Skip to main content

Full text of "The American journal of psychology"

See other formats


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2008  with  funding  from 

IVIicrosoft  Corporation 


http://www.archive.org/details/americanjournalo22austuoft 


r 


(S) 


THE 


AMERICAN 


1^ 


Journal  of  Psychology 


EDITED  BY 

G.   STANI.EY  HALL 


Edmund  Clark  Sanford  Edward  Bradford  Titchener 

Clark  University.  Cornell  University. 


AND  John  Wai,i;ace  Baird 


WITH  THK  CO-OPERATIOlf  OF 


F.  Angei,!*,  Stanford  University;  H.  Beaunis,  Universities  of  Nancy 
and  Paris;  I.  M.  Benti^ey,  Cornell  University;  A.  F.  Cham- 
beri<ain,  Clark  University;  C.  F.  Hodge,  Clark  Uni- 
versity; A.  Kirschmann,  University  of  Toronto; 
O.  KuEiyPE,  University  of  Wiirzburg;  W.  B. 
PiivLSBURY,  University  of  Michigan ;  A. 
D.  WaIvLER,  University  of  I^ondon; 

M.  F.  Washburn,  Vassar  Q 

College. 


VOL.    XXII 


CIvARK  UNIVERSITY,  WORCESTER,  MASS. 
Florence  Chandler,  Publisher 

191 1 


COPYRIGHT,    1911,    BY   G.    STANLEY   HALL 

\ 

As 

v.  XX 


THB     COMMONWEALTH      PRESS 
WORCESTER,  MASS. 


<^ 


TABLE  OK  CONTENTS 


Rudolph  Achkr 

Recent  Freudian  Literature 408-443 

Frank  Angell 

Note  on  Some  of  the  Physical  Factors  Affecting  Reaction 

Time,  together  with  a  Description  of  a  New  Reaction  Key         86-93 
Sarah  B.  Barnholt  and  Madison  Bentley 

Thermal  Intensity  and  the  Area  of  Stimulus      ....       325-332 
Madison  Bentley  and  Sarah  B.  BarnhoIvT 

Thermal  Intensity  and  the  Area  of  Stimulus      ....       325-332 
Dorothy  Ci^ark,  Mary  S.  Goodell,  and  M.  F.  Washburn 

The  Bffect  of  Area  on  the  Pleasantness  of  Colors    .      .      .       578-579 
Helen  Maud  Clarke 

Conscious  Attitudes 214-249 

Ruth  Collins  and  C.  B.  FerrEE 

An  Bxperimental  Demonstration  of  the  Binaural  Ratio 

as  a  Factor  in  Auditory  Localization 250-297 

ISADOR  H.  Coriat 

The  Psychopathology  of  Apraxia 65-85 

Dorothy  Crawford  and  M.  F,  Washburn 

Fluctuations  in  the  Affective  Value  of  Colors  during  Fixa- 
tion for  One  Minute 579-582 

June  B.  Downey 

A  Case  of  Colored  Gustation         528-539 

Knight  Dunlap 

Terminology  in  the  Field  of  Sensation 444 

C.  B.  FerrEE  and  Ruth  Collins 

An  Bxperimental  Demonstration  of  the  Binaural  Ratio  as 

a  Factor  in  Auditory  Localization 250-297 

L.  R.  Geissler  and  B.  B.  Titchener 

A  Bibliography  of    the    Scientific    Writings    of    Wilhelm 

Wundt 586-587 

Mary  S.  Goodell,  Dorothy  Clark,  and  M.  F.  Washburn 

The  Bffect  of  Area  on  the  Pleasantness  of  Colors    .      .      .       578-579 
Samuel  P.  Hayes 

The  Color  Sensations  of  the  Partially  Color-Blind,  A  Cri- 
ticism of  Current  Teaching 369-407 

H.  L.  Hollingworth 

The  Psychology  of  Drowsiness 99-1 1 1 

Bdmund  Jacob  son 

Consciousness  under  Anaesthetics 333-345 

Bdmund  Jacobson 

On  Meaning  and  Understanding         553-577 

Brnest  Jones 

The  Psychopathology  of  Bveryday  Life  ....       477-527 

Hikozo  Kakise 

A  Preliminary  Bxperimental  Study  of  the  Conscious  Con- 
comitants of  Understanding 14-64 


IV  CONTENTS 

Horace  M.  Kali^en 

The  Esthetic  Principle  in  Comedy 13  7-15  7 

Ethel  L.  Norris,  Ai^ice  G.  Twiss,  and  M.  F.  Washburn 

An  Effect  of  Fatigue  on  Judgments  of  the  Affective  Value 

of  Colors 112-114 

IvOuisE  Ellison  Ordahl 

Consciousness  in  Relation  to  Learning 158-213 

F.  H.  Sapford 

Precision  of  Measurements  Applied  to  Psychometric  Func- 
tions       94-98 

Alma  de  Vries  Schaub 

On  the  Intensity  of  Images 346-368 

W.  T.  Shepherd 

The  Discrimination  of  Articulate  Sounds  by  Raccoons  1 16-119 

W.  T.  Shepherd 

Imitation  in  Raccoons 583-585 

E.  B.  TiTCHENER 

A  Note  of  the  Consciousness  of  Self         540-552 

E.  B.  TiTCHENER  and  L.  R.  GeisslER 

A  Bibliography  of  the  Scientific  Writings  of  Wilhelm  Wundt      586-5  87 
Alice  G.  Twiss,  Ethel  L.  Norris,  and  M.  F.  Washburn 
An  Effect  of  Fatigue  on  Judgments  of  the  Affective  Value 

of  Colors 112-114 

F.  M.  Urban 

A  Reply  to  Professor  Safford         298-303 

M.  F.  Washburn 

A  Note  on  the  Affective  Values  of  Colors 114-115 

M.  F.  Washburn  and  Dorothy  Crawford 

Fluctuations  in  the  Affective  Value  of  Colors  during  Fixa- 
tion for  One  Minute 579-582 

M.  F.  Washburn,  Mary  S.  Goodell,  and  Dorothy  Clark 

The  Effect  of  Area  on  the  Pleasantness  of  Colors  .       578-579 

M.  F.  Washburn,  Alice  G.  Twiss,  and  Ethel  L.  Norris 

An  Effect  of  Fatigue  on  Judgments  of  the  Affective  Value 

of  Colors 112-114 

Frederick  Lyman  Wells 

Practice  Effects  in  Free  Association         1-13 

Book  Reviews 120-132,304-318,445-467,588-599 

Book  Notes        132-136,319-324,468-474,600-604 

Commemorative  Note — Dr.  Edmund  Montgomery   .     .     .       475-476 
Note 604 


THE    AMERICAN 

Journal  of  Psychology 

Founded  by  G.  Stani^ey  Hai.1,  in  1887 
Voi,.  XXII  JANUARY,  1911  No.  1 

PRACTICE  EFFECTS  IN  FREE  ASSOCIATION 


By  Frederic  Lyman  Wells,  Ph.  D.,  Psychiatric  Institute,  Ward's  Island, 

N.  Y.,  formerly  Assistant  in  Pathological  Psychology  in  the 

McLean  Hospital,  Waverley,  Mass. 


I 


From  the  Psychological  Laboratory  of  the  McLean  Hospital. 

While  it  is  difficult  to  believe  that  any  extended  series  of 
association  experiments  could  be  made  without  the  appear- 
ance of  some  trace  of  practice  effect,  there  has  yet  been  no 
occasion,  within  the  writer's  knowledge,  for  the  presentation 
of  any  systematized  study  of  these  effects.  To  make  such 
a  study  with  any  degree  of  satisfaction  requires  a  much  larger 
series  of  stimulus  words  than  is  usually  requisite  for  the  im- 
mediate purpose  of  association  experiments.  For  the  present 
study,  a  list  was  constructed  to  consist  of  one  thousand  differ- 
ent stimulus  words,  which  should  be  so  far  as  possible  un- 
ambiguous, and  familiar  to  the  class  of  subjects  dealt  with. 
These  words  were  written  on  as  many  separate  slips  of  paper, 
which  were  then  placed  in  a  large  box  and  thoroughly  shaken 
together  for  15  minutes.  The  slips  were  then  drawn  from  the 
box  at  random,  one  at  a  time,  and  made  up  into  twenty  series 
of  50  words  each.  A  revised  list  will  be  an  improvement 
over  this  one,  which  has,  however,  shown  entirely  sufficient 
adaptability  to  the  present  experiments. 

One  series  of  50  words  was  given  to  each  of  six  subjects 
each  day,  six  days  in  the  week,  until  the  entire  twenty  series 
had  been  given.  On  the  next  two  days  the  first  two  series  of 
50  words  were  repeated.  The  present  results  are  based  essen- 
tially upon  these  experiments,  totalling  6,600  observations; 
especially  on  the  two  series  that  are  repeated.  Two  other  sub- 
jects reacted  to  500  words  each.     About  a  third  as  many 


2  WELIvS 

more  observations  were  made  with  each  of  the  first  six  sub- 
jects, with  reference  to  special  points  in  the  experiment,  but 
these  results  have  only  a  limited  application  for  the  present 
purpose  since  the  experimental  material  was  here  varied  some- 
what for  the  different  subjects. 

While  regretting  that  there  is  no  more  accurate  method  of 
timing  than  the  stopwatch,  which  permits  other  essential  con- 
ditions of  the  experiment  to  be  satisfactorily  preserved,  it 
must  be  acknowledged  the  most  useful  method  available  for 
timing  the  individual  responses  of  the  experiment.  It  was 
employed  in  all  the  observations  here  recorded.  I  have  else- 
where spoken  very  distrustfully  of  this  method,  and  it  cannot 
be  used  for  the  interpretation  of  single  measures  on  a  minute 
scale.  This  is  owing  partly  to  the  inherent  coarseness  of  the 
measure,  partly  also  to  the  inaccuracies  of  operation.  In  the 
present  discussion  the  changes  are  sufficiently  great  as  to  be 
reliably  reflected  in  this  method  of  timing,  which  modifies  the 
external  conditions  for  the  subject  less  than  any  other. 

Of  the  six  subjects  with  whom  we  are  principally  concerned, 
one  is  a  highly  educated  physician  in  middle  life,  the  remainder 
are  women  nurses,  with  one  exception  under  30  years  of  age. 
In  Jung's  classification  of  association  types,  four  of  the  sub- 
jects belong  to  the  Sachlicher  Typus  tending  in  different 
degrees  towards  the  more  subjective  types;  one  is  a  fairly 
distinct  Pradikattypus,  and  one  rather  a  Konstellationstypus. 
The  two  other  subjects,  VII  and  VIII,  are  also  women  nurses 
under  thirty,  one  being  a  Sachlicher  Typus,  the  other  a  less 
marked  Konstellationstypus. 

The  progressive  changes  in  the  time  of  the  response,  and 
the  qualitative  changes  shown  by  the  responses  in  the  repeated 
series,  form  the  basis  of  the  present  discussion.  The  most 
noticeable  practice  effect  is  that  in  reaction- time ;  the  changes 
in  the  content  of  the  responses  are  perhaps  of  an  equally 
interesting  nature,  but  hardly  so  well  defined. 

The  accompanying  cut  illustrates  the  practice  curve  of  the 
association  time  for  each  subject  during  the  twenty  consecu- 
tive daily  series.  The  time  unit,  here  as  elsewhere,  is  1/5  of 
one  second. 

The  range  of  individual  differences  at  the  beginning  of 
practice  is  here  about  2 :  i ,  a  range  that  is  seen  in  many  mental 
measurements,  but  in  other  observations  with  a  larger  number 
of  subjects,  this  range  is  seen  to  be  much  nearer  3:1.  The 
fastest  subject  here  is  about  as  fast  as  the  writer  has  ever 
observed,  but  in  other  subjects  from  this  group  the  median 
of  100  association  times  may  run  as  high  as  20  fifths,  as  in 
several  of  the  series  with  subject  VIII.  The  reaction  times  in 
the  present  experiments  also  run  somewhat  longer  than  those 


\ 


oy 


r 
>     ^ 


PRACTICIS  EFFECTS  IN  FREE  ASSOCIATION  3 

reported  by  Jung,  which,  however,  is  amply  accounted  for 
by  the  greater  difficulty  of  the  individual  series  of  words. 
A  random  selection  of  fifty  from  a  thousand  available  words 
is  naturally  more  difficult  than  a  list  of  one  hundred  or  two 
hundred  words  selected  immediately. 

The  effect  of  practice  seems  to  be  towards  a  diminution  of 
the  individual  differences  in  association  time,  although  such 
a  diminution  is  far  from  being  what  is  found  in  all  mental 
functions.  Between  three  of  the  subjects  (Red,  Orange  and 
Green)  there  is  practically  no  such  individual  difference  at 
any  stage  of  practice,  but  in  general  the  effect  of  practice 
seems  to  be  to  bring  all  the  subjects  near  together  at  a  certain 
psychological  limit  of  quickness,  which  limit  shows  compara- 
tively little  individual  variation.  There  are,  therefore,  very 
great  individual  differences  in  the  closeness  with  which  the 
different  subjects  approximate  to  this  limit  at  the  beginning 
of  their  practice.  Thus  subject  Blue  starts  well  below  any 
level  which  most  of  the  subjects  ever  attain,  and  remains  at 
this  level  throughout,  the  practice  effect  being  almost  absent 
so  far  as  the  association  time  is  concerned.  Other  individuals 
have  been  observed,  who,  during  the  first  observations  with 
this  test  approximated  to  the  short  times  here  given  by  Blue, 
and  might  be  expected  in  further  experiments  to  show  as 
little  practice  effect.  It  seems  fair  to  infer  that  the  limit  of 
quickness  which  any  subject  can  attain  by  practice  in  this 
experiment,  is  equalled,  if  not  surpassed,  by  other  subjects 
at  the  beginning  of  practice,  and  these  subjects  then  show 
little  change  during  special  practice.  Some  are  born  with  the 
capacity  for  the  promptest  reaction,  others  achieve  it  only 
with  special  practice,  and  in  very  different  degrees;  still  others 
perhaps  not  at  all.  And  the  general  mental  characters  which 
give  to  one  individual  an  inherently  short  association  time 
are  probably  of  a  much  more  fundamental  nature,  and  more 
important  factors  in  the  individual's  make-up  than  those 
special  characters  which,  developing  during  special  practice, 
may  give  to  another  subject  a  somewhat  greater  facility  in 
reacting. 

Of  the  two  subjects  reacting  to  500  words  only.  Subject  VII 
shows  nothing  out  of  the  ordinary,  but  the  case  of  Subject  VIII 
who  shows  an  actual  reverse  of  practice  effect,  is  naturally 
of  special  interest.  She  seems  to  have  a  fairly  good  idea  of 
the  cause  of  the  difficulty,  which  she  describes  as  essentially 
a  difficulty  of  choice  between  the  large  numbers  of  responses 
that  would  present  themselves.  Of  this  she  is  able  to  give 
quite  detailed  introspection  in  individual  cases.  She  spoke 
of  a  difficulty  in  sufficiently  focussing  the  "attention"  verho 
ipso.     She  said  that  the  novel  experimental  conditions  had 


WEI.I.S 


20 


Subi/.Tnr 


16 


Soh^rSJL 


Plate  II. 

*' rattled"  her  a  little  only  on  the  first  two  days,  when  as  a 
matter  of  fact  she  was  quickest.  She  denied  absolutely  that 
any  conscious  suppression  of  disagreeable  associations  had 
influenced  the  results  and  was  able  to  definitely  assign  such 
a  process  in  but  one  specific  instance.  It  may  be  added  that 
the  subject  is  of  an  entirely  normal  make-up,  and  in  education, 
mental  balance,  and  professional  efficiency,  will  bear  com- 
parison with  any  other  member  of  the  group. 

One  of  the  most  unfortunate  limitations  of  the  median  as 
a  measure  of  central  tendency  is  the  fact  that,  unlike  the 
average,  it  has  no  convenient  index  of  the  variability  of  the 
distribution  about  it.  As  a  rough  and  ready  index  of  the 
variability  of  the  association  times  in  each  of  the  different 
series  of  fifty  words,  has  been  taken  the  smallest  number  of 
steps  required  to  include  50%  of  the  cases.  Like  the  median 
itself,  however,  this  measure  takes  no  account  for  the  extra 
long  times  but  gives  only  an  indication  of  how  closely  the 
central  reaction-times  are  crowded  together.  In  magnitude, 
this  figure  varies  between  1.5  and  9  fifths  of  a  second.  As  the 
time  decreases  with  practice,  the  variabilit}^  naturally  drops 
also,  although  the  record  of  Subject  Bi^ack,  in  whom  the 


PRACTICE)   SJ^FECTS  IN  FREE  ASSOCIATION  5 

variability  remains  practically  constant  throughout,  shows 
that  it  does  not  necessarily  do  so.  The  fluctuations  in  varia- 
bility are  more  marked,  and  the  individual  differences  less 
distinct,  than  in  the  curves  of  the  reaction-times  themselves. 
The  variability  of  Orange  is  somewhat,  that  of  Black,  very 
disproportionately  low.  These  are  also  the  two  most  intel- 
lectual subjects  in  the  group,  although  widely  differing  in 
their  association  types. 

The  distribution  of  the  individual  reaction-times  in  the 
single  series  of  fifty  words  show  a  rather  interesting  fact  that 
is  contrary  to  what  is  ordinarily  expected  in  such  distributions. 
At  no  time  during  the  practice  is  a  distribution  of  marked 
skewness  the  rule.  The  mode  is  frequently  as  many  as  five 
steps  away  from  the  shortest  reactions,  and  even  during  the 
final  stages  of  practice  there  occur  distributions  exhibiting 
considerable  skew  towards  the  long  end.  Beyond  the  above 
decrease  in  variability,  it  is  difficult  to  state  any  specific 
effect  of  practice  on  the  form  of  the  distribution.  The  natural 
interpretation  of  this  is  that  an  indefinite  amount  of  practice 
would  still  leave  us  a  considerable  distance  from  the  physiologi- 
cal limit  of  association  time  (which  is  more  nearly  approached 
in  the  controlled  associations),  and  the  limit  of  free  asso- 
ciation time,  dependent  as  it  is  upon  the  most  delicate  interplay 
of  the  higher  mental  processes,  is  of  too  fluctuating  a  nature 
to  leave  any  characteristic  impress  on  the  form  of  the  distribu- 
tions. 

Contemporaneous  with  the  free  association  experiment,  the 
first  five  women  subjects  underwent  practice  in  two  other 
psychological  tests.  These  were  the  Kraepelin  addition  test 
and  a  special  form  of  the  ^-test,  both  of  which  belong  to  the 
general  group  of  controlled  association  experiments.  It  is 
interesting  to  compare  susceptibility  to  practice  in  these 
tests,  which  involve  the  continual  repetition  of  the  same  or 
a  few  different  associations,  with  the  susceptibility  to  practice 
in  the  free  association  test,  where  the  experimental  task  is 
a  novel  one  in  each  individual  observation.  For  present 
purposes  it  will  suffice  to  compare  the  mean  performance  of 
the  first  two  records  with  that  of  the  last  two  for  the  period 
of  twenty  days.  In  the  number-checking  test  it  is  more 
desirable  to  take  the  last  two  of  the  entire  thirty  days  for 
which  the  function  was  practiced.  This  comparison  gives  us 
the  following  table: 


6  WEI.I.S 

Figures  Expressing  the  per  cent,  of  Practice  Improvement  in  the 

Free  Association,  the  Addition,  and  the  Number  Checking 

Tests,  indicating  their  Comparative  Susceptibility 

TO  Practice 

{The  Lower  the  Figure,  the  greater  the  Practice) 


Subject 

Free  Association 

Addition 

Number  c 

Brown 

80 

61 

52 

Red 

74 

52 

81 

Orange 

70 

55 

52 

Green 

61 

61 

55 

Blue 

89 

49 

41 

In  the  case  of  the  physician  (Black)  the  practice  in  free 
association  was  75%.  In  these  figures  it  appears  that  while 
the  practice  improvement  is  practically  always  least  in  the 
free  association  test,  it  is  nevertheless  of  the  same  order  of 
magnitude  save  only,  perhaps,  in  Subject  Blue.  This  is  a 
striking  result  in  view  of  the  essential  dififerences  in  the  ex- 
perimental tasks.  In  the  individuality  of  the  successive  situ- 
ations it  presents,  the  free  association  test  is  unique  among 
psychological  experiments.  It  affords  small  opportunity  for 
making  any  given  association  path  more  open  through  fre- 
quent use.  Such  a  conception  of  practice  fails  when  applied 
to  the  results  indicated  in  the  present  experiments.  It  is 
therefore  a  question  how  far  the  practice  in  the  number- 
checking  test  and  in  the  addition  test  is  of  the  same  type,  and 
the  product  of  the  same  causes,  as  that  in  the  free  association 
test.  The  essential  features  in  the  free  association  practice 
can  probably  be  cleared  up  only  through  the  most  accurate 
introspection,  although  it  is  a  very  natural  interpretation  to 
conceive  of  it  almost  wholly  in  terms  of  a  removal  of  inhibi- 
tions. These  decreasing  inhibitions  can  for  the  present  be 
only  loosely  figured  as  a  greater  accustomedness  to  the  ex- 
perimental conditions,  a  lessened  emotional  reaction  to  them, 
feeling  freer  and  more  at  ease,  less  liability  to  distraction, 
and  the  like.  They  are  essentially  conscious  inhibitions, 
although  it  is  not  easy  to  describe  them  accurately  unless  one 
has  had  some  practice  in  introspection.  We  can  probably 
reduce  all  these  factors  to  the  general  term  of  the  elimination 
of  the  inessential.  The  part  which  is  necessarily  played  by 
this  elimination  of  the  inessential  in  the  reduction  of  free 
association  time  throws  a  not  uninteresting  side-light  upon 
its  possible  importance  in  other  sorts  of  practice,  where, 
owing  to  the  fact  that  there  is  more  repeated  traversal  of  the 
same  association  paths,  we  may  tend  to  place  the  burden  of 
explanation  rather  upon  decreased  resistance  in  the  path 
itself. 


PRACTICE   EFlfBCTS   IN   FREE   ASSOCIATION  7 

So  much  for  the  practice  effect  on  association  time.  With 
regard  to  any  possible  effect  on  the  nature  of  the  responses, 
may  be  first  noted  the  number  of  times  the  same  response 
is  repeated  during  the  same  hundred  words  at  the  beginning 
and  end  of  the  practice.  This  per  cent,  of  the  repetition  is 
calculated  for  the  two  series  that  were  repeated,  thus  for  the 
same  stimulus  words,  and  forms  a  basis  for  some  striking 
comparisons.  The  per  cent,  of  repetition  before  practice  and 
after  practice  is  as  follows  for  the  different  subjects: 

Subject       .         .         Black  Brown  Red  Orange  Green  Blue 
Before  Practice  8         11       14       16         17       13 

After  Practice  8  7         7         4         22         8 

The  regular  tendency  is  to  reduce  the  number  of  repetitions. 
In  the  case  of  GrEEn  the  increase  is  essentially  a  matter  of 
the  subject's  developing  a  ''set"  towards  reacting  with  such 
responses  as  large,  small,  and  grand,  whenever  they  were 
available.  With  the  exception  of  the  physician,  the  remainder 
tend  to  particularize  their  responses  more,  as  their  practice 
in  reacting  gives  them  greater  Sprachfertigkeit.  It  seems 
likely  that  Black,  with  his  much  greater  initial  Sprachfertig- 
keit, had  already  developed  the  quality  that  makes  for  de- 
crease in  repetitions  beyond  the  point  where  practice  would 
bring  out  any  special  change.  The  general  trend  towards 
greater  particularization  of  the  responses  by  practice,  of 
which  the  decrease  in  repetitions  is  an  aspect,  will  be  dis- 
cussed below  in  greater  detail. 

Further  individual  difference  appears  in  the  frequency  with 
which  a  given  stimulus  word  elicits  the  same  response  in  both 
the  initial  and  the  repeated  series,  the  figures  on  this  point 
being  as  follows: 

Number  of  Cases  in  which  the  Same  Response  was  given  both  Before 
AND  after  Practice^ 

Black  Brown  Red  Orange  Green  Blue 
Average  number  of  identical  re- 
sponses in  the  two  repeated  vSeries    16  22.5  20.5  9,5  21.5  22.5 
M.  V.  of  this  average      ...         2         2.5  4.5  .5  1,5  1.5 

Save  for  the  probably  negligible  incidence  of  the  memory 
factor,  the  number  of  times  in  which  a  different  response  is 
given  is  in  the  nature  of  an  indication  of  the  adaptability  of 
the  individual's  thought  processes;  that  is,  of  the  capacity 
for  differential  response  in  relatively  similar  external  situa- 
tions. This  is  somewhat  complicated  by  the  factor  of  special 
education,  because  an  educated  subject  possess  an  artificial 

^  There  are  a  few  cases  in  which  the  stimulus  word  was  not  understood 
the  same  in  the  repeated  as  in  the  original  series,  but  these  are  negligible 
for  the  results.  While  it  is  not  strictly  a  practise  phenomenon,  it  is 
worth  quoting  for  comparison  with  the  above.     (Fuhrmann.) 


8  WKI.LS 

capacity  to  differentiate  his  responses  more  than  an  unedu- 
cated one.  Thus,  as  above,  the  physician  again  gives  a 
relatively  small  number  of  repetitions  of  the  responses  under 
these  conditions.  But  of  the  women  subjects  who  have  ap- 
proximately equal  education.  Orange  differentiates  her  re- 
sponses a  great  deal  more  than  any  of  the  others,  more  even 
than  the  physician;  and  she  is  the  same  subject  who  made 
the  greatest  gain  in  differentiation  in  the  previous  table. 
It  may  or  may  not  be  a  coincidence  that  this  subject  has  been 
placed  in  more  responsible  positions,  also  credited  with  more 
than  ordinary  resourcefulness  in  her  professional  work.  And 
however  much  one  might  naturally  incline  to  stress  the  merely 
educational  explanation  of  this  greater  differentiation  of 
responses,  one  must  never  forget  that  superior  education  to 
a  certain  extent  implies  superior  ability  to  acquire  it,  in  the 
fundamental  dynamic  correlation  between  superior  innate 
endowments,  and  superior  opportunities  for  developing  the 
powers  which  they  confer. 

For  these  differentiated  responses,  there  then  presents  itself 
the  question  of  whether  they  are  differentiated  along  any 
particular  lines;  i.  e.,  of  whether  the  response,  besides  changing 
in  form  and  in  content,  tends  also  to  change  in  association 
type. 

Before  attempting  to  consider  any  possible  effect  of  practice 
on  the  form  of  association,  it  must  be  thoroughly  understood 
that  the  ordinary  means  of  classification  are  at  best  very 
subjective.  Such  categories  as  the  Sachliches  Urteil  and 
Werturteil  are  wholly  continuous,  even  though  they  may 
cover  a  considerable  range,  as  from  a  commonplace  predicate 
like  handkerchief — white,  to  such  a  highly  particularized  re- 
actions as  journey — distasteful.  These  last  are  what  Jung 
calls  the  "egocentric  predicates."  The  same  continuity 
exists,  of  course,  between  the  Eingeiibte  sprachliche  Ver- 
bindungen  and  the  Sprichworter  und  Zitate;  thus  one  might 
with  equal  justice  assign  citizen — Roman  to  either  group. 
The  most  unfortunate  confusion,  however,  is  that  likely  to 
arise  between  these  language-motor  responses  and  those 
from  the  upper  associative  categories.  Every  experimental 
series  is  replete  with  reactions  where  this  vital  distinction  is 
itself  largely  a  matter  of  " personliches  Werturteil."  O^ily — 
chance  and  never — settled  may  be  harmless  Gelaufige  Phrasen 
or  highly  egocentric  predicates.  Betray — criminal  may  be  a 
Subjectverhaltniss,  an  Objectverhaltniss  or  an  Urteil;  spread — 
feast  an  identity  or  a  predicate;  lady — gentleman  an  opposite 
or  a  co-existence.  The  stimulus  cart  may  elicit  the  response 
horse  through  the  medium  of  word-compounding,  familiar 
phrase,  or  co-existence.     Shall  we  call  itch — scabies  an  identity, 


PRACTICE   EFFECTS   IN   FREE   ASSOCIATION 


a  co-ordination,  or  a  Kausalabhangigkeit?  Fun — loving  a  Wor- 
terganzung  or  an  Urteil? 

Such  examples  could  be  multipled  indefinitely  but  are, 
perhaps,  sufficient  to  show  the  character  of  the  difficulties 
encountered  in  attempting  an  impartial  classification  of  asso- 
ciative responses  along  the  conventional  lines.  If  available, 
reliable  introspective  data  would  go  far  towards  removing 
them,  but  the  very  nature  of  the  experiment  usually  renders 
this  aid  impracticable.  With  the  more  recondite  responses, 
such  classification  is  nearly  meaningless.  The  interpretation, 
without  reliable  introspective  data,  of  such  reactions  as  pole — 
legSy  satisfy — savage^  almost — conditional,  enough — period,  ex- 
pect— to-morrow,  justice — execution,  and  the  like,  is  little  more 
than  guesswork. 

Subject  to  these  reservations,  then,  the  forms  of  association 
here  justifying  separate  consideration  may  be  enumerated  as 
follows : 


Description 

1 .  Failure  of  response 

2.  Egocentric 

3.  Egocentric  predicate 

4.  Judgment  of  quality 

5.  Simple  predicate 

6.  Subject  relation 

7.  Object  relation 

8.  Causality 

9.  Co-ordination 

10.  Subordination 

11.  Supraordination 

12.  Contrast 

13.  Co-existence 

14.  Identity 

15.  Language — motor 


Approximately  corres- 
ponding to  Jung's 
Ausbleiben  des  Reaktions- 

worts 
Egozentrische  Reaktion 

Direkte  Ichbeziehung 
Egozentrisches  Pradikat 
Werturteil 

Sachliches  Urteil 
Substantiv-Verbum  Sub- 

jektverhaltniss 
Substantiv-Verbum  Objekt 

verhaltniss 
Kausalabhangigkeit 
Beiordnung 
Unterordnung 
Ueberordnung 
Kontrast 
Koexistenz 
Identitat 


Example 


Eingeiibte  sprachliche 
Verbindungen,  etc. 
Word-compounding  or  Wortzusammensetzung, 
completing  Worterganzung 


succeed — I  must 
lonesome — never 
rose — beautiful 

spinach — green 

dog — bite 

deer — shoot 
joke — laughter 
cow — horse 
food — bread 
rat — animal 
sunlight — shadow 
engine — cars 
expensive — costly 

town — state 
side — board 


17.  Pure  sound  associa- 

tions 

18.  Syntactic  change 


Reime 

Syntaktische  Veranderung 


pack — tack 
deep — depth 


The  categories  are  divided  into  three  groups.  In  the  first 
group  are  those  usually  implying  a  special  emotive  element  in 
the  association;  the  second  contains  the  more  intellectual 
associations,  while  the  very  superficial  associations  are  summed 
up  in  the  third  group.     The  associations  from  the  present 


lO  W^LLS 

material  not  falling  into  any  of  the  above  categories,  it  is 
impracticable  to  classify  with  any  pretence  of  objective  valid- 
ity. They  are  also  negligible  in  number,  and  indeed,  several 
of  the  specified  categories  are  very  meagerly  represented. 

The  tables  indicate  that  in  Black  the  type  of  association 
has  undergone  no  particular  change,  except  for  trebling  the 
number  of  contrasts,  and  halving  that  of  the  subordinates. 
The  number  of  supraordinates,  however,  is  remarkably  small, 
which  is  significant  in  connection  with  this  subject's  superior 
education,  and  the  tendency  elsewhere  for  the  supraordinates 
to  decrease  with  practice.  In  Brown,  the  responses  show  a 
slight  tendency  downward  in  the  scale,  and  a  considerable 
decrease  in  the  supraordinates.  In  Red,  this  downward  ten- 
dency of  the  associations  is  more  marked,  there  being  also  a 
loss  of  half  the  supraordinates,  which  become  mainly  co-exis- 
tences, these  trebling  in  number.  There  are  six  of  the  third 
group  of  associations  in  the  repeated  series,  to  none  at  all 
in  the  original  ones.  And  in  respect  to  form  of  association, 
Orange  again  shows  the  most  marked  change  of  all.  The 
predicates,  many  of  which  are  quite  egocentric  in  character, 
are  decreased  by  about  one-half,  being  relegated  mainly  to 
the  language-motor,  the  word-compounds  and  the  co-exist- 
ences. There  are  also  less  than  a  third  of  the  original  number 
of  supraordinates,  these  again  becoming  mainly  co-existences 
and  language-motors.  Consequently  these  lower  forms  of 
reaction  are  greatly  increased  in  number,  there  being  47  of 
them  in  the  repeated  series  compared  with  16  in  the  original. 
Notable  is  the  total  absence  of  contrast  associations,  also 
in  Subject  Green.  The  reactions  of  GrEEn  show  no  special 
change  in  type,  except  for  the  same  decrease  in  the  supraordi- 
nates, which  here  change  to  such  responses  as  large^  small, 
grand  (as  noted  previously),  technically  predicates,  but  it  is 
doubtful  whether  they  are  actually  much  more  than  language- 
motors.  BivUE,  however,  shows  a  peculiar  tendency  to  change 
the  associations  originally  supraordinates  to  predicates  of  a 
higher  order;  e.  g.,  donkey -animal,  donkey-bray.  The  lower 
categories  are  also  better  represented  than  at  the  start,  so  that 
the  general  result  is  to  make  the  association  type  more  vari- 
able than  before.  The  remarkable  shortness  of  the  times  in 
this  subject  will  be  remembered,  and  the  responses  themselves 
show  rather  greater  superficiality  than  can  be  indicated  in 
the  classification. 

In  the  totals,  two  main  trends  are  apparent,  which,  how- 
ever, cross,  and  to  some  extent  mask,  each  other.  First,  the 
tendency,  especially  mentioned  for  some  of  the  individual  sub- 
jects, for  the  whole  body  of  responses  to  move  down  in  the 
scale  of  associations,  and  secondly,  the  tendency  to  greater 


PRACTICE   EFFECTS   IN   ^RH^   ASSOCIATION 


II 


According  to  this  system,  it  seemed  that  the  associations 
in  the  two  repeated  series  were  most  reasonably  to  be  classified 
as  follows: 


aDI^DBJJ 


Thio|»/3»-<-^0'^c<ONioO»oio|]5r<»o 


« 


N  M       ro  >o  lo  cs  r>.oo  looo  fo 

M  C<  MM 


o 


to  M  r^  Ti-00  (s  lo       to  o< 

M  M  c* 


(S 


c< 


lO        WMtoOO         J^>0 


CO        CO  tJ-  M    fO  J^VO  vO  00 


OT  4-»    rt  ;m 

f  fl  fl  d 

Vj    (U    (U    c 

3  o  o  So 

^  9  P'd 
rt  bo  bo  3 


CS    CO 


^WO      S.o 


'S-S 

(~>  't?  +->  -»->    ^    Ui    V-i 

.9  ;3  ;3  .cd  O  ;j 

xnmmOOm 


^  ^  ^ 


>OVO   1^00   On  O 


8 
bo.2 

p  rt  (u  a 

*^  S  o  fa  c 


12 


WEI.I.S 


particularization  of  the  response  as  indicated  mainly  in  the 
decrease  of  over  50  per  cent,  in  the  supraordinates.  The 
latter  is  closely  related  to  the  decrease  in  repetitions  described 
on  page  7,  for  these  repetitions  consist  largely  of  such  supra- 
ordinate  responses  as  animal,  food,  and  the  like,  which  have 
many  subordinates  among  the  stimulus  words.  For  obvious 
reasons,  these  classifications  do  not  lend  themselves  readily 
to  further  illustration  of  this  tendency.  It  is  plain  what  great 
individual  differences  there  are  in  the  amount  of  change  of 
association  type,  but  it  is  not  easy  to  say  just  what  ultimately 
constitutes  these  differences;  they  are  not  closely  related  to 
education.  One  is  practically  reduced  to  the  tautology  that 
as  practice  tends  to  lower  the  association  type  and  to  decrease 
the  supraordinates,  those  individuals  are  most  liable  to  practice 
effects  who  show  the  upper  levels  of  association  type,  or  a 
marked  tendency  to  generalization  in  their  responses.  The 
Sachlicher  Typus  certainly  shows  the  less  change  in  associa- 
tion form,  and  probably  also  in  reaction  time. 

The  precise  nature  of  these  changes  will  perhaps  be  made 
clearer  by  the  following  illustrations.  The  comparative  asso- 
ciation times  before  and  after  practice  are  given,  as  usual,  in 
5ths  of  a  second. 


Stimulus  word 

Response  before 
Practice 

Response  after  Practice 

Greater  Particularization 

ancient 

man  11 

and  Honorable  Artillery  10 

bank 

building  13 

England  9 

contrast 

judgment  46 

black  and  white  8 

dog 

animal  22 

Airedale  16 

engine 

machine  10 

Morris  Heights  21 

herald 

king  8 

Globe  7 

little 

child  16 

statue  12 

parlor 

room  8 

sitting-room  7 

swift 

runner  12 

Mercury  17 

wheat 

vegetable  24 

cream  of  wheat  15 

Greater  Superficiality 

axle 

hub  II 

grease  6 

axle 

wheel  9 

tree  6 

bank 

money  7 

banker  5 

discretion  (twice)  wise  22,  42 

valor  II,  6 

lady 

refined  2 1 

man  19 

pancake 

tough  12 

fl^our  9 

shadow 

shade  16 

wall  6 

spread 

distance  17 

bed  7 

suffer 

weak  II 

pain  4 

weak 

frail  10 

strong  13 

PRACTICE   EFFECTS   IN   FREE   ASSOCIATION  1 3 

In  Spite  of  the  tendency  to  greater  particularization,  it  is 
not  unnatural,  in  view  of  these  latter  instances,  that  such 
actual  "  Komplexmerkmale  "  as  are  given  in  the  reaction  time, 
and  in  the  form  of  the  association  as  well  as  in  the  content  of 
the  response,  should  also  be  somewhat  reduced  by  practice. 
The  subjoined  instances  will  serve  to  show  what  is  meant, 
though  some  of  the  most  striking  examples  of  this  tendency 
are  not  included. 

Stimulus  word     Response  before  Practice         Response  after  Practice 


breast 

face  22 

milk  10 

common 

loose  14 

Boston  8 

flirt 

disgusting  26 

bird  9 

heaven 

peace  18 

hell  6 

person 

woman  40 

body  9 

rat 

ugly  27 

large  10 

sister 

(Anna)  25 

brother  7 

virtue 

good  18 

reward  7 

want 

cherish  38 

wish  9 

whiskey 

dangerous  13 

Bourbon  7 

The  "complexual"  character  of  the  responses  is  apparently 
much  diminished.  This  phenomenon  should  be  attributable 
mainly  to  decreased  emotive  value  in  the  stimulus-words,  and 
only  very  sparingly  to  any  greater  expertness  in  dodging. 
In  the  above  instances,  the  time  is  rather  short  for  dodging, 
even  though  the  occasion  had  presented  itself.  In  this  con- 
nection, it  is  well  to  bear  in  mind  that  special  emotional  reac- 
tion to  a  stimulus  word  may  be  a  product  of  long  association 
time  as  well  as  a  cause  of  it,  since  the  greater  the  tendency  to 
hesitation,  the  greater  the  opportunity  for  emotive  associa- 
tions to  be  introduced.  With  greater  facility  of  response, 
whether  inherent  or  gained  through  practice,  the  importance 
of  such  a  process  is  much  reduced. 

In  brief,  then,  these  experiments  indicate  the  usual  effects 
of  practice  on  free  association  to  be: 

1 .  To  decrease  the  association  time  to  a  limit  approximat- 
ing 6  fifths  of  a  second  for  the  median  of  50  associations.  At 
the  beginning  of  practice,  the  subject  may  be  any  distance 
from  this  limit  up  to  15  fifths  or  more. 

2.  To  further  differentiate  and  particularize  the  responses, 
by  increasing  the  readiness  with  which  the  subject's  entire 
vocabulary  becomes  available  for  the  purpose  of  such  response. 

3.  To  "flatten,"  or  make  more  superficial,  the  form  of 
association  which  the  responses  take. 

4.  To  decrease  the  emotive  value  of  the  experiment,  and 
consequently  its  applicability  for  all  purposes  involving  its 
emotive  value. 


A  PRELIMINARY  EXPERIMENTAL  STUDY  OF  THE 

CONSCIOUS  CONCOMITANTS  OF 

UNDERSTANDING 


By  HiKOZO  Kakisb 


Introduction   ..........  14 

Part  I.     Conditions   of  the   preceding  concomitants           .          .  19 

§1.     Audito-motor  reproduction  of  the  stimulus      .          .          .  19 

§2.     Visual  reproduction  of  the  stimulus         ....  22 

Part  II.     Conditions  of  the  succeeding  concomitants         ,          .  23 

§1.     Memory  images     ........  24 

§2.     "Indicative  images"       .......  26 

§3.     "Organic  images"           .......  28 

§4.     "General  visual-object  images"       .....  29 

§5.     "Suggested  verbal  images"     ......  29 

§6.     Images  with  unfamiliar  stimuli        .         .          .          .          .  31 

§7.     The  "Ausfrage  method"  and  the  customary    method  in 

the  study  of  associations                                                        .  37 

Part  III.     Analysis  of  the  simultaneous  concomitants         .          .  42 

§1.     Historical  sketch  of  the  various  views  of  thought     .          .  42 

§2.     Contents  of  "meaning"  with  familiar  stimuli           .          .  49 

§3.     Selective  experiences   with  unfamiliar  stimuli           .          .  53 

§4.     Ultimate  constituents  of  "meaning"       ....  56 

Introduction 

When  a  word  or  a  phrase  is  presented  to  an  observer  for  a 
certain  interval  of  time,  it  will  awaken  a  succession  of  various 
events  in  his  mind,  such  as  inner  reading  of  the  word,  "sense 
of  meaning,"  suggested  images  of  objects  or  of  other  words, 
and  so  forth,  attended  by  various  feelings  and  emotions. 
In  the  succession  of  these  experiences,  some  will  precede, 
others  succeed,  and  still  others  occur  simultaneously  with 
understanding.  The  purpose  of  the  study  about  to  be  re- 
ported is  to  examine,  by  a  special  method  of  experimentation, 
first  the  relations  of  the  events  preceding  and  succeeding 
to  understanding,  and  then  to  investigate  the  nature  of  the 
simultaneous  events,  i.  e.,   the  consciousnesses  of  meaning. 

The  method  of  experimentation  was  the  same  as  that 
used  by  Marbe,i  Messer,^  Biihler^  and  others  in  their  studies 
of  thought,  the  so-called  ''Ausfrage  experiment"  by  which 


^Marbe,  K.:  Experimentell-psychologische  Untersuchungen  iiber  das 
Urteil,  1 901. 

^Messer,  A.:  Experimentell-psychologische  Untersuchungen  iiber  das 
Denken,  Archiv  fur  die  gesamte  Psychologie,  1906,  Vol.  VIII. 

^Biihler,  K.:     Ueber  Gedanken,  Archiv  fitr  Ges.  Psychol.,  Vol.  IX. 


A   STUDY  OF   UNDERSTANDING  1 5 

the  total  introspection  of  observers  in  reaction  to  words  or 
phrases  is  taken  down  in  the  form  of  protocols  upon  which 
the  conclusions  are  based. 

Remarks  on  the  Method:  In  spite  of  certain  objections  against  the 
method  from  the  side  of  certain  psychologists,  as  Wundt,  who  calls  it 
a  "pseudo  experiment"  {Scheinexperiment)  because  it  satisfies  none  of 
the  four  requirements  of  a  psychological  experiment,  viz.:  concentration 
of  attention,  repetition  of  the  experiment,  methodical  change  of  the  con- 
ditions, and  the  observer's  own  determination  of  the  phenomena  to  be 
observed,^  yet  the  present  writer  had  recourse  to  this  method  partly  as  a 
kind  of  trial,  and  partly  because  there  are  no  other  methods  which  seem 
better  suited  to  the  present  purpose.  The  reasons  for  this  belief  are: 
(i)  That  this  method  leads  to  division  of  labor,  in  that  the  experimenter 
and  the  observer  are  different  persons,  and  thus  permits  the  observer  to 
observe  the  mental  phenomena  more  freely  than  in  ordinary  introspection 
in  which  the  observer  and  the  experimenter  are  one  and  the  same  person 
and  so  attention  must  be  divided  between  two  different  tasks,  one  active 
and  one  passive,  which  fact  itself  is  of  great  detriment  to  the  efficacy  of 
introspection,  especially  when  it  has  to  do  with  merginal  conscious  experi- 
ences, as  is  the  case  with  the  present  study.  Galton^  in  his  early  experiments 
on  association  was  surprised  to  find  so  many  associations  connected  with 
a  single  word,  when  he  separated  the  active  and  the  passive  attitudes 
by  a  special  device.  (2)  As  a  comparative  study,  it  is  freed  from  any 
individual  peculiarities  or  prejudices  of  the  investigator.  And  lastly,  (3) 
as  the  totality  of  the  introspection  is  set  down,  it  permits  the  investigator 
to  take  a  fairer  view  of  the  position  and  significance  of  any  particular 
element  in  the  totality  of  the  mental  reaction  than  would  be  possible  in 
any  other  way.  This  last  characteristic  brings  this  study  into  connection 
at  some  points  with  the  three  important  studies  of  the  present  time,  viz. : 
the  study  of  mental  types,  the  study  of  thought-processes,  and  the  study 
of  associations.  The  study  of  individual  types  deals  principally  with 
the  individual  differences  of  the  means  to  understanding.  The  study  of 
thought-processes  deals  with  the  direct  conscious  concomitants  of  under- 
standing. And  the  study  of  association  deals  with  the  suggested  con- 
scious experiences  after  the  understanding.  Each  of  these  studies  con- 
siders only  one  section  of  the  conscious  concomitants  independent  of  the 
others,  all  of  which  can  be  found  in  the  preceding,  simultaneous  and  suc- 
ceeding concomitants  of  understanding. 

Thk  Technique  of  the  Experiments 

Three  series  of  experiments  were  made  in  succession  for 
the  same  purpose  and  mainly  under  the  same  conditions,  ex- 
cept for  differences  in  observers  and  apparatus  and  in  some 
added  elements  in  the  third  experiment. 

Stimuli.  The  stimuli  were  words  and  phrases  familiar  and 
unfamiliar  (or  easy  and  difficult),  concrete  and  abstract,  mostly 
English  or  foreign.  For  abstract  phrases  proverbs  were 
mostly  used.  For  example:  (familiar  concrete  words),  snake, 
hand,  mountain,  etc.;  (familiar  abstract  words)  philosophy, 
psychology,  fatigue,  etc. ;  (unfamiliar  concrete  words)  timbrel, 

^Psychologische  Studien,  Vol.  Ill,  No.  4,  Sept.,  1907. 
2F.  Galton:     Inquiry  into  Human  Faculty  and  its  Development.     Lon- 
don, 1883,  chapter  on  "Psychometry." 


1 6  KAKIS^ 

nostrum,  nabob,  etc.;  (unfamiliar  abstract  words)  pistology, 
oneirology,  noumenon,  etc.;  (familiar  concrete  phrases)  The 
sea  is  calm;  The  milk  smells  sour,  etc.;  (familiar  abstract 
phrases)  Union  makes  strength;  Duty  before  pleasure,  etc.; 
(unfamiliar  concrete  phrases)  Long  tongue,  short  hand;  One 
man  is  no  man,  etc.;  (unfamiliar  abstract  phrases)  A  sin  con- 
cealed is  half  pardoned;  Time  enough  is  little  enough,  etc. 
A  new  kind  of  stimulus  (meaningless  visual  stimulus),  in  the 
form  of  Chinese  characters,  was  added  to  the  verbal  stimuli 
in  the  third  experiment.  The  account  and  description  of 
these  will  be  given  later  (Part  III,  §  3). 

Forms  of  Reaction.  Two  forms  of  reaction,  an  active  (or 
short)  and  a  passive  (or  prolonged)  were  used.  In  the  active 
reaction  the  observer  was  asked  to  react  by  vaying  "yes" 
in  the  first  experiment,  and  by  pressing  an  electric  key  in 
the  second  and  third  experiments,  as  soon  as  he  understood 
the  word  or  phrase,  and  immediately  afterward  to  report  in 
the  order  of  its  occurrence  the  whole  process  (or  as  much 
as  he  could  recall),  which  took  place  in  the  interval  between 
the  sensory  perception  of  the  stimulus  and  the  reaction.  In 
case  he  did  not  understand  the  stimulus  the  observer  was 
asked  to  give  in  the  same  way  his  introspection  as  to  what 
occurred  in  the  interval  between  the  perception  of  the  stimulus 
and  a  signal  which  was  given  by  the  experimenter  after  the 
lapse  of  five  seconds  from  the  presentation  of  the  stimulus. 
In  the  passive  reaction,  the  observer  was  asked  to  remain 
passive  without  reacting,  but  to  let  the  processes  go  as  they 
would  until  a  signal  for  ceasing  (which  was  given  by  the 
experimenter  this  time  at  the  end  of  three  seconds)  and  then 
to  give  his  total  instropection  for  the  interval  as  before. 

Presentation  of  the  Stimulus.  Two  ways  of  presentation 
were  used:  an  auditory,  in  which  it  was  spoken  by  the  experi- 
menter, and  a  visual,  in  which  it  was  exposed. 

Apparatus.  The  apparatus  for  the  exposure  of  the  stimulus  and  the 
measurement  of  the  time  in  the  first  experiment  was  simply  a  set  of  cards 
with  typewritten  words  and  phrases  and  a  stopwatch  reading  to  one- 
fifth  of  a  second.  In  the  second  and  third  experiments  this  simple  appara- 
tus was  replaced  by  a  more  elaborate  one  constructed  for  the  purpose. 
It  consisted  of  three  principal  parts,  i.  e.,  (i),  an  exposer;  (2),  a  registering 
apparatus,  and  (3),  a  control  pendultmi.  The  exposer  consists  of  a  large 
board  with  an  opening  about  in  the  centre,  behind  which  stimulus-cards 
were  exposed  in  turn  by  means  of  the  rotation  of  a  large  wheel  attached 
behind  the  board.  Between  the  stimulus-card  and  the  opening  there 
was  a  sort  of  fan  which  closed  the  latter  until  it  (the  fan)  was  raised. 

The  fan  was  attached  to  one  end  of  an  electro-magnetic  lever  and  was 
raised  and  lowered  under  the  following  conditions:  (1),  in  case  of  the 
passive  reaction,  it  was  moved  automatically  by  means  of  the  control 
pendulum  which  made  and  broke  the  circuit  to  the  lever,  the  circuit  being 
kept  closed,  and  at  the  same  time  exposed  the  card  for  an  interval  of 
three  seconds;  (2),  in  case  of  the  active  reaction,  the  experimenter  moved 


A   STUDY   OF   UNDERSTANDING  1 7 

the  fan  by  a  make-key;  and  (3),  in  case  the  observer  did  not  react,  owing 
to  the  difficulty  of  understanding,  the  experimenter  lowered  the  fan  at 
the  end  of  five  seconds.  Two  mercury  contacts  at  the  free  end  of  the 
lever  made,  and  the  reaction  key  of  the  observer  broke,  another  circuit 
passing  through  an  electro-magnetic  marker  which  traced  the  reaction 
curves  on  the  smoked  surface  of  the  drum  of  a  Zimmermann  kymograph. 
The  marker  of  a  Jacquet  chronograph  cut  time  units  on  the  curve 
which  could  be  read  by  one-tenth  of  a  second.  Between  the  fan  and  the 
opening  there  were  two  shutters  or  slides  meeting  at  the  middle  of  the 
opening  when  both  were  closed,  and  exposing  one-half  of  the  whole  sur- 
face, when  one  was  opened,  which  was  done  for  words.  With  phrases 
both  slides  were  opened.  Special  care  was  taken  for  the  prevention  of 
all  distracting  noises.  In  its  rotation  the  apparatus  made  but  very  slight 
noise  which  was  almost  totally  shut  off  from  the  observer  by  the  large 
board  of  the  exposer.  The  most  comfortable  position  of  the  observer 
was  obtained  by  the  adjustable  inclinations  of  the  board  and  the  height 
of  the  chair. 

Observers.     Of  the  14  observers,  3  were  Japanese  students 
reading   and   speaking   English   fairly   well,    all   others   were 
English  speaking  people.     The  distribution  of  the  observers 
and  their  qualifications  were  as  follows: 
Experiment  I. 

An.  Outsider. 

Cff.  Student  of  psychology. 

Gl.  Student  of  psychology. 

Hi.  (Jap.)    Outsider. 

Kk.  (Jap.)  Student  of  psychology. 

Kn.  (Jap.)   Student  of  psychology. 
Experiment  II. 

Ac.  Student  of  psychology. 

Ky.  Student  of  psychology. 

Sm.  Student  of  psychology. 

St.  Student  of  psychology. 

Experiment  III. 

Ac.  Student  of  psychology. 

Ch.  Student  of  psychology. 

E.  M.  Student  of  psychology. 

L.  M.  Student  of  psychology. 

Sn.  Professor  of  psychology. 

Remark:  Several  auxiliary  experiments  and  minor  tests 
with  some  of  these  observers  and  several  others  were  made 
for  special  points.  The  description  of  these  experiments  has 
been  omitted  owing  to  the  limits  of  space,  and  references  only 
will  be  made  to  them. 

Samples  of  the  Protocols.  The  following  are  a  few  samples 
of  protocols  from  among  nearly  five  hundred  thus  obtained. 
They  represent  about  the  average  length  or  amount  of  the 
reports,  some  being  shorter  and  simpler,  while  others  are 
longer  and  more  minute.     They  are  the  reactions  of  three 

JOURNAI, — 2 


1 8  KAKISB 

observers,  one  from  each  experiment,  to  familiar  abstract 
words,  (A)  by  the  active  form  of  reaction,  and  (B),  by  the 
passive  form.  The  stimulus-words  for  observer  Cff.,  in  the 
first  experiment,  were  spoken,  while  those  for  others  were 
exposed.  Even  by  reading  these  few,  which  are  typical  in 
many  respects,  the  reader  may  find  traces  of  the  general 
influence  of  these  conditions  upon  certain  of  the  concomitants. 

A.    Active  Reactions 

Fault.  (lexp.  word  spoken;  Obs.  Cff.  No.  w.  20,  time,  i.  5'.)  '  'While 
you  were  saying  the  first  half  of  the  word  I  wondered  what  you  were  say- 
ing. Then  the  sound  Hngered.  And  I  got  the  consonant  at  the  end, 
and  the  meaning  at  the  same  time.  No  image,  but  just  feeling  of  mean- 
ing. There  was  a  feeling  of  satisfaction  and  at  the  same  time  dissatis- 
faction.    It  is  hard  to  analyse." 

Peace.  (II  exp.  word  exposed;  Obs.  Ac.  No.  iii-5,  time,  0.5''.)  "Ex- 
pectant attention  keyed  up  owing  to  the  delay  of  the  arrival  of  the  stimulus 
word.  I  read  it  in  inner  speech  and  grasped  the  word  and  relaxed.  I 
grasped  it  at  once  in  a  very  vague  way,  but  at  the  same  time  with  a  feeling 
of  assurance  that  I  was  right  although  I  had  very  little  of  any  imagery. " 

Psychology.  (Ill  exp.  word  exposed;  Obs.  Ch.  No.  iii-15,  tune,  0.5'.) 
"First  feeling  (of  recognition  of  the  form  of  the  word)  was  followed  in- 
stantly by  the  feeling  of  familiarity.  There  was  no  imagery.  In  this 
particular  case  it  appears  that  the  feeling  of  recognition  and  the  feeling  of 
familiarity  are  the  same  thing.  There  was  n't  any  imagery,  any  attempt 
to  define  the  word.     I  recognized  the  word.     Absolute  certainty." 

B.    Passive  Reactions 

Philosophy.  (I  exp.  word  spoken;  Obs.  Coif.  no.  w.  11.)  "I  got  the 
apperception  of  the  word  at  once.  It  came  in  connection  with  a  recent 
little  discussion  with  a  fellow  student  on  some  question  on  philosophy. 
It  occurred  just  this  morning.  I  had  just  the  sound  of  his  name,  very 
vague,  and  hardly  any  visual  image  of  the  place  where  we  had  discussed. 
Then  I  began  to  pronounce  the  name  of  'Weber'.  Also  the  word  'ex- 
amination' was  present.     But  no  definite  visual  image  of    anything." 

(Remark :  The  date  of  the  experiment  was  shortly  before  the  observer's 
doctor's  examination  and  he  was  then  reading  Weber's  History  of  Phi- 
losophy.) 

Apperception.  (II  exp.  word  exposed;  Obs.  Ac.  No.  w.  36.)  "Read  it 
in  the  same  way  as  before.  I  at  once  thought  of  Dr.  Sanford  in  the  lecture 
room  giving  the  definition  of  the  word.  I  had  a  vague  visual  image  of  him 
and  the  room." 

Apperception.  (Ill  exp.  No.  iii — i,  16,  word  exposed;  Obs.  Ch.)  "Pro- 
nounced the  word.  There  was  no  feehng  of  effort,  but  just  feeling  of 
familiarity  which  came  at  once.  I  did  n't  put  the  meaning  in  words,  but  had 
simply  a  feeling  of  what  it  meant.  Then  I  got  a  peculiar  visual  image  of 
myself  taking  notes  of  the  lectures  in  the  classroom.  The  name  'Wundt' 
came  into  my  mind  in  auditory  form.     The  feeling  was  rather  neutral." 

On  the  Working  up  of  the  Protocols.  These  protocols  were 
read  with  the  following  two  points  in  view:  First,  the  influ- 
ence of  the  conditions  upon  the  frequency  of  the  concomitants. 
The  conditions  were  divided  into,  a,  material  {i.  e.,  concrete- 
ness-abstractness  of  stimuli,  etc.)  b,  experimental  (whether 
the  stimuli  were  exposed  or  spoken,  etc.) ;  c,  individual  (wheth- 


A   STUDY   OF   UNDERSTANDING  1 9 

er  the  observer  belonged  to  the  visual  or  auditory  type,  etc.). 
The  primary  or  vital  influences  were  taken  chiefly  into  con- 
sideration though  sometimes  secondary  influences  were  also 
considered.  The  second  point  was  to  examine  the  relative 
positions  of  the  concomitants  with  reference  to  the  under- 
standing and  to  each  other  in  the  temporal  sequence  of  their 
occurrence. 

Part  I 

Conditions  of  the)  Preceding  Concomitants 

These  concomitants  were  reproductions  of  the  sensory  com- 
ponents of  the  stimulus  word  or  phrase,  i.  e.,  audi  to-motor 
reading  and  visual  imagery  of  the  stimulus.  In  ordinary 
introspection  these  events  are  often  overlooked  by  many,  as 
we  are  accustomed  to  attend  only  to  the  meaning  and  not  to 
the  means  by  which  we  reach  it.  According  to  their  kind 
and  frequency  they  have  been  sometimes  used  as  criteria  for 
individual  differences.  Sometimes  they  have  been  identified 
with  meaning  itself.  In  our  experiments  they  were  first  to  occur, 
following  directly  after  the  sense  perception  of  the  stimulus, 
excepting  some  cases  with  the  visual  reproductions  which 
frequently  followed,  or  occurred  simultaneously  with,  the 
understanding.  With  easy  or  familiar  stimuli  the  understand- 
ing followed  immediately  without  any  intermediary  imagery. 
With  unfamiliar  or  difficult  stimuli  there  occurred  often  inter- 
mediary imagery  such  as  the  appearance  of  other  verbal 
images  in  the  form  of  synonymes,  translations,  definitions, 
etc.,  or  suggested  object  images.  As  these  were  in  their 
nature  exactly  identical  with  suggested  images  or  those 
occurring  after  the  understanding  with  easy  stimuli  we  shall 
consider  them  later  in  Part  II. 

§  I.      AUDITO-MOTOR   REPRODUCTION   OF   THE   STIMULUS 

Influence  upon  the  frequency  of  audito-motor  reproduction 
of  the  stimulus  (i.  e.,  the  reading  of  the  word  in  inner  speech) 
when  (a)  the  stimulus  was  exposed  and  (b)  when  it  was  spoken. 

The  influence  of  these  conditions  was  so  marked  and  definite 
that  the  results  of  the  three  successive  experiments  showed 
the  same  tendency  and  the  influence  of  other  conditions  was 
almost  negligible. 

The  total  number  of  cases  of  this  form  of  imagery  in  ten 
observers  was  291  out  of  311'  or  93%  when  the  stimuli  were 

^  From  this  total,  the  first  one  or  two  (tentative)  reactions  by  most 
observers  are  excluded.  Also  the  reactions  of  four  observers  An.  Kk.  Sm. 
St.  are  excluded,  for  the  reason  that  in  case  of  the  first  two,  the  stimulus 
was  spoken  only.  In  the  case  of  Sm.  the  tendency  was  not  clear  in  the 
earlier  reactions,  with  St.  it  was  not  clear  in  any  of  the  reactions ;  about  these 
see  the  succeeding  accounts. 


20  KAKIS^ 

exposed;  while  it  occurred  in  only  17  out  of  176*  cases,  or 
9%,  when  the  stimuli  were  spoken.  And  these  17  cases  oc- 
curred mostly  when  the  stimuli  were  rather  diflficult  or  the 
pronunciation  by  the  experimenter  were  indistinct. 

We  may  conclude,  therefore,  that  the  inner  reading  of  the 
word  generally  occurs  when  it  is  exposed,  and  occurs  seldom 
when  the  stimulus  is  easy  and  spoken.  In  other  words,  the 
appearance  and  non-appearance  of  the  reading  of  the  stimulus 
in  inner  speech  is  primarily  conditioned  by  the  way  of  pre- 
senting the  stimulus. 

For  the  determination  of  the  secondary  influences  affecting 
the  frequency  of  this  imagery,  i.  e.,  influences  arising  from 
individual  differences  and  from  qualities  of  the  material, 
some  minor  tests  were  made.  The  first  thing  to  be  mentioned 
is  the  fact  that  at  the  start  the  majority  of  our  observers 
did  not  know  about  this  tendency,  but  became  aware  of  it 
after  a  few  reactions,  owing,  perhaps,  to  the  summation  of 
the  faint  impressions  occurring  repeatedly  at  the  same  place, 
i.  e.,  at  the  beginning,  in  each  reaction.  One  observer  (Hi) 
belonging  to  a  very  pronounced  motor  speech  type  was  not 
aware  of  this  tendency  at  first,  but  a  simple  test  of  reading 
with  the  mouth  open,  etc.,  brought  his  attention,  to  his  great 
surprise,  to  what  he  was  actually  doing.  A  lady  (extra  ob- 
server) who  when  asked  about  this  tendency  denied  it,  or 
was  at  least  doubtful  about  it,  was  also  surprised  to  find  it 
after  a  simple  test,  and  confessed  that  in  her  whole  life  she 
was  never  aware  of  it  before.  With  another  extra  observer 
(Ms),  to  whom  the  presence  of  this  tendency  was  doubtful, 
a  test  with  simultaneous  counting  or  speaking  of  a  word 
showed  that  he  could  not  read  understandingly  while  they 
were  continued.  With  two  observers  (Sm,  St)  who  said 
they  read  by  eye,  the  results  of  a  test  in  the  instantaneous 
grasping  of  a  list  of  unconnected  words  or  phrases  showed 
no  differences  from  other  observers,  either  in  the  amounts 
of  reproduction  or  in  the  ways  of  reading,  i.  e.,  instead  of 
grasping  the  whole  at  once  at  a  glance  they  also  read  the  words 
one  by  one  in  the  same  way  as  others.  One  of  them  (Sm), 
who  denied  the  presence  of  this  tendency  in  the  reading  of 
some  phrases,  found  it  later  almost  always  with  words. 
There  was  thus  only  one  observer  remaining  who  did  not  yet 
find  in  himself  this  tendency.  No  further  tests  with  him 
have  yet  been  made,  so  I  cannot  absolutely  decide  at  present 
whether  this  process  is  really  lacking  in  him  or  he  is  only 

^  This  smaller  number  of  spoken  stimuli  is  due  to  the  fact  that  in  the 
majority  of  the  second  and  the  whole  of  third  experiment  the  stimulus 
was  only  exposed. 


A   STUDY   OF   UNDERSTANDING  91 

not  yet  aware  of  what  he  actually  does,  but  from  the  results  of 
the  test  above  stated  and  from  the  reports  of  many  about 
the  difficulty  of  the  introspection  of  this  tendency,  the  most 
probable  supposition  is  that  he  is  subject  to  it  in  spite  of 
himself. 

The  distinction  between  the  auditory  and  motor  elements  in 
inner  reading  our  observers  found  it  hard  to  make.  But  if 
we  call  the  inner  reading  with  the  consciousness  of  the  inner- 
vation or  movements  of  the  organs  of  speech  motor,  and  the 
inner  reading  without  these  auditory,  then  there  was  at 
least  one  observer  (Hi)  who  belonged  to  a  pronounced  motor 
type,  like  that  of  Strieker.  With  difficult  words  or  phrases 
most  of  our  observers  went  over  to  the  motor  speech  form, 
and  inner  reading  became  pronounced.  With  familiar  words 
of  many  syllables  or  with  familiar  phrases,  mutilated  reading 
was  not  uncommon.  In  the  repeated  reading,  in  inner  speech, 
of  unfamiliar  and  difficult  phrases  (mostly  proverbs),  reading 
with  emphasis  upon  the  principal  words,  or  first  a  quick 
reading  of  the  whole  followed  by  a  return  to  the  principal 
words,  was  also  frequent. 

The  conclusions  suggested  by  these  studies  are:  (i)  that 
motor  reading  in  the  sense  above  defined  is  not  universal  as 
was  believed  by  Strieker ^  and  assumed  by  Max  Muller,^ 
but  is  limited  to  some  individuals  only,  and  with  average  in- 
dividuals, to  the  reading  of  difficult  words.  (2)  Auditory 
reading  in  the  above  sense,  on  the  contrary,  seems  universal 
and  necessary  for  the  understanding  of  exposed  words  or 
phrases,  which  favors  the  view  that  the  connection  between 
the  auditory  and  "concept  centres"  is  immediate,  while 
that  for  the  other  senses,  i.  e.,  motor  and  visual,  is  indirect.' 
(3)  Expressed  in  terms  of  conditions,  the  occurrence  of  audi- 
tory reading  is  mainly  conditioned  by  the  method  of  experi- 
mentation (i.  e.,  exposure),  while  that  of  motor  reading  is 
influenced  by  (i),  the  method,''  (2)  the  material,  and  (3),  in- 
dividual  differences. 


^Strieker:  Ueber  die  Sprachvorstellungen.  Wien,  1880.  One  of  his 
tests  is:  "Keeping  the  mouth  open  and  the  tongue  firm  try  to  think  the 
words  papa,  morning,  stammer,  etc. ;  If  you  do  not  succeed  it  means  that 
a  motor  image  is  necessary  to  your  inner  speech." 

2  Max  Miiller:  Lectures  on  the  Science  of  Thought.  1887  (ist  ed.1883), 
Chicago,  In  his  letter  to  Galton  he  unconsciously  betrays  his  type  in 
these  words:  "Yet  if  we  watch  ourselves,  it  is  very  curious  that  we  can 
often  feel  the  vocal  chords  and  the  muscles  of  the  mouth  moving  as  if  we 
were  speaking,"     Ibid.,  Appendix,  p.  8. 

3  Cf.  Dodge:      Die   motorische  Wortvorstellungen,    Wien,  1896,  p,  62. 
^  The  writer  thinks  it  very   likely   that   even   persons  of   pronounced 

motor  type  would  not  experience  innervation  or  movements  of  speech- 
organs  in  the  case  of  hearing  easy  or  familiar  words. 


22  KAKISe 

§2.      VISUAI.  REPRODUCTION  OF  THE  STIMULUS 

Influence  upon  the  frequency  of  visual  reproduction  of  the 
stimulus  when  (a)  it  was  exposed  and  when  (b)  it  was  spoken. 

There  occurred  30  cases  of  visual  imagery  of  the  stimulus 
out  of  81  reactions  with  3  observers  {Gl,  Hi,  Kn)  when  the 
stimuli  were  spoken,  and  not  a  single  case  occurred  in  6 1  reac- 
tions, with  the  same  observers,  when  the  stimuli  were  exposed. 
With  two  other  observers  {Ac,  Cf)  no  case  occurred — neither 
when  the  stimuli  were  exposed  (71  reactions)  nor  when  they 
were  spoken  (65  reactions).  With  the  rest  of  the  observers 
none  occurred  in  179  reactions  to  the  stimuli  which  were 
exposed. 

Of  the  three  observers  with  whom  this  form  occurred,  two 
were  Japanese.  This  naturally  led  to  the  suspicion  that  the 
frequency  of  this  imagery  for  them  might  perhaps  be  the 
result  of  unfamiliarity  with  the  English  language,  and  not 
to  individual  peculiarity.  This  suspicion  was,  however,  soon 
dispelled  by  an  extra  test  with  a  number  of  Japanese  words 
as  stimuli  which  showed  the  same  results;  the  only  difference 
being  that  with  Japanese  words  orally  presented,  the  visual 
image  of  the  stimulus  was  directly  followed  by  understanding 
or  suggested  images,  while  with  English  words,  the  visual 
image  of  the  stimulus  was  sometimes  succeeded  by  the  image 
of  the  corresponding  Japanese  word  before  the  arrival  of 
understanding  or  suggested  images. 

For  instance:  'Traveller* — (Obs.  Hi.).  "First  I  heard  distinctly  the 
sound  'travel'.  There  was  a  moment  of  hesitation  and  doubt.  Then  I  saw 
the  printed  image  of  the  word  'traveller'  accompanied  by  the  images  of 
the  Chinese  characters,  and  at  the  same  time  full  realization  of  the 
meaning.     Then  I  saw  mentally  a  traveller  walking  on  Main  Street. " 

The  form  and  localization  of  the  image  were  almost  con- 
stant in  the  same  individual.  All  three  localized  the  image, 
usually  at  a  distance  of  one  or  two  feet  in  front.  Two  ob- 
servers saw  the  image  in  handwritten  form,  the  other  in 
printed  form. 

About  the  frequency  and  conditions  of  suggested  (associated) 
verbal  imagery  we  shall  see  later. 

These  results  lead  to  the  conclusion:  (i)  that  the  visual 
image  of  the  stimulus  word  occurs  only  occasionally  when  the 
stimulus  is  spoken,  and  scarcely  occurs  at  all  when  it  is  exposed. 
(2)  There  are  great  individual  differences  in  this  experience 
as  in  the  case  of  motor  speech;  in  other  words,  this  imagery 
is  especially  conditioned  by  the  method  of  experimentation 
and  individual  differences. 

The  results  of  the  above  study  in  so  far  as  they  bear 
upon  the  validity  of  the  customary  method  for  the  deter- 
mination of  individual  types  are,  in  certain  respects,  negative, 


A   STUDY   OP   UNDERSTANDING  2$ 

viz.:  (i)  We  cannot  wholly  rely  upon  the  questionnaire 
method  in  the  study  of  types,  because  there  are  many  people 
who  are  not  aware  of  what  they  are  actually  doing.  (2)  Be- 
cause the  frequency  of  these  speech  forms  primarily  depends 
upon  the  manner  of  the  presentations  of  the  words,  we  can- 
not at  once  label  an  individual  as,  for  instance,  of  the 
auditory  or  the  motor  type  simply  because  he  says  that  he 
pronounces  when  he  reads  or  when  he  writes,  etc.^ 

Part  II 
Conditions  of  the  Succeeding  Concomitants 

When  the  stimuli  were  easy  and  familiar,  the  images  of 
other  words  than  the  stimuli  and  the  images  of  objects  or  events 
suggested  by  the  stimuli,  or,  in  short,  what  I  might  call  "sug- 
gested images"^  usually  followed  the  understanding.  When 
the  stimuli  were  difficult  or  unfamiliar,  they  frequently  pre- 
ceded the  understanding,  but  followed  the  images  of  the 
stimulus  words  or  phrases.  These  cases  of  preceding  sug- 
gested images  I  will  call  "intermediary  images."  All  these 
images,  the  preceding,  intermediary  and  succeeding  sug- 
gested images,  were  of  the  same  kinds  dififering  only  in  their 
temporal  relations  to  understanding. 

All  the  suggested  images  which  we  need  consider  may  be 
divided  into  two  main  classes,  according  to  the  nature  of  their 
constituents :  ( i )  object  images,  which  are  the  representations 
of,  or  references  to,  concrete  objects  or  events;  and  (2)  verbal 
images,  which  are  the  visual  or  audito-motor  representations 
of  suggested  or  associated  words. 

I  shall  begin  with  the  succeeding  suggested  images  or 
images  following  the  understanding  of  familiar  stimuli,  and 
first  with  one  of  the  object  images,  namely  with  memory 
images. 

^  These  considerations  seem  to  be  neglected  by  the  following  authors 
Patini,  K. :  Contributo  alio  studio  sperimentale  della  formula  endophasia. 
Napoli,  1907.  Cf.  p.  26,  observation  xlv,  and  others.  Ribot,  T. 
L 'evolution  des  idees  generales.  Paris,  1897.  Cf.  Eng.  tr.  1899,  p.  114  ff. 
Max  Mtiller,  op.  cit.  Appendix  p.  26.  There  in  his  answer  to  Romanes  he 
wants  to  prove  the  universality,  among  all  individuals  as  well  as  under  all 
circumstances,  of  motor  speech  in  thinking,  by  referring  to  special  cases, 
and  says :  '  'How  could  I  hold  pronunciation  necessary  for  thought  when 
I  am  silent  while  I  am  reading,  while  I  am  writing?"  When  one  listens, 
it  is  not  necessary  for  understanding  to  pronounce  each  word. 

^The  term  "image"  is  used  here  in  the  broadest  sense  including  faint 
and  indefinite  experiences  if  they  refer  to  concrete  objects  or  events  which 
can  be  in  other  cases  distinctly  represented.  For  instance,  such  experiences 
as,  "I  thought  of  that  typewriter,"  or,  "I  thought  of  my  buying  a  type- 
writer at  a  store  about  a  year  ago,"  etc.,  were  also  included  as  images 
though  it  is  by  no  means  clear  in  these  cases  what  kinds  of  sensory  imagery, 
(«.  e.,  visual,  auditory,  kinesthetic,  etc.),  were  actually  present.  For 
further  analysis  of  these  experiences  see  Part  III. 


24  KAKISE 

Experimental  conditions.  The  numerical  results  given  in 
the  following  discussion  are  from  the  records  of  reactions  to 
familiar  stimulus  words  (not  phrases)  ^  by  the  ten  observers 
who  assisted  in  the  first  and  second  experiments.  Results 
from  the  third  experiment,  which  confirmed  those  of  the 
preceding  ones,  are  sometimes  referred  to.  The  frequency- 
ratios  of  various  sorts  of  imagery  are  regarded  merely  as 
representing  general  tendencies  or  main  proportions  and  not 
at  all  as  expressing  exact  or  even  approximate  relations. 
The  total  number  of  reactions  to  easy  words^  in  the  first  and 
second  experiments  under  the  different  conditions,  whose  in- 
fluences we  are  about  to  examine,  was  285. 

§  I .      MEMORY  IMAGES 

By  memory  images  here  are  understood  those  which  refer 
to  particular  personal  experiences  with  the  objects  or  events 
indicated  by  the  stimulus.  They  can  always  be  localized  in 
space  (where)  and  time  (when).  They  are  sometimes  called 
reminiscent  associations. 

Results  of  the  Experiments.  1.  This  imagery  not  only  fol- 
lowed the  understanding,  but  also  made  the  terminus  of  the 
reactions  in  which  it  was  found,  i.  e.,  other  suggested  images 
when  they  occurred  generally  preceded,  and  seldom  succeeded, 
the  memory  imagery  in  the  allotted  intervals  of  the  time, 
owing,  perhaps,  to  the  richness  of  contents  or  the  vividness 
of  the  latter. 

For  instance:  Wheel  (passive,  spoken  stimulus,  Obs.  Gl.  No.  w.  22). 
"First  thought  of  all  kinds  of  wheels,  blurred  and  indistinct  images  of 
multitude  of  wheels.  Then  the  one  I  saw  recently  emerged  very  clearly 
in  mental  picture." 

Vacation.  (Passive,  word  exposed,  Obs. .4c.  No.  w.  5.) '  'I  read  and  spelt  the 
word  twice  mentally.  I  thought  of  week-after-next  and  the  work  that  I 
planned  to  do  then.  I  think  I  thought  of  that  because  I  have  been  re- 
cently thinking  about  the  work  to  be  done.  And  then  I  recalled  the  con- 
versation I  had  in  the  Bloomingdale  hospital  a  few  minutes  ago.  Dr. 
C,  proposed  to  meet  his  class  next  week.  Some  one  said  we  had  vacation 
then  and  Dr.  C.  had  trouble  to  understand  on  account  of  his  ear  trouble . 

1  The  results  with  phrases  were  not  calculated  for  the  following  reasons : 
(i).  The  number  of  words  used  as  stimuli,  was  greater  than  that  of  phrases; 
(2),  there  were  no  new  kinds  of  suggested  images  found  in  phrase-reac- 
tions, those  in  the  word-reactions  and  phrase-reactions  being  practically 
the  same  (Ribot  found  the  same  results;  Cf.  op.  114  ff.)  the  only  definite 
difference  being  that  with  phrases  the  suggestions  were  more  definite  a 
matter  which  we  shall  consider  later;  (3),  furthermore  with  phrases,  not 
only  the  suggested  images  were  less  in  number  and  more  limited  in  variety 
but  very  frequently  there  occurred  none  at  all,  perhaps  because  the  reac- 
tions took  more  time  and  energy  than  those  with  words. 

2  Ease  and  difficulty  are  only  relative  distinctions,  some  of  the  easy 
stimuli  turned  out  to  be  rather  difficult  or  unfamiliar  ones  to  some  obser- 
vers.    Cf.  the  remark  under  I  6  (Difficult  stimuli). 


A   STUDY   OF   UNDERSTANDING  2$ 

The  scene  of  the  classroom  was  pretty  vivid,  and  it   was  rather  inter- 
esting, amusing. " 

2.  This  imagery  in  the  case  of  passive  reactions  oc- 
curred in  more  than  tw^o-fifths  of  all  the  reactions  of  all  the 
observers,  the  figures  being  102  cases  out  of  242  passive  reac- 
tions to  easy  words  for  ten  observers  with  no  considerable 
individual  variations  among  them.  The  active  reactions 
with  easy  words  (not  phrases)  in  the  first  experiment  were  in 
all  but  37,  made  by  three  observers  (An,  Gl,  Kn).  In  these  37 
there  were  four  cases  of  the  sort  of  imagery  now  under  consid- 
eration, all  in  the  15  reactions  of  observer  ^w  alone.  The  results 
of  the  third  experiment,  in  which  the  majority  was  of  active  re- 
actions, showed  also  very  definitely  that  a  memory  image 
seldom  occurs  in  active  reactions.  In  all  the  cases  in  which  it 
occurred,  the  observers  reported  it  as  occurring  after  the  reac- 
tions or  at  any  rate  after  the  understanding. 

3.  Abstractness  in  the  stimulus  words  had  little  or  no  in- 
fluence on  the  frequency  of  this  imagery  in  passive  reactions 
to  easy  stimuli,  or,  if  any,  tended  more  toward  inducing 
recent  memory  images  than  did  the  concrete  words.  Of  50 
cases  of  recent  memory  images^  out  of  151  reactions  in  the  case 
of  five  observers  {Ac,  Gl,  Hr,  Kn,  Ky)  30  cases  occurred  with 
74  abstract  words  and  20  with  77  concrete  words  with  no  con- 
siderable individual  variations.  The  same  general  tendency 
is  shown  in  the  results  with  the  rest  of  the  observers.  Like- 
wise, whether  the  stimuli  were  spoken  or  exposed  made  no 
noticeable  difference  with  the  frequency  of  imagery  of  this 
sort. 

4.  Beside  the  passivity  of  reaction,  the  most  important 
factor  for  the  occurrence  of  this  imagery  was  the  recency  of 
association,  (a)  Out  of  106  memory  associations  in  285  total 
reactions  82  were  recent  associations  or  reminiscence  of  events 
falling  within  a  period  of  not  more  than  one  or  two  years 
previous,  2 1  of  remote  associations,  and  only  3  of  boyhood 
associations.^  (b)  Quite  insignificant  and  accidental  associ- 
ations, alone,  without  any  emotional  excitation  or  logical 
connection  or  repetition,  by  sheer  power  of  recency,  occurred 
frequently,  pushing  other  images  aside. 

^  These  were  the  most  frequent  of  all  memory  images ;  for  details,  see 
the  sections  to  follow. 

2  These  results  rather  contradict  those  found  by  Galton.  The  numbers 
which  he  found  were:  boyhood  associations  48,  manhood  57,  while  "quite 
recent  events"  had  only  19,  in  his  four  times  repeated  experiment  with  75 
words.  These  are,  of  course,  the  combined  results  of  the  pure  revivability 
and  the  fixity  or  tenacity  of  associations  as  they  were  repeated.  But  even 
in  his  series  of  the  first  reactions  the  frequency  of  recent  associations  is 
quite  low.     Cf.  ibid.,  p.  195. 


26  KAKISE 

For  instance:  Ink  (Obs.  Ky),  "Pronounced  the  word.  Idea  of  the 
blackness  was  the  first  thing.  Then  I  thought  of  those  ink-blotters  I  got 
this  morning  at  a  down- town  store.  There  was  a  vague  image  of  blotters. 
I  had  also  clear  image  of  my  fingers  being  dabbled  with  ink  which  occurred 
a  couple  of  days  ago." 

Vacation.  (Obs.  Sn.)  "I  think  I  saw  the  middle  of  the  word  and 
noticed  the  syllable  'cat'.  Then  I  read  the  whole  word  to  myself.  I 
think  I  had  an  incipient  pronunciation  of  it  in  inner  speech.  Then  I  re- 
membered that  this  word  was  the  word  which  Dr.  Bolton  read  when  we 
came  here  yesterday.  I  didn't  get  any  definite  image  except  that  asso- 
ciation. I  just  thought  of  it,  an  idea  of  direction  rather  than  a  visuali- 
zation. That  idea  of  direction  is  very  frequent  with  me  as  the  first  thing 
to  come  in  case  of  such  an  association  as  that." 

(c)  With  such  words  as  vacation,  memory,  fatigue,  pedagogy, 
philosophy,  apperception,  etc.,  which  were  purposely  selected 
and  used  in  the  third  experiment  (mixed  among  other  words), 
the  observers  had  in  nearly  all  reactions,  in  spite  of  the  ab- 
stractness  of  the  words,  a  concrete  image  in  the  form  of  a  recent 
memory  association  which  the  experimenter  could  often  pre- 
dict from  his  own  share  in  the  same  recent  and  repeated 
experiences,  e.  g.,  the  images  of  certain  professors,  the  class- 
rooms, certain  authors,  etc. 

For  instance,  Apperception  (Obs.  E.  M.).  "First  slight  tension  and  ac- 
tion on  the  motor  side  with  the  pronunciation  of  the  word.  Then  the  mean- 
ing came,  but  there  was  an  effort  to  get  the  psychological  meaning.  I  had 
a  rather  clear  visual  image  of  pages  in  Wundt's  'Outline  of  Psychology' 
in  which  the  thing  is  treated.  And  then  the  visual  image  of  Dr.  S.  in  the 
lecture  room  and  also  some  auditory  image  of  his  voice." 

Pedagogy.  (Obs.  Sn.)  "I  was  not  quite  ready.  I  read  the  word  in  inner 
speech  but  not  very  loud,  and  was  not  quite  sure  whether  I  read  it  correctly. 
So  I  read  it  again  and  I  had  a  faint  feehng  that  I  knew  the  word.  Then 
I  thought  of  the  direction  of  Dr.  B's  room  and  probably  had  also 
a  very  vague  suggestion  of  Dr.  B.  himself.  The  consciousness  of  direc- 
tion was  very  clear.  I  had  the  word  'teaching,'  probably  in  inner 
speech." 

Remark.  Ribot's  "thinking  by  analogy"  by  which  he 
means  such  reactions  as  "I  thought  of  Hume's  theory  of 
causality",  for  the  stimulus  ''cause'';  or  the  recalling  of 
"Littre's  definition"  for  the  word  ''Justice'',  and  so  forth 
{ih.,  I  i4ff .),  is  merely  our  "memory  imagery,"  and  cannot  there- 
fore be  regarded  as  a  special  mark  of  individual  differences. 
The  whole  matter  rests  upon  the  duration  (slowness  or  quick- 
ness) of  reactions.  Besides,  with  these  familiar  words,  and 
especially  in  scholars,  the  understanding  of  what  the  words 
mean  precedes  any  suggested  images,  so  that  such  memory 
images  are  not  means  to  understanding  but  the  results  of 
natural  and  spontaneous  associations. 

§  2.      INDICATIVE  IMAGES. 

For  the  lack  of  a  better  name,  I  have  called  "indicative 
images"  those  which  referred  to  particular  objects  found  in  the 


A   STUDY  OP  UNDERSTANDING  27 

room  at  the  time  of  the  experiment.  For  instance :  Typewriter, 
I  thought  of  that  typewriter  on  the  table.  Experiment, — I 
thought  of  this  experiment,  etc.  In  their  psychological  nature, 
a  strict  line  of  demarcation  between  this  sort  of  imagery  and 
recent  memory  imagery  is  hard  to  draw  as  the  one  gradually 
passes  into  the  other;  yet  I  found  a  separation,  by  the  con- 
ventional definition  above  given,  necessary  in  the  treatment 
of  the  results  for,  in  the  first  place,  the  frequency  of  indicative 
magery  was  markedly  more  pronounced  under  certain  con- 
ditions than  that  of  memory  imagery ;  and  in  the  second  place, 
it  seemed  to  be  influenced  by  a  new  factor  soon  to  be  mentioned. 
So  that,  when,  for  example,  the  word  Entrance  suggested 
to  some  observers  the  aperture  of  the  experimenting  apparatus, 
and  to  others  the  door  of  the  experimenting  room,  while  to 
a  third  the  gateway  of  the  university  or  that  of  the  library,  and 
to  a  fourth  the  entrance  to  the  court  house  of  this  city,  and  to 
a  fifth  the  entrance  to  the  capitol  in  Washington  and  finally  to 
a  sixth  some  front  steps  leading  up  to  a  building,  I  put  the 
first  two  into  the  category  of  the  indicative  imagery,  the 
third  and  the  fourth  into  the  recent,  the  fifth  into  the  remote 
memory  imagery  and  the  sixth  into  the  general  visual  object 
imagery  described  later  on. 

Sometimes  one  and  the  same  response,  therefore,  may  be- 
come the  one  or  the  other  of  these  types  of  imagery  according 
to  circumstances.  For  instance,  with  the  word  Seminary,  if 
one  thinks  of  Dr.  H — 's  seminary,  or  Dr.  S — 's  or  Dr.  B — 's, 
it  will  be  a  case  of  indicative  imagery  when  the  word  was  given 
there,  while  it  will  be  recent  memory  imagery  when  the  ex- 
periment was  performed  at  some  other  place,  and  remote 
memory  imagery  when  it  was  made  years  after  the  personal 
experiences  of  the  observers. 

But  a  very  small  number  of  appropriate  stimulus  words 
for  the  arousal  of  imagery  of  this  sort,  such  as  room,  window, 
entrance,  watch,  hand,  typewriter,  experiment,  etc.,  happened 
to  be  found  in  our  list  of  stimulus  words.  Nevertheless  the 
following  tendencies  were  rather  definitely  brought  out.  i. 
The  occurrence  of  imagery  of  this  sort  is  primarily  conditioned 
by  a  special  k-pd  of  stimulus  words  which  I  may  call  "in- 
dicative words,"  such  as  those  just  mentioned.  2.  With 
these  words  this  imagery  occurred  in  far  greater  number  of 
cases  when  the  words  were  spoken  than  when  they  were  ex- 
posed, the  frequency  ratios  being  respectively  89%  and  19%. 
Further  inferences  with  reference  to  this  sort  of  imagery  are 
impossible  from  the  data  at  hand,  but  the  following  one  is  also 
suggested  by  the  results,  namely  that  this  sort  of  imagery  is 
determined  by  a  new  factor  which  I  might  call  "implicit 
context";  in  other  words,  the  spoken  stimulus  word  becomes 


28  KAKISE 

virtually  in  its  effect  a  phrase  especially  adapted  to  induce 
imagery  of  this  kind.  In  daily  life  we  are  accustomed  to  react 
to  a  singe  word  under  such  circumstance  when  the  object  indi- 
cated by  the  word  is  near  at  hand  and  the  speaker  wants 
something  to  be  done  with  the  object.  A  single  uttered  word 
then  is,  in  fact,  an  imperative  sentence,  meaning,  for  instance, 
'Please  give  me  that  thing',  or  'Look  at  it',  etc.,  and  the  per- 
son addressed  turns  his  attention  instinctively  to  the  object 
mentioned.  Now  in  the  experiment  when  an  "indicative 
word"  is  uttered  the  observer  falls  unconsciously  into  this 
attitude,  because  of  the  similarity  of  situation;  while,  when 
it  is  exposed,  this  link  of  habitual  associations  becomes  broken, 
whence  the  less  frequency  of  this  sort  of  imagery. 

In  the  temporal  order  of  occurrence,  this  imagery  was,  in 
general,  the  promptest  of  all  suggested  images,  occurring 
immediately  after,  or  sometimes  simultaneously  with,  the 
understanding. 

Remark.  In  this  kind  of  reactions,  which  were,  as  a  rule, 
rather  reflex,  the  full  reahzation  of  the  meaning,  such  as  rich- 
ness of  concept,  came  often  later  than  the  arrival  of  this 
imagery,  though  the  understanding  of  the  word  in  the  sense 
of  recognition  obviously  preceded  it.  To  these  varieties  of 
meaning  we  shall  return  in  Part  III. 

§  3.     ORGANIC   IMAGES 

Under  this  term  I  understand  a  reference  to,  or  becoming 
aware  of,  the  organic  sensations  or  feelings  either  produced 
directly  or  revived,  which  are  habitually  associated  with  the 
words.  The  term  organic  sensations  is  used  here  in  its  broad- 
est sense,  comprising  kinesthesia  or  sensations  of  muscular 
movements  or  innervation,  as  well  as  sensations  attending 
the  conditions  of  internal  organs. 

For  instance:  Excitation:  {Ac)  "Read  it  in  the  same  way.  I  tried 
to  state  it  in  the  sense  given  by  Wundt.  Then  I  tried  to  think  about 
the  psychological  evidences  of  excitation,  and  simulated  to  myself  its 
bodily  state  unconsciously."  Rain.  {Ky)  "First  pronounced  the  word 
inwardly.  Next  there  was  a  visual  image  of  raining  just  outside  of  this 
window  (of  the  experimenting  room).  There  was  also  an  idea  of  wetness 
just  in  the  form  of  bodily  sensation  in  which  no  visual  or'  ^uditory  elements 
were  discernible." 

Results.  I .  This  imagery  occurred  in  a  very  small  number 
of  cases.  2.  It  occurred  only,  (a)  with  a  special  class  of 
stimulus  words  suggestive  of  this  imagery  or  what  I  might 
call  "Organic  words",  with  which  the  organic  associations 
(or  components)  more  or  less  predominate,  such  as,  respiration, 
suffocation,  fatigue,  uneasiness y  etc.,  and  (b)  with  passive  (or 
prolonged)    reactions.      3.   It    seldom    occurred    alone    but 


A   STUDY   OF    UNDERSTANDING  29 

usually  accompanied  by  other  suggested  images,  such  as  verbal 
and  visual  imagery.  In  cases  of  its  concurrence  with  these 
images  it  usually  succeeded  the  latter,  i.  e.,  it  was  less  prompt 
in  its  occurrence  than  visual  and  verbal  suggested  images. 

§4.      GENERAI.   VISUAI^-OBJECT   IMAGES 

These  images,  instead  of  referring  to  any  particular  object 
or  event  of  past  experiences  like  memory  images,  represent, 
predominantly  in  visual  terms,  merely  types  or  concrete  ex- 
amples of  objects  designated  by  the  stimulus  words.  For 
instance,  Box — I  had  a  visual  image  of  a  wooden  box.  This  is 
a  case  of  simple  object  imagery  in  which  only  a  single  object 
is  represented.  It  occurred  often  that  many  objects  belong- 
ing to  the  same  class  were  visualized  simultaneously  or  in  quick 
successions,  producing  VN^hat  I  may  call  "complex  object 
imagery."  In  such  cases  the  visualizations  were,  as  a  rule, 
faint  and  incomplete.  For  instance.  Animal  {An) — I  thought 
of  all  sorts  of  animals  moving  alive,  etc.  Vacation  (L.  M.) — (I 
had  a  very  rapid  visual  impression  of  landscapes.  The  ideas 
or  faint  visual  images  of  a  whole  summer. 

Sometimes  these  general  visual  images,  which  as  a  rule 
preceded  memory  images,  turned  out  to  be  the  first  stage  of 
the  latter,  in  the  same  way  as  free  associations  are  sometimes 
traced  to  particular  incidents.  For  instance.  Cross,  {Ac)  — 
When  I  heard  the  word,  there  came  at  once  the  picture  of  a 
crucifix.  It  seemed  to  be  traced  to  those  pictures  of  cruci- 
fixes which  Dr.  H —  showed  us  in  his  lecture  on  Christ.  It 
impressed  me  at  that  time. 

Results.  I.  There  were  great  individual  differences  in  the 
frequency  of  this  imagery,  ranging  from  zero  to  53%,  in  the 
percentages  for  the  ten  •observers.  2.  In  the  case  of  this 
imagery,  reversing  the  case  with  memory  imagery,  the  con- 
creteness  and  abstractness  of  the  stimulus  word  influenced 
the  frequency  of  the  imagery  in  a  marked  degree,  the  frequency 
with  concrete  words  being  nearly  three  times  as  great  as  that 
with  abstract  words.  3.  The  frequency  of  imagery  in  all 
the  reactions  was  51  cases  in  a  total  of  286,  falling  thus  far 
below  that  of  the  memory  imagery,  but  rising  far  above  that 
of  the  organic  imagery.  4.  In  cases  of  concurrence  this 
imagery  always  preceded  memory  imagery. 

§5.   SUGGESTED  VERBAL  IMAGES 

By  a  "suggested  verbal  image"  is  meant  here  a  visual  or 
audito-motor  reproduction  o^  a  word  associated  with  the  stimu- 
lus-word. It  must  be  distinguished,  therefore,  from  the  verbal 
imagery  of  the  stimulus  word  itself  the  conditions  of  which 
were   treated    at   the    beginning    of   this   paper.     Suggested 


30  KAKISE 

verbal  imagery  may  occur  either  with  or  without  correspond- 
ing object  imagery,  i.  e.,  dependently  or  independently.  All 
independent  imagery  which  appeared  in  our  records  was  in 
the  nature  of  either  sensory  or  conceptual  associations  (i.  e., 
those  having  a  sensory  or  a  conceptual  relationship  with  the 
stimulus  words).  In  sensory  associations  we  found  only 
"klang  associations,"  or  associations  by  the  similarity  of 
sound.  In  conceptual  associations  there  were  roughly  three 
kinds:  i,  synonyms,  2,  contrasts,  and  3,  co-ordinations,  sub- 
ordination and  super  ordination.  For  instance  (co-ordination) 
dog — cat;  (subordination)  city — New  York;  (superordination) 
cat — animal. 

Results:  1.  There  were  very  marked  individual  differ- 
ences in  the  frequency  of  this  sort  of  imagery,  as  in  the  case 
of  general  visual  imagery,  the  ratio  ranging  from  zero  to  100%; 
for  instance  Obs.  Ac.  had  no  cases  of  this  imagery  in  all  his 
reactions,  while  Obs.  Sm  always  had  it.  Some  observers  had  a 
few  cases,  others  many.  2 .  The  frequency  of  this  imagery  like 
that  of  general  visual  imagery  was  also  markedly  influenced  by 
the  nature  of  the  stimulus  word  (abstractness  or  concreteness) 
and  in  this  case  in  inverse  relation.  It  occurred  three  times 
as  frequently  with  abstract  words  as  with  concrete  words. 
3.  As  to  "klang  associations"  there  were  only  three  of  them 
in  all  the  reactions,  and  only  in  the  case  of  one  observer  (5w), 
so  that  this  form  must  be  regarded  as  rather  exceptional, 
at  least  with  easy  stimulus  words.  (Of  the  frequency  of  this 
form  with  unfamiliar  words  we  shall  speak  later.)  We  had 
now  and  then  phrase  reactions  from  four  observers  most  of 
which  appeared  in  the  form  of  definitions  of  abstract  scientific 
terms.  Conceptual  associations  in  the  form  of  synonyms, 
etc.,  however,  made  the  majority  of  the  cases.  4.  As  to  the 
time  of  occurrence:  With  independent  imagery,  it  was  one 
of  the  quickest  to  occur;  in  case  of  concurrence  with  other 
images,  it  generally  preceded  the  general  visual  image  and 
the  memory  image.  With  dependent  verbal  imagery,  the 
time  depended  on  that  of  object  imagery  which  the  verbal 
imagery  accompanied. 

On  the  Tracing  of  Verbal  Imagery 

With  independent  verbal  images  the  observer  in  the  ma- 
jority of  cases  could  not  give  introspectively  any  account 
of  their  origin  owing  to  the  lack  of  conscious  background. 

For  instance.  Excitation:  (Obs.Sm)  "Pronounced.  The  word  psychol- 
ogy came  which  was  pronounced  and  visualized  in  typewritten  form. 
Then  I  saw  the  German  word  Erregung  printed  in  black.  Then  in  inner 
speech  I  said  'I  wonder  why  I  selected  these  words.'" 

This  imagery  though  difficult  to  be  traced  subjectively  is  yet 


A   STUDY   OF   UNDERSTANDING  3 1 

easily  traced  objectively  in  the  sense  that  it  can  be  easily 
brought  under  conceptual  or  logical  classifications.  The 
dependent  verbal  imagery,  on  the  contrary,  is  easy  to  trace 
subjectively  and  hard  to  trace  objectively. 

Suppose  the  observers  reacted  by  uttering  just  the  dependent 
verbal  images  in  response  to  the  stimulus  words  (without  giving 
their  total  introspections)  and  then  the  experimenter  or  any 
outsider  attempted  to  trace  them  objectively,  as  best  as  he 
could.  Then  compare  the  results  obtained  by  conjecture  with 
the  actual  connections  found  in  the  total  introspections  of 
the  observers.  Such  a  comparison  is  easily  made  by  placing 
all  such  verbal  imagery  found  in  the  protocols  directly  after 
the  stimulus  words.  For  instance,  Horse,  (Obs.  Cf.)  [sug- 
gested verbal  images]  "The  name  of  a  friend  of  the  observer" 
and  "horse." 

Introspection:  "The  sound  of  your  voice  lingered.  Then  there  was 
a  sort  of  general  idea.  Then  a  rather  pleasurable  feeling  due  to  the  recog- 
nition of  a  favorite  animal.  There  was  a  complex  vague  association  there, 
such  as  a  vague  notion  of  a  useful  domestic  animal.  Then  I  had  a  visual 
image  of  being  on  horseback,  with  a  sort  of  inner  speech  in  auditory  terms, 
going  riding  with  a  friend  of  mine  who  suggested  it  to  me.  I  heard  or  pro- 
nounced his  name  and  also  the  word  'horse'  pretty  distinctly.  The 
localization  of  the  scene  of  the  riding  was  far  down  in  the  direction  he 
(my  friend)  has  suggested.  The  suggestion  of  his  occurred  but  two  days 
ago. " 

Turkey,  (Obs.  Sm.)  "Bronze."  Introspection:  "First  strong  visual 
impression  of  the  typewritten  word  and  its  color.  Then  came  the  word 
'bronze '  in  the  form  of  inner  speech  and  at  the  same  time  a  rather  imper- 
fect image  of  one  of  those  big  bronze  cqjored  turkeys.  The  color  was  more 
distinct  than  the  outline.  Not  well  localized,  hovering  somewhere  around 
in  the  air.  The  color  came  out  distinctly,  the  shimmer  of  the  iridescent  col- 
or. Considerably  later,  i.  e.,  after  the  shutter  was  closed,  there  came  the 
thought  that  wild  turkeys  were  once  abundant  in  New  England,  but  now 
almost  extinct.  Then  came  the  idea  of  Thanksgiving,  but  not  well  defined, 
just  a  general  idea  of  festivities." 

§6.      IMAGES   WITH   UNFAMIUAR   STIMUI.1 

It  is  known  in  a  general  way  that  the  grades  of  acquaintance, 
i.  e.,  familiarity  and  unfamiliarity,  with  stimulus  words  or 
phrases  have  an  important  influence  on  the  modes  of  reaction. 
Here  we  propose  to  examine  in  particular  their  influence, 
especially  upon  images.^ 

By  unfamiliar  stimuli  is  meant  here  those  words  or  phrases 
in  the  case  of  which  understanding  either  did  not  occur  directly 
(soon  after  the  sensory  reproduction  of  the  stimulus)  or  did 
not  occur  at  all. 

The  criterion  is  thus  totally  subjective  (i.  e.,  according  to 
the  observers'  modes  of  reaction)  though  a  number  of  so- 

^  Their  influences  on  the  "feelings",  we  shall  consider  later  in  Part  III. 


32  KAKISE 

called  unfamiliar  as  also  familiar  stimuli^  were  provisionally- 
fixed  and  used  by  the  experimenter. 

Some  of  these  objectively  fixed  unfamiliar  stimuli  were 
naturally,  by  some  observers,  found  to  be  familiar  and  some 
of  the  objectively  fixed  familiar  stimuli  were  found  by  other 
observers  to  be  unfamiliar,  so  that  the  following  account  of 
the  influence  of  unfamiliar  stimuli  is  taken  from  the  results 
of  all  experiments  (as  we  have  seen  in  the  treatment  of  the 
images  of  stimulus  words). ^ 

Results.  The  following  results  show  that  there  is  a  strik- 
ing similarity  in  the  conditions  of  some  images  which  attend 
the  reactions  to  unfamiliar  words  and  of  those  attending 
unfamiliar  phrases.^ 

The  influence  of  unfamiliar  stimuli  upon  the  the  images 
(auditory,  motor,  and  visual)  of  the  stimulus-words,  such  as 
their  increased  frequency,  accentuation,  repetition,  etc.,  we 
have  already  seen  in  Part  I,  §-i.  The  tendency  to  such 
imagery  already  exists  in  normal  reactions,  and  merely  be- 
comes accentuated  in  difficult  reactions  owing  to  the  retard- 
ation of  understanding. 

A  more  important  and  characteristic  influence  of  an  un- 
familiar stimulus  is  its  awakening  of  intermediary  (or,  pre- 
ceding suggested)  images  which  were  i,  klang- associations, 
2,  paraphrases,  3,  memory  images,  and  4,  synonyms. 
.  I.  Klang-associations.  With  absolutely  unfamiliar  words 
there  occurred  quite  frequently  klang-associations.  In  the 
case  of  some  stimuli,  different  observers  had  often  the  same 
associations:  such  as,  nosology — nose,  mousquetaire — mosquito, 
pistology — pistol,  hyle — hyla,  cabala — cable,  timbrel — timber, 
timbre — timber,  synergism — syllogism,  monad — Monadnock  (a 
mountain  in  N.  H.),  etc. 

Examples.  Nosology:  (Obs.  L.  M.  Ill — i,  5).  "The  pronunciation 
suggested  'noseology'.  Then  I  found  myself  saying,  'nose-ology ',  which 
made  me  laugh.  The  mind  was  blank.  I  hadn't  any  effort  or  tension, 
but  rather  relaxation.     I  had  a  feeling  of  the  amusing,  comical." 

Nosology.  (Obs.  Ch.  Ill — i,  5.)  "First  feeling  of  total  unfamiliarity. 
But  this  unfamiliarity  was  a  little  bit  different  from  the  first  one  because 
I  recognized  the  first  part  of  the  word.  I  pronounced  it  two  or  three  times. 
The  word  first  suggested  nose  and  made  me  think  of  a  science  of  the  nose, 
which  I  knew,  of  course,  was  not  the  correct  meaning  of  the  word. " 

Hyle  (Obs.  L.  M.  Ill — i,  i).  "I  got  no  reaction.  I  just  foimd  myself 
saying  'hyla',  'hyla'.     There  was  a  great  deal  of  tension." 

Hyle  (Obs.  Sn.  Ill — i,  i).  "I  was  attending  to  the  movement  of  appara- 
tus just  before.      Then  as  soon  as  the  word  appeared  I  pronounced  it  men- 

^For  examples,  see  Introduction. 

2  Part  I,  §§  I  and  2. 

^  Ribot  states  that  he  found  practically  the  same  conditions  of  imagery 
in  both  word  and  phrase  reactions,  and  so  dismissed  the  latter  in  his  later 
experiments.     Cf.  op.  cit.,  p.  114  ff. 


A   STUDY   OF   UNDERSTANDING  33 

tally  several  times.  My  first  thought  was  that  it  was  connected  with  hyla, 
a  tree-frog.  And  then  I  read  it  again  and  thought  you  gave  it  because  of 
its  philosophical  meaning — the  word  is  the  same  as  the  Greek  {JXt;  which  would 
be  spelt  in  the  same  way.  And  after  that  I  repeated  it  several  times  and 
was  repeating  it.  There  was  feeling  of  concentration  particularly  marked." 
With  unfamiliar  phrases,  however,  this  form  of  association 
by  similarity  of  mere  sounds,  perhaps  something  like  parody, 
did  not  occur. 

2.  Paraphrase.  With  unfamiHar  and  apparently  com- 
pound words,  it  was  a  common  tendency  to  analyze  them 
first  into  familiar  elements  and  then  to  make  out  the  meaning 
of  the  whole.  For  instance,  synergism:  syn-energy  "working 
together",  uUramontanism — u !tra-mont-ism^  ''doctrine  be- 
yond the  mountain" ;  pachydermata:  pachy-derm-ata^"  a  class 
of  thick-skinned  animals";  Millenarism:  Miller-ism^  "a  doc- 
trine of  Miller, "  etc., 

Example:  Millenarism.  (Obs.  Ch.  Ill,  ii,  17,  Time — ( — })  "Read 
the  word  through  half  a  dozen  times  and  at  the  last  time  I  divided  the 
word  into  two  syllables.  Feeling  of  effort  throughout  the  whole  experi- 
ment; tension  and  the  same  feeling  of  hunting.  The  suggestion  that  came 
to  me  was  a  man  named  Miller  who  had  a  peculiar  theological  doctrine 
something  about  the  end  of  the  world  at  a  certain  time,  I  think.  And  so 
the  feeling  was  not  a  feeling  of  total  strangeness,  but  it  was  a  feeling  of 
recognition  of  the  word.  I  suspected  the  word  was  probably  constructed 
after  the  name  of  that  man  and  stood  for  his  system.  Feeling  of  unpleas- 
antness attached  to  the  strain.  Feeling  of  uncertainty  and  ignorance. 
The  mind  is  not  yet  quite  free  from  work.  There  seems  something  still 
working. " 

Pistology.  (Obs.  Sn.  Ill,  ii.  7,  Time — ( — ^.)  "Read  the  word  in  inner 
speech  and  tried  to  think  of  what  it  could  possibly  mean.  I  had  that 
feeling  of  strain,  of  unfamiliarity,  and  then  I  began  groping  about.  I 
looked  at  the  first  part  of  the  word  and  recognized  the  word  'pistol'  there, 
and  then,  I  think,  I  formulated  it  in  inner  speech  as  'the  science  of  pistol. ' 
And  then  I  rejected  that.  At  the  same  time  there  was  some  sense  of  humor. 
Then  the  words  'science  of  fishes'  came  perhaps  by  way  of  analogy  with  the 
word  'piscatology'  (this  word  did  not  come  into  consciousness).  But  I 
realized  that  that  is  not  the  meaning  of  the  word.  And  so  I  was  still  trying 
further  and  was  thinking  that  I  was  not  able  to  make  out  what  the  word  was 
when  the  shutter  was  closed.  A  feeling  of  unf  amiliarty,  and  a  feeling  of  grop- 
ing about  for  something  were  there,  but  the  feeling  of  unfamiliarity  was 
the  only  one  which  was  in  the  centre  of  consciousness.  There  was  also  a 
certain  feeling  of  helplessness  though  not  clearly  developed.  These  feel- 
ings of  strain  and  eftort  passed  off  more  gradually  this  time  than  in  the 
other  one.  There  was  a  little  curiosity  whether  it  was  not  a  nonsense 
word. " 

With  unfamiliar  and  difi&cult  phrases,  this  tendency  to 
paraphrase  was  more  frequent  and  common  than  with  words. 
An  important  feature  is  the  fact  that  here  two  kinds  of  inter- 
mediaries, a  verbal  and  a  visual,  with  rather  definite  individual 

^  The  sign  " — "  signifies  that  the  understanding  did  not  take  place  within 
5  seconds.     For  details  see  Introduction. 

Journal — 3 


34  KAKISE 

differences,  were  pretty  clearly  brought  out.  In  the  case  of 
the  verbal  intermediary,  the  mind  works  mainly  with  syno- 
nyms, for  the  principal  words  in  a  phrase,  or  with  inner  speech 
in  the  making  out  of  the  meaning.  There  is  seldom  any  trace 
of  visual  images  of  objects. 

For  instance:  "Truth  seeks  no  corner."  (Obs.  Ms.  ph,  4.  Time — ) 
"Read  it  in  the  same  way  as  before.  Turned  back  to  the  two  words  'truth' 
and  'comer'.  I  had  no  visual  image.  From  the  word  'comer'  the  words 
'square  place'  came  by  association.  Interpreted  'Truth  spreads  itself.' 
There  was  a  slight  feeling  of  effort  or  tension.  The  mental  operation 
stopped  with  the  understanding." 

"A  sin  confessed  is  half  forgiven."  (Obs.  Cf.  I,  Ph.  7,  Time — .)  "A 
little  doubt  still  remains  with  this  too.  Some  almost  audible  inner  speech 
with  distinct  articulation  and  movements.  A  rapid  comparison  with  the 
last  one  but  no  pronunciation  of  it.  Everything  was  almost  auditory, 
i.  e.,  words  dealing  with  an  imagined  sin  of  a  child  who  confesses  to  his 
father  some  fault  he  had  done.  That  kind  of  thinking  or  imagination 
seems  to  bring  forth  the  meaning,  namely:  'If  you  tell  him  about  your 
wrong  yourself,  it  wakens  the  good  disposition  of  the  person  you  have 
offended'." 

In  the  case  of  the  visual  intermediary,  the  mind  works 
mainly  with  more  or  less  vivid  visual  images  of  objects  des- 
ignated by  the  principal  words  of  a  phrase,  or  with  visual 
imagination,  in  the  making  out  of  meaning. 

For  instance:  "Riches  have  wings."  (Obs.  Kn.  I,  Ph.  3,  Time — .) 
"Internal  reading.  Then  I  had  a  very  clear  image  of  a  bird  with  wings. 
Then  the  image  of  the  flying  away  of  the  bird,  which  brought  the  idea, 
not  image,  of  the  going  away  of  riches.  Then  the  feeling  of  the  conviction 
that  the  problem  was  correctly  understood.  This  feeling  was  accompanied 
by  a  peculiar  feeling  of  relaxation  and  ease. " 

"Truth  seeks  no  corner."  (Obs.  Hi.  1,  Ph.  4.  Time — .)  "Inner  reading 
with  movements  of  speech  organs  as  before.  I  imagined  and  constructed 
a  square  in  my  mental  vision.  Then  smoothing  the  four  corners  of  the 
square  I  shaped  it  into  a  circle,  and  got  the  following  interpretation. 
'Truth  is  perfect.'  (After  having  reported  his  introspection,  the  ob- 
server confessed  that  he  began  to  doubt  about  his  interpretation.) 

With  some  few  observers  the  use  of  one  of  these  types  of 
imagery  was  so  constant  and  so  firmly  established  that  they 
seldom  went  over  to  the  other  form,  regardless  of  the  con- 
creteness  or  abstractness  of  stimulus. 

An  extra  observer  had  visual  (or  concrete)  intermediary  imagery  nearly 
all  the  time  as  shown  in  the  following  protocol: 

Obs,  Osh.  Ph.  No.  i .  ( Union  is  strength)  3"(stimulus  spoken) .  '  'Saw  white 
grasping  hands,  immediately  followed  by  the  recollection  of  the  scene  of 
the  bridal  ceremony  in  Longfellow's  'Launching  of  the  Ship.'  Then  I 
had  the  sense." 

Ph.  No.  2.  ( Use  makes  perfectness)  3"  (spoken) .  '  'I  had  a  mental  image  of 
each  word  in  the  sentence.  The  style  of  letters  appeared  in  the  form  be- 
tween printed  type  and  handwriting.  Then  followed  the  visual  image  of 
a  vague  shadowy  human  figure.     Then  the  meaning. 

Ph.  No.  3.  {Riches  have  wings)  4."  (spoken).  "Spoken  sound  remained. 
I  had  a  mental  image  of  himting,  and  saw  the  white  wing  of  a  bird.  Then 
the  meaning  flashed  in. 


A   STUDY   OI^   UNDERSTANDING  35 

Ph.  No.  4.  {Truth  seeks  no  corner)  1'  (spoken).  I  had  an  image  of  a 
comer.  There  was  no  repetition  of  the  heard  words.  I  payed  very  little 
attention  to  the  words.     The  sense  flashed. 

Obs.  Cff.  on  the  other  hand,  had  verbal  imagery  or  inner 
speech  in  most  occasions  in  the  understanding  of  unfamiliar 
phrases. 

Several  of  the  other  observers  approached,  in  varying 
degrees,  to  one  or  the  other  of  these  extreme  cases,  while 
the  rest  represented  the  middle  or  neutral  class,  having  no 
special  preference  or  inclination  to  either  sort  of  imagery. 
It  was  the  imagery  of  this  last  class  that  was  influenced 
markedly  by  concreteness  or  abstractness  in  the  stimulus. 

Here  we  have,  therefore,  in  these  images  a  pretty  definite 
and  also  rather  important  criterion — important  because  it 
directly  concerns  the  thinking  —  for  individual  differences. 
The  general  tendency  seems  to  be  that  the  frequency  of  verbal 
and  visual  intermediary  images  corresponds  nearly  to  that 
of  verbal  and  visual  suggested  images  in  cases  of  easy  under- 
standing. 

3.  Memory  images.  If  the  words  or  phrases  were  such 
as  had  been  experienced  once,  or  a  fe#  times,  before,  memory 
images  often  occurred  in  the  form  of  the  recollection  of  the 
circumstances  under  which  the  words  had  been  experienced, 
regardless  of  individual  differences  and  of  the  concreteness 
or  abstractness  of  the  stimulus  words.  This  kind  of  memory 
images  usually  preceded  the  understanding,  but  sometimes 
succeeded  or  occurred  simultaneously  with  it. 

Example:  Synergism.  (Obs.  E.  M.  iii — i,  10.)  "First  a  visual  impression 
of  the  word,  then  the  pronunciation  of  the  word.  Then  I  saw  vaguely 
the  place  in  a  book  where  the  word  was  treated,  but  the  meaning  did  not 
come  to  me.  There  was  quite  a  noticeable  feeling  of  strain  on  account  of 
my  hard  effort  to  recall  the  subject  of  the  treatment  in  which  the  word 
appeared. " 

Noumenon.  (Obs.  Ky.  II,  w — 19.)  "First  the  tendency  to  pronounce. 
Then  the  realization  that  it  means  the  opposite  of  phenomenon  came. 
It  reminded  me  that  I  looked  up  that  word  in  the  dictionary  about  two 
months  ago.  I  had  a  distinct  visual  image  of  the  place;  I  had  been  look- 
ing at  the  dictionary  in  the  library." 

Thinking  is  so  hard  that  many  prefer  judgment  to  it.  (Obs.  Ac.  Ill — iv, 
9,  Time — 3.0".)  "I  read  it  and  the  meaning  flashed  into  my  mind  at 
once.  But  it  was  just  a  feeling.  Then  I  had  a  very  vague  image  of 
the  lecture  room  and  of  Dr.  S.  I  felt  the  statement  to  be  easy  and 
reacted.  After  I  had  reacted,  in  second  thought  I  found  it  was  not 
sure.  The  reason  of  the  occurrence  of  this  image  is  that  Dr.  S  talked  about 
the  difficulty  of  thinking  in  common  people  who  would  rather  decide  with- 
out thinking.  I  did  not  recall  the  idea  of  it  very  clearly,  whence  my  hesita- 
tion afterward.  The  tension  was  only  kept  up  while  I  was  reading  and 
considering.  With  the  reaction  it  went  away  and  some  sense  of  satisfaction 
came  with  it.  But  it  was  soon  dispelled  by  the  sense  of  uncertainty  and 
its  accompanying  feelings  which  persisted  as  in  other  cases  of  difficult 
reactions. 


36  KAKISE 

The  frequency  of  such  memory  imagery,  with  not  quite 
famiHar  words  or  phrases,  is  well  known  to  every  one  of  us 
especially  in  the  study  of  a  new  language.  With  frequent 
repetitions  these  definite  associations  fall  away  giving  place 
to  mere  feeling  of  recognition  or  of  familiarity. 

4.  Synonyms.  A.  With  words.  With  rather,  but  not 
quite,  familiar  words,  there  occurred  sometimes  other  more 
familiar  verbal  images  having  similar  meanings,  or  synonyms 
in  widest  sense.  They  were  synonyms  proper,  definitions, 
and  translations. 

a,  Synonyms  proper,  or  words  having  similar  meanings. 

Apperception.  (Obs.  St.  II,  w — 18.)  "There  was  a  slight  surprise. 
The  word  was  familiar.  It  brought  the  word  'attention'.  Then  I  thought 
of  Dr.  S  explaining  the  meaning  of  the  word  as  mental  grasp  of  the  whole. 
I  visualized  Dr.  S  in  his  recitation  room. " 

b,  Definitions :  This  form  occurred  especially  with  technical 
terms,  such  as,  apperception,  parallelism,  noumenon,  etc. 

These  forms  occurred  mainly  in  observers  belonging  to  the 
verbal  type.  The  observers  belonging  to  visual  or  concrete 
type  visualized,  in  such  cases,  a  concrete  instance  mostly  in 
the  form  of  memory  imagery. 

For  instance:  Parallelism.  (Obs.  Ac.  II,  w — 32.)  "I  spelled  and  pro- 
nounced the  word  mentally.  I  saw  mentally  Dr.  S  drawing  on  the  black- 
board the  diagram  on  parallelism,  and  speaking  of  the  theory,  of  the  state- 
ment of  the  relation  between  body  and  mind." 

c,  Translation.  With  foreign  words  this  form  frequently 
occurred  regardless  of  individual  differences. 

Color.  (Obs.  Kn.  I,  w — 10.)  "Sound  continued.  Translated  into 
Japanese  'iro'  which  was  internally  spoken.  Then  the  understanding, 
and  I  thought  of  the  red  color  of  this  card-box  on  the  table." 

B,  With  phrases.  With  unfamiliar  phrases  there  occurred 
similiar  forms  of  synonyms  nearly  in  the  same  way  as  in  the 
case  of  words. 

a,  Similiar  phrases. 

Example.  A  chariot  will  not  go  on  a  single  wheel.  (Obs.  Cff.  I,  B — I, 
Time — .)  '  'I  tried  to  recognize  the  phrase,  but  failed.  Then  I  recalled  a 
similar  expression,  'A  college  without  a  library  is  like  a  wagon  with  three 
wheels. '  The  situation  in  which  I  had  heard  the  proverb  came  into  my 
mind.  I  had  a  slight  vague  image  of  a  chariot  as  described  in  a  book. 
Then  I  tried  to  compare  two  wheels  to  two  qualities  in  a  person's  nature, 
which  balance  each  other.  The  word  'balance'  was  internally  spoken. 
I  decided  that  the  only  meaning  I  can  get  out  of  it  was  that  'Balance  is 
necessary  for  success. '  The  sentence  was  internally  spoken.  Feeling  of 
dissatisfaction  with  reference  to  my  explanation.  A  feeling  that  something 
is  wrong  with  my  interpretation." 

The  translation  of  foreign  phrases  was  quite  common. 

For  instance:  Lahorare  est  orare.  (Ill — ii,  6.  Obs.  Ch,  Time,  1.9')  "First 
read  it  through  and  understood  it  without  translating  it.       The  under- 


I 


A   STUDY   OF   UNDERSTANDING  37 

standing  was  not  complete,  so  I  read  it  second  time  translating  into 
English  and  I  got  the  sense.  I  experienced  two  sorts  of  certainties,  the 
certainty  about  my  knowledge  of  the  Latin  words,  that  is  about  what 
they  mean  in  English,  and  that  of  the  sense,  I  was  at  the  beginning  a 
little  surprised  to  find  a  Latin  phrase." 

To  conclude:  Unfamiliarity  with  the  stimulus  has  an  im- 
portant influence  on  the  frequency  and  kinds  of  images. 
I.  Unfamiliar  stimuli  accentuate  the  images  of  the  stimuli 
in  general.  2.  Intermediary  images  in  the  forms  of  klang- 
associations,  memory  images,  synonyms,  translations,  defi- 
nitions, etc.,  are  direct  results  of  unfamiliarity.  3.  In  the 
paraphrase,  there  is  a  marked  tendency  to  individual  differ- 
ences in  the  use  of  verbal  and  visual  intermediary  images. 
4.  The  kinds  and  conditions  of  intermediary  images  both 
with  unfamiliar  words  and  phrases  seem,  in  the  main,  nearly 
the  same.^ 

§  7.      AUSFRAGE     METHOD    AND     THE    CUSTOMARY    METHOD  IN 
STUDIES   OF    ASSOCIATION 

The  results  of  our  study  lead  to  the  belief  that  the  Ausfrage 
method,  such  as  was  applied  in  the  above  study,  is  more 
adapted,  in  its  passive  form  of  reaction,  to  the  study  of  the 
actual  phenomena  of  association  than  the  customary  method 
of  the  so-called  association-experiment,  because  it  has  the 
following  advantages  over  the  latter :  i ,  Naturalness  of  asso- 
ciations; 2,  Clearness  of  the  term  suggestion;  3,  Introspection; 
4,  Change  of  conditions.  The  customary  method  lacks  almost 
all  these  conditions  essential  to  the  study. 

I.  Naturalness  of  associations.  The  observer  has  only  to 
remain  passive  to  the  stimulus  letting  the  associations  or 
suggestions  go  as  they  occur  without  interruption  or  dis- 
turbance by  will.  With  the  customary  method,  on  the  con- 
trary, the  course  of  associations  becomes  complicated  or 
jeopardized  in  a  double  way:  i,  By  the  observer's  mere  inten- 
tion or  will  to  fulfill  the  artificial  requirements  of  the  experi- 
ment, and  2,  by  the  actual  fulfillment,  of  them,  a,  The  re- 
action must  be  given  in  one  word;  b,  The  reaction- word  must 
be  different  from  the  stimulus- word ;  c,  The  reaction- word 
must  stand  for  the  first  association;  d,  The  reaction  must  be 
as  quick  as  possible.  It  is  clear  that  the  mere  idea  of  fulfilling 
these  numerous  requirements  is  itself  sufficient  to  change  the 
observer's  attitude  from  a  passive  or  neutral  state  to  an  active 
or  selective  one.  As  to  the  results  of  actual  fulfillment  of 
requirement  a,  it  may  be  asked  how,  in  case  the  observer  has 
as  an  associated  idea,  a  complex  visual  image  or  memory 

^For  the  conditions  of  concomitant  feelings  see  Part  III,  ^  3. 


38  KAKISK 

image,  he  could  express  them  in  a  single  word  without  select- 
ing at  random  the  name  of  one  of  the  represented  objects  or 
a  part  of  one  or  some  idea  such  as  could  be  promptly  expressed. 
Of  requirement  b,  it  may  be  said  that  the  association  existing 
between  an  image  and  its  name  (as  well  as  that  between  a 
perception  of  an  object  and  its  name)  is  one  of  the  strongest; 
and  the  two  operate  reciprocally;  a  name  usually  calls  up  its 
object-image  and  the  object-image  usually  calls  up  its  name. 
When  a  name  calls  forth  its  object-image  in  the  observer's 
mind,  the  natural  tendency  is  to  name  it  again.  But  this 
tendency  must  be  checked,  for  a  reaction  by  repeating  the 
stimulus  word  is  forbidden,  though,  in  such  cases,  it  is  psycho- 
logically quite  different  from  mere  mechanical  repetition  or 
imitation  of  speaker's  voice.  The  result  of  the  fulfillment  of 
the  requirements  c  and  d,  i.  e.,  of  "the  first  association"  and 
of  "promptness,"  is  that  the  majority  of  reactions  will  neces- 
sarily consist  of  independent  verbal  associations  or  what 
Wundt  calls  articulatory  or  pseudo-associations  (Scheinassocia- 
tionen),  since  they  are  in  general  the  first  to  arrive,  but  are 
deprived  of  all  psychical  traits. 

2.  Clearness  of  the  term  ''Suggestion.''  Of  whatever  kinds 
they  may  be,  all  conscious  events  are  "suggestions"  when 
they  succeed  the  perception  of  the  stimulus-word.  Their 
classification  and  sorting  and  sifting  are  all  left  in  the  Ausfrage 
experiment  to  the  experimenter.  The  observer  has  only  to 
state  all  he  has  experienced  in  a  certain  interval  of  time,  and 
there  is  no  room  for  ambiguity  in  the  meaning  of  terms  as  such. 
The  term  "associations,"  as  it  is  used  in  the  'instruction' 
in  the  common  association  experiment,  is,  on  the  contrary, 
ambiguous  and  capable  of  more  than  one  interpretation. 
It  may  mean  purely  articulatory  associations.  It  may  mean 
"real"  associations  i.  e.y  those  with  object-images.  It  may 
mean  associations  between  two  object-images,  as  in  the  case 
of  so-called  "association  of  ideas. "  Finally,  it  may  mean  the 
mixture  of  all  these,  the  most  natural  to  occur  in  real  associ- 
ations. Not  only  does  each  observer  differ  in  these  varieties 
of  possible  interpretations,  but  also  one  and  the  same  observer 
may  fluctuate,  sometimes  voluntarily  sometimes  involuntarily, 
from  one  to  the  other  of  these  interpretations  according  to 
circumstances.^ 

^Sometime  ago,  to  see  how  far  the  results  would  differ  in  the  same  obser- 
vers according  to  the  differences  of  these  interpretations,  I  made  tests  with 
several  observers,  in  the  first  series  of  which  the  observers  were  requested 
to  react  under  the  conditions  of  the  traditional  association-experiment. 
In  the  second  series,  they  were  required  to  react,  if  possible,  after  having 
some  suggested  object-images  or  ideas.  The  protocols,  which  were  taken 
by  the  observers  after  each  reaction,  show  the  result  that  in  the  first  series 


A   STUDY   OF  UNDERSTANDING  39 

3.  Introspection.  In  such  complex  processes  as  word-re- 
action, nothing  gives  a  more  direct  and  trustworthy  account 
than  the  introspection  of  the  observer  himself.  Objectively 
alone  (i.  e.  without  this  essential  help  of  introspection),  it  is 
almost  impossible  even  to  distinguish  an  immediate,  or  artic- 
ulatory  reaction  from  an  intermediate,  or  object-reaction, 
not  to  mention  the  tracing  of  the  same  reaction-words  to 
different  sources,  or  of  any  further  exploitation  of  associations 
in  general. 

4.  Change  of  Conditions.  The  occurrence  of  a  special  asso- 
ciation or  suggestion  to  the  exclusion  of  others  is  directly  con- 
ditioned by  the  resultants  of  the  three  factors:  Procedure 
of  experimentation,  Kinds  of  material,  and  Individual  differ- 
ences. Change  of  conditions  reveals  to  us  the  real  causes  of 
certain  forms  of  associations,  which  is  not  only  ignored  by, 
but  also  will  be  difficult  for,  the  customary  method  because 
of  the  complication  of  many  other  factor^  such  as  were  men- 
tioned in  item  i. 

So  much  for  the  comparison  of  the  new  and  the  customary 
method  in  their  application  to  the  study  of  association.  The 
disadvantages  of  the  latter  are  clear. 

On  Association  Experiments  in  Applied  Psychology 

No  one  can  deny  that  some  important  contributions  to 
psychology  as  well  as  to  practical  life  have  come  from  associa- 
tion experiments  in  applied  psychology.  Their  method,  how- 
ever, is  not  absolutely  free  from  weaknesses,  as  it  is  based  on 
the  same  principles  as  the  preceding. 

Its  study  of  individual  differences  of  normal  and  abnormal 
mentality  consists  of  two  processes:  i.  The  collection  of  a 
number  of  reaction-words  by  the  customary  association 
method;  and  2,  the  interpretation  of  the  reaction- words. 
This  is  undertaken  as  follows:  First,  such  a  logical  scheme 
!or  classification  of  associations  (according  to  the  conceptual 
relations  of  the  reaction- words  to  the  stimulus- word)  is  pre- 
pared, as  will  comprehend  all  possible  forms  of  reactions 
under  these  categories.  Then  the  relative  frequency  with 
normal  subjects  of  associations  of  the  different  sorts  thus 
classified  is  taken  and  serves  as  a  standard  with  which  to  com- 
pare the  frequency  with  abnormal  subjects.  Now,  regarding 
some  of  the  interpretations  or  generalizations  attained  through 

the  reactions  consisted  of  diverse  kinds  of  imagery,  with  the  majority  of 
articulatory  associations  (purely  verbal).  In  the  second  series,  the  ma- 
li'jority  of  the  reactions  consisted  of  memory  associations.  This  illustrates 
how  easy  it  is  to  get  totally  different  kinds  of  associations  from  the  same 
observer  by  the  mere  difference  in  the  interpretation  of  the  term  '  'associa- 
Ition. " 


40  KAKISE 

such  steps  the  following  remarks  may  be  made.  In  the  gener- 
alization that  children,  imbeciles,  idiots,  epileptics,  etc.,  react 
frequently  in  phrase  form,  whereas  with  adults  and  normal 
persons  this  form  occurs  very  seldom  if  at  all,  the  probable 
interpretation  is  that  the  former  do  not  perhaps  understand, 
or  forget,  or  neglect  the  requirement  for  the  use  of  a  single 
reaction- word,  whereas  the  latter  observe  the  rule.  This  fact 
of  disobedience,  etc.,  itself  may  sometimes  be  regarded  as  a 
sign  of  abnormality,  etc.,  but  nothing  more ,  because  phrase 
associations  are  quite  natural  and  frequent  under  certain 
conditions,  as  is  shown  in  our  study.  In  like  manner,  the 
generalization  that  children  and  imbeciles,  etc.,  react  frequently 
by  egocentric  associations,  whereas  normal  persons  react  very 
seldom,  if  at  all,  in  this  form,  cannot  be  interpreted  as  an 
expression  of  a  fair  comparison  of  the  actual  associations, 
because  a  single  word  by  itself  seldom  furnishes  a  clue  of 
egocentricity  to  an  onlooking  psychologist,  unless  it  is  accom- 
panied by  a  personal  pronoun  or  some  other  word,  that  is, 
unless  it  is  put  into  a  phrase  form  which  a  normal  person 
suppresses.  This  fact  perhaps  accounts  for  the  exceedingly 
small  number  of  egocentric  or  personal  associations  with 
normal  persons  which  is  reported  in  these  studies.  In  some 
cases  its  frequency  goes  as  low  as  the  ratio  of  once  in  two 
thousand  reactions.^  In  fact  with  passive  reactions  in  our 
experiment  and  according  to  the  direct  report  of  the 
observers,  this  form,  which  is  merely  our  memory  imagery,^ 
occurred  in  the  ratio  of  once  in  every  two  reactions.  A  large 
discrepancy  indeed ! 

Reactions  by  repetition  of  the  stimulus  word,  which  are 
regarded  in  association  studies,  as  characterizing  the  reactions 
of  children  and  imbeciles,  etc.,  were  found  as  common  and 
natural  associations  with  normal  subjects  in  our  experiment, 
as  was  just  stated.  Reactions  in  the  form  of  explanation  or 
definition,  another  characteristic  of  children,  imbeciles,  etc., 
were  often  found  in  our  experiments,  especially  when  the 
stimulus  word  .was  not  quite  familiar  or  it  was  a  technical 
term  of  the  meaning  of  which  the  observer  was  not  perfectly 
sure.  So  that  this  tendency  to  explanatory  reaction  can 
hardly  be  regarded  as  more  than  an  indication  of  the  degree 
of  acquaintanship  with  words,  i.  e.,  literacy  or  illiteracy. 

To  sum  up,  these  so-called  characteristic  forms  in  children 
and  the  abnormal  can  all  be  found  in  normal  adults  in  their 
natural  associations,  i.  e.,  when  they  react  according  to  natural 

^Jung  und  Riklin:  Diagnostische  Assoziationsstudien.  Leipzig,  1906- 
Cf.  p.  108. 

2"  Die  Einstellung  ist  eine  egozentrische,  in  sofem  das  Reizwort 
vorziiglich  subjective  Erinnerungen  anregt."     Ibid.,  p.  117. 


A   STUDY  OF   UNDERSTANDING  4 1 

and  spontaneous  suggestions,  as  was  the  case  with  our  experi- 
ment, and  do  not  react  according  to  artificial  and  "sophisti- 
cated" associations,  i.  e.,  by  mere  verbal  associations,  as  is 
the  case  in  the  customary  experiment  with  normal  observers 
who  are  expert  enough  to  obey  the  "rules. " 

Remarks  on  association  experiments  as  a  means  of  diagnos- 
ing crimes  as  well  as  diseases.  The  criteria  for  a  so-called 
significant  or  critical  reaction  are:  i.  Prolonged  reaction 
time,  considered  as  due  to  the  disturbances  of  the  "emotional 
complexes";  2,  Apparently  unconnected  reaction  words 
(having  no  conceptual  connection  with  stimulus)  considered 
as  a  "Deck"  or  "evasive"  reaction,  when  the  experimenter 
is  unable  to  account  for  it,  and  as  a  suspicious  reaction  when 
he  is  able  to  do  so.  Sometimes  a  succeeding  reaction  is  ex- 
amined according  to  these  criteria,  on  the  ground  of  the 
phenomenon  of  "Perseveration."  The  final  or  crucial  test 
is  furnished  by  the  confession  of  the  (supposed)  criminal 
or  patient. 

Now,  most  of  our  cases  of  dependent  verbal  imagery  ac- 
companying memory  imagery,  if  they  alone  were  announced  by 
the  observer  (i.  e.,  memory  associations),  no  matter  whether 
they  are  emotional  or  neutral,  significant  or  insignificant, 
would  satisfy  the  two  conditions  just  mentioned,  for  they 
were  slower  than  the  simple  articulatory  associations  and 
lacked,  as  a  rule,  logical  or  outward  connection  to  stimulus  words. ^ 

These  criteria  are  thus  helpless  in  the  distinguishing  of 
^emotional  or  significant  memory  associations  from  neutral 
tor  insignificant  memory  associations.  They  are  effective  only 
[when  the  observers  always  react  in  the  form  of  articulatory 
or  purely  verbal  associations  with  insignificant  words  and  in 
the  form  of  memory  associations  with  significant  words.  This 
may  naturally  occur  in  laboratory  tests,  as  the  observers  are 
[trained  to  articulatory  reactions  with  ordinary  words,  and  are 
laturally  struck  by  recent  memory  associations  of  a  few  min- 
futes  date  which,  of  course,  are  the  strongest  and  most  likely 
j^to  revive,  no  matter  how  insignificant  the  events  were.     But 

^Experiments  were  made  recently  by  Yerkes  and  Berry   {Am.   J.  of 

^sychoL,  Jan.,  1909)  and  also  by  Henke  and  Eddy  (Psy.  Rev.,  Nov.,  1909) 

to  test  the  certainty  of  the  diagnostic  method  in  the  discovery  of  certain 

;ts  executed  by  the  observers  shortly  previous  to  the  tests,  with  the  same 

isults  in  both  studies,  namely:  that  the  method  was  certain  when  it  had 

do  with  the  determination  of  two  alternatives,  even  if  the  observers 

'sometimes  tried  to  "fool"  the  experimenters.     In  these  cases,  it  must  be 

remembered,  we  are  not  dealing  with  the  two  forms  of  reactions,  emotional 

and  neutral,  as  is  commonly  presumed,  but,  in  fact,  with  only  the  two  forms 

of  reactions,  articulatory   associations  and  memory  associations   (in  these 

cases,  with  very  recent  memory  associations),  as  also  is  plainly  seen  in  the 

reading  of  the  tables  and  introspections  in  these  articles. 


42  KAKISB 

such  is  hardly  to  be  expected  in  the  case  of  patients  and  crimi- 
nals in  actual  practice,  because  they  may  be  expected  to 
react  very  frequently  in  the  form  of  real  or  memory  associa- 
tions to  ordinary  words. 

Part   III 

Analysis  of  run  Simultaneous  Concomitants 

The  foregoing  studies  have  dealt  with  the  conditions  of  the 
frequency  of  images  which  either  preceded  or  succeeded  under- 
standing. In  this  last  part  of  the  study  I  shall  examine  the 
nature  of  "meaning"  as  a  simultaneous  concomitant  of  under- 
standing, tracing  up  the  following  three  questions,  i .  Whether 
the  concomitants  precede  or  succeed  or  occur  simultaneously 
with  understanding.  The  preceding  and  succeeding  con- 
comitants may  be  eliminated  from  the  experience  of  under- 
standing itself,  whatever  relations  they  may  have  to  the  latter. 
2.  Whether  or  not  the  simultaneous  concomitants  are  pe- 
culiar to  understanding  or  meaning.  Those  which  occur  as 
fully  even  when  there  is  no  understanding  may  be  eliminated 
from  the  characteristic  constituents  of  meaning,  no  matter 
whether  they  are  constant  or  not.  3.  Whether  or  not  the 
constituents  of  meaning  can  ultimately  be  reduced  to  the 
psychological  elements,  i.  e.,  pure  sensations  and  feelings. 
The  protocols  of  the  foregoing  experiments  directly  answer 
the  purpose  of  the  first  question,  i.  e.,  the  temporal  succession 
of  the  concomitants.  For  the  second  question  an  additional 
experiment  was  made.  The  answer  to  the  third  question 
consists  mainly  of  inferences  from  all  the  preceding  results 
of  introspections.  But  before  entering  on  the  discussion  of 
our  results  let  us  take  a  glance  at  the  main  views  on  the  psy- 
chology of  thought  and  especially  of  meaning  held  by  the 
modern  psychologists  to  whose  work  we  shall  have  frequent 
occasion  to  refer. 

§  I.      AN  HISTORICAL  SKETCH   OF  THE  VARIOUS  VIEWS  OF 
THOUGHT 

I .  Thought  as  identical  with  concrete  representations  (images) . 
Locke  speaks  of  the  possibility  of  our  having  pure  general 
ideas  free  from  any  particular  representations,  for  instance, 
of  "a  triangle  which  must  be  neither  oblique  nor  rectangle, 
neither  equilateral,  equicrural,  nor  scalenon,  but  all  and  nony 
of  these  at  once."^  Berkeley  who  was  quite  surprised  be 
this  conceptualistic  view  of  Locke,  says,  "the  idea  of  man 
that  I  frame  to  myself  must  be  either  of  a  white,  or  a  black, 
or  a  tawny,  a  straight,  or  a  crooked,  a  tall,  or  a  low,  or  a 

^Essay,  Bk.  iv.  ch.  7. 


A   STUDY   OF  UNDERSTANDING  43 

middle-sized  man."^  For  him  meaning,  concept  or  general 
ideas,  as  such,  have  no  psychical  existence  except  in  concrete 
representations . 

Among  modern  psychologists  James,  siding  with  Locke  in 
opposition  to  Berkeley,  says,  "The  note  so  bravely  struck 
by  Berkeley  could  not,  however,  be  well  sustained  in  the  face 
of  the  fact  patent  to  every  human  being  that  we  can  mean 
color  without  meaning  any  particular  color,  and  stature  with- 
out meaning  any  particular  height."^ 

Binet  in  regard  to  Berkeley's  proposition  takes,  like  James, 
the  negative  side  and  refers  to  two  cases  as  an  e^perimentum 
cruets  against  it,  i.  e.,  cases  where  we  have  particular  and  precise 
images  without  having  any  meaning  or  thought,  and  cases 
where  we  have  thought  or  meaning  without  having  any  partic- 
ular or  precise  images.  He  maintains,  also,  that  '  pensSe 
generale'  can  be  properly  explained  by  neither  conceptualism 
nor  nominalism  though  probably  by  "  intentionalism "  which 
he  himself  proposes.^  Biihler  speaks  of  both  being  right  and 
wrong,  that  Berkeley  is  right  in  his  negation  of  sensuous 
representation  of  a  general  triangle,  and  Locke  is  right  in 
his  assertion  of  the  existence  of  the  pure  meaning  of  a  triangle 
without  any  sensory  element,  and  also  that  the  question  of 
general  ideas  is  totally  different  from  that  of  abstract  ideas 
or  (his)  thought  or  knowledge  {Wis sen). ^ 

2 .  Thought  as  identieal  with  the  verbal  image.  This  question 
first  took  its  definite  shape  in  the  controversy  between  Max 
Miiller  on  one  side  and  Galton,  Romanes  and  others  on  the 
other.  The  former  maintains  that  all  thinking  when  intro- 
spectively  viewed  is  merely  inner  speech.  The  latter  refer, 
to  cases  of  chess  playing,  of  the  construction  of  machines  in 
purely  visual  terms,  and  also  to  the  framing  or  searching 
for  the  words  for  an  existent  thought,  a  fact  quite  common 
to  us,  as  insurmountable  difficulties  in  the  way  of  this  propo- 
sition.^ 

Identity  of  abstract  thought  and  verbal  image.  Taine  speaks 
of  his  abstract  ideas  as  quite  different  from  a  particular  repre- 
sentation or  even  from  the  "confused  and  floating  repre- 
sentation of  particular  araucaria,"  alluding  to  the  general 
ideas  of  Galton  and  Huxley.*^  He  says,  "We  think  the  ab- 
stract character  of  things  by  means  of  abstract  names  which 
are  our  abstract  ideas,  and  the  formation  of  our  ideas  are 

^Principle,  Introduction,  lo,  13. 

^Ibid.,  Vol.  I,  p.  470. 

^Binet  A.:  L'etude  experimentale  de  I'intelligence,  1903,  p.  151  ff. 

*Ibid.,  p.  363-364- 

*Max  Miiller:  ibid.,  appendix  (1887). 

^^'intelligence,  II,  139. 


44  KAKISE 

merely  the  formation  of  names  which  substitute  them."^ 
Among  present  authors,  Wundt  says,  "We  do  not  always 
think  in  words;  we  can  easily  recall  actually  experienced  or 
dreamed  events  in  mere  visual  terms.  But  with  abstract 
ideas,  we  usually  think  in  words  often  involuntarily  accom- 
panied by  the  visual  image  of  the  words. "^  Decidedly  op- 
posing this  theory,  James  says,  "The  opinion  as  stoutly 
professed  by  many  that  language  is  essential  to  thought 
seems  to  have  this  much  of  truth  in  it,  that  all  our  inward 
images  tend  invincibly  to  attach  themselves  to  something 
sensible,  so  as  to  gain  in  corporeity  and  life.  Words  serve 
this  purpose,  gestures  serve  it,  stones,  straws,  chalk-marks, 
any  thing  will  do  .  .  .  *  The  bricks  are  alive  to  tell  the 
tale'."^  Biihler  refers  to  the  fact  that  the  verbal  image 
occurs  in  thinking  only  in  a  sporadic  way  and  is  broken  and 
fragmentary  without  running  parallel  with  thought  processes.* 
Ribot  discards  the  theory  simply  as  "inaccep table. "^  The 
other  authors  of  the  school  of  Wurzburg,  e.  g.,  Marbe,  Orth, 
Ach,  Watt  and  Messer,  seem  to  agree  in  the  rejection  of  this 
theory.  On  the  other  hand,  recently  Dearborn  has  attributed 
the  utmost  importance  to  verbal  images  even  in  the  compari- 
son of  ink-blots  by  the  eye.  He  reports  that  he  found  in 
his  experiment  the  presence  of  verbal  images,  in  cases  where 
the  judgments  were  correct,  in  all  of  the  numerous  observers, 
except  one,  who  had  just  a  "true  feeling"  of  likeness  and  un- 
likeness.  This  observer  was,  nevertheless,  the  most  successful 
of  all  in  the  judgments.^ 

3.  Thought  as  identical  with  the  compounds  of  the  three 
dimensional  feelings.  Wundt  calls  those  "intellectual  feel- 
ings" which  attend  complex  intellectual  processes.  "They 
are  in  general  complex  total  feelings,  into  which  simple  feel- 
ings and  ideational  feelings  {Vorstellungsgefuhle)  enter  as 
components."^  "The  feeling  of  doubt  is  an  oscillating  emo- 
tional state  (Gemutzustand)."^  The  "feeling  of  agreement 
(which  is  a  kind  of  Vorstellungsgefuhl)  is  introspectively 
merely  a  feeling  of  relaxation  with  heightened  intensity."' 
"The    feeling    of    recognition   (Wiedererkennunsggefuhl)  is   a 

^Ib.,  I,  ist  ed.,  254. 

^Grundziige  der  Physiologischen  Psychologic,   1902,  5th  cd..  Vol.   Ill, 

p.  543- 

^James,  W.:  Principles  of  Psychology,  Vol.  II,  p.  305. 

'lb.,   317. 

•^"Idees  Generales,"  p.   100. 

^G.  V.  N.  Dearborn:  Experiment  on  the  Judgment  of  lyikeness  and  Un- 
likeness  of  Visual  Form,  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology  and  Scientific 
Method,  Feb.,   19 10,  p.  60. 

Ub.,  Vol.  III.  p.  264.  8/6.,  265.  m.,  510. 


A   STUDY   OF  UNDERSTANDING  45 

subjective  symptom  belonging  not  to  the  ideational  pro- 
cesses but  to  the  subjective  side  of  the  processes," — the 
processes  of  assimilation  of  ideas. ^  Its  subjective  quality 
"seems  a  sudden  and  unhindered  change  between  tension  and 
relaxation,  which  under  circumstances  can  be  joined  by  other 
feeling  qualities."^ 

Most  of  the  Wiirzburg  authors  discredit  this  Wundtian 
view  of  intellectual  or  cognitive  feelings.  Orth  in  his  analysis 
of  *' Bewusstseinslage"  (another  name  proposed  by  Marbe 
for  intellectual  feelings)  as  introspectively  observed  by  him- 
self and  others  while  serving  as  observers  in  Marbe's  study 
on  judgment,  finds  them  related  to  cognition  and  therefore 
implicitly  to  sensation  rather  than  to  feeling,  and  having 
reference  to  the  object  rather  than  to  the  subject.^  Doubt, 
according  to  him  is,  introspectively,  thoroughly  different  from 
sensations,  representations,  and  feelings  proper;  and  the  same 
with  feelings  of  certainty,  contrast,  agreement,  etc.*  "What 
Bewusstseinslagen  really  are,"  he  says  in  summarizing,  "re- 
mains to  be  investigated.  So  much  seems  to  be  certain, 
that  they  resisted  our  analysis  and  that  they  are  not  at  all 
merely  another  name  for  the  psychical  facts  that  Wundt 
comprehends  under  his  two  new  feeling  directions,  for  this 
contradicts,  not  only  self- observation,  but  also  their  great 
manifoldness."^ 

4.  Thought  as  judgment  and  as  knowledge  is  beyond  psy- 
chical experience.  Marbe  in  his  study  on  judgment  arrived 
at  the  conclusion  that  "there  are  no  psychical  conditions  of 
judgment  in  general  that  give  them  the  character  of  judgment 
as  such."^  And  the  same  with  understanding  of  judgment.^ 
Accounting  for  this,  he  says,  "thus  we  see  very  easily  that 
understanding  of  judgment  can  never  be  found  in  conscious- 
ness, because  it  rests  upon  knowledge,  and  knowledge  is  never 
given  in  consciousness."*  As  the  processes  of  judgment  are 
totally  beyond  consciousness,  so  in  its  study  there  is  as  little 
left  for  psychologists  as  of  physiological  chemistry  for  chem- 
ists.® Later  authors  of  the  Wiirzburg  school  agree  in  criti- 
cising Marbe's  reflexive  theory  of  judgment  as  due  to  too 
easy  stimuli.  Biihler  simply  speaks  of  his  "thought"  as 
actual  Wissen  and  not  such  potential  Wissen  as  Marbe  means. ^° 
James  speaks  of  his  feeling  of  tendency  (such  as  feeling  of 
familiarity,  recognition,  etc.)  as  not  a  "psychical  zero,"  but 
a  "psychical  fact"  though  vague  and  difficult  to  name.^^ 

^Ih.,   536. 

'Ih;  537. 

^Orth,  J.:  Gefuhl  und  Bewusstseinslage.     Berlin,  1903,  p.  73. 

*Ib.,  71.         ^Op.  ciU,  p.  42,  43.       8/6.,  p.92.  "0/>.  cit.,  p.  361. 

Hh.,  128.      Uh.,  p.  83.  Hb.,  p.  96.        "/6.,  Vol.  i,  p.  254. 


46  KAKIS^ 

5.  Thought  as  identical  with  reproductive  tendencies.  Ach 
calls  imageless  thought  or  pure  cognition  free  from  any 
"  phenomenological  constituents,  such  as  visual,  acoustic, 
kinesthetic  sensations  or  images,"  ''Bewusstheit,*'^  He  says, 
"When  a  word,  for  instance,  'bell'  is  presented  to  me  and  I 
apperceive  the  symbol,  I  understand  what  it  means.  I  have 
the  Bewusstheit  of  meaning.  According  to  the  theory  of 
Bewusstheit,  it  is  not  necessary  for  understanding  that  one 
have  representations  .  .  .  such  as  auditory  or  visual  images 
of  a  bell  .  .  .  Bach  representation  which  is  given  in  con- 
sciousness, for  instance,  the  impression  of  the  stimulus  word 
'bell,'  puts,  as  is  well  known,  a  number  of  associated  repre- 
sentations into  the  state  of  readiness.  This  putting-into- 
readiness  of  representations,  or  excitation  of  reproductive 
tendencies,  suffices  for  the  conscious  experience  (representa- 
tion) of  what  we  call  sense  or  meaning."^  In  criticism  of  this 
view.  Watt,  speaking  of  meaning  as  different  from  the  vague, 
reverberating  associations  or  tendencies,  says:  "Some  main- 
tain that  this  is  a  mass  of  vague  associations,  word-associa- 
tions or  others,  but  this  is  not  clear  according  to  the  protocol. 
It  rather  points  to  the  fact  that  a  concept,  such  as  appear  in 
free  self-observation,  is  something  different  from  vague  re- 
verberating associations  or  a  certain  number  of  them.'" 
Biihler  excluding  the  mere  consciousness  of  tendencies  from 
his  'thought'  or  'meaning,'  says:  "Thought  is  nothing  vague 
or  half-conscious  but  something  clear,  and  not  a  sum  but  a 
unity.  "^  Titchener  speaks  of  the  necessity,  in  the  awareness 
of  meaning,  of  the  co-operation  of  the  both  Ach's  awareness 
of  reproductive  tendencies  or  'meaning'  and  his  awareness 
of  relation.^ 

6.  Thought  as  identical  with ''fringe' '-experiences.  Accord- 
ing to  James,  thought  as  well  as  meaning  is  the  feeling  of 
relation  which  is  the  felt  "glow,"  "fringe,"  "echo,"  or  "re- 
verberation" and  the  transitive  experience  of  mind  in  dis- 
tinction to  substantive  or  static  experience,  e.  g.,  images, 
sensations,  etc.  He  says,  "The  meaning  of  the  words  which 
we  think  we  understand  as  we  read,  is  a  sign  of  direction,  .  . 
or,  a  bare  image  of  logical  movement  which  is  a  psychic 
transition,  always  on  the  wing,  so  to  speak,  and  not  to  be 

^Ach,  N.:  Ueber  die  Willenstatigkeit  und  das  Denken.  Gottingen, 
1905.     p.  210. 

2/6.,  216-217. 

'Watt,  J.:  Experimentelle  Beitrage  zur  einer  Theorie  des  Denkens, 
Archiv  f.  d.  gesamte  Psychologie,  1905  (4),  289  fif.,  p.  434. 

'^Ibid,  p.  326. 

^Titchener,  E.  B,:  Lectures  on  the  Experimental  Psychology  of  the 
Thought-processes,  N.  Y.,  1909,  p.  107. 


A  STUDY  OF   UNDERSTANDING  47 

glimpsed  except  in  flight."^  Further  characterizing  meaning 
as  feeHng  of  tendencies,  he  says,  "The  sense  of  our  meaning 
is  an  entirely  peculiar  element  of  thought  .  .  .  It  is  one 
of  those  evanescent  and  transitive  facts  of  mind  which  in- 
trospection cannot  turn  round  upon  ...  .  It  pertains  to 
the  fringe  of  the  subjective  state,  and  is  a  feeling  of  tendency, 
whose  netu'al  counterpart  is  undoubtedly  a  lot  of  dawning 
and  dying  processes  too  faint  and  complex  to  be  traced.  "^ 
He  further  characterizes  this  feeling  of  tendency  as  a  tendency 
of  a  "nascent  image, "^  as  a  feeling  antecedent  to  recall,  such 
as  a  "ringing  in  the  ear,"  or  "dancing  in  one's  mind"  of  a 
forgotten  name  or  word,  or  of  the  rhythm  of  a  verse,  as  the 
feeling  of  recognition  or  familiarity  which  is  a  "submaximal 
excitement  of  wide-spreading  association  brain-tracts."^ 

Thus  we  see  Ach's  conception  of  *  reproductive  tendencies ' 
is  quite  similar  to  the  "fringe"  experiences  of  James.  Ribot's 
view  seems  also  to  approach  these  conceptions  when  he  con- 
siders meaning  or  concept  as  an  "unconscious  substratum, 
organized  and  potential  knowledge,  harmonics  which  give  deto- 
nation to  the  word."^  Hoernle  referring  to  James,  says  that 
James  reverses  the  fact  of  ordinary  experiences  where  "we 
notice  more  of  meaning  than  words.  Meaning  stands  in 
the  foreground  and  images  or  ideas  or  sensory  elements  in 
the  background  of  consciousness."^ 

7.  Thought  as  well  as  meaning  as  a  "transcending"  experience. 
According   to    Messer,    sensations    and    sensation-complexes 
are  perceived   merely  as   contents   of  consciousness;   "they 
exist  or  do  not  exist,  but  do  not  point  beyond  themselves; 
they  do  not  mean."     Thought  as  also  perception,  etc.,  on 
the  contrary,  possesses  a  characteristic  attribute  of  'tran- 
scendence.'    "No  thought  thinks  upon  itself,   i.   e.,  on  the 
[constituents  of  consciousness  which  we  can  examine  in  direct 
retrospection."     "He  who,  thinks,"  he  continues,  "that  he 
lould  sufficiently  characterize  thought  and  perception  simply 
)y  looking  at  the  existent  sensations  and  images,  is  like  one 
[who  believes  he  could  find  the  value  of  money  by  merely 
[examining  its  material."^     Further,  in  regard  to  the  experience 
)f  understanding  or  meaning,   he  distinguishes  two  forms 
Lttending  the  reaction  to  the  same  stimulus  word:  i,  general 
mderstanding  which  is  further  unanalyzable;  and  2,   more 
Iconscious  and  definite  understanding  which,  he  says,  some- 
times is  "not  conditioned  by  the  Aufgabe  [problem  or  instruc- 
tion], but  is  such  as  would  be  explained  by  the  predominance 

^Ib.,  Vol.  I,  p.  253.  ^Ib.,  p.  132. 

^Ib.,  Vol.  I,  p.  472.  ^Mind,  Jan.,  1907. 

5/6.,  Vol.  I,  p.  254.  Ub.,  113. 
^Ib.,  p.  258. 


48  KAKISE 

of  the  reproductive  tendencies  in  the  general  constellation."^ 
But  "the  reaction  wherein  the  Aufgabe  enters  and  the  acts 
of  acceptance  and  rejection  take  place,  apparently  cannot 
be  explained  by  the  mechanism  of  mere  reproduction  and 
association,  and  herein  lies  the  justification  for  distinguishing 
the  processes  of  thought  from  those  of  pure  associative 
reproduction.  "2 

8.  Thought  as  a  third  psychical  element.  Biihler,  as  the 
result  of  his  study  on  thought,  came  to  the  conclusion  that 
thought-experiences  are  neither  analyzable  to  sensations  nor 
feelings  but  so  unique  and  specific  that  they  should  be  con- 
sidered as  compounds  of  a  third  psychical  unit  or  element, 
i.  e.,  Gedanke.^  Thought,  according  to  him,  is  act  of  knowing 
{Wissensact) ^  Meaning,  which  is  a  conscious  knowing,  can- 
not be  represented,  but  only  known.*  He  says  that  to  ask 
one  to  explain  knowing  or  thought  merely  by  the  terms  of 
the  quality  and  intensity  of  existent  sensations  is  the  same  as 
asking  one  to  explain  depth  by  the  terms  of  height  and  width.® 

9.  Thought  as  indescribable.  All  the  preceding  authors  who 
regard  thought  as  something  different  from  image  or  feeling 
proper,  agree  in  finding  it  as  further  indescribable.  Marbe, 
in  regard  to  his  Bewusstseinslage  speaks  of  conscious  facts 
whose  contents  either  totally  escape  from  further  characteri- 
zation or  are  difficult  to  approach.  Orth  says,  "Those 
Bewusstseinslagen  which  were  observed  by  Marbe  and  by  us 
are  of  diverse  kinds  and  have  only  this  point  in  common  that 
they  represent  psychical  facts  which  could  not  be  further 
analyzed  by  us.*"  Ach  says,  the  description  of  these  Bewusst- 
heiten  by  the  observers  is  very  difficult  because  of  the  difficulty 
of  verbal  expression,  as  they  lack  "  phenomenological  repre- 
sentations" (sensations  and  images,  etc.).*  Watt,  toward  the 
end  of  his  study  says,"  An  analytical  introspection  in  this  direc- 
tion is  exceedingly  difficult  .  .  .  We  know  psychologically  as 
much  as  nothing  about  the  nature  of  meaning-consciousnesses 
which  accompany  an  abstract  word."^  Messer  speaks  of 
thought-experiences  as  further  unanalyzable.  James  speaks 
repeatedly  of  the  difficulty  of  description  of  fringe-  experiences ; 
their  multitudinous  nuances  or  configurations  can  be  only 
felt. 

10.  Thought,  also  meaning  experiences,  as  identical  with 
kinesthetic  images.  Taking  a  quite  different  view  from  the 
preceding  authors,  Titchener,  in  his  recent  book  on  thought- 
processes,  declares  that  all  these  authors  or  their  observers 
who  find  thought-experiences  something  different  from  the 


17&.. 

,  82 

*ib., 

p. 

361. 

Uh. 

,  p- 

70. 

Uh., 

>  p. 

122. 

Uh., 

p- 

363. 

^Ib. 

,p. 

41. 

m., 

p. 

329- 

m.. 

p. 

361. 

m., 

p- 

435. 

A   STUDY  OF  UNDERSTANDING  49 

existent  elements,  e.  g.,  sensations,  images,  etc.,  are  victims 
of  stimulus-error;  that  they  do  not  separate  or  abstract  what 
they  infer  from  what  they  actually  experience  or  have,  but 
think  them  together,  just  as  an  observer  in  color-experiments, 
instead  of  reacting  to  an  abstracted  red  sensation,  reacts  to 
the  red  paper,  an  object,  the  result  of  both  sensations  and 
inferences;  and  that  the  results  of  their  introspections  are 
mere  intimations  or  indications,  and  not  the  descriptions  of 
what  they  have  experienced*.^  Referring  to  James's  feeling  of 
relation,  he  says  "the  phrase  'feeling  of  relation'  is  no  more 
unequivocal,  as  a  psychological  term,  than  the  phrase  'idea 
of  object'  or  'consciousness  of  meaning.'  It  carries  an  inti- 
mation, an  indication,  a  statement-about ;  it  does  not  describe. 
And  the  question  for  psychology  is  precisely  that:  what  we 
experience  when  we  have  a  feeling  of  relation? "^  The  con- 
sciousnesses of  thought  when  described  are  merely  kinesthetic 
images  or  sensations.  All  other  consciousnesses  are  not  the 
direct  data  of  introspection  but  the  results  of  addition  by 
reflection  and  inference.^  "And  all  such  'feelings,'  he  says, 
— feelings  of  if,  and  why,  and  nevertheless,  and  therefore, 
normally  take  the  form,  in  my  experience,  of  motor  empathy. 
I  act  the  feeling  out,  though  as  a  rule  in  imaginal  and  not  in 
sensational  terms. "^  Regarding  the  distinction  between  kin- 
esthetic images  and  sensations,  he  says,  "Actual  movement 
always  brings  into  play  more  muscles  than  are  necessary, 
while  ideal  movement  is  confined  to  the  precise  group  of 
muscles  concerned. ' '  ' '  The  sensed  or  actual  nod  (that  signifies 
assent  to  an  argument,  and  frown  (that  signifies  perplexity) 
are  coarse  and  rough  in  outlines;  the  imagined  or  mental 
nod  and  frown  are  clean  and  delicately  traced."^  He  wonders 
why  James  does  not  take  the  same  introspective  view  of 
his  '  feeling  of  relation '  as  he  does  with  the  feeling  of  a  *  central 
active  self'  in  which  he  (James)  finds  nothing  but  'bodily 
processes  for  the  most  part  taking  place  within  the  head.'^ 

§2.      CONTENTS   OF   MEANING   WITH   FAMILIAR   STIMULI 

What  are  the  actual  contents  of  consciousness  at  the  instant 
of  understanding,  the  direct  psychical  experiences  which  con- 
stitute the  experience  of  understanding  familiar  and  easy  words 
or  phrases?  The  protocols  of  all  the  foregoing  experiments 
show  that  there  was  not  one  kind  of  such  content  only  but 
several.  Arranged  according  to  the  general  order  of  succession 
or  quickness,  they  were :     i ,  Feeling  of  familiarity  or  recogni- 

^Ib.,  p.  145.  *lb.,  p.  186,  187. 

'/6.,  p.  185,  ^Ib.,  p.  20-22. 

Ub.,  p.  185.  «/&.,  p.  30. 

Journal — 4 


50  KAKISE 

tion  of  the  stimulus;  2,  Feeling  of  concept;  3,  Feeling  of  content; 
4,  Feeling  of  direction;  5  Half- developed  or  indefinite  images; 
and  lastly  6,  Fully  developed  or  definite  images. 

1.  Pure  Feeling  of  Familiarity.  With  a  very  familiar 
word  or  phrase,  or  in  repeated  reaction  to  a  stimulus  pre- 
viously understood,  the  occurrence  of  just  the  feeling  of 
familiarity  alone  or  the  recognition  of  the  stimulus  as  the  one 
understood  before,  was  sufficient  to  release  the  reaction  or 
cause  the  stimulus  to  be  felt  as  understood. 

For  instance:  Mountain.  (Obs.  Sn.  Ill — ii,  Time — 0.9".)  "I  read  it  in 
inner  speech  and  reacted  as  the  word  seemed  famiHar  to  me,  i.  e.,  when  the 
feeling  of  f  amiUarity  came.  I  did  n't  get  any  further  meaning.  No  imagery, 
no  associations  until  after  I  reacted." 

Psychology.  (Obs.  Ch.  Ill — iii — 15,  Time — 0.5".)  "The  first  feeling 
of  recognition  of  the  form  of  the  word  was  followed  instantly  by  the  feeling 
of  familiarity.  There  was  no  imagery.  In  this  particular  case  it  appears 
that  the  feeling  of  recognition  and  the  feeling  of  familiarity  are  the  same 
thing.  There  wasn't  any  imagery,  any  attempt  to  define.  I  recog^nized 
the  word.     Absolute  certainty  as  to  understanding." 

This  type  of  meaning  was  quite  common  and  frequent  with 
all  observers  and  regardless  of  the  concreteness  or  abstract- 
ness  of  the  stimulus  word.  It  was  the  first  and  quickest  to 
occur  of  all  the  types  of  meaning.  It  seldom  occurred, 
however,  with  the  mere  visual  perception  of  the  stimulus  word 
or  phrase.  Audi  to-motor  reading  of  the  stimulus  was  necessary 
to  release  the  reaction  even  in  this  type.  In  active  reactions 
and  with  familiar  abstract  stimuli,  it  was  seldom  followed  by 
any  suggested  images  in  any  observers.  In  active  reactions 
with  familiar  concrete  stimuli,  it  was  sometimes  followed, 
especially  with  observers  of  concrete  (or  visual)  type,  by 
suggested  images  which,  however,  always  occurred  after  the 
reaction.  And  such  was  the  case  with  all  the  passive  reactions 
where  the  suggested  images  made  the  terminus  of  the  reaction 
occurring  long  after  the  entrance  of  the  feeling  of  familiarity 
or  recognition. 

2.  Pure  feeling  of  Concept  or  Meaning.  In  the  preceding 
case  both  sensory  and  conceptual  familiarity  or  recognition 
fused  so  closely  together  that  there  is  difi&culty  of  analysis, 
though  sensory  familiarity  evidently  predominates  in  such 
reflexive  reactions.  With  less  familiar  stimuli,  or  when  the 
observers  waited  longer  with  very  familiar  stimuli,  these  two 
generally  became  separated  and  occurred  in  succession,  the 
sensory  recognition  always  preceding  the  conceptual. 

Example:  Pomology.  (Obs.  Ac.  II,  w — 10.)  "Recognized  the  word 
and  thought  it  familiar,  but  on  closer  examination,  I  found  that  I  could  not 
understand  its  meaning." 

Heaven,  (Obs.  Cf.  II,  w-5.)  Did  not  apperceive  the  word  for  a  minute. 
I  was  not  quite  attentive.  Then  I  got  a  purely  verbal  meaning  of  it  with- 
out imagery.     By  verbal  meaning  I  mean  I  first  recognized  it.     Then  I 


A  STUDY   OP   UNDERSTANDING  5 1 

had  a  slight  feeling.  It  was  not  at  all  a  sort  of  tridimensional  feeling,  but 
an  idea  of  something  sacred.  But  I  call  it  a  feeling  because  it  was  not 
definite. " 

In  its  frequency  and  conditions  of  occurrence,  this  type  of 
meaning  was  practically  the  same  as  the  preceding  one  except 
that  the  latter  always  preceded  the  former  in  case  of  con- 
currence. 

3.  Pure  Feeling  of  Content.  To  this  belong  the  experiences 
which  the  observers  expressed  as  "full  of  meaning, "  or  "con- 
tent," having  "rich  associations, "  or  "  coming  associations, " 
etc.,  which  were  accompanied  by  no  particular  images  or 
associations.  The  chief  marks  were  the  richness  and  poorness 
of  content.  A  feeling  of  rich  content  was  generally  found 
with  stimuli  designating  topics  which  observers  were  interested 
in  or  familiar  with,  and  a  feeling  of  poor  content  with  the  stimuli 
indicating  uninteresting  or  unfamiliar  subjects. 

Example:  Peace.  (Obs.  Sn.  Ill, — iii — 5.  Time — i.o".)  "I  read  it  in 
inner  speech.  But  the  inner  speech  was  not  very  clear  this  time.  And 
I  think,  I  had  a  feeling  of  the  meaning  of  the  word.  Whether  it  was 
different  from  the  feeling  of  familiarity  I  am  not  sure.  But  it  seems  to 
have  been  something  more  than  a  mere  feeling  of  familiarity.  This  some- 
thing may  be  some  feeling  of  moving  toward  something,  or  of  some  possi- 
bility of  development  and  is  very  hard  to  describe." 

House.  (Obs.  Cff.  I,  w — 3.)  "Perception  of  my  voice  [inner  speech]. 
Then  came  the  feeling  of  familiarity.  That  feeling  seems  to  me  to  be 
composed  of  various  kinds  of  images  not  yet  actual.  I  would  call  it  almost 
composite.  If  I  should  think  about  it  longer  I  would  have  some  particular 
images  out  of  it. " 

4.  Feeling  of  Direction.  This  feeling  is  the  experience  of 
the  mind's  pointing  to  or  turning  in  the  direction  of  the  place 
where  a  particular  object  or  event  referred  to  by  the  stimulus 
was  experienced.     It  is  an  incipient  form  of  object  imagery. 

Pedagogy.  (Obs.  Sn.  Ill — ^i — 14.)  "I  read  the  word  in  inner  speech  but 
not  very  loud  and  was  not  quite  sure  whether  I  read  it  correctly.  So  I 
read  it  again  and  had  a  faint  feeling  that  I  knew  the  word.  Then  I  thought 
of  the  direction  of  the  Dr.  B's  room  and  probably  also  had  a  very  vague 
suggestion  of  Dr.  B  himself.  The  consciousness  of  direction  was  very  clear. 
I  had  the  word  'teaching, '  probably  in  inner  speech. " 

Example:  Head.  (Obs.  Cff.  I.)  "Always  an  after  effect  of  sound.  I 
listened  for  the  after  effect  before  the  recognition  of  the  meaning.  Then 
came  the  feeling  of  familiarity  followed  by  a  vague  idea,  almost  a  feeling  of 
location  of  upward,  top  of  human  head,  idea  of  something  above.  I  had 
no  definite  image." 

This  experience  occurred  frequently,  especially  among  ob- 
servers belonging  to  a  rather  non-visual  type.  In  passive 
reactions,  and  especially  with  observers  belonging  rather  to 
the  visual  or  concrete  type  this  experience  was,  in  general, 
replaced  by  rather  fully-developed  object  images. 

5.  Half-developed  Images.  These  were  faint  and  vague 
representations  of  objects  or  circumstances,  which,  on  account 


52  KAKISS 

of  faintness  or  indefiniteness  of  imagery,  were  sometimes 
termed  by  the  observers  "ideas, "  something  "thought  of, '  'etc. 
This  was  especially  the  case  with  a  quick  recapitulation  of 
many  particular  past  experiences. 

Example:  Memory,  (Obs.  L.  M.  Ill — i,  4.)  "First  a  visual  impression 
of  the  word.  Then  reading  in  inner  speech.  And  then  I  had  a  bird's-eye 
view  of  all  that  I  have  been  working  at  for  several  weeks;  I  have  that 
subject.  Some  pleasure  and  satisfaction  in  seeing  the  word.  This  word 
was  very  full  of  meaning,  but  there  were  no  particular  visual  images.  Its 
meaning  could  not  be  expressed  in  so  short  a  time." 

Philosophy.  (Obs.  Ac.  II,  w— 65.)  "I  thought  of  Plato,  Aristotle,  Kant 
and  Hegel  in  connection  with  their  productions.  No  definite  visual  or 
auditory  elements. 

6.  Fully-developed  Images.  These  are  suggested  object- 
images  as  well  as  verbal  images  such  as  have  already  been 
described  (Part  II,  above).  They  were  in  general  the  slowest 
to  occur.  They  were  generally  found  in  passive  (or  prolonged) 
reactions  and  seldom  in  active  (or  quick)  reactions  to  familiar 
stimuli.  In  case  of  concurrence  with  the  preceding  experiences, 
they  were  the  last  to  occur,  that  is,  they  made  the  terminus 
of  the  reaction. 

Conclusions 

1.  These  results  negate  the  theory  of  the  identity  of 
thought  with  concrete  representations  and  also  the  theory  of 
the  identity  of  thought  with  verbal  images  so  far  as  meaning 
experiences  are  concerned,  as  these  images  are  a  part  only  of 
our  fully-developed  images, — one  of  the  six  types  of  meaning. 

2.  A  chief  condition  determining  whether  or  not  one  shall 
have  a  definite  image  (visual  or  verbal  or  other),  in  under- 
standing familiar  words  or  phrases,  is  the  length  of  time  the 
process  continues.  If  one  reacts  quickly,  i.  e.,  at  the  stage  of 
familiarity,  or  concept,  etc.,  one  will  not  have,  as  a  rule,  any 
definite  images,  regardless  of  individual  differences,  and  of 
the  concreteness  or  abstractness  of  the  stimulus.  If  one 
dwells  longer  upon  the  stimulus  one  will  usually  have  some 
particular  representations,  the  majority  of  which  will  be  re- 
cent memorial  associations,  in  predominantly  visual  form,  in 
the  case  of  visualizers,  and  in  predominantly  verbal  form  in 
the  case  of  verbalists,  regardless  of  the  concreteness  or  ab- 
stractness  of  the  stimulus. 

Remark:  Ach  suggests  that  pure  meaning  appears  most  prominently 
in  the  quick  reading  of  a  text  (op.  cit.,  p.  261).  James  speaks  of  the  two 
kinds  of  meaning,  i.  e.,  dynamic  meaning  which  attends  the  understanding 
of  a  phrase  and  is  "usually  reduced  to  the  bare  fringe,"  and  static  mean- 
ing which  attends  the  understanding  of  an  isolated  word  and  is  usually 
accompanied  by  object-images  when  the  word  is  concrete  and  by  nothing 
except  word-images  when  it  is  abstract."  (op.  ciL,  p.  265).  Wundt  says, 
'  'Whether  the  complication  of  these  elements,  ideas,  word-sound  and  word- 


A   STUDY  OF   UNDERSTANDING  53 

script,  occurs  completely  in  our  consciousness  depends  besides  on  which 
of  these  elements  acts  upon  us  directly  in  sense  perception.  The  ideas  can 
stay  isolated  under  certain  circumstances.  The  word-sound  generally 
calls  forth  the  object-image.  The  word-script  awakens  the  word-sound 
with  the  object-image."  {Op.  cit.,  vol.  Ill,  p,  543.)  John  Mill  commenting 
upon  Locke  and  Berkeley's  difference  of  opinion,  says,  '  'While  the  concen- 
tration of  attention  lasts,  if  it  is  sufficiently  intense,  we  may  be  temporarily 
unconscious  of  any  of  the  other  attributes,  and  may  really  for  a  brief  in- 
terval have  nothing  present  to  our  mind  but  the  attributes  constituent  of 
the  concepts  "  (Examination  of  Hamilton,  p,  393).  This  last  view  seems 
to  come  the  nearest  to  the  above  result  of  ours  if  we  change  the  indefinite 
expression  "intense"  in  the  quotation  into  "brief". 

I      §3.      SELECTIVE  EXPERIENCES  WITH  UNFAMILIAR  STIMULI 

In  the  understanding  of  unfamiliar  stimuli  where  the  mean- 
ing did  not  come  promptly  there  appeared  in  consciousness 
a  new  group  of  experiences  in  the  form  of  judgments,  i.  e., 
of  approval  or  rejection  of  the  contents  or  suggestions  as 
right  or  wrong.  They  were  experiences  or  consciousnesses  of 
searching,  waiting,  selection,  rejection,  certainty,  uncertainty, 
hesitation,  etc.,  generally  attended  by  feelings  of  tension 
and  relaxation.  These  are  sometimes  regarded  as  character- 
istic constituents  of  meaning.  A  special  test  was  therefore 
made  in  connection  with  the  third  experiment  to  determine 
how  far  these  experiences  are  alike  and  how  far  they  are  differ- 
ent in  different  types  of  thinking,  i.  e.,  in  the  understanding 
of  phrases  and  words  and  in  the  identification  of  non-sense 
stimuli. 

Procedure.  In  the  third  experiment,  beside  English  words 
and  phrases,  a  number  of  Chinese  characters,  as  a  kind  of 
nonsense  stimulus,  were  added.  With  these  characters,  in- 
stead of  understanding,  the  process  was  one  of  identification. 
The  five  English  speaking  observers  were  requested  to  com- 
pare the  second  of  the  two  stimuli  with  the  first,  or  standard, 
and  to  tell  whether  the  two  were  identical  or  different.  The 
standard  was  exposed  for  one  second  and  immediately  after- 
ward the  comparison  stimulus  which  was  sometimes  identical 
and  sometimes  not  identical,  but  always  quite  similar  in 
shape  to  the  standard.  The  reactions,  all  active,  were  made 
by  pressing  an  electric  key.  Introspections  were  taken  in 
the  same  way  as  with  understanding-reactions.  Easy  and 
difficult  stimuli  were  made  by  different  combinations  of  com- 
plexity and  irregularity  in  the  shapes  and  in  the  degree  of 
resemblance  between  the  standard  and  comparison  stimulus. 
For  instance  the  following  are  some  of  the  pairs  thus  matched, 
having  shapes  apparently  similar  but  not  identical. 


54  KAKISE 

These  identification-reactions  and  the  two  forms  of  under- 
standing-reactions, i.  e.,  of  words  and  of  phrases,  were  arranged 
in  such  a  way  that  a  difficult  reaction  of  one  form  was  fol- 
lowed by  a  difficult  reaction  of  the  other  form;  and  the  same 
with  easy  reactions.  The  observers  were  requested,  after 
giving  the  introspections  of  each  reaction,  to  report,  in  addi- 
tion, what  processes  (or  experiences)  in  the  two  successive 
reactions  they  found  similar  in  their  abstracted  forms  and 
what  different. 

The  following  is  a  sample  of  such  protocols: 

A.    Comparison  of  Difficult  Reactions 

Understanding.  Nostrum,  (Obs.  Ch.  Ill — iii,  2,  time — 2.0")-  "Feel- 
ing of  having  seen  the  word  came  first.  I  read  the  word  through  once. 
First  suggestion  was  that  of  the  Latin  word.  And  there  I  got  the  mean- 
ing of  the  word  but  not  quite  certainly.  A  little  bit  of  feeling  of  tension  is 
staying.  I  was  n't  quite  sm^e  of  the  content.  I  interpreted  it  as  a  sort  of 
fake  medicine. " 

Identification.  ^  ^  (Obs.  Ch.,  time—)  "Not  sure.  What  I  tried 
to  do  was  to  look  at  the  separation  of  the  figure  rather  than  to  judge  by 
general  impression,  and  found  that  some  are  the  same  while  others  are 
doubtful.  So  that  the  feeling  is  one  of  uncertainty,  doubt  in  this  case. 
Also  there  was  a  feeling  of  strain,  tension  with  unpleasant  coloration. " 

Comparison  of  the  experiences.  '  'The  feeling  of  searching  for  something, 
of  groping  is  quite  similar  with  the  cases  of  hard  English  words.  And  also 
the  feeling  of  strain,  tension  with  unpleasant  coloration,  is  just  the  same. " 

B.     Comparison  op  Easy  Reactions 

Identification.  "^  JF^  (Obs.  Ch.  time,  i.o")  "Different.  The  im- 
pression came  from  the  general  form  and  not  from  any  one  particular  line. 
Feeling  of  certainty  is  rather  complete.  At  first  there  was  a  feeling  of 
strain  and  tension  which  dropped  as  soon  as  I  reacted.  The  experiment 
ended  with  a  little  pleasure,  because  I  recognized  the  difference.  So  this 
was  a  personal  feeling  attached  to  the  consciousness  of  success. " 

Understanding.  Peace.  (Obs,  Ch.  time — i.o")  "I  read  it  and  rec- 
ognized it  at  once.  No  feeling  of  tension.  There  was  slight  visual 
imagery.  Feeling  of  certainty  as  to  the  meaning  of  the  word.  In  this 
feeling  of  certainty  there  was  the  feeling  that  rich  associations  could  be 
started." 

Comparison  of  the  experiences.  "The  feeling  of  certainty  with  the 
Chinese  characters  lacks  the  feeling  of  rich  content.  In  the  Chinese  char- 
acters there  is  a  feeling  of  recognition  in  the  strict  sense,  while  in  the  Eng- 
lish there  is  no  revival  of  the  occasion  when  I  first  saw  it.  Thus  the 
recognition  of  the  Chinese  character  is  much  more  a  matter  of  sensory 
form  than  of  content." 

Results  of  the  Comparison 

A.  Feeling  of  tension  and  relaxation.  In  regard  to  the 
qualitative  differences  of  these  feelings,  all  observers  agreed 
in  finding  them  very  similar  or  even  identical  in  character 
in  the  three  types  of  thinking:  identification  of  characters, 
understanding  of  words,  and  understanding  of  phrases.     In 


A  STUDY  OF  UNDERSTANDING  55 

regard  to  the  quantitative  dififerences,  they  found,  as  a  rule, 
more  tension  in  difficult  understanding  than  in  difficult  iden- 
tification, and  in  difficult  understanding  of  phrases  than  in 
that  of  words.  1 

B.  Feeling  of  content.  All  observers  agreed  in  finding 
decidedly  richer  content  feelings  with  words  and  phrases  in 
general  and  very  poor  content  feeling  or  none  at  all  with  the 
characters. ^^  In  words  and  phrases,  they  found  words  fre- 
quently to  have  richer  content  than  phrases.  The  content 
feeling  differed  according  to  the  particular  words  and  phrases. 

C.  Feelings  of  certainty  and  uncertainty,  i.  e.,  of  under- 
standing and  of  judgment.  Three  observers  found  these 
feelings  quite  similar  or  identical  in  the  three  types  of  thinking, 
whereas  the  other  two  observers  found  them  rather  different, 
not  only  among  the  three  types  of  thinking,  but  also  from 
stimulus  to  stimulus  in  each  type  of  thinking. 

It  appears  that  the  other  two  observers,  instead  of  com- 
paring these  feelings  in  their  pure  and  abstracted  forms, 
compared  them  in  their  complex  and  concrete  forms.  This 
is  plainly  seen  from  the  fact  that  in  accounting  for  the  differ- 
ences they  referred  either  to  the  differences  in  content  feelings 
or  to  those  in  associations  or  images.     For  instance: 

Obs.  Ch.  (Ill — iv,  2.)  Comparison — "As  to  the  feeling  of  certainty 
this  experience  [Chinese  character]  is  very  much  less  complex.  It  simply 
consists  in  the  recognition  of  the  visual  image  and  practically  no  associa- 
tions at  all." 

Obs.  Sn.  (Ill — iii,  13 — 14.)  Comparison — "This  feeling  of  certainty 
[with  the  Chinese  character]  in  my  mind  is  connected  with  the  seeing  very 
clearly  the  whole  space  where  I  expected  to  see  a  black  spot.  The  cer- 
tainty in  the  case  of  the  word  is  connected  with  the  feeling  of  easy  associa- 
tion.    In  this  case  it  is  only  a  feeling  of  difference." 

The  following  is  a  typical  case  of  the  comparison  of  these 
feelings  in  their  abstracted  form,  which  was  the  method  of  the 
other  three  observers. 

Obs.  L.  M.  (Ill — iii,  3.)  "There  was  no  meaning  except  the  visual 
impression.  When  my  eye  traversed  the  second  figure  and  came  to  the 
place  where  it  differs  I  felt  that  there  was  something  wrong.  And  then  I 
called  up  the  visual  image  of  the  first  one  and  recognized  the  difference, 
with  a  feeling  of  certainty.  This  feeling  itself  is  just  the  same  as  in  the 
cases  of  the  recognition  of  English  words. " 

The  author  thus  believes  this  discrepancy  is  merely  an 

^  The  maximum  effort  or  tension  was  experienced  not  with  absolutely 
difficult  or  unfamiliar  stimuli  but  with  partially  unfamiliar  ones.  With 
totally  difficult  stimuli,  observers  abandoned  the  attempt  as  hopeless  or 
too  complex  and  therefore  promptly  relaxed. 

2  When  the  reproduction  of  the  standard  was  faint  or  merely  felt,  it 
was  sometimes  regarded  as  having  a  very  poor  content;  when  the  reproduc- 
tion was  more  or  less  distinct  it  was  regarded  as  having  no  content,  but 
simply  as   an   image. 


56  KAKIS^ 

apparent  one  arising  out  of  the  differences  in  the  ways  of 
abstracting  the  phenomenon  to  be  observed/ 

So  much  for  the  experiences  compared  by  all  observers. 
The  other  similar  experiences,  which  were  compared  by  some 
observers  and  viewed  as  similar,  or  practically  the  same,  in 
their  abstracted  forms,  were  feelings  of  searching,  groping, 
waiting  and  the  peculiar,  though  frequent,  experience  of  the 
sudden  appearance  of  images  or  ideas,  feelings  of  satisfaction, 
dissatisfaction,  etc.  These  results  point  to  the  following 
conclusions:  i.  Selective  experiences,  as  also  feelings  of 
tension  and  relaxation,  cannot  be  regarded  as  either  the 
sole  or  the  characteristic  constituents  of  the  meaning  of 
words  or  phrases,  for  they  were  found  as  well  in  reactions 
to  nonsense  stimuli.  2.  On  the  other  hand,  as  the  feeling 
of  content  was  found  to  be  not  merely  different  but  totally 
lacking  in  the  reactions  to  meaningless  stimuli,  this  feeling  may 
with  great  probability  be  regarded  as  one  of  the  characteristic 
constituents  of  the  meaning  of  words  and  phrases. 

§4.      UI^TIMATE  CONSTITUENTS   OF   MEANING 

What  are  the  ultimate  psychical  constituents  of  the  six 
types  of  meaning  mentioned  above,  i.  e.,  can  they  be  reduced 
to  psychological  "elements,"  to  three  dimensional  feeling  and 
sensation  having  two  attributes,  quality  and  intensity,  or  to 
a  specific  image  or  feeling?  This  point  the  observers  were  not 
asked  to  decide.  But  from  the  results  of  all  the  foregoing 
study,  the  writer  may  make  certain  inferences.  Let  us  start  at 
the  last  type  of  meaning. 

(i.)  Fully  Developed  Images.  Of  these,  visual  images  of 
objects,  verbal  images  (in  audito-motor  or  visual  terms), 
suggested  organic  (as  well  as  kinesthetic)  images  are  so  clear 
in  their  ultimate  constituents  as  to  need  no  comment  here. 
The  constituents  of  memory  images  were  complex  and  their 
dominant  factors,  moreover,  varied  according  to  individual 
observers  and  circumstances;  but,  it  seems,  a  visual  factor, 
though  sometimes  faint  and  incipient,  was  a  constant  one,  for  a 
memory  image  has  always  a  spatial  localization,  i.  e.,  repro- 
duces the  place  where  the  object  or  event  was  experienced., 
The  same  thing  may  be  said  about  the  constituents  of  the 

*It  is  interesting  to  note  that  Rousmaniere  had  the  same  result  in  a 
similiar  experiment.  The  report  says  in  part:  "The  subjects  did  not 
agree  in  their  answers  to  the  first  problem.  Some  found  not  only  that  the 
certainty  connected  with  their  belief  in  the  results  of  their  addition  seemed 
to  be  of  a  distinct  type  from  that  connected  immediately  with  the  sense 
of  sight  itself  ....  Others  found  but  one  kind  of  a  feeling  of 
certainty."     (Harvard  Psychol.  Studies,  Vol.  II,  p.  279.) 


A  STUDY   OF   UNDERSTANDING  57 

"indicative  images"  which  are  the  representation  of,  or  a 
pointing  to,  the  concrete  objects  near  at  hand. 

(2.)  Half-developed  Images.  Their  constituents,  in  the 
main,  seem  to  be  the  same  as  those  of  fully  developed  images, 
except  that  in  the  former  they  are  faint  and  incipient. 

(3.)  Feeling  of  Direction.  This  made  an  incipient  stage 
of  object-images  having  particular  localizations,  i.  e.,  memory 
images  and  indicative  images.  Consequently  a  visual  factor 
in  its  faint  and  incipient  form  seems  to  be  a  constant  factor. 
In  the  case  of  some  observers  the  feeling  was  sometimes  ex- 
perienced predominantly  in  kinesthetic  terms. 

For  instance:  Duty  before  pleasure.  (Obs.  Sn.  Ill — ii — 15.)  "I  expected 
a  sentence.  I  read  it  in  inner  speech  and  had  the  familiarity-feeling  for 
it  and  at  about  the  same  time,  perhaps  a  little  bit  later,  I  had  that  sort  of 
classification  which  I  frequently  have  in  such  cases,  and  thought  this  is  a 
moral  maxim.  Then  I  tried  to  get  more  special  cases  of  some  duty  which 
I  have.  I  tried  to  think,  as  an  example  of  this,  of  something  connected 
with  my  own  affairs,  but  I  did  n't  succeed  very  well,  I  had  a  very  vague  and 
indefinite  idea  of  'duty '  and  'pleasure '  and  there  was  a  kind  of  location 
here  in  the  direction  of  my  office.  I  didn't  get  any  further  idea  about  it, 
except  the  thought  about  something  I  had  planned.  But  I  think  it  may 
be  this  that  I  had  some  letters  this  morning  which  I  wished  to  read,  and 
was  thinking  that  I  would  not  be  able  to  read  them  until  after  my  lecture. 
There  was  only  a  tendency  to  run  in  that  direction  without  any  actualiza- 
tion of  the  circtunstance. " 

Victory  or  Westminster  Abbey.  (Obs.  Cff.  I,  A — 14.)  "Feeling  of  sur- 
prise because  I  expected  something  more,  and  also  because  of  the  peculiar 
construction  of  the  sentence.  The  name  Nelson  came  up  almost  at  once, 
partly  because  his  ship  was  called  'Victory '  and  partly  because  it  suggested 
a  saying  such  as  he  might  have  uttered.  A  vague  almost  visual  image  of 
the  picture  of  Westminster  Abbey  and  feeling  of  direction,  i.  e.,  from  the 
sea  where  the  battle  was  fought  to  London  as  if  my  eyes  were  moving  from 
one  point  to  another — I  felt  inner  movements  of  the  eyes.  Feeling  of 
meaning  was  of  a  great  warrior  determined  either  to  win  or  die.  In  this 
case  there  was  n't  much  inner  speech.  The  visual  image  took  the  place  of 
the  auditory  though  it  was  not  very  definite." 

Sometimes  the  description  of  this  feeling  was  too  indefi- 
nite to  surmise. 

For  instance:  i^/ta/)^^^/^.  (Obs.  ^w.  Ill — i — 17.)  "First  my  attention  was 
good.  I  read  the  word  in  inner  speech,  and  I  had  a  suggestion  of  it  in  a 
musical  sense,  a  certain  piece  of  music  called  a  rhapsody.  I  think  there 
was  a  sort  of  direction  toward  Mechanics  Hall  where  the  concert  was  held. 
Two  or  three  years,  or  it  may  be  one  year  ago,  I  heard  the  Hungarian  Rhap- 
sody there.  There  was  a  sort  of  vague  association  with  other  concerts. 
Then  I  read  the  word  again  in  inner  speech  and  then  I  tried  to  get  a  mean- 
ing for  it  and  that  time  a  very  faint,  shadowy  suggestion  of  a  person  in  a 
state  of  rhapsody  was  seen.  The  direction  of  it  was  different  from  that 
to  Mechanics  Hall.  It  was  very  indefinite  and  faint  and  hardly  can  be 
called  an  image  at  all. 

Heaven.  (Obs.  Gl.  1 — w — 15.)  First  sound,  next  understanding.  And 
third,  a  vague  image  of  the  sky  or  rather  opening  above.  The  mind  went 
upwards.     No  visual  image  of  the  color. 

(4.)     Feeling  of  Content.     The  observers  often  described 


58  KAKISK 

this  feeling  as  one  of  coming  associations,  incipient  suggestions, 
etc.,  as  already  mentioned.  This  introspection  is  corrobo- 
rated by  the  following  considerations  in  regard  to  the  rela- 
tion of  the  feelings  of  richness  and  poorness  of  content  to 
their  concomitant  conditions,  i.  e.,  i,  to  the  material  or  kind 
of  stimulus;  2,  to  the  duration  of  the  reaction;  and  3,  to  the 
conditions  under  which  the  stimulus  was  given. 

a.  Material  conditions.  With  absolutely  difficult  or  un- 
familiar stimuli  when  the  observers  had  no  definite  suggestions 
or  associations  and  their  minds  were  "shut  up"  or  "blank," 
no  content  feeling  was  present.  Uninteresting  or  unfamiliar 
words  usually  awoke  poorer  content  feeling  than  interesting 
or  familiar  ones  did.  Chinese  characters  (the  ones  to  be  com- 
pared in  the  identification  experiments)  awoke  no  proper 
content  feeling.  With  a  single  definite  and  vivid  general 
object-image  (no  matter  whether  it  was  visual,  organic  or 
kinesthetic),  excepting  memory  images,  the  observers  seldom 
experienced  a  rich  content  feeling,  excepting  in  some  cases  of 
passive  reaction  where  the  observers  exceptionally  dwelt  long 
on  the  suggested  images. 

b.  Duration  of  reaction.  Content  feeling  was  not  present 
in  the  reflexive  type  of  reaction  released  by  the  pure  feeling 
of  familiarity  or  recognition  alone.  It  was  replaced  or  weak- 
ened on  some  occasions  by  a  definite  or  vivid  image  occurring 
later  in  the  development,  which  shows  that  proper  time 
relations  are  essential  for  the  appearance  of  this  feeling. 

c.  Conditions  under  which  the  stimulus  was  given.  Fa- 
miliar words  or  phrases  presented  simultaneously  in  number 
and  for  a  short  interval  awoke  no  content  feeling.  ^  Isolated 
words  as  a  rule  awoke  richer  content  feeling  than  those  given 
in  phrases.  A  single  noun  awoke  frequently  a  richer  content 
feeling  than  did  a  short  phrase. 

These  phenomena  of  the  concomitances  of  the  subjective 
and  objective  changes  will  be  difficult  to  account  for  ade- 
quately in  any  other  way  than  to  assume  a  content  feeling  as  a 
consciousness  of  the  actual,  simultaneous,  and  incipient  ex- 
citation of  a  number  of  past  experiences  or  images  related 
to  the  stimulus.  If  a  large  number  of  such  associations  is 
actually  excited,  the  result  will  be  the  feeling  of  richness  of 
content.  If  the  number  is  small,  the  result  will  be  the  feeling 
of  poorness  of  content.  If  there  is  no  association,  the  result 
will  be  the  feeling  of  no  content.  The  lack  or  poorness  of 
content  feeling  in  the  case  of  sensory  familiarity,  "pure  con- 
cept," and  a  number  of  simultaneously  exposed  words  and 
phrases,  is  simply  due  to  the  insufficiency  of  necessary  time 

'  This  test  was  made  in  one  of  the  auxiliary  experiments. 


A  STUDY  OF  UNDERSTANDING  59 

for  the  actual  reinstatement  of  past  experiences,  even  in  an 
incipient  way.  Familiar  words  or  phrases  have,  of  course, 
numerous  potential  associations,  but  to  have  a  content  feeling 
it  is  necessary  to  actualize  some  of  them,  at  least.  Too  vivid 
or  too  definite  single  images  work  detrimentally  to  the  feeling 
of  rich  content,  because  they  absorb  too  much  of  the  mental 
energy  to  awake  at  the  same  time  numerous  other  incipient 
reproductions.  Isolated  words  give  richer  feeling  than  phrases 
under  the  same  circumstances,  because  there  the  associations 
are  not  circumscribed  and  the  mind  can  welcome  what- 
ever related  associations  may  revive,  and  the  result  is  the 
crowding  together  of  these  associations  in  their  incipient 
forms  which  is  felt  as  richness  of  content.  But  this  state  of 
experience  does  not  long  endure,  for  one  of  the  strongest  of 
them,  such  as  a  recent  memory  association,  will  soon  push 
itself  up  completely,  as  was  often  the  case  in  our  experiments. 
When  a  word  is  interwoven  in  a  context,  only  such  associations 
are  tolerated  by  the  mind  as  will  conform  to  the  general  pur- 
port or  meaning  of  the  phrase,  and  all  other  incoherent  asso- 
ciations are  suppressed.  ^  The  richer  feeling  often  attending 
a  single  word  in  comparison  with  a  short  phrase  is  perhaps 
due  also  to  insufficiency  in  the  time  allotted  to  each  word 
of  the  phras%  for  the  development  of  its  own  content  feeling, 
i.  e.,  the  mind  moves  on  too  quickly  to  the  next  word.  The 
rich  content  feeling  of  a  memorial  association,  in  spite  some- 
times of  its  comparative  vividness  and  definiteness,  is  very 
likely  due  partly  to  the  details  and  variety  of  the  imagery 
and  partly  to  emotional  excitations.  The  following  instances 
will  illustrate  this  point. 

Philosophy.  (Obs.  L.  M.  Ill,  ii — 2.)  "Sense  came  very  quickly;  not 
with  the  reading  of  the  word  but  immediately  after;  and  it  seemed  to  have 

great  deal  of  meaning,  perhaps  because  of  the  fact  that  I  had  been  read- 
fing  philosophy  last  night.  There  was  feeling  of  tension  and  excitation 
fiuntil  I  got  the  sense.     The  feeling  was  agreeable. " 

Sleep  is  necessary  for  health.  (Obs.  Ch.  Ill — ii — 9.).  .  ."The  feeling  of 
familiarity  was  pretty  complete  because  it  suggested  my  own  condition, 
■that  is,  I  did  not  sleep  last  night  very  well.  So  there  was  a  pleasure  in  it, 
|;and  thus  the  feeling  of  familiarity  had  a  rich  content,  for  it  refers  to  per- 
gonal interest. " 

Sleep  is  necessary  for  health.  (Obs.  E.  M.)  "Perfect  feeling  of  famili- 
^arity  and  certainty  of  judgment.  It  awoke  a  good  deal  of  association  with 
lit,  because  I  have  made  an  effort  without  success  to  sleep  after  dinner  this 
fcafternoon. 

Regarding  the  ultimate  analysis  of  this  feeling  which  is 
le  awareness  of  numerous  simultaneously  excited  incipient 

^  C/.  Huey's  result:  "The  words  given  in  isolation  gave  a  greater 
tyariety  of  association  than  did  the  context  words."  Am.  J.  of  Psychol., 
^ol.  XII,  p.  282  ff. 


6o  KAKISE 

images,  it  is  clear  that  this  feeling  has  nothing  to  do  with 
the  tri-dimensional  feelings  which  may,  or  may  not  accom- 
pany it  by  way  of  addition.  Again,  as  it  is  the  direct  aware- 
ness of  images  themselves,  it  cannot  be  called  a  subjective 
affection  or  emotion,  excepting  in  cases  of  emotional  excita- 
tions in  memorial  association  which  give  the  meaning  a 
"sense  of  reality"  or  "warmth."  Emotions  in  these  cases, 
however,  only  emphasize  and  do  not  make  up  the  content 
itself,  which  is  constituted  of  memorial  associations.  There 
is  need  always  of  incipient  images  for  meaning,  whether  it  is 
cool  or  warm,  dry  or  rich.  Whereas,  emotions  of  various 
form  can  exist  without  understanding  or  sense  of  meaning. 

Neither  can  we  describe  the  content  feeling  in  terms  of  a 
definite  and  specific  image  for  it  is,  first,  the  resultant  of 
many  images  or  associations,  each  of  which  consists  of  more 
than  one  specific  or  sensory  image  (such  as  a  visual,  an  audi- 
tory, a  motor,  etc.);  and,  secondly,  these  images  are  all  only 
incipiently  awakened.  The  pure  feeling  of  richness  or  poor- 
ness of  content,  without  any  subjective  trace  of  images,  may 
be,  in  the  meanwhile,  called  a  "total  feeling,"  not  in  the  sense 
of  the  fusion  of  feelings  proper,  but  in  the  sense  of  the  fusion 
of  faintly  excited  different  images. 

(5.)  Pure  Feeling  of  Concept  or  Meaning.  Owing  to  the 
vagueness  of  the  customary  terms  "concept"  or  "meaning" 
as  regards  their  psychical  constituents,  the  writer  has  no 
direct  basis  for  analysis  when  the  observers  simply  speak 
of  a  concept  or  meaning  without  further  description.  So 
that  so  long  as  there  is  given  no  positive  description  of  this 
experience,  the  only  way  at  hand  is  to  infer  it.  The  inference 
is  made  from  the  nature  of  other  types  of  meaning  which 
generally  immediately  precede  or  succeed  the  feeling  of  con- 
cept, or  sometimes  replace  it.  The  type  which  precedes  is 
the  pure  feeling  of  familiarity,  or  recognition  of  the  stimulus 
as  the  one  already  familiar.  The  type  which  succeeds  is  the 
pure  feeling  of  content.  So  that  a  pure  feeling  of  concept, 
meaning  or  knowing,  without  any  further  configuration  or 
content  may  be  identified  with  the  pure  feeling  of  recognition 
or  familiarity,  or  with  something  quite  similar  in  nature.  If 
the  feeling  of  concept  or  meaning  has  something  more  sub- 
stantial, it  may  be  identified  with  the  content  feeling.  If  its 
nature  becomes  more  materialized,  so  to  speak,  it  will  be 
found  identical  with  the  feeling  of  direction,  or  with  half  or 
fully  developed  images.  But  in  such  cases  it  is  no  more 
pure. 

(6.)  Pure  Feeling  of  Familiarity  or  Recognition.  This  feel- 
ing, as  already  stated,  was  the  first  and  quickest  to  appear  of  all 
types  of  meaning,  and  attached  directly  to  the  stimulus  with- 


A   STUDY   OF   UNDERSTANDING  6 1 

out  any  intermediary  except  audito-motor  reading  when  the 
stimulus  was  exposed.  It  thus  makes  the  first  or  the  most 
primitive  stage  of  the  series  of  reproductive  processes.  As 
a  reproductive  process,  there  seems  to  be  no  important  differ- 
ences between  the  experience  (as  such)  of  familiarity  with 
the  stimulus  as  one  experienced  before  (whether  understood 
or  not)  or  "sensory  recognition,"  and  the  familiarity  with 
the  stimulus  as  one  understood  before  or  known,  or  "con- 
ceptual recognition."! 

In  the  earlier  stage  of  this  feeling  there  was  often  no  sub- 
jective difference  between  the  "sensory  familiarity,"  i.  e.,  the 
recognition  of  the  stimulus  as  one  experienced  before  (whether 
understood  or  not),  and  the  "conceptual  familiarity,"  i.  e., 
the  recognition  of  the  stimulus  as  one,  the  meaning  of  which 
is  known  to  the  observer.  This  fact  is  shown  in  the  cases  of 
premature  or  mistaken  reaction,  as  mentioned  before.  Thus 
in  their  first  stage  of  reproduction  both  sensory  and  conceptual 
familiarity  must  be  very  much  alike  or  identical.^  The  sub- 
jective criterion  by  which  the  observers  became  soon  after 
aware  of  their  mistakes  must  very  likely  be  the  presence  and 
absence  of  content  feeling  or  "coming  associations." 

So  much  for  the  psychological  nature  of  pure  knowing  as 
meaning;  now  regarding  the  ultimate  constituents  of  sensory 
familiarity.  Let  us  take  the  simplest  case.  Perhaps  the 
simplest,  purest  and  at  the  same  time  the  most  durable  type 
of  this  feeling  is  that  which  was  experienced  by  the  observers 
in  the  recognition  of  the  Chinese  characters  in  the  forms  of 
purely  visual  nonsense  stimuli  practically  free  from  associa- 
tions. Though  obviously  this  feeling  is  thoroughly  originated 
by  the  previous  impression  of  the  same  stimulus,  the  observers 
found  it  difficult  to  give  any  positive  description  of  it  in  terms 
of  psychical  elements.  By  way  of  negative  description,  it 
may  be  noted  that  not  only  was  there  no  one  of  our  observers 
who  ever  positively  identified  this  experience  with  tridimen- 
sional feeling  but  also  there  were  many  who  reported  it  as 
decidedly  different.  That  this  feeling  is  not  a  mere  alterna- 
tion of  the  feelings  of  tension  and  relaxation  is  seen  in  the 

ict  that  observers  often  relaxed  (thinking  the  characters  too 

>mplex  to  identify  and  so  giving  up  the  attempt)  without 

^The  reader  should  not  confuse   this    case  of  the   reproduction  of  the 
feeling  of  knowing  of  once  known  (or  easy)  stimuli  with  the  processes  of 

lowing  for  the  first  time  of  unfamihar  stimuH. 

^  ^  It  must  be  remembered  that  we  are  dealing  here   with  the  reproduc- 

^on  of  the  feeling  of  knowing  awakened  by  the  perception  of  once  known 

understood,  i.  e.,  familiar  or  easy  stimuli,  and  not  with  the  processes  of 

lowing  for  the  first  time  of  unfamiliar  or  difficult  stimuli  which  are  quite 

)mplex. 


62  KAKISE 

having  the  experience  of  famiUarity  or  recognition.  Nor  can 
it  be  regarded  as  a  specific  image,  for  it  occurred  earlier  than 
any  definite  image.  Even  organic  imagery  or  sensation  which 
is  more  primitive  and  undifferentiated  and  consequently 
more  all-embracing  than  kinesthetic  imagery,  will  no  more 
cover  this  feeling  than  do  feelings  of  tension  and  relaxation. 
One  will,  perhaps,  find  this  feeling  in  its  bare  form  to  be  localized 
centrally  rather  than  peripherally,  as  "spiritual"  rather  than 
corporeal.  I  may  say,  therefore,  that  this  feeling  is  a  funda- 
mental, not  further  reducible,  retrospective  quality  of  a  present 
impression,  i.  e.,  a  coloration  or  configuration  given  to  the 
present  impression  by  the  rudimentary  revival  of  its  past 
experience.  The  present  impression  may  be  any  existing 
content,  sensation,  feeling,  image,  idea,  thought,  etc.  It  is 
thus  different  from  ordinary  quality  or  intensity  of  sensations. 
It  is  not  an  independent  element,  as  it  attaches  always  to 
sensations  or  feelings  and  never  occurs  alone.  The  pure  feeling 
of  knowing  awakened  by  familiar  stimuli  is  only  a  special 
case  of  this  feeling  of  familiarity;  consequently  "thought" 
in  such  a  sense  is  neither  a  third  element^  nor  a  highly  ele- 
vated something,  but  merely  the  most  primitive  and  rudi- 
mentary form  of  reproduction.  Thought  in  the  sense  of '  *  tran- 
scendental" reference^  which  seems  to  have  more  content  than 
pure  recognition  or  knowing,  may  be  found  in  our  content 
feeling  if  its  introspective  aspect  is  indefinite,  or  in  the  feeling 
of  direction  or  the  indicative  images  if  it  is  more  definite. 
Biihler's  "intention"'  in  the  sense  of  condensed  thought  or 
quick  recapitulation  may  be  foun,d  in  our  complex  memorial 
associations  as  half -developed  images.  In  short  all  varieties 
of  meaning-experiences  are  found  as  belonging  to  one  or 
other  of  the  different  stages  of  the  revival  of  the  related  past 
experiences. 

Social  and  practical  custom  attaches  a  certain  cluster  of 
associations  to  a  word  or  phrase  as  its  meaning  to  the  exclusion 
of  others,  so  that  our  understanding  of  a  word  or  phrase, 
which  is  a  direct  or  indirect,*  incipient  or  full  recalling  of 
such  related  associations,  is,  in  all  cases,  a  selective  or  pur- 
posive action  from  the  logical  or  outer  point  of  view.  With 
easy  or  familiar  words  such  selected  associations  are,  however, 
ever  ready  and  come  promptly  without  any  subjective  or 
psychological  experiences  of  the  sort  which  usually  character- 
ize the  selective  processes,  so  that  psychologically,  or  from 

1  Cf.  Biihler:    Op.  cit.,  p.  329. 
^Messer:   Op.  cit.,  113. 
^Op.  cit.,  p.  346  ff. 

*  That  is,  through  the  associations  of  intermediary  images  whose  mean- 
ings are  well  known. 


I 


A   STUDY  OF   UNDERSTANDING  63 

the  inner  point  of  view,  a  cluster  of  selected  associations  or 
meaning  once  mechanized  becomes  identical  with  a  cluster 
of  random  associations,  or  pure  reproductions.  What  is  then 
the  meaning  in  case  of  an  unfamiliar  or  difficult  word  or 
phrase  the  comprehension  of  which  is  attended  by  a  series 
of  selective  experiences,  such  as,  feelings  of  effort,  suspense, 
hesitation,  searching,  rejection,  doubt,  uncertainty,  etc.?  The 
answer  is  that  a  meaning,  as  a  resultant,  remains  always 
the  same  whether  it  is  reached  through  a  strenuous  or  an  easy 
process,  whether  it  is  consciously  selected  or  mechanically 
reproduced.  These  selective  experiences  were  not  only 
common  in  all  types  of  active  or  volitional  thinking,  whether 
it  is  understanding  of  abstract  phrases  or  comparison  of  sense 
impressions,  but  are  also  found  in  their  pure  forms  to  be  very 
much  alike  or  identical.  They  were  found  to  be  stereotyped  and 
did  not  develop  to  such  successive  series  as  did  the  reproductive 
tendencies,  excepting  that  they  showed  changes  in  intensity 
and  oppositions  like  those  of  feeling  proper.  Their  apparent 
configurations  and  development  must  be,  in  reality,  those 
of  the  content  or  reproductive  series  to  which  they  attach. 
Clearness  and  unclearness  of  meaning,  abstracted  from  con- 
tent-feeling or  reproduction,  may  be  reduced  to  the  mere 
feelings  of  certainty  and  uncertainty. 

Further  inquiry  into  the  ultimate  constituents  of  feelings 
of  certainty  and  uncertainty  and  other  selective  experiences, 
which  can  be  found  in  simpler  and  purer  forms  in  the  identifi- 
cation or  comparison  of  purely  sensory  stimuli,  is  left  for 
later  studies. 

Summary  of  the  Principai,  Resui^ts  of  the  Study 

1.  Whether  we  have  audito-motor  or  visual  imagery  of 
the  stimulus  word  depends  primarily  upon  whether  the  word 
is  exposed  or  spoken. 

2.  The  kinds  of  imagery,  the  frequency  of  which  seemed 
markedly  influenced  by  the  individual  peculiarities  of  the 
observers,  were  as  follows:  i,  Motor  speech;  2,  visual  speech; 
3,  associated  (suggested)  word-images;  4,  associated  object- 
images  in  visual  terms. 

3.  The  frequency  of  memory  images  is  primarily  condi- 
tioned neither  by  the  concreteness  or  abstractness  of  the 
stimulus  word  nor  by  individual  peculiarities,  but  by  the 
slowness  or  quickness  of  the  reaction. 

4.  The  customary  method  of  association  experiments 
seems  to  be  too  artificial  for  the  study  of  natural  or  real 
associations.  Whereas  the  Ausfrage  method  seems  to  be 
better  adapted  both  to  the  study  of  the  general  laws  of  asso- 
ciation and  to  the  study  of  individual  peculiarities  of  asso- 
ciation. 


64  KAKISE  , 

5.  Whether  or  not  one  has  in  the  understanding  of  a  word 
or  phrase  a  concrete  representation  depends  primarily  upon 
the  duration,  i.  e.,  upon  the  time  one  dwells  upon  it. 

6.  The  characteristic  constituents  of  the  meaning  of  a 
word  or  phrase  are  not  selective  experiences,  but  series  of 
different  phases  of  reproduction. 

7.  " Feeling  of  concept"  may  be  reduced  to  either  "feeling 
of  familiarity  "  or  "  feeling  of  content. "  "  Feeling  of  content, ' ' 
which  is  the  awareness  of  the  more  or  less  fused  aggregate 
of  incipient  associations,  seems  to  be  hardly  reducible  to  any 
specific  images.  "Feeling  of  familiarity,"  which  is  the  most 
fundamental  and  elementary  form  of  the  reproductive  experi- 
ence and  seems  to  be  reducible  neither  to  the  feelings  proper 
nor  to  the  so-called  intensity-quality  attributes  of  sensations, 
may  be  regarded  for  the  present  as  a  third  or  retrospective 
quality  of  sensations  or  other  psychic  experiences.  ^ 

1 1  wish  here  heartily  to  thank  Dr.  R.  Acher,  Mr.  C.  Ankeney,  Dr.  H.  W. 
Chase,  Dr.  E.  W.  Coffin,  Dr.  C.  Guillet,  Mr.  G.  Hirose,  Mr.  S.  Kanda, 
Mr.  M.  A.  Kaylor,  Dr.  T.  Misawa,  Dr.  E.  Mumford,  Mrs.  L.  Mumford, 
Dr.  C.  A.  Osborne,  Dr.  E.  C.  Sanford,  Dr.  T.  L.  Smith,  and  Dr.  G.  H.  Steves 
for  their  kind  services  as  observers.  I  desire  especially  to  acknowledge 
my  great  obligation  to  Dr.  E.  C.  Sanford  for  his  kind  assistance  in  many 
ways   essential   to   the   completion   of   this   paper. 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  APRAXIA 


By  ISADOR  H.  CoRiAT,  M.  D.,  Boston,  Mass. 


It  is  only  under  special  and  favorable  circumstances,  either 
of  experiment  or  of  disease,  that  certain  complex  psychic  or 
motor  disturbances  can  be  traced  to  an  exact  cerebral  local- 
ization. The  most  interesting  and  at  the  same  time  the  most 
complicated  of  these  disturbances  seem  to  be  localized  in 
some  portion  of  the  left  hemisphere,  particularly  those  con- 
ditions in  which  there  seems  to  be  a  loss  of  the  various  types 
of  speech  images  (aphasia)  or  a  loss  of  the  motor  memories 
of  the  limb  movements  for  a  definite  act  or  purpose  (motor 
apraxia) .  According  to  recent  researches,  the  left  hemisphere 
seems  to  preponderate,  in  certain  requested  or  spontaneous 
movements  of  the  limbs  in  the  same  manner  that  it  prepon- 
derates in  speech.  For  instance  in  many  lesions  of  the  left 
hemisphere  in  which  the  right  arm  and  leg  are  paralyzed,  there 
may  result  a  motor  apraxia  of  the  non-paralyzed  left  arm,  thus 
indicating  the  existence  of  a  special  action  of  the  motor  centres 
of  the  left  side  of  the  brain.  It  seems  likely  that  these  various 
complex  phenomena  are  really  disorders  of  associative  memory, 
either  for  identification  or  motility.  There  are  not  only  dif- 
rerent  types  of  these  disturbances  but  also  different  varieties 
of  the  same  type,  from  the  simplest  to  the  most  complex. 

It  is  the  purpose  of  this  paper  to  review  the  recent  literature 
on  apraxia,  to  attempt  to  determine  what  light  these  studies 
throw  upon  a  complicated  psychic  disturbance  which  seems 
to  have  a  fairly  definite  cerebral  localization  and  finally  to 
study  two  cases  of  apraxia  which  have  come  under  personal 
observation.  The  harmonizing  of  certain  anatomical  data 
with  mental  disturbances  is  of  the  greatest  psychological  im- 
portance, and  nowhere  can  this  be  better  done  than  in  the 
problem  of  apraxia. 

Apraxia  was  a  term  formerly  applied  to  the  intellectual  non- 
recognition  of  objects,  but  the  more  recent  investigations  have 
shown  that  the  term  had  best  be  limited  to  certain  essential 
disorders  of  voluntary  acts  and  movements.  The  chief  dis- 
turbance in  motor  apraxia  is  an  inability  to  make  movements 
for  the  purpose  demanded  by  the  will,  although  the  subject 
may  understand  commands  and  the  use  of  objects;  memory 
and  attention  may  be  normal  and  the  limbs  may  be  free  from 

Journal — 5 


66  CORIAT 

paralysis,  ataxia  or  tremor.  Liepmann's  case  of  unilateral 
apraxia  which  was  studied  clinically  and  anatomically  in  a 
most  thorough  manner,  has  formed  the  basis  of  the  modern 
conceptions  of  the  condition.  In  this  case  there  was  success- 
ful correlation  of  the  clinical  symptom-complex  with  the 
pathological  findings.  Later  Liepmann  extended  his  studies 
to  comprise  all  the  motor  disturbances  of  brain  disease.^ 

Previous  to  the  work  of  Liepmann  the  ideas  concerning  the 
nature  of  apraxia  were  in  a  very  unsatisfactory  condition. 
It  was  looked  upon  as  a  form  of  a  disorder  of  identification 
related  to  mind  blindness.  Hughlings  Jackson's  ideas  con- 
cerning imperception  or  Allen  Starr's  description  of  the  loss 
of  object  memories,  are  instances  of  the  older  interpretations. 
Monakow  had  also  observed  that  certain  aphasics  showed 
either  an  inability  to  execute  certain  movements  on  command 
or  misused  familiar  objects.  Under  the  name  of  asymboly 
there  also  was  described  a  loss  of  images  of  palpation,  of  kin- 
etic movements  and  of  the  use  of  objects.  The  term  asymboly 
has  also  been  applied  to  an  imperfect  grasp  of  the  nature  and 
use  of  common  objects,  such  as  occurs  in  confusional  or  deli- 
rious states.  In  a  review  of  the  question  of  tactile  aphasia,^ 
I  pointed  out  that  the  term  can  also  be  used  to  designate  not 
only  a  failure  to  know  the  shapes  of  objects  and  their  cardinal 
qualities,   but  also  the  ultimate  recognition  of  the  objects 

1  The  following  is  a  bibliography  of  Liepmann's  principal  writings  on 
apraxia. 

A.  Das  Krankheitsbild  der  Apraxie  (Motorischen  Asymbolie)  auf  Grand 
eines  Falles  von  einseitiger  Apraxie — Monat.  f.  Psychiatric  u.  Neu- 
rologic—Bd.  VIII. 

B.  Der  wcitcre  Krankheitsverlauf  bei  dem  einseitigen  Apraktischen  und 
der  Gehimbefund  auf  Grund  von  Serienschnitten — Ibid. — Bd.  XVII 
and  XIX. 

C.  Ueber  Storungcn  des  Handclns  bei  Gehim-Klranken — 1905. 

D.  Drei  Aufsatze   aus   dem  Apraxiegebiet — 1908. 

(This  monograph  is  a  collection  of  three  previously  published  articles 
on  apraxia — Kleine  Hilfs-Mittel  bei  ber  Untersuchung  von  Gehirn-Krank- 
en — (1905).  Ueber  die  Function  des  Balkens  beim  Handeln  und  die 
Beziehungen  von  Aphasie  und  Apraxie  zur  Intelligenz.  (1907)  Die 
linke  Hemisphere  und  das  Handeln  (1905). 

B.  The  section  Die  Krankheiten  des  Gehirns  in  Lehrbuch  der  Nerven- 
krankheiten  (Herausgegeben  von  Hans  Curschmann — 1909)  is  by 
Liepmann  and  contains  a  summary  of  his  latest  views  on  apraxia. 

F.  Bin  Fall  von  Hnksseitiger  Agraphie  und  Apraxie  bei  rechtsseitiger 
Lahmung  (Liepmann  and  Maas) — Jour,  f .  Psychologic  u.  Neurologic — 
Bd.  X,   1908. 

G.  Ein  neuer  Fall  von  motorischer  Aphasie  mit  Anatomischen  Befund 
(Liepmann  and  Quensel) — Monat.  f.  Psychiatric  u.  Neurol.  Sept., 
1909. 

2  The  Question  of  Tactile  Aphasia — ^Journal  Abnormal  Psychology — 
Vol.  I,  No.  6,  1907. 


THS   PSYCHOPATHOIyOGY   OF   APRAXIA  67 

themselves.  In  its  broadest  sense,  therefore,  basing  it  at  least 
upon  the  available  data  of  our  clinical  analyses,  we  may  say 
that  apraxia  in  general  is  motor  perplexity  plus  a  disorder  of 
identification.  Apraxia  may  be  divided  into  the  motor  and 
ideational  forms.  In  motor  apraxia  the  limbs  do  not  obey  the 
psychical  wish :  there  is  pure  motor  perplexity.  The  motor 
memories  for  movements  of  the  limbs  may  be  preserved  but 
these  memories  are  distorted,  isolated  or  insufficiently  con- 
nected with  other  portions  of  the  cortex.  In  motor  apraxia 
there  is  also  a  defect  in  the  use  of  objects,  although  the  objects 
may  be  perfectly  recognized.  The  subject  merely  fumbles 
with  objects;  he  is  unable  to  translate  a  subjective  purpose 
into  an  objective  action.  In  ideational  apraxia  or  agnosia 
the  subject  misuses  objects  because  there  is  a  disturbance  of 
identification.  For  instance,  he  may  think  a  comb  is  a  cigar 
and  so  put  it  in  his  mouth  as  if  smoking  it.  The  term  apraxia 
should  therefore  be  limited  to  certain  motor  disorders,  and 
it  is  best  to  refer  to  the  ideational  disturbance  as  agnosia. 

Before  the  case  of  unilateral  apraxia  came  under  Liepmann's 
observation,  the  patient  was  believed  to  be  suffering  from 
aphasia  and  post-apoplectic  dementia.  The  principal  physi- 
cal symptoms  in  this  case  were  left  facial  paralysis,  unequal 
pupils  and  weakness  of  the  left  leg,  but  no  real  paralysis  of  any 
of  the  limbs.  There  was  pure  motor  aphasia  and  some  alexia, 
but  no  word  deafness,  mind  blindness,  hemianopsia  or  uni- 
lateral psychic  blindness.  There  was  a  marked  disorder  of 
the  stereognostic  sense  and  slight  hypoesthesia  of  the  left 
hand.  Orientation,  memory  and  attention  were  normal. 
The  movements  of  the  right  arm  were  poorly  executed,  ill- 
directed  and  fumbling.  With  the  left  leg  and  arm,  however, 
everything  was  correctly  done.  It  was  demonstrated,  after 
careful  study,  that  a  typical  right-sided  motor  apraxia  was 
present.  The  analysis  of  this  peculiar  psychic  condition  pre- 
sented many  difficulties,  but  it  was  at  last  successfully  accom- 
plished. With  the  right  hand  responses  to  simple  orders, 
such  as  touching  the  nose  or  buttoning  the  coat,  and  the 
imitation  of  movements  were  incorrectly  done  and  with  much 
fumbling.  All  commands,  however,  were  correctly  and  prompt- 
ly executed  with  the  left  hand.  The  patient  blundered  at 
every  attempt  to  use  objects  with  the  right  hand.  For 
instance  when  a  comb  was  placed  in  his  right  hand  he  would 
put  it  behind  his  ear  like  a  penholder.  Writing  was  defective 
with  the  right  hand;  the  left  hand  produced  mirror  writing. 
For  further  clinical  details  the  original  monograph  should 
be  consulted. 

The  interpretation  of  the  symptom  complex  in  this  case  is 
a  striking  example  of  what  may  be  accomplished  by  careful 


68  CORIAT 

clinical  observation.  Word  blindness  and  word  deafness  were 
both  absent,  as  all  orders,  movements  and  likewise  the  imita- 
tion of  movements,  were  correctly  performed  with  the  left 
hand.  The  question  may  be  raised  that  because  the  patient 
identified  and  correctly  used  objects  with  the  left  hand,  and 
not  with  the  right,  there  existed  a  right  unilateral  psychic 
blindness.  This  objection  had  no  basis  in  fact,  because  ob- 
jects placed  in  the  right  visual  field  were  promptly  identified. 
Because  of  the  above  condition  Liepmann  believed  that  the 
apraxia  was  not  dependent  on  defective  recognition  of  objects. 
In  attempting  an  explanation  of  the  condition  he  stated  that 
the  centripetal  stimuli  from  the  limbs  on  the  right  were  per- 
ceived in  the  left  sensory-motor  area  of  the  brain  (the  anterior 
and  post-central  convolutions  and  probably  a  portion  of  the 
parietal  lobe),  but  on  arriving  there  the  impulses  were  blocked 
and  therefore  not  transmitted  to  other  cerebral  centres.  The 
left  sensory  motor  area  was  therefore  cut  off  from  all  communi- 
cation with  the  rest  of  the  cortex.  The  patient  had  lost  the 
kinetic  memories  of  movements  of  the  right  side  because  the 
left  or  leading  hemisphere  was  isolated.  He  perceived  the 
position,  movements  and  tactile  sensations  of  his  limbs  on 
the  right,  but  was  incapable  of  synthesizing  these  elements. 
The  localizing  diagnosis  of  the  condition  based  on  the  clinical 
symptoms,  showed  how  carefully  the  case  was  observed  and 
analyzed,  particularly  if  this  be  compared  with  the  later 
anatomical  findings.  Because  of  the  absence  of  word  deafness, 
paralysis,  sensory  disturbances,  hemianopsia,  or  psychic 
blindness,  the  corresponding  brain  centres  must  have  been 
intact.  The  motor  aphasia  indicated  a  lesion  of  the  third 
left  frontal  convolution  and  probably  of  the  insula.  The 
motor  area  and  the  gyrus  angularis  could  not  have  been 
involved,  because  there  was  no  paralysis  and  no  symptoms 
pointing  to  the  central  optic  tracts.  The  supra  marginal 
gyrus  and  superior  portions  of  the  parietal  lobe  were  probably 
destroyed.  The  corpus  callosum  was  probably  also  involved 
in  the  process,  because  of  the  interruption  of  communication 
with  the  right  hemisphere. 

The  patient  died  two  years  later  from  an  apoplectiform 
attack.  The  anatomical  findings  corresponded  in  a  re- 
markable manner  with  the  earlier  localizing  diagnosis.  The 
autopsy  showed  in  the  left  hemisphere  two  foci  of  softening 
in  the  third  left  frontal  convolution  and  a  subcortical  cyst 
in  the  inferior  portion  of  the  ascending  parietal  convolution. 
In  the  right  hemisphere  there  was  a  destruction  of  a  majority 
of  fibres  for  the  face  and  limbs  on  the  left  side,  and  foci  of 
softening  in  the  supra-marginal  and  angular  gyri.  The  corpus 
callosum   had   entirely   disappeared,    with   the  exception   of 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOLOGY   OF  APRAXIA  69 

the  splenium.  The  serial  sections  of  the  brain  showed  these 
lesions  with  great  clearness.  The  degeneration  of  the  corpus 
callosum  and  of  the  tapetum,  the  softening  and  degeneration 
of  the  right  internal  capsule,  the  cyst  of  the  insula  and  the 
shrunken  inner  nucleus  of  the  right  thalamus,  were  well 
marked.  This  degeneration  of  the  corpus  callosum  is  an 
important  point,  for  Liepmann  has  shown  that  the  left  hemis- 
phere is  influenced  by  the  motor  region  of  the  right  cortex 
through  the  fibres  of  corpus  callosum,  and  when  these  fibres 
are  destroyed,   the  left  hemisphere  becomes  isolated. 

It  was  not  long  before  lyiepmann's  work  was  confirmed  by 
other  investigators.  The  fundamental  difference  between 
apraxia  and  aphasia  was  recognized  by  Oppenheim,  and  later 
Pick  reported  an  arterio-sclerotic  and  senile  case  in  which 
apraxic  symptoms  were  episodic.  In  a  case  reported  by  Liep- 
mann  and  Maas,  there  was  a  right-sided  paralysis  with  a 
left-sided  agraphia  and  apraxia.  The  agraphia  may  be  re- 
garded as  merely  one  of  the  manifestations  of  the  apraxia. 
The  right  hemisphere  was  intact.  In  the  left  hemisphere, 
however,  there  was  an  area  of  softening  involving  the  whole 
of  the  left  half  of  the  corpus  callosum.  In  the  serial  sections 
of  the  brain  the  softening  could  be  traced  along  the  whole 
left  side  of  the  corpus  callosum  from  the  knee  through  the 
body  to  the  splenium.  In  interpreting  their  case  the  authors 
stated  that  the  left-sided  apraxia  was  due  either  to  the  separa- 
tion of  the  left  hand  from  the  memory  centres  of  the  left 
hemisphere,  or  perhaps  the  direct  pathway  for  impulses  to 
the  sensory-motor  area  of  the  right  brain  had  been  destroyed. 
In  "Strohmayer's  case,i  in  which  aphasic  and  ataxic  symptoms 
were  absent,  and  the  muscular  and  palpation  senses  intact, 
the  patient  recognized  and  named  objects  correctly,  but  mis- 
used them.  Anatomically  there  was  found  a  lesion  of  the 
left  inferior  parietal  lobe,  the  supra-marginal  gyrus,  the  for- 
ceps major  and  the  superior  longitudinal  bundle.  The  gyrus 
angularis  was  not  involved.  Abraham^  observed  apraxic 
phenomena  in  two  general  paralytics  and  in  a  later  contri- 
bution he  reported  a  case  of  unilateral  apraxia  which  on 
autopsy  showed  a  lesion  of  the  superior  parietal  lobe  on  the 
left.  In  Marcuse's  case  the  apraxic  symptoms  were  due  to 
a  general  senile  brain  atrophy. 3 

^^B^  ^Strohmayer:  Ueber  subcorticale  Alexie  mit  Agraphie  und  Apraxie, 
|^K)eut.  Zeit.  f.  Nervenheilkunde,  Bd.  XXIV,  1903. 

^^K^^K.  Abraham:  Ueber  einige  seltene  Zustandsbilder  bei  Progressiver 
^•aralyse — Allg.  Zeit.  f.  Psychiatrie,  Bd.  LXI.  1904. 

^^H  Ibid.:  Beitrage  Zur  Kenntnis  der  motorischen  Apraxie  auf  Grund 
P^pnes  Falles  von  einseitiger  Apraxie — Centralbl.  f.  Nervenheilk.  u.  Psy- 
I    -  chiatrie.  Mar,  1-15,  1907. 

I  ^Marcuse:     Apraktische  Symptome  bei  einem  Fall  von  Senile  Demenz. 

Centralbl.  f.  Nervenheilk.  u.  Psychiatrie,  Dec.,  1904. 


70  CORIAT 

Here  the  defects  of  the  voluntary  acts  were  caused  by  a 
continuous  amnesia.  The  patient  would  probably  forget  the 
course  of  a  movement  after  it  was  once  started,  in  the  same 
way  that  the  tactile  asymboly  reported  by  Bourdon  and  Dide, 
was  due  to  a  kind  of  a  continuous  amnesia  for  tactile  impres- 
sions. ^  However,  very  extensive  amnesias  may  be  free  from 
any  form  of  apraxia,  as  in  the  Lowell  case  of  amnesia,  a 
proof  that  these  particular  disorders  of  memory  play  little 
or  no  part  in  the  mechanism  of  apraxia.  2  Pick  insists  strongly 
on  the  psychic  element  in  all  cases  of  apraxia. ^ 

D'HoUander^  has  reported  two  cases  of  apraxia.  The  first 
of  these  occurred  in  a  case  of  focal  general  paralysis  and  was 
bilateral.  Anatomically  nothing  was  found  which  could  ex- 
plain the  condition  other  than  the  significant  point  that  the 
left  hemisphere  of  the  brain  was  smaller  than  the  right.  In 
the  second  case,  one  of  alcoholic  dementia,  there  gradually 
developed  a  slight  paralysis  of  the  right  arm  and  leg  with  a 
left-sided  apraxia,  thus  showing  the  supremacy  of  the  left 
hemisphere  in  the  execution  of  voluntary  movements.  For 
localizing  diagnosis  the  author  suggCvSted  a  lesion  on  the 
left  side  of  the  brain  extending  to  the  central  semiovale,  and 
involving  the  callosal  fibres  that  go  from  the  left  to  the  right 
hemisphere. 

Goldstein^  has  reported  a  case  in  which  after  the  disap- 
pearance of  a  left-sided  paralysis  there  appeared  a  motor- 
apraxia  limited  to  the  same  side.  For  localizing  diagnosis 
he  suggested  a  lesion  in  the  subcortex  of  the  right  central 
convolution,  damaging  its  connections  with  the  frontal  lobe 
and  involving  the  fibres  of  the  corpus  callosum.  A  year 
later,  an  anatomical  examination  disclosed,  among  other 
things,  a  complete  destruction  of  the  corpus  callosum  through- 
out its  whole  extent.® 

In  Rhein's^  case  the  right  hand  was  apraxic;  apraxic  phe- 
nomena were  present  in  chewing  and  walking  while  the  left 
hand  was  capable  of  only  elementary  reflex  acts.     The  pos- 

^B.  Bourdon  and  M.  Dide:  L'Annee  Psychologique,  1904.  (See  my 
abstract  in  the  American  Journal  of  Psychology,  April,  1905,  pp.  252-254.) 

^Isador  H.  Coriat:  The  Lowell  case  of  Amnesia,  Journal  Abnormal 
Psychology,  Vol.  II,  No.  3,  1907. 

^A.  Pick:  Studien  ueber  Motorische  Apraxie,    1905. 

^F.  D'Hollander:  Bulletin  de  la  Soci6t6  Medicine  Mentale  de  Belgique, 
1907-8  (an  excellent  summary  of  all  the  literature,  with  a  report  of  two 
personal  observations). 

^K.  Goldstein:  Zur  Lehre  von  der  motorischen  Apraxie,  Journal  f. 
Psychologic  u.  Neurologic,  Bd.  XI.     H.  4-5-6-. 

^Der  makroskopische  Hirnbefund  in  meinem  Falle  von  linksseitiger 
motorischen  Apraxie,  Neurol.  Centralblatt.,  ySept.  i,  1909. 

' /,  H.  Rhein:  A  case  of  apraxia  with  autopsy.  Journal  of  Nervous  and 
Mental  Disease,  Vol.  35,  Oct.,  1908. 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOIvOGY   OF  APRAXIA  71' 

terior  portion  of  the  corpus  callosum  was  found  degenerated 
at  autopsy. 

In  Vleuten's^  case,  there  was  a  sarcoma  in  the  left  hemis- 
phere, which  by  invasion  and  pressure  destroyed  the  cingu- 
lum,  the  whole  of  the  left  half  of  the  corpus  callosum  and  part 
of  the  right  genu.  The  right  hand  and  arm  was  tremulous, 
while  the  left  hand  and  arm  showed  apraxia.  Here  the  left-sided 
apraxia  was  produced  by  a  lesion  which  destroyed  the  callosal 
fibres.  Bychowski^  has  reported  a  case  in  which  the  apraxia 
was  found  to  be  due  to  a  cyst  in  the  left  hemisphere  which 
destroyed  and  displaced  a  portion  of  the  left  side  of  the  corpus 
callosum.  In  Hartmann's^  three  cases  of  apraxia,  one  was 
due  to  a  tumor  in  the  left  frontal  region,  and  the  second  to  a 
tumor  involvement  of  the  corpus  callosum.  In  a  case  re- 
cently reported  by  Tooth^  there  was  an  inconstant  motor- 
apraxia  of  the  left  hand.  At  autopsy  there  was  found  a 
tumor  occupying  a  portion  of  the  right  frontal  lobe,  involving 
the  anterior  half  of  the  corpus  callosum. 

In  discussing  the  psycho  motor  disturbances  of  various 
mental  diseases  Kleist  has  shown  how  apraxic  phenomena 
may  appear  in  the  hyperkinetic  and  akinetic  motility  psy- 
choses. He  thinks  that  these  disturbances  are  probably  due 
to  psychic  factors  and  that  they  may  have  a  definite  cerebral 
localization,  particularly  in  the  parietal  lobe.^  This  is  of 
interest  if  we  remember  that  in  some  cases  of  unilateral 
motor  apraxia,  the  parietal  lobe  was  found  involved  as  well 
as  the  corpus  callosum.  For  instance  in  one  case  of  an  akinetic 
motility  psychosis  which  came  under  personal  observation, 
it  was  noted  that  the  subject  had  lost  all  knowledge  of  the 
use  of  simple  objects.  Stransky^  has  shown  how  apraxic 
phenomena  may  appear  in  dementia  praecox.  In  these  cases 
he  interprets  it  as  due  to  a  loss  of  unity  between  the  under- 
standing and  the  will. 

Apraxia  may  also  occur  as  a  disorder  of  consciousness  in 
delirium  and  post-epileptic  states  and  under  both  these  con- 
ditions without  any  definite  focal  lesion.     Here  the  apraxia 

^C.  F.  V.  Vleuten:  Linksseitige  motorische  Apraxie,  Kin  Beitrag  zur 
Physiologic  des  Balkens,  AUg.  Zeit.  f.  Psychiatric,  1907. 

2Z.  Bychowski:  Bcitragc  zur  Nosographie  der  Apraxie — Monat.  f. 
Psychiatric  u.  Neurologic.  Bd.  XXV,  1909. 

^E.  Hartmann:  Bcitragc  zur  Apraxidchrc,  Monat.  f.  Psychiatric  u. 
Neurologic.  Bd.  XXI,  1907. 

W.  H.  Tooth:  (Abstract  in  Review  Neurology  and  Psychiatry,  July, 
1909,  pp.  475-476.) 

'^K.  Kleist:  Untcrsuchungen  zur  Kenntnis  der  psychomotorischen 
Bewegungsstorungen  bei  Geistcskranken,  1908. 

^E.  Stransky:  Zur  Auffassung  gewisser  Symptomeder  Dementia  Praecox, 
Neurol.  Centralbl.,  Dec,  1904. 


72  CORIAT 

is  ideational,  in  the  sense  of  a  disorder  of  indentification.  In 
these  cases  the  phenomena  tend  to  disappear  as  the  mental 
state  improves.  In  my  study  of  a  delirious  state  associated 
with  vestibular  disturbances,  apraxic  phenomena  were  present.  ^ 

Motor  apraxia  has  been  found  to  occur  in  aphasia.  The 
disorders  of  movement  which  one  frequently  finds  in  aphasics 
are  very  likely  not  due  to  any  intellectual  defect  as  claimed 
by  Marie,  but  to  a  disorder  independent  of  aphasia,  namely 
apraxia.  Cases  of  dementia  very  rarely  show  symptoms  of 
apraxia.  It  cannot  be  said  that  apraxia  is  due  to  any  in- 
tellectual disorder  because  in  disturbances  of  motility  where 
the  apraxia  is  limited  to  one  side  of  the  body,  the  other  side 
of  the  body  will  be  found  to  be  absolutely  normal.  This 
shows  that  intellectual  defects  may  be  practically  ruled  out 
in  motor  apraxia,  at  least  in  the  unilateral  types,  unless  it 
is  absurdly  assumed  that  only  one  side  of  the  brain  is  demented. 
In  one  of  my  cases  of  sensory  aphasia  the  patient  was  bright 
and  alert  and  yet  he  ridiculously  insisted  on  eating  an  egg, 
shell  and  all.  Here  we  have  an  example  of  apraxia  occurring 
in  an  aphasic  subject  without  mental  defect.  Ideational 
apraxia  (agnosia),  however,  may  occur  in  certain  abnormal 
mental  states,  such  as  in  delirious  conditions  or  in  multiple 
brain  lesions. 

There  are  many  striking  points  of  similarity  between  motor 
aphasia  and  motor  apraxia.  The  motor  speech  mechanism 
is  really  a  form  of  movement  without  objects.  The  centre 
for  motor  speech  is  located  in  the  left  hemishpere  and  it  has 
also  been  shown  how  the  kinetic  memories  for  co-ordinated 
movements  likewise  preponderate  in  the  left  hemisphere,  at 
least  in  right-handed  subjects.  In  complicated  movements 
which  through  habit  and  evolution,  have  become  bilateral, 
such  as  the  lip-tongue-larynx  movements  in  speech,  there  is 
usually  a  loss  of  these  movements  in  a  lesion  of  the  motor 
speech  area.  In  the  limb  movements  which  as  a  rule  are  not 
bilateral,  but  in  which  right  and  left  are  independent  and  in 
marked  contrast,  there  results  a  unilateral  apraxia  when  a 
lesion  on  one  side  of  the  brain  is  favorably  situated. 

How  then  are  we  to  explain  these  complex  phenomena  and 
what  light  can  be  thrown  upon  them  by  brain  anatomy  and 
physiology?  Certainly  the  subject  of  apraxia  opens  up  one 
of  the  most  inviting  and  at  the  same  time  one  of  the  most 
diflScult  fields  in  psychopathology.  At  first  it  will  be  well 
to  attempt  to  analyze  apraxia  on  the  basis  of  the  data  fur- 
nished by  those  cases  where  it  was  possible  to  make  an  anatomi- 
cal examination  of  the  brain. 

iThe  Cerebellar- Vestibular  Syndrome,  American  Journal  of  Insanity, 
Vol.  LXIII,  No.  3,  Jan.,  1907. 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OP  APRAXIA  73 

The  point  of  significance  in  the  majority  of  apraxic  cases 
was  the  involvement  of  some  portion  of  the  corpus  callosum. 
The  corpus  callosum  must  then  be  possessed  of  a  definite 
function,  as  its  involvement  seems  to  have  been  as  invariably 
present  in  motor  apraxia  as  a  lesion  of  Broca's  convolution 
in  motor  aphasia  or  of  the  central  optic  tracts  or  the  cuneus  in 
hemianopsia.  What  then  is  the  function  of  the  corpus  callo- 
sum and  how  are  we  to  harmonize  the  motor  and  psychic 
disturbances  with  the  anatomical  findings? 

The  fibres  of  the  corpus  callosum  connect  the  two  opposite 
sides  of  the  brain.  In  fact  in  experimental  lesions  of  the 
thumb  centre  in  monkeys,  the  degenerated  fibres  could  be 
traced  directly  through  the  corpus  callosum  to  a  similar  area 
on  the  hemisphere  of  the  opposite  side.  The  knee  of  the 
corpus  callosum  sends  its  fibres  to  the  fore  brain  as  the  for- 
ceps anterior.  The  fibres  of  the  splenium  go  to  the  hind 
brain  (occiptal  region)  and  to  the  temporal  lobes  as  the  for- 
ceps posterior  and  make  up  the  greater  part  of  the  tapetum. 
The  body  of  the  corpus  callosum  connects  the  two  hemis- 
pheres in  the  mid  position.  Both  the  left  and  the  right  hand 
centres,  corresponding  respectively  to  the  movements  of  the 
right  and  left  hands,  are  connected  by  means  of  the  fibres  of 
the  corpus  callosum. 

By  reason  of  its  wide  connections,  the  corpus  callosum 
plays  an  important  part  in  the  execution  and  association  of 
voluntary  movements.  In  tumors  of  the  corpus  callosum, 
disorders  of  movements  are  frequently  seen,  such  as  apraxia, 
tremor  and  ataxia.  In  a  case  of  tumor  of  the  splenium  of 
the  corpus  callosum  which  came  under  personal  observation, 
there  was  a  paralysis  of  the  right  arm  and  of  the  right  side 
of  the  face  and  a  continual  coarse  tremor  of  the  left  arm. 
A  lesion  of  the  corpus  callosum  alone  causes  a  left-sided 
motor  apraxia  without  paralysis  or  apraxia  on  the  right. 
A  lesion  of  the  left  hand  centre  causes  paralysis  on  the  right 
side  and  apraxia  on  the  left.  It  seems  that  certain  left-sided 
lesions  produce  a  left-sided  apraxia  because  the  control  of  the 
right  hemisphere  over  the  innervation  of  the  left  arm  by  means 
of  the  corpus  callosum  has  been  cut  off.  The  left  hemis- 
phere thus  becomes  isolated  and  leaderless. 

The  following  diagram  will  indicate  the  various  brain 
lesions  which  may  produce  motor  apraxia. 

(See  figure  I.) 

A  lesion  at  I  (the  left  brain  centre  for  the  right  arm)  will 
produce  a  paralysis  of  the  right  arm  and  an  apraxia  of  the 
left  arm  because  this  centre  is  either  isolated  or  is  deprived 
of  the  guidance  of  the  right  hemisphere.  A  lesion  at  II 
(in   the  subcortex  of  the  left   Rolandic   area),  injuring  the 


74 


CORIAT 


projection  and  callosal  fibres  to  the  right  hemisphere,  will 
also  produce  a  paralysis  of  the  right  arm  and  an  apraxia  of 
the  left  for  the  same  reason  as  indicated  under  lesion  I.  A 
lesion  at  III  (the  left  internal  capsule)  will  cause  a  right- 
sided  paralysis,  without  any  apraxia  on  the  left,  because  the 
corpus  callosum  is  not  injured.  A  lesion  at  IV  (in  the  corpus 
callosum)  will  cause  a  left-sided  apraxia.  A  lesion  at  V 
(in  the  left  centrum  ovale,  catching  only  callosal  fibres)  will 
likewise  cause  a  left-sided  apraxia.     In  both  these  conditions, 


ie.H;> 


Fig.  I 

A  diagrammatic  horizontal  section  of  the  brain,  to  illustrate  the  ana- 
tomical basis  of  motor  apraxia. 

L.  H.     Left  brain  centre  for  right  hand. 
R.  H.     Right  brain  centre  for  left  hand. 
The  anterior  and  posterior  and  the  lateral  course  of  the  fibres  of  the 
corpus  callosum  are  shown  diagrammatically. 

the  apraxia  is  due  either  to  a  loss  of  the  guiding  influence  of 
the  right-hand  centre  over  the  left  hand  or  to  an  isolation  of 
the  hand  centre  from  the  rest  of  the  left  hemisphere.  A  lesion 
at  VI  may  cause  a  right-sided  apraxia  from  an  interruption  of 
the  callosal  fibres  passing  to  the  left  side  of  the  brain.  (Liep- 
mann  's  first  case.)  A  lesion  at  VII  (Broca's  convolution)  would 


THK   PSYCHOPATHOI.OGY   OI?   APRAXIA  75 

produce  motor  aphasia,  and  if  the  lesion  be  of  sufficient  size 
and  extent  to  catch  the  radiations  of  the  genu  of  the  corpus 
callosum  (or  forceps  anterior),  there  will  be  likewise  caused 
a  left-sided  motor  apraxia.  That  this  latter  combination  is 
not  impossible,  is  shown  by  the  case  recently  published  by 
Liepmann  and  Quensel  and  also  by  the  second  of  my  reported 
cases. 

We  must  admit  that  the  psychical  condition  of  apraxic  sub- 
jects presents  great  difficulties  of  analysis,  even  more  so  than 
the  analysis  of  disturbances  of  the  language  mechanism  in  the 
various  types  of  aphasia.  Probably  with  increasing  knowl- 
edge of  apraxia  some  of  these  difficulties  may  be  overcome. 
Motor  apraxia  in  its  strictest  sense  is  rarely  bilateral  as  can 
be  easily  seen  from  the  reported  observations.  It  is  in  idea- 
tional apraxia  or  agnosia  that  the  bilateral  nature  of  the  dis- 
turbance may  be  detected.  In  fact,  agnosia  seldom  or  never 
occurs  as  a  pure  isolated  disorder  in  focal  brain  disease.  When 
it  does  occur  in  focal  disturbances  of  the  brain,  it  is  merely 
as  a  complication  of  the  motor  type  of  apraxia.  Agnosia  is 
most  frequently  found  in  diffuse  brain  affections  (senile 
dementia),  in  delirious  states  particularly  due  to  epilepsy  or 
alcohol  or  in  the  motility  psychoses.  Hence  agnosia  is  a  more 
general  disturbance,  while  apraxia  is  a  focal  disorder  limited 
to  certain  limbs  or  to  muscle  groups. 

In  motor  apraxia  the  limbs  do  not  obey  the  psychical  wish, 
although  that  wish  and  the  motor  image  of  the  willed  move- 
ment may  be  clearly  present  in  the  mind  of  the  subject.  It 
is  this  inability,  on  the  part  of  the  subject,  to  transfer  the 
psychical  wish  into  a  specified  innervation  of  a  limb,  which 
causes  motor  apraxia.  In  ataxia  it  is  the  elementary  condi- 
tion of  the  movements  which  is  at  fault,  while  in  apraxia 
there  exists  a  disharmony  between  the  purpose  of  the  move- 
ment and  the  idea  of  the  object  with  which  the  purpose  is 
carried  out.  In  other  words,  in  motor  apraxia  there  is  a  de- 
ficient adjustment  to  a  purpose.  In  motor  apraxia  the  co- 
ordination of  movements  is  normal,  but  there  is  a  faulty 
intrapsychic  process  and  so  the  ultimate  purpose  of  these 
movements  becomes  incorrect.  The  motor  apraxic  cannot 
translate  the  subjective  idea  of  a  movement  or  of  the  use  of  an 
object  into  its  objective  reaction.  Motor  apraxia  therefore 
may  originate  from  either  an  insufficiency  of  the  directing 
idea,  from  derailment  or  irradiation  of  the  directing  idea  upon 
the  neighboring  ideas,  from  the  omission  of  portions  of  the 
motor  act  and  the  predominance  of  the  last  portion  of  the 
act  or  from  the  substitution  of  the  directing  idea  by  another 
idea. 

All  normal  voluntary  activities  seem  to  be  due  to  two 


76  CORIAT 

mechanisms — the  representation  in  the  sensory  sphere  of  the 
successive  series  of  partial  acts  which  make  up  the  entire  act 
(the  kinetic  formula  for  movements)  and  the  faculty  of  chang- 
ing this  sensory  representation  into  external  movements  (the 
ability  of  exteriorization).  The  kinetic  formulae  for  move- 
ments are  really  the  memories  of  successive  movements  and  can 
be  compared  to  certain  chain  or  sequence  reflexes,  a  point  upon 
which  I  had  previously  insisted  in  my  studies  on  amnesia.  In 
motor  apraxia,  this  kinetic  formula  is  defective.  Therefore  it 
acts  in  an  abnormal  manner  upon  the  innervation  of  the  specific 
action,  according  to  which  of  the  kinetic  elements  is  disturbed. 
Motor  apraxia  consists,  therefore,  in  a  rupture  of  the  physio- 
logical connections  between  the*  innervation  of  a  specified 
limb  and  the  ideas  concerned  in  the  carrying  out  of  a  specified 
purpose.  It  is  really  a  motor  dissociation,  in  which  special 
kinaesthetic  memories  lie  outside  of  the  field  of  general  motor 
innervation.  This  isolation  of  the  kinsesthetic  memories  is 
probably  due  to  an  isolation  of  a  certain  portion  of  the  left 
hemisphere  in  which  these  motor  memories  are  stored  up,  an 
isolation  resulting  in  most  cases,  from  a  rupture  in  the  con- 
duction of  the  fibres  of  the  corpus  callosum.  The  centripetal 
stimuli  reach  the  centrifugal  pathway  without  entering  the 
special  ideational  or  motor  centres  by  a  kind  of  "short  cir- 
cuit." This  is  pure  motor  apraxia;  when  in  addition  there 
exists  a  disorder  or  identification,  we  have  motor  apraxia  plus 
asymboly  or  ideational  apraxia  (agnosia).  In  all  cases  of 
motor  apraxia  the  chief  difficulty  seems  to  lie  in  the  inability 
of  the  subject  to  transfer  the  directing  ideas  or  rather  the  will- 
ing of  the  directing  ideas  to  the  motor  sphere  because  they 
are  partially  cut  off,  isolated  or  derailed. 

The  behavior  of  apraxic  patients  is  a  subject  of  much 
interest.  Movements  of  substitution  which  are  so  common 
in  motor  apraxia,  may  be  compared  to  paraphasia.  Occasion- 
ally the  subject  may  begin  a  movement  and  only  partly  com- 
plete it.  Here  the  reaction  is  referred  to  as  curtailed.  Some- 
times a  movement  may  bear  no  resemblance  whatsoever 
either  to  the  usual  acts  of  everyday  life  or  to  a  specially 
skilled  reaction.  Unde  these  conditions  we  describe  it  as 
a  formless  or  an  amphorous  reaction.  On  still  other  occa- 
sions the  first  part  of  the  movement  may  be  immediately 
followed  by  the  last  part  without  any  intervening  motions. 
This  is  called  a  short  circuited  reaction  ("  Kurzschluss  Reak- 
tion").  Perseveration  is  the  monotonous  automatic  repe- 
tition of  an  act.  Sometimes  indeed  the  subject  becomes  petri- 
fied, as  it  were,  in  the  attitude  of  executing  a  simple  or  a  com- 
plex act  either  requested  or  spontaneous.  To  the  first  form 
is  applied  the  term  clonic  perseveration;  the  latter  is  known 


THK   PSYCHOPATHOLOGY   OI^   APRAXIA  77 

as  tonic  perseveration.  Clonic  perseveration  strongly  re- 
sembles the  recurrent  utterances  of  sensory  aphasia,  while 
tonic  perseveration  is  analogous  to  the  mutism  of  a  severe 
motor  aphasia. 

Scheme  of  disturbances  of  kinetic  formula  for  movement. 
A  — >  B  — )  C  — )  D  =  Normal  Motor  Reaction. 

A )  D  :=  Short  Circuited  Reaction. 

A  — )  B  =  Curtailed  Reaction. 

A  — )  A  — )  A — )       =  Clonic  Perseveration. 
A  =  Tonic  Perseveration. 

Fig.  II. 

A  graphic  analysis  will  make  this  clearer  (see  figure  II). 
Let  A.  B.  C.  D.  represent  the  kinetic  formula  for  a  certain 
movement,  each  letter  indicating  one  element  of  the  action. 
The  normal  movement  could  occur  only  when  the  individual 
elements  acted  serially.  Any  change  in  the  position  of  the 
elements  or  any  omission,  would  result  in  disordered  activity 
or  apraxia.  For  instance  if  the  action  took  place  as  A-D. 
with  the  intervening  elements  omitted,  we  would  have  a  short 
circuited  reaction.  If  the  movement  was  A — B.  with  the 
other  two  elements  omitted,  then  the  action  ceases  soon  after 
it  has  been  started;  in  other  words,  it  has  become  curtailed. 
If  the  action  should  be  A.  A.  A,  the  first  portion  of  the  action 
will  then  tend  to  be  indefinitely  repeated.  A  clonic  persever- 
ation could  result.  If  the  action  was  A.  alone,  and  no  further 
elements  of  the  kinetic  formula  followed,  the  subject  then 
would  become  stuck  at  the  first  of  the  series.  Here  we  have 
a  tonic  perseveration.  Many  apraxic  subjects  show  a  marked 
lack  of  spontaneity,  a  condition  which  strongly  resembles,  if 
it  is  not  identical  with  tonic  perseveration.  As  a  rule  most 
requested  or  spontaneous  movements  in  apraxic  subjects  are 
ill  directed  and  fumbling,  show  a  deficient  adjustment  to  a 
purpose  and  yet  they  are  not  ataxic. 

Von  Monakow^  has  brought  forth  an  ingenious  theory  to 
explain  certain  focal  disturbances  of  the  brain,  particularly 
aphasia  and  apraxia.  According  to  this  theory,  mere  anatomi- 
cal interruption  of  the  continuity  of  fibres  in  the  central  ner- 
vous system  will  not  fully  explain  the  various  form  of  focal 
disorders.  Therefore  there  must  be  a  special  form  of  action 
at  a  distance  from  which  may  arise  temporary  or  permanent 
suspensions  of  function.  To  this  action  at  a  distance,  von 
Monakow  applies  the  term  "  diaschisis. "  This  diaschisis  re- 
sembles certain  physiological  irradiations,  in  which  a  reflex 
effect  can  spread  in  various  directions  from  a  focus  of  reflex 
discharge. 

1  Von  Monakow:    Neurol.  Centrablatt,  Nov.  i6,  1906. 


78  CORIAT 

The  study  and  analysis  of  two  cases  of  motor  apraxia  which 
came  under  personal  observation  will  now  be  taken  up.  The 
difficulty  of  correlating  the  motor  reactions  with  the  mental 
state  of  the  subject  will  excuse  the  lengthy  details  of  the 
reports.  In  fact,  in  apraxia  as  well  as  in  aphasia,  a  rigid  ex- 
amination scheme  has  but  a  limited  value,  as  not  only  do  the 
types  and  the  conditions  vary,  but  the  same  type  may  present 
different  aspects  in  different  subjects.  Our  present  knowledge 
of  apraxia  is  due  entirely  to  minute  clinical  investigations,  to 
which,  when  possible,  the  anatomical  findings  have  been  added. 

Case  I.  When  the  patient  K.,  who  was  twenty-four  years  of 
age,  first  came  under  observation  he  had  been  suffering  from 
severe  headaches  for  two  months.  On  several  occasions  the 
headaches  became  so  intense  that  vomiting  followed.  Up  to 
this  period  the  patient  had  been  perfectly  healthy.  An  exam- 
ination disclosed  the  following  condition.  Only  the  essential 
neurological  details  are  given.  Tongue  tremulous  and  pro- 
truded to  the  right,  tremor  of  outstretched  hands,  the  right 
knee  jerk  and  right  Achilles  jerk  were  brisk;  while  the  left 
knee  jerk  and  the  left  Achilles  jerk  were  absent.  There  was 
a  subjective  sense  of  weakness  and  numbness  on  the  left  side 
of  the  body.  There  was  no  ankle  clonus  or  Babinski  reflex. 
The  pupils  were  equal  and  reacted  promptly  to  light  and 
accommodation;  there  was  no  paralysis  of  the  ocular  muscles 
and  no  nystagmus,  but  an  ophthalmoscopic  examination  dis- 
closed a  blurring  of  the  optic  disc  without  swelling  (beginning 
optic  neuritis). 

About  three  weeks  later  a  sudden  but  transitory  paralysis 
of  the  left  arm  and  leg  took  place.  Within  a  few  days  this 
improved  until  only  a  slight  weakness  could  be  detected. 
The  physical  condition  has  since  remained  the  same  with  the 
exception  of  a  blunted  sensation  in  the  left  hand,  associated 
with  a  weakness  of  grasp.  Word  deafness  and  motor  aphasia 
were  absent  during  the  entire  course  of  the  disease.  The 
patient  was  right-handed. 

There  was  no  hemianopsia  and  no  unilateral  mind  blind- 
ness, because  objects  placed  in  each  visual  fields  were  promptly 
recognized.  An  analysis  showed  a  typical  motor  apraxia  of 
the  left  arm,  while  the  right  arm  was  entirely  free  from  any 
motility  disturbance.  This  unilateral  apraxia  was  not  de- 
pendent on  any  defective  recognition  of  objects,  because  the 
patient  could  correctly  select  objects  with  either  hand,  but 
did  not  know  how  to  correctly  use  them  with  the  left  hand 
after  they  had  been  selected.  He  was  always  oriented,  and 
there  was  no  disorder  of  memory  either  for  recent  or  remote 
events.  Unilateral  agraphia  was  absent;  he  was  able  to  write 
spontaneously  and  to  dictation  fairly  well  with  either  hand. 


THB  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  APRAXIA  79 

There  was  no  apraxia  of  the  left  leg  or  of  the  muscles  of  facial 
expression  for  either  side.  This  appearance  of  a  motor  apraxia 
in  a  limb  from  which  a  previous  transitory  paralysis  had  dis- 
appeared, resembles  the  observation  of  Goldstein,  to  which 
we  referred  above. 

Examination  for  Apraxia,  Motility  and 
Sensation  of  the  Left  Arm 

The  general  movements  of  the  left  arm  were  weak  and 
fumbling.  The  dynamometer  for  the  right  hand  registered 
seventy,  while  for  the  left  hand  it  was  twenty.  The  left  arm 
was  not  paralyzed  and  all  the  movements  could  be  fairly  well 
performed  but  they  were  ill-directed  and  awkward.  The  abnor- 
mal motor  reactions  of  the  left  arm  on  analysis  seemed  to  be 
entirely  due  to  a  motor  apraxia  and  not  to  any  motor  weakness 
or  ataxia.  With  the  eyes  closed  the  movements  of  the  left 
arm  were  decidedly  more  fumbling  and  ill- directed  than  when 
the  eyes  were  open.  In  spite  of  the  fumbling  and  slight  weak- 
ness and  spasticity  of  the  left  arm,  he  could  spontaneously 
lift  it  above  his  head,  flex,  extend,  pronate,  supinate,  fairly 
well  extend  and  flex  the  fingers  and  give  a  fair  grasp,  although 
there  was  a  disinclination  on  the  part  of  the  subject  to  spon- 
taneously use  this  left  arm.  This  tendency  to  akinesis  was 
probably  due  partly  to  the  patient's  appreciation  of  his  local- 
ized motor  apraxia  and  partly  to  a  state  of  tonic  perseveration. 
An  examination  of  the  sensation  of  the  left  arm,  forearm  and 
hand  showed  anaesthesia  and  hypoalgesia. 

The  testing  of  the  muscular  sense  of  position  showed  that 
when  the  right  forearm  was  placed  at  a  right  angle  to  the 
right  arm,  after  some  fumbling  he  was  able  to  correctly  imi- 
tate the  position  with  the  left  arm.  When  the  right  arm 
was  placed  vertically  above  the  head  he  promptly  placed  the 
left  arm  in  the  same  position.  With  the  eyes  closed,  when 
the  right  arm  was  passively  elevated  above  the  head  and  the 
patient  was  requested  to  imitate  the  position  with  the  left 
arm,  he  merely  placed  the  latter  horizontally  on  the  same 
level  with  the  shoulder.  Right  arm  passively  extended  hori- 
zontally forward  with  the  palm  upwards;  he  imitated  it  by 
placing  the  left  arm  in  the  same  position  but  with  the  palm 
downwards.  Right  index  finger  placed  at  right  angles;  with 
the  left  hand  he  merely  made  a  fist. 

Reaction  to  Requests 

R.  Hand  L.  Hand 
Buttoning  coat                                   Correct  Grasps  edge  of  coat 
Touching  tip  of  nose  with  right  fore- 
finger                                                        "  Puts  palm  to  mouth 
Touching  right  ear  with  right  fore 
finger                                                         "  Places  finger  back  of  head 


8o                                                        CORIAT 

R.  Hand. 

L.  Hand. 

Movement  of  sewing                           Correct 

Fumbles 

Movement  of  cutting  with  scissors        " 

Fumbles 

Snapping  fingers 

Makes  fist 

Turning  hand-organ 

Makes  fist 

Movement  of  turning  key  in  lock 

Makes  fist 

Movement  of  shaving 

Places  hand  behind  ear 

Movement  of  combing  hair                     " 

Rubs  head  with  palm  of  hand 

Movement  of  use  of  cork-screw              " 

Fimibles 

Military  Salute                                           " 

Fumbles 

In  the  three  successive  reactions  with  the  left  hand  in  which 
the  patient  made  a  fist  in  response  to  different  requests,  we 
have  an  example  of  clonic  perseveration  or  the  frequent  mo- 
notonous repetition  of  an  act. 

Reaction  to  the  Use  of  Objects 

R.  Hand  L.  Hand 

Comb  Correct    Rubs  hair  with  smooth  back  of  comb 

Tooth  brush  "         Correct  but  fumbles 

Hair  brush  "         Holds  back  of  brush  several  inches  above  head 

without  any  brushing  motion 
Key  "        Cutting  movements  as  though  it  were  a  knife 

Match  "         Correct  but  fumbles 

Spoon  "         Cutting  and  stabbing  movements 

Cigarette  "         Grasps  it  clumsily,  puts  it  to  chin  and  then  puts 

wrong  end  in  mouth 

In  the  reaction  to  requests  and  to  the  use  of  objects  the 
left-sided  apraxia  became  more  marked  when  the  patient's 
eyes  were  closed.  The  same  fact  was  noted  in  testing  for  the 
sense  of  position  in  the  apraxic  limb.  For  instance,  in  one 
series  of  tests  a  key,  a  match  and  a  drinking  glass  were  used 
correctly  with  the  right  hand  and  decidedly  awkwardly  and 
fumblingly  with  the  left.  When  attempts  were  made  to  use 
these  same  objects  with  the  eyes  closed,  the  left  hand  seemed 
to  become  petrified,  as  it  were,  after  an  abortive  start.  In 
other  words  we  seem  to  have  here  the  phenomenon  of  tonic 
perseveration.  On  other  occasions,  even  with  the  eyes  open, 
he  would  start  to  use  an  object  correctly  with  the  left  hand, 
and  then  would  hopelessly  fumble,  either  going  into  a  condi- 
tion of  tonic  perseveration  or  would  finish  up  with  a  substi- 
tuted movement,  as  if  the  object  or  the  request  had  been 
changed.  Sometimes,  too,  in  the  use  of  objects  with  the  left 
hand,  the  movements  would  bear  no  relation  to  the  nature  of 
the  object;  they  would  become  decidedly  amorphous.  The 
stereognostic  sense  was  entirely  lost  on  the  left  hand  and  to  a 
certain  extent,  at  least  for  larger  and  coarser  objects,  on  the 
sole  of  the  left  foot.  The  increase  of  apraxia  when  the  eyes 
were  closed,  was  not  due  to  any  astereognosis,  because  the 
patient  was  always  told  the  nature  of  the  object.     At  no  time 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOI.OGY   OF  APRAXIA  8 1 

was  there  any  loss  of  the  knowledge  of  the  use  of  objects. 
He  was  always  able  to  describe  their  uses  and  from  a  number 
of  objects  spread  before  him  he  was  able,  on  request,  to  pick 
out  the  correct  one  with  either  hand.  The  patient  always 
knew  when  he  used  an  object  incorrectly  with  the  left  hand. 
The  apraxia  seemed  therefore  not  dependent  on  any  defective 
recognition  of  objects;  in  other  words,  it  was  not  ideational 
but  was  almost  entirely  a  motor  disorder.  His  knowledge  of 
the  use  of  objects  was  always  correct,  even  when  he  was  not 
permitted  to  touch  the  objects. 

In  order  to  further  show  that  there  was  no  disorder  of  identi- 
fication and  that  the  inability  to  correctly  use  objects  with  the 
left  hand  was  purely  a  motor  disturbance,  the  following  ob- 
servations are  of  interest.  When  the  patient  was  shown  a 
match  and  requested  to  describe  its  use,  he  replied  "To  make 
fire."  When  asked  to  show  the  use  of  a  match  he  did  so 
correctly  with  the  right  hand.  With  the  left  hand,  however, 
he  clumsily  grasped  the  entire  match  in  his  fist,  leaving  only 
a  small  portion  of  the  head  exposed  and  then  made  stabbing 
instead  of  scratching  motions  with  it.  When  a  cigarette  was 
given  to  him,  with  the  right  hand  he  correctly  placed  it  in 
his  mouth.  With  the  left  hand  he  grasped  the  cigarette  so 
clumsily  in  his  fist  that  it  was  almost  broken  in  half,  then  he 
placed  it  to  his  chin,  then  after  some  hesitation  brought  his 
fist  to  his  mouth,  still  holding  the  cigarette  tightly  and  with 
the  mouth  end  completely  covered  up  with  his  hand.  When 
a  match-box  was  placed  in  the  left  hand  he  promptly  opened 
the  cover,  took  out  a  match  and  showed  correctly  how  to  use 
it.  When  the  match-box  was  placed  in  the  right  hand, 
attempts  to  repeat  the  performance  with  the  left  hand  brought 
out  a  very  typical  motor  apraxia.  After  considerable  fum- 
bling and  perplexity  he  opened  the  cover,  took  out  each  match 
separately  and  allowed  each  to  fall  back  into  the  box  without 
any  attempt  at  scratching  them.  When  a  pipe  was  placed 
in  the  right  hand  he  promptly  put  the  stem  in  his  mouth. 
With  the  left  hand,  however,  he  took  it  by  the  bowl  and  plac- 
ing the  bowl  to  his  chest  said  **  I  know  it  is  a  pipe,  but  I  can't 
use  it  with  this  hand."  It  appears  that  these  details  point 
out  the  significant  fact  that  the  inability  to  use  objects  with 
the  left  hand  was  due  not  to  any  lack  of  knowledge  or  identi- 
fication of  the  object,  but  to  a  derailing  of  a  motor  wish  into 
a  false  motor  reaction. 

The  imitation  of  movements  also  brought  out  a  left-sided 
motor  apraxia  as  follows: 

R.  Hand  L.  Hand 

Saluting  Correct  Fumbles 

Shaving  "  Merely  places  hand  on  cheek 

Shining  shoes        "  Grabs  ankle 

Journal — 6 


82  CORIAT 

When  requested  to  perform  these  same  actions  with  the 
left  arm  and  the  eyes  closed,  fumbling  and  lack  of  direction 
in  movements  became  greatly  increased.  It  seems  from  these 
observations  that  visual  impressions  could  partially  correct 
the  left-sided  motor  apraxia.  When  the  visual  stimuli  were 
cut  off  by  having  the  patient  close  his  eyes,  he  went  completely 
off  the  rails.  The  movements  of  the  left  hand  without  objects, 
were  as  apraxic  as  when  objects  were  used. 

In  this  case  we  are  probably  dealing  with  a  brain  tumor  for 
with  the  following  localizing  diagnosis  may  be  suggested.  The 
tumor  is  probably  in  the  right  motor  sub-cortex  or  centrum 
ovale,  involving  a  portion  of  the  fibres  of  the  pyramidal  tract 
and  of  the  parietal  region  and  probably  a  large  portion  of  the 
fibres  of  the  corpus  callosum.  A  lesion  here  from  its  position 
could  cause  the  motor  disturbance  of  the  left  side  of  the  body, 
that  is,  a  transitory  paralysis  and  weakness  of  the  left  arm  and 
to  a  slighter  extent  of  the  left  leg,  aiid  also  a  typical  motor 
apraxia  of  the  left  arm.  This  latter  is  due  to  a  loss  of  the 
guiding  and  directing  influence  of  the  right  arm  centre  upon 
the  left  arm  through  a  destruction  of  the  fibres  of  the  corpus 
callosum. 

In  the  second  observation  we  have  the  combination  of  an 
aphasic  speech  disturbance  and  a  lef t-vSided  motor  apraxia, 
both  occurring  in  a  right-handed  subject.  Such  a  combi- 
nation is  of  importance,  for  it  demonstrates  that  a  left-sided 
brain  lesion  may  be  so  situated  as  to  cause  an  aphasia  and  a 
left-sided  apraxia. 

Case  II.  The  patient  L.,  57  years  of  age,  a  right-handed  man, 
began  to  suffer  with  a  severe  headache  localized  on  the  left  side 
of  the  head,  combined  with  dizziness  and  a  weakness  of  the  right 
arm.  Shortly  afterwards  he  suddenly  began  to  repeat  *  *  oilcloth, 
oilcloth"  spontaneously  and  in  reply  to  all  questions.  This 
recurrent  utterance  lasted  about  an  hour,  after  which  speech 
became  normal,  although  a  little  dysarthric.  Somewhat  later 
that  same  day  he  again  suddenly  began  to  talk  in  a  jargon. 
In  this  jargon  German  sounds  (his  native  language)  pre- 
dominated, while  all  knowledge  of  English  (an  acquired  lan- 
guage) was  completely  lost.  This  condition  lasted  for  four 
days  and  during  this  time  the  left-sided  headache,  dizziness, 
weakness  and  numbness  of  the  right  arm  and  leg  continued 
although  no  actual  paralysis  was  ever  noticed.  All  requests 
and  commands  were  understood.  He  knew  the  hours  for 
meals  and  his  various  wants  of  his  everyday  life.  At  the  end 
of  four  days  he  suddenly  regained  his  normal  speech  in  both 
languages.  Since  then  when  fatigued  or  frequently  in  the 
late  afternoon  he  will  forget  the  names  of  objects  in  English 
and  will  call  them  only  by  their  German  names.     This  is  a 


TH^   PSYCHOPATHOI.OGY  OF   APRAXIA  83 

feature  of  interest  which  I  had  previously  pointed  out  in  the 
Lowell  case  of  amnesia.  It  is  indicated  that  the  acquired 
memories  in  certain  forms  of  amnesia  were  the  first  to  dis- 
appear, while  the  deeper  and  more  closely  knit  associations 
were  preserved. 

The  neurological  examination  may  be  briefly  summarized 
as  follows:  Marked  arterio-sclerosis  with  a  high  blood  press- 
ure, speech  occasionally  dysarthric,  no  hemianopsia,  grip  of 
right  hand  decidedly  weaker  than  that  of  left,  no  paralysis, 
pupils  slightly  unequal,  the  right  reacting  slightly  to  light, 
the  left  rigid,  the  right  knee  jerk  diminished  as  compared  to 
the  left,  no  Babinski  reflex,  no  facial  paresis  or  deviation  of 
the  tongue.  The  gait  was  weak  but  not  hemiplegic  while  the 
station  was  normal.  There  were  no  sensory  disturbances  in 
any  of  the  extremities.  All  objects  were  quickly  and  correctly 
recognized  and  named  and  their  uses  accurately  described. 
The  amnesic  aphasia  was  episodic  and  usually  appeared  only 
after  the  fatigue  of  a  long  examination  or  in  the  late  afternoon. 
The  patient  was  clearly  oriented  and  showed  no  signs  of  in- 
tellectual defect. 

An  examination  of  the  motility  of  the  left  hand  showed 
that  while  it  was  slightly  weaker  than  the  right,  it  was  free 
from  paralysis,  ataxia  or  tremor.  All  voluntary  movements 
were  present,  yet  it  was  possible  to  demonstrate  a  typical 
left-sided  motor  apraxia.  The  false  motor  reactions  of  the 
left  hand  were  due  to  a  motor  apraxia  and  not  to  any  inability 
to  understand  requests,  because  there  was  no  intellectual  de- 
fect and  no  word  deafness.  The  facial  muscles  were  free  from 
apraxia.  The  inability  to  name  objects,  although  he  could 
indicate  their  uses  with  the  right  hand,  took  place  only  during 
the  temporary  anmesic  aphasia  due  to  fatigue.  Repetition 
of  printed  letters  was  normal.  Copying  was  correctly  done 
with  each  hand.  All  objects  were  correctly  recognized  in 
each  visual  field  and  therefore  there  was  no  unilateral  mind- 
blindness.  Astreognosis  was  absent.  The  apraxia  may  be 
tabulated  as  follows: 

Reaction  to  Requests 

R.  Hand  L.  Hand 

Making  a  fist  Correct    Correct 

Spreading  the  fingers  "       Shows  palm  of  hand 

Using  cork-screw  "       Fumbles,  first  part  of  action  correct,  then 

makes  cutting  instead  of  pulling  move- 
ments 

Saluting  "       Correct 

Smoking  a  cigar  "       Saluting  movements 

The  attempt  to  show  the  use  of  a  cork-screw  with  the  left 
hand  is  an  example  of  a  curtailed  reaction,  while  the  persist- 


84  CORIAT 

ence  of  saluting  movements  to  different  requests  indicates  a 
clonic  perseveration. 

Reaction  to  Use  of  Objects 

R.  Hand  L.  Hand 

Scissors  Correct   Fumbles  but  correct 

Key  "       Turns  it  upside  down  and  holds  it  there 

Match  "       Holds  it  like  a  pencil  and  makes  writing 

motions 
Pencil  "       Correct 

Shoehorn  "       Rubs  it  against  leg 

A  number  of  other  objects  were  correctly  used  in  the  left 
hand  but  in  a  fumbling  and  awkward  manner.  The  imitation 
of  movements  was  also  somewhat  apraxic  on  the  left.  The 
imitations  of  movements  of  the  right  arm  with  the  left  arm 
led  to  some  interesting  reactions.  When  the  patient  was 
requested  to  make  certain  movements  with  the  left  arm  alone, 
an  apraxia  always  resulted,  but  this  apraxia  practically  dis- 
appeared if  the  patient  was  allowed  to  imitate  the  movements 
of  the  right  arm  with  his  left.  The  apraxia  to  imaginary 
movements  or  in  the  use  of  objects  was  increased  when  the 
eyes  were  closed ;  or  if  apraxia  was  absent  when  the  eyes  were 
open,  it  tended  to  appear  when  the  same  tests  were  made  with 
the  eyes  closed.  These  observations,  demonstrated  as  in  the 
previous  case,  that  visual  impressions  are  able  to  partially 
correct  a  motor  apraxia  in  the  same  manner  that  a  subject  is 
less  ataxic  when  the  eyes  are  open. 

For  an  anatomical  localizing  diagnosis  we  would  suggest  a 
probable  area  of  softening  at  the  angle  of  the  third  left  frontal 
convolution  and  the  Sylvian  Fissure,  extending  below  to  the 
white  matter  of  the  corona  radiata  and  to  the  radiations  of 
the  genu  of  the  corpus  callosum  (forceps  anterior).  A  lesion 
here  would  cause  a  motor  aphasia  and  also  a  motor  apraxia  of 
the  left  arm,  because  the  guiding  influence  of  the  right  side 
of  the  brain  upon  the  left  side  of  the  body  would  be  cut 
off.  The  motor  centre  would  thus  become  isolated.  Here 
again  we  see  the  importance  of  the  integrity  of  the  cal- 
losal  fibres  from  preventing  any  motility  disturbance.  The 
weakness  and  numbness  of  the  right  arm  is  probably  due  to 
either  a  backward  extension  of  the  lesion  or  to  a  pathologi- 
cal irradiation  involving  the  anterior  central  convolution  on 
the  left. 

Any  analysis  of  these  two  cases  demonstrated  that  the  chief 
difficulty  lay  in  an  inability  to  transfer  a  subjective  choice 
process  into  an  objective  reaction.  The  cause  of  this  dis- 
order could  be  easily  traced  to  a  definitely  localized  lesion  in 
the  brain,  which  disturbed  the  kinetic  memories  for  move- 


TH^  PSYCHOPATHOI^OGY  OF  APRAXIA 


85 


ments  and  produced  new  and  abnormal  combinations.  The 
disordered  movements  and  misuse  of  objects  could  be  partially 
corrected  through  visual  impressions,  probably  because  these 
impressions  may  have  stimulated  certain  non-affected  por- 
tions of  the  brain,  to  function  in  a  normal  manner. 


NOTE    ON    SOME    OF    THE     PHYSICAL    FACTORS 

AFFECTING  REACTION  TIME,  TOGETHER 

WITH  A  DESCRIPTION     OF  A  NEW 

REACTION     KEY 


By  Frank  Angell, 


The  history  of  reaction-time  investigations  discloses  a  curi- 
ous combination  of  painstaking  accuracy  in  regard  to  the 
functioning  of  the  time-measuring  apparatus  together  with  a 
more  or  less  happy-go-lucky  arrangement  at  the  other  end  of 
the  experiment. 

Thus  the  chronoscope  and  its  standardizing  instruments 
have  been  the  subjects  of  minute  and  laborious  investigation, 
whilst  the  reagent,  after  assuming  his  'convenient  and  com- 
fortable position'  has  usually  been  left  to  his  own  devices  in 
carrying  out  the  reaction  prescriptions.  Whether  however  the 
reagent  obeyed  the  directions,  whether,  for  example,  wrist 
and  forearm  movements  did  not  enter  into  play  where  finger 
movements  were  prescribed,  are  matters  which  the  experi- 
menter has  rarely  been  in  a  position  to  determine.  Indeed  it 
has  only  been  of  comparatively  recent  date  that  investigation 
has  been  directed  to  the  initial  pressure,  the  "antagonistic 
motion"  of  the  break  reaction. 

Among  other  neglected  factors  in  these  experiments  has  been 
the  effect  of  the  tension  of  the  reaction  key  spring.  This  has 
usually  been  set  at  a  '  comfortable  and  convenient'  resistance, 
and  variations  within  these  'comfortable  and  convenient'  limits 
have  been  regarded  as  negligible.  This  may  be  the  case,  but 
it  is  a  minor  question  quite  as  well  worth  investigating  as  a 
variation  of  2  or  3  sigma  in  the  readings  of  the  chronoscope. 

The  question  was  taken  up  as  a  "minor  study"  by  two 
students  in  the  advanced  course  in  psychology — Miss  Lank- 
tree  and  Miss  Morrison.  The  lever  arm  of  a  Morse  key  was  set 
at  tensions  of  10,  20,  50,  100,  and  200  grams  respectively,  and 
for  each  tension  10  series  of  10  reactions  each  were  taken. 
The  first  of  these  series  does  not  enter  into  the  averages  given 
in  Table  I  as  the  fall-hammer  showed  irregularities  in  the 
chronoscope  at  the  time  this  series  was  taken.  Each  day  the 
5  series  were  run  through  twice — the  second  time  reversing 
the  order  of  the  first,  the  order  of  the  several  series  changing 
from  day  to  day.  The  15  volt  current  was  furnished  by  a 
mercury  rectifier  and  maintained  at  the   same  strength  for 


FACTORS  AFFECTING  REACTION  TIME 


87 


each  day,  usually  at  0.47  amp.  The  mean  variation  of 
the  hammer  readings  ran  from  one  to  three  sigma — not  very 
accurate  but  sufficiently  so  for  the  purposes  of  the  experiment/ 
The  stimulus  came  from  a  sound-hammer  placed  behind  the 
reagent,  who  occupied  a  room  adjacent  to  that  of  the  experi- 
menter. The  reagents  noted  the  condition  of  attention  as 
good,  moderate  or  strained  (the  last  referring  to  the  accom- 
panying muscular  tension)  and  in  addition  marked  the  reac- 
tion as  sensory  or  muscular.  Almost  all  of  the  reactions  were 
characterized  as  sensory; — seemingly  from  strain  sensations 
in  the  ear  adapting  it  to  the  direction  of  the  stimulus.  L.  had 
already  been  reagent  in  another  investigation  for  more  than 
a  semester  and  both  had  been  experimenting  on  reaction  time 
in  the  second  year's  course  of  laboratory  work. 

Table  I  gives  the  results  of  the  experimentation  for  the 
several  tensions  of  the  reaction  key.  It  shows  noticeable 
differences  for  all  tensions  in  case  of  L.  and  a  noticeable  differ- 
ence between  the  tension  of  200  grams  and  the  remainder  of 
the  series  for  M. 

Table  I 

Reaction  times  for  different  tensions  of  spring  of  telegraph  key. 
Reagents  L.  and  M. 

L  S  M  ' 


Tension 

Grams 

r.  t. 

m.   V. 

r.  t. 

m.  V. 

:                10 

129.8 

8.0 

136.9 

8:6 

20 

127.3 

7-5 

136.I 

6.6 

50 

122.4 

4.9 

135.2 

9-1 

100 

120.8 

7-7 

135. 1 

10.9 

200 

I16.O 

4.7 

127.0 

7-9 

The  introspections  do  not  indicate  any  marked  change  in 

le  attitude  of  the  reagents  for  the  stronger  pressures  of  the 

:ey.     Once  M.  notes  a  strain  in  the  hand  with  200  grams,  but 

{the  reaction  itself  is  noted  as  sensory,  i.  e.,  the  sensory  content 

|of  consciousness  at  the  moment  of  reaction  was  strain  sen- 

itions  in  the  head  or  ears  directed  toward  the  source  of  sound. 

*he  increase  in  tension,  therefore,  would  not  seem  to  result 

for  the  reagent  in  a  direction  of  attention  to  the  hand  and  a 

change  to  the  muscular  form  of  reaction.     L.  asserted  that  there 


'It  is,  perhaps,  worth  while  to  note  that  the  chronoscope  "neuerer 
Construction"  used  in  this  investigation,  with  only  4  years  of  use  is  a 
luch  less  steady  instrument  than  our  old  chronoscope;  also  "neuerer 
Construction"  which  has  weathered  20  years  of  general  laboratory  service. 


88  ANGELL 

was  no  noticeable  difference  to  her  in  the  set  of  the  hand  for 
the  lo,  20  and  50  grams  of  pressure,  but  that  the  transition 
from  any  of  these  to  100  grams  and  from  100  to  200  was  marked. 
Nevertheless  L's  reactions  show  a  steady  decrease  in  quickness 
from  10  to  200  grams.  The  shortening  of  the  reaction  time 
with  increase  in  tension  of  the  key  spring  is,  therefore,  probably 
physical  and  due  to  an  acceleration  of  the  motion  of  the  reacting 
finger  imparted  by  the  recoil  of  the  spring.  The  tension  at  which 
the  acceleration  would  be  noticeable  would  depend  on  the 
manner  of  reaction:  ten  grams  pressure  might  accelerate  a 
finger  reaction  but  not  one  from  the  wrist  or  elbow.  As  a 
result  of  long  practice,  L.  had  become  skilled  in  the  finger  re- 
action. This  is  possibly  the  reason  why,  for  this  reagent, 
the  effects  of  each  tension  were  noticeable.  A  measurement 
of  the  rapidity  of  the  free  recoil  of  the  spring  for  10  grams  of 
tension  showed  that  a  separation  of  the  contacts  of  3^  of  a 
millimeter — more  than  sufficient  to  break  the  current — took 
place  in  0.0005  sec.  which  of  course  is  considerable  faster  than 
the  reacting  finger  can  move  at  the  beginning  of  its  course. 
This  is  to  answer  the  possible  objection  that  for  the  weaker 
tensions,  the  reacting  finger  moved  up  faster  than  the  key-bar. 

Part  2.     Experiments  with  Trigger  Reaction  Key. 

As  is  the  case  with  much  of  its  apparatus,  experimental 
psychology  found  the  ordinary  telegraph  key  already  in  use 
and  adopted  it  for  its  own  purposes.  The  key  is  very  con- 
venient in  manipulation  and  the  motion  it  calls  for  is  'natu- 
ral.' Serious  objections  to  it  are  the  antagonistic  motion 
with  the  break  reaction  and  variability  of  extent  of  the  reaction 
motion.  Another  easy  and  natural  motion  is  that  of  the  fin- 
ger in  pulling  a  trigger,  with  the  advantage  of  a  very  slight 
tendency,  if  any,  towards  the  opposed  reaction,  though  it 
may  well  permit  an  anticipatory  contraction.  The  experi- 
ments presently  to  be  described  were  carried  out  with  a  new 
key  of  the  trigger  type. 

The  elimination  of  the  antagonistic  reaction  would,  in  itself, 
hardly  be  a  sufficient  reason  for  adding  another  instrument  to 
the  already  long  list  of  reaction  keys.  This  trigger  key,  however, 
measures  the  force  and  extent  of  the  reaction  movement  as 
well  as  its  time.  As  is  evident  from  the  accompanying  figure, 
the  key  is  simple  in  construction.  A  cylindrical,  self -register- 
ing spring  balance  is  mounted  horizontally.  The  movable  end 
is  provided  with  a  ring  for  the  reacting  finger  and  in  front  of 
this  stands  an  adjustable  post  serving  as  a  brace  for  the  hand. 
Electrical  contact  is  made  through  the  horizontal  adjustable 
rod  R.  mounted  parallel  to  the  cylinder.  This  rod  is  con- 
nected with  the  binding-screw  S"  the  other  binding  post  S!^. 


FACTORS  AFFECTING  REACTION  TIME  89 


I 


Fig.  I. 

being  connected  with  the  index  of  the  balance.  In  reacting,  the 
reagent  closes  the  hand  around  the  post  P. — adjusted  to  the 
proper  distance  from  the  'trigger',  and  inserts  the  forefinger  in 
the  ring  as  far  as  the  first  joint.  When  the  stimulus  comes  the 
reagent  pulls  the  'trigger', which  breaks  the  contact  between  the 
rod  R.  and  the  scale  index.  The  pull  carries  along  the  register- 
ing ring  C.  which  is  left  in  place  at  the  forward  end  of  the  pull 
thus  showing  the  force  and  extent  of  the  reaction  movement. 
If  it  is  desired  to  change  the  initial  tension  of  the  spring,  the 
rod  R.  can  be  pushed  along  the  side  of  the  scale  and  the  spring 
set  at  any  tension.  In  this  way  the  influence  of  the  initial 
tension  on  the  reaction  movement  can  be  easily  ascertained. 
Any  anticipatory  pull  for  o  grams  of  tension  is  signalized  by 
the  failure  of  the  chronoscope  hands  to  move. 

For  the  sake  of  comparison  of  the  keys,  pairs  of  series  of 
reactions  were  taken  with  each  of  10  reagents,  each  key  being 
used  in  one  series  of  a  pair.  The  number  of  reactions  in  a 
series  was  20,  and  one  series  in  each  pair  was  taken  in  halves 
with  the  other  series  sandwiched  in  between  the  halves  to 
compensate  possible  practice  effects.  As  the  object  of  this 
experiment  was  merely  to  test  the  relative  trustworthiness 
of  the  two  keys,  it  will  be  sufficient  to  make  a  general  state- 
ment of  the  results. 

Although  the  reagents  were  inexperienced  in  reacting,  the 
eaction  times  as  well  as  the  variations  differed  in  no  marked 
egree  from  those  of  experienced  reagents  with  whom  the 
processes  of  reaction  had  not  passed  over  into  the  mechanical 
stage. 

The  figures  showed  the  shorter  reaction  time  for  7  of  the  10 
reagents  with  the  telegraph  key.  If  we  were  to  'guess'  at 
the  reason  for  this  difference  we  should  say  it  might  in  part, 
be  due  to  the  upward  push  of  the  key  spring,  and  in  part  to 
the  stronger  tendency  towards  muscular  reaction  involved  in 


90  ANGELI. 

the  reacting  position  for  the  telegraph  key.  With  the  trig- 
ger key,  the  hand  and  arm  He  in  a  position  producing  less  mus- 
cular strain  than  is  the  case  with  the  Morse  instrument, 
and  no  tension  is  required  to  hold  in  place  the  moving  part 
of  the  instrument.  Accordingly  the  content  in  consciousness 
of  muscular  strain  is  usually  less  for  beginners  with  the  trigger 
form  of  key  and  the  reactions  tend  more  to  approach  the  sen- 
sory form. 

The  differences  of  proportional  mean  variation  between  the 
two  keys  were  less  marked  than  differences  of  reaction  time  and 
in  general,  so  far  as  the  data  go,  we  should  be  inclined  to 
say  that  taking  merely  the  question  of  the  time  factor  into 
account,  the  trigger  key  is  as  trustworthy  an  instrument  as 
the  old  key. 

Force  and  Extent  of  the  Reaction  Movement 

So  far  no  attention  has  been  paid  to  the  other  factors  of 
the  reaction  given  by  the  trigger  key,  i.  e.,  to  the  factors  of 
force  and  extent  of  pull.  The  object  so  far  has  been  merely  to 
compare  the  time  data  of  the  instruments,  and  with  such 
VersuchsLiere  as  beginners  in  psychology  there  is  every  in- 
centive to  keep  the  conditions  of  investigation  as  simple  as 
possible. 

The  experiment  that  follows  is  a  preliminary  survey  with 
one  reagent  of  all  the  data  given  by  the  trigger  key — the 
force  and  extent  of  the  reaction  movement  in  relation  to 
each  other  and  to  the  reaction  time.  The  reagent  for  this 
purpose  was  Miss  Shumate  who  had  done  much  reacting  both 
in  the  regular  course  of  laboratory  work  and  in  investigations. 
Before  coming  to  this  work  and  during  it,  she  had  been  using 
the  telegraph  key  for  reacting  to  light  stimuli  with  variable 
signal.  Under  these  conditions  her  reactions  were  of  the 
sensory  type.  She  had  also  taken  part  in  the  comparison 
experiment  along  with  the  unpracticed  reagents,  but  had  re- 
acted eight  periods  instead  of  one.  The  results  for  seven  of 
these  periods  (omitting  the  first  where  the  data  are  imperfect) 
were: 

Tel.  Key      Trig.  Key 

Reaction  time — median  of  7  series  257  225 

Av.  of  m.  V.  of  7  series  26  22 

A  number  of  series  was  next  taken  with  the  trigger  key  set 
at  different  tensions  from  o  grams  to  1,000  grams — the  re- 
agent noting  each  time  the  extent,  and  consequently  the 
force,  of  the  reaction  pull.  The  instructions  to  S.  were  simply 
to  mark  the  condition  of  the  tension — classing  it  as  "high," 
"medium,"  or  "low"  and  to  note  extent  of  pull.     Reactions 


FACTORS  AFFECTING   REACTION   TIME  91 

which  the  reagent  classed  as  of  "low  attention"  are  not  included 
in  results.  The  interval  between  signal  and  stimulus  was 
varied  slightly  to  prevent  reactions  from  becoming  mechan- 
ical. In  response  to  inquiry,  the  reagent  said  that  her  motions 
were  not  influenced  through  noting  their  extent  and  force; 
in  the  process  of  reaction  she  had  in  mind  chiefly  the  time 
factor  with  no  thought  of  making  the  pulls  uniform  in  extent. 

About  40  reactions  were  taken  each  period,  distributed  in  four 
series  corresponding  to  four  different  tensions  of  the  key. 
Under  these  regular  conditions,  with  but  slight  interruption 
for  introspections,  the  effects  of  practice  became  very  notice- 
able, so  that  at  the  end  of  a  month  the  reagent's  average  reac- 
tion time  had  decreased  75  to  100  sigma.  Table  II  gives  the 
figures  for  all  the  reactions  of  this  experiment.  Taking  the  April 
result,  where  practice  effects  practically  disappeared,  we 
find  with  this  key,  too,  an  increase  in  reaction  time  with  in- 
creasing tension  of  the  spring  and  along  with  this  a  tendency 
towards  a  decreasing  absolute  mean  variation.  With  the 
weaker  tensions  the  reactions  were  fairly  mechanical ;  the  reac- 
tion motion  followed  the  stimulus  without  a  conscious  will 
impulse.  With  the  higher  tensions  this  was  less  the  case, 
but  whether  with  1,000  grams,  for  example,  each  reaction 
motion  was  preceded  by  a  deliberate  impulse,  or  whether  a 
general  state,  or  *set'  of  preparation  for  stronger  impulses  pre- 
ceded the  entire  series,  we  do  not  yet  know.  In  order  to  get 
mental  conditions  that  were  as  far  as  possible  constant,  the 
introspections  were  reduced  to  a  minimum.  The  tendency 
towards  a  smaller  m.  v.  with  the  stronger  tension  indicates 
however,  that  the  latter  condition  was  the  case. 

To  what  is  the  increase  in  r.  t.  with  increased  tension  due : — 
to  the  greater  time  required  for  the  greater  impulse  or  to  the 
greater  resistance  to  the  movement  of  reaction?  The  in- 
dications from  the  table  are  that  the  latter  is  the  case.  The 
columns  headed  atS  ap^  at^  ap^  give  the  averages  of  the  three 
quickest  and  the  three  slowest  reaction-times  respectively,  to- 
gether with  the  averages  of  the  length  (and  strength)  of  pulls 
corresponding  to  these  reactions.  The  table  shows  no  agree- 
ment for  any  given  resistance  between  length  of  reaction  time 
and  strength  of  pulP;  of  the  32  series  tabulated,  the  quickest 
reactions  give  16  longer  and  14  shorter  pulls  than  the  slowest, 
while  for  2  series  within  the  limits  of  error  of  reading,  the  pulls 
are  equal.  In  one  of  these  series  (10  reactions)  the  times  ranged 
from  133  to  177  sigma,  while  the  pulls  were  all  of  1,775 
grams;   in   the  other,  the   time  range  was  from  144  to  183, 

^Curiously  enough  Ach  (Willenstaetigkeit  und  Denken,  S.  158)  assumes 
that  the  opposite  is  true:  i.  e.,  he  regards  it  as  "sicher"  that  the  quicker 
reaction  follows  the  stronger  impulse. 


92 


ANGELL 


TABI.E  II.     TriggBR-Kby 
Reaction  data  of  S  for  different  tensions  of  spring 

at^  means  average  of  }/i  of  shortest  reactions 
at^  means  average  of  3^  of  longest  reactions 
ap^  means  average  pulls  for  at^ 
ap2  means  average  pulls  for  at^. 


Grams 

No. 

av. 

av.  pull. 

tension 

react. 

Date 

r.  t. 

m.v. 

ati 

ap' 

at2 

ap2 

m.  m. 

o  grams 

II 

Apr.  20 

139 

10 

123 

608 

153 

650 

33 

o  " 

10 

"   22 

135 

18 

125 

812 

179 

787 

42 

o  " 

ID 

'"  25 

143 

II 

129 

767 

158 

742 

41 

o  " 

9 

"   27 

132 

9 

116 

800 

145 

782 

41 

o  " 

II 

"   29 

154 

24 

124 

717 

169 

733 

38 

av. 

141 

14 

39 

IOC  grams 

9 

Apr.  20 

146 

7 

133 

875 

154 

862 

35 

200  " 

II 

"   22 

139 

10 

127 

908 

155 

925 

38 

200  " 

9 

"   25 

176 

9 

135 

887 

187 

900 

36 

200  " 

10 

"   27 

145 

16 

124 

908 

169 

975 

39 

200  " 

10 

"   29 

159 

7 

149 

825 

172 

833 

33 

200  " 

II 

"   18 

149 

14 

125 

883 

167 

871 

35 

av. 

152 

10 
17 

167 

955 

207 

960 

36 

300  grams 

20 

Mch.  2 

190 

34 

300  " 

17 

"   14 

172 

9 

162 

955 

185 

860 

32 

400  grams 

20 

Mch.  16 

185 

15 

163 

970 

209 

1075 

2,2> 

400  " 

25 

"   21 

176 

14 

153 

1075 

211 

1050 

35 

500  grams 

19 

Apr.  8 

154 

26 

124 

1070 

198 

IIIO 

31 

600  grams 

10 

Apr.  II 

162 

15 

139 

1200 

184 

1225 

32 

600  " 

10 

"   18 

153 

5 

143 

1250 

160 

1242 

32 

600  " 

II 

20 

145 

13 

13.S 

1 167 

173 

1133 

29 

600 

8 

"   22 

153 

24 

128 

1275 

184 

1287 

34 

600  " 

10 

"   25 

176 

9 

162 

1208 

189 

1200 

32 

600  " 

10 

"   27 

139 

7 

129 

1283 

147 

1312 

36 

600  " 

10 

"   29 

157 

II 

129 

1175 

147 

1175 

30 

av. 

155 

12 
24 

148 

1388 

32 

800  grams 

18 

Mch.  23 

177 

215 

1360 

30 

800  " 

20 

Apr.  13 

138 

14 

116 

1370 

161 

1395 

31 

800  " 

20 

"   15 

162 

12 

144 

1435 

185 

1425 

33 

av. 

159 

17 

31 

1000  grams 

10 

Apr.  18 

159 

12 

141 

1567 

171 

1583 

30 

1000    " 

II 

20 

163 

14 

145 

1542 

188 

1525 

28 

1000    " 

10 

"   22 

176 

18 

146 

1566 

203 

1533 

29 

1000    " 

9 

"   25 

169 

8 

158 

1600 

186 

1550 

29 

1000    " 

10 

"   27 

163 

8 

149 

1600 

173 

1600 

30 

1000 

10 

"   29 

171 

9 

157 

1567 

184 

1575 

30 

av. 

167 

10 

29 

FACTORS  AFFECTING  REACTION   TIM]©  93 

with  a  uniform  pull  of  i  ,600  grams.  There  is  therefore  here  no 
proportion  between  the  reaction-time  and  strength  of  motor 
impulse  for  any  given  resistance.  In  addition,  the  m.  v. 
show  no  increase  with  increase  in  resistance ;  indeed  there  is, 
for  this  reagent,  a  slight  tendency  towards  a  decrease  of  this 
quantity.  If  the  observed  increase  in  reaction  time  with  in- 
creased tension  were  due  to  increased  time  in  the  discharge 
of  the  motor  impulse,  there  would  probably  be  an  increase  in 
the  resulting  m.  v. 

The  last  column  in  Table  II  gives  in  millimeters  the  average 
distance  pulled  for  the  several  tensions.  The  length  of  the  re- 
acting scale  for  2,000  grams  of  weight  is  105  millimeters.  Con- 
sequently the  distance  pulled  may  be  found  from  the  formula 
d=i  .0525  {l-t)  where  /  is  the  strength  of  the  pull  and  t  the  initial 
tension  at  which  the  index  was  set.  For  this  table  /  is  taken  as 
the  average  of  ap^  and  ap"^  which  is  very  close  to  the  average  pull 
for  any  tension,  and  in  some  cases  coincides  with  it.  The 
table  indicates  a  tendency  to  decrease  the  distance  pulled  with 
increase  in  initial  tension  t  the  falling  off  amounting  to  about 
one  centimeter  in  going  from  o  grams  initial  tension  to  1,000 
grams.  We  have  accordingly  with  increased  tension  of  pull 
an  increased  reaction  time  with  a  tendency  towards  smaller 
mean  variation  and  a  decrease  in  distance  pulled.  As  this 
article  is  merely  a  preliminary  survey  of  the  field  with  one 
reagent,  any  attempt  to  evaluate  the  results  would  be  pre- 
mature. It  is  hoped  that  experiments  with  additional  reagents 
supplementing  those  already  performed,  will  show  that  the 
trigger  key  is  helpful  in  the  investigation  of  reaction  processes. 


PRECISION  OF  MEASUREMENTS  APPLIED  TO 
PSYCHOMETRIC  FUNCTIONS 


By   F.   H.   S AFFORD 


In  three  closely  related  articles/  Dr.  F.  M.  Urban  has 
treated  Psychometric  Functions  by  the  aid  of  statistical 
methods.  For  convenience  these  articles  will  be  referred  to 
as  /,  //,  ///,  respectively.  The  object  of  this  paper  is  to  dis- 
cuss his  use  of  these  methods  from  the  standpoint  of  physical 
measurements  only,  and  not  to  enter  into  the  psychological 
questions  involved. 

In  considering  the  results  of  physical  measurements  it  is 
necessary  to  keep  in  view  the  precision  of  the  observations, 
the  extent  to  which  deductions  may  be  carried,  and  the 
methods  of  computation  which  will  give  the  results  without 
unnecessary  labor.  It  is  of  course  useless  to  expect  good  re- 
sults from  insufficient  data,  and  equally  useless  to  sacrifice 
good  data  by  an  incomplete  analysis. 

In  order  to  be  able  to  discuss  the  three  articles  intelligently 
it  is  desirable  to  refer  to  several  fundamental  principles  of 
computation. 

In  most  cases  the  term  "precision"  should  be  restricted  to 
fractional  precision,  i.  e.,  the  ratio  of  the  error  of  a  quantity 
to  the  entire  quantity.  When  a  result  of  a  measurement  of 
any  kind  is  stated  as  25,306,  it  is  understood  to  show  that  the 
result  lies  between  25,305.5  and  25,306.5,  or  that  the  value  is 
known  with  an  error  of  not  over  one  unit  in  the  last  digit. 
The  fractional  precision  is  this  case  is  thus,  approximately, 
one  part  in  25,000.  Had  the  original  result  been  2,530,600.  j 
the  fractional  precision  would  have  been  the  Same.  The  two 
ciphers  at  the  end  are  "insignificant"  digits,  serving  only  to 
indicate  the  position  of  the  decimal  point.  The  cipher  be- 
tween 3  and  6  is  a  significant  digit,  and  the  same  is  true  of  the 
ciphers  in  such  a  result  as  .12500.     If  the  last  two  digits  are 


^I.  The  Application  of  Statistical  Methods  to  the  Problems  of  Psy- 
chophysics.     The  Psychological  Clinic  Press,  Philadelphia,  Pa.,   1908. 

II.  Die  psychophysischen  Massmethoden  als  Grundlagen  empirischer 
Messungen,  Archiv  f.  d.  ges.  Psychologic,  Vol.  15,  Part  3  and  4,  Leipzig, 
1909. 

III.  Die  psychophysischen  Massmethoden  als  Grundlagen  empirischer 
Messungen,  Archiv  f.  d.  ges.  Psychologie,  Vol.  16,  Part  i  and  2,  Leipzig, 
1909. 


PRECISION   OI^   MEASUREMENTS  95 

written,  they  indicate,  as  before,  that  the  result  is  between 
.124995  and  .125005.  When  the  result  lies  between  .1245 
and  .1255  the  correct  form  is  .125.  But  in  .0012500  the  first 
ciphers  are  now  "insignificant,"  serving  as  before  to  locate 
the  decimal  point.  When  a  measurement  is  actually  a  count- 
ing of  individuals,  the  last  digit  is  not  subject  to  an  error  in 
the  sense  used  above.  In  general,  the  last  digit  of  a  measure- 
ment is  liable  to  an  error  of  one  half-unit  in  that  place,  and  to 
an  average  error  of  a  quarter-unit.  The  precision  of  a  measure- 
ment may  be  indicated  for  practical  purposes  by  stating  the 
number  of  significant  digits,  and  it  is  not  influenced  by  the 
position  of  the  decimal  point. 

In  the  case  of  the  four  arithmetical  processes  the  precision 
of  the  result  is  usually  the  same  as  that  of  the  least  precise 
element,  a  principle  which  may  be  deduced  as  follows.  The 
product  of  .234  and  126.5  is  29.6010;  but  if  the  given  numbers 
are  measurements,  they  should  be  considered  as  .234:k;  and 
126.5X,  where  x  indicates  unknown  digits.  In  adding  the 
several  partial  products,  each  column  containing  an  x  must 
be  rejected,  leaving  the  result  29.6.  This  result  is  not  as  im- 
pressive as  the  former,  but  it  is  the  only  one  justified  by  the 
data.  The  proof  of  the  rule  for  division  is  similar.  When 
a  child  is  taught  to  annex  ciphers  to  a  dividend  to  facilitate 
division,  he  learns  a  rule  which  has  no  place  in  computation 
of  physical  measurements;  and  a  division  which  is  carried  on 
after  all  the  digits  of  the  original  dividend  have  been  "brought 
down"  presents  a  familiar  exhibition  of  false  accuracy.  In 
addition  and  subtraction,  the  position  of  the  decimal  point 
affects  the  precision  of  the  result,  which  is  usually  the  preci- 
sion of  the  numerically  largest  element,  the  use  of  an  x  at  the 
end  of  each  measured  element  affording  a  quick  and  reliable 
means  of  testing  a  result.  When  two  elements  in  a  subtrac- 
tion are  nearly  equal,  the  result  is  often  disappointingly  in- 
accurate, so  that  an  original  precision  of  seven  digits  may  be 
reduced  even  to  one  digit.  Of  course,  logarithmic  work  is 
•subject  to  similar  criteria.  The  logarithm  of  54.32  taken  from 
a  seven-place  table  may  range  from  1.7349 198  to  1.7349997, 
so  that  1.7349  o^  I -7350  is  as  accurate  as  the  given  number 
will  permit.  If  the  given  number  were  54.32000,  indicating 
a  precision  of  seven  digits,  the  seven  place  table  would  be 
properly  chosen  for  use.  Conversely,  if  the  logarithm  of  a 
number  is  2.34127,  the  number  is  anywhere  from  219.4143  to 
219.4194,  i.  e.,  is  correct  to  five  digits  only.  Thus,  in  general, 
the  number  of  places  in  the  log.  table  should  be  that  of  the 
digits  in  the  number.  With  few  exceptions  the  precision  of 
a  result  is  not  more  than  that  of  the  data,  and  it  is  usually 
less. 


96  SAFFORD 

It  will  be  necessary  later  to  employ  the  term  average  devia- 
tion of  the  mean.  If  the  sum  of  n  quantities  is  divided  by  w,the 
result  is  the  arithmetic  mean.  The  sum  of  the  differences 
between  the  arithmetic  mean  and  the  quantities,  taken  with- 
out regard  to  sign,  and  divided  by  w,  is  the  average  deviation 
of  a  single  observed  quantity.  If  this  deviation  is  divided  by 
\/n,  the  result  is  called  the  average  deviation  of  the  mean  and 
gives  a  precision  measure  in  common  use  by  physicists.  It 
is  customary  to  compute  this  to  two  places  of  significant  figures 
and  then  to  retain  in  the  arithmetic  mean  no  digit  be3^ond 
this  second  digit,  since  more  than  these  are  useless.  The 
combined  result  is  often  written  in  the  form  35.123  ±  .012. 

The  experiments  which  were  the  basis  of  Dr.  Urban' s 
articles  are  described  in  /,  page  i,  and  in  II,  page  261.  A 
set  of  brass  cylinders  externally  identical  and  of  weights  vary- 
ing by  four  grams  from  84  to  104  gms.  was  arranged  at  equi- 
distant intervals  determined  by  numbers  from  i  to  14,  around 
the  circumference  of  a  circular  table.  Standard  weights  of 
100  gms.  were  placed  at  the  odd  numbers.  The  individual  to 
be  tested  was  requested  to  lift  each  weight  in  turn,  and  to 
give  his  judgment  as  to  the  relative  weight  of  each  cylinder  at 
an  even  number  and  the  standard  cylinders  at  the  preceding 
odd  number.  The  table  was  rotated  so  as  to  bring  the  weights 
in  succession  under  the  hand  of  the  observer,  who  stated  his 
judgments  at  the  rate  of  eleven  and  one-half  per  minute. 
Bach  experiment  consisted  of  50  comparisons  of  each  weight 
with  the  standard,  and  the  results  of  each  experiment  were 
separately  tabulated,  the  judgments  being  classified  as  heavier, 
lighter  or  equal. 

Seven  observers  were  employed,  of  whom  the  first  three 
performed  nine  experiments,  and  the  others  six.  The  "fre- 
quencies" for  each  of  the  three  types  of  judgment  were  com- 
puted by  dividing  the  total  number  of  judgments  of  each  type 
and  for  each  weight  by  the  total  number  of  judgments  in  the 
nine  or  six  experiments.  Observer  1°  gave  the  judgment 
"equal"  28  times  for  the  84  gm.  weight  and  56  times  for  the 
88  gm.  weight.  So  that  the  two  frequencies  were  28  -^450  and 
56-V-450  respectively.  This  process  gave  eventually  a  table 
of  frequencies  having  seven  entries,  one  for  each  weight.  By 
interpolation,  frequencies  were  found  corresponding  to  weights 
varying  by  single  grams  from  84  to  108,  but  only  the  seven 
original  entries  were  experimental  results.  After  the  plotting 
of  these  extended  results  for  each  observer  and  for  each  type 
of  judgment,  smooth  curves  were  drawn  through  the  twenty- 
five  points  of  each  plot.  The  curves  for  equality  judgments 
were  somewhat  like  the  ordinary  probability  curve,  while  those 


PRECISION   OF   MEASUREMENTS  97 

for  lighter  and  heavier  judgments  were  low  and  high  respec- 
tively at  the  right  ends  and  vice  versa  at  the  left  ends. 

The  equality  curve  for  observer  1°  was  treated  most  elabo- 
rately and  so  will  require  the  most  attention  in  this  paper. 
The  original  frequencies  for  observer  1°  (/,  table  85)  were: 

.0622,   .1244,   .3311,   .4422,   .4644,   .0911,  .0533. 

The  number  28  above  mentioned,  which  is  the  total  for 
nine  experiments,  is  the  sum  of  widely  varying  components, 
viz.,  4,  3,  4,  4,  2,  5,  2,  3,  I.  If  we  follow  the  procedure  pre- 
viously explained  and  compute  the  average  deviation  of  the 
mean,  these  values  give  3.11  ±  .34.  In  this  manner  the  orig- 
inal frequencies  revised  and  with  useless  digits  omitted  are: 

.0622  ±  .0067,  .124  ±  .019,  .331  ±  .045,  .442  ±  .025. 

.464  ±  .045,  .0911  ±  .0061.  .0533  ±  .0099. 

Thus  a  three  place  log.  table  is  sufficiently  accurate  for  the 
computation,  though  it  must  not  be  inferred  that  this  means 
rough  approximation ;  for,  on  the  scale  adopted  by  Dr.  Urban, 
a  change  of  a  unit  in  the  third  decimal  place  of  an  ordinate 
is  not  visible  to  the  naked  eye.  Granting  the  use  of  these 
ordinates  to  four  digits  and  no  further,  it  should  be  observed 
that  these  ordinates  and  the  corresponding  abscissae  84,  88, 
etc.,  give  seven  points  and  no  more  for  the  purpose  of  defining 
the  psychometric  curve  of  this  observer. 

At  /,  page  1 2 6, Dr.  Urban  proceeded  by  the  use  of  Lagrange's 
formula  to  obtain  the  equation  of  this  curve  in  Cartesian 
co-ordinates,  since  in  that  form  the  result  is  easily  differen- 
tiated, thus  enabling  one  to  locate  the  maximum  ordinate.  In 
this  computation  the  seven  ordinates  were  treated  as  if  exact 
to  any  desired  extent,  i.  e.y  in  the  divisions,  zeros  were  added 
to  the  dividends  giving  some  quotients  to  twenty-four  signi- 
ficant figures.  Such  precision  is  equivalent  to  stating  the 
volume  of  the  earth  with  an  error  of  not  over  one  cubic  inch. 
On  an  inserted  sheet  (/,  p.  129),  giving  only  a  portion  of  the 
details,  there  are  over  fifteen  hundred  digits,  and  but  for  two 
accidents  the  equation  of  the  psychometric  curve  would  have 
coefficients  correct  to  eighteen  digits.  One  accident  is  that 
certain  of  the  results  are  computed  to  only  eleven  digits;  the 
other  is  an  error  in  the  computation  of  a,<^  (x):  (x — 84)  mi, 
where  the  coefficient  of  X^  is  given  as  .003035422096*013889, 
when  it  should  be  .003035422092013889.  This  error  gives  the 
ordinate  of  the  point  for  which  X^  100  the  value  .4650  instead 
of  .4644  as  in  the  data.  Newton's  method  of  differences 
gives  a  formula  which  is  theoretically  the  same  as  that  by 
Lagrange,  and  requires  about  one- tenth  of  the  labor.  While 
this  is  not  in  a  form  for  easy  differentiation,  the  method  of 
approximation  will  quickly  locate  the  maximum  ordinate, 
giving  its  location  far  closer  than  the  data  will  warrant. 

Journal — 7 


98  SAFFORD 

Certain  theoretical  topics  about  this  curve  must  now  be 
treated.  In  /,  page  139,  this  statement  occurs.  "Inter- 
polation by  Lagrange's  formula  has  not  the  character  of  a 
definite  hypothesis  on  the  nature  of  the  psychometric  function 
but  it  is  rather  a  method  of  completing  a  set  of  observations. " 
Lagrange's  formula  gives  the  equation  of  a  curve  through  n 
points,  whose  degree  is  not  greater  than  n  and  the  n  points  de- 
determine  the  curve  completely.  In  fact,  for  any  set  of  n  points 
only  one  curve  exists  of  the  type  which  Lagrange's  formula  as- 
sumes. The  use  of  Lagrange's  formula  certainly  makes  a  definite 
assumption  about  the  type  of  the  psychometric  function,  which 
is  all  the  more  open  to  objection  because  all  of  the  probability 
curves,  both  symmetrical  and  asymmetrical,  are  definitely  ex- 
cluded. An  infinity  of  curves  of  the  same  general  form,  if 
desired,  but  of  higher  degree  may  be  made  to  pass  through  any  n 
points,  so  that  it  seems  utterly  useless  to  spend  energy  in  locat- 
ing within  one  one-thousandth  of  an  inch  the  maximum  point  of 
a  curve  whose  only  claim  for  consideration  is  the  fact  that  its 
equation  is  simpler  than  that  of  other  curves.  Circles  were  once 
considered  the  only  perfect  curves;  hence  it  was  argued  that 
heavenly  bodies  must  have  circular  orbits.  As  a  last  comment 
on  the  quotation  above,  if  Lagrange's  formula  enables  one  to 
complete  a  set  of  observations,  why  not  make  fewer  observa- 
tions and  use  the  formula  instead?  Thus  from  two  observa- 
tions one  could  obtain  an  indefinite  number  of  new  "observa- 
tions," but  unfortunately  all  would  lie  on  a  straight  line 
through  the  two  original  points. 

Without  detracting  from  the  very  able  mathematical  treat- 
ment of  the  theoretical  psychometric  curves,  it  is  important 
to  notice  that  the  observation  curves  in  /  and  //  show  such 
divergence  from  the  theoretical  curves  in  ///  that  deductions 
from  the  latter  are  not  applicable  to  the  former.  But  the 
former  are  not  a  necessary  conclusion  from  the  seven  points. 
From  a  mathematical  standpoint  it  is  desirable  to  have  more 
points  for  the  curves,  and  these  must  not  be  obtained  by  any 
formula  of  interpolation,  since  this  process  introduces  an 
assumption  about  the  curves,  in  fact  is  equivalent  to  defining 
the  curves  completely.  Under  the  conditions  provided  in 
these  experiments  the  deductions  may  quite  as  well  be  ob- 
tained from  the  plots  themselves,  since  the  observations  are 
not  sufficiently  precise  to  justify  such  exhaustive  mathematical 
treatment. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  DROWSINESS 
An  iNTRosp^cTivie  AND  Anai^yticai.  Study 


■        By  H.  L.  Hoi.iyiNGWORTH,  Barnard  College,  Columbia  University 


'  The  investigation  of  sleep  and  dreams  seems  to  the  writer 
to  have  neglected  to  explore  in  an  adequate  way  a  region  of 
normal  conscious  life  which  merits  more  attention.  This 
region  is  the  state  of  drowsiness,  which  usually  precedes  the 
sleep  state,  and  which  is  especially  prominent  and  long 
drawn  out  in  conditions  of  over  work  or  unduly  protracted 
waking  hours.  Much,  of  course,  is  known  of  the  dreamy 
mental  states  so  clearly  described  by  Crichton-Brown^  and 
intimately  related  to  the  aurse  which  frequently  precede 
epileptic  seizures,  and  of  the  various  disturbances  of  sensation 
and  perception  in  neuraesthenia,  psychaesthenia  and  the 
many  pronounced  types  of  alienation.^  Something  is  known 
of  the  variously  named  hypnoid,  hypnagogic  or  pre-sleep- 
ing  state  which  is  often  found  to  precede  the  hypnotic 
trance,  and  of  the  dissociations  found  in  hysteria.  The 
"dreamy  mental  states"  described  by  Crichton-Brown  in 
his  Cavendish  lecture  were  such  experiences  as  "double  con- 
sciousness— loss  of  personal  identity — a  going  back  to  child- 
hood— vivid  return  of  an  old  dream — losing  touch  with  the 
world — deprivation  of  corporeal  substance — loss  of  sense  of 
proportion, — momentary  black  despair — being  at  the  Day  of 
Judgment,"  etc.  And  they  are  asserted  to  be  "abnormal  in 
their  essence  and  morbid  in  their  tendencies." 

But  references  are  few  in  the  literature  to  the  suggestive 
and  quite  common  hallucinations  and  perceptual  complica- 
tions experienced  by  supposedly  normal  people  in  the  state  of 
drowsiness,  and  such  search  as  the  writer  has  been  able  to 
make  has  disclosed  no  careful  description  or  analysis  of  this 
state.  Prince^  has  recently  asserted  that  the  pre-sleeping  state 
has  "certain  marked  characteristics  which  distinguish  it 
from  the  alert  state  of  waking  life  and  is  worthy  of  study  in 
itself."     M.  Maury^  in  the  report  of  his  experiments  on  dream 

^Dreamy  Mental  States — The  Lancet,  July  6,  13,  1895;  Nos.  3749-50. 
^Paton:    Psychiatry,  pp.  26-127. 

^Mechanism  and  Interpretation  of  Dreams.     Jour.  Ab,  Psy.,  19 10,  p.  139. 
*Le  Sommeil  et  les  R^ves.     p.  42,  etc. 


lOO  HOIvUNGWORTH 

production  describes  the  so-called  "hypnagogic  hallucination" 
which  he  regarded  as  constituting  "the  chaos  out  of  which 
the  dream  cosmos  is  evolved,"  and  HerscheP  has  described 
"sensorial  visions"  which  occur  during  the  waking  state, 
but  these  seem  to  be  merely  the  familiar  entoptic  phenomena 
of  waking  life.  Sully2  calls  attention  to  the  presence  of  transi- 
tion states  between  sleeping  and  waking  and  to  the  compara- 
tive ease  with  which  sense  illusions  occur  in  these  states. 
These  seem  to  be  the  "hypnagogic  states"  of  Maury,  "states 
of  somnolence  or  sleepiness  in  which  external  impressions 
cease  to  act,  the  internal  attention  is  relaxed,  and  the  wierd 
imagery  of  sleep  begins  to  unfold  itself."  But  Sully's  chief 
emphasis  is  on  the  persistence  of  the  dream  hallucination 
proper  into  the  postsomnial  condition. 

Conceivably  the  state  of  drowsiness  might  throw  consider- 
able light  on  dream  formation,  the  relation  between  the  latent 
and  the  manifest  content  of  dreams,  and  the  various  ways  in 
which  external  impressions  and  central  dispositions  are  trans- 
formed and  related  in  the  serial  dream.  Drowsiness  is  the 
transition  state  between  waking  consciousness  and  dream  life, 
and  careful  observation  of  this  state  should  be  able  to  catch 
dreams  in  the  making  and  to  disclose  the  tendencies  which 
attain  their  maximal  operation  in  the  sleep  state  proper. 
Whether  or  not  it  be  true  that  the  genuine  dream  is  experi- 
enced only  in  moments  of  awaking  from  or  falling  into  the 
sleep  state  is  immaterial.  The  dream  as  a  more  or  less 
systematic  articulation  and  fabrication  is  quite  distinguish- 
able from  the  unique  fusions  which  come  in  moments  of  drowsi- 
ness. In  the  experience  of  the  writer  and  his  observers  these 
latter  are  more  often  momentary  perceptual  states,  flashlights 
of  imagery  of  unwonted  vividness  which  may  as  such  be 
repeated  in  successive  moments  but  which  do  not  tend  to 
lead  on  to  new  situations  as  do  dream  states.  And  yet  these 
perceptual  fusions  show  striking  points  of  similiarity  in  their 
composition  to  the  various  units  of  the  serial  dream. 

The  purpose  of  this  paper  is  to  describe  several  typical 
cases  of  the  drowsiness  hallucination  and  to  analyze  out  some 
of  the  principles  which  clearly  contribute  to  their  formation. 
Two  observers,  the  writer  (H)  and  his  wife  (L),  have  for  the 
last  two  years  been  recording  these  experiences,  with  the 
result  that  an  accumulation  of  cases  has  been  acquired  which 
seem  to  show  sufficiently  pronounced  characteristics  and 
similiarities  to  make  their  discussion  worth  while.  The  ob- 
servations  have   invariably   been   made   in   the   pre-sleeping 

^"On  Sensorial  Visions"  in  Popular  Lectures  on  Scientific  Subjects. 
^Illusions,  p.   184. 


« 


THE   PSYCHOLOGY   OF  DROWSINESS  lOI 

state,  for  neither  of  the  observers  has  the  drowsiness  hallucina- 
tion in  any  marked  degree  in  the  pre-waking  state.  In  all 
cases  the  observer  has  been  aware  of  the  hallucinatory  char- 
acter of  the  experience,  and  has  immediately  written  out  the 
description  or  narrated  it  to  the  other  observer. 

The  imagery  type  of  the  observer,  as  will  be  shown  later, 
seems  to  be  to  some  extent,  a  determining  factor  in  the  com- 
position of  the  hallucination  content,  in  that  modes  which 
are  only  vague  and  seldom  used  in  the  waking  state  become 
vivid  and  active  in  the  drowsy  condition,  while  the  type 
modes  fall  into  the  background.  It  will  then  be  of  interest 
to  know  that  according  to  frequent  imagery  tests  L  is  pre- 
dominately visual  and  visual-verbal  in  type  with  almost  no 
auditory  or  motor  tendencies,  while  H  is  very  highly  auditor- 
motor,  both  as  to  imagery  and  memory  type,  has  frequently 
had  auditory  and  motor  hallucinations,  especially  marked 
in  childhood,  but  is  a  very  poor  visualizer.  Typical  cases 
are  given  in  the  following  paragraphs,  and  in  the  subsequent 
analysis  these  cases  will  be  referred  to  by  number. 

Case  I.  Observer  H.  On  board  ocean-liner,  dressing  for 
dinner  in  suit  purchased  abroad,  sitting  drowsily  on  edge  of 
berth  and  thinking  that  the  suit  had  turned  out  to  be  a  bad 
investment  and  had  been  forced  on  to  me  by  a  tricky  salesman. 
Planning  to  buy  cloth  this  time  to  be  made  up  in  United  States 
and  wondering  if  it  would  pass  Customs.  Suddenly  the  rush 
of  water  heard  through  the  porthole  becomes  transformed 
into  the  husky  voice  of  a  salesman  trying  to  sell  me  a  suit. 
I  fall  to  musing  in  the  process,  wondering,  while  he  talks,  at 
his  husky  voice  and  why  he  has  no  more  inflection. 

Case  II.  Observer  H.  At  Victor  Herbert's  opening  con- 
cert, 1 909,  L — ,  E — ,  and  myself  were  talking  of  the  cartoons  of 
Mr.  Bug  in  "Life."  L —  described  a  cartoon  in  which  the 
six  legs  of  Deacon  Fire-fly  were  represented  as  grasping 
different  objects  such  as  a  Bible,  a  prayer  book,  etc.,  while 
Mr.  Bug  held  playing  cards,  a  bottle,  a  cigar,  etc.  I  had  been 
working  all  day  on  comparative  nervous  anatomy,  preparing 
a  lecture  on  complications  of  stimulus  and  response,  and  had 

y  head  full  of  segments  and  nervous  arcs.  The  orchestra 
layed  Grieg's  "Wedding  Day  at  Hegstad."  In  the  last 
bar   there   were   three   finishing   blasts   with   full   orchestra. 

had  become  very  drowsy  and  these  blasts  seemed  to  me 

be  movements  of  some  huge  bug  which  came  sailing  from 
ehind  the  wings,  suddenly  alighting  on  the  stage,  first  on 
the  two  hind  feet,  then  bringing  down  the  middle  pair,  and 
finally  the  two  front  feet  with  the  final  blast.  The  visual 
elements  present  were  of  huge,  vague,  rather  reddish  brown 
jointed  legs,  the  feet  not  clear  and  only  the  lower  ventral  side 


I02  HOLI.ING  WORTH 

of  the  body  dimly  suggested,  but  flashing  out  at  each  "land" 
of  the  feet. 

Case  III.  Observer  H.  In  bed,  winter  '09,  with  "grippe." 
Kept  tossing  from  side  to  back,  then  to  other  side.  As  I  tossed 
the  numbers  50,  2,  36  kept  running  in  my  head,  appearing 
clearly  visually  as  5236,  and  auditorially  as  "fifty  two — thirty 
six."  Now  these  (50,  2,  36)  were  the  combination  numbers 
of  my  gym  locker,  which  I  opened  by  turning  the  knob  left- 
right-left-right,  four  turns,  very  much  as  I  now  tossed  in  bed. 
In  my  tossing  the  numbers  rang  and  rang  in  my  head,  the 
left  side  seeming  52,  the  right  side  36,  the  back  5236.  It 
seemed  that  if  I  could  juggle  these  numbers  into  the  right 
combination  I  could  find  a  comfortable  position. 

Case  IV.  Observer  L.  Tossing  experience  similar  to  above, 
but  seemed  to  be  going  to  Brooklyn  and  back,  Mrs.  M. — 
who  lives  there  having  lately  been  uppermost  in  mind  through 
conversation,  letters  and  a  recent  visit. 

Case  V.  Observer  H.  Played  checkers  nearly  all  day  on 
steamer.  Retiring  to  cabin  before  sleeping  time,  threw  myself 
drowsily  on  my  bunk  and  fell  to  ruminating  over  some  pro- 
jected experiments  on  the  comic,  wondering  whether  to  follow 
method  of  order  of  merit  or  that  of  assigning  numerical  grade 
to  each  comic  situation.  I  decide,  but  in  my  half  awake  con- 
sciousness the  decision  takes  the  form  of  a  move  in  checkers.  I 
I  decide  to  move  my  white  man  up  to  the  king  row  and  men-  "i 
tally  see  C —  jump  it  with  his  black. 

Case  VI.  Observer  H.  Lying  in  bed  talking.  In  a  pause 
I  see  a  large  marble  toad-stool  which  seems  to  stand  on  a  hill 
and  to  resemble  the  dome  of  the  New  York  University  Library, 
around  which  runs  the  Hall  of  Fame.  On  top  of  the  toad- 
stool bell  were  stamped  in  large  black  letters,  three  names, 
"Jastrow,"  "Gillis,"  and  another  blurred  one  which  I  could 
not  make  out.  At  once  I  told  my  companion  of  the  vision, 
saying  "  I  see  a  curious  hall  of  fame,"  etc.  That  evening  I  had 
read  some  comments  on  Jastrow's  magazine  article  on"  Ma- 
licious Animal  Magnetism"  and  had  also  seen  in  a  comic  paper  a 
picture  called  "The  Annual  Ball  of  the  Mushrooms."  Psycho- 
analysis threw  no  light  on  the  name  "Gillis"  nor  on  the 
blurred  name. 

Case  VII.  Observer  L.  Had  a  bad  toothache,  and  though 
very  sleepy  and  worn  out  could  not  sink  into  a  sound  slumber 
because  of  the  pain.  For  several  hours  I  lay  in  a  state  of 
semi-consciousness,  tossing  from  side  to  side  in  a  drowsy 
effort  to  find  a  comfortable  position.  All  day  I  had  been 
very  intently  working  on  a  coat  which  I  was  making,  and 
my  tossings  back  and  forth  were  all  in  terms  of  the  seams  on 
the  coat,  i.  e.,  as  I  turned  to  the  right  the  seam  down  the 


THS   PSYCHOLOGY   OF   DROWSINESS  IO3 

right  side  of  the  garment  was  inspected,  then  as  that  position 
gradually  grew  unbearable  the  seam  began  to  wrinkle,  to 
pucker,  and  to  become  quite  unmanageable.  Thereupon  I' 
decided  to  work  awhile  on  the  other  seam,  and  turned  to  the 
left  side  and  carefully  basted  and  pressed  the  seam  on  the 
left  side  of  the  coat.  But,  though  it  behaved  very  satis- 
factorily for  a  time,  it  too,  soon  began  to  wrinkle  and  the 
thread  to  snarl.  In  despair  I  attacked  the  seam  on  the  right 
side  again,  that  is,  I  turned  over  to  my  right  side  once  more. 
This  continued  for  an  indefinite  time.  I  was  in  despair. 
I  feared  the  garment  would  be  quite  ruined.  All  through 
these  hours  I  was  conscious  of  the  slight  flapping  of  the  window 
blind  and  twice  I  replied  quite  sensibly  to  the  questions  of 
my  companion,  and  noted  the  striking  of  the  hours  on  a  clock 
in  another  apartment.  But  the  illusion  that  I  was  wrestling 
with  the  seams  of  a  refractory  garment  was  not  dispelled  till 
I  fell  asleep  at  daylight. 

Case  VIII.     Conversations  during  the  drowsy  state. 

(a)  L —  Let's  hurry  and  get  there  by  ten  o'clock. 

H —  That's  easy.     I  could  get  there  by  a  nickel  to  ten. 
(It  was  then  9.50) 

(b)  H —  (As  L  rises  from  the  sofa  where  she  has  been 
resting  and  leaves  the  room)     So  you  want  some  water,  huh? 

t, — (Entering  again)     What  did  you  ask  about  a  drink? 

H — Nothing. 

L — But  you  asked  me  something  about  water. 

H — (drowsily)     It  was  n't  an  asker,  it  was  just  a  sayer. 

(c)  H  is  said  to  behave  when  drowsy  much  like  a  child 
;.or  like  a  half-intoxicated  man, — thus:  he  approaches  an  old 
Ipillow  spotted  with  ink  blots  and  asserts  in  a  child-like  way 
iquite  without  provocation  or  connection, — "Red  ink!  black 
fink!"  pointing  to  the  spots  meanwhile. 

(d)  L  asks  question  to  which  H  replies,  quite  without 
relevance,   "I  don't  think  you  could  see  the  manuscript." 

(e)  L —  "How  curious  the  moon  looks  behind  the  clouds !" 
H — Yes,  just  like  a  thin  place  in  the  sky." 

Case  IX.  The  writer  has  frequently  recorded  fantastic 
[periments  and  conclusions  developed  either  alone  or  during 
liscussions,  late  at  night.  At  the  time  of  their  conception 
11  of  these  plans  and  insights  seemed  highly  rational,  strikingly 
[original  and  wonderfully  significant,  and  the  observer  has  usu- 
lly  marvelled  that  nobody  had  ever  seen  the  thing  so  clearly 
)efore.  He  has  frequently  gone  ahead  after  the  midnight 
|hours  and  prepared  the  material  for  one  of  the  revolutionary 
ixperiments  or  demonstrations  just  conceived.  But  when 
the  plan  or  conclusion  has  been  gone  over  on  the  following 
lorning  the  most  striking  thing  about  it  has  been  its  splendor 


I04  HOLIylNGWORTH 

as  a  work  of  unbridled  imagination,  but  its  absurdity  as  a 
scientific  achievement.  The  argument  is  found  to  abound 
with  fallacies  or  the  experimental  procedure  with  sources  of 
error  that  were  lightly  bridged  over  the  night  before.  The 
experience  is  no  doubt  a  very  common  one.  It  seems  much 
like  the  nocturnal  aereonautic  inspection  of  a  line  of  march 
which  must  be  gone  over  on  foot  when  daylight  comes. 

Case  X.  The  reason  for  citing  the  two  following  literary 
references  will  be  seen  later.  They  are  typical  drowsiness 
figures. 

(a)  This  passage  from  Stevenson's  letters  to  Henry  James 
(Stevenson,  Letters,  p.  435)  must  have  been  written  late  at 
night  and  in  a  state  of  drowsiness.  In  fact  Stevenson  says 
earlier  in  the  letter  "my  wife  being  at  a  concert  and  a  story 
being  done,"  indicating  a  late  hour,  and  (especially  in  Steven- 
son's case)  fatigue.  Speaking  of  the  "Henry  James  chair" 
the  writer  of  the  letter  says,  "It  has  been  consecrated  to 
guests  by  your  approval  and  now  stands  at  my  elbow  gaping. 
We  have  a  new  room,  too,  to  introduce  to  you — our  last 
baby,  the  drawing  room;  it  never  cries  and  has  cut  its  teeth. 
Likewise  there  is  a  cat  now." 

(b)  De  Balzac,  who  wrote  the  following  passage  must 
have  been  a  night  worker, — "He  saw  his  teeth  departing  one 
by  one  like  brilliantly  dressed  ladies  from  a  ball  room." 

The  experiences  here  recorded  can  hardly  be  classed  as 
dream  states  though  it  is  true  that  only  a  little  elaboration 
would  be  needed  to  make  them  develop  into  such  states. 
They  all  occurred  during  waking  moments,  and  frequently 
(See  Cases  2,  5,  7)  there  is  clear  evidence  that  the  observer  is 
actively  engaged  in  some  waking  employment  or  lively  thought 
process  or  is  conscious  of  external  events.  Yet  most  of  them 
are  hallucinatory  in  character.  Examination  of  such  cases  as 
those  given  above  reveals  several  rather  clearly  defined  princi- 
ples of  composition  or  general  tendency.  Chief  among  these 
are  the  following,  the  exposition  of  which  seems  to  constitute 
a  fairly  true,  though  perhaps,  only  partially  complete  analysis 
of  the  state  of  drowsiness.  Other  experiences  of  much  the 
same  kind  could  be  given,  some  of  which  are  withheld  only 
because  of  their  close  personal  character,  but  all  point  in  the 
same  direction  as  the  cases  here  given,  some  of  them  even  more 
definitely. 

I.    Transformation  of  Imagery  Type 

Modes  ordinarily  vague  and  feeble  become  here  dominant 
and  vivid,  even  tending  to  replace  customary  imagery  habits. 
Thus  H,  who  is  predominantly  auditory  and  motor  in  type  and 
can  only  with  difficulty  summon  up  visual  images  of  even 


t 


THE   PSYCHOLOGY  OF  DROWSINESS  IO5 

the  most  moderate  vividness,  has,  in  the  drowsy  state,  visual 
experiences  which  constantly  amaze  him  by  their  clearness. 
(See  Cases  2,  3,  5,  6.)  L,  to  whom  sharp  visual  imagery  is 
a  common  habit,  but  who,  in  her  waking  consciousness  cannot 
understand  what  kinesthetic  imagery  is  like,  tends,  in  the 
drowsy  state,  to  relive  motor  experiences  almost  exclusively. 
(See  Cases  4  and  7).  Along  with  this  emphasis  of  unusual 
modes  goes  the  subordination  of  dominant  modes,  so  that  in 
the  drowsy  state  as  in  dream  life,  images  even  of  these  unusual 
types  seem  to  exceed  by  far  in  intensity  the  clearest  images 
of  the  waking  state. 

It  seems  to  be  generally  true  that  with  increased  age,  in- 
creased book  learning  and,  in  general,  with  practice  in  verbal 
modes  of  thinking,  sense  imagery  gives  way  to  word  imagery 
of  one  kind  and  another.^  Parallelling  this  fact,  many 
people  have  complained  to  the  writer  that  with  maturity  they 
lose  their  long  drawn  out  delight  in  books,  and  especially  in 
descriptive  literature.  They  tend  more  and  more  merely 
to  scan  such  passages  and  hence  to  read  books  much  more 
quickly.  They  may  regret  the  loss  of  the  old  source  of  sat- 
isfaction, the  character  of  which  they  do  not  understand. 
Evidently  what  happens  is  that  sense  imagery  is  waning 
and  description  no  longer  has  its  old  power  of  awakening 
interest  or  calling  forth  emotion.  In  drowsiness  this  state 
tends  to  disappear.  The  dominant  modes  in  which  one  has 
become  accustomed  to  think  in  the  more  rigorous  sense,  seem 
to  tend  toward  sleep  more  quickly,  while  the  lower,  more 
strictly  sensory  centres  remain  active  or  go  to  sleep  more 
slowly. 

{Note.  Since  the  preceding  paragraph  was  written  the 
writer,  in  re-reading  Professor  Titchener's  striking  analysis^ 
of  his  own  imagery  processes,  has  found  what  seems  to  be 
another  clear  instance  of  the  transformation  of  imagery 
type.  Although  this  observer  says  it  is  possible  for  him  to 
*' trust  to  the  guidance  of  kinaesthesis,"  this  mode  of  imagery 
does  not  seem  to  predominate  in  his  daily  life.  The  following 
statements  show  the  apparent  superiority  of  his  visual  and 
auditory  imagery.  "I  rely  in  my  thinking  upon  visual 
imagery  ..."  etc.  "My  visual  imagery,  voluntarily 
aroused,  is  extremely  vivid."  "  .  .  .  visual  imagery  which 
is  always  at  my  disposal  and  which  I  can  mould  and  direct 
at  will."  But  he  also  has  "vivid  and  persistent  auditory 
imagery"  and  never  sits  down  to  work  without  a  "musical 
accompaniment."     Kinaesthesis  seems  to  play  a  rather  sub- 

^Galton:  Inquiries  into  Human  Faculty,  p.  60. 
^Experimental  Study  of  the  Thought  Processes,  1909,  p.  9. 


I06  HOI.UNG  WORTH 

ordinate  r61e,  although  we  do  find  the  remark,  "As  a  rule  I 
look  to  all  three  kinds  of  prompting  in  the  course  of  a  single 
hour."  But,  and  this  is  the  interesting  point  in  the  present 
connection,  "  .  .  .  when  I  am  tired  (italics  mine)  I  find 
that  vision  and  audition  are  likely  to  lapse,  and  I  am  left 
alone  with  kingesthesis.") 

In  this  state  the  condition  of  early  childhood  is  reproduced 
and  sense  imagery  may  become  vivid,  intense  and  grotesque. 
This  tendency,  along  with  the  absence  of  sensory  stimulation 
probably  accounts  as  well  for  the  greater  vividness  of  images 
in  dreams.  The  frequency  and  character  of  dream  imagery 
has  sometimes  been  taken  as  an  index  of  the  type  habits  of 
waking  life,  but  the  transformation  tendency  shown  in  the 
observations  here  presented  seems  to  show  clearly  that  this 
is  not  the  case  on  the  state  of  drowsiness.  The  difference 
may,  perhaps,  be  explained  by  supposing  that  in  sleep  all 
the  centres  are  more  nearly  equally  quiescent,  while  in  drowsi- 
ness the  type  centres  slumber  first,  thus  giving  prominence 
to  modes  not  usually  relied  on. 

2.    Substitution 

Within  the  content  of  the  drowsiness  fusion  it  will  be  seen 
that  a  present  impression,  a  preservative  tendency  or,  perhaps, 
even  a  pure  memory  element  often  substitutes  itself  for  some 
other  datum  whose  r61e  it  fills  in  the  perceived  composition  of 
the  hallucination.  Illustrations  of  these  forms  of  substitution 
are  afforded  by  the  cases  here  reported. 

(a)  Sensory  Substitution.  Here  a  present  sensory  im- 
pression takes  upon  itself  the  task  of  impersonating  more 
ideal  or  memory  contents,  of  bearing  their  qualities,  carrying 
out  their  behavior  and  in  a  general  way  acting  for  them. 
Thus  in  Case  I  the  sound  of  the  waves  washing  against  the 
sides  of  the  boat  assumes  the  role  of  the  foreign  salesman, 
becomes  his  voice  and  seems  to  constitute  his  conversation. 
In  Cases  3,  4,  and  7  present  motor  processes  (tossings,  turn- 
ings and  other  changes  of  position)  become  the  vehicle  on 
which  are  borne  memory  experiences  of  a  day  or  two  before. 

(b)  Perseverative  Substitution.  Case  V  in  which  the 
thinking  out  of  the  technique  of  an  experimental  problem 
seemed  to  be  carried  on  in  terms  of  the  manipulation  of  the 
white  men  on  a  checker  board,  affords  an  excellent  illustration 
of  the  tendency  of  perseverative  impressions  to  play  the  role 
of  other  data. 

(c)  Ideal  Substitution, — in  which  an  ordinarily  revived 
image  becomes  the  substantive  for  experiences  more  or  less 
remote  or  assists  in  the  interpretation  of  a  present  impression 
is  rather  difficult  to  demonstrate  for  two  reasons.     In  the  first 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY   OF  DROWSINESS  I07 

place  it  is  not  easy  to  draw  the  line  between  perseverative 
impressions  and  supposedly  revived  images.  Thus  in  Case  I 
the  huge  bug  which  was  conceived  as  alighting  on  the  plat- 
form in  order  to  apperceive  the  three  successive  orchestra 
blasts,  was  evidently  a  pure  object  of  "creative imagination," 
for  no  previous  impression  had  corresponded  to  a  creature  of 
such  dimensions.  Yet  the  character  of  this  imagery  content 
was  probably  determined  by  certain  perseverative  tendencies 
arising  from  the  prolonged  consideration  of  the  various  types 
of  nervous  anatomy.  In  the  second  place,  substitutions  of  the 
sensory  and  perseverative  type  usually  involve  a  correlative 
displacement  of  the  ideal  content  for  which  they  act,  and  in 
setting  up  ideal  substitution  as  a  third  type,  on  the  basis  of 
the  data  at  hand,  one  is  perhaps,  merely  paraphrasing  what 
he  has  already  said. 

At  any  rate  it  is  clear  that  interchange  of  ideal  with  both 
sensory  and  perseverative  content  and  interchange  of  sensory 
with  perseverative  content  occurs.  Whether  one  pure  ideal 
datum  may  act  as  substitute  for  another,  future  observation 
may  show.  DeBalzac's  simile  (x,  b)  which  sounds  much  like 
the  conversation  of  a  drowsy  man,  seems  to  be  a  case  of  such 
substitution.  More  will  be  said  of  such  literary  figures  in 
the  following  paragraphs. 

3.    Fluid  Association  on  a  Sensory  Basis 

with  removal  of  constraining  mental  sets  and  controls.  This 
leads  to  bizarre  analogies,  naive  statements  and  unusual 
verbal  combinations.  In  this  respect  the  state  of  drowsiness 
seems  to  be  quite  like  genuine  dream  consciousness,  in  which 
such  free  association  tendencies  are  so  pronounced.  Thus  De 
Manaceine^  points  out  "the  tendency  which  compels  us  during 
sleep  and  during  enfeebled  states  of  consciousness  generally 
to  associate  everything  which  presents  some  common  resem- 
blance, for  example  — words  according  to  their  sound,  and 
images  according  to  some  accidental  and  external  resem- 
blance. The  same  tendency  is  observed  in  the  uneducated 
and  very  markedly  in  the  insane.  .  .  Any  resemblance  in 
color  or  form  is  enough  to  associate  images  which  are  alto- 
gether (i)  heterogeneous."  Again,  "There  is  a  well  known 
tendency  in  dreams  for  the  perpetration  of  bad  puns,  sound 
leading  sense,  as  happens  frequently  with  the  insane,  idiots 
and  young  children."  Prince^  in  referring  incidentally  to  the 
characteristics  of  the  pre-sleeping  state  has  written,  "ideas 
course  through  the  mind  in  what  appears  to  be  a  disconnected 
fashion,     although    probably    determined    by    associations. 

^Sleep,  p.  283  £f.  ^Op.  cti. 


I08  HOLUNG  WORTH 

Memories  of  the  preceding  day  and  of  past  thoughts  which 
express  the  interests,  desires,  fears  and  anxieties  of  the  psy- 
chological life  and  attitudes  of  the  individual  float  in  a  stream 
through  the  mind  like  a  phantasmagoria." 

Examples  a,  b,  c,  d,  and  e  under  CaseVIII  afford  concrete 
illustrations  of  such  uncontrolled  accidental  association. 
Formal,  practical  and  conceptual  constraints  being  removed, 
resemblances  of  a  sensory  and  ordinarily  unnoticed  kind,  which 
seem  to  involve  only  lower  nervous  centres  become  predomi- 
nant, verbal  plays  (b),  naive  confusion  of  related  concepts 
(a),  absurd  juxtapositions  (d)  and  attention  to  irrelevant 
details  (c)  abound  in  the  state  of  drowsiness.  Not  infre- 
quently similes  and  affective  chords  are  hit  upon  which  with 
only  a  little  treatment  would  become  adequate  literary  figures 
(e). 

Indeed,  many  of  the  choicest  paragraphs  to  be  found  in 
the  works  of  imaginative  writers  bear  all  the  birth  marks  of 
a  drowsiness  conception.  The  illustration  from  Stevenson's 
letters  (loa)  is  clearly  a  case  of  unusually  vivid  imagery, 
sensory  substitution  and  uncontrolled  association.  In  this 
connection  Marsh's  study^  of  the  favorite  work  hours  of  i6o 
eminent  writers  is  extremely  interesting.  Some  of  Marsh's 
conclusions  are  as  follows : 

"If  the  poets  and  novelists  are  roughly  designated  as  an 
imaginative  class  and  the  historians,  clergymen,  essayists, 
critics,  journalists,  philosophers,  etc.,  as  a  broader  intellective 
class  we  shall  find  the  former  predominant  in  the  morning 
and  night  groups  and  the  latter  in  the  day  ones;"  "  .  .  .  of 
the  after  midnight  workers  all  are  of  the  imaginative  type;" 
"  .  .  .  excitation  of  some  sort  is  most  often  the  precondition 
of  the  highest  imaginative  work."  "  .  .  .  numerous  and 
well-patronized  methods  of  mental  stimulation — from  ordinary 
walking,  riding  or  music  to  hourly  service  of  blackest  coffee, 
greenest  tea  or  strongest  opium  or  to  constant  use  of  tobacco, 
before  and  during  composition.  The  extensiveness  of  this  prac- 
tice among  the  imaginative  writers  is  striking." 

One  might  mention  in  the  same  connection  the  fact  that 
Mark  Twain  is  said  to  have  done  most  of  his  writing  in  bed, 
if  not  while  actually  sleepy  at  least  in  the  sleeping  posture, 
and  the  further  fact  that  certain  favorite  poets  have  pro- 
duced nothing  of  note  since  they  were  induced  to  sign  the 
temperance  pledge.  The  use  of  drugs  and  the  preference  for 
night  hours  both  point  in  the  same  direction.  It  seems  to 
have  been  shown  plainly  that  the  apparent  stimulating  effect 

^Diurnal  Course  of  Efficiency,  Archives  of  Psychol.  No.  7,  1906,  pp. 
59-69. 


THS   PSYCHOLOGY   OI^  DROWSINESS  IO9 

of  such  drugs  as  are  used  depends  on  the  fact  that  they  nar- 
cotize the  higher  centres,  on  the  functioning  of  which  depend 
our  control  processes  and  constraining  mental  sets.  And 
much  the  same  condition  seems  to  be  the  cause  both  of  the  in- 
volved serial  dream  states  and  of  the  vivid  perceptual  drowsi- 
ness complications.  The  similarity  of  these  states  to  the  oft 
described  alienation  psychoses  will  at  once  remind  the  reader 
of  Nordau's  fervent  chapter^  on  Mysticism. 

The  artist  and  the  poet  must  in  some  way  get  out  of  the 
world  of  percepts  and  into  the  world  of  pure  sensory  qualities. 
And  this  is  npt  an  easy  thing  for  most  of  us  to  do.  Most 
of  us  were  there  when  we  were  children  and  the  most  prosaic 
of  us  tend  to  slip  over  the  frontier  in  the  pre-sleeping  state 
or  when  under  the  influence  of  artificially  induced  drowsiness. 
A  very  few  of  us  are  vagabonds  enough  to  be  able  to  wander 
back  and  forth  at  will,  and  these  are  the  artists  and  poets. 

4.    Isolation  of  Association  Trains 

This  characteristic  of  drowsy  states  is  closely  related  to 
that  described  in  the  foregoing  section.  The  difference  lies 
in  the  fact  that  there  we  were  dealing  with  single  percep- 
tual or  ideational  contents  while  here  we  have  to  do  with 
such  serial  chains  of  associations  as  may  sometimes  be  set 
up.  In  the  drowsy  state  proper,  in  the  experience  of  the 
writer,  these  chains  do  not  develop, — the  genuine  drowsiness 
complication  being  either  a  simple  "flashlight"  hallucina- 
tion or  else  a  sort  of  "boomerang"  composition,  tending 
to  return  always  upon  itself  rather  than  to  lead  on  to  further 
and  new  associations.  But  such  experiences  as  those  de- 
scribed under  Case  IX  seem  to  belong  to  much  the  same 
state.  These  fantastic  thought  systems  evolve  most  easily 
in  times  of  fatigue,  loss  of  sleep  or  unduly  prolonged  intel- 
lectual work.  When  the  drowsy  state  is  thus  extended  over 
a  long  period  of  time,  association  chains  and  reasoning 
show  much  the  same  behavior  that  perceptual  or  ideational 
states  do  in  the  drowsiness  state  proper.  The  essential  thing 
is  the  release  of  all  intellectual  inhibition.  An  idea,  plan 
or  desire  is  thus  able  to  make  unimpeded  progress  from  stage 
to  stage  of  its  development  with  what  seems  at  the  time  to 
be  unerring  logic.  Its  evolution  is  accompanied  by  the  strong 
emotion  and  the  feelings  of  exuberance,  bouyancy,  confidence 
and  eager  enthusiasm  characteristic  of  the  night  worker. 
In  my  own  case  the  feverish  plans,  insights  and  conclusions 
developed  in  midnight  hours  have  almost  invariably  faded  into 
pale  grays  on  the  arrival  of  the  next  "waking  consciousness" 

^  Degeneration,  Ch.  I. 


no  HOI.UNG  WORTH 

much  as  did  Maeterlinck's  "Bluebird"  when  brought  into 
the  sunlight. 

The  drowsiness  thought  process  behaves  much  as  do  the 
familiar  dream  states  in  which  cosmic  riddles  are  solved  and 
impossible  mechanical  devices  evolved.  One  recalls  in  this 
connection  the  oft-told  case  cited  by  Crichton-Brown  of  the 
man  who  determined  to  write  out  the  solution  arrived  at  in 
order  to  preserve  it  from  the  amnesia  which  usually  developed 
on  awaking.  When  morning  came  he  looked  eagerly  for  the 
paper  on  which  he  had  written  during  the  night  and  read 
there  only  the  single  mystic  sentence,  "A  strong  smell  of 
turpentine  pervades  the  whole." 

Rivers  and  Weber^  have  shown  that  mental  fatigue,  an- 
sesthetization  of  the  muscle  involved,  or  small  doses  of  alcohol 
may  have  the  same  effect,  viz.:  a  momentary  falling  off  of 
fatigue  due  to  disregard  of  secondary  afferent  impulses  which 
are  the  basis  of  the  fatigue  feeling.  Much  the  same  situation 
seems  to  be  present  in  the  drowsy  state  and  the  disregard  of 
obstacles  and  treacherous  points  in  the  chain  of  reasoning 
is  probably  due  to  quiescence  of  the  higher  centres  which 
control  both  motor  output  and  processes  of  inference.  Such 
a  condition  is  reconcilable  with  any  of  the  current  theories 
of  sleep  and  with  most  theories  of  epilepsy,  to  the  intellectual 
aurse  of  which  the  drowsiness  hallucinations  seem  to  bear  a 
close  resemblance. 

5.    Grandeur  and  Vastness 

Closely  connected  with  the  transformation  of  imagery  type 
and  the  isolation  of  association  chains  is  the  tendency  toward 
grandeur  and  vastness  which  usually  characterizes  the  drowsy 
states.  This  is  true  of  the  simpler  perceptual  complications 
as  well  as  of  the  further  developed  thought  processes.  Thus 
in  Case  II  the  idea  of  a  gigantic  insect,  and  in  Cases  3,  4, 
and  7,  the  interpretation  of  limited  motor  processes  in  terms 
of  long  journeys  or  of  complicated  activities  such  as  dress- 
making and  opening  combination  locks,  and  in  Case  I  the 
personification  of  monotonous  noises,  show  the  tendency 
to  magnify  simply  sensory  impressions.  In  another  case,  not 
recorded  here,  a  space  of  perhaps  three  feet  was  taken  to 
represent  the  ocean. 

When  a  chain  of  reasoning  is  involved,  all  projects  are  fer- 
tile and  all  outcomes  expansive.  The  common  tendency  for 
the  disagreeable,  the  undesirable  and  the  unfavorable  fact 
to  oblivesce  seems  here  to  be  especially  strong.  The  drowsi- 
ness experience,  in  the  case  of  the  present  observers  at  least  ^  ] 

^On  the  Effect  of  Small  Doses  of  Alcohol.  British  Journal  of  Psychology, 
Jan.,  1908. 


TH^   PSYCHOIvOGY   OF   DROWSINEJSS  III 

resembles  that  following  upon  the  inhalation  of  diluted  nitrous 
oxide  gas, — "the  mental  symptoms  consist  in  convictions  of 
emancipation,  relief  and  happiness,  in  grand  and  sublime 
ideas  which  in  their  expansion  seem  to  break  down  all  barriers 
of  doubt  and  difficulty  and  to  make  a  wish  and  its  realization 

one It  is  at  the  point  where  the  habitual  control 

or  check  of  the  highest  centres  is  withdrawn  and  where  sub- 
ordinate centres  are  free  to  indulge  in  unwonted  activity 
that  the  expansive  dreamy  thoughts  and  exalted  feelings 
present  themselves  in  the  progress  of  nitrous  pxide  gas  intoxi- 
cation."^ 

6.    Amnesia  for  Processes  and  Events 

occurring  during  the  drowsy  state  comes  quickly.  This  is 
shown  by  the  tendencies  of  these  experiences  to  escape  obser- 
vation unless  special  interest  directs  attention  to  them. 
Further,  unless  they  are  recorded  or  reported  promptly  they 
are  soon  forgotten  or  elaborated  by  the  retrospective  attempts 
of  waking  consciousness. 

7.    Absence  of  Symbolism 

So  far  as  the  writer  has  been  able  to  discover  there  is  no 
evidence  of  special  symbolism  in  these  states  except  in  so 
far  as  they  reflect  the  recent  experiences  or  occupations  of 
the  individual.  The  composition  of  their  content  seems  to 
consist  chiefly  in  "flashlight"  perceptual  complications  of  the 
memories  of  recent  experiences  with  perseverative  tendencies 
and  present  sensory  impressions.  Only  in  so  far  as  the  data 
from  these  three  sources  is  somewhat  dependent  on  the  funda- 
mental interests  of  the  observer  can  the  drowsiness  psychosis 
be  said  to  be  symbolical. 

{Note).  Sidis  (Experimental  Study  of  Sleep)  has  given 
"extreme  suggestibility"  as  one  mark  of  the  hypnoidal  state. 
This  state  bears  a  close  resemblance  to  the  condition  of 
normal  drowsiness,  and  may,  perhaps,  be  identical  with  it. 
But  suggestibility  seems  to  be  a  general  statement  of  the 
possibilities  of  the  pre-sleeping  state,  rather  than  an  intro- 
spective description  of  the  drowsiness  consciousness.) 

By  way  of  summary  we  may  say,  finally,  that  the  drowsi- 
ness hallucination  seems  to  be  a  "flashlight"  perceptual 
fusion  or  complication,  and  is  further  characterized  by  trans- 
formation of  imagery  type;  sensory,  perseverative  and  ideal 
substitution ;  fluid  association  chiefly  on  a  sensory  basis ;  and  by 
isolation  of  association  trains  when  they  develop ;  and  that  it  is 
accompanied  by  tendencies  toward  grandeur  and  vastness,  by 
rapidly  developed  amnesia  and  by  absence  of  symbolism. 

^Crichton-Brown :  op.  cit. 


MINOR  STUDIES  FROM  THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL 
LABORATORY  OF  VASSAR  COLLEGE 

XIV.    An  Effect  of  Fatigue  on  Judgments  of  the 
Affective  Vai.ue  of  Coi^ors 

By  Ethel  L.  Nokris,  Alice  G.  Twiss,  and  M.  F.  Washburn 

A  state  of  fatigue  may  naturally  be  expected  to  lessen  the  pleasantness^ 
of  pleasant  experiences  and  to  increase  the  unpleasantness  of  unpleasant 
experiences.  The  present  study  is  an  attempt  to  get  experimental  con- 
firmation, within  a  certain  very  limited  sphere,  of  this  conclusion  drawn 
from  general  experience.  As  the  source  of  pleasant  and  unpleasant  affec- 
tion we  chose  colored  papers.  With  regard  to  the  source  of  fatigue,  evi- 
dently a  number  of  possibilities  were  open :  we  might  have  used  some  form 
of  physical  fatigue,  but  we  chose  mental  fatigue  instead.  Here,  again,  we 
might  have  produced  fatigue  in  our  observers  by  means  of  some  kind  of 
mental  work,  such  as  mental  arithmetic,  quite  different  from  the  work  of 
judging  the  affective  values  of  colors.  We  undertook,  however,  the  prob- 
lem of  finding  how  far  judgments  of  the  affective  value  of  colors  are  in- 
fluenced when  the  observer  is  required  to  perform  a  long  series  of  such 
judgments.  That  is,  the  fatigue  was  produced  by  the  same  kind  of  mental 
process  as  that  upon  which  it  was  supposed  to  act. 

Our  method  was  as  follows:     A  piece  2.9  cm.  square  was  cut  from  each 
of  the  ninety  colored  papers  in  the  Bradley  series,  comprising  eighteen 
saturated  colors,  namely,  red  violet,  violet,  blue  violet,  violet  blue,  blue, 
green  blue,  blue  green,  green,  yellow  green,  green  yellow,  yellow,  orange 
yellow,  yellow  orange,  orange,  red  orange,  orange  red,  red,  violet  red;  to- 
gether with  two  shades  and  two  tints  of  each  color.     Bach  piece  of  paper 
was  placed  on  a  white  background  before  the  observer,  who  was  required 
to  look  at  it  for  ten  seconds  and  to  record  her  judgment  of  its  affective 
value  in  nimierical  terms,  using  the  ntunbers  from  i   to  7  to  designate 
respectively  the  following  degrees :  very  unpleasant,  moderately  unpleasant, 
slightly  unpleasant,   indifferent,   slightly  pleasant,   moderately  pleasant, 
very  pleasant.     The  colors  were  shown  in  wholly  irregular  order.     After 
judgment  had  been  passed  upon  the  whole  ninety,  without  any  pause 
in  the  operations  the  observer  was  given  in  succession  the  first  six  colors 
of  the  experimental  series,  in  their  original  order,  and  required  to  record 
anew  her  judgment  of  their  pleasantness  or  unpleasantness.     In  no  case 
did  the  observer  report  remembering  what  her  previous  judgment  had 
been.     The  whole  proceeding  took  from  three-quarters  of  an  hour  to  an 
hour.     The  effect  of  fatigue  upon  the  affective  tone  of  the  six  colors  selected 
to  begin  the  series  was  then  calculated  as  follows.     When  the  number 
assigned  to  a  color  at  the  end  of  the  series  differed  from  the  number  assigned 
to  the  same  color  at  the  beginning,  the  amount  of  the  difference  together 
with  its  sign,  i.  e.,  whether  it  was  an  increase  or  a  decrease,  was  noted,  and 
these  differences  were  averaged,  regard  being  paid  to  signs.     Thus  for  one 
observer  the  affective  value  of  one  of  the  six  colors  dropped  two  numbers, 
that  of  another  color  dropped  one  number,  that  of  a  third  rose  one  number, 
and  that  of  three  colors  showed  no  change.     The  total  change  for  all  the 
colors  tested  was  then  i — 3,  or — 2 ;  and  dividing  this  number  by  6,  the  number 
of  colors  tested,  we  find  the  average  fall  in  affective  value  to  be  .3. 


MINOR   STUDIES  II 3 

There  were  thirty-five  observers,  all  women  and  all  but  four  college 
students.  Out  of  these,  the  averages  of  seven  showed  a  rise  instead  of  a 
fall  in  the  affective  value  of  the  colors  at  the  end  of  the  series,  and  for  three 
the  affective  values  were  exactly  the  same  at  the  beginning  and  at  the  end. 
Twenty- three  observers  show  an  average  drop  of  from  .i  to  1.5.  In  the 
case  of  three  observers  every  change  in  the  affective  value  of  a  color  was 
an  increase:  in  the  case  of  ten,  every  change  was  a  decrease. 

It  is  unnecessary  to  point  out  that  we  cannot  be  sure  of  producing  uni- 
form degrees  of  fatigue  by  this  method.  Aside  from  individual  differences 
in  physical  condition  and  previous  fatigue,  the  process  of  judging  required 
is  undoubtedly  more  fatiguing  to  some  people  than  to  others.  Thus  one 
of  the  three  observers  for  whom  the  affective  values  were  greater  at  the 
end  than  at  the  beginning  of  the  series  was  an  artist,  to  whom  the  (tolors 
had  probably  more  interest  than  to  the  other  observers.  Again,  in  the 
case  of  those  observers  who  were  acquainted  with  the  method  the  knowl- 
edge that  the  end  of  the  series  was  approaching  produced  a  cheering  up 
which  might  have  been  expected  to  counterbalance  fatigue;  although  this 
did  not  prove  to  be  the  case  with  two  out  of  the  three  authors  of  this  study. 
When  a  drop  in  the  affective  value  of  a  color  does  appear  at  the  end  of  the 
series,  we  have  no  assurance  that  it  is  produced  by  fatigue;  but  since  the 
other  sources  of  variation  might  be  expected  to  produce  a  rise  as  often 
as  a  drop,  the  results  do  indicate  that  for  sixty-five  per  cent,  of  our  observers 
fatigue  was  the  prevailing  source  of  change. 

Two  further  facts  may  be  noted.  The  total  number  of  points  by  which 
the  saturated  colors  were  raised  in  affective  value  at  the  end  of  the  series 
was  29;  the  total  number  of  points  by  which  they  were  lowered  was  35; 
the  excess  of  lowering  over  raising  is  then  only  6.  The  corresponding 
excess  for  tints  is  31,  and  for  shades,  40.  Shades,  tints,  and  saturated 
colors  were  selected  with  about  equal  frequency  for  use  as  the  test  colors 
at  the  beginning  and  end  of  the  experimental  series.  These  results,  then, 
seem  to  mean  that  under  the  experimental  conditions  described,  the  effect  of 
fatigue  in  lowering  affective  value  is  very  decidedly  less  marked  in  the  case  of 
saturated  colors  than  in  that  of  shades  and  tints..  On  the  other  hand,  the 
variations  from  other  sources  than  fatigue  seemed  to  influence  saturated 
colors,  shades,  and  tints  to  nearly  the  same  degree,  if  we  may  judge  from 
the  fact  that  the  percentage  of  cases  where  the  affective  value  of  a  color 
was  the  same  at  the  beginning  as  at  the  end  of  a  series  was,  for  saturated 
colors,  40;  for  tints,  34,  and  for  shades,  45.  It  looks,  however,  as  though 
the  affective  impression  made  by  saturated  colors,  whether  pleasant  or 
unpleasant,  were  so  definite  that  fatigue  induced  by  this  method  alters  it 
but  little;  although  we  might  expect  that  continuous  experience  with  a 
saturated  color  would  cause  a  rapid  drop  in  its  pleasantness. 

Secondly,  we  undertook  to  find  what  kind  of  judgments  were  most  in- 
fluenced by  fatigue.  When  we  counted  the  number  of  times  each  numer- 
ical judgment  from  2  to  7  appeared  in  connection  with  the  first  six  colors 
of  the  series,  and  found  in  what  percentage  of  this  number  the  judgments 
were  lowered  at  the  end  of  the  series,  there  appeared  to  be  no  uniform 
relation  between  the  degree  of  pleasantness  or  unpleasantness  in  the  first 
experience  and  the  amount  of  lowering  of  affective  value  in  the  second. 
We  noted  that  other  sources  of  variation  appeared  to  affect  extreme  judg- 
ments, I  and  7,  more  than  moderate  judgments:  the  percentage  of  cases 
involving  no  change  whatever  in  affective  value  was  highest  for  the  judg- 
ments 7  and  I .  We  at  first  thought  that  this  result  pointed  to  a  conclusion 
regarding  the  variability  of  a  given  individual's  affective  reaction  to  a 
given  color,  which  might  be  expressed  in  some  such  terms  as  that  we  are 
less  likely  to  change  our  minds  with  regard  to  the  objects  of  our  extreme 
likes  and  dislikes  than  with  regard  to  those  which  produce  more  moderate 
affective  reactions.     But  later  reflection  showed  us  that  the  real  cause  of 

Journal — 8 


114  NORRIS,   TWISS  AND   WASHBURN 

the  fact  that  the  extreme  judgments  appeared  to  be  more  constant  than  the 
moderate  ones  lay  in  the  conditions  of  the  experiment.  If  the  first  judg- 
ment upon  a  color  has  been  a  moderate  one,  there  are  three  possibilities 
with  regard  to  the  second:  it  may  express  the  same  affective  value  as  the 
first,  or  a  greater  affective  value,  or  a  less  one.  If  on  the  other  hand  the 
first  judgment  has  assigned  either  the  highest  or  the  lowest  affective  value 
to  a  color,  there  are  only  two  possibilities  with  regard  to  the  second  judg- 
ment: it  may  be  the  same  as  the  first,  or  it  may  vary  from  it  in  one  direction 
only.  It  naturally  follows  that  the  percentage  of  cases  showing  no  change 
will,  if  there  is  no  constant  tendency  present,  be  greater  where  the  first 
judgment  has  assigned  the  highest  or  the  lowest  affective  values. 

XV.    A  Note  on  the  Affective  Values  of  Colors 


By  M.  F.  Washburn 


In  the  preceding  study  each  of  thirty-five  observers  was  required  to 
record  in  numerical  terms  her  judgment  on  the  pleasantness  or  unpleasant- 
ness of  ninety  colors,  each  color  being  presented  in  the  form  of  a  paper 
square  2.9  cm.  a  side,  on  a  white  background,  and  looked  at  for  ten  seconds. 
From  the  results  thus  obtained  the  verdicts  of  the  different  observers  on  a 
given  color  have  been  selected  out,  and  their  average  calculated  together 
with  the  mean  variation.  The  whole  series  contained  ninety  saturated 
colors  besides  two  tints  and  two  shades  of  each  color.  To  avoid  what 
seemed  unnecessary  labor,  the  calculations  to  be  discussed  were  made  only 
for  the  lighter  tint  and  the  darker  shade  of  each  color:  thus  for  eighteen 
tints  and  eighteen  shades. 

It  appears  that  for  our  thirty-five  observers,  all  women  and  nearly  all 
college  students,  the  affective  value  of  the  tints  is  highest  (average  from  all 
observers,  4.7);  that  of  the  shades  is  next  (average  from  all  observers,  4.1), 
and  that  of  the  saturated  colors  is  lowest  (average  from  all  observers,  3.6). 
Further,  that  the  affective  reaction  to  saturated  colors,  whether  pleasant  or 
unpleasant,  is  more  positive  than  that  to  shades  and  tints,  and  that  to  tints 
more  positive  than  that  to  shades,  is  indicated  by  the  fact  that  the  total 
number  of  judgments  '4'  (indifferent)  is  for  saturated  colors,  50;  for  tints, 
89,  and  for  shades,  loi. 

Among  saturated  colors,  the  order  of  increasing  pleasantness,  together 
with  the  average  affective  value  assigned  to  each  color  by  our  observers, 
is  as  follows:  green  yellow,  2.1 ;  orange  and  yellow  green,  2.6;  red  violet  and 
green,  3;  yellow,  3.3;  yellow  orange  and  blue  green,  3.4;  red  orange,  3.6; 
violet  red,  3.7;  violet  blue  and  blue,  3.8;  orange  yellow  and  blue  violet,  4; 
violet,  4.4;  orange  red,  4.5;  green  blue,  5.3;  red,  5.6.  Pure  red  is  the 
pleasantest  saturated  color,  and  green  blue  comes  next.  There  is  a  tendency  to 
dislike  yellows  and  yellow  greens. 

Among  ti'nts,  the  order  of  increasing  pleasantness  is  the  following:  violet 
red,  3.4;  green  yellow,  3.8;  orange,  4.3;  yellow  and  orange  yellow,  4.4; 
yellow  orange,  4.5;  blue  green,  red  orange,  and  red,  4.6;  green  blue  and 
orange  red,  4.7;  green,  4.3;  yellow  green,  5;  violet  blue,  5.1 ;  blue  violet,  5.5; 
red  violet  and  violet,  5.9;  blue,  6,  Bltce  is  the  pleasantest  light  tint,  and  in- 
deed the  pleasantest  color  in  the  whole  series. 

Among  shades,  we  have  the  following  order  of  increasing  pleasantness; 
yellow,  2.3;  orange  yellow,  2.7;  blue  green,  3.7;  red  violet,  green  yellow, 
yellow  orange,  and  orange,  3.8;  violet  red,  3.9;  red  orange  and  orange  red, 
4.3;  violet,  4.4;  blue  violet,  green  blue,  and  green,  4.5;  red  and  violet  blue, 
4.8;  blue,  5;  yellow  green,  5.3.  Yellow  green  is  the  pleasantest  dark  shade 
£Lnd  blue  comes  next. 

It  might  seem  that  a  study  of  the  mean  variations  of  these  averages 


MINOR  STUDIES  II 5 

would  be  of  interest,  as  indicating  the  amount  of  unanimity  in  the  tastes 
of  our  observers.  But  further  thought  reveals  the  fact  that  the  mean 
variations  are  necessarily  involved  with  the  degree  of  pleasantness  or  un- 
pleasantness indicated  by  the  averages,  and  can  have  no  independent 
significance.  The  smallest  mean  variations  must  belong  to  the  highest 
and  lowest  averages,  the  largest  mean  variations  to  the  averages  of  medium 
amount.  For  evidently  if  the  average  affective  value  of  a  color  is  four,  the 
mean  variation  of  that  average  may  rise  as  high  as  three,  since  jndgments 
from  one  to  seven  are  possible:  but  if  the  average  affective  value  of  a  color 
is  six  or  two,  the  mean  variation  can  hardly  rise  above  one  and  a  fraction, 
since  there  can  be  no  judgments  above  seven  or  under  one. 


THE  DISCRIMINATION  OF  ARTICULATE  SOUNDS 
BY  RACCOONS. 


By  W.  T.  Shepherd,  Ph.D. 


The  present  paper  in  some  respects  may  be  considered  as 
a  supplementary  report  to  one  on  the  same  subject  made  by 
Professor  L-  W.  Cole,  and  published  by  him  about  three  years 
ago.^  In  the  work  reported  by  Professor  Cole,  in  which  I 
assisted,  four  raccoons  were  used  and  in  this  later  work,  now 
to  be  presented,  the  same  animals  were  employed.  The 
results  which  are  given  here  have  not  previously  been  pub- 
lished, and  only  in  a  minor  degree  can  they  be  considered 
merely  supplementary  to  the  work  of  Cole.  The  experiments 
to  be  reported  are  concerned  with  the  Discrimination  of 
Articulate  Sounds  by  Raccoons. 

It  is  commonly  believed,  and  with  some  degree  of  reason, 
that  the  higher  mammals  can  be  taught  to  respond  to  their 
names,  or  to  express  it  more  accurately,  to  discriminate  articu- 
late sounds  and  to  make  appropriate  motor  responses  thereto. 
It  is  well  known  that  cats,  dogs,  horses  and  other  domesti- 
cated animals  learn  to  respond  to  their  given  names ;  but  it  is 
not  known,  from  well  conducted  experiments,  whether  there 
is  in  these  cases  a  discrimination  of  quality,  of  loudness,  or 
of  time  of  the  sound.  The  results  that  have  been  obtained 
with  animals  under  experimental  conditions  have  been  few, 
and  in  some  cases  the  differentiation  of  tone,  and  intensity 
has  not  been  made.  Thorndike,  it  will  be  remembered, 
found  that  cats  were  apparently  able  to  discriminate  sounds 
made  by  him,  though  not  with  a  great  degree  of  delicacy .^ 
The  sounds  that  Thorndike  used  were  quite  complex  in 
character,  such  as,  "I  must  feed  those  cats"  and  "My  name 
is  Thorndike."  In  his  work  on  the  functions  of  the  tem- 
poral lobes  Kalisher  reported^  having  been  able  to  get  dogs 
to  discriminate  sounds  made  by  an  harmonium,  but  he  was 
more  interested  in  producing  the  association  for  the  purpose 
of  determining   (after  extirpation  of  different  parts  of  the 

^Concerning  the  Intelligence  of  Raccoons,  Jour.  Comp.  Neur.  And  Psych. 
Vol.    17,  p.  211. 

^Animal  Intelligence,  1898. 

^Eine  neue  Horpriifungsmethode  bei  Hunden,  Sitz.  d.  Kgl.  Ak.  d.  Wiss., 
X,   1907.  p.  204  S. 


ARTICUI^ATE   SOUNDS   BY   RACCOONS  II7 

cerebral  cortex)    the  cortical   centres  for  sound  perception 
than  ability  in  his  animals  to  discriminate  sounds. 

At  the  time  the  experiments  were  begun  the  raccoons  were 
about  six  months  old,  and  they  had  been  trained  for  two 
months  on  various  motor  acts,  reported  in  Cole's  paper. 
In  the  early  training  period  we  had  spoken  to  the  animals, 
using  different  names,  but  the  naming  and  calling  was  not 
done  regularly  and  systematically.  During  the  course  of 
these  preliminary  experiments  some  of  the  animals  had  given 
indications  of  associating  the  sounds  with  reactions,  and  one 
in  particular  reacted  often.  Since  no  record  of  these  experi- 
ments was  made  we  cannot  say  how  often  the  stimuli  were 
given,  and  how  well  or  poorly  each  animal  reacted.  For  a 
period  of  two  months  following  these  trials  no  experiments 
on  sound  discrimination  were  made.  Then  the  present  work 
was  begun. 

For  these  tests  each  raccoon  was  placed  in  a  separate  cage 
which  had  a  wire  netting  front.  The  four  cages  were  arranged 
in  different  parts  of  the  room  and  I  sat  at  a  distance  of  from 
four  to  eight  feet  from  the  cages.  The  names  of  the  raccoons 
were  called  in  irregular  order,  and  I  noted  whether  each 
responded  only  to  the  sound  of  his  own  name  or  to  all  the 
names.  Each  animal  was  fed  when  he  responded  to  his  own 
name  (and  was  not  fed  when  the  other  names  were  called). 
The  animals  were  named.  Jack,  Jim,  Tom,  and  Dolly.  During 
these  experiments  all  were  kept  very  hungry. 

ist  day:  In  168  experiments  (42  trials  for  each  animal) 
in  which  the  reaction  of  turning  and  looking  at  me  was  taken 
as  response.  Jack  reacted  correctly  6  times,  3  doubtfully 
correct;  Jim,  11  correct,  3  doubtful;  Tom,  9  correct,  5,  doubt- 
ful; Dolly,  I  correct,  2  doubtful.  All  the  animals  responded 
to  the  first  call,  but  it  is  likely  that  was  only  an  attention 
reaction;  i.  e.,  a  movement  following  a  stimulus  given  by 
one  familiar  to  the  animals. 

2nd  day:  After  the  preliminary  trials  of  the  first  day  I  no 
longer  fed  the  animals  for  this  simple  reaction.  Responses 
were  only  noted  correct  when  they  climbed  up  the  side  of 
the  cage,  in  addition  to  looking  at  me.  Each  raccoon  was  fed 
after  his  name  was  called,  whether  or  not  he  gave  the  proper 
reaction.  In  188  experiments  (47  for  each  animal)  Jack 
reacted  correctly  21  times;  Jim,  9;  Tom,  only  2  doubtful; 
Dolly,  I  correct  with  4  doubtful.  The  results  of  these  two 
days'  experiments  indicated  that  Jack  and  Jim  could  easily 
learn  to  respond  to  their  names. 

3rd  day:  Throughout  the  remainder  of  the  experiments 
each  animal  was  tested  separately  and  the  other  three  were 
kept  out  of  his  sight.     I  called  the  name  of  the  animal,  waited 


Il8  SHEPHERD 

lo  seconds,  if  need  be,  for  response,  and  then,  whether  or 
not  a  response  was  obtained,  the  animal  was  fed.  Alternately 
with  the  name,  the  words  "no  feed' '  were  called,  and  at  these 
times  the  animal  was  not  fed.  In  each  case,  as  noted  above, 
the  correct  reaction  was  considered  to  be  obtained  only  when 
the  raccoon  looked  at  me  and  climbed  up  the  side  of  the  cage. 
In  50  trials  on  each  kind  of  auditory  stimulus  Jack  correctly 
reacted  to  his  name  39  times  and  to  "no  feed"  22;  in  30 
similar  trials  Jim  correctly  reacted  to  his  name  21  times  and 
to  "no  feed"  15;  Tom  in  30  trials  correctly  reacted  to  his 
name  16  times,  to  "no  feed"  10,  with  13  doubtful  in  all; 
Dolly  in  30  trials  correctly  responded  to  her  name  15,  to 
"no  feed"  5,  with  i  doubtful. 

The  experiments  were  continued  in  this  way  for  18  days, 
at  the  end  of  which  time  all  the  animals  appeared  to  know 
their  names  perfectly.  Thirteen  days  after  the  beginning 
of  the  experiments  Jack  correctly  reacted  to  his  name  every 
time  (25  trials),  and  incorrectly  to  the  "no  feed"  signal  only 
3  times  (25  trials).  About  the  same  percentages  of  correct 
and  incorrect  responses  were  obtained  for  Jack  during  the  8 
succeeding  days  of  the  experiment.  It  appeared  to  me  that 
Jack's  few  errors  from  this  point  might  be  accounted  for  by  his 
eagerness  for  food. 

After  the  names  appeared  to  be  well  learned,  as  further  test 
of  auditory  discrimination,  I  called  other  names,  in  addition 
to  the  individual's  name,  such  as  "box,"  "floor,"  after  each 
name:  i.  e.,  1  called  Jack,  "box,"  "floor"  in  succession,  and 
not  alternately.  No  substantial  difference  in  the  percentage 
of  proper  responses  was  noted.  It  seems  evident,  therefore, 
that  the  animals  had  formed  the  habit  of  responding  only 
when  the  appropriate  sound  was  heard,  and  of  not  responding 
to  other  sounds.  To  further  test  the  animals,  I  called  the  names 
and  sounds  in  varying  tones  of  voice,  the  lowest  to  the  highest 
possible  to  me,  and  also  had  other  persons  call  the  words 
and  names.  With  all  the  animals  the  responses  were  strik- 
ingly characteristic  of  discrimination. 

May  we,  therefore,  conclude  that  raccoons  discriminate 
names  or  articulate  sounds?  The  answer  to  this  question 
will  depend  to  a  large  extent  upon  the  acceptance  of  the  later 
experiments  as  conclusive.  A  serious  objection  to  such  a 
conclusion  may  be  urged  by  some.  It  may  well  be  said  that, 
in  the  major  part  of  the  experiments,  where  the  name  and 
"no  feed"  were  called  alternately,  the  raccoons  had  learned 
to  react  alternately  and  that  they  reacted  only  to  the  rhythm 
of  the  stimuli.  On  the  other  hand,  it  must  be  remembered 
that  following  those  experiments  of  alternate  calls,  there  was 
a  series  in  which  the  names  were  not  called  in  any  regular 


ARTICULATE   SOUNDS  BY  RACCOONS 


119 


order,  and  there  was  the  same  percentage  of  correct  responses. 
Moreover,  the  addition  of  extra  sounds  to  the  names  did 
not  alter  the  proportional  number  of  responses.  Both  of 
these  later  tests  permit  us  to  conclude,  therefore,  that  the 
discrimination  did  take  place. 

It  is  of  some  interest  to  note  that.  Jack,  which  judging  from 
the  results  of  the  earlier  tests  and  from  others  to  be  reported 
in  a  later  paper,  was  the  most  intelligent  animal  of  the  four, 
learned  to  associate  the  name  with  the  proper  response 
in  270^  trials,  Tom  took  375  trials,  Jim  425,  while  500  trials 
were  required  for  Dolly.  This  individual  difference  in  animals 
experimented  upon  has  been  a  noticeable  feature  in  other 
experimenters'  work,  but  to  the  mind  of  the  writer  not  sufficient 
attention  has  been  paid  to  it,  and  therefore  animal  psycholo- 
gists have  been  content  to  work  with  a  small  number  of  ani- 
mals (four,  two,  or  even  one)  and  to  draw  from  their  results 
too  broad  conclusions. 


^That  is  to  say  I  called  Jack's  name  270  times  and  the  other  words 
'no  feed,"  etc.,  in  addition. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 


Die  Sprachstdmme  des  Erdkreises.  Von  Prof.  Dr.  Franz  Nikolaus  Finck 
in  Berlin,  Druck  und  Verlag  von  B.  G.  Teubner  in  Leipzig,  1909.  p. 
viii,  143.  Aus  Natur  und  Geisteswelt.  Sammlung  wissenschaftlich- 
gemeinverstandlicher  Darstellungen.  267.  Bandchen. 
Die  HaupUypen  des  Sprachbaus.  Von  Dr.  Franz  Nikolaus  Finck, 
Professor  an  der  Universitat  Berlin,  Druck  und  Verlag  von  B.  G.  Teub- 
ner in  Leipzig,  1910.  pp.  vi,  136.  Ibid.,  268.  Bandchen. 
These  two  latest  additions  to  this  excellent  series  of  German  handbooks  on 
all  manner  of  topics  from  superstition  to  forestry,  and  from  the  theatre  to 
electro-chemistry,  cannot  fail  to  be  of  value  to  all  interested  in  the  com- 
parative study  of  languages,  although  it  is  quite  evident  that  a  number  of 
the  problems  raised  of  late  years  by  the  special  investigations  of  the  speech- 
forms  of  the  American  aborigines  have  not  come  to  the  author's  attention. 
The  first  volimie,  "The  Linguistic  Stocks  of  the  Globe,"  is  a  decided  im- 
provement upon  the  list  in  the  second  edition  (1879)  of  Friedrich  MuUer's 
"Allgemeine  Ethnographic, "  as  may  easily  be  proved  by  a  glance  at  the 
indexes  of  the  two  books,  and  Miiller's  list  has  long  remained  the  most 
complete  and  accessible  to  the  German  public.  But  the  investigations  of 
the  last  twenty-five  years  have  put  it  altogether  out  of  date,  both  as  to 
accuracy  and  as  to  completeness.  Dr.  Finck  classifies  the  languages  of  man- 
kind under  four  races :  Caucasian,  American,  Mongolian,  Ethiopian  (African 
and  Oceanic  Negroes).  Under  the  Caucasian  he  lists  the  Indo-Germanic,  the 
Hamito-Semitic,  the  languages  of  the  peoples  of  the  Caucasus  (Caucasian 
in  the  minor  sense),  the  Dravidian  tongues  of  India  and  the  Basque  and 
Etruscan,  besides  certain  other  long  extinct  forms  of  speech  belonging  to 
Asia  Minor,  etc.,  such  as  Elamite,  Chaldic,  Hittite,  Lycian,  etc.  There  is 
too  much  mixtiwe  of  race  and  speech  in  this  classification.  While,  doubt- 
less all  the  peoples  of  the  Caucasus  belong  to  the  Caucasian  or  "white" 
race,  ethnologists  will  hardly  follow  the  author  in  separating  the  Dravidians 
entirely  from  the  Australian  aborigines  and  making  them  full-fledged  Cau- 
casians, against  which  view  there  are  also  arguments  of  a  linguistic  character. 
As  members  of  the  Mongolian  race,  the  so-called  Austro-Asiatic  tongues 
(Kolarian,  Mon-Khmer,  Khasi,  Nicobar,  Semang,  Senoi),  Austronesian 
(Indonesian,  Melanesian,  Polynesian, — Malayo-Polynesian),  Indo-Chinese 
(Tibeto-Burmese,  Siamo-Chinese),  Ural-Altaic  (Samoyed,  Finnic-Ugric, 
Turkic,  Mongolic,  Tungusic,  Japanese,  Korean,  etc.),  Arctic  or  Hyperbo- 
rean (Yenesseian,  Jukaghir,  Chukchee-Kamtchatkan,  Ainu,  Aleuto-Eskimo), 
a  classification  impossible  to  justify  in  the  light  of  the  most  recent 
investigations.  The  studies  resulting  from  the  Jesup  Northwest  Pacific 
Expedition,  under  the  direction  of  Dr.  Franz  Boas,  have  rendered  it  ex- 
tremely probable  that  the  languages  of  the  so-called  Paleo-Asiatic  peoples 
of  Northeastern  Asia  (Koriak,  Kamtchatkan,  Chukchee,  Yukaghir,  etc.) 
will  be  finally  classed  with  the  American  IndiaA  tongues.  The  Ainu  must 
still  be  recognized  as  isolated  among  the  Asiatic  peoples,  but  there  is  more 
reason  for  affiliating  them  with  the  Caucasian  race,  than  there  is  for  so  doing 
with  the  Dravidian.  The  inclusion  of  the  Kolarian,  the  Mon-Khmer  and 
the  Melanesian  in  one  group  is  open  to  fatal  objections,  while  the  Semang 
and  Sakai  of  Malacca  are  hardly  to  be  looked  upon  as  Mongolian,  nor 
can  one  be  sure  in  placing  there  the  Nicobarese,  etc.  And  there  is  no  good 
reason  for  cutting  off  the  Eskimo  from  the  rest  of  the  American  aborigines 


BOOK   REVmWS  121 

as  Dr.  Finck  does.  The  Sumerians  of  ancient  Babylonia,  about  whose 
ethnological  relations  there  is  still  not  a  little  doubt,  are  here  listed  as 
Mongolian.  The  languages  of  the  American  race  receive  the  most  lengthy- 
treatment  (pp.  68-105)  of  any  of  the  groups,  the  author  following  the  regional 
method  of  cataloguing  the  chief  stocks  (North  Pacific,  North  Atlantic, 
Central,  Amazonian,  Pampas,  Andine  or  South  Pacific),  with  indications 
of  many  of  the  smaller  isolated  tongues  within  these  large  areas.  For 
North  America  Powell  seems  to  have  been  followed  generally,  with  some 
reference  to  later  authorities  (to  judge  from  certain  portions  of  the  text). 
The  modifications  in  the  Powellian  list,  made  necessary  as  the  result  of  the 
more  recent  investigations  of  American  philologists  (and  not  included  in 
Dr.  Finck's  siunmary)  will  be  found  in  the  articles  on  '  'Linguistic  Stocks' ' 
in  the  "Hand  book  of  American  Indians  North  of  Mexico"  (Washington, 
Vol.  I,  1907)  and  in  the  article  on  "North  American  Indians"  in  the  forth- 
coming new  edition  of  the  "Encyclopedia  Britannica."  Dr.  Finck,  how- 
ever, notes  some  of  these  latter  results,  e.  g.,  the  inclusion  of  the  Adaizan 
with  the  Caddoan,  the  Piman  with  Uto-Aztecan,  etc.  The  latest  researches  of 
Lehmann  in  the  Central  American  region  seem  likely  to  lead  to  some  changes 
in  the  arrangement  of  the  linguistic  stocks  between  Mexico  and  Panama. 
To  the  linguistic  stocks  of  South  America  the  writer  of  this  review  has 
devoted  considerable  attention,  and  a  monograph  on  that  subject  is  pre- 
paring for  publication.  Dr.  Finck's  list  of  South  American  stocks,  while, 
of  course,  not  exhaustive,  takes  in  such  comparatively  recent  items  as  the 
recognition  as  independent  forms  of  speech  of  the  Trumaian,  Bororoan, 
Makuan,  Miranhan,  Guatoan,  etc.  The  Onan  of  Tierra  del  Fuego  is, 
without  justification,  classed  as  a  dialect  of  Tsonekan  (Patagonian) ;  the 
evidence  in  hand  still  makes  it  necessary  to  list  it  as  an  independent  stock. 
The  independent  character  of  Atacamenan,  is  however,  recognized.  On 
the  whole,  the  list  of  South  American  stocks  is  fairly  accurate  so  far  as  it 
goes,  and  free  from  any  important  errors.  The  languages  of  the  Ethiopan 
race  include  those  of  the  Negroes  of  Africa  (Paleo-African,  i.  e.,  Bushman, 
Hottentot;  Neo- African:  Bantu,  West-Sudan,  Central-Sudan,  Nilotic,  etc.) 
and  the  Oceanic  Negroes  (Australian  andTasmanian,  Papuan,  Andamanese). 
The  most  recent  studies  of  the  linguistic  relations  of  the  peoples  of  New 
Guinea  and  adjacent  islands  will  necessitate  some  modifications  of  the  lists 
in  this  region.  In  the  introduction  the  author  touches  upon  the  question 
of  the  hrnnan  "Ursprache,"  but  wisely  remarks  in  conclusion  (p.  7)  "dis- 
cussion of  the  temporal  sequence  of  the  various  linguistic  stocks  is  im- 
possible, and  even  the  degree  of  their  antiquity  cannot  be  settled,  since  we 
are  altogether  ignorant  of  the  supposed  unitary  primitive  tongue  of  all  man- 
kind." In  the  second  volmne  on  "the  Chief  Types  of  Language,"  Professor 
Finck  selects  and  discusses,  with  considerable  detail,  the  grammatical  and 
morphological  peculiarities  and  characteristics  of  types  of  human  languages 
(Chinese,  Greenland  Eskimo,  Subija, — a  language  of  the  Zambezi  region  in 
South  Africa,  Samoan,  Arabian,  Greek  and  Georgian  of  the  Caucasus). 
These  eight  languages  are  treated  as  "typical  representatives  of  eight 
groups,  to  which,  in  my  opinion,  can  without  any  great  violence,  be  assigned 
the  languages  of  the  whole  earth  (p.  v.)."  If  one  takes  as  criterion  the 
idea-content  of  the  word,  these  languages,  "with  the  gradual  strength- 
ening of  the  fragmentary  character  and  the  increasing  morselizing  of  the 
idea  masses  present  before  the  beginning  of  speaking,"  the  languages  in 
question  can  be  arranged  in  the  following  order:  Eskimo,  Turkish,  Georgic, 
Arabic,  Chinese,  Greek,  Samoan,  Subija.  From  another  point  of  view, 
that  of  the  organization  of  the  elements  of  the  sentence,  etc.,  quite  another 
order  is  necessary,  and  Dr.  Finck  distinguishes  them  thus:  Root-isolat- 
ing (Chinese),  stem-isolating  (Samoan),  root-inflecting  (Arabic),  stem- 
inflecting  (Greek),  group-inflecting  (Georgic),  subordinating  (Turkish), 
incorporating    (Eskimo),    and    ordinating    (Subija).     ^till   other   arrange- 


122  BOOK   REVIEWS 

ments,  from  other  points  of  view  are  of  course  possible.  The  difficulties 
of  such  a  type-theory  as  that  set  forth  by  Professor  Finck  are  apparent 
from  consideration  of  the  languages  of  the  Old  World,  but  they  multiply 
and  intensify  themselves  when  the  linguistic  stocks  of  the  New  World  are 
carefully  examined.  The  "Handbook  of  American  Indian  Languages 
North  of  Mexico,"  soon  to  be  published  by  the  Bureau  of  American  Eth- 
nology, under  the  competent  editorship  of  Dr.  Franz  Boas,  will,  for  the  first 
time,  present  accurate  and  convincing  evidence  upon  many  points  connected 
with  the  speech-types  of  the  aborigines  of  the  United  States  and  Canada. 
Suffice  it  to  say,  for  the  present,  that  the  Eskimo  of  Greenland  can  hardly 
serve  as  representative  for  all  the  Indian  tongues  of  that  region,  much  less 
for  all  those  others  of  Mexico,  Central  and  South  America  as  well.  Under 
any  system  of  type-listing  there  must  be  many  more  than  one  type  among 
the  many  scores  of  linguistic  stocks  hving  and  dead  in  primitive  America. 
A  valuable  part  of  this  volume,  and  one  especially  interesting  to  psycholo- 
gists, will  be  found  in  the  analyses  of  texts  accompanying  the  discussion  of 
each  linguistic  type.  The  first  volume  has  an  exhaustive  index,  and  the 
presence  of  one  of  some  sort  would  not  have  injured  the  second, 

Alexander  F.  Chamberlain. 

Studies  in  Spiritism,  by  Amy  E.  Tanner,  Ph,  D,,  with  an  introduction 
by  G.  Stanley  Hall,  Ph.  D„  LL.  D.  New  York,  Appleton,  1910. 
408  pp. 

This  volume  records  the  findings  and  verdict  of  a  patient  investigation 
sustained  by  a  scientific  conscience  and  enthusiasm.  It  represents  con- 
structively a  logical  interpretation  of  a  group  of  phenomena  whose  psycho- 
logical importance,  though  distinctive,  seems  modest  when  compared  with 
the  far-reaching  conclusions  attached  to  them  by  the  popular  verdict 
in  favor  of  the  supernatural.  The  convincing  emphasis  of  the  book  is 
its  indication  that  the  "psychic  research"  platform  is  not  only  logically 
inadequate  but  psychologically  perverse. 

While  the  psychology  of  Paladino  has  been  relegated  to  the  limbo  of 
fraud  and  credulity,  the  psychology  of  Mrs.  Piper  remains;  for  there 
seems  no  doubt  that  her  sittings,  whatever  their  more  subtle  or  question- 
able implications,  represent  distinct  if  evasive  phases  of  a  secondary 
personality.  Therein  lies  their  interest,  and  not  in  their  supposed  evi- 
dential revelations.  For  exhibiting  clearly  and  with  illustrative  detail  the 
evidence  that  mediumistic  trance  is  psychologically  a  form  of  lightly  or 
deeply  held  secondary  personality.  Dr.  Hall  and  Miss  Tanner  deserve 
credit  and  gratitude.  Though  the  position, — and  it  would  be  surprising 
to  find  it  otherwise, — has  been  favored  and  presented  by  other  psycholo- 
gists, it  has  not  as  yet  received  so  clear  a  statement,  so  full  a  demonstra- 
tion, nor  indeed  so  original  an  exposition. 

It  is  difficult  soberly  to  take  space  to  recount  the  endless  records  by  which 
the  advocates  of  Mrs,  Piper's  supernormal  powers  support  their  claim. 
In  the  "test"  messages  some  objective  control  is  exercised;  and  complex 
coincidences, — difficult,  if  not  impossible  to  appraise, — enter  to  make 
or  mar  the  case.  Miss  Tanner  pursues  the  only  way  open  to  the  dauntless 
critic:  she  analyzes  the  incidents,  lays  bare  the  constant  sources  of  error, 
the  looseness  of  interpretation,  the  ready  play  of  chance,  and  with  the 
structure  thus  stripped  of  prejudicial  veneer  she  displays  its  card-board 
architecture.  For  the  apologetics  that  have  been  used  to  make  coinci- 
dence startling,  and  to  read  mysteries  into  commonplace  trifles  are  no 
less  amazing  when  one  considers  the  intellectual  standing  of  the  protago- 
nists. The  psychological  transgression  is  no  less  astounding;  the  credence 
given  to  long-range  memories,  the  scant  appreciation  of  the  efficiency 
of  suggestion,  the  neglect  of  control  experiments,  as  well  as  the  amateurish 
attitude  towards  such  every-day  foibles  as  "fishing,"  fooling,  and  lying, 
arouse  pity  or  irritation,  according  to  temperament. 


BOOK   REVIEWS  123 

Yet  the  great  bulk  of  the  "evidence"  is  of  yet  looser  construction, 
and  depends  upon  the  presumption  that  Mrs.  Piper's  inspired  hand  can 
write  messages  revealing  details  that  the  terrestrial  Mrs.  Piper  could 
not  normally  have  acquired.  Once  more  the  truth  is  simple.  It  is  abun- 
dantly clear  that  Mrs.  Piper's  auditory  centres  are  keenly  alert  when  her 
eyes  are  closed  in  trance;  her  surviving  consciousness  listens  acutely, 
"fishes"  adroitly,  and  her  reeling  in  to  suit  the  sporting  impulses  of  the 
victim  is  nothing  less  than  professional.  As  in  dreams,  the  subject  un- 
wittingly contributes  the  data  for  the  solution,  and  then  marvels  at  the 
revelation  when  it  appears.  As  for  the  spiritual  hypothesis,  why  not 
be  frank  and  say  with  Dr.  Hall:  "It  is  an  utter  psychological  impossibility 
to  treat  this  subject  seriously." 

Mrs.  Piper  pretends  to  be  controlled  by  the  actual  disembodied  Richard 
Hodgson.  Not  only,  however,  does  the  latter  fail  to  prove  his  identity, 
but  he  is  vSuggestible,  ignorant,  inconsequential  and  Piperian.  With 
alacrity  he  summoned  from  the  spirit-world  wholly  fictitious  personages, 
as  well  as  the  shades  of  the  known  departed;  he  fell  into  the  most  simple 
logical  traps,  and  through  Mrs.  Piper's  organism  exhibited  pique  and  ill- 
temper  at  being  exposed, — quite  out  of  the  r61e  of  the  shrewd  exposer  of 
mystery  that  Hodgson  was.  A  few  whiffs  of  this  atmosphere  sends  one 
back  gasping  to  the  fresh  air.  '  'Spiritism  is  the  ruck  and  muck  of  modem 
culture,  the  common  enemy  of  true  science  and  of  true  religion;  and  to 
drain  its  dismal  and  miasmatic  marshes  is  the  great  work  of  modem  culture. 

We  have  largely  evicted  superstition  from  the  physical 

universe,  which  used  to  be  the  dumping-ground  of  the  miraculous.  Super- 
stition to-day  has  its  strongest  hold  in  the  dark  terrae  incognitae  of  the 
unconscious  soul  of  man  towards  which  researchers  to-day  are  just  as 
superstitious  as  savages  are  towards  lightning,  eclipses,  comets  and  earth- 
quakes." 

Taking  seriously  the  proposition  that  telepathy  is  supported  by  pre- 
monitions and  experiments,  that  trance  messages  really  foretell  the  future 
and  reveal  the  past,  that  the  controls  of  mediums  bring  back  credentials 
which  are  adequate  for  the  identification  of  the  recently  departed,  psy- 
chology accepts  the  challenge  and  undertakes  to  show  that  a  pervasive 
bias  and  a  defective  insight  have  shaped  the  data  to  distorted  or  imaginary 
significance.  The  evidence  for  this  position  cannot  be  summarized. 
Those  who  are  interested  in  acquiring  a  hold  upon  it  have  now  available 
Miss  Tanner's  presentation.  On  the  other  hand,  recognizing  that  sub- 
conscious abnormalities  arise  spontaneously,  and  grow  by  what  they  feed 
upon,  psychology  finds  in  the  encouragement  given  to  the  medium's 
sittings,  in  the  serious  systematic  acceptance  of  the  spiritistic  hypothesis, 
and  in  the  devout  personal  reactions  of  sitters,  the  hot-house  atmosphere 
and  the  coddling  ministration  that  such  parasitic  growths  absorb. 
The  conspicuous  suggestibility  of  such  temperaments  makes  them  assume 
the  forms  that  excite  interest  and  claim  attention.  They  are  allied  to  a 
recognized  group  of  hysterical  manifestations  in  the  nearly  normal,  which 
in  turn  grow  to  troublesome  intmsion  or  withdraw  to  manageable  control 
according  to  the  wisdom  and  insight  with  which  they  are  met.  The 
modern  attitude  towards  such  phenomena  is  a  therapeutic  one.  The 
mediumistic  or  secondary  personality  is  to  be  appeased,  persuaded,  sup- 
pressed, and  the  patient's  resources  united  and  made  to  see  and  to  live 
life  steadily  and  whole.  Such  a  consummation  can  never  be,  if  the  ab- 
normality is  displayed,  cherished,  and  embraced  as  a  means  of  livelihood. 

Dr.  Hall  is  confident  that  '  'the  mysteries  of  our  psychic  being  are  bound 
ere  long  to  be  cleared  up.  Every  one  of  these  ghostly  phenomena  will 
be  brought  under  the  domain  of  law.  The  present  recrudescence  here 
of  ancient  faiths  in  the  supernatural  is  very  interesting  as  a  psychic  atavism, 
as  the  last  flashing  up  of  a  group  of  old  psychoses  soon  to  become  extinct. 


124  BOOK   REVIEWS 

When  genetic  psychology  has  done  its  work,  all  these  psychic  researches  will 
take  their  places  among  the  solemn  absurdities  in  the  history  of  thought; 
and  the  instincts  which  prompted  them  will  be  recognized  as  only  psychic 
rudimentary  organs  that  ought  to  be  and  will  be  left  to  atrophy.  " 
University  of  Wisconsin.  Joseph  Jastrow. 

The  Metaphysics  of  a  Naturalist;  Philosophical  and  Psychological  Fragments. 
By  the  late  C.  L.  Herrick.  Bulletin  of  the  Scientific  Laboratories 
of  Denison  University,  Vol.  XV.  Granville,  Ohio,  1910.  99  pp. 
This  book  aims  to  supplement  and,  to  some  extent,  to  unify  such  of  the 
distinctive  philosophical  teachings  of  Professor  Herrick  as  have  already 
been  published,  by  adding  to  them  and  correlating  with  them  material 
brought  together  from  papers  and  manuscripts  hitherto  unpubhshed. 
The  first  chapter  is  entitled  "The  Summation-Irradiation  Theory  of 
Pleasure-Pain."  It  gives  an  analysis  of  feeling  and  of  emotion,  and 
explains  them  in  terms  of  physiological  tensions  and  adjustments,  basing 
the  arguments  on  bodily  structure  and  function  and  upon  introspection. 
There  is  also  included  a  table  of  the  other  classes  of  mental  processes, 
with  their  physiological  parallels.  At  the  end  of  the  book  are  four  short, 
less  technical  and  less  distinctive,  chapters  on  the  freedom  of  the  will, 
the  problem  of  evil,  immortality,  and  ethical  conclusions.  The  book  is 
chiefly  concerned  to  present  the  metaphysical  theory  of  dynamic  monism, 
and  to  explain,  in  terms  of  this  theory,  the  concept  of  consciousness,  the 
relation  of  mind  and  body,  individuality,  matter,  life,  etc.  Some  of  the 
fundamental  conclusions  are:  Existence  (being)  and  energy  are  identical; 
Energy  is  pure  spontaniety;  Unimpeded  infinite  energy  would  seem  to  us 
indistinguishable  from  non-existence;  Force  arises  from  the  interference 
of  energy,  and  implies  resistance;  The  complexity  of  resistance  measures 
the  quality  of  the  force,  the  degree  of  resistance  measures  the  quantity 
of  the  force;  Matter  is  a  subjective  interpretation  of  forces  in  a  state  of 
relative  equilibrium;  Consciousness  is  the  focussing  of  diverse  forces  upon 
the  complicated  neural  equilibrium;  Conscious  states  are  epiphenomena, 
due  to  the  constant  becoming  between  energy  and  force.  The  writer 
makes  frequent  reference  to  the  theories  and  results  of  the  natural  sciences, 
especially  those  of  physics,  physiology,  and  mathematics,  and  he  takes 
over  into  his  metaphysics,  almost  directly,  such  scientific  concepts  as 
inertia,  resistance,  motion,  energy,  vortices,  vectors,  etc.  According  to 
the  editors,  the  book  is  intended  as  a  contribution  to  work  on  the  method- 
ology of  the  sciences,  of  the  sort  done  by  Tyndall,  Huxley,  Kelvin, 
Helmholtz,  Mach  and  Ostwald.  W.  S.  Foster. 

Les  rSves  et  leur  interpretation.     Par  Paui^  MeuniBr  et  Rene  Masselon. 

(Collection  Psychologic  Exeprimentale  et  de    Metapsychie).    Bloud 

et  Cie,  Paris,  19 10.  211  p. 
This  is  an  essay  in  morbid  psychology,  both  of  the  authors  being  psy- 
chiatrists. The  first  chapter,  entitled  the  psychological  mechanism  of 
dreams,  gives  a  partial  resume  of  the  scientific  literature  of  dreams,  chiefly 
of  French  work,  supplemented  by  contributions  from  the  authors'  own 
observations.  The  second  chapter  discusses  the  diagnostic  value  of  dreams. 
V/hile  there  is  much  difficulty  in  distinguishing  the  truly  prodromic  or 
symptomatic  dream  from  accidental  dreams  without  pathological  signifi- 
cance, the  authors,  nevertheless,  conclude  that  dreams  are  in  some  cases 
of  considerable  value  in  diagnosis  and  the  following  chapters  are  devoted 
to  a  discussion  of  the  distinguishing  characteristics  of  dreams  in  infections 
and  intoxications,  neuroses  and  insanities,  which  have  diagnostic  signifi- 
cance, e.  g.,  the  color,  red,  persistently  appearing  in  dreams  is  a  frequent 
phenomenon  in  premenstrual  periods,  cardiac  affections,  premeningeal 
attacks,  inflammatory  infections  of  the  eye  and  the  aura  of  epileptic  attacks. 
Terrifying  hallucinations   and    zooscopy  are  characteristic  not  only  of 


BOOK  RKVmWS  125 

alcoholism  but  are  liable  to  occur  in  all   toxic   affections.     Stereoptyped 
dreams  occur  in  epilepsy  and  hysteria. 

In  psychoses,  the  dream  may  reveal  an  obsession  or  an  impulsive  tendency 
before  it  has  been  manifested  in  the  waking  state.  Finally,  in  mental 
pathology  the  persistence  of  dreams  is  a  sign  of  the  manifest  activity  of 
morbid  processes  and  in  convalescence,  the  type  of  dreams  may  be  of  great 
importance  for  determining  the  state  of  the  patient. 

The  book  is  disappointing  in  that  it  takes  no  account  of  Freud's 
Traumdeutung  or  of  De  Sanctis'  later  work,  by  far  the  two  most  important 
contributions  to  the  psychology  of  dreams  and  without  consideration  of 
which  any  discussion  of  the  subject  must  be  inadequate. 

Theodatb  L.  Smith. 

L'  annie  psychologique,  publiee  par  Alfri^d  BinET.  Paris,  Masson,  19 10. 
500  p.  Seizieme  annee. 
Besides  the  usual  literature,  the  author  himself  has  monographs  upon 
the  physical  signs  of  intelligence,  on  Rembrandt  in  relation  to  the  new 
style  of  art  criticism,  the  mental  states  of  the  insane;  while  with  Simon 
he  gives  us  an  extensive  study  of  hysteria  and  on  insanity  with  conscious- 
ness of  it,  of  the  maniacal  depressive  type,  the  systematized  form,  and 
dementia,  retardation,  formulating  a  new  classification.  Finally  comes 
a  brief  article  on  judicial  diagnostics,  while  the  bibliography  occupies 
pages  382  to  500. 

A     beginner's    history    of    philosophy,    by    Herbert  Ernest  Cushman. 

V.  I .     Ancient  and  mediaeval  philosophy.     Boston,  Houghton,  Mifflin 

(1910).  406  p. 
This  work  is  dedicated  to  Professor  Palmer  and  is  intended  as  a  text- 
book for  sketch-courses  in  the  history  of  philosophy.  It  is  for  the  student 
rather  than  the  teacher;  and  is  written  on  the  background  of  geography 
and  literary  and  political  history  and  uses  many  tables.  The  present 
volume  begins  with  the  early  Greeks  and  ends  with  Ockham. 

Psychologie  des  Kindes,  von  Robert  Gaupp.  2d  enl.  ed.  Leipzig, 
Teubner,  19 10.  163  p. 
This  work  is  divided  into  three  parts.  The  first  treats  the  psychology 
of  the  little  child,  beginning  with  a  brief  historical  sketch  of  child  psychol- 
ogy, a  discussion  of  its  methods,  literature,  the  development  of  the  first 
year  of  attention,  speech,  Gemtit,  will,  thought,  lies,  impulses,  sense  play, 
etc.  The  second  part  is  on  the  psychology  of  the  school  child,  beginning 
with  entrance,  and  discussing  memory,  attention,  power  of  achievement 
and  control,  fatigue,  power  of  jtidgment,  writing,  the  child  and  its  relations 
to  art.     The  third  part  treats  of  children  who  are  psychically  abnormal. 

Trick  methods  of  Eusapia  Palladino,  by  Stanley  LE  Fevre  Krebs.  Re- 
printed from  The  Reformed  Church  Review,  Vol.  XIV,  July,  1910. 
Phila.,  1910.  p.  331-3^3- 
This  author  concludes  that  Palladino  uses  no  confederate,  that  there 
are  no  traps  or  sliding  panels,  that  all  her  phenomena  are  produced  in  an 
area  within  the  stretch  of  her  arm  or  leg,  certainly  if  lengthened  a  little 
by  the  use  of  a  flower  stand  as  a  reacher  and  a  shoe-ledge  as  a  fulcrum  for 
levitation.  The  author  does  not  believe  that  she  has  any  extraordinary 
or  telekinetic  power.  If  she  had  she  ought  to  be  '  'lifted  out  of  the  realm 
of  showdom;"  nor  does  he  believe  that  the  hypothesis  of  survival  after 
death  will  be  proven  by  any  phenomena  like  hers.  It  is  all  a  deception 
of  sight  and  touch,  '  'the  psychological  atmosphere  being  helped  along  by 
intentional  suggestions."  She  always  dresses  ii;  black  and  her  cabinet 
is  painted  black  inside ;  he  would  have  her  dress  in  white.  He  thinks,  too, 
that  if  she  were  placed  at  the  broadside  of  a  table  and  had  only  one  per- 


126  BOOK  REVIEWS 

son  control  both  her  hands  and  both  her  feet,  "John,"  her  control,  would 
be  put  out  of  business.  He  would  tie  her  ankles  and  wrists  with  a  slack 
of  only  four  or  five  inches,  but  none  of  these  she  will  allow, 

ijber  Ermii  dungs stoffe,  von  Wolfgang  WeichardT.  Stuttgart,  Enke, 
1910.  66  p. 
This  is  an  interesting  and  compendious  account  of  the  large  subject 
treated.  Symptoms  of  extreme  general  fatigue  are  first  described;  then 
the  fatigue  of  special  parts  and  organs,  investigations  on  immuni^  and 
fatigue  stuffs,  the  attempts  to  apply  chemical  and  physical  means  to 
muscle  extraction  and  to  albumen,  how  kenotoxine  can  be  influenced, 
active  immunization,  anti-somatic  influences,  how  pathological  processes 
can  be  influenced  by  antikenotoxine. 

An  introduction  to  the  study  of  hypnotism,  experimental  and  therapeutic, 
by  H.  E.  WiNGFiELD.  London,  Bailli^re,  Tindall  &  Cox,  1910.  175  p. 
This  book  is  an  attempt  to  supply  a  simple  answer  to  the  question 
What  is  hypnotism?  and  makes  no  effort  to  range  itself  with  the  many 
larger  works  on  the  subject  but  intends  rather  to  serve  as  an  introduction 
to  these.  The  matter  is  treated  mainly  from  the  experimental  point  of 
view  and  the  author  does  not  attempt  to  include  anything  that  those 
already  familiar  with  the  subject  did  not  already  know.  Its  chapters  are 
on  the  subconscious,  the  methods  of  inducing  hypnosis,  its  phenomena 
and  stages,  other  hysterical  phenomena,  treatment  by  suggestion,  and 
the  case  against  hypnotism. 

The  concept  standard,  a  historical  survey  of  what  men  have  conceived  as 
constituting  or  determining  life  values ;  criticism  and  interpretation  of 
the  different  theories.     By  Anne  M.  Nicholson.     Teachers  College 
Columbia  University  Contributions  to  Education,  No.  29.     New  York, 
Teachers  College,   19 10.     138  p. 
The  chapters  are :  the  fundamental  categories  and  principles,  the  standard 
in  primitive  societies  and  the  genetic  point  of  view,  review  of  the  concep- 
tion of  the  standard  and  its  method  of  functioning  from  the  first  historic 
to  present   time,   standard  as  conceived   in  epochs  Judaean,   Medieval, 
Renaissance,  Protestantism,  Cartesian,  the  English  School,  German  ideal- 
ism, the  materialistic  concept  of  this  standard,  its  function  in  national 
crises. 

A  text-book  of  psychology,  by  Edward  Bradford  Titchener.  New  York* 
Macmillan  Company,  19 10.  565  p. 
This  work  was  written  to  take  the  place  of  the  author's  Outlines  of 
Psychology  in  1896  which  has  passed  beyond  the  possibility  of  revision. 
Still  it  follows  the  general  lines  laid  down  in  the  Outline,  although  with 
less  space  devoted  to  nervous  physiology.  The  work  in  its  present  form 
will  be  gratefully  received  by  teachers  and  it  is  unquestionably  the  best 
in  its  own  specific,  if  restricted,  field. 

The  qualities  of  men,  by  Joseph  Jastrow.  Boston,  Houghton,  Mifflin  Co., 
1910.  183  p. 
A  study  of  the  qualities  of  men  in  which  a  physiological  interest  in 
humanity  is  prominent  may  properly  be  expected  to  undertake  the  analysis 
of  the  fundamental  factors  in  human  nature,  their  transformation,  values 
in  growth,  education  and  vocation.  This  is  the  basal  problem  in  the 
psychology  of  human  traits.  For  the  elucidation  of  this  theme,  the  author 
is  preparing  a  work  entitled  Character  and  Temperament,  but  in  the  prepa- 
ration for  this  work  he  found  the  more  general  bearing  of  the  problems  of 
human  quality  of  growing  importance  and  felt  the  need  of  a  more  general 
form  and  statement  and  a  wider  appeal.  Hence  this  book,  the  chapters 
of  which  are  the  sensibilities,  the  ideals  of  appreciation,  the  support  of  the 


BOOK   REVIEWS  127 

sensibilities,  the  analysis  of  quality,  quality  in  circumstance,  compatibili- 
ties of  quality,  the  poietic  qualities,  the  social  encouragement  of  quality, 
its  upper  ranges,  its  interactions  with  environment,  its  relation  to  careers 
and  the  realm  of  practice. 

Die  Phantasie  nach  ihrem  Wesen  und  ihrer  Bedeutung  fur  das  Geistesleberi' 
von  A.  ScHOPPA.  Leipzig,  Diirr,  1909.  144  p. 
The  chief  topics  here  are  the  essence  of  phantasy,  its  relations  to  psychic 
life,  with  a  good  section  on  the  playing,  speaking,  narrating,  drawing, 
child,  on  the  instruction  of  the  fancy  in  childhood,  phantasy  in  everyday 
life,  in  poetry,  rhyme,  rhythm,  saga,  legend,  idyll,  romance,  fable,  drama, 
phantasy  in  music,  in  the  plastic  arts,  in  science,  and  finally  in  religion. 
The  author's  psychology  is  mainly  under  the  influence  of  Wundt,  Lipps 
and  Mach. 

Die   Sinnesorgane   der   Pflanzen,   von   G.  Haberlandt.     Sonderabdruck 

aus  der  vierten  Auflage  der  physiologischen  Pflanzenanatomie,  S.   520- 

573.     Leipzig,  Engelmann,  1909. 

This  reprint  is  an  excellent  little  epitome  of  its  subject,  discussing  the 

relations  of  the  organ  to  the  stimulus,  with  many  cuts  of  sensory  hairs, 

bristles,  statoliths,  stalks,  leaves,  with  experimental  observations  on  the 

connection  of  statoliths  and  geopterception.     The  writer  discusses  the 

light  sense  in  leaves,  the  nature  of  their  papillary  epidermis  and  of  optical 

spots,  etc. 

The  metabolism  and  energy  transformations  of  healthy  man  during  rest, 
by  Francis  G.  Benedict  and  Thorne  M.  Carpenter.     Washington, 
Carnegie  Institution,   19 10.     255  p. 
The  first  part  of  this  book  is  introductory,  telling  what  has  been  done 
before  and  elsewhere.     The  second  is  statistics  of  experiments;  and  the 
third  and  most  elaborate  is  the  discussion  of  results,  which  are  not,  un- 
fortunately for  the  reader,  summarized. 

Der  Traum  und  seine  Deutung,  nebst  erkldrten  Traumbeispielen,  von  E.  J.  G. 
Stumpf.  Leipzig,  Mutze,  1899.  188  p. 
This  book,  although  not  new,  may  have  a  certain  added  interest  just 
now  on  account  of  the  prominence  which  the  problem  of  dream  psychology 
has  assumed  in  this  country  owing  to  the  recent  influence  of  Freud.  Stumpf 
treats  in  the  successive  chapters,  day  and  night  in  their  reciprocal  rela- 
tions, and  the  nature  and  essence  of  dreams.  These  are  the  two  sections 
of  the  book.  If  the  author  had  designed  to  block  every  one's  endeavor 
to  get  at  the  root  idea  of  his  treatment  without  reading  every  sentence 
in  the  book,  he  could  hardly  have  succeeded  better,  for  there  is  no  index 
or  titles  of  any  kind,  apparently  no  summaries  or  epitomes,  nothing  itali- 
cized; so  that  as  it  is  the  book  stands  like  a  castle,  attractive  outside  and 
doubtless  full  of  good  things  within,  but  open  under  no  conditions  to 
casual  visitors  but  only  those  who  desire  to  reside  in  it. 

first  book  in  psychology,  by  Mary  Whiton  Cai^kins.  New  York, 
Macmillan,   19 10.     419  p. 

This  book  is  written  under  a  growing  conviction  that  psychology  is 
2st  treated  as  a  study  of  conscious  selves  in  relation  to  other  selves  and 

outer  objects.  This  book  differs  from  an  introduction  to  psychology, 
rith  which  it  is  liable  to  be  confounded,  for  here  the  approach  is  simpler 
id  more  direct.  In  the  former  book,  psychology  is  treated  both  as  a 
nence  of  selves  and  of  ideas  and  all  is  discussed  from  both  points  of  view, 
[ere  the  double  treatment  is  abandoned.     Here,  too,  the  author  has  tried 

embody  the  results  of  functional  psychology,  that  is,  taking  an  account 

bodily  reactions  and  environment  which  accompany  thought,  feeling 
id  will.     An  appendix,  too,  treats  of  the  physiology  of  the  nervous  system 


128  BOOK  REVIEWS 

and  the  senses  and  abnormalities.  "This  is,  then,  a  new  book,  not  the 
condensation  of  an  old  one,  yet  it  does  not  teach  a  new  form  of  psychology," 
The  chief  sections  here  are,  methods  and  uses,  perception  and  imagination, 
other  sensory  elements,  their  combinations  and  differentiations,  effect, 
attention,  productive  imagination,  memory,  selective  association,  recogni- 
tion, thought,  conception,  judgment,  reason,  emotion,  will,  faith  and  belief, 
the  social  and  religious  consciousness.  The  appendix  includes  pages  273 
to  417. 

Straight  goods  in  philosophy,  by  Paul  Karishka.  New  York,  Roger 
Brothers,  1910.  207  p. 
This  name,  we  take,  it,  is  a  pseudonym.  The  author,  who  has  already 
written  several  other  very  stimulating  but  inadequately  appreciated  works, 
is  evidently  a  thinker  born  and  trained.  He  here  gives  up  the  more  erudite 
subtleties  of  metaphysics  and  speaks  to  the  plain  man  and  tells  him  that 
philosophy  simply  means  wisdom  in  work.  It  is  really  impossible  to  give 
an  adequate  conception  of  this  work,  which  certainly  shows  a  very  wide 
repertoire  of  insights  and  interests  on  the  author's  part.  It  has  nearly 
forty  chapters.  Some  of  them  are  loving  everybody,  the  professional 
philosophy,  healing  the  body  by  mind,  posing,  the  things  we  hate,  sympa- 
thy, the  funeral  of  a  living  corpse,  weeds,  man  and  woman,  thoughts  that 
kill,  food,  why  women  are  sly,  old  age,  the  law  of  opposites,  privileged 
people,  the  essentials  of  a  philosophic  life.  The  book  is  certainly  original, 
suggestive  and  stimulating. 

Educational  psychology,  by  Edward  L.  Thorndiku.  2d  ed.,  rev.  &  enl. 
Teachers  College,  Columbia  University,  N.  Y.,  1910.  248  p. 
This  book  is  a  revision  of  a  work  which  appeared  in  1903.  Its  primary 
purpose  is  to  provide  students  in  advanced  courses  in  educational  psychol- 
ogy with  the  material  which  thej'  would  otherwise  have  to  get  at  lectures 
at  great  time  and  cost.  The  author  has  admitted  the  influence  of  special 
training  upon  more  general  abilities.  He  treats  the  measurement  of  in- 
dividual differences,  the  influence  of  sex,  of  remote  ancestory  or  race,  of 
immediate  ancestry  or  family,  of  maturity  and  environment,  the  nature 
and  amount  of  individual  differences  in  single  traits,  the  relation  betvvreen 
the  amounts  of  different  traits  in  the  same  individual,  the  nature  and  amount 
of  individual  differences  in  combinations  of  traits,  types  of  intellect  and 
character,  extreme  individual  differences,  and  exceptional  children,  with 
several  appendixes. 

The  World  a  Spiritual  System.  An  outline  of  metaphysics.  By  JamBS 
H.  Snowden.  N.  Y.,  Macmillan,  1910.  316  p. 
The  author  is  evidently  in  an  apologetic  state  of  mind,  at  least  in  his 
preface,  quoting  various  definitions  of  metaphysics,  such  as  "a  blind  man 
looking  on  a  dark  night  for  a  black  cat  that  isn't  there."  However  he 
tells  us  that  the  difficulties  and  the  confusion  are  more  apparent  than  real. 
He  discusses  in  successive  chapters  the  nature  of  metaphysics,  including 
its  definition,  method,  assumptions,  spirit,  object  and  system.  He  then 
discusses  the  different  points  of  view  from  which  the  world  is  regarded, 
viz.:  from  that  of  plain  men,  the  scientist  and  the  metaphysician;  the 
subjectivity  of  space,  with  its  theory  and  reasons,  that  of  time,  subjec- 
tive reality,  the  soul's  knowledge  of  itself,  its  fundamental  character, 
general  character;  how  we  reach  objective  reality;  its  nature,  including 
the  world  as  phenomenon;  as  life,  as  thought,  sensibility,  will,  the  general 
character  of  the  world  and  man  as  its  key.  Then  follow  the  relations  of 
the  world  and  God  as  revealed  as  cause  in  its  relations  to  man,  and  finally 
the  applications  of  idealism  as  seen  in  the  relations  of  mind  and  body,  im- 
mortality, problem  of  evil,  ideahsm  in  religion  and  Hfe,  with  a  brief  sug- 
gestive course  of  reading  and  some  account  of  the  chief  modern  writers 
upon  these  subjects. 


BOOK   REVmWS  129 

Tlie  use  of  the  Theory  of  Correlation  in  Psychology.     WiIvLiam  Brown,  Cam- 
bridge, Printed  privately  at  the  University  Press,  19 10.     p.  83. 
Some  Experimental  Results  in  the  Correlation  of  Mental  Abilities.     William 

Brown.     The  Journal  of  Psychology,  Vol.  3,  1910,  296-322. 
An  objective  Study  of  Mathematical  Intelligence.     William  Brown.     Bio- 

metrica.  Vol.  7,  1910,  p.  352-367/ 
The  use  of  the  Theory  of  Correlation  in  Psychology.  William  Brown. 
Cambridge.  Printed  privately  at  the  University  Press,  1910.  p.  83. 
The  paper,  which  is  a  doctor's  thesis,  consists  of  three  parts,  the  first  of 
which  contains  an  exposition  of  the  theory  of  correlation,  the  second  the  his- 
tory of  the  use  to  which  this  theory  has  been  put  in  psychology,  and  the  third 
the  description  of  a  series  of  investigations  undertaken  by  the  author.  The 
third  part  has  appeared  separately  under  the  title  "Some  Experimental 
Results  in  the  Correlation  of  Mental  Abilities"  in  the  British  Journal  of 
Psychology,  1910,  Vol.  3,  p.  296-322. 

Starting  from  the  notion  of  the  regression  curve  and  regression  line  the 
author  develops  formulae  for  the  coefficient  of  correlation,  for  the  correla- 
tion ratio,  for  the  probable  errors  and  for  multiple  correlation  and  then  pro- 
ceeds to  discuss  some  other  methods  of  measuring  correlation.  The  method 
of  ranks  and  its  critisicm  by  Pearson  is  discussed  in  some  detail.  Pear- 
son's objections  against  this  method  are  directed  (i.)  against  the  use  of 
rank  as  a  quantitative  measure  of  character,  and  (2.)  against  the  formulae 
derived  by  Spearman,  for  which  new  ones  are  substituted.  Rank  must 
not  be  used  as  a  quantitative  measure  of  character,  because  this  assumes 
that  the  unit  of  rank  is  the  same  throughout  the  scale,  which  is  not  the  case 
since  the  unit  of  rank  between  mediocrities  is  practically  zero,  while  it  is 
very  large  between  extreme  individuals.  This  argument  of  Pearson  gains 
additional  interest  in  view  of  Cattell's  classification  of  men  of  science 
according  to  ranks  attributed  to  them  by  a  number  of  more  or  less  prominent 
men.  If  Pearson's  argument  should  turn  out  to  be  correct,  the  suppo- 
sition for  averaging  the  ranks  attributed  to  the  same  man  in  the  different 
classifications  are  not  given.  Brown's  short  presentation  of  the  theory 
of  correlation  is  all  the  more  significant,  because  it  carries  with  it  the  author- 
ity of  Pearson  who  read  the  proof.  The  notation  used  is  the  one  cus- 
tomary in  biometric  treatises,  which  is  perhaps  not  the  most  fortunate.  The 
difficulties  for  the  reader  increase,  if  new  signs  are  introduced  without 
definition,  as  happens  to  be  the  case  on  p.  7. 

Brown's  discussion  of  the  significance  of  the  coefficient  of  correlation 
is  very  interesting.  He  insists  on  the  fact  that  this  quantity  has  a  signifi- 
cance as  a  measure  of  the  degree  of  community  or  identity  of  causation,  if 
the  regression  curve  is  linear.  He  considers  a  general  answer  as  to  the  sig- 
nificance of  the  coefficient  of  correlation  impossible,  but  he  tries  to  make  it 
clear  by  an  example  known  by  the  name  of  Weldon's  experiment.  A 
dozen  dice  are  cast  a  number  of  times  and  the  number  of  dice  showing  four 
or  more  spots  is  recorded.  The  results  of  the  ist,  3d,  5th,  .  .  .  throws 
obviously  will  be  in  no  relation  to  those  of  the  2nd,  4th,  6th,  .  .  .  throws. 
We  now  make  the  results  of  the  even  throws  dependent  on  those  of  the 
uneven.  We  stain  six  of  the  dice  red  and  we  make  the  even  throws  only  with 
the  six  white  ones,  leaving  the  red  ones  on  the  table  but  counting  indiscrimi- 
nately the  dice  which  show  four  or  more  spots.  The  results  of  the  even 
throws  will  be  correlated  to  those  of  the  uneven  throws  and  it  is  shown  that 
in  this  case  the  proportion  of  factors  common  to  the  two  series  is  given 
b}"  the  coefficient  of  correlation  itself.  This,  however,  is  an  exception  since 
the  extent  of  identity  of  causation  as  a  rule  is  measured  by  an  unknown 
function  of  the  coefficient  of  correlation.  Brown  thinks  that  "a  general 
lack  of  knowledge  of  the  mathematical  theory  of  correlation  among  psy- 
chologists" is  responsible  for  the  fact  that  in  psychology,  comparatively 

Journal — 9 


I30  BOOK  REVIEWS 

little  use  is  made  of  this  theory,  but  it  is  the  reviewer's  opinion  that  this  lack 
of  interest  may  be  attributed  largely  to  the  difficulty  of  explaining  the  real 
significance  of  the  coefficient  of  correlation.  Bruns,  Lipps  and  Lachmann 
have  supplied  examples,  where  this  quantity  is  void  of  significance  and 
almost  every  one  can  construct  examples  where  it  is  misleading.  The  special- 
ists ought  to  give  us  a  clear  presentation  of  the  theory  of  correlation  and  its 
applications  to  psychology  and  demonstrate  at  least  the  conditions  under 
which  the  extent  of  community  of  causation  is  measm-ed  by  an  uneven 
function  of  the  coefficient  of  correlation,  because  in  this  case  one  would  be 
sure  that  a  negative  value  of  the  coefficient  of  correlation  does  not  indicate 
a  positive  correlation. 

The  historical  part  of  the  paper  shows  that  the  theory  of  correlation  has 
been  used  in  psychology  chiefly  for  the  study  of  the  relation  of  different 
mental  abilities  to  one  another  and  to  general  intelligence.  The  first  in- 
vestigation showing  any  mathematical  precision  was  undertaken  by  Clark 
Wissler,  and  was  followed  by  one  by  Aikins  and  Thomdike;  the  cor- 
relations between  mental  abilities  were  generally  low.  Spearman,  instead 
of  working  on  large  groups,  took  groups  of  small  size,  making  up  for 
this  deficiency  by  subjecting  his  raw  data  to  a  mathematical  treatment. 
He  finds  a  hierarchy  among  the  different  school  subjects  and  concludes  that 
these  different  mental  activities  are  saturated  with  one  common  fundamen- 
tal function  (or  group  of  functions).  This  essential  element  in  intelligence 
is  supposed  to  coincide  with  the  essential  element  in  sensory  functions. 
Spearman's  results  were  tested  by  Thorndike,  Lay  and  Dean,  who 
concluded  from  their  results  that  there  exists  a  complex  set  of  bonds 
between  the  formal  side  of  thought  and  its  content,  and  that  there  is  nothing 
whatever  in  common  to  all  mental  functions  or  to  any  half  of  them.  C. 
Burt  confirmed  Spearman's  results  in  so  far  as  he  found  a  hierarchy 
in  the  subjects  tested,  but  he  believes  that  the  central  factor  is  voluntary 
attention.  The  author  then  mentions  the  paper  of  Pearson  on  the  re- 
lationship of  intelligence  to  physical  and  mental  characters,  the  work  of 
Miss  Elderton,  who  evaluated  the  data  collected  by  Heymans  and 
Wiersma  and  those  of  Ivahhoff,  the  later  work  of  Thomdike  and  of 
his  pupils  and  his  own  Objective  Study  of  Mathematical  Intelligence  (in 
Biometrica,  Vol.  7,  1910,  p.  352-363).  He  found  that  algebra  and  geome- 
try show  hardly  any  correlation,  a  result  which  coincides  with  the  one  ob- 
tained by  Burris  that  the  coefficients  for  the  correlation  between  algebra  and 
geometry  is  nearly  as  low  as  that  between  mathematics  and  a  non  mathe- 
matical subject. 

The  author's  own  experimental  investigations  were  undertaken  with  a 
view  of  ascertaining  the  correlation  of  certain  very  simple  mental  activ- 
ities to  one  another  and  to  general  intelligence  as  measured  by  school 
marks,  teacher's  judgments,  etc.  The  experiments  were  made  on  tolerably 
large  and  fairly  homogeneous  groups  of  students,  who  were  as  far  as  possible 
identically  situated  in  respect  to  previous  practice,  general  training  and 
intelligence.  The  tests  comprised  crossing  out  letters  (two  letters,  four 
letters  and  all  the  letters)  in  a  page  of  meaningless  words,  adding  up 
digits  in  Kraepelin's  Rechenhefte,  bisecting  and  trisecting  lines,  measuring 
the  Mueller-Lyer  and  the  vertical-horizontal  illusions,  memorizing  non- 
sense syllables  and  memorizing  poerty,  and  combination  (tested  by  the 
method  of  Ebbinghaus).  The  observation  that  a  large  proportion  of 
the  subjects  show  a  negative  vertical-horizontal  illusion  (i.  e.  underestimate 
the  vertical  line)  is  curious  and  of  interest  to  the  experimentalist  also.  The 
table  of  the  coefficients  of  correlation  shows  no  hierarchical  arrangement 
except  in  one  case  where  spurious  correlation  may  be  suspected.  Extrane- 
ous sources  of  correlation,  such  as,  e.  g.,  differences  in  the  discipline,  may 
influence  the  results  in  a  constant  direction  and  thus  produce  the  hierarchi- 
cal arrangement.  The  question  as  to  the  existence  or  non-existence  of  a 
central  function  is  not  answered  definitely,  but  a  number  of  results  may  be 


BOOK   REVIEWS  131 

taken  as  arguments  against  its  existence.  A  definite  answer  can  be  given 
only  on  the  basis  of  experiments  on  much  larger  groups,  which  will  give  re- 
sults with  smaller  probable  errors.  Brown's  results  may  be  considered  to 
bear  out  to  some  extent  the  views  of  Thomdike  and  to  contradict  those 
of  Spearman.  F.  M.  Urban. 

Der  Begriff  des  Instinktes,  einst  und  jetzt;  eine  Studie  uber  die  Geschichte  und 

die    Grundlagen    der     Tierpsychologie.     Hkinrich    Ernst    Ziegi^ER- 

Zweite,  verbesserte  und  vermehrte  Auflage.     Jena,  Gustav  Fischer. 

1910.  VI+112. 

This  book  sketches  the  historical  development  of  the  concept  of  instinct 

and  discusses  the  modem  significance  of  the  term.     The  author  points  out 

that  in  early  Greek  thought  no  sharp  distinction  was  made  between  the 

characteristics  which  were  attributed  to  human  and  to  animal  conscious- 

Iness.  But  in  the  system  of  Plato  abstract  thought  was  held  to  be  the  essen- 
tial activity  of  mind ;  since  this  capacity  cannot  be  ascribed  to  animals  a  sharp 
line  of  demarcation  was  now  drawn,  for  the  first  time,  between  the  human 
and  the  animal  mind.  And  perhaps  the  most  valuable  contribution  which 
the  author  ofters  to  his  readers  is  his  elaboration  of  the  thesis  that  ever  since 
the  time  of  Plato  there  have  existed  side  by  side,  a  tendency  to  magnify 
or  even  to  humanize  the  animal  mind,  and  a  counter-tendency  to  relegate 
it  to  a  low  level  on  the  scale  of  consciousness,  if  not  to  deny  its  existence. 
The  doctrines  of  the  Christian  church  were  influenced  by  Greek  idealism, 
and  the  Platonic  conception  of  the  animal  mind  was  appropriated  and  em- 
phasized by  the  theologians.  But  if  animals  are  wholly  lacking  in  intelli- 
gence how  is  one  to  explain  the  manifest  appropriateness  and  efficiency  of 
their  behavior^  The  question  was  answered  by  an  appeal  to  instinct, — a 
concept  which  had  been  introduced  by  the  Stoics, — and  instinct  was  con- 
ceived to  be  an  institution  of  nature  in  virtue  of  which  animals  are  enabled 
to  react  appropriately  without  themselves  being  able  to  foresee,  or  even 
to  perceive,  the  appropriateness  of  their  reactions.  Instincts  were  held 
to  be  divine  creations,  and  they  were  even  cited  as  proofs  of  the  wisdom  of 
their  creator.  This  view  was  defended  by  Aquinas,  Descartes  and  others, 
and  it  came  to  be  a  dogma  of  theology, — and  Ziegler  cites  Altum  and  Was- 
mann  as  its  modern  representatives.  The  position  which  the  vitalists  as- 
sumed was  not  essentially  different.  This  dogma  was  opposed  by  Montaigne 
and  by  Gassendi;  and  subsequent  contributions  to  the  humanizing  or  an- 
thropomorphic movement  were  made  by  Leibnitz,  Condillac,  La  Mettrie, 
Brehm,  Vogt,  Biichner,  and  numerous  others.  A  new  era  in  the  history 
of  instinct  begins  with  Darwin.  Instinct  is  no  longer  regarded  as  the  pecu- 
liar characteristic  of  animal  endowment;  numerous  hirnian  instincts  are 
shown  to  exist  and  to  be  of  profoimd  significance.  Moreover  the  fact  that 
instincts  are  appropriate  and  serviceable  is  now  explained  from  natural 
causes.  Ziegler  discusses  and  rejects  Lamarckianism, — among  whose  repre- 
sentatives he  mentions  Haeckel,  Preyer,  Hering,  Wundt  and  Semon.  His 
own  view  of  instinct  is  based  upon  the  Weismann  conception,  and  has,  as 
the  author  shows,  much  in  common  with  the  view  of  Lloyd  Morgan.  He 
umerates  a  list  of  criteria  which  differentiate  instinctive  from  intelligent 
ehavior,  but  the  list  contains  nothing  which  is  essentially  new.  The 
fference  between  instinctive  action  and  intelligent  action  is  referred  to 
the  assumption  that  the  former  is  due  to  inherited  paths  in  the  nervous 
system,  while  the  latter  is  due  to  acquired  paths. 

In  an  (illustrated)  appendix  Ziegler  discusses  the  brain  anatomy  of  the 

bee  and  the  ant,  and  points  out  that  the  three  classes  within  the  colony 

(queens,  drones  and  workers;  males,  females  and  workers)  which  manifest 

ypically  different  instincts,  also  possess  typical  differences  of  brain  structure. 

The  book  is  written  by  a  zoologist,  whose  discussions  frequently  display 

lack  of  critical  insight  into  the  problems  of  comparative  psychology.   But 

is  historical  sketch  is  a  valuable  contribution  to  the  literature. 

J.  W.  Baird. 


132  BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  phenomenology  of  mind,  by  G.  W.  F.  Hegel.  Edited,  with  an  intro- 
duction and  notes,  by  J.  B.  Baillie.  London,  Swan  Sonnenschein, 
1910.     2   V. 

The  translator  well  says  that  this  has  long  been  recognized  as  a  unique 
product  of  Teutonic  genius,  "on  the  whole  perhaps  the  most  remarkable 
treatise  in  the  history  of  modem  philosophy."  This  is  true  both  as  to  the 
style  of  thinking,  its  expression  and  the  comprehensiveness  of  its  theme.  It 
is  an  attempt  to  give  an  exhaustive  analysis  of  the  life  history  of  the  human 
spirit,  to  reduce  its  complex  and  involved  harmonies  to  their  elemental 
leading  motives,  and  to  express  these  controllong  ideas  in  an  orderly  and 
connected  system.  The  courage  that  made  this  effort  possible  was  due  to 
the  state  of  the  intellectual  atmosphere  of  the  times,  which  was  charged  with 
grandiose  ideas  that  were  capable  of  stimulating  and  sustaining  philosophical 
enthusiasm  and  exciting  and  intoxicating  speculative  ambition.  The  writer 
thinks  that  Hegel  was  inspired  by  Kant  to  sail  these  unknown  speculative 
seas  with  only  a  fraction  of  his  scientific  knowledge  and  none  of  his  philo- 
sophical prudence.  Still  there  is  an  enormous  wealth  of  presentative  material 
behind  this  treatise  which  shines  through  it.  The  discussion  is  often  fore- 
shortened and  the  scheme  of  the  work  is  out  of  proportion,  some  points 
being  treated  with  great  elaborateness  and  others  very  concisely.  The  last 
part  of  the  work  is  especially  unsatisfactory  and  it  is  no  excuse  that  it 
was  written  hastily  just  before  the  battle  of  Jena  in  1806. 

The  translator  certainly  had  a  difficult  task  before  him  and  he  merits 
the  very  hearty  thanks  of  all  students  of  philosophy  who  have  for  years 
looked,  no  matter  how  well  they  read  German,  to  this  work  with  mingled 
feelings  of  curiosity  and  awe. 

Manual  of  mental  and  physical  tests;  a  book  of  directions  compiled  with 
special  reference  to  the  experimental  study  of  school  children  in  the 
laboratory   or   classroom,  by  Guy   Montrose  Whipple.    Baltimore, 
Warwick  &  York,  1910.     534  p. 
All  psychologists  will  be  grateful  to  the  author  for  the  compilation  of  this 
manual.     The  general  groups  of  tests  are  anthropometric,  those  of  phsyical, 
mental  and  sensory  capacity,  of  attention  and  perception,  of  effort  and  de- 
scription, of  association,  learning  and  memory,  of  suggestibility,  of  imagina- 
tion and  invention,  of  intellectual  development,  besides  general  tests. 

A  text-book  of  psychology,  by  Edward  Bradford  Titchener.  N.  Y., 
Macmillan,  1910.  565  p. 
The  present  work  has  been  written  to  take  the  place  of  the  author's  '  'Out- 
lines of  Psychology,"  which  was  stereotyped  in  1896  and  which,  owing  to 
the  rapid  progress  of  the  science,  has  long  since  passed  beyond  the  possibility 
of  revision,  despite  the  continued  demand  for  the  book.  The  author  would 
have  preferred  to  let  it  die  a  natural  death,  feeling  that  it  would  be  impossible 
to  recover  the  freshness  and  vigor  of  the  first  reading,  but  finally  deciding 
to  re- write,  a  first  part,  containing  about  half  of  this  work,  appeared  in  1909, 
and  we  now  have  the  remainder  of  it.  The  author  and  publisher  intend 
to  withdraw  the  "Outlines"  from  the  market  in  the  near  future  in  the  hope 
that  this  work,  which  follows  the  same  general  lines,  will  take  its  place. 

Psyche:  a  concise  and  easily  comprehensible  treatise  on  the  elements  of 
psychiatry  and  psychology  for  students  of  medicine  and  law,  by  Max 
Talmey.     N.  Y.,  Medico-Legal  Publishing  Co.,  19 10.    282  p. 
The  writer  divides  the  work  into  several  parts,  as  follows :  the  psychology 

or  physiology  of  the  mental  functions  and  their  pathology,  following  under 

this  latter  section  the  rubrics  of  feelings,  ideation,  will  and  consciousness. 

Part  three  treats  of  the  etiology  of  insanity;  part  four,  its  therapy;  part 

five,  special  pathology. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  133 

The  psychology  and  training  of  the  horse,  by  Count  Kugenio  Martinengo 
CesarESCO.  London,  Unwin,  1906.  334  p. 
The  chief  sections  of  this  book  are  headed,  the  mind  of  the  horse,  how  the 
horse  learns  and  how  he  must  be  taught,  how  he  is  taught  obedience,  fear 
and  how  to  overcome  it.  The  work  is  attractively  written,  bound  and 
printed. 

Ueber    den    Traum.     Experimentel-psychologische   Untersuchungen,    von  J. 
Hourly  VoIvD.     Herausgegeben  von  O.  Klemm.     Erster  Band.     Leip- 
zig, Barth,  19 10.     435  p. 
This  is  a  very  interesting  experimental  study  by  a  man  who  long  practised 
upon  himself  and  others  binding  limbs  and  otherwise  restricting  freedom  of 
movement,  noting  the  effect  upon  the  dreams.     The   conclusion   shows  a 
very  systematic  relation  and  suggests  the  desirability  of  further  experiments 
upon  others. 

Dogmatism  and  evolution.     Studies  in  modern  philosophy.     By  ThEdorE  Db 
Lacuna  and  Grace  Andrus  De  Lacuna.     N.  Y.,  Macmillan,  1910. 
259  p. 
Dogmatism  here  denotes  the  body  of  logical  assumptions  which  were 
generally  made  by  the  thinkers  of  all  schools  before  the  rise  of  theories  of 
organic  and  social  evolution.     Its  application  is  therefore  very  wide,  includ- 
ing the  empiricism  of  Berkeley  and  Hume  as  well  as  the  rationalism  of  Des- 
cartes and  Leibnitz.     These  studies  do  not  claim  systematic  unity. 

The  science  of  poetry  and  the  philosophy  of  language,  by  Hudson  Maxim. 
N.  Y.,  Funk  &  Wagnalls,  1910.  294. 
After  laying  down  some  fundamental  principles,  the  author  proceeds  to 
describe  the  evolution  of  analogical  speech  and  discusses  the  question  what 
poetry  is  and  what  not.  Then  follows  an  interesting  chapter  on  profanity. 
Still  others  on  the  application  of  fundamental  principles,  the  dynamics  of 
hiunan  speech,  philosophy  of  English  verse,  oratory,  poetry,  etc.  The  work 
is  illustrated  by  a  dozen  or  more  quaint  and  mystic  illustrations.  The  re- 
viewer feels  that  it  is  difficult  to  do  justice  to  this  book. 

The  reasoning  ability  of  children,  by  Frederick  G.  BonsER.     N.  Y.,  Colima- 
bia  University,  19 10.  133  p.    (Coliunbia  University  Teachers  College. 
Contributions  to  Education,  No.  37.) 
The  author  tested  children  chiefly  of  the  middle  and  upper  grades  in 
problems  of  simple  arithmetic,  in  supplying  omitted  words  or  completing 
sentences,  in  scoring  out  wrong  words,  in  writing  opposites,  in  selecting 
the  best  from  ten  reasons  given  for  four  different  things,  in  selecting  defini- 
tions, in  giving  in  their  own  words  the  substance  of  poems.     Returns  were 
obtained  from  757  children.     The  best  test  of  general  ability  was  that  of 
opposites  and  the  poorest  of  interpreting  poems.     The  work  is  careful  and 
painstaking  in  a  high  degree,  but  it  tells  us  very  little  about  children's  power 
of  reasoning  and  should  have  been  designated  a  test  of  general  ability  among 
children. 

Muscle-reading;  a  method  of  investigating  involuntary  movements  and  mental 
types,  by  June  E.  Downey.  Reprinted  from  the  Psychological  Re- 
view, July,|i909.     Vol.  XVI,  no.  4,  pp.  257-301. 

The  central  tendency  of  judgment,  by  H.  L.  Holi^incworTh.  Reprinted  from 
the  journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology  and  Scientific  methods,  Aug. 
18,  1 9 10.     Vol.  VII,  no.  17,  pp.  461-469. 

The  perceptual  basis  for  judgments  of  extent,  by  H.  L.  HollincworTh.  Re- 
printed from  the  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology  and  Scientific 
Methods,  Nov.  11,  1909.  Vol.  IV,  no.  23,  pp.  623-626. 


134  BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  suggestive  power  of  hypnotism,  by  L.  Forbes  Winsi^ow.  London, 
Rebman,  Ltd.,  1910.     90  p. 

This  work,  which  is  dedicated  to  the  officers  and  members  of  the  Psycho- 
therapeutic Society,  regards  its  work  as  an  old  prophecy  fulfilled,  for  Sir 
James  Paget  long  ago  said  that  some  day  some  clever  quack  would  dis- 
grace physicians  by  curing  by  his  will  what  they  could  not  do  by  their 
remedies.  After  giving  a  general  account  of  suggestion,  duality  of  mind, 
the  differences  between  subjective  and  objective,  the  author  gives  us  the 
history  of  hypnotism,  tells  us  of  its  schools  and  those  of  therapeutics, 
pays  his  respects  to  the  pioneers  of  psychotherapy,  discusses  the  rules 
governing  its  use,  relations  between  crime  and  hypnotism,  auto  suggestion, 
hypnotism  in  the  courts,  power  of  suggestion  in  causing  illness,  the  case  of 
EUiotson,  explains  the  secret  of  the  pilgrimages  to  Lourdes,  describes  the 
effects  of  suggestion  in  dealing  with  inebriety  and  the  drug  habit,  describes 
transference,  fashion,  which  is  purely  suggestion,  and  concludes  with  a 
felicitation  to  the  profession  upon  the  fact  that  nearly  all  inteUigent  and 
progressive  physicians  have  now  accepted  the  main  facts  in  this  field. 

Les  lots  morhides  de  Vassociation  des  iddes,  par  M.  Pei^I/ETier.  Paris, 
Rousset,  1904.  148  p. 
After  discussing  the  place  of  association  of  ideas  in  the  psychic  processes 
in  general,  the  author  characterizes  them  in  the  normal  state  and  then 
discusses  symptoms  of  mania  and  the  incoherence  of  ideas  that  character- 
izes it  and  the  causes  of  this  incoherence.  A  final  chapter  treats  of  debility 
and  how  incomplete  coherence  affects  them.  The  work  is  written  essen- 
tially from  the  standpoint  of  a  clinician. 

Bulletin  No.  2,  Government  Hospital  for  the  Insane,  Washington,  D.  C. 
Edited  by  Wiluam  A.  White.  Washington,  Gov't  Printing  Office, 
1910.     135  p. 

This  work  contains  the  following  articles  by  Dr.  S.  I.  Franz.  The  knee 
jerk  in  paresis,  sensations  following  nerve  division,  touch  sensations  in 
different  bodily  segments,  and  Some  considerations  of  the  association 
word  experiment.  Dr.  Achucarro  writes  on  some  pathological  findings 
in  the  neuroglia  and  in  the  ganglion  cells  of  the  cortex  in  senile  conditions, 
on  elongated  and  other  cells  in  the  Ammon's  horn  of  the  rabbit,  plaque 
lesions  in  the  ependyma  of  the  lateral  ventricles.  The  work  ends  with  a 
final  article  by  Dr.  W.  H.  Hough  on  the  comparative  diagnostic  value  of 
the  Noguchi  butyric  acid  reaction  and  cytological  examination  of  the 
cerebro-spinal  fluid. 

Die  Frommigkeit  des  Graf  en  Ludwig  von  Zinzendorf.  Bin  psychoanaly- 
tischer  Beitrag  zur  Kenntnis  der  religiosen  Sublimierungsprozesse  und 
zur  Erklarung  des  Pietismus,  von  Oskar  Pfister.  Leipzig,  Deuticke, 
1910.     122  p. 

This  work  is  dedicated  to  Professor  Jung  of  Zurich  and  is  an  interesting 
new  contribution  to  the  rapidly  growing  number  of  Freudian  interpreta- 
tions 9f  life. 

Nature  and  man,  by  Edwin  Ray  Lankester.  The  Ro  mane's  Lecture 
1905.     Oxford,  Clarendon  Press,  1905.     61  p. 

Criticism  and  beauty;  a  lecture  rewritten.     Being  the  Romane's  lecture  for, 

1909,  by  Arthur  James  Bai^four.     Oxford,  Clarendon  Press,  1910. 
48  p. 

The  judgment  of  difference  with  special  reference  to  the  doctrine  of  the  threshold  ^ 
in  the  case  of  lifted  weights.  By  Warner  Brown.  University  of  Cali- 
fornia Publications  in  Psychology.     Vol.1,  No.  I,  pp.  1-71.     Sept.,  24, 

1910.  Berkeley,  the  University  Press. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  135 

Biological  mechanics.  Book  I,  Psychology  as  a  natural  science.  By 
M.  CuNE.     Oct.,  1910.     75  p. 

An  experimental  study  of  sleep.  (From  the  physiological  laboratory  of  the 
Harvard  Medical  School  and  from  Sidis'  laboratory),  by  Boris  Sidis. 
Boston,  Richard  G.  Badger,  1909.     106  p. 

My  life  as  a  dissociated  personality,  by  B.  C.  A.  With  an  introduction 
by  Morton  Prince.     Boston,  Richard  G.  Badger,  1909.     47  p. 

Die  psychologene  Sehnstorung  in  psychoanalytischer  Auffassung,  von  Sigmund 
Freud.  Sonderabdruck  aus  Aerztliche  Standeszeitung.  Jahrgang, 
1910.     No.  9,  7  p. 

Uber  den  Gegensinn  der  Urworte.  Referat  tiber  die  gleichnamige  Broschure 
von  Karl  Abel,  1884,  von  Sigmund  Freud.  Sonderabdruck  aus  dem 
Jahrbuch  fiir  psychoanalytischeundpsychopathologische  Forschungen. 
Band  II.     pp. 179-184. 

Die  zukitnftigen  Chancen  der  psychoanalytischen  Therapie,  von  Sigmund 
Freud.  (Vortrag;  gehalten  auf  dem  zweiten  Privatkongress  der 
Psychoanalytiker  zu  Niirnberg  19 10.)     9  p. 

The  metaphysics  of  a  naturalist;  philosophical  and  psychological  fragments, 
by  C.  L.  Herrick.     Granville,  O.,  1910.     99  p. 

Kleine  Schriften,  von  W.  WundT.    Bd.  i.    Leipzig,  Engelmann,  1910.  640  p. 

Der  Begriff  des  Instinkts,  einst  und  jetzt,  von  H.  E.  ZiEglER,  2d.  rev.  and 
enl.     Jena,  Fischer,  1910.     112  p. 

Leitfaden  der  experimentellen  Psychopathologie,  von  Adalbert  GrEgor. 
Beriin,  Karger,  1910.     222  p. 

Evolution  and  Consciousness,  by  C.  H.  Judd.  Reprinted  from  the  Psy- 
chological Review,  March,  19 10.     Vol.  XVII,  pp.  77-97. 

Der  Begriff  des  Ideals.  Empirisch-psychologische  Untersuchung  des 
Idealerlebnisses.  (i.  Lieferung),  von  A.  SchlEsinger.  Sonder- 
abdruck aus  dem  Archiv  fiir  die  gesamte  Psychologic,  Bd.  XVII,  i  and 
2  Heft.     Wilhelm  Engelmann,  Leipzig,  1910.     pp.  231-309. 

Die  taktile  Schdtzung  von  ausgefMlten  und  leeren  Strecken,  von  HELEN 
Dodd  Cook.  Mit.  2  Figuren  und  17  Kurven  im  Text.  Sonderabdruck 
aus  dem  Archiv  fiir  die  gesamte  Psychologic  Bd.  XVI,  3  and  4  Heft. 
Wilhelm  Engelmann,  Leipzig,  19 10.     pp.  130. 

Mitbewegungen  beim  Singen,  Sprechen  und  Horen,  von  Felix  KruEgER. 
Breitkopf  &  Hartel,  1910.     pp.  22. 

Rassenhygiene.  Eine  gemeinverstandliche  Darstellung,  von  Hugo  Rib- 
BERT.     Mit.     4  Figuren.     Bonn,  Friedrich  Cohen,  1910.     pp.  65. 

Die  Variabilitdt  niederer  Organismen.  Eine  deszendenztheoretische  Studie, 
von  Hans  Pringsheim.     Berlin,  Julius  Springer,  1910.     216  p. 

Die  Evolution  der  Materie  auf  den  Himmelskdrpern.  Eine  theoretische 
Ableitung  des  periodischen  Systems,  vqn  N.  A.  MorosoEF.  Auto- 
risierte  Uebersetzung  von  B.  Pines  &  Dr.  A.  Orechoff.  Dresden, 
Theodor  Stein-Kopff,  1910.     41  p. 

Vierteljahrsberichte  des  Wissenschaftlich-humanitdren  Komitees.  April, 
1 910.  Jahrgang  i.  Heft  3.  Fortsetzung  der  Monatsberichte  und 
des  Jahrbuchs  fiir  sexuellen  Zwischenstufen  mit  Beriicksichtigung 
der  Homo-sexualitat,  von  Magnus  Hirschfeld.     Leipzig. 


t 


136  BOOK   REVIEWS 

An  experimental  Study  of  Dementia  Prcecox,  by  L.  C.  Gatewood.  The 
Review  Publishing  Co.,  Baltimore.  70  p.  (Reprint  from  The  Psy- 
chological Review,  November,  1909,  Vol.  XI.  No.  2.  Ohio  State 
University  Psychological  Studies,  Vol.  I,  No.  i.) 

Proceedings  of  the  Fifth  Annual  Meeting  of  the  Southern  Society  for  Phi- 
losophy and  Psychology,  Charlotte,  N.  C,  December  28,  1909.  (Re- 
print from  The  Psychological  Bulletin,  February  15,  1910,  Vol.  VII, 
pp.  65-74.) 

Beitrag  zur  Lehre  vom  Querulantenwahn,  von  Max  Lowy.  J.  A.  Barth, 
Leipzig.  (Sonder-Abdruck  aus  Zentralblatt  fiir  Nervenheilkunde 
und  Psychiatric,  neue  Folge,  21.     Band,  1910.     pp.  81-97.) 

A  nnali  della  Clinica  delle,  Malattie  Mentali  e  Nervose  delta  R.  Universita  di 
Palermo  diretta  del  Rosolino  Colella.  Vol.  III.  Stabilimento  tipo- 
grafico  Virzi,  Palermo,  1909.     435  p. 

A  Report  on  the  Circulation  of  the  Lobar  Ganglia,  by  H.  F.  Aitken.  The 
Fort  Hill  Press,  Boston.  (Reprint  from  the  Boston  Medical  and 
Surgical  Journal,  Vol.  CLX,  No.  18,  May  6,  1909.) 

Die  Methoden  der  Immunodiagnostik  und  Immunotherapie  und  ihre  prak- 
tische  Verwertung,  von  Julius  Citron.  Leipzig,  George  Thirme, 
1910.     232  p. 

Die  Haupttypen  des  Sprachbaus,  von  Franz  Nicholaus  Finck.  B.  G. 
Teubner,  Leipzig,  191  o.  156P.  (Aus  Natur-  und  Geisteswelt. 
Sammlungwissenschaftlich-gemeinverstandlichenDarstellungen.Band- 
chen  268.) 

Das  Beharren  und  die  Gegensdtzlichkeit  des  Erlebens,  von  Juuus  PiklER. 
Franckh'sche  Verlagshandlung,  Stuttgart,  1908.     pp.  40. 

Die  Stelle  des  Bewusstseins  in  der  Natur:  eine  hypothesenfreie  Zergliederung 
desselben  in  rein  objektive  Elemente.  Von  Julius  PiklER.  Johann 
Ambrosius  Barth,  Leipzig,  19 10.     pp.  34. 

Ueber  die  biologische  Funktion  des  Bewusstseins.  Estratto  della  Rivista 
di  Scienza  "Scientia, "  Vol.  V,  Anno  III  (1909)  N.  X.  2.  Wilhelm 
Engelmann,  Leipzig,  pp.  13. 

Die  Psychanalyse:  ihre  Bedeutung  fiir  die  AufiFassung  und  Behandlung 
psychoneurotischer  Zustande,  Vortrag  gehalten  in  der  Versammlung 
schweizerischer  Psychiater  in  Ziirrich  am  21  November,  1909.,  Von 
L.  Frank.     Ernst  Reinhardt,  Miinchen,  19 10.     pp.  42. 

Les  Ddgdndrescences  Auditives,  par  A.  Marie.  Bloud  &  Cie.,  Paris,  1909. 
103  p.  (Bibliotheque  de  psychologic  experimentale  et  de  meta- 
psychie.) 

Les  Folies  a  Eclipse,  par  Le  Docteur  LEGrain.  Bloud  &  Cie.,  Paris, 
1910.  117  p.  (Bibliothdque  de  psychologic  experimentale  et  de 
m^tapsychie.) 

The  land  of  living  men,  by  Ralph  Waldo  Trine.  N.  Y.,  Crowell,  19 10. 
288+14  p. 

Esquisse  d'une  science  pedagogique;  les  fails  et  lots  de  I'ddu^ation,  par  LuciEn 
Cell^riER.     Paris,  Alcan,  1910,     393  p. 

La  psychologic  de  Vattention,  par  N.  Vaschidb  et  Raymond  MeuniER. 
Collection  experimentale  et  de  metapsychie.  Nos.  18-19.  Paris,  Bloud, 
n.  d.  199  p. 


pi 


THE    AMERICAN 

Journal  of   Psychology 

Founded  by  G.  Stani^ey  Hai^i,  in  1887 
Voi,.  XXII  APRIL,  1911  No.  2 

THE  ESTHETIC  PRINCIPLE  IN  COMEDY  ^ 


By  Horace  M.  KallEn,  Ph.  D.,  Harvard  University 


Although  it  is  fashionable  nowadays  to  praise  the  'sense  of 
humor, '  there  is  a  traditional  role  for  critics  of  art  which  con- 
sists in  deploring  and  cavilling  at  the  human  love  of  laughter. 
To  pursue  the  laughable  is  almost  invariably,  according  to 
this  tradition,  to  sacrifice  the  high  for  the  low,  the  excellent 
for  the  perverse.  Supremacy,  in  art  as  in  all  walks  of  life, 
is  taken  to  be  isolated  and  sorrowful;  beauty's  majesty  must 
wear  the  buskin.  The  marriage  of  aesthetic  excellence  with 
tragedy  is  indeed  not  only  a  legend  of  the  elect,  it  is  a  common- 
place of  popular  culture.  The  acclaimed  art  of  our  human 
inheritance  has  the  power  to  awaken  sadness;  the  acclaimed 
masters  are  masters  of  the  mournful  note, — -^schylus,  Eu- 
ripides, Michael  Angelo,  Dante,  Shakespeare,  Goethe,  and 
who  else  you  will, — their  best  is  their  most  funereal.  Never- 
theless increase  in  humane  quality  may  be  fairly  gauged  by 
gain  in  the  scope  of  laughter.  While  it  is  untrue  that  savages 
are  without  a  sense  of  humor,  it  is  true  that  their  derision  has 
a  narrow  range  and  fixes  itself  upon  the  more  fleshly  if  pro- 
founder  aspects  of  the  common  lot, — upon  the  pursuit  and 
capture  of  food,  upon  the  business  of  marriage  and  child- 
bearing,  upon  the  enhancement  and  glory  of  the  self.  These 
great  central  interests  are,  no  doubt,  the  piteous  matter  of 
amusement  for  civilization  also,  and  our  populace  has  hardly 
attained  a  wide  vision  of  the  comedy  in  the  residual  world; 
but  it  nevertheless  has  such  a  vision,  and  is  appreciative  of 

^This  paper  is  part  of  the  third  chapter  in  a  book — "Beauty  and  Use: 
Outlines  of  a  Pragmatic  Philosophy  of  Art" — now  in  preparation. 


138  KAIyl^KN 

the  range  of  the  comic  through  institutions  and  ideas,  through 
the  sacred  and  the  lofty,  as  well  as  through  the  natural  and 
the  instinctive.  Civilized  mankind  has  gained  on  the  un- 
sophisticated in  so  far  as  it  can  laugh  and  command  where  the 
savage  trembles  and  is  afraid,  while  the  greatest  master 
of  life  seems  to  be  he  who,  like  Democritus,  understanding  the 
world's  nature,  laughs  at  its  manners. 

A  profound  and  vital  reason  exists  for  this  human  love  of 
the  comic,  for  this  increasing  power  to  find  and  to  place  it, 
for  the  fact  that  the  majority  pursue  it,  if  not  more  eagerly, 
as  eagerly  as  they  pursue  beauty;  for  the  fact  that  the  cult 
of  the  'sense  of  humor'  has  perhaps  more  shrines  and  a  greater 
body  of  worshippers  than  the  institutional  cult  of  beauty.  The 
love  of  beauty  is  the  love  of  happiness;  its  possession  in  the 
aesthetic  experience  is  the  joy  of  successful  self -conservation. 
Beauty  is  the  directly-felt  goodness  of  the  environment. 
The  environment  arrests  you  as  you  plod  or  scurry  in  your 
daily  routine;  it  holds  you,  brings  all  the  faculties  of  your 
organic  self  to  play  upon  it  instantaneously,  integrates  them, 
sums  them,  until  you  attain  whatever  enduring  optimum  of 
value  the  environment  offers.  Beauty  is  this  optimum  of  value, 
this  realized  entelechy  of  harmonious  and  instant  interplay  in 
adaptation  of  your  whole  self  with  that  particular  environment. 
Now  the  behavior  of  the  comic  is  much  the  same.  It,  too, 
comes  upon  you  suddenly  during  the  affair  of  living;  it,  too, 
arrests  and  deploys  your  life,  compelling  it  to  take  hold  of  the 
comic  essence  it  offers  you,  and  to  it  also  you  are  adapted  in 
the  instant,  harmoniously,  completely,  directly.  On  the 
other  hand,  there  are  certain  well-marked  differences  between 
the  experience  of  the  comic  and  the  experience  of  the  beauti- 
ful. The  former  seems  more  complex,  both  with  regard  to 
your  own  state  and  the  condition  of  the  object.  Their  ele- 
ments are  harder  to  grasp  and  more  difficult  to  hold.  For 
yourself, — you  smile,  at  the  very  least;  ordinarily,  you  laugh. 
For  the  object,  there  is  something  that  corresponds  to  your 
own  condition, — an  uncertainty,  a  movement,  in  character 
and  in  form. 

Consider  these  differences  more  closely,  of  course  only  so 
far  as  they  are  ordinary,  healthy  and  normal;  the  trans- 
normal  marvels  of  laughter  are  not  our  affair.  In  your  own 
attitude  the  most  striking  point  is  the  fact  that  it  is  an  action; 
this  smiling  and  laughing  is  something  doing,  and  it  is  a  doing 
which  you  love,  which  you  prefer  and  persist  in.  To  laugh 
is  a  privilege  and  a  delight;  and  to  be  laughed  at  is,  signifi- 
cantly, a  degradation  and  a  pain.  It  is  not  so  with  beauty; 
to  be  beautiful  is  even  more  agreeable  than  to  enjoy  beauty. 
This  irreversible  direction  of  laughter,  well-exemplified  in  its 


THK  i^STHBTlC  PRINCIPI.^  IN  COMEDY  1 39 

contagion,  becomes  still  more  significant  when  we  observe  its 
details.  There  is  first  the  smile;  the  corners  of  the  upper  lip 
are  drawn  up,  the  canines  and  the  incisors,  the  renders  and 
the  cutters,  are  laid  bare,  wrinkles  form  under  the  eyes,  which 
narrow  and  brighten;  there  is  a  slight  heightening  of  the  res- 
piration. There  is  also,  perhaps,  a  barely  perceptible  out- 
ward movement  of  the  hands.  Very  little  is  needed  to  pass 
from  this  smile,  which  may  of  course  be  reduced  to  mere  up- 
ward twitch  of  the  lips  or  a  mere  wrinkling  of  the  eyes,  to  the 
quiet,  audible  laugh, — just  a  deep,  not  frequently  noticed 
inspiration,  then  expiration  in  short,  quick  puffs,  or  chuckles 
or  gurgles,  accompanied  by  more  noticeable  wider  expansive 
movements  of  hands  and  legs.  If  the  laughter  grows  farther, 
is  less  restrained,  then  the  head  is  thrown  back  as  when  swallow- 
ing a  very  agreeable  morsel,  the  alternating  inspiratory  and 
expiratory  processes  grow  more  and  more  obvious  and  pro- 
longed, the  explosion  of  sounds  louder,  of  varying  pitch;  the 
eyes  are  narrowed  to  a  frown,  tears  come,  the  limbs  are  thrown 
far  out,  or  the  body  sways  back  and  forth  rhythmically,  in 
wider  and  wider  arcs,  the  hands  are  extended  and  slapped 
together.  If  the  occasion  or  witness  of  the  laughter  is  a  per- 
son, he  may  be  slapped  on  the  back,  poked  in  the  ribs,  or 
even  embraced.  Withal  the  blood-vessels  are  dilated,  the 
blood  comes  faster  through  the  system,  more  oxygen  reaches 
it.  In  a  word,  the  general  vitality  is  heightened,  the  basis  of 
being  extended.  The  whole  phenomenon  of  laughter  seems 
expansive,  enlarging,  vitalizing;  all  its  movements  appear 
as  if  intended  to  embrace  and  absorb  their  occasion. 

And  that  occasion, — supplied  by  nature,  created  and  mod- 
ified by  art?  However  it  occurs,  it  must  be  given  whole 
before  it  can  evoke  its  laughing  response.  The  maker  of  an 
unpremeditated  joke  does  not  laugh  when  he  makes  it,  he 
cannot;  he  laughs  like  his  auditors,  after  he  has  heard  it, 
after  he  has  taken  in  the  comic  substance  for  what  it  is.  And 
the  apparently  frequent  anticipatory  laughter  of  the  auditor, 
that  is  in  no  sense  directed  upon  what  is  not  yet  but  will  be; 
it  is  directed  upon  a  content  already  offered  and  found  comic. 
The  essential  condition  of  laughter, — paradoxical,  common- 
place as  it  may  be, — is  the  actual  apprehension  of  the  con- 
cretely present  laughable. 

This,  both  in  nature  and  in  art,  has  many  forms,  widely 
diverse,  disparate  and  difficult  of  comprehension  under  a 
single  rubric.  In  nature  there  is  earliest  of  all,  the  eleemosy- 
nary 'laugh'  of  the  well-fed,  replete,  resting  child  repeating  in 
its  contentment  the  pleasurable  movements  of  sucking,  so  much 
like  laughter,  so  essentially  a  smile.  The  object  which  es- 
pecially evokes  it  is  said  to  be  the  rise  of  the  food  in  the  gullet, 


I40  KALIy^N 

SO  that  the  action  would  be  Hke  chewing  a  vicarious  cud.  But 
this  is  the  mere  beginning  of  laughter,  and  its  occasion  is 
problematic.  A  far  more  certain  occasion  is  tickling.  Now 
tickling  seems  to  be  a  pleasure  both  sought  and  dreaded. 
The  child's  responsive  actions  to  the  tickling  stimulus  are 
partly  defensive,  opposing,  mainly  expansive  and  embracing. 
It  seems  to  contain  two  elements  uncertainly  mixed,  alter- 
nating, undirected,  carrying  both  menace  and  safety,  with  the 
element  of  safety  predominating.  Under  favorable  conditions 
the  whole  or  any  portion  of  the  body  responds  to  it.  An 
expected  contact  of  an  unknown  and  thus  far  discomforting 
stimulus  turns  out  to  be  a  contact  of  pleasure  and  delight. 
There  is  an  essential  conflict  and  titillation  between  two  di- 
verse elements  of  which  the  personality-feeling,  whatever 
that  be,  finally  finds  itself  free  and  master. 

The  daily  life  offers  many  instances  which  are  determinable 
as  complications  of  the  characteristic  contents  of  tickling. 
The  laughter  which  follows  fear,  emotional  or  intellectual 
tension,  is  such.  So  when  a  child  laughs  after  having  been 
frightened  by  a  dog,  a  woman  after  having  heard  bad  news 
or  on  the  shock  of  some  vision  or  encounter,  the  terrifying 
object  has  seized  on  the  mind,  disorganized  it,  upset  its  equili- 
brium, emotionally  or  otherwise,  is  a  menace  to  its  proper 
character.  When  for  whatever  reason,  it  lapses,  when  this 
process  dies  down,  when  the  organism  has,  with  temporary 
or  permanent  success,  resisted  and  vanquished  its  enemy, 
the  engaged  energies  are  released,  the  disturbed  equilibrium  is 
restored,  the  organism  is  again  in  possession  of  itself,  and  in 
a  single  instant  or  a  longer  period,  it  does  not  matter,  appre- 
hends the  whole  of  the  lapsed  situation  with  the  failure  of  its 
enemy  and  laughs,  spontaneously,  instinctively.  Literature 
affords  many  instances  of  the  same  thing, — the  typical 
laughter  of  mad  Ophelia,  Hamlet's  curious  ironical  play  with 
the  ghost: 

"Well  said,  old  mole.  Canst  work  i'  the  ground  so  fast? 
A  worthy  pioneer" 

are  instances.  The  preceding  experience  seems,  so  to  speak, 
to  break  off  and  to  constitute  an  object  in  which  an  element 
formerly  a  menace  or  a  terror,  exalted  above  the  protagonist, 
has  been  thrown  in  the  dust  and  made  of  low  degree. 

The  laughter  of  sheer  health  might  seem  to  be  almost  an- 
tithetical to  this, — frequent,  free,  easy,  evoked  by  the  most 
trifling  instances, — the  sight  of  food,  of  friends,  of  strangers, 
the  most  ordinary  events  and  actions.  But  it  is  not  intrinsi- 
cally different.  Joyous  though  this  laughter  is,  it  is  most  prone 
to  break  out  upon  sudden  stimuli,  the  overflowing  energy  of 
health  seizes  its  unsuspecting  object,  is  master  of  it  ah  initio, 


run   i^STH^TlC  PRINCIPLE    IN   COMlBDY  I4I 

and  perverts  its  natural  and  proper  relations  to  the  world  in 
which  it  belongs.  The  apparently  meaningless  laughter  of 
sturdy  children  is  such  an  action,  the  laughter  of  savages  who 
are  sufi&ciently  familiar  with  strangers  no  longer  to  fear  them, 
the  very  confident  laughter  of  crowds,  the  careless  laughter 
of  people  in  power.  Health,  which  is  self-assured,  stable, 
optimistic,  finds  everything  grist  for  its  mill  of  laughter, 
that  is  in  the  least  different  from  it, — that  is  less  stable  than 
it.  Health  is  literally  wholeness,  a  self-sufl&ciency  and  com- 
pleteness. The  laughable,  in  so  far  as  it  is  like  tickling,  is  con- 
versely not  sufficient  in  itself,  nor  complete  nor  balanced  nor 
stable.     It  seems  less  than  health,  and  at  its  mercy. 

This  is  perhaps  nowhere  so  apparent  as  in  play  and  make- 
believe.  Those  who  have  watched  children  at  it  must  remem- 
ber pleasantly  how,  wherever  this  play  is  collective,  it  is 
punctuated  by  continual  bursts  of  laughter,  sometimes  ac- 
companied by  screams  of  it.  Those  who  have  questioned 
children  about  the  persons  and  objects  of  their  simulation, 
the  characters  they  and  their  playthings  assume,  will  not  fail 
to  recognize  how  deep  a  sense  of  the  stability  and  reality  of 
their  customary  environment  children  really  have,  and  how 
rare  are  illusions  on  their  part  concerning  the  status  of  their 
fictions.  For  most  of  them,  even  the  youngest,  there  is 
nothing  magical  or  strange  even  in  the  most  mechanical  toys. 
Their  sense  of  mechanism,  indeed,  seems  stronger  than  their 
sense  of  mystery,  of  personality,  of  faerie.  They  do  with 
their  make-believes  what  suits  their  convenience;  and  what 
essentially  suits  their  convenience  is  the  domination  and 
supremacy  of  the  person  they  are.  If  they  "play  school" 
they  insist  either  on  being  teacher,  or  on  being  victoriously 
troublesome  pupils;  if  they  personate  characters,  they  insist 
on  being  the  gloating  all- vanquishing  champion ;  Tom  Sawyer 
as  bold  Robin  Hood  must  kill  the  sheriff  of  Nottingham,  but 
then  Bill  Harper,  who  was  the  dead  sheriff  of  Nottingham, 
must  also  subdue  Robin  Hood.  He  cannot  endure  to  be 
dead,  even  imaginatively.  The  laughter  of  play,  then,  apart 
from  the  physiological  elements  which  like  tickling  depend 
upon  titillation  of  expectancies,  of  physical  contacts  aimed 
and  missed,  of  purposes  crossed  and  frustrated,  is  a  laughter 
directed  upon  an  immediately  apprehended  difference  between 
fiction  and  reality;  and  is  the  sense  of  vital  power  of  control 
over  both.  In  that  more  malicious  form  of  play  known  as 
teasing,  this  becomes  still  more  evident, — for  teasing  is  play 
on  the  edge  of  earnest,  pleasure  on  the  edge  of  pain.  Both 
the  teaser  and  the  teased  laugh, — the  teaser  because  he  sees 
the  contrast  between  the  expectations  of  his  victim  and  the 
character  of  his  own  intentions,  because  in  that  respect  his 


142  KALL^N 

victim  is  at  his  mercy;  the  teased,  because  he  recognizes  the 
deceitful  nature  of  his  ostensible  danger,  because  in  his  alarm 
at  its  on-coming  he  can  still  take  it  for  what  it  is  and  so  cause 
it  to  fall  short  of  its  intent.  If  he  succeeds  in  doing  so  utterly, 
he  turns  the  tables  on  his  persecutor  who  thereby  himself  be- 
comes the  victim;  if  he  fails  in  doing  so,  he  becomes  angered 
and  the  situation  turns  from  fun  to  gravity.  And  with  what 
ease,  so  often!  A  wink,  a  look,  a  word,  may  serve  to  turn  a 
play  of  wit  into  a  quarrel,  a  friendly  game  at  cross  purposes 
into  a  struggle  for  life. 

Laughter,  indeed,  is  intimately  and  often  the  clearest  ex- 
pression of  victory  in  such  vital  struggles.  The  shouting 
laughter  of  partisans  at  great  spectacular  games  in  which 
their  sides  are  successful,  the  wide,  expansive,  absorbing 
movements  of  throwing  arms  and  limbs  far  out  into  the  air, 
swinging  hats  and  dancing  attest  this  relation.  It  is  evinced 
in  the  traditional  report  of  the  sucessful  prize-fighter  who  to- 
ward the  end  of  his  combat  'comes  up  smiling.'  Usage  in- 
dicates it  in  'the  self-confident  smile'  attributed  to  any  one 
who  is  master  of  an  art  or  of  a  situation.  Popular  wisdom  ex- 
presses it  in  the  proverb  'He  laughs  best  who  laughs  last.' 
Victory  in  combat  of  any  sort  whatsoever  may  be  accompanied 
by  laughter, — when  the  tension  of  the  combat  is  relaxed, 
when  the  mind  erects  itself  and  surveys  the  event  and  the  pros- 
trate enemy.  The  laughter  does  not  occur  during  the  battle ; 
during  the  battle  there  is  silence,  grim  absorption  in  the 
business  at  hand.  The  occasion  of  laughter  is  not  the  combat, 
but  the  fallen  in  combat,  the  vanquished  enemy,  the  mighty 
laid  low,  the  peer  reduced,  the  apparent  strength  unmasked 
and  laid  bare  for  the  weakness  it  really  is,  while  the  victor  re- 
mains firm,  unshaken  and  laughing  in  his  might. 

The  denudation  or  exposure  of  things,  the  inversion  of 
appearance  by  reality  before  a  witness  whose  own  'reality' 
remains  firm,  whose  seeming  and  being  are  by  contrast  one, 
is  indeed  the  basis,  together  with  this  envisagement  of  the 
defeated  enemy,  of  the  most  universal  matter  of  laughter 
nature  supplies, — the  laughter  of  sex.  Fully  nine-tenths  of 
the  witticisms  of  daily  life,  and  more  than  half  the  wit  of 
literature  plays  on  sex.  Sex  is  laughable  because  social  life 
requires  that  it  be  hidden,  set  aside,  submerged;  while  the 
natural  endowment  of  man  impels  the  instinct  to  raise  its 
head  out  of  the  darkness,  to  peer  into  the  light  of  day.  This 
traditional  throwing-off  of  linguistic,  sartorial  or  customary 
convention  causes  laughter.  The  peasant  and  the  boor,  by 
use  of  language,  do  so  directly, — the  mere  mention  of  matters 
allied  to  the  reproductive  function  brings  laughter;  the  more- 
trained,  self-controlled,  sophisticated  individual  is  indirect. 


THE    .ESTHETIC   PRINCIPI.E   IN    COMEDY  1 43 

He  proceeds  by  innuendo,  ambiguities,  covert  references. 
The  submerged  intent  has  farther  to  travel,  more  inhibitions 
to  vanquish,  in  order  to  reach  the  open  field  of  consciousness. 
But  all  classes  of  society  laugh  at  suddenly  discovered  lovers, 
at  amatory  irregularities,  directly  and  without  thought. 
When  they  take  thought  they  condemn  them;  and  often, 
even  in  condemning,  laugh. 

Something  like  denudation  or  exposure  is  involved  in  the 
laughable  character  of  novelties.  The  comedy  of  newness 
is  almost  universal.  Even  if  the  newness  is  circular  and 
seasonal,  it  is  still  funny, — so  the  'first  straw  hat'  is  every  sea- 
son an  object  of  derision;  a  boy's  first  'long  trousers,*  or  first 
dress-coat.  Savages  are  said  to  laugh  continually  at  their 
first  white  visitor  and  his  appurtenances;  children  and  even 
adults  will  tease  and  persecute  people  with  an  unaccustomed 
beard,  a  different  cut  of  clothes,  another  accent.  The  new  is  new 
just  because  it  is  distinctive,  different,  a  variation  from  the 
habitual  and  customary.  It  is  a  little  thing,  isolate,  against 
a  massive  tradition,  a  universal  manner,  a  cumulative  habit. 
It  is  a  deviation  from  the  type,  a  deformity  like  the  tradi- 
tionally laughable  hunch-back,  club-foot,  magnified  nose  or 
hare-lip.  At  the  moment  of  its  appearance,  it  is  at  an  evident 
disadvantage.  It  is  an  intruder,  without  the  power  to  make  its 
intrusion  good.  It  is  laughed  at.  To  it  may  be  assimilated  the 
whole  assemblage  of  little  drolls  which  people  and  diversify  the 
daily  life — irruptions  of  irregularity,  violations  of  the  per- 
vasive conventions  which  constitute  the  economy  of  social 
intercourse, — such  are  wearing  the  wrong  clothes,  using  the 
wrong  utensil,  petty  misfortunes,  clumsiness  of  manner  or 
of  speech, — the  whole  host  of  disharmonies  and  incongruities 
at  which  we  laugh.  Of  these  the  essence  is  the  irruption 
of  an  unexpected,  a  new  and  discordant  yet  impotent  factor 
into  a  harmonious  and  well-balanced  situation. 

The  occasions  of  laughter,  then,  as  they  naturally  arise  in  the 
events  of  the  daily  life  are  occasions  which  contain  at  least 
two  elements,  not  in  harmony  with  each  other.  In  tickling 
we  have  given  the  dual  nature  of  a  stimulus;  in  terror  the 
sudden  fall  or  breaking-off  and  lapse  of  a  dominating  tension ; 
in  pure  health,  the  weakness  of  other  things;  in  play  and 
teasing  and  battle  and  victory,  the  contrast  between  make- 
believe  and  actuality,  apparent  strength  and  real  weakness; 
in  sex  and  novelty,  the  conflict  of  the  natural  flux  and  the 
social  order.  In  each  case  the  occasion  offers  us  a  contrast 
or  conflict  between  two  elements  in  which  the  spectator  does 
not  participate.  In  the  course  of  life  they  appear  impure, 
adulterate  with  extraneous  elements,  not  altogether  detached 
from  the  residual  flux.     Their  arrestive  and  vitalizing  power 


144  KAI^I^^N 

is  restrained  by  other  and  ulterior  conditions,  by  almost 
equally  potent  simultaneous  impetus  from  interests  looking 
in  other  directions,  toward  other  ends.  The  art  of  comedy 
consists  in  abstracting  these  essentially  comic  complexes 
from  their  habitations  in  the  flux,  in  freeing  them  of  extranei- 
ties,  and  throwing  them  into  relief.  The  comic  of  art,  hence, 
has  a  rather  different  character  from  the  comic  of  life, — it 
accumulates  a  certain  desiderative  value  which  is  akin  to 
beauty.  In  art,  the  comic  might,  indeed,  be  called  the  beauty 
of  disintegration. 

Although  comedy  has  chiefly  been  associated  with  letters 
and  the  stage,  there  is  no  telling  with  what  degree  of  adequacy 
it  might  not  be  expressed  in  the  other  arts.  A  limit  is  sug- 
gested in  the  fact  that  movement,  action,  invariably  intensifies 
comic  effect,  but  the  least  degree  of  movement  required  is 
perhaps  impossible  of  determination.  It  is  certain,  however, 
that  painted  and  carved  objects  are  more  laughable  either 
when  they  are  very  simple,  or  when  they  occur  in  a  progressive 
series.  They  appear  either  to  tell  stories,  which  need  to  be 
supplemented  by  verbal  rubrics,  or  to  present  very  obvious 
direct  contrasts,  exaggerations,  novelties,  whimsicalities, 
oddities.  They  involve  an  essential  paradox  which  is,  at 
one  of  its  extremes,  caricature,  at  another,  grotesque  sym- 
bolism. Animals  with  human  expressions  on  their  features; 
human  beings  with  bestial  characteristics;  inanimate  objects 
with  some  of  the  attributes  of  life;  living  beings  with  the 
appurtenances  of  the  non-living;  inverted  natural  propor- 
tions; and  so  on  to  no  end, — these  constitute  the  material 
of  the  plastic  comic.  Sculpture  is  one  of  the  arts  perhaps 
least  amenable  to  the  comic  ideal.  Most  laughable  sculpture 
is  caricature,  often  caricature  by  accident,  not  by  intention. 
The  material  of  sculpture,  in  spite  of  modern  practice  and  am- 
bition, does  not  readily  lend  itself  to  the  representation  of  that 
disintegrating  essence  which  is  the  comic  material.  It  is  more 
adequate  to  the  representation  of  repose  than  of  action,  and  the 
movements  it  most  successfully  represents  are  the  integrative 
and  co-operative  movements  that  enhance  poise  and  stability, 
not  those  that  express  inner  diversity  and  disintegration. 
Grotesque  sculpture  is  not,  by  nature,  comic;  for  the  genuinely 
grotesque  is  the  harmony  of  the  extraordinary.  Comic 
sculpture,  when  intentional,  is  caricature ;  when  unintentional 
is  maladroitness  of  the  sculptor.  That  it  has  a  larger  capacity 
for  comic  expression  than  it  has  thus  far  exhibited  must 
nevertheless  be  admitted.  But  such  larger  expression  would 
need  to  be  serial  and  cumulative,  not  instantaneous.  It 
would  require  explanatory  legend,  and  would  approximate 
very  closely  to  the  comic  of  painting.     Painting  which  shall 


THE   ESTHETIC  PRINCIPI.E  IN  COMEDY  1 45 

be  intrinsically  comic  by  virtue  of  its  coloring  or  design  is 
not  ordinarily  conceived.  There  is  no  inherent  exclusion  of 
such  laughableness;  the  famous  Schopenhauerian  example 
of  the  comic, — the  curve  and  its  tangent, — indicate  that  in 
one  instance,  at  any  rate,  pure  geometrical  form  was  appre- 
hended as  laughable.  There  is  no  reason  why  minds  habit- 
uated to  the  apprehension  of  forms  and  colors  as  such  should 
not  discover  an  infinite  deal  of  the  laughable  in  them.  There 
might  be  a  pure  comedy  of  design  and  of  landscape,  as  well 
as  of  human  feature  and  action.  Hogarth,  indeed,  approxi- 
mates some  such  thing  in  his  ludicrous  example  of  the  conse- 
quences that  follow  on  ignorance  of  the  laws  of  perspective. 
But  taken  as  a  whole,  comic  pictures  are  mainly  caricatures; 
they  have  a  social  subject-matter,  and  are  most  effective  in 
series.  Our  'humorous'  literature  is  full  of  illustrations  of 
this  principle;  the  daily  newspapers  teem  with  them;  they 
are  the  essence  of  the  "comic  supplement."  They  appear, 
significantly,  to  be  studies  of  manners.  The  rich  comedy 
of  such  series  as  Hogarth's  'Hudibras,'  'The  Rake's  Progress,' 
'The  Good  and  the  Idle  Apprentice'  seems  to  lie  in  the  cumu- 
lative integration  of  cross-intentions  with  caricature;  and 
it  is  doubtful  whether  this  integration  would  be  so  funny 
without  the  attached  verbal  legends,  and  the  presence  of 
laughing  or  smiling  human  faces.  The  latter  constitute  a 
very  important  element  in  the  comic  effect  of  pictures;  and 
their  presence  is  usually  a  drawback  to  the  determination  of 
intrinsic  comic  quality. 

The  enhancing  effect  of  movement  on  comic  quality  indi- 
cates clearly  why  comedy  is  more  frequently  a  matter  for 
literature  and  the  drama  than  for  the  plastic  arts.  Literature 
and  the  drama  are  intrinsically  serial  and  climactic;  while 
painting  and  sculpture  are  simultaneous  and  sudden.  Music, 
the  other  temporal  art,  whose  very  essence  is  time,  is  not  so 
often  said  to  contain  or  to  offer  comic  content.  Nevertheless 
music  has  its  distinctly  comic  material  and  method,  and  its 
characteristic  comedy.  This  seems  mainly  to  be  provided 
by  a  combination  of  light,  staccato  instrumentation  with  deep- 
pitched  notes,  by  the  use  of  uncompleted  phrases,  and  latterly 
by  imitative  natural  noises  like  the  crowing  of  cocks,  the 
cries  of  children,  the  whistling  of  birds, — all  in  careful  'har- 
mony' with  the  theme  of  the  composition.  That  the  first 
I  two  devices  are  musically  amusing  may  be  granted.  But 
jiirhether  the  comedy  of  the  last  device  springs  from  the  nature 
mi  the  art  itself  or  from  the  more  apparent  intrusion  of  a 
loreign  element  into  the  musical  complex  is  an  open  question, 
Kiough  barely  so.     But  whatever  the  basis  of  the  laughter, 


146  KAIvLEN 

In  drama  and  literature,  the  nature  of  the  mirth-provok- 
ing object  is  less  open  to  question.  The  material  of  laughter 
is  here  purely  human,  purely  relevant  to  complex  or  simple 
human  interests.  Indeed,  according  to  one  writer  the  human 
is  the  only  material  that  laughter  can  have.  This  material 
may  be  internal  or  external ;  it  may  offer  itself  in  the  individ- 
ual solely,  or  in  the  confrontation  of  individuals  with  each 
other  or  with  their  environments.  The  outer  marks  of  the 
comic  individual  may  be  merely  clumsiness  or  deformity; 
may  be  speech  incompatible  with  gesture,  gesture  with  speech, 
the  merest  physiological  malapropism,  the  lisp,  the  stutter, 
the  bare  misuse  of  language.  Any  one  of  these  may  be  amus- 
ing; all  of  them  taken  together  constitute  the  representative 
comic  figure,  Mr.  Punch.  Falstaff  is  funny  by  his  mere  avoir- 
dupois, Bardolph  by  his  flaming  nose,  Pistol  by  his  rhodo- 
montade.  Bring  them  into  action,  and  these  purely  external 
traits  may  distort  purpose,  and  throw  the  most  excellent  in- 
tention out  of  gear.  A  fat  man  makes  a  shadowy  trooper;  a 
ranting  rascal  cannot  tell  a  straight  story. 

But  this  derailing  of  a  swift-moving  intention  need  not  de- 
pend merely  upon  the  external  characteristics  of  the  comic 
protagonist.  Loosely  interpreted,  it  is  the  essence  of  every 
comic  situation,  which  is  in  Aristotle's  excellent  simile  "in 
the  nature  of  the  missing  of  a  mark."  The  situation  is  created 
by  the  fact  that  the  characters  do  not  hit  it  off.  Its  clearest 
type  is  perhaps  Mr.  Pickwick  chasing  his  wind-blown  hat. 
The  situation  has  come  upon  him  suddenly,  out  of  the  blue. 
The  orderly  march  of  his  life  has  been  broken  up.  His  hat, 
which  properly  belongs  on  his  head  and  should  protect  him 
from  the  wind  and  weather,  has  betrayed  him  to  the  wind  and 
weather;  and  to  add  insult  to  injury,  leads  him  a  sorry 
dance  away  from  his  proper  affairs,  for  the  purpose  of  restor- 
ing the  disturbed  balance  without  which  they  do  not  easily 
go  on.  The  hat  must  be  back  on  the  man's  head  before  the 
man  can  return  to  his  business.  This  is  very  laughable;  but 
normally  the  laughter  is  killed  if  the  man  is  compelled  to  re- 
turn hatless  to  the  routine  of  his  life.  Where  hatlessness 
begins,  tragedy  begins;  and  this  is  a  very  significant  feature 
in  all  comedy.  The  hat  may  not  be  utterly  lost  if  the  laughter 
is  to  be  saved. 

The  hat-hunt  runs  over  us  from  practically  every  cranny  of 
the  comic  scene.  Its  principle  is  an  inversion  of  the  ordinary, 
— an  inversion  shocking,  fresh  and  unexpected.  Instead  of 
a  trick  or  perversity  of  things,  it  may  be  an  encounter  of 
limps  or  persons.  The  runner  who  trips  over  his  own  feet 
is  funny;  but  the  clown  whose  running  is  brought  to  a  sud- 
den stop  by  the  identically  similar  running  of  an  identically 


THE   .ESTHETIC   PRINCIPLE   IN   COMEDY  I47 

similar  clown  is  funnier.  The  classic  comedy,  so  well  re- 
presented by  the  'Comedy  of  Errors,'  is  based  fundamentally 
upon  this  sort  of  inversion, — the  kind  of  inversion  that  a  per- 
son undergoes  in  a  mirror.  He  is  there,  he  is  himself;  yet 
he  is  not  there,  he  is  another,  opposed  and  inimical.  The 
alter-ego  is  the  source  of  the  deeds  for  which  the  ego  suffers  or 
is  rewarded.  The  Syracusan  and  Ephesian  Dromios  are  so 
related  in  practical  life  that  the  mere  mirrored  image  of  the 
one,  having  a  dijfferent  history,  different  antecedents,  and  a 
different  status  pays  for  the  defects  of  the  other.  It  is  as  if 
the  image  in  the  mirror  were  beaten  for  the  impudence  of  the 
grimace  it  reflected.  It  is  the  "sudden  glory"  of  the  insig- 
nificant, the  irruption  and  domination  of  the  irrational. 

Still  another  variant  of  it  is  the  direct  inversion  of  catas- 
trophe, as  the  sudden  and  unprophesiable  ups-and-downs  of 
Face  and  his  crew  in  the  'Alchemist,'  the  reversals  of  Epi- 
coene,  the  inversions  of  the  'School  for  Scandal.'  This  is  so 
obvious  that  more  than  to  mention  it  is  superfluous.  The 
persistent  repetition  of  such  an  inversion,  always  reconstitut- 
ing the  same  situation,  is  another  typical  mode  of  the  comic 
process.  The  battle  between  Punch  and  the  devil  is  its  key- 
form.  Punch  strikes  the  devil  down  with  a  blow  that  should 
deal  him  his  eternal  quietus;  and  the  obstinate  devil  rises 
unharmed  again  and  again  and  yet  again  to  return  to  the 
attack  as  horrible  as  ever.  Or  perhaps  the  condition  of  the 
protagonist  is  that  of  the  jumping- jack.  Its  limbs  appear 
to  move  so  spontaneously,  so  freely,  so  irresponsibly,  while 
in  reality  they  obey  the  inexorable  leverage  of  strings  and 
pulleys.  I  cannot  think  of  a  better  instance  of  this  type  of 
inversion  than  Malvolio,  so  apparently  pursuing  his  own 
freely-chosen  purpose,  so  clearly  the  dupe  and  the  toy  of 
Maria  and  her  fellow-conspirators.  The  comedies  of  Ben 
Jonson  are  full  of  such  types,  from  the  La  Fooles,  the  Dappers 
the  Druggers,  to  the  Voltores  and  Moscas  and  Volpones. 

Seek  where  you  will  in  the  comic  of  the  stage  or  of  letters, 
and  invariably  you  will  find  something  corresponding  to  one 
of  these  forms  of  inversion.  If  it  is  the  comedy  of  mere  in- 
cident, it  will  consist  of  the  irruption  of  the  unusual,  an  upset 
or  reversal,  of  some  sort,  in  nature  essentially  a  disharmony  like 
that  of  the  man  chasing  his  hat.  In  the  comedy  of  manners, 
one  :  finds  private  habit  opposed  to  public  usage,  the  mode 
to  good  sense,  the  individual  preference  to  the  social  sanction : 
the  comedy  consists  of  the  titillation,  the  see-sawing  of  the 
one  with  the  other.  In  the  comedy  of  character  one  finds 
no  less  the  same  thing,  with  another  emphasis.  The  individ- 
ual idiosyncrasies  which  are  the  deep-sunk  well-springs  of 
motive,  pressing  up  action  after  action,  with  inexorable  con- 


148  KAI^I^BN 

sistency,  are  exhibited  in  conflict  with  social  norms  and  con- 
ventional preferences.  Here  we  are  face  to  face  with  the 
comic  object  whose  ludicrousness  is  internal  first  of  all.  It 
is  the  source  of  all  else  that  is  laughable,  infecting  with  its 
distortions  all  that  it  touches.  The  comic  of  character  is  the 
internal  homologue  of  the  comic  of  person.  It  is  founded 
on  the  internal  disharmony  of  traits,  on  malproportion, 
moral  deformity,  as  the  other  is  based  on  physical  deformity. 
The  theory  of  humors,  on  which  Ben  Jonson  has  based  all  his 
comic  pieces,  fantastic  and  untrue  though  it  be,  has  neverthe- 
less grasped  the  secret  of  ludicrous  character.  It  offers  as 
the  standard  excellence  the  nature  in  which  each  of  the  four 
humors  is  present  in  right  measure,  just  sufficiently  choleric, 
phlegmatic,  sanguine  and  melancholic  to  be  of  nice  balance, 
poised  for  any  flight  you  will.  But  change  the  proportion  of 
any  one  of  these  humors,  and  you  upset  this  excellent  balance, 
and  destroy  the  fine  poise.  The  greater  humor  is  at  war  with 
the  others,  perverts  them  to  its  own  uses,  interferes  in  their 
business,  and  ultimately  breaks  up  the  nature  it  distorts. 
The  inner  disharmony  is  expressed  outwardly  in  a  thousand 
ways,  and  this  outer  expression  is  comedy  of  character.  Now 
multiply  these  humors  a  thousand  fold,  consider  the  relation 
of  any  one  of  the  numberless  preferences,  habits,  desires,  in- 
tellections, tricks  of  speech,  manner  and  gesture  as  well  as  of 
soul,  to  the  remainder,  and  you  cannot  help  seeing  that  this 
relation  is  identical  with  the  relation  between  the  weightier 
humor  and  the  others.  It  is  a  combat,  a  distortion,  a  dis- 
integrative maladjustment.  The  consuming  passion  for 
silence  in  Morose,  the  self-conceit  of  Malvolio,  the  didacticis- 
ing  stupidity  of  Polonius,  the  avarice  of  Harpagon,  the  mag- 
niloquent aimlessness  of  Mr.  Micawber,  the  hypocrisy  of 
Tartuffe,  the  subtly  rigid  self- worship  of  Willoughby  Patterne, 
and  I  care  not  what  other  trait  of  what  other  person  you  will, — 
each  is  a  trait  which  is  comic  only  because  disproportionate, 
and  hence,  wherever  it  appears,  disorganizing.  Harpagon 
loses  his  wealth  because  he  loves  it  so;  and,  by  the  way,  is 
made  altogether  ridiculous  because  his  moral  deformity  in- 
trudes and  operates  where  it  should  not.  Had  Shylock  loved 
revenge  less,  he  would  have  suffered  less;  and  Malvolio, 
certainly  an  efficient  steward,  had  nothing  but  his  cancerous 
self-love  to  thank  for  his  degradation  and  misfortune.  Hy- 
pertrophy of  imagination  over  common  sense  in  the  Knight 
of  La  Mancha,  the  atrophy  of  imagination  in  Sancho,  the  flesh- 
ly weakness  in  Falstaff, — such  are  the  fountains  of  comedy  in 
these  heroes  of  the  sock.  Whenever  any  one  quality  is  called 
into  play,  this  forestalls  it,  snatches  its  action  from  it,  or  spoils 
it  by  its  influence.     Perhaps   all  comic   traits   are  no  more 


THE   iESTHKTiC   PRINCIPLK  IN   COMEDY  1 49 

than  the  love  of  life,  the  instinct  for  self-preservation,  no  more 
than  the  spontaneous  and  natural  egoism  of  mankind,  taking 
a  perverted  direction,  so  eager  to  live  well  as  to  belie  fantas- 
tically the  most  fundamental  conditions  as  well  as  the  most 
subtle  of  right  living.  The  greatest  of  all  ruinous  mispropor- 
tions  is,  of  course,  that  of  self-deception.  Invariably  by  its 
means  diverse  social  and  natural  antagonisms  are  exhibited 
and  made  explicit,  whether  in  the  adventure  on  Gadshill,  the 
wind-mill  tilt,  the  tantalizing  dinner,  or  the  cross-gartering. 
What  "moves  men  merrily"  is  the  far-spreading  infectious 
disharmony. 

This  patent  malproportion  in  character  which  is  the  prime 
source  of  comedy  has  led  to  an  opinion,  variously  held,  that 
the  comic  figure  is  an  abstraction,  that  he  is  less  individual 
and  more  'universal'  than  the  protagonist  of  tragedy;  and 
that  the  function  of  comedy  is  that  of  social  correction.  There 
are  some  grounds  for  this  inference.  The  practice  of  the 
Greeks  in  the  use  of  types  and  type-names, — names  like 
Phidippides,  Dicaeopolis,  Mania  of  the  Aristophanic  comedy, 
or  Gly cerium.  Palaestra,  Bombomachides  of  the  Plautan 
comedy,  the  Vol  tores  and  Corbaccios,  the  La  Fooles  and 
Moroses,  the  Mammons,  Subtles,  Faces  of  Jonson,  the  similar 
practice  of  his  successors  far  into  the  eighteenth  century, 
attest  that  dramatists  seemed  to  be  dramatizing  moral  quali- 
ties and  types  rather  than  persons.  The  very  titles  of  the 
comedies:  "Wasps,"  "Birds,"  "Volpone,"  "Kpicoene,"  "L'- 
Avare,' '  "Les  Precieuses' '  bespeak  traits  rather  than  persons. 
But  moral  tragedies  like  "Everyman"  and  "Ghosts"  are 
no  less  typically  and  abstractly  named;  and  there  is  scarcely 
a  tragic  character  that  cannot,  as  properly  as  any  protagonist 
of  comedy,  be  labelled  by  the  peculiar  trait  which  constitutes 
his  tragic  nature.  In  point  of  fact,  comedy  has  no  monopoly 
over  these  forms  of  art  in  the  chastisement  of  the  anti-social. 
And  what,  moreover,  is  anti-social?  A  convention,  a  mode  or 
habit  which  has  attained  universality  is  as  often  the  object 
of  laughter  as  an  isolated  individual,  a  group  as  often  as  a 
habit.  And  these  are  as  frequently  condemned  by  tragedy  as 
by  comedy.  Satire  and  irony, 'indeed,  are  correctives.  But 
the  corrective  principle  of  these  is  not  their  comic  quality, 
but  their  tragic  earnestness.  Satire  is  a  battle,  not  a  joke; 
comedy  turns  the  battle  into  a  joke.  Where  comedy  becomes 
corrective  it  is  no  longer  truly  comic.  For  the  subject  of  a 
joke  there  can  be  no  sting  if  he  is  to  laugh;  and  if  it  stings 
he  cannot  laugh.  The  laugher  can  have  no  portion  in  the  ruin 
which  moves  him  to  mirth. 

That  it  is  a  ruin  which  moves  to  mirth,  and  that  the  merry 
man  must  have  no  share  in  it,  is  most  patent  in  the  comic  of 


I50  KALI^^N 

words.  Civilized  comedy  is  at  its  highest  in  words.  These 
alone  can  render  the  very  refinements  of  mal-adjustment, 
the  delicate  disharmonies  of  the  spirit.  They  reveal  the  range 
of  battle  between  mind  and  mind  as  nothing  else  can.  Yet 
what  target  of  a  poisoned  verbal  dart  ever  responded  to  the 
impact  with  laughter  or  admired  the  accuracy  of  the  aim  or  the 
sharpness  of  the  missile?  Invariably  his  first  action  is  the 
aggression  or  withdrawal  of  defence.  A  return  shot,  scorn- 
ful silence, — but  no  broadside  of  laughter.  The  play  of  wit 
has  always  imminent  over  it  the  play  of  the  sword.  The 
quip  becomes  the  stab  with  a  turn  of  the  hand,  and  this  just 
because  the  object  of  witty  play  is  a  ruin,  or  like  to  be  one 
in  that  play.  Recall  by  way  of  example  that  superb  witti- 
cism of  Heine's  at  a  certain  Parisian  salon,  where  he,  Souli^ 
and  an  enormously  wealthy  parvenu  were  guests.  The  par- 
venu naturally  received  more  attention  than  the  two  men  of 
letters, — which  moved  Souli^  to  remark:  "Even  in  the  nine- 
teenth century,  they  still  worship  the  golden  calf."  "Yes," 
assented  Heine,  "but  this  one  is  much  older."  This  charac- 
teristic Heinesque  remark  makes  of  its  subject  an  ox;  and 
*ox'  is  the  German  Schimpfwort  for  stupidity,  dullness,  mala- 
droit idiocy.  To  call  a  man  an  ox  is  to  insult  and  to  degrade 
him;  it  is,  by  a  stretch  of  meaning,  to  ruin  his  reputation  for 
intelligence,  to  destroy  his  human  dignity,  and  to  make  him 
like  the  beasts  of  the  field.  This  Heine  has  done.  Moreover, 
he  has  not  done  it  by  a  direct  aggression.  He  has  ostensibly 
referred  only  to  the  age  of  the  parvenu;  he  has  ostensibly 
even  defended  him  against  attack.  He  has  said  nothing 
overtly  insulting,  yet  he  has  called  the  man  a  calf  of  advanced 
years.  In  the  phrase,  "much  older,"  therefore,  there  are  two 
ideas  not  compatible,  not  belonging  together,  titillating  the 
attention  of  the  auditor.  And  this  enhances  the  excellence 
of  the  witticism.  Of  wit  which  is  impersonal,  which  is  the 
play  of  ideas  as  such,  and  has  no  moral  lilt  against  another 
person,  the  essence  is  this  unstable  union  of  thoughts,  this 
conflict,  incongruity,  crush,  and  interference  of  two  or  more 
ideas,  struggling  for  place  in  one  word.  The  pun  is,  of  course, 
the  most  obvious  example  of  tTiis  fact ;  but  it  may  be  brought 
about  in  many  ways, — by  a  slight  diflference-  in  emphasis, 
metonymy,  inversion,  metaphor.  Invariably  there  is  an 
ambiguity  between  denotation  and  connotation,  between 
figurative  and  literal  meaning,  which  is  the  soul  of  the  double 
entendre,  as  well  as  of  the  bald  disharmony  of  ideas  or  of 
objects.  Much  of  its  quality  is  evident  in  the  reply  of  one 
soldier  to  another  who  had  called  his  attention  to  the  bold 
escape  and. the  immediate  pursuit  of  a  spy.  "He  is  running 
for  dear  life"  said  the   one,  and  the  other   replied   "He  *11 


THE    ESTHETIC   PRINCIPIvK   IN  COMEDY  15I 

never  buy  it  at  that  rate."  It  will  be  seen  here  that  the 
literal  and  the  figurative  intention  are  jammed  together 
in  a  strange  and  not  incongruous  contact.  The  pleasure  and 
the  taste  of  it  are  due  to  the  jam.  Still  more  potent  does  this 
become  where  there  is  no  relevance  whatever  between  objects, 
as  in  the  wide  perversion  of  the  Twainesque  humor,  or  in  the 
attempt  of  the  Scotchman  to  make  his  friend  understand 
the  meaning  of  'miracle.'  Tam  had  tried  hard  to  teach  him, 
but  with  ill-success.  Finally  he  resorted  to  parable.  * '  Look  ye, ' ' 
he  said,  "when  ye  see  a  coo  sittin'  doon,  that's  no'  a  mirrecl. 
When  ye  see  a  thistle  standin'  up,  that's  no'  a  mirrecl  neither. 
An'  it's  no'  mirrecl  when  ye  hear  the  throstle  whistlin'  in  the 
tree.  But  when  ye  see  the  coo  sittin'  on  the  thistle,  and 
singin'  like  the  throstle,  that 's  a  mirrecl  mon,  that 's  a  mirrecl." 
The  incongruities  are  here  obvious.  Their  violent  refusal 
to  hang  harmoniously  together  is  the  strength  whereby  they 
"move  men  merrily."  A  most  subtle  form  of  it  is  the  famous 
"  'T  was  brillig  .  .  .  "in   'Through  the  Looking  Glass.' 

From  the  coarse  and  obvious  comedy  of  the  clown  with  his 
falls  and  tumbles,  to  subtle  and  recondite  plays  of  wit  the 
material  of  the  laughable  remains  invariably  a  disharmony, 
a  maladjustment  ranging  from  the  impact  of  bodies  to  the 
clash  of  souls.  No  less  do  the  depth  and  scope  of  philosophy, 
where  surely  there  should  be  little  place  for  laughter,  offer 
the  great  and  eternal  disharmony,  a  spectacle  which,  as 
poets  have  more  than  once  sung,  moves  the  gods  merrily. 
But  men  are  so  moved  no  less  than  gods.  The  cosmic  vision 
may  stir  the  thinker  to  cosmic  laughter.  History  offers  us 
one  strange  and  wonderful  figure,  isolate  among  his  kind, 
whom  tradition  names  ' '  the  laughing  philosopher, ' '  Democri- 
tus  of  Abdera  saw  the  great  contrast  between  man's  hopes  and 
his  condition,  his  conceit  of  himself,  his  belief  in  his  own  power, 
his  headlong  passion  and  pursuit  of  his  petty  ends  as  though 
they  were  the  world's  will  and  the  world's  purposes,  as  though 
his  struggle  were  the  cosmic  joy  and  sorrow.  But  the  cosmos 
is  a  void,  and  a  hurly-burly  of  atoms.  Against  the  volume  of 
their  inexorable  tumult,  man's  cries  are  as  utter  silence; 
against  the  background  of  their  fatal  onward  rush  his  willings 
and  achievings,  but  the  uncouth  jerkings  of  the  jumping- 
jack's  limbs  when  the  strings  are  pulled.  Man  is  the  ruined 
victim  of  his  own  illusions.  His  destiny  is  death  because  it 
is  self-deception.  Therefore  Democritus  laughed.  Laughter, 
cheerfulness,  evOvjxLa,  is  a  restoration  of  the  true  propor- 
tions. It  rests  upon  a  recognition  of  the  narrow  limits  and 
the  eternal  conditions  of  human  well-being.  It  is  a  turn- 
ing of  destiny  to  scorn  by  accepting  it,  as  one  destroys  the 
sting  of  rebuke  and  the  violence  of  anger  by  offering  them  no 


152  KAX,I«EN 

resistance.  They  are  turned  to  derision  because  they  are 
spent  on  a  void,  losing  meaning  and  purpose.  Thus  the 
laughter  of  the  sage  is  a  double  laughter.  Its  subject  is  the 
self-deception  of  man  which  combats  the  inexorable  cosmos, 
but  its  subject  is  also  the  rage  of  the  cosmos  spent  upon 
nothing  at  all.  In  both  cases  there  is  an  inversion,  a  disin- 
tegrating disharmony,  outside  of  which  the  sage  stands,  and 
the  master  of  which  he  feels  himself  to  be.  He  is  upon  the 
Lucretian  rock,  watching  and  enjoying  the  storm  and  the 
shipwreck  below. 

The  range  of  the  comic  scene,  we  gather,  is  no  less  than  the 
cosmos  itself.  The  occasion  of  the  laughter  may  be  the 
compass  of  one  small  baby's  toe,  or  the  unbounded  universe. 
It  plays  over  the  whole  gamut  of  human  relationship  and  cos- 
mic disharmony.  Nothing  may  escape  it,  from  the  attenu- 
ated malproportions  of  abstract  mathematics  to  the  terribly 
weighted  deflections  of  the  universe.  But  of  laughter  two 
things  seem  true.  The  first  is  the  fact  that  it  cannot  endure. 
Custom  kills  comedy.  What  is  habitual,  what  we  are  well- 
adapted  to,  what  is  for  a  long  time  a  part  of  our  own  lives 
cannot  move  us  merrily.  To  do  so,  it  must  exclude  us, 
make  us  foreign  to  it.  It  must  become  something  in  which 
we  no  longer  have  a  portion,  and  which  for  the  time,  has  no 
portion  in  us.  The  traveller  is  likely  to  feel  this  most  keenly ; 
that  is,  if  he  is  a  laugher,  rather  than  a  creator  of  laughter. 
The  creator  of  laughter,  the  professional  humorist,  can 
scarcely  be  a  laugher.  He  is  not  a  humorist  because  he  sees 
the  comedy  in  things,  but  because  he  twists  things  and  distorts 
them  so  as  to  make  them  comical.  He  is  invariably  a  pre- 
ternaturally  solemn  person.  Laughter  must  be  free,  but  the 
cause  of  laughter  is  always  bond.  The  maker  of  the  laughable 
is  the  servant  of  his  vocation;  he  cannot  laugh  and  render 
service  at  the  same  time.  The  laugher  is  served,  but  serves 
not.  Hence,  then,  the  traveller  who  can  laugh  finds  all 
things  in  a  new  country  ludicrous  at  the  beginning.  Customs 
and  modes,  habits  of  life  and  manners,  the  very  scenery  move 
him  to  laughter.  But  as  his  stay  is  prolonged,  the  dis- 
harmonies seem  to  rub  off;  the  articulation  of  life  becomes 
smoother  and  less  noisy.  He  himself  has  now  become,  to 
some  degree,  a  part  of  the  structure ;  speech,  manners,  dress, — 
his  own  have  somehow  become  confluent  with  them,  have  set 
him  at  their  centre,  where  he  once  was  at  the  periphery.  He 
can  no  longer  laugh;  nor  can  he  understand  his  original 
laughter.  This  process  is  true  no  less  of  an  oft-repeated  game, 
a  witticism,  a  relieved  nervous  tension  or  a  philosophy. 
Familiarity  breeds  seriousness  or  indifference  before  it  breeds 
contempt.     The  second  characteristic  of  laughter  is  that  it 


THE   iESTHETIC  PRINCIPLE    IN   COMEDY  1 53 

enhances  or  preserves  the  laugher's  impHcit  values,  not 
always  obviously  or  directly,  but  invariably.  The  outcome 
of  the  comic  situation  is  an  alterative  outcome,  not  a  des- 
tructive outcome.  The  disintegration  which  is  the  object  of 
laughter  leads  to  re-distribution,  re-adjustment,  harmony, 
not  to  real  human  loss.  The  upshot  of  any  comedy  shows  a 
harmony  attained  by  attrition  and  elimination  of  excres- 
cences, by  the  reduction  of  the  evil,  by  a  restoration,  even 
if  only  a  momentary  one,  of  things  to  their  normal, — one 
may  even  say,  to  their  normative, — relationships.  The  in- 
version of  the  natural  order  in  which  most  comedy  begins, 
proceeds  in  the  course  of  the  action,  by  the  mere  inertia  of 
the  comic  disharmony,  to  right  itself.  Don  Quixote  is  led  by 
the  effects  of  his  madness  to  realize  and  see  it  truly.  Har- 
pagon  is  led  by  the  operation  of  his  avarice  to  comprehend 
its  evil  nature;  Willoughby  Patterne  loses  some  of  his  self- 
love,  Volpone  passes  from  his  dishonorable  bandages  to  his 
more  dishonorable  chains.  The  new  harmony  may  not  be 
enduring,  but  it  ends  the  comedy.  And  it  is,  of  course,  true 
that  not  always  are  the  normal  social  standards  re-asserted 
and  the  habitual  conceptions  of  virtue  victorious.  In  Epicoene 
the  punishment  of  Morose  is  to  our  modern  sense  perhaps 
harder  than  his  deformity  of  spirit  deserves;  the  enrichment 
of  Sir  Dauphine  by  a  swindler's  trick,  our  contemporary  moral 
sense  will  hardly  stomach.  But,  notoriously,  nothing  is  so 
variable  as  the  actual  social  standard  of  mankind  from  period 
to  period.  Whenever  we  look  more  closely  at  the  post- 
comedial  harmony,  we  find  that  the  standards  of  the  age  to 
which  the  comedy  belongs  have  been  vindicated.  The 
standards  of  all  time  have  little  to  do  with  comedy.  It  is 
sufficient  that  any  prized  thing  shall  be  preserved  or  enhanced, 
that  any  distortion  or  evil  shall  be  destroyed  or  decreased, 
even  if  for  the  moment  only,  not  alone  in  the  drama  but 
wherever  the  comic  occurs  in  sculpture,  in  painting,  in  the 
events  and  routine  of  daily  life.  The  hat-chaser  must  re- 
cover his  hat  if  he  is  to  remain  merely  a  comic  figure. 

Considering  all  of  these  facts  together,  what  do  they  yield 
as  the  aesthetic  principle  in  comedy?  What  is  there  identical 
between  the  tickled  toe  of  a  suckling  infant  and  the  philoso- 
phy of  a  Democritus  ?  Students  of  the  comic  have  given  this 
question  widely  varying  answers.  There  has  been  perhaps 
as  much  confusion  in  the  definition  of  the  comic,  as  in  the  defi- 
nition of  the  beautiful.  Theories  may  be  roughly  divided 
into  three  classes,  yielding  a  certain  minimum  of  unanimity. 

The  first  group  of  theories  may  be  called  "degradation 
theories."  They  conceive  the  object  of  laughter  as  reduced 
in  worth;  and  the  laugher  as  enhanced  therein.     As  Hobbes 

Journal — 2 


154  KA.IvI.EN 

has  it:  "Laughter  is  nothing  else  but  sudden  glory  arising  from 
some  sudden  conception  of  some  eminency  in  ourselves  by 
comparison  with  the  infirmities  our  own  formerly.  .  .  .  (It) 
proceedeth  from  a  sudden  conception  of  some  ability  in 
himself  that  laugheth.  Men  laugh  at  the  infirmities  of 
others,  by  comparison  of  which  their  own  abilities  are 
set  off  and  illustrated."  Laughter  here  is  self -enhancement 
at  the  cost  of  one's  fellow.  The  self-enhancement  is  as 
important  as  the  degradation  of  the  other.  Other  writers, 
however,  take  only  the  degradation  to  be  significant.  So 
Bain  finds  the  "occasion  of  the  ludicrous"  to  be  "the  deg- 
radation of  some  person  or  interest  possessing  dignity,  in 
circumstances  that  arouse  no  other  strong  emotion."  The 
dignities,  moreover,  must  not  "command  serious  homage;" 
and  Groos  finds  the  comic  object  to  be  one  in  a  topsy-turvy  con- 
dition, and  hence  regarded  with  a  feeling  of  superiority.  But 
for  all  three  the  object  of  laughter  has  in  some  way  been  reduced 
from  its  high  estate.  Something  of  the  same  sort  may  have 
been  in  Spencer's  mind  when  he  wrote  that  laughter  naturally 
comes  when  there  is  "a  descending  incongruity,"  a  turning 
from  great  things  to  small,  a  degradation. 

The  theory  of  degradation  fails,  however,  to  square  with  the 
obvious  fact  that  degradation  is  a  matter  of  geography,  in- 
clination, breeding  and  incidental  affection.  As  one  man's 
meat  is  another  man's  poison,  so  what  may  seem  degradation 
to  one  may  be  exaltation  to  another.  The  mental  state  of 
the  laugher  is  hardly  one  which  feels  the  sentiment  implied 
in  degradation.  It  does  not  seem,  in  most  cases,  to  possess 
what  the  Germans  call  Tendenz  or  Schadenfreude.  As  comic 
sense  it  carries  detachment  and  freedom  rather  than  malicious 
intention.  The  correct  envisagement  of  fact  which  the 
theory  offers  is  more  simply  because  more  freely  offered  in 
those  explanations  of  the  comic  whose  key- word  is  "  contrast." 
The  "contrast"  theories  emphasize  differently  the  elements 
contrasted,  but  their  intent  is  the  same  throughout.  One 
author  finds  the  contrast  to  consist  in  the  complete  exposure 
of  weakness  through  the  presence  of  a  superior  power.  Scho- 
penhauer sees  it  as  the  "unexpected  subsumption  of  an  object 
under  a  conception  which  in  other  respects  is  different  from 
it."  Hence  he  infers  that  "the  phenomenon  of  laughter  al- 
ways means  the  sudden  apprehension  of  an  incongruity  be- 
tween such  a  conception,  and  the  real  object  thought  under 
it,  thus  between  the  abstract  and  the  concrete  object  of  per- 
ception." Bergson  finds  it  in  the  opposition  of  the  suppleness 
of  life  with  the  stiffness  of  mechanism,  the  substitution  of  one 
for  the  other;  Freud  in  the  release  of  repressed  and  submerged 
— chiefly  sexual — complexes.     And  there  are  many  other  ways 


TH^   ^STHieTlC  PRINCIPIyK  IN   COMEDY  1 55 

of  Specifying  contrasts.  But  they  are,  it  will  be  seen,  no 
more  than  specifications;  their  common  element  is  the 
"contrast." 

The  contrast  theory  of  the  comic  defines  the  comic  by 
considering  its  objective  nature.  Aristotle's  description  of  it  as 
"in  the  nature  of  a  missing  of  the  target"  stands  between  this 
objective  description  and  the  more  directly  psychological 
theory  of  Kant  and  his  followers.  This  theory  might  be 
called  the  theory  of  ' '  disappointed  expectation. "  "  Laughter, ' ' 
writes  Kant,  "is  an  affection  arising  from  a  sudden  transforma- 
tion of  a  strained  expectation  into  nothing.  ...  A 
jest  must  be  capable  of  deceiving  for  a  moment.  Hence 
when  the  illusion  is  dissipated,  the  mind  turns  back  to  try 
it  once  again,  and  thus  through  a  rapidly  alternating  tension 
and  relaxation,  it  is  jerked  back  and  put  into  a  state  of  os- 
cillation." The  first  of  these  Kantian  suggestions  is  hardly 
more  than  paraphrased  by  Lipps  for  whom  "the  comic  arises, 
if  in  place  of  something  expected  to  be  important  and  strik- 
ing, something  else  comes  up  (of  course  under  the  assumption 
of  the  ideas  we  were  expecting)  which  is  of  lesser  significance." 
The  other  half  of  the  Kantian  description  has  been  more  pop- 
ular. We  might  call  it  the  "oscillation  theory"  although  it 
is  essentially  a  form  of  contrast.  It  has  received  the  endorse- 
ment of  Hecker  and  of  Wundt,  and  has  been  attached  by 
them  to  the  term  "contrast." 

The  variations  in  these  fundamental  notions  are  innumera- 
ble.   Writers  have  found  the  comic  to  be  only  that  which  vio- 
lates social  usage,  or  only  that  which  conflicts  with  established 
moral,  intellectual  or  aesthetic  standards.     The  net  result  of 
a  review  of  all  of  these  theories  is  that  they  are  all  true,  and 
I    in  so  far  as  they  deal  with  unrelated  facts,  all  exclusive  of  one- 
another.   They  are  specifications  of  comedy  under  special  condi- 
I    tions  and  in  various  fields.     They  contain  the  essence  of  the 
j   comic ;  but  they  have  not  really  isolated  it.  Our  journey  through 
!   the  field  of  laughter  has  shown  us  that  this  essence  may  reside 
I   anywhere  in  the  universe.     It  is    not    confined    to   human 
I  beings  or  to  social  norms,  as  certain  authors  believe;  nor  is 
i  it  limited  to  the  merely  living.     Its  habitat  is  as  wide  as  ex- 
i  perience.     It  ranges  from  the  tangent  which  so  stirred  the 
jocund  Schopenhauer,  to  the  universe  which  amused  Democ- 
I  ritus.     As  anything  may  be  beautiful,  so  anything  may  be 
!  comic.     It  becomes  comic,  as  all  the  comic  objects  which  we 
j  have  examined  have  shown  us,  and  as  the  theories  of  the  com- 
ic which  we  have  considered  obviously  afl&rm,  when  somehow 
it  is  at  a  disadvantage,  out  of  proportion,  mal-adjusted.     It 
becomes  comic  when  it  constitutes  a  disharmony.     This  dis- 
I  harmony  is  the  basis  of  contrast,  the  cause  of  oscillation,  of 


156  KAI.I.KN 

disappointed  expectation,  the  essence  of  degradation.  But 
by  the  mere  fact  of  being  a  disharmony  the  object  is  not  yet 
comic.  The  daily  Hfe  and  the  arts  offer  the  mind  an  infinity 
of  disharmonies  which  are  either  tragic  or  indifferent.  In- 
trinsically, things  are  no  more  comic  than  they  are  beautiful. 
The  comic,  like  the  beautiful,  is  not  a  property  which  things 
possess,  but  a  relation  which  they  bear  to  the  mind.  We  do 
not  laugh  at  a  thing  because  it  is  funny;  it  is  funny  because 
we  laugh  at  it. 

An  examination  of  the  nature  of  laughter  itself  will  show  us 
that  which  more  specifically  constitutes  comedy.  We  have 
found  laughter  to  be  a  wide-ranging  action,  corresponding 
to  the  active  character  of  its  object.  But  this  action  does 
not  have  the  purposeful,  rapt  nature  of  other  human  activities. 
It  seems  to  be  a  detached  and  free  thing, — a  thing  which  is 
leisurely  and  secure.  Even  when  it  ensues  upon  absorbing 
fear,  upon  the  madness  of  anger,  the  anguish  of  passion,  it 
seems  to  have  this  liberty  and  security,  this  leisure,  as  opposed 
to  the  precedent  breathlessness  and  extreme  intentness.  It 
seems  indeed  often  to  be  a  cry  of  freedom,  of  relief,  a  roulade 
of  triumph.  When  we  seek  the  earliest  semblance  of  an  appre- 
hension of  the  comic,  we  find  it  in  the  replete  child,  repeating 
the  pleasurable  act  of  sucking.  Its  normal  expression  in  the 
\  smile  requires  the  baring  of  the  rending  and  cutting  teeth, 
*  the  assumption  of  an  appearance  which,  when  well-considered, 
bears  a  startling  resemblance  to  an  animal  about  to  rend  and 
devour  its  prey.  In  the  hungry  beast  of  the  jungle,  that 
has  fought  for  its  life  in  a  double  sense,  and  has  triumphed 
in  its  struggle,  may  lie  the  ultimate  parentage  of  laughter. 
The  explosions  of  breath,  the  gurgitations,  the  throwing 
back  of  the  head  as  if  to  swallow,  the  sprawhng,  expansive 
movements  of  the  limbs, — those  are  actions  that  beasts  still 
perform  when  they  have  their  prey  completely  at  their  mercy. 
And  this  prey,  up  to  the  moment  of  possession,  was  a  peer. 
The  struggle  to  live  matches  not  kind  with  kind,  but  every  kind 
with  all  other  kinds;  its  may  be  a  contest  of  strength  against 
swiftness,  ear  against  eye,  eye  against  nose.  And  the  strugglej 
invariably  carries  its  essential  hazard  which  makes  even  th« 
weakling  his  enemy's  peer.  There  is  therefore  the  inevitable 
absorption  and  tension  and  breathlessness.  In  no  mattei 
how  unequal  a  combat,  there  is  even  for  the  victor  one  mo-" 
ment  of  dread  and  menace,  and  there  is  the  final  triumph  and 
relief  in  laughter.  The  primeval  laugher  is  the  triumphant 
beast,  with  its  paw  upon  its  defeated  enemy,  and  its  jaws^ 
set  for  the  act  of  devouring.  The  first  laughter  is  life's  earliest  * 
cry  of  victory  over  the  elemental  world-wide  enemy  that  wages 
the  titanic  battle  with  it.     Laughter  is  perhaps  a  mutation 


TH^   i^STH^TlC   PRINCIPIvR   IN   COMEDY  1 57 

from  feeding,  and  it  serves  the  same  result :  it  strengthens 
life  by  heightening  its  vitality.  Its  scope  has  expanded  as 
the  world  has  expanded.  The  laughter  of  man  has  all  things 
for  its  object, — all  things  that  may  enthrall  him  or  do  him  hurt, 
in  whatever  sense.  It  'degrades'  them,  makes  them  man's 
proper  food;  it  contrasts  them  with  what  they  were;  it  de- 
stroys their  power  over  him.  He  stands  outside  and  beyond 
them;  they  cannot  touch  him.  The  object  of  laughter  is 
ridiculous,  not  in  so  far  as  it  is  good,  but  in  so  far  as  it  is  danger- 
ous. It  is  the  frustrated  menace  in  things,  personal,  social 
or  cosmic, — that  moves  men  merrily,  when  their  power  for 
evil  is  turned  to  emptiness.  The  novel,  the  dark,  the  cancer- 
ous in  the  life  of  the  spirit  and  in  the  life  of  the  body  becomes 
ridiculous  when  we  recognize  that  it  is  ineffectual.  And 
conversely,  to  turn  a  thing  to  ridicule  is  to  make  it  ineffectual, 
to  throw  it  out  of  gear,  to  rob  it  of  its  place,  to  compel  it  to 
spend  its  energy  in  a  vacuum.  This  is  true  degradation,  and 
the  laughter  in  it  is  not  appreciation  but  malice.  It  is  for 
this  reason  that  even  to  so  intelligent  and  sympathetic  a 
student  of  the  comedy  as  Bergson  or  Meredith,  comedy  seems 
to  be  a  social  corrective.  But  they  fail  to  see  that  the  comic 
force  lies  not  in  the  correction,  but  in  the  joy  of  the  corrector. 
There  is  always  the  possibility  of  a  certain  cruelty  in  comedy, 
an  utter  brutish  joy  in  victory  which  is  ethically  more  out- 
rageous than  the  thing  it  destroys,  until  one  remembers  that 
what  laughter  consumes,  laughter  first  finds  evil. 

This  observation  yields  the  key  to  the  right  definition  of 
comedy.  Beauty,  it  has  been  noted,  is  the  relation  between 
the  mind  and  the  environment  when  the  two  are  adapted  to 
each  other  harmoniously,  perfectly  and  immediately.  And 
the  environment  which  beauty  presents  to  the  mind  is  good 
in  itself,  an  intrinsic  and  direct  excellence.  Now  the  environ- 
ment which  comedy  presents  to  the  mind  is  primarily  an  evil, 
full  of  discord  and  unrest.  This  evil  comes  to  us,  however, 
not  as  our  peer,  but  as  our  slave,  bankrupt  and  stripped  of 
its  power  to  harm.  And  to  it,  as  to  the  thing  of  beauty,  we 
are  adapted  directly  and  instantly.  Comedy,  then,  like 
beauty,  is  a  relation,  but  it  is  a  relation  in  which  we  are  harmo- 
niously  "and  ^onipletely  adapted  to  what  is  in  itself  a  dishar- 
mony, a  mal-adjustment.  It  is  a  relation  which  converts 
evil  into  goodness.  It  adapts  us  adequately  to  disharmony 
and  mal-adjustment,  snatching  as  it  were,  life's  victory  from 
the  jaws  of  death  itself. 


CONSCIOUSNESS    IN    RELATION    TO    LEARNING 


By  LouisB  Ei^LisoN  Ordahi, 

CONTENTS 

I.      Introduction 158 

II.      The    Concepts  of    Consciousness,  Unconsciousness  and  Sub- 
consciousness   159 

Unconsciousness 161 

Subconsciousness 161 

Unconscious  and  Subconscious  as  used  by  Psychopathologists    .  1 66 

General  Discussion  of  the  above  mentioned  Concepts  1 68 

Consciousness  in  Animals 1 72 

III.  The  Relation  of  Consciousness  to  Learning  172 

The  Learning  Process 1 72 

Clear  Consciousness  and  Learning 174 

Subconscious  and  Unconscious  Learning         176 

IV.  An  Experimental  Study  of  the  Relation  of  Consciousness  to 

Learning 179 

1.  Do  Unnoticed  Items  assist  in  the  Formation  of  Associative 

Links? 179 

2.  The  Effect  of  Attention  and  Distraction  on  the  Formation  of 

the  "Motor  Set"  (Motorische  Einstellung)      .      .      .      .181 

3.  The  Role  of  Consciousness  in  the  Acquirement  of  Muscular 

Skill 188 

4.  Learning  to  write  in  Unaccustomed  Ways 189 

5.  Learning  to  multiply  Large  Numbers  Mentally       .      .      .194 

6.  Results  of  the  last  three  Series 202 

V.  Summary 203 

VI.  Conclusions 205 

VII.  Appendix:  Detailed  Statements  with  regard  to  the  Experiment 

on  the  Learning  of  Meaningless  Syllables 206 

I.  Introduction 
The  question  of  the  relation  of  consciousness  to  learning,  in 
the  case  of  man,  was  suggested  by  the  disagreement  among 
psychologists  as  to  the  value  of  **  ability  to  learn"  as  a  cri- 
terion of  consciousness  in  animals.  From  a  purely  metaphysi- 
cal standpoint,  those  who  accept  the  doctrine  of  psychophysi- 
cal parallelism  would  admit  consciousness  of  some  sort  as 
an  attendant  of  the  activities  of  all  animals.  Those  who 
attack   the   problem   from   a   purely  empirical    standpoint^ 

^Bethe,  A.:  Die  anatomischen  Elemente  des  Nervensystems,  und  ihre 
physiologische  Bedeutung,  Biol.  Cent.  1898,  XVIII.     pp.  863  ff. 

Nuel,  J.  P.:  La  psychologic  compar^e,  est-elle  legitime?  Arch,  de  psy., 
1904.  V.  p.  320. 

Ziegler,  H.  E.:  Theoretisches  zur  Tierpsychologie  und  vergleichenden 
Neurophysiologie,  Biol.  Cent.,  1900,  XX.     p.  i. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN   RELATION   TO  LEARNING  1 59 

either  attempt  a  complete  explanation  of  animal  behavior 
from  the  physiological  side  without  the  assumption  of  mental 
qualities,  or  else  they  argue  that  consciousness  is  present  only 
when  the  animal  is  able  to  profit  from  experience,  or  to  profit 
from  it  rapidly  enough  to  argue  the  presence  of  a  psychic  re- 
sultant of  former  experience.^  Still  others  assume  that  con- 
sciousness may  be  present  in  all  animal  forms ;  but  the  power 
of  associative  memory  is  a  measure  of  its  grade,  or  a  proof  of 
its  existence.2  Those^  who  deny  the  possibility  of  a  compara- 
tive psychology  are  met  by  the  answer  that  the  ascription  of 
consciousness  even  to  human  beings  rests  upon  inference  and 
assumption,  no  mental  states  being  capable  of  proof  but  our 
own/  Before  considering  the  question  of  the  possibility  of 
learning  without  consciousness,  and  the  relation  of  learning 
to  consciousness, — which  are  the  main  themes  of  this  study, — 
we  shall  consider  briefly  a  few  definitions  of  the  term  **  con- 
sciousness," and  the  related  terms  "unconsciousness,"  and 
* '  subconsciousness. ' ' 

II.   The   Concepts   of   Consciousness,  Unconsciousness 
AND  Subconsciousness 

Practically  all  admit  that  "consciousness,' '  being  an  ultima- 
mate,  is  incapable  of  definition;  yet  it  has  been  variously 
described  and  explained.**  For  Descartes  it  was  equivalent 
to  self-consciousness;  Wolff  was  the  first  to  give  it  the  mean- 
ing of  "ultimate  property  of  the  soul;"  while  others  consider 
self-consciousness  to  be  only  a  particular  form  of  conscious- 
ness. For  Lipps  it  is  identical  with  the  ego."  Usually  it  is 
broadly  an  equivalent  for  awareness  or  experience,  and  an 
opposite  to  the  unconsciousness  of  coma,  fainting,  dreamless 
sleep,  etc.  Some  writers  make  it  synonymous  with  atten- 
tion, or  a  general  term  for  that  experience  of  which  attention 

^Loeb,  J. :  Comparative  Physiology  of  the  Brain  and  Comparative  Psy- 
chology, New  York,  1903.     p.  12;    p.  118. 

Washburn,  M.  F. :  The  Animal  Mind.     New  York,  1908.     p.  33. 

Romanes,  G.  J.:  Animal  Intelligence,  New  York,  1883.     p.  4. 

^Wundt,  W. :  Grundziige  der  physiologischen  Psychologic.  (Fifth 
Edition.)     Leipzig,   1902.  III.  pp.  324  ff. 

Romanes,  G.  J. :  Op.  cit.,  p.  4. 

'Ziegler:    Op.  cit.,  p.  2. 

Nuel:  Op.  cit.,  p.  343. 

^Yerkes,  R.  M,:  Objective  Nomenclature,  Comparative  Psychology  and 
Animal  Behavior.     Jour.  Comp.  Neurol,  and  Psy.  1906.     XVI.  p.  383. 

Forel,  A.:  Ants  and  some  other  Insects.     (Trans.)    Chicago,  1904.  p.  2, 

^See  Horwicz,  A.:  Psychologische  Analysen,  Halle,  1872- 1875,  for 
review. 

•Lipps,  T.:  Leitfaden  der  Psychologic,  Leipzig,  1909.     p.  6. 


l6o  ORDAHIy 

is  only  a  high  degree,  or  with  selective  consciousness.  De- 
fined as  "meaning"  it  is  almost  equivalent  with  appercep- 
tion. Memory  and  consciousness  are  sometimes  identified, 
but  on  the  other  hand,  memory  and  unconsciousness  are  also 
identified,  memory  being  regarded  as  a  function  of  all  matter, 
and  perfect  memory  a  characteristic  of  automatized  acts 
unconsciously  performed.  Consciousness  is  frequently  an 
equal  term  with  "experience"  and  "psychic."  It  describes 
the  "sum- total  of  our  mental  experience."^  It  is  the  inter- 
connection of  our  psychic  processes,^  or  a  series  of  ideas  con- 
nected with  each  other.'  It  is  "co-ordinated psychic  activity,"* 
synthesis,  change,  or  an  "orderly  succession  of  changes." 
It  is  characterized  by  the  pursuance  of  future  ends,  and  is 
a  synthetic  unity. ^ 

Consciousness  is  supposed  to  accompany  only  afferent  im- 
pulses sent  in  from  a  moving  organ,^  or  "neural  processes  of 
peculiar  organization,"  or  complex  constellations  of  neurones.'^ 
It  is  supposed  to  arise  "only  when  the  motor  cells  are  ready  to 
discharge  toward  the  periphery,"*  when  the  sensory  impression 
is  being  followed  by  the  motor  reaction;^  "it  involves  not 
only  the  sensory  side,  but  the  motor  discharge."^"  "It  va- 
ries with  the  novelty  of    the    neural    processes    concerned, 

and  accompanies  new  connections;""  it  "attends  new  complex 
functions."i2 

Since  any  definition  of  consciousness  touches  either  di- 
rectly or  indirectly  upon  the  disputed   question  of  "uncon- 


^Wundt:  Grundziige,   III,   p.   321. 

'Wundt:     Ibid. 

Titchener,  B.  B.:  An  Outline  of  Psychology.     New  York,  1908.    p.  13. 

'Calkins,  M.  W. :  An  Introduction  to  Psychology,  New  York,  1901,  p.  150. 

^Marshall,  H.  R. :  Instinct  and  Reason,  New  York,  1898,  p.  43. 

^James,  W.:  Principles  of  Psychology,  New  York,  1890,  I,  p.  8;  p.  139. 

Morgan,  C.  L.:  Introduction  to  Comparative  Psychology,  New  York, 
1906.     (Second  Edition.)     p.  154. 

^Morgan,  C.  Iv.:  Animal  Behaviour,  London,  1900.     p.  45. 

''Sidis,  B.  and  Goodhart,  S.  P.:  Multiple  Personality,  New  York,  1905. 
pp.  3  ff. 

^Kirkpatrick,  E.  A.:  The  Part  Played  by  Consciousness  in  Mental 
Operations.     Jour,  of  Phil.,  Psy.  &  Sci.  Methods,  1908.     V.  pp.  421-429. 

Breese,  B.  B.:  On  Inhibition.  Psy.  Rev.  Mono.  Supp.,  1899,  Vol.  3,  No. 
I,  pp.  1-65. 

'Maudsley,  H. :  The  Physical  Basis  of  Consciousness,  Jour,  of  Mental 
Science,  L,  1909.     p.  12. 

^"Munsterberg,  H.:  Grundzuge  der  Psychologie,  Leipzig,  1900.    I.  53i-  ff- 

"McDougall,  W.:  A  Contribution  towards  an  Improvement  in  Psy- 
chological Method,  Mind,  1898.    N.  S.,  VII,  p.  366. 

"Royce,  J.:  Outlines  of  Psychology,  New  York,  1903.  pp.  81-2. 


I 


CONSCIOUSNESS   IN  RELATION   TO   I^EARNING  l6l 

scious"    or   "subconscious"    mental   processes,    a   brief   dis- 
cussion of  the  two  terms  is  expedient. 

UNCONSCIOUSNESS 

"  Unconsciousness"  is  a  negative  term  denoting  the  oppo- 
site of  consciousness.  It  is  employed  in  describing  states  like 
fainting,  epilepsy,  or  dreamless  sleep  where  every  mental 
quality  is  wanting.  It  is  also  applied  to  psychophysical 
processes  which  lack  their  normal  conscious  accompaniment, 
as  pain  or  deep  emotion  temporarily  forgotten  during  great 
excitement,  and  to  perceptual  processes  such  as  the  uncon- 
scious inference  of  depth  from  the  fusion  of  the  two  retinal 
images,  and  the  perception  of  a  clang  of  definite  quality  from 
the  fusion  of  partial  tones  which  analysis  alone  discloses. 
Automatic  acts  are  "unconscious."  The  word  is  also  loosely 
used  for  "unreflective,"  "unintentional,"  or  "inattentive." 
"Unconscious  mental  process"  may  have  various  meanings. 
It  may  indicate  the  physiological  process  correlated  with  a 
conscious  process,  or  a  physiological  process  with  no  psychic 
accompaniment,  but  determining  consciousness  later,  or  a 
neural  process  with  psychic  accompaniment  of  which  for  some 
reason  the  individual  possesses  no  awareness.  These  uses 
will  be  discussed  later.  Whatever  the  metaphysical  implica- 
tions, the  term  when  carefully  used  is  a  limiting  concept 
opposed  in  its  significance  to  "consciousness." 

SUBCONSCIOUSNESS 

"Subconscious"  is  more  ambiguous  in  meaning  than  either 
of  the  two  preceding  terms,  and  though  it  is  frequently  inter- 
changeable with  "unconscious,"  it  usually  implies  something 
more  definitely  psychic.  It  denotes  (i)  the  forgotten,  (2) 
the  purposeless,  (3)  the  unnoticed,  (4)  the  mechanized,  (5) 
the  reproducible,  (6)  the  productive,  (7)  the  psychic  real.^ 
It  is  also  used  to  describe  (8)  simultaneously  existing  secondary 
streams  of  consciousness  thought  to  appear  in  the  pathological 
phenomena  of  divided  personality,  (9)  and  dissociated  states 
which  some  writers  believe  to  be  synthesized  into  a  sublimi- 
nal, submerged  self  and  to  constitute  a  large  part  of  mind.* 
The  first  three  uses  of  the  term  subconscious  (or  unconscious) 
are  descriptive  of  facts  of  experience,  the  5th,  6th  and  7th 
are  metaphysical  interpretations  of  results  whose  causes  are 
unknown,  and  the  fourth  and  fifth  are  a  mixture  of  facts  and 

^Hellpach:  Das  Unbewusste,  Centralblait  f .  Nervenheilkunde  u.  Psychia- 
trie,  1908,  XXXI,  pp.  65-66. 

^Summary  by  Prince.  A  Symposium  on  the  Subconscious.  Jour,  of  Ab- 
normal Psy.,  1907-8,  II,  pp.  69  ff. 


I 62  ORDAHL 

interpretation;  the  last  two  uses  are  descriptive  and  explan- 
tory  of  anomalies  of  consciousness  and  will  be  considered  later. 

Used  in  the  sense  of  unnoticed  or  unattended,  "subcon- 
scious' '  (or  "unconscious' ')  belongs  to  the  realm  of  experience 
and  is  used  in  the  sense  of  "least  consciousness."  As  such 
no  metaphysical  implications  are  involved.  But  it  is  an  easy 
step  from  dim  consciousness  to  complete  loss  of  consciousness, 
and  many  authors  make  the  transition,  including,  as  psychic, 
processes  beyond  the  point  where  we  are  even  dimly  aware 
of  them.  Discussion  as  to  the  psychic  nature  of  processes  of 
which  we  are  not  introspectively  aware  began  with  Leibnitz^ 
and  the  later  treatment  of  Hamilton,  Mill,  Brentano  and 
Carpenter.  The  use  of  the  conception  in  explanation  of  the 
pathological  phenomena  of  multiple  personality,  hysterical 
manifestations,  hypnotism  and  other  anomalies  of  conscious- 
ness has  more  recently  brought  the  question  into  prominence 
again.  The  following  are  most  of  the  representative  argu- 
ments for  the  hypothesis  that  the  mental  life  is  wider  than  ex- 
perience, with  the  opposing  views: 

(i)  Total  perceptions  must  be  composed  of  an  infinite  num- 
ber of  infra-conscious  sensations.  The  roar  of  the  ocean  is 
made  up  of  the  imperceptible  sound  of  each  wave,  the  greenness 
of  the  forest  of  the  color  of  each  separate  leaf.^  "But,"  it 
is  answered,  "this  is  not  necessarily  so,  for  a  sum  of  magni- 
tudes differs  from  its  parts,  not  merely  quantitively,  but 
qualitatively."  A  lesser  degree  than  zero  changes  water  not 
partially,  but  completely  to  ice.^  A  sufficient  quantity  of  the 
cause  may  be  necessary  to  produce  any  of  the  effect.*  The 
infra-sensible  stimuli  affect  the  nerve  and  help  the  birth  of 
the  sensation  when  other  stimuli  come,  but  it  is  a  matter  till 
then  of  the  nerve-cell  only.** 

(2)  By  far  the  larger  part  of  our  spiritual  possessions  are 
not  in  consciousness,  but  are  the  forgotten  memories,  un- 
conscious habits  and  the  results  of  early  experiences.  That 
these  are  really  concerned  is  shown  by  cases  where  delirious 
patients  speak  the  forgotten  language  of  early  childhood, 

^Leibnitz:  New  Essays  Concerning  Human  Understanding  (trans.), 
N.  Y.  1896.     pp.  47-52. 

Hamilton,  Sir  Wm.:  Lectures  on  Metaphysics,  Edin.,  1877,  Vol.  i, 
p.    339   ff. 

Mill,  J.  S. :  An  Examination  of  Sir  Wm.  Hamilton's  Philosophy,  London, 
1878,  Vol.  I,  ch.  8. 

Brentano,  F.:  Psychologic,  Leipzig,  1874,  Ch.  4. 

^Leibnitz:  op.  cit.,  pp.  47-52. 

Hamilton:  op.  cit.  p.  339  f. 

'Brentano :  loc.  cit. 

<Mill:  loc.  cit. 

^James,  Wm,:  Principles  of  Psychology,  N.  Y.  1902.  Vol.  i,  p.  159. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN   RELATION  TO  lyEARNING  1 63 

and  idiots  remember  things  they  have  heard  but  not  under- 
stood, also  the  oft  cited  case  of  the  ignorant  servant  who 
quoted  in  deHrium  passages  of  Hebrew  she  had  heard  her 
master  read.  Contrary  opinion  contends  that  not  the  ideas, 
but  the  power  of  reproducing  them  remains  latent,  physio- 
logical modifications  only  being  concerned.  Understanding 
what  one  hears  is  different  from  consciousness,  and  probably 
the  idiots  and  the  servant  were  aware  of  the  sounds,  but  not 
of  their  import.  In  memories,  not  the  concept  is  conserved, 
as  Herbart  believed,  but  "molecular  habits  of  the  brain. "^ 
"  Unconscious  psychic  dispositions'  *  would  have  to  be  assumed 
just  as  much  for  newly  produced  as  reproduced  ideas. 

(3)  Habitual  actions  which  are  at  first  entirely  conscious 
become  mechanized  and  imconscious.  Complete  activities 
formerly  requiring  a  voluntary  initiation  of  every  act  in  the 
series,  now  run  on  of  themselves  when  consciously  started. 
One  party  holds  this  fact  to  be  evidence  that  the  psychic  side 
exists  unconsciously;  the  other,  that  the  process  has  become 
merely  a  matter  of  physiology. 

(4)  Unconscious  psychic  processes  are  manifested  by  re- 
sults existing  in  consciousness — results  whose  underlying 
processes  are  entirely  unknown  to  us.  Examples  are  the  per- 
ception of  depth  from  the  fusion  of  simultaneous  double 
retinal  images,  the  perception  of  direction  of  sound  by  its 
relative  intensity  in  the  two  ears,  and  other  judgments  or 
inferences  spontaneously  made  without  consciousness  of  the 
reasons  or  of  the  underlying  principles.  Also,  there  are 
sometimes  present  in  the  after-image  details  which  were  not 
seen  in  the  original  image.^  Against  the  last  example  Bren- 
tano  urges  that  the  after-image  is  really  due  to  a  prolongation 
of  the  physiological  excitation.  In  the  original  perception 
consciousness  was  occupied  with  something  else,  but  is  free 
later  so  that  the  unnoticed  phase  makes  itself  evident  in  the 
after-image.  A  similar  argument,  i.  e.,  that  details  of  which 
we  were  unconscious  in  the  original  experience  are  frequently 
observed  later  in  the  memory  image,  might  be  met  by  the 
explanation  that  such  details  were  actually  present,  but  were 
not  in  the  focus  of  attention. 

A  physiological  explanation  is  thought  to  meet  the  next  three 
arguments. 

(5)  By  turning  our  attention  to  something  entirely  different 
we  are  frequently  enabled  to  recall  a  forgotten  name,  etc., 
which  has  been  supposed  to  prove  that  an  unconscious  pro- 

^Miinsterberg,  H.:  Grundziige,  d.  Psychologic,  Leipzig,  1900, pp.  223-224. 
^Helmholtz:  Handbuch  d.  physiologischen  Optik.   Hamburg,  1896.    pp. 
602,  962. 


164  ORDAHL 

cess  has  gone  on  to  call  it  up.  Profound  sleep  may  recover 
lost  ideas,  because,  it  is  held,  the  process  goes  on  undistiwbed 
by  our  fruitless  efforts.  (A  refreshed  and  rested  brain  may 
be  responsible  for  quicker  association.) 

(6)  The  same  thing  is  seen  in  the  recall  of  forgotten  facts, 
and  even  unnoticed  details  of  a  former  experience,  while  a 
different  stream  of  conscious  thought  flows  along  beside  it. 
Automatic  writing,  "crystal  gazing"  or  "shell  hearing"  may 
make  known  to  us  facts  which  it  has  been  impossible  for  us 
to  recall  or  even  of  which  we  were  "unconscious"  before. 
(The  automatic  writing  is  explained  as  a  purely  physiological 
process,  with  no  "detached  consciousness"  and  the  "un- 
conscious' '  perceptions  as  conscious  but  rapidly  forgotten.) 

(7)  Activities  similar  to  conscious  activities  except  that 
they  are  carried  on  during  abstraction  and  so  lack  the  con- 
scious quality  are  supposed  to  show  unconscious  psychic  pro- 
cesses. For  example,  one  may  take  one's  way  along  the 
street,  choosing  one  of  many  possible  directions,  while  one 
is  so  absorbed  in  deep  thought  that  he  is  unconscious  of  what 
he  is  doing.  Or  one  may  hear  a  sound,  detect  an  odor  or  feel 
a  pressure  while  absorbed  without  being  conscious  of  it,  but 
when  the  engrossing  thought  is  past  it  may  come  to  full  con- 
sciousness. Bleuler,  who  thinks  consciousness  occurs  only 
with  the  association  of  a  complex  with  the  ego-complex,^  ex- 
plains such  cases  by  saying  that  the  object  was  perceived  by 
the  psyche,  but  not  so  associated.  The  explanation  by 
those  opposed  is  that  what  we  have  is  perception  with  rapid 
oblivescence. 

(8)  "Mediate  associations  where  ideas  arise  which  have 
no  causal  connection  in  consciousness  show  the  efficiency  of 
unconscious  links."  Jerusalem  reports  such  a  case,  as  fol- 
lows: A  man  was  busy  at  his  work  when  suddenly  there 
flashed  before  him  a  scene  witnessed  many  years  before,  which 
was  totally  out  of  keeping  with  his  present  occupation. 
Search  for  the  connecting  link  finally  resulted  in  finding  a 
tiny  hidden  flower,  which  he  had  not  known  was  present,  and 
which  had  been  directly  associated  with  the  earlier  experience. 
The  odor,  of  which  he  was  "unconscious"  had  probably  been 
responsible  for  the  association.  Wundt  answers  to  this  and 
like  cases  that  the  odor  was  conscious  but  unnoticed,^  and 
other  opponents  take  the  same  attitude.  Scripture  per- 
formed a  series  of  experiments  which  seemed  to  show  that 
associations  were  formed  between  nonsense  syllables  by  iden- 

^Bleuler,  E. :  Bewusstsein  und  Assodation,  Journal  f.  Psy.  u.  Neurol.  VI, 
1906,  154.  Re-published  in  C.  G.  Jung's  Diagnostische  Associationsstu- 
dien,  Leipzig,  1906.     I.  257. 

"Wundt's  Philosophische  Studien,  X,  1894.     S.  326-8. 


CONSCIOUSNESS   IN   RELATION   TO   LEARNING 


165 


tical  characters  written  on  the  outer  part  of  the  cards  used  so 
that  they  were  not  noticed.^  Cordes  and  Messer  think  they 
find  cases  of  mediate  association,  but  Munsterberg,^  W.  G. 
Smith  and  Howe^  get  only  negative  results.  Pierce*  sug- 
gests as  an  explanation  for  cases  like  finding  one's  self  saying  a 
word  which  later  we  discover  to  be  written  somewhere  but 
which  we  have  not  "seen,"  as  the  'translation'  of  the  image  into 
another  field  than  that  in  which  it  was  received.  Out  of  892 
observations  of  "free  rising"  ideas  Kiesow  reports  that  41% 
could  be  accounted  for,  and  believes  that  his  experiment 
proves  all  such  links  to  be  conscious  and  either  ideational  or 
emotional  in  character.^  By  some,  "free  rising  ideas"  re- 
ceive a  physiological  explanation. 

(9)  Closely  connected  with  mediate  associations  are  the 
sudden  flashes  and  insights — ideas  which  apparently  come 
from  nowhere — and  the  exaggerated  and  more  brilliant  form 
of  the  same  thing  seen  in  the  inspirations  of  the  genius  and 
the  fancies  of  the  poet.  Not  an  unconscious  ideational  con- 
nection, but  a  purely  physiological  basis  of  the  association 
satisfies  the  opponents  of  the  "unconscious." 

(10)  Decisions  have  sometimes  been  reached  or  problems 
worked  out  in  sleep.  In  dreams  the  result  may  be  arrived 
at,  but  the  setting  may  be  fantastic  or  absurd.  Here,  too, 
the  physiological  mechanism  may  been  have  started  and 
carried  the  whole  thing  out  by  itself,  or  if  the  process  is  accom- 
panied by  dreaming  it  is  none  the  less  conscious  for  the  fact 
that  associations  are  lacking  to  make  the  setting  normal. 

(11)  Development  of  emotional  states  is  often  unconscious. 
Prejudices  are  formed  for  no  conscious  reason;  appreciation 
of  art  rests  on  unconscious  factors;  a  man  may  be  in  love 
without  being  conscious  of  it.  Here  the  usage  of  the  term 
rests  on  the  identification  of  consciousness  and  self-conscious- 
ness. Because  an  attitude  is  "unreasoned"  it  is  not  necessa- 
rily unconscious.  Experiencing  an  emotion  or  idea  and 
having  it  as  an  object  of    consciousness    are  two  different 


^Scripture,  K.  W. :  Uber  den  associativen  Verlauf  der  Vorstellungen, 
Leipzig,  1891.     Diss.     pp.  76-87. 

Cordes,  G. :  Experimentelle  Untersuchungen  liber  Association.  Philos. 
Studien,  XVII.     1901.     S.  73. 

Messer,  A. :  Experimentell-psychologische  Untersuchungen  iiber das  Den- 
ken,  Arch.  /.  d.  gesam.  Psy.,  VIII.    1906,  63  ff. 

^Miinsterberg,  H. :  Beitrdge,  Bd.  4  1892  S.  2-8. 

Smith,  W.  G.:  Mind,  N.  S.  III.     1894.     p.  301. 

^Am.  Jour.  Psy.,  VI,  1894.     pp.  239-41. 

^Jour.  Phil.  Psy.  &*  Sc.  Meth.,  1,  1904.     pp.  400-3. 

^Kiesow,  F.:  Ueber  sogenannte  "freisteigende"  Vorstellungen,  usw. 
Arch.  f.  d.  Gesam.  Psy.,  VI,  1906.     357-90. 


1 66  ORDAHL 

matters.     (James.)  The   man   in   love   is  conscious  of   each 
feeling  and  sensation,  but  not  of  the  fact  itself  (Brentano). 

Unconscious  and  Subconscious  as  Used  by 
psychopathologists 

The  use  of  the  terms  "unconscious"  or  "subconscious" 
by  the  psychopathologists  to  describe  anomalies  of  con- 
sciousness deserves  special  attention  because  the  sense  is 
somewhat  different  from  any  of  the  preceding  cases.  Con- 
sciousness is  conceived  as  split  into  two  consciousnesses,  one 
usually  more  firmly  knit  together  and  predominant  than  the 
other,  the  secondary  consciousness,  "co-consciousness,"  or 
"subconsciousness."  These  two  (or  sometimes  more)  con- 
sciousnesses may  exist  simultaneously  or  alternate  with  each 
other.  Prince  explains  the  phenomena  thus.  Ideas  mak- 
ing up  an  experience  tend  to  become  organized  into  a  complex 
which  may  be  a  subject,  time  or  mood  complex.  Dissociation 
of  personality  may  take  its  line  of  cleavage  along  any  one  of 
these  three  complexes  and  in  abnormal  conditions  a  complex 
which  is  only  one  side  of  a  character  may  become  the  main  or 
sole  complex  of  the  new  personality.  Complexes  may  be  ar- 
tificially organized  in  hypnosis,  trances,  etc.  The  formation 
of  complexes  has  its  basis  in  the  organization  of  the  neurones 
into  complexes,  which  retain  their  organization  so  that  stim- 
ulation of  one  element  starts  the  whole  process.  Physiologi- 
cal complexes  can  be  conserved  despite  absence  of  awareness  in 
the  original  experience.  Strong  organization  of  physiological 
complexes  together  with  lowered  physiological  threshold  and 
decreased  inhibition,  might  render  them  accessible  to  minimal 
stimulation,  whether  peripheral  or  central,  and  cause  them  to 
function  automatically  as  different  groups  of  ideas.  If  the 
threshold  were  sufiiciently  low,  it  might  become  "co-con- 
scious," without  entering  the  field  of  personal  consciousness. 
This  co-conscibusness  is  really  conscious  because  it  behaves 
so,  being  able  to  solve  problems,  and  because  it  says  it  is  con- 
scious. For  Prince  there  is  no  normal  "subconscious  or  sub- 
liminal self  or  hidden  self." 

Janet^  who  likewise  limits  "subconscious"  to  the  patho- 
logical co-activity  of  divided  personality,  thinks  there  may  be 
a  group  of  co-existing  ideas  in  the  normal  individual  because 
"pathological  phenomena  have  their  germ  in  normal  physio- 
logy." This  aggregation  is  due  to  weakness  in  power  of 
synthesis.  In  hysteria  the  power  of  psychic  synthesis  is  so 
weakened  and  consciousness  so  narrow  that  when  one  per- 

1  Janet,  P.:  A  Symposium  on  the  Subconscious.  Jour.  Abnormal  Psy., 
1907-8,  II,  p.  62. 


CONSCIOUSNESS   IN   RELATION   TO  LEARNING  1 67 

ceives  an  impression  he  is  inaccessible  to  others.  Sometimes 
he  is  unable  to  receive  impressions  from  more  than  one  sense 
realm,  or  he  may  even  be  able  to  obtain  data  from  im- 
pressions from  one  side  of  the  body  only.  Ideas  are  not  asso- 
ciated with  one  another  as  with  normal  people,  but  every  idea 
takes  up  the  whole  narrow  activity  of  consciousness. 

Sidis,  on  the  other  hand,  considers  a  sub-conscious  self  the 
possession  of  every  individual  normal  and  abnormal.  The 
subconscious  is  not  an  unconscious  physiological  mechanism, 
it  is  a  secondary  consciousness,  a  secondary  self.^  It  may 
possess  some  degree  of  self-consciousness,  may  grow  and  de- 
velop. "As  a  rule  the  stream  of  sub- waking  consciousness 
is  broader  than  that  of  waking  consciousness,  so  that  the  sub- 
merged, sub-waking  self  knows  the  life  of  the  upper,  pri- 
mary, waking  self,  but  the  latter  does  not  know^  the  former. 
This  self  is  manifested  by  all  the  facts  of  "crystal  gazing," 
"shell  hearing,"  automatic  writing  and  the  like.  They  "re- 
veal the  presence  of  a  secondary,  submerged,  hyperaesthetic 
consciousness  that  sees,  hears  and  perceives  what  is  outside 
the  range  of  perception  of  the  primary  personal  self."  This 
sub-awaking^  self  shows  itself  present  in  post-hypnotic  sugges- 
tion, "shell-hearing,"  "crystal  vision,"  etc.  It  is  extraor- 
dinarily plastic  and  devoid  of  all  personal  character.  The 
subconscious  is  by  no  means  identical  with  states  of  low  in- 
tensity, but  includes  psychic  states  ranging  from  the  lowest  to 
the  highest  tension  and  vividness  of  mental  activity.^  In  the 
functional  relation  of  nervous  elements  he  finds  the  physio- 
logical basis  for  the  disaggregation  of  consciousness.  The 
neurons  form  combinations  of  ever  increasing  complexity, 
and  the  more  complex  their  organization  the  greater  the  or- 
ganization of  psychic  units  into  systems.  The  individual 
mind  is  therefore  a  complex  system  of  many  minds.  "There 
may  be  as  many  different  personalities,  parasitic  or  secondary, 
as  there  are  possible  combinations  and  disaggregations  of 
psychophysiological  aggregates."  A  neuron  aggregate,  enter- 
ing into  association  with  other  aggregates  and  being  called 
into  activity  from  as  many  different  directions  as  there  are 
^-ggregates  in  the  associated  cluster,  has  its  neuron  energy 
kept  within  the  limits  of  the  physiological  level.  A  dissociated 
neuron  aggregate,  on  the  contrary,  is  not  affected  by  the 
activity  of  the  other  aggregates;  it  is  rarely  called  upon  to 
function  and  stores  up  a  great  amount  of  neuron  energy, — 

^Sidis,  B.  and  Goodhart,  S.  P.:  Multiple  Personalty,  N.  Y.,  1905,  p.  128. 
"^Ibid.,  p.  138. 
^Ihid.,  p.  45  and  184. 
*Ibid.,  p.  45  and  184. 


1 68  ORDAHL 

with  the  equihbrium  of  the  neuron  aggregates,  with  the  syn- 
thesis of  the  dissociated  systems,  the  subconscious  eruptions, 
attacks  or  'seizures*  vanish  never  to  return.^ 

The  explanation  of  Breuer  and  Freud  for  like  phenomena  is 
similar  to  that  of  Sidis.  In  some  cases  we  find  that  "great 
complexes  of  ideas  and  complex  psychic  processes,  rich  in 
consequences,  remain  completely  unconscious  in  many 
patients  and  coexist  with  the  conscious  psychic  life."^ 

Cleavage  is  usually  caused  by  the  suppression  from  con- 
sciousness of  a  painful  experience.  Ideas  producing  the 
hysterical  phenomena,  though  of  long  standing,  are  lively  and 
actually  present,  their  continued  liveliness  being  due  to  a 
dearth  of  associations  and  external  impressions.  Cure  con- 
sists in  associating  the  suppressed  experience  with  the  rest  of 
consciousness,  for  when  an  emotion  is  denied  expression  in 
reaction  the  intra-cerebral  excitation  is  greatly  increased  but 
used  neither  in  motor  nor  associative  activity,  and  in  some 
cases  abnormal  reactions  enter  and  there  is  an  "anomalous 
expression  of  the  emotional  life."  When  the  complex  is 
associated  with  other  neural  complexes,  its  excess  energy  dis- 
charges itself.  Phenomena  of  daily  life  show  the  repression 
of  painful  memories  and  evidences  of  the  effect  of  unconscious 
ideas,  such  as  forgetting  good  resolutions  or  the  return  of  a  de- 
sired but  borrowed  book,  and  many  symptomatic  and  accidental 
acts.  Unconscious  motives  determine  many  of  our  actions. 
Dream  work  is  a  complex  thought  structure  formed  in  the 
daytime  and  not  discharged,  leaving  a  remnant  which  persists 
and  would  disturb  sleep  were  it  not  converted  into  dreams. 

Jung'  finds  longer  reaction  times  when  the  stimulus  word 
is  associated  with  an  idea  complex  possessing  a  strong  feeling 
tone.  This  complex,  momentarily  separated  from  conscious- 
ness, exercises  an  effect  which  concurs  with  the  ego-complex. 
The  "constellating"  of  an  association  is  mostly  unconscious, 
the  complex  playing  the  r6le  of  a  quasi-independent  existence, 
a  "second  consciousness." 

GENERAL  DISCUSSION    OF     THE    ABOVE    MENTIONED   CONCEPTS 

The  above  are  the  representative  uses  of  the  terms  "con- 
scious," "subconscious' '  and  "unconscious,' '  with  the  disputes 
therein  involved.  Objections  to  speaking  of  "unconscious 
psychic' '  processes  are  mainly  on  the  logical  ground  that  un- 

^Sidis,  B.:  Psychopathological  Researches,  N.  Y.,  1902,  p.  212. 

^Breuer  and  Freud:  Studien  iiber  Hysteric,  Leipzig,  1895,  p.  194. 

'Jung:  Ueber  das  Verhalten  der  Reactionszeit  beim  Assoziationsexperi- 
mente.  Journal  /.  Psy.  u.  Neurol.,  VI.  1905.  29.  (Republished  in  C. 
G.  Jung's  Diagnostische  Assoziationsstudien,  Leipzig,    1906,  I.     221  ff.) 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING  1 69 

conscious  and  psychic  are  contradictory  terms.  Metaphysical 
considerations  on  the  other  hand  are  responsible  for  the  con- 
trary opinion,  for  it  is  held  that  the  law  of  universal  causa- 
tion must  hold  for  the  mental  as  well  as  the  physical  world. 
Changes  often  occur  in  consciousness  with  no  consciousness, 
i.  e. ,  with  no  consciously  observable  cause ;  therefore  they  must 
have  an  unconscious  mental  cause.  The  problem  reduces 
therefore  to  one  of  epistemology;^  the  identification  of  con- 
sciousness and  the  psychic  or  the  extension  of  "  psychic"  to 
cover  the  accompaniment  of  all  material  changes.  As  Hellpach 
points  out,  the  unconscious  can  never  be  discovered  by  investi- 
gation, but  only  by  hypothesis,  by  analogy,  or  metaphysics. 
He  who  denies  the  unconscious  retreats  to  the  empirical  and 
has  to  explain  all  from  the  conscious  side  in  which  there  are 
vast  gaps.  If  he  makes  any  assumptions  he  must  say  that 
consciousness  causes  physical  changes  and  these  again  con- 
scious ones,  which  is  the  interactionist's  position,  or  that 
physical  and  mental  changes  are  parallel,  which  is  the  posi- 
tion of  either  monistic  or  dualistic  parallelism. ^  The  attitude 
one  takes  reduces,  therefore,  ultimately,  to  a  question  of  his 
temperament.  Practically,  it  makes  little  difference  whether 
one  assumes  the  changes  going  on  without  consciousness  but 
later  affecting  it  to  be  complex  neural  changes  only,^  or  changes 
possessing  the  conscious  character  in  structure  but  lacking 
the  conscious  quality,  or  a  psychic  reality  accompanying 
all  existence,  or  a  psychic  accompaniment  of  molecular 
changes  different  in  degree  from  those  underlying  conscious 
experiences. 

Let  us  consider  somewhat  more  fully  the  use  of  the  terms 
"unconscious  psychic  process"  in  this  metaphysical  sense  of 
the  psychic  accompaniment  of  physical  processes  lacking 
the  conscious  quality.  By  consciousness  we  mean  that  in- 
definable ultimate  best  described  as  experience  or  awareness. 
It  is  not  identical  with  self-consciousness,  which  is  only  con- 
sciousness of  one's  past  states  of  consciousness,  immediate  or 
remote.  Consciousness  is  the  broader  term.  Conscious  states, 
however,  are  those  which  can  become  self-conscious  later. 
Consciousness  is  always  more  or  less  complex,  the  elements 
entering  therein  contributing  to  the  character  of  the  whole, 
which  is  qualitatively  different  from  these  elements.  It  is 
the  interconnection  of  the  psychic  processes,  i.e.yit  is  the  associa- 
tion of  the   elements    constituting  it.     Where  association  is 

^Miinsterberg,  H.:  Symposium  on  the  Subconscious,  Jour.  Abnormal  Psy. 
II.    1907-08,  p.  28. 

'Hellpach:  Das  Unbewusste,  Central,  f.  Nervenheilkunde  und  Psychiatrie, 
1908,  Bd.  31,  S.  65-6. 

'Miinsterberg;     Psychotherapy,  N.  Y.,  1909,  p.  140;  p.  147. 

Journal — 3 


lyo  ORDAHL 

strongest  consciousness  is  most  intense.  We  assume  the  exist- 
ence of  a  psychic  side  concomitant  with  all  material  changes, 
both  conscious  and  unconscious.  "Unconscious"  we  use  as 
diametrically  opposed  to  "conscious,"  "psychic  process"  in 
the  metaphysical  sense  of  the  psychic  side  of  a  process  possess- 
ing a  concomitant  physical  side.  Such  a  psychic  side  we  con- 
ceive to  be  present  in  all  organic  matter,  if  not  in  all  matter. 
With  the  activity  of  each  neuron,  therefore,  there  is  psychic 
process,  but  consciousness  probably  does  not  occur  until  there 
is  a  complex  functioning  of  neurons  in  one  system  or  pattern. 
The  pattern  may  change  and  shift  in  its  organization,  now 
dropping  out  some  elements  now  taking  up  others,  but  the 
whole  is  usually  in  a  more  or  less  close  functional  connection. 
It  is  however  conceivable  that  two  or  more  different  complexes 
may  be  functioning  with  sufficient  intensity  to  give  different 
alternating  or  simultaneously  existing  streams  of  conscious- 
ness. Association  of  an  aggregate  with  the  personal  ag- 
gregate is  probably  necessary  for  consciousness  —  in  other 
words,  association  of  elements  with  the  general  bodily  sensa- 
tions and  feelings  which  constitute  the  fundamental  part  of 
our  personality — what  Bleuler  probably  means  by  "the  asso- 
ciation with  the  ego-complex." 

According  to  this  view  ideas  out  of  consciousness  do  not 
become  physiological  processes  any  more  than  they  were  such 
before.  We  must  assume  some  disintegration  of  the  neuron 
aggregates  underlying  the  idea  and  with  this  disintegration 
some  change  in  the  idea  itself,  according  to  which  it  no  longer 
possesses  its  former  character,  but  is  the  psychic  accompani- 
ment of  the  physiological  process. 

As  for  the  objection  to  the  term  "unconscious  psychic  pro- 
cess," we  agree  with  Lipps^  that  every  psychic  process  is 
unconscious.  All  that  is  given  in  experience  is  each  separate 
state  of  consciousness,  the  process  underlying  the  sequence 
of  ideas  or  feelings  never  being  a  matter  of  consciousness,  but 
something  which  is  merely  inferred.  The  inspirations  of  the 
poet  and  the  associations  of  the  genius  are  not  more  spontaneous 
than  those  of  the  ordinary  man,  only  richer  and  more  varied. 
The  ordinary  man  may  be  able  to  trace  and  explain  the  se- 
quences better  than  his  more  fortunate  brother,  but  the  pro- 
cesses underlying  them  are  none  the  less  unconscious. 

As  for  "free-rising"  ideas,  or  "mediate"  associations, 
conscious  connective  links,  rapidly  forgotten,  without  doubt 
exist  in  many  cases.  When  the  idea  can  be  traced  to  an 
association  started  from  some  external  cause,  of  which  the 
subject  was  absolutely  unconscious,  a  peripheral  physiological 

*Ivipps,  T.:  Leitfaden  d.  Psychologic,  I^ipzig,  1909,  p.  83  f. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RlSlyATlON  TO   I^EARNING  171 

excitation  has  probably  set  into  action  a  neuron  complex  out 
of  connection  with  the  main  system,  which  is  concerned  in 
some  other  different  state  of  consciousness.  When  this  widens 
and  the  emphasis  of  activity  shifts,  the  aggregate  stimulated 
peripherally,  without  conscious,  but  with  psychic,  accom- 
paniment may  be  taken  up  in  the  new  arrangement  of  neuron 
complexes  and  become  conscious.  But  sometimes  an  idea 
enters  with  no  traceable  connection.  Here  aggregates  con- 
cerned in  the  ''free  rising'  *  idea  may  be  in  a  state  of  functional 
activity  of  a  greater  or  less  degree  but  separated  from  the 
centre  of  activity.  Cells  concerned  but  slightly  in  the  con- 
scious processes  of  the  moment  may  set  in  activity  others  in- 
volved in  the  detached  aggregate,  which  functions  then  with 
such  completeness  as  to  shift  the  centre  of  activity  from  the 
original  to  the  new  position,  the  new  idea  becoming  the  centre 
of  consciousness. 

The  divided  consciousness  of  multiple  personality,  and 
similar  states  sometimes  experienced  by  normal  individuals 
in  dreams  or  abstracted  conditions  where  consciousness  seems 
to  be  divided  into  two  alternating  or  coincident  streams,  is 
of  the  same  general  character  as  consciousness.  The  term 
'  *  co-consciousness' '  is  a  better  name  for  this  experience  than 
"subconsciousness,"  and  is  more  definite  in  its  meaning. 
Used  in  such  a  sense  "subconscious"  is  too  easily  extended, 
even  by  the  writer  who  so  uses  it,  to  cover  something  which  is 
literally  under  consciousness,  out  of  which  consciousness 
arises  and  into  which  it  descends.  Used  in  such  a  way,  it  takes 
the  place  of  the  older  concept  of  the  "soul' '  as  an  independent 
creative  entity.  Just  as  the  soul  was  responsible  for  our 
actions  or  looked  out  upon  our  thoughts,  so  its  successor,  the 
"subconscious  self"  is  supposed  to  do. 

Consciousness  does  not  fade  off  from  distinctness  by  ever 
fainter  degrees  into  unconsciousness.  Facts  in  the  margin 
of  consciousness  are  qualitatively  the  same  as  those  in  the 
focus,  but  the  difference  between  the  outer  limits  of  the  mar- 
gin and  the  region  beyond  is  absolute.  "Subconscious," 
when  used  to  denote  the  periphery  of  the  conscious  field, 
is  a  term  descriptive  of  a  condition  of  actual  consciousness, 
different  in  degree;  but  as  it  is  too  easily  extended  to  de- 
scribe processes  outside  of  consciousness,  "perceptual"  is 
a  better  term. 

Analysis  shows  that  expressions  like  * '  resting  back  on  the  sub- 
conscious" in  prayer  and  meditation  mean  the  relieving  of 
mental  tension  by  widening  attention,  so  that  activity  can 
shift  from  newer,  less  firmly  established  association  com- 
plexes to  older,  well  developed  complexes  which  have  had 
survival  value.     The  individual  is  "larger  than  his  conscious- 


I 


172  ORDAHIy 

ness,* '  in  that  consciousness  at  best  is  so  narrow  as  to  embrace 
but  a  small  part  of  the  results  of  his  own  past  habits  and  ex- 
periences, and  those  of  the  race  seen  in  tendencies,  appetencies 
or  instincts.  In  such  a  sense  any  present  experience  is  only  to 
a  small  degree  determined  by  conscious  factors.  One's 
motives  for  action  are  seldom  clearly  analyzed  or  made  focal 
in  consciousness.  Oftener  they  are  entirely  without  conscious- 
ness, being  the  results  of  past  experiences  and  training  which 
have  developed  characteristic  modes  of  spontaneous  response. 
• 

CONSCIOUSNESS   IN   ANIMAI^S 

No  objective  proof  of  consciousness  in  animals  is  possible,^ 
but  the  assumption  of  consciousness  in  them  rests  on  in- 
ference, just  as  it  does  in  our  fellow  beings,  for  the  only  place 
it  can  be  positively  known  is  in  the  individual  himself.  Deny- 
ing the  possibility  of  comparative  psychology  would  there- 
fore logically  result  in  a  like  attitude  toward  human  psychol- 
ogy.2  Any  objective  criterion  of  consciousness  must  be 
arbitrary.  "Learning"  or  "modifiability  of  behavior"  as 
an  indication  of  its  presence  is  not  good,  for  there  is  evidence 
that  plants  learn,^  and  even  material*  objects  adapt  them- 
selves to  repeated  stimuli  or  changed  conditions  as  the  season- 
ing of  a  violin  to  strains  of  the  master.  There  are  also  some 
indications  that  human  learning  goes  on  unconsciously. 

III.    The  REI.ATION  OF  Consciousness  to  Learning 

The  relation  of  consciousness  to  learning  has  received  some 
discussion  as  well  as  experimental  testing.  The  problem  of 
learning  in  general  I  have  reviewed  elsewhere^  and  shall 
consider  here  only  the  results  bearing  directly  on  the  subject 
in  hand. 

THE  LEARNING  PROCESS 

We  may  define  learning  as  the  formation  of  associations 
between  certain  stimuli  and  definite  modes  of  reaction.  The 
simpler  and  less  varied  the  stimuli  the  simpler  the  learning 
process  will  necessarily  be,  and  the  more  permanent  the  value  of 

^Yerkes,  R.  M. :  Objective  Nomenclature,  Comparative  Psychology  and 
Animal  Behavior,  Jour  Comp.  Neur.  and  Psy.,  1906,  XVI,  p.  388. 

'Clapar^de,  E.:  La  psychologic  comparee,  est-elle  legitime?  Arch,  de 
psy.,  1905-6,  V.  p.  34- 

^Darwin  and  Pertz:  On  the  Artificial  Production  of  Rhythm  in  Plants. 
Annals  of  BoL,  1903,  XVII,  pp.  93-106. 

*Washburn,  M.  F.:  Animal  Mind,  N.  Y.,  1908,  p.  33. 

Claparede,  E.:  The  Consciousness  of  Animals.  Internal.  Quart.,  1903-4. 
VIII,  pp.  296-315. 

"Ellison,  L. :  The  Acquisition  of  Technical  Skill,  Fed.  Sent.,  1909,  XVI,  pp. 
49-63. 


CONSCIOUSNESS   IN   R^I^ATION  TO   LEARNING  1 73 

the  associations  formed,  the  simplest  form  probably  being  that 
in  the  case  of  lower  animals  where  the  association  is  between 
a  single  stimulus  and  a  simple  movement,  the  highest  and 
most  complex  form  in  man,  where  complicated  movements 
must  often  be  preceded  by  a  train  of  thought  possessing  little 
motor  accompaniment.  The  simplest  form  of  learning  in- 
volves, then,  direct  motor  response  to  a  simple  stimulus,  the 
highest,  however,  lacks  much  of  this  motor  element,  being 
for  the  most  part  an  association  of  symbols,  such  as  the  growth 
in  meaning  of  words,  and  the  power  of  generalization  from 
previous  experience.  Most  learning  involves  both  these 
factors. 

Observation  and  experiment  goes  to  show  that  learning 
to  meet  any  new  situation  involves  a  specialization  and  per- 
fection of  some  part  of  an  already  existing  habit  or  mental 
possession.  As  Morgan  points  out,  effective  consciousness^ 
finds  itself  a  partner  in  a  "going  concern."  The  perform- 
ance of  the  instinctive  act  whose  co-ordinations  are  heredi- 
tary, and  the  consciousness  such  a  performance  evokes,  are 
simultaneous.^  The  behavior  and  the  conditions  producing 
it  occupy  consciousness,  but  "the  effects  of  the  behavior, 
as  the  animal  becomes  conscious  of  the  acts  concerned,  serve 
to  complete  and  render  definite  the  conscious  situation.  Con- 
sciousness, however,  probably  receives  information  of  the 
net  results  of  the  progress  of  behavior  and  not  of  the  minute 
and  separate  details  of  muscular  contraction."^  As  Sherring- 
ton puts  it,  "the  controlling  centres  can  pick  out  from  some 
ancestrally  given  motor  reaction  some  part  of  it  so  as  to 
isolate  that  as  a  separate  movement,  and  by  enhancement 
this  can  become  a  skilled  adapted  act  added  to  the  powers  of 
the  individual."'*  When  a  new  movement  is  initiated  an  ex- 
cess of  energy  is  expended  and  with  it  occur  many  more  or 
less  random  movements;  of  these,  as  the  effort  is  repeated, 
a  special  movement,  or  a  special  series,  finally  stands  out 
from  the  scattered  mass.  The  clearer  its  separateness  from 
the  rest,  the  more  vivid  its  conscious  accompaniment  and 
the  power  of  conscious  control.  Consciousness  of  the  way 
a  movement  feels  is  necessary  for  its  voluntary  performance, 
hence,  as  Judd's^  experiments  show,  an  abstract  idea  cannot 

^Morgan,  C.  L.:  Introduction  to  Comparative  Psychology,  N.  Y.,  1906, 

P-  51. 

^Ibid.,  pp.  99,  loi. 

^Ihid.,  p.  105. 

^Sherrington,  C.  S. :  Integrative  Action  of  the  Nervous  System,  N.  Y., 
1906,  p.  389. 

5Judd,  C.  H. :  Practice  and  its  Effects  on  the  Perception  of  Illusions,  Psy. 
Rev.,  1902,  IX,  pp.  27-59. 


174  ORDAHI* 

take  the  place  of  direct  perceptual  experience.  The  way  to 
get  control  of  a  movement  as  the  experiments  of  Bair^  and  of 
Swift^  show,  is  by  working  outward  from  some  general  move- 
ment over  which  we  already  have  control.  In  Bair's  ex- 
periment on  learning  to  move  the  ears,  the  subjects  began 
with  the  muscles  over  which  they  had  conscious  control, 
such  as  raising  the  brow,  clinching  the  teeth,  making  more 
and  more  strenuous  effort  to  get  closer  to  the  ear,  an  excess 
of  motor  energy  being  discharged  with  proximate  muscles. 
"As  soon  as  the  sensation  arising  from  the  movement  of  the 
ear  was  associated  with  the  concomitant  sensations  of  muscles 
close  to  it,  over  which  there  was  already  voluntary  control, 
there  was  a  basis  for  learning  the  voluntary  control  of  the  ear." 
The  definite  idea  of  the  movement  given  by  electrical  stim- 
ulation of  the  retrahens  muscle  was  not  sufficient  to  produce 
the  movement,  but  it  gave  a  general  idea  as  to  the  direction 
the  innervation  was  to  take.  As  control  developed  attention 
was  narrowed  down  from  the  general  sensation  of  the  adjacent 
muscles  to  that  of  the  specific  movement  sought  for.  Like- 
wise, in  the  control  of  the  reflex  wink,  Swift  found  it  necessary 
to  begin  with  the  muscles  around  the  eyes  over  which  there 
was  conscious  control.  What  Bair'  says  in  regard  to  the 
general  ability  given  by  special  training,  e.  g.,  "to  a  new 
situation  we  react  by  a  general  discriminative  reaction  and 
are  more  likely  to  hit  on  a  favorable  response  than  without 
this  special  training,"  is  true  of  all  learning.  For  no  matter 
what  new  acquisition  is  undertaken,  if  it  is  possible  to  master 
it,  some  previous  general  training  has  either  been  developed 
by  the  individual  or  through  the  inherited  co-ordinations  of 
his  ancestors.  Experiments  on  acquisitions  of  a  more  complex 
kind  show  the  same  fact — attentive  consciousness  cannot 
be  directly  and  advantageously  applied  at  first,  because  of 
the  multiplicity  of  details  which  overwhelm  it.  The  new 
experience  calls  up  too  many  old  associations  which  are  not 
pertinent.  Such  facts  account  for  the  rapid  rise  of  the  learn- 
ing curve  at  first,  when  responses  are  selected  from  a  mass  of 
older  habitual  reactions,  and  its  slower  ascent  later,  when 
associations  really  new  are  being  formed. 

ClyKAR  CONSCIOUSNieSS  AND  LEARNING 

The  importance  of  clear  consciousness  in  learning  is  shown 
by  the  following  facts.     Experiences  causing  greatest  atten- 

ifiair,  J.  H.:  Development  of  Voluntary  Control,  Psy.  Rev.,  Yllh 
p.  499. 

^Swift,  E.  J.:  Studies  in  the  Physiology  and  Psychology  of  Learning, 
Am.  Jour.  Psy.,  1903,  XIV,  pp.  200-251. 

^Bair,  J.  H.:  The  Practice  Curve,  Psy.  Rev.,  Mon.  Sup.,  1902  V. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN   RBLATION  TO   I.EARNING  1 75 

tion  are  best  remembered.  Desire  to  succeed  and  intense 
effort  are  necessary  for  progress,  which  means  that  one  must 
attend  closely  to  the  matter  at  hand.  Even  in  learning  of  a 
purely  muscular  sort,  where  attention  to  the  movement  it- 
self has  been  found  to  be  a  hindrance,  attention  to  the  object- 
ive features  of  the  task  is  required  for  the  perfection  of  the  un- 
conscious or  dimly  conscious  part  of  the  reaction.  The  fact 
that  subjects  of  a  given  mental  type  are  most  interfered  with 
in  their  learning,  by  distractions  appealing  to  that  type  of 
imagery,  shows  that  undisturbed  consciousness  is  essential. 
Trying  to  recite  a  syllable  series  is  more  effective  in  establish- 
ing the  syllables  than  merely  reading  them,^  because  of  the  nar- 
rower attention  required.  Figures  drawn  with  the  left  hand 
are  better  remembered  than  those  drawn  with  the  right,  for 
the  same  reason  ;2  the  greater  ease  of  remembering  sense 
material  as  compared  with  nonsense  is  also  probably  due  in 
part  to  the  easier  application  of  attention. 

Results  from  experiments  on  cross  education  point  to  like 
conditions,  for  the  more  similar  the  training  and  the  test 
material  the  greater  the  transference.^  Improvement  con- 
sists in  more  economic  methods  of  work,*  and  is  essentially 
"attention  training."  Transference  consists  in  the  carrying 
over  of  right  hand  "methods"  to  the  left  hand.  Perhaps 
the  most  adequate  study  of  this  problem  is  a  recent  one  by 
Fracker,^  who  finds  that  the  most  essential  element  in  trans- 
ference is  imagery  and  that  improvement  occurs  if  imagery 
is  developed  in  the  training  series  which  can  be  transferred 
and  advantageously  used  in  the  test  series.  It  may  be  sub- 
consciously developed,  but  if  it  comes  to  be  consciously 
recognized,  the  improvement  is  more  rapid.  "The  rate  of  im- 
provement seems  to  depend  directly  upon  the  conscious  rec- 
ognition of  the  imagery  and  upon  attention  to  its  use.  The 
transference  of  elements  is  a  conscious  transference."  Im- 
provement during  intervals  of  no  practice  seems  to  be  due 
in  part  to  freshness  and  better  attention,  in  part  to  the  fact 
that  interfering  habits  are  forgotten,  so  that  better  and  more 

^Witasek,  S. :  Ueber  Lesen  tind  Rezitieren.  .  Zeits.  f.  Psy.,  1907  Bd.  44; 
pp.  161-185;  246-282 

Katzaroff,  D.:  Experiences  sur  le  r61e  de  la  recitation,  ^rcA.  de  Psy., 
1908,  VII,  pp.  255-8. 

2Rowe  and  Washburn:  The  Motor  Memory  of  the  Left  Hand,  Am.  Jour. 
Psy.,  1908,  XIX,  p.  243. 

^Ebert  u.  Meumann:  Ueber  einige  Gnindfragen  der  Psychologic  der 
Uebungsphanomene,  Arch.f.  d.  ges.  Psy.  1905,  IV,  S  i — 232. 

*Swift:  Op.  cit. 

^Fracker,  G.  C:  On  the  Transference  of  Training  in  Memory,  Psy.  Rev., 
Mon.  Sup.,  IX,  1908,  56-102. 


176  ORDAHL 

practiced  ones  may  be  free  to  assert  themselves.^  Then,  too, 
attention  is  not  distracted  by  the  new  elements  of  the  situation, 
but  can  be  more  economically  applied.  The  value  of  clear 
consciousness  in  learning  is  that  it  assists  the  selecting  of 
good  elements  from  the  complex  reaction  and  the  eliminating 
of  disadvantageous  factors.  When  the  subject  is  weary  he 
is  apt  to  fall  into  bad  habits  which  are  more  difl&cult  to  modify 
because  unconscious. 

Consciousness  of  details  and  elements  of  a  process  grad- 
ually gives  place  to  consciousness  of  larger  and  more  complex 
diflSculties.  These  elements  gradually  form  themselves  into 
larger  wholes  and  consciousness  works  with  greater  units. 
This  is  true  not  only  of  muscular  learning,  but  of  more  in- 
tellectual activities  such  as  typewriting,  the  telegraph  lan- 
guage and  chess.  As  Cleveland^  puts  it,  with  reference  to 
chess,  "  learing  requires  the  perfection  of  the  elements  and  their 
organization  into  ever  larger  groups,  so  that  attention  is  not 
bound  to  details,  but  left  free  to  forge  ahead  and  anticipate 
difi&culties."  In  the  writing  processes,  first  letters,  then 
words,  then  sentences  are  grasped.  In  chess  one  grasps  the 
situation  by  larger  and  larger  wholes.  Cleveland  puts  it  thus, 
"Progress  in  chess  consists  in  the  formation  of  an  increas- 
ing symbolism  which  permits  the  manipulation  of  larger  and 
larger  complexes.  .  .  .  There  is  something  in  the  purely 
intellectual  life  corresponding  to  motor  automatism,  which  is 
shown  in  the  ability  to  think  symbolically  or  abstractly,  and 
thus  to  handle  large  masses  of  detail  with  a  minimum  of  con- 
scious effort.  It  involves  the  increasing  ability  to  take  in 
during  a  single  pulse  of  attention  a  larger  and  larger  group 
of  details  which  means,  of  course,  that  the  attention  is  no 
longer  needed  for  each  one." 

The  importance  of  the  'motor  element  in  learning  verbal 
material  is  without  doubt  due  to  clearer  consciousness  of  the 
task,  the  material  appealing  not  only  to  vision,  but  to  hear- 
ing and  the  kinsesthetic  senses. 

SUBCONSCIOUS  AND  UNCONSCIOUS  LEARNING 

Such  are  some  of  the  observations  as  to  the  r61e  of  conscious- 
ness in  learning,  but  much  of  our  learning  goes  on  below  con- 
sciousness. As  Kuhlmann^  points  out,  much  of  our  most  im- 
portant learning — the  use  and  functional  activity  of  our  own 

^Book,  W.  F.:  The  Psychology  of  Skill,  U.  of  Montana  Bull.,  No. 
53,   1908,  p.  6  £F. 

^Cleveland,  A.  A. :  The  Psychology  of  Chess  and  Learning  to  Play  it. 
Am.  Jour.  Psy.,  1907,  XVIII,  pp.  269-308. 

^Kuhlmann,  F.:  The  Place  of  Mental  Imagery  and  Memory  among 
Mental  Fimctions.  Am.  Jour.  Psy.,  1905,  XVI,  p.  337-356. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO    LEARNING  1 77 

bodies — goes  on  with  no  conscious  direction.  The  digestive 
apparatus  must  learn  to  do  its  work,  and  so  must  other  internal 
organs  Early  reflexes  such  as  the  reflex  wink  and  mimetic 
expressions,  binocular  vision,  the  co-ordination  of  voluntary 
muscles,  develop  without  voluntary  use  of  incoming  stimuli 
for  their  guidance. 

The  very  possibility  of  learning  rests  on  an  unconscious 
basis  of  physiological  endowment.  The  dullard  and  the 
genius  are  alike  dependent  upon  their  physiological  inherit- 
ance, and  the  quick  wits  of  the  healthy  child  are  as  much 
beyond  his  conscious  control  as  are  those  of  the  feeble  defective. 

We  are  not  conscious  of  the  "process"  underlying  our 
associations,  but  merely  of  the  results  as  they  present  them- 
selves to  consciousness.  In  fact  learning  may  progress  with- 
out our  knowledge  of  the  fact,  as  is  seen  in  the  development 
of  unconscious  automatisms.  For  example,  one  may  develop 
peculiar  manners  of  gait  or  expression  without  knowledge, 
having  unconsciously  imitated  some  one  possessing  a  like 
peculiarity.  Through  the  ever  present  suggestions  of  a  new 
environment  we  may  develop  new  ideals  and  new  apperceptive 
attitudes  of  which  we  are  unconscious  until  we  are  taken  back 
to  our  old  surroundings.  In  learning  of  a  muscular  sort  we 
may  have  been  conscious  of  every  sensation  leading  up  to  the 
subsequent  habit,  without  consciousness  of  the  method  in 
which  we  work,  or  of  the  existence  of  the  habit  itself.  An 
example  is  given  by  Pfungst.^  Having  directed  his  subjects 
to  think  of  one  of  two  similarly  sounding  words  of  a  series 
to  which  he  would  respond  with  certain  arm  movements, 
he  was  able  to  tell  by  the  direction  of  the  head  or  eye  move- 
ments, of  which  word  they  were  thinking  and  to  which  they 
expected  him  to  react.  By  changing  his  manner  of  respond- 
ing he  obtained  a  similar  change  in  their  movements.  He  was 
also  able  to  tell  by  head  movements  of  which  direction,  left 
or  right,  his  subjects  were  thinking.  He  concludes  that  "the 
changing  of  natural  movements  of  expression  and  the  acquisi- 
tion of  new  ones  are  both  possible  without  knowledge  of  the 
person." 

Our  environment  is  one  of  the  strongest  factors  in  training 
us,  whether  it  operates  consciously  or  unconsciously.  One 
hears  good  language  continuously,  and  easily  forms  the  habit 
of  using  it  himself.  The  development  of  our  ethical  ideals  and 
aesthetic  feelings  and  our  very  forms  of  thinking  unfold  before 
we  are  conscious  of  their  existence.  Such  habit  formation 
rests  on  instinctive  imitation  and  forms  one  of  the  most  im- 
portant classes  of  learning. 

^Pfungst,  O.:  Das  Pferd  des  Herrn  von  Osten,  Leipzig,  1907,  p.  77  ff. 


178  ORDAHL 

Learning  may  also  progress  without  consciousness  of  the 
end  or  purpose.  Such  a  fact  has  its  best  illustration  in  the 
instinctive  activities  of  animals  and  the  play  of  children 
and  animals.  Play  is  a  training  process  for  life  where  most 
of  the  activities  required  in  later  life  have  their  initial,  though 
unwitting,  development. 

The  formation  and  strengthening  of  associations  below  con- 
sciousness is  indicated  by  some  of  the  laboratory  experiments 
on  learning.  This  must  be  the  explanation  of  the  fact  that 
scattered  repetitions,  which  deal  with  older  associations, 
give  best  results.  Miiller  and  Pilzecker  think  the  greater 
strength  of  the  older  associations  is  due  to  the  tendency  of 
an  excitation  to  outlast  the  stimulus — to  a  "perseveration 
tendency" — as  a  result  of  which  an  idea  rises  of  its  own  accord 
into  consciousness  without  associative  connections.  Illus- 
trations other  than  those  found  in  learning  nonsense  syllables 
are  the  following:  The  histologist's  illusion  which  occurs 
after  working  long  and  intently  with  the  microscope;  images 
seen  with  closed  eyes  often  have  then  the  character  of  the  micro- 
scopic forms.  Similarly  when  one  studies  or  thinks  intently 
of  any  subject,  carelessly  perceived  objects  tend  to  take  on 
its  character.  While  studying  the  anatomy  of  the  internal 
ear  every  gas  jet  or  twisted  twig  was  a  cochlea,  for  the  writer. 
It  is  not  uncommon  to  see,  before  sleeping,  scenes  which  have 
passed  before  the  eyes  while  traveUing,  or  on  a  tramp.  "  Crys- 
tal vision' '  may  illustrate  the  same  phenomenon,  freeing  the 
mind  for  the  appearance  of  ideas  underlying  which  is  this 
perseveration  tendency.  This  fixing  of  the  association 
probably  goes  on  physiologically  whether  the  ideas  crop  out 
into  consciousness  or  not,  for  Miiller  and  Pilzecker  found  that 
attention  to  any  other  engrossing  matter  prevented  their  re- 
call, although  free  reproduction  was  not  a  tendency  with  all 
their  subjects;  nor  was  the  hindrance  due  to  preventing  the 
subject  from  thinking  over  the  series.  They  conclude  that 
"after  the  reading  of  a  syllable  series,  certain  physiological 
processes  which  serve  for  the  strengthening  of  the  associations 
formed  by  the  reading  of  a  series  continue  for  a  certain  time 
with  gradually  diminishing  intensity."^ 

"Retroactive  amnesia"  or  the  forgetting,  after  a  shock, 
of  incidents  extending  backward  from  the  shock  to  several 
hours  or  more,  likewise  points  to  the  probability  of  the  phy- 
siological fixing  of  associations.^ 

Experiments  on  the  acquisition  of  skill  show  that  uncon- 
scious habits  are  developed  which  consciousness  either  selects 

^Miiller  u.  Pilzecker:  Zeit.f.  Psych.,  Erganzungsband  I,  1900.     p.  196. 
^Bumham,  W.  H.:  Retroactive  Amnesia.     Am.  Jour.  Psy.,  1903,  XIV, 
p.  386-7. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO   LEARNING  1 79 

or  represses.  As  Swift  says,  "Consciousness  discovers  certain 
methods  in  operation  and  approves  or  disapproves  them."^ 
Subjects  improve  by  "hitting  upon"  better  ways  of  working, 
without  any  further  conscious  selection,  at  first,  than  the 
general  effort  to  succeed.  Book's  experiment  shows  the  same 
thing.  "A  mass  of  old  associations  are  called  up,  only  a  few 
of  which  are  directly  serviceable  for  the  work.  From  these  there 
are  unconsciously  built  up,  by  the  double  process  of  elimination 
and  selection  and  reorganization,  the  first  elementary  associa- 
tions (letter  associations)  used,  and  from  these  in  turn  the  later, 
higher  order  habits.  There  comes  to  be  .  .  .a  sort  of  uncon- 
scious struggle  for  existence  among  the  many  modes  of  action, 
ending  in  the  survival  of  the  one  direct  and  economic  way  of 
reaching  the  goal  desired.'  '^ 

Automatization  of  elements  previously  conscious  occurs 
in  the  perfection  of  all  activities,  leaving  consciousness  free 
to  undertake  more  difficult  features. 

IV.    An   Experimental  Study   of  the   Relation   of 
Consciousness   to   I^earning 

Our  own  investigations  undertook  to  discover  by  experiment 
(i)  whether  learning  is  helped  by  factors  which  never  come 
into  consciousness,  or  are  present  only  to  a  minimal  degree, 
(2)  whether  the  formation  of  a  habit  of  whose  existence  and 
development  one  is  unconscious  can  progress  as  well  under  dis- 
traction, when  consciousness  is  removed  as  completely  as  possi- 
ble from  all  the  elements  which  go  to  make  up  the  habit  forma- 
tion ;  and  finally,  to  find  the  r61e  of  consciousness  in  learning 
simple  tasks  involving,  (3)  almost  no  intellectual  factor,  (4)  a 
complex  co-ordination  of  muscular  impluses,  and  (5)  learning 
of  purely  intellectual  character. 

I.  Do  Unnoticed  Items  Assist  in  the  Formation  of  Associative 

Links ? 

Experiment  i  was  suggested  by  Scripture's  experi- 
ments on  the  associative  course  of  ideas,^  and  work  of 
a  similar  sort,^  which  seemed  to  show  that  unnoticed 
features  of  a  total  impression  (like  an  inconspicuous  Jap- 
anese symbol  or  a  numeral  placed  beside  a  word  or  a  picture) 
could  serve  as  a  bond  to  connect  the  given  word  or  picture 
with  another  word  or  picture  which  had  been  elsewhere 
accompanied  by  the  same  symbol  or  numeral.     The  theoreti- 

^Swift,  B.  J. :  Studies  in  the  Psychology  and  Physiology  of  Learning.   Am. 
Jour.  Psy.,   1903,  XIV,  p.  201-251. 
^Book,  W.  F.:  Univ.  Montana  Bull.,  No.  53,  1908. 
'Scripture:    Op.  cit. 
*Sidis:  The  Psychology  of  Suggestion,  N.  Y.,  1898,  p.  171. 


l8o  ORDAHL 

cal  importance  of  the  question  and  the  fact  that  most  attempts 
to  repeat  Scripture's  work  had  led  to  negative  results  invited 
a  new  attack.  The  plan  which  we  undertook  may  be  illus- 
trated by  the  following  scheme,  though  the  actual  execution 
of  the  experiment  was  carried  out  with  greater  refinement 
and  in  a  different  way  as  to  details. 

The  observer  is  presented  with  a  triple  series  of  meaning- 
less syllables,  as  in  Group  I  below,  and  is  required  to  read 
series  b  a  certain  number  of  times  and  if  possible  learn  it. 
Series  a  and  c  are  of  course  all  the  time  before  his  eyes  though 
not  involved  in  his  task.  After  reading  b  the  required  number 
of  times,  his  knowledge  of  it  is  tested  by  the  "  Treffer  method,' ' 
and  his  success  in  giving  the  required  syllables  recorded. 
Then  after  a  brief  interval  he  is  presented  with  Group  II  of 
which  the  middle  series  is  the  same  as  one  of  the  side  series 
in  Group  I,  e.  g.,  series  a,  and  he  is  required  to  read  (and  learn) 
series  a  in  the  same  manner  in  which  he  has  just  read  (and 
learned)  series  b. 

Group  I  Group  II 


a 

b 

c 

jex 

mil 

peb 

yal 

hud 

yom 

bup 

gib 

lur 

dof 

dep 

zal 

tem 

voz 

bic 

fuj 

POg 

vop 

nen 

lek 

loh 

gop 

gaj 

nat 

riz 

fiv 

jof 

mod 

yem 

wam 

d 

a 

e 

miv 

jex 

hal 

sem 

yal 

M 

coj 

bup 

pom 

fet 

dof 

das 

dib 

tem 

lef 

vil 

fuj 

roj 

buj 

nen 

zup 

hix 

gop 

fab 

kug 

riz 

uls 

len 

mod 

veb 

If  a  is  on  the  average  learned  with  greater  ease  or  complete- 
ness than  by  the  inference  is  that  the  previous  presentation  of 
a  in  indirect  vision  has  somehow  been  helpful — directly  by 
rendering  the  syllables  individually  more  familiar,  or  in- 
directly through  their  association  with  the  syllables  of  series 
b  which  have  in  the  learning  been  associated  with  each  other. 
If  a  is  not  learned  on  the  average  more  easily  or  perfectly  than 
b  the  inference  is  either  that  no  assistance  is  gained  by  the 
"unconscious"  perception  of  a  or  that  the  gain  is  not  of 
sufficient  amount  to  be  determined  by  this  method  of  experi- 
mentation. 

Such  experiments  were  carried  out  on  two  trained  observers 
through  a  considerable  number  of  days,  but  it  may  be  said  at 
once  that  the  results  were  on  the  whole  negative.  There  was 
no  clear  evidence  of  any  advantage.  The  presumption  is  that 
the  assistance  gained  is  small  in  amount — too  small  to  be  deter- 


CONSCIOUSNESS   IN  RKI.ATION  TO   I.KARNING  l8l 

mined  by  this  method.  Later  experiments  undertaken  ex- 
pressly to  determine  the  deHcacy  of  the  method  showed  that 
one  reading  of  the  a  series  with  full  attention  had  no  beneficial 
effect  upon  the  learning  of  the  a  series  after  an  interval  of 
ten  minutes  during  which  the  b  series  had  been  learned. 

Though  the  results  of  this  series  of  experiments  must  there- 
fore be  set  down  as  inconclusive,  they  may  have,  perhaps,  a 
certain  value  in  other  connections  and  are  therefore  given  in 
the  Appendix  of  this  paper. 

2.     The  Effect  of  Attention  and  Distraction  on  the  Formation 
of  the  Motor  ''Set'*  (Motorische  Einstellung) 

Experiment  2.  The  purpose  of  the  second  series  of  ex- 
periments was  to  find  the  effect  on  the  ''Motorische  Einstel- 
lung** of  attention  and  distraction.  The  term  "Motorische 
Einstellung**  indicates  the  effect  which  repeated  lifting  of  a 
heavy  weight  has  in  making  subsequent  lighter  weights  seem 
too  light.  It  is  probably  due  to  a  temporary  habit  of  the 
nervous  system.  The  problem  in  our  case  was  to  discover 
whether  a  neural  habit  of  this  sort,  of  whose  existence  the 
subject  was  unaware,  would  be  more  readily  formed  when  he 
was  attending  to  the  lifting  of  the  heavy  weight  than  when  he 
was  inattentive  to  it. 

The  phenomenon  of  "Motorische  Einstellung**  was  first 
reported  by  Miiller  and  Schumann.^  They  lifted  a  moderate 
weight  of,  say,  600  grams  and,  after  it,  lifted  a  heavier  weight 
of  2,400  grams  to  an  equal  height  a  certain  number  of  times, 
in  a  definite  rhythm.  Then  a  weight  of  800  grams  was  lifted 
and  found  to  seem  lighter  than  the  600  grams,  lifted  before 
the  training  with  the  weight  of  2,400  grams.  They  explain 
the  illusion  by  saying  that  the  800  grams,  which  is  lifted  with 
an  unusually  powerful  impulse  after  the  work  with  the  weight 
of  2,400  grams,  rises  with  unusual  speed  and  therefore  seems 
lighter  than  the  first  weight,  because  we  are  apt  to  judge  as 
lighter  a  weight  which  raises  more  quickly.  The  repetition 
of  the  lifting  of  the  heavy  weight  has  set  up  a  tendency  in 
certain  sub-cortical  centres  to  discharge  automatically  with 
a  somewhat  extra  intensity.  Experimentation  of  this  kind 
was  carried  further  by  Steffens.^ 

The  apparatus  used  is  pictured  in  the  accompanying  cut. 
Two  boards  measuring  about  eighteen  inches  long  were 
clamped  to  the  sides  of  the  bottom  of  a  chair  so  that  the  ends 

^Miiller  u.  Schumann:  Ueber  die  psychologischen  Gnmdlagen  der 
Vergleichung  gehobener  Gewichte,  Pfiiiger's  Archiv,  XLV,  1889,  37-122. 

^Steffens:  Ueber  die  motorische  Einstellung.  Zeits.  f.  Psy.,  Bd.  23, 
S.    240-308. 


1 82  ORDAHI, 

extended  about  seven  inches  beyond  the  front  edge.  Holes 
were  bored  near  the  forward  ends  of  the  boards  and  through 
these  were  passed  the  ends  of  two  handles  by  which  the  weights 
were  lifted.  The  upper  parts  of  the  handles  were  made  of  wood 
and  were  provided  with  grooves  into  which  fitted  the  fingers 
of  the  observer,  enabling  him  to  hold  the  handles  firmly  and 
in  the  same  way  each  time  he  lifted.  The  handles  below  the 
board  consisted  of  brass  rods  having  at  their  lower  ends 
disks  of  wood,  on  which  the  weights  rested.  An  iron  needle 
was  passed  through  each  brass  rod  in  the  middle,  making  it 
possible  to  raise  the  handles  only  a  given  distance.  To  pre- 
vent the  needles  hitting  against  the  boards  with  a  jar,  a 
string  was  fastened  in  front  of  the  chair,  by  means  of  two  iron 
standards  clamped  to  the  table,  at  such  a  height  that  the  ob- 
server's hands  would  touch  the  string  before  the  needles  came 
in  contact  with  the  boards;  as  soon  as  the  hand  touched  the 
string  the  weight  was  lowered.  A  disk  of  cork  was  used  on 
each  handle  to  prevent  the  clinking  of  the  weights  against 
each  other.  The  entire  weight  of  each  handle  with  the 
cork  disk  was  loo  grams. 

The  chair  stood  on  one  of  the  large  laboratory  tables.  As 
far  as  possible  from  the  observer  a  metronome  was  placed, 
its  noise  being  deadened  by  a  cloth  pad  between  it  and  the 
table.  The  experimenter  sat  at  the  side  of  the  table  to  the 
observer's  left,  and  changed  the  weights  as  the  experiment 
required.  These  were  flat  and  circular  in  form  with  a  rather 
large  slit  so  that  they  would  slip  on  and  off  the  handles  easily. 

The  method  of  the  experiment  was  this:  The  right-hand 
weight  was  always  the  standard,  and  was  always  kept  at  300 
grams,  i.  e.,  a  200  gr.  weight  plus  the  weight  of  the  handles. 
By  trying  different  weights  a  weight  was  found  for  the  left 
hand  which  usually  seemed  equal  to  the  right-hand  weight. 
Owing  to  the  difference  in  strength  between  the  right  and 
left  hands  this  was  actually  a  weight  much  smaller  than  the 
standard.  Since  practice  was  apt  to  increase  the  strength 
of  the  left  hand,  it  was  necessary  to  determine  what  this  weight 
was  before  every  experiment;  and  doing  this  counteracted 
also  any  influence  which  might  have  been  carried  over  from 
lifting  heavy  weights  in  the  experiment  of  a  previous  day. 
After  determining  the  apparently  equal  weight,  twenty  judg- 
ments were  made,  upon  weights  offered  for  comparison  with  the 
standard  (300  grams  in  the  right  hand),  four  with  the  weight 
which  had  been  judged  equal,  and  four  each  with  weights  ten 
and  twenty  grams  above  and  ten  and  twenty  grams  below 
the  "equal"  weight.  If  the  judgments  were  perfect  the 
results  would  of  course  show  four  judgments  "equal,"  eight 
"heavier"  and  eight  "lighter."     As  a  matter  of  fact  they 


Oy 


i^ 


Fig.  I. 


\ 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO   LEARNING  1 83 

varied  a  little,  this  way  and  that,  as  is  common  in  such  ex- 
periments. The  lifting  was  done  rhythmically  to  the  stroke 
of  the  metronome,  which  beat  at  about  four  per  second  for 
the  different  observers,  some  requiring  a  slower  rhythm  than 
others.  The  rhythm  was  constant,  however,  for  each  subject. 
At  *  *  one* '  the  standard  was  raised,  at '  *  two' '  lowered,  on  * '  three' ' 
the  comparison  weight  was  raised  and  on  "four"  lowered. 

The  results  of  the  twenty  lifts  just  described  served  as  a 
basis  of  comparison  for  similar  lifts  after  a  period  of  lifting  a 
heavier  weight  to  establish  the  Einstellung.  This  heavy  weight, 
which  was  called  the  "training"  weight,  was  for  all  subjects 
a  weight  twice  as  great  as  the  one  which  had  seemed  equal. 
The  experiment  here  differed  a  little  in  its  method  for  the 
lifting  "with  attention"  and  "with  distraction,"  though 
the  actual  weight  lifted  and  the  rhythm  for  lifting  were  the 
same  for  each.  In  the  experiment  "with  attention,"  the 
subject  was  told  that  he  must  determine,  by  estimation,  a 
weight  twice  that  of  the  standard,  and  that  he  would  be  given 
two  weights  above  and  two  weights  below  this  double  weight, 
and  sometimes  the  double  weight  itself.  He  was  to  raise 
the  standard  just  as  he  had  done  in  the  previous  judgments 
of  equals,  which  would  aid  him  in  his  judgment,  and  he  was  to 
judge  as  quickly  as  possible.  Here  the  standard  was  raised 
on  "one,* '  lowered  on  "two,"  a  pause  on  "three,"  the  variable 
raised  on  "four,"  lowered  on  "five,**  and  the  judgment  given 
immediately.  While  the  judgment  was  being  given  the  ex- 
perimenter shifted  the  weights,  and  the  subject  began  to 
raise  the  standard  in  nearly  all  cases  after  the  sixth  count. 
The  method  of  lifting  was  at  first  not  carried  out  in  this  three- 
six  rhythm,  but  in  a  two-four  rhythm ;  but  was  changed  after 
three  days  of  experimentation  to  make  the  rhythm  the  same 
for  the  experiments  "with  attention*'  and  "with  distraction.'* 
All  the  results  are  incorporated  in  the  tables  which  follow,  as 
the  change  of  rhythm  seemed  to  have  no  disturbing  effect. 
Ten  judgments  w^ere  made,  four  of  the  weights  being  greater 
than  the  "double**  weight,  four  less,  and  two  the  "double 
weight*  *  itself,  so  that  the  actual  weight  lifted  amounted  to 
lifting  the  double  weight  ten  times.  Immediately  after 
giving  the  tenth  judgment  the  five  original  {i.  e.,  nearly 
"equal*  *)  weights  were  compared  with  the  standard,  to  test  the 
Einstellung,  and  the  results  recorded.  After  a  rest  of  from  one 
to  two  minutes  the  double  weight  was  raised  five  times  more, 
in  the  manner  just  described,  to  refresh  the  Einstellung;  and 
immediately  after,  the  original  (nearly  "equal'*)  weights  were 
again  compared.  This  was  done  until  the  training  weight  had 
been  raised  twenty  times  in  all  and  the  original  weights  had 
been  compared  twenty  times.     In   schematic   form    the  ex- 


184  ORDAHL 

periment  was:  (i)  to  determine  a  weight  which  when  lifted 
by  the  left  hand  should  seem  equal  to  the  standard  weight, 
when  lifted  by  the  right  hand.  This  was  done  by  offering 
the  original  weights  in  such  a  way  that  the  "equal"  weight 
was  raised  four  times,  the  ten  and  twenty  grams  "heavier," 
four  times  each,  and  the  ten  and  twenty  grams  lighter,  four 
times  each.  (2)  Ten  lifts  of  the  training  weight,  followed  by 
five  comparisons  of  the  original  weights  arranged  according 
to  a  regular  permutation.  (3)  Five  lifts  of  the  training  weight, 
with  five  judgments  of  the  original  weights.  (4)  Repetition  of 
(3).  (5)  Repetition  of  (3). 

The  experiment  ' '  with  distraction' '  differed  from  that  with 
full  attention  only  in  so  far  as  lifting  the  training  weight 
was  concerned.  Here  the  "double"  weight  only  was  lifted 
ten  times,  with  a  pause,  then  five  times  with  a  pause,  and  so 
on,  until  twenty  lifts  had  been  made ;  the  actual  weight  lifted, 
however,  amounted  to  the  same  for  both  forms  of  the  ex- 
periment. While  the  observer  was  lifting  the  training  weight 
in  the  "distraction"  experiment,  the  experimenter  read  as 
distinctly  as  possible  from  some  interesting  reading  matter. 
After  the  lifting  of  the  original  weights,  which  immediately 
followed  that  of  the  training  weight,  the  subject  was  asked 
to  give  the  content  of  what  had  been  read,  and  a  record  was 
made  of  his  success. 

Four  university  students  of  psychology,  two  men  and  two 
women,  served  as  observers.  The  number  of  experiments 
per  observer  varied  from  14  for  observer  I,  to  28  for  observer 
IV,  owing  to  modifications  made  necessary  by  the  differences 
of  the  individual  observers.  Each  experiment  represents 
twenty  lifts  for  the  original  weights,  twenty  for  the  training 
weight,  and  twenty  again  for  the  original  weights. 

The  Einstellung  was  present  unmistakably  in  the  case  of 
each  observer.  Observer  I  showed  a  clear  and  decided  differ- 
ence in  the  intensity  of  the  Einstellung  under  the  two  condi- 
tions of  the  experiment,  the  effect  being  much  greater  when 
the  training  weight  was  lifted  with  attention  than  where  dis- 
traction was  used.  This  is  true  for  the  total  and  also  for  all 
except  one  of  the  single  pairs  of  days  on  which  experiments 
with  attention  and  with  distraction  were  made.  The  other 
observers,  however,  showed  this  difference  but  slightly  or  not 
at  all.  The  difference  was  so  clear  for  observer  I  that  an 
explanation  was  sought  for  the  indefiniteness  of  the  records 
of  the  other  three  observers.  As  none  could  be  found  at  first 
for  observer  IV,  his  work  was  continued  until  18  complete 
experiments  had  been  performed.  The  difficulty  was  dis- 
covered for  observers  II  and  III  and  the  experiment  modified 
after  12  complete  experiments.  The  following  table  gives  the 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING 


185 


results  obtained  from   the  work   just   described.     The  first 
column  represents  the  observer,  the  second  the  number  of 


« 

V 

0 

T 

1 

+ 

I " 

00 

T 

VO 
+ 

CO 

+ 

VO 
+ 

h4 

+ 

+ 

+ 

I 

w 

^ 

? 

t^ 

? 

f 

73 

T 

0 

T 

^ 

+ 

+ 

VO 

+ 

w 

? 

On 

? 

M 
1 

CO 

f 

h4 

+ 

+ 

+ 

a 

t^ 

c« 

Ov 

g   « 

^ 

0 

vS- 

f4 

2 

% 

0 
i-i 

ffi 

^ 

>o 

s 

? 

rt    w 

■ft 

^ 

% 

00 
00 

h4 

00 

CO 

^ 

tJ- 

CO 

w 

VO 

0 

M 

00 

00 

H    ^ 

M 

M 

vS" 

^ 

CO 

M 
M 

2 

On 
On 

2 

w 

^ 

»o 

fs  ^ 

ft 

VO 
CO 

VO        «o 
CO       00 

h4 

0 
^ 

S> 

^       % 

No. 

of 

lifts 

M 

M 

0 

eg 

1 

0 

1-^ 

> 

lifts,  the  third  (Ra)  the  results  before  training  on  days  when 
the  training  weight  was  lifted  with  attention,  the  fourth  (Ta) 
the  results  after  training  on  days  when  the  training  weight 

JOURNAI*— 4 


1 86  ORDAHI^ 

was  lifted  with  attention.  Column  Rd  contains  the  results 
from  the  lifting  of  the  original  weights  before  training  on  the 
days  of  the  "distraction  experiment,"  and  Td,  those  ob- 
tained after  lifting  the  training  weight  on  the  same  days.  Dif. 
a  shows  the  difference  between  the  results  before  and  after  the 
training  weight,  in  other  words  the  amount  of  the  Einstellung, 
for  the  experiments  with  attention.  Dif.  d  gives  amount  of 
the  Einstellung  for  the  distraction  experiments.  Column  a — d 
gives  the  difference  between  the  Einstellungen  in  the  two 
cases.  ly,  E,  H,  stand  for  "lighter,"  "equal,"  and  "heavier" 
cases  respectively.  It  will  be  noticed  that  some  superiority 
of  the  Einstellung  with  attention  exists  over  that  with  distrac- 
tion except  for  observer  IV,  in  whose  case  the  opposite  is  true. 

The  Einstellung  came  out  so  clearly  in  both  forms  of  the 
experiment  with  observers  II  and  III,  that  it  was  thought  that 
the  training  weight  was  so  heavy  as  to  give  a  tolerably  intense 
Einstellung,  irrespective  of  attention  and  distraction.  It 
was  therefore  reduced  a  hundred  grams  to  make  the  Ein- 
stellung more  moderate,  and  the  greater  effect  "with  atten- 
tion" immediately  showed  clearly  against  that  "with  dis- 
traction." The  explanation  for  observer  IV  was  different, 
and  was  obtained  by  an  examination  of  the  columns  giving 
the  results  before  the  training  weight  had  been  lifted  (columns 
Ra  and  Rd).  The  equal  cases  should  number  something  near 
one-fifth  of  the  total  number  and  the  heavier  and  lighter 
about  two-fifths  each;  but  the  proportion  is  almost  reversed, 
showing  that  weights  just  above  and  just  below  the  "equal' ' 
weights  were  not  discriminated  from  the  "equal."  To  rem- 
edy this  difficulty  the  training  weight  was  kept  as  before, 
but  the  original  weights  were  decreased  (and  increased)  from 
ID  and  20  grams  below  and  above  the  "equal"  to  20  and  40 
grams  below  and  above,  in  order  to  make  the  possibility  of 
discriminating  greater.  His  results  then  showed  the  same  ten- 
dencies as  the  other  observers.  Table  II  gives  the  results. 
The  lettering  of  the  columns  has  the  same  significance  as  for 
the  preceding  table.  The  first  line  of  figures  for  each  observer 
reading  across  the  table  gives  the  results  of  the  modified 
experiment.  The  second  gives  the  combined  results  of  the  first 
and  second  form.  Observer  I,  performing  the  experiment  only 
in  its  original  form,  is  represented  by  but  one  line  of  figures. 

After  the  experiment  was  closed  a  final  test  was  made  with 
each  observer  both  with  distraction  and  with  attention,  but 
the  observer  was  asked  to  notice  his  manner  of  lifting,  and  to 
see  if  it  differed  subjectively  in  either  case.  Observers  I  and  II 
reported  them  the  same.  Observer  III  held  the  weights  a 
little  looser  in  the  lifting  with  attention  but  the  lifting  itself 
was  the  same.     Observer  IV  raised  the  weights  a  little  more 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING 


187 


I 

W 

1 

00  QO 

t>.vo 

1   1 

W 

00 
1 

10  i-i 

W    1^ 

1         1 

'    + 

h) 

+  + 

^VO 

M    lO 

+  + 

Q 

w 

r 

1^    M 

1  T 

"r 

r^ 

w 

M 

M 
1 

M  00 

+  r 

Tf 

H^ 

M 

+ 

++ 

1^  w 

+  + 

++ 

w 

? 

to  Ov 

rr 

n 

w 

1 

+    ' 

TV 

M     OV 
M 
1        1 

h4 

+ 

00  VO 

+  + 

IH  00 

00     10 

(N  00 
+  + 

t-H 

s 

w 

M 

VO   CO 

t^  Ov 

VO  m 

I 

w 

CO  >0 

s^ 

R^ 

h4 

COVO 
1^  t^ 

>o  »o 

s 

a 

0 

CO  00 

^^ 

VO  «o 
CO  00 

« 

N  VO 

00  00 

00  VO 

«^     HI 

h4 

00 

to 

%^ 

1^00 
«0  ON 

CO  f* 

i2 

w 

NO 

vovo 

M    N 

CO    M 

Ov»>. 

w 

M 

»o  t^ 

u->00 

^S^ 

f-j 

fO 

On  I^ 
t^OO 

M 

M     HI 
M 

^? 

,2 

w 

5- 

fi     10 

CO  >0 

«  VO 

%^ 

w 

R 

00     Tt- 
M     »0 

VO  n 
NVO 

CO  00 
CO  « 

h4 

^ 

I-I     HI 

VO  •-• 

1^  CO 

»0  Ov 

SS' 

No. 

of 

lifts 

^ 

S5 

88 

0  00 

i-i 

i 

1— 1 
t-( 

1— t 

> 
1— ( 

irply  and  slightly  higher  "with  distraction."     This  differ- 
ice  was  too  slight  to  be  detected  by  the  experimenter.     Ob- 


I 88  ORDAHL 

server  IV  was  the  only  one  who  had  any  idea  as  to  the  pur- 
pose of  the  experiment,  and  he  had  surmised  it. 

Taking  all  facts  into  consideration  it  seems  certain  that 
with  a  training  weight  which  gives  a  moderate  Einstellung 
and  original  weights  which  are  different  enough  in  value  to 
render  discrimination  easy,  hfting  the  training  weight  with 
full  attention  produces  a  more  intense  Einstellung  than  lifting 
the  same  weight  in  the  same  manner,  but  with   distraction. 

J.     The  R6le  of  Consciousness  in  the  Acquirement  of 
Muscular  Skill 

The  third  series  of  experiments  was  of  a  very  simple  character 
and  useful  chiefly  in  furnishing  opportunity  for  introspection. 
It  consisted  in  learning  to  throw  balls  at  a  target  about  eight 
feet  in  diameter,  from  a  distance  of  14  to  18  feet.  Two  uni- 
versity students  of  the  psychological  department  served  as 
observers.  One,  the  writer,  had  almost  no  previous  ex- 
perience of  the  sort;  the  other,  a  gentleman,  had  thrown 
some,  but  "not  enough  to  amount  to  anything."  Ten  throws 
were  made  in  close  succession,  then  a  pause  until  the  observer 
was  rested,  then  ten  more  throws  until  fifty  had  been  made. 
The  experiment  covered  16  days  of  50  throws  each,  these  days 
occurring,  with  few  exceptions,  in  uninterrupted  succession. 

The  experiment  was  not  prolonged  far  enough  to  give  a 
satisfactory  learning-curve,  such  as  has  been  found  for  similar 
work  by  other  experimenters,  e.  g.,  Bair,  Book,  Swift,  and 
others,  since  general  introspective  results  were  the  main 
object  of  our  work.  It  may  be  said,  however,  that  the  great- 
est gain,  both  in  uniformity  and  amount  of  score,  came  for 
each  subject  in  the  first  few  days. 

In  learning  to  throw  at  a  target  one  must  specialize  and 
perfect  certain  elements  of  the  complex  mass  of  neuro-muscular 
co-ordinations  of  which  he  is  in  possession  through  inheritance 
and  his  own  practice  in  general  activities.  His  conscious- 
ness is  taken  up  primarily  with  the  target  and  the  ball  in  his 
hand  and  vaguely  with  those  particular  and  general  bodily 
sensations  which  enter  in  to  make  up  the  "set' '  of  the  situation. 
Only  gross  errors,  such  as  standing  too  far  to  the  right  or  the 
left,  or  throwing  with  too  great  or  too  little  force,  are  consciously 
corrected.  The  minuter,  more  skilful  adjustments  developed 
of  themselves  out  of  the  larger,  less  perfect  ones  already  exist- 
ing, and  were  then  perhaps  consciously  continued  or  avoided. 
Attention  to  the  mechanical  side  of  the  throwing  only  resulted 
in  inferior  work;  yet  clear  consciousness  was  necessary  for 
good  results,  but  it  was  consciousness  of  objective  elements — 
the  target  and  to  a  certain  extent  of  the  ball — rather  than  of 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  REI.ATION  TO  I.EARNING  1 89 

one's  arm  or  its  movements.  After  a  little  practice  both  ob- 
servers mentioned  the  fact  that  greater  concentration  and 
fixation  of  attention  on  the  target  resulted  in  better  throws. 
When  greater  effort  consisted  in  deliberate  attention  to  the 
mark,  good  throws  resulted;  but  when,  as  occasionally  hap- 
pened, the  observer  tried  to  regulate  the  process  and  attended 
to  the  hand,  arm,  or  ball,  random  shots  were  sure  to  occur. 
One  observer  remarked:  "  I  don't  believe  thinking  of  the  thing 
will  do  any  good.  All  I  can  do  is  to  stand  before  the  target 
and  wish  to  throw  well;"  the  other  said  that  he  was  simply 
trying  to  make  good  throws  but  did  not  know  how  he  did  it. 

Good  physiological  condition,  interest  in  the  work  and  a 
tonic  muscular  condition  seem  to  be  concomitants  of  success, 
for  when  observers  are  ill  they  lack  energy  and  interest,  throw 
almost  listlessly,  and  with  poor  results.  On  good  days  they 
stand  erect  with  muscles  tense  and  eyes  fixed  on  the  target 
and  do  their  best  work.  One  observer  at  such  a  time  even 
found  himself  forcibly  squeezing  the  ball.  The  amount  of  en- 
ergy put  forth  grew  more  regular  with  practice,  i.  e.,  there 
was  better  co-ordination. 

The  introspections  show  that,  in  such  an  almost  purely  sen- 
sory-muscular process,  skill  develops  without  consciousness 
of  the  details.  The  peripheral  sensations  accompanying  or 
preceding  the  reaction  contribute  to  form  the  background  of 
consciousness  and  to  produce  feelings  of  satisfaction  or  dissatis- 
faction according  as  the  movements  are  rightly  or  wrongly 
made.  Consciousness  has  little  place  "as  guide,"  save  in  the 
grosser  features  of  the  task,  but  attentive  consciousness  of  the 
end  was  necessary  for  the  development  of  these  peripheral 
adjustments.  Clear  consciousness  seemed  to  be  accompanied 
by  a  general  neuro- muscular  tonicity  favorable  to  the  best 
work.  Probably  with  clear  consciousness  the  organism  is  act- 
ing more  as  a  unit  of  closely  knit  parts,  each  of  which  is  then 
more  effective  on  every  other  part  while  it  is  active,  than 
in  a  state  of  disintegration  where  association  is  loose. 

4.    Learning  to  Write  in  Unaccustomed  Ways 

The  experiments  of  this  series  were,  like  the  last,  of  a  simple 
sort,  though  they  involved  skill  of  a  somewhat  greater  com- 
plexity. They  consisted  in  learning  to  write  ordinary  script 
with  the  left  hand,  and  mirror  script  with  both  the  right  and 
left  hands. 

Left-hand  Writing,  In  the  normal  script  experiments  eight 
observers  assisted,  four  of  whom  were  men  and  four  women. 
All  were  trained  psychologists,  except  one  woman  who,  never- 
theless, had  had   much  practice  as   an  observer   and  was 


I90  ORDAHI, 

excellent  at  introspecting.  One  observer  was  almost  ambi- 
dextrous, two  were  left-handed.  No  definite  tests  of  mental 
type  were  made,  but  the  indications  are  that  two  observers 
were,  in  this  sort  of  work,  predominantly  motor. 

The  conditions  of  the  experiment  were  kept  as  nearly  con- 
stant as  possible  for  each  individual  during  all  his  work  The 
experiment  covered  a  period  of  about  fourteen  days.  The 
standard  sentence,  written  by  all,  was,  "Motives  are  like 
chemicals.  The  more  you  analyze  them  the  worse  they  smell." 
This  the  observer  repeated  several  times  before  beginning  to 
write  in  order  to  learn  it.  The  sentence  was  written  three 
times  with  the  right  hand  with  timing  (with  a  stop  watch) ; 
then  once  without,  and  three  times  with  the  left  with  timing 
and  once  without,  with  sufficient  pauses  between  tests  to 
avoid  fatigue.  It  was  explained  to  the  observers  beforehand 
that  the  timing  was  merely  an  incidental  matter  and  that 
they  should  write  at  a  convenient  speed,  merely  writing 
each  sentence  continuously.  After  each  sentence  had  been 
written,  the  observer  was  asked  to  give  introspections  as  to 
methods  used,  points  attended  to,  and  any  other  items  which 
might  be  of  interest. 

Inference  as  to  the  part  "unconscious"  factors  play  must 
rest  partly  on  the  fact  that  the  observer  fails  to  mention  them 
and  it  is  therefore  open  to  the  error  of  supposing  that  facts 
not  remarked  upon  are  unconscious,  whereas  the  fault  may  be 
due  to  incomplete  introspection  or  report.  Yet  it  was  im- 
possible to  ask  definite  questions  as  to  position  or  methods, 
for  then  entirely  unnoticed  factors  became  clearly  conscious 
and  the  subsequent  course  of  procedure  was  apt  to  be  changed. 
Exact  objective  measurements  of  improvement  in  writing 
are  naturally,  impossible,  but  must  be  judged  in  a  rough  way 
by  greater  uniformity  in  the  slant  and  strength  of  the  charac- 
ters, and  by  their  greater  clearness  and  legibility. 

The  different  observers  manifested  individual  differences 
in  their  adaptation  to  the  task,  their  methods  of  procedure 
and  the  speed  and  proficiency  acquired ;  yet  there  are  elements 
common  to  all.  It  is  evident  that  easy  and  natural  writing 
movements  with  the  left  hand  cannot  be  made  unless  one 
assumes  a  position  nearly  symmetrical  to  the  customary 
right-hand  position  and  lets  the  hand  take  a  free  and  un- 
cramped  movement.  This  will  result  in  script  with  a  "back 
hand'  *  slant  of  a  rather  uniform  character  if  one  writes  on  a 
horizontal  plane.  It  was  to  this  position  and  writing  that 
all  observers  tended,  though  they  arrived  at  it  in  various  ways 
and  adopted  it  to  different  degrees. 

Only  three  observers  assumed  an  entirely  symmetrical 
position  from  the  start.     Two  of  these,  who  were  left-handed 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING  191 

observers,  did  so  unconsciously,  guided  purely  by  the  "feel" 
of  the  thing.  The  other  observer  analyzed  the  situation, 
discovered  that  this  would  be  the  proper  way,  and  so  took  the 
position  voluntarily.  A  fourth  observer  assumed  a  position 
almost  symmetrical,  and  one  which  was  little  changed  dturing 
the  progress  of  the  experiment.  This  he  said  he  did  "con- 
sciously and  unconsciously,"  i.  e.,  semi-consciously.  Of  the  re- 
maining four  observers  all  began  with  the  paper  in  exactly  the 
position  used  for  the  right  hand,  with  the  body  turned  at  the 
same  angle  to  the  table  and  the  left  hand  and  arm  twisted  into 
an  awkward  position,  the  wrist  cramped  over  to  the  right  side  of 
the  body.  With  one  observer  the  right  hand  held  the  paper 
at  the  upper  left  corner,  taking  the  position  which  the  left 
hand  had  always  used,  thus  showing  that  each  hand  had 
changed  places  with  the  other. 

All  observers,  save  one,  finally  used  some  finger  movements 
for  the  left  hand,  but  only  four  began  with  them.  Two  of  these 
were  left-handed  and  one  ambidextrous,  and  used  the  move- 
ments unconsciously.  Observer  V,  who  analyzed  his  position 
and  assumed  a  symmetrical  one  consciously,  used  finger 
movements  at  first,  but  after  the  first  sentence  the  natural 
tendency  to  use  larger  arm  movements  manifested  itself, 
and  the  finger  movements  disappeared.  One  observer  made 
them  to  get  out  of  a  difficulty  and  after  that  tried  for  them; 
another  noticed  her  right  hand  carefully  while  writing,  ob- 
served the  finger  movements,  realized  that  skill  could  be 
obtained  only  if  the  finger  movements  were  used  in  the  left  hand, 
and  therefore  consciously  adopted  them,  but  with  considerable 
effort,  and  it  was  only  when  attention  was  directed  to  the 
hand  that  they  were  constantly  made.  Another  observer 
"found  finger  movements  coming  of  themselves"  and  con- 
tinued them  because  the  writing  as  a  result  was  better,  but 
even  then  they  were  hard  to  keep.  Of  the  observers  who  did 
not  use  finger  movements  at  the  start,  one  adopted  them  on 
the  second  day,  one  on  the  fourth  and  one  on  the  fifth.  The 
only  observers  using  finger  movements  naturally  are  those 
possessed  at  the  start  of  some  skill  with  the  left  hand. 

Four  observers  went  from  a  larger  to  a  smaller  hand,  three 
to  a  slightly  larger  one,  and  for  one,  size  remained  about 
the  same. 

The  large  movements  at  the  start  may  be  due  to  one  of  two 
things.  They  may  be  the  result  of  a  general  tensing  up  of 
all  the  muscles  in  the  intense  effort  of  the  new  occupation, 
and  a  general  spread  of  energy  over  the  whole  body — a  thing 
which  could  be  observed  in  the  tense  muscles  of  the  hand  in 
five  cases;  in  the  digging  and  scraping  of  the  pen  in  three 
cases;  and  in  tension  about  the  mouth,  head-movements  or 


192  ORDAHI^ 

raising  the  heels  from  the  floor,  some  of  which  were  noticeable 
in  all  but  the  left-handed  subjects.  Or  they  may  be  due  to 
the  fact  that  the  muscles  involved  in  the  larger  movements 
have  been  trained  in  many  daily  occupations  while  the  finer 
movements  have  been  very  little  practiced.  In  the  progress 
of  the  race  one  hand  has  been  specialized  for  the  more  skilful 
work,  the  other  hand  (in  most  people,  the  left)  being  used  far 
less.  The  left  hand  of  an  adult  just  learning  to  use  it  in  left- 
hand  writing,  is  in  about  the  same  condition  as  the  right 
hand  of  a  child  who  learns  writing  for  the  first  time.  The 
child's  arm  and  hand  have  been  used  in  larger  activities,  but 
the  finer  adjustments  have  not  been  practiced.  When,  there- 
fore, the  child  and  the  adult  begin  the  new  task  there  is  in  both  a 
general  innervation  of  all  the  muscles  and  the  larger  move- 
ments are  first  made.  The  finer  ones  together  with  economy 
of  energy  appear  later. 

Writing  in  reversed  slant  appeared  to  a  greater  or  less 
degree  with  all  the  subjects.  In  three  cases  the  natural 
tendency  was  noticed  in  a  few  strokes  and  consciously  con- 
tinued; in  two  it  was  the  result  of  letting  the  hand  take  its 
own  position  and  "swing."  Another  tried  to  let  the  writing 
take  its  natural  slant,  which  finally  resulted  in  "back  hand" 
script. 

Improvement  is  characterized  subjectively  by  a  freeing  of 
attention  from  the  writing  itself  so  that  the  observer  is 
able  to  attend  to  details,  to  correct  errors,  and  to  make  im- 
provement in  methods.  Attention  at  first  is  so  absorbed 
in  the  writing  that  the  observer  is  not  aware  of  his  awkward 
methods.  One  by  one  he  notices  these  and  corrects  them. 
Observers  starting  with  good  methods  have  fewer  difficulties 
at  the  beginning  and  are  able  to  anticipate  them  sooner. 
Attention  is  not  only  differently  directed,  but  far  narrower  at 
the  beginning  than  at  the  end  of  practice.  As  skill  begins 
to  develop,  consciousness  is  wider  and  attention  can  shift  from 
the  task  to  extraneous  matters  with  little  disadvantage;  where, 
as  in  the  beginning,  wandering  of  attention  means  distraction, 
and  the  work  suffers.  The  relation,  which  exists  between 
late  and  early  conditions,  exists  also  between  the  right  and 
left-hand  writing.  In  the  latter,  attention  is  easily  disturbed ; 
a  strange  pen,  a  slight  illness,  or  a  simple  external  hindrance 
have  far  more  effect. 

The  general  results  of  these  tests  with  left-hand  writing  show 
the  role  of  consciousness  in  learning  of  this  kind  to  be  correct- 
ive, its  function  being  to  criticise,  to  eliminate  habits  pro- 
ducing either  physical  discomfort  or  dissatisfaction  with  the 
product,  and  to  make  permanent  any  favorable  variations 
which   may  chance   to   occur.     The  fociis   of  consciousness 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING  1 93 

changes  during  the  learning,  attention  at  first  being  on  the  pro- 
cess itself,  the  details  existing  in  consciousness  only  marginally 
or  not  at  all.  Later  the  learner  attends  to  his  methods  and  at 
the  same  time  is  more  clearly  aware  of  the  elements  leading  to 
his  satisfaction  or  dissatisfaction.  As  the  methods  are  per- 
fected they  in  turn  become  automatic,  the  learner  assuming 
automatically  the  position  which  he  has  acquired  consciously. 
As  the  process  becomes  still  more  automatic,  attention  wan- 
ders from  it  from  time  to  time  to  foreign  matters,  without 
interference. 

Mirror  Script  Experiments.  Experiments  in  learning  to  write 
mirror  script  (that  is,  writing  which  begins  at  the  right-hand 
side  of  the  paper,  and  may  be  read  by  holding  it  up  to  a  mirror 
or  from  the  reversed  side  of  the  sheet)  were  carried  on  for  a 
period  of  fourteen  days  with  six  observers,  all  of  whom  had 
served  in  the  above  mentioned  left-hand  experiments.  The 
general  conditions  were  the  same  as  before.  The  subjects  wrote 
the  standard  sentence  three  times  with  the  right  hand  and 
three  times  with  the  left,  and  vice  versa  on  alternate  days,  the 
writing  of  each  sentence  being  timed  as  before  except  in  two 
cases.  No  untimed  tests  were  taken  save  in  the  case  of  two 
observers.  As  timing  seemed  to  have  no  effect,  untimed 
experiments  were  not  made  by  the  others. 

The  greatest  diflSLCulty  was  noticed  by  all  observers  in  the 
first  few  trials,  and  consisted  in  knowing  what  the  form  of  the 
letters  should  be.  A  certain  amount  of  extraneous  practice 
was  allowed  in  order  to  meet  this  peculiar  hindrance.  Two 
observers  began  by  writing  on  the  blackboard  with  both  hands 
at  once,  mirror  script  with  the  left  hand  and  normal  script 
with  the  right.  This  was  easier  than  the  writing  with  the 
pen,  which  required  smaller  movements.  The  other  observers, 
seated  at  a  desk  with  paper  before  them,  were  told  to  write  the 
sentence  in  mirror  script,  after  it  had  been  explained  to  them 
what  mirror  script  was,  and  were  allowed  to  write  the  sentence, 
to  hold  the  paper  to  the  light  and  to  correct  mistakes. 

Attention  at  the  start  was  confined  to  the  writing  as  a  whole, 
but  soon  general  difficulties  decreased  and  particular  ones 
were  attended  to,  certain  letter  combinations  being  more 
difficult  than  others.  After  trying  to  make  a  letter  of  a  certain 
more  difficult  form,  the  observers  consciously  chose  a  simpler 
style.  As  in  the  normal  script  experiments,  excessive  muscular 
tension  was  shown  at  first  but  later  disappeared.  With  ease 
in  writing,  foreign  ideas  again  begin  to  enter  in  every  case; 
but  attention  cannot  get  too  far  from  the  process  without 
disastrous  results.  One  observer,  for  example,  became  so 
absorbed  in  a  train  of  thought  that  he  stopped  writing. 
Ease  of  writing  and  freedom  of  attention,  as  before,  allowed 


194  ORDAHL 

difficulties  to  be  anticipated  and  overcome  before  they 
were  met.  One  observer  consciously  pronounced  the  difficult 
letters,  because  he  found  himself  doing  this  in  one  instance 
with  good  results.  Two  observers  visualized  the  movements, 
in  difficult  places,  before  making  them.  No  observer  men- 
tioned attending  to  the  process  itself  as  a  means  to  improve- 
ment, but  two  stated  that  attention  to  the  process  brought 
confusion.^ 

Had  there  been  a  good  copy  to  give  an  idea  of  the  letter 
forms,  and  had  instruction  been  given  as  to  position  and  re- 
laxation of  muscles  in  hand  and  arm,  much  of  the  difficulty 
would  probably  have  been  obviated.^ 

Learning  to  write,  as  evidenced  in  the  above  experiments, 
depends  on  consciousness  mainly  for  perfection  of  methods. 
Adjustments  which  are  at  first  "unconscious"  become  highly 
conscious  then  later  automatic,  a  great  degree  of  perfection 
requiring  the  third  stage  —  automaticity.  It  is  only  as  the 
grosser  elements  become  automatic  that  attention  is  free  to 
consider  the  finer  ones. 

A  certain  degree  of  difficulty  is  necessary  to  interest.  As 
the  task  becomes  automatic  and  easy,  it  is  impossible  to  keep 
foreign  ideas  out  of  mind. 

Progress  is  from  coarse  to  finer  muscular  adjustments,  and 
from  larger  to  finer  writing  in  most  cases.  This  means  a 
specialization  of  the  smaller  finger  and  hand  movements,  and 
a  saving  in  energy,  since  less  exertion  is  needed  to  call  these 
into  use,  than  for  the  larger  arm  movements. 

Progress  may  take  place  without  a  high  degree  of  con- 
sciousness, yet  it  will  not  go  so  far  nor  proceed  so  rapidly  as 
when  there  is  consciousness  of  the  process  itself. 

5.     Learning  to  Multiply  large  Numbers  Mentally 

The  experiments  of  this  series  consisted  in  learning  to 
square  three-place  numbers  mentally,  and  were  suggested  by 
recent  work  of  Thorndike  in  multiplying  mentally  a  three- 

^The  matter  of  increased  speed  in  the  writing  does  not  especially  con- 
cern us  here,  though  the  records  were  kept  and  tabulated.  It  may  be  men- 
tioned in  passing,  however,  that  there  was  very  often  to  be  observed  an  in- 
crease in  speed  in  the  left-hand  writing,  in  the  mirror  script  and  even 
in  the  normal  writing  with  the  right  hand,  from  the  first  to  the  third  execu- 
tions of  the  standard  sentence  in  a  single  test — a  transient  gain  in  skill  by 
practice  of  a  particular  set  of  movements. 

2In  any  instruction  it  is  just  this  which  should  be  the  function  of  the 
teacher,  i.  e.,  to  provide  good  methods  and  to  call  attention  to  errors  which 
the  narrow  attention  of  the  learner  will  not  enable  him  to  see.  In  a  task 
like  writing  much  mechanical  repetition  is  needed;  yet  repetition  without 
attention  will  not  result  in  improvement  but  merely  in  the  strengthening 
of  abilities  then  possessed,  and  even  of  awkward  procedures. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING  1 95 

place  number  by  a  three-place  number.^  He  found  in  the  33 
observers  who  did  from  28  to  96  examples  of  that  sort,  a  gain 
of  over  50  per  cent,  in  skill,  but  gives  no  introspective  results, 
except  that  strength  of  visual  imagery  was  not  responsible 
for  the  improvement,  and  that  more  individuals  reported  de- 
crease than  increase  of  visual  imagery.  My  own  experi- 
ments were  carried  out  in  a  manner  similar  to  his,  except 
that  for  simplicity's  sake  my  observers  squared  one  number 
instead  of  multiplying  two  different  numbers  together.  This 
made  it  necessary  to  hold  but  three  digits  in  mind  at  the  start, 
instead  of  six.  In  making  the  number  list,  digits  above  two 
were  written  on  cards  and  drawn  at  random  from  a  box.  If 
a  number  contained  the  same  two  digits  as  the  number  before 
it,  it  was  given  a  later  place  in  the  list,  in  order  to  avoid  the 
distraction,  or  aid,  of  too  great  similarity. 

The  manner  of  conducting  the  experiment  was  as  follows: 
A  number  was  read  to  the  subject,  the  observer  repeated  it, 
and  the  stop-watch  was  started.  When  he  finished  the  ex- 
ample he  gave  the  result,  the  watch  was  stopped  and  the  time 
recorded.  In  the  first  day's  trials  the  observer  was  asked  to 
work  aloud,  but  in  some  cases  this  proved  a  distraction  and 
was  not  required  later,  though  those  who  wished  to  work 
aloud  were  permitted  to  do  so.  In  reckoning  the  results 
Thorndike's  arbitrary  method  of  transmuting  errors  into 
time  by  adding  to  the  watch  time  one-tenth  of  its  amount  for 
each  error  made,  was  used. 

Preliminary  tests  consisting  in  running  through  the  forty- 
nine  two-place  numbers  possible  from  combinations  of  digits 
above  the  digit  three  were  carried  out  with  two  observers, 
and  took  six  and  five  days  respectively.  In  this  short  time 
great  improvement  was  made;  for  observer  A  the  average 
daily  score  in  seconds  for  each  multiplication  was  51.1,  40.1, 
35,  43.1,  41.9,  30.6,  and  for  B,  81.7,  29.1,  26.2,  16.3,  21.4. 
(B's  last  score  was  raised  by  one  exceptionally  long  time  where 
the  example  was  worked  twice.  If  this  one  case  be  left  out 
the  last  score  is  16.2.) 

Introspection  showed  that  the  gain  was  partly  the  result  of 
the  refreshing  of  the  mathematical  associations,  i.  e.,  practice 
in  multiplying  and  adding,  but  far  more,  of  choosing  and  using 
new  methods  to  avoid  obvious  difficulties,  and  of  improvement 
of  methods  already  in  use.  Ideas  as  to  means  of  improve- 
ment were  not  the  result  of  analysis  previous  to  work,  but 
came  after  some  practical  experience,  when  the  observer  was 
oriented   and  realized  his   deficiencies.     The  formulation  of 


iThoradike:  The  Effect  of  Practice  in  the  Case  of  a  Purely  Intellectual 
Function,  Am.  Jour.  Psy.,  XIX,  1908,  374-384. 


196  ORDAHL 

such  improved  procedures  was  really  a  process  of  generaliza- 
tion. When  the  same  peculiarity  occurred  several  times,  the 
observer  recognized  its  universal  character  spontaneously, 
and  not  as  the  result  of  conscious  search  after  it.  The  com- 
mon element  seemed  to  drop  out  of  itself.  Then,  because  of 
his  strong  desire  for  improvement,  he  consciously  made  use 
of  it;  but  had  he  not  been  alert,  it  might  easily  have  escaped 
his  notice,  and  have  been  of  no  profit  to  him  in  his  progress. 

Instances  of  this  process  are  the  following :  After  a  few  examples  A  real- 
ized that,  with  the  niunbers  in  use,  the  answer  must  always  have  four  digits. 
Visualization  for  this  observer  was  at  first  impossible,  the  whole  process 
having  to  be  carried  on  in  auditory-motor  terms.  The  two  partial  products 
were  retained  as  a  sound  whole ;  and  to  get  the  separate  digits  for  the  addi- 
tion the  observer  must  run  through  these  products  several  times  till  the 
required  digit  was  found.  After  several  such  experiences  she  realized  that 
it  was  only  in  an  auditory-motor  way  that  work  could  be  done,  so  in  adding, 
she  repeated  the  first  partial  product  through  as  far  as  the  units  digit,  held 
that  in  mind  as  the  units  digit  of  the  complete  product,  repeated  the  first 
partial  product  again  as  far  as  the  third  digit  from  the  left  and  the  second  par- 
tial product  as  far  as  its  final  digit,  added  these  two  and  placed  them  in  the 
tens  place  of  the  complete  product,  and  so  on.  Later,  visualization  increased 
to  some  extent  as  the  result  of  extreme  effort,  but  remained  almost  entirely 
visualization  of  a  special  "form"  into  which  the  digits  were  fitted  as  they  were 
required.  ? After  practice  in  addition,  it  was  noticed  that  the  first  digit  from 
the  left  of  the  second  partial  product  and  the  last  of  the  first  partial  product 
had  no  digits  above  or  below  them  to  add  to  them;  and  consciously  less 
attention  was  given  to  them  and  more  to  the  other  four  digits.  Again, 
having  worked  slowly  and  deliberately  so  that  one  partial  product  escaped 
her  by  the  time  the  other  was  obtained,  she  worked  more  rapidly  in  sub- 
sequent multiplications,  spending  more  time  repeating  and  emphasizing 
the  results. 

Observer  B  worked  a  single  day,  multiplying  the  numbers  out  by  full 
multiplication.  He  then  served  as  experimenter,  with  A  as  observer,  and 
while  so  doing  realized  that  the  binomial  method  might  be  used,  and  used 
it  in  going  over  A's  work.  In  his  next  work  as  observer  the  change  of 
method  reduced  his  record  from  81  to  29.  The  process  was  first  as  follows: 
Required  to  square  35.  a^  +  2ab+ b^,  35^  =  (30  +  5)2  =30^ -f- 2.30.5  +  52. 
Later  he  noticed  that  a^  always  ended  in  two  zeros  and  simplified  the  pro- 
cess by  simply  setting  together  a^  and  b^  then  adding  2ab.  Then  the  method 
unconsciously  came  of  getting  2ab  while  repeating  a^  +  b^,  was  recognized 
as  a  method  and  continued.  Later,  while  making  notes,  it  occurred  to  him 
that  in  multiples  of  numbers  ending  in  5,  2ab  will  be  the  first  digit  X  100. 
This  was  then  consciously  used  with  success.  Superfluous  words  fall  away 
in  the  process,  only  numerical  results  being  given.  This  last  was  uncon- 
scious, however,  as  to  intent.  In  all  such  work,  a  rule  which  is  first  conscious 
becomes  an  unconscious  habit. 

In  squaring  three-place  numbers  six  persons  served  as  ob- 
servers, three  men  and  three  women,  all  of  whom  were  univer- 
sity students.  Observer  V  is  the  same  as  observer  A  of  the 
two-place  number  experiments.  The  observers  were  practiced 
for  two  days  on  two-place  numbers  and  three-place  numbers, 
each  subject  working  three  three-place  problems  before  the 
regular  experiments  began.  The  results  included  in  the 
tables  are  only  those  of  the  regular  experiments.     The  rec- 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  REI^ATION  TO  LEARNING  1 97 

ords  are  based  on  the  fifty  examples  worked  by  each  subject, 
and  cover  between  ten  and  fifteen  days.  Each  worked  half 
an  hour  a  day.  The  method  of  timing  was  that  described 
above  for  the  two-place  numbers.  A  rest  of  from  two  to 
five  minutes  between  problems  was  given.  If  the  original 
number  was  forgotten  in  the  midst  of  the  work,  that  problem 
was  given  up,  and  after  a  rest,  a  new  one  taken.  As  the  ob- 
servers worked  at  different  rates,  and  as  some  forgot  more  num- 
bers than  others,  the  number  of  days  taken  varies.  The 
following  tables  give  the  average  results  in  errors,  time  and 
combined  result  for  the  six  observers. 

A  decided  gain  is  clear  as  far  as  speed  is  concerned,  though 
accuracy  seems  to  remain  about  the  same,  unless  in  the  case 
of  observer  IV,  where  there  is  slight  improvement.  This, 
however,  may  be  a  matter  of  chance.  The  accuracy  corres- 
ponds to  one's  skill  with  the  addition  and  multiplication 
tables,  which  have  been  so  much  practiced  that  they  have 
reached  a  "plateau  stage"  where  no  further  improvement 
is  likely.  Improvement,  in  this  experiment,  is  not  in  accuracy 
of  work,  not  in  the  speed  of  computing  (at  least  not  to  an 
observable  extent)  but  in  the  ability  to  hold  more  things  in 
mind  and  to  attack  the  work  directly  and  with  more  advan- 
tageous methods.  The  asterisks  in  the  table  indicate  the 
points  at  which  new  methods  were  introduced.  An  asterisk 
occurring  before  the  first  day's  score  indicates  that  a  method  of 
work  peculiar  to  the  observer  was  developed  in  the  preliminary 
three-place  examples.  Observer  VI  began  the  first  day's  regular 
experiments  with  a  method  which  required  the  retention  of 
but  a  few  numbers  at  a  time  and  made  use  of  no  new  method. 
Observers  I,  II,  IV  had  developed  methods  before  this  day, 
but  made  improvements  in  them  during  the  progress  of  the 
experiment.  It  will  be  noticed  that  introduction  of  new 
methods  resulted  in  a  large  drop  in  the  time,  except  in  the 
case  of  observer  IV,  who  did  not  continue  methods  used 
after  they  were  once  developed,  except  the  general  method 
used  on  the  first  day. 

The  most  difficult  part  of  squaring  three-place  numbers  by 
full  multiplication  was  found,  by  all  observers,  to  be  the  reten- 
tion of  the  partial  products  long  enough  to  add  them,  and  to 
add  the  proper  digits  together.  As  they  were  allowed  to 
work  in  any  way  they  chose,  the  effort  of  each  was  to  find 
some  way  to  lessen  this  difficulty.  Visualizers,  as  might  be 
expected,  had  less  difficulty  than  observers  with  little  visual 
imagery.  A  brief  account  of  the  procedure  of  each  of  the 
six  observers  will  best  show  the  methods  of  improvement. 
Fatigue  or  distraction  made  retention  difficult  for  all  the 
observers  and  affected  chiefly  that  part  of  the  work. 


198 


ORDAHL 


0 

tl 

VO 

1 

«o 

M 

VO 

r» 

M 

M 

CI 

M 

M 

Ov 

Ov 

>* 

M 

0 

IM 

M 

Ci 

to 

M 

M 

VO 

VO 

00 

to 

5" 

§• 

M 

M 

M 

N 

ci 

„ 

M 

M 

r^ 

00 

« 

r* 

"<*• 

M 

M 

yo 

00 

M 

0 

M 

M 

M 

VO 

Ov 

t^ 

0 

M 

0 

CI 

M 

to 

»o 

M 

«o 

»o 

VO 

0 

«o 

Ov 

00 

00 

VO 

VO 

M 

00 

t^ 

VO 

M 

to 

•^ 

M 

M 

to 

r* 

M 

« 

to 

M 

CI 

•^ 

VO 

OV 

Ov 

VO 

Ov 

OV 

•"^ 

to 

•^ 

l-« 

«o 

1^ 

vOt 

fi 

• 

>o 

r^ 

CI 

* 

Ov 

0 

c< 

CO 

to 

"t 

to 

Ov 

VO 

VO 

CI 

CI 

VO 

VO 

'^ 

to 

d 

to 

VO 

t^ 

M 

M 

10 

«o 

t^ 

CI 

CI 

»^» 

10 

VO 

CI 

CI 

to 

M 

M 

c< 

0 

-4- 

N 

0 

-* 

»o 

»H 

s 

1 

^" 

1 

1 

CI 

VO 

M 

to 

« 
10 

VO 

M 

M 

0 

to 

00 

»o 

vd 

0 

00 

00 

0 

i 

Ov 

«o 

1^ 

00 

00 

"«»■ 

s 

to 

r* 

0 

CI 

1 

to 

Ov 

VO 

«o 

>o 

8, 

«o 

0 

VO 

0^ 
00 

"i- 

to 

0. 

to 

to 

«o 

to 

VO 

00 
CI 

M 

CI 

>o 

to 

i 

M 

00 

M 

HI 

to 
to 

s 

M 

«o 

% 

t— ( 

1 

1 

1 

* 

w 

? 

<«*■ 
t 

M 

Tt- 

00 

N 

VO 

»o 

0 

VO 

to 

CI 

>o 
«o 

• 

Ov 

CI 

00 

10 

«o 
1-^ 

00 

VO 

to 

Ov 

1^ 

00 
M 

CI 

c« 

M 

to 

VO 

VO 

CI 

VO 

to 

»o 

>o 

CI 

CI 

M 

CI 

rf 

0 

CI 

CI 

ov 

0 

# 

to 

CI 

to 

1^ 

M 

M 

CI 

VO 

CI 

VO 
00 

00 

i 

» 

- 

to 

CI 

00* 

00 

to 

CI 

i 

2 

H 

♦ 

CONSCIOUSNJeSS  IN  R:ei.ATlON  TO  LEARNING 


199 


VO 

0 

Tt 

CO 

0 

M 

VO 

M 

N 

00 

•O 

to 

w 

00 

(^ 

»H 

VO 

M 

° 

NO 

t^ 

»o 

M 

M 

Ov 

^ 

M 

N 

VO 

t-> 

„ 

„ 

Ov 

t^ 

" 

OV 

CI 

VO 

OV 

0 

0 

"«*■ 

VO 

00 

M 

OV 

M 

-^ 

•^ 

VO 

o\ 

0 

r>. 

<-~s 

00 

00 

>t 

M 

<0 

^ 

8 

rO 

CO 

^'r 

00 

M 

N 

r- 

5» 

t>. 

00 

*^ 

M 

Ox 

Tl- 

^ 

r^ 

''t- 

CO 

1— ( 

>o 

VO 

t— ( 

C« 

c< 

w 

VO 

VO 

< 

VO 

0 

«o 

CO 

* 

H 

«o 

CO 

t^ 

«s 

00 

«o 

M 
CO 

Ov 
CO 

ro 

0 

00 

"^ 

•^ 

00 
04 

0 

VO 

VO 

«o 

•^ 

Ov 
CO 

«o 

M 

•H 

w 

*^ 

1^ 

CO 

OV 

""l- 

•^ 

M 

CO 

vg^ 
CO 

> 

g 

1 

ja 

0 

w 

H 

^ 

1 

0 

t^ 

0 

'<t- 

c« 

»^ 

0 

t^ 

M 

•H 

d 

»o 

M 

ov 

CO 

M 

M 

00 

»o 

00 

•^ 

"^ 

VO 

Ov 

VO 

M 

M 

CV| 

t". 

'^ 

0 

N 

CO 

0 

0 

0 

^ 

^ 

0 

Tt- 

M 

Th 

VO 

CI 

CI 

0 

VO 

Ov 

0 

CH 

d 

CI 

«o 

00 

VO 

0 

00 

Ov 

M 

ov 

M 

CI 

CO 
VO 

« 

0 

t^ 

0 

00 

PI 

I^ 

OV 

10 

00 

^ 

•^ 

0 

00 

>o 

r^ 

^ 

^ 

CI 

CI 

CO 

VO 

'^ 

VO 

M 

CI 
CI 
CI 

CI 

»o 

» 

M 

M 

>o 

N 

to 

CI 

00 

-"l- 

d 

CO 

0 

>o 

00 

Tt- 

„ 

CO 

^  ^ 

CO 

VO  ♦ 

CO 

CO 

CO 

»o 

M 

CO 

^ 

^ 

10 

CO 

CO 

0 

CO 

Ov 

c< 

N 

0 

00 

^ 

"«*■ 

0 

Ov 

>o 

CS 

CI 

Ov 

M 

CO 

Ov 

CO 

CO 

« 

> 

u 

4 

i 

g 

y 

0 

pl^ 

H 

u 

1 

M 

CO 

00 

CO 

00 

0 
M 

w 

ov 

«o 

d 
>o 

Ov 

0 

10 

i 

c* 

M 

10 

00 

0 

CO 
CO 

0 

t^ 

0 

10 

VO 

vd 
to 

VO 

»o 

CO 

Ov 
CO 

CO 
CO 

•0 

- 

M 

OV 

Th 

0 

Ov 

«o 

HI 

CO 

VO 

VO 

00 

CI 

»o 

M 

CI 

CI 

- 

0 

4 

CI 
CO 

M 

> 

1 

1 

1 

* 

I 


200  ORDAHL 

Observer  I.  This  subject  possessed  no  visual  imagery  for  this  sort  of  work. 
By  the  second  example  of  the  preliminary  practice,  he  was  consciously 
repeating  the  first  partial  product  to  the  last  digit,  setting  this  in  the 
answer;  then  the  third  digit  of  the  first  and  the  last  of  the  second  were  ob- 
tained in  the  same  manner  and  added,  etc.  As  the  required  figures  were 
taken  out  and  embodied  in  the  sum  they  were  forgotten.  The  next  day 
he  tried  to  add  two  columns  at  once.  On  the  day  before  the  regular  ex- 
periment he  was  permitted  to  make  writing  movements  with  his  pencil, 
which  he  did  henceforth,  finding  it  an  advantage.  On  the  second  day 
of  the  regular  tests  he  tried  remembering  the  numbers  by  pairs.  (Notice 
the  decrease  on  this  day  from  504.1  to  265.7.)  On  the  fifth  day  the  very 
advantageous  idea  of  adding  the  first  two  partial  products  and  adding  the 
third  to  their  sum  was  hit  upon,  thus  having  at  no  time  more  than  two 
numbers  to  keep  in  mind.  After  this  the  drop  is  decided.  The  increase 
in  time  in  the  last  three  days  was  due  to  fatigue  from  other  work  earlier 
in  the  day. 

Observer  II.  This  observer  is  a  good  visualizer  and  has  had  experience 
in  teaching  mathematics.  On  the  first  day  the  observer  tried  to  square 
two  numbers,  but  did  not  succeed  in  either  case,  and  refused  to  work.  The 
next  morning  while  thinking  of  other  things,  a  method  occurred  to  her,  which 
she  used  with  success  throughout  the  work.  It  was  to  multiply  the  number 
by  the  multiple  of  a  hundred  which  stood  nearest,  then  by  the  hundreds 
digit  multiplied  by  ten,  and  adding  or  subtracting  the  result,  according  as 
the  first  multiplier  was  below  or  above  the  original  number,  then  mul- 
tiplying by  the  units  digit  and  adding  or  subtracting.  Thus  only  two  sets 
of  numbers  had  to  be  retained  and  work  was  considerably  in  ciphers.  For 
the  first  two  days  of  the  regular  experiment  a  few  seconds  were  taken  to 
think  out  the  method  of  work,  but  later  this  became  unnecessary  and  the 
problem  was  attacked  directly.  The  method  had  grown  automatic.  On 
the  fifth  day  a  permanent  modification  occurred  in  adding  or  subtracting 
by  thousands,  tens,  and  imits  visually.  A  question  by  the  experimenter  as 
to  the  way  the  work  had  been  done  suggested  this. 

Observer  III — A  visualizer.  The  first  three-place  number  was  declared 
to  be  "terrible,"  the  greatest  difficulty  being  to  retain  and  add  the  partial 
products.  In  the  second  example  she  added  the  first  two  partial  products 
and  then  the  third.  The  next  day  the  method  was  improved  further,  con- 
ciously,  by  getting  the  sum  of  the  first  two  partial  products  before  multiply- 
ing for  the  third.  The  regular  experiments  were  begun  with  this  method, 
which  was  afterward  modified  but  slightly.  The  modifications  were  as 
follows:  "putting"  the  first  partial  product  on  all  the  four  fingers  of  the 
left  hand  and  the  second  on  all  but  tie  little  finger  and  including  the  simi. 
This  resulted  in  the  thumb  and  little  finger  having  only  one  digit,  and  the 
others  two;  this  method  was  not  continued.  The  third  partial  product 
was  '  'put' '  spatially  above  the  sum  of  the  first  two  on  the  fourth  day.  On 
the  eighth  day  she '  'put  the  first  sum  in  the  left  ear' '  and  got  it  again  when 
needed.  From  the  first,  the  observer  automatically  made  writing  move- 
ments on  the  table  to  accompany  her  work. 

Observer  IV  (no  visual  imagery  for  this  sort  of  thing).  The  observer 
developed  no  method  until  the  sixth  day  except  the  repetition  of  the  partial 
products  until  he  came  to  the  digit  required  for  the  addition,  as  described 
for  observer  I.  He  consciously  hurried  through  the  process  of  multipli- 
cation in  order  to  spend  the  time  on  repetition  and  emphasis  of  the  result. 
Notice  the  decided  decrease  in  the  score  after  the  sixth  day  when  the  new 
method  was  taken  by  adding  the  figures  as  soon  as  they  were  obtained  in- 
stead of  first  multiplying  for  each  partial  product.  Subjectively  the  work 
was  much  easier  after  this  way  was  taken. 

Observer  V  (the  writer,  little  visualization  for  this  sort  of  work).  The 
method  of  observer  III,  namely,  the  addition  of  the  first  two  partial  pro- 
ducts was  deliberately  borrowed  and  used  in  the  first  day's  work.     The 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  REI.ATION  TO  LEARNING  20I 

calculation  was  consciously  made  as  rapidly  as  possible  that  the  parts  might 
not  be  forgotten  before  the  whole  had  been  secured.  On  the  fourth  day 
the  last  two  digits  of  the  first  sum  were  discarded  leaving  only  a  three- 
place  number  to  add.  Figures  when  they  were  required  for  addition  were 
fitted  into  a  visual '  'number-form' '  which  had  unconsciously  developed.  On 
the  sixth  and  eighth  days  new  methods  were  tried  which  worked  well  at  the 
time,  but  were  used  only  on  that  occasion.  The  first  was  to  add  the  first 
and  third  products  first,  the  second  to  place  the  digits  on  the  fingers  of 
each  hand  and  set  in  proper  juxtaposition.  It  was  evidently  forgotten. 
Two  column  addition  was  consciously  tried  and  used  in  instances  when  the 
numbers  to  handle  were  not  too  large. 

Observer  VI.  This  subject  developed  his  method  in  the  practice  tests 
and  did  not  change  it;  improvement  for  him  therefore  consisted  in  practice 
in  the  use  of  his  method.  It  was  to  break  the  mmiber  up  into  two  numbers, 
the  first  consisting  of  the  hundreds  and  tens  and  the  last  of  the  units,  and  to 
use  the  binomial  method  of  squaring;  in  obtaining  the  square  of  the  first 
(two-place)  number,  the  a^,  the  binomial  formula  was  also  used.  This 
method  occurred  to  the  subject  after  he  had  gone  to  bed  on  the  first  day  of 
squaring  a  three-place  number  by  full  multiplication,  and  he  considered  it 
an  original  method  until  several  days  later  a  distinct  visual  image  of  his 
old  arithmetic  book  with  its  thumb-worn  page  bearing  an  illustration  of 
a  formula  similar  to  this  for  extracting  the  square  root,  flashed  up  before 
him.  Part  of  the  original  experience,  without  its  localization  in  time  or 
place,  had  been  recalled,  and  given  him  what  he  considered  an  original 
idea.  Stronger  stimulation  of  the  complex  brought  it  back  in  all  its 
original  setting.  By  the  third  day  introspection  shows  less  attention  and 
strain  than  at  first,  the  method  had  become  spontaneous  and  it  was  easier 
to  keep  two  different  sets  of  numbers  in  mind.  Practice  had  resulted  in 
a  widening  of  the  field  of  consciousness.  The  sixth  day  the  observer  said 
the  work  was  easier  because  he  got  his  results  almost  at  a  glance  and  when 
they  came  he  saw  the  figures  under  the  ones  to  which  they  should  be  added. 
When  he  added  a  certain  column  he  saw  only  these  figures  distinctly;  the 
others  were  hazy,  but  he  could  call  them  up  when  he  wanted  them. 

At  the  close  of  the  experiment,  each  observer  was  asked  to 
give  a  report  as  to  what  he  thought  his  improvement  had 
consisted  in,  what  part  of  the  processes  was  conscious  and  what 
unconscious.  All  said  the  task  was  easier  at  the  close  than  at 
first.  Observer  II,  who  developed  a  very  simple  method  at 
first,  said  that  after  the  first  few  days  she  was  conscious  of 
little  improvement.  Three  observers  attribute  most  of  their 
improvement  to  the  adoption  of  an  easier  method,  and  three 
assigned  "practice"  a  large  place.  For  all,  the  calculation 
itself  was  a  highly  conscious  affair,  though  for  three,  the  re- 
sults sometimes  seemed  to  come  spontaneously.  Adoption  of 
new  methods  was  in  every  case  clearly  conscious,  and  not 
from  falling  into  a  certain  habit,  noticing,  and  continuing  it, 
as  was  the  case  in  the  target  throwing  and  the  writing.  Very 
slight  suggestions  from  one's  own  work  or  from  outside  were 
often  responsible  for  the  idea  of  the  new  way  of  working,  or 
it  "just  popped  in"  as  one  observer  stated.  However  it 
came,  the  idea  had  to  be  there  to  effect  the  change.  After 
the  method  was  practiced  a  little,  it  was  used  directly  and  with- 

J0URNA1.--5 


«02  ORDAHIv 

out  thought.  "Unconscious"  improvement  came  in  the 
widening  of  the  conscious  field,  adaptation  to  the  experiment 
and  the  Hke,  so  that  the  feeUng  of  strangeness  and  awkward- 
ness disappeared.  What  at  first  seemed  an  impossible  task 
no  longer  looked  so  when  one  became  oriented.  Possibly 
another  "unconscious' '  factor  was  the  gain  in  speed  in  making 
computations  as  the  result  of  greater  familiarity  with,  or  rather, 
refreshing  of,  the  addition  and  multiplication  tables.  Mere 
practice  caused  improvement  in  the  use  of  methods  con- 
sciously adopted. 

6,     Results  of  the  Last  Three  Series  of  Experiments 

The  results  of  the  last  three  series  of  experiments  seem  to 
agree  in  showing  that  the  function  of  consciousness  in  learn- 
ing is  to  improve  the  process  by  bringing  errors  to  light  and 
correcting  them,  and  by  adopting  improved  methods  suggested 
by  some  habit  fallen  into,  or  by  some  idea  as  to  better  possi- 
bilities. The  more  purely  muscular  the  process  to  be  learned, 
the  less  conscious  the  learning  of  it.  In  the  target  throwing 
improved  methods  of  throwing  came  about  of  themselves 
and  were  not  noticed  until  later.  Attention  to  the  mechanism 
only  resulted  in  disaster.  The  most  one  could  do  consciously 
was  to  attend  closely  to  the  bull's-eye  and  throw,  the  proper 
co-ordinations  seeming  to  take  place  of  themselves;  gross 
errors  only  were  consciously  corrected.  In  the  writing  ex- 
periments, consciousness  played  a  greater  r61e  in  supervising 
and  correcting  the  process,  and  for  some  observers  in  starting 
an  advantageous  method.  In  the  intellectual  task  of  squar- 
ing a  three-place  number  every  decided  step  in  advance  was 
the  result  of  a  conscious  change. 

But  these  three  grades  of  learning  all  showed  "unconscious' ' 
improvement  as  the  result  of  repetition  (even  the  arithmeti- 
cal computations),  improvement  which  was  entirely  at  the 
physiological  level.  Improvement,  therefore,  does  take  place 
without  the  control  of  consciousness.  Yet  even  at  the  grade 
of  learning  where  this  is  the  truest,  we  cannot  say  that  one  is 
unconscious,  but  perhaps  rather  that  marginal  awareness,  in 
the  sense  of  organic  and  peripheral  sensations,  and  feelings 
of  satisfaction  and  dissatisfaction,  is  always  present  and  affects 
the  result.  It  is,  one  may  conjecture,  a  feeling  of  dim  aware- 
ness akin  to  this  unanalyzable,  undifferentiated  state  which 
accompanies  the  learning  of  animals  low  in  the  scale.  That 
it  directs  the  learning  is  at  least  not  certain,  if  one  reasons 
by  analogy  from  human  learning  where  only  the  higher, 
more  specialized  acts  are  under  conscious  control.  The  sim- 
pler and  more  "muscular"  the  learning,  the  more  vague  and 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  REI^ATION  TO  LEARNING  203 

indefinite  the  subjective  accompaniment.  Practice  alone  is 
the  improving  factor.  In  more  complex  processes  like  writ- 
ing the  learner  is  able  to  assume  an  objective  attitude  and 
direct  and  criticise  his  own  activities  and  to  shorten,  by  choos- 
ing new  methods  or  avoiding  observable  mistakes,  a  process 
which  would  otherwise  require  much  mechanical  repetition. 
In  still  higher  operations,  like  arithmetical  calculations,  con- 
sciousness of  the  process  is  still  clearer.  It  acts  vicariously 
for  practice,  which  takes  a  subordinate  r61e.  The  r61e  of 
consciousness  is  similar  to  that  of  the  teacher  who  can  do  little 
for  one  learning  feats  of  muscular  skill  save  give  a  few  simple 
instructions,  leaving  the  rest  for  the  pupil  to  get  by  the  hit 
and  miss  of  practice;  but  in  more  complex  activities  he  can 
act  as  a  pattern,  giving  methods  and  pointing  out  deviations 
from  them.  Since  right  methods  and  easier  work  result  in 
a  widening  of  consciousness,  this  will  leave  the  pupil's  atten- 
tion free  for  still  further  advances. 

Summary 

In  Part  I  we  have  considered  consciousness  as  an  ultimate 
fact,  undefinable,  identical  with  awareness.  Unconscious- 
ness denotes  for  us  its  opposite —  entire  absence  of  awareness, 
that  which  is  entirely  outside  of  our  experience  at  any  moment 
of  time.  Subconsciousness,  for  which  we  prefer  to  substitute 
"perceptual"  factors,  gives  focal  consciousness  its  qualitative 
character.  Subconsciousness  is  consciousness  of  a  less  distinct 
degree.  Divided  consciousness,  such  as  is  present  in  cases  of 
multiple  personality,  is  best  called  "co-consciousness." 

The  question  of  the  existence  of  "unconscious  psychic 
processes,"  i.  e.,  psychic  accompaniments  of  physiological 
processes  lacking  awareness,  depends  for  its  answer  on  one's 
metaphysical  concepts,  which  are  in  the  end  a  purely  tempera- 
mental matter.  Denying  them  leads  to  the  interactionist 
position.  Throughgoing  psychophysical  parallelism  demands 
the  assumption  of  psychic  factors  accompanying  physiological 
changes,  and  this  position  we  have  taken,  insisting,  however, 
that  such  "psychic"  processes  are  qualitatively  different 
from  anything  which  enters  into  consciousness.  According 
to  such  a  view  one  may  speak  of  physiological  processes  in 
addition  to  "unconscious  psychic  processes." 

We  have  incidentally  reviewed  the  arguments  pro  and  con 
as  to  the  presence  of  "unconscious"  factors  and  their  influ- 
ence on  mental  phenomena.  Our  main  interest  was,  however, 
in  the  relation  of  consciousness  to  learning.  From  general 
observation  we  have  seen  no  case  of  learning  where  one  is 
absolutely  unconscious,  yet  one  may  be  unconscious  of  the 


204  ORDAHL 

end,  the  process  and  even  of  the  development  of  the  habit 
or  association  itself. 

Our  own  experimental  results  are  the  following : 

1.  Our  experiments  on  the  nonsense-syllable  material 
give  chiefly  negative  results,  but  justify,  so  far  as  the  conditions 
of  the  experiment  permit,  an  inference  that  what  is  entirely 
outside  of  consciousness,  though  it  is  in  such  a  position  that  it 
might  easily  become  conscious,  has  no  great  effect,  positive 
or  negative,  on  the  learning  of  the  same  material  when  it  is 
presented  later  to  clear  attentive  consciousness. 

2.  In  the  experiments  on  the  "Motor  Set"  (Motorische 
Einstellung)  we  find  that  a  habit  may  be  formed  despite  the 
fact  that  one  is  unconscious  that  one  is  forming  it.  Yet,  withal, 
attention  to  the  task  produces  in  all  cases  a  more  definite 
habit,  a  stronger  "Einstellung,"  than  that  which  is  caused  when 
one  is  almost  unconscious  of  his  performance.  Attentive 
consciousness  without  doubt  is  accompanied  by  greater  ten- 
sion in  the  particular  muscles  involved  in  the  current  activity 
of  the  organism  and  in  their  nervous  connections.  Here 
activity  is  concentrated.  The  more  fully  the  physiological 
mechanism  is  thus  put  into  activity  the  more  it  is  affected 
in  the  direction  of  easier  and  more  efl&cient  activity  of  the 
same  sort. 

3.  The  experiments  on  throwing  at  a  target  involved 
learning  of  a  sensory- motor  kind,  the  doing  of  a  definite  thing : 
it  was  practice  with  a  fixed  aim  in  view.  Here  focal  con- 
sciousness was  almost  entirely  projected  on  the  target,  the 
ball  and  hand  occupying  a  peripheral  place.  Conscious  con- 
trol was  exercised  only  over  the  grosser  parts  of  the  process. 
Methods  gradually  changed,  and  improvement  appeared,  with- 
out conscious  change  or  control.  The  sensations  from  the  arm 
and  body  no  doubt  contributed  to  the  improvement,  but  these 
were  always  at  the  "perceptual"  level  and  consisted  rather 
of  an  undifferentiated  background. 

4.  In  the  writing  experiments  conscious  direction  of  the 
process  and  methods  was  more  marked.  At  first  consciousness 
is  bound  down  to  the  general  execution  of  the  task.  The 
more  general,  larger  elements,  becoming  automatic,  leave 
consciousness  free  to  turn  to  details,  when  disadvantageous 
methods  are  noticed  one  by  one  and  eliminated.  Un- 
consciously modifications  in  the  method  crop  out,  and  as 
consciousness  becomes  freed  from  details  these  are  noticed, 
practiced,  and  improved  upon.  This  sometimes  results  in 
a  considerable  change  of  adjustment  of  the  different  factors. 

5.  In  the  experiments  on  mental  multiplication  conscious- 
ness had  a  more  immediate  effect  than  in  the  more  "muscular  " 
sorts  of  learning.    Here  advantageous  methods  occurred  to  the 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING  205 

subjects  while  they  were  working,  or  between  the  experiments, 
and  when  these  were  adopted  the  improvement  was  immediate 
and  permanent,  whereas  in  the  more  ''muscular"  sorts  of  learn- 
ing one's  muscular  co-ordinations  had  to  be  practiced  somewhat 
before  the  new  method  was  perfected.  In  the  number  experi- 
ments, just  because  one  is  alive  to  the  situation,  he  notices 
clumsy  methods  and  slight  errors,  and  is  therefore  ready  to 
improve  upon  them.  After  a  method  was  consciously  developed, 
however,  it  was  soon  used  unreflectingly — it  became  a  habit. 
In  proportion  as  an  activity  is  conscious,  consciousness  is  an 
aid  or  even  an  essential  factor  in  its  acquisition.  This  applies 
to  details  and  part-processes  as  well  as  to  the  larger  units  of 
activities. 


Conclusions 

In  conclusion  we  may  say  that  in  learning  of  any  sort  both 
conscious  and  unconscious  factors  exist.  Unconscious  fac- 
tors are  those  involved  in  the  fixing  of  the  association  by 
practice,  and  the  cropping  out  of  modifications  of  behavior 
subsequently  utilized  by  consciousness. 

The  more  intellectual  and  highly  conscious  the  material 
to  be  learned,  the  more  direct  and  immediate  the  effect  of 
conscious  control.  Practice  results  in  a  standing  out  of 
common  features  of  the  process;  these  are  focalized,  and 
generalized  into  rules  for  new  and  better  procedure,  which 
immediately  takes  place. 

In  complex  processes  involving  both  an  intellectual  and 
a  muscular  side,  the  activity  as  a  whole  is  conscious.  Details 
are  gradually  mechanized,  leaving  attention  free  to  attack 
new  difficulties.  Factors  of  the  activity  which  are  at  first 
only  at  the  "perceptual"  level  become  clearly  conscious,  are 
then  practiced  and  improved  upon,  and  finally  become 
mechanized  and  unconscious  again.  Consciousness  is  a 
corrective  agent,  eliminating  errors,  improving  on  elements 
unconsciously  developed,  and  organizing  the  whole  procedure. 

In  learning  simple  muscular  co-ordinations  consciousness  is 
focussed  entirely  on  the  end — on  the  outcome  of  the  move- 
ment. One  is  only  dimly  aware  of  the  different  sensations 
and  feelings  entering  into  his  bodily  adjustment,  and  should 
any  of  these  become  the  object  of  attention,  disturbance  of 
co-ordination  results. 

Learning  can  progress,  however,  without  consciousness  of 
the  end  or  of  the  fact  that  one  is  learning,  but  even  here  a 
high  degree  of  attention  to  one's  task  brings  more  marked 
results  than  work  under  distraction. 


2G6  ordahl 

So  far  as  our  experiments  go,  factors  never  entering  con- 
sciousness have  neither  a  beneficial  nor  hindering  effect  on  the 
learning.^ 

^The  writer  wishes  to  express  iher  obligation  for  the  faithful  service  of 
those  who  served  as  observers  in  the  above  experiments,  and  particularly 
to  Dr.  E.  C.  Sanford,  in  whose  laboratory  the  work  was  done  and  at  whose 
suggestion  the  subject  was  begun. 

Appendix 
Experiments  with  Meaningless  Syllables 

The  general  plan  of  these  experiments  has  already  been  described  in  the 
body  of  the  paper  (pp  179  ff).  It  is  only  necessary  here  to  record  the  details 
of  procedure.  The  work  was  done  with  twelve-syllable  series  of  meaning- 
less syllables  prepared  in  accordance  with  the  method  of  MuUer  and 
Schumann's  "verschdrft  normal"  series,^  except  that  additional  letters 
were  used  to  increase  the  possible  number  of  syllables  and  to  adapt  them  to 
English  speaking  observers  familiar  with  German.  There  were  20  initial 
consonants  and  double  consonants,  (b,  d,  f,  g,  h,  j,  k,  1,  m,  n,  p,  r,  s,  t,  v, 
w,  z,  th,  sh,  ch),  19  finals,  (b,  d,  f,  g,  j,  k,  1,  m,  v,  p,  r,  s,  t,  v,  x,  z,  th,  sh,  ch) 
and  14  vowels  and  diphthongs  (a,  e,  i,  o,  u,  y,  a,  6,  ii,  ai,  oi,  ee,  00,  ou).* 
These  syllables  were  presented  by  means  of  a  rotating  dnun  of  the  inter- 
mittent-movement type,  manufactured  by  Spindler  and  Hoyer  of  Gottin- 
gen,  which  permitted  the  syllables  to  remain  at  rest  during  the  greater 
part  of  the  time  of  their  exposure.  (See  Fig.  II  which  shows  the 
apparatus  from  the  back  and  side.)  The  syllables  were  seen  through  the 
opening  of  a  suitable  screen  (See  Fig.  Ill)  in  such  fashion  that  a  single 
syllable  of  the  series  to  be  learned  appeared  each  time  between  two 
syllables  of  series  with  which  at  the  moment  the  observer  had  nothing 
to  do.     Thus  the  syllables 

tarn      pog      hex 
would  be  shown,  the  observer  being  required  to  learn  the  middle  series  to 
which  pog  belongs,  but  having  nothing  to  do  at  the  time  with  the  series 
to  which  tarn  and  hex  belong. 

The  observer  sat  before  the  screen  and  read  the  syllables  of  the  middle 
series  as  they  appeared  through  the  slit.  The  experimenter  sat  at  the 
side  of  the  machine  to  the  observer's  right,  his  movements  being  entirely 
concealed  from  the  latter  by  a  large  screen  of  gray  cardboard.  Directly 
in  front  of  the  apparatus  and  resting  on  the  same  table  was  a  second  drum, 
a  portion  of  the  surface  of  which  could  be  seen  through  a  slit  in  the  black 
cardboard  screen  before  it.  (See  Fig.  III.)  The  syllables  were  all  learned 
by  the  "Treffer  method,"  and  the  "TrefTer  syllables"  were  shown  on 
this  drum,  which  was  turned  by  the  subject  as  the  syllables  were  required. 

The  syllables  to  be  learned  were  written  on  strips  of  white  paper  123^ 
X  3  inches,  ruled  with  fourteen  lines  and  so  proportioned  to  the  drum,  that 
after  one  complete  presentation  of  the  series,  two  blank  spaces  were 
shown  before  the  first  syllable  of  the  series  reappeared.  The  odd  ntmi- 
bered  members  of  the  series — the  "Treffer  syllables" — were  also  written  on 
strips  lo]/^  X  3  inches  to  fit  the  smaller  drum. 

The  experiments  fell  into  three  series.  A,  B,  and  C,  and  were  carried 
out  with  two  trained  observers  S  and  E. 

1  Mullet  u.  Schumann :  Experimentelle  Beitrage  zur  Untersuchuog  des  Gedachtnisses, 
Zeit.  f.  Psych..  VI,  1893-94,  106. 

2  The  series  were  prepared  throughout  the  greater  part  of  the  work  by  a  competent  assist- 
ant not  otherwise  connected  with  the  cucperiment. 


(^ 


Fig.  II 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING  207 

Experiment  A.  Problem:  If  a  series  of  syllables  is  presented  within 
the  range  of  clear  vision  alongside  of  a  second  series  which  is  to  be  learned, 
and  engages  the  observer's  attention,  to  find  whether  such  a  side  series 
to  which  no  especial  attention  has  been  given  will  later  be  more  easily 
learned  because  of  its  exposure  to  possible  "unconscious"  perception. 
If  Sidis's  and  Scripture's  experiments  are  vahd  in  their  results,  it  was 
judged  that  we  should  find  evidence  of  '  'subconscious' '  learning  in  the  more 
ready  memorizing  of  series  which  have  been  so  exposed. 

Three  of  the  above  mentioned  twelve-syllable  series  were  written  in 
three  vertical  columns,  so  that  the  first  syllable  of  each  series  appeared 
to  the  observer  through  the  slit  at  the  same  time,  then,  as  the  dnma  turned, 
the  second  syllable  of  the  three  series  together,  and  so  on  to  the  end. 
These  series  we  shall  call  a,  b,  c,  reading  from  left  to  right,  h  being  the 
middle  series,  and  the  one  learned.^  On  a  second  strip  were  written  three 
series,  d,  a,  e;  d  and  e  being  entirely  new  series  and  a,  the  one  which  had 
stood  to  the  left  of  b,  the  first  series  learned.  On  a  third  strip  was  written 
an  entirely  new  set  of  three  series,  /,  g,  h;  on  a  fourth  strip,  i,  h,  j,  of 
which  h  had  stood  to  the  right  of  g,  the  series  previously  learned.  All  ten 
of  these  series  were  "verschdrft"  series,  and  the  ten  together  constituted  a 
regular  set. 

The  number  of  series  which  could  be  used  for  each  subject  was,  from 
the  nature  of  the  case,  limited  (11  sets  for  5  and  12  for  E).  The  method 
of  obtaining  syllables  enough  for  all  the  experiments  and  avoiding  familiar- 
ity with  the  syllables  as  much  as  possible  was  this.  Syllable  series  which 
had  been  side  syllables  for  E,  but  not  learned  (there  were  6  such  in  every 
set),  were  transposed  so  that  they  occupied  the  places  of  b,  a,  g  and  h  which 
had  been  learned,  and  were  then  given  to  S,  and  vice  versa.  Thus,  if 
series  retained  their  former  lettering  they  would  read  j,  i,  h;  g,  j,  f;  e,  d,  c; 
h,  c,  a.  After  each  subject  had  learned  these  transformed  series,  E.  was  given 
the  transformed  series  for  S,  and  S  for  E.  Then  each  was  given  the  series 
the  other  had  learned  first,  but  the  syllables  of  the  individual  series  were 
shifted.  This  made  a  possibility  of  552  new  syllables  for  each  subject. 
When  these  had  been  run  through,  the  second  and  third  permutation 
(which  the  subject  had  learned  before)  was  repeated. 

An  extra  series  (indicated  in  what  follows  by  x)  was  also  used  each  day 
and  was  obtained  by  taking  a  strip  from  an  unused  set  and  learning  the 
middle  series.  One  set  thus  divided  furnished  extra  series  for  four  days. 
This  extra  series  was  given  sometimes  first,  sometimes  third  and  sometimes 
fifth  in  the  order  of  the  day,  each  subject  being  kept  in  ignorance  of  its 
position,  so  that  he  was  never  aware  of  which  series  he  was  learning.  The 
order  which  was  maintained  for  the  learning  was,  therefore,  either:  x,  b, 
fl,  g>  h;  or  b,  a,  x,  g,  h;  or  b,  a,  g,  h,  x. 

The  odd  nmnbered  syllables  of  the  middle  series  of  each  strip  were 
written  in  the  centre  of  a  slip  fitting  the  "Treffer"  drum;  here,  therefore, 
there  appeared  through  the  slit  only  one  syllable  at  a  time  instead  of  three. 
For  the  first  three  days,  the  "Treffer"  order  was  given  according  to  the 
permutations  of  Muller  and  Pilzecker*  but  afterwards  the  "Treffer*^  sylla- 
bles were  written  in  a  direct  order  from  one  to  eleven,  as  it  was  decided 
that  a  varied  scheme  would  give  less  uniform  results  with  a  moderate  num- 
ber of  experiments,  and  would  not  in  any  case  influence  the  point  at  issue 
in  the  experiment. 

The  average  time  taken  for  ten  revolutions  of  the  drum  during  the  practice 
work  and  for  two  days  of  regular  work  was  87.1  seconds  for  ten  revolutions 
or  0.62  -I-  seconds  per  syllable.  This  speed  was  accelerated  on  March  10 
(the  third  day),  and  from  then  on  was  80.2  sec.  per  10  revolutions  or  0.57  -f 
second  per  single  syllable. 

^  The  middle  series  is  always  the  one  learned  in  these  experiments. 

^MilUer  u.  Pilzecker:  Experimentelle  Beitrage  ztir  Lebre  vom  Gedachtniss.  Zci/. /.  FjycA. 
Erg.  Bd.  I.  1900. 


208  ORDAHL 

Each  observer  served  as  experimenter  when  the  other  was  observer. 
Both  knew  the  object  of  the  experiment,  but  neither  knew  the  results 
until  the  experiment  was  finished,  as  no  accounts  were  cast  until  the  end. 
With  the  exception  of  the  first  two  days  of  regular  experimentation,  when 
E.  worked  at  2  p.  m.,  E.  served  as  subject  from  8  until  9  a.  m.  and  5.  from 
12  to  I  p.  M.  (The  time  for  E.  was  changed  because  syllables  which  5.  had 
recited  at  12  persisted  and  acted  as  a  disturbing  factor.) 

From  January  24,  1909,  to  March  7  practice  work  was  carried  on  every 
day  except  Sunday  and  four  days  of  the  Easter  Vacation.  Regular  work 
began  March  8  and  was  carried  on  every  day  except  Sunday  and  one  day 
when  5'.  was  out  of  town  and  another  day  for  E.  when  the  machine  was  out 
of  order,  making  25  days  of  regular  work  for  5.  and  24  for  E. 

At  the  words  "In  your  place"  the  observer  took  his  seat  before  the  ma- 
chine. This  was  started  and  the  drum  allowed  to  make  one  revolution 
to  get  its  speed;  as  the  first  blank  space  appeared  the  experimenter  called 
'  'ready,"  and  lowered  a  shutter  previously  hiding  the  drum.  The  observer 
began  to  read  as  soon  as  the  first  syllable  appeared,  reading  through  the 
whole  series  of  twelve  syllables.  After  the  two  blank  spaces  had  passed 
the  series  was  read  through  again,  and  so  on,  imtil  it  had  been  repeated 
twelve  times.  The  syllables  were  read  pair-wise,  at  first  in  trochaic 
rhythm;  later  both  observers  fell  into  the  iambic.  When  the  last  syllable 
was  read  on  the  twelfth  revolution,  the  experimenter  raised  the  shutter 
and  started  a  stop  watch.  The  observer  began  immediately  to  turn  the 
'  'Treffer' '  dnmi,  which  was  adjusted  so  that  a  single  blank  space  preceded 
the  first  "Treffer"  syllable,  and  read  each  "Treffer"  syllable  as  it  came  up, 
giving,  if  possible,  its  associated  syllable  {i.  e.,  the  syllable  which  had 
formed  the  other  half  of  the  pair) ;  when  he  could  not  recall  a  syllable  he 
said  '  'don't  know' '  and  passed  on  to  the  next.  When  the  last  associated 
syllable  had  been  given  (or  given  up)  the  stop  watch  was  stopped.  This 
made  a  somewhat  rough  method  of  timing,  but  was  effective  enough  for 
this  experiment  in  which  time  was  only  a  minor  consideration.  The  obser- 
ver was  neither  hindered  nor  helped  by  the  fact  that  he  was  being  timed. 
A  list  of  each  series  to  be  learned  had  previously  been  written  in  a  blank 
book  and  opposite  each  syllable  was  placed  a  check  mark,  if  the  correct 
syllable  were  given,  a  dash  if  none  came,  or  the  syllable  which  was  given  if 
a  wrong  one  was  given.  After  testing  his  associations  with  the  "Treffer" 
syllables  the  observer's  introspections  were  taken  on  such  items  as  the 
difficulty  of  the  series,  the  conditions  of  his  attention,  and  influences  which 
might  have  favored  or  been  disadvantageous  to  the  learning  or  reproduc- 
ing of  the  series.  The  whole  process — repeating  the  series,  giving  the 
associated  syllables  and  the  introspections — took,  on  an  average,  two  and 
a  half  minutes.  Ten  minutes  after  the  first  series  was  begun,  the  experi- 
menter again  called,  "In  your  place,"  and  began  the  second  series  by 
starting  the  drum  and,  at  a  ready  signal,  letting  down  the  shutter.  Be- 
tween the  learnings  a  free  time  of  about  seven  and  a  half  minutes  elapsed. 
In  this  interval  the  observer  was  allowed  to  relax  as  he  pleased,  either  in 
looking  over  books,  walking  around  the  room,  or  gazing  out  of  the  window. 
But  any  taxing  occupation  which  absorbed  the  attention  to  a  considerable 
degree  was  avoided  as  it  was  found  to  have  an  unfavorable  effect  on  suc- 
ceeding series. 

In  computing  the  results  a  unit  was  allowed  for  each  perfect  syllable, 
6  therefore  being  the  score  for  a  perfect  record,  i.  e.,  the  recall  of  each  of  the 
six  even  numbered  syllables.  An  average  was  taken  for  each  of  the 
series  for  the  whole  period  of  the  experiment  (24-25  days).  A  modified 
average  was  also  made  in  order  to  include  partial  successes  as  follows: 
One-third  was  given  for  each  vowel,  diphthong,  consonant  or  double 
consonant  correctly  given.  Thus  a  syllable  having  only  the  vowel 
correct  would  sctwe  i  and  one  having  its  two  consonants  or  a  consonant 
and  the  vowels,  |. 


Fig.  III. 

Fig.  III.  In  this  figure  the  screen  of  the  upper  drum  is  arranged  to  show  but  a  single  syl- 
lable, an  arrangement  used  in  Experiments  B  and  C  below.  In  Experiment  A  it  was  open 
full  width  horizontally  and  showed  three  syllables  at  a  time.  The  treffer  drum  is  seen 
below  behind  the  black  cardboard  screen. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING 


209 


The  average  of  these  results  gives  the  modified  average.  Stated  in 
tabular  form  the  results  are  as  follows:  The  figures  in  parentheses  stand 
for  the  averages  reckoned  from  perfect  syllables  only,  and  those  standing 
free,  for  the  modified  averages. 


06 

«o 

W 

Ph' 

-H 

-H 

^_^ 

^ 

•^ 

"«*• 

'^ 

00 

M 

o^ 

*? 

00 

0» 

pi 

«o 

c< 

to 

" — ' 

v-^ 

w 

2 

Ov 

(k 

-H 

-H 

0 

VO 

0 

ji 

00 

00 

q 

c< 

fO 

fi 

CO 

"" 

'  ' 

W 

w 

M 

o; 

41 

-H 

t-t 

w 

vO 

T»- 

fi 

8 

i 

bo 

00 

N 

Tt- 

N 

«o 

c« 

«o 

H 

.^ 

0 

t^ 

w 

-M 

-w 

et 

? 

S 

to 

to 

»o 

ro 

to 

^_^ 

w 

M 
CI 

fO 

^ 

-H 

+1 

^ 

c« 

c< 

OO" 

10 

Xi 

vq 

M 

M 

>o 

c* 

«o 

v!2 

to 

"^ 

s 

CO 

W 

"C 

« 

s 

For  observer  5  the  a  series  has  a  slight  advantage  over  the  b  series,  btit 
the  P.  E.  is  so  large  that  its  advantage  is  quite  uncertain.  The  h  series  is 
inferior  to  the  g  series.  Taking  account  of  subjective  conditions  we  find 
that  the  a  series  was  on  the  average  learned  under  more  favorable  circum- 


3IO 


ORDAHL 


Stances  than  the  b  series,  and  the  g  series  than  the  k  series;  i.  e.,  there  were 
more  "mnemonics,"  the  syllables  were  easier,  or  attentive  conditions  were 
better.  For  E  the  a  series  is  poorer  on  the  average  than  the  b  series,  but 
the  h  series  is  better  than  the  g  series,  if  only  perfect  syllables  are  considered ; 
if  the  modified  averages  are  compared  the  two  are  equal.  Here  subjective 
conditions  are  slightly  in  favor  of  the  g  series.  We  may  therefore  infer 
from  the  results  of  both  observers  that  tie  mere  fact  of  having  been  shown 
as  a  side  series  does  not  favor  that  series  when  that  series  itself  is  to  be 
learned — at  least  not  to  a  degree  suflBcient  to  be  detected  by  this  method 
of  experimentation. 

If  we  arrange  the  averages  of  each  series  according  to  the  position  it 
occupied  in  the  day's  programme  we  have  the  following  table: 


Observer  5 


Table  II 


Observer  E 


Place  in 
day's  pro- 
gramme 

I  St 

2nd 

3rd 

4th 

5th 

I  St 

2nd 

3rd 

4th 

5th 

X 

3-2 

3. 

2.5 

3.0 

2.9 

2.8 

B 

2.8 

2.3 

3.37 

3- 

A 

2.9 

325 

3.19 

2.6 

G 

3-3 

2.68 

2.43 

2.42 

H 

3-3 

2.75 

329 

2.77 

Average 

3.0 

2.6 

3.18 

2.99 

2.62 

3.18 

3  09 

2.64 

2.85 

2.80 

The  figures  on  the  first  line,  reading  across,  denote  the  place  in  the  day's 
work;  the  first  column  gives  the  name  of  the  series.  The  partial  successes 
are  included  in  the  figures  used  for  this  table.  These  figures  show  that 
when  series  of  a  certain  denomination  come  early,  they  almost  without 
exception  show  better  results  than  when  they  occupy  a  later  place  in  the 
experiment,  and  there  is  also  a  tendency  to  a  general  decrease  from  the 
first  to  fifth  place  as  the  X  series  and  the  averages  show.  We  find  a  slight 
exception  for  S,  where  there  is  a  rise  for  the  third  series  of  the  set  after  a 
low  score  for  the  second  series.  Subjective  conditions  probably  account 
for  the  increase  here.  What  we  had  therefore  in  Table  I  is  probably  only 
the  result  of  this  general  tendency. 

Experiment  B  was  next  undertaken.  The  problem  was  to  find  whether 
a  side  series  actually  read  a  single  time  with  full  attention  would  be  learned 
more  readily  for  that  fact,  if  between  the  reading  and  the  learning,  another 
series  were  learned.  The  apparatus  and  conditions  of  the  experiment 
were  those  for  experiment  A  with  the  following  changes:  Two  pieces  of 
black  cardboard  were  made  to  fit  in  a  groove  under  the  slit  in  the  screen. 
One  was  a  straight  piece  which  was  just  long  enough  to  cover  the  middle 
and  one  side  syllable,  letting  the  other  side  syllable  show.  This  could  be 
slipped  to  the  right  or  the  left,  exposing  the  syllables  of  whichever  side 
was  desired.  A  second  piece  of  cardboard  had  a  square  hole  cut  in  the 
middle,  so  that  when  it  was  slipped  into  the  groove,  only  the  middle  one 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING 


211 


of  the  three  series  appeared.  One  or  the  other  of  these  pieces  of  cardboard 
was  kept  before  the  slit  all  the  time,  so  that  only  one  syllable  ever  appeared 
to  the  subject  at  a  time,  and  that  a  syllable  of  the  series  being  read  or 
"learned."  The  cardboards  were  manipulated  by  the  observer.  The 
procedure  was  as  follows:  One  series  was  read  a  single  time  by  the  ob- 
server, the  shutter  was  closed  by  the  experimenter  and  the  cardboard 
changed  or  shifted  so  that  the  series  to  be  "learned"  would  show;  the 
experimenter  lowered  the  shutter  at  the  end  of  the  one  intervening  revolu- 
tion, and  the  observer  then  began  the  reading  of  the  series  to  be  "learned." 
As  before,  ten  minutes  intervened  for  rest  and  introspections  between  the 
beginning  of  successive  series.  The  programme  in  outline  is  as  follows, — 
Read  a  once,  and  wait  i  revolution  of  the  drum 
"Learn"   b,  i.  e.,  read  6  12  times 

"        a      "      "a  "      "    beginning  10  min.  after  beginning  b 
g       "       "    g  "      "  "  "       "       "  "  a 

h      "      "    h  "      "  "  "      "      "  "  g 

Read  i  beginning  10  min.  after  learning  h;  wait  i  turn  of  the  drum 
"Learn"  j,   i.  e.,  read  j  12  times 

"        i,      "      "      i"       "  beginning  10  min.  after  beginning  J. 

The  a  series  was  always  written  at  the  left  of  one  strip,  the  b  series  in 
the  middle,  the  g  series  in  the  middle  and  h  on  the  right  of  a  second  strip, 
the  i  and  j  series  on  the  left  and  right,  respectively,  of  a  third  strip  of  paper. 
No  extra  series  were  used.  The  g  and  h  series,  which  were  learned  without 
having  been  previously  read  were  used  as  a  check  on  the  results  of  the 
other  four  series. 

The  experiment  extended  from  April  14  through  April  24,  omitting  the 
intervening  Sunday,  making  ten  days  of  experimental  work.  Twelve 
repetitions  were  used  for  each  series  except  for  S,  for  whom  the  number 
of  repetitions  was  reduced  to  ten  on  the  seventh  day,  because  he  was  fre- 
quently getting  more  than  half  the  syllables  right. 

The  results  are  given  in  the  following  table: 


Table  III 


Series    b   (P.E.) 


a  (P.E.) 


g  (P.E.) 


h   (P.E.) 


j    (P.E.) 


i    (P.E.) 


Obs.  S4-7       36 

4-7       36 


3-7 
3-5 


•15 
.23 


4.6 
4-3 


3.2 
30 


19 
27 

24 
23 


4-5 
41 

3-3 
30 


.26 
■15 

•30 
•17 


3-7 
3-5 

3-4 
31 


26 
23 

17 
21 


3.7 
3-3 

3-2 
2.8 


.26 
•23 

.28 
.28 


4.7 

4-5 

3.4 
Z2> 


24 
31 

32 

37 


The  second  line  of  averages,  reading  across,  are  those  for  perfect  syllables 
only. 

If  a  single  reading  of  the  series  before  learning  a  second  series  has  helped 
the  first  series  when  it  was  learned  ten  minutes  later,  the  a  series  will  be 
better  than  the  b  and  the  *  than  the  j.  But  considering  the  large  P.  E. 
neither  series  for  E  is  helped  by  its  reading,  nor  the  a  series  for  5.  But 
for  the  latter  the  *  series  shows  a  marked  superiority  to  the  j  series.  This 
is  in  part  explained  by  the  introspective  accounts  which  show  that  this 
series  was  favored  by  slightly  better  conditions,  as  ease  of  syllables  and 
attention  paid  while  learning  the  series.  The  superiority  of  the  g  over  the 
h  series  is  also  to  be  explained  in  the  same  way. 


212 


ORDAHIy 


It  was  thought,  after  obtaining  these  results  that  perhaps  the  a  series 
did  not  show  an  increased  average  because  the  average  of  the  b  series  was 
kept  high  by  the  fact  that  it  was  the  first  series  and,  for  that  reason,  learned 
with  special  energy;  also,  the  i  series  might  have  been  favored  above  the  j 
series  because  of  a  renewed  impulse  to  succeed  which  often  comes  when 
one  is  almost  at  the  end  of  his  task.  Therefore,  a  third  variation  was 
tried  as  follows: 

Experiment  C.  The  two  indifferent  series,  g  and  h,  were  made  respectively 
the  first  and  last  series  learned.  The  places  of  the  a  and  b  series  on  the 
drimi  were  interchanged,  and  also  those  of  the  i  and  j  series  to  avoid  any 
effects  which  position  at  the  right  or  left  of  the  paper  might  have  had. 
The  principle  of  the  experiment  is,  however,  precisely  that  of  Experiment  B, 
viz.,  one  series  was  read,  a  second  learned,  and  then  the  series  which  had 
been  read  was  learned.  The  time  intervals  are  those  of  Experiment  B. 
The  scheme  in  outline  is: 

Learn  g  Read  j 

Read  b  Learn  i 

Learn  a  Learn  j 

Learn  b  Learn  h 

In  order  to  get  as  exact  information  as  possible  as  to  the  relative  ease 

of  the  series  compared,  account  was  taken  of  all  the  "mnemonics"  and 

of  slight  associative  aids.     After  giving  the  syllables  associated  with  the 

"Treffer"  syllables,  the  observer  was  shown  the  series  again  and  asked  to 

give  with  that  help  any  '  'mnemonics' '  or  other  aid  he  had  had  in  learning 

the  series,  and  these  the  experimenter  noted  down. 

The  experiment  extended  from  April  28  through  May  10,  omitting  Sun- 
day, May  2,  and  covered  ten  experimental  days.  The  results  are  given 
in  Table  IV.  The  second  line  of  averages  for  each  subject  takes  account 
of  perfect  syllables  only. 


Tablk  IV 

Series 

g  (P.B.) 

a  (P.E.) 

b  (P.E.) 

i  (P.E.; 

j    (P.E.) 

h   (P.E.) 

Obs.  S 
E 

4-7      .17 
4.2      .14 

4.2      .21 
4.1      .21 

4-5      .22 
4.2      .23 

4-3      .24 
4.1      .26 

3-9      .23 
3-6      .25 

4.1      .30 
3.9      .32 

3-4       30 
3-1      .32 

2.9      .40 
2.6      .42 

4.2     .33 
3.7     .26 

4.0     .24 
3.7     .23 

3.7     .20 
3-5      .25 

3-7      .31 
3.5      .31 

If  reading  the  series  were  a  help,  the  b  series  would  show  better  results 
than  the  a  series,  and  the  j  than  the  i,  but  this  is  not  the  case  except  for 
the  i  and  j  series  when  learned  by  E,  where,  despite  the  large  P.  E.,  the  j 
series  shows  a  real  superiority.  This  is  due  to  the  fact  that  on  two  of  the 
experimental  days  the  j  series  was  extraordinarily  better  than  the  i,  and 
if  these  two  days  are  left  out  of  consideration  the  difference  is  too  slight 
to  be  of  importance.  As  experiments  B  and  C  are  really  two  divisions  of 
the  same  experiment,  there  being  no  difference  in  character,  we  may  average 
the  results  of  the  two,  which  will  give  the  results  for  twenty  days  experi- 
mentation. Series  i  and  3  are  those  learned  without  previous  reading, 
and  2  and  4  those  learned  with  one  reading  before  an  intervening  series 
was  learned.  They  are  contained  in  the  table  following;  only  the  averages 
including  partially  correct  syllables  are  given. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  IN  RELATION  TO  LEARNING 
TABI.B  V 


213 


Series 

I     (P.E.) 

2    (P.E.) 

3    (P.E.) 

4    (P.E.) 

Obs.  S  Av. 
Exper.  B 
C 
Av. 

Observer  E 
Exper.  B 
Exper.  C 
Av. 

4.7     .36 

4.5  .22 

4.6  .29 

3.7  .15 
4.3     .24 
4.0     .20 

4.6  .19 
3.9     .23 
4.3     .21 

3.2     .24 
4.1     .30 

3.7  .27 

3.7    .26 
3.4    .30 
3.6    .28 

3.2    .17 
2.9    .40 
3.1    .29 

4.7     .24 
4-2      .33 
4.5       29 

3-4      .32 
4.0     .24 
3.7      .28 

If  the  extra  reading  was  of  advantage.  Series  2  should  be  better  than 
series  i,  and  4  than  3.  This  is  indeed  the  case  with  series  4  for  5  and  to  a 
slighter  degree  for  E,  but  for  series  i  and  2  the  required  relation  is  exactly 
reversed.  Unless  one  is  willing  to  infer  that  the  preliminary  reading  is  a 
hindrance  at  the  beginning  of  the  day's  session  and  a  help  at  its  close  (for 
which  there  seems  no  obvious  reason),  one  is  forced  to  regard  the  result 
of  the  experiment  as  negative.  Subjective  conditions,  such  as  better 
attention,  will  perhaps  explain  the  difference. 

In  conclusion  we  may  say,  then,  that  the  results  of  all  our  experiments 
with  meaningless  syllables  were  negative.  The  presence  of  a  series  on 
the  side  of  a  series  learned  did  not  cause  this  side  series  to  show  more 
facile  learning  than  the  series  not  so  aided,  at  least  to  a  degree  discoverable 
by  our  method.  Nor  did  actually  reading  the  series  before  learning  a 
series  give  clearly  better  results  for  this  series  when  it  was  learned  later. 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES' 


By  H0LSN  Maud  Clarke 


CONTENTS 


Introduction         214 

Incidental  Analyses 215 

1.  Types  of  Observers 216 

2.  Attitudes  Analysed 217 

3.  Gradation  of  Imagery 221 

Detailed  Analyses 224 

I.     Explicit 224 

Surprise 225 

Seeking 225 

Doubt,  Hesitation,  Uncertainty    .  .      ,      .      .  .227 

2.     Genetic 230 

Aufgabe  or  Task 230 

Recognition 232 

Understanding 236 

Relation 242 

Conclusion 247 

The  term  Bewusstseinslage^  in  the  sense  of  'conscious  atti- 
tude,* was  introduced  into  experimental  psychology,  at  Marbe  's 
suggestion  (1901),  by  Mayer  and  Orth,  who  employed  it  to 
characterise  certain  conscious  phenomena,  describable  neither 
as  determinate  ideas  nor  as  volitions,  which  appeared  in  the 
course  of  a  quaHtative  study  of  association.  These  phenome- 
na are  referred  to  by  Marbe  himself  (1901)  as  "obvious  facts 
of  consciousness,  whose  contents,  nevertheless,  either  do  not 
permit  at  all  of  a  detailed  characterisation,  or  at  any  rate  are 
difficult  to  characterise;"  instances  are  doubt,  difficulty, 
effort,  assent,  conviction.  Marbe  offers,  then,  no  definition 
of  the  conscious  attitude;  he  gives  only  a  negative  criterion 
and  a  list  of  examples.  Messer  (1906)  adds  to  the  list,  and  at 
the  same  time  extends  the  range  of  the  term,  using  it  to  in- 
clude experiences  of  logical  relation,  of  the  meaning  of  words 
and  sentences,  etc.  Biihler  (1907)  restricts  the  attitudes  to 
the  "mehr  zustandlichen  Erlebnisstrecken,  die  als  Zweifeln, 
Besinnen,  Abwarten,  Erstaunen,  usw.  beschrieben  werden." 
Marbe  seems  not  to  approve  of  the  restriction:  "die  neuer- 
dings  versuchte  Einschrankung  des  Begriffes  der  Bewusstseins- 
lage  entspricht  nicht  den  Ausfiihrungen   Marbes,"   declares 

>  From  the  Psychological  Laboratory  of  Cornell  Uniyersity. 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES 


215 


a  recent  writer  from  the  Wiirzburg  laboratory;  and  the  im- 
plication is  that  Marbe  holds  to  his  original  ideas.  ^ 

It  is  clear  that  to  attempt  a  definition  of  'conscious  attitude* 
at  the  present  time,  would  be  premature.  We  use  the  phrase 
to  denote  certain  large  and  comprehensive  experiences,  not 
evidently  imaginal  in  character;  and  it  is  our  aim,  in  this 
study,  to  bring  these  experiences  to  the  test  of  introspective 
observation,  and  thus  to  discover  whether  or  not  they  are 
analy sable.  Whatever  be  the  outcome  of  the  discussion  of 
'imageless  thought,'  it  is  probable  that  the  name  'conscious 
attitude'  will  be  retained  as  a  descriptive  term;  but  how  the 
attitudes  are  to  be  distinguished,  analytically,  from  'thoughts' 
on  the  one  hand,  and  'emotions'  on  the  other,  must  be  left  for 
the  future  to  decide. 

Incidentai.  Analyses 

The  conscious  attitude  is,  in  general,  an  elusive  experience, 
which  it  is  difficult  to  secure  in  isolation;  we  therefore  re- 
sorted in  the  main  to  an  indirect  method,  and  sought  to  arouse 
conscious  situations  in  which  various  attitudes  would  be  likely 
to  occur.  The  observers  were  instructed  to  give  complete 
introspections.  Th6  stimuli  in  the  first  series  of  experiments 
were  letters  or  words  which  were  written  in  the  blind  point- 
alphabet,  and  were  perceived  tactually.  At  the  first  sitting 
the  observer  was  given  a  slip  bearing  several  letters  in  their 
alphabetical  order,  and  was  allowed  to  feel  them,  and  to 
associate  the  name  to  the  tactual  perception  in  any  way  that 
he  chose.  Then  letters  or  words  were  given  him  to  be  rec- 
ognised. The  experiments  by  this  method  fall  into  two 
periods.  Those  performed  during  the  spring  term  of  1909 
were  tentative,  and  their  results  were  used  for  the  improve- 
ment of  the  method.  The  stimuli  for  single  experiments 
were  short  words  or  nonsense-combinations  of  letters.  The 
introspections  were  written  by  the  observers. 

When  the  work  was  taken  up  again  in  October,  the  method 
was  somewhat  modified.  Only  single  letters,  the  first  ten 
of  the  alphabet,  were  used  as  stimuli.  The  whole  of  a  word, 
perceived  tactually,  cannot  be  'taken  in  at  a  glance'  as  in  visual 
perception.  If  the  letters  were  mere  nonsense-combinations, 
each  letter  had  to  be  recognised  separately;  the  experiences 
thus  became  complex,  and  the  introspective  report  might  be 
incomplete.  If  the  letters  made  a  word,  the  observer  tended 
to  interpret  from  context,  which  further  complicated  the  prob- 
lem.    In  the  new  series,  the  reports  were  dictated,  and  writ- 

^On  conscious  attitudes  in  general,  see  E.  B.  Titchener,  Exp.  Psychol,  of 
the  Thought-processes,  1909,  98  fif.,  270,  etc.;  E.  von  Aster,  Zeits.  f.  Psychol., 
xlix.,  1908,  60  fif.;  on  Marbe's  position,  M.  Beer,  ibid.,  Ivi.,  1910,  265. 


2l6  CLARKE 

ten  down  by  the  experimenter.  The  most  important  change  in 
method,  however,  was  the  measurement  of  the  reaction-time. 
The  instrument  used  was  a  Vernier  chronoscope,  one  key  of 
which  had  been  replaced  by  a  lever  arranged  just  above  the 
letter  to  be  felt.  When  the  observer  touched  the  letter  he 
moved  the  lever,  and  thus  broke  a  current  and  released  the 
pendulum.  A  finger  of  the  left  hand  rested  throughout  on 
the  other  reaction  key;  as  soon  as  the  observer  recognised  the 
letter,  he  pressed  this  key,  and  released  the  other  pendulum. 
In  these,  as  in  the  earlier  experiments,  the  observer  was  given 
the  letters,  in  alphabetical  order,  to  feel  at  the  beginning  of 
every  hour,  unless  he  declared,  of  his  own  accord,  that  the 
letters  were  clear  in  memory.  There  was  constant  instruc- 
tion to  reduce  all  experience  to  its  lowest  terms. 

The  observers  were  Dr.  Pyle  (P),  Dr.  Okabe  (O),  Mr.  Foster 
(F),  and  Miss  de  Vries  (V).  The  first  was  at  the  time  assist- 
ant in  psychology,  and  the  other  three  were  graduate  students 
of  considerable  experience  in  introspection.  When  the  ex- 
periments were  given  in  their  changed  form.  Dr.  Geissler  (G), 
instructor  in  psychology,  took  the  place  of  Dr.  Pyle.  Miss 
Mary  Clarke  (MC)  and  the  writer  (HC)  were  observers  in 
some  later  experiments.  MC  was  untrained  in  psychology, 
though  advanced  in  other  lines. 

I.  Types  of  Observers 

P  is  predominantly  verbal  in  type.  He  reports  verbal  ideas 
in  sentence  form,  with  a  few  visual  images,  sensations  of  strain, 
organic  sensations  and  feeHngs.  Thus,  CAB.  cab.  "I  per- 
ceived the  first  letter  and  said  C,  but  had  verbal  ideas  like  *I 
am  not  sure  whether  it  is  or  not.'  " 

V  represents  a  mixed  type.  Visual  images  play  a  large  part 
in  her  consciousness,  and  many  of  these  are  colored.  Rec- 
ognition is  often  mediated  by  a  tactual  image  on  the  finger. 
Verbal  ideas,  affective  processes,  kinaesthetic  and  organic  sen- 
sations are  also  numerous.  Thus,  DC.  dc.  "Felt  the  dots  and 
said  d,  c.  Unpleasant.  Got  visual  image  at  once  from  the 
feel,  and  then  said  the  letter."  B.  e,  i.  20.  "  Very  pleasant. 
Sensations  from  mouth  in  smiHng.  The  dot  fitted  into  a  hole 
in  my  finger  which  corresponded  to  E.  Reaction  automatic 
and  hardly  conscious.  I  visualised  the  round  dot  and  a  printed 
E.     Smiled  at  the  similarity  of  these." 

O  is  also  of  a  mixed  type,  reporting  visual,  verbal  and  audi- 
tory images  in  great  numbers.  Organic  sensations  and  strain 
play  a  great  part  in  his  consciousness,  as  do  also  affective 
processes,  kinaesthetic  and  tactual  images,  pain  and  tempera- 
ture sensations.    Thus,  I.  i,  5.12.    "Attention  well  concentra- 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  217 

ted  and  body  well  adjusted.  When  I  touched  the  lever,  shock 
from  muscular  contraction.  Vacant  consciousness,  state  of 
waiting.  Organic  sensation  like  irritation  in  back.  Stamp- 
ing of  foot,  frowning,  extreme  unpleasantness.  Feeling  of 
motion  on  left  finger;  probably  a  real  motion,  not  an  image. 
Suddenly  a  visual- verbal  image  I." 

F  reports  verbal,  visual  and  auditory  images ;  more  auditory 
than  any  other  observer  except  O.  Kinaesthetic  images  and 
organic  and  strain  sensations  are  also  reported,  as  well  as  a 
few  affective  processes.  Thus,  IF.  if.  "The  two  letters 
have  different  organic  sensations.  I  cannot  describe  them 
except  by  saying  that  that  which  is  with  I  is  long,  and  that 
which  is  with  F  is  broad;  both  are  narrow,  like  the  letters 
themselves." 

In  the  introspections  of  G,  all  imagery  except  verbal  is  al- 
most entirely  lacking.  Sensations,  both  kinaesthetic  and  or- 
ganic, and  affective  processes  are  prominent  in  conscious- 
ness. When  G  felt  the  alphabet  in  order  to  learn  the  letters, 
he  described  every  letter  aloud,  and  associated  the  verbal 
description  with  the  tactual  perception.  G  reports  that  his 
consciousness  in  general  is  almost  without  images,  and  his 
memory  of  scenes  and  events  is  in  verbal  form.  He  places 
things  spatially  by  means  of  eye-movements,  which  are  un- 
accompanied by  images.  Thus,  B.  b,  4.42.  "At  the  first 
touch  perception  of  a  long  row  of  dots  with  absolute  clear- 
ness. It  confused  me,  that  is,  it  excited  a  complex  of  organic 
sensations,  and  the  verbal  idea.  Why  can't  I  tell  what  it  is? 
Organic  sensations  especially  from  diaphragm.  I  said,  I  have 
to  see  whether  there  is  a  dot  below  or  a  changed  dot  at  the 
end.  Then  another  careful  touch  of  the  letter,  with  the  little 
dot  below  most  prominent.  Verbal  ideas:  ph,  yes,  that  is 
B.     The  whole  strongly  pleasant." 

MC  is  of  a  pronounced  visual  type,  but  reports  some  imagery 
from  other  senses.^  Thus,  Symposium.  "Verbal  image  of 
the  word  with  sensations  in  throat.  Visual  image  of  a  pic- 
ture of  a  Greek  symposium  from  a  Greek  history,  followed 
by  image  of  a  table  with  people  seated  around  it.  Image  of 
a  convention  and  auditory  image.  Round  table." 

HC  is  of  the  same  type  of  imagery  as  MC.  Thus,  Re- 
liability. "Visual  and  verbal  images  of  the  word.  Very  vague 
visual  image  of  some  kind  of  support  bearing  a  heavy  weight." 

2.  Attitudes  Analysed 

In  going  over  the  introspections,  to  discover  what  attitudes 
have  been  analysed  by  the  observers,  we  meet  with  some  am- 

^For  the  method  employed  with  MC  and  HC,  see  p.  236  below. 
Journal — 6 


2l8  CLARKE 

biguity  and  confusion  of  terms.  So  far  as  attitudes  have  been 
named,  they  have  been  listed  under  the  name  appHed  by  the 
observer.  With  this  word  of  caution  we  proceed  to  consider 
the  analyses  of  various  attitudes  to  be  found  in  the  reports. 

Approval.  V.     Pleasantness,  with  some  general  kinaesthesis. 

AwFULNSSS.  G.  Once  analysed  as  a  strong  unpleasantness  and  frown- 
ing, and  again  as  the  same  with  the  addition  of  inhibition  of  breathing. 

Baffled  Expectation.  O.  Visual  image  of  face  and  frowning  fore- 
head. Left  foot  stamped.  Slight  burning  sensation  in  back.  Bodily 
and  mental  attitude  was  adjusted  to  a  more  difficult  letter.  Partial  re- 
laxation and  muscular  strain  in  upper  part  of  body.  Organic  sensation 
and  muscular  strain  which  I  could  not  localise. 

Caution.  V.  Verbal  idea.  Be  careful. 

Comfort.  V.  Organic  sensation  and  smiling. 

Comparison.     HC,     The  two  things  were  side  by  side,  visually. 

Confidence.  O.  A  good  adjustment  of  muscles,  and  sensations  from 
them.  Agreeable  organic  sensations.  V.  "I  sat  up  straight  and  took 
deep  breaths,  and  had  a  sense  of  stiffness  in  the  spine,  and  pleasantness." 

Confusion  is  analysed  by  G  as  '  'a  complex  of  organic  sensations,  and 
verbal  idea,  Why  can't  I  tell  what  it  is?"  "Unpleasantness,  organic 
attitude  of  inhibited  movement  of  diaphragm  and  of  breathing."  F 
analyses  it  once  as  a  munber  of  conflicting  strains. 

O  reports  the  repeated  appearance  of  conflicting  verbal  ideas:  "It  may 
mean  B  and  it  may  mean  C,"  unpleasantness,  and  organic  sensations  in 
abdomen  which  seemed  to  travel  upward  and  to  be  checked  by  some  ob- 
stacle. "Several  initial  associations  of  auditory-kinaesthetic  images. 
Muscular  strain  in  head,  organic  sensation  in  trunk."  V  reports  holding 
of  breath  and  blank  consciousness. 

Consciousness  of  Fitness.  O.  Relaxation  of  organic  and  muscular 
strain,  stretching  of  back,  long  breathing. 

Consciousness  that  the  Letter  was  too  Small.  O.  Muscular  strain 
and  organic  sensations. 

Decision.  O.  Slightly  agreeable  feeling  and  successive  auditory  images, 
It  must  be  so. — Auditory  image.  Kinaesthetic  bodily  attitude.  Oganic 
sensations. — Bodily  attitude  and  relaxation  of  muscular  strain. — Memory 
image,  visual  or  tactual  or  both,  of  E.  Change  of  organic  and  muscular 
sensations.  (This  attitude  is  analysed  several  times  by  the  same  observer 
in  the  same  way.) 

Decision  to  Disregard  the  Lever.  F.  Visual  and  kinaesthetic 
images  of  this  action.     I  saw  myself  doing  it. 

Determination.  G.  Pleasant  mood.  Verbal  idea,  I  am  going  to  do 
that  well.  F.  Nodding  of  head  toward  finger,  and  attending  to  tactual 
image  of  coming  sensation.  V.  Verbal  ideas,  biting  the  teeth  and  jerking 
the  head. 

Difficulty.  G.  Trouble  to  get  a  verbal  idea.  Three  ideas  a,  e,  and 
i  were  ready,  but  I  do  not  know  how. 

Disappointment.  V.  Organic  and  verbal.  I  said  Oh.  My  muscles  had 
been  strained,  but  were  now  relaxed  all  over.  Sensation  from  frowning. 
Very  unpleasant. 

Disgust.    O.    Organic  sensations  throughout  the  body.    Unpleasantness. 

Dissatisfaction.  O.  Reported  twice.  Once  not  analysed.  Once  re- 
ported as  consisting  of  muscular  strain,  organic  sensations,  and  impleasant- 
ness. 

Distance  and  Direction.  MC.  In  almost  every  experiment  this  ob- 
server reports  a  sense  of  distance  and  direction  towards  a  place  that  is 
thought  of.  The  two  usually  occur  together,  though  sometimes  the  one 
is  reported  alone.     "Direction  goes  on  in  front  of  my  head,  and  it  feels  as 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  219 

if  something  inside  of  my  head  were  moving  in  the  given  direction.  I  think 
this  is  an  image,  not  a  real  movement."  "Distance  is  a  visual  image  of 
the  space,  boiled  down,  which  lies  between  the  two  places.  It  is  a  schematic 
visual  image."  In  one  case,  in  which  the  observer  had  been  thinking  of, 
picturing,  scenes  in  the  east,  these  were  replaced  by  images  of  places  in 
her  home  town,  and  she  says:  "In  going  from  one  to  the  other  my  mind 
distinctly  moved  west.  This  movement  is  located  in  the  top  of  the  head, 
and  seems  like  a  movement  of  something  inside  of  the  head."  In  some 
cases  MC  says  her  mind  'flew'  to  a  certain  place,  and  this  experience  seems 
to  have  been  a  seen  motion  across  a  visual  area  with  some  kinaesthesis. 

Ease  op  Recognition.  G,  LocaUsed  once  in  the  trunk,  and  again  as 
vaguely  organic. 

Easiness.  (This  is  partially  analysed  by  O  fifteen  times,  and  is  men- 
tioned without  analysis  four  times.)  Agreeableness,  and  motor  tendency  to 
say  Easy. — Motor  tendency  to  say  Quite  easy.  Faint  but  massive  organic 
sensation  in  background. — Verbal  idea,  This  is  easy,  and  visual  image  of 
my  smiling  face.  —  Bodily  attitude  and  relaxed  muscular  sensation.  (In 
the  remaining  analyses  the  same  factors  are  repeated.) 

Expectation.  Analysis  agrees  with  those  of  Pyle's  observers  (this 
Journal,  XX,  1909,  530  ff.). 

Fear  That  I  had  Reacted  too  Quickly.  F.  Slight  sinking  in  the 
stomach  or  diaphragm.  Lack  of  clearness  of  perception,  and  sensations 
from  breathing. 

V  reports  a  state  which  she  calls  Fright,  and  which  usually  occurs  at 
the  beginning  of  an  experiment.  This  is  analysed  three  times  as  consisting 
of  a  shiver  down  the  back,  and  a  shrinking  backward.  Once  it  consisted, 
in  addition,  of  holding  the  breath  and  gasping;  and  once  it  is  described  as 
a  feeling  of  nervousness  and  a  shiver.  The  state  of  Scare,  which  might 
be  supposed  to  resemble  fright,  is  reported  only  once,  and  is  described  as  a 
sudden  muscular  contraction.  C  twice  reports  fear  as  an  unsteady  or- 
ganic sensation. 

G-CoNSCiousNESS  is  reported  by  G  three  times.  Once  it  is  not  analysed; 
once,  said  to  be  motor;  and  once,  to  consist  of  the  muscular  setting  of  the 
tongue. 

Have  Finished  my  Work.  O.  Bodily  attitude  which  cannot  be  local- 
ised.    Tendency  to  straighten  up  the  body. 

The  I-CoNSCiousNESS.  C.  Was  a  kinaesthetic  sensation  in  the  back 
of  the  mouth. 

I  Ought  to  Know  That.  O.  Organic  sensation  and  disagreeable 
feeling. 

Impatience.     O.  Frowning,  and  the  verbal  idea  Let 's  go. 

Injustice.  V.  Gasping  for  breath.  I  started  back  and  threw  my  head 
back. 

Irritation.  O.  Sensation  from  frowning.  Visual  image  of  frowning 
face.  Tendency  to  lower  and  shake  the  head.  Hot  sensation  in  head  and 
back.  [In  the  fotu*  rather  full  analyses  that  follow,  the  above  facts  are 
repeated,  and  in  addition  strain  in  back  and  neck  (three  times),  disagreea- 
ble feeling  (three  times),  organic  sensation  throughout  the  body  (three 
times),  verbal  ideas  This  is  hard  (once)  are  reported.] 

It  Must  be  C.  G.  A  pleasant  touch-motor  complex,  with  a  horizontal 
movement,  and  a  downward  movement  at  the  end.  In  the  same  report, 
this  statement  was  followed  by  the  attitude  /  had  C  before,  which  was 
verbal-kinaesthetic.  The  articulation  was  inhibited.  This  again  gave  place 
to  the  attitude  That  is  C  ail  right,  which  was  a  touch-motor  complex  with 
clear  articulation. 

Meaning.  G.  A  single  dot  below  the  line  means  a  broken  T.  This 
is  a  motor  complex.  O.  Elinaesthetic  and  auditory  image  of  the  letters. 
Meaning  carried  by  the  shape  of  the  figure  itself. 


220  CLARKE 

The  MEANING  OF  C  is  reported  by  G  as  an  attitude,  and  is  analysed  as 
a  complex  of  tongue-sensations  and  temperature  in  the  mouth.  Tendency 
to  say  the  letter;  pleasantness. 

Newness.  F.  "It  impresses  me  as  a  cutting  edge,  as  a  bit  of  a  knife 
blade  turned  up.  Definite  organic  sensations.  The  whole  complex  I 
should   call   newness." 

Non-Recognition.     F.     Includes  vague  visual  image. 

The  Passage  of  Time.  V  describes  this  three  times  as  a  perception 
resembling  that  of  air  currents,  passing  around  and  over  the  observer  from 
back  to  front;  in  one  case  there  was  the  verbal  idea  That  was  slow. 
O  says  that  a  feeling  of  length  of  time  came  in  kinaesthetic  terms,  and  re- 
sembled   fatigue. 

Fastness.  HC.  The  image  was  projected  back  into  the  past.  Fast- 
ness is  more  visual  than  anything  else.  It  seems  far  away,  and  foreshort- 
ened. 

FowERLESSNESS.  HC.  This  was  a  peculiar  tingling  sensation  all  over 
the  body,  with  sensations  similar  to  fatigue,  and  warmth. 

Pride.  O.  Slight  tendency  to  straighten  up  my  neck  and  smile.  Fleas- 
ant  feeling. 

The  Readiness  to  say  a  Certain  Word  is  in  one  case  localised  by  G 
in  the  lower  part  of  the  head,  and  again  analysed  as  a  disposition  or  set 
of  the  muscles  of  the  mouth. 

HC.  Reasoning  that,  if  Canute  was  connected  with  1026,  Alfred  was 
in  the  loth  centtiry.  This  was  partly  represented  by  a  visual  schema  of 
the  centuries.  Canute  was  in  white  at  1026,  Alfred  in  dark,  therefore 
in  the  loth  century. 

Reflection.  O.  Thought  turned  alternately  from  A  to  B.  (No 
further  analysis.) 

Relief.  G.  Pleasiu-e,  and  disappearance  of  organic  complex.  Pro- 
nounced exhaling.     O.  Consists  of  organic  sensation. 

Satisfaction.  C  connects  this  with  pleasantness.  O.  Instantaneous 
pleasant  feeling;  faint  visual  image  of  my  smiling  face.  Organic  sensations. 
— Pleasant  feeling,  tendency  to  smile,  organic  sensations. — Tendency 
to  smile.  Verbal  ideas:  Yes,  it  is  quite  sure.  (These  analyses  are  re- 
peated a  number  of  times,  while  there  are  also  cases  in  which  satisfaction 
is  named  but  not  analysed.) 

Security.  V.  Long,  easy  breathing  and  straight  position  of  body;  re- 
laxation. 

Strangeness.  F.  Weak  organic  feeUng  all  over  the  body.  Strain, 
and  sensations  from  breathing,  and  special  sensation  from  diaphragm. 
This  last  is  not  a  strain.  It  must  be  one  of  the  sensations  that  we  get  when 
we  fall  in  dreams.  O.  Insufficient  adaptation  of  body,  fingers,  and  hand. 
General  inhibition,  which  was  a  kind  of  organic  sensation;  inhibition  of 
arm-movement. 

Tendency  to  Stay  and  Find  Something  Else.  O.  Consisted  of 
bodily  attitude. 

Conviction  That  I  was  Right.  V.  Reappearance  of  the  verbal  im- 
age of  the  letter  to  which  I  had  reacted. 

The  attitude  That  I  Should  Have  Pressed  Sooner,  V  describes  as 
a  twitch  in  the  finger,  organic  sensation,  and  catching  of  breath. 

The  conviction  That  it  Was  Not  any  of  the  Others.  G.  An  in- 
hibited motion  of  the  lips  to  say  B,  and  the  fact  that  I  did  not  move  hori- 
zontally and  therefore  it  could  not  be  H.  This  was  partly  kinaesthetic,  in 
the  fingers  and  mouth. 

That  it  was  Probably  Not  G.  V.  Verbal  ideas,  and  visual  and  kinaes- 
thetic images,  of  the  other  letters. 

Thinking  over.  O.  Consisted  of  bodily  set,  and  of  associations  which 
were  not  perfected.     D  and  J  were  repeated  several  times  in  auditory  terms. 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  221 

Uneasiness.  O.  Reported  four  times.  Once  identified  with  uncer- 
tainty. Once  includes  image  of  frowning  face,  and  sensations  in  back  of 
head  and  neck.  Once  is  a  verbal  idea,  That  has  no  meaning.  Once  is 
not  analysed. 

UnfamiIvIArity,  G.  The  touch-motor  complex  was  unfamiliar  and  un- 
pleasant. It  led  to  movements  of  tongue  and  lips  in  whispering:  Oh  me, 
that  must  be  H.  Organic  attitude  in  trunk;  unsteady  shutting  of  eyes 
and  horizontal  movement  of  eye-balls.  V.  Rapid  mental  comparison  of 
feeling  of  C  now  with  feeling  of  C  last  year,  though  I  do  not  remember 
how  C  felt  then. 

The  Upper  Row  was  Too  Short  for  J.  O.  Tactual  memory  of  J. 
Bodily  attitude. 

Waiting.  O.  This  is  described  twice,  in  almost  exactly  the  same  words. 
Sensation  of  heat  in  back,  stamping  of  feet,  and  extreme  unpleasantness. 

Wondering.  V.  Once  not  analysed;  once  organic  attitude,  holding  the 
breath  and  strain.  HC.  Once  merely  reported ;  once  described  as  a  com- 
plex of  sensations  in  the  top  of  the  head. 

Attitudes  Named  but  not  Analysed.  Besides  the  attitudes  named, 
there  are  others  which  are  merely  reported  and  not  analysed.  They  include 
one  case  each  of  identity  of  self  with  the  lever  (G),  the  motive  to  distinguish 
the  dots  (G),  the  consciousness  that  I  had  reacted  (G),  the  C-consciousness 
(G),  not  being  right  (F),  curiosity  (O),  relation  (O),  that  has  no  meaning 
(O),  indecision  (O),  consciousness  of  an  obstacle  (O),  unknownness  (V), 
fast  reaction  (V),  contrast  (MC),  sense  of  past  time  (HC) ;  and  two  cases 
each  of  certainty  (V),  wondering  (MC),  and  ownership  (MC;  this  was  at 
least  partly  visual). 

Many  of  these  incidental  analyses  are,  evidently,  imper- 
fect. Even  at  the  best,  the  observers  might  report  in  large 
and  sweeping  phrases,  such  as  'bodily  attitude*  or  'organic 
sensation.'  There  is,  however,  no  doubt  that  the  reports 
were  intended  at  the  time  to  represent  the  attitudes  them- 
selves, and  not  merely  incidental  or  concomitant  occurrences. 
After  the  second  set  of  experiments,  the  observers  were  con- 
fronted with  an  outline  of  their  reports  upon  various  atti- 
tudes, and  were  asked  to  say  whether,  so  far  as  they  could 
remember,  the  analyses  read  were,  as  analyses,  correct.  The 
regular  answer  was  that  they  were  correct,  and  in  several 
cases  the  observer  added,  of  his  own  accord,  that  he  could 
reproduce  the  attitude,  at  the  moment,  and  that  it  corres- 
ponded with  the  analysis  given. 

While,  therefore,  we  readily  admit  that  introspective 
analysis  might,  under  more  favorable  conditions,  have  been 
pushed  further,  we  believe  that  the  descriptions  given  are 
reliable,  and  that  more  detailed  work  would  simply  resolve 
the  complexes  mentioned  into  their  elements. 

3.  Gradation  of  Imagery 

Messer  finds  five  stages  in  the  Entfaltung  of  visual  images: 
(i)  mere  spatial  direction  or  externality;  (2)  a  trace  of  visual 
localisation;  (3)  vague  and  schematic  images;  (4)  images 
just  named,  and  not  characterised  as    to  degree;    (5)  very 


222  CI.ARKE 

clear  and  strong  images.  In  addition,  he  distinguishes  general 
and  particular,  partial,  changing  and  moving,  and  symbolic 
images.  The  stages  found  in  the  observers  in  our  own  ex- 
periments are  as  follows: 

P  mentions  only  two  stages,  and  these  were  only  in  visual 
and  verbal  imagery.  The  two  stages  were  the  vague,  and 
those  merely  named. 

F  distinguishes  the  following  stages .  For  visual  images,  mere 
localisation,  vague,  and  just  named.  For  verbal  images,  which 
do  not  lend  themselves  to  exactly  the  same  classification, 
very  vague,  just  named.  Auditory  images  fall  into  the 
same  two  classes.  The  idea  of  movement,  which  is  both  vis- 
ual and  kinaesthetic,  is  very  often  merely  named.  Organic 
sensations  were  faint,  and  just  named. 

V.  For  visual  images:  faint,  just  named,  very  clear,  partial 
image,  change,  and  movement.  For  verbal:  faint,  just 
named,  and  very  clear. 

MC.  For  visual  images :  vague,  schematic,  very  clear,  par- 
tial, change,  generic.  For  verbal:  vague,  just  named,  very 
clear,  aloud,  partial.     For  auditory:  very  vague,  just  named. 

HC's  images  are  in  general  much  like  MC's.  Visual:  lo- 
calisation vague,  just  named,  very  clear,  partial,  change. 
Verbal:  very  clear.  Kinaesthetic:  vague,  just  named.  Motor: 
very  clear.     Auditory :  vague,  just  named. 

O  has  for  visual  images:  localisation,  vague,  just  named, 
clear,  incomplete,  movement.  He  also  speaks  on  several 
occasions  of  'initial  associations,'  which  seem  to  have  been 
inhibited  tendencies  toward  the  articulation  of  words.  For 
verbal:  faint,  just  named,  very  clear,  aloud,  partial.  Audi- 
tory :  same  as  the  verbal,  and  usually  connected  with  them. 
Organic:  faint,  just  named,  very  clear,  changing,  movement. 

G  reports  for  visual  imagery  only  three  cases ;  for  kinaesthetic 
other  than  verbal,  five;  and  these  are  all  described  as  vague. 
His  organic  sensations  are  mostly  merely  named,  but  a  few  are 
faint.  On  any  page  of  G's  reports  the  verbal  stages  just 
named,  whispered,  and  aloud,  may  be  found;  yet  there  is  an 
unmistakable  general  tendency  which,  as  in  the  case  of  V,  is  in 
the  opposite  direction  to  the  order  here  given.  G  invariably 
read  the  letters  aloud  when  they  were  being  felt  for  the  first 
time.  As  they  recur  again  and  again,  the  verbal  ideas  involved 
in  recognition  fade  out,  from  whispered  to  vaguely  verbal, 
and  finally  to  a  mere  setting  of  the  mouth  or  right  breathing 
for  the  utterance  or  a  certain  letter. 

Illustrations  of  the  Stages  of  Imagery. 

These  typical  illustrations  of  visual  imagery  represent  a  large  body  of 
similar  cases,  which  cannot  be  quoted  for  lack  of  space.     No  one  of  the 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  223 

observers  was  instructed  to  report  on  the  intensity  of  his  images;  the  ex- 
perimenter had  not  this  specific  problem  in  mind  at  the  time  when  the  in- 
trospections were  taken.  As  the  illustrations  show,  it  is  extremely  difficult 
to  draw  a  sharp  line  between  the  consciousness  which  is  rich  in  images  and 
that  which  is  'imageless.'  Images  may  be  so  vague  as  to  be  noticed  only 
by  the  most  careful  introspection;  and  there  is  every  reason  to  believe 
that  some  may  escape  notice  entirely;  that,  in  certain  cases,  the  intro- 
pections  even  of  trained  observers  may  not  be  complete. 

MC. 

Vague.  Vague  image  of  a  Massachusetts  street.  Vague  image  of  a  drug 
store.  Schematic.  Visual  schematic  image  of  June  in  my  representation 
of  the  months.  An  image  of  an  environment,  a  sort  of  mist,  but  very 
vague.  Very  Clear.  An  image  of  the  girl,  including  details  with  much 
distinctness,  such  as  her  fight,  fluffy  hair,  bright  pleasant  eyes,  and  short 
dresses. 

Partial.  Detached  image  of  a  face  with  no  setting.  Image  of  a  man  in 
the  rigging  of  a  ship,  but  no  setting,  even  of  a  whole  ship.  Change.  Image 
of  the  man  stepping  into  the  room  from  the  street  and  looking  at  himself 
in  the  glass.  This  picture  was  painted  before  me.  It  was  not  distinct  at 
first,  but  one  part  became  clear  and  then  another,  till  the  whole  was  clear. 

O. 

Localisation.  Localisation  of  the  letter  in  the  alphabet  sfip.  (This 
is  repeated  many  times.)  Vague.  Vague  pyramidal  image  of  something. 
Just  named.     Image  of  H  in  point.     Clear.     Clear  image  of  the  letters. 

Incomplete.  Incomplete  image  of  a  Japanese  key.  Movement.  Image 
of  a  worm  moving. 

V  on  the  recognition  of  A 

The  illustrations  begin  at  the  point  where  color  is  first  associated  with  A. 
Oct.  22:  Visual  image  of  A  written  in  red;  Oct.  26:  Very  briUiant  red;  Oct. 
28:  Vivid  flash  of  red;  Oct.  30:  Visual  image  of  red  A  in  front  of  me;  Nov. 
2:  A  red  flash  and  a  little  visual  written  A;  Nov.  4:  Visual  image  of  A  in 
front  of  my  eyes,  and  a  flash  of  red ;  Nov.  6:  Faint  flash  of  red;  Nov.  6, 
later:  I  visualised  the  two  dots;  Nov.  9:  Slight  red  blot.  After  the  re- 
action, a  faint  visual  A.     (See  p.  234.) 

To  demonstrate  a  series  of  gradual  steps  from  clear  images  to 
'imageless'  thought  may  not  prove  conclusively  that  the  latter 
is  a  fiction;  but,  at  any  rate,  it  suggests  an  origin  and  deri- 
vation. Imageless  thought,  as  its  name  implies,  is,  so  far 
at  least,  an  entirely  negative  concept.  We  perform  acts  of 
thought  in  which  we  can  discover  no  imagery  in  conscious- 
ness, and  hence  we  infer  that  thought  may  be  'imageless.' 
Just  what  an  imageless  thought  is  like,  or  how  it  differs  from 
that  in  which  images  are  present,  has  never  been  shown,  or 
even  attempted  to  be  shown,  except  by  way  of  classifications 
fsuch  as  that  of  Buhler.  In  fact  the  term  'imageless'  is  unfor- 
[tunate;  it  lends  itself  easily  to  misunderstanding.  'Image,' 
iin  popular  parlance  and  often  in  psychology,  means  a  cen- 
[trally  aroused  representation  of  a  visual  impression.  We 
[must,  of  course,  recognise  also  the  place  of  auditory,  tactual, 

ind  kinaesthetic  imagery,  and  theoretically  of  images  of  taste 
[and  smell,  though  these  appear  to  play  but  a  small  part  in  con- 

riousness.     The  verbal  image,  which  is  especially  important 


224  CLARKE 

in  the  thought-process,  may  itself  be  visual,  auditory,  kinaes- 
thetic,  or  mixed.  Even  this  list,  however,  does  not  exhaust 
the  contents  of  thought.  It  is  becoming  increasingly  apparent 
that  our  conscious  states  take  much  of  their  peculiar  quality 
from  the  organic  sensations,  the  felt  bodily  adjustments, 
which  enter  into  certain  situations.  The  affective  pro- 
cesses are  also  often  present,  even  in  thought.  It  is  obvious, 
therefore,  that  the  term  'imageless'  is  inadequate  to  designate 
a  thought  from  which  all  these  elements  are  absent.  Even 
the  term  *non-sensory, '  which  is  better,  disregards  the  part 
played  by  feeling.  We  all  know  in  a  general  way,  however, 
what  sort  of  state  is  meant  by  'imageless  thought,'  and  it  is 
just  this  state  which  the  above  introspections  tend  to  discredit. 
For  they  show  that  imagery  does  not  need  to  be  specific 
and  elaborate  in  order  to  carry  thought.  We  may  repeat  an 
argument,  or  review  an  article,  in  a  very  small  part  of  the  words 
used  in  the  original,  without  sacrificing  the  essentials  of  the 
content.  When  we  are  thinking  in  verbal  images,  it  is  by  no 
means  necessary  to  say  every  word  which  we  should  use  if  we 
were  talking  aloud.  Again,  just  because  we  are  not  speak- 
ing aloud,  it  is  not  necessary  that  every  word  should  be  clear- 
ly articulated  or  completed,  either  in  actual  throat  movements 
or  in  images  of  such  movements.  The  reports  of  G,  especially, 
show  that  the  mere  setting  of  the  mouth,  or  the  right  mode  of 
exhalation,  serves  as  well  as  the  complete  word.  A  young 
child  just  beginning  to  read  gets  no  meaning  from  his  words 
unless  he  reads  them  aloud.  Thought  consists  for  him  in  the 
sound  of  his  own  voice  or  that  of  another,  or  in  the  feeling 
of  the  throat  movements  involved  in  speaking.  When  he 
first  learns  to  read  quietly,  he  whispers;  then  he  confines 
himself  to  a  mere  lip  motion;  and  later,  he  can  dispense  with 
this  expression.  The  reports  of  our  observers  take  up  this 
progress  where  the  child  leaves  off,  or  from  an  even  earlier 
point,  when  the. words  are  still  spoken  aloud,  and  show  that 
and  how  the  suppression  of  sound  and  the  shortening  of  the 
total  process  may  be  carried  in  the  adult  to  a  stage  yet  more 
remote  from  the  starting  point.  ^ 

Detailed  Analyses 
I.  Explicit 
The  attitudes  so  far  analysed  have  been  those  which  oc- 
curred only  a  few  times.     It  shall  be  our  task  now  to  consider 

^We  are  able,  owing  to  limitations  of  space,  to  print  only  the  few  samples 
of  visual  Entfaltung  given  in  this  section.  We  have  a  very  considerable 
amount  of  introspective  material  bearing  upon  the  gradations,  not  only 
of  visual,  but  also  of  auditory,  kinaesthetic  and  verbal  imagery,  and  of  or- 
ganic set  or  adjustment.     We  hope  to  present  this  material  in  a  later  article. 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  225 

some  of  the  more  common  attitudes  in  greater  detail.  One 
of  those  which  is  most  often  reported  is  surprise.  Surprise, 
of  course,  may  have  various  occasions,  and  whenever  these  are 
stated  by  the  observer,  they  are  given  in  the  following  quo- 
tations. 

G.  Surprise  at  the  smallness  of  the  letter.  Kinaesthetic  adjustment,  or 
inhibition  of  movement,  in  finger  and  back. 

That  I  did  not  feel  the  letter.  Organic  sensation,  involving  inhibited 
breathing  and  fixity  of  the  diaphragm. 

At  not  feeling  the  letter.  Something  moving  along  inside  the  body,  a  dull 
pressure  goiug  upward  from  the  stomach  to  the  back  of  the  mouth. 

Check  of  horizontal  movement  and  change  to  vertical. 

Peculiar  movement  of  mouth,  dropping  of  jaw,  and  slight  sensation  in 
chest. 

'inhibition  in  diaphragm  and  setting  of  the  mouth  to  say  Oh.  [This  last 
is  repeated  several  times  in  almost  exactly  the  same  words.  In  two  cases 
the  attitude  is  not  analysed  at  all,  and  in  others  it  is  merely  localised.] 

O.  Muscular  strain  and  visual  image  of  a  working  nerve.  Unpleasant 
feeling. 

Change  of  position.  Organic  and  muscular  sensations  somewhere,  and 
blank  consciousness. 

Relaxation  of  muscular  strain,  and  a  tendency  to  change  the  bodily 
attitude, 

V.  Holding  of  breath  and  kinaesthetic  sensation  at  finger  tips. 

Rimning  of  warm  currents  all  over  the  body,  and  tingling  sensation. 
Very  pleasant. 

Verbal   exclamation. 

Kinaesthetic  and  verbal.  I  dropped  my  jaw,  and  opened  my  mouth. 
Sudden  muscular  contraction,  a  gasp,  and  turning  the  head. 

Muscular  contraction. 

Held  my  breath  and  gasped  and  contracted  muscles. 

On  comparing  these  reports,  we  find  that  surprise  is,  in 
general,  an  inhibition  of  movement,  or  change  in  its  direction, 
often  accompanied  by  sensations  from  inhibited  breathing, 
organic  sensations,  verbal  exclamations,  and  affective  pro- 
cesses. The  important  thing  seems  to  be  the  change  or  in- 
hibition of  muscular  reaction.  Surprise  may  be  called  the  con- 
scious aspect  of  the  adjustment  to  a  new  and  sudden  event 
in  the  environment. 

The  consciousness  of  seeking  for  something,  of  trying  to  re- 
member, is  called  by  Marbe  a  Bewusstseinslage,  and  is  classed 
by  Messer  as  an  affective  attitude,  in  which  the  relation  of  the 
Aufgabe  to  the  object  recedes,  leaving  a  subjective  state  for 
whose  solution  the  Aufgabe  suffices.  Watt  affirms  that  the 
consciousness  of  seeking  for  the  reaction-word  is  not  present 
in  every  experiment;  when  present,  it  consists  of  a  conscious- 
ness of  direction,  and  an  emptiness  of  consciousness,  with 
a  repetition  of  the  Aufgabe,  and  sometimes  a  visual  image. 
Orth  says  that  the  attitude  of  striving  to  find  is  a  complex 
of  organic  sensations,  bound  up  with  the  representation  or 
immediate  consciousness  of  a  goal.     Messer  assumes  an  at- 


226  CLARKIS 

titude  of  seeking,  which  is  unanalysable,  but  finds  with  this 
in  the  whole  situation  motor  processes,  movements  of  the 
head  and  eyes  or  representations  of  such  movements,  organic 
sensations,  strain  and  obstructed  breathing..  All  these  com- 
ponents may  not  be  present  in  a  given  case.  In  his  "Snap 
Shot  of  a  Hunt  for  a  Lost  Name,"  Bailey  finds  three  stages, 
which  include  visual  images,  kinaesthetic  and  organic  sensa- 
tions, and  pleasure,  beside  several  complexes  such  as  belief.^ 
As  the  experiments  on  point-letters  were  not  suited  to 
bring  out  this  attitude,  special  introspections  were  taken. 
The  observers  were  MC  and  HC.  Some  of  the  analyses 
occur  in  experiments  given  for  another  purpose,  and  in  a  few 
cases  the  occasion  for  trying  to  recall  arose  incidentally,  and 
the  descriptions  were  written  down  immediately.  Since  these 
cases  did  not  promise  to  be  very  numerous,  however,  a  special 
method  was  devised.  The  observer  was  shown  an  old  and 
almost  forgotten  picture  of  her  classmates  in  the  High  School. 
All  of  the  picture  was  covered  except  one  face,  and  the  ob- 
server was  asked  to  recall  who  the  person  was.  Whenever 
the  response  was  immediate  and  no  seeking  was  required,  the 
case  was  thrown  out,  and  another  face  exposed. 

MC.  Visual  image  of  the  face,  and  verbal  idea  of  the  name  X.  In  trying 
to  think  of  the  right  name,  I  experienced  a  kind  of  working  or  agitation 
localised  in  the  top  and  back  of  the  head.  Several  names  came  to  conscious- 
ness, and  visual  images  of  persons  that  I  associate  with  this  girl. 

Visual  image  of  the  picture  and  also  of  the  girl.  The  first  glance  brought 
a  verbal  image  of  a  name  XY,  followed  by  images  of  XY  in  two  situations. 
I  have  also  a  feeling  of  time,  that  is  that  XY  was  much  farther  back  in 
time  than  the  subject  of  the  picture.  I  do  not  know  what  this  is.  It 
seems  to  be  chiefly  a  series  of  instantaneous  pictures. — 

In  other  cases,  events  and  scenes  which  might  suggest  the  name  are  re- 
called visually,  laughter  and  voices  are  heard  in  image,  and  even  the  pe- 
culiar carriage  and  gesture  of  the  person  are  imaged  by  the  observer.  In 
most  of  the  cases  recorded  the  attempt  to  recall  was  unsuccessful.  The 
reports  contain  also  frequent  reference  to  sensations  from  squinting  and 
closing  the  eyes,  sensations  of  'drawing'  in  the  top  of  the  head,  'emptiness 
in  the  head  caused  by  the  inability  to  recall  the  name.'  Again:  "The 
brain  working  seems  in  this  case  to  be  in  the  front  of  the  head  instead  of 
the  back  as  before.  Sensation  in  the  eyes  and  vaguely  in  stomach.  Feel- 
ing of  impleasantness  caused  by  inability  to  remember." 

The  sense  of  seeking  for  something  occurs  about  thirty  times  in  the  same 
observer's  later  introspections  upon  the  meaning  of  words,  and  is  invaria- 
ably  described  as  a  groping  feeling  in  the  top  of  the  head,  with  sometimes 
a  knitting  of  the  brows,  wrinkling  of  the  forehead,  squinting  of  the  eyes, 
and  sometimes  a  visual  experience  which  is  described  as  staring  into  a  blank 
field.  Occasionally  the  object  of  search  finally  appears  as  a  small  object 
in  the  middle  of  this  field.  Consciousness  seems  less  rich  in  content  in 
these  latter  reports  than  in  the  earlier. 

The  introspections  of  HC  were  obtained  under  exactly  the  same  con- 
ditions as  those  already  discussed.  The  common  element  in  them  all 
is  sensation  from  the  diaphragm,  though  that  from  head  and  eyes  is  often 

^Journal  of  Philosophy,  etc.,  iv.,  1907,  337. 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  227 

present.  In  the  cases  of  seeking  which  occurred  incidentally,  the  strain  is 
very  often  in  the  eyes  and  forehead.  Visual  images  abound,  while  kinaes- 
thetic  and  auditory  imagery  is  sometimes  reported. 

It  is  evident  that  the  consciousness  of  seeking  consists  of 
strain  in  the  head  and  eyes  or  internal  organs,  and  a  feeling 
of  effort  localised  in  the  head,  together  with  images  of  any 
kind  which  have  any  connection  with  the  required  fact  and 
would  be  likely  to  recall  it. 

The  attitude  which  occurs  most  often  incidentally  is  doubt. 
No  sharp  line  can  be  drawn,  it  seems,  between  doubt,  uncertain- 
ty, and  hesitation.  The  term  used  by  the  observer  has,  how- 
ever, been  preserved  in  the  quotations,  so  that,  if  there  is  any 
inaccuracy  in  this  interchangeable  use  of  terms,  it  affects  the 
deductions  alone,  and  not  the  results  from  which  they  are 
drawn.  It  is  certain,  at  all  events,  that  in  many  cases  the 
observers  themselves  did  not  distinguish  the  three  attitudes, 
and  that  the  same  kind  of  analysis  is  given  under  all  three 
names. 

Doubt  is  one  of  the  attitudes  most  often  named  by  Marbe, 
Orth,  and  others;  and  in  Ach's  separation  of  Bewusstseinslage 
from  Bewusstheit,  it  is  included  in  the  former  class.  It  is 
assumed  in  general,  all  through  this  series  of  papers,  that 
doubt  cannot  be  analysed.  Thus,  Orth  finds  doubt  accom- 
panied by  sensations  in  the  head,  organic  and  kinaesthetic 
sensations,  images  and  feelings.  "Doubt  is  not  a  feeling,  but 
a  complex  state,  whose  constitutive  element  is  the  Bewusst- 
seinslage peculiar  to  it."  Here  is  really  an  analysis  of  doubt, 
plus  the  assumption  that  the  analysis  is  incomplete,  and  that 
there  is  a  central  thread  running  through  the  experiences,  which 
is  indescribable  except  by  the  phrase  that  it  always  charac- 
terises doubt.  Whether  or  not  there  is  such  an  element  is 
a  question  for  introspection  to  decide. 

The  following  accounts  are  taken  from  the  introspections  of  G.  Uncer- 
tainty. Slight  organic  excitement  in  the  abdominal  region.  Verbal 
ideas:  Well,  what  is  that?  The  movement  changed  from  the  B  to  the  C 
movement,  which  was  actually  repeated.  Long  dwelling  on  one  impression. 
The  disturbing  other  dot  was  always  there.  There  was  nothing  pleasant 
after  the  reaction,  because  I  was  not  sure. — Suspension  of  verbal  associa- 
tion, or  inhibition  of  movement  in  the  mouth.  The  mouth  did  not  set 
itself  till  the  recognition  was  complete. — Verbal  idea:  What  the  deuce  is 
that?  The  letter  seemed  too  short;  inhibited  breathing,  and  pressure  in 
larynx. — Hesitation.  Hesitation  between  B  and  J.  I  set  my  mouth  for  B, 
then  for  nothing  at  all.  Renewed  touch-motor  complex. — Familiar,  then 
unfamiliar  aspect.     Kept  finger  on  letter  and  pressed  harder  on  last  dot. 

F,  I  was  not  certain.  It  did  not  feel  quite  right.  I  compared  it  with  the 
tactual  images.  The  perception  had  a  blank  place  in  it  which  did  not  be- 
long to  H,  and  the  real  H  was  in  this  space, — It  was  not  a  clear  cut  G  and 
did  not  come  forcibly. — Doubt.  A  came,  but  it  was  not  exactly  as  it  ought 
to  be ;  E  came,  but  I  could  not  decide  which  it  was.  Strain  from  hesitation. 
I  was  not  sure.  Kinaesthetic  sensation  high  up  in  arm.  Not  being  sure 
was  not  anything  in  consciousness;  I  just  did  not  react. — Hesitation.     It 


2  28  CLARKE 

was  not  clear,  and  I  kept  feeling  it.  It  was  not  H  because  not  bulky 
enough;  I  said  J,  but  it  did  not  seem  to  be  J  because  too  big.  I  said  C, 
but  it  was  too  big  for  C.  Visual  image  of  a  triangle.  J  came,  but  it  still 
seemed  too  big. — Kinsesthetic  image  in  forearm  and  finger.  Tactual 
sensation  not  very  clear.     I  did  not  react. 

It  will  be  noticed  that  the  element  common  to  almost  all  of 
these  cases  is  one  which  may  be  called  negative:  the  failure 
to  move  on,  and  to  complete  the  reaction.  When  there  is  no 
doubt,  the  process  proceeds  without  interruption;  but  in 
doubt  there  is  "long  dwelling  on  one  impression,' '  "the  finger 
is  kept  on  the  letter,"  there  is  "renewed  touch-motor  com- 
plex." In  addition  to  this,  there  is,  especially  in  hesitation, 
a  vacillation  between  two  tendencies;  two  aspects  alternate 
in  consciousness,  or  the  mouth  is  set  to  say  now  one  letter  and 
now  another,  without  saying  either.  Verbal  ideas  and  or- 
ganic sensations  may  be  present.  Doubt  is  connected  with  a 
lack  of  clearness  of  the  tactual  perception.  As  the  reaction 
is  delayed,  the  attempt  to  recognise  is  repeated,  and  the  re- 
action is  prepared  for  again  and  again. 

O.  Uncertainty.  Swift  succession  of  auditory-kinaesthetic  verbal  images, 
initial  movements  of  tongue,  and  faint  sounds.  Queer  sensation  from 
bodily  and  facial  attitude.  Visual  image  of  my  face  full  of  confusion  and 
unpleasant  feeling. — Doubt.  Several  initial  associations,  consisting  of  sen- 
sations from  irregularly  contracted  muscles,  and  a  visual  image  of  them; 
unpleasant  feeling,  organic  sensation  above  abdomen,  and  sensation  from 
irregular  breathing.  Interruption  of  breathing,  organic  sensation  in 
chest,  and  pain  in  back  of  neck.  Organic  sensation  in  back  and  spine. — 
The  same,  with  verbal  images.  —  Organic  sensation  in  head,  chest  and 
abdomen,  unpleasant  excitement,  faint  visual  image  of  my  vexed  face,  or- 
ganic sensation  in  both  shoulders,  muscular  strain  in  neck. — Auditory- 
kinaesthetic  images  of  A,  and  something  unclear  tried  to  come  into  con- 
sciousness but  was  inhibited.  Organic  and  muscular  strain  in  head  and 
chest.  (This  is  practically  repeated  several  times.) — Initial  tendency  to 
produce  B,  C,  or  D.  Faint  verbal  and  auditory  image  of  J,  then  "it  can 
not  be,"  with  organic  sensation.  (This  last  is  often  repeated,  sometimes 
with  unpleasant  feeling.) — Unsteady  and  recurring  organic  sensations, 
which  continued  a  long  time. — Organic  sensation  like  heat  in  the  brain, 
holding  of  breath,  muscular  sensation  and  pain.  Absence  of  relief,  the 
muscular  strain  persisted.  Verbal  idea  "I  might  be  mistaken."  (Almost 
every  introspection  given  here  is  reported  a  number  of  times.  There  are 
three  unanalysed  cases  of  doubt.) — Hesitation.  Verbal  image  of  D  and  C 
alternately.  Verbal  idea  that  the  dots  are  very  strange,  disagreeable  feel- 
ing, sensation  in  back.  (This  is  essentially  repeated  several  times.) — 
Tendency  to  stay  and  find  something  else.    (Hesitation  is  once  unanalysed.) 

O's  consciousness  is  made  up  very  largely  of  organic  sen- 
sations and  strains,  and  shows  much  more  affective  coloring 
than  those  of  G  and  F.  Doubt  and  uncertainty  were  unpleas- 
ant and  irritating. 

P  gives  introspective  accounts  of  the  attitudes  of  doubt, 
uncertainty  and  hesitation;  the  analyses  agree  almost  com- 
pletely in  being  verbal.  P's  consciousness  is  so  strongly 
verbal  that  whatever  else  was  present  seems,  in  most  cases, 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  229 

to  have  been  so  far  in  the  background  as  to  be  overlooked. 
There  are  a  few  references  to  organic  and  kinesthetic  sensa- 
tions, unpleasantness,  holding  of  breath,  and  general  strain. 
The  fingers  were  sometimes  moved  over  the  letter  again  and 
again. 

V's  analyses  of  uncertainty  are  meagre. 

I  frowned  and  held  my  breath. — Unpleasant  and  annoying. — I  could 
not  tell  the  number  of  dots.  I  tried  to  count  them  separately,  but  finally 
had  to  rely  on  the  image  I  got  from  the  whole  sensation. — Doubt.  The 
dot  seemed  flat  and  did  not  fit  well  into  the  finger. — The  letter  did  not  fit. 
I  held  my  breath  and  muscles  stiffened.  Muscular  strain  and  verbal 
idea.  Perhaps  it  was  D. — Frowning,  vague  organic  complex,  and  verbal 
idea:  I  am  not  sure.  (These  are  all  repeated  several  times.  For  V  the 
doubt  in  these  recognition  experiments  usually  came  after  the  reaction, 
so  that  it  could  not  consist  in  the  inhibition  of  reaction.  V's  recognition, 
whether  right  or  wrong,  was  usually  immediate,  and  the  reaction  time  was 
very  short.  In  the  few  cases  in  which  doubt  occurred  before  the  reaction, 
the  time  is  increased  above  the  average.  As  the  feeling  of  fitting  on  the 
finger  is  the  most  common  element  in  V's  recognition,  so  the  absence  of 
this  fitting  most  often  marks  doubt,  but  it  is  very  often  accompanied  by 
an  inhibition  of  breathing,  muscular  strains,  and  verbal  ideas  of  doubt.) 

Doubt  does  not  occur  in  MC's  reports,  and  occurs  only  three  times  in 
HC's.  It  is  here  analysed  as  a  feeling  of  displeasure,  organic  sensations 
from  stomach  and  diaphragm,  and  alternation  of  attention  from  one  visual 
image  to  another. 

Although  the  observers  differ  strongly  in  type,  it  is  easy  to 
see  that  there  is  a  general  agreement  in  the  analyses  of  doubt. 
It  involves  an  inhibition  of  the  reaction,  a  checking  of  the 
habitually  smooth-running  process.  So  far,  it  might  seem 
that  doubt  and  surprise  are  alike;  but  there  is  a  difference. 
Surprise  involves  a  sudden  checking  or  changing  of  the  motion 
begun,  whatever  it  is.  Doubt  tends  to  check  the  reaction,  if 
it  has  not  already  taken  place, — to  lengthen  the  reaction  time. 
The  motion  involved  in  feeling  the  letter,  however,  is  not 
checked,  but  is  prolonged  or  repeated.  The  observers  of  verbal 
type  have  verbal  ideas  of  doubt ;  others  have  organic  and  strain 
sensations,  and  often  unpleasantness.  There  is  a  marked 
tendency  to  use  the  term  hesitation  when  there  is  a  vacillation 
from  one  word,  image  or  form  of  reaction  to  another.  The 
organism  meets  a  situation  to  which  it  is  not  prepared  to  react 
promptly.  This  may  be  because  a  particular  reaction  is 
begun,  and  then  inhibited,  or  because  several  are  initiated  in 
swift  succession,  and  inhibit  one  other.  We  may  recall 
Washburn's  derivation  of  the  feeling  of  "but."  The  incipient 
movements  of  developed  consciousness,  in  which  the  mouth 
sets  itself  to  say  now  one  word,  now  another,  or  the  hand  to 
make  this  or  that  reaction,  may  be  vestiges  of  larger  move- 
ments following  one  another  in  swift  succession  and  tending 
to  carry  the  body  in  opposite  directions  or  to  set  it  for  in- 
compatible acts. 


230  CIvARKB 

2.  Genetic 

The  fact  of  development  has  already  been  recognised  by  the 
writers  on  attitudes,  though  its  whole  bearing  upon  the 
question  has  apparently  not  been  seen.  This  statement  holds 
in  particular  of  the  case  of  the  Aufgabe  or  task.  Marbe  re- 
ports a  Bewusstseinslage  which  the  observer  called  'memory 
that  it  must  be  answered  in  a  sentence,'  and  again  one  that  the 
observer  called  'recollection  of  the  problem.'  The  first  of 
these  is  referred  to,  with  approval,  by  Orth,  and  is  placed  by 
him  in  the  second  group  of  his  classification.  If  we  turn  to 
Watt's  work,  in  which  the  course  of  the  experiment  is  divided 
into  four  parts,  we  find  that  the  Aufgabe  is  not  only  clearly 
recognised,  but  is  also  analysed  and  genetically  developed. 
Watt  is  specific  upon  the  point  that  the  task  (or  part  of  it) 
gradually  drops  from  consciousness  as  the  series  proceeds, 
but  that  the  degree  of  consciousness  of  the  preparation  has 
no  relation  to  its  effectiveness.  Messer  is,  in  this  matter,  in 
entire  agreement  with  Watt  and  Ach. 

The  course  of  our  own  experiments  was  at  no  time  divided 
into  parts,  and  in  general  little  attention  was  paid  to  the  con- 
sciousness of  the  task.  Sometimes,  however,  voluntary  re- 
ports were  made,  and  at  other  times  the  observer  was  asked, 
at  the  time  of  introspection,  if  the  task  had  been  present  before 
the  reaction.  The  instructions  were  not  repeated  at  the 
beginning  of  every  hour.  At  the  time,  this  fact  did  not  seem 
worthy  of  notice;  but  we  believe  that  they  were  never  spe- 
cifically repeated,  to  any  observer,  after  the  first  hour  of  work. 
The  instruction  to  recognise  a  letter  is  so  simple  as  not  to  need 
repetition.  The  letters  in  alphabetical  order  were  usually  given 
to  the  observer  at  the  beginning  of  the  hour;  but  sometimes 
he  reported,  as  we  have  remarked,  that  he  did  not  need  them 
again.  This  reminder  may  have  served  as  a  renewal  of  the 
general  consciousness  belonging  to  the  task.  Again,  the 
general  position  of  the  body  must  be  resumed  at  every  sitting ; 
that  is,  one  finger  must  be  on  the  reaction  key,  another  at  the 
edge  of  the  card  holder,  the  eyes  shut.  In  so  far  as  the  Auf- 
gabe is  carried  by  bodily  position,  it  must  always  have  been 
present. 

The  TASK  is  specifically  reported  in  a  few  instances. 

G.  Verbal  ideas :  I  must  make  up  my  mind  to  react,  and  an  uncomfort- 
able bodily  attitude,  very  unpleasant.  (This  was  not  reported  as  a  part  of 
the  fore-period.  The  recognition  and  reaction  seem  to  have  been  delayed, 
and  the  task  is  recalled  in  order  to  hasten  reaction.  This  occurs  in  the  sec- 
ond experiment  of  an  hour,  the  ten  letters  having  been  felt  at  the  beginning.) 
In  a  second  case,  the  task  is  analysed  as  the  organic  setting  in  saying: 
Hurry  up,  don't  be  so  long.  (This  too  is  a  case  of  delayed  reaction,  and 
is  the  seventh  of  a  sitting,  the  letters  having  been  felt  at  first.)  V  reports 
the  task  to  press  the  button  as  being  present  in  kinaesthetic  terms.     This 


f 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  2  3 1 

is  in  the  fourth  experiment  of  the  first  hour  of  the  second  series.  The 
recall  to  consciousness  does  not  seem  to  have  been  occasioned  by  any 
difficulty.  In  the  third  reaction  of  the  next  hour  V  "forgot  the  Aufgabe 
to  react,"  and  therefore  did  not  react  as  soon  as  she  recognised  the  letter. 
The  whole  present  purpose  was  to  recognise  the  letter,  and  this  purpose 
was  a  muscular  adjustment,  and  concentration  of  attention  on  the  finger  tip. 
In  the  second  experiment  of  the  next  hour  the  task  was  present  in  motor 
terms,  and  especially  in  a  strain  sensation  in  the  finger,  which  relaxed 
after  the  reaction.  F  reports  what  he  calls  the  '  'hurry-up' '  consciousness, 
and  again  the  Bewusstseinslage  that  I  must  do  it  quickly.  The  former  is 
analysed  thus:  Strain  became  noticeable  in  the  abdomen,  as  if  two  sen- 
sations came  from  the  sides  and  met.  The  '  'hurry-up  consciousness' '  is 
mostly  strain.  Again :  Organic  sensations  from  diaphragm.  The  muscles 
of  the  diaphragm  seem  to  come  up  and  press  the  lungs,  and  the  muscles  of 
the  ribs  seem  to  tighten.  (This  always  comes  with  the  strain  of  waiting.) 
Again :  Strain  when  I  heard  some  one  walking.  The  strain  meant '  'hurry 
up."  (This  is  often  repeated  in  the  same  terms.  The  "Aufgabe  to  do  it 
quickly"  is  described  twice  as  consisting  of  muscular  strain.) 

Nearly  all  these  cases  occur  early  in  the  second  series,  and  the  Aufgabe 
is  not  later  reported  by  name.  It  does  not  follow,  of  course,  that  it  was 
not  in  consciousness  at  any  other  time,  or  that  it  was  not  reported  in  its 
elements.  The  conscious  contents  occurring  before  the  perception  of  the 
stimtdus  were  often  complex  and  important,  and  in  some  cases  occupied 
much  more  space  than  the  rest  of  the  introspection. 

In  the  early  part  of  the  series  O  reports  sensations  from  the  difi"erent 
parts  of  the  body,  as  the  bending  of  the  neck,  stamping  of  the  feet  on  the 
floor,  pressing  together  of  the  teeth,  and  auditory  images  of  the  sound 
made  by  the  finger  in  moving  over  the  paper.  About  the  middle  of  the 
series  he  several  times  remarks:  "I  did  not  notice  the  bodily  adjustment 
of  attention,"  and  in  the  last  thirty  or  more  experiments  the  introspection 
usually  begins  with  the  perception  of  the  letter.  If  there  is  anything 
before  this,  it  is  usually  the  auditory  sensation  from  the  rubbing  of  the 
fingers  over  the  paper.  The  strained  condition  of  the  body  is  mentioned 
only  once  in  the  last  thirty  cases.  In  the  reports  of  F,  also,  we  notice  a 
marked  f alling-off  in  the  number  of  conscious  contents  occurring  before  the 
appearance  of  the  stimulus.  The  first  introspection  is  almost  entirely  an 
account  of  the  fore-period,  and  includes  strain,  breathing  sensations,  kin- 
aesthetic,  temperature,  verbal  and  visual  images,  some  of  these  occurring 
several  times.  In  the  experiments  immediately  following,  the  contents  of 
this  waiting  period  are  only  slightly  decreased.  Later  the  observer  reports : 
Kinaesthetic  and  visual  images  of  moving  fast  over  the  letter,  later, 
again:  The  'ready'  set  me  off  without  a  conscious  Aufgabe.  The  idea  of 
movement  with  the  tactual  image  is  repeated  a  great  many  times,  but  to- 
ward the  last  is  described  as  vague,  and  does  not  appear  at  all  in  some  of  the 
latest  observations  of  the  series. 

The  conclusions  to  be  gathered  from  these  data  are  in 
entire  agreement  with  the  findings  of  Watt,  Ach,  and  Messer, 
who  offer  us  not  only  avowed  analyses  of  the  Aufgabe-con- 
sciousness  at  the  beginning  of  a  series,  but  also  repeated 
proof  that  it  is  shortened  and  modified  and  tends  entirely  to 
disappear.  If  any  observer  were  stopped  just  before  a  re- 
action, and  asked  to  state  in  words  what  he  was  about  to  do, 
he  would  doubtless  be  able  to  reply.  We  may  reason,  logic- 
ally, that  he  could  not  state  what  he  did  not  know,  and 
that  here  is  therefore  a  case  of  'imageless'  knowledge.     It 


232  CLARKE 

may  be  answered:  (i)  that  such  a  statement  would  be  a  clear 
case  of  Kundgabe,  a  report  of  the  significance  of  a  total  state 
and  not  a  description  of  contents;  (2)  that,  even  if  such  a 
report  be  conceded  to  be  the  verbal  expression  of  an  'im- 
ageless'  state,  it  is  nevertheless  shown  to  have  derived  by 
direct  development  from  a  consciousness  whose  contents 
could  easily  be  isolated;  and  (3)  that,  so  far  from  any  in- 
dication that  the  Aufgabe  was  present  in  other  than  sensory 
terms,  it  is  specifically  said  not  to  have  been  consciously  there 
at  all,  and  yet  to  have  been  active.  The  reports  throw  us  back 
upon  unconscious  tendencies,  but  not  upon  an  unanalysable 
attitude  or  an  imageless  thought. 

The  attitude  which  in  our  experiments  shows  best  from  a 
developmental  point  of  view  is  recognition.  From  the  na- 
ture of  the  point-letter  experiments,  it  follows  that  every 
introspection  is  really  an  analysis  of  the  recognitive  conscious- 
ness. It  may  not  be  complete,  and  it  may  on  the  other  hand 
contain  experiences  that  were  incidental,  but  in  the  main  it 
represents  recognition.  The  letters  were  absolutely  new  to 
the  observers  when  the  experiments  were  begun,  and  when 
they  were  ended  most  of  the  letters  were  recognised  both 
accurately  and  promptly.  Our  conclusions  will,  however, 
be  based  chiefly  upon  the  second  series,  in  which  the  time  was 
measured.  To  part  of  the  observers  the  letters  at  the  begin- 
ning of  this  series  were  not  entirely  unfamiliar. 

It  is  to  be  supposed  a  priori  that,  as  the  experiments  pro- 
ceed and  a  letter  is  given  again  and  again,  it  becomes  more 
and  more  familiar.  This  inference  is  supported  in  a  general 
way  by  the  curves  of  accuracy  and  of  time,  which  show  that 
on  the  whole  all  the  observers  make  fewer  mistakes  toward 
the  end  of  the  series  than  toward  the  beginning,  and  that  the 
time  required  for  reaction  becomes  progressively  shorter. 
Sometimes,  it  is  true,  cases  of  false  recognition  or  of  long 
reaction-time  occur  at  the  end  of  a  series.  These  can  usually 
be  explained,  however,  as  due  to  accidental  causes.  For 
example,  the  raised  letters  tended  to  become  worn  off,  and  to 
grow  less  distinct  with  repeated  rubbing.  Care  was  taken 
that  they  should  be  replaced  before  this  injury  occurred,  but 
sometimes  it  escaped  notice.  The  introspections  enable  us 
to  trace  most  of  the  irregularities  to  these  and  other  causes. 
Even  without  this  allowance,  however,  the  curves  show  a 
striking  similarity  of  form,  and,  with  one  exception,  an  in- 
variable tendency  to  decrease  both  of  mistakes  and  of  re- 
action-time as  the  series  advances.  Curves  of  the  length  of 
the  introspections,  in  lines  or  words,  would  show  the  same 
general  slant  from  left  to  right.  Of  course,  such  a  result 
could  have  only  the  most  general  application,  but  the  differ- 


I 


CONSCIOUS   ATTITUDES  233 

ence  in  length  of  introspections  is  sticking,  and,  taken  with  the 
other  indications  of  shortening,  has  a  certain  significance.  At 
the  beginning  of  any  series  there  are  usually  one  or  one  and  a 
half  introspections  to  a  type- written  page,  while  at  the  end 
they  average  from  five  to  ten,  according  to  the  observer. 

The  letters  chosen,  which  were  the  first  ten  of  the  alphabet, 
turned  out  to  vary  greatly  in  degree  of  difl&culty.  E,  being  a 
single  point,  was  the  easiest  of  all.  F,  I,  and  A  were  also  easy, 
while  G,  D,  H,  and  J  were  difficult,  and  B  and  C  stood  mid- 
way. The  intermingling  of  these  difficult  and  easy  letters 
brings  irregularities  into  the  times,  and  makes  it  necessary  to 
study  the  letters  separately. 

The  letter  which  gave  O  the  most  trouble  was  D.  The  average  time 
for  D  was  longer  than  that  for  any  of  the  other  letters,  and  the  letter  was 
usually  not  correctly  recognised.  In  fact,  it  was  called  D  only  once,  the 
last  time  that  it  was  given.  The  reaction-times  are  very  irregular,  in- 
creasing gradually  from  the  beginning,  suddenly  dropping  about  the  middle 
of  the  series,  and  then  again  increasing.  At  first  D  is  confused  with  G, 
but  later  consistently  with  J.  The  nimiber  of  elementary  experiences 
reported  varies  roughly  with  the  reaction- time.  When  D  first  occurs 
(p.  j,  4.42),  the  introspection  includes  perception  of  shape,  organic  sensa- 
tion, disagreeable  feeling,  and  images.  In  the  next  case  (D.  g,  8.40)  the 
image  of  the  reaction-letter  comes  verbally  as  well  as  auditorily,  and  there 
is  doubt.  Otherwise  the  report  is  essentially  the  same.  In  the  third  case 
(D.  j,  11.62),  consciousness  is  still  more  complex,  and  includes  repeated 
perception,  more  complex  verbal  images,  and  several  visual  images,  of  which 
some  are  merely  associative.  In  the  fourth  (D.  j,  10.24),  there  are  added 
frowning,  irritation,  organic  sensations  throughout  the  body.  "Very 
disagreeable.  So  many  sensations  and  images  that  I  cannot  remember  them 
all."  In  the  next,  there  is  a  marked  decrease.  In  the  next  three  or  four, 
there  is  increase  again;  and  in  the  final  case  (D.  d,  15.42),  the  observer 
says:  '  'Auditory  image  J,  or  D.  I  thought  it  over  again  and  again.  This 
was  bodily  setting,  and  associations  which  were  not  perfected.  The  whole 
was  accompanied  by  strains  and  organic  sensations,  verbal  and  visual 
images,  and  unpleasantness,  especially  at  the  last."  Evidently  the  ob- 
server himself  was  not  satisfied,  and  the  reaction  to  D  was  not  a  true  rec- 
ognition. 

This  series  will  serve  as  an  example  of  the  correspondence  between 
amount  of  content  and  reaction  time.  It  is  evident  that  we  have  not 
here  before  us  a  growth  of  the  recognitive  consciousness.  As  the  letters 
in  alphabetical  order  were  given  to  the  observer  at  the  beginning  of  the 
hour,  he  could  not  form  a  closer  and  closer  association  between  the  letter 
D  and  the  name  J,  which  the  repeated  wrong  reactions  might  otherwise 
have  caused.  So  we  find  irregularities,  with  a  tendency  toward  increase 
rather  than  decrease.  The  result  shows,  so  far  as  one  case  may  do,  that 
the  shortening  to  be  observed  with  increasing  ease  of  recognition  is  not  to 
be  attributed  to  a  general  habituation  to  this  form  of  experiment.  The 
change  due  to  habituation  can  be  observed,  but  it  occurs  mostly  in  the 
fore-period,  and  it  is  not  sufficient  to  account  for  the  progressively  shorter 
reactions  to  particular  stimuli. 

The  letter  A,  which  for  most  observers  was  one  of  the  easiest,  was  for 
O  next  in  difiiculty  to  J.  It  shows,  however,  a  different  change  in  conscious- 
ness. A  is  always  recognised  correctly  except  in  one  place,  in  spite  of  its 
difficulty,  and  consciousness  shows  a  general  though  very  irregular  prog- 

JOURNAL— 7 


234  CLARKE 

ress  from  complexity  to  comparative  simplicity.  In  the  beginning  (A.  a, 
14.78)  O  reports  difficulty  of  perception,  organic  sensations  in  abdomen, 
spine  and  back,  disagreeable  feeling,  verbal  ideas,  auditory-motor  images, 
and  doubt,  which  last  was  a  tactual  memory  image  of  the  former  size  of 
the  dot  and  a  comparison  of  this  with  the  sensation.  In  an  introspection 
chosen  from  the  latter  part  of  the  series,  there  are  only  tactual  perception, 
visual  image  of  dots,  verbal  idea  A,  and  surprise.  In  this  case  the  letter 
was  rightly  recognised,  and  the  time  was  2.78  sec.  F  and  E  show  the 
shortest  times,  but  they  are  not  very  regular.  Practice  was  not  carried 
far  enough  with  O  to  reach  automatic  and  prompt  recognition.  With 
every  letter  except  D  there  is  a  change  toward  simplicity  of  consciousness 
and  shortening  of  reaction  time. 

The  letter  C  was  one  of  the  easiest  for  the  observer  F.  The  introspec- 
tions may  be  compared  with  the  time  curve.  C.  c,  3.20.  The  reaction 
was  unnecessarily  long,  I  forgot  to  react.  Tactual  images  as  I  moved  my 
finger,  especially  an  image  of  touching  the  lever.  Sensation  of  strain  in 
shoulders  and  chest,  slight  interruption  of  breathing.  Attention  all  on 
tactual  images.  As  I  was  moving  across  I  had  the  verbal  idea:  Tactual 
images.  C  is  a  movement  across  and  down.  It  is  kinaesthetic  and  tactual. 
C  came  up  verbally  and  auditorily.  Saying  C  recalled  the  Aufgahe  to 
react,  in  what  form  I  do  not  know.  C.  d,  3.30.  Visual  and  kinaesthetic 
image  of  movement.  I  said  'as  before'  while  I  was  moving  across.  Tac- 
tual image  of  a  point.  Touched  the  letter,  and  I  came  up  verbally.  I 
knew  that  it  was  not  clear  enough;  it  did  not  fit  into  what  I  know  I  is. 
The  whole  complex  was  not  just  right  to  produce  reaction.  I  felt  twice 
more  and  D  came  up.  The  reaction  still  seems  just  like  saying  the  letter. 
'As  before'  meant  going  over  it  without  attending  to  the  lever.  C.  c,  2.16. 
Idea  of  movement,  partly  visual  and  involving  eye  movement.  D  came 
up  at  first;  then  I  felt  the  rest  of  the  letter,  and  C  came  up  verbally  and 
auditorily.  The  breathing  was  right  to  say  C.  I  was  trying  to  catch  the 
verbal  image  and  noticed  the  breathing.  C. — 1.96.  Strain  when  I  heard 
some  one  walking.  This  strain  meant  'hurry-up.'  I  touched  the  letter 
and  it  was  not  clear  at  first.  I  felt  it  again.  It  was  familiar,  but  I  could 
not  think  what  it  was.  C.  c,  2.10.  I  felt  two  dots  above.  Attention 
on  upper  dots,  then  vague  perception  of  lower  one,  and  I  moved  down  to 
feel  it.  This  motion  named  the  letter.  C.  c,  0.96.  Tactual  and  kin- 
aesthetic image  of  feeling  the  letter.  The  location  of  the  letter  in  advance 
is  kinaesthetic  and  tactual.  C  was  visualised  as  a  dark  mark.  C. — 1.16. 
I  did  not  recognise  the  letter.  It  was  very  clear.  I  reacted  to  the  tactual 
sensation.  C.  c,  0.62.  I  set  myself  muscularly,  touched  the  letter,  and 
moved  part  way  over  it.  F  came  up  auditorily.  I  moved  the  rest  of  the 
way  and  C  came  up.  Reaction  and  relaxation.  C.  c,  0.44.  Vague  tac- 
tual image  and  muscular  set.  Clear  tactual  and  kinaesthetic  sensation. 
There  is  an  image  of  the  kinaesthetic  sensation  which  enters  in  and  makes 
a  part  of  the  C.  When  I  move  my  finger  straight  across,  it  seems  as  if  I 
had  moved  it  down.  This  is  an  image.  Auditory  image  C  after  reaction. 
C.  c,  0.36.     Idea  of  movement.     I  felt  it,  and  the  letter  C  came  up. 

The  reaction  times  of  V  are  uniformly  short,  but  show  a  very  regular 
decrease.  There  is  a  striking  similarity  among  the  curves,  some  of  them 
being  scarcely  distinguishable.  Early  in  the  series  there  are  mistakes, 
and  some  entire  failures  to  recognise  the  letter.  In  far  the  larger  number 
of  cases,  however,  the  recognition  is  unerring  and  the  reaction  times  are 
short.  It  has  already  been  shown  (p.  223)that  the  color  images,  which  accom- 
pany certain  letters  for  V,  gradually  fade  out.  In  the  introspections,  of  which 
we  give  but  the  briefest  sample,  there  is  a  corresponding  disappearance 
of  other  conscious  contents. 

In  the  case  of  H,  V  reacted  to  a  vague  mass.  The  voluminousness 
seemed  to  be  the  one  thing  recognised;  and  she  recognised  the  letter  in 
a  fraction  of  a  second  just  from  its  voluminousness,  long  before  the  shape 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  235 

began  to  be  definite.  J  was  associated  verbally  at  the  beginning  with  the 
strange  thing  which  did  not  fit,  but  this  letter  too  came  later  to  have  more 
definite  outlines. 

As  G  had  done  no  experiments  in  the  first  series,  the  introspections  here 
given  represent  the  whole  course  of  improvement  from  the  first  presentation 
of  a  letter  to  its  almost  automatic  recognition.  I.  i,  1.86.  At  first  a  touch 
complex  which  was  focal.  Repeated  movement  in  the  vertical  direction, 
which  led  at  once  to  recognition  and  verbal  idea  I;  movement  and  verbal 
idea  focal,  organic  complex  vague.  Feeling  of  recognition  pleasant. 
I.  i,  2.82.  Horizontal  movement  with  complex  touch  led  to  no  recognition 
but  to  vertical  movement  over  the  dots.  Visual  image  of  I  and  very 
pleasant  mood,  localised  in  trunk.  This  might  be  called  ease  of  recogni- 
tion. I.  i,  2.60.  Slight  surprise,  that  is  a  check  of  the  horizontal  move- 
ment, and  a  change  into  the  vertical,  with  peculiar  movement  of  the  mouth, 
a  dropping  of  the  lower  jaw,  and  slight  sensation  in  chest.  The  setting 
of  the  mouth  led  involuntarily  to  saying  I  aloud,  and  reaction.  Last 
slightly  pleasant.  I.  i,  i .  40.  I  is  recognised  by  the  checking  of  the  horizon- 
tal movement  and  the  substitution  of  the  vertical.  Setting  of  the  mouth 
to  say  I.  Reaction  automatic.  I.  i,  1.14.  Inhibited  horizontal  move- 
ment. Strong  setting  of  the  mouth  to  say  I,  which  lasted  after  the  reaction 
and  led  to  saying  I.  SHghtly  pleasant.  I.  i,  2,40.  Slight  setting  of  the 
mouth  to  say  I.  Indififerent  or  slightly  pleasant.  I.  i,  1.16.  Different 
from  the  usual  I-consciousness.  Motion  not  inhibited.  Vertical  motion 
replaced  by  tactual  perception  of  two  dots,  one  above  the  other.  Slight 
pressing  down  of  the  lower  part  of  the  mouth,  vaguely  localised.  I.  i,  1.60. 
Movement  horizontal,  then  vertical.  Organic  and  affective  inhibition  of 
horizontal  movement.  As  soon  as  this  vertical  movement  was  established, 
slight  pressure  of  the  larynx  in  setting  of  the  mouth  to  say  I.  I.  i,  2.22. 
Touch-motor  consciousness,  with  change  from  horizontal  to  vertical  very 
clear.  Vague  pressure  in  back  of  mouth.  This  was  the  I-consciousness. 
Slightly  pleasant.  I.  i,  1.36.  Stereotyped  I-consciousness.  I.  i,  1.36. 
Stereotyped  I-consciousness.  Kinaesthetic  part  in  back  of  mouth  more 
pronounced  than  usual.  Auditory  image:  I  again.  I,  i.  1.60.  Surprise. 
This  was  inhibited  breathing  and  setting  of  the  larynx  and  back  of  mouth 
Later  the  common  I-consciousness. 

There  can  be  no  doubt  that  the  introspections  given,  and 
the  far  larger  body  from  which  they  are  taken,  represent 
recognition  in  the  making.  In  the  whole  number  of  reports 
there  are  at  most  only  one  or  two  cases  of  the  comparison  of  a 
percept  with  a  memory  image.  There  is  not  a  single  allusion 
to  a  quality  of  knownness  attaching  to  the  perception.  The 
feeling  of  familiarity  is  reported  thirty-five  times,  but  in  all 
but  four  it  is  analysed.  The  introspections  of  any  observer 
show,  in  general,  a  dropping  out  of  conscious  contents,  and  a 
shortening  of  reaction-time  going  parallel  with  increased  ease 
of  recognition.  Only  one  case  was  noted  in  which  the  process 
was  reversed;  the  reaction-times  here  become  longer  instead 
of  shorter,  the  conscious  contents  increase  in  complexity,  and 
the  letter  is  continually  mistaken  for  another. 

The  cases  of  reported  familiarity  almost  all  occur  in  the 
first  half  of  a  series.  Their  analyses  show  that  they  are  complex 
states,  consisting  mostly  of  strain  and  organic  sensations, 
with  some  affective  processes  and  accidental  associations. 


236  CLARKB 

Among  the  final  experiments  of  most  series,  where  we  may 
assume  that  complete  recognition  occurs,  we  find  cases  in 
which  the  reaction  is  said  to  be  automatic,  and  the  letter  may 
be  represented  in  consciousness  by  a  setting  of  the  mouth  to 
say  it,  a  visual  image,  a  flash  of  color,  or  by  nothing  at  all. 

If  the  terms  'familiarity'  and  'recognition'  are  used  inter- 
changeably by  writers  on  the  subject,  it  may  well  be  that  they 
were  also  confused  by  our  observers.  We  should  not  lay  too 
great  stress  upon  the  names  applied  to  the  attitude. 
With  all  allowance  made  for  inaccuracy,  however,  there  are 
suggestions  here  for  the  arrangement  of  familiarity  and  rec- 
ognition along  a  scale  of  continuously  varying  complexity.^ 

If  recognition  has  received  considerable  attention  from 
psychologists,  so  also  has  understanding.  In  fact,  the  two 
approach  each  other  so  closely  in  experience  that  it  is  impossible 
sharply  to  distinguish  them.  Our  own  experiments  combined 
the  methods  of  Ribot,  Binet  and  Taylor.  The  stimuli  were 
words,  sentences,  and  paragraphs  cut  from  magazines,  which 
were  read  sometimes  to  the  observer,  sometimes  by  her.  The 
stimuli  were  varied  in  two  directions,  from  simplicity  to  com- 
plexity by  means  of  the  length  of  the  passage  to  be  read,  and 
from  sense  to  nonsense,  some  of  the  stimuli  being  strange 
or  impossible  words.  If  there  is  a  special  consciousness  of 
understanding,  it  ought  to  stand  out,  by  contrast,  in  a  series 
in  which  part  of  the  stimuli  are  not  understood.  The  ex- 
periments were  performed  during  the  summer  of  1909  with 
the  observers  MC  and  HC.  The  latter  wrote  introspections 
on  only  100  single  words;  MC  was  given  the  same  number  of 
words  and,  in  addition,  50  sentences  and  20  paragraphs.  The 
general  procedure  was  that  the  observer  drew  a  slip  from  an 
envelope,  read  the  stimulus,  and  wrote  the  introspection. 
When  the  report  was  dictated,  or  the  stimulus  read  by  the 
experimenter,  the  fact  is  noted.  The  words  used  include 
nouns,  both  abstract  and  concrete,  and  various  other  parts 
of  speech.  In  almost  every  case  MC  reports  verbal  and  visual 
images  of  the  word  as  the  first  thing  in  consciousness;  and 
sometimes,  if  the  word  is  not  very  familiar  or  is  one  whose 
meaning  does  not  easily  appear  in  visual  images,  it  is  repeated 
several  times. 

MC.  It  was  invariably  the  case  that,  if  the  word  was  unknown  to  the 
observer,  she  immediately  associated  it  verbally  to  some  known  word  of 
similar  sound,  and  the  other  contents  of  consciousness  referred  to  the 
meaning  of  the  known  word.     Sometimes  only  a  part  of  a  word  was  con- 

*Lack  of  space,  again,  forbids  a  discussion,  in  this  and  the  following  sec- 
tions, of  the  views  and  results  of  earlier  investigators.  General  reference 
may  be  made  to  Titchener,  Exp.  Psychol,  of  the  Thought-processes.  We 
hope  to  recur  to  the  theory  of  recognition,  in  particular,  in  a  later  article, 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  237 

cerned  in  this  association.  Metappos.  Visual  image  of  Italy  and  Switz- 
erland on  the  map,  accompanied  by  sense  of  direction.  Verbal  image  of 
the  words  Matterhom  and  Metaphysics.  Frostilla.  Visual  image  of  a 
frosted  cake,  then  of  frost  on  a  window  pane.  I  do  not  know  the  meaning 
of  the  word,  but  think  it  may  apply  to  some  kind  of  extract. 

Even  when  the  word  was  understood,  it  was  sometimes  associated  to 
others  of  similar  sound,  or  divided  into  parts  and  then  connected  with 
images  which  referred  to  but  a  single  part.  This  verbal  association  oc- 
cured  most  often  when  the  word  was  a  pronoun  or  preposition  whose 
meaning  was  hard  to  grasp  apart  from  context.  Display.  Visual  image 
of  the  two  syllables  separately,  and  of  a  stage  at  the  theatre.  Later  visual 
image  of  a  woman  overdressed,  not  very  distinct.  Which.  Verbal  image 
Witch,  with  visual  image  of  a  volume  of  Scott  and  of  Meg  Merrilies. 
Then  repeated  verbal  image  of  the  stimulus  word,  with  slight  groping  in 
mind,  followed  by  image  of  a  page  in  a  grammar. 

By  far  the  greater  number  of  meanings  were  represented  by  visual 
images,  and  these  were  most  likely  to  occur  with  words  denoting  concrete 
objects,  though  they  were  not  confined  to  them.  Compartment.  Image 
of  a  train,  and  of  the  words  'train'  and  'European.'  Sense  of  direction 
and  distance.     Visual  image  of  some  pigeon-holes. 

The  contents  of  consciousness  were  usually  far  poorer  in  the  understand- 
ing of  such  words  as  prepositions,  which  have  little  meaning  apart  from 
context.  From.  Repeated  visual  and  verbal  images  of  the  word.  Sense 
of  distance  and  direction  in  going  from  one  place  to  another.  Visual 
image  of  a  country  road  between  two  familiar  places.  The.  Visual  image 
of  the  word,  then  again  in  big  letters  at  the  top  of  a  newspaper;  no  par- 
ticular one.  Then  a  blank.  I  shut  my  eyes  and  looked  into  a  blank  field. 
Consciousness  of  'seeking,'  but  nothing  came. 

Sometimes  the  setting  which  the  word  called  up  was  verbal  rather  than 
visual,  and  sometimes  the  verbal  ideas  constituted  a  definition.  Adjacent. 
Word  at  first  seen  sidewise  and  not  recognised.  The  J  was  most  con- 
spicuous, and  this  came  as  a  visual  image,  followed  by  verbal  image;  Dr. 
Jekyl  and  Mr.  Hyde.  Then  visual  and  verbal  image  of  the  word,  the  latter 
many  times  repeated,  and  a  sense  of  groping  and  looking  into  a  blank  held, 
though  less  blank  than  usual.  It  seems  at  times  to  be  dotted  with  con- 
spicuous black  letters  such  as  made  up  the  stimulus  word.  Later  verbal 
idea:  Things  close  to  each  other.  Marvelous.  Visual  image  of  a  house 
occupied  by  Prof.  M  (name  similar  in  sound  to  stimulus).  Later  verbal 
image:  Wonderful.  Rose.  Visual  image  of  a  rosebush,  and  of  two  girls 
named  Ross.  Verbal  idea:  Roman  de  la  Rose.  Images  were  unusually 
numerous  here,  and  I  cannot  recall  the  others.  They  seemed  to  be  present 
all  at  once. 

As  might  be  expected,  there  are  cases  reported  in  which  the  word  was 
understood,  but  the  observer  could  not  analyse  the  understanding.  There 
are,  however,  only  seven  or  eight  of  these  among  the  hundred  words,  and 
in  most  of  the  exceptional  cases  there  is  some  indication  that  sensations 
or  images  were  present.  Right.  An  immediate  consciousness  of  the  idea 
'to  do  right.'  '  'This  was  partly  verbal,  but  I  seemed  also  to  see  something 
of  a  schematic  nature.  I  looked  downward  to  see  this."  (Whatever  the 
observer  looked  down  to  see  must  have  been  of  a  visual  nature.)  In- 
dividuals. Image  of  a  light  place  (probably  an  after-image)  with  the  word 
in  it.  It  all  seemed  to  be  inside  my  head,  then  I  seemed  to  try  to  get  it 
out.  Paralysed  feeling,  I  knew  what  the  word  meant,  but  it  did  not 
suggest  anything.  Then  visual  image  of  individual  people  walking.  They 
bowed.  Knowing  what  it  meant  was  a  kind  of  comfortable  feeling,  a  feel- 
ing that  I  could  define  the  word.  This  was  in  the  back  of  the  head  and 
throat.  (The  feeling  that  she  could  define  the  word,  localised  in  the  back 
of  the  throat,  was  probably  the  setting  of  the  vocal  cords  to  articulate  the 
definition.) 


238  CLARKE 

These  introspections,  like  those  of  Binet,  Ribot,  and  Bagley,  show  cases 
in  which  the  images  were  inadequate  or  contradictory  to  thought.  Noise- 
less. Visual  image  of  a  house,  of  a  very  noisy  family  of  boys  who  occupy 
it,  also  an  auditory  image  of  the  noise  of  those  children.  This  was  ac- 
companied by  a  sense  of  contrast,  but  I  am  too  tired  to  analyse  this. 
Electric.  Visual  image  of  a  park  that  I  once  visited  which,  however,  was 
not  electric.  There  seemed  to  be  in  the  background  images  of  several 
electric  parks  but  the  other  was  more  distinct. 

In  the  next  series,  of  50  experiments,  the  stimuli  were  sentences  of  va- 
rious lengths.  Here,  too,  the  meaning  is  most  often  represented  by  visual 
images,  if  the  sentence  describes  a  visible  object  or  a  scene.  In  such  cases 
the  whole  scene  may  be  painted  before  the  observer's  eyes,  a  part  at  a 
time,  as  the  words  come.  The  engineer  and  fireman  and  one  or  two 
others  were  standing  by  the  engine  staring  at  it;  and  so  they  hastened  thither, 
well  ahead  of  the  outpour  of  people  behind  them.  (Read  by  E.)  The  series 
of  visual  images  came  during  the  reading.  Verbal  images  of  first  two  or 
three  words.  Visual  images  of  engineer,  fireman,  engine  and  crowd. 
He  climbed  up  the  straight  iron  steps  to  the  gangway.  Visual  image  of  iron 
filigree  work.  Verbal  image  of  whole  sentence.  Image  of  a  person  going 
up  a  gangplank  in  the  Brooklyn  Navy  Yards.  Second  verbal  repetition 
of  the  whole  sentence. 

For  this  observer  all  sentences,  even  of  an  abstract  natiu-e,  arouse  visual 
images  which  represent,  more  or  less  schematically,  the  meaning  of  the 
whole  or  of  single  words.  Sentences  which  are  not  descriptive  may  never- 
theless be  represented  visually.  Every  vigorous  state  pursues  two  principal 
aims:  to  enlarge  its  dominions  and  to  preserve  its  independence.  Visual  and 
verbal  images  of  sentence.  Words  'principal,'  'territory,'  and  'independ- 
ence' stood  out  most  prominently.  Even  while  I  read,  I  connected  it 
with  my  history  work.  Visual  image  of  table  at  which  I  work,  and  a 
'feeling'  that  the  sentence  belonged  to  me.  Visual  image  of  the  Mississippi 
valley,  schematic  and  a  good  deal  in  the  background.  The  country  was 
being  extended  into  this  valley.  Sense  of  distance  and  direction  to  Atlan- 
tic states.  The  word  'independence'  meant  the  Revolution.  This  was 
mostly  direction  and  distance,  and  a  schematic  image  of  the  Revolution. 
Independence  Hall  was  included. 

Some  sentences  arouse  very  little  imagery,  and  yet  are  understood. 
Life  is  ruled  by  the  power  of  the  deed.  'Deed'  was  at  first  read  as  'dead,' 
and  gave  an  image  of  Egypt  and  some  mummies.  When  I  read  it  again, 
I  knew  what  it  meant,-  but  it  was  not  as  clear  as  usual.  Slow  repetition 
of  the  sentence.  Emphasis  on  'life',  'rules',  power',  and  'deed'.  'Life' 
called  up  an  image  of  a  Chicago  street.  'Deed'  gave  an  image  of  myself 
doing  something. 

The  third  series  was  similar,  except  that  the  stimuU  were  whole  para- 
graphs, varying  in  length,  but  all  longer  than  the  sentences.  Here  again 
a  description  of  anything  which  could  have  been  seen  is  very  fully  illustrated 
by  visual  images.  In  some  cases  these  are  added  as  the  words  come,  and 
make  a  whole  pictiu-e;  in  others  the  images  seem  to  refer  to  individual 
meanings  of  the  words,  and  not  to  the  whole  situation.  An  arduous  task 
must  have  been  that  of  the  first  ministers  of  the  Jamestown  Church.  A  part 
of  religious  services  enjoined  were  as  follows:  on  week  days,  early  in  the  morn- 
ing, the  captain  sent  for  tools  in  place  of  arms,  when  the  '  serjeant-major'  or 
captain  of  the  watch,  upon  their  knees,  made  public  and  faithful  prayers  to 
Almighty  God  for  His  blessings  and  protection  to  attend  them  in  their  busi- 
ness for  the  whole  day  after  succeeding.  Visual  image  of  some  ministers. 
Sense  of  distance  and  direction  to  Jamestown,  visual  image  of  the  town, 
and  vaguely  of  a  church.  At  'religious  services,'  image  of  a  chiu-ch. 
'Early  in  the  morning'  gave  an  image  which  seems  to  grow  or  develop. 
First  there  was  what  I  call  the  representation  of  a  morning,  which  was  partly 
visual  but  included  other  sensations,  such  as  the  pressure  of  air  on  the 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  239 

face.  Visual  images  of  captain,  tool,  army,  etc.  'Upon  their  knees,* 
image  of  people  praying. — Even  when  the  meaning  is  abstract,  there  is 
still  imagery. 

The  second  series  shows  an  interesting  case  of  the  process  by  which  a 
visual  image  becomes  stereotyped  and  loses  its  particular  quaUty  as  it  re- 
curs repeatedly  in  the  same  connection.  Several  of  the  sentences  were 
from  an  article  on  Buddhism,  and  this  word  called  up  the  same  association 
each  time,  with  some  modification,  as  follows,  (i)  Visual  image  of  the 
word  Buddhism  and  of  a  Dr.  X  whom  I  once  heard  lecture  on  this  subject. 
Visual  image  of  something  brown,  which  represents  India,  and  contains  an 
idol.  (2)  'Buddhist'  gave  image  of  Dr.  X.  A  long  row  of  idols  and 
something  brown.  (3)  Image  of  a  sort  of  conventionalised  Dr.  X.  Any 
reference  to  Buddhism  always  calls  up  Dr.  X,  and  this  has  happened  so 
often  that  the  image  seems  to  have  ceased  to  be  personal.  (4)  Visual 
image  of  Dr.  X;  it  was  rather  an  image  of  an  image.  (5)  Schematic  image 
of  Dr.  X. 

The  100  introspections  written  by  HC  on  the  understanding  of  single 
words  need  not  be  discussed  in  detail.  Some  of  the  reports  show  that  tiie 
meaning  of  a  word  may  be  carried,  in  whole  or  in  part,  by  a  motor  image 
or  an  organic  sensation.  Grip.  Visual  image  of  a  hand  reached  out  to 
grasp  something,  and  muscular  image  of  the  sensation  in  right  arm  and  hand 
when  something  is  grasped.  Approval.  Image  of  a  person  vaguely  seen 
nodding  his  head  and  smiling.  This  was  accompanied  by  motor  images 
of  the  action,  which  were  much  stronger  than  the  visual,  and  yet  the  latter 
was  not  of  myself.  Stroke.  Swift  motor  image  of  striking  something. 
Wanted.     Organic  sensation  in  stomach. 

Several  of  these  reports  show  well  how  the  mind  goes  from  one  to  another 
of  several  possible  meanings  when  the  word  is  presented  without  context. 
Glasses.  Visual  image  of  spectacles  alone,  then  on  a  person.  Then  of 
ttmiblers  on  a  table.  Reproduced.  Verbal  image  of  the  word.  Visual 
image  of  my  abbreviation  for  'reproductive  tendencies,'  then  of  some  eggs, 
then  of  two  sheets  of  typewritten  matter  with  a  carbon  sheet  between. 
Verbal  image  'manifold.' 

Perhaps  this  is  the  least  inappropriate  place  to  say  a  few 
words  about  a  series  of  experiments  which  do  not  belong  ex- 
clusively to  the  discussion  of  any  particular  attitude,  and  yet 
throw  some  light  upon  the  whole  subject.  Their  only  con- 
nection with  the  preceding  is  the  fact  that  they  were  per- 
formed by  the  same  observer  (MC)  at  about  the  same  time; 
their  bearing  is  rather  on  imageless  thought  than  on  the  at- 
titudes proper.  It  will  be  remembered  that  Marbe  used  the 
Ausfragemethodey  and  that  his  questions  were  criticised  upon 
the  ground  that  they  were  too  simple,  and  could  be  answered 
merely  associatively,  without  any  thought.  Buhler  avoided 
this  danger  by  giving  aphorisms,  which  offered  some  diflSculty 
to  understanding,  or  asking  questions,  which  required,  for 
instance,  the  consideration  of  whole  periods  in  the  history  of 
philosophy  in  a  brief  time. 

The  object  of  the  present  series  was  to  combine  these  meth- 
ods into  a  differential  or  contrast  method  in  order  to  bring  out 
the  difference  in  consciousness  between  the  answer  which  re- 
quired thought  and  that  which  did  not.  The  subject  chosen 
was  history,  because  this  was  of  special  interest  to  the  obser- 


240  CIvARKE 

ver.  She  was  asked  50  questions,  chosen  indiscriminately 
from  many  periods  of  general  history,  and  ranging  in  diffi- 
culty from  "When  was  America  discovered?"  to  "What 
were  the  constitutional  difficulties  in  the  way  of  reconstruc- 
tion after  the  Civil  War?" 

We  find  that  visual  images  play  an  important  part  in  this  observer's 
memory  of  history.  Centuries  and  special  dates  within  them  are  seen  sche- 
matically and  often  in  colors,  while  persons  and  events  are  assigned  to 
certain  periods  because  they  are  seen  to  be  in  them  or  like  them  in  color. 
Name  the  first  five  presidents  of  the  Uiiited  States.  Answer:  Washington,, 
J.  Adams,  Jefferson,  Madison,  Monroe.  Visual  image  of  each  man  as  his 
name  was  given.  Jefferson  was  especially  clear.  With  Adams,  image  of 
date  1 801.  Schematic  image  of  length  of  terms.  It  was  dark  colored  and 
had  some  spaces  marked  off,  twice  as  much  for  two  terms  as  for  one.  In 
connection  with  Madison,  image  of  War  of  1812  and  of  an  old  book  on  the 
subject.     Adams  seemed  to  stand  in  a  comer,  a  turn  between  two  centuries. 

The  facts  of  history  as  well  as  their  dates  are  in  many  cases  apparently 
read  off  from  visual  images  which  had  represented  them  in  the  past.  Was 
there  any  connection  between  th^  French  and  American  Revolutions'^  Answer: 
Yes,  The  French  assisted  the  American  Revolution  and  are  said  to  have 
incited  it.  The  French  Revolution  was  influenced  by  the  example  of  the 
American.  Visual  image  of  a  book  on  the  subject.  Image  of  the  American 
Revolution  and  of  arms  and  ammunition  on  a  ship  being  sent  by  the  French 
to  America.  Then  of  a  Frenchman  sitting  in  a  coffee-house  finding  out 
public  opinion  about  the  Revolution.  I  seemed  to  see  the  two  wars  at  the 
same  time,  and  to  know  that  the  American  happened  first  and  was  an  ex- 
ample. What  became  of  the  Celts  when  the  Teutons  invaded  England  ? 
Answer:  They  were  partly  absorbed,  partly  exterminated,  partly  pushed 
into  Wales.  Image  of  Wales  and  of  Celts  and  Teutons  fighting.  Then 
of  the  whole  country  with  some  Celts  and  Teutons  intermingled.  This  is 
what  made  me  say  'absorbed.' 

Sometimes  the  answer  is  so  familiar  and  comes  so  readily  that  there  is 
very  little  else  in  consciousness.  When  was  America  discovered}  Answer: 
1492.  Visual  image  of  the  date  with  a  red  halo,  also  of  Columbus  in  Spain 
with  distance  and  direction  to  Spain.  Who  first  sailed  around  the  globe} 
Answer :  Magellan.  Visual  image  of  Straits  of  Magellan,  of  the  man,  and 
later  of  the  name.  When  was  the  fall  of  Rome?  Answer :  476.  Image  of 
date,  and  of  Rome  surrounded  by  barbarous  hordes. 

Let  us  summarise  the  facts  which  the  two  hundred  and 
seventy  introspections  show  in  regard  to  the  understanding 
of  words  and  sentences. 

(i)  A  word  which  is  not  familiar  calls  up  others  which  are 
similar  to  it  in  sound,  and  the  images  are  appropriate  to  these 
familiar  words.  (2)  Words  like  'to,'  'which,'  'of,'  which  do 
not  ordinarily  occur  without  context  and  do  not  refer  to  an 
object  that  can  be  represented  by  an  image,  also  show  to  some 
extent  the  tendency  toward  mere  auditory  association.  Their 
appearance  in  this  strangely  unconnected  position  is  usually 
followed  by  groping  or  blankness  of  consciousness.  They  often 
form  a  context  for  themselves,  by  verbal  association  with  some 
word  which  could  grammatically  follow  them.  (3)  Words 
which  refer  to  objects  of  sense,  visual  or  otherwise,  are  often 
represented  by  images.     (4)  Words  which  are  capable  of  more 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  24 1 

than  one  interpretation  usually  excite  in  quick  succession 
images  appropriate  to  the  different  meanings.  (5)  In  com- 
paring the  average  length  of  the  introspections  on  words,  sen- 
tences, and  paragraphs,  we  find  that  they  are  in  no  sense  pro- 
portional to  the  length  of  the  stimulus;  on  the  contrary,  they 
are  all  of  about  the  same  length. 

The  very  fact  that  the  single  words  stood  alone,  out  of  all 
connection,  introduced  an  unfamiliar  element,  and  gave 
opportunity  for  all  sorts  of  associations.  Experiments  upon 
single  words  are,  in  fact,  comparable  to  'free  associations.' 
When  a  word  comes  without  context,  and  the  time  which  the 
introspection  is  to  cover  is  not  definitely  limited,  the  images, 
visual,  verbal  and  other,  which  are  aroused,  are  likely  to  be 
numerous  and  varied.  Most  of  them  refer  in  some  way  to 
some  meaning  of  the  word,  or  to  its  connection  with  events 
of  our  own  lives;  but  some  may  be  irrelevant.  If  now,  we 
read  the  same  word  as  part  of  a  short  sentence,  we  get  some- 
what the  same  effect  as  when  an  association  is  guided  by  a  word 
just  heard,  or  when  the  observer  adds  to  the  Aufgabe  an  ad- 
ditional self-imposed  condition.  The  Aufgabe  now  is  not 
"Get  any  meaning  of  the  word,"  but  "Get  a  meaning  which 
goes  with  these  other  words."  Moreover,  the  time  is  short- 
ened; the  words  follow  one  another  in  quick  succession.  This 
limitation  in  time  tends  to  inhibit  part  of  the  images,  and  the 
context  determines  which  of  them  shall  be  suppressed. 

It  may  be  objected  that  it  is  not  always  the  wrong  associa- 
tion that  is  inhibited.  Our  introspections,  as  well  as  those 
of  previous  writers,  show  that  often  the  images  are  inad- 
equate, irrelevant,  or  even  contradictory.  So  far  as  inad- 
equacy is  concerned,  however,  we  have  no  criterion,  save  the 
facts  themselves,  by  which  we  can  decide  how  clear  or  com- 
plete an  image  must  be  in  order  to  carry  a  meaning.  Again, 
the  image  which  is  logically  contradictory  may  yet  have  enough 
in  common  with  the  meaning  of  the  word  to  be  psychologically 
adequate  to  this  meaning.  Two  words  cannot,  indeed,  be 
spoken  of  as  contradictory,  unless  they  have  something  in 
common;  they  must  at  least  belong  to  the  same  universe  of 
discourse,  to  the  same  context;  and  it  is  just  this  context 
which,  recalled  in  any  form  whatever,  constitutes  a  more  or 
less  general  meaning.  Logically,  it  is  not  easy  to  see  why  a 
bird,  described  as  white  with  a  black  ring  around  its  neck, 
should  be  imaged  in  its  ordinary  colors;  or  why  a  description 
of  dogs  carried  in  a  basket  should  give  rise  to  images  of  cats 
jumping  out  of  a  panier.  Our  own  experiments  are  not  free 
from  such  anomalies.  The  word  'noiseless'  arouses  an  image 
of  some  particular  noisy  children;  'electric'  is  followed  by  an 
image  of  a  park  which  is  not  electric;  'home'  recalls  France, 


242  CLARKB 

and  the  idea  that  the  language  of  that  country  has  no  word  of 
the  same  meaning.  In  every  one  of  these  cases,  however, 
there  is  sufficient  connection  between  the  logical  meaning 
of  the  word,  and  the  psychological  content  of  the  act  of  under- 
standing, for  the  latter  to  carry  a  general  meaning. 

The  third  case,  that  in  which  the  imagery  is  neither  inade- 
quate nor  contradictory,  but  irrelevant,  is  less  easy  to  ex- 
plain. It  is  a  fact  of  observation  that  the  wrong  meaning 
is  not  always  inhibited  by  the  setting  and  the  additional 
Aufgabe,  but  runs  along  parallel  with  the  understanding  of  the 
sentence.  Every  word,  however,  is  not  of  equal  importance 
for  the  understanding  of  the  whole;  and  even  if  a  single  word 
is  given  a  wrong  interpretation  at  the  time  of  reading,  the 
meaning  of  the  whole  may  be  fairly  clear.  The  introspections 
show  cases  in  which  the  word  was  seen  only  in  part,  or  was 
at  first  misread,  and  the  context  of  the  wrong  reading  immedi- 
ately appeared  in  consciousness.  This  often  occurs  in  every- 
day experience,  without  attracting  attention.  The  mistake 
is  corrected  as  we  go  on,  and  the  wrong  image  is  replaced  by 
others  which  are  more  consistent  with  the  meaning  of  the 
situation. 

These  attempts  at  explanation  are  tentative  only.  We 
have  the  fact  that  understanding  may  at  times  be  mediated, 
psychologically,  by  images  which  logically  are  inadequate, 
irrelevant  or  directly  unsuited  to  their  office.  The  road  to 
final  explanation  lies  through  a  detailed  study  of  the  condi- 
tions under  which  such  representations  of  the  act  of  under- 
standing take  shape.  Their  appearance  in  experiments  like 
our  own  probably  depends,  in  many  cases,  upon  ingrained 
habits  of  reproductive  tendency,  which  by  lapse  of  time  are 
inaccessible  to  introspection.  Our  aim  must  be  to  catch 
them  in  the  making, — either  by  casual  observation  in  every- 
day life,  or  by  way  of  specially  shaped  observations  in  the 
laboratory. 

Unanalysable  feelings  of  relation  have  been  postulated 
by  various  writers.  Woodworth,  in  particular,  has  made 
experiments  with  words  and  with  papers  of  different  colors 
and  shapes,  arranged  according  to  the  rule  of  three,  which,  as 
he  believes,  show  that  a  relation  is  sometimes  conscious  as  an 
*imageless*  thought.  His  verbal  stimuli  were  presented  in 
the  form  London:  England  :  :  Paris:  X.  The  observer 
was  to  supply  the  fourth  term  of  the  proportion,  and  to  give 
a  complete  introspection.  The  reports  fall  into  four  classes, 
(i)  When  the  relation  is  easy  to  grasp  and  the  missing  term 
is  readily  found,  very  little  consciousness  appears.  "There 
was  nothing  in  my  mind,"  said  one  of  the  subjects,  "except 
that  I  wanted  to  answer  your  question  right."     The  answer 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  243 

comes  immediately,  on  the  hearing  of  the  three  given  terms. 
(2)  When  there  is  more  difificulty,  the  relation  sometimes  re- 
ceives a  name  before  the  answer  is  found.  (3)  Sometimes 
the  relation  is  pictured,  in  some  form  of  imagery.  (4)  Some- 
times the  subject  reports  that  he  felt  the  relation,  but  did  not 
name  it  or  have  an  image  of  it. 

Unfortunately,  the  author  does  not  tell  us  what  fraction  of 
the  whole  number  of  experiments  belongs  to  the  fourth  class. 
If  the  reports  of  this  group  were  numerous,  they  might  offer 
some  evidence  for  the  existence  of  unanalysable  feelings  of 
relation.  If  they  were  not,  they  may  well  be  explained  by 
the  incompleteness  of  introspection.  All  observers  probably 
fail  at  times  to  analyse  into  simplest  terms,  or  to  report  all  the 
contents  of  consciousness. 

We  have  ourselves  made  several  series  of  experiments  on 
this  subject,  all  of  which,  in  form  at  least,  are  based  on  those 
of  Woodworth.  In  the  first  series,  the  stimulus  consisted  of 
three  words  in  the  form  of  a  proportion  with  the  fourth  to  be 
supplied,  exactly  as  in  Woodworth's  experiments.  In  fact, 
a  few  of  the  examples  were  taken  bodily  from  his  paper.  The 
observers  were  V,  G,  and  F. 

The  relation  is  sometimes  present  in  consciousness  as  a  word. 

V.  A  book:  a  magazine: :  a  chair:  a  stool.  Visual  image  of  a  red  book  and 
a  magazine  side  by  side.  At  hearing  the  word  'chair'  great  surprise, — a 
muscular  contraction  and  a  gasp.  I  looked  at  a  chair  in  the  room,  then 
at  a  table.  Tendency  to  say  'table,'  because  I  had  a  kinaesthetic  idea  that 
a  book  is  squarer  and  higher  than  a  magazine.  Same  of  table  and  chair. 
This  was  inhibited,  I  don't  know  how.  Visual  image  of  a  footstool. 
Then  I  said  'less  than  a  chair.'  Then  said  'stool'  aloud.  No  balance. 
The  whole  took  effort. 

F.  Red:  blue::  green:  yellow.  I  started  to  say  this  automatically.  Then 
I  repeated  the  stimulus  and  said  'intermediate'  verbally.  Some  kind  of 
consciousness  that  meant  'principal  colors'.     I  did  not  say  'principal.' 

G.  Family :  individual :  tree :  fruit.  Verbal  completion  in  background. 
Said  'group  to  one.'  When  you  said  'tree,'  I  said  'tree  is  individual  itself.' 
This  was  in  the  background.  Articulated  'Tree  produces  what?  Fruit.' 
There  was  no  association  ready,  and  I  had  to  make  one  by  making  a  new 
sentence.     'Species'  also  present  verbally.     Verbal  part  in  background. 

Sometimes  the  relation  is  represented  visually,  as  in  Wood- 
worth's  third  division. 

F.  Book:  chair  ::  table:  floor.  I  saw  a  chair  with  a  book  on  it.  Visual 
image  of  a  table  on  the  floor.     The  relation  was  kinaesthetic  and  visual. 

y.  Man:  boy  ::  woman:  girl.  Visual  image  of  a  small  boy  in  a  blue 
sailor  suit.  Meaning  of  'woman'  carried  by  a  vague  image  of  a  red  plaid 
skirt.  Then  a  blank.  I  said  'girl,'  but  I  don't  know  why.  I  was  surprised 
when  I  said  it.  This  was  vaguely  organic,  and  a  little  gasp  occurred.  The 
relation  between  man  and  boy  was  one  of  height, — a  tall  and  a  short  line 
side  by  side.  Just  after  I  finished,  I  thought  perhaps  I  should  have  said 
'little  girl.'     This  was  vaguely  verbal. 

By  far  the  larger  number  of  relations  which  were  carried 
in  sensory  terms  could  not  be  put  strictly  in  either  of  these 


244  CLARKE 

classes,  but  were  combinations  of  images  from  different  sense 
departments.  Organic  sensations  were  prominent  for  all  the 
observers. 

V.  London:  England  ::  Paris:  France.  I  did  not  think  of  London  till 
I  heard  'England.'  Vague  image  of  the  map  of  England  with  a  black 
dot  standing  for  London.  Kinaesthetic  image  of  drawing  a  circle  and 
putting  a  dot  inside  it.  At  'Paris'  I  had  a  kinaesthetic  image  of  making  a 
dot,  and  visual  image  of  a  black  dot.  Without  any  effort  I  said  'France,' 
and  had  image  of  drawing  a  circle  around  the  dot.  Very  pleasant.  The 
pleasantness  included  a  kind  of  balance  which  was  vaguely  visual  and 
organic.  At  'London'  image  of  a  capital  L,  and  at  'France'  image  of  a 
capital   F. 

F.  To:  fro  ::  back:  front.  Repeated  the  stimulus  twice.  Organic  and 
kinaesthetic  images  or  sensations  of  swinging  arm  in  a  circle  while  saying 
'to  and  fro.'  I  marked  the  rhythm  with  words  and  breathing.  Very 
vague  visual  images.  A  thin  black  thing  which  was  moving  like  a  pendu- 
lum. I  could  not  see  the  whole  pendulum,  but  only  the  arc  that  it  described. 
Organic  sensations  with  the  pendulum.  Suddenly  'back'  coincided  with 
one  swing,  and  'front'  with  the  return  swing.  The  visual  part  was  six 
or  eight  feet  off  and  below  me. 

G.  /;  we  ::  he:  they.  This  was  kinaesthetic.  I  put  'I'  in  the  first  line, 
'we'  in  the  fourth,  he  (he,  she,  it)  in  the  third,  and  'they'  in  the  sixth. 
This  was  the  declension  in  an  old  grammar.  I  did  not  see  'he,  she,  it,' 
but  the  line  was  long  kinaesthetically,  while  'I'  and  'they'  were  dots. 

Woodworth's  fourth  class,  of  cases  in  which  the  relation  was 
present  in  consciousness  but  not  analysable  into  sensory  or 
affective  terms, — the  class  upon  which  he  bases  his  whole  con- 
clusion,— reduces,  in  our  own  experiments,  to  two  equivocal 
instances. 

G.  Color:  brightness  ::  tone:  intensity.  (G  thought  of  intensity  as  an 
attribute.)  Short  period  of  confusion,  which  was  muscular  contraction. 
I  repeated  verbal  stimulus  and  completed  it  almost  automatically.  Back- 
ground filled  with  vague  memories,  in  visual  images  and  eye-movement, 
of  experiments  and  discussions  on  brightness  and  intensity, 

F.  London:  England ::  Paris:  France.  I  fell  into  the  swing  as  soon 
as  you  started  to  read.  It  was  familiar.  This  was  a  real  change  of  muscular 
attitude,  a  sort  of  relaxation. 

Woodworth's  first  class,  in  which  the  relation  is  not  present 
in  consciousness  in  any  form,  is  abundantly  illustrated. 

G.  Father:  son :  :  mother:  daughter.  Purely  verbal.  The  vaguest  ar- 
ticulation of  'mother.'     No  relation  about  it. 

G.  Red:  blue  :  :  green:  yellow.  No  relation.  I  was  listening  to  the 
colors,  and  added  the  one  you  did  not  name,  as  I  should  have  been  ready 
to  mention  any  one. 

F.  Is:  are  ::  was:  been.  Verbal  rhythm.  I  used  to  say  'is,  are,  was, 
been.'     There  was  just  the  swing. 

F.     Boy:  man  ::  girl:  woman.     Verbal.     No  image. 

V.  Is:  are::  was  :  (am)  were.  Strong  tendency  to  say 'am,' though  I 
knew  it  wasn't  right.  This  was  kinaesthetic.  When  the  stimulus  was 
repeated,  the  'r'  in  'are'  caused  me  to  say  'were,'  the  two  r's  balanced.  I 
did  not  think  of  the  meaning  till  afterwards. 

These  seemed  to  be  cases  of  mere  association,  in  which  the 
relation  had  no  part.  In  order  to  test  this  conclusion,  the 
method  was  slightly  modified  in  two  ways.     Mingled  with  the 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  245 

other  stimuli  were  proportions  made  of  pairs  of  familiar  ex- 
pressions, in  which  there  was  either  no  relation  or  one  that 
could  be  recognised  only  with  some  ingenuity.  The  question 
implied  was,  whether  these  pairs  would  be  replied  to  as  prompt- 
ly as  the  true  relation  pairs.  Almost  invariably  this  was  the 
case.  The  other  modification  was  the  introduction  of  pro- 
portions in  which  the  relation  was  reversed,  that  is,  in  which 
the  third  term  really  corresponded  with  the  second  and  the 
fourth  (to  be  supplied)  with  the  first.  In  a  few  cases  the  ob- 
server refused  to  react ;  but  this  inhibition  occurred  only  after 
such  a  proportion  had  already  been  given,  and  automatically 
reacted  to.  After  the  reaction,  the  observer  sometimes  saw 
that  the  order  was  wrong,  and  was  therefore  more  careful  the 
next  time.  In  some  instances,  the  change  was  never  dis- 
covered at  all.  The  following  will  illustrate  the  reactions  to 
familiar  phrases. 

V.  Up:  down  ::  out:  in.  I  responded  immediately  without  reason- 
ing, then  wondered  aloud  why  this  was  right.     Felt  tired. 

G.  Loud:  soft  ::  dark:  light.  Almost  reflexly.  A  little  pause  of  hesi- 
tation during  which  I  quickly  went  over  the  whole  again  in  abbreviated 
form.     No  relation  conscious. 

F.  Live:  die  ::  sink:  swim.  Mere  verbal  association.  When  I  stop 
to  think,  there  is  opposition,  but  this  was  not  conscious.  (F.  can  repeat  the 
quotation  from  which  this  proportion  is  .taken,  but  was  not  conscious  of 
it  when  the  reaction  was  made.) 

Some  of  the  wrong  proportions  were  reacted  to  as  follows: 

F.  Father:  mother ::  aunt:  uncle.  Quite  verbal.  I  don't  know  whether 
the  answer  is  right  or  not. 

F.  Day:  night ::  winter:  summer.  It  is  a  muscular  attitude  which 
makes  me  answer.  I  was  set  for  the  rhythm,  and  reacted  just  as  I  should 
fill  out  an  incomplete  line  of  metre.  The  word  came  up  of  itself;  winter 
and  summer  go  together. 

V.  Day:  night ::  winter:  summer.  I  said  'summer'  because  it  seemed 
to  belong  there.  I  heard  myself  saying  it  before  I  said  it.  Later  had  a 
kinaesthetic  feeling  that  it  was  backwards, — lack  of  balance  and  a  feeling 
of  twisting  around. 

A  few  experiments  were  performed,  with  the  same  obser- 
vers, by  means  of  little  slips  of  colored  paper.  Three  colors 
were  given,  and  a  fourth  was  to  be  added  that  would  have  the 
same  relation  to  the  third  as  the  first  to  the  second.  The 
relations  were  not  complicated  by  the  introduction  of  different 
shapes  and  sizes.  The  method  was  not  promising,  and  was 
soon  discarded.  When  three  of  the  four  principal  colors  of  the 
spectrum  were  given,  the  fourth  was  added  without  any 
'feehng  of  relation.'  It  was  simply  the  'fiUing  out  of  the 
series.'  In  the  remaining  cases,  the  relation  was  represented 
visually,  verbally,  or  kinaesthetically. 

The  next  series  was  intended  to  approach  the  problem  of 
relation  from  a  genetic  standpoint.     The  purpose  was  to 


246  CIvARKE 

establish  some  arbitrary  relation,  and  to  observe  what  took 
place  in  consciousness  as  it  became  more  and  more  familiar. 

The  observer  was  told  that 
S  is  the  cause  of  T 
H"  "  "  "  K 
L  "  "  "  "  M 
The  proportions  then  combined  three  of  the  letters,  in  various  ways,  and 
the  observer  was  asked  to  add  the  fourth  term.  The  association  was 
made  by  G  originally  from  the  written  page.  He  was  given  the  above 
statement  to  read  and  fix  in  mind.  He  disregarded  the  word  'cause'  en- 
tirely, and  remembered  the  letters  as  related  merely  by  spatial  arrangement, 
not  visually,  but  by  eye-movement.  A  movement  of  the  eyes  across  and 
down  must  be  followed  by  another  in  the  same  direction  in  order  to  make 
the  relation  correct.  When  the  proportion  H :  M : :  S :  ?  was  given,  G  reacted 
with  K  because  this  reply  made  two  parallel  diagonal  lines.  Although  the 
proportions  were  too  easy  at  the  start  to  give  the  method  a  fair  trial,  the 
76  experiments  done  with  G  show  some  effect  of  habit.  At  the  beginning, 
the  whole  relation  was  carried  by  eye-movement;  it  was  movements  that 
were  equated  and  that  therefore  represented  the  relation.  Verbal  ideas 
sometimes  entered  in.  As  early  as  the  fourth  experiment,  H:  K  ::  L:  M, 
G  reports:  'I  did  not  jump  to  L.  I  went  down  from  K  to  M.'  Abbrevia- 
tion is  beginning.  From  the  twenty-eighth,  the  verbal  reactions  are  nu- 
merous, though  the  eye-movement  continues  to  some  extent  to  the  end. 
When  H:  K  ::  L:?  was  given,  G  simply  went  down  the  alphabet  automat- 
ically. 

In  order  to  prevent  this  unforeseen  possibility,  different  letters  were  given 
to    F. 

D  is  the  cause  of  E 

R   "     "        "    "  L 

tr\      n        II  II       11    /~v 

The  statement  was  read  to  him,  in  order  that  a  merely  spatial  relation 
might  not  fix  itself  in  the  mind.  Nevertheless,  this  result  appeared,  to 
a  certain  extent;  the  causal  idea  was  entirely  forgotten.  Two  letters  of 
a  pair  were  associated,  and  at  first  F  did  not  distinguish  the  first  from  the 
second.  If  both  numbers  of  one  pair  were  given  and  only  one  of  another, 
the  missing  term  was  immediately  added.  F  also  tended  to  read  meanings 
into  the  letters.  These  methods  of  association  made  the  reaction  so  easy 
that  it  was  automatic,  and  conscious  content  was  lacking  from  the  first.  F 
explained  his  reactions  by  saying  that  they  'just  go  together.'  As  the  series 
offered  no  chance  for  improvement,  it  was  abandoned  after  the  nineteenth 
experiment. 

The  same  letters  were  read  to  V.  She  visualised  the  top  pair  with 
'cause'  written  between  them,  and  the  others  below  with  ditto  marks 
under  the  'cause,'  though  she  had  not  seen  the  paper.  Sometimes  the  re- 
actions were  merely  read  off  from  this  image.  The  fourth  term  was  often 
supplied  because  it  went  with  the  third;  there  was  no  reference  to  what  had 
come  before.     Only  fifteen  tests  were  given. 

In  all  the  experiments  by  this  method,  there  is  not  a  single 
case  of  a  relation  being  consciously  carried  in  non-sensory 
terms.  Either  it  is  definitely  describable,  or  it  is  not  conscious 
at  all  and  the  reaction  is  automatic.  In  the  latter  case  it 
was  usually  immaterial  to  the  observer  whether  the  answer 
was  right  or  not.  Sometimes  it  was  worked  out  carefully 
afterwards,  and  judged  as  to  correctness;  but  in  that  event 
the  relation  was  represented  in  some  form  of  imagery. 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES  247 

As  this  method  had  proved  too  easy  to  exhibit  the  automatic 
reaction  in  process  of  development,  another  was  devised. 
This  time  the  stimuU  belonged  to  three  sense-orders,  auditory, 
tactual  and  kinaesthetic.  The  observer  sat  with  his  right 
arm  on  a  Sanford  elbow-board,  and  the  index-finger  of  his 
left  hand  on  a  small  lever  which  moved  up  and  down.  The 
tactual  stimuli,  large  and  small  pieces  of  sand-paper  and  of 
felt,  were  presented  by  being  laid  under  the  fingers  of  the  right 
hand  on  the  arm  rest.  A  low  and  a  high  tuning-fork  stood 
near  by.  The  observer  was  told  that  the  low  tone  was  to  be 
thought  of  as  large,  the  high  as  small,  while  each  one  might 
be  either  strong  or  weak.  The  sand-paper  was  intended  to 
represent  strength  or  harshness,  the  felt  weakness  or  softness ; 
each  might  be  either  large  and  small.  The  arm  movement  was 
large,  the  linger  movement  small,  while  each  might  be  either 
strong  or  weak.  This  arrangement  was,  no  doubt,  arbitrary, 
but  it  was  arbitrary  for  a  purpose.  Easily  perceived  re- 
lationships had  proved  inadequate,  and  it  was  hoped  that  the 
artificiality  of  these  new  ones  would  make  the  reactions  suffi- 
ciently difficult.  Only  G  and  V  took  part  in  this  series  of 
experiments. 

G's  reactions  were  at  first  almost  without  exception  mediated  by  verbal 
expressions  of  the  relation.  He  would  say  'loud-soft'  or  'strong- weak,' 
and  the  reaction  followed.  The  verbal  ideas  were  sometimes  more  com- 
plex than  this,  or  the  relation  was  partly  kinaesthetic.  It  will  give  some 
idea  of  the  progress  of  mechanisation  if  we  fractionate  the  results.  In  the 
first  24  experiments  there  is  not  a  single  automatic  reaction.  The  relations 
are  carried  in  verbal  terms.  From  the  twenty-fifth  to  the  forty-eighth 
there  are  1 1  automatic  reactions,  in  which  the  relation  was  not  conscious. 
From  the  forty-ninth  to  the  seventy-second  there  are  13,  and  from  the  seven- 
ty-third to  the  ninety-sixth,  17.  The  reactions  are  most  often  automatic 
when  the  three  given  stimuli  are  from  the  same  sense  department.  There 
were  only  four  possible  variations  in  one  sense  department,  and  when 
three  were  given  the  fourth  followed  automatically.  The  series  was 
carried  so  far,  however,  that  even  proportions  between  stimuli  of  different 
sense  orders  were  sometimes  reacted  to  automatically. 

V  made  40  experiments  by  this  method  but  with  no  new  result.  The 
relation  was  usually  verbal,  once  or  twice  kinaesthetic,  and  several  times 
purely  associative. 

When  we  consider  all  of  the  relation  experiments,  we  see 
that  by  far  the  larger  part  of  the  reactions  were  accompanied 
by  some  'consciousness  of  relation*  in  terms  of  sensory  or 
verbal  images,  and  that  the  rest  prove  to  be  mere  associations 
or  else  tendencies  to  fill  out  a  group,  by  adding  the  inevitable 
fourth  member,  without  any  consciousness.  Woodworth's 
fourth  group  is  not  paralleled  in  our  experiments. 

C0NCI.US10N 

In  conclusion,  we  may  attempt  to  sum  up  the  arguments 
which  make  against  the  simplicity  of  the  'conscious  attitude' 


248  CLARKE 

and  the  existence  of  'imageless'  thought.  These  may  be 
divided  into  the  negative  or  critical,  and  the  positive  or  those 
based  upon  our  own  experimental  work.  Under  the  former 
head  the  following  may  be  noted: 

(i)  Having  been  named  and  negatively  defined  by  Marbe, 
the  Bewusstseinslagen  are  henceforth  taken  for  granted. 
They  are  reported,  along  with  sensation  and  image  and  feeling, 
in  the  analyses  of  complex  states,  and  little  or  no  attempt  is 
made  to  analyse  them. 

(2)  Nevertheless,  they  are,  on  several  occasions,  at  least 
partly  analysed,  as  witness  Orth's  account  of  doubt,  Messer's 
and  Watt's  of  trying  to  remember,  and  the  discussions  of  the 
Aufgabe,  which  show  it  to  be  an  attitude  derived  by  practice 
from  an  analy sable  situation. 

(3)  The  cases  in  which  thought-elements  or  imageless 
thoughts  or  attitudes  are  reported  as  the  'consciousness  that,' 
etc.,  are  cases  not  of  psychological  description,  but  of  the 
translation  into  words  of  the  meaning  of  a  conscious  state 
(Kundgabe). 

(4)  Our  own  conclusions  are  based  upon  the  introspec- 
tions of  seven  observers,  of  whom  all  but  one  had  had  several 
years  of  psychological  training.  These  observers  were  not 
all  of  one  type,  but  ranged  from  the  strongly  visual  to  one 
who  almost  never  has  visual  images,  and  from  those  who  al- 
most never  report  kinaesthetic  sensations  to  those  for  whom 
these  sensations  and  images  are  essential.  These  seven 
persons  wrote,  altogether,  somewhat  more  than  fourteen 
hundred  introspections.  In  the  series  with  point-letters 
alone,  over  four  hundred  cases  of  attitude  are  specifically 
reported, —  aside  from  recognition,  which  is  assumed  to  be 
present  in  all  observations.  Of  these  four  hundred,  about 
one  fourth  were  merely  named,  while  the  remaining  three 
fourths  are  more  or  less  completely  analysed.  When  the 
attitudes  occur  often  enough  to  give  a  basis  for  generalisation, 
there  is  striking  agreement  between  different  observers  and 
for  the  same  observer  at  different  times,  and  we  are  thus  able 
to  pick  out,  with  a  fair  degree  of  assurance,  the  pattern  of  con- 
sciousness which  represents  a  given  situation.  The  introspec- 
tions of  any  one  observer  show  different  stages  of  clearness 
and  intensity  of  imagery,  which  allow  us  to  connect,  by  a 
graded  series  of  intermediate  steps,  a  complex  of  vivid  and 
explicit  imagery  with  a  vague  and  condensed  consciousness 
which  we  suppose  to  represent  what  is  called  'imageless' 
thought.  The  Aufgabe,  recognition,  and  the  feeling  of  relation 
are  shown  to  be  capable  of  development,  by  a  process  of 
change  and  mechanisation,  from  states  which  are  obviously 
complex  and  imaginal. 


CONSCIOUS  ATTITUDES 


249 


It  may,  we  think,  be  fairly  said  that  the  attitudes  here  ana- 
lysed are  typical  of  the  whole  class ;  they  are  certainly  among 
those  most  often  mentioned  by  writers  on  the  subject.  But, 
if  part  of  the  class  can  be  reduced  to  simpler  terms  so  often,  so 
definitely,  and  so  uniformly,  there  is  every  reason  to  believe 
that  the  rest  will  show  themselves  similarly  complex,  when  they 
are  subjected  to  the  same  analytical  treatment.  The  general 
conclusion  to  be  drawn  from  the  sum  of  our  results  is  that 
conscious  attitudes  can  be  analysed  into  sensations  and 
images  and  feelings,  or  traced  genetically  to  such  analysable 
complexes,  and  therefore  do  not  warrant  the  proposal  of  an 
additional  conscious  element. 


JOURNAI, — 8 


AN    EXPERIMENTAL    DEMONSTRATION    OF    THE 

BINAURAL    RATIO    AS   A,^ -FACTOR    IN    AUDITORY 

LOCALIZATION 


By  C.  E.  FerrEE  and  Ruth  Goli^ins,  Bryn  Mawr  College 


TABLE  OF  CONTENTS 

I.     Historical  250 

II.     Experimental  271 

A.  The  Demonstration  of -the  Binam-al  Ratio  as  a  Factor        271 

(a)  Lines  of  Argument  271 
(i)  Observers  having  a  natural  difference  in  sensitivity 

for  the  two  ears  show  a  constant  tendency  to  dis- 
place the  sound  in  the  direction  of  the  stronger 
ear;  and,  conversely,  observers  without  this  differ- 
ence show  no  tendency  toward  right  or  left  dis- 
placement 

(2)  Changes  in  the  ratio  of  sensitivity  produced  by  plug- 

ging either  of  the  two  ears  are  followed  by  corres- 
ponding displacements  of  the  sound  toward  the 
stronger  ear 

(3)  A  natural  tendency  toward  right  or  left  displace- 

ment can  be  corrected  by  making  the  proper 
change  in  the  ratio  of  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears 

(b)  Description  of  Method  and  Apparatus  273 

(c)  Residts  276 

B.  The  Relative  Importance  of  Intensity  and  Timbre  as  Fac- 
tors in  Localization  282 

C.  Individual  Preferences^  and  Their  Explanations  for  the 
Observers  Used  290 

D.  The  Question  of  Changes  in  these  Preferences  with  Lapse  of 
Time^  293 

III.    Summary  of  Results  294 

I.  Historical 

It  is  difficult  to  ascertain  just  when  the  belief  in  the  binaural 
ratio  as  a  factor  in  auditory  localization  came  into  vogue. 
The  experimental  arguments  offered  in  favor  of  this  belief, 
however,  are  not  so  hard  to  trace.  They  began  with  the 
tuning-fork  experiment  of   Weber,''  and  have  been  continued 

^Vide  von  Kries:  Ueber  das  Erkennen  der  Schallrichtung,  Zeitschr.  f. 
Psychol,  u.  Physiol.,  I,  1890,  236-251;  and  Dimlap:  The  Localization  of 
Sounds,  Psychol.  Rev.,  Monog.  Suppl.,  Vol.  X,  No.  i,  1908,  pp.  5,  8,  15. 

^Vide  Dimlap:  Op.  ciL,  pp.  5,  10,  and  15. 

2 Weber:  Programm.  Coll.,  4  2.  This  experiment  was  not  offered  by 
Weber  as  an  argument  for  the  binaural  ratio  of  intensity,  although  it  has 
frequently  been  cited  as  furnishing  such  argument. 


AUDITORY  LOCAUZATION  25 1 

by  the  work  of  Fechner,^  Rayleigh,^  Politzer,'  von  Kries 
and  Auerbach/  Tarchanoff/  Steinhauser/  Urbantschitsch/ 
Thompson,'  KesseP  von  Bezold/"  Schaefer^S  Smith,"  Bloch," 
Pierce/*  Matsumoto,^^  Melati,^'Stenger,"  Starch,"  and  Wilson 
and  Myers." 

A  r^sum^  of  this  work  down  to  190 1  has  been  given  by  Pierce 
It  will  be  sufficient,  therefore,  for  the  purpose  of  this  report 
to  continue  the  r^sum^  up  to  the  present  time,  and  to  make  a 
brief  statement  of  all  the  lines  of  argument  that  have  been 
advanced  for  the  binaural  ratio  as  a  factor  in  auditory  locali- 
zation. 

^Fechner,  G.  T. :  Ueher  einige  Verhdltnisse  des  binocular  en  Sehens  (Chap* 
XVIII,  Ueber  einige  Verhdltnisse  des  zweiseitigen  Hdrens).  Abhdlg.  d' 
Sachs.  Gesellsch.  d.  Wiss.     (Mathemat.  Klasse  V),  Bd.  V,  S.  543.     i86i* 

'Rayleigh,  Lord:  Our  Perception  of  the  Direction  of  a  Source  of  Sound, 
Trans.     Mus.  Ass.  1876;  Acoustical  Observations,  Philos.  Mag.  (5)  Vol.  Ill, 

1877.  p.  456. 
'Politzer:  Studien  iiber  die  Paracusis  Loci,  Archiv.  f.  Ohrenheilk.  1876, 

XI.  231. 

*von  Kries  u.  Auerbach:  Die  Zeitdauer  einfachster  psychischer  Vorgange, 
Archiv  fiir  Anatom.  u.  Physiol,,  1877,  321-337. 

^Tarchanoff:  Das  Telephon  als  Anzeiger  der  N erven  und  Muskelstrome 
beim  Menschen  und  den  Thieren,   St.  Petersburger  med.    Wochenschrift, 

1878,  No.  43,  pp.  353-354. 
®Steinhauser,  Anton:  The  Theory  of  Binaural  Audition:  A  Contribution 

to  the  Theory  of  Sound,  Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  5,  Vol.  VII,  1879,  pp.  261-274. 

'Urbantschitsch,  V. :  Zur  Lehre  von  der  Schallempfindung,  Pfiuger's  Archiv, 
XXIV,  1 88 1,  579. 

^Sylvanus  Thompson:  The  Pseudophone,  Philos.  Mag.  (5),  VIII,  1879, 
385-390.  On  the  Function  of  the  Two  Ears  in  the  Perception  of  Space,  Philos. 
Mag.  (5),  XIII,  1882,  406-416. 

^Kessel :  Ueber  die  Functionl  der  Ohrmuschel,  bei  den  Raumwahrnehmungen, 
Archiv  f.  Ohrenheilk.  XVIII,  1882,  p.  120. 

*°W.  von  Bezold:  Urteilstduschung  nach  Beseitigung  einseitiger  Hartr 
hdrigkeit,  Zeitschr.  f.  Psychol,  u.  Physiol.,  1890,  pp.  486-488. 

"Schaefer,  K.  L. :  Lokalisation  diotischen  Wahrnehmungen,  Zeitschr.  f . 
Psychol,  u.  Physiol.,  I,  1890,  S.  300-309. 

"Smith,  G. :  How  do  we  Detect  the  Direction  from  which  Sound  Comes? 
Cincin.     Lancet- Clinic,  n.  s.,  XXVIII.  1892,  p.  542. 

^^Bloch:  Das  binaurale  Hdren,Wiesha.de.n,  1893,  pp.  61 ;  Zeitschr.  f.  Ohren- 
heilk., XXIV,  1893,  pp.  25-86. 

"Pierce,  A.  H. :  Studies  in  Space  Perception,  1901. 

^^Matsumoto:  Researches  in  Acoustic  SpCLce,  Studies  from  the  Yale  Psy- 
chological Laboratory,  V,   1897. 

^^Melati,  Gino:  Ueber  binaurales  Hdren,  Philos.  Studien,  XVII  (3),  1901, 
431-461. 

^^Stenger:  Zur  Theorie  des  binauralen  Hdrens,  Zeitschr.  f.  Ohrenheilk., 
XLVIII,  219. 

^^Starch,  D. :  Perimetry  of  the  Localization  of  Sound,  Psychol.  Rev.,  Monog. 
Suppl.  (Univ.  of  Iowa  Studies),  Vol.  IV,  No.  28,  1905,  pp.  1-45;  ibid.. 
Vol.  IX,  No.  2,  1908,  pp.  1-55 
_  "Wilson,  H.  A.  and  Myers,  C.  S. :  The  Influence  of  Binaural  Phase  Differ- 
IBj  ences  in  the  Localizations  of  Sound,  The  British  Journal  of  Psychology, 
■■i  1908,  II,  pp,  362-386. 

r 


252  FERREE  AND  COLUNS 

Since  1901  reports  of  work  on  the  general  subject  of  auditory 
localization  have  been  published  by  the  following  investiga- 
tors: Lobsien,^  Angell  and  Fite,^  Melati,^  Gamble,*  Angell/ 
Seashore/  Bing/  Urbantschitsch/  Stenger/  Bard/°  Starch," 
Rayleigh/^  More  and  Fry,"  Bowlker/*  Wilson  and  Myers," 
and  Hicks  and  Washburn. ^^ 

Of  these  only  six  bear  with  sufficient  directness  and  defi- 
niteness  upon  the  subject  of  this  report  to  warrant  consider- 
ation here;  namely,  the  papers  of  Angell,  Angell  and  Fite, 
Starch,  Rayleigh,  More  and  Fry,  and  Wilson  and  Myers. 

In  1903  Angell,"  in  furtherance  of  the  suggestions  and  ob- 

^Lobsien,  Marx:  Ueher  binaurales  Hdren  und  auffdllige  Schalllocalisation. 
Zeitschr.  f.  Psychol,  u.  Physiol.,  XXIV,  1900,  S.  285-295. 

^Angell,  J.  R.  and  Fite,  W:  The  Monaural  Localization  of  Sound,  Psychol. 
Rev.,  VIII,  1901,  pp.  225-247;  Further  Observations  on  the  Monaural  Lo- 
calization of  Sound,  ibid.,  449-459. 

'Melati,  Gino:  Op.  cit. 

^Gamble,  E.  A.  McC. :  The  Perception  of  Sound  Direction  as  a  Conscious 
Process,  Psychol.  Rev.,  IX,  1902,  357-373;  Intensity  as  a  Criterion  in 
Estimating  the  Distance  of  Sounds,  Psychol.  Rev.,  XVI,  1909,  416-426. 

^Angell,  J.  R. :  .4  Preliminary  Study  of  the  Significance  of  Partial  Tones 
in  the  Localization  of  Sound,  Psychol.  Rev.,  X,  1903,  pp.  1-15. 

^Seashore,  C.  E.:  Localization  of  Sound  in  the  Median  Plane,  Univ.  of 
Iowa  Studies  in  Psychology,  1899,  11,  46-54;  A  Sound  Perimeter,  Psychol. 
Rev.,  X,  1903,  pp.  64-68;  The  Localization  of  Sound,  Middletonian,  1903 
(Dec),  pp.  15. 

'Bing,  A. :  Bemerkungen  zur  Lokalisation  der  Tonwahrnehmung,  Monatschr. 
f.  Ohrenheilk.,  XXXVIII,  1904,  220-225. 

^Urbantschitsch,  V.:  Ueber  die  Lokalisation  der  Tonempfindungen, 
Archiv.    f.  d.  ges.  Physiol.  (Pfliiger's),  CI,  1904,  154-182. 

^Stenger:  Op.  cit. 

i°Bard,  L. :  L' orientation  auditive  angulaire,  Archiv.  gen.  de  Med.,  CXCV, 
1905,  257. 

"Starch,  D.:  Op.  cit. 

"Rayleigh,  Lord:  On  our  Perception  of  Sound  Direction,  Philos.  Mag., 
XIII,  Ser.  6,  1907,  pp.  214-232;  Acoustical  Notes,  Sensations  of  Right  and 
Left  from  a  Revolving  Magnet  and  Telephones,  ibid.,  pp.  316-319;  Acoustical 
Notes,  Discrimination  between  Sounds  Directly  in  Front  and  Directly  Behind 
the  Observer,  ibid.,  XVI,  1908,  pp.  240-241. 

"More,  L.  T.  and  Fry,  H.  S. :  On  the  Appreciation  of  Phase  of  Sound  Waves, 
Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  6,  XVII,  1907,  pp.  452-459. 

**Bowlker,  T.  J. :  On  the  Factors  Serving  to  Determine  the  Direction  of  Sound, 
Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  6,  XV,  1908,  pp.  318-332. 

"Wilson,  H.  A.  and  Myers,  C.  S. :  The  Influence  of  Binaural  Phase  Differ- 
ences on  the  Localization  of  Sounds,  British  Journal  of  Psychology,  II,  1908, 
pp.  362-384. 

^^Hicks,  J.  and  Washburn,  M.  F. :  A  Suggestion  towards  a  Study  of  the 
Perception  of  Sound  Movement,  Am.  Jour,  of  Psychol.,  XIX,  1908,  247-248. 

"Angell.  J.  R.:  Op.  €it. 


AUDITORY  LOCALIZATION  253 

servations  made  by  Rayleigh/  Thompson,^  Mach,'  and  Pierce,* 
undertook  a  systematic  investigation  of  the  influence  of  timbre 
on  the  localization  of  sound.  Careful  observations,  in  the 
open  air,  were  made  of  the  accuracy  of  the  localization  of  sim- 
ple tones  and  of  clangs.  The  sounds  employed  were  a  tuning- 
fork  of  1,000  vibrations  per  second,  a  stopped  pipe  of  768  vibra- 
tions, a  reed  pipe  of  768  vibrations,  a  bell  with  a  fundamental 
tone  of  2,048  vibrations,  and  the  noise  made  by  a  telegraph 
sounder.  An  interpretation  of  his  results,  based  on  the  relative 
accuracy  of  localization  at  different  points  in  the  vertical,  hori- 
zontal, and  transverse  planes,  led  him  to  conclude  that  intensity 
differences  alone  are  sufficient  to  enable  our  confident  and  cor- 
rect assignment  of  the  sound  (even  in  case  of  pure  tones)  to  the 
median  plane,  the  lateral  hemisphere,  and,  in  a  general  way, 
to  the  transverse  plane.  But  accuracy  as  regards  altitude  in 
the  transverse  plane,  or  in  the  region  between  the  transverse 
plane  and  the  median  plane,  is  apparently  dependent  upon  the 
modifications  of  timbre  which  complex  sounds,  coming  from 
different  directions,  undergo,  through  changes  in  the  intensity 
of  their  partials.  Considered  with  reference  to  its  bearing 
on  the  binaural  ratio,  the  paper,  in  its  general  tone,  is  against 
the  ascription  of  too  much  importance  to  this  ratio  as  a  factor 
in  localization.  This  position  is  further  supported  by  ex- 
periments conducted  by  Angell  and  Fite.^ 

The  object  of  these  experiments  was  to  determine  the  lo- 
calizing power  of  subjects  who  were  deaf  in  one  ear.  In  the 
first  series,  only  one  subject  was  experimented  upon;  in  the 
second,  several  were  used  differing  in  age  and  varying  in  the 
length  of  their  period  of  deafness  from  one  to  thirty  years. 
The  results  of  the  experiments  are  as  follows,  (i)  These 
subjects,  especially  when  practiced,  are  not  greatly  inferior, 
in  their  power  to  localize,  to  subjects  of  normal  hearing.^     Dis- 

iRayleigh,  Lord:  Transactions  of  the  Musical  Association,  1876;  and 
Philos.  Mag.  (5),  III,  1877,  p.  456. 

2Philos.  Mag.,  XIII,  1882,  p.  415;  ibid.  (5),  VIII,  1879,  pp.  385-390. 

'Mach,  E. :  Bemerkungen  uber  die  Function  der  Ohrmuschel,  Archiv  f . 
Ohrenheilkunde,  IX,  1875,  p.  72;  Bemerkungen  ilher  den  Raumsinn  des 
Ohres,  Poggen.  Annalen,  CXXVI,  1865,  p.  331;  Ueher  einige  der  physiolo- 
gischen  Akustik  angehorigen  ErscJieinungen,  Sitzungsberichte  der  Wiener 
Akademie,  Abth.  2,  L.,  1864.  pp.  342-363;  Zur  Theorie  des  Gehor organs, 
ibid.,  Abth.  2,  XLVIII,  1863,  pp.  283-300. 

*0p.  ciL,  pp.  92  and  163. 

^Angell,  J.  R.  and  Kite,  W. :  Op.  cit. 

•^It  is  assumed  here  that  these  writers  would  exercise  caution  in  drawing 
conclusions,  with  regard  to  the  relative  importance  of  timbre  and  the  bi- 
naural ratio  of  intensity  in  normal  subjects,  from  the  localizing  power  shown 
by  subjects  who  have  been  deaf  in  one  ear  for  a  number  of  years;  because 
the  latter,  deprived  of  the  use  of  the  binaural  ratio  as  an  aid  to  localization, 
would  doubtless  develop  a  discrimination  of  direction  based  upon  diflference 


254  FKRREE  AND  COLUNS 

tinctions  between  front  and  back  may  be  even  sharper  for 
these  subjects  than  for  those  of  normal  hearing.  The  locaHza- 
tion,  however,  is  generally  not  so  prompt  for  them  as  for  the 
normal  subject,  nor  are  these  subjects  so  accurate  in  dealing 
with  unfamiliar  sounds.  (2)  Complex  sounds,  especially 
those  in  which  qualitative  differences  can  be  introspectively 
distinguished  for  the  different  positions,  are  localized  best. 
The  more  nearly  the  sound  approximates  a  simple  tone,  the 
more  inaccurate  is  the  localization.  "Genuinely  pure  tones 
are  essentially  unlocalizable."  (3)  There  is  a  marked  in- 
crease in  accuracy  with  practice.  The  accuracy  of  the  prac- 
ticed monaural  subject,  for  example,  was  found  to  compare 
very  favorably  with  that  of  the  unpracticed  normal  subject. 
(4)  Accuracy  was  also  observed  to  sustain  a  close  relation  to 
the  length  of  time  the  defect  had  existed,  and  to  the  age  at 
which  it  began.  For  example,  subjects  of  advanced  age  who 
had  recently  become  deaf  showed  much  poorer  ability  to 
localize  than  younger  subjects  who  had  been  deaf  for  a  num- 
ber  of  years. 

Working  in  1905  and  again  in  1908,  Starch^  carried  out  an 
extended  series  of  experiments  on  the  localization  of  simple 
tones  and  clangs.  Both  monaural  and  binaural  hearing  were 
investigated.  In  the  experiments  with  clangs,  a  singing  flame, 
a  Galton  whistle  of  10,000,  20,000,  and  30,000  vibrations,  the 
human  voice,  an  electric  hammer,  a  wooden  clapper,  and  a 
whiff  of  air  were  used  as  the  sources  of  sound.  In  the  experi- 
ments with  simple  tones,  a  tuning-fork  of  100  vibrations  per 
second  was  used.  In  the  latter  experiments,  tests  were  made 
at  different  points  in  the  different  planes  of  direction,  (a)  of 
the  accuracy  of  localization,  (b)  of  the  size  of  the  j.  n.  d.  of 
direction,  (c)  of  the  limen  and  j.  n.  d.  of  intensity,  and  (d)  of 
the  j.  n.  d.  of  pitch.  A  number  of  conclusions  were  drawn 
relative  to  intensity  and  timbre  as  factors  in  localization. 

Space  will  be  taken  here  only  for  a  r^sum^  of  the  evidence 
bearing  upon  the  binaural  ratio  as  a  factor  in  normal  hearing, 
and  upon  intensity  difference  as  a  factor  in  monaural  hearing. 
No  new  evidence  is  advanced  in  support  of  the  binaural  ratio, 
the  object  of  the  experiments  apparently  being  a  testing  of 
the  arguments  already  advanced  by  Rayleigh,   Thompson, 

in  timbre,  considerably  beyond  that  possessed  by  the  normal  subject.  This 
supposition  is,  in  fact,  borne  out  by  their  own  results,  which  show  how  poorly 
subjects  recently  deaf  localize  as  compared  with  those  in  whom  the  defect 
had  existed  for  a  nimiber  of  years.  For  example,  Case  F.  {Op.  cit.,  p.  453). 
aged  60  years,  deaf  one  year,  gave  correct  judgments  of  location  in  only 
19.5  per  cent,  of  the  total  number  of  cases;  while  Case  C,  deaf  from  26  to 
30  years,  gave  55  per  cent,  of  the  total  number  correctly. 
^Starch,  D.:  Op.  cit. 


AUDITORY  I.OCAUZATION 


255 


Bloch,  and  others.  Starch  finds  these  arguments  confirmed  by 
his  own  results.  The  arguments  are:  (a)  the  presence  of 
front-back  confusion,  and  its  special  case,  the  difficulty  of 
median  plane  localizations;  (b)  the  inferiority  of  monaural 
localization ;  and  (c)  the  occurrence  of  the  greatest  accuracy  of 
localization  at  points  where  slight  changes  in  the  binaural 
ratio  are  most  readily  perceived,  i.  e.,  in  front  and  back 
near  the  median  plane,  and  the  poorest  where  these  changes 
are  least  readily  perceived,  i.  e.,  at  the  sides  near  the  aural 
axis.  Starch  disagrees  with  Angell  as  to  the  factors  in  mo- 
naural localization.  He  maintains  that,  in  addition  to  changes 
in  the  quality  of  a  sound  when  it  comes  from  different  direc- 
tions, there  are  systematic  changes  in  intensity,  which  serve 
as  a  localizing  clue.^  The  following  evidence  is  given  for 
systematic  changes  in  intensity:  (i)  the  limen  for  intensity, 
which  is  lowest  in  the  region  of  the  aural  axis,  and  highest  in 
front  and  back;  (2)  the  observers'  introspections  with  supra- 
liminal sounds;  (3)  the  distance  tests,  which  showed  that  a 
sound  is  estimated  to  be  nearest  in  the  region  of  the  aural 
axis.  That  these  changes  of  intensive  serve  as  a  localizing 
clue  is  attested  (i)  by  the  introspection  of  the  observers,  and 
(2)  by  the  poor  localization  when  the  intensity  of  the  stimulus 
was  varied  frequently  during  the  course  of  a  series  of  experi- 
ments. The  smaller  j.  n.  d.  of  direction  for  front  and  back,  as 
compared  with  the  region  near  the  aural  axis,^  he  thinks,  how- 
ever, cannot  be  due  to  the  intensity  factor,  for  there  is  no 
corresponding  difference  in  the  intensity  j.  n.  d.'s  in  these 
positions.  He  seems  inclined  to  attribute  this  smaller  j.  n.  d. 
of  direction  in  front  and  back,  at  least  in  the  case  of  his  own 
experiments  with  the  tuning-fork,  to  the  qualitative  factor; 
for  his  results  show  a  smaller  j.  n.  d.  for  pitch  in  front  and  back 
than  in  the  region  of  the  aural  axis.  Starch  interprets  his  re- 
sults as,  on  the  whole,  favoring  the  intensity  theory.  The 
traditional  intensity  theory  is  in  the  main  correct;  but,  in 
order  to  account  for  monaural  localization,  and  localization 
in  the  median  plane  and  the  planes  parallel  to  it,  this  theory 
must  be  supplemented  by  the  quality  and  the  monaural  in- 
tensity factors. 

In  February,  1907,  Rayleigh^  published  an  article  in  which 
he  attempted  to  show  that  the  binaural  ratio  cannot  be 
a  factor  in  the  localization  of  sounds  with  a  vibration  fre- 


^Starch:  Psychol.  Rev.,  Monog.  Suppl.,  No.  IV,  Vol.  VI,  1905,  pp.  11- 
'12;  ibid.,  No.  V,  Vol.  IX,  1908,  pp.  52-53. 

^  Vide  Bloch:  Op.  cit.,  p.  55-58;  Matsumoto:  Op.  cit.,  p.  65-69. 

•Rayleigh,  Lord:  On  our  Perception  of  Sound  Direction,  Philos.  Mag., 
Ser.  6,  XIII,  1907,  pp.  214-232. 


256  FBRRBE  AND  COLLINS 

quency  of  128  per  second,  or  less.  In  a  previous  article,  pub- 
lished in  1876,^  he  had  shown  by  calculations  relating  to  the 
incidence  of  plane  waves  upon  a  rigid  spherical  obstacle,  that 
a  sound-wave  of  that  vibration-frequency  travelling  in  the 
line  of  the  aural  axis  could  not  differ  in  intensity  at  the  orifices 
of  the  two  ears  by  as  much  as  one  per  cent,  of  its  total  intensity. 
It  is  difficult  for  him  to  see  how  so  small  a  difference  could  play 
a  very  important  part  in  localization;  yet  he  finds,  at  least 
within  the  limitations  of  his  somewhat  rough  tests,  that  the 
tones  of  forks  of  128  and  96  vibrations  per  second  are  localized 
as  accurately  as  those  of  higher  frequency.  He  infers,  there- 
fore, that  there  must  be  some  other  localizing  clue  for  tones 
of  low  pitch.  The  only  alternative  to  the  intensity  factor, 
he  thinks,  is  a  direct  recognition  of  phase  differences  by  the 
auditory  organ.^ 

He  discusses  phase  difference  in  its  relation  to  localization 
as  follows.  When  the  stimulus  is  at  one  side,  in  the  line  of  the 
aural  axis,  the  opposite  ear  is  "roughly  about  one  foot" 
(measured  on  the  circumference  of  the  head)  farther  from  the 
stimulus  than  the  nearer  ear.  For  a  fork  of  128  vibrations 
per  second,  this  would  make  the  phase  difference  between  the 
ears  about  Vs  period;  for  a  fork  of  256  vibrations,  about  J^ 
period ;  for  a  fork  of  5 1 2  vibrations,  about  3^  period ;  and  for 
a  fork  of  1,024  vibrations,  about  a  whole  period.  "Now  it  is 
certain,"  he  says,  "that  a  phase  relationship  of  J^  period 
furnishes  no  material  for  a  decision  that  the  source  of  sound 
is  on  the  right  rather  than  on  the  left,  seeing  that  there  is  no 
difference  between  a  retardation  and  an  acceleration  of  }/2 
period.  It  is  even  more  evident  that  a  retardation  of  a  whole 
period  or  any  number  of  whole  periods  would  be  of  no  avail." 

Having  shown  that  sounds  of  128  vibrations  or  less  per 
second  reach  the  ears  in  a  difference  of  phase  which  a  priori 
might  be  considered  recognizable  in  sensation,  Rayleigh  next 
attempts  to  show  that  these  differences  actually  furnish  the 
clue  for  the  localization  of  the  graver  tones.  He  works  with 
two  slowly  beating  tones  of  near  128  vibrations  per  second. 
In  completing  a  cycle  or  beat,  the  phase  differences  of  these 
tones  assume  all  possible  values.  When  the  tones  are  led  to 
the  two  ears  simultaneously,  but  separately,  he  finds  that  in- 
stead of  getting  plainly  recognizable  beats,  as  would  have 
occurred  had  both  the  sound-waves  been  given  to  each  ear,  the 

^Rayleigh,  Lord :  Our  Perception  of  the  Direction  of  a  Source  of  Sound. 
Transactions  of  the  Musical  Association,  1876. 

^The  sound  wave  coming  directly  to  both  ears  from  a  single  source  could 
show  differences  only  in  complexity,  intensity,  and  phase.  The  first  of 
these  differences  is  ruled  out  of  consideration  by  the  use  of  the  tuning-fork ; 
the  second,  by  his  mathematical  calculations. 


AUDITORY  IvOCALIZATlON 


257 


whole  sound  mass  seems  to  be  transferred  alternately  from  one 
side  to  the  other.  In  order  to  interpret  these  results,  he  con- 
ducted a  second  series  of  experiments.  The  following  results 
were  obtained,  (i)  It  was  shown  that  the  transference  of 
the  sound  from  one  side  to  the  other  came  directly  after  ("fol- 
lowed") the  maxima  and  minima  of  sound  as  heard  by  a 
second  observer,  for  whom  the  beats  were  allowed  to  occur. 
This  established  a  correlation  between  the  maximal  changes 
in  phase  of  the  sound-waves  received  by  the  two  ears  and  the 
phenomenon  of  transfer.  (2)  It  was  found,  in  addition,  that 
when  the  wave  of  greater  frequency  was  received  by  the  right 
ear,  for  instance,  the  transfer  to  right  occurred  directly  after 
agreement  of  phase,  and  the  transfer  to  left  came  directly 
after  the  maximal  opposition  of  phase.  "The  transitions 
between  right  and  left  effects  correspond  to  agreement  and 
opposition  of  phase,  not  usually  recognized.  When  the  vi- 
bration on  the  right  is  the  quicker,  the  sensation  of  right  fol- 
lows agreement  of  phase,  and  (what  is  better  observed)  the 
sensation  of  left  follows  opposition  of  phase."  The  writer  in- 
terprets this  quotation  to  mean  that  the  sound  is  heard  on  the 
right  from  agreement  to  opposition  of  phase,  and  on  the  left 
from  opposition  to  agreement.  Now  a  consideration  of  the 
phase  relationships  of  two  sound-waves  differing  in  frequency 
shows  that  the  wave  of  greater  frequency  leads  in  phase  from 
agreement  to  opposition,  and  the  wave  of  lesser  frequency 
leads  from  opposition  to  agreement.^ 

^The  writer  can  best  show  in  the  following  manner  what  he  conceives 
Rayleigh  to  mean  by  leading  in  phase.  The  vibrating  particles  forming 
each  sound-wave  execute  simple  harmonic  motion.  They  may  thus,  in 
each  case,  be  considered  as  moving  on  the  circumference  of  a  circle  whose 
diameter  is  equal  to  the  amplitude  of  vibration.  For  the  sake  of  ready 
comparison,  their  amplitudes  of  vibration  may  be  assumed  as  equal;  and 
both  may  be  considered  as  moving  on  the  circumference  of  the  same  circle. 


Fig. 


Fig.  2 


but  at  different  rates  of  speed.  Taking  any  two  corresponding  particles 
of  the  two  waves,  he  considers  that  when  the  angle  6  (the  angle  separating 
the  radii  at  the  outer  termini  of  which  the  two  moving  particles  are  located, 
measured  in  the  direction  in  which  the  particles  are  moving)  is  less  than 
180°,  the  particle  moving  at  the  greater  rate  of  speed,  considered  with  ref- 
erence to  the  direction  in  which  both  are  moving,  will  be  ahead  of   the 


258  FERRKE  AND  COLLINS 

Thus  it  can  be  inferred  that  the  sound  was  referred  through- 
out in  these  experiments  to  the  side  receiving  the  wave 
leading  in  phase.  Rayleigh  proposes  to  make  of  this  a  locaHz- 
ing  clue,  and  applies  it  as  a  principle  of  explanation  to  the 
phenomenon  of  localization,  as  ordinarily  observed,  for  all 
tones  of  low  pitch.  For  example,  when  the  source  of  sound 
is  situated  to  the  right  or  left  of  the  median  plane,  the  sensa- 
tion is  referred  to  the  right  or  left,  as  the  case  may  be,  because 
at  any  given  instant  the  wave  acting  upon  the  ear  in  question 
leads  in  phase  the  wave  acting  upon  the  other  ear.  And  when 
the  source  is  in  the  median  plane,  the  sound  is  referred  to  that 
plane  because  the  wave  reaches  the  two  ears  in  phase  agree- 
ment. Continuing  his  experiments  with  forks  of  higher  pitch, 
Rayleigh  finds  that  the  right  and  left  effects  occur  without 
considerable  diminution  up  to  pitches  of  320  vibrations  per 
second.  At  this  point  the  phenomenon  begins  to  become  in- 
definite and  confused.  After  careful  variations  of  his  condi- 
tions, he  concludes  that  768  vibrations  per  second  furnish  the 
limit  beyond  which  no  trace  of  the  effect  is  observed. 

In  a  later  report  of  work,^  Rayleigh  says :  "When  the  sounds 
proceed  from  tuning-forks  vibrating  independently,  the  phase 
differences  pass  cyclically  through  all  degrees,  and  if  the 
beat  be  slow  enough  there  is  good  opportunity  for  observation. 
But  it  is  not  possible  to  stop  anywhere,  or  in  some  uses  of  the 
method  to  bring  into  juxtaposition  phase  relationships  which 
differ  finitely."  He  then  describes  a  method  of  experimenta- 
tion which  allows  any  particular  phase  relation  to  be  main- 
tained at  pleasure.  Two  telephone  receivers  were  used  as  sources 
of  sound.  They  were  excited  by  a  revolving  magnet  which 
acted  indirectly  upon  two  coils,  one  in  each  of  the  telephone 
circuits.  The  planes  of  the  coils  were  vertical,  their  centres 
being  at  the  same  level  as  the  magnet.  One  was  fixed,  and  the 
other  was  so  mounted  that  it  could  revolve  about  an  axis 
coincident  with  that  of  the  magnet.     The  angle  between  the 

slower  particle;  and,  conversely,  when  the  angle  6  is  greater  than  180°,  the 
faster  particle  will  always  be  behind  the  slower  particle.  To  illustrate 
(Fig.  i),  let  /I  represent  the  position  of  the  faster  particle  on  the  circle 
of  reference  and  B  the  position  of  the  slower  particle,  both  moving  in  a 
counter-clock- wise  direction.  When  angle  ^  is  less  than  180°,  A  will  be 
ahead  of  B;  but  when  angle  6  is  greater  than  180°  (Fig.  2),  B  will  be 
ahead  of  A.     When  angle  8  is  180°,  or  360°,  neither  will  lead  in  phase. 

The  phase  relations  which  any  two  partides  vibrating  at  different  rates 
will  sustain  at  different  times  can  be  very  prettily  shown  for  class  demon- 
stration by  two  hands  geared  to  move  at  the  required  speeds  around  a 
graduated  dial. 

^Lord  Rayleigh:  Acoustical  Notes,  Sensations  of  Right  and  Left  from  a 
Revolving  Magnet  and  Telephone,  Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  6,  XIII,  1907,  pp. 
316-319. 


AUDITORY  I^OCAUZATION  259 

planes  of  the  coils  represents  the  phase  differences  of  the  peri- 
odic electro-motive  forces,  subject  it  may  be  to  an  ambiguity 
of  half  a  period,  dependent  upon  the  way  the  connections  are 
made.  If  the  circuits  are  similar,  as  is  believed,  the  phase 
differences  of  the  circuits  and  the  electro-motive  forces  are  the 
same.  The  circuit  of  one  telephone  included  a  commutator 
by  means  of  which  the  current  through  the  instrument  could 
be  reversed,  corresponding  to  a  phase  change  of  180°. 

In  conducting  an  observation,  the  sounds  given  by  the  two 
telephones  are  brought  to  equal  intensities  by  a  proper  regu- 
lation of  the  distances  between  the  magnets  and  the  inductor 
coils.  The  telephones  are  thus  brought  into  simultaneous 
action,  and  differences  of  phase  are  produced  by  rotating  the 
movable  coil;  or  if  complete  reversal  is  wanted,  it  may  btf 
got  by  means  of  the  commutator.  The  results,  he  says, 
confirm  those  obtained  with  the  tuning  forks.  A  lead  in  phase 
was  followed  by  the  reference  of  the  sound  to  the  side  receiv- 
ing the  wave  which  led  in  phase,  and  when  the  planes  of  the 
coils  were  parallel,  i.  e.,  when  the  phases  were  in  agreement  or 
opposition,  the  sound  was  located  in  the  median  plane. 

It  may  be  of  interest  to  note  here  the  results  of  other  observations 
made  under  conditions  similar  to  those  obtaining  in  Rayleigh's  experiments. 
Thompson,  working  in  the  following  way,  reports  beats,  but  makes  no  men- 
tion of  right  and  left  effects,  (i)  Tuning-forks,  unresonated,  were  held 
one  to  each  ear.  (2)  The  sound  of  one  fork  was  conducted  to  one  ear 
through  a  rubber  tube  and  the  second  fork  was  held  to  the  other  ear.  (3) 
The  forks  were  placed  in  different  rooms  and  the  sound  was  conducted 
separately  through  rubber  tubes  to  the  ears.  The  sounds  had  no  opportu- 
nity of  mingling  externally  or  of  acting  jointly  on  any  portion  of  the  air 
columns  along  which  the  sound  travelled.  Speaking  of  this  observation, 
he  says  (Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  5,  III,  1877,  p.  274):  "The  beats  were  most 
distinctly  heard,  and  seemed  to  take  place  within  the  cerebellum."  So 
W.  H.  Stone  reports  (Ibid.,  p.  278)  that  he  has  been  in  the  habit  of  using 
both  ears,  with  a  tuning-fork  applied  to  each,  in  counting  beats;  and  that 
he  finds  no  difference  between  the  results  of  this  method  and  that  of  Hsten- 
ing  to  both  forks  with  one  ear.  Rayleigh  (On  our  Perception  of  Sound 
Direction,  Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  6,  XIII,  1907,  p.  220),  speaking  of  Thompson's 
results,  says:  "In  an  observation  of  my  own  (Philos.  Mag.,  Vol.  II,  1901, 
p.  280;  Scientific  Papers,  Vol.  IV,  p.  553),  when  tones  supposed  to  be  moder- 
ately pure  were  led  to  the  ears  by  means  of  telephones,  a  nearly  identical 
conclusion  was  reached.  But  although  the  cycle  was  recognized,  in  neither 
case,  apparently,  was  there  any  suggestion  of  right  and  left  effect.  In  re- 
peating the  experiments  recently,  I  was  desirous  of  avoiding  the  use  of 
telephones  or  tubes  in  contact  with  the  ears,  under  which  artificial  condi- 
tions an  instinctive  judgment  would  perhaps  be  disturbed.  It  seemed  that 
it  might  suffice  to  lead  the  sounds  through  tubes  whose  open  ends  were 
merely  in  close  proximity  one  to  each  ear,  an  arrangement  which  has  the 
advantage  of  allowing  the  relative  intensities  to  be  controlled  by  a  slight 
lateral  displacement  of  the  head  toward  one  or  the  other  source."  This 
apparently  was  the  only  difference  in  the  conditions  between  the  experi- 
ments which  gave  beats  and  no  right  and  left  effects,  and  the  experiments 
which  gave  right  and  left  effects  but  not  "plainly  recognizable  beats." 
Hermann    {Zur    Theorie  der    Comhinationstone,   Pfliiger's   Archiv,  XLIX, 


I 


26o  FERREE  AND  COLUNS 

1 89 1,  pp.  499-518)  found  that  when  the  waves  from  two  tuning  forks  were 
conducted  one  to  each  ear,  he  heard  both  beats  and  combination  tones.  In 
this  case  he  supposed  that  the  tones,  through  the  mediation  of  the  bones 
in  the  head,  both  acted  together  on  each  ear.  No  mention  is  made  of  right 
and  left  effects.  Cross  and  Goodwin  (Charles  R.  Cross  and  H.  M.  Goodwin: 
Some  Considerations  Regarding  Helmholtz's  Theory  of  Consonance,  Proc.  of 
the  Am.  Acad,  of  Arts  and  Sciences,  XXVII,  1891,  pp.  1-12)  found  beats 
and  apparently  the  phenomenon  of  transfer  from  ear  to  ear.  The  meatus 
was  closed  with  beeswax,  leaving  an  air  column  between  it  and  the  tympanic 
membrane.  The  conduction  under  these  conditions  they  think  was  directly 
to  the  tympanic  membrane  by  means  of  the  air  column  and  not  through  the 
bones  of  the  head  to  the  middle  ear  or  cochlea,  because  the  sound  of  the 
fork,  when  the  stem  was  touched  to  the  wax,  was  heard  long  after  it  had 
ceased  to  be  audible  when  the  stem  was  touched  to  the  pinna  of  the  ear. 
It  was  also  found  that  it  could  be  heard  longer  when  the  stem  was  touched 
to  the  wax  than  when  it  was  held  against  the  teeth.  When  two  small  tono- 
meter forks,  tuned  to  four  beats  per  second,  were  struck  and  their  stems 

held  against  the  teeth,  '  'loud  beats  were  heard  in  the  ears The 

forks  were  held  in  this  position  until  the  beats  had  entirely  ceased  to  be 
audible,  when  they  were  removed  and  the  stem  of  each  was  touched  to  the 
wax  closing  the  two  ears.  Instantly  the  two  notes  were  heard,  faintly  but 
distinctly,  in  the  ears  to  which  they  were  held,  and  accompanying  them 
were  faint  beats  seeming  to  wander  in  the  head  from  ear  to  ear,  as  is  always 
the  case  with  binaural  beats."  The  experiment  was  then  varied  slightly 
as  follows.  One  ear  only  was  closed  with  wax;  the  other  was  immersed 
in  a  large  basin  of  water.  '  'The  experiment  was  then  repeated  as  above, 
with  the  difference  that  one  fork,  instead  of  being  touched  to  the  ear,  was 
touched  to  the  marble  basin,  its  vibrations  being  transmitted  to  the  en- 
closed ear  through  the  water.  The  same  results  were  obtained  as  before." 
One  of  the  conclusions  drawn  from  these  experiments,  which  is  especially 
of  interest  relative  to  Wilson  and  Myers'  experiments  and  their  explana- 
tion of  the  localization  of  tones  of  low  pitch  {Vide  this  paper,  pp  .266-69),  is 
that  '  'aerial  vibrations  acting  upon  the  ear  are  not  transmitted  through  the 
skull,  or  bony  parts  of  the  head,  from  one  ear  to  the  other." 

The  phenomenon  of  beats  has  also  been  reported  in  this  connection  by 
the  following  experimenters,  but  none  of  them  has  mentioned  a  right-left 
transfer:  Dove  (Repertorium  der  Physik,  Bd.  Ill,  1839,  S.  494;  Fogg. 
Annal.,  CVII,  1859,8.653);  Seebeck  (Fogg.  Annal.,  LIX,  1841,  S.  417; 
ibid.,  lyXVIII,  1846,  S.  449;  Akustik,  Abschn.  II,  Gehler's  Repertoriimi  der 
Physik,  1849,  S.  107);  Mach  (Wiener  Sitzungsber,  L,  1864,  p.  356.);  Stumpf 
(Tonpsychologie,  Bd.  II,  S.  208,  458,  470);  Bernstein  (Ffliiger's  Archiv., 
LIX,  S.  475);  Ewald  (Ffliiger's  Archiv,  LVII,  1894,  S.  80);  Schaefer 
(Zeitschr.  f.  Psychol.,  u.  Physiol.,  I,  1890,  81);  and  Melati  (Philos.  Stu- 
dien,  Bd.  XVII,  1901,  pp.  431-461).  Sanford  (Experimental  Psychology, 
1898,  p.  82),  however,  working  with  forks  beating  once  in  two  or  three 
seconds  notices,  a  shifting  of  the  sound  from  ear  to  ear  corresponding  to  the 
rate  of  beating. 

It  is  with  considerable  reluctance  that  the  writers  present 
the  preceding  brief  exposition  of  Rayleigh's  theory  and  its 
experimental  confirmation,  because  neither  of  these  is  worked 
out  in  the  original  article  with  sufficient  detail  to  warrant  the 
risk  of  a  definite  interpretation.  In  every  case,  therefore, 
where  more  than  one  interpretation  has  seemed  possible,  the 
one  most  favorable  to  the  theory  has  been  chosen.  Until  all 
the  points  involved  both  in  the  theory  and  in  its  confirm- 
ation have  received  more  definite  treatment    by    Rayleigh 


AUDITORY  LOCALIZATION 


261 


the  writers  feel  that  positive  criticism,  either  favorable  or 
adverse,  is  out  of  the  question.  The  following  comments, 
however,  may  not  be  out  of  order,  (i)  The  theory  is  purely 
physical.  No  attempt  is  made  in  any  of  the  points  to  bridge 
over  the  gap  between  stimulus  and  sensation.  In  the  treat- 
ment of  lead  and  lag,  for  example,  no  consideration  is  given 
to  what  the  ear,  as  a  sense-organ,  might  be  assumed  to  recog- 
nize as  lead  and  lag.  The  mathematical  propriety  of  Rayleigh's 
use  of  the  terms  is  granted.  And  by  mathematical  definition, 
the  faster  wave  will  lead  when  angle  0  is  less  than  180°.  There 
will  always  be  this  characteristic  phase  relation  between  the 
waves  coming  to  the  two  ears.  But  to  grant  that  the  ear  can 
discriminate  which  is  leading  and  which  lagging,  when  no 
position  or  motion  of  any  of  the  vibrating  parts  of  the  ear  can, 
in  the  complete  cycles  of  its  changes,  characteristically  stand 
for  lead  or  lag,  and  when  no  lead  and  lag  aspect  can  be  dis- 
covered in  the  sound  sensation  itself,  seems  to  be  ascribing  to 
the  auditory  mechanism  a  logical  or  mathematical  power  which 
not  even  all  educated  beings  possess  as  an  item  of  culture. 
For  example,  when  angle  0  is  say  160°,  the  faster  wave  may, 
at  different  times  when  this  angle  of  separation  occurs,  be  in 
every  conceivable  stage  either  of  condensation  or  of  rarefaction. 
During  a  part  of  this  time,  the  slower  wave  will  be  at  appro- 
priate points  in  rarefaction  when  the  faster  is  in  condensa- 
tion, and  vice  versa;  and  the  rest  of  the  time  both  waves 
will  be  either  in  rarefaction  or  condensation.  Thus  there  is 
nothing  in  the  position  or  motion  of  the  vibrating  structures 
of  the  ear  that  can  be  seized  upon  as  characteristic  of  the  lead 
or  lag,  as  Rayleigh  uses  the  terms,  except  a  relation  between 
direction  of  motion  and  angles  of  separation,  and  this  is  dis- 
covered only  by  a  mathematical  consideration  of  simple  har- 
monic motion.^     Just  as  Helmholtz's    theory  of    vision    has 


^There  is,  for  example,  an  alternative  interpretation  of  lead  and  lag, 
which,  it  seems  to  the  writers,  the  ear  might  more  plausibly  be  assumed  to 
recognize;  namely,  neither  particle  might  be  said  to  lead  or  lag  unless 
both  be  moving  either  in  condensation  or  rarefaction.  Then  the  vibrating 
structures  of  the  ear  will  be  moving  in  the  same  direction,  and  at  any  given 
moment  will  be  displaced  in  the  same  direction.  Thus,  as  far  as  sensations 
of  motion  or  position  are  concerned,  if  such  sensations  can  be  assumed  for 
any  of  the  vibrating  structures  of  the  ear,  there  would  be  a  better  chance  for 
comparison  than  by  the  former  interpretation.  The  writers,  however,  do 
not  consider  that  this  is  the  interpretation  Rayleigh  means  to  be  taken  for 
lead  and  lag;  because  (i)  it  is  not  the  interpretation  commonly  given  to  the 
terms,  and  (2)  in  his  experiments,  it  would  leave  the  ear  apart  of  the  time 
in  both  halves  of  the  cycle  of  changes  without  a  localizing  clue,  for  there  will 
come  times  both  from  agreement  to  opposition  and  from  opposition  to  agree- 
ment when  one  wave  will  be  in  condensation  and  the  other  in  rarefaction, 
and  conversely.  Thus  for  a  part  of  the  time,  in  both  cases  of  reference, 
right  and  left,  there  would  be  no  localizing  clue.     This  interpretation  would 


262  FERREE  AND  COLUNS 

been  called  pre-psychological,  so  may  this  theory  of  localiza- 
tion be  called  pre-psychological. 

(2)  Speaking  of  the  difference  in  phase  in  which  the 
sound-wave  from  a  source  to  the  right  on  the  aural  axis 
would  arrive  at  the  Orifices  of  the  two  ears,  Rayleigh  says '} 
**It  is  easy  to  see  that  the  retardation  of  distance  at  the  left 
ear  is  of  the  order  of  the  semicircumference  of  the  head,  say 
one  foot.  At  this  rate,  the  retardation  for  middle  C  (C'=256) 
is  nearly  one  quarter  of  a  period;  for  C"  (512)  nearly  half  a 
period;  for  C^"  (1024)  nearly  a  whole  period,  and  so  on.  Now 
it  is  certain  that  a  phase  retardation  of  half  a  period  affords  no 
material  for  a  decision  that  the  source  is  on  the  right  rather 
than  on  the  left,  seeing  that  there  is  no  difference  between  a 
retardation  and  an  acceleration  of  half  a  period.  It  is  even 
more  evident  that  a  retardation  of  a  whole  period  or  of  any 
number  of  whole  periods  would  be  of  no  avail. ' '  In  the  pre- 
ceding quotation  just  two  stages  of  phase  relationship  are 
ruled  out  as  furnishing  no  localizing  clue ;  namely,  a  difference 
of  a  half  period,  and  a  difference  of  a  whole  period.  A  differ- 
ence of  a  half  period  furnishes  no  clue,  because  the  angular 
separation  of  corresponding  particles  of  the  two  waves  is  180° ; 
hence  it  would  be  the  same  whether  considered  as  acceleration 
or  retardation.  Similarly,  a  difference  of  a  whole  period  fur- 
nishes no  clue,  because  the  angular  separation  of  the  corres- 
ponding particles  of  the  two  waves  is  360°,  hence  would  be  the 
same  considered  either  as  acceleration  or  retardation.  But  in 
the  scale  of  pitches,  there  are  only  certain  members  higher 
than  512  and  i  ,024  vibrations  whose  sound-waves  coming  from 
a  given  direction  would  always  arrive  at  the  two  ears  with  a 
difference  of  180°  or  360°.  Phase  difference,  so  far  as  can  be 
readily  seen,  should  furnish  a  clue  for  the  localization  of  the 
higher  just  as  well  as  of  the  lower  pitches.  There  seems  to  be 
no  good  reason,  then,  for  making  the  direct  recognition  of 
phase  difference  a  localizing  clue  for  the  lower  pitches  only, 
and  for  giving  over  to  difference  of  intensity  the  exclusive 
r6le  for  the  higher  pitches.  And  again,  if  a  direct  recognition 
of  phase  difference  be  a  localizing  clue,  it  is  not  easy  to  see 
why  the  right  and  left  effects  in  Rayleigh's  experiments  should 
suffer  considerable  diminution  when  the  tones  were  as  high  as 
320,  and  should  cease  entirely  near  768  or  above.  It  is  just 
as  clear  that  the  faster  wave  will  lead  from  agreement  to  op- 
position and  the  slower  from  opposition  to  agreement  in 
this  case  as  in  the  case  of  lower  tones.     And  if  the  tones 

work  even  worse  in  localization  as  ordinarily  observed,  for  in  every  direction 
there  would  be  certain  distances  from  the  ear  for  which  there  would  be  no 
localizing  clue. 
^Op.  cit.  p.  218. 


AUDITORY  LOCAUZATION  263 

were  near  together  in  pitch,  the  transitions  from  right  to 
left  effects  should  have  come  just  as  slowly  and  should 
therefore  have  been  just  as  easily  observed.  That  is,  if 
768  and  769  forks  were  used,  for  example,  the  change  from 
agreement  to  opposition  and  from  opposition  to  agreement, 
and  the  corresponding  right-left,  left-right  transfers,  should  have 
occurred  only  once  per  second,  just  as  would  have  occurred 
with  forks  of  128  and  129  vibrations  per  second.  (3)  Phase 
difference  must  make  itself  felt  in  consciousness  either  by 
means  of  some  change  in  the  sound  sensation  itself,  or  by  set- 
ting up  some  new  sensation  alongside  the  sound  sensation ;  for 
example,  a  sensation  of  position  or  movement  of  some  of  the 
vibrating  structures  of  the  ear.  Wilson  and  Myers^  conclude 
that  phase  difference  makes  itself  felt  as  a  difference  in 
the  intensity  of  the  sound  heard  by  the  two  ears.  They  ex- 
plain the  localizations  in  Rayleigh's  experiments  in  terms  of 
this  difference  in  intensity  produced  by  cyclic  changes  of  inter- 
ference between  the  sound-waves  coming  directly  to  the  two 
ears  and  those  transmitted  from  one  ear  to  the  other  through 
the  bones  of  the  head.  Rayleigh,  however,  obviously  considers 
that  the  effect  of  phase  difference  is  extra  to  any  differences  that 
may  occur  in  the  intensity  aspect  of  the  sensations  given  to 
the  two  ears.  The  question  arises  as  to  whether  either  expla- 
nation can  be  applied  further  than  to  the  special  phenomenon 
created  by  the  experimental  conditions  under  which  they 
worked.  This  point  will  be  taken  up  in  a  later  section  of  this 
paper.  (4)  Until  more  sensitive  tests  than  those  conducted 
by  Rayleigh  are  made  to  find  out  the  relative  sensitivity  of 
direction-discrimination  for  low  and  high  tones,  it  is  not  dem- 
onstrated that  there  is  any  need  for  a  supplement  to  the  in- 
tensity theory,  to  account  for  the  localization  of  low  tones. 

Later,  in  1907,  More  and  Fry^  also  attempted  to  show  that 
phase  difference  serves  as  a  clue  for  the  localization  of  sound. 
They  worked  with  tuning-forks  of  320  and  512  vibrations  per 
second.  The  observer  was  seated  at  the  centre  of  a  large 
circle  marked  on  the  floor  of  a  room.  The  zero  point  in  the 
circle  was  taken  directly  behind  the  observer,  the  180°  point 
in  front,  and  the  90°  points  at  the  sides.  A  glass  funnel  13.5 
cm.  in  diameter  was  mounted  horizontally  on  a  table  at  the 
zero  point,  about  7  ft.  behind  the  observer.  Heavy  rubber 
tubing  with  an  inner  diameter  of  about  1.2  cm.  connected  the 
funnel  with  the  stem  of  a  glass  Y-tube,  on  the  two  branches  of 
which  rubber  tubing  of  the  same  size  was  fitted.  These  branch 
tubes  ended  in  glass  tubes  bent  so  as  to  fit  into  the  ears  of  the  ob- 

^Vide  pp.  267-68,  this  paper. 
^Op.  cit. 


264  FERREE  AND  COLUNS 

server.  Each  of  the  branch  tubes  was  cut  in  two  at  the  middle ; 
and  by  inserting  pieces  of  glass  tubing,  the  experimenter 
readily  altered  their  lengths  without  the  listener's  being  aware 
of  the  change.  Fourteen  observers  were  used.  The  sound 
was  given  at  the  mouth  of  the  funnel,  and  the  observer  was 
asked  to  indicate  the  direction  from  which  it  came.  This 
direction  was  estimated  by  means  of  the  graduated  circle  at 
the  centre  of  which  the  observer  sat.  Before  each  observa- 
tion, the  length  of  one  of  the  tubes  was  changed  }/s,  34,  %, 
3^»  %}  M>  or  J^  of  a  wave-length  of  the  sound  used  as  stimulus. 
The  results,  expressed  in  general  terms,  showed  that  when  the 
tubes  were  exactly  equal  in  length,  the  sound  seemed  to  come 
directly  from  behind;  but  if  one  tube  was  made  shorter  than 
the  other,  by  as  much  as  2  cm.,  the  sound  was  referred  to  the 
side  having  the  shorter  tube.  These  results  were  taken  to 
indicate  that  sound  is  localized  by  a  direct  appreciation  of  the 
difiference  of  phase  of  the  waves  coming  to  the  two  ears. 

With  regard  to  this  work,  the  writer  would  point  out  the 
following  facts,  (i)  The  forks  employed  were  both  above  the 
pitch  limit  at  which  Rayleigh  claims  the  difference  in  intensity 
becomes  too  small  to  serve  as  a  localizing  clue.  Hence  these 
writers,  in  their  support  of  the  phase  difference  theory,  work 
with  tones  for  which  Rayleigh  claims  the  localizing  clue  is 
difference  of  intensity  and  not  of  phase.  (2)  Their  results, 
stated  in  general  terms,  do  not  seem  to  have  any  differential 
value.  When  one  tube  is  made  shorter  than  the  other,  the 
stimulus  received  by  the  ear  on  that  side  is  more  intensive  than 
that  received  by  the  other  ear ;  hence,  by  the  intensity  theory, 
as  well  as  by  the  phase  difference  theory,  the  sound  should 
be  referred  to  that  side.  The  sounds  worked  with  had  a  wave- 
length of  64  (512  fork)  and  104  (320  fork)  cm.  per  sec.  A 
change  in  the  length  of  one  of  these  comparatively  short  tubes 
by  from  J^  -  J^  of  a  wave-length  of  these  sounds  would  pro- 
duce a  considerable  change  in  the  ratio  of  the  distances  the 
sound  had  to  travel  to  reach  the  two  ears ;  hence  it  would  pro- 
duce a  considerable  difference  in  the  energy  of  the  stimulation 
given.  As  nearly  as  the  writer  can  determine,  by  comparing 
the  measurements  and  localizations  given  by  More  and  Fry 
with  the  measurements  of  the  direct  paths  of  transmission  of 
the  sound  to  the  two  ears  from  these  locations  in  his  own 
sound-cage,  the  change  of  ratio  is  quite  of  the  same  order  in 
the  two  cases. 

(3)  Although  it  may  be  considered  that  the  results  in  general 
are  not  differential  as  between  the  two  theories.  More  and  Fry 
find  a  crucial  argument  in  the  fact  that  as  one  tube  was  pro- 
gressively made  longer  than  the  other,  there  was  not  a  constant 
increase  in  the  displacement  of  the  sound  toward  the  ear  sup- 


AUDITORY  LOCALIZATION  265 

plied  with  the  shorter  tube.  In  a  few  cases,  for  example,  the 
90°  displacement  was  made  when  the  change  in  the  length  of 
the  tube  was  only  %-5^  of  the  wave-length;  and  from  that 
point  on  to  a  change  of  a  whole  wave-length,  there  was  even, 
in  certain  cases,  a  decrease  in  the  angle  of  displacement.  This, 
they  say,  on  the  basis  of  the  intensity  theory,  ought  not  to  be. 
There  should  be,  following  a  change  in  the  relative  lengths  of 
the  tubes,  a  regular  increase  of  displacement.  To  quote: 
"If  it  were  a  question  of  change  of  intensity,  the  change  in 
direction  would  increase  continually  and  not  reach  an  angle 
where  further  increase  in  the  length  of  the  tube  produces 
either  a  doubtful  increase  in  angle  or  even  at  times  a  decrease." 
In  reply  to  this,  it  may  be  pointed  out  {a)  that  a  sound  cannot 
be  displaced  more  than  90°  to  either  side,  and  the  ratio  of  the 
length  of  the  tubes  which  gave  their  observers  a  displacement 
of  the  sound  90°  to  the  right  was  of  the  same  order  as  the  ratio 
of  the  lengths  of  the  direct  paths  of  transmission  to  the  two 
ears  when  the  sound  is  actually  given  90°  to  the  right  in  the 
sound-cage  used  in  our  own  experiments.  Moreover,  as  lo- 
calizations ordinarily  occur  in  everyday  life,  the  ratio  of  the 
distances  the  sound  travels  in  order  to  reach  the  two  ears  is, 
in  most  cases,  not  even  so  great  as  it  is  with  the  Titchener 
sound-cage.  The  above  result,  then,  is  all  that  could  be  ex- 
pected by  the  intensity  theory,  {b)  To  account  for  the  de- 
crease in  the  angle  of  displacement  in  a  few  cases  mentioned, 
it  may  be  said  that  when  the  ratio  of  intensity,  by  the  condi- 
tions of  the  experiment,  is  made  to  exceed  any  ratio  that  could 
occur  in  our  daily  life,  there  is  no  basis  for  the  association  of 
any  given  direction  with  that  ratio;  hence,  once  this  limit  is 
exceeded,  regularity  of  results  should  not  be  expected.  Under 
such  conditions,  one  might  expect  almost  any  irregularity, 
but  certainly  not  regularity. 

(4)  The  discrepancy  between  More  and  Fry's  and  Wilson 
and  Myers's^  results  should  not  be  ignored.  In  both  cases 
apparently  the  same  method  of  working  was  used,  yet  very 
different  results  were  obtained.  For  More  and  Fry's  observers 
a  change  in  the  relative  lengths  of  the  tubes  was  followed  uni- 
formly by  a  displacement  of  the  sound  toward  the  side  of  the 
shorter  tube;  while  for  Wilson  and  Myers's  observers,  changes 
in  the  length  of  the  tubes  were  followed  by  a  cycle  of  changes 
of  localization, — first  to  the  side  of  the  shorter  tube,  then  to 
the  median  plane,  to  the  side  of  the  longer  tube,  back  to 
the  median  plane,  and  so  on.  So  great  a  discrepancy  cannot 
but  throw  both  sets  of  results  open  to  question,  until  more 
work  is  done  under  similar  conditions. 

^Vide  this  paper,  pp.  266-67. 

JOURNAl, — 9 


266  FERREE  AND  COLLINS 

In  October,  1908,  Wilson  and  Myers  reported  a  series  of 
experiments  suggested  by  the  work  of  Rayleigh.  The  general 
plan  of  experimentation  was  similar  to  that  used  by  More  and 
Fry.  The  apparatus/  however,  was  more  carefully  designed, 
and  the  effect  of  changes  in  the  ratio  of  the  length  of  conducting 
paths  was  possibly  more  minutely  tested  out.^  The  sound 
was  led  to  the  ears  separately  by  the  two  arms  of  a  rectangle 
made  of  tubes  of  glass  and  brass  joined  at  the  corners  by  India 
rubber  tubing.  The  observer's  head,  in  position,  occupied  the 
mid-point  in  the  back  of  this  rectangle.  Opposite  his  head, 
in  the  mid  region  of  the  front  of  the  rectangle,  a  section  120  cm. 
long  was  removed  and  in  its  place  a  section  of  T-tubing  was 
inserted,  the  horizontal  arm  of  which  was  small  enough  in 
diameter  to  slide  freely  within  the  main  tube,  and  long  enough 
to  permit  the  perpendicular  arm  to  be  moved  60  cm.  on  each 
side  of  the  median  plane.  The  perpendicular  arm  ended  in  a 
funnel-shaped  collector,  in  front  of  which  the  tuning-fork  was 
sounded.  A  centimeter  scale  was  mounted  behind  the  T-tube, 
upon  which  could  be  read  the  displacements  of  the  perpendic- 
ular arm  to  the  right  or  left  of  the  median  plane.  The  tubes 
leading  to  the  ears  ended  in  wooden  receivers  or  ear-caps, 
which  were  pressed  against  the  observer's  head,  and  held  in 
place  by  retort  stands  fastened  to  the  table  in  front  of  the  ob- 
server. The  movements  of  the  experimenter  were  shut  off 
from  the  observer's  view  by  a  large  screen  across  the  median 
plane.  When  the  funnel  receiving  the  sound  was  placed  in 
the  median  plane,  the  arms  leading  to  the  ears  were  of  equal 
length,  in  most  cases  317  cm.  each.  In  this  position  it  was 
found  that  the  sound  was  located  in  the  median  plane.  When 
the  funnel  was  displaced  by  amounts  varying  from  o — A./4  (^^= 
wave  length)  or  A./2 — 3V4»  the  sound  was  referred  to  the  side 
toward  which  the  displacement  had  been  made.     When  it 

^Apparatus  somewhat  similar  to  that  used  by  Wilson  and  Myers  is 
described    by  Urbantschitsch   (Arch.  f.  d.    ges.  Physiol.,    1881,  XXIV, 

579-585). 

2Sylvanus  Thompson  (Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  V,  Vol.  VI,  1878,  pp.  386-387) 
worked  in  much  the  same  fashion  as  Wilson  and  Myers,  but  with  less 
minute  measurement.  The  ends  of  a  curved  copper  wire  3  ft.  long,  bent 
into  two  rings,  were  inserted  one  into  each  of  the  observer's  ears.  It  was 
found  that  when  the  stem  of  a  vibrating  fork  was  set  on  this  wire  at  the  mid 
point,  the  sound  seemed  to  come  from  the  ends  of  the  wire  in  each  ear.  A 
change  of  an  inch  and  a  half  from  this  position  produced  a  sufficient  differ- 
ence in  the  length  of  the  path  travelled  by  the  sound  to  cause  it  to  reach  the 
two  ears  in  complete  difference  of  phase.  Given  in  this  position,  the  sound 
seemed  to  come  from  the  back  of  the  head.  When  the  sound  was  given  in 
intermediate  positions,  the  effect  was  of  a  mixed  character;  part  of  the 
sound  seemed  as  if  located  in  the  ears  themselves,  and  part  of  it  seemed  to 
come  from  the  back  of  the  head.  No  change  in  this  result  was  observed 
with  forks  of  different  pitches,  providing  that  the  proper  differences  in 
length  of  path  were  chosen. 


AUDITORY  I.OCALIZATION  267 

was  displaced  by  amounts  varying  from  X/4 — X/2  or  3  V4 — K 
the  sound  was  referred  to  the  side  opposite  to  that  toward  which 
the  displacement  had  been  made.  The  same  relations  between 
the  reference  of  the  sound  and  the  displacements  of  the  stimu- 
lus were  observed  to  hold  for  simple  multiples  of  A.  Thus  it 
was  found  that  when  the  stimulus  is  displaced  either  to  the 
right  or  left  of  the  median  plane,  the  sound  is  successively 
referred,  as  the  displacement  is  increased,  first  to  the  side  to- 
ward which  the  displacement  is  made,  back  to  the  median 
plane,  to  the  opposite  side,  and  back  to  the  median  plane,  re- 
peating the  cycle  when  the  displacement  reaches  an  amount 
exceeding  one  wave  length. 

In  explaining  these  results,  Wilson  and  Myers  agree  with 
Rayleigh  that  the  localization  of  tones  of  low  pitch  is  depend- 
ent upon  the  difference  in  the  phase  of  vibration  in  which  the 
sound  waves  reach  the  two  ears.  They  do  not,  however,  be- 
lieve it  is  necessary  to  assume  that  the  localizing  clue  is  a  direct 
recognition  of  phase  difference  by  the  two  ears.  They  con- 
tend that  "while  binaural  differences  in  phase  are  a  primary 
cause  of  the  observed  lateral  effects,  these  effects  are  ultimately 
referable  to  binaural  differences  in  intensity."  The  stimulus 
in  either  ear  is  a  resultant  of  two  vibrations,  one  communicated 
directly  to  the  ear,  the  other  indirectly,  through  bone  conduc- 
tion from  the  opposite  ear.  The  resultant,  now  stronger  in 
one  ear,  now  in  the  other,  now  equal  in  both  ears,  because  of 
progressively  changing  phase  differences  between  the  direct 
and  transmitted  waves,  determines  the  direction-reference. 
Suppose,  as  in  the  case  of  the  Rayleigh  experiments,  two 
sound-waves  of  equal  amplitude  but  of  unequal  frequency 
enter  the  two  ears.  Then  from  agreement  to  opposition  the 
faster  wave  will  lead  the  slower  in  phase,  and  from  opposition 
to  agreement  the  converse  will  be  true.  When  the  faster  is 
leading,  the  resultant  of  the  direct  and  transmitted  waves  in  the 
ear  receiving  the  faster  wave  will  be  of  greater  intensity  than  in 
the  ear  receiving  the  slower  wave,  and  the  total  sound  mass 
will  be  referred  to  that  side.  Similarly,  when  the  slower 
leads  in  phase,  the  resultant  will  be  stronger  in  the  ear  receiv- 
ing the  slower  wave,  and  the  localization  will  occur  on  that 
side.  When,  however,  the  two  waves  are  in  opposition  or 
agreement,  the  resultants  in  both  ears  will  be  equal,  and  the 
localization  will  be  in  the  median  plane,  as  the  intensity  theory 
requires.  Since,  as  they  believe,  this  hypothesis  satisfactorily 
explains  the  results  of  Rayleigh's  experiments,  they  do  not 
think  that  these  experiments  should  be  considered  as  afford- 
ing differential  evidence  for  the  phase-difference  theory.  Nor 
do  they  claim  differential  value  for  their  own  experiments. 
With  reference  to  physical  features  alone,  both  hypotheses  are 


268  FERREE  AND  COLUNS 

capable  of  explaining  both  sets  of  results.  Wilson  and  Myers, 
however,  claim  an  advantage  for  their  hypothesis  on  the  ground 
of  its  greater  plausibility  and  of  the  auxiliary  facts  that  can  be 
cited  in  its  support.  On  the  ground  of  plausibility,  they  main- 
tain that  their  hypothesis  is  in  better  accord  with  the  prevailing 
conception  of  the  origin  and  nature  of  nervous  impulses.  For 
example,  Rayleigh  states:^  "It  seems  no  longer  possible  that 
the  vibratory  character  of  sound  terminates  at  the  outer  ends 
of  the  nerves  along  which  the  communication  with  the  brain 
is  established.  On  the  contrary,  the  processes  in  the  nerve 
must  in  themselves  be  vibratory,  not  in  the  gross  mechanical 
sense,  but  with  the  preservation  of  the  period  and  retaining 
the  characteristic  of  phase — a  view  advocated  by  Rutherford 
as  long  ago  as  1886."  Wilson  and  Myers  believe  that  there 
is  too  much  evidence  of  the  specific  functioning  of  end-organs 
to  be  overweighed  by  the  results  of  Rayleigh' s  experiments. 
A  special  sense-organ  may  be  excited  not  only  by  the  stimuli 
to  which  it  is  especially  adapted  to  respond  ("adequate" 
stimuli),  but  also  by  "inadequate"  stimuli;  for  example, 
electrical,  chemical,  and  mechanical.  "  Inasmuch  as  the 
sensations  are  similar  despite  the  diverse  character  of  the 
stimuli,  we  have  hitherto  believed  that  the  impulses  ascending 
a  sensory  nerve  depend  on  the  mode  of  response  of  the  end  organ 
and  not  directly  on  the  character  of  the  stimulus."  By  way  of 
auxiliary  facts,  they  cite  theresultsof  Mader,2the  tuning-fork  ex- 
periment of  Weber,  and  its  modification  suggested  by  Schaefer,' 

^Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  6,  Vol.  XIII,  1907,  pp.  224-225. 

'In  Mader's  experiments  (Sitzungsber.  d,  kais.  Akad.  d.  Wissens.,  Wien, 
1900,  Bd.  CIX,  Abth,  3,  S.  37-75)  two  tones  of  neariy  identical  pitch  were 
separately  led  one  to  each  ear  hole  of  a  skull.  A  microphone  applied  to 
the  roof  of  the  skull  gave  evidence  of  beats.  This  is  cited  as  presumptive 
evidence  that  the  tones  were  actually  passing  across  the  roof  of  the  skull 
from  one  ear  to  the  other.  (Both  tones,  however,  were  generated  in  the 
same  room,  hence  there  is  no  guarantee  that  the  microphone  was  not  acted 
upon  by  beats  in  the  air  wave.) 

^Schaefer,  K.  L.:  Zeitschr.  f.  Psychol,  u.  Physiol,  d.  Sinnesorg.  1891, 
Bd.  II,  S.  111-114.  Wilson  and  Myers  {Op.  a7.,  p.  318)  describe  this 
experiment  as  follows:  "A  fork,  fixed  at  some  distance  from  one  side  of 
the  observer,  is  very  gently  struck.  The  observer  listens,  and  notes  when 
the  dying  tone  has  become  quite  inaudible.  He  then  inserts  an  appro- 
priately attuned  resonator  into  the  ear  which  is  nearest  the  fork ;  whereupon, 
the  tone  is  at  once  softly  heard  again  on  that  side,  as  if  it  came  from  the 
resonator.  If  the  meatus  of  the  more  distant  ear  be  now  closed,  the  tone 
becomes  at  once  stronger,  and  its  localization  approaches  the  median  plane. 
If  the  meatus  be  then  re-opened,  the  tone  immediately  leaps  back  again 
to  the  ear  in  which  the  resonator  is  inserted." 

Mach  has  suggested  that  when  a  tuning-fork  is  placed  on  the  vertex, 
and  the  meatus  of  one  ear  is  closed,  the  tone  is  localized  to  that  side,  be- 
cause the  sound  travelling  by  bone  conduction  to  that  ear  not  only  stimu- 
lates the  cochlea,  but  sets  up  in  the  meatus  vibrations  which  are  reflected 
back  and  intensify  the  sound  in  that  ear. 


AUDITORY  I^OCALIZATION  269 

as  evidence  of  bone  conduction^  under  conditions  similar  to 
those  in  their  own  and  in  Rayleigh's  experiments.^ 

As  was  stated  earlier  in  the  paper,  this  review  will  be  con- 
cluded by  a  brief  resum6  of  the  arguments  Khat  have  been 
advanced,  up  to  the  present  time,  for  the  binaural  ratio  as  a 
factor  in  auditory  localization.  They  are  as  follows.  ( i )  Con- 
fusion points  are  found  in  the  median  plane  and  in  the  planes 
parallel  to  it  on  either  side  (Rayleigh,^  von  Kries  and  Auer- 
bach,^  Pierce,^  and  Starch®).  (2)  Monaural  localization  is 
inferior  to  binaural  localization.  (Politzer,^  Arnheim,*  Preyer,' 
Bloch,'Von  Bezold,ii  Smith,i2  AngellandFitc^^and  Starch.^*) 
Politzer,  Arnheim,  Preyer,  and  Bloch  worked  with  cases  of 
monaural  hearing  artificially  produced ;  von  Bezold,  Angell  and 
Fite,  and  Smith  worked  with  pathological  cases.  Starch  worked 
with  two  observers  in  which  the  defect  was  artificially  produced, 
and  two  in  which  it  was  pathological.  For  Politzer,  Arnheim, 
Preyer,  Smith,  and  Angell  and  Fite,  the  test  used  was  ac- 
curacy of  localization;  for  Bloch  it  was  the  size  of  the  j.  n.  d. ; 
and  for  Starch  it  was  both  accuracy  of  localization  and  the 
size  of  the  j.  n.  d. 

(3)  The  greatest  accuracy  of  localization  occurs  at  points 
where  a  change  of  direction  produces  the  greatest  change  in 

^Against  bone  conduction  vide  the  experiments  and  conclusions  of  Cross 
and  Goodwin  (this  paper  p.  260.) 

^There  may  be  cited  additional  casual  advantages,  so  obvious,  however, 
as  to  be  scarcely  worthy  of  mention,  (i)  Wilson  and  Myers's  explanation 
does  not  involve  the  assumption  of  any  new  power  on  the  part  of  the  ear, 
hence  it  has  the  advantage  of  systematic  simplicity.  (2)  Introspective 
analysis  does  not  show  any  aspect  of  the  sound  sensation,  or  any  new 
sensation  simultaneous  with  the  sound  sensation,  corresponding  to  differ- 
ence of  phase. 

'Rayleigh,  Lord:  Acoustical  Observations,  Perception  of  the  Direction  of 
a  Source  of  Sound,  Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  5,  Vol.  Ill,  1877,  pp.  456-458. 

*0p.  cit.,  p.  330,  336. 

^Op.  cit.,  pp.  56-78. 

^Psychol.  Rev.,  Monog.  Suppl.,  Vol.  IX,  1908,  p.  53. 

"^Op.  cit.,  p.  231-236. 

^Arnheim:  Beitrage  zur  Theorie  der  Lokal.  von  Schallemp.  mittl.  derBo- 
gengange.     Diss.  Jena,  1887. 

'Preyer:  Die  Wahrnehmung  der  Schallrichtung  mittelst  der  Bogengdnge, 
Pfliiger's  Archiv,  XL,  1887,  pp.  618-619.  It  will  be  remembered,  however, 
that  Preyer  and  Arnheim  believed  that  the  localization  is  in  terms  of  space 
feelings  aroused  directly  by  the  action  of  the  sound  wave  upon  the  semi- 
circular canals. 

»"0^.  cit.,  p.  59-73- 

"0/>.  cit.,  p.  486-487. 

"0/>.  cit.,  p.  542. 

^^Op.  cit.,  pp.  225-246  and  449-458.  Angell  and  Fite  claim  that  a  con- 
siderable degree  of  inferiority  of  monaural  hearing  exists  only  in  the  case  of 
unpracticed  monaural  subjects.  Monaural  subjects  can  be  practiced  up 
to  the  point  of  locaUzing  almost  as  well  as  the  unpracticed  normal  subject. 

"Psychol.  Rev.,  Monog.  Suppl.,  IX,  1908,  pp.  40-48. 


» 


27©  FERREB  AND  COI.UNS 

the  binaural  ratio,  i.  e.,  in  front  and  back  near  the  median 
plane;  and  the  poorest  localization  occurs  where  a  change  of 
direction  produces  the  least  change  in  the  binaural  ratio,  i.  e., 
at  the  sides,  near  the  aural  axis^  (Bloch,^    and  Starch^). 

(4)  A  difference  in  the  amount  of  collection  of  the  sound- 
wave at  the  orifices  of  the  ears  determines  the  localization  to 
the  side  receiving  the  greater  energy  of  the  wave  (Thomp- 
son,^ and  KesseP) . 

The  total  sound-mass  is  referred  to  the  side  of  the  stronger 
stimulus  when  two  sounds,  one  stronger  than  the  other,  are 
given  to  the  two  ears.  (Steinhauser,®  Tarchanoff,'  and  Mat- 
sumoto^). 

When  two  tuning-forks  sounding  with  equal  intensity  are 
placed  one  on  each  side  of  the  head,  but  one  nearer  to  the  ear 
than  the  other,  the  total  sound-mass  is  referred  to  the  side  on 
which  the  nearer  fork  is  located  (Stenger'). 

When  two  tuning-forks,  sounding  with  equal  intensity  and 
located  in  the  aural  axis  on  either  side  at  the  same  distance 
from  the  ears,  are  swung  in  unison  from  left  to  right  and  right 
to  left,  a  transfer  in  the  localization  of  the  total  sound  mass 
takes  place  following  the  rhythm  of  the  swing.  When  both  are 
swinging  to  the  left,  the  sound  is  referred  to  the  right,  and, 
conversely,  when  both  are  swinging  to  the  right,  the  localiza- 
tion is  on  the  left.  When  both  are  swinging  with  equal  speed 
in  opposite  directions,  the  localization  is  in  the  median  plane 
(Fechner"). 

When  two  vibrating  bodies  are  in  contact  with  the  head  or 
very  near  to  it,  and  the  energy  of  vibration  is  unequal,  the 

^Starch  (Op.  cit.,  p.  52.)  phrases  this  as  follows.  "The  accuracy  of  lo- 
calization is  greatest  where  slight  changes  in  the  ratio  are  most  readily 
perceived,  *.  e.,  in  front  and  back.  Localization  is  poorest  where  changes  in 
the  ratio  are  not  so  easily  perceived,  i.  e.,  on  the  sides,  in  the  region  of  the 
aural  axis." 

^Op  cit.,  pp.  31,  35. 

'Psychol.  Rev.,  Monog,  Suppl.,  Vol.  VI,  No.  4,  1904-05,  pp.  11-12  and 
44;  ibid.,  Vol.  IX,  No.  2,  1908,  pp.  52-53. 

^Thompson:  Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  5,  Vol.  VIII,  1879,  p.  386;  ibid.,  Vol. 
XIII,  1882,  p.  412. 

^Op.  cit.,  p.  120. 

^Op.  cit.,  pp.  188-189.  Steinhauser  used  as  the  source  of  sound  an  instru- 
ment called  by  him  the  homophone.  This  instrument  consisted  of  two 
organ  pipes  of  the  same  pitch,  one  of  which  was  supported  near  to  each  ear 
on  the  level  with  it.  The  intensity  of  the  sound  was  regulated  by  means 
of  valves  controlling  the  pressure  of  the  air  blast  used  to  excite  it. 

''Op.  cit.,  p.  354. 

^Op.  cit.,  p.  18.  Matsumoto  used  two  telephone  receivers  placed  opposite 
the  two  ears,  one  on  each  side.  The  intensity  of  the  sound  in  each  ear  was 
controlled  by  a  sliding  inductorium. 

^Stenger:  Op.  cit.,  p.  223. 

"Fechner,   G.  T.:  Op.  cit.,  p.  543. 


AUDITORY  LOCAUZATION  27 1 

sound  is  localized  within  the  head  but  is  referred  to  the  side 
receiving  the  greater  energy  of  vibration  (Urbantschitsch,* 
and  Thompson^). 

When  the  stem  of  a  vibrating  tuning  fork  is  placed  on  the 
vertex  of  the  skull,  the  tone  is  localized  somewhere  midway 
between  the  two  ears ;  but  if  the  meatus  of  one  ear  is  stopped 
and  the  wave  is  reflected  back  toward  the  internal  ear,  the 
sound  is  transferred  immediately  to  that  side  (Weber^). 

When  a  tuning-fork  is  faintly  sounded  on  one  side  and  heard 
by  the  ear  on  that  side  by  means  of  a  resonator,  the  sound  is 
referred  to  that  side;  but  when  the  meatus  of  the  opposite 
ear  is  stopped,  the  sound  approaches  the  median  plane 
(Schaefer^). 

One  of  two  fusing  sounds  may  be  placed  in  either  of  the 
lateral  quadrants  without  altering  the  localization  of  the 
fusion  (Pierce^). 

II.   ExPERIMENTAIv 
A.   THE   DEMONSTRATION   OF   THE   BINAURAI^  RATIO 
AS  A   FACTOR 

(a)  Lines  of  Argument.  The  object  of  this  paper  is  to  add 
three  lines  of  argument  to  those  mentioned  above,  (i)  Ob- 
servers having  a  natural  difference  in  sensitivity  of  the  two 
ears  show  a  constant  tendency  to  displace  the  source  of  sound 
toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  stronger  ear;  and,  con- 
versely, observers  without  this  difference  in  sensitivity  show  no 
consistent  tendency  toward  right  or  left  displacement.  (2) 
Changes  in  the  ratio  of  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears,  produced 
by  plugging  either  ear,  are  followed  by  corresponding  dis- 
placements of  the  sound  toward  the  more  sensitive  ear.  (3) 
A  natural  tendency  toward  right  or  left  displacement  can  be 
corrected  by  making  the  proper  change  in  the  ratio  of  sensi- 
tivity of  the  two  ears. 

The  principle  involved  in  the  second  argument  is  not  en- 
tirely new.^     It  aims  at  a  direct  and  systematic  correlation 

^Urbantschitsch:  Lehre  von  der  Schallempfindung,  Pfliiger's  Archiv, 
XXIV,  1 88 1,  579. 

^Thompson,  On  Binaural  Audition,  Philos.  Mag.,  Ser.  5,  Vol  .IV,  1877, 
pp.  274-276;  Phenomena  of  Binaural  Audition,  ibid.,  Ser.  5,  Vol.  VI,  1878, 
PP-  383-391. 

^Weber:  Op.  cit.,  p.  42. 

^Schaefer:  Op.  cit.,  pp.  111-114. 

^Pierce:  Op.  cit.,  pp.  63  and  147. 

•It  might  probably  be  said  that  the  principle  involved  in  the  first  line  of 
argument  is  also  not  entirely  new.  Results  of  monaural  localization  have 
been  reported  by  numerous  investigators;  and  occasional  mention  has  been 
made  of  a  suspected  influence  of  difference  in  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears  upon 
the  results  obtained  in  cases  of  binaural  localization.  (For  the  best  example 
of  this,  vide  Seashore :  Localization  of  Sound  in  the  Median  Plane,  Univ.  of 


272  FERRHE  AND  COIyUNS 

between  the  intensity  of  the  sound  as  heard  by  the  two  ears, 
and  the  direction  in  which  it  is  referred.  This  has  not  been 
attempted  before,  although  it  has  been  shown  more  or  less 
definitely  that  a  difference  in  the  energy  of  the  sound-wave 
delivered  to  the  two  ears  affects  localization.  Thompson,^  for 
example,  with  his  pseudophone,  tried  to  produce  a  difference  in 
the  energy  of  the  stimuli  given  to  the  two  ears  by  means  of  the 
way  in  which  the  shell-shaped  collectors  were  turned  with  refer- 
ence to  the  direction  of  the  stimulus,  and  to  show  thereby  that 
the  localization  was  determined  toward  the  side  receiving  the 
stronger  stimulation.  Though  the  underlying  principle  of 
this  general  line  of  argument  is  not  new,  the  writers  have  fol- 
lowed it  up  for  the  following  reasons,  (i)  Its  possibilities 
for  demonstrating  the  binaural  ratio  as  a  factor  in  localiza- 
tion have  not  been  fully  utilized.  (2)  In  order  to  confirm 
the  intensity  theory,  it  is  necessary  to  show  a  definite  corre- 
lation between  the  ratio  of  intensity  of  sensation,  and  the 
direction  in  which  the  sound  is  referred.  The  method  of 
varying  the  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears  gives  a  much  safer 
and  more  direct  means  of  establishing  this  correlation  than 
is  given  by  varying  the  intensity  of  the  stimuli.  The  writers 
find,  for  example,  that  the  ears  of  many  people  vary  greatly 
in  sensitivity.  In  fact,  so  far  as  his  experience  goes,  it  is 
more  common  to  find  a  difference  than  to  find  the  ears  of 

Iowa  Studies  in  Psychol.,  1899,  II,  p.  49).  But  for  theory,  monaural  hear- 
ing presents  a  very  different  case  from  difference  in  sensitivity  in  binaural 
hearing  (when  working  with  monaural  hearing  the  binaural  factors  drop 
out  entirely) ;  and,  furthermore,  no  systematic  attempt  has  ever  been  made 
to  utihze  differences  in  sensitivity  as  a  means  of  demonstrating  the  influ- 
ence of  the  binaural  ratio. 

For  reports  on  monaural  localization,  see  Politzer  {Loc.  cit.);  Preyer  (Die 
Wahrnehmung  der  Schallrichtung  mittelst  der  Bogengdnge,  Pfltiger's  Archiv, 
XL,  1887,  S.  586);  Amheim  (Beitrdge  zur  Theorie  der  Lokal.  von  Schallempf. 
mittelst  der  Bogengdnge,  Diss.  1887.);  Miinsterberg  {Raumsinn  des  Ohres, 
Beitrage  zur  Exp.  Psy.,  Bd.  II,  1889,  S.  182),  von  Bezold  (Urteilstduschun- 
gen  nach  Beseitigung  einseitiger  Harthdrigkeit,  Zeit.  f.  Psy.  u.  Physiol.  II, 
1890,  S.  486);  Schafer  {Ein  Versuch  iiber  die  interkranielle  Leitung  leisester 
Tone  von  Ohr  zu  Ohr,  Zeit.  f.  Psy.  u.  Physiol.  II,  1891,  S.  iii);  Smith  {How 
do  we  Detect  the  Direction  from  which  Sound  Comes  ?  Cincin.  Lancet- 
Clmic,  N.  S.  XXVIII,  1892,  542);  Angell  and  Fite  (The  Monaural  Localiza- 
tion of  Sound,  Psy.  Rev.  VIII,  1910,  225-266,  and  Further  Observations  on 
the  Monaural  Localization  of  Sound,  Ibid.,  449-458);  and  Starch  (Perime- 
try of  the  Localization  of  Sound,  Psy.  Rev.  Mon.  Supp.  IX,  2,  1908,  1-55)- 
For  mention  of  a  suspected  influence  of  difference  in  the  sensitivity  of  the  two 
ears  upon  localization,  see  Pierce  (Op.  cit.,  p.  106),  and  Starch  (Op.  cit.,  pp. 
43-44).  An  influence  of  difference  of  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears  is  suggested 
by  Amheim  (Op.  cit.,  p.  10,  note)  to  explain  his  results  when  working  with 
monaural  hearing  artificially  produced.  The  left  ear  was  found  to  have  the 
superior  power  to  localize  correctly.  He  thought  this  might  be  due  to  its 
better  blood  supply.  Pierce  speaks  against  this  part  of  Amheim's  work 
{Op.  cit.,  p.  107). 

^Op.  cit.,  pp.  385-390- 


AUDITORY  LOCALIZATION  273 

approximately  equal  sensitivity.^  A  method,  then,  which 
seeks  to  vary  the  intensity  of  the  sound  as  heard  by  the  two 
ears,  and  does  not  take  into  account  their  probable  difference 
in  sensitivity,  is  obviously  at  fault;  for  there  is  no  guarantee 
that  a  slight  difference  in  the  energy  of  the  sound-waves  de- 
livered to  the  two  ears,  such  as  was  produced  by  a  different 
setting  of  the  small  shell-shaped  collectors  of  Thompson's 
pseudophone,  will  be  sensed  as  the  relative  intensities  of  the 
stimuli  would  indicate.  If  one  ear  should  be  more  sensitive 
than  the  other,  the  two  sound-waves,  although  one  is  stronger 
than  the  other,  may  be  sensed  as  equal  in  intensity;  or  the 
ratio  indicated  by  the  stimuli  may  be  reversed.  Because, 
then,  of  the  common  occurrence  of  a  natural  difference  in 
sensitivity  between  the  ears,  a  method  that  attempts  to 
measure  the  ratio  of  intensity  of  the  sensations  experienced 
by  the  ratio  of  intensity  of  the  stimuli  given,  does  not  afford 
a  safe  basis  for  a  correlation  between  the  intensity  of  the 
sound  as  heard  by  the  two  ears  and  its  localization.  (3)  Apart 
from  the  propriety  of  method,  a  third  reason  for  contin- 
uing this  line  of  attack  is  that  the  results  reported  from  it 
have  been  too  vague  and  uncertain  to  give  much  support  to 
the  intensity  theory.  For  example,  (a)  the  shell-shaped 
collectors  in  Thompson's  pseudophone  were  assumed  to  col- 
lect more  sound  when  given  one  direction  than  when  given 
another;  but  there  was  no  objective  determination  of  how 
much  they  varied  the  intensity  of  the  wave  impinging  upon 
the  tympanum,  or  whether  they  varied  it  at  all.  No  proper 
basis  was  laid  even  for  a  correlation  of  ratio  of  intensity  of 
the  two  stimuli  with  the  direction  in  which  the  sound  was 
referred,  (b)  The  method  used  for  recording  Thompson's 
localizations  was  indefinite,  and  his  report  of  results  is  vague 
and  uncertain.  In  short,  a  characteristic  displacement  of  the 
sound  toward  the  side  receiving  the  more  intensive  stimula- 
tion is  expressed  (in  the  paper  of  1879)  as  a  matter  of  belief 
rather  than  as  an  established  fact.^ 

(b)  Description  of  Method  and  Apparatus.  The  writers  were 
led  to  make  this  study  by  the  results  of  tests  they  had  been 
conducting  on  the  relative  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears  in  differ- 
ent people.  The  large  number  of  subjects  who  were  found 
to  have  a  marked  difference  in  sensitivity  seemed  to  make 
possible  a  determination  of  whether  or  not  the  hearing  of  a 

^Fechner,  investigating  the  relative  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears  ( Ueher  die 
ungleiche  Deutlichkeit  des  Gehdrs  auf  linkem  und  rechtem  Ohre,  Berichte 
der  kgl.  Sachs.  Ges.  der  Wiss.  Math.-phys.  Classe,  XII,  i860,  166-174) » 
found  that  out  of  2 15  persons  examined  only  51  had  ears  of  approximately 
equal  sensitivity. 

^Op.  cit.,  pp.  388-390. 


2  74  F^RREE  AND  COLUNS 

sound  more  strongly  by  one  ear  than  the  other  leads  to  con- 
stant errors  in  localization.  Assuming  that  the  binaural 
ratio  is  a  factor  in  localizing,  there  seem  a  priori  to  be  two 
possibilities  relative  to  this  question,  (a)  The  subject  so 
affected  may,  in  proportion  to  his  defect,  show  a  constant 
tendency  to  displace  the  sound  towards  the  aural  axis  on  the 
side  of  the  more  sensitive  ear,  or  (b)  this  tendency  may  have 
been  wholly  or  in  part  corrected  in  the  subject's  past  expe- 
rience, through  the  influence  of  the  space  reference  of  other 
sense  organs,  in  such  a  fashion  that  the  false  ratio  has  shown  a 
tendency  to  become  associated  with  the  true  reference.  If  so, 
the  amount  of  the  constant  error  probably  should  sustain  some 
ratio  to  the  length  of  time  the  defect  had  existed.  If,  for  ex- 
ample, it  were  congenital  or  contracted  very  early  in  life,  one 
might  expect  less  error  in  localization  than  if  it  were  of  recent 
occurrence.  Unfortunately  the  subjects,  up  to  the  time  of  these 
tests,  were  not  aware  of  their  defect,  consequently  no  data 
of  the  sort  were  available.  The  effect  of  recency  of  defect, 
however,  came  out  strongly  in  the  experiments  in  which  the 
ratio  was  varied  by  artificial  means.  Differences  in  sensi- 
tivity, artificially  produced,  exerted  a  much  more  marked  in- 
fluence upon  localization  than  did  approximately  equal  differ- 
ences due  to  natural  defect. 

Artificial  variations  were  produced  both  upon  defective 
subjects  and  upon  subjects  in  whom  the  sensitivity  of  the  two 
ears  was  approximately  equal.  In  both  cases  the  effect  was 
marked  and  consistent.  In  case  of  the  normal  subjects,  in 
turn  first  one  ear  was  made  more  sensitive,  then  the  other. 
In  case  of  the  defective  subjects  three  variations  were  intro- 
duced, (a)  The  defect  was  exaggerated,  i.  e.,  the  difference 
in  sensitivity  was  rendered  greater  by  plugging  the  less  sensi- 
tive ear.^  (b)  An  effort  was  made  to  correct  the  defect  by 
decreasing  the  sensitivity  of  the  stronger  ear.  Our  object 
here  was  to  establish  a  ratio  of  sensitivity  that  should  elimi- 
nate any  approach  to  a  constant  tendency  to  displace  the 
sound  in  either  direction.  This  was  a  procedure  involving 
many  trials  and  much  patience.  Our  first  idea  was  that 
this  result  should  be  attained  by  equating  the  sensitivity  of 
the  two  ears.     This  device,  however,  in  case  of  the  subjects 

^In  all  cases  of  plugging  one  ear,  care  was  taken  that  monaural  hearing 
was  not  produced.  Before  the  observation  began,  both  ears  were  firmly 
closed  by  the  hands  or  some  other  efifective  means,  until  the  stimulus  used 
in  the  localizing  experiments  could  no  longer  be  heard,  whatever  position  it 
might  be  given  in  the  system  used.  The  plugged  ear  was  then  uncovered, 
and  the  stimulus  given  at  the  most  remote  positions  to  be  used  in  the  ex- 
periment which  was  to  follow.  In  no  case  was  the  observer  imable  to  hear 
the  sotmd. 


AUDITORY  IvOCAUZATlON 


275 


used,  overshot  the  mark.  When  the  sensitivity  of  the  stronger 
ear  was  decreased  until  it  approximately  equalled  that  of 
the  weaker  ear,  a  constant  tendency  to  displace  towards  the 
normally  weaker  ear  resulted.  A  compromise  position  then 
had  to  be  sought.  We  finally  succeeded  in  getting,  with 
each  subject,  a  ratio  such  that  the  error,  roughly  speaking, 
was  apparently  about  as  much  and  as  frequently  to  one  side  as 
to  the  other  of  the  true  location,  (c)  A  third  variation  was 
to  plug  the  stronger  ear  until  it  became  less  sensitive  than  the 
weaker  ear. 

In  all  of  our  experiments,  in  order  to  guard  against  a  wrong 
correlation  of  ratio  with  localization  error,  due  to  possible 
variations  in  sensitivity  from  day  to  day,  or  even  from  the 
beginning  to  the  end  of  the  experiment,  sensitivity  determina- 
tions were  made  at  each  sitting  both  immediately  before  and 
immediately  after  the  localizing  tests  were  made. 

The  ratio  of  sensitivity  was  obtained  by  comparing  the  limen 
of  sound  for  the  two  ears.  The  observer  was  blindfolded  and 
required  to  bite  an  impression  previously  made  in  a  wax  mouth- 
board.  A  wooden  bar  was  supported  in  the  line  of  the  axis 
of  the  two  ears,  one  end  reaching  as  near  as  possible  to  the 
ear  that  was  being  tested.  The  other  ear  was  carefully  plugged. 
A  watch  was  carried  out  along  the  bar  until  the  limen  was 
reached.  An  average  of  the  results  obtained  by  the  method 
of  approach  and  recession  was  taken  as  the  final  liminal  dis- 
tance, and  the  ratio  of  these  distances  was  taken  to  represent 
the  ratio  of  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears.  To  make  sure  that 
the  plugged  ear  was  not  functioning  in  these  tests,  the  watch 
was  held  as  closely  as  possible  to  it  without  touching  the  lobe 
and  the  observer  required  to  tell  whether  it  could  be  heard 
or  not. 

The  localizing  experiments  were  carried  on  by  means  of 
the  Titchener  sound-cage.  A  Galton  whistle  set  at  20,000 
vibrations  per  second  was  used  for  the  stimulus.  As  to  de- 
vices for  indicating  the  location  of  the  sound,  the  pointing 
method,  the  chart  method,  and  a  combination  of  the  two 
were  used  at  different  times.  The  authors  have  not  made  an 
exhaustive  study  of  the  relative  merits  of  these  methods  but 
is  inclined  to  prefer,  on  the  basis  of  what  they  have  done,  a  care- 
ful use  of  the  pointing  method  alone.  Any  method  involv- 
ing the  use  of  the  chart  has,  in  his  experience,  fostered  a  tend- 
ency on  the  part  of  the  observer  to  delay  the  reference,  to 
become  uncertain  and  hesitating,  to  reason  and  debate  with 
himself  rather  than  to  let  whatever  sensory  mechanism  for 
localizing  with  which  nature  may  have  provided  him  work 
itself  out  automatically.  The  errors  arising  from  this  tendency 
are,  in  our  opinion,  greater  and  more  capricious  than  those  from 


276 


FERREE  AND  COLUNS 


wrong  pointing,  if  proper  care  is  exercised  to  make  sure  that 
the  observer  is  pointing  as  he  intends  to  point.  The  ques- 
tion of  methods  of  recording,  however,  makes  little  difference 
for  or  against  the  validity  of  our  demonstration;  for  (a) 
the  constant  displacement  tendency  appears  whatever  the 
method  used,  and  (b)  no  method,  however  comprehensive  its 
faults,  could  account  for  the  consistent  throw  in  opposite  di- 
rections in  case  of  different  observers,  or  in  the  case  of  the  same 
observer,  when  first  one  ear  then  the  other  is  made  more 
sensitive. 


fP%.r 


itcrr. 


fjof?, 


fo'nr 


Fig.  Ill 


o°B. 

180°  F. 

45°  R.  F.  or  L.  F. 

135°  R.  F.  or  L.  F 

50°  R.  F.  or  L.  F. 

130°  R.  F.  or  L.  F 

60°  R.  F.  or  L.  F. 

120°  R.  F.  orlv.  F 

70°  R.  F.  or  L.  F. 

iio^'R.  F.  orL.  F 

150°  R.  F.  or  L.  F. 

30°  R.  F.  or  L.  F 

160°  R.  F.  or  L.  F. 

20°  R.  F.  or  L.  F 

Thus  far  results  have  been  obtained  from  ten  observers  in 
the  investigation  proper.  In  addition,  the  writers  have  roughly 
used,  at  one  time  or  another  for  two  years,  all  of  the  variations 
as  a  part  of  the  drill  course  in  his  undergraduate  laboratory. 

(c)  Results.  The  following  tables  have  been  compiled 
from  the  results  of  three  of  these  observers,  who  were  selected 
as  representative:  the  Misses  Friend  (F.),  Root  (R.),  and 


AUDITORY  LOCALIZATION 


277 


Sharp  (5.).  Tables  I-XII,  inclusive,  show  the  results  of  the 
experiments  devised  to  demonstrate  the  importance  of  the 
binaural  ratio  as  a  factor  in  auditory  localization.  In  all  the 
tables  given  throughout  the  paper,  locations  in  the  horizontal 
plane  are  expressed  in  terms  of  the  readings  of  the  Titchener 
sound-cage.  In  this  system  of  reference,  the  zero  point  is 
placed  in  the  median  plane,  behind ;  the  90°  points  in  the  aural 
axis,  right  and  left;  and  the  180°  point  in  the  median  plane 
in  front.  It  was  found  more  convenient,  however,  in  the 
vertical  planes,  to  deviate  from  the  scale  of  the  sound-cage; 
the  zero  point  was  taken  in  the  plane  of  the  aural  axis,  and 
directions  were  read  90°  up  and  down.  Displacements  to 
right  or  left  were  estimated  from  the  actual  position  of  the 
stimulus,  or  from  its  corresponding  point  front  or  back,  as 
the  case  happened  to  be.  For  example,  a  stimulus  given  at 
160°  right  front  (R.  F.)  might  be  referred  by  the  observer 
either  to  160°  R.  F.  or  to  its  corresponding  point,  20°  R.  F., 
without  the  reference  being  considered  a  displacement  toward 
either  ear.     But  if  a  stimulus  were  given  at  160°  R.  F.  and 

Tablb  I 

Observer  F.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  upon  the  locali- 
zation of  clangs.  Natural  sensitivity  series.  Liminal  distance  for  right 
ear,  40  cm. ;  for  left  ear,  40  cm.  Ratio,  Left :  Right  =  i .  Stimulus,  Galton 
whistle,  20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

toward  axis  of 
right  ear 

toward  axis  of 
left  ear 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

45°  RF 

0'' 

50°  RF 

o°d 

5° 

135°  L  F 

0° 

50°  Iv  F 

8°d 

5° 

o«B 

0° 

o^B 

5°d 

0° 

0° 

135°  R  F 

0*' 

125"  R  F 

5°u 

10" 

45°  LF 

45°  u 

50"  L  F 

5°u 

5° 

180*'       F 

O** 

20°  L  F 

0'' 

20*' 

135°  L  F 

45°  u 

40"  L  F 

20*' d 

5° 

45°  L  F 

45°  d 

50"'  L  F 

40"  d 

5° 

150°  R  F 

0" 

145°  R  F 

0" 

5° 

o°B 

45°  u 

10''  R  F 

0" 

10" 

45°  RF 

45°  u 

50°  R  F 

0*" 

5° 

180**       F 

45°  u 

o°B 

40°  u 

0'' 

0° 

135°  R  F 

45°  u 

135°  R  F 

30"  u 

o** 

o** 

150*'  L  F 

45°  u 

35°  L  F 

25°  u 

5° 

o^B 

90**  u 

20°  RF 

20**  U 

20*^ 

70''  L  F 

0° 

70"  LF 

o'' 

0° 

0** 

50°  R  F 

45°  d 

120"  R  F 

5°d 

10'' 

70°  R  F 

o'* 

80°  R  F 

Q° 

10*' 

o^'B 

0- 

0"  B 

0" 

0" 

0° 

Average  displacement  from  median  plane  2.1°  (right). 


278 


FERREE  AND  COLUNS 


were  referred  either  to  140°  R.  F.  or  to  40°  R.  F.,  the  reference 
would  be  considered  a  displacement  toward  the  axis  of  the 
right  ear.  Fig.  3  shows  a  diagram  of  the  horizontal  plane 
of  reference,  with  two  pairs  of  corresponding  points  repre- 
sented. Below  it  are  given  readings  in  degrees  for  the  corres- 
ponding points  used  in  the  experiments. 

Tables  I,  II,  and  III  show  the  results  for  the  natural  differ- 
ence in  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears  for  Observers  F.,  R.,  and 
5.,  respectively.     In  each  case,  the  liminal  distance  for  the 

Tabids  II 

Observer  R.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  localiza- 
tion of  clangs.  Natural  sensitivity  series.  Liminal  distance:  right  ear, 
18.5  cm.;  left  ear,  72  cm.  Ratio,  Left  :  Right =4.  Stimulus,  Galton 
whistle,   20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

toward  axis  of 
stronger  ear 

toward  axis  of 
weaker  ear 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

45"  RF 

o'' 

25°  RF 

30°  d 

20** 

135"  I.  F 

0° 

50"  L  F 

30°  d 

5° 

o^B 

0° 

15°  Iv  F 

50°  d 

15° 

135°  R  F 

0° 

40''  R  F 

38'*d 

5° 

45**  Iv  F 

45°  u 

60**  L  F 

35°  d 

15° 

iSo'*       F 

0° 

35°  L  F 

20"  d 

35° 

135°  L  F 

45°  ti 

70°  L  F 

38°  d 

25° 

45^  L  F 

45°  d 

55°  h  F 

33°  d 

10° 

150°  R  F 

0° 

40°  R  F 

42"  d 

io'» 

o«B 

45°  u 

35°  L  F 

35°  d 

35° 

45"  RF 

45°  u 

10°  R  F 

45°  d 

35° 

i8o«       F 

45°  u 

30"  L  F 

42M 

30° 

135"  R  F 

45°  u 

15°  RF 

45°  d 

30'' 

ISO**  L  F 

45°  u 

40"  L  F 

35°  d 

io« 

o^'B 

90°  u 

50°  L  F 

10'' d 

50^* 

yo**  L  F 

o** 

70°  L  F 

loM 

o** 

o*' 

50**  RF 

45°  d 

15°  R  F 

50°  d 

35° 

70**  R  F 

o** 

50**  R  F 

38°  d 

20° 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,   20.3° 

ticking  of  a  watch  was  determined  for  each  ear  both  before 
and  after  the  observations,  and  the  ratio  of  sensitivity  was 
computed  from  these  distances.  For  observer  F.  this  distance 
was  found  to  be  40  cm.  for  each  ear.  Estimated  in  terms  of 
these  distances,  then,  the  observer's  ears  were  approximately 
equal  in  sensitivity.  As  the  tables  show,  the  ears  of  observers 
R.  and  S.  were  found  to  be  of  unequal  sensitivity.  It  will 
be  noted  that  a  rough  correspondence  holds  in  each  case  be- 
tween the  ratio  of  sensitivity  of  the  ears,  and  the  observer's 
characteristic  localizing  tendency. 


AUDITORY  LOCAUZATION 


279 


Table  III 

Observer  S.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  clangs.  Natural  sensitivity  series.  Liminal  distance:  right 
ear,  97  cm.;  left  ear,  33  cm.  Ratio,  Right  :  Left  =  2.9.  Stimulus,  Galton 
whistle,   20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

frtMffarcl  nvi*?  r»f 

toward  axis  of 
weaker  ear 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Stronger  ear 

135°  R  F 

o*' 

5°  RF 

5°d 

40° 

45**  L  F 

o*' 

30°  L  F 

o** 

15° 

ISO**  L  F 

45°  d 

10°  L  F 

0° 

20^ 

o°B 

45°  u 

o''B 

45°  u 

o*' 

o** 

180°       F 

45°  d 

5°Iv  F 

35°  d 

5° 

45**  RF 

45°  u 

50°  R  F 

35°  u 

5° 

135*  R  F 

45°  u 

45°  RF 

52°  u 

0^ 

0'' 

160''  L  F 

0** 

0° 

o*' 

20'' 

o-B 

90°  u 

30'*  RF 

12**  U 

30° 

70^  L  F 

0° 

65°  L  F 

0° 

5° 

135"  h  F 

0^ 

25°  h  F 

O** 

20» 

45°  RF 

45°  d 

10"  R  F 

15°  d 

35° 

o°B 

90°  u 

25°  RF 

12'' u 

25° 

60*  RF 

0° 

70°  R  F 

18°  u 

10'' 

150''  R  F 

o** 

50*^  R  F 

15°  u 

20° 

45''I.  F 

45°  u 

o-B 

2''d 

45° 

60''  L  F 

45°  u 

5°  I.  F 

30°  u 

55° 

160*'  R  F 

0^ 

25°  R  F 

10**  u 

5° 

60**  L  F 

45°  d 

40°  L  F 

loM 

20° 

o^'B 

0° 

o'^B 

5°d 

0° 

o« 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  10.7°. 

Tables  IV  and  V  show  the  effect  upon  localization  for  ob- 
servers R.  and  5.,  produced  by  exaggerating  the  natural  ratio 
of  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears  by  plugging  the  weaker  ear.  It 
will  be  noticed  that  in  each  case  the  observer's  tendency  to 
displace  the  sound  toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  stronger 
ear  is  increased.  For  example,  with  the  natural  difference  in 
sensitivity,  Observer  R.'s  average  displacement  toward  the 
axis  on  the  side  of  the  stronger  ear  was  20.3°  (Table  II) ;  with 
the  exaggeration  of  the  natural  difference,  the  average  dis- 
placement became  31.6°  (Table  IV).  For  Observer  S.,  the 
average  displacement  toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the 
stronger  ear,  with  the  natural  difference  in  sensitivity,  was 
10.7°  (Table  III) ;  with  the  exaggeration  of  this  difference,  the 
displacement  was  increased  to  17.2°  (Table  V). 

Tables  VI  and  VII  show  the  effect  upon  localization,  for 
Observers  R.  and  S.,  produced  by  plugging  the  stronger  ear 
until  it  became  less  sensitive  than  the  weaker  ear.  The  re- 
sult in  each  case  was  to  change  the  characteristic  displacement 
to  the  opposite  side — now  the  side  of  the  stronger  ear.     For 


28o 


FBRREE  AND  COLUNS 


example,  for  Observer  R.,  when  the  ratio  was  changed  from 
left:  right=4,  to  right:  left  =  6.2,  the  average  displacement  of 
20.3°  toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  left  ear  was  changed 
to  an  average  displacement  on  the  side  of  the  right  ear  of 
34.4°.  And  for  Observer  S.,  when  the  ratio  right: left  =  2.9 
was  changed  to  left :  right  =  3.8,  the  average  displacement  was 
changed  from  10.7°  toward  the  right  to  34.6°  toward  the  left. 

Table  IV 

Observer  R.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  clangs.  Artificial  sensitivity  series.  Right  ear  plugged.  Limi- 
nal  distance:  right  ear,  3  cm.;  left  ear,  71  cm.  Ratio,  Left  :  Right  =  23.6. 
Stimulus,  Galton  whistle,  20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

toward  axis  of 
stronger  ear 

toward  axis  of 
weaker  ear 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

o°B 

0° 

30°  L  F 

40*' d 

30** 

45"  RF 

O** 

10*'  L  F 

35°  d 

55° 

iSo**       F 

0° 

60''  L  F 

10°  d 

60'' 

135"  L  F 

o** 

55°  L  F 

15°  d 

10° 

60°  L  F 

o** 

70"  L  F 

15°  d 

10" 

o^'B 

45"  u 

40"  h  F 

48°  d 

40° 

135"  R  F 

0'' 

45°  RF 

40°  d 

0° 

0'' 

180°       F 

45°  u 

40"  L  F 

50°  d 

40° 

45**  L  F 

45'' d 

55°  L  F 

12*' d 

lO** 

135°  R  F 

45°  d 

40''  R  F 

43°  d 

5° 

o**B 

45°  d 

35°  L  F 

25°  d 

35° 

180°       F 

45°  d 

30°  L  F 

15°  d 

30- 

45^  RF 

45°  u 

25°  h  F 

45°  d 

TO'' 

iSS''  h  F 

45°  u 

50"  L  F 

15°  d 

5° 

45"  L  F 

45°  u 

60^  L  F 

40°  d 

15° 

135^  R  F 

45°  u 

15°  L  F 

32°  d 

60" 

o^'B 

90**  u 

15°  L  F 

15°  d 

15° 

45"  RF 

45°  d 

35°  L  F 

18°  d 

80° 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  31.6**. 

Tables  VIII  and  IX  show  the  effect  upon  localization  made 
by  producing  artifi^cial  differences  in  the  sensitivity  of  the  ears 
for  Observer  F.,  whose  natural  sensitivity  is  approximately 
equal  for  both  ears.  When  the  left  ear  was  plugged  until  the 
ratio  right: left  =  4.3  was  obtained,  the  average  displace- 
ment toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  right  ear  was  found 
to  be  17°.  And  when  the  right  ear  was  plugged  until  the 
ratio  left :  right  =  4.1  was  obtained,  the  average  displacement 
toward  the  side  of  the  left  ear  was  found  to  be  18.2°.  It  will 
be  remembered  from  Table  I  that  the  average  of  the  locali- 
zations for  this  observer  with  natural  hearing  showed  a  dis- 
placement toward  the  right  of  2.1°. 


I 


AUDITORY  LOCAUZATION 


281 


TabIvE  V 

Observer  S.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the 
localization  of  clangs.  Artificial  sensitivity  series.  Left  ear  plugged, 
iriminal  distance:  right  ear,  97  cm.;  left  ear,  10  cm.  Ratio,  Right  :  Iveft  = 
9.7.     Stimulus,  Galton  whistle,  20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

toward  axis  of 
stronger  ear 

toward  axis  of 
weaker  ear 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

O^B 

0" 

45°  RF 

0** 

45° 

45"  R  F 

0° 

35°  RF 

0° 

10^ 

135"  L  F 

0° 

5°  L  F 

7°d 

40° 

180**       F 

0" 

10"  R  F 

8«d 

lO** 

135"  R  F 

0'' 

20°  R  F 

0° 

25° 

45"  L  F 

45°  u 

5°  Iv  F 

14°  d 

40* 

o-'B 

45°  u 

50''  R  F 

15°  u 

50° 

135"  R  F 

45°  u 

40"  R  F 

8*»u 

5° 

135"  L  F 

45°  u 

25°  L  F 

12°  u 

20** 

180°       F 

45°  u 

30°  RF 

20°  u 

30" 

45°  RF 

45°  u 

52°  RF 

30'' u 

7° 

45°  L  F 

45°  d 

35"  L  F 

8°d 

10" 

o*'B 

45°  d 

20**  R  F 

8^u 

20« 

45°  RF 

45°  d 

ao**  R  F 

15°  u 

15° 

135°  h  F 

45°  d 

45°  Iv  F 

30*  u 

o** 

o** 

180°       F 

45°  d 

20°  R  F 

15°  u 

20« 

135°  R  F 

45°  d 

45°  RF 

10*  u 

0^ 

0** 

o°B 

90°  u 

40''  R  F 

10°  u 

40° 

60"  L  F 

0° 

40*'  L  F 

10°  u 

20*' 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  17.2**. 

Table  X  shows  the  effect  upon  localization,  in  the  case  of 
Observer  R.,  of  an  attempt  to  equate  the  sensitivity  of  the  ears. 
The  natural  ratio  of  sensitivity  for  this  observer  (Table  II) 
was  left: right  =  4.  When  this  was  changed  by  plugging  the 
left  ear  until  the  ratio  right:  left  =  1.02  (18.5-^18.2)  was  ob- 
tained, there  resulted  an  average  displacement  31.4°  toward 
the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  right  ear.  Results  of  this  kind 
were  obtained  for  all  observers.  A  characteristic  tendency 
to  displace  the  sound  to  right  or  left  cannot  be  corrected  by 
equating  the  ratio  of  sensitivity  of  the  ears.  A  value  must 
be  obtained  somewhere  between  the  natural  ratio  and  equal 
sensitivity.^ 

^That  the  effect  of  equating  the  sensitivity  should  overshoot  the  mark  is 
not  at  all  strange.  If  one  ear  naturally  hears  more  loudly  than  the  other, 
an  equal  intensity  of  sensation  has  never  been  associated  in  the  observer's 
experience  with  objects  in  the  median  plane,  but  always  with  some  position 
displaced  from  the  median  plane  toward  the  naturally  weaker  ear.  Then 
when  the  stronger  ear  is  plugged  until  it  is  of  the  same  sensitivity  as  the 
weaker  ear,  sounds  which  can  be  heard  as  equally  loud  by  both  ears,  i.  e., 
sounds  coming  from  the  median  plane,  will  not  be  referred  to  that  plane, 

JouRNAi, — 10 


282 


FERREE  AND  COLUNS 


Table  VI 
Observer  R.     Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  clangs.     Artificial  sensitivity  series.     Left  ear  plugged.     Liminal 
distance:  right  ear,   18.5  cm,;  left  ear,  3  cm.     Ratio,  Right  :  Left  =  6. 2. 
Stimulus,  Galton  whistle,  20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

toward  axis  of 
stronger  ear 

toward  axis  of 
weaker  ear 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

45"  RF 

0° 

65°  RF 

0° 

20** 

o«B 

90"  U 

15°  RF 

42M 

15° 

180°       F 

45°  d 

25°  RF 

40M 

25° 

60**  L  F 

0" 

25°  RF 

40°  d 

85° 

135"  R  F 

0" 

40''  R  F 

25°  d 

5° 

45°  RF 

45°  d 

45°  RF 

18°  d 

o'' 

0° 

las''  Iv  F 

45°  d 

4°  RF 

40M 

49° 

o°B 

45°  d 

30"  R  F 

32°  d 

30° 

45°  Iv  F 

45°  d 

55°  RF 

20M 

100*' 

135°  L  F 

45°  u 

5°  RF 

35°  d 

50° 

135°  R  F 

0° 

40"  R  F 

20**  d 

5° 

45°  RF 

45°  u 

SO*'  RF 

10"  d 

5° 

180"       F 

45°  u 

25°  RF 

38M 

25° 

45°  L  F 

45°  u 

45°  RF 

42''d 

90° 

135°  R  F 

45°  u 

45°  RF 

45°  d 

0" 

0° 

o°B 

45°  u 

45°  RF 

20°  d 

45° 

180"       F 

0° 

25°  R  F 

38°  d 

25° 

135°  L  F 

0^ 

5°  R  F 

28"  d 

50° 

o^'B 

c** 

50''  R  F 

40**  d 

50'' 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  34.4**. 

Tables  XI  and  XII  show  the  results  of  fairly  successful 
attempts  to  correct  this  observer's  tendency  to  displace  sounds 
towards  the  left.  In  Table  XII  with  a  ratio  left  :right  =  i  .5  we 
find  an  average  displacement  of  2.1°  towards  the  right;  in 
Table  XI  with  a  ratio  left: right  =  2.1  we  find  an  average 
displacement  of  1.4°  towards  the  left.  The  former  tables 
thus  show  over-correction;  the  latter,  under-correction. 


B.   THE    RELATIVE     IMPORTANCE     OP     INTENSITY    AND    TIMBRE 
AS  FACTORS   IN  I^OCALIZATION 

In  these  experiments,  tuning  forks  were  used  as  the  source 
of  sound.  The  object  was  to  find  out  to  what  extent  the  con- 
but  will  be  displaced  toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  weaker  ear,  because 
sounds  of  equal  intensity  have  always  had  that  connotation  in  the  observer's 
past  experience.  Likewise,  when  the  ears  have  been  made  equally  sensitive 
by  plugging  the  stronger,  sounds  which  come  from  positions  to  either  side 
of  the  median  plane  will  always  be  displaced  toward  the  naturally  weaker 
ear,  because  now  they  are  heard  by  the  two  ears  with  a  relative  loudness 
which,  in  the  observer's  past  experience,  has  always  connoted  a  position 
relatively  nearer  the  weaker  ear. 


AUDITORY  lyOCAUZATlON 


283 


Table  VII 
Observer  S.     Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  clangs.    Artificial  sensitivity  series.    Right  ear  plugged.     Liminal 
distance:  right  ear,  18  cm.;  left  ear,  70  cm.     Ratio,  Left  :  Right  =  3.8. 
Stimulus,  Galton  whistle,   20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

friTxrarrl  qyic  r»f 

toward  axis  of 
weaker  ear 

Hori7:nntal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

stronger  ear 

o^B 

0** 

30"  L  F 

5°d 

30° 

180*'       F 

O** 

30°  L  F 

2o'*d 

30" 

45"  RF 

0'' 

10"  L  F 

5°d 

55° 

45"  Iv  F 

45^  u 

eo**  L  F 

5°u 

15° 

o'^B 

45°  u 

33°  Iv  F 

22"  d 

33° 

135°  R  F 

0° 

20°  h  F 

5°d 

65° 

135^  I.  F 

0° 

50^*  Iv  F 

15°  d 

5° 

180°       F 

45"  u 

30"  h  F 

0'' 

30'' 

135"  R  F 

45°  u 

20''  h  F 

18"  u 

65° 

135°  h  F 

45°  u 

65°  h  F 

5°u 

20^ 

o^B 

45°  d 

25°  L  F 

o'' 

25° 

45''  RF 

45°  u 

35°  L  F 

lO**  u 

80'' 

45"  Iv  F 

45°  d 

50°  L  F 

15°  u 

5° 

60°  L  F 

o« 

6"  L  F 

5°u 

54° 

45''  RF 

45°  d 

30"  L  F 

12- d 

75° 

180°       F 

45°  d 

40^  L  F 

I2«'d 

40° 

135''  R  F 

45°  d 

30''  L  F 

5°d 

75° 

o^'B 

90   u 

30°  h  F 

5°d 

30° 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  34.6^. 

ditions  obtaining  in  the  former  experiments  influence  the 
localization  of  simple  tones.  Three  cases  are  possible,  (a) 
These  conditions  may  exert  no  influence  at  all.  We  should 
then  have  to  conclude  that,  in  the  former  experiments,  the 
binaural  ratio  produces  its  effect  wholly  as  a  difference  in  the 
timbre  of  the  sound  as  heard  by  the  two  ears.  That  is,  since 
timbre  depends  upon  the  number  and  the  proportionate 
strength  of  the  overtones  in  the  clang,  in  case  one  ear  is 
more  sensitive  than  the  other,  the  timbre  of  the  sound  heard 
by  one  ear  will  differ  from  that  heard  by  the  other  ear  be- 
cause of  the  different  number  of  overtones  present  in  the  two 
cases. ^    (b)  The  conditions  may  exert  some  influence,  but  not 

^This  view  of  the  way  the  binaural  ratio  serves  as  a  localizing  clue  was 
first  advanced  by  Rayleighin  1876,  and  later  by  Sylvanus  Thompson  (Op. 
cit.,p.  415)  in  1882.  Thompson  says :  "Judgments  as  to  the  direction  of 
sound  are  based,  in  general,  upon  the  sensations  of  different  intensity  in 
the  two  ears,  but  the  perceived  difference  of  intensity  upon  which  a  judg- 
ment is  based  is  not  usually  the  difference  in  intensity  in  the  lowest  or 
fundamental  tone  of  the  compound  (or  'clang'),  but  upon  the  difference 
in  intensity  of  the  individual  tone  or  tones  of  the  clang  for  which  the 
intensity  difference  has  the  greatest  effective  restdt  in  the  quality  of  the 

sound It  is  completely  open  to  doubt  whether  a  pure 

simple  tone  heard  in  one  ear  could  suggest  any  direction  at  all." 


284 


FERREH  AND  COI^UNS 


as  much  as  was  exerted  upon  the  sound  of  the  Galton  whistle. 
In  this  case,  we  should  have  to  conclude  that  diJBferences  of 
intensity  both  in  the  fundamental  and  in  the  overtones  of  the 
clang  served  as  a  localizing  clue  in  our  experiments,  (c)  They 
may  exert  an  equal  influence  upon  the  sound  of  the  tuning 
fork  and  upon  the  clang.  This  would  indicate  that  differences 
in  the  intensity  of  the  fundamental  tone  alone  were  operative 
as  local  signature. 

Table  VIII. 
Observer  F.     Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  clangs.     Artificial  sensitivity  series.     Left  ear  plugged.     Liminal 
distance:  right  ear,  39  cm.;   left  ear,   8  cm.     Ratio,  Right  :  Left  =4.9. 
Stimulus,  Galton  whistle,  20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

fowrarH  nvi^  of 

frfsxrari^  qyi*.  of 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

t^KJ  TV  <*JL  ^A     CUkA3    \Jk 

stronger  ear 

weaker  ear 

45"  RF 

0" 

70«  R  F 

S^'u 

30' 

135°  L  F 

o** 

35°  Iv  F 

o« 

IO« 

o''B 

O*' 

35°  RF 

o« 

35° 

135*'  R  F 

0" 

50°  RF 

0" 

5° 

45°  LF 

45°  u 

50*^  L  F 

o*- 

5' 

180°       F 

0'' 

o*'B 

o« 

o** 

0* 

135"  L  F 

45°  u 

45°  L  F 

30**  d 

0** 

o*' 

45°  LF 

45°  d 

o°B 

30'' d 

< 

ISO**  R  F 

o** 

30**  RF 

5°d 

0" 

o» 

o^'B 

45°  u 

10"  R  F 

10°  d 

10*' 

45°  RF 

45°  u 

45°  RF 

20*  u 

0** 

0" 

180°       F 

45°  u 

155°  R  F 

10"  u 

25° 

135°  R  F 

45°  u 

170"  R  F 

20°  u 

35° 

150°  L  F 

45°  u 

35°  L  F 

o*" 

5° 

o°B 

90°  u 

25°  R  F 

0'' 

25° 

45°  L  F 

0^ 

o^'B 

20"  d 

45° 

o^'B 

45°  d 

40**  R  F 

lo^'d 

40° 

180''       F 

0° 

15°  R  F 

io*'u 

15° 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  17°. 


The  stimulus  was  given  as  follows  in  these  experiments. 
The  observer,  blindfolded,  with  head  firmly  clamped  and 
ears  tightly  closed,  sat  in  position  in  the  sound-cage.  A 
heavy  unmounted  tuning  fork  of  480  vibrations  per  second 
and  a  cylindrical  resonator  were  used  as  the  source  of  sound. 
These  were  substituted  for  the  telephone  receiver  of  the  sound- 
cage.  The  fork  was  plucked  by  the  fingers  covered  by  a 
chamois  glove,  and  was  allowed  to  vibrate  for  a  few  seconds 
to  allow  possible  high  overtones,  harmonic  or  inharmonic, 
to  die  out.     It  was  then  held  over  the  mouth  of  the  resonator. 


I 


AUDITORY  LOCALIZATION 


28s 


As  soon  as  the  tone  became  audible,  the  observer's  ears  were 
uncovered  and  the  sound  was  listened  to  for  about  one  second, 
at  the  end  of  which  time  the  fork  was  removed  from  the  mouth 
of  the  resonator,  and  the  direction  in  which  the  sound  was 
heard  was  indicated  by  the  observer.  In  no  case  were  any 
of  the  noises  attendant  upon  the  stimulation  of  the  fork  heard ; 
and  a  tone  as  simple  as  a  tuning  fork  is  capable  of  giving  was 
obtained.     The  duration  of  the  stimulus  was  roughly  the  same 

Table  IX 
Observer  F.     Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  clangs.     Artificial  sensitivity  series.     Right  ear  plugged.     Liminal 
distance:  right  ear,   10  cm.;  left  ear,  41  cm.     Ratio,    Left:  Right  =4.1. 
Stimulus,  Galton  whistle,   20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

toward  axis  of 
stronger  ear 

toward  axis  of 
weaker  ear 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

45°  RF 

0° 

40**  R  F 

0° 

5° 

135"  I.  F 

0° 

IIO^  L  F 

0" 

25° 

o^B 

0" 

15°  L  F 

10'' u 

15° 

135**  R  F 

0'' 

15°  RF 

20**  U 

30** 

45°  L  F 

45°  U 

60°  L  F 

5°u 

15° 

180°       F 

o*' 

50°  Iv  F 

25°  u 

50'' 

135°  L  F 

45°  u 

90**  L  F 

35°  u 

45° 

45°  L  F 

45°  d 

55°  L  F 

loM 

10'' 

150''  R  F 

0° 

120*'  R  F 

18°  u 

30* 

o°B 

45°  u 

25°  L  F 

30°  u 

25° 

45°  RF 

45°  u 

25°  RF 

30°  u 

20- 

180**       F 

45°  u 

35°  L  F 

32°  u 

35° 

135°  R  F 

45°  u 

15°  R  F 

35°  u 

30" 

150"  L  F 

45°  u 

90°  L  F 

5°u 

60" 

o^'B 

90°  u 

5°  RF 

20°  u 

5° 

70*  L  F 

o** 

75°  L  F 

0° 

5° 

50°  RF 

45°  d 

120**  R  F 

15°  u 

lO* 

70°  R  F 

0'' 

30''  RF 

15°  u 

40° 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  18.2°. 


as  that  of  the  Galton  whistle  used  in  the  earlier  experiments, 
and  care  was  taken  to  give  the  stimulus  as  nearly  as  possible 
the  same  intensity  each  time.  The  stimuli  were  all  given  at 
the  level  of  the  ears,  and  no  account  of  vertical  displacements 
was  taken  in  recording  the  results,  since  these  have  no  direct 
bearing  upon  the  purpose  of  the  experiment. 

Tables  XIII,  XIV,  and  XV  give  the  results  of  this  investi- 
gation. These  results,  on  the  average,  show  that  the  ratio 
of  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears  affects  the  localization  of  simple 
tones  almost,  if  not  quite,  as  much  as  it  does  the  localization 
of  clangs  of  the  degree  of  complexity  of  the  Galton  whistle. 


286 


F]eRRKE  AND  COLUNS 
Table  X 


Observer  R.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali« 
zation  of  clangs.  Sensitivity  of  two  ears  equated.  Left  ear  plugged. 
Liminal  distance:  right  ear,  18.5;  left  ear,  18.2  cm.;  Stimulus,  Galton 
whistle,  20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

fcwwarf^  jiYiQ  of 

fckwart^  flYiQ  nf 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

right  ear 

left  ear 

o°B 

0** 

50**  RF 

42°  d 

50** 

180°       F 

0'' 

35°  RF 

30"  d 

35° 

o°B 

45"  u 

40°  R  F 

30°  d 

40° 

180"       F 

45**" 

50"  R  F 

8M 

50'' 

G^'B 

45°  d 

40°  R  F 

25°  d 

40° 

180°       F 

45°  d 

30"  R  F 

25°  d 

30** 

o*'B 

90°  u 

30*"  R  F 

42*' d 

30« 

o°B 

0'' 

35°  RF 

40«d 

35° 

180*'       F 

0** 

30"  R  F 

44°  d 

30'' 

o'^B 

45°  u 

20°  R  F 

28**  d 

20" 

180*       F 

45°  u 

20**  R  F 

32°  d 

20" 

o°B 

45°  d 

10°  R  F 

35°  d 

lO** 

180*'       F 

45°  d 

35°  RF 

35°  d 

35° 

o^'B 

90**  u 

15°  RF 

38"  d 

15° 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  right  ear,  31.4**. 

Table  XI 

Observer  R.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  clangs.  Attempt  to  correct  localizing  error.  Left  ear  plugged. 
Liminal  distance:  right  ear,  19  cm,;  left  ear,  40  cm.  Ratio,  Left  :  Right  = 
2.1.     Stimulus,  Galton  whistle,  20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

right  ear 

left  ear 

o^B 

0'' 

10°  R  F 

28M 

10" 

180**       F 

0° 

20°  L  F 

35°  d 

20« 

Q°B 

45°  U 

o°B 

32°  d 

o** 

0*' 

180*'       F 

45°  U 

10**  L  F 

25°  d 

10*' 

o^'B 

45°  d 

o^'B 

35°  d 

0*' 

o» 

180*'       F 

45°  d 

5°  R  F 

35°  d 

5° 

o**B 

90"  u 

5°  R  F 

50M 

5° 

o^'B 

o'* 

o^'B 

32^  d 

0" 

0° 

180*'       F 

0" 

o°B 

20**  d 

0*' 

o« 

o^'B 

45°  u 

io*»  L  F 

35°  d 

IO« 

180**       F 

45°  u 

5°  Iv  F 

30'' d 

5° 

o^B 

45°  d 

15°  R  F 

32°  d 

15° 

180"       F 

45°  d 

o^'B 

20°  d 

o** 

o-B 

90°  u 

10°  L  F 

42«d 

10'' 

Average  displacement  from  median  plane,  1.4**  (left). 


AUDITORY  LOCALIZATION 
Table  XII 


287 


Observer  R.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  clangs.  Artificial  sensitivity  series.  Attempt  to  correct 
localizing  error.  Left  ear  plugged.  Liminal  distance:  right  ear,  19  cm,; 
left  ear,  29  cm.  Ratio,  Left:  Right  =  1.5.  Stimulus,  Galton  whistle, 
20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Set 

Heard 

Displacement 

Displacement 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

Horizontal 

Vertical 

right  ear 

left  ear 

o°B 

0*' 

5°  RF 

30°  d 

5° 

180''       F 

0*' 

5°  L  F 

15°  d 

5° 

o^-B 

45°" 

10''  RF 

30M 

10° 

iSo**       F 

45"  U 

o°B 

ao^'d 

0'' 

0** 

o^'B 

45'' d 

o^'B 

15°  d 

o** 

o** 

180*'       F 

45°  d 

o°B 

15°  d 

0'' 

0° 

o^B 

90°  u 

o^B 

40'' d 

0° 

0** 

o^'B 

0*" 

5°  RF 

38°  d 

5° 

180**       F 

0" 

5°  Iv  F 

22°  d 

5° 

o^'B 

45°  u 

15°  R  F 

30*' d 

15° 

180°       F 

45°  u 

o«B 

35°  d 

o*' 

o** 

o^B 

45°  d 

o°B 

25°  d 

0° 

0° 

180''       F 

45°  d 

o^B 

25°  d 

0" 

0° 

o^'B 

90   u 

5°  RF 

40^ 

5° 

Average  displacement  from  median  plane,  2.1°  (right). 

But  the  effect  is  not  nearly  so  consistent  in  the  individual 
judgments.  When  the  Galton  whistle  was  used  as  stimulus, 
the  sound  was  displaced  toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the 
stronger  ear  in  a  very  large  percentage  of  cases,  and,  relatively 
speaking,  in  not  widely  varying  amounts.  In  the  case  of  the 
tuning  fork,  however,  a  very  large  displacement  of  the  sound 
toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  stronger  ear  was  frequently 
followed  by  one  toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  weaker  ear, 
the  variation  in  the  individual  judgments  from  the  true  posi- 
tion being,  in  general,  very  much  greater  than  for  the  Galton 
whistle.  It  would  appear  then,  in  these  experiments,  that  the 
binaural  ratio  has  exerted  its  influence  both  as  difference  in  in- 
tensit^^  and  as  change  of  timbre.^   For  the  sake  of  comparison, 

^A  few  words,  further  explaining  and  qualifying  the  above  argument,  are 
probably  not  out  of  place  here.  The  tone  of  the  Galton  whistle  set  at 
20,000  vibrations  is  relatively  simple.  The  first  overtone,  for  example,  has 
a  vibration  rate  of  40,000,  and  the  second  of  60,000,  which  is  above  the  limit 
of  audibility.  Thus  our  argument  that  the  above  mentioned  displacements 
have  been  made  in  terms  of  the  intensity  factor  should  not  rest  so  much, 
probably,  upon  a  correspondence  of  results  when  Galton  whistle  and  tuning 
fork  are  used  as  sources  of  sound,  as  upon  the  fact  that  the  large  displace- 
ments observed  took  place  both  when  a  vsimple  and  a  relatively  simple  tone 
were  used  as  stimuli.     To  complete  the  investigation  a  comparison  should 


288 


FBRREE  AND  COLUNS 
Table  XIII 


Observer  F.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali' 
zation  of  simple  tones.  Liminal  distance:  right  ear,  40  cm.;  left  ear,  40 
cm.  Ratio,  Right :  Left  =  i .  Stimulus,  tuning  fork,  480  vibrations  per 
second. 


Displacement 

Displacement 

Set 

Heard 

toward  axis  of 

toward  axis  of 

right  ear 

left  ear 

135"  I.  F 

70°  L  F 

25° 

o*'B 

o°B 

o"* 

0" 

45°  L  F 

Go''  L  F 

15° 

135"  R  F 

45°  L  F 

90° 

60**  L  F 

60"'  L  F 

o'* 

0'' 

120°  L  F 

120°  L  F 

0" 

0" 

50°  L  F 

80"  L  F 

30*' 

180"       F 

o°B 

0" 

0'' 

150"  L  F 

65°  L  F 

35° 

0°  B 

o^'B 

o'' 

o"* 

135"  L  F 

90*'  R  F 

135° 

45°  RF 

45°  R  F 

0" 

0* 

0*'  B 

125°  R  F 

55° 

60°  R  F 

15°  RF 

45* 

180*'       F 

85°  L  F 

85° 

120*'  R  F 

60**  R  F 

0* 

o** 

30°  R  F 

130°  R  F 

20'' 

150"  R  F 

135°  R  F 

15° 

0°  B 

10^  RF 

lO** 

45°  RF 

go*'  R  F 

45° 

i8o'       F 

20''  L  F 

20* 

Average  displacement  from  median  plane,  3.09*  (left). 

the  same  observers  were  used  here  that  were  used  in  the  experi- 
ments with  the  Galton  whistle.  In  order  to  show  the  effect 
of  the  binaural  ratio,  it  was  deemed  advantageous,  in  both 
cases,  to  work  with  observers  both  of  equal  and  of  unequal 
sensitivity  of  the  two  ears. 

Table  XIV  shows  the  results  for  Observer  R.  The  ratio  of 
sensitivity  was  chosen  so  that  left:  right  =  2.3 ;  the  average  dis- 
placement toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  stronger  ear  was 
found  to  be  15°.  A  correlation  of  average  displacement 
with  ratio  of  sensitivity  shows,  roughly  speaking,  for  this 
observer,  quite  as  much  tendency  to  displace  the  sound  to  the 
side  of  the  stronger  ear  as  was  shown  for  the  Galton  whistle. 

Results  with  the  Galton  whistle  are  brought  forward  from 
Tables  II,  IV,  and  VI  for  comparison.     Table  II  shows  for  R. 

be  made  further  of  the  results  obtained  with  these  two  sources  of  sound 
and  one  still  more  complex  than  the  Galton  whistle.  This  comparison  will 
be  included  in  the  work  on  this  problem  still  in  progress  in  this  laboratory. 


AUDITORY  lyOCAUZATlON 


289 


a  ratio  of  sensitivity  left:  right  =  4,  an  average  displacement 
toward  left  of  20.3°;  Table  IV,  a  ratio  of  sensitivity  left:  right 
=  23.6,  an  average  displacement  toward  the  left  of  31.6°;  Table 
VI,  a  ratio  of  sensitivity  right:  left  =  6.2,  and  an  average  dis- 
placement of  34.4°  toward  the  right. 

Table  XV  shows  the  results  for  Observer  S.,  with  a  ratio  of 
sensitivity  chosen  so  that  right: left  =1.9.  With  this  ratio 
it  was  found  that  the  sound  was  displaced,  on  the  average, 
7.5° : toward  the  side  of  the  stronger  ear.  When  compared 
with  a  ratio  left:  right  =  2.9  and  an  average  displacement 
of  10.7°  toward  the  left  ear  (Table  III),  a  ratio  right:  left  =  9. 7 
and  an  average  displacement  toward  the  right  of  17.2°  (Table 
V),  and  a  ratio  left:  right  =  3.8  with  an  average  displacement 
toward  the  left  of  34.6°  (Table  VII),  these  results  also  show 
probably  as  strong  a  tendency  to  displace  the  simple  tone 
toward  the  stronger  ear  as  was  shown  in  the  case  of  the  clang. 


Table  XIV 

Observer  R.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  simple  tones.  Liminal  distance:  left  ear,  49  cm.;  right  ear,  21 
cm.  Ratio,  Left  :  Right  =  2.3.  Stimulus,  tuning  fork,  480  vibrations  per 
second. 


displacement 

Displacement 

Set 

Heard 

toward  axis  of 

toward  axis  of 

stronger  ear 

weaker  ear 

45"  RF 

85''  R  F 

4° 

las'*  R  F 

30^*  RF 

15° 

o«B 

40''  L  F 

40° 

60"  RF 

40**  R  F 

20" 

180"       F 

o°B 

0^ 

o*» 

30^  R  F 

55'*RF 

25° 

150"  R  F 

40''  L  F 

70'' 

o°B 

55°  RF 

55° 

45*'  RF 

55°  RF 

lO** 

135"  R  F 

50''  L  F 

95° 

.o'^B 

85°  L  F 

85° 

135"  h  F 

35°  L  F 

ID** 

o^'B 

35°  RF 

35° 

45°  h  F 

75°  I.  F 

30° 

o°B 

50°  L  F 

50° 

I20*'  L  F 

55°  L  F 

5° 

50*"  L  F 

55°!.  F 

5° 

180°       F 

60°  L  F 

60'' 

150"  h  F 

40°  RF 

70° 

o*B 

45°  L  F 

45° 

135"  h  F 

70''  L  F 

25° 

45''  LF 

85"  L  F 

40° 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  15**. 


290 


I^SRREK  AND  COI.UNS 
Table  XV 


Observer  S.  Showing  the  influence  of  the  binaural  ratio  on  the  locali- 
zation of  simple  tones.  Liminal  distance:  right  ear,  86  cm,;  left  ear,  46 
cm.  Ratio,  Right  :  Left  =  1.9.  Stimulus,  tuning  fork,  480  vibrations  per 
second. 


Displacement 

Displacement 

Set 

Heard 

toward  axis  of 

toward  axis  of 

stronger  ear 

weaker  ear 

135°  L  F 

35°  RF 

8o'> 

o^B 

25°  L  F 

25° 

45*'  h  F 

35°  L  F 

lO** 

o°B 

40°  L  F 

40° 

60**  L  F 

70'*  L  F 

io'» 

I20*'  L  F 

40°  R  F 

100° 

50"  L  F 

65^*1.  F 

15° 

180*'       F 

45°  RF 

45° 

135"  R  F 

o^'B 

45° 

150*'  L  F 

10°  L  F 

20'' 

o^'B 

50**  RF 

50** 

180*'       F 

10*'  L  F 

10" 

135°  L  F 

120**  R  F 

105° 

45°  LF 

75°  h  F 

30° 

45°  RF 

lo*'  R  F 

25° 

o**B 

70**  L  F 

70° 

60°  R  F 

75°  RF 

15° 

o^'B 

15°  Iv  F 

15* 

180°       F 

50''  RF 

50° 

120**  R  F 

45°  RF 

15° 

30**  RF 

60°  RF 

30* 

45°  RF 

45°  LF 

90» 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  7.5* 


C.     INDIVIDUAL  PREFERENCES 

Of  the  individual  preferences  reported  by  von  Kries^  and 
Dunlap,^  the  writers  find  this  much  evidence.     There  is  (i)  a 

*The  individual  preferences  mentioned  by  von  Kries  (Ueber  das  Erkennen 
der  Schallrichtung,  Ztschr.  f.  Psychol.,  I,  1890,  s.  242-243)  are  confined 
to  points  in  the  median  plane.  The  results  obtained  by  us  bear  more  spe- 
cifically upon  the  preferences  reported  by  Dunlap. 

^Dunlap  (The  Localization  of  Sounds,  Psychol.  Rev.  Monog.  Suppl, 
1909,  Vol.  X,  No.  40,  I -16)  says:  "Several  years  ago  I  commenced  the 
attempt  to  make  comparisons  between  the  location  of  soimds  with  both  ears 
and  the  location  with  one  ear,  the  other  being  stopped  as  well  as  might  be. 
The  results  of  my  first  tests  were  rather  odd,  showing  a  condition  which 
made  it  impossible  to  get  at  the  comparisons  I  wished,  at  least  in  any 
clear  way;  and  subsequent  tests  which  I  have  made  from  time  to  time,  and 
which  students  have  made  for  me,  on  different  subjects,  have  resulted  in  the 
same  way.  The  condition  mentioned  has  had  so  little  (if  any)  consideration 
in  connection  with  the  problem  of  the  location  of  sounds,  that  I  have  thought 
it  important  to  give  some  accoimt  of  my  exx)eriments."     The  condition 


AUDITORY  LOCALIZATION 


291 


tendency  in  case  of  a  stronger  ear,  to  refer  the  sound  in  the 
direction  of  this  ear;  and  (2)  in  the  case  of  his  observers,  and  the 
relatively  weak  stimulus  used,  there  seemed  to  be  a  fairly  con- 
sistent tendency  to  prefer  the  back  to  the  front  locations ;  in  fact, 
some  observers  never  located  a  sound  in  front.  The  former  tend- 
ency gave  certain  observers  a  decided  right  or  left  "preference," 
depending  upon  their  defect;  and  this, combined  with  the  second 
tendency,  tended  to  limit  the  localizations  to  a  single  quadrant. 
That  is,  the  back  tendency  operating  to  limit  the  sound  to 
one  hemisphere,  and  the  right  or  left  tendency  to  a  hemisphere 
at  right  angles  to  this,  would  tend  to  confine  the  localizations 
to  one  quadrant  for  a  given  observer.  But  these  tendencies 
can  hardly  be  called  capricious,  as  Dunlap  apparently  found 
them  to  be.  To  show  that  the  one  conforms  to  law,  i.  e.,  is  corre- 
lated with  a  definite  sensory  characteristic,  has  been  the  ob- 
ject of  this  paper.     The  other  is  still  under  investigation.^ 


which  discouraged  further  work  on  his  problem  may  be  summed  up  in  his 
own  words :  *  'The  position  in  the  area  of  location  bears  precious  little  rela- 
tion to  the  actual  position  of  the  sound.  The  marks  representing  the  sounds 
at  the  various  points  might  to  all  intents  and  purposes  be  shaken  up  in  a 
box  and  dumped  down  on  the  preferred  area  on  the  chart.  This  appearance 
is  amply  confirmed  by  other  series  on  the  subjects.  Repeated  series  give 
results  which  have  no  uniformity,  except  in  the  general  area  of  location. 

"The  preferred  position  is  not  determined  by  the  character  of  the  sound  or 
by  the  environment.  Two  subjects  in  exactly  the  same  circtunstances  may 
have  quite  different  preferences.  A  subject  may  show  the  same  preference 
after  six  months  or  a  year,  or  may  show  a  decidedly  different  one,  without 
any  known  reason  for  the  change.  The  subject  shows  the  same  preference 
in  different  rooms,  or  if  he  is  reversed  in  the  same  room.  Alterations  in 
the  intensity  of  the  sound  produced  no  definite  alterations  in  the  pre- 
ferred area.  The  Galton  whistle  gives  practically  the  same  results  as 
the  buzzer  or  the  telephone  receiver.  So  far  I  have  not  found  a  subject 
who  does  not  locaUze  in  this  preferential  way.  What  the  causes  are,  I 
cannot  say.  There  are  possible  theories  and  nothing  more.  Meantime, 
how  to  conduct  profitable  experiments  in  localization  before  solving  this 
problem  is  another  problem." 

The  writers  admit  that  the  irregularity  of  Dunlap's  results  is  discourag- 
ing. After  a  careful  study  of  Dunlap's  charts  of  results,  they  also  admit 
that  the  factors  underlying  the  evidences  of  individual  preferences  of  their 
own  observers  fail  utterly  to  solve  "the  puzzle."  They  can  only  repeat 
that  in  their  contention  for  a  lawful  mechanism,  they  do  not  wish  to  go 
beyond  the  results  and  conditions  of  their  own  experiments ;  and  merely 
suggest  that  Dimlap  may  have  worked  with  the  subjective  type  of  observer, 
and  may  have  fostered  this  subjective  tendency  by  the  use  of  the  chart 
method  for  indicating  directions. 

^It  has  been  discussed  at  various  times  in  the  literature  of  auditory  lo- 
calization whether  back  reference  may  not  have  become  associated  with  weak 
intensities  of  sound.  (Thompson:  The  Pseudophone,  Phil.  Mag.  (5)  VIII, 
1879,  385-390;  Bloch:  Das  hinaurale  Hdren.  Wiesbaden,  1893,  pp.  52-6; 
Pierce:  Op.  cit.  90-1.  A  reason  for  this  association  has  been  found  in  the 
shape  of  the  external  ear  as  a  collector  of  sound  (Pierce:  Op.  cit.,  p.  90; 
Bloch:  Op.  cit.,  pp.  25-52).  But  apart  from  the  cause  the  writers  are  in- 
vestigating the  fact  in  the  following  way.     Observers  are  selected  who. 


2  92  FERREE  AND  COI^UNS 

Moreover,  no  variation  that  could  be  called  a  consivStent 
change  occurred  in  these  tendencies  after  a  lapse  of  some  four 
months.  Certainly  nothing  has  come  out  with  regard  to  the 
right  or  left  tendency,  from  time  to  time,  that  cannot  be 
roughly  correlated  with  the  results  of  the  accompanying 
sensitivity  tests,  as  will  be  shown  by  the  results  given  in  the 
next  section  of  this  paper. 

However,  in  contending  for  a  lawful  mechanism,  and  in 
suggesting  an  explanation,  of  what,  on  the  surface,  might  be 
considered  as  capricious,  the  writer  has  no  desire  to  go  beyond 
the  results  and  conditions  of  his  own  experiments.  Bach  case 
must  be  tried  out  on  its  own  merits. 

Table  XVI  shows  the  preference  for  the  back  locations. 
This  table  was  compiled  from  the  results  of  Tables  I-XV  in- 
clusive and  from  Table  XVII.  The  number  of  readings  given 
back  and  in  front  of  the  aural  axis,  the  number  of  times  the 
sound  was  localized  in  the  correct  hemisphere  and  the  number 
of  times  it  was  displaced  to  the  opposite  hemisphere  was 
determined  from  the  tables;  and  the  ratio  of  the  number  of 
backward  displacements  to  the  number  of  forward  displace- 
ments was  computed  from  these  results. 

with  the  comparatively  weak  stimulus  used  in  the  preceding  experiments, 
show  a  marked  tendency  to  locate  the  sound  behind.  A  graded  series  of 
stimuli  is  then  provided,  ranging  from  very  weak  to  very  strong,  and  the 
regular  localizing  series  is  given  for  each  stimulus.  If,  with  an  increase 
in  the  intensity  of  the  stimulus,  there  is  found  to  be  a  decrease  in  the  per- 
centage of  back  references,  the  intensity  of  the  stimulus  may  fairly  be  said 
to  sustain  an  associative  relation  to  this  direction  reference.  This  method  of 
procedure,  the  writers  believe,  offers  better  possibilities  of  getting  results 
from  which  conclusions  can  be  drawn  than  do  the  experiments  of  the  kind 
performed  by  Bloch,  even  though  Bloch's  principle  of  working  be  carried 
out  imder  laboratory  conditions.  Bloch  selected  a  sound  of  such  intensity 
that  when  it  was  given  behind,  it  was  localized  behind  by  his  observers;  and 
then  he  tried  the  effect  of  an  increase  of  intensity.  He  claimed  thus  to  be 
able  to  cause  a  reversal  of  the  localization,  or  the  illusion  of  front.  Bloch's 
method  of  experimenting  was  extremely  crude.  The  experiments  were 
made  in  the  open  air  in  a  court  enclosed  on  three  sides.  "The  observer 
stood  5  meters  from  the  end  wall  and  pebbles  were  thrown  on  the  stone  pave- 
ment in  front  or  behind  him.  The  result  was  that  when  his  face  was  turned 
towards  the  wall,  the  legitimate  influence  of  the  pinna  was  merely  increased 
and  the  localizations  were  mostly  correct.  When,  on  the  contrary,  the 
back  was  turned  towards  the  wall,  sounds  coming  from  behind  were  apt  to 
be  falsely  located  in  front,  since  now  the  reflection  of  the  sound  waves  by 
the  wall  produced  an  unwonted  intensity  in  the  sound."  Applying  this 
principle  of  working  under  laboratory  conditions  in  various  ways,  the  writers 
have  always  failed  to  get  anything  like  consistent  results.  Any  attempt  to 
confirm  the  association  of  the  back  or  front  reference  with  the  intensity  of 
the  sound,  based  upon  individual  judgments,  they  believe  is  doomed  to 
failure.  If  conclusions  are  to  be  reached  at  all  they  must  be  reached  from  a 
comparison  of  averages  got  by  a  systematic  variation  of  intensity. 


AUDITORY  LOCALIZATION 


293 


Tablb  XVI 

Showing,  with  the  comparatively  weak  stimulus  used,  the  preference  of 
our  observers  for  back  locations. 


No.  of 

No. 

No.  dis- 

No. of 

No. 

No.  dis- 

Ratio of 
displace- 

Tables from 

readings 

localized 

placed  in 

readings 

localized 

placed 

ment 

which  data 

given 

in  correct 

front  of 

given  in 

front  of 

aural 

in  correct 

back  of 

back  to 

are  taken 

back  of 
aural 

hemis- 
phere 

atu-al 
avis 

hemis- 
phere 

aural 
axis 

displace- 
ment 

axis 

axis 

front 

Table  I 

II 

10 

I 

8 

3 

5 

5  :  I 

Table  II 

10 

ID 

0 

8 

0 

8 

8:0 

Table  III 

12 

12 

0 

8 

0 

8 

8:0 

Table  IV 

10 

10 

0 

8 

0 

8 

8  :o 

Table  V 

10 

ID 

0 

9 

0 

9 

9  :o 

Table  VI 

10 

ID 

0 

9 

0 

9 

9  :o 

Table  VII 

10 

ID 

0 

8 

0 

8 

8  :o 

Table  VIII 

9 

9 

0 

9 

2 

7 

7  :  0 

Table  IX 

10 

9 

I 

8 

4 

4 

4  '■  I 

Table  X 

8 

8 

0 

6 

0 

6 

6  :o 

Table  XI 

8 

8 

0 

6 

0 

6 

6  :o 

Table  XII 

8 

8 

0 

6 

0 

6 

6  :o 

Table  XIII 

II 

9 

2 

10 

3 

7 

7  :  2 

Table  XIV 

13 

13 

0 

9 

0 

9 

9  :  0 

Table  XV 

13 

13 

0 

9 

I 

8 

8  :o 

Table  XVII 

9 

9 

0 

8 

0 

8 

8  :o 

D.    THE  QUESTION  OF  CHANGES  IN   THESE   PREFERENCES    WITH 
LAPSE    OF    TIME 


Experiments  were  conducted  to  find  out  whether  any 
considerable  change  occurred  in  the  observer's  tendency  to 
localize  during  the  course  of  several  months,  or,  more  espe- 
cially, to  determine  whether  there  occurred  any  change 
that  could  not  be  correlated  with  a  corresponding  change 
in  the  ratio  of  sensitivity  of  the  ears.  No  change  of  any 
significance  was  found  to  have  taken  place  in  any  of  the  cases 
examined.  Table  XVII  shows  the  results  obtained  for  ob- 
server R.  three  months  later  than  those  given  in  Table  II. 
These  results  may  be  taken  as  representative.  In  Table  II, 
the  ratio  left: right  =  4,  and  the  displacement  is  20.3°  toward 
the  left;  and  in  the  table  given  below,  the  ratio  left: right  = 
3.7,  and  the  displacement  is  23.3°.  This  comparison  shows 
a  slight  increase  in  the  observer's  tendency  to  refer  the  sound 
to  the  side  of  the  stronger  ear,  but  in  a  field  where  the  results 
show  such  a  large  mean  variation  the  writers  have  not  con- 


294 


FSRREE  AND  COLUNS 


sidered,  either  here  or  elsewhere  in  the  work,  that  so  small  a 
change  in  results  is  at  all  significant. 

By  comparing  the  results  of  Table  XVII  with  Tables  II, 
VI,  VII,  X,  XI,  XII,  and  XIV,  in  Table  XVI,  it  will  be  found 
also  that  no  significant  change  has  occurred  in  the  observer's 
preference  for  the  back  locations. 

Table  XVII 

Observer  R.  Showing  that  no  change  of  any  consequence  has  taken 
place  in  the  localizing  tendency  of  our  observers  after  a  lapse  of  three 
months.  (Compare  with  Table  II.)  Liminal  distance:  right  ear,  19  cm.; 
left  ear,  71  cm.  Ratio,  Left  :  Right  =  3.7.  Stimulus,  Galton  whistle, 
20,000  vibrations  per  second. 


Displacement 

Displacement 

Set 

Heard 

toward  axis  of 

toward  axis  of 

stronger  ear 

weaker  ear 

o«  B 

25°  L  F 

25° 

180**       F 

50**  L  F 

so'' 

45^*  h  F 

65"  L  F 

20° 

130°  L  F 

65**  L  F 

15** 

70**  L  F 

70°  L  F 

0° 

o** 

135"  Iv  F 

80''  L  F 

35" 

o^'B 

15"  h  F 

IS'' 

135**  R  F 

IS**  R  F 

30» 

45"  RF 

25"  R  F 

20"' 

150°  R  F 

20**  R  F 

10'' 

60"  h  F 

TS'^L  F 

IS** 

135"  R  F 

10°  R  F 

SS'' 

eo**  R  F 

10"  RF 

SO** 

50°  h  F 

eo**  h  F 

lO** 

130''  R  F 

25**  R  F 

2S'* 

180*'       F 

20*'  h  F 

20" 

0^  B 

20*'  L  F 

20*' 

Average  displacement  toward  axis  of  stronger  ear,  23.2". 


III.  Summary  of  Results. 

(i)  Subjects  having  a  natural  difference  in  the  sensitivity 
of  the  two  ears  show  a  constant  tendency  to  displace  the 
sound  toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  stronger  ear;  and, 
conversely,  subjects  without  this  difference  in  sensitivity  do 
not  show  this  tendency.  The  greater  number  of  subjects 
examined  showed  a  difference  in  sensitivity. 

(2)  Changes  in  the  ratio  of  sensitivity,  produced  by  plug- 
ging either  ear,  were  followed  by  corresponding  displacements 
of  the  sound  toward  the  axis  on  the  side  of  the  stronger  ear. 
Differences  in  sensitivity,   artificially  produced,   apparently 


AUDITORY  I.OCAUZATION  295 

exerted  a  greater  influence  upon  localization  than  did  approxi- 
mately equal  differences  due  to  natural  defect.  This  is  proba- 
bly because,  in  the  case  of  a  natural  defect,  the  localization 
error  has  been  partly  corrected,  in  the  past  experience  of  the 
subject,  through  association  with  the  direction  reference  oi 
other    sense-organs. 

(3)  In  the  case  of  observers  who  showed  a  characteristic 
right  or  left  tendency,  it  was  found  possible  to  change  the 
ratio  of  sensitivity  so  that  the  error  in  localization  was  cor- 
rected. This  result  was  not  accomplished  by  equating  the 
sensitivity  of  the  two  ears.  The  desired  ratio  was  always 
found  to  have  a  value  somewhere  between  equal  sensitivity 
and  the  old  ratio. 

(4)  The  average  results  showed  that  changes  in  the  bi- 
naural ratio  affected  the  localization  of  simple  tones  almost, 
if  not  quite,  as  much  as  it  did  the  localization  of  clangs  of  the 
degree  of  complexity  of  the  Gal  ton  whistle.  The  individual 
judgments,  however,  showed  a  much  larger  variation  from 
the  true  position  in  the  case  of  the  simple  tones.  It  would 
appear,  then,  that  in  these  experiments  the  binaural  ratio 
exerted  its  influence  both  as  difference  in  intensity  and  as 
change  of  timbre,  but  predominantly  as  difference  in  intensity. 

(5)  The  writers  find  this  much  evidence  of  individual  pref- 
erences in  localization  (von  Kries',  Dunlap).  (a)  There  is 
a  tendency  in  case  of  a  stronger  ear  to  refer  the  sound  in  the 
direction  of  ,that  ear.  This  gave  certain  observers  a  decided 
right  or  left  tendency,  depending  upon  the  kind  and  amount 
of  their  defect,  (b)  With  the  relatively  weak  stimulus  used, 
there  seemed  to  be  a  fairly  constant  tendency  for  the  observers 
to  prefer  back  to  front  locations.  But  these  tendencies  can- 
not in  any  sense  be  called  capricious.  One  is  directly  traceable 
to  the  binaural  ratio;  the  other  is  still  under  investigation, 
and  is  probably  an  effect  of  the  intensity  of  the  stimulus  used. 

(6)  No  changes  of  any  consequence  in  these  tendencies 
were  found  during  the  course  of  several  months,  as  occurred  in 
the  case  of  Dunlap's  observers, — certainly  none  that  could 
not  be  correlated  with  a  definite  change  in  the  localizing  clue. 
For  example,  a  cold,  or  what  not,  was  sometimes  found  to  pro- 
duce a  change  in  the  observer's  right  or  left  tendency,  but 
tests  of  the  sensitivity  of  the  two  ears  always  disclosed  a 
corresponding  change  in  the  binaural  ratio. 

In  this  study,  nothing  was  undertaken  bearing  upon  the 
later  aspects  of  the  intensity  theory  brought  out  by  the  papers 
of  Rayleigh^  and  Wilson  and  Myers.^     The  writers,  however, 

^Rayleigh:  On  our  Perception  of  Sound  Direction,  Philos.  Mag.  (6),  XIII, 
1907,  pp.  214-32. 
^Op.  cit. 


296  FERREJE  AND  COLLINS 

have  begun  experiments  upon  three  points  relative  to  these 
aspects.  (i)It  will  bedetermined  whether  tones  of  128  vibrations 
or  less  per  second  have  a  larger  j.  n.  d.  of  direction  than  tones  of 
higher  pitch.  This  the  intensity  theory  would  seem  to  require, 
according  to  Rayleigh's  calculations  of  the  relative  intensity  of 
the  waves  received  by  the  two  ears.  Rayleigh's  tests  of  this 
point  were  as  rough  as  possible.  They  consisted,  it  will  be  re- 
membered, in  determining  whether  stimuli  of  both  low  and  high 
pitch,  given  in  the  region  of  the  aural  axis,  could  be  judged  as 
right  or  left  without  mistake.  Now,  working  under  these  condi- 
tions, a  considerable  difference  in  direction-sensitivity  might  ob- 
tain for  the  two  kinds  of  tones,  and  still  no  mistake  be  made  in 
either  case.  The  positions  chosen  give  the  largest  possible 
binaural  ratio,  and  the  judgments  required  are  the  most 
general  that  could  possibly  be  made.  In  short,  a  less  sensi- 
tive method  for  detecting  small  differences  in  power  to  dis- 
criminate direction  could  hardly  have  been  devised.  The  size 
of  the  j.  n.  d.  is  obviously  the  proper  criterion  to  apply.  (2) 
The  series  of  experiments  used  in  this  paper  will  be  repeated, 
using  forks  of  low  and  high  frequency.  If  there  is  found  as 
much  tendency  to  displace  the  tones  of  low  pitch  as  those  of 
high  pitch,  the  results  should  argue  that  the  localizing  clue 
for  low  tones  is  the  binaural  ratio,  instead  of  the  power  di- 
rectly to  detect  phase  differences ;  because  (a)  the  change  in  the 
sensitivity  of  the  ear  does  not  affect  the  phase  of  the  sound 
wave,  and  (b)  it  could  not  affect  the  detection  of  the  phase 
differences  by  the  ear  in  such  a  manner  as  to  displace  the  sound 
toward  the  stronger  ear,  for  by  this  hypothesis,  ratio  of  effect 
has  nothing  to  do  with  localization.  At  least,  it  cannot  be 
assumed  that  the  binaural  ratio,  which  is  computed  in  terms  of 
intensive  difference,  could  be  translated  directly  into  terms 
of  recognition  of  phase  difference.  Apparently  the  only  effect 
that  could  follow  a  decrease  of  sensitivity  of  one  ear  would  be 
a  proportionate  confusion  and  uncertainty  of  localization,  not 
a  definite  and  characteristic  displacement  toward  the  axis  on 
the  side  of  the  stronger  ear.  (3)  The  settings  given  to  the 
stimuli  in  Wilson  and  Myers's  experiments  will  be  repeated 
under  ordinary  localizing  conditions,  in  order  to  see  whether 
the  transfer  of  the  sound  from  one  side  of  the  median  plane  to 
the  other  takes  place  when  the  direct  paths  of  transmission  to 
the  two  ears  are  changed  by  the  amounts  they  used.  If  the 
transfers  do  not  take  place,  some  evidence,  at  least,  will  be 
afforded  that  the  experiments  they  describe  and  the  conclu- 
sions they  reach  do  not  bear  directly  upon  the  phenomenon 
of  localization  as  it  ordinarily  occurs,  but  only  upon  a  special 


AUDITORY  LOCAUZATION  297 

phenomenon  created  by  their  conditions,  which  favored  bone 
conduction. 

The  writers  present  this  report  with  the  hope  that  their  re- 
sults establish  a  more  definite  correlation  between  the  binaural 
ratio  and  direction-reference  than  has  previously  been  attained, 
and  that  the  experiments  described  will  provide  an  easily 
available  means  of  clearly  demonstrating  this  correlation  in 
the  teaching  laboratory. 


I 


JOURNAl* — 1 1 


A  REPLY  TO  PROFESSOR  SAFFORD 


By  F.  M.  Urban,  University  of  Pennsylvania 


Professor  Safford  published  in  the  January  number  of  this  Journal  a  little 
note  containing  a  criticism  of  my  theory  of  psychophysical  measurements. 
His  objections  are  two  in  number.  Thefirst  refers  to  the  number  of  decimals 
which  have  been  retained  in  my  tables;  he  is  of  the  opinion  that  the  compu- 
tation should  have  been  carried  to  the  third  decimal  only  rather  than  to  the 
fourth.  The  second  objection  is  of  a  more  complicated  nature,  and  refers 
to  my  use  of  Lagrange's  formula.  Professor  Safford's  ideas  are  very  inter- 
esting and  I  am  glad  to  have  an  opportunity  to  explain  some  considera- 
tions, at  which  my  original  articles  merely  hint.  My  book  would  have 
become  very  voluminous,  had  I  undertaken  to  present  all  the  chains  of 
reasoning  which  I  later  found  to  be  wrong,  or  to  describe  all  the  con- 
siderations which  decided  me  to  adopt  a  certain  manner  of  procedure. 
Both  of  Professor  Safford's  objections  occurred  to  me  in  the  course  of  work- 
ing out  my  data,  and  I  may  be  allowed  to  state  the  reasons  why  I  believe 
that  they  are  erroneous. 

Before  answering  the  first  objection  I  want  to  say  that  in  computing 
data  of  this  sort  it  is  customary  to  express  one's  results  in  four  places  of 
decimals.  The  majority  of  statistical  investigations,  however,  do  not  use 
relative  frequencies,  as  I  did,  but  percentages  calculated  to  the  second  deci- 
mal. Precentages  are  found  from  relative  frequencies  by  multiplying  by  i  oo ; 
two  decimals  in  percentages,  therefore,  correspond  to  four  decimals  in  rela- 
tive frequencies.  Saying  that  an  event  has  the  relative  frequency  0.4422  is 
the  same  as  saying  tiiat  this  event  occurs  in  44.22  per  cent,  of  the  cases. 
The  latter  form  is,  perhaps  a  little  more  familiar  to  the  eye ;  but  relative 
frequencies  have  the  advantage  over  percentages  of  being  the  more  primi- 
tive notions. 

The  relative  frequencies  of  the  different  judgments  form  the  starting- 
point  of  my  exposition  of  the  theory  of  psychophysical  measurements; 
and  I  naturally  gave  much  thought  to  the  question  of  how  many  decimals 
should  be  retained.  The  mere  physical  labor  of  carrying  out  the  computa- 
tions— including  the  unavoidable  wild  goose  chases — was  very  considerable 
indeed,  and  it  seemed  highly  desirable  not  to  increase  the  task  by  carrying 
too  many  decimals.  Not  being  satisfied  with  the  reference  to  custom  and 
being  acquainted  with  the  theory  of  physical  measurements,  my  mind 
naturally  drifted  into  the  channels  pointed  out  by  Professor  Safford.  I 
found  out  very  soon  that  there  does  not  exist  a  universal  agreement  as  to 
the  munber  of  decimals  which  should  be  retained  in  the  result,  and  that 
the  rules  explained  by  Professor  Safford  are  not  the  only  way  of  approaching 
the  problem,  for  no  less  an  authority  than  Gauss  advocates  the  rule  that 
the  computations  should  be  carried  so  far  that  the  final  result  should  enable 
one  to  calculate  the  actual  data  of  observation  with  their  original  precision. 

Professor  Safford  says  that  it  is  customary  to  use  the  average  deviation  as 
a  measure  of  precision  and  to  retain  two  significant  figures  of  it.  There  does 
not  exist  any  such  general  custom.  In  Germany  and  Austria  the  mean  error 
is  in  almost  exclusive  use,  while  English,  American  and  some  French  text- 
books on  the  method  of  least  squares  recommend  the  probable  error.  Some- 
thing may  be  said  in  favor  of  each  one  of  these  quantities,  but  this  is  not  the 


A  REPLY  TO  PROFESSOR  SAFFORD  299 

topic  of  the  present  discussion,  where  we  only  want  to  see  whether  there  exists 
a  universal  agreement  as  to  the  quantity  which  is  to  be  used  as  a  measure  of 
precision.  Neither  does  there  exist  an  agreement  as  to  the  ntunber  of  signifi- 
cant figures  to  be  retained  in  the  measiu-e  of  precision.  I  open  the  chapter 
on  the  adjustment  of  observations  in  Czuber's  text-book  of  the  calculus  of 
probabilities  and  find  on  pages  293,  294  and  298  examples  in  which  the 
mean  error  is  calculated  to  one,  two,  three  and  four  significant  figures. 
Some  of  these  examples  are  taken  from  authoritative  sources,  so  that  one 
cannot  possibly  say  that  there  exists  a  general  rule  as  to  the  number  of  deci- 
mals which  should  be  retained  in  the  result.  Two  or  three  significant 
figures  in  the  measure  of  precision  seem  to  be  most  frequently  used. 

There  exists  a  fundamental  difference  between  the  data  of  statistical 
observation  and  the  results  of  physical  measurements,  which  Professor 
Safford  entirely  overlooks.  The  results  of  physical  measurements  are 
exact  within  one-half  of  the  last  significant  figure.  Thus  if  we  put  down 
29  inches  as  the  length  of  a  line,  this  result  means  that  the  line  is  not  longer 
than  29.5  nor  shorter  than  28.5  inches.  When  using  this  result  in  a  compu- 
tation, one  must  not  add  digits  to  it,  because  the  following  figures  are  en- 
tirely unknown.  The  case  of  statistical  observation  is  different.  If  we 
observe  that  an  event  takes  place  29  times  in  100  cases,  both  these  numbers 
are  absolutely  exact.  The  figure  29  does  not  indicate  a  result  which  may 
vary  between  28.5  and  29.5;  but  it  means  exactly  29  and  we  may  add  as 
many  zeros  as  seems  necessary.  The  number  of  decimal  places  retained  is 
merely  a  question  of  convenience,  and  one  cannot  be  accused  of  publishing 
a  misleading  result  if  the  accuracy  of  the  determination  accompanies  it. 

It  took  me  some  time  to  see  that  the  theory  of  physical  measurement  is 
not  the  most  direct  w^  of  determining  the  precision  of  my  observations. 
The  original  data  of  my  experiments  are  determinations  of  the  probabilities 
of  the  different  judgments.  The  most  direct  way  of  finding  the  precision 
of  these  observations  is  given  by  Bernoulli's  theorem.  This  theorem  refers 
to  observations,  in  which  a  chance  event  A  occurred  « times  in  a  total  number 
of  cases  iV;  and  it  gives  the  most  probable  value  of  the  unknown  probability 
of  this  event  and  the  limits  of  the  accuracy"  of  this  determination.  This  is 
exactly  the  case  of  my  experiments  and  I  chose  the  probable  error  deter- 
mined by  Bernoulli's  theorem  as  the  measure  of  precision.  A  table  of  these 
probable  errors  is  printed  in  the  .4 rc^ii//.  d.  ges.  Psychologie,  igog,  Vol.  15, 
p.  287.  The  probable  errors  in  the  determination  of  the  probabilities  of 
the  "greater"  judgments  for  Subject  /  on  the  comparison  stimuli  84,  88, 
92,  96,  100,  104  and  108  were  found  to  be  0.0015,  0.0044,  0.0090,  0.0132, 
0.0157,  0.0097  and  0.0076.  Admitting  that  two  or  three  significant  figvues 
in  the  measure  of  precision  is  a  conservative  accuracy,  I  decided  to  retain 
four  decimals  in  the  tables  of  the  relative  frequencies  of  the  judgments. 

It  was  the  traditional  custom  in  statistics  and  psychophysics  to  use  the 
methods  of  physical  measurement  uncritically.  Lexis  and  his  followers  have 
shown  how  statistical  data  must  be  treated,  and  I  tried  to  develop  the 
theory  of  psychophysical  measurement.  That  this  can  be  done  has  been 
shown.  At  present  we  have  a  number  of  psychophysical  methods  which  may 
stand  alone  on  their  own  merit.  Neither  did  I  decide  hastily,  in  breaking 
away  from  the  old  notions.  It  may  be  that  there  is  a  connection  between 
the  theories  of  physical  and  of  psychophysical  measurement;  but  at  present 
we  know  only  little  about  it,  and  the  only  statement  which  one  could  make 
with  any  kind  of  confidence  is,  that  the  theory  of  physical  measurement 
must  be  based  on  that  of  psychophysical  measurement.  The  so-called  law 
of  the  distribution  of  errors  of  observation  has  resisted  all  attempts  at  a 
purely  mathematical  demonstration.  Innumerable  attempts  have  been 
made  to  explain  this  law — some  of  them  by  the  cleverest  mathematicians  the 
world  has  known — but  all  have  failed  in  so  far  as  their  proofs  necessitated 
the  introduction  of  some  one  assumption  which  is  equivalent  to  the  propo- 


300  URBAN 

sition  to  be  proved.  It  is  only  natural  to  suppose  that  this  law  contains 
some  supposition  of  non-mathematical  natiu-e.  It  seems  that  it  depends, 
in  some  way,  on  our  method  of  making  observations,  and  that  the  so-called 
Gaussian  coefficient  of  precision  is  closely  related  to  the  threshold  of 
difference,  a  fact  which  would  justify  Gauss  in  putting  this  quantity  directly 
proportional  to  the  accuracy  of  observation.  The  threshold  of  difference 
is  an  object  of  psychophysical  investigation,  and  for  this  reason  I  believe 
that  the  theory  of  physical  measurement  ought  to  be  based  on  that  of 
psychophysical  measurement. 

We  now  turn  to  Professor  Safford's  second  objection.  His  criticism  of  my 
use  of  Lagrange's  formula  of  interpolation  is  twofold:  first  that  the  calcula- 
tion is  carried  entirely  too  far,  and  second  that  the  interpolation  should 
have  been  effected  by  the  graphic  method.  Before  entering  upon  the 
discussion  of  these  objections  I  want  to  say  something  about  the  general 
piupose  of  interpolation.  It  frequently  happens  that  the  values  of  a  func- 
tion are  given  for  a  certain  number  of  values  of  the  independent  variable, 
and  that  one  wants  to  know  something  about  the  values  of  the  function  for 
intermediate  values  of  the  argument.  Every  procedure  which  serves  this 
pmpose  is  called  a  method  of  interpolation.  In  the  graphic  method  one 
plots  the  results  on  millimeter  paper  and  connects  these  points  by  a  smooth 
curve.  Every  point  of  the  curve  corresponds  to  a  certain  value  of  the  func- 
tion, which  in  many  cases  may  be  read  off  with  sufficient  accuracy.  This 
is  the  method  which  Professor  Safford  thinks  I  should  have  employed.  I 
have  done  so  as  a  matter  of  fact;  but  I  did  not  consider  such  results  of 
sufficient  interest  to  publish,  and  only  published  a  notice  in  the  Archivf.  d. 
ges.  Psychologie,  1910,  Vol.  18,  p.  410,  that  the  charts  are  at  the  command 
of  every  scientific  investigator,  who  may  be  interested  in  them.  The 
chief  objection  against  graphic  interpolation  is  that  it  is  too  arbitrary;  and 
for  this  reason  I  relied  upon  numerical  interpolation  alone. 

There  is  a  great  variety  of  methods  of  numerical  interpolation ;  but  the 
essential  feature  of  all  these  methods  is  that  an  algebraic  expression  is 
given,  which  may  be  fitted  to  the  course  of  any  function.  Two  of  the  best 
known  methods  are  known  as  Newton's  method  of  differences  and  La- 
grange's formula  of  interpolation.  Both  methods  are  essentially  identical, 
since  they  both  suppose  that  the  function  may  be  represented  by  an  alge- 
braic function  of  degree  n.  The  greater  the  number  of  observed  values  is, 
the  more  reliable  is  the  result  of  interpolation ;  and  it  is,  therefore,  desirable 
to  have  as  many  observed  values  as  possible.  In  a  scientific  investigation, 
however,  one  has  to  take  into  account  that  the  time  and  energy  of  the  ob- 
server are  limited  and  that  it  is  better  to  have  a  few  carefully  made  observa- 
tions than  a  mass  of  not  very  dependable  results.  In  planning  an  investi- 
gation one  has  to  strike  a  happy  medium,  which  gives  as  many  carefully 
made  observations  as  possible.  Experience  shows  that  in  the  study  of 
the  psychometric  fimctions  seven  values  of  the  comparison  stimulus  are 
as  much  as  can  be  handled  easily  and  effectively.  I  may  support  in  this 
respect  my  own  opinion  by  the  authority  of  G.  E.  Mueller.  It  is  obvious 
that  one  cannot  make  observations  for  every  intensity  of  the  comparison 
stimulus,  and  that  one  has  to  fall  back  upon  interpolation,  if  one  wants  to 
know  something  about  the  intermediate  values.  I,  therefore,  cannot  see 
the  reason  why  Professor  Safford  should  find  fault  with  my  tables,  because 
only  seven  entries  were  original  results,  a  fact  which  could  not  fail  to  be 
noted  by  anybody  who  read  the  text.  Tables  of  interpolated  values  are 
plentiful  in  physics  and  astronomy,  and  no  one  objects  to  them,  if  they  are 
properly  pointed  out  as  such. 

I  now  want  to  call  attention  to  a  small  error  in  Professor  Safford's  text 
and  a  slight  inconsistency  in  his  position.  He  says  on  p.  97  that  the 
seven  ordinates  were  treated  as  absolutely  exact.  This  is  not  quite  correct ; 
the  abscissae  were  so  treated.     He,  furthermore,  objects  to  the  actual  set- 


A  REPLY  TO   PROFESSOR   SAFFORD  30I 

ting  up  of  the  equations  by  Lagrange's  formula  on  account  of  the  great 
number  of  decimals  which  must  be  retained  in  the  coefficients,  but  does  not 
raise  the  same  objection  against  the  interpolation  without  setting  up  the 
equation.  The  advantage  of  this  formula  is  that  the  interpolation  can  be 
effected  without  setting  up  the  equation,  but  the  use  of  the  formula  never- 
theless implies  the  equation.  To  be  consistent  Professor  Safford  should 
have  objected  to  the  use  of  Lagrange's  formula  in  any  shape,  but  this 
would  have  precluded  the  use  of  Newton's  formula,  which  Professor  Safford 
favors,  because  it  gives  the  same  result  "and  requires  about  one-tenth  of 
the  labor."  I  beg  to  differ  on  this  score.  I  tried  both  methods  and  found 
that  the  nimiber  of  figures  to  be  written  down  to  effect  the  interpolation  for 
one  intermediate  value  and  all  my  seven  subjects  was  smaller  for  Lagrange's 
formula  than  for  Newton's  method  of  differences. 

Professor  Safford's  clever-  criticism  of  the  equation  set  up  for  the  psycho- 
metric function  for  Subject  /  is  likely  to  carry  the  most  conviction  to  the 
reader.  The  discrepancy  between  the  amount  of  work  spent  in  setting  up 
the  equation  and  the  result  obtained  is  so  great  that  one  cannot  possibly 
help  being  struck  by  it.  In  this  part  of  the  work  I  had  the  good  fortune  to 
obtain  the  services  of  a  professional  computer,  who  first  set  up  the  equation 
with  six  decimal  places  of  the  coefficients  only.  The  results  of  interpolation 
by  this  formula  were  fantastic,  because  the  curve  did  not  follow  the  actual 
results  at  all.  The  necessity  of  retaining  as  many  decimals  as  were  actually 
used  later  on,  began  to  dawn  upon  me  only  after  I  had  reasoned  out  that 
each  one  of  these  coefficients  had  to  be  multiplied  by  high  powers  of  num- 
bers around  100.  I  then  realized  the  necessity  of  carrying  out  all  divisions  to 
the  bitter  end,  and  incidentally  won  an  insight  into  the  nature  of  Lagrange's 
formula.  This  formula  is  a  merely  artificial  construction,  the  coefficients  of 
which  have  not  immediate  physical  significance  at  all.  The  formula  of 
interpolation  is  a  means  of  achieving  a  certain  purpose  and  he  who  wills  the 
purpose  must  will  the  means. 

It  is  very  interesting  to  analyze  Professor  Safford's  criticism  of  my 
statement  that  the  use  of  Lagrange's  formula  does  not  imply  a  definite 
hypothesis  about  the  psychometric  functions.  The  meaning  of  this  ex- 
pression, which  I  explained  at  some  length  elsewhere,  is  this.  The  psycho- 
metric functions  give  the  dependence  of  the  probabilities  of  the  different 
judgments  on  the  intensity  of  the  comparison  stimulus.  We  do  not  know 
anything  about  this  dependence,  but  we  have  to  make  some  hypothesis 
about  it  for  the  purpose  of  interpolation.  This  can  be  done  in  two  ways :  by 
assuming  a  function  which  fits  any  kind  of  results,  or  by  assuming  a  definite 
law  of  distribution.  Lagrange's  formula  belongs  to  the  first  class,  because  the 
degree  of  the  function  depends  on  the  number  of  observations  only.  The 
form  of  the  function  is,  therefore,  different  in  different  cases.  A  further  dif- 
ference between  these  assumptions  and  a  definite  hypothesis  about  the 
psychometric  functions  consists  in  the  fact  that  the  latter  admits  of  an 
extrapolation,  whereas  the  former  as  a  rule,  do  not. 

I  may  illustrate  this  distinction  by  the  following  example.  Suppose  that 
a  table  be  given,  which  we  know  contains  the  values  of  either  the  sine 
or  tangent  for  small  angles  but  we  do  not  know  which.  We  may  use 
Lagrange's  formula  for  interpolating  in  this  table,  and  we  may  represent 
the  course  of  the  function  in  this  interval  by  this  formula,  but  we  fully 
realize  that  this  hypothesis  is  not  definitive  but  subject  to  correction  and  that 
the  formula  will  not  represent  the  course  of  the  function  outside  the  interval. 
If,  however,  we  possess  some  further  information,  which  leads  us  to  beheve 
that  the  tables  contain  the  values  of  the  function  sine,  we  make  a  defini- 
tive hypothesis  about  the  function.  My  monograph  on  statistical  methods 
contains  only  a  casual  mention  of  this  distinction,  but  the  articles  in  the 
Archiv  leave  no  doubt  as  to  the  meaning  which  I  wanted  to  convey  by 
these  words. 


302  URBAN 

Professor  Safford's  criticism  is  this:  "Lagrange's  formula  gives  the 
equation  of  a  curve  through  n  points,  whose  degree  is  not  greater  than  n 
(tiiis  is  not  correct,  it  should  read  n-i ;  remark  of  the  writer),  and  the  n 
points  determine  the  curve  completely."  There  is  an  infinity  of  ciu^es  of 
the  same  type  and  Lagrange's  formula  merely  ha  s  the  merit  of  being  the 
simplest,  and  it  is  therefore  useless  to  spend  much  energy  upon  it.  This  is 
the  standpoint  of  the  mathematician,  whose  interest  Hes  in  the  study  of  the 
properties  of  whole  groups  of  curves.  The  standpoint  of  the  practical 
calculator  is  different.  He  attempts  to  reach  his  goal  by  the  shortest 
possible  route;  and  I,  for  one,  refuse  to  consider  a  method  of  which  I  know 
beforehand  that  it  has  no  merit  over  another  excepting  that  it  is  more 
complicated.  Whether  in  a  scientific  investigation  energy  is  spent  use- 
lessly or  not,  depends  upon  the  importance  of  the  results  obtained ;  and 
this  can  be  judged  by  the  specialist  alone.  I  do  not  believe  that  my  energy 
was  wasted  in  this  case,  for  I  am  willing  to  go  through  all  the  trouble  of 
working  out  my  data  merely  for  the  sake  of  fiinding  the  result,  that  the 
maximum  of  the  psychometric  function  of  the  equality  judgments  must  be 
related  to  the  threshold  of  difference. 

Professor  Safford  sees  a  further  objection  to  the  use  of  Lagrange's  formula 
in  the  fact  that  it  excludes  at  once  all  probability  curves,  symmetrical  as 
well  as  asymmetrical.  In  my  opinion,  this  is  one  of  the  greatest  advantages 
of  direct  interpolation  that  it  fits  the  actual  data  of  observation  without 
making  the  assumption  of  a  definite  law  of  distribution.  If  the  data 
follow  one  of  these  functions,  the  interpolation  by  Lagrange's  formula  will 
follow  it  closely  enough.  I  may  remark  that  I  am  at  this  point  in  perfect 
agreement  with  W.  Wirth,  who  in  his  latest  publication  employs  the  method 
of  direct  interpolation.  One  of  the  most  distressing  features  of  the  history 
of  psychophysics  is  the  endless  discussion  as  to  the  applicability  of  a  definite 
law  of  distribution.  It  was  my  purpose  to  get  away  from  this  discussion 
and  to  see  how  the  curves  would  look,  if  the  data  were  not  adjusted  accord- 
ing to  a  definite  law  of  distribution. 

Professor  Safford's  last  objection  is  based  on  the  fact  that  the  results  of 
direct  interpolation  do  not  agree  very  well  with  what  he  calls  the  theoreti- 
cal curves.  I  may  remark  here,  that  I  made  it  a  point  to  speak  of  hypo- 
thetical curves  and  not  of  theoretical  curves.  There  is,  of  course,  only 
little  difference  between  a  theory  and  an  hypothesis,  because  many  theories 
should  be  caHed  hypotheses ;  but  it  seems  to  be  a  pretty  general  rule  that 
one  does  not  call  a  doctrine  an  hypothesis,  unless  one  wants  to  emphasize 
the  hypothetical  element  in  it.  The  supposition  that  the  psychometric 
functions  belong  to  a  certain  type  has  the  character  of  an  hypothesis  in  a 
very  high  degree.  There  is  no  possibility  of  deciding  beforehand  whether 
the  data  will  fit  such  a  curve;  and  for  this  reason  one  ought  to  insist  on 
calling  such  an  assumption  an  hypothesis  and  not  a  theory.^  The  fact  that 
the  actual  distribution  does  not  coincide  with  the  hypothetical  one,  is  very 

II  may  be  allowed  to  state  here  the  reason  which  prompted  me  to  choose  the  term  0(7) 
hypothesis  instead  of  the  customary  name  of  Gaussian  distribution.  It  seems  to  me  that  this 
term  should  be  restricted  to  the  distribution  of  errors  of  observations  exclusively.  In  the 
work  of  Gauss  there  is  no  passage  known,  to  me,  which  could  lead  us  to  believe  that  Gauss 
would  have  applied  this  law  to  empirical  distributions  of  all  descriptions.  Considering  the 
practical  turn  of  Gauss's  mind,  it  seems  very  unlikely  indeed  that  he  would  have  favored  such 
an  unwarranted  generalization.  One,  therefore,  ought  to  speak  of  a  distribution  according 
to  the  probability  integral  or  to  the  0(7)  function.  To  call  this  function  by  the  name  of 
Kramp-Laplace,  as  Opitz  has  done,  makes  the  name  a  little  clumsy,  and  is  not  entirely 
justified  from  the  historical  point  of  view.  It  is  entirely  inadmissible  to  call  this  function 
by  the  name  of  Gauss;  and  the  chances  are  that  Gauss  himself  would  have  been  very  much 
surprised  by  this  honor.  In  the  Theoria  Motus  Corporum  CoeUstium  {Werke,  Vol.  vii,  p.  238) 
the  integral  is  referred  to  Laplace,  but  as  a  matter  of  fact  this  integral  was  already  known 
to  Euler.  Gauss  was  acquainted  with  this  fact,  as  may  be  seen  from  a  letter  dated  February 
10.  1810,  and  from  a  manuscript  note  to  the  Theoria  Motus.  To  call  the  function  by  the 
name  of  its  inventor,  one  has  to  take  one's  stand  in  a  complicated  historical  question,  for  the 
decision  of  which  the  complete  material  is  not  yet  at  hand. 


A  REPLY  TO  PROI^KSSOR  SAFPORD  303 

interesting  in  view  of  the  above  mentioned  discussion ;  but  it  is  not  so  much 
an  argument  against  the  use  of  direct  interpolation  as  one  against  the  use 
of  some  hypothetical  probability  curve. 

After  paying  me  some  compliments  as  to  the  mathematical  treatment  of 
my  problems,  of  which,  as  coming  from  an  authoritative  source,  I  am 
highly  appreciative.  Professor  Saflford  remarks  that  my  data  are  hardly 
sufficient  to  warrant  an  extensive  treatment.  Of  course  I  agree  that  it 
would  be  eminently  desirable  to  have  a  more  extended  material,  and  that 
it  would  be  possible  to  improve  upon  my  results ;  ^  but  I  must  insist  that  it 
is  at  present  the  most  suitable  material  for  testing  [the  different  psychophy- 
sical methods.  Other  statistical  sciences  make  very  extended  use  of  mathe- 
matical methods,  and  their  material  is  not  always  as  good  as  that  of  my 
experiments.  The  work  of  constructing  mortality  tables  requires  efforts 
compared  to  which  my  work — as  being  done  by  one  individual — shrinks 
into  insignificance ;  but  the  data  used  do  not  always  show  the  high  degree  of 
stability  of  those  found  in  my  experiments.  This  fact  may  readily  be  seen 
from  the  values  of  the  coefficients  of  divergence:  But  few  statistical  invest- 
igations deal  with  data  of  a  similar  degree  of  stability.  I  do  hope  that  we 
may  soon  possess  an  experimental  material  still  more  extended  than  my 
own;  but  until  then  my  data  are  the  best  available  for  the  specific  purpose 
of  testing  the  different  psychophysical  methods.  And  if  one  wants  to 
make  such  a  test  one  has  to  make  the  best  of  the  material  at  hand. 

Professor  Safford  has  iJresented  his  criticism  with  admirable  clearness 
and  precision;  but  I  am  convinced  that  his  position  is  untenable,  and  his 
argument  is  unsound.  The  methods  of  physical  measurement  cannot  be 
taken  over  bodily  and  applied  directly  to  the  problems  of  statistics  and  of 
psychophysics.  And  while  we  are  always  grateful  for  the  mathematician's 
interest  in  psychophysical  discussions,  yet  it  is  a  truism  that  every  science 
is  obliged  to  develop  its  own  methods,  and  to  grapple  with  its  problems  in 
its  own  way.  That  the  methods  and  the  problems  of  the  theory  of  obser- 
vations and  of  psychophysics  are  the  same  cannot  be  maintained;  whether, 
indeed,  any  intimate  relationship  obtains  between  these  two  fields  of  scien- 
tific endeavor  still  remains  to  be  determined. 


i 


BOOK  REVIEWS 


Dogmatism  and  Evolution.  By  Theodore  de  Lacuna  and  Grace  Andrus 
DE  Lacuna.     New  York,  The  Macmillan  Co.,  1910.     pp.  iv,  259. 

The  term  dogmatism,  as  employed  in  the  title  of  this  work,  is  intended 
"to  denote  the  body  of  logical  assumptions  which  were  generally  made  by 
thinkers  of  all  schools,  before  the  rise  of  theories  of  social  and  organic 
evolution.  Its  application  is  therefore  wider  than  common  usage  would 
warrant.  The  empiricism  of  Berkeley  and  Hume,  as  well  as  the  ration- 
alism of  Descartes  and  Leibniz,  is  induded  in  its  scope"  (Preface).  This 
usage  of  the  term  is  sufficiently  justified  by  the  presentation.  The  authors 
aim  to  make  prominent  the  fact  that  empiricism  and  rationalism,  in  spite 
of  their  wide  divergences,  are  founded  upon  a  common  basis,  and  that  this 
identity  of  assumption  is  more  significant  for  present-day  philosophy  than 
are  the  differences.  The  fundamental  dogma  behind  both  standpoints 
is  also  present  in  the  philosophy  of  Kant,  and  in  absolute  idealism.  The 
pragmatic  movement,  moreover,  which  is  principally  a  protest  against 
these  earlier  philosophies,  is  to  some  extent  misdirected,  since  it  perpetu- 
ates in  a  measure  this  self-same  dogma.  It  suffers  further  from  the 
inevitable  extravagances  and  overstatements  pertaining  to  doctrines  that 
express  the  irritation  of  a  reaction;  and  hence,  while  it  represents  an  im- 
portant truth,  it  requires  re-interpretation  and  correction. 

In  presentation  the  first  two  parts  of  the  book  in  particular  are  not  only 
compact  and  closely-reasoned,  but  coherent  and  lucid.  The  treatment 
of  the  subject-matter  can  lay  claim  to  originality,  and  is  splendidly  stimu- 
lating and  suggestive.  Historical  rationalism  and  empiricism  differ  in 
that  the  one  makes  an  appeal  to  mathematics  as  its  ideal  of  knowledge, 
while  the  other  relies  upon  introspection.  In  spite  of  this  contrast,  how- 
ever, they  both  assume  that  experience  presents  us  with  certain  unanalyz- 
able  elements,  which  serve  as  the  foundation  for  all  further  knowledge.  In 
the  case  of  rationalism,  these  simple  elements  are  imiversal  propositions 
possessing  intuitive  certainty;  in  the  case  of  empiricism,  they  are  particulars 
which  are  capable  of  entering  into  various  combinations.  Hence  both  en- 
counter the  same  difficulty,  for  both  are  committed  to  the  view  that  re- 
lations are  external  to  their  terms.  This  is  obviously  true  of  empiricism; 
but  it  is  no  less  true  of  rationalism,  for  the  relation  of  inclusion  cannot 
obtain  between  simple  concepts,  and  hence  rationalism  must  take  as  its 
starting-point,  not  concepts,  but  judgments  which  are  indemonstrable 
and  sjoithetical.  Spinoza,  indeed,  attempts  to  start  with  a  concept  in 
which  all  other  concepts  are  implicit,  viz.,  that  of  substance.  But 
the  exposition  runs  smoothly  merely  because  the  concept  is  at  once  com- 
pletely simple  (or  indeterminate)  and  infinitely  determined.  Rationalism 
fails  to  justify  either  the  syntlietic  character  of  its  most  fundamental 
judgments  or  the  passage  from  a  system  of  universal  truths  to  the  'in- 
finite determinations'  of  fact  in  which  this  system  finds  embodiment. 

This  result  sets  the  problem  for  Kant.  The  fact,  however,  that  'syn- 
thetic a  priori  judgments'  present  a  problem  at  all  is  due  to  the  assumption, 
whidi  Kant  shares  with  his  predecessors,  that  analysis  must  yield  final 
elements.  "No  proposition  could  be  determined  as  synthetic,  tmless 
a  complete  definition  of' its  terms  had  exhibited  their  ultimate  disparate- 
ness" (p.  73).  In  other  words,  Kant  proceeds  on  the  assmnption  that  pure 
thought  suppUes  to  experience  certain  universal  modes  of  relationship  to 


BOOK  REVIEWS  305 

which  every  experience  must  be  subject.  This  assumption  persists  in  ab- 
solute idealism.  At  first  sight,  the  contrast  between  rationalism  and  ab- 
solute idealism  is  as  great  as  could  well  be  imagined.  The  former  made 
relations  external;  the  latter  asserts  that '  'the  essences  of  things  are  wholly 
constituted  by  their  relations"  (88).  The  procedure  of  rationahsm  is  a 
descent  from  first  premises ;  that  of  absolute  idealism  is  an  ascent  of  which 
the  fimdamental  principle  of  the  entire  scheme  is  the  goal.  Yet  absolute 
idealism,  like  rationalism,  is  committed  to  the  proposition  that  '  'the  order 
and  connection  of  thoughts  and  the  order  and  connection  of  things  are  the 
same"  (108).  It  necessarily  depends  upon  an  inner  dialectic  for  the  move- 
ment of  its  self-contained  system  of  thought,  and  hence  it  has  to  choose  be- 
tween the  claim  of  being  able  to  account  antecedently  for  all  the  contingent 
facts  of  history,  or  else  to  accept  existing  irrational  facts,  and  thus  to  admit 
an  irreconcilable  contradiction  in  its  theory  of  actuality. 

It  appears,  then,  that  rationalism,  empiricism  and  absolute  idealism  are 
all  dogmatic,  in  that  they  all  proceed  upon  the  basis  of  an  untested  assump- 
tion with  regard  to  the  'simple  elements'  or  constituents  of  experience.  On 
the  other  hand,  pragmatism  bases  itself  upon  evolution  and  endeavors  to 
give  a  functional  interpretation  of  logical  and  psychological  problems. 
With  this  endeavor  the  authors  profess  themselves  in  sympathy.  Their 
argument,  however,  is  intended  neither  as  a  defense  of  pragmatism  nor 
as  an  attack  upon  it,  but  as  a  justification  of  the  charge  that  current  prag- 
matism is  "only  half -free  from  the  grip  of  the  traditions  which  it  openly 
repudiates,"  and  thus  untrue  to  the  deeper  spirit  of  its  own  standpoint. 

As  a  matter  of  presentation  it  is  unfortunate  that  the  authors  do  not 
connect  the  discussion  of  pragmatism  more  closely  with  the  results  of  the 
preceding  exposition.  As  they  themselves  admit  in  the  preface,  this  omission 
detracts  appreciably  from  the  unity  of  treatment.  The  basis  for  the  charge 
against  pragmatism,  it  seems,  is  the  fact  that  the  latter  has  formed  en- 
tangling alliances  with  immediatism.  While  pragmatism  is  right  in  its 
emphasis  upon  functionalism,  its  most  prominent  advocates  have  all  pro- 
fessed their  adherence  to  some  form  of  immediatism.  This  creed  is  not 
only  inessential  to  pragmatism  as  such,  but  is  incompatible  with  its  deeper 
meaning,  for  it  introduces  once  more  the  attempt  to  base  our  thinking 
upon  a  'simple  element'  or  'given.'  A  starting-point  of  this  kind  neces- 
sarily leads  to  perverted  notions  regarding  the  nature  of  thought.  In 
effect  it  means  that  relations  once  more  become  external,  as  appears  most 
strikingly  in  Professor  James's  contention  that  "the  self -same  piece  of 
experience  taken  twice  over  in  different  contexts"  is  equivalent  to  the  dis- 
tinction between  knower  and  known.  The  relations  are  treated  as  merely 
additive,  /.  e.,  as  exerting  no  influence  upon  the  character  of  the  ex- 
perience. Essentially  the  same  criticism  applies  to  the  pragmatic  treat- 
ment of  concepts.  While  it  is  true  that  concepts  necessarily  have  reference 
to  conduct,  it  does  not  follow  that  the  nature  of  the  concept  is  exhausted 
in  any  direct  and  'external'  relation  of  the  given  experience  to  a  specific 
form  of  conduct.  The  relation  of  the  concept  to  conduct  is  more  indirect 
and  equivocal.  '  'From  the  standpoint  of  biological  utility  it  is  clear  that 
the  object,  so  far  from  meaning  a  definite  type  of  behavior,  is  recognized 
as  an  object  only  as  it  is  associated  with  important  diversity  of  behavior 
in  characteristically  different  situations"  (p.  168).  In  other  words,  the 
concept  is  of  necessity  more  inclusive  than  any  given  type  of  behavior. 
The  concept  cannot  be  identified  with  any  conscious  process,  however 
complex,  for  "the  group  of  associations  which  constitutes  the  concept 
may  never  in  its  entirety  be  present  to  consciousness  in  any  single  ex- 
perience" (p.  170).  It  follows,  furthermore,  that  "apart  from  this  refer- 
ence of  thought  to  conduct,  that  is  to  say,  in  the  limitless  interrelations 
of  concepts  with  each  other,  thought  has  as  distinctive  a  form  as  any  ab- 
stractly considered  entity  whatsoever"  (p.  207). 


306  BOOK  REVIEWS 

The  gist  of  the  matter,  then,  as  regards  current  pragmatism,  seems  to 
lie  in  the  proposition  thatfimctionalism  may  be  divorced  from  immediatism. 
On  just  this  point,  however,  the  position  taken  in  the  book  does  not  seem 
to  be  altogether  consistent.  In  the  discussion  of  J,  S.  Mill's  theory  of 
objectivity  (pp.  173-185),  it  is  pointed  out  that  Mill's  fundamental  mistake 
lies  in  the  fact  that  he  takes  simple  elements  of  sensation  as  his  starting- 
point.  These  elements  are  held  together  by  connections  which  Mill  re- 
gards as  'real'  but  as  inexplicable.  The  alternative  proposed  by  the  authors 
is  that  sensation  is  a  scientific  construct,  that  the  distinction  between  sen- 
sations and  relations  is  simply  a  matter  of  logical  analysis.  In  other  words, 
the  relations  fall  within  the  experience  quite  as  much  as  do  the  sense-ele- 
ments. This  is  only  another  way  of  saying  that  objects  are  immediately 
presented — however  we  may  see  fit  to  interpret  objectivity.  Earlier  in 
the  chapter,  however,  the  distinction  between  the  'given'  and  its  relations 
is  drawn  in  quite  as  hard  and  fast  a  way  as  was  ever  done  by  Mill.  A 
passage  was  quoted  in  the  preceding  paragraph  to  the  effect  that  the  con- 
cept is  never  in  its  entirety  present  to  consciousness  in  any  single  experience. 
So  far  as  the  exposition  goes,  there  is  no  ground  for  the  belief  that  it  is 
ever  present  to  any  degree  or  in  any  intelligible  sense  whatever.  On  page 
171  the  question  is  raised:" How,  indeed,  can  given  conscious  contents 
'represent'  or  'mean'  or  'point  to'  other  possible  contents  not  given?" 
The  answer  which  is  suggested  is  that  there  is  a  tendency  on  the  part  of 
the  associated  experiences  to  rise  to  clear  consciousness,  and  that  "such 
inhibited  tendencies  to  revival  may  affect  in  a  distinctive  manner  the 
qualitative  tone  of  the  existing  content."  Such  an  explanation  obviously 
fails  to  explain.  We  must  either  identify  the  concept  with  these  nascent 
associations,  which  is  incompatible  with  the  general  account  given  of  the 
concept,  or  we  are  forced  to  recognize  that  the  tendencies  in  question  can, 
at  most,  effect  a  change  in  the  quality  or  structure  of  what  is  presented  or 
experienced,  a  change  which  may  perhaps  be  interpreted  as  corresponding 
to  the  function,  but  which  is  in  no  sense  identical  with  it.  In  other  words, 
the  relations  or  functions,  regarded  as  such,  necessarily  fall  outside  the  experi- 
ence .  That  this  is  the  intention  is  evidenced  by  the  general  tenor  of  the  book, 
and  in  particular  by  the  avowed  agreement  on  this  point  with  Berkeley 
and  by  the  assertion  that  the  'real'  is  never  experienced  but  always  re- 
mains ideal. 

The  implication  of  the  foregoing,  it  is  evident,  is  that  Dogmatism  and 
Evolution  is  itself  in  bondage  to  the  tradition  which  it  accuses  pragmatism 
of  perpetuating.  It  is  committed  to  the  very  opposition  of  imiversal  and 
particular  which  it  charges  against  the  '  'immediate  empiricism"  of  Profes- 
sor Dewey  (pp.  244,  246).  In  the  end,  the  denial  of  immediatism  is  purely 
verbal,  for  the  relations  or  meanings  which  are  necessary  to  constitute 
things  are  opposed  to  what  is  'given.'  Hence  we  have  the  assertion  that 
the  'real'  is  "never  immediately  experienced  at  all;  it  is  always  ideal" 
(p.  245).  This  charge,  however,  is  significant,  for  it  seems  to  indicate 
the  source  of  the  trouble.  The  immediatism  attributed  to  Professor 
Dewey  is  essentially  that  of  the  older  empiricism — the  immediatism  which 
constitutes  a  contrast  to  all  forms  of  interpretation  or  mediation.  It  is 
urged,  for  example,  that  immediate  experience  can  contain  no  imcertainty 
and  doubtfulness;  also  that  the  Zollner  lines  cannot  be  immediately  ex- 
perienced as  convergent, — the  reason  in  the  latter  case  being  that  conver- 
gent lines  are  lines  which  when  extended  meet  in  a  point,  whereas  the  lines 
in  question  do  not  meet  imless  conceived  as  extended.  In  other  words,  if 
the  lines  are  conceived  as  extended,  the  experience  is  held  to  be  no  longer 
immediate.  The  point  of  Dewey's  contention,  however,  is  that  both  the 
immediate  and  the  mediate  of  ordinary  philosophical  usage  are  enveloped 
in  a  wider  immediacy,  and  that  this  immediacy  is  meant  when  the  assertion 
is  made  that  things  are  what  they  are  experienced  as.     Moreover,  as  Pro- 


BOOK  REVIEWS  307 

fessor  Dewey  says,  this  proposition  is  not  identical  with  the  platitude  that 
experience  is  experience,  but  has  the  significance  of  a  method  of  philo- 
sophical analysis.  If  mediation  is  itsel  1  immediately  experienced,  the 
proper  way  to  find  out  its  nature  is  to  observe  its  operations  as  they 
occur,  instead  of  applying  the  mediation  ah  extra,  as  has  been  done  so  fre- 
quently in  the  past. 

In  brief,  then,  it  would  seem  that  if  the  function  and  content  of  concepts 
are  not  immediately  experienced,  we  are  back  at  the  standpoint  of  Mill, 
and  left  to  derive  what  comfort  we  can  from  the  classification  of  a  con- 
tradiction as  an  'ultimate  mystery.'  On  this  ground,  moreover,  we  seem 
compelled  to  choose  between  the  alternatives  offered  by  Professor  Royce, 
viz.,  a  validism  of  Mill's  type,  and  a  world  which  is  the  embodiment  of  an 
"absolute  system  of  ideas."  At  all  events,  we  can  hardly  be  content  to 
say  merely  that  the  real  is  always  ideal.  On  the  other  hand,  if  mediation 
is  directly  experienced,  there  seems  to  be  no  ground  for  identifying  the 
real  with  something  beyond  experience  or  with  any  particular  kind  of  ex- 
perience.    One  experience  is  then,  to  all  appearances,  as  real  as  another. 

In  conclusion  the  reviewer  piay  be  allowed  to  say  that  since  limitations 
of  space  do  not  permit  comment  upon  the  many  excellent  discussions  con- 
tained in  the  book,  the  foregoing  critisicm  may  well  seem  disproportionate, 
in  view  of  the  many  solid  merits  of  the  work.  But  disagreement,  even 
though  pretty  fundamental,  is  entirely  compatible  with  sincere  respect  and 
appreciation.  Readers  who  remain  unconvinced  by  the  third  part  will 
nevertheless  find  the  work  one  of  distinct  and  unusual  ability,  a  work  that 
will  abundantly  repay  a  careful  reading.  B.  H.  Bode 

University  of  Illinois 

Manual  of  Mental  and  Physical  Tests.     By  Guy  Montrose  Whipple,Ph.D. 
Baltimore,  Warwick  and  York,  1910.     pp.  ix,534. 

This  manual  includes  a  description  of  the  apparatus  and  method  of  ad- 
ministration of  fifty-four  tests  or  groups  of  tests,  a  series  of  accoimts  of  the 
chief  results  obtained  by  those  who  have  used  them,  and  a  corresponding 
series  of  bibliographies.  There  is  also  a  summary  of  the  formulae  and 
tables  useful  in  calculating  central  tendencies,  variabilities,  reliabilities  and 
correlations  from  the  obtained  measures. 

Eighty  pages  are  given  to  means  of  measuring  height,  weight,  head-shape 
and  size,  breathing  capacity,  and  muscular  strength,  speed,  precision  and 
steadiness.  The  next  ninety  pages  concern  tests  of  sensory  capacity. 
Under  the  headings  'Tests  of  Attention  and  Perception'  and  'Tests  of 
Description  and  Report,'  we  have,  in  the  next  ninety  pages,  carefully  elab- 
orated forms  of  tests  in  perceiving  letters, words,  etc.,  exposed  by  the  tach- 
istoscope,  in  cancelling  words,  letters,  etc.,  printed  amongst  others,  in 
counting  dots,  in  reading,  in  adding  a  one  place  number  to  three  given  mun- 
bers  in  succession,  in  simultaneous  reading  and  writing,  and  in  describing 
and  passing  a  detailed  examination  upon  objects.  A  fourth  portion  of  the 
same  length  covers  tests  of  association  (thinking  of  a  word,  of  a  word  to 
fulfill  certain  requirements,  and  of  the  facts  needed  for  simple  computations), 
learning  (to  copy  drawings  seen  in  a  mirror  and  to  translate  certain  char- 
acters into  nmnbers  with  the  aid  of  a  'dictionary'  printed  on  the  blank),  and 
memory  (of  series  of  digits,  letters  and  words,  and  of  passages).  Finally, 
in  somewhat  over  a  himdred  pages  we  find  tests  of  suggestibility,  imagina- 
tion, invention,  intellectual  equipment,  and  developmental  diagnosis. 
These  include,  often  in  improved  forms,  the  size-weight  illusion,  Binet's 
other  tests  for  suggestibiHty,  tests  of  the  effect  of  suggested  warmth,  Dear- 
born's ink-blot  test,  the  familiar  school  tasks  of  including  given  words  in 
a  sentence,  completing  sentences  and  writing  compositions,  word-building 
from  given  letters,  the  Ebbinghaus  'Combination'  test.  Swift's  interpreta- 
tion of  fables,  Kirkpatrick's  test  of  knowledge  of  the  meaning  of  words. 


308  BOOK  REVIEWS 

Whipple's  test  of  range  of  information  and  the  De  Sanctis  and  Binet- 
Simon  tests  of  intelligence. 

The  tests  have  been  chosen  on  the  basis  of  thorough  knowledge  of  the 
work  that  has  been  done  in  the  field  and  with  due  appreciation  of  the  uses 
to  which  they  will  be  put.  Although  probably  no  student  of  the  subject 
will  agree  with  Mr.  Whipple 's  selections  in  every  case,  all  will  admire  their 
general  worth  and  timeliness.  And  those  who  find  the  most  to  disagree 
with  will  perhaps  appreciate  their  general  worth  most  fully.  Any  one  who 
plans  to  measure  intellectual  abilities  of  whatever  sort,  should  as  a  first  step 
become  familiar  with  the  tests  recommended  in  this  Manual. 

The  chief  desiderata  in  means  of  measuring  mental  traits  are  that  some- 
thing of  importance  be  measured,  that  the  resulting  quantity  be  objective 
or  verifiable  by  any  competent  observer,  that  the  precision  or  freedom 
from  variable  error  attainable  from  a  given  expenditure  of  a  subject's 
time  be  reasonably  great,  that  the  time  and  energy  of  the  experimenter  be 
economized,  and  that  the  results  be  commensurate  with  those  hitherto  ob- 
tained in  measurements  of  the  mental  trait  in  question.  There  results  a 
balance  of  goods  in  the  selection  or  invention  of  a  test  in  the  case  of  almost 
every  mental  trait.  Consequently,  a  practically  infinite  amount  of  ingenu- 
ity can  be  expended  in  devising  tests  to  satisfy  best  these  desiderata.  A  stand- 
ard test,  in  the  sense  of  an  imimprovable  one,  probably  does  not  now,  and 
will  not  for  a  long  time,  exist  in  the  case  of  any  mental  trait. 

Professor  Whipple  has  all  these  facts  in  mind,  but,  I  think,  in  two  ways 
does  not  quite  maintain  the  most  serviceable  balance  amongst  them.  In 
some  cases  he  perhaps  imposes  too  great  a  burden  upon  the  experimenter 
in  order  to  make  too  slight  a  gain  in  objectivity,  precision  or  comparability 
with  previous  work.  He  is  also  too  modest  in  reconmiending  a  test  which 
happens  to  have  been  used  by  some  one  a  few  times,  instead  of  devising  a 
far  better  one  himself.  For  example,  counting  dots  (Test  27),  adding  a 
given  number,  say  3,  in  succession  to  three  numbers  and  continuing  with 
the  sums  thus  obtained  (Test  29),  amenability  to  oral  suggestions  from  the 
experimenter  (Test  43),  and  the  interpretation  of  fables  (Test  49)  have  been 
very  seldom  used  and  could  easily  be  very  much  improved. 

The  very  difficult  task  of  giving  instructions  in  the  administration  of  all 
these  tests  is  well  done.  Often  the  desirable  plan  of  printing  exactly  what 
the  experimenter  shall  say  is  followed.  A  mass  of  minor  information  hither- 
to acquired  at  great  cost  of  time  by  imitation,  can  thus  be  put  into  the  student's 
hands  once  for  all.  If  mental  measurements  are  to  be  made  by  others 
than  trained  experts,  such  detailed  instructions  (possibly  even  still  more 
detailed  and  rigorous  instructions)  must  be  accessible  in  print. 

It  would  have  been  a  great  addition  to  the  usefulness  of  the  manual  if 
Mr.  Whipple  had  given  approximate  measures  of  the  nujnber  of  trials  with 
each  test  necessary  to  secure  a  given  degree  of  reliability.  For  individual 
diagnosis  and  prognosis,  for  measurements  of  change  and  for  measurements 
of  the  relations  between  mental  abilities,  it  is  of  very  great  importance  to 
reduce  the  unreliability  of  the  average  or  median  ability  found  for  an  in- 
dividual to  a  small  per  cent.  Investigators  commonly  err  by  dispersing 
their  time  over  too  many  individuals,  not  measuring  each  one  precisely 
enough  to  allow  straightforward  inferences  about  anything  save  group 
averages. 

Where  the  author  does  announce  the  number  of  trials  to  be  made,  I 
fear  that  he  gives  too  few.  For  example,  in  measurements  of  the  delicacy 
of  sensory  discrimination,  he  commonly  requires,  after  a  brief  preliminary 
series,  only  ten  judgments  with  the  difference  chosen,  ten  with  one  a  little 
greater  and  ten  with  one  a  little  less.  It  would  seem  that  if  sensory  dis- 
crimination is  to  be  measured  by  the  per  cent,  of  right  judgments,  at  least 
fifty  judgments  of  a  given  difference  should  be  taken.     If  only  ten  are  to 


BOOK  REVIEWS  309 

be  taken,  an  arran-gement  to  use  the  average  error  made  by  the  subject 
seems  preferable  in  many  cases. 

I  may  note  also  that  to  give  only  differences  and  permit  only  judgments 
of  more  ...  or  less  .  .  .  relieves  the  experimenter  from  very  annoying  elements 
in  the  latter  calculations  and  on  the  whole  seems  better  than  to  allow  judg- 
ments of  'equal.'     The  author's  instructions  vary  on  this  point. 

The  chapter  on  statistical  methods  gives  the  standard  formulae  with 
illustrations  of  their  calculation.  It  is  made  specially  useful  by  including 
the  later  short  methods  of  calculating  correlations.  I  regret  that  the 
author  accepts  Pearson's  speculative  assumption  that  to  compare  the  vari- 
abilities of  two  series  each  gross  variability  should  be  divided  by  the  cor- 
responding central  tendency.  No  one  method  o  rendering  the  variabilities 
of  the  same  group  in  different  traits  or  different  groups  in  the  same  trait 
comparable  is  universally  valid,  and  certainly  not  the  method  of  dividing 
by  the  central  tendency.  Dividing  by  the  square  root  of  the  central  ten- 
dency will  be  more  often  and  more  nearly  right. 

The  summaries  of  work  done  and  the  bibliographies  accompanying  them 
represent  a  scholarly  heroism  all  of  whose  sins  of  commission  and  omission 
will  readily  be  pardoned  by  any  one  who  has  tried  to  do  the  like.  The 
only  serious  fault,  I  think,  is  in  quoting  as  measures  of  correlations,  figures 
'  got  before  the  effect  of  the  variable  errors  of  the  original  deviation-measures 
in  reducing  the  obtained  correlation  from  the  true  correlation  toward  zero 
had  been  discovered  by  Spearman.  The  obtained  correlations  of  Aikins, 
Thomdike  and  Hubbell  and  Wissler  were  thus  necessarily  far  too  low.  Mr. 
Whipple's  interest  in  the  generally  neglected  subject  of  correlations  also 
leads  him  to  mislead  the  ordinary  reader  by  quoting  resemblances  of  related 
individuals  in  the  same  trait  along  with  the  resemblances  of  a  person's  degree 
of  ability  in  one  trait  to  his  ability  in  another.  The  former  should  be 
carefully  explained  if  quoted  at  all  in  such  connection. 

It  is  to  be  hoped  that  this  book  and  the  reports  that  are  being  issued  by 
the  American  Psychological  Association's  committee  on  tests  will  be  studied 
and  used  by  every  investigator  of  human  intellectual  performance  here  and 
abroad.  The  earlier  expectations  from  tests  of  human  faculty  on  the  basis  of 
the  faculty  psychology,  being  too  great,  were  destined  to  disappointment, 
but  now  that  the  complexity,  variability  and  relative  independence  of  men- 
tal functions  are  being  understood  and  allowed  for,  we  may  hope  for  a  revival 
of  interest  in  inventories  of  individual  intellects,  in  measuring  the  changes 
which  they  undergo  by  growth  and  training,  and  the  causes  of  their  original 
capacities.  If  Professor  Whipple's  work  did  nothing  more  than  stimulate 
other  investigators  to  measure  the  reliability  of  his  tests,  their  susceptibility 
to  practice  effect  and  their  value  as  symptoms  of  more  general  conditions, 
and  so  to  amend  or  even  replace  them,  it  would  have  abundantly  justified 
itself.     It  will  do  much  more  than  this.  E.  L.  Thorndikb 

Teachers  College,  Colimibia  University 

The  Phenomenology  of  Mind,  by  G.  W.  F.  Hegel.  Edited,  with  an  intro- 
duction and  notes,  by  J.  B.  Baillie.  London,  Swan  Sonnenschein 
&  Co.,  1910.  2  volumes.  Vol.  i,  pp.  xHv.,  427;  vol.  ii,  pp.  viii.,  429- 
823. 

In  Professor  J.  B.  Baillie's  recent  translation  we  have  now  before  us 
Hegel's  Phdnomenologie  des  Geistes  in  an  adequate  English  dress.  The 
Teuton  has  so  far  failed  to  make  anything  worth  while  out  of  this  unique 
intellectual  product  from  a  fellow-member  of  his  race.  It  is  now  handed  over 
to  a  more  distant  relative,  but  perhaps  none  the  less  close  still  to  the  central 
intellectual  tendencies  of  the  Germanic  races  for  the  rapport  necessary  to 
its  understanding,  in  a  form  to  make  it  more  readily  accessible,  and  so  to 
give  the  Anglo-Saxon  a  turn  at  its  interpretation.  As  is,  in  part,  implied 
in  these  two  sentences,  we  shall  probably  have  to  approach  the  translation, 


3IO  BOOK  REVIEWS 

which  as  adequately  represents  the  original  as  this  is  possible  in  a  transla- 
tion, on  the  assumption  that  it  is  only  a  means  to  an  end,  for  two  reasons. 
First,  the  genius  of  language,  reflecting  the  habits  of  thought  of  a  race,  is 
sufficiently  diverse  in  the  English  and  the  German  to  require  a  closer  adap- 
tation of  the  methods  of  presentation  than  a  mere  translation  affords. 
Secondly,  Hegel's  presentation  is,  in  fact,  inadequate  to  begin  with,  and 
naturally  so  because  he  had  undertaken  a  task  to  which  there  were  no 
established  precedents  other  than  mere  vague  effort;  and  the  great  bulk 
of  modem  scientific  work  giving  a  training  in  accurate  formulation  has  all 
come  after  him,  so  that  his  work  needs  first  of  all  to  be  modernized.  But 
the  present  translation  will  now  unite  the  efforts  of  interpretation  over  a 
greatly  extended  area. 

In  a  brief  appreciation  of  such  a  book  as  the  present  there  are  perhaps 
essentially  two  things  of  interest  to  the  reader.  First  comes  the 
question  as  to  the  piu-pose  of  the  book,  and  as  to  whether  its  preparation 
is  adequate  to  the  purpose.  Second,  and  of  equal  importance  would,  in 
the  present  instance,  probably  be  additional  suggestions  calculated  to 
enhance  the  value  of  the  book.  The  first  has  probably  been  sufficiently 
considered  above;  to  the  second  we  might  now  give  a  little  more  attention. 
In  general,  the  cynical  aspersion  on  Hegel's  work  of  its  being  an  intellect- 
ual travesty  cannot  satisfy  an  impartial  mind  upon  a  glance  at  the  table 
of  contents  and  a  mere  superficial  perusal  of  the  text  of  the  Phdnomenologie. 
Particularly,  great  emphasis  is  everywhere  put  on  the  unity  of  all  matter  of 
experience,  and  on  the  need  of  taking  fully  into  account  the  presuppositions 
implied  in  our  expositions  in  science  through  this  unity  of  all  matter  of 
experience.  This  receives  practically  no  attention  in  present-day  science, 
while  its  recognition  would  bring  about  a  far  reaching  revolution  in  science. 
To  get  into  Hegel's  analysis  in  the  present  work,  a  very  close  study  of  his 
Introduction,  with  all  the  implications,  is  advisable  for  the  necessary  point 
of  view.  This  point  of  view  is  not  that  experience  as  a  whole  must  be  ex- 
plained in  terms  of  some  single  definite  conception,  as  idealism,  monism, 
materialism,  psychophysical  parallelism,  and  so  on;  but  that  these  very 
conceptions  themselves  are  all  elements  in  the  form  of  stages  in  this  experi- 
ence, while  the  single  fact  of  experience  as  a  distinct  conception  is  nothing 
for  us.  Perhaps  due  largely  to  its  subject-matter,  the  English  rendering 
of  the  Introduction  is  particularly  good,  so  that  not  even  an  original  re- 
formulation in  the  English  could  improve  it  much.  One  suggestion  might 
here  be  made,  which  has  reference  more  especially  to  the  genius  of  the 
English  language  and  the  Anglo-Saxon  habit  of  mind.  If  in  place  of  the 
abstract  noun  representing  completed  action  the  present  participle  of 
continuing  action  were  more  generally  used,  or  if  the  reader  will  more 
generally  supply  the  sense  of  a  continuing  for  that  of  a  completed  action, 
the  representation  of  the  original  would  be  more  exact;  as  for  instance 
near  the  top  of  page  78,  by  putting  for  die  Darstellung  des  ersckeinenden 
Wissens,  "the  presentation  of  a  developing  knowing  "  instead  of  "the  expo- 
sition of  knowledge  as  a  phenomenon."  This  will  make  awkward  EngUsh, 
but  it  more  adequately  represents  the  continuous  flux  of  conceptions  as 
necessary  to  understand  Hegel,  contrasting  with  the  fixedness  or  permanent 
demarcation  of  conceptions  in  the  English. 

It  might  be  to  the  point  to  consider  this  flux  of  conceptions  in  Hegel's 
method  a  little  farther;  and  the  real  nature  of  this  flux  is  best  shown  by  its 
formal  recognition  in  the  antinomy.  In  the  antinomy,  we  have  a  contrast 
of  two  mutually  exclusive  or  incompatible  appearances  of  the  same  matter 
of  experience  of  such  a  nature  that  one  of  them  complete  and  distinct,  but 
only  one,  is  necessarily  present  while  the  other  is  impossible  for  the  time 
being.  Upon  close  examination  and  analysis  of  the  appearance  present, 
however,  it  literally  dissolves,  as  if  by  magic,  under  our  very  eyes ;  and  its 
contrasting  opposite  appears  and  immediately  takes  its  place.  Moreover, 
only  at  the  completion  of  the  actual  perversion  are  the  full  meaning  and  all 


BOOK   REVIEWS  311 

implications  of  each  of  the  two  forms  of  appearance  of  the  experience 
wholly  understood.  Classic  among  such  antinomies  are  those  regarding 
the  nature  of  motion  in  our  environment  developed  among  the  ancient 
Greeks;  regarding  the  innateness  of  ideas,  developed  by  ways  of  reaction 
between  Descartes  and  Locke;  regarding  the  nature  of  the  reality  of  the 
matter  of  our  experience,  developed  by  Berkeley  and  Hiune;  and  the  cosmo- 
logical  antinomies  of  Kant.  Besides  these  particular  instances,  the  an- 
tinomy can,  however,  be  found  permeating  our  experience  everywhere. 
Through  it  is  revealed  an  actual  single  inner  movement  and  unity,  in 
the  universe  as  it  surrounds  us,  totally  different  from  the  cosmic  motion 
of  the  Copemican  system  and  not  recognized  in  present-day  science  but 
which  alone  will  account  for  such  perplexing  phenomena  as  the  action  of 
force  at  a  distance.  The  fixedness  of  conception,  then,  as  most  character- 
istic of  the  Anglo-Saxon  mind,  here  invariably  leads  to  confusion  and  a 
sense  of  loss  of  reality  with  the  passing  of  the  forms  present,  because  the 
continued  presence  simply  of  thi  fixed  forms  is  taken  to  be  the  reality, 
while  philosophical  analysis  invariably  shows  that  the  forms  cannot  be 
so  retained.  The  Introduction,  from  page  82  to  89  of  the  translation, 
read  in  the  light  of  this  suggestion,  may  prove  to  be  of  more  value,  reference 
being  had  not  only  to  the  fact  of  flux,  but  also  to  the  mode  of  flux,  of  con- 
ceptions. 

Futhermore,  Hegel  in  his  analyses  exhibits  a  kind  of  pedagogical  ungain- 
liness,  which  borne  in  mind  will  explain  and  clear  up  no  small  part  of  his 
obscurity.  So  the  following  summary  may  serve  to  guide  and  elucidate. 
The  *  'Meaning  "  in  the  section  heading  on  page  90  of  the  translation  should 
be  understood  in  the  sense  of  "Supposing;"  for  this  beginning  section, 
subordinated  under  the  general  head  of  Consciousness,  is  a  discussion  of 
the  sinnliche  Gewissheit  eines  gemeinten  Diesen.  the  sensations  or  sensuous 
awareness  of  a  supposed  this  as  apart  by  itself,  over  against  the  knowing, 
which  is  the  beginning  of  all  conscious  knowledge.  The  next  sub-section 
under  the  head  of  Perception  (page  104)  examines  the  development  and 
nature  of  the  unities  in  things,  under  another  aspect  also  called  universals, 
as  essentially  forming  the  basis  of  our  conceptions  of  the  nature  of  things. 
The  third  sub-section  under  the  head  of  Understanding  (page  124)  discusses 
the  formation  of  a  continuous  scheme  of  things  constituting  our  conception 
of  the  nature  of  things  and  consisting  of  two  fundamentally  distinct  parts 
or  elements,  the  physical  occurrence  or  fact  of  experience,  and  the  apper- 
ceptive content  or  metaphysical  part  in  an  AristoteHan  sense.  Following 
these  three  sub-sections  under  the  general  heading  of  Self-consciousness 
(page  163)  is  shown  the  mode  of  appearance  of  a  persisting  self  possible 
only  through  a  succession  of  antinomies  or  course  of  antinomic  dialectic. 
The  preceding  sub-sections  show  the  essential  elements  in  ordinary  know- 
ing in  their  more  or  less  independently  distinct  character;  in  this  section 
we  have  these  elements,  mutually  dependent,  forming  an  indissoluble 
system.  The  rest  of  the  work,  beginning  with  a  section  under  the  head  of 
Reason  (page  220),  then  shows  how  out  of  the  movement  of  successive 
reactions  between  the  antinomic  moments,  in  a  single  movement,  of  a 
persisting  self  knowing  and  an  other  than  the  self  known,  develops  the 
comprehensive  structure  of  science,  the  conventionalized  conscious  content 
of  our  experience.  A  closing  section  under  the  head  of  Absolute  Knowl- 
edge (page  800)  then  considers  various  characteristic  incidents  of  the 
independent  absolute  form  attained  in  our  experience  by  the  foregoing 
mode  of  analysis.  Hsnry  Heitmann 

Clark  University 

De  Vorigine  et  de  la  nature  mnemoniques  des  tendances  affectives.     Par  K. 

RiGNANO.     Estratto  da  "  Scienticia":  Rivista  di  Scienza.     Vol.  9, 

Anno  5  (i9ii).N.     XVII.  i.Traduit  par  le  Prof.   J.    Dubois.  35  P- 

In  this  article  the  author  outlines  a  genetic  theory  of  the  affective  states. 

The  term  affective  is  restricted  to  the  special  category  of  organic  tendencies 


312  BOOK  REVIEWS 

which  manifest  themselves  subjectively  in  man  as  desires,  appetites  or 
needs,  and  which  objectively,  in  both  man  and  animals,  are  translated  into 
non-mechanized  movements.  Admitting  this  definition,  the  author  re- 
duces the  entire  series  of  the  principal  affective  tendencies  to  the  single 
fundamental  tendency  of  the  organism  toward  its  own  physiological  state 
of  equilibrium.  This  tendency  may  be  observed  in  all  unicellular  organ- 
isms, e.  g.,  hunger  which  is  the  most  fundamental  affective  state  is  redu- 
cible to  a  tendency  to  maintain  or  re-establish  in  the  nutritive  internal 
milieu  the  qualitative  and  quantitative  conditions  which  permit  a  station- 
ary metabolic  state.  This  tendency  toward  a  state  of  metabolic  equili- 
brium has  become,  in  the  course  of  phyletic  evolution,  a  tendency  to  accom- 
plish all  the  acts  necessary  to  proctue  food.  The  hydra  and  sea  anemone, 
for  example,  react  positively  to  food  only  if  the  metabolism  is  in  such  a 
state  as  to  require  more  material.  The  localization  of  hunger  in  the  higher 
animals  is  a  secondary  development,  and  merely  one  of  the  multiple  aspects 
of  the  part  functioning  vicariously  for  the  whole  which  characterizes  all  the 
physiological  mnemonic  processes.  It  is  the  same  with  thirst,  which  though 
localized  in  the  glands  of  the  throat,  is  a  need  of  the  entire  organism.  Simi- 
larly, the  need  of  elimination  of  substances  produced  by  general  metabol- 
ism, which  the  organism  is  not  able  to  utilize,  whether  in  the  simplest 
infusoria  or  the  most  complicated  vertebrate,  follows  the  same  general  rule. 
In  this  category  of  affective  eliminative  tendencies,  the  author  places  the 
sex  instinct.  To  this  fundamental  property  that  every  organism  possesses, 
i.  e.,  the  tendency  to  conserve  the  equilibrium  of  its  own  normal  physio- 
logical state  or  to  re-establish  it  if  it  has  been  disturbed,  must  be  added 
another  which  in  its  turn  becomes  the  source  of  new  affectivities.  When 
the  original  state  cannot  be  re-established  then  the  organism  tends  to  pass 
into  a  new  static  condition  adapted  to  the  new  external  or  internal  milieu. 
In  this  way,  the  whole  series  of  the  phenomena  of  adaptation  is  produced. 
The  experiments  of  Dallinger  and  others  on  the  acclimation  of  lower  organ- 
isms have  shown  conclusively  that  this  secondary  state  once  established 
tends  to  perpetuate  itself.  This  tendency  is  of  a  purely  mnemonic  nature 
and  implies  for  the  different  elementary  physiological  states,  forming 
altogether  the  general  physiological  state,  the  faculty  of  leaving  behind  a 
specific  accumulation  or  mnemonic  residue  susceptible  to  revival  or  recall. 
The  extension  of  this  faculty  of  specific  acamiulation  to  all  physiological 
phenomena  in  general  is  in  harmony  with  the  hypothesis  which  posits 
nervous  energy  as  the  basis  of  all  vital  phenomena. 

With  the  extension  of  this  mnemonic  faculty  to  all  the  elementary  physio- 
logical processes,  we  arrive  at  a  somatic  or  visceral  theory  of  fundamental 
affective  tendencies.  Naturally  in  organisms  endowed  with  a  nervous 
system  there  would  gradually  be  developed  along  with  the  affective  ten- 
dencies whose  origin  is  purely  somatic,  the  tendency,  sometimes  co-opera- 
tive and  sometimes  vicarious, '  'represented  by  the  corresponding  mnemonic 
accumulations,  deposited  in  liiat  special  zone  of  the  nervous  system  which  is 
directly  connected  with  respective  points  of  the  body."  In  man,  this  zone 
would  be  the  KdrperfUhlssphdre  of  Flechsig,  to  whidi  is  added  in  certain 
cases  the  frontal  zone.  These  mnemonic  cerebral  accumulations  once 
established  under  direct  somatic  action  are  able,  even  after  communication 
with  the  body  has  been  severed,  to  represent  the  original  affective  tendency 
in  which  they  originated,  e.  g.,  Sherrington's  "spinal"  dog  showed  the 
same  repugnance  to  dog  flesh  in  precisely  the  same  way  as  a  normal  dog. 
Finally  affective  tendencies  owe  their  subjectivity  to  their  mnemonic, 
physiological  origin,  from  the  fact  that  the  organism  finds  itself  endowed 
with  specific  affective  tendencies  in  accordance  with  the  particular  environ- 
mental history  of  the  species  or  individual.  In  support  of  the  foregoing 
hypothesis  thus  briefly  sketched,  the  author  cites  various  examples  from 
the  higher  animals  and  man,  e.  g.,  he  finds  the  origin  of  maternal  love  in 


BOOK  REVIEWS  313 

the  principle  of  elimination,  the  need  of  being  nursed.  Homesickness  is 
due  to  the  disturbance  of  fixed  paths  of  habituation.  As  a  further  confirma- 
tion of  the  hypothesis  of  the  mnemonic  nature  of  the  affective  tendencies 
Ribot's  principle  of  transfert  is  utilized. 

In  accordance  with  this  principle,  in  itself  of  mnemonic  origin,  all  affec- 
tivities  not  directly  traceable  to  a  mnemonic  source  are  derived  from  those 
which  are  thus  referable,  and  are  therefore  of  indirect  mnemonic  origin,  e.  g., 
secondary  sex  affectivities,  cruelty  as  an  end  in  itself,  derived  from  the 
original  tendency  of  tearing  prey  to  satisfy  hunger,  the  desire  of  victory 
for  itself,  originally  self  defence,  the  desire  of  amassing  wealth,  which  is  a 
transfer  from  the  original  simple  impulse  to  satify  hunger  plus  the  intellect- 
ual element  of  foreseeing  its  recurrence. 

Emotions  according  to  this  theory  '  'are  only  sudden  and  intensive  modes 
of  putting  in  action  those  accumulated  energies,  which  constitute  precisely 
the  affective  tendencies."  Emotions  and  affective  tendencies  are  distin- 
guished from  each  other  by  the  ?act  that  the  same  affective  tendency  may, 
under  different  circumstances,  give  rise  to  very  diverse  emotions;  to  emo- 
tions of  different  intensities  or  even,  in  some  cases,  to  no  emotion  at  all  in 
the  proper  sense  of  the  word,  e.  g.,  the  affective  tendency  of  a  dog  for  his 
piece  of  meat  may  be  translated,  according  to  circumstances,  into  flight, 
anger,  or  merely  a  search  for  a  quiet  place  in  which  to  enjoy  it.  As  all 
affective  tendencies  result  in  movement,  external  or  internal,  the  theory  is 
here  in  accord  with  that  of  Ribot  and  the  Lange- James  theory. 

The  will  is  only  an  affective  tendency  inhibiting  or  impelling  to  action 
like  every  other  affective  tendency.  As  to  pleasure  and  pain,  the  theory 
is  in  accord  with  that  which  interprets  pleasure  as  the  subjective  accompa- 
niment of  unimpeded  activity  and  pain  as  due  to  its  inhibition. 

Th^odate    L.  Smith 

A  Text  Book  of  Psychology.  E.  B.  TitchEner.  Macmillan  Company, 
New  York,  1910.  pp.  xx  +  565. 
Professor  Titchener  in  the  present  volume  has  given  us  more  than  a  text- 
book of  psychology.  The  book  comes  fairly  close  to  being  a  brief,  system- 
atic psychology  —  an  earnest,  certainly,  of  what  the  author  will  give  us 
when  his  more  complete  study  is  ready.  At  the  present  time,  in  English, 
we  have  at  our  disposal  many  elementary  texts  on  psychology,  and  many 
elementary  laboratory  manuals;  but  we  are  poverty-stricken  for  advanced 
works  in  general,  systematic  psychology  (based  step  by  step  on  experiment), 
and  for  advanced  experimental  manuals  on  the  various  sense-fields, — at- 
tention, association,  etc.  Titchener's  book,  while  supposed  to  be  for  elem- 
entary students,  is  far  from  being  an  easy  text.  Indeed,  the  author's  own 
way  of  thinking  has  become  so  much  more  complex  since  the  writing  of  the 
Outline  that  I  doubt  if  he  himself  clearly  realizes  just  how  much  of  his  more 
recondite  reflections  have  become  incorporated  in  the  book.  If  I  were 
seeking  a  quarrel  with  the  Text-book  I  should  find  the  grounds  for  it  on  the 
score  of  too  great  complexity.  It  is  a  little  heavy  for  the  average  junior  or 
senior.  But  psychological  classes  differ  greatly  in  the  different  institutions. 
In  some,  psychology  is  required;  in  others,  elective.  In  some  the  '  'quarter' 
system  is  in  vogue,  and  only  one  quarter  is  allotted  to  psychology;  in  others, 
psychology  runs  the  year  through.  It  is  doubtful  whether  Titchener's 
book  can  be  adapted  to  meet  the  requirements  of  a  short  course.  In  institu- 
tions where  the  elective  system  is  in  operation,  and  where  a  full  year  can  be 
given  to  psychology,  I  know  of  no  text  better  to  use  than  the  one  under  dis- 
cussion. In  view  of  the  fact  that  the  author  introduces  experiments  every- 
where and  that  he  discusses  methods  and  results  the  book  lends  itself 
easily  both  to  systematic  and  to  experimental  presentation.  Any  student 
going  carefully  over  the  work  with  a  competent  instructor  will  come  out  at 
the  end  of  the  year  with  an  increased  respect  for  psychology  and  with  the 

JouRNAi, — 12 


314  BOOK  REVIEWS 

ability  to  think  along  psychological  lines  and  to  read  and  follow  the  future 
progress  of  psychology  even  if  he  carries  his  training  no  further. 

In  a  book  which  is  so  full  of  factual  material,  we  cannot  hope  in  a  review 
to  discuss  chapter  and  verse  in  any  adequate  way.  Certain  interesting 
points  of  view  developed  by  the  author,  alone  can  be  discussed.  In  the  first 
place,  Titchener's  series  of  chapters  on  sensation  is  excellent — by  far  the 
best  treatment  we  have.  For,  in  addition  to  the  full  treatment  of  the  ordi- 
nary laws  and  principles  involved  in  sensation,  we  have  the  more  recondite 
phenomena  touched  upon.  Much  additional  material  over  that  treated 
in  the  Outline  appears.  For  example,  we  have  a  fuller  treatment  of  color- 
theories;  of  the  vestibular  and  ampullar  senses;  of  the  sensitivity  of  the 
abdominal  tissue;  of  sensations  arising  from  the  digestive  and  urinary 
systems;  and  from  the  circulatory  and  respiratory  system. 

In  discussing  the  attributes  of  sensation  in  general,  the  author  tells  us 
that  there  are  four  distinct  attributes;  quality,  intensity,  clearness  and 
duration.  The  reviewer  is  puzzled  by  the  attribute  clearness.  We  all 
admit  clearness  as  an  attribute  of  complex  conscious  experience,  but  not 
as  a  fundamental  aspect  of  the  sensation-process — not  in  the  sense  in  which 
duration  and  intensity  are  attributes.  He  says,  "Clearness,  again,  is  the 
attribute  which  gives  the  sensation  its  particular  place  in  consciousness; 
the  clearer  sensation  is  dominant,  independent,  outstanding ;  the  less  clear 
sensation  is  subordinate,  undistinguished  in  the  background  of  conscious- 
ness." This  is  certainly  to  be  admitted,  but  surely  what  Titchener  is  writ- 
ing of  here  is  an  attention-state,  in  which  a  given  "sensation"  is  focal, 
while  others  appear  in  what  James  calls  the  "fringe."  In  other  words, 
clearness  is  one  of  the  descriptive  words  which  we  apply  to  perceptual, 
ideational  and  other  complex  mental  states.  With  this  given  as  an  attri- 
bute of  sensation  one  would  expect  to  find  it  taken  account  of  somewhere 
along  with  the  other  attributes  of  sensation.  But  in  his  chapters  on  the 
special  senses  he  speaks  only  of  the  usual  attributes  of  each  group,  introdu- 
cing certain  changes  in  terminology,  to  be  sure,  as  for  example,  he  speaks 
now  of  the  qualitative  attributes  of  a  color  as  being  hue,  tint  and 
chroma.^  And  further,  in  audition,  he  speaks  of  size  and  diffusion  as  an 
attribute  of  tone.  It  would  seem  in  places  that  he  means  to  use  this  attri- 
bute of  clearness  in  the  same  sense  as  we  should  use  clearness  in  describing  a 
perceptual  state ;  but  this  would  carry  with  it  the  inference,  it  seems  to  me, 
that  sensation  is  something  more  than  an  abstraction — something  that  can 
actually  present  itself.  Futhermore,  in  order  to  reaHze  the  conditions  for 
the  appearance  of  clearness,  we  should  have  to  have  at  least  two  such  '  'sen- 
sation processes"  attempting  to  run  their  courses  simultaneoulsy.  But 
this  is  certainly  the  process  which  we  know  as  perception.  The  confusion, 
if  I  understand  Titchener's  statements,  is  similar  to  that  found  in 
James  where  sensation  is  at  times  discussed  as  an  abstraction  and  at 
others  as  a  process  corelative  with  perception. 

It  is  interesting  to  note  that  he  treats  of  the  sense-image  imder  the  general 
chapter  heading  of  synaesthesia;  since  the  image  is  the  normal  process,  and 
synaesthesia  the  anomalous  one,  we  should  suppose  that  the  traditional 
order  of  treatment  were  best.  One  would  hardly  begin  a  chapter  on 
color  vision  for  elementary  students  with  a  discussion  of  red-green  blindness. 
His  early  discussion  of  imagery  is  rather  disappointing.  Only  two  pages 
are  given  over  to  it.  One  finds  there  few  statements  concerning  the  ex- 
perimental mode  of  investigating  the  image,  and  very  little  of  individual 
differences.  This  lack  of  emphasis  of  the  image  in  an  early  place  would 
seem  to  be  a  real  limitation  in  the  use  of  the  book  as  a  text.  The  average 
undergraduate  rarely  wakes  up  to  real  introspective  interest  in  psycho- 
logical problems  until  he  has  learned  that  he  has  imagery  and  can  stand 

1  His  introduction  of  the  words  chroma  and  tint  are  of  doubtful  value,  since  the  word 
saturation,  now  in  common  use,  seems  adequate. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 


315 


off  and  look  at  it,  as  it  were,  in  the  absence  of  a  perceptual  world.  A  brief 
study  of  the  image  awakens  him  far  more  rapidly  than  does  a  much  longer 
drill  on  sensation-processes.  Later  on  in  the  book,  however,  the  author 
completes  the  treatment  of  imagery  under  the  headings,  association, 
memory  and  imagination.     Here  the  treatment  is  full  and  adequate. 

Following  the  chapter  on  synaesthesia  is  one  on  the  intensity  of  sensation, 
which  includes  a  discussion  of  mental  measurement,  liminal  and  terminal 
stimuli,  just  noticeable  differences,  and  Weber's  law.  The  chapter  is 
concise,  but  clear,  and  since  these  topics  are  valuable  to  the  student,  such 
a  chapter  is  a  real  contribution  on  the  pedagogical  side. 

Then  follows  the  chapter  on  affection.  He  stands  by  his  position  stated 
in  the  Outline.  "The  writer  holds  that  there  is  an  elementary  affective 
process;  a  feeling  element.  .  .  .'*-  "He  holds  further  that  there  are  only 
two  kinds  or  qualities  of  affection,  pleasantness  and  unpleasantness." 
Although  the  reviewer  thinks  he  finds  himself  in  another  'camp,*  it  gives 
him  a  sense  of  security  to  find  a  psychologist  of  Titchener's  eminence  who 
admits  his  position  so  frankly  on  such  a  vexed  question  as  that  of  affection. 
On  page  228,  in  a  discussion  of  the  relation  between  sensation  and  affection, 
he  again  enumerates  the  attributes  of  sensation — qimlity,  intensity,  clear- 
ness, duration.  Those  of  affection  on  the  other  hand,  are  quality,  intensity, 
duration.  On  page  231,  he  uses  clearness  as  the  distinguishing  criterion 
between  sensation  and  affection.  '  'Pleasantness  and  unpleasantness  may 
be  intensive  and  lasting,  but  they  are  never  clear."  This  is  due,  in  short, 
the  author  says,  to  our  inability  to  attend  to  an  affection.  '  'The  lack  of 
the  attribute  of  clearness  is  sufficient  in  itself  to  differentiate  affection 

from  sensation "     Again,  this  attribute  of  clearness  attaching  to 

sensation  and  not  to  affection,  and  further  the  fact  that  we  cannot  attend  to 
affection,  make  the  author  reject  the  view  that  affection  is  really  a  complex 
or  fusion  of  the  accompanying  organic  sensations.  While  there  is  no  time 
to  argue  the  question,  I  cannot  see  that  Titchener  makes  his  point  against 
this  latter  view.  If  we  should  grant  his  premises,  namely,  that  affection 
lacks  clearness,  and  that  it  cannot  be  attended  to,  we  should  be  forced  to 
admit  his  point.     But  these  are  just  the  questions  at  issue. 

He  discusses  two  methods  of  investigating  affection:  that  of  "paired 
comparison,"  and  the  method  of  "expression."  He  devotes  about  six 
pages  to  the  method  of  expression,  but  is  in  agreement  with  the  majority 
of  psychologists  in  denying  any  great  usefulness  to  it.  It  seems  like  a 
useless  luxiu-y  in  a  text-book  to  treat  so  at  length  of  a  method  which  has 
absolutely  nothing  to  recommend  it.  The  tridimensional  theory  of  feeling 
is  well  and  critically  diccussed. 

Space  does  not  permit  of  even  a  brief  review  of  further  chapters;  atten- 
tion, perception,  association,  memory  and  imagination,  action,  emotion, 
and  thought.  The  chapters  on  attention  and  on  thought  are  striking  and 
are  both  readable  and  teachable. 

In  the  chapter  on  action  it  is  with  a  shock  that  one  again  meets  with 
his  earlier  expressed  view  that  the  first  movements  of  organisms  were 
conscious  movements  (agreeing  thus  with  Wundt,  Ward  and  Cope).  Ac- 
cording to  this  view,  voluntary  action  degenerates  into  ideo-motor  or  sen- 
sory-rnotor  action,  and  then  into  the  reflex.  But  in  animal  life  we  find 
two  kinds  of  responses,  in  every  organism,  beginning  with  the  protozoa 
(as  shown  by  the  recent  work  of  Gibbs  and  Smith,  of  Bentley  and  others) : 
the  one  type  being  fixed  and  definite;  the  other  diffuse,  leading  itself  to 
habit-formation.  Certainly  I  should  agree  with  Titchener  that  conscious- 
ness is  as  old  as  life,  but  I  should  certainly  connect  consciousness  with 
the  diffuse  type  of  response.  I  should  say  further  that  the  very  first  organism 
started  with  both  types  of  response.  Surely  nothing  is  gained,  and  confu- 
sion is  introduced  by  the  conception  of  Titchener  that  all  movement  was 
first  a  voluntary  acquisition,  and  that  only  later  do  we  begin  to  find  fixity 


3l6  BOOK  REVmWS 

in  the  responses  of  organisms.  There  is  not  a  scintilla  of  evidence  thaXfixed 
and  automatic  reactions  do  not  appear  with  the  first  appearance  of  organ- 
isms. And  there  is  abundant  reason  to  say  that  each  new  species  as  it 
appears,  e.  g.,  by  mutation  (see  the  work  of  Tower  et  al.),  gives  evidence 
of  a  reflex  repertoire  and  of  a  plastic  repertoire.  Titchener  argues  that  the 
reason  we  do  not  see  this  complete  plasticity  (which  would  be  called  for 
on  his  theory)  in  the  unicellular  form  to-day,  is  that  the  protozoa  have 
travelled  all  the  way  from  plasticity  to  fixity. 

Looking  at  the  book  as  a  whole,  it  seems  to  the  reviewer  that  in  many 
places  Titchener  has  adhered  too  rigidly  to  the  introspective  method. 
Surely  in  his  treatment  of  meaning  he  could  have  leaned  advantageously  a 
little  way  toward  the  functional  side,  without  giving  up  the  guiding  princi- 
ples of  the  book.  Nevertheless  in  this  day  when,  if  I  can  read  the  signs 
aright,  the  pendulum  is  swinging  another  way — toward  a  study  of  life- 
situations  as  a  whole,  and  the  adequacy,  permanency  and  diff^erent  types 
of  adjustjtnent  which  such  situations  call  forth — Titchener  gives  us  an  envia- 
ble example  of  a  man  unafraid  of  his  own  views  of  the  problems  of  psy- 
chology, and  of  his  own  methods  of  solving  them.        John  B.  Watson 

The  Johns  Hopkins  University 

U  annde  psychologique,  publ.  par  A.  Binbt,  avec  la  collaboration de  LarguiER 
DBS  Bancels  et  Dr.  Th.  Simon,  etc.  Seiziteie  ann6e.  Paris,  Masson  et 
Cie.  1910,  pp.  IX,  500. 
The  introduction  reviews  the  progress  of  psychology  in  1909,  treating 
especially  the  work  on  thought  and  on  pathological  states,  and  the  work 
in  experimental  pedagogy  and  judicial  psychology.  The  first  original 
contribution,  by  A.  Binet,  is  entitled  "The  physical  signs  of  intelligence 
in  children."  Greater  or  less  degrees  of  correlation  are  found  between 
intelligence  and  size  of  head,  the  so-called  signs  of  degeneracy  (abnormally 
shaped  head,  ears,  etc.),  facial  expression,  and  hands.  The  habit  of  biting 
the  finger-nails  is  found  to  be  without  significance  in  this  respect.  The 
correlations  found  hold  in  general  only  for  the  group,  not  always  for  the 
individual.  The  physical  signs  are  useful  for  confirming,  rather  than  for 
making,  estimates  of  intellectual  level.  Next  in  order  is  an  examination 
of  the  art  of  Rembrandt,  by  A.  and  A.  Binet.  The  authors  attempt  to 
show  how,  by  avoiding  extremes  of  contrast  and  by  accentuating  unity  of 
lighting,  Rembrandt  has  succeeded  in  giving  those  impressions  of  distance, 
of  imity,  and  of  light  which  characterize  his  work.  "Tachistoscopic 
Researches,"  by  B.  Bourdon,  is  an  investigation  of  the  times  of  choice- 
reactions  made  by  observers  to  whom  colors,  rectangles  of  different  lengths 
and  figures,  have  been  tachistoscopically  exposed.  The  writer  measures 
the  time  of  reactions  involving  judgments  of  resemblance,  identification, 
localization,  comparison,  or  combinations  of  these  processes.  The  eight 
following  papers,  by  A.  Binet  and  Th.  Simon,  are  concerned  with  defining 
the  various  mental  derangements.  Up  to  the  present,  the  authors  believe, 
definitions  have  been  too  inclusive  and  general,  have  failed  to  show  the 
essential  characteristic  which  marks  off  the  disorder,  and  have  been  couched 
in  terms  only  partly  psychological.  They  themselves  classify  the  de- 
rangements as  (i)  hysteria,  (2)  derangement  with  knowledge  (fears,  im- 
pulsions, etc.),  (3)  manic-depressive  insanity,  (4)  systematized  insanity 
(paranoia),  (5)  the  dementias  (general  paresis,  senile  dementia,  dementia 
praecox),  and  (6)  subnormality.  They  consider  the  history  of  the  con- 
ceptions of  the  various  disorders,  the  theories  propounded  and  the  attempts 
at  definition.  They  also  review  the  characteristic  mental  states,  symptoms, 
and  attitudes  of  patients,  both  as  reported  by  others,  and  as  shown  by  the 
new  data  here  published.  They  compare  the  special  derangement  under 
consideration  with  the  other  types  of  derangement,  and  finally  arrive  at  a 
conclusion  as  to  its  essential  character.     Of  hysteria,  they  find  character- 


BOOK  Reviews 


317 


istic,  separation;  of  derangement  with  knowledge,  conflict;  of  manic- 
depressive  insanity,  domination;  of  paranoia,  deviation;  of  the  dementias, 
disorganization;  of  subnormality,  arrest  of  development.  The  psychologi- 
cal significance  of  these  terms  is  discussed  and  explained  at  length,  and  an 
attempt  is  made  to  bring  them  all  into  relation.  "Judicial  Diagnosis 
by  the  Association-method,"  by  A.  Binet,  argues  against  unlimited  con- 
fidence in  the  method  for  application  in  practice.  The  writer  reviews  the 
experiments  of  Henke  and  Eddy  and  of  Yerkes  and  Berry,  pointing  out 
chances  for  error,  and  showing  on  both  theoretical  and  practical  grounds 
that  the  method,  as  used  in  the  laboratory  or  classroom,  is  not  suited  to 
the  conditions  of  the  criminal  court.  The  psychological  literature  of  1909 
is  reviewed  by  Beaunis,  Binet,  Bovet,  Larguier  des  Bancels,  Maigre,  and 
Stem,  under  the  headings  of  physiological  psychology,  sensations  and 
movements,  perceptions  and  illusions,  associations,  attention,  memory 
and  images,  language,  feelings,  aesthetics,  thought,  suggestion,  individual 
psychology,  child  psychology  and  pedagogy,  animal  psychology,  judicial 
psychology,  pathology,  dreams,  treatises  and  methods,  and  philosophical 
questions.  W.  S.  Foster 

//  sentimento  giuridico.   Giorgio  dei*  Vecchio.     Seconda  Edizione.  Roma: 
Fratelli  Bocca,  1908.     pp.  26. 

Professor  del  Vecchio,  of  the  University  of  Sassari,  who  has  previously 
published  several  articles  on  kindred  topics, — Uetica  evoluzionista  (1903), 
Diritto  e  personalitd  umana  nella  storia  del  pensiero  (1904), — discusses  in  the 
present  monograph  the  "feeling  (or  sense)  of  justice"  in  man,  its  origin 
and  development.  From  the  time  of  Aristotle  down  this  '  'sense  of  justice' ' 
has  been  attributed  to  man,  but  the  philosophers  have  disputed  much  as 
to  its  primary  or  derived  character  (these  arguments  the  author  briefly 
summarizes).  According  to  Professor  del  Vecchio,  "the  origin  and  nature 
of  the  sense  of  justice  is  essentially  a  problem  of  the  metaphysical  order" 
(p.  12).  This,  however,  does  not  prejudice  in  any  way  the  analysis  of 
the  psychic  datum  and  its  proper  functions.  The  "sense  of  justice"  is 
thus  '  'primary  and  normal  datum  of  the  ethical  conscience,  an  element  or 
an  aspect  of  it;  and  its  nature  is  affective  and,  at  the  same  time,  ideological." 
A  fundamental  and  distinctive  characteristic  of  the  "sense  of  justice"  is 
its  independence  of  all  exterior  sanction, — that  is  just,  which  is  right  in- 
dependent of  all  positive  historical  sanction.  Thus  justice  and  law  differ. 
No  prescription  of  law  can  destroy  this  original  faculty  of  conscience  to 
oppose  itself,  as  supreme  principle,  to  the  authority  of  constituted  law 
(p.  23),  this,  Hobbes  to  the  contrary  notwithstanding.  The  philosophy 
of  law  is  rooted  in  the  "jtuidical  vocation  of  conscience."  The  "sense  of 
justice"  is  "the  anthropological  exigence  of  law,  its  primary  indication, 
and  the  psychic  expression  of  its  human  necessity." 

Alexander  F.  Chamberlain 
Sulla  Craniologia  degli  Herero.     Dorr.  Sergio  Sergi.  Roma,  1908.  pp.  lo. 
(Estr.  dal  Boll.  d.  R.  Accad.  Med.  di  Roma,  Anno  XXXIV,  Fasc.  I). 
Contrihuto  alio  Studio  del  Lobo  frontale  et  parietale  nelle  Razze  umane.     Os- 
servazioni  sul  Cervello  degli  Herero.     Pel  DoTT.  Sergio  Sergi.  Roma: 
Fratelli  Pallotta,  1908.    p.  107,  i  pi. 

In  the  first  of  these  studies  Professor  S.  Sergi  gives  the  results  of  his 
examination  (description,  measm-ements)  of  6  male  crania  of  the  Herero 
(a  Bantu  people  of  Damara  Land,  German  Southwest  Africa) ,  now  in  the 
collection  of  the  Anatomical  Institute,  Berlin.  The  skull-capacities  range 
from  1,315  to  1,590  ccm.  (4  are  1,500  or  over);  the  cephalic  indices  from 
67.5  to  72.9  (4  below  71).  The  Herero  have  a  skull-capacity  approaching 
that  of  the  Kaffirs  of  the  S.  E.  coast, — it  is  a  curious  fact  that  the  Bantu 
peoples  of  the  S.  W.  and  S.  E.  coasts  have  a  cranial  capacity  greater  than 
that  of  those  of  Central  Africa  and  the  region  of  the  upper  Congo.  The 
cephahc  index  of  the  Herero  ranks  them  among  the  more  dolichocephalic 


3l8  BOOK  REVIEWS 

Bantu.  Previous  to  this  paper,  but  two  Herero  skulls  have  been  studied 
(one  by  Fritsch  in  1872,  the  other  by  Virchow  in  1895). 

In  his  monograph  on  the  brain  of  the  Herero  Professor  Sergi  treats  in 
detail  of  14  young  adult  brains  (male  11,  female  3)  in  the  Anatomical  In- 
stitute of  the  University  of  Berlin,  with  special  reference  to  the  frontal  and 
parietal  lobes.  A  few  of  these  brains  had  been  previously  investigated 
in  a  general  way  by  Waldeyer  in  1906.  Anatomical  description  and  meas- 
urements are  exhaustive:  fissure  of  Sylvius,  fissiu-e  of  Rolando  and  the 
relative  development  of  the  frontal  lobe,  sulci  of  lateral  surface  of  the  front- 
al lobe,  sulci  of  the  orbital  surface,  fronto-parietal  median  sulci,  sulci  of 
the  cranial  surface  of  the  parietal  lobe,  etc.  Comparisons  are  made  with 
similar  data  for  other  races,  and  the  8  figures  in  the  accompanying  plate 
demonstrate  well  the  anatomical  facts,  by  reference  to  the  text-descriptions. 
The  weights  of  the  fresh  brains  range  from  1,146  to  1,470  gr.  (the  3  female 
are  all  below  1,200;  6  of  the  male  below  1,300  and  2  above  1,400), — the 
Herero  are  said  to  average  1,800  mm.  in  stature,  with  head  relatively  small 
as  compared  with  the  body.  Intellectually  the  Herero  are  inferior  to  the 
Hottentots,  whose  skeleton  and  musculatm-e  are  of  a  finer  structure  (their 
average  height  is  1,700  mm.).  Both  Herero  and  Hottentots  belong  to  the 
Bantu  division  of  the  Negro  Race.  Some  of  the  facts  brought  out  show 
how  dangerous  it  is  togeneralize,  e.  g.,  for '  'all  Negroes,"  as  Parkerdoes  with 
respect  to  the  direction  of  the  Silvan  fissiu-e.  In  the  method  of  termina- 
tion of  this  fissure  the  Herero  show  1 7  simple  and  1 1  bifurcate,  a  propor- 
tion close  to  that  of  the  Polish  brains  studied  by  Weinberg  (Javanese, 
Swedish,  Lett  and  Esthonian  brains  show  a  large  majority  the  other  way). 
The  development  of  the  upper  and  lower  frontal  lobe  is  more  variable  in 
males;  and  in  both  males  and  females  more  variable  on  the  right  than  on 
the  left.  The  absolute  development  of  all  the  frontal  lobe  is  greater  in 
males  than  in  females.  The  fissm-e  of  Rolando  is  more  irregular  on  the 
right  in  male  brains,  on  the  left  in  female.  In  male  brains  left  rami,  in 
female  right  rami  predominate.  As  has  been  shown  for  the  Hylobates,  the 
facts  indicate,  according  to  Professor  Sergi,  the  existence  in  the  human  frontal 
lobes  of  two  distinct  zones,  an  upper  and  a  lower,  which  follow  different 
laws  of  development.  Of  these  "the  upper  left  has  in  female  brains 
reached  its  proportional  development  with  respect  to  the  other  parts  of 
the  brain,  while  in  male  brains  has  still  a  considerable  evolution  to  undergo" 
(p.  40).  In  the  greater  frequency  of  the  separation  of  the  inferior  frontal 
sulcus  from  the  precentral  and  the  less  frequency  of  a  close  anastomosis 
between  them,  the  Herero  brains  differ  from  those  of  all  other  races  so  far 
examined.  In  the  Herero  the  upper  and  lower  frontal  sulcus  shows  more 
divisions  than  in  the  European.  With  respect  to  the  varieties  of  disposi- 
tion of  the  retrocentral  sulcus  the  Herero  brains  '  'reveal  neither  a  condition 
of  ontogenetric  arrest,  nor  a  phylogenetic  record"  (p.  83).  While  not 
venturing  to  draw  any  dogmatic  general  conclusion  from  the  facts  recorded, 
the  author  feels  authorized  to  make  this  statement  (p.  103):  "The  more 
rational  analytical  method  for  the  determination  of  the  variability  of  the 
cerebral  sulci  is  still  in  its  infancy  waiting  for  the  aid  of  microscopic  research; 
and  at  present  it  can  be  asserted  that  we  do  not  know  a  single  morpho- 
logical characteristic  of  the  cerebral  sidcatiu-e,  which  belongs  exclusively 
to  a  given  himian  race.  But  the  frequency  of  determinate  variations 
indicates  sometimes  the  tendency  toward  oscillations  and  divergences, 
which,  with  certain  limits,  seem  to  be  proper  to  a  given  human  group; 
but  more  noteworthy  still  is  the  tendency  toward  the  persistence  of  certain 
morphological  characteristics  of  the  cerebral  sulcature  in  relation  to  sex 
independently  of  all  ethnic  differences." 

A  complete  analytic  study  of  all  the  Herero  brains  here  considered  will 
be  found  in  Professor  Sergi's  more  extensive  monograph  Cerebra  Hererica 
to  appear  in  '  'Ergebnisse  einer  zoologischen  Forschungsreise  in  Siidafrika 
mit  Unterstiitzung  der  Kgl.  Preuss.  Akademie  der  Wissenschaften  zu 
Berlin  von  Dr.  Leonhard  Schultze."         Albxandbr  F.  Chamberlain 


BOOK  NOTES 


Das  Bewusstsein,  von  Johannes  Rehmke.  Heidelberg,  Carl  Winter,  1910. 
250  p. 

Philosophes  et  penseurs.  Buchez  {i^g6-i86s),  par  G.  Castella.  Paris, 
Bloud,  191 1.     64  p. 

Institut  de  Sociologie,  Bulletin  Mbnsuel.  No.  i,  Janvier,  19 10.  Instituts 
Solvay,  Pare  Leopold,  Bruxelles. 

Philosophes  et  penseurs.  Leonard  de  Vinci,  par  le  Barron  Carra  dE 
Vaux.     Paris,  Bloud,  19 10.     62  p. 

Kant  and  Spencer.  A  study  of  the  fallacies  of  agnosticism,  by  Paul  Carus. 
2d.  ed.     Chicago,  Open  Court  Pub.  Co.,  1904.     107  p. 

Kant's  Prolegomena  to  any  future  metaphysics,  edited  in  English  by  Paui. 
Carus.     Chicago,  Open  Court  Pub.     Co.,  1902.     301  p. 

The  fundamentals.  A  testimony  to  the  truth.  Vol.  4.  Compliments  of  two 
Christian  laymen.     Chicago,  Testimony  Publishing  Co.,  n.  d.  128  p. 

The  concept  of  method,  by  Gerhard  R.  LomER.  Published  by  Teachers 
College,  Columbia  University,  New  York  City,  1910.  99  p.  (Con- 
tributions to  Education,  No.  34.) 

Subconscious  Phenomena,  by  Hugo  MunsterbErg,  TheodulE  Ribot, 
Pierre  Janet,  Joseph  Jastrow,  Bernard  Hart  and  Morton  Prince. 
Richard  G.  Badger,  Boston.     1910.     141  p. 

On  the  genesis  and  development  of  conscious  attitudes  (Bewusstseinslagen), 
by  W11.LIAM  Frederick  Book.  Reprinted  from  the  Psychological 
Review,  November,  1910.     Vol.  XVII,  pp.  381-389. 

Transactions  of  the  Congress  of  American  Physicians  and  Surgeons.  Eighth 
Triennial  Session,  held  at  Washington,  D.  C,  May  3rd  and  4th, 
1910.     New  Haven,  Conn.,  published  by  the  Congress,  1910.     456  p. 

The  influence  of  complexity  and  dissimilarity  on  memory,  by  Harvey 
Andrew  Peterson,  Ph.D.  Dissertation,  University  of  Chicago; 
Monograph  Supplement,  No.  49,  of  the  Psychological  Review,  n.d. 
87  p. 

Im  Kampf  um  die  Tierseele,  von  J.  voN  UexkulIv.  Separat-Abdruck 
aus  Ergebnisse  der  Physiologic,  11.  abt.,  hrsg.  von  L-.  Asher  in 
Bern  und  K.  Spiro  in  Strassburg  I.  E.  Wiesbaden,  Bergmann, 
1902.     24  p. 

The  first  principles  of  heredity,  by  S.  Herbert.    London,  Adam  &  Charles 

Black,  1910.     199.  p. 
This  compend  on  heredity  has  sections  on  the  germ  cell,  theories,  inheri- 
tance of  acquired  characters,  of  diseases,  Mendehsm  and  biometrics,  with 
its  conclusions. 
Text-book  of  nervous  diseases  for  physicians  and  students,  by  H.  OppEnheim. 

Authorized  translation  by  Alexander  Bruce.  Edinburgh,  Otto  Schulze 

&  Co.,  1911.     2  V. 
This  is  the  fifth,  enlarged  and  improved  edition  with  432  illustrations 
in  the  text  and  8  plates. 


320  BOOK  NOTES 

Report  of  the  committee  of  the  American  Psychological  Association  on  the 
standardizing  of  procedure  in  experimental  tests.  Committee :  Charles 
Hubbard  Judd,  Walter  B.  Pillsbury,  Carl  E.  Seashore,  Robert 
S.  WooDWORTH,  James  R.  Angell,  Chairman.  Published  by  the 
Association.  The  Psychological  Monographs,  Dec,  1910.  Vol.  13, 
No.  I.     108  p. 

The  evolution  of  mind,  by  Joseph  McCabe.  London,  Adam  &  Charles 
Black,  1 910.  287  p. 
The  writer  discusses  the  lowest  and  earliest  forms  of  life,  appearance  of 
the  brain,  development  of  the  fish,  invasion  of  the  land,  insects  and  intelli- 
gence in  them,  mind  in  the  bird,  growth  of  the  mammal  brain,  law  of  hered- 
ity, and  advance  in  man. 

Die  innere  Werkstatt  des  Musikers,  von  Max  Graf.  Stuttgart,  Ferdinand 
Bnke,  1 910.  270  p. 
This  work  treats  of  the  unconscious,  how  it  has  affected  romantic  and 
classical  productions  in  the  field  of  art,  the  creative  mode,  artistic  concep- 
tion, outer  impulse  and  inspiration,  critical  work,  the  sketch,  technique, 
the  classical  and  the  great  style. 

Heredity  in  the  light  of  recent  research,  by  L.  Doncaster.  Cambridge, 
University  Press,  1910.  140  p. 
The  writer  considers  variation,  its  causes,  a  statistical  study  of  heredity, 
Mendelian  heredity,  disputed  questions,  heredity  in  man,  historical  smn- 
mary  of  theories,  the  material  basis  of  inheritance.  The  work  is  all  it  claims 
to  be,  a  simple  introduction  to  the  subject. 

Vom  Selbstgefiihl,  von  Else  Voigtlander.  Leipzig,  R.  Voigtlander,  1910. 
119  p. 
After  a  general  characterization  of  self -feeling,  the  author  gives  its  types, 
vital,  self-conscious,  etc.  Then  she  discusses  mirror-consciousness  and 
its  various  forms.  The  writer's  point  of  view  is  original  and  naive.  She 
goes  to  nature  rather  than  to  books  for  data. 

Das  vorgeschichtliche  Europa,  Kulturen  und  Volker,  von  Hans  HahnE. 

Monographien  zur  Weltgeschichte,  herausgegeben  von  Ed.  Heyck. 

Bielefeld,  Velhagen  und  Klasing.     1910.     130  p. 
This  is  a  very  interesting  and  comprehensive  compend,  with  illustra- 
tions on  nearly  every  page,  the  whole  designed  to  give  the  beginner  a  general 
survey  of  the  results,  up  to  date,  ©f  the  investigations  into  prehistoric 
times  in  Europe. 
A   study  of  association  in  insanity,  by  Grace  Helen  Kent  and  A  J. 

RosANOFF.     Reprinted    from  The  American  Journal    of    Insanity, 

1 910.     Vol.  LXVII,  Nos.  I  and  2,  142  p. 
This  work,  on  the  background  of  association  in  normal  subjects,  passes 
to  that  of  a  number  of  insane  people,  giving  stimulus  and  reaction-words, 
and  making  careful  generalizations  from  a  large  nimiber  of  cases,  and  finally 
analyzing  out  certain  symptoms. 
Hereditary  characters  and  their  modes  of  transmission,  by  Charles  Edward 

Walker.  London,  Edward  Arnold,  1910.  239  p. 
This  is  an  interesting  text-book  beginning  with  the  cell  and  passing  to 
instinct,  theories  of  evolution,  mutation  hypothesis,  continuity  between 
species,  protective  coloring,  law  of  frequency,  immunity  to  disease,  Galton's 
theories,  environment,  trypanosomes,  ants  and  bees,  Mendel's  experiments, 
breeding,  sex  determinants,  etc. 
Zeitschrift  fiir  Psychotherapie  und  medizinische  Psychologic,  von  Albert 

Moll.     Ferdinand  Enke,  Stuttgart,  1909.     i  Band,  384  p. 
In  this  first  volume  we  have  a  very  imposing  array  of  articles  by  eminent 
experts  making  original  contributions  to  the  subject.     The  references,  too. 


BOOK  NOTES 


321 


and  the  record  of  sittings,  with  a  miscellaneous  section,  make  a  good  and 
very  interesting  and  attractive  collection  of  view-points  in  a  subject  which 
at  present  is  rather  unusually  lacking  in  harmony. 

The  age  of  mammals  in   Europe,  Asia   and    North  America,  by  Henry 
Fairfield  Osborn.     N.  Y.,  Macmillan,  1910.     635  p. 

The  writer  has  here  brought  together  a  very  valuable  report  of  the  state 
of  the  topic  under  discussion,  together  with  his  own  investigations  which 
have  been  comprehensive.  He  divides  his  work  by  geological  periods, 
eocene,  oligocene,  miocene,  pliocene,  and  pleistocene,  discussing  under 
each  the  characteristics  forms  found  in  different  countries.  He  does  not 
enter  the  field  of  man. 

The  book  of  the  animal  kingdom;  Mammals.     By  W.  Percivai,  WestelI/. 
London,  Dent,  19 10.     379  p^. 

Perhaps  the  best  thing  about  tihds  book  is  its  many  and  excellent  illustra- 
tions from  life,  too  often,  alas!  life  in  captivity,  of  the  many  mammals 
described.  A  number  of  the  best  colored  cuts  are  reproductions  of  extinct 
forms  of  Hfe.  Special  attention  is  given,  too,  to  the  rarer  and  remoter 
forms.  The  work  is  rather  popular,  and  approximates  what  a  boy's  ani- 
mal book  ought  to  be. 

Individualism,  by  Warner  Fite.  New  York,  Longmans,  Green  &  Co., 
1911.  310  p. 
This  book  is  four  lectures  on  the  significance  of  consciousness  for  social 
relations,  given  in  1909  at  the  Summer  School  in  Chicago,  but  here  very 
greatly  developed.  The  author's  general  position  is  insistence  upon  indi- 
vidualism, versus  the  present  emphasis  laid  by  men  like  Dewey  and  Royce 
upon  social  relations.  Indeed,  the  book  is  in  part  a  friendly  criticism  of  the 
views  of  these  authors. 

L'dtat  mental  des  hysterigues,  par  PiERRE  JanET.     Paris,  Felix  Alcan,i9ii. 

Deuxieme  edition.     708  p.     (Travaux  du  laboratoire  de  Psychologic 

de  la  Clinique  k  la  Salp6tri^re — Cinquieme  serie.) 
This  is  simply  a  reprint  of  the  first  edition  of  the  first  volume  of  the 
author's  work  which  was  published  in  1893  and  1894  and  it  is  here  reprinted 
almost  exactly,  without  change,  because  the  author  found  that  he  must 
choose  between  this  method  and  that  of  radically  reconstructing  his  work, 
and  because  much  of  this  volmne  is  devoted  to  plain  descriptions  of  cases 
vaHd  under  any  theory. 

Moto-sensory  development:  Observations  on  the  first  three  years  of  a  child.     By 
George  V.  N.  Dearborn.     Baltimore,  Warwick  &  York,  Inc.,  1910. 
215  p.     (Educational  Psychology  Monographs.) 
This  is  a  study  of  the  author's  own  child  from  birth  up  to  the  152nd 
week.     The  frontispiece  is  the  baby  itself,  and  there  are  notes  on  observa- 
tion, which  constitute  the  bulk  of  the  book;  certain  inductive  considera- 
tions; a  chronological  epitome  of  observed  development  which  presents 
salient  facts  in  a  condensed  way;  and  lastly,  the  various  first  appearances 
are  alphabetically  arranged. 

Mentally  deficient  children,  their  treatment  and  training,  by  G.  E.  Shuttle- 
worth  and  W.  A.  PoTTs.  3d  ed.  Philadelphia,  Blakiston  1910.  236P. 
This  is  a  new  edition  of  an  almost  standard  work  and  contains  some  addi- 
tional material.  After  an  historical  retrospect  there  follows  a  characteri- 
zation of  feeble-minded,  degenerate  and  epileptic  children;  then  comes  a 
description  of  the  instruction  they  require,  pathological  classification, 
etiology,  diagnosis  and  prognosis,  mental  examination  of  children  requiring 
special  instruction,  treatment,  intellectual,  industrial  and  moral  training, 
recreation,  with  results  and  conclusions.  An  appendix  lists  institutions 
in  England  and  America,  gives  speaking  exercises,  and  a  bibUography  is 
appended. 


322  BOOK  NOT^S 

Modern  theories  of  criminality,  by  C.  Bbrnaldo  dE  Quir6s.    Tr.  from  the 

Spanish  by  Alfonso  de  Salvio.     Boston,  Little,  Brown,  and  Co.,  191 1. 

249  p. 

This  is  an  admirable  survey  and  begins  with  origins,  laying  special  stress 

upon  Lombroso,  Ferri  and  Garafalo.   Then  the  writer  discusses  theories  of 

anthropology,   degeneration,   pathology,    sociology,   parasitism,    criminal 

tendencies.     The  book  was  written  to  furnish  Spanish  scholars  and  jiuists 

with  a  general  survey  of  what  is  being  done  in  this  field.     This  commission 

which  has  been  given  the  author  has  been  admirably  executed  by  him. 

Questioned  documents.     A  study  of  questioned  documents  with  an  outline  of 
methods  by  which  the  facts  may  he  discovered  and  shown.   By  Albert  S. 
OsBORN.     Rochester,  N.  Y.,  The  Lawyers'  Co-operative  Pub.  Co., 
1910.     501  p. 
This  is  a  comprehensive  and  excellent  work  on  modes  of  testing  hand- 
writing and  other  topics  therewith  connected,  describing  how  questioned 
documents  of  various  classes  have  been  cared  for,  the  standard  of  compari- 
son,iphotography,  the  microscope,  alignment,  pen  position  and  pressure,  writ- 
ing instnunents,  variations  in  style,  forgeries,  disputed  letters,  ink,  paper, 
folds,  erasures,  age  of  dociunents.     The  work  contains  over  two  hundred 
illustrations  and  is  written  mainly  from  the  legal  point  of  view  without 
signs  of  much  acquaintance,  even  in  the  brief  bibliography  appended,  with 
the  recent  voluminous  studies  in  this  field. 

Introduction  to  philosophy,  by  William  Jerusalem.  Authorized  transla- 
tion from  the  4th  edition  by  Charles  F.  Saunders.  New  York,  Mac- 
millan,  1910.  319  p. 
This  translation  endeavors  to  help  all  who  have  a  real  interest  in  phi- 
losophy to  an  acquaintance  with  its  language  and  its  problems,  and 
thus  to  stimulate  independent  reflection.  The  author's  watchwords 
throughout  have  been  "objectivity,  perspicacity  and  brevity."  The 
Germans  have  shown  their  appreciation  by  the  fact  that  the  book  went 
through  four  editions  in  ten  years.  Its  second  aim  is  to  examine  the  prob- 
lems themselves  and  to  make  contributions  toward  their  solution.  The 
author's  philosophy  is  characterized  by  the  empirical  view-point,  the  genetic 
method,  and  the  biological  and  social  mode  of  interpreting  the  human  mind. 
He  first  treats  preparation,  principles,  then  criticises  knowledge  and  epistem- 
ology,  passes  then  to  metaphysics  and  ontology,  then  to  the  methods  of 
aesthetics,  and  finally  to  those  of  ethics  and  sociology. 

Studies  in  the  psychology  of  sex.  Erotic  symbolism;  the  mechanism  of  detumes- 
cence;  the  psychic  state  in  pregnancy.  By  Havelock  Ellis.  Phila- 
delphia, F.  A.  Davis  Co.,  1906.  285  p. 
In  this  book  the  phenomena  of  the  sexual  processes  are  discussed  before 
the  attempt  is  made  in  the  concluding  volume  to  consider  the  bearings  of 
the  psychology  of  sex  on  social  hygiene.  Under  erotic  symbolism  the 
author  includes  all  the  aberrations  of  the  sex  instinct  although  some  have 
been  deemed  important  enough  for  special  volumes.  Much  stress  is  laid 
upon  sexual  equivalents.  The  mechanism  of  detumescence  brings  us  to 
the  final  climax  for  which  the  earlier  and  more  prolonged  stage  of  tumes- 
cence is  an  elaborate  preliminary.  The  art  of  love  is  that  of  preparation. 
The  author,  too,  has  treated  at  some  length  the  psychic  state  of  pregnancy, 
where  the  whole  process  in  a  sense  reaches  its  goal.  Woman  in  this  state 
is  *  'the  everlasting  miracle  which  all  the  romance  of  love  and  all  the  cunning 
devices  of  tumescence  and  detumescence  have  been  invented  to  make 
more  manifest."  This  is  "the  supreme  position "  which  life  has  to  offer 
and  has  its  own  problems.     The  book  is  full  of  suggestiveness. 


BOOK  NOTES  323 

Die  Philosophie  der  Gegenwart;  eine  internationale  Jahresubersicht.     Heraus- 
gegeben  von  ArnoIvD  Ruge.     Band  i  (Doppelband),  Literatur  1908 
und  1909.    Heidelberg,  Weisssche  Universitatsbuchhandlung.     19 10. 
532  p. 
This  is  an  extremely  serviceable  book.     It  divides  philosophical  litera- 
ture into  12  departments,  viz.,  (i)  journals,  creative  works  and  diction- 
aries; (2)  texts,  translations  and  critical  works;  (3)  history  of  philoso- 
phy; (4)  general    philosophy;  (5)  logic    and   theory    of    knowledge;  (6) 
moral,  social  and  legal  philosophy;  (7)  philosophy  of  history,  language 
and   culture;    (8)    natural   philosophy;  (9)  philosophy   of   rehgion;  (10) 
art;  (11)  psychology;  (12)  more  poptdar  works,  aphorisms  and  essays. 
Two  reflections  are  suggested  here.     One  is  that  this  division  of  subjects  is 
far  too  elaborate.     In  looking  for  some  special  work  or  article,  the  writer 
of  this  notice  had  to  look  through  several  of  these  rubrics  before  finding 
what  he  wanted,  but  the  chief  criticism  of  the  arrangement  is  that  psychol- 
ogy is  given  so  small  a  place  and  that  so  many  works  one  would  naturally 
expect  to  find  under  this  caption  are  found  under  philosophy. 

The  Journal  of  Animal  Behavior.  New  York,  Henry  Holt  &  Company. 
Vol.  I,  No.  I,  January-February,  191 1, 
This  is  a  new  journal  in  a  new  topic.  The  editorial  board  is  composed 
of  Madison  Bentley,  of  Cornell  University,  Harvey  A.  Carr,  of  The  Univer- 
sity of  Chicago,  Samuel  J.  Holmes,  of  The  University  of  Wisconsin,  Herbert 
S.  Jennings,  of  The  Johns  Hopkins  University,  Edward  L.  Thorndike,  of 
Columbia  University,  Margaret  F.  Washbtun,  of  Vassar  College,  John  B. 
Watson,  of  The  Johns  Hopkins  University,  William  M.  Wheeler  and 
Robert  M,  Yerkes,  pf  Harvard  University.  It  is  published  by  Henry  Holt 
and  Company,  of  New  York,  and  the  first  number  contains  77  pages.  The 
first  article  is  an  experimental  study  of  the  turtle,  by  D.  B.  Casteel.  Then 
follow  articles  on  The  Reactions  of  Mosquitoes  to  Light  in  Different 
Periods  of  their  Life  History,  by  S.  J.  Holmes;  A  Study  of  Trial  and 
Error  Reactions  in  Mammals,  by  G.  V.  Hamilton;  A  Note  on  Learning 
in  Paramecium,  by  Lucy  M.  Day  and  Madison  Bentley;  and  a  note  by 
Robert  M.  Yerkes  on  Wheeler  on  Ants.  Save  the  last,  there  is  nothing 
approaching  a  book  review.  We  are  glad  to  know  that  the  Journal  is 
to  have  a  book-review  department. 

Spiritism  and  Insanity,  by  MarcEL  Vioi^ETT.  Swan,  Sonnenschein  and 
Co.,  1910.     pp.  134. 

In  the  presence  of  spiritistic  facts  men  react  diversely.  Sceptics  deny 
everything  en  bloc;  serious  savants  endeavor  to  apply  their  scientific  meth- 
ods, but  up  to  the  present  their  efforts  have  remained  barren;  the  rest  are 
essentially  believers.  An  imperious  need  inclines  them  to  accord  a  super- 
natural origin  to  what  they  cannot  understand  naturally.  Such  a  method 
is  risky,  but  where  is  the  science  which  risks  nothing? 

At  a  spiritistic  meeting  the  air  fairly  vibrates  with  mystery,  and  all 
believe;  but  when  they  leave  the  seance  most  become  preoccupied  with 
everyday  affairs,  and  the  belief  has  little  practical  importance.  Far 
otherwise  is  the  case  with  certain  ones  of  instable  mental  equilibrium. 
Here  we  find  those  of  congenitally  weak  intelligence,  for  whom  life  is  at 
best  difficult,  who  seek  consolation  in  spiritism,  and  find  there  only  new 
tortures.  Here,  too,  are  the  paranoiac  temperaments,  those  suspicious  of 
others,  inclined  to  beliefs  in  persecution,  whose  weariness  of  life  leads  them 
to  spiritism.  Here  are  the  self  distrustful  and  melancholiac,  and  especially 
the  hysterical  and  neuropathic,  who  tend  to  become  subjects-  Here  some 
bring  actual  insanity,  senile  decay,  minds  weakened  by  excesses,  all  of 
which  give  the  best  of  soils  for  spiritism  to  grow  in. 


324  BOOK  NOT^S 

For  the  very  core  of  spiritism  is  the  mystery  of  its  facts;  not  what  the 
facts  are,  but  that  they  seem  to  be  without  natural  cause.  But  this  is 
closely  analogous  to  hallucination.  Both  appear  abruptly,  without  transi- 
tion, without  progression,  preparation  or  natural  explanation,  and  as  the 
hallucination  tends  to  produce  automatism  in  its  subject,  so  does  the  spirit- 
istic phenomenon  produce  it  in  the  sitters,  already  predisposed,  selected 
in  many  cases  as  we  have  seen,  from  the  instable. 

To  the  spiritist,  evoking  a  spirit  means  to  bring  back  the  perispirit,  which 
is  the  mean  between  body  and  soul  and  the  Intermediary  between  us  and 
the  invisible  volitions  about  us.  Th  eidea  of  this  constant  entourage, 
the  uncertainty  as  to  the  power  of  these  spirits,  of  their  intentions  towards 
us,  of  our  possible  displeasing  of  them,  of  otu-  weakness  and  defenselessness 
against  them — all  this  is  hypothesis,  but  hypothesis  which  offers  no  barriers, 
which  can  never  be  refuted,  and  which  opens  to  infinite  other  hypotheses 
the  more  it  is  considered.  Its  guarantees  are  the  senses  of  the  spectators 
and  their  unanimous  consent  to  the  dogma  and  doctrines.  But  it  may  be 
compared  to  deliriiun  in  these  respects:  it  originates,  like  delirimn,  in  a 
miraculous  fact,  and  the  consequences  drawn  from  this  fact  are  purely 
hypothetical.  Whether  it  be  actual  delirium  or  not,  it  constitutes  a  vast 
culture  infusion  for  all  errors,  disequilibrations  and  madness. 

So  we  get  two  classes  of  spiritistic  insanities:  i,  those  evolving  among 
the  predisposed  whose  attack  is  referable  to  spiritistic  preoccupations; 
and,  2,  those  who  would  have  gone  insane  in  any  case,  but  to  whom  spirit- 
ism has  given  its  own  coloring. 

Under  the  first  come  those  exterior  mediunmopaths,  who  are  tormented 
by  wicked  spirits  outside  themselves;  interior  mediumnopaths,  when  the 
demon  has  taken  possession.  This  possession  may  vary  greatly  in  degree, 
the  torments  of  the  victim  increasing  imtil  complete  possession  is  attained, 
when  depersonalization  is  complete,  the  delirium  of  greatness  sets  in,  and 
the  case  passes  into  mediumnomania.  The  patient  now  considers  himself 
a  medium  and  is  glad  to  be  one,  the  spirit  praises  him,  he  has  dreams  of  estab- 
lishing a  new  religion,  etc.  All  sorts  of  hallucinations  may  develop,  and  in 
the  extreme  stages  the  person  loses  all  memory  of  his  former  self,  perhaps 
even  the  notion  of  the  existence  of  his  body,  becomes  immovable  and  silent, 
but  shows  by  the  happy  and  calm  expression,  the  ecstasy  at  which  we  can 
only  guess.     But  some  always  remain  melancholic. 

In  all  these  cases  there  are  hallucinations,  but  in  others  there  are  none. 
Such  cases  rest  their  beliefs  on  illusions  and  delirious  interpretations,  espe- 
cially the  latter,  and  will  evolve,  according  to  temperament,  towards  melan- 
cholia, the  delirium  of  persecution  or  of  greatness.  The  last  two  are  usually 
combined,  the  intelligence  is  intact  on  other  points,  and  so  the  patient 
systematizes  his  delusion  with  much  subtlety.  His  delusion  becomes  his 
curse,  he  is  the  persecuted  victim,  and  he  must  defend  himself  by  all  means, 
often,  in  the  end,  by  physical  violence  or  even  murder. 

Spiritism  may  give  a  coloring  to  dementia  praecox  in  its  various  forms, 
to  general  paralysis,  to  senile  dementia,  but  these  diseases  would  have 
evolved  in  any  case. 

In  view  of  these  facts  a  word  of  warning  should  be  spoken,  especially 
to  the  spiritists  themselves:  Sift  your  seances.  Keep  out  the  degenerate 
and  unbalanced,  and  thus  spare  them  possible  madness  and  spiritism  the 
discredit,  danger,  and  fraud  involved  in  having  them  for  supporters. 


^i^i. 


THE    AMEEIOAN 

Journal  of  Psychology 

Founded  by  G.  Stani^Ey  Hai^i,  in  1887 
Vol..  XXII  JULY,  1911  No.  3 

THERMAL  INTENSITY  AND  THE  AREA 
OF  STIMULUS' 


By  Sarah  E.  Barnholt  and  Madison  Bentl^y 


At  present  the  formulation  of  a  general  rule  expressing  the 
relation  of  sensational  intensity  to  the  area  of  stimulus  seems 
to  be  impracticable.  The  obvious  reason  is  the  lack  of  uni- 
formity in  the  facts;  and  this  lack  appears  to  arise  from  the 
diversity  of  organic  conditions  within  the  several  senses.  The 
spread  or  multiplication  of  a  tactual  stimulus  upon  the  skin  is 
different  from  the  areal  increase  of  light  upon  the  retina,  and 
both  offer  a  mode  of  attack  upon  the  organism  which  is  again 
unlike  that  sustained  under  the  numerical  increase  of  tones  or 
noises.  The  problem  itself  may  indeed  be  given  a  single  for- 
mulation, namely:  does  an  areal  or  numerical  increase  of 
stimulus  produce  an  intensive  increment  in  sensation?  But 
the  solution  must  be  sought  separately  in  the  individual  de- 
partments of  sense.  And  first  of  all,  we  must  distinguish 
between  those  cases  where  the  increase  of  stimulus  leads  to 
qualitative  increase  in  sensation  (e.  g.,  the  musical  chord) 
and  those  where  it  produces  a  like  quality  of  different  locality 
or  different  extent  (e.  g.,  the  spread  of  a  tactual  or  gustatory 
stimulus).  The  problem  under  consideration  falls  within  the 
second  group  of  cases. 

Stumpf2  found  occasion  to  discuss  the  matter  in  his  analysis 
of  tonal  fusion.  He  divides  the  question  into  two  parts,  which 
he  states  as  follows :  first,  *is  the  intensity  of  a  tone  affected  by 
the  presence  in  consciousness  of  other  tones?'  and  secondly, 
'is  a  tonal  complex  stronger  than  each  of  its  constituent  tones?* 

^From  the  psychological  laboratory  of  Cornell  University. 
'Tonpsychologie,  ii,  1890,  416  fF. 


326  BARNHOLT   AND   BKNTI.EY 

In  answer  to  the  first  question,  Stumpf  asserts  that  the  individ- 
ual tone  is  diminished,  not  augmented,  by  the  presence  of  other 
tones ;  and  that  the  decrease  in  intensity  is  a  true  weakening, 
not  a  phenomenon  of  attention.  Heymans  has  since  main- 
tained that  intensive  'inhibition'  is  general  among  sensory 
processes.^  In  answer  to  the  second  question,  Stumpf  denies 
the  intensive  summation  of  different  tones.  Two  tones  of 
like  strength  may  be  fuller,  richer,  or  more  'voluminous'  than 
one,  but  not  stronger. 

In  vision,  the  matter  is  more  complicated.  Here  one  must 
inquire  (a)  whether  binocular  intensity  is  greater  or  less  than 
monocular;  (b)  whether  two  disparate  retinal  areas,  either  of 
the  same  or  of  different  eyes,  produce  an  interactive  effect 
upon  intensity;  and  finally,  (c)  whether  the  enlargement  of  a 
single  stimulus-area  affects  the  strength  of  the  resultant  sen- 
sation. The  facts  are  further  complicated  for  vision  by  the 
peculiar  relations  of  intensive  to  qualitative  change.  The 
dependence  of  visual  sensation  upon  area  appears  in  such 
problems  as  the  spatial  limen  for  colors  and  the  sensitivity  of 
peripheral  vision,  and  in  the  facts  of  contrast  and  induction. 

The  intensity  of  pressure  is  obviously  dependent  upon  the 
size  of  stimulus.  But  the  mechanics  of  deformation  plays  an 
important  part  in  determining  the  excitation  of  the  tactual 
organs.^  Von  Frey  found  that  the  stimulus  limen  for  mod- 
erate areas  is  approximately  proportional  to  the  surface 
affected  and  he  lays  it  down  that  the  neural  excitation  is  a 
function  of  hydrostatic  pressure.  Bruckner,  who  stimulated 
neighboring  pressure-organs  with  the  blunt  end  of  a  fine 
needle,  found  evidences  of  physiological  (central)  summation 
under  simultaneous  stimulation,  even  where  the  two  points 
were  discriminated.^ 

As  regards  temperature,  the  traditional  view  correlates  the 
size  of  a  heated  or  cooled  area  upon  the  skin  with  the  intensity 
of  the  resulting  warmth  or  cold  sensation.  This  view  is 
frequently  supported  by  the  observation  that  the  finger 
plunged  into  warm  or  cold  water  gives  a  weaker  sensation 
than  the  immersion  of  the  whole  hand  or  the  entire  body.^ 
The  experience  itself  is  undeniable.  But  whether  the  obser- 
vation may  safely  be  interpreted  to  mean  that  the  higher 

^G.  Heymans:  Untersuch.  ueber  psychische  Hemmung,  Zeitschr.f.  Psych, 
u.  Physiol,  d.  Sinnesorgane,  XXI,  32 1 ;  XXVI.  305 ;  XXXIV.  15 ;  XLI.  28,  89. 

^V.  Frey,  M.:  Untersuch.  u.  d.  Sinnes function,  der  menschlicJien  Haut, 
1896. 

'A.  Bruckner:  Die  Raumschwelle  bei  Simultanreizung,  Zeitschr.  f. 
Psych,  u.  Physiol,  d.  Sinnesorgane,  XXVI,  1901,  33. 

^E.  g.,  E.  H.  Weber  in  Wagner's  Handwdrterbuch  der  Physiol.,  iii,  2,  553. 
Weber  explains  in  terms  of  cerebral  summation.  Cf.  Stumpf,  Tonpsych., 
ii,   1890.  445. 


THERMAL   INTENSITY  327 

intensity  rests  directly  upon  the  exposure  of  a  larger  area  is 
doubtful.  It  may  rest  upon  (i)  adaptation,  (2)  an  augmenta- 
tion of  sensory  feeling,  (3)  the  presence  or  absence  of  such 
organic  accompaniments  as  shiver,  goose-flesh,  or  visceral 
displacement,  (4)  the  addition  of  highly  tuned  temperature- 
organs,  (5)  the  confusion  of  extent  with  intensity,  (6)  the 
confusion  of  pressure  with  temperature,  or  finally  (7)  the  dif- 
ference in  cutaneous  conduction  over  large  and  small  extents. 
The  four  methods  used  in  our  experiments  were  designed 
to  test  these  various  possibilities. 

Method  I.    Immersion 

The  observer's  eight  fingers  were  ringed  with  indelible  ink 
}4.  iiich  and  2  inches  from  the  tips.  The  forearm  was  sup- 
ported, and  the  hand  was  allowed  to  hang  down  in  a  natural 
position.  Water  was  kept  at  a  constant  temperature  (45°  C.)  in 
a  small  vessel,  and  the  vessel  was  raised  by  the  experimenter 
until  the  water  reached  either  the  first  or  the  second  ring  upon 
a  single  finger.  The  observer  was  not  required  to  move  his 
hand  or  fingers.  Immersion  lasted  one  second.  After  it, 
the  finger  was  dried  gently  and  without  friction,  by  applying 
an  absorbent  cloth.  Then  the  same  or  another  finger  was 
immersed  in  the  same  way  up  to  the  second  or  first  ring.  The 
usual  precautions  against  the  constant  errors  of  space  and 
time  were  taken.  The  observer  was  asked  to  report  which 
sensation  was  the  stronger.  Preliminary  trials  were  made  in 
which  the  danger  of  confusing  extent  and  intensity  was  im- 
pressed upon  him.  In  all  but  two  out  of  forty-eight  experi- 
ments, the  two  trained  observers  (H.  and  S.)  reported  an 
intenser  warmth  from  immersion  of  the  larger  surface.  This 
result  confirms  common  observation;  while,  at  the  same 
time,  the  method  makes  it  clear  that  the  judgment  of  difference 
rests  neither  upon  the  repeated  use  of  a  common  part-area 
(adaptation)  nor  upon  the  temporal  order  of  comparison. 
Furthermore,  the  introspections  indicate  that  the  judgments 
were  true  comparisons  of  intensity,  not  of  area.  It  is  possible, 
however,  that  the  finger-tips  are  uniformly  less  sensitive  to 
warmth  than  the  rest  of  the  hand,  and  that  the  results  reached 
under  Method  I.  are  to  be  referred  to  this  difference.  To 
eliminate  this  possibility,  and  also  the  strong  suggestion  of 
degree  that  arises  from  gradual  immersion,  a  new  method  was 
devised. 

Method  II.    Circular  Areas 

An  area  3.5  x  4.0  cm.  was  laid  off  on  the  palm  of  the  hand 
or  on  the  volar  forearm  and  stimulated,  under  the  procedure 
of  paired  comparisons,  by  a  graded  series  of  five  brass  cylinders, 
all  of  the  same  weight,  and  of  diameters  which  ranged  from 


328  BARNHOIvT   AND   BENTI^^Y 

1.4  cm.  to  3.3  cm.  The  cylinders  stood  at  5°  C.  (cold 
stimulus).  Their  flat  circular  ends  were  set  down  at  all  parts 
of  the  chosen  rectangular  area  mapped  upon  the  skin,  so  that 
the  same  temperature  organs  should  be  brought  into  function, 
in  the  course  of  the  experiments,  by  both  large  and  small 
cylinders.  Altogether,  24  series  of  10  comparisons  each  were 
made  with  three  observers  (H.,  S.,  and  F.).  Of  the  240  com- 
parisons, 170  (70%)  gave  an  intenser  cold  with  the  larger  areal 
stimulus  (72%,  72%,  and  67%,  by  observers). 

The  methods  of  immersion  and  circular  areas  have  reduced 
our  list  of  possibilities  as  follows,  (i)  Adaptation  is  elimina- 
ted by  the  successive  stimulation  of  different  areas,  (2)  af- 
fective indifference  is  secured  by  the  use  of  small  areas  and  of 
moderate  intensities  of  stimulus,  (3)  organic  complexes  are 
avoided  by  the  same  means,  (4)  inequalities  of  "tuning"  are 
partially  compensated  by  the  distribution  of  stimuli  over  a 
common  field  of  exploration  (method  of  circular  areas),  and 
(5)  and(6)  the  confusion  of  thermal  intensity  with  extent  and 
with  pressure  is  avoided  by  practice-series  carried  out  under 
definite  instructions. 

The  fourth  possibility  is  only  partially  provided  against; 
for  the  chances  that  a  large  stimulus  will  strike  a  highly  tuned 
region  exceed  the  chances  for  a  small  stimulus.  And  the 
greater  physiological  efficacy  of  a  large  stimulus  through  con- 
duction (7)  may  account  for  the  greater  intensity  of  the  large 
sensation.     Let  us  first  consider  the  fourth  possibility. 

Method  III.  Weak  and  Strong  Areas 
The  direct  comparison  of  areas  of  high  and  low  sensitivity 
seemed  to  us  the  simplest  way  of  arriving  at  the  value  of 
tuning  in  areal  stimulation.  So  we  selected  a  region  upon  the 
upper  arm  which  gave,  under  the  cylinders,  a  bright  lively 
cold  and  an  intensive  warmth,  and  we  then  instituted  a  one- 
to-one  comparison  between  it  and  a  dull  region  on  the  ulnar 
side  of  the  palm.  Forearm  and  forehead  were  similarly  com- 
pared. The  smallest  of  the  five  cylinders  was  used  upon  the 
place  of  high  sensitivity, — designated  Ii  (cylinder- 1  on  in- 
tensive area), — and  all  the  cylinders  were  compared  with  it, 
in  haphazard  order,  upon  the  weak  area  (designated  Wi, 
W2,   .    .    .   W5). 

The  number  of  intensive  judgments  in  which  the  small- 
strong  area  was  sensed  as  colder  (or  warmer)  than  any  one  of 
the  large-weak  areas  is  set  down  in  Table  I.  The  initials  of  the 
Obs.  are  written  at  the  top.  Each  place  in  the  columns  rep- 
resents a  total  of  six  judgments.  Thus  Ii  was  pronounced 
"warmer"  than  Wi  (the  same  stimulus  set  on  a  weak- warm 
area)  47  times  out  of  a  total  of6x9  =  54;Ii  "colder"  than  Wi 


THERMAIv  INTENSITY 
TABI.B  I 


329 


WARM 

H 

s 

F 

Total 

COLD 

H 

S 

] 

P 

Total 

Ii>  Wi 

4 

6 

6 

4 

3 

6 

6 

6 

6 

47 

Ii>  Wi 

6 

6 

4 

6 

6 

6 

5 

5 

44 

Ii>  W2 

4 

6 

3 

2 

3 

5 

5 

3 

6 

37 

Ii>  W2 

6 

6 

I 

3 

5 

3 

3 

4 

31 

Ii>  W3 

4 

2 

2 

I 

2 

4 

5 

3 

3 

26 

Ii>  W3 

2 

5 

0 

2 

3 

5 

2 

2 

21 

Ii>  W4 

^ 

3 

2 

0 

0 

4 

4 

4 

2 

22 

Ii>  W4 

3 

2 

3 

0 

3 

4 

2 

4 

21 

Ii>  Ws 

2 

I 

2 

0 

0 

2 

4 

2 

2 

15 

Ii>  Ws 

I 

2 

3 

I 

I 

2 

2 

2 

14 

(weak-cold  area)  44  times  out  of  a  total  of  6  x  8  =  48.  But 
Ii>  Ws  =  |f  (warm)  and  J|  (cold).  Although  equality-judg- 
ments were  discouraged  by  the  instructions  and  therefore 
appeared  but  rarely,  it  will  be  seen  from  the  Table  that  sub- 
jective equality  lies  just  above  W3;  |f  and  H;  i.  e.,  the  thermal 
intensity  from  a  cylinder  1.4  cm.  diameter  set  in  one  certain 
region  of  high  sensitivity  is  approximately  equal  to  the  thermal 
intensity  from  a  cylinder  of  2  cm.  diameter  applied  to  a  certain 
other  region  of  low  sensitivity. 

Thus  the  fourth  item  in  our  Hst  of  possibilities  is  accounted 
for  by  the  discovery  that  a  large  area  of  low  tuning  can  actu- 
ally be  made  equal  for  sensation  to  a  small  area  of  higher  sen- 
sitivity. 

The  seve]p.th  item  is  left.  Size  of  stimulus  seems  clearly  to 
be  translatable  into  intensity  of  sensation.  It  remains,  how- 
ever, to  be  seen  whether  the  translation  is  due  to  a  process  of 
summation  or  to  the  different  conduction  through  the  skin  of 
large  and  small  stimuli.  The  obvious  recourse  is  to  the  in- 
dividual sense-organ  for  cold  and  warmth. 


Method  IV.  Temperature  Spots 

Three  separate  organs  for  cold  were  found  within  the  radius 
of  a  few  millimeters  upon  the  volar  forearm.  A  like  group  of 
warm-organs  was  also  identified  and  mapped  in  the  same 
general  region.  The  organs  in  the  cold  group  were  designated 
as  a,  b,  and  c,  those  in  the  warm  group  as  a',  b',  and  c'.  They 
were  explored  with  blunt  pointed  temperature-cyHnders  held 
at  approximately  a  constant  temperature  (water  at  5°  and 
45°  C) .  Again,  we  proceeded  with  paired  comparisons,  taking 
one  organ  with  one,  and  one  with  two.  Thus  the  intensity 
of  each  sensation  was  compared  with  that  from  the  other  two 
organs,  taken  singly  and  also  together.  The  simultaneous 
stimulation  of  two  spots  was  effected  by  the  use  of  a  double  v. 
Frey  stimulator,  in  which  the  bristles  were  replaced  by  smooth 
blunt  copper  wires  of  i-mm.  diameter.  Adaptation  was 
avoided  by  taking  each  organ  only  once  in  any  comparison; 


I 


330 


BARNHOLT   AND   BENTLEY 


thus  a  was  compared  with  h  and  c,  never  directly  with  a  or  ah 
or  ac. 

The  following  Table  (II)  gives  the  results  of  515  experi- 
ments from  three  observers  (initials  at  the  left) for  cold  and 
warmth.     The  columns  show  the  number  of  times  each  of  the 


Table  II 


COLD 

WARM 

a>,. 

a>,c 

.>,c 

Totals 

a'>.b' 

.•><•■ 

.><e. 

Totals 

H 

S 
F 

20    1    10 

20  1    12 

15  1     9 

25 
28 

21 

5 
4 
2 

23 

21 
15 

6 
II 

8 

89 
96 
70 

— 

15       8 
12       4 

9l    7 

22  1    2 
13  1     2 
15  1     I 

14       9 
10      6 

13       3 

70 

47 
48 

~~"~ 

55  1  31 

74  1  II 

59  1  25 

255 

36  1  19 

50  1    5 

37  1  18 

165 

420 

% 

64I36 

87  1  13 

70  1  30 

%. 

65I35 

91  1     9 

67  1  33 

ac>^b 

a  >  >bc 

ab>  .  c 

aV>^  b' 

a'^^bV 

a'b'>^' 

H 
S 
F 

4 
3 
3 

2 
3 
3 

3 
3 
4 

3 
3 
2 

5 
5 
4 

I 
I 
2 

18 
18 
18 

4 
4 
2 

I 
0 

2 

2 

2 
3 

4 

2 
I 

4 
4 
4 

2 
0 
0 

17 

12 
12 

■~^~ 

10  1    8 

10  1    8 

14  1    4 

54 

% 

10  1    3 

7l     7 

12  1    2 

41 

95 

% 

56I44 

56I44 

78I22 

309 

77  1  23 

50  1  50 

86  1  14 

206 

515 

three  temperature  organs  in  the  group  returned  the  intenser 
sensation.  Thus  in  thirty  a-h  comparisons,  H.  judged  a  colder 
twenty  times,  h  colder  ten  times.  In  twenty-three  a'-b'  com- 
parisons, H.  judged  a'  warmer  fifteen  times,  h'  warmer  eight 
times.  Totals,  recorded  both  in  numbers  and  in  percentages 
for  each  comparison,  are  added  at  the  bottom.  The  last 
half  of  the  Table  gives  the  results  for  the  one-to-two  compari- 
sons. Thus  H.  judged  ac  taken  together  colder  than  b  four 
times  out  of  six,  and  a'  c'  warmer  than  b'  four  times  out  of  five. 
The  relative  tuning  of  the  sense-organs  is  indicated  by 
the  following  results;  a  was  pronounced  colder  than  h  ox  c 
(taken  singly)  in  75.5%  of  the  comparisons  made,  and  a' 
warmer  than  b'  or  c'  in  78%.  The  corresponding  numbers 
for  the  other  spots  stand;  6  =  53%,  6' =  51%,  c  =  21.5%, 
c'=:2i%.  Thus  it  becomes  evident  that  the  differences  in 
tuning  are  considerable.  The  following  order  of  sensory 
intensity  may  therefore  be  set  down ;  a  (or  a')  >  h  (or  h')  >  c 
(or  d). 


THERMAL   INTENSITY 


331 


Now  we  are  in  a  position  to  discover  whether  reenforce- 
ment  of  one  sense-organ  by  another  occurs.  If  it  does  occur, 
we  might  expect  to  find  ac^  a  when  both  are  compared  with 
b,  bey  b  when  compared  with  a,  etc.  The  one-to-one  and  the 
one-to-two  comparisons  are  brought  together  in  Table  III. 


Tabls  III 


COLD 

%DIFF. 

WARM 

%DIFF. 

A    >     A    (b) 
A    >     A    cc) 
B    (c)     >      B 

9 
8 
8 

A'  >    A'  (b') 
A'  (c')    >    A' 
B'  (c')    >    B' 

5 
12 

15 

(A)  b   >      b 

(B)  c    >     c 
(A)     c    >      c 

8 
26 

(A')    b'>    b' 
(B')   c'   >    c' 
(A')   c'   >     c' 

19 
44 

The  upper  half  of  the  Table  shows  the  result  of  adding  a 
second,  weaker  sense-organ  to  a  first,  stronger;  the  lower  half, 
the  result  of  adding  a  second  stronger  organ  to  a  weaker  first. 
For  the  sake  of  clearness,  the  stronger  component  is  indicated 
by  a  capital  letter,  and  the  third  letter  added — in  the  one- 
to-two  comparisons — is  enclosed  in  parentheses. 

It  will  be  seen  (upper  half)  that  bovc  (weak  spots)  added  to 
A,  or  c  added  to  B,  decreases  as  often  as  it  increases  (3  to  3) 
the  relative  intensity  of  the  cold  or  warmth;  but  that,  on  the 
other  hand,  the  addition  of  a  more  highly  tuned  organ  (lower 
half)  to  6  or  c  invariably  raises  the  intensity  of  the  sensation. 
We  are  led  to  infer,  therefore,  that  under  the  given  conditions 
no  sensible  process  of  summation  takes  place ;  that  the  inten- 
sity of  the  temperature  sensation  is  determined,  instead,  by  the 
most  highly  responsive  component  in  the  excitation.  This  law 
may  not  obtain,  of  course,  where  two  or  more  thermal  areas 
are  separately  localized.  Even  within  the  narrow  limits  of  a 
cylinder-area  (Method  II)  the  observers  noted  at  times  a 
plurality  of  colds  or  of  warmths  of  unequal  degree. 

The  apparent  summation  under  our  cylinders  is  very  likely 
a  matter  of  conduction.  The  excitation- value  of  a  1.5-cm. 
cylinder  is  different  from  that  of  one  3-cm.  in  diameter.  In 
the  first  place,  the  thermal  gradients  from  centre  to  periphery 
are  unequal;  and  in  the  second  place,  the  difference  in  tem- 
perature between  the  skin  and  the  stimulus  will  naturally  be 


332  BARNHOLT   AND   BENTI.EY 

more  quickly  reduced  with  the  stimulus  of  smaller  area.^  Our 
punctiform  stimulus  of  constant  area  (Method  III)  eliminates 
both  of  these  complicating  factors. 

Temperature-sensations  seem  to  stand,  then,  as  regards 
intensity,  in  the  same  case  as  tones.  Without  analysis,  that 
excitatory  factor  which  possesses  the  highest  valence  deter- 
mines the  intensity  of  the  sensation.  With  (local)  analysis, 
it  seems  probable  that  each  mental  constituent  appears  in 
approximately  its  own  proper  strength.  Whether  mutual 
'inhibition,'  however,  tends  slightly  to  blunt  the  constituent 
intensities  under  analysis,  our  results  do  not  clearly  inform  us. 

Summary.  The  common  observation  that  large  surfaces  are 
sensed  as  colder  or  warmer  than  small  suggests  that  thermal 
intensity  may  be  a  function  of  the  number  of  temperature- 
organs  stimulated.  But  in  working  with  individual  end- 
organs  we  found  no  evidence  of  summation;  we  found,  in- 
stead, that  the  strength  of  sensation  is  primarily  determined 
by  the  most  highly  tuned  of  the  organs  involved.  Tuning 
does  not,  however,  wholly  explain  the  common  observation. 
After  the  consideration  of  six  other  possible  factors,  we  con- 
clude that  the  high  intensity  of  the  'large'  sensation  is  also 
owing,  in  part,  to  the  more  favorable  conditions  afforded  by 
the  stimulus  of  great  area  for  conduction  from  the  surface 
of  the  body  to  the  true  organs  for  temperature. 

^In  order  to  demonstrate  the  difference  of  conduction  we  proceeded  as 
follows.  An  ordinary  thermometer  reading  to  yV°  C.  was  laid  upon  a  flat 
horizontal  surface.  A  sheet  of  cardboard  with  a  thickness  slightly  in  excess 
of  that  of  the  lower  end  of  the  thermometer  was  cut  to  receive  the  bulb. 
Then  a  strip  of  pliable  lamb's  leather  was  stretched  over  both  and  tacked 
in  place.  The  mercury  bulb  represented  the  organs  of  temperature  and 
the  leather  the  cuticle  of  the  skin.  The  thermometer  was  brought  to  the 
temperature  of  the  room  (23.5°)  and  the  five  cylinders  used  in  Methods 
II.  and  III.  were  brought  to  zero,  and  then  applied  in  succession  to  the 
leather  sheet  just  over  the  bulb.  Each  cylinder  remained  upon  the  leather 
for  one  minute,  during  which  thermometric  readings  were  taken  every  five 
seconds.  The  rate  of  drop  in  temperature  accorded  with  the  size  of  the 
cylinder,  as  is  shown  by  the  final  readings,  which  stand  for  cylinders  i 
(smallest)  to  5(largest):  1.6°,  2.1°,  2.7°,  2,9°,  and  3.0°.  The  whole  course 
of  the  twelve  readings  for  each  cylinder  (every  5  sec.  for  i  min.),  when 
platted,  also  showed  in  a  very  striking  way  the  difference  in  physiological 
efficiency  of  the  five  brass  areas  standing  at  one  and  the  same  temperature. 
A  repetition  of  the  observations  indicated  that  the  differences  fell  well 
within  the  probable  error  of  observation.  To  make  sure  that  the  thermal 
gradient  from  centre  to  periphery  is  likewise  a  function  of  the  size  of  stim- 
ulus, we  took  similar  sets  of  readings  with  the  bulb  set  directly  under  (i) 
the  centre,  (2)  the  middle  of  a  radius,  and  (3)  the  margin  of  cylinder  5,  and 
under  (i)  the  centre,  and  (2)  the  margin  of  cylinder  i.  The  averages  of  two 
sets  of  final  readings  (initial  temperature  21.°)  were  the  following:  for 
cyl.  5,  (i)  1.85°  ±.15,  (2)  1.7°  ±. 10,  (3)  1.15°  ±.05;  forcyl.  i,  (i)  1.2°  ± 
o,  (3)  1 .0  ±  o.  Thus  it  appears,  even  from  our  rough  method  of  determina- 
tion, first,  that  the  total  conductivity  of  the  different  areas  is  different, 
and  s'fecondly,  that  conduction  within  one  and  the  same  stimulus-area  varies 
from  centre  to  margin. 


CONSCIOUSNESS  UNDER  ANESTHETICS. 


By  Edmund  Jacobson 


As  yet  it  has  been  for  the  most  part  left  to  the  surgeons 
to  describe  the  nature  of  experiences  under  anaesthetics.  They 
have  worked  out  a  semi-popular  psychology,  and  thereby 
meet  the  demands  of  their  practice  with  such  success  as  a 
common-sense  method  can  be  expected  to  secure.  But  some- 
times their  problem  becomes  very  delicate,  and  invites  the 
subtlest  refinements  of  scientific  consideration, — for  what 
they  have  to  deal  with,  and  what  life  itself  depends  upon,  is 
the  employment  of  tests  for  the  presence  or  absence  of  psycho- 
neural  functions.  Now  objective  tests  for  consciousness 
should,  when  possible,  be  confirmed  with  introspections  from 
the  subject,  and  in  so  important  a  matter  as  the  present  it 
is  desirable  that  those  introspections  be  as  accurate  and  as 
detailed  as  possible.  That  the  psychologists  are  commencing 
to  assist  in  this  introspective  task  is  shown  by  the  fact  that 
three  articles,  recounting  personal  experiences  and  attempting 
to  make  generalizations,  have  recently  appeared  in  their 
journals.  That  many  more  will  be  needed  is  evident;  and 
therefore  we  add  the  present  report  to  their  number.  Cer- 
tainly the  most  startling  thing  we  have  to  describe  is  that 
the  patient  was  conscious  under  the  anaesthetic  at  the  very 
height  of  the  operation. 

The  case  to  be  cited  occurred  at  Wesley  Hospital  of  North- 
western University  in  October,  1910,  upon  the  occasion  of 
an  operation  for  the  removal  of  the  appendix  under  the  in- 
fluence of  nitrous  oxid  and  air.  The  anaesthesia  lasted  sixteeen 
minutes.  With  reference  to  the  patient's  physical  and  mental 
condition  at  the  time,  it  is  important  to  remark  that  he  had 
not  recently  been  ill,  so  that  at  the  outset  both  physical  and 
mental  condition  were  normal,  except  in  so  far  as  he  was  stimu- 
lated by  the  serious  and  novel  situation.  Hence  attention 
was  unusually  keen,  and  the  subsequent  memories  clear  and 
detailed;  so,  for  illustration,  the  minuticB  of  the  conversation 
between  two  of  the  operators  concerning  the  movements  of  the 
meniscus  of  the  sphygmomanometer  which  they  were  pre- 
paring for  use  are  still,  after  several  months,  vividly  recallable. 
It  should  be  added  that  the  patient  had  previously  half  jest- 
ingly remarked  that  he  might  take  subjective  observations; 


334  JACOBSON 

for  this  virtually  constituted  an  Aufgabe,  and  hence  was  one  of 
the  factors  which  determined  his  mental  attitude  toward  the 
experience/ 

With  some  abridgment  and  alteration  to  suit  present  pur- 
poses, we  shall  quote  from  memoranda  which  were  not  written 
down  until  from  four  to  six  weeks  after  the  operation,  but 
which  nevertheless  are,  as  we  believe,  accurate.  Here  and  there 
we  shall  interrupt  the  account  with  explanatory  comments. 
The  experienced  reader  will  readily  distinguish  the  points 
at  which  we  are  unable  to  give  direct  descriptions  of  the  psy- 
chic processes,  and  therefore  are  obliged  to  substitute  impres- 
sionistic indications  or  statements  of  meaning. 

"After  I  had  been  placed  upon  the  operating  table  and  while 
preparations  were  under  way,  I  remember  that  I  conversed 
with  one  of  the  surgeons,  that  he  inquired  whether  I  was 
nervous,  and  that  I  answered  'No.' 

"The  time  came  for  the  application  of  the  gas.  I  was  told 
that  air  would  be  given  first,  and  then  the  gas  gradually  mixed 
with  it,  but  that  I  should  not  be  able  to  detect  the  latter, 
since  it  was  odorless.  Then  the  bell  was  put  on,  leaving  my 
eyes  partially  or  wholly  exposed.  My  left  arm  was  extended, 
and  rested  in  the  blood  pressure  apparatus,  but  the  hand 
grasped  the  wrist  of  one  of  the  surgeons,  Dr.  P.  I  breathed 
and  waited.  Nothing  happened  for  a  short  time,  and  I 
squeezed  the  wrist  to  show  that  I  was  fully  awake.  Presently 
I  detected  the  oncoming  of  the  gas,  and  I  squeezed  the  wrist 
again,  and  silently  thought  that  they  were  mistaken  in  saying 
that  the  gas  had  no  odor.  I  breathed  in  the  gas  for  a  little 
time  and  worried  slightly  because  it  did  not  seem  to  affect  my 
consciousness.  Then  the  gas  began  to  operate,  and  I  reacted 
by  squeezing  the  wrist.  There  was  no  sense  of  suffocation, 
nor  again  of  giddiness.  Objects  commenced  to  slip  from  the 
mental  grasp,  and  there  was  a  sort  of  blurring  of  those  that 
remained  in  consciousness.  My  central  thoughts  remained 
perfectly  firm.  Then  came  a  striking  experience.  My  eyes 
were  open,  and  though  the  bell  occupied  the  centre  of  the 
visual  field,  yet  it  did  not  obscure  the  rest  of  the  room.  Now 
gradually  the  sight  began  to  alter.  The  outlines  of  things 
became  blurred,  and  at  the  same  time  the  perspective  began 
to  disappear,  until  the  field  became  perfectly  flat,  and  what 
with  the  four  or  five  heads  of  the  operators,  as  they  appeared 
arranged  around  the  bell,  the  whole  (apart  from  the  blurring) 
looked  like  a  picture  of  the  early  Florentine  school ;  though  of 
course  I  make  this  comparison  now  and  did  not  then  think 

^Habits  of  continual  self-observation,  also,  will  have  to  be  taken  into 
account. 


CONSCIOUSNESS   UNDER  ANAESTHETICS  335 

of  it.  A  moment  later  and  this  also  was  gone  and  I  saw  no 
more;  excepting  that  very  nearly  colorless  lights  danced  out- 
ward accompanied  by  a  dull  buzzing.  I  said  to  myself,  *I 
don't  care;  I  don't  care.'  This  was  in  some  measure  true 
and  spontaneous;  but  also,  in  part,  it  came  as  a  deliberate 
auto-suggestion,  and  was  followed  shortly  after  by  a  fleeting 
and  half-developed  realization  that  the  suggestion  was  not 
working  negatively. 

"At  one  time,  when  consciousness  was  perceptibly  affected, 
the  hand  of  an  assistant  was  pressing  heavily,  and  I  muttered 
a  protest;  and  when  some  one  said  'Keep  quiet,'  I  laughed  in  a 
guttural  manner  to  show  that  I  was  so.  At  another  time — I 
do  not  know  precisely  when — after  vision  had  gone,  the 
surgeon  laid  his  hand  on  the  body,  and  I  cried  out,  'Not  yet! 
I  am  awake!'  Again,  after  I  was  no  longer  able  to  squeeze 
the  wrist,  I  tried  to  show  that  I  was  awake  by  muttering 
'um — um'  with  each  expiration.  While  I  was  able  later  to 
recall  that  I  had  squeezed  the  wrist  and  had  laughed,  the 
facts  of  having  muttered  and  of  having  exclaimed  that  I  was 
awake  did  not  recur  to  me  until  I  was  told  of  them. 

"There  were  other  thoughts  during  the  administration  of 
the  anaesthetic  which  now  escape  recall.  I  remember  with  great 
clearness,  however,  the  way  in  which  the  gas  seemed  to  affect 
consciousness,  for  I  was  deeply  interested  in  it  at  the  time, 
and  described  the  processes  to  myself  even  while  they  were 
occurring,  though  not  always  in  verbal  terms.  So  that  finally, 
when  things  had  almost  all  fallen  away,  I  said  to  myself,  very, 
very  slowly,  'Dim-in-ish-ing,  dim-in-ish-ing  con-scious-ness !' 
That  was  the  last  word,  and  I  knew  nothing  more;  but  as 
these  words  appeared  there  occurred  an  intellectual  process, 
which  containd  no  distinct  verbal  images,  and  the  meaning 
of  which  was,  'Your  personality  must  be  psychological  at 
its  core,  if  you  think  of  such  things  at  this  moment'." 

There  came  a  break  in  consciousness  here.  The  experiences 
which  we  are  about  to  describe  are  more  or  less  disordered  and 
confused.  Subsequently,  in  recalling  them,  they  appear 
without  temporal  setting,  and  as  more  or  less  disconnected 
from  the  experiences  during  the  waning  of  consciousness. 

"  '  Are  you  ready,  Doctor?'  'Just  a  minute,  please.'^ 

"Possibly  there  was  a  dull  whirring  and  buzzing;  voices 
moved  to  and  fro;  my  ideas  were  confused  and  troubled.  I 
did  not  rightly  know  where  I  was,  nor  what  was  happening. 
One  thing  stood  out  clear ;  there,  in  the  right  side, — the  pain ! 

^When  later  I  repeated  the  remark  to  Mr.  B.,  I  learned  that  it  was 
addressed  to  the  anaesthetist;  and  therefore  it  doubtless  meant  that  I 
should  soon  be  in  the  state  of  deep  anaesthesia.  I  was  not  able  of  myself 
to  recall  when  I  heard  these  words. 


336  JACOBSON 

It  was  sharp,  griping;  it  seemed  to  be  drawing  the  whole  body- 
to  that  spot.  It  was  agony.  I  have  never  endured,  never 
before  even  imagined  such  intense  torture.  I  groaned  again 
and  again,  in  helpless,  uncomprehending  protest. 

'  *  I  had  many  troubled  dream  experiences,  which  afterwards  I 
could  not  recall,  yet  knew  that  I  had  had  them.  The  pain 
lasted  long,  long,  and  around  it  my  dreams  centered.  Sudden- 
ly— I  do  not  know  just  how  suddenly — I  realized  it  all:  This 
agony  I  cannot  escape ;  I  am  being  operated  upon !  I  am  here 
on  the  operating  table !     And  I  am  conscious ! 

"Conscious!  I  tried  voluntarily  to  suppress  the  pain  and 
seemed  in  some  degree  to  succeed.  I  stopped  groaning.^  I 
was  thinking  now,  perhaps  with  breaks  and  disordered  inter- 
ruptions, but  yet  in  fair  measure  logically  and  coherently.  I 
am  under  the  anaesthetic  and  I  am  conscious !  It  is  secondary 
consciousness !  Amnesia  will  follow.  I  must  try  to  remember 
what  is  happening  in  order  afterwards  to  relate  it  and  prove 
that  I  was  conscious.  At  about  this  time  I  spoke  aloud  to 
those  about  me,  exclaiming,  'I've  made  a  discovery;  I've 
made  a  discovery!  The  secondary  consciousness — .'  Ac- 
cording to  my  subsequent  memory,  I  said  three  words  more 
before  I  stopped  without  completing  the  sentence.  It  seemed 
as  if  I  had  said,  'The  secondary  consciousness  is  the  primary 
consciousness — '  and  I  intended  to  go  on  and  say  that  the 
same  /  was  present  in  both,  and  perhaps  to  say  something 
else,  which  I  have  since  forgotten;  but  I  ceased,  owing  to  the 
difl&culty  of  putting  the  matter  into  words  and  owing  to  lack 
of  strength. 2 

^In  this  connection  it  is  interesting  to  note  that  Dr.  C.  reported,  'There 
was  a  time  when  you  (the  patient)  seemed  to  reconcile  yourself  to  it,  and 
you  stopped  groaning.'  I  report  tliis  voluntary  suppression  because  I 
have  a  memory  of  it;  it  is  not,  however,  in  accord  with  my  waking  experi- 
ences, since  I  am  not  ordinarily  successful  in  suppressing  pain  in  this  way. 

^Those  present  state  that  I  never  mentioned  'primary  consciousness'  at 
all,  but  that  I  repeatedly  said  'secondary  consciousness'  in  rapid  succession. 
In  subsequent  conversations  with  the  surgeons  I  stated  that  I  had  used  the 
term  'secondary'  not  in  the  usual  sense  (i.  e.,  of  double  consciousness),  but 
rather  to  signify  a  type  separated  from  primary  or  waking  consciousness 
by  amnesia.  I  trace  the  associative  source  of  this  idea  to  reading  certain 
passages  in  Bramwell  a  few  weeks  before,  though  that  author  of  course 
observes  the  customary  usage.  (Especially  p.  390,  Hypnotism.  London, 
1906.) 

I  had  never  had  any  anticipation  that  I  should  be  conscious  during  the 
operation.  For  the  sake  of  completeness  a  trivial  incident  may  be  men- 
tioned in  this  record;  a  week  before  the  operation  a  layman  had  asked 
another  in  my  presence  whether  anaesthetised  people  ever  felt  anything 
and  had  got  the  answer,  'No.'  The  incident  passed  out  of  my  mind  at  once 
and  did  not  recur  to  me  until  after  the  operation,  when  I  tried  to  recall  what 
remarks  about  anaesthetics  I  had  recently  read  or  heard.  The  incident 
is  entirely  negligible,  I  believe,  and  I  mention  it  only  because  the  record 
requires. 


CONSCIOUSNESS   UNDER  ANAESTHETICS  337 

"  'Stop  the  anaesthetic! '  It  was  probably  just  a  little  after 
this  was  said  that  marked  changes  took  place.  The  griping 
pain,  sharply  located  in  the  region  about  McBurney's  point, 
was  giving  place  to  a  very  mild  pain,  different  in  quality  and 
referred  to  the  region  about  the  umbilicus.  The  latter  was 
quite  tolerable,  and  was  the  kind  of  pain  which  in  stronger 
form  remained  more  or  less  continuously  for  about  thirty-six 
hours  after  the  operation.  I  was  'waking  up,'  and  as  audition 
was  present,  I  commenced  to  make  a  series  of  remarks  which 
ceased  when  vision  began  to  come  back.  Most  striking  was 
the  reappearance  of  the  visual  field, — at  first  like  a  fiat  (Floren- 
tine) picture,  and  then  gradually  regaining  perspective  and 
clearness, — just  the  reverse  of  the  initial  experience.  It  was 
this  that  prompted  me  to  say  aloud,  'It  all  ends  just  as  it 
began!'  "^ 

About  two  minutes  after  the  stopping  of  the  anaesthetic,  the  patient 
was  fully  awake  and  rational.  He  entered  into  conversation  about  his 
experiences  at  once,  suggested  to  the  internes  not  to  make  the  bandages  too 
tight,  etc.  Though  talking  was  very  difficult,  this  conversation  was  for  a 
while  continued  after  the  patient  had  been  put  to  bed.  Temperature  and 
pulse  fairly  soon  became  normal,  and  recovery  was  very  rapid.  The  case 
had  no  subsequent  history,  though  it  may  be  mentioned  that  during  dozing 
in  subsequent  nights,  there  occurred  three  local  nervous  spasms,  which 
were  painful  and  accompanied  by  slight  psychical  disturbance. 

Excepting  where  otherwise  specified,  the  report  quoted  is  based  upon  the 
memories  of  the  patient,  and  there  is  evidence  that  they  are  on  the  whole 
satisfactorily  faithful.  In  support  of  this  may  be  mentioned  that  he  re- 
peated to  the  surgeons  that  he  had  laughed  and  had  periodically  squeezed  the 
wrist  he  held;  although  it  came  as  news  to  him  that  eventually  the  lingers 
had  closed  about  the  wrist  with  a  vise-like  grip.  At  various  places  in  this 
paper  we  specify  things  not  recalled  at  all,  and  also  things  recalled  only 
after  others  had  first  mentioned  them.  Most  important  is  it  to  remind  the 
reader  that,  while  the  operation  was  going  on,  the  patient  determined  to 
remember  what  was  happening,  in  order  later  to  be  able  to  prove  that  he 
had  been  conscious.  This  was  virtually  an  auto-suggestion  to  remember, 
and  in  the  light  of  current  knowledge,  we  should  expect  it  to  have  efficacy; 
for  it  is  well  known  that  the  amnesia  which  characteristically  follows  deep 
hypnotic  states  can  be  prevented,  if  suggestion  to  remember  be  given  while 
the  state  is  in  course ;  and  again,  in  normal  psychology  it  has  been  experi- 
mentally verified  that  the  intention  to  remember  and  to  relate  psycho- 
logical experiences  has  a  similar  efficacy.  (Messer,  A.  Experimentell- 
psychologische  Untersuchungen  iiher  das  Denken.  Arch.  f.  d.  ges.  Psy.,  8, 
1906,  20.  Also,  Ach,  N.  Ueber  die  Willenstatigkeit  und  das  Denken.  Got- 
tingen,  1905,  p.  11.)  Therefore  it  is  particularly  interesting  to  state  that 
immediately  after  waking,  the  patient  was  able  to  enter  into  conversation 
about  "secondary  consciousness,"  "discovery,"  and  the  like,  without 
needing  to  be  informed  of  having  spoken  aloud  of  these  things.  Further- 
more, his  memory  of  the  question  "Are  you  ready.  Doctor?"  and  the 
answer  "Just  a  minute,  please"  was  corroborated  by  Mr.  B.,  who  was 

^This  accords  with  the  statement  of  Hewitt,  '  'When  the  administration 
is  discontinued  and  fresh  air  admitted  to  the  lungs,  a  kind  of  retrogression 
in  the  patient's  symptoms  commences."  Ancesthetics  and  their  Adminis- 
tration.    London,  1893,  p.  327. 


338  JACOBSON 

present  during  the  operation.  But  the  most  interesting  verification  of  all 
was  the  repetition  of  the  groan  to  Dr.  C.  and  Mr.  B.,  who  were  able  to  recog- 
nize it  without  a  doubt  because  of  its  very  peculiar  character.  It  was  the 
kinaesthetic-auditory  memory-image  of  this  groan  and  the  auditory  image, 
"Are  you  ready,  Doctor? — Just  a  minute,  please,"  that  the  patient 
found  associated  with  the  memory  of  his  conscious  determination  to  re- 
member. 

We  have  some  brief  notes  kindly  dictated  to  us  by  Dr.  G.  T.  Courtenay 
and  Mr.  J.  R,  Buchbinder,  both  of  whom  assisted  in  the  operation,  but 
unfortunately  not  given  until  three  weeks  after  the  operation  and  therefore 
somewhat  inaccurate  and  incomplete.  We  give  them,  however,  since  they 
are  all  that  we  have ;  for  the  sake  of  clearness  we  have  somewhat  altered 
their  style. 

Dr.  C. — Before  the  incision  the  patient  said,  "I  am  not  asleep," 
again  and  again.  Dr.  R.  put  his  hand  on  the  abdomen  and  he  said,  "Not 
yet!  I  am  awake!"  He  was  not  thought  to  be  under  as  yet.  He  had 
been  muttering.  The  incision  was  made.  During  this  time,  and  up  to 
the  moment  when  the  operator  came  to  the  appendix,  there  was  no  mutter- 
ing and  nothing  was  said,  but  there  was  muscular  rigidity.  Then  the 
patient  cried,  "Oh — h!" — groaning.  As  I  remember  it,  he  then  cried 
loudly,  "I  am  awake!"  and  repeated  this  several  times.  While  the  skin- 
clips  were  being  put  in  he  exclaimed,  "It's  the  secondary  consciousness! 
I  have  made  a  discovery!"     (See  also  p.  336.) 

Mr.  B. — While  the  gas  was  being  given  to  induce  anaesthesia,  the 
patient  said  nothing.  After  two  minutes  Dr.  R.  said,  "Are  you  ready. 
Doctor?"  (When  the  writer  reminded  Mr.  B.  that  the  answer  came, 
"Just  a  minute,  please,"  he  recalled  the  remark  and  supplied  the  informa- 
tion that  it  was  addressed  to  the  anaesthetist.)  Before  the  incision  there 
occurred  inarticulate  muttering.  Probably  during  or  after  the  incision 
(I  cannot  positively  say  which)  the  patient  said,  "I  am  conscious."  A 
minute  or  two  elapsed,  during  which  the  operator  was  getting  the  tip  of  the 
appendix  and  the  patient  was  quiet.  While  the  caecum  was  being  manipu- 
lated he  said,  "I  have  made  a  discovery; — an  important  psychological 
discovery!"  This  was  repeated  many  times,  each  one  faster  than  before. 
The  appendix  was  cut  off  and  the  patient  squeezed  the  wrist  of  Dr.  P.  with 
a  very  strong  grip.  Then  he  repeated  '  'important  discovery  "  and  "second- 
ary consciousness"  a  few  times.  (It  will  be  recalled  that  the  report  of  the 
patient  shows  no  remembrance  of  the  phrases  having  been  thus  repeated. 
In  this  respect  Mr.  B.'s  report  supplements  the  former,  and  is  without 
question  correct;  but  we  doubt  that  the  terms  "important"  and  "psycho- 
logical" were  used.)  After  the  first  skin-clip  had  been  put  on,  the  admin- 
istration of  the  anaesthetic  was  stopped  and  the  suggestion  given,  "You 
can  wake  up."  During  the  last  few  minutes  the  patient  was  quiet,  and 
after  waking  said  to  me,  "I've  made  some  interesting  observations.  Did 
you  take  notes?"  (Mr.  B.  amended  the  above  account  after  the  patient 
purposely  repeated  the  groan  for  him.  Like  Dr.  C,  he  was  able  to  recall 
with  certainty  that  it  occurred,  but  unlike  him,  was  not  perfectly  sure 
when  it  occurred,  adding,  however,  that  the  balance  of  probability  seemed 
in  favor  of  its  having  occurred  after  incision.)  During  the  operation  the 
blood-pressure,  as  indicated  by  the  sphygmomanometer,  remained  constant. 

Now  let  us  proceed  to  general  matters. — It  is  more  or  less 
the  custom,  in  treatises  on  anaesthesia,  to  include  an  account  of 
the  order  of  disappearance  of  the  functions  of  the  nervous 
system.  So,  for  instance,  Patton  says,  "There  is  irritation, 
depression,  and  finally  paralysis  of  the  nervous  system.  The 
cerebral  cortex,  the  cerebellum  and  ganglia  of  the  base,  the 


CONSCIOUSNESS   UNDER   ANAESTHETICS  339 

sensory  tracts  and  centres  of  the  cord,  the  cerebrospinal  motor 
tracts  and  centres,  and  the  respiratory  and  cardiac  centres 
seem  to  be  affected  in  the  order  mentioned."^  Experimental 
and  clinical  observations  have  led  to  formulae  of  this  sort,  which 
therefore  must  have  at  least  a  certain  rough  validity.  Every- 
day clinical  experience  makes  it  familiar  that  circulation  and 
respiration  almost  always  remain  when  other  functions  have 
failed;  and  it  is  equally  certain  that  the  loss  of  the  conjunctival 
reflex  is  a  useful  indication  of  the  loss  of  various  other  nervous 
functions.  There  are  other  gross  correlations  of  this  sort,  the 
validity  of  which  is  fairly  beyond  challenge.  The  principle  of 
such  correlations  is,  therefore,  true  and  useful — if  not  carried  to 
the  extreme.  But  the  current  formula  that  the  nervous  func- 
tions disappear  in  hierarchical  order  cannot,  we  believe,  be 
completely  relied  upon.  It  appears  that  sometimes,  at  least, 
a  higher  function  may  remain  even  when  certain  lower  ones 
have  gone ;  that  the  absence  of  certain  lower  functions  is  not  an 
invariable  guarantee  of  the  absence  of  all  higher  ones.  In  evi- 
dence of  this  may  be  adduced  our  own  case  as  a  fair  example  of 
the  highest  psychoneural  function,  namely  intellection,  remain- 
ing present  even  when  lower  ones  such  as  vision  were  in 
abeyance.  Nor  does  this  observation  seem  to  be  exceptional, 
for  the  same  thing  is  reported,  with  respect  to  the  period  of 
the  waning  of  consciousness,  not  alone  in  the  psychological 
papers  of  Jones,  Johnston,  and  Hill,  but  also  in  Hare's  article 
in  Keen's  Surgery"^.  Therefore  we  seem  warranted  in  generaliz- 
ing, at  least  with  respect  to  persons  who  make  habitual  use  of 
the  higher  intellectual  functions,  that  generally  these  persist 
even  after  vision  and  other  psychical  and  physiological  lower 
functions  have  gone. 

As  to  the  psychological  situation,  there  seem  to  be  some 
strange  misunderstandings  (or  else  carelessnesses)  in  certain 

^Patton,  J.  M.:  "Anaesthesia  and  Anaesthetics. "  Chicago,  1905,  p.  30* 
2  "After  all  sensations  were  damped  down  completely  there  still  remained 
an  inner  consciousness  which  for  the  most  part  was  perfectly  normal. 
Memory  seemed  pretty  accurate,  and  the  reasoning  powers  only  slightly 
deficient."  Jones,  B.  E.  The  Waning  of  Consciousness  under  Chloroform. 
Psy.  Rev.  16,  1909,  53-54.  "The  special  sense  organs  become  inactive 
long  before  general  consciousness  is  lost."  (Speaking  of  the  process  of 
recovery  of  normal  consciousness,  the  same  writer  says,  '  'Feeling  is  first 
reinstated.  Purely  intellectual  activity- — is  next  in  order."  Johnston, 
H.  J.  The  Role  of  Sensations  and  Feelings  under  Ether.  Jour.  Abn. 
Psy.  4,  1909,  29.  ' ' — there  — remained  to  the  final  fading  out  of  conscious 
experience  an  awareness  of  personal  identity."  Hill,  Prof,  and  Mrs.  D.  S. 
Loss  and  Recovery  of  Consciousness  under  Anaesthesia.  Psy.  Bull.,  7,3,81, 
' ' — chloroform,  after  a  brief  quickening  of  the  pulse  and  of  respiration, 
causes  a  gradual  decrease  in  the  activity  of  the  perceptive  portions  of  the 
cerebrum,  followed  or  accompanied  by  a  similar  obtunding  of  the  intellect- 
ual activities."  Hare,  H.  A.  Keen's  Surgery,  Philadelphia,  1909,  V,  1019. 
Similarly  in  the  case  of  ether,  1027. 


340  JACOBSON 

of  the  surgical  works.  For  example,  in  speaking  of  the  second 
degree  of  general  anaesthesia,  Patton  states  that  it  is  a  "stage 
of  unconscious  reflex  activity."^  Here,  as  he  says,  he  is 
following  Hewitt,  and  therefore  we  shall  quote  the  views  of 
that  writer.^  "Second  Degree  or  Stage. — (Ether)  Loss 
of  consciousness  takes  place  abruptly.  The  patient  passes 
into  a  condition  in  which,  although  memory,  volition,  and  in- 
telligence are  abrogated,  he  will  readily  respond  to  stimuli. 
The  response  may  have  all  the  appearance  of  conscious 
response.  (N.  B !)  Questions  may  be  answered;  but  the  answers 
will  be  nonsensical." 

If  we  understand  the  above  passage  rightly,  it  means  that 
a  time  comes  at  which  the  patient  is  to  be  considered  uncon- 
scious, yet  at  which  he  will  give  answers  to  questions  as  well  as 
simulate  conscious  response  in  other  ways.  This  view  is  so 
naive  that  the  psychological  reader  will  not  demand  that  we 
argue  the  matter.  Hewitt  also  says,  "Laughing,  struggling, 
shouting  and  singing  may  be  met  with  at  the  commencement 
of  this  stage  if  the  administration  be  slowly  conducted." 
We  scarcely  believe  that  he  wishes  to  consider  these  reactions 
also  as  unconscious.  But  without  making  assumptions  in  this 
regard,  we  may  state  in  reply  that,  by  virtue  of  analogy  with 
our  general  psychological  experience,  there  need  be  no  doubt 
that  the  patient  is  conscious  when  such  things  occur  as  answer- 
ing questions,  shouting,  singing,  talking,  laughing,  or  true 
groaning.^  It  is  absurd  to  call  a  stage  which  may  be  character- 
ized by  the  presence  of  such  reactions  one  of  "unconscious 
reflex  activity."  Such  a  use  of  the  term  "unconscious"  is 
lamentable,  for  it  contains  the  confusion,  sometimes  popularly 
made,  between  absence  of  intelligent  response  and  absence  of 
conscious  response.^ 

^Op.  ciL,  33- 

^Op.  ciL,  153. 

^We  use  the  expression  true  groaning  in  order  to  exclude  stertor  and  also 
expiratory  noises  due  merely  to  obclusion  of  the  air  and  vocal  passages  by 
tongue,  mucus,  or  other  foreign  substance. 

^When  a  reaction  is  nonsensical,  this  indicates  the  presence  of  disorganiza- 
tion in  consciousness ;  the  processes  do  not  function  as  usual,  relatively  to 
each  other.  Complete  nonsense  would  mean  utter  disorganization  of 
conscious  processes,  but  it  would  be  incorrect  to  take  it  to  mean  complete 
absence  of  conscious  process.  This  fact  being  clear,  there  is  left  an  invit- 
ing problem  for  investigation  by  psycho-analj'^sis  as  to  whether  the  utter- 
ances of  patients  under  ether  or  chloroform  delirium  have  not  a  "  latent 
meaning"  under  their  apparent  absurdity.  Apropos  of  this,  the  writer 
recalls  the  deep  significance  possessed  by  his  groan.  It  meant  uncom- 
prehending and  helpless  protest  against  the  pain.  Physiologically  it 
was  the  development  or  consummation  of  the  process  of  uttering  '  'tun — 
um,"  for  it  was  made  with  the  same  laryngeal  adjustment,  except  that 
instead  of  an  almost  constant  pitch  it  had  a  large  rise  and  fall,  was  much 
higher,  and  much  more  prolonged.  The  former  utterance  had  the  meaning 
"Not  yet!     I  am  awake!" 


CONSCIOUSNESS   UNDER   ANAESTHETICS  34 1 

In  the  light  of  these  considerations,  and  if  even  highly- 
organized  consciousness  has  the  tenacity  which  we  have  indi- 
cated, it  is  apparent  how  great  ought  to  be  the  caution  in  judg- 
ing that  the  patient  is  unconscious  on  the  ground  that  certain 
reflexes  are  absent  and  notwithstanding  that  other  ones  are 
present.  To  be  sure,  with  sufficiently  deep  ether  or  chloroform 
anaesthesia,  a  condition  may  be  attained  which  is  suggestive 
of  natural  sleep;  respiration  and  circulation  are  the  chief 
visible  activities  that  remain;  there  is  quiet  (except  for  stertor) 
and  relaxation,  and  the  spinal  reflexes  are  largely  absent  and 
inelicitable.  When  things  are  so,  it  seems  reasonable  enough, 
on  grounds  that  we  shall  formulate  later  on,  to  assume  uncon- 
sciousness; for  although  this  conclusion  cannot  be  proved 
with  absolute  certainty,  yet  at  any  rate  it  has  high  probability.  ^ 
But  there  are  statements  in  the  surgical  books  which  go  farther 
and  assume  the  absence  of  consciousness  even  when  such 
quiet  and  absence  of  function  are  not  attained.  So,  for  ex- 
ample, the  International  Text-Book  of  Surgery,  in  arguing 
for  a  sparing  use  of  ether  in  prolonged  operations,  says:  "A 
few  whiffs  of  ether  now  and  again  will  keep  him  free  from  pain, 
anxiety  and  fright.  As  he  knows  little  or  nothing,  a  moderate 
amount  of  involuntary  struggling  unattended  with  suffering 
does  no  harm."^  We  submit,  however,  that  it  is  not  safe 
generally  to  affirm  that  when  a  * '  moderate  amount  of  invol- 
untary struggling"  is  present  the  patient  nevertheless 
"knows  little  or  nothing."  It  is  a  very  delicate  matter  indeed 
to  say  when  struggling  occurs  unaccompanied  by  the  conscious 
functioning  of  the  higher  nerve-centres.  For  if,  on  the  one 
hand,  it  is  fairly  certain  that  such  functions  as  answering 
questions  are  always  accompanied  by  higher  consciousness, 
while,  on  the  other,  it  is  also  fairly  certain  that  such  functions 
as  circulation  are  accompanied  at  most  by  only  a  very  low 
form  of  consciousness,  yet  the  most  that  it  seems  fair  to  concede 
with  regard  to  struggling  is  that  it  can  upon  occasion  belong  to 
either  class  of  experiences.  Why  this  is  so  will  be  made  clear 
in  the  following  paragraph. 

Jactitation  is  a  phenomenon  likely  to  occur  when  nitrous 
oxid  is  given  without  oxygen  or  air  and  is  described,  for  ex- 
ample, by  Ivuke,  as  consisting  of  ' '  clonic  muscular  contractions 
commencing  in  the  orbicularis  palpebrarum  and  extending  to 
the  limbs. "^     If,  as  a  test  case,  one  is  looking  for  reasons  why 

^In  judging  depth  of  anaesthesia  the  surgeon  is  guided  by  observation 
of  some  or  all  of  the  following :  the  respiration,  the  occurrence  of  swallowing 
movements,  the  lid-reflex,  the  state  of  the  eye  and  pupil,  the  pulse,  the 
color  of  the  face  and  lips,  the  rigidity  of  the  skeletal  muscles  (Hewitt). 

2phil.,  I,  1902,  448. 

^Guide  to  AncBsthetics,  Phil.,  1906,  19. 

2 — Journal 


342  JACOBSON 

this  activity  should  be  considered  unconscious  or  conscious, 
the  important  fact  must  be  noted  that  under  normal  con- 
ditions it  cannot  be  consciously  initiated  (at  any  rate  not  in 
the  absence  of  a  preliminary  learning  process).  By  analogy 
with  normal  experience,  therefore,  there  is  no  compulsion 
to  assume  that  jactitation  is  a  conscious  phenemenon.  And 
in  general  it  may  be  said  that  there  is  no  logical  requirement 
to  assume  consciousness  in  case  of  activities  which  under  normal 
conditions  are  incapable  of  conscious  initiation.^  Again,  if  one 
is  considering  another  class  of  functions,  those,  namely,  of  the 
autonomic  nervous  system, — circulation,  respiration,  secre- 
tion, etc.,  what  needs  to  be  taken  into  account  is  that  under 
normal  conditions  these  do  not  require  the  attendance  of 
consciousness  in  order  that  they  may  go  on.  By  analogy 
with  normal  experience,  therefore,  there  is  also  no  compulsion 
to  assume  that  these  phenomena  under  anaesthesia  are  accom- 
panied by  consciousness.  Or,  to  put  this  matter  also  generally, 
there  is  no  logical  requirement  to  assume  consciousness  in  case 
of  activities  which  under  normal  conditions  may  go  on  without 
conscious  attendance.  It  is  now  clear  why  it  is  permissible 
to  assume  that  deep  states  of  ether  and  chloroform  narcosis 
are  probably  unconscious;  for  all  the  activities  that  are 
observably  present  in  these  states  are  either  such  as  may 
under  normal  conditions  go  on  without  conscious  attendance 
or  else  such  as  are  normally  incapable  of  conscious  initiation. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  phenomenon  of  struggling  does  not 
fall  into  either  of  these  two  categories;  for  under  normal  con- 
ditions it  can  be  consciously  initiated  and  it  never  occurs 
without  conscious  attendance.  Therefore  there  is  an  element 
of  hazard  in  calling  it  unconscious  at  any  particular  time; 
and  at  all  events,  when  it  occurs  concomitantly  with  shouting, 
true  groaning,  or  the  like,  it  should — like  these  reactions 
themselves — be  regarded  as  conscious. 

The  mere  fact  that  the  patient  is  subsequently  without 
memory  of  his  reactions  must  not  be  assumed  to  prove  that 
consciousness  was  absent.  For  his  psychophysiological  state 
is  so  disturbed — not  alone  during  the  administration  of 
the  anaesthetic,  but  also  usually  for  some  time  thereafter — 
that  memory  may  be  expected  to  be  deficient.  So  it  is  in  the 
case  of  Hill,  whose  record  shows  that  there  was  a  period  follow- 
ing the  first  signs  of  awakening  during  which  he  did  such 
conscious  things  as  calling  for  air  and  chattering  more  or  less 
irrationally  about  his  experiences,  but  of  which  he  subse- 
quently had  no  recollection.^  The  fact  of  forgetfulness  was 
noted  by  Buxton  in  his  discussion  of  chloroform  narcosis. 

1/.  e.,  voluntary  initiation. 
^Op.  cit.,  p.  79- 


I 


CONSCIOUSNESS   UNDER   ANiESTHETlCS  343 

"In  the  second  stage  [Buxton  recognized  five  stages]  the  mental 
powers  are  impaired  although  not  suspended ....  As 
a  rule  struggles  or  experiences  of  pain  which  show  themselves 
at  the  time  are  not  subsequently  remembered."^  A  further 
reason  for  presuming  that  experiences  during  gas,  ether,  or 
chloroform  narcosis  might  not  be  subsequently  recalled,  even 
if  conscious  at  the  time,  is  that  amnesia  characterizes  kindred 
psychophysiological  states,  namely  deep  hypnosis,  deep  alco- 
holic intoxication,  and  the  dream  states  of  natural  sleep. 
This  tendency  toward  amnesia,  which  we  must  therefore 
recognize,  is  an  obvious  hindrance  to  proving  that  the 
patient  was  unconscious.  One  must  give  him  a  fair  chance 
to  remember:  Follow  the  example  of  the  workeis  on  deep 
hypnosis:  experimentally  produce  a  state  of  ether  narcosis 
in  which  involuntary  struggling,  groaning,  and  the  like 
occur;  during  this  state  or  previous  to  it,  get  en  rapport  with 
the  patient  and  suggest  to  him  that  he  will  remember  all  that 
occurs ;  next,  quickly  bring  him  back  to  normal  consciousness, 
avoiding  post-anaesthetic  disturbance  as  much  as  possible, 
and  learn  whether  the  patient  then  retains  any  memory  I^ 
If  he  does  not,  this  is  evidence  that  he  had  no  high  form  of 
consciousness;  not  an  absolutely  conclusive  test,  however, 
since  a  low  or  disorganized  state  of  consciousness  might  be 
present  and  yet  fail  to  respond  to  suggestion.  But  at  any 
rate,  in  the  absence  of  experimental  tests  of  this  kind,  it  is  a 
risky  hypothesis  to  assume  that  such  things  as  struggling  and 
groaning  in  anaesthesia  are  other  than  what  they  are  in  normal 
activity,  namely,  signs  of  unpleasant  consciousness. 

In  this  connection,  attention  may  be  called  to  the  fact 
(recognized,  for  instance,  by  Hewitt)  that  nitrous  oxid  does 
not  give  that  complete  freedom  from  reflex  movement  and 
phonation  which  characterizes  the  third  degree  of  ether  or 
chloroform  anaesthesia.^  Or  again,  as  A.  D.  Bevan  recently 
put  it, — "  (Nitrous  oxid)  anaesthesia  is  not  as  profound  as  that 
of  ether  or  chloroform,  and  the  occasional  talking  of  the  patient 
may  be  disconcerting  to  one  not  familiar  with  the  method."* 

^Buxton,  D.  W. :  Ancesihetics,  London,  1888,  69. 

^Anaesthetics  characteristically  produce  a  state  of  heightened  suggesti- 
bility. So  in  clinical  work  it  is  found  advisable  not  do  do  anything  to  or 
say  anything  before  the  patient  during  the  waning  of  consciousness  that 
might  act  as  a  harmful  suggestion.  The  close  relationship  which  anaes- 
thetic narcosis  bears  to  such  a  state  of  heightened  suggestibility  as  hypno- 
sis is  shown  on  the  one  hand  by  the  fact  that  chloroform,  for  instance,  may 
be  used  as  a  decided  aid  to  suggestion  in  inducing  hypnosis  (e.  g.,  Bram- 
well,  op.  cit.,  p.  45),  and  on  the  other  hand  by  the  fact  that  suggestion 
may  be  used  as  a  decided  aid  to  chloroform  in  inducing  surgical  anaesthesia 
{e.  g.,  Munro,  H.  S.  Influence  of  Suggestion  as  an  Adjunct  in  the  Admin- 
istration of  AncBsthetics.  St.  Louis  Med.  Rev.,  Nov.,  1908.) 

^Op.  cit.,  p.  no. 

*Jour.  Am.  Med.  Ass.,  1907,  49,  3,  197. 


344  JACOB SON 

What  seems  to  us  the  probable  significance  of  the  presence  of 
such  reactions  has  already  been  sufficiently  indicated.  Talk- 
ing does  not  possess  the  distinguishing  marks  that  belong  to 
activities  which  may  permissibly  be  considered  as  uncon- 
scious; for  under  normal  conditions  it  is  capable  of  conscious 
initiation  and  it  never  occurs  without  conscious  attendance. 
Therefore  the  conclusion  that  it  is  unconscious  when  it  occurs 
during  ansesthesia  is  unwarranted.  If  nitrous  oxid  anaesthesia 
is  characterized  by  the  presence  of  such  reactions,  it  does  not 
seem  warranted  to  believe  it  to  be  a  state  of  continuous  un- 
consciousness. Nor,  as  previously  indicated,  should  the 
assumption  of  unconsciousness  be  made  with  regard  to  chloro- 
form or  ether  ansesthesia  unless  these  drugs  be  given  in  suffi- 
cient quantity  to  suppress  "involuntary  struggling"  and  the 
like. 

It  goes  without  saying,  however,  that  the  psychologist 
can  have  no  opinion  on  questions  concerning  the  choice  of  an 
anaesthetic  for  a  given  operation,  or  again,  concerning  the 
advisability  of  permitting  slight  consciousness  in  prolonged 
operations  in  preference  to  running  the  dangers  of  exhaustion 
and  collapse  which  prolonged  and  deep  anaethesia  involves. 
Matters  of  practice  concern  only  the  surgeon.  The  sole  inter- 
est of  the  psychologist  is  to  analyze  the  mental  situation. 

Before  closing  the  paper,  a  few  words  of  discussion  may  be 
added  in  regard  to  the  psychological  articles  that  have  recently 
appeared.  Jones  presents  the  record  of  three  experiences  under 
chloroform,  two  of  which  were  produced  for  observational 
purposes  alone,  and  with  the  aid  of  simple  laboratory  devices. 
His  account  is  therefore  more  full  than  could  otherwise  be  the 
case,  and  is  important  because  of  its  qualitative  descriptions 
of  sensory  processes  and  its  tests  as  to  the  order  of  disappear- 
ance of  mental  functions.  That  order  was:  hearing,  touch, 
gross  muscular  movement,  highly  specialized  movement 
(fingers),  vision,  reasoning,  memory.  To  be  sure,  Jones  fails 
to  state  whether  this  order  was  precisely  maintained  in  all 
three  cases,  and  one  is  frequently  at  a  loss  to  know  whether 
a  given  phenomenon  that  he  describes  occurred  in  only  one 
of  his  experiences  or  in  all  three.  It  is  to  be  regretted  that 
he  made  the  methodological  error  of  failing  to  be  clear  and 
full  as  to  what  were  their  similarities  and  differences.  Hill  is 
especially  interested  in  marking  the  similarities  and  differences 
between  his  experiences  and  those  of  Jones.  If  we  have  not 
misunderstood  the  latter's  paper,  he  was  awake — able  to  reason, 
and  remember — after  muscular  control  had  disappeared.^ 
If  so,  then  Hill  scarcely  seems  justified  in  saying  that  "the 

^Op.  cit.,  p.  53-4. 


CONSCIOUSNESS   UNDER   ANi^STH^TlCS  345 

persistence  of  motor  ability  in  the  observation  of  both  Jones 
and  myself  as  witnessed  in  the  waning  of  consciousness 
attests  its  fundamental  position,  and  also  that  artificial  sleep 
as  well  as  natural  sleep.  .  .  is  most  closely  related  to  the 
cessation  of  voluntary  motor  ability."  If  one  is  seeking  a  key 
to  the  explanation  of  sleep,  and  regards  'persistence'  as  the 
road  to  finding  it,  why  select  Voluntary  motor  ability'  in 
preference,  say,  to  voluntary  memory, — which  in  Jones'  case 
was  the  more  persistent?  It  is  relevant  to  mention  the  case 
of  the  patient  described  by  Johnson,  who  becomes  awake  (to 
the  extent  of  having  various  sensations  and  feelings)  at  a 
time  when  the  limbs  were  not  under  control.^  To  be  sure, 
if  voluntary  motor  ability  is  absent,  one  would  ipso  facto  not 
expect  normal  consciousness  to  be  present.  But  if  anything 
further  than  this  is  to  be  established,  and  if  voluntary  motor 
ability  is  to  be  exalted  over  its  brother  functions,  a  wider 
range  of  evidence  should  be  offered  than  that  given  by  Hill. 

Johnson's  paper  is  valuable — among  other  things — for  its 
description  of  the  waning  of  voluntary  inhibitory  power, 
wherein  it  resembles  that  of  Hill,  but  differs  from  that  of 
Jones  and  our  own  since  the  loss  is  not  reported  by  the  latter 
two.  The  order  of  disappearance  of  functions,  also,  differs 
from  that  of  Jones :  vision  went  before  touch.  ^  Johnson  termi- 
nates his  paper  with  a  discussion  of  the  nature  of  feelings, 
imageless  activity,  and  the  like;  but  these  are  general  matters, 
better  left  for  laboratory  investigation.  Efforts  should  be 
focused  on  the  attempt  to  understand  the  anaesthetic  experi- 
ence itself,  with  special  endeavor  to  describe  minutely  the 
conscious  events  in  their  temporal  order,  and  in  addition,  when 
possible,  to  state  the  physiological  concomitants.^ 

^Op.  cit.,  p.  23. 

2This  suggests  the  matter  of  individual  differences,  which  vary  greatly 
with  (i)  the  anaesthetic  used,  and  (2)  the  temporary  and  permanent  psycho- 
physiological conditions  of  the  patient.  An  adequate  account  of  individ- 
ual differences  cannot  yet  be  written,  although  the  surgical  books  furnish 
some  material.  Of  particular  practical  importance  would  it  be  to  deter- 
mine how  frequently  the  pain  sense  persists  during  the  second  and  third 
stages. 

3 An  excellent  list  of  problems  has  been  published  by  Jastrow.  Am.  Med.^ 
Philadelphia,  1905,  X,  202.  Same  also  in  Pacific  M.  J.,  San  Francisco, 
1906,  XLIX,  140. 


ON  THE  INTENSITY  OF  IMAGES* 


By  Alma  de  Vries  Schaub 

CONTENTS 

PAGE 

I. 

Introduction 

346 

(a)    Historical 

347 

(b)    Experimental 

349 

II. 

Difficulties  and  sources  of  error 

351 

III. 

Experimental  procedure 

353 

IV. 

Results 

I.    With  reference  to  Intensity 

357 

(a)    Ascription  of  intensity  to  images 

357 

(b)    Varying  degrees  of  imaginal  intensity 

358 

2.    With  reference  to  the  Non-intensive  Differences  between 

Sensation  and  Image 

364 

V. 

Conclusion 

366 

Introduction 

Until  recent  years  the  experimental  investigation  of  images 
has  been  comparatively  neglected,  and  even  at  the  present 
time  the  subject  does  not  seem  to  receive  either  the  extended 
or  the  detailed  study  that  is  given  to  sensation.  Thus,  while 
there  have  been  studies  of  the  general  nature  of  mental  imagery, 
of  the  memory  image,  and  of  the  image  of  imagination,  these 
have  treated  the  subject  mostly  from  the  point  of  view  of  recog- 
nition and  recall,  and  a  specific  investigation  of  the  attributes 
of  the  image  has  been  neglected.  Especially  meagre  in  the 
existing  experimental  work  on  imagery  is  reference  to  its 
intensive  aspect,  a  subject  that  has  played  an  important  r61e 
in  the  study  of  sensation.  Our  aim  in  the  present  investiga- 
tion has,  therefore,  been  to  attack  the  problem  of  images  from 
the  point  of  view  of  their  intensity.  More  specifically,  we 
seek  to  answer  two  questions:  (i)  Do  images  possess  the  attri- 
bute of  intensity?  and,  if  so,  (2)  Is  this  intensity  comparable 
with  that  of  sensations,  and  in  how  far?  A  brief  review  of  the 
mention  of  this  subject  in  psychological  literature  and  in  experi- 
mental investigation  will  serve  not  only  to  introduce  the  prob- 
lem but  also  to  show  the  urgent  need  for  its  careful  examina- 
tion. 

^From  the  Psychological  Laboratory  of  Cornell  University 


ON  THE  INTENSITY  OF  IMAGES  347 

(a)     Historical 

Though  almost  all  writers  agree  in  accepting  intensity  as  one  of  the 
attributes  of  sensation,  there  is  by  no  means  such  agreement  with  regard 
to  the  intensity  of  images.  Indeed,  many  of  the  earlier  writers,  and  a  few 
of  the  more  recent  as  well,  seem  to  find  in  intensity  the  main  difference 
between  images  and  sensations.  They  have  either  denied  this  attribute 
altogether  to  certain  images,  or,  at  best,  have  granted  them  but  a  small 
measure  of  it.  The  clearest  and  most  concise  expression  of  this  view, 
perhaps,  is  that  of  Hume.  "All  the  perceptions  of  the  human  mind,"  he 
tells  us,  "resolve  themselves  into  two  distinct  kinds  which  I  shall  call 
Impressions  and  Ideas.  The  difference  betwixt  these  consists  in  the  degree 
of  force  and  liveliness  with  which  they  strike  upon  the  mind.  .... 
Those  perceptions  which  enter  with  most  force  and  violence  we  may  name 
impressions;  .  .  .  By  ideas  1  mean  the  faint  images  of  these  in  thinking 
and  reasoning.  "1  That  Hume  regards  difference  in  intensity  as  the  dis- 
tinguishing mark  of  the  image,  appears  also  in  such  statements  as  the  follow- 
ing: "The  first  circumstance  that  strikes  my  eye,  is  the  great  resemblance 
betwixt  our  impressions  and  ideas,  in  every  other  particular  except  their 
degree  of  force  and  vivacity."^  "That  idea  of  red,  which  we  form  in  the 
dark,  and  that  impression,  which  strikes  our  eyes  in  the  sunshine,  differ 
only  in  degree  not  in  nature."^  While  Bain  is  not  so  explicit  in  regarding 
intensity  rather  than  quality  as  the  essential  difference  between  image  and 
sensation,  he,  nevertheless,  calls  it  the  most  obvious  point  of  difference.* 
Hobbes^,  John  Stuart  Mill",  and  Hamilton^,  barely  touch  upon  the  subject, 
yet  indicate  their  assent  to  this  view.  Spencer  undoubtedly  confuses 
intensity  with  clearness  or  vividness,  but  on  close  examination  his  doctrine 
appears  to  agree  with  that  of  Bain,  He  divides  feelings  into  "those  pri- 
mary and  vivid  feelings  produced  by  direct  excitation,  and  those  secondary 
or  faint  feelings  produced  by  indirect  excitations,"  adding  that  he  wishes 
to  emphasize  "not  difference  in  kind,  but  difference  in  degree."^ 

Of  the  German  writers,  Lotze  seems  to  deny  absolutely  that  images 
possess  the  attribute  of  intensity.  There  has  been  some  discussion  with 
regard  to  his  statement  that  '  'the  idea  of  the  brightest  radiance  does  not 
shine,  that  of  the  intensest  noise  does  not  sound,  that  of  the  greatest  tor- 
ture produces  no  pain."^  Such  a  statement,  in  the  opinion  of  Titchener, 
reflects  a  form  of  the  stimulus  error.^"  Another  statement  of  Lotze's  which 
must  be  regarded  as  doubtful  and  which,  by  the  way,  is  not  consistent  with 
the  sentence  quoted  above,  is  the  following:  "Only  sensations  of  moderate 
intensity  allow  of  a  reproduction  that  is  in  some  measure  faithful.  "^^  Eb- 
binghaus,  while  not  actually  denying  intensity  to  images,  grants  them  only 
a  scant  allowance.  In  one  passage,  indeed,  he  says:  "The  imaged  sun  does 
not  shine  and  its  imaged  heat  with  its  thousandfold  degrees  gives  no  warmth ; 
the  last  spark  of  a  flickering  match  is  far  more  effective  in  both  respects. "^^ 

1  David  Hume:  A  Treatise  of  Human  Nature,  ed.  bv  L.  A.  Selby-Bigge,  1889,  i. 
'Op.  cit.,  2. 
^Op.  cit..  3. 

*J.  Mill:  Analysis  of  the  Phenomena  of  the  Human   Mind,  1878,  I.,  63  note;  A.  Bain: 
The  Senses  and  the  Intellect,  i888.  338. 
'T.  Hobbes:  Leviathan,  1881,  6. 

6  J.  Mill:  Op.  cit.,  68;  note  by  J.  S.  MUl. 

7  Sir  W.  Hamilton:  Lectures  on  Metaphysics,  1859.  II.,  Lect.  XXIII.,  259  Cf. 
*H.  Spencer:   The  Principles  of  Psychology,  1890,  I.,  288. 

*H.  Lotze:  Outlines  of  Psychology,  tr.,  1886,  28;  cf.  also  Medicinische  Psychologie, 
1852    477  ff.;  Microcosmus,  i,   203  f. 

i"E.  B.  Titchener:  A  Text-Book  of  Psychology,  1910.  II.,  398  note. 

^^"Nur  Eindruecke  von  mittlerer  Groesse  scheinen  sich  einigermassen  entsprechend  re- 
producieren  zu  lassen."     Medicinische  Psychologie,  1852,  479. 

12  "Die  vorgestellte  Sonne  leuchtet  nicht  und  die  vorgestellte  Glut  ihrer  Tausende  von 
Waermegraden  waermt  nicht;  das  letzte  Fuenkchen  eines  verglimmerenden  Streichhoelz- 
chens  leistet  in  beiden  Beziehungen  weit  mehr."  H.  Ebbinghaus:  Grundzuege  der  Psy- 
chologie, J.,  1905,  549. 


348  SCHAUB 

Statements  as  strong  as  this  inevitably  raise  doubts;  it  seems  at  least 
possible  that  there  should  be  many  to  whom  the  memory  of  the  burning 
heat  of  the  summer  sun  would  convey  more  warmth  than  the  dying  glimmer 
of  a  match.  We  must  not  neglect,  however,  to  notice  those  passages  in 
which  Ebbinghaus  admits  that,  in  certain  cases,  images  may  have  a 
measure  of  intensity.  He  tells  us  that  there  are  circumstances  under  which 
the  intensity  of  an  image  may  be  increased  so  as  to  be  comparable  to  that 
of  the  weakest  sensation.^ 

Turning  from  the  German  psychologists,  we  find  that  Paulhan  speaks  of 
the  image  as  the  feeble  reproducton  of  a  perception,^  and  Rabier  states 
plainly  that  the  difTerence  between  sensation  and  image  is  one  of  degree  and 
not  of  nature.'  Sully  tells  us  that  '  'the  most  obvious  point  of  difference 
is  the  greater  intensity  of  the  sensational  or  presentative  element  in  the 
percept  which  gives  the  whole  structtue  its  peculiar  vividness  (or  strength)."* 
Baldwin  summarizes  the  general  positions  held  on  the  subject  as  follows: 
'  'On  the  one  hand  it  is  maintained  that  there  is  a  specific  difference  between 
presentations  and  their  revived  images;  a  difference  of  nature. 
Others  hold  that  between  primary  and  secondarj'-  states,  there  is  only  a 
difference  of  degree."^  He  proceeds  to  take  his  stand  with  the  latter 
group,  holding  that  presentations  and  representations  have  the  same  ante- 
cedents and  effects,  and  "we  are  aware  in  consciousness  of  no  peculiar 
marks  of  revived  states  by  which  to  distinguish  them  from  percepts  except 
that  they  are  prevailingly  of  less  intensity."^  So  far,  then,  there  is  agreement 
that  certain  images  either  lack  intensity  except  in  the  case  of  hallucinations 
(which  are  regarded  as  abnormal  phenomena),  or  at  least  have  but  a  small 
degree  of  intensity.  The  difference  between  images  and  sensations  is  re- 
garded as  one  of  intensity  or  strength,  not  of  nature  or  quality. 

Opposed  to  the  above  position  are  a  number  of  prominent  psychologists 
who  regard  nature  or  texture  as  the  more  important  differentia  of  images, 
emphasizing  the  fact  that  these  are  incomplete,  indistinct,  fleeting.  They 
admit  that  images  are  ordinarily  less  intense  than  sensations,  but  maintain 
that  this  is  not  universally  the  case.  Images,  for  these  writers,  have  a  marked 
degree  of  intensity;  indeed,  they  may  be  just  as  intense  as  sensations.  Of 
those  who  uphold  this  view  it  is  sufficient  to  mention  Wundt,  Kuelpe, 
Hoeffding,  Taine,  James,  and  Ladd.  Wundt  insists  that  while  images 
and  sense  perceptions  usually  differ  in  intensity,  it  is  the  difference  in  ele- 
mentary composition  that  is  all-important.^  Kuelpe  goes  into  the  matter 
at  greater  length.  While  admitting  that  images  are  usually  of  lesser  inten- 
sity, duration,  and  extension  than  perceptions,  he  nevertheless  insists  that 
'  'centrally  excited  sensations,  like  peripherally  excited,  must  be  accredited 
with  quality,  intensity,  and  a  temporal  and  spatial  character.  "^  In  tempo- 
ral and  spatial  determination  and  in  their  results,  centrally  and  peripher- 
ally excited  sensations,  we  are  told,  differ  widely.  The  position  of  Hoeff- 
ding with  regard  to  the  subject  is  clear.  He  says:  "There  is,  indeed,  as  a 
rule  a  difference  in  the  degree  of  strength  of  a  memory-image  and  a  percept ; 
but  this  difference  may  be  very  small,  and  may  even  quite  disappear."^ 
Taine  seems  to  confuse  intensity  with  clearness,  but  may  nevertheless  be 
classed  with  this  group.  "We  may  confidently  assert,  then,"  he  says, 
'  'that  the  internal  event  which  we  call  a  sensation  ...  is  reproduced 
in  us  without  impression  from  without — in  the  majority  of  cases  partially, 
feebly,  and  vaguely,  but  in  many  cases  with  greater  clearness  and  force. "^° 

^See  op.  cit.,  552. 

*F.  Paulhan:  I^'activit^  mentale,  1889,  106. 

^E.  Rabier:  Lemons  de  philosophie,  I.,  1896,  157. 

•♦J.Sully:  The  Human  Mind,  1892,  I.,  283;  Outlines  of  Psychology,  1891,  157. 

*  J.  M.  Baldwin:  Handbook  of  Psychology,  Senses  and  Intellect,  1890,  146-7, 

6  Op.  cit..  147. 

■^W.  Wundt:  Outlines  of  Psychology,  tr.  1901.  282. 

^O.  Kuelpe:  Outlines  of  Psychology,  tr.  1901,  182. 

^H.  Hoeffding:  Outlines  of  Psychology,  tr.  1891,  130. 

"^H.  Taine:  On  Intelligence,  tr.  1899,  I.,  40. 


ON  THE  INTENSITY  OF  IMAGES  349 

Ladd  and  James  discuss  our  subject  only  briefly.  The  former  tells  us  that 
the  image  often  lingers  persistently  in  consciousness  at  a  marked  degree  of 
intensity,  and  that  images  and  perceptions  differ  mainly  in  their  other 
characteristics.^  James  asserts  that  "the  difference  between  the  two  pro- 
cesses feels  like  one  of  kind  and  not  like  a  mere  'more'  or  'less'  of  the  same."^ 
Then  he  adds:  "The  subjective  difference  between  imagined  and  felt 
objects  is  less  absolute  than  has  been  claimed."^ 

As  a  third  group  we  must  mention  three  writers,  Stout,  Jodl,  and  Ziehen, 
who  hold  the  general  view  that  images  and  sensations  are  toto  genere  dif- 
ferent and  therefore  incomparable  things.  It  follows  as  a  corollary  that 
their  intensities  also  do  not  admit  of  comparison.  Stout  beUeves  that  images 
have  intensity,  but  that  this  differs  radically  from  the  intensity  that  we 
attribute  to  sensations.*  Sense  experience  for  Stout  has  an  aggressive 
character  which  is  essential  to  its  nature  and  not  merely  due  to  concomitant 
motor  or  organic  sensations.  The  image,  we  are  told,  may  be  just  as  bright 
and  loud  as  the  sensations,  but  it  lacks  the  element  of  aggressiveness  which 
alone  could  make  its  brightness  or  loudness  like  that  of  a  sense  perception. 
Jodl  insists  that  images  may  have  all  the  degrees  of  intensity  that  are  to  be 
found  among  sensations,  but  because  they  are  essentially  of  different  com- 
position, are  made  of  different  material,  we  can  never  compare  the  intensity 
of  an  image  with  that  of  a  sensation.  "Is  Oi  fortissimo  that  we  image  softer 
than  a  fortissimo  that  we  hear,  is  sunlight  that  we  perceive  brighter  than 
sunlight  that  we  image,  is  imaged  sugar  less  sweet  than  tasted  sugar?  Every 
attempt  to  answer  this  leads  to  absurdity. "^  Ziehen's  position  is  more 
difficult  to  define.  He  regards  the  nature  of  images  as  such  that  they  can 
have  no  intensity,  properly  speaking.  "It  is  not  a  difference  in  intensity 
between  the  idea  and  the  sensation,  but  above  all  a  qualitative  difference. 
The  sensual  vivacity,  characteristic  of  every  sensation,  does  not  belong 
at  all  to  the  idea,  not  even  in  a  diminished  intensity.  "^ 

It  is  difficult,  of  course,  in  any  grouping  of  writers,  to  avoid  a  certain 
amount  of  misplacement  and  complication,  since  point  of  view  and  general 
treatment  differ  widely.  We  find,  however,  as  has  just  been  shown,  three 
types  of  theories  regarding  the  intensity  of  images.  The  first  takes  as  its 
watch- word  the  phrase,  "Images  are  faint  copies  of  sensation;"  it  regards 
images  as  identical  with  sensations  in  quality  but  as  much  less  intense. 
The  second  holds  that  intensity  may  differ,  but  that  it  frequently  does  not ; 
the  textural  difference  is  all-important.  The  third  regards  difference  in 
nature  as  an  insuperable  obstacle  to  any  comparison  of  the  intensities  of 
image  and  sensation.  To  abstract  consideration  it  would  appear  that  the 
first  class  slurs  those  characteristic  differences  which  make  mind  the  rich 
and  interesting  thing  it  is,  and  that  the  third  class  so  overemphasizes  these 
differences  as  to  do  away  with  that  degree  of  unity  which  mind  seems  to 
possess.  Whether  or  not  the  view  of  the  second  class  mentioned  above 
IS  tenable  must  be  decided,  however,  not  by  a  priori  speculation  but  by 
experimental  investigation  alone. 

{b)    Experimental 

Thus  far  there  has  been  no  experimental  work  especially  directed  to  the 
question  of  the  intensity  of  images.  Mention  of  the  subject  has  been  made 
incidentally,  in  connection  with  the  discussion  of  other  problems.     It  will 

^G.  T.  Ladd:  Psychology,  Descriptive  and  Explanatory,  1894,  239,  241. 

'  W.  James:  The  Principles  of  Psychology,  1905,  70. 

^Op.  cit.,  72. 

*  G.  F.  Stout:  A  Manual  of  Psychology,  1899,  399. 

^"  1st  ein  Fortissimo  welches  wir  vorstellen  leiser  als  ein  Fortissimo  welches  wir  hoeren. 
ist  Sonnenlicht  das  wir  sehen  heller  als  Sonnenlicht  welches  wir  vorstellen;  vorgestellter 
Zucker  minder  siiss  als  geschmeckter?  jeder  Versuch  darauf  eine  Antwort  zu  finden. 
fuehrt  ins  Absurde."     F.  Jodl:  Lehrbuch  der  Psyckologie.  1903.  II..  92  f. 

*T.  Ziehen:  Introduction  to  Psychological  Psychology,  tr.  1893,  152. 


350  SCHAUB 

be  necessary  for  us  to  glance  only  at  the  results  that  refer  to  the  memory 
image. 

Experimental  investigations  of  memory  are  practically  confined  to  the 
last  fifteen  years.  Prior  to  this  time  we  have  only  the  introspective  record 
of  Galton,  who  remarks  that  a  remembered  object  is  to  him  quite  compara- 
ble to  the  real  object.  "I  feel  as  though  I  was  dazzled  when  recalling  the 
sun  to  my  mental  vision."^  Other  instances  also  are  given  in  which  the 
memory  image  appeared  to  be  as  bright  as  the  actual  scene.  The  investi- 
gation of  mental  imagery  by  Lay  in  1 898^  rests  on  the  questionary  method, 
and  its  results  ought  not  to  be  accepted  without  careful  criticism.  We 
find,  however,  a  record  of  images  of  considerable  intensity,  though  this 
fails  to  measure  up  to  the  intensity  of  corresponding  sensation.  Meakin' 
and  Moore^  worked  respectively  on  the  mutual  inhibition  and  on  the  control 
of  memory  images.  The  former  makes  no  mention  of  intensity,  and  Moore 
tells  us  only  that  an  image  may  be  vivid  for  a  period  of  five  minutes.  More 
to  our  purpose  are  the  experiments  of  Kuhlmann.  In  his  first  series,  he 
investigated  the  nature  of  imagery  in  the  recall  of  a  given  material;  he 
directed  his  subjects  to  recall,  aft'er  a  long  interval,  and  to  draw  certain 
meaningless  visual  forms.*  Two  types  of  images  were  found,  the  sponta- 
neous and  the  slowly  developing  image,  yet  these  in  their  completed  state 
differed  not  so  much  in  intensity  as  in  other  attributes.  Kuhlmann  tells  us 
that  "less  intensity  and  vividness  is  among  the  least  of  the  characteristics 
in  which  the  memory  differed  from  its  perceptive  experience."^  In  another 
article  this  author  states  that,  in  the  case  of  the  spontaneous  images,  '  'the 
words  would  ring  out  clear  and  intense"  and  "the  imagery  then  approached 
the  perceptive  quality  characteristic  of  all  vivid  recall."^  In  a  further 
study,  dealing  with  recognition,  Kuhlmann  says:  "We  have  ceased  to  be 
satisfied  with  the  conception  of  memory  as  reproduced  past  experience,  of 
images  as  faint  copies  of  original  perception.  We  may  regard  this  condi- 
tion as  a  good  index  of  the  state  of  our  progress."^  Gore,  in  an  article 
entitled  "Image  or  Sensation,"  entirely  rejects  intensive  difference  between 
images  and  sensations.  "Could  you  rule  out  the  ideational  or  perceptual 
setting,  your  image  would  leave  off  being  an  image.  It  would  become 
sensational  in  quality  and  value."'  H.  B.  Alexander  has  also  touched 
upon  our  problem,  but  gives  us  simply  a  record  of  personal  observation 
during  several  years.  He  finds  that  "with  reference  to  vividness,  three 
grades  of  intensities  are  to  be  discriminated."^"  His  description  of  the  three 
classes,  however,  betrays  a  confusion  between  intensity  and  clearness.  The 
first,  fleeting  images  of  common  thinking,  are  described  as  vague,  fragile, 
and  ephemeral;  the  second  as  small  and  watery,  but  growing  clearer  and 
assuming  color  under  attention;  the  images  of  the  third  class  are  life-sized, 
clear,  and  bright,  with  definite  background.  Memory  images,  he  says, 
are  often  more  vivid  than  after-images  or  than  dim  perceptions.  Slaughter"^ 
and  Murray^2  barely  mention  the  question  of  intensity,  both  laying  em- 
phasis upon  the  motor  and  kinaesthetic  elements  in  reproduction. 

iSir  F.  Galton:  Inquiries  into  Human  Faculty,  1883,  89  f. 

2W.  Lay:  Mental  Imagery,  1898. 

^F.  Meakin:  Mutual  Inhibition  of  Memory  Images,  Harv.  Psych.  Studies,  I,  1903,  244. 

*C.  S.  Moore:  Control  of  the  Memory  Image,  Harv.  Psych.  Studies,  I,  1903,  282. 

•^F.  Kuhlmann:  Analysis  of  the  Memory  Consciousness,  Psych.  Rev.,  XIII,  1906,  316. 

«  Op.  cit.,  342. 

^F.  Kuhlmann:  On  the  Analysis  of  Auditory  Memory  Consciousness,  Amer.  Jour. 
Psvch.,  XX.,  1909.  200. 

^F.  Kuhlmann:  Problems  in  Analysis  of  Memory  Consciousness,  J.  of  Phil.,  Psych., 
and  Sci.  Meth.,  IV,  1907,   1. 

9  W.  C.  Gore:  Image  or  Sensation?     J.  of  Ph.,  Psy.,  and  Sci.  Meth..  1,  1904.  437-8. 

i"H.  B.  Alexander:  Some  Observations  on  Visual  Imagery,  Psych.  Rev.,  XI,    1904.  320. 

^^  J.  W.  Slaughter:  A  Preliminary  Study  of  the  Behavior  of  Mental  Images,  Amer.  Jour. 
Psych.,  XIII,  1902. 

'*E.  Murray:  Peripheral  and  Central  Factors  in  Memory  Images  of  VisucU  Forms  and 
Color.  Amer.  Jour.  Psych.,  XVII.  1906. 


I 


ON   TH^   INTENSITY   OF   IMAGES  35 1 

The  studies  of  the  memory  image  made  by  Bentley^  and  Whipple,^  the 
one  dealing  with  vision  and  the  other  with  audition,  make  no  reference  to 
our  problem,  with  the  exception  of  Whipple's  statement  that  the  image, 
when  held,  decreases  rapidly  in  intensity.  Kennedy  gives  a  brief  summary 
of  the  results  thus  far  obtained  with  regard  to  judgments  of  intensity  in 
paired  memory  images.  "In  the  case  of  the  intensity  of  sound  we  find 
a  decrease  in  the  intensity  of  the  memory  image ;  in  the  case  of  light,  either 
a  decrease  or  increase  of  the  intensity  of  the  image  according  to  the  intensity 
of  the  object  itself ;  and  in  the  case  of  squares  and  of  pressure,  a  quantitative 
increase  in  the  image.  "^  The  general  light  thrown  upon  our  subject  by  the 
above  investigations,  then,  is  merely  an  indication  that  introspection  reveals 
intensity  as  an  attribute  of  images  and  that  this  intensity  has  various 
degrees.     The  need  for  further  and  more  definite  study  is  apparent. 

DiFFlCUIvTiES  AND  SOURCES  OF  ErROR 

The  study  of  imagery  is  subject  to  certain  difficulties  to 
which  we  ought  to  pay  regard  at  the  outset.  One  of  the  great- 
est of  these,  and  one  which  occurs  in  the  field  of  sensation  as 
well,  though  in  a  less  serious  form,  is  what  is  technically  known 
as  the  stimulus-error.  It  is  the  tendency  to  evaluate  sensa- 
tions and  images  in  terms  of  the  stimuli  which  produce  them, 
instead  of  in  terms  of  the  conscious  experience  itself;  the 
error  of  allowing  a  knowledge  of  the  objective  order  of  things 
to  bias  introspection.  Unless  this  error  is  avoided,  results 
become  practically  worthless.  In  our  experiments,  therefore, 
we  have  attempted  in  various  ways  to  eliminate  it.  The  two 
sounds  whose  images  were  to  be  compared  were  produced  by 
the  same  stimulus ;  there  was  no  difference  in  pitch  or  timbre, 
but  only  in  intensity.  Thus,  there  is  no  reason  why  reference 
to  the  stimulus  should  influence  judgment.  Moreover,  the 
actual  stimulus  was  not  seen  by  the  observers;  they  saw 
neither  the  force  of  the  stroke  upon  the  fork  nor  the  distance 
of  the  drop  of  the  sound-pendulum.  There  were  cases  in 
which  one  of  our  observers,  especially,  had  visual  images  of 
this  distance;  but  this  fact  could  not  be  regarded  as  evidence 
of  the  stimulus-error,  since  her  visual  imagery  was  avowedly 
based  upon  actually  experienced  (that  is,  heard)  intensities, 
and  not  upon  a  memory  or  perception  of  the  distance  of  the 
swinging  pendulum.  The  danger  of  the  stimulus-error  was 
further  reduced  by  the  fact  that  our  observers  were  merely 
instructed  to  compare  memory  images,  and  it  was  this  com- 
parison, and  never  that  of  the  sensations,  that  received  em- 
phasis throughout  the  entire  experiment.  The  judgments 
of  the  observers  were  thus  directed  a  step  farther  than  sensa- 
tion from  the  original  stimulus.     With  these  various  precau- 

1 1.  M.  Bentley:  The  Memory  Imagery  and  its  Qualitative  Fidelity,  Amer.  Jour.  Psych., 
XI,  1899. 

^G.  M.  Whipple:  An  Analytic  Study  of  the  Memory  Image  and  the  Process  of  Judgment 
in  the  Discrimination  of  Clangs  and  Tones,  Amer.  Jour.  Psych.,  XII,  1900-01. 

8  P.  Kennedy:  On  the  Experimental  Investigation  of  Memory,  Psych.  Rev.,  V,  1898.  493. 


352  SCHAUB 

tions  our  results  would  seem  to  be  practically,  if  not  entirely, 
free  from  stimulus-error. 

More  serious  even  than  the  danger  just  mentioned  is  that  of 
confusing  intensity  with  clearness.  With  respect  to  this 
Wundt  cautions  us  as  follows:  "We  must  be  especially  care- 
ful not  to  confuse  the  clearness  of  an  idea  with  its  intensity. 
That  is  simply  dependent  upon  the  sensations  which  consti- 
tute it.  The  intensity  of  perceptual  ideas  is  determined  by 
the  strength  of  the  sense  stimuli,  that  of  memorial  ideas  by 
other  conditions  which  have  nothing  to  do  with  ideational 
clearness.  At  the  same  time,  intensity  usually  promotes 
clearness  and  distinctness."^  By  clearness  we  mean  that 
sharpness  or  focal  distinctness  which  depends  upon,  or  is  iden- 
tical with,  the  degree  of  attention.  "As  applied  to  our  ideas, 
then,"  says  Wundt,  "clearness  and  distinctness  denote  prop- 
erties which  depend  directly  upon  the  activity  of  ideation."' 
Intensity,  in  the  psychological  sense,  is  the  strength  or  force 
of  a  sensation  or  image  in  consciousness.'  It  is  an  attribute 
of  a  sensation  or  image,  and,  if  not  absolutely,  is  at  least  rela- 
tively independent  of  the  attitude  of  the  observer,  even  if 
upon  further  investigation  it  should  develop  that  attention 
affects  intensity. 

Before  taking  up  our  experiments,  therefore,  it  was  neces- 
sary by  means  of  preliminary  experiments  so  to  familiarize 
our  observers  with  the  introspective  difference  between  clear- 
ness and  intensity  that  their  reports  should  be  free  from  any 
confusion  of  the  two.  In  these  preliminary  experiments,  two 
metronomes  of  different  intensities  were  allowed  to  beat,  and 
the  observers  were  instructed  to  perform  aloud  some  task, 
such  as  spelling,  reciting,  or  adding,  and  to  attend  now  to  the 
loud,  now  to  the  weak  metronome,  or  else  to  their  task.  After 
40  seconds  they  dictated  their  introspections.  The  results 
of  these  experiments  show  that  the  observers  were  able  to 
hold  the  weak  metronome  at  a  maximal  clearness  for  most  of 
the  time,  even  in  the  face  of  the  more  intense  metronome  and 
of  the  task  that  was  being  performed.  When  the  weak  metro- 
nome was  maximally  clear,  the  task  and  the  louder  metronome 
usually  alternated  in  the  background.  The  experiments  were 
then  repeated,  with  the  exception  that  the  task  was  now  per- 
formed in  terms  of  mental  imagery.  The  observer  was  told 
to  attend  to  one  of  the  metronomes  while  employing  visual 
imagery  in  counting,  spelling,  or  reciting,  having  auditory 
images  of  the  chimes  playing  a  familiar   air,  or  kinaesthetic 

^W.  Wundt:  Lectures  on  Human  and  Animal  Psychology,  tr.  1901,  247. 
^Op.  ciL,  246. 

^See  W.  H.  Sheldon:  Definitions  of  Intensity,  Jour,  of  Ph.,  Psy.,  and 
Sci.  Meth.,  I.,  1904,  233-237. 


ON  THE  INTENSITY  OF  IMAGES  353 

images  of  lifting  weights.  After  a  brief  practice  in  this,  the 
attention  of  the  observers  was  directed  to  the  task  instead 
of  to  the  metronome.  With  Httle  difficulty  they  were  able 
to  get  very  clear  images,  while  scarcely  hearing  at  all  either 
the  loud  or  the  weak  metronome.  In  the  next  and  final  group 
of  preliminary  experiments  only  one  metronome,  loud  or 
weak,  was  sounded,  the  observer  performing  a  task  aloud  and 
getting  an  auditory  image  of  the  other  metronome.  At  the 
beginning  of  each  experiment  the  metronome  to  be  recalled  in 
image  was  sounded  for  an  instant,  and  an  interval  was  allowed 
to  intervene  before  the  observers'  recall.  That  all  of  our 
observers  found  it  possible,  while  performing  mechanically 
some  task,  to  keep  clear  and  focal  the  image  of  a  weak  metro- 
nome and  yet  to  be  conscious  that  the  real  metronome  beating 
in  the  background  was  louder  than  the  image,  goes  to  show  that 
they  had  succeeded  in  sharply  distinguishing  intensity  from 
clearness.  Entirely  of  their  own  accord  the  observers  gave 
many  reports  of  "weak  metronome  clear,  loud  metronome 
vague  and  dim."  These  results,  added  to  the  fact  that  all  of 
our  observers  were  practised  in  introspection,  seemed  to 
warrant  us  in  proceeding  to  our  specific  study  regarding  the 
intensity  of  images  with  the  assurance  that  this  would  not 
be  confused  with  clearness. 

ExPERiMENTAiy  Procedure 

Our  experimental  investigation  of  the  problem  of  the  inten- 
sity of  images  was  confined  to  the  memory  image,  with  the 
exception  of  a  few  experiments  involving  the  image  of  imagina- 
tion. ^  The  memory  image  has  been  variously  defined.  For 
us,  however,  the  term  designates  that  experience  which  does 
not  come  to  us  through  external  sense  perception,  yet  repro- 
duces this  perception  to  consciousness  with  its  specific  tem- 
poral reference  in  such  a  way  as  to  be  clothed  with  recogni- 
tion. This,  then,  is  the  image  whose  intensity  we  endeavored 
to  investigate.  The  'mental  image'  or  general,  timeless  image 
was  left  entirely  out  of  account.^ 

Four  observers  took  part  in  these  experiments:  Dr.  Helen 
M.  Clarke  (C),  fellow  in  psychology;  Dr.  L.  R.  Geissler 
(G),  instructor;  Mr.  W.  S.  Foster  (F),  assistant;  and  Dr. 
T.  Okabe  (O),  scholar  in  psychology.  AH  of  these  observers 
had  had  an  exceptional  amount  of  training  and  practice  in 

^For  a  discussion  of  the  differences  between  images  of  memory  and 
of  imagination,  see  C.  W.  Perky:  Amer.  Jour,  of  Psych.,  XXI.,  1910, 
422-452. 

^See  Bentley:  The  Memory  Image  and  its  Qualitative  Fidelity,  Amer. 
Jour,  of  Psych.,  XI.,  1899,  27  note;  also  Slaughter:  A  Preliminary  Study 
of  the  Behavior  of  Mental  Images,  Amer.  Jour,  of  Psych.,  XIII.,  1902,  526. 


\ 


354  SCHAUB 

introspection.  Throughout  the  experiments  they  were  kept 
in  ignorance  of  the  purpose  of  our  investigation.  They  were 
asked  merely  to  reproduce  an  experience  in  memory,  and  to 
write  their  introspections  upon  the  event.  Since  these  intro- 
spections were  not  guided  by  suggestions  of  any  kind,  there 
were  numerous  instances  in  which  no  mention  whatever  was 
made  of  intensity.  The  fact  that  many  of  the  introspections 
failed  to  speak  of  intensity,  therefore,  does  not  militate  in 
any  way  against  our  conclusions. 

Our  experiments  fall  into  eight  series  as  follows : 

Series  i.  The  purpose  here  was  to  find  out  in  a  prelimi- 
nary way  whether  or  not  the  observers  spoke  of  intensity  and, 
if  so,  in  what  terms.  The  observer  was  seated  with  his  back 
to  a  table  three  meters  distant.  Upon  this  table  stood  a  tun- 
ing-fork on  a  resonance  box.  After  giving  a  'ready'  signal,  the 
experimenter  struck  the  fork  with  a  felt  hammer  and  allowed 
it  to  sound  for  one  second  before  damping.  After  an  interval 
of  half  a  second  the  fork  was  struck  again,  the  stroke  being 
either  markedly  louder  or  weaker  than,  or  approximately  equal 
to,  the  first  stroke.  Again  the  fork  was  allowed  to  sound  for  one 
second.  The  observer  was  told  to  wait  until  all  memory 
after-images  had  passed,  and  then  to  reproduce  the  whole 
experience  in  memory.  After  every  such  experience  he  care- 
fully recorded  his  introspections. 

Series  2.  In  order  to  secure  a  greater  uniformity  of  condi- 
tions, it  seemed  wise  to  control  the  length  of  the  interval  be- 
tween the  stimulus  and  the  image,  and  to  secure  a  check  upon 
the  nxemtal  operations  of  the  observer  during  this  time.  After 
a  number  of  trials  with  all  of  our  observers,  we  decided  upon 
20  seconds  as  the  shortest  interval  which  might  safely  be 
assumed  to  free  the  observer  from  the  effects  of  memory  after- 
images. The  above  experiments  were  then  repeated  with  the 
following  modifications:  After  giving  the  two  sounds,  a  20 
second  interval  was  allowed  to  pass.  These  intervals  were 
filled  alternately  by  allowing  the  observer's  attention  to  follow 
its  own  capricious  course  and  by  directing  it  into  certain 
channels  through  the  following  means:  noise,  either  voice  or 
metronome;  tone,  either  tone  variator  or  harmonical;  or 
vision,  either  colors  or  pictures.  In  this  manner  we  attempted 
to  avoid  the  danger  of  having  the  image  affected  by  special 
or  persistent  characteristics  of  the  experiences  that  might 
fill  up  the  interval  before  recall. 

Series  3.  Having  tried  the  shortest  possible  interval  after 
the  cessation  of  memory  after-images,  we  next  undertook  a 
brief  series  of  experiments  with  a  decidedly  longer  interval, 
in  order  to  see  if  the  length  of  the  interval  had  any  effect  upon 
intensity.     The  method  of  Series  2  was  repeated  in  all  details, 


ON   THE   INTENSITY   OF   IMAGES  355 

except  that  the  20  second  interval  was  lengthened  to  one 
minute. 

Series  4.  Even  at  this  point  it  was  clear  that  our  observers 
ascribed  intensity  to  the  image,  and  that  this  imaginal  inten- 
sity had  many  different  degrees.  The  question  then  arose  in 
how  far  these  various  degrees  were  comparable  with  those  of 
the  sensational  scale.  In  attempting  the  answer,  we  pro- 
duced sensations  both  noticeably  and  just  noticeably  different^ 
in  intensity,  determining  in  each  case,  of  course,  just  what  this 
difference  should  be.  Some  objective  scale  of  stimulus  inten- 
sities thus  became  necessary.  Instead  of  the  tuning-fork, 
therefore,  we  resorted  to  the  sound-pendulum.  Series  of 
four  just  noticeably  different  strokes — on  the  pendulum  scale, 
for  instance,  20°,  32°,  40°,  55° — were  given  both  ascending 
and  descending;  also  a  series  of  three  strokes  noticeably  dif- 
ferent-^20°,  45°,  75° — in  ascending  and  descending  order; 
and  a  series  of  two  just  noticeably  different  strokes — for  in- 
stance, 32°,  40° — ascending  and  descending.  Bach  of  these  six 
stimulus  series  was  repeated  four  times  in  all  without  definite 
or  consecutive  order.  At  the  fourth  or  final  trial  of  each  series 
the  stimulus  was  given  while  the  observer  had  his  memory 
image,  in  order  thus  to  get  some  control  or  check  upon  the  ab- 
solute intensity  of  the  image.  It  seemed  best  in  these  experi- 
ments to  lengthen  the  interval  between  the  stimulus  and  the 
getting  of  memory  images  from  20  to  30  seconds,  because 
of  the  slightly  longer  duration  of  the  memory  after-images  in 
the  case  of  the  four-stroke  series.  From  the  three  observers 
who  gave  their  results  on  auditory  imagery  we  thus  obtained 
seventy-two  introspections.  G's  auditory  imagery  having 
shown  itself  to  be  very  meagre,  the  above  experiments  were 
carried  out  in  his  case  with  weights  as  stimuli  instead  of 
sounds,  the  procedure  in  all  other  respects  being  analogous  to 
the  above. 

Series  5.  In  this  series  we  again  used  noticeable  and  just 
noticeable  differences,  but  changed  the  preceding  conditions 
in  the  two  following  ways:  (a)  Only  pairs  of  strokes  were 
used ;  and  (b)  the  interval  preceding  recall  was  now  of  various 
lengths — not  only  30  seconds  as  before,  but  also  60  and  120 
seconds.  As  to  the  direction  of  the  observer's  attention 
during  the  interval,  the  procedure  of  the  former  series  was 

^The  'just  noticeable  difference'  of  this  paper  is  not  the  ordinary  differ- 
ential limen  of  the  psychophysical  methods,  but  a  difference  such  as 
would  be  recognized  by  the  observer  in  at  least  90  of  100  consecutive  trials. 
In  other  words,  it  is  a  Fechnerian  just  noticeable  difference,  the  least  differ- 
ence that  an  observer  can  'carry  in  his  head,'  the  just  noticeable  difference 
of  Ebbinghaus'  first  form  of  the  method  of  that  name.  This  difference 
was  carefully  determined,  for  each  observer,  at  the  beginning  of  our  experi- 
ments, and  was  tested,  less  accurately,  at  intervals  during  their  progress. 


356  SCHAUB 

not  changed.  It  should  be  mentioned  that  at  various  times 
throughout  the  course  of  this  series  the  stimulus  was  repeated 
for  the  purpose  of  comparison  with  the  observer's  image. 
For  observer  G  the  stimuli  were  again  lifted  weights. 

Series  6.  Observations  were  now  made  on  images  of  imag- 
ination instead  of  upon  memory  images.  At  the  beginning 
of  every  sitting  the  experimenter  sounded  on  the  pendulum 
a  stroke  of  moderate  intensity,  40°  on  the  scale.  After  this 
sound,  five  minutes  were  allowed  to  pass  in  general  conversa- 
tion, and  then  the  observer  was  asked  to  imagine,  according 
to  the  direction  of  the  experimenter,  certain  pairs  of  strokes. 
These  pairs  were  both  ascending  and  descending  in  order, 
now  noticeably  different,  now  just  noticeably  diifferent  in  the 
centre  of  the  scale,  now  just  noticeably  at  the  loud  end  of  the 
scale,  and  now  just  noticeably  different  at  the  weak  end.  The 
observer  signalled  the  appearance  of  the  image,  and  the  experi- 
menter immediately  sounded  two  strokes  such  as  the  ob- 
server had  been  told  to  imagine.  The  latter  thereupon 
reported  how  his  images  compared  in  intensity  with  the 
strokes  just  sounded.  In  the  cases  of  a  failure  of  correspond- 
ence, the  experimenter  continued  giving  other  pairs  of  strokes 
until  the  observer  said  "My  images  were  like  those."  This 
usually  took  only  one  or  two  trials — too  few  for  the  observer's 
image  to  fade  in  the  meantime.  The  method,  though  not  free 
from  error,  was  accurate  enough  to  show  us  the  nature  of  just 
noticeable  differences  and  noticeable  differences  in  the  image, 
as  compared  with  those  on  the  scale  of  sensory  intensities. 

Series  y.  A  series  of  experiments  was  now  performed  in 
order  to  investigate  the  minimal  and  maximal  limits  of  imaginal 
intensity.  Both  very  loud  and  very  weak  sounds  were  given 
on  the  gravity  phonometer  as  well  as  on  the  sound-pendulum. 
After  a  30  second  interval,  the  observer  was  asked  to  reproduce 
the  sound  in  image. 

Series  8.  In  order  to  compare  our  results  in  the  field  of 
auditory  imagery  with  those  which  might  be  obtained  in  other 
fields,  we  instituted  a  series  of  tests  on  brightnesses.  The 
brightness-discrimination  box  was  used,  an  apparatus  which 
enables  the  observer  to  see  simultaneously  two  brightnesses 
side  by  side.  The  brightness  of  both  openings,  or  of  either 
one  singly,  could  be  regulated  at  will  and  determined  by  a  scale 
on  the  box.^  The  observer  sat  directly  in  front  of  the  centre 
of  the  box  in  a  dark  room  and  after  a  period  of  adaptation 
two  brightnesses,  either  noticeably  or  just  noticeably  different, 
were  shown.     He  then  waited  until  all  after-images  had  dis- 

^For  a  fuller  description  of  this  apparatus,  see  G.  M.  Whipple:  Man- 
ual of  Mental  and  Physical  Tests,  1910,  163. 


r  ON  THE  INTENSITY  OF  IMAGKS  357 

appeared,  and  recalled  the  experience  in  a  memory  image, 
dictating  his  introspections  to  the  experimenter. 

The  results  of  the  above  experiments  seemed  sufficient  to 
warrant  conclusions  regarding  the  intensity  of  auditory  mem- 
ory images,  and  to  tell  us  something  also  regarding  visual  and 
kinesthetic  memory  images. 

RESUI.TS 

I.     Intensity,     (a)      Ascription  of  intensity  to  images 

The  first  part  of  our  problem  was  to  determine  whether  or 
not  the  image  possessed  intensity.  For  the  answer  to  this 
question  we  may  simply  turn  to  the  introspections  that  were 
given.  As  has  been  mentioned  above,  our  observers  were  not 
aware  of  the  object  or  purpose  of  the  experiments, — they  did 
not  know  that  our  concern  was  with  intensity  at  all.  Their 
very  frequent  references  to  intensity,  as  an  attribute  of  images, 
are  therefore  the  more  significant  since  there  was  absolutely 
no  ground  for  supposing  that  they  were  reporting  anything 
other  than  that  which  introspection  actually  revealed  to  them. 
Only  a  very  few  of  the  statements  regarding  this  subject  may 
be  quoted  here.  They  are  selected  at  random  and  may  be 
regarded  as  typical. 

Series  i.  Observer  C.  '  'Very  clear  auditory  images,  like  the  sensations  in 
pitch,  intensity,  and  time-interval."  "Purely  auditory  images  like  the 
sensations  in  intensity."  "Good  images  like  the  heard  tones  in  pitch  and 
intensity."  "Intensity  of  the  images  a  little  weaker  than  that  of  the  sen- 
sations." 

Series  J.  Observer  F.  "I  think  the  images  are  very  accurate  copies  of  the 
sensations  both  as  to  quality  and  intensity."  "Good  images  with  intensi- 
ties about  like  that  of  sensations."  "The  images  were  not  quite  so  dear 
as   in   sensation." 

Series  6.  Observer  O.  '  'Images  just  exactly  like  sensations  in  loudness. 
The  sensations  and  images  differ  in  quality  so  that  unless  there  were  an 
element  common  to  both  I  could  not  compare  them  without  making  an 
arbitrary  standard.  I  do  not  do  this  but  compare  them  by  their  intensi- 
ties ;  therefore  I  know  that  intensity  is  the  common  element,  although  they 
differ  in  every  other  way,  force,  liveliness,  purity,  etc."  '  'Got  good  images 
but  the  first  was  a  little  too  strong.  The  second  was  just  like  the  sensa- 
tion in  intensity." 

Series  4.  Observer  G  (lifted  weights).  "In  the  image  the  second  was 
distinctly  more  intense."     "Images  like  the  sensations  in  intensity."  ^ 

Series  2.  Observer  F.  '  'I  think  the  images  are  very  accurate  copies  of 
the  sensations  as  to  intensity."  "Intensities  of  images  about  correct." 
"Loud  image  good  and  like  the  sensation  in  intensity,  weak  image  not 
clear  this  time  and  a  little  too  loud." 

Thus,  our  observers  spontaneously  attributed  intensity  to 
the  image,  and  this  occurred  in  by  far  the  greater  number  of  our 
experiments. 

The  question  naturally  arises,  in  this  connection,  whether 
the  images  induced  under  experimental  conditions  are  the 
3— Journal 


L 


358 


SCHAUB 


same  as  "the  normal  waking  images  of  every-day  life."^  This 
query  occurred  to  Slaughter,  and  he  tells  us  that  it  is  impossible 
to  answer  it.  It  is,  however,  merely  the  old  question  of  the 
value  of  experimental  introspection,  recurring  in  special  form, 
and  as  such  is  possible  to  answer.  All  of  our  observers  re- 
garded the  images  evoked  in  the  laboratory  as  like  their  ordi- 
nary images,  with  the  possible  exception  of  G.  This  observer 
had  very  poor  auditory  images,  and  reported  them  as  being 
so  weak  as  almost  to  lack  intensity  altogether,  although,  as  he 
said,  his  ordinary,  normal  auditory  images,  while  they  are  usu- 
ally vague,  often  have  a  marked  degree  of  intensity.  Such 
statements  did  not  occur  in  the  case  of  our  other  observers,  nor 
with  G  in  the  field  of  kinsesthesis.  It  may  be  questioned 
whether  the  meagre  auditory  images  which  G  had  in  the 
laboratory  were  really  memory  images  at  all,  for  he  tells  us 
that  in  numerous  cases  "the  images  involve  no  reference  to  the 
previous  sensations;  they  occur  as  independent  conscious 
events." 

(b)     Varying  degrees  of  imaginal  intensity 

The  following  results  furnish  the  answer,  in  par£  at  least, 
to  the  second  portion  of  our  problem,  the  question.  Can  the 
intensities  of  images  be  compared  with  sensational  intensities, 
and  to  what  extent?  The  results  of  the  different  series,  so  far 
as  they  bear  upon  the  varying  degrees  of  imaginal  intensity, 
may  conveniently  be  thrown  into  the  form  of  Tables.     Con- 

Tablb  I 

Series  i:    Tuning-fork  struck  at  two  noticeably  different  intensities; 
no  definite  interval  before  recall. 


Obs. 

Exp'ts  made 

Absolute 
imag.  int. 
mentioned 

Imaginal  •= 

sensational 

intensity 

Both  images 
weaker 

2nd  im.  weaker 
or  stronger 
than  first 

C 

33 

II 

9 

2 

F 

29 

13 

12 

I 

O 

32 

18 

6 

12 

cerning  the  judgments  in  this  series  (column  4)  and  in  all 
following  series  under  the  rubric  'both  images  weaker,'  it  is 
important  to  mention  that  our  observers  also  reported  that 
the  difference  in  intensity  between  the  images  was  the  same  as 
the  intensive  difference  between  the  sensations.     Thus,   C 


^Cf.  Slaughter:  A  Preliminary  Study  of  the  Behavior  of  Mental  Images, 
Amer.  Jour.  Psych.,  XVIII.,  1902,  548. 


ON   THE   INTENSITY   O^   IMAGES 


359 


reports :  "The  auditory  images  were  like  the  sounds  in  relative 
intensity,  but  both  images  were  a  little  less  intense  than  the 
corresponding  sensations;"  "both  images  weaker,  but  like 
the  sounds  in  difference  of  intensity."  The  following  state- 
ment of  F  is  to  the  same  effect :  "  Both  images  weaker  than  cor- 
respondin-g  sensations  .  .  .  intensive  difference  between  images 
like  that  between  the  sensations."  O,  indeed,  gave  two  judg- 
ments reporting  the  difference  in  intensity  as  greater  in  image 
than  in  sensation.  "The  difference  in  loudness  between  the 
two  images  seemed  greater  than  in  sensation, — it  seemed  too 
great;"  "the  images  were  pure  and  simple  and  the  difference 
in  loudness  seemed  too  great." 

The  experiments  with  G  are  not  recorded  in  the  Tables 
because  his  auditory  imagery  was,  as  a  rule,  too  poor  to  admit 
of  full  introspective  accounts.  We  give  three  of  his  most  defi- 
nite introspections:  "I  get  no  intensive  difference  between 
the  images,  although  it  was  plain  enough  in  the  sensations;" 
"there  seemed  to  be  no  difference  in  intensity  between  the 
images;"  "the  intensive  difference  between  the  two  sensa- 
tions was  marked,  but  the  only  difference  between  the  images 
is  a  stronger  breathing  accompanying  the  image  which  cor- 
responds to  the  louder  sensations." 

Tabls  II 
Series  2:    Fork  struck  at  two  n.  d.  intensities;  before  recall  a  20  sec. 
interval  either  left  for  O  to  fill  or  filled  by  E  with  noise,  tone, 
or  visual  stimuli. 


Obs. 

Exp'ts 
made 

Absolute 
imag.  int. 
mentioned 

Im.=Tsens. 
intensity 

One  im. 
correct 

Bothim. 
weaker 

Both  dif- 
ferent in  int 

C 

24 

12 

8 

4 

F 

24 

7 

3 

2 

2 

0 

24 

8 

2 

3 

^ 

2 

The  reports  of  columns  5,  like  the  corresponding  reports  of 
Series  i,  include  also  the  judgments  that  the  difference  in 
imaginal  intensity  was  the  same  as  that  between  the  intensities 
of  the  sensations.  Besides  the  above,  F  and  O  reported  four 
and  ten  times  respectively  that  the  difference  in  the  intensity 
of  the  images  was  the  same  as  the  difference  between  the 
sensations,  without,  however,  making  mention  of  absolute 
intensity. 

Nearly  all  of  G's  images  came  in  kinaesthetic  instead  of  in 
auditory  terms.  As  regards  the  direction  of  the  observer's 
attention  during  the  interval,  we  find  that,  in  all  but  two  of 
the  cases  in  which  the  intensity  of  the  images  was  like  that  of 


36o 


SCHAUB 


the  sensations,  this  occurred  when  O's  attention  was  allowed 
free  play.  The  two  exceptions  were  reported  by  O  and  oc- 
curred when  the  interval  was  filled  by  E's  reading  nonsense 
syllables. 

Tabls  III 

Series  j:  Series  2  repeated  with  one  minute  interval  before  recall  instead 
of  20  sec.  interval. 


Obs. 

Exp'ts  made 

Absolute 
imag.  int. 
mentioned 

Imag.  =  sens, 
intensity 

Oneim. 
correct 

Both  images 
weaker 

C 

10 

5 

4 

I 

F 

10 

5 

3 

2 

0 

10 

4 

I 

3 

C  here  reported  two  cases  in  which  the  difference  between 
the  images  was  like  that  between  the  sensations,  but  she 
failed  to  make  any  statement  regarding  their  absolute  in- 
tensity. There  is  no  evidence  in  the  results  of  this  series  that 
the  filling  of  the  interval  affected  the  images,  except  O's  state- 
ment that  his  images  are  easier  to  get  after  an  'empty*  interval, 
i.  e.,  an  interval  in  which  attention  was  allowed  to  follow  its 
own  course.  In  two  cases  F  mentions  that  his  image  seems 
to  be  a  'general'  image  rather  than  a  memory  image,  and  in 
his  final  introspection  he  states  it  as  his  belief  that  the  same 
thing  was  true  in  a  number  of  cases.  In  this  series  of  experi- 
ments, G  was  able  to  report  two  cases  in  which  imaginal 
intensity  was  like  that  of  sensation  The  results  of  this  series, 
it  will  be  noticed,  agree  in  general  with  those  of  the  above 
series. 

Table  IV 

Series  4:  Sound-pendulum;  six  series  consisting  of  2  j.  n.  d.  strokes,  4  j.  n 

d.  strokes,  and  3  n.  d.  strokes,  in  ascending  and  descending  orders. 

Interval  of  30  sec.  (filled  or  empty)  before  recall. 


Obs. 

Exp'ts  made 

Absolute 
imag.  inten. 
mentioned 

Imaginal  = 

sensational 

intensity 

Both  images 
weaker 

C 

27 

6 

6 

F 

26 

8 

4 

4 

0 

25 

3 

3 

Besides  the  seven  cases  (in  column  4)  in  which  both  images 
were  weaker  but  the  intensive  difference  between  them  was 
the  same  as  that  between   the  sensations,  C  reported  two 


ON  run   INTENSITY  OF  IMAGES 


361 


cases  of  correct  difference  without  mentioning  absolute  inten- 
sity. There  seems  to  be  no  regularity  as  to  which  series 
is  most  often  reproduced  correctly  in  image. 

This  set  of  experiments,  however,  brought  out  an  interest- 
ing fact  in  connection  with  images  of  noticeable  and  just 
noticeable' differences.  F  reported  four  cases  in  which  a  just 
noticeable  difference  was  increased  in  image,  and  two  in  which 
such  a  difference  seemed  to  grow  even  smaller;  in  the  case  of 
noticeable  differences,  three  introspections  tell  us  that  the 
difference  is  lessened  in  the  image.  The  following  record  of 
F's  reports  makes  this  point  clear: 

Stimulus  2  j.  n.  d.  sounds.  "1  think  that  the  difference  between  the  two 
intensities  in  the  image  was  greater  than  that  between  the  two  sensations;" 
'  'the  difference  in  the  intensity  of  the  two  was  greater  in  image  than  in 
sensation;"  "good  auditory  image  of  first  sound  with  intensity  like  that  of 
sensation,  but  the  second  image  had  greater  intensity  than  the  second  sen- 
sation had."  Stimulus  4J.  n.  d.  sounds.  "1  think  the  weakest  image  was 
too  strong  and  the  strongest  too  weak."  Stimulus  j  n.  d.  sounds.  "There 
was  less  difference  of  intensity  in  the  series  of  images  than  in  sensation;" 
"loudest  image  not  loud  enough  and  weakest  too  loud;"  "loudest  image  not 
loud  enough  and  weakest  too  strong." 

Both  F  and  C  mentioned  cases  in  which  a  j.  n.  d.  was  elimi- 
nated and  the  two  sounded  equal  in  image : 

F.  Stimulus  2  j.  n.  d.  sounds.  "Images  of  equal  intensity;"  "sounds 
alike  in  intensity  in  image." 

C.  Stimulus  2.j.  n.  d.  sounds.  "Auditory  images  of  the  same  intensity;' 
"both  images  were  equally  intense." 

Table  V 

Series  5.     Pairs  of  j.  n.  d.  and  n.  d.  strokes;  interval  of  30  sec,  60  sec, 
or  120  sec  (filled  or  empty)  before  recall. 


Obs. 

Exp'ts  made 

Absolute 
imag.  in  ten. 
mentioned 

Imaginal  

sensational 
intensity 

Both   images 
weaker 

c 

18 

3 

i(n.d.  60  sec) 

(120  sec) 
(  30  sec.) 

F 

21 

6 

(j.  n.  d.  30) 
(j.  n.  d.  30) 
^  (n.  d.6osec.) 
(n.  d.6o  sec.) 

2   (60  sec) 

0 

20 

4 

(j.  n.  d.  30) 
3  (j.  n.  d.  60) 
(j.  n.  d.  120) 

I  (30  sec) 

For  the  sake  of  uniformity  in  the  Tables,  we  have  arranged 
the  results  of  this  series  also  with  reference  to  absolute 
intensity.  The  series  was  undertaken,  however,  primarily  in 
order  to  observe  the  effect  of  different  time-intervals  upon  the 
noticeable  and  just  noticeable  differences.  Our  results  with 
regard  to  this  point  follow. 


362  SCHAUB 

Just  noticeable  difference  too  great  in  image:  C,  i  case  (120  sec);  F, 
2  cases  (120  sec);  O,  3  cases  (30  sec,  60  sec,  120  sec).  Just  noticeable 
difference  noticeable  in  image  (images  equal);  C,  i  case  (60  sec);  O,  2  cases 
(120  sec).  Noticeable  difference  too  small  in  image:  C,  i  case  (120  sec); 
F,  2  cases  (120  sec);  O,  4  cases  (30,  60,  120,  120  sec).  Thirty-one  tests 
with  lifted  weights  were  made  with  G,  with  the  following  results :  5  mentions 
made  of  absolute  intensity;  3  cases  in  which  a  just  noticeable  difference 
was  too  great  in  image  (60  sec,  120  sec,  120  sec);  8  cases  in  which  a 
noticeable  difference  was  too  small  in  image  (either  60  sec.  or  120  sec). 

The  fact  that  in  many  cases  the  just  noticeable  differences 
are  greater  and  the  noticeable  differences  less  in  the  image 
suggests  Leuba's  hypothesis  with  regard  to  the  intensity  of 
the  single  image.  "There  seems  to  be  a  natural  tendency 
in  us  to  shift  the  sensations  held  in  memory  towards  the 
middle  of  the  scale  of  intensities.  It  might  be  conceived  to 
operate  somewhat  as  follows.  The  image  of  a  recent  sensa- 
tion tends  to  recall  by  association  the  united  residual  of  all 
past  sensations  of  the  same  kind."^  As  far  as  absolute  inten- 
sity goes, — and  it  is  to  this  that  the  quotation  refers, — we  have 
found  in  our  experiments  no  traces  of  such  a  tendency.  Our 
results,  however,  show  that  at  times  the  relative  intensity  or  dif- 
ference in  intensity  between  two  images  does  seem  to  approach 
a  mean,  the  just  noticeable  differences  increasing,  and  the  notice- 
able differences  decreasing,  in  imagery.  A  closer  study  of  our 
results  shows  that  this  change  occurred  almost  entirely  after  the 
long  intervals.  Thus  we  can  regard  it  as  one  of  the  effects  of 
time  upon  the  two  images,  rather  than  as  a  general  character- 
istic of  all  pairs  of  images.  F  reported  that  after  the  longer 
intervals  he  was  conscious  of  getting  not  a  real  memory  image 
but  a  sort  of  'general'  image,  referring  to  no  sensations  in 
particular.  His  reports  in  the  case  of  the  one  minute  interval 
of  Series  3  are  in  harmony  with  his  observation  in  this  series. 
From  his  introspections  we  gather  that  this  'general'  image, 
probably  the  'mental  image'  of  psychologists,  is  usually  of 
moderate  intensity.  We  quote  one  report:  " Relaxation  at 
the  tone  which  was  of  moderate  intensity.  I  reproduced  a 
'general'  experience  and  not  the  particular  one  this  time.  I 
feel  that  this  is  what  I  have  been  doing  usually  after  the  long 
interval." 

Leuba's  reference  to  the  "residual  of  all  past  sensations" 
indicates  that  he  refers  to  this  timeless  mental  image  and  not 
to  the  specific  memory  image.  We  must  not,  however,  be  un- 
derstood to  mean  that  in  every  case  in  which  our  observers  had 
an  increase  in  image  of  what  was  a  small  intensive  difference 
for  sensation,  or  a  decrease  in  image  of  the  intensive  difference 
of  a  markedly  large  sensory* step,  they  did  not  get  memory 
images  at  all.     In  a  number  of  such  cases  the  introspections 

^J.  H.  Leuba:  A  New  Instrument  for  Weber's  Law,  Amer.  Jour.  Psych., 
v.,  1892-93,  382  f. 


ON   run   INTENSITY   OF   IMAGES  363 

tell  US  that  the  one  of  the  images  was  like  the  sensation  in 
intensity,  while  the  other  was  either  too  weak  or  too  strong  as 
the  case  might  be;  and  this  change  in  the  one  of  the  images 
may  be  accounted  for  in  numerous  ways.  We  regard  as 
'general'  or  'mental'  images  only  those  few  in  which  the  dif- 
ference in  intensity  was  changed  by  the  weakening  or  strength- 
ening of  both  th'e  images,  and  the  images  were  thus  brought  to 
a  moderate  or  medium  degree  of  intensity.  For  our  observers, 
such  images  occurred  relatively  frequently  when  there  was 
an  interval  of  one  minute  or  more  between  the  giving  of  the 
sensation  and  its  recall  in  image. 

Series  6:  Moderate  stroke  given ;  pause  of  five  minutes ;  imaginary  images 

called  up  by  O  according  to  E's  directions,  either  j.  n.  d.  or  n.  d,, 

ascending  or  descending,  on  loud,  weak,  or  medium  part  of  scale. 

A  Table  here  would  only  complicate  matters,  since  we  are 
dealing  with  images  of  imagination,  and  also  since  the  matter 
of  absolute  intensity  is  a  side-issue,  the  important  thing  being 
the  noticeable  or  just  noticeable  differences.  We  found, 
however,  that  in  numerous  cases  the  observer's  pair  of  images 
corresponded  exactly  with  the  first  pair  of  strokes  later  given 
by  the  experimenter.  Of  these  cases  O  reports  four;  F,  six; 
and  C,  six;  with  O  the  cases  occurred  with  just  noticeable 
differences  on  the  strong  end  of  the  scale;  with  F  and  C  they 
occurred  with  weak  just  noticeable  differences,  and  a  few  with 
noticeable  differences.  The  introspections  of  our  observers 
corroborate  the  results  which  we  tabulated  in  the  course  of  the 
series.  O  tells  us:  "It  is  much  harder  to  get  just  noticeable 
differences  when  both  are  weak;"  "easiest  to  imagine  strong 
just  noticeable  differences."  C:  "Weak  images  are  more 
likely  to  be  like  the  sounds  than  the  strong  ones  are;"  "very 
hard  and  unpleasant  to  try  to  get  strong  images."  F:  "Weak 
images  are  easier  to  get." 

Further  results  regarding  noticeable  and  just  noticeable 
differences  are  as  follows:  Out  of  sixteen  tests,  O  reported 
six  cases  in  which  that  which  he  supposed  to  be  a  just  noticeable 
difference  in  his  imaginative  image  proved,  on  comparison 
with  a  just  noticeable  difference  between  sensations,  to  be 
greater  than  this.  Out  of  twelve  tests,  observer  F  reported 
I  case  in  which  an  imagined  just  noticeable  difference  proved 
to  be  too  great,  and  three  cases  where  an  imagined  noticeable 
difference  proved  to  be  too  small,  when  compared  with  the 
corresponding  differences  in  sensation.  Out  of  twenty  tests, 
C  reported  four  cases  of  just  noticeable  difference  too  great, 
and  two  of  noticeable  difference'  too  small,  in  the  image  of 
imagination.  This  seems  to  indicate  that,  while  we  can  image 
in  imagination  both  large  and  small  intensive  differences,  there 
is  a  slight  tendency  for  these  differences  to  approach  a  type  or 


364 


SCHAUB 


mean.     In  so  far,  then,  their  behavior  resembles  that  of  the 
'mental  image'  mentioned  above. 

This  result  leads  us  to  a  series  of  experiments  concerned  with 
the  limits  of  the  intensive  scale  in  imagery. 

Series  7:  Loud  or  weak  sounds   given  on  sound-pendulum  or  gravity 
phonometer ;  O  told    to    reproduce    in    imagery. 

The  results  here  merely  show  that  for  observers  C  and  O  there 
were  apparently  no  limits  to  the  intensive  scale  of  images. 
There  was  no  sensation,  however  weak  or  strong,  of  which  they 
were  not  able  to  get  an  adequately  intensive  men^ory  image. 
A  few  of  the  introspections  follow. 

O.  Fall  of  I  meter  on  phonometer.  '  'Intensity  in  the  image,  taken  by  itself, 
could  not  be  distinguished  from  that  of  the  stimulus, — the  only  difference 
was  in  thinness." 

4°  on  sound-pendulum.     "Good  image  just  like  sensation  in  loudness." 

C.  One  meter  on  phonometer.  "Image  thin  with  less  body  than  sensa- 
tion, but  intensity  just  the  same." 

80°  on  sound-pendulum..  "Got  good  image  just  like  it."  Stimulus  was 
repeated  and  C  said,  "yes,  my  image  was  just  as  intense  as  that  sound." 

4*^  on  sound-pendulum.     "Image  just  like  that  in  intensity." 

F  could  get  very  weak  images,  but  he  was  unable  to  call  to 
mind  any  that  were  louder  than  a  fall  of  75°  on  the  pendulum 
or  85  cm.  on  the  phonometer. 


Series  8: 


Table  VI 
Pairs  of  brightnesses; 


recall  in  imagery. 


Obs. 

Exp'ts 
made 

Absolute 
intensity 
mentioned 

Im.=sens. 
intensity 

Im.  of  dark 
stimulus 
too  light 

Im.  of  light 
stimulus 
too  dark 

Bothim. 
too  dark 

C 

23 

19 

18 

I 

F 

22 

13 

6 

3 

4 

0 

II 

3 

2 

I 

There  were  two  cases  for  each  observer  in  which  absolute 
intensity  was  not  mentioned,  but  the  difference  in  intensity 
between  the  images  was  reported  as  being  like  that  between 
the  sensations.  There  were  also  five  cases  for  O  and  one  for  F 
where  a  small  difference  was  imaged  as  greater,  and  one  for  O 
and  four  for  F  where  a  large  difference  was  imaged  as  smaller 
than  in  sensation.  C  is  of  a  markedly  visual  type,  which 
fact  probably  accounts  for  the  large  proportion  of  her  accurate 
images.  In  the  field  of  vision,  then,  our  results  parallel  those 
obtained  in  audition  and  kinaesthesis. 

2.     Non-intensive  Differences  between  Sensation  and  Image 
In  the  comparison  of  images  with  sensations,  several  facts 
of  interest  were  brought  out  besides  those  immediately  con- 


ON   THE    INTENSITY   OF   IMAGES 


365 


nected  with  our  main  problem.  The  results  above  described 
with  reference  to  intensity  show,  as  we  have  seen,  that  it  is  not 
here  that  the  distinguishing  mark  between  images  and  sensa- 
tions is  to  be  found.  For  our  observers,  as  we  shall  see,  this 
difference  lay  in  other  characters  of  the  two  experiences.  They 
all  repeatedly  emphasized  the  incompleteness^  of  the  image  as 
compared  with  sensation  and  found  here  the  main  point  of 
differentiation.  Indirectly,  then,  we  find  in  these  statements 
a  verification  of  our  conclusions. 

The  introspections  regarding  this  point  are  so  numerous 
that  only  a  few  can  here  be  given.  They  are  chosen  at  random 
from  all  the  series. 

F.  *  'The  images  seem  finer,  less  bulky  and  thick  than  the  actual  sounds;" 
"the  tones  are  as  intense  in  image  as  in  sensation  but  they  lack  'volume,' 
that  is,  concomitant  muscular  and  organic  sensations;"  "the  images  are 
abbreviated  in  some  way, — they  lack  a  fullness,  vividness,  aliveness,  sharp- 
ness, which  the  sensations  have;"  "usually  concomitants  such  as  sharp 
clang  or  after  tone  and  organic  sensations  are  not  reproduced  in  imagery;" 
'  'hard  to  say  how  the  images  differed  from  the  sensations,  but  I  know  they 
lack  certain  qualities  partly  of  sound  and  also  perhaps  of  organic  and, 
muscular  strains  and  attitudinal  setting.  'Deadness'  of  sound  is  partly 
lack  of  certain  qualities,  especially  certain  higher  pitches;"  "the  visual 
image  is  thin  and  threadlike  as  compared  with  the  sensations.  Images 
are  very  instable  and  the  main  difference  between  them  and  sensation  is 
the  fact  that  they  are  so  abbreviated." 

O.  "Good  images  of  correct  intensity.  With  the  sensations  there  are 
kinaesthetic  accompainments  which  are  not  present  in  the  image;"  "the 
sensation  is  fuller  and  has  an  element  of  impressiveness  that  the  image 
lacks";  "the  sensations  are  accompanied  by  kinaesthetic  sensations  and 
also  by  noises  and  overtones,  but  none  of  these  occur  in  the  image,  which 
was  purer  and  more  simple  than  the  sensation;"  "images  differ  from  sensa- 
tions not  in  intensity  but  in  fullness  and  kinaesthetic  sensations  accom- 
panying them;"  "the  only  element  common  to  image  and  sensation  is  in- 
tensity, they  differ  in  every  other  way." 

C.  "Image  less  steady  and  impressive  than  sensation;"  "got  two  images 
exactly  like  the  sensations  in  intensity,  but  they  were  more  subjective  and 
did  not  give  the  kinaesthetic  shock  that  accompanied  the  stimuli;" 
"images  thin  and  abbreviated  but  like  the  stimuli  in  intensity." 

G.  *  'The  images  differed  from  the  sensations  mostly  in  their  accompany- 
ing kinaesthetic  sensations;"    "I  do  not  know  what  the  difference  between 

'image  and  sensation  is,  or  how  I  can  tell  which  is  which.  The  image  has  a 
sort  of  'Verschwommenheit,'  is  thin,  diffuse,  vaporous,  and  not  as  clear- 
cut  as  the  sensation.  The  difference  is  less  a  matter  of  degree  than  of 
quahty;"  "images  are  pure  and  there  are  no  accompanying  strains.  The 
concomitants  such  as  pressure  and  strains  are  not  reproduced  in  image, — 
the  images  are  isolated." 

These  and  many  other  similar  introspections  made  by 
four  observers,  differing  widely  in  imaginal  type,  indicate  that 
the  difference  between  sensation  and  image  is  not  one  of 
intensity. 

^Cf.  Kuhlmann:    On  the  Analysis  of  Auditory  Memory   Consciousness, 
jy      Amer.  Jour.  Psych.,  XX.,  1909,  214;  E.  Murray:    Peripheral  and  Central 
Factors  in  Memory  Images  of  Visual  Form  and  Color,  Amer.  Jour.  Psych., 
XVII.,  1906,  231. 


366  SCHAUB 

Another  point  upon  which  our  introspections  throw  some 
Hght  is  the  time-relation  in  imagery.  In  by  far  the  greater 
number  of  introspections  we  find  mention  of  the  fact  that  the 
time-relations  of  images  exactly  correspond  to  those  of  sen- 
ations.  There  were,  indeed,  a  few  cases  in  which  each  indi- 
vidual image  lasted  too  long  and  the  interval  between  them 
was  too  short,  and,  conversely,  a  few  in  which  the  time  interval 
was  appreciably  lengthened.  The  latter,  however,  occurred 
in  the  cases  in  which  there  was  a  long  interval  before  recall  and 
in  which,  as  is  stated  above,  the  images  partook  of  the  nature 
of  'mental'  rather  than  of  memory  images.  On  the  basis  of  our 
results,  therefore,  we  are  able  to  say  that  memory  images 
tend,  in  introspection,  to  reproduce  exactly  the  time-relations 
of  the  original  sensational  experience.  The  images,  moreover, 
always  tended  to  become  less  accurate,  both  as  to  intensity  and 
as  to  temporal  relation,  when  there  were  a  number  of  repeti- 
tions of  the  recall  of  the  original  sensation. 

Of  the  many  minor  facts  brought  out  by  our  experiments  we 
should,  perhaps,  mention  also  the  important  r61e  that  kinaes- 
thesis  plays  in  imagery.  Others  who  have  investigated  audi- 
tory imagery  have  noticed  this  same  fact.  Kuhlmann,  for 
example,  tells  us  that  in  many  cases  "only  one-fourth  or 
one-half  of  the  sound  was  imaged  in  auditory  terms. "^  While 
our  observers,  as  already  stated,  differentiated  images  from 
sensations  by  the  lack  of  certain  kinaesthetic  elements,  never- 
theless, in  their  descriptions  of  imagery,  they  reported  the 
presence  of  other  kinaesthetic  elements  which  were  lacking 
in  sensation.  They  found  all  manner  of  throat  strains  and 
organic  attitudes  that  aided  correct  reproduction  and  carried 
much  of  the  'meaning'  of  the  image.  The  shock  produced  by 
a  stroke  was  not  accompanied  in  the  imagery  by  those  starts 
and  strains  characteristic  of  the  sensation,  but  other  bodily 
tensions  and  kinaesthetic  elements  were  substituted  for  them, 
and  gave  meaning  to  the  memory  image.  While  pitch  was 
usually  recalled  in  auditory  terms,  it  was  sometimes  carried 
in  the  memory  images  by  throat  settings  of  which  there 
was  no  trace  in  the  sensation.  Thus,  corroborating  the  results 
of  Kuhlmann,  our  observers  also  reproduced  the  sound  only 
partially  in  auditory  terms.  In  this  fact  there  is  a  further 
distinguishing  mark  of  images,  but  a  mark  which,  again,  is 
not  intensive. 

CONCIyUSION 

The  results  of  our  experiments,  then,  as  above  described, 
warrant  the  drawing  of  certain  conclusions  concerning  the 

^Kuhlmann:  On  the  Analysis  of  Auditory  Memory  Consciousness, 
Amer.  Jour.  Psych.,  XX.,  1909,  214. 


ON   TH^   INTENSITY   OF   IMAGES 


367 


intensity  of  images.  Our  problem  included  the  questions 
whether  intensity  is  an  attribute  of  images  and,  if  so,  whether 
there  is  a  scale  of  imaginal  intensity,  and  what  the  nature  of 
such  a  possible  scale  may  be.  The  answer  to  the  first  of 
these  questions  we  have  found  in  the  introspections  of  our 
observers.  It  appears  beyond  doubt  that,  at  least  under 
ordinary  laboratory  conditions,  images  possess  the  attribute 
of  intensity.  It  is  undoubtedly  true  that,  oftentimes,  the 
image  is  to  some  extent  weaker  than  the  original  sensation,  but 
it  is  far  from  true  that  this  is  always  or  necessarily  the  case. 
The  true  memory  image  frequently  reproduces  very  exactly 
the  sensational  intensity,  be  it  weak  or  strong;  the  intensity 
of  the  image  of  imagination,  though  likely  to  be  of  a  moderate 
degree,  may  at  times  be  very  strong  as  well  as  very  weak.  The 
'general'  or  'mental'  image,  being  a  type-image  referring  not 
to  any  particular  sensation  but  to  a  number  of  past  sensations 
of  varying  degrees,  is  almost  always  of  medium  intensity. 

The  question  regarding  the  nature  of  imaginal  intensity 
cannot  be  so  briefly  or  so  definitely  answered.  We  have  every 
reason  to  believe  that  there  are  not  two  different  kinds  of 
intensities,  but  that  the  intensive  attribute  is  one  and  the  same 
whether  it  be  that  of  sensation  or  of  the  image.  In  no  case 
did  any  of  our  observers  note  any  difference  in  the  nature  of 
imaginal  and  sensational  intensities.  But  we  need  not  rely 
on  negative  evidence  alone,  for,  as  above  quoted,  there  were 
introspections  which  stated  that  intensity  is  the  one  element 
common  to  image  and  sensation.  The  question  that  has  at 
times  been  raised,  ''Could  imaginal  intensity,  as  such,  replace 
sensational  intensity?"  we  are,  therefore,  inclined  to  answer 
in  the  affirmative.  One  observer  explicity  stated  that  imagi- 
nal intensity,  taken  by  itself,  is  the  same  thing  as  sensational 
intensity.  Certain  it  is  that  none  of  our  observers  found  any 
difficulty  in  comparing  the  intensities  of  images  and  sensations. 
As  regards,  more  specifically,  the  scale  of  intensities,  we 
find  that  with  the  possible  exception  of  the  very  loud  end  of  the 
scale  the  degrees  of  imaginal  intensity  correspond  with  those  of 
sensational  intensity.  About  very  weak  sounds  there  is  no 
doubt,  and  it  is  certain,  too,  that  some  intense  sounds  can  be 
exactly  reproduced  in  memory  imagery.  Whether,  however, 
we  can  thus  image  the  loudest  possible  sound,  or  the  brightest 
possible  light,  or  the  heaviest  possible  weight,  we  have  not 
ascertained.  With  this  exception  all  manner  of  intensive 
differences,  even  those  just  noticeable  in  sensation,  we  have 
found  to  be  accurately  reproduced  in  memory;  indeed,  with 
le  exception  of  very  loud  sounds  in  the  case  of  observer  F, 
10  degree  of  intensity  was  given  to  our  observers  that  was 
lot   correctly   reproduced    by   them.     From    this   it    would 


368  SCHAUB 

appear  that  the  intensive  scales  of  sensations  and  images  are 
identical. 

Incidental  to  the  negative  conclusion  that  the  difference 
between  images  and  sensations  is  not  one  of  intensity,  we  have 
gained  positive  introspections  as  to  the  nature  of  this  differ- 
ence. Our  observers  regarded  the  incompleteness,  thinness, 
abbreviatedness  of  the  image  as  its  main  point  of  differentia- 
tion from  sensation.  Compared  with  the  latter,  the  image 
lacks  a  certain  'aliveness'  or  kinaesthetic  complex,  and  it  is 
this  which  makes  of  it  a  very  different  thing.  In  so  far,  our 
results  confirm  the  views  entertained  by  the  second  group  of 
writers  to  whom  we  referred  in  our  historical  note, — those, 
namely,  who  regard  imaginal  as  quite  comparable  with 
sensational  intensity,  but  maintain  that  the  image  differs 
from  sensation  in  texture  or  nature. 

We  ought  perhaps  also  to  refer  briefly  to  two  other  points : 
the  influence  of  individual  differences  in  imaginal  type,  and 
the  question  of  physiological  substrate.  As  regards  the  former 
we  may  remark  that  observer  C,  markedly  visual  in  type,  had 
more  good  and  accurately  intensive  visual  images  than  any 
of  the  other  observers;  G  had  almost  no  images  except  those 
of  kinaesthesis,  and  we  find  him  hesitant  about  intensity  until 
he  is  tested  with  kinaesthetic  images ;  the  other  two  observers, 
individuals  of  mixed  type,  seemed  to  get  all  images  with  equal 
ease.  As  regards  physiological  substrate,  the  question  arises 
what  relation  we  must  assume  to  exist  between  the  cortical 
centres  of  sensation  and  memory,  such  that  a  correspondence 
in  intensity  may  be  rendered  intelligible. 

While  our  experiments  point  to  certain  positive  conclusions 
regarding  imaginal  intensity,  we  are  well  aware  that,  owing  to 
their  limited  scope  and  to  the  small  number  of  our  observers, 
we  are  not  justified  in  assuming  a  dogmatic  attitude.  The 
intensity  of  images  still  remains  a  promising  field  for  experi- 
mental investigation,  an  especially  interesting  problem  being 
that  of  the  upper  limit  of  the  intensive  scale.  In  such  an 
investigation  the  stimulus-error  would  assume  large  propor- 
tions; yet  it  might  be  overcome,  we  believe,  by  suitable 
apparatus  and  by  a  method  similar  to  that  which  we  have 
employed. 


THE  COLOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIALLY 

COLOR-BLIND,  A  CRITICISM  OF  CURRENT 

TEACHING 


By  SAMUEiy  P.  Hayes,  Ph.  D./  Mount  Holyoke  College 


A.  Introduction 369 

B.  Historical  Cases  of  Monocular  (Red-Green)  Color-Blindness  .  372 

C.  A  new  Case  of  Monocular  Protanopia 377 

1.  Color  Confusions 378 

2.  Color  Discriminations 381 

3.  Color  Equations 394 

D.  Conclusions  .     , 402 

E.  Bibliography 404 

A.     Introduction 

Although  the  existence  of  color-blindness  has  been  known 
since  1777  (32,  cj.  76),  and  although  large  numbers  of  cases 
have  been  studied  and  described  (19)  during  the  century  and 
a  quarter  which  has  elapsed  since  that  date,  the  general  topic 
of  color-blindness  is  still  in  a  state  which  many  psychologists 
consider  to  be  most  disgraceful  to  their  science.  One  reason 
for  this  backward  condition  is  undoubtedly  to  be  found  in  the 
extreme  complexity  of  the  subject,  and  the  enormous  varia- 
tion from  case  to  case;  but  an  even  greater  obstacle  to  the 
progress  of  knowledge  has  been  the  almost  universal  practice 
of  studying  and  classifying  cases  under  the  domination  of 
some  pre-conceived  color-theory  (36).  Perhaps  the  most 
notable  example  of  this  practice  is  to  be  found  in  the  descrip- 
tion of  the  sensations  of  the  red-blind,  which  Helmholtz  gives 
in  the  first  edition  of  his  Optik.^  But  even  to-day,  after 
fifty  additional  years  of  extended  observation  and  experi- 
mentation upon  color-defectives,  many  psychologists  seem 
disposed  to  discuss  the  topic  in  such  a  loose  and  superficial 
fashion  as  will  make  it  accord  with  the  color  theory  which 
they  have  espoused,  rather  than  to  work  out  a  full  and  clear 

^The  writer  wishes  to  express  his  gratitude  to  Professors  E.  B.  Titchener 
and  J.  W.  Baird  for  much  helpful  criticism  and  suggestion. 

^Helmholtz  (18,  p.  298)  states  that  red,  if  seen  at  all,  is  seen  as  a  weak 
green;  yellow,  as  a  stronger,  saturated  green;  green,  as  a  whitish  green; 
blue  and  violet,  as  blue;  and  white  as  greenish  blue.  Holmgren  (quoted 
33»  P-  29)  describes  the  sensations  of  the  green-blind  and  of  the  violet 
blind,  in  the  same  fashion ;  his  procedure  is  essentially  a  logical  process, 
and  his  description  is  an  inference  as  to  how  the  defective  retina  must 
see  colors  when  its  green-sensing  or  its  violet-sensing  fibres  are  lacking. 


370  HAYES 

statement  of  the  facts  thus  far  known,  regardless  of  their 
theoretical  implications. 

Ever  since  the  work  of  Seebeck  (69) ,  in  the  early  part  of  the 
nineteenth  century,  it  has  been  customary  to  divide  the  par- 
tially color-blinds  into  two  or  more  classes, — the  writers  of 
the  Helmholtzian  school  tending  to  distinguish  three  groups, 
while  those  who  advocate  a  four  color-element  theory  tend 
to  distinguish  two.  Seebeck  regarded  the  shortening  of  the 
spectrum,  which  he  found  in  certain  cases,  as  a  fundamental 
basis  of  differentiation;  and,  in  present-day  usage,  the  two 
best  established  groups  of  partially  color-blinds  are  those 
which  are  distinguished  by  the  different  lengths  of  their 
spectrums:  Deuteranopes,  whose  color-system  is  reduced  to 
blue,  yellow  and  grey,  but  who  see  color  throughout  the  whole 
length  of  the  spectrum;  and  Protanopes,  who  likewise  see 
only  blue,  yellow  and  grey,  but  whose  spectrum  is  shortened 
at  the  red-end,  and  who  show  the  Purkinje  phenomenon  in 
ordinary  light,  i  e.,  whose  region  of  maximum  brightness  is 
displaced  from  yellow  toward  blue  (40).  Authorities  disagree 
upon  the  question  of  the  existence  of  a  third  group  of  partially 
color-blinds — Tritanopes,  whose  color  system  is  reduced  to 
red  and  green  (40,  71,  74).  All  three  groups  are  commonly 
referred  to  as  dichromates,  because  their  color  system  is  assumed 
to  be  reduced  to  two  colors. 

Unfortunately  this  simple  classification  does  not  provide 
for  all  the  cases  of  color  deficiency  which  have  been  discovered. 
Seebeck  (69,  pp.  216  ff.)  found  mild  cases  of  color  deficiency 
which  he  was  loath  to  include  in  either  class ;  and  ever  since  his 
time,  no  wide  survey  of  cases  has  failed  to  reveal  a  considerable 
number  of  marginal  forms  which  were  neither  normal  nor 
limited  to  a  two-color  spectrum.  These  cases  were  long 
spoken  of  as  "color- weak"  or  "incompletely  color-blind," 
until  Rayleigh's  work  (62)  led  to  the  conclusion  that  many  of 
them  were  unequally  sensitive  to  red  and  to  green.  The 
equation  by  which  Rayleigh  made  this  discovery, — the  mix- 
ture of  red  and  green  to  match  yellow, — is  commonly  spoken  of 
as  the  "Rayleigh  equation."  Ever  since  Konig's  work  (39)  upon 
defectives  of  this  type,  they  have  been  known  by  the  name 
which  he  applied  to  them, — "anomalous  trichromates,"  i.  e., 
persons  whose  color-system  includes  all  three  of  the  funda- 
mental colors  of  Helmholtz  (red,  green  and  violet),  but  whose 
sensitiveness  to  red  or  green  is  abnormal.  It  is  now  custom- 
ary (15,  37,  40,  42,  43,  52)  to  distinguish  two  groups  of  anomal- 
ous trichromates,  upon  the  analogy  of  the  two  groups  of 
dichromates, — the  red-anomalous  or  protanomalous  trichro- 
mates, whose  sensitiveness  to  red  is  below  normal,  and  the 
green-anomalous    or    deuteranomalous    trichromates,    whose 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIALLY  COLOR-BLIND      37 1 

sensitiveness  to  green  is  below  normal.  Recent  writers  report 
other  peculiarities  of  this  group,  the  most  marked  of  which 
is  a  heightened  ♦sensitivity  to  contrast.  Guttmann^  identifies 
color-weakness  with  anomalous  trichromacy,  claiming  that 
the  defect  is  a  complex  state  involving  seven  inter-related 
symptoms.  Nagel  insists  that  color- weakness  is  the  wider 
term, — that  color-weakness  may  occur  without  the  other 
symptoms  of  anomalous  trichromacy  being  present. 

It  has  been  the  purpose  of  the  writer  to  examine  the  evi- 
dence upon  which  is  based  the  assumption  that  the  partially 
color-blinds  are  dichromates, — see  only  blue  and  yellow, — 
and  to  present  a  body  of  new  experimental  evidence  upon  the 
question  of  the  color  sensations  of  col  or- defectives. 

A  survey  of  the  literature  of  color-blindness  indicates  that 
we  are  indebted  to  Herschel  (21)  for  the  first  suggestion  of  the 
idea  that  the  color-system  of  the  color-blind  is  reduced  to 
blue  and  yellow;  and  that  the  general  acceptance  of  this  idea 
is  based  upon  the  following  lines  of  evidence  (61): — 

1.  Testimony  of  the  color-blinds  themselves,  and  infer- 
ence from  color-confusions,  from  the  naming  of  spectral  colors 
and  the  colors  of  objects. 

2.  Color  equations  in  which  the  various  colors  have  been 
matched  by  mixtures  of  blue,  yellow,  black  and  white. 

3.  The  study  of  acquired  and  temporary  color  defects. 

4.  The  analogy  of  peripheral  color-blindness. 

5.  The  study  of  monocular  cases  of  color-blindness.  Of 
these  five  sorts  of  evidence,  the  last  is  by  far  the  most  im- 
portant, since  its  evidence  is  direct. 

But  it  seems  very  clear  to  the  writer  that  theory  has,  in  many 
cases,  prejudiced  the  interpretation  of  the  facts  obtained  from 
all  five  sources,  and  that  we  have  no  right  to  conclude  from 
the  evidence  at  hand  that  all  typical  cases  of  partial  color-blind- 
ness are  dichromates.  Almost  every  writer  who  has  had  any 
wide  experience  with  color  defectives  has  seen  mild  cases  of 
color-blindness, ' '  incomplete  "  color-blindness,  etc.,  in  which  the 
subjects  give  evidence  of  seeing  some  kinds  of  red  or  green; 
and  the  conviction  seems  to  be  growing  common  that  dichro- 
mates are  the  extreme  and  not  the  typical  forms  of  partial 
color-blindness, — that  there  are  protanopes  who  see  some 
greens,  deuteranopes  who  see  some  reds,  etc. 

In  view  of  the  great  importance  attaching  to  monocular 
cases,  it  has  seemed  best  to  review  all  such  cases  available. 
After  this  the  experiments  performed  by  the  writer  upon  a 
monocular  protanope  will  be  described;  and  the  evidence 
derived  from  this  study  will  be  compared  with  the  results  of 

^For  the  discussion  of  this  question  by  Guttmann  and  Nagel,  see  the 
series  of  articles  in  the  Zsch.  f.  Sinnesphysiol.  41-43. 


372  HAYKS 

similar  experiments  upon  a  number  of  color-blind  subjects 
whose  defect  extends  to  both  eyes. 

B.  Historical  Cases  of  Monocular  (rbd-grebn)  Color- 
Blindness^ 

1.  Woinow's  case  of  green-blindness  in  one  eye  (iSyi) 

The  earliest  case  of  monocular  partial  color-blindness 
known  to  the  writer  is  that  reported  by  Dr.  N.  Woinow  (78) 
of  Moscow  in  1871.  The  patient,  a  woman  34  years  old,  was 
tested  with  rotating  discs  and  her  case  was  diagnosed  as  green- 
blindness.  The  following  equations  are  reported: — 
Left  (normal)  eye: 

225  black  4-135  white  =  135  red  +  125  green  -j-  100  violet 
Right  (color-blind)  eye: 

220  black  +140  white  =105  violet  +  255  red 

310  black  -f  50  white  =  30  violet  -|-  330  green 

Dr.  Woinow  evidently  studied  this  case  with  the  Helmholtz 
three-color  theory  in  mind;  but  his  equations  seem  to  indi- 
cate that  his  patient  was  very  deficient  both  in  red  and  in 
green  vision.  The  case  was  not  so  simple  as  this,  however. 
The  patient  seems  to  have  had  an  hysterical  fear  of  reds,  and 
both  eyes  appeared  to  be  somehow  sensitive  to  this  color.  She 
said  she  could  not  bear  to  look  at  red  or  orange,  but  that,  if 
she  had  to  do  so,  "she  felt  better"  with  her  right  (color-blind) 
eye  closed.  Moreover,  she  reported  that  when  she  looked 
with  her  right  eye  alone,  "everything  was  tinged  with  red." 
Woinow  concluded  that  she  was  color-blind  to  green  only. 
But  in  view  of  the  complications  involved,  and  the  small 
number  of  tests  made,  this  case  seems  to  have  practically  no 
value  as  evidence  of  the  actual  color  sensations  of  the  color- 
blind. 

2,  von  HippeVs  monocular  partially  color-blind  subject    (1880) 
In  the  literature  of  the  last  thirty  years,  constant  reference 

is  made  to  the  case  of  monocular  color-blindness  which  was 
studied  and  described  by  von  Hippel  (28)  in  1880.  The 
subject,  a  young  man,  came  to  von  Hippel  for  spectacles  to 
correct  double  vision,  and  in  von  Hippel's  exploration  of  the 
subject's  right  visual  field  with  a  Forster  perimeter,  constant 
confusions  of  red  and  green  with  yellow  were  noticed.  Before 
this  the  subject  had  known  nothing  of  his  color  defect.  Von 
Hippel  then  made  a  long  and  careful  series  of  experiments, 
using  a  Hoffmann  spectroscope,  Radde's  international  color 

I  The  monocular  cases  described  by  Niemetscheck  (59),  Hohngren  (31), 
Kirschmann  (35)  and  Piper  (60)  are  intentionally  omitted  because  tliis 
paper  deals  only  with  protanopia  and  deuteranopia. 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  OI^  THE  PARTIALLY  COLOR-BLIND      373 

charts,  Holmgren's  worsteds,  Stilling's  pseudo-isochromatische 
Tafeln,  contrast  shadows  and  tissue  contrast,  color  equations 
with  rotating  discs.  Dor's  charts  for  the  recognition  of  colors 
at  a  distance  of  five  meters,  and  von  Hippel's  photometer  with 
colored  glasses.  In  all  these  experiments,  the  subject's  left 
eye  seemed  perfectly  normal,  while  with  his  right  eye  he 
made  constant  confusions  of  red  and  green  with  yellow,  although 
occasionally  using  the  words  "red"  and  "green"  correctly. 
In  the  experiments  with  the  spectroscope,  von  Hippel  reported 
that  when  the  whole  spectrum  was  shown  at  once  the  subject 
claimed  to  see  red,  yellow  or  greenish,  and  blue;  but,  when 
only  a  narrow  band  was  shown,  the  whole  warm-end  of  the 
spectrum  was  called  yellow. 

Von  Hippel  diagnosed  his  case  as  one  of  red-green  blindness, 
and  there  seems  little  ground  for  questioning  his  decision. 
As  he  found  no  shortening  of  the  spectrum,  the  subject  was 
probably  a  deuteranope. 

Holmgren  (30)  studied  the  same  case,  and  diagnosed  it  as 
"a  typical  case  of  red-blindness,"  with  shortened  spectrum, 
and  the  two  fundamental  colors  which  such  a  case  should  have, 
according  to  the  form  of  the  Helmholtz  theory  presented  in  the 
first  edition  of  the  Optik  (18), — a  greenish  yellow,  and  a  blue 
tinged  with  violet. 

Von  Hippel  (29)  then  made  further  experiments  with  the 
spectroscope,  and  substantiated  his  claim  that  the  subject's 
spectrum  was  not  shortened.  He  also  carefully  compared  the 
subject's  judgments  of  color  made  with  his  normal  and  his 
color-blind  eye,  and  showed  that  he  used  '  'blue"  and  "yellow" 
for  the  same  kinds  of  sensations  in  the  two  eyes.  He  added 
a  series  of  experiments  with  negative  after-images,  in  which 
the  subject  reported  normal  after-images  for  the  left  eye, 
but  for  the  right  gave  blue  as  the  color  of  all  after-images 
from  red,  orange,  yellow  and  green;  yellow  as  the  color  of 
after-images  from  blue  and  violet. 

On  the  whole,  there  seems  good  evidence  that  this  subject 
saw  only  two  colors  (probably  yellow  and  blue) ;  and,  as  this 
was  the  first  monocular  case  pointing  clearly  towards  dichro- 
macy,  one  can  easily  understand  its  importance. 

Holmgren  claims  to  have  seen  another  case  of  monocular 
color-blindness  in  1879,  which,  however,  "unhappily  became 
useless  through  an  accident"  (31). 

J.  Stejffan'scaseof  monocular  color-blindness  (i^,  ^0,^3)  (1881) 
We  get  no  clear  light  on  our  problem  from  this  case.  The 
patient  was  a  man  sixty-two  years  old,  who  showed  defective 
color-vision  in  one  eye  after  an  attack  of  apoplexy.  It  is 
interesting  to  note  that  although,  the  patient  showed  lowered 

4 — JOURNAI, 


374  HAYES 

sensitivity  for  all  colors,  the  only  color  he  completely  lost  was 
green;  but  considering  our  present  uncertainty  as  to  the  rela- 
tion of  atypical  acquired  color-blindness  to  typical  congenital 
color-blindness,  we  have  no  right  to  reason  from  the  one  kind 
to  the  other  (38,  56,  71). 

4.  Kolbe's  case  of  "monocular  red-green  weakness''     {1882) 
Kolbe  (37b)  used  many  of  the  same  tests  as  von  Hippel;  and 

while  this  case  does  not  show  the  grave  color  deficiency  of  von 
Hippel' s  case,  repeated  evidences  of  sub-normal  color  vision 
were  found.  No  neutral  band  in  the  spectrum  was  established. 
But  at  518  /x/x  the  subject  said  at  one  time  that  the  color  was 
weaker  than  in  the  neighboring  region;  and  at  another  time 
he  reported  that  from  508  to  520  was  an  uncertain  color.  In 
the  use  of  the  Holmgren  wools,  the  Stilling  cards  of  1879  and 
Dor's  charts,  the  subject  showed  himself  below  normal,  but 
considerably  more  color-capable  than  von  Hippel's  subject. 
In  a  series  of  tests  of  color  sensitivity,  Kolbe's  subject  showed 
decidedly  high  thresholds  for  both  red  and  green.  In  the 
experiments  with  contrast  shadows  and  negative  after-images, 
this  subject  gave  normal  results  for  blue  and  yellow;  but  his 
reactions  with  red  and  green  were  practically  those  of  a  color- 
blind person. 

From  Kolbe's  report,  it  would  seem  that  this  case  might 
well  be  diagnosed  as  a  mild  case  of  color-blindness,  although 
one  hesitates  to  form  such  a  conclusion  without  the  use  of 
color-equations,  and  a  repetition  of  the  spectral  experiments. 

Kolbe  refers  to  a  monocular  case  of  "red-green"  blindness 
described  by  Hermann  (26a)  in  a  pamphlet  not  accessible  to 
the  present  writer.  This  subject's  spectrum  was  shortened  at 
the  violet  end, — the  brightest  region  from  588  /a/a  to  583  /a/a, 
which  appeared  as  a  dull  band,  separating  red,  on  the  left, 
from  green,  on  the  right.  These  details  seem  to  point  rather 
to  violet-\Ain6.n^ss. 

5.  SchufelVs  case  of  monocular  color-blindness  (^7)     {188 j) 

Following  are  the  observations  made  upon  "a  healthy 
young  man  twenty-one  years  old"  when  tested  with  the 
Holmgren  wools: — 

"With  both  eyes  open,  he  succeeded,  without  trouble  oi 
hesitation,  in  picking  out  a  series  of  purples  and  greens  t< 
match  the  test  shade;  but  he  exhibited  a  good  deal  of  uncer- 
tainty when  called  upon  to  do  the  same  for  the  reds,  the  test 
color  being  a  bright  red-lead  shade.  The  worsteds  beinj 
again  mixed  up,  he  successfully  chose  the  purple  and  greei 
shades  with  either  eye,  one  or  the  other  being  closed,  and  th< 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIAI.I.Y  COI.OR-BI.IND      375 

reds  with  the  right  eye,  the  left  one  being  closed.  The  worsteds 
were  mixed  once  more,  and  he  was  asked  to  close  his  right  eye, 
and  to  pick  out  the  red  shades.  This  he  essayed  to  do  by 
first  selecting  a  pale  shade  of  brown,  placing  it  on  one  side, 
and  with  considerable  hesitation  of  manner,  he  proceeded  in 
the  same  way  until  he  had  laid  aside  a  full  series  of  brown 
shades  from  dark  to  light  ochre.  It  was  amusing  to  see  his 
confusion  when  I  suddenly  released  his  right  eye,  'as  the  lids 
were  kept  together  with  my  finger,  and  quickly  closing  his 
left,  allowed  him  to  see  what  he  had  done," 

This  case  adds  very  little  to  our  knowledge.  One  would 
hesitate  to  base  any  conclusions  upon  a  preliminary  test  with 
the  Holmgren  worsteds.  The  case  is  included  in  this  paper 
simply  for  completeness  in  reviewing  the  evidence. 

6.     A  case  of  color-blindness  limited  to  the  nasal  half  of  the  left 
retina,  described  by  Hess  in  18 go  (27) 

A  young  man,  thirty-one  years  old,  found  he  had  difiiculty  in 
distinguishing  colors  and  thought  his  difi&culty  a  matter  of 
recent  origin.  Upon  examination,  it  was  found  that  on  the 
nasal  half  of  his  left  retina  he  was  quite  insensitive  to  red, 
and  had  a  decidedly  lowered  sensitivity  for  the  other  colors, 
while  on  the  other  half  of  this  retina,  and  on  the  whole  of  the 
other  retina  his  color- vision  was  normal.  Colors  were  pre- 
sented simultaneously  to  the  right  and  to  the  left  of  a  given 
fixation-point;  and  he  was  asked  to  tell  what  colors  he  saw. 
His  replies  were  as  follows: 

Normal  (temporal)  half  of  left  eye  Color  blind  (nasal)  half  of  left  eye 

Red  appeared  red  "dirty  dark  yellow" 

Orange    "     orange  "dirty  sulphur  color" 

Yellow     "     yellow  "yellow" 

Yellow-green,  normal  * '  weak  yellowish  grey ' ' 

Urgriin  appeared  "  "greenish  grey" 

Blue  "  "  "blue  with  violet  tone" 

Violet  "  "  "  less  saturated  violet  than 

that  on  temporal  side' ' 

Purple  "  "  "  greyish  violet " 

Experiments  with  spectral  lights  gave  similar  results.  It 
seems  plain  that  this  subject  thought  he  saw  green  with  his 
affected  tract.  In  one  place  he  especially  said  that  "green 
looked  neither  yellow  nor  blue; "  and  since  his  other  eye  seems 
to  have  been  completely  normal,  there  is  no  apparent  reason 
why  he  should  use  the  wrong  name  for  what  he  called  "green." 
In  spite  of  the  fact  that  the  patient  thought  he  saw  green, 
Hess  diagnosed  the  case  as  red-green  blindness,  explaining  its 


376  HAYES 

presence  by  the  assumption  that  the  red-green  substance, 
posited  by  the  Hering  theory,  was  quite  out  of  function.  But 
one  feels  loath  to  accept  this  conclusion.  The  fact  that  the 
defect  was  limited  to  one  half  of  one  eye,  and  that  the  patient 
thought  his  difi&culty  a  recent  thing,  would  suggest  that  the 
case  was  possibly  of  central  origin  and  acquired.  Hence, 
whatever  the  results  obtained  by  Hess,  we  ought  not  too 
readily  to  accept  them  as  representative  of  typical  partial 
color-blindness.  And  Guttmann  (15,  p.  280)  has  recently 
suggested  that,  under  similar  tests,  a  red-anomalous  trichro- 
mate  would  have  responded  in  much  the  same  way,  for,  when 
small  areas  outside  the  fovea  are  simultaneously  stimulated, 
the  anomalous  trichromate  responds  in  much  the  same  way 
as  a  patient  who  is  typically  color-blind. 

7.     Hering's   case   of  monocular   partial   color-blindness    (25) 

{1890) 

In  the  same  volume  with  the  case  just  described,  we  find 
an  account  of  a  series  of  experiments  by  Hering  upon  a  patient 
with  partial  color-blindness  in  one  eye.  The  method  of  experi- 
menting was  practically  the  same :  with  a  simple  stereoscopic 
device  he  presented  patches  of  color  to  the  two  eyes  simul- 
taneously, and  asked  the  subject  to  compare  them,  and  report 
what  colors  he  saw  with  each  eye.  By  means  of  mirrors, 
Hering  was  able  to  change  the  brightness  and  saturation  of 
either  color  presented.  Occasionally  he  tried,  by  increasing 
or  decreasing  the  illumination,  to  present  to  the  normal  eye 
a  color  or  a  grey  that  should  match  the  sensation  experienced  by 
the  affected  eye;  but  he  gives  no  numerical  values,  and  hence 
it  is  impossible  to  know  exactly  what  his  results  mean,  or  to 
compare  them  with  the  results  obtained  from  other  subjects. 
To  the  affected  eye,  bluish  red  was  reported  to  look  "grey  with 
a  reddish  shimmer ; ' '  spectral  red, ' '  dark  yellowish  grey ; ' '  orange, 
yellow  and  yellowish  green,  "whitish  yellow;"  Urgran,  "light 
grey;"  ultramarine  blue,  "whitish  blue;"  and  violet,  "dark 
blue." 

Upon  the  basis  of  these  results,  Hering  diagnosed  his  case 
as  one  of  red-green  blindness,  with  weakened  sensitivity  for 
blue  and  yellow. 

In  a  spectrum  of  moderate  brightness,  this  patient  reported 
three  colors;  yellow,  green  and  blue.  When  the  brightness 
was  increased,  only  a  "  greenish  shimmer "  was  mentioned, 
though  the  normal  eye  saw  a  beautiful  saturated  green.  The 
spectrum  was  shortened  at  the  red  end, — the  spectrum  be- 
ginning at  wave-length  630  /w,/x  for  the  affected  eye,  while  the 
normal  eye  saw  color  at  670  /m/x.     From  630  /a/a  inward,  the 


COI^OR  SENSATIONS  OP  THK  PARTIAL,I.Y  COI.OR-BI.IND      377 

patient  saw  only  yellow  with  the  affected  eye,  where  red- 
orange  and  orange  were  visible  to  the  normal  eye. 

Looking  through  a  telescope  at  the  spectrum,  the  patient 
described  light  of  630  /m/a  as  yellow-red,  but  still  more  yellow- 
ish than  it  appeared  to  the  normal  eye;  light  of  600  /x/x  she 
described  as  orange;  light  of  570  fi/w,  as  cream  colored.  The 
lights  from  500-420  /ix/x  she  described,  sometimes  as  grey,  at 
other  times  as  greenish  grey. 

On  the  whole,  Hering  seems  scarcely  justified  in  calling 
this  a  case  of  red-green  blindness,  for  in  one  test  or  another 
the  subject  correctly  named  both  red  and  green.  Guttmann 
(15,  p.  279)  suggests  that  this  case  also  closely  resembles  red- 
anomalous  trichromacy,  and  there  is  enough  similarity  to 
prevent  our  complete  acceptance  of  the  case  as  evidence  for  the 
claim  that  dichromates  see  only  blue  and  yellow.  Wundt  (79, 
p.  229,  note)  says  of  these  cases  reported  by  Hess  and  Hering, 
"In  these  two  cases  we  find  complete  red-blindness,  while 
the  sensitivity  for  green  as  well  as  for  the  other  colors  is 
merely  lowered." 

Of  all  the  above  cases,  that  of  von  Hippel  alone  furnishes 
evidence  for  the  claim  that  partially  color-blinds  are  dichro- 
mates. In  Woinow's  case,  the  results  are  complicated  by  the 
patient's  emotional  reaction  to  red,  which  she  was  supposed 
not  to  see;  in  Steffan's  case  there  was  probably  some  disturb- 
ance in  the  cortex,  and  in  Hess's  case  there  would  seem  to 
have  been  an  acquired  disorder  of  some  kind;  Hering' s  sub- 
ject seemed  to  recognize  all  the  colors  when  they  were  intense 
enough,  and  should  perhaps  be  classed  as  a  red-anomalous 
trichromate;  the  preliminary  test  performed  upon  Schufelt's 
case  is  suggestive  but  not  conclusive.  Von  Hippel's  subject 
was  probably  a  dichromate,  and  von  Hippel's  work  furnishes 
sufficient  evidence  that  there  can  be  clear-cut  blue-yellow 
vision.  But  when  one  considers  the  great  variation  among 
color  blind  subjects  which  has  constantly  been  noted  by  experi- 
menters, one  scarcely  feels  justified  in  jumping  to  the  con- 
clusion that  all  partially  color-blind  subjects  see  only  blue 
and  yellow.  On  the  whole  there  seems  good  ground  for  the 
following  confession  of  von  Kries  (40,  p.  166): — "In  general, 
one  may  well  admit  that  the  factual  basis  for  the  oft-made 
assertion  that  dichromates  are  blind  to  red  and  green  but  see 
yellow  and  blue,  is  very  insufficient.  In  reality  this  claim 
is  the  result  of  theorizing,  and  its  value  is  to  be  estimated 
according  to  its  harmony  with  theory." 

C.      A  NSW  CASK  OF  MONOCULAR  PROtANOPIA 

During  some  work  with  colors  in  the  year  1907-08,  Miss  G. 
S.,  a  Senior  in  Mt.  Holyoke  College,  made  some  remarks  which 


378  HAYES 

indicated  that  her  color  vision  was  not  normal.  Preliminary 
tests  showed  that  she  was  quite  unable  to  recognize  reds  with 
her  right  eye,  while  no  lack  of  ability  with  this  or  any  other 
color  was  shown  when  the  left  eye  was  tested. 

She  had  studied  psychology  for  two  semesters  before  the 
following  experiments  were  begun, — one  semester  of  intro- 
ductory text-book  work  and  one  semester  of  elementary 
laboratory  work.  She  seemed  to  be  an  intelligent,  carefiil 
observer  of  the  "objective  type."  The  experiments  described 
below  were  performed  in  June,.  1908,  October,  1908,  and  Novem- 
ber, 1909.  The  subject  was  in  good  health  at  each  of  these 
periods.  In  November,  1909,  she  was  examined  by  a  pro- 
fessional oculist,  who  reported  that  the  ophthalmoscope 
showed  nothing  abnormal  in  either  eye,  but  that  she  was  slightly 
myopic  in  her  left  eye,  and  had  some  weakness  of  vision  in 
the  right  eye  which  no  lens  seemed  to  correct.  The  subject 
reports  that  her  maternal  grandfather  was  color-blind,  but 
she  knows  nothing  about  the  details  of  his  defect,  and  has 
never  heard  of  any  other  case  of  defective  color  vision  in  her 
family. 

I.     Color  confusions 
a.  Test  with  the  Nagel  cards  (fifth  edition) 

With  the  left  eye,  the  subject  made  no  mistakes.  With 
the  right  eye,  she  could  see  no  red  on  any  cards,  and  selected 
as  grey  A  9  (correct),  and  numbers  A  3,  7  and  15  which  have 
upon  them  red  or  red  and  grey  dots.  As  green  she  selected 
the  one  green  card  A  5.  In  series  B  she  thought  the  reds  and 
browns  were  black  and  grey,  but  correctly  named  the  green 
in  B  3  and  the  yellow-green  in  B  i. 

In  the  Nagel  test,  then,  the  subject  showed  herself  blind 
to  red,  but  made  no  mistakes  in  green.  This  is  the  more 
remarkable,  because  many  persons  who,  upon  further  exami- 
nation, show  only  slight  defects  in  color  discrimination  make 
numerous  confusions  between  green  and  grey. 

b.     Test  with  Bradley  papers 

Fifty  pieces  of  Bradley  paper,  3  cm.  square,  including  all 
the  standard  colors  and  many  tints  and  shades,  with  similar 
squares  of  the  ten  Bradley  blacks,  whites  and  greys,  were 
spread  upon  a  table  in  a  good  light.  The  subject  stood 
before  the  table  with  her  left  eye  covered.  The  test  was 
conducted  in  the  same  manner  as  the  Holmgren  worsted  test, 
the  subject  being  given  a  sample  and  requested  to  select  ten 
or  a  dozen  pieces  of  paper  of  the  same  color.  She  selected 
green  and  yellow  pieces  to  match  the  green  sample  (green 
yellow  shade  2) ;  four  reddish  pieces,  one  light  orange,  and  six 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  OI?  THB  PARTIALITY  COLOR-BUND      379 

greys  to  match  the  rose  sample  (red  tint  2) ;  and  nine  light 
and  dark  reds,  four  orange  pieces  and  seven  greys  to  match 
the  red  sample  (red  tint  i). 

c.  Tests  with  Holmgren  worsteds^ 

Green  A,  presented  to  the  right  eye,  was  matched  by  worsteds 
2,  4,  6,  8  and  12,  all  of  which  are  green  or  yellowish  green.  14, 
16  and  18  looked  like  the  sample  to  her,  but  darker.  10  and 
20  seemed  about  the  same  in  brightness  as  the  sample,  but 
bluer. 

Rose  B,  presented  to  the  right  eye,  was  matched  by  28, 
32,  34,  36,  38  and  40,  all  of  which  have  red  in  them,  by  the 
confusion  colors  13,  15,  19,  33,  35,  37  and  39,  all  of  which  are 
browns  and  far  removed  from  the  rose  sample,  and  by  the 
confusion  colors  i  and  3  which  are  faint  greys  with  very  little 
color  of  any  kind  in  them.  The  grey  5,  the  light  blue  21,  and 
the  bluish  reds  22,  24,  26  and  30  were  selected  as  like  one  sam- 
ple, but  "tending  more  or  less  toward  blue."  In  these  tests 
we  have  a  strong  indication  of  red  blindness. 

Red  C,  presented  to  the  right  eye,  was  matched  by  32,  34, 
36  and  38,  all  of  which  are  reds.  40  looked  like  the  sample  but 
darker.     In  this  test  she  made  no  color  confusions. 

In  all  of  these  tests,  the  subject  refrained  from  holding  the 
sample  close  to  each  bunch  as  she  examined  it,  but,  glancing 
at  the  sample  and  then  at  the  other,  decided  by  memory.  In 
most  cases  she  decided  quickly  and  easily. 

d.     Tests  with  dots  of  Hering  papers  on  grey  cards'^ 

In  view  of  the  fact  that  color-blindness  has  been  reported 
(51,  52,  57,  68)  to  be  sometimes  more  extreme  at  the  fovea 
than  elsewhere  on  the  retina,  a  special  series  of  experiments 
was  performed  to  decide  the  point  in  this  case.  Thirty-two 
grey  cards  8  cm.  square  were  secured,  and  at  the  centre  of  each 
was  pasted  a  round  dot  of  Hering  paper  4  mm.  in  diameter, — 
small  enough  so  that  when  viewed  directly  at  a  distance  of  half 
a  meter,  only  the  fovea  would  be  stimulated.  The  cards  were 
spread  out  upon  a  table  in  a  good  light,  and  the  subject,  with 
one  eye  closed,  was  asked  to  pick  out  all  the  cards  having  a 
dot  of  the  same  color  as  one  given  as  a  sample.  Hering 
papers  1-12  were  each  represented  by  two  cards  (except  red 
no.  2  with  which  four  cards  were  used),  and  upon  4  other 
cards  dots  of  Hering  grey  no.  8  were  pasted. 

'Forty  skeins  with  metal  tag  attached.  Supplied  by  Chicago  Labora- 
tory Supply  &  Scales  Co. 

^Rothe  papers  made  under  Hering's  direction. 


380  HAYES 

With  the  right  (color-bhnd)  eye,  Miss  G.  S.  selected  red  and 
grey  to  match  the  red  sample;  purple,  violet  and  blue  to 
match  the  blue  sample;  green  and  yellow-green  to  match  the 
green  sample;  and  orange  and  yellow  to  match  the  yellow 
sample.  There  was  no  evidence  that  she  was  more  color- 
blind at  the  fovea.  With  the  left  eye  all  the  colors  were 
correctly  and  exactly  chosen  and  named. 

e.     Additional  confusion  tests 

The  subject  stood  before  a  window  and  looked  skyward 
through  colored  films  and  glasses.  The  right  eye  was  tested 
first.  Blue,  yellow  and  green  were  easily  recognized;  red 
looked  dark  grey,  and  all  mixed  colors  which  contained  red 
lost  their  red  element;  blue-green  looked  greyish.  With  the 
left  eye  all  the  colors  were  correctly  named.  When  a  film  or 
glass  was  moved  over  from  the  left  to  the  right  eye,  the  subject 
said  it  always  looked  darker. 

A  rough  test  was  made  to  determine  whether  the  subject 
used  color  associations  in  recognizing  greens,  etc.  Seven 
black  and  white  reprints  of  famous  pictures  were  colored 
contrary  to  nature  with  crayons  and  water  colors, — a  face 
was  painted  a  strong  green,  a  cow  purple,  a  tree  red,  four 
kittens  were  colored  red,  yellow,  green  and  grey,  a  sky  green, 
etc.  With  her  right  (color-blind)  eye,  the  subject  detected 
the  trick  in  most  cases,  naming  all  the  strong  greens,  yellows 
and  blues  correctly.  None  of  the  reds  appeared  to  her  to 
have  color;  and  in  those  places  where  the  green  was  weakened 
by  the  black  of  the  print  underneath  the  thin  paint  she  failed 
to  detect  the  green. 

From  these  confusion  tests  one  must  conclude  that  this 
protanope  is  unable,  under  ordinary  conditions,  to  see  red 
as  a  color,  but  that  under  the  same  conditions  she  is  repeatedly 
able  to  recognize  and  correctly  name  various  kinds  of  green, — 
even  such  greens  as  those  upon  the  Nagel  cards.  Now  since 
this  subject  seems  to  have  perfectly  normal  color  sensitiveness 
with  her  left  eye,  we  must  assume  that  she  knows  what  the 
sensation  of  green  is  like,  and  when  she  correctly  insists  that 
a  certain  color  seen  with  her  color-blind  eye  is  green,  we  have 
very  strong  evidence  for  the  conviction  that  green  (as  a  specific 
color  quality  different  from  yellow  and  grey)  is  included  in  the 
color  system  of  her  protanopic  (right)  eye.  At  the  same  time, 
her  occasional  difficulty  with  greens  gave  evidence  of  a  lowered 
sensitiveness  for  that  color,  and  seems  entirely  consistent  with 
the  later  discovery  that  there  is  a  certain  region  in  the  neigh- 
borhood of  the  blue-greens  which  this  subject  confused  with 
a  light  red. 


COLOR  SEJNSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIALLY  COLOR-BLIND      38 1 

2.     Experiments  in  color  discrimination 
a.  Determination  of  the  color  threshold  with  rotating  discs^ 

Upon  white  discs  with  a  radius  of  95  mm.  were  pasted 
circular  rings  of  the  four  standard  Hering  colors  5  mm.  in 
width,  at  a  distance  of  60  mm.  from  the  centre  of  the  discs, 
one  color  being  pasted  upon  each  disc.  Upon  a  fifth  disc  a 
strip  of  Bradley's  neutral  grey  no.  2  was  pasted,  and  this 
disc  and  a  pure  white  one  were  interwoven  with  the  discs 
bearing  colors,  and  all  mounted  on  the  color-wheel  together. 

The  subject  was  seated  about  one  meter  from  the  color- 
wheel,  with  her  back  to  the  source  of  light,  and  her  left  eye 
covered.  The  experimenter  stood  in  front  of  the  color- wheel 
when  it  was  not  in  motion,  to  conceal  it  from  the  subject,  in 
order  that  she  might  not  know  in  advance  what  color  was  to  be 
given.  The  experimeter  would  then  draw  out  one  of  the 
colors  or  the  grey,  so  that  a  small  number  of  degrees  were 
exposed,  set  the  mixer  rotating  and  ask  the  subject  to  name  the 
colored  ring.  By  varying  the  colors  and  the  amount  given, 
and  by  occasionally  introducing  grey  to  make  sure  that  the 
subject  was  not  merely  guessing  at  the  colors,  a  minimum 
amount  was  at  length  determined  upon  as  the  least  amount 
of  each  color  which  the  subject  could  correctly  name.  Fre- 
quent rests  were  given.  After  completing  the  series  with  the 
right  eye,  the  experiments  were  repeated  with  the  other  eye. 

Table  I 

Showing  the  Color  Thresholds,  as  determined  by  means  of  rings  of  Hering  paper 
upon  white  discs.     {The  determinations  are  expressed  in  degrees.) 

RED        GREEN  YELLOW    BLUE 

Miss  G.  S.     Protanope  Right  Eye 

Miss  M.  S.    Deuteranope      Right  Bye 

Left  Eye 
Miss  H.  B.    Deuteranope      Right  Eye 

Left  Eye 
Miss  G.  B.    Deuteranope      Right  Eye 

Left  Bye 
Miss  B.  C.    Deuteranope      Right  Eye 

Left  Eye 
Miss  I.  B.  Deuteranope  Left  Bye 
Average  of  40  eyes, — 20  women  who 

made  no  mistakes  with  the  Nagel  test  21  22  25  21 

^It  is  a  matter  of  considerable  regret  that  it  was  impossible  to  use  spectral 
lights  for  many  of  the  experiments  now  to  be  reported  upon.  The  recent 
work  of  Nagel,  von  Kries  and  their  pupils  shows  the  great  advantage  of  such 
lights.  But  unfortunately  the  great  cost  of  the  apparatus  necessary 
renders  it  unattainable  in  a  small  College  laboratory.  Rivers  found  the 
Lovibond  Tintometer  (44)  very useftd  for  quantitative  determinations  of  the 
color  sensitiveness  of  the  natives  of  Torres  Straits ;  but  this  apparatus,  with 
a  sufficiently  large  assortment  of  colored  glasses,  proved  too  expensive  for 


X 

105 

65 

50 

no 

X 

40 

25 

140 

X 

35 

22 

270 

320 

200 

210 

285 

320 

250 

210 

230 

225 

250 

205 

210 

210 

285 

180 

315 

350 

270 

180 

325 

330 

260 

180 

148 

180 

55 

90 

382  HAYBS 

In  the  foregoing  table  the  results  obtained  with  Miss  G.  S.'s 
right  eye  are  compared  with  the  results  of  similar  tests  upon 
five  deuteranopes,  the  last  two  of  whom  are  mild  cases;  and 
with  the  results  of  tests  upon  normal  eyes.  An  "x"  in  the 
table  indicates  that  no  color  was  recognized  even  when  the 
whole  ring  (360°)  was  exposed  to  view. 

Slight  differences  in  the  color  sensitivity  of  the  two  eyes 
have  been  noted  by  many  observers.  Hence  the  eyes  of  all 
the  subjects  mentioned  in  this  paper  were  tested  separately, 
with  the  exception  of  the  test  with  the  Hegg  sheet  and  the 
experiments  in  contrast.  When  there  was  not  time  to  test 
both  eyes,  only  the  right  was  experimented  upon,  except  in 
the  case  of  Miss  I.  B.  whose  left  eye  was  found  to  be  weaker  in 
color  sensitivity  than  the  right,  and  therefore  more  nearly 
comparable  with  the  other  subjects. 

The  foregoing  experiment  is  subject  to  criticism  upon  the 
ground  that  the  colors  used  were  not  the  best  ones  for  testing 
the  color  sensitivity  of  the  color-blind.  In  making  an  equa- 
tion of  red  and  green  with  color-blind  observers,  it  is  often 
necessary  to  add  blue  to  the  red,  or  to  the  green,  or  to  both  these 
colors,  in  order  to  make  them  both  appear  grey.  A  second 
series  of  experiments  was  therefore  performed  using  Hegg's 
pigments^  instead  of  the  Hering  papers.  Four  discs  10  cm. 
in  diameter  were  cut  from  Hering' s  grey  paper  number  14, 
and  upon  these  discs  rings  5  mm.  in  width  were  painted  with 
Hegg's  pigments,  the  rings  being  60  mm.  from  the  centre  of 
the  discs,  as  in  the  earlier  tests.  No.  14  grey  was  selected 
because  that  appeared  to  the  writer  and  to  two  other  normal 
observers  to  be  the  nearest  in  brightness  to  the  grey  upon  the 
sheet  of  colors  which  is  provided  with  the  Hegg  set.^  Before 
the  experiments  upon  the  color  threshold  were  begun,  this 
sheet  of  colors  was  presented  to  Miss  G.  S.,  with  the  request 
that  she  name  any  colors  she  saw.  Using  her  right  eye,  she  at 
once  named  the  blue  and  the  green,  but  she  recognized  neither 
the  red  nor  the  yellow.  The  yellow  she  called  grey,  and  said 
it  was  lighter  than  the  grey  band  in  the  middle  of  the  sheet; 
the  red  also  seemed  grey  to  her,  but  of  the  same  brightness  as 
the  central  grey.  With  her  left  eye  she  named  the  four  "in- 
variable" colors  correctly,  although  she  was  at  first  a  little 
uncertain  about  the  yellow,  and  said  it  was  a  very  poor  yellow 
at  best. 

Table  II  presents  the  results  of  the  tests  with  Hegg's  pig- 
ments.   The  results  with  Miss  G.  S.  are  compared  with  those  of 

^Baird  (4,  p.  29)  gives  an  account  of  the  way  in  which  these  colors  were 
decided  upon. 

^Unfortunately  no  apparatus  for  the  exact  evaluation  of  brightness  was 
available  in  the  laboratory. 


COIvOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIALLY  COLOR-BLIND      383 

five  deuteranopes.  Miss  G.  B.  was  not  tested  with  the  Hegg 
pigments,  so  the  results  of  the  Hegg  test  with  another  deuter- 
anope,  Mr.  A.  H.  P.,  are  substituted.  The  superiority  of  the 
Hegg  red  and  green  for  a  threshold  test  with  color-blind  subjects 
is  clearly  demonstrated.  Evidently  these  colors  approximate 
the  neutral  bands  of  the  partially  color-blind.  The  high 
thresholds  for  blue  and  yellow  may  possibly  indicate  a  slightly 
decreased  sensitivity  for  these  colors;  but  in  view  of  the 
difficulty  which  normal  observers  have  in  distinguishing  them, 
when  mixed  with  a  considerable  amount  of  bluish  grey,  it  is 
perhaps  unwise  to  come  to  such  a  conclusion  as  yet. 


TABI.E  II 

Showing  the  Color  Thresholds,  as  determined  hy 

means  of  the  Hegg  pigments 

upon  a  grey  background.    {Results  are  expressed  in  degrees.) 

RED 

GREEN 

YElvtOW 

BLUE 

Miss  G.  S.     Protanope 

Right  Eye 

X 

75 

100 

70 

Miss  M.  S.    Deuteranope 

Right  Eye 

240 

X 

X 

1 10 

Left  Eye 

250 

X 

270 

50 

Miss  H.  B.    Deuteranope 

Right  Eye 

X 

X 

X 

240 

Left  Eye 

X 

X 

X 

240 

Mr.  A.  H.  P.Deuteranope 

Right  Eye 

200 

X 

210 

90 

Miss  E.  C.    Deuteranope 

Right  Eye 

X 

270 

X 

315 

Left  Eye 

X 

340 

X 

X 

Miss  I.  B.     Deuteranope 

Right  Eye 

X 

55 

X 

125 

Left  Eye 

X 

X 

X 

70 

Average  of  40  eyes, — 24  women  who 

made  no  mistakes  with  the  Nagel  test 

57-1 

74.6 

98.8 

71.6 

For  the  general  thesis  of  this  paper,  the  most  important 
point  in  this  table  is  this,  that  almost  all  of  these  color-blind 
subjects  recognized  either  red  or  green  repeatedly,  when  a 
considerable  amount  was  given,  and  Miss  G.  S.  was  sure  of 
green  at  75°, — about  the  average  for  normal  observers. 

The  value  of  the  Hegg  pigments  as  confusion  colors  was 

Nrther  tested  by  showing  the  sheet  of  colors  painted  with  the 
^gg  pigments  to  a  considerable  number  of  color-blind  sub- 
cts  with  the  request  that  they  name  the  colors.  This  sheet 
easures  16  x  10  cm.  Across  the  middle  there  is  a  band  of 
jutral  grey  2.5  x  10  cm;  on  each  side  of  this  band  are  two 
itches  of  color  5  x  about  6.75  cm.  in  area,  the  red  and  the 
green  being  on  one  side,  the  blue  and  the  yellow  on  the  other. 
The  following  table,  number  III,  shows  how  these  colors  were 
named.  Of  course,  this  test  is  of  secondary  importance,  since 
a  shrewd  subject  might  readily  assume  that  the  four  fundamen- 
tal colors  were  displayed  and  then  guess  correctly  which  was 
red  and  which  was  green.  In  general,  however,  the  subjects 
did  not  seem  to  think  of  this ;  and  as  the  table  shows,  the  grey 
band  was  several  times  reported  to  be  colored. 


384  HAYES 


Table  III 

Showing  the 

names  that  were  employed  in  describing  the  Hegg  pigments 

RED 

GREEN 

GREY 

YEl^IvOW                   BLUB 

Miss  G.  vS 

Protanope       Grey 

Green 

Grey 

Grey                    Blue 

Miss  M.  S. 

Deuteranope  Pink 

Grey 

Grey 

Brown                 Blue 

Miss  E.  C. 

Deuteranope  Pink 

Grey 

Grey 

Grey                     Blue 

Miss  I.  B. 

Deuteranope  Red 

Green 

Grey 

Yellow                 Blue 

Mr.  A.  H.  P. 

Deuteranope  Grey 

Grey 

Grey 

Grayish- Yellow  Blue 

Miss  H.  B. 

Deuteranope  Grey 

Grey 

Grey 

Brown                  Blue 

Mr.  D.  B.  Y. 

Deuteranope  Grey 

Reddish 

L  Grey 

Grey                     Blue 

Mr.  M.  H.  H. 

Deuteranope  Grey 

Green 

Green 

Brown                  Blue 

Mr.J.F.McD.  Deuteranope  Red(?) 

Green 

Pink 

Yellow                 Blue 

Mr.  A.  B.  C. 

Deuteranope  Pink 

Green 

Green 

?                 Blue 

Mr.  C.  R.  B. 

Deuteranope  Red 

Brown 

Grey 

Red  or  Brown     Blue 

h.     Determination  of  the  distance  threshold  for  colors 

Upon  a  sheet  of  Hering  paper  (no.  14  grey),  four  rows  of 
squares  were  painted  with  the  Hegg  pigments,  —  three  hori- 
zontal rows  on  the  right  half  of  the  sheet,  and  one  row  at  the 
middle  of  the  left  half.  The  sizes  and  colors  of  these  patches 
were  as  follows: 

15  mm.  blue,  green,  red,  yellow. 
2.5  mm.  green,  red,  yellow,  blue.         5  mm.  red,  yellow,  blue,  green. 

ID  mm.  green,  blue,  yellow,  red. 

The  subject  was  stationed  14  meters  from  the  card,  with 
her  left  eye  covered.  She  was  asked  to  tell  whether  she  saw 
any  patches  of  color  upon  the  grey  sheet.  As  she  could  see 
none  at  that  distance,  she  was  asked  to  advance  slowly  until 
she  could  see  some  colored  patch.  At  3.5  meters  she  correctly 
named  the  largest  blue  square;  at  2,  the  largest  green  square; 
and  at  1.5,  the  largest  yellow  square.  The  smallest  squares 
were  recognized  at  o.  i  m.  She  wholly  failed  to  recognize  the 
red  patches  as  colored. 

Table  IV. 

Showing  the    distances    at   which    small    squares    of  colored    paper    were 
correctly  identified  {monocular  vision) 

DISTANCES  RIGHT  EYE  LEFT  EYE 

(expressed 
in  meters) 
14  15  mm.  Red 

13 
12 
II  15  mm.   Green  called  Green 

or  Blue 
10 
9 

8.5 

8  15  mm.  Blue;  15  mm.  Yellow 

called  White 


COLOR  SKNSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIALLY  COLOR-BLIND      385 


7 

6.5 

6 

5.5 
5 

4.5 

4 

3-5 

3 

2.5 

2 

1-5 
.5 
.1 


15  mm.  Blue 


15  mm.  Green;  10  mm.  Blue 
15  mm.  Yellow;  5  mm.  Blue; 
10  mm.  Yellow;  10  mm.  Green; 
5  mm.  Yellow;  5  mm.  Green 

2.5  mm  Blue;  2.5  Green; 
2.5  mm.  Yellow 


15  mm.  Yellow;  10  mm.  Red 


15  mm.  Green;  10  mm.  Blue; 
10  mm.  Yellow  called  White 
10  mm.  Green 

ID  mm.  Yellow 

5  mm.  Blue;  5  mm.  Red 
5  mm.  Green 

5  mm.  Yellow;  2.5  mm.  Red 
2.5  mm.  Blue;  2.5  nmi.  Green 
2.5  mm.  Yellow 


A  comparison  of  these  results  with  the  results  of  similar 
experiments  upon  twenty  normal  women  and  the  six  deuteran- 
opes  mentioned  in  Tables  I  and  II  shows  that  Miss  G.  S.  occupies 
a  middle  position  between  the  two  groups  in  her  recognition 
of  green.  Normal  women  recognize  the  largest  green  squares 
at  9  meters,  and  the  smallest  at  1.5  m;  Miss  G.  S.  recognized 
the  largest  green  squares  at  2  m.  and  the  smallest  at  o.i  m. 
Three  of  the  deuteranopes  did  not  recognize  the  green  squares 
of  any  size  at  any  distance;  and  the  three  who  did  recognize 
them  succeeded  at  about  the  same  distance  as  Miss  G.  S. 
When  one  remembers  that  this  subject's  visual  acuity,  in  her 
color-blind  eye,  is  somewhat  below  normal,  it  is  quite  surprising 
that  she  recognizes  green  so  well.  Possibly  her  inability  to  see 
yellow  or  blue  at  a  distance  is  to  be  explained  in  the  same  way, 
although  the  deuteranopes  also  have  considerable  difficulty 
with  these  colors,  especially  in  their  recognition  of  the  small 
squares.  Miss  G.  S.  did  not  appear  to  detect  the  red  patches 
at  all.  In  the  tests  with  her  left  eye.  Miss  G.  S,  compares 
favorably  with  the  normal  women. 

The  experiments  in  color  confusion  showed  very  plainly 
that  with  her  right  eye  Miss  G.  S.  is  color-blind  to  all  kinds  of 
reds  tried,  but  that  she  fails  to  recognize  green  only  when  it  is 
weak  or  mixed  with  blue.  The  experiments  upon  the  color 
threshold  and  the  distance  threshold  gave  similar  results.  To 
the  Hering  and  the  Hegg  reds  the  subject  is  quite  blind;  to 
both  the  Hering  and  the  Hegg  green,  however,  she  seems  to  be 
sensitive,  failing  to  recognize  them  only  when  they  are  quite 
reduced  in  saturation,  or  at  a  considerable  distance  from  her 
eye.  Her  color  threshold  for  green  is  conspicuously  lower 
than  that  of  the  other  color-blind  subjects.  It  would  seem 
then  that  if  the  subject  is  blind  to  any  kind  of  green,  presented 
in  saturated  form,  it  must  be  of  a  somewhat  different  tone 


386  HAYES 

from  the  Hering,  Hegg,  Holmgren,  Nagel  and  Bradley  greens. 
In  the  color  equations  to  be  described  later,  the  particular 
green  to  which  this  subject  is  insensitive  was  determined. 
But  it  is  already  pretty  obvious  that  this  subject's  color 
sensations  are  not  limited  to  blue  and  yellow.  If  her  two  eyes 
were  defective,  one  might  perhaps  explain  her  recognition  of 
green  from  an  employment  of  secondary  criteria  of  some  kind, 
such  as  we  have  to  assume  (lo,  71)  in  subjects  who  repeatedly 
recognize  greens  and  reds  in  experiments  with  colored  papers, 
but  are  able  to  see  only  yellow  and  blue  in  the  spectrum.  But 
since  Miss  G.  S.  sees  the  colors  normally  with  her  left  eye,  she 
has  a  clear  consciousness  of  green  as  a  quality  distinct  from 
yellow  or  grey;  and  when  she  uses  the  word  "green "  to  describe 
the  sensations  aroused  by  stimulation  of  her  right  (color- 
blind) eye,  we  must  assume  that  she  sees  green  as  green. 


c.    Campimetry  experiments 

Preliminary  experiments  were  performed  with  Hering 
papers.  The  standard  red,  yellow,  green,  and  blue  were  placed 
upon  a  color  mixer  one  at  a  time,  and  rotated  behind  a  grey 
screen,  through  which  a  hole  15  mm.  in  diameter  had  been  cut. 
Upon  the  screen  were  pasted  strips  of  millimeter  paper,  lead- 
ing away  from  the  hole  in  four  directions.  The  subject  fixed 
her  gaze  upon  a  pencil  point  which  was  moved  outward  or 
inward.  The  results  showed  coincidence  of  the  green  with 
the  yellow  and  blue  zones,  and  relatively  constricted  color 
areas  in  the  right  eye. 

Further  tests  were  made  with  the  Hegg  pigments  by  means 
of  a  small  perimeter.  In  these  tests  the  stimuli  were  always 
introduced  first  at  the  extreme  periphery,  and  every  precau- 
tion was  taken  to  prevent  the  subject  from  anticipating  which 
color  was  to  be  presented.  The  left  eye  showed  the  normal 
color  zones,  and  is  quite  comparable  with  the  eyes  of  five  nor- 
mal women  tested  in  the  same  way.  The  right  eye  again 
showed  coincidence  of  the  green  with  the  yellow  and  blue 
zones,  and  constricted  color  areas.  It  is,  of  course,  possible 
that  in  the  outer  color  zone  this  subject  confused  green  with 
yellow,  though  one  would  rather  expect  that  this  green  would 
there  appear  grey,  as  it  does  to  normal  eyes.  The  matter  is 
further  complicated  by  the  fact  that  the  subject  repeatedly 
recognized  it  as  green.  Blue  also  was  twice  called  "green." 
The  red  disc  was  called  "white"  and  seen  far  out  beyond  the 
color  zones.  Yellow  and  green  were  called  "white"  on  the 
extreme  periphery,  but  blue  was  twice  seen  first  as  "black." 


COLOR  SISNSATIONS  OP  THK  PARTIAI,I,Y  COI,OR-BI,IND      387 

d.     Contrast  and  Negative  After-images 

Ever  since  Stilling's  suggestion,  in  the  seventies,  that  con- 
trast shadows  might  be  successfully  used  for  the  diagnosis 
of  color-blindness,  many  experimenters  have  tested  the  ability 
of  the  color-blind  to  obtain  contrast  colors  (6,  15,  75)  and 
colored  after-images.^  The  writer  has  used  various  methods 
with  Miss  G.  S.  and  the  other  subjects, — contrast  rings  upon 
rotating  discs,  tissue  contrast  (grey  strip  on  a  color,  all  covered 
over  with  tissue  paper),  the  Hering  contrast  box  after  Ragona 
Scina's  method,  and  negative  after-images  from  colored  patch- 
es of  Hering  paper  9  cm.  square,  upon  grey  cards  40  x  50  cm., 
the  after-images  being  projected  upon  grey  cards  with  a 
black  fixation  dot  in  the  centre.  The  following  Table  shows 
the  results,  i.  e.,  the  colors  induced  in  the  various  experiments. 

Table  V 

Showing  the  color-names  which  were  employed  in  describing  the  induction 
effects  in  the  contrast  and  after-image  experiments 

NEGATIVE 


RINGS      TISSUE 

HERING  BOX 

AFTER-IMAGES 

Miss  G.  S.    Prot. 

Blue        Blue 

Blue 

Yellow     Yellow 

Yellow 

Mr.  J.  W.  P.  Prot. 

Blue  and  Yellow 

Miss  E.  C.    Deut. 

None       None 

Blue  and  Yellow 

Miss  I.  B.     Deut. 

Blue 
Yellow 

Miss  H.  B.    Deut. 

Blue 
Yellow 

Blue  and  Yellow 

Mr.D.B.Y.Deut. 

Blue  and  Yellow 

Blue 
Yellow 

In  general,  these  subjects  seemed  to  be  less  sensitive  to 
contrast  than  normal  observers.  Occasionally  a  subject 
would  report  a  slight  tinge  of  pink  or  green  as  an  induced  color, 
but  from  the  other  experiments  upon  the  same  subjects  it 
seemed  more  likely  that  the  words  were  used  by  chance,  as 
color  names  are  so  often  used  by  such  persons.  Generally 
blue  was  reported  as  the  contrast  color  both  for  red  and  for 
green,  though  often  only  a  brightness  contrast  was  noted. 


e.     Rapidity  of  color  discrimination 

Miss  G.  S.,  the  monocular  protanope,  and  four  of  the  women 
deuteranopes  were  tested  for  rapidity  in  sorting  into  6  piles, 
60  pieces  of  Milton  Bradley  paper  30  mm.  square,  mounted  on 
pieces  of  white  cardboard  88  mm,  square.^  All  five  subjects 
sorted  tints  and  shades  of  blue  and  yellow  more  rapidly  than 

^Von  Hippel  (29)  and  Guttmann  (16)  report  blue  and  yellow  after- 
images from  all  colors. 

^This  test  is  modeled  after  that  described  by  Henmon  (20). 


388  HAYES 

tints  and  shades  of  red,  orange-red  and  green.  Miss  G.  S. 
made  the  typical  confusions  with  reds,  putting  them  all  in 
one  pile  which  she  called  "black;"  but  she  correctly  sorted  and 
named  the  greens,  confusing  only  the  darker  shade  of  green 
with  the  standard  green.  The  other  subjects,  also,  showed 
considerable  ability  in  recognizing  and  correctly  sorting  reds 
and  greens.  Of  course,  it  is  possible  that  in  all  such  cases  the 
color-blind  is  assisted  by  secondary  criteria,  and  to  make  this 
test  of  real  value  colors  should  be  used  which  are  nearer  to  the 
reds  and  greens  which  the  color-blind  calls  grey,  such  as  the 
Hegg  pigments.  But  even  then  one  should  have  a  slightly 
different  set  for  protanopes  and  deuteranopes  in  order  that  the 
reds  and  greens  may  appear  to  be  greys  of  equal  brightness. 

/.     Experiments  with  Spectral  Lights 
(i).     With  the  Schmidt  and  Haensch  direct-vision  spectroscope 

The  subject  was  first  asked  to  look  through  the  spectro- 
scope toward  a  cloudy  sky,  and  read  off  in  wave-lengths  the 
limits  of  all  the  colors  she  could  see  with  her  right  eye.  But 
she  was  unable  to  do  this,  because  the  lenses  provided  with  the 
spectroscope  were  not  suited  to  correct  her  visual  defect.^ 

A  collection  of  pieces  of  Hering  paper  4  cm.  square  (in- 
cluding 2  pieces  of  each  of  the  1 2  colored  papers,  and  grays 
I,  5,  10,  15,  20,  25,  30,  35,  40,  45,  and  50)  was  then  spread  out 
upon  a  table;  and,  using  only  the  right  eye,  the  subject  was 
asked  to  select  papers  like  those  seen  in  the  spectroscope  and 
arrange  them  in  the  same  order.^  After  looking  into  the 
spectroscope  several  times,  the  following  papers  were  chosen 
and  arranged  in  the  order  given: — 50  grey,  20  grey,  5  grey, 
yellow  5,  green-yellow  6,  green-blue  8,  blue  10  and  violet  11. 
From  these  results  it  seems  highly  probable  that  the  red-end 
of  the  spectrum  is  colorless  and  shortened,  and  that  she  may 
have  seen  some  green.  Of  course,  there  is  the  alternative 
that  she  remembered  that  green  comes  between  yellow  and  blue 
in  the  spectrum ;  but  then  we  must  admit  that  she  sees  green 
in  the  colored  papers. 

When  the  papers  were  mixed  up  again,  and  the  experiment 
was  repeated  with  the  left  eye  only,  she  put  two  squares  of 
red  2,  and  one  of  yellow  5,  in  place  of  the  greys  at  the  red-end 
of  the  series. 

The  Schmidt  and  Haensch  spectroscope  was  found  to  be  a 
very  convenient  instrument  for  roughly  determining  whether 
or  not  a  subject's  spectrum  was   shortened  at  the  red-end. 

*  See  test  by  optician  mentioned  above  p.  378. 

'In  1878  Magnus  (45)  recommended  the  matching  of  spectral  colors  with 
Holmgren  wools  to  avoid  the  use  of  color  names. 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIAI.I,Y  COI.OR-BUND      389 


0 

•+J 

-3 

51 

•. 

s 

&> 

J 

<u 

; 

0 

&> 

S 

3 

; 

1 

= 

> 

> 

s 

pp 

PQ 

> 

s 

« 

pq 

p. 

iJ 

-t-> 

0) 

& 

"o 

w 

S 

^ 

i> 

P 

3 

Ul 

L4 

S 

(U 

(U 

0 

(U 

o; 

-(-> 

ii 

(U 

0 

0) 

&> 

(L) 

4; 

a 

4J 

a 

s 

d 

^ 

3 

3 

d 

3 

^ 

^ 

In 

•  1-4 

s 

0 

w 

s 

s 

« 

s 

> 

s 

w 

s 

W 

0. 

a 

OJ 

i 

P 

^ 

^ 

: 

r»-. 

^ 
^ 

: 

2 

'd 

a 

^ 

;§ 

; 

1 

"S 

"S 

13 

(U 

«-i 

a> 

u 

u 

0 

>H 

>^ 

>H 

rt 

0 

>^ 

0 

>^ 

^ 

0 

q 

§ 

1 

i 

0 

S 

^ 

^ 

^ 

rt 

^ 

a 

1 

^ 

0 

0 

0 

§ 
^ 

0 

^ 

0 

'S 

^ 

3 

" 

* 

-s 

2 

^ 

^ 

»v. 

^ 

>^ 

>^ 

>< 

0 

>* 

p< 

0 

>^ 

>^ 

i 

1 

1           '              " 

^ 

_Q 

^ 

> 

Q 

l4 

W 

0 

« 

^ 

^ 

g 

^ 

0) 

TJ 

TJ 

^ 

TJ 

Td 

^ 

•d 

0 

•0 

TJ 

i!^ 

0) 

0) 

U 

o; 

^ 

OJ 

«H 

0) 

a> 

0 

P^ 

(^ 

>^ 

P^ 

6 

rt 

0 

P^ 

>H 

P< 

rt 

S 

0 

0 

0 

0 

0 

0 

0 

0 

0 

0 

0 

0 

s. 

r»-. 

c< 

»o 

>D 

>o 

»o 

T*- 

«o 

VO 

»o 

»o 

>o 

«o 

s 

vO 

VO 

VO 

VO 

VO 

VO 

VO 

VO 

VO 

VO 

VO 

VO 

^ 

hJ 

^ 

■^ 

■M 

+j 

4J 

-M 

•t-i 

-M 

-w 

^J 

0 

n 

s 

3 

S 

S 

S 

;3 

;:! 

;J 

g 

2 

2 

(U 

(U 

0) 

<u 

a> 

(U 

(U 

(U 

V 

lU 

p: 

PLh 

p 

Q 

Q 

Q 

Q 

Q 

^ 

^ 

Q 

Q 

PM 

,-x 

m 

pq 

CJ 

W 

1 

rt 

■Ph* 

CO 

>^* 

ui 

^ 

CO 

pi 

^ 

CJ 

« 

W 

to 

Q 

w 

n 

pci 

6 
1 

•-% 

0 

d 

J 

< 

^ 

^ 

0 

<i 

to 

Q 

u 

<^ 

v* 

u 

u 

v^ 

u 

111 

wl 

u 

S 

^ 

s 

S 

:^ 

1^ 

s 

1^ 

S 

s 

s 

s 

S 

Journal — 5 


390  HAYlBS 

And  while  the  subject  was  using  the  instrument,  the  experi- 
menter asked  what  colors  were  visible.  None  of  the  subjects 
claimed  to  see  more  than  three  colors,  although  several  of  them 
recognized  the  instrument  and  knew  what  colors  they  ought 
to  see.  No  great  importance  is  attached  to  the  use  of  color 
names  in  the  following  table,  although  several  of  the  subjects 
who  claimed  to  see  colors  other  than  blue  and  yellow  showed 
a  similar  ability  to  distinguish  these  colors  in  other  experiments. 
Other  experimenters  (28)  have  noted  the  tendency  of  color- 
blind subjects  to  see  three  colors  when  the  whole  spectrum  is 
shown  at  once ;  and  it  was  a  matter  for  regret  that  our  instru- 
ment had  not  an  attachment  for  exposing  one  color  at  a  time.^ 
Table  VI  gives  the  results  of  these  experiments. 

(2) .     Viewing  a  petroleum  flame  through  a  spectroscope 

It  was  attempted  to  determine  the  length  of  Miss  G.  S.'s 
spectrum  by  having  the  subject  set  the  instrument  in  such  a 
position  that  all  color  appeared  at  the  right  of  the  vertical 
line  across  the  centre  of  the  field  of  the  spectroscope.  The 
setting  of  the  instrument  was  read  off  in  degrees.  The  instru- 
ment was  then  adjusted  until  all  color  was  at  the  left  of  the 
vertical  line.     The  following  table  shows  the  results  obtained. 

Table    VII 

Showing  the   Limits   of  Visibility  in  the  Spectrum.     {Results  expressed  in 
terms  of  our  scale  readings.) 

RED  END     VIOLET  END 

Miss  G.  S.    Right  Eye,  Protanopic  285°  282°    9' 

Left  Eye,  Normal  285°  40'  281°  28' 

Miss  M.  S.    Right  Eye,  Deuteranopic  285°  33'  281°  21' 

MissL.  D.    Right  Eye  Normal  285°  40'  281°  40' 

Mr.  S.  P.  H.  Right  Eye  Normal  285^26'  281°  25' 

The  typical  shortening  at  the  red  end  is  plainly  seen  in 
the  case  of  Miss  G.  S.'s  protanopic  right  eye;  there  would  seem 
to  be  a  shortening  at  the  violet  end  also. 

( j) .     Experiment  with  bisulphide  of  carbon  prisms 

A  wide  beam  of  light  was  sent  from  an  electric  lantern 
through  two  slits  and  then  through  two  bisulphide  of  carbon 
prisms^  placed  side  by  side  in  a  darkened  room.  The  two 
spectra  produced,  were  interrupted  at  two  meters  by  a  screen 
in  which  two  slits  had  been  cut,  so  that  on  the  next  screen 
beyond,  two  patches  of  colored  light  could  be  seen,  each  6  cm. 
high  and  i  cm.  wide.     The  prisms  rested  upon  discs  of  card- 

^Cohn  (7,  pp.  84  f.)  describes  such  an  instrument. 

2Made  by  Wm.  Gaertner  &  Co.,  Chicago,  111.,  Cat.  No.  L,  4025. 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  O^  THE  PARTIALLY  COLOR-BLIND      39 1 

board,  which  were  held  in  place  by  thumb  tacks  pushed  through 
the  centre  of  each.  These  discs  could  be  rotated  easily  to 
right  or  left ;  and  by  this  means  the  colors  seen  on  the  farthest 
screen  could  be  changed  from  red  to  violet.  The  movements 
necessary  to  cause  these  changes  in  color  were  so  slight 
that  the  vividness  of  the  colors  was  not  materially  affected; 
and  in  the  case  of  red,  green,  blue  and  violet,  the  colored 
patch  was  approximately  monochromatic.  Yellow  always 
had  a  fringe  of  orange  an  one  side,  or  of  green  on  the  other. 

The  subject  was  seated  in  front  of  the  last  screen,  about 
one  meter  from  it,  where  she  could  not  see  any  colors  except 
those  shown  in  the  two  patches. 

As  a  preliminary  experiment,  the  subject  was  asked  to  close 
her  left  eye,  and  name  the  colors  shown  her.  Only  one  prism 
was  used  in  this  experiment.  This  prism  was  turned  so  that 
the  extreme  red  appeared  on  the  farther  screen.  The  subject 
reported  no  color,  so  the  prism  was  very  slowly  rotated  until 
the  subject  said  she  saw  "yellow."  The  colors  then  in  the 
patch  were  yellow  and  orange.  The  prism  was  then  moved 
slowly  again ;  and  as  soon  as  the  yellow  began  to  turn  greenish, 
the  subject  said  she  saw  "green."  She  continued  to  report 
green  until  that  color  was  no  longer  visible  to  the  experimenter, 
and  then  she  at  once  said  she  saw  "blue,"  which  she  continued 
to  report  well  out  into  the  violet.  The  subject  was  then  asked 
to  rest  her  eyes,  and  the  prism  was  turned  back  until  the  patch 
was  a  strong  pure  red.  The  subject  was  now  asked  to  tell 
what  she  saw,  and  she  replied  that  she  saw  a  patch  of  "grey." 

oc.     Color  comparison  with  two  prisms 

The  subject  turned  away  from  the  screen,  and  both  prisms 
were  illuminated.  The  left  prism  was  set  so  that  it  gave  a 
pure  green  patch,  the  right  prism  at  the  extreme  red.  The 
subject  was  then  asked  to  look  at  the  screen  with  her  right 
eye  only,  and  report  what  she  saw.  She  replied  that  the  left 
patch  was  green  and  the  right  grey.  She  was  then  instructed 
to  watch  the  patches  and  tell  when  they  looked  just  alike. 
The  right  prism  was  then  slowly  turned,  and  not  until  both 
patches  were  pure  green  did  the  subject  judge  them  alike. 
Evidently  it  was  impossible  to  match  spectral  green  with 
spectral  red  or  yellow  of  any  kind. 

The  subject  turned  away  from  the  screen  again;  the  left 
prism  was  now  set  at  red,  and  the  right  at  the  extreme  violet. 
She  reported  that  she  saw  grey  at  the  left  and  faint  blue  at 
the  right.  The  right  prism  was  slowly  turned,  with  frequent 
stops,  but  she  was  not  satisfied  with  the  match  until  this  prism 
also  gave  a  pure  red  patch.     In  this  test  the  attempt  to  match 


392  HAYES 

red  with  blue-green,  green  or  yellow  was  unsuccessful.  No 
attempt  was  made  to  equate  brightnesses;  the  subject  insisted 
throughout  that  there  was  a  qualitative  difference. 

These  experiments  with  spectral  lights  emphasize  the  same 
fact  that  was  indicated  in  the  experiments  with  colored  papers 
and  the  Hegg  pigments, — that  the  subject  is  blind  to  red,  but 
not  blind  to  green. 

p.     Determination  of  the  Color  Threshold  with  Spectral  Lights 

Only  one  prism  was  illuminated,  and  an  episkotister  was 
set  up  just  beyond  the  screen  with  the  slits  in  it.  The  prism 
was  turned  to  give  pure  green  on  the  patch,  the  episkotister 
set  at  5°  and  rotated  by  means  of  an  electric  motor.  The 
subject  was  asked  to  look  with  her  right  (protanopic)  eye  at 
the  screen  where  the  left  colored  patch  had  appeared  in  the 
earlier  experiments.  She  reported  that  she  could  see  nothing. 
She  closed  her  eye  and  the  episkotister  was  set  at  io°.  The 
subject  now  reported  that  she  saw  green,  although  there  had 
been  no  intimation  on  the  part  of  the  experimenter  that  green 
would  be  the  first  color  shown.  The  prism  was  moved  back 
and  forth,  but  she  could  recognize  no  other  color.  The  epis- 
kotister was  set  at  8,  6  and  4  degrees  in  successive  tests;  but 
below  10°  the  subject  saw  no  color.  At  6°  she  claimed  she 
saw  a  faint  line  of  light  when  the  prism  was  turned  to  green. 

The  episkotister  was  again  set  at  10°,  and  the  prism  moved 
back  and  forth;  green  alone  was  recognized.  At  15°  no  other 
color  was  seen.  The  episkotister  was  opened  5°  at  a  time, 
in  successive  tests,  and  the  prism  turned  through  the  series 
of  colors,  with  each  new  opening.  At  30°,  blue  was  recognized 
and  at  55°,  yellow. 

No  definite  attempt  was  made  in  these  experiments  to 
attain  dark  adaptation  in  the  right  eye.  There  was  consid- 
erable light  in  that  part  of  the  room  where  the  lantern  was 
stationed;  and  in  most  of  the  experiments  the  subject  gazed 
about  freely  during  the  intervals  between  tests.  In  this 
particular  series  of  tests,  however,  the  subject  was  asked  to 
close  her  eye  while  the  episkotister  was  being  adjusted,  so 
that  she  might  not  see  what  changes  were  being  made.  The 
conditions,  then,  were  favorable  for  dark  adaptation,  and  we 
cannot  say  with  certainty  whether  the  extreme  brightness  of 
the  green  was  merely  a  manifestation  of  the  Purkinje  phenome- 
non in  dim  light,  or  the  displacement  of  the  maximal  bright- 
ness which  we  would  expect  of  a  protanope  even  without  dark 
adaptation. 

The  experiment  was  repeated  with  the  left  eye  only,  and 
all  four  colors,  red,  yellow,  green  and  blue,  were  repeatedly 
recognized  and  correctly  named  at  5°  opening. 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THK  PARTIALITY  COLOR-BLIND      393 

Of  course  these  experiments  with  a  home-made  spectral 
apparatus  are  open  to  the  grave  criticism  that  no  provision 
was  made  for  determining  objectively  just  what  lights  were 
given  to  the  subject, — instead  of  a  statement  of  the  exact  wave 
length  of  the  patches  of  color  exposed,  the  reader  has  only  the 
writer's  assurance  that  red,  green,  etc.,  were  given.  But  the 
apparatus  necessary  to  conduct  this  experiment  objectively 
was  too  expensive  to  be  bought  from  the  funds  of  a  small 
laboratory;  and  since  the  results  of  these  rough  tests  are  quite 
in  harmony  with  those  obtained  by  the  use  of  colored  papers, 
they  certainly  add  considerable  weight  to  the  total  mass  of 
evidence  in  favor  of  the  view  that  this  protanope  is  not  blind 
to  green.  It  should  also  be  said  that  repeated  tests  have 
shown  the  experimenter's  color  sense  to  be  perfectly  normal, 
so  that  there  is  no  possibility  that  wrong  colors  were  given  by 
mistake. 

From  the  experiments  thus  far  described,  certain  conclusions 
regarding  the  color  sensations  of  Miss  G.  S.  seem  amply 
justified.  There  can  be  no  doubt  that  her  right  eye  is  totally 
insensitive  to  the  quality  red.  She  never  used  the  word  red 
to  describe  any  sensations  obtained  through  her  right  eye, 
in  any  of  the  experiments.  It  seems  equally  clear  that  her 
right  eye  is  not  insensitive  to  the  quality  green.  With  scarcely 
a  single  error,  she  repeatedly  recognized  green  in  the  Nagel 
cards,  the  Holmgren  worsteds,  the  Milton  Bradley  and  Hering 
papers,  in  gelatine  films,  in  prints  painted  with  water  colors, 
in  spectral  lights,  and  in  the  Hegg  pigments.  And  since 
she  is  familiar  with  the  quality  green,  through  the  use  of  her 
normal  left  eye,  we  must  grant  that  the  sensation  which  she  cor- 
rectly names  "  green  ",  when  her  right  (protanopic)  eye  is  stimu- 
lated, is  probably  the  same  sensation-quality  which  normal 
persons  describe  by  the  use  of  the  term  "green."  In  other 
words,  her  spectrum  is  not  reduced  to  blue  and  yellow,  although 
in  general  she  shows  the  ordinary  characteristics  of  protanopia. 
When  the  greens  used  are  reduced  in  saturation  or  in  bright- 
ness, however,  or  when  only  a  very  small  patch  of  color  is 
presented,  Miss  G.  S.  shows  herself  somewhat  less  sensitive 
to  green  than  normal  persons.  She  shows  a  slightly  sub- 
normal sensitivity  for  blue  and  yellow  also ;  but  these  colors 
are  less  affected  than  green. 

It  is  considerably  more  difficult  to  decide  whether  the  other 
subjects  see  either  red  or  green  as  normal  persons  do.  There 
is,  of  course,  no  doubt  that  color-blind  subjects  can  distinguish 
many  reds  and  greens  from  each  other  and  from  yellows 
and  blues.  Some  of  the  subjects  mentioned  in  this  paper 
showed  a  good  deal  of  facility  in  distinguishing  colors,  so  that 
from  day  to  day  the  writer  hesitated  whether  or  not  to  class 


394  HAYES 

them  as  color-blind.  This  decision  was,  however,  somewhat 
simplified  by  a  change  in  mental  state  on  the  part  of  several 
of  the  doubtful  subjects.  Misses  H.  E.  and  E.  C,  for  instance, 
long  maintained  that  it  was  ridiculous  to  class  them  as  color- 
blinds,  insisting  that  they  could  distinguish  the  reds  and  greens 
one  encounters  in  the  daily  use  of  colored  objects,  even  though 
they  could  not  always  correctly  name  the  weak  colors  with 
which  they  were  tested  in  the  laboratory ;  but  after  a  considera- 
ble number  of  equations  had  been  made,  and  the  results 
exhibited  to  them,^  these  subjects  took  a  more  calm  and  object- 
ive attitude  in  the  matter,  frankly  giving  themselves  up  to  the 
task  of  ascertaining  just  how  much  their  color  sense  was  affect- 
ed, and  even  recounting  instances  in  which  their  friends  had 
detected  their  errors  in  the  naming  of  colors.  In  order  to 
eliminate  the  "secondary  criteria"  by  which  such  subjects 
are  supposed  to  distinguish  colors,^  as  many  as  possible  of  these 
subjects  also  were  tested  with  spectral  lights,  using  an  arrange- 
ment of  apparatus  similar  to  that  used  with  Miss  G.  S.  But  a 
lime  light  was  substituted  for  electricity,  the  experiment  was 
performed  in  a  dark  room,  and  the  carbon  bisulphide  prisms 
were  placed  one  above  the  other  with  a  movable  slit  in  front 
of  each  to  give  the  different  colors.  Three  of  the  subjects,^ 
the  protanope  and  two  deuteranopes,  reported  only  blue  and 
yellow;  red,  yellow  and  green  all  looked  alike  to  them,  but 
no  equation  between  red  and  blue-green  could  be  made, 
because  the  blue-green  was  reported  to  be  whitish  and  lacking 
in  the  yellowish  tinge  which  they  saw  in  the  red.  These 
three  subjects,  however,  are  extreme  cases  of  color-blindness. 
Misses  E.  C.  and  I.  B.  insisted  that  they  saw  red  as  a  color 
distinct  from  yellow,  and  repeatedly  recognized  it.  Miss  I.  B., 
whose  color  defect  is  the  least  marked  of  all  the  cases  reported 
in  this  paper,  recognized  green  also  with  quite  as  much  cer- 
tainty as  the  extreme  cases  did  blue  and  yellow.  And  since 
these  two  subjects  are  the  ones  who  have  showed  the  greatest 
keenness  in  distinguishing  reds  and  greens  in  the  other  tests, 
one  must  interpret  this  as  another  indication  that  only  extreme 
cases  of  partial  color-blindness  are  limited  to  blue  and  yellow. 

J.     Color  Equations 
a.     Equations  with  the  Hering  color  sense  apparatus^ 
This  apparatus  is  so  constructed  that  the  subject,  on  looking 

^Following  Maxwell's  suggestion  (46,  p.  287)  thesubjects were  occasionally 
requested  to  look  at  their  equations  through  a  colored  glass.  The  inequality 
in  the  mixtures  thus  demonstrated  helped  greatly  in  inducing  the  objective 
attitude. 

^Differences  in  brightness,  saturation,  color  associations,  etc.    10  p.  210. 

^Mr.  J.  W.  P.  (protanope),  Mr.  D.  B.  Y.  (deuteranope),  and  Miss 
H.  B.  (deuteranope). 

*This  instrument  is  described  and  figured  by  Hering  (24). 


COIvOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THIS  PARTIAI.I.Y  COLOR-BUND      395 

down  a  dark  tube  may  see  a  disc  one  half  of  which  is  colored 
by  light  filtered  through  one  colored  glass,  the  other  half  by  a 
mixture  of  lights  transmitted  through  two  glasses.  The 
intensity  of  the  color  presented  is  varied  by  the  amount  of 
light  reflected  through  the  colored  glasses  from  movable 
reflectors,  whose  position  is  indicated  upon  a  dial.  It  is  thus 
fairly  easy  to  form  color  equations,  such  as  red  =  green  + 
blue,  etc. ;  and  to  read  off  from  the  dial  the  amount  of  light 
passing  through  each  glass.  When  fully  open  the  reflectors 
register  120  units.  The  following  table  shows  the  result  of  the 
experiments  with  this  apparatus  upon  Miss  G.  S.  and  various 
other  subjects. 


TABI.E  VIII 

• 

Equations  with  the  Hering  Color  Sense  Apparatus. 

(Results  are  expressed 

in 

degrees 

,  120 

being  the 

maximum 

reading  possible) 

. GREEN  : 

=  RED  + 

BIvUE 

RED=GREEN  +  BLUE 

Miss  G.  S. 

Prot. 

R. 

40 

120 

120 

120 

60 

120 

Mr.  J.  C.  H. 

Deut. 

R. 

30 

70 

90 

Deut. 

L. 

30 

62 

90 

Miss  M.  S. 

Deut. 

R. 

40 

120 

75 

60 

120 

50 

Deut. 

L. 

30 

120 

95 

35 

120 

90 

Miss  H.  E. 

Deut. 

R. 

80 

60 

120 

Deut 

L. 

60 

50 

120 

Miss  G.  B. 

Deut. 

R. 

50 

45 

120 

120 

120 

120 

Deut. 

L. 

80 

85 

120 

120 

120 

30 

Miss  H.  B. 

Deut. 

R. 

120 

120 

0 

Mr.  D.  B.  Y. 

Deut. 

R. 

120 

120 

0 

Miss  E.  C. 

Deut. 

R. 

120 

55 

120 

120 

120 

120 

Deut. 

L. 

120 

120 

120 

120 

120 

120 

Miss  I.  B. 

Deut. 

R. 

33 

25 

35 

Deut. 

L. 

20 

55 

20 

120 

50 

80 

Miss  L.  W. 

Deut. 

R. 

120 

25 

50 

Deut. 

L. 

120 

40 

60 

Mr.  J.  W.  P. 

Prot. 

R. 

108 

120 

30 

The  wide  variation  in  the  results  for  different  subjects  can 
probably  be  partly  accounted  for  by  differences  in  the  amount 
of  sunlight  on  different  days,  or  at  different  hours  of  the  day.^ 
But  the  constant  insistence  of  many  subjects,  besides  the  mo- 
nocular protanope,  that  they  saw  red  or  green  when  more 
than  a  certain  amount  of  either  color  was  used,  gives  added 
evidence  that  many  color-blind  are  not  dichromates.  Miss 
G.  S.  was  very  sure  she  saw  green  when  50  was  given  alone, 
or  70  mixed  with  blue. 

The  instrument  would  be  greatly  improved  if  four  glasses 
could  be  used  at  the  same  time,  so  that  blue  could  be  mixed 

tboth  with  red  and  with  green  simultaneously.     The  subjects 


^A  series  of  experiments  upon  Miss  H.  E.  (Deut.)  extending  over  5  days 
in  the  spring  of  1909  showed  a  variation  of  from  20  red  on  a  bright  day, 
to  120  red  on  a  dark  day. 


396  HAYES 

were  told  that  a  colorless  equation  was  to  be  made;  and  the 
small  amounts  of  red  or  green  allowed  when  given  alone  may- 
be attributed  to  the  natural  confusion  of  these  colors  with 
yellow,  and  the  insistence  that  the  single  glass  should  appear 
colorless.  A  slight  admixture  of  blue  would  obviate  this  diffi- 
culty. But  the  small  amount  of  red  or  green  allowed  by  some 
subjects,  when  mixed  with  a  large  amount  of  blue,  remains  as 
evidence  for  the  main  thesis  of  this  paper, — that  red  or  green 
sensations  may  be  possible  to  the  partially  color-blind. 

It  seems  quite  likely  that  the  neutral  grey  bands  of  differ- 
ent deuteranopes  may  occupy  slightly  different  regions  of  the 
spectrum  (40,  p.  158).  If  this  is  the  case,  those  whose  bands 
are  most  nearly  represented  by  the  particular  red  and  green 
glasses  of  the  Hering  apparatus  would  accept  a  much  larger 
amount  of  red  or  green  when  given  alone  in  this  instrument. 

b.     Equations  obtained  with  rotating  discs 

Ever  since  Maxwell's  work  (46,  47)  with  rotating  discs  in 
the  fifties,  it  has  been  customary  to  make  color  equations 
which  shall  indicate  the  extent  of  color  confusion  to  which 
color-blind  subjects  are  liable,  and  to  determine  whether  all 
colors  can  be  matched  by  the  mixture  of  blue  and  yellow,  black 
and  white. 

(i).     The  Rayleigh  equation 

It  is  commonly  asserted  (41,  64)  that  all  equations  which 
hold  for  normal  observers  will  be  found  to  hold  also  for  the 
partially  color-blind.  From  a  theoretical  point  of  view,  one 
would  expect  that  deuteranopes,  at  least,  who  are  blind  to 
both  red  and  green,  would  accept  all  normal  equations;  and 
the  writer  found  that  all  the  deuteranopes  tested  with  such 
equations  did  accept  them.  But  in  protanopia,  the  shift  of 
maximum  brightness  might  be  expected  to  vitiate  the  equa- 
tion somewhat.  It  was  mainly  to  test  the  validity  of  this 
assumption  that  Miss  G.  S.  was  tested  with  the  equation  red 
-f  green  =  yellow;  but  the  unexpected  result  of  the  experi- 
ment led  to  the  testing  of  a  number  of  the  other  subjects  in  the 
same  way. 

The  normal  Rayleigh  equation, — the  equation  accepted 
on  a  bright  day  by  a  number  of  normal,  trained  observers, 
from  which  30  untrained  observers  varied  by  only  about  10 
degrees, — was  presented  to  the  subject.  Miss  G.  S.  found 
the  mixture  much  too  green,  and  was  not  satisfied  until  the 
green  was  reduced  to  63°.  All  the  other  subjects  accepted 
not  only  the  normal  equation,  but  also  wide  variations  from 
it.     The  following  table  gives  the  normal  equation  with  the 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  01^  THE  PARTIALITY  COLOR-BLIND      397 

Hering  papers,  the  equation  formed  for  Miss  G.  S.  and  the 
extreme  amounts  of  red  and  green  accepted  by  the  other  obser- 
vers. The  amounts  of  yellow,  black  and  white  are  omitted, 
as  not  pertinent  to  the  question. 

Tabls  IX 
Rayleigh  equation  of  color-blind  subjects 

RHU  +  GREIBN  ==  YBlylvOW  +  WHITE   +  BIvACK 

278 
290 


Normal  Equation 

175 

185 

33 

49 

Miss  G.  S. 

Prot. 

R. 

297 

63 

70 

Extremes 

allowed  by 

other  color 

-blind 

RED  +  GREEN 

RED  +  G 

REEN 

Mr.  J.  W.  P. 

Prot. 

R. 

300 

60 

0 

360 

Miss  M.  S. 

Deut. 

R. 

315 

45 

90 

270 

Miss  H.  E. 

Deut. 

R. 

225 

135 

no 

250 

Deut. 

L. 

225 

135 

75 

285 

Miss  E.  C. 

Deut. 

R. 

182 

178 

65 

295 

Deut. 

L. 

190 

170 

95 

265 

Miss  I.  B. 

Deut. 

R. 

192 

168 

160 

2CO 

Deut. 

L. 

190 

170 

125 

235 

Miss  L.  W. 

Deut. 

R. 

190 

170 

160 

200 

Deut. 

L. 

200 

160 

160 

200 

Miss  H.  B. 

Deut. 

R. 

190 

170 

130 

230 

Mr.  D.  B.  Y 

Deut. 

R. 

300 

60 

0 

360 

Mr.  A.  H.  P. 

Deut. 

R. 

178 

182 

50 

310 

The  wide  variation  in  the  amounts  of  red  and  green  accepted 
in  the  Rayleigh  equation  by  these  subjects  is  in  striking 
contrast  with  the  results  obtained  with  Miss  G.  S.  who  would 
not  allow  a  variation  of  more  than  5°  in  the  green.  In  this 
she  resembles  the  anomalous  trichromates  discovered  by  the 
use  of  this  equation,  as  she  does  also  in  her  sensitiveness  to 
green  in  the  other  experiments.  But  in  view  of  the  fact  that, 
unlike  them,  she  is  completely  lacking  in  sensitivity  to  red,  has 
a  neutral  band  in  the  blue-green  {cf.  the  experiments  with  the 
Plering  color-sense  apparatus  p.  395),  and  appears  to  get  no 
contrast  colors  nor  after-images  from  red  or  green,  she  would 
seem  to  be  more  properly  classed  with  the  protanopes  than 
with  the  anomalous  trichromates.  Nagel  (52)  reports  a 
similar  experience  with  the  Rayleigh  equation,  in  comparing 
his  own  vision  with  that  of  two  normal  observers.  Their 
equation,  made  up  of  about  180°  each  of  red  and  of  green, 
seemed  very  red  to  him,  and  had  to  be  changed  to  between  140 
and  150  red  on  a  dark  day,  and  to  between  89  and  95  red  on  a 
bright  day.  His  variation  was  then  hardly  more  than  that 
of  Miss  G.  S. 

It  will  also  be  noticed  that  some  subjects  show  a  much  wider 
variation  than  others.  The  subjects  who  vary  between  the 
widest  limits  in  this  equation  are  the  subjects  who  made  the 
worst  confusions  of  colors  in  the  other  tests,  and  have  therefore 
been  classed  by  the  writer  as  extreme  cases  of  color-blindness. 


398  HAYES 

The  subjects  whose  Rayleigh  equations  did  not  exhibit  such 
wide  variations  are  those  who  have  shown  such  keen  sensitivity 
to  reds  and  greens  that  it  has  often  seemed  absurd  to  class 
them  as  color-bHnds  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  they  signally 
fail  in  such  tests  as  those  of  Nagel,  Holmgren  and  Stilling,  and 
accept  an  equation  in  which  a  weak  bluish  red  is  matched  with 
a  weak  bluish  green  upon  the  color  mixer.  These  cases  re- 
mind one  of  Holmgren's  "incompletely  color-blind"  (31, 
33,  pp.  40-41);  their  acceptance  of  the  normal  Rayleigh 
equation  excludes  them  from  the  group  of  anomalous  trichro- 
mates. 

All  the  subjects  objected  to  wider  extremes  of  red  and  green 
by  correctly  naming  red  or  green  when  either  one  was  increased 
beyond  the  limits  finally  decided  upon;  they  insisted  that  the 
mixture  was  different  in  quality  from  the  dirty  yellow  with 
which  it  was  being  matched,  no  matter  how  the  yellow  mix- 
ture was  varied.  Now,  since  dichromates  are  supposed  to  see 
red  and  green  as  yellow,  it  is  difficult  to  imagine  how  they  were 
able  to  detect  the  reds  and  greens  under  the  conditions,  unless 
we  grant  the  possibility  that  they  may  have  some  sense  of 
red  and  green  as  a  color  quality  distinct  from  yellow. 

(2).  The  dichr ornate  equation 
The  confusion  of  red  with  green  has,  from  the  beginning, 
been  regarded  as  one  of  the  chief  peculiarities  of  the  color- 
blind; but  it  was  soon  observed  that,  even  in  extreme  cases 
of  color-blindness,  the  subject  did  not  confuse  all  greens  and 
all  reds.  It  is  now  well  established  that  those  reds  and  greens 
which,  like  the  physiological  primaries,  have  a  bluish  tinge, 
and  are  somewhat  unsaturated,  are  most  likely  to  be  confused, 
since  they  both  appear  colorless  to  the  color-blind.  In  the 
dichr omate  equation,  the  attempt  was  made  to  make  an 
equation  in  which  green  was  declared  to  be  identical  with 
red,  adding  to  both  sides  as  little  blue,  black  and  white  as 
possible.     The  following  table  gives  the  results  of  these  tests. 


Table  X 

Dichromate  equations 

RED  -f-BLUE  -h  WHITE- 

=GREEN 

-f- BLUE -|- BLACK -f- WHITE 

Miss  G.  S.     Prot. 

R.  360 

38 

22 

300 

Mr.  J.  W.  P.  Prot. 

R.  262 

98 

330 

30 

Miss  M.  S.    Deut. 

R.  230       55 

75 

360 

Miss  H.  E.    Deut. 

R.  290 

70 

300 

45 

15 

Miss  G.  B.    Deut. 

R.  210       50 

100 

270 

90 

Miss  H.Y.B.  Deut. 

R.  210       45 

105 

280 

80 

Mr.  A.  H.  P. Deut. 

R.  300 

60 

220 

140 

Mr.  D.B.Y.  Deut. 

R.  232       40 

88 

260 

35 

65 

Miss  E.  C.     Deut. 

R.  100       73 

187 

107 

53 

200 

Miss  I.  B.      Deut. 

L.     50       55 

255 

85 

55 

220 

Miss  L.  W.    Deut. 

R.     50     200 

no 

198 

45 

87 

30 

COLOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIAI^LY  COIyOR-BUND      399 

The  most  striking  point  in  this  table  is  the  very  small 
amount  of  green  allowed  by  Miss  G.  S.  When  more  was  in- 
troduced, she  at  once  objected  to  it,  insisting  that  the  mixture 
then  had  a  greenish  tinge.  As  the  subjects  were  kept  in 
complete  ignorance  in  regard  to  the  changes  made  in  these 
equations,  it  is  difficult  to  understand  how  she  could  repeatedly 
make  correct  judgments,  if  she  did  not  see  green  somewhat 
as  normal  persons  do. 

The  relatively  small  amounts  of  red  and  green  allowed  by  the 
last  three  subjects  is  also  striking.  When  more  red  or  green 
was  added,  they  were  quite  as  sure  of  the  change  as  was  Miss 
G.  S.  in  the  case  of  green;  and  no  increase  in  the  amount  of 
blue  served  to  cancel  the  additional  red  or  green,  as  one  would 
expect  if  red  and  green  appear  yellowish  to  these  subjects. 
To  be  sure,  other  tests  have  shown  that  these  three  subjects 
are  mild  cases  of  color-blindness;  but  such  cases  are  quite 
valuable  for  the  main  contention  of  this  paper,  that  people 
properly  classed  as  color-blinds  have  some  sensations  of  red 
and  green. 

( j) .     Monocular  comparison  of  colors 

In  order  to  test  still  further  the  claim  that  all  colors  per- 
ceived by  the  color-blind  can  be  matched  by  mixtures  of  blue 
and  yellow,  and  at  the  same  time  to  obtain  a  full  statement 
of  the  appearance  of  the  different  colors,  each  of  the  Hering 
papers  was  rotated  before  Miss  G.  S.'s  protanopic  right  eye, 
and  matched  by  a  mixture  of  colors  rotated  before  her  left 
eye.  Two  color-mixers  were  set  up  and  operated  behind  a 
screen,  and  the  subject  looked  through  two  blackened  card- 
board tubes  6  cm.  in  diameter  and  55  cm.  long.  In  this  way 
she  saw  only  the  standard  papers  with  her  right  eye  and  only 
the  mixtures  with  her  left.  The  results  appear  in  the  appen- 
ded table. 

Table  XI 
Showing  how  the  Hering  papers  appear  to  a  protanopic  eye 

BLUB 


YELLOW- 

BLUE- 

WHITE 

BLACK 

YELLOW 

GREEN 

GREEN 

GREEN 

Red  No.  I 

35 

325 

Red  No.  2 

10 

340 

10 

Orange  3 

75 

170 

115 

Y-Orange  4 

105 

62 

193 

Yellow  5 

50 

175 

135 

Y-Green  6 

12 

22 

55 

271 

Green  7 

13 

32 

150 

165 

B-Green  8 

42 

68 

130 

Blue  10 

68 

78 

Violet  II 

20 

265 

Purple  12 

70 

220 

120 

214 

75 
70 


400  HAYES 

In  this  experiment,  the  colors  were  presented  to  the  right  eye 
in  random  order ;  and  in  each  equation,  the  attempt  was  made 
to  match  the  color  presented  to  the  right  eye  by  a  mixture 
of  black  and  white  with  yellow  or  blue.  Green  was  introduced 
only  after  every  effort  to  make  an  equation  without  it  had 
failed,  and  green  had  been  insisted  upon  by  name.  As  the 
table  shows,  there  was  no  need  of  red  to  match  red  or  orange. 
This  experiment  then  gives  additional  evidence  in  support 
of  our  contention  that  this  protanope  perceives  green  but 
not  red. 

A  long  series  of  color  equations  was  formed  for  two  deuter- 
anopes.  Misses  M.  S.  and  H.  B-,  in  which  the  attempt  was  made 
to  match  mixtures  of  red  and  yellow,  red  and  blue,  green  and 
yellow,  and  green  and  blue,  by  mixtures  of  blue  and  yellow 
with  black  and  white.  In  these  tests,  the  equations  were 
formed  by  the  use  of  large  and  small  discs  on  a  single  color- 
mixer,  and  the  mixtures  to  be  matched  were  given  in  irregular 
order,  a  few  at  a  time,  through  a  period  of  three  weeks.  In 
the  case  of  Miss  M.  S.  green  was  not  distinguished  at  all; 
but  red  was  regularly  distinguished  from  yellow  and  grey 
mixtures  whenever  a  large  amount  of  red  was  used,  even 
though  the  red  was  mixed  with  considerable  yellow  or  blue. 
Miss  H.  K.  recognized  both  red  and  green  when  presented  in 
large  quantities. 

In  order  to  gather  upon  a  single  page  a  large  part  of  the 
evidence  for  the  contention  that  partially  color-blinds  are  not 
dichromates,  excepting  in  extreme  forms  of  the  defect,  the 
following  table  has  been  constructed.  In  the  vertical  column 
are  given  the  tests  which  seem  of  most  importance  for  this 
question,  and  which  were  used  with  a  considerable  number  of 
subjects.  Under  the  initials  of  each  subject,  R.  or  G.  is  used 
to  indicate  that  the  subject  showed  considerable  ability  in 
recognizing  red  or  green  under  the  conditions  of  the  various 
experiments  mentioned;  "con."  indicates  that  the  subject 
made  the  typical  color-blind  confusions,  though  occasionally 
distinguishing  red  or  green  correctly.  The  proportion  of 
confusions  to  recognitions  gives  a  fair  idea  of  the  degree  of  the 
color-blindness  in  each  of  the  subjects.  Miss  G.  S.,  Prot., 
distinguished  green  in  practically  every  test,  and  the  other 
women  all  recognized  red  or  green  (or  both)  repeatedly;  the 
three  men  appeared  to  use  the  color  names  capriciously, 
although  occasionally  applying  them  correctly.  They  are 
probably  as  insensitive  to  both  red  and  green  as  Miss  G.  S.  is 
to  red  and  Miss  M.  S.  is  to  green. 

The  Stilling  plates  were  not  obtained  until  after  the  first  four 
women  mentioned  in  this  Table  had  left  college.  Thirteen 
color-blind  subjects  have  been  tested  with  these  plates,  one 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIALITY  COLOR-BUND      401 


I 


•2  '^ 


,"o    »< 


•C2    C 


•5  ^  ^ 

^  i  i| 


f2i 


■a  0 

to*     K 


2 

&i  "^  ♦>- 


CO  -rS  ^ 


^ 

p^      pfi 

»i 

d 

d 

4 

rt 

p^ 

« 

§§§^ 

d 

§0 

d 

d 

d 

1— 1 

OCJOp^- 

pd 

^^ 

pi 

p^ 

p^* 

0 

I 

|«« 

rt 

d 

d 

p^' 

(k 

d 

d  d  d 

^ 

d 

w 

0 

u 

(3c36 

0 

0 

a 

0 

< 

d    .  d  d 
Oq'  0  0 

0 

i 

pi 

pi 

^ 

pq 

.d     d 

d 

d 

s 

d 

^p^  5 

p^ 

pi 

Q 

m 

pi.^     ^ 

d 

d 

d 

d 

X 

^0    0 

rt 

0 

pi 

pi 

m 

d  d  d  d 

d    .    . 

d 

d 

:^ 

0000 
0000 

pi 

opStf 

a 

0 

u 

rt 

> 

;i  ^  d  d 

d  d 

d 

^ 

^ 

' 

0000 

0  0 

0 

Q 

0 

PQ 

0000 

00 

0 

0 

0 

Q 

CO 

fii 

d  d  d  d 

d 

d 

d 

d 

6J 

^ 

0000 

0 

0 

0 

0 

^ 

OOOO 

0 

0 

0 

0 

0 

§ 

»-A 

H 

. 

0 

t/i 

•    •       d 

& 

d 

00    0 

d 

666 

d 

d 

d 

^^^ 

xn 

1 

2-  -s 

S     g 
1  a 

1 

0 

1 

bo 

a 

p.    da 

bO      ±i 

•s 

CO 

<5 

■g 

bO      'O 

(L) 

g 

Cards 

gren  Worsteds 
ig's  Plates 
g  Color-Sense 

W 

'0 

Threshold  (H 
Sheet 
roscope  (Schm 

1 
1 

en 

1 

ll-l 

S 

fegs 

-M 

^ 

rt  0  • -3  a> 

a 

0  <i>  0. 

tl 

13 

402  HAY^S 

protanope,  Mr.  J.  W.  P.,  nine  men  and  three  women  deuter- 
anopes.  All  except  two  of  these  subjects  read  Plates  4  and  12 
correctly,  though  according  to  Stilling  (72,  p.  11)  deuteranopes 
should  read  only  4  and  13-15,  protanopes  only  1,12,  and  13-15. 
Five  of  these  deuteranopes  read  some  figures  in  Plate  i ;  and 
three  read  parts  of  5,  6,  7,  8  and  9.  Mr.  J.  W.  P.  (Prot.),  read 
I,  12,  13-15;  Miss  E.  C.  was  the  only  subject  who  had  real 
difficulty  with  12.  She  read  parts  of  Plates  i,  2,  3,  4,  5,  6,  and 
8,  and  the  whole  of  Plates  13-15. 

D.      CONCIvUSIONS 

What,  then,  must  be  our  conclusion  regarding  the  color- 
system  of  the  partially  color-blind?  How  many  qualitatively 
different  sensations  of  color  does  he  possess?  From  a  study 
of  the  literature,  no  less  than  from  an  experimental  investi- 
gation of  numerous  cases  of  defective  color-vision,  the  writer 
has  been  convinced  that  partial  color-blindness  is  not  identical 
with  dichromatism.  The  statement  that  sensations  of  blue 
and  of  yellow  alone  are  possible  to  the  partially  color-blind 
cannot  be  reconciled  with  our  findings.  A  brief  review  of  the 
evidence  which  has  been  brought  forward  in  the  literature, 
in  support  of  the  contention  that  dichromatism  is  identical 
with  partial  color-blindness,  will  make  our  position  clearer. 

I.  Certain  color-blinds,  who  have  made  a  careful  study 
of  their  color-systems,  have  declared  that  they  are  limited  to 
sensations  of  blue  and  of  yellow  (Dalton,  Pole).  Opposed  to 
this  is  the  testimony  of  five  of  our  observers  (Misses  M.  S., 
H.  B.,  G.  B.,  E.  C,  and  I.  B.)  that  red  and  green  are  specifically 
different  color  qualities  from  yellow  and  grey.^  There  are 
doubtless  cases  of  defective  color  vision  where  only  sensations 
of  blue  and  of  yellow  are  possible.  Of  our  observers,  Messrs. 
J.  W.  P.,  D.  B.  Y.,  and  A.  H.  P.,  probably  belong  to  this 
extreme  type  of  defective,  which  is  represented  by  Dalton  and 
Pole.  But  this  conjecture  does  not  justify  the  inference  that 
all  partial  color-blinds  belong  to  the  extreme  type.  The 
evidence  which  has  been  presented  in  this  paper  supports  the 
contrary  view, — that  many  intermediate  or  transitional  stages 
and  degrees  of  abnormality  may  be  found  to  exist  between 
dichromatism  and  normal  col  or- vision, — and  that,  moreover, 
these  intermediate  forms  need  not  be  identical  with  anomalous 
trichromatism. 

^Nagel  (52,  p.  32)  came  to  the  conclusion  that  he,  a  deuteranope,  saw  red 
as  a  specific  sensation-quality  when  an  extra-foveal  region  was  adequately 
stimulated;  and  Schumann  (68)  reports  that  he  also,  a  deuteranope  (?),  can 
see  red  as  red,  and  can  distinguish  it  from  yellow.  But  Guttmann  (15) 
classes  Schtunann  as  a  green-anomalous  trichromate. 


COU)R  SENSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIALITY  COLOR-BUND      403 

This  view  is  further  supported  by  the  inferences  which  may- 
be drawn  from  our  findings  regarding  color  confusions  and  color 
naming.  The  repeated  recognition  of  greens  and  of  reds 
throughout,  and  even  under  relatively  unfavorable  conditions, 
furnishes  a  body  of  indirect  evidence  which  cannot  be  ruled 
out  of  court  by  assuming  the  participation  of  secondary  criteria. 

2.  When  reds  and  greens  were  presented  under  favorable 
conditions  of  stimulation,  many  of  our  observers  have  wholly 
failed  to  match  them  with  mixtures  of  yellow,  black  and  white. 
When  the  conditions  of  stimulation  are  unfavorable,  reds  and 
greens  may  be  matched  with  such  mixtures,  or  with  each 
other,  if  blue  be  added  to  one  or  to  both.  But  when  a  con- 
siderable amount  of  red  or  of  green  was  employed,  the  red 
or  the  green  was  seen  in  the  mixture  by  all  of  our  less  pro- 
nounced cases  of  color-blinds,  and  by  certain  of  the  extreme 
cases,  even  when  every  precaution  was  taken  to  eliminate  the 
influence  of  '  chance '  and  of  '  guessing.'  The  evidence  which  is 
furnished  by  our  color  equations,  then,  points  to  the  existence 
of  specific  sensations  of  red  and  of  green  in  the  color-systems 
of  the  less  pronounced  cases  of  color-blindness. 

3.  This  paper  has  included  no  data  derived  from  an  exami- 
nation of  acquired  and  temporary  defects  of  color  vision.  In 
the  opinion  of  the  writer,  it  is  premature  and  unsafe  to  seek  for 
analogies  between  these  atypical  cases  and  cases  of  congenital 
color-blindness,  although  Stilling  (71)  seems  to  advocate  such  a 
procedure.  The  findings  of  other  investigators,  however, 
(38)  raise  a  significant  question,  whose  ultimate  solution  prom- 
ises to  support  the  thesis  of  the  present  paper.  If  sensi- 
tivity to  green  may  lapse  before  sensitivity  to  red  is  lost,  and 
if  transitional  forms  between  trichromatism  and  dichromatism 
occur  in  acquired  color-blindness,  what  theoretical  warrant 
can  there  be  for  refusing  to  believe  that  an  analogous  series  of 
transitional  forms  occurs  in  congenital  color-blindness?  The 
less  pronounced  cases  which  we  have  described  would  fit 
into  such  a  series. 

4.  Light  is  thrown  upon  the  general  problem  of  abnormal 
color-systems  by  a  consideration  of  the  phenomena  of  indirect 
vision.  Recent  explorations  of  the  peripheral  retina  (4,  pp. 
53  f .)  have  yielded  results  which  support  the  thesis  of  the  pres- 
ent paper, — that  retinal  function  lapses,  when  it  does  lapse, 
in  a  gradual  and  not  in  an  abrupt  fashion.  "The  whole 
retinal  surface,  with  the  exception  of  the  macula  and  the  blind 
spot,  is  endowed  with  a  similar  function,  to  the  extent,  at 
least,  that  no  region  possesses  a  capacity  which  is  wholly 
lacking  in  any  other  region.  The  color  sensitivity  of  the 
periphery  is  unquestionably  less  acute  than  that  of  more 
central  areas ;  and  in  consequence  of  this  diminished  sensitivity 


404  HAYKS 

a  constant  stimulus  may  arouse  different  sensations  at  different 
regions.  It  cannot,  however,  be  said  that  any  part  of  the 
normal  retina,  save  the  macula  and  the  blind-spot,  is  wholly 
or  even  partially  color-blind.  For  the  whole  manifold  of 
sensation  qualities  which  any  region  is  capable  of  furnishing 
may,  under  appropriate  conditions  of  stimulation,  be  furnished 
by  every  other  region."     (4,  p.  65.) 

5.  Cases  of  monocular  color-blindness  constitute  the  crux 
of  the  whole  question.  Our  review  of  the  monocular  cases 
which  have  been  reported  in  the  literature  showed  that, 
with  the  exception  of  von  Hippel's,  they  reveal  nothing  but 
meagre  experimentation,  glaring  contradiction,  and  theoretical 
bias.  A  survey  of  Table  XII  (p.  401  of  this  paper)  shows,  in  strik- 
ing form,  the  trend  of  the  evidence  which  has  been  obtained 
from  a  study  of  Miss  G.  S.  Green  was  recognized,  and  its 
specific  quality  was  insisted  upon,  in  almost  every  Experiment 
with  spectral  colors,  as  well  as  with  pigments, — colored  papers, 
glasses,  gelatines,  etc.  There  can  be  no  justification  for  the 
statement  that  she  sees  only  blue  and  yellow.  Yet  she  is 
clearly  a  protanope,  and  not  an  anomalous  trichromats  If 
we  grant  that  von  Hippel's  patient  saw  only  blue  and  yellow, 
must  we  not  also  grant  that  Miss  G.  S.  sees  green,  blue  and  yel- 
low? This  assumption  is  supported  by  abundant  indications 
that  many  others  of  our  color-blinds  possess  a  similar  sensi- 
tivity to  red  or  to  green. ^ 

There  seems,  then,  to  be  a  large  mass  of  evidence,  direct 
and  indirect,  which  attests  the  presence  of  sensations  of  red 
and  green  in  the  color  systems  of  the  partially  color-blind. 
The  reader  who  still  insists  that  partial  color-blindness  is 
identical  with  dichromatism  must  find  some  means  of  explain- 
ing away  this  mass  of  evidence.  It  seems  much  more  reason- 
able to  admit  that  a  strict  classification  of  color  defectives 
is  necessarily  artificial;  to  assume  the  existence  of  slight 
degrees  of  variation  from  normality,  and  numerous  transitional 
forms  between  normality  and  total  color-blindness;  and  to 
regard  dichromacy  as  an  extreme  variation,  and  not  as  a 
typical  condition  of  the  partially  color-blind. 

E.    BiBUOGRAPHY 
Selected  bibliography  of  books  and  articles  of  importance  in  connection 
with  the  particular  problem  of  this  paper.     For  more  extended  references 
see  Helmholz's  Optik  for  the  older  literature,  and  the  various  periodical 
indices  for  the  newer  writings. 
I.     Abney,  W.  deW.     Colour  Vision.     New  York.     (No    date.)     The 
Tyndall  Lectures  delivered  at  the  Royal  Institution  in  1894. 

^  Nagel  (57)  reported  that  among  thirty  dichromates,  both  protanopes 
and  deuteranopes,  who  were  recently  examined  by  him,  none  failed  to 
recognize  various  shades  of  red  when  a  suflBiciently  large  area  of  the  retina 
was  stimulated. 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  OF  THE  PARTIALITY  COLOR-BUND      405 

2.  Allen,  Frank.     Persistence  of  Vision  in  Color-blind  Subjects.  Phy 

Rev.,  1902,  15,  193-225. 

3.  Angier,  Roswell  p.     Vergleichende  Bestimmungen  der  Peripherie- 

werte     des    trichromatischen    und    des    deuteranopischen    Auges. 
Zsch.  f.  Psychol.,   1904,  37,  401-413. 

4.  Baird,  J.  W.     Color  Sensitivity  of  the  Peripheral  Retina.     Washing- 

ton, Carnegie  Institution,  1905. 

5.  Bi\iRD,   J,   W.     The   Problems  of   Color-blindness.  Psychol.   Bull., 

1908,  5,  294-300. 

6.  CoHN,  H,     Der  Simultankontrast  zur  Diagnose  der  Farbenblindheit. 

Centralhl.  f.  prakt.  Augenheilk.,  1878,  2,  35-36. 

7.  CoHN,  H.     Ueber  Farbenblindheit.     Centralbl.  f.  prakt.  Augenheilk., 

1878,  2,  84-85,  264. 

8.  DoNDERS,  F.  C.    Ueber Farbensysteme.     Arch.f.Ophthalm.  (Graefe), 

1881,  27,  I,   155-223. 

9.  DoNDERS,  F.  C.     Noch  einmal  die  Farbensysteme.     Arch.  f.  Oph- 

thalm.     {Graefe),    1884,  30,  I,  15-90. 

10.  Ebbinghaus,  H.    Grundziige  der  Psychologie.  2nd  Ed.  Leipzig,  Veit, 

1905,  I,  209-212. 

11.  Edridge-GrEEn,    F.    W.     Colour-Blindness  and  Colour-Perception. 

2nd  Ed.  London,  Kegan,  Paul,  Trench,  Triibner  &  Co.,  1909. 

12.  Favre,  a.     Resume  des  memoires  sur  le  Daltonisme.     1877. 

13.  Guttmann,  a.    Untersuchungen  am  sogenannten  Farbenschwachen. 

Bericht  d.  I,  Kong.  f.  Exp.  Psy.,  1904,  6-10. 

14.  Guttmann,  A.     Ein    Fall  von    Griinblindheit    (Deuteranopic)    mit 

ungewohnlichen    Complicationen.     Zsch.  f.    Sinnesphysiol.,    1906, 
4i»  45-56. 

15.  Guttmann,    A.     Untersuchungen   iiber   Farbenschwache.     Zsch.  f. 

Sinnesphysiol.,    1908,   42,    24-64,   250-270;  43,    146-162,    199-223, 
255-298. 

16.  Guttmann,  A.     Anomale  Nachbilder.     Zsch.  f.  Psychol.,  1910,  57, 

271-292. 

17.  Helmholtz,  H.  von.     On  the  Theory  of  Compound  Colours.  Phil. 

Mag.,  1852,  (4)  4,  519-534- 

18.  Helmholtz,  H.  von.  Handbuch  der  physiologischen  Optik.    Leipzig, 

Voss.     1 856- 1 866. 

19.  Helmholtz,  H.  von.     Handbuch  der  physiologischen  Optik.     2nd 

Ed.     Leipzig,  Voss.     1885- 1896. 

20.  Henmon,   V.  A.  C.     The  Detection  of  Color-blindness.     J.  of  Phil., 

Psychol,  etc.,  1906,  3,  341-344. 

21.  Henry,  W.  C.     Memoirs  of  the  Life  and  Scientific  Researches  of 

John  Dalton.     1854.     Pages  25-26  give  Herschel's  letter  to  Dalton, 
written  in  1833. 

22.  Hering,  E.  Zur  Lehre  von  Lichtsinne.     Wien,  Carl  Gerold's  Sohn, 

1874.     2nd.  Ed.     1878. 

23.  Hering,  E.    Zur  Erklarung  der  Farbenblindheit  aus  der  Theorie  der 

Gegenfarben.     Lotos,  N.  F.  1880,  i.     Auch  separat,  Prag,i88o. 

24.  Hering,  E.    Zur  Diagnostik  der  Farbenblindheit.    Arch.f.Ophthalm. 

{Graefe),  1890,  36,  I,  217-233. 

25.  Hering,  E.    Die  Untersuchung  einseitiger    Storungen  des   Farben- 

sinnes  mittelst  binocularer  Farbengleichungen.  Arch.  f.  Ophthalm. 

{Graefe),  1890,  36,  III,  1-23. 
a6.     Herschel,  J.  F.  W.     Remarks  on  Colour  Blindness.     Phil.    Mag., 

1859,   (4)   19,   148-158. 
26a .     Hermann,  G.  Ein  Beitrag  zur  Casuistikder  Farbenblindheit,  Inaug. 

Diss.     Dorpat,  1882. 
27.     Hess,  C.    Untersuchungen  eines  Falles  von  halbseitiger  Farbensinn- 

storung  amlinken  Auge.     Arch.f.  Ophthalm.  {Graefe),  1890,  36,  III, 

24-36. 

Journal— 6 


4o6  HAYKS 

28.  HiPPEL,  A.  von.     Bin  Fall  von  einsei tiger,  congenitaler  Roth-Griin- 

blindheit  bei  normalem  Farbensinn  des  anderen  Auges.  Arch.  f. 
Ophthalm.  (Graefe),  1880,  26,  II,  176-186. 

29.  HiPPEL,  A.  von.     Ueber  einseitige  Farbenblindheit.     Arch.  f.  Oph- 

thalm. (Graefe),  1881,  27,  III,  47-55. 

30.  Holmgren,  F.     Ueber  die  subjective  Farbenempfindimg  der  Farben- 

blinden.  Centralhl.  /.  d.  med.  Wiss.  Berlin,  1880,  No.  49,  898-900, 
No.  50,  913-916. 

31.  Holmgren,  F.     How  do  the  color-blind  see  the  different  colors? 

London  Roy.  Soc.  Proc,  1881,  31,  302-306. 

32.  HuDDART,  J.  An  account  of  persons  who  could  not  distinguish  colours. 

Phil.  Trans.     1777,    67,    260-265. 
:i3.     Jeffries,   B.    Joy.     Color-blindness:    its    dangers    and    detection. 
Boston,  Houghton,  Osgood  &  Co.,  1879. 

34.  Jennings,  J.  E.     Color- Vision  and    Color-Blindness.     Philadelphia, 

Davis,  1896. 

35.  Kirschmann,  a.     Beitrage  zur  Kentniss  der  Farbenblindheit.  Phil. 

Stud.,  1893,  8,  173-230.  407-430. 

36.  Kirschmann,  A.     Normale  und  anomede  Farbensysteme.     Arch.f.  d. 

ges.  Psych.,  1906,  6,  397-424. 

37.  KoFFKA,   Kurt.     Untersuchungen  an  einem  protanomalen  Systeme. 

Zsch.  f.  Sinnesphysiol.,  1909,  43,  123-145. 
37b.     KoLBE,  B.     Ein  Fall  von  angeborenereinseitiger  Rothgriinschwache, 
Centralbl.  f.  prakt.    Augenheilk.     1882,6,291-296. 

38.  KoLLNER,  H.     Zur  Entstehung    der  erworbenen  Rotgriinblindheit. 

Zsch.  f.  Sinnesphysiol.,  1910,  44,  269-292. 

39.  KoNiG,  Arthur  und  Dieterici,  Conrad.     Die  Grundempfindungen 

in  normalen  und  anomalen  Farbensystemen  imd  ihre  Intensitats- 
verteilung  im  Spectrum.     Zsch.  f.  Psychol.,  1893,  4,  241-347. 

40.  Kries,    J.    von.     Die    Gesichtsempfindungen.     Nagel's    Handbuch 

der  Physiologie  des  Menschen.     Braunschweig,   1905,  3,   109-282. 

41.  I^add-Franklin,   C.     Vision.     Baldwin's   Diet,   of  Phil,  and  Psy.. 

New  York,    1902,  2,  765-799. 

42.  Levy,  Max.     Ueber  einen  zweiten  Typus  des  anomalen  trichroma- 

tischen  Farbensystems  nebst  einigen  Bemerkungen  iiber  den 
schwachen  Farbensinn.  Diss.  Freiburg  i.  B.,  Speyer  and  Kaemer, 
1903. * 

43.  I^tze,  Arthur.     Untersuchungen  eines  anomalen  trichromatischen 

Farbensystems.     Diss.  Freiburg  i.  B.,  Kuttruff,  1898. 

44.  Lovibond,.  J.  W.     Measurement  of  Light  and  Color  Sensations. 

London,  Geo.  Gill  and  Sons,  1893. 

45.  Magnus,    H.    Zur  spectroskopischen  Untersuchung  Farbenblinder. 

Centralbl.  f.  prakt.  Augenheilk.,  1878,  2,  80-81,  233-235,  287. 

46.  Maxwell,  J.  C.     Experiments  on  colour,  perceived  by  the  eye,  with 

remarks  on  colour-blindness.     Edin.  Trans.,  1855,  21,  275-297. 

47.  Maxwell,  J.  C.   Account  of  Experiments  on  the  Perception  of  Colour. 

Phil.  Mag.,   1857,   (4)   14,  40-47. 

48.  MuLLER,    G.    E.     Zur    Psychophysik    der     Gesichtsempfindimgen. 

Zsch.  f.  Psychol.,  1896,  10,  1-82;  1897,  14,  1-76,  161-196. 

49.  MuLLER,   G.  E.     Die  Theorie  der  Gegenfarben   und    die    Farben- 

blindheit.    Bericht  d.  I,  Kong.  f.  Exp.  Psy.,  1904,  6-10. 

50.  Nagel,  W.  a.     Ueber  dichromatische  Farbensysteme.     Vortrag  geh. 

i.  d.  29.  Vers,  der  Ophthalm.  Gesellsch.  zu  Heidelberg,  1901. 
Wiesbaden,  Bergmann. 

51.  Nagel,    W.  A.    Dichromatische  Fovea,  trichromatische  Peripherie. 

Zsch.  f.   Psychol.,    1905,   39,  93-101. 

52.  Nagel,  W.  A.     Fortgesetzte  Untersuchungen  ziu-  Symptomatologie 

und  Diagnostik  der  angeborenen  Storungen  des  Farbensinns. 
Zsch.  f.  Sinnesphysiol.,  1906,  41,  239-282,  319-337. 


COLOR  SENSATIONS  O^  THE  PARTIALLY  COLOR-BLIND     407 


53.  Nagel,  W.  a.     Versuche  mit  Eisenbahn-Signallichtem  an  Personen 

mit  normalen  und  abnormem  Farbensinm.     Zsch.  f.  Sinnesphysiol. 
1907.     41,  455-473- 

54.  Nagel,  W.  a.     Zur  Nomenklatur  des  Farbensinnsstorungen.     Zsch. 

f.  Sinnesphysiol.,  1907,  42,  65-68. 

55.  Nagel,  W.  a.     Einfiihrung  in  die  Kenntnis  der  Farbensinnstorungen 

und  ihre  Diagnose.     Wiesbaden,  Bergmann,  1908. 

56.  Nagel,  W.  a.     Ueber  typische  und  atypische  Farbensinnstorungen 

nebst  einem  Anhang:  Erwiderung  an    Herrn    Dr.  A.  Guttmann. 
Zsch.  f.  Sinnesphysiol.,  1908,  43,  299-314. 

57.  Nagel,  W.  a.     Farbenumstimmung  beim  Dichromaten.     Zsch.  f. 

Psychol.,  1909,  44,  5-17. 

58.  Nagel,  W.  A.     Tafeln  zur  Untersuchung  des  Farbenunterscheidungs- 

vermogens.     Wiesbaden,  Bergmann.     Sechste    Auflage,    1909. 

59.  NiEMETscHECK.  Ueber  Farbenblindheit.  Prag.  Vierteljahrsschr.  1868, 

25,   IV,   224-238. 

60.  Piper,  H.    Beobachtungen  an  einem  Fall  von  totaler  Farbenblindheit 

des    Netzhautzentrums    im   einen     und   von  Violettblindheit  des 
anderen  Auges.     Zsch.  f.  Psychol.,  1905,  38,  155-188. 

61.  Pole,  W.     On  the  Present  State  of  ICnowledge  and  Opinion  in  regard 

to  Colour  Blindness.     Trans.  Roy.  Soc.  Edin.  1893,  37,  441-480. 

62.  RaylEigh.     Experiments  on  Colour.     Nature,  1881,  25,  64-66. 

63.  Report  of  the  Committee  on  Colour  Vision.    Roy.  Soc.  Proc,  1892,  51, 

281-396. 

64.  Rivers,  W.  H.  R.     Vision.     Schafer's  Text-Book  of  Physiology,  Lon- 

don,  1900,  2,   1026-1148. 

65.  Rood,  O.  N.     Colour,  A  Text-Book  of  Modem  Chromatics.     4th  Ed. 

London,  Kegan,  Paul,  Trench,  Triibner  and  Co.,  1904. 

66.  Rosmanit,  J.     Zur  Farbensinnspriifung  im  Eisenbahn-  und  Marin- 

edienste.     Wien,  Braumiiller,  1907, 

67.  SCHUFELT,  S.  W.     A  case  of  Daltonism  affecting  one  eye.     N.   Y. 

Med.  Rev.,  1883,   23,  319. 

68.  Schumann,  F.  Ein  ungewohnlicher  Fall  von  Farbenblindheit. 
Bericht  der  I.  Kong.  f.  exp.  Psy.,  1904,  10-13. 

69.  Seebeck,  a.  Ueber  den  bei  manchen  Personen  vorkommenden 
Mangel  an  Farbensinn.     Pogg.  Ann.,  1837,  42,  177-233. 

70.  Steffan,  Ph.  Beitrag  zur  Pathologic  der  Farbensinnes.  Arch.  f. 
Ophthalm.    (Graefe),  1881,  27,  II,  1-24. 

71.  Stilling,  J.  Ueber  Entstehung  und  Wesen  der  Anomalien  des 
Farbensinnes.     Zsch.  f.  Sinnesphysiol.,  19 10,  44,  371-427. 

1 72.  Stilling,  J.  Pseudo-Isochromatische  Tafeln  zur  Priifung  des  Far- 
bensinnes.    Leipzig,  Geo.  Thieme.     Dreizehnte  Auflage,  1910. 

'73.  Thompson,  W.  and  WiEland,  C.  Detection  of  Color-Blindness. 
Norris  and  Oliver's  System  of  Diseases  of  the  Eye.  Phila.,  Lip- 
pincott,  1900,  2,  315-352. 

74.  TitchEnER,  E.  B.     Text-Book  of  Psychology.     New  York,  Macmil- 

lan,    1 9 10,    80-85. 

75.  TscHERMAK,     Ueber  Contrast  und  Irradiation.  Ergehnissed.  Physiol., 

1903,  2,  726-798. 
^76.     Tuber viLLE,  D.    Several  remarkable  cases  in  physick,  relating  chiefly 

to  the  eyes.     P"hil.  Trans.,  1684,  14,  736. 
[77.     Wilson,  G.    Researches  on  Colour-Blindness.  Edin.,  Sutherland  and 

Knox,  1855. 
[78.     WoiNOW,  M.    Zur  Diagnose  der  Farbenblindheit.   Arch.  f.  Ophthalm. 

{Graefe),  1871,  17,  II,  241-248. 
^79.     WuNDT,  W.     Grundziige  der  physiologischen  Psychologic  (5th.  Ed.), 

Leipzig,  Engelmann,  1902,  2,  226-232. 


RECENT  FREUDIAN  LITERATURE 


By  Rudolph  Ach^r. 


I.     Freud,  S.  Eine  Kindheitserinnerung  des  Leonardo  da   Vinci.     Wien, 
1910.     71  pp. 

The  one  fundamental  assumption  of  all  practical  experts  in  psychoanaly- 
sis is  that  all  psychic  phenomena  including  dreams,  gestures,  automatisms 
and  reveries  are  governed  by  law  and  order,  and  have  a  causal  sequence 
which  it  is  possible  to  discover  if  the  proper  data  are  at  hand.  Psycho- 
analysts not  only  make  this  assumption  theoretically  but  they  proceed  to  lay 
bare  these  laws  and  principles  of  psychic  life  in  concrete  cases  by  an  exami- 
nation and  interpretation  of  the  psychic  manifestations.  The  materials 
for  psychoanalytical  investigation  are  the  facts  of  the  life-history  of  the 
individual,  including,  on  the  one  hand,  the  environmental  influences  and, 
on  the  other  hand,  the  reactions  of  the  individual  to  this  environment. 
Supported  by  his  knowledge  of  the  psychic  mechanism,  the  psychoanalyst 
attempts  to  grasp  the  dynamic  factors  of  the  individual's  make-up,  and  to 
discover  the  sources  of  the  mental  motive  power,  as  well  as  its  later  trans- 
formation and  development.  If  the  psychoanalysis  is  successful,  the  inner 
characteristics  of  the  individual  personality  resulting  from  inner  energy 
and  outer  influences  are  explained.  While  they  deal  largely  with  a  class  of 
persons  whose  mental  condition  is  pathological  and  who  might  be  consid- 
ered more  or  less  abnormal,  they  strongly  insist  that  the  distinction  between 
normal  and  abnormal  cannot  be  sharply  drawn,  and  that  the  laws  and 
principles  which  they  discover  in  the  psychic  life  of  their  patients  hold  for 
normal  life  also.  Thus  they  proceed  to  apply  the  laws  of  psychic  life, 
which  they  have  discovered,  to  an  interpretation  of  the  life  and  character 
of  historic  personages,  as  well  as  to  characters  in  drama  and  fiction.  Their 
aim  is  to  lay  bare  the  very  inmost  workings  of  the  human  soul  by  an  inter- 
pretation of  its  manifestations.  This  does  not  seem  so  hazardous  in  cases 
where  there  are  sufficient  data  at  hand  concerning  the  lives  of  the  persons 
under  consideration.  But  they  do  not  stop  here.  In  cases  where  many 
of  the  facts  of  the  lives  of  noted  characters  are  wanting  and  the  data  meagre 
they  attempt  to  fill  out  the  gaps  by  making  the  known  facts  tell  the  full 
story  which  they  implicitly  contain.  A  certain  apparently  insignificant 
experience  or  impression  of  the  person  under  consideration  is  made  to 
bristle  with  meaning  and  significance  under  the  magic  touch  of  the  psycho- 
analyst. 

Perhaps  the  boldest  of  these  attempts  to  give  a  new  and  fuller  interpreta- 
tion to  a  great  historic  character  is  that  of  Freud  in  his  treatment  of  the 
childhood  memories  of  Leonardo  da  Vinci.  Although  Freud  does  not 
claim  absolute  authenticity  for  his  findings,  he  declares  that  they  have  a 
reasonable  degree  of  plausibility,  and  that  they  seem  to  him  more  satisfac- 
tory than  other  attempts  to  account  for  this  remarkable  character.  An 
effort  will  be  made  in  what  follows  to  give  a  summary  of  the  main  points  in 
Freud's  analysis  of  this  man. 

The  significant  facts  of  the  life  of  da  Vinci,  so  far  as  they  are  known,  are 
given  by  Freud  and  are  somewhat  as  follows: 


RSCeNT   FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  409 

Bom  in  1452,  da  Vinci  was  one  of  the  foremost  and  most  versatile  char- 
acters of  the  Italian  Renaissance.  He  was  not  only  a  paramount  painter; 
he  was  also  a  noted  and  original  scientist.  In  fact  these  two  capacities  were 
never  quite  separated  from  each  other,  the  spirit  of  investigation  always 
manifesting  itself  along  with  the  artistic  genius ;  and,  in  the  end,  the  former 
almost  wholly  overshadowed  the  latter.  He  was  not  only  great  but  well 
balanced,  being  possessed  of  a  keen  intellect,  a  strong  body,  an  admirable 
address  and  a  happy  and  lovable  disposition.  His  scientific  interests  made 
him  a  worthy  forerunner  of  Bacon.  He  prosecuted  all  kinds  of  researches; 
he  dissected  the  bodies  of  horses  and  of  men,  built  flying  machines,  studied 
the  nourishment  of  plants  and  their  reactions  to  poisons.  It  is  said  that 
at  thirty  he  made  this  famous  representation  to  the  Duke  of  Milan:  that 
he  understood  instruments  of  war  and  implements  of  peace;  that  he  could 
construct  bridges  both  light  and  strong;  that  he  could  cut  off  the  water 
from  the  trenches  of  a  besieged  fortress,  make  pontoons  and  scaling  ladders, 
and  construct  cannon  which  would  be  light  and  easy  to  transport,  but 
which  would  throw  small  stones  like  hail;  that  in  times  of  peace  he  could 
construct  buildings  both  public  and  private,  conduct  water  from  place  to 
place,  execute  sculpture  in  marble,  bronze  or  clay;  and  that  in  painting 
he  surpassed  all  of  his  contemporaries. 

As  has  already  been  indicated,  his  scientific  interests  caused  him  to 
devote  less  time  to  painting,  often  led  him  to  abandon  unfinished  works, 
and  made  him  careless  concerning  the  condition  of  his  products.  In  these 
respects  he  was  peculiar.  The  slowness  with  which  he  worked  was  prover- 
bial. He  worked  three  years  on  the  "Lord's  Supper"  in  the  cloister  at 
Santa  Mariadelle  Grazie  at  Milan,  after  the  most  painstaking  prepara- 
tory study.  He  would,  at  times,  work  from  daylight  until  dark  without 
taking  the  brush  from  his  hands.  Then  days  would  pass  when  nothing 
was  attempted  other  than  an  examination  of  the  work  and  an  inward  test- 
ing of  it.  He  worked  four  years  on  the  portrait  of  Monna  Lisa,  the  wife 
of  Francesco  del  Giocondo,  without  finishing  it. 

The  extraordinary  number  of  preparatory  sketches  in  his  note  book,  and 
the  great  number  of  notes  which  he  made  as  to  motive  in  his  paintings 
show  that  carelessness  or  unsteadiness  had  nothing  to  do  with  his  attitude 
toward  his  work.  On  the  contrary,  the  very  extent  of  his  preparation  and 
the  great  amount  of  preliminary  study  made  the  wealth  of  possibilities  so 
great  that  definite  decision  was  often  difficult.  This  led  to  a  sort  of  inhibi- 
tion in  the  execution  of  his  work.  The  slowness  with  which  he  worked  was 
a  symptom  of  this  inhibition  and  prophetic  of  his  later  turning  away 
from  painting  entirely.  He  was  never  aggressive,  and  always  avoided 
opposition  and  quarrels.  He  refused  to  eat  meat  because  he  thought  it 
not  right  to  take  the  lives  of  animals.  It  gave  him  great  pleasure  to  buy 
birds  in  the  market  place  and  give  them  their  freedom.  He  severely 
arraigned  war  and  bloodshed ;  and  he  called  man  not  king  of  the  animal 
world  so  much  as  the  worst  of  wild  beasts.  But  this  feminine  tenderness 
of  feeling  did  not  prevent  him  from  leading  condemned  criminals  to  their 
execution  in  order  that  he  might  study  their  horrified  facial  expressions 
and  draw  them  in  his  note-book;  neither  did  it  prevent  his  drawing  the 
most  horrible  weapons,  nor  his  entering  the  service  of  Cesare  Borgia  as 
chief  military  engineer. 

What  is  known  about  his  sex  life  is  limited,  but  significant.  In  a  time 
which  saw  boundless  sensuality  struggling  with  gloomy  asceticism,  da 
Vinci  was  the  embodiment  of  sexual  indifference, — a  thing  which  one  would 
scarcely  expect  to  find  in  an  artist  who  sets  forth  in  his  work  the  beauty  of 
woman.  His  writings,  which  deal  not  only  with  the  most  profound  scien- 
tific problems  but  also  contain  much  varied  and  indifferent  matter,  are,  as 
a  rule,  free  from  erotic  reference  to  a  degree  scarcely  found  in  the  literature 
of  our  own  day.     In  this  respect  he  was  in  marked  contrast  with  other 


4IO  ACHSR 

great  artists,  who  took  peculiar  pleasure  in  setting  forth  their  fancy  in 
erotic  and  even  obscene  expressions. 

There  is  no  evidence  that  he  ever  loved  a  woman  or  had  any  spiritual 
intimacy  with  one,  such  as  Michel  Angelo  had  with  Vittoria  Colonna. 
There  is  good  evidence  that  he  had  homosexual  tendencies  which  were 
however  either  sublimated  or,  in  the  main,  successfully  repressed. 

This  peculiarity  of  emotional  and  sexual  life,  in  connection  with  his 
double  nature  as  artist  and  scientist,  is,  in  the  opinion  of  Freud,  to  be  under- 
stood in  only  one  way.  He  subordinated  all  feeling  and  emotion  to  intel- 
lectual pursuits.  This  idea  is  expressed  by  da  Vinci  himself,  in  his  '  'Trac- 
tate on  Painting,"  in  which  he  defends  himself  against  accusations  of  being 
irreligious.  He  says  these  accusers  may  well  hold  their  peace,  for  to  know 
and  love  the  creator  we  must  understand  his  works.  Great  love  springs 
from  great  knowledge  of  the  loved  one.  This,  as  Freud  points  out,  is  not 
true;  for  love  is  an  emotion,  and  thought  about  an  object  tends  to  deaden 
the  emotion  aroused  by  it.  Da  Vinci's  idea  was  to  withhold  emotion  and 
make  it  subordinate  to  thought;  and  this  he  succeeded  in  doing.  He 
neither  loved  nor  hated;  was  indifferent  to  good  and  bad;  was  always  calm 
and  unperturbed,  because  he  subordinated  all  else  to  the  interests  of  thought. 
He  was,  however,  not  apathetic.  He  did  not  dispense  with  the  divine 
spark  that  is  either  directly  or  indirectly  the  dynamic  force  of  all  human 
activity;  but  he  transformed  it  into  the  impulse  to  know.  He  devoted 
himself  to  an  investigation  of  natural  phenomena,  with  a  persistence  and 
steadiness  that  can  come  only  from  the  enforcement  of  transformed  feeling. 
Only  after  the  conquest  of  knowledge  did  he  allow  the  inhibited  feeling 
to  break  forth  as  the  stream  that  has  driven  the  wheel,  and  is  then  allowed 
to  go  on  its  way.  He  has  been  called  the  Italian  Faust  because  of  his  insa- 
tiable desire  for  scientific  knowledge;  but  he  was  more  akin  to  Spinoza  in  his 
development.  The  significant  thing  about  this  programme  was  that  in 
trying  to  know  before  loving  he  made  the  latter  impossible.  In  his  efforts 
to  do  so,  emotion  was  largely  swallowed  up  in  the  interests  of  intellectual 
activity.  This  is  the  key  that  unlocks  the  mystery  of  da  Vinci's  hunger 
for  knowledge,  and  his  apparent  indifference  to  the  emotional  phases  of  life. 

It  is  possible  that  he  began  his  investigations  in  behalf  of  his  own  art 
for  the  purpose  of  mastering  the  laws  of  light,  color,  shade  and  perspective, 
in  order  to  be  true  to  nature.     Then  he  was  forced  by  the  interests  of  the 
painter  to  investigate  the  objects  to  be  painted:  the  animals,  the  plants, 
the  proportions  of  the  human  body,  the  inner  structure  of  all  these,  and  the 
functions  which  manifest  themselves  without  and  need  to  be  consideredi 
by  the  artist.     But  his  scientific  interests,  thus  begun  in  behalf  of  the  ai 
of  painting,  led  him  far  away  from  the  demands  of  his  art,  and  finally^ 
impelled  him  to  abandon  it  almost  entirely  in  behalf  of  pure  science. 

Freud  grants  that  any  marked  capacity  in  a  character  such  as  the  scien- 
tific spirit  in  da  Vinci  rests  on  special  native  endowment.     But  he  hok 
that  such  a  strong  bent  of  mind  has  very  probably  strengthened  itself  inj 
early  childhood  through  some  external  influence  and  that  it  originally] 
attracted,  to  its  use,  energy  from  the  sexual  sphere.     In  this  wa3^  it  derives] 
its  strength  partly  from  the  sex  field  and  acts  as  a  substitute  for  it  in  late 
life.     Such  a  person  would  later  take  great  delight  in  scientific  investiga-j 
tions  at  the  expense  of  emotional  life.     This  whole  theor3'^  is  based  upoi 
the  assumption  that  the  energy  that  is  usually  spent  in  the  sphere  of  se 
can  be  sublimated  into  non-sexual  ends.     That  such  contributions 
made  from  the  sex  realm  to  other  special  spheres  of  activity  is  shown  b] 
daily  observation.     This  process  is  unquestioned,  Freud  thinks,  if  durii 
childhood  this  overpowering  spirit  of  curiosity  served  sexual  interests  and! 
if  later,  during  mature  life,  there  is  a  strong  development  of  this  same  spirit  j 
of  curiosity  directed  toward  scientific  ends  accompanied  by  sexual  indiffer-j 
ence.     Objection  would  generally  be  made  to  such  a  theory  on  the  grounc 
that  young  children  have  neither  the  spirit  of  investigation  nor  sexualj 


RECENT  FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  4II 

interests.  But  Freud  holds  that  the  curiosity  of  little  children  is  abun- 
dantly shown  by  their  endless  questioning.  He  thinks  these  questions  are 
circumlocutions,  and  that  they  have  no  end  since  the  child  wishes  to  ask 
one  question  which  it  does  not  state.  Psychoanalysis  shows  that  all  chil- 
dren, but  more  especially  the  bright  ones,  pass  through  a  period,  beginning 
with  about  the  third  year,  which  might  be  called  the  infantile  sexual  inves- 
tigation period.  This  curiosity  is  usually  awaked  by  some  sexual  im- 
pression, such  as  the  birth  of  a  sister,  or  brother,  by  which  the  egoistic 
interests  are  threatened.  This  curiosity  has,  for  its  object,  the  solution 
of  the  problem  as  to  where  babies  come  from,  just  as  if  the  child  would 
wish  to  prevent  their  coming.  It  has  been  found  that  the  child  does  not 
believe  the  stork  story,  and  that  from  this  date  there  arises  a  mental  inde- 
pendence because  the  child  feels  himself  opposed  by  adults,  and  never  again 
pardons  them  for  deceiving  him  about  this  matter.  The  child  begins  to 
investigate  in  its  own  way,  usually  guesses  the  source  to  be  the  mother's 
body;  and  from  its  own  sexuality  it  gets  impressions  that  help  it  work  out 
theories,  about  the  source  of  babies  as  a  result  of  eating,  of  being  bom 
through  the  alimentary  tract,  and  may  touch  the  role  of  the  father  which 
appears  to  it  as  something  malignant  and  forced.  But  owing  to  their  own 
very  immaturity,  they  never  reach  a  satisfactory  solution,  and  finally 
leave  it  in  this  unsolved  condition.  The  failure  of  the  first  attempt  at  inde- 
pendent investigation  makes  a  profound  impression,  and  affects  the  attitude 
of  mind  in  all  later  investigations  in  a  somewhat  similar  way. 

When  this  period  of  infantile  sexual  investigation  ceases  through  sexual 
repression,  there  may  result  any  one  of  three  possible  conditions  which 
affect  the  future  impulse  to  investigate,  as  a  consequence  of  its  early  con- 
nection with  sexual  interests.  In  the  first  type,  the  spirit  of  investigation 
shares  the  fate  of  sexuality  and  is  repressed;  the  desire  for  knowledge  is 
inhibited,  and  the  free  exercise  of  the  intellect  remains  limited,  especially 
if  later,  during  puberty,  the  powerful  religious  thought-inhibition  is  brought 
into  play.     This  is  the  type  known  as  neurotic  inhibition. 

In  the  second  type,  the  intellectual  development  is  strong  enough  to 
withstand  the  sexual  repression,  and  is  not  repressed  with  it  as  in  the  first 
type.  Some  time  after  the  disappearance  of  the  infantile  sexual  investi- 
gation and  when  the  intelligence  is  strengthened,  it  bids  for  its  return  to 
help  evade  sex  repression.  This  repressed  sexual  investigation  energy 
returns  from  the  unconscious  as  imperative  brooding  (Griibelzwang)  some- 
what distorted  and  hampered  but  sufficiently  powerful  to  sexualize  the 
thinking,  and  to  color  the  intellectual  operation  with  pleasure  and  anxiety 
of  the  individual's  own  sexual  processes.  The  investigation  is  turned 
towards  sexual  activity,  often  almost  exclusively;  the  feeling  of  success  in 
thought  takes  the  place  of  actual  sexual  satisfaction;  but  the  indefinite 
character  of  the  infantile  investigation  shows  itself  in  the  fact  that  the  brood- 
ing never  finds  its  end,  and  the  sought-for  intellectual  feeling  accompanying 
its  solution  moves  further  into  the  distance. 

The  third  type  is  the  rarest  and  most  completely  developed.  The 
sexual  repression  is  present  here,  too,  but  it  does  not  suceed  in  repressing  a 
part  of  the  sex  impulses  into  the  unconscious.  The  Libido  withdraws  it- 
self from  the  conditions  of  repression  by  being  sublimated  at  once  into  a 
thirst  for  knowledge  which  strengthens  the  already  strong  impulse  to  inves- 
tigation. Here  intellectual  interests  are  powerfully  reinforced  by  the 
sublimated  energy  from  the  sex  realm. 

Now,  when  we  consider  the  fact  that  in  da  Vinci  the  overpowering  spirit 
of  investigation  appeared  in  connection  with  a  greatly  diminished  sex  in- 
stinct which  was  limited  to  ideal  homosexuality,  it  seems  very  probable  that 
he  was  an  excellent  example  of  this  third  type.  If  we  knew  the  details  of 
his  early  life,  it  would  be  possible  to  decide  this  point  with  certainty.  But 
very  little  is  known  about  this  stage  of  his  life.  It  is  known  that  he  was 
an  illegitimate  child,  that  his  mother,  Catarina  by  name,  was  a  peasant 


412  ACHER 

girl  and  that  his  father,  Sir  Piero  da  Vinci,  belonged  to  a  considerably 
higher  stratum  of  society  than  his  mother.  When  Leonardo  was  five  years 
of  age  he  went  to  live  with  his  father  who  had  married  another  woman. 
Here  he  remained  until  he  went  away  to  school. 

Though  the  account  of  Leonardo's  childhood  is  scant,  there  is  one  record 
of  his  childhood  memories  that  he  himself  made,  which  Freud  thinks  is 
very  significant  to  the  psychoanalytical  expert.  It  throws  a  flood  of 
light  upon  those  childhood  experiences  which  were  important  in  determin- 
ing his  later  life.  It  is  from  this  record  of  his  memories  of  childhood  Uiat 
Freud  extracts,  by  means  of  the  psychoanalytical  method,  the  significant 
facts  in  Leonardo's  early  life. 

The  reference  to  this  memory  of  his  childhood  seems  to  have  been 
entirely  incidental  to  the  theme  under  discussion.  In  an  article  which  deals 
with  the  flight  of  the  vulture,  he  turns  from  the  main  thought  to  what 
appears  to  be  the  reason  for  his  great  interest  in  this  bird.  He  says  that 
there  comes  to  his  mind  what  appears  to  be  a  very  early  memory.  While 
he  was  yet  in  the  cradle  a  vulture  flew  down  to  him,  opened  his  mouth  with 
its  tail  and  pushed  its  tail  against  his  lips  many  times.  This  is  a  strange 
and  improbable  story  and  could  not  possibly  have  been  a  memory  of  a  real 
experience.  It  was  a  fancy  of  later  life,  projected  into  the  time  of  his  in- 
fancy. This  is  frequently  the  case  with  so-called  memories  of  childhood. 
They  are  not  recalled  until  childhood  is  past,  and  then  they  are  modified 
and  falsified  in  the  interests  of  later  tendencies  so  that  there  is  not  much 
to  distinguish  them  from  pure  fancies.  The  individual  is,  in  this  respect, 
much  like  the  race.  While  the  race  is  young  and  struggling  for  existence 
with  all  manner  of  enemies  there  is  no  effort  to  record  its  history.  But 
later,  when  it  grows  powerful,  and  there  is  more  time  for  meditation,  the 
desire  for  a  past  history  arises.  Then  one  employs  all  available  material 
such  as  tradition,  sayings  and  proverbs,  and  weaves  them  into  a  story  of 
one's  past  in  which  one's  present  wishes  and  desires  tend  to  fill  in  gaps, 
distorting  much  of  the  evidence,  and  misinterpreting  the  rest.  The  result 
is  not  history;  neither  is  it  pure  fancy.  It  is  a  combination  of  the  two.  To 
treat  it  as  pure  fancy  would  be  to  throw  away  valuable  historical  material. 
It  is  the  business  of  the  historian  to  separate  fact  from  fancy  and  interpret 
both.  Just  so  is  it  with  the  vulture  story.  What  a  person  thinks  he 
remembers  of  his  childhood  experiences  is  very  significant;  as  a  rule,  the 
most  telling  evidences  of  his  mental  development  are  hidden  in  these  sup- 
posed early  memories. 

It  is  just  here  that  the  technical  skill  of  the  psychoanalist  is  needed  to 
follow  out  and  interpret  these  alleged  memories,  and  discover  their  hidden 
meaning.  It  is  in  this  way  that  an  attempt  is  made  to  fill  out  the  gaps  in 
Leonardo's  early  life  through  the  analysis  of  the  vulture  story. 

Similar  material  is  found  in  dreams ;  and  it  needs  to  be  treated  similarly. 
The  story  is  symbolic.  It  is  erotic  in  its  meaning  and  symbolizes  fellatio. 
Tail  {coda)  is  a  symbol  of  the  male  sex  organ  no  less  in  Italian  than  in  other 
countries.  The  passive  part  of  the  subject  in  the  story  is  significant.  It 
is  similar  to  the  dreams  and  fancies  of  homosexuals.  The  experience  which 
furnishes  the  material  for  this  is  nothing  less  than  the  infantile  means  of 
securing  its  food  from  the  mother's  breast.  This  is  why  the  story  is  pro- 
jected back  into  Leonardo's  infancy.  Back  of  this  fancy  is  hidden  the 
faint  remembrance  of  his  infantile  food-getting.  In  his  later  life  this 
beautiful  scene  was  often  painted  in  the  form  of  the  infant  Jesus  and  his 
mother.  This  reminiscence  was  converted  into  a  passive  homosexual 
fancy.  But  in  the  place  of  his  mother  was  substituted  a  vulture.  How 
came  this  to  pass? 

In  the  holy  picture-writing  of  the  Egyptians,  the  mother  is  always  rep- 
resented by  the  picture  of  a  vulture.  The  Egyptians  also  worshipped  a 
goddess  called  Mut,  who  was  represented  by  a  vulture-headed  statue. 
Perhaps  the  vulture  was  a  symbol  of  motherhood  because  it  was  supposed 


RECENT  FREUDIAN  UTERATURE  413 

that  there  were  only  female  birds  of  this  species.  The  wind  performed  the 
male  function  as  they  flew  through  the  air.  There  is  good  evidence  that 
Leonardo  was  familiar  with  the  fact  that  the  Egyptians  used  the  vulture 
as  a  means  to  represent  motherhood.  He  was  a  voluminous  and  omniv- 
orous reader.  Milan  was  the  chief  centre  of  books  and  libraries.  The 
church  fathers  often  used  this  story  to  support  the  story  of  the  conception 
of  the  holy  virgin. 

Thus  the  origin  of  the  vulture  fancy  of  Leonardo  might  be  conceived 
somewhat  as  follows :  As  he  may  at  some  time  have  heard  the  story  from  a 
church  father,  or  read  from  a  book  of  natural  science  that  there  were  only 
female  vultures  and  that  they  reproduced  themselves  without  the  assist- 
ance of  males,  there  appeared  faint  echoes  of  a  memory  which  took  the 
form  of  the  story  as  he  later  recorded  it,  in  which  he  unconsciously  identified 
himself  with  the  vulture's  offspring ;  for  he  too  had  a  mother  but  no  father, 
and  with  it  there  was  associated  in  a  manner  as  only  such  old  impressions 
can  express  themselves  an  echo  of  the  pleasure  which  he  enjoyed  at  his 
mother's  breast.  Perhaps  the  idea  of  the  virgin  with  her  son  led  him  to 
value  the  fancy  more  than  usual.  He,  in  a  measure,  identified  himself  with 
the  Saviour.  The  substitution  of  the  vulture  for  the  mother  indicates  that 
the  child,  being  illegimate,  missed  the  father.  It  is  known  that  he  spent 
the  few  first  few  years  alone  with  his  mother.  In  this  sense  he  was  a  vulture 
child.     This  is  the  key  to  the  memory  of  later  years. 

In  the  first  few  years  of  a  child's  life,  experiences  are  so  indelibly  impressed 
that  they  never  again  lose  their  meaning  and  effect  in  later  life.  If  it  is 
true  that  the  unintelligible  childhood  memories,  and  the  later  fancies  built 
upon  these,  portray  the  most  important  features  in  the  mental  unfolding 
of  an  individual,  then  the  fact  that  Leonardo  spent  the  first  few  years  of  his 
life  with  his  mother  alone  must  have  had  the  most  profound  influence  in 
moulding  his  inner  life.  Under  the  influence  of  this  constellation  it  could 
not  but  happen  that  the  child,  who,  in  his  first  years,  found  a  problem  in 
addition  to  that  of  other  children,  began  to  ponder  with  special  interest 
upon  the  riddle  of  the  origin  of  children,  and  whether  or  not  the  father  had 
anything  to  do  with  it.  He  thus  early  became  an  investigator.  Leon- 
ardo himself  seems  later  to  have  perceived  some  faint  echo  of  the 
connection  between  his  childhood  struggles  and  his  later  investigations, 
for  he  is  led  to  remark  that  it  seemed  to  have  been  destined  for  him  to 
investigate  the  problem  of  the  flight  of  the  vulture  since  he  was  visited  by 
one  while  he  was  yet  in  his  cradle. 

As  has  been  stated  before,  the  vulture  story  symbolizes  Leonardo's 
homosexual  tendencies.  But  since  the  vulture  was  considered  the  symbol 
of  the  female  why  was  she  also  given  male  attributes?  It  is  well  known 
that  many  Egyptian  goddesses,  as  well  as  those  of  Greek  creation,  were 
composites  of  both  male  and  female  organs;  and  it  is  very  probable  that 
Leonardo  derived  this  knowledge  from  books.  But  how  are  we  to  account 
for  the  fact  that  he  accepted  this  notion  and  incorporated  it  in  his  so-called 
memory  of  childhood? 

To  understand  this  we  must  consider  the  infantile  sex  theories  which 
young  children  create.  There  is  a  time  in  the  child's  early  life  when  first 
he  begins  to  have  his  curiosity  aroused  concerning  sex  matters,  when  he 
believes  that  everybody  has  organs  similar  to  his  own.  The  male  child 
thinks  his  own  sex  organs  so  interesting  and  important  that  he  cannot 
think  of  any  one  without  one.  He  has  great  curiosity  to  see  others.  Later, 
when  he  discovers  that  his  conclusion  was  wrong  and  that  the  female  is 
different  in  structure,  this  curiosity  gives  way  to  disgust  which  at  the  time 
of  puberty  may  lead  to  psychic  impotence  and  permanent  homosexuality. 

But  the  intensity  with  which  the  child  works  out  this  early  sex  theory 
leaves  permanent  traces  upon  his  mind.  Certain  foot  fetishes  seem  to  be 
the  outgrowth  of  a  substitution  of  the  foot,  for  this  much-valued  organ, 
Freud  points  out  that  his  notion  of  the  child's  interest  in  sex  matters  will 


414  ACH^R 

not  receive  much  credence  from  those  who  hold  to  the  modem  attitude  of 
minimizing  the  elements  of  sex  in  life,  and  regarding  it  with  shame  and 
disgust.  He  thinks  that  the  great  sexual  interest  which  children  manifest 
has  its  analogue  in  primitive  races.  He  holds  that  most  primitive  people 
followed  some  form  of  phallic  worship ;  and  that  many  gods  arose  from 
this  primitive  worship  through  sublimation  to  higher  non-sexual  divinities. 
The  childish  assumption  that  the  mother  has  a  male  organ  similar  to  his 
own  originated  in  the  same  way  that  the  androgynous  conception  of  the 
goddesses  of  old  originated.  The  old  hermaphroditic  goddesses  were  in 
reality  feminine  figures  with  male  sex  organs  attached  just  as  the  child 
conceives  the  case  to  be.  In  this  respect,  the  child  recapitulates  the  race. 
Thus  the  alleged  memory  of  da  Vinci  concerning  the  vulture's  tail  had 
its  origin  in  his  early  life  when  he  attributed  to  his  mother  a  male  organ 
similar  to  his  own.  If  this  interpretation  is  correct,  it  furnishes  further 
evidence  that  his  infantile  curiosity  was  unusually  active.  Freud  thinks 
there  was  a  causal  relation  between  da  Vinci's  early  sex  theory  and  his 
later  homosexual  tendency.  This  causal  relation  has  been  discovered  many 
times  in  the  psychoanalysis  of  homosexual  patients.  In  all  these  cases, 
there  occurred  in  early  childhood  a  very  intensive  erotic  attraction  towards 
the  mother,  due  to  over- tenderness  of  the  mother,  and  perhaps  strengthened 
by  the  absence  of  the  father.  Later  this  attitude  toward  the  mother  is 
repressed.  The  child  identifies  himself  with  the  mother,  takes  his  own 
person  as  ideal,  and  chooses  an  object  of  love  similar  to  his  ideal, — and  thus 
becomes  homosexual. 

In  reality  he  has  gone  back  to  auto-erotism,  since  the  boys  to  whom  he  is 
attracted  are  only  memories  of  his  own  childish  person  which  he  loves  as 
his  mother  loved  him  in  his  infancy.  He  finds  his  object  of  love  as  did  the 
Greek  Narcissus.  Freud  thinks  that  such  homosexuals  retain  in  the 
unconscious  a  memory  of  their  mother.  Through  the  repression  of  the 
love  of  mother,  he  conserves  it  in  his  unconscious,  and  remains  true  to  her. 
If  he  appears  to  seek  boys  upon  whom  to  bestow  his  love,  he  is,  in  reality, 
running  away  from  those  women  who  might  make  him  untrue.  Observa- 
tion has  also  shown  that  those  homosexuals  who  are  apparently  stimulated 
only  by  males  are,  in  reality,  moved  by  the  attraction  which  comes  from  a 
woman.  But  they  hasten  to  transfer  the  stimulus  received  from  a  woman 
to  a  man;  and  therefore  rehearse  the  same  psychic  mechanism  that  made 
them  homosexual  in  the  first  place.  This  may  only  produce  one  type  of 
homosexuals.  Da  Vinci's  was  of  this  type.  Although  he  succeeded  in 
sublimating  most  of  his  sexual  tendencies,  yet  it  cannot  be  assumed  that  he 
succeeded  absolutely  as  this  can  never  be  attained.  Other  than  mere 
hints  of  erotic  love  must  not  then  be  expected  in  him.  These  were  homosex- 
ual. It  is  well  known  that  he  selected  only  beautiful  boys  for  his  school 
and  not  promising  ones.  Other  evidences  are  found  in  a  record  of  some 
purchases  which  he  made  for  some  of  his  students.  He  kept  a  note  book  in 
which  he  used  signs  which  only  he  understood.  These  records  are  few, 
and  apparently  of  little  significance;  but  they  mean  much  to  the  psy- 
choanalyst. 

The  record  shows  a  very  exact  account  of  a  small  outlay  of  money,  as  if 
he  were  keeping  the  strictest  account  of  household  expenses.  However 
the  expenditure  of  larger  sums  is  not  recorded,  and  there  is  no  evidence 
that  he  was  a  strict  economist.  One  of  these  records  is  the  purchase  of  a 
new  coat  for  one  of  his  students;  other  similar  records  are  found  of  the 
purchase  of  wearing  apparel  for  other  students.  Most  biographers  simply 
regard  this  event  as  evidence  of  his  foresight  and  goodness  toward  his 
students.  But  this  does  not  satisfactorily  account  for  these  records;  we 
must  look  for  some  affective  motive  that  led  him  to  make  them.  The  cue 
to  this  is  found  in  another  record,  the  motive  of  which  is  more  certain  and 
evident.  This  other  record  consists  of  a  statement  of  the  funeral  expenses 
of  his  mother  who  died  while  visiting  him  at  Milan.    Da  Vinci  had  succeeded 


I 


RECENT  FR]eUDIAN   UT^RATURK  415 

in  forcing  his  feelings  under  the  yoke  of  investigation  and  thus  inhibited 
their  free  expression.  But  there  were  times  when  his  repressed  feeling 
manifested  itself  by  attaching  itself  to  some  apparently  insignificant 
object ;  and  the  death  of  his  once  intensely  loved  mother  was  one  of  these 
times.  In  this  record  we  have  the  distorted  expression  of  grief  for  the 
mother.  This  is  not  a  normal  expression  of  feeling,  but  in  so-called  impera- 
tive neurosis,  this  is  a  common  phenomenon.  In  these  cases  we  see  intense 
feeling,  which  has  become  unconscious  through  repression,  attaching  itself 
to  some  trifling  matter.  The  repressive  factors  have  succeeded  in  diminish- 
ing the  expression  of  this  feeling  to  such  a  degree  that  its  intensity  would 
never  be  guessed  were  it  not  for  certain  evidences  of  an  inner  demand  that 
the  apparently  insignificant  feeling  be  expressed.  The  recording  of  the 
ftmeral  expenses  of  his  mother  is  just  such  a  case  of  the  disguised  expression 
of  a  strong  though  unconscious  feeling  towards  his  mother.  The  strong 
repressive  factors  of  his  later  life  which  repressed  the  infantile  feeling  would 
not  allow  a  more  worthy  memorial  to  be  made;  so  there  was  a  compromise 
in  the  form  of  the  record  of  funeral  expenses.  The  same  affective  motive 
was  at  the  basis  of  the  record  of  expenses  for  his  students. 

The  vulture  story  has  still  other  significance.  The  expression  that  the 
tail  pressed  against  his  lips  many  times  suggests  the  intensely  erotic  relation 
between  mother  and  child.  It  is  not  far-fetched  to  assume  that  the  mother 
planted  numerous  kisses  upon  his  mouth.  Thus  the  vulture  fancy  is  a 
synthesis  from  the  memory  of  nursing  at  his  mother's  breast,  and  being 
fondled  and  kissed  over-much  by  her.  The  artist  succeeded  in  uncon- 
sciously expressing  in  his  artistic  work  the  elements  that  were  perhaps  his 
strongest  mental  stimuli  during  early  childhood.  These  elements  are 
contained  in  the  remarkable,  fascinating  and  enigmatical  smile  which  he 
has  placed  upon  the  face  of  his  feminine  characters  in  his  paintings.  It  is 
strictly  characteristic  of  his  work;  and  has  been  called  Leonardesque. 
In  the  strangely  beautiful  countenance  of  Monna  Lisa  it  has  affected  visit- 
ors most  strikingly.  Much  has  been  written  in  explanation  of  it,  and  the 
most  varied  interpretations  given.  He  worked  upon  this  portrait  four 
years,  and  left  it  unfinished.  After  this  painting  all  his  later  feminine 
characters  wore  this  smile.  The  smile  fascinated  him  no  less  than  it  has 
those  who  contemplated  it  during  the  past  four  hundred  years.  Since  he 
first  gave  expression  to  this  smile  while  painting  a  portrait,  many  critics 
have  assumed  that  this  model  must  have  possessed  the  smile.  Freud 
believes  this  is  not  the  true  explanation,  and  that  she  only  awakened  a 
memory  that  had  long  slumbered  in  the  unconscious.  Its  arousal  so 
fascinated  him  that  he  never  again  could  free  himself  from  its  influence.  It 
was  nothing  less  than  the  smile  of  his  own  mother,  which  he  had  forgotten, 
but  which  was  revived  by  the  model.  Chronologically,  the  next  painting 
was  the  holy  Anna  with  Mary  and  the  boy  Jesus.  Both  these  feminine 
characters  have  the  Leonardesque  smile.  This  painting  is  a  synthesis 
of  his  childhood  experiences.  When  he  was  five  years  of  age  he  went  to 
live  with  his  father;  here  he  not  only  found  another  mother,  but  also  a 
grandmother  who  was  very  attentive  to  him.  This  suggested  to  him  the 
mother  and  the  grandmother  idea.  But,  in  the  picture,  the  grandmother 
is  yet  young  and  with  unfaded  beauty.  In  reality,  the  boy  has  been  given 
two  mothers,  one  reaching  for  him  and  the  other  in  the  back-ground.  This 
exactly  embodies  Leonardo's  own  childhood,  for  he  had  two  mothers, — 
his  real  mother  a  little  older  than  his  stepmother  and  a  little  farther  away 
from  him,  just  as  the  grandmother  is  represented  in  the  painting. 

Another  entry  is  found  in  the  notebook  concerning  the  death  of  his 
father,  which  only  the  psychoanayst  can  interpret.  The  error  is  a  repeti- 
tion of  the  time  of  day  when  his  father  died.  Ordinarily  this  might  be 
considered  as  a  matter  of  inattention;  but  such  is  not  the  case.  Such  a 
repetition  is  called  perseveration.  It  is  a  key  which  shows  an  affective 
coloring  as  a  result  of  the  momentary  suspension  of  inhibition  in  which 


41 6  ACHER 

the  strong,  suppressed  feeling  attaches  itself  to  an  unimportant  matter. 
His  father  was  a  man  of  great  strength,  and  became  an  important  factor 
in  the  psychosexual  development  of  Leonardo,  not  only  in  a  negative  way 
through  his  early  absence,  but,  positively,  in  his  later  childhood. 

Whoever  as  a  child  was  attracted  to  his  mother  cannot  but  want  to 
place  himself  in  his  father's  stead,  and  identify  himself  with  him  in  his 
fancy,  and  so  lays  the  foundation  for  a  later  attempt  to  accomplish  the 
conquests  which  his  father  made.  The  father  was  a  gentleman;  and  Leon- 
ardo tried  to  be  like  him  in  this  respect,  although  his  means  would  not 
always  allow  him  to  do  so.  Since  an  artist  has  the  attitude  of  a  father 
towards  his  productions,  da  Vinci  identified  himself  with  his  father  here 
also,  because  he  was  indifferent  to  the  children  of  his  brush  just  as  his 
father  had  been  indifferent  toward  him. 

But  if  his  imitation  of  his  father  injured  his  artistic  success,  his  father's 
neglect  made  him  a  great  scientist.  The  keenness  and  independence  of  his 
later  scientific  investigations  were  due,  in  a  measure,  to  his  early  sexual 
investigation  caused  by  his  father's  absence.  It  has  been  found  by  psycho- 
analysts that  the  idea  of  and  the  belief  in  God  is  closely  related  to  the  father 
complex;  and  that  the  personal  God  is  psychologically  nothing  else  than  an 
enlarged  idea  of  father.  The  idea  of  nature  is  the  embodiment  of  the  mother 
complex.  Thus  God  and  nature  are  grand  sublimations  of  the  father  and 
mother  complexes.  Da  Vinci  illustrates  this  tendency  very  well.  He  was 
entirely  free  from  religious  dogma;  and  he  worshipped  nature.  His  close 
study  of  natural  phenomena  enabled  him  to  guess  some  of  the  most  funda- 
mental of  later  scientific  discoveries.  His  was  not  a  personal  religion,  but 
a  natural  one.  External  authority  in  matters  of  religion  had  no  significance 
for  him. 

One  great  ambition  of  da  Vinci's  whole  life  was  to  build  and  to  operate 
a  flying  machine.  He  seems  to  have  desired  to  do  in  this  world  what  most 
people  of  his  time  hoped  to  accomplish  in  the  next.  Why  this  interest  in  fly- 
ing? Psychoanalysts  have  found  that  this  wish  is  only  a  thinly  veiled  means 
of  expressing  another  wish.  The  stork  story,  the  winged  phallus  of  old 
suggest  the  meaning  of  the  wish.  The  most  frequently  used  expression 
for  the  sexual  act  is  called  vogeln.  By  Italians,  the  male  organ  is  termed 
vogel.  {uccello).  All  of  this  suggests  that  the  desire  to  fly  does  not  mean  any- 
thing other  than  the  desire  to  be  able  to  carry  on  sexual  activities.  This  is 
an  early  infantile  desire.  It  has  been  thought  that  children  are  satisfied  by 
the  incidents  of  each  moment.  But  the  desire  to  be  large  like  adults  ever 
haunts  them,  and  determines  most  of  their  plays.  If  they  learn  that  mature 
people  can  do  something  in  the  sexual  sphere,  which  they  must  wait  to  do, 
they  are  consumed  by  the  desire  to  do  likewise,  and  dream  of  it  in  the  form 
of  flying.  Thus  modern  aviation  has  its  infantile  erotic  roots.  In  da 
Vinci's  case  both  the  suppressed  wish  and  the  symbolical  embodiment  were 
doomed  to  failure. 

This  symbolism  is  scarcely  intelligible  unless  one  has  followed  the  ex- 
tensive literature  on  this  subject,  which  has  recently  received  so  much 
attention  from  the  Freudians. 

2.     Pfister,    Oskar.     Die   Frdmmigkeit   des  Graf  en  Ludwig  von  Zinzen- 

dorf.      Ein    psychoanalytischer    Beitrag    zur    Kenntnis    der   religiosen 

Sublimierungsprozesse  und  zur  Erkldrung  des  Pietismus.     Zurich,  1910, 

118  pp. 

This  psychoanalysis  of  the  life  of  Count  Zinzendorf  shows,  in  yet  another 

instance,  how  closely  sex  and  religion  are  united,  and  how  inextricably  they 

become  intertwined  in  the  same  individual.     His  whole  religious  life  and 

piety  were  dominated  by  his  erotic  life.     His  feeling  towards  Jesus  was 

plainly  of  a  homosexual  nature.     God  and  the  Holy  Ghost,  the  other  two 

elements  in  the  Trinity,  were  almost  crowded  off  the  stage, — so  completely 

did  Jesus  receive  the  religious  devotion  of  this  man. 


RieCENT   FREUDIAN   UTKRATURE  417 

Two  factors  were,  in  a  measure,  responsible  for  this  strange  co-mingling 
of  sex  and  religion  in  the  life  of  Zinzendorf.  The  first  of  these  was  the 
spirit  of  the  times,  which  looked  upon  all  pleasures  as  the  work  of  the  devil. 
All  Christians  were  called  upon  to  wage  warfare  against  this  foe  of  man 
and  God.  The  "lusts  of  the  flesh"  were  preeminently  the  most  difficult 
to  conquer,  and  therefore  received  most  attention.  This  severe  repression 
often  led  to  surrogates  where  they  were  least  expected.  In  the  case  of 
Zinzendorf  Jesus  became  this  surrogate  unconsciously. 

The  second  factor  was  the  early  impressions  received  by  Zinzendorf 
from  his  mother  and  teachers.  He  was  born  in  a  rigidly  pietistic  family. 
Spener,  the  father  of  Pietism,  laid  hands  on  him  at  four  years  of  age  for  the 
kingdom  of  Christ.  His  father,  being  tubercular,  found  compensation,  in 
the  world  of  belief,  for  his  earthly  suffering;  but  he  died  a  few  months  after 
the  count's  birth.  The  latter  was  profoundly  impressed  by  the  story  of  his 
father's  love  of  Jesus  as  told  him,  over  and  over  again,  by  his  mother.  Her 
fondest  hope  was  to  have  her  son  become  a  devoted  follower  of  the  mar- 
tyred Jesus;  and  to  this  end  she  detailed  with  the  greatest  minuteness  his 
suffering  and  crucifixion.  She  dominated  her  son's  early  life  to  such  an 
extent  that  he  always  considered  himself  subject  to  his  mother.  This 
attitude  of  the  son  towards  the  mother  was  erotic  at  first,  but  later  Jesus 
became  the  substitute.  From  early  infancy  he  was  refused  worldly  pleas- 
ures. He  could  not  and  dared  not  be  a  child.  Association  with  other 
children  was  forbidden.  Prayer  to  Jesus  was  the  only  form  of  pastime 
which  he  was  allowed  to  indulge  in  without  restraint.  Jesus  thus  became 
a  substitute  for  friends,  companions,  brothers,  mother,  and  father.  At 
four  years  of  age,  he  already  learned  that  Jesus  was  our  brother,  that  he  had 
died  for  us.  He  was  deeply  affected  by  this.  The  songs  of  Jesus'  martyr- 
dom pleased  him  early  in  life.  Before  six  years  of  age  he  decided  to  live 
for  Jesus  who  had  died  for  him;  and  at  seven  he  had  his  first  feeling  of 
how  the  wounds  of  Jesus  felt,  and  he  shed  tears  over  it.  He  wrote  a  letter 
to  Jesus  which  he  threw  out  of  the  window.  The  seeds  of  his  later  sadistic 
and  masochistic  tendencies  were  here  sown.  He  later  preached  what  he 
felt  in  these  early  years.  Even  his  closest  friends  thought  he  went  too  far 
in  his  love  for  Jesus.  Their  criticism,  however,  made  him  feel  happy 
because  he  was  suffering  for  Jesus'  sake.  From  the  time  he  was  eight  years 
old  he  never  allowed  himself  to  forget  for  a  moment  the  wounds  of  Jesus. 
He  early  developed  a  condition  of  anxiety  which  was  plainly  a  result  of  sex 
repression. 

At  ten  years  of  age  he  went  to  live  with  Francke,  the  great  teacher  at 
Halle.  When  his  mother  delivered  him  to  his  teacher,  she  reminded  him 
that  her  son  had  shown  unmistakable  signs  of  pride,  which  must  be  crushed. 
This  was  successfully  accomplished.  In  all  this  difficulty  Jesus  was  the 
youth's  only  friend  and  guide ;  he  acquired  a  real  hunger  for  suffering.  At 
thirteen  years  of  age,  he  wrote  to  Jesus  thus:  "Receive  us  into  thy  wounded 
sides;  from  there  we  will  fight  the  evil  and  conquer."  At  sixteen  he  wrote 
that  the  devil  could  not  harm  him  while  he  rested  body  and  soul  in  the 
wounds  of  Jesus.  As  a  boy  at  school,  he  founded  organizations  and  prayer 
meetings.  In  all  of  these  the  suffering,  wounds,  and  death  of  Jesus  were 
the  only  themes.  The  Lord's  Supper  with  its  revival  of  the  memory  of 
Jesus'  suffering  would  almost  put  him  into  an  ecstasy. 

At  the  University  of  Wittenberg,  his  pietistic  tendencies  were  strength- 
ened rather  than  dampened.  Believing  that  his  nature  was  essentially  bad, 
he  became  an  ascetic;  he  prayed  whole  nights,  and  read  the  Bible,  When 
1 9  years  old  he  said  that  if  he  could  die  he  would  look  upon  it  as  a  wedding 
joy.     He  wanted  to  come  nearer  to  Jesus. 

He  felt  it  his  duty  to  marry  but  could  not  persuade  himself  to  love  a 
woman  for  fear  of  doing  an  injustice  to  Jesus.  Four  times  he  was  about 
to  marry,  but  each  time  decided  that  his  fiancee  suited  some  one  else  better, 
and  surrendered  her.     Finally,  however,  he  was  persuaded  by  friends  that 


r 


418  ACHER 

a  marriage  would  not  interfere  with  his  duty  to  Jesus.  He  married  and  had 
twelve  children,  four  of  whom  lived.  He  never  cultivated  domestic  happi- 
ness, and  never  manifested  more  than  respect  for  his  wife.  He  entered 
the  service  of  the  state  with  tears  because  he  felt  this  would  do  Jesus 
little  honor. 

His  homosexual  attitude  towards  Jesus  was  manifested  throughout  his 
life  by  the  terms  which  he  employed.  He  referred  to  Jesus  as  the  bride- 
groom of  his  soul;  he  prayed  that  strange  love  might  be  extinguished 
from  his  soul  and  that  he  might  be  allowed  to  win  his  Saviour's  love.  He 
preferred  to  consider  his  soul  as  the  bride  of  Jesus,  and  used  the  most 
extravagant  terms  in  his  praise  of  the  bridegroom.  He  said  it  was  Jesus' 
own  business  if  he  kissed  us  after  he  had  forgiven  our  sins.  He  also  talked 
of  the  embrace  of  Jesus.  The  manner  by  which  Elisha  called  back  to  life 
the  woman's  son  who  died  had  great  fascination  for  him.  He  declared  that 
Jesus  forgave  sins  in  this  identical  way,  and  that  the  thrill  which  was  felt 
throughout  the  body  and  soul  when  this  took  place  could  only  be  compared 
to  the  feeling  of  a  wife  when  loved  by  her  husband. 

At  the  age  of  forty  there  seems  to  have  been  a  new  outbreak  of  his  re- 
pressed homosexual,  sadistic  and  masochistic  tendencies.  The  author  thinks 
this  was  due  to  the  fact  that  the  repression  of  his  sex  impulses  was  more 
severely  complete  than  before  and  therefore  needed  other  means  of  expres- 
sion. This  led  to  a  polymorphous  perverse  expression.  At  this  time  he  also 
came  to  rely  more  fully  upon  himself;  and  his  authority  in  matters  of 
religious  experience  became  greater.  He  trusted  his  own  fancies  and 
sub-conscious  manifestations  more  and  more.  As  a  result  his  natural 
inclinations  were  given  full  sway  and  his  unconscious  impulses  had  full 
expression. 

Aside  from  the  unmistakable  homosexual  manifestations,  which  now 
became  more  outspoken,  other  perverse  expressions  were  the  following: 
the  tendency  to  necrophilism  was  clearly  shown  by  his  emotional  excitement 
in  contemplating  the  dead  body  of  Jesus,  in  partaking  of  the  Lord's  Supper, 
and  in  advising  the  wife  to  place  her  arms  about  her  dead  husband's  neck 
for  a  stated  period.  The  tendency  to  sadism  is  shown  by  his  outspoken 
pleasure  in  contemplating  the  wounds  of  Jesus.  He  prepared  a  wound 
litany  which  the  author  pronounces  as  monstrous.  Among  other  things 
which  are  addressed  in  this  litany  are  the  scratches  made  by  the  crown  of 
thorns;  the  mouth  with  saliva  dripping  from  it;  the  cheeks  which  were  spat 
upon;  the  exhausted  eyes;  the  bloody  foam;  the  sweat-covered  hair,  and 
finally  the  wounds.  The  wounds  became  the  only  and  highest  good  towards  ^ 
which  his  whole  life  turned.  The  blood  of  Jesus,  too,  became  a  fetish  with 
the  most  extravagant  sentiment  woven  about  it.  Its  appeal  to  his  sense 
of  taste,  smell  and  sight  is  always  evident.  The  sweat  of  Jesus,  too,  made 
a  peculiar  appeal  which  could  only  feed  his  sadistic  tendency.  The  wounds 
in  Jesus'  sides  were  of  greatest  interest.  They  were  called  feminine 
genitals,  organs  of  birth,  and  sources  of  greatest  pleasure.  The  author 
quotes  endless  passages  to  show  that  the  count 's  thought  and  feelings  were 
strongly  colored  by  his  erotic  life,  when  contemplating  the  details  of  the 
crucifixion. 

Zinzendorf  introduced,  as  church  ceremonies,  footwashing,  the  brotherly 
kiss,  the  night-watch,  and  the  love-feast, — all  of  which  the  author  thinks 
sprang  from  his  erotic  needs.  The  same  was  true  of  his  celebration  of 
other  religious  ceremonies,  such  as  baptism,  the  Lord's  Supper,  confirma- 
tion, funeral  ceremonies,  ascetic  practices,  mission-work,  training  of  chil- 
dren, and  his  founding  of  the  United  Brethren  organization. 

In  all  this  manifestation  of  his  erotic  life  there  was  left  no  room  for  the 
ethical  teachings  of  Jesus.  They  made  no  appeal  to  him  because  Jesus, 
as  the  object  of  his  erotic  life,  excluded  all  else. 

Although  there  may  have  been  a  natural  predisposition  to  begin  with, 
it  is  nevertheless  true  that  in  much  of  Count  Zinzendorf' s  later  life  we  see  i 


k 


RECENT   FREUDIAN   LlT^RATURB  419 

the  direct  influence  of  his  early  impressions  and  teachings.  They  laid 
well  the  foundation  for  just  such  a  career  as  he  led.  The  count  perhaps 
never  suspected  the  nature  of  his  piety,  but  recent  studies  in  sexual  abnor- 
malities show  very  clearly  that  his  attitude  towards  Jesus  could  be  almost 
exactly  duplicated  in  the  attitude  of  perverts  towards  the  object  of  their 
sexual  desire. 

The  effort  of  his  elders  to  have  him  concentrate  his  early  attention  upon 
the  martyred  Jesus  paved  the  way  for  his  later  libidinous  attitude.  The 
fact  that  he  did  not  know  his  father  in  childhood,  except  as  his  mother  in- 
formed him  of  his  love  for  Jesus,  accounts  for  the  fact  that  he  had  no  place 
for  God  in  his  later  religion.  The  great  emphasis  which  his  mother,  early 
in  his  life,  placed  upon  Jesus,  to  the  exclusion  of  relatives,  friends  and  com- 
panions, accounts  in  a  large  measure  for  the  count's  later  lack  of  interest 
in  the  social  message  of  Jesus.  The  tears  of  joy  of  the  seven-year-old  over 
the  bloody  Jesus  on  the  cross  may  well  have  laid  the  foundation  for  his 
adult  sadistic  tendency.  His  desire,  at  the  beginning  of  puberty,  to  be 
taken  up  into  the  wounds  of  Jesus  later  found  satisfaction  in  his  cult  in- 
volving the  wounded  sides  of  Jesus. 

The  author  gives  a  wealth  of  quotations  from  Zinzendorf's  works  to 
substantiate  every  point  he  makes ;  but  only  the  merest  outline  could  here 
be  given.  This  psychoanalysis  adds  another  valuable  chapter  to  the 
now  rapidly  growing  literature  which  shows  how  large  a  part  sex  plays  in 
human  life,  and  often  in  ways  not  usually  suspected,  so  plastic  is  the  sex 
instinct. 

3.     Graf,  Max.   Richard   Wagner  im  "Fliegenden  Hollander."  Ein  Bei- 
trag  zur  Psychologie  des  kiinstlerischen  Schaffens.  Leipzig,  191 1,  46  pp. 

An  effort  is  here  made  to  explain  the  life  and  works  of  Richard  Wagner 
by  showing  how  his  early  experiences  influenced  his  later  conduct,  but 
more  especially  his  musical  and  dramatic  productions.  These  early  ex- 
periences are  conceived  as  resulting  in  dynamic  factors  which  gave  color 
and  direction  to  his  whole  later  life. 

The  Flying  Dutchman  more  than  any  of  his  other  productions  gives  this 
key  to  Wagner's  personality  and  psychic  peculiarities.  It  is  the  one  pro- 
duction in  which  the  author  reflects  his  life  history,  his  inner  conflicts,  his 
unconscious  longings  and  wishes.  When,  as  a  young  man,  he  first  heard 
the  story  or  legend  as  told  by  the  author,  Heine,  it  fascinated  him  because 
it  contained  something  akin  to  his  own  inner  struggles.  Wagner's  sea- 
voyage  to  London  and  Paris,  and  his  high  hopes  and  crushing  defeats  at  the 
latter  city,  all  tended  to  deepen  his  feeling  of  identity  with  the  legendary 
Flying  Dutchman,  and  prepared  him  for  the  production  of  the  opera  by 
that  name.  After  he  had  written  out  a  rough  sketch  of  this  opera,  he 
versified  it  in  ten  days  and  set  it  to  music  in  seven  weeks, — so  completely 
had  both  the  music  and  verse  taken  form  before  he  began  to  write  it  out. 

He  found  it  necessary  to  modify  completely  the  motif  of  the  romantic 
operas  of  his  time,  in  order  to  express  himself.  Before  his  modifications 
were  introduced,  the  three  main  characters  in  the  opera  were  as  follows: 

A  virtuous  young  woman  and  a  worthy  young  man  love  each  other  de- 
votedly. A  demon  with  supernatural  powers  appears,  and  carries  away 
the  maiden  into  captivity.  But  the  power  of  the  demon  is  only  temporary, 
because  virtue  must  triumph  in  the  end ;  and  so  the  maiden  is  subsequently 
recovered  by  her  lover. 

Wagner  retained  the  three  characters  but  their  relations  are  entirely 
changed.  Two  persons  are  in  love,  as  in  the  previous  operas,  and  an  unlucky, 
demon-like  man  approaches  as  before;  but  now  the  maiden  suddenly  ex- 
periences a  complete  change  of  heart,  and  receives  him  with  open  arms  be- 
cause she  dreamed  of  his  coming  and  his  presence  wakes  her  slumbering 
love  for  him.     By  her  devotion  to  the  new-comer,  she  saves  him  from  some 


42 O  ACHER 

terrible  doom.  She  willingly  offers  her  life  as  a  sacrifice  to  show  her 
fidelity;  and  by  this  act  the  spell,  which  held  the  unfortunate  man 
captive,  is  broken  and  his  struggles  are  over. 

This  is  the  central  motif  of  practically  all  of  Wagner's  works.  This  one 
theme  seems  to  have  occupied  him  throughout  his  life.  He  could  never 
get  away  from  it.  He  found  it  necessary  to  change  somewhat  the  story 
of  the  Flying  Dutchman  in  order  to  express  his  own  life  by  introducing  the 
character  Brie,  as  the  lover  of  his  heroine,  before  the  main  character  ap- 
peared. But  into  the  character  of  the  Flying  Dutchman  himself,  he  seems 
to  have  projected  a  complete  embodiment  of  his  own  sufferings;  and  in 
Senta  he  found  his  ideal  of  woman  as  she  appeared  in  his  dreams  and  visions, 
when  his  innermost  feelings  determined  their  character.  In  fact,  the 
women  of  his  artistic  creation  are  all  of  one  type.  All  have  longings  for 
something  more  or  less  fantastic,  something  not  to  be  found  in  their  im- 
mediate environment. 

Thus  in  all  of  Wagner's  productions,  but  more  especially  in  the  one  here 
under  consideration,  there  seem  to  be  evidences  of  the  fact  that  his  soul 
experienced  something  which  pressed  for  expression,  either  in  imagination 
or  in  life;  a  phantom,  an  idea,  a  dream  fancy,  an  intensive  wish,  longed  for 
fulfillment  if  only  in  fancy.  Odysseus  and  Columbus  both  made  a  strong 
appeal  to  him ;  but  neither  quite  embodied  his  case  and  it  was  only  when 
he  heard  the  story  of  the  Flying  Dutchman  that  he  saw  the  reflection  of  his 
own  life.  The  fact  that  the  hero  could  be  saved  only  by  the  sacrifice  of  a 
true  woman  seems  to  have  been  the  feature  of  the  story  which  touched 
Wagner.  At  the  age  of  twenty-three  he  was  rather  hastily  married,  but 
after  seven  months  his  wife  left  him;  and  although  there  was  latec  a 
reconciliation  it  never  completely  effaced  the  disharmony.  They  were 
separated  by  a  fancy  or  dream  of  his,  in  which  he  embodied  the  form  of  an 
ideal,  self-sacrificing,  insightful  woman,  who  would  be  faithful  unto  death, 
and  whose  love  would  soften  his  troubles. 

Why  this  conflict  in  Richard  Wagner's  life  and  in  his  artistic  produc- 
tions? The  answer  to  this  question  is  found  in  his  early  childhood  experi- 
ences. When  he  was  six  months  old  his  father  died.  After  six  months  of 
widowhood,  his  mother  married  the  painter  and  actor,  Ludwig  Geyer,  who 
had  befriended  the  family  after  the  death  of  her  first  husband.  Geyer 
seems  to  have  made  a  profound  impression  upon  young  Wagner;  for 
the  latter  as  a  boy  was  fond  of  the  belief  that  he  might  have  been  the  son  of 
Geyer.  This  belief  is  not  uncommon  among  boys.  The  wish  is  father 
to  the  thought  that  they  might  be  the  son  of  some  other  more  famous  man, 
king  or  even  God,  than  their  legal  father.  Goethe  and  Beethoven  enter- 
tained this  idea  in  their  youth.  The  same  notion  is  also  found  in  myth  and 
poetry.  It  gives  the  son  a  chance  to  choose  his  father.  As  a  boy,  Wagner 
seems  to  have  toyed  with  this  idea  that  Geyer  was  his  father.  But  the 
very  satisfaction  which  he  derived  from  this  possibility  so  impressed  the 
youth  that  he  came  to  act  as  if  the  assumption  were  true.  Even  in  his 
later  life,  this  attitude  toward  Geyer  was  not  abandoned.  He  always 
liked  to  have  Geyer's  portrait  with  him;  he  adorned  his  step-father's 
grave;  and  referred  to  him  often  in  letters,  but  never  to  his  real  father. 
He  even  dressed  himself  as  Geyer  did,  and  wore  the  latter's  cap  and  gown. 
What  is  the  motive  of  this  fancy  of  Wagner's  youth,  and  that  of  other  boys? 
The  CEdipus  complex  is  at  the  basis  of  this  fancy.  The  child's  attitude 
towards  the  mother  is  more  or  less  erotic,  and  is  due  to  over-fondness  of  the 
mother.  This  stimulates  a  rivalry  with  the  father,  whom  the  son  would 
like  to  equal,  but  to  whom  he  is  subordinate.  Thus  the  father  is  the  rival 
and  yet  the  ideal  of  the  son.  Although  the  fancy  of  having  a  different 
father  involves  the  infidelity  of  the  mother,  it  is  by  this  means  that  the 
rival  father  is  set  aside.  At  the  same  time,  the  ideal  qualities  of  the  father 
as  conceived  by  the  son  are  given  to  the  God,  king,  or  prince,  whom  his 
fancy  chooses  as  his  father.     The  conflict  between  the  love  of  the  father 


RECENT  FREUDIAN   I^ITERATURE  42 1 

and  the  rivalry  with  him  is  settled  by  setting  aside  the  rival  father,  and  at 
the  same  time  giving  his  qualities  to  a  new  father. 

This  attitude  of  the  son  towards  the  mother  may  easily  give  rise  to  fancies 
in  which  the  infidelity  of  the  mother  plays  a  large  r61e.  The  ambition  of 
the  little  CEdipus  to  equal  his  father  extends  to  the  latter's  relation  with  his 
mother.  In  normal  children,  and  under  normal  conditions,  this  attitude 
towards  the  mother  is  repressed,  and  dies  out  entirely.  But  if  there  is  a  nat- 
ural precocity,  or  if  the  mother  is  unduly  tender  with  the  child,  and  caresses 
him  too  much,  the  erotic  impulses  may  become  so  strong  that  the  fancies 
of  rivalry  and  infidelity  become  so  established  that  they  can  never  be 
wholly  overcome.  Repression  and  suppression  may  remove  them  from 
consciousness,  but  they  enter  the  unconscious  realm  as  active  forces,  and 
constantly  exert  a  determining  influence  on  conduct. 

This  is  just  what  seems  to  have  been  the  case  with  Richard  Wagner. 
His  father  having  died  when  he  was  six  months  of  age,  his  mother  lavished 
her  affection  upon  the  little  son  to  drown  her  grief;  and  from  this  he  never 
recovered.  As  a  man,  he  was  always  hungering  for  love  and  honor.  No 
sacrifice  of  friends  was  too  great,  and  no  honor  and  praise  from  women 
admirers  was  ever  sufficient  to  satisfy  him.  His  memory  of  his  childhood 
was  unusually  keen;  and  his  childhood  characteristics  were  remarkably 
well  retained.  His  hate  and  his  love,  his  suffering  and  his  ecstasy  were 
all  very  childlike. 

Thus  the  motif  of  the  Flying  Dutchman,  and  of  some  of  the  other  of 
Wagner's  greatest  works,  springs  from  his  childhood  experiences  and 
fancies.  The  overfondness  of  the  mother  made  such  an  impression  upon 
the  child's  mind  that  he  was  never  afterwards  entirely  free  from  her  person- 
ality and  characteristics.  His  heroines  all  embody  the  idealized  qualities 
which  he  conceived  his  mother  to  have  possessed.  When  the  Flying 
Dutchman  first  saw  Senta  he  said:  "How  strangely  this  maiden  standing 
before  me  seems  to  arise  from  long  past  memories!"  This  shows  how 
closely  his  mother's  memory  entered  into  his  heroines.  His  fondness 
for  the  fancy  that  Geyer  might  be  his  father  sprang  from  the  childish 
wish  that  his  mother  had  been  unfaithful  to  his  father  for  his  sake.  He 
identified  himself  with  Geyer,  and  remembered  the  latter  because  he 
attributed  to  him  what  was  in  his  own  early  childish  fancy.  This  attitude 
of  rivalry  left  such  a  strong  impression  upon  his  psychic  life  that  his 
whole  career  was  colored  by  it.  It  is  just  this  relation  of  rivalry  that 
is  manifested  by  nearly  all  of  his  heroes.  They  come,  as  a  third  party, 
into  the  relations  of  two  lovers,  and  successfully  compete  for  the  maiden's 
love  as  did  the  Flying  Dutchman.  In  the  original  story,  this  rivalry 
was  absent ;  but  Wagner  created  the  character  Eric  as  Senta's  lover,  prior 
to  the  arrival  of  the  Flying  Dutchman,  in  order  to  embody  the  demands 
of  his  life  and  to  fulfill  his  own  wishes.  He  looked  upon  his  artistic  pro- 
ductions as  a  means  of  realizing  his  unfulfilled  wishes,  in  actual  life.  He 
said  that  if  life  itself  were  lived  in  its  completeness  there  were  no  need  of 
art. 

Although  Wagner  himself  never  guessed  the  source  of  these  unfulfilled 
wishes,  psychoanalysis  seems  to  make  it  clear  that  they  sprang  from  his 
childhood  impressions;  and  that  they  were  revived  in  his  later  life  and  ful- 
filled in  the  heroes  of  his  creation.  They  embodied  what  had  always  been 
to  him  a  fancy  and  a  dream ;  and  the  Flying  Dutchman  was  par  excellence 
the  expression  of  this  dream. 

An  effort  has  been  made  to  give  a  somewhat  condensed  resume  of  the 
main  facts  and  principles  involved  in  each  of  foregoing  articles.  These 
attempts  at  an  intensive  study  of  individual  characters  and  personalities 
are  so  thoroughly  of  the  nature  of  pioneer  work,  and  go  so  far  beyond  the 
accepted  standards  of  orthodox  psychology  in  many  of  their  explorations, 
that  it  is  difficult  to  attempt  an  evaluation.     Perhaps  it  is  not  yet  time 

Journal— 7 


422  ACHBR 

to  become  too  critical.  It  is  in  their  effort  to  get  at  the  dynamic  factors  of 
psychic  life  that  these  studies  are  of  immense  importance.  Whether  one 
accepts  all  their  conclusions  or  not,  they  are  still  highly  suggestive,  if 
not  illuminating;  and  it  does  not  seem  too  much  to  say  that  they  are 
prophetic  of  what  the  psychology  of  the  future  will  largely  concern  itself 
with.  The  emphasis  placed  on  the  evolutionary  and  genetic  aspects  of 
psychic  functioning  cannot  but  meet  the  approval  of  all  thorough-going 
evolutionists.  The  effort  to  trace  out  the  modification  and  sublimation  of 
the  basic  racial  impulses  into  ever  higher  and  more  complex  forms  of  which 
all  civilization  is  the  expression  is  a  stupendous  programme, — but  a  most 
fruitful  one.  One  cannot  but  feel  that  these  men  are  grappling  with  the 
vital  factors  of  mental  life;  and  that,  although  their  methods  and  conclusions 
at  times  seem  somewhat  crude,  they  are  opening  rich  mines  of  information 
concerning  psychic  life,  which  are  destined  to  make  much  of  the  present 
introspective,  laboratory  psychology  look  pale  and  frothy  if  it  is  n't  under- 
mined entirely.  The  evidence  which  shows  that  consciousness  is  not  to  be 
trusted  in  attempting  to  explain  its  own  motives  has  already  grown  over- 
whelming. The  tremendous  part  played  by  unconscous  complexes,  in 
the  mental  life  of  every  normal  person,  cannot  longer  be  doubted.  In 
the  light  of  these  facts  it  seems  a  little  belated  to  continue  the  discussion 
as  to  whether  or  not  there  is  imageless  thought. 

It  seems  important,  therefore,  that  this  school  of  psychologists  should 
be  given  a  full  and  free  hearing.  Nothing  so  tests  one's  open-mindedness, 
and  one's  desire  for  more  light,  than  such  departures  from  the  accepted 
standards  as  the  above  studies  are.  The  summary  dismissal  of  the  contri- 
butions of  the  Freudian  School  as  unscientific  and  without  a  basis  of  fact, 
as  some  have  a  tendency  to  do,  is  simply  a  reflection  of  their  own  inability 
to  weigh  principles  in  an  unbiased  fashion.  Would  it  not  be  better  to 
adopt  the  same  attitude  towards  these  new  contributions  to  psychology 
that  some  denominations  do  towards  repentant  sinners;  and  put  them  on 
probation  for,  say,  a  period  of  from  five  to  ten  years? 

Coming  now  to  closer  quarters  with  these  studies,  an  effort  will  be  made 
to  point  out  a  few  of  the  common  principles  running  through  all  of  them. 

Great  emphasis  is  placed  on  sex  in  each  of  the  studies,  which  is  in  har- 
mony with  one  of  the  fundamental  principles  of  the  Freudian  school.  This, 
in  itself,  is  sufficient,  in  the  eyes  of  many,  to  condemn  it;  although  it  is 
safe  to  assume  that  not  very  many  of  those  who  criticise  have  clearly  in 
mind  Freud's  use  of  the  term.  He  uses  it  in  a  very  much  larger  sense 
than  current  usage  would  warrant.  He  assumes  that  all  evolutionary 
variations  and  sublimations  of  the  primitive  impulse  to  procreate,  in  the 
lower  forms  of  life,  can  rightfully  be  designated  sexual.  In  this  he  is 
justified  by  Darwin's  use  of  the  term,  as  well  as  by  all  modem  scientific 
students  of  the  subject.  He  accepts  the  dictum  of  the  poet  that  hunger 
and  love  rule  the  world;  and  he  uses  the  terms  sex  and  love  synonymously. 

The  contention  that  the  so-called  partial  sexual  impulses  manifest 
themselves  early  in  the  infant's  life,  and  virtually  determine  its  later  career, 
is  difficult  to  believe.  While  the  above  studies  consider  only  the  facts 
as  they  actually  occurred,  and  do  not  speculate  as  to  what  might. have 
happened  if  conditions  had  been  different,  yet  it  does  not  seeem  to  do 
violence  to  the  spirit  of  these  studies  to  say  that,  on  their  contention  of  the 
great  influence  of  the  first  years  of  infant  life  on  the  later  career,  Leonardo 
da  Vinci's  life  would  have  been  completely  changed  if  he  had  enjoyed  the 
presence  of  his  father  during  the  first  four  years  of  his  life ;  and  that  Wagner 
received  his  lasting  impressions  by  the  time  he  was  a  year  old. 

In  the  case  of  Zinzendorf ,  the  evidence  of  the  effect  of  the  early  impressions 
upon  his  later  sex  life  is  more  convincing.  The  repression  of  practically 
every  form  of  play  activity,  and  every  other  means  of  outlet  for  energy,  and 
the  increasing  emphasis  upon  the  crucifixion  of  Jesus,  with  its  tendency  to 
arouse  strong  emotions,  were  well  fitted  to  give  direction  to  his  entire  emo- 


R^CBNT   FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  423 

tional  life.  The  religious  care  with  which  his  mother  fostered  every  incipi- 
ent emotional  attitude  towards  Jesus,  even  in  his  earliest  years,  could  not 
have  been  better  planned  to  bring  about  his  adult  attitude. 

The  testimony  which  the  Freudians  marshal  in  support  of  the  conten- 
tion that  infancy  and  childhood  give  evidence  of  sex  manifestations  is 
being  extended,  from  time  to  time,  and  is  growing  convincing.  It  is  safe 
to  say  that  several  chapters  are  yet  to  be  written  on  the  early  sex  life  of 
children,  of  which  Freud  has  at  least  written  the  headings.  That  over- 
much fondling,  petting,  and  kissing  tend  to  sensitize  an  infant  to  this  form 
of  treatment,  and  make  it  sexually  precocious,  is  now  generally  granted  by 
all  close  students  of  this  phase  of  infant  life.  That  this  should  leave  per- 
manent traces  in  the  unconscious  is  easily  possible.  The  following  up  of 
early  impressions,  and  the  tracing  of  their  influence  upon  later  life  is  a 
challenging  problem,  but  one  not  yet  fully  developed.  Freud  has  here 
given  direction  to  a  line  of  investigation  that  is  sure  to  yield  an  abundant 
harvest. 

So  little  is  known  about  Leonardo  da  Vinci's  early  life  that  it  seems  a  pity 
that  some  other  more  familiar  character  was  not  chosen  in  preference  to 
him;  and  yet  when  one  reads  this  classic  analysis  by  that  prince  of  psy- 
choanalysts, one  almost  feels  that,  if  more  facts  had  been  at  hand,  his  almost 
magic  subtlety  of  analysis  would  have  had  less  opportunity  to  reveal  its 
power  and  penetration.  It  is  to  be  hoped  that  Freud  will,  in  the  near 
future,  psychoanalyze  Goethe,  Napoleon,  Alexander  the  Great,  or  some 
other  great  man,  concerning  whose  life  more  facts  are  at  hand. 

One  great  contribution  of  the  Freudian  investigations  to  the  knowledge 
of  sex  is  the  demonstration  that  the  energy  expended  in  the  satisfaction  of 
the  sex  impulse  may  be  sublimated  to  higher  mental  activities.  This  prin- 
ciple is  illustrated  most  fully  by  the  life  of  Leonardo  da  Vinci.  In  the  case 
of  Wagner,  it  was  not  nearly  so  complete;  while  Count  von  Zinzendorf 
offers  a  perhaps  unique  illustration  of  the  pathological  possibilities  in  this 
respect.  Instead  of  sublimating  his  sex  impulse,  he  directed  it  towards 
the  physical  Jesus  almost  in  toto.  It  was  simply  the  substitution  of  one 
sex  object  for  another,  and  the  transfer  of  physical  satisfaction  to  a  satis- 
faction due  to  the  active  use  of  the  imagination. 

This  sublimation  of  sex  energy  into  higher  mental  powers  and  capacities 
is  assumed  by  the  Freudians  to  have  been  the  very  means  of  establishing 
civilization.  It  was  the  long-circuiting  of  the  sex  impulse  that  produced 
art,  religion,  poetry  and  scientific  achievements.  It  is  when  sublimation 
does  not  take  place,  and  there  is  a  successful  effort  to  suppress  the  normal 
physical  expression  of  the  sex  impulse,  that  pathological  mental  symptoms 
may  begin  to  manifest  themselves. 

This  whole  problem  of  the  sublimation  of  energy  usually  expended  in  the 
sexual  sphere  to  higher  ends  is  of  immense  practical,  as  well  as  of  moral  and 
hygienic,  importance.  The  scientific  study  of  this  phase  of  life  cannot  be 
too  strongly  commended.  What  the  possibilities  and  limits  of  sublimation 
are,  is,  of  course,  not  yet  clear;  but  here  again  the  Freudians  have  begun  a 
line  of  investigation  that  promises  to  give  a  scientific  basis  for  dealing  with 
this  most  perplexing  and  far-reaching  of  human  problems.  It  might  be 
said,  in  passing,  that  it  is  this  inclusive  conception  of  sexuality  that  must 
be  adopted,  if  one  is  to  follow  the  sublimation  theory  as  worked  out  by  the 
Freudians. 

The  large  place  given  to  the  unconscious,  in  these  studies,  seems  to  the 
writer  to  be  wholly  justified,  even  if  one  is  unable  to  accept  all  the  com- 
plicated mechanism  and  symbolism  attributed  to  it.  The  Leonardesque 
smile  is  most  effectively  accounted  for  from  this  point  of  view.  The  same 
might  be  said  about  the  peculiar  characteristic  of  Wagner's  musical  and 
dramatic  productions,  with  their  triangular  complications,  of  which  the 
Flying  Dutchman  is  perhaps  the  best  type.  In  the  case  of  Zinzendorf  the 
evidence  of  the  effect  of  the  early  impressions  upon  his  later  life,  through 


424  ACHER 

the  mechanism  of  the  unconscious,  is  so  unmistakable  that  few  are  likely 
to  question  it. 

Another  prominent  characteristic  of  the  Freudian  theory  of  the  uncon- 
scious is  that  there  is  a  positive  tendency  to  suppress  those  elements  of 
childhood  experience  which  do  not  conform  to  the  moral  standards  of 
adults,  and  that  this  suppression  forces  these  memories  into  the  uncon- 
scious, where  they  have  a  positive  influence  in  directing  conduct.  This 
is  so  thoroughly  established  by  the  clinical  experience  of  the  psychoanalysts 
that  it  is  beyond  the  realm  of  controversy.  And  yet  this  point  is  frequently 
objected  to  on  the  ground  that  the  objecter  does  not  find  it  so  in  his  own  case. 
This  kind  of  argument  is  about  as  effective  as  was  that  which  attempted 
to  refute  Berkeley's  idealism  by  striking  the  earth  with  a  cane.  If  a  thing 
is  suppressed  and  forgotten  the  person  who  forgot  it  is  certainly  not  in 
a  position  to  argue  whether  or  not  it  has  been  forgotten.  That  the  child, 
in  each  of  the  above  cases,  should  have  suppressed  his  erotic  attitude  to- 
wards his  mother  cannot  be  doubted  in  the  light  of  the  mass  of  clinical 
evidence  adduced  by  the  psychoanalysts.  Here,  in  the  unconscious,  it 
still  exerted  a  great  influence  upon  the  adult  mind  in  all  of  these  characters. 

4.  Freud,  S.  Die  zukiinftigen  Chancen  der  psychoanalytischen  Therapie. 
Zentralblatt  fiir  Psychoanalyse,  1 910,     i .  Jahrgang,  Hef t  3^.     pp.  1-9. 

Freud  wisely  admits  that  psychoanalytical  therapy  has  not  yet  com- 
pletely won  its  battle,  much  as  it  has  already  accomplish  ed  in  the  treatment 
of  nervous  diseases.  He  believes,  however,  that  this  method  of  treatment 
has  a  bright  future  and  he  enumerates  the  sources  from  which  it  will 
derive  more  strength  as  time  goes  on. 

The  first  source  from  which  strength  will  come  will  be  a  better  under- 
standing of  the  mechanism  of  the  unconscious.  This  is  necessary  to  a 
correct  diagnosis.  Advances  may  be  expected  along  the  lines  of  a  proper 
interpretation  of  the  symbolism  of  dreams,  and  of  the  unconscious.  The 
symbolism  of  dreams  is  a  rich  field,  and  needs  yet  to  be  fully  developed 
and  explained. 

Another  source  of  strength  will  be  a  more  thorough  mastery  of  the  tech- 
nique of  psychoanalysis.  Two  problems  are  involved  here:  the  lessening 
of  the  labors  of  the  physician,  and  the  discovery  of  a  direct  avenue  to  the 
unconscious.  Considerable  change  in  the  technique  has  developed  since 
the  beginning  of  this  method  of  treatment.  Attention  was  at  first  directed 
to  an  explanation  of  the  symptoms;  then  to  the  discovery  of  the  com- 
plexes; and  now  attention  is  given  to  the  forces  of  opposition.  In 
order  to  be  successful  in  the  technique,  the  physician  must  have  examined 
his  own  psychic  life  sufficiently  to  recognize  symptoms  in  the  patient. 

An  inevitable  increase  in  authority  and  in  prestige  will  constitute  a  third 
source  of  strength.  Heretofore,  authority  with  its  powerful  ally,  sugges- 
tion, has  been  against  the  psychoanalyst.  The  very  truths  which  psycho- 
analysis discovers  tend  to  be  used  as  weapons  against  it.  But  truth  must 
ultimately  prevail  and  Freud  has  faith  that  it  will  be  so  in  the  case  of 
psychoanalysis. 

A  fourth  source  of  strength  will  come  when  the  knowledge  of  the  nature 
of  these  psychoneuroses  becomes  generally  known.  These  psychoneuroses 
are  due  to  the  disguised  compensatory  satisfaction  of  an  impulse,  whose 
existence  is  denied  by  the  patient  himself.  Its  very  success  depends  upon 
this  distorted  and  unrecognized  process.  When  the  symptoms  of  these 
neuroses  become  generally  known,  and  the  patient  knows  that  his  ail- 
ment is  generally  understood,  he  will  try  to  conceal  this  symptom  and  this 
concealment  will  effect  a  cure.  At  one  time,  peasant  maidens  were  fre- 
quently afflicted  with  the  delusion  of  being  the  holy  virgin,  for  it  received 
some  credence  among  the  people.  But  now  when  such  cases  occur,  people 
feel  that  the  girl  is  in  need  of  medical  treatment,  and  consequently  such 
delusions  are  rare.     Just  so  will  it  be  with  the  psychoneuroses. 


RECENT   FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  425 

Freud  gives  a  word  of  warning  against  the  invariable  employment  of 
therapeutic  and  hygienic  measures  in  all  cases  of  psychoneuroses.  He 
thinks  the  psychoneurosis  may  at  times  be  the  mildest  and  best  outlet  of 
an  impulse  that  would  lead  to  something  worse  if  this  means  of  expression 
were  cut  off. 

5.     Freud,  S.      Ueher  '-wilde'  Psychoanalyse.     Zentralblatt  fiir  Psychoan- 
alyse.    1910.     I  Jahrgang,  Heft  3.    pp.  91-95. 

This  article  is  a  protest  against  the  use  of  psychoanalysis  as  a  therapeutic 
measure  by  those  who  show,  by  their  application  of  it,  that  they  have 
mastered  neither  its  scientific  principles  nor  its  technical  details.  The 
paper  was  inspired  by  the  complaint  of  a  patient,  who  stated  that  she  had 
been  given  advice  by  a  young  physician  which  it  was  impossible  to  follow; 
and  that  her  feeling  of  anxiety  became  more  intense  after  consulting  this 
physician.  He  had  told  her  that  her  condition  was  due  to  unsatisfied 
sexual  needs,  and  that  she  should  return  to  her  divorced  husband  or  secure 
a  lover. 

Freud  laments  the  fact  that  any  one  should  do  such  violence  to  the 
principles  of  psychoanalysis,  when  a  study  of  the  literature  of  the  subject 
would  prevent  any  such  unpardonable  misapplication  of  its  principles 
and  techinque. 

The  first  blunder  which  this  physician  made  was  to  narrow  the  term 
sexual  life  to  the  merely  somatic  phases  of  the  term,  whereas  psychoan- 
alysis uses  the  term  in  a  very  much  more  inclusive  way.  This  is  justified 
from  the  genetic  point  of  view.  All  of  the  tender  emotions  are  considered 
to  be  a  part  of  the  sexual  life  which  had  their  source  in  the  primitive  sexual 
impulse,  even  though  they  inhibit  the  original  sexual  end  or  transform  it 
to  non-sexual  ends.  Psycho-sexuality  is  preferred  by  psychoanalysts, 
because  it  gives  proper  emphasis  to  the  psychic  factors.  It  is  almost 
synonymous  with  the  term  love.  The  author  points  out  that  there  are 
cases  which  show  every  indication  of  a  lack  of  mental  satisfaction,  with  all 
its  consequences,  accompanying  no  lack  of  sexual  indulgence  in  the  somatic 
sense  of  the  term.  These  unsatisfied  sexual  strivings,  which  often  create 
a  sort  of  substitute  satisfaction  that  shows  itself  in  nervous  symptoms, 
are  helped  very  little  by  sexual  indulgence.  Freud  emphasizes  the  fact 
that  those  who  limit  the  term  sexuality  to  the  merely  somatic  factors  have 
no  right  to  apply  the  principles  of  psychoanalysis  as  therapeutic  measures. 
It  deals  with  the  etiological  significance  of  sex,  and  must  include  all  factors 
however  remote  they  may  have  come  to  be,  through  individual  and  racial 
sublimation. 

A  second  misconception  of  the  above  mentioned  young  physician  was 
the  contention  that  want  of  sexual  satisfaction  is  the  cause  of  nervous 
disorders.  It  is  not  the  lack  of  satisfaction,  but  the  conflict  between  the 
hbidinous  impulse  and  the  effort  to  suppress  it  that  causes  the  trouble. 
Another  error  is  to  assume  that  all  symptoms  that  indicate  anxiety  are 
due  to  anxiety  neuroses,  and  can  be  cured  by  somatic  therapeutics.  It 
is  necessary  to  know  the  symptoms  which  indicate  anxiety  neurosis,  so  as  to 
distinguish  this  form  of  nervous  disorder  from  other  pathological  conditions 
with  anxiety  as  a  symptom.  No  adequate  therapeutic  measures  can  be 
applied  without  a  clear  grasp  of  this  distinction,  because  their  etiology  is 
different  in  each  case,  and  the  treatment  must  likewise  be  different. 

The  assumption  that  mere  lack  of  knowledge  of  the  cause  of  the  symp- 
toms does  the  injury,  and  that  this  information  given  to  the  patient  can 
effect  a  cure  is  as  foolish,  says  Freud,  as  to  assume  that  the  menu  card  can 
satisfy  the  appetite.  It  is  not  the  ignorance,  but  the  opposition  which 
causes  this  ignorance  by  suppressing  and  repressing  the  knowledge  of  the 
facts,  that  produces  the  psychic  disorder.  It  is  the  problem  of  therapeutics 
to  conquer  this  opposition,  and  to  bring  to  the  surface  the  facts  in  the  case. 


426  ACH^R 

Mere  telling  would  not  suffice.  The  physician  must  prepare  the  patient 
for  the  information,  and  must,  at  the  same  time,  secure  the  patient's  con- 
fidence so  that  when  the  true  state  of  affairs  begins  to  dawn  upon  the  pa- 
tient's consciousness,  he  will  believe  it  and  trust  the  physician.  This  takes 
infinite  tact  and  patience;  and  it  is  difficult  to  acquire  the  requisite 
technique.  To  avoid  responsibility  for  the  universal  application  of  psy- 
choanalysis, the  leaders  in  this  field  have  effected  an  international  organi- 
zation whose  membership  is  limited  to  practitioners  who  are  competent 
to  apply  psychoanalytical  principles.  In  this  way,  it  is  hoped  that  the 
friends  of  psychoanalysis  will  be  protected  from  the  blunders  of  those  who 
would  apply  it  without  a  mastery  of  its  fundamental  principles. 

6.  Freud,  S.  Die  psychogene  Sehstorung  in  psychoanalytischer  Auffassung. 
Arztliche  Fortbilding.     Jahrgang  1910,  Nr.  9.    pp.  1-7. 

Freud  is  not  satisfied  with  the  explanation  of  the  psychogenic  visual 
disturbances  which  is  offered  by  the  French  school,  of  which  Janet  is  the 
chief  exponent;  and  he  offers  a  theory  of  his  own,  which  he  believes  comes 
much  nearer  to  the  facts.  All  psychopathologists  have  come  to  recognize 
the  unconscious  as  an  ever  present  phenomenon  in  cases  of  hysteria.  For 
example,  in  the  hysterically  blind  certain  visual  stimuli  will  awaken 
strong  emotions,  even  though  the  patient  declares  he  sees  nothing.  These 
people  are  blind  only  for  consciousness.  For  the  unconscious  they  can 
see.  It  is  such  phenomena  as  these  that  force  us  to  recognize  a  distinction 
between  the  conscious  and  the  unconscious. 

Why  this  conscious  blindness  and  the  unconscious  ability  to  see?  The 
French  school  answers  with  the  statement  that  there  is  a  tendency  to 
dissociation.  Perhaps  the  idea  of  being  blind  acts  as  an  auto-suggestion; 
and  the  actual  state  of  blindness  follows.  In  this  way,  many  unconscious 
processes  become  separated  from  conscious  processes.  In  all  of  this,  there 
is  an  innate,  dispositional  inability  to  synthetize  experiences,  due  perhaps 
to  native  weakness. 

Freud  holds  that  this  is  only  substituting  one  riddle  for  another.  He 
points  out  that  it  is  difficult  to  harmonize  the  following  phases  of  Janet's 
theory;  the  rise  of  an  idea  that  acts  as  an  auto-suggestion;  his  discrimi- 
nation between  conscious  and  unconscious  mental  processes;  and  the 
assumption  that  there  is  a  mental  tendency  to  dissociation.  All  of  these 
are  used  by  the  French  school  in  their  effort  to  explain  these  cases. 

Psychonalysis  offers  a  more  satisfactory  explanation.  It  accepts  the 
ideas  of  the  unconscious  and  of  dissociation;  but  it  considers  them  in  a 
different  relation.  It  considers  the  psychic  life  as  made  up  of  dynamic 
factors  which  enforce  or  inhibit  one  another.  If  a  group  of  ideas  is  in  the 
unconscious,  it  does  not  assume  a  constitutional  inability  to  synthetize 
the  various  psychic  elements  as  the  basis  of  this  dissociation.  It  considers 
this  group  of  ideas  in  the  unconscious  as  having  come  in  conflict  with 
another  group  of  ideas,  and  as  having  been  repressed  by  them  into  the 
unconscious.  It  assumes  that  such  repressions  play  an  extraordinarily 
important  role  in  our  mental  life,  and  that  disturbances  may  often  arise 
as  a  result  of  an  unsuccessful  effort  to  repress  ideas.  This  gives  rise  to  the 
symptoms  of  hysteria. 

When  in  psychogenic  disturbances  of  sight,  certain  ideas  connected  with 
sight  are  shut  out  from  consciousness,  psychoanalysis  assumes  that  these 
ideas  came  into  opposition  with  other  stronger  ideas  which  forced  them 
into  the  unconscious  by  an  act  of  repression.  This  latter  group  of  ideas 
may  be  termed  the  self  group.  Why  this  conflict  between  groups  of 
ideas?  Here  we  must  consider  the  significance  of  impulses  for  the  rise 
and  decline  of  ideas.  Every  impulse  tends  to  arouse  and  appropriate 
to  its  use  all  those  ideas  which  serve  its  ends.  These  impulses  do  not 
always  have  the  same  ends;  and  conflict  of  interests  is  common.  The 
conflict  of  ideas,   therefore,   rests  upon    a  conflict  of  impulses.     There 


RECENT  FREUDIAN  UTKRATURE  427 

is  an  undoubted  conflict  between  those  impulses  which  have  sexual 
pleasures  for  their  object  and  those  others  which  tend  to  the  preservation 
of  the  individual.  These  latter  might  be  called  the  self-preservation 
impulses ;  and  they  might  correspond  to  the  group  of  ideas  whidi  were  men- 
tioned above,  and  which  are  known  as  the  self  group.  Freud  accepts  the 
words  of  the  poet  that  hunger  and  love  rule  the  world;  and  holds  that  all 
organic  impulses  which  manifest  themselves  in  the  psychic  life  of  the 
individual  could  be  classified  under  the  terms  hunger  and  love. 

The  sexual  impulse  has  been  followed  from  its  first  manifestations  in 
childhood  to  its  mature  development ;  and  it  has  been  found  to  be  made  up 
of  a  number  of  partial  impulses,  which  arise  from  the  stimulation  of  various 
parts  of  the  body.  It  has  also  been  found  that  these  isolated  impulses 
must  undergo  a  complex  development  before  they  can  be  brought  to  serve 
their  final  purpose  of  procreation.  The  application  of  psychology  to  the 
study  of  cultural  development  shows  that  culture  arises  by  means  of  the 
sublimation,  inhibition  and  repression  of  these  isolated  or  partial  impulses. 
All  disorders,  known  as  neuroses,  are  traceable  to  the  miscarriage  of  these 
attempted  transformations  of  the  partial  sexual  impulses.  The  impulse 
to  self-preservation  feels  that  it  is  threatened  by  the  demands  of  the  sexual 
impulse,  and  protects  itself  through  repressions,  which  do  not  always  have 
the  desired  result.  These  repressed  impulses  may  establish  a  substitute 
as  a  means  of  satisfaction ;  and  they  will  thus  have  an  injurious  effect  upon 
the  mental  integrity  of  the  individual.  In  this  way  the  symptoms  known 
as  neuroses  are  built  up. 

From  this  point  of  view  the  neuroses  are  brought  into  vital  relation  with 
the  whole  psychic  life.  Returning  now  to  the  special  problem  under  consid- 
eration, it  must  be  granted  that  all  organs  and  systems  of  the  body  may 
serve  both  the  sexual  impulse,  and  the  impulse  to  self-preservation.  Sex- 
ual pleasure  is  not  limited  to  the  genitals.  The  mouth  serves  for  kissing, 
as  well  as  for  eating.  The  eyes  not  only  observe  what  is  necessary  for  the 
preservation  of  life,  but  also  those  features  of  an  object  that  make  it  an 
object  of  love.  It  is  not  easy  to  serve  two  masters.  The  more  such  an  organ 
with  a  double  function  serves  the  one  impulse,  the  less  it  tends  to  serve 
the  other.  This  principle  must  lead  to  pathological  consequences,  when 
the  two  fundamental  impulses  work  at  cross  purposes,  and  the  self  pres- 
ervation impulse  represses  any  partial  impulse  that  might  serve  the 
sexual  end.  The  application  of  this  to  visual  disturbances  can  easily 
be  made.  The  partial  sexual  impulse  connected  with  the  eye  might  be 
called  sexual  curiosity.  If  this  impulse,  on  account  of  its  undue  service 
in  the  interests  of  sexual  pleasure,  draws  to  itself  the  opposition  of  the  self- 
impulse,  so  that  the  ideas  in  which  it  expresses  itself  are  repressed,  and  do 
not  come  to  consciousness,  there  is  sure  to  be  a  disturbance  in  the  relations 
of  vision  to  consciousness.  The  self  has  lost  its  domination  over  the  eye, 
which  now  gives  itself  over  entirely  to  the  service  of  the  repressed  sexual 
impulse.  It  gives  the  impression  of  having  gone  too  far  in  the  repression 
of  the  partial  sexual  impulse,  in  that  the  self  now  refuses  to  see  at  all, 
since  the  sexual  interests  pressed  forward  so  vigorously  in  sight.  As  a  sort 
of  retaliation  the  repressed  impulse  claims  the  exclusive  use  of  the  eye; 
and  this  is  the  price  consciousness  has  to  pay  for  the  repression. 

A  similar  case  is  that  of  the  hand  which  becomes  hysterically  paralyzed 
after  it  has  attempted  to  carry  out  some  sexual  aggression,  but  is  inhibited 
from  accomplishing  its  purpose,  just  as  if  it  remained  stubbornly  by  its 
impulse  to  carry  out  the  repressed  innervation.  In  the  beautiful  legend 
of  Lady  Godiva,  all  the  townspeople  hid  themselves  behind  closed  shutters 
in  order  to  lighten  the  task  of  this  lady  who  was  required  to  ride  through 
the  streets  naked  in  daylight.  Any  one  who  looked  at  the  naked  beauty 
was  punished  by  losing  his  eye-sight.  This  legend  is  one  of  many  in  which 
the  key  to  interpretation  is  found  in  neuroticism. 


428  ACH^R 

F'reud  says  the  criticism  that  these  pathological  processes  are  explained 
by  purely  psychological  theory  is  unjust,  since  the  emphasis  in  all  of  these 
cases  is  placed  upon  the  pathogenic  role  of  sexuality,  which  is  certainly 
not  exclusively  psychic.  Psychoanalysis  never  forgets  that  the  psychic 
factors  rest  on  the  organic,  although  its  work  only  leads  to  the  latter,  and 
it  does  not  attempt  an  organic  explanation.  It  is  also  ready  to  postulate 
that  not  all  functional  disturbances  of  vision  are  of  psychic  origin.  When 
an  organ  which  serves  both  kinds  of  impulses  increases  its  erotic  role,  it  is  very 
probable  that  this  does  not  happen  without  a  change  of  irritability  and 
innervation,  which  manifest  themselves  as  disturbances  of  the  function  of 
the  organ  in  its  service  of  the  self.  It  is  not  improbable  that  there  may  be 
toxic  changes  at  the  basis  of  a  change  of  the  organ's  service  from  that  of 
self  to  that  of  sexual  ends.  The  term  neurotic  disturbances  covers  dis- 
orders of  functional  or  physiological  as  well  as  of  toxic  origin. 

7.  FrBud,  S.  Ueher  den  Gegensinn  der  Urworte.  Jahrbuch  f  iir  psycho- 
analytische  und  psychopathologische  Forschungen.  Band  II.  1910. 
pp.  179-184. 

In  this  article  Freud  points  out  a  striking  parallel  between  certain 
dream  phenomena  and  certain  ancient  linguistic  usages.  He  maintains 
that,  in  dreams,  the  negative  does  not  occur.  Opposites  are  brought  into 
unity,  or  are  presented  as  one,  with  peculiar  predilection.  Since  in  dreams 
all  desirable  things  are  attained,  because  of  the  law  of  wish  fulfilment, 
there  can  be  no  opposite  or  opposing  factor. 

The  dream  intrepreters  of  old  seem  to  have  recognized  the  fact  that  in 
a  dream  a  thing  can  represent  its  opposite. 

Freud  says  he  reached  an  understanding  of  this  peculiar  dream  phe- 
nomenon of  avoiding  the  negative  and  of  presenting  opposites  with  the 
same  word,  on  reading  Abel's  pamphlet.  This  author  points  out  the  great 
age  of  the  Egyptian  language,  and  then  shows  that  in  this  language  there 
are  many  words  which  possess  two  meanings,  the  one  of  which  is  the 
direct  opposite  of  the  other.  It  will  thus  be  seen  that  this  familiar  char- 
acteristic of  dreams  is  identical  with  that  of  the  oldest  of  ancient  languages. 

The  explanation  which  Abel  offers  for  this  characteristic  of  ancient  lan- 
guages is  as  follows:  Our  notions  of  things  are  a  product  of  a  process  of 
comparison.  If  it  were  always  light,  we  could  have  no  conception  of  dark- 
ness. All  things  are  thus  relative  to  one  other.  Thus  every  conception 
is,  in  a  sense,  a  twin  of  its  opposite;  and,  originally,  the  one  could  not  be 
thought  of  without  the  other.  Thus,  one  word  always  brought  to  mind 
both  ideas;  and  the  two  ideas  were  expressed  by  the  one  word.  It  was 
by  a  gradual  process  that  each  idea  came  to  have  a  term  of  its  own,  and 
could  be  thought  of  without  its  opposite.  In  writing,  the  ancient  Egyp- 
tians always  used  a  determining  picture  before  the  word  to  designate  the 
meaning  intended.  Two  words  were  subsequently  evolved  which  sprang 
from  the  same  root  with  its  double  meaning.  According  to  this  writer, 
the  same  characteristic  is  common  to  the  Semitic  and  to  various  European 
languages.  In  Latin,  altus — means  high,  and  deep;  sacer, — holy,  and 
danmed.  Some  phonetic  modification  may  be  made  as  clamare,  to  cry 
out — clam,  quiet;  siccus,  dry — succus,  soft.  In  German  Boden  means  the 
uppermost  as  well  as  the  lowest  in  the  house,  even  to-day.  From  bos 
(schlecht)  sprang  bass  which  means  good;  in  old  Saxon  bat,  which  means 
good,  as  against  the  English,  bad.  In  English,  "to  lock,"  as  against  the 
German  Liicke,  a  hole,  illustrates  the  same  phenomenon. 

Another  peculiarity  of  the  Egyptian  language  is  that  the  letters  of  a 
word  may  be  reversed  and  still  represent  the  same  thing.  If  bad  were 
Egyptian  it  might  also  be  written  dab.  This  also  holds  true  of  other  lan- 
guages. It  is  also  a  thing  which  children  take  a  peculiar  pleasure  in  doing. 
In  dreams,  the  material  is  often  reversed  to  serve  a  definite  end.  Here, 


RieC^NT   FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  429 

however,  it  is  not  letters  that  are  reversed,  but  ideas  and  images.  Freud 
thinks  that  this  similarity  between  dreams  and  ancient  languages  justifies 
the  inference  that  dreams  are  regressive  and  archaic  in  character;  and  that, 
to  understand  dreams,  we  must  know  more  of  the  evolution  of  language 
and  speech. 

8.  Freud,  S.  Beitrdge  zur  Psychologie  des  Liebeslebens.  Jarhbuch  fiir 
psychoanalytische  und  psychopathologische  Forschungen.  Band  II. 
1910.     pp.  389-397- 

Freud  believes  that  poets  have  been  entrusted  too  exclusively  to  tell  us 
about  the  psychology  of  love,  and  its  various  manifestations.  Their  aims 
have  never  been  to  be  true  to  the  fact,  for  they  always  make  full  use  of 
poetic  license  in  dealing  with  this  theme. 

Psychoanalysis  gives  special  opportunity  to  obtain  glimpses  into  the 
love-life  of  patients,  which  one  may  also  notice  in  daily  life  after  one's  atten- 
tion has  been  called  to  it.  Certain  types  are  discovered  on  the  basis  of 
object  choice.  The  type  here  discussed  is  characterized  by  several  con- 
ditions which  call  forth  the  feeling. 

The  first  condition  is  that  of  including  an  injured  third  party.  Such 
a  man  never  loves  a  woman  who  is  free  or  has  no  lover.  Sometimes  the 
woman  may  even  be  ridiculed  until  she  enters  into  the  above-mentioned 
relation,  when  she  at  once  becomes  the  object  of  the  most  intense  love. 

The  second  condition  of  love  is  that  the  woman  be  not  virtuous,  or,  at 
least,  not  above  si'spicion.  This  characteristic  may  vary  from  the  flirt  to 
the  genuinely  polygamous  coquette. 

As  the  first  condition  gives  opportunity  for  satisfying  the  malignant 
feeling  or  impulse  towards  the  man  whose  loved  one  is  won  away  from 
him,  the  second  condition  gives  opportunity  for  the  exercise  of  the  feeling 
of  jealousy,  which  seems  to  be  a  necessary  accompaniment  of  this  type  of 
Igve.  It  is  only  then  that  the  woman  attains  to  full  worth  in  the  eyes  of 
the  lover.  Strangely  enough,  jealousy  is  never  directed  against  the  right- 
ful possessor  of  the  loved  one,  but  against  the  new-comer,  with  whom  the 
woman  might  be  brought  into  question.  It  is  only  during  this  triangular 
relation  that  the  love  continues.  This  is  an  abnormal  condition,  be- 
cause, in  normal  love,  the  moral  integrity  of  the  woman  is  a  necessary 
pre-condition.  A  peculiar  trait  of  this  type  of  lover  is  that  he  wants  to 
save  his  object  of  love  from  a  career  of  vice.  But  a  successful  accomplish- 
ment of  this  purpose  does  not  intensify  the  love  relationship;  in  fact, 
failure  to  save  her  increases  his  love. 

A  psychoanalysis  of  these  characters  reveals  the  fact  that  there  is 
one  determining  cause  for  these  various  conditions  of  masculine  love. 
It  springs  from  the  infantile  tenderness  towards  the  mother,  which  has 
become  fixed.  In  normal  love,  there  remain  few  traces  of  this  early 
attitude  towards  the  mother.  Occasionally  they  manifest  themselves  in 
cases  in  which  young  men  fall  in  love  with  older  women.  In  the  type 
here  under  discussion,  the  object  of  love  is  a  mother  surrogate,  because 
the  mother's  influence  cannot  be  cast  off.  This  accounts  for  the  fact 
that  the  woman  who  attracts  attention  must  be  attached  to  a  third 
party.  The  child  soon  learns  that  the  mother  is  united  to  the  father;  and 
the  latter  becomes  the  injured  third  party.  The  intensity  and  fidelity  of 
the  devotion  of  this  type  of  lover  is  also  an  echo  of  the  undivided  love  of 
mother.  The  frequent  change  of  the  object  of  love  also  suggests  that  the 
surrogate  does  not  fully  satisfy  the  unconscious  demands  of  the  individual. 

How  does  this  love  for  an  unfaithful  coquette  spring  from  the  mother- 
constellation  of  the  child,  when  the  very  term  mother  is  the  direct  opposite 
of  prostitute  in  our  adult  conscious  minds?  The  unconscious  often  con- 
siders as  one  what  consciousness  separates  into  opposites.  Here,  again, 
we  must  go  back  for  an  explanation  to  the  time  when  the  child  obtains 


430  ACHl^R 

his  first  knowledge  of  the  sexual  relations  of  adults.  This  information  often 
comes  in  ways  that  destroy  the  child's  faith  in  adults.  He  may  even  deny 
that  this  relation  between  adults  of  the  opposite  sex  applies  to  his  own 
parents.  At  about  this  time,  he  also  learns  that  some  women  become 
prostitutes;  and  that  their  conduct  destroys  people's  respect  for  them. 
When  he  learns  that  his  mother  is  not  different  from  other  parents  in  sexual 
matters,  he  cynically  says  that,  after  all,  there  is  not  such  a  great  difference 
between  his  mother  and  the  prostitute,  because  both  are  guilty  of  the  same 
thing.  This  information  awakes  his  memories  of  his  infantile  impres- 
sions and  wishes,  which  again  become  active.  But  the  father  stands  be- 
tween him  and  his  desire.  The  CEdipus  complex  becomes  active.  He 
therefore  lives,  in  fancy,  his  wish  fulfilment.  The  two  motives  of  desire 
and  revenge  are  favorable  to  the  fancy  that  the  mother  is  untrue.  The 
lover  with  whom  she  is  untrue  is  usually  the  idealized,  mature  self. 

It  is  thus  easy  to  see  that  this  family  romance  leaves  traces  in  the  uncon- 
scious ;  and  that  this  is  why  it  is  necessary  for  the  woman  to  be  a  coquette 
or  a  prostitute  in  order  to  arouse  the  passion  of  love  in  the  adult.  The 
pubertal  fancies  persist  in  the  unconscious,  and  demand  satisfaction  in 
the  reality  of  later  life. 

The  desire  to  save  the  woman  who  is  loved  springs  from  the  parent-com- 
plex. When  the  son  learns  that  he  owes  his  life  to  his  parents,  he  is  seized 
with  a  desire  to  repay  them  in  some  equally  worthy  way.  His  attitude 
toward  the  father  becomes  more  haughty  and  he  fancies  that  he  saves 
him  from  some  great  danger.  Toward  his  mother,  his  attitude  is  more 
tender  and  worthy,  and  the  notion  of  saving  his  mother  is  transformed, 
in  the  unconscious,  to  a  desire  to  present  her  with  a  child, — naturally  a 
child  like  himself.  The  mother  has  given  the  child  his  life,  and  he  can 
only  give  her  another  life,  that  of  a  child  which  resembles  himself.  In 
this  sense  he  identifies  himself  with  his  father,  and  wishes  to  become  his 
own  father.  Thus,  the  notion  of  saving  the  woman  he  loves  really  means 
to  bring  a  child  to  birth ;  and  the  symbol  must  be  interpreted  just  as  in 
dreams.  The  idea  of  danger  is  associated  with  the  birth  of  the  child.  Freud 
thinks  the  experience  of  being  bom  is  a  sort  of  type  of  all  later  danger 
and  anxiety,  since  it  left  an  affective  impression  which  developed  into 
anxiety. 

9.  Sadger,  J.  Aus  dem  Lieheslehen  Nicolaus  Lenaus.  Schriften  zur 
angewandten  Seelenkunde,  1909.       Sechstes  Heft.     pp.  1-98. 

This  is  a  psychoanalytical  study  of  the  love  between  the  poet  Lenau 
and  Sophie,  the  wife  of  his  friend  Max  Lowenthal.  The  writer  points  out 
that  in  any  such  triangular  relation,  the  situation  is  wholly  in  the  hands 
of  the  woman.  Sophie  Lowenthal  was  an  intelligent  woman,  who  married 
at  the  urgent  entreaties  of  her  parents,  and  not  because  she  loved  her  hus- 
band. She  felt  he  was  not  her  equal.  She  had  three  children;  and,  at 
twenty-six  years  of  age,  refused  to  have  further  sexual  relations  with  her 
husband.  She  was  sexually  anaesthetic,  excepting  that  she  loved  to  be 
caressed  and  kissed.  This  she  received  from  Lenau  freely  and  almost 
daily  during  their  period  of  love.  Her  husband  was  assured  that  Lenau 
would  not  go  too  far  because  of  her  peculiar  condition.  This  is  a 
typical  symptom  of  hysteria,  in  the  case  of  women  who  have  borne  children. 
Sophie  had  other  symptoms  of  hysteria  also. 

The  influence  of  her  father  dominated  her  entire  life.  He  had  the  patri- 
archal attitude  and  Sophie  had  more  than  a  child's  love  for  him.  He 
called  the  children  together  two  or  three  times  a  week  to  tell  them  of  nature 
and  of  history,  and  to  these  recitals  Sophie  listened  intently.  From  this 
relation  with  her  father,  she  acquired  the  longing  to  associate  with  famous 
men. 

It  is  well  known  that  the  first  love  of  children  is  always  the  parent  of  the 
opposite  sex;  and  that  later  so-called  first  loves  are  simply  the  renewal  of 


RE)CE;nT   FREUDIAN   UT^RATURE  43 1 

this  earlier  love  in  disguise.  This  was  strikingly  true  in  the  case  of  Sophie. 
The  two  men  whom  she  really  loved  resembled  her  father  in  many  ways. 

The  love  of  the  child  for  its  parent  should  not  be  confused  with  the  con- 
scious sexual  love  of  later  years.  The  tender  love  of  Sophie  for  her  father 
is  a  universal  phenomenon,  and  contained  nothing  but  the  purest  sentiment. 
He  kissed  her,  embraced  her,  took  her  on  his  lap,  carried  her  upon  his  arm, 
and  the  like,  as  any  father  would  do.  However,  it  is  nevertheless  true 
that  this  early  experience  sinks  deeply  into  the  child's  very  soul  and  often 
determines  its  later  love-choice.  It  is  held  by  many  writers  that,  in 
cases  where  two  persons  fall  in  love  at  first  sight,  they  resemble  each 
other.  This  is  explained  by  the  fact  that  the  man  selects  a  woman  that 
resembles  his  first  love,  i.  e.,  his  mother,  whom  he  naturally  resembles. 
The  same  is  true  with  the  woman.  Thus  each  resembles  a  parent  of  the 
other  which  insures  their  resemblance  to  each  other.  The  innocent  love 
between  the  child  and  parent,  therefore,  teaches  the  child  to  love,  in  later 
fife,  and  determines  the  choice,  all  unconsciously. 

This  explains  Sophie's  attitude  toward  Lenau.  He  was  a  noted  man 
like  her  father,  as  she  thought.  She  granted  him  everything  which  her 
father  granted  her,  in  her  childhood  and  refused  other  concessions  because 
she  repressed  these  in  her  attitude  toward  her  father.  Sexually  anaesthetic 
women  are  often  made  so  by  the  fact  that  they  repress  the  incestuous  feel- 
ing toward  the  parent  of  the  opposite  sex  at  puberty,  and  continue  in  this 
attitude  toward  the  men  of  their  choice  throughout  life. 

Her  piety  also  sprang  from  her  love  for  her  father,  which  shows  that  re- 
ligion and  love  have  the  same  foundation.  God  becomes  the  embodiment 
of  fatherly  virtues.  At  fifteen,  she  placed  all  suffering  upon  the  Lord  who 
cares  for  all  as  her  father  cared  for  his  children.  Her  hope  for  another  life 
was  due  to  her  unsatisfied  longings  in  this  life.  This  played  an  important 
role  in  her  love  for  Kochil,  her  first  lover,  whom  she  surrendered  at  the  re- 
quest of  her  father.  The  only  other  man  she  ever  loved  was  Lenau ;  and 
toward  him  she  manifested  the  same  attitude  that  she  did  towards  her 
father. 

In  Lenau's  early  life  the  (Edipus  complex  was  unusually  well  developed; 
and  he  never  succeeded  in  getting  away  from  his  mother's  influence.  She 
was  intensely  emotional  and  violently  passionate.  She  threatened  to  take 
her  life,  when  her  dear  ones  died,  just  as  Lenau  later  threatened  to  do. 
Her  attitude  toward  her  son,  Lenau,  was  always  characterized  by  the 
strongest  emotion  and  love.  She  saw  his  father's  traits  in  her  son,  and 
loved  him  the  more  for  this  because  her  husband  died  when  Lenau  was 
five  years  old.  She  idolized  him  in  the  most  extreme  manner.  At  times 
she  was  possessed  with  the  idea  that  she  might  lose  her  son,  or  that  some- 
thing had  happened  to  him  when  away  from  her.  She  frequently  deserted 
her  second  husband  and  children  to  follow  him.  She  often  prepared 
special  food  for  him,  and  served  it  while  he  was  still  in  bed.  His  will  was 
always  supreme.  His  mother  sowed  the  seeds  of  megalomania  in  many 
ways;  and  in  adult  life  these  childhood  fancies  and  impressions  dictated 
his  entire  life.  He  felt  that  the  world  did  not  recognize  his  worth,  and  did 
not  reward  him  as  he  deserved.  He  tried  to  act  the  part  of  a  nobleman 
although  his  means  did  not  allow  it.  He  could  not  endure  a  joke  at  his 
expense;  and  tolerated  moods  only  in  himself.  He  became  desperate, 
when  fate  did  not  always  deal  with  him  as  his  mother  did.  He  became 
intolerably  indolent  in  adult  life,  because  his  bodily  and  mental  wants  as 
a  child  had  been  so  completely  satisfied  by  his  mother.  He  refused  to 
strive  or  plead  for  anything  as  a  man  because  such  a  course  had  not  been 
necessary  to  secure  what  he  wanted  from  his  mother. 

He  could  never  love  a  woman  unless  the  conditions  were  identical  with 
those  of  his  early  home  life.  He  must  be  the  centre  of  attraction,  with  no 
rival  in  sight.  He  must  be  allowed  to  live  the  same  life  of  indolence  and 
carelessness  as  when  he  was  a  boy;  he  must  be  allowed  to  come  and  go 


432  ACHER 

when  he  pleased,  to  talk  or  be  silent  as  his  mood  dictated.  Three  families 
catered  to  these  caprices.  The  jfirst  was  that  of  his  sister,  Therese,  who 
was  attached  to  him  from  childhood.  She  loved  him  more  than  her  hus- 
band and  children;  her  attitude  toward  him  was  similar  t^o  that  of  his 
mother.  Emile  Reinbeck  also  gave  him  the  same  attention,  and  he  loved 
her  devotedly.  But  the  woman  who  most  nearly  embodied  his  mother's 
attitude  toward  him  and  whose  intuition  led  her  to  adjust  herself  more 
and  more  to  this  pattern  of  his  mother  was  Sophie  Lowenthal. 

He  even  demanded  good  food  from  his  feminine  friends  as  his  mother  had 
always  catered  to  his  appetite.  He  never  went  walking  for  his  health, 
never  took  a  bath,  never  ventilated  his  room.  His  mother's  influence  was 
evident  even  in  such  matters  as  his  sleeping  with  the  candle  burning,  and 
his  invariable  habit  of  taking  more  personal  effects  (umbrellas,  books, 
canes)  with  him  than  he  needed,  whenever  he  travelled. 

It  is  clear  that  through  his  mother's  mistaken  kindness,  Lenau  was 
mightily  influenced  in  large  matters  as  in  small,  in  youth  as  in  later  life, 
in  his  character  as  in  his  bodily  condition;  and  this  gave  direction  to  his 
insanity.  Every  woman,  whom  the  poet  could  love,  must  remind  him 
of  his  mother.  In  fact,  in  loving  other  women,  he  only  loved  his  mother 
in  disguise. 

He  had  sadistic,  as  well  as  homosexual,  tendencies,  which,  however,  did 
not  crop  out  until  his  insane  period  when  his  inhibitions  were  removed. 

His  love  for  his  violin  and  guitar  was  distinctly  erotic.  Both  these  in- 
struments have  long  been  regarded  as  symbols  of  the  feminine  form,  and 
this  was  plainly  the  case  with  Lenau.  This  was  more  evident  in  his  in- 
sane period,  when  he  adopted  the  same  tender  attitude  toward  his  violin 
that  he  had  previously  manifested  toward  the  women  of  his  love.  He 
would  allow  no  one  to  touch  it.  Both  homosexual  as  well  as  heterosexual 
motives  were  associated  with  the  violin.  When  he  disliked  his  violin 
teacher,  he  also  discarded  the  instrument  for  the  guitar.  But  when  he 
found  a  violin  teacher  whom  he  loved,  his  love  for  this  instrument  also  re- 
turned. At  times  he  played  his  violin  all  night  long;  this  long-continued 
activity  gave  rise  to  a  state  of  intense  exaltation,  but  it  was  followed  by  a 
reaction.  At  times,  he  played  Beethoven  with  such  vigor  that  drops  of 
perspiration  appeared  upon  his  face,  and  he  became  completely  exhausted. 
When  he  was  intensely  in  love  with  a  woman  who  responded  to  his  love, 
his  interest  in  his  violin  decreased,  but  was  again  awakened  when  his  love 
grew  cold. 

There  is  evidence  for  a  belief  that  he  masturbated  more  or  less.  In 
conversation  he  was  pains-takingly  careful  not  to  allude  to  anything  ques- 
tionable, and  he  was  mortally  offended  when  others  mentioned  such  sub- 
jects to  him.  This  phenomenon  is  frequently  caused  by  a  desire  to  com- 
pensate for  a  secret  vice.  The  healthy  man  does  not  take  pleasure  in 
sensual  conversation ;  neither  is  he  deeply  affected  by  it. 

His  teacher,  Kovesdy,  stimulated  his  homosexual  nature  as  his  mother 
did  his  heterosexual. 

His  love  episode  with  Bertha  left  an  indeUble  impression  upon  him.  Her 
unfaithfulness  to  him  caused  him  more  pain  and  misery,  in  his  later  life, 
that  can  fully  be  accounted  for  by  the  fact  that  he  inherited  a  despondent 
disposition.  This  suffering  did  not  begin  until  after  his  mother's  death. 
It  would  seem  that  he,  in  some  way,  identified  his  mother  with  Bertha, 
because  in  his  childhood  his  mother  was  untrue  to  him  in  that  she  bore 
children  to  his  step-father.  But  more  likely  there  was  also  an  element  of 
self-condemnation  in  it,  because  he  was  untrue  to  his  first  love. 

His  fixed  idea  to  come  to  America  in  spite  of  the  protestations  of  friends 
and  relatives  points  to  unconscious,  repressed,  erotic  feelings.  First  of 
all  this  idea  sprang  from  his  identifying  himself  with  Kovesdy,  who  had 
failed  to  carry  out  his  plan  of  coming  to  America.  Lenau  thus  wanted 
to  complete  his  friend's  wish,  and  at  the  same  time  to  regain  his  purity  in 


RECENT   FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  433 

a  strange  land,  in  order  thereby  to  become  worthy  of  his  mother  again. 
He  carried  out  his  idea  faithfully  while  in  America;  but,  after  his  return, 
intense  happiness  alternated  with  deep  melancholy.  It  was  at  this  time 
that  Sophie  Lowenthal  began  to  exercise  her  influence  over  him.  His 
identification  of  Sophie  with  his  mother  was  a  very  gradual  process.  She 
first  manifested  great  interest  in  his  poetic  works,  which  enabled  her  to 
creep  into  his  affections.  Her  indifference  toward  her  husband  led  her 
to  value  his  attentions.  His  mother's  recent  death  left  a  vacant  place  in 
his  affections  which  Sophie  soon  began  to  occupy,  because  of  her  tender- 
ness to  him.  When  he  discovered  her  to  be  with  child  there  returned  the 
old  feeling  which  he  had  formerly  experienced  toward  his  mother  when  as 
a  child  she  became  pregnant  from  his  step-father.  His  love  for  Sophie 
now  became  all  the  more  intense. 

From  this  time  on,  Sophie  refused  her  husband  marital  intimacy,  and 
informed  Lenau  of  the  fact.  This  fulfilled  a  strong  childhood  wish  in 
reference  to  his  mother  and  completed  the  identity  of  Sophie  and  his 
mother. 

A  peculiar  relation  existed  between  his  love  and  his  piety.  When  in 
love,  he  was  very  religious;  when  not  in  love,  he  was  sceptical.  At  times 
he  almost  identified  God  and  Sophie.  Both  he  and  Sophie  believed  that, 
in  the  hereafter,  their  fondest  hopes  and  longings  would  be  realized.  He 
pictured  the  hearafter  thus:  "My  atmosphere  will  be  your  breath;  my 
light  will  be  your  eye;  my  drink  will  be  your  word;  my  blood,  your  kiss; 
my  bed,  your  heart;  my  place  of  abode,  the  kingdom  of  God  with  you, 
dear  Sophie!" 

Sophie's  hysteria  demanded  a  lover  who  was  satisfied  with  the  satis- 
faction of  the  impulse  to  contrectation  without  detumescence,  to  use  Moll's 
terminology.  Both  were  saved  from  the  evil  consequences  of  unsatisfied 
sexual  excitement  by  a  greater  ailment.  It  was  a  case  of  a  smaller  evil 
being  swallowed  up  by  a  larger  one.  In  her  case,  it  was  hysteria;  in  his 
case,  his  serious  afifliction  which  later  culminated  in  insanity.  Under 
similar  circumstances,  a  normal  person  would  have  been  subject  to  anxiety 
neuroses.  Sophie's  jealousy  was  in  a  measure  due  to  this  partial  unsatis- 
faction,  as  is  the  case  with  most  women  who  are  jealous. 

There  is  little  doubt  that,  if  Lenau  and  Sophie  had  been  free  to  marry, 
they  would  never  have  lived  together  long.  His  inability  to  attach  his 
attention  to  any  one  thing  for  a  long  time,  as  well  as  her  anaesthetic  nature, 
would  have  tended  against  this.  It  was  only  the  thought  of  constant 
danger  of  separation  that  bound  them  together.  Lenau  appreciated 
this  when  he  said  that  his  misfortune  was  the  greatest  joy  of  his  life.  In 
both  cases,  they  obeyed  the  law  of  love,  and  ignored  every  other  considera- 
tion. At  one  time  Caroline  linger  seemed  about  to  supplant  Sophie.  Her 
success  was,  at  first,  due  to  her  motherly  kindness  to  him,  and  her  effort 
to  make  him  happy.  But  later,  she  began  to  ask  favors  herself  instead  of 
giving  them;  and  this  was  so  different  from  his  mother's  attitude  that  he 
soon  cast  her  off.  But  the  subtle  influence  of  Sophie  in'  portraying  her 
lack  of  virtue  and  in  pleading  with  him  also  had  its  effect.  Here  again  his 
despondency  upon  finding  that  Caroline  was  unworthy  seems  to  have  made 
an  impression  somewhat  akin  to  his  Bertha  experience,  and  it  may  be 
explained  in  the  same  way. 

His  later  life  was  filled  with  various  premonitions  of  the  final  catastrophe 
which  culminated,  in  1844,  in  insanity  due  to  a  syphilitic  infection  which 
he  had  acquired  some  twelve  years  before.  It  is  very  likely  that  Sophie's 
love  and  attention  tended  to  cheer  and  sustain  the  poet  in  his  last  years  of 
affliction  before  the  final  breakdown. 

10.     FbrEnczi,  S.     Introjektion  und  Uebertragung.     Jahrbuch  fur  Psycho- 
analytische   und  psychopathologische  Forschungen,  19 10.     Band.  I. 
pp.  1-38. 
This  article  is  composed  of  two  parts. 


434  ACHER 

I.  Die  Introjektion  in  der  Neurose,  and  2.  Die  Rolle  der  Uebertragung 
bei  der  Hypnose  und  Suggestion. 

The  most  prominent  feature  in  the  psychoanalytical  treatment  of  hysteria 
is  the  process  known  as  transference  {Uebertragung)  of  emotional  activity 
from  some  person  previously  known  by  the  patient,  to  the  physician. 
However,  this  transference,  or  tendency  to  transference  of  emotion,  is 
not  alone  characteristic  of  the  ^psychoanalytic  treatment,  but  is  mani- 
fest at  all  times,  and  seems  to  be  a  fundamental  attribute  of  this  form  of 
the  psychic  mechanism.  The  apparently  unmotived  but  extreme  expres- 
sion of  love,  hate,  or  sympathy  of  neurotics  is  the  transference  of  feeling 
from  some  long-forgotten  psychic  experience  to  the  person  under  consider- 
ation. In  these  cases,  the  unconscious  complexes  which  are  strongly  toned 
with  feeling  over-emphasize  the  emotion  manifested  towards  the  per- 
son, by  being  brought  into  some  kind  of  association  with  the  idea  of  him. 
This  extreme  manifestation  of  emotion  has  long  been  noticed  in  hysteri- 
cals ;  but  it  was  regarded  as  a  simulation  of  feeling,  because  there  could  be 
discovered  no  adequate  motive  for  the  feeling.  The  feeling  is,  however, 
genuine,  and  receives  its  motivation  from  the  unconscious  complexes  which 
remain  in  the  background,  but  use  this  means  of  expressing  the  accumu- 
lated emotion  that  has  been  waiting  for  an  outlet.  The  discovery  of  this 
mechanism  is  due  to  the  investigations  of  Freud.  The  tendency  of  psycho- 
neurotics to  simulate,  and  the  so-called  "psychic  infection"  among  hys- 
tericals  are  not  simple  automatisms,  but  find  their  explanation  in  the 
unconscious  wishes  and  desires  of  the  patients.  Frequently,  a  patient 
assumes  the  symptoms  of  another  person,  because  he  identifies  himself  with 
that  person,  for  one  reason  or  another.  Intense  sympathy  springs  from 
this  same  source.  The  impulsive  acts  of  generosity  and  charity  are,  also, 
reactions  to  these  unconscious  demands  and  may,  in  the  last  analysis,  prove 
to  be  egotistical. 

The  fact  that  movements  of  reform  or  movements  of  a  humanita- 
rian nature  often  secure  recruits,  in  large  measure,  from  neuropaths  is 
due  to  the  transfer  of  interests  from  egotistic,  self-condemned  tendencies 
of  the  unconscious,  to  subjects  in  which  these  interests  can  find  expression 
without  repression  and  criticism  or  condemnation.  The  tendency  of 
hystericals  to  eat  indigestible  foods,  their  desire  to  eat  at  a  strange  table, 
or  to  eat  food  of  a  peculiar  form  or  consistency  all  point  to  a  transfer  of 
interest  from  repressed,  erotic  tendencies,  and  reveal  a  state  of  unsatisfied 
sexual  impulses. 

The  business  of  the  psychoanalyst  is  to  provide  a  means  by  which  the 
emotion  attached  to  a  repressed  complex  may  find  expression,  by  being 
transferred  to  some  other  object;  and  the  physician  usually  becomes  this 
object.  But  this  is  only  a  temporary  make-shift,  and  the  real  cure  is 
brought  about  by  leading  the  patient  to  resurrect  in  consciousness  the 
source  of  his  emotions  in  the  repressed  unconscious  complexes. 

The  reason  why  the  physician  is  so  often  the  object  toward  which  the 
transference  is  made  is  that  the  CEdipus  complex  is  almost  invariably 
present  in  the  patient ;  and  the  physician's  fatherly  care  easily  leads  to  the 
same  attitude  towards  him  that  was  manifested  toward  the  parent  in  child- 
hood. Sometimes,  a  trivial  factor  may  bring  about  the  transference,  such 
as  the  color  of  the  hair,  the  facial  expression,  a  gesture,  the  manner  of  hold- 
ing the  cigarette  or  the  pen,  the  identity  of  name  with  that  of  a  friend  of 
the  patient,  etc.  The  sex  of  the  physician  is,  of  course,  important.  In 
the  case  of  female  patients,  this  frequently  suffices  to  attach  this  feeling 
to  a  male  physician.  But  the  homosexual  component,  that  Hes  hidden  in 
every  male,  may  lead  male  patients  to  make  the  transference. 

This  transfer  of  emotion  from  one  object  to  another  is  a  fundamental 
characteristic  of  neuroticism;  it  explains  conversion  and  substitution 
as  symptoms  of  hysteria.  All  neurotics  suffer  as  a  result  of  withdrawing 
the  libido  from  certain,  previously  pleasur ably- toned  complexes  of  ideas. 


RSCSNT   FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  435 

If  the  withdrawal  is  not  complete,  the  interest  in  that  which  was  previously- 
loved  or  hated  is  lessened.  If  it  is  more  complete,  the  complex  is  wholly- 
repressed  and  forgotten  for  consciousness.  But  it  appears  that  the  psychic 
mechanism  cannot  endure  the  libido  separated  from  its  complex;  it  is, 
therefore,  transformed  into  anxiety.  Psycho-neurotics  have  a  similar 
tendency  to  withdraw  the  psychic  libido  from  certain  complexes;  and  this 
gives  rise  to  a  form  of  enduring  unrest  which  the  patient  seeks  to  mitigate. 
It  may  succeed,  partially,  in  conversion, — which  leads  to  hysteria, — 
and  in  substitution, — which  leads  to  anxiety  neuroses.  But  this  never 
succeeds  completely;  and  there  always  appears  to  be  a  portion  of  the  im- 
pulse which  seems  to  seek  satisfaction  in  the  external  world.  This  accounts 
for  the  neurotic's  tendency  to  transfer  emotion  from  one  object  to  another. 

A  comparison  of  neurotics  with  those  who  suffer  from  dementia  praecox 
and  paranoia  will  throw  light  upon  the  former.  In  dementia  praecox  the 
patient  loses  his  interest  in  the  external  and  becomes  autoerotic.  The 
paranoiac  projects  all  interests,  which  have  become  painful,  into  the  ex- 
ternal world.  The  psychoneurotic  acts  in  a  manner  which  is  diametrically 
opposite  to  paranoia.  He  takes  up  a  great  part  of  the  external  world 
into  the  self,  and  uses  it  as  a  basis  for  unconscious  fancy.  It  is  a  sort  of 
attenuation  process  by  which  the  free,  unsatisfied  and  not  to  be  satisfied 
unconscious  wish  stimuli  are  weakened.  This  process  is  called  introjec- 
tion  as  opposed  to  projection.  The  neurotic  is  constantly  in  search  of 
objects,  with  which  he  can  identify  himself  and  to  which  he  can  transfer 
feelings,  and  which  he  introjects,  or  draws  into  the  circle  of  his  interests. 
The  illness  is  due  to  an  enlargement  of  the  self.  Both  projection  and  in- 
trojection  are  extreme  forms  of  psychic  processes  which  are  present  in  normal 
life.  In  the  child,  everything  is  projected  into  the  external  world,  and 
in  paranoia  the  same  thing  is  true,  in  an  effort  to  minimize  the  self.  The 
first  love  and  hate  are  a  transference  of  autoerotic  pleasure  and  displeasure 
to  the  object  that  arouses  these  feelings.  Freud  even  goes  so  far  as  to  say 
that  man's  philosophy  and  religious  metaphysics  are  only  a  projection  of 
his  feeling  stimuli  into  the  outer  world. 

But  introjection  plays  an  equally  great  role.  This  is  indicated  by  the 
fact  that  so  much  of  possible  human  experience  is  reflected  in  mythology. 

The  neurotic  thus  uses  a  normal  mechanism  when  he  attaches  his  feel- 
ing to  all  possible  objects  which  are  not  directly  related  to  him,  in  order 
to  be  able  to  leave  in  the  unconscious  the  attachment  to  objects  that  are 
closely  related  to  him. 

The  difference  between  the  normal  and  the  abnormal  is  one  of  quantity. 
The  normal  person  transfers  his  affection  upon  much  better  grounds,  and 
does  not  dissipate  his  mental  energy  in  such  useless  ways  as  the  neurotic. 
In  the  normal  person  the  introjection  is  a  much  more  conscious  process, 
while  with  the  neurotic  it  is  largely  a  matter  of  unconscious  activity. 

This  transference  of  affects  from  the  patient  to  the  physician  is  at  the 
basis  of  all  cures  brought  about  by  electro-,  mechano-,  hydro-therapy 
and  massage;  as  well  as  all  other  cures  wrought  by  suggestion  and  hyp- 
notism. 

The  second  part  of  this  article  applies  the  principle  of  transference  to 
suggestion  and  hypnosis.  The  explanation  of  these  phenomena,  which 
assumes  that  the  implanting  of  the  idea  of  sleep  by  the  hypnotist  leads  to 
dissociation,  and  that  ideas  presented  to  the  subject  will  then  easily  have 
the  right  of  way  over  others,  does  not  seem  satisfactory.  There  are  cer- 
tainly deeper  psychic  forces  at  work,  of  which,  as  yet,  no  full  account  has 
been  taken.  Evidence  is  accumulating  daily,  which  points  to  the  fact  that 
the  main  work  in  hypnosis  and  suggestion  is  done  not  by  the  hypnotist 
but  by  the  subject  himself.  The  existence  of  auto-suggestion  and  auto- 
hypnosis,  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  work  of  the  so-called  "mediums,"  on 
the  other,  argue  that  the  function  of  the  hypnotist  is  a  subordinate  one. 
Psychoanalysis  has  shown  that  even  in  normal  persons  in  the  waking  state. 


436  ACHER 

the  conditions  for  dissociation  are  always  highly  favorable.  It  has  also 
shown,  that  in  the  course  of  the  development  of  the  civilized  individual, 
many  impulses  are  repressed,  and  that  these  repressed  impulses,  with 
their  accompanying  unsatisfied  affects,  are  always  ready  to  transfer  them- 
selves to  persons  and  objects  in  the  external  world,  and  to  bring  the  latter 
unconsciously  into  touch  with  the  self  or  to  introject  them.  In  hypnotism 
and  in  suggestion,  the  role  of  the  hypnotist  reduces  itself  to  an  object  to 
which  the  unconscious  transfers  affects  for  its  own  relief. 

The  significant  part  which  the  parental  complex  plays  in  the  life  of 
each  individual  is  the  basis  for  this  transference  of  emotion  in  hypnotism 
and  in  suggestion.  The  same  complexes  are  brought  into  play  in  the  nor- 
mal individual  that  are  active  in  psychoneuroses.  The  hypnotist  may  turn 
toward  himself  certain  complexes  in  the  subject's  unconscious  mental  life, 
that  are  toned  with  fear,  hate,  anxiety,  etc.,  because  something  about  him 
leads  the  subject  to  identify  him  with  some  person  who  has  previously 
aroused  these  same  feelings.  This  usually  goes  back  to  childhood  ex- 
periences, that  were  repressed  in  later  life. 

It  has  been  found  that  sympathy  and  respect  greatly  enhance  the  possi- 
bility of  suggestion  and  hypnotism.  There  is  much  evidence  for  believ- 
ing that  the  unconscious  affects  play  the  principal  role  in  both  suggestion 
and  hypnotism ;  and  that  these  are,  in  the  last  analysis,  feelings  connected 
with  the  sexual  impulse,  which  are  transferred  from  the  child-parent  com- 
plex to  the  hypnotist-subject  complex  Everything  points  to  the  fact  that, 
at  the  basis  of  every  feeling  of  sympathy,  there  is  an  unconscious  sexual 
element;  and  when  two  persons  meet,  the  unconscious  factors  attempt 
to  make  the  transference.  If  the  transference  is  successful,  be  it  a  purely 
erotic  feeling,  or  a  sublimated  one  of  respect,  esteem,  friendship,  etc.,  there 
springs  up  the  feeling  of  sympathy  between  the  two.  If  there  is  objection 
to  this  transference  on  the  part  of  the  fore-conscious,  other  feelings  spring 
up  which  may  lead  to  antipathy,  disgust,  etc.  The  question  as  to  whether 
any  person  can  be  hypnotized  depends  for  its  answer  upon  whether  there 
is  a  possibility  of  transference  of  the  unconscious  sexual  attitude  of  the 
subject  to  the  hypnotist.  This,  in  turn,  is  determined  by  the  parent-com- 
plex. The  great  variation  in  the  proportion  of  hypnotizable  persons,  as 
reported  by  various  authorities,  finds  its  explanation  here.  Some  succeed 
in  only  about  fifty  per  cent,  of  their  cases,  others  reach  as  high  as  ninety- 
six  per  cent.  An  imposing-looking  hypnotist  is  much  more  successful  than 
one  of  a  different  type.  Long,  black  beard,  great  stature,  heavy  eye- 
brows, penetrating  eyes,  forceful  but  trust-awakening  countenance,  self 
confidence,  good  standing  in  the  community, — all  help.  Commands  given 
with  force  and  clearness,  so  that  opposition  seems  impossible,  are  helpful. 
Sometimes  a  surprise,  a  sudden  and  loud  call,  a  bright  object,  a  tense  and 
rigid  expression  of  face,  clenched  fists,  succeed  when  other  means  fail. 

An  entirely  different  method  may  be  used.  This  requires  a  darkened 
room,  absolute  quietness,  friendly  talking  in  a  monotone,  a  mild  melodious 
voice,  gentle  stroking  of  the  hair  and  forehead,  etc. 

These  two  methods  might  be  considered  as  making  use  of  anxiety  and 
fear,  on  the  one  hand,  and  of  love,  on  the  other.  Experts  adopt  one  or  the 
other  of  these  methods,  as  the  case  requires.  The  one  method  involves 
the  attitude  of  the  father  toward  his  children;  and  the  other  that  of  the 
mother.  In  each  case  the  unconscious  complexes  which  were  established 
in  infancy  are  appealed  to.  These  complexes  were  usually  fixed  by  the 
parents,  in  trying  to  induce  sleep  in  the  children.  Even  holding  before  the 
eyes  a  bright  object,  or  placing  a  ticking  watch  to  the  ear,  both  of  which 
methods  are,  at  times,  employed  to  induce  hypnosis,  are  excellent  means 
of  arousing  childhood  memories.  This  child-attitude,  on  the  part  of  adults, 
is  not  so  foreign  to  maturity  as  might  appear,  because  this  attitude  plays 
a  prominent  part  in  our  dreams. 


RKC^NT   FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  437 

Forgetting,  in  the  sense  of  complete  disappearance  of  all  traces  of  a  for- 
mer experience,  is  as  foreign  to  the  facts,  as  the  annihilation  of  energy  or 
matter  is  in  the  physical  world.  Psychic  processes  may  be  revived  after 
decades  of  oblivescence. 

The  unconscious,  childhood  memories  tend  to  make  the  adult  submis- 
sive to  those  persons  who  resemble,  in  any  way,  his  parents.  There  is  rea- 
son to  believe  that  the  hypnotic  credulity  and  docility  has  its  roots  in  the 
masochistic  compounds  of  the  sexual  impulse.  Masochism  is  pleasurable 
obedience  which  the  child  learns  from  its  parents.  The  parental  influence 
often  acts  almost  like  a  past  hypnotic  suggestion  upon  the  later  life  of  the 
child.  Both  hypnotism  and  suggestion  are  due  to  the  transference  of  the 
repressed  elements  of  the  sexual  impiilse  from  the  subject  to  the  hypnotist. 
This  is  due  to  the  child-parent  complex  which  becomes  active  between 
the  subject  and  the  hypnotist. 

II.     Jones,  E.     The  Action  of  Suggestion  in  Psychotherapy.     Journal  of 
Abnormal  Psychology,  Dec,  1910,  Jan.,  1911.    pp.  217-254. 

This  discussion  is  based  upon  the  conception  of  suggestion  and  hypno- 
tism, as  worked  out  by  Ferenczi  in  " Introjektion  und  Uebertragung,"  and 
since  the  main  facts  of  this  paper  are  summarized  above  it  will  not  be 
necessary  to  restate  them  here.  Dr.  Jones  agrees  fully  with  Ferenczi  in 
giving  emotion  a  prominent  place  in  making  suggestion  possible.  This 
is  in  harmony  with  the  views  of  Bleuler  and  Lipps.  "The  peculiar  rap- 
port between  the  operator  and  the  subject,  so  characteristic  of  the  hyp- 
notic state,  is  identical  with  that  obtaining  between  physician  and  patient 
in  the  spontaneous  somnambulism  of  hysteria. "  The  basis  of  this  rapport 
is  sexual  attraction.  In  the  majority  of  cases,  it  is  unconscious,  but  not 
in  every  case.  This  was  foreshadowed  long  ago  in  the  theories  which 
postulated  a  magnetic  fluid,  vital  fluid,  nervous  fluid  or  an  all-prevading 
ether,  and  lastly  a  special  psychical  influence  of  the  hypnotist.  This 
was  supposed  to  be  emitted  from  the  eye,  because  the  eye  has  been  sym- 
bolical of  the  male  organ  and  its  function. 

Janet  is  quoted  to  show  that  hypnosis  induces  the  following  changes  in 
the  subject:  any  fear  of,  or  repugnance  toward,  hypnosis  is  replaced  by  a 
passionate  desire  for  its  repetition,  and  the  patient  is  excessively  preoccu- 
pied with  the  physician.  At  times  a  period  of  somnambulic  passion  lasts 
until  the  next  seance.  Janet  further  writes:  "What  one  most  frequently 
observes  is  a  feeling  of  affection,  which  may  become  extremely  intense. 
The  subject  feels  happy,  when  he  sees  his  hypnotizer,  when  he  speaks  to 
him;  he  experiences  pleasure  when  he  thinks  of  him;  and  consequently 
soon  comes  to  the  point  of  feeling  a  strong  love  for  him."  Hystericals  are 
very  jealous  of  the  physician's  attention  and  interest  in  them. 

Dr.  Jones  believes  that  this  attitude  of  '  'warm  affection,  dread,  jealousy, 
veneration,  exactingness "  toward  the  physician  is  derived  from  the  psy- 
chosexual  group  of  activities.  Janet  rejects  this  interpretation;  but  Jones 
is  convinced  that  Janet  has  not  traced  these  conscious  emotions  to  their 
source;  if  he  has  done  so,  he  could  not  fail  to  recognize  their  nature. 

The  relation  of  suggestion  to  psychoanalysis  must  first  be  pointed  out, 
before  an  evaluation  of  each  of  these  methods  of  treating  psychoneuroses 
can  be  made.  In  both  methods,  there  is  a  transference  of  psychosexual 
affections  from  the  patient  to  the  physician ;  but,  where  suggestion  alone 
is  employed,  the  treatment  stops  here,  while,  in  psychoanalysis,  the  pa- 
tient is  helped  to  trace  his  illness  to  its  source;  and  liien  "the  wishes,  desires, 
etc.,  which  had  previously  found  unsatisfactory  expression  in  the  creation 
of  various  symptoms,  are  now  free  to  be  applied,  through  the  process  of  sub- 
limation, to  non-sexual  social  aims." 

Treatment,  by  means  of  suggestion  alone,  really  intensifies  the  trans- 
erence.  The  result  of  this  is  that  the  patient  never  really  is  cured  nor 
Journal — 8 


438  ACH^R 

becomes  independent  of  the  physician.  If  one  sympton  is  removed,  another 
takes  its  place;  and  chronic  invahdism  often  results.  Psychoanalysis 
brings  permanent  relief  wherever  transference  can  first  be  brought  about 
by  helping  the  patient  to  sublimate  the  psychosexual  emotions  to  higher 
ends. 

12.  Brill,  A.  A.  A  Contribution  to  the  Psychopathology  of  Everyday  Life. 
Psychotherapy,  Vol.  Ill,  No.  i.  pp.  5-20. 

Dr.  Brill  is  a  disciple  of  Freud,  and  employs  the  terms  unconscious,  repres- 
sion, and  complex,  in  the  Freudian  sense.  He  conceives  all  hysterical  symp- 
toms to  be  the  expression  of  a  repressed  wish,  which  is  active  in  the  uncon- 
scious. Unconscious  processes  are  defined  as  those  processes  which  show 
active  manifestations,  but  of  which  the  person  concerned  is  not  conscious 
because  of  repression,  due  to  conflicting  impulses.  This  psychic  mechanism 
in  hysteria,  Dr.  Brill  conceives  to  be  common,  in  a  mild  form,  to  all  nor- 
mal minds.  This  is  manifested  in  dreams,  and  in  everyday  actions.  The 
tendency  to  forget,  or  crowd  out  of  consciousness  all  thoughts  of  a  disa- 
greeable or  painful  nature,  is  at  the  basis  of  these  everyday  manifestations. 
These  thoughts  are  not  really  forgotten;  they  are  repressed,  and  they  re- 
main in  the  unconscious  as  complexes.  Here  they  lie  dormant  until  some 
experience  or  association  taps  their  feeling  content  which  is  always  strong. 
There  is  always  a  resistance  to  their  becoming  conscious  so  that  the  indi- 
vidual is  never  able  to  tell  just  what  is  actually  taking  place. 

In  everyday  life  these  repressed  complexes  manifest  themselves  in  '  'lap- 
ses of  memory,  in  talking,  writing,  etc." 

Familiar  illustrations  of  this  are  the  forgetting  of  the  names  of  well 
known  persons,  and  the  like.  This  is  due  to  the  fact  that  the  name  is  asso- 
ciated with  some  repressed  complex,  which  prevents  recall.  Later,  when 
the  association  is  broken  the  name  may  come  freely. 

A  woman  refers  to  one  of  her  married  friends,  but  by  mistake  uses  her 
maiden  name  instead  of  her  husband's  name.  Psychoanalysis  shows  that 
she  does  n't  like  her  friend's  husband,  and  wishes  her  friend  had  never 
married  him.  In  using  her  friend's  maiden  name,  she  fulfilled  a  wish  and 
revealed  that  the  husband's  name  was  repressed.  She  was,  of  course,  un- 
conscious of  the  motive  for  this. 

A  man  is  urged  by  his  wife  to  attend  a  social  function,  which  he  does  not 
care  for  but  agrees  to  attend.  In  dressing  for  the  occasion  he  suddenly 
finds  the  trunk  containing  his  dress  suit  locked  and  the  key  lost.  This 
compels  the  sending  of  regrets.  Next  day  the  key  is  found  in  the  trunk. 
The  husband  declares  he  did  not  conceal  the  key  intentionally.  But  the 
motive  is  clear;  it  carried  itself  out  when  he  was  off  his  guard. 

Many  so-called  meaningless,  or  automatic,  indifferent  or  accidental 
actions  such  as  '  'scribbling  with  one's  lead  pencil,  jingling  the  coins  in  one's 
pocket,  kneading  soft  substances,  etc.,  conceal  sense  and  meaning  for 
which  any  other  outlet  is  closed." 

A  maiden  lady  wears  a  wedding  ring  "because  it  was  grandmother's." 
A  patient,  who  despairs  of  life,  manifests  special  interest  in  Ibsen's  '  'When 
the  Dead  Awaken."  An  embezzler  is  discovered  in  a  distant  city  read- 
ing the  book,  "Will  I  ever  go  back?" 

Dr.  Brill  gives  a  wealth  of  illustrations  to  show  that  so-called  meaning- 
less actions  are  symbolical  of  a  deeper  meaning,  and  adds :  '  'These  examples 
show  that  there  is  nothing  arbitrary  or  fortuitous  in  our  actions,  that,  no 
matter  how  we  may  try  to  conceal  things,  we  always  betray  ourselves. 
Our  repressed  thoughts  forever  strive  to  come  to  the  surface;  and  just  as 
the  insane  realize  their  ideals  in  their  insanities,  we  realize  our  wishes 
through  our  dreams,  and  in  the  'little  ways'  of  everyday  life." 

If  Dr.  Brill's  contention  is  true  that  the  determining  motives  to  conduct 
are  often,  if  not  usually,  below  the  threshold  of  consciousness,  it  has  the 
very  greatest  significance  for  the  student  of  normal  psychology.     In  fact. 


RECENT  FREUDIAN  UTERATURE  439 

it  almost  becomes  revolutionary,  and  challenges  the  truthfulness  of  all  so- 
called  introspection.  If  one  cannot  tell  what  motives  lead  to  this  or  that 
choice,  action  or  even  association,  much  of  what  has  been  accepted  as 
orthodox  psychology  must  be  radically  revised.  The  validity  of  all  ex- 
perimental laboratory  psychology  that  is  based  on  introspection  is  thus 
brought  into  question.  It  also  plays  havoc  with  the  contention  that  con- 
sciousness is  the  only  legitimate  field  for  the  student  of  psychology.  Dr. 
Brill  is,  of  course,  not  alone  in  his  point  of  view.  Evidence  in  support  of 
this  view  is  being  accumulated  daily  by  the  whole  Freudian  school. 

The  genetic  psychologist,  too,  is  taking  this  stand  for  reasons  other  than 
those  of  the  Freudian  school.  From  an  evolutional  view-point,  it  is  fully 
justified.  In  fact,  it  forces  itself  upon  any  one  who  attempts  to  follow 
up  the  evolutioti  of  psychic  life  from  primitive  forms  of  life,  as  leading 
geneticists  are  pointing  out. 

13.  Putnam,  J.  J.  Personal  Impressions  of  Sigmund  Freud  and  his  Work, 
with  Special  Reference  to  his  Recent  Lectures  at  Clark  University. 
Journal  of  Abnormal  Psychology,  Dec,  1909,  March,  1910.     pp.  1-26, 

Dr.  Putnam  laments  the  fact  that  the  Freudian  theories  have  been  so 
long  neglected,  and  considers  it  to  be  '  'a  reflection  on  our  energy  and  in- 
telligence that  we  have  not  gained  a  closer  knowledge  of  the  claims  and 
merits  of  his  doctrines."  He  also  points  out  the  peculiar  prejudices  and 
misconceptions  that  are  current  concerning  Freud's  point  of  view,  and 
thinks  that  a  better  acquaintance  with  his  work  would  remove  much  of 
this  unfavorable  attitude.  The  emphasis  which  he  places  on  "sexual 
life  in  the  etiology  of  psycho-neuroses"  is  largely  responsible  for  this 
prejudice. 

This  is  itself  in  need  of  psychoanalysis.  It  supports  Freud's  conten- 
tion that  the  motives  which  actuate  conduct  are  usually  below  the  level  of 
consciousness:  and  that  the  individual  never  gives  the  real  reason  for  his 
behavior  or  attitude  of  mind.  "Motives  are  made  up  of  'attraction,'  'de- 
sire' and  'acceptance,'  on  the  one  hand,  and,  on  the  other  hand,  of  'repulsion,' 
'repression,'  'denial,'  mixed  in  equal  parts."  The  very  intensity  of  the 
opposition  to  Freud's  theory  indicates  that  it  touches  a  tender  spot,  for 
the  opposition  springs  up  even  before  the  theory  is  tested. 

A  strong  prejudice  often  involves  the  "half-felt  but  perhaps  wholly 
suppressed  truth"  of  the  matter  under  consideration,  which  cannot,  at 
present,  be  put  to  the  test  of  reason. 

Dr.  Putnam's  aim  is  to  modify  this  prejudice,  which  he  himself  once 
shared,  by  setting  forth  some  of  these  Freudian  principles  in  a  manner  best 
calculated  to  remove  misconceptions  and  invite  unbiased  consideration. 
As  far  back  as  1881,  Freud  and  Breuer  treated  their  first  case  of  hysteria, 
and  revealed  the  germs  of  Freud's  later  theories.  After  a  number  of  years 
of  study  with  Charcot  in  Paris,  and  with  other  psychiatrists,  he  continued 
his  treatment  of  cases  of  hysteria;  and  in  all  of  these,  he  became  convinced 
that  the  childhood  experiences  played  a  very  great  r61e  in  producing  the 
later  difficulties.  The  system  of  psycho-analysis  was  evolved;  and  it 
was  found  that  the  emotions  of  childhood  often  cropped  out  in  new  forms, 
in  later  life.  Old  and  forgotten  memories  were  revived;  and  it  was  dis- 
covered that  these  were  at  the  basis  of  the  illness,  and  that  when  brought 
up  to  the  level  of  consciousness  the  patient  recovered.  This  necessarily 
gave  rise  to  a  new  and  larger  view  of  the  unconscious  life  than  had  hereto- 
fore been  held.  The  unconscious  proved  to  be  the  "dwelling-place  and 
working  place  of  emotions  that  we  could  not  utilize  in  the  personality 
that  we  had  shaped  and  rounded." 

Dr.  Putnam  thinks  that  '  'looked  at  broadly  and  as  a  whole' '  Freud's 
main  contribution  has  been  this  emphasis  of  the  unconscious  phase  of  life 
as  an  active  principle  rather  than  the  attempt  to  push  forward  the  sexual 


440  ACH^R 

element  in  our  experience.  This  latter  factor  is  stressed  by  Freud,  but 
he  is  fully  justified  in  his  conclusions  by  the  evidence  bearing  upon  this 
point  which  he  secured  from  his  patients.  His  critics  seem  to  have  lost 
sight  of  everything  else  in  their  '  'attack  against  the  remarkable  and  truth- 
seeking  observations  of  a  remarkable  man. "  A  plea  is  made  for  open- 
mindedness  in  considering  this  phase  of  Freud's  theory,  on  the  ground 
that  it  is  the  first  duty  of  any  seeker  after  truth  to  hold  his  prejudices  in 
abeyance  and  examine  the  facts  in  an  unbiased  manner,  even  though  the 
subject  be  disagreeable.  The  attitude  of  many  people  towards  the  sub- 
ject of  sex  is  easily  explained  on  Freud's  theory  of  repression.  This  very 
repression  leads  to  a  denial  of  its  importance.  Nevertheless  the  subject 
has  a  "hold  on  us,  or  a  right  to  demand  our  interest  and  attention,"  even 
if  "we  would  persuade  ourselves  that  this  was  not  the  case."  "This  hold 
upon  our  attention  which  we  instinctively  feel  this  subject  has  the  right 
to  claim,  even  when  we  repudiate  this  right,  constitutes  one  instance  of 
the  'desire'  which  is  made  to  play  such  a  large  part  in  Freud's  doctrines." 

The  repression  of  this  instinctive  desire  may  lead  to  one  of  three  con- 
sequences. The  repression  may  be  adequate,  and  the  instinctive  curiosity 
may  find  an  outlet  in  some  other  channel.  The  repression  may  go  too 
far,  and  produce  an  over-sensitive  individual  who  is  over-refined  and  over- 
watchful  of  himself.  Again,  the  repression  may  be  unsuccessful  and  the 
person  is  then  in  conflict  with  himself,  and  becomes  hysterical,  or  falls  a 
prey  to  one  of  the  phobias.  The  conflicting  impulses  in  a  human  being  are 
so  varied  and  complicated  that  we  are  never  able  to  grasp  them  in  their 
completeness ;  and  perhaps  every  one  could  find  in  himself  traces  of  what 
would,  in  a  larger  scale,  be  regarded  as  criminal. 

The  struggles  of  the  soul  are  immensely  more  complex  than  is  generally 
assumed.  "Desire  or  craving  furnishes  the  motive  for  many  thoughts 
and  acts  that  seem  actuated  by  sentiments  of  a  diff'erent,  and  even  of  an 
opposite,  character."     The  fable  of  the  sour  grapes  illustrates  this. 

When  desire  cannot  be  satisfied  in  one  way,  it  is  often  satisfied  in  another. 
This  substitution  of  one  situation  for  another  is  at  the  basis  of  the  principle 
of  "conversion"  in  hysteria,  by  which  the  physical  symptoms  are  pro- 
duced. This  principle  of  substitution  is  helped  by  the  tendency  to  forget 
the  unpleasant  experiences  of  life.  This  latter  is  a  feature  of  every  normal 
life,  although  in  hysteria  it  becomes  exaggerated.  It  is  due  to  repression 
which  is  an  active  factor  in  mental  life.  In  dream  life  these  repressions 
have  a  chance  to  express /themselves  in  a  somewhat  disturbed  form,  be- 
cause they,  like  psychoses,  are  in  a  measure  a  compromise  between  con- 
flicting motives. 

Freud's  therapeutic  method  is  often  criticised  on  the  ground  that  it 
brings  to  mind  what  was  unwholesome  in  the  individual's  experience  and 
that  this  should  be  forgotten.  However  the  best  answer  to  this  criticism 
is  that  the  psychoanalytic  method  of  bringing  to  consciousness  the  for- 
gotten memories  actually  brings  peace,  comfort  and  contentment  to  the 
patient  and  that  no  other  method  of  treatment  can  effect  the  same  cure. 

Freud  lays  much  more  stress  upon  early  experiences  and  environment 
in  producing  psycho-neuroses  than  upon  hereditary  and  nervous  insta- 
bility. While  heredity  varies  greatly  in  degree  of  soundness  and  vigor, 
it  is  still  the  early  experiences  "which  make  us  sick  or  well. "  His  theory, 
therefore,  tends  to  exalt  early  education  as  a  hygienic  measure  in  the 
broadest  sense  of  the  term  education. 

In  the  final  section  of  this  article  attention  is  given  to  the  subject  which 
arouses  more  antagonism  to  Freud's  theory  than  anything  else:  namely 
his  emphasis  of  sex  as  a  causative  factor  in  psycho-neuroses.  However, 
the  fact  that  the  unfavorable  criticism  is  of  the  most  contradictory  sort 
indicates  that  the  critics  have  been  moved  by  deep  seated  prejudice  rather 
than  by  cool  consideration  of  the  merits  of  his  theory.  In  spite  of  the  fact 
'  'that  this  immense  subject  was  daily  and  hourly  thrusting  itself  upon  our 


RECENT   FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  441 

notice  whether  as  the  cause  of  terrible  suffering,  of  terrible  crimes,  of  terri- 
ble misunderstandings  and  misjudgments,  and  that  it  has  played  a  huge 
part  in  the  history  of  religion  and  of  civic  progress, "  there  has  been  a  ten- 
dency to  blind  ourselves  to  the  facts  and  to  refuse  to  study  the  subject 
scientifically. 

One  reason  for  this  is  that  the  term  sexual  is  confused  with  the  term 
sensual.  Hence  to  assume  that  sexual  influence  is  basic  for  psychopathol- 
ogy  would  be  to  charge  every  one  so  afflicted  with  immoral  characteristics 
according  to  this  false  view.  Freud  uses  the  term  in  a  much  more  com- 
prehensive sense  and  includes  all  emotions  that  have  differentiated  from 
the  primitive  sex  impulse.  This  includes  all  that  has  produced  the  high- 
est and  noblest  in  civilization.  The  experiences  of  infancy  are  causative 
factors  of  later  neuropathic  states  but  cannot  be  considered  sensual.  All 
students  of  the  subject  now  agree  that  the  term  sex  is  much  more  compre- 
hensive than  has  been  customary  to  regard  it  and  that  the  distinction  be- 
tween normal  and  abnormal  is  not  to  be  too  sharply  drawn.  Freud  assumes 
that  civilization  has  been  built  up  at  the  expense  of  sex  interests  and  that 
the  sublimation  and  repression  of  the  sexual  energy  is  the  means  of  attain- 
ing a  higher  culture.  It  is  in  an  effort  to  accomplish  this  end  that  repres- 
sion sometimes  goes  too  far  in  those  persons  who  have  a  predisposition 
to  neuropathic  states.  Since  much  of  this  conflict  takes  place  in  the  un- 
conscious, and  the  symptoms  of  over  repression  are  never  traceable  to 
their  source  by  the  patient,  unaided,  there  is  after  all  no  question  of  moral 
responsibility.  It  is  an  unsuccessful  struggle  with  factors  that  are  clearly 
beyond  the  reach  of  consciousness.  The  infantile  experiences  in  the  sex 
realm  may  easily  sow  the  seed  of  later  troubles  because  the  child  gives 
free  and  full  expression  to  all  impulses.  In  later  life  these  impulses  are 
found  to  be  out  of  harmony  with  civilized  life  and  are  repressed  only  to 
retreat  to  the  unconscious  realm  where  they  are  still  active.  The  adjust- 
ment of  the  legitimate  demands  of  the  procreative  instinct  on  the  one  hand 
and  the  demands  of  civilization  for  repression  and  sublimation  on  the 
other  is  the  great  problem  of  modern  life.  Tt  is  just  here  that  the  Freudian 
investigations  are  most  helpful,  and  Dr.  Putnam  believes  that  Freud  and 
his  co-laborers  have  a  distinct  message  for  the  present  age  in  dealing  with 
this  important  and  ever  present  problem. 

Abraham  Karl.  Giovanni  Segantini,  ein  psychoanalytischer  Versuch.  Schrif- 
ten  zur  angewandten  Seelenkunde,  Elf tes  Heft.     Leipzig,  191 1.     p.  65. 

This  is  another  contribution  to  the  psychology  of  the  artist.  Giovanni 
Segantini  was  a  famous  Italian  painter  of  the  last  half  of  the  ninteenth 
century.  His  development,  his  outer  and  inner  life,  his  artistic  capacity 
and  his  works  were  all  unique,  and  challenge  an  explanation  from  the  point 
of  view  of  individual  psychology.  This  study  applies  the  principles  of 
psychoanalysis  to  the  life  and  works  of  Segantini.  The  unconscious  mech- 
anism of  neurotics  and  artists  is  similar  in  many  respects  and  the  phy- 
sician who  is  acquainted  with  the  method  of  psychoanalysis  of  the  former 
has  a  peculiar  advantage  therefore  in  the  study  of  the  latter. 

Segantini 's  paintings  are  in  a  peculiar  sense  the  expression  of  his  inner 
soul  experiences.  His  theory  of  painting  was  that  it  should  reveal  and 
express  the  deepest  emotions  of  the  artist  rather  than  attempt  a  true  re- 
production of  any  external  object  or  scene.  Art,  he  says,  shall  glorify 
work,  love,  mother,  and  death.  These  were  the  sources  from  which  he 
derived  his  inspiration.  Although  other  artists  have  dwelt  on  these  themes, 
Segantini  has  given  them  a  touch  peculiar  to  himself  and  his  genius  is 
limited  to  these  subjects. 

His  lack  of  early  education  and  his  unwholesome  environment  did  little 
to  exalt  these  themes.  They  therefore  came  largely  from  his  own  inner 
tendencies.  Psychoanalysis  can  throw  much  light  upon  the  source  of  these 
themes  because  it  goes  back  to  childhood  and  traces  the  beginnings  of  the 
life  impulses.     Segantini  himself  thought  that  a  true  explanation  of  his 


442  ACH^R 

genius  would  have  to  go  back  to  his  earliest  childhood  and  analyze  all 
sensations  of  the  soul,  even  to  their  faintest  beginnings.  His  mind  was 
free  from  the  burden  of  traditional  schooling  and  absorbed  from  his  environ- 
ment whatever  it  was  fitted  to  assimilate. 

The  most  profound  single  event  of  Segantini's  early  life  was  the  death 
of  his  mother,  when  he  Was  scarcely  five  years  old.  After  that  he  lost  the 
influence  of  a  home,  was  neglected  by  his  father,  and  became  more  or  less 
of  a  wanderer.  During  all  this  time  the  early  influence  of  his  mother 
made  her  the  centre  of  his  thought.  In  his  autobiography  he  says  that  he 
has  a  clear  definite  and  accurate  image  of  her.  He  says  she  was  young,  tall, 
and  beautiful  and  compares  her  to  sunset  in  the  spring.  This  lofty  senti- 
ment of  love  is  the  sublimated,  infantile,  erotic  attitude  toward  her.  The 
neurotic  and  the  artist  both  have  abnormally  strong  impulses  which  are 
greatly  transformed  through  repression  and  sublimation.  Both  have  a  very 
strong  fancy.  In  the  case  of  the  neurotic  the  repressed  fancies  are  converted 
into  symptoms  of  illness.  In  the  artist  they  find  partial  expression  in  his 
works.  The  other  part  is  usually  sublimated  into  some  other  form  of 
expression.  In  Segantini  this  last  element  was  transformed  into  a  com- 
pensatory over-emphasis  of  and  admiration  for  motherhood.  This  is 
why  Segantini  embodied  motherhood  as  the  central  theme  of  so  many  of 
his  paintings.  The  painting  called  "The  Fruit  of  Love,"  was  evolved  in 
his  fancy  by  the  transformation  of  a  beautiful  rose  that  came  from  heaven 
into  the  form  of  a  mother  and  child.  Here  the  influence  of  his  long  de- 
parted mother  is  seen.     He  often  associated  her  beauty  with  that  of  a  rose. 

The  infantile  erotic  attitude  towards  the  mother  often  gives  rise  to 
feelings  of  cruelty  against  the  loved  one.  This  is  due  to  a  sort  of  feeling 
of  revenge  for  supposed  mistreatment.  This  manifests  itself  in  desiring 
the  death  of  the  loved  one;  or  if  death  actually  takes  place  in  a  sort  of  joy 
that  it  occurred.  Later  when  this  feeling  of  cruelty  is  repressed  and  subli- 
mated there  arises  in  the  mind  of  the  neurotic  a  feeling  of  guilt  even  though 
no  good  reason  can  be  given  for  it.  The  dead  one  is  glorified  and  an  effort 
is  made  to  call  him  or  her  back  to  life  in  fancy. 

That  Segantini  had  this  feeling  of  cruelty  in  childhood  is  shown  by  the 
fact  that  when  twelve  j'^ears  of  age  he  derived  real  pleasure  in  trying  to 
paint  the  face  of  a  dead  child  at  its  mother's  request  and  worked  for  hours 
at  his  task.  In  his  later  description  of  this  mother,  he  spoke  of  her  beauty 
and  used  the  same  adjectives  that  he  did  in  describing  his  own  mother.  It 
was  a  case  of  transference  of  his  feeling  for  his  mother  to  this  woman  and 
he  thus  undertook  the  task  through  his  mother's  unconscious  influence. 
In  his  effort  to  please  this  mother  we  see  the  beginning  of  the  sublimation 
of  the  feeling  of  cruelty  to  a  desire  to  compensate  for  this  feeling.  This 
is  a  frequent  phenomenon  in  his  later  paintings.  Thus  death  and  mother- 
hood came  to  occupy  his  attention  during  the  first  thirty  years  of  his  life, 
and  this  points  to  his  mother's  early  influence.  He  was  twenty-two  years 
old  before  he  became  sufficiently  free  from  her  influence  to  fall  in  love. 

The  influence  of  Segantini's  father  is  not  noticeable  because  of  his  father's 
treatment  of  him.  In  fact  all  traces  of  a  father's  influence  such  as  conser- 
vatism, obedience  to  authority,  reverence  for  God,  etc.,  are  negative  in  the 
character  of  Segantini.  Home,  mother,  nature  form  a  closely  knit  complex 
in  his  life.  When  he  lost  his  mother  he  lost  home  and  the  native  scenery 
that  he  loved. 

In  his  adolescent  years  the  repression  of  his  sex  impulse  had  a  tendency 
to  make  him  melancholj''  and  passive.  He  embodied  this  emotion  and 
passivity  in  the  paintings  of  this  time.  Fancies  of  death  also  inspired  many 
of  his  works  at  this  time. 

Later,  at  about  the  age  of  thirty,  this  melancholy  gave  place  to  an 
aggressive  impulse  to  labor.  He  moved  into  the  high  Alps  and  there 
studied  the  natural  scenery  as  he  had  seen  it  in  his  childhood.  Everything 
seemed  to  inspire  him  to  greater  efforts.     He  was  seized  with  an  impulse 


RECENT   FREUDIAN   LITERATURE  443 

to  work  and  seemed  never  to  tire.  The  aggressive  impulse  was  sublimated 
into  the  impulse  to  work.  Here  he  did  his  best  work.  All  this  time  the 
mother  complex  remained  the  same.  It  was  at  this  time  that  he  painted 
the  masterpiece  called  "The  Two  Mothers." 

At  this  time  he  acquired  a  techinque  of  color  analysis  to  a  high  degree 
and  used  it  very  effectively  in  his  paintings.  This  was  a  great  triimiph. 
It  was,  however,  not  so  much  a  result  of  his  artistic  genius  as  it  was  a  demand 
of  his  soul  in  order  to  give  adequate  expression  to  his  emotions.  Light  and 
color  were  to  him  the  source  of  the  highest  ecstasy.  This  was  due  to  the 
sublimation  of  that  component  of  the  sex  impulse  known  as  sex  curiosity. 

Later  there  was  again  a  return  of  melancholy.  At  this  time  he  painted 
several  works  that  are  difficult  to  explain.  One  of  these  is  "The  Bad 
Mothers."  All  products  of  the  imagination  according  to  Freud  have  a 
manifest  and  a  latent  content.  The  manifest  content  is  that  which  con- 
sciousness is  concerned  with  while  the  latent  content  escapes  its  notice 
although  it  is  the  more  significant.  The  latent  content  is  the  expression 
of  a  suppressed  impulse.  This  was  the  case  with  the  mystical  works  of 
Segantini  above  mentioned.  Only  the  manifest  content  has  received 
attention  by  students  of  his  works.  Although  he  got  his  idea  of  the  punish- 
ment of  bad  mothers  from  Buddhistic  mythology,  this  does  not  account  for 
his  interest  in  the  idea.  Here  again  the  unconscious  motive  springs  from 
the  repressed  infantile  anger  towards  his  mother  for  dividing  her  love  with 
his  rival. 

The  idea  of  death  seems  to  have  had  a  peculiar  fascination  for  him, 
motivated  many  of  his  works,  and  at  times  there  seem  to  have  been  uncon- 
scious longings  for  death,  which  in  the  end  helped  disease  hasten  disinte- 
gration. His  early  acquaintance  with  death  in  the  loss  ot  his  brother  and 
mother  does  not  fully  account  for  the  dominance  of  this  idea.  We  must 
look  deeper  for  the  motive  to  this  and  it  is  found  in  the  impulses  of  his 
childhood.  His  sadistic  impulses,  his  feeling  of  hate  and  his  desire  for 
the  death  of  a  loved  one  had  to  be  withdrawn  from  the  objects  against 
whom  they  were  directed  as  he  grew  older.  They  were  partly  transformed 
to  thoughts  of  his  own  death  and  partly  sublimated  into  an  impulse  to 
live.  This  conflict  of  conscious  and  unconscious  impulses  is  the  secret 
of  the  tragedy  which  ended  in  his  premature  death. 


TERMINOLOGY  IN  THE  FIELD  OF  SENSATION. 

There  is  at  the  present  time  a  great  deal  of  confusion  in  the  scientific 
terminology  of  sensory  processes.  In  some  cases  several  words  have  been 
manufactured  which  are  used  to  signify  the  same  thing,  and  some  of  the 
terms  are  quite  indefensible.  Acoumeter  and  audiometer  are  examples  of 
one  such  case.  In  other  cases  the  same  term  has  been  used  in  entirely 
different  meanings.  Perhaps  the  worst  examples  of  this  confusion  are 
the  terms  hemeralopsia  and  nyctalopsia,  each  of  which  is  currently  used  to 
signify  both  day-blindness  and  night-blindness.  The  unauthentic  usage 
of  these  words  possibly  results  from  an  erroneous  impression  that  the  -al- 
ls privative.     A  large  list  of  illustrations  might  be  given. 

I  suggest  the  following  list  of  terms  to  cover  a  part  of  the  field.  Practi- 
cally all  are  in  use,  with  the  exception  of  those  included  in  6,  7,  and  8.  In 
these  cases  innovation  is  absolutely  necessary,  and  the  forms  there  given 
are  analogous  to  the  forms  under  the  other  headings,  and  are  from  the 
roots  suggested  by  Professor  C.  W.  E.  Miller  as  the  most  logical.  The 
table  is  not  complete,  but  the  terms  to  cover  the  remainder  of  the  field 
should  be  constructed  in  accordance  with  the  principles  applied  here,  which 
are  drawn  from  the  best  present  usage. 

1.  Taste     geus(ia)     a-,  para-,  hypo-,  hyper-,;  -imeter,  -ic. 

2.  Smell    osm(ia)     an-,  par-,  hyp-,  hyper-;  -ometer,  -etic. 

3.  Sight     ops(ia)     an-,  par-,  hyp-,  hyper-;  -imeter,  -ic. 

4.  Hearing     acu(sia)     an-,  par-,  hyp-,  hyper-,;  -meter,  -sic. 

5.  Touch     (h)ap(hia)     an-,  par-,  hyp-,  hyper-;  -tometer,  -tic. 

6.  Warmth-sense     thalpo(sia)     a-,  para-,  hypo-,  hyper-;  -meter,   -tic. 

7.  Cold-sense     rhigo(sia)     ar-,  para-,  hypo-,  hyper-;  -meter,  -tic. 

8.  Tickle-sense    gargal-esthe(sia)     -an-,  -par-,  -hyp-,  -hyper-;  -tic. 

9.  Hair-sensibility  tricho-esthe(sia)    -an-,  -par-,  -hyp-,  -hyper-;  -siometer, 

-tic,  -sis. 

10.  Muscular-sense    kinesthe(sia)     a-,    para-,  hypo-,  hjrper-;  -siometer, 

-tic 

11.  Body-sense    coenesthe(sia)  a-,  para-,  hypo-,  hyper-;  -tic,  -sis. 

12.  Pain-sense     alge  (sia)  an-,  hyp-,  hyper-;  -simeter,  -tic,  -sis. 

13.  Vibration-sense     palmesthe(sia)     -an-,   hypo-,  hyper-;   -tic. 

The  termination  ia  is  of  course  used  only  with  a  prefix.  It  would  be 
perfectly  legitimate  to  use  the  suffix  is  to  indicate  the  sense  itself,  in  all 
cases  (as  is  done  in  algesis,  for  example),  as  we  are  not  bound  strictly  to 
the  Greek  precedent;  but  as  a  matter  of  fact  no  one  has  ventured  to  do 
this. 

Special  attention  might  be  called  to  the  use  of  acusic  and  opsic  to  des- 
ignate the  sensational  facts;  in  place  of  optic  and  acoustic,  which  have 
special  significance.  It  is  very  desirable  also  that  the  special  prefixes 
chrom-,  achrom-,  monochrom-,  dichrom-,  etc. ;  and  hemian-,  hemeral-,  nyctal-, 
and  ambly-  should  be  used  with  opsia,  and  not  with  opia,  as  the  latter  com- 
bination is  illogical,  although  it  is  found  at  present  about  as  often  as 
is  the  other  usage.  In  place  of  the  color-prefixes  indicated,  chromat-, 
achromat-,  etc.,  are  frequently  used,  but  there  seems  to  be  no  sufficient 
reason  for  the  -at-,  and  it  should  be  dropped  to  bring  these  words  into 
harmony  with  others  already  established. 

Ope  is  used  as  a  combining  form  to  indicate  either  the  possessor  of  a 
certain  sort  of  eye  {myope,  emmetrope,  etc.)  or  the  subject  of  a  certain  form 
of  disorder  of  sensibility  (amblyope,  nyctalope,  etc.).  This  usage  is  well 
established  and  gives  rise  to  no  confusion. 

The  prefix  dipl-  is  uniformly  applied  to  opsia  (although  some  authors 
persist  in  writing  diplopia !)  and  to  acusia.  It  might  legitimately  be  ap- 
plied to  aphia  also.  Ambly-  has  been  applied  to  acusia  in  place  of  hypo, 
but  the  usage  does  not  seem  commendable.  Amblacusia  might,  however, 
be  logically  applied  to  the  lack  of  accuracy  in  pitch  discrimination. 

Knight  Duni,ap. 

The  Johns  Hopkins  University. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 


Das  Geddchtnis  im  Lichte  des  Experiments.  Von  A.  WrESCHNER.  Zweite 
vermehrte  Auflage.     Zurich,  Art.  Institute  Fiissli,  1 910.     pp.77. 

Here,  in  the  compass  of  exactly  70  pages, — less  than  half  the  space  often 
taken  for  a  single  article, — is  a  clear  and  well-proportioned  account  of 
the  experimental  work  on  memory,  from  Ebbinghaus  down  to  Katz  and 
Revesz.  Professor  Wreschner  has  earned  the  gratitude,  not  only  of  the 
teachers  for  whom  his  work  was  originally  intended,  but  of  psychologists 
as  well.     A  translation  would  be  useful. 

The  two-page  bibliography  is  not  wholly  free  from  printer's  errors,  and, 
curiously,  omits  the  dates  of  many  of  the  papers  cited.  S.  Power 

Observations  d'un  musicien  americain.  Par  Louis  Lombard.  Traduit 
par  R.  de  Lagenardiere.  Paris,  L.  Theuveny,  1905.  pp.  xxi.,  198. 
Mr,  Lombard,  the  author  of  Observations  of  a  Bachelor,  and  the  founder 
and  sometime  director  of  the  Conservatory  of  Music  at  Utica,  N.  Y.,  has 
here  brought  together  a  number  of  notes  and  addresses,  dealing  with 
musical  subjects.  We  have  strictures  on  the  songs,  operatic  performances, 
composers  and  conservatories  of  America ;  strictures  also  on  the  music  and 
dancing  of  modem  Spain,  and  on  the  Japanese  productions  of  western 
music;  a  number  of  practical  recommendations  to  students  of  music;  and  a 
few  theoretical  discussions, — of  the  sense  in  which  music  may  be  termed  a 
universal  language,  of  the  adaptation  of  musical  performances  to  the  taste 
of  the  people,  of  the  social  utility  of  art,  and  so  forth.  It  is  all  readable 
enough,  and  the  practical  advice  is  sensible;  more  cannot  be  said. 

J.  Field 

La  vie  mentale  de  V  adolescent  et  ses  anomalies.  Par  A.  LemaitrE.  Saint- 
Blaise,  Foyer  Solidariste,  1910.  Pp.  240.  Price  fr.  3. 
The  work  of  M.  Lemaitre,  who  is  a  professor  in  the  College  of  Geneva, 
is  well  known  to  students  of  applied  psychology.  In  1901  M.  Lemaitre 
published  a  work  on  colored  hearing,  the  material  for  which  he  had  gath- 
ered among  his  pupils;  and  since  the  foundation  of  the  Archives  de  Psycho- 
logie  in  1902,  he  has  contributed  to  this  journal  a  number  of  articles  dealing 
with  the  adolescent  mind,  and  especially  with  what  one  may  call  its  shadow 
side.  The  present  volume  brings  together,  in  convenient  form,  the  sub- 
stance of  papers  published  by  the  author  in  the  Archives,  in  Janet's  Journal 
and  in  the  Rivista  di  Psicologia.  The  titles  of  the  chapters  are  Adolescent 
Thinking  (students'  views  on  class  disciphne,  on  the  ideal  fellow-student, 
on  spending  money),  the  More  Common  and  the  Rarer  Forms  of  Synopsia 
(three  cases  of  an  uncommon  type  are  detailed).  Internal  Speech,  the  Forms 
of  Paramnesia,  Mental  Dissociation,  Complex  Hallucinations  (two  cases). 
Multiple  Personalities,  Parapsychism  (a  name  given  to  a  transient  state 
of  reverie,  obsession,  or  what  not,  which  results  from  a  physiological  crisis 
and  may  help  in  the  prognosis  of  a  disease  like  tuberculosis  or  of  the  various 
modes  of  psychasthenia).  Bad  Habits,  and  Adolescent  Suicide.  In  an 
epilogue,  M.  Lemaitre  makes  a  plea  for  individual  education.  There  is  no 
single  type  of  the  adolescent  mind :  ce  type  moyen  est  une  pure  convention, 
qui  ne  correspond  d,  aucun  sujet  pris  isolement;  the  mental  life  is  in  instable 
equilibrium,  and  its  oscillations  are  not  only  uneven  but  may  also  be  so 


446  BOOK  R^VI^WS 

brusque  as  to  set  up  aberrant  types  of  a  permanent  but  wholly  unexpected 
kind.  Education  will,  in  the  future,  be  of  the  individual  sort;  meantime, 
the  author  recommends  a  system  of  compensations,  whereby  excellence  in 
certain  studies  shall  be  allowed  to  counterbalance  deficiency  in  certain 
others.  Francis  Jones 

The  Dawn  of  Character;  X  Study  of  Child  Life.  By  E.  E.  R.  Mumpord. 
London,  Longmans  Green  &  Co.,   1910.     pp.  xi.,  225. 

This  is  a  very  practical  little  book,  written  for  the  guidance  of  mothers, 
aunts,  nurses,  governesses, — of  all  who,  without  special  training,  are  called 
upon  to  take  care  of  young  children.  "My  endeavor  has  been,  "the 
author  tells  us,  '  'to  interpret  the  child's  experiences  from  his  own  point  of 
view.  Both  in  the  earlier  psychological  chapters,  in  which  I  have  tried  to 
trace  his  own  development;  and  in  the  later  chapters,  concerned  with  his 
development  in  relation  to  us  and  our  attitude  towards  him;  the  aim  has 
been  to  see,  as  far  as  possible,  with  the  child's  eyes."  The  object  is  worthy, 
and  Mrs.  Mumford,  so  far  as  the  mere  adult  can  judge,  has  attained  a 
very  considerable  measure  of  success. 

After  an  introductory  plea  for  the  closer  study  of  child  life,  we  have  seven 
psychological  chapters:  on  the  contents  and  the  growth  of  the  child's 
mind,  on  the  growth  of  imagination,  on  the  law  and  growth  of  habit,  and  on 
the  development  and  training  of  the  will.  For  these  chapters  the  writer 
has  had  the  advantage  of  the  critical  scrutiny  of  Professor  Carveth  Read. 
There  follow  chapters  on  the  place  of  punishment  in  education,  on  freedom 
within  the  law,  on  childish  curiosity,  on  the  dawn  of  religion,  on  some  dif- 
ferent types  of  children,  and  on  the  child's  point  of  view.  There  are  few 
references;  the  author  acknowledges  indebtedness  especially  to  McCunn's 
Making  of  Character,  and  to  the  teaching  of  Dr.  Sophie  Bryant  and  the 
Rev.  Stopford  Brooke. 

An  Appendix,  on  the  gaining  of  voluntary  control  in  the  functioning  of 
the  bladder  in  infancy  and  childhood,  closes  the  book  which,  unfortunately, 
is  not  provided  with  an  index.  O.  PerlER 

Kleine  Schriften.  Von  Wilhelm  Wundt.  Erster  Band.  Leipzig,  W. 
Engelmann,  1910.     pp.  viii.,  640. 

Every  teacher  of  psychology  has  hoped  that  Wundt  might,  some  day 
or  other,  bring  together  his  scattered  psychological  essays  in  book  form. 
The  essays  supplement  the  books,  at  many  points;  if  they  are  less  systematic, 
they  are  also  more  human;  and  their  full  discussion  of  controverted  issues 
is  often  illuminating.  It  seems,  now,  that  this  hope  is  in  a  fair  way  of 
being  realised;  we  have  the  first  volume  of  the  Kleine  Schriften — a  truly 
German  misnomer ! — and  though  the  present  instalment  is  concerned  with 
philosophy,  the  next  will  in  all  probability  be  psychological. 

Here  are  reprinted,  in  revised  and  extended  form,  the  articles  Ueher  das 
kosmologische  Problem  (1876),  Kants  kosmologische  Antinomien  und  das 
Problem  des  Unendlichen  (1885),  Was  soil  uns  Kant  nicht  sein?  Bemerk- 
ungen  zu  Kants  Philosophic  (1892),  Zur  Geschichte  und  Theorie  der  ab^trakten 
Begriffe;  eine  erkenntnistheoretische  Betrachtung  (1885),  and  Ueber  naiven  und 
kritischen  Realismus  (1896).  To  these  is  added  (1910)  a  very  timely  paper 
on  P sychologismus  und  Logizismus,  which  may  be  heartily  recommended  to 
every  serious  student  of  psychology.  From  it  he  will  learn  that  the  experi- 
mental method  came  in,  not  simply  as  an  improvement  upon,  but  also  as  a 
protest  against  Selbstbeobachtung;  he  will  see  Brentano's  work  in  historical 
perspective,  and  will  understand  its  enormous  influence;  he  will  grasp  the 
psychological  significance  of  Husserl's  Logische  Untersuchungen;  he  will 
discover,  among  many  other  interesting  things,  why  the  physiologist 
Helmholtz  went  for  his  psychology  to  John  Mill's  Logic.  No  one  but  Wundt 
could  have  given  us  this  authoritative  exposition.    It  is  only  to  be  regretted 


BOOK  REVIEWS  447 

that  he  has  not  put  it  upon  the  market  in  separate  form;  experimental 
psychologists  will  hardly  be  attracted  by  a  large  volume  of  philosophical 
essays,  B.  B.  TitchEnEr 

Handbook  of   American  Indians  North    of    Mexico.     Edited  by  F.     W. 
Hodge.     Pt.  2.     Washington,    Govt.  Printing  Office,  1910.     pp.  iv., 
1221. 
Antiquities  of  Central  and  Southeastern  Missouri.     By  G.  FowkE.     Wash- 
ington,    Govt.  Printing  Office.     1910,  pp.  vii.,   116. 
Chippewa  Music.     By  Frances   Densmore.     Washington,  Govt.   Print- 
ing Office,  1 9 10.     pp.  xix,,  216. 
The  three  works  above  mentioned  are  Bulletins  30,  37,  and  45  of  the 
Bureau  of  American  Ethnology,  published  by  the  Smithsonian  Institution. 
The  first  of  them  completes  the  very  useful  Handbook  of  American  Indians, 
covering   the    letters    N  to    Z.     Dr.  Wissler    contributes   an    article    on 
Psychology,  the  upshot  of  which  is  that  we  know  practically  nothing  of  the 
subject, — surely  a  strong  indictment  against  those  directors  of  laboratories 
who  have  Indian  subjects  within  their  reach;  and  Professor  Boas  writes, 
with  more  to  say,  upon  Religion.     There  are  many  other  articles  of  psy- 
chological interest  in  the  volume. 

The  second  Bulletin  reports  the  results  of  mound-excavation  in  Missouri. 
The  burial  vaults  found  are  a  new  feature  in  American  archaeology  so  far 
as  concerns  the  region  east  of  the  Rocky  Mountains.  At  least  two  different 
stages  of  culture  are  indicated;  dates  cannot  be  given,  but  the  later  stage 
may  perhaps  be  connected  with  the  Siouian  Indians. 

The  third  item  upon  our  list  gives  the  transcription  and  analysis  of  nearly 
two  hundred  Chippewa  songs,  collected  in  northern  Minnesota.  The 
author  finds  that  rhythm  is  the  essential  part  of  the  songs;  words,  and 
even  the  less  important  melodic  progressions,  may  vary,  but  the  rhythm  is 
constant.  The  songs  are  classified  as  harmonic  and  melodic:  as  harmonic, 
if  their  accented  tones  follow  the  intervals  of  diatonic  chords,  as  melodic, 
if  their  contiguous  accented  tones  have  no  apparent  chord-relationship:  of 
180  songs,  41  are  harmonic  and  139  melodic.  The  work  is  well  illustrated 
with  portraits,  photographs  of  musical  instruments,  and  cuts  of  the  song- 
pictures.  J.  Field 

Examination  [of  Prof.  William  James's  Psychology.  By  Ikbal  Kishen 
Sharga,  Principal  S.  P.  H.  College,  Srinagar,  Kashmir.  Allahabad, 
Ram  Narin  Lai,   1910.    pp.  v.,  118.     Prince  One  Rupee. 

When  the  incoming  graduate  student  is  asked  what  books  he  has  read, 
the  first  item  on  his  list  is  likely  to  be  James'  Principles  of  Psychology. 
And  when  he  is  asked,  further,  whether  he  understands  and  can  reproduce 
James'  views,  the  reply  is  likely  to  be  a  cheerful  affirmative.  But  if  the 
enquiring  professor  go  on  to  ask  for  James'  conception  of  the  psychological 
self,  or  for  his  view  of  the  relation  of  mind  to  nervous  system,  or  even 
for  his  theory  of  emotion,  the  situation  may  take  on  an  aspect  the  reverse 
of  cheerful;  James'  doctrine  is  not,  after  all,  as  clear-cut  as  it  had  ap- 
peared; passages  from  the  book  that  seem  to  speak  definitely  in  a  certain 
sense  may  be  met  by  passages  that  seem  to  speak,  no  less  definitely,  in 
another. 

Some  of  these  contradictions  are  real,  some  only  apparent ;  and  none  de- 
tract from  the  greatness  of  James'  achievement  or  offer  a  serious  stumbling- 
block  to  the  trained  reader,  Nevertheless,  it  is  just  as  well  that  they  be 
brought  out  into  clear  daylight;  and  the  author  of  the  work  before  us 
has  done  psychology  a  service  in  publishing  the  results  of  a  thorough  com- 
parative study  of  James'  text.  Unfortunately,  perhaps,  he  has  combined 
the  internal  and  the  external  methods  of  criticism;  he  is  not  content  to 
find  James  inconsistent,  or  to  show  reasons  for  the  inconsistency,  but  he 


I 


448  BOOK  REVIEWS 

attacks,  from  the  outside,  some  of  the  tendencies  and  principles  of  the 
Jamesian  psychology.  The  two  aims  are  entirely  legitimate;  but  they 
are  also  distinct;  and  disagreement  with  a  writer's  general  attitude  may 
easily  lead  you  to  overestimate  his  slips,  and  to  find  contradiction  where 
sympathy  would  have  found  only  change  of  standpoint,  or  mere  verbal 
discrepancy.  In  some  instances,  our  author  seems  to  have  fallen  into 
this  trap ;  in  most,  however,  he  has  his  finger  on  real  weaknesses  in  James' 
exposition. 

The  special  points  discussed  are:  the  relation  of  brain  to  mind,  the 
doctrine  of  the  externality  of  sensation,  the  doctrine  of  the  indivisibility 
of  states  of  consciousness,  the  self  as  knower  and  as  known,  and  James' 
theories  of  conception,  emotion  and  volition.  S.  Power 

An  Adventure.  By 'EuzabETh  Morison' and 'Frances  Lamont.'  London, 
Macmillan  &  Co.,  Ltd.,   191 1.     pp.  vii.,  162. 

The  gist  of  the  'adventure'  is  this:  On  August  10,  1901,  two  English 
ladies  paid  their  first  visit  to  the  Petit  Trianon  at  Versailles.  It  was,  of 
course,  broad  daylight;  and  the  visitors,  who  were  in  good  health,  knew 
practically  nothing  of  the  history  of  the  place.  They  nevertheless  saw 
scenes  and  met  persons  of  the  time  of  the  Revolution;  'Miss  Morison'  saw 
the  Queen  herself.  On  Jan.  22,  1902,  'Miss  Lamont'  visited  the  place  alone, 
and  had  similar  experiences.  Subsequent  visits,  by  both  the  narrators, 
passed  off  normally. 

Ch.  i.  of  the  present  account  details  the  events  of  the  various  visits, 
the  two  authors  writing  independently;  on  the  two  critical  occasions  they 
did  not  see  alike  at  every  point.  Ch.  ii.  gives  the  results  of  research: 
identification  of  the  figures  seen,  the  buildings  and  grounds  passed  and 
traversed,  the  music  heard,  etc.  Ch.  iii.  answers  some  of  the  questions 
and  meets  some  of  the  attempted  explanations  proposed  to  the  writers  by 
sceptical  friends.  Ch.  iv.  seeks  to  account  for  the  whole  set  of  experi- 
ences as  the  reproduction  of  a  memory  of  Marie  Antoinette's.  On  August 
10,  1792,  the  royal  family  was  penned  up  for  many  hours  in  the  little 
room  opening  into  the  Hall  of  the  Assembly;  the  Queen,  exhausted 
and  exasperated,  sought  a  fleeting  relief  in  recalling  the  simple  pleasures  and 
the  country  freedom  of  the  Petit  Trianon;  as  her  thoughts  wandered, 
incident  after  incident  flashed  upon  her  mind, — the  incidents  re-experienced 
by  the  two  ladies,  more  than  a  hundred  years  later. 

The  publishers  guarantee  "that  the  authors  have  put  down  what  happened 
to  them  as  faithfully  and  accurately  as  was  in  their  power;"  the  names 
appended  to  the  narrative  are  the  only  fictitious  things  in  the  book.  Now 
let  conjecture  do  its  work!  J.  Waterlow 

The  Concept  of  Method.     By   C.  R.  LomeR.     Controversies  over  the  Imita- 
tion of  Cicero  as  a  Model  for  Style,  and  Some  Phases  of  their  Influence  on 
the   Schools    of  the   Renaissance.     By   I.   Scott.     Teachers    College, 
Columbia  University,  New  York  City,  19 10.     Contributions  to  Educa- 
tion, 34,  35,     pp.  99;  v.,  145. 
Dr.  Lomer's  object  is  '  'to  emphasise  the  strong  necessity,  in  the  edu- 
cational theory  of  the  present  day,  for  an  analysis  of  the  process  of  experi- 
ence itself,  with  a  view  to  realising  its  organic  character,  to  making  apparent 
its  impUcations,  and  to  maintaining  its  ultimate  reality,  in  idea,  as  the 
method  of  our  existence."     Educational  theory  has  been  largely  occupied 
either  with  the  materials  of  education  or,  from  a  purely  formal  standpoint, 
with  special  details  of  educational  procedure.     We  have  in  fact,  as  the 
terminal  aspects  in  the  educational  process,  the  materials  that  are  selected 
as  educationally  valuable  in  the  school  course,  and  the  child  itself,  with  its 
impulses,  instincts,  activities  and  energies.     The  problem  is,  then,  to  see 
how  these  two  elements  are  related  in  actual  experience;  to  understand 
education  as  a  method  of  giving  form  to  the  experience  of  the  child.    From 


BOOK  REVIEWS  449 

this  point  of  view,  the  author  first  reviews  some  historical  types  of  method 
(the  Greeks,  Bacon,  Descartes,  Comenius,  Kant),  and  then  attempts  con- 
structive work  on  the  function  and  interpretation  of  method  (the  idea  of 
development;  the  interpretation  of  experience;  the  function  of  method). 
Unfortunately,  his  style  is  obscure,  and  the  connection  of  his  thought  not 
always  apparent.  As,  however,  he  has  read  widely,  and  does  not  fear  to 
face  ultimate  problems,  we  may  expect  from  him,  later,  a  systematic,  trea- 
tise that  will  be  better  suited  to  the  average  reader. 

Dr.  Scott  writes  of  Ciceronianism,  in  the  sense  of  '  'the  trend  of  literary 
opinion  in  regard  to  accepting  Cicero  as  a  model  for  imitation  in  composi- 
tion," The  work  before  us  has  an  introductory  chapter  on  the  influence  of 
Cicero  from  his  own  time  to  that  of  Poggio  and  Valla  (c.  1450),  when 
men  of  letters  began  a  series  of  controversies  over  his  merits  as  a  model  of 
style ;  chapters  treating  of  these  controversies ;  and  a  study  of  the  connec- 
tion of  the  entire  movement  with  the  history  of  education.  '  'At  the  close 
of  the  1 6th  century,  the  Renaissance  spirit  in  general  had  furnished  to 
the  schools,  as  the  aim  of  education,  the  mastery  of  the  Greek  and  Latin 
languages;  but  the  cult  of  the  ultra- Ciceronians  had  wielded  so  great 
influence  that  that  aim,  so  far  as  Latin  was  concerned,  had  degenerated 
into  the  purely  imitative  treatment  of  the  authors  studied,  among  whom 
Cicero  was  given  by  far  the  greatest  prominence.  The  dialectic  of  the 
Middle  Ages  had  been  largely  supplanted  by  rhetoric,  and  some  effort  had 
been  made  to  connect  this  study  with  life;  but,  on  the  whole,  the  reign  of 
form  had  been  transferred  from  logic  to  rhetoric,  and  was  fighting  for  pres- 
tige there  under  the  banner  of  New  Learning."  An  appendix  contains 
translations  of  the  controversial  letters  of  Pico  and  Bembo,  and  of  the  Cice- 
ronianus  of  Erasmus.  W.  Francis 

Ueber  die  korperlichen  Begleiterscheinungen  psychischer  Vorgdnge.  O.  Bumke^. 
Wiesbaden,  J.  F.  Bergmann,  1909.  pp.  16.  Price  pf.  65. 
A  popular  lecture  delivered  to  the  Naturforschende  Gesellschaft  of  Frei- 
burg. The  writer  first  touches  upon  the  pupillar  reflex,  and  the  expres- 
sive changes  of  f pulse,  respiration  and  volume;  illustrations  are  given 
from  Lehmann.  All  these  movements  are  expressive  of  feeling  or  emotion; 
if  they  accompany  attention  or  reflective  thought,  that  is  because  all  mental 
processes  whatsoever  are  attended  by  feeling.  He  then  turns  to  Sommer's 
tridimensional  analysis  of  involuntary  finger  movements,  which  he  uses 
to  explain  certain  card-tricks  and  phenomena  of  thought-reading.  From 
these  it  is  natural  to  proceed  to  table-turning:  the  motor  effect  of  a  defi- 
nitely directed  expectation  is  illustrated  by  the  pendulum  experiment  of 
Bacon  and  Chevreul,  by  the  mistakes  of  the  self-conscious  performer  and 
reciter,  by  the  disasters  of  a  first  attempt  at  bicycle-riding;  the  surety  of 
movement  when  there  is  no  interference  by  expectation  is  shown  in  the 
trance- dancing  of  the  well-known  'Madeleine.'  Coming  back  to  thought- 
reading,  Dr.  Bumke  then  outlines  the  results  of  Lehmann  and  Hansen  on  the 
unconscious  whisper,  and  the  story  of  the  trick-horse  Hans,  with  Pfungst's 
related  experiments.  He  is  doubtful  of  the  promise  of  Veraguth's  psycho- 
galvanic reflex;  partly  because,  like  the  pupillar  reflex,  it  shows  only 
one  single  form  of  reaction,  without  qualitative  differentiation,  partly 
because  it  is  too  delicate  a  test  of  disturbance  of  mental  equilibrium.  Fi- 
nally, he  discusses  Berger's  observations  of  the  exposed  brain,  in  order  to 
gain  light  on  the  question  whether  the  physical  changes  are  co-ordinate 
with  or  subordinate  to  the  corresponding  mental  processes.  The  brain 
changes  precede  the  changes  in  other  parts  of  the  body,  but  are  nevertheless 
themselves  of  a  secondary  or  subordinate  kind ;  the  observations,  therefore, 
tell  us  nothing  of  the  intimate  nature  of  psychophysical  parallelism. 

The  lecture  thus  covers  a  good  deal  of  interesting  ground,  and  the  expo- 
sition is  in  the  main  sound.  There  is  some  vacillation  as  to  the  mental 
antecedents  of  involuntary  movement;  the  general  teaching  appears  to  be 


450  BOOK  REVIEWS 

that  expressive  movements  are  always  expressive  of  feeling;  but  we  are  also 
told  that  the  mere  idea  {Idee)  that  a  movement  may  occur  suffices  to  set  the 
muscles  in  involuntary  activity.  The  James-Lange  theory  of  emotion  is 
dismissed  with  the  remark  that  it  was  never  demonstrable  and  to-day  is 
refuted :  here  the  writer's  logic  seems  to  have  gone  astray,  to  say  nothing 
of  his  psychology.  The  concluding  paragraphs,  on  Berger's  results  and 
their  connection  with  parallelsim,  must  have  been  unintelligible  to  the 
majority  of  the  audience  as  they  will  be  unintelligible  to  most  readers  of  the 
lecture.  Francis  Jones 

Sprache,  Gesang  und  Korperhaltung:  Handbuch  zur  Typenlehre  Ruiz. 
Von  Dr.  Ottmar  Rutz.  Miinchen,  O.  Beck.  191 1.  pp.  vi.,  152. 
With  plates  and  tables.     Price  Mk.  2.80. 

All  amateur  singers  have  observed  that  there  are  certain  songs  which, 
though  simple  in  composition  and  well  within  the  compass  of  the  voice,  do 
not  'suit.'  It  seems  that  professional  singers  have  the  same  experience. 
And  about  the  year  i860,  the  German  professional  singer  Joseph  Rutz 
made  the  discovery  that  every  song  demands  a  very  definite  modality  of 
voice,  can  be  sung  adequately  only  in  one  particular  way.  At  first,  he 
sought  to  find  an  explanation  in  the  adjustment  of  larynx,  mouth  and  throat ; 
but  repeated  trial  showed  that  the  essential  thing  is  the  carriage  of  the  body, 
the  attitude  of  the  trunk.  Joseph  Rutz  died  in  1895,  without  having  com- 
mitted his  results  to  paper ;  but  his  wife  and  son — the  son  is  the  author  of  the 
present  book,  and  of  a  work  entitled  Neue  Entdeckungen  von  der  menschli- 
chen  Stimme,  which  appeared  in  1908 — ^have  worked  further  upon  the 
subject,  and  have  reached  conclusions  of  great  scientific  and  practical  im- 
portance. Authorities  of  no  less  weight  than  Wundt  and  Sievers  have 
given  the  Typenlehre  Rutz  their  approval,  and  have  started  enquiry  into 
the  scientific  aspects  of  the  discovery. 

Briefly  stated,  the  thesis  is  this:  that  every  mode  of  expression  in  tone 
and  word — music,  poetry,  prose,  oratory,  letter-writing — presupposes  in 
the  individual  a  special  bodily  attitude,  and  can  be  reproduced  only  by 
an  individual  to  whom  the  attitude  in  question  is  either  natural  or  by 
practice  familiar.  Speech,  song  and  the  carriage  of  the  body,  are  closely 
interrelated,  and  are  one  and  all  related  further  to  certain  fundamental 
tendencies  of  the  life  of  mind,  the  temperamental  tendencies  that  underlie 
mood  and  the  other  forms  of  affective  reaction.  Not,  of  course,  that  the 
principle  of  individuation  must  be  pressed  too  far;  the  three  great  types 
distinguished  by  the  author  are  national  or  racial  types,  the  Italian,  the 
German  (which  includes  the  English  also),  and  the  French;  but  these  types 
have  sub-types  or  sub-forms,  which  may  be  variously  combined,  and  which 
may  be  differently  displayed  by  a  given  individual  at  different  times.  It 
is  important  to  remark  that  the  Rutz  types  are  exclusively  types  of  feeling, 
not  of  character  or  of  intelligence;  if  a  man  is  able  to  shift  from  one  type 
to  another,  as  Schumann  shifts  from  his  naturally  German  type  to  the 
French  in  the  Two  Grenadiers,  this  is  by  virtue  of  a  power  of  imitative  or 
empathic  feeling. 

The  theory  of  the  matter  has  been  set  forth  in  Dr.  Rutz'  earlier  works, 
in  an  article  in  Meumann's  Arckiv,  and  elsewhere.  The  present  book  is 
practical.  It  gives  a  list  of  the  types,  and  of  their  sub-forms,  with  illustra- 
tive plates,  and  draws  up  rules  for  the  student.  It  also  gives  (pp.  60-144) 
an  alphabetical  index  of  authors  and  musicians,  classified  by  type.  The 
mastery  of  the  directions  for  the  carriage  of  the  body  is,  at  least  in  the  rough, 
by  no  means  difficult,  and  the  reader  will  be  repaid  if  he  spend  a  little  time 
upon  them,  and  then  test  them  by  extracts  from  the  writers  quoted.  There 
can  be  no  doubt  that  the  Rutz  types  are  real,  and  that  the  Rutz  discovery  is 
destined  to  play  a  large  part  in  the  psychology  of  expression.  Had  Thorn- 
dike  taken  these  types  into  account,  he  could  hardly  have  written  so 
strongly  against  the  multiple-type  theory  as  he  has  done  in  the  new 
edition  of  his  Educational  Psychology.  A.  Isaacson 


BOOK  REVIEWS  451 

Leitfaden  der  experimentellen  Psychopathologie.  Vorlesungen  gehalten 
an  der  Universitat  Leipzig  von  Privatdozent  Dr.  A  GrEgor,  Oberarzt 
der  psychiatrisch-neurologischen  Klinik,  Leipzig.  Berlin,  S.  Karger. 
1910.     Pp.  X.,  222.     Price  Mk.  5.60. 

In  1 900,  Dr.  Storring — at  that  time  also  a  Privatdozent  in  the  University 
of  Leipzig,  but  a  Privatdozent  of  Philosophy — published  a  volume  of  Lec- 
tures on  Psychopathology,  which  has  recently  been  translated  into  English. 
This  work  naturally  comes  to  mind,  as  one  opens  the  present  volume;  but 
a  reading  of  Dr.  Gregor's  lectures  shows  that  the  intention  of  the  authors 
is  entirely  different.  Storring,  it  will  be  remembered,  aims  to  bring  out 
the  significance  of  psychopathology  for  normal  psychology,  and  outlines 
the  psychological  principles  of  a  theory  of  knowledge.  Gregor  avails 
himself  of  the  experimental  method  (we  might  say  of  Sommer's  methods) 
in  psychopathology,  in  order  to  obtain  results  that  shall  be  useful  for  treat- 
ment, and  in  order,  at  the  same  time,  to  enhance  the  capacity  of  clinical 
observation  and  of  diagnosis  (p.  13).  The  older  work  views  psychopatholo- 
gy from  the  standpoint  of  the  psychologist;  the  newer  views  psychology 
and  psychological  method  from  the  standpoint  of  the  psychiatrist.  In  a 
certain  broad  sense,  therefore,  the  two  series  of  lectures  are  complementary, 
though  the  lapse  of  time  by  which  they  are  separated,  and  the  differences 
in  the  authors'  training  and  attitude,  make  this  relation  partial  and  incom- 
plete.    At  any  rate,  it  is  instructive  to  read  the  books  together. 

It  may  be  said  at  once  that  Dr.  Gregor  is  a  worthy  successor  to  Storring. 
He  is  already  favorably  known  by  the  experimental  studies  which,  alone 
or  in  collaboration,  he  has  published  since  the  year  1906,  and  in  which 
he  has  applied  psychological  methods  to  the  study  of  such  functions  as  the 
appreciation  of  time,  the  apprehension  of  visual  stimuli  tachistoscopically  ex- 
posed, the  range  of  memory,  etc.,  in  cases  of  mental  disorder,  and  notably  in 
cases  of  what  is  called  Korsakow's  disease  (a  toxaemic  neurosis,  characterized 
by  defects  of  associative  memory,  confusion  with  a  marked  tendency  to  con- 
fabulate and  to  indulge  in  pseudo-reminiscences,  hallucinations  and  delu- 
sions, a  marked  fluctuation  of  the  affective  life,  and  oftentimes  disturbance 
of  function  of  peripheral  nerves).  The  results  of  these  studies,  together 
with  those  of  other  investigators,  are  here  brought  together  in  a  systematic 
way.  An  introductory  lecture  deals  in  general  terms  with  the  relation 
between  pychology  and  psychiatry.  Then  follow  lectures  on  the  psycho- 
pathology of  the  time-sense,  on  reaction  experiments,  on  visual  perception 
{Auffassung,  in  the  sense  of  Kraepelin  and  Cron),  association  (2),  memory 
(2),  the  psychology  of  testimony  (2),  attention  (2),  the  external  volun- 
tary action,  the  bodily  expression  of  psychical  states,  the  formal  as- 
pects of  mental  work,  and  tests  of  intelligence.  In  every  instance  the 
technique  and  results  of  normal  experiments  are  first  set  forth,  and  then 
we  have  an  account  of  method,  as  modified  for  application  to  the  patient, 
and  of  the  results  so  far  obtained.  The  exposition  is  clear,  and  the  author 
has  a  good  knowledge  of  the  normal  work.  In  Lect.  VI.  he  outlines  his 
positon  to  Freud's  psychoanalytic  method:  the  procedure  is  personal,  and 
the  material  not  altogether  objective;  nevertheless,  if  used  with  caution, 
psychoanalysis  is  a  valuable  instrument  (p.  76).  The  view  of  attention 
taken  in  Lect.  XI.  is  that  of  Durr:  the  motor  attitude  of  readiness  for 
stimuli  is  a  concomitant  phenomenon  only;  the  essential  thing  in  attention 
is  clear  and  definite  apprehension  of  objects,  vividness  and  compelling 
character  of  conscious  contents  (p.  137). 

The  book  has  two  external  defects  which  call  for  notice.  In  the  first 
place  there  is  no  index.  In  the  second,  there  is  neither  a  paged  table  of 
contents  nor  any  sort  of  page  heading !  The  consequence  is,  that  if  one  wants 
to  find,  say,  the  experiments  on  testimony  made  with  abnormal  subjects, 
one  has  first  to  look  through  the  table  of  contents;  there  one  discovers 
that  Lect.  X.  is  the  place  required ;  and  then  one  has  to  turn  the  pages  of 


452  BOOK  R^VIJeWS 

the  book  at  random,  till  one  happens  to  strike  the  title  Zehnte  Vorlesung 
on  p.  123.  Why  the  reader  should  be  exposed  to  these  indignities,  only  a 
German  publisher  could  explain.  A  useful  bibliography  (pp.  215-222) 
is  not  mentioned  in  the  table  of  contents.  W.  Asher 

The  Dweller  on  the  Threshold,  by  Robert  Hichens.  New  York,  The  Cen- 
tury Co.     191 1,     pp.  273.     Price  $1.10  net. 

It  is  seldom  that  a  psychologist  is  called  upon  to  review  the  Latest  Novel. 
The  present  reviewer  has  read  and  enjoyed  other  works  by  Mr.  Hidiens, — 
The  Garden  of  Allah,  and  Bella  Donna;  this  newer  work  he  has  read  with- 
out enjoyment. 

The  story  has  to  do  principally  with  the  Rector  of  a  London  parish  and 
his  senior  curate.  At  the  beginning  of  their  relationship,  before  the  narra- 
tive opens,  these  men  stand  in  sharp  contrast:  the  Rector  is  talented,  am- 
bitious, self-confident,  the  Curate  is  industrious,  dutiful,  humble-minded. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  Rector  is  troubled  by  sceptical  doubts,  and  is  be- 
trayed by  grossness  of  fibre  into  occasional  lapses  from  right-doing,  while 
the  Curate,  amiable  and  easily  led  as  he  is,  has  at  any  rate  the  strength 
that  comes  from  an  unshaken  faith  and  personal  purity  of  living.  The 
Rector  now  conceives  the  idea  of  using  the  Curate  as  a  medium  whereby 
he  may  obtain  communications  from  the  spirit  world;  he  thus  satisfies 
his  lust  of  power,  and  at  the  same  time  hopes  to  settle  his  religious  doubts. 
The  Curate,  however,  has  to  be  inveigled  into  'sitting';  and  the  Rector 
gains  his  point  by  the  lying  assurance  that  the  whole  object  of  the  proceed- 
ings is  to  strengthen  the  Curate's  will,  to  inspire  him  with  something  of  the 
mental  power  that  he  admittedly  lacks  and  that  he  admires  in  his  superior. 
So  the  sittings  begin.  But  the  Rector  fails  after  all,  to  'entrance'  his 
weaker-minded  colleague, — who,  on  his  side,  feels  himself  strengthened  in 
the  manner  promised.  And  so  it  presently  comes  to  pass  that  the  Curate 
is  the  dominant  and  strong-willed,  the  Rector  the  dominated  and  suggesti- 
ble member  of  the  duo;  the  parts  have  been  reversed  or  exchanged.  But 
here  is  the  mysterious  consequence:  the  Rector  remains  consciously  what 
he  was,  the  Rector,  only  that  he  is  now  a  weakling,  aware  of  his  weakness 
and  trending  steadily  down  hill;  the  Curate,  who  has  sucked  the  Rector's 
strength  from  him,  becomes  a  dual  personality,  in  whom  the  original  Rector 
predominates  and  the  Curate  is  entirely  subordinate.  In  other  words,  the 
Curate  henceforth  is  the  'double'  of  the  Rector,  knows  and  feels  himself 
to  be  in  the  main  identical  with  the  Rector,  while  his  own  curate's  nature 
remains  largely  in  abeyance,  though  it  is  not  wholly  lost;  he  therefore 
watches  the  Rector,  fears  on  his  behalf,  suffers  with  and  for  him,  seeks  to 
guide  or  direct  him,  precisely  as  a  man  would  act  and  suffer  in  his  own 
interest;  and  the  Rector,  harassed  by  this  perpetual  scrutiny,  this  ever- 
present  influence  to  which  he  must  yield  while  he  fails  to  understand  it, 
breaks  down  with  a  completeness  that  ends  in  death.  The  Curate,  as  the 
watchful  and  critical  double,  is  thus — as  one  may  suppose — the  'dweller' 
on  the  Rector's  'threshold.'  The  Rector's  death  dissolves  the  bond  be- 
tween the  two  men;  the  Curate  reverts  at  once  to  his  original,  sequential 
state;  sincerely  mourns  the  loss  of  his  hero;  has  no  memory  of  the  insight 
into  the  Rector's  character  and  motives  that  he  gained  from  the  sittings; 
and  loses,  once  and  for  all,  the  foreign  personality  that  had  well  nigh  ousted 
his  proper  nature. 

That  is  the  story.  The  remaining  persons  of  the  drama  are  a  Professor 
who,  in  the  quest  of  scientific  fact,  devotes  himself  to  psychical  research, 
and  whose  watchwords  seem,  hitherto,  to  have  been  telepathy  and  nervous 
dyspepsia;  a  Gentleman  of  Independent  Means,  who  is  somewhat  more 
human  than  the  Professor,  but  shows  a  like  devotion,  and  has  worked  under 
the  Professor's  direction;  and  the  Rector's  Wife,  a  lady  whose  fate  it  is 
to  worship  at  the  shrine  of  masculine  success,  and  who  therefore,  after  an 
interlude  of  keen  dislike  of  the  Curate,  definitely  transfers  her  admiration 


BOOK  Reviews  453 

from  her  broken  husband  to  his  masterful  coadjutor.  The  Professor  is 
wont  to  refer  to  this  lady  as  the  Link,  though  her  connective  office  is  not 
clear;  the  confessions  of  the  Rector  to  the  Independent  Gentleman,  and 
of  the  Curate  to  the  Professor,  make  the  story  plain  enough  without  her. 

More  interesting  than  the  novel  itself  is  the  psychology  of  its  author. 
Why  did  he  write  it?  To  point  the  moral  that,  if  we  could  but  see  our- 
selves with  a  perfect  vision,  we  should  be  horrified  at  the  revelation?  But 
that  is  trite  morality;  and  most  readers,  it  may  be  assumed,  will  compare 
themselves  favorably  with  the  Reverend  Marcus  Harding.  To  plead  the 
cause  of  psychical  research,  on  the  ground  that  there  are  more  things  in 
heaven  and  earth  than  science  dreams  of?  But  an  imaginative  tale  will 
not  convince  any  who  are  not  convinced  already.  As  a  tour  de  force,  to 
prove  that  the  modern  novelist  can  make  plausible  use  of  the  'supernatural?' 
Perhaps:  the  title  seems  to  point  to  some  such  intention.  But  then — 
plausibility  is  a  relative  matter,  and  the  book  should  not  be  sent  for  review 
to  a  psychologist.  Wm.  Krskinb 

The  Evolution  of  Mind.  By  Joseph  McCabE.  London,  A.  &  C.  Black. 
New  York,  The  Macmillan  Co.,  1910.     pp.  xvii.,  287. 

In  this  fluently — at  times  brilliantly — written  essay,  Mr.  McCabe  seeks 
to  solve  the  cosmic  problem  of  the  birth  and  development  of  mind.  It 
is  usual,  he  tells  us,  to  postulate  two  evolutionary  series:  the  material, 
where  '  'all  varieties  of  energy  and  matter  arise  out  of  the  abysmal  womb 
of  ether,"  and  the  mental,  which  "set  in  when  the  earth  reached  a  certain 
stage  of  its  development."  Is  this  dualism  tenable?  When,  and  in  what 
form,  did  consciousness  first  appear?  Can  mind  be  brought  into  the  cosmic 
unity  by  tracing  its  gradual  emergence  from  the  etheric  matrix?  These 
are  the  questions  which  the  present  work  essays  to  answer. 

All  living  matter,  whether  plant  or  animal,  shows,  when  it  has  freedom 
of  movement,  two  properties  which  we  may,  if  we  will,  term  'mental'  or 
'psychical:'  namely,  sensitiveness  or  irritability  or  responsiveness  to 
stimulation,  and  spontaneous  or  self-initiated  movement.  But  sensi- 
tiveness is  also  a  widespread  attribute  of  inorganic  matter;  and  sponta- 
neous movement  always  turns  out,  on  careful  scrutiny,  to  be  a  response  to 
environmental  stimuli.  Here,  therefore,  is  no  evidence  of  consciousness; 
if  we  speak  of  'mind'  at  all,  we  are  stripping  the  word  of  the  distinctive 
significance  that  it  has  in  our  own  experience.  What  we  are  looking 
for  is  proof  of  consciousness. 

But  what,  then,  the  reader  may  ask,  is  consciousness?  "I  make  no 
attempt  to  define  consciousness,"  replies  our  author, "partly  because  it 
defines  itself  more  clearly  than  words  can  do,  partly  because  all  attempts 
to  define  it  have  proved  abortive."  Nevertheless,  he  knows  very  well 
what  he  is  in  search  of.  "The  question  to  be  answered  is  not,  can  we 
find  any  actions  in  a  lower  animal  which  are  consistent  with  a  theory  of 
consciousness,  but  can  we  find  any  which  are  inconsistent  with  a  purely 
neural  action.  The  question  of  consciousness  does  not  arise  till  then." 
"What  I  am  chiefly  seeking  to  determine  is  whether  a  new  reality,  or 
agency,  besides  ether,  intervenes  at  some  point  in  the  earth's  story." 
"The  plain  purpose  I  have  in  view  is  to  see  whether,  and  when,  a  new 
reality,  other  than  ether  and  its  products  or  aspects,  enters  into  the  tissue 
of  our  planetary  life."  And  so  he  works  up  the  scale  of  organic  evolution, 
and  reaches  one  negative  conclusion  after  another.  "There  is  no  proof 
that  consciousness  had  appeared  before  the  Devonian  period,  or  has  since 
developed  in  any  of  the  modern  representatives  of  Pre-Devonian  animals." 
'  'We  have  no  clear  or  cogent  indication  of  conscious  states  in  the  whole 
invertebrate  world,  or  in  any  type  of  animal  that  lived  before  the  Permian 
revolution  in  the  earth's  history,"  "We  have  not  found  a  single  pre- 
Tertiary  animal  whose  activities  cannot  be  explained  without  an  assump- 

JOURNAL — 9 


454  BOOK  REVIEWS 

tion  of  consciousness."     The  whole  history  so  far  is  a  history  of  the  progress 
of  mechanism. 

Of  course  it  is!  But  then,  so  is  the  subsequent  history,  that  of  man  in- 
cluded. Mr.  McCabe  is  the  victim  of  a  false  antithesis.  The  opposite 
of  conscious  is  unconscious, — not  mechanical  or  neural;  the  opposite  of 
reflex  or  automatic  is  complex  or  delayed, — not  conscious.  And  this 
criticism  holds,  on  any  definition  of  'consciousness.'  "Inferences  from 
external  manifestations  are  precarious,"  says  our  author.  One  may  reply 
that,  on  his  own  principles,  they  are  impossible;  for  external  manifestations 
can  never  give  evidence  of  a  new  reality,  different  from  ether;  they  must, 
just  because  they  are  external,  belong  wholly  and  solely  to  the  material 
sphere.  The  most  highly  deliberative  action  of  the  civilized  adult,  no  less 
than  the  simplest  tropism  of  the  unicellular  organism,  must  be  explicable, 
as  an  'etheric'  derivative,  in  physico-chemical  terms.  The  logic  of  this 
issue  is  so  elementary,  and  the  point  has  been  so  often  made,  that  one 
wonders  to  find  Mr.  McCabe  the  victim  of  the  pitfall. 

But  now,  for  Mr.  McCabe  as  for  all  of  us,  human  consciousness  is  a 
brute  fact,  and  all  the  ether  in  the  imiverse  cannot  away  with  it.  What  is 
to  be  done?  "I  submit  that  the  only  way  to  come  to  any  conclusion  is  to 
compare  the  organ  of  consciousness  in  ourselves  with  the  presumed  organ" 
in  other  creatures.  The  criterion,  therefore,  is  to  be  external,  after  all! 
The  fishes  have  an  archipallium;  possibly  then,  a  dull  glow  of  conscious- 
ness may  accompany  their  activities;  but  its  presence  is  disputable,  and 
its  nature  (if  it  is  present)  must  be  insubstantial.  The  part  of  the  brain 
which  in  higher  animals  is  associated  with  consciousness  is  in  the  amphibia 
and  reptiles  extremely  small,  and  cannot  with  any  confidence  be  regarded 
as  an  index  of  consciousness.  In  the  birds,  the  cerebral  hemispheres  have 
at  last  gained  conspicuously  on  the  other  parts  of  the  brain ;  here,  according- 
ly, we  may  assume  some  consciousness,  though  its  degree  must  remain  un- 
known.    Wherewith  we  pass  to  the  mammals,  and  are  on  firmer  ground. 

And  consciousness  itself?  '  'It  seems  to  me  quite  hopeless  to  speculate  on 
the  origin  of  consciousness,  so  long  as  its  organ  is  so  wrapped  in  obscurity. 
And  precisely  for  the  same  reason  I  decline  to  see  in  it  the  emergence  or 
accession  of  a  new  reality,  other  than  ether,  or  ether-compacted  nerve. 
Until  we  know  the  cortex  sufiiciently  well  to  say  that  its  structure  throws 
no  light  on  the  nature  of  consciousness,  the  question  must  be  left  open. 
At  present,  our  knowledge  of  the  cortex,  the  most  transcendently  important 
thing  that  science  approaches,  is  appallingly  meagre."  "It  is  the  most 
reprehensible  dogmatism  to  say  that  consciousness  may  not  have  arisen  in, 
and  be  a  function  of  it."  '  'Any  further  discussion  of  the  point  would  take 
us  into  metaphysical  considerations."  Apparently  it  would, — if  we  are 
not  in  the  realm  of  such  considerations  already. 

Here  the  general  argument  ends.  It  is  clear  that  Mr.  McCabe  is  at 
least  under  obligation  to  distinguish  between  the  two  current  uses  of 
the  term  'consciousness;'  to  say  whether,  for  him,  it  means  'awareness'  or 
whether  it  is  identical  with  'mind'  or  'mentality'  at  large.  It  is  clear,  too, 
that  he  has  not  fully  understood  his  authorities:  he  is  not  at  home  with 
Wundt's  theory  of  the  instinct,  or  with  Thomdike's  doctrine  of  free  ideas; 
and,  indeed,  his  conception  of  modem  psychology  seems  to  be  that  of  an 
objective  body  of  arguments  rather  than  that  of  a  group  of  empirical  and 
subjectively  verifiable  observations.  These,  however,  are  minor  points: 
the  great  fault  of  the  essay  is  the  logical  fallacy  which  we  have  noted  above. 

The  two  concluding  chapters,  on  the  Dawn  of  Humanity  and  the  Ad- 
vance of  Mind  in  Civilization,  presuppose  the  appearance  of  consciousness, 
and  need  not  be  discussed.  They,  like  all  the  book,  are  written  with  a 
nerve  and  swing  that  fascinate  the  reader.  Mr.  McCabe  has  an  unusually 
wide  range  of  knowledge,  and  a  delightful  style;  it  is  a  pity  that  his  great 
powers  of  popularization  are  not  exercised  by  a  more  logical  mind. 

P.  E.  Winter 


BOOK  REVIEWS  455 

Ueher  den  Traum:  experimental-psychologische  Untersuchungen.  Von  Dr. 
J,  MouRLY  VoLD,  well.  Professor  an  der  Universitat  Kristiania. 
Herausgegeben  von  O.  Klemm,  Privatdozent  an  der  Universitat 
Leipzig.  Erster  Band,  Leipzig,  J.  A.  Earth,  1910.  Pp.  xiii.,  435. 
With  portrait  of  the  author.     Price  Mk.  11. 

John  Mourly  Void,  professor  of  philosophy  in  the  university  of  Chris- 
tiania,  died  in  1907,  at  the  age  of  fifty-seven.  For  twenty-five  years, 
Mourly  Void  had  been  engaged  in  the  observation  of  dream  phenomena; 
some  of  his  results  are  published  in  articles,  in  the  Revue  de  I'  Hypnotisme  et 
de  la  Psychologie,  1896,  in  the  Zeitschrift  fiir  Psychiatrie,  1900,  and  especially 
in  the  Zeitschrift  jiir  Psychologie,  1897.  He  left,  at  his  death,  besides  a 
large  body  of  scattered  notes,  the  manuscript  (in  German  )  of  a  large  work 
on  the  experimental  study  of  dreams ;  the  first  volume  of  this  work,  edited 
by  Dr.  Klemm,  lies  before  us.  Dr.  Klemm  has,  no  doubt,  been  well- 
advised  to  print  the  manuscript  as  it  stood;  the  author's  German,  though 
not  always  idiomatic,  is  always  intelligible ;  and  while  the  book  might  have 
been  very  considerably  condensed,  the  reader  would  have  missed,  in  the 
abbreviated  form,  a  valuable  lesson  in  scientific  method.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  editor  should,  by  all  means,  have  supplied  an  index.  It  is  true 
that  index-making  is  mechanical  work;  but  then  it  is  also  mechanical 
work  of  the  expert  kind ;  and  if  an  editor  shrinks  from  it,  he  should  decline 
outright  the  editorial  duties. 

The  book  is,  as  we  have  said,  a  valuable  lesson  in  scientific  method. 
The  author  takes  us  painfully  and  point  by  point  through  all  the  difficul- 
ties of  dream-observation ;  shows  us  all  the  successive  improvements  in  his 
own  manner  of  working;  and  discusses  in  all  detail  the  interpretation  of 
dreams  experimentally  aroused  or  influenced.  His  method  is,  in  every 
sense,  comparative:  he  compares  the  experimental  dreams  with  dreams  of 
the  preceding  normal  night;  he  gathers  the  dreams  of  a  large  number  of 
practised  and  unpractised  observers, — of  several  hundred  university 
students  and  school  teachers  (both  sexes);  he  has,  to  fall  back  upon,  a 
personal  experience  that  is  probably  unequalled;  he  does  not  neglect  the 
comparison  of  the  dream  with  the  waking  state.  The  first  58  pages,  on 
method,  should  be  read  by  advanced  students  of  psychology,  whatever 
their  interest;  only  the  specialist,  we  fear,  will  read  critically  through  the 
remainder  of  the  book;  more  particularly  now  that  Freud's  interpretation 
of  the  dream-consciousness  has  turned  inquiry  in  a  difi^erent  direction. 
Yet  the  remainder,  though  it  fill  nearly  400  octavo  pages,  is  well  worth 
reading. 

The  experimental  dreams  here  reported  are  but  a  fraction  of  the  whole: 
they  are  dreams  whose  peripheral  motive  consisted  in  a  cutaneous-muscular 
stimulation  of  the  lower  extremities,  more  especially  of  the  ankles.  The 
first  of  the  two  principal  chapters  gives  an  account  of  experiments  in 
which  a  band  is  placed  about  the  left  ankle,  and  remains  in  position  all 
night;  the  resulting  dreams  are  compared  with  those  of  the  preceding 
normal  night.  In  other  experiments,  a  band  is  tied  around  sole  and  in- 
step, as  well  as  about  the  ankle ;  in  yet  others,  the  foot  is  encased  in  a  sock. 
Both  types  of  experiments  are,  in  one  case,  carried  to  the  point  of  habitua- 
tion. The  second  principal  chapter  gives  an  account  of  experiments  in 
which  the  two  ankles  are  separately  bound,  either  for  the  whole  night  or 
for  the  evening  only.  In  other  experiments,  the  two  ankles  are  not  only 
separately  bound,  but  are  also  tied  together  by  a  third  band.  The  result- 
ing dreams  are  compared  with  those  of  the  normal  nights,  and  also  with 
those  reported  in  the  preceding  chapter.  A  promised  Appendix,  on  the 
part  played  by  the  hip  joint  (p.  216),  is  not  mentioned  in  the  table  of 
contents  and  does  not  appear  in  the  text. 

The  net  result  of  the  investigation  can  best  be  shown  in  the  form  of  a 
Table, 


456  BOOK  REVIEWS 

I.     Ideas  of  pressure  and  temperature  are  aroused  only  in  slight  measure. 
II.     Motor  ideas  are  aroused  most  commonly. 

1.  a.  Free  active  movements  of  high  intensity  are  the  specific 
result  of  the  stimulus,  and  outweigh  in  number  all  the  other 
motor   ideas   put   together. 

b.     Parallel  movements  of  the  feet  cannot  with  certainty  be 
brought  into  connection  with  the  stimulus. 

2.  The  same  thing  holds  of  inhibited  movement. 

3.  Static  conditions  show  a  clear  causal  relation  to  the  stimulus; 
they  are  by  no  means  intensive,  yet  stand  in  number  next  after 
the  free  active  movements. 

4.  Passive  movements  of  the  whole  body  cannot  with  certainty  be 

related  to  the  stimulus. 

5.  Motor   objects    and 

6.  Abstract  motives  to  movement  are  causally  related  to  the 
stimulus,  though  they  are  dream-factors  that  rarely  appear  in 
isolation. 

III.     I.     Ideas  coincident  in  time  with  the  experiment  or  with  the  dis- 
cussion of  it  are  aroused  only  in  slight  measure. 
2.     The  unpleasurable  common    sensations  cannot  with  certainty 
be  attributed  to  the  operation  of  the  stimulus  alone;  the  free 
active  movements  were  accompanied  by  a  pleasurable  organic 
complex. 
This  meagre  statement  of  the  outcome  must  here  suffice.    We  may  expect, 
in  the  second  volume,  a  full  theoretical  discussion  of  the  dream-conscious- 
ness; meanwhile,  the  remarks  made  on  pp.  9  f.,  416  ff.,  are  significant. 
The  questionary  used  by  the  author  is   printed  on  pp.  31  ff.       J.  Field 

Parenthood  and  Race  Culture;  An  Outline  of  Eugenics.  Caleb  W.  Saleeby. 
Moffat,  Yard  and  Company,  New  York,   1909.     Pp.  xv,  389. 

This  book  lays  claim  to  the  distinction  of  being  the  first  to  survey  the 
whole  field  of  eugenics.  The  author  states  in  the  preface  that  there  is  need 
to-day  of  a  "general  introduction  to  eugenics  which  is  at  least  responsible;" 
and  adds  that  he  is  "indebted  to  more  than  one  pair  of  searching  and  illus- 
trious eyes,  ....  for  reading  the  proofs  of  this  volume."  The  present  dis- 
cussion, it  would  seem,  is  a  continuation  of  the  author's  previous  campaign 
of  advocacy.  Further,  the  book  is  to  be  regarded  as  an  exposition,  not  as 
a  contribution  of  original  material.  Dr.  Saleeby  seeks  to  review  and  arrange 
the  results  of  Galton  and  of  the  other  investigators;  still,  the  author  is 
himself  a  man  of  opinions,  and  he  devotes  much  space  to  his  own  particu- 
lar crotchets.  Unfortunately  the  book  is  swelled  by  some  tiu-gid  writing. 
It  stands  in  this  regard  in  strong  contrast  with  Galton's  own  condensed, 
close-knit  manner  of  utterance.  Had  the  present  volume  been  boiled  down 
to  half  its  size,  its  effectiveness  would  have  been  doubled. 

The  contents  are  divided  into  two  parts:  "The  Theory  of  Eugenics" 
(Part  I)  and  "The  Practice  of  Eugenics"  (Part  II).  Part  II  falls  into 
two  complementary  themes,  "negative"  and  "positive"  eugenics; — per- 
haps "restrictive "  and  "constructive"  would  have  been  better  terms.  Nega- 
tive eugenics,  as  the  author  defines  it,  seeks  to  discourage  the  parenthood 
of  the  least  desirable.  Positive  eugenics  is  the  effort  to  encourage  parent- 
hood on  the  part  of  the  most  desirable. 

Only  one  of  his  chief  tasks  does  Dr.  Saleeby  perform  with  thoroughness. 
That  task  is  destructive.  Errors  and  illusions  are  mercilessly  slaughtered. 
On  page  28,  the  author  sweeps  the  Nietzschean  view  of  selection  off  the 
boards.  The  superstition  of  maternal  impressions  is  quashed  on  page  128. 
Farther  along  Mr.  Bernard  Shaw's  erratic  proposals  for  a  stud-farm  to  be 
devoted  to  race-culture  are  dispatched.  It  is  shown  in  Chapter  X  that 
eugenics  does  not  propose  a  destruction  of  the  family;  that  it  endorses, 
indeed,  exalts  monogamy.     And  so  throughout.     The  tone  of  the  book  is 


BOOK  Reviews  457 

distinctly  controversial.  Unfortunately  the  author  over-reaches  himself. 
He  is  too  combative,  lacking  the  calm  temper  of  the  scientist.  He  assumes 
ignorance,  misconception  and  indifference  in  his  audience;  and  the  conse- 
quent attitude  of  defiance  is  at  times  unpleasant. 

Eugenic  endeavor,  declares  Dr.  Saleeby,  centres  about  "selection  for 
parenthood."  Parenthood  the  unfit  must  be  denied.  The  lowering  of  the 
death-rate  among  infants  (and  adults  as  well)  tends  to  keep  alive  until 
the  reproductive  age  many  inherently  weak  constitutions  which  reduce 
the  average  vitality  of  the  stock;  this  fact  emphasizes  the  need  of  man's 
further  interference  with  the  processes  of  selection.       * 

The  Chapters  on  "Heredity  and  Race  Culture"  and  "Education  and 
Race  Culture"  define  the  relative  importance  of  nature  and  nurture  and 
demonstrate  the  need  of  progressive  improvement  of  the  germ-plasm.  The 
section  on  "Lines  of  Eugenic  Education"  is  excellent,  although  it  should 
be  transposed  to  Part  II  of  the  book.  In  his  discussion  of  terminology. 
Dr.  Saleeby  appears  to  be  trying  to  clear  up  his  own  ideas,  and,  on  the  whole, 
he  succeeds.  Yet  it  is  rather  curious,  after  his  demand  that  "conceptional " 
be  substituted  for  "congenital,"  to  come  across  the  word  "congenital" 
(p.  20I,  near  bottom)  used  in  the  very  sense  which  the  writer  had  before 
violently  repudiated. 

The  author's  proposals  are  invariably  mild.  He  desires  no  revolution 
of  moral  or  marital  relations.  Motherlove,  he  thinks,  should  have  survival- 
value  in  the  minds  of  eugenists  to  the  same  degree  as  physique,  ability  and 
character.  "I  confess  myself  opposed  to  the  principle  of  bribing  a  woman 
to  become  a  mother,  whether  in  the  guise  of  State-aid  or  in  the  form  of 
eugenic  premiums  for  maternity."  Equally  repugnant  are  the  German 
projects  for  a  "eugenic"  universal  polygamy  and  polyandry  (echoes  of 
Plato!)  and  Chesterton's  definition  of  eugenics:  "that  people  should  be 
forcibly  married  to  each  other  by  the  police."  Monogamic  marriage  has 
survived  and  become  dominant  because  of  its  supreme  services  to  mother- 
hood, and  hence  to  the  race.  The  conclusion  is  that  the  best  form  of  sex- 
relation  secures  the  common  parental  care  of  the  offspring;  the  support  of 
motherhood  by  fatherhood. 

Society  must  prevent  propagation  of  the  criminal,  the  insane,  the  epi- 
leptic, and  the  feeble-minded.  Means  to  this  end,  however,  the  author 
leaves  undefined.  Permanent  detention  is  mentioned;  surgery  rejected. 
Although  Dr.  Saleeby  has  enormous  faith  in  the  'power  of  pubhc  opinion,' 
he  puts  little  trust  in  the  formal  embodiment  of  it — legislation. 

In  general,  it  is  true  that  acquired  characters,  or  modifications,  are  not 
inherited.  A  few  virulent  diseases  and  substances,  however,  sink  deeply 
enough  into  the  bodily  constitution  to  damage  the  germ-plasm.  In  such 
cases  the  offspring  suffer.  The  more  common  of  these  "racial  poisons, " 
as  Dr.  Saleeby  names  them,  are  alcohol,  lead,  narcotics  and  syphilis.  The 
discussion  of  racial  poisons,  though  inexcusably  prolix,  constitutes  one  of 
the  most  original  contributions  to  eugenic  literature  in  the  book. 

Nowhere  does  Dr.  Saleeby  speak  out  positively  enough  for  constructive 
eugenics.  He  says  rather  lukewarmly,  "positive  eugenics  must  largely 
take  the  form,  at  present,  of  removing  such  disabilities  as  now  weigh  upon 
the  desirable  members  of  the  community,  especially  the  more  prudent 
sort."  Surely  this  is  not  the  utterance  of  a  soldier  in  the  "moral  crusade" 
for  children  which  Professor  Karl  Pearson  emphasizes.  In  this  connection 
a  line  from  Galton  is  apropos:  "The  possibility  of  improving  the  race  or  a 
nation  depends  on  the  power  of  increasing  the  productivity  of  the  best 
stock.  This  is  far  more  important  than  that  of  repressing  the  productivity 
of  the  worst."  The  present  book  disagrees  with  Galton,  not  overtly  but 
implicitly. 

Eugenics,  for  Dr.  Saleeby,  is  the  final  arbiter  of  all  disputes.  He  cares 
not  whether  a  "proposal  is  socialistic,  individualistic,  or  anything  else"  so 
long  as  it  is  eugenic.     "When  by  means  of  eugenics  we  give  education  the 


458  BOOK  REVIEWS 

right  materials  to  work  upon  we  shall  have  a  Utopia,  and  as  for  forms  of 
government  they  may  be  left  for  fools  to  contest."  Here  we  have  the 
ardor  of  the  reformer,  bordering  on  fanaticism !  Eugenics  the  only  salva- 
tion! This  kind  of  enthusiasm  seems  to  be  responsible  for  many  of  the 
faults  of  the  book. 

The  volume  is,  without  doubt,  suitable  for  popular  consumption.  If 
it  is  verbose,  it  is,  in  the  main,  clear.  If  it  hammers  and  scolds,  it  meets 
enough  opposition  and  inertia  to  justify  its  censoriousness.  If  certain 
details  are  questionable,  the  main  outline  is  reliable.  It  will  help,  not 
hurt,  the  eugenic  propaganda.  Nevertheless,  it  cannot  be  regarded  as 
a  definitive  exposition  of  eugenics  as  that  science  at  present  stands.  It 
should  be  superseded  before  long  by  a  far  abler  treatise.    C.  R.  Hugins. 

Cornell  University. 

The  Science  of  Poetry  and  the  Philosophy  of  Language,  by  Hudson  Maxim. 
New  York,  Funk  &  Wagnalls  Company,  1910.     pp.  XIII  +  294. 

The  core  of  this  book  is  that  language  both  expresses  and  impresses 
thought  (p.  84).  Thought  may  be  so  abstract  that  it  cannot  be  expressed 
except  in  the  most  literal  way ;  again,  it  can  be  figuratively  expressed.  The 
latter  gives  poetry  (Chap.  Ill,  IV).  Poetry  is  non-emotional  (Chap.  Ill, 
IV);  it  is  also  what  separates  man  from  the  brute  (Chap.  II).  Language 
impresses  thought,  on  the  other  hand,  by  the  moving  power  of  sound.  Here 
is  the  source  of  all  emotion  in  letters  (Chap.  V).  This  power  can  be  assigned 
largely  to  the  four  properties  of  sound,  each  of  which  is  connected 
with  a  specific  phase  of  emotion  and  is  traced  by  analysis  to  a  physiologi- 
cal process  (Chap.  I,  VI,  VII) ;  indeed,  everything  mental  is  physiological 
(Chap.  I).  This  impressiveness  is  given  the  name  potentry  (Chap.  V),  a 
word  that  carries  in  its  train  a  new  nomenclature  for  all  varieties  of  lin- 
guistic arts,  to  a  treatment  of  which  later  chapters  are  devoted.  From  the 
tone  of  the  whole  book,  one  judges  that  science  is  the  panacea  for  all 
mysticism;  those  who  see  anything  mysterious  in  poetry  are  belabored 
right  and  left  with  much  ridicule. 

In  its  foundation  principles  the  book  is  dogmatically  materialistic.  Surely 
much  may  be  said  against  consciousness  being  a  physiological  process 
merely.  And  while  it  is  true  that  "consciousness  is  the  sense  of  awareness 
of  the  other  senses"  (p.  i),  it  is  also  aware  of  more  than  the  psychical  ele- 
ments into  which  it  can  be  resolved.  This  principle  holds  with  the  analy- 
sis of  all  compounds;  and  the  failure  to  see  it  gives  a  false  tone  to  the 
whole  book.  No  one  will  deny  that  "there  is  a  science  of  poetry"  (p.  44), 
but  there  is  something  in  poetry  which  eludes  us  if  we  analyze  it  scientifi- 
cally. Let  men  try  to  tell  just  what  any  familiar  substance  really  is ;  their 
statements  will  be  as  mysterious  as  the  definitions  of  poetry  criticised  by 
Mr.  Maxim  from  the  standpoint  of  science.  The  quarrel  then  is  not  with 
those  who  find  a  touch  of  mystery  in  poetry,  but  with  those  who,  taking  their 
own  restricted  view  of  experience  for  the  whole  of  it,  refuse  to  countenance 
the  revelations  of  that  experience  from  any  other  viewpoint.  There  has  been 
no  "coalition  against  the  scientific  investigation  of  poetry"  (p.  191).  but 
Mr.  Maxim  does  not  see  the  significance  of  admitting  (p.  44)  Coleridge's 
claim,  that  poetry  is  the  antithesis  of  science.  For  science  seeks  the 
relations  of  experience  apart  from  subjectivity,  is  objective;  poetry — 
an  art — expresses  experience  linked  with  life,  is  subjective.  One's  attitude 
to  bread  when  he  is  hungry  (p.  66)  is  quite  different  from  his  attitude  of 
curiosity  as  to  the  chemical  constituents  of  bread;  the  latter  gives  us 
science,  is  intellectual;  the  other  gives  us  art,  is  emotional.  Poetry  is  a 
form  of  art.  The  fundamental  unsoundness  of  the  whole  book  then  in  its 
treatment  of  poetry  is  evident  in  the  statement  that  "as  we  go  away  from  the 
emotions  and  in  the  direction  of  thought  at  the  expense  of  emotion  .... 
the  more  poetry  we  get"  (p.  66) ;  this  is  in  the  direction  of  science  and  gives 
us,  not  poetry,  but  mathematics — the  multiplication  table.     This  antithe- 


BOOK  REVIEWS  459 

sis  of  poetry  and  science  gives  to  many  of  the  statements  about  poetry 
quoted  in  the  book  under  review  a  relevancy  not  to  be  broken  by  the 
cheap  playing  to  gullibility  that  characterizes  much  of  Mr.  Maxim's 
criticism  of  them.  (See,  for  instance,  Chapter  IV,  bottom  of  page  51.) 
Poetry  is  not  then  the  expression  of  mere  ideas  (p.  91).  The  use  of  trope 
itself  implies  a  heightened  idea.  The  source  of  the  moving  power  of  any 
poetry  worth  the  name  must  lie  primarily  in  a  certain  enthusiasm  of  the 
personality.  Remove  this  and  poetry  is  gone.  It  was  this  ardor  of  life  the 
Greeks  symbolized  in  Pegasus ;  Mr.  Maxim  has  tamed  Pegasus,  but  he  has 
killed  poetry. 

The  theory  that  language  both  expresses  and  impresses  thought  is  not 
after  all  so  brand-new.  Men  in  reality  have  taken  this  for  granted.  Every 
idea  has  some  feeling  tone, — every  sound  some  power  to  attract  the  hearer. 
This  is  admitted  (p.  80).  Moreover,  ideas  assume  naturally  the  form 
best  fitted  both  to  express  and  impress  themselves,  giving  us  the  poles  of 
science  and  art  according  as  we  emphasize  intellect  or  personality.  Looked 
at  from  the  standpoint  of  its  impressiveness,  language  has  long  been  known 
as  the  pleasure-giving  art  of  letters.  In  this  pleasingness  lies  what  Mr. 
Maxim  calls  the  impressive  power  of  language, — "the  conversion  of  energy 
into  pleasurable  emotions,  which  serve  to  energize  perceptions  (p.  79)." 
Where  then  is  the  need  for  coining  the  word  potentry  and  all  that  rigmarole 
of  nomenclature  that  depends  on  it?  Better  to  have  called  a  much  needed 
attention  to  the  practical  value  of  art. 

The  valuable  part  of  the  book  discusses  this  impressive  power  of  language 
(Chap.  V,  VII,  VIII).  The  four  properties  of  sound — loudness,  duration, 
pitch  and  timbre — are  linked  with  specific  phases  of  emotion;  loudness  and 
duration  with  importance;  pitch  with  intensity;  and  timbre  with  pleasure 
and  pain  (Chap.  VII).  The  theory  is  suggestive,  but  lacks — especially 
that  timbre  expresses  pleasure  and  pain — scientific  confirmation.  Spencer 
is  followed  largely,  but  Chap.  V  links  to  his  principle  of  economy  the  need 
for  added  expenditure  of  energy  in  impressiveness  of  utterance.  Spencer 
says  the  vocal  apparatus  should  be  simple  and  do  its  work  with  the  least 
expenditure  of  energy.  Maxim  would  say,  Use  economically  as  much 
energy  as  you  like,  so  long  as  it  produces  pleasurable  emotions  with  the 
thought  conveyed.  Both  practice  economy;  Maxim  does  additional 
business  in  another  field.  This  is  very  important  and  valuable,  but  Mr. 
Maxim  does  not  see  (i)  that  he  is  here  in  the  province  of  art  as  opposed  to 
science,  and  (2)  that  the  principle  of  economy  is  here  applied  only  in 
the  very  loosest  way,  if  at  all.  Science  looks  at  the  apple  and  finds 
economy.  Think  though  of  the  blossoms  that  do  not  fructify.  This, 
too,  is  nature.  What  economy  of  energy  is  in  the  play  of  a  healthy  boy? 
Or  in  his  work  either,  if  he  enjoy  it?  Nature  plays  and  works,  better 
plays  in  work.  Art  in  literature  corresponds  to  this  play.  In  giving  Mac- 
beth six  Imes  to  ask  the  doctor  a  question  easily  expressed  in  six  words,  the 
artist  reveals  a  healthy  natural  indifference  to  any  law  of  mere  parsimony 
in  speech.  In  the  utterance  of  science  there  may  be  economy  of  energy; 
a  certain  generosity  characterizes  the  larger  utterance  of  art. 

Chap.  VII  also  gives  a  theory  of  rhythm,  which  Spencer  did  not  attempt. 
Rhythm  is  the  ebb  and  flow  of  nerve  impulse  according  as  muscles  are 
contracted  or  relaxed.  "The  beats  of  the  verse  are  in  harmony  with  the 
beats  of  the  nerve  spasms  which  the  nerve  potential  of  passion  tends  to 
induce"  (p.  147).  "Under  emotion,  then,  vocal  phenomena  must  necessa- 
rily be  rhythmical."  The  theory  is  not  conclusive.  No  reason  is  given  for 
the  fact  that  the  tension  and  relaxation  of  muscles  is  regular  in  poetical 
rhythm  and  irregular  in  that  of  prose.  How  account,  moreover,  for  the 
rhythm  of  the  wheels  on  the  rail  joints  to  the  unmoved  passenger?  The 
theory  also  implies  an  unsatisfactory  explanation  of  time.  The  feelings  of 
muscular  contraction  and  relaxation  are  themselves  in  time:  to  conclude 


I 


460  BOOK  REVIEWS 

then  that  these  are  the  data  of  our  feeling  of  time  seems  to  be  begging  the 
question. 

The  book  contributes  nothing  to  the  problem  of  the  origin  of  language. 
In  taking  the  position  that  the  use  of  trope  and  not  articulate  language 
separates  man  from  the  animals  (Chapter  II),  it  seems  to  be  using  articulate 
in  the  sense  of  uttered,  spoken;  but  what  men  mean  by  articulate  speech 
when  they  deny  it  to  animals  is  that  orderly  grouping  of  words  correspond- 
ing to  ideas  articulated  logically  so  as  to  produce  an  intended  end.  It  is 
true  animals  do  not  use  metaphor;  it  is  almost  equally  evident  they  do 
not  form  concepts, — the  first  requisite  in  reasoning.  Nor  is  the  discussion 
of  the  development  of  speech  in  the  race  in  the  least  fruitful.  The  develop- 
ment of  the  child  linguistically  contributes  little  to  our  knowledge  of  that 
general  development;  for  there  is  no  meaning  to  the  babblings  of  an  infant 
until  the  mother  has  by  gestures  or  in  other  ways  aroused  an  association 
in  the  child's  mind  between  certain  sounds  and  certain  objects.  The 
statement,  "Every  mother  in  the  world,  of  whatever  race,  can  understand 
the  baby  talk  of  any  child  of  the  race"  (p.  20)  is  in  its  extravagance  typical 
of  the  book.  Much  less  space,  indeed,  might  have  expressed  all  that  is 
valuable  in  it  either  as  science  or  as  poetry.  Marlow  A.  Shaw. 

State  University  of  Iowa. 

(i)     Les  degenerescences  auditives.     Par  A.  Marie.     1909.     pp.   iii. 

(2)  Reeducation  physique  et  psychique.     Par  H.  Lavrand.     1909.    pp.123. 

(3)  Les  f dies  a  eclipse.     Par  Lkgrain.     19 id.     pp.  120. 

(4),  (5)  Les  rives  et  leur  interpretation.      Par  P.  Meunibr  et  R.  MassElon. 

1910.    pp.  213. 
(6)     La  suggestion  et  ses  limites.     Par  BajEnopf  et  OssiPOPif.    191 1.    pp. 

119. 
(7),  (8)     La  psychologic  de  I'attention.     Par  N.  Vaschide  et  R.  MeuniKR. 
1910.     pp.  199. 

These  six  volumes  form  nos.  12-19  of  the  Bibliotheque  de  Psychologic 
experimentale  et  de  Metapsychie,  edited  by  Dr.  Raymond  Meunier  and  issued 
by  the  Librairie  Bloud  et  Cie  of  Paris. 

(i)  Dr.  Marie,  senior  physician  at  the  Asile  de  Villejuif,  published  in 
1908  (as  no,  3  of  the  present  series)  a  little  book  entitled  L' Audition  morhide, 
in  which  he  briefly  discussed  the  pathological  physiology  of  hearing  in 
cases  of  mental  and  nervous  disease.  The  work  before  us  is  concerned  with 
the  principal  anatomical  anomalies  of  the  peripheral  or  central  auditory 
apparatus.  After  a  general  introduction,  treating  of  the  diJBficulties  of 
diagnosis,  the  diagnostic  value  of  symptoms,  etc.,  the  author  takes  up  in 
order,  from  without  inwards,  the  various  divisions  of  the  auditory  mech- 
anism. To  the  chapter  on  the  external  and  middle  ear  he  contributes  a 
table  of  auricular  measurements,  with  their  craniological  complements. 
The  chapter  on  the  internal  ear  is  sketchy;  in  particular,  the  problem  of 
heredity  should  have  been  approached  in  the  light  of  the  Mendelian  hy- 
pothesis. In  the  chapter  on  central  lesion  and  cortical  hearing,  the  author 
quotes,  apparently  with  approval,  the  opinion  of  Dr.  P.  Marie  that  isolated 
sensory  aphasia,  and  especially  pure  verbal  deafness,  does  not  occur.  He 
here  describes  a  case  (with  autopsy)  of  dementia  with  motor  verbal  aphasia, 
agraphia  to  dictation,  and  verbal  deafness.  A  final  chapter  deals  with 
arrest  of  auditory  development,  physical  and  mental.  Dr.  Marie  insists 
strongly  on  the  necessity  of  a  precise  diagnosis  of  the  cause  of  deaf-mutism, 
and  pleads  for  systematic  education  of  such  patients  as  are  educable.  It 
seems  clear  that  the  appeal  to  public  sentiment  made  in  this  chapter  was 
the  author's  chief  motive  in  writing  the  book. 

(2)  According  to  Dr.  Lavrand,  who  is  professor  at  Lille,  mind  and  body 
are  not  separate  and  separable  phenomena,  but  constitute  a  'substantial 
unity' ;  mind  therefore  acts  upon  body,  body  upon  mind.  There  is,  indeed, 
a  constant  interaction  among  all  organic  functions,  the  conscious  included; 


BOOK  R^VmWS  461 

and  since  the  symptoms  of  functional  disturbance  far  outrun,  in  most  cases, 
the  actual  lesion  of  the  organism,  there  is  good  hope  of  a  successful  re- 
education. The  model  for  this  is,  of  course,  given  with  the  primary  process, 
that  of  education;  the  author  accordingly  outlines  the  genesis  of  ideas  in 
the  child,  the  growth  in  complexity  of  bodily  movements,  and  the  co- 
function  of  ideas  and  movements  in  what  he  calls  psychomotor  acts;  he 
finally  formulates  the  end  of  education  as  the  transformation  of  conscious 
and  attentively  executed  actions  into  subconscious  or  automatic  activity. 
Passing  from  theory  to  practice,  he  first  takes  up  the  question  of  mental 
reeducation,  i.  e.,  of  the  effect  of  psychotherapeutics  upon  various  forms  of 
mental  disorder,  from  hysteria  down  to  a  practically  normal  psychasthenia. 
Next  follows  a  chapter  on  motor  reeducation, — locomotor  ataxia,  paralysis, 
tics,  speech  derangements,  aphasia,  deaf-mutism, — which  contains  much 
empirical  material,  plainly  of  the  writer's  own  observation.  Dr.  Lavrand 
then  proceeds  to  discuss  sensory  reeducation,  with  special  reference  to 
Rousselot's  method  of  treating  deafness;  organic  reeducation,  with  refer- 
ence to  imaginary  dyspepsia;  respiratory  reeducation,  with  reference  to 
the  alleviation  of  asthma;  and  ends  with  a  brief  mention  of  circulatory 
reeducation,  and  of  the  reeducation  (or  rather  education)  of  the  idiot 
by  Bourneville's  method. 

(3)  The  third  volume  on  our  list,  from  the  pen  of  Dr.  Legrain,  senior 
physician  of  the  hospitals  for  the  insane  in  the  Department  of  Seine,  is 
mainly  taken  up  with  the  symptomatology  of  what  the  author  terms 
eclipsed  insanities.  There  is,  says,  Dr.  Legrain,  between  the  conscious 
and  the  unconscious,  a  wide  region  of  subconsciousness;  it  is  manifest  in 
the  phenomena  of  instinct  and  habit,  and  covers  the  whole  field  of  the 
forgotten.  This  subconsciousness  is  not  inactive;  it  has  its  own  life  and 
activity,  even  though  it  does  not  come  to  consciousness.  Wherever,  now, 
there  is  mental  disorder  involving  hallucinatory  experiences,  the  contents 
of  the  hallucination  may  disappear  into  the  subconscious;  the  patient  is 
then  not  cured,  though  he  is  free  of  the  obsessing  ideas ;  the  hallucinations 
are  under  eclipse,  but  may  emerge  again.  (A  second  volume  is  to  be  de- 
voted to  this  fact  of  resuscitation.)  The  impermanence  of  the  cure  is 
favored  by  general  mental  weakness;  and  the  condition  of  eclipse  is  evi- 
denced by  the  fact  that  the  hallucinations  are  accepted  by  the  apparently 
normal  patient  as  real  items  of  past  experience.  In  conclusion,  the  author 
recommends  to  experimental  psychologists  the  study  of  the  hallucinatory 
idea,  especially  under  the  headings  of  strength  and  duration  of  impression. 

(4),  (5)  The  work  of  Drs.  Meunier  and  Masselon,  on  dreams  and  their 
interpretations,  opens  with  a  psychological  analysis,  couched  in  general 
terms,  of  the  nature  and  sources  of  the  dream-consciousness.  The  writers 
regard  all  dreams,  except  those  that  appear  in  the  hypnagogic  state  just 
before  or  after  sleep,  as  in  some  measure  pathological.  They  attach 
special  importance  to  dreams  of  coenaesthetic  or  organic  origin,  which 
are  of  two  kinds:  in  the  one  case,  the  organic  derangement  is  clearly 
localized,  and  the  dream-images  bear  directly  upon  it;  in  the  other,  the 
organic  state  is  intellectualized  by  way  of  a  diffuse  emotion,  and  the  dream- 
images  are  emotively  suggested.  These  dreams  constitute  "a  veritable 
microscope  of  sensibility;  they  throw  into  relief  slight  disturbances  that 
escape  the  notice  of  the  waking  consciousness."  A  review  of  drearns  in 
general  pathology,  in  infections  and  intoxications,  in  neurotic  conditions, 
and  in  the  various  forms  and  stages  of  insanity — this  review  makes  up  the 
body  of  the  book — shows,  in  fact,  that  they  may  reveal  a  functional  dis- 
turbance which  is  not  apparent  in  the  waking  life,  and  which  may  be  the 
indication  either  of  some  organic  disease  or  of  a  hitherto  latent  mode  of 
mental  disequilibration.  Dreams  are  thus  a  touchstone  of  the  stability 
of  the  psychophysical  organism.  If  they  are  ordinarily  neglected,  in  prog- 
nosis, this  is  only  because  they  are  considered  too  delicate  and  too  variable 
a  reagent  for  the  physician's  purpose.     In  fact,  however,  there  are  certain 


462  BOOK  REVIEWS 

characters  that  make  them  available.  There  is  jSrst  of  all  distress,  especially 
when  intense  (as  terror)  and  sharply  localized  (as  physical  pain);  this 
may  lead  to  the  sleeper's  actual  arousal  in  the  middle  of  the  night;  and 
the  arousal,  if  really  due  to  the  distress,  is  unquestionably  a  pathological 
symptom.  The  homogeneity  of  the  dream,  shown  perhaps  in  the  recur- 
rence of  leading  motives,  is  also  evidence  of  the  persistence  of  the  causal 
substrate.  The  stereotyped  dream  attests  the  presence  of  an  identical 
cause,  organic  or  psychic,  which  exerts  its  influence  at  recurrent  intervals 
of  time.  (The  writers  emphasize  the  importance  of  this  phenomenon  of 
stereotypism  of  dreams,  and  devote  a  special  chapter  to  its  consideration.) 
The  fact  that  a  dream  is  remembered  on  waking  is  also  significant.  The 
contents  of  the  dream,  finally,  must  always  be  taken  into  account.  No 
one  of  these  characters,  it  is  true,  stamps  the  condition  of  the  dreamer  as 
at  all  gravely  pathological ;  but  each  and  all  of  them  point  to  an  anomaly, 
to  a  nervous  susceptibility,  and  so  suggest  a  closer  study  of  the  patient's 
bodily  and  mental  state.  In  a  word,  dreams  have  a  very  real  prognostic 
value;  but  they  are  indicative  only,  and  not  demonstrative;  and  the  indi- 
cation should  not  be  acted  upon  till  it  has  been  confirmed  by  other  and  more 
technical  methods  of  examination. 

(6)  Professor  Bajenoff  and  Dr.  Ossipoff,  leading  alienists  of  Moscow, 
write  upon  the  facts  and  theories  of  suggestion.  The  six  chapters  which 
make  up  the  book,  entitled  respectively  the  history  of  hypnosis  and  sugges- 
tion, psychological  automatism,  hypnotism  and  suggestion,  collective 
suggestion,  current  theories  of  therapeutic  theory,  and  the  psychological 
mechanism  of  suggestion,  contain  little  more  than  a  brief  resume  of  the 
work  done  and  the  views  expressed  by  other  investigators ;  but  the  authors 
command  a  clear  and  vivid  style,  and  have  the  happy  knack  of  literary 
illustration, — as  when  they  draw  upon  certain  of  Tolstoi's  characters  to 
exemplify  the  procedure  of  psychotherapy.  The  central  aim  of  the  book 
is  the  divorcement  of  suggestion  from  hypnosis.  Suggestion  is  not  the 
essential  characteristic  of  hypnosis;  it  may  be  exerted  more  effectually 
in  the  waking  state  (p.  ii).  It  is  ordinarily  supposed  that  the  subject  in 
profound  hypnosis  is  peculiarly  liable  to  suggestion;  "this  opinion  is  ab- 
solutely erroneous"  (p.  36).  Hypnotic  suggestion  has  its  definite  limits 
(pp.  39  ff.,  114);  while  suggestibility  itself  is  a  psychophysiological  phe- 
nomenon of  practically  universal  occurrence  (pp.  58,  112).  The  mechanism 
of  suggestion  is  described,  schematically,  as  '  'the  disaggregation  of  psychical 
activity,  the  rupture  of  the  normal  co-ordination  and  subordination  of  the 
elements  of  the  mental  life,  and,  as  a  result,  the  more  or  less  complete 
dissociation  of  the  personality"  (pp.  35,  113)- 

(7),  (8)  The  Psychology  of  Attention,  written  in  collaboration  with  the 
late  Dr.  Vaschide  by  Dr.  R.  Meunier,  psychopathologist  at  the  Asile  de 
Villejuif,  is  a  companion  volume  to  the  Pathology  0}  Attention  (no.  5  of  this 
series)  published  by  the  same  authors  in  1908.  It  is  not  a  text-book  in 
the  psychology  of  attention;  the  writers'  intention  is  at  once  narrower  and 
wider  than  that  of  the  compiler;  they  present,  first,  a  report  of  carefully 
selected  experimental  data,  and  on  the  basis  of  this  approved  material  they 
rise  to  an  inclusive  theory  of  attention  in  dynamic  terms.  The  first  two 
chapters  discuss  the  technique  of  the  study  of  attention  and  the  results  of 
experimental  investigation;  the  reader — unless  he  recall  the  contents  of 
the  previous  volume — will  be  surprised  to  find  that  the  great  bulk  of  the 
space  is  given  to  the  reaction  experiment.  However,  the  complete  pro- 
gramme of  an  experimental  enquiry  would  cover,  in  the  authors'  judgment, 
ten  tests;  those  of  cutaneous  sensitivity,  of  muscular  strength  voluntarily 
exerted,  of  speed  of  movement,  of  voluntary  attention  (canceUing  letters, 
discrimination  of  forms  applied  to  wrist  or  palm,  grasp  of  the  sense  of  a 
printed  page  by  a  rapid  glance  over  it),  of  color- vision  and  extent  of  the 
visual  field,  of  audition  and  extent  of  the  auditory  field,  of  rapidity  of 
thought  (reaction  experiment  in  various  forms),  of  memory  of  words  and 


BOOK  REVIEWS  463 

figures,  of  mental  arithmetic,  and  of  association  of  ideas.  '  'The  examina- 
tion of  a  subject  by  means  of  these  ten  experimental  series  will  show  that 
it  is  possible  to  catch  the  attention  at  work,  to  seize  its  dynamic  character. 
And  theoretical  conceptions  will  in  so  far  be  modified"  (p.  61).  It  seems 
to  the  reviewer  that  some  of  the  tests  would  require  a  great  deal  of  psycho- 
logical interpretation  before  they  could  be  turned  to  account  for  the  char- 
acterization of  attention;  at  all  events,  the  writers  do  not  justify  their 
statement.  Chapter  3,  on  attention  during  sleep,  reports  an  experimental 
study  (made  by  Vaschide)  of  the  ability  to  wake  at  a  set  time  in  the  morning. 
Out  of  40  chosen  subjects,  of  different  sex,  age  (20  to  76),  occupation, 
education  and  nationality,  33  proved  available  for  the  test.  The  tendency 
was  to  wake  too  early;  the  amount  of  error,  for  26  subjects,  was  in  rough 
average  21  minutes;  the  error  might,  however,  be  as  great  as  an  hour  and 
a  half,  and  might  reduce  to  12  seconds.  The  chapter  gives  many  interest- 
ing facts,  objective  and  introspective,  but  offers  no  connected  theory  of  the 
phenomenon.  Ch.  4,  on  suggestibility  and  attention,  reports  Binet's  ex- 
periments on  the  suggestibility  of  school-children  (lines,  weights),  and 
concludes  that,  while  there  is  no  direct  relation  between  suggestibihty  and 
attention,  suggestibility  may  be  considered  as  a  state  of  emotive  dis- 
turbance, the  first  effect  of  which  is  a  disturbance  of  attention.  Ch.  5, 
on  hypnosis  and  attention,  is  mainly  occupied  with  an  account  of  Beaunis' 
well-known  experiments.  No  theory  of  hypnosis  is  at  present  possible; 
it  is,  however,  characterized  rather  by  paraprosexia  than  by  hyperprosexia, 
— that  is,  if  the  reviewer  understands  these  terms,  rather  by  diversion  of 
attention  than  by  extreme  concentration  of  attention, — and  by  a  high  devel- 
opment of  the  'forces  of  automatic  attention.'  Ch.  6  reviews  and  criticises 
the  prevailing  theories  of  attention,  imder  the  rubrics  peripheral,  motor, 
affective  (Ribot,  Bain),  and  sensory,  voluntaristic,  perceptive,  central 
(Marillier,  Kreibig,  Rageot,  Nayrac).  The  authors  conclude  that  attention 
is  intimately  related  to  emotion ;  that  it  is  a  phenomenon  of  central  origin ; 
and  that  it  is  essentially  a  dynamic  function.  "It  is  to  the  intellect  what 
reflex  irritability  is  to  the  nervous  system;  it  is  not  a  state,  but  an  act." 
Let  us  hope  that  they  find  this  conclusion  satisfactory! — 

As,  now,  we  glance  back  over  this  series  of  books,  we  realize  that,  while 
they  leave  much  to  be  desired  on  the  score  of  systematic  presentation,  they 
are  none  the  less  readable  and  valuable,  since  every  writer  has  some  per- 
sonal contribution  to  make  to  the  existing  stock  of  knowledge.  A  good 
part  of  the  contents  strikes  the  reader  as  perfunctory;  but  there  is  always 
some  central  chapter  which  brings  new  material  or  original  ideas.  Whether, 
under  these  circumstances,  it  is  worth  while  to  publish  books  rather  than 
special  articles  is,  perhaps,  a  question  of  taste;  the  reviewer,  for  his  part, 
would  prefer  to  dispense  with  the  second-hand  discussions. 

The  proof-reading  is  usually  poor.  The  punctuation  is  erratic;  the 
line-divisions  show  such  monstrosities  as  ins-upportahle,  o-hservation;  and 
names  are  massacred  (Et.  Slonon  for  E.  E.  Slosson,  etc.). 

James  Field 

The  World  of  Dreams,  by  Havelock  Ellis.  Boston  &  New  York, 
Houghton  Mifflin  Company,  1911.  pp.  xii.,  288.  Price  $2.00  net. 
There  are  at  least  four  different  ways,  Mr.  Ellis  tells  us,  of  writing  a 
book  on  dreams.  There  is  the  literary  method,  which  may  be  dismissed  at 
once  as  wholly  unscientific;  there  is  the  clinical  method,  followed  for  in- 
stance by  de  Sanctis  in  his  /  Sogni;  there  is  the  experimental  method,  of 
which  Mourly  Void  has  recently  given  us  an  excellent  example;  and  there 
is  the  introspective  method,  for  a  special  form  of  which  we  are  referred, 
rather  curiously,  to  Freud's  Traumdeutung.  However,  we  need  not  split 
hairs  about  classification.  The  field  of  dreams  is,  in  fact,  the  playground 
of  all  sorts  of  psychological  opinion ;  the  time  has  not  yet  come  for  anything 
like  a  final  synthesis;  and  so  long  as  an  author  appeals  to  actual  observa- 


464  BOOK   REVIEWS 

tion,  and  so  long  as  he  takes  up  a  definite  position  with  regard  to  the  phe- 
nomena observed,  we  may  be  grateful  for  what  he  gives  us.  Mr.  Ellis  has 
been  noting  down  his  dream-experiences  for  more  than  twenty  years,  and 
in  the  present  volume  throws  the  outcome  of  his  studies  into  popular  form. 
Let  us  see  what  his  standpoint  is. 

Perhaps  the  first  question  that  one  asks  of  a  writer  upon  dreams  is  that 
of  his  attitude  to  the  Subconscious.  There  is,  indeed,  no  question  upon 
which  the  psychologists  of  this  generation  are  more  sharply  divided ;  there 
is  also  no  question  which  more  imperatively  demands  a  positive  and  clear- 
cut  reply;  either  one  explains  the  conscious  by  a  subconscious  which  is 
still  mental,  or  one  draws  the  line  of  mind  at  the  boundary  of  consciousness 
itself.  Mr.  Ellis  seeks  the  middle  way,  where  the  faring  is  least  secure. 
Consciousness  is  for  him — as  for  the  definers  of  the  term  in  the  Dictionary 
of  Philosophy  and  Psychology — 'the  distinctive  character  of  whatever  may 
be  called  mental  life.'  Subconscious  is  for  the  Dictionary  'not  clearly 
recognized  in  a  present  state  of  consciousness,  yet  entering  into  the  devel- 
opment of  subsequent  states  of  consciousness,' — a  definition  that  is 
obviously  equivocal,  and  that  is  immediately  particularized.  Mr.  Ellis 
cites  it  without  comment,  adding  only  that  subconscious  states  are  'slightly, 
partially,  or  imperfectly  conscious, '  and  that  "any  objection  to  so  precise 
and  convenient  a  term  ( !)  seems  to  belong  to  the  sphere  of  personal  idiosyn- 
crasy" (p.  4).  What  then  does  the  term  precisely  mean?  Consciousness 
covers,  by  definition,  the  whole  of  the  mental  life;  is  the  subconscious  not- 
mental?  No:  it  is  slightly,  partially  mental,  or  imperfectly  mental.  But, 
if  it  is  the  former,  is  the  remaining  'part'  of  it  material?  Then,  surely,  our 
author's  objection  to  'dispositions  of  brain  cells'  falls  to  the  ground.  Or, 
if  it  is  the  latter,  can  Mr.  Ellis  explain  how  a  phenomenon  may  show  'im- 
perfectly' the  distinctive  character  that  makes  it  what  it  is? 

A  second  question,  of  a  more  topical  nature,  that  the  modem  reader  asks 
of  a  book  on  dreams  is  the  question  of  the  writer's  attitude  towards  the  psy- 
choanalytic school.  And  here  again  Mr.  Ellis  strikes  a  middle  path  which, 
to  the  reviewer,  seems  to  lose  itself  in  equivocation.  "Freud's  subtle 
and  searching  analytic  genius  has  greatly  contributed  to  enlarge  our 
knowledge  of  this  world  of  sleep.  We  may  recognize  the  value  of  his  con- 
tribution to  the  psychology  of  dreams  while  refusing  to  accept  a  premature 
and  narrow  generalization"  (pp.  174  f.).  But  is  not  this  an  attempt  to  eat 
one's  cake  and  have  it  too?  We  are  to  accept  all  the  Freudian  analyses, 
as  holding  for  the  dreams  analyzed;  but  we  are  to  reserve  a  large  body  of 
unanalyzed  dreams,  as  belonging  to  'quite  distinct'  types.  Mr.  Ellis 
disclaims  in  his  Preface  (p.  vii.)  any  use  of  the  psychoanalytic  method; 
how,  therefore,  does  he  know  that  the  unanalyzed  dreams  would  not  have 
submitted  to  a  Freudian  interpretation?  And,  in  larger  terms,  how  shall 
one  gain  the  right  to  declare  a  generalization  premature  and  narrow,  save 
by  producing  negative  instances  within  the  imiverse  of  discourse  to  which 
the  generalization  belongs?  The  reviewer,  be  it  noted,  is  not  here  arguing 
on  behalf  of  Freud,  as  he  was  not  arguing  just  now  against  any  and  every 
doctrine  of  the  Subconscious;  he  is  urging,  simply,  that  unclear  definition 
and  dogmatic  statement  are  out  of  place  in  science,  however  popular  the 
form  in  which  the  scientific  presentation  may  be  cast. 

What  is  the  mechanism  of  dreaming?  Mr.  Ellis'  view  is  not  easy  to 
expound:  partly  because  his  own  exposition  is  spread  serially  over  a  number 
of  chapters,  partly  because  he  is  by  no  means  careful  in  expression.  He 
inclines  strongly  to  the  opinion  that  all  dreams  are  peripherally  initiated; 
"we  seem  entitled  to  say  that  in  all  dreams  there  is  probably  a  presentative 
element,"  that  every  dream  has  "received  an  initial  stimulus  from  some 
external  or,  at  all  events,  peripheral  source"  (pp.  72  f.).  The  dream-con- 
sciousness is,  therefore,  always  thrown  into  gear,  so  to  say,  by  a  peripheral 
stimulus,  external  or  organic.  When  the  gearing  has  been  effected,  move- 
ment may  be  kept  up,  even  after  the  energy  of  the  stimulus  is  exhausted, 


BOOK  REVIEWS  465 

by  an  inherent  tendency  of  images  to  assert  themselves  in  consciousness. 
A  'more  or  less  spontaneous  procession  of  images'  is  the  elemental  stuff 
of  dreams  (pp.  24  f.).  In  the  most  elementary  form  of  dreaming,  in  which 
the  peripheral  element  plays  its  largest  part,  we  have  a  'seemingly  spon- 
taneous,' 'mechanical  flow  of  images,  regulated  by  associations  of  resem- 
blance' (p.  27).  The  stimulus,  however,  is  never  presented  directly  to 
consciousness,  as  it  would  be  in  the  waking  life,  but  "serves  to  arouse  old 
memories  and  ideas  which  the  dream  consciousness  accepts  as  a  reasonable 
explanation  of  it"  (p.  73).  This  circumstance  would  appear  to  determine 
the  character  of  our  dreams ;  and  the  author  admits  that  the  dream-con- 
sciousness may  show  "what  we  call  a  deliberate  subconscious  selection  of 
imagery,"  so  that  a  'real  subconscious  link'  connects  any  two  successive 
images.  Nevertheless,  he  insists  that  there  may  be  sheer  discontinuity; 
"mental  imagery  is  deeper  and  more  elemental  than  any  of  the  higher 
psychic  functions  even  when  exerted  subconsciously.  Discontinuous  images 
may  arise  from  a  psychic  basis  deeper  than  choice,  their  appearance 
being  determined  by  their  own  dynamic  condition  at  the  moment."  "If 
we  hold  to  the  belief  that  dreaming  is  based  on  a  fundamental  and  elemen- 
tary tendency  to  the  formation  of  continuous  or  discontinuous  images, 
which  may  or  may  not  be  controlled  by  psychic  emotions  and  impulses, 
we  shall  be  delivered  from  many  hazardous  speculations"  (p.  24). 

The  passages  are  not  clear.  If  the  occurrence  of  the  initial  stimulus  is 
universal,  it  is  probably  also  necessary;  yet,  if  images  have  a  tendency  to 
spontaneous  irruption  into  consciousness,  there  is  no  reason  why  a  dream 
should  not  be  initiated  at  the  centre;  no  reason,  indeed,  why  we  should 
cease  from  dreaming  at  all.  Contrariwise,  if  the  images  are  held  together 
by  associations  of  resemblance,  then  the  initial  stimulus,  plus  the  law  of 
association  of  ideas,  is  adequate  to  the  result;  the  spontaneity  of  the 
images  is  illusory. 

It  seems  that  Mr.  EUis  has  found  certain  dreams  which  suggest  a  sub- 
conscious elaboration,  and  certain  others  which  have  a  mechanical  or 
disconnected  look;  he  has  accordingly  called  in,  as  explanatory  principles, 
both  the  Subconscious  and  a  dynamic  Bereitschaft  of  images.  His  anti- 
physiological  bias,  leading  him  to  emphasize  the  Subconscious  and  the 
Image  as  psychological  terms,  has  then  prevented  the  enquiry  whether  the 
'dynamic  condition'  of  the  images  is  not  an  alternative  to,  or  an  equivalent 
of,  the  hypothesis  of  the  Subconscious,  and  has  also  encouraged  him  to 
traverse  the  accepted  doctrine  of  psychology  that  Bereitschaft  is  always 
strictly  conditioned.  This,  at  any  rate,  is  the  interpretation  which  the 
reviewer  has  put  upon  a  puzzling  subject. 

The  primary  stimulus,  we  have  learned,  does  not  come  to  consciousness 
in  its  own  right,  but  arouses  old  memories  and  ideas.  The  arousal,  how- 
ever, is  again  not  direct.  The  stimulus,  if  it  appeal  to  one  of  the  higher 
senses,  suggests  motor  activities  which  cannot  be  carried  out;  the  excita- 
tion, entering  motor  channels,  is  impeded,  broken  up,  scattered;  and 
this  process  "is  transmitted  to  the  brain  as  a  wave  of  emotion."  If  the 
stimulus  is  internal, — alimentary,  cardiac,  respiratory, — then  the  organic 
sensations  which  it  sets  up  themselves  constitute  emotional  excitement. 
While,  therefore,  the  elemental  stuff  of  dreams  is  a  procession  of  images, 
"the  fundamental  source  of  our  dream  life  may  be  said  to  be  emotion" 
(p.  107).  How  does  the  stimulus,  after  its  emotive  transformation,  arouse  a 
dream?  "The  chief  function  of  dreams  is  to  supply  adequate  theories  to 
account  for  the  magnified  emotional  impulses  which  are  borne  in  on  sleep- 
ing consciousness.  This  is  the  key  to  imagination  in  dreams  .  .  .  Unable  to 
detect  the  origin"  of  the  emotive  waves,  sleeping  consciousness  "invents  an 
explanation  of  them"  (ibid.).  This  "craving  for  reasons  is  instinctive" 
(p.  8);  "every  dream  is  the  outcome  of  this  strenuous,  wide-ranging 
instinct  to  reason"  (p.  57);  "all  dreaming  is  a  process  of  reasoning"  (p.  56). 
Reasoning,  however,  is  a   "synthesis  of  images  suggested  by  resemblance 


466  BOOK  REVIEWS 

and  contiguity,"  and  "the  whole  phenomenon  of  dreaming  is  really  the 
same  process  of  image  formation,  based  on  resemblance  and  contiguity" 
(p.  57).  The  possibility  of  subconscious  elaboration  is  here  given  with  the 
instinct  to  explain.  But  will  not  the  hand  of  the  instinct  be  forced,  so  to 
speak,  time  and  again,  by  the  inherent  self-assertiveness  of  the  images? 

The  reviewer  has,  perhaps,  dwelt  unduly  upon  obscurities  which  Mr. 
Ellis  will,  doubtless,  be  able  to  clear  up.  At  the  same  time,  the  obscurities 
are  here,  a  stumbling-block  to  the  reader.  And  they  appear  again  in 
connection  with  another  question.  What  do  we  mean  when  we  ask  whether 
a  particular  conscious  function  or  formation  'occurs'  in  dreaming?  We 
may  mean:  Does  it  operate  or  appear  as  it  does  in  the  waking  life?  Is 
the  mechanism  of  the  dream  consciousness,  in  its  regard,  to  be  considered  as 
normal?  Or  we  may  mean :  Do  we  ever  dream  of  it  as  operating  or  appear- 
ing? Mr.  Ellis  is  not  careful  to  distinguish  these  two  forms  of  the  question. 
When  he  declares,  for  instance,  that  the  attention  of  dreams  is  for  the  most 
part  involuntary  attention,  he  means,  of  course,  that  the  general  function 
of  attention  in  dreams  is  of  the  same  kind  as  the  function  of  involuntary 
attention  in  waking;  we  are  'really'  only  involuntarily  attentive,  whatever 
we  may  dream  ourselves  to  be.  Since,  however,  he  has  just  described  two 
dreams  in  which  the  state  of  voluntary  attention,  as  dream-phenomenon, 
is  well  marked  (a  dream  in  which  a  particular  kind  of  postage  stamp  is 
looked  for  among  the  contents  of  a  pocket-book,  and  a  dream  in  which  a 
particular  hat  is  sought  in  a  row  of  hats  of  all  shapes  and  sizes),  it  would 
have  been  worth  while  to  make  the  distinction  explicit.  Again,  there  is  no 
doubt  that  many  persons  have,  not  infrequently,  the  dream-experience 
that  they  are  dreaming.  Mr.  Ellis  comments  on  the  evidence  as  follows: 
"I  have  never  detected  in  my  own  dreams  any  recognition  that  they  are 
dreams.  I  may  say,  indeed,  that  I  do  not  consider  that  such  a  thing  is  really 
possible"  (p.  65).  Truly,  it  is  not  'really'  possible  to  'recognize'  in  dreams 
the  dream-character  of  one's  experience;  for  that,  one  must  have  waked. 
But  just  as  in  the  waking  life  one  may  say,  on  the  ground  of  specific  con- 
scious experience,  'I  was  thinking. '  'I  was  trying  to  remember, '  'I  must 
have  been  dreaming, '  so  may  one  dream,  specifically,  that  one  is  thinking, 
or  trying  to  remember,  or  dreaming.  To  dream  'I  am  dreaming'  is  no  more  re- 
markable than  to  dream  'I  am  looking  for  stamps  in  a  pocket-book.'  Indeed, 
if  the  word  'occur'  is  taken  in  its  second  sense,  there  is  no  mode  or  item 
of  waking  experience  that  may  not  occur  in  the  dream-consciousness: 
voluntary  attention,  deliberative  thought,  high  resolve  appear  on  equal 
terms  with  involuntary  attention,  overwhelming  emotion,  or  the  dream- 
state  itself. 

Mr.  Ellis  is  not  at  his  best  in  discussions  of  a  technically  psychological 
sort.  On  the  other  hand,  his  wide  reading  and  practised  fluency  of  writing 
stand  him  in  good  stead  when  he  turns  to  special  subjects.  There  is,  e.  g., 
an  interesting  chapter  on  Aviation  in  Dreams.  Mr.  Ellis  rejects  Stanley 
Hall's  theory  of  a  hydro-psychosis,  and  explains  the  flying  dream  in  the 
orthodox  way  (though  he  achieved  orthodoxy  unawares,  by  his  own  obser- 
vations) as  reflecting  the  rise  and  fall  of  respiration.  It  is  odd  that  he  has 
not  thought  of  the  possibility  of  a  dendro-psychosis.  If  the  falling  dream 
suggested  to  one  of  Mr.  Hutchinson's  correspondents  {Dreams  and  their 
Meanings,  1901,  108),  the  fear  of  falling  from  trees  in  sleep,  the  flying  dream 
suggests  no  less  definitely  the  swing  of  our  arboreal  ancestor,  Mowgli-like, 
from  tree  to  tree.  This  derivation  would  further  account  for  the  fact — a 
difficulty  to  Mr.  Ellis — that  the  dream  of  flying  is  usually  agreeable,  the 
dream  of  falling  usually  disagreeable.  The  start  from  the  sensations  of 
breathing  is  not  hereby  denied;  but  on  the  writer's  own  principles  some 
reason  must  be  given  for  their  imaginative  dream-interpretation  as  the 
movement  of  flight. 

Another  chapter,  on  Dreams  of  the  Dead,  is  based  upon  a  paper  published 
in  the  Psychological  Review  in  1895.     At  that  date,  Mr.  Ellis  could  not. 


BOOK   REVIEWS  467 

of  course,  have  read  Mr.  Kipling's  wonderful  story  of  They;  but  it  might 
have  been  worth  while,  in  the  present  recasting  of  his  material,  to  raise 
explicitly  the  question  whether  'one  never  sees  a  dead  person's  face  in 
a  dream.'  The  reviewer  made  some  enquiry  on  this  matter,  in  1904,  and 
found  (in  accordance  with  his  own  experience)  that  the  dead  face  not 
uncommonly  appears,  as  clearly  and  vividly  as  the  face  of  a  living  person. 
The  chapter  on  Memory  in  Dreams  contains  a  long  excursus  on  false 
recognition  or  paramnesia.  The  author  believes  that  the  necessary  pre- 
liminary to  paramnesia  is  a  general  condition  of  temporary  or  chronic 
nervous  fatigue,  though  no  sense  of  exhaustion  need  be  felt.  An  externally 
aroused  perception  begins,  in  this  state,  without  sufficient  strength  to 
afford  the  realization  that  it  is  beginning;  it  is  brought  down  to  a  lower  and 
fainter  stage,  at  which  it  is  on  a  level  with  an  internally  aroused  perception 
or  memory-image ;  and  when  consciousness  has  become  sufficiently  devel- 
oped to  apprehend  the  nature  of  the  perception,  it  also  becomes  aware  that 
the  experience  has  been  continuing  for  an  indefinite  time  (pp.  251,  258). 
"The  mind  has  become  flaccid  and  enfeebled;  its  loosened  texture  has,  as 
it  were,  abnormally  enlarged  the  meshes  in  which  sensations  are  caught 
and  sifted,  so  that  they  run  through  too  easily.  They  are  not  properly 
apperceived.  To  use  a  crude  simile,  it  is  as  though  we  poured  water  into  a 
sieve.  The  impressions  of  the  world  which  are  actual  sensations  as  they 
strike  the  relaxed  psychic  meshwork  are  instantaneously  passed  through 
to  become  memories,  and  we  see  them  in  both  forms  at  the  same  moment, 
and  are  unable  to  distinguish  one  from  the  other"  (p.  259).  The  difficulty 
in  this  hypothesis  is  that  the  'actual  present'  reaches  consciousness  in  the 
'enfeebled  shape'  of  a  memory;  for  an  enfeebled  perception  is  not,  ipso 
facto,  an  image  of  memory.  Mr.  Ellis  has  spared  no  pains  to  acquaint 
himself  with  previous  attempts  at  explanation,  but  he  has  missed  the 
ingenious  analysis  offered  by  Linwiirzky  in  Meumann's  Archiv. 

Otto  Perler 


BOOK  NOTES 


Unsoundness  of  mind,  by  T.  S.  Clouston.  London,  Methuen  &  Co., 
1911.  361  p. 
The  author  is  of  tJie  conviction  that  unsoundness  of  mind  is  a  topic  that 
urgently  claims  the  attention  not  only  of  medical  men  but  of  intelligent 
laymen ;  this  on  account  both  of  the  vagueness  and  vastness  of  its  problems 
but  also  on  account  of  the  odium  with  which  ignorance  and  prejudice  have 
surrounded  it.  Thus,  medical  specialists  to-day  owe  a  duty  to  the  pubhc 
as  well  as  to  the  profession,  and  it  is  to  discharge  this  duty  that  the  author 
writes  this  book  into  which  he  has  put  the  results  of  a  long  life  rich  in 
experience  with  the  insane.  He  has  taken  the  broadest  view  of  the  topic, 
dealing  with  such  themes  as  the  hygiene  of  mind,  education,  the  tragedy 
of  mental  unsoundness,  its  relation  to  crime,  borderland  phenomena,  etc. 

The  origin  of  life:  being  an  account  of  experiments  with  certain  super-heated 
saline  solutions  in  hermetically  sealed  vessels,  by  H.  Charlton  Bastian. 
London,  Watts  &  Co.,  191 1.     76  p.  (with  ten  plates). 
This  is  a  reproduction  of  an  article  lately  submitted  to  the  Royal  Society 
and  which  it  did  not  consider  suitable  for  acceptance.     To  this,  the  author 
replies  that  very  few  believe  that  there  was  any  non-natural  cause  of  life. 
Most  think  that  there  were  certain  conditions  early  in  the  history  of  the 
earth  that  made  abiogenesis  possible.     This  work  represents  six  recent 
years  of  investigation  upon  the  same  subject  which  the  author  wrought  on 
in  the  years  ending  in  1872,  under  the  title  Heterogenesis  or  Archebiosis. 
We  are  reminded  that  the  same  society  turned  down  Joule's  "The  Mechani- 
cal Equivalent  of  Heat,"  but  published  Tyndall's  rather  unsystematic 
studies. 

Famous  impostors,  by  Bram  Stoker.  London,  Sidgwick  &  Jackson,  Ltd., 
1910.  349  p. 
This  book,  with  ten  illustrations,  briefly  characterizes  five  pretenders, 
three  practitioners  of  magic,  the  Wandering  Jew,  John  Law,  six  cases  of 
witchcraft,  Tichbome  claimant,  women  as  men,  ten  hoaxes.  Chevalier 
d'Eon  and  the  Bisley  Boy.  The  tales  are  very  crudely  told,  with  very  dis- 
turbing affectation  of  scholarship.  The  only  really  valuable  article  is  the 
last  one  and  the  longest,  on  the  Bisley  Boy,  where  the  author  tries  to 
make  out  the  case  that  Queen  Elizabeth  was  practically  sequestered  from 
her  father  and  died  at  about  the  age  of  nine,  while  her  keepers,  fearing  the 
king's  wrath,  found  the  only  possible  substitute  that  would  pass  muster 
for  her  in  a  boy  nearby  who  assumed  her  role  and  lived  it  out  through  life. 
He  proved  to  be  very  able  and  remarkably  adapted  to  his  role,  so 
that,  if  this  view  were  true.  Queen  Elizabeth  was  a  man.  His-her  remark- 
able and  unreasonable  devotion  to  the  interests  of  two  or  three  people, 
otherwise  unworthy,  is  explained  by  the  fact  that  they  alone  knew  her 
secret  which  had  to  be  guarded  in  every  possible  manner. 

The  nervous  life,  by  G.  E.  Partridge.  New  York,  Sturgis  &  Walton 
Company,  1911.  216  p. 
The  author  uses  this  term  for  two  conditions:  first,  the  nervous  social 
industrial  life  best  typified  by  the  stress  and  strife  of  the  great  cities;  and 
secondly,  as  expressed  in  the  temperament  in  nervous  individuals.  Both 
these  elements  of  nervous  life  are  on  the  increase  and  each  produces  the  other. 


BOOK  NOTES  469 

The  problem  is  more  pressing  than  ever  before.  After  stating  some  bio- 
logical laws  and  the  need  of  self  knowledge,  the  author  discusses  the  prin- 
ciples of  control,  the  optimum  life,  food,  skin,  exercise,  sleep,  rest,  work, 
recreation,  emotions,  intellect,  suggestion  and  mental  healing. 

Some  mental  processes  of  the  rhesus  monkey,  by  William  T.  Shepherd. 
From  the  Psychological  Laboratory  of  the  George  Washington  Uni- 
versity.    The  Psychological  Monographs,  Vol.  XII,  No.  5.    Nov.,  1910. 
Whole  No.  52.    61  p. 
The  author  studied  these  monkeys  with  reference  to  the  formation  of 
habits  in  releasing  fastenings,  in  visual  discrimination  of  brightness  and 
color,  auditory  of  noise  and  pitch,  inhibition  of  habits,  imitation,  ideation, 
reasoning,  adaptive  intelligence  and    memory.     He  found  that  monkeys 
discriminate  brightness  but  take  a  long  time  to  do  so  unless  there  is  a  direct 
incentive  to  their  work,  but  do  so  very  readily  if  connected  with  objects 
they  are  familiar  with.     So  too  with  colors,  if  of  their  food.     Habits  are 
rapidly  formed  if  there  is  good  inducement,  and  they  inhibit  former  habits 
easily.     In  this  respect,  they  are  superior  to  raccoons,  dogs,  cats,  elephants, 
otters,  or  any  other  animals  yet  tested.     They  have  retentive  number 
memory.     Their  higher  powers  are  rudimentary,  but  they  have  what  may 
be  called  practical  ideas.     Two  learned  by  imitation,  six  did  not  appear  to. 
All  seemed  to  reach  a  generalized  mode  of  action  in  dealing  with  problems 
without  attaining  true  general  notions.     They  have  an  adaptive  intelli- 
gence and  lower  forms  of  reason  of  a  mental  status  inferior  to  true  reason 

The  value  and  dignity  of  human  life  as  shown  in  the  striving  and  suffering 
of  the  individual,  by  Charles  Gray  Shaw.  Boston,  Richard  G. 
Badger,  1 9 11 .  403  p . 
This  book  is  written  with  the  conviction  that  a  change  is  taking  place 
in  our  notion  of  human  ideas  and  activities  and,  indeed,  of  the  value  of 
life.  It  is  dedicated  to  Professor  Eucken  who  has  the  same  conviction. 
In  the  first  part,  entitled  the  problems  of  human  life,  the  author  discusses 
the  striving  of  humanity,  the  continuity  of  the  former,  the  human  world. 
In  part  two,  he  takes  up  the  naturalistic  view  of  life,  that  of  humanity  and 
sense  in  pleasure,  desire,  self,  transmutation  of  naturalism  and  moralism, 
eudemonism.  The  third  part  is  characterized  ethics  of  the  life  of  humanity 
and  the  will,  conscience,  rectitude,  freedom,  practical  demands,  rigorism, 
destiny  of  man,  etc.  Part  four  is  humanistic  ethics,  major  and  minor, 
morality,  category  of  virtue,  virtue  as  an  ethical  sanction,  human  dignity 
in  the  ethical  category,  the  dignity  of  selfhood,  the  triumph  of  hvunanity 
in  major  morals. 

Three  thousand  years  of  mental  healing,  by  George  Barton  CuTTEn.  New 
York,  Charles  Scribner's  Sons,  1911.  318  p. 
The  writer  has  given  us  a  rather  hasty  but  interesting  sketch  of  mental 
healing  from  the  very  earliest  civilization  before  Christianity  down  to 
Schlatter,  the  Holy  Ghost  and  Us,  Dowie,  Mrs.  Eddy,  and  Emmanuelism. 
with  interesting  chapters  on  relics  and  shrines,  healers,  talismans,  amulets, 
charms,  royal  touch,  Mesmer  and  after,  with  eight  interesting  illustrations. 
The  book  is  popular  and  does  not  attempt  to  go  into  details  of  scholarship. 
It  is  a  little  difficult  to  know  just  what  the  author  aimed  at.  Perhaps  it 
was  to  show  the  community  of  all  these  different  types  of  healing  or  to 
show  the  persistence  of  the  type  down  all  the  ages.  This  is,  at  any  rate, 
an  impression  the  book  gives  us.  The  author  does  not  attempt  either 
criticism  or  defence  of  the  movement  and  indeed  he  has  left  us  very  im- 
certain  what  his  own  attitude  toward  it  is,  unless  the  reader  infers,  as 
perhaps  he  will  inevitably  do,  that  a  writer  who  would  spend  so  much  time 
upon  such  a  topic  must  believe  that  there  is  something  of  great  consequence 
involved  in  his  theme.  The  book  is  strangely  pragmatic,  non-committal , 
Journal — 10 


470  BOOK  NOTHS 

attempting  almost  nothing  in  the  way  of  psychological  or  philosophical 
explanation.     Perhaps  the  author  intends  fuller  treatment  later. 

Die  Mimik  der  Kinder  beim  kiinstlerischen  Geniessen,  von  Rudolf  SchulzE. 
Leipzig,  Voigtlander,  1906.  34  p. 
The  author  showed  a  series  of  pictures  of  very  diverse  character  to  a 
group  of  12  girls,  and  a  few  seconds  after  the  exposure  of  each  picture  photo- 
graphed their  faces  in  order  to  show  the  effect  of  the  pictures.  The  charac- 
ter of  the  pictures  ranged  all  the  way  from  very  comic  scenes  to  very  serious 
including  the  Crucifixion,  and  the  faces  of  these  girls  are  very  expressive, 
the  picture  and  the  expression  being  given  on  the  same  page  and  described. 

The  soul  of  the  Indian;  an  interpretation,  by  Charles  Alexander  Eastman 
(ChiyEsa).  Boston,  Houghton,  Mifflin  &  Co.,  191 1.  170  p. 
This  is  one  of  the  most  charming  and  fascinating  of  books.  The  author, 
in  spite  of  the  high  civilization  he  has  attained,  has  remained  loyal  to, 
and  sympathetic  with,  the  faith  of  his  people  and  give  us  a  most  interesting 
account  of  how  the  great  world  looks  to  them.  He  treats  the  great  mystery, 
the  family  altar,  ceremonial  and  symbolic  worship,  barbarism,  the  moral 
code,  the  unwritten  Scriptures,  on  the  borderland  of  spirits.  We  have  no 
space  here  to  do  justice  in  a  psychological  journal  to  this  work.  It  should 
be  in  the  hands  of  every  one  who  has  any  interest  in  the  Indian,  and  particu- 
larly in  the  hands  of  those  who  have  to  deal  with  him  ofl&cially. 

Beitrag  zur  Aetiologie  der  Melancholie,  by  Emil  Villiger.     Basel,  Schwei- 
zer,  1898.     77  p.  .  ^ 

This  thesis  leads  the  author  to  conclude  that  melancholy  is  a  psychosis 
that  may  attack  any  age  but  is  more  common  in  men  from  45  to  55  and  in 
women  from  30  to  50.  It  is  more  common  among  women  than  men  and 
more  among  the  unmarried  than  the  married,  more  common  among  country 
than  city  people.  While  there  are  many  causes,  heredity  and  the  psycho- 
pathic constitution  are  the  chief.     The  psychic  causes  are  shock  and  illness. 

Affe  und  Mensch  in  ihrer  hiologischen  Eigenart,  von  Alexander  Sokolow- 
SKY.  Leipzig,  Theod.  Thomas,  191 1.  147  p. 
This  work  is  by  an  assistant  director  of  the  Zoological  Garden  in  Ham- 
biu"g  and  contains  a  number  of  interesting  characterizations.  The  first 
part  is  devoted  to  apes,  the  last  to  primitive  man,  and  a  few,  though  it 
must  be  admitted,  rather  superficial  resemblances  in  the  mode  of  life 
between  the  two  are  pointed  out. 

Magical  titbits,  by  Louis  Hoffmann.  N.  Y.,  E.  P.  Button  &  Co.,  191 1. 
221  p. 
The  first  part  of  this  volume  describes  a  few  items  of  magic  that  are  new, 
and  in  the  second  part  the  author  has  put  into  more  permanent  shape  a 
number  of  ingenious  inventions  of  his  old  friend  Hartz  which  have  hitherto 
been  accessible  only  in  serial  form. 

The  beginning  of  speech:  a  treatise  on  the  uni-radical  origin  of  Indo-European 

words,  by  A.  L.  Snell.      London,  Kegan  Paul,  Trench,  Triibrier  & 

Co.,  1910.     267  p. 

This  work  is  the  result  of  twenty-five  years'  study  of  some  fifty  langiiages, 

chiefly  Indo-European.     It  has  involved  not  merely  a  study  of  lists  of 

words  but  a  great  deal  of  reading  and  note-taking.     The  author  is  evidently 

not  familiar  with  modem  philology,  and  so  apologizes  for  not  quoting. 

He  found,  as  the  book  was  going  to  press,  that  one  or  more  of  his  important 

conclusions  had  been  anticipated  by  J.  W.  Donaldson's  New  Cratylus. 

He  holds  that  the  number  of  simple,  underived  words  in  these  languages 

is  small  and  that  these  consist  of  three  letters  and  can  be  traced  from  one 

language  to  another,  not  by  permutation  of    initial  consonants  but  by 


BOOK   NOTES  471 

considerations  of  basal  meaning;  that  each  of  these  words  is  but  one  of  a 
vast  number  of  modifications  of  one  primal,  photo-mimetic  utterance.  His 
five  laws  are  as  follows.  Monosyllabic  words  ending  in  1,  m,  n,  or  r,  were 
once  disyllabic  and  have  been  shortend  by  dropping  an  internal  guttural 
after  its  weakening  to  the  aspirate.  Words  now  beginning  with  1,  m,  n,  or 
r,  have  lost  initial  wa,  and  so  by  the  above  law  have  retained  no  part  of 
the  original  word.  Words  now  beginning  with  a  vowel  have  lost  a 
consonant  and  those  now  ending  with  a  vowel  have  lost  an  original  final 
guttural.  Words  now  containing  an  internal  n  or  m  must,  for  philological 
purposes,  be  written  without  these  letters,  which  are  merely  nasal  symbols 
and  no  part  of  the  original  word. 

The  main  thesis  of  this  whole  book  is  that  each  of  these  words  is  but  one 
of  a  vast  number  of  modifications  of  one  primal  photo-mimetic  utterance. 
The  original  word  from  which  all  others  have  been  derived  must  have  been 
something  like  vig,  wag,  jag,  twav,  jaw,  and  so  on,  36  words  which  are 
basal.  These  36  he  reduces  to  6  and  these  6  are  all  reduced  by  his  laws  to 
waw,  the  primal,  photo-mimetic  utterance  from  which  every  word  in  all 
the  Indo-European  languages  has  arisen.  To  the  eye  this  word  conveys 
little,  but  when  pronounced  it  is  obviously  the  common  cry  of  many  birds 
which  the  genius  of  primitive  man  transmuted  into  the  foundation  or 
nucleus  of  human  language.  This  is  not  humiliation  for  we  are  of  lowly 
origin. 

Der  Einfiuss  psychischer   Vorgdnge  auf  den  Korper,  inshesondere  auf  die 

Blutverteilung,  von    Ernst    WebER.     Berlin,  Julius  Springer,   19 10. 

426  p. 
The  writer  discusses  first  the  various  physiological  methods  of  register- 
ing the  accompaniments  of  psychic  changes,  especially  the  blood  which 
is  without  the  brain  and  within  it  in  men  and  animals.  He  takes  up  the 
effect  of  the  concepts  of  movement  upon  the  distribution  of  blood  in  the 
human  body.  He  seeks  to  prove  from  experiments  on  animals  the  inde- 
pendence of  the  brain  in  regulating  its  own  blood  supply.  Oh  this  basis 
he  shows  the  changes  of  the  volume  of  blood  in  the  human  brain  in  connec- 
tion with  different  psychic  processes,  the  reversal  of  the  normal  blood 
distribution  by  physiological  and  pathological  fatigue,  the  significance 
of  the  variations  of  the  blood  distribution  within  the  body  under  the 
influence  of  psychic  processes.  The  work  closes  with  an  excellent  and 
extended  bibliography. 
Bilderatlas  zum  ersten  Bande  der  Grundzuge  der  Sprachpsychologie,    von 

Ottmar  DiTTrich.     Halle  a.  S.,  Max  Meineyer,  1903.     95  p. 
This  atlas  is  by  far  the  best  now  extant  for  the  study  of  speech  physiology 
and  defects.      There  are  many  very  ingenious  modes  of  representing  the 
various  types  of  both  normal  and  abnormal  speech  physiology  which  will 
commend  themselves  to  all  who  have  to  teach  the  subject. 
Truth  on  trial:  an  exposition  of  the  nature  of  truth.  Preceded  by  a  Critique 

on  Pragmatism  and  an  Appreciation  of  its  Leader,  by  PauIv  Carus. 

This  work  is  dedicated  to  William  James.     It  discusses  Pragmatism, 

the  philosophy  of  personal  equation,  the  rock  of  ages,  the  nature  of  truth, 

with  an  appendix  on  Pragmatism. 

Personality  with  special  reference  to  super-personalities  and  the  inter-personal 

character  of  ideas,  by  PauIv  Carus.     Chicago,  Open  Court  Publishing 

Co.,  191 1.  68  p. 
This  work  first  discusses  the  following  topics :  significance  of  personality, 
the  word  persona  and  its  history,  problem  of  unity  ideas,  inter-personal 
super-personalities,  trinity  conceptions,  the  super-personal  God.  These 
titles  will  in  general  give  sufficient  intimation  of  the  content  of  the  book  to 
those  who  are  familiar  with  the  Monist. 


472  BOOK  NOTES 

Technique  de  psychologie  experimental e,  par  Ed.  Toulouse  et  H.  Pieron. 
Paris,  Octave   Doin  et  Fils,  191 1.     Tome  premier,  303  p.,  et  Tome 
second,   288  p.    (Encyclopedie  scientifique.) 
These  two  volumes  constitute  a  very  convenient  manual  for  the  labora- 
tory student  and  practitioner.     The  authors  have  well  availed  themselves 
of  the  work  of  their  predecessors,  Sanford  and  Titchener,  although  their 
book,  from  the  nature  of  a  subject  growing  so  fast,  will  not  be  considered 
by  all  as  up  to  date. 

An  introduction  to  experimental  psychology,  by  Charles  Myers.    Cam- 
bridge, The  University  Press.  191 1.     156  p. 
This  little  primer  of  psychology  discusses  touch,   temperature,   pain, 
color  vision,  the  Miiller-Lyer  illusion,  memory,  mental  tests,  and  has  a  good 
bibliography,  index  and  a  few  colored  plates. 

Clever  Hans,  by  Oskar  Pfungst.     With  an  introduction  by  Professor  C. 

Stumpf.  Translated  from  the  German  by  Carl  L.  Rahn.     New  York, 

Henry  Holt  &  Co.,  191 1.  274  p. 
Every  one  will  thank  the  author  of  this  volimie  for  bringing  together 
in  the  characteristic  German  and  thorough  way  the  whole  story  of  the 
rise  and  fall  of  this  remarkable  episode  in  the  history  of  animal  psychology. 
The  author  himself  examined  the  horse  and  reached  his  own  conclusions 
and  describes  in  great  detail  how  the  trainer.  Von  Osten,  directed  his 
actions  unconsciously,  and  what  was  still  more  marvellous,  how  other  people 
did  the  same. 

Experiments  with  drosophila  ampelophila  concerning  evolution,  by  Frank 
E.  LuTz.     Pub.  by  the  Carnegie  Institution  of  Washington,  Washing- 
ton, D.  C,  191 1.     40  p. 
These  very  interesting  experimental  studies  lead  the  author  to  the  con- 
clusion that  "there  is  no  evidence  that  the  constant  disuse  of  wings  during 
forty  generation  has  had  any  effect"  in  modifying  the  venation  or  other- 
wise affecting  the  form  of  the  wing  of  the  sand  fly. 

Among  friends.  By  S.  McC.  Crothers.  Boston  and  New  York,  Houghton 
Mifflin  Co.  1910.  pp.  iii.,  278.  Price  $1.25. 
A  collecton  of  nine  essays,  in  which  literary  reminiscence  is  blended  with 
shrewd  and  kindly  criticism  of  current  social  attitudes.  "The  Anglo- 
American  School  of  Polite  Unlearning,"  "The  Hundred  Worst  Books," 
"The  Romance  of  Ethics,"  "The  Merry  Devil  of  Education."  such  titles 
speak  for  themselves. 

The  Corsican:  a  diary  of  Napoleon's  life  in  his  own  words.     Compiled  by 
R.  M.  Johnston.     Boston  and   New  York,  Houghton  Mifflin   Co., 
1910.     pp.  vi.,  526.     Price  $1.75. 
It  was  a  happy  idea  which  led  Professor  Johnston  to  bring  together,  in  a 
single  volume,  the  recorded  utterances  of  the  great  Napoleon.     Conversa- 
tions,  letters,   notes,   proclamations  are  here  arranged    in  chronological 
order,  with  enough  of  explanatory  comment  to  make  the  narrative  continu- 
ous for  any  reader  who  possesses  an  elementary  knowledge  of  the  period. 
The  whole  forms  a  htmian  document  of  extreme  interest. 

Publication  of  the  Massachusetts  General  Hospital:  Medical  and  Surgical 

Papers.     Boston,  19 10.     374  p. 
The  adolescent,  by  J.  W.  Slaughter.     With  an  introduction  by  J.  J. 

Findlay.     London,  Swan  Sonnenschein  &  Co.,  191 1.     100  p. 

Introduction  to  philosphy,  by  Wh^liam  Jerusalem.  Authorized  transla- 
tion from  the  fourth  edition  by  Charles  F.  Sanders.  New  York, 
The  Macmillian   Co.,    1910.     219  p. 


BOOK  NOTKS  473 

Otto  Weiningers  Tod,  von  Hermann  Swob oda.     Vienna,  Deuticke,  191 1. 
100  p. 

Pubertal  und  Auge,  von  Rudolf  Schneider.     Miinchen,  Otto  Gmelin, 
1911.     17  p. 

Festschrift  zum  sechzigsten  Geburtstag  Richard  Her  twigs.  Jena,  Gustav 
Fischer,  19 10.  3  vols.  (Arbeiten  aus  dem  Gebiet  der  Zellenlehre 
und  Protozoenkunde.)  674,  624,  308  p. 
The  maturation  of  the  egg  of  the  mouse,  by  J.  A.  Lang  and  E.  L.  Mark. 
Washington,  Published  by  the  Carnegie  Institution  of  Washington, 
191 1.  72  pages  and  6  plates. 
Das   Wesen  der    Vernunft,   von  Adolf  KELLER.     Gross-Lichterfelde,   J. 

Univerdorben  &  Co.,  191 1.  12  p. 
L'analyse   physiologique   de   la   perception,    par    Edouard    Abramowski. 
Paris,  Bloud  &  Cie,  1911.     121  p.     (Collection  de  psychologie  experi- 
mentale  et  de  Metaphyschie,     Directeur  Raymond  Meunier.) 
Kliene  Schriften,  von  Wilhelm  Wundt.     Leipzig,  Wilhelm  Engelmann, 

191 1.     496  p.     (ZweiterBd.) 
Creative  evolution,  by  Henri  Bergson.     Translation  by  Arthur  Mitchell. 

New  York,  Henry  Holt  &  Co.,  191 1.     407  p. 
Die  Methode  der  historisch-volkerpsychologischen  Begriffsanalyse,  von  Abra- 
ham   ScHLESiNGER.     Sonderabdruck    aus    Archiv    fiir    die    gesamte 
Psychologie,  XX  Bd,  2  Heft.     Leipzig,  Wilhelm  Englemann,   191 1. 
pp.  150-185. 
The  place  of  movement  in  consciousness,  by  W.  B.  Pillsbury.     Reprinted 
from  the  Psychological  Review,  March.  191 1.    Vol.  XVIII,  pp.  83-99. 
Psychotherapy  from  a  psychological  standpoint,  by  David  S.  Booth.     Re- 
printed from  The  Alienist  and  Neurologist,  February,    191 1.     Vol. 
XXXII,  No.  I,  24  p. 
Notebook  of  American  Indian  languages,  by  Franz  Boas.     Washington, 
Government    Printing    Office,    191 1.     1069  p.     (»Smithsonian    Insti- 
tution.    Bureau  of  American  Ethnology  Bulletin  40,) 
Psychic  phenomena,  science  and  immortality,  by  Henry  Frank.     Boston, 
Sherman,  French  &  Co.,  191 1.     556  p. 
In  the  first  book,  the  author  deals  with  psychic  phenomena  and  has 
much  to  tell  us  concerning  the  soul's  secret  scroll,  sub-conscious  mind, 
correspondence,  superphysical  senses.  Sir  William   Crookes,  the  sleepless 
self,  spirit  forms  and  materializations.     The  second  book  is  entitled  scien- 
tific interpretation.     Here  he  deals  with  ultimate  matter  and  vital  energy, 
occult  forces,  the  subtle  seat  of  human  intelligence,  biology  of  the  soul, 
its  body,  radio-activity,  telepathy  and  substantiality  of  thought.     The 
third  book  deals  with  problems  of  immortality.     He  deems  that  the  studies 
which  he  enumerates  demonstrate  beyond  all  question  the  survival  of  the 
soul  after  death. 

Influencing  men  in  business,  by  Walter  Dill  Scott.  New  York,  The 
Ronald  Press  Co.,  191 1.  168  p. 
This  book  assumes  that  we  can  increase  our  ability  to  influence  men  by 
mastering  a  few  simple  laws  for  influencing  their  minds.  To  find  these, 
he  analyzes  deliberation  and  suggestion  and  tells  how  to  decide  questions 
and  reach  conclusions,  when  to  use  arguments  and  when  suggestion,  and 
how  to  make  both  effective. 

Precis   d' auto-suggestion   volontaire,    par    G:^raud  Bonnet.     Paris,  Jules 
Roussett,  191 1.     297  p. 
After  preliminary  explanations,  the  author  discusses  hypnotism  and 


474  BOOK  NOTES 

auto-suggestion,  the  education  of  the  will,  the  influence  of  the  self,  con- 
centration of  thought  and  personal  power. 

Les  syncinesies,  par  G.  Strouhlin.     Paris,  G.  Steinheil,  191 1.     147  p. 

In  the  first,  clinical  part,  the  author  discusses  movements  associated 
with  normal  states,  those  with  motor  debility,  those  with  volitive  syncin- 
esias,  those  with  hemiplegia,  and  then  gives  us  his  scheme  of  diagnosis. 
In  the  second,  physiological  part,  he  follows  the  same  fourfold  division  of 
his  material  and  gives  a  few  general  conclusions. 

Das  kranke  Geddchtnis,  von  Paul  Ranschburg.  Leipzig,  Johann  Ambro- 
sius  Barth,  191 1.  138  p.  Mit  6  Kurven  und  27  Abbildungen  im  Text. 
This  work  is  divided  into  two  parts.  The  first  is  the  result  of  experi- 
mental psychopathology  in  the  study  of  memory.  First  the  retrospective, 
and  then  the  anterograde  direction  of  memory  is  considered.  The  second 
part  describes  the  ways  of  experimental  investigation  in  the  pathology  of 
memory,  how  to  investigate  recognition,  reproductive  activity  and  those  of 
investigating  morbid  memories  by  means  of  special  apparatus.  The  work 
has  many  cuts  and  contains  an  excellent  bibliography. 

The  psychology  0}  education,  by  J.  Welton.  London,  Macmillan  &  Co., 
1911.  507  p. 
The  chapters  are  as  follows :  the  relations  between  education  and  psy- 
chology, the  study  of  mental  life,  bodily  endowment,  general  mental  endow- 
ment, variations  in  mental  endowment,  nature  of  experience,  development 
of  interests,  direction  of  activity,  learning  by  direct  experience,  learning 
through  communicated  experience,  critical  thought,  ideals,  character. 

Scientific  method  in  animal  psychology,  by  Robert  M.  Yerkes.  13  p. 
Kxtrait  des  Comptes  rendus  du  VI^  Congres  international  de  Psy- 
chologic.    (Geneve  1909.     Pages  808-819). 

The  psychological  aspects  of  illuminating  engineering,  by  Robert  M.  Yerkbs. 
(A  lecture  delivered  at  the  Johns  Hopkins  University,  October- 
November,  1910.)     pp.  575-604. 

Do  kittens  instinctively  kill  mice?  by  Robert  M.  Yerkes  and  DaniEi< 
Bloomfield.  Reprinted  from  the  Psychological  Bulletin,  August, 
1910.     Vol.  VII,  pp.  253-263. 

Psychology  in  its  relations  to  biology,  by  Robert  M.  Yerkes.  Reprinted 
from  The  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology  and  Scientific  Methods, 
Vol.  VII,  No.  5,  March  3,  1910.     pp.  1 13-124. 

The  method  of  Pawlow  in  animal  psychology,  by  Robert  M.  Yerkes  and 
Sergius  Morgulis.  Psychological  Biilletin,  Vol.  6,  No.  8,  August 
15,  1909-     pp.  257-273. 

Modifiahility  of  behavior  in  its  relations  to  the  age  and  sex  of  the  dancing 
mouse,  by  Robert  M.  Yerkes.  Reprinted  from  The  Journal  of 
Comparative  Neurology  and  Psychology,  Vol.  XIX,  No.  3,  June,  1909. 
pp.  237-271. 

Die  Spuren  interessebetonter  Erlebnisse  und  ihre  Symptome,  von  Otto 
LiPMANN.  Leipzig,  Johann  Ambrosius  Barth,  191 1.  96  p.  (Beihefte 
ziu-  Zeitschrift  fiir  angewandte  Psychologic  und  psychologische 
Sammelforschrung.,  hrsg.  von  William  Stem  und  Otto  Lipmann.  i) 

Untersuchungen  iiber  Geschlechts-, Alter s-und  Begabungs-Unterschiede  bei 
Schiilern,  von  Jonas  Cohn  und  Julius  Dieffenbacher.  Leipzig, 
Johann  Ambrosius  Barth,  1911.  213  S.  und  drei  Tafeln.  (Beihefte 
zur  Zeitschrift  fiir  angewandte  Psychologic  und  psychologische 
Sammelforschung,  hrsg  von  William  Stern  und  Otto  Lipmann.  2) 


DR.  EDMUND  MONTGOMERY 


The  following  note  by  Mr.  B.  F.  Underwood,  of  the  Quincy,  111.,  Journal, 
refers  to  a  writer  whose  work  is  familiar  to  many  of  our  readers. — 

At  Hempstead,  Texas,  died  a  few  days  ago  Dr.  Edmund  Montgomery. 
Probably  there  was  some  mention  of  his  death  in  the  local  papers  of  the 
community,  in  which  he  was  a  well-known  citizen;  but  the  writer  of  this 
article  has  seen  no  reference  to  the  event  in  any  Journal.  Yet  Dr.  Mont- 
gomery was  the  author  of  original  scientific  and  philosophical  works, — 
some  of  them  written  in  English,  others  in  German, — which  are  in  all  the 
great  libraries  of  the  world.  In  his  fields  of  thought  he  had  an  interna- 
tional reputation.  He  wrote  on  "Theories  of  Knowledge,"  "Our  Ideas 
of  Time  and  Space,"  "TheFormation  of  So-Called  Cells,"  "Vital  Organiza- 
tion," "The  Unity  of  the  Organic  Individual,"  "The  Dual  Aspect  of  Our 
Nature,"  "Protoplasm  of  the  Muscles,"  "Transcendentalism,"  "Vital 
Motility,"  etc. 

Dr.  Montgomery  was  for  years  a  contributor  to  Mind,  the  Popular  Science 
Monthly,  and  the  Boston  Index,  besides  other  journals  in  this  country. 

Dr.  Montgomery  was  born  in  Edinburgh,  Scotland,  in  1835,  of  Scotch 
parents.  He  was  taken  to  Paris  in  care  of  a  French  nurse  so  early  that  the 
first  language  he  learned  to  speak  was  French.  At  nine  he  was  taken  to 
Frankfort,  Germany,  where,  educated  in  German,  he  began  early  the  study 
of  the  natural  sciences  and  philosophy. 

He  was  acquainted  with  Feuerbach ;  and  at  Heidelberg  he  attended  the 
lectures  of  Moleschott  and  Kuno  Fischer.  He  used  to  see  Schopenhauer, 
with  his  poodle,  daily,  and  was  much  interested  in  the  philosopher  of  pes- 
simism. At  Bonn  he  attended  Helmholtz's  famous  lectures  on  the  "Phy- 
siology of  the  Senses."  He  studied  at  German  universities — Heidelberg, 
Berlin,  Bonn,  Wiirzburg  (where  he  received  the  M.  D.  degree),  Prague  and 
Vienna.  He  wrote  in  German  a  reply  to  Kant's  "Critique  of  Pure  Reason," 
at  Munich  in  1871.  From  i860  to  1863  he  was  lecturer  on  Physiology 
in  St.  Thomas,  Hospital,  London,  where  the  effects  of  a  dissecting  wound  put 
an  end  to  his  work  in  that  institution,  where  he  used  to  meet  and  converse 
with  Darwin. 

For  six  years  he  practised  medicine  at  Madeira,  Men  tone,  and  Rome; 
and  in  1869,  with  a  competence,  he  retired  to  give  his  whole  attention  to 
science. 

In  1 87 1  he  went  to  Texas  and  bought  the  Liendo  plantation,  paying 
for  it  $40,000.  In  a  letter  to  the  writer  he  wrote:  "The  first  seven  years 
here  in  the  South  were  devoted  to  laborious  biological  research;  no  writing 
at  all." 

Dr.  Montgomery's  wife  was  Elizabeth  Ney,  a  grandniece  of  Marshal 
Ney  of  France.  She  acquired  a  reputation  as  an  artist,  and  designed  and 
executed  some  of  the  finest  pieces  of  sculpture  in  the  state  capital  at 
Austin. 

Late  in  the  eighties  Dr.  Montgomery,  by  request,  sent  a  paper  to  be 
read  before  the  "Concord  School  of  Philosophy,"  whose  programme  that 
season  included  lectures  by  Dr.  W.  R.  Alger  and  Dr.  W.  T.  Harris,  whose 
terminology  caused  no  little  merriment  among  those  unacquainted  with 
scientific  and  philosophic  thought.  In  the  Boston  Record  from  some  bright 
reporter  appeared  the  following,  indicating  the  impression  Dr.  Mont- 
gomery's paper  had  produced  among  those  not  so  much  interesetd  in  the 
thought  as  they  were  confounded  by  the  language : 


476  DR.    EDMUND    MONTGOMERY 

"A  Texan  has  floored  the  Concord  crowd. 
Sing  high,  and  sing  ho!  for  the  great  Southwest; 

He  sent  'em  a  paper  to  read  aloud. 

And  't  was  done  up  in  style  by  one  of  their  best. 

"The  Texan,  he  loaded  his  biggest  gun 

With  all  the  wise  words  he  ever  had  seen, 
And  he  fired  at  long  range  with  death-grim  fun. 

And  slew  all  the  sages  with  his  machine. 

"He  muddled  the  muddlers  with  brain-cracking  lore. 
He  went  in  so  deep  that  his  followers  were  drowned, 

But  he  swam  out  himself  to  the  telluric  shore, 
And  crowed  in  his  glee  o'er  the  earthlings  around. 

V  Envoy 

"Oh  Plato,  dear  Plato,  come  back  from  the  past! 

And  we  '11  forgive  all  that  you  ever  did  to  vex  us. 
If  you  '11  only  arrange  for  a  colony  vast. 

And  whisk  these  philosophers  all  off  to  Texas." 

In  scientific  and  philosophical  circles  the  paper  attracted  wide  attention, 
and  is  included  among  his  published  writings.  Dr.  Montgomery  was  in 
personal  appearance  as  handsome  and  impressive  and  in  manners  as  courtly 
and  courteous  as  he  was  intellectually  brilliant. 


JfT) 


THE    AMERICAN 

Journal  of  Psychology 

Founded  by  G.  Stani^ey  Hai.Iv  in  1887 
Voi,.  XXII.  OCTOBER,  1911  No.      4 

THE  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  LIFE^ 
By  Ernest  Jones,  M.  D.  (London),  University  of  Toronto 

CONTENTS 

I.     Introduction.     Psychical  determinism 477 

II.     Forgetting.     Errors  in  memory  .      .      . 479 

III.  Lapsus  linguae 492 

IV.  Lapsus  calami 498 

V.     Misprints  503 

VI.     False  visual  recognition S04 

VII.     Mislaying  of  objects 506 

VIII.     Erroneously  carried  out  actions 508 

IX.     S5anptomatic  acts         510 

X.     General  observations 515 

(i)     Warrant  for  interpretations 515 

(2)  Bearing  on  psycho-analytic  method  of  treatment   .  520 

(3)  Relation  to  health  and  disease 521 

(4)  Determinism  and  free  will 521 

(5)  Social  significance         522 

XI.     Summary 526 

I.  Introduction 
-  Under  this  title  Freud  has  written  an  interesting  volume^ 
dealing  with  a  number  of  mental  processes  that  previously 
had  received  little  or  no  attention  from  psychologists.  The 
material  of  this  kind  that  lends  itself  to  study,  like  that  of 
dreams,  is  very  extensive,  and  is  accessible  to  every  one;  it 
is,  therefore,  of  importance  to  those  who  wish  to  test  Freud's 
general  psychological  conclusions,  and  who  have  not  the 
opportunity  of  investigating  the  more  obscure  problems  of 
the  psycho-neuroses.  Freud's  study  of  the  mental  processes 
in  question  is  of  especial  interest  as  showing  that  mechanisms 
similar  to  those  observable  in  the  abnormal  also  occur  in  the 

^Elaborated  from  an  address  delivered  before   the    Detroit   Academy 
of  Medicine,  May  1 6th,  1 9 1 1 . 

'Freud,  S.:  Zur  Psychopathologie  des  Alltagslebens.  Dritte  Auflage,  19 10. 


478  jONies 

normal;  indeed  from  a  psychological  point  of  view  these  pro- 
cesses may  be  termed  symptoms,  although  they  occur  in  per- 
fect health.  They  may  be  further  likened  to  neurotic  symp- 
toms in  that  they  represent  flaws  in  the  normal  functioning 
of  the  mind. 

Freud's  principal  thesis  in  this  connection  may  be  thus 
stated:  Certain  inadequacies  of  our  mental  functioning, 
and  certain  apparently  purposeless  performances,  can  be 
shown  by  means  of  psycho-analysis  to  have  been  determined 
by  motives  of  which  we  were  not  at  the  time  aware.  The 
occurrences  in  question  have  the  following  characteristics  in 
common :  They  belong  to  what  may  be  called  normal  behavior. 
They  are  only  temporary  disturbances  of  a  function  which 
at  another  moment  would  be  correctly  performed.  Their 
incorrectness  is  at  once  recognized  as  soon  as  attention  is 
drawn  to  them.  We  can  trace  no  motive  for  them  at  first, 
but  always  attribute  them  to  "inattention,"  to  "chance," 
and  so  on. 

It  will  be  seen  from  this  that,  according  to  Freud,  our  mental 
processes  are  more  rigorously  determined  than  is  commonly 
believed,  and  that  many  of  them  generally  thought  to  be 
causeless  have  in  fact  a  very  precise  and  definable  cause^ 
The  same  remark  applies  to  many  mental  processes  where  we 
believe  we  have  a  perfectly  free  choice.  A  typical  instance 
of  this  is  afforded  by  the  child  game  "think  of  a  number." 
Whereas  at  first  sight  it  would  appear  that  we  are  free  to 
choose  any  possible  number,  careful  analysis  shows,  as  was 
first  pointed  out  by  Adler^  a  few  years  ago,  that  the  number 
actually  chosen  is  always  connected  with  some  mental  process 
of  considerable  personal  significance,  though  this  may  never 
have  been  realized  by  the  subject,  and  that  the  choice  has  been 
determined  by  definite  preceding  mental  constellations.  I 
may  relate  an  example  of  this,  obtained  from  an  unbelieving 
acquaintance.  He  produced  the  number  986,  and  defied  me 
to  connect  it  with  anything  of  especial  interest  in  his  mind. 
Using  the  free-association  method  he  first  recalled  a  memory, 
which  had  not  previously  been  present  to  him,  and  which  was 
to  the  following  effect.  Six  years  ago,  on  the  hottest  day  he 
could  remember,  he  had  seen  a  joke  in  an  evening  newspaper, 
which  stated  that  the  thermometer  had  stood  at  986  deg.  F., 
evidently  an  exaggeration  of  98.6  deg.  F.  We  were  at  the 
time  seated  in  front  of  a  very  hot  fire,  from  which  he  had  just 
drawn  back,  and  he  remarked,  probably  quite  correctly,  that 
the  heat  had  aroused  this  dormant  memory.     However,   I 

1  Alfred  Adler:  Drei  Psycho- Analysen  von  Zahleneinf alien  und  ob- 
sedierenden  Zahlen.     Psychiatr-Neurol.  Woch.  1905.    Jahrg.  VII.    S.  263. 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOIyOGY  OF   EVERYDAY  UFE  479 

was  curious  to  know  why  this  memory  had  persisted  with  such 
vividness  as  to  be  so  readily  brought  out,  for  with  most  people 
it  surely  would  have  been  forgotten  beyond  recall,  unless  it 
had  become  associated  with  some  other  mental  experience  of 
more  significance.  He  told  me  that  on  reading  the  joke  he  had 
laughed  uproariously,  and  that  on  many  subsequent  occasions 
he  had  recalled  it  with  great  relish.  As  the  joke  was  obviously 
of  an  exceedingly  tenuous  nature,  this  strengthened  my  ex- 
pectation that  more  lay  behind.  His  next  thought  was  the 
general  reflection  that  the  conception  of  heat  had  always 
greatly  impressed  him,  that  heat  was  the  most  important 
thing  in  the  universe,  the  source  of  all  life,  and  so  on.  This 
remarkable  attitude  of  a  quite  prosaic  young  man  certainly 
needed  some  explanation,  so  I  asked  him  to  continue  his  free 
associations.  The  next  thought  was  of  a  factory  stack  which 
he  could  see  from  his  bedroom  window.  He  often  stood  of  an 
evening  watching  the  flame  and  smoke  issuing  out  of  it,  and 
reflecting  on  this  deplorable  waste  of  energy.  Heat,  flame, 
the  source  of  life,  the  waste  of  vital  energy  issuing  from  an 
upright,  hollow  tube — it  was  not  hard  to  divine  from  such 
associations  that  the  ideas  of  heat  and  fire  were  unconsciously 
linked  in  his  mind  with  the  idea  of  love,  as  is  so  frequent  in 
symbolic  thinking,  and  that  there  was  a  strong  masturbation 
complex  present,  a  conclusion  that  he  presently  confirmed. 
His  choice  of  the  number  was  therefore  far  from  being  a  free 
one,  being  in  fact  related  to  a  very  significant  personal  con- 
stellation. 


II.    Forgetting 

One  of  Freud's  most  notable  contributions  to  psychology, 
and  a  conception  fundamental  in  his  study  of  the  present 
group  of  mental  processes,  was  his  discovery  that,  in  addition 
to  the  other  causes  of  forgetting,  *' repression"  (Verdrdngung) 
plays  a  most  important  part.  Others  before  Freud  had  realized 
the  existence  of  this,  but  it  was  reserved  for  him  to  demon- 
strate the  extent  to  which  it  is  operative  in  both  normal  and 
abnormal  mental  life. 

Freud  regards  repression  as  a  biological  defence-mechanism, 
the  function  of  which  is  to  guard  the  mind  from  painful  ex- 
periences. He  holds  that  there  is  in  the  mind  of  every  one  a 
tendency  to  forget  the  things  that  the  person  does  not  like  to 
be  reminded  of,  in  other  words,  painful  or  disagreeable  memo- 
ries. It  is  true  that  we  often  remember  against  our  will 
matters  that  we  would  rather  forget,  but  there  are  two  expla- 
nations for  this.  In  the  first  place,  such  disagreeable  haunting 
memories  are  frequently  themselves  only  the  replacements 


480  JONISS 

of  buried  and  still  more  disagreeable  ones,  with  which  they 
are  associated,  an  occurrence  allied  to  that  concerned  in  the 
genesis  of  true  obsessions.  In  the  second  place,  the  capacity 
to  forget  painful  experiences  is  only  of  a  certain  strength, 
which  differs  greatly  in  different  people,  and  is  not  always  suc- 
cessful in  achieving  its  aim.  It  is  but  rarely  that  one  can  for- 
get the  death  of  a  dear  relative,  however  desirable  that  might 
be,  for  the  associative  links  to  other  conscious  memories  are 
too  well  formed.  In  such  cases,  what  happens  is  that  trivial 
memories,  which  by  association  might  serve  unnecessarily 
to  remind  us  of  the  painful  event,  are  apt  to  get  forgotten, 
the  name  of  the  medical  attendant,  details  as  to  the  fatal 
malady,  and  so  on;  the  tide  of  amnesia  covers  the  base  of  the 
hill,  but  cannot  reach  the  summit.  By  this  means  an  economy 
is  effected  in  the  number  of  times  that  the  painful  memory  is 
recalled  to  consciousness.  Further,  it  must  be  remarked  that, 
for  reasons  which  cannot  here  be  gone  into,  repression  acts 
much  more  extensively  in  causing  forgetfulness  of  in- 
ternal, extremely  intimate,  and  personal,  mental  processes 
than  of  what  may  be  called  external  memories,  known  to 
the  world,  such  as  failure,  grief,  and  so  on.  As  is  well  known, 
Freud  has  applied  his  conception  of  repression  to  a  number  of 
other  fields,  notably  to  the  explanation  of  infantile  and  hys- 
terical amnesias,^  which  do  not  here  concern  us. 

A  good  instance  of  the  recognition  of  the  part  played  in 
everyday  life  by  repression  has  been  furnished  by  Darwin,  in 
a  passage  that  does  equal  credit  to  his  scientific  honesty  and 
his  psychological  acumen.^  He  writes,  in  his  autobiography: 
"I  had,  during  many  years,  followed  a  golden  rule,  namely, 
that  whenever  a  published  fact,  a  new  observation  or  thought 
came  across  me,  which  was  opposed  to  my  general  results,  to 
make  a  memorandum  of  it  without  fail  and  at  once;  for  I 
had  found  by  experience  that  such  facts  and  thoughts  were 
far  more  apt  to  escape  from  the  memory  than  favourable 
ones."  Pick^  quotes  a  number  of  authors  who  more  or  less 
clearly  recognize  that  a  defensive  striving  against  painful 
memories  can  lead  to  their  becoming  forgotten,  but,  as  Freud 
remarks,  no  one  has  so  exhaustively  and  at  the  same  time  so 
incisively  described  both  the  process  itself  and  the  psychologi- 
cal basis  of  it  as  has  Nietzche  in  his  Jenseits  von  Gut  und 
Bose;   "Das  habe  ich  getan,  sagt    mein   Gedachtnis.     Das 

iFreud:  Selected  Papers  on  Hysteria,  and  Three  Contributions  to 
Sexual  Theory.     Transl.  by  A.  A.  Brill. 

^lytfe  of  Charles  Darwin.     Ed.  by  Francis  Darwin.     1902.     p.  42. 

'Pick :  Zur  Psychologic  des  Vergessen  bei  Geistes-  und  Nervenkranken. 
Arch.  f.  Kriminal-Anthropologie  u.  Kriminalistik.  1905.  Bd.  XVIII 
S.  251. 


THE   PSYCH  OP  ATHOLOGY   O^  EVERYDAY   LIFE  48 1 

kann  ich  nicht  getan  haben,  sagt  mein  Stolz  und  bleibt  uner- 
bittlich.     Endlich — gibt  das  Cedachtnis  nach." 

The  class  of  forgotten  thoughts  in  everyday  life  to  which 
this  mechanism  applies  is  of  course  that  where  the  other 
causes  of  forgetting  do  not  provide  adequate  explanations; 
in  other  words,  it  principally  concerns  matters  that  we  should 
normally  expect  to  remember.  For  instance,  one  would  ex- 
pect some  hidden  reason  in  the  case  of  the  name  of  a  near 
relative  or  friend  being  forgotten  much  more  readily  than  in 
the  case  of  a  casual  acquaintance.  The  examples  of  the 
mechanism  may  conveniently  be  divided  into  two  groups: 
(i)  forgetting  to  carry  out  some  intended  purpose  (Vergessen 
von  Vorsatzen),  and  (2)  forgetting  a  given  memory. 

(i)     Forgetting  to  carry  out  an  intention 

A  field  in  which  some  counter-will  frequently  leads  to  for- 
getting is  that  regarding  the  making  or  keeping  of  appoint- 
ments. A  man  unwillingly  feels  that  he  should  invite  a 
given  acquaintance  to  a  social  function  he  is  giving  in  the  near 
future.  He  says  to  him,  "You  will  be  sure  to  come,  won't 
you.  I  am  not  absolutely  certain  of  the  date  at  this  moment, 
but  I  will  send  you  a  written  invitation  and  let  you  know." 
He  forgets,  until  it  is  too  late,  and  his  excessive  self-reproach 
betrays  his  unconscious  culpability  and  shows  that  the  for- 
getting was  not  altogether  an  accident.  Maeder^  relates  the 
case  of  a  lady  who  forgot  to  keep  her  appointment  with  the 
dressmaker  to  try  on  her  bridal  gown  the  day  before  the  wed- 
ding, recollecting  it  only  at  eight  in  the  evening.  One  must 
suppose  that  her  whole  heart  was  not  in  the  marriage,  and  in 
fact  she  has  since  been  divorced.  In  my  own  life  I  have 
noted  numerous  instances  of  a  purposeful  forgetting  of  ap- 
pointments, particularly  with  patients.  If  a  given  patient 
is  very  tedious  and  uninteresting,  I  am  very  apt  to  forget  that 
I  have  to  see  him  at  a  certain  hour,  and  if  a  doctor  telephones 
to  ask  me  whether  I  can  see  an  interesting  case  at  that  hour, 
I  am  more  likely  than  not  to  tell  him  that  I  shall  be  free  then. 
Indeed  I  can  recall  several  annoying  quandaries  that  this  habit 
has  led  me  into.  One  is  perhaps  worth  repeating,  as  showing 
how  complete  can  be  the  divorce  between  two  memories  when 
an  Unlust  motive  is  in  action.  Some  years  ago,  when  in  a 
junior  position  at  a  certain  hospital,  I  was  asked  by  my  chief 
to  see  his  out-patients  on  Friday,  as  he  wished  to  attend  an 
important  luncheon  at  the  time.  It  was  an  exceptional 
request,  for  the  rule  was  that  approbation  of  the  committee 
had  to  be  obtained  before  a  substitute  was  allowed  to  act, 

^Maeder:  Contributions  k  la  psychopathologie  de  la  vie  quotidienne. 
Arch,  de  Psychol.  1907.     t.  VI.  p.  150. 


482  JONES 

and  I  gladly  consented,  quite  forgetting  that  I  already  had 
at  the  same  time  an  appointment  which  I  was  very  desirous 
of  keeping,  and  which  would  have  been  particularly  incon- 
venient to  postpone.  On  several  occasions  during  the  week, 
while  going  over  my  future  engagements,  I  thought  of  both 
these,  but  never  together;  the  thought  would  come,  "let  me 
see,  at  one  on  Friday  I  have  to  be  at  such-and-such  a  place," 
and  a  few  hours  later  a  similar  thought  would  come  concern- 
ing the  other  place.  The  two  intentions,  both  of  which  I 
was  anxious  not  to  forget,  were  kept  distinct  from  each  other, 
as  if  in  water-tight  compartments.  When  the  time  came  I 
forgot  the  hospital  appointment,  and  to  my  intense  chagrin 
heard  that  my  chief  was  very  annoyed  about  being  called 
away  from  his  luncheon  on  account  of  my  apparent  unpardon- 
able remissness.  At  the  present  time  my  memory  chiefly 
fails  in  this  respect  in  regard  to  visiting  patients  in  nursing- 
homes,  a  duty  I  find  irksome  on  account  of  the  time  consumed. 
Often  when  I  am  busy  I  conveniently  forget,  and  recently  I 
left  a  patient  without  her  daily  visit  for  nearly  a  week.  The 
self-reproach  one  feels  on  recollecting  the  forgotten  duty  on 
these  and  similar  occasions  is  indicative  of  the  true  significance 
of  the  occurrence.  This  significance  is  intuitively  realized 
in  the  case  of  lovers.  A  man  who  has  failed  to  appear  at  a 
rendezvous  will  seek  in  vain  to  be  forgiven  on  the  plea  that  he 
had  forgotten  about  it,  will  indeed  with  this  plea  only  increase 
the  lady's  resentment.  Even  if  he  falls  back  on  the  customary 
psychological  explanations,  and  describes  how  urgent  business 
had  filled  his  mind,  he  will  only  get  as  reply,  "How  curious 
that  such  things  didn't  happen  last  year;  it  only  means  that 
you  think  less  of  me."  Similarly,  when  a  man  begins  to  be 
forgetful  about  paying  accustomed  attentions  to  his  wife, 
overlooks  her  birthday,  and  so  on,  she  correctly  interprets 
it  as  a  sign  of  a  change  in  their  relations. 

Another  field  where  forgetting  occurs  to  an  untoward  extent 
is  in  giving,  a  fact  that  indicates  a  more  wide-spread  objection 
to  giving  than  is  agreeable  to  our  altruistic  conceptions.  Most 
of  those  who  have  filled  secretarial  positions  have  been  aston- 
ished to  find  the  difficulty  there  is  in  collecting  subscriptions 
as  they  fall  due,  and  the  ease  with  which  people  with  other- 
wise good  memories  "overlook"  such  matters.  It  is  far 
from  rare  for  them  even  to  falsify  their  memory,  and  to  assert 
firmly  that  they  have  already  paid.  A  few,  dimly  conscious 
of  their  weakness,  compensate  for  it  by  forming  the  habit 
of  promptly  paying  every  bill  as  soon  as  it  arrives.  In  general, 
however,  there  is  a  striking  difference  between  the  ease  with 
which  one  remembers  to  send  to  the  bank  incoming  cheques, 
and  that  with  which  one  forgets  to  pay  incoming  bills.     The 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  I.IFE  483 

same  tendency  is  the  explanation  of  the  constant  "forgetting" 
to  return  borrowed  books  that  seems  to  afflict  so  many  people, 
a  habit  which  must  have  distressed  most  people  who  have  a 
good  library.  This  observation  will  be  confirmed  by  any  one 
who  has  tried  to  establish  a  permanent  library  in  an  insti- 
tution where  many  coming  and  going  students  have  ready 
access  to  it. 

Almost  as  common  is  the  habit  of  forgetting  to  post  letters. 
Here,  also,  unconscious  motives  can  sometimes  be  detected 
in  individual  instances.  Sometimes  one  leaves  a  letter  on 
one's  desk  for  several  days,  forgetting  each  time  to  take  it 
with  one;  in  such  cases  it  may  be  reckoned  on  that  there  is 
some  secret  opposition  to  sending  the  given  letter.  In  one 
instance  of  the  kind  I  ultimately  posted  the  letter,  but  forgot 
to  address  the  envelope.  It  was  returned  to  me  through  the 
dead  letter  office,  I  addressed  it,  and  again  posted  it,  but 
this  time  without  a  stamp.  I  was  then  forced  to  recognize 
that  there  was  in  me  an  unconscious  opposition  to  the  sending 
of  the  letter,  one  of  which  I  had  previously  been  unaware, 
but  which  manifested  itself  in  external  inhibitions.  One  does 
not  forget  to  post  a  letter  that  one's  mind  is  in  full  har- 
mony about  sending;  for  instance,  a  love  letter.  One  is  more 
apt  to  forget  to  send  a  letter  containing  a  cheque  than  one 
containing  an  account.  Often  the  resistance  is  of  a  general 
order.  Thus  a  busy  man  forgets  to  post  letters  entrusted 
to  him — to  his  slight  annoyance — by  his  wife,  just  as  he  may 
"forget"  to  carry  out  her  shopping  orders.  Inhibitions  of 
this  kind  sometimes  betray  a  veiled  antagonism  towards  the 
person  whose  behests  we  forget  to  fulfil.  They  constitute 
a  way  of  depreciating  the  importance  of  the  other  person  for 
ourselves,  and  when  pronounced  in  general  they  indicate  a 
lack  of  consideration  for  others,  based  on  an  excessive  self- 
absorption  or  abnormally  high  self-estimation. 

In  examples  similar  to  these  preceding  the  counter-impulse 
that  inhibits  the  memory  is  as  a  rule  directed  immediately 
against  the  conscious  intention.  In  a  more  complicated 
series  of  cases,  which  the  Germans  term  Fehlleistungen,  it  is 
directed  against  some  other  mental  process,  which,  however, 
stands  in  associative  relation  to  it;  this  mental  process  is, 
so  to  speak,  symbolized  in  the  conscious  intention.  The 
following  are  two  examples  of  the  kind.  Maeder^  relates  the 
case  of  a  hospital  interne  who  had  an  important  business  ap- 
pointment in  the  town,  but  who  was  not  allowed  to  leave  the 
hospital  until  his  chief,  who  was  out  for  the  evening,  returned. 
He  decided  to  leave  his  post,  nevertheless,  and   on   getting 

^Maeder:  Une  voie  nouvelle  en  psychologic;  Freud  et  son  ecole. 
Coenobium.     Gennaio  1909.     Anno.  III.  p.  100. 


484  JONSS 

back  late  in  the  evening,  was  astonished  to  find  he  had  left 
the  light  burning  in  his  room,  a  thing  he  had  never  done  before 
during  his  two  years  of  service.  He  at  once  perceived  the 
reason  for  his  omission;  his  chief  always  passed  by  the  win- 
dow on  his  way  to  his  own  house,  would  see  the  light  burning 
and  conclude  that  the  assistant  was  at  home.  The  cause 
for  the  inhibition  having  passed,  the  subject  readily  appre- 
ciated it.  A  patient  of  mine  on  a  number  of  occasions  made 
the  remarkable  omission  of  forgetting  to  shave  the  right 
side  of  his  face.  It  was  always  the  same  side,  and  it  was  the 
one  that  was  turned  towards  me  during  the  treatment.  Analy- 
sis of  the  occurrence  showed  that  it  was  determined  by  a  num- 
ber of  unconscious  processes,  of  which  the  following  was  one. 
The  idea  of  hair  was  connected  with  various  sexual  ideas, 
and  the  non-shaving  of  the  side  turned  to  me  symbolized  a 
disinclination  to  lay  bare  his  sexual  life,  the  occurrence  always 
synchronizing  in  fact  with  an  outburst  of  resistance  against 
the  treatment. 

2.     Forgetting  a  given  memory 

We  are  concerned  only  with  striking  lapses  in  memory, 
namely,  regarding  matters  that  as  a  rule  we  can  easily  recall. 
An  instance,  which  is  hard  to  credit,  though  I  can  vouch  for 
the  accuracy  of  it,  was  related  to  me  by  a  medical  friend. 
His  wife  was  seriously  ill  with  some  obscure  abdominal  malady, 
and,  while  anxiously  pondering  over  the  possible  nature  of 
it,  he  remarked  to  her,  "It  is  comforting  to  think  that  there 
has  been  no  tuberculosis  in  your  family."  She  turned  to  him 
very  astonished,  and  said  "Have  you  forgotten  that  my 
mother  died  of  tuberculosis,  and  that  my  sister  recovered 
from  it  only  after  having  been  given  up  by  the  doctors?" 
His  anxiety  lest  the  obscure  symptoms  should  prove  to  be 
tubercular  had  made  him  forget  a  piece  of  knowledge  that 
was  thoroughly  familiar  to  him.  Those  accustomed  to 
psycho-analysis  will  surmise  that  there  is  more  to  be  said 
about  the  matter,  but  the  example  will  serve  to  illustrate  the 
influence  affective  processes  have  in  connection  with  for- 
getting. 

It  is  with  proper  names  that  one  observes  the  most  striking 
instances  of  this  process.  In  the  majority  of  cases  the  counter- 
will  that  prevents  a  familiar  name  from  being  recalled  is 
directed  against  some  mental  process  that  is  associated  with 
the  one  to  be  recalled,  rather  than  against  this  itself.  On 
account  of  some  disagreeable  experience  we  would  rather  not 
recall  a  given  name;  we  may  actually  succeed  in  forgetting 
it,  but  more  often  the  tendency  is  shown  indirectly  in  our 
being  unable  to  recall  other  names  resembling  it  and  which 


THE    PSYCHO  PATHOLOGY  OF   EVERYDAY   UFE  485 

might  bring  the  undesired  one  to  our  mind.  In  other  words, 
we  have  to  think  of  the  undesired  name  at  times,  but  we 
guard  ourselves  against  doing  so  more  often  than  is  necessary. 
A  hospital  interne  got  to  know  a  nurse,  whom  he  of  course 
addressed  by  her  surname,  and  in  his  work  saw  her  daily  for 
about  a  year.  They  later  got  more  intimate  and  he  now 
experienced  great  difficulty  in  recalling  her  surname  so  as  to 
address  envelopes  to  her.  On  one  occasion  he  was  unable  to 
write  to  her  for  three  weeks ;  recourse  to  her  letters  was  of  no 
use,  for  she  always  signed  only  her  Christian  name  in  them. 
Investigation  of  the  matter  brought  to  light  the  fact  that  her 
Christian  name  was  the  same  as  that  of  a  girl  he  had  pre- 
viously jilted,  and  also  of  another  girl  he  had  been  passionately 
in  love  with  throughout  his  boyhood.  This  name  he  could 
not  forget.  What  had  happened  was  that  he  had  successively 
transferred  his  affections  from  one  girl  to  the  other,  the  three 
being  unconsciously  identified  in  his  mind.  He  was  thus 
always  true  to  his  love,  and  did  not  wish  to  recall  any  fact,  such 
as  the  different  surname,  that  would  tend  to  remind  him  of  his 
faithlessness.  The  surnames  in  no  way  resembled  one  another. 
BrilP  relates  the  following  example  from  his  own  ex- 
perience. When  working  at  Zurich  he  wished  to  recall  the 
name  of  an  old  patient  of  his,  on  whose  case  he  had  specially 
worked  for  some  months,  but  was  totally  unable  to  do  so. 
He  had  painstakingly  prepared  an  account  of  the  case  for 
publication,  but  at  the  last  moment  his  chief  intervened,  and 
decided  to  report  it  before  a  local  society.  He  was  unex- 
pectedly prevented  from  doing  so,  and  Brill  was  sent  to  read 
the  paper  at  the  meeting,  this  being  credited  to  the  chief. 
In  trying  to  recall  his  patient's  name,  the  name  of  another 
patient,  Appenzeller,  who  was  suffering  from  the  same  disease, 
persistently  presented  itself.  In  the  psycho-analysis  under- 
taken one  apparently  irrelevant  memory  kept  recurring  over 
and  over  again.  This  was  an  actual  scene,  in  which  the  chief 
in  question  had  aimed  with  a  shot-gun  at  a  rabbit,  and  had 
missed,  to  the  amusement  of  Brill  and  the  bystanders.  The 
sought  for  name  ultimately  flashed  up — Lapin  (rabbit),  the 
patient  being  a  French- Canadian.  The  example  is  instructive 
in  illustrating  the  associative  replacement-formations  that 
come  to  the  mind  instead  of  the  proper  memory.  The  sound 
of  the  first  part  of  Appenzeller' s  name  resembles  the  French 
pronunciation  of  Lapin,  and  the  scene  that  kept  recurring, 
the  failure  of  the  chief  to  bag  the  rabbit,  symbolized  the  whole 
incident  that  was  the  cause  of  the  inhibition. 

*A.  A.  Brill:     A  Contribution  to  the  Psychopathology  of  Everyday  Life. 
Psychotherapy,  1909.     p.  9. 


486  JONES 

The  following  instance  is  rather  more  complex,  but  shows 
how  fine  are  the  threads  connecting  unconscious  mental  pro- 
cesses. A  lady  was  unable  to  recall  the  Christian  name  of 
a  near  friend.  The  full  name  was  Isabell  Brown,  but  she 
could  only  recall  the  surname;  instead  of  the  other  the  name 
Isidore  presented  itself,  to  be  at  once  rejected  as  incorrect. 
Thus  the  failure  in  memory  consisted  only  in  the  replacement 
of  the  syllable  Bell  by  Dore.  I  asked  her  to  associate  to  the 
word  Brown,  and  the  two  names  Owlie  and  Leen  at  once 
came  to  her  mind.  It  will  be  noticed  that  the  first  two  letters 
of  the  first  word  and  the  last  one  of  the  second  word  are  con- 
tained in  Brown;  the  only  foreign  ones  in  each  case  form  the 
syllable  **ly"  in  pronunciation,  a  fact  to  be  borne  in  mind. 
The  two  words  were  pet  names  of  two  common  friends,  who 
used  to  live  together  with  the  subject,  and  it  was  in  their 
company  that  she  used  to  see  Miss  Brown.  Concerning  the 
first  one  she  said  that  she  was  at  present  pregnant  for  the 
first  time,  and  that  she  was  anxious  as  to  the  outcome,  be- 
cause certain  characteristics  in  her  figure  had  led  her  to  sus- 
pect that  pelvic  narrowing  might  give  rise  to  difficulties  in 
the  confinement.  She  also  mentioned  another  friend,  Dora 
D.,  who  had  similar  characteristics,  and  Isadora  D.,  a  famous 
dancer,  whom  she  knew  personally,  and  whose  perfect  figure 
she  greatly  admired.  The  name  Isidore,  which  it  will  be 
remembered  was  the  replacement-memory,  reminded  her  of 
the  poem  by  Edgar  Allan  Poe,  Beautiful  Isidore  Lee  (ly). 
I  told  her  that  the  correct  name  of  the  poem  was  Beautiful 
Annabel  Lee;  some  inhibition  was  therefore  acting  against 
the  syllables  Anna  and  Bell.  Thought  of  the  name  Annabel 
brought  to  her  mind  the  name  of  Owlie's  sister  Annie  Sybil, 
which  is  a  sound-contraction  of  Anna  Isabell,  and  at  once 
Miss  Brown's  proper  name  Isabell,  which  I  personally  did 
not  know,  came  to  her  mind.  The  subject  had  recently  had 
a  painful  quarrel  with  Annie  Sybil,  in  which  also  the  latter' s 
sister  had  unfortunately  become  involved;  she  had  always 
thought  it  a  pity  that  the  sister  she  disliked  had  a  better 
figure,  and  was  more  suited  for  matrimony,  than  the  one 
she  was  so  fond  of.  There  were  thus  two  painful  thoughts 
at  the  bottom  of  the  amnesia,  one  the  anxiety  about  Owlie's 
confinement,  and  the  other  that  in  this  respect  the  disliked 
sister  was  more  favorably  situated. 

The  names  first  recalled  by  the  subject,  namely,  Isidore 
Brown,  one  incorrect,  the  other  correct,  were  both  directly 
associated  to  the  syllable  "ly. "  The  suppressed  syllable 
was  "Bell."  In  view  of  the  fact  that  the  word  "belly"  sum- 
marized the  whole  situation,  it  is  difficult  to  avoid  the  in- 
ference that  the  amnesia  for  the  syllable  "Bell"  had  thus 


THE   PSYCHOPATH OI.OGY   OP  EVERYDAY  UPE  487 

proceeded:  One  must  suppose  that  the  thought  of  Miss 
Isabell  Brown  had  unconsciously  reminded  the  patient  of 
their  common  friend  and  her  sister;  the  diphthong  in  the 
surname  further  is  identical  with  that  in  the  former's  name, 
Owlie,  and  the  Christian  name  resembles  the  second  part  of 
the  latter's  name,  Annie  Sybil.  The  first  part  of  the  latter 
name,  Annie,  reminded  her  of  "Beautiful  Annabel  Lee," 
making  the  word  "belly"  which  symbolized  the  painful 
thoughts  in  question.  These  thoughts  nevertheless  came 
to  expression  in  the  false  replacement-memory.  First  the 
accent  was  shifted  from  the  first  syllable,  "bell,"  of  the 
objectionable  word  to  the  second,  "ly,"  which  was  also  the 
second  syllable  of  Owlie's  name.  This,  however,  was  un- 
suitable for  forming  a  name  by  being  added  to  the  remembered 
part  "Isi,"  so  that  a  further  shifting  took  place  in  which  it 
was  replaced  by  "dore."  Dora  was  the  name  of  a  friend 
with  similar  characteristics  to  Owlie's,  but  in  combination 
with  "Isi"  it  was  the  name  of  another  person,  Isadora  D.,  who 
was  strikingly  free  from  them.  The  subject,  therefore,  invests 
her  friend  with  the  beautiful  and  healthy  attributes  of  the 
famous  dancer.  One  might  even  go  farther  and  surmise  that 
the  reason  why  Dore  had  appeared  rather  than  Dora  was  be- 
cause the  word  "door,"  which  is  constantly  used  symbolically 
for  any  exit  (for  instance,  of  the  body,  as  in  the  Song  of  Songs) 
was  better  adapted  to  symbolize  the  suppressed  complex  than 
the  word  Dora  is.  To  many  readers  this  reconstruction  will 
probably  appear  as  too  fine-spun.  In  my  opinion,  however, 
they  underestimate  the  combination  of  delicacy  and  rigor 
with  which  unconscious  and  foreconscious  processes  are  deter- 
mined, a  conclusion  which  can  readily  be  confirmed  by  a  pains- 
taking study  of  similar  material.^ 

A  simple  illustration  of  the  way  in  which  a  strong  affect 
will  cleave  to  a  name,  and  be  transferred  to  any  other  person 
bearing  the  same  or  similar  name,  is  afforded  by  Shakspere 
in  Julius  Caesar  (Act.  Ill  Sc.  3): 

First  Citizen.     Your  name,  sir,  truly. 

Cinna.     Truly,  my  name  is  Cinna. 

First  Citizen.      Tear  him  in  pieces,  he  's  a  conspirator. 

Cinna.  I  am  Cinna  the  poet;  I  am  not  Cinna  the  conspi- 
\^  rator. 

Second  Citizen.  It  is  no  matter;  his  name's  Cinna;  pluck 
but  his  name  out  of  his  heart,  and  turn  him  going. 

A  field  in  which  significance  is  apt  to  be  intuitively  attribu- 
ted to  the  forgetting  of  names,  is  that  where  our  own  are  for- 

^In  the  Zentralbl.  f.  Psychoanalyse,  Jahrg.  i.  Heft  9,  this  analysis  is 
carried  to  a  farther  stage. 


488  JONES 

gotten.  Few  people  can  avoid  feeling  a  twinge  of  resentment 
when  they  find  that  their  name  has  been  forgotten,  particu- 
larly if  it  is  by  some  one  with  whom  they  had  hoped  or  ex- 
pected it  would  be  remembered.  They  instinctively  realize 
that  if  they  had  made  a  greater  impression  on  the  person's 
mind  he  would  certainly  have  remembered  them  again,  for 
the  name  is  an  integral  part  of  the  personality.  Similarly, 
few  things  are  more  flattering  to  most  people  than  to  find 
themselves  addressed  by  name  by  a  great  personage  where 
they  could  hardly  have  anticipated  it.  Napoleon,  like  most 
leaders  of  men,  was  a  master  of  this  art.  In  the  midst  of  the 
disastrous  Campaign  of  France,  in  1814,  he  gave  an  amazing 
proof  of  his  memory  in  this  direction.  When  in  a  town  near 
Craonne  he  recollected  that  he  had  met  the  mayor,  De  Bussy, 
over  twenty  years  ago  in  the  La  Fere  regiment ;  the  delighted 
De  Bussy  at  once  threw  himself  into  his  service  with  extra- 
ordinary zeal.  Conversely  there  is  no  surer  way  of  affronting 
some  one  than  by  pretending  to  forget  his  name;  the  insinua- 
tion is  thus  conveyed  that  the  person  is  so  unimportant  in  our 
eyes  that  we  cannot  be  bothered  to  remember  his  name. 
This  device  is  often  exploited  in  literature.  In  Turgenev's 
Smoke  (p.  255)  the  following  passage  occurs.  "  'So  you  still 
find  Baden  entertaining,  M'sieu — Litvinov.*  Ratmirov  al- 
ways uttered  Litvinov's  surname  with  hesitation,  every  time, 
as  though  he  had  forgotten  it,  and  could  not  at  once  recall  it. 
In  this  way,  as  well  as  by  the  lofty  flourish  of  his  hat  in  salut- 
ing him,  he  meant  to  insult  his  pride."  The  same  author  in 
his  Fathers  and  Children  (p.  107)  writes,  "The  Governor 
invited  Kirsanov  and  Bazarov  to  his  ball,  and  within  a  few 
minutes  invited  them  a  second  time,  regarding  them  as 
brothers,  and  calling  them  Kisarov."  Here  the  forgetting  that 
he  had  spoken  to  them,  the  mistake  in  the  names,  and  the 
inability  to  distinguish  between  the  two  young  men,  con- 
stitute a  culmination  of  disparagement.^  Falsification  of  a 
name  has  the  same  significance  as  forgetting  it;  it  is  only  a 
step  towards  complete  amnesia.  The  word-contamination 
in  this  instance  shows  a  striking  psychological  intuition  of 
the  process  termed  by  Freud  "identification;"  it  indicated 
that  in  the  Governor's  eyes  the  characteristics  of  the  young 
men  were  so  little  marked,  and  the  men  so  unimportant,  that 
he  did  not  think  it  worth  while  to  make  the  effort  of  differ- 
entiating one  from  the  other.     Sensitiveness  about  the  correct 

iln  literature  disparagement  is  often  indicated  by  the  forgetting  of  other 
matters  besides  names.  Thus  in  Bernard  Shaw's  "Caesar  and  Cleopatra," 
Caesar's  indifference  to  Cleopatra  is  depicted  by  his  being  vexed,  on  leaving 
Egypt,  at  having  forgotten  something  he  has  to  do;  finally  he  recollects 
what  it  is — to  say  Good-bye  to  Cleopatra. 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  LIFE      489 

Spelling  of  one's  name  is  extremely  frequent;  we  all  know  the 
profound  difference  that  members  of  Scottish  clans  see  between 
Mc  and  Mac,  and  a  practical  psychologist  realizes  the  impor- 
tance of  being  sound  on  the  matter  every  time  he  writes  such 
a  name.  I  had  thought  personally  that  I  was  free  from  such 
sensitiveness  until  a  little  occurrence  some  time  ago  taught 
me  the  contrary.  An  article  of  mine  had  been  published  in  a 
German  journal;  only  my  surname  was  printed,  with  the  letters 
M.  D.  (which  are  not  used  prof essionally  in  Germany)  attached, 
as  if  they  were  the  initials.  The  same  morning  I  had  occa- 
sion to  fill  up  a  lunacy  certificate,  and  was  surprised  at  the 
secretary  laughing  when  I  handed  it  in;  I  had  signed  it  with 
my  Christian  name  only,  thus  compensating  for  the  omission 
in  the  article.  This  sensitiveness  has  sometimes  deeper 
roots  than  mere  personal  self-esteem;  Stekel^  has  traced  it  to 
infantile  complexes  relating  to  the  giver  of  the  name — the 
father. 

The  following  two  instances  in  my  own  experience  are 
similar  to  those  quoted  from  Turgenev.  The  first  relates  to 
Mr.  Mayo  Robson,  the  eminent  gastro-intestinal  surgeon, 
after  whom  was  named  a  bobbin  he  had  invented  for  the  oper- 
ation of  entero-anastomosis.  Another  surgeon,  almost  equally 
eminent  in  the  same  field  of  work,  and  living  in  the  same  town, 
remarked  one  day  in  a  lofty  and  contemptuous  manner, 
"This  patient  had  previously  been  unsuccessfully  operated 
on  by  a  man  called  Rayo  Bobson,  or  Bayo  Dobson,  or  some 
such  name."  His  motive  was  evident,  and,  of  course,  quite 
conscious.  In  the  second  instance  the  mistake  in  the  name 
was  quite  unconsciously  made  as  the  result  of  a  falsification 
of  memory,  but  the  significance  was  very  similar.  It  was  at 
a  university  graduation  ceremony,  where  a  number  of  visitors 
were  present  arrayed  in  multi-colored  and  imposing  robes. 
Those  so  attired  formed  a  procession  in  double  file.  A  friend 
of  mine,  a  foreigner,  remarked  as  Professor  Titchener  passed, 
"Let  me  see,  who  is  that?  Is  n't  it  Kitchener?"  Many  would 
be  inclined  to  see  no  significance  in  the  mistake,  although 
my  friend  knew  the  names  of  Lord  Kitchener  and  Professor 
Titchener  fairly  well.  I  have,  however,  to  add  these  two 
additional  facts.  A  few  minutes  before,  while  talking  about 
experimental  psychologists  in  general,  he  allowed  himself 
to  make  the  scurrilous  remark  that  in  his  opinon  they 
should  be  called  the  pantry-cooks  of  psychology  on  account 


/Stekel:  Warum  sie  den  eigenen  Namen  hassen.  Zentralbl.  f.  Psy- 
choanalyse, Jahrg.  I,  Heft  3,  S.  109.  See  also  his  article,  Die  Verpflichtung 
des  Namens.  Zeitschr.  f.  Psychother.  u.  med.  Psychol.  Feb.,  191 1.  Bd.  III. 
S.  110. 


490  JONISS 

of  their  menial  field  of  work;  the  passage  from  "cook"  to 
"kitchen"  is  obvious.  Secondly  he  had  also  commented  on 
the  martial  appearance  of  this  dazzling  procession,  and  I  can 
readily  imagine  his  being  especially  struck  by  Professor  Titch- 
ener's  soldierly  bearing.  It  is  difficult  to  avoid  the  inference 
that  these  two  trends  of  thought,  present  in  his  mind  so  re- 
cently, played  their  part  in  the  falsification  of  the  name,  which 
thus  betrayed  his  private  opinion  of  the  field  of  work  in  which 
Professor  Titchener^  is  so  eminent. 

Many  people  have  a  strikingly  bad  memory  for  names,  even 
when  their  memory  is  otherwise  good.  This  is  generally 
explained  by  saying  that  proper  names  are  among  the  latest 
acquired  knowledge,  so  that  our  memory  of  them  is  especially 
fragile ;  in  accordance  with  the  law  of  dissolution  these  memo- 
ries are  among  the  first  to  be  lost,  a  process  that  constitutes 
one  of  the  most  characteristic  signs  of  approaching  senility. 
This  explanation  is  difficult  to  harmonize  with  two  facts, 
first  that  in  many  cases  the  memory  is  weak  in  this  connection 
when  it  is  notably  good  in  regard  to  other  more  complex  and 
later  acquired  matters,  such  as  scientific  formulae,  and  so  on, 
and  secondly  that  the  characteristic  in  question  is  much  more 
pronounced  with  some  people  than  with  others.  When  the 
opportunity  of  making  a  psycho-analysis  with  some  one  of 
this  type  presents  itself  two  other  matters  are  brought  to  light 
with  considerable  constancy,  namely,  that  for  various  reasons 
the  person's  own  name  has  acquired  an  unusual  psychical 
significance,  so  that  it  becomes  invested  with  the  feeling-tone 
of  the  whole  personality,  and  that  there  is  a  strong  ego-com- 
plex present.  It  would  seem,  therefore,  that  the  general 
inability  to  bear  other  people's  names  in  mind  is  an  expression 
of  an  excessively  high  estimation  of  the  importance  of  one's 
own  name  and  of  oneself  in  general,  with  a  corresponding 
indifference  to  or  depreciation  of  other  people.  In  my  own 
experience  I  have  most  often  found  this  characteristic  with  peo- 
ple having  either  an  extremely  common  or  an  extremely  rare 
name,  both  contingencies  leading  to  undue  sensitiveness  in 
the  matter,  but  I  cannot  put  this  forward  as  being  a  general 
rule.  It  further  seems  to  me  probable  that  the  increasing 
difficulty  of  retaining  names  that  is  such  a  frequent  accom- 
paniment of  advancing  years,  may  in  part  at  least  b*e  attributed 
to  the  growing  self-esteem  brought  by  success  and  by  cessation 
from  the  turmoils  and  conflicts  of  youth. 

^I  trust  that  Mr.  Robson  and  Professor  Titchener  will  pardon  my  sacri- 
ficing the  personal  privacy  of  their  names  in  the  cause  of  science.  I  have 
purposely  selected,  from  a  large  number  of  similar  instances,  two  in  which 
the  contrast  between  a  rare  individual  disparagement  and  an  otherwise 
universal  respect  is  especially  striking. 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOLOGY   OF   EVERYDAY  I.IFE  49 1 

Falsification  of  memory,  as  was  indicated  above,  is  closely 
related  to  forgetting,  and  is  influenced  by  the  same  motive. 
A  common  instance  is  the  mistakes  made  with  regard  to  the 
day  of  the  week.  Some  one  who  is  eagerly  anticipating  an 
event  at  the  end  of  the  week  is  very  apt  to  think  it  is  Wednes- 
day when  it  is  only  Tuesday,  and  so  on;  their  impatience  at 
the  slowness  with  which  the  week  is  passing  manifests  itself 
as  an  error — in  the  desired  direction — as  to  the  present  date. 

Other  mental  operations,  besides  recollecting,  may  be 
falsified  in  the  same  way,  a  process  designated  by  Freud  as 
an  "  Irrtum.''  Several  examples  related  elsewhere  in  this 
paper  might  be  classified  in  this  group,  so  that  one  here  will 
suffice.  I  was  buying  some  flowers,  and  put  two  dollars,  the 
exact  price  of  them,  on  the  counter.  While  they  were  being 
got  ready,  I  changed  my  mind  about  one  bunch,  and  told  the 
woman  serving  me  to  leave  it  out;  it  should  be  said  that 
she  was  the  owner  of  the  shop.  On  taking  the  money  a  few 
moments  later  she  said,  '  *  that  bunch  cost  forty  cents,  so  that 
will  make  two  dollars  forty."  Her  wish  that  I  were  making 
the  order  larger  instead  of  smaller  was  probably  concerned 
in  the  mistake. 

A  few  concluding  remarks  may  be  added  on  this  mechanism 
of  forgetting.  The  main  points  may  be  summarized  in  the 
statements  that  forgetting  is  often  determined  by  a  painful 
mental  process  (Unlust)  of  which  the  subject  is  unaware, 
either  at  the  time  only  or  permanently;  that  this  inhibiting 
mental  process  may  be  a  counter-will  to  recollecting  the 
matter  in  question  or  may  be  associated  to  this  in  a  more  com- 
plex way;  and  that  a  false  memory  presenting  itself  in  the 
place  of  the  true  is  a  symbolic  substitute  of  this,  standing 
in  associative  connection  with  it.  Two  general  considera- 
tions indicate  that  acts  of  forgetting,  of  the  type  illustrated 
above,  are  not,  as  is  commonly  supposed,  accidental  or  due  to 
chance.  First  is  the  fact  that  the  same  one  tends  to  be  re- 
peated. If  we  forget  to  carry  out  a  given  intention,  or  are 
unable  to  recall  a  given  name,  the  failure  is  apt  to  recur,  thus 
suggesting  that  it  has  a  specific  cause.  Secondly  is  the  fact 
that  in  at  least  two  spheres  of  life  it  is  universally  recognized 
that  remembering  is  under  control  of  the  will,  so  that  a  failure 
to  remember  is  regarded  as  synonymous  with  a  not  wanting 
to  remember.  Freud^  writes:  " Frauendienst  wie  Militar- 
dienst  erheben  den  Anspruch,  dass  alles  zu  ihnen  Gehorige  dem 
Vergessen  entriickt  sein  miisse,  und  erwecken  so  die  Meinung, 
Vergessen  sei  zulassig  bei  unwichtigen  Dingen,  wahrend  es  bei 
wichtigen  Dingen  ein  Anzeichen  davon  sei,  dass  man  sie  wie 

^Freud:     Op.  cit.,  S.  83. 


492  JONES 

unwichtige  behandeln  wolle,  ihnen  also  die  Wichtigkeit  ab- 
spreche."  A  soldier  who  forgets  to  perform  a  given  duty  is 
punished  regardless  of  the  excuse.  He  is  not  allowed  to  forget, 
and  whether  his  not  wanting  to  perform  the  duty  is  openly 
expressed,  or  indirectly,  as  by  his  forgetting,  is  considered  by 
his  officer  as  comparatively  irrelevant.  The  standard  set  by 
women  is  equally  severe;  a  lover  who  forgets  his  lady's  wishes 
is  treated  as  though  he  openly  declared  them  unimportant. 


III.    Lapsus  Lingu.^ 

The  everyday  occurrence  of  the  defect  in  psycho-physical 
functioning  popularly  known  as  a  slip  of  the  tongue  has  not 
received  much  attention  from  psychologists.  The  attempts 
made,  by  Meringer  and  Mayer  and  others,  to  explain  on  pho- 
netic grounds  the  particular  mistake  made  have  signally 
failed,  for  on  the  one  hand  many  cases  are  to  be  observed  where 
no  phonetic  factors  are  in  operation,  and  on  the  other  hand 
careful  study  shows  that  such  factors  are  at  the  most  accessory 
or  adjuvant  in  nature,  and  are  never  the  essential  cause. 

According  to  Freud  the  word  said  in  mistake  is  a  manifes- 
tation of  a  second  suppressed  thought,  and  thus  arises  outside 
the  train  of  thought  that  the  speaker  is  intending  to  express. 
It  may  be  a  word,  or  phrase,  entirely  foreign  to  this  train  of 
thought,  being  taken  in  its  entirety  from  the  outlying  thought, 
or  it  may  be  a  compromise-formation,  in  which  both  come  to 
expression.  In  the  latter  case  the  false  word  may  be  a  neolo- 
gism ;  a  common  example  of  this  is  where  a  speaker,  intending 
to  use  the  word  "aggravating,"  says  " How  very  aggravoking," 
the  word  "provoking"  having  intruded  itself;  many  mal- 
apropisms  are  formed  in  this  way,  being  the  result  of  uncer- 
tainty as  to  which  is  the  most  appropriate  word. 

The  secondary  thought  that  thus  obstrudes  itself  on  the  in- 
tended speech  may,  like  the  motives  of  repressive  forgetting, 
be  of  two  kinds:  (i)  a  general  counter-impulse  (Gegenwillen) 
directed  immediately  against  the  speech,  or  (2)  another 
thought  accidentally  aroused  by  it.  In  the  latter  case  it  can 
represent  either  a  continuation  of  a  theme  previously  in  the 
speaker's  mind,  or  a  thought  aroused,  through  a  superficial 
association,  by  the  theme  that  is  intended  to  be  spoken;  even 
when  it  represents  a  continuation  of  a  previous  theme  it  will 
generally,  if  not  always,  be  found  that  there  is  some  association 
between  this  and  the  theme  of  the  speech.  It  will  readily  be 
understood  that  in  many  cases  the  disturbing  thought  is  not 
evident,  but  can  be  revealed  only  by  investigation,  sometimes 
a  searching  psycho-analysis  being  necessary. 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  LIFE      493 

Cases  where  the  disturbing  thought  is  a  direct  counter- 
impulse  are  usually  easy  to  interpret.  One  instance  will 
suffice.  A  President  of  the  Austrian  Reichstag  finished  his 
introductory  remarks  by  declaring  the  session  closed,  instead 
of  opened;  as  the  particular  session  promised  nothing  but 
fruitless  wrangles,  one  can  sympathize  with  his  wish  that  it 
were  already  at  an  end. 

Some  cases  where  the  disturbing  thought  is  nearly  related 
to  the  intended  theme  are  equally  simple.  A  French  gov- 
erness in  Dr.  Stekel's  family^  asked  his  wife  that  she  might  re- 
tain her  testimonials,  saying:  "Je  cherche  encore  pour  les 
apres-midis,  pardon,  pour  les  avant-midis."  The  slip  betrayed 
her  feeling  of  dissatisfaction  with  th^ afternoon  engagement, 
and  her  intention  to  look  for  another  situation  for  the  after- 
noons as  well  as  the  mornings,  an  intention  she  proceeded  to 
carry  out. 

A  friend  of  mine  was  driving  his  motor-car  slowly  and  cau- 
tiously one  day,  when  a  cyclist,  who  was  riding  with  his  head 
down,  furiously,  and  on  the  wrong  side  of  the  street,  ran  into 
him  and  damaged  his  bicycle.  He  sent  in  a  bill  for  $50.00, 
and,  as  my  friend  refused  to  pay,  he  sued  him  in  court.  When 
I  enquired  as  to  the  result  of  the  action  my  friend  said,  "the 
judge  reprimanded  the  prisoner  for  careless  riding."  I 
corrected  him,  "You  mean  the  plaintiff,  not  the  prisoner." 
"Well,"  he  replied,  "I  think  the  fellow  should  have  been 
arrested  for  furious  riding." 

A  lady  when  speaking  of  Bernard  Shaw's  works  said  to  me, 
"I  think  very  highly  of  all  my  writings,"  instead  of  "all  his 
writings."     She  was  an  amateur  writer  of  short  stories. 

An  unmarried  man,  a  patient,  remarked,  "my  father  was 
devoted  to  my  wife."  He  meant,  of  course,  either ' '  his  wife ' '  or 
"my  mother."  This  is  a  typical  instance  of  a  lapsus  that  would 
pass  as  being  entirely  accidental  and  devoid  of  significance. 
I  must  add,  however,  that  one  of  the  main  causes  of  the 
patient's  neurosis  was  an  unconscious  incestuous  attachment 
to  his  mother,  so  that  his  unsuppressed  thoughts  on  the  sub- 
ject of  the  remark  would  run  in  full,  "My  attitude  towards 
my  mother  is  the  same  as  that  of  my  father."  No  alteration 
is  too  slight  to  have  a  meaning.  The  instance  narrated  above, 
in  which  the  first  letter  only  of  Titchener's  name  was  replaced 
by  a  K,2  belongs  to  the  subject  of  lapsus  linguae  equally  as  much 
as  to  that  of  forgetting. 

^Related  by  Freud.     Op.  cit.  S.  48. 

2This  replacing  of  the  initial  letter  of  a  word  by  that  of  another  word, 
typically  from  the  same  sentence,  is  known  in  Oxford  as  a  Spoonerism, 
on  accoimt  of  a  distinguished  professor  who  had  the  habit  of  committing 
the  particular  slip. 

JOURNAI, — 2 


494  JONES 

Such  self -betrayals  as  those  just  related  sometimes  afford 
valuable  insight  into  character  and  motive.  I  was  present 
at  the  International  Congress  in  Amsterdam  when  the  fol- 
lowing curious  episode  occurred.  There  was  a  heated  dis- 
cussion regarding  Freud's  theory  of  hysteria.  One  of  the  most 
violent  opponents,  who  is  noted  as  having  worked  long  and 
fruitlessly  on  the  subject  of  hysteria,  was  grudgingly  admitting 
the  value  of  the  earlier  work  of  Breuer  and  Freud — the  con- 
clusions of  which  he  had  himself  discovered  to  be  true — as 
a  prelude  to  a  vehement  denunciation  of  the  dangerous  ten- 
dencies of  Freud's  later  work.  During  his  speech  he  twice 
said,  "Breuer  and  ich  haben  bekanntlich  nachgewiesen,"  thus 
replacing  Freud's  name  by  his  own,  and  revealing  his  envy 
of  Freud's  originality. 

The  following  example  is  more  complicated.  In  talking 
of  the  financial  standards  so  prevalent  in  modern  civilization 
I  said,  "In  yesterday's  newspaper  there  were  the  headings  'Ten 
million  dollar  fire  in  Halifax;  six  lives  lost.'"  It  was  at 
once  pointed  out  to  me  that  I  had  said  Halifax  instead  of 
Bangor,  Maine.  Analysis  brought  the  following  free  asso- 
ciations. Until  a  few  years  ago  I  was  disgracefully  ignorant 
of  the  existence  of  Bangor,  Maine,  and  I  remember  in  college 
days  being  puzzled  by  the  reference  to  Maine  in  the  well- 
known  student  song  "Riding  down  from  Bangor,"  as  in  my 
ignorance  I  supposed  that  this  related  to  Bangor,  the  univer- 
sity town  of  Carnarvonshire,  Wales.  The  name  Bangor 
essentially  stands  in  my  mind  for  the  original  Bangor.  It 
brought  up  a  memory  of  the  recent  controversy  as  to  whether 
the  new  National  Welsh  Library  should  be  established  at 
Bangor,  at  Swansea  (my  home),  or  at  Cardiff  (the  university 
town  where  I  studied).  This  reminded  me  of  interests  I 
have  in  the  contents  of  this  library,  in  Celtic  mythology, 
which  naturally  carried  me  to  the  valuable  library  of  mytho- 
logical books  that  I  possess  myself.  Then  I  remembered  that 
what  had  especially  struck  me  in  reading  about  the  recent 
fire  was  the  fact  that  a  valuable  collection  of  books  had  been 
destroyed  in  it,  and  that  this  had  made  me  enter  a  note  not 
to  forget  to  renew  my  fire  insurance,  which  had  recently  lapsed, 
before  leaving  in  the  coming  week  for  a  fortnight's  visit  to 
the  United  States. 

The  meaning  of  my  lapsus  is  beginning  to  emerge.  A 
library  fire  at  Bangor  was  too  near  home  for  my  peace  of  mind, 
and  my  unconscious  had  consolingly  relegated  it  to  some 
other  spot.  The  next  problem  is  to  discover  the  motive  for 
the  replacement  of  Bangor  by  Halifax,  a  process  that  was 
greatly  "over-determined."  Maine  is  from  its  geographical 
position  closely  associated  in  my  mind  with  the  Maritime 


THS    PSYCHOPATHOLOGY   OF   EVERYDAY   I.IFE  495 

Provinces  of  Canada,  and  only  on  the  preceding  day  a  Cana- 
dian had  been  demonstrating  to  me  on  a  map,  for  the 
nth  time,  how  Maine  should  rightfully  have  formed  part  of 
these  Provinces.  Still  that  does  not  explain  why  I  selected 
Halifax  rather  than  St.  John,  the  other  town  I  know  the  name 
of  in  the  Maritime  Provinces.  One  reason  doubtless  was  the 
fact  that  at  the  time  I  was  treating  a  patient  from  Halifax, 
Nova  Scotia,  who  had  recently  been  telling  me  that  the  houses 
there  were  mostly  built  of  wood,  and  therefore  were  exposed 
to  the  danger  of  fire.  The  name  Halifax,  however,  is  better 
known  to  me  as  an  English  euphemisim  for  Hell,  as  in  the  ex- 
pression, "Go  to  Hal-ifax."  This  called  up  the  memory  of 
half-forgotten  childhood  fears,  for,  like  most  Welsh  children, 
I  was  carefully  nurtured  with  a  proper  dread  of  what  was 
called  "the  burning  fire;"  as  I  grew  up  I  was  comforted  to 
learn  the  groundlessness  of  this  particular  dread.  My  slip  of 
the  tongue,  therefore,  registered  my  desire  that  any  library 
fire  should  be  in  some  other  place  than  in  my  home,  and  if 
possible  in  a  non-existent  locality.^ 

An  example,  for  which  I  am  indebted  to  Dr.  A.  A.  Brill, 
is  peculiar  in  that  the  slip  of  the  tongue  represented  a  resolu- 
tion in  opposition  to  the  conscious  intention.  A  man,  who 
on  account  of  homosexual  practices  was  in  constant  fear  of 
coming  into  conflict  with  the  law,  invited  two  lady  friends  to 
spend  an  evening  at  the  theatre.  They  expressed  a  wish  to 
see  a  play  called  "Alias  Jimmy  Valentine,"  which  deals 
largely  with  convicts  and  prisons.  He  was  far  from  comfort- 
able at  the  idea  of  spending  an  evening  with  such  thoughts, 
but  could  not  well  avoid  it.  On  getting  into  the  cab  to  drive 
to  the  theatre,  however,  he  accidentally  gave  the  driver  the 
name  of  another  theatre,  and  did  not  notice  the  mistake  until 
they  arrived  there,  when  it  was  too  late  to  rectify  it.  At 
this  theatre  the  play  was  about  the  cleverness  with  which  a 
daughter  outwitted  her  selfish  old  father.  It  was  not  without 
significance  that  the  subject's  attitude  towards  his  own  father 
was  one  of  pronounced  hostility,  so  that  his  slip  of  the  tongue 
had  the  effect  of  exchanging  an  evening  with  a  painful  topic 
for  one  with  a  topic  that  he  greatly  enjoyed. 

Several  non-scientific  writers  before  Freud  had  noted  the 
psychological  significance  of  accidental  slips  of  the  tongue. 
Freud^  quotes  examples  of  this  from,  for  instance,  Brantome 
and  Wallenstein.  Shakspere  himself  furnishes  a  beautiful 
one  in  the  Merchant  of  Venice  (Act.  Ill  Sc.  2).  It  occurs  in 
the  scene  where  Portia  is  expressing  her  anxiety  lest  the  fa- 

^This  analysis  led  further  into  previously  unconscious  thoughts,  which 
are  too  intimate  for  me  to  describe  here. 
2Freud:     Op.  ciL,  S.  50,  58. 


k 


496  JONKS 

vored  suitor  should  fare  as  badly  as  the  distasteful  ones  in 
the  hazard  set  for  them  by  her  father.  She  wants  to  tell 
Bassanio  that  in  the  event  of  his  failure  she  would  nevertheless 
belong  to  him,  but  is  prevented  by  her  promise  to  her  father. 
In  this  mental  discord  she  speaks: — 

There  is  something  tells  me  (but  it  is  not  love), 
I  would  not  lose  you;  and  you  know  yourself 
Hate  counsels  not  in  such  a  quality. 
But  lest  you  should  not  understand  me  well, 
(And  yet  a  maiden  hath  no  tongue  but  thought) 
I  would  detain  you  here  a  month  or  two, 
Before  you  venture  for  me.     I  could  teach  you 
How  to  choose  right,  but  then  I  am  forsworn; 
So  will  I  never  be;  so  may  you  miss  me; 
But  if  you  do,  you  '11  make  me  wish  a  sin. 
That  I  had  been  forsworn.     Beshrew  your  eyes. 
They  have  o'erlooked  me,  and  divided  me: 
One  half  of  me  is  yours,  the  other  half  yours, — 
Mine  own,  I  would  say;  but  if  mine,  then  yours, 
And  so  all  yours. 

Rank^  comments  on  this  passage:  "Gerade  das,  was  sie 
ihm  also  bloss  leise  andeuten  mochte,  weil  sie  es  eigentlich 
ihm  iiberhaupt  verschweigen  sollte,  dass  sie  namlich  schon 
vor  der  Wahl  ganz  die  seine  sei  und  ihn  liebe,  das  lasst  der 
Dichter  mit  bewundernswertem  psychologischem  Feingefiihl 
in  dem  Versprechen  sich  offen  durchdrangen  und  weiss  durch 
diesen  Kunstgriff  die  unertragliche  Ungewissheit  des  Liebenden 
sowie  die  gleichgestimmte  Spannung  des  Zuhorers  iiber  den 
Ausgang  der  Wahl  zu  beruhigen. " 

Our  greatest  novelist,  George  Meredith,  in  his  masterpiece. 
The  Egoist,  shows  an  even  finer  understanding  of  the  mech- 
anism. The  plot  of  the  novel  is,  shortly,  as  follows :  Sir  Wil- 
loughby  Patterne,  an  aristocrat  greatly  admired  by  his  circle, 
becomes  engaged  to  a  Miss  Constantia  Durham.  She  dis- 
covers in  him  an  intense  egoism,  which  he  skilfully  conceals 
from  the  world,  and,  to  escape  the  marriage,  she  elopes  with 
a  Captain  Oxford.  Some  years  later  Patterne  becomes  en- 
gaged to  a  Miss  Clara  Middleton,  and  most  of  the  book  is 
taken  up  with  a  detailed  description  of  the  conflict  that  arises 
in  her  mind  on  also  discovering  his  egoism.  External  circum- 
stances, and  her  conception  of  honor,  hold  her  to  her  pledge, 
while  he  becomes  more  and  more  distasteful  in  her  eyes.  She 
partly  confides  in  his  cousin  and  secretary,  Vernon  Whitford, 
the  man  whom  she  ultimately  marries,  but,  from  a  mixture 
of  motives,  he  stands  aloof. 

^Otto  Rank:  Zentralbl.  f.  Psychoanalyse.    Heft  3,  S.  110. 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOI^OGY  OP  EVERYDAY  UPE      497 

In  a  soliloquy  Clara  speaks  as  follows:  "If  some  noble 
gentleman  could  see  me  as  I  am  and  not  disdain  to  aid  me! 
Oh!  to  be  caught  out  of  this  prison  of  thorns  and  brambles. 
I  cannot  tear  my  own  way  out.  I  am  a  coward.  A  beckon- 
ing of  a  finger  would  change  me,  I  believe.  I  could  fly  bleed- 
ing and  through  hootings  to  a  comrade.  .  .  .  Constantia  met 
a  soldier.  Perhaps  she  prayed  and  her  prayer  was  answered. 
She  did  ill.  But,  oh,  how  I  love  her  for  it.  His  name  was 
Harry  Oxford.  .  .  .  She  did  not  waver,  she  cut  the  links, 
she  signed  herself  over.  O  brave  girl,  what  do  you  think  of 
me?  But  I  have  no  Harry  Whitford,  I  am  alone"  .... 
"the  sudden  consciousness  that  she  had  put  another  name 
for  Oxford,  struck  her  a  buiffet,  drowning  her  in  crimson." 

The  fact  that  both  men's  names  end  in  "ford"  evidently 
renders  the  confounding  of  them  more  easy,  and  would  by 
many  be  regarded  as  an  adequate  cause  for  this,  but  the 
real  underlying  motive  for  it  is  plainly  indicated  by  the  author. 
In  another  passage  the  same  lapsus  occurs,  and  is  followed 
by  the  hesitation  and  change  of  subject  that  one  is  familiar 
with  in  psycho-analysis  when  a  half- conscious  complex  is 
touched.  Sir  Willoughby  patronizingly  says  of  Whitford: 
"False  alarm.  The  resolution  to  do  anything  unaccustomed 
is  quite  beyond  poor  old  Vernon."  Clara  replies:  "But  if 
Mr.  Oxford — Whitford  .  .  .  your  swans  coming  sailing  up 
the  lake,  how  beautiful  they  look  when  they  are  indignant.^ 
I  was  going  to  ask  you,  surely  men  witnessing  a  marked  ad- 
miration for  some  one  else  will  naturally  be  discouraged?" 
"Sir  Willoughby  stiffened  with  sudden  enlightenment." 

In  still  another  passage  Clara  by  another  lapsus  betrays 
her  secret  wish  that  she  was  on  a  more  intimate  footing  with 
Vernon  Whitford.  Speaking  to  a  boy  friend  she  says:  "Tell 
Mr.  Vernon— tell  Mr.  Whitford." 

In  relation  to  these  two  literary  passages  I  made  a  personal 
slip  of  the  tongue  that  illustrates  the  probity  of  the  uncon- 
scious mind  as  contrasted  with  the  duplicity  of  the  conscious 
one.  Expounding  the  subject  of  lapsus  linguae  to  some  one 
I  said  that  I  had  come  across  two  interesting  literary  examples, 
in  Meredith's  Egoist  and  in  Shakspere's  Love's  Labour  Lost; 
when  detailing  the  second  I  noticed  that  I  had  named  the 
wrong  play.  Analysis  of  the  mistake  brought  the  following 
memories.  On  the  preceding  day,  while  talking  of  the  sources 
of  Shakspere's  plots,  I  had  made  the  remark  that  the  only 
one  he  had  not  taken  from  previous  authors  was  that  con- 

^The  nature  of  the  change  of  the  subject  here  accurately  betrays  the  con- 
tent of  the  imderlying  affect,  indignation  at  Patteme's  disparagement  of 
Whitford,  just  as  a  mediate  association  reaction  indicates  the  nature  of 
the  complex  stimulated. 


498  JONES 

tained  in  Love's  Labour  Lost.  Some  six  months  before, 
Professor  Freud  had  told  me  that  he  had  heard  from  Dr. 
Otto  Rank  that  there  was  in  the  Merchant  of  Venice  an  ex- 
ample of  lapsus  linguae  attributed  to  the  disturbing  influence 
of  a  suppressed  thought,  but  he  could  not  tell  me  where  it  oc- 
curred. On  looking  back  I  realize  that  I  felt  just  a  touch  of 
pique,  though  I  did  not  pay  any  attention  to  it  at  the  time,  at 
not  having  observed  it  myself,  and  took  the  first  opportunity  to 
re-read  the  play,  when  of  course  I  came  across  the  example. 
The  one  in  the  Egoist  I  had  really  observed  myself.  My 
statement  that  I  had  discovered  the  two  examples  in  question 
was  therefore  only  three  parts  true.  The  fact,  which  I  had 
suppressed,^  that  Dr.  Rank  deserved  some  credit,  leaked 
through  to  external  expression  in  my  error  of  naming  the 
wrong  play,  substituting  Shakspere's  only  original  one.  An  in- 
teresting feature  of  the  example  is  the  fact  that  a  few  minutes 
before  I  had  been  relating  how  a  man  not  over-scrupulous  in  the 
matter  of  priority  had  betrayed  his  dishonesty  in  a  treacherous 
slip  of  the  tongue.  No  doubt  deeper  factors  than  interest  in 
scientific  priority  were  also  operative  in  my  own  case,  such 
as  rivalry  and  an  "English"  complex,  both  of  which  are 
matters  that  play  a  very  subordinate  part  in  my  conscious 
mental  life. 

IV.    Lapsus  Calami 

The  introductory  remarks  made  on  the  subject  of  slips  of 
the  tongue  apply  almost  literally  to  slips  of  the  pen.  One 
principal  difference  is  that  the  delay  interposed  by  the  mechan- 
ical acts  of  writing  enables  disturbances  of  co-ordination  to 
occur  with  especial  readiness,  as  can  be  illustrated  by  a  glance 
over  any  author's  manuscript.  The  necessity  for  numerous 
corrections  indicates  that,  whether  owing  to  the  intricacy 
of  the  subject-matter  or  to  a  lack  of  clearness  in  the  author's 
mind,  a  harmonious  flow  is  far  from  being  attained.  General 
perplexities  mirror  themselves  in  half-conscious  hesitations 
as  to  the  choice  of  individual  words.  Thus,  a  correspondent, 
who  could  n't  decide  as  to  the  advisability  of  a  given  proposal, 
wrote  to  me  that  it  might  turn  out  to  be  "umpracticle," 
evidently  a  contamination  of  "impracticable"  and  "unprac- 
tical." 

A  field  of  frequent  errors  is  that  of  dates.  Many  people 
continue  to  write  the  date  of  the  previous  year  throughout 
a  great  part  of  January.  Not  all  such  mistakes  are  due  to 
the  fixation  of  habit,  as  is  readily  assumed ;  sometimes  they  sig- 
nify a  disinclination  to  accept  the  fact  that  yet  another  by-gone 

^Naturally  I  excused  this  to  myself  on  the  ground  that  pedantic  ac- 
curacy is  uncalled  for  in  conversation;  but  the  facts  remain. 


TH:e  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  UFE     499 

year  has  brought  them  nearer  to  old  age,  a  reflection  that  is  apt 
to  be  prevalent  at  the  turn  of  the  year.  Regrets  that  such  and 
such  a  date  is  already  past,  or  impatience  that  it  has  not  yet 
arrived,  are  common  motives  of  such  unconscious  mistakes. 
A  student  dated  a  letter  to  me  April  11,  191 1,  instead  of  April 
22.  An  examination  was  due  in  the  first  week  of  May  for 
which  he  was  very  unprepared,  and  I  attributed  his  slip  to 
the  wish  that  there  was  twice  as  much  time  ahead  of  him  in 
which  to  get  ready.  That  the  date  he  actually  wrote  was  the 
1 1  th  was  no  doubt  influenced  by  the  presence  of  these  ciphers 
at  the  end  of  191 1,  but  it  is  to  be  noted  even  in  this  connection 
that  his  mistake  consisting  in  writing  them  earlier  than  he 
should,  i.  e.,  in  putting  the  date  earlier.  As  with  the  phonetic 
factors  entering  into  slips  of  the  tongue,  the  fact  that  the 
part  wrongly  written  occurs  elsewhere  in  the  same  line  only 
predisposes  to  the  mistake;  such  factors  do  not  cause  the 
mistake,  they  only  make  it  easier  to  assume  that  particular 
form. 

For  the  following  example  I  am  indebted  to  Dr.  A.  A.  Brill. 
A  patient  wrote  to  him  on  the  subject  of  his  sufferings,  which 
he  tried  to  attribute  to  worry  about  his  financial  affairs  in- 
duced by  a  cotton  crisis :  "  my  trouble  is  all  due  to  that  damned 
frigid  wave;^  there  isn't  even  any  seed."  What  he  really 
wrote,  however,  was  not  "wave"  but  "wife."  In  the  bottom 
of  his  heart  he  cherished  half-avowed  reproaches  against  his 
wife,  on  account  of  her  sexual  anaesthesia  and  childlessness, 
and  he  dimly  realized,  with  right,  that  his  life  of  enforced 
abstinence  played  an  important  part  in  the  genesis  of  his 
symptoms. 

As  with  slips  of  the  tongue,  no  mistake  is  too  slight  to  be 
significant.  The  following  four  are  instances,  selected  from 
a  considerable  number  of  similar  ones,  in  which  it  consisted 
only  in  the  replacement  of  one  letter  by  another. 

A  correspondent  of  mine  had  published  a  scientific  paper 
on  a  sexual  subject,  and  was  writing  to  me  about  a  virulent 
criticism  of  it  that  had  appeared;  the  critic  had  used  such 
passionately  denunciatory  language  as  to  make  it  evident 
that  the  topic  of  the  paper  had  aroused  some  strong  personal 
complex.  My  correspondent's  first  sentence  was  "Have 
you  seen  X's  satyrical  criticism  of  my  paper.'*",  plainly  in- 
dicating by  his  unconscious  substitution  of  "y"  for  "i"  his 
estimate  of  the  nature  of  the  criticism. 

Some  two  years  ago  I  was  writing  to  an  old  friend,  whom  I 
had  always  called  by  his  surname.  On  account  of  family 
ties  it  became  more  appropriate  to  address  him  by  his  Christian 

*  Meaning  in  the  money-market. 


500  JONES 

name,  and,  after  a  momentary  embarrassment  natural  under 
the  circumstances,  I  took  up  my  pen  and  began,  "Dear 
Fred."  To  my  amazement,  however,  I  saw  that  I  had  sHpped 
in  a  "u"  before  the  final  letter  of  the  name.  This  may  seem 
a  very  trivial  mistake,  and  due  to  the  similarity  of  the  two 
words,  but  a  psycho-analytic  conscience  tends  to  be  more 
unsparing  in  the  criticism  of  its  owner,  as  it  is  more  sparing 
in  that  of  others.  Two  memories  at  once  rushed  to  my  mind. 
One  was  of  a  dream  I  had  had  two  years  before,  at  a  time 
when  I  was  debating  with  myself  whether  it  would  be  politic 
openly  to  defend  the  Freudian  principles,  the  truth  of  which 
my  experience  had  made  me  accept.  In  the  dream  I  was  in 
a  swiftly-moving  motor-omnibus,  the  driver  of  which  was  a 
composite  figure  (Sammelperson)  ,^  bearing  mostly  the  linea- 
ments of  my  friend.  An  angry  crowd  surrounded  us,  and 
threatened  the  driver  for  "going  so  fast."  It  became  necessa- 
ry for  me  to  decide  whether  to  stand  aloof  or  to  side  with  the 
driver,  and  I  did  the  latter.  I  need  not  give  the  other  details 
of  the  dream,  but  the  analysis  showed  it  to  be  a  presentation 
of  my  waking  dilemma,  the  driver  being  a  replacement-figure 
for  Professor  Freud.  I  had  recently  been  taken  for  a  long 
motor  ride  by  my  friend,  who  by  the  way  has  a  German  sur- 
name, and  though  at  first  I  had  qualms  as  to  the  recklessness 
of  his  driving  I  soon  perceived,  to  my  relief,  that  this  was  only 
apparent  and  that  he  was  really  an  exceedingly  skilful  and 
reliable  driver.  Before  the  incident  of  the  lapsus  calami, 
therefore,  he  had  long  been  unconsciously  associated  in  my 
mind  with  Professor  Freud.  The  second  memory  was  of  a 
letter  I  had  recently  written  to  a  Canadian  Professor  of  a 
subject  allied  to  my  own.  On  coming  to  Canada  I  had  felt 
very  awkward  and  constrained  at  the  American  custom  of 
formally  prefacing  a  man's  title  to  his  name  when  addressing 
him,  and  it  was  a  long  time  before  I  got  accustomed  to  being 
spoken  to  by  both  younger  and  older  colleagues  as  Dr.  Jones 
or  as  Doctor.  It  embarrassed  me  to  have  to  speak  to  even 
fairly  intimate  friends  in  this  way,  and  in  the  case  of  the  gentle- 
man in  question  I  frankly  told  him,  in  the  letter  referred  to 
above,  that  my  English  prejudices  would  not  let  me  do  it  with 
any  degree  of  comfort.  As  he  was  some  fifteen  years  older 
than  myself  I  wondered  afterwards  whether  he  might  resent 
a  younger  man  taking  the  initiative  of  addressing  him  simply 
by  his  surname.  The  slip  of  the  pen  now  began  to  take  on 
a  different  aspect,  and  I  was  obliged  to  recognize  in  it  the 
manifestation  of  a  snobbish  wish  that  I  was  on  sufficiently 
close  personal  terms  with  Professor  Freud  to  allow  such  a 

^SeeAmer.  Journ.  of  Psychol.,  April,  1910,  p.  287. 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOLOGY   OF   EVERYDAY  LIFE  50I 

familiar  mode  of  address.  I  feel  certain  that  no  thought  of 
the  kind  had  ever  entered  my  consciousness,  to  which  it  is 
quite  strange,  though  my  intense  reaction  of  shame  con- 
vinced me  of  the  reality  of  its  existence.  The  circumstances 
of  the  slip  of  the  pen  were  extraordinarily  favorable  to  its 
occurrence,  the  similarity  in  the  names,  the  previous  identi- 
fication of  the  men,  the  occasion  of  the  letter  following  so 
soon  after  the  other  one,  and  so  on.  If  it  were  not  for  this, 
I  hardly  think  that  such  a  deeply  repressed  wish  could  have 
come  to  expression,  at  least  not  so  flagrantly. 

I  am  indebted  to  Dr.  A.  A.  Brill  for  the  following  personal 
example.  Although  by  custom  a  strict  teetotaler,  he  yielded 
to  a  friend's  importunity  one  evening,  in  order  to  avoid  offend- 
ing him,  and  took  a  little  wine.  During  the  next  morning  an 
exacerbation  of  an  eye-strain  headache  gave  him  cause  to  re- 
gret this  slight  indulgence,  and  his  reflections  on  the  subject 
found  expression  in  the  following  slip  of  the  pen.  Having 
occasion  to  write  the  name  of  a  girl  mentioned  by  a  patient 
he  wrote  not  Ethel  but  Ethyl. ^  It  happened  that  the  girl 
in  question  was  rather  too  fond  of  drink,  and  in  Dr.  Brill's^ 
mood  at  the  time  this  characteristic  of  hers  stood  out  with 
conspicuous  significance. 

Some  three  years  ago  I  was  writing  to  a  friend  in  England, 
and  gave  the  letter  to  a  member  of  my  family  to  post.  For- 
tunately she  noticed  I  had  made  a  mistake  in  the  address, 
having  written  as  the  street  number  19  instead  of  55.  The 
two  numbers  do  not  even  resemble  each  other,  so  that  the 
customary  explanations  are  here  more  than  ever  in  default. 
I  will  relate  a  few  of  the  associations  as  they  occurred.  The 
name  of  the  street,  Gordon  St.,  brought  "Gordon  Highlanders — 
the  Highlands — the  thought  that  my  friend  is  an  ardent  mount- 
aineer— the  thought  that  Professor  Freud  is  very  fond  of  the 
mountains  —  Berg  (=Mountain)  —  Berggasse,  the  street  in 
Vienna  in  which  Professor  Freud  lives, — the  number  of  his 
house,  19."  The  friend's  name,  Morris  brought  "morris — 
dancers — maypole — phallus — sex — Professor  Freud's  works  on 
sexual  subjects."  In  desperation  I  started  again  with  Gordon, 
which  now  brought  "the  regiment  called  the  Gay  Gordons — 
gay  women   (the  London  euphemism  for  prostitutes) — the 

^Ethyl  alcohol  is  of  course  the  chemical  name  for  ordinary  alcohol. 

^In  writing  my  manuscript  I  made  the  slip  of  replacing  the  word  Brill 
by  that  of  Bree,  the  name  of  another  medical  friend.  The  mistake  is 
evidently  a  contamination  derived  from  the  word-picture  of  *  'Brill  on  the 
spree,"  and  is  determined  by  the  memory  of  tenuous  jests  relating  to  Berlin 
on  the  (river)  Spree;  both  the  vowel  and  the  consonants  of  Brill  are  con- 
tained in  the  word  Berlin.  It  is  only  right  to  add,  however,  that  the 
thoughts  of  both  Dr.  Brill  and  Dr.  Bree  are  intimately  connected  in  my 
mind  with  Berlin  in  ways  that  discretion  prevents  me  from  describing. 


502  JONES 

German  equivalent,  Freudenmadchen — a  cheap  joke  I  had 
heard  in  Germany  in  this  connection  on  Professor  Freud's 
name;"  as  a  matter  of  fact  I  had  on  the  previous  evening  read  a 
passage  in  his  Traumdeutung  where  he  refers  to  jokes  on  names. 
Turn  which  way  I  would  I  arrived  at  the  same  end-point,  and  I 
began  to  suspect  that  this  was  not  chance.  It  might  be  said 
that  for  some  reason  or  other,  whether  from  the  number 
coinciding  with  that  in  the  Berggasse  or  what  not,  thoughts 
relating  to  Professor  Freud  were  at  the  time  occupying  my 
mind  to  the  exclusion  of  all  else,  in  reply  to  which  I  have  to 
say  that  I  do  not  find  this  so  in  other  analyses,  and  that  in  my 
experience,  whenever  free,  unforced  associations  constantly 
lead  in  the  same  direction  there  is  some  good  reason  for  it; 
in  such  cases  there  is  invariably  some  essential,  significant 
connection  between  the  starting-point  and  the  end  reached. 
Further,  the  more  far-fetched  and  strained  the  associations 
appear,  as  in  this  example,  in  other  words  the  more  superficial 
they  are,  the  more  important  is  the  underlying  essential 
connection  found  to  be.  This  conclusion,  clearly  demon- 
strated in  Jung's  experimental  work,  was  fully  confirmed  in 
the  present  instance.  Although  I  could  see  no  possible  con- 
nection between  my  friend  and  Professor  Freud,  of  whom 
he  knew  nothing,  I  was  led  to  investigate  the  contents  of  the 
letter  I  had  sent  him.  To  my  amazement  I  found  that 
the  main  feature  of  it  could  be  applied  to  Professor  Freud 
in  the  same  sense,  and  that  I  must  unknowingly  have 
harbored  a  wish  to  send  it  to  him ;  in  the  slip  in  writing 
I  had  expressed  my  unconscious  wish  to  send  the  letter  to 
another  man  by  addressing  the  envelope  partly  to  him  and 
partly  to  the  one  I  consciously  intended  it  to  go  to.  There 
can  be  no  question  as  to  the  intense  personal  significance  of  the 
complex  covered  by  the  superficial  associations  of  the  analysis, 
for  wild  horses  would  not  tear  from  me  the  contents  of  that 
letter. 

Mistakes  in  addressing  envelopes,  as  in  the  example  just 
mentioned,  are  generally  manifestations  of  some  disturbing 
thought  that  the  writer  does  not  mean  to  express.  •  A  young 
lady  was  secretly  engaged  to  a  medical  man,  whom  we  will 
call  Arthur  X.  She  addressed  a  letter  one  day  not  to  Dr. 
Arthur  X.,  but  to  Dear  Arthur  X,  thus  expressing  her  desire 
to  let  all  the  world  know  of  their  relationship. 

Not  long  ago  I  was  treating  a  case  of  exceptional  interest  in 
a  patient  who  lived  some  sixty  miles  from  Toronto.  On 
account  of  the  distance  the  patient,  who  could  not  leave  his 
work,  was  able  to  visit  me  only  twice  a  week.  I  found  it  im- 
possible to  treat  him  on  these  conditions,  and  wrote  to  tell 
him  so.     Instead  of  writing  the  name  of  his  town  on  the 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  LIFE      503 

envelope,    however,    I   wrote   Toronto,    displaying   my   wish 
that  he  were  more  conveniently  situated. 

V.     Misprints 

Misprints  may  of  course  arise  from  errors  made  by  the 
writer,  the  editor,  the  proof-reader,  or  the  printer.  From 
time  to  time  the  press  records  amusing  instances  of  a  dis- 
agreeable truth  unintentionally  leaking  out  in  the  form  of  a 
misprint;  in  Freud's  book  several  examples  of  this  are  related.^ 
Unlike  the  other  kinds  of  failure  under  discussion  one 
here  is  rarely  in  a  position  to  obtain  an  objective  verification 
of  a  given  interpretation,  but  sometimes  this  in  itself  reaches 
a  high  grade  of  probability.  At  all  events  general  principles 
indicate  that  the  mistake  made  must  be  determined  by  per- 
sonal constellations  of  whoever  made  it,  and  cannot  be  al- 
together accidental. 

In  a  recent  number  of  the  Zentralblatt  fiir  Psycho-analyse^ 
the  title  of  a  book  of  Gross'  is  wrongly  given  as  "  Das  Freud'- 
sche  Ideogenitatsmonument"  instead  of  Ideogenitatsmoment. 
As  both  the  writer  of  the  article,  and  the  editorial  staff  (Drs. 
Adler  and  Stekel)  regard  the  conception  as  a  monumental  one, 
it  is  possible  that  the  overlooking  of  the  mistake  is  to  be  corre- 
lated with  this  fact. 

In  a  paper  of  my  own  on  nightmare  I  wrote  the  sentence, 
"The  association  in  general  between  the  sex  instinct  and  the 
emotions  of  fear  and  dread  is  a  very  intimate  one."  This 
was  correctly  rendered  in  the  proof,  but  on  the  second  occasion 
of  reading  it  the  proof-reader  was  shocked  to  think  that  I 
could  make  such  an  obviously  outrageous  mistake,  and  altered 
the  word  ''intimate"  to  "distant,"  in  which  form  it  appeared 
in  print. 

In  a  broschure  of  mine  that  appeared  as  a  German  transla- 
tion a  mistake  was  made  of  a  less  unfortunate  kind.  One 
of  my  main  theses  was  that  the  conception  of  Hamlet  rep- 
resented a  projection  of  the  most  intimate  part  of  Shakspere's 
personality,  and  so  thoroughly  did  the  translator  absorb  my 
view  of  the  identity  of  the  two  that,  when  he  came  to  a  passage 
on  the  death  of  Shakspere's  father,  he  substituted  the  name 
Hamlet  for  Shakspere  and  rendered  the  passage  as  referring 
to  "the  death  of  Hamlet's  father  in  1601."  The  substitution 
was  overlooked  in  the  proof  by  two  other  readers  thoroughly 
familiar  with  the  subject. 

In  the  notorious  Wicked  Bible,  issued  in  1631,  the  word 
"not"   was   omitted  from   the   Seventh   Commandment,    so 

^S.  66,  etc. 

2Jahrg.  5,  Heft.  16,  S.  197. 


504  JONES 

that  this  read,  **Thou  shalt  commit  adultery."  The  possi- 
bihty  is  not  to  be  excluded  that  the  editor  had  a  personal 
interest  in  the  subject  of  the  commandment.  At  all  events 
he  was  heavily  fined,  it  being  empirically  recognized  that 
whether  his  purpose  was  conscious  or  unconscious  he  was 
equally  responsible  for  it,  and  that  he  had  no  right,  even  "ac- 
cidentally," to  impute  such  commandments  to  Jahve. 

Type- writing,  being  a  form  of  writing,  is  subject  to  the  same 
influence  as  this.  Mistakes  made  may  be  due  to  either  a 
**  Verschreiben"  or  a  "  Verlesen,"  in  any  case  being  determined 
by  the  previous  mental  constellations  of  the  typist.  Thus 
my  typist,  having  worked  long  in  a  lawyer's  office,  is  fond  of 
replacing  "illogical"  by  "illegal,"  and,  being  of  a  very  proper 
turn  of  mind,  makes  such  mistakes  as  changing  "a  vulgar 
word"  to  "a  regular  word."  I  have  found  that  distinctness 
of  calligraphy  is  powerless  to  prevent  such  mistakes. 

One  practical  aspect  of  this  matter  is  generally  recognized, 
namely,  that  accuracy  in  correcting  proofs  can  be  attained 
only  by  getting  some  one  else  to  do  it  for  one.  A  mistake 
once  made  in  the  manuscript,  and  then  copied,  is  very  apt  to 
get  overlooked  by  the  person  who  made  it.  The  affective 
blindness  that  enabled  him  to  make  the  mistake,  or,  more 
strictly,  that  enabled  an  unconscious  impulse  to  come  to 
expression,  will  very  Hkely  continue  its  action  by  preventing 
him  from  recognizing  it. 

VI.    False  Visual  Recognition 

In  visual  perception  the  same  mistakes  of  affective  origin 
that  were  discussed  in  connection  with  memory  are  frequently 
to  be  observed,  and  here  also  they  are  of  two  kinds,  a  failure 
to  see  something  that  for  various  reasons  we  do  not  want  to 
see,  and  a  falsification  of  perception  in  the  light  of  personal 
complexes.  Examples  of  the  former  kind  are  very  common 
in  connection  with  reading  the  newspaper.  Thus,  just  when 
a  relative  was  crossing  the  Atlantic  last  year,  I  saw  in  the  news- 
headings  that  a  serious  accident  had  happened  to  a  liner, 
but  I  had  the  greatest  difficulty  in  finding  the  account  of  it 
in  the  paper,  overlooking  it  again  and  again. 

False  perceptions  perhaps  consist  most  often  in  catching 
sight  of  one's  name  where  it  really  does  n't  occur.  As  a  rule 
the  word  that  has  attracted  one's  attention  is  very  similar  to 
one's  name,  containing  perhaps  the  same  letters  differently  ar- 
ranged. Professor  Bleuler^  relates  an  example  where  this 
was  not  so,  and  where,  therefore,  the  essential  cause  of  the 
mistake  must  have  been  of  a  greater  affective  intensity;    the 

^Bleuler:    Afifektivitat,  Suggestibilitat,  Paranoia,  1906,  S.  121. 


THK  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY   OF  EVERYDAY  UFE  505 

word  was  really  "Blutkorperchen,"  only  the  first  two  letters 
being  common  to  the  two  words.  He  explained  it  thus: 
"In  diesem  Falle  Hess  sich  aber  der  Beziehungswahn  und 
die  Illusion  sehr  leicht  begriinden:  Was  ich  gerade  las, 
war  das  Ende  einer  Bemerkung  liber  eine  Art  schlechten  Stiles 
von  wissenschaftlichen  Arbeiten,  von  der  ich  mich  nicht  frei 
fiihlte." 

Freud^  quotes  an  example  from  Lichtenberg:  "He  always 
mistook  "angenomnen"  for  "Agamemnon,"  so  thoroughly 
had  he  read  his  Homer."  In  searching  an  American  news- 
paper for  English  political  news  at  the  time  of  the  Navy  scare, 
my  attention  was  caught  by  the  heading  "German  danger;" 
on  looking  nearer  I  saw  that  it  was  "General  danger." 

Similar  observations  can  be  made  in  regard  to  the  percep- 
tion of  other  objects  than  written  matter,  and  especially  with 
the  recognizing  of  other  people.  False  recognition  is  quite 
commonly  due  to  a  pervading  desire  to  meet  the  person  in 
question;  a  lover  who  has  a  rendezvous  with  his  mistress 
fancies  he  sees  her  coming  many  times  over,  when  really  the 
women  he  mistakes  for  her  bear  only  the  faintest  resem- 
blance to  her. 

The  failure  to  greet  a  friend  or  acquaintance  in  the  street 
is  not  always  due  to  not  seeing  them,  and  one  knows  how 
gradual  are  the  shades  between  a  direct  "cut,"  where  one 
person  consciously  pretends  he  does  not  see  the  other,  and  a 
not  seeing  that  is  due  to  a  not  wanting  to  see.^  Women  in- 
tuitively feel  that  the  difference  between  the  two  is  unim- 
portant, and  are  as  much  offended  by  the  one  as  by  the  other; 
some  one  who  thinks  highly  of  them  has  no  right  not  to  see 
them  when  they  pass. 

A  striking  instance  of  this  affective  blindness  occurred  to 
me  not  long  ago.  It  is  part  of  my  routine  duty  to  check  the 
invoices  for  laboratory  apparatus  as  they  come  in,  and  hand 
them  over  to  the  assistant  superintendent  to  see  that  they 
get  paid.  On  one  occasion  I  had  neglected  to  do  this  until 
a  small  number  collected.  I  then  went  through  them,  and 
took  them  with  me  into  the  assistant  superintendent's  office. 
I  was  very  pressed  for  time,  and  hoped  he  would  n't  be  there 
so  that  I  could  simply  deposit  them  on  his  desk;  especially 
so,  as  there  was  a  small  error  in  one  of  them  that  I  had  to 
point  out  to  him,  and  I  realized  that  his  over-conscientious- 
ness would  mean  a  tedious  investigation  of  the  error.  I 
felt,  however,  that  I  ought  to  try  to  find  him,  and  explain 

ipreud:  Op.  cit.  S.  64. 

^One  might  invert  the  familiar  proverb  and  say:  "What  the  heart 
doesn't  grieve  over,  the  eye  doesn't  see." 


5o6  JONES 

the  point  to  him.  On  going  into  his  office  I  saw  several  men 
there,  went  up  to  one  of  them  who  had  his  back  to  me,  and 
said,  "Do  you  know  where  Dr.  X.  is?**  To  my  astonishment 
he  repHed,  "Why,  I  am  Dr.  X."  My  not  recognizing  him  was 
faciHtated  by  the  fact  of  his  having  an  unfamihar  hat  on, 
but  the  actual  cause  of  it  I  knew  well  enough. 

The  phenomenon  of  "fausse  reconnaissance,"  or  "d^ja  vu," 
which  has  perplexed  so  many  psychologists,  is  closely  allied 
to  the  same  category.  Freud  has  finally  solved  this  riddle,^ 
but  as  the  explanation  of  it  is  of  a  more  complex  order  than 
with  the  other  occurrences  under  consideration,  I  shall  not 
go  into  it  here. 

VII.    Mislaying  of  Objects 

It  is  probable  that  objects  are  never  accidentally  mislaid. 
The  underlying  motive  manifests  itself  in  two  ways,  in  the 
act  of  mislaying  the  object,  and  in  the  subsequent  amnesia; 
in  other  words  a  "Verlegen"  is  a  composite  of  a  **  Vergreifen" 
and  a  "Vergessen,"  the  latter  being  the  main  feature.  As 
before,  the  motive  may  be  a  counter-impulse  directed  against 
the  use  of  the  object,  or  against  an  idea  associated  with  the 
use  of  it.     Instances  of  both  will  be  given,  first  of  the  former. 

We  are  all  more  apt  to  mislay  bills  rather  than  cheques, 
and  in  general  objects  that  we  don't  want  to  see  rather  than 
those  we  do.  Apparent  exceptions  to  this  rule,  such  as  the 
mislaying  of  valuable  objects,  come  under  the  second  category, 
where  our  objection  is  not  to  the  thing  itself,  but  to  what  it 
can  remind  us  of. 

A  common  experience,  which  has  often  occurred  to  me  per- 
sonally, is  the  following:  Whenever  I  suffer  from  the  effects 
of  over-smoking,  I  notice  that  it  is  much  harder  to  find  my 
pipe;  it  has  got  put  behind  ornaments  or  books,  and  in  all 
sorts  of  unusual  places  that  it  normally  does  not  occupy. 

A  patient  of  mine  was  recently  very  put  out  at  having 
lost  an  important  bunch  of  keys.  He  told  me  that  he  urgently 
wanted  them  .that  afternoon  to  open  the  lock  of  a  minute 
book  at  a  meeting  with  his  auditor  and  solicitor.  I  en- 
quired ae  to  the  purpose  of  the  meeting.  It  appeared  that  an 
important  resolution  had  been  passed  at  an  annual  directors' 
meeting,  and  that  he  had  omitted  to  enter  it  in  the  minute 
book.  He  was  the  managing  director,  and  it  became  a  ques- 
tion legally  whether  a  certain  action  could  be  taken  without 
the  formal  consent  of  the  other  directors,  or  whether  possibly 
the  minute  could  be  subsequently  added  by  private  arrange- 
ment with  them.     At  all  events  it  was  an  annoying  situation, 

»Freud:     Op.  cit.  S.  139. 


THH  PSYCHOPATHOIyOGY   OF   EVERYDAY   LIFE  507 

and  I  felt  sure  that  his  dishke  of  having  to  face  it  was  connected 
with  the  loss  of  the  key.  Further  enquiry  showed  that  he 
had  used  the  keys  only  once  that  morning,  to  open  his  office 
desk;  after  doing  this  it  was  his  custom  immediately  to  re- 
place them  in  his  pocket,  the  desk  being  provided  with  an 
automatic  closing  lock.  He  had  missed  the  keys  as  soon  as 
he  got  into  the  street  car  to  come  to  see  me,  and  had  telephoned 
a  message  for  a  clerk  to  search  the  short  distance  between 
his  private  office  and  the  car  line.  The  surmise  was  near  that 
he  must  have  flung  the  bunch  into  his  desk  behind  some  papers, 
later  closing  it  in  the  usual  way;  on  telephoning  to  have  the 
desk  forcibly  opened,  this  was  found  to  be  correct. 

The  following  example  is  a  little  more  complicated.  A  lady 
had  lost  the  key  of  a  box  containing  phonograph  records, 
and  had  thoroughly  ransacked  her  rooms  for  it  many  times 
during  six  weeks,  but  all  in  vain.  The  records  belonged  to 
a  correspondence  college,  and  were  a  means  of  learning  French 
pronunciation.  They  had  been  put  away  early  in  the  summer, 
and  now,  in  the  autumn,  she  wanted  them  for  the  purpose  of 
renewing  her  French  studies.  Her  whole  heart  was  not  in 
these,  however,  for  it  happened  that  she  was  fond  of  singing 
and  hoped  to  get  accepted  in  an  orchestral  choir,  the  rehearsals 
of  which  would  leave  her  no  time  for  other  studies.  As  time 
went  on  she  despaired  more  and  more  of  being  accepted,  and 
fell  back  on  the  French  as  the  next  best  way  of  occupying 
her  winter  evenings.  Soon  after  her  definite  rejection  by 
the  choir  she  discovered  the  lost  key,  which  had  been  carefully 
stowed  away  in  the  corner  of  an  attic.  She  recollected  lock- 
ing the  box  in  the  early  summer,  and  thinking  that  she  would 
not  need  it  again  for  a  long  time,  but  had  no  memory  of  putting 
the  key  away.  She  was  extremely  proud  of  her  voice,  and 
had  built  on  "her  application  being  successful.  Taking  up 
the  French  studies  connoted  failure  of  her  hopes.  Her  in- 
ability to  find  the  key  thus  symbolized  her  lothness  to  be- 
lieve that  her  vocal  reputation  would  be  slighted. 

To  lose  or  misplace  a  present,  especially  if  it  happens  more 
than  once,  is  not  generally  considered  a  compliment  to  the 
giver,  and  with  right,  for  it  often  is  an  unconscious  expression 
of  disdain,  disregard,  or  indifference.  When  a  wife  repeatedly 
loses  her  wedding  ring  during  the  honeymoon,  it  does  not 
augur  well  for  the  future  happiness  of  the  marriage.  Freud 
relates  an  example  of  misplacing  where  the  motive  was  of  this 
kind,  and  which,  like  the  last  mentioned  example,  is  interest- 
ing in  regard  to  the  circumstances  under  which  the  object  was 
again  found.  It  concerned  a  married  couple  who  lived  rather 
aloof  lives  from  each  other,  any  marks  of  tenderness  being  of  a 
distinctly    lukewarm    nature;  the    fault,    according    to    the 


508  JONES 

husband,  lay  in  the  emotional  apathy  of  his  wife.  One  day 
she  made  him  a  present  of  a  book  that  would  interest  him.  He 
thanked  her  for  the  attention,  promised  to  read  it,  put  it  aside, 
and  could  n't  find  it  again.  In  the  next  six  months  he  made 
several  vain  attempts  to  find  it.  At  the  end  of  this  time  his 
mother,  to  whom  he  was  devoted,  got  seriously  ill,  and  was 
very  tenderly  nursed  by  his  wife.  His  affection  for  his  wife 
rapidly  increased,  and  one  evening,  coming  home  from  the' 
sick  bed  with  his  heart  filled  with  gratitude  towards  her,  he 
went  to  his  desk  and,  without  any  conscious  purpose,  un- 
hesitatingly opened  a  drawer  and  took  out  the  lost  book. 

Leaving  things  behind  one  is  a  common  type  of  mislaying. 
To  do  so  in  the  street  or  in  a  public  conveyance  has  a  very 
different  significance  from  doing  so  in  the  house  of  a  friend. 
In  the  latter  case  it  often  expresses  the  person's  attachment, 
and  the  difficulty  he  has  in  tearing  himself  away.  One 
can  almost  measure  the  success  with  which  a  physician  is 
practising  psychotherapy,  for  instance,  by  the  size  of  the 
collection  of  umbrellas,  handkerchiefs,  purses,  and  so  on,  that 
he  could  make  in  a  month. 

VIII.    Erroneously  Carried  Out  Actions 

A  secondary  suppressed  tendency  may  manifest  itself  in 
the  disturbance  not  only  of  writing,  but  also  of  any  other 
conscious  motor  act,  an  occurrence  Freud  terms  a  "  Vergreifen." 
The  intended  action  is  not  carried  out,  or  only  incorrectly, 
being  entirely  or  partly  replaced  by  an  action  corresponding 
with  the  suppressed  impulse  that  breaks  through.  As  in  the 
former  cases  this  secondary  tendency  is  associated,  either 
directly  or  indirectly,  with  the  conscious  intention,  and  the 
faulty  action  is  customarily  explained  as  being  due  to  "chance," 
* '  accident, "    or    *  *  carelessness . ' ' 

A  trite  example  will  perhaps  best  illustrate  the  type  of 
occurrence.  On  starting  to  open  a  fresh  tin  of  tobacco  I 
economically  reflected  that  I  should  first  finish  the  rather  dry 
remains  of  the  previous  one.  A  few  minutes  later,  however, 
while  engrossed  in  reading,  I  wanted  to  refill  my  pipe,  and  to 
my  surprise  detected  myself  in  the  act  of  opening  the  new  tin, 
although  I  had  pushed  it  farther  away  from  me  than  the  other. 
My  checked  wish  to  enjoy  the  fresh  tobacco  had  taken  advant- 
age of  my  distraction,  and  so  interfered  with  my  conscious 
intention  of  filling  the  pipe  from  the  old  tin. 

An  equally  simple  example  is  the  following.  It  is  my 
custom  to  put  scientific  journals,  as  they  arrive,  on  a  stool  in 
the  corner  of  my  study.  On  reading  them  I  write  on  the  back 
the  page  number  of  any  articles  I  wish  to  enter  in  my  refer- 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOIvOGY  OI^  EVERYDAY  LIFE  509 

ence  books;  the  journals  not  so  marked  are  put  on  top  of  the 
files,  to  be  bound  at  the  end  of  the  year,  while  the  others  are 
placed  on  a  pile  at  one  side  of  my  desk.  Once  a  week  or  so  I 
go  through  this  pile  and  enter  the  references,  but,  whenever 
I  have  neglected  this  for  so  long  that  the  pile  begins  to  assume 
formidable  dimensions,  I  find  I  have  a  pronounced  tendency 
to  put  no  more  there,  and  to  put  on  the  files  any  fresh  journal 
I  read,  whether  it  has  articles  that  should  be  entered  or  not. 
The  motive  is  obvious,  to  save  myself  the  trouble  of  having 
to  enter  more  than  I  already  have  to. 

A  lady  went  to  post  some  letters  which  had  come  for  her 
brother,  and  which  had  to  be  re-addressed  and  forwarded  on 
account  of  his  absence.  When  she  got  home  she  found  the 
letters  still  in  her  hand-bag,  but  realized  that  she  had  posted 
two  letters  addressed  to  herself,  which  she  had  opened  that 
morning;  they  duly  arrived  on  the  next  day.  At  the  time 
another  younger  brother  was  at  home  seriously  ill  with  typhoid 
fever,  and  she  had  just  written  to  the  elder  brother  begging 
him  to  come  home  as  soon  as  possible.  She  knew,  however, 
that  on  account  of  urgent  business  he  would  not  be  able  to 
leave  immediately,  but  her  posting  letters  addressed  to  the 
home  under  the  impression  that  she  was  sending  them  to 
her  brother,  indicated  her  keen  anxiety  that  he  was  already 
there. 

A  patient  came  up  from  the  country  to  get  advice  about 
various  obsessing  ideas  that  greatly  distressed  him.  He  had 
been  recommended  to  consult  two  physicians,  another  one 
and  myself.  The  other  physician  told  him  *  'not  to  think 
about  the  ideas,"  and  advised  him  to  take  a  course  of  physical 
exercise  at  a  special  gymnasium  that  he  kept  for  the  purpose. 
I  of  course  advised  psycho-analytic  treatment,  which  has 
since  cured  him.  He  promised  us  both  that  he  would  think 
the  matter  over,  and  let  us  know  what  he  decided.  That 
night,  on  getting  home,  he  wrote  to  each  of  us,  to  the  other 
physician  that  he  could  n't  yet  make  up  his  mind,  and  to  me 
that  he  would  like  to  make  an  appointment  to  begin  the  treat- 
ment as  soon  as  possible.  He  put  the  letters  into  the  wrong 
envelopes.  During  the  subsequent  psycho-analysis  it  be- 
came evident  that  this  "accidental"  mistake  was  unconscious- 
ly determined  by  the  spiteful  desire  to  let  both  the  other 
physician  and  myself  know  what  his  opinion  was  of  the 
former's  advice. 

The  use  of  keys  is  a  fertile  source  of  occurrences  of  this  kind, 
of  which  two  examples  may  be  given.  If  I  am  disturbed  in  the 
midst  of  some  engrossing  work  at  home  by  having  to  go  to  the 
hospital  to  carry  out  some  routine  work,  I  am  very  apt  to  find 
myself  trying  to  open  the  door  of  my  laboratory  there  with 

Journal— 3 


5IO  JONES 

the  key  of  my  desk  at  home,  although  the  two  keys  are  quite 
unHke  each  other.  The  mistake  unconsciously  demonstrates 
where  I  would  rather  be  at  the  moment. 

Some  years  ago  I  was  acting  in  a  subordinate  position  at  a 
certain  institution,  the  front  door  of  which  was  kept  locked, 
so  that  it  was  necessary  to  ring  for  admission.  On  several 
occasions  I  found  myself  making  serious  attempts  to  open  the 
door  with  my  house  key.  Bach  one  of  the  permanent  visiting 
staff,  of  which  I  aspired  to  be  a  member,  was  provided  with  a 
key,  to  avoid  the  trouble  of  having  to  wait  at  the  door.  My 
mistakes  thus  expressed  my  desire  to  be  on  a  similar  footing, 
and  to  be  quite  "at  home"  there. 

Two  other  everyday  sets  of  occurrences  may  briefly  be 
mentioned  where  unconscious  disturbances  of  otherwise  in- 
tended actions  are  very  frequent.  The  one  is  the  matter  of 
paying  out  money,  and  particularly  of  giving  change.  It 
would  be  an  interesting  experiment  to  establish  statistically 
the  percentage  of  such  mistakes  that  are  in  favor  of  the 
person  making  them,  in  comparison  with  that  of  the  opposite 
sort. 

The  second  is  the  sphere  of  domestic  breakages.  It  can 
be  observed  that  after  a  servant  has  been  reprimanded,  es- 
pecially when  the  reprimand  is  more  than  usually  unjust  in 
her  eyes,  is  a  favorite  time  for  crockery  to  * '  come  to  pieces  in 
her  hand."  Careless  breakage  of  valuable  china,  an  event  that 
often  perplexes  the  owner  as  much  as  it  incenses  her,  may  be 
the  product  of  a  number  of  factors  in  the  mind  of  the  trans- 
gressor, class  envy  of  valuable  property,  ignorant  lack  of 
appreciation  for  objects  of  art,  resentment  at  having  to  devote 
so  much  labor  to  the  care  of  what  appear  to  be  senseless 
objects  of  enthusiasm,  personal  hostility  towards  the  owner, 
and  so  on. 

IX.    Symptomatic  Acts 

Under  the  name  of  "  Symptomhandlungen "  Freud  dis- 
cusses a  series  of  unconsciously  performed  actions  that  differ 
from  the  last-mentioned  ones  in  being  independent  activities, 
and  not  grafted  on  to  another  conscious  one.  They  are  done 
"without  thinking"  or  "by  chance,"  and  no  significance  is 
seen  in  them.  Analysis  of  them,  however,  shows  that  they 
are  the  symbolic  expression  of  some  suppressed  tendency, 
usually  a  wish.  In  many  instances  the  action  is  a  complicated 
one,  and  performed  on  only  one  occasion;  in  others  it  is  a 
constant  habit  that  often  is  characteristic  of  the  person. 
The  mannerisms  of  dress,  of  fingering  the  moustache  or 
elothes-buttons,  the  playing  with  coins  in  the  pocket,  and  so 


TH^  PSYCHOPATHOI.OGY  OF  EVERYDAY  UFE      511 

on,  are  examples  of  this  kind;  they  all  have  their  logical 
meaning,  though  this  needs  to  be  read  before  becoming  evident. 

Different  ways  of  occupying  the  hands  often  betray  thoughts 
that  the  person  does  not  wish  to  express  or  even  does  not 
know  of.  It  is  related  of  Eleonora  Duse  that  in  a  divorce 
play,  while  in  a  soliloquy  following  a  wrangle  with  the  hus- 
band, she  kept  playing  with  her  wedding-ring,  taking  it  off, 
replacing  it,  and  finally  taking  it  off  again;  she  is  now  ready 
for  the  seducer.  The  action  illustrates  the  profundity  of  the 
great  actress'  character  studies. 

Maeder^  tells  the  following  story  of  a  Zurich  colleague  who 
had  a  free  day  and  was  hesitating  between  making  an  agree- 
able holiday  of  it  and  paying  a  distasteful  duty  call  on  some 
people  in  Lucerne.  He  ultimately  decided  on  the  latter,  and 
dolefully  set  out.  Half  way  to  Lucerne  he  had  to  change 
trains;  he  did  this  mechanically,  and  settled  down  in  the 
other  train  to  continue  his  reading  of  the  morning  papers. 
When  the  ticket  collector  came  round  he  discovered  that  he 
had  taken  a  train  back  to  Zurich.  His  wish  to  spend  the  day 
there  and  not  in  Lucerne  had  proved  too  strong  for  his  good 
intentions. 

In  most  of  the  examples  previously  mentioned  in  this  paper, 
and  of  those  encountered  in  real  life,  it  is  possible  to  discover 
a  motive  for  the  given  occurrence  that  logically  accounts  for 
this,  but  which  does  not  lie  particularly  deep  in  the  person's 
mind.  In  other  words,  it  is,  in  Freud's  language,  fore-con- 
scious,2  and  the  subject  has  no  particular  difficulty  in  recogniz- 
ing it  as  an  integral  part  of  his  personality.  The  problem, 
however,  is  far  from  exhausted  at  this  point.  It  is  next 
necessary  to  discover  the  origin  of  the  motive  or  tendency  in 
question,  or  to  explain  why  it  needs  to  be  expressed  at  all. 
In  this  investigation  one  reaches  the  realm  of  the  unconscious 
proper,  and  here  it  often  turns  out  that  the  error  which  is 
being  analyzed  has  a  deeper  meaning,  that  it  symbolizes  more 
than  the  fore-conscious  motive,  and  expresses  tendencies  of 
much  greater  personal  significance;  this  may  be  the  case, 
however  trivial  the  error  in  itself.  In  some  of  the  preceding 
examples  the  fore-conscious  motive  disclosed  appears  trite, 
and  it  seems  unlikely  that  such  a  trifling  matter  should  need 
a  complicated  psychological  mechanism  to  manifest  itself. 
In  the  cases  of  this  kind  that  I  have  had  the  opportunity  of 
submitting  to  a  detailed  psycho-analysis,  I  have  found  that 
the    unconscious    associations    often   shed   an    unexpectedly 

^Maeder:  Nouvelles  contributions  a  la  psychopathologie  de  la  vie 
quotidienne.     Arch,  de  Psychol.,  1908.    VII,  p.  296. 

^For  the  explanation  of  this  and  allied  terms  see  Psychol.  Bull.,  April, 
1910.     p.  III. 


5 1 2  JONES 

instructive  light  on  the  full  meaning  of  the  occurrence.  Un- 
fortunately, however,  the  motives  thus  reached  are  usually  of 
so  intimate  a  nature  that  discretion  forbids  the  publishing  of 
them. 

In  still  other  cases  no  fore-conscious  motive  can  be  dis- 
cerned, and  the  error  appears  to  be  quite  meaningless  until 
the  truly  unconscious  sources  are  reached.  In  the  following 
example^  the  fore-conscious  motive  was  not  discovered  until 
the  resistance  to  the  unconscious  sources  of  it  were  broken 
down.  It  is  further  peculiarly  instructive  in  illustrating 
what  important  and  fundamental  traits  of  character  may  be 
revealed  by  the  analysis  of  an  absolutely  trivial  occurrence. 

A  doctor  on  re-arranging  his  furniture  in  a  new  house  came 
across  an  old-fashioned,  straight,  wooden  stethoscope,  and 
after  pausing  to  decide  where  he  should  put  it,  was  impelled  to 
place  it  on  the  side  of  his  writing-desk  in  such  a  position  that 
it  stood  exactly  between  his  chair  and  the  one  reserved  for  his 
patients.  The  act  in  itself  was  certainly  odd,  for  in  the  first 
place  the  straight  stethoscope  served  no  purpose,  as  he  invari- 
ably used  a  binaural  one;  and  in  the  second  place  all  his 
medical  apparatus  and  instruments  were  kept  put  away  in 
drawers,  with  the  sole  exception  of  this  one.  However,  he 
gave  no  thought  at  all  to  the  matter  until  one  day  it  was 
brought  to  his  notice  by  a  patient,  who  had  never  seen  a 
wooden  stethoscope,  asking  him  what  it  was.  On  being  told, 
she  asked  why  he  kept  it  just  there;  he  answered  in  an  off- 
hand way  that  that  place  was  as  good  as  any  other.  This 
started  him  thinking,  however,  and  he  wondered  whether 
there  had  been  any  unconscious  motive  in  his  action. 
Being  interested  in  the  psycho-analytic  method  he  asked  me 
to  investigate  the  matter. 

The  first  memory  that  occurred  to  him  was  the  fact  that 
when  a  medical  student  he  had  been  struck  by  the  habit  his 
hospital  interne  had  of  always  carrying  in  his  hand  a  wooden 
stethoscope  on  his  ward  visits,  although  he  never  used  it. 
He  greatly  admired  this  interne,  and  was  much  attached  to 
him.  Later  on,  when  he  himself  became  an  interne,  he  con- 
tracted the  same  habit,  and  would  feel  very  uncomfortable 
if  by  mistake  he  left  his  room  without  having  the  instrument 
to  swing  in  his  hand.  The  aimlessness  of  the  habit  was  shown 
not  only  by  the  fact  that  the  only  stethoscope  he  ever  used  was 
a  binaural  one,  which  he  carried  in  his  pocket,  but  also  in  that 
it  was  continued  when  he  was  a  surgical  interne  and  never 
needed  any  stethoscope  at  all. 

^In  the  Zentralb.  f.  Psychoanalyse,  Jahrg.  i,  S.  96,  I  have  published  a 
fuller  account  of  this  example. 


THE   PSYCHO  PATHOLOGY  OF   EVERYDAY   LIFE  513 

From  this  it  was  evident  that  the  idea  of  the  instrument  in 
question  had  in  some  way  or  other  become  invested  with  a 
greater  psychical  significance  than  normally  belongs  to  it,  in 
other  words,  that  to  the  subject  it  stood  for  more  than  it  does 
with  other  people.  The  idea  must  have  got  unconsciously 
associated  with  some  other  one,  which  it  symbolized,  and  from 
which  it  derived  its  additional  fulness  of  meaning.  I  will 
forestall  the  rest  of  the  analysis  by  saying  what  this  secondary 
idea  was,  namely  a  phallic  one ;  the  way  in  which  this  curious 
association  had  been  formed  will  presently  be  related.  The 
discomfort  he  experienced  in  hospital  on  missing  the  instru- 
ment, and  the  reUef  and  reassurance  the  presence  of  it  gave 
him,  was  related  to  what  is  known  as  a  "castration-complex;" 
namely,  a  childhood  fear,  often  continued  in  a  disguised  form 
into  adult  life,  lest  a  private  part  of  his  body  should  be  taken 
away  from  him,  just  as  playthings  so  often  were;  the  fear  was 
due  to  paternal  threats  that  it  would  be  cut  off  if  he  were  not 
a  good  boy,  particularly  in  a  certain  direction.  This  is  a  very 
common  complex,  and  accounts  for  a  great  deal  of  general 
nervousness,  and  lack  of  confidence,  in  later  years. 

Then  came  a  number  of  childhood  memories  relating  to  his 
family  doctor.  He  had  been  strongly  attached  to  this  doctor 
as  a  child,  and  during  the  analysis  long  buried  memories  were 
recovered  of  a  double  phantasy^  he  had  in  his  fourth  year 
concerning  the  birth  of  a  younger  sister,  namely  that  she  was 
the  child  (i)  of  himself  and  his  mother,  the  father  being  rele- 
gated to  the  background,  and  (2)  of  the  doctor  and  himself; 
in  this  he  thus  played  both  a  masculine  and  feminine  part.  At 
the  time,  when  his  curiosity  was  being  aroused  by  the  event, 
he  could  not  help  noticing  the  prominent  share  taken  by  the 
doctor  in  the  proceedings,  and  the  subordinate  position  occu- 
pied by  the  father ;  the  significance  of  this  for  later  life  will 
presently  be  pointed  out. 

The  stethoscope  association  was  formed  through  many 
connections.  In  the  first  place,  the  physical  appearance  of 
the  instrument,  a  straight,  rigid,  hollow  tube,  having  a  small 
bulbous  summit  at  one  extremity,  and  a  broad  base  at  the 
other,  and  the  fact  of  its  being  the  essential  part  of  the  medical 
paraphernalia,  the  instrument  with  which  the  doctor  performed 
his  magical  and  interesting  feats,  were  matters  that  attracted 
his  boyish  attention.  He  had  had  his  chest  repeatedly  ex- 
amined by  the  doctor  at  the  age  of  six,  and  distinctly  recollect- 
ed the  voluptuous  sensation  of  feeling  the  latter' s  head  near 
him  pressing  the  wooden  stethoscope  into  his  chest,  and  of  the 

^Psycho-analytic  research,  with  the  penetration  of  infantile  amnesia* 
has  shown  that  this  apparent  precocity  is  a  less  abnormal  occurrence  than 
was  previously  supposed. 


514     •  JONES 

rhythmic  to-and-fro  respiratory  movement.  He  had  been 
struck  by  the  doctor's  habit  of  carrying  his  stethoscope  inside 
his  hat;  he  found  it  interesting  that  the  doctor  should  carry 
his  chief  instrument  concealed  about  his  person,  always  handy 
when  he  went  to  see  patients,  and  that  he  only  had  to  take  off 
his  hat  {i.  e.  a  part  of  his  clothing)  and  "pull  it  out."  At 
the  age  of  eight  he  was  impressed  by  being  told  by  an  older 
boy  that  it  was  the  doctor's  custom  to  get  into  bed  with  his 
women  patients.  It  is  certain  that  the  doctor,  who  was 
young  and  handsome,  was  extremely  popular  among  the 
women  of  the  neighborhood,  including  the  subject's  own 
mother.  The  doctor  and  his  "instrument"  were  therefore 
the  objects  of  great  interest  throughout  his  boyhood. 

It  is  probable  that,  as  in  many  other  cases,  unconscious 
identification  with  the  family  doctor  had  been  a  main  motive 
in  determining  the  subject's  choice  of  profession.  It  was  here 
doubly  conditioned,  (i)  by  the  superiority  of  the  doctor  on 
certain  interesting  occasions  to  the  father,  of  whom  the  subject 
was  very  jealous,  and  (2)  by  the  doctor's  knowledge  of  for- 
bidden topics^  and  his  opportunities  for  illicit  indulgence.  The 
subject  admitted  that  he  had  on  several  occasions  experienced 
erotic  temptations  in  regard  to  his  women  patients;  he  had 
twice  fallen  in  love  with  one,  and  finally  had  married  one. 

The  next  memory  was  of  a  dream,  which  I  have  published 
elsewhere,^  plainly  of  a  homosexual-masochistic  nature;  in  it 
a  man,  who  proved  to  be  a  replacement-figure  of  the  family 
doctor,  attacked  the  subject  with  a  "sword."  The  idea  of  a 
sword,  as  is  so  frequently  the  case  in  dreams,  represented 
the  same  idea  that  was  mentioned  above  to  be  associated  with 
that  of  a  wooden  stethoscope.  The  thought  of  a  sword  re- 
minded the  subject  of  the  passage  in  the  Nibelung  Saga  where 
Sigurd  sleeps  with  his  naked  sword  (Gram)  between  him  and 
Brunhilda,  an  incident  that  had  always  greatly  struck  his 
imagination. 

The  meaning  of  the  symptomatic  act  now  at  last  became 
clear.  The  subject  had  placed  his  wooden  stethescope  between 
him  and  his  patients,  just  as  Sigurd  had  placed  his  sword  (an 
equivalent  symbol)  between  him  and  the  maiden  he  was  not 
to  touch.  The  act  was  a  compromise-formation;  it  served 
both  to  gratify  in  his  imagination  the  repressed  wish  to  enter 
into  nearer  relations  with  an  attractive  patient  (interposition 
of  phallus),  and  at  the  same  time  to  remind  him  that  this  wish 
was  not  to  become  a  reality  (interposition  of  sword).  It  was, 
so  to  speak,  a  charm  against  yielding  to  temptation. 

^The  term  "medical  questions"  is  a  common  periphrasis  for  "sexual 
questions." 

^Amer.  Journal  oj  Psychol.,  April,  1910,  p.  301. 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  UFE      5^5 

X.    Generai.  Observations 
( j)  Warrant  for  Interpretations 

The  first  criticism  of  the  theses  here  maintained  that  nat- 
urally presents  itself  is  the  question  as  to  the  reliability  of  the 
individual  interpretations.  It  is  not  likely  that  any  one  will 
reject  them  all  as  improbable,  but,  particularly  with  the  more 
complex  analyses,  doubt  must  arise  concerning  the  trust- 
worthiness of  the  results.  This  is  especially  so  in  regard  to  the 
personal,  subjective  factor  in  the  interpretations,  although  as 
a  matter  of  fact  the  very  constancy  of  the  way  in  which  similar 
conclusions  are  reached  by  different  observers  indicates  that 
this  factor  is  less  potent  than  might  be  imagined.  Experience 
shows  that,  when  attention  is  carefully  directed  to  the  objective 
aspects  of  the  analysis,  the  importance  of  the  personal  factor, 
which  from  the  unavoidable  nature  of  the  circumstances  can 
never  be  entirely  eliminated,  can  be  reduced  to  a  degree  where 
it  is  practically  negligible.  In  most  scientific  work  the  per- 
sonal factor  has  to  be  reckoned  with,  but  appreciation  of  the 
way  in  which  it  acts,  especially  when  this  is  based  on  psycho- 
logical knowledge,  as  a  rule  enables  it  to  be  excluded  to  such 
an  extent  as  not  to  interfere  with  conclusions  being  formulated 
that  are  valid  enough  to  stand  the  objective  test  of  verifiability. 
It  is  contended  that  this  statement  applies  unrestrictedly  to 
psycho-analytic  interpretations.  It  is,  of  course,  to  be  conce- 
ded that  the  probable  accuracy  of  these  interpretations  varies 
considerably  in  different  instances,  as  conclusions  do  else- 
where in  science.  Thus,  in  a  chemical  analysis,  the  conclu- 
sion as  to  whether  a  given  substance  is  present  or  not  varies 
in  probability  according  to  the  quality  and  amount  of  evi- 
dence obtainable;  in  some  cases  the  confirmatory  tests  are 
so  unequivocal  that  the  final  decision  is  a  practically  certain 
one,  in  others  it  is  very  probable,  in  still  others  it  is  only  a 
plausible  possibility,  and  so  on. 

The  view  that  the  psycho-analytic  interpretations  of  the 
class  of  occurrences  under  discussion  are  reliable  is  based  on, 
among  others,  the  following  considerations: 

(a)  The  psychological  correctness  of  the  principles  of  the 
free  association  method.  This  is  too  complex  a  matter  to  be 
gone  into  here,  and  I  will  only  refer  the  reader  to  Jung's  well- 
known  works^  on  the  subject. 

(b)  The  constancy  of  the  findings  by  different  observers, 
and  the  harmony  of  the  conclusions  with  those  reached  in  the 
study  of  other  fields,  e.  g.,  dreams,  psycho-neuroses,  mythology, 
etc.     It  is  extremely  unlikely  that  this  is  due  to  coincidence, 

ijung:  Diagnostische  Assoziationsstudien.     Bd.  /,  1906,  Bd.  //,  19 10. 


5i6  JON^S 

and  still  more  so  that  it  is  due  to  identical  prejudices  on  the 
part  of  the  different  workers,  for  in  the  first  place  this  would 
be  postulating  a  very  remarkable  uniformity  in  their  individual 
mental  constellations,  and  in  the  second  place  psycho-analytic 
research  brings  with  it  an  eradication  of  personal  prejudice, 
and  an  appreciation  of  personal  complexes,  that  is  rarely 
attained  elsewhere  in  the  same  degree. 

(c)  The  increased  intelligibility  of  the  processes  in  question. 
An  occurrence  that  previously  was  obscure  and  meaningless 
now  becomes  throughout  comprehensible,  and  an  integral  part 
of  the  rest  of  the  person's  mental  operations.  It  is  seen  to 
be  merely  an  irregular  manifestation  of  a  logical  tendency  that 
is  an  essential  constituent  of  the  personality,  the  unusual 
features  having  certain  definite  reasons  for  their  occurrence. 
Moreover,  the  discovery  of  the  underlying  motive,  and  its 
connection  with  the  manifestation  being  analyzed,  is  a  matter 
that  commonly  lends  itself  to  external  verification.  When, 
in  an  analysis,  one  traces  a  given  error  in  mental  functioning, 
such  as  a  lapsus  linguae,  to  a  thought  that  the  person  was 
desirous  of  keeping  back,  it  is  usually  easy  to  confirm  the 
truth  of  the  conclusion.  Very  significant  in  this  connection 
is  the  unmistakable  evidence  of  the  resulting  affect  in  the 
person,  which  accurately  corresponds  with  that  characteristic 
of  the  revealed  mental  process.  Often  this  is  so  pronounced 
that  it  is  quite  impossible  to  doubt  the  truth  of  the  interpreta- 
tion made ;  this  especially  is  a  matter  where  personal  experi- 
ence is  more  convincing  than  any  possible  amount  of  discussion. 

(d)  The  fact  that  in  many  fields  the  principles  in  question 
are  generally  recognized  to  be  valid.  Freud's  study  is  only  a 
detailed  working-out  of  laws  that  were  already  known  to  hold 
true  over  a  limited  area.  When  a  man  is  hurt  at  finding  his 
name  unfortunately  forgotten,  or  at  unexpectedly  being 
passed  by  unrecognized  in  the  street ;  when  a  lady  is  offended 
by  some  one  who  professes  regard  for  her  forgetting  to  carry 
out  her  behests  or  to  keep  a  rendezvous,  they  are  displaying 
an  affect  that  accords  perfectly  with  the  inferences  of  the 
psycho-analyst,  and  with  no  others.  In  this  correct  intuition 
of  mankind  lies  already  the  essential  nucleus  of  the  conclusions 
maintained  by  Freud. 

Indeed  it  is  quite  impossible  to  go  through  life  without 
constantly  making  interpretations  of  just  this  kind,  though 
usually  they  are  simpler  and  more  evident  than  those  needing 
a  special  psycho-analysis.  Observation  of  a  very  few  jokes 
is  sufficient  to  illustrate  this,  and  we  ' '  read  between  the  lines ' ' 
of  the  people  we  have  to  do  with,  doubting  the  scientific  justi- 
fication of  our  right  to  do  so  as  little  as  we  do  in  the  interpreta- 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OK   EVERYDAY   LII^E  517 

tions  of  jokes. ^  This  holds  in  the  most  manifold  fields  of 
mental  activity.  Three  examples  may  be  quoted,  of  a  kind 
that  could  be  multiplied  indefinitely.  With  Mr.  E.  R. 
Bennett's  play  "The  Servant  in  the  House,"  no  one  can  wit- 
ness it  intelligently  and  doubt  that  the  Hindoo  servant,  who 
is  the  principal  character,  is  a  presentation  of  Jesus  Christ,  or 
that  his  name  "Manson"  is  a  disguised  form  of  the  title 
"Son  of  Man."  Yet  we  should  find  it  difficult  to  "prove" 
this  to  a  carping  critic  who  is  bent  on  avoiding  the  obvious 
inference,  and  still  more  to  "prove"  our  assumption  that  the 
disguise  was  the  product  of  definite  motives  in  the  author's 
mind.  In  Mr.  Bernard  Shaw's  play  "Press  Cuttings"  one 
of  the  characters,  the  Prime  Minister  of  England,  is  called 
"  Balsquith."  When  one  infers  that  he  compounded  the  word 
from  the  names  of  two  Prime  Ministers,  Balfour  and  Asquith, 
the  critic  may  accuse  us  of  reading  into  Mr.  Shaw's  mind  views 
of  our  own  that  never  existed  there.^  In  Shelley's  "(Edipus 
Tyrannus"  what  right  have  we  to  assume  that  in  his  ridicule 
of  the  Ionian  Minotaur^  the  author  was  satirizing  the  English- 
man of  his  time?  Our  answer  in  all  these  cases  is  the  same, 
namely,  that  we  feel  justified  in  making  the  inferences  in 
question  because  they  make  something  intelligible  that  other- 
wise would  have  no  meaning.  This  answer  is  perfectly  correct, 
for  in  the  last  analysis  the  justification  of  every  scientific 
generalization  is  that  it  enables  us  to  comprehend  something 
that  is  otherwise  obscure,  namely,  the  relations  between 
apparently  dissimilar  phenomena. 

To  this  it  may  be  said  that  in  such  cases  as  those  just  men- 
tioned a  logical  meaning  is  given  to  something  that  from  pre- 
vious experience  we  have  every  reason  to  expect  has  one,  but 
that  the  point  in  dispute  about  the  * 'psychopathological " 
occurrences  of  everyday  life  is  whether  they  have  such  a 
meaning  or  not.  Here  a  priori  argument  can  take  us  no 
farther,  and  the  question  can  only  be  referred  for  solution  to 
actual  investigation,  a  matter  usually  considered  unnecessary, 
on  the  pure  assumption  that  the  occurrences  have  no  logical 
meaning.  Freud's  scepticism  made  him  challenge  the  neces- 
sity of  this  assumption,  and  prefer  to  leave  the  question  open 

*In  "Der  Witz  und  seine  Beziehung  zum  Unbewussten  "  Freud  has  made 
a  detailed  study  of  this  subject.  As  with  the  occurrences  studied  in  the 
present  paper,  he  has  shown  that  the  insight  consciously  obtained  is  often 
only  a  partial  one,  and  that  the  true  significance  is  often  related  to  uncon- 
scious sources. 

'The  royal  censor  refused  to  let  the  play  be  acted  until  the  name  was 
replaced  by  one  less  open  to  this  personal  interpretation,  namely,  Johnson; 
the  name  of  the  commander  in  chief,  Mitchener(from  Milner  and  Kitchener), 
had  to  be  altered  to  Bones. 

3:= John  Bull. 


5i8  JONES 

until  it  was  investigated.  On  doing  so  he  found  as  a  matter  of 
experience  two  things,  namely,  that  the  realm  of  psychical 
determinism  is  more  extensive  than  is  generally  supposed,  and 
that  awareness  of  a  motive  at  a  given  moment  is  not  a  neces- 
sary accompaniment  of  the  external  manifestation  of  this. 

Freud  further  came  to  the  conclusion  that  there  was  a 
definite  cause  for  the  popular  belief  that  so  many  blunders  in 
our  mental  functioning  are  meaningless.  He  holds  that  this 
belief  is  due  to  the  same  cause  as  the  blunders  themselves, 
namely,  to  repression.  Various  repressed  thoughts  are  in 
every  one  of  us  constantly  coming  to  expression  in  the  shape 
of  "  meaningless  "  blunders,  the  significance  of  which  necessa- 
rily escapes  us.  Being  thus  accustomed  to  the  occurrence  of 
such  matters  in  ourselves  we  naturally  attach  no  significance 
to  them  in  others;  we  "explain"  these  as  we  do  our  own,  or 
accept  the  "explanations"  proffered  just  as  we  expect  others 
to  accept  the  "explanations"  of  our  own  blunders. 

As  to  these  explanations  little  more  need  be  added.  Where 
the  factors  they  have  recourse  to  are  operative  at  all,  they  act 
only  as  predisposing  conditions,  not  as  the  true  cause.  Freud^ 
gives  the  following  apposite  illustration  of  the  actual  state  of 
affairs.  "Suppose  I  have  been  so  incautious  as  to  go  for  a 
stroll  in  a  lonely  part  of  the  town,  where  I  am  attacked  and 
robbed  of  my  watch  and  money.  At  the  next  police  station 
I  give  information  with  the  words :  I  have  been  in  this  and 
that  street,  where  loneliness  and  darkness  stole  my  watch  and 
money.  Although  in  these  words  I  should  have  said  nothing 
that  was  not  correct,  still  from  the  wording  of  my  information 
I  run  the  danger  of  being  thought  not  quite  right  in  the  head. 
The  state  of  affairs  can  correctly  be  described  only  thus,  that 
favored  by  the  loneliness  of  the  spot,  and  unrecognizable 
through  the  protection  of  the  darkness,  a  thief  has  robbed  me 
of  my  valuables.  Now,  the  state  of  affairs  in  the  forgetting 
of  a  name  need  not  be  otherwise;  favored  by  fatigue,  circula- 
tory disturbances  and  poisoning,  some  unknown  psychical 
agent  robs  me  of  the  proper  names  that  belong  to  my  memory, 
the  same  agent  that  on  other  occasions  can  bring  about  the 
same  failure  of  memory,  during  perfect  health  and  capacity." 
Similarly  such  a  mistake  as  a  slip  of  the  tongue  is  often  attrib- 
uted by  psychologists  (e.  g.  Wundt)  to  a  momentary  in- 
attentiveness.  It  is  certainly  a  question  of  conscious 
attention,  but  Freud^  has  pointed  out  that  the  defect  is  more 
accurately  described  as  a  disturbance  of  attention  than  as  a 
diminution,  the  true  cause  being  the  disturbing  influence  of  a 

^Freud:     Zur  Psychopathologie.     S.  22. 
^Freud:     Op.  cit.  S.  68. 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  LIFE      519 

second  train  of  thought.  The  same  remarks  apply  to  all  the 
other  explanations  urged.  Several  examples  were  given  above 
in  which  names  and  other  words  differing  by  only  one  letter 
were  confounded  or  interchanged,  and  evidence  was  brought 
forward  to  show  that  this  external  association  was  merely  a 
predisposing  circumstance,  and  not  the  actual  cause  of  the 
mistake.  Many  such  circumstances  favor  the  occurrence  of  a 
blunder,  that  is,  they  permit  a  repressed  thought  to  slip  partly 
through.  Alcoholic  intoxication  is  notoriously  one.  Emo- 
tional excitement  is  another.  Many  blunders,  forgettings, 
and  other  oversights,  are  attributed  to  the  confusion  of  hurry. 
Thus,  for  instance,  I  have  noticed  that  the  using  of  the  wrong 
key,  in  the  examples  quoted  above,  most  often  occurred  when 
I  was  in  a  great  hurry  (the  same  was  true  of  the  not  recogni- 
zing the  assistant  superintendent  in  his  office),  but  if  haste 
were  the  true  cause  it  would  be  curious  that  it  should  bring 
about  a  blunder  of  a  kind  that  defeats  its  own  object;  strictly 
speaking  it  is  the  emotional  confusion  or  excitement  engendered 
by  hurry  that  permits  a  second  repressed  impulse  to  manifest 
itself  in  what  externally  appears  as  a  blunder. 

As  has  been  remarked  above,  there  are  certain  occasions 
in  everyday  life  when  the  normal  person  divines  the  motiva- 
tion of  unintentional  errors,  though  these  are  rare  in  comparison 
with  the  occasions  on  which  it  escapes  him.  Freud^  has 
pointed  out  that  there  are  two  other  groups  of  processes  in 
which  an  unconscious,  and  therefore  distorted,  knowledge  of 
this  motivation  is  manifested,  namely  in  paranoia  and  in 
superstitions.  In  both  these  the  subject  reads  a  meaning  into 
external  happenings  that  have  no  such  psychical  meaning,  and, 
in  a  very  interesting  discussion  of  the  subject,  Freud  produces 
reasons  to  believe  that  this  erroneous  functioning  is  due  to  a 
projection  to  the  outside  of  motives  that  exist  in  the  subject's 
mind  and  are  full  of  meaning  there,  but  which  he  does  not 
directly  perceive. 

A  little  may  be  said  on  a  feature  of  some  of  the  analyses 
quoted  that  may  strike  the  reader  as  odd,  namely,  the  remark- 
able play  on  words  that  is  so  often  found.  Whoever  is  sur- 
prised at  this  needs  to  be  reminded  of  the  almost  boundless 
extent  to  which  the  same  feature  occurs  in  other  fields  of  mental 
activity,  in  wit,  dreams,  insanity,  and  so  on.  Even  in  the 
serious  affairs  of  everyday  life  it  is  far  from  unusual.  Thus, 
to  cite  a  few  business  announcements,  we  see  the  National 
Drug  Company  using  as  its  trade  motto  "  Nadru,"  the  National 
Liquorice  Company  (N.  L.  Co.)  that  of  "Enelco,"  we  find 
the  Levy  Jewellery  Company  reversing  its  first  name  into  the 

^Freud:     Op.  cit.     S.     131  et  seq. 


520  JONES 

more  pretentious  one  of  Yvel,  and  advertisements  of  "  Uneeda" 
biscuits  and  "  Phiteezi"  boots  are  familiar  to  every  one.  This 
tendency  to  play  on  words,  and  to  produce  a  more  useful  or 
pleasing  result  (mirror-writing,  ciphers,  and  rhyming  slang^ 
also  belong  here),  is  evidently  dictated  by  the  same  Unlust 
motives — to  avoid  banal  or  otherwise  unattractive  words — 
that  so  much  stress  has  been  laid  on  above.  It  is  one  that  has 
far-reaching  roots  in  early  childhood  life.  In  fore-conscious 
and  unconscious  mental  activities  this  play  on  words — clang 
associations — is  much  more  extensive  than  in  consciousness, 
and  serves  for  the  transference  of  a  given  affect  from  one  mode 
of  expression  to  a  more  suitable  and  convenient  one. 

(2)     Bearing  on  psycho-analytic  method  oj  treatment 

Three  brief  remarks  may  be  made  on  this  matter.  In 
the  first  place,  investigation  of  the  errors  and  slips  of  everyday 
life  is  perhaps  the  best  mode  of  approach  to  the  study  of 
psycho-analysis,  and  affords  a  convenient  preliminary  to  the 
more  difficult,  and  more  important,  subject  of  dreams.  The 
greatest  value  is  to  be  attached  to  self-analysis,  a  fact  to 
which  attention  cannot  too  often  be  called.  In  the  second 
place,  analysis  of  the  occurrences  in  question  is  of  great  service 
in  the  treatment  of  neurotic  patients.  Their  behavior  in 
this  respect  needs  to  be  closely  observed,  and  frequently  a 
quite  trivial  occurrence  will,  when  investigated,  provide  clues 
to  the  elucidation  of  the  main  problems.  Thirdly,  considera- 
tion of  the  mechanism  of  these  erroneous  functionings  makes 
it  easy  to  understand  the  way  in  which  psycho-analysis  brings 
about  its  therapeutic  effects.  Both  the  errors  and  neurotic 
symptoms  are  the  manifestations  of  dissociated  conative 
trends  which  are  weaker  than  the  rest  of  the  personality 
opposed  to  them,  are  consequently  repressed,  and  can  come 
to  expression  only  in  indirect  ways  and  only  under  certain 
circumstances.  An  essential  condition  for  this  is  non-aware- 
ness of  the  process.  Psycho-analysis  by  directing  the  disso- 
ciated trend  into  consciousness  abolishes  this  condition, 
and  therefore  brings  the  trend  under  the  control  of  the  con- 
scious inhibiting  forces.  Conscious  control  is  substituted  for 
automatic  expression,  the  significance  of  which  was  not  real- 
ized. These  considerations  may  be  illustrated  by  the  tritest 
of  the  examples  given  above,  namely,  my  opening  of  a  fresh 

^The  following  are  instances  from  the  Cockney  type  of  this.  "Aristotle" 
=bottle.  "Cain  and  Abel' '=table.  "Harry  Nichols "=pickles.  Mediate 
forms  are:  "Christmas"  (card)=guard :  "Bull"  (and  cow)=row: 
"Malcolm"  (Scott)=hot;  "Stockton "  (on-Tees)=cheese :  "Rosie"  (Loader) 
=soda,  and  so  on. 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF   EVERYDAY   UPE  52 1 

tobacco  tin  although  I  wished  first  to  finish  the  old  one.  Here 
it  is  quite  obvious  that  the  rule  just  stated  holds,  that  an 
essential  condition  of  the  erroneous  functioning  is  non-aware- 
ness of  the  significance  of  the  process;  I  knew  that  I  was 
reaching  for  tobacco,  but  did  n't  notice  which  tin  it  was.  The 
moment  I  realized  the  situation  I  of  course  checked  the  error, 
and  controlled  the  wish  that  was  taking  advantage  of  my 
absent-mindedness  to  come  to  expression.  On  a  larger  scale 
the  same  is  true  of  neurotic  symptoms;  realization  of  their 
significance  checks  the  morbid  expression  of  the  underlying 
impulse.  The  cardinal  proposition  is,  that  consciousness  of  an 
aberrant  impulse  means  increased  control  of  it. 

(3)     Relation  to  health  and  disease 

This  matter  should  be  fairly  evident  from  the  preceding 
considerations,  so  that  the  two  corollaries  that  follow  in  this 
respect  need  only  to  be  stated.  The  first  is  that  from  a  psy- 
chological point  of  view  perfect  mental  normality  does  not 
exist.  In  other  words,  every  one  shows  numerous  defects  in 
mental  functioning  that  are  manifestations  of  dissociated, 
repressed,  psychical  material,  and  which  are  brought  about 
by  the  same  psychological  mechanisms  as  those  operative  in 
the  case  of  the  psycho-neuroses.  A  further  matter  not  brought 
out  in  the  preceding  study  is  that  this  material  is  ultimately  of 
the  same  nature  as  that  from  which  neuroses  are  produced. 
The  second  corollary  is  that  the  border-line  between  mental 
health  and  disease  is  much  less  sharp  even  than  is  generally 
supposed.  The  distinction  between  the  two  is  really  a  social 
one,  rather  than  a  psychopathological  one,  just  as  the  dis- 
tinction between  sanity  and  insanity  is  primarily  a  legal  one. 
When  the  erroneous  mental  functioning  happens  to  carry  with 
it  a  social  incapacity  or  disability  the  condition  is  called  a 
neurosis,  and  when  it  does  not  it  is  called  absent-mindedness, 
eccentricity,  personal  mannerism,  and  so  on.  Further  reflec- 
tions on  the  significance  of  these  conclusions  will  here  be 
omitted,  as  they  are  not  relevant  to  the  main  purpose  of  the 
paper. 

(4)     Determinism  and  Free  WilV- 

One  of  the  psychological  arguments  against  the  belief  in  a 
complete  mental  determinism  is  the  intense  feeling  of  con- 
viction that  we  have  a  perfectly  free  choice  in  the  performance 
of  many  acts.  This  feeling  of  conviction  must  be  justified 
by  something,  but  at  the  same  time  it  is  entirely  compatible 
with  a  complete  determinism.     It  is  curious  that  it  is  not 

^This  section  is  largely  paraphrased  from  Freud,  Op.  cit.  S.  130. 


522  JONES 

often  prominent  with  important  and  weighty  decisions;  on 
these  occasions  one  has  much  more  the  feeUng  of  being  irresis- 
tibly impelled  in  a  given  direction  (compare  Luther's  "Hier 
stehe  ich,  ich  kann  nicht  anders").  On  the  contrary  it  is  with 
trivial  and  indifferent  resolutions  that  one  is  sure  that  one 
could  just  as  well  have  acted  otherwise,  that  one  has  acted 
from  non- motived  free  will.  From  the  psycho-analytic  point 
of  view  the  right  of  this  feeling  of  conviction  is  not  contested. 
It  only  means  that  the  person  is  not  aware  of  any  conscious 
motive.  When,  however,  conscious  motivation  is  distin- 
guished from  unconscious  motivation,  this  feeling  of  conviction 
teaches  us  that  the  former  does  not  extend  over  all  our  motor 
resolutions.  What  is  left  free  from  the  one  side  receives  its 
motive  from  the  other,  from  the  unconscious,  and  so  the 
psychical  determinism  is  flawlessly  carried  through.  A  knowl- 
edge of  unconscious  motivation  is  indispensable  even  for 
philosophical  discussion  of  determinism. 

(5)     Social  Significance 

It  would  be  interesting  to  speculate  as  to  the  result  of  a 
general  knowledge  of  the  unconscious  motives  that  underlie 
the  failures  of  mental  functioning  in  everyday  life,  but  it  is 
perhaps  more  profitable  to  review  some  of  the  present  results 
of  ignorance  of  them. 

One  of  these  is  that  both  intellectual  and  moral  dishonesty 
is  facilitated  to  an  extraordinary  extent.  There  is  no  doubt 
that  dishonesty  of  which  the  subject  is  not  conscious  is  much 
commoner  than  deliberate  dishonesty,  a  fact  of  considerable 
importance  in,  for  jnstance,  juristic  matters.  The  hysteric 
who  cannot  move  her  leg  because  unconsciously  she  wishes 
it  to  be  paralyzed,  the  tourist  who  oversees  a  prohibiting 
notice  because  he  finds  such  things  annoying,  and  the  impecu- 
nious man  who  forgets  to  pay  a  bill  because  he  does  n't  want 
to,  are  all  instances  of  this.  At  the  same  time  the  line  between 
these  two  types  of  dishonesty  is  nowhere  a  sharp  one,  and  in 
many  cases  one  can  only  conclude  that  the  subject  could  with 
a  very  little  effort  recognize  the  suppressed  motive,  which  is 
more  than  half  conscious.  In  psycho-analytic  treatment  this 
is  constantly  to  be  observed ;  the  following  slight  example  of  it 
may  be  quoted.  A  young  woman  told  me  of  a  certain  experi- 
ence she  had  had  in  her  childhood  in  company  with  a  boy. 
I  had  every  reason  to  believe  that  this  was  far  from  being  an 
isolated  one,  and  asked  her  whether  it  had  occurred  with 
any  one  else.  She  said,  "  Not  that  I  can  remember."  Notic- 
ing the  wording  of  her  answer  and  a  certain  expression  in  her 
face,  I  asked,"  What  about  the  times  that  you  can't  remember?" 


THE   PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  UFE  523 

She  exclaimed  "Oh,  shucks,"  and  in  such  a  disconcerted  tone 
that  I  was  sure  my  surmise  had  been  well-founded.  She  then 
made  the  remark,  "Well,  I  really  had  forgotten  the  other 
times  till  this  minute,"  the  truth  of  which  was  probably  only 
partial.  The  incident  made  me  think  of  Nietzsche's  epigram: 
"  One  may  indeed  lie  with  the  mouth,  but  with  the  accompany- 
ing grimace  one  nevertheless  tells  the  truth."  Half -amnesias 
of  this  kind  are  extremely  common  in  daily  life. 

In  spite  of  the  constant  endeavor  to  keep  back  disagreeable 
or  unacceptable  thoughts,  these  very  thoughts  betray  them- 
selves in  blunders  of  the  type  under  discussion.  By  the 
world  this  self -betrayal  is  passed  by  unnoticed,  but  it  does  not 
escape  any  one  who  has  made  a  study  of  unconscious  function- 
ing. Freud^  in  no  way  exaggerates  when  he  says:  "He  who 
has  eyes  to  see,  and  ears  to  hear,  becomes  convinced  that 
mortals  can  hide  no  secret.  Whoever  is  silent  with  the  lips, 
tattles  with  the  finger-tips;  betrayal  oozes  out  of  every  pore." 
Morevoer,  even  with  a  direct  lie,  careful  observation  of  the 
undue  emphasis  here  and  the  distortion  there  will  usually 
disclose  what  the  person  is  trying  to  conceal,  for  the  lie  is  a 
creation  of  the  same  mind  that  at  the  moment  is  cognizant 
of  the  truth.  It  is  very  rare,  especially  on  emotional  occa- 
sions, for  self-control  to  be  so  complete  as  to  inhibit  all  uncon- 
scious manifestations,  which  to  an  attentive  observer  will 
indicate  the  truth.  Strictly  speaking,  one  cannot  lie  to  another, 
only  to  oneself,  and  skilled  introspection  makes  even  this 
increasingly  difficult. 

An  important  consequence  of  this  is  that  every  one  is  apt 
to  know  more  about  the  inner  motives  of  those  near  to  him 
than  they  themselves  know,  inasmuch  as  every  one  is  continu- 
ally performing  at  all  events  some  simple  kind  of  psychical 
analysis  on  those  around  him.  This  is  a  fertile  source  of 
misunderstandings  and  friction,^  especially  in  family  and  mar- 
ried life  where  contact  is  much  nearer.  One  person  intuitively 
recognizes  an  intention  or  tendency  in  the  other  that  the 
latter  refuses  to  admit  even  to  himself.  When  the  unavoidable 
inferences  are  presented  to  him,  he  is  indignant,  rebuts  them 
as  being  groundless,  and  complains  that  he  is  misunderstood. 
Strictly  speaking,  such  misunderstanding  is' really  a  too  fine 
understanding.  The  more  nervous  two  people  are,  the  more 
often  do  they  give  rise  to  schisms,  the  reasons  for  which  are  as 
categorically  denied  by  the  one  as  they  are  obvious  to  the 
other.  This  is  the  punishment  for  the  inner  improbity,  that, 
under  the  pretext  of  forgetting,  absent-mindedness,  and  so  on, 

^Freud:     Sammlung  kleiner  Schriften.     Zweite  Folge.     S.  69. 
^Freud.     Zur  Psychopathologie,  S.  114. 


524  JONES 

people  allow  tendencies  to  come  to  expression  which  they 
would  do  better  to  admit  to  themselves  and  others,  unless 
they  can  control  them. 

Most  important,  however,  is  the  extension  of  these  princi- 
ples to  the  sphere  of  human  judgment,  for  it  is  probable  that 
repressed  complexes  play  as  prominent  a  part  in  distortion 
here  as  they  do  in  the  minor  errors  of  memory  mentioned 
above.  On  a  large  scale  this  is  shown  in  two  ways,  in  the 
minimum  of  evidence  often  necessary  to  secure  the  acceptance 
of  an  idea  that  is  in  harmony  with  existing  mental  constella- 
tions, or  to  reject  one  that  is  incompatible  with  these.  In 
both  cases  it  is  often  affective  influences  rather  than  intellectual 
operations  that  decide  the  question.  The  same  evidence  is 
construed  quite  differently  when  viewed  in  the  light  of  one 
affective  constellation  from  the  way  it  is  when  viewed  in  the 
light  of  another.  Further,  when  the  general  attitude  towards 
a  question  changes  in  the  course  of  time,  this  is  often  due  at 
least  as  much  to  modification  of  the  prevailing  affective  influ- 
ences as  to  the  accumulation  of  external  evidence ;  for  instance, 
the  average  man  of  to-day  does  not  hesitate  to  reject  the  same 
evidence  of  witchcraft  that  was  so  convincing  to  the  man  of 
three  centuries  ago,  though  he  usually  knows  no  more  about 
the  true  explanation  of  it  than  the  latter  did. 

Ignorance  of  the  importance  of  affective  factors  in  this 
respect,  combined  with  the  ineradicable  popular  belief  in  the 
rationality  of  the  individual  mind,  has  the  interesting  result 
that  strong  differences  of  opinion  are  attributed  by  each  side 
to  a  defect  in  reasoning  capacity  on  the  part  of  the  other.  In 
an  exposition  of  this  matter  Trotter^  writes:  "The  religious 
man  accuses  the  atheist  of  being  shallow  and  irrational,  and  is 
met  with  a  similar  reply;  to  the  Conservative,  the  amazing 
thing  about  the  Liberal  is  his  incapacity  to  see  reason  and  ac- 
cept the  only  possible  solution  of  public  problems.  Examination 
reveals  the  fact  that  the  differences  are  not  due  to  the  commis- 
sion of  the  mere  mechanical  fallacies  of  logic,  since  these  are 
easily  avoided,  even  by  the  politician,  and  since  there  is  no 
reason  to  suppose  that  one  party  in  such  controversies  is  less 
logical  than  the  other.  The  difference  is  due  rather  to  the 
fundamental  assumptions  of  the  antagonists  being  hostile, 
and  these  assumptions  are  derived  from  herd  suggestion." 

There  is  a  certain  amount  of  truth  in  this  imputation  of 
stupidity  to  the  person  on  the  opposite  side,  for  in  his  blind 
refusal  to  appreciate  or  even  to  perceive  the  evidence  adduced 
by  his  opponent  he  may  give  an  unavoidable  appearance  of 

^Wilfred  Trotter:  Herd  Instinct  and  its  Bearing  on  the  Psychology  of 
Civilised  Man.     Sociological  Review,  July,  1908.     (P.  19  of  reprint.) 


THE  PSYCHOPATHOLOGY  OF  EVERYDAY  UFE      525 

marked  stupidity.  A  further  reason  for  this  is  that  some  one 
under  the  sway  of  strongly  affective  influences  thinks  not  only 
that  any  one  differing  from  him  must  be  deficient  in  reasoning 
power,  but  also  that  the  views  of  the  latter  are  themselves 
stupid.  In  attempting  to  controvert  these,  therefore,  he  uncon- 
sciously distorts  them  until  they  really  are  foolish,  and  he  then 
finds  it  easy  to  demolish  them.  Any  man  of  the  period  who 
read  only  the  account  of  Darwin's  views  that  was  promulgated 
by  his  theological  and  scientific  opponents  must  have  wondered 
why  it  was  worth  while  to  attack  such  obvious  nonsense,  while 
our  wonder,  on  the  other  hand,  is  that  reputable  and  other- 
wise intelligent  men  could  have  managed  so  to  pervert  and 
misunderstand  statements  that  to  us  are  lucidity  itself.  Simi- 
larly at  the  present  time  if  some  of  the  remarkable  accounts 
of  Freud's  views  that  are  given  by  his  opponents  represented 
anything  like  what  he  really  holds,  the  fact  would  need  much 
explanation  that  so  many  scientific  men  can  accept  them  and 
yet  remain  sane. 

Yet  this  astonishing  stupidity  in  apprehending  the  argu- 
ments of  opponents,  and  in  defending  preconceived  views,  is 
only  apparent.  The  men  who  so  grossly  misinterpreted 
Darwin  were  often  men  of  the  highest  intellectual  power,  and 
the  same  is  true  of  many  of  Freud's  opponents;  similarly  no 
one  can  read  closely  the  Malleus  Maleficarum  without  admira- 
tion for  the  amazing  intellectual  ingenuity  with  which  the 
most  fantastic  propositions  are  there  defended.  The  process 
is  one  that  psychiatrists  call  "emotional  stupidity,"  a  symp- 
tom seen  in  patients  who  have  no  real  defect  of  reasoning 
power,  but  who  through  various  affective  influences  are  in  a 
condition  that  at  first  sight  gives  rise  to  a  strong  suspicion  of 
some  organic  defect  of  the  brain. 

On  observing  the  general  attitude  towards  people  whose 
"emotional  stupidity"  has  in  the  course  of  time  become 
apparent,  two  things  are  noticeable.  In  the  first  place,  as 
was  remarked  above,  the  fault  is  attributed  much  more  to 
intellectual  inferiority  than  to  the  more  important  affective 
causes.  Hence  the  present  day  supercilious  pity  for  the 
scholastics  of  the  "dark  ages, "  an  attitude  considerably  modi- 
fied by  an  objective  comparison  of  the  reasoning  powers 
characteristic  of  the  two  civilizations.  In  the  second  place,  far 
greater  leniency  is  shown  towards  a  stupidity  that  expressed 
itself  in  the  form  of  blind  adherence  to  accepted  errors,  than 
that  which  expressed  itself  in  the  form  of  blind  rejection  of  a 
novel  truth;  in  other  words,  credulousness  is  always  more 
harshly  judged  than  incredulousness,  though  they  are  both 
merely   different   aspects   of  the  same  fundamental  failing, 

Journal — 4 


526  JONES 

namely,  lack  of  true  scepticism.  Yet  the  one  is  hardly  more 
characteristic  of  human  weakness  than  the  other — as  Nietzsche 
put  it:  "Mankind  has  a  bad  ear  for  new  music" — and  it 
would  be  hard  to  convince  a  student  of  human  progress  that 
the  first  manifestation  has  a  greater  retarding  influence  on 
this  than  the  second.  In  any  case  these  considerations  go  to 
show  the  fallacy  of  the  popular  belief  that  the  will  is  the  servant 
of  reason,  the  truth  being  that  reason  has  always  been,  and 
probably  always  must  be,  only  the  handmaid  of  the  will. 

XI.    Summary 

Only  a  small  part  of  the  subject  matter  dealt  with  by  Freud 
has  been  covered  in  the  present  paper.  Those  interested  are 
referred  to  his  book  for  richer  and  more  numerous  examples, 
and  for  the  lucid  and  penetrating  discussion  there  given  of  the 
theoretical  aspects  of  the  subject.  It  is  perhaps  desirable, 
however,  to  summarize  here  the  main  conclusions  on  the 
topics    discussed    above. 

The  occurrences  that  form  the  subject-matter  of  this  study, 
the  general  characteristics  of  which  were  defined  in  the 
introductory  section,^  may  be  divided  into  motor  and  sensory.^ 
The  defects  of  the  former  class  that  enter  into  consideration 
are  two,  (i)  the  erroneous  carrying  out  of  an  intended  purpose 
(slips  of  the  tongue  and  pen,  erroneously  carried  out  actions), 
and  (2)  the  carrying  out  of  an  unintended  purpose  (symp- 
tomatic acts) .  The  defects  of  the  latter  class  are  also  two,  ( i ) 
simple  failure  of  perception  (forgetting,  not  seeing),  and  (2) 
erroneous  perception  (false  recollection,  false  visual  perception) . 
In  each  class  the  distinction  between  the  two  kinds  of  defects 
is  not  sharp;  thus  in  the  latter  one,  for  instance,  a  failure  to 
remember  is  always  accompanied  by  an  over-prominent 
remembrance  of  some  associated  memory,  a  false  recollection. 
Further,  the  distinction  between  the  two  classes  themselves 
is  not  a  sharp  one,  both  motor  and  sensory  processes  playing 
a  part  in  many  instances;  thus  in  the  mislaying  of  objects, 
the  object  is  first  misplaced,  and  then  the  memory  of  the  act 
is  forgotten. 

Common  to  all  forms  is  the  fact  that  the  subject,  and  most 
observers,  either  give  an  obviously  inadequate  explanation 
of  the  particular  occurrence,  such  as  that  it  was  due  to  "inat- 
tention,"   "absent-mindedness,"    "chance,"    and   so   on,    or 

iln  Germany  the  cironeousness  of  the  process  is  conveniently  indicated 
by  the  preface  "ver";  thus,  verdnicken,  vergessen,  vergreifen,  verlegen,  ver- 
lesen,  verschreiben,  versehen,  versprechen,  etc. 

'This  term  is  here  used  in  its  neuro-biological  sense,  and  hence  includes 
perceptive  and  apperceptive  processes. 


TH^  PSYCHOPATHOI^OGY  OF  EVERYDAY  UFE      527 

frankly  maintain  that  it  has  no  explanation  at  all.  On  the 
contrary  psycho-analysis  shows  that  there  is  not  only  a  defi- 
nite psychical  cause  for  the  occurrence,  but  that  this  has 
always  a  logical  meaning,  and  may  strictly  be  called  a  motive. 
This  motive  is  some  secondary  tendency  or  train  of  thought, 
of  which  the  subject  is  not  aware  at  the  time.  Usually  it  is 
fore-conscious,  or,  in  popular  language,  unconscious;  in 
many  cases  it  is  unconscious  in  the  strict  sense,  and  is  then 
correspondingly  more  difficult  to  reveal.  In  most  cases  there 
are  both  a  fore-conscious  and  unconscious  motive,  which  are 
associated  with  each  other.  The  motive  is  repressed  by  the 
subject,  the  repression  being  a  defence-mechanism  that  sub- 
serves the  function  of  keeping  from  consciousness  undesirable 
or  painful  thoughts.  The  motive  may  be  one  of  two  kinds: 
either  it  is  a  counter-impulse  {Gegenwillen)  directed  immediately 
against  the  mental  operation  that  is  intended,  or  it  is  an 
impulse  directed  against  some  mental  tendency  that  stands 
in  associative  connection  with  this  operation;  that  is  to  say, 
the  association  between  the  two  mental  processes  may  be 
either  intrinsic  or  extrinsic.  As  a  result  of  the  repression  any 
direct  manifestation  of  the  tendency  is  inhibited,  and  it  can 
come  to  expression  only  as  a  parasitic  process  engrafted  on 
another,  conscious  one.  The  disturbance  thus  caused  con- 
stitutes a  temporary  failure  or  error  of  normal  mental  func- 
tioning. 

This  error  can  psychologically  be  compared  with  a  psycho- 
neurotic symptom,  the  mechanisms  by  which  the  two  are 
brought  about  are  almost  the  same,  and  the  psychical  material 
that  is  the  source  of  them  is  closely  similar  in  the  two  cases. 
It  is  maintained  that  appreciation  of  the  significance  of  these 
everyday  errors  is  important  for  both  the  practice  and  theory 
of  psychology;  this  is  especially  so  in  the  contribution  it 
furnishes  to  the  problem  of  psychical  determinism,  and  in  the 
understanding  it  gives  to  the  deeper,  non-conscious  motives 
of  conduct.  It  further  throws  a  valuable  light  on  certain 
social  problems,  notably  the  question  of  mutual  misunder- 
standings in  everyday  life,  and  on  the  importance  of  aJBFect- 
ive  influences  in  forming  decisions  and  judgments. 


A  CASE  OF  COLORED  GUSTATION 


By  JuNB  E.  Downey,  University  of  Wyoming 


Cases  of  colored  gustation  have  been  described  in  less  detail 
than  the  more  common  instances  of  colored  audition.  The 
relative  infrequency  with  which  colored  tastes  and  colored 
odors  have  been  reported  has  been  explained  from  the  fact 
that  taste  and  odor  are  so  bound  up  with  the  perception  of 
a  colored  body  that  one's  attention  is  attracted  away  from  the 
photism  even  when  it  is  attracted  to  the  color  of  the  object. 
The  photisms  are  said  to  be  most  readily  perceived  in  cases 
where  an  odor  or  a  taste  from  an  unknown  source  suddenly 
attracts  the  attention.  In  the  present  instance  there  has 
been  no  difficulty  in  perceiving  the  taste-color,  because  the 
latter  is  very  brilliant,  and  it  frequently  persists  more  than 
ten  minutes.  Moreover,  the  taste-color  is  quite  as  intensive 
and  quite  as  fully  saturated  as  are  the  colors  of  objects;  it 
can  therefore  be  maintained  without  difficulty  in  the  presence 
of  the  latter. 

The  young  man  (5.),  who  reports  the  present  case,  is  a 
senior  in  college,  has  had  some  practice  in  psychological  ex- 
perimentation, and  is  an  excellent  observer.  He  has  been 
under  observation  a  year.  So  far  as  he  can  remember,  he 
has  always  experienced  tastes  as  colored.  He  reports  that, 
as  children,  he  and  his  sister  employed  color-names  in  describ- 
ing their  tastes.  His  taste-colors  are  located  in  the  mouth; 
and  they  are  intensified  by  closing  his  eyes.  He  recalls  an 
illness  during  which  his  tastes  were  especially  highly  colored. 
In  eating  his  meals,  he  ignores  the  induced  colors;  and, 
indeed,  one  color  is  frequently  cancelled  by  another,  during 
the  act  of  eating.  When  the  induced  taste-color  does  not 
correspond  with  the^actual  color  of  the  food,  a  most  disagreea- 
ble experience  results.  For  instance,  brown  and  yellow 
mints  are  extremely  distasteful,  because  of  conflict  of  these 
colors  with  the  green  taste-color  which  is  common  to  all 
mints.  In  general,  pink  and  lavender  tastes  are  agreeable; 
reds  and  browns  are  disagreeable.  Blue  tastes  are  never 
experienced.  S.  reports  that  colors  suggest  tactual  experi- 
ences, and  that  tactual  impressions  suggest  color. 

In  our  investigation  of  the  case,  the  following  questions 
were  kept  in  mind  throughout:     i.  Does  S.  possess  a  normal 


A  CASE  OF  COLORED  GUSTATION  529 

sensitivity  to  taste?  2.  Are  the  color- tones  of  his  tastes  uni- 
formly determined  by  any  particular  factor  in  the  gustatory 
complex?  3.  Is  the  induced  color  sensational  or  imaginal? 
4.  Are  his  associations  of  touch  and  color  comparable  with 
his  associations  of  taste  and  color?  5.  Is  there  a  correspon- 
dence between  the  feeling-tone  of  taste  and  that  of  its  atten- 
dant color? 

I.     Does    our   Subject  Possess    a   Normai,   Gustatory 
Sensitivity? 

In  our  determination  of  the.  limens  both  for  the  presence 
and  for  the  recognition  of  taste  sensation,  the  method  em- 
ployed by  Miss  Thompson^  was  followed  precisely,  in  order 
that  our  results  might  be  comparable  with  hers.  5.'s  limens 
of  presence  were  as  follows, — all  solutions  being  prepared  with 
distilled  water,  and  each  limen  being  regarded  as  established 
only  when  three  out  of  four  judgments  were  correct:  Sweet, 
.0005  per  cent,  saccharin;  salt,  .04  per  cent,  pure  sodium 
chloride;  sour,  .003  per  cent,  sulphuric  acid;  bitter,  .00008 
per  cent,  sulphate  of  quinine.  A  reference  to  Miss  Thomp- 
son's curves  shows  that  five  of  her  twenty-five  male  subjects 
gave  a  limen  for  sweet  as  low  as  that  of  the  present  subject; 
four  of  her  subjects  gave  a. limen  for  salt  as  low  as  S.,  and  two 
subjects  a  lower  limen.  Seven  gave  the  same  limen  for  sour, 
and  four  subjects  gave  a  lower  limen.  Miss  Thompson  reports 
no  subject  whose  limen  for  the  presence  of  bitter  was  as  low 
as  that  obtained  for  S. 

In  our  investigation  of  the  limens  of  recognition  it  was 
found  that  S.  showed  great  facility  in  describing  the  tactual 
accompaniments  of  the  four  taste  qualities.  His  judgments 
of  the  taste  qualities  were  usually  indirect  inferences  which 
were  based  upon  the  local  tactual  or  color  accompaniments. 
He  described  salt,  sweet,  sour  and  bitter  as  merely  'feels '  upon 
the  tongue.  He  insisted  that  a  lump  of  sugar  had  no  taste; 
and  he  remarked  casually  that  rock-candy  was  salt.  None 
the  less,  his  gustatory  sensitivity  appeared  normal,  or  supra- 
normal. 

The  limen  for  the  recognition  of  sweet  was  .0005  per  cent, 
saccharin, — a  lower  limen  than  Miss  Thompson  obtained 
for  any  of  her  male  subjects.  Discrimination  both  of  this 
taste  quality  and  of  its  relative  intensity  was  due  to  the  pres- 
ence of  the  concomitant  black,  which  was  present  even  with 
the  weakest  solution  which  we  employed.  The  'feel'  of  sweet 
was  usually  located  at  the  tip  of  the  tongue. 

^H.  B.  Thompson:  Psychological  Norms  in  Men  and  Women.  University 
of  Chicago  Contributions  to  Philosophy,  IV.  i.     1903,  50  f. 


530  DOWNEY 

The  limen  for  the  recognition  of  salt  was  about  average, — 
.II  per  cent,  sodium  chloride.  Four  of  Miss  Thompson's 
subjects  gave  the  same,  and  ten  gave  a  lower  limen.  Color 
rarely  appeared  with  this  solution;  when  it  did  appear  it  was 
slate  or  dirty  white.  The  discrimination  of  salt  from  sweet 
revealed  the  following  characteristics:  It  was  differently 
localized;  it  failed  to  persist;  it  had  no  color.  The  judgments 
were  given  slowly,  and  with  clear  consciousness  of  the  founda- 
tion upon  which  they  were  based. 

The  limen  for  recognition  of  sour  was  also  average,  or 
somewhat  high, — .007  per  cent,  sulphuric  acid,  a  limen  which 
Miss  Thompson  found  for  twelve  of  her  subjects,  while  seven 
of  her  subjects  gave  a  lower  limen.  Color  entered  the  ex- 
perience, but  without  much  uniformity, — brown,  red  and  green 
being  reported.  The  distinctive  tactual  component  was  its 
puckering  character. 

The  limen  for  recognition  of  bitter  was  low.  At  the  point 
where  discrimination  began, — .0003  per  cent,  sulphate  of 
quinine, — a  dull  orange-red  entered  the  experience,  and  be- 
came more  pronounced  as  the  solutions  increased  in  intensity. 
The  tactual  component  was  a  roughness.  S.  remarked  that 
the  solution  tasted  exactly  like  a  mixture  of  red  pepper  and 
water.  Only  one  of  Miss  Thompson's  male  subjects  gave  the 
same  limen  as  S.,  and  only  two  gave  a  lower  limen.  It  seems 
to  be  significant  that  the  two  solutions  which  gave  the  lowest 
limens  for  recognition, — the  sweet  and  the  bitter, — are  just 
those  taste  qualities  which  are  most  unambiguously  colored. 

Individual  papillae  were  stimulated  by  means  of  strong 
solutions  of  the  four  sapid  substances,  and  it  was  found  that 
the  color  component  did  not  occur  with  minutely  circum- 
scribed stimulation.  Here  as  before,  discrimination  proved 
to  be  a  product  of  tactual  differentiae,  excepting  in  the  case 
of  bitter.  The  rough  effect  which  was  noticeable  in  the  case 
of  bitter  with  extensive  stimulation  was  lacking  in  the  papillary 
test.  5.  identified  bitter  by  successively  eliminating  the  other 
three  taste  qualities.  He  also  reported  an  inter  mi  ttence  or 
'beating'  of  sensation,  which  facilitated  his  identification; 
the  identification  was  made  very  slowly  but  with  considerable 
accuracy.  When,  on  withdrawing  the  tongue,  the  solution 
spread  over  the  lingual  surface,  the  familiar  orange-red  ap- 
peared. In  not  a  single  instance  did  5.  detect  the  purely 
bitter  quality  of  the  solution, — a  two  per  cent,  solution  of  hy- 
drochlorate  of  quinine. 

Although  our  tests  suggest  the  inference  that  S.  's  sense  of 
taste  may  be  defective,  they  do  no  more  than  suggest  it.  A 
crucial  test  would  involve  a  separation  of  tactual  and  gustatory 


A   CASE   OF   COI.OR:eD   GUSTATION  53 1 

qualities, — a  separation  which,  indeed,  we  attempted  but 
without  success. 

The  most  convincing  evidence  of  a  defective  gustatory 
sensitivity  is  furnished  by  S.'s  insistence  that  solutions  of 
cayenne  pepper  and  of  quinine  taste  exactly  alike.  He  was, 
indeed,  unable  to  distinguish  between  strong  solutions  of 
red  pepper  and  of  quinine,  because  both  produced  the  same 
'feel'  upon  the  tongue,  and  both  were  accompanied  by  the 
same  color.  After  rubbing  his  forehead  with  capsicum 
vaseline,  S.  reported  a  'smart'  or  'burn,'  which,  although  not 
accompanied  by  color,  gave  'the  same  tactual  feeling  as  the 
taste  of  bitter. '  It  would  seem  that,  for  5.,  bitter  is  simply  a 
rough,  burning  sensation.  He  does  not  find  the  taste  of 
quinine  unduly  disagreeable;  and  he  shows  none  of  the 
ordinary  reactions  to  an  intensive  bitter.  He  is,  moreover, 
unable  to  understand  how  bitter,  as  he  employs  the  term,  is, 
in  the  slightest  degree,  characteristic  of  the  taste  of  unsweet- 
ened chocolate  or  of  ground  coffee,  both  of  which  gave  the 
color  brown.  All  spices,  on  the  other  hand,  induced  red  or 
reddish  brown  colors,  similar  to  the  color  of  pepper.  His 
recognition  of  spices  was  slow.  Cinnamon  and  mustard  were 
named,  but  without  any  high  degree  of  confidence;  and 
ginger  was  stated  to  be  either  cinnamon  or  pepper.  It  is 
a  significant  fact  that  the  taste  of  bitter,  which  furnished  the 
best  evidence  of  a  gustatory  defect,  was  also  the  taste  which 
was  most  uniformly  and  most  unambiguously  accompanied 
by  color. 

As  already  stated,  S.  describes  sugar  as  a  'feel.'  He  sugars 
his  food  in  order  to  make  the  taste  milder;  and  he  is  accus- 
tomed to  put  a  pinch  of  salt  into  chocolate  in  order  to  change 
its  'feel'.  When  a  drop  of  peppermint,  or  of  lemon  juice  was 
added  to  salt,  S.  identified  the  salt  very  slowly,  and  even 
confused  it  with  sugar. 

His  recognition  of  tastes  was  often  retarded  to  a  remarkable 
degree.  In  one  instance,  strong  essence  of  peppermint  was 
not  identified  until  after  three  minutes.  In  repeated  ex- 
periments with  anise,  which  is  attended  by  a  brilliant  black 
color,  it  was  found  that  this  color  appeared  in  time  to  serve 
as  a  mark  of  identification.  Sarsaparilla  syrup,  which  like- 
wise induced  black,  was  also  identified  as  anise.  Listerine 
was  at  first  called  camphor  and  alum;  and,  after  four  tests  in 
which  its  name  was  furnished  to  S.,  he  still  failed  to  recog- 
nize it. 

The  question  naturally  arises  as  to  whether  5.'s  olfactory 
sense  is  normal.  A  test  with  the  olfactometer  showed  that  it  is. 
It  is  possible  that  the  recognition  of  strongly  odoriferous 
substances  was,  at  times,  retarded  by  the  brilliant  taste-colors, 


532  DOWNEY 

which  may  have  served  to  distract  attention.  It  was  found, 
however,  that  odors  are  not  colored  for  S.  save  in  rare  instances. 
In  the  few  positive  cases  which  we  discovered  during  the 
course  of  the  investigation,  a  distinct  taste  was  found  to  be 
induced  by  the  olfactory  stimulation. 

2.    Is  THE  Color-tone  of  Tastes  Uniformly  Determined 

BY  any  Particular  Component  in  the 

Gustatory  Complex? 

Here  the  writer  recognized  the  possibility  that  odor  was  the 
factor  which  determined  the  color-tone  of  the  taste;  and  this 
possibility  was  carefully  tested.  Solutions  including  syrups 
of  orange,  lemon,  cherry,  pineapple,  the  essences  of  wintergreen, 
anise,  and  bitter  almonds  together  with  lime-juice  and  alum 
were  employed.  5.  plugged  his  nostrils  and  the  central 
region  of  the  tongue  was  painted  lightly  with  the  solution, 
S.  immediately  recording  his  experience  without  withdrawing 
his  tongue.  The  sides  and  tip  of  the  lingual  surface  were  then 
painted,  and  records  were  made  as  before.  Then  a  few  drops 
of  the  solution  were  placed  upon  the  tongue  and  allowed  to 
spread,  and  to  be  swallowed.  And  finally  the  nostrils  were 
unplugged,  and  a  few  drops  of  the  solution  were  taken  and 
immediately  swallowed.  The  results  of  these  experiments 
were  clear-cut  and  definite.  Excepting  in  the  case  of  the 
intensely  sweet  solutions,  color  entered  the  complex  only 
when  the  solution  spread  over  the  surface  of  the  tongue. 
This  color  became  more  intensive  and  more  persistent  when, 
on  the  nostrils  being  unplugged,  the  olfactory  component 
was  added  to  the  gustatory  complex. 

The  author  was  tempted  to  conclude  that  the  presence  of 
color  in  the  complex  was  largely  due  to  the  olfactory  com- 
ponent. But  this  conclusion  is  not  in  accord  with  the  fact 
that  odorless  tastes, — those  from  our  sweet,  sour  and  bitter 
solutions  aroused  colors;  and  with  the  additional  fact  that 
odors  themselves  were  uncolored,  save  in  rare  instances.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  fact  that  the  taste-colors  were  frequently 
intensified  by  unplugging  the  nostrils,  and  the  fact  that  in- 
tensive colors  were  more  frequently  present  when  the  sub- 
stances were  more  strongly  flavored,  suggest  the  influence  of 
odor  as  an  inducer  of  color.  The  presence  of  odor  and  of 
extensive  stimulation  certainly  increases  the  vividness  and 
the  persistence  of  the  taste-colors. 

The  writer  is  convinced  that  a  thoroughgoing  analysis 
would  reveal  the  existence  of  a  constant  and  uniform  principle 
which  determines  the  color  tones  of  various  tastes.  It  must 
be  confessed,  however,  that  certain  facts  still  remain  unac- 
counted for,  even  after  extensive  experimentation.     A  cata- 


A  CASE  OF  COLORED  GUSTATION  533 

logue  of  the  colors  which  are  induced  by  various  stimulations 
shows  that  it  is  impossible  to  classify  them  upon  the  basis 
of  the  olfactory  component ;  it  is  possible,  however,  to  a  certain 
extent,  to  classify  them  upon  the  basis  of  the  four  taste 
qualities.  It  must  be  borne  in  mind  that,  for  S.,  the  chief 
characteristic  of  a  taste  is  frequently  its  tactual,  and  particu- 
larly its  pungent  or  cooling  effect.  And  this  peculiarity  must 
be  reckoned  with  in  any  attempted  classification  of  tastes. 
But  so  distinct  are  the  complexes  experienced  that  any  en- 
deavor to  classify  the  very  individual  gustatory  fusions  under 
four  heads  must  appear  to  be  forced.  With  these  reservations 
in  mind,  however,  we  shall  attempt  the  classification. 

Strong  solutions  of  sugar  and  weak  solutions  of  saccharin 
were  found  to  give  black,  although,  strangely  enough,  neither 
granulated  nor  lump  sugar  gave  a  colored  taste.  The  latter, 
in  fact,  were  not  found  to  be  intensively  sweet,  although  they 
produced  a  distinct  tactual  sensation.  Anise,  cherry  syrup 
and  sarsaparilla  syrup  were  described  as  sweet,  and  induced 
black, — that  of  anise  being  very  brilliant.  Tar-water  also 
gave  a  black  taste;  but  S.  was  uncertain  whether,  in  this 
case,  he  actually  experienced  a  true  synaesthesia.  The  in- 
duced black  seemed  to  him  to  be  imaginal  rather  than  sen- 
sational. 

Quinine  solutions,  both  strong  and  weak,  gave  a  dull 
orange-red  taste, — an  orange-red  which  re- appeared  in  the 
taste  of  red-pepper,  essence  of  bitter  almonds,  and  alum.  A 
modified  red  was  induced  by  lime  juice,  peach  flavor,  pine- 
apple syrup,  and  various  spices.  As  previously  mentioned,  the 
burn  or  sting  of  the  sensation  was  a  prominent  part  of  such 
tastes. 

Saturated  salt  solution  was  found  to  giv&  a  crystal-clear 
experience.  Moreover,  it  was  found  that  a  salt  solution 
would  remove  mouth-colors  which  were  already  present, — a 
discovery  which  proved  to  be  most  valuable  in  experimenta- 
tion, since  the  long  persistence  of  the  taste-colors  made  ex- 
perimentation an  exceedingly  slow  and  laborious  process. 
Listerine  was  the  only  other  solution  found  to  have  this  effect. 

The  results  obtained  from  sour  were  less  clear-cut  than  those 
from  other  taste-qualities.  Green  is,  perhaps,  the  color  of 
purely  sour  solutions.  An  occasional  flash  of  green  appeared 
in  the  test  with  minimal  solutions.  Eight  per  cent,  tartaric 
acid  was  used  as  a  strong  solution,  and  this  also  gave,  at  times, 
a  flash  of  green.  It  was  noticeable  that  even  this  strong  sour 
solution  was  sometimes  confused  with  bitter.  An  attempt 
was  made  to  provide  tastes  that  S.  would  find  very  sour. 
This  proved  to  be  difficult.     A  lemon  juice  that  the  experi- 


534  DOWNEY 

menter  found  excessively  sour  seemed  to  S.  to  be  only  moder- 
ately so.  This  lemon  juice  was  found  to  give,  however,  a 
flash  of  green,  a  green  which  was  more  certainly  induced  when 
the  lemon  juice  was  cooled.  A  sour,  lemon-pineapple  sherbet 
was  reported  as  very  green,  a  green  which  persisted.  In 
the  laboratory  tests,  peppermint  was  the  only  solution  that 
gave  uniformly  a  persistent  and  vivid  green.  It  would  seem 
from  these  facts  that  a  cooling-effect  is  essential  to  green 
tastes.  It  is,  moreover,  not  without  interest  that  S.  classi- 
fies peppermint  as  a  sour  taste. 

Usually,  in  the  tests  in  which  green  appeared,  it  was  very 
unstable,  alternating  with  the  color  pink  or  red.  Such  alter- 
nation was  observed  for  orange  syrup,  peach  syrup  and,  above 
all,  for  wintergreen.  Wintergreen,  in  fact,  gave  the  most 
interesting  results.  The  taste-color  of  wintergreen  was  a 
brilliant  pink,  which,  however,  was  preceded  by  green  or 
alternated  with  green.  Usually  the  green  persisted  only  a 
few  seconds,  while  the  pink  lasted  many  minutes.  When, 
however,  the  wintergreen  solution  was  cooled,  it  gave  a  green 
that  persisted  nearly  two  minutes  before  changing  to  pink, 
while  the  same  solution  when  warmed,  gave  a  deeper  pink 
than  usual,  and  no  green. 

The  alternation  of  green  with  pink  raises  an  interesting 
question,  as  to  the  possibility  of  obtaining  after-image  effects 
from  colored  tastes.  In  support  of  the  affirmative  answer  to 
this  question,  are  two  other  casual  observations.  Once  a 
black  taste  became  white;  and  5.  reported  a  grape- juice  punch 
that  in  course  of  eating  changed  from  a  purple  to  a  yellow 
taste.  On  the  other  hand,  on  this  assumption,  it  is  diflficult 
to  understand  why  the  vivid  green  of  peppermint,  which  at 
times  persisted  many  minutes,  should  fail  to  give  an  after- 
image. In  any  case,  we  are  left  with  pink  as  an  unexplained 
color. 

Tests  of  the  effect  of  mixing  the  standard  solutions,  and 
the  effect  of  successive  applications  of  such  solutions,  were 
next  planned.  The  mixed  solutions  gave  the  following  re- 
sults: Salt  and  sweet  produced  a  sweet  taste  without  color; 
salt  and  tartaric  acid  tasted  salt  and  bitter  and  induced 
dark  orange;  salt  and  quinine  gave  a  bitter  taste  and  a 
faint  suggestion  of  red;  tartaric  acid  and  sweet  gave,  upon 
one  occasion,  a  sour-sweet  taste,  and  a  pink  color;  a  second 
time,  a  sour  taste  with  a  flash  of  green;  tartaric  acid  and 
quinine  produced  a  bitter  taste  and  a  reddish  color,  which  was 
less  pronounced  than  usual;  quinine  and  sugar  solution 
tasted  sweet,  although  the  combination  was  very  bitter  for 
the  experimenter,  and  produced  a  "queer  hollow  black" 
which  vanished  as  soon  as  the  solution  was  swallowed. 


A  CASE  OP  COLORED  GUSTATION  535 

Application  of  the  standard  solutions  in  pairs  was  next 
attempted,  each  pair  being  utilized  twice,  and  the  order  of 
application  varied.  The  results,  on  the  application  of  the 
second  solution,  were  as  follows:  Salt-sweet,  no  taste,  no 
color;  sweet-salt,  no  taste,  no  color;  salt- tartaric  acid,  bit- 
ing effect  of  salt  intensified,  no  color;  tartaric  acid-salt, 
salty  taste,  no  color;  salt-quinine,  neutralized  taste,  red  color 
as  soon  as  salt  effect  wears  off;  quinine-salt,  second  taste 
clears  up  the  first,  then  orange-red  returns;  tartaric  acid- 
sweet,  neutral  taste,  no  color;  sweet-tartaric  acid,  sweet  then 
sour  taste,  green  with  sour  taste;  tartaric  acid — quinine, 
taste  not  recorded,  color  red,  a  different  red  from  that  pro- 
duced by  pure  taste  of  bitter;  quinine-tartaric  acid,  taste  not 
recorded,  orange-red  of  bitter  taste  brightened  by  sour  stimu- 
lation ;  quinine-sugar,  taste  unrecorded,  orange-red  unchanged ; 
sugar-quinine,  bitter  taste  prevailed,  red  darker  than  bitter- 
red. 

One  seems  justified  in  concluding  that  salt  "clears  up"  the 
colors  induced  by  the  other  solutions,  but  that  this  "clearing- 
up"  is  least  stable  in  the  case  of  bitter.  Sour  is  found  to 
modify  the  orange-red  of  bitter,  and  to  neutralize  sweet,  once 
giving  pink,  in  this  combination;  bitter  and  sweet  appear, 
at  times,  to  give  a  color  intermediate  between  the  colors  of 
the  pure  solutions. 

It  seemed  possible  that  pink  represented  a  sour- sweet  taste, 
lycmon  juice  was  accordingly  sweetened  in  the  hope  of  pro- 
ducing a  pink  taste.  One  attempt  was  successful;  but  a 
second  attempt  gave  yellow  instead.  It  is  very  difficult  to 
make  the  sweet  in  a  mixture  perceptible  for  5.  Peppermint 
essence  was  dropped  on  sugar;  but  the  sugar  was  "not  even 
tasted"  and  the  green  taste  remained  unchanged.  If,  in 
fact,  pink  be  a  sour-sweet  taste,  the  color  is  certainly  not  a 
mixture  of  the  colors  obtained  from  piure  sour  and  a  saturated 
sugar  solution. 

The  pink  of  wintergreen  unites  with  the  golden  color  induced 
by  a  lime  wafer,  to  produce  a  rose-color,  unlike  the  usual 
pink  of  wintergreen.  If  anise  be  taken  while  the  wintergreen 
pink  is  still  bright,  there  is  a  change  to  brilliant  black.  This 
black  persists  for  a  short  time  only;  and  a  dirty  pink  results, 
which,  in  time,  clears  up,  and  gives  a  light  pink  which  lasts 
several  minutes. 

The  only  other  color  that  remains  unaccounted  for  is  yellow, 
with  its  variants, — tan  and  brown.  This  color  was  obtained 
from  the  following  solutions:  sweetened  lemon  juice,  yellow 
(once);  peppermint  on  salt,  yellow  (tried  once);  vanilla,  tan 
or  brown  (constant);  lime  juice,  yellow  (once,  alternating 
with  red) ;  lime  candy  wafer,  golden  (constant) ;  lemon  candy 


536  DOWNEY 

wafer,  yellow  and  brown  (tried  once) ;  lemon  essence  diluted, 
yellowish  brown  mixed  with  green;  sassafras  candy  wafer, 
pink  shot  with  yellow  light  (tried  once);  hot  oil  of  cloves 
diluted,  tannish  brown  (tried  once);  same  solution  on  salt, 
flash  of  brown  (tried  once) ;  chocolate  and  coffee,  dark  brown 
(constant);  nuts  of  various  kinds, — brown,  minced  English 
walnuts  giving  the  lightest  color.  Once,  while  the  green  taste 
of  peppermint  was  still  vivid,  wintergreen  was  given.  This 
stimulation  resulted  in  a  bright  and  pronounced  pink,  which 
changed  finally  to  tan. 

It  is  perhaps  unnecessary  to  state  that  all  tests  were  tried 
without  5.'s  knowledge  of  the  stimulus  to  be  given  and  that 
his  eyes  were  usually  closed,  during  the  test. 

3.     Is  THE  Induced  C01.OR  Sensationai.  or  Imaginal? 

That  the  color  element  in  the  tastes  under  consideration  was 
sensational  in  value  seems  to  us  to  be  proved  by  its  constancy 
in  tone  for  a  given  taste,  as  shown  by  tests  at  widely  separated 
intervals ;  by  its  persistence ;  by  its  localization  in  the  mouth ; 
and  by  the  fact  that  results  were  novel  and  unanticipated  by 
S.,  who  was  curious  as  to  what  might  come,  and  reported 
results  as  in  a  sensation  test.  Several  of  the  solutions  were 
new  to  him,  as,  for  instance,  anise ;  but  these  new  gustatory  ex- 
periences yielded  as  constant  colors  as  did  the  familiar  tastes. 
It  was  noticeable  that  the  color  was  usually  named  before  a 
taste  was  recognized;  in  fact,  S.  frequently  relies  upon  color 
as  an  aid  in  recognition.  These  taste-colors  were  not  influ- 
enced by  suggestion,  as  was  shown  by  tests.  Moreover, 
when  colored  candy  wafers  were  used,  and  the  eyes  kept  open, 
the  color  experienced  was  not  affected  by  the  objective  color. 

S.  found  difficulty  in  describing  the  taste-colors.  For  in- 
stance, he  reported  that  the  beautiful  glazed  black  of  anise, 
had  never  been  experienced  in  any  other  connection.  S. 
insisted  that  color  is  an  integral  part  of  the  taste-fusion,  and 
reported  that  wintergreen  changed  perceptibly  in  taste  when  it 
shifted  from  green  to  pink. 

That  the  colors  were  not  called  up  voluntarily  is  shown  by 
the  fact  that,  when  asked  to  give  from  memory  the  color  of 
a  particular  taste,  S.  frequently  made  mistakes,  even  in  the 
case  of  solutions  that  gave  perfectly  uniform  results  during 
experimentation.  Furthermore,  S.  showed  very  little  capacity 
in  voluntary  visualization  of  colors,  and  was  unable  to  pro- 
ject these  colors. 

6".  also  showed  little  capacity  in  the  voluntary  projection  of 
a  taste-color  to  an  external  surface.  Twice,  however,  the 
surface  upon  which  he  was  gazing  became,  to  his  surprise,  a 


A   CASK   OF   COIvORKD   GUSTATION  537 

brilliant  pink,  the  color  of  the  wintergreen  which  he  was 
tasting.  Both  of  these  occurrences  were  spontaneous  and 
unexpected.  Attempts  to  throw  the  mouth-color  upon  a 
colored  surface,  in  order  to  test  the  effect  of  such  super- 
position, met  with  little  success.  In  general,  when  instructed 
to  gaze  steadfastly  at  a  colored  surface  while  experiencing 
a  taste-color,  S.  reported  most  disagreeable  tension  with 
dizziness.  The  mouth-color  was  fully  as  vivid  as  the  objec- 
tive color,  but  was  differently  localized. 

The  following  were  among  the  tests  which  we  attempted. 
Strong  essence  of  wintergreen  was  given,  and  pink  color  ob- 
tained in  mouth ;  disc  of  spectral  green  placed  before  5. ;  no 
fusion.  Attempt  made  to  throw  green  peppermint  taste- 
color  upon  rose  paper;  unsuccessful.  5.  unable  to  keep  at- 
tention off  mouth-color  even  when  so  instructed;  rose  finally 
fixated  for  45  sec;  eyes  then  closed;  5".  got  gray  in  front  of 
eyes,  and  green  in  mouth;  then  a  rose-red  image  came,  and 
seemed  to  fuse  with  green;  green  returned.  Attempt  made 
to  throw  the  brown  obtained  from  cinnamon  candy  wafer 
upon  dark  blue  paper;  no  fusion;  intermittent  attention; 
blue  caused  confusion  and  dizziness;  blue  did  not  banish 
brown  which  became  darker.  Orange-red  pepper  taste  ob- 
tained and  dark  green  paper  used  to  stimulate  eyes ;  attention 
fluctuates;  no  fusion.  After-images  were  also  obtained  before 
giving  a  taste-stimulation  and  an  attempt  made  to  fuse  these 
colors  with  those  induced  by  taste,  but  without  success.  The 
eyes  were  fatigued  for  a  certain  color  without  any  perceptible 
effect  upon  a  mouth-color  of  the  same  general  tone.  Thus, 
fatiguing  for  black  had  apparently  no  effect  upon  the  black 
taste  of  anise;  and  fatiguing  for  green  had  no  effect  upon  the 
green  peppermint  taste.  While  maintaining  green  in  the  mouth, 
S.  could  get  an  after-image  from  spectral  green  without 
interference  of  colors.  It  has  already  been  mentioned  that 
peppermint  green  can  be  maintained  as  long  as  seven  minutes, 
without  failure  of  the  color  through  fatigue. 

4.  Ark  thk  Associations  of  Touch  and  Color  Compar- 

ABLK  WITH  THK  ASSOCIATIONS  OF  TaSTK  AND  COLOR? 

Our  experimental  results  lead  us  to  answer  this  question 
in  the  negative.  Color  calls  up  tactual  experiences  much  more 
consistently  and  much  more  frequently  than  touch  evokes 
color.  In  an  investigation  of  the  latter  situation,  it  was 
found  that  certain  tactual  experiences  frequently  suggested 
color,  but  that  these  colors  were  only  rarely  sensational  in 
value,  and  were  not  uniform  in  tone.  Occasionally  there  were 
instances  of  true  synaesthesia;  but  there  was  no  evidence  of 


538  DOWNEY 

a  systematic  case.  On  the  other  hand,  colors  do,  apparently, 
call  up  true  tactual  sensations.  5.  named  the  ** tactual  feel" 
of  every  color  in  the  Bradley  chart  of  spectrum  scales, — a  test 
which  left  his  hand  itching  and  in  a  disagreeable  condition. 
Nevertheless,  it  is  very  difficult  to  determine  in  how  far  these 
tactual  experiences  were  anything  more  than  the  usual  secon- 
dary accompaniment  to  visual  perception.  With  his  eyes 
closed,  5.  was  frequently  unable  to  confirm,  by  stroking  the 
material,  the  tactual  impression  which  he  received  from  the 
visual  stimulation.  On  the  whole,  however,  it  was  evident  that 
S.  obtained  unusually  acute  suggestions  of  tactual  texture  from 
visual  texture.  It  is  obvious  that  a  satisfactory  explanation 
of  synsesthesia  must  await  a  more  complete  understanding  of 
the  secondary  element  in  perception.  In  the  meanwhile, 
border-line  cases  deserve  more  careful  examination  than  they 
have  received. 

It  is  not  without  interest  that  5.'s  preferred  form  of  atten- 
tion is  auditory.  He  is  very  musical,  and  has  an  excellent 
command  of  auditory  imagery.  Colored  audition  seems  to 
him  to  be  forced  and  extraordinary.  Yet,  during  a  recent 
test,  on  the  imagery  aroused  by  poetic  fragments,  he  has  twice 
reported  changing  an  auditory  suggestion  into  a  play  of 
imaginal  colors. 

5.    Is  THERE  A  Correspondence  Between  the  Feeung 

Tone  of  each  Taste  and  the  Feeung  Tone  of  its 

Induced  Color? 

It  has  been  suggested  that  synaesthetic  experiences  involve 
associations  through  emotional  similarity.  The  suggestion 
has,  perhaps,  been  couched  in  too  general  terms  to  deserve 
detailed  consideration.  Our  conclusion,  after  a  careful  obser- 
vation of  5.  for  a  year,  is  that  his  experiences  of  taste-color 
are,  on  the  whole,  indifferent  to  him,  and  that  there  has  been 
no  aesthetic  organization  of  tastes  on  a  color  basis,  as  has  been 
suggested  to  be  a  possibility  in  such  cases.  Violets  and  blues, 
which  were  found  by  the  method  of  paired  comparison  to  be 
►S.'s  preferred  colors,  play  no  part  in  these  experiences.  The 
judgment  'agreeable'  or  'disagreeable'  is,  apparently,  given 
on  the  basis  of  the  whole  gustatory  experience  of  which  color 
constitutes  an  essential  part.  In  at  least  one  case,  however, 
the  taste  of  lime  candy,  S.  spoke  of  the  color,  golden,  as  being 
very  "pretty,"  while  the  taste  was  not  "particularly  agreea- 
ble." There  was  frequent  disagreement  between  the  affec- 
tive tone  of  the  color  and  of  its  tactual  accompaniment.  Thus, 
green  has  an  agreeable  "feel,"  but  is  not  an  agreeable  color. 
Violet-blues  are  agreeable  in  color,  but  not  particularly  so  in 


A   CASE   OF   COI.ORED   GUSTATION  539 

"feel."  Blue-greens  give  a  "perfectly  awful  feeling,  like 
running  the  hand  over  sand-paper;  disagreeable  to  both 
sight  and  touch."  The  double  arousal  of  sense-qualities,  in 
the  manner  under  discussion,  is  not  without  interest  in  the 
investigation  of  feeling- tone.  It  would  seem  to  afford  an 
especially  good  opportunity  for  the  investigation  of  mixed 
feelings.  Our  observations  on  this  latter  point  were  too 
meagre  to  lead  to  any  definite  conclusion,  except  the  unlike- 
lihood of  the  synaesthetic  experiences,  in  the  present  case, 
being  explicable  upon  an  affective  basis. 

In  conclusion,  the  following  facts,  as  deduced  from  the 
present  study,  are  important  in  a  theoretical  consideration 
of  synsesthesia : 

1.  The  synaesthetic  factor  is  sensational  in  value,  as  has 
been  demonstrated  in  many  other  cases. 

2.  The  color  hallucination  may  be  induced  by  the  minimal 
sensory  intensity  of  the  primary  component  of  the  gusta- 
tory fusion.  Other  reported  cases  have  also  shown  sensory 
defects  of  the  primary  sense-organ.  Thus  Pierce  reports  de- 
fective hearing  in  connection  with  gustatory  audition.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  literature  of  the  subject  frequently  states 
that,  in  particular  instances,  no  sensory  defects  were  found. 
The  reliance,  in  the  majority  of  the  cases  reported,  upon  a 
descriptive  rather  than  upon  an  analytical  method  may  induce 
hesitation  in  accepting  the  evidence  upon  this  point. 

3.  In  the  case  of  colored  tastes  or  odors,  color  may  enter 
the  perceptual  fusion  from  experience  of  the  source  of  taste  as 
colored.  The  color  of  the  object  is  an  important  component 
of  the  usual  gustatory  or  olfactory  perception.  It  is  easily 
comprehensible  that  the  odor  of  violets  should  be  blue  in  tone, 
in  a  given  instance;  and  that,  too,  without  rejecting  the  syn- 
aesthetic element  as  a  sensational  part  of  the  perceptual  fusion, 
and  interpreting  it,  instead,  as  an  artificial  association.  Re- 
duce the  intensity  of  a  primary  element  in  a  perceptual  fusion, 
and  its  place  may  be  taken  by  a  normally  secondary  factor. 
Thus,  we  can  understand  why  for  S.  red  pepper  should  taste 
dull  red,  and  why  possibly  sweet  tastes  are  black,  if,  as  S. 
is  inclined  to  believe,  burnt  sugar  figured  in  a  vivid  experience 
of  childhood.  It  is,  however,  difficult  to  understand  how, 
in  colored  audition,  tonal  vision,  or  gustatory  audition,  the 
synaesthetic  factor  is  involved  in  perceptual  experience.  In 
my  opinion,  we  shall  not  understand  synaesthesia  until  we 
have  made  a  more  thoroughgoing  analysis  of  perception. 


A    NOTE    OF    THE    CONSCIOUSNESS    OF    SELF 


By  E-  B.  TiTCHENER 


It  happens  that  a  number  of  graduates,  in  the  department 
of  psychology  at  Cornell  University,  have  received,  during  the 
past  few  years,  an  unusually  thorough  training  in  '  systematic 
experimental  introspection.'  Many  thousands  of  observations 
have  been  taken,  under  controlled  conditions,  of  such  con- 
sciousnesses as  understanding,  recognition,  relation,  expecta- 
tion, belief;  the  classical  experiments  on  the  thought-processes 
have  been  repeated  and,  in  some  cases,  varied ;  different  kinds 
of  imagery  have  been  studied  and  their  temporal  courses 
traced.  Here,  then,  is  a  group  of  observers  who  seem  to  be 
especially  well  qualified  to  report  upon  the  nature  and  appear- 
ance of  the  self-consciousness, — about  which,  as  it  is  hardly 
necessary  to  say,  psychologists  are  very  far  from  agreement. 

The  reports  were  obtained  as  answers  to  questions  which 
were  laid,  one  at  a  time,  before  the  individual  observers.  The 
method  is  crude,  and  I  should  be  the  last  to  claim  anything 
like  finality  for  the  results.  For  one  thing,  the  reports  are 
necessarily  partial  and  imperfect;  a  complete  account  of  the 
psychological  self,  and  of  the  conditions  of  its  appearance, 
would  need  to  be  pieced  out  from  observations  taken  over  an 
extended  period  of  time.  For  another  thing,  the  bare  state- 
ment, even  of  a  highly  trained  observer,  that  this  or  that  mode 
of  experience  is  habitual  with  him,  or  that  this  or  the  other 
form  of  experience  is  unknown,  cannot  be  accepted  as  of  equal 
value  with  the — often  unconscious — self-revelation  of  an  ex- 
perimental record.^  As  regards  the  first  point,  however,  I 
am  satisfied  if  the  reports  are  correct  so  far  as  they  go ;  and, 
as  regards  the  second,  I  rely  upon  the  nature  of  the  questions 
themselves  and  upon  the  way  in  which  the  enquiry  was  con- 
ducted. The  questions  were  of  a  large  and  simple  kind,  and, 
after  the  first  sets  of  answers  had  been  received,  were  again 
laid  before  the  observers,  who  were  instructed  to  note  at  their 
leisure  the  facts  appearing  in  daily  life  and  in  the  course  of 
laboratory  work,  and  to  hand  in  another  set,  of  corrected 
answers,  if  they  found  correction  to  be  necessary. 

^Cf.  G.  E.  MuUer,  Zur  Analyse  der  Gedachtnistatigkeit  imd  des  Vorstel- 
lungsverlaufes,  191 1,  143  ff. 


THE   CONSCIOUSNESS   OF   SElvF  54 1 

The  first  question  raises  the  point  of  the  continuity  or  inter- 
mittence  of  the  self -experience.  In  my  own  case,  "the  con- 
scious self,  while  it  can  always  be  constructed  by  a  voluntary 
effort,  is  of  comparatively  rare  occurrence."^  Wundt  writes 
to  the  same  effect:  "Psychologically  regarded,  it  is  in  normal 
circumstances  the  ordinary  state  of  affairs  that  objects  are 
given  simply  as  objects,  without  there  being  any  thought 
whatever  of  the  ideating  and  sensing  subject.  .  .  [The 
expression]  '  f orgetf ulness  of  self  ...  is  misleading,  in  so 
far  as  it  is  prompted  by  the  tendency  to  consider  reference 
to  the  subject  as  the  normal  .  .  .  state  of  affairs. "^  And 
Mach,  in  his  polemic  against  the  ego,  reminds  us  that  not  only 
in  sleep,  but  also  "when  we  are  absorbed  in  contemplation  or 
thought,  in  the  very  happiest  moments  of  our  lives,  the  self 
may  be  partly  or  wholly  lost(  fehlen  kann).''^  On  the  other 
side,  we  read  in  Calkins  that  "I  am  always,  inattentively  or 
attentively,  conscious  of  the  private,  personal  object,  myself, 
whatever  the  other  objects  of  my  consciousness;"^ and  James, 
speaking  of  the  '  material '  self,  remarks  that  "we  feel  the  whole 
cubic  mass  of  our  body  all  the  while,  it  gives  us  an  unceasing 
sense  of  personal  existence."^ 

The  second  and  third  questions  deal  with  the  mode  of 
appearance  of  the  self  in  consciousness,  and  of  the  conditions 
under  which  it  appears.  It  seems,  if  we  consult  the  current 
works  upon  psychology,  that  there  are  three  principal  ways 
in  which  the  self  may  become  conscious,  (i)  There  may  be  a 
certain  class  of  mental  processes  which,  apart  from  any  deter- 
mination of  present  consciousness,  carries  the  self-meaning. 
For  Lipps,  e.  g.,  all  conscious  experiences  fall  into  the  one  or 
the  other  of  two  great  groups,  conscious  contents  and  self- 
experiences ;  and  the  self-experiences  are  '  feelings  in  the  wider 
sense  of  the  term.'^  These  'subjective'  experiences  always 
appear  together  with  the  'objective';  "I  always  feel  myself 
somehow."^     (2)    The   self -experience   may   proceed   from   a 

^Text-book  of  Psychology,  19 10,  544  f. 

^W.  Wundt,  Ueber  naiven  und  kritischen  Realismus,  Phil.  Stud.,  xii., 
1896,  342  f. ;  Kleine  Schriften,  i.,  1910,  291  f. 

^E.  Mach,  Beitrage  zur  Analyse  der  Empfindungen,  1886,  18  n;  Die 
Analyse  der  Empfindungen  und  das  Verhaltniss  des  Physischen  zum 
Psychischen,  1900,  17. 

^M.  W.  Calkins,  First  Book  in  Psychology,  19 10,  4. 

^W.  James,  Principles  of  Psychology,  i.,  1890,  333.  I  may  here  remark 
that  the  quotations  made  in  this  Note  are  illustrative  only;  I  do  not  attempt 
either  to  furnish  a  complete  list  of  authorities  or  adequately  to  characterise 
the  positions  of  the  authors  cited. 

*T.  Lipps,  Leitfaden  der  Psychologic,  1906,  3  f.,  281;  cf.  G.  Kafka,  Ver- 
such  einer  kritischen  Darstellung  der  neueren  Anschauungen  uber  das 
Ichproblem,  in  Arch.  f.  d.  ges.  Psych.,  xix.,  1910,  116  fif. 

'T.  Lipps,  Das  Selbstbewusstsein ;  Empfindimg  und    Gefuhl,  1901,  13. 

Journal— 5 


542  TITCHENSR 

determination;  and  may  then  be  either  expHcit  or  implicit.^ 
When  it  is  explicit,  the  self-meaning  is  carried  by  a  character- 
istic group  of  conscious  processes  which  is,  so  to  say,  set  apart 
for  this  special  office;  for  Wundt,  e.  g.,  the  self -experience 
consists  "in  essentials  of  a  total  feeling,  whose  predominating 
elements  are  the  apperceptive  feelings,  and  whose  secondary 
and  more  variable  constituents  are  other  feelings  and  sensa- 
tions connected  with"  the  vital  functions,  the  movements  of 
the  limbs,  the  condition  of  the  internal  organs. ^  Where  it  is 
implicit,  we  have — under  the  determination — a  certain 
arrangement  and  temporal  course  of  processes  which,  other- 
wise determined,  would  lack  the  special  self -reference.  Here 
we  may,  perhaps  (for  I  am  not  sure  of  the  instance),  mention 
James'  reduction  of  the  spiritual,  central  or  active  self  to 
kinaesthetic  sensations  in  head,  throat,  and  respiratory  mech- 
anism.^ (3)  Finally,  conscious  selfhood  may  inhere  in  the 
whole  of  conscious  experience,  e.  g.  as  the  character  of  'warmth 
and  intimacy'  which,  according  to  James,  distinguishes  all  of 
*my'  ideas  from  the  ideas  that  I  ascribe  to  any  'you'.'* 

So  much  may  suffice  by  way  of  introduction ;  I  turn  now  to 
the  reports.  The  letters  A,  B,  etc.,  denote  the  observers; 
their  present  status,  as  student  or  teacher  of  psychology,  is 
indicated  by  s  or  t;  and  sex  is  shown  by  the  letter  m  or  f. 
Further  reports,  from  present  members  of  my  graduate  semin- 
ary,— students  trained  in  introspection,  but  not  trained  so 
widely  or  for  so  long  a  period  as  the  members  of  the  other 
group, — are  distinguished  by  the  use  of  italicised  capitals, 
^,^,etc.     Corrected  reports  are  placed  within  square  brackets. 

Question  I.  "  '  I  am  always,  inattentively  or  attentively, 
conscious  of  myself  ^  whatever  the  other  objects  of  my  conscious- 
ness.' Is  this  statement  true,  as  a  matter  of  experience,  (a)  in 
everyday  life,  {h)  in  the  introspective  exercises  of  the  labora- 
tory?" 

Asf.  (a)  No.  {b)  No.  The  statement  is  true  as  a  rule  at  the  beginning 
of  an  experiment  (when  I  am  0),  before  I  have  become  used  to  the  demands 
of  E.  It  holds  only  occasionally  after  I  have  become  practised  and  have 
forgotten  that  I  am  under  £*s  observation. 

Btm.  (a)  No.  In  seeing  a  play,  I  am  often  another  person,  portrayed 
by  the  actor,  and  do  not  realise  that  I  am  a  spectator  until  my  neighbor 
speaks.  So  also  when  I  am  absorbed  in  a  book,  {b)  No.  I  do  not  realise  often 
that  there  is  any  I  which  perceives  the  stimuli.     I  should  say  that  the 

^Cf.  the  analysis  of  Belief  offered  by  T.  Okabe,  this  Journal,  xxi.,  594. 

2W.  Wundt,  Grundziige  der  physiologischen  Psychologic,  iii.,  191 1,  353  ff. 

^W.  James,  Principles  of  Psychology,  i.,  1890,  301;  Does  'Consciousness' 
exist?     in  Journ.  Phil.  Psych.  Sci.  Meth.,  i.,  1904,  491. 

^Principles  of  Psychology,  i.,  1890,  330  fif.  The  precise  nature  of  the 
'warmth'  (cf.  p.  333)  does  not  here  concern  us;  nor  does  the  question  of  its 
recognition  or  realisation  (apparently  answered  by  James  in  the  doctrine 
that  the  experience  of  'mine'  is  genetically  prior  to  the  experience  of  'me') . 


TH^  CONSCIOUSNESS  OF  SELF  543 

consciousness  of  self  is  no  more  frequent  than  the  'feeling  of  familiarity.' 
I  take  myself  for  granted,  very  much  as  I  take  familiarity  for  granted 
in  'immediate  apprehension.' 

[(a)  No.  Only  occasionally  do  I  realise  that  there  is  any  I  which  is 
standing  over  against  objects  or  situations.  I  do  become  self-conscious, 
most  strongly,  in  just  those  situations  which  seem  to  demand  that  I  appear 
not  to  be  self-conscious ;  when  I  know  myself  to  be  watched,  when  there  is  de- 
manded the  making  or  keeping  of  some  motor  adjustment  (bodily  move- 
ment, verbal  reply).  In  such  cases  there  are  usually  the  situation  (external 
perception  of  place  and  people  and  so  on)  and  beside  it  the  I  (kinaesthetic 
sensations  in  upper  chest  and  arms,  and  organic  sensations)  and  my  emo- 
tive reaction  (pleasantness  or  unpleasantness,  with  abdominal  organic 
sensations).  This  analysis  (which  I  believe  to  be  typical)  is  mainly  from 
an  actual  experience  yesterday,  (b)  No;  even  less  than  in  everyday  life. 
The  very  instruction  from  E  leaves  no  chance  for  one  to  get  self-conscious. 
The  things  to  be  watched  are  sensations  and  images  and  so  on,  and  one 
watches  them  just  exactly  as  one  watches  a  thermometer  rise.  The  more 
careful  and  strenuous  the  observation,  the  less  chance  does  there  seem  to  be 
for  the  realisation  of  anything  else  than  the  thing  observed.] 

Ctm.  (a)  Not  in  my  case;  I  am  only  very  rarely  'conscious  of  myself.* 
By  'myself  I  mean  not  only  the  sum  total  of  organic  and  kinaesthetic  sen- 
sations representing  my  body  and  its  movements,  but  also  'unified  experi- 
ence' vaguely  and  verbally  referred  to  as  'my '  experience.  Very  often  my 
experiences,  simultaneous  or  immediately  successive,  are  not  'unified,* 
not  referred  to  a  single  and  identical  agent,  but  they  run  side  by  side. 
(b)  Not  in  my  case,  if  the  introspection  is  what  I  call  successful,  that  is, 
if  I  did  not  catch  myself  introspecting.  It  is  true  that  in  introspective 
exercises  I  notice  much  more  easily  kinaesthetic  and  organic  processes, 
also  more  verbal  imagery,  than  in  everyday  life,  because  of  their  greater 
clearness  and  reproducibility.  I  become  'self-conscious,'  however,  only 
if  their  intensity  rises  above  the  normal  degree,  and  that  is  very  rarely. 
The  matter  of  'unified  experience'  has  never  come  up  in  my  introspections, 
as  far  as  I  can  remember. 

Dsf .  (a)  No.  I  am  usually  inattentively,  and  at  times  very  attentively, 
conscious  of  myself,  but  there  occur  fairly  numerous  instances  when  I 
am  not  self-conscious  at  all.  These  periods  when  I  am  not  conscious  of 
self  are  of  comparatively  short  duration  (usually  when  I  am  deeply  inter- 
ested in  a  book,  in  listening  to  music,  studying  a  picture,  etc.),  and  often — 
but  not  always — returning  self-consciousness  leaves  me  with  a  feeling  of 
surprise,  (b)  The  mere  fact  of  being  an  observer  in  a  laboratory  exercise 
seems  to  imply  self -consciousness.  I  think  that  I  am  always  somewhat 
conscious  of  myself  when  busied  in  this  way.  Yet  even  in  the  laboratory 
there  are  times  when  self-consciousness  is  decidedly  marginal.  These 
times  are  usually  during  the  experiment  itself,  when  perhaps  attention  is 
fixed  upon  some  external  stimulus;  but  the  vague  feeling  that  I  am  soon 
to  answer  the  question  'what  was  my  experience'  is  always  faintly  present. 
[This  observer  had  no  opportunity  to  correct  her  first  answers.] 

Etf .  (a)  I  should  say  almost  always.  Occasionally  I  become  so  absorbed 
in  a  book  or  task  or  train  of  thought  that,  when  interruption  comes,  I 
feel  almost  as  I  do  when  I  have  waked  from  sleep,  and  the  immediate  past 
seems  almost  blank,  and  cut  off  from  the  rest  of  my  experience.  I  believe 
that  consciousness  of  self  is  at  a  minimum  if  not  wholly  lacking  at  such 
times,  (b)  Yes,  I  believe  so.  I  tend  to  visualise  anything  that  I  am 
thinking  about,  and  so  in  writing  introspections:  the  mental  facts  or 
processes  that  I  try  to  describe  are  placed  in  a  large  dark  vagueness  which 
represents  my  own  mind.  This  is  situated  at  about  the  level  of  my  head, 
but  is  much  larger.  Again,  the  effort  of  introspection  is  usually  accom- 
panied by  wrinkling  of  forehead,  drawing  of  eyes,  and  vague  feeling  of 
tension  in  head.     These  things  constitute  in  part  what  I  mean  by  conscious- 


544  TITCHENER 

ness  of  self  in  the  present  case.  I  never  forget  that  I  am  looking  in,  and 
this  realisation  is  so  strong  sometimes  as  to  amount  to  sensations  from  eyes 
as  if  turning  inward.  [This  observer  had  no  opportunity  to  correct  her 
first  answers.] 

Ftm.  (a)  No.  (b)  I  have  never  worked  under  the  Aufgabe  of  this 
question ;  but  my  impression  is  that  'consciousness  of  myself  is  occasional, 
except  in  the  early  stages  of  practice. 

Am.  (a)  Yes.  I  am  seldom  attentively  conscious  of  myself.  There 
seems,  however,  to  be  always  in  my  consciousness  the  obsciu-e  groundwork 
of  pressures,  strains  and  organic  sensations  which,  become  clearer  and  sup- 
plemented by  visual  images,  make  up  my  attentive  consciousness  of  self. 
(b)  Yes.  The  laboratory  experience  does  not  seem  to  differ  from  the  every- 
day experience,  [(a)  No.  Observation  since  my  first  report  leads  me  to 
reverse  my  opinion.  I  am  now  confident  that  I  am  not  always  conscious 
of  myself.  Self -consciousness  carried  kinaesthetically  with  possible  visual 
images  occurs  comparatively  seldom.  Only  when  there  is  some  special 
experience  calling  attention  to  myself,  either  directly  as  my  physical  self 
or  indirectly  as  in  a  difl&cult  or  baffling  action  or  problem  (which  nearly 
always  calls  up  the  kinaesthetic  self),  do  I  have  this  self -consciousness . 
The  experience  may  be  clear,  as  when  accompanied  by  visual  images  of  self 
or  in  the  strong  kinaesthetic  self  of  an  unusually  difficult  situation;  or  it 
may  be  unclear,  as  in  vague  kinaesthetic  feelings  of  effort.  Consciousness 
is,  however,  made  up  most  of  the  time  by  mixed  perceptional  and  ideational 
contents  without  reference  to  the  experiencing  self,  (b)  I  have  not  observed 
any  difference  in  the  consciousness  of  self  under  laboratory  conditions 
from  that  of  everyday  experience.  Even  introspection  in  the  laboratory 
does  not  involve  a  constant  reference  to  the  introspecting  self,  although 
this  reference  is  very  frequently  present,  and  often  very  clear.] 

J5m.     (a),  (b)  No. 

a.       (a),  (6)  No. 

Dm.  (a),  (b)  There  are  certain  sensations  which  characterise  my  ali- 
mentary canal;  others  my  arms,  face,  legs,  etc.;  varying,  to  be  sure,  with 
my  activity,  but  nevertheless  for  any  given  activity  possessing  a  fair  con- 
stancy. There  are  thus  a  large  number  of  groups  of  sensations  which  are 
frequently  present  in  the  various  parts  of  my  body;  and  when  some  such 
groups  are  present  (which  is  practically  always)  there  is  consciousness  of 
self;  that  is,  these  sensations,  by  virtue  of  their  habitual  attendance  upon 
my  activities,  possess  logical  reference  to  self. 

In  addition,  my  ways  of  thinking  and  acting — in  so  far  as  they  are  con- 
scious— bear  my  stamp ;  the  feeling  of  them  is  characteristic.  Hence  when 
under  an  Aufgabe  or  in  a  particular  situation  I  speak  of  them,  I  naturally 
use  the  term  /  think  or  /  act,  just  as  I  say  /  feel,  when  speaking  of  the 
somatic  sensations. 

But  when  I  do  thus  make  specific  use  of  the  idea  of  self ;  when  I  do  thus 
have  some  psychic  term  (e.  g.,  the  kinaesthetic  and  verbal  image  /)  which 
specifically  designates  the  I-ness;  then  I  have  no  longer  mere  sensations, 
images,  etc.,  with  their  vague  reference  to  self,  but  now  an  actual  perception. 
This  perception  may  have  various  degrees  of  clearness.  It  waxes  and  wanes 
and  revives  again.  It  comes  most  close  to  being  lost  altogether  when  I 
become  completely  engrossed — 'lose  myself — in  a  task.  Then,  if  only 
for  a  very  brief  time,  I  become  objective.  It  is  especially  frequent  in 
occurrence  with  images  of  future  activity. 

[Yes.  By  'myself  I  mean:  This  centre  of  material,  psychical,  social, 
etc.  relations.  By  being  conscious  of  myself  I  mean  that  states  or  processes 
of  consciousness  are  present  such  that  they  carry  a  reference  to  sdf .  Em- 
pirically one  finds  ^at  the  self  which  one  means  is  seldom  totally  the  same 
in  any  two  cases;  it  is  myself  in  this  or  that  particular  situation  that  is 
referred  to.  Empirically  one  finds  also  that  the  psychical  phenomena  which 
carry  these  references  are  varied,  and  seldom  totally  the  same.     One  does 


THE   CONSCIOUSNESS  OF  SELF  545 

not  find,  that  is,  that  any  particular  set  of  constant  psychical  factors 
(such  as  sensations  of  respiration)  is  the  exclusive  or  predominant  vehicle. 

On  the  other  hand,  generally  speaking,  continually  recurring  psychical 
phenomena  (at  least,  those  of  somatic  character)  do  seem  to  me  at  this 
writing  to  be  the  vehicle  of  self-reference.  There  seems  to  be  something 
of  self-reference  in  the  very  feeling  of  moving  my  eyes,  uttering  a  word, 
or  moving  or  resting  a  limb;  and  this  quite  apart  from  any  specially  set 
Aufgabe.  However,  I  am  quite  doubtful  as  to  whether  or  not  familiar 
sights,  sounds  and  touches  do  ipso  facto  refer  to  self. 

I  should  be  inclined  to  distinguish  between  sensations  of  self  and  per- 
ceptions of  self.  Of  the  former  sort  were  the  tonic  sensations  in  the  right 
leg  which  were  present  five  minutes  ago.  These  bore  a  reference  (even 
though  vague  and  almost  formless)  to  myself;  they  referred  not  at  all  to 
the  red  house  across  the  valley  (which  I  was  not  thinking  of). 

There  are  degrees  of  clearness  or  intensity  of  perceptions  of  self,  and 
there  are  different  kinds  of  perception,  as  above  indicated.] 

Em.,  (a)  No.  When  I  am  alone,  when  I  am  engrossed  in  work,  when  a 
problem  has  presented  itself,  I  am  not  conscious  of  myself  at  all.  It  is  only 
when  the  environment  is  new  and  unfamiliar,  or  when  I  am  in  personal 
conversation  with  someone  else,  or  when  other  individuals  suggest  the 
visualisation  of  myself  among  them,  that  I  am  conscious  of  myself.  Strong 
kinaesthesis,  and  especially  organic  movements,  emphasise  self- conscious- 
ness, (b)  I  am  strongly  conscious  of  myself,  especially  at  the  beginning  of 
an  experiment,  because  I  feel  that  the  situation  is  new,  E  converses  with  me, 
and  I  visualise  myself,  I  feel  that  the  reports  are  of  processes  peculiarly 
my  own.  Kinaesthesis  comes  out  strongly,  and  this  emphasises  conscious- 
ness of  self. 

[(a)  No.  My  consciousness  of  self  depends  decidedly  upon  'the  other 
objects  of  my  consciousness.'  I  should  lay  less  stress  on  the  situation 
(mentioned  in  my  first  answer)  in  which  I  am  thrown  into  a  new  environ- 
ment as  the  occasion  of  self-consciousness,  since  I  find  that  even  here  I  am 
very  little  self-conscious.  As  a  rule,  however,  when  kinaesthesis  and  par- 
ticularly organic  sensations  are  strong,  or  when  I  see  or  hear  a  reference 
to  myself,  then  I  am  conscious  of  self.  (6)  No,  not  often.  Here  again 
when  reference  is  made  to  my  experiences,  my  introspections,  my  sensations, 
etc.,  I  may  sometimes  get  a  momentary  consciousness  of  self,  mainly  in 
visual  terms  (as  one  sitting  before  an  experimenter).  Seldom,  and  only 
in  the  most  trying  and  unusual  circumstances,  am  I  continuously  aware  of 
myself  for  any  length  of  time,  here  as  elsewhere.] 

Fi.  (a)  No.  I  often  lose  all  consciousness  of  myself;  not,  however,  for 
a  long  period.  An  uncomfortable  position,  some  distraction  of  attention 
occurs,  and  I  am  suddenly  aware  of  myself  in  all  sorts  of  organic  sensations. 
On  some  days  this  awareness  is  more  apparent,  more  frequent  than  on 
other  days.  With  certain  persons  consciousness  of  myself  is  invariably 
present.  [Further  observation  shows  that  the  frequency  of  self -awareness 
is  dependent  upon  my  physical  condition.]  (b)  Yes.  The  very  fact  that 
introspections  are  to  be  given  makes  me  aware  of  myself.  I  am  then 
conscious  of  organic  sensations  of  which,  ordinarily,  I  am  totally  unaware. 
[The  self  is  usually  in  the  background;  yet  I  am  conscious  of  organic 
sensations,  of  changes  of  mental  attitude,  of  effort,  which  generally  persist 
during  the  entire  introspective  period.] 

Gi.     (a),  (b)  No. 

Question  II.  The  second  question  called  for  a  description  of 
the  self-consciousness,  which  should  be  made  "as  definite  as 
possible.  Is  the  consciousness  of  self  explicit  {e.  g.,  visual 
image,  organic  sensations)  or  implicit  (intrinsic  to  the  nature 
of  consciousness,  inherent  in  the  course  of  consciousness)? 


546  TITCHENIBR 

Can  you  bring  out  the  character  of  the  self-consciousness  by 
comparing  or  contrasting  it  with  other  phases  of  a  total  con- 
sciousness?" 

The  replies  should  fall  into  three  natural  groups:  (i)  the 
reports  of  those  who  answer  I.  (a)  in  the  affirmative,  and 
thus  assert  that  they  are  always  self-conscious;  (2)  the  reports 
of  those  who  answer  I.  (a)  in  the  negative,  but  I.  (b)  in  the 
affirmative,  and  thus  assert  that  the  introspective  attitude 
always  implies  self-consciousness;  and  (3)  the  reports  of  those 
who  answer  both  members  of  Question  I.  in  the  negative. 
In  fact,  the  replies  are  not  all  as  clean-cut  as  this  grouping 
demands,  and  we  must  therefore  be  content,  under  the  first 
two  headings,  with  a  classification  a  potiori. 

(i)  Etf.  (  "I  should  say  almost  always.")  I  have  already  described  my 
self -consciousness  during  introspection.  It  is  hard  to  describe  that  which 
is  present  in  everyday  life  because,  when  I  attempt  to  do  so,  it  is  this 
introspective  self-consciousness  which  is  present.  I  believe  that  the  more 
natural  kind  is  somewhat  different  on  different  occasions.  It  often  involves 
organic  sensations,  and  feelings  of  bodily  position  and  of  comfort  and  dis- 
comfort. In  the  presence  of  other  people  it  is  often  connected  in  some  way 
with  their  approval  or  disapproval ;  and  almost  always,  whether  I  am  alone 
or  not,  there  is  a  strong  sense  of  my  own  approval  or  disapproval.  In 
other  words,  it  is  affectively  toned. 

Dm.  (Occasionally  'loses  himself.*)  I  have  virtually  already  answered 
this  question.  I  find  my  self -consciousness  in  groups  of  psychic  entities 
which  habitually  reocciu-.  When  my  sensations,  feelings,  images  and 
activities  are  changed,  and  somewhat  new  ones  take  their  place,  I  have 
less  feeling  of  self.  If  they  were  in  continual  change  and  did  not  character- 
istically reoccur,  I  deduce  that  I  should  be  without  the  self-consciousness 
I  now  have. 

I  have  not  said  that  the  consciousness  of  self  is  a  'phase  of  a  total  con- 
sciousness'. Rather  the  self  is  a  thing  meant,  a  complex  logical  entity, 
which  in  the  past  has  lived  in  X,  is  now  studying  psychology,  etc.  But 
that  logical  entity  is  represented  in  the  total  consciousness  of  almost  any 
moment  in  that  way  which  I  have  already  mentioned,  viz.,  the  habitual 
attendance  of  certain  psychic  groups.  Other  designatory  terms,  so  to  call 
them,  are  visual  images  of  myself  in  a  particular  situation,  also  auditory 
images  of  my  voice  and  of  voices  speaking  to  me,  and  again  various  combina- 
tions of  these  with  kinaesthetic  images  of  activity. 

(2)  Dsf.  (Self -consciousness  sometimes  decidedly  marginal.)  The 
consciousness  of  self  is  not  comparable  with  the  consciousness  of  external 
objects.  It  is  not  explicit  in  the  sense  of  coming  as  visual  imagery  or 
organic  sensations.  It  is  rather  an  inherent  feeling  or  knowledge  or  atti- 
tude that  tells  me  that  I  am  that  which  has  images  and  sensations.  Not  a 
consciousness  of  my  physical  self  as  the  object  of  experience,  but  an  under- 
lying imique  knowledge  of  myself  as  the  experiencing  subject.  I  cannot 
seem  to  be  able  to  get  at  it  or  to  analyse  it  further  in  introspection.  Often 
it  is  intense,  but  often  it  is  merely  the  background  of  experience. 

Fi.  (No  qualification.)  Sometimes  the  self  appears  as  a  visual  image, 
as  if  it  were  a  thing  apart  and  separate.  The  self  to  which  I  refer  in  my 
answer  is,  however,  an  intangible  something,  forming  a  sort  of  background, 
in  which  (as  I  have  said)  I  can  distinguish  organic  sensations. 

(3)  Asf.  Occasioiially  in  the  form  of  an  indefinite  visual  image  (this 
is  often  implied  by  a  vague  kinaesthetic  complex);  sometimes  I  have  also 


THE   CONSCIOUSNESS   OJf   SELI^  547 

vague  visual  images  (or  kinaesthetic  substitutes  for  them)  of  other  people. 
Usually  via  organic  sensations,  nausea,  tightening  of  diaphragm,  changes 
in  respiratory  sensations;  frequently  accompanied  by  a  slight  watering  of 
the  eyes  (this  almost  invariably  occurs  when  I  am  'touched'). 

Btm.  Self-consciousness  appears  usually  in  the  form  of  kinaesthetic 
sensations  from  the  lower  trunk  or  from  parts  of  the  body  in  strained  posi- 
tions.    Sometimes  in  visual  images. 

Ctm.  My  self -consciousness  is  usually  intensely  organic,  a  'sinking  of 
the  stomach,*  a  blushing  and  flushing  of  the  face,  hot  and  uncomfortable; 
I  am  conscious  of  the  position  of  my  body,  and  especially  of  the  movements 
of  my  limbs,  through  intensely  unpleasant  kinaesthetic  and  cutaneous 
sensations,  of  great  variety  and  disconnectedness.  If  I  am  standing,  the 
weight  of  the  body  is  awkwardly  shifted  from  one  foot  to  the  other,  and 
one  or  both  hands  are  put  under  the  coat  at  the  hips,  thumbs  pointing 
backwards.  All  these  processes  have  a  fair  degree  of  clearness,  with  one 
or  another  now  and  then  shooting  to  the  extreme  focus  of  attention,  ousting 
momentarily  some  intellectual  process  which  happens  to  be  running  its 
course  in  the  meanwhile. 

Ftm.  Chiefly  organic  sensation.  At  times,  a  vague  visual  image  (as 
if  I  stood  before  myself  and  saw  my  own  face) .  At  times,  the  Bewusstseins- 
lage  of  responsibility.  [I  find  that  my  self-consciousness  is  usually  emo- 
tional.] 

Ara.  My  self -consciousness  is  definitely  explicit.  In  its  clearest  form 
it  consists  of  organic  sensations  (of  a  kind  of  'nervous  strain'  quality)  in  the 
body,  especially  in  the  chest;  and,  when  connected  with  my  'willing  self' 
or  my  'thinking  self,'  of  deep  strain  sensations  in  the  head.  There  are 
sometimes  also  vague  strain  sensations  in  the  limbs;  these  are  stronger 
when  self-consciousness  means  my  'willing  self.'  Besides  the  dear  sensa- 
tions in  self-consciousness,  there  are  always  poorly  defined  visual  images, 
such  as  translucent  rays  being  projected  from  the  region  of  my  chest  where 
the  organic  sensations  are  strongest,  and  meaning  'I  am  the  centre  of  this 
experience.' 

The  self-conscious  experience  seems  more  often  to  be  a  part  of  other 
experiences  than  a  thing  of  itself.  It  colors  the  meaning  of  the  others. 
In  itself  it  resembles  the  experience  of  effort,  but  differs  slightly  in  meaning 
and  in  its  persistence. 

Bm.  It  seems  to  me  that  all  sorts  of  sensations  and  feelings  may  refer 
to  that  which  experiences,  to  that  which  owns  and  appropriates  the  experi- 
ence. I  cannot  now  be  more  explicit.  [Further  observation  shows  me 
that  the  self-meaning  is  most  commonly  carried  by  organic  sensations,  or 
by  visual  memory-images  of  my  body  doing  something;  but  it  is  also  carried 
by  other  sensations  and  images.  The  verbal  ideas  I  and  my  may  or  may  not 
appear.  The  complex  is  affectively  toned;  there  is  a  feeling  of  warmth  or 
familiarity.  I  have  noticed  that  the  consciousness  of  self  is  clearer  during 
inhalation.     The  experience  with  me  is  rare.] 

a.  Chiefly  organic  sensations ;  a  visual  image  may  be  present  too . 
The  consciousness  is  explicit. 

Em..  Self-consciousness  is  partly  explicit,  manifest  in  a  visual  image  of 
myself,  organic  sensations  and  kinaesthesis,  and  in  part  implicit,  as  when 
I  recognise  my  introspections  as  material  peculiarly  my  own,  which  E 
could  not  directly  know.  When  I  am  conducting  a  piece  of  work,  I  am 
never  conscious  of  myself  as  master  of  my  hands  and  muscles,  brain,  etc. 
The  visual  image  of  the  work  as  it  is  completed  is  almost  continually  before 
me  as  an  end, — of  course,  with  many  interruptions;  I  mean  the  visual 
image  is  the  majority  factor.  It  is  only  when  the  work,  problem  or  experi- 
ment, has  been  completed  that  I  say  'I  have  done  that.'  If,  however, 
a  hitch  comes  (new  situation),  I  may  again  be  enormously  aware  of  myself, 
as  before  the  problem  was  begun.     The  consciousness  of  self  is  partly  a 


548  TITCHENER 

visual  image  of  myself  at  present,  plus  a  vague  memory  image  or  images 
(whether  visual  or  not  I  do  not  know)  of  big  experiences  in  the  past. 
Gi.     For  the  most  part,  verbal  imagery  and  organic  sensations. 

Question  III.  The  third  question,  addressed  only  to  those 
who  had  answered  I.  (a)  in  the  negative,  points  out  that  this 
answer  "implies  that  self-consciousness  is  intermittent. 
Under  what  circumstances,  then,  is  it  likely  to  appear?" 

Asf .  Whenever  I  know  that  other  people  are  observing  my  physical  or 
psychophysical  self,  i.  e.,  when  I  see  their  eyes  fixed  on  me,  or  when  I  think 
of  other  people's  opinion  of  me;  when  I  am  emotionally  stirred  up;  in 
comparing  my  physical  or  mental  characteristics  with  those  of  others,  or 
with  those  of  myself  at  some  other  time;  always  when  something  occurs 
which,  as  I  say,  'touches'  me,  rather  unexpectedly,  e.  g.,z.  word  of  commen- 
dation or  reproof  from  another  person;  when  another  person  refers  to  a 
characteristic  which  he  designates  as  mine ;  when  I  am  very  elated,  fatigued, 
sick;  when  I  am  wearing  new  or  ill-fitting  clothes;  when  sitting  for  a 
photograph.     In  general,  when  I  am  in  an  unusual  situation. 

Btm.  Particularly  when  a  new  situation  is  to  be  met,  when  there  is 
necessity  for  making  or  keeping  a  new  or  not  entirely  familiar  bodily 
adjustment;  or  when  the  adjustment  was  unsuitable.  Often  also  as  a 
bodily  reaction  to  a  situation  involving  other  persons. 

Ctm.  Most  strongly  immediately  before  appearing  in  public  or  before 
some  personage  of  importance;  when  I  hear  somebody  speaking  about  me, 
or  read  my  name  in  print  as  mentioned  by  somebody  else;  when  I  open  a 
telegram;  in  the  course  of  talking,  when  a  familiar  word  has  slipped  my 
memory,  or  when  I  get  tangled  up  in  an  argument.  [You  have  called  my 
attention  to  the  fact  that  my  answers  seem  to  make  self-consciousness 
mainly  an  unpleasant  experience.  It  is,  however,  true  (I  have  verified 
the  point  by  recent  observations)  that  my  states  of  self -consciousness  are 
almost  invariably  unpleasant.  There  is  sometimes  a  'glow'  of  self-con- 
sciousness, which  is  pleasurable,  after  praise,  recognition,  etc.,  but  this 
is  not  marked,  and  in  any  case  is  soon  replaced  by  indifference  or  (if  the 
self-consciousness  continues)  by  an  unpleasant,  often  a  strongly  unpleasant 
mood  of  self-criticism.  I  am  myself  a  little  surprised  at  the  constancy  of 
the  unpleasantness,  now  that  I  have  definitely  realised  it,  since  I  am  by 
no  means  of  a  pessimistic  temperament.] 

Dsf.  Self -consciousness  appears  usually  under  some  of  the  following 
circumstances:  in  cases  of  physical  pain  (organic  discomfort),  nervous 
condition,  tiredness,  when  one  has  made  a  blunder  and  feels  foolish  or  has 
done  something  one  regrets,  in  a  feeling  of  uselessness  or  inability  to  do 
what  is  expected  of  one  (by  self  or  others),  in  vanity  or  jealousy,  in  fear, 
whenever  as  a  rule  one  thinks  of  oneself  in  relation  to  other  persons  or 
during  purposeful  introspection.  There  are  other  circumstances  in  which 
self-consciousness  appears,  and  often  it  is  present  all  the  time. 

Ftm.  I  think  in  the  early  stages  of  laboratory  practice.  Also,  I  suspect , 
in  observations  that  involve  perception  of  body  {e.  g.,  compass  points  on 
skin)  and  in  those  that  involve  extreme  capacity  of  a  mental  function 
{e.  g.,  memorial  learning). 

Ara..  [I  am  apt  to  experience  consciousness  of  self  under  the  following 
situations,  (i)  In  many  situations  of  shame.  Often,  though  not  always, 
when  I  am  undressed  in  the  presence  of  strangers;  also  when  I  am  in  an 
embarrassing  position,  especially  when  I  have  done  something  physically 
awkward  or  have  discovered  something  wrong  with  my  clothing.  In  the 
last  case  one  of  the  most  prominent  factors  in  the  self -consciousness  is  a 
strong  tactual  perception  [or  image?]  directly  under  the  part  of  my  dress 
affected.  I  am  also  generally  conscious  of  self  when  I  am  ashamed  or 
belittled  morally  or  intellectually,  as  when  I  am  surprised  in  doing  some- 


THE   CONSCIOUSNESS   OF   SEI.F 


549 


thing  of  which  I  am  ashamed,  when  I  realise  that  I  am  acting  hypocritically , 
and  especially  when  I  am  violently  accused,  whether  rightly  or  wrongly ; 
also  sometimes  when  I  am  badly  defeated  in  an  argument.  I  experience 
self -consciousness  in  this  last  situation  chiefly  as  a  feeling  of  mental  isola- 
tion. I  get  exactly  the  same  consciousness  when  I  realise  that  I  can  know 
directly  no  one  but  myself  and  that  I  am  separated  from  all  others  by 
mediating  sensations.  (2)  In  many  situations  of  elation.  I  am  conscious 
of  self  when  I  have  a  strong  feeling  of  exaltation,  as  after  an  intellectual 
victory,  after  being  paid  a  compliment,  or  some  other  success.  This  is  a 
definite  complex  of  strong  organic  sensations  in  the  chest, — which  does  not 
always  occur  even  in  these  situations.  It  used  to  be  most  definite  in  relig- 
ious fervor.  It  now  occurs  most  often  in  the  enthusiasm  of  a  new  idea; 
in  enthusiasm  there  is  a  set  of  intoxicating  muscular  and  organic  sensations, 
a  large  part  of  which  I  should  interpret  as  consciousness  of  self.  (3)  In 
many  situations  of  mental  effort.  The  strains  that  go  to  make  up  the  feeling 
of  mental  effort  are  in  many  cases  identical  with  self -consciousness.  They 
are  most  prominent  in  this  way  in  the  feeling  of  resolve  or  determination, 
especially  in  repeated  resolve  that  cannot  have  any  immediate  motor 
result.  Another  striking  instance  is  in  stage-fright,  where  in  place  of  the 
imaged  speech  consciousness  is  largely  filled  with  strains  and  organic 
sensations  meaning  self.] 

Bra.  When  thinking  of  nearest  and  dearest  relations  and  friends;  but 
not  always.  When  thinking  about  what  I  ought  to  do  in  a  given  case; 
sometimes,  but  not  always.  Sometimes  when  praised  or  blamed.  Espe- 
cially when  alone  after  having  left  home  with  people  sorry  to  see  me  leave, 
etc. 

Cf.  It  is  likely  to  appear  in  one's  social  relations,  in  some  emotional 
states  and  religious  experiences,  rather  than  when  one  is  absorbed  in  a 
given  task. 

Em..     I  have  already  answeried  this  question,  under  II. 

Fi.  I  have  already  answered  this  question.  When  attention  is  delib- 
erately turned  upon  the  self,  as  in  observations  in  laboratory.  Under  the 
other  circumstances  mentioned. 

Gf.  The  consciousness  of  self  appears  under  unusual  circumstances. 
When  I  set  myself  the  task  of  introspecting,  or  when  I  am  conscious  of 
being  alone,  or  when  I  feel  myself  under  strict  observation :  these  are  some 
of  the  circumstances  under  which  self-consciousness  appears. 

The  replies  do  not,  by  any  means,  stand  upon  the  same 
psychological  level.  They  show  clear  differences  of  intro- 
spective ability.  They  show,  also,  differences  of  attitude,  of 
training,  of  point  of  view.  They  show,  I  am  afraid,  different 
degrees  of  interest  in  the  subject;  there  are  answers,  of  a 
partial  and  tentative  sort,  which  have  not  been  supplemented 
or  corrected.  Can  any  conclusions  be  drawn  from  such 
material? 

Question  I.  asks  whether  self -consciousness  is  persistent  or 
intermittent .  I  group  the  replies  under  the  rubric  of  sex,  and 
also  under  that  of  introspective  experience  (m,  f ,  for  the  senior 
and  m,  /,  for  the  junior  group  of  observers) ;  I  add  a  q,  in  cases 
in  which  the  reply  was  qualified. 

Total 


(i)  Persistent  throughout  the  waking  hfe 

(2)  Persistent  during  introspection 

(3)  Intermittent 


m 

f 

m 

/ 

iq 

iq 

I,  iq 

iq 

I 

3 

I 

3 

2 

550  TITCHENER 

Here  ii  out  of  13  observers  (7  men  and  6  women)  deny  the 
persistence  of  self-consciousness  throughout  the  waking  hfe, 
and  9  out  of  13  deny  its  persistence  during  introspective  as 
well  as  during  everyday  experience.  The  1 1  include  5  seniors 
and  6  juniors;  the  9  include  4  seniors  and  5  juniors.  The  11 
include  6  men  and  5  women;  the  9  include  6  men  and  3  women. 

Even  the  two  observers  who  affirm  the  continuity  of  self- 
consciousness  qualify  their  answers:  the  testimony  to  inter- 
mi  ttence  is  therefore  stronger  than  I  have  made  it.  And  I  do 
not  hesitate  to  draw  the  conclusion  that  self-consciousness  is, 
in  many  cases,  an  intermittent  and  even  a  rare  experience.  It 
may,  of  course,  be  maintained,  in  spite  of  what  I  have  said 
above,  that  the  method  is  altogether  worthless;  or  it  may  be 
objected  that  the  results  are  due  to  'laboratory  atmosphere.' 
But,  at  the  worst,  it  is  not  likely  that  the  text-book  statements 
of  the  persistence  and  continuity  of  self-consciousness  rest 
upon  any  better  method;  and  the  argument  from  suggestion, 
in  a  matter  like  this,  becomes  a  little  ridiculous.  Graduate 
students  are  not  simple  sheep. 

If  this  conclusion  is  accepted,  it  remains  to  account  for  the  positive 
replies  of  the  four  observers  in  the  first  and  second  horizontal  lines  of  the 
Table.  It  is  possible  that  the  four  are  mistaken.  The  two  senior  women 
of  column  f  had  no  opportunity  to  revise  their  answers;  and  another  obser- 
ver, as  we  have  seen  (p.  544),  changes  on  revision  from  Yes  to  No.  Con- 
trariwise, the  m  of  these  two  lines  does  not  change.  It  is  possible,  again, 
that  the  two  groups  of  observers,  the  four  and  the  nine,  may  have  under- 
stood the  question  differently,  and  are  therefore  talking  of  different  things. 
But  it  is  not  easy  to  make  this  possibility  concrete,  to  use  it  as  a  ground  of 
explanation;  it  is  at  the  best  a  possibility,  and  by  no  means  a  probability; 
and  the  fact  of  change  from  Yes  to  No  again  tells  against  it.  So  I  incline 
to  the  hypothesis  of  individual  difference.  The  tendency  to  conscious  self- 
hood is,  I  believe,  one  of  those  "tendencies  which  represent  total  directive 
pressures  laid  upon  the  organism,  more  strongly  upon  some  individuals 
and  more  weakly  upon  others,  but  in  some  measure  upon  all ;  and  which  are 
realised  or  expressed  on  very  various  occasions,  and  with  very  varying 
accompaniment  of  consciousness"  (Text-book  of  Psychology,  19 10,  464, 

544). 

The  persistence  of  self-consciousness  need  not — if  our  results  are  to  be 
trusted — betray  itself  in  the  intercourse  of  everyday  life.  Four  observers, 
two  men  and  two  women,  were  asked  to  name  the  man  and  the  woman  to 
whom  they  would  most  confidently  attribute  such  persistence.  All  four 
mentioned  the  m,  no  one  mentioned  the  f,  of  the  first  horizontal  line  of  the 
Table.  Reference  to  the  repUes  of  Etf  and  Dm  will  show  that  the  self- 
consciousness  takes  on  very  different  forms  in  the  two  cases. 

I  had  thought  that  the  women  might  prove  to  be  more  persistently  self- 
conscious  than  the  men.  The  question  must,  however,  be  left  open,  not 
only  because  our  observers  are  few,  but,  in  particular,  because  the  women  of 
column  f  had  no  opportunity  to  revise  their  answers. 

Question  II.  asks  for  a  description  of  the  self -consciousness. 
Under  this  heading,  the  following  general  results  may  be 
noted,  (i)  There  is  no  evidence  of  a  special  class  of  'subject- 
ive' processes  (Lipps).     (2)  With  one  possible  exception,  all 


THK   CONSCIOUSNieSS  OF  SELF  551 

the  reports  fall  under  the  rubric  of  determination.  We  find 
reference  to  an  implicit  self-consciousness  in  C's  'unified 
experience,*  in  D's  mention  of  *my  ways  of  thinking  and 
acting,'  and  in  statements  {B,  D,  for  example)  of  the  variable 
contents  of  the  self-conscious  experience.  We  find  self- 
consciousness  explicit  in  E's  'large  dark  vagueness  which 
represents  my  own  mind,'  in  ^'s  'translucent  rays  projected 
from  the  chest,' — probably,  indeed,  in  all  the  cases  of  visual 
imagery,  as  well  as  in  many  organic  complexes  (A,  C).  For 
the  most  part,  however,  no  hard  and  fast  line  of  distinction 
can  be  drawn  between  the  explicit  and  the  implicit  conscious- 
nesses. (3)  A  possible  instance  of  continuous  and  all-perva- 
sive conscious  selfhood  is  furnished  by  the  observer  D. 

I  do  not  think  it  wise  to  press  the  data  further.  I  add  only  a  rough  list 
of  the  constituents  of  the  self-consciousness,  in  the  order  of  frequency  of 
mention : 

Organic  complexes  12 

Visual  imagery  lo 

Affective  processes  8  (implied  in  4  other  cases) 

Kinaesthetic  complexes  8  (probably,  in  other  cases, 

merged  in  organic) 
Conscious  attitudes  4 

Verbal-auditory  images  4 

Cutaneous  sensations  2 

The  attitudes  are  those  of  responsibility  (F),  recognition  of  ownership  of 
introspections  (£),  ownership  of  experience  (D),  and  activity  in  back- 
ground of  consciousness  (F). 

Question  III.  asks  for  the  circumstances  under  which  self- 
consciousness  is  likely  to  appear.  Here  the  one  outstanding 
result  is  that  the  experience  of  self  is  preponderantly  a  social 
matter.  Of  the  11  observers  who  replied  to  the  question, 
10  (A,  B,  C,  D,  ^,  B,  C,  E,  F,  G)  refer  to  some  situation  which 
involves  the  ascription  of  selfhood  by  others,  or  implies  per- 
sonal relations  to  others. 

It  seems,  then,  that  the  'material  self  and  the  'spiritual  self  are,  for 
observers  of  our  sort,  subordinate  to  the  'social  self;'  that  the  realisation  of 
the  self  occurs,  usually,  under  a  consciously  social  determination.  Here 
of  course,  is  nothing  new.  But  it  is  reassuring,  in  view  of  the  testimony 
to  intermittence,  to  find  that  the  fact  appears  thus  plainly. 

Next  in  order  comes  the  unusual  or  novel  situation  (A,  B,  C,  E  [with 
qualification],  G). 

I  conclude,  therefore,  that  it  is  not  permissible  to  define 
psychology  as  "the  science  of  the  self  as  conscious."^  This 
definition  was,  in  fact,  rejected  by  one  and  all  of  our  thirteen 
observers. 2     Self-consciousness  appears,  in  many  cases,  as  an 

*M.  W.  Calkins,  A  First  Book  in  Psychology,  1910,  i. 

*By  twelve,  for  empirical  reasons;  by  the  thirteenth,  for  reasons  that  are 
mainly  theoretical.  "No.  For  suppose  that  there  were  periods  in  the 
consciousness  of  any  individual  which  were  without  reference  to  self: 


552  TITCHEN^R 

intermittent  mode  of  conscious  experience.  Like  other  con- 
scious attitudes,  it  takes  shape,  explicitly  or  implicitly,  under 
determination.  And  so  far  as  our  results  go,  the  determin- 
ation is  usually  social  in  character. 

then  such  periods  of  consciousness  would  not  be  subject-matter  for  psy- 
chology. Whether  such  periods  exist  is  a  matter  for  psychology  to  investi- 
gate ;  it  may  not  assume  their  absence  beforehand.  Or  suppose  that  there 
were  phases  of  consciousness  which  in  no  measure  had  reference  to  self, — as 
indeed  there  seem  to  be:  then  such  phases  would  be  barred  from  the  study 
of  psychology." 


ON  MEANING  AND  UNDERSTANDING' 


By  Edmund  Jacobson 


CONTENTS 

PAGB 

§1.  Introduction     .        .        * 553 

I2.  The  Perception  of  Letters 557 

§3.  The  Understanding  of  Words 562 

14.  The  Understanding  of  Sentences 569 

15.  In  Reply  to  Criticism 594 

§  I.    Introduction. 

We  give,  in  the  following  pages,  the  results  of  experiments 
on  the  perception  of  single  letters,  the  understanding  of  words, 
and  the  understanding  of  sentences.  The  experiments  were 
performed  by  what  is  known  as  Binet's  method,  or  the  Wurz- 
burg  method,  or  the  method  of  examination:  the  stimulus, 
written  or  printed,  was  laid  before  the  observer,  who  upon 
signal  opened  his  eyes,  fixated  the  paper  before  him,  and  after 
performance  of  the  assigned  task  gave  a  report  of  his  experi- 
ence. The  observers  were  Miss  L.  M.  Day  (assistant  in 
psychology),  Mr.  W.  S.  Foster  (assistant)  and  Dr.  L.  R. 
Geissler  (instructor  in  psychology) ;  all  three  had  had  thorough 
introspective  training.  In  the  experiments  of  §§  2,  3,  the 
writer  also  served  as  observer. 

The  method  of  examination  is,  without  question,  merely 
the  first  beginnings  of  an  experimental  method.  Okabe 
and  Clarke,  in  work  published  from  this  laboratory, ^  have 
proposed  to  supplement  it  by  the  method  of  confrontation. 
We  ourselves,  at  one  point  or  another  in  the  course  of  the 
present  experiments,  introduced  three  novel  features,  (i) 
In  the  experiments  of  §§  2  and  4  the  observer  was  instructed 
to  give  his  account  of  conscious  events  in  their  strict  temporal 
order.  Spontaneous  reference  to  this  order  is  customarily 
made,  in  most  extended  reports  by  the  method  of  examina- 

^From  the  psychological  laboratory  of  Cornell  University. 

2This  Journal,  xxi.,  Oct.  1910  and  xxii.,  April  191 1.  Ogden  curiously 
regards  the  addition  as  worthless,  because  alterations  were  not  suggested 
{Psych.  Bulletin,  viii.,  191 1,  194);  it  seems  to  us  that  confirmation  is  as 
valuable  as  correction.  Ogden's  suggestion  that  the  confrontation  was 
"quite  a  perfunctory  affair"  is  both  gratuitous  and  incorrect. 


554  JACOBSON 

tion,  through  such  terms  as  then,  after  that,  etc.  We  thought 
it  worth  while  specifically  to  give  the  temporal  instruction : 
partly  in  order  to  increase  the  fullness  of  the  reports,  partly 
in  order  to  attain  as  great  an  accuracy  in  the  reproduction 
of  the  experience  as  the  circumstances  of  the  experiments 
permitted.  As  regards  the  latter  point,  we  found  that  con- 
siderable training  was  required  before  the  observers  indicated 
the  temporal  position  of  every  reported  event;  and  we  are 
thus  forced  to  the  conclusion  that  the  sequences  and  coin- 
cidences noted  by  previous  writers  have  a  certain  inadequacy. 
As  regards  the  former  point,  we  found  that  the  temporal 
arrangement  was  of  material  aid  in  the  correlation  of  'pro- 
cess' and  'meaning,' — phases  of  the  reports  which  will  be 
explained  under  (2)  below.  The  actual  instruction  was  to 
give  as  precise  and  minute  an  account  as  possible  of  every- 
thing that  occurred  in  consciousness,  in  temporal  order,  making 
liberal  use  of  such  terms  as  next,  then,  simultaneous  with, 
and  overlapping.  When  the  report  failed  to  specify  the  tem- 
poral position  of  an  event,  a  question  was  usually  asked; 
but  the  necessity  of  such  questions  diminishes  with  practice. 
The  experimenter,  who  took  down  the  observer's  dictation, 
began  a  new  paragraph  whenever  next,  then,  after  that,  or  any 
term  definitely  denoting  succession  was  employed:  so  that 
the  events  of  a  quoted  paragraph  are  to  be  considered  either 
as  simultaneous  or  as  belonging  to  a  single  (though  extended) 
conscious  present.  But  it  should  be  noted  that  the  break  of 
consciousness  between  paragraphs  is  relative  only;  neither 
'process'  nor  'meaning'  terminates  abruptly,  in  order  directly 
to  give  place  to  a  successor ;  and  the  observers  were  asked 
expressly  to  declare  when  an  event  of  one  paragraph  lasted 
over  into  the  next. 

(2)  The  observer  in  these  §§  2  and  4  was  also  instructed 
to  place  everything,  except  the  direct  description  of  conscious 
processes,  in  parenthesis.  Previous  students  of  the  thought- 
processes  have  distinguished  between  description  proper 
{Beschreibung)  and  a  mode  of  report  that  is  variously  named 
Kundgabe  or  sprachlicher  Ausdruck  or  the  objective  reference 
involved  in  the  stimulus-error.  We  do  not  here  enter  upon 
the  question  whether  these  three  terms  cover  precisely  the 
same  material  and  designate  precisely  the  same  attitude  on 
the  part  of  the  observer;  nor  do  we  now  identify  our  owti 
reports  of  'meaning'  with  any  one  of  them;  it  is  enough  for  the 
present  if  intimation,  linguistic  expression,  objective  reference 
and  report  of  meaning  be  regarded  as  four  species  of  the  same 
genus.  What  we  desired  was  that  attributive  description 
of  conscious  processes  should  be  marked  off,  by  the  observers 
themselves,  from  whatever  else  might  enter  into  the  reports; 


ON  MEANING  AND  UNDERSTANDING  555 

and  we  accordingly  required  them  to  put  direct  description 
of  conscious  processes  outside  of  parentheses,  and  statements 
concerning  meanings,  objects,  stimuli  and  physiological  oc- 
currences inside.  The  procedure  was  justified  by  the  results: 
for  though  failure  to  specify  now  a  meaning  and  now  a  pro- 
cess was  at  first  not  infrequent,  it  grew  less  and  less  common 
with  practice,  until  the  twofold  report  became  characteristic 
of  the  experiments.  It  is,  of  course,  out  of  the  question  that 
the  observer  should  on  every  occasion  specify  the  attri- 
butes of  every  process  and  the  details  of  every  meaning: 
where  analysis  is  not  imperative,  e.  g.,  it  is  sufificient  to  report 
'perception  of  signal',  'sensations  from  eye-movement',  or 
'sensations  from  the  stimulus'.  But  it  is  necessary  that  the 
observer  be  trained  to  distinguish  such  references  to  meaning 
or  to  the  physiological  source  of  his  experiences  or  to  the  stim- 
ulus from  description  of  the  concomitant  conscious  processes; 
since  the  perception  of  a  given  object  or  of  the  same  phy- 
siological occurrence  or  of  an  identical  stimulus  may,  under 
different  conditions,  be  accompanied  by  different  conscious 
processes,  and  what  the  latter  are  often  needs  to  be  investi- 
gated. Moreover,  the  object  of  perception  is  not  to  be  con- 
fused with  the  presented  stimulus ;  if  the  experimenter  desires  to 
know  what  the  observer  is  perceiving,  at  a  particular  moment, 
he  must  obtain  special  reports  on  the  matter  from  the  ob- 
server; he  cannot  assume  that  the  stimulus  is  perceived  as 
he  himself  perceives  it. — By  the  use  of  parentheses  we  secured 
in  any  given  experiment  a  fuller  description  of  processes, 
where  the  observer  had  a  tendency  to  report  in  meanings, 
and  a  fuller  statement  of  meanings,  where  the  observer 
tended  to  report  solely  in  terms  of  processes.^ 

(3)  In  the  experiments  of  §  3,  and  to  a  slight  degree  in 
those  of  §  2,  we  availed  ourselves  of  a  special  mode  of  repe- 
tition. If  the  observer  had  failed  adequately  to  analyse  some 
complex  experience,  or  if  we  wished  him  to  verify  an  analysis 
already  given,  or  to  answer  some  question  after  the  event,  we 
restored  the  original  conditions  of  the  observation  and  in- 
structed the  observer  to  'get  back  the  original  complex'.  We 
found  that  it  was  often  possible,  in  this  way,  to  reinstate  the 
former  experience, — so  far,  at  any  rate,  as  that  the  observer 

^It  should  be  said  that,  while  F  and  J  tended,  after  practice,  to  make 
their  reports  of  meanings  as  full  and  detailed  as  their  reports  of  processes, 
D  and  G  (owing,  as  was  later  discovered,  to  a  partial  misunderstanding 
of  the  instructions  given)  sometimes  reported  meanings  with  less  complete- 
ness.    In  these  cases  the  experimenter  usually  had  recourse  to  questions. 

The  marks  of  parenthesis  were,  as  a  rule,  either  entered  by  the  observers 
themselves  upon  the  dictated  report,  or  inserted  by  the  experimenter  with 
the  approval  of  the  observer.  The  reports  quoted  in  the  present  paper 
have  been  submitted  to  their  authors  and  approved. 


556  JACOBSON 

recognised  the  present  complex  as  a  revival  of  the  old.  Some- 
times the  experiment  failed;  and  it  speaks  for  the  reliability 
of  the  observers  that  they  did  not  hesitate  to  report  failures. 
Sometimes  specific  differences  were  realised  between  the 
second  and  the  first  experiences.  Complete  success,  under 
the  limitations  of  the  method,  was  usual  with  D,  G  and  J; 
less  frequent  with  F.^ 

(i)  The  method  of  examination  furnishes  two  kinds  of  report:  the 
'selective',  in  which  the  observer  gives  special  attention  to  certain  features 
of  his  experience,  and  the  'complete',  in  which  he  seeks  to  reproduce  the 
experience  as  a  whole.  Since  we  were  unable  to  say  beforehand  what  was 
relevant  and  what  irrelevant  to  our  problems,  we  asked  only  for  the  com- 
plete account. 

By  putting  questions  to  the  observer,  it  is  often  possible  to  gain  informa- 
tion as  to  matters  omitted  from  the  report;  and,  what  is  more  important, 
the  bringing  of  the  observer's  attention  to  these  omissions  leads  to  their 
avoidance  in  future.  Owing  to  the  danger  of  undesirable  suggestion,  very 
great  care  is  needed  in  framing  the  questions;  and  a  careful  record  of 
question  and  answer  must  always  be  kept.  Our  object  in  the  work  of 
§§2  and  4  was  to  drop  them  entirely,  as  soon  as  the  reports  became 
spontaneously  complete.  During  the  stage  of  training,  however,  the 
observers  were  frequently  requested  by  the  experimenter  to  supplement  a 
process-report  by  naming  the  meaning,  or  conversely  to  supplement  a 
meaning-report  by  an  analysis  of  processes.  After  some  practice,  the  re- 
course to  parentheses  became  familiar:  though  it  should  be  added  that  no 
observer  was  wholly  consistent  in  their  use,  or  entirely  regular  in  paralleling 
process  and  meaning. 

(2)  We  cannot  insist  too  strongly  upon  the  necessity  of  repeated  in- 
struction; the  task  set  is  so  difficult  that  even  the  most  reliable  and  most 
willing  observers  tend  to  omissions.  A  meaning  may  be  stated,  while  the 
corresponding  process  is  in  whole  or  part  omitted:  thus,  an  observer  re- 
ports "general  notion  of  a  discussion  in  that  book  about  the  psychology 
of  genetics,"  and  a  question  is  needed  to  bring  out  the  fact  that  the  'general 
notion'  was  carried  in  kinaesthetic  and  verbal  terms.  Or  a  process  may  be 
described,  while  the  corresponding  meaning  is  in  whole  or  part  omitted: 
thus,  an  observer  reports  "sensations  of  slight  strain  in  chest,  as  breath 
was  held  for  a  moment;  sinking  in  abdomen;  other  sensations  of  touch 
from  clothes;  other  organic  sensations  not  so  clear  in  consciousness," 
without  giving  any  indication  of  the  meaning  of  the  attitude.  There  is 
often  failure,  even  after  practice,  to  report  the  time  of  an  occturence,  to 
state  fully  the  object  of  perception,  to  give  the  stages  in  the  development 
of  a  meaning,  to  rehearse  the  conscious  processes  present.  The  observer 
must  therefore  be  keyed  up  to  his  task  by  insistent  repetition  of  the  in- 
struction. 

(3)  We  do  not  here  enter  upon  the  question — which  indeed  is  a  ques- 
tion rather  for  epistemology  than  for  psychology — how  it  is  possible  to 
give  two  parallel  accoimts,  in  terms  of  process  and  in  terms  of  meaning,  of 

^This  method  of  repetition  was  introduced  in  order  that  we  might  deter- 
mine whether  the  method  of  examination  satisJSed  Wundt's  requirement  of 
"Wiederholung  bei  gleichem  beobachteten  Inhalt"  (Psych.  Studien,  iii., 
1907,  332  f.).  The  results  are  encouraging;  though  we  offer  them  only  as 
a  first  contribution  to  the  settlement  of  the  question. 

It  is  perhaps  needless  to  add  that  recognition  is  not  conditioned  upon 
possibility  of  description;  we  often  recognise,  quite  definitely,  something 
that  we  are  entirely  unable  to  describe. 


ON   MEANING    AND    UNDERSTANDING  557 

one  and  the  same  total  experience.  The  possibiUty  has  been  taken  for 
granted  by  previous  investigators  (Biihler,  Diirr,  von  Aster),  and  we  sim- 
ply follow  in  their  footsteps.  It  should,  however,  be  said  expressly  that 
the  shift  of  attitude,  from  process  to  meaning  or  conversely,  presented — 
after  preliminary  training — no  insuperable  difficulty  to  the  observer.  If 
a  process  or  a  meaning  stood  alone  in  the  report,  the  failure  was  due  to  in- 
advertence. All  the  observers  found  that  duplicate  accounts  were  possible, 
that  processes  could  be  summed  up  in  a  meaning,  and  that  meanings  could 
be  paralleled  by  processes.  We  may  add  that  the  word  'process'  was 
chosen,  not  as  the  equivalent  by  definition  of  sensations,  images  and 
feelings,  but  in  order  to  leave  room  for  any  other  conscious  form  (e.  g.,  an 
imageless  thought)  that  might  be  discovered. 

(4)  We  append  a  full  report  on  the  experience  of  understanding  a 
sentence.  The  observer  was  instructed  to  open  his  eyes  upon  signal,  to 
look  at  the  paper,  to  get  the  meaning  of  the  sentence  written  upon  it,  and 
then  to  close  his  eyes  and  dictate  his  report.  The  notes  which  follow  the 
quotation  call  attention  to  the  details  of  the  method. 

Observer  F.  Stimulus  sentence:  She  came  in  secretly.  Time:  1.25  sec. 
"Purple  (from  written  words) ^  clear.  White  (from  paper) ^  and  black 
(from  cardboard)^  in  background,  and  these  were  [comparatively ]2  unclear. 
Simultaneous  with  the  visual  clearness,  kinaesthetic-auditory  images  (cor- 
responding to  the  words) ;  weak  intensity,  more  as  if  whispered  than  as  if 
said  in  ordinary  voice;  i.  e.,  lacked  deeper  tones;  and  slightly  faster  than 
I  should  ordinarily  say  them.  (The  words  did  not  come  singly,  but  the 
sentence  as  a  whole  made  a  single  impression  on  me;  e.  g.,  the  period 
at  the  end  was  a  part  of  the  total  impression.  [All  this  wasl^  Perception  of 
sentence  as  visual  and  kinaesthetic-auditory  impression.)' 

"Then  vague  visual  and  kinaesthetic  image  (of  Miss  X.  coming  in  a 
stealthy  position,  on  tip-toe  with  legs  bent,  through  the  door  into  the 
Audition  Room  from  the  Haptics  Room)S  i.  e.,  blue  visual  image  (upper 
left  part  of  skirt)*  and  very  vague,  featureless  image,  flesh-colored  (of 
left  side  of  face).'*  The  image  (was  projected  straight  ahead  of  me,  to  the 
position  in  which  the  door  actually  is).^  Kinaesthetic  images  in  own  right 
upper  leg^  (which  was  directly  opposite  in  position  to  the  image,  as  if  my 
own  leg  was  bent);  also  kinaesthetic  images  or  sensations  in  muscles, 
probably  intercostals,  of  right  side  (such  as  I  get  when  standing  and  bend- 
ing right  leg).  (The  sentence  meant:  Miss  X.  came  in  over  there,  through 
the  door,  secretly.)^ 

"In  the  fore-period  (I  told  myself:  Get  the  meaning,  and  set  myself 
muscularly  to  work  hard)."^ 
Notes. — 

^Reference  to  stimulus. 

^Insertions  by  the  experimenter,  for  the  sake  of  clearness. 

^Statement  of  object  of  perception:  a  sentence  which,  as  yet,  was 
meaningless. 

^Statement  of  object  of  image. 

^O  fails  to  say  what  processes  carried  this  projection. 

®By  agreement,  the  reference  of  a  process  to  the  body  was  not  included 
in  parentheses. 

'Completion  of  understanding ;  meaning  of  sentence  has  been  specialised. 

*The  contents  of  the  fore-period  were  here  not  under  analysis. 

§  2.    The  Perception  of  Letters 

Our  problem,  in  this  group  of  experiments,  was  to  determine 
what  precisely  occurs  in  consciousness  when  there  is  'percep- 
tion'  of  a   single  letter.     The   method  has  been  described. 

Journal— 6 


558  JACOBSON 

The  stimulus  was  a  letter  written  in  long-hand ;  the  time  of 
exposure  was  left  to  the  decision  of  the  observer,  the  instruc- 
tion being  that  he  should  close  his  eyes  as  soon  as  he  had 
experienced  as  much  as  he  could  report  with  accuracy  and 
completeness.  Usually,  the  time  of  observation  was  i  to  3 
sec. 

The  processes  involved  in  perception. — For  the  most  part, 
the  visual  sensations  aroused  by  the  stimulus  are  not  sufiScient, 
of  themselves,  to  constitute  a  perception  of  the  particular 
letter;  some  additional  process  or  processes  must  supervene. 
Since  the  office  of  these  additional  processes  is  to  designate 
the  object  of  perception,  we  shall  call  them,  in  brief,  'designa- 
tory  processes*.  They  generally  consist  of  kinaesthetic  or 
auditory  sensations  or  images  as  of  pronouncing  or  hearing 
the  letter,  or  of  a  combination  of  the  two.  The  following 
Table  summarises  the  results. 


Total  number 

Associative  processes 

Observer 

of  perceptions 

D.  P.  reported 

reported  without 

of  letter 

perception 

D 

14 

13 

I 

F 

15 

10 

0 

G 

10 

9 

2 

J^ 

21 

21 

2 

(i)  If  the  D.  P.  are  absent,  there  is  usually  no  perception  of  the  letter. 
Two  instances  are  appended. 

Observer  D.  Stimulus  Y. —  .  .  .  Then  sensations  in  throat  (of  repeated 
contraction  and  relaxation)  accompanied  by  faint  auditory  images  (of  the 
sound).  In  the  course  of  this,  the  perception  (of  Y)  faded  away,  and 
attention  during  this  time  was  on  the  kinaesthetic  sensations  and  on  the 
idea  (that  I  must  not  utter  the  word). 

Then  (was  aware  that  eyes,  which  had  not  been  carefully  fixating,  were 
now  doing  it).     Strain  sensations  in  muscles  around  sides  of  eyes. 

Then  sensations  (of  eye-movement)  and  awareness  (that  I  was  follow- 
ing the  Y  around;  and  while  doing  this  it  was  not  Y  for  me  hut  just  a  line 
gure). 

Observer  F.  Stimulus  Z. — When  first  opened  eyes,  the  black  white  and 
grayish  sensations  became  clear  (the  stimuli  being  the  paper,  ink,  letter 
and  black  background).  The  extent  of  the  visual  field  was  [0  indicates  a 
rough  circular  outline  on  the  table].  This  state  was  of  short  duration. 
(All  this  was  perception  of  [some]  letter  on  white  paper  on  black  ground.) 

Later  came  the  auditory  image  Z  and  with  it  the  perception  (of  Z). 
[All  that  was  at  first  perceived,  as  the  observer  specified  on  question,  was 
letter  in  general.]  * 

(2)  In  order  to  test  the  above  result,  the  observer  was  sometimes  in- 
structed (oftenest  in  the  case  of  J)  to  wait  till  a  time  arrived  when  there 
were  present  in  consciousness  no  kinaesthetic  or  auditory  images  or  sensa- 
tions as  of  uttering  or  hearing  the  letter,  and  to  begin  the  report  from  that 
time.    Two  instances  may  be  given. 

^In  two  cases  from  J,  in  which  the  kinaesthetic-auditory  image  as  of 
utterance  of  the  letter  was  probably  or  certainly  lacking,  the  D.  P.  were 
given  in  the  form  of  images  of  incipient  right-hand  movements,  as  for  the 
writing  of  the  letter.  These  cases  are  not  included  in  the  Table.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  Table  contains  7  'repetition'  experiments,  4  from  F  and  3 
from  J:  cf.  (5)  below. 


ON  MEANING  AND  UNDERSTANDING  559 

Observer  G.  Letter  G. — Strong  strain  sensations  (from  fixation  of 
thickest  part  of  the  letter),  with  great  clearness  of  blue  localised  to  the 
upper  right  half,  and  with  special  clearness  of  its  extent  and  form.  Much 
less  clear  were  the  other  blues  of  certain  extent  and  form  interrupted  here 
and  there  by  white  (as  if  the  letter  was  incomplete,  or  as  if  there  were 
breaks  in  the  line.)  These  other  blues  were  blurred  in  outline  and  indefinite 
in  shape  and  direction  They  were  simply  there,  (without  seeming  to  be- 
long together, — which  is  now  carried  into  this  previous  experience) ;  [The 
observer  means  that  the  incoherence  was  present  in  the  original  experience, 
but  that  he  was  not  aware  of  it  as  such ;  he  now  notices  it,  as  he  frames  his 
report.]  (this  I  call  blank  empty  staring  at  the  stimulus) ;  accompanied 
intermittently  by  temperature  and  pressm-e  and  auditory  sensations  (of 
expiration)  alternately  with  warm  and  pressure  sensations  (of  tip  of  tongue 
against  upper  teeth)  and  by  vague  white  somewhere  surrounding  the  blues. 
These  blues  were  constant.  This  whole  experience  is  not  a  perception 
( of  the  letter  G  ),  but  merely  a  conglomeration  or  concurrence  of  certain 
sensations.     No  conscious  tendency  was  present  to  articulate. 

Observer  J.  Letter  W. — There  were  the  black  and  white  sensations, 
but  I  can  scarcely  say  that  at  any  time  there  was  perception  (of  any  figure 
or  indeed  of  anything  at  all),  despite  the  fact  that  the  visual  sensations  were 
clear  and  intense.  The  best  I  can  say  is,  that  these  visual  sensations, 
along  with  a  vague  complex  of  background  processes — (those  resulting 
from  position  of  body,  eyes,  and  possibly  also  from  gastro-intestinal 
organs) — made  up  a  general  attitude  of  staring,  which,  however,  involved 
no  perception  at  the  time,  (though  it  would  be  correct  afterwards  to  say  I 
perceive,  from  memory,  that  there  was  a  figure  of  such  and  such  a  type). — 

From  these  and  similar  reports  it  would  follow  that  sensations  may 
appear  in  consciousness  as  such,  without  necessarily  forming  part  of  a 
particular  perception. 

(3)  It  may  not  be  superfluous  to  state  that  the  D.  P.  appear  in  other 
perceptions  than  those  of  letters.     Here  are  three  instances : 

Observer  G.  Letter  Y. — ^Visual  perception,  clear  (of  first  part  of 
letter),  with  slight  kincBsthetic  sensations  (of  fixating  that  part)  and  other 
slight  visual  sensations  (of  rest  of  white  field). 

Observer  J.  Letter  B. — [Next]  a  period  (when  the  eye  changingly 
rested  on  certain  parts  of  the  upper  strokes  of  the  letter)  and  there  was 
simultaneous  kincesthetic-auditory  verbal  imagery  'thin'  (meaning  the  lines 
were  thin,  and  thus  constituting  a  perception  that  they  were  so).  This 
perception  may  have  had  other  components,  but  certainly  those  men- 
tioned were  the  only  prominent  ones. 

Observer  F.  Letter  Z. — Then  attention  (caught  by  pendulum  swinging) . 
That  is,  sensations  (from  pendulum  bob  seen  in  indirect  vision)  were  clear, 
and  there  were  kincBsthetic  images  in  neck  (as  if  to  swing  head  with  the  bob). 

A  rivalry  of  perceptions  from  the  same  stimulus  may  show  itself  in  al- 
ternation of  the  D.  P.     An  illustration  follows: 

Observer  J.  Letter  C. — There  was  a  fluctuation,  a  struggle  of  perceptions 
in  successive  order.  Predominant  was  a  perception  (of  an  apple.  Visual 
fixation  was  on  left  side  of  base  of  stem  of  apple).  There  is  no  visual 
image  (of  an  apple),  but  verbal-motor  incipient  utterance  'apple'  occurred. 
(When  the  letter  C  was  perceived,  the  visual  fixation  was  not  as  just  de- 
scribed), and  there  was  no  verbal  image  'apple'.  At  times  during  the  per- 
ception (of  C  there  was  incipient  motor  innervation  of  the  index  finger  of 
the  right  hand  to  follow  the  curve  of  C;  at  times  also  to  continue  the 
movement  in  the  form  of  an  .4 ) ;  and  simultaneous  with  this  was  a  visual 
image  with  very  faint,  hazy  and  shadowy  outlines.  I  do  not  reniember 
whether  verbal  images  were  or  were  not  present  simultaneously  with  the 
perception  (of  the  letter). 
I  (4)     Sometimes  the  observer  fails  to  report  the  presence  of  D.  P.,  and 

!      a  question  is  needed  to  bri&g  them  to  light.     Thus  in  one  case  the  observer 


560  JACOB  SON 

reports  'attention  attracted  to  the  horizontal  line,' and  only  in  reply  to 
question  by  the  experimenter  is  it  added  that  there  were  simultaneous 
kinaesthetic  sensations  from  eye-movement, — though  these  obviously 
played  the  part  of  D.  P.  in  the  perception.^ 

We  have  said  that,  if  the  D.  P.  are  absent,  there  is  'usually'  no  percep- 
tion of  the  letter.  The  rule  has  possible  exceptions.  Especially  during 
the  earlier  observations,  J  was  often  in  doubt  whether  there  was  a  per- 
ception of  the  letter  at  times  when  the  contents  of  consciousness  were  pre- 
dominantly visual.  Thus,  with  stimulus  G,  he  reports  "a  period  during 
which  the  visual  sensations  alone  were  prominent,  with  simultaneous 
pain  and  pressure  sensations  about  eyelids  and  probably  in  other  muscles 
of  eyes.  During  this  period  there  was  no  well-defined  well-developed  per- 
ception of  G;  at  most  there  was  a  hazy  and  ill-defined  perception;  but  I 
cannot  say  with  surety  whether  there  was  this  or  none  at  all." 

(5)  The  Table  mentions  five  cases  in  which  no  perception  occurs, 
notwithstanding  the  presence  of  associated  processes.  In  three  of  these, 
the  first,  third,  and  fifth  of  those  quoted  below,  this  failure  seems  to  be 
due  to  the  absence  of  clear  visual  sensations  from  the  stimulus;  the  fourth 
may  have  a  like  cause,  since  G,  in  mentioning  vague  visual  sensations  in 
the  fifth,  says  that  perhaps  the  fourth  case  was  similar;  but  for  the  second 
case  we  have  no  explanation  farther  than  that  suggested  in  the  report  it- 
self. 

Observer  D.  Letter  B. — Then  sensations  in  larynx,  repeatedly  inrhythm. 
At  the  same  time  there  was  no  visual  perception  (of  letter  B), — only 
vague  indistinct  sensations  {of  blackness  and  whiteness),  of  long  duration. 

Observer  J.  Letter  M.  Time,  20  sec.  Instruction:  Repeat  to  get 
back  the  visual  sensations  as  they  occur  when  perception  of  M  is  absent. 
[A  previous  regular  report,  as  well  as  repetitions  of  this  occurrence  with  the 
letter,  had  been  made.] — I  am  unable  to  report  according  to  temporal  order 
this  time.  (The  eyes  kept  running  over  the  stimulus  and  there  was  con- 
tinual tendency  periodically  to  utter  M.)  At  most  of  these  times  there 
was  perception  (of  M),  but  there  were  other  times  when  this  imaginal 
utterance  was  present  simultaneously  with  visual  sensations  from  the  stimu- 
lus, yet  no  visual  perception  (of  M).  This  was  succeeded  by  a  period  in 
which,  with  the  same  kind  of  imaginal  utterance,  there  was  again  visual 
perception  (of  M).  It  was  apparent  that  there  was  some  difference  in  the 
visual  sensations  or  in  the  concomitant  kinaesthesis,  i.  e.  images  (of  eye- 
movement  or  head-movement).  But  the  difference  was  delicate  and 
hard  qualitatively  to  describe. 

Observer  J.  Same  letter.  Instruction:  Repeat  and  imaginally  utter 
Jlf  periodically.  Time,  3  sec. —  (The  periodic  utterance  occurred.)  lam 
not  sure  but  that  the  visual  sensations  were  attentionally  clearer  between 
utterances  than  at  the  points  of  utterance.  But  it  was  apparent  that  the 
strong  perception  (of  M)  that  usually  attends  such  utterance  was  absent. 

Observer  G.  Letter  Y. —  ....  Next  clear  verbal  kinaesthetic-auditory 
complex  (whispering  Y)  with  faint  kinaesthetic  sensations  (from  eye-move- 
ment over  the  whole  letter  successively  in  the  order  of  writing  it).  (All 
of  this  is  perception  of  the  letter.) 

(Next  repeated  whispering)  with  kinaesthetic  sensations  (from  eyes 
moving  backwards  over  whole  letter) ;  same  kinaesthetic-tactual-tempera- 
ture  [complex]  (from  exhaled  breath)  vaguely  present.  (This  repetition 
is  not  a  perception, — but  merely  a  concurrence  of  these  mental  processes. 
I  am  unable  to  say  what  exactly  is  the  difference  in  consciousness  [between 

iThe  stimulus  in  this  case  was  a  geometrical  figure.  With  the  letters, 
and  indeed  with  any  form  of  frequently  recurring  stimulus,  such  cases  be- 
come, in  our  experience,  rare.  It  should,  however,  be  added  that  the 
D.  P.  are  by  no  means  always  obvious;  sometimes  both  skill  and  practice 
are  required  for  their  detection. 


ON  MEANING  AND  UNDERSTANDING         56 1 

the  perception  and  non-perception  as  they  occurred  above].  Am  doubtful 
as  to  whether  there  was  any  conscious  difference,  unless  the  first  repetition 
was  accompanied  by  a  vague,  feeling  of  familiarity — slightly  pleasant, 
while  the  later  repetitions  were  indifferent,  and,  so  to  say,  automatically 
continued.) 

Observer  G.  Same  letter.  Instruction:  Repeat  the  mental  situation 
[as  above]. —  ....  Next  (whispering)  complex  becomes  still  less  clear. 
Vague  visual  sensations,  black  and  white,  without  any  connection  between 
them  in  consciousness, — no  consciousness  of  their  form  or  extent.  Drowsy 
sensations  practically  indifferent.  (All  this  is  not  perception  of  Y.)  This 
description  of  the  non-perception  of  Y  differs  from  the  original  non-percep- 
tion [i.  e.  that  described  in  G's  report  above]  in  point  of  the  drowsy  sensa- 
tions and  the  vague  visual  sensations, — both  of  which  may  have  been 
previously  present,  but  which  were  not  reported. 

Perception  as  meaning. — We  turn  now  to  the  'meanings'  that 
appear  parenthesized  in  the  reports  of  our  observers.  The 
main  point  to  note  is  that  the  precise  statement  of  meanings  is 
by  no  means  easy.  Just  as  processes  flit  by  on  the  passing 
instant,  so  do  meanings  change  and  elude  the  observer;  and 
the  skill  in  expression  of  meaning  acquired  in  daily  life  is 
comparatively  rough  and  superficial.  This  fact  may  be  illus- 
trated in  two  ways. 

First,  it  is  often  not  enough  to  record  simply  that  'the  per- 
ception of  the  letter'  occurred ;  what  is  perceived  is  frequently 
— perhaps  always — something  more  complex.  We  gave  to 
F  the  special  instruction  that  he  should  state,  precisely,  what 
he  perceived;  and  the  result  justified  the  specialisation  of 
method.     For  example : 

Letter  Z. — (As  soon  as  I  opened  eyes)  perception  {of  Z  placed  on  white 
paper  in  a  particular  direction  from  left  upper  corner  of  paper).  This  was 
clear  visual  sensations  (from  black  Z  and  white  paper),  also  sensations 
(from  upper  left-hand  comer  of  paper).  The  attribute  of  extent  [form 
and  position]  of  this  corner  and  the  visual  sensations  (from  Z)  were 
clearer  than  the  sensations  (from  the  white  paper),  v/hich  in  turn  were 
perhaps  clearer  than  those  (from  the  black  background).  Simulta- 
neous or  immediately  after  and  forming  a  part  of  this  perception,  abbre- 
viated auditory  image  Z.  ( (I  notice  now,  in  reporting,  that  this  image  was 
purely  sibilant.))  There  were  also  vague  kinaesthetic  images  or  sensations 
in  throat  and  lips,  those  in  lips  being  the  more  noticeable. 

Letter  D. — (Soon  as  opened  eyes)  gray  and  white  clear  (from  paper  and 
ink).  Simultaneous  auditory  image  D.  These  visual  sensations  were 
clear  only  for  a  brief  time,  about  one- tenth  of  the  whole  period.  The 
auditory  image  was  of  higher  pitch  and  less  intensity  than  it  would  be 
from  spoken  D.  Its  other  attributes,  clearness  and  duration,  were  the 
same  as  if  I  had  uttered  D.     (There  was  perception  of  D  on  white  paper.) 

Secondly,  the  stimulus  frequently  arouses  other  perceptions 
than  those  of  the  particular  letter,  and  the  object  of  these 
perceptions  needs  careful  statement.  Examples  may  be 
found  in  reports  already  quoted;  we  add  one  further  instance: 

Observer  D.  Letter  A. — Kinaesthetic  sensations  retreat  to  margin  of 
consciousness;  become  non-focal,  non-clear;  simultaneous  visual  percep- 
tion {of  a  dark  line  of  the  shape  A  on  a  white  ground;  it  was  not  perception  of 


562  JACOBSON 

A).  Sensations  of  eye-movement,  plus  an  awareness  (of  the  same  along 
the  figure,  thus)  [observer  indicates  the  direction,  which  is  that  taken  by 
the  pen  in  writing  the  letter],  plus  kinaesthetic  sensations  especially  in  the 
neck,  but  not  definitely  localised  and  not  distinct. 

Summary. — The  perception  of  a.  particular  letter  usually 
depends  upon  the  arousal  of  contextual  associates,  which  we 
have  termed  'designatory  processes'.  The  direct  visual 
apprehension  of  the  stimulus,  i.  e.  the  presence  merely  of 
ordered  visual  sensations,  does  not  suffice  as  a  rule,  under 
the  conditions  of  our  experiments,  for  the  perception  of  the 
letter. 

These  designatory  processes  may  characterise  other  per- 
ceptions, as  well  as  the  perception  of  a  letter. 

From  knowledge  of  the  stimulus,  the  experimenter  cannot 
determine  the  nature  of  the  perception  at  a  given  instant; 
a  report  of  the  precise  object  of  perception  must  be  obtained 
from  the  observer. 

Variation  of  the  object  of  perception,  with  a  given  stimulus, 
is  accompanied — again,  under  the  conditions  of  our  ex- 
periments— by  variation  of  the  concomitant  or  underlying 
'processes' ;  this  variation  may  usually  be  traced  both  in  the 
designatory  processes  and  in  the  processes  which  subserve 
accommodation  of  attention. 

§  3.     Th^  Meaning  of  Words 

The  experiments  now  to  be  reported  were  the  first  made  in 
the  present  investigation;  the  method  was  tentative,  and  the 
observers  were  comparatively  unpractised  for  the  problem 
in  hand.  The  usual  method  of  procedure  was  as  follows: 
A  written  word  was  laid  before  the  observer  for  a  period  of 
I  min.  He  was  instructed  to  fixate  the  word,  to  utter  it  with 
quick  repetition,  and  to  get  its  meaning.  The  concluding 
10  sec.  were  marked  off  by  signals;  and  the  observer's  task 
was  to  report  what  occurred  in  consciousness  during  this 
particular  interval. 

Our  aim  in  adopting  this  method  was  to  secure  frequent  appearances 
and  disappearances  of  the  verbal  meaning,  and  so  to  provide  repeated 
opportunities  for  its  analysis.  The  method  was  fairly  successful,  though 
the  period  of  10  sec.  proved  to  be  too  long  for  a  complete  report;  thie  ex- 
perimenter was  therefore  obliged  in  many  cases  to  have  recourse  to  ques- 
tions— made  as  little  suggestive  as  possible — in  order  to  secure  omitted  in- 
formation and,  less  frequently,  in  order  to  verify  the  absence  of  an  unreported 
item. 

The  special  form  of  the  method  which  involved  repetition  has  been  de- 
scribed above,  p.  555.  Another  variation  was  sometimes  introduced,  by 
which  a  feature  of  the  original  report  was  eliminated,  and  the  consequence 
of  this  elimination  noted.  Thus,  with  the  word  silently  G  reports  the  pres- 
ence of  kinaesthetic- verbal  images  'still'  and  'silently  means  ruhig';  these 
images  carry  the  meaning  of  the  stimulus- word.     He  is  thereupon  in- 


ON  MEANING   AND    UNDEJRSTANDING  563 

structed  to  fixate  the  word  and  to  articulate,  as  before,  but  not  to  permit 
the  rise  of  such  verbal  associations.  The  report  of  the  changed  situation 
reads:  'No  meaning  to  the  word.  Just  sounds  and  just  sensations  from 
articulation.' 

The  repetition  and  prolonged  fixation  of  the  stimulus-word  had  the 
effect,  as  we  expected,  of  intermittently  destroying  associations.  But 
they  led  also,  in  some  cases,  to  the  disintegration  of  the  perception  itself. 
Special  parts  of  the  word  might  stand  out  and  be  perceived  in  place  of  the 
whole.  Thus,  a  kinaesthetic  or  auditory  or  combined  image  of  one  of  the 
letters  arises,  accompanied  by  visual  fixation  of  that  letter,  and  perhaps 
leaving  the  rest  of  the  word  visually  (peripherally)  obscure:  then  there  is 
perception  of  the  single  letter  rather  than  of  the  whole  word,  despite 
the  fact  that  the  word  is  being  uttered.  Our  records  suggest,  though  they 
do  not  prove,  that  so  long  as  there  are  visual  sensations  from  the  whole 
of  the  word,  with  simultaneous  enunciation  of  it,  the  perception  remains. 
—Cf.  E.  Severance  and  M.  F.  Washburn,  this  Journal,  xviii.,  1907,  182  ff. 

No  definition  of  'meaning*  was  furnished  by  the  experi- 
menter. F  at  first  showed  occasional  uncertainty  as  to  what 
constituted  meaning;  and  D  for  some  time  showed  occasional 
doubt  and  inconsistency.  Eventually,  however,  the  reports 
of  all  four  observers  became  practically  uniform.  It  is  need- 
less to  say  that  no  observer  was  informed  of  the  results  ob- 
tained from  the  others,  and  that  all  were  cautioned  not  to 
discuss  the  experiments  outside  of  the  laboratory.  Illustra- 
tions of  what  were  called  'meanings'  follow. 

Observer  D,  Stimulus  bloody.  [The  word  has  been  articulated  and 
fixated  for  the  previous  50  sec,  and  these  activities  are  continued  during  the 
final  10  sec]  After  the  signal  I  said  to  myself,  Must  get  meaning  again; 
and  then  said.  Must  the  blood  be  running? — accompanied  by  a  visual 
image  of  an  animal  of  indefinite  shape  with  a  flowing  wound :  Or  may  it 
be  dry? — now  with  a  visual  image  of  same  animal,  but  I  was  looking  at 
the  edges  of  the  wound  where  there  was  coagulation.  Visual  image  of  some 
animal  on  table,  and  of  Mr.  X  saying:  So-and-so  is  fond  of  seeing  blood 
run.     Then  lost  meaning. 

Observer  D.  Stimulus  secretly.  [Conditions  as  above.]  Just  after 
the  signal  I  tried  voluntarily  to  get  back  to  what  I  had  before,  when  I  had 
the  bodily  attitude  of  hiding  or  concealing.  [Later]  a  visual  image  of  a 
girl  whispering  to  me  disappeared  suddenly,  and  I  was  left  just  saying  the 
word. 

[In  order  to  give  opportunity  for  the  analysis  of  this  imaginal  bodily 
attitude  two  repetitions  (p.  555)  were  made.  Both  were  successful;  in 
the  first  repetition  the  attitude  was  declared  more  distinct  than  in  the  ori- 
ginal experience.  The  reports,  supplemented  by  questions,  brought  out 
the  fact  that  the  attitude  was  wholly  kinaesthetic;  the  observer  was  crouch- 
ing, and  concealing  an  object  in  front  of  her  with  body  and  hands;  she 
was  aware  of  people  behind  her,  who,  however,  were  not  given  in  visual 
images,  but  were  implied  by  the  nature  of  the  attitude.] 

Observer  F.  Stimulus  face.  [Conditions  as  above.]  When  signal 
came  was  saying  to  myself:  Wonder  whether  he  wants  me  to  get  a  noun  or 
a  verb.  Then  pulled  myself  together  [observer  indicates  retractive  move- 
ment of  arms  and  inward  movement  of  chest,  with  forward  tension  of 
shoulders  and  head  leaning  forward].  Now  with  attention  to  sound  of 
voice  it  was  as  if  I  were  telling  myself  to  face  something.  All  strains 
seemed  to  drag  me  to  the  front,  and  I  said:  Verb, — ^with  accompanying 
auditory  image.     Then  vague  visual  image  of  experimenter's  face,  and 


564  JACOBSON 

then  of  my  own.  .  .  ,  [The  attitude  here  carried  the  verbal  meaning,  the 
visual  images  the  substantive  meaning.] 

Observer  F.  Stimulus  to.  [Conditions  as  above.]  Visual  image  of  a 
clothed  right  arm  reaching  out  to  the  storm-door  at  the  front  of  this  build- 
ing. While  this  image  lasted,  attention  was  on  sound  of  voice;  and  then 
the  arm  reached  to  the  door,  but  did  not  open  it.  This  recurred  once  or 
twice,  except  that  attention  was  no  longer  on  the  voice.  Then  I  thought 
I  ought  to  get  some  other  meaning.  Then  verbal-auditory  image  to  him, 
with  kinaesthetic  image  of  moving  left  hand,  which  was  held  forward,  from 
left  to  right.  [During  the  entire  period  the  observer  had  nodded  his  head 
vigorously  with  each  enunciation;  and  questions  bring  out  the  fact  that 
this  gesture  means  for  him  the  instruction:  Get  that  meaning!] 

Observer  G.  Stimulus  to.  [Conditions  as  above.  Two  meanings  are 
given  below;  the  rest  of  the  report,  containing  two  other  meanings,  is 
omitted.]  Strong  kinaesthetic  tendency  to  move  to  right  in  the  direction 
of  the  end-stroke  of  the  letter  o.  The  to  meant  a  direction,  a  going  some- 
where, similar  to  that  given  by  a  guide-post,  and  there  was  a  sense  of  being 
at  a  loss.  .  .  .  Then  the  numerical  meaning,  in  the  form  of  putting  two  fingers 
on  the  table. 

[Instruction:  Repeat,  and  get  back  the  first  meaning. — I  do  not  know 
whether  it  came  as  completely  as  before.  There  was  a  tendency  to  move 
eyes  and  body  to  the  right,  and  to  pronounce  the  word  briefly  as  if  saying : 
To — some  place.  There  was  no  more  of  the  Bewusstheit  of  direction  than 
this.     There  was  strong  fixation  of  the  last  part  of  the  word.] 

Observer  G.  Stimulus  cutting.  [Conditions  as  above.]  Meaning 
present  as  a  faint  visual  image  of  a  knife-blade  and  a  kinaesthetic  tendency 
to  press  it  down.  [Where  was  that  tendency?]  In  the  first  three  fingers 
of  right  hand ;  it  was  accompanied  by  movement  of  eyes  to  the  place  on  the 
right. 

Observer  J.  Stimulus  botany.  [Conditions  as  above.]  .  .  .  Remembrance 
that  must  concentrate  on  meaning.  [Not  analysed.]  Then  visual  image 
of  green  plants  and  a  recently  seen  hot-house.  This  disappeared,  leaving 
only  the  sounds  from  enunciation.  Later  an  attempt  again  to  follow  the 
instructions  [not  analysed]  was  followed  by  the  motor  expression  'study 
of  plants'  and  still  later  by  'study  of  plants  and  flowers,'  and  these  phrases 
were  frequently  repeated,  notwithstanding  the  simultaneous  enunciation 
of  'botany'. 

The  meaning  of  the  stimulus- words  were  thus  carried  by  vis- 
ual, auditory  and  kinaesthetic  processes;  or,  to  speak  more 
precisely,  the  meanings  which  these  processes  bore  were  the 
meanings  of  the  stimulus-words,  in  so  far  as  the  latter  were 
consciously  realised.  If  we  may  use  the  term  'association'  in 
the  widest  sense,  to  denote  peripheral-kina^sthetic  as  well  as 
imaginal  processes,  we  may  say  that  the  meanings  were  given 
in  the  shape  of  associations  to  the  words.  But  the  associa- 
tions to  a  given  word  do  not  remain  constant :  thus,  the  visual 
image  of  plants  and  a  hot-house,  associated  to  the  word  botany, 
gives  way  a  moment  later  to  the  verbal-motor  'study  of 
plants'.  It  seems  to  follow  that  the  meanings  of  the  words, 
so  far  as  they  are  conscious,  vary  as  the  associations  vary.  The 
logical  meaning  of  a  word,  as  expressed  in  a  formal  definition, 
does  not  change ;  but  what  we  are  studying  is  not  this  perfect 
logical  meaning,  but  rather  the  phases  of  meaning  or  the  part- 


ON    MEANING  AND  UNDERSTANDING  565 

meanings  carried  by  certain  transient  processes;  and  as  thus 
understood  the  meaning  must  be  said  to  vary. 

If  the  associations  are  absent,  meaning  is  also  reported  as 
lacking.     Here  are  some  examples : 

Observer  G.  Stimulus  loud. — The  first  impression  was  of  an  Aufgabe 
given  me  by  the  word,  and  I  started  to  speak  loudly.  After  several  repeti- 
tions this  Aufgabe  came  again,  but  then  gradually  became  unconscious,  and 
there  was  mere  mechanical  pronunciation.  Then  verbal  image  laut,  lead- 
ing to  stronger  accent  on  the  d  during  enunciation.  With  a  new  inhalation 
the  same  Aufgabe  returned,  and  there  was  greater  muscular  effort  in  articu- 
lation for  the  next  few  pronunciations. 

[Instruction:  Repeat,  without  getting  this  Aufgabe  association  or  other 
similar  ones;  but  try  to  get  what  you  can  of  the  meaning,  and  then 
report. — Practically  nothing  under  these  conditions  besides  the  visual 
and  kinaesthetic  perceptions,  the  latter  being  especially  clear.  The  word 
has  an  empty  look;  I  don't  know  how  to  describe  it.] 

For  another  like  case  with  G.,  see  pp.  562  f. 

Observer  D.  Stimulus  kill. — The  first  signal  suppressed  a  coming  visual 
image  of  an  object  floating  on  the  water,  a  clipping  from  a  newspaper,  etc. 
[Then]  visual  image  of  the  physiological  laboratory  and  of  a  pithed  frog, 
with  appropriate  tactual  and  organic  sensations.  Visual  image  of  the 
operating  room  and  of  an  animal  I  had  killed  through  over-etherization. 
Then  [other  similar  images]. 

[Instruction:  Repeat,  and  get  none  of  these  associations,  and  then  de- 
scribe.— I  got  a  few  motor-auditory  verbal  images, — 'to  murder',  and 
'to  destroy  life'.  There  were  vague  sensations  from  bodily  position,  and 
a  strain  to  get  something  else  besides  these  images.  [What?]  Tension  in 
my  head,  and  a  slight  tendency  to  scowl. 

Instruction:  Repeat,  and  do  not  get  these  verbal  images. — The  word 
is  quite  lifeless  and  meaningless.  [The  observer  adds  incidentally  that 
this  meaninglessness  had  its  organic  side — weak  breathing,  a  let-go  feel- 
ing, a  depression.]  ] 

Observer  J,  Stimulus  piano. —  .  .  .  Then  the  writing  was  no  longer  in 
consciousness  as  a  word,  but  rather  as  a  collection  of  curved  lines. 

[Instruction:  Repeat,  to  see  what  is  in  consciousness  when  only  these 
lines  are  present. — I  fixated  one  letter  after  another,  each  time  pronounc- 
ing the  whole  word.  The  other  letters  were  all  in  consciousness,  but  not 
so  clear;  nevertheless  the  word  was  present  as 'a  whole.  But  at  times, 
when  fixation  was  on  the  a  or  the  n,  there  occurred  slight  optical  divergence, 
and  the  whole  word  became  slightly  [peripherally]  unclear.  This  was  con- 
tinued until  there  was  no  consciousness  of  any  of  the  individual  letters 
seen  as  such,  but  only  a  consciousness  of  wavy  blue  lines  with  a  tendency 
to  follow  them  with  the  eyes  and  with  the  right  hand  from  left  to  right  and 
back  again.  But  in  this  the  lower  parts  of  the  o  and  a  were  omitted. 
[Apparently  here  also  there  are  no  associations  to  the  word  as  such,  and 
it  is  meaningless.]  ] 

We  did  not  find  a  characteristic  variation  of  associations 
with  the  different  parts  of  speech.  Those  which  stood  for 
the  meanings  of  prepositions,  e.  g.,  were  not  invariably  motor 
tensions  or  impulses.^  On  the  whole,  kinaesthesis  was  more 
prominent  with  prepositions  than  with  nouns  like  'piano'  and 
'dog';  but  visual  and  auditory  processes  were  also  involved 
in  the  meanings.     Here  are  instances  of  various  kinds: 

^Cf.  B.  H.  Rowland:  The  Psychological  Experiences  connected  with  the 
Different  Parts  of  Speech,  Psych.  Rev.  Mon.  Suppl.  32,  1907,  25. 


566  JACOBSON 

With  F,  stimulus  to,  the  report  cited  on  p.  564  shows  that  the  preposi- 
tional meaning  is  at  first  carried  purely  in  visual  and  auditory  terms. 
Again,  with  stimulus  for,  a  report  runs:  Auditory  'for  me',  with  visual 
image  of  me  written  on  the  paper.  Slight  tendency  to  lean  forward; 
rather  pleasant.  Auditory  image:  What  for?  with  accent  on  the  for.  The 
for  became  very  clear. 

Again,  vision  may  be  mixed  with  kinaesthesis.  Observer  D.  Stimulus 
upon. — In  the  fore-period  I  had  visual-kinaesthetic  images  of  myself 
standing  on  a  pile  of  wood.  And  I  had  various  objects  given  more  kinaes- 
thetically  than  visually, — usually  adjusting  body  for  looking  from  one  to 
another. 

Similarly,  the  meaning  of  adverbs  may  be  given  visually,  auditorily 
or  kinaesthetically.  Observer  F.  Stimulus  heavily. — Visual  image  of  gray 
cube  of  iron  several  times  falling  on  floor  of  the  Audition  Room.  An  im- 
clear  auditory  image  of  the  noise.  Strains  in  ear-drum.  Organic  sensa- 
tions in  abdomen  such  as  are  involved  in  hearing  a  weight  dropped,  and 
such  images  as  one  would  get  from  a  jar  of  the  building.  Whole  experi- 
ence repeated  a  number  of  times,  not  quite  as  fast  as  I  uttered  the  word. 
Tendency  to  nod  head  sjmchronously  with  utterance:  meant  'heavily'. 

It  would  be  tedious  to  illustrate  this  point  with  reference 
to  adjectives,  substantives  and  verbs;  let  it  suffice  to  say  that 
with  these  as  with  the  other  parts  of  speech,  as  classes,  there 
appeared  no  characteristic  differentice  of  associations.^ — 

There  were  associations  reported  which  were  not  called 
'meanings'.     Thus,  G  reports  with  stimulus  cunning: 

Certain  verbal  processes  which  I  should  call  meanings,  and  certain 
others  which  I  should  not.  Belonging  to  the  last  class  was  'Cunningham, ' 
formed  by  adding  'ham'  to  what  was  being  said  aloud.  Then  visual 
image  of  a  ham.  Then  verbal  question:  What  is  cunning?  followed  by 
verbal  image  wise.  Verbal  question:  What  else?  then  vague  complex  of 
the  difficulty  I  should  have  in  writing  a  definition  of  cunning.  I  cannot 
analyse  this,  but  it  included  frowning  and  strains  in  neck. 

What,  now,  is  the  difference  between  these  two  kinds  of 
associates, — those  that  carry  the  meaning  of  the  stimulus- 
word  and  those  that  do  not?  The  question  may  be  answered 
from  two  points  of  view.  If  we  regard  the  associates  as  'pro- 
cesses', in  the  sense  of  §  2,  then  we  must  reply  that  the  mean- 
ing-associates proceed  from  the  instruction  given,  while  the 
not- meaning-associates  are  external  to  the  instruction;  the 
former  indicate  the  activity  of  a  particular  determining  ten- 
dency, the  latter  indicate  the  activity  of  reproductive  ten- 
dencies not  connected  with  this  determination.  If,  on  the 
other  hand,  we  regard  the  associates  as  themselves  'mean- 
ings', again  in  the  sense  of  §  2,  then  we  must  reply  that  the 
associates  which  carry  the  meaning  of  the  stimulus- word  are, 
as  independent  part-meanings,  logically  relevant  to  the  total 
word-meaning,  while  the  associates  which  do  not  carry  the 
meaning  of    the    word    are    as    independent  part-meanings 

^Thus,  we  found  nothing  that  could  warrant  such  a  generalisation  as 
Rowland  makes  in  the  case  of  adverbs:  op.  cit.,  27  ff. 


ON   MEANING  AND  UNDERSTANDING  567 

logically  irrelevant  to  the  total  word-meaning.  Both  of  these 
replies,  however,  require  qualifying  comment.  First,  the 
observer  is  not  (at  least,  in  our  experiments  was  not)  aware 
of  any  introspective  difference  between  the  processes  associated 
under  the  instruction,  and  the  external  associates, — between 
the  processes  which  carried  the  word-meaning  and  the  pro- 
cesses which  were  outside  of  that  meaning.  There  is  no 
modal  or  qualitative  difference;  there  is  no  special  'feel' 
of  'belonging'  to  the  instruction,  or  to  the  situation  in- 
duced by  it^;  simply,  the  observer  is  able,  on  question,  to 
point  to  certain  associated  processes  as  carrying  the  mean- 
ing of  the  word  and  to  certain  other  processes  as  not  involved 
in  the  word-meaning.  Secondly,  the  independent  part-mean- 
ings borne  by  the  associates  are  not  necessarily  their  obvious 
or  face-meanings ;  the  test  of  logical  relevancy  or  irrelevancy 
cannot,  any  more  than  the  test  of  procession  from  the  instruc- 
tion, be  applied  by  the  experimenter  on  behalf  of  the  observer; 
some  ingrained  habit  of  the  observer  in  regard  to  reproductive 
tendency,  or  the  disposition  into  which  he  is  brought  by  the 
present  situation,  may  give  all  manner  of  warps  and  twists  to 
the  part-meanings  carried  by  the  associates  as  such;  con- 
stituent processes,  which  appeal  to  the  experimenter  as  vehicles 
of  a  definite  part-meaning,  may  prove  to  be  extrinsic  to  mean- 
ing, may  (in  popular  phrase)  be  'ignored'  by  the  observer; 
and  constituent  processes  which  appeal  to  the  experimenter 
as  casual  may  turn  out  to  be,  for  the  part-meaning,  essential. 
In  every  case,  then,  we  are  forced  back  upon  the  distinctions 
drawn  by  the  observer;  there  is  no  criterion,  whether  psy- 
chological or  logical,  which  can  be  applied  by  the  experimenter 
in  default  of  the  observer's  specific  statement. 

If  we  seek  to  analyse  the  instance  given  above  (Observer  G,  Stimulus 
cunning),  we  reach  the  following  general  result.  First,  to  take  the  asso- 
ciates as  processes :  we  have  the  utterance  of  cunning  arousing,  by  mechan- 
ical sound-association  outside  of  the  instruction,  the  familiar  name  Cun- 
ningham (the  name  of  a  friend  and  colleague) ;  and  we  have  then  the  added 
member  -ham  (the  observer  himself  notes  the  'addition'  of  this  member) 
arousing,  still  outside  of  the  instruction,  the  image  of  a  ham.  Thereupon 
the  observer  harks  back  to  his  instruction:  and  his  return  is  effected, 
typically,  in  verbal  imagery.  'What  is  cunning?'  he  asks,  in  internal 
speech,  and  the  verbal  image  wise  appears,  issuing  from  the  instruction 
'Get  the  meaning.'  The  processes  Cunningham  and  ham  do  not  aid  in 
carrying  the  meaning  of  the  stimulus- word;  the  process  wise  does  so  aid. 

Secondly,  to  take  the  associates  as  meanings:  Cunningham  a.nd  ham 
have  their  own  independent  meanings,  irrelevant  to  the  meaning  of  the 
stimulus-word  cunning;  they  form  separate  constellations,  outside  of  the 

^It  should  be  said  that  the  observers  were  not  specially  questioned  upon 
this  point.  As  the  reports  stand,  however,  there  is  no  indication  of 
any  'feeling'  of  direction  or  of  guidance  or  of  any  regional  consciousness. 
The  instruction  itself  was  carried  in  the  usual  and  typical  ways;  we  do  not 
think  it  necessary  to  give  illustrations. 


568  JACOBSON 

instruction.     Wise,  on  the  contrary,  has  a  fringe  of  meaning  of  its  own, 
which  is  logically  relevant  to  the  meaning  of  cunning. 

We  have  chosen  this  instance  for  analysis,  because  it  is  unusually  simple; 
because  in  it  the  experimenter  can,  to  some  extent,  put  himself  in  the  ob- 
server's place,  and  see  the  'reason '  for  the  admission  of  some  associates  to 
the  rank  of  vehicles  of  word-meaning,  and  for  the  rejection  of  others.  But 
the  simplicity  of  the  instance  is  quite  unusual;  and,  for  that  matter,  we 
have  no  doubt  that  our  analysis,  undertaken  after  the  event  and  on  general 
psychological  principles  only,  is  far  from  complete. 

Although  the  observer  was  able,  v^ithout  hesitation,  to  make 
the  distinction  between  meaning-associates  and  associates 
that  had  no  share  in  the  meaning  of  the  stimulus-word,  the 
relation  of  the  meaning-associates  to  the  word-perception  was 
never  reported  as  a  specific  and  characteristic  conscious 
reference.  Special  questions  were  therefore  asked,  in  order 
to  determine  whether  such  a  specific  reference  came  to  con- 
sciousness. 

Observer  G.  Stimulus  cutting.  [Question,  following  report  on  p.  564: 
What  was  the  connection  in  consciousness?]  Simply  simultaneity.  There 
was  no  apperception  of  their  belonging  together ;  in  fact  they  did  not  occur 
at  the  same  place,  as  the  kinaesthetic  motor  tendency  was  in  the  right  hand 
and  the  faint  visual  image  was  here  [indicating  a  certain  place  on  the 
table  toward  which  the  eye  moved  and  where  the  imaged  hand  had  not  been]. 
[Was  there  any  conscious  connection  between  the  visual  image  and  the 
word,  i.  e.,  the  sound  and  sight  of  it?]     No. 

Observer  G.  Stimulus  Roosevelt.  .  .  .  Vague  visual  image,  a  circle  with 
three  lines  in  it.  [What  connection  had  the  circle  with  Roosevelt?]  That 
is  the  visual  image  I  have  from  caricatures  of  Roosevelt,  the  circle  meaning 
his  head,  the  lines  his  teeth,  [What  connection  was  there  consciously 
between  the  circle  and  Roosevelt?]  I  don't  know  what  you  mean  by 
connection;  the  only  connection  I  see  is  that  they  came  simultaneously  or 
successively. 

Observer  D.  Stimulus  face.  The  observer  reports  visual  image  of  a 
mask  and  slight  eye  and  head  movements  as  if  to  look  at  it.  [What  was 
the  conscious  relation  of  that  mask  to  the  visual-auditory-kinsesthetic 
impressions  from  the  word?]  It  did  not  have  any;  I  did  not  consciously 
refer  it  to  what  I  was  seeing  at  all. 

Observer  J.  Stimulus  was  a  proper  name,  and  verbal  imagery  'the  ex- 
perimental psychologist'  had  been  reported.  Observer  adds:  I  cannot 
answer  the  question  whether  there  was  any  conscious  connection  between 
the  sensations  from  enunciation  and  this  verbal  image.  The  question 
seems  strange. 

[Instruction  was  given  to  repeat.]  The  images  came  as  before,  but 
more  vaguely.  ...  I  found  a  certain  conscious  spatial  relationship,  namely, 
the  visual  image  appeared  close  to  the  word  seen;  but  I  was  not  able  to 
ascertain  whether  there  were  other  conscious  relationships. 

We  are  thus  led  to  the  conclusion,  indicated  in  a  previous 
paragraph,  that  the  conscious  'meanings'  brought  out  in  these 
experiments  are  not  the  perfect  and  static  logical  meanings  of 
definition,  but  rather  partial  meanings,  particular  exemplifi- 
cations, or  what  not,  touched  off  under  the  given  instruction 
by  the  habit  or  the  momentary  disposition  of  the  observer. 
Logically,  the  representation  of  meaning  is  inadequate;  psy- 


ON  MEANING   AND   UNDERSTANDING  569 

chologicaliy,  it  is  adequate  to  the  demands  of  the  occasion. 
We  may  add  that,  especially  at  the  beginning  of  the  work, 
the  observers  often  showed  a  tendency  to  verbalise  a  defini- 
tion of  the  stimulus-word,  and  thus  to  meet  the  situation  with 
logical  as  well  as  with  psychological  adequacy.^ 

§   4.    The    Understanding    of    Sentences 

In  this  part  of  our  study,  the  stimuli  were  simple  sentences, 
type-written.  These  were  laid  before  the  observer,  who  was 
instructed  to  open  his  eyes  upon  a  signal;  to  read  and  under- 
stand the  sentence  before  him;  and  then  to  close  his  eyes  and 
recount  his  experience. 

We  shall  outline  the  results  from  each  one  of  the  observers. 

Observer  D.  Stimulus  Her  dress  was  white.  Time  2.5  sec. — (After  the 
ready  signal)  sensations  of  kinaesthesis  and  strain  in  head  and  neck  region. 
Simultaneous  awareness  (of  the  Aufgabe,  and  determination  to  get  full 
meaning);  a  special  set  of  strain  and  other  organic  sensations  belongs  to 
this. 

(Then  signal  Now,  and  opened  eyes.)  Kor  a  moment  dazed  feeling  and 
blurry  sensations  (from  incomplete  fixation)  of  light  on  dark. 

Then  a  kinaesthetic  dart  or  snap  in  head  and  (sentence)  was  visually 
clear.  [Later  question:  Describe  this  dart  or  snap.  'In  top  of  head  and 
around  eyes'.     In  scalp?     'No;  inside  head'.] 

Then  vague  kinaesthetic  sensations  in  throat  and  indefinite  auditory 
images  (accompanied  by  automatic  reading  of  sentence). 

Then  mixed-up  feeling,  unpleasant;  sensations  of  nausea  and  (of 
inhibited  breathing),  (all  this  meaning:  I  don't  know  what  I  am  to  do). 
The  whole  field  of  vision  was  obscure. 

Then  (rapid  eye-movement);  quite  definite  kinaesthetic  sensations, 
but  hard  to  describe.     Mixed-up  feeling  continues. 

Then  visual  image  (of  myself  in  a  particular  white  dress).  Image  was 
very  small  and  very  indistinct,  and  the  kinaesthetic  accompaniments  were 
more  prominent  than  the  visual.     (Definitely  localised  to  the  left.) 

Then  feeling  of  doubt ;  (again  rapid  eye-movement) ;  muddle  of  organic 
sensations  and  unpleasantness.     (Signifying:  Is  this  the  meaning?) 

Then  feeling  of  relief;  (general  relaxation);  totally  different  set  of  or- 
ganic sensations  from  above.  Pleasant.  Kinaesthetic  sensations  in  throat 
(meant  assurance  that  I  had  the  meaning). 

This  report  is  typical,  in  so  far  that  D  always  records  the 
automatic  reading  before  she  gets  the  meaning  of  the  sentence. 
It  is  typical  of  about  one-half  of  her  reports,  in  that  it  shows 
her  doubt  whether  she  shall  identify  the  associated  ideas, 
aroused  by  the  stimulus,  with  its  meaning.     It   is  apparent 

^Since  the  experiments  here  reported  were  concluded,  the  writer  has 
found  that,  if  he  reads  any  particular  word  upon  a  printed  sheet  (looks 
at  the  word,  and  gets  a  kinaesthetic-auditory  repetition  of  it),  there  is 
usually  attached  to  it  a  thin  coat  of  meaning  which  distinguishes  it  from 
other  words  similarly  read,  though  there  is  a  total  absence  of  recognisable 
associations.  Save  for  two  or  three  possible  instances,  whose  interpreta- 
tion is  not  clear,  such  direct  or  incorporated  meaning  did  not  appear  in  the 
experiments  of  this  Section.  On  the  general  question,  see  Titchener, 
Thought-processes,  1909,  177. 


570  JACOB SON 

that  she  finally  does  thus  identify,  after  finding  that  nothing 
else  occurs  which  can  be  termed  meaning.  The  following 
excerpts  from  other  reports  illustrate  this  point : 

D.  It  is  very  warm  in  this  room.  Kinaesthetic  sensations  in  throat 
plus  auditory  images  (of  words).     (Read  the  line.) 

Then  a  curious  feeling,  largely  organic  sensations  of  general  laziness, 
pleasant  warmth,  drowsiness,  and  kinaesthetic  sensations  (chiefly  of  eye- 
movement  and  strains  in  head  that  meant  my  Office,  where  I  had  ten 
minutes  ago  been  very  warm).  [The  observer  reports  that  here  was  the 
meaning  of  the  stimulus  sentence.] 

D.  Let  him  bring  a  glass  of  water.  .  .  .  Then  feeling  (of  relief),  that  is, 
mild  pleasantness  and  less  strain  in  head  and  different  organic  sensations  in 
region  of  diaphragm.  Verbal  kinaesthetic  idea  (meaning  I  don't  have  to 
do  or  say  anything  to  get  the  meaning;  I  just  know  I  understand  it).  At 
same  time  there  was  some  kinaesthesis  (from  eye-movement?)  (that  con- 
stituted meaning  of  sentence). 

Then  and  slightly  overlapping  the  above,  very  vague  schematic  visual 
image  (of  some  man  in  tha  laboratory,  I  don't  know  who,  standing  at  sink 
and  holding  a  glass  before  the  running  water).     All  this  was  just  in  grays. 

Then  verbal  kinaesthetic  idea  (Perhaps  this  has  something  to  do  with  the 
meaning). 

D.  She  came  in  secretly.  .  .  .  Then  slight  kinaesthesis  (from  automatic 
reading  of  the  sentence).  At  last  word  kinaesthesis  (accompanied  by 
sudden  eye-movement  or  Winking).  (After  this  did  not  fixate  paper.) 
[Later  question:  Was  the  meaning  of  the  sentence  present  here?  'No.' 
Did  you  perceive  the  words  or  sentence?  'Yes;  but  secretly  is  the  only 
word  I  perceived  very  clearly.'] 

Then  a  visual  image,  vague  and  schematic  (of  a  girl  who  was  some- 
times myself  and  sometimes  Miss  X  walking  on  tiptoe  into  my  Office). 
At  the  same  time  organic  and  kinaesthetic  sensations  (as  if  I  were  going 
through  that  performance),  namely,  respiratory  sensations  (from  repressed 
breathing),  general  kinaesthesis  (from  slight  tremor  of  whole  body),  ar- 
ticulatory  sensations,  kinaesthetic  sensations  (from  walking  on  tiptoe), 
and  contact  sensations  in  arms  and  hand  (from  touching  sides  of  doorway 
as  I  entered).  All  this  organic  and  kinaesthetic  complex  was  the  clearest 
thing  in  consciousness.  There  were  quick  alternations  of  pleasant  and 
unpleasant  feelings  accompanied  by  kinaesthesis  which  I  can't  analyse  now, 
though  it  was  definite  at  the  time. 

Then  feeling  (of  assurance)  in  terms  of  respiratory  sensations  (from 
rather  deep  and  free  breathing),  and  a  certain  kinaesthetic  complex  (from 
eye-movement,  meaning  that  this  attitude  of  walking  in  secretly  conveyed 
the  meaning  of  the  sentence.) 

Next  we  give  a  sample  of  G's  reports.  It  will  be  seen  that 
there  is  a  very  full  description  of  processes.  The  reader  is 
requested  to  attempt,  as  he  goes  through  the  report,  definitely 
to  decide  at  what  point,  if  at  all,  the  meaning  of  the  sentence 
was  realised. 

Observer  G.  Stimulus  Did  you  see  him  kill  the  man  ?  Time  3  sec. — 
Auditory  perception  (of  word  Ready).  Simultaneous  unpleasant  strain 
and  tactual  sensations  (from  hands  on  face  and  general  position). 

Then  a  pinkish  grayish  limitless  visual  perception  (of  the  field  of  the 
closed  eyelids)  accompanied  by  vague  kinaesthetic  strain  in  region  of  eyes 
and  in  eyes. 

Then  auditory  perception  (of  Now).  Faint  verbal  idea  (meaning  What 
a  difference  in  intensity  between  the  Now  and  the  Ready) !    The  opening 


ON   MEANING   AND   UNDERSTANDING  57 1 

of  the  eyes  is  accompanied  by  a  succession  of  blurs,  partly  gradual,  partly 
sudden,  with  vague  strains  from  the  front  part  of  the  eyes  themselves.  At 
the  same  time  recognition  (of  the  white  strip)  with  indefinite  indistinct  out- 
Hnes,  and  with  similarly  indefinite  blue  sensations  strung  along  a  horizontal 
line  in  center  of  the  white  area. 

Then  faint  strains  (from  fixation  of  blue  complex)  accompanied  by 
verbal  ideas  of  articulation. 

Then  (new  fixation)  and  repetition  of  these  ideas.  Background  of 
consciousness  almost  zero. 

After  the  perception  (of  the  last  word)  a  sudden  rise  of  all  sorts  of  or- 
ganic, kinaesthetic  and  tactual  sensations  localised  in  abdominal  region, 
mouth  region,  elbow,  and  facial  areas  touched  by  hand,  together  with  a 
new  visual  perception.  [Later  question:  Of  what?  'Of  objects  on  table, 
eyes  being  open'.] 

Followed  by  verbal  idea  (What  is  it?) 

Then  a  general,  organic  and  respiratory,  conscious  attitude  (of  relief). 
(No  meaning  all  the  way  through.) 

It  is  certain,  if  we  may  trust  our  own  experience,  that  the 
reader  who  tried  to  discover  the  point  at  which  a  meaning 
might  have  been  realised  failed  in  the  attempt;  and  the 
failure  emphasizes  the  difference  that  we  have  drawn  between 
report  of  'meanings'  and  report  of  'processes'.  Or,  to  put  the 
matter  differently:  If  the  observer  had  omitted  the  informa- 
tion *No  meaning',  and  had  challenged  the  experimenter  or  any 
one  else  to  state  when  (if  at  all)  the  meaning  of  the  sentence 
was  realised,  and  what  this  particular  meaning  was,  the  per- 
son thus  challenged  would  have  found  it  impossible  to  infer 
the  meaning  from  the  description  given  of  the  corresponding 
processes.  Information  about  meanings  as  well  as  descrip- 
tion of  processes — we  have  made  the  point  before,  and  we 
shall  recur  to  it  again — must  come  always  from  the  observer 
himself. — 

There  are  five  other  cases  in  which  no  meaning  is  reached. 
Sometimes  meaningless  reading  is  followed  by  the  meaning. 
Thus: 

Observer  G.  Stimulus  The  iron  cube  fell  heavily  on  the  floor.  Time 
4.5  sec. — Visual  perception  (of  words)  accompanied  by  imaginal  and 
articulatory  processes  (of  reading).  The  first  perception  (of  the  third 
word)  was  vague;  (in  fact,  it  was  not  a  word  but  a  blot).  It  became  a 
word  as  soon  as  certain  parts  (of  the  blot)  stood  out  more  clearly  and  were 
verbalised.  (The  rest  of  the  sentence  was  first  perceived  as  meaningless 
words,  tiien  re-read)  with  strong  motor  tendencies  around  the  eyes  (mean- 
ing attempt  to  see  an  iron  cube  fall  down  from  the  table.)  The  perception 
(of  the  word  Floor)  was  accompanied  by  a  faint  auditory  image  (meaning 
a  very  loud  sound).     (Then  closed  eyes.) 

In  yet  other  cases  the  meaning  comes  simultaneously  with 
the  perception  of  the  words,  and  is  carried  by  non-verbal 
images  or  sensations.  We  may  therefore  say  that  (save  for 
one  instance,  which  resembles  the  three  peculiar  reports  of  F 
to  be  discussed  below)  the  reports  of  G  are  like  those  of  D ; 
the  perception  of  the  words,  that  is,  visual  sensations  accom- 


572  JACOBSON 

panied  by  designatory  processes,  does  not  necessarily  involve 
awareness  of  the  meaning  of  the  sentence,  which  either  ( i )  comes 
in  terms  of  non-verbal  images  or  sensations,  appearing  simul- 
taneously or  later,  or  (2)  does  not  come  at  all. 

The  reports  of  F  show  two  types:  in  the  one,  perception 
of  the  words  or  of  the  sentence  precedes  the  meaning,  which 
finally  appears  in  terms  of  non-verbal  images  or  sensations; 
in  the  other,  these  meaning-associates  occur  simultaneously 
with  the  perception.  There  are,  however,  three  reports  which 
stand  by  themselves.     We  give  two  of  them,  in  part: 

F.  It  is  very  warm  in  this  room.  2  sec. — Purple  sensations  (from  words) 
clear.  White  sensation  (from  paper)  and  black  (from  background)  in 
background  of  consciousness.  Also  very  weak  strain  sensations  in  chest, 
in  background,  which  remained  comparatively  constant  in  intensity 
while  I  was  reading.  Simultaneously  with  the  reading,  auditory  images 
(of  the  words).  (Strain  sensations  mean:  I  am  under  Aufgabe  to  read 
and  interpret  and  not  to  waste  too  much  time.  Visual  sensations  plus 
auditory  images  carried  in  themselves  the  meaning  of  the  sentence.) 

F.  The  affair  was  bewildering,  i  sec. — White  and  black  sensations 
(from  paper  and  background)  in  background  of  consciousness.  Simulta- 
neous with  the  visual  clearing  of  each  word,  auditory  images.  (The  mean- 
ing of  the  sentence  was  in  the  auditory  images  and  visual  sensations 
themselves.     No  other  context  to  carry  the  meaning  tJmt  I  can  find.) 

If  we  may  assume  that  F  has  not  overlooked  something, 
we  have  the  result  (confirmed  by  a  single  case  from  G)  that 
the  visual  and  auditory  images  and  sensations  from  reading 
might  be  the  sole  processes  present  in  consciousness,  while  yet 
the  sentence  had  meaning.^ 

We  turn  now  from  'processes'  to  'meanings'.  And  we  note 
that  it  is  not  enough  for  the  observer  to  make  the  bare  state- 
ment that  he  did,  or  did  not,  understand  the  sentence.  For 
oftentimes,  at  the  moment  of  understanding,  the  sentence 
has  a  special  or  peculiar  meaning. 

An  illustration  has  been  given  in  the  report  on  p.  557.     Another  follows. 

F.  His  face  was  very  serious.  .  .  .  (Read  the  sentence  over  again),  that  is, 
visual  sensations  and  auditory  images  as  before,  except  at  a  slower  speed. 
Accompanied  by  kinaesthetic  sensations  in  face  (from  frowning)  and,  I 
think,  sensations  or  images  from  (slight  nods  of  head  towards  the  words, 
for  emphasis).  (Determined  effort  to  see  what  the  sentence  meant. 
Meaning  clear  this  time.)  [Question:  What  was  that  meaning?  The 
answer  came  with  conviction  and  immediately.]     {My  face  is  very  serious.) 

^Cf.  p.  569.  The  writer  finds  that  he  can  converse  or  think  in  words 
or  in  incipient  verbal  articulations,  with  the  meaning  present,  while  for 
considerable  periods  of  time  he  can  discern  no  vestige  of  sensations  or 
images  other  than  those  from  the  words  themselves.  There  are,  in  the 
background,  sensations  due  to  bodily  position  and  to  general  set;  but 
while  it  is  introspectively  clear  that  these  play  an  important  part  in  the 
whole  experience,  they  do  not  seem  to  vary  correspondingly  with  the  verbal 
meanings,  as  the  conversation  proceeds  or  the  thought  goes  on. 

Our  results  do  not  tell  us  what  is  the  difference,  if  any,  between  the 
processes  occurring  in  these  cases  and  in  those  of  meaningless  reading  of 
the  sentence. 


ON   MEANING   AND   UNDERSTANDING  573 

So  in  the  case  of  G:  two  reports  obtained  from  the  same  sentence  Her 

dress  was  white  show  that  on  the  one  occasion  her  referred  to  a  particular 
person,  on  the  other  to  nobody  in  particular. 

The  Single  Word  and  the  Word  in  Context. — Every  sentence  employed 
as  stimulus  in  these  experiments  contained,  in  a  prominent  place,  one  of 
the  words  that  had  been  employed  singly  in  the  experiments  of  §  3. 
Several  months  intervened  between  the  two  sets  of  experiments;  and  we 
have  no  reason  to  suppose  that  the  repetition  was  remarked  by  any  of 
our  observers.  Our  object  was  to  compare  the  meaning  of  a  word  presented 
singly  with  the  meaning  of  the  same  word  given  in  a  verbal  context.  The 
conditions  of  the  two  sets  of  experiments  were  by  no  means  parallel; 
still,  certain  results  appear  to  be  trustworthy. 

There  are  a  few  cases  in  which  the  associates  of  the  single  word  recur 
(usually  with  some  alteration  of  form)  in  the  cluster  of  associates  aroused 
by  the  sentence.  Thus,  in  both  experiments  a  proper  name  calls  up,  for 
one  observer,  a  visual  image  of  the  same  person;  'process'  and  'meaning' 
are  identical  in  the  two  reports.  In  another  instance,  the  word  face  has 
the  same  reported  meaning  under  both  conditions,  though  the  'process' 
appears  in  the  one  experiment  as  a  visual  image,  in  the  other  as  a  kinaes- 
thetic  complex. 

In  the  great  majority  of  cases,  however,  the  associations  traceable  to 
the  word  in  context  are  not  those  previously  aroused  by  it  in  isolation. 
This  result  harmonises  with  the  statement  made  on  p.  564  regarding  the 
variable  character  of  meaningful  associations.  The  word-in-sentence  is 
not  a  separate  stimulus,  but  merely  a  constituent  of  a  total  stimulus,  which 
is  the  sentence;  as  constituent  of  the  total  stimulus  it  may,  of  course,  set 
up  determining  tendencies  in  the  sense  of  its  own  meaning;  but  this 
meaning  is  now  only  a  phase  of  the  total  meaning  of  the  sentence, 
a  meaning  of  incorporation  or  of  implication;  and  it  is  therefore  impossible 
to  predict,  from  the  report  on  the  single  word,  how  the  meaning  of  the 
word-in-sentence  shall  appear  in  consciousness.  G  reports,  with  the 
stimulus  heavily,  'Meaning  was  mostly  kinaesthetic,  and  secondarily  or- 
ganic' With  the  stimulus-sentence  The  iron  cube  fell  heavily  on  the  floor, 
this  mode  of  meaning  has  lapsed;  the  effect  of  the  word  heavily  shows  only 
in  the  'faint  auditory  image  (meaning  a  very  loud  sound').  We  may  refer 
also  to  the  reports  of  D  on  secretly  and  She  came  in  secretly  (pp.  563,  570), 
which  illustrate  the  same  point.  The  difference  was  especially  marked 
in  the  case  of  prepositions:  taken  alone,  these  words  tended  to  form  a 
context  of  their  own,  verbal  or  attitudinal  (by  gesture) ;  occurring  in  a 
sentence,  they  simply  colored  the  meaning  of  the  total  stimulus. — Cf. 
the  remarks  of  H.  M.  Clarke,  this  Journal,  xxii.,  1911,  236  ff. 

Summary,  i.  The  meaning  of  a  sentence  is  often  entirely- 
lacking  at  the  first  reading,  i.  e.  the  initial  perception  of  it, 
and  appears  later,  borne  by  processes  representative  of  its 
content  or  of  some  response  to  that  content  made  by  the 
observer. 

2.  Sometimes  these  representative  processes  come  with  the 
initial  perception,  and  the  sentence  at  once  has  meaning; 
sometimes  they  seem  to  be  absent,  while  the  meaning  neverthe- 
less arises. 

3.  The  same  stimulus-sentence  may  give  rise  to  different 
meanings  for  the  same  observer,  so  that  it  is  not  enough  for 
him  to  say  that  he  understood  it ;  he  must  be  asked  to  specify 
precisely  what  he  understood. 

Journal — 7 


574  jacobson 

§  5.     In  Repi^y  to  Criticism. 

The  discussion  of  Imageless  Thought  has  led,  time  and  again, 
to  personal  exchanges  of  regrettable  warmth.  Yet  the  issue 
is,  after  all,  an  issue  of  fact ;  it  is  the  observations  that  coimt, 
and  not  the  thrusts  of  controversy.  When,  for  instance, 
Dr.  Watt  suggests  that  an  observation  made  in  the  Wiirzburg 
laboratory  is  eo  ipso  more  dependable  than  an  observation 
taken  in  the  Cornell  laboratory  ;^  when,  forgetting  the  genesis  of 
his  own  Theory  of  Thinking,  he  belittles  the  work  of  graduate 
students  ;2  when  Professor  Ogden  charges  that  Okabe's  analyses 
of  Belief  ' '  would  apply  equally  well  to  a  description  of  the 
aesthetic  attitude,  the  ethical  attitude,  the  consciousness  of 
understanding,  or  indeed  any  other  of  the  higher  apperceptive 
states  of  mind;"^  when  he  remarks  that  Clarke's  conscious 
attitudes  are  "unblushingly"  analysed  into  sensory  and  im- 
aginal  components;*  when  he  declares  that  the  method  of 
confrontation  is  "quite  a  perfunctory  affair"  and  leads  to  an 
"equivocal  result;"^  when  he  cleverly  dubs  the  sensation- 
alistic  school  'the  opposition',  and  thus  puts  the  champions  of 
imageless  contents  into  the  secure  position  of  governmental 
orthodoxy:^ — in  all  these,  and  in  many  similar  instances,  the 
polemics  simply  mean  "I  refuse  to  accept  your  results."  Or 
perhaps,  since  the  phrases  are  polemical,  they  may  carry  the 
further  meaning,  "although  I  can't  explain  them  away;" 
for  emotion  is  likely  to  appear  when  argument  has  broken 
down. 

Let  these  things  pass,  then,  and  let  us  come  to  close  quarters 
with  Professor  Ogden's  criticism.  This  is,  in  a  nutshell,  that 
Cornell  observers  have  been  predisposed  against  "the  discovery 
of  meanings  in  experience",  and  have  therefore  confined  their 
introspections  to  the  "known  mental  categories  of  sensation, 
image  and  feeling  in  which  [they]  have  been  schooled."  The 
best  reply  to  the  first  of  these  statements  is  the  fact  of  the 
present  paper.  Professor  Ogden's  critique  appeared  on  June 
15,  1911;  and,  by  that  date,  the  experiments  by  our  'method 
of  parentheses'  had  been  concluded.  It  is  true  that  previous 
Cornell  experimenters  have  intentionally  neglected  meanings, 
in  the  sense  of  this  term  used  in  the  present  paper.  But,  so  far 
from  having  a  predisposition  against  meanings,  we  have  in 
the  present  work  made  a  systematic  attempt  to  cultivate 
reports  about  them.     And  we  reach  a  result  which  does  not 

*Mind,  XX.,  191 1,  403. 

^Ihid.,  403  f. 

'Psychol.  Bulletin,  viii.,  191 1,  194. 

*Ihid. 

Hbid. 

Ubid.,  186  f. 


ON  MEANING  AND  UNDERSTANDING         575 

accord  with  Professor  Ogden's  views:  we  find  that  wherever 
there  is  meaning  there  are  also  processes,  and  we  find  that  the 
correlated  meanings  and  processes  are  two  renderings,  from 
different  points  of  view,  of  one  and  the  same  experience. 

We  have  already  stated  that  it  is  frequently  no  easy  matter  to  give  a 
detailed  account  both  of  attributes  of  process  and  of  shades  of  meaning, 
the  beginner  who  is  set  for  the  report  of  meanings  will  be  likely  to  over- 
look the  corresponding  processes,  and  conversely,  just  as,  if  he  is  set  for 
the  report  of  the  quality  of  a  sensation,  he  will  be  likely  to  overlook  the 
correlated  sensory  intensity,  and  conversely.  To  be  sure,  after  considera- 
ble practice  it  becomes  tolerably  easy  to  report  the  principal  features  of 
the  double  task,  but  even  then  omissions  sometimes  occur. 

But  it  must  be  remembered  that  the  danger  of  defect  is  two-sided;  it 
inheres  in  either  mode  of  predisposition.  When  Professor  Ogden  writes: 
"It  is  precisely  in  the  brief  moments  of  active  thinking  that  the  thought- 
factor  is  most  apparent"  {op.  cit.,  187),  he  lays  himself  open  to  the  very 
objection  that  he  is  urging  against  his  opponents.  If  by  the  thought- 
factor  is  meant  the  meaning,  the  topic  or  object  of  thought,  that  must,  in 
the  very  nature  of  things,  be  most  apparent  under  the  conditions  of  quick 
active  thinking;  and,  again  in  the  nature  of  things,  the  corresponding 
processes  must,  under  such  circumstances,  be  least  apparent;  the  observer 
is  set  for  meaning, — and  even  if  the  instruction  is  changed,  and  he  is  later 
set  for  the  reporting  of  processes,  the  brevity  of  the  experience  will  work 
against  him.  But  there  is  absolutely  nothing  in  the  case  to  compel  our 
belief  that  meaning  without  process  exhausts  the  experience,  that  process  is 
altogether  absent. 

A  like  reply  might  be  made  to  the  complaint  of  Professor  Ogden's  col- 
league {op.  cit.,  193).  If  the  relatively  untrained  observers  gave  plentiful 
meanings  in  their  original  reports,  and  failed  to  specify  processes,  that  is 
because  they  had  not  been  taught  to  distinguish  between  process  and  mean- 
ing and  to  report  on  the  former  as  well  as  on  the  latter.  If  the  trained 
observers  of  the  later  work  gave  nothing  but  sensations  and  images  and 
feelings,  that  is  because  they  had  been  taught  to  observe  processes,  and 
the  experimenter  did  not  demand  of  them  the  statement  of  meanings.  Our 
experience  shows  conclusively  that  observers  who  have  had  a  long  training 
in  process-report  are  able,  after  training,  to  parallel  the  processes  by 
meanings. 

And  the  same  reply,  once  more,  invalidates  Professor  Ogden's  dis- 
covery of  imageless  thought  in  the  quoted  report  of  our  observer  F  {op.  cit., 
195).  "Red  :  blue  ::  green  :  yellow.  I  started  to  say  this  automati- 
cally. Then  I  repeated  the  stimulus  and  said  'intermediate'  verbally. 
Some  kind  of  consciousness  that  meant  'principal  colors.'  I  did  not  say 
'principal'."  Rewritten  in  terms  of  our  method  of  parentheses,  the  last 
sentences  would  be:  "Some  kind  of  consciousness  (that  meant  principal 
colors.)  I  did  not  say  principal".  F  found  a  meaning  present,  the  mean- 
ing of  principal  colors;  and  he  found  also  a  corresponding  process,  about 
which,  however,  he  could  say  nothing  more  than  that  it  was  not  a  kinaes- 
thetic-auditory  verbal  image. 

As  to  the  second  member  of  Professor  Ogden's  criticism, 
that  Cornell  observers  have  confined  their  reports  to  the  de- 
scription of  sensations,  images,  feelings,  and  like  familiar  modes, 
and  have  failed  to  find  a  new  process  (if  we  use  this  term  again 
in  our  present  sense), — we  must  admit  the  fact.  But  Professor 
Ogden  has,  nevertheless,  confused  the  deed  of  this  non-dis- 
covery   with  the  will.     The  observers  did  not,  it  is   true, 


576  JACOBSON 

report  on  'meanings'  as  well  as  on  'processes,*  in  the  sense  of 
the  present  study;  for  this  is,  we  believe,  the  first  instance  of 
the  intentional  and  systematic  assignment  of  the  double  task 
in  any  laboratory.  They  did,  however,  have  the  Aufgabe  to 
report  all  the  processes  that  were  present  in  their  experiences. 
Thus,  Okabe  writes:  ''No  hint  was  given  that  certain  processes 
were  wanted  or  expected  by  the  experimenter,  and  no  limit  was 
set  to  the  observer's  vocabulary.''  "  It  seems  especially  important 
to  note  that  G  finds  no  trace  of  imageless  contents,  since  he 
is  precisely  of  what  has  been  described  as  the  imageless  type."^ 
Can  the  critic  have  overlooked  these  and  similar  passages? 
The  aim  of  Clarke's  study  of  Conscious  Attitudes  was  to 
"bring  these  experiences  to  the  test  of  introspective  observa- 
tion, and  thus  to  discover  whether  or  not  they  are  analy sable." 
"The  introspections  of  any  one  observer  show  different  stages 
of  clearness  and  intensity  of  imagery,  which  allow  us  to  connect, 
by  a  graded  series  of  intermediate  steps,  a  complex  of  vivid  and 
explicit  imagery  with  a  vague  and  condensed  consciousness 
which  we  suppose  to  represent  what  is  called  'imageless 
thought '."2  Has  the  critic  again  read  a  little  hastily? — 
Let  us  make  the  rejoinder  concrete.  Suppose  that  you  are 
told :  * '  Here  is  a  pile  of  coins,  of  various  denominations,  some 
of  which  are  American,  some  English,  some  French.  Sort 
the  coins  out,  both  by  country  and  by  denomination.  We 
are  informed  that  there  are  also  German  coins  in  the  pile. 
Keep  an  eye  especially  keenly  on  this  possibility."  You  sort, 
and  you  find  nothing  but  American,  EngUsh  and  French 
pieces.  And  your  conclusion  is  summarily  rejected,  on  the 
ground  that  you  have  had  special  training  in  the  identification  and 
discrimination  of  American,  English  and  French  money! 

A  final  word  on  Biihler  and  his  thought-elements.  "I 
was  fortunate  enough,"says  Biihler,  "to  find  two  experienced 
psychologists  who  put  themselves  at  my  disposal  for  the  ex- 
periments. .  .  In  the  present  paper.  .  .  I  shall  refer  always 
and  only  to  the  observations  of  Kiilpe  and  Diirr.  .  .  The 
experimenter  must  feel  himself  into  the  position  of  his  obser- 
vers, must  experience  with  them,  if  he  is  properly  to  understand 
them;  he  must  be  able  to  go  into  their  peculiarities,  and  to 
speak  with  them  in  their  own  language."^  Biihler,  then, 
sought  to  feel  himself  into  the  position  of  his  two  observers; 
and,  as  regards  the  one  of  them,  Diirr,  the  attempt — as  Diirr 
has  himself  written — was  unsuccessful.  Biihler's  thought- 
element  rests,  therefore,  upon  his  interpretation  of  Kiilpe's 
reports.     And  Professor  Ogden  now  tells  us  that  it  occurred 


^This  Journal,  xxi.,  1910,  563,  567,  593. 

2This  Journal,  xxii.,  191 1,  215,  248. 

^Arch.  f.  d.  ges.  Psychol.,  ix.,  1907,  306,  309. 


1 


ON   MEANING   AND   UNDERSTANDING  577 

to  Kiilpe,  while  lecturing  on  Leibniz,  "that  the  monads  were 
not  'concepts'  but  thoughts;'*  here,  still  according  to  Professor 
Ogden,  is  Kiilpe's  first  idea  "regarding  the  character  of  thought 
as  a  distinct  mental  element."^  But  was  not  Kiilpe,  then, — 
to  borrow  a  word  of  Professor  Ogden 's — predisposed  to  the 
discovery  of  the  thought-element? 

We  greatly  regret  that  we  have  been  unable  to  compare 
our  results,  in  detail,  with  those  of  former  workers  in  the 
same  field.  Limits  of  space  forbid;  as  they  forbid,  also,  a 
further  exploitation,  at  this  time,  of  our  observers'  reports. 

^Op.  cit.,  185. 


MINOR  STUDIES  FROM  THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL 

LABORATORY  OF  VASSAR  COLLEGE 
XVI.    Thh  Effect  of  Area  on  the  Pleasantness  of  Colors 


By  Dorothy  Clark,  Mary  S.  Goodell,  and  M.  F.  Washburn 


The  arrangement  of  apparatus  in  the  experiments  to  be  described  was 
as  follows.  Two  sets  of  colored  paper  squares  were  provided,  one  set 
being  5  cm.  a  side,  the  other  25  cm.  a  side.  The  small  squares  were  pasted, 
the  large  ones  fastened  with  small  wire  clips,  to  cardboard  squares  of 
the  same  size  as  the  paper,  in  order  to  give  them  stiffness.  The  colors 
used  were  from  the  Bradley  series  and  comprised  the  following:  saturated 
violet,  blue,  green,  yellow,  orange,  and  red,  with  the  lighter  tint  and  the 
darker  shade  of  each.  For  every  color  there  were  two  squares,  a  larger 
and  a  smaller  one.  In  performing  an  experiment  one  of  the  colored  squares 
was  suspended  by  means  of  wire  so  that  it  was  seen  against  a  background 
of  the  gray  laboratory  wall  about  a  meter  and  a  half  away,  and  the  observer 
sat  at  a  distance  of  one  and  a  half  meters  from  the  square,  which  was  hung 
at  about  the  level  of  her  eyes.  This  arrangement  was  suggested  by  Dr. 
E.  Murray  as  being  likely,  by  rendering  the  background  indefinite,  to 
lessen  its  influence.  The  observer  at  a  signal  looked  at  the  colored  square 
for  ten  seconds  and  recorded  her  judgment  of  its  pleasantness  or  unpleasant- 
ness in  numerical  terms,  using  the  numbers  i  to  7  to  indicate  the  following 
affective  grades:  very  unpleasant,  moderately  unpleasant,  slightly  un- 
pleasant, indifferent,  slightly  pleasant,  moderately  pleasant,  very  pleasant. 
The  colors  were  shown  in  irregular  order,  which  was,  however,  kept  constant 
for  all  observers.  A  large  and  a  small  square  of  the  same  color  were  never 
shown  in  immediate  succession,  as  our  object  was  to  obtain  independent 
judgments  of  the  affective  value  of  each  square,  not  comparisons  of  one  with 
another.  Nearly  all  of  the  observations  were  taken  upon  bright  days. 
The  observers  were  twenty-three  in  number,  all  women  and  all  but  three 
college  students. 

The  results  were  treated  in  two  ways.  First,  the  number  of  observers 
who  assigned  a  higher  affective  value  to  the  larger  area  of  each  color  was 
counted  and  compared  with  the  number  of  those  who  assigned  a  lower  value 
to  the  larger  area.  This  method  took  no  account  of  the  degree  of  the  pref- 
erence, that  is,  of  how  much  greater,  numerically  expressed,  the  observer's 
estimate  was  of  the  pleasantness  of  one  area  as  compared  with  that  of  the 
other.  The  following  conclusions  were  drawn  from  this  method  of  con- 
sidering the  results.  Among  saturated  colors,  red  was  the  only  one  which 
the  majority  of  the  observers  preferred  in  large  rather  than  in  small  area. 
All  the  others  were  preferred  by  more  observers  in  the  smaller  area,  though 
the  majority  in  the  cases  of  yellow  and  violet  was  slight.  In  the  case  of 
all  of  the  tints,  a  slight  majority  preferred  the  larger  area.  In  the  case  of 
all  the  shades  the  larger  area  was  preferred,  though  the  majority  was  small 
for  green  and  violet. 

Secondly,  the  numerical  values  assigned  by  all  the  observers  to  the  large 
area  of  a  color  were  added,  and  divided  by  the  sum  of  the  nimierical  values 
assigned  by  all  the  observers  to  the  small  area  of  the  same  color.  This 
proceeding  gave  the  ratio  of  the  total  affective  values  of  the  two  areas  of  a 
given  color.     The  following  facts  resulted  from  a  study  of  the  figures  thus 


MINOR    STUDIES  579 

obtained.  In  saturated  colors,  the  smaller  area  is  pleasanter  except  in  the 
case  of  saturated  red,  where  the  larger  area  is  pleasanter.  All  the  tints 
showed  slightly  higher  affective  values  for  the  larger  areas.  In  the  case 
of  the  shades  there  was  a  more  marked  preference  for  the  larger  areas 
except  in  the  case  of  green. 

We  may  conclude,  then,  that  under  the  experimental  conditions  described 
(i)  saturated  colors  are  preferred  in  smaller  area,  with  the  exception  of  saturated 
red,  which  is  preferred  in  larger  area;  (2)  the  larger  area  of  tints  is  slightly 
preferred;  and  (3)  the  larger  area  of  shades  is  preferred,  the  preference  being 
least  in  the  cases  of  green  and  violet. 

There  was  no  correspondence  between  the  absolute  affective  value  of 
a  color  and  the  preference  for  it  in  larger  or  smaller  area.  It  may  be  noted 
that  in  this  study  as  in  the  preceding  ones,  the  highest  absolute  affective 
value  was  that  of  the  blue  tint  and  the  next  highest  that  of  saturated  red, 
also  that  yellow  and  orange  had  the  lowest  affective  values  among  saturated 
colors,  tints,  and  shades  alike.  Twelve  of  the  twenty-three  observers  in 
this  study  were  also  observers  in  the  study  on  An  Effect  of  Fatigue  on  Judg- 
ments of  the  Affective  Value  of  Colors. 


XVII.    Fluctuations  in  the  Affective  Value  of  Colors  During 
Fixation  for  One  Minute. 


By  Dorothy  Crawford  and  M.  F.  Washburn 


The  materials  used  in  this  experiment  consisted  of  pieces  of  the  Bradley 
colored  papers,  2.9  cm.  square.  This  size  was  used  in  the  present  study,  as  in 
some  of  our  other  studies  on  the  affective  value  of  colors,  for  the  reason  that 
it  can  be  conveniently  cut  from  the  sample  books  issued  by  the  Bradley 
Company.  Eighteen  colors  were  used:  saturated  violet,  blue,  green, 
yellow,  orange,  and  red,  and  the  lightest  tint  and  darkest  shade  of  each. 
Each  piece  of  paper  was  laid  on  a  white  ground  before  the  observer,  who 
was  asked  to  express  her  judgment  as  to  its  pleasantness  or  unpleasantness 
by  using  one  of  the  numbers  from  one  to  seven,  in  the  ordinary  way.  The 
observer  was  further  asked  to  look  steadily  at  the  color  for  an  interval  of 
one  minute,  measured  by  the  experimenter,  and  to  report  by  means  of  the 
appropriate  numbers  any  changes  in  the  affective  value  of  the  color.  At 
the  end  of  the  period  of  fixation  she  was  asked  to  give  the  reasons  for  the 
changes  which  had  occurred.  The  same  proceeding  was  repeated  for  each 
of  the  eighteen  colors,  in  random  order.  Fourteen  observers  worked  on 
the  problem;  all,  as  usual,  women,  and  nearly  all  students.  Eight  of  the 
observers  had  had  practice  in  introspection.  Several  of  them  made  the 
experiment  more  than  once,  at  considerable  intervals,  so  that  the  total 
number  of  experiments  performed  was  twenty-seven. 

For  most  of  the  observers  some  fluctuation  did  occur  during  the  one 
minute  period:  the  number  of  colors  with  which  no  fluctuation  took  place 
varied  from  fourteen,  out  of  the  eighteen,  to  none,  and  averaged  between 
four  and  five.  Our  principal  interest  was  in  the  causes  which  produced  the 
changes  in  affective  value.  These  changes  may  be  roughly  divided  into 
two  groups:  alterations  due  to  changes  in  the  color  itself,  and  alterations  due 
to  purely  mental  causes. 

Under  the  first  head,  two  obvious  factors  suggest  themselves :  adaptation 
and  the  presence  of  a  negative  after-image,  due  to  shifting  of  fixation,  in 
the  neighborhood  of  the  color.  The  effects  of  adaptation  were  variously 
described  as  'fading,'  'dulling,'  'getting  dirty,'  'getting  darker.'  The  most 
important  purely  mental  cause  for  change  in  the  pleasantness  or  unpleasant- 
ness of  a  color  lay  in  the  occurrence  of  associated  ideas.  These  were  most 
frequently  of  definite  things,  such  as  violets  or  wall-paper;  sometimes  of 


580  CRAWFORD  AND    WASHBNRN 

touch  experiences,  indicated  by  the  words  'velvety,'  'soft,'  Other  mental 
causes  of  change  concerned  the  affective  process  itself :  they  were  expressed 
by  'getting  used  to  it,'  or  'getting  tired  of  it.'  Both  of  these  last  comments 
were  surprisingly  rare;  getting  used  to  the  color  was  mentioned  only  six 
times  as  a  cause  of  increased  pleasantness,  and  getting  tired  of  a  color  was 
twenty-two  times  given  as  a  cause  of  increased  unpleasantness.  This  is 
in  comparison  with  one  hundred  and  twenty-seven  cases  where  change 
was  due  to  the  occiu'rence  of  an  association. 

When  the  number  of  cases  of  change  due  to  each  of  these  two  principal 
classes  of  causes  was  counted  up  for  each  of  the  eighteen  colors,  it  was 
found  that  changes  caused  by  alteration  in  the  actual  appearance  of  the  color 
were  decidedly  more  numerous  in  the  case  of  the  saturated  colors  (133)  than  in 
that  of  the  shades  (93)  or  tints  (70).  The  principal  reason  for  this  difference 
seemed  to  be  the  greater  frequency  with  which  an  after-image  was  noticed 
in  the  case  of  the  saturated  colors  (thirty- three  times,  as  compared  with  three 
times  for  the  tints  and  six  times  for  the  shades).  The  process  of  adapta- 
tion was  about  equally  influential  upon  the  three  classes  of  colors.  Be- 
sides adaptation  and  the  negative  after-image,  our  observers  occasionally 
reported  other  changes  in  the  appearance  of  the  colors,  such  as  alteration 
in  the  color- tone,  orange  getting  pinker,  green  shade  growing  less  yellow, 
and  so  on,  which  could  not  with  certainty  be  ascribed  to  adaptation.  Once 
in  a  while  an  observer  would  report  that  a  color  grew  brighter  as  it  was 
looked  at :  it  is  possible  that  this  was  due  to  renewed  fixation  after  having 
shifted  the  eyes. 

On  the  other  hand,  changes  due  to  purely  mental  causes  were  most  frequent 
in  the  case  of  tints  (70);  shades  came  next  (59),  and  saturated  colors  last  (55). 
This  difference  was  in  large  measure  due  to  the  fact  that  associations  oc- 
casioned a  greater  number  of  changes  in  affective  value  in  the  case  of  tints 
(47)  than  in  the  case  of  shades  (39)  or  saturated  colors  (31).  Saturated 
colors  occur  with  less  frequency  in  nature  than  unsaturated  colors,  and 
this  fact  would  naturally  make  them  poorer  in  associations:  why  tints 
should  be  superior  to  shades  in  associative  power  is  not  clear.  The  oc- 
currence of  an  associated  idea,  when  it  produces  a  change  in  the  pleasant- 
ness or  unpleasantness  of  a  color,  is  equivalent,  of  course,  to  a  change  in 
the  source  of  the  afi"ection,  just  as  truly  as  when  the  color  itself  changes 
under  the  influence  of  adaptation.  But  when  an  observer  reports  that  she 
has  grown  'used  to,'  or  'tired  of  a  color,  these  terms  probably  refer  to  a 
dulling  of  the  affective  process  itself,  apart  from  an  alteration  in  its  source. 
We  have  already  noted  that,  in  the  comparatively  short  interval  which  we 
used,  such  changes  were  rare.  This  result  was  in  part  due,  no  doubt,  to 
the  fact  that  the  conditions  of  the  experiment  set  the  mind  of  the  observer 
towards  finding  some  affective  value,  pleasant  or  unpleasant,  in  the  colors, 
and  growing  used  to  and  tired  of  a  color  are  processes  leading  to  the  dis- 
appearance of  affective  value.  The  six  cases  of  'getting  used'  to  a  color 
were  equally  divided  among  shades,  tints,  and  saturated  colors.  The 
shades  gave  the  most  instances  of  lowered  affective  value  through  getting  tired  of 
the  color  (11);  the  saturated  colors  came  next  (8),  and  the  tints  last  (3).  Very 
likely  the  tendency  to  get  tired  of  shades  is  due  to  their  being  some;what 
depressing.  Getting  used  to  and  tired  of  colors  may  be  called  processes 
of  affective  adaptation.  In  addition  to  them,  certain  changes  were  re- 
ported which  seemed  to  refer  to  the  affective  process  itself  rather  than  to 
its  cause,  but  which  were  too  indefinite  to  be  classified;  such,  for  instance, 
as  'growing  depressing,'  'growing  insipid.' 

A  further  question  which  suggests  itself  is  whether  the  above-mentioned 
causes  of  change  in  the  affective  value  of  colors  were  causes  of  increased 
or  diminished  pleasantness.  This  question  is  not  a  simple  one.  If  we 
find,  for  instance,  that  a  given  cause  such  as  adaptation  produces  in  a 
given  color  more  changes  in  the  direction  of  increased  affective  value  than 
in  that  of  diminished  affective  value,  we  must  bear  in  mind  that  a  color 


MINOR    STUDIES  58 1 

which  started  at  the  beginning  of  the  one-minute  interval  with  the  max- 
imum affective  value,  7,  would  have  no  chance  of  increasing,  while  one 
which  started  at  i  would  have  no  chance  of  decreasing.  On  the  other 
hand,  by  far  the  greatest  number  of  changes  in  affective  value  that  occurred 
under  the  conditions  of  this  experiment  were  changes  of  one  place  only 
in  the  scale.  Therefore  if  the  initial  value  of  a  color  were  anything  but  7 
or  I,  the  chances  were  about  equal  for  a  rise  or  a  fall.  It  ought  to  be 
sufficient,  then,  to  correct  our  comparison  of  the  number  of  rises  in  affec- 
tive value  produced  by  a  given  cause  for  a  given  color  with  the  munber  of 
falls,  by  taking  account  merely  of  the  number  of  maximum  and  minimum 
judgments  of  initial  affective  value  made  for  that  color. 

Adaptation  and  association  were  the  only  causes  of  change  that  occurred 
with  sufficient  frequency  to  make  this  calculation  worth  while.  Its  re- 
sults were  as  follows: 

Saturated  violet  had  7  for  its  initial  value  once,  and  i  not  at  all.  It  had 
therefore  a  very  slightly  greater  chance  for  decrease  than  for  increase. 
There  were  six  cases  where  associations  produced  an  increase  and  two 
cases  where  they  produced  a  decrease.  Associations  then,  on  the  whole, 
exerted  a  favorable  influence.  There  were  seven  cases  where  adaptation 
produced  increase  and  three  where  it  produced  decrease:  the  influence  of 
adaptation,  then,  is  also  favorable  to  this  color. 

Saturated  blue  had  7  once  for  its  initial  value  and  i  three  times.  It  had 
therefore  more  chance  to  increase  than  to  diminish.  Associations  pro- 
duced three  increases  and  no  decreases ;  hence  they  had  no  demonstrable 
influence.  Adaptation  on  the  other  hand  produced  sixteen  increases  to 
one  decrease,  and  undoubtedly  had  a  favorable  influence  on  the  pleasant- 
ness of  this  color. 

Saturated  green  as  regards  initial  values  was  exactly  like  satiu-ated  blue. 
Associations  had  almost  no  influence  upon  it,  occurring  only  twice  as  a 
cause  of  increase  and  not  at  all  as  a  cause  of  decrease.  Adaptation  was 
favorable,  with  nine  cases  of  increase  to  two  of  decrease,  but  its  effect  was 
not  very  marked. 

Saturated  yellow  never  had  7  for  its  initial  value,  while  it  had  i  three 
times;  its  chance  for  increase  was  therefore  greater  than  that  of  blue  and 
green.  The  effect  of  association  was  on  the  whole  favorable;  there  were 
six  increases  and  no  decreases.  The  effect  of  adaptation  was  rather  un- 
favorable :  four  increases  to  an  equal  number  of  decreases. 

Saturated  orange  never  had  7  for  initial  value,  and  had  i  five  times.  It 
had  therefore  decidedly  more  chance  for  increase  than  for  diminution.  As- 
sociations had  little  effect,  the  proportion  of  increase  to  decrease  being  five 
to  two.  Adaptation  was  also  of  small  influence,  the  proportion  being 
seven  to  four. 

Saturated  red  never  had  i  for  an  initial  value,  and  had  7  seven  times. 
Thus  it  had  much  more  chance  to  diminish  than  to  rise  in  affective  value. 
On  the  whole  the  influence  of  association  on  this  color  must  be  considered 
favorable,  for  there  were  two  increases  and  only  three  decreases,  despite 
the  greater  likelihood  of  the  latter.  Adaptation  on  the  other  hand  did 
saturated  red  no  good;  there  were  ten  cases  where  it  brought  about  a  fall, 
and  four  where  it  brought  about  a  rise. 

Violet  shade,  having  7  and  i  for  initial  values  once  each,  had  balanced 
chances.  The  influence  of  association  was  then  wholly  favorable,  the 
ratio  of  rises  to  falls  being  five  to  nothing.  Adaptation  was  nearly  as 
often  unfavorable  as  favorable  (six  to  eight). 

Blue  shade  had  decidedly  more  chance  for  fall  than  rise,  7  occurring  ten 
times  as  initial  value  and  i  once.  The  influence  of  associations  was 
negligible,  as  they  produced  change  in  two  instances  only.  The  effect  of 
adaptation  must  be  considered  favorable,  as  there  was  an  equal  number, 
five  each,  of  rises  and  falls  assigned  to  it. 

Green  shade  had  equal  chances  for  rise  and  fall,  as  neither  of  the  extreme 
numbers  was  ever  assigned  to  it  at  the  outset.     Associations  were  dis- 


582  CRAWFORD    AND  WASHBURN 

tinctly  favorable  to  it,  the  ratio  of  rise  to  fall  being  six  to  one.  Adaptation 
on  the  other  hand  had  an  unfavorable  effect  nearly  as  often  as  a  favorable 
one  (five  to  six). 

Yellow  shade  had  greatly  more  chance  for  increase  than  for  decrease,  i 
occurring  twelve  times  as  initial  value  and  7  not  at  all.  The  influence  of 
associations  was  then  but  slightly  favorable,  the  ratio  of  rise  to  fall  being 
five  to  one.  Adaptation  seemed  to  have  a  somewhat  unfavorable  effect, 
causing  four  decreases  to  seven  increases. 

Orange  shade  had  equal  chances  for  increase  and  decrease,  neither  ex- 
treme occurring  as  its  initial  value.  Associations  were  distinctly  favorable 
to  it,  in  the  proportion  of  ten  to  three.  Adaptation  was  a  little  more 
favorable  than  unfavorable  (seven  to  five). 

Red  shade  had  more  chance  of  decrease  than  of  increase,  as  7  was  assigned 
to  it  four  times  at  the  outset  and  i  never.  The  influence  of  association 
must  then  be  reckoned  as  decidedly  favorable,  since  it  produced  six  rises 
and  no  falls.  Adaptation  on  the  other  hand  was  perhaps  a  little  more 
unfavorable  than  favorable  in  its  influence,  producing  eight  falls  to  four 
rises. 

Violet  tint  had  7  for  its  initial  value  nine  times  and  i  not  at  all ;  it  was 
therefore  much  more  likely  to  fall  than  to  rise.  Association  thus  must  have 
had  a  distinctly  favorable  influence  to  produce  six  increases  and  no  de- 
crease. Adaptation  on  the  other  hand  had  little  if  any  effect,  the  propor- 
tion of  falls  to  rises  being  two  to  ten. 

Blue  tint  had  somewhat  more  chance  of  decrease  than  increase,  7  occurring 
twice  and  i  not  at  all  as  its  initial  value.  The  effect  of  associations  was 
favorable,  though  not  so  markedly  as  with  violet  tint,  the  ratio  of  rise  to 
fall  being  seven  to  two.  Adaptation  was  unfavorable,  causing  nine  de- 
creases to  four  increases.  Green  tint  had  7  six  times  and  i  once  for  initial 
value,  and  so  was  more  likely  to  fall  than  to  rise.  Associations  were 
favorable,  producing  five  rises  to  one  fall.  Adaptation  was  distinctly 
unfavorable,  causing  thirteen  falls  to  two  rises. 

Yellow  tint  had  equal  chances,  7  occm-ring  twice  and  i  twice.  Associa- 
tion produced  less  effect  upon  this  tint  than  upon  any  of  the  other  tints, 
but  such  effect  as  existed  was  mostly  favorable  (five  to  one).  Adaptation 
was  equally  unfavorable,  producing  one  rise  and  five  falls. 

Orange  tint  had  more  chance  of  fall  than  of  rise,  7  occurring  five  times  and 
I  once.  The  effect  of  association  was  on  the  whole  favorable,  producing 
eight  rises  and  five  falls.  Adaptation  had  little  effect,  but  that  little  was 
probably  favorable,  there  being  three  increases  to  four  decreases. 

Red  tint  had  nearly  equal  chances,  leaning  slightly  towards  fall,  with 
two  cases  of  7  and  one  of  i .  Associations  were  favorable  to  it,  in  the  pro- 
portion of  seven  to  one,  but  the  effects  of  adaptation  were  balanced,  eight 
to  seven. 

These  results  may  be  simimarized  in  the  following  statements.  For 
saturated  colors,  associations  have  little  influence,  but  what  they  have  is  pre- 
dominantly favorable.  Adaptation  is  favorable  to  violet,  blue,  and  green, 
rather  unfavorable  to  yellow  and  red,  and  without  definite  effect  on  the  affective 
value  of  orange.  The  colors  of  the  warm  end  of  the  spectrum  our  observers 
seem  to  have  liked  quite  as  well  in  their  original  saturation  as  in  the  duller 
tones  produced  by  adaptation.  In  the  case  of  shades,  association  produced 
a  favorable  effect  upon  violet,  green,  orange,  and  red;  little  effect  of  any  ;.  ind 
upon  blue,  and  nearly  as  much  unfavorable  as  favorable  effect  upon  yellow. 
The  effects  of  adaptation  were  on  the  whole  as  often  unfavorable  as  favorable 
to  the  shades.  Associations  are  favorable  to  tints  without  exception,  and 
adaptation  was  on  the  whole  unfavorable.  Broadly  speaking,  the  tendency 
of  associated  ideas  is  to  raise  the  pleasantness  of  a  color,  and  the  tendency  of 
adaptation  is  to  lower  it  rather  than  raise  it. 

With  two  exceptions,  in  every  case  where  an  after-image  was  noticed, 
it  diminished  the  pleasantness  of  the  color. 


IMITATION  IN  RACCOONS 


By  W.  T.  Shepherd,  Ph.  D.,  The  George  Washington  University 


This  paper  is,  in  certain  respects,  supplementary  to  work  which  has 
already  been  published  by  Cole,^  and  by  the  present  writer.^  The  same 
four  raccoons  which  served  as  subjects  in  those  earlier  investigations  were 
employed  in  the  present  study.  At  the  time  when  these  later  experiments 
were  undertaken,  the  animals  were  seven  months  old.  They  had  all  been 
trained,  for  a  period  of  nearly  three  months,  in  'puzzle-box'  and  other 
tests;  but,  with  the  exception  of  one  individual,  they  had  had  no  experience 
with  experiments  similar  to  those  which  were  here  undertaken. 

For  the  purposes  of  comparative  psychology,  three  sorts  of  imitation  may 
be  distinguished.  Instinctive  imitation  is  illustrated  in  the  reaction  of  the 
chick  which  pecks  at  an  object  on  seeing  another  chick  do  so.  Gregarious 
imitation  is  exemplified  by  the  stampede  of  the  herd  when  one  of  its  num- 
ber becomes  alarmed  and  flees.  When  a  monkey  sees  one  of  its  fellows 
obtain  food  by  pressing  a  lever  and  releasing  a  door,  and  himself  proceeds 
to  an  intelligent  performance  of  the  same  act,  we  have  a  case  of  inferential 
imitation.  The  present  study  is  concerned  with  an  investigation  of  this 
higher,  or  inferential  type  of  imitation. 

Our  apparatus  consisted  of  an  inclined  plane  of  poultry  netting,  1,5  m. 
long  by  25  cm,  wide;  it  was  supported  at  one  end  upon  a  box,  in  such 
fashion  that  it  extended  in  a  slightly  upward  and  diagonal  direction  across 
a  corner  of  the  room  to  a  platform,  which  was  30  cm.  wide  and  50  cm.  long. 
The  platform  was  90  cm.  high ;  and  the  other  end  of  the  inclined  plane  was 
65  cm.  above  the  floor.  At  the  lower  end  of  the  plane,  stood  a  box-step, 
32  cm.  high,  by  means  of  which  the  raccoons  could  easily  climb  upon  the 
plane. 

At  a  given  signal,  the  raccoon  went  up  the  step  and  along  the  plane  to  the 
platform,  where  he  was  fed.  The  experimenter  stood  at  a  distance  of  about 
a  meter  from  the  plane.  In  earlier  experiments,  one  of  the  raccoons  (Jim) 
had  learned  to  go  up  to  the  platform  to  be  fed.  He  now  served  as  imitatee, 
while  the  other  three  animals  were  employed  as  possible  imitators  of  his 
acts.  The  procedure  consisted  in  releasing  the  imitator  in  the  room  where 
he  was  able  to  make  several  observations  of  Jim's  performance  of  the 
act  of  climbing  and  obtaining  food.  Immediately  afterwards,  the  imitator 
was  given  an  opportunity  to  perform  the  act  alone.  We  kept  a  record  of  the 
number  of  times  that  he  clearly  saw  the  act  performed,  of  the  number  of 
times  he  probably  saw  it,  of  any  apparent  tendency  to  imitate,  and  of  all 
other  significant  facts. 

Tom.  First  day.  Tom  was  present  in  the  room  while  Jim  went  through 
twenty-one  repetitions  of  the  act  of  going  up  the  step,  and  along  the  plane 
to  the  platform  and  receiving  food.  Tom  apparently^  saw  seven  of  the 
twenty-one  repetitions  of  the  act;  and  he  probably  saw  the  act  in  five 
other  repetitions.     Then  Tom  was  placed  in  the  room  alone,  in  order  that 

*L.  W.  Cole:  Concerning  the  Intelligence  of  Raccoons,  Jour.  Comp.  Neur.  and  Psychol., 
XVII,  1907,  211-261. 

^W.  T.  Shepherd:  The  Discrimination  of  Articulate  Sounds  by  Raccoons.  Atner.  Jour. 
Psychol.,  XXII,  19H,  116-119. 

'^This  qualification  is  necessary  because  it  is  diflScult  to  be  entirely  sure  that  one  s 
has  really  seen  the  action  of  another. 


584  SHEPHERD 

he  might  imitate  Jim's  reaction  under  similar  conditions.  He  failed  to 
accomplish  it  during  a  period  which  lasted  one  minute  and  twenty  seconds 
Second  day.  (Six  days  after  the  first  trial.)  Tom  saw  Jim  perform  the 
act  three  times ;  and  he  probably  saw  the  reaction  five  times  in  all.  When 
tested  alone  for  a  period  of  ten  minutes,  he  failed  to  repeat  the  act, — indeed 
he  showed  no  indication  of  any  tendency  to  imitate  Jim's  reaction.  Third 
day.  (One  day  after  the  preceding  trial.)  Jim's  reaction  was  seen  four 
times,  and  probably  was  seen  nine  times,  in  all.  When  tested  alone,  Tom 
gave  no  indication  of  any  tendency  to  imitate,  and  had  not  accomplished  the 
act  at  the  end  of  ten  minutes.  In  three  of  Jim's  repetitions,  however, 
after  the  imitatee  had  performed  the  act  and  was  eating  his  food,  or  had 
just  eaten  it  on  the  platform,  Tom  went  up  also  and  sniffed  about  on  the 
platform. 

Dolly.  First  day.  Dolly  was  in  the  room  while  Jim  went  through  the 
act  fifteen  times.  She  saw  four  of  his  reactions,  and  probably  saw  eight 
more.  When  tested  alone,  she  showed  no  tendency  to  imitate,  and  had  not 
accomplished  the  act  at  the  end  of  ten  minutes.  Second  day.  (Seven  days 
later.)  She  saw  Jim's  reaction  eleven  times,  and  probably  saw  it  three 
times  more.  During  his  tenth  reaction,  she  went  up  the  plane  and  to  the 
platform,  where  she  sniffed  about.  During  the  subsequent  test  of  her 
imitation,  she  climbed  upon  the  experimenter  for  food,  and  rambled 
casually  about  the  room.  She  then  went  up  the  step  to  the  plane,  and 
down  again,  and  again  wandered  about  the  room. 

Jack.  First  day.  Jack  saw  six  of  Jim's  twenty-one  reactions,  and 
probably  saw  seven  more.  During  Jim's  eighth  reaction,  Jack  went  up  the 
step,  and  crossed  the  plane  to  the  platform,  where,  if  one  may  judge  from 
his  actions,  he  seemed  to  expect  to  be  fed.  But  when  tested  alone  immedi- 
ately afterwards  he  wholly  failed.  In  no  way  did  he  indicate  any  tendency 
to  imitate  Jim's  reaction.  Second  day.  (Five  days  later.)  Jack  saw  seven 
of  Jim's  reactions,  and  probably  saw  four  others.  During  the  progress  of 
Jim's  fifteenth  reaction.  Jack  went  up  the  step  and  partially  up  the  plane  to 
a  coat  which  hung  upon  the  wall  near-by.  Jim  had  aheady  gone  to  the 
platform.  Jack  did  not  appear,  however,  to  expect  food.  In  the  first 
trial  where  Jack  was  tested  alone,  after  the  usual  signal  had  been  given, 
he  played  about  the  room,  went  to  the  window  and  to  various  boxes  in  the 
room;  he  finally  ascended  the  step  and  the  plane  to  the  platform  and  was 
fed  there.  His  time  for  this  trial  was  two  minutes  and  fifteen  seconds. 
When  the  signal  was  given  for  the  second  trial,  he  went  up  on  a  box  at  the 
other  side  of  the  room,  and  looked  at  the  experimenter  for  food, — as  it 
appeared.  Finally,  he  went  to  the  platform  and  was  fed.  In  the  third 
trial,  his  behavior  was  similar  to  that  in  the  second  trial.  He  went  up  to 
the  platform  in  twelve  and  a  half  seconds.  In  the  fourth  trial,  he  did  the 
act  in  twenty  seconds,  first  going  part  way  up  the  plane  and  looking  toward 
the  experimenter.  In  the  fifth  to  the  eighth  trials,  his  behavior  was  similar 
to  that  during  the  fourth  trial ;  his  times  for  the  accomplishment  of  the 
act  during  these  trials  were  thirty-seven,  twenty-five,  thirty-two,  and 
thirteen  seconds  respectively.  In  the  ninth  trial  he  reacted  correctly  in 
eleven  seconds;  and  in  the  tenth,  in  thirteen  seconds.  In  both  of  these 
latter  trials  he  made  but  a  brief  stop  during  the  act  of  ascending  the  plane. 

The  results  of  these  experiments  may  be  regarded  as  wholly  negative. 
When  tested  alone,  after  seeing  Jim's  reactions,  neither  Tom  nor  Dolly 
made  any  attempt  to  imitate  the  act  which  they  had  just  seen.  It  is  true 
that  they  went  up  the  step  or  up  the  plane  during  the  process  of  Jim's 
reaction;  and  Tom's  behaviour  on  the  third  day, — when  on  three  occasions 
he  went  up  on  the  platform  where  Jim  was  eating, — seems  to  be  imitative. 
But  if  the  raccoons  perceived  the  results  of  Jim's  reactions,  it  is  diflScult 
to  understand  why  they  did  not  themselves  react  to  that  intelligent  percep- 
tion of  the  results  of  Jim's  actions,  when  tested  for  a  period  of  ten  minutes 
immediately  afterwards.     It  seems  probable  that  some  mental  process 


J 


IMITATION    IN   RACCOONS  585 

of  no  higher  order  than  'instinctive'  imitation  is  sufficient  to  account  for 
these  reactions. 

Jack's  reactions  appear  to  be  somewhat  more  doubtful.  But  when  we 
consider  all  of  the  evidence,  and  especially  when  we  note  his  hesitating 
behavior  on  the  second  day — where  he  apparently  had  formed,  or  almost 
formed,  the  appropriate  associations, — it  would  appear  that  we  may  attrib- 
ute his  learning  to  the  humbler  procedure  of  'trial  and  error,'  and  not  to  an 
'inferential'  imitation  of  Jim's  reactions. 

We  conclude,  therefore,  that  these  brief  experiments  have  failed  to  show 
that  'inferential'  imitation  (involving  ideation)  is  a  part  of  the  mental 
equipment  of  the  raccoon.  And  it  may  be  recalled  that  another  investi- 
gation of  imitation,  in  which  we  employed  the  same  animal,^  yielded  wholly 
negative  results.  Davis's^  interesting  observations  of  the  raccoon  likewise 
failed  to  reveal  the  presence  of  the  higher  form  of  imitation. 

iL.  W.  Cole:  Op.  cit.     pp.  232-235. 

2H.  B.  Davis:  Tlie  Raccoon:  A  Study  in  Animal  Intelligence.  Amer.  Jour.  Psychol., 
XVIII,  1908,  447-489. 


A    BIBLIOGRAPHY    OF    THE    SCIENTIFIC    WRITINGS 
OF  WILHELM  WUNDT 


By  E.  B.  TiTCHENER  ^nd  L.  R.  Geissler 


{Third  supplementary  list) 

1861 

(7)  Der  Blick.  Eine  physiognomische  Studie.  K.  Gutzkow's  Unter- 
haltungen  am  hauslichen  Herd,  dritte  Folge,  i.,  1028-1033. 

1862 

(11)  Der  Mund.  Physiognomische  Studie.  K.  Gutzkow's  Unter- 
haltungen  am  hauslichen  Herd,  dritte  Folge,  ii.,  505-510. 

(12)  Die  Zeit.  K.  Gutzkow's  Unterhaltungen  am  hauslichen  Herd, 
dritte  Folge,  ii.,  590-593- 

1898 
(5)     Leerboek  der  zielkunde.     Bew,  naar  den  2en  druk  van  [W.  Wundt's] 
Grundriss  der  Psychologic  door  M.  H.  Lem.  Large  8vo.     Amsterdam, 
A.  Versluys.     pp.  300. 

1906 

(8)  Ipnotismo  e  suggestions:  studio  critico.  Traduzione  autorizzata 
dair  autore  del  dott.  Leonardo  Tucci.  16  mo.  Palermo,  R.  Sandron 
(F.  Ando).     pp.  174. 

1910 

(5)  Elementi  di  psicologia.  Nuova  traduzione  italiana.  8vo.  Pian- 
cenza,  Societi  editrice  libraria  Pontremolese  (Rocca  S.  Casciano,  L. 
Cappelli).     pp.  363. 

(6)  Volkerpsychologie.  Eine  Untersuchung  der  Entwicklungesetze 
von  Sprache,  Mythus  und  Sitte.  Vol.  iv.  Mythus  und  Religion,  erster 
Teil.  Zweite,  neu  bearbeitete  Auflage.  With  8  illustrations.  Large  8vo. 
Leipzig,  W.  Engelmann.  pp.  xii.,  587.  [For  the  new  arrangement  of 
this  work,  see  1908  (4).] 

(7)  Kleine  Schriften.  Vol.  i.  Large  8vo.  Leipzig,  W.  Engelmann. 
pp.  viii.,  640.  (Philosophical  essays.  Ueber  das  kosmologische  Problem 
[revision  of  1877  (2)  ];  Kants  kosmologische  Antinomien  und  das  Problem 
des  Unendlichen  [revision  of  1885  (3)  ];  Was  soil  uns  Kant  nicht  sein? 
[revision  of  1891  (7)  ];  Zur  Geschichte  und  Theorie  der  abstrakten  BegrifiFe 
[revision  of  1884  (3)  ];  Ueber  naiven  und  kritischen  ReaHsmus  [revision  of 
1896  (3),  (4);  1897  (6)];  Psychologismus  und  Logizismus  [new;  pp. 
511-634]). 

1911 

(i)  Grundziige  der  physiologischen  Psychologie.  Sechste,  umgearbeitete 
Auflage.  Vol.  iii.,  with  71  illustrations  and  indices.  Large  8vo.  Leipzig, 
W.  Engelmann.     pp.  xi.,  810. 

(2)  Grundriss  der  Psychologie.  Zehnte,  verbesserte  Auflage.  With 
23   illustrations.     Large  8vo.     Leipzig,   W.   Engelmann.     pp.   xvi.,   414. 


WRITINGS  OF    WII^HBlyM  WUNDT  587 

(3)  Vorlesungen  uber  die  Menschen-  und  Tierseele.  Fiinfte  Auflage. 
With  53  illustrations.  Large  8vo.  Hamburg  and  Leipzig,  L.  Voss. 
pp.  xii.,  558. 

(4)  Kleine  Schriften.  Vol.  ii.  Large  Svo.  Leipzig,  W.  Engelraann. 
pp.  vii.,  496.  (Psychological  essays.  Ueber  psychische  Kausalitat 
[revision  of  1894  (2)];  Die  Definition  der  Psychologie  [revision  of  1895  (i)]; 
Ueber  psychologische  Methoden  [revision  of  1891  (3),  1899  (i),  1907  (3), 
1909  (i),  1904  (2)];  Zur  Lehre  von  den  Gemiitsbewegungen  [revision  of 
1 89 1   (i)];  Hypnotismus  und  Suggestion  [revision  of  1892  (2),  (3)]). 

(5)  Prohlemeder  Volkerpsychologie.  Large  8vo.  Leipzig,  E.  Wiegandt. 
pp.  vii,,   120. 

(6)  Hypnotismus    und    Suggestion.     Zweite,    durchgesehene    Auflage. 
From  Kleine  Schriften,  ii.]     Large  Svo.    Leipzig,  W.  Engelmann.     pp.  69. 


BOOK  REVIEWS 


Introduction  to  philosophy,  by  W.  Jerusalem,  translated  by  C.  F.  Sanders. 
New  York,  The  Macmillan  Company,  1910.     pp.  VIII,  319. 

An  excellent  compendium  of  the  philosophical  schools  and  theories, 
objective  and  impartial,  yet  with  a  clear  platform  of  its  own,  is  here  made 
more  accessible  to  American  students.  For  completeness  in  historical 
orientation  of  the  theories,  and  in  exposition  of  their  recent  developments, 
we  hardly  know  a  better  book.  Its  standpoint  is  empirical,  practical, 
social,  and  devoted  to  common-sense.  Judged  as  a  text  for  beginners  in 
this  country,  it  seems  to  presuppose  a  more  thorough  general  preparation 
and  more  mature  habits  of  thought  than  one  ordinarily  finds  in  the  Ameri- 
can student;  its  greatest  utility  here  would  perhaps  lie  in  its  compendious 
character.  For  graduate  students  wishing  a  summary  view  it  should  be 
invaluable.  Every  problem  is  historically  grounded,  and  the  bibliographies 
are  carefully  prepared  and  well-balanced. 

Jerusalem's  philosophy  "is  characterized  by  the  empirical  view-point, 
the  genetic  method,  and  the  biological  and  social  method  of  interpreting 
the  human  mind"  (p.  vi).  It  is  "rather  close  to  pragmatism  in  epistem- 
ology,"  but  gives  "a  further  development  of  the  pragmatic  concept  of  truth  " 
(p.  vi).  The  following  are  typical  phrases:  "the  airy  realm  of  the  tran- 
scendental," "come  down  to  the  level  of  reality,"  "understand  life  itself," 
"define  its  ideal  and  destiny"  (p.  vii).  Philosophy  is  defined  as  "world 
theory,  "which  is  "obliged  to  keep  in  close  touch  with  science,"  and  "to  con- 
struct the  fragments,  beyond  which  scientific  investigation  can  never  attain, 
into  consistent,  articulated  system  "  (p.  2).  Emotional  and  practical  motives 
also  play  a  part.  Philosophy  "should  teach  us  to  regard  the  world  and 
life  from  nobler  view-points  "(p.  3).  In  its  unity  and  in  its  study  of  the 
methods  by  which  unity  is  gained,  lies  the  distinction  between  philosophy 
and  science  (p.  14).  Thus  "the  investigation  of  the  foundations  of  knowl- 
edge" is  philosophy's  "most  important  task"  (p.  15).  But  its  field  is  very 
broad.  It  includes  psychology  and  logic  as  Propaedeutik,  epistemology, 
metaphysics,  aesthetics,  and  ethics  (including  sociology), — all  of  which  are 
to  be  studied  historically  as  well  as  systematically. 

The  second  division  of  the  book,  which  deals  with  psychology  and  logic, 
limits  itself  mainly  to  the  defining  of  the  subject-matter  of  these  two 
sciences.  Psychology  studies  processes,  not  states;  knows  nothing  of 
substance  (soul);  and  is  independent  of  metaphysics  (p.  26),  although 
contributory  to  the  problem  of  knowledge,  and  to  other  problems  (p.  40). 
The  sections  on  logic,  comprising  the  theory  of  judgment,  are  rather  ad- 
vanced reading,  but  they  constitute  an  admirable  summary. 

The  third  division,  "Criticism  of  Knowledge  and  Epistemology,"  traces 
the  theories  historically  from  naive  realism  through  Kantianism  and  ideal- 
ism to  the  author's  view,  critical  realism.  Idealism,  he  finds,  fails  to  account 
for  social  agreement;  and  since  a  universal  consciousness  is  "psychologi- 
cally practically  inconceivable"  (p.  82),  critical  realism  alone  remains. 
The  discussion  of  epistemology  includes  sensualism,  intellectualism  (ra- 
tionalism), mysticism  and  pragmatism.  The  author  identifies  modem 
mysticism  (wrongly,  in  the  opinion  of  the  reviewer)  with  spiritism;  and  in 
his  criticism  of  pragmatism,  he  seems  to  overlook  its  chief  difiiculty,  i.  e., 
its  failure  to  account  for  the  need  of  knowledge  for  its  own  sake,  apart 
from  further  consequences.     The  governing  category  of  knowledge  he 


BOOK   REVIEWS  589 

finds  genetically  to  be  "fundamental  apperception,"  which  seems  to  be 
Kant's  "transcendental  unity"  with  a  psychological  body  (p.  108).  This, 
as  well  as  the  more  particular  categories,  is  evolved  by  natural  selection, 
in  accordance  with  the  pragmatic  principle  of  useful  adaptation  to  environ- 
ment (p.  III).  Abstract  reasoning  is  the  best  substitute  we  can  find,  in  the 
absence  of  concrete  verifiability;  this  furnishes  the  origin  of  the  apparent 
independence  of  logic  (pp.  1 18-120).  There  is  really  no  a  priori  knowledge 
(p.  123).  On  the  whole,  the  discussion,  although  difficult  for  a  beginner, 
is  a  masterpiece  of  logical  arrangement  and  clearness. 

The  fourth  division,  "Metaphysics  or  Ontology,"  first  discusses  the 
ontological  problem.  Monism  is  either  materialism,  spiritualism  (panpsy- 
chism),  monism  of  being  (Haeckel)  or  of  becoming  (Mach,  Avenarius). 
The  author  doubts  the  conservation  of  energy  in  psychical  process,  and 
inclines  to  accept  Wundt's  "creative  synthesis"  (p.  147).  Panpsychism 
is  condemned  (unfairly,  we  believe)  as  not  accounting  for  the  physical. 
The  author  is  a  dualist  and  an  interactionist;  he  regards  will  as  the  type  of 
causation  (p.  181).  Pluralism  is  less  completely  discussed  than  other 
topics,  inasmuch  as  radical  empiricism  does  not  seem  to  be  understood. 
Its  attempt  to  defend  plurality  from  the  point  of  view  of  immediacy  is  not 
mentioned  (p.  184).  In  his  discussion  of  the  cosmological  problem  the 
author  follows  Paulsen,  in  the  main. 

The  fifth  division  treats  of  .Esthetics;  and  the  sixth,  of  Ethics  and 
Sociology.  In  the  opinion  of  the  author,  indeed,  ethics  is  sociology.  Its 
subject-matter  is  not  "deportment,"  but  "volition"  (p.  241),  "the  evalua- 
tion of  an  act  in  its  social  significance"  (p.  265).  Strangely  enough,  he 
brings  the  problem  of  freedom  under  ethics,  rather  than  under  metaphysics. 
He  upholds  psychological  freedom,  or  the  "absence  of  the  feeling  of  external 
or  internal  constraint;"  but  denies  metaphysical  freedom,  or  the  view  that 
acts  are  "outside  the  law  of  causality"  (p.  256).  As  to  sociology,  so  much 
does  he  value  it  that  he  says  "the  sociology  of  the  future  .... 
might  well  become  the  foundation  of  all  philosophy"  (p.  285). 

From  the  "Concluding  Reflections"  many  quotations  might  be  cited 
to  confirm  our  general  estimate  of  the  author's  position.  "Philosophy 
must  return  to  the  theory  ....  of  sound  common-sense"  (p. 
293).  "The  ultimate  object  of  knowledge  is,  after  all,  the  preservation  and 
improvement  of  life"  (p.  300).  Intellectualistic  idealism  is  "an  hyper- 
trophy of  the  cognitive  impulse"  (p.  300).  The  universe  is  a  vast  will 
(pp.  306-307) ;  and  "the  investigation  of  the  laws  of  this  divine  will  furnishes 
the  sublime  problem  of  all  science"  (p.  307).  Is  not  this  panpsychism? 
Or  at  least,  is  it  not  just  a  little  above  common-sense? 

But,  all  criticisms  apart,  the  book  is  a  remarkable,  and  on  the  whole,  a 
very  just  summary  of  philosophy.  One  finds  it  impossible,  in  a  short 
review,  to  do  justice  to  its  historical  perspective,  and  its  logical  arrange- 
ment of  the  problems.  May  it  meet  with  the  hearty  welcome  which  it 
deserves.  W.  H.  Sheldon. 

Dartmouth  College, 

The  Process  of  Abstraction:  An  Experimental  Study,  by  Thomas  Vernbr 

MooRB.     University  of  California  Publications  in  Psychology,  i,  2, 

1910,  pp.  73-197. 

Following  in  the  wake  of  the  Wurzburg  school  which  has  tried,  during 

the  past  ten  years,  to  study  experimentally  the  higher  thought  processes, 

Moore  attempts  to  determine  experimentally  the  mental  processes  involved 

in  the  process  of  abstraction,  or  the  formation  of  our  general  ideas.     He 

seeks  to  discover  how  general  ideas  form  and  develop,  and  what  mental 

processes  are  involved  in  their  formation. 

His  method  consisted  in  presenting  to  his  subjects,  a  series  of  groups  of 
geometrical  figures  so  drawn  and  arranged  that  a  common  element  con- 
stantly recurred  in  each  group,  while  the  other  figures  in  the  group  were  con- 
JOURNAL — 8 


590  BOOK   REVIEWS 

stantly  varied.  As  soon  as  the  subject  felt  sure  that  the  same  figure  had 
occurred  more  than  once,  he  stopped  the  exposure-apparatus;  he  then 
described  his  state  of  mind  during  the  experiment  stating,  especially,  what 
it  was  that  he  first  noticed  in  isolating  and  perceiving  the  common  element. 

It  was  found  that  the  groups  of  figures  thus  exposed  constituted  some- 
thing of  a  unit  which  underwent  rather  definite  changes  as  the  common 
element  became  isolated  and  perceived.  That  is  to  say,  the  elements  of 
these  groups  had  a  different  mental  value  after  the  common  element  had 
been  perceived  from  what  they  had  before.  This  made  it  possible  to  study 
the  process  of  abstraction  genetically.  Four  stages  or  steps  in  the  process  of 
abstraction  were  ascertained:  (i)  The  breaking  up  of  the  groups  of  figures 
and  the  selection  of  the  common  element.  (2)  The  process  of  perceiving 
or  apprehending  this  common  element.  (3)  Holding  this  common  element 
in  immediate  memory,  until  (4)  it  was  recognized  as  having  occurred  before . 
Each  of  these  stages  was  made  the  subject  of  special  observation,  with  a 
view  to  determining  the  mental  processes  involved. 

On  the  first  point,  the  breaking  up  of  the  group,  and  the  isolation  of  the 
common  element,  nothing  new  was  determined.  Moore  simply  says  that 
the  selection  of  the  common  element  depended  upon  the  degree  to  which 
the  repeated  figure  attracted  the  observer's  attention.  This  step  seems  not 
to  have  been  worked  out  in  detail.  No  psychological  history  of  the  mental 
process  actually  employed  in  selecting  the  common  element  was  obtained; 
but  it  was  determined  that,  when  the  group  was  finally  broken  up,  the 
common  element  always  became  accentuated  at  the  expense  of  the  surround- 
ing elements,  which  seemed  to  be  positively  cast  aside  and  swept  more  or 
less  completely  from  the  field  of  consciousness. 

The  second  step,  the  perception  the  common  element,  was  initiated  by 
this  breaking  up  of  the  group.  The  sensations  aroused  by  the  recurrent 
figure  were  attended  to.  This,  at  once,  instituted  a  process  of  appercep- 
tion or  mental  assimilation,  by  means  of  which  the  sensations  were  related 
or  joined  to  one  or  more  appropriate  categories.  A  general  idea  that  some 
kind  of  a  figure  (roundish,  open,  pointed,  etc.)  had  been  repeated,  was  the 
result;  but  no  definite  information  about  the  shape  or  nature  of  this  figure 
could  be  given.  The  figure  was  clearly  apprehended  but  not  in  represen- 
tative terms.  "Mental  images  formed  no  essential  part  in  this  first  appre- 
hension of  the  figure."  There  was  not  even  a  more  or  less  specialized 
general  concept  of  the  form  of  the  figure  perceived.  After  the  knowledge 
that  some  kind  of  figure  had  been  repeated,  the  memory  of  this  fact  usually 
lingered  in  consciousness  until  a  clearer  idea  of  the  figure  was  formed.  But 
this  second  idea  of  the  common  element  might  still  be  expressed  in  perfectly 
general  and  non-representative  terms.  It  was  only  rarely  represented 
in  consciousness  in  imaginal  terms,  or  accompanied  by  feelings  of  pleasant- 
ness or  unpleasantness,  strain,  and  the  like.  The  third  step  in  the  percep- 
tion of  the  common  element  was  the  acquisition  of  a  correct  idea  of  the 
figure  and  a  clear  knowledge  of  its  shape ;  this  stage  was  attended  by  doubt 
or  error  as  to  the  orientation  of  the  figure  in  the  group.  The  fourth  and 
last  step  in  the  perception  of  the  common  element  involved  forming  a 
correct  idea  of  the  figure  and  its  shape,  with  a  true  knowledge  of  its  orienta- 
tion in  the  group.  It  is,  therefore,  clear  that  the  perception  of  the  common 
element  in  abstraction  proceeded  from  that  which  was  general  and  vague 
and  imageless  to  that  which  was  particular  and  definite  and  clear.  Mental 
images  belonged  only  to  the  later  and  more  unessential  stages  of  the  per- 
ception of  the  common  figure. 

After  the  common  element  had  been  isolated  and  perceived,  it  had  to  be 
held  in  immediate  memory  until  it  could  be  certainly  recognized  as  having 
been  seen  before.  This  memorial  process  was  investigated,  and  three 
factors  were  found  to  affect  the  memorial  permanency  of  the  common 
element:  (i)  The  method  of  memorial  visualization,  motorization,  asso- 
ciation, analysis,  etc.     (2)  The  appearance  and  noting  of  impressions 


BOOK  R^vmWS  591 

between  the  time  when  the  common  element  was  first  noticed,  and  its  final 
perception  and  recognition.  (3)  The  focality  of  the  common  element,  when 
perceived.  The  most  economic  method  of  memorizing  the  common  ele- 
ment, and  the  method  most  often  used,  was  that  of  association  and  analysis. 
Analyzing  the  vague  idea  of  the  figure  "to  see  what  it  was  made  up  of,  what 
it  resembled,  its  possible  use,"  etc.,  was  found  to  be  the  most  effective 
method  of  fixing  it.  This  mental  analysis,  while  never  put  into  actual  words 
or  representative  terms,  was  found  to  have  a  greater  effect  for  memorial 
permanency  than  the  combined  effects  of  any  visual  and  motor  imagery 
employed  by  the  subjects.  "Subjects  often  remarked  that  figures  were 
remembered  in  this  way  when  they  were  attempting  to  memorize  them  by 
visualization."  But  the  method  of  memorizing  is  not  the  only  element  that 
influenced  the  memorial  permanency  of  the  common  element.  Succeeding 
impressions  had  a  positive  tendency  to  impair  the  subject's  memory  for  the 
common  element.  In  every  case,  the  perception  of  new  figures  tended  to 
obliterate  from  memory  the  figure  already  perceived.  Then,  too,  the 
farther  the  figure  was  from  the  focal  point  of  vision  when  perceived,  the 
less  accurately  could  it  be  held  and  reproduced. 

The  last  stage  in  the  process  of  abstraction, — the  recognition  of  the  com- 
mon element,  or  the  knowledge  that  the  figure  had  been  seen  before, — was  an 
entirely  different  mental  process  from  the  selection,  perception  or  retention 
of  this  common  element.  It  often  occurred  that  the  figure  which  the  sub- 
jects had  in  mind  for  some  time  was  later  recognized  as  the  common  ele- 
ment, "Certainty  that  the  figure  apprehended  had  been  seen  before  was 
what  was  dawning  upon  the  subject  during  the  interval  when  his  mind  was 
thus  being  fully  made  up."  In  the  development  of  this  recognitive  certainty 
there  was  (i)  an  intimation  or  feeling  of  weak  probability  that  a  figure  had 
been  seen  before;  (2)  a  stage  of  actual  probability  that  a  common  element 
was  present;  (3)  a  final  stage  of  certainty.  While  the  process  of  recognizing 
was  thus  distinct  from  the  process  of  perceiving  the  common  element,  it 
must  not  be  inferred  that  the  process  of  perception  was  regularly  completed 
before  the  process  of  recognition  began.  "What  actually  happened  was  that 
almost  any  degree  or  certainty  of  recognition  might  co-exist  with  any  degree 
of  the  perfection  of  perception."  There  might  be  (i)  an  intimation  of  a 
common  element,  without  any  knowledge  of  its  form;  (2)  probability  that 
a  common  element  was  present,  but  an  imperfect  idea  of  its  form;  (3) 
probability  that  a  common  element  was  present,  and  a  true  idea  of  its  form; 
(4)  certainty  that  a  common  element  was  present,  but  an  imperfect  idea 
of  its  form;  (5)  certainty  that  a  figure  was  repeated  without  any  knowledge 
of  its  form.  These  results  were  obtained  by  stopping  the  apparatus,  during 
some  of  the  experiments  before  absolute  certainty  had  developed.  In  this 
way,  cross-section  analyses  of  the  recognitive  consciousness  were  obtained 
which  showed  the  process  at  all  stages  of  its  development.  The  subjects 
were  also  shown  discs  without  a  common  element,  and  discs  containing  more 
than  one  common  element,  to  insure  accurate  observation.  Certain 
recognition,  is,  therefore,  not  dependent  upon  perfect  perception;  neither 
is  it  dependent  upon  a  comparison  of  mental  images.  It  often  took  place 
without  the  formation  of  any  mental  image  of  the  thing  that  was  recog- 
nized. "A  person  might  be  certain  that  a  figure  was  repeated,  and  have  a 
perfect  image  of  the  figure,  or  an  imperfect  image,  or  no  image  at  all."  "A 
comparison  of  mental  images  is  not  the  normal  method  of  recognition." 

In  this  process  of  recognition,  an  element  of  certainty  or  uncertainty  was 
always  involved.  This  imphed  assent  or  doubt,  and,  consequently, an 
actual  or  suspended  judgment.  The  final  question,  therefore,  is  to  determine 
the  psychological  basis  of  this  recognitive  judgment.  How  was  this 
judgment  or  feeling  of  certainty  arrived  at  in  the  experiment?  Moore's 
answer  to  this  question  is  theoretical.  The  actual  development  of  this 
feeling  of  certainty  was  not  determined;  but  "recognition  took  place  not 
only  when  there  was  no  revived  mental  image  of  the  past  perception,  but 


592  BOOK   EEVIKWS 

when  the  present  perception  itself  was  too  imperfect  to  leave  any  trace  of 
mental  imagery  on  the  mind"  (p.  173). 

The  real  basis  of  this  recognitive  certainty,  "was  the  series  of  associated 
concepts  or  appropriate  mental  categories  which  the  sensations  of  the 
common  element  aroused."  "The  subject's  first  idea  of  the  common 
element  was  made  up  of  the  sensations  from  the  repeating  figure  plus  the 
concepts  or  mental  categories  which  these  recalled.  These  two  processes 
fused  and  formed  a  new  psychical  product, — the  subject's  first  apprehen- 
sion or  idea  of  the  common  figure.  When  the  common  element  was  seen 
again,  a  new  percept  was  formed  and  assimilated  to  the  old."  Just  how 
this  occurred  Moore  does  not  say.  "The  old  series  of  associated  concepts 
readily  falls  in  with  the  new,  and  gives  rise  to  the  feeling  of  familiarity  and 
certainty."  How  or  why,  Moore  does  not  determine.  "The  new  concepts 
thus  formed  readily  fit  in  with  the  old.  There  is  nothing  to  jar  the  process 
of  their  assimilation,  but  often  a  re-enforcement  of  at  least  some  members 
of  the  associated  train  of  concepts."  The  figure's  series  of  associated 
concepts,  therefore,  not  only  formed  the  chief  factor  in  perception,  and  the 
factor  by  means  of  which  the  subjects  recalled  the  figures,  but  also  the  factor 
that  enabled  them  to  recognize  the  figure  as  having  occurred  before  (p. 
175).  These  mental  categories  or  concepts  were  also  the  final  product  of 
the  whole  process  of  abstraction. 

Two  things  were  determined  about  this  final  product  of  abstraction  or 
learning:  (i)  That  the  mental  categories  and  concepts  formed  in  the  process 
of  this  experiment  were  the  result  of  the  subject's  experience  with  the 
repeating  figures  of  the  groups.  All  other  categories  and  concepts  possessed 
by  the  individual  are  products  of  the  individual's  past  experience  in  the 
process  of  learning.  (2)  These  mental  categories  or  concepts  represent 
compound  psychic  processes  which  are  separate  and  distinct  from  mental 
images  and  feelings, — a  result  supported  by  the  author's  careful  summary 
of  related  studies  in  the  psychology  of  thought  with  which  his  study  begins. 

The  character  and  nature  of  these  concepts  was  not  determined  or 
described;  and  the  reader  seeks  in  vain  for  a  more  detailed  psychological 
history  of  the  formation  and  development  of  the  particular  concepts  formed 
in  the  course  of  the  experiment.  One  is  curious  to  know  the  nature  and 
origin  of  the  imageless  mental  contents  arrived  at;  and  how  these  actually 
operated  in  the  process  of  forming  other  mental  categories  and  concepts. 
The  reviewer  feels  that  a  more  detailed  psychological  history  of  the  forma- 
tion and  development  of  the  particular  concepts  formed  in  the  cotu-se  of  the 
experiment  would  have  told  us  much  about  the  nature  and  origin  of  these 
imageless  processes.  The  author  should  have  told  us  exactly  how  the 
common  element  was  perceived ;  he  should  have  determined,  by  controlled 
and  repeated  observations,  exactly  how  the  feeling  of  recognitive  certainty 
was  acquired,  how  the  common  element  was  actually  selected,  etc., — a  very 
difficult  but  not  impossible  task  which  must  be  squarely  met  if  we  are  to 
obtain  the  psychological  facts.  What,  to  the  reviewer,  seems  to  be  needed 
most  in  all  such  studies  as  this  is  a  complete  psychological  history  of  the 
processes  studied.  We  should  be  supplied  with  enough  accurate,  cross- 
section  analyses  of  the  mental  processes  involved  to  enable  us  to  trace, 
with  assurance,  the  whole  course  of  their  development.  This  is  a  method 
and  point  of  view,  which  is  not  clearly  apprehended  in  the  present  study. 
In  fact,  the  reviewer  feels  that  the  author  is  at  times  describing  logical 
deductions  instead  of  psychological  facts;  that  he  is  trying  to  tell  how  he 
thought  certain  processes  worked  instead  of  giving  us  actual  verified 
observations  from  his  subjects.  Nevertheless,  Moore  has  done  a  careful 
and  important  piece  of  work.  His  study  is,  without  doubt,  the  best  in 
the  field,  for  it  not  only  makes  an  important  contribution  to  the  ever- 
growing psychology  of  the  higher  thought  processes,  but  it  also  raises  an 
array  of  definite  problems  for  future  work,  some  of  which  I  have  tried  to 
indicate  in  this  review.  W.  F.  Book. 

University  of  Montana. 


BOOK  REVIEWS  593 

Technique  de  psychologie  experimentale  de  Toulouse,  Vaschide  et  Pieron. 
Par  E.  Toulouse  et  H.  Pie;ron.  Paris,  O.  Doin  et  Fils,  191 1.  Two 
vols.  pp.  303,  288. 

This  is  the  second  edition,  carefully  revised  and  largely  extended,  of 
a  one- volume  work  published  by  Toulouse,  Vaschide  and  Pieron  in  1904. 
In  its  original  form,  the  Technique  was  practically  a  manual  of  mental 
tests,  the  sublimated  result  of  ten  years  of  teaching  and  investigation; 
it  grew  out  of  Toulouse's  study  of  Zola  (1896),  where  the  need  for  precise 
methods  was  keenly  felt.  The  authors  accordingly  made  a  clean  sweep 
of  experimental  tradition,  and  started  out  to  devise,  on  their  own  behalf, 
rules  for  the  examen  des  sujets  (see  this  Journal,  xvi.,  1905,  139). 
The  new  two- volume  work  has  a  wider  scope;  "it  allows  a  very  large  place 
to  the  methods  customarily  employed  in  the  various  laboratories  of  France, 
Germany,  England  and  the  United  States  of  America;"  it  devotes  a  chapter 
to  the  doctrine  of  averages  and  the  formulae  of  correlation;  it  pays  special 
attention  to  the  'higher  processes;'  it  describes  new  experiments  (especially 
in  the  domain  of  visual  perception)  and  new  apparatus;  finally,  it  omits 
the  theoretical  framework  of  the  earlier  exposition,  and  so  gains  space 
for  maxims  of  actual  laboratory  practice. 

Nevertheless,  the  reader  who  turns  to  the  book  with  the  expectation 
of  finding  in  it  a  monographic  review  of  the  methods  of  experimental  psy- 
chology will  be  sadly  disappointed.  There  is  not  a  single  reference  that 
extends  beyond  the  bare  name  of  a  writer,  and  the  bibliographical  index 
contains  only  four  works,  the  manuals  of  Jud#,  Myers,  Sanford  and  Titch- 
ener.  There  is  no  discussion  of  method  proper:  the  methods  of  experi- 
mental psychology  "are  implied  in  our  technique,  but  the  man  of  science 
uses  methods,  and  it  is  the  philosopher  who  reflects  upon  them  after  the 
event  and  appraises  or  judges  them;  so  that  this  is  not  our  business." 
Unfortunately,  the  methods  implied  in  the  technique  are  of  an  empirical 
and  proximate  kind;  the  trail  of  the  mental  test  is  still  apparent.  How- 
ever, the  value  of  the  book,  at  any  rate  to  the  American  psychologist,  is 
found  precisely  in  its  limitations.  It  has  the  qualities  of  its  defects:  it 
shows  us  what  a  course  in  experimental  psychology  becomes  when  the 
primary  interest  of  the  instructors  is  in  individual  psychology,  and  when 
the  practical  application  of  laboratory  results  is  a  constant  motive  in 
the  shaping  of  the  experiments. 

As  a  paradigm  of  the  writers'  treatment  we  may  take  the  first  section 
of  the  work,  the  seven  and  a  half  pages  allotted  to  Sensations  of  Pressure. 
The  student  is  warned,  at  the  outset,  that  the  experiment  is  concerned, 
not  with  the  limen  of  duality,  but  with  the  single  sensation  of  contact; 
nothing  is  said  of  the  nature  of  the  sensation,  A  brief  account  is  given  (with 
figure)  of  von  Frey's  hair  sesthesiometer.  Then  follows  a  longer  account 
(with  figure)  of  the  haphiaesthesiometric  needle-points  of  Toulouse  and 
Vaschide;  von  Frey's  formula  for  tension  values  is  stated  in  a  foot-note. 
Beaunis'  aesthesiometric  needle-point  is  figured  and  described,  at  the  ex- 
pense of  a  page  and  a  half,  although  it  is  difficult  of  manipulation,  too 
heavy  for  the  lower  limens,  and  'has  hardly  ever  been  employed.'  So 
we  come  to  the  paragraphs  headed  Technique.  A  circle  of  at  most  2  mm. 
in  diameter  is  marked  with  a  rubber  stamp  on  the  front  surface  of  the 
observer's  wrist,  where  there  is  no  hair.  The  observer's  eyes  are  blind- 
folded, and  his  hand  placed  in  a  fixed  position  on  a  felt-covered  table. 
He  is  instructed  that  he  will  be  touched  from  time  to  time  on  the  back  ( !) 
of  the  wrist,  and  that  he  is  to  say  Yes  whenever  he  feels  the  pressure.  Rate, 
order  of  touches  and  blank  experiments,  ready-signal,  form  of  enquiry  for 
the  experimenter,  are  all  prescribed.  'The  series  is  ascending,  from  light 
to  heavy;  when  the  observer  says  Yes,  the  point  evoking  this  response  is 
to  be  used  in  a  special  series,  consisting  about  one-half  of  actual  touches  and 
one-half  of  blanks;  if  the  reply  is  always  correct,  the  next  lighter  point  is 
taken.     Thus  one  obtains  either  the  limen  of  certainty  or  a  lower  limen  of 


594  BOOK  REvmws 

arbitrary  value  (touch  sensed  in  three-quarters  or  less  of  the  cases).  Pauses 
must  be  made,  in  order  to  the  avoidance  of  fatigue.  Preliminary  experi- 
ments are  required,  that  the  observer  may  understand  the  problem.  The 
point  must  be  applied  slowly  and  in  a  strictly  vertical  position;  it  must 
remain  on  the  skin  for  a  constant  period  of  time.  All  points  must  be 
kept,  during  the  experiment,  in  a  dry-chamber  of  38**  temperature. — Here 
is  no  lack  of  details;  and  yet  the  account  of  the  experiment  leaves  much 
to  be  desired.  At  what  place  within  the  circle  of  2  mm.  diameter  is  the 
point  of  yV  ini^-  diameter  to  be  set  down;  always  at  the  same  spot  or 
indifferently  at  any  place  within  the  circle?  How  is  the  hand  of  the  obser- 
ver to  be  'immobilised'  upon  the  felt-covered  table?  Even  if  the  method 
employed — an  ascending  series,  interrupted  by  blank  experiments — does 
not  call  for  explanation  and  justification,  why  is  not  a  descending  series 
taken,  and  the  two  results  averaged  (this  procedure  has  been  recommended 
in  the  Introduction,  p.  23)?  What  meaning  will  the  student  attach  to  the 
technical  term  seuil,  when  its  value  may  be  correspond  to  100%  of  right 
cases,  to  75%,  to  'a  lesser  number,'  or  (p.  20)  to  four  successive  right 
answers?  Are  the  limens  obtained  by  the  various  members  of  the  class 
to  be  averaged,  whether  or  not  they  chance  to  be  derived  from  pressure- 
spots?  These  and  similar  questions  must  be  answered,  if  the  experiment 
is  to  be  taken  in  psychological  earnest. 

Finally,  what  of  the  instrument  used?  The  hair  aesthesiometer  is  re- 
jected, partly  on  account  of  the  hygroscopic  properties  of  the  hair,  partly 
on  account  of  the  variation  (presumably  as  the  result  of  bending)  of  its 
stimulus-value.  We  have,  instead,  the  haphiaesthesiometric  needle- 
points of  tempered  steel.  We  are  warned,  however,  that  the  manipulation 
of  these  points  is  by  no  means  easy.  The  holder  is  small,  oftentimes  very 
small;  too  sudden  an  application  brings  the  head  of  the  needle  against 
the  roof -plate  of  the  holder;  an  application  in  any  but  an  exactly  vertical 
position  means  friction  of  the  needle  in  the  guide,  so  that  the  experimenter 
must  rest  his  elbows  solidly  on  the  table,  fixate  the  head  of  the  needle,  and 
follow  its  course  from  various  points  of  view;  the  points  must  be  kept 
in  the  dry-chamber,  at  a  certain  temperature,  or  a  temperature  sensation 
will  precede  or  accompany  the  sensation  of  contact ;  and  the  heavier  points 
(this  caution  would  hardly  have  been  given  had  not  experience  proved  it 
necessary)  are  liable  to  rust.  The  reviewer  has  had  no  experience  with 
the  haphiaesthesiometer,  but  on  general  principles  he  must  believe  that  the 
use  of  the  points  calls  for  the  constant  supervision  of  the  instructor,  and  in 
particular  that  the  error  arising  from  friction  is  serious.  If  the  authors 
are  absolutely  determined  against  the  introduction  into  the  laboratory  of 
'capillary  organic  matter,'  and  if  the  experiment  requires  stimulus-points 
of  minimal  diameter,  it  would  seem  better  to  have  recourse  to  Thunberg's 
standardized  glass  'hairs.' 

All  these  criticisms  carry  a  single  moral:  that  the  experiment  of  ex- 
perimental psychology  is  one  thing,  and  the  mental  test  another.  In 
psychophysics  the  limen  must  be  rigorously  defined;  for  test  purposes, 
an  arbitrary  limen  may  be  set  up,  to  meet  the  special  conditions  of  the 
tests.  In  the  psychological  laboratory,  the  choice  of  method  and  appara- 
tus is  determined  by  scientific  reasons  and  by  these  alone;  in  the  case. of 
mental  tests,  it  is  influenced  by  other  considerations, — simplicity,  ease  of 
manipulation,  portability,  quickness  of  application  and  of  calculation. 
It  seems  that  in  this  first  experiment,  on  pressure,  the  authors  of  the  work 
under  review  have  fallen  between  the  two  stools:  their  method  is  unduly 
rough,  and  their  instruments  are  too  delicate  for  any  but  the  most  skilled 
and  careful  use. 

The  reviewer,  however,  wishes  to  bring  out  the  qualities  of  the  two 
volumes;  and  this  end  can,  perhaps,  best  be  accomplished  by  way  of  a  com- 
plete synopsis  of  their  contents.  Pt.  I.  discusses  the  measurement  of  the 
elementary  phenomena  of  sense.     Ch.  i.,  on  the  measurement  of  cutaneous 


BOOK  RBvmws  595 

sensations,  opens  with  (i)  the  experiment  on  sensations  of  pressure  which 
has  just  been  described.  Sensations  of  temperature  (2)  are  measured  by 
means  of  a  thermoaesthesiometer,  which  deposits  on  the  skin  drops  of 
warmed  or  cooled  water.  Kiesow's  cone  is  figured.  Sensations  of  pain 
(3)  are  obtained  by  the  compression,  in  a  pincers-Hke  algoaesthesiometer, 
of  a  fold  of  the  skin;  the  direct-pressure  instruments  of  Macdonald  and 
Cheron  are  figured.  Sections  follow  on  (4)  the  electrical  sensations  (!) 
produced  by  faradisation  of  the  skin,  and  (5)  miscellaneous  cutaneous 
sensations, — caustic  sensations,  due  to  the  application  of  caustic  potash 
in  various  strengths  of  solution;  sensations  of  traction;  pilary  sensations; 
sensations  of  tickling.  Finally,  directions  are  given  for  the  determination 
(6)  of  the  duration  of  cutaneous  sensations  (method  of  intermittent  stimuli). 
Ch.  ii.,  on  the  measurement  of  the  subcutaneous  sensations,  is  devoted  to 
(i)  sensations  of  vibration,  evoked  by  the  tuning  fork,  and  (2)  kinsesthetic 
or,  as  the  authors  prefer  to  call  them,  kinesic  sensations.  The  latter  are 
of  three  kinds:  sensations  of  muscular  effort  (myoaesthesiometer:  a  set 
of  holders  and  weights),  static  sensations  (schesiaesthesiometer :  an  adjust- 
able support  for  the  hand,  whereby  positions  of  the  arm  may  be  varied  and 
reinstated),  and  dynamic  sensations  of  passive  and  active  movement 
(schesiaesthesiometer,  moving  car;  boards  with  grooved  patterns,  moving 
car).  Ch.  iii.  brings  us  to  the  measurement  of  sensations  of  taste  and 
smell.  The  instruments  recommended  are  the  gueusiaesthesiometer 
(geusiaesthesiometer?),  a  set  of  flasks  containing  standard  solutions,  with 
droppers  inserted  in  the  corks,  and  the  osmiaesthesionieter,  a  set  of  wide- 
mouthed  bottles  containing  34  aqueous  solutions  of  camphor,  of  known 
degrees  of  concentration,  10  typical  scents  (for  recognition),  and  5  strengths 
each  of  liquid  ammonia  and  of  aqueous  sulphuric  ether  (for  testing  the 
tactual  sensitivity  of  the  mucosa).  Ch.  iv.  deals  with  the  measurement  of 
visual  sensations.  Two  experiments  fall  under  the  heading  (i)  sensations 
of  light.  The  minimum  perceptihile  is  determined  by  an  instrument  con- 
structed on  the  principle  of  Charpentier's  photoptometer;  the  source  of 
light  is  controlled  by  the  Blondel-Broca  photometer.  Bouguer's  and 
Biondel's  diaphragms  are  figured.  The  differential  limen  is  determined 
either  by  a  differential  photoaesthesiometer  built  on  the  same  principle 
(rays  from  a  single  source  are  directed  by  two  total-reflection  prisms  upon 
diffusing  screens,  which  are  viewed  through  tubes  containing  a  diaphragm) 
or  by  rotating  discs.  (2)  Sensations  of  color  have  four  experiments.  For 
the  absolute  limen  of  color,  and  for  the  differential  limen  of  chroma  ('color 
intensity'),  the  authors  recommend  a  chromatoassthesiometer,  made  up 
of  colored  solutions  in  rectangular  glass  vessels;  directions  are  given  for 
the  preparation  of  the  solutions.  The  extreme  limits  of  color  sensitivity 
are  fixed  by  reference  to  a  spectrum.  The  differential  limen  of  hue  is 
spectrometrically  determined.  The  equation  of  tint,  in  the  determination 
of  the  differential  limen  of  chroma, — a  precaution  neglected  in  the  initial 
experiment, — may  be  effected,  though  only  at  the  cost  of  much  labor,  by 
suitable  combinations  of  the  colored  solutions;  it  is  better,  therefore,  to 
have  recourse  to  rotating  discs ;  these  then  permit  also  of  the  determination 
of  the  absolute  color  limen,  under  the  same  conditions ;  they  permit,  further, 
by  the  addition  of  increments  of  black  or  white,  of  the  determination  of  the 
differential  limen  of  nuance  {nuances  claires  and  nuances  foncces,  that  is, 
changes  of  tint  involving  at  the  same  time  changes  of  chroma.  Nothing 
is  said  of  the  equation  of  tint  and  chroma  as  a  preliminary  to  the  finding 
of  the  differential  limen  of  hue.)  (3)  Visual  acuity  is  measured  by  a  set  of 
optotypes,  resembling  those  of  Sulzer,  (4)  and  the  extent  of  the  field  of 
vision  by  Polack's  perimeter,  (5)  The  duration  of  visual  sensations 
(method  of  intermittence)  may  be  ascertained  either  by  rotating  discs 
(Pierre  Janet's  arrangement,  with  regulator  and  counter)  or  by  Michotte  's 
tachistoscope.  Ch.  v.  deals  with  the  measurement  of  auditory  sensations, 
(i)  The  acousiaesthesiometer  (drops  of  water  fall  upon  a  sloping  plate  of 


59^  BOOK  REVIEWS 

aluminium  which  gives  the  a  of  217.5  vs.:  apparently,  the  authors  count 
in  complete  vibrations)  takes  the  place  of  the  more  familiar  acoumeters. 
(2)  The  lower  limit  of  pitch  is  found  by  the  siren;  the  upper  limit  by 
Koenig's  cylinders  or  the  Galton  whistle;  the  differential  limen  by  forks 
of  variable  pitch.  (3)  The  temporal  limen  of  tone  is  also  found  by  the 
siren;  the  duration  of  tonal  sensation  by  means  of  Sanford's  pendulum 
and  tuning  fork.  Ch.  vi.  describes  the  measurement  of  the  labyrinthine 
sensations,  (i)  Sensations  of  rotation  require  a  turn-table,  (2)  sensations 
of  translation  a  car  running  upon  rails. 

Pt.  II.  discusses  the  measurement  of  the  complex  phenomena  of  sense. 
Ch.  i.,  on  the  measurement  of  the  perceptions  connected  with  cutaneous 
sensations,  opens  with  experiments  on  (i)  the  cutaneous  space-sense. 
Here  we  have  four  main  experiments,  the  first  of  which,  on  the  differen- 
tiation of  contacts,  has  three  subdivisions:  the  distinction  of  simultaneous 
contacts  (haphiaesthesiometric  compasses  of  the  writers,  and  of  Michotte), 
the  spatial  distinction  of  successive  contacts,  and  the  spatial  discrimination 
of  two  points,  the  one  of  which  is  fixed,  while  the  other  is  moved  away  from 
it  at  an  uniform  rate  (Michotte).  Then  follow  experiments  on  the  localisa- 
tion of  a  contact,  absolute  or  relative;  on  the  various  movement  limens 
(kinesimeter  with  horse-hair  stimulator) ;  and  on  the  cutaneous  perception 
of  form  (stereoaesthesiometer).  (2)  The  stereognostic  perception  of  form 
is  determined  by  means  of  a  series  of  copper  balls  varying  from  sphere  to 
ovoid;  the  forms  are  rolled  between  thumb  and  finger  tips  (dynamic 
stereoaesthesiometer).  (3)  The  perception  of  the  position  and  movement 
of  the  body  is  effected  by  a  vertical  tilt-board  (somatic  perception  of  the 
vertical)  and  an  adjustable  swing  (perception  of  displacement  in  the  ver- 
tical direction).  (4)  The  concluding  experiment  measures  the  illusion, 
with  passive  pressure,  of  open  and  filled  space.  Ch.  ii.  takes  up  the  per- 
ceptions connected  with  associated  visual  sensations,  (i)  The  percep- 
tion of  depth  is  studied  by  means  of  luminous  points  in  a  dark  room.  (2) 
Five  experiments  are  grouped  under  the  heading  of  perception  of  magnitude : 
the  discrimination  of  the  lengths  of  horizontal  and  vertical  lines;  of  the 
relative  position  of  two  points  within  a  circle  (the  one  point  is  fixed,  the 
other  is  radially  and  angularly  variable) ;  of  angles  of  different  magnitudes ; 
and  of  the  areas  of  circles  and  squares.  (3)  The  perception  of  form  may 
be  measured  either  by  the  solid  forms  of  the  stereoaesthesiometer,  or  by 
way  of  series  of  plane  figures,  in  which  the  circle  changes  to  the  ellipse  or  the 
square  to  the  oblong.  (4)  The  movement  limens  are  determined  by  the 
aid  of  luminous  points  in  a  dark  room.  (5)  A  few  typical  phenomena  of 
stereoscopic  vision  are  observed,  with  and  without  the  Brewster  prisms. 
(6)  The  time  of  perception  is  roughly  measured  by  a  simple  form  of  tach- 
istoscope  (photographic  shutter).  The  concluding  experiments  are 
devoted  (7)  to  some  typical  geometrical  illusions  (length  of  lines,  magni- 
tude of  areas,  direction  of  lines)  and  (8)  to  the  size- weight  illusion.  Ch. 
iii.,  on  the  measurement  of  perceptions  connected  with  associated  auditory 
sensations,  comprises  a  single  experiment,  on  the  localisation  of  sound  (the 
acousiaesthesiometer  is  employed).  Ch.  iv.  describes  two  experiments 
on  the  measurement  of  perceptions  connected  with  associated  sensations 
of  diverse  modalities,  (i)  The  sense  of  time  requires  somewhat  elaborate 
apparatus:  the  authors  describe  a  new-pattern  electric  chronoscope  (vol. 
ii.,  p.  31),  fitted  with  Pieron's  interrupter.  Short,  moderate  and  long 
times  (e.  g.,  times  of  150,  600  and  2,400  cr)  are  Hmited  by  impressions  of 
light  (Pliicker's  tube)  or  sound  (bell).  (2)  The  sense  of  rhythm  is  studied 
by  means  of  notched  discs  actuating  an  electric  interrupter.  Ch.  v.  brings 
us  to  the  measurement  of  sensory  attention,  (i)  The  difference  between 
surprised,  reflex  and  voluntary  attention  is  measured  by  the  brief  exposure, 
in  a  dark  room,  of  a  series  of  objects  presented  for  recognition, — without 
signal,  with  a  flash  of  light  given  0.02  sec.  before  illumination,  and  with  a 
preparatory  'Attention!'     (2)  The  reinforcement  of  sensory  intensity  is 


BOOK  REVIEWS  597 

shown  by  the  lowering  of  the  differential  limen  (Michotte's  movement- 
limen,  determined  as  in  ch.  i.,  compared  with  the  same  limen  under  simple 
distraction),  by  sustained  precision  of  perception  with  monotonous  repeti- 
tion of  stimuli  (special  form  of  the  cancellation  test),  and  by  the  fluctua- 
tion of  a  liminal  stimulus  (acousiaesthesiometer).  (3)  The  acceleration 
of  mental  processes  in  attention  is  proved  by  experiment  (i)  as  just 
described,  and  by  change  in  the  duration  of  simple  and  choice  reactions. 
(4)  The  fluctuations  of  attention  are  indicated  by  the  mean  variation  of 
the  reaction  times.  Ch.  vi.,  on  the  measurement  of  sensory  affectivity, 
recommends  experiments  by  the  serial  method  or  the  method  of  paired 
comparison  on  colors  and  tones,  taken  singly  or  in  groups  of  simultaneous 
or  successive  terms. 

Pt.  III.  discusses  the  measurement  of  phenomena  of  objectification . 
A  subjective  experience  may  be  objectified  in  two  ways:  by  stimulating 
to  a  motor  reaction,  which  produces  consequences  in  the  external  world, 
and  by  arousing  an  affirmation  of  external  existence.  The  second  or 
affirmative  mode  of  objectification  is  treated  in  ch.  i.  (i)  Assurance  of  testi- 
mony is  measured  by  the  familiar  test-picture  and  questionary.  (2) Suggesti- 
bility is  measured,  in  the  same  experiment,  by  the  addition  of  suggestive 
questions,  and  (on  its  sensory  side)  by  the  subjects'  liability  to  an  illusion 
of  warmth.  Ch.  ii.,  on  the  motor  mode  of  objectification,  opens  (i)  with 
an  account  of  the  apparatus  required  for  the  reaction  experiment;  we 
have  already  noticed  the  new  electric  chronoscope,  run  by  a  50  or  100  vs. 
electric  fork;  the  authors'  complete  set  of  instruments  for  visual,  auditory 
and  cutaneous  reactions  is  shown  on  p.  39.  (2)  Rate  of  voluntary  move- 
ment is  measured  by  a  simple  tapping  test  and  by  a  sorting  test.  (3) 
Accuracy  of  movement  is  measured,  most  simply,  by  a  tracing  test;  with 
sensory-motor  adaptation,  by  an  aiming  test;  symmetrically  by  rectilineal 
arm-movements  across  a  vertical  surface.  (4)  Motor  fatigue  and  the 
fluctuation  of  voluntary  effort  are  studied  by  the  dynamograph  or  ergo- 
graph.  (5)  Motor  suggestibility  is  measured  by  Binet's  belted  wheels; 
tendency  to  involuntary  movement  by  one  or  other  of  the  familiar  in- 
struments: the  observer  is  instructed  to  inhibit  all  movement  when  a 
certain  word  appears  in  a  list  read  out  to  him,  and  the  instruction  has  a 
positively  suggestive  effect.  (6)  The  limits  of  voluntary  movement  are 
determined  by  instruction  to  move  the  nostrils,  ears,  etc.,  and  by  experi- 
ments in  free  stereoscopy.  (7)  Motor  inhibition  is  approached  by  way 
of  the  reflex  wink  and  the  knee-jerk;  the  authors  figure  a  special  reflex- 
ometer  for  the  measurement  of  the  patellar  reflex. 

Pt.  IV.  discusses  the  measurement  of  intellectual  phenomena;  ch.  i.  is 
devoted  to  memory,  (i)  The  memory  of  elementary  perceptions  may  be 
determined  by  the  method  of  recognition,  with  all  forms  of  sensory  tech- 
nique; a  uniform  interval  of  i  min.  is  prescribed,  (2)  Special  tests  are 
outlined  for  the  memory  of  complex  perceptions:  kinesic  memory  is  in- 
vestigated by  means  of  tracing-forms;  auditory  memory  by  musical  tones, 
triads,  arpeggios,  and  melodic  fragments  (the  material  used  is  given  in  an 
appendix);  visual  memory  by  combinations  of  curved  and  straight  lines, 
by  pictures  of  simple  objects,  and  (as  memory  of  attitude  and  expression) 
by  observation  of  an  artist's  lay-figure.  This  last  test  seems  to  the  writer 
to  be  worthy  of  introduction  into  American  laboratories.  Memory  of 
physiognomy  and  of  complex  scenes  is  tested  by  means  of  paired  pictures, 
the  members  of  the  pair  differing  in  slight  details;  the  use  of  picture 
post-cards  is  recommended.  Five  experiments  are  described  under  the 
heading  (3)  verbal  and  intellectual  memory.  A  preliminary  section  deals 
with  the  manner  of  presentation  of  the  material ;  a  simple  exposure-screen, 
with  two  openings  for  alternate  use,  is  figured.  The  experiments — or 
rather  tests — are  concerned  with  the  memory  of  letters  and  figures,  of 
words  and  syllables,  of  phrases,  and  of  ideas  (meanings),  and  with  types  of 
memory;  samples  of  material  are  given  in  an  appendix.     The  tests  present 


598  BOOK   REVIEWS 

nothing  new;  and  we  therefore  pass  to  (4)  the  tests  of  acquisition.  These 
are  merely  outlined,  under  the  headings:  time  of  learning  (nonsense 
syllables),  economy  of  learning  (optimal  interval;  partial  vs.  global  learn- 
ing), the  influence  of  fatigue,  the  mutual  influence  of  the  perceptual  ele- 
ments (series  of  words  with  first  or  last  syllable  identical,  etc.),  and  motor 
apprenticeship  (typewriting  with  change  of  keys).  (5)  The  phenomena 
of  forgetting  are  examined  in  two  ways:  by  increase  of  the  interval  elaps- 
ing between  impression  and  recall,  and  by  counting  the  repetitions  neces- 
sary for  the  rememorising  of  a  forgotten  syllabic  series.  (6)  A  final  experi- 
ment is  devoted  to  the  phenomena  of  localisation,  i.  e.,  the  reproductiqn 
of  a  presented  temporal  or  spatial  order.  Ch.  ii.  deals  with  the  measure- 
ment of  the  phenomena  of  association.  Here  we  have  (i)  experiments  on 
free  association;  rate  is  measured  by  the  reaction  time  of  the  single 
association,  wealth  of  ideas  by  the  number  of  associations  effected  in  a 
given  time;  the  forms  of  connection  may  be  classified  as  intellectual, 
verbal,  and  accidental.  (2)  Constrained  association  may  be  simply  studied 
in  the  same  two  ways;  a  special  experiment  is  devoted  to  abstraction 
(superordination).  Imagination  is  also  brought  under  this  rubric:  an 
elementary  test  consists  in  the  presentation  of  words  (visual  or  auditory) 
for  reproduction  in  the  reverse  (literal  or  syllabic)  order;  complex  tests 
are  the  building  up  of  a  sentence  from  a  word,  or  of  a  narrative  from  a  phrase, 
and  the  description  of  a  picture.  Ch.  iii.  advances  to  the  measurement  of 
logical  phenomena,  (i)  Understanding  is  tested  by  the  time  required 
for  the  solution  of  a  very  simple  geometrical  problem.  (2)  Judgment  is 
tested,  ingeniously,  by  the  presentation  to  the  subject  of  sentences  or 
pictures,  some  of  which  are  reasonable  and  others  absurd;  the  element  of 
improbability  is  to  be  indicated.  (3)  Reasoning  is  tested  by  the  characteri- 
sation of  completed  syllogisms  as  correct  or  incorrect,  and  by  the  drawing 
of  a  conclusion  from  presented  premises.  (4)  Ingenuity  is  tested  by  a 
puzzle  (arrangement  of  blocks). 

Pt.  V.  is  entitled  "Determination  of  the  Individual  S5mthesis."  Ch. 
i.,  written  in  collaboration  with  Dr.  M.  Mignard,  treats  of  voluntary  con- 
trol, i.  e.,  of  the  synthesis  and  direction,  in  the  concrete  case,  of  the  ele- 
mentary functions  already  measured.  The  apparatus  used  for  the  reaction 
experiment  is  employed  to  determine  starting- times  (action),  stopping- 
times  (inhibition)  and  times  of  change  (decision);  the  actions  called  for 
are  simple, — tapping,  continuous  addition  or  subtraction,  etc.  Mental 
stability  is  tested  by  the  performance  of  experiments  under  various  forms 
of  distraction.  Finally,  the  extent  of  the  field  of  attention  is  measured  by 
the  assignment  of  a  twofold  instruction  (alternate  types  of  constrained 
association;  addition  and  counting  metronome  beats),  and  the  comparison 
of  the  results  with  those  of  the  corresponding  regular  experiments.  Ch. 
ii.  discusses  functional  correlations  and  the  comparison  of  individuals. 
It  is  impossible,  if  we  start  out  with  the  tests,  to  reach  a  general  measure 
of  character  or  ability,  or  to  determine  the  aptitude  of  the  subjects  for 
special  vocations.  On  the  other  hand,  we  may  start  out  with  subjects  of 
known  ability  or  disability,  and  by  examining  them  may  be  able  to  establish 
a  norm  of  test-performance;  or  with  any  selected  group  of  individuals, 
whom  we  may  rank  in  the  order  of  their  standing  under  some  particular 
test.  These  partial  comparisons  involve  a  comprehension  of  the  nature 
of  averages,  deviations,  and  formulas  of  correlation,  to  which  accordingly 
the  main  body  of  the  chapter  is  devoted.  Ch.  iii.  then  takes  up  the  role 
of  observation  in  the  determination  of  individual  type.  The  peculiarly 
social  side  of  human  nature  is  beyond  the  reach  of  experiment;  we  cannot 
study  our  fellow-men  as  we  can  study  animals,  under  the  all-inclusive 
rubric  of  behavior.  Even  if  we  have  at  our  disposal  the  backward  forms 
of  civilised  mentality,  or  specimens  of  the  backward  races,  a  measurement 
of  total  human  capacity  is  beyond  our  reach;  subjective  estimation  must 
still  play  a  part.     Indeed,  a  field  will  always  remain,  in  psychology,  for 


BOOK  RKVI^WS 


599 


observation:  individual  acquisition,  the  intellectual  sentiments,  automatic 
and  affective  tendencies,  the  forms  and  degrees  of  self-control, — topics  of 
this  kind  can  be  approached  only  by  the  observational  method,  which 
"deserves  a  kind  of  technique  of  its  own."  Whether  the  authors  intend 
to  write  this  supplementary  manual,  as  Dr.  Hallion  has  undertaken  to 
write  upon  physiological  psychology,  we  are  not  informed;  but  the  book 
is  advertised  to  appear  in  the  series.  B.  B.  T. 


BOOK  NOTES 


Zur   Analyse   der   Geddchtnistdtigkeit   und   des    Vorstellungsverlaufes,  von 
G.  E.  MU1.LER.     I   Teil.     Leipzig,   Johann  Ambrosius  Barth,    191 1. 
403  p.  I.  Abteilung,  Zeitsch.  f.  Psychologic,  hrsg.  von  F.  Schumann 
Brg.-Bd.  5. 
This  work  is  divided  into  four  parts,     i.  A  general  introduction,  state- 
ment of  problems,  discussion  of  types  and  their  mixtures,  etc.     2.  Self 
perception,  especially  in  experiments  on  memory;  here  are  included  the 
discussion  of  subjective  and  objective  observation,  the  psychic  process 
in  the  description  of  an  outer  object,  the  operation  of  self -observation  in  its 
various  forms,  methods  of  reminiscence,  etc.     3.  This  part  treats  of  the 
investigation  of  prominent  events  of  memory.     Here  we  have  accounts  of 
Riickel's  number,  sense  and  other  tests.     4.  The  fourth  division  treats  of  the 
complexes  built  during  the  process  of  learning. 

Les  localisations  cerehrales.  Esquisse  medicale  et  psychologique,  par  Jean 
Ferrand.  Paris,  Jules  Rousset,  191 1.  87  p. 
This  writer  concludes  that  the  point  of  departure  of  writers  of  researches 
on  cerebral  localizations  is  false.  Upon  certain  erroneous  facts  has  been 
built  a  wrong  psychic  doctrine  destined  to  give  intelligence  a  material 
explanation.  Certain  clinical,  anatomical  and  physiological  facts  have 
been  used  to  serve  a  philosophic  cause;  and  this  has  been  allowed  to  go  on 
on  account  of  the  preoccupations  of  metaphysicians.  One  result  is  the 
condemnation  of  the  theory  of  images  and  the  magnification  of  association- 
ism,  which  seems  now  to  have  triumphed  over  the  old  philosophical  spirit- 
ualism. 

The  function  of  suspense  in  the  catharsis,  by  W.  D.  Moriarty.  Ann 
Arbor,  Mich.,  George  Wahr,  191 1.  61  p. 
The  author  thinks  he  can  do  justice  to  this  subject  by  refraining  from 
such  questions  as  the  history  of  the  Aristotelian  catharsis  and  competing 
theories  and  confining  himself  to  discussing  the  function  of  suspense  in 
general,  then  in  the  drama,  and  third,  in  the  catharsis.  Starting,  then, 
from  the  drama,  the  author,  we  may  say,  cuts  loose  from  Aristotle.  The 
author  does  not  deem  it  necessary  to  define  exactly  beforehand  the  meaning 
of  suspense,  any  more  than  critics  agree  upon  what  catharsis  itself  is.  In 
the  higher  psychocrasis  the  author  distinguishes  the  functions  of  entangle- 
ment and  disentanglement  and  denouement;  and  in  the  last  part,  on  the 
nature  and  scope  of  the  catharsis,  he  tells  us  of  its  surface  theories,  its 
deeper  basis,  the  reasons  for  diverse  views,  and  its  true  scope. 

La  theorie  du  rythme  et  le  rythme  du  fran^ais  declame,  par  Eugene  Landray. 
Paris,  Librairie  Honore  Champion,  191 1.  427  p. 
This  comprehensive  work  is  divided  into  three  parts,  the  first  on  the 
theory  of  rhythm,  its  relations  to  movement,  perception,  art  and  discourse. 
The  second  part  treats  of  rhythm  in  French  contemporaneous  declamation, 
deals  with  energy  ,  duration,  accent,  pauses,  rhythmic  divisions,  syllabiza- 
tion,  verse  scansion,  metre.  The  third  part  is  devoted  to  examples  of 
declamation,  for  instance  in  comedy,  Mounet-Sully,  the  poets,  Italian 
verse,  nuance  of  duration  in  music,  etc. 


BOOK   NOTKS  •      6oi 

Experimental  studies  of  rhythm  and  time,  by  J.  E.  Wallace  Wallin.  Re- 
printed from  the  Psychological  Review,  March,   191 1.     Vol.   18,  p. 
100-131. 
This  investigation  leads  the  author  to  the  following  conclusions,     i. 
The  different  thresholds  for  time  are  invariably  smaller  than  the  first 
rhythm  limen  although  the  difference  is  not  large.     2.  The  different  thresh- 
olds are  relatively  smaller  for  the  longer  intervals.     3.  If  we  compare  the 
two  methods,  using  the  same  pattern,  it  appears  that  the  threshold  for  the 
continuous  method  is  slightly  smaller.     4.  As  to  patterns,  the  limens  are 
smdler  for  the  trochaic  than  for  the  iambic  type  of  measure.     5.  As  to  the 
size  of  the  time  limens,  the  smallest  relatively  to  the  interval  length  is  4.5%. 

The  essentials  of  mental  measurement,  by  Willlam  Brown.  Cambridge, 
University  Press,  1911.  i54P- 
This  work  is  written  for  the  professed  psychologists  who  are  interested 
in  quantitative  methods  and  in  biometric  methods  of  correlation.  The 
correlation  theory  ought  to  interest  educational  psychologists.  In  the 
first  part,  on  psychophysics,  the  author  discusses  mental  measurements  and 
psychophysical  methods,  and  in  the  second  part,  on  psychophysical  methods, 
its  mathematical  theory,  its  history,  its  experimental  results  and  its  signifi- 
cance in  psychology.  In  an  appendix  he  discusses  the  theories  of  Fechner, 
Miiller  and  Urban,  with  correlation  table,  etc.,  with  an  excellent  bibliog- 
raphy.    The  work  is  to  quite  an  extent  mathematical. 

An  introductory  psychology,  with  some  educational  applications,  by  Mel- 
bourne Stuart  Read.  Boston,  Ginn  &  Co.,  191 1.  309  p. 
This  writer  holds  that  the  main  truths  of  psychology  can  be  presented 
in  simple,  straightforward,  interesting  fashion  such  as  he  here  attempts. 
He  strives  especially  to  avoid  technicalities  that  would  tend  to  repel  rather 
than  attract,  and  give  the  impression  that  the  topics  are  abstruse  and  far 
away  instead  of  being  closest  of  all.  The  author  attempts  nothing  original 
but  merely  seeks  to  make  selections,  to  emphasize,  etc.  On  this  principle, 
he  first  discusses  consciousness  and  then  the  nervous  system,  attention, 
instinct,  impulse,  habit,  the  senses,  apperception,  feeling,  interest,  associa- 
tion, memory,  imagination,  concept,  emotion,  sentiment  and  will. 

The  essentials  of  psychology,  by  W.  B.  Pillsbury.  New  York,  the  Mac- 
millan  Company,  191 1.  362  p. 
The  author  attempts  here  to  present  the  accepted  facts  of  psychology, 
emphasis  being  placed  upon  fact  rather  than  theory.  Where  theories 
conflict  the  better  one  has  been  chosen  and  the  others  merely  neglected. 
His  point  of  view  is  functional  with  attention  to  what  mind  does  rather 
than  what  it  is.  He  stresses  the  outer  manifestations  of  consciousness,  and 
yet  uses  the  results  of  structural  psychology,  making  large  use  of  the 
hypothesis  of  the  synapse.  Thus  he  treats  first  of  the  nervous  system  and 
neural  action  in  relation  to  consciousness  and  behavior,  and  then  discusses 
sensation,  selection  and  control,  attention,  retention  and  association,  apper- 
ception, memory  and  magination,  reasoning,  instinct,  feelings,  the  emotions, 
action  and  will,  work,  fatigue  and  sleep,  interrelation  of  mental  functions, 
and  finally  the  cell. 

Introduction  to  psychology,  by  Robert  M.  Yerkes.  New  York,  Henry 
Holt  &  Co.,  191 1.  427  p. 
The  author  regards  psychology  as  a  description  of  consciousness,  and 
so  after  an  introductory  chapter  discusses  this  topic  in  various  aspects,  e.  g., 
concrete  experiences  or  varieties  of  consciousness,  analysis  and  the  problem 
of  psychological  elements,  syntheses  and  complex  experiences,  sensations  as 
elements  of  consciousness  and  their  properties,  psychic  complexes  of  apper- 
ception, feeling,  memory  and  imagination.     The  next  part  discusses  psy- 


6o2  BOOK   NOTKS 

chology  as  the  history  of  consciousness  or  genetic  description  in  the  individ- 
ual and  in  the  race.  This  subject  is  despatched  in  short  metre  and  the 
author  does  but  very  slight  justice  to  it.  The  next  part  treats  psychology 
as  generalizations  dealing  with  observations,  laws,  principles,  as  found  in 
apperception,  association,  affection  and  memory.  The  next  part  is  psy- 
chology as  explanation  and  correlation,  physical  and  psychic,  bodily  and 
mental  processes,  behavior  and  consciousness,  while  the  last  part  deals 
with  the  control  of  the  mental  life,  education,  eugenics,  etc. 

Some  neglected  factors  in  evolution;  an  essay  in  constructive  biology.     By 
Henry  M.  Bernard.  Edited  by  Matilda  Bernard.     New  York,  G.  P. 
Putnam's  Sons,  191 1.     489  p. 
This  book  contains  the  mature  results  of  twenty  years  of  biological 
research  to  which  the  author  brought  a  mind  trained  by  mathematical  and 
philosophical  studies.     In  1889,  under  Haeckel  at  Jena,  he  took  up  the 
problem  of  the  origin  of  the  Crustacea.     He  later  became  greatly  interested 
in  entoptic  phenomena  and  made  a  comparative  study  of  vertebrate  retinas 
which  he  thought  did  not  consist  of  cells,  as  is  usually  stated,  but  a  network 
of  nodes  which  are  formed  by  nuclei.   This  led  him  to  doubt  that  the  cell  is, 
after  all,  the  unit  of  structure  of  all  tissue ;  he  felt  that  it  needed  explanation. 
He  finally  reached  the  conclusion  that  in  all  living  organisms  there  is  a 
"protomitomic  network."     There  must  be  more  than  one  unit  of  structure. 
Periodicity  and  rhythm  interested  him  also. 

Medical  revolution,  by  Sydney  W.  Macilwaine.  London,  P.  S.  King 
&  Son,  191 1.  162  p. 
This  author  pleads  for  a  national  preservation  of  health  based  on  the 
natural  interpretation  of  disease.  He  has  lately  retired  from  a  long  experi- 
ence and  puts  his  criticisms  of  the  present  practice  of  medicine  in  a  plain, 
simple  way  in  the  form  of  an  appeal  to  the  people.  His  conception  is 
based  on  Darwinism.  All  depends  on  the  conception  of  disease,  whether 
it  is  only  negatively  a  deficiency  of  health  or  a  symptom  group  with  a 
special  causation  as  in  specific  diseases.  Diseases  are  of  two  kinds:  those 
arising  from  the  environment,  extrinsic,  and  these  may  be  of  three  kinds 
— parasitism,  poisoning  and  traumatism;  and  the  second  class  rising  from 
the  patient's  constitution.  These  are  intrinsic  and  fall  into  five  groups — 
incomplete  development,  constitutional  defect,  overwork,  deficient  work, 
wear  and  tear.  Now  to  diagnose  is  to  determine  which  series  the  disease 
belongs  to.  Merely  to  determine  the  symptom  group  is  not  to  find  the 
cause.  Specialism  must  disappear  and  the  hospital  system  must  be  re- 
formed. 

La  pensee  contemporaine:  les  grands  problemes.  Par  Paui*  Gaui^TiER. 
Paris,  Hachette  et  Cie,  191 1.  312  p. 
The  great  problems  here  discussed  are  convention  in  the  sciences,  the 
reality  of  the  sensible  world,  the  inner  life,  the  originality  of  sentiment, 
the  reign  of  liberty,  the  beauty  of  art,  the  virtue  of  morals,  social  reform, 
political  necessity,  the  end  of  monism,  the  future  of  pluralism,  and  the 
value  of  action.  These  he  deems  the  chief  problems  of  our  day  in  both  the 
theoretical  and  the  practical  field.  He  strives  to  be  at  once  ideaUstic  and 
practical. 

L'annee  psychologique,  publiee  par  AjuFrED  BinET.  17th  year.  Paris, 
Masson  et  Cie,  191 1.  498  p. 
In  this  volume  the  bibliographical  analyses  include  pages  389  to  496  and 
follow  the  usual  rubrics;  all  the  rest  of  the  volume  is  taken  up  with  original 
memoirs.  In  one  Binet  discusses  what  is  an  emotion  and  what  is  an  in- 
tellectual act;  Cruchet,  the  psycho-physoliogical  development  of  the  infant 
from  birth  to  two  years.     There  are  articles  on  special  methods  in  psychol- 


BOOK  NOTES  603 

ogy;  the  relation  of  the  school  and  society;  psycho-physiology  and  mystic 
states;  new  studies  on  the  measure  of  intellectual  level  of  school  children; 
psychic  functions  in  mental  diseases;  morbid  altruism;  the  delirium  of 
interpretation  and  systematized  delusions;  definition  of  alienation;  mental 
confusion;  parallels  in  the  classification  of  alienists. 

Puhertdt  und  Sexualitdt;  Untersuchungen  zur  Psychologie  des  EntwicklungS' 
alters,  von  August  Kohl.  Wurzburg  Curt  Kabitzsch,  191 1.  82  p. 
The  author  first  discusses  the  time  of  unconscious  sexuality  or  of  ignorance 
as  to  the  nature  of  these  phenomena,  which  he  describes  as  a  period  of 
longing,  yearning,  vague  and  indefinite  as  is  its  nature.  In  the  second 
chapter  he  characterizes  the  pubertal  development  of  the  young  man  and 
devotes  another  chapter  to  the  young  woman.  The  best  trait  of  the  book 
is  the  description  of  the  mental  characteristics  of  the  dim  and  vague  mental 
trance  of  this  period  of  life. 

Die  Traumdeutung,  von  Sigm.  Freud.  3d.  enl.  ed.  Leipzig,  Franz  Deu- 
ticke,  191 1.  418  p. 
Although  nine  years  elapsed  between  the  first  and  the  second,  only  a  little 
more  than  one  year  passed  between  the  second  and  the  third  editions  of 
this  work.  In  this  new  edition,  the  writer  has  taken  note  of  his  coadjutors, 
particularly  Steckel  and  Otto  Ranck,  who  have  co-operated  with  him  in 
making  additions  and  particularly  the  new  citations  of  literature. 

Recherches  sur  les  sensations  de  rotation,  par  B.  Bourdon.  Rennes,  Oberthur, 
191 1.  46  p.  (Extrait  du  Bulletin  de  la  Societe  scientifique  et  medi- 
cale  de  r Quest,     t.  XX,  no.  i,  1911.) 

II  subcosciente,  da  Roberto  Assagiou.  Firenze,  Biblioteca  Filosofica 
1911.     30  p. 

Un  nouvel  accoumetre,  par  B.  Bourdon.  Extrait  du  Bulletin  de  la  Societ6 
scientifique  et  medicale  de  I'Ouest,  4^  trimestre  1910.     6  p. 

L'anima.     Firenzi,  Anno  i,  Numero  2,  Febbraio  191 1.     pp  35-62. 

Psychologische  Studien,  hrsg  von  Wilhelm  Wundt.  Leipzig,  Wilhelm 
Engelmann,  191 1 .  140  p.  (Neue  Folge  der  ^hilosophischen  Studien.) 
VII.  Hefte  I  und  2. 

Trasformazione  e  suhlimazione  delle  energie  sessuali,  da  R.  Assagioli. 
Bologna,  Emiliano,  191 1.  11  p.  (Estratto  dalla  Rivistadi  Psicologia 
Applicata,  pubblicata  e  diretta  da  G.  C.  Ferrari.  Maggio-Giugno 
191 1,  Anno  VII,  N.  3.) 

Proceedings  of  the  Society  for  Psychical  Research.  August,  191 1.  p.  364- 
476.  Printed  for  the  Society  by  Robert  Maclehose  &  Co.,  Limited, 
Glasgow,  University  Press. 

Proceedings  of  the  American  Medico-Psychological  Association  at  the  66th 
annual  meeting,  held  in  Washington,  D.  C,  May  3-6,  1910.  Published 
by  the  Medico-Psychological  Association,   1910.     514  p. 

On  certain  electrical  processes  in  the  human  body  and  their  relation  to  emotional 
reactions,  by  Frederick  Lyman  Wells  and  Alexander  Forbes. 
Archives  of  Psychology,  No.  16,  March,  191 1.  New  York,  Science 
Press.     39  p. 

Suhakute  Raucher paranoia  und  einige  andere  Fdlle  von  diffusem  Beachtungs- 
wahn  aus  dem  Gefiihle  suhjektiver  Unruhe  oder  unbestimmter  Angst 
{drohenden  Unheils),  unbestimmter  Erwartung,  und  aus  dem  Gefiihle 
allegmein  erhohter  Importanz  der  Eindrucke,  von  Max  Lowy.  Zeit- 
schrift  fiir  die  gesamte  Neurologic  und  Psychiatric,  19 10.  Band  5, 
Heft  4.     p.  605-632. 


604  BOOK  NOTES 

Stereotype  " pseudokatatone"  Bewegungen  bei  leichtester  Bewusstseinsstdrung 
(im  "hysterischen"  Ausnahmszustande),  von  Max  Lowy.  Zeitschrift 
fiir  die  gesamte  Neurolgie  und  Psychiatric.  19 lo.  Band  i,  Heft  3, 
p.  330-340. 

Indian  languages  of  Mexico  and  Central  America  and  their  geographical 
distribution,  by  Cyrus  Thomas,  assisted  by  John  R.  Swanton. 
Accompanied  by  a  linguistic  map.  Gov't  printing  office,  1 9 1 1 .  1 08  p . 
Smithsonian  Institution,  Bureau  of  American  Ethnology,  Bulletin  44. 

Antiquities  of  the  Mesa  Verde  National  Park,  Cliff  Palace,  by  jEssiB  Walter 
Fewkes.  Gov't  printing  office,  191 1.  82  p.  Smithsonian  Institu- 
tion, Bureau  of  American  Ethnology,  Bulletin  51. 

Indian  tribes  of  the  lower  Mississippi  valley  and  adjacent  coast  of  the  gulf  of 
Mexico,  by  John  R.  Swanton.  Gov't  printing  office,  191 1.  387  p. 
Smithsonian  Institution,  Bureau  of  American  Ethnology,  Bulletin  43. 

Preliminary  report  on  a  visit  to  the  Navaho  national  monument,  Arizona, 
by  Jesse  Walter  Fewkes.  Gov't  printing  office,  191 1.  35  p. 
Smithsonian  Institution,  Bureau  of  American  Ethnology,  Bulletin  50. 


BERLIN  RESEARCH  FELLOWSHIP 

It  is  perhaps  not  generally  known  that  the  Sarah  Berliner  Research 
Fellowship  for  Women  (an  annual  fellowship  of  $1,000  "open  to  women 
holding  the  degree  of  doctorate  of  philosophy  or  to  those  similarly  equipped," 
and  "available  for  study  and  research  in  physics,  chemistry  or  biology"), 
and  the  biennial  prize  of  $1,000  offered  by  the  Naples  Table  Association 
"for  the  best  thesis  written  by  a  woman,  on  a  scientific  subject,  embodying 
new  observations  and  new  conclusions  based  on  an  independent  laboratory 
research  in  biological,  chemical  or  physical  science"  are  open  to  workers 
in  psychology.  Applications  for  the  exact  conditions  should  be  made  to 
Mrs.  C.  L.  Franklin,  Chairman  of  the  Sarah  Berliner  Committee,  527 
Cathedral  Parkway,  New  York,  or  to  Dr.  Jane  Welch,  Baltimore,  Md., 
of  the  Naples  Table  Association. 


SUBJECT  INDEX 


Abnormal  psychology,  323;  408;  460;  abnormalities  of  adolescence,  445; 
apraxia,  65;  drowsiness,  99;  experimental  psychopathology,  460; 
psychopathology  of  every  day  life,  477. 

Abstraction,  589. 

Adolescence,  mental  abnormalities  of,  445. 

^Esthetics,  137. 

Affection:  affective  tendencies,  311;  affective  value  of  colors,  112;  114; 
fluctuations  in  affection,  579;  affective  influence  of  area  of  stimulus, 
578;  affective  influence  of  fatigue,  112. 

Anaesthetics,  333. 

Animal  psychology.     See  comparative  psychology. 

Annee  psychologique,  316. 

Anthropology,   317;  447;  linguistic  stocks,    120;  linguistic  types,    120. 

Area  of  stimulus,  thermal,  325;  affective,  578. 

Association :  effect  of  practice,  i , 

Attention,  462. 

Attitudes  of  consciousness,  214. 

Auditory  localization,  250. 

Body  and  mind,  449. 

Book  notes;  132;  319;  468;  600. 

Child  study,  125;  446;  reasoning  in  children,  133. 

Color-blindness,  369. 

Comedy:  the  aesthetic  principle  in,  139. 

Comparative  psychology:  auditory  discrimination  in  raccoons,  116;  imi- 
tation in  raccoons  583;  instinct,   131;  mental  evolution,  453. 

Consciousness,  and  learning,  158;  anaesthetics,  333;  conscious  attitudes, 
214;  consciousness  of  self,  540. 

Correlation  in  psychology,  129. 

Craniometry,  317.  *" 

Dreams,  124;  127;  455;  460;  463. 

Drowsiness,  99. 

Emotion,  311;  317. 

Eugenics,  456. 

Evolution,  304;  453. 

Fatigue  and  affective  judgments,  112;  products  of  fatigue,  126. 

Freudian  literature,  408. 

Gustation,  528. 

Hypnotism  and  suggestion,  126;  134;  462. 

Images,  intensity  of,  346. 

Imagination,  127. 

Imitation  in  raccoons,  583. 

Instinct,  131. 


6o6  SUBJECT  INDEX 

James's  psychology,  447. 

Learning,  158. 

Meaning,  553. 

Memory,  445. 

Mental  measurement,  94;  298;  307. 

Miscellaneous:  American  music,  445;  Annee  psychologique,  316;  craniome- 
try, 317;  James's  psychology,  447;  Palladino,  125;  sense-organs  of 
plants,  127. 

Montgomery,  Edmund,  475. 

Philosophy:  dogmatism  and  evolution,  304;  history  of  philosophy,   125; 
introduction  to  philosophy,   588;  metaphysics  of  a  naturalist,    124;  ^ 
phenomenology  of  mind,  309. 

Physical  factors  affecting  reaction  time,  86. 

Practice  effects  in  free  association,  i. 

Psychometry,  94;  298. 

Psychopathology  of  apraxia,  65;  of  everyday  life,  477. 

Reaction  time,  86;  reaction  key,  86. 

Self,  consciousness  of,  541. 

Spatial  perception,  auditory,  250. 

Spiritism,  122;  323. 

Synaesthesia,  528. 

Thermal  sensitivity,  325. 

Terminology,  444. 

Tests,  mental  and  physical,  129;  307, 

Text-books  of    psychology:    Calkins,  127;     Pillsbury,  601;    Read,    601;  :: 

Thorndike,  128;  Titchener,  313;  Toulouse  and  Pieron,  593;  Yerkes,  \ 

601. 

Understanding,  conscious  concomitants  of,  14;  meaning  and  under- 
standing, 553. 

Wundt,  Kleine  Schriften,  446;  bibliography,  586. 


NAMES  OF  AUTHORS 


(The  names  of  those  who  have  contributed  original  matter  are  printed 

in  SMAIvL   CAPITALS.) 


Abramowski,  Edouard  473 
AcHKR,  Rudolph  408 
Aitken,  H.  F.  136 
Angell,  Frank  86 
AsHER,  W.  451 
Assagioli,  Roberto  603 

Baillie,  J.  B.  132,  309 
Baird,  J.  W.  131 
Bajenoff,  —  460 
Balfour,  Arthur  James  134 
Barnholt,  Sarah  E.  325 
Bastian,  H.  Charlton  468 
Benedict,  Francis  G.  127 
Bentley,  Madison  325 
Bergson,  Henri  473 
Bemaldo  de  Quiros,  C.  322 
Bernard,  Henry  M.  602 
Bernard,  Matilda  602 
Binet,  Alfred  125,  316,  602 
Bloomfield,  Daniel  474 
Boas,  Franz  473 
Bode,  B.  H.  304 
Bonnet,  Geraud  473 
Bonser,  Frederick  G.  133 
Book,  W.  F.  319,  589 
Booth,  David  S.  473 
Bourdon,  B.  603 
Brown,  Warner  134 
Brown,  William  129,  601 
Bruce,  Alexander  319 
Bumke,  O.  449 

Calkins,  Mary  Whiton  127 

Carpenter,  Thome  M.  127 

Cams,  Paul  319,  471 

Castella,  G.  319 

Cellerier,  Lucien  136 

Cesaresco,  Eugenio  Martinengo  133 

Chamberlain,  Alexander  F.  120, 

317 
Citron,  Julius  136 
Clark,  Dorothy  578 
Clarke,  Helen  Maud  214 
Cline,  M.  135 
Clouston,  T.  S.  468 
Cohn,  Jonas  474 


Collins,  Ruth  250 
Cook,  Helen  Dodd  135 
CoRiAT,  Isador  H.  65 
Crawford,  Dorothy  579 
Crothers,  S.  McC.  472 
Cushman,  Herbert  Ernest  125 
Cutten,  George  Barton  469 

Dearborn,  George  V.  N.  321 
Densmore,  Frances  447 
Des  Bancels,  Larguier  316 
Dieffenbacher,  Julius  474 
Dittrich,  Ottmar  471 
Doncaster,  L.  320 
Downey,  June  E.  133,  528 
Dubois,  J.  311 
Dunlap,  Knight  444 

Eastman,  Charles  Alexander  470 
Ellis,  Havelock  322,  463 
Erskine,  William  452 

Ferrand,  Jean  600 

Ferree,  C.  E.  250 

Fewkes,  Jesse  Walter  604 

Field,  James  445,  447,  455,  460 

Finck,  Franz  Nikolaus  120,  136 

Findlay,  J.  J.  472 

Fite,  Warner  321 

Forbes,  Alexander  603 

Foster,  W.  S.  124,  316 

Fowke,  G.  447 

Francis,  W.  448 

Frank,  Henry  473 

Frank,  L.  136 

Freud,  Sigmund  135,  603 

Gatewood,  L.  C.  136 
Gaultier,  Paul  602 
Gaupp,  Robert  125 
Geissler,  Iv.  R.  586 
GooDELL,  Mary  S.  578 
Graf,  Max  320 
Gregor,  Adalbert  135,  451 

Haberlandt,  G.  127 
Hahne,  Hans  320 


6o8 


NAMES   OF    AUTHORS 


Hall,  G.  Stanley  122 
Hart,  Bernard  319 
Hayes,  Samuel  P.  369 
Hegel,  G.  W.  F.  132,  309 
Heitmann,  Henry  309 
Herbert,  S.  319 
Herrick,  C.  L.  124,  135 
Hichens,  Robert  452 
Hirschfeld,  Magnus  135 
Hodge,  F.  W.  447 
Hoflfman,  Louis  470 
HOLLING WORTH,  H.  L.  99,  133 
HUGINS,  C.  R.  456 

Isaacson,  A.  450 

Jacobson,  Edmund  333,  553 
Janet,  Pierre  319,  321 
J  astro  w,  Joseph  122,  126,  319 
Jerusalem,  William  322,  472,  588 
Johnston,  R.  M.  472 
Jones,  Ernest  477 
Jones,  Francis  445,  449 
Judd,  C.  H.  135 

Kakise,  Hikozo  14 
KAI.LEN,  Horace  M.  137 
Karishka,  Paul  128 
Keller.  Adolf  473 
Kent,  Grace  Helen  320 
Kohl,  August  603 
Krebs,  Stanley  Le  Fevre  125 
Krueger,  Felix  135 

Lagenardi^re,  R.  de  445 

Laguna,  Grace  Andrus  De  133,  304 

Laguna,  Theodore  De  133,  304 

Lamont,  Frances  448 

Landray,  Eugene  600 

Lang,  J.  A.  473 

Lankester,  Edwin  Ray  134 

Lavrand,  H.  460 

Legrain,  —  136,  460 

Lemaitre,  A,  445 

Lipmann,  Otto  474 

Lombard,  Louis  445 

Lomer,  C.  R.  448 

Lomer,  Gerhard  R.  319 

Lowy,  Max  136,  603,  604 

Lutz,  Frank  E.  472 

Macilwaine,  Sydney  W.  602 
Marie,  A.  136,  460 
Mark,  E.  L.  473 
Masselon,  Rene  124,  460 
Maxim,  Hudson  133,  458 
McCabe,  Joseph  320,  453 
Meunier,  Paul  124,  460 
Meunier,  Raymond  136,  460 


Mitchell,  Arthur  473 
Moll,  Albert  320 
Moore,  Thomas  Vemer  589 
Morgulis,  Sergius  474 
Moriarty,  W.  D.  600 
Morison,  Elizabeth  448 
Morosoef,  N.  A.  135 
Miiller,  G.  E.  600 
Mumford,  E.  E.  R.  446 
Miinsterberg,  Hugo  319 
Myers,  Charles  472 

Nicholson,  Anne  M.  126 
NoRRis,  Ethel  L.  112 

Oppenheim,  H.  319 
Ordahl,  Louise  Ellison  158 
/3sbom,  Albert  S.  322 
Osborn,  Henry  Fairfield  32 1 
Ossipoff,  —  460 

Partridge,  G.  E.  468 
Pelletier,  M.  134 
Perler,  Otto  446,  463 
Peterson,  Harvey  Andrew  319 
Pfister,  Oskar  134 
Pfungst,  Oskar  472 
Pieron,  H.  472,  593 
Pikler,  Julius  136 
Pillsbury,  W.  B.  473,  601 
Potts,  W.  A.  321 
Power,  S.  445,  447 
Prince,  Morton  135,  319 
Pringsheim,  Hans  135 

Rahn,  Carl  L.  472 
Ranschburg,  Paul  474 
Read,  Melbourne  Stuart  601 
Rehmke,  Johannes  319 
Ribbert,  Hugo  135 
Ribot,  Theodule  319 
Rignano,  E.  311 
Rosanoff,  A.  J.  320 
Ruge,  Arnold  323 
Rutz,  Ottmar  450 

Safford,  F.  H.  94 

Saleeby,  Caleb  W.  456 

Salvio,  Alfonso  de  322 

Sanders,  Charles  F.  322,  472,  588 

Schaub,  Alma  de  VriES  346 

Schlesinger,  Abraham  135,  473 

Schneider,  Rudolf  473 

Schoppa,  A.  127 

Schulze,  Rudolf  470 

Scott,  I.  448 

Scott,  Walter  Dill  473 

Sergi,  Sergio  317 

Sharga,  Ikbal  Kishen  447 


NAMES  OF   AUTHORS 


609 


Shaw,  Charles  Gray  469 
Shaw,  Marino w  A.  458 
Sheldon,  W.  H.  588 
Shepherd,  William  T.   116,  469, 

583 
Shuttleworth,  G.  E.  321 
Sidis,  Boris  135 
Simon,  Th.  316 
Slaughter,  J.  W.  472 
Smith,  Theodate  L.  124,  311 
Snell,  A.  L.  470 
Snowden,  James  H.  128 
Sokolowsky,  Alexander  470 
Stoker,  Bram  468 
Stroehlin,  G.  474 
Stumpf,  C.  472 
Stumpf,  E.  J.  G.  127 
Swanton,  John  R.  604 
Swoboda,  Hermann  473 

Talmey,  Max  132 
Tanner,  Amy  E.  122 
Thomas,  Cyrus  604 
Thorndike,  E.  L.  128,  307 
TiTCHENER,  Edward  Bradford 

126,  313,  446,  540,  586,  593 
Toulouse,  Ed.  472,  593 
Trine,  Ralph  Waldo  136 
Twiss,  Alice  G.  112 

Uexkiill,  J.  von  319 
Urban,  F.  M.  129,  298 


Vaschide,  N.  136,  460 
Vaux,  Carra  de  319 
Vecchio,  Giorgio  del  317 
Villiger,  Emil  470 
Violett,  Marcel  323 
Voigtlander,  Else  320 
Void,  J.  Mourly  133.  455 


Walker,  Charles  Edward  320 

Wallin,  J.  E.  Wallace  601 

Washburn,  M.  F.  112,  114, 578, 579 

Waterlow,  J.  448 

Watson,  John  B,  313 

Weber,  Ernst  471 

Weichardt,  Wolfgang  126 

Wells,  Frederic  Lyman  i,  603 

Welton,  J.  474 

Westell,  W.  Percival  321 

Whipple,  Guy  Montrose  132,  307 

White,  William  A.  134 

Wingfield,  H.  E.  126 

Winslow,  ly.  Forbes  134 

Winter,  P.  E.  453 

Wreschner,  A.  445 

Wundt,  W.  135,  446,  473,  603 


Yerkes,  Robert  M.  474,  601 
Ziegler,  Heinrich  Ernst  131,  135 


A 


0 


BlNOiw^  ^^'^   ^^^ 


1 

A5 

V.22 


American  journal  of 
psychology 


® 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY