 
quae  perfecta  sunt  ad  perditionem,  quae  illis  debita  redditur, 
sibi  hoc  imputent,  quia  ex  ea  massa  facta  sunt,  quam  propter 
unius   peccatuin,  in  quo  omnes    peccaverunt,   merito  Deus 
justeque  damnavit." — Ep.  194.  c.  6. 

Jansen  interprets  S.  Augustine  as  making  the  whole  mass  of 


NOTE  xrai.  403 

actual  sin  in  the  world  the  simple  effect  and  development  of 
original.  "  Positive  reprobationis  causa  .  .  .  peccata  omnia 
cum  quibus  morituri  sunt,  etiam  originale  peccatum.  Nam 
ex  illius  suppliciis  quicquid  peccatorum  a  reprobatis  perpetra- 
tum  est  accessu  libers  voluntatis,  fluxit  .  .  .  ut  proinde  ilia 
tota  suppliciorum  concatenatio,  usque  ad  damnationem  in 
ignem  aeternam,  radicaliter  et  mediate  in  peccati  originalis 
meritum  referenda  videatur.  Immediate  tamen  prima  poc- 
narum  istarum  promeretur  secundam,  et  ita  deinceps,  donee 
ultima  tandem,  velut  praecedentium  complementum,  infera- 
tm:"—De  Gratia  Christi,  p.  1019. 


NOTE  XVIII.  p.  130. 

"  ET  propterea  conantur  parvulis  non  baptizatis  innocentiae 
merito  salutem  ac  vitam  aeternam  tribuere ;  sed,  quia  bap- 
tizati  non  sunt,  eos  a  regno  coelorum  facere  alienos :  nova 
quadam  et  mirabili  praesumptione,  quasi  salus  ac  vita  aeterna 
possit  esse  prseter  Christi  haereditatem,  praeter  regnum  ccelo- 
rum.  .  .  .  Profecto  illi  quibus  Sacramentum  defuerit  in  eis 
habendi  sunt  qui  non  credunt  Filio ;  atque  ideo,  si  hujus 
inanes  gratiae  de  corpore  exierint,  sequetur  eos  quod  dictum 
est,  '  Non  habebunt  vitam  sed  ira  Dei  manet  super  eos.' 
Unde  hoc,  quando  eos  clarum  est  peccata  propria  non  habere, 
si  nee  originali  peccato  teneantur  obnoxii."  —  De  Peccat. 
Merit,  et  Bern.  1.  1.  c.  xx. 

"  Quia  ergo  de  ovibus  ejus  non  esse  incipiunt  parvuli  nisi 
per  baptismum ;  profecto,  si  hoc  non  accipiunt,  peribunt." — 
Ibid.  c.  xxvii. 

"  Quemadmodum  enim  omnes  omnino  pertinentes  ad 
generationem  voluntatis  carnis  non  moriuntur  nisi  in  Adam 
in  quo  omnes  peccaverunt:  sic  ex  his  omnes  omnino  per- 
tinentes ad  regenerationem  voluntatis  spiritus  non  vivi- 
ficantur  nisi  in  Christo,  in  quo  omnes  justificantur.  Quia 
sicut  per  unum  omnes  ad  condemnationem,  sic  per  unuin 
omnes  ad  justificationem.  Nee  est  ullus  medius  locus  ut 
possit  esse  nisi  cum  diabolo,  qui  non  est  cum  Christo.  Hie  et 

D    D    2 


404  NOTE   XVIII. 

ipse  Dominus  volens  auferre  de  cordibus  male  credcntium 
istam  nescio  quara  medietatem,  quam  conantur  quidam  par- 
vulis  non  baptizatis  tribuere,  ut  quasi  merito  innocentiae  sint  in 
vita  aeterna,  sed  quia  non  sunt  baptizati  non  gint  cum  Christo 
in  regno  ejus,  definitivam  protulit  ad  haec  ora  obstruenda 
sententiam,  ubi  ait :  '  Qui  mecuin  non  est,  adversum  me  est.' 
Constitue  igitur  quemlibet  parvulum  :  si  jam  cum  Christo 
est,  ut  quid  baptizatur?  Si  autem,  quod  habet  veritas,  ideo 
baptizatur  ut  sit  cum  Christo,  profecto  non  baptizatus  non  est 
cum  Christo,  et,  quia  non  est  cum  Christo,  ad  versus  Christum 
est." — Hid.  c.  xxviii. 

"  Unde  fit  consequens  ut,  quoniam  nihil  agitur  aliud,  cum 
parvuli  baptizantur,  nisi  ut  incorporentur  ecclesiae,  id  est, 
Christi  corpori  membrisque  associentur ;  inanifetstum  est  eos 
ad  damnationem,  nisi  hoc  eis  collatum  fuerit,  pertinere.  Non 
autem  damnari  possent,  si  peccatum  utique  non  haberent. 
Hoc  quia  ilia  aetas  nulla  in  vita  propria  contrahere  potuit, 
restat  intelligere  vel,  si  hoc  nondum  possumus,  saltern  credere, 
trahere  parvulos  originate  peccatum."  —  Ibid.  1.  3.  c.  iv. 

ee  Absit  ut  causam  parvulorum  sic  relinquamus,  ut  esse 
nobis  dicamus  incertum,  utrum  in  Christo  regenerati,  si  mo- 
riantur  parvuli,  transeant  in  aeternam  salutem;  non  regenerati 
autem  transeant  in  mortem  secundam  ;  quoniam  quod  scrip- 
turn  est,  *  Per  unum  hominem  peccatum  intravit  in  mundum, 
et  per  peccatum  mors ;  et  ita  in  omnes  homines  pertransiit,' 
aliter  recte  intelligi  non  potest :  nee  a  morte  perpetua  qua3 
justissime  est  retributa  peccato,  liberat  quenquam  pusillorum 
atque  magnorum,  nisi  ille  qui  propter  remittenda  et  originalia 
et  propria  nostra  peccata  mortuus  est,  sine  ullo  suo  originali  et 
proprio  peccato.  Sed  quare  illos  potius  quam  illos?  Iterum 
atque  iterum  dicimus,  nee  nos  piget,  *  O  homo,  tu  quis  es  qui 
respondeas  Deo  ?  ";  —  De  Dono  Perseverantice,  c.  xii. 

"  Sed  ut  id  quod  dicimus  alicujus  exempli  manifestatione 
clarescat,  constituamus  aliquos  ab  aliqua  meretrice  geminos 
editos,  atque  ut  ab  aliis  colligerentur,  expositos :  horum  sine 
baptismo  expiravit  unus,  alius  baptizatus.  ...  Quid  restat 
quantum  ad  baptizatum  attinet,  nisi  gratia  Dei  quae  vasis 
factis  in  honorem  gratis  datur;  quantum  autem  ad  non 
baptizatum,  ira  Dei,  quae  vasis  factis  ad  contumeliam  pro 


NOTE   XVIII.  405 

ipsius  massae  mentis  redclitur  ?" — Contra  Duas,  Ep.  Pel.  1.  2. 
c.  vii. 

"  Ac  per  hoc,  quia  nihil  ipsi  male  vivendo  addiderunt  ad 
originale  peccatum,  potest  eorum  merito  dici  in  ilia  damna- 
tioiie  minima  poena,  non  tamen  nulla.  Quisquis  autem  putat 
diversitatem  futuram  non  esse  poenarum,  legat  quod  scriptum 
est,  '  Tolerabilius  erit  Sodomas  in  die  judicii,  quam  illi 
civitati.'  Non  ergo  a  deceptoribus  inter  regnum  et  suppli- 
cium  medius  locus  quseratur  infantibus ;  sed  transeant  a 
diabolo  ad  Christum,  hoc  est,"  a  morte  ad  vitam,  ne  ira  Dei 
maneat  super  eos."  —  Ep.  184.  c.  1. 

"  Respondeat  quid  de  illo  futuram  sit,  qui,  nulla  sua  culpa 
non  baptizatus,  ista  fuerit  temporal!  morte  praeventus.  Si 
non  putamus  esse  dicturum  quod  innocentern  Deus,  nee 
habentem  originale  peccatum  ante  annos  quibus  habere 
poterat  proprium,  aeterna  morte  damnabit ;  cogitur  itaque 
respondere  quod  Pelagius  in  ecclesiastico  judicio,  ut  aliquo 
modo  catholicus  pronuntiaretur,  anathematizare  compulsus 
est,  infantes,  etiamsi  non  baptizentur,  habere  vitam  aeternam: 
hac  enim  negata,  quid  nisi  mors  aeterna  remanebit?"  —  Ep. 
186.  c.  viiL 

(f  Primus  hie  error  aversandus  ab  auribus,  exstirpandus  a 
mentibus.  Hoc  novum  in  ecclesia,  prius  inauditum  est,  esse 
vitam  aeternam  praster  regnum  coelorum,  esse  salutem  aeternam 
praster  regnum  Dei.  Primo  vide,  frater,  ne  forte  hie  con- 
sentire  nobis  debeas,  quisquis  ad  regnum  Dei  non  pertinet, 
eum  ad  damnationem  sine  dubio  pertinere.  Venturus  Domi- 
nus,  et  judicaturus  de  vivis  et  mortuis,  sicut  evangelium 
loquitur,  duas  partes  facturus  est,  dextram  et  sinistram. 
Sinistris  dicturus,  Ite  in  ignem  (Bternam,  qui  paratus  est 
Diabolo  et  anyelis  ejus ;  dextris  dicturus,  Venite  benedictl 
Patris  mei,  percipite  regnum  quod  vobis  paiatum  est)  ab  origine 
mundi.  Hac  regnum  nominat,  hac  cum  diabolo  damnationem. 
Nullus  relictus  est  medius  locus,  ubi  ponere  queas  infantes. 
De  vivis  et  mortuis  judicabitur :  alii  erunt  ad  dextram,  alii  ad 
sinistram :  non  novi  aliud,  Qui  inducis  medium,  recede 
de  medio,  sed  noli  in  sinistram.  Si  ergo  dextra  erit,  et 
sinistra,  et  nullum  medium  locum  in  Evangelio  novimus ;  ecce 
in  dextra  regnum  ccelorum  est,  Percipite,  inquit,  regnum. 

D  n  3 


40(>  NOTE    XIX. 

Qui  ibi  non  est  in  sinistra  est.  Quid  erit  in  sinistra  ?  Ite  in 
ignem  ceternum.  In  dextra  ad  regnum,  utique  seternum  ;  in 
sinistra  in  ignem  sternum.  Qui  non  in  dextra,  procul  dubio 
in  sinistra:  ergo  qui  non  in  regno,  procul  dubio  in  ignc 
ajterno.  Certe  habere  potest  vitam  a3ternam  qui  non  bapti- 
zatur  ?  Non  est  in  dextra,  id  est,  non  erit  in  regno.  Vitam 
seternam  computas  ignem  sempiternum  ?  Et  de  ipsa  vita 
eeterna  audi  expressius,  quia  nihil  aliud  est  regnum  quam  vita 
aeterna.  Prius  regnum  nominavit,  sed  in  dextris;  ignem 
seternum  in  sinistris.  Extrema  autem  sententia,  ut  docerct 
quid  sit  regnum,  et  quid  sit  ignis  sempiternus —  Tune,  inquit, 
abibunt  isti  in  ambustionem  ceternam  ;  justi  autem  in  vitam 
ceternam. 

"  Ecce  exposuit  tibi  quid  sit  regnum,  et  quid  sit  ignis  icter- 
nus ;  ut  quando  confitearis  parvulum  non  futurum  in  regno, 
fatearis  futurum  in  igne  aeterno." — Serm.  294.  c.  iii. 


NOTE  XIX.  p.  139. 

HOOKER  states  S.  Augustine's  doctrine  of  predestination  as 
the  doctrine  "  that  the  whole  body  of  mankind  in  the  view 
of  God's  eternal  knowledge  lay  universally  polluted  with 
sin,  worthy  of  condemnation  and  death ;  that  over  the  mass 
of  corruption  there  passed  two  acts  of  the  will  of  God,  an 
act  of  favour,  liberality,  and  grace,  choosing  part  to  be  made 
partakers  of  everlasting  glory;  and  an  act  of  justice,  forsak- 
ing the  rest  and  adjudging  them  to  endless  perdition ;  these 
vessels  of  wrath,  those  of  mercy ;  which  mercy  is  to  God's 
elect  so  peculiar,  that  to  them  and  none  else  (for  their  num- 
ber is  definitely  known,  and  can  neither  be  increased  nor 
diminished),  to  them  it  allotteth  immortality  and  all  things 
thereunto  appertaining ;  them  it  predestinateth,  it  calleth, 
justifieth,  glorifieth  them ;  it  poureth  voluntarily  that  spirit 
into  their  hearts,  which  spirit  so  given  is  the  root  of  their 


NOTE   XIX.  407 

very  first  desires  and  motions  tending  to  immortality ;  as  for 
others  on  whom  such  grace  is  not  bestowed,  there  is  justly 
assigned,  and  immutably  to  every  of  them,  the  lot  of  eternal 
condemnation."  —  Appendix  to  bk.  v.  Keble's  edition, 
p.  730. 

Another  statement,  a  little  further  on,  not  so  much  of 
Augustine's  doctrine  as  professing  to  be  founded  upon  it,  is 
somewhat  less  rigid  :  "  To  proceed,  we  have  seen  the  general 
inclination  of  God  towards  all  men's  everlasting  happiness, 
notwithstanding  sin  ;  we  have  seen  that  the  natural  love  of 
God  towards  mankind  was  the  cause  of  appointing  or  pre« 
destinatino;  Christ  to  suffer  for  the  si  us  of  the  whole  world — 

O 

we  have  seen  that  our  Lord,  who  made  Himself  a  sacrifice 
for  our  sins,  did  it  in  the  bowels  of  a  merciful  desire  that  no 
man  might  perish  —  we  have  seen  that  God,  nevertheless, 
hath  found  most  just  occasion  to  decree  the  death  and  con- 
demnation of  some  —  we  have  seen  that  the  whole  cause  why 
such  are  excluded  from  life  resteth  altogether  in  themselves^ — 
we  have  seen  that  the  natural  will  of  God  being  incline'.! 
toward  all  men's  salvation,  and  His  occasioned  will  having  set 
down  the  death  but  of  some  in  such  condemnation,  as  hath 
been  shewed,  it  must  needs  follow  that  of  the  rest  there  is  a 
determinate  ordinance  proceeding  from  the  good  pleasure  of 
God,  whereby  they  are,  and  have  been  before  all  worlds, 
predestinated  heirs  of  eternal  bliss  —  we  have  seen  that  in 
Christ,  the  Prince  of  God's  elect,  all  worthiness  was  foreseen  ; 
that  in  the  elect  angels  there  was  not  foreseen  any  matter  for 
just  indignation  and  wrath  to  work  upon ;  that  in  all  other 
God  foresaw  iniquity,  for  which  an  irrevocable  sentence  of 
death  and  condemnation  might  most  justly  have  passed  over 
all ;  for  it  can  never  be  too  often  inculcated  that  touching  the 
very  decree  of  endless  destruction  and  death,  God  is  the  Judge 
from  whom  it  cometh,  but  man  the  cause  from  which  it 
grew.  Salvation  contrariwise,  and  life  proceedeth  only  both 
from  God  and  of  God.  We  are  receivers  through  grace  and 
mercy,  authors  through  merit  and  desert  we  are  not,  of  our 
own  salvation.  In  the  children  of  perdition  we  must  always 
remember  that  of  the  Prophet,  '  Thy  destruction,  O  Israel, 

i>  o  4 


08  NOTE   XIX. 

is  of  thyself ;'  lest  we  teach  men  blasphemously  to  cast  the 
blame  of  all  their  misery  upon  God.  Again,  lest  we  take  to 
ourselves  the  glory  of  that  happiness,  which,  if  He  did  not 
freely  and  voluntarily  bestow,  we  should  never  be  made 
partakers  thereof,  it  must  ever,  in  the  election  of  saints,  be 
remembered,  that  to  choose  is  an  act  of  God's  good  pleasure, 
which  presupposeth  in  us  sufficient  cause  to  avert,  but  none 
to  deserve  it.  For  this  cause,  whereas  S.  Augustine  had 
some  time  been  of  opinion  that  God  chose  Jacob  and  hated 
Esau,  the  one  in  regard  of  belief,  the  other  of  infidelity, 
which  was  foreseen,  his  mind  he  afterwards  delivered  thus: 
'Jacob  I  have  loved;  behold  what  God  doth  freely  bestow. 
/  have  hated  Esau ;  behold  what  man  doth  justly  deserve." — 
p.  737. 

There  is  some  departure  here  from  the  rigour  of  the  real 
Augustinian  language,  though  no  positive  inconsistency 
with  the  Augustinian  doctrine.  The  modification  is  given 
by  suppression  ;  "  We  have  seen,"  he  says,  "  that  the  whole 
cause  why  such  are  excluded  from  life  resteth  altogether 
in  themselves"  S.  Augustine  would  say  this,  but  he 
would  explain  at  the  same  time  that  this  cause  in  man 
himself  was  not  foreseen  personal  sin,  but  original  sin. 
Hooker  suppresses  this  interpretation,  and  leaves  men's 
actual  foreseen  sins  as  the  cause,  according  to  the  natural 
meaning  of  his  phrase,  of  their  exclusion  from  the  decree  of 
predestination  to  life. 

A  third  statement  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination  reverts 
to  a  stricter  line.  "It  followeth,  therefore, —  1.  That  God 
hath  predestinated  certain  men,  not  all  men :  2.  That  the 
cause  moving  Him  hereunto  was  not  the  foresight  of  any 
virtue  in  us  at  all :  3.  That  to  Him  the  number  of  His  elect 
is  definitely  known :  4.  That  it  cannot  be  but  their  sins 
must  condemn  them  to  whom  the  purpose  of  His  saving 
mercy  doth  not  extend :  5.  That  to  God's  foreknown  elect 
final  continuance  in  grace  is  given :  6.  That  inward  grace 
whereby  to  be  saved  is  deservedly  not  given  unto  all  men: 
7.  That  no  man  cometh  unto  Christ,  whom  God  by  the  in- 
ward grace  of  the  Spirit  draweth  not :  8.  And  that  it  is  not 
in  every  one,  no,  not  in  any  man's  mere  ability,  freedom,  and 


NOTE    XX.  409 

power,  to  be  saved;  no  man's  salvation  being  possible  without 
grace.  Howbeit,  God  is  no  favourer  of  sloth,  and  therefore 
there  can  be  no  such  absolute  decree  touching  man's  salva- 
tion, as  on  our  part  includeth  no  necessity  of  care  and  tra- 
vail, but  shall  certainly  take  effect,  whether  we  ourselves 
do  wake  or  sleep."  —  p.  752.  The  difference  between  this 
statement  and  the  Lambeth  Articles  consists  in  an  omis- 
sion and  insertion,  softening  the  general  effect  of  the  lan- 
guage, while  the  substantial  ground  is  the  same.  Thus  the 
first  Lambeth  Article  mentions  reprobation,  which  the  first 
article  of  this  statement  does  not;  but  reprobation  is  im- 
plied in  it.  Again,  the  7th  Lambeth  Article  says,  "  Gratia 
salutaris  non  tribuitur  universis  hominibus  qua  servari 
possint,  si  voluerint."  Hookerjnserts  after  "is  not  given," 
"  deservedly?  which  softens  the  effect,  though  the  desert  may 
be  admitted  by  the  most  rigid  predestinarian  in  the  shape 
of  original  sin.  There  is  a  real  difference  between  the  two 
statements  of  doctrine,  in  the  omission  in  Hooker's  of  the 
doctrine  of  assurance,  which  is  asserted  in  the  Lambeth 
document. 


NOTE  XX.  p.  251. 

IN  the  controversy  in  the  Gallican  Church,  on  the  subject  of 
predestination,  which  arose  out  of  the  doctrinal  statements  of 
Gotteschalcus ;  which  was  conducted  by  Hinckmar,  archbishop 
of  Rheirns,  on  the  one  side,  and  Remigius,  archbishop  of  Lyons, 
on  the  other,  and  which  produced  the  Councils  of  Quiercy 
and  Valence ;  neither  side  appears  to  have  sifted  the  question 
to  its  foundation,  or  to  have  understood  its  really  turning 
points;  and  there  is,  accordingly,  a  good  deal  of  arbitrary 
adoption  and  arbitrary  rejection  of  language  on  both  sides ; 
a  good  deal  of  reliance  on  distinctions  without  a  difference, 
that  is  to  say,  on  words.  The  doctrinal  statement  of  Gottes- 
chalcus embraces  the  following  five  points. —  Usher's  Gottes- 
chalci  Historia,  p.  27. 


410  NOTE    XX. 

"  1 .  Ante  omnia  secula,  et  antequam  quicquam  faceret,  a 
principio  Deus  quos  voluit  prasdestinavit  ad  regnum,  et  quos 
voluit  praedestinavit  ad  interitum. 

"  2.  Qui  praedestinati  sunt  ad  interitum  salvari  non  possunt, 
et  qui  pra3destinati  sunt  ad  regnura  perire  non  possunt. 

((  3.  Deus  non  vult  omnes  homines  salvos  fieri,  sed  eos  tan- 
turn  qui  salvantur  :  et  quod  dicit  Apostolus  '  Qui  vult  omnes 
homines  salvos  fieri,'  illos  dicit  omnes  qui  tantummodo  sal- 
vantur. 

"  4.  Christus  non  venit  ut  omnes  salvaret ;  nee  passus  est 
pro  omnibus,  nisi  solummodo  pro  his  qui  passionis  ejus  sal- 
vantur mysterio. 

<s  5.  Postquam  primus  homo  libero  arbitrio  cecidit,  nemo 
nostrum  ad  bene  agendum,  sed  tantummodo  ad  male  agendum, 
libero  potest  uti  arbitrio." 

This  statement  of  doctrine  is  substantially  Augustinian, 
and  nothing  more  ;  and  Remigius  approves  of  it  as  a  whole, 
making  an  exception  against  the  5th  proposition  ;  respecting 
the  meaning  of  which  he  must  have  been  under  some  mistake, 
for  the  language  expresses  no  more  than  \vhat  is  necessarily 
involved  in  the  doctrine  of  original  sin.  With  this  excep- 
tion, he  maintains  this  doctrinal  statement  to  be  supported, 
"  uno  sensu  uno  ore,"  by  the  fathers  and  the  Church,  and 
appeals  to  the  undisputed  authority  of  Augustine  in  their 
favour — "  Beatissimi  patris  Augustini  ab  omni  semper  ecclesia 
venerabiliter  recepti  et  usque  in  finem  scculi  recipiendi"  ex- 
plaining the  text  "Qui  vult  omnes  homines  salvos  fieri," 
apparently  contradicted  in  the  3rd  proposition,  according  to 
Augustine's  interpretation :,  (1.)  "  Ut  omnes  homines  omnia 
hominum  genera  accipiamus : "  (2.)  "  non  quod  omnes  salven- 
tur,  sed  quod  nemo  nisi  miserationis  ejus  voluntate  salve- 
tur."  On  the  4th  he  says :  "  Si  inveniantur  aliqui  patrum 
qui  etiam  pro  impiis  in  sua  impietate  permansuris  Domi- 
num  crucifixum  dicant ;"  if  they  can  prove  it  out  of  Scripture 
well,  if  not,  "  quis  non  videat  potiorem  illam  esse  auctorita- 
tem,  quae  et  tarn  evidenti  ratione  et  tarn  multiplici  Scriptu- 
rarum  attestatione  firmatur  ?  ...  Si  autem  placet,  propter 
pacem,  non  renuatur.  .  .  .  Nihil  tamen  definiatur." — p.  34. 

The  Council  of  Quiercy  (Concilium  Carisiacense)   sum- 


NOTE    XX.  411 

moned  by  Hinckmar,  condemned  the  opinions  of  Gotteschal- 
cus,  and  published  a  counter  statement  of  doctrine,  which 
placed  the  doctrine  of  predestination  upon  a  ground  of  fore- 
knowledge :  ' (  Secundum  pr&scientiam  suam  quos  per  gratiam 
predestinavit  ad  vitam  elegit  ex  massa  perditionis.  Caeteros 
autem  quos  justitiae  judicio  in  massa  perditionis  reliquit, 
perituros  praescivit,  sed  non  ut  perirent  praedestinavit." — 
p.  67.  There  is  nothing  in  the  language  of  this  proposition 
to  which  the  most  rigid  predestinarian  might  not  subscribe ; 
but  Remigius  interprets  the  prcescienfia  as  the  foreknowledge 
of  the  individual's  good  life,  and  as  implying  the  resting  of 
the  doctrine  of  predestination  on  that  ground  :  "  Quod  mani- 
feste  contrarium  est  Catholics  fidei.  Quia  Omnipotens  Deus 
in  electione  eorum  quos  prsedestinavit,  et  vocavit  ad  vitam 
rcternam,  non  eorum  merita  praescivit."  On  the  subject  of 
the  Divine  will  to  save  all  mankind  the  Council  decreed  : 
'*  Deus  omnipotens  omnes  homines  sine  exceptione  vult  salvos 
fieri,  licet  non  omnes  salventur,"  to  which  proposition  Remi- 
gius opposes  the  fact  of  the  heathen  world,  the  damnation  of 
which  he  considers  to  be  a  point  which  has  been  decided  by 
the  Church.  The  same  question  was  taken  up  by  the 
Council  in  another  form ;  viz.  whether  Christ  did  or  did  not 
suffer  for  all  men,  which  it  decided  in  the  affirmative. 
"  Christus  Jesus  Dominus  noster,  sicut  nullus  homo  est  fuit  vel 
erit  cujus  natura  in  illo  assumpta  non  fuerit,  ita  nullus  est  fuit 
vel  erat  homo  pro  quo  passus  non  fuerit ;  licet  non  omnes  pas- 
sionis  ejus  mysterio  redimantur."  On  this  argument  Reini- 
gius  remarks  :  "  Quod  dicitur  quod  nullus  homo  est  fuit  vel 
erit  cujus  natura  in  Christo  assumpta  non  fuerit.  .  .  .  Sus- 
ceptio  ilia  naturae  humanae  in  Christo  non  fuit  ex  necessitate 
originis,  sed  ex  potestate  et  gratia  et  misericordia  et  digna- 
tione  suscipientis.  Quia  ergo  ista  tarn  divina  et  singularis 
generatio  hominis  Christi  non  aliqua  naturali  necessitate,  sed 
sola  ejus  potestate  et  gratia  et  misericordia  facta  est;  sic  per 
omnes  generationes  caro  ejus  descendit  :  sic  ex  eis  veraciter 
natus  verus  homo  factus  est  ut  quod  ei  placuit  miserendo,  et 
sanando,  et  redimendo  inde  assumeret,  quod  autem  non  placuit 
reprobaret."  —  ip.  79.  The  argument  is,  that  our  Lord's  as- 
sumption of  human  nature  being  itself  a  condescension,  and 


412  NOTE    XX. 

special  dispensation,  has  a  particular  limited  scope,  according 
to  the  Divine  pleasure,  and  only  brings  Him,  as  possessing 
this  nature,  into  communion  with  a  certain  portion  of  those 
whom  this  nature  includes,  and  is  only  beneficial  to  this 
portion. 

The  controversy,  which  is  thus  substantially  between  the 
Augustinian  and  the  Semi-Pelagian  doctrines,  exhibits,  how- 
ever, much  confusion,  and  is  encumbered  by  false  distinctions. 
A  great  deal  is  made  of  the  question  of  the  duplex  prcedesti- 
natio.  Hinckmar  admitting  a  predestination  to  life  eternal, 
refuses  to  admit  a  predestination  to  punishment,  and  insists 
on  the  distinction  between  leaving  men  in  their  sinful  state,  of 
which  punishment  will  be  the  consequence,  and  ordaining 
men  to  such  punishment.  "  Quosdam  autem,  sicut  praesci- 
vit,  non  ad  mortem  neque  ad  ignem  praedestinavit,  sed  in 
massa  peccati  et  perditionis  juste  deseruit,  a  qua  eos  praedes- 
tinatione  sua  (z.  e.  gratis  prasparatione)  occulto  sed  non  in- 
justo  judicio  nequaquarn  eripuit." — p.  93.  But  the  most 
rigid  predestinarian  would  not  object  to  this  statement. 
There  is  no  real  distinction  between  abandoning  men  to  a 
certain  state,  of  which  punishment  will  be  the  consequence, 
and  ordaining  them  to  that  punishment.  The  only  distinc- 
tion which  would  make  a  difference,  respects  the  nature  of 
this  sinful  state,  to  which  men  are  abandoned,  whether  it  is 
original  sin  or  their  own  personal  perseverance  in  sin.  The 
abandonment  of  a  certain  portion  of  mankind  to  the  state 
of  sin  in  which  they  are  born,  is  predestinarian  reprobation, 
whether  we  express  it  as  abandonment  to  sin,  or  as  ordaining 
to  punishment.  Remigius  exposes  the  irrelevancy  of  this 
distinction:  "Mirum  valde  est  quomodo  negare  contendunt 
eum  aeternam  ipsorum  damnationem  praedestinasse,  quos  jam 
ab  ipso  mundi  exordio,  cum  primus  homo  peccavit,  et  omne 
humanum  genus  ex  se  propagandum  unam  massam  damna- 
tionis  et  perditionis  fecit,  manifesto  dicant  in  eadem  massa 
damnationis  et  perditionis  justo  Dei  judicio  deputatos  et  de- 
relictos.  Quid  est  enim  massa  damnationis  et  perditionis  ab 
initio  mundi  divino  judicio  efFecta,  nisi  eodem  divino  judicio 
aeternae  damnationiet  perditioni  destinata  et  tradita?" — p.  93. 

Hinckmar  insists  again  on  the  Augustinian  definition  of 


NOTE   XXI.  413 

predestination  as  gratice  prceparatio  (p.  94.),  as  favouring 
his  denial  of  any  prcedestinatio  damnationis  ;  to  which  Remi- 
gius  replies,  that  a  predestination  to  life  did  not  exclude 
the  predestination  to  punishment.  It  is  obvious  that  the 
whole  of  this  discussion  is  verbal,  and  is  not  concerned  with 
the  real  grounds  and  substance  of  the  controversy. 


NOTE  XXL  p.  285. 

I  SEE  no  substantial  difference  between  the  Augustinian  and 
Thomist,  and  the  Calvinist  doctrine  of  predestination.  S. 
Augustine  and  Calvin  alike  hold  an  eternal  Divine  decree, 
which,  antecedently  to  all  action,  separates  one  portion  of 
mankind  from  another,  and  ordains  one  to  everlasting  life 
and  the  other  to  everlasting  punishment.  That  is  the  funda- 
mental statement  of  both ;  and  it  is  evident,  that  while  this 
fundamental  statement  is  the  same,  there  can  be  no  sub- 
stantial difference  in  the  two  doctrines.  This  statement  is 
the  sum  and  substance  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination  :  and 
therefore  if  Augustine  and  Calvin  agree  in  this  statement,  it 
may  be  pronounced  in  limine  idle  to  talk  of  any  real  dif- 
ference between  their  respective  doctrines  on  this  subject. 
Let  persons  only  consider  what  this  statement  is,  and  what 
it  necessarily  involves,  and  they  must  see  it  is  impossible  that 
there  can  be  any  real  distinction  of  doctrine  on  the  particular 
subject  of  predestination,  after  this  statement  has  been  agreed 
in  by  the  two.  Those  who  suppose  that  S.  Augustine 
differs  from  Calvin  in  his  doctrine  of  predestination,  do  not 
really  know  the  doctrine  which  S.  Augustine  held  on  the 
subject,  and  suppose  it  to  be  different  from  what  it  was. 
They  suppose  it  to  be  a  qualified  doctrine  of  predestination 
to  privileges  and  means  of  grace ;  or  they  have  some  general 
idea  that  S.  Augustine  did  not  hold  such  a  doctrine  as  Cal- 
vin held,  —  an  assumption  which  settles  to  begin  with  the 


414  NOTE   XXI. 

question  for  them.  But  if  Augustine's  doctrine  was  the  one 
which  has  been  here  stated  to  be  his,  and  if  it  was  expressed 
in  the  above  fundamental  statement,  it  must  be  seen  imme- 
diately that  it  is  the  same  as  Calvin's  doctrine. 

And  the  identity  of  the  two  "doctrines  thus  apparent  at 
first  sight,  and  from  the  fundamental  statement  by  which 
they  are  expressed,  will  appear  further  from  the  cautions 
and  checks  by  which  each  guards'  the  doctrine.  We  may 
be  referred  to  various  cautions  and  checks  which  S.  Au- 
gustine and  his  followers  in  the  schools  appended  to  the 
doctrine  of  predestination;  from  which  it  will  be  argued 
that  the  doctrine  was  not  the  same  as  the  Calvinistic  one. 
But  it  will  be  found  on  examination  that  Calvin  has  just  the 
same  cautions  and  checks. 

The  checks  and  cautions,  which  S.  Augustine  and  his  fol- 
lowers in  the  schools  appended  to  their  doctrine  of  predesti- 
nation, were  substantially  these  t\vo:  that  God  was  not  the 
author  of  evil ;  and  that  man  had  ivill,  and  was,  as  having 
a  will,  responsible  for  his  own  sins.  The  doctrine  of  pre- 
destination was  relieved  from  two  consequences  which  ap- 
peared to  follow  from  it.  If  God  is  the  sole  author  and 
cause  of  our  goodness,  how  is  He  not  the  author  and  cause 
of  our  sin  too?  If  we  are  bound  to  refer  the  one  to  Him, 
why  not  the  other  ?  The  doctrine  thus  led  to  the  consequence 
that  God  was  the  author  of  evil.  This  consequence,  then, 
was  cut  off  by  a  formal  check,  accompanied  with  more  or  less 
of  argument,  that  God  was  not  the  author  of  evil.  In  the 
same  way  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  maintaining  sin  as 
necessary,  led  to  the  result  that  man  was  not  responsible  for 
his  sins.  This  consequence  then  was  cut  off,  as  the  former 
was,  by  a  formal  check,  also  accompanied  by  more  or  less  of 
argument,  —  that  man  had  a  will,  that  he  sinned  with  this 
will  or  willingly,  and  that  sinning  willingly  he  was  re- 
sponsible for  his  sins. 

But  this  whole  check  to  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  viz. 
that  man  is  responsible  for  his  own  sins,  and  not  God,  is  ap- 
pended to  that  doctrine  by  Calvin  ju,1 1  as  much  as  it  is  by 
Augustine.  Indeed,  no  one  who  professed  to  be  a  Christian 
could  teach  the  doctrine  without  such  a  check.  No  Christian 


NOTE   XXT.  415 

of  any  school  could  make  God  the  author  of  evil,  or  say  that 
sin  was  not  blameworthy. 

First,  Calvin  protests  generally  against  fatalism;  i.  e.  any 
doctrine  that  denies  contingency,  and  asserts  all  events  to  take 
place  according  to  a  certain  fixed  and  inevitable  order,  which 
could  not  have  been  otherwise :   "  Vetus  ista  calumnia  fuir, 
qua  se  Augustinus  injuste  fuisse  gravatum  alicubi  conqueri- 
tur :  mine  obsoletam  esse  decebat.     Certe  hominibus  probis 
et   ingenuis,   si   modo   iidem   docti   sint,  valde  indigna  est» 
Qualis  fuerit  Stoicorum  imaginatio,  notum  est.     Fatum  suum 
texebant  ex   Gordiano  causarum  complexu:    in   quern  cuin 
Deum  ipsum  involuerant,  fabricabant  aureas  catenas,  ut  est 
in  fabulis,  quibus  Deum  vincirent,  ut   subjectus    esset   in- 
ferioribus  causis.     Stoicos  hodie  imitantur  astrologi,  quibus 
fatalis  ex  stellarum  positu  dependet  rerum  necessitas.     Valeant 
igitur  cum  suo  fato  Stoici :  nobis  libera  Dei  voluntas  omnium 
sit    moderatrix.       Sed    c anting entiam    tolli    ex    mundo   valde 
absurdum   est.      Omitto    qua3   in    Scholis    usitata3  sunt   dis- 
tinctiones.     Quod  afferam  simplex,  meo  judicio,  et  minime 
coactum  erit,  deinde  ad  vitaj  usum  accomodatum.     Sic  evenire 
necesse  est  quod  statuit  Deus,  ut  tamen  neque  prsecise  neque 
suapte  natura  necessarium  sit.     Exemplum  in  Christi  ossibus 
fumiliare  habeo.     Christum   corpus    habuisse  prorsus  nostro 
simile  Scriptura  testatur.     Quare  fragilia  illi  ossa  fuisse  fateri 
nemo  sanus  dubitabit.     Sed  alia  mihi  videtur   ac  separata 
quaastio,    an  ullum   os    ejus  frangi  potuerit.     Nam   Integra 
omnia  et  illaesa  manere,  quia  fixo  Dei  decreto  ita  statutum 
erat,  necessario  oportuit.     Nee  vero  quod  a  receptis  loquendi 
formis  de  necessitate  secundum  quid  et  absoluta,  item  con- 
sequentis  et  consequential  abhorream,  ita  loquor  ;  sed  ne  qua; 
lectoris  argutia  impediat,  quin  agnoscat  vel  rudissimus  quis- 
que  verum  esse  quod  dico.  .  .  .  Ac  memoria  tenendum  est, 
quod  ante  posui,  ubi  Deus  per  mcdias  et  inferiores  causas 
virtutem  suam    exerit,  non  esse   ab  illis  separandam.     Te- 
mulenta  est  ista  cogitatio  :  decrevit  Deus  quid  futurum  sit ; 
ergo  curam  et  studium  nostrum  interponere  supervacuum  est. 
Atqui,  cum  nobis  quid  agendum  sit,  praescribat,  et  virtutis 
sure  organa  nos  esse  velit ;  fas  nobis  est  ne  putemus  separare 
quae  ille  conjunxit.  .  .  .  Ergo  quantum  ad  futurum  tempus, 


641  NOTE   XXI. 

quia  nos  adhuc  rerura  eventus  latent,  perinde  ad  officium 
suura  intentus  esse  quisque  debet,  ac  si  nihil  in  utramvis 
partem  constitutum  foret.  Yel  lit  magis  proprie  loquar, 
talem  in  omnibus  quae  ex  Dei  mandate  aggreditur,  successum 
sperare  debet,  ut  in  rebus  sibi  incognitis  contingentiam  cum 
certa  Dei  providentia  conciliet.  .  .  .  Hac  voce  pius  vir  sedivinas 
providential  organum  constitui  agnoscet.  Hac  eadem  pro- 
missione  fretus,  alacriter  ad  opus  se  accinget,  quia  persuasus 
erit,  non  fortuitam  se  operam  in  acre  jacere.  .  .  .  Invoca- 
tionem  adeo  non  impedit,  utpotius  stabiliat.  .  .  .  Non  sequitur 
quin  rerum  adversarum  culpam  vel  ignavia  nostra,  vel  teme- 
ritas,  vel  incogitantia,  vel  aliud  vitium  merito  sustineat." — - 
De  Pr&destinatione,  vol.  x.  p.  725. 

Here  is  the  doctrine  of  the  schools  respecting  mediate  and 
secondary  causes ;  that  events  take  their  character  from  the 
causes  that  produce  them,  and  are  necessary  or  contingent, 
according  as  their  causes  are  the  one  or  the  other.  Calvin 
refers  in  the  passage  to  the  distinctions  of  the  schools,  with 
which  he  says  he  does  not  disagree ;  and  his  statement  is  only 
another  form  of  that  of  Aquinas:  "Deus  omnia  movet 
secundum  eorum  conditioner!!  ;  ita  quod  ex  causis  necessariis 
per  motionem  divinam  sequuntur  effectus  ex  necessitate,  ex 
causis  autem  contingentibus  sequuntur  effectus  contingentes.' 
Supra,  p.  254.  He  protests  against  indolence  or  careless 
ness  in  temporal  or  spiritual  matters,  as  a  wholly  illegitimate 
result  to  fasten  on  his  doctrine ;  and  says  that  people  must 
act  as  if  events  were  contingent,  and  not  suppose  that,  be- 
cause events  are  foreordained,  that  therefore  they  are  fore- 
ordained without  the  necessary  means  to  bring  them  about ; 
which  means  lie  in  our  own  conduct  and  course  of  action. 

Thus,  while  maintaining  the  Divine  infallible  decree  of 
predestination,  he  protests  against  men  making  that  decree 
their  starting  point,  and  putting  it  in  prior  order  to  action, 
in  their  own  ideas  and  thoughts  about  themselves :  "  Neque 
ego  sane  ad  arcanam  Dei  electionem  homines  ablego,  ut  inde 
salutem  hiantes  expectent :  sed  recte  ad  Christum  pergere 
jubeo,  in  quo  nobis  proposita  est  salus ;  quas  alioqui  in  Deo 
abscondita  lateret.  Nam  quisquis  planam  fidei  viam  non 
ingreditur,  illi  Dei  electio  nihil  quam  exitialis  erit  labaryn 


NOTE   XXI.  417 

thus.  .  .  .  Hinc  minime  faciendum  est  exordium,  quid  de  nobis 
ante  mundum  conditum  Deus  statuerit ;  sed  quid  de  paterno 
ejus  amore  nobis  in  Christo  sit  patefactum,  et  quotidie  per 
evangelium  Christus  ipse  prasdicet.  Nihil  altius  nobis  quas- 
rendum,  quam  ut  Dei  filii  simus. "  -  —  Yol.  x.  p.  708. 

After  this  protest  against  fatalism,  Calvin  proceeds  to 
acknowledge  a  true  will  in  man ;  that  he  acts  willingly  and 
without  constraint ;  and  that  consequently  the  blame  of  his 
sins  rests  entirely  upon  himself;  and  that  to  charge  God 
with  the  authorship  of  them  is  impiety  and  blasphemy.  The 
ground  he  takes  is  strictly  Augustinian :  "  Voluntas,  quia 
inseparabilis  est  ab  hominis  natura,  non  periit;  sed  pravis 
cupiditatibus  devincta  fuit,  ut  nihil  rectum  appetere  queat." — 
Instit.  1.  2.  c.  2.  s.  12.  "Non  voluntate  privatus  est  homo 
quum  in  hanc  necessitatem  se  addixit,  sed  voluntatis  sani- 
tate  Si  liberam  Dei  voluntatem  in  bene  agendo  non 

impedit,  quod  necesse  est  ilium  bene  agere :  si  diabolus,  qui 
nonnisi  male  agere  potest,  voluntate  tamen  peccat;  quis 
hominem  ideo  minus  voluntarie  peccare  dicet,  quod  sit  pec- 
candi  necessitati  obnoxius  ?  Hanc  necessitatem  quum  ubique 
prasdicet  Augustinus,  dum  etiam  invidiose  Coelestii  cavillo 
urgeretur,  ne  turn  quidem  asserere  dubitavit  — f  Per  liberta- 
tem  factum  est  ut  esset  homo  cum  peccato :  sed  jam  prenalis 
vitiositas  subsequuta  ex  libertate  fecit  necessitatem.'  Ac 
quoties  incidit  ejus  rei  mentio,  non  dubitat  in  hunc  modum 
loqui,  de  necessaria  peccati  servitute.  Haec  igitur  distinc- 
tionis  summa  observetur,  hominem,  ut  vitiatus  est  ex  lapsu, 
volentem  quidem  peccare,  non  invitum  nee  coactum :  affectione 
animi  propinquissima. . . .  Augustino  subscribens  Bernardus  ita 
scribit,  '  Solus  homo  inter  animalia  liber :  et  tamen,  inter- 
veniente  peccato,  patitur  quandam  vim  et  ipse,  sed  a  voluntate 
non  a  natura,  ut  ne  sic  quidem  ingenita  libertate  privetur. 
Quod  enim  voluntarium  etiam  liberum.'  Et  paulo  post  — 
( Ita  nescio  quo  pravo  et  miro  modo  ipsa  sibi  voluntas,  pec- 
cato quidem  in  deterius  mutata,  necessitatem  facit;  ut  nee 
necessitas  (cum  voluntaria  sit)  excusare  valeat  voluntatem, 
nee  voluntas  (quum  sit  illecta)  excludere  necessitatem.'  Est 
enim  necessitas  haec  quodammodo  voluntaria." — L.  2.  c.  3.  s.  5. 

E  E 


418  NOTE   XXI. 

"  Yoluntatem  dico  aboleri  non  quatenus  est  voluntas,  quia  in 
hominis  conversione  integrum  manet  quod  primae  est  naturas ; 
creari  etiam  novam  dico,  non  ut  voluntas  esse  incipiat,  sed 
ut  vertatur  ex  mala  in  bonam.  —  L.  2.  c.  3.  s.  6. 

Upon  the  ground,  then,  of  the  existence  of  this  true  will 
in  man,  he  lays  the  responsibility  of  sin  entirely  upon  man 
himself:  "  Nego  peccatum  ideo  minus  debere  imputari,  quod 
necessarium  est." — Instit.  1.  2.  c.  4.  s.  5.  "  Eant  nunc  qui 
Deum  suis  vitiis  inscribere  audent,  quia  dicimus  naturaliter 
vitiosos  esse  homines.  ...  A  carnis  nostrae  culpa  non  a  Deo 
nostra  perditio  est." — L.  2.  c.  1.  s.  10.  "  Respondeant,  pos- 
sintne  inficiari  causam  contumacia3  pravam  suam  voluntatem 
fuisse.  Si  mali  fontem  intra  se  reperiant,  quid  vestigandis 
extraneis  causis  inhiant,  ne  sibi  ipsi  fuisse  exitii  authores 
videantur." —  L.  2.  c.  5.  s.  11.  "Non  extrinseco  impulsu, 
sed  spontaneo  cordis  affectu,  scientes  ac  volentes  peccarunt." 
—  De  Freed,  vol.  x.  p.  709.  "  Ad  reatum  satis  superque 
voluntaries  trangressio  sufficit.  Neque  enim  propria  genui- 
naque  peccati  causa  est  arcanum  Dei  consilitim,  sed  aperta 

hominis  voluntas Intus  mali  sui  causam  quum  inve- 

niat  homo,  quid  circuire  prodest,  ut  earn  in  coalo  quaerat  ? 
Palam  in  eo  apparet  culpa  quod  peccare  voluerit.  Cur  in 
coeli  adyta  perrumpens  in  labarynthum  se  demergit  ?  Quan- 
quam  ut  per  immensas  ambages  vagando,  deludere  se  homines 
conentur,  nunquam  ita  se  obstupef'acient,  quin  sensum  peccati 
in  cordibus  suis  insculptum  retineant.  Hominem  igitur,  quern 
ipsius  sui  conscientia  damnat,  frustra  absolvere  tendit  impie- 
tas."  —  De  Freed,  vol.  x.  p.  7 1 1 .  "  Neque  in  Deum  transferi- 
mus  indurationis  causam  acsi  non  sponte  propriaque  malitia 
seipsos  ad  pervicaciam  acuerent." — p.  727.  "  Quum  perditis 
exitium  denuntiat  Scriptura,  causam  in  aeternum  Dei  consiliuni 
minime  rejicit,  vel  transfer! ;  sed  residcre  in  ipsis  testatur. 
Nos  vero  non  ideo  reprobos  tradimus  destitui  Dei  Spiritu, 
ut  scelerum  suorum  culpam  in  Deum  imputent.  Quicquid 
peccant  homines  sibi  imputent  Quod  si  quis  subterfugiat, 
conscientias  vinculis  fortius  constringi  dico,  quam  ut  se  a 
justa  danmatione  expediat.  ...  Si  quis  obstrepat,  prompta 
eet  exceptio,  Perditio  tua  ex  te  Israel.  .  .  .  Non  audiendi 
sunt  qui  procul  remotas  causas  e  nubibus  accersunt,  ut  culpa3 


NOTE    XXI.  419 

suae  notitiam,  quae  et  eorum  cordibus  penitus  insidet,  neque 
occulta  latere  potest,  utcunque  obscurent." — p.  721. 

The  cautions  and  checks,  then,  which  Calvin  appends  to 
the  doctrine  of  predestination  are  substantially  the  same  with 
those  we  find  appended  to  the  doctrine  in  S.  Augustine  and 
the  Augustinian  schoolmen.  Predestination,  according  to 
Calvin,  is  no  excuse  for  spiritual  indolence  or  carelessness ; 
it  does  not  detract  at  all  from  man's  responsibility,  who  is  as 
much  to  blame  for  his  sins  upon  this  doctrine  as  upon  the 
contrary  one ;  and  therefore  whether  we  look  to  the  funda- 
mental statement  of  the  doctrine,  or  to  the  checks  and  cau- 
tions with  which  it  is  surrounded,  the  doctrine  of  Calvin  on 
this  subject  is  seen  to  be  the  same  as  that  of  S.  Augustine. 

It  is  true  Calvin  condemns  the  scholastic  treatment  of  this 
question,  and  after  S.  Augustine  nobody,  except  perhaps  S. 
Bernard,  seems  to  satisfy  him.  But  this  complaint  is  quali- 
fied. He  acknowledges,  in  the  first  place,  that  however  their 
own  interpretations  of  such  doctrines  may  have  fallen  short, 
the  fundamental  doctrines  of  the  schools  were  Augustinian 
and  orthodox  on  this  question :  "  Qui  postea  secuti  sunt, 
alii  post  alios  in  deterius  continuo  delapsi  sunt ;  donee  eo 
ventum  est  ut  vulgo  putaretur  homo  sensuali  tandein 
parte  corruptus Interea  volitavit  illud  in  ore  om- 
nium, naturalia  dona  in  homine  corrupta  esse,  supernatu- 
ralia  vero  dblata.  Sed  quorsum  tenderet,  vix  centesimus 
quisque  leviter  gustavit.  Ego  certe  si  dilucide  tradere 
velim  qualis  sit  naturae  corruptela,  his  verbis  facile  sim  con- 
tentus"  —  Instit.  1.  2.  c.  2.  s.  4.  He  admits  here  a  certain 
foundation  in  the  teaching  of  the  schools  which  was  orthodox, 
though  it  was  overlaid  with  weak  or  injurious  commentary. 
In  the  next  place  he  makes  a  distinction  amongst  schoolmen ; 
and  while  he  complains  of  the  refinements  of  Lombard  and 
Aquinas,  regards  them  as  in  the  main  orthodox :  "  Longiore 
intervallo  a  recentioribus  sophistis  differo"  —  Inst.  1.  2.  c.  2. 
s.  6.  The  older  commentators  he  considers  to  have  main- 
tained, though  with  too  little  boldness  and  openness,  and 
with  too  great  an  appearance  of  compromise,  the  Augustinian 
ground.  Thus  he  complains  of  Lombard's  use  of  the  term 
freewill:  "Ac  principalem  quidem  causam  in  gratia  esse 


420  NOTE   XXI. 

non  negant :  sed  eo  tamen  contendunt  non  excludi  liberum 
arbitrium,  per  quod  sit  omne  meritura.  Neque  id  tradunt 
posteriores  modo  sophistae,  sed  eorurn  Pythagoras  Lombardus  ; 
quern,  si  cum  istis  compares,  sanum  et  sobrium  esse  dicas. 
Mirae  profecto  caecitatis  fuit,  quum  Augustinum  toties  in  ore 
haberet,  non  vidisse  quanta  solicitudine  vir  ille  caverit  ne 
ulla  ex  bonis  operibus  gloriae  particula  in  hominem  derivare- 
tur." —  Instit.  1.  3.  c.  15.  s.  7.  "  Magister  sententiarum  du- 
plicem  gratiam  necessarian!  esse  nobis  docet,  quo  reddamur  ad 
opus  bonum  idonei.  Alteram  vocat  Operantem,  qua  fit  ut 
efficaciter  velimus  bonum ;  Cooperantem  alteram  quae  bonam 
voluntatem  sequitur  adjuvando.  In  qua  partitione  hoc  mihi 
displicet,  quod  dum  Gratiae  Dei  tribuit  efficacem  boni  appeti- 
tum,  innuit  hominem  jam  suapte  natura  bonum  quodam- 
modo  licet  inefficaciter  appetere.  ...  In  secundo  membro  am- 
biguitas  me  offendit,  quae  perversam  genuit  interpretationem. 
Ideo  enim  putarunt  nos  secundae  Dei  gratias  cooperari,  quod 
nostri  juris  sit  primam  gratiam  vel  respuendo  irritam  facere, 
Tel  obedienter  sequendo  confirmare.  .  .  .  Hcec  duo  notare 
obiter  libuit,  ut  videas  jam  lector,  quantum  a  sanioribus  scho- 

lasticis  dissentiam Utcunque,  ex  hac  tamen  partitione 

intelligimus  qua  ratione  liberum  dederint  arbitrium  homini. 
Pronuntiat  enim  tandem  Lombardus,  non  liberi  arbitrii  ideo  nos 
esse,  quod  ad  bonum  vel  ad  malum  vel  agendum  vel  cogitan- 
dum  perceque  polleamus,  sed  duntaxat  quod  coactione  soluti 
sumus.  .  .  .  Optirne  id  quidem,  sed  quorsum  attinebat,  rem 

lantulam   adeo  superbo   titulo  insignire Equidem 

Xo7o fjua^ias  abominor,  quibus  frustra  ecclesia  fatigatur ;  sed 
religiose  censeo  cavendas  eas  voces  quae  absurdum  aliquid 
sonant,  praesertim  ubi  perniciose  erratur.  Quotus  enim  quasso 
quisque  est,  qui,  dum  assignari  homini  liberum  arbitrium 
audit,  non  statim  concipit  ilium  esse  et  mentis  sua3  et  volun- 
tatis  dominum,  qui  flectere  se  in  utramvis  partem  a  seipso 
possit?  Atqui  (dicet  quispiam)  sublatum  erit  hujusmodi 
^periculum,  si  de  significatione  diligenter  plebs  admoneatur. 
Imo  vero  cum  in  falsitatem  ultro  humanum  ingenium  pro- 
pendeat,  citius  errorem  ex  verbulo  uno  hauriet,  quam  verita- 
tem  ex  prolixa  oratione." — Instit.  1.  2.  c.  2.  ss.  6,  7. 

It  is  evident  that  Calvin's  quarrel  with  Lombard  here  is 
about  the  use  of  a  word,  and  not  about  a  substantial  point  of 


NOTE    XXI.  421 

doctrine.  In  substantial  doctrine  he  considers  they  both 
agree,  though  he  thinks  Lombard's  distinction  of  operative 
and  co-operative  grace  so  worded  as  to  tend  to  mislead,  and 
though  he  objects  to  the  use  of  the  word  freewill  altogether, 
which  he  thinks  will  always  be  practically  understood  by  the 
mass  of  men  in  the  sense  of  a  self-determining  will.  He 
would  not  object  to  the  word  if  Lombard's  sense  could  be 
fastened  upon  it ;  but  he  differs  from  him  as  to  the  expediency 
of  using  a  term  on  which  it  will  be  so  difficult  to  fasten  this 
meaning;  and  which  will  always  more  readily  suggest  another 
and  an  erroneous  one.  His  disagreement  with  Lombard  is 
thus  of  the  same  kind  with  the  disagreement  noticed  above, 
p.  285.,  with  Aquinas,  which  was  concerned  with  language 
and  mode  of  statement  as  distinguished  from  substantial 
doctrine. 

Calvin's  reflections  on  the  schoolmen,  then,  do  not  appear  to 
prove  any  substantial  difference  on  the  subject  of  predestina- 
tion, grace,  and  freewill,  between  himself  and  the  Augus- 
tinian  portion  of  the  schoolmen.  And  this  conclusion  obliges 
me  to  notice  some  remarks  of  Pascal  bearing  on  this  ques- 
tion in  the  Provincial  Letters. 

I  must  admit,  then,  that  I  have  against  me,  on  this  point, 
the  authority  of  Pascal,  who  endeavours  in  the  Provincial 
Letters  to  prove  a  strong  distinction  between  the  doctrine  of 
Calvin  and  the  Reformers,  and  the  Augustinian  and  Jan- 
senist  doctrine,  on  the  subject  of  grace  and  freewill.  But  I 
admit  it  the  more  readily,  for  the  obvious  consideration,  that 
Pascal  was  not  in  a  position  to  acknowledge  such  an  identity 
in  the  doctrine  of  the  two  schools.  As  an  attached  member 
of  the  Roman  communion,  he  was  obliged  by  his  position  to 
disconnect  his  own  and  his  party's  doctrine  as  much  as  pos- 
sible from  that  of  the  Reformers,  and  to  make  out  a  wide  dif- 
ference between  them.  The  Jansenists  were  attacked  on  all 
sides  as  disaffected  members  of  the  Roman  Church,  Re- 
formers in  heart,  though  outwardly  Catholics.  They  dis- 
owned and  repelled  the  charge  with  indignation.  But  what 
is  the  natural,  the  irresistible  disposition  of  a  religious  party 
under  such  circumstances,  with  respect  to  the  doctrines  upon 
which  such  a  charge  is  founded  ?  It  is,  of  course,  to  make 

E    E    3 


422  NOTE   XXI. 

out,  in  any  way  they  can.  a  difference  between  these  doctrines 
and  those  of  the  other  school,  with  which  their  opponents 
identify  them.  Under  such  circumstances,  the  authority  even 
of  Pascal  has  not,  upon  the  present  question,  any  irresistible 
weight.  And  when  we  come  to  examine  his  argument,  and 
the  reasons  upon  which  he  erects  the  difference  he  does 
between  the  Augustinian  and  the  Calvinistic  doctrine  of 
grace  any  weight  that  we  might  previously  have  been  in- 
clined to  give  his  conclusion  is  much  diminished.  r, 

Every  reader  of  the  Provincial  Letters  will  remember  the 
great  argumentative  clearness  and  penetration,  supported 
by  the  keenest  irony,  with  which  Pascal  proves  the  identity, 
under  a  guise  of  verbal  difference,  of  the  Thomist  doctrine  of 
grace  with  the  Jansenist.  The  Thomist  members  of  the 
Sorbonne,  siding  with  the  Jesuits  against  the  Jansenists,  had 
distinguished  their  own  doctrine  of  grace  from  that  of  the 
Jansenists  by  a  particular  term;  to  the  use  of  which,  though 
apparently  counter  to  their  own  Augustinian  doctrine,  they 
had  by  an  arrangement  consented  among  themselves,  but  to 
which  the  Jansenists  would  not  consent.  This  was  the  term 
prochain  —  proximus.  The  Thomists  maintained  that  every 
Christian  had  the  pouvoir  prochain  to  obey  the  Divine  com- 
mandments, and  so  attain  eternal  life  ;  while  the  Jansenists, 
admitting  the  power  of  any  Christian  to  do  this,  would  not  ad- 
mit that  this  power  was  prochain  ;  the  distinction  being,  that 
the  term  power  of  itself,  in  the  Augustinian  sense  (even  suppos- 
ing every  one  had  such  power),  committed  them  to  no  assertion 
contrary  to  the  exclusive  and  predestinarian  doctrine,  which 
made  salvation  only  really  attainable  by  the  elect.  For  power 
in  the  Augustinian  sense  only  means  potestas  si  vult ;  in  which 
sense  the  admission  that  all  Christians  have  the  power  is  not 
at  all  opposed  to  the  doctrine  that  only  the  elect  have  the 
will  given  to  them  to  lead  that  good  life  on  which  salvation 
depends.  But  the  addition  of  the  term  "  prochain  "  to  "power" 
seemed  to  fix  on  the  word  power  a  freewill  sense,  as  distin- 
guished from  the  Augustinian  one ;  and  to  imply  the  admis- 
sion that  every  one  had  the  full  and  complete  power,  in  the 
natural  sense  of  the  term,  to  attain  eternal  life,  —  which  was 
opposed  to  the  predestinarian  doctrine.  The  Jansenists, 


NOTE   XXI.  423 

therefore,  would  not  admit  the  terra  " prochain"  Now  it  is 
evident  that  in  this  refusal  they  laid  themselves  open  to  a  charge 
of  inconsistency ;  for  if  they  were  ready  to  admit  "  power  " 
in  an  artificial  sense,  they  might  have  admitted  "prochain" 
in  an  artificial  sense  too.  But  Pascal  adroitly  diverts  atten- 
tion from  the  inconsistency  of  the  Jansenists  in  their  meaning 
of  the  word  power,  to  the  inconsistency  of  the  Thomists  in 
the  meaning  they  gave  to  f<  power  prochain  ;  "  separating,  as 
the  latter  did  from  the  Jansenists,  on  the  express  ground  of 
this  phrase  being  refused,  when  they  themselves  held  the 
phrase  in  a  Jansenist  sense — i.  e.  so  as  to  be  consistent  with 
the  exclusive  and  predestinarian  doctrine  :  "  Mais  quoi !  mon 
pere,  s'il  manque  quelque  chose  a  ce  pouvoir,  1'appelez  vous 
prochain  ?  et  direz  vous,  par  exemple,  qu'un  homme  ait,  la 
nuit,  et  sous  aucune  lumiere,  le  pouvoir  de  voir  ?  Oui-da,  il 
1'auroit  selon  nous,  s'il  n'est  pas  aveugle." — 1st  Letter.  It 
is  obvious  that  in  this  sense  the  whole  Christian  body  might 
have  the  pouvoir  prochain,  and  still  not  a  real  and  bond  fide 
power  of  attaining  salvation,  which  might  still  be  confined  to 
.the  elect.  He  thus  shows  that  the  Thomists  only  differed 
from. the  Jansenists  in  the  use  of  a  word,  and  agreed  with 
them  in  meaning  and  doctrine.  And  he  proves  the  same 
thing  in  the  case  of  the  term  "grace  suffisante"  which  the 
Thomists  admitted  while  the  Jansenists  rejected  it :  "  Mais 
enfin,  mon  pere,  cette  grace  donnee  a  tous  les  hommes  est 
suffisante^  Oui  dit-il.  Et  neanmoins  elle  n'a  mil  effet 
sans  grace  efficace?  Cela  est  vrai,  dit-il.  Et  tons  les 
hommes  ont  la  suffisante,  continuai-je,  et  tous  n'ont  pas  efficace? 
II  est  vrai,  dit-il.  C'est-a-dire,  lui  dis-je,  que  tous  n'ont 
assez  de  grace,  et  que  tous  n'en  ont  pas  assez ;  c'est-a-dire, 
que  cette  grace  suffit,  quoiqu'elle  ne  suffise  pas ;  c'est-a-dire, 
qu'elle  est  suffisante  de  nom,  et  insuffisante  en  effet."  —  2nd 
Letter.  The  Thomists  then  admitted  the  term  "  suffisante  " 
in  an  artificial  sense,  which  enabled  them  to  say  that  such 
sufficient  grace  was  given  to  all,  while  they  really  held  that 
sufficient  grace,  in  the  natural  sense  of  the  word,  was  only 
given  to  the  elect.  And  therefore  Pascal  shows  in  this 
instance  again,  that  the  Thomists  only  differed  from  the  Jan- 

K    E    4 


424  NOTE    XXI. 

senists  upon  a  word,  while  they  agreed  with  them  in  meaning 
and  doctrine. 

But  the  same  argument  by  which  Pascal  proves  that  the 
Thomists  of  the  Sorbonne  agreed  in  doctrine  with  the  Jansen- 
ists, proves  equally  that  the  Janseriist  or  Augustinian  agreed 
in  doctrine  with  the  Calvinist.  The  eighteenth  Provincial 
Letter  contains  a  long  statement  and  argument  to  show  that 
the  Jansenist  doctrine  of  efficacious  grace  differed  from  the 
Calvinist :  the  argument  resting  upon  a  particular  admission 
with  respect  to  this  grace,  which  the  Calvinists  did  not  make, 
and  the  Jansenists  did,  —  the  admission,  viz.  that  man  had 
the  power  to  resist  this  grace.  He  raises  on  this  ground  a 
broad  distinction  between  the  Jansenists  and  the  Calvinists ; 
that  the  Jansenists  allow  freewill,  while  the  Calvinists  re- 
present man  as  moved  like  an  inanimate  machine.  I  will 
extract  at  some  length  from  this  part  of  the  Letter. 

"  Vous  verriez,  mon  pere,  que  non-seulement  ils  tiennent 
qu'on  resiste  eftectivement  a  ces  graces  faibles,  qu'on  appelle 
excitantes  ou  inefficaces,  en  n'executant  pas  le  bien  qu'elles 
nous  inspirent,  mais  qu'ils  sont  encore  aussi  fermes  a  soutenir 
contre  Calvin  le  pouvoir  que  la  volonte  a  de  resister  meme  a  la 
grace  efficace  et  victorieuse  qu'a  defendre  contre  Molina  le  pou- 
voir de  cette  grace  sur  la  volonte,  aussi  jaloux  de  Tune  de  ces 
verites  que  de  1'autre.  Ils  ne  savent  que  trop  que  1'homme, 
par  sa  propre  nature.,  a  toujours  le  pouvoir  de  pecker  et  de  re- 
sister  a  la  grace,  et  que,  depuis  sa  corruption,  il  porte  un 
fonds  malheureux  de  concupiscence  qui  lui  augmente  infini- 
ment  ce  pouvoir ;  mais  que  neanmoins,  quand  il  plait  a  Dieu 
de  le  toucher  par  sa  misericorde,  il  lui  fait  faire  ce  qrfil  vent 
et  en  la  maniere  qiiil  le  veut9  sans  que  cette  infaillibilite  de 
1'operation  de  Dieu  detruise  en  aucune  sorte  la  liberte  natu- 
relle  de  1'homme,  par  les  secretes  et  admirables  manieres  dont 
Dieu  opere  ce  changement,  que  saint  Augustin  a  si  excellem- 
ment  expliquees,  et  qui  dissipent  toutes  les  contradictions 
imaginaires  que  les  ennemis  de  la  grace  efficace  se  figurent 
entre  le  pouvoir  souverain  de  la  grace  sur  le  libre  arbitre,  et 
la  puissance  qu'a  le  libre  arbitre  de  resister  a  la  grace ;  car, 
selon  ce  grand  saint,  que  les  papes  de  1'Eglise  ont  donne  pour 


NOTE   XXI.  425 

regie  en  cette  matiere,  Dieu  change  le  coeur  de  1'homme  par 
une  douceur  celeste  qu'il  y  repand,  qui,  surmontant  la  delec- 
tation de  la  chair,  fait  que  1'homme,  sentant  d'un  cote  sa  mor- 
talite  et  son  neant,  et  decouvrant  de  1'autre  la  grandeur  et 
1'eternite  de  Dieu,  consoit  du  degout  pour  les  delices  du  pe- 
che  qui  le  separent  du  bien  incorruptible.  Trouvant  sa  plus 
grande  joie  dans  le  Dieu  qui  le  charme,  il  s'y  porte  infaillible- 
ment  de  lui-nieme  par  un  mouvement  tout  libre,  tout  volon- 
taire,  tout  amoureux ;  de  sorte  de  ce  lui  serait  une  piene  et 
un  supplice  de  s'en  separer.  Ce  n'est  pas  qu'il  ne  puisse  tou- 
jours  s'en  eloigner,  et  qu'il  ne  s'en  eloigndt  effectivement  s*il  le 
voulait.  Mais  comment  le  voudrait-il,  puisque  la  volonte  ne  se 
porte  jamais  qiia  ce  qui  lui  plait  le  plus,  et  que  rien  ne  lui 
plait  tant  alors  que  ce  bien  unique,  qui  comprend  en  soi  tous 
les  autres  biens  ?  Quod  enim  amplius  nos  delectat,  secundum 
id  operemur  necesse  est,  comme  dit  saint  Augustin.  —  Exp. 
Ep.  ad  Gal.  n.  49. 

"  C'est  ainsi  que  Dieu  dispose  de  la  volonte  libre  de  1'homme 
sans  lui  imposer  de  necessite,  et  que  le  libre  arbitre,  qui  pent 
toujours  resister  a  la  grace,  mais  qui  ne  le  veut  pas  toujours,  se 
porte.  aussi  librement  qu'infailliblement  a  Dieu,  lorsqu'il  veut 
1'attirer  par  la  douceur  de  ses  inspirations  efficaces. 

"  Ce  sont  la,  mon  pere,  lesdivins  principes  de  saint  Augustin 
et  de  saint  Thomas,  selon  lesquels  il  est  veritable  que  '  nous 

pouvons  resister  a  la  grace,'  centre  Fopinion  de  Calvin 

"  C'est  par  la  qu'est  detruite  cette  impiete  de  Luther,  con- 
damnee  par  le  meme  concile :  f  Que  nous  ne  cooperons  en  au- 
cune  sorte  a  notre  salut,  non  plus  que  des  choses  inanimees '  .  . . 
"  Et  c'est  enfin  par  ce  moyen  que  s'accordent  tous 
ces  passages  de  1'Ecriture,  qui  semblent  les  plus  opposes : 
que,  coinme  dit  saint  Augustin,  '  nos  ac- 
tions sont  notres,  a  cause  du  libre  arbitre  qui  les  produit ; 
et  qu'elles  sont  aussi  de  Dieu,  a  cause  de  sa  grace  qui  fait 
que  notre  arbitre  les  produit.'  Et  que,  comme  il  dit  ailleurs, 
Dieu  nous  fait  faire  ce  qu'il  lui  plait,  en  nous  faisant  vouloir 
ce  que  nous  pourrions  ne  vouloir  pas :  A  Deo  factum  est  ut 
vellent  quod  nolle  potuissent. 

"  Ainsi,  mon  pere,  vos  adversaires  sont  parfaitement  d'ac- 
cord  avec  les  nouveuux  thomistes  memes,  puisque  les  thomistes 


426  NOTE   XXI. 

tiennent  comrne  eux,  et  le  pouvoir  de  resister  a  la  grace,  et 
1'infaillibilite  de  1'eiFet  de  la  grace,  qu'ils  font  profession  de 
soutenir  si  hautement,  selon  cette  maxime  capitale  de  leur 
doctrine,  qu' Alvarez,  1'im  des  plus  considerables  d'entre  eux, 
repete  si  souvent  dans  son  livre,  et  qu'il  exprime  (Disp.  72. 
1.  viii.  n.  4.),  en  ces  termes:  f  Quand  la  grace  efficace  meut 
le  libre  arbitre,  il  consent  infailliblement ;  parce  que  1'eiFet 
de  la  grace  est  de  faire  qu 'encore  qrfil  puisse  ne  pas  consentir, 
il  consente  neanmoins  en  effet?  Dont  il  donne  pour  raison 
celle-ci  de  saint  Thomas,  son  maitre  (1.  2.  q.  1 1 2.  a.  3.) :  *  Que 
la  volonte  de  Dieu  ne  peut  manquer  d'etre  accomplie ;  et 
qu'ainsi,  quand  il  veut  qu'un  homme  consente  a  la  grace,  il 
consent  infailliblement,  et  meme  necessairement,  non  pas 
d'une  necessite  absolue,  mais  d'une  necessite  d'infuillibilite.' 
En  quoi  la  grace  ne  blesse  pas  '  le  pouvoir  qu'on  a  de  resister 
si  on  la  veut;'  puisqu'elle  fait  seulement  qu'on  ne  veut  pas  y 
resister,  comme  votre  pere  Petau  le  reconnait  en  ces  termes 
(t.  i.  Theol  Dogm.  1.  ix.  c.  7.  p.  602.)  :  <  La  grace  de  Jesus- 
Christ  fait  qu'on  persevere  infailliblement  dans  la  piete, 
quoique  non  par  necessite :  car  on  peut  riy  pas  consentir  si 
on  le  veut,  comme  dit  le  concile ;  mais  cette  meme  grace  fait 
que  Ton  ne  le  veut  pas? 

"  C'est  la,  mon  pere,  la  doctrine  constante  de  saint  Augustin, 
de  saint  Prosper,  des  peres  qui  les  ont  suivis,  des  conciles,  de 
saint  Thomas,  et  de  tous  les  thomistes  en  general.  C'est 
aussi  celle  de  vos  adversaires,  quoique  vous  ne  1'ayez  pas 
pense  .... 

"  •'  Pour  savoir,  dites-vous,  si  Jansenius  est  a  couvert,  il  faut 
savoir  s'il  defend  la  grace  efficace  a  la  maniere  de  Calvin,  qui 
nie  qu'on  ait  le  pouvoir  d'y  resister ;  car  alors  il  serait  here- 
tique  :  ou  a  la  maniere  des  thomistes,  qui  1'admettent ;  car 
alors  il  serait  catholique.'  Voyez  done,  mon  pere,  s'il  tient 
qu'on  a  le  pouvoir  de  resister,  quand  il  dit,  dans  des  traites 
entiers,  et  entre  autres  au  torn.  iii.  1.  viii.  c.  20. :  '  Qu'on 
a  toujours  le  pouvoir  de  resister  a  la  grace,  selon  le  concile : 
QUE  LE  LIBRE  4RBITRE  PEUT  TOUJOURS  AGIR  ET  N^AGIR 
PAS,  vouloir  et  ne  vouloir  pas,  consentir  et  ne  consentir  pas, 
faire  le  lien  et  le  mal ;  et  que  Vhomme  en  cette  vie  a  toujours 
ces  deux  libertes,  que  vous  appelez  de  contrariete  et  de  contra- 


NOTE    XXI.  427 

diction.''  Voyez  de  meme  s'il  n'est  pas  contraire  a.  1'erreur 
de  Calvin,  telle  qne  vous-meme  la  representez,  lui  qui  montre, 
dans  tout  le  chapitre  21.,  'que  1'Eglise  a  condamne  cet  here- 
tique,  qui  soutient  que  la  grace  efficace  n'agit  pas  snr  le  libre 
arbitre  en  la  maniere  qu'on  1'a  cru  si  longtemps  dans  1'Eglise, 
en  sorte  qu'il  soit  ensuite  au  pouvoir  du  libre  arbitre  de  con- 
sentir ou  de  ne  consentir  pas  :  au  lieu  que,  selon  saint  Au- 
gustin  et  le  concile,  072  a  toujours  le  pouvoir  de  ne  consentir 
pas,  si  on  le  veut" 

In  this  passage,  then,  we  have  the  ground  on  which  Pascal 
claims  a  great  distinction  to  be  made  between  the  Jansenist  and 
the  Calvinist  doctrine  of  efficacious  grace ;  the  ground  being 
that  while  the  Calvinists  deny  the  Jansenists  admit  —  le  pou- 
voir que  la  volonte  a  de  resistir  meme  d  la  grace  efficace  et 
victorieuse.  Now  this  admission  is  in  its  very  form  plainly 
and  at  first  sight  unmeaning ;  for  the  only  admission  which 
would  carry  freewill  with  it  would  be  that  man  could  resist 
effectively  this  grace;  and  certainly  no  effective  resistance 
can  by  the  very  force  of  the  terms  be  made  to  "  victorious 
grace."  But  the  true  explanation  of  this  whole  argument  is 
to  be.  found  in  a  particular  meaning  in  which  the  Augustinian 
school  understood  the  term  power.  Pascal  rests  the  whole 
claim  of  the  Jansenists  to  be  considered  believers  in  freewill 
on  their  use  of  this  word  —  their  admission  that  man  has  the 
power  to  resist  grace :  "  Us  ne  savent  que  trop  que  1'homme 
a  toujours  le  pouvoir  de  pecher  et  de  resister  a  la  grace." 
But  the  Augustinian  definition  of  power  entirely  nullifies 
this  as  any  admission  really  of  freewill ;  for  in  this  definition 
power  is  defined  to  be  potestas  si  vult.  But,  power  being  thus 
understood,  this  admission  leaves  the  whole  question  of  the 
will  and  its  determination  open,  and  allows  the  person  who 
makes  it  to  maintain  that,  while  every  one  has  the  power  to  re- 
sist grace  if  he  wills,  no  one  who  is  moved  by  Divine  grace  wills. 
Nor  is  this  meaning  of  the  term  power  at  all  concealed  in  this 
letter,  in  which  Pascal  expressly  time  after  time  thus  quali- 
fies the  term  power,  and  appends  to  it  this  condition :  "  Ce 
n'est  pas  qu'il  ne  puisse  toujours  s'en  eloigner,  et  qu'il  ne 
s'en  eloignat  sil  le  voulait.  Mais  comment  ce  voudrait-il, 
puisque  la  volonte  ne  se  porto  jamuis  qu'a  ce  qui  lui  pluit, 


428  NOTE   XXI. 

etc Le  libre  arbitre,  qui  peut  toujours  resister  a  la 

grace,  mais  qui  ne  le  veut  pas La  grace  ne  blesse  pas 

le  pouvoir  qu'on  a  de  resister  si  on  le  veut Car  on 

peut  n'y  pas  consentir  si  on   le  veut On  a  toujours 

le  pouvoir  de  ne  consentir  pas  si  on  le  veut."  Pascal  tells 
us,  then,  that  by  man's  power  to  resist  grace  is  meant  power 
if  fie  wills.  But  would  Calvin  object  to  admit  man's  power 
to  resist  grace  in  this  sense  f  He  could  not,  for  it  would  leave 
him  free  to  hold  his  whole  doctrine  of  irresistible  grace.  The 
doctrine  of  irresistible  grace  is  concerned  with  the  will  alone, 
and  its  determination  ;  and  this  admission  says  nothing  about 
the  determination  of  the  will.  Calvin,  then,  would  allow  at 
once  that  man  had  the  power  to  resist  grace  if  he  willed,  but 
that  he  could  not  will  to  resist  effective  grace ;  for  that  this 
grace  determined  his  will  and  inclination  itself,  and  caused  it 
to  be  what  it  was.  He  would  simply  say  with  Pascal  him- 
self, "  Mais  comment  le  voudrait-il?  "  with  the  writer  whom 
Pascal  quotes,  "  Encore  qu'il  puisse  ne  pas  consentir,  il  con- 
sente  neaamoins  en  effet;"  and  with  Augustine,  "A  Deo 
factum  est  ut  vellent  quod  nolle  potuissent." 

This  sense  of  the  term  power  is  the  key  to  the  statement 
quoted  from  Jansen  :  "  Qu'on  a  toujours  le  pouvoir  de  resister 
a  la  grace,  selon  le  concile  ;  que  le  libre  arbitre  peut  toujours 
ajfir  et  n'agir  pas,  vouloir  et  ne  vouloir  pas,  consentir  et  ne 
consentir  pas,  faire  le  bien  et  le  mal,  et  que  1'homme  en  cette 
vie  a  toujours  ces  deux  libertes,  que  vous  appelez  de  con- 
trariete  et  de  contradiction."  The  power  spoken  of  is  potestas 
si  vult;  on  which  understanding  the  admission  comes  to  no- 
thing ;  Jansen  expressly  saying  that  practically  the  individual 
cannot  act  but  in  the  way  in  which  grace  moves  :  "  Non  quod 
cessatio  ab  actu  quern  tune  (gratia)  elicit,  cum  gratia  delectantis 
mfluxu  consistere  possit  .  .  .  quamvis  fieri  nequeat  ut  ipsa  non 
actio  cumgraticB  operatione  in  eadem  simul  voluntate  copuletur." 
—  De  Grat.  Christi,  p.  870.  In  short,  all  that  the  Augustinian 
and  Jansenist  admission  with  respect  to  freewill  amounts  to, 
is  the  admission  of  a  will  in  man  ;  and  this  admission  Calvin 
is  equally  ready  to  make.  The  position  condemned  by  the 
Council  of  Trent,  as  that  of  the  Reformers,  that  man  was  moved 
by  Divine  grace  like  an  inanimate  thing,  was  not  their  posi- 


NOTE   XXI.  429 

tion ;  they  fully  acknowledged  a  will  in  man,  that  he  acted 
willingly  and  without  constraint ;  they  acknowledged  all  the 
facts  of  our  consciousness;  and,  admitting  them,  they  admitted 
all  that  S.  Augustine  and  his  school  admitted. 


THE   END. 


LONDON : 

A.  and  G.  A.  SPOTTISWOODE, 
New -street- Square. 


MURRAY'S  BRITISH  CLASSICS. 

PUBLISHING    IN    DEMY    OCTAVO    MONTHLY    VOLUMES. 


Examiner.  —  "  Mr.  Murray's  British  Classics,  so  edited  and  printed  as  to  take 
the  highest  place  in  any  library.  Beyond  all  question  the  cheapest  books  of 
the  day." 

AthencBum.  —  "  Those  who  love  to  collect  our  standard  authors  in  handsome 
library  editions,  may  well  congratulate  themselves  on  the  issue." 

Notes  and  Queries.  —  "  Distinguished  by  skilful  editorship,  beautiful  and  legible 
type,  fine  paper,  compactness  of  bulk,  and  economy  of  price." 

Quarterly  Review.  —  "A  series  of  the  British  Classics  which  is  undoubtedly  the 
best  selected  and  edited,  the  cheapest  and  the  handsomest  that  has  ever  issued  from 
the  press." 

THE  FOLLOWING  WORKS  ARE  NOW  COMPLETED. 
I. 

JOHNSON'S  LIVES  OF  THE  ENGLISH  POETS.  Edited  with 
Corrective  and  Explanatory  Notes.  By  PETER  CUNNINGHAM,  F.S.A. 
3  vols.  8yo.  22s.  6d. 

"The  most  popular  and  entertaining  of  all  Dr.  Johnson's  works." — Croker. 
"  The  richest,  most  beautiful,  and,  indeed,  most  perfect,  production  of  Johson's 
pen." — Boswell 

"  This  Edition  is  destined  hereafter  to  be  the  standard  one  in  English  litera- 
ture. Mr.  Cunningham  has  gone  about  his  work  in  a  workmanlike  manner." — 
Literary  Gazette. 

II. 

GIBBON'S  DECLINE  AND  FALL  OF  THE  ROMAN  EM- 
PIRE. Edited,  with  Notes,  By  WILLIAM  SMITH,  LL.D.,  and  very 
carefully  compiled  Index.  Portrait  and  Maps.  8  vols.  8vo.  60s. 

This  Edition  includes  the  Autobiography  of  Gibbon,  and  is  distinguished  by  careful 
revision  of  the  text,  verification  of  all  the  references  to  ancient  writers,  and  Notes  in- 
corporating the  researches  of  Modern  Scholars  and  Travellers. 

"An  edition  incomparably  the  best  in  every  respect  that  has  hitherto  appeared." 
— Examiner. 

"  The  task  of  editing  could  not  have  fallen  into  abler  hands.  If  there  be  any 
man  capable  of  bringing  to  bear  upon  the  improvement  of  Gibbon's  work  the  va- 
rious additions  which  have  been  made,  to  our  knowledge,  since  his  time,  it  is 
Dr.  Wm.  Smith." — Athenaeum. 

III. 

GOLDSMITH'S  WORKS.     Edited,   with   Notes.     By  PETER 

CUNNINGHAM,  F.S.A.     Vignettes.     4  vols.     8vo.     30s. 
"  Well  edited,  and  beautifully  printed." — The  Times. 

"  The  best  editions  have  been  consulted,  and  gives  evidence  of  careful  and 
conscientious  editing." — Guardian. 

"  The  first  complete  and  accurate  reprint  of  Goldsmith.  Numerous  errors  which 
had  crept  into  previous  editions  are  corrected,  omitted  passages  are  restored,  and 
entire  pieces  have  been  added." — Quarterly  Review. 

JOHN  MURRAY,  Albemarle  Street. 


ROBERTSON'S  CHURCH  HISTORY. 


This  day,  One  Volume  (544  pp.),  8vo.  12s.1 

HISTORY  OE  THE  CHRISTIAN  CHURCH  *TO  THE 
PONTIFICATE  OF  GREGORY  THE  GREAT,  A.  D.  590.  Intended  for 
General  Readers  as  well  as  for  Students  in  Theology.  By  Rev.  JAMES  C. 
ROBERTSON,  M.  A.,  Vicar  of  Bekesbourne. 

"ROBERTSON'S  '  CHURCH  HISTORY'  is  to.be  spoken  of  with  much  respect  as  a 
Useful,  learned,  and  conscientious  book.  He  speaks  of  it  himself,  indeed,  in  lan- 
guage of  excessive  modesty,  as  merely  *  a  readable  introduction'  to  an  ecclesiastical 
history.  No  doubt  it  is  a  compilation,  but  one  very  ably  and  fairly  done  ;  the 
authorities,  English  and  foreign,  who  have  been  consulted,  are  the  best  writers  on 
the  different  subjects." —  Guardian. 

"  ROBERTSON'S  CHURCH  HISTORY  traces  with  great  distinctness  the  history  of 
the  Church,  or  rather  of  the  Christians  who  composed  it ;  exhibits  briefly,  yet 
sufficiently,  the  leading  persons  among  the  Fathers  and  Martyrs ;  expounds  suc- 
cinctly the  opinions  or  doctrines  of  the  different  heresies,  and  judiciously  comments 
upon  the  whole  in  a  tone  alike  removed  from  fanaticism  or  coldness. " —  Spectator. 

"  ROBERTSON'S  CHURCH  HISTORY  brings  within  a  reasonable  compass  the  most 
important  events,  and  the  most  conspicuous  features  of  the  progressive  development 
of  the  external  form  of  her  doctrines  and  her  institutions.  The  spirit  in  which  the 
narrative  is  composed  is  that  of  a  sound  English  Churchman.  Clergymen  and 
Divinity  students  will  find  the  work  exceedingly  valuable  as  a  guide  in  the  prose- 
cution of  their  studies."  —  John  Bull. 

"  ROBERTSON'S  CHURCH  HISTORY.     Theological  students  will  find  the  learned 
annotations  to  this  volume  of  the  greatest  use.     It  has  a  table  of  the  various  wor 
cited,  and  is  supplied  with  an  excellent  index.     Its  genuine  scholarship  and  wi 
research  will  obtain  for  its  author  considerable  reputation."  —  The  Press. 

"  ROBERTSON'S  CHURCH  HISTORY  enjoys  the  rare  merit  of  being  free  from  par- 
tisanship, or  at  least  of  effectually  excluding  it  from  historical  investigation  ;  and 
the  diligence  with  which  the  author  has  searched  for  the  truth,  as  well  as  the  clear- 
ness with  which  he  has  exhibited  the  results,  will  render  his  book  a  popular  source 
of  information  on  the  subject."  —  Morning  Post. 

"  ROBERTSON'S  CHURCH  HISTORY  only  professes  to  supply  us  with  a  '  readable 
introduction  '  to  the  early  history  of  the  Church  ;  but  with  the  volume  in  our 
hands  we  are  disposed  to  rank  it  somewhat  higher.  It  is  written  by  a  man  who 
understands  the  bearings  of  his  subject,  and  exhibits  more  than  ordinary  skill  in 
the  construction  of  his  materials  ;  but  the  features  we  select  for  special  commen- 
dation are  his  candour,  honesty,  and  independence  in  handling  controverted  ques- 
tions."— Journal  of  Classical  and  Sacred  Philology. 

"  ROBERTSON'S  CHURCH  HISTORY  during  the  first  six  centuries  is  a  manly,  solid, 
straightforward,  and  clear-headed  performance,  evincing  large  scholarship,  prompt 
and  vigorous  discernment.  The  author  is  a  man  of  moderate  views,  but  nowise 
wanting  in  decision  and  firmness  in  expressing  them.  Modest  of  pretension,  and 
without  much  that  is  absolutely  new,  it  presents  a  faithful  and  compact  digest  of 
all  that  modern  research  has  rendered  available  for  such  an  undertaking." — New 
York  Churchman. 

"  ROBERTSON'S  CHURCH  HISTORY  is  of  great  service  to  the  educated  classes  of 
the  British  community,  by  furnishing  them  with  a  really  good  compendium  of 
ancient  Church  history.  Although  the  present  publication  is  not  called  a  first 
volume  of  General  Church  history,  but  appears  in  an  entire  form,  there  are  not 
wanting  indications  of  the  author's  purpose  to  continue  his  work,  and  we  sincerely 
wish  him  health  and  strength  to  do  so." — Scottish  Ecclesiastical  Journal. 

JOHN  MURRAY,  Albemarle  Street. 


ALBEJIABLE  STREET, 

January,  1855. 


ME,  MURKAY'S 
GENERAL    LIST    OF    WORKS. 


ABBOTT'S  (REV.  J.)  Philip  Musgrave ;  or,  Memoirs  of  a  Church  of 

England  Missionary  in  the  North  American  Colonies.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

ABERCROMBIE'S  (JOHN,  M.D.)  Enquiries  concerning  the  Intel- 
lectual Powers  and  the  Investigation  of  Truth.  Fourteenth  Edition. 
Fcap.  8vo.  6s.  6d. 

-  Philosophy   of     the  Moral   Feelings.    Ninth 

Edition.    Fcap.  8vo.    4s. 

Pathological  and  Practical  Researches  on  the 


Diseases  of  the  Stomach,  the  Intestinal  Canal,  the  Liver,  and  other 
Viscera  of  the  Abdomen.  Third  Edition.  Fcap.  8vo.  6s. 

AC/LAND'S  (REV.  CHARLES)  Popular  Account  of  the  Manners  and 
Customs  of  India,  Illustrated  with  Numerous  Anecdotes.  PostSvo.  2s. Qd. 

ADDISON'S   WORKS.     A  New  Edition,  with  a  New  Life  and 

Notes.    By  Rev.  WHITWELL  ELWIN.    4  Vols.    8vo.    In  Preparation. 

AESCHYLUS.      (The  Agamemnon    and  Choephorse).      A   New 

Edition  of  the  Text,  with  Notes,  Critical,  Explanatory,  and  Philological, 
for  the  Use  of  Students.  By  Rev.  W.  PEILE,  D.D..  Second  Edition. 
2  Vols.  8vo.  9s.  each. 

AESOP'S  FABLES.  A  New  Version,  chiefly  from  the  Original 
Greek.  By  Rev.  THOMAS  JAMES,  M.A.  Illustrated  with  100  Woodcuts, 
by  JOHN  TENNIEL.  21s«  Edition.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

AGRICULTURAL  (THE)  JOURNAL.  Published  (half-yearly)  by  the 
Royal  Agricultural  Society  of  England.  8vo.  10s. 

AMBER-WITCH  (THE).  The  most  interesting  Trial  for  Witch- 
craft ever  known.  Edited  by  Dr.  MEINHOLD.  Translated  from  the 
German  by  LADY  DUFF  GORDON.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

ARABIAN  NIGHTS.     A  New  Translation.    By  E.  W.  LANE. 

With  Explanatory  Notes.    600  Woodcuts.    Medium  8vo.    21*. 

ARISTOPHANES.  The  Birds  and  the  Clouds.  Translated 
from  SUVERN  by  W.  R.  HAMILTON,  F.R.S.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo.  9s. 

ARTHUR'S  (LITTLE)  History  of   England.    By   LADY   CALLCOTT. 

Seventeenth  Edition.    Woodcuts.    18mo. 

AUNT  IDA'S  Walks  and  Talks  ;  a  Story  Book  for  Children.  By 
a  LADY.  Woodcuts.  16mo.  6s. 


LIST  OF  WORKS 


ADMIRALTY  PUBLICATIONS ;  Issued  by  direction  of  the  Lords 

Commissioners  of  the  Admiralty: — 

1.  A  MANUAL  OF  SCIENTIFIC  ENQUIRY,  for  the  Use  of  Officers  in 

H.M.  Navy  and  Travellers  in  General.    By  Various  Hands.    Edited 
by  SIR  J.  F.  HEKSCHEL,  Bart.    Second  Edition.    Post  8vo.    10s.  6d. 

2.  AIRY'S  ASTRONOMICAL  OBSERVATIONS  MADE  AT  GREENWICH 

1836  to  1847.    Royal  4to.    50s.  each. 

3. APPENDIX  TO  THE  ASTRONOMICAL  OBSERVATIONS. 

1836, 1837, 1842,  8s.  each ;  and  1847, 14s.    Royal  4to. 

CONTENTS. 

1836.— Bessel's  Refraction  Tables. 

Tables  for  converting  Errors  of  R.A.  and  N.P.D.  into  Errors 

of  Longitude  and  Ecliptic  P.D. 
1837.— Logarithms  of  Sines  and  Cosines  to  every  Ten  Seconds 

of  Time. 

Table  for  converting  Sidereal  into  Mean  Solar  Time. 
1842.— Catalogue  of  1439  Stars. 
1847.— Twelve  Years'  Catalogue  of  Stars. 

4. MAGNETICAL     AND     METEOROLOGICAL    OBSERVA- 
TIONS.   1840  to  1847.    Royal  4to.    50s.  each. 

5. ASTRONOMICAL,    MAGNETICAL,    AND     METEOROLO- 
GICAL  OBSERVATIONS,  1848  to  1852.    Royal  4to.    50s.  each. 
REDUCTION   OF    THE   OBSERVATIONS   OF  PLANETS. 


1750  to  1830.    Royal  4to.    60s. 

7.  -  LUNAR  OBSERVATIONS.    1750 

to  1830.    2Vols.    Royal  4to.    50s.  each. 

8.  BERNOULLI'S  SEXCENTENARY  TABLE.    London,  1779.    4to.    5s. 

9.  BESSEL'S  AUXILIARY  TABLES  FOR  HIS  METHOD  OF  CLEAR- 

ING LUNAR  DISTANCES.    8vo. 

10.  —        — FUNDAMENTA  ASTRONOMIC :  Eegiomonti.  1818.  Folio.  60s 

11.  BIRD'S  METHOD    OF   CONSTRUCTING  MURAL  QUADRANTS. 

London,  1768.    4to.    2s.  Qd. 

12.  METHOD    OF    DIVIDING  ASTRONOMICAL   INSTRU- 
MENTS.   London,  1767.     4to.    2s.  6d. 

13.  COOK,  KING,  AND  BAYLY'S  ASTRONOMICAL  OBSERVATIONS. 

London,  1782.    4to.    21s. 

14.  EIFFE'S  ACCOUNT  OF  IMPROVEMENTS  IN  CHRONOMETERS. 

4to.    2s. 

15.  ENCKE'S  BERLINER  JAHRBUCH,  for  1830.    Berlin,  1828.    8vo.    9s. 

16.  GROOMBRIDGE'S    CATALOGUE    OF    CIRCUMPOLAR    STARS. 

4to.    10s. 

17.  HARRISON'S    PRINCIPLES    OF    HIS    TIME-KEEPER.    PLATES 

1767.    4to.    5s. 

18.  BUTTON'S   TABLES    OF    THE  PRODUCTS  AND  POWERS  OF 

NUMBERS.    1781.    Folio.    7s.  6d. 

19.  LAX'S  TABLES  FOR  FINDING   THE   LATITUDE  AND  LONGI- 

TUDE.   1821.    8vo.    10s. 

20.  LUNAR  OBSERVATIONS  at  GREENWICH.  1783  to  1819.  Compared 

with  the  Tables,  1821.    4to.    7s.  &d. 

21.  DISTANCES  of  the  MOON'S  CENTRE  from  the  PLANETS. 

1822,  3s.;  1823,  4s.  Qd.  1824  to  1835.  8vo.  4s.  each. 

22.  MASKELYNE'S  ACCOUNT   OF    THE   GOING  OF  HARRISON'S 

WATCH.    1767.    4to.    2s.  6d. 

23.  MAYER'S    THEORIA    LUN^E    JUXTA    SYSTEMA   NEWTONI- 

ANUM.    4to.    2s.'6rf. 

24. TABULA  MOTUUM  SOLIS  ET  LUN^E.    1770.    4to.    5s. 

25    ASTRONOMICAL    OBSERVATIONS  MADE  AT  GOT- 

TINGEN,  from  1756  to  1761.    1826.    Folio.    7s.  6d. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY. 


ADMIRALTY  PUBLICATIONS—  continued. 

26.  NAUTICAL  ALMANACS,  from  1767  to  1858.    8vo.    2s.  6d.  each. 

27.  SELECTIONS  FROM   THE  ADDITIONS 

up  to  1812.    8vo.    5s.    1834-54.    8vo.    5s. 

28.  SUPPLEMENTS,  1828  to  1833, 1837  and  1838. 

8vo.    2s.  each. 

TABLE  requisite  to  be  used  with  the  N.A. 


1781.    8vo.    5s. 

30.  POND'S  ASTRONOMICAL  OBSERVATIONS.  1811  to  1835.  4to.  21s. 

each. 

31.  RAMSDEN'S   ENGINE  for  DIVIDING   MATHEMATICAL  INSTKUMENTS. 

4to.    5s. 

32.  —  —  ENGINE  for  DIVIDING  STRAIGHT  LINES.    4to.    5s. 

33.  SABINE'S  PENDULUM  EXPERIMENTS  to  DETEBMINE  THE  FIGURE 

OF  THE  EARTH.    1825.    4to.    40s. 

34.  SHEPHERD'S    TABLES   for  CORRECTING  LUNAB   DISTANCES.    1772. 

Royal  4to.    21s. 

35.  TABLES,    GENERAL,  of  the  MOON'S  DISTANCE 

from  the  SUN,  and  10  STARS.    1787.    Folio.    5s.  6d. 

36.  TAYLOR'S  SEXAGESIMAL  TABLE.    1780.    4to.    15s. 
37. TABLES  OF  LOGARITHMS.    4to.    31. 

38.  TIARK'S   ASTRONOMICAL   OBSERVATIONS  for  the  LONGITUDE 

of  MADEIRA.    1822.    4to.    5s. 

39.  •    CHRONOMETRICAL  OBSERVATIONS    for  DIFFERENCES 
of  LONGITUDE  between  DOVER,  PORTSMOUTH,  and  FALMOUTH.    1823. 
4to.    5s. 

40.  VENUS  and  JUPITER:  OBSERVATIONS  of,  compared  with  the  TABLES. 

London,  1822.    4to.    2s. 

41.  WALES'    AND    BAYLY'S    ASTRONOMICAL    OBSERVATIONS. 

1777.    4to.    21s. 

42.  WALES'  REDUCTION    OF    ASTRONOMICAL    OBSERVATIONS 

MADE     IN     THE     SOUTHERN     HEMISPHERE.      1764—1771.      1788.       4tO. 

10s.  6d. 

AUSTIN'S    (SARAH)     Fragments    from    German  Prose    Writers. 
Translated,  with  Biographical  Notes.    Post.  8vo.    10s. 

Translation    of   Eanke's    Political    and    Ecclesiastical 

History  of  the  Popes  of  Rome.     Third  Edition.    2  Vols.    8vo.    24s. 

B  ABB  AGE'S  (CHARLES)  Economy  of  Machinery  and  Manufactures. 

Fourth  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo.    6s. 

Table  of  the  Logarithms  of  the  Natural  Numbers 

from  1  to  108000.    Fourth  Edition.    Royal  8vo.    6s. 

-   Ninth  Bridgewater  Treatise.    Second  Edition.    8vo. 

9s.  Gd. 

Keflections  on  the  Decline  of  Science  in  England, 


and  on  some  of  its  Causes.    4to.    15s. 


-   Exposition  of  1851 ;  or,  Yiews  of  the  Industry,  the 
Science,  and  the  Government  of  England.    Second  Edition.    8vo.    7s.  6d. 

BANKES'  (RIGHT  HON.  G.)  STORY  OF  CORFE  CASTLE,  with 
documents  relating  to  the  Time  of  the  Civil  Wars,  &c.  Woodcuts.  Post 
8vo.  10s.  6d. 

BASSOMPIERRE'S  Memoirs  of  his  Embassy  to  the  Court  of 
England  in  1626.  Translated,  with  Notes.  8vo.  9s.  6^. 


LIST  OF  WORKS 


BARROW'S  (SiE  JOHN)  Autobiographical  Memoir,  including 
Reflections,  Observations,  and  Reminiscences  at  Home  and  Abroad. 
From  Early  Life  to  Advanced  Age.  Portrait.  8vo.  16*. 

Voyages    of    Discovery    and    Research    within    the 

Arctic  Regions,  from  1818  to  the  present  time,   in  search  of  a  North- 
West  Passage :  with  Two  Attempts  to  reach  the  North  Pole.    Abridged 
and  arranged  from  the  Official  Narratives.    8vo.    15s. 

(JOHN)  Naval  Worthies  of  Queen  Elizabeth's  Reign, 

their  Gallant  Deeds,  Daring  Adventures,  and  Services  in  the  infant  state 
of  the  British  Navy.    8vo.    14s. 

Life  and  Voyages  of  Sir  Francis  Drake.    With  nume- 
rous Original  Letters.    Post  8vo.    2s.  6d. 

BEES  AND  FLOWERS.  Two  Essays,  by  a  CLERGYMAN,  reprinted 
from  the  "  Quarterly  Review."  Fcap.  8vo.  Is.  each. 

BELL'S  (SiK  CHARLES)  Anatomy  and  Philosophy  of  Expression  as 
connected  with  the  Fine  Arts,  fourth  Edition.  Plates.  Impl.  8vo.  21s. 

Mechanism    and    Yital    Endowments    of    the    Hand   as 

evincing  Design.    The  Bridgewater  Treatise.      Fifth  Edition.    Plates. 
PostSvo.    7s.  6d. 

BENEDICT'S   (JULES)   Sketch  of  the  Life    and  Works  of  Felix 

Mendelssohn  Bartholdy.    Second  Edition.    8vo.    2s.  6d. 

BERTHA'S  Journal  during  a  Visit  to  her  Uncle  in  England. 
Containing  a  Variety  of  Interesting  and  Instructive  Information.  Seventh 
Edition.  Woodcuts.  12mo.  7s.  6d. 

-   The  Heiress   in    her    Minority ;    or,  the   Progress  of 
Character.    By  Author  of  "  BEETHA'S  JOURNAL."    2  Vols.    12mo. 

BIRCH'S  (SAMUEL)  History  of  Ancient  Pottery  :  Egyptian,  Asiatic, 
Greek,  Roman,  Etruscan,  and  Celtic.  With  Illustrations.  8vo.  (Nearly 


BIRT'S  (W.  R.)  Hurricane  Guide.  Being  an  Attempt  to  connect 
the  Rotatory  Gale,  or  Revolving  Storm,  with  Atmospheric  Waves. 
With  Circles  on  Cards.  PostSvo.  3s. 

BIOSCOPE  (THE)  ;  or,  the  Dial  of  Life  explained.     By  GRANVILLE 

PENN.    Second  Edition.    With  Plate.    12mo.    12s. 

BLAINE  (ROBERTON)  on  the  Laws  of  Artistic  Copyright  and  their 
Defects,  for  Artists,  Engravers,  Printsellers,  &c.  8vo.  3s.  6d. 

BLUNT'S  (REV.  J.  J.)  Undesigned  Coincidences  in  the  Writings 
of  the  Old  and  New  Testament,  an  Argument  of  their  Veracity  :  with 
an  Appendix  containing  Undesigned  Coincidences  between  the  Gospels, 
Acts,  and  Josephus.  Fourth  Edition.  8vo.  9s. 

Principles  for  the  proper  understanding  of  the  Mosaic 

Writings,  stated  and  applied,  together  with  an  Incidental  Argument  for 
the  truth  of  the  Resurrection  of  our  Lord.  Being  the  HULSEA*  LECTURES 
for  1832.  PostSvo.  6s.  6d. 

BOOK  OF  COMMON  PRAYER.  With  1000  Illustrations  of 
Borders,  Initials,  and  Woodcut  Vignettes.  A  New  Edition.  Medium 
8vo.  21s.  cloth,  31*.  6d.  calf,  or  42s.  morocco. 

BOSWELL'S  (JAMES)  Life  of  Dr.  Samuel  Johnson.  Including  the 
Tour  to  the  Hebrides,  with  Notes  by  Sir  W.  SCOTT.  Edited  by  the  Right 
Hon.  JOHN  WILSON  CKOKEE.  A  New  Edition,  with  much  additional 
Matter.  Portraits.  One  Volume  Royal  8vo.  15s. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY. 


BORROWS  (GEORGE)  Lavengro  ;   The  Scholar — The  Gipsy — and 
the  Priest.    Portrait.    3  Vols.    PostSvo.    30s. 

-  Bible  in  Spain;  or  the  Journeys,  Adventures,  and 
Imprisonments  of  an  Englishman  in  an  Attempt  to  circulate  the 
Scriptures  in  the  Peninsula.  3  Vols.  Post  8vo.  27*.,  or  Cheap  Edition, 
16mo,  5s. 

Zincali,  or  the   Gipsies  of  Spain;    their  Manners, 


Customs,  Keligion,  and  Language.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo.  18s.,  or  Cheap 
Edition,  16mo.5s. 

BRAY'S  (MBS.)  Life  of  Thomas  Stothard,  R.A.  With  Personal 
Reminiscences.  Illustrated  with  Portrait  and  60  Woodcuts  of  his 
chief  works.  4to.  21s. 

BREWSTER'S  (SiR  DAVID)  Martyrs  of  Science,  or  the  Lives  of 

Galileo,  Tycho  Brahe,  and  Kepler.    Second  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo.    4s.  Qd. 

More    Worlds    than    One.       The   Creed   of    the 

Philosopher  and  the  Hope  of  the  Christian.  Sixth  Edition.  PostSvo.  6s. 

BRITISH  CLASSICS.  A  New  Series  of  Standard  English 
Authors,  printed  from  the  most  correct  text,  and  edited  with  elucidatory 
notes.  Published  in  Monthly  Volumes,  demy  8vo.,  7s.  Qd.  each. 

Already  Published. 
GOLDSMITH'S    WORKS.      Edited    by   PETEE    CUNNINGHAM,    F.S.A. 

Vignettes.   4  Vols. 
GIBBON'S    DECLINE    AND    FALL    OF    THE    ROMAN    EMPIRE. 

Edited  by  WILLIAM  SMITH,  LL.D.    Portrait  and  Maps.    8  Vols. 
JOHNSON'S  LIVES  OF  THE  ENGLISH  POETS.    Edited  with  Notes. 

ByPETEB  CUNNINGHAM,  F.S.A. 

In  Preparation. 
WORKS   OF  ALEXANDER  POPE.    Edited  by  the  RIGHT  HON.  JOHN 

WILSON  CROKER.    Assisted  by  PETER  CUNNINGHAM,  F.S.A. 
WORKS  OF  DRYDEN.    Edited  with  Notes. 
HUME'S  HISTORY  OF  ENGLAND.     A  new  Edition,  carefully  revised 

throughout,  with  Notes  and  Commentations,  to  correct  his  errors  and 

supply  his  deficiencies. 
WORKS  OF  SWIFT.    Edited  with  Notes. 
POETICAL  WORKS  OF  LORD  BYRON.    Edited,  with  Notes. 
WORKS  OF  JOSEPH  ADDISON.    Edited,  with  Notes. 

BRITISH  ASSOCIATION  REPORTS.    8vo.     York  and  Oxford, 

1831-32, 13s.  6d.  Cambridge,  1833,  12s.  Edinburgh,  1834, 15s.  Dublin, 
1835,  13s.  6d.  Bristol,  1836,  12s.  Liverpool,  1837,  16s.  6d.  Newcastle, 
1838,15s.  Birmingham,  1839,  13. 6d.  Glasgow,  1840,  15s.  Plymouth, 
1841,  13s.  6d.  Manchester,  1842,  10s.  Qd.  Cork,  1843,  12s.  York,  1844, 
20s.  Cambridge,  1845, 12s.  Southampton,  1846, 15s.  Oxford,  1847, 18s. 
Swansea,  1848,  9s.  Birmingham,  1849,  10s.  Edinburgh,  1850,  15s. 
Ipswich,  1851, 16s.  6d.  Belfast,  1852, 15s.  Hull,  1853, 10s.  6d. 

BROGDEN'S  (REV.  JAS.)  Illustrations  of  the  Liturgy  and  Ritual 

of  the  United  Church  of  England  and  Ireland.  Being  Sermons  and 
Discourses  selected  from  the  Works  of  eminent  Divines  of  the  17th 
Century.  3  Vols.  Post  8vo.  27s. 

—  Catholic  Safeguards  against  the  Errors,  Corruptions, 
and  Novelties  of  the  Church  of  Rome.  Being  Sermons  and  Tracts  selected 
from  the  Works  of  eminent  Divines  of  the  17th  Century.  Second  Edition 
With  Preface  and  Index.  3  Vols.  8vo.  36s. 


LIST  OF  WORKS 


BKOOKE'S  (SiR  JAMES)  Journals  of  Events  in  Borneo,  including 
,    the  Occupation  of  Labuan,  and  a  Visit  to  the  Celebes.    Together  with 
the    Expedition    of   H.M.S.  Iris.    By    CAPT.   RODNEY  MUNDY,   R.N. 
Plates.    2Vols.  8vo.     32s. 

BROUGHTON'S   (LORD)   Journey    through    Albania    and    other 

Provinces  of  Turkey  in  Europe  and  Asia,  to  Constantinople,  1809—10. 
New  Edition.    2  Vols.    8vo. 

BUBBLES  FROM  THE  BRUNNEN  OF  NASSAU.    By  an  OLD 

MAN.     Sixth  Edition.    16mo. 

BUNBURY'S  (C.  J.  F.)  Journal  of  a  Residence  at  the  Cape  of  Good 
Hope;  with  Excursions  into  the  Interior,  and  Notes  on  the  Natural 
History  and  Native  Tribes  of  the  Country.  Woodcuts.  Post  8vo.  9s. 

BUNYAN  (JOHN)  and  Oliver  Cromwell  Select  Biographies.  By 
ROBERT  SOUTHEY.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

BURGHERSH'S  (LORD)  Memoir  of  the  Operations  of  the  Allied 
Armies  under  Prince  Schwarzenberg  and  Marshal  Blucher  during  the 
latter  end  of  1813-14.  8vo.  21s. 

-  Early  Campaigns  of  the  Duke  of  Wellington  in 

Portugal  and  Spain.    8vo.    8s.  6d. 

BURN'S  (LiEUT.-CoL.)  French  and  English  Dictionary  of  Naval 
and  Military  Technical  Terms.  Third  Edition.  Crown  8vo.  15s. 

BURNES'  (SiR   ALEXANDER)    Journey    to    the    City    of    Cabool. 

Second  Edition.    Plates.    8vo.    18s. 

BURNS'  (ROBERT)  Life.  Br  JOHN  GIBSON  LOCKHART.  Fifth 
Edition.  Fcap.  8vo.  3s. 

BURR'S  (G.  D.)  Instructions  in  Practical  Surveying,  Topogra- 
phical Plan-drawing,  and  on  sketching  ground  without  Instruments. 
Second  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Post  8vo.  7s.  6d. 

BUXTON'S  (SiR  FOWELL)  Memoirs.  With  Selections  from  his 
Correspondence.  By  his  Son.  fourth  Edition.  8vx>.  16*.;  or,  Popular 
Edition.  Post  8vo.  8s.  6d. 

BYRON'S  (LORD)  Life  and  Letters.    By  THOMAS  MOORE.     Plates. 

6  Vols.    Fcap.  8vo.    18s.    Or,  One  Volume,  royal  8vo     12s. 

Poetical  Works.     Plates.     10  Yols.     Fcap.  8vo.    30s. 


Or,  One  Volume.    Royal  8vo.    12s. 

Pocket  Edition.    8  Yols.  24mo.    20s. 


Sold  separately  as  follows,  Prvte  2s.  6d.  each  volume  : 


Childe  Harold. 
Dramas,  2  Vols. 
Tales  and  Poems. 


Miscellanies,  2  Vols. 
Beppo  and  Don  Juan, 
2  Vols. 


Childe     Harold's    Pilgrimage.      Illustrated    Edition. 

With  30  Vignettes.    Crown  8vo.    10s.  Qd. 

-  Beauties — Poetry  and  Prose.     Fcap.  8vo.    3s. 

BUTTMAN'S  LEXILOGUS ;  or,  a  Critical  Examination  of  the 
Meaning  and  Etymology  of  numerous  Greek  Words  and  Passages, 
intended  principally  for  Homerand  Hesiod.  Translated,  and  edited,  with 
Explanatory  Notes  and  copious  Indexes,  by  REV.  J.  R.  FISHLAKE. 
Third  Edition.  8vo.  14s. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY. 


BUTTMAN'S  Catalogue  of  Irregular  Greek  Verbs ;    With  all  the 

Tenses  extant— their  Formation,  Meaning,  and  Usage,  accompanied  by 
an  Index.  Translated,  with  Notes,  by  REV.  J.  R.  FISHLAKE.  Second 
Edition.  8vo.  7*.  6d. 

CALVIN'S  (JOHN)  Life.  With  Extracts  from  his  Correspondence. 
By  THOMAS  H.  DYER.  Portrait.  8vo.  15s. 

CALLCOTT'S  (LADY)  Little  Arthur's  History  of  England.  Seven- 
teenth Edition.  Woodcuts.  18mo.  2s.  6d. 

CAREME'S    FRENCH    COOKERY.      Translated  by  W.  HALL. 

Second  Edition.    Plates.    8vo.    15s. 

CARMICHAEL'S    (A.  N.)     Greek    Verbs,     Their    Formations, 

Irregularities,  and  Defects.    Second  Edition.    Post  8vo.    8s.  6d. 

CARNARVON'S  (LORD)  Portugal,  Gallicia,  and  the  Basque 
Provinces.  From  Notes  made  during  a  Journey  to  those  Countries. 
Third  Edition.  Post  8vo.  5s. 

CAMPBELL'S  (LORD)  Lives  of  the  Lord  Chancellors  and  Keepers 
of  the  Great  Seal  of  England.  From  the  Earliest  Times  to  the  Death  of 
Lord  Eldon  in  1S38.  Third  Edition.  1  Vols.  8vo.  102s. 


Lives  of  the  Chief  Justices  of  England.    From  the 

Norman  Conquest  to  the  Death  of  Lord  Mansfield.   2  Vols.  8vo.    30s. 

Life  of  Lord  Bacon.     Reprinted  from  the  Lives  of 


the  Chancellors.    Fcap.  8vo.    2s. 

(GEORGE).    Modern  India.    A  Sketch  of  the  System 


of  Civil  Government.    With  some  Account  of  the  Natives  and  Native 
Institutions.    Second  Edition.    8vo.    16s. 

—  India  as  it  may  be.    An  Outline  of  a  proposed 

Government  and  Policy.    8vo.    12s. 

(THOS.)  Specimens  of  the  British  Poets.    With  Bio- 


graphical and  Critical  Notices,  and  an  Essay  on  English  Poetry.    Third 
Edition.    Portrait.    Royal  8vo.    15s. 

—  Short  Lives  of  the  British  Poets.    With  an  Essay 

on  English  Poetry.    Post  8vo.    5s. 

CASTLEREAGH  (THE)  DESPATCHES,  from  the  commencement 
of  the  official  career  of  the  late  Viscount  Castlereagh  to  the  close  of  his 
life.  Edited  by  the  MARQUIS  OF  LONDONDERRY.  12  Vols.  8vo.  14s.  each. 

CATHCART'S  (SIR  GEORGE)  Commentaries  on  the  War  in  Russia 

and  Germany,  1812-13.    Plans.    8vo.    14s. 

CEYLON.  An  Historical  and  Descriptive  Account  of  its  Past 
and  Present  Condition.  Post  8vo. 

CHARMED  ROE  (THE)  ;  or,  The  Story  of  the  Little  Brother  and 
Sister.  By  OTTO  SPECKTER.  Plates.  16mo.  5s. 

CLARENDON  (LORD  CHANCELLOR)  ;  Lives  of  his  Friends  and 
Contemporaries,  illustrative  of  Portraits  in  his  Gallery.  By  Lady 
THERESA  LEWIS.  Portraits.  3  Vols.  8vo.  42s. 

CLARK  (SiR  JAMES)  On  the  Sanative  Influence  of  Climate,  with  an 
Account  of  the  Best  Places  for  Invalids  in  the  South  of  Europe,  &c.  Fourth 
Edition.  Post  8vo.  10s.  6d. 

CLAUSEWITZ'S  (GENERAL  CARL  VON)  Campaign  of  1812,  in 
Russia.  Translated  from  the  German.  Map.  8vo.  10s.  6d. 


LIST  OF  WORKS 


OLIVE'S  (LORD);  Life.    By  REV.  G.  R.  GLEIG,  M.A.    Post  8vo.    5s. 

COLERIDGE'S  (SAMUEL  TAYLOR)  Table-Talk.  Fourth  Edition. 
Portrait.  Fcap.  8vo.  6s. 

-    (HENRY  NELSON)     Introductions  to  the  Study  of 
the  Greek  Classic  Poets.    Third  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo.  5s.  6d. 

COLONIAL  LIBRARY.     [See  Home  and  Colonial  Library.] 

COMBER'S  (DEAN)  Friendly  Advice  to  the  Roman  Catholics 
of  England.  By  Rev.  Dr.  HOOK.  .Fcap.  8vo.  3s. 

COOKERY  (DOMESTIC).  Founded  on  Principles  of  Economy  and 
Practical  Knowledge,  and  adapted  for  Private  Families.  New  and 
Cheaper  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  5s. 

CRABBE'S  (REV.  GEORGE)  Life  and  Letters.  By  his  SON.  Portrait. 
Fcap.  8vo.  3s. 

-  Life  and  Poetical  Works.     Plates.    8  Yols.  Fcap.  8vo. 
24s. ;  or,  One  Volume.    Royal  8vo.  10s.  6d. 

CUMMING'S  (R.  GORDON)  Five  Years  of  a  Hunter's  Life  in  the  Far 

Interior  of  South  Africa.    Fourth  and  Cheaper  Edition.    With  Woodcuts. 
2  Vols.    PostSvo.    12s. 

CURZON'S  (HoN.  ROBERT)  Yisits  to  the  Monasteries  of  the  Levant. 

Fourth  Edition.    Woodcuts.    PostSvo.    15s. 

-  ARMENIA  AND  ERZEROUM.     A  Year  on  the  Frontiers 

of  Russia,  Turkey,  and  Persia.     Third  Edition.    Map  and  Woodcuts. 
Post  8vo.     7s.  6d. 

CUNNINGHAM'S  (ALLAN)  Life  of  Sir  David  Wilkie.    With  his 

Journals,  and  Critical  Remarks  on  Works  of  Art.    Portrait.    3  Vols. 
8vo.    42s. 


Poems  and  Songs.     Now  first  collected 

and  arranged,  with  Biographical  Notice.    24mo.   2s.  6d. 

(CAPT.  J.  D.)  History  of    the   Sikhs.     From 


the  Origin  of  the  Nation  to  the  Battle  of  the  Sutlej.  Second  Edition. 
Maps.  8vo.  15s. 

-  (PETER)  London—  Past  and  Present.    A  Hand- 

book to  the  Antiquities,  Curiosities,  Churches,  Works  of  Art,  Public 
Buildings,  and  Places  connected  with  interesting  and  historical  asso- 
ciations. Second  Edition.  Post  8vo.  16s. 


-  Modern  London.  A  complete  Guide  for 
Visitors  to  the  Metropolis.  Map.  16mo.  5s. 

—  Environs  of  London.  Including  a  circle  of  25 
miles  round  St.  Paul's.  With  Hints  for  Excursions  by  Rail,—  Road,— 
and  River.  Post  8vo.  In  the  Press. 


-  Westminster  Abbey.      Its  Art,  Architecture, 
and  Associations.    Woodcuts.    Fcap.  8vo.    Is. 

Works  of  Oliver  Goldsmith.     A  New  Edition 


now  first  printed  from  the  last  editions  which  passed  under  the  Author's 
own  eye.    Vignettes.    4  vols.   8vo.    30s. 


Lives  of  Eminent  English  Poets.     By  SAMUEL 


JOHNSON,  D.D.  A  New  Edition,  with  Notes.   3  vols.   8vo.  22s.  6d. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY. 


CROKER'S  (RIGHT  HON.  J.  W.)  Progressive  Geography  for  Children. 

Fourth  Edition.    18mo.    Is.  6d. 

Stories   for    Children   Selected  from   the    History    of 

England.    Fifteenth  Edition.    Woodcuts.     16mo«    2s.  6d. 

-  Boswell's  Life  of  Johnson.    Including  the  Tour  to  the 
Hebrides.    A  New  Edition.    Portraits.    Royal  8vo.    15s. 

-  LORD  HERVEY'S  Memoirs  of  the  Reign  of  George  the 
Second,  from  his  accession  to  the  death  of  Queen  Caroline.     Edited 
with  Notes.    Second  and  Cheaper  Edition.    Portrait.    2  Vols.    8vo.  21s. 

-  History  of  the  Guillotine.    Woodcuts.    Fcap.  8vo.    Is. 

CROMWELL   (OLIVER)  and  John  Bunyan.     Select  Biographies. 

By  EOBEET  SOUTHEY.    Post  8vo.   2s.  6d. 

DARWIN'S  (CHARLES)  Journal  of  Researches  into  the  Natural 
History  and  Geology  of  the  Countries  visited  during  a  Voyage  round  the 
World.  Post  8vo.  7s.  6d. 

DAVY'S  (SiR  HUMPHRY)  Consolations  in  Travel;  or,  Last  Days 
of  a  Philosopher.  Fifth  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  6s. 

—  Salmonia ;  or,  Days  of  Fly  Fishing.  With  some  Account 
of  the  Habits  of  Fishes  belonging  to  the  genus  Salmo.  Fourth  Edition. 
Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  6s. 

DENNIS'  (GEORGE)  Cities  and  Cemeteries  of  Etruria;  or,  the 
extant  Local  Remains  of  Etruscan  Art.  Plates.  2  Vols.  8vo.  42s. 

-  Summer  in  Andalusia.      New  Edition.      Post  8vo.    In 

the  Presf. 

DEVEREUX'S  (HoN.  CAPT.,  R.N.)  Lives  and  Letters  of  the  Devereux 

Earls  of  Essex,  in  the  Reigns  of  Elizabeth,  James  I.,  and  Charles  I., 
1540 — 1646.  Chiefly  from  unpublished  documents.  Portraits.  2  Vols. 
8vo.  30s. 

DODGSON'S  (REV.  C.)  Controversy  of  Faith ;  or,  Advice  to  Candi- 
dates for  Holy  Orders.  Containing  an  Analysis  and  Exposition  of  the 
Argument  by  which  the  Catholic  Interpretation  of  the  Baptismal  Services 
is  to  be  vindicated.  12mo.  3s. 

DOG-BREAKING ;  the  Most  Expeditious,  Certain,  and  Easy 
Method,  whether  great  excellence  or  only  mediocrity  be  required.  By 
LiEUT.-CoL.  HUTCHINSON.  Second  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.Svo.  7s.  6d. 

DOMESTIC  MODERN   COOKERY.     Founded  on  Principles  of 

Economy  and  Practical  Knowledge,  and  adapted  for  Private  Families. 
New  and  Cheaper  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  5s. 

DOUGLAS'S    (GENERAL  SIR    HOWARD)   Treatise   on  the  Theory 

and  Practice  of  Gunnery.    Fourth  Edition.    Plates.    8vo.    21s. 

—  Treatise  on  the  Principle  and  Construction  of  Military 
Bridges,  and  the  Passage  of  Rivers  in  Military  Operations.  Third 
Edition.  Plates.  8vo.  21s. 

DRAKE'S    (SiR  FRANCIS)  Life,  Yoyages,  and  Exploits,  by  Sea  and 

Land.    By  JOHN  BARROW.     Third  Edition.    Post  8vo.    2s.  Qd. 

DRINKWATER'S  (JOHN)  History  of  the  Siege  of  Gibraltar. 
1779-1783.  With  a  Description  and  Account  of  that  Garrison  from  the 
Earliest  Periods.  Post  8vo.  2s.  Qd. 


10 


LIST  OF  WORKS 


DRYDEN'S  (JOHN)  Works.  A  New  Edition,  based  upon  Sir 
Walter  Scott's  Edition,  entirely  revised.  Svo.  In  Preparation. 

DUDLEY'S  (EARL  OF)  Letters  to  the  late  Bishop  of  Llandaff. 

Second  Edition.    Portrait.    Svo.    10s.  6d. 

DURHAM'S  (ADMIRAL  SIR  PHILIP)  Naval  Life  and  Services.  By 
CAPT.  ALEXANDER  MURRAY.  Svo.  5s.  6d. 

DYER'S  (THOMAS  H.)  Life  and  Letters' of  John  Calvin.  Compiled 
from  authentic  Sources.  Portrait.  Svo.  15s. 

EASTLAKE  (Sm  CHARLES)  The  Schools  of  Painting  in  Italy. 
From  the  Earliest  times.  From  the  German  of  KUGLER.  Edited,  with 
Notes.  Third  Edition.  Illustrated  with  100  Engravings  from  the  Old 
Masters.  2  Vols.  PostSvo. 

Contributions  to  the  Literature  of  the  Fine  Arts. 


8vo.   12j. 
EDWARDS'  (W.  H.)  Yoyage  up  the  River  Amazon,  including  a 

Visit  to  Para.    Post  8vo.    2s.  6d. 

EGERTON'S  (HoN.  CAPT.  FRANCIS)  Journal  of  a  Winter's  Tour  in 
India;  with  a  Visit  to  Nepaul.  Woodcuts.  2  Vols.  PostSvo.  18s. 

ELDON'S  (LORD  CHANCELLOR)  Public  and  Private  Life,  with  Selec- 
tions from  his  Correspondence  and  Diaries.  By  HORACE  Twiss.  Third 
Edition.  Portrait.  2  Vols.  Post  Svo.  21*. 

ELLESMERE'S  (LORD)  Two  Sieges  of  Vienna  by  the  Turks. 
Translated  from  the  German.  Post  Svo.  2s.  6d. 

-  Second    Campaign  of  Radetzky   in    Piedmont. 
The  Defence  of  Temeswar  and  the  Camp  of  the  Ban .    From  the  German. 
PostSvo.    6s.  6d. 

-  Life  and  Character  of  the  Duke  of  Wellington ; 

a  Discourse.    Second  Edition.    Fcap.  Svo.    6d. 

Campaign  of  1812  in  Russia,  from  the  German 

of  General  Carl  Von  Clausewitz.    Map.    Svo.    10s.  6d. 

-  The  Pilgrimage,  the   18th  of  November,    and 
other  Poems.    Post  Svo. 

ELPHINSTONE'S    (HON.   MOTIOTSTTTABT)   History  of  India— the 

Hindoo  and  Mahomedan  Periods.    Third  Edition.    Map.    Svo.    18s. 

EL  WIN'S  (REV.  W.)  Lives  of  Eminent  British  Poets.  From 
Chaucer  to  Wordsworth.  4  Vols.  Svo.  In  Preparation. 

ENGLAND  (HISTORY  OF)  From  the  Peace  of  Utrecht  to  the  Peace 

of  Versailles,  1713—83.    By  LORD  MAHON.    Library  Edition,  7  Vols., 
Svo,  93s.;  or,  Popular  Edition,  7  Vols.    Post  Svo,  42s. 

From  the  First  Invasion  by  the  Romans, 

down  to  the  14th  year  of  Queen  Victoria's  Reign.    By  MRS.  MARKHAM. 
68th  Thousand.    Woodcuts.    12mo.    6s. 

As  IT  is :  Social,   Political,  and  Industrial,   in  the 

Middle  of  the  19th  Century.    By  W.  JOHNSTON.    2  Vols.    PostSvo.  18s. 

and  '  France    under    the     House    of      Lancaster. 


With  an  Introductory  View  of  the  Early  Reformation.    Svo.    15s. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY.  11 


ERSKINE'S  (CAPT.,  R.N.)  Journal  of  a  Cruise  among  the  Islands 
of  the  Western  Pacific,  including  the  Fejees  and  others  inhabited  by 
the  Polynesian  Negro  Races.  Plates.  8vo.  16s. 

ESKIMAUX  (THE)  and  English  Yocabulary,  for  the  use  of  Travellers 

in  the  Arctic  Regions.    16mo.    3s.  6d. 

ESSAYS  FROM  "THE  TIMES."  Being  a  Selection  from  the 
LITERARY  PAPERS  which  have  appeared  in  that  Journal.  6th  Thousand. 
2  vols.  Fcap.  8vo.  8s. 

ENGLISHWOMAN  IN  RUSSIA :  or,  Impressions  of  Manners 
and  Society  during  a  Ten  Years'  Residence  in  that  Country.  Wood 
cuts.  Post  8vo.  10s  6d. 

EXETER'S  (BISHOP  OP)  Letters  to  the  late  Charles  Butler,  on  the 

Theological  parts  of  his  Book  of  the  Roman  Catholic  Church;  with 
Remarks  on  certain  Works  of  Dr.  Milner  and  Dr.  Lingard,  and  on  some 
parts  of  the  Evidence  of  Dr.  Doyle.  Second  Edition.  8vo.  16s. 

FAIRY  RING  (THE),  A  Collection  of  TALES  and  STORIES  for  Young 
Persons.  From  the  German.  By  J.  E.  TAYLOR.  Illustrated  by  RICHARD 
DOYLE.  Second  Edition.  Fcap.  8vo. 

PALKNER'S  (FRED.)  Muck  Manual  for  the  Use  of  Farmers.    A 

Treatise  on  the  Nature  and  Value  of  Manures.  Second  Edition,  with  a 
Glossary  of  Terms  and  an  Index.  Fcap.  8vo.  5s. 

FAMILY  RECEIPT-BOOK.    A  Collection  of  a  Thousand  Valuable 

and  Useful  Receipts.    Fcap.  8vo.    5s.  6d. 

FANCOURT'S  (CoL.)  History  of  Yucatan,  from  its  Discovery 
to  the  Close  of  the  17th  Century.  With  Map.  8vo.  10s.  Qd. 

FARINI'S  (Lumi  CARLO)  History  of  the  Roman  State,  1815-50. 
Translated  from  the  Italian.  By  Right  Hon.  W.  E.  GLADSTONE. 
Vols.  3  &  4.  8vo.  12s.  each. 

FEATHERSTONHAUGH'S  (G.  W.)  Tour  through  the  Slave  States 
of  North  America,  from  the  River  Potomac,  to  Texas  and  the  Frontiers 
of  Mexico.  Plates.  2  Vols.  8vo.  26s. 

FELLOWS'  (SiR  CHARLES)  Travels  and  Researches  in  Asia  Minor, 
more  particularly  in  the  Province  of  Lycia.  New  Edition.  Plates.  Post 
8vo.  9s. 

FERGUSON'S  (ROBERT,  M.D.)  Essays  on  the  Diseases  of  Women. 

Part  I.  Puerperal  Fever.    Post  8vo.    9s.  Gd. 

FERGUSSON'S  (JAMES)  Palaces  of  Nineveh  and  Persepolis 
Restored :  an  Essay  on  Ancient  Assyrian  and  Persian  Architecture. 
With  45  Woodcuts.  8vo.  16s. 


Peril  of  Portsmouth ;  or  French  Fleets  and  English 


Forts.     Third  Edition.    Plan.    8vo.    3s. 


•  Handbook    of   Architecture.      Being    a 

Concise  and  Popular  Account  of  the  Different  Styles  prevailing  in  all 
Ages  and  Countries  in  the  World.  With  a  Description  of  the  most 
remarkable  Buildings.  With  1000  Illustrations.  8vo.  In  the  Press. 

FEUERBACH'S  Remarkable  German  Crimes  and  Trials.    Trans- 
lated from  the  German  by  Lady  DUFF  GORDON.    8vo.    12s. 


12  LIST  OF  WORKS 


FISHER'S  (REV.  GEORGE)  Elements  of  Geometry,  for  the  Use  of 

Schools.    ThirdEdition.    18mo.   3s. 

First  Principles  of  Algebra,   for  the  Use  of  Schools. 

Third  Edition.    18mo.    3s. 

FISHL  AKE'S  (REV.  J.  R.)  Translation  of  Buttman's  Lexilogus ;  A 

Critical  Examination  of  the  Meaning  and  Etymology  of  numerous  Greek 
Words  and  Passages,  intended  principally  for  Homer  and  Hesiod.  With 
Explanatory  Notes  and  Copious  Indexes.  Third  Edition.  8vo.  14*. 

Translation  of  Buttman's  Catalogue  of  Irregular 
Greek  Verbs;  with  all  the  Tenses  extant — their  Formation,  Meaning, 
and  Usage.  With  Explanatory  Notes,  and  accompanied  hy  an  Index. 
Second  Edition.  8vo.  7s.  6d. 

FLOWER  GARDEN  (THE).  An  Essay  reprinted  from  the 
"  Quarterly  Review."  Fcap.  8vo.  Is. 

FORD'S  (RICHARD)  Handbook  for  Spain,  Andalusia,  Ronda,  Valencia. 
Catalonia,  Granada,  Gallicia,  Arragon,  Navarre,  &c.  Third  and  entirely 
Revised  Edition.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo. 

—  Gatherings  from  Spain.     Post  8vo.     6s. 

FORSYTH'S  (WILLIAM)  Hortensius,  or  the  Advocate :  an  Historical 
Essay  on  the  Office  and  Duties  of  an  Advocate.  Post  8vo.  12». 

-  History  of  Napoleon  at  St.  Helena.  From  the 
Letters  and  Journals  of  SIR  HUDSON  LOWE.  Portrait  and  Maps.  3  Vols. 
8vo.  45s. 

FORTUNE'S  (ROBERT)  Narrative  of  Two  Visits  to  China,  between 
the  years  1843-52,  with  full  Descriptions  of  the  Culture  of  the  Tea 
Plant.  Third  Edition.  Woodcuts.  £  Vols.  Post  8vo.  18s. 

FRANCE  (HISTORY  OF).  From  the  Conquest  by  the  Gauls  to  the  Death 

of  Louis  Philippe.  By  Mrs.  MARKHAM.  QQth  Thousand.  Woodcuts. 
12mo.  6s.  t 

FRENCH  (THE)  in  Algiers ;  The  Soldier  of  the  Foreign  Legion — 
and  the  Prisoners  of  Abd-el-Kadir.  Translated  by  Lady  DUFF  GORDON. 
Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

GALTON'S  (FRANCIS)  Art  of  Travel ;  or,  Hints  on  the  Shifts  and 
Contrivances  available  in  Wild  Countries.  Woodcuts.  Post  8vo.  6*. 

GEOGRAPHICAL  (THE)  Journal.  Published  by  the  Royal  Geo- 
graphical Society  of  London.  8vo. 

GERMANY  (HISTORY  OF).  From  the  Invasion  by  Marius,  to  the 
present  time.  On  the  plan  of  Mrs.  MARKHAM.  6th  Thousand.  Woodcuts. 
12mo.  6s. 

GIBBON'S  (EDWARD)  Life  and  Correspondence.  By  DEAN  MILMAN. 
Portrait.  8vo.  9*. 

-  Decline  and  Fall  of  the  Roman  Empire.  A  New 
Edition.  Preceded  by  the  Autobiography  of  GIBBON.  Edited  with 
Notes  by  Dr.  WM.  SMITH.  Portrait  and  Maps.  8  Vols.  8vo.  60s. 

GIFFARD'S  (EDWARD)  Deeds  of  Naval  Daring ;  or,  Anecdotes  of 
the  British  Navy.  2  Vols.  Fcap.Svo.  5s. 

GISBORNE'S  (THOMAS)  Essays  on  Agriculture.  Third  Edition. 
Post  8vo.  5s. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY.  13 

GLADSTONE'S   (RIGHT  HON.  W.  E.)  Prayers  arranged  from  the 

Liturgy  for  Family  Use.    Second  Edition.    12mo.    2s.  6d. 

-  History  of  the  Roman  State.     Translated  from  the 
Italian  of  LUIGI  CAHLO  FARINI.    Vols.  3  and  4.    8vo.    12s.  each. 

GOLDSMITH'S  (OLIVER)  Works.    A  New  Edition.     Printed  from 

the  last  editions  revised  hy  the  Author.    Edited  by  PETES  CUNNING- 
HAM.   Vignettes.    4Vols.8vo.    30s. 

GLEIG'S  (REV.  G.  R.)  Campaigns  of  the  British  Army  at  Washing- 
ton and  New  Orleans.    Post  8vo.    2*.  6d. 

Story  of  the  Battle  of  Waterloo.    Compiled  from  Public 

and  Authentic  Sources.    Post  8vo.    5s. 

Narrative  of  Sir  Robert  Sale's  Brigade  in  Afghanistan, 

with  an  Account  of  the  Seizure  and  Defence  of  Jellalabad.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

—  Life  of  Robert  Lord  Clive.     Post  8vo.     5s. 
Life  and  Letters  of  General  Sir  Thomas  Munro.    Post 


8vo.    5s.  "  . 

GOOCH  (ROBERT,  M.D.),  On  the  most  Important  Diseases  peculiar  to 

Women.    Second  Edition.    8vo.    12s. 

GORDON'S  (SiR  ALEX.  DUFF)  Sketches  of  German  Life,  and  Scenes 
from  the  War  of  Liberation.  From  the  German.  Post  8vo.  5s. 

—  (LADY  DUFF),   Amber- Witch  :    the  most  interesting 
Trial  for  Witchcraft  ever  known.    From  the  German.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

French    in  Algiers.     1.  The  Soldier  of  the  Foreign 

Legion.  2.  The  Prisoners  of  Abd-el-Kadir.  From  the  French. 
Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

-   Remarkable  German  Crimes  and  Trials.     From  the 
German.    8vo.    12s. 

GOSPEL  STORIES  FOR  CHILDREN.  An  Attempt  to  render  the 
Chief  Events  of  the  Life  of  Our  Saviour  intelligible  and  profitable. 
Second  Edition.  18mo.  3s.  6d. 

GRANT'S  (ASAHEL),  Nestorians,  or  the  Lost  Tribes  ;   containing 
Evidence  of  their  Identity,  their  Manners,  Customs,  and  Ceremonies    ; 
with  Sketches  of  Travel  in  Ancient  Assyria,  Armenia,  and  Mesopotamia; 
and  Illustrations  of  Scripture  Prophecy.    Third  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo.    6*. 

GRENVILLE  (THE)  LETTERS  AND  DIARIES ;  being  the  Public 
and  Private  Correspondence  of  George  Grenville,  his  Friends  and  Con- 
temporaries, during  a  period  of  30  years. — Including  his  DIARY  OF 
POLITICAL  EVENTS  while  First  Lord  of  the  Treasury.  Edited,  with 
Notes,  by  W.  J.  SMITH.  4  Vols.  8vo.  16s.  each. 

GREEK  GRAMMAR  FOR  SCHOOLS.  Abridged  from  Matthise. 
By  the  BISHOP  OP  LONDON.  Eighth  Edition,  revised  by  Eev.  J.  EDWARDS. 
12mo.  3s. 

—  Accidence  for  Schools.  Abridged  from  Matthias. 
By  the  BISHOP  OF  LONDON.  Fourth  Edition,  revised  by  Rev.  J.  EDWARDS. 
12mo.  2s. 

GREY'S  (SiR  GEORGE)  Polynesian"1  Mythology,  and  Ancient 
Traditional  History  of  the  New  Zealand  Race.  Woodcuts.  Post 
8vo.  10s.  6d. 


14  LIST  OF  WORKS 


QUOTE'S  (GEORGE)  History  of  Greece.     From  the  Earliest  Period 
to  the  death  of  Alexander  the  Great.    Maps.    12  vols.    8vo.    16s.  each. 
The  Work  may  be  had  as  follows : — 
VOLS.  I.— II. — Legendary  Greece.    Grecian  History  to  the  Reign  of 

Peisistratus  at  Athens. 
VOLS.  III.— IV.— History  of  Early  Athens,  and  the  Legislation  of  Solon. 

Grecian  Colonies.   View  of  the  Contemporary  Nations  surrounding 

Greece.    Grecian  History  down  to  the  first  Persian  Invasion,  and  the 

Battle  of  Marathon. 
VOLS.  V. — VI. — Persian  War  and  Invasion  of  Greece  by  Xerxes.  Period 

between  the  Persian  and  the  Peloponnesian  Wars.    Peloponnesian 

War  down  to  the  Expedition  of  the  Athenians  against  Syracuse. 
VOLS.  VII.— VIII.— The  Peace  of  Nikias  down  to  the  Battle  of  Knidus. 

Socrates  and  the  Sophists. 
VOLS.  IX.— XL— From  the  Restoration  of  the  Democracy  at  Athens  down 

to  the  Death  of  Philip  of  Macedon  (B.C.  403—359). 
VOL.  XII.— The  end  of  the  Reign  of  Alexander  the  Great.    Review  of 

Plato  and  Aristotle. 

GUIZOT  (M.),  on  the  Causes  of  the  Success  of  the  English 
Revolution  of  1640-1688.  8vo.  6s. ;  or  Cheap  Edition,  12mo,  Is. 

—  Democracy  in  France.    Sixth  Edition.    8vo.    8s.  Qd. 

GURWOOD'S  (CoL.)  Despatches  of  the  Duke  of  Wellington  during 
his  various  Campaigns.  Compiled  from  Official  and  Authentic  Docu- 
ments. New,  enlarged,  and  complete  Edition.  8  vols.  8vo.  21s.  each. 

Selections  from  the  Wellington  Despatches 

and  General  Orders.    New  Edition.    8vo.    18s. 

Speeches    in   Parliament   of   the  Duke    of 


Wellington.    2  Vols.    8vo. 

GUSTAYUS  YASA  (History  of),  King  of  Sweden.  With  Extracts 
from  his  Correspondence.  Portrait.  8vo.  10s.  6d. 

HALLAM'S  (HENRY)  Constitutional  History  of  England)  from  the 
Accession  of  Henry  the  Seventh  to  the  Death  of  George  the  Second. 
Seventh  Edition.  3  Vols.  8vo.  30s. 

—  History  of  Europe  during  the  Middle  Ages.     Tenth 

Edition.    3  Vols.    8vo.    30s. 

Introduction  to  the  Literary  History  of  Europe,  during 


the  16th,  17th,  and  18th  Centuries.    Fourth  Edition.    3  Vols.    8vo.  36s. 
Literary  Essays   and  Characters.    Selected  from  the 


last  work.    Fcap.  8vo.    2s. 
HAMILTON'S  (WALTER)  Hindostan,  Geographically,  Statistically, 
and  Historically.    Map.    2  Vols.    4to.    94s.  6d. 

(W.  J.)  Eesearches  in  Asia  Minor,  Pontus,  and 
Armenia;  with  some  Account  of  the  Antiquities  and  Geology  of  those 
Countries.  Plates.  2  Vols.  8vo.  38s. 

HAMPDEN'S  (BISHOP)  Essay  on  the  Philosophical  Evidence  of 
Christianity,  or  the  Credibility  obtained  to  a  Scripture  Revelation 
from  its  Coincidence  with  the  Facts  of  Nature.  8vo.  9s.  6d. 

HARCOURT'S  (EDWARD  YERNON)  Sketch  of  Madeira ;  with  Map 
and  Plates.  Post  8vo.  8s.  6d. 

HART'S  ARMY  LIST.  (Published  Quarterly  and  Annually.)  8vo. 

HAY'S  (J.  H.  D*UMMOND)  Western  Barbary,  its  wild  Tribes  and 
savage  Animals.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY. 


HAND-BOOK    OF     TRAVEL-TALK;    or,     Conversations     in 
English,  German,  French,  and  Italian.    18mo.   3s.  6d. 

-  BELGIUM  AND  THE  RHINE.  Maps.  Post  Svo.  5s. 

-  NORTH   GERMANY— HOLLAND,    BELGIUM,    and 
the  Khine  to  Switzerland.    Map.    Post  Svo.   9s. 

SOUTH  GERMANY— Bavaria,  Austria,  Salzberg, 
the  Austrian  and  Bavarian  Alps,  the  Tyrol,  and  the  Danube,  from  Ulm 
to  the  Black  Sea.  Map.  Post  8vo.  9s. 


SWITZERLAND— the  Alps  of  Savoy,  and  Piedmont. 

Maps.    Post  8vo.    7s.  6d. 

OF   FRANCE— Normandy,  Brittany,  the    French 


Alps,  the  Rivers  Loire,  Seine,  Rhone,  and  Garonne,aDauphine,  Provence, 
and  the  Pyrenees.    Maps.    Post  Svo.    9s. 

-  SPAIN — Andalusia,    Ronda,     Granada,    Valencia, 
Catalonia,  Gallicia,  Arragon,  and  Navarre.    Maps.    2  Vols.   Post  Svo. 

-  PORTUGAL.    Map.    Post  Svo. 

PAINTING — the   German,    Dutch,    Spanish,  and 


French    Schools.     From    the  German    of  KUGLEB.     Edited  by  SIB 
EDMUND  HEAD.   Woodcuts.    2  Vols.    Post  Svo. 

-  NORTH   ITALY— Florence,  Sardinia,  Genoa,  the 
Riviera,  Venice,    Lombardy ,  and  Tuscany.    Map.    Post  Svo.    9s. 

CENTRAL    ITALY— SOUTH    TUSCANY    and    the 


PAPAL  STATES.    Map.    Post  Svo.    7s. 

ROME— AND  ITS    ENVIRONS.     Map.      Post 


Svo.    7s. 

-  SOUTH  ITALY— Naples,  Pompeii,  Herculaneum, 

Vesuvius,  &c.    Map.    Post  Svo.    15s. 

PAINTING— the  Italian  Schools.    From  the  Ger- 


man of  KUGLEB.  Edited  by  Sir  CHARLES  EASTLAKE.     Woodcuts.    2 
Vols.  Post  Svo. 


PICTURE    GALLERIES    OF   ITALY.     Being  a 

Biographical  Dictionary  of  Italian  Painters :  with  a  Table  of  the  Con- 
temporary Schools.  By  a  LADY.  Edited  by  RALPH  N.  WOBNUM. 
Post  Svo.  6s.  6d. 

-    GREECE— the   Ionian  Islands,  Albania,  Thessaly, 

and  Macedonia.    Maps.    Post  Svo.    15s. 

TURKEY — MALTA,  ASIA  MINOR,  CONSTANTINOPLE, 


Armenia,  Mesopotamia,  &c.    Maps.    Post  Svo.  10s. 
r-    EGYPT — Thebes,    the    Nile,    Alexandria,     Cairo, 

the  Pyramids,  Mount  Sinai,  &c.    Map.    Post  Svo.   15s. 

DENMARK — NORWAY  and  SWEDEN.    Maps.    Post 


Svo.    12s. 


-  RUSSIA — THE  BALTIC  AND  FINLAND.  Maps.    Post 

Svo.    12s. 

-  DEVON  AND  CORNWALL.  Maps.  Post  Svo.  6s. 

-  LONDON,  PAST  AND  PRESENT.     Being  an  Alpha- 
betical Account  of  all   the  Antiquities,  Curiosities,  Churches,  Works 
of  Art,  Places,  and  Streets  connected  with  Interesting  and  Historical 
Associations.    Post  Svo.    16s. 


16  LIST  OF  WORKS 


HAND-BOOK  OP  MODERN  LONDON.    A  Guide  to  all  objects 

of  interest  in  the  Metropolis.    Map.    16mo.  5*. 

ENVIRONS  OF  LONDON.     Including  a  Circle  of 


30  Miles  round  St.  Paul's.    Maps.    Post  8vo.    (Nearly  ready.) 


BRITISH  MUSEUM;  ITS  ANTIQUITIES  AND  SCULP-' 


TUBE.    300  Woodcuts.    Post  8vo.    7s.  6d. 


PICTURE    GALLERIES    IN  AND    NEAR    LONDON. 


With  Critical  Notices.    Post  8vo.    10s. 


-  WESTMINSTER   ABBEY— its  Art,  Architecture, 

and  Associations.    Woodcuts.    16mo.    Is. 

HISTORY,  Alphabetically  arranged.  8vo.  (Nearly 


Beady.) 

(OFFICIAL).     Giving  an  Historical  Account  of  the 


Duties  attached  to  the  various  Civil  and  Ecclesiastical  Departments  of 
the  Government.    Post  8vo.    6s. 


-  FAMILIAR  QUOTATIONS.   Chiefly  from  English 

Authors.    A  New  Edition  with  an  Index.    Fcap.  8vo.    5s. 

-  ARCHITECTURE.     Being  a  Concise  and  Popular 
Account  of  the  Different  Styles  prevailing  in  all  Ages  and  Countries 
in  the  World.    With  a  Description  of  the  most  remarkable  Buildings. 
By  JAMES  FERGUSSON.    Illustrations.    8vo.    In  the  Press. 

-  CATHEDRALS  OF  ENGLAND.      With    Plates. 

Post  8vo.    In  Preparation. 

MEDL3SYAL  ART.     Translated  from  the  French 


of  M.  Jules  Labarthe,  and  Edited  by  Mrs.  PALLISEB.  With  Illustrations. 
,8vo.    In  the  Press. 

HEAD'S  (SiR  FRANCIS)  Rough  Notes  of  some  Rapid  Journeys  across 
the  Pampas  and  over  the  Andes.  Post  8vo.  2s.  Qd. 

Bubbles  from  the  Brunnen  of  Nassau.     By  an  OLD  MAN. 

Sixth  Edition.    16mo.   6*. 

•  Emigrant.     Sixth  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo.    2*.  Qd. 

Stokers  and  Pokers,  or  the  London  and  North- Western 

Railway.    Post  8vo.    2s.  Qd. 

Defenceless  State  of  Great  Britain.  Contents— 1.  Mili- 
tary Warfare.  2.  Naval  Warfare.  3.  The  Invasion  of  England.  4.  The 
Capture  of  London  by  a  French  Army.  5.  The  Treatment  of  Women 
in  War.  6.  How  to  Defend  Great  Britain.  Post  8vo.  12*. 

Faggot  of  French  Sticks,  or  description  of  Paris  in  1851. 

2  Vols.     Post  8vo.    24s. 

Fortnight  in  Ireland.    Second  Edition.   Map.    8vo.    12s. 

(SiR  GEORGE)  Forest  Scenes  and  Incidents  in  Canada. 

Second  Edition.    Post  8vo.    10*. 

Home  Tour  through    the   Manufacturing  Districts   of 

England,  Scotland,  and  Ireland,  including  the  Channel  Islands,  and  the 
Isle  of  Man.    Third  Edition.    2  Vols.  Post  8vo.    12s. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY.  17 


HEAD'S  (SiB  EDMUND)  Handbook  of  Painting — the  German, 
Dutch,  Spanish  and  French  Schools.  Partly  from  the  German  of 
KUGLEB.  With  Illustrations.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo,  24s. 

HEBER'S  (BISHOP)  Parish  Sermons ;  on  the  Lessons,  the  Gospel, 
or  the  Epistle,  for  every  Sunday  in  the  Year,  and  for  Week-day  Festivals. 
Sixth  Edition.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo.  16s. 

Sermons  Preached  in  England.    Second  Edition.    8vo. 


95.  6d. 


—  Hymns  written    and  adapted    for  the  weekly  Church 
Service  of  the  Year.    Twelfth  Edition.    16mo.   2s. 

Poetical    Works.    Fifth  Edition.    Portrait.    Fcap.  8vo. 


7s.  e 

(BISHOP)  Journey  through  the  Upper  Provinces  of  India. 

From  Calcutta  to  Bombay,  with  a  Journey  to  Madras  and  the  Southern 
Provinces.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo.  10s. 

HEIRESS  (THE)  in  Her  Minority ;  or,  The  Progress  of  Character. 
By  the  Author  of  "  BEBTHA'S  JOUBNAL."  2  Vols.  12mo.  18s. 

HERODOTUS.    A  New  English  Version.      Translated  from  the 

TextofGAiSFOBD,  and  Edited  with  Notes,  illustrating  the  History  and 
Geography  of  Herodotus,  from  the  most  recent  sources  of  information. 
By  Rev.  G.  RAWLINSON,  COLONEL  RAWLINSON,  and  SIB  J.  G.  WILKINSON. 
4  Vols.  8vo.  In  Preparation. 

HERSCHEL'S  (SiR  J.  W.  F.)  Manual  of  Scientific  Enquiry,  for  the 

Use  of  Travellers.  By  various  Writers.  Second  Edition.  PostSvo.  10s.  6d. 

HERVEY'S  (LORD)  Memoirs  of  the  Reign  of  George  the  Second, 

from  his  Accession  to  the  Death  of  Queen  Caroline.  Edited,  with  Notes, 
by  Right  Hon.  J.  W.  CBOKEB.  Second  and  CJieaper  Edition.  Portrait. 
2Vols.8vo.  21s. 

HICKMAN'S  (WM.)  Treatise  on  the  Law  and  Practice  of  Naval 

Courts  Martial.    8vo.    10s.  6d. 

HILL  (FREDERIC)  On  Crime  :  its  Amount,  Causes,  and  Remedies. 
8vo.  12s. 

HILLARD'S  (G.  S.)  Six  Months  in  Italy.    2  Yols.    Post  8vo.    16s. 

HISTORY  OF  ENGLAND  AND  FRANCE  UNDER  THE  HOUSE 
OF  LANCASTEB.  With  an  Introductory  View  of  the  Early  Reformation.. 
8vo.  15s. 

—  the  late  War:  with  Sketches  of  Nelson,  Wellington, 
and  Napoleon.    By  J.  G.  LOCKHABT.    18mo.    2s.  6d. 

HOLLAND'S  (REV.  W.  B.)  Psalms  and  Hymns,  selected  and 
adapted  to  the  various  Solemnities  of  the  Church.  Third  Edition.  24mo. 
Is.  3d. 

HOLL WAY'S  (J.  G.)  Month  in  Norway.    Fcap.  8vo.     2s. 

HONEY  BEE  (THE).  An  Essay  by  a  Clergyman.  Reprinted 
from  the  "  Quarterly  Review."  Fcap.  8vo.  Is. 

c 


18 


LIST  OF  WORKS 


HOME  AND  COLONIAL  LIBRARY.    Complete  in  76  Parts. 

Post  8vo,  or  bound  in  37  Volumes,  cloth. 

CONTENTS  OF  THE   SERIES. 

THE  BIBLE  IN  SPAIN.    By  GEOEGE  BOREOW. 

JOURNALS  IN  INDIA.    By  BISHOP  HEBER. 

TRAVELS  IN  THE  HOLY  LAND.    By  CAPTAINS  IEBY  and  MANGLES. 

THE  SIEGE  OP  GIBRALTAR.    By  JOHN  DRINKWATEB. 

MOROCCO  AND  THE  MOORS.    By  J.  DRUMMOND  HAY. 

LETTERS  FROM  THE  BALTIC.    By  a  LADY. 

THE  AMBER  WITCH.    By  LADY  DUFF  GORDON. 

OLIVER  CROMWELL  &  JOHN  BUNYAN.    By  ROBERT  SOUTHET. 

NEW  SOUTH  WALES.    By  MRS.  MEREDITH. 

LIFE  OF  SIR  FRANCIS  DRAKE.    By  JOHN  BARROW. 

FATHER  RIPA'S  MEMOIRS  OF  THE  COURT  OF  CHINA. 

A  RESIDENCE  IN  THE  WEST   INDIES.     By  M.G.LEWIS. 

SKETCHES  OF  PERSIA.    By  SIR  JOHN  MALCOLM. 

THE  FRENCH  IN  ALGIERS.    By  LADY  DUFF  GORDON. 

BRACEBRIDGE  HALL.    By  WASHINGTON  IRVING. 

VOYAGE  OF  A  NATURALIST.  By  CHARLES  DARWIN. 

HISTORY  OF  THE  FALL  OF  THE  JESUITS. 

LIFE  OF  LOUIS  PRINCE  OF  CONDE.    By  LORD  MAHON. 

GIPSIES  OF  SPAIN.    By  GEORGE  BORROW. 

THE  MARQUESAS.     By  HERMANN  MELVILLB. 

LIVONIAN  TALES.    By  a  Lady. 

MISSIONARY  LIFE  IN  CANADA.    By  REV.  J.  ABBOTT. 

SALE'S  BRIGADE  IN  AFFGHANISTAN.    By  REV.  G.  R.  GLEIG. 
LETTERS  FROM  MADRAS.    By  a  LADY. 

HIGHLAND  SPORTS.    By  CHARLES  ST.  JOHN. 
JOURNEYS  ACROSS  THE  PAMPAS.    By  SIR  F.  B.  HKAD. 

GATHERINGS  FROM  SPAIN.    By  RICHARD  FORD. 

SIEGES  OF  VIENNA  BY  THE  TURKS.    By  LORD  ELLESMEBE. 

SKETCHES  OF  GERMAN  LIFE.    By  SIR  A.  GORDON. 

ADVENTURES  IN  THE  SOUTH  SEAS.    By  HERMANN  MELVILLE. 

STORY  OF  BATTLE  OF  WATERLOO.    By  REV.  G.  R.  GLEIG. 

A  VOYAGE  UP  THE  RIVER  AMAZON.     By  W.  H.  EDWARDS. 

THE  WAYSIDE  CROSS.    By  CAPT.  MILMAN. 

MANNERS  &  CUSTOMS  OF  INDIA.    By  REV.  C.  ACLAND. 

CAMPAIGNS  AT  WASHINGTON.    By  REV.  G.  R.  GLEIG. 

ADVENTURES  IN  MEXICO.    By  G.  F.  RUXTON. 

PORTUGAL  AND  GALLICIA.    By  LORD  CARNARVON. 

LIFE  OF  LORD  CLIVE.    By  REV.  G.  R.  GLEIG. 

BUSH  LIFE  IN  AUSTRALIA.    By  H.  W.  HAYGARTH. 

THE  AUTOBIOGRAHY  OF  HENRY  STEFFENS. 

TALES  OF  A  TRAVELLER.    By  WASHINGTON  IRVING.  - 

SHORT  LIVES  OF  THE  POETS.  By  THOMAS  CAMPBELL. 

HISTORICAL  ESSAYS.    By  LORD  MAHON. 

LONDON  &  NORTH-WESTERN  RAILWAY.    By  SIR  F.  B.  HEAD. 

ADVENTURES  IN  THE  LYBIAN  DESERT.     By  BAYLE  ST.  JOHN. 

A  RESIDENCE  AT  SIERRA  LEONE.    By  a  LADY. 

LIFE  OF  GENERAL  MUNRO.    By  REV.  G.  R.  GLEIG. 

MEMOIRS  OF  SIR  FOWELL  BUXTON.    By  bis  SON. 

LIFE  OF  OLIVER  GOLDSMITH.    By  WASHINGTON  IRVING. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY.  19 


HOOK'S  (REV.  DR.)  Church  Dictionary.    Seventh  Edition.  8vo.  16s. 

—  Discourses   on  the  Religious   Controversies  of   the  Day. 
8vo.    9s. 

Advice  to  the  Roman  Catholics.     By  DEAN  COMBEE.    A 

New  Edition.   With  Notes.    Fcap.   8vo.    3s. 

(THEODORE)  Life.  An  Essay.  Reprinted  from  the  "  Quarterly 

Review."    Fcap.  8vo.    1*. 

HOOKER'S  (J.  D.)  Himalayan  Journals ;  or,  Notes  of  an  Oriental 
Naturalist  in  Bengal,  the  Sikkim  and  Nepal  Himalayas,  the  Khasia 
Mountains,  &c.  Second  Edition.  Weodcuts.  2  vols.  Post  8vo. 

HOOPER'S  (LIEUT.)  Ten  Months  among  the  Tents  of  the  Tuski ; 
with  Incidents  of  an  Arctic  Boat  Expedition  in  Search  of  Sir  John 
Franklin.  By  LIEUT.  HOOPER,  R.N.  Plates  8vo.  14s. 

HORACE  (Works  of).  Edited  by  DEAN  MILMAN.  New  Edition. 
With  300  Woodcuts.  Crown  8vo.  21s. 

(Life  of).    By  DEAN  MILMAN.    New  Edition.    Woodcuts, 

and  coloured  Borders.    8vo.    9s. 

HORNER'S  (FRANCIS)   Memoirs  and  Letters.     By  his  BROTHER. 

Second  Edition.    Portrait.    2  Vols.  8vo.    30s. 

HOSPITALS  AND  SISTERHOODS.    Second  Edition.   Fcap.  8vo. 

3s.  6d. 

HOUSTOUN'S  (MRS.)   Yacht  Yoyage  to  Texas  and  the  Gulf  of 

Mexico.    Plates.    2  Vols.    PostSvo.    21s. 

HUMBOLDTS  (ALEX.)  Cosmos ;  or,  a  Physical  Description  of  the 
World.  Translated  by  COL.  and  MBS.  SABINE.  Seventh  Edition.  3  Vols, 
Post  8vo.  10s.  6d. 

Aspects  of  Nature  in   different    Lands  and   in 

different  Climates.    Translated  by   COL.  and  MBS.  SABINE.     2  Vols. 
Post  8vo.    5s. 

HUTCHINSON  (COLONEL)  on  Dog-Breaking;  the  most  expe- 
ditious, certain,  and  easy  Method,  whether  great  Excellence  or  only 
Mediocrity  be  required.  Second  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  7s.  Qd. 

INKERSLEY'S  (Tnos.)  Gothic  Architecture  in  France ;  Being  an 
Inquiry  into  the  Chronological  Succession  of  the  Romanesque  and 
Pointed  Styles;  with  Notices  of  some  of  the  principal  Buildings,  and 
an  Index.  8vo.  12s.  • 

IRBY  AND  MANGLES'  Travels  in  Egypt,  Nubia,  Syria,  and 
the  Holy  Land,  including  a  Journey  round  the  Dead  Sea,  and  through 
the  Country  east  of  the  Jordan.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

JAMES'  (REV.  THOMAS)  Fables  of  M&op.  A  New  Yersion,  chiefly 
from  the  Original  Greek.  With  100  Original  Designs,  by  JOHN 
TENNIEL.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

JAMESON'S  (MRS.)  Handbook  to  the  Picture  Galleries  in  and 
near  London.  With  Historical,  Biographical,  and  Critical  Notices 
Post  8vo.  Second  Edition.  10s. 

JAPAN  AND  THE  JAPANESE.    Described  from  the  Accounts 

of  Recent  Dutch  Travellers.    New  Edition.    Post  8vo.    6s. 

JERYIS'S  (LIEUT.)  Manual  of  Operations  in  the  Field,  for  the  Use  of 
Officers.  Post  8vo.  9s.  6d. 

c  2 


20  LIST  OF  WORKS 


JESSE'S  (EDWARD)  Visits  to  Spots  of  Interest  in  the  Yicinity  of 
Windsor  and  Eton.    Woodcuts.    Post  8vo.    12s. 

—  Scenes  and  Occupations  of  Country  Life.     With  Recol- 
lections of  Natural  History.    Third  Edition.   Woodcuts.    Fcap.  8vo.  6s. 

Gleanings  in  Natural  History.     With  Anecdotes  of  the 


Sagacity  and  Instinct  of  Animals.    Sixth  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo. 

JOCELYN'S  (LORD)  Six  Months  with  the  Chinese  Expedition ;  or, 
Leaves  from  a  Soldier's  Note-Book.  Seventh  Edition.  Fcap.  8vo.  5s.  6d 

JOHNSON'S  (DR.  SAMUEL)  Life  :  By  James  Boswell.  Including 
the  Tour  to  the  Hebrides,  with  Notes  by  SIB  W.  SCOTT.  Edited  by 
the  Right  Hon.  JOHN  WILSON  CHOKER.  A  New  Edition,  with  much 
additional  matter.  1  Vol.  Portraits.  Royal  8vo.  15s. 

-  Lives  of  the  most  eminent  English 

Poets.   A  New  Edition.  Edited  and  annotated.  By  PETER  CUNNINGHAM. 
3vols.    8vo.    22s.  Qd. 

JOHNSTON'S  (WM.)    England  as  it  is  :  Social,  Political,   and 

Industrial,  in  the  Middle  of  the  19th  Century.    2  Vols.    PostSvo.    18s. 

JONES'S  (REV.  RICHARD)  Essay  on  the  Distribution  of  Wealth, 
and  on  the  Source's  of  Taxation.  Part  I.— RENT.  Second  Edition.  Post 
8vo.  7s.  Qd. 

JOURNAL  OF  A  NATURALIST.    Fourth  Edition.     Woodcuts. 

Post  8vo.    9s.  Qd. 

JOWETT'S  (Rev.  B.)  Commentary  on  St.  Paul's  Epistles  to  the 
Thessalonians,  Galatians,  and  Romans.  With  Notes  and  Dissertations. 
8vo.  In  the  Press. 

KEN'S  (BISHOP)  Life.    By  A  LAYMAN.    Second  Edition.    Portrait. 

2  Vols.    8vo.    18s. 

Exposition  of  the  Apostles  Creed.     Extracted  from  his 

''Practice  of  Divine  Love."    New  Edition.    Fcap.    Is.  Qd. 

Approach  to  the  Holy  Altar.    Extracted  from  his  a  Manual 

of  Prayer  "  and  "  Practice  of  Divine  Love."    New  Edition.    Fcap.Svo 
or  24mo.    Is.  Qd.  each. 

KING  EDWARD  Vlin's  Latin  Grammar;  or,  an  Introduction 
to  the  Latin  Tongue,  for  the  Use  of  Schools.  Tenth  Edition.  12mo.  3s.  Qd. 

— 5 First  Latin  Book,  or  the  Accidence, 

Syntax  and  Prosody,  with  an  English  Translation  for  the  Use  of  Junior 
Classes.    Second  Edition.    12mo.    2s. 

KINNEAR'S  (JOHN  G.)  Cairo,  Petra,  and  Damascus,  described 
from  Notes  made  during  a  Tour  in  those  Countries  :  with  Remarks  on 
the  Government  of  Mehemet  Ali,  and  on  the  present  prospects  of  Syria. 
PostSvo.  9s.  Qd. 

KNIGHT'S  (CHARLES)  Knowledge  is  Power  :  a  View  of  the 
Productive  forces  of  Modern  Society,  and  the  results  of  Labour,  Capital 
and  Skill.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  7s.  6d. 

—  Once  upon  a  Time.    2  Yols.    Fcap.  8vo.    105. 

—  Old  Printer  and  Modern  Press.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.Svo.  5s. 

KOCH'S  (PROFESSOR)  Crimea  and  Odessa;  their  Climate  and  Re- 
sources, described  from  personal  knowledge.  Map.  Post  8vo. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY.  21 


KUGLER'S    (Dr.   FRANZ)  Handbook  to  the  History  of  Painting 

(the  Italian  Schools).  Translated  from  the  German.  Edited,  with 
Notes,  by  SIR  CHARLES  EASTLAKE.  Third  Edition.  With  Woodcuts 
from  the  Old  Masters.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo. 

—  (the  German,  Dutch,  Spanish, 

and  French  Schools).  Partly  Translated  from  the  German.  Edited, 
with  Notes,  by  SIR  EDMUND  HEAD,  Bart.  With  Woodcuts  from  the  Old 
Masters.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo.  24s. 

LABARTHE'S  (M.  JULES)  Handbook  of  Mediaeval  Art.  Trans- 
lated from  the  French  of  M.  JULES  LABARTHE,  and  edited  with  notes  and 
illustrations,  by  MRS.  PALLISER.  Woodcuts.  8vo. 

LABORDE'S  (LEON  DE)  Journey  through  Arabia  Petraea,  to  Mount 
Sinai,  and  the  Excavated  City  of  Petrsea, — the  Edom  of  the  Prophecies. 
Second  Edition.  With  Plates.  8vo.  18*. 

LAMBERT'S  (Miss)  Church  Needlework.  With  Practical  Remarks 
on  its  Preparation  and  Arrangement.  Plates.  Post  8vo.  9s.  6d. 

—  My  Knitting  Book.  Woodcuts.  Two  Parts.  16mo.  3s. 

—  My  Crochet  Sampler.  Woodcuts.  Two  Parts.  16mo.  4s. 
Hints  on  Decorative  Needlework.     16mo.     Is.  6d. 

LANE'S  (E.  W.)  Arabian  Nights.     Translated  with  Explanatory 

Notes.    With  Woodcuts.    Royal  8vo.    21s. 

LATIN   GRAMMAR  (KING  EDWARD  THE  Vim's.)     For  the  Use 

of  Schools.    Eighth  Edition.    12mo.    3*.  6d. 

-  First  Book  (KING  EDWARD  VI.)  ;"•"  or,  the  Accidence, 
Syntax,  and  Prosody,  with  English  Translation  for  Junior  Classes. 
Second  Edition.  12mo.  2s. 

LA  YARD'S  (AUSTEN  H.)   Nineveh    and  its  Remains.     Being  a 

Narrative  of  Researches  and  Discoveries  amidst  the  Ruins  of  Assyria. 
With  an  Account  of  the  Chaldean  Christians  of  Kurdistan ;  the  Yezedis, 
or  Devil-worshippers ;  and  an  Enquiry  into  the  Manners  and  Arts  of 
the  Ancient  Assyrians.  Sixth  Edition.  Plates  and  Woodcuts.  2  Vols. 
8vo.  36s. 

Nineveh  and  Babylon ;  being  the  Result 


of  a  Second  Expedition  to  Assyria.    Fourteenth  Thousand.    Plates  and 
Woodcuts.    8vo.    21s.    Or  Fine  Paper.    2  Vols.    8vo.    30s. 

•    Popular  Account  of  Nineveh.    15th  Edition.     With 
Woodcuts.    Post  8vo.    5s. 

Monuments  of  Nineveh.    Illustrated  by  One  Hundred 

Engravings.   Imperial  Folio,  10Z.  10s. 

Second  Series.    Illustrated  by 


Seventy  Plates.    Imperial  Folio.    10Z.  10s. 

LEAKE'S  (CoL.  W.  MARTIN)  Topography  of  Athens,  with  Remarks 
on  its  Antiquities;  to  which  is  added,  the  Demi  of  Attica.  Second 
Edition.  Plates.  2  Vols.  8vo.  30s. 

—  Travels  in  Northern  Greece.    Maps.    4  Vols.  8vo.     60s. 

-  Greece  at  the  End  of  Twenty-three  Years  Protection. 

8vo.    6d. 

Peloponnesiaca :  A  Supplement  to  Travels  in  the  Morea. 


8vo.    15s. 


—  Thoughts  on  the  Degradation  of  Science  in  England. 

8vo.    3s.  6d. 


22  LIST  OF  WORKS 


LESLIE'S  (C.  R.)  Handbook  for  Young  Painters.    "With  Illustra- 
tions.   Post  3vo.    10s.  Qd. 

LETTERS  FROM  THE  SHORES   OF   THE  BALTIC.      By  a 
LADY.    Post  8vo.   2s.  6d. 

-    Madras ;     or,  First  Impressions  of  Life  and 
Manners  in  India.    By  a  LADY.    Post  8vo.    2s.  Qd. 

Sierra  Leone,  written  to    Friends  at  Home. 


By  a  LADY.    Edited  by  Mrs.  NOKTON.    Post  8vo.    5s. 

LEWIS'  (G.  CORNEWALL)  Essay  on  the  Government  of  Dependencies. 

8vo.    12*. 

-  Glossary  of  Provincial  Words  used  in  Herefordshire  and 

some  of  the  adjoining  Counties.    12mo.    4a.  6d. 

Essay  on  the   Origin  and  Formation  of   the   Romance 

Languages :  Second  Edition.    8vo.    12«. 

(LADY   THERESA)  Friends    and   Contemporaries'  of   the 

Lord  Chancellor  Clarendon,  illustrative  of  Portraits  in  his  Gallery. 
With  an  Introduction,  containing  a  Descriptive  Catalogue  of  the  Pictures, 
and  an  Account  of  the  Origin  of  the  Collection.  Portraits.  3  Vols. 
8vo.  42s. 

(M.  G.)  Journal  of  a  Residence  among  the  Negroes  in  the 

West  Indies.    Post  8vo.    2s.  Qd. 

LEXINGTON  (THE)  PAPERS;  or,  Some  Account  of  the  Courts 
of  London  and  Vienna  at  the  end  of  the  17th  Century.  Extracted  from 
Official  and  Private  Correspondence,  1694-1698.  Edited  by  HON.  H. 
MANNERS  SDTTON.  8vo.  14s. 

LIDDELL'S  (H.  G.)  History  of  the  Republic  of  Rome.  From  the 
close  of  the  Second  Punic  War  to  the  death  of  Sylla.  2  Vols.  8vo.  In 
Preparation. 

School  History  of  Rome.     From  the  Earliest  Times  to 

the  Establishment  of  the  Empire.    Woodcuts.    PostSvo.    7s.  Qd. 

LINDSAY'S   (LORD)  Sketches  of  the  History  of  Christian  Art. 

3Vols.8vo.    31s.  6d. 

—  Lives  of  the  Lindsays ;  or,  a  Memoir  of  the  Houses 

of  Crawford  and  Balcarres.  To  which  are  added,  Extracts  from  the 
Official  Correspondence  of  Alexander,  sixth  Earl  of  Balcarres,  during 
the  Maroon  War ;  together  with  Personal  Narratives,  by  his  Brothers, 
the  Hon.  Robert,  Colin,  James,  John,  and  Hugh  Lindsay;  and  by  his 
Sister,  Lady  Anne  Barnard.  3  Vols.  8vo.  42s. 

Progression  by  Antagonism.      A  Theory,  involving 

Considerations  touching  the  Present  Position,  Duties,  and  Destiny  of 
Great  Britain.    8vo.   6s. 

(Rev.  HENRY)  Practical  Lectures  on  the  Historical 

Books  of  the  Old  Testament.    2  Vols.  16mo.    10s. 

LITTLE  ARTHUR'S   HISTORY    OF    ENGLAND.     By  LADY 

CALLCOTT.    Seventeenth  Edition.    18mo.    2s.  Qd. 

LIYONIAN  TALES.— The  Disponent.— The  Wolves.— The  Jewess. 

By  the  Author  of  "  Letters  from  the  Baltic."    Post  8vo.     2s.  6d. 
LOCKHART'S  (J.  G.)  Ancient  Spanish  Ballads.   New  Edition,  with 
Illuminated  Titles,  Borders,  &c.  4to.  Or  Cheap  Edition.  PostSvo.  2s.  Qd. 
-  Life  of  Robert  Burns.  Fifth  Edition.  Fcap.  8vo.  3s. 

- — History  of  the  Late  War :  with  Sketches  of  Nelson, 

Wellington,  and  Napoleon.    18mo.    2s.  Qd. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY.  23 


LOUDON'S  (MRS.)  Ladies'  Gardener;  or,  Instructions  in  Gardening. 
With  Directions  for  Every  Month  in  the  Year,  and  a  Calendar  of 
Operations.  Eighth  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  5s. 

—  Modern  Botany  for  Ladies ;  or,  a  Popular  Introduction 
to  the  Natural  System  of  Plants.  Second  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.6s. 

LOWE'S  (SiR  HUDSON)  Letters  and  Journals,  during  the  Captivity 
of  Napoleon  at  St.  Helena.  By  WILLIAM  FOESYTH.  Portrait.  3  Vols. 
8vo.  45s. 

LTELL'S  (SiR  CHARLES)  Principles  of  Geology;  or,  the  Modern 
Changes  of  the  Earth  and  its  Inhabitants  considered  as  illustrative  of 
Geology.  Ninth  Edition.  Woodcuts.  8vo.  18s. 

Manual  of  Elementary  Geology ;  or,  the  Ancient  Changes 

of  the  Earth  and  its  Inhabitants  illustrated  by  its  Geological  Monuments. 
Fifth  Edition.    Woodcuts.    8vo. 

Travels  in  North  America,  1841-2;  with  Observations  on 

the  United  States,  Canada,  and  Nova  Scotia.  Plates.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo. 

Second  Visit  to  the  United  States  of  North  America, 

1845-6.    2  Vols.    PostSvo. 

MAHON'S  (LORD)  History  of  England,  from  the  Peace  of  Utrecht 
to  the  Peace  of  Versailles,  1713—83.  Third  Edition.  7  Vols.  8vo. 
93s. ;  or,  Popular  Edition.  7  Vols.  Post  8vo.  42s. 

-  "Forty-Five;"    or,  a  Narrative  of  the  Rebellion  in 
Scotland.   PostSvo.    3s. 

-  History  of  the  War  of  the  Succession  in  Spain.    Second 

Edition.    Map.    8vo.    15s. 

Spain  under  Charles  the  Second ;  or,  Extracts  from  the 
Correspondence  of  the  Hon.  ALEXANDER  STANHOPE,  British  Minister  at 
Madrid  from  1690  to  1700.  Second  Edition.  Post  8vo.  6s.  6d. 

Life  of  Louis  Prince  of  Conde",  surnamed  the  Great. 
Post  8vo.  5s. 

Life  of  Belisarius.    Second  Edition.    Post  8vo.  10s.  Qd. 

Historical  and  Critical  Essays.     Post  8vo.    5s. 
-  Story  of  Joan  of  Arc.    Fcap.  8vo.     Is. 
M'CULLOCH'S  (J.  R.) ;  Collected  Edition  of  RICARDO'S  Political 

Works.    With  Notes  and  Memoir.    Second  Edition.    8vo.  16s. 

MALCOLM'S    (SiR  JOHN)  Sketches  of  Persia.      Third  Edition. 

PostSvo.    5s. 

MANTELL'S  (GIDEON  A.)  Thoughts  on  Animalcules;  or,  the 
Invisible  World,  as  revealed  by  the  Microscope.  Second  Edition.  Plates. 
16mo.  6s. 

MANUAL  OF  SCIENTIFIC  ENQUIRY,  Prepared  for  the  Use  of 

Officers  and  Travellers  in  general.  By  various  Writers.  Edited  by  SIB 
J.  HERSCHEL,  Bart.  Second  Edition.  Maps.  Post  8vo.  10s.  6d.  (Pub- 
lished by  order  of  the  Lords  of  the  Admiralty) 

MARKHAM'S  (MRS.)  History  of  England.  From  the  First  Inva- 
sion by  the  Romans,  down  to  the  fourteenth  year  of  Queen  Victoria's 
Reign.  68th  Edition.  Woodcuts.  12mo.  6s. 

-  History  of  France.    From  the  Conquest  by  the  Gauls, 
to  the  Death  of  Louis  Philippe.   30th  Edition.    Woodcuts.    12mo.    6s. 


LIST  OF  WOEKS 


MAEKH AM'S  History  of  Germany.    From  the  Invasion  by  Marius, 

to  the  present  time.     6th  Edition.    Woodcuts.  12mo.  6s. 

-  History  of  Greece.  With  Chapters  on  the  Literature, 
Art,  and  Domestic  Manners  of  the  Greeks.  By  Dr.  WM.  SMITH. 
6th  Edition.  Woodcuts.  12mo.  Is.  6d. 

History  of  Eome  from  the  Earliest  Times  to  the 


Establishment  of  the  Empire.    By  H.  G.  LIDDELL,  M.A.     Woodcuts 
12mo.    Is.  6d. 

-  Sermons  for  Children.  Second  Edition.  Fcap.Svo.  3s. 

MAEKLAND'S  (J.  H.)  Eemarks  on  English  Churches,  and  Sepul- 
chral Memorials.  Fourth  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.Svo.  6s.  6d. 

-  Eeverence  due  to  Holy  Places.      Third  Edition. 
Fcap.  8vo.    2s. 

MAEEYAT'S   (JOSEPH)  History  of  Pottery  and  Porcelain,  in  the 
15th,  16th,  17th,  and  18th  Centuries.     With  a  Description  of  the  Manu- 
facture, a  Glossary,  and  a  List  of  Monograms.    With  Coloured  Plates 
and  Woodcuts.   8vo.  31s.  6d. 
%*  A  few  copies  on  India  Proofs,  mounted  on  Large  Paper.    4to.    51. 5s. 

MATTHIAS  (AUGUSTUS)  Greek  Grammar  for  Schools.  Abridged 
from  the  Larger  Grammar.  By  Blomfield.  8th  Edition.  Revised  hy 
EDWAEDS.  12mo.  3s. 

-  Greek    Accidence    for    Schools.       Abridged    by 
BLOMFIELD.  Fourth  Edition,  revised  by  EDWAEDS.  12mo.  2s. 

MAUEEL'S  (JULES)  Essay  on  the  Character,  Actions,  and  Writings 

of  the  Duke  of  Wellington.    Second  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo.    Is.  6d. 

MAWE'S  (H.  L.)  Journal  of  a  Passage  from  the  Pacific  to  the 
Atlantic,  crossing  the  Andes  in  the  Northern  Provinces  of  Peru,  and 
descending  the  great  River  Maranon.  8vo.  12s. 

MAXIMS  AND  HINTS  for  an  Angler,  and  the  Miseries  of 
Fishing.  By  RICHAED  PENN.  Second  Edition.  Woodcuts.  12mo.  5s. 

MAYO'S  (DR.)  Pathology  of  the  Human  Mind.   Fcap.    8vo.  5s.  6d. 

MELVILLE'S  (HERMANN)  Typee  and  Omoo;  or,  Adventures 
amongst  the  Marquesas  and  South  Seas.  2  Vols.  Post  8vo.  10*. 

MENDELSSOHN'S  (FELIX  BARTHOLDY)  Life.    By  JULES  BENEDICT. 

8vo.    2s.  6d. 

MEEEIFIELD   (MRS.)  on  the  Arts  of  Painting  in  Oil,  Miniature, 

Mosaic,  and  Glass  ;  Gilding,  Dyeing,  and  the  Preparation  of  Colours 
and  Artificial  Gems,  described  in  several  old  Manuscripts.  2  Vols.  8vo. 
30*. 

MEEEDITH'S  (MRS.  CHARLES)  Notes  and  Sketches  of  New  South 
Wales,  during  a  Residence  from  1839  to  1844.  Post  8vo.  2s.  6d. 

Tasmania,  during  a  Eesidence  of  Nine  Years.   With 

Illustrations.    2  Vols.  Post  8vo.    18s.. 

MILFOED'S  (JOHN)  Norway  and  her  Laplanders  in  1841 ;  with  a 
Few  Hints  to  the  Salmon  Fisher.  8vo.  10s.  6d. 

MITCHELL'S  (THOMAS)  Plays  of  Aristophanes.  With  English 
Notes.  8vo.— 1. CLOUDS,  10s— 2.  WASPS,  10s.— 3.  FROGS,  15s. 

MODEEN  DOMESTIC  COOKEEY.  Founded  on  Principles  of 
Economy  and  Practical  Knowledge,  and  adapted  for  Private  Families. 
New  and  Cfaaper  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  5s. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY. 


25 


MILMAN'S  (DEAN)  History  of  Christianity,  from  the  Birth  of 
Christ  to  the  Extinction  of  Paganism  in  the  Roman  Empire.  3  Vols. 
8vo.  36s. 

— History  of  Latin  Christianity;   including  that  of  the 
Popes  to  the  Pontificate  of  Nicholas  V.  6  Vols.  8vo.  Vols.  I.  to  III.  36s. 

Character  and  Conduct'of  the  Apostles  considered  as 


an  Evidence  of  Christianity.  8vo.  10s.  6d. 
Life  and  Correspondence  of  Edward    Gibbon.    Portrait. 

8vo.   9s. 

-  Life  and  Works   of  Horace.     With  300  Woodcuts. 

New  Edition.    2  Vols.     Crown  8vo.    30s. 

-  Poetical  Works.    Plates.     3  Yols.    Fcap.  8vo.     18s. 

-  Fall  of  Jerusalem.     Fcap.  8vo.  Is. 

MILMAN'S  (CAPT.  E.  A.)  Wayside  Cross ;  or,  the  Raid  of  Gomez. 

A  Tale  of  the  C artist  War.    Post  8vo.    2s.  Gd. 
MONASTERY  AND  THE  MOUNTAIN  CHURCH.   By  Author 

of  "  Sunlight  through  the  Mist."    Woodcuts.    16mo.    4s. 

MOLTKE'S  (BARON)  Russian  Campaigns  on  the  Danube  and  the 
Passage  of  the  Balkan,  1828— 9.  Plans.  8vo.  14s. 

MOORE'S  (THOMAS)  Life  and  Letters  of  Lord  Byron.  Plates. 
6  Vols.  Fcap.  8vo.  18s. ;  or,  One  Volume.  Royal  8vo.  12s. 

MUCK  MANUAL  (The)  for  the  Use  of  Farmers.  A  Practical  Treatise 
on  the  Chemical  Properties,  Management,  and  Application  of  Manures. 
By  FREDERICK  FALKNER.  Second  Edition.  Fcap.  8vo.  5s. 

MUNDY'S  (CAPT.  RODNEY)  Events  in  Borneo,  including  the  Occu- 
pation of  Labuan  and  Visit  to  the  Celebes.  Plates.  2  Vols.  8vo.  32s. 

MUNRO'S  (GENERAL  SIR  THOMAS)  Life  and  Letters.  By  the  REV. 
G.  R.  GLEIG.  Post  8vo.  5s. 

MURCHISON'S  (SiR  RODERICK)  Russia  in  Europe  and  the  Ural 
Mountains;  Geologically  Illustrated.  With  Coloured  Maps,  Plates, 
Sections,  &c.  2  Vols.  Royal  4to.  81. 8s. 

Siluria  ;  or,  a  History  of  the  Oldest  Rocks  con- 
taining Organic  Remains.  With  Map' and  Plates.  8vo.  30s. 

MURRAY'S  (CAPT.  A.)  Naval  Life  and  Services  of  Admiral  Sir 

Philip  Durham.    8vo.    5s.  6d. 

MURRAY'S  RAILWAY  READING.  Published  occasionally; 
varying  in  size  and  price,  and  suited  for  all  classes  of  Readers. 

[The  following  are  published i\ 


WELLINGTON.  By  LORD  ELLBSMERK.   6rf. 

NlMRODONTHE    CHASE,  1*. 

ESSAYS  FROM  "THE  TIMES."  2  Vols.  8s. 

Music  AND  DRESS.    Is. 

LA  YARD'S  POPULAR  ACCOUNT  OF  NINEVEH. 

MILMAN'S  FALL  OF  JERUSALEM.    Is. 

MAHON'S  " FORTY-FIVE.."    3s. 

LIFE  OF  THEODORE  HOOK.    Is. 

DEEDS  OF  NAVAL  DARING.    2  Vols.    5s. 

THE  HONEY  BEE.    Is. 

JAMES'  ^SOP'S  FABLKS.    2s.  fid. 

NlMROD    ON    THE    TURF.      Is.  (></. 

OLIPHANT'S  NEPAUL.    2s.  6d. 
ABT  OP  DINING.    1«.  6d. 


HALLAM'S  LITERARY  ESSAYS.    2s. 
MAHON'S  JOAN  OF  ARC.    Is. 
HEAD'S  EMIGRANT.    2s.  6<J. 

NlMROD    ON    THE  ROAD.   Is. 

WILKINSON'S  ANCIENT  EGYPTIANS.    12s. 

CROKER  ON  THE  GUILLOTINE.    Is. 

HOLLWAY'S  NORWAY.    2s. 

MAURKL'S  WELLINGTON.    ls.6d. 

CAMPBELL'S  LIFE  OF  BACON.    2s. 

THE  FLOWER  GARDEN,  Is. 

LOCKU  ART'S  SPANISH  BALLADS.    2s.  Gd. 

LUCAS  ON  HISTORY.    6rf. 

BEAUTIES  OF  BYRON.    3s. 

TAYLOR'S  NOTES  FROM  LIFE.    2s. 

REJECTED  ADDRESSES.    Is. 


26  LIST  OF  WORKS 


MUSIC  AND  DRESS.  Two  Essays  by  a  Lady.  Reprinted  from 
the  "  Quarterly  Review."  Fcap.  Svo.  Is. 

NAUTICAL   ALMANACK   (The).     (Published  by  Order  of  the 

Lords  Commissioners  of  the  Admiralty.)    Royal  Svo.    2s.  Qd. 

NAVY  LIST  (The  Royal).  (Published  Quarterly,  by  Authority.) 
12mo.  2s.  6d. 

NEWBOLD'S  (LIEUT.)  Straits  of  Malacca,  Penang,  and  Singapore. 

2Vols.8vo.    26s. 

NICHOLLS'  (SiR  GEORGE)  History  of  the  English  Poor  Law  :  in 
connection  with  the  Condition  of  the  People.  2  Vols.  Svo.  28s. 

NIMROD  On  the  Chace— The  Turf—and  The  Road.    Reprinted 

from  the  "  Quarterly  Review."    Woodcuts.    Fcap.  Svo.    3s.  Qd. 

NORTON'S  (HoN.  CAROLINE)  Letters  from  Sierra  Leone,  to  Friends 
at  Home.  By  a  LADY.  Edited  by  Mrs.  NOBTON.  Post  Svo.  5s. 

O'BYRNE'S  (W.  R.)  Naval  Biographical  Dictionary,  comprising 
the  Life  and  Services  of  every  Living  Officer  in  H.  M.  Navy,  from  the 
Rank  of  Admiral  to  that  of  Lieutenant.  Compiled  from  Authentic  and 
Family  Documents.  Royal  Svo.  42s. 

O'CONNOR'S  (R.)  Field  Sports  of  France ;  or,  Hunting,  Shooting, 
and  Fishing  on  the  Continent.  Woodcuts.  12mo.  7s.  Qd. 

OLIPHANT'S  (LAURENCE)  Journey  to  Katmandu,  with  Visit  to 
the  Camp  of  the  Nepaulese  Ambassador.  Fcap.  Svo.  2s.  Qd. 

OXENHAM'S  (REY.  W.)  English  Notes  for  Latin  Elegiacs  ;  designed 

for  early  Proficients  in  the  Art  of  Latin  Versification,  with  Prefatory 
Rules  of  Composition  in  Elegiac  Metre.  Second  Edition.  12mo.  4s. 

PAGET'S  (JOHN)  Hungary  and  Transylvania.  "With  Remarks  on 
their  Condition,  Social,  Political,  and  Economical.  Third  and  Cheaper 
Edition.  Woodcuts.  2  Vols.  Svo.  18s. 

PARISH'S  (SiR  WOODBINE)  Buenos  Ayres  and  the  Provinces  of  the 
Rio  de  la  Plata.  Their  First  Discovery  and  Conquest,  Present  State, 
Trade,  Debt,  &c.  Second  Edition.  Map  and  Woodcuts.  Svo.  15s. 

PARIS'S  (T.  C.)  Letters  from  the  Pyrenees  during  Three  Months' 
Pedestrian  Wanderings  amidst  the  Wildest  Scenes  of  the  French  and 
Spanish  Pyrenees.  Woodcuts.  Post  Svo.  10s.  Qd. 

PARKYNS'  (MANSFIELD)  Personal  Narrative  of  Three  Years'  Resi- 
dence and  Adventures  in  Abyssinia.  Woodcuts.  2  Vols.  Svo.  30s. 

PEILE'S  (REV.  DR.)  Agamemnon  of  JEschylus.     A  New  Edition 

of  the  Text,  with  Notes,  Critical,  Explanatory,  and  Philological,  for 
the  Use  of  Students.  Second  Edition.  Svo.  9s. 

Choephorae  of  JEschylus.    A  New  Edition  of  the  Text, 

with  Notes,  Critical,  Explanatory,  and  Philological,  for  the  Use  of 
Students.  Second  Edition.  8vo.  9s. 

PELLEW'S  (DEAN  OF  NORWICH)  Life  of  Lord  Sidmouth,  with 
his  Correspondence.  Portraits.  3  Vols.  Svo,  42s. 

PENN'S  (RICHARD)  Maxims  and  Hints  for  an  Angler,  and  the 
Miseries  of  Fishing.  To  which  is  added,  Maxims  and  Hints  for  a 
Chess-player.  Second  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fca'p.  8vo.  5s. 

—  (GRANVILLE)  Bioscope ;  or,  Dial  of  Life  Explained.     To 

which  is  added,  a  Translation  of  St.  Paulinus'  Epistle  to  Celantia,  on 
the  Rule  of  Christian  Life ;  and  an  Elementary  View  of  General  Chro- 
nology. Second  Edition.  With  Dial  Plate.  12mo.  12s. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY.  27 


PENROSE'S  (REV.  JOHN)  Lives  of  Vice-Admiral  Sir  C.  V.  Penrose, 
and  Captain  James  Trevenen.  Portraits.  Svo.  10s.  6d. 

-  (F.  C.)  Principles  of  Athenian  Architecture,  and  the 

Optical  Refinements  exhibited  in  the  Construction  of  the  Ancient 
Buildings  at  Athens,  from  a  Survey.  With  40  Plates.  Eolio.  51. 5s. 
(Published  under  the  direction  of  the  Dilettanti  Society.) 

PERRY'S  (SiR  ERSKINE)  Bird's-Eye  Yiew  of  India.  With  Extracts 
from  a  Journal  kept  in  the  Provinces,  Nepaul,  &c.  Fcap.  Svo. 

PHILLIPS'  (JOHN)  Memoirs  of  William  Smith,  LL.D.,  (the  Geo- 
logist). Portrait.  Svo.  7s.  6d. 

Geology  of  Yorkshire.     The  Yorkshire  Coast,  and  the 

Mountain-Limestone  District.    Plates  4to.    Part  I.,  31s.  6d.— Part  II., 
52s.  6d. 

The  Rivers,  Mountains,  and  Sea  Coast  of  Yorkshire. 

With  Essays  on  the  Climate,  Scenery,  and  Ancient  Inhabitants  of  the 
Country.  Second  Edition,  with  36  Plates.  Svo.  15s. 

PHILOSOPHY  IN  SPORT  MADE  SCIENCE  IN  EARNEST  ; 

or,  the  First  Principles  of  Natural  Philosophy  inculcated  by  aid  of  the  Toys 
and  Sports  of  Youth.  Seventh  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  Svo.  7s.  Qd. 

PHILPOTT'S  (BISHOP)  Letters  to  the  late  Charles  Butler,  on  the 

Theological  parts  of  his  "  Book  of  the  Roman  Catholic  Church  ; "  with 
Remarks  on  certain  Works  of  Dr.  Milner  and  Dr.  Lingard,  and  on  some 
parts  of  the  Evidence  of  Dr.  Doyle.  Second  Edition.  Svo.  16s. 

PHIPPS'  (HoN.  EDMUND)  Memoir,  Correspondence,  Literary  and 
Unpublished  Diaries  of  Robert  Plumer  Ward.  Portrait.  2Vols.  Svo.  28s. 

POOLE'S  (R.  S.)  Horae  Egyptiacse  ;  or,  the  Chronology  of  Ancient 
Egypt,  discovered  from  Astronomical  and  Hieroglyphic  Records  upon 
its  Monuments.  Plates.  Svo.  10s.  6d. 

(REV.  G.  A.)  Handbook  for  the  Cathedrals  of  England. 

Containing  Descriptions  of  each.    Woodcuts.    Post  Svo.   In  Preparation. 

POPE'S  (ALEXANDER)  WORKS.  An  entirely  New  Edition.  Edited 
by  the  Right  Hon.  JOHN  WILSON  CBOKEB  assisted  by  PETEB  CUNNING- 
HAM, F.S.A.  Svo.  In  the  Press. 

PORTER'S  (G.  R.)  Progress  of  the  Nation,  in  its  various  Social  and 
Economical  Relations,  from  the  beginning  of  the  Nineteenth  Century. 
Tfiird  Edition.  Svo.  24s. 

-  (MRS.  G.R.)  Rational  Arithmetic  for  Schools  and  for 
Private  Instruction.    12mo.    3s.  6d. 

POWELL'S  (REV.  W-P.^Latin  Grammar  simplified.    12mo.  Bs.  6d. 

PRAYER-BOOK  (THE),  Illuminated  with  1000  Illustrations  of  Bor- 
ders, Initials,  Vignettes,  &c.    Medium  Svo.    Cloth,  21s.;  Calf,  31s.  6d. 
Morocco,  42s. 

PROGRESS  OF  RUSSIA  IN  THE  EAST,  An  Historical  Sum- 
mary, continued  to  the  Present  Time.  With  Map  by  AKBOWSMITH. 
Third  Edition.  Svo.  6s.  6d. 

QUARTERLY  REVIEW  (THE).    Svo.    6s. 

RANKE'S  (LEOPOLD)  Political  and  Ecclesiastical  History  of  the 
Popes  of  Rome,  during  the  Sixteenth  and  Seventeenth  Centuries.  Trans- 
lated from  the  German  by  MRS.  AUSTIN.  Third  Edition.  2  Vols.  Svo.  24s. 


28  LIST  OF  WORKS 


RAWLINSON'S  (REV.  GEORGE)  Herodotus.  A  New  English 
Version.  Translated  from  the  Text  of  GAISFORD,  and  Edited  with 
Notes,  illustrating  the  History  and  Geography  of  Herodotus,  from  the 
most  recent  sources  of  information,  embodying  the  chief  Results, 
Historical  and  Ethnographical,  which  have  been  arrived  at  in  the  pro- 
gress of  Cuneiform  and  Hieroglyphical  Discovery.  Assisted  by  COLONEL 
RAWLINSON,  and  SIR  J.  G.  WILKINSON.  4  Vols.  8vo.  In  Preparation. 

REJECTED  ADDRESSES  (THE).     By  JAMES  AND  HORACE  SMITH. 

With  Biographies  of  the  Authors,  and  additional  Notes.  New  Edition, 
with  the  Author's  latest  Corrections.  Portraits.  Fcap.  8vo.  Is.,  or  on 
Fine  Paper.  With  Portrait  and  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  5s. 

RICARDO'S    (DAVID)    Political   Works.    With  a  Notice  of  his 

Life  and  Writings.    By  J.  R.  M'CuLLOCH.    New  Edition.    8vo.    16s. 

RIPA'S  (FATHER)  Memoirs  during  Thirteen  Years'  Residence  at  the 
Court  of  Peking,  in  the  Service  of  the  Emperor  of  China.  Translated 
from  the  Italian.  By  FORTUNATO  PRANDI.  Post  8vo.  2s.  Qd. 

ROBERTSON'S  (REV.  J.  C.)  History  of  the  Christian  Church,  to 
the  Pontificate  of  Gregory  the  Great :  a  Manual  for  general  Readers  as 
well  as  for  Students  in  Theology.  8vo.  12s. 

ROBINSON'S  (EDWD.,  D.D.)  Biblical  Researches  in  the  Holy  Land. 

A  New  and  Revised  Edition.  With  Maps.  2  Vols.  8vo.  In  Preparation. 

—  Later  Biblical  Researches  in  the  Holy  Land  in  the 
in  the  year  1852.    Maps.    8vo.    In  Preparation. 

ROMILLY'S  (SiR  SAMUEL)  Memoirs  and  Political  Diary.     By  his 

SONS.     Third  Edition.    Portrait.    2  Vols.  Fcap.  8vo.    12s. 

ROSS'S  (SiR  JAMES)  Voyage  of  Discovery  and  Research  in  the 
Southern  and  Antarctic  Regions  during  the  years  1839-43.  Plates. 
2Vols.8vo.  36s. 

ROYAL  SOCIETY  OF  LITERATURE  (THE).  TRANSACTIONS. 
Plates.  Vols.  I.  to  III.  8vo.  12s.  each. 

RUNDELL'S  (MRS.)  Domestic   Cookery,    founded    on  Principles 

of  Economy  and  Practice,  and  adapted  for  Private  Families.  New  and 
Cheaper  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Fcap.  8vo.  5s. 

RUXTON'S  (GEORGE  F.)  Travels  in  Mexico;  with  Adventures 
among  the  Wild  Tribes  and  Animals  of  the  Prairies  and  Rocky  Moun- 
tains. PostSvo.  5s. 

SALE'S  (LADY)  Journal  of  the  Disasters  in  Affghanistan.     Eighth 

Edition.    PostSvo.    12s. 

(SiR  ROBERT)  Brigade  in  Affghanistan.  With  an  Account  of 

the  Seizure  and  Defence  of  Jellalabad.  ByREv.G.R.GLEio.  Post  8vo.2s.6d. 

SCROPE'S  (WILLIAM)  Days  of  Deer-Stalking  in  the  Forest  of  Atholl ; 
with  some  Account  of  the  Nature  and  Habits  of  the  Red  Deer.  Third 
Edition.  Woodcuts.  Crown  8vo.  20s. 

—  Days  and  Nights  of  Salmon  Fishing  in  the  Tweed ; 

with  a  short  Account  of  the  Natural  History  and  Habits  of  the  Salmon. 
Second  Edition.  Woodcuts.  Royal  8vo. 


(G-.  p.)  Memoir  of  Lord  Sydenham,  and  his  Administra- 
tion in  Canada.  Second  Edition.  Portrait.  8vo.  9s.  Qd. 

SENTENCES  FROM  THE  PROVERBS.  In  English,  French, 
Italian,  and  German.  For  the  Daily  Use  of  Young  Persons.  By  A  LADY. 
16mo.  3s.  6d. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY.  29 


SEYMOUR'S  (H.  DANBY)  Account  of  the  Crimea  and  the  Shores 
of  the  Sea  of  Azoff.    Map.    8vo. 

SHAW'S  (THOS.  B.)  Outlines  of  English  Literature,  for  the  Use  of 

Young  Students.    Post  8vo.    12s. 

SIDMOUTH'S  (LORD)  Life  and  Correspondence.    By  the  HON.  and 
REV.  GEOEGE  PELLEW,  DEAN  OF  NORWICH.  Portraits.  3  Vols.  8vo.    42s. 

SIERRA  LEONE  ;  Described  in  a  Series  of  Letters  to  Friends  at 
Home.    By  A  LADY.    Edited  by  MRS.  NORTON.    Post  8vo.    5s. 

SMITH'S  (WM.,  LL.D.)  Dictionary  of  Greek   and  Roman  Anti- 

quities.   Second  Edition.    With  500  Woodcuts.    8vo.   42s. 

-  Smaller  Dictionary  of  Greek  and  Roman  Antiquities, 

Third  Edition.    With  200  Woodcuts.    Crown  8vo.    7s.  6d. 

—  Dictionary  of  Greek  and   Roman    Biography  and  My- 
thology.   With  500  Woodcuts.    3  Vols.    8vo.    51.  15s.  6d. 

-  Dictionary  of  Greek  and  Roman  Geography.   Woodcuts. 
Vol.  I.    8vo.    36s. 

-  -  New  Classical  Dictionary  for  Schools.    Compiled  from 

the  two  last  works.     Third  Edition.    8vo.  15s. 


Smaller  Classical  Dictionary.       Third  Edition.     With 


200  Woodcuts.  Crown  8vo.  7s.  Qd. 

—  New  Latin-English  Dictionary  for  Colleges  and  Schools. 

Medium.    8vo. 

—  Smaller  Latin-English  Dictionary.     Square  8vo. 

—  School  History  of  Greece ;  from  the  Earliest  Times  to 

the  Roman  Conquest,  with  Supplementary  Chapters  on  the  History  of 
Literature  and  Art.    Woodcuts.  •  Sixth  Edition.    Crown  8vo.    7s.  6d. 

-  School  History  of  Rome ;  from  the  Earliest  Times  to 
the  Establishment  of  the  Empire.    By  H.  G.  LIDDELL,  M.A.,  Head 
Master  of  Westminster  School.    Woodcuts.    Post  8vo.    7*.  6d. 

-  Edition  of  Gibbon's  Decline  and  Fall  of  the  Roman 
Empire.    With  Notes  by  MILMAN  and  GUIZOT.     Portrait  and  Map. 
8  Vols.    8vo.    60s. 

(WM.  JAS.)  Grenville   Letters  and  Diaries,  including 

MR.  GRENVILLE'S  DIARY  OF  POLITICAL  EVENTS,  while  First  Lord  of 
the  Treasury.    Edited  with  Notes.    4  Vols.     8vo.    64s. 

(JAMES  &  HORACE)  Rejected  Addresses.      Twenty-third 

Edition,  with  Author's  latest  corrections.    Fcap.  8vo.    [Is.,  or  on  Fine 
Paper.  With  Portrait  and  Woodcuts.    Fcap  8vo.    5s. 

SOMERVILLE'S  (MART)    Physical   Geography.      Third  Edition. 
Portrait.    2  Vols.    Fcap.  8vo.    12s. 

Connexion    of   the   Physical    Sciences.      Eighth 

Edition.    Plates.    Fcap.  8vo.    10s.  6d. 

SOUTHEY'S  (ROBERT)  Book  of  the  Church ;  with  Notes  contain- 
ing the  Authorities,  and  an  Index.    Sixth  Edition.  8vo.  12s. 

Lives  of  John  Bunyan  &  Oliver  Cromwell.  Post  8vo.  2*.6d. 


30  LIST  OF  WORKS 


SPECKTER'S  (OTTO)   Charmed  Roe;   or,  the  Story  of  the  Little 
Brother  and  Sister.  Illustrated.    16mo.    5s. 

STANLEY'S  (EDWARD,  D.D.,  Bp.  of   Norwich)    ADDRESSES   AND 

CHARGES.    With  a  Memoir  of  his  Life.    By  His  SON.    Second  Edition. 
8vo.    10s.  6d. 

-  (ARTHUR  P.)  Commentary  on  St.  Paul's  Epistles  to 
the  Corinthians,  with  Notes  and  Dissertations.  2  Vols.  8vo.  In  the 
Press. 

-  Historical  Memoirs  of  Canterbury.     The  Landing  of 
Augustine— The  Murder  of  Becket— The  Black  Prince— The  Shrine  of 
Becket.    Woodcuts.    8vo.    Is.  6d. 

-  Sinai    and    Palestine.      In   Connexion    with  their 

History.    Map.    8vo. 

ST.  JOHN'S  (CHARLES)  Field  Notes  of  a  Sportsman  and  Naturalist 

in  Sutherland.    Woodcuts.    2  Vols.    Post  8vo.    18s. 


Post  8vo.    5s. 


Wild  Sports  and  Natural  History  of  the  Highlands. 


—  (BATLE)  Adventures  in  the  Libyan  Desert  and  the 

Oasis  of  Jupiter  Ammon.    Woodcuts.    Post  8vo.    2s.  Qd . 

STISTED'S  (MRS.  HENRY)  Letters  from  the  Bye- Ways  of  Italy. 

Plates.    8vo.    18s. 

STOTHARD'S  (Tnos.,  R.  A.)  Life.     With  Personal  Reminiscences. 

By  Mrs.  BRAY.     With  Portrait,  and  60  Woodcuts.    4to.    21s. 

STRIFE  FOR  THE  MASTERY.  Two  Allegories.  With  Illus- 
trations. Crown  8vo.  6s. 

SUNLIGHT  THROUGH  THE  MIST;  or,  Practical  Lessons 
drawn  from  the  Lives  of  Good  Men,  intended  as  a  Sunday  Book  for 
Children.  By  A  LADY.  Second  Edition.  16mo.  3s.  6d. 

SUTTON  (HoN.  H.  MANNERS).      Some  Account  of  the  Courts  of 

London  and  Vienna,  at  the  end  of  the  Seventeenth  Century,  extracted 
from  the  Official  and  Private  Correspondence  of  Robert  Sutton  (late 
Lord  Lexington)  while  British  Minister  at  Vienna,  1694-98.  8vo.  14s. 

SWIFT'S  (JONATHAN)  Works.  New  Edition,  based  upon  Sir 
Walter  Scott's  Edition,  entirely  revised.  8vo.  In  Preparation. 

SYDENHAM'S  (LORD)  Memoirs.  With  his  Administration  in 
Canada.  By  G.PouLETScROPE,M.P.  Second  Edition.  Portrait.  8vo.  9s.6d 

TALBOT'S  (H.  Fox)  English  Etymologies.    8vo.    12s. 
TAYLOR'S    (HENRY)   Notes    from    Life.      Post  8vo.     6s.;    or, 

Cheop  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo.    2s. 

—  Notes  from  Books.     Third  Edition.    Post  8vo.     9s. 

—  (J.  E.)  Fairy  Ring.    A  Collection  of  Stories  for  Young 
Persons.    From  the  German.    With  Illustrations  by  RICHARD  DOYLE. 
Second  Edition.    Woodcuts.    Fcap.  8vo.    7s.  6d. 

TENNENT'S  (Sin  J.  E.)  Christianity  in  Ceylon.  Its  Introduction 
and  Progress  under  the  Portuguese,  Dutch,  British,  and  American  Mis- 
sions. With  an  Historical  Sketch  of  the  Brahmanical  and  Buddhist 
Superstitions  Woodcuts.  8vo.  14s. 


PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY.  31 


THEEE-LEAVED  MANUAL  OF  FAMILY  PEAYEE  ;  arranged 

so  as  to  save  the  trouble  of  turning  the  Pages  backwards  and  forwards. 
Royal  8vo.     2s. 

THEESHOLD  (THE)  OF  LIFE.    A  Series  of  Letters  addressed  to 

a  Son  on  his  Entrance  into  the  -world.    Fcap.  8vo.    In  the  Press. 

TICKNOE'S  (GEORGE)  History  of  Spanish  Literature.  With  Criti- 
cisms on  particular  Works,  and  Biographical  Notices  of  Prominent 
Writers.  Second  and  Cheaper  Edition.  3  Vols.  8vo.  24s. 

TEEMENHEEEE'S  (H.  S.)  Political  Experience  of  the  Ancients, 
in  its  bearing  on  Modern  Times.  Fcap.  8vo.  2s.  Qd. 

Notes  on   Public  Subjects,  made  during  a 


Tour  in  the  United  States  and  Canada.    Post  8vo.    10s.  Qd. 

-  Constitution  of  the  United  States  compared 

with  our  own.    Post  8vo.    9s.  Qd. 

TUENBULL'S  (P.  E.)  Narrative  of  Travels  in  Austria,  with 
Remarks  on  its  Social  and  Political  Condition.  2  Vols.  8vo.  24s. 

TWISS'  (HORACE)  Public  and  Private  Life  of  Lord  Chancellor  Eldon, 
with  Selections  from  his  Correspondence.  Portrait.  Third  Edition  . 
2  Vols.  PostSvo.  21s. 

UBICINI'S  (M.  A.)  Letters  on  Turkey  and  its  Inhabitants—  the 
Moslems,  Greeks,  Armenians,  &c.  2  Vols.  PostSvo. 

VAUGHAN'S  (EEV.  DR.)  Sermons   preached  in  Harrow  School. 

8vo.    10s.  Qd. 

-  Nine  New  Sermons.     12mo.     5s. 

VAUX'S  (W.  S.  W.)  Handbook  to  the  Antiquities  in  the  British 
Museum;  being  a  Description  of  the  Remains  of  Greek,  Assyrian, 
Egyptian,  and  Etruscan  Art  preserved  there.  With  300  Woodcuts. 
Post  8vo.  Is.  Qd. 

VOYAGE  to  the  Mauritius  and  back,  touching  at  the  Cape  of  Good 
Hope,  and  St.  Helena.  By  Author  of  "  PADDIANA."  Post  8vo.  9s.  Qd. 

WAAGEN'S  (DR.)  Treasures  of  Art  in  Great  Britain.     Being  an 

Account  of  the  Chief  Collections  of  Paintings,  Sculpture,  Manuscripts, 
Miniatures,  &c.  &c.,  in  this  Country.  Obtained  from  Personal  Inspec- 
tion during  Visits  to  England.  3  Vols.  8vo.  36s. 

WADDINGTON'S  (DEAN)  The  Condition  and  Prospects  of  the 

Greek  Church.    New  Edition.    Fcap.  8vo.    3s.  6d. 

WAKEFIELD'S  (E.  J.)  Adventures  in  New  Zealand.  With 
some  Account  of  the  Beginning  of  the  British  Colonisation  of  the 
Island.  Map.  2  Vols.  8vo.  28s. 

WALKS  AND  TALKS.  A  Story-book  for  Young  Children.  By 
AUNT  IDA.  With  Woodcuts.  16mo.  5s. 

WAED'S  (EGBERT  PLUMER)  Memoir,  Correspondence,  Literary  and 
Unpublished  Diaries  and  Remains.  By  the  HON.  EDMUND  PHIPPS. 
Portrait.  2  Vols.  8vo.  28s. 

WATT  (JAMES)  ;  Origin  and  Progress  of  his  Mechanical  Inventions. 
Illustrated  by  his  correspondence  with  his  friends.  Edited  with  an 
Introductory  Memoir,  by  J.P.  MUIEHEAD.  Plates,  3  vols.  8vo.,  45s.  ; 
or  Large  Paper.  4to.  48s. 

WELLESLEY'S  (EEV.  DR.)  Anthologia  Polyglotta  ;  a  Selection 
of  Versions  in  various  Languages  chiefly  from  the  Greek  Anthology. 
8vo,15s.;  or4to,42s. 


32      LIST  OF  WORKS  PUBLISHED  BY  MR.  MURRAY. 


WELLINGTON'S  (THE  DUKE  OF)  Character,  Actions,  and  Writings. 
By  JULES  MAUREL.  Second  Edition.    Is.  6d. 


Despatches    during    his    various    Campaigns. 

Compiled  from  Official  and  other  Authentic   Documents.     By  COL. 
GUBWOOD,  C.B.   New  Enlarged  JEdition.    8  Vols.  8vo.    21s.  each. 

-  Selections    from    his   Despatches  and   General 
Orders.    8vo.    18s. 

Speeches  in  Parliament.  Collected  and  Arranged 


with  his  sanction.    2  Vols.    8vo.    42s. 

WILKIE'S  (SiR  DAVID)  Life,  Journals,  Tours,  and  Critical  Eemarks 
on  Works  of  Art,  with  a  Selection  from  his  Correspondence.  By  ALLAN 
CUNNINGHAM.  Portrait.  3  Vols.  8vo.  42s, 

WILKINSON'S  (SiR  J.  G.)  Popular  Account  of  the  Private  Life, 
Manners,  and  Customs  of  the  Ancient  Egyptians.  With  500  Wood- 
cuts. 2  Vols.  Post  8vo.  12s. 

-  Dalmatia  and  Montenegro ;  with  a  Journey  to 
Mostar  in  Hertzegovina,  and  Kemarks  on  the  Slavonic  Nations.  Plates 
and  Woodcuts.  2  Vols.  8vo.  42s. 


-  Handbook  for  Egypt.— Thebes,  the  Nile,   Alex- 
andria, Cairo,  the  Pyramids,  Mount  Sinai,  &c.    Map.    Post  8vo.   15s. 
(MATTHEW,  D.D.)  School  Sermons,  preached  in  the 


Chapel  of  Marlborough  College.    8vo. 

(G.  B.)  Working  Man's  Handbook  to  South  Aus- 


tralia ;  with  Advice  to  the  Farmer,  and  Detailed  Information  for  the 
several  Classes  of  Labourers  and  Artisans.    Map.    18mo.    Is.  Qd. 

WOOD'S  (LIEUT.)  Voyage  up  the  Indus  to  the  Source  of  the 
River  Oxus,  by  Kabul  and  Badakhshan.  Map.  8vo.  14$. 

WOODWARD'S  (B.B.)  Handbook  of  History;  or  Chronology 
Alphabetically  Arranged  to  Facilitate  Reference.  8vo. 

WORDSWORTH'S   (REV.  DR.)  Athens  and  Attica.    Journal  of  a 

Tour.     Third  Edition.    Plates.    Post  8vo.    8s.  6d. 

King  Edward  Vlth's  Latin  Grammar,  for  the 

Use  of  Schools.    1  Qth  Edition,  revised.    12mo.    3s.  6d. 

-  First  Latin  Book,  or  the  Accidence,  Syntax 
and  Prosody,  with  English  Translation  for  Junior  Classes.  Second 
Edition.  12mo.  2s. 

WORNUM'S  (RALPH)  Biographical  Dictionary  of  Italian  Painters : 
with  a  Table  of  the  Contemporary  Schools  of  Italy,  designed  as  a 
Handbook  to  the  Picture  Galleries  of  Italy.  By  a  LADY.  With  a 
Chart.  Post  8vo.  6s.  6d. 

WORSAAE'S  (J.  J.  A.)  Account  of  the  Danes  and  Northmen  in 
England,  Scotland,  and  Ireland.  Woodcuts.  8vo.  10s.  Qd. 

YOUNG'S  (DR.  THOS.)  (the  Discoverer  of  Hieroglyphics)  Life. 
By  GEORGE  PEACOCK,  D.D.,  Dean  of  Ely.  Portrait.  8vo. 

•  Miscellaneous  Works,  edited,  by  DEAN  PEACOCK  and 

JOHN  LEITCH.  Plates  and  Woodcuts.  3  Vols.  8vo. 




EKADBURY    AND   EVAKS,   riU.VTEKS,   WHITEl'BIAB 


|P 

~, 


•*  BOUND  BY