Skip to main content

Full text of "Ancient law : its connection with the early history of society and its relation to modern ideas"

See other formats


This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on library shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project 
to make the world's books discoverable online. 

It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject 
to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books 
are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that's often difficult to discover. 

Marks, notations and other marginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book's long journey from the 
publisher to a library and finally to you. 

Usage guidelines 

Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the 
public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing this resource, we have taken steps to 
prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. 

We also ask that you: 

+ Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for 
personal, non-commercial purposes. 

+ Refrain from automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google's system: If you are conducting research on machine 
translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us. We encourage the 
use of public domain materials for these purposes and may be able to help. 

+ Maintain attribution The Google "watermark" you see on each file is essential for informing people about this project and helping them find 
additional materials through Google Book Search. Please do not remove it. 

+ Keep it legal Whatever your use, remember that you are responsible for ensuring that what you are doing is legal. Do not assume that just 
because we believe a book is in the public domain for users in the United States, that the work is also in the public domain for users in other 
countries. Whether a book is still in copyright varies from country to country, and we can't offer guidance on whether any specific use of 
any specific book is allowed. Please do not assume that a book's appearance in Google Book Search means it can be used in any manner 
anywhere in the world. Copyright infringement liability can be quite severe. 

About Google Book Search 

Google's mission is to organize the world's information and to make it universally accessible and useful. Google Book Search helps readers 
discover the world's books while helping authors and publishers reach new audiences. You can search through the full text of this book on the web 



at |http : //books . google . com/ 



HI 



3 2044 049 682 206 









L "^^ 



\ 

>' 






^," 



■Q/' 










yH 2 




; 



I 









4:!.- 



^ ANCIENT Lit : •''"'■''''M 



ITS CONNEOTION 
WITH THE BAELT HISTOBT OF SOCIETT, KSil> ITS BELATION TO 

MOBEEN IDEAS. 



BY HENEY SUMNEE MAINE, 

KJBAsmB cnr jtoisvbusisos ars> chs oxtil law at thi middlb nicru, akd vobicsblt bxoius 
nonsBOB ov xhb cnrn, law nr vhb uitiybbsztt ov cahbbisob. 



LONDON! 

JOHN MFEEAT, ALBEMAELE 8TEEET. 

1861. 



lY'^l 



M^i^A 



Le ip- <- ■ /^^ 



/ 



f 



PREFACE. 



The chief object of the following pages is to indicate 
some of the earliest ideas of mankind, as they are 
reflected in Ancient Law, and to point out the rela- 
tion of those ideas to modem thought. Much of the 
inquiry attempted could not have been prosecuted 
with the slightest hope of a useful result if there had 
not existed a body of law, like that of the Romans, 
bearing in its earliest portions the traces of the most 
remote antiquity and supplying from its later rules 
the staple of the civil institutions by which modem 
society is even now controlled. The necessity of 
taking the Roman law as a typical system, has com- 
pelled the author to draw from it what may appear 
a disproportionate number of his illustrations; but it 
has not been his intention to write a treatise on Ro- 
man jurisprudence, and he has as much as possible 
avoided aU discussions which might give that appear- 



VI PREFACE. 

ance to his work. The space allotted in the Third 
and Fourth Chapters to certain philosophical theories * 
of the Roman Jurisconsults, has been appropriated to 
them for two reasons. In the first place, those theo- 
ries appear to the author to have had a much wider 
and more permanent influence on the thought and 
action of the world than is usually supposed. Se- 
condly, they are believed to be the ultimate source of 
most of the views which have been prevalent, till 
quite recently, on the subjects treated of in this 
volume. It was impossible for the author to proceed 
far with his undertaking, without stating his opinion 
on the origin, meaning, and value of those specu- 
lations. 

H. S. M. 

London : January, 1861. 



CONTENTS. 







Chap. 

I. Ancient Codes 

II. Legal Fictions 

III. Law of Nature and Equity .... 

IV. The Modern History of the Law of Nature 
V. Primitive Society and Ancient Law 

VI. The Early History of Testamentary Succession 

VII. Ancient and Modern Ideas respecting Wills and 

Successions 

VJII. The Early History of Property 
EX. The Early History of Contract 
X. The Early History of Delict and Crime 



Paoi 
1 

21 

44 

73 

113 

171 

215 
244 
304 
367 



ERRATA. 

Page 6, line 9 from top, for " circumatanced " read " circumstence " 
16, line 11 from bottom, for •' attained" read "obtained " 



ANCIENT LAW. 



CHAPTER I. 

ANCIENT CODES. 



The most celebrated system of jurisprudence known 
to the world begins, as it ends, with a Code. From 
the commencement to the close of its history, the ex- 
positors of Roman Law consistently employed language 
which implied that the body of their system rested on 
the Twelve Decemviral Tables, and therefore on a 
basis of written law. Except in one particular, no 
institutions anterior to the Twelve Tables were re- 
cognised at Rome. The theoretical descent of Roman 
jurisprudence from a code, the theoretical ascrip- 
tion of English law to immemorial unwritten tradi- 
tion, were the chief reasons why the development of 
their system differed from the development of ours. 

/ ^ 



2 ANaENT CODES. chap. i. 

Neither theory corresponded exactly with the facts, 
but each produced consequences of the utmost im- 
portance. 

I need hardly say that the publication of the 
Twelve Tables is not the earliest point at which we 
can take up the history of law. The ancient Roman 
code belongs to a class of which almost every civilised 
nation in the world can show a sample, and which, so 
far as the Roman and Hellenic worlds were con- 
cerned, were largely diffused over them at epochs 
not widely distant from one another. They appeared 
under exceedingly similar circumstances, and were 
produced, to our knowledge, by very similar causes. 
Unquestionably, many jural phenomena lie behind 
these codes and preceded them in point of time. Not 
a few documentary records exist which profess to 
give us information concerning the early phenomena 
of law; but, until philology has effected a complete 
analysis of the Sanskrit literature, our best sources 
of knowledge are undoubtedly the Greek Homeric 
poems, considered of course not as a history of actual 
occurrences, but as a description, not wholly ideal- 
ised, of a state of society known to the writer. How- 
ever the fancy of the poet may have exaggerated 
certain features of the heroic age, the prowess of 
warriors and the potency of gods, there is no reason 
to believe that it has tampered with moral or meta- 
physical conceptions which were not yet the subjects 



CHAP. I. RUDIMENTARY JURAL IDEAS. D 

of conscious observation ; and in this respect the 
Homeric literature is far more trustworthy than 
those relatively later documents which pretend to 
give an account of times similarly early, but which 
were compiled under philosophical or theological in- 
fluences. If by any means we can determine the early 
forms of jural conceptions, they will be invaluable to 
us. These rudimentary ideas are to the jurist what 
the primary crusts of the earth are to the geologist. 
They contain, potentially, all the forms in which law 
has subsequently exhibited itself. The haste or the 
prejudice which has generally refused them all but 
the most superficial examination, must bear the 
blame of the unsatisfactory condition in which we 
find the science of jurisprudence. The inquiries of 
the jurist are in truth prosecuted much as inquiry 
in physics and physiology was prosecuted before 
observation had taken the place of assumption. 
Theories, plausible and comprehensive, but absolutely 
unverified, such as the Law of Nature or the Social 
Compact, enjoy a universal preference over sober re- 
search into the primitive history of society and law ; 
and they obscure the truth not only by diverting 
attention from the only quarter in which it can be 
found, but by that most real and most important 
influence which, when once entertained and believed 
in, they are enabled to exercise on the later stages of 
jurisprudence. 

B 2 



4 ANCIENT CODES. chap. i. 

The earliest notions connected with the conception, 
now so fully developed, of a law or rule of life, are 
those contained in the Homeric words " Themis " and 
" Themistes." " Themis," it is well known, appears 
in the later Greek pantheon as the Goddess of 
Justice, but this is a modem and much developed 
idea, and it is in a very different sense that Themis 
is described in the Iliad as the assessor of Zeus. It is 
now clearly seen by all trustworthy observers of the 
primitive condition of mankind that, in the infancy 
of the race, men could only account for sustained or 
periodically recurring action by supposing a personal 
agent. Thus, the wind blowing was a person and of 
course a divine person ; the sun rising, culminating, 
and setting was a person and a divine person; the 
earth yielding her increase was a person and divine. 
As, then, in the physical world, so in the moral. 
When a king decided a dispute by a sentence, the 
judgment was assumed to be the result of direct 
inspiration. The divine agent, suggesting judicial 
awards to kings or to gods, the greatest of kings, 
was Themis. The peculiarity of the conception is 
brought out by the use of the plural. Themistes^ 
Themises, the plural of Themis, are the awards them- 
selves, divinely dictated to the judge. Kings are 
spoken of as if they had a store of " Themistes" ready 
to hand for use; but it must be distinctly understood 
that they are not laws, but judgments. " Zeus, or 




CHAP. I. TIIEMISTES. 

the human king on earth," says Mr. 
History of Greece, " is not a law-mal 
judge." He is provided with Themistes, but, con- 
sistently mth the belief in their emanation from 
above, they cannot be supposed to be connected by 
any thread of principle; they are separate, isolated 
judgments. 

Even in the Homeric poems, we can see that these 
ideas are transient. Parities of circumstancell^were 
probably commoner in the simple mechanism of an- 
cient society than they are now, and in the succes- 
sion of similar cases awards are likely to follow and 
resemble each other. Here we have the germ or 
rudiment of a Custom, a conception posterior to that 
of Themistes or judgments. However strongly we, 
with our modern associations, may be inclined to lay 
down a priori that the notion of a Custom must pre- 
cede that of a judicial sentence, and that a judgment 
must affirm a Custom or punish its breach, it seems 
quite certain that the historical order of the ideas is 
that in which I have placed them. The Homeric 
word for a custom in the embryo is sometimes 
" Themis" in the singular — more often " Dike," the 
meaning of which visibly fluctuates between a "judg- 
ment" and a " custom" or " usage." iNo/jto^, a Law, 
so great and famous a term in the political voca- 
bulary of the later Greek society, does not occur in 
Homer. 

II 3 



(M 



6 ANCIENT CODES. chat. i. 

This notion of a divine agency, suggesting the 
Themistes, and itself impersonated in Themis, must 
be kept apart from other primitive beliefs with which 
a superficial inquirer might confound it. The con- 
ception of the Deity dictating an entire code or body 
of law, as in the case of the Hindoo laws of Menu, 
seems to belong to a range of ideas more recent and 
more advanced. " Themis " and " Themistes " are 
much less remotely linked with that persuasion 
which clung so long and so tenaciously to the human 
mind, of a divine influence underlying and support- 
ing every relation of life, every social institution. In 
early law, and amid the rudiments of political 
thought, symptoms of this belief meet us on all 
sides. A supernatural presidency is supposed to 
consecrate and keep together all the cardinal institu- 
tions of those times, the State, the Race, and the 
Family. Men, grouped together in the different re- 
lations which those institutions imply, are bound to 
celebrate periodically common rites and to offer 
common sacrifices ; and every now and then the 
same duty is even more significantly recognised in 
the purifications and expiations which they perform, 
and which appear intended to deprecate punishment 
for involuntary or neglectful disrespect. Everybody 
acquainted >vith ordinary classical literature will 
remember the aacra gentilicia^ which exercised so 
important an influence on the early Roman law of 



CHAP. I. BENTHAM'S ANALYSIS. 7 

adoption and of wills. And to this hour the Hindoo 
Customary Law, in which some of the most curious 
features of primitive society are stereotyped, makes 
almost all the rights of persons and all the rules of 
succession hinge on the due solemnisation of fixed 
ceremonies at the dead man's funeral, that is, at 
every point where a breach occurs in the continuity 
of the family.. 

Before we quit this stage of jurisprudence, a 
caution may be usefully given to the English stu- 
dent. Bentham, in his " Fragment on Government," 
and Austin, in his " Province of Jurisprudence De- 
termined," resolve every law into a command of 
the lawgiver, an obligation imposed thereby on the 
citizen, and a sanction threatened in the event of 
disobedience ; and it is further predicated of the 
command^ which is the first element in a law, that 
it must prescribe, not a single act, but a series or 
number of acts of the same class or kind. The 
results of this separation of ingredients tally exactly 
with the facts of mature jurisprudence ; and, by a 
little straining of language, they may be made to 
correspond in form with all law, of all kinds, at all 
epochs. It is not, however, asserted that the notion 
of law entertained by the generality is even now 
quite in conformity with this dissection ; and it is 
curious that, the farther we penetrate into the primi- 
tive history of thought, the farther we find ourselves 

B 4 



8 ANCIENT CODES. chap. i. 

from a conception of law which at all resembles a 
compound of the elements which Bentham deter- 
mined. It is certain that, in the infancy of man- 
kind, no sort of legislature, not even a distinct 
author of law, is contemplated or conceived of. 
Law has scarcely reached the footing of custom; 
it is rather a habit. It is, to use a French phrase, 
"in the air." The only authoritative . statement of 
right and wrong is a judicial sentence after the 
facts, not one presupposing a law which has been 
\ violated, but one which is breathed for the first time 
Iby a higher power into the judge's mind at the 
Jmoment of adjudication. It is of course extremely 
difficult for us to realise a view so far removed 
from us in point both of time and of association, but 
it will become more credible when we dwell more 
at length on the constitution of ancient society, in 
which every man, living during the greater part of 
his life under the patriarchal despotism, was practically 
controlled in all his actions by a regimen not of law 
but of caprice. I may add that an Englishman 
should be better able than* a foreigner to appreciate 
the historical fact that the " Themistes " preceded 
any conception of law, because, amid the many in- 
consistent theories which prevail concerning the cha- 
racter of English jurisprudence, the most popular, or 
at all events the one which most afiects practice, is 
certainly a theory which assumes that adjudged 



f ^ 



CHAP. I. CUSTOMARY LAW. 9 

cases and precedents exist antecedently to rules, 
principles, and distinctions. The " Themistes " have 
too, it should be remarked, the characteristic which, 
in the view of Bentham and Austin, distinguishes 
single or mere commands from laws. A true law 
enjoins on all the citizens indiflferently a number 
of acts similar in class or kind ; and this is exactly 
the feature of a law which has most deeply impressed 
itself on the popular mind, causing the term " law " 
to be applied to mere uniformities, successions, and 
similitudes. A command prescribes only a single 
act, and it is to commands, therefore, that *' The- 
mistes" are more akin than to laws. They are 
simply adjudications on insulated states of fact, and 
do not necessarily follow each other in any orderly 
sequence. 

The literature of the heroic age discloses to us 
law in the germ under the " Themistes " and a little 
more developed in the conception of " Dike." The 
next stage which we reach in the history of juris- 
prudence is strongly marked and surrounded by the 
utmost interest. Mr. Grote, in the second part and 
second chapter of his History, has fully described 
the mode in which society gradually clothed itself 
with a different character from that delineated by 
Homer. Heroic kingship depended partly on divinely 
given prerogative, and partly on the possession of 
supereminent strength, courage, and wisdom. Gra- 

/LAW ^\m\X 

LIBRAiir.^ 




10 ANCIENT CODES. chap. t. 

dually, as the impression of the monarch's sacredness 
became weakened, and feeble members occurred in 
the series of hereditary kings, the royal power de- 
cayed, and at last gave way to the dominion of 
aristocracies. If language so precise can be used of 
the revolution, we might say that the office of the 
king was usurped by that council of chiefs which 
Homer repeatedly alludes to and depicts. At all 
events from an epoch of kingly rule we come every- 
where in Europe to an era of oligarchies; and even 
where the name of the monarchical functions does 
not absolutely disappear, the authority of the king 
is reduced to a mere shadow. He becomes a mere 
hereditary general, as in LacedaBmon, a mere func- 
tionary, as the King Archon at Athens, or a mere 
formal hierophant, like the Rex Sacrijiculus at Rome. 
In Greece, Italy, and Asia Minor, the dominant 
orders seem to have universally consisted of a 
number of families united by an assumed relation- 
ship in blood, and, though they all appear at first 
to have laid claim to a quasi-sacred character, their 
strength does not seem to have resided in their 
pretended sanctity. Unless they were prematurely 
overthrown by the popular party, they all ulti- 
mately approached very closely to what we should 
now understand by a political aristocracy. The 
changes which society underwent in the commu- 
nities of the further Asia occurred of course at 



CHAP. I. ARISTOCRATIC PERIOD. 11 

periods long anterior in point of time to these revo- 
lutions of the Italian and Hellenic worlds; but their 
relative place in civilisation appears to have been 
the same, and they seem to have 'been exceedingly 
similar in general character. There is some evidence 
that the races which were subsequently united under 
the Persian monarchy, and those which peopled the 
peninsiila of India, had all their heroic age and their 
era of aristocracies ; but a military and a religious 
oligarchy appear to have grown up separately, nor 
was the authority of the king generally superseded. 
Contrary, too, to the course of events in the West, 
the religious element in the East tended to get the 
better of the military and political. Military and 
civil aristocracies disappear, annihilated or crushed 
into insignificance between the kings and the sacer- 
dotal order; and the ultimate result at which we 
arrive is, a monarch enjoying great power, but cir- 
cumscribed by the privileges of a caste of priests. 
With these differences, however, that in the East 
aristocracies became religious, in the West civil or 
political, the proposition that a historical era of 
aristocracies .succeeded a historical era of heroic 
kings itiay be considered as true, if not of all man- 
kind, at aU events of all branches of the Indo-Euro- 
pean family of nations. 

The important point for the jurist is that these 
aristocracies were universally the depositaries and 



12 ANCIENT CODES. chap. r. 

administrators of law. They seem to have succeeded 
to the prerogatives of the king, with the important 
difference, however, that they do not appear to have 
pretended to direct inspiration for each sentence. 
The connection of ideas which caused the judgments 
of the patriarchal chieftain to be attributed to 
superhuman dictation still shows itself here and 
there in the claim of a divine origin for the entire 
body of rules, or for certain parts of it, but the 
pi?ogress of thought no longer permits the solution 
of particular disputes to be explained by supposing 
an extra-human interposition. What the juristical 
oligarchy now claims is to monopolise the know- 
ledge of the laws, to have the exclusive possession 
of the principles by which quarrels are decided. 
We have in fact arrived at the epoch of Customary 
Law. Customs or Observances now exist as a sub- 
stantive aggregate, and are assumed to be precisely 
known to the aristocratic order or caste. Our au- 
thorities leave us no doubt that the trust lodged 
with the oligarchy was sometimes abused, but it 
certainly ought not to be regarded as a mere usur- 
pation or engine of tyranny. Before the invention 
of writing, and during the infancy of the art, an 
aristocracy invested with judicial privileges formed 
the only expedient by which accurate preservation 
of the customs of the race or tribe could be at all 
approximated to. Their genuineness was, so far as 



CHAP. I. CUSTOMARY LAW. 13 

possible, insured by confiding them to the recollec- 
tion of a limited portion of the community. 

The epoch of Customary Law, and of its custody 
by a privileged order, is a very remarkable one. The 
condition of the jurisprudence which it implies has 
left traces which may still be detected in legal and 
popular phraseology. The law, thus known exclu- 
sively to a privileged minority, whether a caste, an 
aristocracy, a priestly tribe, or a sacerdotal college, 
is true unwritten law. Except this, there is no such 
thing as unwritten law in the world. English case-law 
is sometimes spoken of as unwritten, and there are 
some English theorists who assure us that if a code 
of English jurisprudence were prepared we should 
be turning unwritten law into written — a conversion, 
as they insist, if not of doubtful policy, at aU events 
of the greatest seriousness. Now, it is quite true 
that there was once a period at which the English 
common law might reasonably have been termed un- 
written. The elder English judges did really pretend 
to knowledge of rules, principles, and distinctions 
which were" not entirely revealed to the bar and to 
the lay-public. Whether all the law which they 
claimed to monopolise was really unwritten, is ex- 
ceedingly questionable ; but at all events, on the 
assumption that there was once a large mass of civil 
and criminal rules known exclusively to the judges, 
it presently ceased to be unwritten law. As soon as 



14 ANCIENT CODES. chap. i. 

the Courts at Westminster Hall began to base their 
judgments on cases recorded, whether in the year, 
books or elsewhere, the law which they administered 
became written law. At the present moment a rule 
of English law has first to be disentangled from the 
recorded facts of adjudged printed precedents, then 
thrown into a form of words varying with the taste, 
precision, and knowledge of the particular judge, and 
then applied to the circumstances of the case for ad- 
judication. But at no stage of this process has it 
any characteristic which distinguishes it from wiitten 
law. It is written case-law, and only diflferent from 
code-law because it is written in a different way. 

From the period of Customary Law we come to 
another sharply defined epoch in the history of juris- 
prudence. We arrive at the era of Codes, those 
ancient codes of which the Twelve Tables of Rome 
were the most famous specimen. In Greece, in Italy, 
on the Hellenised sea-board of Western Asia, these 
codes all made their appearance at periods much the 
same everywhere, not, I mean, at periods identical in 
point of time, but similar in point of the relative 
progress of each community. Everywhere, in the 
countries I have named, laws engraven on tablets and 
published to the people take the place of usages 
deposited with the recollection of a privileged oli- 
garchy. It must not for a moment be supposed that 
the refined considerations now urged in favour of what 



CHAP. I. ANCIENT CODES. 15 

is called codification had any part or place in the 
change I have described. The ancient codes were 
doubtless originally suggested by the discovery and 
diffusion of the art of writing. It is true that the 
aristocracies seem to have abused their monopoly of 
legal knowledge; and at all events their exclusive 
possession of the law was a formidable impediment to 
the success of those popular movements which began 
to be universal in the western world. But, though 
democratic sentiment may have added to their popu- 
larity, the codes were certainly in the main a direct 
result of the invention of writing. Inscribed tablets 
were seen to be a better depositary of law, and a 
better security for its accurate preservation, than the 
memory of a number of persons however strength- 
ened by habitual exercise. 

The Roman code belongs to the class of codes I 
have been describing. Their value did not consist in 
any approach to S3nnmetrical classifications, or to 
terseness and clearness of expression, but in their 
publicity, and in the knowledge which they furnished 
to everybody, as to what he was to do, and what not 
to do. It is, indeed, true that the Twelve Tables of 
Rome do exhibit some traces of systematic arrange- 
ment, but this is probably explained by the tradition 
that the framers of that body of law called in the 
assistance of Greeks who enjoyed the later Greek ex- 
perience in the art of law-making. The fragments of 



16 ANCIENT CODES. chap. i. 

the Attic Code of Solon show, however, that it had 
but little order, and probably the laws of Draco had 
even less. Quite enough too remains of these collec- 
tions, both in the East and in the West, to show that 
they mingled up religious, civil, and merely moral 
ordinances, without any regard to diflferences in their 
essential character; and this is consistent with all 
we know of early thought from other sources, the 
severance of law from morality, and of religion from 
law, belonging very distinctly to the later stages of 
mental progress. 

But, whatever to a modem eye are the singularities 
of these Codes, their importance to ancient societies 
was unspeakable. The question — and it was one 
which affected the whole future of each community — 
was not so much whether there should be a code at 
all, for the majority of ancient societies seem to have 
^ • 'attained them sooner or later, and, but for the great 
interruption in the history of jurisprudence created 
by feudalism, it is likely that all modem law would be 
distinctly traceable to one or more of these fountain- 
heads. But the point on which turned the history 
of the race was, at what period, at what stage of their 
social progress, they should have their laws put into 
writing. In the western world the plebeian or popular 
element in each State successfully assailed the oli- 
garchical monopoly, and a code was nearly universally 
obtained early in the history of the Commonwealth. 



CHAP. I. LAWS OF MENU. 17 

But, in the East, as I have before mentioned, the ruling 
aristocracies tended to become religious rather than 
military or political, and gained, therefore, rather than 
lost in power; while in some instances the physical 
conformation of Asiatic countries had the eflfect of 
making individual communities larger and more nu- 
merous than in the West ; and it is a known social law 
that the larger the space over which a particular set \ 
of institutions is diffused, the greater is its tenacity^ 
and vitality. From whatever cause, the codes obtained 
by Eastern societies were obtained, relatively, much 
later than by Western, and wore a very different cha- 
racter. The religious oligarchies of Asia, either for 
their own guidance, or for the relief of their memory, 
or for the instruction of their disciples, seem in all 
cases to have ultimately embodied their legal learn- 
ing in a code; but the opportunity of increasing 
and consolidating their influence was probably too 
tempting to be resisted. Their complete monopoly 
of legal knowledge appears to have enabled them to 
put off on the world collections, not so much of the 
rules actually observed as of the rules which the 
priestly order considered proper to be observed. The 
Hindoo code, called the Laws of Menu, which is 
certainly a Brahmin compilation, undoubtedly en- 
shrines many genuine observances of the Hindoo race, 
but the opinion of the best contemporary orientalists 
is, that it does not, as a whole, represent a set of rules 

c 



18 ANCIENT CODES. chap. i. 

ever actually administered in Hindostan. It is, in 
great part, an ideal picture of that which, in the view 
of the Brahmins, ought to be the law. It is consistent 
with human nature and with the special motives of 
their authors, that codes like that of Menu should 
pretend to the highest antiquity and claim to have 
emanated in their complete form from the Deity. 
Menu, according to Hindoo mythology, is an emana- 
tion from the supreme God ; but the compilation which 
bears his name, though its exact date is not easily dis- 
covered, is, in point of the relative progress of Hindoo 
jurisprudence, a recent production. 

Among the chief advantages which the Twelve 
Tables and similar codes conferred on the societies 
which obtained them, was the protection which they 
afforded against the frauds of the privileged oligarchy 
and also against the spontaneous depravation and 
debasement of the national institutions. The Roman 
Code was merely an enunciation in words of the 
existing customs of the Roman people. Relatively 
to the progress of the Romans in civilisation, it was 
a remarkably early code, and it was published at a 
time when Roman society had barely emerged from 
that intellectual condition in which civil obligation 
and religious duty are inevitably confounded. Now 
a barbarous society practising a body of customs, 
is exposed to some especial dangers which may be 
absolutely fatal to its progress in civilisation. The 



CHAF. I. VALUE OF THE CODES. 19 

usages which a particular community is found to 
have adopted in its infancy and in its primitive seats 
are generally those which are on the whole best 
suited to promote its physical and moral well-being; 
and, if they are retained in their integrity until new 
social wants have taught new practices, the upward 
march of society is almost certain. But unhappily 
there is a law of development which ever threatens 
to operate upon unwritten usage. The customs are 
of course obeyed by multitudes who are incapable of 
understanding the true ground of their expediency, 
and who are therefore left inevitably to invent su- 
perstitious reasons for their permanence. A process 
then commences which may be shortly described 
by saying that usage which is reasonable generates 
usage which is unreasonable. Analogy, the^most 
valuable of instruments in the maturity of jurispru- 
dence, is the most dangerous of snares in its infancy. 
ProhibiticMis and ordinances, originally confined, for 
good reasons, to a single description of acts, are made 
to apply to all acts of the same class, because a man 
menaced with the anger of the gods for doing one 
thing, feels a natural terror in doing any other thing 
which is remotely like it. After one kind of food 
has been interdicted for sanitary reasons, the prohi- 
bition is extended to all food resembling it, though 
the resemblance occasionally depends on analogies 
the most fanciful. So, again, a wise provision for 

c 2 



20 ANCIENT CODES. chap. x. 

insuring general cleanliness dictates in time long 
routines of ceremonial ablution; and that division 
into classes which at a particular crisis of social 
history is necessary for the maintenance of the na- 
,tional existence degenerates into the most disastrous 
; and blighting of all human institutions — Caste. The 
fate of the Hindoo law is, in fact, the measure of the 
value of the Roman code. Ethnology shows us that 
the Romans and the Hindoos sprang from the same 
original stock, and there is indeed a striking resem- 
blance between what appear to have been their 
original customs. Even now, Hindoo jurisprudence 
has a substratum of forethought and sound judg- 
ment, but irrational imitation has engrafted in it an 
immense apparatus of cruel absurdities. From these 
comfptions the Romans were protected by their code. 
It was compiled while usage was still wholesome, and 
a hundred years afterwards it might have been too 
late. The Hindoo law has been to a great extent 
embodied in writing, but, ancient as in one sense are 
the compendia which still exist in Sanskrit, they 
contain ample evidence that they were drawn up 
after the mischief had been done. .We are not of 
course entitled to say that if the Twelve Tables had 
not been published the Romans would have been con- 
demned to a civilisation as feeble and perverted as 
that of the Hindoos, but thus much at least is certain, 
that with their code they were exempt from the very 
chance of so unhappy a destiny. 



CHAP. II. LEGAL FICTIONS. 21 



CHAP. 11. 
LEGAL FICTIONS. 

When primitive law has once been embodied in a 
Code, there is an end to what may be called its spon- 
taneous development. Henceforward the changes 
effected in it, if effected at all, are effected deliberately 
and from without. It is impossible to suppose that 
the customs of any race or tribe remained unaltered 
during the whole of the long — in some instances 
the immense — interval between their declaration 
by a patriarchal monarch and their publication in 
writing. It would be unsafe too to af&rm that no part 
of the alteration was effected deliberately. But from 
the little we know of the progress of law during this 
period, we are justified in assuming that set purpose 
had the very smallest share in producing change. 
Such innovations on the earliest usages as disclose 
themselves appear to have been dictated by feelings 
and modes of thought which, under our present men- 
tal conditions, we are unable to comprehend. A new 
era begins, however, with the Codes. Wherever, after 
this epoch, we trace the course of legal modification 
we are able to attribute it to the conscious desire of 
improvement, or at all events of compassing objects 

c 3 



22 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap. ii. 

other than those which were aimed at in the primitive 
times. 

It may seem at first sight that no general proposi- 
tions worth trusting can be elicited from the history 
of legal systems subsequent to the codes. The field 
is too vast. We cannot be sure that we have included 
a sufficient number of phenomena in our observations, 
or that we accurately understand those which we 
have observed. But the undertaking will be seen 
to be more feasible, if we consider that after the epoch 
of codes the distinction between stationary and pro- 
gressive societies begins to make itself felt. It is 
only with the progressive societies that we are con- - 
cerned, and nothing is more remarkable than their 
extreme fewness. In spite of overwhelming evidence, 
it is most difficult for a citizen of western Europe to 
bring thoroughly home to himself the truth that the 
civilisation which surrounds him is a rare exception 
in the history of the world. The tone of thought 
common among us, all our hopes, fears, and specula- 
tions, would be materially aflPected, if we had vividly 
before us the relation of the progressive races to the 
totality of human life. It is indisputable that much 
the greatest part of mankind has never shown a par- 
ticle of desire that its civil institutions should be 
improved since the moment when external complete- 
ness was first given to them by their embodiment in 
some permanent record. One set of usages has occa- 



CHAP. u. STATIONARY AND PROGRESSIVE SOdETIES. 23 

sionally been violently overthrown and superseded by 
another; here and there a primitive code, pretending 
to a supernatural origin, has been greatly extended, 
and distorted into the most surprising forms, by the 
perversity of sacerdotal commentators; but, except 
in a small section of the world, there has been nothing 
like the gradual amelioration of a legal system. 
There has been material civilisation, but, instead of 
the civilisation expanding the law, the law has limited 
the civilisation. The study of races in their primi- 
tive condition affords us some clue to the point at 
which the development of certain societies has 
stopped. We can see that Brahminical India has not 
passed beyond a stage which occurs in the history of 
all the families of mankind, the stage at which a rule 
of law is not yet discriminated from a rule of religion. 
The members of such a society consider that the 
transgression of a religious ordinance should be pu- 
nished by ciyil penalties, and that the violation of a 
civil duty exposes the delinquent to divine correction. 
In China this point has been past, but progress seems 
to have been there arrested, because the civil laws are 
coextensive with aU the ideas of which the race is 
capable. The difference between the stationary and 
progressive societies is, however, one of the great 
secrets which inquiry has yet to penetrate. Among 
partial explanations of it I venture to place the con- 
siderations urged at the end of the last chapter. It 

c 4 



24 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap. ii. 

may further be remarked that^ no one is likely to 
succeed in the investigation who does not clearly 
realise that the stationary condition of the human 
race is the rule, the progressive the exception. And 
another indispensable condition of success is an ac- 
curate knowledge of Roman law in all its principal 
stages. The Roman jurisprudence has the longest 
known history of any set of human institutions. The 
character of all the changes which it imderwent is 
tolerably well ascertained. From its commencement 
to its close, it was progressively modified for the 
better, or for what the authors of the modification 
conceived to be the better, and the course of improve- 
ment was continued through periods at which all the 
rest of human thought and action materially slackened 
its pace, and repeatedly threatened to settle down into 
stagnation. 

I confine myself in what follows to the progressive 
societies. With respect to them it may be laid down 
that social necessities and social opinion are always 
more or less in advance of Law. We may come inde- 
finitely near to the closing of the gap between them, 
but it has a perpetual tendency to reopen. Law is 
stable ; the societies we are speaking of are progres- 
sive. The greater or less happiness of a people 
depends on the degree of promptitude with which the 
gulf is narrowed. 

A general proposition of some value may be ad- 




CHAP. II. FICTIONS, EQUITY, AND LEGISL. 

vanced with respect to the agencies by wl 
brought into harmony with society. These" 
mentalities seem to me to be three in number, Legal 
Fictions, Equity, and Legislation. Their historical 
order is that in which I have placed them. Sometimes 
two of them will be seen operating together, and there 
are legal systems which have escaped the influence of 
one or other of them. But I know of no instance in 
which the order of their appearance has been changed 
or inverted. The early history of one of them. 
Equity, is universally obscure, and hence it may be 
thought by some that certain isolated statutes, refor- 
matory of the civil law, are older than any equitable 
jurisdiction. My own belief is that remedial Equity 
is everjrwhere older than remedial Legislation ; but, 
should this be not strictly true, it would only be 
necessary to limit the proposition respecting their 
order of sequence to the periods at which they exer- 
cise a sustained and substantial influence in trans- 
forming the original law. 

I employ the word "fiction," in a sense consider- 
ably wider that that in which English lawyers are 
accustomed to use it, and with a meaning much more 
extensive than that which belonged to the Roman 
" fictiones." Fictio, in old Roman law, is properly a 
term of pleading, and signifies a false averment on 
the part of the plaintifi^ which the defendant was not 
allowed to traverse; such, for example, as an aver- 



V 



26 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap. n. 

ment that the plaintiff was a Roman citizen, when in 
truth he was a foreigner. The object of these " fic- 
tiones " was, of course, to give jurisdiction, and they 
therefore strongly resembled the allegations in the 
writs of the English Queen's Bench and Exchequer, 
by which those Courts contrived to usurp the juris- 
diction of the Common Pleas : — the allegation that 
the defendant was in custody of the king's mar- 
shal, or that the plaintiff was the king's debtor, and 
could not pay his debt by reason of the defendant's 
default. But I now employ the expression " Legal 
Fiction " to signify any assumption which conceals, or 
affects to conceal, the fact that a rule of law has un- 
dergone alteration, its letter remaining imchanged, 
its operation being modified. The words, therefore, 
include the instances of fictions wjiich I have cited 
from the English and Roman law, but they embrace 
much more, for I should speak both of the English 
Case-law and of the Roman Responsa Prudentum as 
resting on fictions. Both these examples will be 
examined presently. The fact is in both cases that 
the law has been wholly changed ; the fiction is that 
it remains what it always was. It is not difficult to 
understand why fictions in all their forms are parti- 
cularly congenial to the infancy of society. They 
satisfy the desire for improvement, which is not 
quite wanting, at the same time that they do not 
offend the superstitious disrelish for change which is 



CHAP. u. LEGAL FICTIONS. 27 

always present. At a particular stage of social pro- 
gress they are invaluable expedients for overcoming 
the rigidity of law, and, indeed, without one of them^ 
the Fiction of Adoption which permits the family 
tie to be artificially created, it is difficult to under- 
stand how society would ever have escaped from its 
swaddling-clothes, and taken its first steps towards 
civilisation. We must, therefore, not suffer our- 
selves to be affected by the ridicule which Bentham 
pours on legal fictions wherever he meets them. To 
revile them as merely fraudulent is to betray igno- 
rance of their peculiar office in the historical deve- 
lopment of law. But at the same time it would be 
equally foolish to agree with those theorists who, 
discerning that fictions have had their uses, argue 
that they ought to be stereotyped in our system. 
They have had their day, but it has long since 
gone by. It is unworthy of us to effect an ad- 
mittedly beneficial object by so rude a device as a 
legal fiction. I cannot admit any anomaly to be 
innocent, which makes the law either more difficult 
to understand or harder to arrange in harmonious 
order. Now legal fictions are the greatest of obstacles 
to symmetrical classification. The rule of law re- 
mains sticking in the system, but it is a mere shell. 
It has been long ago undermined, and a new rule 
hides itself under its cover. Hence there is at once 
a difficulty in knowing whether the rule which is 



28 EQUITT. CHAP. II, 

actually operative should be classed in its true or in 
its apparent place, and minds of different casts will 
differ as to the branch of the alternative which ought 
to be selected. K the English law is ever to assume 
an orderly distribution, it wiU be necessary to prune 
away the legal fictions which, in spite of some recent 
legislative improvements, are still abundant in it. 

The next instrumentality by which the adaptation 
of law to social wants is carried on I call Equity, 
meaning by that word any body of rules existing by 
the side of the original civil law, founded on distinct 
principles and claiming incidentally to supersede the 
civil law in virtue of a superior sanctity inherent in 
those principles. The Equity whether of the Roman 
Prastors or of the English Chancellors, differs from the 
Fictions which in each case preceded it, in that the 
interference with law is open and avowed. On the 
other hand, it differs from Legislation, the agent of 
legal improvement which comes after it, in that its 
claim to authority is grounded, not on the preroga- 
tive of any external person or body, not even on that 
of the magistrate who enunciates it, but on the 
special nature of its principles, to which it is alleged 
that all law ought to conform. The very conception 
of a set of principles, invested with a higher sacredness 
than those of. the original law and demanding appli- 
cation independently of the consent of any external 
body, belongs to a much more advanced stage of 



CHAP. If. LEGISLATION. 29 

thought than that to which legal fictions originally 
suggested themselves. 

Legislation, the enactments of a legislature which, 
whether it take the form of an autocratic prince or 
of a parliamentary assembly, is the assumed organ of 
the entire society, is the last of the ameliorating in- 
strumentalities. It dififers from Legal Fictions just as 
Equity diflfers from them, and it is also distinguished 
from Equity, as deriving its authority from an external 
body or person. Its obligatory force is independent 
of its principles. The legislature, whatever be the 
actual restraints imposed on it by public opinion, is 
in theory empowered to impose what obligations it 
pleases on the members of the community. There is 
nothing to prevent its legislating in the wantonness 
of caprice. Legislation may be dictated by equity, if 
that last word be used to indicate some standard of 
right and wrong to which its enactments happen to 
be adjusted; but then these enactments are indebted 
for their binding force to the authority of the legis- 
lature and not to that of the principles on which the 
legislature acted; and thus they differ from rules of 
Equity, in the technical sense of the word, which pre- 
tend to a paramount sacredness entitling them at 
once to the recognition of the courts even without 
the concurrence of prince or parliamentary assem- 
bly. It is the more necessary to note these differ- 
ences, because a student of Bentham would be apt to 



30 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap. ii. 

confound Fictions, Equity, and Statute law under 
the single head of legislation. They all, he would 
say, involve law-making; they differ only in respect 
of the machinery by which the new law is produced. 
That is perfectly true, and we must never forget it; 
but it furnishes no reason why we should deprive 
ourselves of so convenient a term as Legislation in the 
special sense. Legislation and Equity are disjoined 
in the popular mind and in the ndnds of most law- 
yers; and it will never do to neglect the distinction 
between them, however conventional, when important 
practical consequences follow from it. 

It would be easy to select from almost any regu- 
larly developed body of rules examples of legal fxi- 
tions^ which at once betray their true character to the 
modern observer. In the two instances which I pro- 
ceed to consider, the nature of the expedient em- 
ployed is not so readily detected. The first authors 
of these fictions did not perhaps intend to innovate, 
certainly did not wish to be suspected of innovating. 
There are, moreover, and always have been, persons 
who refuse to see any fiction in the process, and 
conventional language bears out their refusal. No 
examples, therefore, can be better calculated to illus- 
trate the wide diffusion of legal fictions, and the 
efficiency with which they perform their two-fold 
office of transforming a system of laws and of con- 
cealing the transformation. 



CKAF. 11. CASE-LAW. 31 

We in England are well accustomed to the exten- 
sion, modification, and improvement of law by a 
machinery which, in theory, is incapable of altering 
one jot or one line of existing jurisprudence. The 
process by which this virtual legislation is effected is 
not so much insensible as unacknowledged. With 
respect to that great portion of our legal system 
which is enshrined in cases and recorded in law 
reports, we habitually employ a double language and 
entertain, as it would appear, a double and incon- 
sistent set of ideas. When a group of facts come 
before an English Court for adjudication, the whole 
course of the discussion between the judge and the 
advocates assumes that no question is, or can be, 
raised which will call for the application of any 
principles but old ones, or of any distinctions but 
such as have long since been allowed. It is taken 
absolutely for granted that there is somewhere a rule 
of known law which will cover the facts of the 
dispute now litigated, and that, if such a rule be not 
discovered, it is only that the necessary patience, 
knowledge, or acumen is not forthcoming to detect it. 
Yet the moment the judgment has been rendered 
and reported, we slide unconsciously or unavowedly 
into a new language and a new train of thought. 
We now admit that the new decision has modified 
the law. The rules applicable have, to use the very 
inaccurate expression sometimes employed, become 



32 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap. n. 

more elastic. In fact they have been changed. A 
clear addition has been made to the precedents, and 
the canon of law elicited by comparing the prece- 
dents is not the same with that which would have 
been obtained if the series of cases had been curtailed 
by a single example. The fact^that the old rule has 
been repealed, and that a new one has replaced it, 
eludes us, because we are not in the habit of throwing 
into precise language the legal formulas which we 
derive from the precedents, so that a change in their 
tenor is not easily detected unless it is violent and 
glaring. I shall not now pause to consider at length 
the causes which have led English lawyers to ac- 
quiesce in these curious anomalies. Probably it will 
be found that originally it was the received doctrine 
that somewhere, in nuhihus or in gremio magisiratuum^ 
there existed a complete, coherent, symmetrical body 
of English law, of an amplitude sufficient to furnish 
principles which would apply to any conceivable 
combination of circumstances. The theory was at 
first much more thoroughly believed in than it is 
now, and indeed it may have had a better founda- 
tion. The judges of the thirteenth century may 
have really had at their command a mine of law 
unrevealed to the bar and to the lay-public, for 
there is some reason for suspecting that in secret 
they borrowed freely, though not always wisely, from 
current compendia of the Roman and Canon laws. 



CHAP. IX. ANSWERS OF THE LEARNED. 33 

But that storehouse was closed so soon as the points 
decided at Westminster Hall became numerous 
enough to supply a basis for a substantive system of 
jurisprudence ; and now for centuries English prac- 
titioners have so expressed themselves as to convey 
the paradoxical proposition that, except by Equity 
and Statute law, nothing has been added to the basis 
since it was first constituted. We do not admit that 
our tribunals legislate; we imply that they have 
never legislated ; and yet we maintain that the rules 
of the English common law, with some assistance 
from the Court of Chancery and from Parliament, 
are coextensive with the complicated interests of 
modem society. 

A body of law bearing a very close and very in- 
structive resemblance to our case-law in those par- 
ticulars which I have noticed, was known to the 
Romans under the name of the Responsa Prudentum, 
the " answers of the learned in the law." The form of 
these Responses varied a good deal at different periods 
of the Roman jurisprudence, but throughout its 
whole course they consisted of explanatory glosses on 
authoritative written documents, and at first they 
were exclusively collections of opinions interpretative 
of the Twelve Tables. As with us, all legal language 
adjusted itself to the assumption that the text of the 
old Code remained unchanged. There was the ex- 
press rule. It overrode all glosses and comments, 

D 



34 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap. ii. 

and no one openly admitted that any interpretation 
of it, however eminent the interpreter, was safe from 
revision on appeal to the venerable texts. Yet in 
point of fact, Books of Responses bearing the names of 
leading jurisconsults obtained an authority at least 
equal to that of our reported cases, and constantly 
modified, extended, limited or practically overruled 
the provisions of the Decemviral law. The authors 
of the new jurisprudence during the whole progress 
of its formation professed the most sedulous respect 
for the letter of the Code. They were merely 
explaining it, deciphering it, bringing out its full 
meaning; but then, in the result, by piecing texts 
together, by adjusting the law to states of fact which 
actually presented themselves and by speculating on 
its possible application to others which might occur, 
by introducing principles of interpretation derived 
from the exegesis of other written documents which 
fell under their observation, they educed a vast 
variety of canons which had never been dreamed of by 
the compilers of the Twelve Tables and which were 
in truth rarely or never to be found there. All 
these treatises of the jurisconsults claimed respect on 
the ground of their assumed conformity with the 
Code, but their comparative authority depended on 
the reputation of the particular jurisconsults who 
gave them to the world. Any name of univer- 
sally acknowledged greatness clothed a Book of 



CHAP. II. ANSWERS OF THE LEARNED. B6 

Kesponses with a binding force hardly less than that 
which belonged to enactments of the legislature; 
and such a book in its turn constituted a new foiyi- 
dation on which a further body of jurisprudence 
might rest. The Responses of the early lawyers were 
not however published, in the modem sense, by 
their author. They were recorded and edited by 
his pupils, and were not therefore in all probability 
arranged according to any scheme of classification. 
The part of the students in these publications must 
be carefully noted, because the service they rendered 
to their teacher seems to have been generally repaid 
by his sedulous attention to the pupils' education. 
The educational treatises called Institutes or Com- 
mentaries, which are a later fruit of the duty then 
recognised, are among the most remarkable features 
of the Roman system. It was apparently in these 
Institutional works, and not in the books intended 
for trained lawyers, that the jurisconsults gave to the 
public their classifications and their proposals for 
modifying and improving the technical phraseology. 
In comparing the Roman Responsa Prudentum with 
their nearest English counterpart, it must be care- 
fully borne in mind that the authority by which this 
part of the Roman jurisprudence was expounded was 
not the benck^ but the bar. The decision of a Roman 
tribunal, though conclusive in the particular case, 
had no ulterior authority except such as was given 

D 2 



36 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap. ii. 

by the professional repute of the magistrate who hap- 
pened to be in office for the time. Properly speaking, 
there was no institution at Rome during the republic 
analogous to the English Bench, the Chambers of 
Imperial Germany, or the Parliaments of Monarchical 
France. There were magistrates indeed, invested 
with momentous judicial functions in their several 
departments, but the tenure of the magistracies was 
but for a single year, so that they are much less aptly 
compared to a permanent judicature than to a cycle 
of offices briskly circulating among the leaders of the 
bar. Much might be said on the origin of a condi- 
tion of things which looks to us like a startling 
anomaly, but which was in fact much more congenial 
than our own system to the spirit of ancient societies, 
tending, as they alwa5'^s did, to split into distinct orders 
which, however exclusive themselves, tolerated no 
professional hierarchy above them. 

It is remarkable that this system did not produce 
certain effects which might on the whole have been 
expected from it. It did not, for example, popularise 
the Roman law, — it did not, as in some of the Greek 
republics, lessen the effort of intellect required for 
the mastery of the science, although its diffusion and 
authoritative exposition were opposed by no artificial 
barriers. On the contrary, if it had not been for the 
operation of a separate set of causes, there were strong 
probabilities that the Roman jurisprudence would 



ciiAP. 11. ANSWERS OF THE LEARNED. 37 

have become as minute, technical, and difficult as any 
system which has since prevailed. Again, a conse- 
quence which might have still more naturally have 
been looked for, does not appear at any time to have 
exhibited itself. The jurisconsults, until the liberties 
of Rome were overthrown, formed a class which was 
quite undefined and must have fluctuated greatly in 
numbers ; nevertheless, there does not seem to have 
existed a doubt as to the particular individuals whose 
opinion, in their generation, was conclusive on the 
cases submitted to them. The vivid pictures of a 
leading jurisconsult's daily practice which abound in 
Latin literature — the clients from the country flocking 
to his antechamber in the early morning, and the 
students standing round with their note-books to 
record the great lawyer's replies — are seldom or never 
identified at any given period with more than one or 
two conspicuous names. Owing too to the direct 
contact of the client and the advocate, the Roman 
people itself seems to have been always alive to the rise 
and fall of professional reputation, and there is 
abundance of proof, more particularly in the well- 
known oration of Cicero, " Pro Mursena," that the 
reverence of the commons for forensic success was 
apt to be excessive rather than deficient. 

We cannot doubt that the peculiarities which have 
been noted in the instrumentality by which the deve- 
lopment of the Roman law was first efiected, were the 

D 3 



38 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap, ii. 

source of its characteristic excellence, its early wealth 
in principles. The growth and exuberance of prin- 
ciple was fostered, in part, by the competition among 
the expositors of the law, an influence wholly un- 
known where there exists a Bench, the depositaries 
intrusted by king or commonwealth with the prero- 
gative of justice. But the chief agency, no doubt, 
was the uncontrolled multiplication of cases for legal 
decision. The state of facts which caused genuine 
perplexity to a country client was not a whit more 
entitled to form the basis of the jurisconsult's Re- 
sponse, or legal decision, than a set of hypothetical 
circumstances propounded by an ingenious pupil- 
All combinations of fact were on precisely the same 
footing, whether they were real or imaginary. It 
was nothing to the jurisconsult that his opinion was 
overruled for the moment by the magistrate who ad- 
judicated on his client's case, unless that magistrate 
happened to rank above him in legal knowledge or 
the esteem of his profession. I do not, indeed, mean 
it to be inferred that he would wholly omit to con- 
sider his client's advantage, for the client was in 
earlier times the great lawyer's constituent and at a 
later period his paymaster, but the main road to the 
rewards of ambition lay through the good opinion of 
his order, and it is obvious that under such a system 
as I have been describing this was much more likely 
to be secured by viewing each case as an illustration 



CHAP. n. ANSWERS OP THE LEARNED. 39 

of a great principle, or an exemplification of a broad 
rule, than by merely shaping it for an insulated 
forensic triumph. A still more powerful influence 
must have been exercised by the want of any distinct 
check on the suggestion or invention of possible ques* 
tions. Where the data can be multiplied at pleasure, 
the facilities for evolving a general rule are immensely 
increased. As the law is administered among our- 
selves, the judge cannot travel out of the sets of facts 
exhibited before him or before his predecessors. 
Accordingly each group of circumstances which is 
adjudicated upon receives, to employ a Gallicism, a 
sort of consecration. It acquires certain qualities 
which distinguish it from every other case genuine 
or hypothetical. But at Rome, as I have attempted 
to explain, there was nothing resembling a Bench or 
Chamber of judges; and therefore no combination of 
facts possessed any particular value more than an- 
other. When a difficulty came for opinion before 
the jurisconsult, there was nothing to prevent a per- 
son endowed with a nice perception of analogy from 
at once proceeding to adduce and consider an entire 
class of supposed questions with which a particular 
feature connected it. Whatever were the practical 
advice given to the client, the responsum treasured 
up in the note-books of listening pupils would doubt- 
less contemplate the circumstances as governed by a 
great principle, or included in a sweeping rule. 

^ / 



i 






40 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap. ii. 

Nothing like this has ever been possible among our- 
selves, and it should be acknowledged that in many 
criticisms passed on the English law the manner in 
which it has been enunciated seems to have been lost 
sight of. The hesitation of our courts in declaring 
principles may be much more reasonably attributed 
to the comparative scantiness of our precedents, 
voluminous as they appear to him who is acquainted 
with no other system, than to the temper of our judges. 
It is true that in the wealth of legal principle we are 
considerably poorer than several modern European 
nations. But they, it must be remembered, took the 
Eoman jurisprudence for the foundation of their civil 
institutions. They built the debris of the Roman 
law into their walls; but in the materials and work- 
manship of the residue there is not much which 
distinguishes it favourably from the structure erected 
by the English judicature. 

The period of Roman freedom was the period during 
which the stamp of a distinctive character was im- 
pressed on the Roman jurisprudence; and through 
all the earlier part of it, it was by the Responses of 
the jurisconsults that the development of the law was 
mainly carried on. But as we approach the fall of 
the republic there are signs that the Responses are 
assuming a form which must have been fatal to their 
farther expansion. They are becoming systematised 
and reduced into compendia. Q. Mucins Scaevola, the 



CHAP. II. LATER JURISCONSULTS. 41 

Pontifex, is said to have published a manual of the 
entire CivU Law, and there are traces in the writings 
of Cicero of growing disrelish for the old methods, as 
compared with the more active instruments of legal 
innovation. Other agencies had in fact by this time 
been brought to bear on the law. The Edict, or 
annual proclamation of the Praetor, had risen into 
credit as the principal engine of law reform, and 
L. Cornelius Sylla, by causing to be enacted the 
great group of statutes called the Leges Comelice^ had 
shown what rapid and speedy improvements can be 
effected by direct legislation. The final blow to the 
Responses was dealt by Augustus, who limited to a 
few leading jurisconsults the right of giving binding 
opinions on cases submitted to them, a change which, 
though it brings us nearer the ideas of the modem 
world, must obviously have altered fundamentally 
the characteristics of the legal profession and the 
nature of its influence on Eoman law. At a later 
period another school of jurisconsults arose, the great 
lights of jurisprudence for all time. But Ulpian 
and Paulus, Gains and Papinian, were not authors 
of Responses. Their works were regular treatises 
on particular departments of the law, more especially 
on the Praetor's Edict. 

The Equity of the Romans and the Praetorian Edict 
by which it was worked into their system, will be 
considered in the next chapter. Of the Statute Law 



42 LEGAL FICTIONS. chap, ii, 

it is only necessary to say that it was scanty during 
the republic, but became very voluminous under the 
empire. In the youth and infancy of a nation it is a 
rare thing for the legislature to be called into action 
for the general reform of private law. The cry of 
the people is not for change in the laws, which are 
usually valued above their real worth, but solely for 
their pure, complete, and easy administration; and 
recourse to the legislative body is generally directed 
to the removal of some great abuse, or the decision of 
some incurable quarrel between classes and d3masties. 
There seems in the minds of the Romans to have 
been some association between the enactment of a 
large body of statutes and the settlement of society 
after a great civil commotion. Sylla signalised his 
reconstitution of the republic by the Leges Comeliae; 
Julius Caesar contemplated vast additions to the 
Statute Law; Augustus caused to be passed the all- 
important group of Leges Juliaa; and among later 
emperors the most active promulgators of constitu- 
tions are princes who, like Constantine, have the 
concerns of the world to readjust. The true period 
of Roman Statute Law does not begin tiU the esta- 
blishment of the empire. The enactments of the 
emperors, clothed at first in the pretence of popular 
sanction, but afterwards emanating undisguisedly 
from the imperial prerogative, extend in increasing 
massiveness from the consolidation of Augustus's 



CHAP. II. ROMAN STATUTES. 43 

power to the publication of the Code of Justinian. 
It will be seen that even in the reign of the second 
emperor a considerable approximation is made to that 
condition of the law and that mode of administering 
it with which we are all familiar. A statute law 
and a limited board of expositors have risen into be- 
ing ; a permanent court of appeal and a collection of 
approved commentaries will very shortly be added; 
and thus we are brought close on the ideas of our 
own day. 



44 EQUITY. CHAP. in. 



CHAP. III. 

LAW OF NATURE AND EQUITY. 

The theory of a set of legal principles, entitled by 
their intrinsic superiority to supersede the older law, 
very early obtained currency both in the Roman 
state and in England. Such a body of principles, 
existing in any system, has in the foregoing chapters 
been denominated Equity, a term which, as will pre- 
sently be seen, was one (though only one) of the 
designations by which this agent of legal change was 
known to the Roman jurisconsults. The jurispru- 
dence of the Court of Chancery, which bears the 
name of Equity in England, could only be adequately 
discussed in a separate treatise. It is extremely 
complex in its texture and derives its materials from 
several heterogeneous sources. The early ecclesias- 
tical chancellors contributed to it, from the Canon 
Law, many of the principles which lie deepest in its 
structure. The Roman law, more fertile than the 
Canon Law in rules applicable to secular disputes, 
was not seldom resorted to by a later generation of 
Chancery judges, amid whose recorded dicta we of- 
ten find entire texts from the Corpus Juris Civilis 



CHAF. m. EQUITY. 45 

imbedded, with their terms unaltered, though their 
origin is never acknowledged. Still more recently, and 
particularly at the middle and during the latter half 
of the 18th century, the mixed systems of jurispru- 
dence and morals constructed by the publicists of the 
Low Countries appear to have been much studied 
by English lawyers, and from the chancellorship of 
Lord Talbot to the commencement of Lord Eldon's 
chancellorship these works had considerable effect on 
the rulings of the Court of Chancery. The system, 
which obtained its ingredients from these various 
quarters, was greatly controlled in its growth by the 
necessity imposed on it of conforming itself to the 
analogies of the common law, but it has always an- 
swered the description of a body of comparatively 
novel legal principles claiming to override the older 
jurisprudence of the country on the strength of an 
intrinsic ethical superiority. 

The Equity of Rome was a much simpler structure, 
and its development from its first appearance can 
be much more easily traced. Both its character and 
its history deserve attentive examination. It is the 
root of several conceptions which have exercised 
profound influence on human thought, and through 
human thought have seriously affected the destinies 
of mankind. 

The Romans described their legal system as con- 
sisting of two ingredients. " All nations," says the 



46 LAW OF NATIONS AND OF NATURE. chap. hi. 

Institutional Treatise published under the authority of 
the Emperor Justinian, " who are ruled by laws and 
customs, are governed partly by their own particular 
laws, and partly by those laws which are common to 
all mankind. The law which a people enacts is called 
the Civil Law of that people, but that which natural 
reason appoints for all mankind is called the Law of 
Nations, because all nations use it." The part of the 
law " which natural reason appoints for all mankind " 
was the element which the Edict of the PrsBtor was 
supposed to have worked into Roman jurisprudence. 
Elsewhere it is styled more simply Jus Naturale, or 
the Law of Nature ; and its ordinances are said to 
be dictated by Natural Equity (naturalis cequitas) 
as well as by natural reason. I shall attempt to 
discover the origin of these famous phrases, Law of 
Nations, Law of Nature, Equity, and to determine 
how the conceptions which they indicate are related 
to one another. 

The most superficial student of Roman history 
must be struck by the extraordinary degree in which 
the fortunes of the republic were affected by the 
presence of foreigners, under different names, on her 
soil. The causes of this immigration are discernible 
enough at a later period, for we can readily under- 
stand why men of all races should flock to the mistress 
of the world ; but the same phenomenon of a large 
population of foreigners and denizens meets us in 



CHAP. III. LAW OF NATIONS AND OP NATURE. 47 

the very earliest records of the Roman State. No 
doubt^ the instability of society in ancient Italy, 
composed as it was in great measure of robber tribes, 
gave men considerable inducement to locate them- 
selves in the territory of any community strong 
enough to protect itself and them from external 
attack, even though protection should be purchased at 
the cost of heavy taxation, political disfranchisement, 
and much social humiliation. It is probable, however, 
that this explanation is imperfect, and that it could 
only be completed by taking into account those active 
commercial relations which, though they are little 
reflected in the military traditions of the republic, 
Rome appears certainly to have had with Carthage 
and with the interior of Italy in pre-historic times. 
Whatever were the circumstances to which it was 
attributable, the foreign element in the commonwealth 
determined the whole course of its history, which, at 
all its stages, is little more than a narrative of 
conflicts Jbetween a stubborn nationality and an alien 
population. Nothing like this has been seen in 
modem times; on the one hand, because modern 
European communities have seldom or never received 
any accession of foreign immigrants which was large 
enough to make itself felt by the bulk of the native 
citizens, and on the other, because modem states, 
being held together by allegiance to a king or political 
superior, absorb considerable bodies of immigrant 



48 LAW OF NATIONS AND OF NATURE. chap. iii. 

settlers with a quickness unknown to the ancient 
world, where the original citizens of a commonwealth 
always believed themselves to be united by Idnship in 
blood, and resented a claim to equality of privilege 
as a usurpation of their birthright. In the early 
Roman republic the principle of the absolute ex- 
clusion of foreigners pervaded the Civil Law no less 
than the Constitution. The alien or denizen could 
have no share in any institution supposed to be coeval 
with the State. He could not have the benefit of 
Quiritarian law. He could not be a party to the 
nexum which was at once the conveyance and the 
contract of the primitive Romans. He could not sue 
by the Sacramental Action, a mode of litigation of 
which the origin mounts up to the very infancy of 
civilisation. Still, neither the interest nor the security 
of Rome permitted him to be quite outlawed. All 
ancient communities ran the risk of being overthrown 
by a very slight disturbance of equilibrium, and the 
mere instinct of self-preservation would force the 
Romans to devise some method of adjusting the rights 
and duties of foreigners, who might otherwise — and 
this was a danger of real importance in the ancient 
world — have decided their controversies by armed 
strife. Moreover, at no period of Roman history 
was foreign trade entirely neglected. It was there- 
fore probably half as a measure of police and half in 
furtherance of commerce that jurisdiction was first 



CHAP. III. LAW OP NATIONS. 49 

assumed in disputes to which the parties were either 
foreigners or a native and a foreigner. The as- 
sumption of such a jurisdiction brought with it 
the immediate necessity of discovering some prin* 
ciples on which the questions to be adjudicated upon 
could be settled, and the principles applied to this 
object by the Roman lawyers were eminently character- 
istic of the time. They refused, as I have said before, 
to decide the new cases by pure Roman Civil Law. 
They refused, no doubt because it seemed to involve 
some kind of degradation, to apply the law of the par- 
ticular State from which the foreign litigant came. 
The expedient to which they resorted was that of se- 
lecting the rules of law common to Rome and to the 
different Italian communities in which the immigrants 
were bom. In other words, they set themselves to form 
a system answering to the primitive and literal meaning 
of Jus Gentium, that is. Law common to all Nations. 
Jus Gentium was, in fact, the sum of the common 
ingredients in the customs of the old Italian tribes, 
for they were all the nations whom the Romans had 
the means of observing, stnd who sent successive 
swarms of immigrants to Roman soil. Whenever a 
particular usage was seen to be practised by a large 
number of separate races in common it was set down 
as part of the Law common to all Nations, or Jus 
Gentium. Thus, although the conveyance of property 
was certainly accompanied by very different forms in 



60 LAW OF NATIONS. chap. iii. 

the diflFerent commonwealths surrounding Rome, the 
abtual transfer, tradition, or delivery of the article 
intended to be conveyed was a part of the ceremonial 
in all of them. It was, for instance, a part, though 
a subordinate part, in the Mancipation or conveyance 
peculiar to Rome. Tradition, therefore, being in all 
probability the only common ingredient in the modes 
of conveyance which the jurisconsults had the means 
of observing, was set down as an institution Juris 
Gentium, or rule of the Law common to all Nations. 
A vast number of other observances were scrutinised 
with the same result. Some common characteristic 
was discovered in all of them, which had a common 
object, and this characteristic was classed in the Jus 
Gentium. The Jus Gentium was accordingly a col- 
lection of rules and principles, determined by ob- 
servation to be common to the institutions which 
prevailed among the various Italian tribes. 

The circumstances of the origin of the Jus Gentium 
are probably a sufficient safeguard against the mis- 
take of supposing that the Roman lawyers had 
any special respect for it. It was the fruit in part 
of their disdain for all foreign law, and in part of 
their disinclination to give the foreigner the advan- 
tage of their own indigenous Jus Civile. It is true 
that we, at the present day, should probably take a 
very diflFerent view of the Jus Gentium, if we were 
performing the operation which was eflfected by the 



CHAP. m. LAW OP NATIONS. 5i 

Roman jurisconsults. We should attach some vague 
superiority or precedence to the element which we 
had thus discerned uaderlying and pervading so 
great a variety of usage. We should have a sort of 
respect for rules and principles so universal. Per- 
haps we should speak of the common ingredient 
as being of the essence of the transaction into which it 
entered, and should stigmatise the remaining appa- 
ratus of ceremony, which varied in different com- 
munities, as adventitious and accidental. Or it may 
be, we should infer that the races which we were 
comparing had once obeyed a great system of com- 
mon institutions of which the Jus Gentium was the 
reproduction, and that the complicated usages of 
separate commonwealths were only corruptions and 
depravations of the simpler ordinances which had 
once regulated their primitive state. But the re- 
sults to which modem ideas conduct the observer 
are, as nearly as possible, the reverse of those 
which were instinctively brought home to the primi- 
tive Roman. What we respect or admire, he dis- 
liked or regarded with jealous dread. The parts of 
jurisprudence which he looked upon with affection 
were exactly those which a modem theorist leaves 
out of consideration as accidental and transitory; 
the solemn gestures of the mancipation ; the nicely 
adjusted questions and answers of the verbal con- 
tract; the endless formalities of pleading and pro- 

B 2 



52 LAW OF NATURE. cuap. hi. 

cedure. The Jus Gentium was merely a system 
forced on his attention by a political necessity. He 
loved it as little as he loved the foreigners from 
whose institutions it was derived and for whose 
benefit it was intended. A complete revolution in 
his ideas was required before it could challenge his 
respect, but so complete was it when it did occur, 
that the true reason why our modem estimate of the 
Jus Gentium differs from that which has just been 
described, is that both modem jurisprudence and 
modern philosophy have inherited the matured views 
of the later jurisconsults on this subject. There did 
come a time when, from an ignoble appendage of the 
Jus Civile, the Jus Gentium came to be considered a 
great though as yet imperfectly developed model to 
which all law ought as far as possible to conform. 
This crisis arrived when the Greek theory of a Law of 
Nature was applied to the practical Roman adminis- 
tration of the Law common to all Nations. 
y ' The Jus Naturale, or Law of Nature, is simply the 
Jus Gentium or Law of Nations seen in the light of 
a peculiar theory. An unfortunate attempt to dis- 
criminate them was made by the jurisconsult Ulpian, 
with the propensity to distinguish characteristic of a 
lawyer, but the language of Gains, a much higher au- 
thority, and the passage quoted before from the Insti- 
tutes leave no room for doubt, that the expressions 
were practically convertible. The difference be- 



ciiAF. m. NATURE. 53 

tween them was entirely historical, and no distinction 
in essence could ever be established between them. 
It is almost unnecessary to add that the confusion 
between Jus Gentium, or Law common to all Nations, 
and international law is entirely modern. The classi- 
cal expression for international law is Jus Feciale or 
the law of negotiation and diplomacy. It is, however, 
unquestionable that indistinct impressions as to the 
meaning of Jus Gentium had considerable share in 
producing the modern theory that the relations 
of independent states are governed by the Law of 
Nature. 

It becomes necessary to investigate the Greek 
conceptions of nature and her law. The word ^vcrt^, 
which was rendered in the Latin natura and our 
nature^ denoted beyond all doubt originally the 
material universe, but it was the material universe 
contemplated under an aspect which — such is our 
intellectual distance from those times — it is not 
very easy to delineate in modern language. Nature 
signified the physical world regarded as the result of 
some primordial element or law. The oldest Greek 
philosophers had been accustomed to explain the 
fabric of creation as the manifestation of some single 
principle which they variously asserted to be move- 
ment, force, fire, moisture, or generation. In its 
simplest and most ancient sense, Nature is precisely 
the physical universe looked upon in this way as the 

E 3 



54 NATURE. chap, hi, 

manifestation of a principle. Afterwards, the later 
Greek sects, returning to a path from which the 
greatest intellects of Greece had meanwhile strayed, 
added the moral to the physical world in the con- 
ception of Nature. They extended the term till it 
embraced not merely the visible creation, but the 
thoughts, observances, and aspirations of mankind. 
Still, as before, it was not solely the moral phe- 
nomena of human society which they understood by 
Nature, but these phenomena considered as resolv- 
able into some general and simple laws. 

Now, just as the oldest Greek theorists supposed 
that the sports of chance had changed the material 
universe from its simple primitive form into its 
present heterogeneous condition, so their intellectual 
descendants imagined that but for untoward acci- 
dent the human race would have conformed itself 
to simpler rules of conduct and a less tempestuous 
life. To live according to nature game to be con- 
sidered as the end for which man was created, and 
which the best men were bound to compass. To 
live according to nature was to rise above the dis- 
orderly habits and gross indulgences of the vulgar 
to higher laws of action which nothing but self- 
denial and self-command would enable the aspirant 
to observe. It is notorious that this proposition — 
live according to nature — was the sum of the tenets 
of the famous Stoic philosophy. Now on the subju- 



CHAP. m. THE STOICS. 65 

gation of Greece that philosophy made instantaneous 
progress in Roman society. It possessed natural 
fascinations for the powerful class who, in theory at 
least, adhered to the siihple habits of the ancient 
Italian race, and disdained to surrender themselves 
to the innovations of foreign fashion. Such persons 
began immediately to affect the Stoic precepts of 
life according to nature — an affectation all the 
more grateful, and, I may add, all the more noble, 
firom its contrast with the unbounded profligacy 
which was being diffused through the imperial city 
by the pillage of the world and by the example of its 
most luxurious races. In the front of the disciples of 
the new Greek school, we might be sure, even if we 
did not know it historically, that the Romans lawyers 
figured. We have abundant proof that, there being 
substantially but two professions in the Roman re- 
public, the military men were generally identified 
with the party of movement, but the lawyers were 
tmiversally at the head of the party of resistance. 

The alliance of the lawyers with the Stoic philo- 
sophers lasted through many centuries. Some of 
the earliest names in the series of renowned juris- 
consults are associated with Stoicism, and ultimately 
we have the golden age of Roman jurisprudence 
fixed by general consent at the era of the Antonine 
Caesars, the most famous disciples to whom that 
philosophy has given a rule of life. The long diffu- 

B 4 



56 LAW OF NATURE. chap.jii. 

sion of these doctrines among the members of a 
particular profession was sure to affect the art which 
they practised and influenced. Several positions 
which we find in the remains of the Roman juris- 
consults are scarcely intelligible, unless we use the 
Stoic tenets as our key ; but at the same time it is a 
serious, though a very conunon, error to measure 
the influence of Stoicism on Roman law by counting 
up the number of legal rules which can be con- 
fidently affiliated on Stoical dogmas. It has often 
been observed that the strength of Stoicism resided 
not in its canons of conduct, which were often re- 
pulsive or ridiculous, but in the great though vague 
principle which it inculcated of resistance to passion. 
Just in the same way the influence on jurisprudence 
of the Greek theories, which had their most distinct 
expression in Stoicism, consisted not in the num- 
ber of specific positions which they contributed to 
Roman law, but in the single fundamental assump- 
tion which they lent to it. After Nature had 
become a household word in the mouths of the 
Romans, the belief gradually prevailed among the 
Roman lawyers that the old Jus Gentium was in 
fact the lost code of Nature, and that the Praetor 
in framing an Edictal jurisprudence on the prin- 
ciples of the Jus Gentium was gradually restoring a 
type from which law had only departed to deteriorate. 
The inference from this belief was immediate that it 



CDAP. III. EQUITY. 67 

was the Praetor's duty to supersede the Civil Law as 
much as possible by the Edict, to revive as far as 
might be the institutions by which Nature had go- 
verned man in the primitive state. Of course there 
were many impediments to the amelioration of law by 
this agency. There may have been prejudices to over- 
come even in the legal profession itself, and Roman 
habits were far too tenacious to give way at once 
to mere philosophical theory. The indirect methods 
by which the Edict combated certain technical anoma- 
lies, show the caution which its authors were compelled 
to observe, and down to the very days of Justinian 
there was some part of the old law which had ob- 
stinately resisted its influence. But, on the whole, 
the progress of the Romans in legal improvement 
was astonishingly rapid as soon as stimulus was 
applied to it by the theory of Natural Law. The 
ideas of simplification and generalisalion had always 
been associated with the conception of Nature; sim- 
plicity, symmetry, and intelligibility came therefore 
to be regarded as the characteristics of a good legal 
system, and the taste for involved language, mul- 
tiplied ceremonials, and . useless difficulties disap- 
peared altogether. The strong will and unusual 
opportunities of Justinian were needed to bring the 
Roman law to its existing shape, but the ground 
plan of the system had been sketched long before 
the imperial reforms were effected. 



5S EQUITr. CHAP. iir. 

What was the exact point of contact between the 
old Jus Gentium and the Law of Nature ? I think 
that they touch and blend through jEquitas, or 
Equity in its original sense; and here we seem to 
come to the first appearance in jurisprudence of this 
famous term, Equity. In examining an expression 
which has so remote an origin and so long a history 
as this, it is always safest to penetrate, if possible, 
to the simple metaphor or figure which at first 
shadowed forth the conception. It has generally 
been supposed that ^quitas is the equivalent of the 
Greek leronj^, \, e. the principle of equal or propor- 
tionate distribution. The equal division of numbers 
or physical magnitudes is doubtless closely entmned 
with our perceptions of justice; there are few asso- 
ciations which keep their ground in the mind so 
stubbornly or are dismissed from it with such diffi- 
culty by the deepest thinkers. Yet in tracing the 
history of this association, it certainly does not 
seem to have suggested itself to very early thought, 
but is rather the offispring of a comparatively late 
philosophy. It is remarkable too that the "equality" 
of laws on which the Greek democracies prided 
themselves — that equality which, in the beautiful 
drinking song of Callistratus, Harmodius and Ari- 
stogiton are said to have given to Athens — had 
little in common with the " equity " of the Romans. 
The first was an equal administration of civil laws 



CHAP. III. EQUITY. 59 

among the citizens, however limited the class of 
citizens might be; the last implied the applicability 
of a law, which was not civil law, to a class which 
did not necessarily consist of citizens. The first 
excluded a despot ; the last included foreigners, and 
for some purposes slaves. On the whole, I should 
be disposed to look in another direction for the germ 
of the Roman *' Equity." The Latin word "aequus" 
carries with it more distinctly than the Greek "/tro^" 
the sense of levelling. Now its levelling tendency 
was exactly the characteristic of the Jus Gentium, 
which would be most striking to a primitive Roman. 
The pure Quiritarian law recognised a multitude of 
arbitrary distinctions between classes of men and 
kinds of property ; the Jus Gentium, generalised from 
a comparison of various customs, neglected the 
Quiritarian divisions. The old Roman law esta- 
blished, for example, a fundamental difference be- 
tween " Agnatic " and " Cognatic " relationship, 
that is, between the Family considered as based 
upon common subjection to patriarchal authority 
and the Family considered (in conformity with mo- 
dem ideas) as united through the mere fact of a 
common descent. This distinction disappears in the 
^Maw common to all nations," as also does the 
difference between the archaic forms of property, 
Things " Mancipi " and Things " nee Mancipi." The 
neglect of demarcations and boundaries seems to 



60 LAW OF NATURE. chap. iii. 

me, therefore, the feature of the Jus Gentium which 
was depicted in jEquitas. I imagine that the word 
was at first a mere description of that constant 
levelling or removal of irregularities whicH went on 
wherever the praetorian system was applied to the 
cases of foreign litigants. Probably no colour of 
ethical meaning belonged at first to the expression ; 
nor is there any reason to believe that the process 
which it indicated was otherwise than extremely 
distastefiil to the primitive Roman mind. 

On the other hand, the feature of the Jus Gentium 
which was presented to the apprehension of a Roman 
by the word Equity, was exactly the first and most 
vividly realised characteristic of the hypothetical 
state of nature. Nature implied symmetrical order, 
first in the physical world, and next in the moral, 
and the earliest notion of order doubtless involved 
straight lines, even surfaces, and measured distances. 
The same sort of picture or figure would be uncon- 
sciously before the mind's eye, whether it strove to 
form the outlines of the supposed natural state, or 
whether it took in at a glance the actual administra- 
tion of the " law common to all nations; " and all we 
know of primitive thought would lead us to conclude 
that this ideal similarity would do much to encourage 
the belief in an identity of the two conceptions. But 
then, while the Jus Gentium had little or no antecedent 
credit at Rome, the theory of a Law of Nature came 




CHAP. III. THE EDICT. 

in surrounded with all the prestige of philWphical 
authority, and invested with the charms of associa 
with an elder and more blissful condition of the race. 
It is easy to understand how the difference in the 
point of view would affect the dignity of the term 
Avhich at once described the operation of the old 
principles and the results of the new theory. Even 
to modem ears it is not at all the same thing to 
describe a process as one of " levelling " and to call 
it the " correction of anomalies," though the me- 
taphor IS precisely the same. Nor do I doubt that, 
when once -^quitas was understood to convey an 
allusion to the Greek theory, associations which grew 
out of the Greek notion of larori^g began to cluster 
round it. The language of Cicero renders it more 
than likely that this was so, and it was the first 
stage of a transmutation of the conception of 
Equity, which almost every ethical system which has 
appeared sioce those days has more or less helped to 
carry on. 

Something must be said of the formal instrumen- 
tality by which the principles and distinctions asso- 
ciated, first with the Law common to aU Nations, and 
afterwards with the Law of Nature, were gradually 
incorporated with the Roman law. At the crisis of 
primitive Roman history which is marked by the 
expulsion of the Tarquins, a change occurred which 
has its parallel in the early annals of many ancient 



02 THE PR^TOR. cqap. hi. 

states, but which had little in common with those 
passages of political affairs which we now term revo- 
lutions. It may best be described by saying that 
the monarchy was put into commission. The powers 
heretofore accumulated in the hands of a single per- 
son were parcelled out among a number of elective 
functionaries, the very name of the kingly office 
being retained and imposed on a personage known 
subsequently as the Rex Sacrorum or Rex Sacrifi- 
culus. As part of the change, the settled duties of 
the supreme judicial office devolved on the Praetor, 
at the time the first functionary in the commonwealth, 
and together with these duties was transferred the 
undefined supremacy over law and legislation which 
always attached to ancient sovereigns, and which is 
not obscurely related to the patriarchal and heroic 
authority they had once enjoyed. The circumstances 
of Rome gave great importance to the more indefinite 
portion of the functions thus transferred, as with the 
establishment of the republic began that series of re- 
current trials which overtook the state, in the diffi- 
culty of dealing with a multitude of persons who, 
not coming within the technical description of indige- 
nous Romans, were nevertheless permanently located 
within Roman jurisdiction. Controversies between 
such persons, or between such persons and native-bom 
citizens, would have remained without the pale of the 
remedies provided by Roman law, if the Pnetor had 



CHAP. III. THE EDICT. 63 

not undertaken to decide them, and he inust soon have 
addressed himself to the more critical disputes which 
in the extension of commerce arose between Roman 
subjects and avowed foreigners. The great increase 
of such cases in the Roman Courts about the period 
of the first Punic War is marked by the appointment 
of a special Praetor, known subsequently as the 
Praetor Peregrinus, who gave them his undivided 
attention. Meantime, one precaution of the Roman 
people against the revival of oppression, had con- 
sisted in obliging every magistrate whose duties had 
any tendency to expand their sphere, to publish, on 
commencing his year of office, an Edict or pro- 
clamation, in which he declared the manner in 
which he intended to administer his department* 
The Praetor fell under the rule with other magi- 
strates; but as it was necessarily impossible to con- 
struct each year a separate system of principles, he 
seems to have regularly republished his predeces- 
sor's Edict with such additions and changes as the 
exigency of the moment or his own views of the law 
compelled him to introduce. The Praetor's proclama- 
tion, thus lengthened by a new portion every year, 
obtained the name of the Edictum Perpetuum, that 
is, the continuous or unbroken edict. The immense 
length to which it extended, together perhaps with 
some distaste for its necessarily disorderly texture, 



64 THE PRAETOR. cuap. hi. 

caused the practice of increasing it to be stopped in 
the year of Salvius Julianus, who occupied the magi- 
stracy in the reign of the Emperor Hadrian. The 
edict of that Praetor embraced therefore the whole 
body of equity jurisprudence, which it probably dis- 
posed in new and symmetrical order, and the perpe- 
tual edict is therefore often cited in Roman law 
merely as the Edict of Julianus. 

Perhaps the first inquiry which occurs to an Eng- 
lishman who considers the peculiar mechanism of 
the Edict is, what were the limitations by which these 
extensive powers of the Praetor were restrained? 
How was authority so little definite reconciled with a 
settled condition of society and of law ? The answer 
can only be supplied by careful observation of the 
conditions under which our own English law is ad- 
ministered. The Praetor, it should be recollected, 
was a jurisconsult himself, or a person entirely in the 
hands of advisers who were jurisconsults, and it is 
probable that every Roman lawyer waited impatiently 
for the time when he should fill or control the great 
judicial magistracy. In the interval, his tastes, feel- 
ings, prejudices, and degree of enlightenment were 
inevitably those of his own order, and the qualifica- 
tions which he ultimately brought to office were those 
which he had acquired in the practice and study of 
his profession. An English Chancellor goes through 
precisely the same training, and carries to the wool- 



CHAP. 111. RESTRAINTS ON THE PE^TOR. 65 

sack the same qualifications. It is certain when he 
aissumes office that he will have, to some extent, mo- 
dified the law before he leaves it ; but until he has 
quitted his seat, and the series of his decisions in the 
Law Reports has been completed, we cannot discover 
how far he has elucidated or added to the principles 
which his predecessors bequeathed to him. The in- 
fluence of the PraBtor on Roman jurisprudence differed 
only in respect of the period at which its amount was 
ascertained. As was before stated, he was in office 
but for a year, and his decisions rendered during his 
year, though of course irreversible as regarded the 
litigants, were of no ulterior value. The most natu- 
ral moment for declaring the changes he proposed to 
effect occurred therefore at his entrance on the praB- 
torship, and hence, when commencing his duties, he 
did openly and avowedly that which in the end his 
English representative does insensibly and sometimes 
unconsciously. The checks on his apparent liberty 
are precisely those imposed on an English judge. 
Theoretically there seems to be hardly any limit to 
the powers of either of them, but practically the Ro- 
man Praetor, no less than the English Chancellor, 
was kept within the narrowest bounds by the prepos- 
sessions imbibed from early training and by the 
strong restraints of professional opinion, restraints of 
which the stringency can only be appreciated by 
those who have personally experienced them. It may 



GG EQUITY. CHAP. in. 

be added that the lines within which movement is 
permitted, and beyond which there is to be no travel- 
ling, were chalked with as much distinctness in the 
one case as in the other. In England the judge fol- 
lows the analogies of reported decisions on insulated 
groups of facts. At Rome, as the intervention of the 
Praetor was at first dictated by simple concern for the 
safety of the state, it is likely that in the earliest 
times it was proportioned to the difficulty which it 
attempted to get rid of. Afterwards, when the taste 
for principle had been diflFused by the Responses, he no 
doubt, used the Edict as the means of giving a wider 
application to those fundamental principles which he 
and the other practising jurisconsults, his contempo- 
raries, believed themselves to have detected under- 
lying the law. Latterly he acted wholly under the 
influence of Greek philosophical theories, which at 
once tempted him to advance and confined him to a 
particular course of progress. 

The nature of the measures attributed to Salvius 
Julianus has been much disputed. Whatever they 
were, their effects on the Edict are sufficiently plain. 
It ceased to be extended by annual additions, and 
henceforward the equity jurisprudence of Rome 
was developed by the labours of a succession of 
great jurisconsults who fill with their writings the 
interval between the reign of Hadrian and the reign 
of Alexander Severus. A fragment of the won- 



CHAP. ui. ROMAN EQUITY. 67 

derfiil system which they built up survives in the 
Pandects of Justinian, and supplies evidence that 
their works took the form of treatises on all parts 
of Roman law, but chiefly that of commentaries on 
the Edict. Indeed, whatever be the immediate sub- 
ject of a jurisconsult of this epoch, he may always 
be called an expositor of Equity. The principles 
of the Edict had, before the epoch of its cessation, 
made their way into every part of Roman jurispru- 
dence. The Equity of Rome, it should be understood, 
even when most distinct from the Civil Law, was 
always administered by the same tribunals. The 
Praetor was the chief equity judge as well as the great 
common law magistrate, and as soon as the Edict had 
evolved an equitable rule the Praetor's court began to 
apply it in place of or by the side of the old rule of 
the Civil Law, which was thus directly or indirectly 
repealed without any express enactment of the legis- 
lature. The result, of course, fell considerably short 
of a complete fusion of law and equity, which was not 
carried out till the reforms of Justinian. The techni- 
cal severance of the two elements of jurisprudence 
entailed some confusion and some inconvenience, 
and there were certain of the stubbomer doctrines 
of the Civil Law with which neither the authors 
nor the expositors of the Edict had ventured to in- 
terfere. But at the same time there was no corner 
of the field of jurisprudence which was not more or 

p 2 



lis EQUITY. CHAP. III. 

less swept over by the influence of Equity. It sup- 
plied the jurist with all his materials for generalisa- 
tion, with all his methods of interpretation, with 
his elucidations of first principles, and with that 
great mass of limiting rules which are rarely inter- 
fered with by the legislator, but which seriously 
control the application of every legislative act. 

The period of jurists ends with Alexander Severus. 
From Hadrian to that emperor the improvement of 
law was carried on, as it is at the present moment in 
most continental countries, partly by approved com- 
mentaries and partly by direct legislation. But in 
the reign of Alexander Severus the power of growth 
in Roman Equity seems to be exhausted, and the suc- 
cession of jurisconsults comes to a close. • The remain- 
ing history of the Roman law is the history of the 
imperial constitutions, and, at the last, of attempts to 
codify what had now become the unwieldy body of 
Roman jurisprudence. We have the latest and most 
celebrated experiment of this kind in the Corpus Juris 
of Justinian. 

It would be wearisome to enter on a detailed com- 
parison or contrast of English and Roman Equity, 
but it may be worth while to mention two features 
\ which they have in common. The first may be 

stated as follows. Each of them tended, and all 
such systems tend, to exactly the same state in 
which the old common law was when Equity first 



CHAP. III. EKGLISU AND ROMAN EQUITY. 6^ 

interfered with it. A time always comes at which 
the moral principles originally adopted have been 
carried out to all their legitimate consequences, and 
then the system founded on them becomes as rigid, 
as unexpansive, and as liable to fall behind moral 
progress as the sternest code of rules avowedly legal. 
Such an epoch was reached at Rome in the reign 
of Alexander Severus; after which, though the 
whole Roman world was undergoing a moral revo- 
lution, the Equity of Rome ceased to expand. The 
same point of legal history was attained in Eng- 
land under the chancellorship of Lord Eldon, the 
first of our equity judges who, instead of enlarg- 
ing the jurisprudence of his court by indirect 
legislation, devoted himself through life to explain- 
ing and harmonising it. If the philosophy of legal 
history were better understood in England, Lord 
Eldon's services would be less exaggerated on the 
one hand and better appreciated on the other than 
than they appear to be among contemporary lawyers. 
Other misapprehensions too, which bear some prac; 
tical fruit, would perhaps be avoided. It is easily 
seen by English lawyers that English Equity is a 
system founded on moral rules; but it is forgotten 
that these rules are the morality of past centuries — 
not of the present — that they have received nearly 
as much application as they are capable of, and that, 
though of course they do not differ largely from the 

F 3 



70 EQUITY. cuAP. iii. 

ethical creed of our own day, they are not necessarily 
on a level with it. The imperfect theories of the 
subject which are commonly adopted have generated 
errors of opposite sorts. Many writers of treatises 
on Equity, struck with the completeness of the system 
in its present state, commit themselves expressly 
or implicitly to the paradoxical assertion that the 
founders of the chancery jurisprudence contem- 
plated its present fixity of form when they were 
settling its first bases. Others, again, complain — 
and this is a grievance frequently observed upon in 
forensic arguments — that the moral rules enforced 
by the Court of Chancery fall short of the ethical 
standard of the present day. They would have 
each Lord Chancellor perform precisely the same 
ojQSce for the jurisprudence which he finds ready 
to his hand, which was performed for the old com- 
mon law by the fathers of English equity. But this 
is to invert the order of the agencies by which the 
improvement of the law is carried on. Equity has its 
place and its time; but 1 have pointed out that 
another instrumentality is ready to succeed it when 
its energies are spent. 

Another remarkable characteristic of both English 
and Roman Equity is the falsehood of the assump- 
tions upon which the claim of the equitable to supe- 
riority over the legal rule is originally defended. 
Nothing is more distasteful to men, either as indi- 



CHAP. m. ENGLISH AND ROMAN EQUITY. 71 

viduals or as masses, than the admission of their 
moral progress as a substantive reality. This un- 
willingness shows itself, as regards individuals, in the 
exaggerated respect which is ordinarily paid to the 
doubtful virtue of consistency. The movement of the 
collective opinion of a whole society is too palpable 
to be ignored, and is generally too visibly for the 
better to be decried; but there is the greatest dis- 
inclination to accep* it as a primary phenomenon, and 
it is commonly explained as the recovery of a lost 
perfection — the gradual return to a state from which 
the race has lapsed. This tendency to look back- 
ward instead of forward for the goal of moral pro- 
gress produced anciently, as we have seen, on Roman 
jurisprudence effects the most serious and perma- 
nent. The Roman jurisconsults, in order to account 
for the improvement of their jurisprudence by the 
Praetor, borrowed from Greece the doctrine of a 
Natural state of man — a Natural society — anterior 
to the organisation of commonwealths governed by 
positive laws. In England, on the other hand, a 
range of ideas especially congenial to Englishmen of 
that day, explained the claim of Equity to override 
the common law by supposing a general right to 
superintend the administration of justice which was 
assumed to be vested in the king as a natural result 
of his paternal authority. The same view appears 
in a different and a quainter form in the old doctrine 

F 4 



72 EQUITY. CHAP. iii. 

that Equity flowed from the king^s conscience — the 
improvement which had in fact taken place in the 
moral standard of the community being thus referred 
to an inherent elevation in the moral sense of the 
sovereign. The growth of the English constitution 
rendered such a theory unpalatable after a time; 
but, as the jurisdiction of the Chancery was then 
firmly established, it was not worth while to devise 
any formal substitute for it. The theories found 
in modem manuals of Equity are very various, but all 
are alike in their untenabUity. Most of them are 
modifications of the Roman doctrine of a natural 
law, which is indeed adopted in tenour by those 
writers who begin a discussion of the jurisdiction 
of the Court of Chancery by laying down a dis- 
tinction between natural justice and civil. 



CHAP. IV, I^AW OP NATURE. 73 

CHAP. IV. 
THE MODERN HISTORY OF THE LAW OF NATURE. 

It will be inferred from what has been said that 
the theory which transformed the Roman jurispru- 
dence had no claim to philosophical precision. It 
involved, in fact, one of those "mixed modes of 
thought" which are now acknowledged to have 
characterised all but the highest minds during the 
infancy of speculation, and which are far from un- 
discoverable even in the mental efforts of our own 
day. The Law of Nature confused the Past and the 
Present. Logically, it implied a state of Nature 
which had once been regulated by natural law; yet 
the jurisconsults do not speak clearly or confidently 
of the existence of such a state, which indeed is little 
noticed by the ancients except where it finds a 
poetical expression in the fancy of a golden age. 
Natural law, for all practical purposes, was something 
belonging to the present, something entwined with 
existing institutions, something which could be dis- 
tinguished from them by a competent observer. The 
test which separated the ordinances of Nature from 
the gross ingredients with which they were mingled 
was a sense of simplicity and harmony ; yet it was not 
on account of their simplicity and harmony that these 



74 MODERN HISTORY OF NATURAL LAW. chap. iv. 

finer elements were primarily respected, but on the 
score of 'their descent from the aboriginal reign of 
Nature. This confusion has not been successfully 
explained away by the modem disciples of the juris- 
consults, and in truth modem speculations on the 
Law of Nature betray much more indistinctness of 
perception and are vitiated by much more hopeless 
ambiguity of language than the Roman lawyers can 
be justly charged with. There are some writers on 
the subject who attempt to evade the fundamental 
difficulty by contending that the code of Nature 
exists in the future and is the goal to which all civil 
laws are moving, but this is to reverse the assump- 
tions on which the old theory rested or rather 
perhaps to mix together two inconsistent theories. 
The tendency to look not to the past but to the future 
for types of perfection was brought into the world 
by Christianity. Ancient literature ^ves few or 
no hints of a belief that the progress of society is 
necessarily from worse to better. 

But the importance of this theory to mankind has 
been very much greater than its philosophical de- 
ficiencies would lead us to expect. Indeed, it is not 
easy to say what turn the history of thought, and 
therefore, of the human race, would have taken, if the 
belief in a law natural had not become universal in 
the ancient world. 

There are two special dangers to which law, and 



CHAP. ir. PERILS OF EARLY SOCIETY. 75 

society which is held together by law, appear to be 
liable in their infancy. One of them is that law 
may be too rapidly developed. This occurred with 
the codes of the more progressive Greek commu- 
nities, which disembarrassed themselves with as- 
tonishing facility from cumbrous forms of procedure 
and needless terms of art, and soon ceased to attach 
any superstitious value^ to rigid rules and prescrip- 
tions. It was not for the ultimate advantage of 
mankind that they did so, though the immediate 
benefit conferred on their citizens may have been 
considerable. One of the rarest qualities of national 
character is the capacity for applying and working 
out the law, as such, at the cost of constant mis- 
carriages of abstract justice, without at the same 
time losing the hope or the wish that law may be 
conformed to a higher ideal. The Greek intellect, 
with all its nobility and elasticity, was quite unable to 
confine itself within the strait waistcoat of a legal 
formula; and, if we may judge them by the popular 
courts of Athens of whose working we possess ac- 
curate knowledge, the Greek tribunals exhibited the 
strongest tendency to confound law and fact. The 
remains of the Orators and the forensic common- 
places preserved by Aristotle in his Treatise on 
Rhetoric, show that questions of pure law were con- 
stantly argued on every consideration which could 
possibly influence the mind of the judges. No durable 



76 NATURAL LAW OF THE JURISCONSULTS, chap. iv. 

system of jurisprudence could be produced in this 
way. A community which never hesitated to relax 
rules of written law whenever they stood in the way 
of an ideally perfect decision on the facts of particular 
cases, would only, if it bequeathed any body of 
judicial principles to posterity, bequeath one con- 
sisting of the ideas of right and wrong which hap- 
pened to be prevalent at the time. Such a juris- 
prudence would contain no framework to which the 
more advanced conceptions of subsequent ages could 
be fitted. It would amount at best to a philosophy, 
marked with the imperfections of the civilisation 
under which it grew up- 
Few national societies have had their jurispru- 
dence menaced by this peculiar danger of precocious 
maturity and untimely disintegration. It is cer- 
tainly doubtful whether the Romans were ever 
seriously threatened by it, but at any rate they had 
adequate protection in their theory of Natural Law. 
For the Natural Law of the jurisconsults was dis- 
tinctly conceived by them as a system which ought 
gradually to absorb civil laws, without superseding 
them so long as they remained unrepealed. There 
was no such impression of its sanctity abroad, that 
an appeal to it would be likely to overpower the 
mind of a judge who was charged with the superin- 
tendence of a particular litigation. The value and 
serviceableness of the conception arose from its 



CHAP. IV. LAW OF NATURE, 77 

keeping before the mental vision a type of perfect 
law, and from its inspiring the hope of an indefinite 
approximation to it, at the same time that it never 
tempted the practitioner or the citizen to deny the 
obligation of existing laws which had not yet been ad- 
justed to the theory. It is important too to observe 
that this model system, unlike many of those which 
have mocked men's hopes in later days, was not 
entirely the product of imagination. It was never 
thought of as founded on quite untested principles. 
The notion was that it underlay existing law and 
must be looked for through it. Its functions were 
in short remedial, not revolutionary or anarchical. 
And this, unfortunately, is the exact poiot at which 
the modern view of a Law of Nature has often ceased 
to resemble the ancient. 

The other liability to which the infancy of society 
is exposed has prevented or arrested the progress of 
far the greater part of mankind. The rigidity of 
primitive law, arising chiefly from its early associa- 
tion and identification with religion, has chained 
down the mass of the human race to those views 
of life and conduct which they entertained at the 
time when their usages were first consolidated into 
a systematic form. There were one or two races 
exempted by a marvellous fate from this calamity, 
and grafts from these stocks have fertilised a few 
modem societies, but it is still true that, over the 



.<<^^r.VA.J 



\ >; 






78 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

larger part of the world, the perfection of law has 
always been considered as consisting in adherence to 
the ground plan supposed to have been marked out by 
the original legislator. If intellect has in such cases 
been exercised on jurisprudence, it has uniformly 
prided itself on the subtle perversity of the conclu- 
sions it could build on ancient texts, without dis- 
coverable departure from their literal tenour, I know 
no reason why the law of the Romans should be su- 
perior to the laws of the Hindoos, unless the theory 
of Natural Law had given it a type of excellence 
different from the usual one. In this one excep- 
tional instance, simplicity and symmetry were kept 
before the eyes of a society whose influence on man- 
kind was destined to be prodigious from other causes, 
as the characteristics of an ideal and absolutely per- 
fect law. It is impossible to overrate the importance 
to a nation or profession of having a distinct object 
to aim at in the pursuit of improvement. The secret 
of Bentham's immense influence in England during 
the past thirty years is his success in placing such 
an object before the country. He gave us a clear 
rule of reform. English lawyers of the last century 
were probably too acute to be blinded by the para- 
doxical commonplace that English law was the per- 
fection of human reason, but they acted as if they 
believed it for want of any other principle to pro- 



CHAP. ;v. BENTFIAMISM. 79 

ceed upoB. Bentham made the good of the com- 
munity take precedence of every other object, and 
thus gave escape to a current which had long been 
trying to find its way outwards. 

It is not an altogether fanciful comparison if we call 
the assumptions we have been describing the ancient 
counterpart of Benthamism. The Roman theory 
guided men's efforts in the same direction as the 
theory put into shape by the Englishman ; its prac- 
tical results were not widely different from those 
which would have been attained by a sect of law- 
reformers who maintained a steady pursuit of the 
general good of the community. It would be a 
mistake, however, to suppose it a conscious anticipa- 
tion of Bentham's principles. The happiness of 
mankind is, no doubt, sometimes assigned, both in 
the popular and in the legal literature of the Romans, 
as the proper object of remedial legislation, but it is 
very remarkable how few and faint are the testimonies 
to this principle compared with the tributes which are 
constantly offered to the overshadowing claims of the 
Law of Nature. It was not to anything resembling 
philanthropy, but to their sense of simplicity and 
harmony — of what they significantly termed " ele- 
gance " — that the Roman jurisconsults fi*eely surren- 
dered themselves. The coincidence of their labours 
with those which a more precise philosophy would 



80 niSTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

have counselled has been part of the good fortune 
of mankind. 

Turning to the modern history of the law of nature, 
we find it easier to convince ourselves of the vast- 
ness of its influence than to pronounce confidently 
whether that influence has been exerted for good or 
for evil. The doctrines and institutions which may 
be attributed to it are the material of some of the 
most violent controversies debated in our time, as 
will be seen when it is stated that the theory of 
Natural Law is the source of almost all the special 
ideas as to law, politics, and society which France 
during the last hundred years has been the instru- 
ment of diffusing over the western world. The part 
played by jurists in French history, and the sphere 
of jural conceptions in French thought, have always 
been remarkably large. It was not indeed in France, 
but in Italy, that the juridical science of modem 
Europe took its rise, but of the schools founded by 
emissaries of the Italian universities in aU parts of 
the continent, and attempted (though vainly) to be 
set up in our island, that established in France pro- 
duced the greatest effect on the fortunes of the 
country. The lawyers of France immediately formed 
a strict alliance with the kings of the house of Capet, 
and it was as much through their assertions of royal 
prerogative, and through their interpretations of the 
rules of feudal succession, as by the power of the 



CHAP. IV. THE FRENCH LAWYERS. 81 

sword, that the French monarchy at last grew to- 
gether out of the agglomeration of provinces and 
dependencies. The enormous advantage which their 
understanding with the lawyers conferred on the 
French kings in the prosecution of their struggle 
with the great feudatories, the aristocracy, and the 
church, can only be appreciated if we take into 
account the ideas which prevailed in Europe far down 
into the middle ages. There was, in the first place, 
a great enthusiasm for generalisation and a curious 
admiration for all general propositions, and conse- 
quently, in the field of law, an involuntary reverence 
for every general formula which seemed to embrace 
and sum up a number of the insulated rules which 
were practised as usages in various localities. Such 
general formulas it was, of course, not difficult for 
practitioners familiar with the Corpus Juris or the 
Glosses to supply in almost any quantity. There was, 
however, another cause which added yet more consi- 
derably to the lawyers' power. At the period of 
which we are speaking, there was universal vagueness 
of ideas as to the degree and nature of the authority 
residing in written texts of law. For the most part,^ 
the peremptory preface, Ita scriptum est^ seems to 
have been sufficient to silence all objections. Where 
a mind of our own day would jealously scrutinise the 
formula which had been quoted, would inquire its 
source, and would (if necessary) deny that the body 



82 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap, i v. 

of law to which it belonged had any authority to 
supersede local customs, the elder jurist would not 
probably have ventured to do more than question the 
applicability of the rule, or at best cite some counter- 
proposition from the Pandects or the Canon Law. It 
is extremely necessary to bear in mind the uncer- 
tainty of men's notions on this most important side 
of juridical controversies, not only because it helps to 
explain the weight which the lawyers threw into the 
monarchical scale, but on account of the light which 
it sheds on several curious historical problems. The 
motives of the author of the Forged Decretals and 
his extraordinary success are rendered more intelli- 
gible by it. And, to take a phenomenon of smaller 
interest, it assists us, though only partially, to under- 
stand the plagiarisms of Bracton. That an English 
writer of the time of Henry III. should have been 
able to put off on his countrymen as a compendium 
of pure English law a treatise of which the entire 
form and a third of the contents were directly bor- 
rowed from the Corpus Juris, and that he should have 
ventured on this experiment in a country where the 
systematic study of the Roman law was formally 
proscribed, will always be among the most hopeless 
enigmas in the history of jurisprudence; but still it 
is something to lessen our surprise when we compre- 
hend the state of opinion at the period as to the 
obligatory force of written texts, apart from all con- 
sideration of the source whence they were derived. 



HAP. IV. THE FRENCH LAWYERS. 83 

When the kings of France had brought their long 
struggle for supremacy to a successful close, an epoch 
which may be placed roughly at the accession of the 
Hbranch of Valois-Angoulfeme to the throne, the situa- 
tion of the French jurists was peculiar and continued 
to be so down to the outbreak of the revolution. On 
the one hand, they formed the best instructed and 
nearly the most powerful class in the nation. They 
had made good their footing as a privileged order by 
the side of the feudal aristocracy, and they had assured 
their influence by an organisation which distributed 
their profession over France in great chartered corpo- 
rations possessing large defined powers and still larger 
indefinite claims. In aU the qualities of the advocate, 
the judge, and the legislator, they far excelled their 
compeers throughout Europe. Their juridical tact, 
their ease of expression, their fine sense of analogy 
and harmony, and (if they may be judged by the 
highest names among them) their passionate devotion 
to their conceptions of justice, were as remarkable as 
the singular variety of talent which they included, a 
variety covering the whole ground between the oppo- 
site poles of Cujas and Montesquieu, of D'Aguesseau 
and Dumoulin. But, on the other hand, the system of 
laws which they had to administer stood in striking 
contrast with the habits of mind which they had cul- 
tivated. The France which had been in great part 
constituted by their efforts was smitten with the 

G 3 



84 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

curse of an anomalous and dissonant jurisprudence 
beyond every other country in Europe. One great 
division ran through the country and separated it 
into Pays du Droit Ecrit and Pays du Droit Coutu-* 
mierj the first acknowledging the written Roman law 
as the basis of their jurisprudence, the last admitting 
it only so far as it supplied general forms of expres- 
sion, and courses of juridical reasoning, which were 
reconcileable with the local usages. The sections 
thus formed were again variously subdivided. In 
the Pays du Droit Coutumier province differed from 
province, county from county, municipality from 
municipality, in the nature of its customs. In the 
Pays du Droit Ecrit the stratum of feudal rules 
which overlay the Roman law was of the most miscel- 
laneous composition. No such confusion as this ever 
existed in England. In Germany it did exist, but 
was too much in harmony with the deep political and 
religious divisions of the country to be lamented or 
even felt. It was the special peculiarity of France 
that an extraordinary diversity of laws continued 
without sensible alteration while the central authority 
of the monarchy was constantly strengthening itself, 
while rapid approaches were being made to complete 
administrative unity, and while a fervid national 
spirit had been developed among the people. The 
contrast was one which fructified in many serious 
results, and among them we must rank the effect 
which it produced on the minds of the French 



CHAP. IT. THE FRENCH LAWYERS. 85 

lawyers. Their speculative opinions and their intel- 
lectual bias were in the strongest opposition to their 
interests and professional habits. With the keenest 
sense and the fullest recognition of those perfections 
of jurisprudence which consist in simplicity and 
uniformity, they believed, or seemed to believe, that 
the vices which actually infested French law were 
ineradicable; and in practice they often resisted the 
reformation of abuses with an obstinacy which was 
not shown by many among their less enlightened 
countrymen. But there was a way to reconcile these 
contradictions. They became passionate enthusiasts 
for Natural Law. The Law of Nature overleapt all 
provincial and municipal boundaries ;• it disregarded 
all distinctions between noble and burgess, between 
burgess and peasant ; it gave the most exalted place 
to lucidity, simplicity and system ; but it committed 
its devotees to no specific improvement, and did not 
directly threaten any venerable or lucrative technica- 
lity. Natural law may said to have become the 
common law of France, or, at all events, the admis- 
sion of its dignity and claims was the one tenet which 
all French practitioners alike subscribed to. The 
language of the prae-revolutionary jurists in its eulogy 
is singularly unqualified, and it is remarkable that 
the writers on the Customs, who often made it their 
duty to speak disparagingly of the pure Roman law, 
speak even more fervidly of Nature and her rules than 

G 3 



86 mSTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

the civilians who professed an exclusive respect for 
the Digest and the Code. Dumoulin, the highest of 
all authorities on old French Customary Law, has 
some extravagant passages on the Law of Nature; 
and his panegyrics have a peculiar rhetorical turn 
which indicates a considerable departure from the 
caution of the Eoman jurisconsults. The hypothesis 
of a Natural Law had become not so much a theory 
guiding practice as an article of speculative faith, 
and accordingly we shall find that, in the transfor- 
mation which it more recently underwent, its weakest 
parts rose to the level of its strongest in the esteem 
of its supporters. 

The eighteenth century was half over when the 
most critical period in the history of Natural Law was 
reached. Had the discussion of the theory and of 
its consequences continued to be exclusively the em- 
ployment of the legal profession, there would pos- 
sibly have been an abatement of the respect which it 
commanded; for by this time the Esprit des Lois had 
appeared. Bearing in some exaggerations the marks 
of the excessive violence with which its author's 
mind had recoiled from assumptions usually suf- 
fered to pass without scrutiny, yet showing in some 
ambiguities the traces of a desire to compromise with 
existing prejudice, the book of Montesquieu, with 
all its defects, still proceeded on that Historical 
Method before which the Law of Nature has never 
maintained its footing for an instant. Its influence 



CHAP. IV. ROUSSEAU. 87 

on thought ought to have been as great as its 
general popularity ; but, in fact, it was never allowed 
time to put it forth, for the counter-hypothesis 
which it seemed destined to destroy passed sud- 
denly from the forum to the street, and became the 
key-note of controversies far more exciting than 
are ever agitated in the courts or the schools. The 
person who launched it on its new career was that 
remarkable man who, without learning, with few 
virtues, and with no strength of character, has 
nevertheless stamped himself ineffaceably on history 
by the force of a vivid imagination, and by the help 
of a genuine and burning love for his fellow-men, 
for which much will always have to be forgiven him. 
We have never seen in our own generation — indeed 
the world has not seen more than once or twice in all 
the course of history — a literature which has exer- 
cised such prodigious influence over the minds of 
men, over every cast and shade of intellect, as that 
which emanated from Rousseau between 1749 and 
1762. It was the first attempt to re-erect the edifice 
of human belief after the purely iconoclastic efibrts 
commenced by Bayle, and in part by our own Locke, 
and consummated by Voltaire ; and besides the supe- 
riority which every constructive effort will always 
enjoy over one that is merely destructive, it possessed 
the immense advantage of appearing amid an all 
but universal scepticism as to the soundness of all 

G 4 



8B HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

foregone knowledge in matters speculative. Now, in 
all the speculations of Rousseau, the central figure, 
whether arrayed in an English dress as the signa- 
tary of a social compact, or simply stripped naked of 
all historical qualities, is uniformly Man, in a sup- 
posed state of nature. Every law or institution 
which would misbeseem this imaginary being under 
these ideal circumstances is to be condemned as 
having lapsed from an original perfection; every 
transformation of society which would give it a 
closer resemblance to the world over which the 
creature of Nature reigned, is admirable and worthy 
to be eflfected at any apparent cost. The theory is 
stiU that of the Roman lawyers, for in the phan- 
tasmagoria with which the Natural Condition is 
peopled, every feature and characteristic eludes the 
mind except the simplicity and harmony which pos- 
sessed such charms for the jurisconsult; but the 
theory is, as it were, turned upside down. It is not 
the Law of Nature, but the State of Nature, which is 
now the primary subject of contemplation. The 
Roman had conceived that by careful observation 
of existing institutions parts of them could be singled 
out which either exhibited already, or could by 
judicious purification be made to exhibit, the vestiges 
of that reign of nature whose reality he faintly 
affirmed. Rousseau's belief was that a perfect social 
order could be evolved from the unassisted considera- 



CHAP. IV. THEORIES OF ROUSSEAU. 89 

tion of the natural state, a social order wholly irre- 
spective of the actual condition of the world and 
wholly unlike it. The great difference between the 
views is that one bitterly and broadly condemns the 
present for its unlikeness to the ideal past ; while the 
other, assuming the present to be as necessary as the 
past, does not affect to disregard or censure it. It is 
not worth our while to analyse with any particu- 
larity that philosophy of politics, art, education, 
ethics, and social relation which was constructed on 
the basis of a state of nature. It still possesses 
singular fascination for the looser thinkers of every 
country, and is no doubt the parent, more or less 
remote, of almost all the prepossessions which im- 
pede the employment of the Historical Method of in- 
quiry, but its discredit with the higher minds of our 
day is deep enough to astonish those who are familiar 
with the extraordinary vitality of speculative error. 
Perhaps the question most frequently asked nowa- 
days is not what is the value of these opinions, but 
what were the causes which gave them such over- 
shadowing prominence a hundred years ago. The 
answer is, I conceive, a simple one. The study 
which in the last century would best have corrected 
the misapprehensions into which an exclusive atten- 
tion to legal antiquities is apt to betray was the 
study of religion. But Greek religion, as then under- 
stood, was dissipated in imaginative myths. The 



DO HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

Oriental religions, if noticed at all, appeared to be 
lost in vain cosmogonies. There was but one body 
of primitive records which was worth studying — the 
early history of the Jews. But resort to this was 
prevented by the prejudices of the time. One of the 
few characteristics which the school of Eousseau had 
in common with the school of Voltaire was an utter 
disdain of all religious antiquities; and, more than 
all, of those of the Hebrew race. It is well known 
that it was a point of honour with the reasoners of 
that day to assume not merely that the institutions 
called after Moses were not divinely dictated, nor 
even that they were codified at a later diate than that 
attributed to them, but that they and the entire 
Pentateuch were a gratuitous forgery, executed after 
the return from the Captivity. Debarred, therefore, 
from one chief security against speculative delusion, 
the philosophers of France, in their eagerness to 
escape from what they deemed a superstition of the 
priests, flung themselves headlong into a superstition 
of the lawyers. 

But though the philosophy founded on the hypo- 
thesis of a state of nature has fallen low in general 
esteem, in so far as it is looked upon under its coarser 
and more palpable aspect, it does not follow that in 
its subtler disguises it has lost plausibility, popu- 
larity, or power. I believe, as I have said, that it is 
still the great antagonist of the Historical Method; 



CHAP. IT. THE FRENCH REVOLUTION. 91 

and whenever (religious objections apart) any mind 
is seen to resist or contemn that mode of investi- 
gation, it will generally be found under the influence 
of a prejudice or vicious bias traceable to a conscious 
or unconscious reliance on a non-historic, natural, 
condition of society or the individual. It is chiefly, 
however, by allying themselves with political and 
jsocial tendencies that the doctrines of Nature and her 
law have preserved their energy. Some of these tend- 
encies they have stimulated, others they have actually 
created, to a great number they have given expres- 
sion and form. They visibly enter largely into the 
ideas which constantly radiate from France over the 
civilised world, and thus become part of the general 
body of thought by which its civilisation is modified. 
The value of the influence which they thus exercise 
over the fortunes of the race is of course one of the 
points which our age debates most warmly, and it 
is beside the purpose of this treatise to discuss it. 
Looking back, however, to the period at which the 
theory of the state of nature acquired the maximum 
of political importance, there are few who will deny 
that it helped most powerfully to bring about the 
grosser disappointments of which the first French 
Revolution was fertile. It gave birth, or intense 
stimulus, to the vices of mental habit all but uni- 
versal at the time, disdain of positive law, impatience 
of experience, and the preference of a priori to all 



92 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

other reasoning. In proportion too as this philo- 
sophy fixes its grasp on minds which have thought 
less than others and fortified themselves with smaller 
observation, its tendency is to become distinctly 
anarchical. It is surprising to note how many of the 
Sophismes Anarchiques which Dumont published for 
Bentham, and which embody Bentham's exposure of 
errors distinctively French, are derived from the 
Roman hypothesis in its French transformation, and 
are unintelligible unless referred to it. On this point 
too it is a curious exercise to consult the Moniteur 
during the principal eras of the Revolution. The ap- 
peals to the Law and State of Nature become thicker 
as the times grow darker. They are comparatively 
rare in the Constituent Assembly; they are much 
more frequent in the Legislative; in the Convention, 
amid the din of debate on conspiracy and war, they 
are perpetual. 

There is a single example which very strikingly 
illustrates the effects of the theory of natural law on 
modem society, and indicates how very far are those 
effects from being exhausted. There cannot, I con- 
ceive, be any question that to the assumption of a 
Law Natural we owe the doctrine of the fundamental 
equality of human beings. That " all men are equal" 
is one of a large number of legal propositions which, 
in progress of time, have become political. The Ro- 
man jurisconsults of the Antonine era lay down that 



CHAP. IV. EQUALITY OF MEX. 

" omnes homines naturft sequales sunt," but 
eyes this is a strictly juridical axiom. They in' 
to affirm that, under the hypothetical Law of Nature, 
and in so far as positive law approximates to it, the 
arbitrary distinctions which the Roman CivU Law 
maintained between classes of persons cease to have 
a legal existence. The rule was one of considerable 
importance to the Roman practitioner, who required 
to be reminded that, wherever Roman jurisprudence 
was assumed to conform itself exactly to the code of 
Nature, there was no difference in the contemplation 
of the Roman tribunals between citizen and foreigner, 
between freeman and slave, between Agnate and Cog- 
nate. The jurisconsults who thus expressed themselves 
most certainly never intended to censure the social 
arrangements under which civil law fell somewhat 
short of its speculative type ; nor did they apparently 
believe that the world would ever see human society 
completely assimilated to the economy of nature. 
But when the doctrine of human equality makes its 
appearance in a modem dress it has evidently clothed 
itself with a new shade of meaning. Where the Ro- 
man jurisconsult had written " SBquales sunt," mean- 
ing exactly what he said, the modem civilian wrote 
"all men are equal" in the sense of "all men ought 
to be equal." The peculiar Roman idea that na- 
tural law coexisted with civil law and gradually ab- 
sorbed it, had evidently been lost sight of, or had 




94 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. ir. 

become unintelligible, and the words which had at 
most conveyed a theory concerning the origin, com- 
position, and development of human institutions, were 
beginning to express the sense of a great standing 
wrong suffered by mankind. As early as the beginning 
of the fourteenth century, the current language con- 
cerning the birth-state of men, though visibly intended 
to be identical with that of Ulpian and his contempo- 
raries, has assumed an altogether different form and 
meaning. The preamble to the celebrated ordinance 
of King Louis Hutin enfranchising the serfs of the 
royal domains would have sounded strangely to 
Roman ears. " Whereas, according to natural law, 
everybody ought to be born free ; and by some usages 
and customs which, from long antiquity, have been 
introduced and kept until now in our realm, and per- 
adventure by reason of the misdeeds of their prede- 
cessors, many persons of our common people have 
fallen into servitude, therefore, We, &c." This is the 
enunciation not of a legal rule but of a political 
dogma; and from this time the equality of men is 
spoken of by the French lawyers just as if it were a 
political truth which happened to have been preserved 
among the archives of their science. Like all other 
deductions from the hypothesis of a Law Natural, and 
like the belief itself in a Law of Nature, it was lan- 
guidly assented to and suffered to have little influence 
on opinion and practice until it passed out of the 
possession of the lawyers into that of the literary 



CHAP. IV. DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE. 95 

men of the eighteenth century and of the public which 
sat at their feet. With them it became the most 
distinct tenet of their creed, and was even regarded as 
a summary of all the others. It is probable, however, 
that the power which it ultimately acquired over the 
events of 1789 was not entirely owing to its popularity 
in France, for in the middle of the century it passed 
over to America. The American lawyers of the 
time, and particularly those of Virginia, appear to 
have possessed a stock of knowledge which differed 
chiefly from that of their English contemporaries in 
including much which could only have been derived 
from the legal literature of continental Europe. A 
very few glances at the writings of Jefferson will show 
how strongly his mind was affected by the semi-juri- 
dical, semi-popular opinions which were fashionable in 
France, and we cannot doubt that it was sympathy 
with the peculiar ideas of the French jurists which 
led him and the other colonial lawyers who guided 
the course of events in America to join the specially 
French assumption that " all men are bom equal " 
with the assumption, more familiar to Englishmen, 
that " all men are bom free," in the very first lines 
of their Declaration of Independence. The passage 
was one of great importance to the history of the 
doctrine before us. The American lawyers, in thus 
prominently and emphatically affirming the fun- 
damental equality of human beings, gave an im- 
pulse to political movements in their own country, 



96 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. ohap. iv. 

and in a less degree in Great Britain, which is far 
from having yet spent itself; but besides this they 
returned the dogma they had adopted to its home in 
France, endowed with vastly greater energy and en- 
joying much greater claims on general reception and 
respect. Even the more cautious politicians of the first 
Constituent Assembly repeated Ulpian's proposition 
as if it at once commended itself to the instincts and 
intuitions of mankind; and of all the "principles of 
1789 " it is the one which has been least strenuously 
assailed, which has most thoroughly leavened modem 
opinion, and which promises to modify most deeply 
the constitution of societies and the politics of states. 

The grandest function of the Law of Nature was 
discharged in giving birth to modem International 
Law and to the modern Law of War, but this part 
of its effects must here be dismissed with consider- 
ation very unequal to its importance. 

Among the postulates which form the foundation 
of International Law, or of so much of it as retains 
the figure which it received from its original archi- 
tects, there are two or three of preeminent import- 
ance. The first of all is expressed in the position 
that there is a determinable Law of Nature. Gro- 
tius and his successors took the assumption directly 
from the Romans, but they differed widely from 
the Roman jurisconsults and from each other in 
their ideas as to the mode of determination. The 



CHAP. IV. . INTERNATIONAL LAW. 97 

ambition of almost every Publicist who has flourished 
since the revival of letters has been to provide new 
and more manageable definitions of Nature and of her 
law, and it is indisputable that the conception in 
passing through the long series of writers on Public 
Law has gathered round it a large accretion, con- 
sisting of fragments of ideas derived from nearly 
every theory of ethics which has in its turn taken 
possession of the schools. Yet it is a remarkable 
proof of the essentially historical character of the 
conception that, after all the efforts which have been 
made to evolve the code of nature from the necessary 
characteristics of the natural state, so much of the 
result is just what it would have been if men had 
been satisfied to adopt the dicta of the Roman 
lawyers without questioning or reviewing them. 
Setting aside the Conventional or Treaty Law of 
Nations, it is surprising how large a part of the 
system is made up of pure Roman law. Wherever 
there is a doctrine of the jurisconsults affirmed by 
them to be harmony with the Jus Gentium, the 
publicists have found a reason for borrowing it, 
however plainly it may bear the marks of a distinc- 
tively Roman origin. We may observe too that the 
derivative theories are afflicted with the weakness 
of the primary notion. In the majority of the 
Publicists, the mode of thought is still "mixed." 
In studying these writers, the great difficulty is 



^ 



U8 UISTOUY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

always to discover whether they are discussing law 
or morality — whether the state of international re- 
lations they describe is actual or ideal — whether 
they lay down that which is, or that which, in their 
opinion, ought to be. 

The assumption that Natural Law is binding on 
states inter se is the next in rank of those which 
underlie International Law. A series of assertions or 
admissions of this principle may be traced up to the 
very infancy of modem juridical science, and at first 
sight it seems a direct inference from the teaching of 
the Romans. The civil condition of society being 
distinguished from the natural by the fact that in the 
first there is a distinct author of law, while in the 
last there is none, it appears as if the moment a 
number of units were acknowledged to obey no com- 
mon sovereign or political superior they were thrown 
back on the ulterior behests of the Law Natural. 
States are such units ; the hypothesis of their inde- 
pendence excludes the notion of a common lawgiver, 
and draws with it, therefore, according to a certain 
range of ideas, the notion of subjection to the primeval 
order of nature. The alternative is to consider in- 
dependent communities as not related to each other 
by any law, but this condition of lawlessness is ex- 
actly the vacuum which the Nature of the juris- 
consults abhorred. There is certainly apparent reason 
for ^hinking that if the mind of a Koman lawyer 



CHAP. IV. INTERNATIONAL LAW. m 

rested on any sphere from which civil law was 
banished, it would instantly fill the void with the 
ordinances of Nature. It is never safe, however, to 
assume that conclusions, however certain and im- 
mediate in our own eyes, were actually drawn at 
any period of history. No passage has ever been ad- 
duced from the remains of Roman law which, in my 
judgment, proves the jurisconsults to have believed 
natural law to have obligatory force between inde- 
pendent commonwealths ; and we cannot but see that 
to citizens of the Roman empire, who regarded their 
sovereign's dominions as conterminous with civili- 
sation, the equal subjection of states to the Law of 
Nature, if contemplated at all, must have seemed at 
most an extreme result of curious speculation. The 
truth appears to be that modem International Law, 
undoubted as is its descent from Roman law, is only 
connected with it by an irregular filiation. The early 
modern interpreters of the jurisprudence of Rome, 
misconceiving the meaning of Jus Gentium, assumed 
without hesitation that the Romans had bequeathed* 
to them a system of rules for the adjustment of 
international transactions. This " Law of Nations " 
was at first an authority which had formidable com- 
petitors to strive with, and the condition of Europe 
was^long such as to preclude its universal reception. 
Gradually, however, the western world arranged itself 
in a form more favourable to the theory of the 

H 2 



100 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. ir. 

civilians; circumstances destroyed the credit of rival 
doctrines; and at last, at a peculiarly felicitous con- 
juncture, Ayala and Grotius were able to obtain for it 
the enthusiastic assent of Europe, an assent which has 
been over and over again renewed in every variety of 
solemn engagement. The great men to whom its 
triumph is chiefly owing attempted, it need scarcely be 
said, to place it pn an entirely new basis, and it is un- 
questionable that in the course of this displacement 
they altered much of its structure, though far less 
of it than is commonly supposed. Having adopted 
from the Antonine jurisconsults the position that the 
Jus Gentium and the Jus Naturae were identical, 
Grotius, with his immediate predecessors and his im- 
mediate successors, attributed to the Law of Nature 
an authority which would never perhaps have been 
claimed for it, if " Law of Nations " had not in that 
age been an ambiguous expression. They laid down 
unreservedly that Natural^aw is the code of states, 
and thus put in operation a process which has con- 
tinued almost down to our own day, the process of 
engrafting on the international system rules which 
are supposed to have been evolved from the un- 
assisted contemplation of the conception of Nature. 
There is too one consequence of immense practical 
importance to mankind which, though not unknown 
during the early modem history of Europe, was 
never clearly or universally acknowledged till the 
doctrines of the Grotian school had prevailed. If 



CHAP. IV. INTERNATIONAL LAW. 101 

the society of nations is governed by Natural Law, 
the atoms which compose it must be absolutely equal. 
Men under the sceptre of Nature are all equal, and 
accordingly commonwealths are equal if the inter- 
national state be one of nature. The proposition 
that independent communities, however different in 
size and power, are all equal in the view of the law 
of nations, has largely contributed to the happiness 
of mankind, though it is constantly threatened by 
the political tendencies of each successive age. It 
is a doctrine which probably would never have 
obtained a secure footing at all if International Law 
had not been entirely derived from the majestic 
claims of Nature by the Publicists who wrote after 
the revival of letters. 

On the whole, however, it is astonishing, as I have 
observed before, how small a proportion the additions 
made to International Law since Grotius's day bear to 
the ingredients which have been simply taken from 
the most ancient stratum of the Roman Jus Gentium. 
Acquisition of territory has always been the great 
spur of national ambition, and the rules which govern 
this acquisition, together with the rules which mode- 
rate the wars in which it too frequently results, are 
merely transcribed from the part of the Roman law 
which treats of the modes of acquiring property ^t^r^ 
gentium. These modes of acquisition were obtained 
by the elder jurisconsults, as I have attempted to 

u 3 



102 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. ly. 

explain, by abstracting a common ingredient from 
the usages observed to prevail among the various 
tribes surrounding Rome ; and, having been classed 
on account of their origin in the " law common to 
all nations," they were thought by the later lawyers 
to fit in, on the score of their simplicity, with the 
more recent conception of a Law Natural. They thus 
made their way into the modern Law of Nations, and 
the result is that those parts of the international 
system which refer to dominion^ its nature, its limi- 
tations, the modes of acquiring and securing it, are 
pure Roman Property Law — so much, that is to say, 
of the Roman Law of Property as the Antonine juris- 
consults imagined to exhibit a certain congruity with 
the natural state. In order that these chapters of 
International Law may be capable of application, it is 
necessary that sovereigns should be related to each 
other like the members of a group of Roman pro- 
prietors. This is another of the postulates which lie 
at the threshold of the International Code, and it is 
also one which could not possibly have been sub- 
scribed to during the first centuries of modem 
European history. It is resolvable into the double 
proposition that " sovereignty is territorial," i. e. that 
it is always associated with the proprietorship of a 
limited portion of the earth's surface, and that "sove- 
reigns inter se are to be deemed not paramount^ but 
absolute^ o^vners of the state's territory." 



CHAP. IV. INTERN ATIONAL LAW. 103 

Many contemporary writers on International Law 
tacitly assume that the doctrines of iheir system, 
founded on principles of equity and common sense, 
were capable of being readily reasoned out in every 
stage of modem civilisation. But this assumption, 
while it conceals some real defects of the inter- 
national theory, is altogether untenable so far as 
regards a large part of modem history. It is not 
true that the authority of the Jus Gentium in the 
concerns of nations was always uncontradicted ; on 
the contrary, it had to struggle long against the 
claims of several competing systems. It is again 
not true that the territorial character of sovereignty 
was always recognised, for long after the dissolution 
of the Roman dominion the minds of men were 
under the empire of ideas irreconcileable with such 
a conception. An old order of things, and of views 
founded on it, had to decay — a new Europe, and 
an apparatus of new notions congenial to it, had to 
spring up — before two of the chiefest postulates of 
International Law could be universally conceded. 

It is a consideration well worthy to be kept in 
view, that during a large part of what we usually 
term modem history no such conception was enter- 
tained as that of " territorial sovereignty.^^ Sove- 
reignty was not associated with dominion over a 
portion or subdivision of the earth. The world had 
lain for so many centuries under the shadow of 

H 4 



104 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. it. 

Imperial liome as to have forgotten that distribu- 
tion of the vast spaces comprised in the empire 
which had once parcelled them out into a number of 
independent commonwealths, claiming immunity from 
extrinsic interference, and pretending to equality of 
national rights. After the subsidence of the bar- 
barian irruptions, the notion of sovereignty that 
prevailed seems to have been twofold. On the one 
hand it assumed the form of what may be called 
" fnJ^-sovereignty." The Franks, the Burgundians, 
the Vandals, the Lombards, and Visigoths were 
masters, of course, of the territories which they 
occupied, and to which some of them have given a 
geographical appellation; but they based no claim 
of right upon the fact of territorial possession, and 
indeed attached no importance to it whatever. They 
appear to have retained the traditions which they 
brought with them from the forest and the steppe, 
and to have still been in- their own view a patriarchal 
society, a nomad horde, merely encamped for the time 
upon the soil which afforded them sustenance. Part 
of Transalpine Gaul, with part of Germany, had now 
become the country de facto occupied by the Franks 
— it was France; but the Merovingian line of chief- 
tains, the descendants of Clovis, were not Kings of 
France, they were Kings of the Franks. The alter- 
native to this peculiar notion of sovereignty appears 
to have been — and this is the important point — the 



CHAP. IV. TERRITORIAL SOVEREIGNTY. 105 

idea of universal dominion. The moment a monarch 
departed from the special relation of chief to clans- 
men, and became solicitous, for purposes of his own, 
to invest himself with a novel form of sovereignty, 
the only precedent which suggested itself for his 
adoption was the domination of the Emperors of 
Rome. To parody a common quotation, he became 
" aut Ccesar aut nuUus.^^ Either he pretended to 
the full prerogative of the Byzantine Emperor, or 
he had no political status whatever. In our own age, 
when a new dynasty is desirous of obliterating the 
prescriptive title of a deposed line of sovereigns, it 
takes its designation from the people^ instead of the 
territory. Thus we have Emperors and Kings of the 
French, and a King of the Belgians. At the period 
of which we have been speaking, under similar cir- 
cumstances, a different alternative presented itself. 
The Chieftain who would no longer call himself King 
of the tribe must claim to be Emperor of the world. 
Thus, when the hereditary Mayors of the Palace had 
ceased to compromise with the monarchs they had 
long since virtually dethroned, they soon became 
unwilling to call themselves Kings of the Franks, a 
title which belonged to the displaced Merovings; but 
they could not style themselves Kings of France, for 
such a designation, though apparently not unknown, 
was not a title of dignity. Accordingly they came 
forward as aspirants to universal empire. Their 



106 HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

motive has been greatly misappreheDded. It has 
been taken for granted by recent French writers that 
Charlemagne was far before his age, quite as much 
in the character of his designs as in the energy 
with which he prosecuted them. Whether it be true 
or not that anybody is at any time before his age, it 
is certainly true that Charlemagne, in aiming at an 
unlimited dominion, was emphatically taking the only 
course which the characteristic ideas of his age per- 
mitted him to follow. Of his intellectual eminence 
there cannot be a question, but it is proved by his 
acts and not by his theory. 

These singularities of view were not altered on the 
partition of the inheritance of Charlemagne among 
his three grandsons. Charles the Bald, Lewis, and 
Lothair were still theoretically — if it be proper to 
use the word — Emperors of Rome. Just as the 
CsBsars of the Eastern and Western Empires had each 
been de jure emperor of the whole world, with de 
facto control over half of it, so the three Carlovin- 
gians appearto have considered their power as limited, 
but their title as unqualified. The same speculative 
universality of sovereignty continued to be associated 
with the Imperial throne after the second division on 
the death of Charles the Fat, and, indeed, was never 
thoroughly dissociated from it so long as the empire 
of Germany lasted. Territorial sovereignty — the 
view which connects sovereignty with the possession 



CHAF. IT. TERRITORIAL SOVEREIGNTY. 107 

of a limited portion of the earth's surface — was dis- 
tinctly an offshoot, though a tardy one, oi feudalism. 
This might have been expected h priori^ for it was 
feudalism which for the first time linked personal 
duties, and by consequence personal rights, to the 
ownership of land. Whatever be the proper view of 
its origin and legal nature, the best mode of vividly 
picturing to ourselves the feudal organisation is to 
begin with the basis, to consider the relation of the 
tenant to the patch of soil which created and limited 
his services — and then to mount up, through narrow- 
ing circles of super-feudation, till we approximate to 
the apex of the system. Where that summit exactly 
was during the later portion of the dark ages it is not 
easy to decide. Probably, wherever the conception 
of tribe sovereignty had really decayed, the topmost 
point was always assigned to the supposed successor 
of the Caesars of the West. But before long, when the 
actual sphere of Imperial authority had immensely 
contracted, and when the emperors had concentrated 
the scanty remains of their power upon Germany and 
North Italy, the highest feudal superiors in all the 
outlying portions of the former Carlovingian empire 
found themselves practically without a supreme head. 
Gradually they habituated themselves to the new 
situation, and the fact of immunity put at last out of 
sight the theory of dependence ; but there are many 
sjmiptoms that this change was not quite easily ac- 



108 HISTORY OF LAW OP NATURE. chap, iit 

complished; and, indeed, to the impression that in the 
nature of things there must necessarily be a cuhni- 
nating domination somewhere, we may, no doubt, 
refer the increasing tendency to attribute secular 
superiority to the See of Rome. The completion of 
the first stage in the revolution of opinion is marked, 
of course, by the accession of the Capetian dynasty in 
France. When the feudal prince of a limited territory 
surrounding Paris began, from the accident of his 
uniting an unusual number of suzerainties in his own 
person, to call himself King of France^ he became king 
in quite a new sense, a sovereign standing in the same 
relation to the soil of France as the baron to his estate, 
the tenant to his freehold. The precedent, however, 
was as influential as it was novel, and the form of the 
monarchy in France had visible effects in hastening 
changes which were elsewhere proceeding in the same 
direction. The kingship of our Anglo-Saxon regal 
houses was midway between the chieftainship of a 
tribe and a territorial supremacy; but the superiority 
of the Norman raonarchs, imitated from that of the 
King of France, was distinctly a territorial sovereignty. 
Every subsequent dominion which was established or 
consolidated was formed on the later model. Spain, 
Naples, and the principalities founded on the ruins 
of municipal freedom in Italy, were all under rulers 
whose sovereignty was territorial. Few things, I 
may add, are more curious than the gradual lapse of 



CHAP. IV. INTERNATIONAL LAW. 109 

the Venetians from one view to the other. At the 
commencement of its foreign conquests, the republic 
regarded itself as an antitype of the Roman common- 
wealth, governing a number of subject provinces. 
Move a century onwards, and you find that it wishes 
to be looked upon as a corporate sovereign, claiming 
the rights of a feudal suzerain over its possessions in 
Italy and the -^gean. 

During the period through which the popular ideas 
on the subject of sovereignty were undergoing this 
remarkable change, the system which stood in the 
place of what we now call International Law, was 
heterogeneous in form and inconsistent in the prin- 
ciples to which it appealed. Over so much of Europe 
as was comprised in the Romano-German empire, the 
connection of the confederate states was regulated by 
the complex and as yet incomplete mechanism of the 
Imperial constitution ; and, surprising as it may seem 
to us, it was a favourite notion of German lawyers 
that the relations of commonwealths, whether inside 
or outside the empire, ought to be regulated not by 
the Jus Gentium^ but by the pure Roman jurispru- 
dence, of which Caesar was still the centre. This 
doctrine was less confidently repudiated in the out- 
lying countries than we might have supposed antece- 
dently ; but substantially, through the rest of Europe 
feudal subordinations furnished a substitute for a 
public law; and when those were undetermined or 



no HISTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iv. 

ambiguous, there lay behind, in theory at least, a 
supreme regulating force in the authority of the head 
of the Church. It is certain, however, that both 
feudal and ecclesiastical influences were rapidly de- 
caying during the fifteenth, and even the fourteenth 
century; and if we closely examine the current pre- 
texts of wars, and the avowed motives of alliances, 
it will be seen that, step by step with the displace- 
ment of the old principles, the views afterwards har- 
monised and consolidated by Ayala and Grotius were 
making considerable progress, though it was silent 
anci^but slow. Whether the fusion of all the sources 
of authority would ultimately have evolved a system 
of international relations, and whether that system 
would have exhibited material differences froBi the 
fabric of Grotius, is not now possible to decide, for as 
a matter of fact the Reformation annihilated all its 
potential elements except one. Beginning in Ger- 
many, it divided the princes of the empire by a 
gulf too broad to be bridged over by the Imperial 
supremacy, even if the Imperial superior had stood 
neutral. He, however, was forced to take colour 
with the church against the refolTners; the Pope was, 
as a matter of course, in the same predicament; and 
thus the two authorities to whom belonged the office 
of mediation between combatants became themselves 
the chiefs of one great faction in the schism of the 
nations. Feudalism, already enfeebled and discredited 



CHAP. IV. GROTIUS. Ill 

as a principle of public relations, furnished no bond 
whatever which was stable enough to countervail the 
alliances of religion. In a condition, therefore, of 
public law which was little less than chaotic, those 
views of a state system to which the Roman juriscon- 
sults were supposed to have given their sanction 
alone remained standing. The shape, the symmetry, 
and the prominence which they assumed in the hands 
of Grotius are known to every educated man ; but the 
great marvel of the Treatise " De Jure Belli et 
Pacis," was its rapid, complete, and universal success. 
The horrors of the Thirty Years' War, the boundless 
terror and pity which the unbridled license of the 
soldiery was exciting, must, no doubt, be taken to 
explaift. that success in some measure, but they do 
not wholly account for it. Very little penetration 
into the ideas of that age is required to convince one 
that, if the ground plan of the international edifice 
which was sketched in the great book of Grotius had 
not appeared to be theoretically perfect, it would have 
been discarded by jurists and neglected by statesmen 
and soldiers. 

It is obvious that the speculative perfection of the 
Grotian system is intimately connected with that 
conception of territorial sovereignty which we have 
been discussing. The theory of International Law 
assumes that commonwealths are, relatively to each 
other, in a state of nature ; but the component atoms 



112 IflSTORY OF LAW OF NATURE. chap. iir. 

of a natural society must, by the fundamental as- 
sumption, be insulated and independent of each 
other. If there be a higher power connecting them, 
however slightly and occasionally, by the claim of 
common supremacy, the very conception of a com- 
mon superior introduces the notion of positive law, 
and excludes the idea of a law natural. It follows, 
therefore, that if the universal suzerainty of an 
Imperial head had been admitted even in bare theory, 
the labours of Grotius would have been idle. Nor 
is this the only point of junction between modem 
public law and those views of sovereignty of which 
I have endeavoured to describe the development. I 
have said that there are entire departments of inter- 
national jurisprudence which consist of the Roman 
Law of Property. What then is the inference? It 
is, that if there had been no such change as I have 
described in the estimate of sovereignty — if sove- 
reignty had not been associated with the proprietor- 
ship of a limited portion of the earth, had not, in 
other words, become territorial — three parts of the 
Grotian theory would have been incapable of appli- 
cation. 



CHAP. T. rRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. 113 



CHAP. V. 
PEmiTIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. 

The necessity of submitting the subject of jurispru- 
dence to scientific treatment has never been entirely 
lost sight of in modern times, and the essays which 
the consciousness of this, necessity has produced 
have proceeded from minds of very various calibre^ 
but there is not much presumption, I think, in as- 
serting that what has hitherto stood in the place of 
a science has for the most part been a set of guesses, 
those very guesses of the Roman lawyers which were 
examined in the two preceding chapters. A series 
of explicit statements, recognising and adopting 
these conjectural theories of a natural state, and of a 
system of principles congenial to it, has been con- 
tinued with but brief interruption from the days of 
their inventors to our own. They appear in the 
annotations of the Glossators who founded modem 
jurisprudence, and in the writings of the scholastic 
jurists who succeeded them. They are visible in 
the dogmas of the canonists. They are thrust into 
prominence by those civilians of marvellous erudi- 
tion, who flourished at the revival of ancient letters. 

I 



114 PRIMITIVB SOaETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

Grotins and his successors invested them not less 
with brilliancy and plausibility than with practical 
importance. They may be read in the introductory 
chapters of our own Blackstone, who has transcribed 
them textually from Burlamaqui, and wherever the 
manuals published in the present day for the guid- 
ance of the student or the practitioner begin with 
any discussion of the first principles of law, it 
always resolves itself into a restatement of the ^ 
Roman hypothesis. It is however from the disguises 
with which these conjectures sometimes clothe them- 
selves, quite as much as from their native form, that 
we gain an adequate idea of the subtlety with -which 
they mix themselves in human thought. The Lockeian 
theory of the origin of Law in a Social Compact 
scarcely conceals its Roman derivation, and indeed is 
only the dress by which the ancient views were ren- 
dered more attractive to a particular generation of 
the modems ; but on the other hand the theory of 
Hobbes on the same subject was purposely devised 
to repudiate the reality of a law of nature as con- 
ceived by the Romans and their disciples. Yet 
these two theories, which long divided the reflecting 
politicians of England into hostUe camps, resemble 
each other strictly in their fundamental assumption 
of a non-historic, unverifiable, condition of the race. 
Their authors differed as to the characteristics of the 
prae-social state, and as to the nature of the abnormal 



CHAF. V. MONTESQUIEU. 115 

action by which men lifted themselves out of it into 
that social organisation with which alone we are 
acquainted, but they agreed in thinking that a great 
chasm separated man in his primitive condition from 
man in society, and this notion we cannot doubt that 
they borrowed, consciously or unconsciously, from the 
Romans. If indeed the phenomena of law be re- 
garded in the way in which these theorists regarded 
them — that is, as one vast complex whole — it is not 
surprising that the mind should often evade the task 
it has set to itself by falling back on some ingenious 
conjecture which (plausibly interpreted) will seem 
to reconcile everything, or else thai it should some- 
times abjure in despair the labour of systematization. 
From the theories of jurisprudence which have 
the same speculative basis as the Roman doctrine 
two of much celebrity must be excepted. The first 
of them is that associated with the great name of 
Montesquieu. Though there are some ambiguous 
expressions in the early part of the Esprit des Loisj 
which seem to show its writer's unwiUingness to 
break quite openly with the views hitherto popular, 
the general drift of the book is certainly to indicate 
a very difierent conception of its subject from any 
which had been entertained before. It has often 
been noticed that, amidst the vast variety of ex- 
amples which, in its immense width of survey, it 
sweeps together from supposed systems of juris- 

I 2 



116 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chaf. v. 

prudence, there is an evident anxiety to thrust 
into especial prominence those manners and institu- 
tions which astonish the civilised reader by their 
uncouthness, strangeness, or indecency. The in- 
ference constantly suggested is, that laws are the 
creatures of climate, local situation, accident, or im- 
posture — the fruit of any causes except those which 
appear to operate with tolerable constancy. Mon- 
tesquieu seems, in fact, to have looked on the nature 
of man as entirely plastic, as passively reproducing the 
impressions, and submitting implicitly to the impulses, 
which it receives from without. And here no doubt 
lies the error which vitiates his system as a system. 
He greatly underrates the stability of human nature- 
He pays little or no regard to the inherited qualities 
of the race, those qualities which each generation 
receives from its predecessors, and transmits but 
slightly altered to the generation which follows it. 
It is quite true, indeed, that no complete account can 
be given of social phenomena, and consequently of 
laws, till due allowance has been made for those 
modifying causes which are noticed in the Esprit des 
Lois; but their number and their force appear to 
have been overestimated by Montesquieu. Many 
of the anomalies which he parades have since been 
shown to rest on false report or erroneous construc- 
tion, and of those which remain not a few prove the 
permanence rather than the variableness of man's 



CHAP. Y. MONTESQUIEU AND BENTHAM, 117 

nature, since they are reKcs of older stages of the 
race which have obstinately defied the influences 
that have elsewhere had efiect. The truth is that 
the stable part of our mental, moral, and physical 
constitution is the largest part of it, and the resist- 
ance it opposes to change is such that, though the 
variations of human society in a portion of the world 
are plain enough, they are neither so rapid nor so 
extensive that their amount, character, and general 
direction cannot be ascertained. An approximation 
to truth may be all that is attainable with our 
present knowledge, but there is no ireason for think- 
ing that is so remote, or (what is the same thing) 
that it requires so much future correction, as to be 
entirely useless and uninstructive. 

The other theory which has been adverted to is, 
the historical theory of Bentham. This theory 
which is obscurely (and, it might even be said, ti- 
midly) propounded in several parts of Bentham's 
works is quite distinct from that analysis of the con- 
ception of law which he commenced in the "Fragment 
on Government," and which was more recently com- 
pleted by Mr. John Austin. The resolution of a 
law into a command of a particular nature, imposed 
under special conditions, does not afiect to do more 
than protect us against a difficulty -»- a most formi- 
dable one certainly — of language. The whole ques- 
tion remains open as to the motives of societies in 

I 3 



118 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap, v- 

imposing these commands on themselves, as to the 
connexion of these commands with each other, and 
the nature of their dependence on those which pre- 
ceded them, and which they have superseded. Ben- 
tham suggests the answer that societies modify, and 
have always modified, their laws according to modi- 
fications of their views of general expediency. It is 
difficult to say that this proposition is false, but it 
certainly appears to be unfruitfiil. For that which 
seems expedient to a society, or rather to the go- 
verning part of it, when it alters a rule of law is 
surely the same thing as the object, whatever it may 
be, which it has in view when it makes the change. 
Expediency and the greatest good are nothing more 
than different names for the impulse which prompts 
the modification ; and when we lay down expediency 
as the rule of change in law or opinion, all we get 
by the proposition is the substitution of an express 
term for a term which is necessarily implied when 
we say that a change takes place. 

There is such wide-spread dissatisfaction with 
existing theories of jurisprudence, and so general a 
conviction that they do not really solve the questions 
they pretend to dispose of, as to justify the suspicion 
that some line of inquiry, necessary to a perfect 
result, has been incompletely followed or altogether 
omitted by their authors. And indeed there is one 
remarkable omission with which all these specula- 



cHAP.v. PROPER MODE OF INQUmY. 119 

tions are chargeable, except perhaps those of Mon- 
tesquieu. They take no account of what law has 
actually been at epochs remote from the particular 
period at which they made their appearance. Their 
originators carefully observed the institutions of their 
own age and civilisation, and those of other ages and 
civilisations with which they had some degree of 
intellectual sympathy, but, when they turned their 
attention to archaic states of society which exhibited 
much superficial difference from their own, they uni- 
formly ceased to observe and began guessing. The 
mistake which they committed is therefore analogous 
to the error of one who, in investigating the laws of 
the material universe, should commence by contem- 
plating the existing physical world as a whole, in- 
stead of beginning with the particles which are its 
simplest ingredients. One does not certainly see 
why such a scientific solecism should be more de- 
fensible in jurisprudence than in any other region of 
thought. It would seem antecedently that we ought 
to commence with the simplest social forms in a 
state as near as possible to their rudimentary condi^ 
tion. In other words, if we followed the course 
usual in such inquiries, we should penetrate as far 
up as we could in the history of primitive societies. 
The phenomena which early societies present us with 
are not easy at first to understand, but the difficulty 
of grappling with them bears no proportion to the 

I 4 



120 PRIMITIVE SOCIETr AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

perplexities which beset us in considering the baffling 
entanglement of modem social organisation. It is a 
difficulty arising from their strangeness and un- 
couthness, not from their number and complexity. 
One does not readily get over the surprise which 
they occasion when looked at from a modem point 
of view; but when that is surmounted they are fqw 
enough and simple enough. But, even if they gave 
more trouble than they do, no pains would be wasted 
in ascertaining the germs out of which has assuredly 
been unfolded every form of moral restraint which 
controls our actions and shapes our conduct at the 
present moment. 

The rudiments of the social state, so far as they are 
known to us at all, are known through testimony of 
three sorts — accounts by contemporary observers of 
civilisations less advanced than their own, the records 
which particular races have preserved concerning 
their primitive history, and ancient law. The first 
kind of evidence is the best we could have expected. 
As societies do not advance concurrently, but at dif- 
ferent rates of progress, there have been epochs at 
which men trained to habits of methodical observa- 
tion have really been in a position to watch and de- 
scribe the infancy of mankind. Tacitus made the most 
of such an opportunity; but the Germany^ unlike 
most celebrated classical books, has not induced others 
to follow the excellent example set by its author, and 



CHAP. V. THE GERMANY OF TACITUS. 121 

the amount of this sort of testimony which we pos- 
sess is exceedingly small. The lofty contempt which 
a civilised people entertains for barbarous neighbours 
has caused a remarkable negligence in observing 
them, and this jcarelessness has been aggravated at 
times by fear, by religious prejudice, and even by 
the use of these very terms — civilisation and bar- 
barism — which convey to most persons the impres- 
sion of a difference not merely in degree but in kind. 
Even the Germany has been suspected by some 
critics of sacrificing fidelity to poignancy of contrast 
and picturesqueness of narrative. Other histories 
too, which have been handed down to us among the 
archives of the people to whose infancy they relate, 
have been thought distorted by the pride of race or 
by the religious sentiment of a newer age. It is 
important then to observe that these suspicions, whe- 
ther groundless or rational, do not attach io a great 
deal of archaic law. Much of the old law which has 
descended to us was preserved merely because it was 
old. Those who practised and obeyed it did not 
pretend to understand it; and in some cases they 
even ridiculed and despised it. They offered no 
account of it except that it had come down to them 
from their ancestors. If we confine our attention, 
then, to those fragments of ancient institutions which 
cannot reasonably be supposed to have been tampered 
Avith, we are able to gain a clear conception of certain 



122 PRIMITIVE SOdETT AND AITCIENT LAW. chap v- 

great characteristics of the society to which they 
originally belonged. Advancing a step further, we 
can apply our knowledge to systems of law which, 
like the Code of Menu, are as a whole of suspicious 
authenticity; and, using the key we have obtained, 
we are in a position to discriminate those portions of 
them which are truly archaic from those which have 
been affected by the prejudices, interests, or ignorance 
of the compUer. It will at least be acknowledged 
that, if the materials for this process are sufficient, 
and if the comparisons be accurately executed, the 
methods followed are as little objectionable as those 
which have led to such surprising results in compara- 
tive philology. 

The effect of the evidence derived from compara- 
tive jurisprudence is to establish that view of the 
primeval condition of the human race which is known 
as the Patriarchal Theory. There is no doubt, of 
course, that this theory was originally based on the 
Scriptural history of the Hebrew patriarchs in Lower 
Asia; but, as has been explained already, its con- 
nexion with Scripture rather militated than other- 
wise against Its reception as a complete theory, since 
the majority of the inquirers who till recently ad- 
dressed themselves with most earnestness to the colli- 
gation of social phenomena, were either influenced 
by the strongest prejudice against Hebrew antiquities 
or by the strongest desire to construct their system 



CHAP. V. SCRIPTURAL ACCOUNTS. 123 

without the assistance of religious records. Even now 
there is perhaps a disposition to undervalue these 
accounts, or rather to decline generalising from them, 
as forming part of the traditions of a Semitic people. 
It is to be noted, however, that the legal testimony 
comes nearly exclusively from the institutions of 
societies belonging to the Indo-European stock, the 
Romans, Hindoos, and Sclavonians supplying the 
greater part of it; and indeed the difficulty, at the 
present stage of the inquiry, is to know where to 
stop, to say of what races of men it is not allowable 
to lay down that the society in which they are united 
was originally organised on the patriarchal model. 
The chief lineaments of such a society, as collected 
from the early chapters in Genesis, I need not attempt 
to depict with any minuteness, both because they are 
familiar to most of us from our earliest childhood, 
and because, from the interest once attaching to the 
controversy which takes it name from the debate 
between Locke and Filmer, they fill a whole chapter, 
thought not a very profitable one, in English litera- 
ture. The points which lie on the surface of the 
history are these: — The eldest male parent — the 
eldest ascendant — is absolutely supreme in his house- 
hold. His dominion extends to life and death, and 
is as unqualified over his children and their houses as 
over his slaves; indeed the relations of sonship and 
serfdom appear to differ in little beyond the higher 




124 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

capacity which the child in blood possesses of be- 
coming one day the head of a family himself. The 
flocks and herds of the children are the flocks and 
herds of the father, and the possessions of the parent, 
which he holds in a representative rather than in 
a proprietary character, are equally divided at his 
death among his descendants in the first degree, the 
eldest son sometimes receiving a double share under 
the name of birthright, but more generally endowed 
with no hereditary advantage beyond an honorary 
precedence. A less obvious inference from the Scrip- 
tural accounts is that they seem to plant us on the 
traces of the breach which is first efifected in the 
empire of the parent. The families of Jacob and 
Esau separate and form two nations; but the families 
of Jacob's children hold together and become a people. 
This looks like the immature germ of a state or com- 
monwealth, and of an order of rights superior to the 
claims of family relation. 

If I were attempting for the more special purposes 
of the jurist to express compendiously the charac- 
teristics of the situation in which mankind disclose 
themselves at the dawn of their history, I should be 
satisfied to quote a few verses from the Odysaee of 
Homer : 

Toiaiv b* ovT dyopai fiovKrifpopoi owrc difntrriQ, 
. Otfii(rTevt.i be £i:aerroc 

iralbwy ijb* dXoxiavy oW AXX^Xuv aXiyovfny. 



CHAP. y. PRIMITIVE SOCIETY* 125 

" They have neither assemblies for consultation nor 
ihemistes^ but every one exercises jurisdiction over 
his wives and his children, and they pay no regard to 
one another." These lines are applied to the Cyclops, 
and it may not perhaps be an altogether fanciful 
idea when I suggest that the Cyclops is Homer's 
type of an alien and less advanced civilisation; for 
the almost physical loathing which a primitive com- 
munity feels for men of widely different manners 
from its own usually expresses itself by describing 
them as monsters, such as giants, or even (which is 
almost always the case in Oriental mythology) as 
demons. However that may be, the verses condense 
in themselves the sum of the hints which are given 
us by legal antiquities. Men are first seen distributed 
in perfectly insulated groups, held together by obe- 
dience to the parent. Law is the parent's word, but 
it is hot yet in the condition of those themistes which 
^were analysed in the first chapter of this work. 
When we go forward to the state of society in which 
these early legal conceptions show themselves as 
formed, we find that they still partake of the mystery 
and spontaneity which must have seemed to charac- 
terise a despotic father's commands, but that at the 
same time, inasmuch as they proceed from a sovereign, 
they presuppose a union of family groups in some 
wider organisation. The next question is, what is the 
nature of this union and the degree of intimacy which 



126 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

it involves. It is just here that archaic law renders 
us one of the greatest of its services and fills up a gap 
which otherwise could only have been bridged by con- 
jecture. It is full, in aU its provinces, of the clearest 
indications that society in primitive times was not 
what it is assumed to be at present, a collection of 
individuals. In fact, and in the view of the men 
who composed it, it was an aggregation of families. 
The contrast may be most forcibly expressed by 
saying that the unit of an ancient society was the Fa- 
mily, of a modem society the Individual. We must 
be prepared to find in ancient law all the conse- 
quences of this difference. It is so framed as to be 
adjusted to a system of smaU independent corpo- 
rations. .It is therefore scanty, because it is sup- 
plemented by the despotic commands of the heads of 
households. It is ceremonious, because the transac- 
tions to which it pays regard resemble international 
concerns much more than the quick play of inter-* 
course between individuals. Above all it has a pecu- 
liarity of which the full importance canQot be shown 
at present. It takes a view of life wholly unlike any 
which appears in developed jurisprudence. Corpo- 
rations never die^ and accordingly primitive law 
considers the entities with which it deals, i.e. the 
patriarchal or family groups, as perpetual and inex- 
tinguishable. This view is closely allied to the pecu- 
liar aspect under which, in very ancient times, moral 



CHAP. V. EARLY MORAL DOCTRINES. 127 

attributes present themsdves. The moral elevation 
and moral debasement of the individual appear to be 
confounded with, or postponed to, the merits and 
offences of the group to which the individual belongs. 
If the community sins, its guilt is much more than 
the sum of the offences committed by its members; 
the crime is a corporate act, and extends in its con- 
sequences to many more persons than have shared in 
its actual perpetration. If, on the other hand, the 
individual is conspicuously guilty, it is his children, 
his kinsfolk, his tribesmen, or his fellow-citizens, who 
suffer with him, and sometimes for him. It thus 
happens that the ideas of moral responsibility and 
retribution often seem to be more clearly realised at 
very ancient than at more advanced periods, for, as 
the family group is immortal, and its liability to 
punishment indefinite, the primitive mind is not per- 
plexed by the questions which become troublesome 
as soon as the individual is conceived as altogether 
separate from the group. One step in the transition 
from the ancient and simple view of the matter to the 
theological or metaphysical explanations of later days 
is marked by the early Greek notion of an inherited 
curse. The bequest received by his posterity from 
the original criminal was not a liability to punish- 
ment, but a liability to the commission of fresh 
offences which drew with them a condign retribution ; 
and thus the responsibility of the family was reconciled 



128 PRIMITIVE SOaETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

with the newer phase of thought which limited the 
consequences of crime to the person of the actual 
delinquent. 

It would be a very simple explanation of the origin 
of society if we could base a general conclusion on the 
hint furnished us by the Scriptural example already 
adverted to, and could suppose that communities be-, 
gan to exist wherever a family held together instead 
of separating at the death of its patriarchal chieftain. 
In most of the Greek states and in Rome there 
long remained the vestiges of an ascending series of 
groups out of which the State was at first constituted. 
The Family, House, and Tribe of the Romans may be 
taken as the type of them, and they are so described 
to us that we can scarcely help conceiving them as a 
system of concentric circles which have gradually 
expanded from the same point. The elementary 
group is the Family, connected by common subjection 
to the highest male ascendant. The aggregation of 
Families forms the Gens or House. The aggregation 
of Houses makes the Tribe. The aggregation of Tribes 
constitutes the Commonwealth. Are we at liberty to 
follow these indications, and to lay down that the 
commonwealth is a collection of persons united by 
common descent from the progenitor of an original 
family? Of this we may at least be certain, that all 
ancient societies regarded themselves as having pro- 
ceeded from one original stock, and even laboured 



CHAP. V. EATILY POLITICAL IDEAS. 129 , 

under an incapacity for comprehending any reason 
except this for their holding together in political 
union. The history of political ideas begins, in fact, 
with the assumption that kinship in blood is the sole 
possible ground of community in political functions ; 
nor is there any of those subversions of feeling, which 
we term emphatically revolutions, so startling and so 
complete as the change which is accomplished when 
some other principle — such as that, for instance, of 
local contiguity — establishes itself for the first time 
as the basis of common political action. It may be 
affirmed then of early commonwealths that their citi- 
zens considered all the groups in which they claimed 
membership to be founded on common lineage. 
What was obviously true of the Family was believed 
to be true first of the House, next of the Tribe, lastly 
of the State. And yet we find that along with this 
belief, or, if we may use the word, this theory, each 
community preserved records or traditions which 
distinctly showed that the fundamental assumption 
was false. Whether we look to the Greek states, or 
to Rome, or to the Teutonic aristocracies in Ditmarsh 
which ftimished Niebuhr with so many valuable 
illustrations, or to the Celtic clan associations, or to 
that strange social organisation of the Sclavonic 
Russians and Poles which has only lately attracted 
notice, everywhere we discover traces of passages in 
their history when men of alien descent were admit- 

K 



130 PRIMinVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

ted to, and amalgamated with, the original brother- 
hood* Adverting to Rome singly, we perceive that 
the primary group, the Family, was being constantly 
adulterated by the practice of adoption, while stories 
seem to have been always current respecting the 
exotic extraction of one of the original Tribes and 
concerning a large addition to the Houses made by 
one of the early kings. The composition of the state, 
uniformly assumed to be natural, was nevertheless 
known to be in great measure artificial. This con- 
flict between belief or theory and notorious fact is 
at first sight extremely perplexing ; but what it really 
illustrates is the efficiency with which Legal Fictions 
do their work in the infancy of society. The earliest 
and most extensively employed of legal fictions was 
that which permitted family relations to be created 
artificially, and there is none to which I conceive 
mankind to be more deeply indebted. If it had nev^r 
existed, I do not see how any one of the primitive 
groups, whatever were their nature, could have ab- 
sorbed another, or on what terms any two of them 
could have combined, except those of absolute superi- 
ority on one side and absolute subjection on the other. 
No doubt, when with our modem ideas we contem- 
plate the union of independent communities, we can 
suggest a hundred modes of carrying it out, the 
simplest of all being that the individuals comprised 
in the coalescing groups shall vote or act together 



CHAP. V. FICTION OF ADOPTION- 131 

according to local propinquity; but tke idea that a 
number of persons should exercise political rights in 
common simply because they happened to live within 
the same topographical limits was utterly strange and 
monstrous to primitive antiquity. The expedient 
which in those times commanded favour was that the 
incoming population should feign themselves to be 
descended from the same stock as the people on 
whom they were engrafted ; and it is precisely the 
good faith of this fiction, and the closeness with 
which it seemed to imitate reality, that we cannot 
now hope to understand. One circumstance, how- 
ever, which it is important to recollect, is that the 
men who formed the various political groups were 
certainly in the habit of meeting together periodically, 
for the purpose of acknowledging and consecrating 
their association by common sacrifices. Strangers 
amalgamated with the brotherhood were doubtless 
admitted to. these sacrifices; and when that was once 
done, we can believe that it seemed equally easy, or 
not more difficult, to conceive them as sharing in the 
common lineage. The conclusion then which is sug- 
gested by the evidence is, not that all early societies 
were formed by descent from the same ancestor, but 
that all of them which had any permanence and 
solidity either were so descended or assumed that they 
were. An indefinite number of causes may have 
shattered the primitive groups, but wherever their 



132 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

ingredients recombined, it was on the model or prin- 
ciple of an association of kindred. Whatever were the 
fact, all thought, language, and law adjusted them- 
selves to the assumption. But though all this seems 
to me to be established with reference to the commu- 
nities with whose records we are acquainted, the 
remainder of their history sustains the position before 
laid down as to the essentially transient and termi- 
nable influence of the most powerful Legal Fictions. 
At some point of time — probably as soon as they felt 
themselves strong enough to resist extrinsic pres- 
sure — all these states ceased to recruit themselves 
by factitious extensions of consanguinity. They ne- 
cessarily, therefore, became Aristocracies, in all cases 
where a fresh population from any cause collected 
around them which could put in no claim to commu- 
nity of origin. Their sternness in maintaining the 
central principle of a system under which political 
rights were attainable on no terms whatever except 
connexion in blood, real or artificial, taught their 
inferiors another principle, which proved to be en- 
dowed with a far higher measure of vitality. This 
was the principle of local contiguity^ now recognised 
everywhere -as the condition of community in poli* 
tical functions. A new set of political ideas came at 
once into existence, which, being those of ourselves, 
our contemporaries, and in great measure of our 
ancestors, rather obscure our perception of the older 
theory which they vanquished and dethroned. 



CHAP. V. THE ANCIENT FAMILY. 133 

The Family then is the type of an archaic society 
in all the modifications which it was capable of 
assuming; but the family here spoken of is not ex- 
actly the family as understood by a modem. In 
order to reach the ancient conception we must give 
to our modern ideas an important extension and an 
important limitation. We must look on the family 
as constantly enlarged by the absorption of strangers 
within its circle, and we must try to regard the 
fiction of adoption as so closely simulating the reality 
of kinship that neither law nor opinion makts the 
slightest difference between a real and an adoptive 
connexion. On the other hand, the persons theo- 
retically amalgamated into a family by their common 
descent are practically held together by common obe- 
dience to their highest living ascendant, the father, 
grandfather, or great-grandfather. The patriarchal 
authority of a chieftain is as necessary an ingredient 
in the notion of the family group as the fact (or as- 
sumed fact) of its having sprung from his loins; and 
hence we must understand that if there be any persons 
who, however truly included in the brotherhood by 
virtue of their blood-relationship, have nevertheless 
de facto withdrawn themselves from the empire of 
its ruler, they are always, in the beginnings of law, 
considered as lost to the family. It is this patriarchal 
aggregate — the modern family thus cut down on one 
side and extended on the other — which meets us on 

K 3 



134 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW, cuap. v. 

the threshold of primitive jurisprudence. Older pro- 
bably than the State, the Tribe, and the House, it left 
traces of itself on private law long after the House 
and the Tribe had been forgotten, and long after con- 
sanguinity had ceased to be associated with the com- 
position of States. It will be found to have stamped 
itself on aU the great departments of jurisprudence, 
and may be detected, I think, as the true source of 
many of their most important and most durable cha- 
racteristics. At the outset, the peculiarities of law 
in it« most ancient state lead us irresistibly to the 
conclusion that it took precisely the same view of the 
family group which is taken of individual men by the 
systems of rights and duties now prevalent through- 
out Europe. There are societies open to our observa- 
tion at this very moment whose laws and usages can 
scarcely be explained unless they are supposed never 
to have emerged from this primitive condition ; but 
in communities more fortunately circumstanced the 
fabric of jurisprudence fell gradually to pieces, and 
if we carefully observe the disintegration we shall 
perceive that it took place principally in those por- 
tions of each system which were most deeply affected 
by the primitive conception of the family. In one 
all-important instance, that of the Romaft law, the 
change was effected so slowly, that from epoch to 
epoch we can observe the line and direction which it 
followed, and can even give some idea of the ultimate 



CHAP. V. THE PATRIA POTESTAS. 135 

result to which it was tending. And, in pursuing 
this last inquiry, we need not suffer ourselves to be 
stopped by the imaginary barrier which separates the 
modem from the ancient world. For one effect of 
that mixture of refined Roman law with primitive 
barbaric usage, which is known to us by the deceptive 
name of feudalism, was to revive many features of 
archaic jurisprudence which had died out of the 
Roman world, so that the decomposition which had 
seemed to be over commenced again, and to some 
extent is stiU proceeding. 

On a few systems of law the family organisation of 
the earliest society has left a plain and broad mark in 
the life-long authority of the Father or other ancestor 
over the person and property of his descendants, an 
authority which we may conveniently caU by its later 
Roman name of Patria Potestas. No feature of the 
rudimentary associations of mankind is deposed to by 
a greater amount of evidence than this, and yet none 
seems to have disappeared so generally and so rapidly 
from the usages of advancing communities. Gains, 
writing under the Antonines, describes the insti- 
tution as distinctively Roman. It is true that, had 
he glanced across the Rhine or the Danube to those 
tribes of barbarians which were exciting the curiosity 
of some among his contemporaries, he would have seen 
examples of patriarchal power in its crudest form; 
and in the far East a branch of the same ethnical 

K 4 



136 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANQENT LAW. chap. v. 

stock fipom which the Romans sprang was repeating 
their Patria Potestas in some of its most technical 
incidents. But among the races understood to be 
comprised within the Roman empire, Gains could 
find none which exhibited an institution resembling 
the Roman " Power of the Father," except only the 
Asiatic Galatse. There are reasons, indeed, as it seems 
to me, why the direct authority of the ancestor should, 
in the greater number of progressive societies, very 
shortly assume humbler proportions than belonged to 
it in their earliest state. The unplicit obedience of 
rude men to their parent is doubtless a primary fact, 
which it would be absurd to explain away altogether by 
attributing to them any calculation of its advantages ; 
but, at the same time, if it is natural in the sons to 
obey the father, it is equally natural that they should 
look to him for superior strength or superior wisdom. 
Hence, when societies are placed under circumstances 
which cause an especial value to be attached to 
bodily and mental vigour, there is an influence at 
work which tends to confine the Patria Potestas to 
the cases where its possessor is actually skilful and 
strong. When we obtain our first glimpse of orga- 
nised Hellenic society, it seems as if supereminent 
wisdom would keep alive the father's power in per- 
sons whose bodily strength had decayed; but the 
relations of Ulysses and Laertes in the Odyssee appear 
to show that, where extraordinary valour and sagacity 



CHAP. V. THE PATRIA POTESTAS. 137 

were united in the son, the father in the decrepitude 
of age was deposed from the headship of the family. 
In the mature Greek jurisprudence, the rule advances 
a few steps on the practice hinted at in the Homeric 
literature; and though very mq,ny traces of stringent 
family obligation remain, the direct authority of the 
parent is limited, as in European codes, to the non- 
age or minority of the children, or, in other words, 
to the period during which their mental and physical 
inferiority may always be presumed. The Roman 
law, however, with its remarkable tendency to inno- 
vate on ancient usage only just so far as the exigency 
of the commonwealth may require, preserves both 
the primeval institution and the natural limitation to 
which I conceive it to have been subject. In every 
relation of life in which the collective community 
might have occasion to avail itself of his wisdom and 
strength, for all purposes of counsel or of war, the 
filius familias, or Son under Power, was as free as his- 
father. It was a maxim of Roman jurisprudence' 
that the Patria Potestas did not extend to the Jus 
Publicum. Father and son voted together in the 
city, and fought side by side in the field; indeed, the 
son, as general, might happen to command the father, 
or, as magistrate, decide on his contracts and punish 
his delinquencies. But in all the relations created by 
Private Law, the son lived under a domestic-despotism 
which, considering the severity it retained to the last, 



138 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

and the number of centuries through which it en- 
dured, constitutes one of the strangest problems in 
legal history. ^ 

The Patria Potestas of the Romans, which is neces- 
sarily our type of the primeval paternal authority, is 
equally difficult to understand as an institution of 
civilised life, whether we consider its incidence on the 
person or its effects on property. It is to be regretted 
that a chasm which exists in its history cannot be 
more completely filled. So far as regards the person, 
the parent, when our information commences, has 
over his children the jus vitce necisque^ the power of 
life and death, and a fortiori of uncontrolled corporal 
chastisement; he can modify their personal condition 
at pleasure ; he can give a wife to his son ; he can give 
his daughter in marriage ; he can divorce his children 
of .either sex; he can transfer them to another family 
by adoption ; and he can sell them. Late in the Im- 
perial period we find vestiges of all these powers, but 
they are reduced within very narrow limits. The 
unqualified right t)f domestic chastisement has become 
a right of bringing domestic offences under the cog- 
nisance of the civil magistrate; the privilege of dic- 
tating marriage has declined into a conditional veto; 
the liberty of selling has been virtually abolished, 
and adoption itself, destined to lose ahnbst all its 
ancient importance in the reformed system of Justi- 
nian, can no longer be effected without the assent of 



CHAP. V. THE PATRIA POTESTAS. 139 

the child transferred ta the adoptive parentage. In 
short, we are brought very close to the verge of the 
ideas which have at length prevailed in the modem 
world. But between these widely distant epochs 
there is an interval of obscurity, and we can only 
guess at the causes which permitted thePatriaPotestas 
to last as long as it did by rendering it more tolerable 
than it appears. The active discharge of ihe most 
important among the duties which the son owed to the 
state must have tempered the authority of his parent 
if they did not annul it. We can readily persuade 
ourselves that the paternal despotism could not be 
brought into play without great scandal against a 
man of full age occupying a high civil office. During 
the earlier history, however, such cases of practical 
emancipation would be rare compared with those 
which must have been created by the constant wars 
of the Roman republic. The military tribune and 
the private soldier who were in the field three quar- 
ters of a year during the earlier contests, at a later 
period the proconsul in charge of a province, and the 
legionaries who occupied it, cannot have had practical 
reason to regard themselves as the slaves of a despotic 
master; and all these avenues of escape tended con- 
stantly to multiply themselves. Victories led to 
conquests, conquests to occupations; the mode of 
occupation by colonies was exchanged for the system 
of occupying provinces by standing armies. Each 



140 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

step in advance was a call* for the expatriation of 
more Roman citizens and a fresh draft on the blood 
of the failing Latin race. We may infer, I think, 
that a strong sentiment in favour of the relaxation 
of the Patria Potestas had become fixed by the time 
that the pacification of the world commenced on 
the establishment of the Empire. The first serious 
blows at the ancient institution are attributed to the 
earlier Caesars, and some isolated interferences of 
Trajan and Hadrian seem to have prepared the 
ground for a series of express enactments which, 
though we cannot always determine their dates, we 
know to have limited the father's powers on the one 
hand, and on the other to have multiplied facilities 
for their voluntary surrender. The older mode of 
getting rid of the Potestas, by efi^ecting a triple sale 
of the son's person, is evidence, I may remark, of a 
veryearly feeling against the unnecessary prolongation 
^f the powers. The rule which declared that the son 
should be free after having been three times sold 
by his father seems to have been originally meant 
to entail penal consequences on a practice which 
revolted even the imperfect morality of the primitive 
Roman. But even before the publication of the Twelve 
Tables it had been turned, by the ingenuity of the 
jurisconsults, into an expedient for destroying the 
parental authority wherever the father desired that it 
should cease. 



cHAP.v. THE PATRIA POTESTAS. 141 

Many of the causes which helped to litigate the 
stringency of the father's power over the persons of 
his children are doubtless among those which do not 
lie upon the face of history. We cannot tell how 
far public opinion may have paralysed an authority 
which the law conferred, or how far natural affection 
may have rendered it endurable. But though the 
powers over the person may have been latterly 
nominal, the whole tenour of the extant Roman juris- 
prudence suggests that the father's rights over the 
son's property were always exercised without scruple 
to the full extent to which they were sanctioned by 
law. There is nothing to astonish us in the latitude 
of these rights when they first show themselves. 
The ancient law of Rome forbade the Children under 
Power to hold property apart from their parent, or 
(we should rather say) never contemplated the pos- 
sibility of their claiming a separate ownership. The 
father was entitled to take the whole of the son's 
acquisitions, and to enjoy the benefit of his contracts 
without being entangled in any compensating lia- 
bility. So much as this we should expect from the 
constitution of the earliest Roman society, for we 
can hardly form a notion of the primitive family 
group unless we suppose that its members brought 
their earnings of all kinds into the common stock 
while they were unable to bind it by improvident 
individual engagements. The true enigma of the 



142 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. cbap. v. 

Patria FollBtas does not reside here, but in the slow- 
ness with which these proprietary privileges of the 
parent were curtailed, and in the circumstance that, 
before they were seriously diminished, the whole 
civilised worid was brought within their sphere. No 
innovation of any kind was attempted till the first 
years of the Empire, when the acquisitions of soldiers 
on service were withdrawn from the operation of the 
Patria Potestas, doubtless as part of the reward of 
the armies which had overthrown the free common- 
wealth. Three centuries afterwards the same inunu- 
nity was extended to the earnings of persons who 
were in the civil employment of the state. Both 
changes were obviously limited in their application, 
and they were so contrived in technical form as 
to interfere as little as possible with the principle 
of Patria Potestas. A certain qualified and dependent 
ownership had always been recognised by the Roman 
law in the perquisites and savings which slaves and 
sons under power were not compelled to include in 
the household accounts, and the special name of this 
permissive property, Peculium, was applied to the 
acquisitions newly relieved from Patria Potestas, which 
were called in the case of soldiers Castrense Peculium, 
and Quasi-castrense Peculium in the case of civil ser- 
vants. Other modifications of the parental privileges 
followed, which showed a less studious outward 
respect for the ancient principle. Shortly after the 



CHAP. V. THE PATRIA POTESTAS. 143 

introduction of the Quasi-castrense Peculium, Con- 
stantine the Great took away the father's absolute 
control over property which his children had inherited 
from their mother, and reduced it to a usufruct^ or 
life-interest, A few more changes of slight import- 
ance followed in the Western Empire, but the furthest 
point reached was in the East, under Justinian, who 
enacted that unless the acquidtions of the child were 
derived from the parent's own property, the parent's 
rights over, them should not extend beyond enjoy- 
ing their produce for the period of his life. Even 
this, the utmost relaxation of the Roman Fatria 
Pot^stAS, left it far ampler and severer than any 
analogous institution of the modern world. The 
earliest modem writers on jurisprudence remark that 
it was only the fiercer and ruder of the conquerors of 
the empire, and notably the nations of Sclavonic 
origin, which exhibited a Patria Potestas at all re- 
sembling that which was described in the Pandects 
and the Code. All the Germanic immigrants seem 
to have recognised a corporate union of the family 
under the mund^ or authority of a patriarchal chief ; 
but his powers are obviously only the relics of a de- 
cayed Patria Potestas, and fell far short of those 
enjoyed by the Roman father. The Franks are 
particularly mentioned as not having the Roman 
Institution, and accordingly the old French law- 
yers, even when most busily engaged in filling the 



144 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANaENT LAW. chap. v. 

interstices of barbarous custom with rules of Roman 
law, were obliged to protect themselves against the 
intrusion of the Potestas by the express maxim, 
Puyssance de phre en France rHa lieu. The tenacity 
of the Romans in maintaining this relic of their most 
ancient condition is in itself remarkable, but it is less 
remarkable than the difiusion of the Potestas over 
the whole of a civilisation from which it had once 
disappeared. While the Castrense Peculium consti- 
tuted as yet the sole exception to the -father's power 
over property, and while his power over his children's 
persons was stiU extensive, the Roman citizenship, 
and with it the Patria Potestas, were spreading into 
every comer of the empire. Every African or 
Spaniard, every Gaul, Briton, or Jew, who received 
this honour by gift, purchase, or inheritance, placed 
himself under the Roman Law of Persons, and, though 
our authorities intimate that children bom before the 
acquisition of citizenship could not be brought under 
Power against their will, children born after it and 
all ulterior descendants were on the ordinary footing 
of a Roman j'iZeW/amzYia^. It does not fall within the 
province of this treatise to examine the mechanism of 
the later Roman society, but I may be permitted to 
remark that there is little foundation for the opinion 
which represents the constitution of Antoninus Cara- 
calla conferring Roman citizenship on the whole of 
his subjects as a measure of small importance. How- 



CHAP. V. THE PATRIA POTESTAS. 145 

ever we may interpret it, it must have enormously 
enlarged the sphere of the Patria Potestas, and it 
seems to me that the tightening of family relations 
which it effected is an agency which ought to be kept 
in view more than it has been, in accounting for the 
great moral revolution which was transforming the 
world. 

Before this branch of our subject is dismissed, 
it should be observed that the Paterfamilias was 
answerable for the delicts (or torts) of his Sons under 
Power. He was similarly liable for the torts of his 
slaves ; but in both cases he originally possessed the 
singular privilege of tendering the delinquent's person 
in full satisfaction of the damage. The responsibility 
thus incurred on behalf of sons, coupled with the 
mutual incapacity of Parent and Child under Power 
to sue one another, has seemed to some jurists to be 
best explained by the assumption of a " unity of 
person" between the Pater-familias and the Filius- 
familias* In the Chapter on Successions I shall at- 
tempt to show in what sense, and to what extent, this 
" unity " can be accepted as a reality. I can only say 
at present that these responsibilities of the Paterfami- 
lias, and other legal phenomena which will be discussed 
hereafter, appear to me to point at certain duties of 
the primitive Patriarchal chieftain which balanced his 
rights, I conceive that, if he disposed absolutely of 
the persons and fortune of his clansmen, this repre- 

L 



146 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. ▼. 

sentative ownership was coextensive with a liability 
to provide for all members of the brotherhood out of 
the common fund. The difficulty is to throw our- 
selves out of our habitual associations sufficiently for 
conceiving the nature of his obligation. It was not 
a legal duty, for law had not yet penetrated into the 
precinct of the Family. To call it moral is perhaps 
to anticipate the ideas belonging to a later stage of 
mental development; but the expression " moral 
obligation " is significant enough for our purpose, if 
we understand by it a duty semi-consciously followed 
and enforced rather by instinct and habit than by 
definite sanctions. 

The Patria Potestas, in its normal shape, has not 
been, and, as it seems to me, could not have been, a 
generally durable institution. The proof of its former 
universality is therefore incomplete so long as we 
consider it by itself; but the demonstration may be 
carried much further by examining other departments 
of ancient law which depend on it ultimately, but not 
by a thread of connexion visible in all its parts or to 
all eyes. Let us turn for example to Kinship, or in 
other words, to the scale on which the proximity of 
relatives to each other is calculated in archaic juris- 
prudence. Here again it will be convenient to em- 
ploy the Roman terms. Agnatic and Cognatic relation- 
ship. Cognatic relationship is simply the conception 
of kinship familiar to modem ideas ; it is the relation- 



CHAP. V. AGNATION AND COGNATION. 147 

ship arising through common descent from the same 
pair of married persons, whether the descent be 
traced through males or females. Agnatic relation- 
ship is something very different : it excludes a num- 
ber of persons whom we in our day should certainly 
consider of kin to ourselves, and it includes many 
more whom we should never reckon among our 
kindred. It is in truth the connexion existing be- 
tween the members of the Family, conceived as it 
was in the most ancient times. The limits of this 
connexion are far from conterminous with those 
of modem relationship. 

Cognates then are all those persons who can trace 
their blood to a single ancestor and ancestress ; or, if 
we take the strict technical meaning of the word in 
Roman law, they are all who trace their blood to the 
legitimate marriage of a common pair. " Cognation " 
is therefore a relative term, and the degree of con- 
nexion in blood which it indicates depends on the 
particular marriage which is selected as the com- 
mencement of the calculation. If we begin with the 
marriage of father and mother. Cognation will only 
express the relationship of brothers and sisters ; if we 
take that of the grandfather and grandmother, then 
uncles, aunts, and their descendants will also be in- 
cluded in the notion of Cognation, and following the 
same process a larger number of Cognates may be 
continually obtained by choosing the starting point 

L 2 



\ 



148 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

higher and higher up in the line of ascent. All this 
is easily understood by a modem; but who are the 
Agnates? In the first place, they are all the Cognates 
who trace their connexion exclusively through males. 
A table of Cognates is, of course, formed by taking 
each lineal ancestor in turn and including all his 
descendant^ of both sexes in the tabular view; if 
then, in tracing the various branches of such a ge- 
nealogical table or tree, we stop whenever we come 
to the name of a female and pursue that particular 
branch or ramification no further, all who remain 
after the descendants of women have been excluded 
are Agnates, and their connexion together is Agnatic 
Relationship. I dwell a little on the process which is 
practically followed in separating them from the Cog- 
nates, because it explains a memorable legal maxim, 
"^ " Mulier est finis familisB" — a woman is the terminus 
of the family. A female name closes the branch or 
twig of the genealogy in which it occurs. None of 
the descendants of a female are included in the pri- 
mitive notion of family relationship. 

If the system of archaic law at which we are look- 
ing be one which admits Adoption, we must add to 
the Agnates thus obtained all persons, male or female, 
who have been brought into the Family by the artifi- 
cial extension of its boundaries. But the descendants 
of such persons will only be Agnates, if they satisfy 
the conditions which have just been described. 



CHAP. V. AGNATIOJf. 149 

What then is the reason of this arbitrary inclusion 
and exclusion? Why should a conception of Kinship, 
so elastic as to include strangers brought into the 
family by adoption, be nevertheless so narrow as to 
shut out the descendants of a female member? To 
solve these questions, we must recur to the Patria 
Potestas. The foundation of Agnation is not the 
marriage of Father and Mother, but the authority of 
the Father. All persons are Agnatically connected to- 
gether who are imder the same Paternal Power, or 
who have been under it, or who might have been 
under it if their lineal ancestor had lived long enough 
to exercise his empire. In truth, in the primitive 
view. Relationship is exactly limited by Patria Potes- 
tas. Where the Potestas begins, Kinship begins; 
and therefore adoptive relatives are among the 
kindred. Where the Potestas ends. Kinship ends ; so 
that a son emancipated by his father loses all rights 
of Agnation. And here we have the reason why the 
descendants of female? are outside the limits of archaic 
kinship. If a woman died unmarried, she could 
have no legitimate descendants. If she married, her 
children feU under the Patria Potestas, not of her 
Father, but of her Husband, and thus were lost to her 
own family. It is obvious that the organisation of 
primitive societies would have been confounded, if 
men had called themselves relatives of their mother's 
relatives. The inference would have been that a per- 

L 3 



150 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap, v. 

son might be subject to two distinct Patriae Potestates ; 
but distinct Patriae Potestates implied distinct juris- 
dictions, so that anybody amenable to two of them at 
the same time would have lived under two different 
dispensations. As long as the Family was an impe- 
rium in imperio, a community within the common- 
wealth, governed by its own institutions of which the 
parent was the source, the limitation of relationship 
to the Agnates was a necessary security against a 
conflict of laws in the domestic forum. 

The Parental Powers proper are extinguished by 
the death of the Parent, but Agnation is as it were a 
mould which retains their imprint after they have 
ceased to exist. Hence comes the interest of Agna- 
tion for the inquirer into the history of jurisprudence. 
The Powers themselves are discernible in compara- 
tively few 'monuments of ancient law, but Agnatic 
Relationship, which implies their former existence, is 
discoverable almost everywhere. There are few 
indigenous bodies of law belonging to communities of 
the Indo-European stock, which do not exhibit pecu- 
liarities in the most ancient part of their structure 
which are clearly referable to Agnation. In Hin- 
doo law, for example, which is saturated with the 
primitive notions of family dependency, kinship is 
entirely Agnatic, and I am informed that in Hindoo 
genealogies the names of women are generally omit- 
ted altogether. The same view of relationship per- 



CHAP. V. THE HALF-BLOOD. 151 

vades so mucli of the laws of the races who overran 
the Roman Empire as appears to have really formed 
part of their primitive usage, and we may suspect 
that it would have perpetuated itself even more than 
it has in modem European jurisprudence, if it had 
not been for the vast influence of the later Roman 
law on modern thought. The Praetors early laid hold 
on Cognation as the natural form of kinship, and 
spared no pains in purifying their system from the 
older conception. Their ideas have descended to us, 
but still traces of Agnation are to be seen in many of 
the modem rules of succession after death. The ex- 
clusion of females andtheir children from governmental 
functions, commonly attributed to the usage of the 
Salian Franks, has certainly an agnatic origin, being 
descended from the ancient German rule of succes- 
sion to allodial property. In Agnation too is to 
be sought the explanation of that extraordinary rule 
of English Law, only recently repealed, which prohi- 
bited brothers of the half-blood from succeeding to 
one another's lands. In the Customs of Normandy, 
the rule applies to uterine brothers only, that is, to 
brothers by the same mother but not by the same 
father; and, limited in this way, it is a strict de- 
duction from the system of Agnation, under which 
uterine brothers are no relations at all to one another. 
When it was transplanted to England, the English 
judges, who had no clue to its principle,* interpreted 

L 4 



152 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

it as a general prohibition against the succession of 
the half-blood, and extended it to consanguineous 
brothers, that is to sons of the same father by differ- 
ent wives. In all the literature which enshrines the 
pretended philosophy of law, there is nothing more 
curious than the pages of elaborate sophistry in 
which Blackstone attempts to explain and justify the 
exclusion of the half-blood. 

It may be shown, I think, that the Family, as held 
together by the Patria Potestas, is the nidus out of 
which the entire Law of Persons has germinated. Of 
all the chapters of that Law the most important is 
that which is concerned with the status of Females. 
It has just been stated that Primitive Jurisprudence, 
though it does not allow a Woman to communicate 
any rights of Agnation to her descendants, includes 
herself nevertheless in the Agnatic bond. Indeed, 
the relation of a female to the family in which she 
was born is much stricter, closer, and more durable 
than that which unites her male kinsmen. We have 
several times laid down that early law takes notice of 
Families only ; this is the same thing as saying that 
it only takes notice of persons exercising Patria 
Potestas, and accordingly the only principle on which 
it enfranchises a son or grandson at the death of his 
Parent, is a consideration of the capacity inherent in 
such son or grandson to become himself the head of a 
new family*and the root of a new set of Parental 



CHAP. V. GUARDIANSHIP OF WOMEN. 153 

Powers. But a woman, of course, has no capacity of 
the kind, and no title accordingly to the liberation 
which it confers. There is therefore a peculiar 
contrivance of archaic jurisprudence for retaining her 
in the bondage of the Family for life. This is the 
institution known to the oldest Roman law as the 
Perpetual Tutelage of Women, under which a Female, 
though relieved from her Parent's authority by his 
decease, continues subject through life to her nearest 
male relations as her Guardians. Perpetual Guardian- 
ship is obviously neither more nor less than an 
artificial prolongation of the Patria Potestas, when 
for other purposes it has been dissolved. In India, 
the system survives in absolute completeness, and its 
operation is so strict that a Hindoo Mother frequently 
becomes the ward of her own sons. Even in Europe, 
the laws of the Scandinavian nations respecting wo- 
men preserved it until quite recently. The invaders 
of the Western Empire had it universally among 
their indigenous usages, and indeed their ideas on 
the subject of Guardianship, in all its forms, were 
among the most retrogressive of those which they 
introduced into the Western world. But from the 
mature Roman jurisprudence it had entirely disap- 
peared. We should know almost nothing about it, if 
we had only the compilations of Justinian to consult; 
but the discovery of the manuscript of Gains discloses 
it to us at a most interesting epoch, just when it had 



/,•;,: m '^ ^IMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap, v^ 

Mien into complete discredit and was verging on 
extinction. The great jurisconsult himself scouts the 
popular apology offered for it in the mental inferiority 
of the female sex, and a considerable part of his 
volume is taken up with descriptions of the numerous 
expedients, some of them displaymg extraordinary 
ingenuity, which the Roman lawyers had devised for 
enabling Women to defeat the ancient rules. Led by 
their theory of Natural Law, the jurisconsults had 
evidently at this time assumed the equality of the 
sexes as a principle of their code of equity. The 
restrictions which they attacked were, it is to be 
observed, restrictions on the disposition of property, 
for which the assent of the woman's guardians were 
still formally required. Control of her person was 
apparently quite obsolete. 
— Ancient law subordinates the woman to her blood- 
relations, while a prime phenomenon of modem 
jurisprudence has been her subordination to her 
husband. The history of the change is remarkable. 
It begins far back in the annals of Rome. Anciently, 
there were three modes in which marriage might be 
contracted according to Roman usage, one involving 
a religious solemnity, the other two the observance of 
certain secular formalities. By the religious marriage 
or Confarreation ; by the higher form of civil marriage, 
which was called Coemption; and by the lower form, 
which was termed Ustis, the Husband acquired a 



ANCIENT ROMAN MARRIAGE. /|.#AWl4M1lOUL^ 

number of rights over the person and propekyWtftR ART. 
wife, which were on the whole in excess of sucn^ 
conferred on him in any system of modem jurispru- 
dence. But in what capacity did he acquire them? 
Not as Husband^ but as Father. By the Confarreation, 
Coemption, and Usus, the woman passed in manum 
viri^ that is, in law she became the Daughter of 
her husband. She was included in his Patria 
Potestas. She incurred aU the liabilities springing 
out of it while it subsisted, and surviving it when it 
had expired. All her property became absolutely 
his, and she was retained in tutelage after his death 
to the guardian whom he had appointed by will. 
These three ancient forms of marriage fell, however, 
gradually into disuse, so that, at the most splendid 
period of Roman greatness, they had almost entirely 
given place to a fashion of wedlock — old apparently, 
but not hitherto considered reputable — which was 
founded on a modification of the lower form of civil 
marriage. Without explaining the technical mecha- 
nism of the institution now generally popular, I may 
describe it as amounting in law to little more than a 
temporary deposit of the woman by her family. The 
rights of the family remained unimpaired, and the 
lady continued in the tutelage of guardians whom her 
parents had appointed and whose privileges of con- 
trol overrode, in many material respects, the inferior 
authority of her husband. The consequence was 



156 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

that the situation of the Roman female, whether mar- 
ried or unmarried, became one of great personal and 
proprietary independence, for the tendency of the 
later law, as I have already hinted, was to reduce 
the power of the guardian to a nullity, while the 
form of marriage in fashion conferred on the husband 
no compensating superiority. But Christianity tended 
somewhat from the very first to narrow this remark- 
able liberty. Led at first by justifiable disrelish for 
the loose practices of the decaying heathen world, 
but afterwards hurried on by a passion of asceticism, 
the professors of the new faith looked with disfavour 
on a marital tie which was in fact the laxest the West- 
em world has seen. The latest Roman law, so far as it 
is touched by the Constitutions of the Christian Em- 
perors, bears some marks of a reaction against the 
liberal doctrines of the great Antonine jurisconsults. 
And the prevalent state of religious sentiment may 
explain why it is that modern jurisprudence, forged in 
the fiimace of barbarian conquest, and formed by the 
fusion of Roman jurisprudence with patriarchal usage^ 
has absorbed, among its rudiments, much more than 
usual of those rules concerning the position of women 
which belong peculiarly to an imperfect civilisation. 
During the troubled era which begins modem history, 
and while the laws of the Germanic and Sclavonic 
immigrants remained superposed like a separate layer 
above the Roman jurisprudence of their provincial 



CHAP. V. COiroiTION OF WOMEN. 157 

subjects, the women of the dominant races are seen 
-everywhere under various forms of archaic guardian- 
ship, and the husband who takes a wife from any 
family except his own pays a money-price to her 
relations for the tutelage which they surrender to 
him. When we move onwards, and the code of the 
middle ages has been formed by the amalgamation of 
the two systems, the law relating to women carries 
the stamp of its double origin. The principle of 
the Eoman jurisprudence is so far triumphant that 
unmarried females are generally (though there are 
local exceptions to the rule) relieved from the bondage 
of the family ; but the archaic principle of the barba- 
rians has fixed the position of married women, and 
the husband has drawn to himself in his marital 
character the powers which had once belonged to his 
wife's male kindred, the only difference being that he 
no longer purchases his privileges. At this point there- 
fore the modern law of Western and Southern Europe 
begins to be distinguished by one of its chief cha- 
racteristics, the comparative freedom it allows to 
unmarried women and widows, the heavy disabilities 
it imposes on wives. It was very long befqje the 
subordination entailed on the other sex by marriage 
was sensibly diminished. The principal and most 
powerful solvent of the revived barbarism of Europe 
was always the codified jurisprudence of Justi- 
nian, wherever it was studied with that passionate 



158 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANaENT LAW. chap. v. 

enthusiasm which it seldom failed to awaken. It 
covertly but most efficaciously undermined the cus- 
toms which it pretended merely to interpret. But 
the Chapter of law relating to married women was 
for the most part read by the light, not of Roman, 
but of Canon Law, which in no one particular departs 
so widely from the spirit of the secular jurisprudence 
as in the view it takes of the relations created by 
marriage. This was in part inevitable, since no 
society which preserves any tincture of Christian 
institution is likely to restore to married women the 
personal liberty conferred on them by the middle 
Roman law, but the proprietary disabilities of married 
females stand on quite a different basis from their 
personal incapacities, and it is by keeping alive and 
consolidating the former that the expositors of the 
Canon Law have deeply injured civilisation. There 
are many vestiges of a struggle between the secular 
and ecclesiastical principles, but the Canon Law 
nearly everywhere prevailed. In some of the French 
provinces, married women, of a rank below nobility, 
obtained all the powers of dealing with property 
which Roman jurisprudence had allowed, and this 
local law has been largely followed by the Code 
Napoleon; but the state of the Scottish law shows 
that scrupulous deference to the doctrines of the 
Roman jurisconsults did not always extend to miti- 



CHAP. V. CONDITION OP WOMEN. 159 

gating the disabilities of wives. The systems how- 
ever which are least indulgent to married women are 
invariably those which have followed the Canon Law 
excltteively, or those which, from the lateness of their 
contact with European civilisation, have never had 
their archaisms weeded out. The Scandinavian laws, 
harsh till lately to aU females, are still remarkable for 
their severity to wives. And scarcely less stringent in 
the proprietary incapacities it imposes is the English 
Common Law, which borrows for the greatest number 
of its fundamental principles from the jurisprudence 
of the Canonists. Indeed, the part of the Common 
Law which prescribes the legal situation of married 
women may serve to give an Englishman clear notions 
of the great institution which has been the principal 
subject of this chapter. I do not know how the 
operation and nature of the ancient Patria Potestas 
can be brought so vividly before the mind as by 
reflecting on the prerogatives attached to the husband 
by the pure English Common Law, and by recalling 
the rigorous consistency with which the view of a 
complete legal subjection on the part of the wife is 
carried by it, where it is untouched by equity or 
statutes, through every department of rights, duties, 
and remedies. The distance between the eldest and 
latest Roman law on the subject of Children under 
Power may be considered as equivalent to the differ- 



> 



160 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap, v 

ence between the Common Law and the jurisprudence 
of the Court of Chancery in the rules which they 
respectively apply to wives. 

If we were to lose sight of the true origin of 
Guardianship in both its forms and were to employ 
the common language on these topics, we should find 
ourselves remarking that, while theTutelage of Women 
is an instance in which systems of archaic law push to 
an extravagant length the fiction of suspended rights, 
the rules which they lay down for the Guardianship 
of Male Orphans are an example of a fault in precisely 
the opposite direction. All such systems terminate the 
Tutelage of males at an extraordinary early period. 
Under the ancient Eoman law, which maybe taken as 
their type, the son who was delivered fromPatriaPotes- 
tas by the death of his Father or Grandfather remained 
under guardianship till an epoch which for general pur- 
poses may be described as arriving with his fifteenth 
year; but the arrival of that epoch placed him at once 
in the full enjoyment of personal and proprietary inde- 
pendence. The period of minority appears therefore 
to have been as unreasonably short as the duration 
of the disabilities of women was preposterously long. 
But, in point of fact, there was no element either of 
excess or of shortcoming in the circumstances which 
gave their original form to the two kinds of guardian- 
ship. Neither the one nor the other of them was 
based on the slightest consideration of public or 



CHAP. V. GUARDIANSHIP OF ORPHANS. 161 

private convenience. The guardianship of male 
orphans was no more designed originally to shield 
them till the arrival of years of discretion than the 
tutelage of women was intended to protect the other 
sex against its own feebleness. The reason why the 
death of the father delivered the son from the bond- 
age of the femily was the son's capacity for becoming 
himself the head of a new family and the founder of a 
newPatriaPotestas ; no such capacity was possessed by 
the woman and therefore she was never enfranchised. 
Accordingly the Guardianship of Male Orphans was a 
contrivance for keeping alive the semblance of subor- 
dination to the family of the Parent, up to the time 
when the child was supposed capable of becoming a 
parent himself. It was a prolongation of the Patria 
Potestas up to the period of bare physical manhood. 
It ended with puberty, for the rigour of the theory 
demanded that it should do so. Inasmuch, however, 
as it did not profess to conduct the orphan ward to 
the age of intellectual maturity or fitness for affairs, 
it was quite unequal to the purposes of general con- 
venience; and this the Romans seem to have dis- 
covered at a very early stage of their social progress. 
One of the very oldest monuments of Roman legisla- 
tion is the Lex Lcetoria or Plcetoria which placed all 
free males who were of full years and rights under 
the temporary control of a new class of guardians, 
called Curatores^ whose sanction was required to 

M 



^^ 



162 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

validate their acts or contracts. The twenty-sixth 
year of the young man's age was the limit of this 
statutory supervision; and it is exclusively with 
reference to the age of twenty-five that the terms 
" majority " and" minority " are employed in Roman 
law. Pupilage or wardship in modem jurisprudence 
had adjusted itself with tolerable regularity to the 
simple principle of protection to the immaturity of 
youth both bodily and mental. It has its natural 
termination with years of discretion. But for pro- 
tection against physical weakness and for protection 
against intellectual incapacity, the Romans looked to 
two different institutions, distinct both in theory and 
design. The ideas attendant on both are combined 
in the modem idea of guardianship. 

The Law of Persons contains but one other chapter 
which can be usefully cited for our present purpose. 
The legal rules by which systems of mature juris- 
prudence regulate the connection oi Master and Slave^ 
present no very distinct traces of the original condi- 
tion common to ancient societies. But there are 
reasons for this exception. There seems to be some- 
thing in the institution of Slavery which has at 
aU times either shocked or perplexed mankind, 
however little habituated to reflection, and however 
slightly advanced in the cultivation of its moral 
instincts. The compunction which ancient commu- 
nities almost unconsciously experienced appears to 
have always resulted in the adoption of some imagi- 



CHAP. V, MASTER AND SLAVE. 163 

nary principle upon which a defence, or at least a 
rationale, of slavery could be plausibly founded. 
Very early in their history the Greeks explained the 
institution as grounded on the intellectual inferiority 
of certain races and their consequent natural aptitude 
for the servile condition. The Romans, in a spirit 
equally characteristic, derived it from a supposed 
agreement between the victor and the vanquished in 
which the first stipulated for the perpetual services 
of his foe; and the other gained in consideration 
the life which he had legitimately forfeited. Such 
theories were not only unsound but plainly unequal 
to the case for which they affected to account. Still 
they exercised powerful influence in many ways. 
They satisfied the conscience of the Master. They 
perpetuated and probably increased the debasement 
the Slave. And they naturally tended to put out of 
sight the relation in which servitude had originally 
stood to the rest of the domestic system. The 
relation, though not clearly exhibited, is casually 
indicated in* many parts of primitive law, and more 
particularly in the typical system — that of ancient 
Rome. 

Much industry and some learning have been be- 
stowed in the United States of America on the ques- 
tion whether the Slave was in the early stages of 
society a recognised member of the Family. There is 
a sense in which an affirmative answer must certainly 

11 2 



164 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. cbap. v. 

be given. It is clear, from the testimony both of 
ancient law and of many primeval histories, that the 
Slave might under certain conditions be made the 
Heir, or Universal Successor, of the Master, and this 
significant faculty, as I shall explain in the Chapter 
on Succession, implies that the government and re- 
presentation of the Family might, in a particular state 
of circumstances, devolve on the bondman. It seems, 
however, to be assumed in the American arguments 
on the subject that, if we allow Slavery to have been 
a primitive Family institution, the acknowledgment 
is pregnant with an admission of the moral defensi- 
bility of Negro-servitude at the present moment. 
What then is meant by saying that the Slave was 
origitially included in the Family ? Not that his situa- 
tion may not have been ^ the fruit of the coarsest - 
motives which can actuate man. The simple wish to 
use the bodily powers of another person as a means of 
ministering to one's own ease or pleasure is doubtless 
the foundation of Slavery, and as old as human nature. 
When we speak of the Slave as anciently included 
in the Family, we intend to assert nothing as to the 
motives of those who brought him into it or kept him 
there; we merely imply that the tie which bound 
him to his master was regarded as one of the same 
general character with that which united every other 
member of the group to its chieftain. This conse- 
quence is, in fact, carried in the general assertion 



CHAP. V. SLAVERY. 165 

already made that the primitive ideas of mankind 
were unequal to comprehending any basis of the con- 
nection inter se of individuals, apart from the rela- 
tions of familyr The Family consisted primarily of 
those who belonged to it by consanguinity and next 
of those who had been engrafted on it by adoption ; 
but there was still a third class of persons who were 
only joined to it by common subjection to its head, 
and these were the Slaves. The bom and the adopted 
subjects of the chief were raised above the Slave by 
the certainty that in the ordinary course of events 
they would be relieved from bondage and entitled to 
exercise powers of their own ; but that the inferiority 
of the Slave was not such as to place him outside the 
pale of the Family, or such as to degrade him to the 
footing of inanimate property, is clearly proved, I 
think, by the many traces which remain of his ancient 
capacity for inheritance in the last resort. It would, 
of course, be unsafe in the highest degree to hazard 
conjectures how far the lot of the Slave was mitigated, 
in the beginnings of society, by having a definite 
place reserved to him in the empire of the Father. It 
is, perhaps, more probable that the son was practi- 
cally assimilated to the Slave, than that the Slave 
shared any of the tenderness which in later times was 
shown to the son. But it may be asserted with some 
confidence of advanced and matured codes that, 
wherever servitude is sanctioned, the slave has uni- 

M 3 



166 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

formly greater advantages under systems which pre- 
serve some memento of his earlier condition than 
under those which have adopted some other theory of 
his civil degradation. The point of view from which 
jurisprudence regards the Slave is always of great 
importance to him. The Roman law was arrested 
in its growing tendency to look upon him more and 
more as an article of property by the theory of the 
Law of Nature; and hence it is that, wherever servi- 
tude is sanctioned by institutions which have been 
deeply affected by Roman jurisprudence, the servile 
condition is never intolerably wretched. There is a 
great deal of evidence that in those American States 
which have taken the highly Romanised code of 
Louisiana as the basis of their jurisprudence, the lot 
and prospects of the negro-population are better in 
many material respects than under institutions 
founded on the English Common Law, which, as 
recently interpreted, has no true place for the Slave, 
and can only therefore regard him as a chattel. 

We have now examined all parts of the ancient 
Law of Persons which fall within the scope of this 
treatise, and the result of the inquiry is, I trust, to 
give additional definiteness and precision to our view 
of the infancy of jurisprudence. The Civil laws of 
States first make their appearance as the Themistes 
of a patriarchal sovereign, and we can now see that 
these Themistes are probably only a developed form 



CHAP. V. ANCIENT LAW. 167 

of the irresponsible commands which, in a still earlier 
condition of the race, the head of each isolated house- 
hold may have addressed to his wives, his children, 
and his slaves. But, even after the State has been 
organised, the laws have still an extremely limited 
application. Whether they retain their primitive 
character as Themistes, or whether they advance to 
the condition of Customs or Codified Texts, they are 
binding not on individuals, but on Families. Ancient 
jurisprudence, if a perhaps deceptive comparison may 
be employed, may be likened to International Law, 
filling nothing, as it were, excepting the interstices 
between the great groups which are the atoms of so- 
ciety. In a community so situated, the legislation 
of assemblies and the jurisdiction of Courts reaches 
only to the heads of families, and to every other 
individual the rule of conduct is the law of his home, 
of which his Parent is the legislator. But the sphere 
of civil law, small at first, tends steadily to enlarge 
itself. The agents of legal change, Fictions, Equity, 
and Legislation, are brought in turn to bear on the 
primeval institutions, and at every point of the pro- 
gress, a greater number of personal rights and a 
larger amount of property are removed from the do- 
mestic forum to the cognizance of the public tribu- 
nals. The ordinances of the government obtain 
gradually the same efficacy in private concerns as 
in matters of state, and are no longer liable to be 

M 4 



168 PRIMITIVE SOCIETY AND ANQENT LAW. chap, r- 

overridden by the behests of a despot enthroned by 
each hearthstone. We have in the annals of Roman 
law a nearly complete history of the crumbling away 
of an archaic system, and of the formation of new in- 
stitutions from the re-combined materials, institutions 
some of which descended unimpaired to the modern 
world, while others, destroyed or corrupted by con- 
tact with barbarism in the dark ages, had again to be 
recovered by mankind. When we leave this juris- 
prudence at the epoch of its final reconstruction by 
Justinian, few traces of archaism can be discovered in 
any part of it except in the single article of the ex- 
tensive powers still reserved to the living Parent. 
Everywhere else principles of convenience, or of sym- 
metry, or of simplification — new principles at any 
rate — have usurped the authority of the jejune con- 
siderations which satisfied the conscience of ancient 
times. Everywhere a new morality has displaced the 
canons of conduct and the reasons of acquiescence 
which were in unison with the ancient usages, because 
in fact they were bom of them. 

The movement of the progressive societies has 
been uniform in one respect. Through all its course 
it has been distinguished by the gradual dissolution 4 
of family dependency and the growth of individual 
obligation in its place. The Individual is steadily 
substituted for the Family, as the unit of which civil 
laws take account. The advance has been accom- 
plished at varying rates of celerity, and there are 



CHAP. V. DISINTEGRATION OP THE FAMILY. 169 

societies not absolutely stationary in which the col- 
lapse of the ancient organisation can only be perceived 
by careful study of the phenomena they present. 
But, whatever its pace, the change has not been 
subject to reaction or recoil, and apparent retarda- 
tions will be found to have been occasioned through 
the absorption of archaic ideas and customs from 
some entirely foreign source. Nor is it difficult to see 
what is the tie between man and man which replaces 
by degrees those forms of reciprocity in rights and 
duties which have their origin in the Family. It is 
Contract. Starting, as from one terminus of history, 
from a condition of society in which all the relations 
of Persons are summed up in the relations of Family, 
we seem to have steadily moved towards a phase of 
social order in which all these relations arise from 
the free agreement of Individuals. In Western 
Europe the progress achieved in this direction has 
been considerable. Thus the status of the Slave has 
disappeared — it has been superseded by the contrac- 
tual relation of the servant to his master. The 
status of the Female under Tutelage, if the tutelage 
be understood of persons other than her husband, has 
also ceased to exist; from her coming of age to her 
marriage all the relations she may form are relations 
of contract. So too the status of the Son under Power 
has no true place in law of modem European societies. 
If any civil obligation binds together the Parent and 
the child of full age, it is one to which only contract 



170 PRimnVE SOCIETY AND ANCIENT LAW. chap. v. 

gives its legal validity. The apparent exceptions are 
exceptions of that stamp which illustrate the rule. 
The child before years of discretion, the orphan under 
guardianship, the adjudged lunatic, have all their 
capacities and incapacities regulated by the Law 
of Persons. But why ? The reason is diflferently 
expressed in the conventional language of different 
systems, but fxi substance it is stated to the same 
effect by all. The great majority of Jurists are 
constant to the principle that the classes of persons 
just mentioned are subject to extrinsic control on the 
single ground that they do not possess the faculty of 
forming a judgment on their own interests; in other 
words, that they are wanting in the first essential of 
an engagement by Contract. 

The word Status may be usefully employed to 
construct a formula expressing the law of progress 
thus indicated, which, whatever be its value, seems 
to me to be sufficiently ascertained. All the forms 
of Status taken notice of in the Law of Persons were 
derived from, and to some extent are still coloured 
by, the powers and privileges anciently residing in 
the Family. If then we employ Status, agreeably 
with the usage of the best writers, to signify these 
personal conditions only, and avoid applying the 
term to such conditions as are the immediate or 
remote result of agreement, we may say that the 
movement of the progressive societies has hitherto 
been a movement /r(?/?i Status to Contract. 



CHAP. VI. TESTAMENTS. 171 



CHAP. VI. 

THE EARLY HISTORY OF TESTAMENTARY SUCCESSION. 

If an attempt were made to demonstrate in England 
the superiority of the historical method of investiga- 
tion to the modes of inquiry concerning Juris- 
prudence which are in fashion among us, no depart- 
ment of Law would better serve as an example than 
Testaments or Wills. Its capabilities it owes to its 
great length and great continuity. At the beginning 
of its history we find ourselves in the very infancy of 
the social state^ surrounded by conceptions which it 
requires some effort of mind to realise in their an- 
cient form; while here, at the other extremity of its 
line of progress, we are in the midst of legal notions 
which are nothing more than those same conceptions 
disguised by the phraseology and by the habits of 
thought which belong to modem times, and exhibit- 
ing therefore a difficulty of another kind, the diffi- 
culty of believing that ideas which form part of our 
everyday mental stock can really stand in need of 
analysis and examination. The growth of the Law of 



172 TESTAMENTARY LAW. chap. vi. 

Wills between these extreme points can be traced 
with remarkable distinctness. It was much less in- 
terrupted at the epoch of the birth of feudalism, than 
the history of most other branches of law. It is, in- 
deed, true that as regards all provinces of jurispru- 
dence, the break caused by the division between 
ancient and modern history, or in other words by the 
dissolution of the Roman empire, has been very 
greatly exaggerated. Indolence has disinclined many 
writers to be at the pains of looking for threads of 
connection entangled and obscured by the confusions 
of six troubled centuries, while other inquirers, not 
naturally deficient in patience and industry, have 
been misled by idle pride in the legal system of their 
country, and by consequent unwillingness to confess 
its obligations to the jurisprudence of Rome. But 
these unfavourable influences have had comparatively 
little effect on the province of Testamentary Law. 
The barbarians were confessedly strangers to any 
such conception as that of a Will. The best 
authorities agree that there is no trace of it in 
those parts of their written codes which comprise 
the customs practised by them in their original seats, 
and in their subsequent settlements on the edge 
of the Roman Empire. But soon after they became 
mixed with the population of the Roman provinces 
they appropriated from the Imperial jurisprudence 
the conception of a Will, at first in part, and after- 



CHAP. VI. INFLUENCE OF THE CUURCII. 173 

wards in all its integrity. The influence of the 
Church had much to do with this rapid assimilation. 
The ecclesiastical power had very early succeeded to 
those privileges of custody and registration of Testa- 
ments which several of the heathen temples had en-» 
joyed; and even thus early it was almost exclusively 
to private bequests that the religious foundations 
owed their temporal possessions. Hence it is that 
the decrees of the earliest Provincial Councils per- 
petually contain anathemas against those who deny 
the sanctity of Wills. Here, in England, Church in- 
fluence was certainly chief among the causes which 
by universal acknowledgment have prevented that 
discontinuity in the history of Testamentary Law, 
which is sometimes believed to exist in the history of 
other provinces of Jurisprudence. The jurisdiction 
over one class of Wills was delegated to the Eccle- 
siastical Courts, which applied to them, though not 
always intelligently, the principles of Roraan juris- 
prudence; and, though neither the courts of Common 
Law nor the Court of Chancery owned any positive 
obligation to follow the Ecclesiastical tribunals, they 
could not escape the potent influence of a system of 
settled rules in course of application by their side. 
The English law of testamentary succession to per- 
sonalty has become a modified form of the dispen- 
sation under which the inheritances of Boman citizens 
were administered. 



174 ANCIENT WILLS. chap. vi. 

It is not difficult to point out the extreme difference 
of the conclusions forced on us by the historical treat- 
ment of the subject, from those to which we are con- 
ducted when, without the help of history, we merely 
strive to analyse our primA facie impressions. I sup- 
pose there is nobody who, starting from the popular or 
even the legal conception of a Will, would not imagine 
that certain qualities are necessarily attached to it. 
He would say, for example, that a Will necessarily 
takes effect at death only^ — ^that it is secret^ not known 
as a matter of course to persons taking interests 
under its provisions, — that it is revocable^ i.e. always 
capable of being superseded by a new act of testation. 
Yet I shall be able to show that there was a time 
when none of these characteristics belonged to a Will. 
The Testaments from which our Wills are directly 
descended at first took effect immediately on their exe- 
cution ; they were not secret ; they were not revocable. 
Few legal agencies are, in fact, the fruit of more 
complex historical agencies than that by which a 
man's written intentions control the posthumous dis- 
position of his goods. Testaments very slowly and 
gradually gathered round them the qualities I have 
mentioned ; and they did this from causes and under 
pressure of events which may be called casual, or 
which at any rate have no interest for us at present, 
except so far as they have affected the history of 
law. 



CHAP. yi. NATURAL RIGHT OF TESTATION. 175 

At a time when legal theories were more abundant 
than at present, — ^theories which, it is true, were for 
the most part gratuitous and premature enough, but 
which nevertheless rescued jurisprudence from that 
worse and more ignoble condition, not unknown to 
ourselves, in which nothing like a generalisation is 
aspired to, and law is regarded as a mere empirical 
pursuit — it was the fashion to explain the ready 
and apparently intuitive perception which we have 
of certain qualities in a WiU, by saying that they 
were natural to it, or, as the phrase would run in 
full, attached to it by the Law of Nature. Nobody, I 
imagine, would affect to maintain such a doctrine, 
when once it was ascertained that all these character- 
istics had their origin within historical memory; at 
the same time, vestiges of the theory of which the 
doctrine is an offshoot, linger in forms of expression 
which we all of us use and perhaps scarcely know how 
to dispense with. I inay illustrate this by mention- 
ing a position common in the legal literature of the 
17th century. The jurists of that period very com- 
monly assert that the power of Testation itself is of 
Natural Law, that it is a right conferred by the Law 
of Nature. Their teaching, though all persons may 
not at once see the connection, is in substance followed 
by those who affirm that the right of dictating or 
controlling the posthumous disposal of property is a 
necessary or natural consequence of the proprietary 



176 NATURAL RIGHT OF TESTATION. chap. vi. 

rights themselves. And every student of technical 
jurisprudence must have come across the same view, 
clothed in the language of a rather different school, 
which, in its rationale of this department of law, 
treats succession ex testamento as the mode of devolu- 
tion which the property of deceased persons ought 
primarily to follow, and then proceeds to account for 
succession ah intestato as the incidental provision of 
the lawgiver for the discharge of a function which 
was only left unperformed through the neglect or 
misfortune of the deceased proprietor. These opinions 
are only expanded forms of the more compendious 
doctrine that Testamentary disposition is an institu- 
tion of the Law of Nature. It is certainly never quite 
safe to pronounce dogmatically as to the range of 
association embraced by modem minds, when they 
reflect on Nature and her Law; but I believe that 
most persons, who affirm that the Testamentary 
Power is of Natural Law, may be taken to imply 
either that, as a matter of fact, it is universal, or that 
nations are prompted to sanction it by an original in- 
stinct and impulse. With respect to the first of these 
positions, I think that, when explicitly set forth, it 
can never be seriously contended for in an age which 
has seen the severe restraints imposed on the Testa- 
mentary Power by the Code Napoleon^ and has wit- 
nessed the steady multiplication of systems for which 
the French codes have served as a model. To the 



CHAP. VI. NATURE OF A WILL. 177 

second assertion we must object that it is contrary to 
the best-ascertained facts in the early history of law, 
and I venture to affirm generally that, in all indi- 
genous societies, a condition of jurisprudence in which 
Testamentary privileges are not allowed, or rather 
not contemplated, has preceded that later stage of 
legal development in which the mere will of the pro- 
prietor is permitted under more or less of restriction 
to override the claims of his kindred in blood. 

The conception of a Will or Testament cannot be 
considered by itself. It is a member, and not the 
first, of a series of conceptions. In itself a Will is 
simply the instrument by which the intention of the 
testator is declared. It must be clear, I think, that 
before such an instrument takes its turn for dis- 
cussion, there are several preliminary points to be 
examined, — as for example, what is it, what sort of 
right or interest, which passes from a dead man on 
his decease ? to whom and in what form does it pass? 
and how came it that the dead were allowed to 
control the posthumous disposition of their property? 
Thrown into technical language, the dependence of 
the various conceptions which contribute to the 
notion of a Will is thus expressed. A Will or Testa- 
ment is an instrument by which the devolution of an 
inheritance is prescribed. Inheritance is a form of 
universal succession. A universal succession is a 
succession to a universitas juris, or university of 

N 



178 UNIVERSITAS JURIS. chap. vi. 

rights and duties. Inverting this order we have 
therefore to inquire what is a universitaa juris ; what 
is a universal succession ; what is the form of uni- 
versal succession which is called an inheritance. 
And there are also two further questions, independent 
to some extent of the points I have mooted, but 
demanding solution before the subject of Wills can 
be exhausted. These are, how came an inheritance 
to be controlled in any case by the testator's volition, 
and what is the nature of the instrument by which it 
came to be controlled? 

The first question relates to the universitas juris ; 
that is, a university (or bundle) of rights and duties. 
K universitas juris is a collection of rights and duties 
united by the single circumstance of their having 
belonged at one time to some one person. It is as it 
were, the legal clothing of some given individual. It 
is not formed by grouping together any rights and 
any duties. It can only be constituted by taking all 
the rights and all the duties of a particular person. 
The tie which so connects a number of rights of 
property, rights of way, rights to legacies, duties of 
specific performance, debts, obligations to compensate 
-wrongs — ^which so connects all these legal privileges 
and duties together as to constitute them a universitaa 
juris^ is the fact of their having attached to some 
individual capable of exercising them. Without this 
fact there is no university of rights and duties. The 



CHAP. VI. UNIVERSAL SUCCESSION. 179 

expression universitas juris is not classical, but for the 
notion jurisprudence is exclusively indebted to Roman 
law ; nor is it aU difficult to seize. We must endeavour 
to collect under one conception the whole set of legal 
relations in which each one of us stands to the rest 
of the world. These, whatever be their character and 
composition, make up together a universitas juris ; 
and there is but little danger of mistake in forming 
the notion, if we are only careful to remember that 
duties enter into it quite as much as rights. Our 
duties may overbalance our rights. A man may owe 
more than he is worth, and therefore if a money 
value is set on his collective legal relations he may 
be what is called insolvent. But for all that the 
entire group of rights and duties which centres in 
him is not the less a "juris universitas." 

We come next to a "universal succession." A 
universal succession is a succession to a universitas 
juris. It occurs when one man is iQvested with the 
legal clothing of another, becoming at the same 
moment subject to all his liabilities and entitled to all 
his rights. In order that the universal succession 
may be true and perfect, the devolution must take 
place uno ictu^ as the jurists phrase it. It is of 
course possible to conceive one man acquiring the 
whole of the rights and duties of another at different 
periods, as for example by successive purchases ; or 
he might acquire them in different capacities, part as 

H 2 



180 UNIVERSAL SUCCESSION. chap. vi. 

heir, part as purchaser, part as legatee. But though 
the group of rights and duties thus made up should 
in fact amount to the whole legal personality of a 
particular individual, the acquisition would not be a 
universal succession. In order that there may be a 
true universal succession, the transmission must be 
such as to pass the whole aggregate of rights and 
duties at the ^ame' moment and in virtue of the same 
legal capacity in the recipient. The notion of a 
universal succession, like that of a juris universitas, 
is permanent in jurisprudence, though in the English 
legal system it is obscured by the great variety of 
capacities in which rights are acquired, and, above 
all, by the distinction between the two great provinces 
of English property, "realty" and "personalty." 
The succession of an assignee in bankruptcy to the 
entire property of the bankrupt is, however, a uni- 
versal succession, though as the assignee only pays 
debts to the extent of the assets this is only a modified 
form of the primary notion. Were it common among 
us for persons to take assignments of cdl a man's 
property on condition of paying cUl his debts, such 
transfers would exactly resemble the universal suc- 
cessions known to the oldest Roman Law. When a 
Roman citizen adrogated a son, i. e. took a man, not 
already under Patria Potestas, as his adoptive child, 
he succeeded universally to the adoptive child's estate, 
i.e. he took all the property and became liable for all 



CHAP. VI. THE UNIVERSAL SUCCESSOR. 181 

the obligations. Several other forms of universal 
succession appear in the primitive Roman Law, but 
infinitely the most important and the most durable of 
all was that one with which we are more immediately 
concerned, Haareditas or Inheritance. Inheritance 
was a universal succession occurring at a death. 
The universal successor was Haeres or Heir. He 
stepped at once into all the rights and all the duties of 
the dead man. He was instantly clothed with his 
entire legal person, and I need scarcely add that the 
special character of the Hseres remained the same, 
whether he was named by a Will or whether he took 
on an Intestacy. The term HsBres is no more emphati- 
cally used of the Intestate than of the Testamentary 
Heir, for the manner in which a man became Haeres 
had nothing to do with the legal character he sus- 
tained. The dead man's universal successor, however 
he became so, whether by WiU or by Intestacy, was his 
Heir. But the Heir was not necessarily a single person. 
A group of persons considered in law as a single unit, 
might succeed as co-heirs to the Inheritance. 
• Let me now quote the usual Boman definition 
of an Inheritance. The reader will be in a posi- 
tion to appreciate the full force of the separate 
terms. Hcereditaa est successio in unix^ersum jus quod 
defunctus habuit ("an inheritance is a succession to 
the entire legal position of a deceased man "). The 
notion was that, though the physical person of the 

n 3 



18-2 THE HEIR. chap. vi. 

deceased had perished, his legal personality survived 
and descended unimpaired on his Heir or Co-heirs, 
in whom his identity (so far as the law was con- 
cerned) was continued. Our own law, in constitu- 
ting the Executor or Administrator the representative 
of the deceased to the extent of his personal assets, 
may serve as an illustration of the theory firom which 
it emanated, but, although it illustrates, it does not 
explain it. The view of even the later Roman Law 
required a closeness of correspondence between the 
position of the deceased and of his Heir which is no 
feature of an English representation; and in the 
primitive jurisprudence everything turned on the 
continuity of succession. Unless provision was made 
in the will for the instant devolution of the testator^s 
rights and duties on the Heir or Co-heirs, the testa- 
ment lost all its effect. 

In modem Testamentary jurisprudence, as in the 
later Roman law, the object of first importance is the 
execution of the testator's intentions. In the ancient 
law of Rome the subject of corresponding carefulness 
was the bestowal of the Universal Succession. One of 
these rules seems to our eyes a principle dictated by 
common sense, while the other looks very much like 
an idle crotchet. Yet that without the second of 
them the first would never have come into being is 
as certain as any proposition of the kind can be. 

In order to solve this apparent paradox, and to 



CHAF. Ti. PRIMITIVE SOCIETY. 183 

bring into greater clearness the train of ideas which 
I have been endeavouring to indicate, I must borrow 
the results of the inquiry which was attempted in the 
earlier portion of the preceding chapter. We saw 
one peculiarity invariably distinguishing the infancy 
of society. Men are regarded and treated, not as 
individuals, but always as members of a particular 
group. Everybody is first a citizen, and then, as a 
citizen, he is a member of his order — of an aristocracy 
or a democracy, of an order of patricians or plebeians ; 
or, in those societies which an unhappy fate has 
afflicted with a special perversion in their course of 
development, of a caste. Next, he is a member of a 
gens, house, or clan ; and lastly, he is a member of 
\n& family. This last was the narrowest and most 
personal relation in which he stood; nor, paradoxical 
as it may seem, was he ever regarded as himself as a 
distinct individual. His individuality was swallowed 
up in his family. I repeat the definition of a primi- 
tive society given before. It has for its units, not 
individuals, but groups of men united by the reality 
or the fiction of blood-relationship. 
. It is in the peculiarities of an undeveloped society 
that we seize the first trace of a universal succession. 
Contrasted with the organisation of a modem state, 
the commonwealths of primitive times may be fairly 
described as consisting of a number of little despotic 
governments, each perfectly distinct from the rest, 

N 4 



184 THE PRIMITIVE FAMILY. chap. vi. 

each absolutely controlled by the prerogative of a 
single monarch. But though the Patriarch, for we 
must not yet call him the Pater-familias, had rights 
thus extensive, it is impossible to doubt that he 
lay under an equal amplitude of obligations. If he 
governed the family, it was for its behoof. If he was 
lord of its possessions, he held them as trustee for his 
children and kindred. He had no privilege or position 
distinct from that conferred on him by his relation to 
the petty conmionwealth which he governed. The 
Family, in fact, was a Corporation; and he was its 
representative or, we might almost say, its Public 
officer. He enjoyed rights and stood under duties, 
but the rights and the duties were, in the contempla- 
tion of his fellow-citizens and in the eye of the law, 
quite as much those of the collective body as his own. 
Let us consider for a moment the effect which would 
be produced by the death of such a representative. 
In the eye of the law, in the view of the civU magis- 
trate, the demise of the domestic authority would be 
a perfectly immaterial event. The person represent- 
ing the collective body of the family and primarily 
responsible to mimicipal jurisdiction would bear a 
different name ; and that would be all. The rights 
and obligations which attached to the deceased head 
of the house would attach, without breach of con- 
tinuity, to his successor; for, in point of fact, they 
would be the rights and obligations of the family, and 



CHAP. VI. THE FAMILY A- COKPORATION. 185 

the family had the distinctive characteristic of a 
corporation — that it never died. Creditors would 
have the same remedies against the new chieftain as 
against the old, for the liability being that of the still 
existing family would be absolutely unchanged. All 
rights available to the family would be as available 
after the demise of the headship as before it — except 
that the Corporation would be obliged — if indeed 
language so precise and technical can be properly 
used of these early times — would be obliged to site 
under a slightly modified name. 

The history of jurisprudence must be followed in 
its whole course, if we are to understand how 
gradually and tardily society dissolved itself into the 
component atoms of which it is now constituted — by 
what insensible gradations the relation of man to man 
substituted itself for the relation of the individual to 
his family and of families to each other. The point 
now to be attended to is that even when the revolu- 
tion had apparently quite accomplished itself, even 
when the magistrate had in great measure assumed 
the place of the Pater-familias, and the civil tribunal 
substituted itself for the domestic forum, nevertheless 
the whole scheme of rights and duties administered 
by the judicial authorities remained shaped by the 
influence of the obsolete privileges and coloured in 
every part by their reflection. There seems little 
question that the devolution of the Universitas Juris, 



186 FAMILIES AND INDIVIDUALS. chap. vi. 

SO strenuously insisted upon by the Roman Law as 
the first condition of a testamentary or inteBtefee suc- 
cession, was a feature of the older form of society 
which men's minds had been unable to dissociate from 
the new, though with that newer phase it had no true 
or proper connection. It seems, in truth, that the pro- 
longation of a man's legal existence in his heir, or in 
a group of co-heirs, is neither more nor less than a cha- 
racteristic of the family transferred by a fiction to the 
individitaL Succession in corporations is necessarily 
universal, and the family was a corporation. Corpo- 
rations never die. The decease of individual members 
makes no difference to the collective existence of the 
aggregate body, and does not in any way affect its legal 
incidents, its faculties or liabilities. Now in the idea 
of a Roman universal succession all these qualities of 
a corporation seem to have been transferred to the 
individual citizen. His physical death is allowed to 
exercise no effect on the legal position which he filled, 
apparently on the principle that that position is to be 
adjusted as closely as possible to the analogies of a 
family, which, in its corporate character, was not of 
course liable to physical extinction. 

I observe that not a few continental jurists have 
much difficulty in comprehending the nature of the 
connection between the conceptions blended in a uni- 
versal succession, and there is perhaps no topic in the 
philosophy of jurisprudence on which their specula- 



CHAP, VI. CORPORATIONS SOLE. 187 

tions, as a general rule, possess so little valae. But 
the student of English law ought to be in no danger 
of Btumblmg at the analysis of the idea which we are 
examinmg. Much light is cast upon it by a fiction 
in our own system with which all lawyers are familiar. 
English lawyers classify corporations as Corporations 
aggregate and Corporations sole. A Corporation 
aggregate is a true Corporation, but a Corporation 
sole is an individual, being a member of a series of 
individuals, who is invested by a fiction with the 
qualities of a Corporation. I need hardly cite the 
King or the Parson of a Parish as instances of Cor- 
porations sole. The capacity or office is here consi- 
dered apart fi^om the particular person who from 
time to time may occupy it, and, this capacity being 
perpetual, the series of individuals who fill it are 
clothed with the leading attribute of Corporations — 
Perpetuity. Now in the older theory of Roman Law 
the individual bore to the family precisely the same 
relation which in the rationale of English jurispru- 
dence a Corporation sole bears to a Corporation 
aggregate. The derivation and association of ideas 
are exactly the same. In fact, if we say to ourselves 
that for purposes of Roman Testamentary Juris- 
prudence each individual citizen was a Corporation 
sole, we shall not only realise the full conception of 
an inheritance, but have constantly at command the 
clue to the assumption in which it originated. It is 



189 INTESTATE SUCCESSION, chap, vt- 

an axiom with us that the King never dies, being a 
Corporation sole. His capacities are instantly filled 
by his successor, and the continuity of dominion is 
not deemed to have been interrupted. With the 
Romans it seemed an equally simple and natural 
process, to eliminate the fact of death from the devo- 
lution of rights and obligations. The testator lived 
on in his heir or in the group of his co-heirs. He was 
in law the same person with them, and if any one in 
his testamentary dispositions had even constructively 
violated the principle which united his actual and his 
posthxunous existence, the law rejected the defective 
instrument, and gave the inheritance to the kindred 
in blood, whose capacity to fulfil the conditions of 
heirship was conferred on them by the law itself, and 
not by any document which by possibility might be 
erroneously framed. 

When a Roman citizen died intestate or leaving no 
valid Will, his descendants or kindred became his 
heirs according to a scale which will be presently 
described. The person or class of persons who suc- 
ceeded did not simply represent the deceased, but, in 
conformity with the theory just delineated, they con- 
tinued his civil life, his legal existence. The same 
results followed when the order of succession was 
determined by a Will, but the theory of the identity 
between the dead man and his heirs was certainly much 
older than any form of Testament or phase of Testa- 



CHAP. VI. OLD NOTION OF INHERITANCE. 189 

mentary jurisprudence. This indeed is the proper 
moment for suggesting a doubt which will press on 
us with greater force the further we plumb the depths 
of this subject, — whether wills would ever have come 
into being at all if it had not been for these remark- 
able ideas connected with universal succession. Tes- 
tamentary law is the application of a principle which 
may be explained on a variety of philosophical hy- 
potheses as plausible as they are gratuitous; it is 
interwoven with every part of modem society, and it 
is defensible on the broadest grounds of general 
expediency. But the warning can never be too often 
repeated, that the grand source of mistake in questions 
of jurisprudence is the impression that those reasons 
which actuate us at the present moment, in the main- 
tenance of an existing institution, have necessarily 
anything in common with the sentiment in which the 
institution originated. It is certain that, in the old 
Roman Law of Inheritance, the notion of a will or 
testament is inextricably mixed up, I might almost 
say confounded, with the theory of a man's posthu- 
mous existence in the person of his heir. 

The conception of a universal succession, firmly as 
it has taken root in jurisprudence, has not occurred 
spontaneously to the framers of every body of laws. 
Wherever it is now found, it may be shown to have 
descended from Roman law; and with it have come 
down a host of legal rules on the subject of Testa- 



190 SUCCESSION TO THE FAMILY. chap. vi. 

ments and Testamentary gifts, which modern practi- 
tioners apply without discerning their relation to the 
parent theory. But, in the pure Roman jurisprudence, 
the principle that a man lives on in his Heir — the 
elimination, if we may so speak, of the fact of death 
— is too obviously for mistake the centre round which 
the whole Law of Testamentary and Intestate suc- 
cession is circling. The unflinching sternness of the 
Roman law in enforcing compliance with the govern- 
ing theoiy would in itself suggest that the theory 
grew out of something in the primitive constitution 
of Roman society; but we may push the proof a good 
way beyond the presumption. It happens that several 
technical expressions, dating from the earliest insti- 
tution of Wills at Rome, have been accidentally pre- 
served to us. We have in Gains the formula of 
investiture by which the universal successor was 
created. We have the ancient name by which the 
person afterwards called Heir was at first designated. 
We have further the text of the celebrated clause in 
the Twelve Tables by which the Testamentary power 
was expressly recognised, and the clauses regulating 
Intestate Succession have also been preserved. All these 
archaic phrases have one salient peculiarity. They in- 
dicate that what passed from the Testator to the Heir 
was the Family^ that is, the aggregate of rights and 
duties contained in the Patria Potestas and growing 
out of it. The material property is in three instances 



CHAP. VI. ORIGINAL OBJECT OF WILLS. 191 

not mentioned at all ; in two others, it is visibly named 
as an adjunct or appendage of the Family. The 
original Will or Testament was therefore an instru- 
ment, or (for it was probably not at first in writing) 
a proceeding, by which the devolution of the Family 
was regulated. It was a mode of declaring who 
was to have the chieftainship, in succession to the 
Testator. When Wills are understood to have this 
for their original object, we see at once how it is 
that they came to be connected with one of the 
most curious relics of ancient religion and law, 
the sacra^ or Family Rites. These sacra were the 
Roman form of an institution which shows itself 
wherever society has not whoUy shaken itself free 
from its primitive clothing. They are the sacrifices 
and ceremonies by which the brotherhood of the 
family is commemorated, the pledge and the witness 
of its perpetuity. Whatever be their nature, — 
whether it be true or not that in all cases they are 
the worship of some mythical ancestor, — they are 
everywhere employed to attest the sacredness of the 
family-relation ; and therefore they acquire prominent 
significance and importance, whenever the continuous 
existence of the Family is endangered by a change in 
the person of its chief. Accordingly, we hear most 
about them in connection with demises of domestic 
sovereignty. Among the Hindoos, the right to in- 
herit a dead man's property is exactly co-extensive 



102 THE HINDOO SACRA. chap. vi. 

with the duty of performing his obsequies. If the 
rites are not property performed or not performed by 
the proper person, no relation is considered as es- 
tablished between the deceased and anybody surviving 
him; the Law of Succession does not apply, and 
nobody can inherit the property. Every great event 
in the life of a Hindoo seems to be regarded as 
leading up to and bearing upon these solemnities. 
If he marries, it is to have children who may celebrate 
them after his death ; if he has no children, he lies 
under the strongest obligation to adopt them from, 
another family, "with a view," writes the Hindoo 
doctor, "to the funeral cake, the water, and the 
solenm sacrifice." The sphere preserved to the Roman 
sacra in the time of Cicero, was not less in extent. 
It embraced Inheritances and Adoptions. No Adop- 
tion was allowed to take place without due provision 
for the sacra of the family from which the adoptive 
son was transferred, and no Testament was allowed to 
distribute an Inheritance without a strict apportion- 
ment of the expenses of these ceremonies among the 
diflFerent co-heirs. The differences between the Roman 
law at this epoch, when we obtain our last glimpse 
of the sacra^ and the existing Hindoo system, are 
most instructive. Among the Hindoos, the religious 
element in law has acquired a complete predominance. 
Family sacrifices have become the keystone of all the 
Law of Persons and much of the Law of Things. 



CHAP. VI. ROMAN AND HINDOO SACRA. J93 

They have even received a monstrous extension, for 
it is a plausible opinion that the self-immolation of the 
widow at her husband's funeral, a practice continued 
to historical times by the Hindoos, and commemorated 
in the traditions of several Indo-European races, 
was an addition grafted on the primitive sacra^ 
under the influence of the impression, which always 
accompanies the idea of sacrifice, that human blood is 
the most precious of all oblations. With the Romans, 
on the contrary, the legal obligation and the religious 
duty have ceased to be blended. The necessity of 
solemnising the sacra forms no part of the theory of 
civil law, but they are under the separate jurisdic- 
tion of the College of Pontiffs. The letters of 
Cicero to Atticus, which are full of allusions to them, 
leave no doubt that they constituted an intolerable 
burden on Inheritances; but the point of develop- 
ment at which law breaks away from religion has 
been passed, and we are prepared for their entire dis- 
appearance from the later jurisprudence. 

In Hindoo law there is no such thing as a true 
Will. The place filled by Wills is occupied by Adop- 
tions. We can now see the relation of the Testa- 
mentary Power to the Faculty of Adoption, and the 
reason why the exercise of either of them could call 
up a peculiar solicitude for the performance of the 
sacra. Both a Will and an Adoption threaten a dis- 
tortion of the ordinary course of Family descent, but 

o 



194 WILLS AND ADOmONS. chap. vi. 

they are obviously contrivances for preventing the 
descent being wholly interrupted, when there is 
no succession of kindred to carry it on. Of the 
two expedients Adoption, the factitious creation of 
blood-relationship, is the only one which has sug- 
gested itself to the greater part of archaic socie- 
ties. The Hindoos have indeed advanced one point 
on what was doubtless the antique practice, by allow- 
ing the widow to adopt when the father has neg- 
lected to do so, and there are in the local customs of 
Bengal some faint traces of the Testamentary powers. 
But to the Romans belongs pre-eminently the credit 
of inventing the Will, the institution which, next to 
the Contract, has exercised the greatest influence in 
transforming human society. We must be careful not 
to attribute to it in its earliest shape the functions 
which have attended it in more recent times. It 
was at first, not a mode of distributing a dead man's 
goods, but one among several ways of transferring 
the representation of the household to a new chief. 
The goods descend no doubt to the Heir, but that is 
only because the government of the family carries 
with it in its devolution the power of disposing of 
the common stock. We are very far as yet from 
that stage in the history of Wills in which they 
become powerful instruments in modifying society 
through the stimulus they give to the circulation 
of property and the plasticity they produce in pro- 



CHAP. VI. ROMAN IDEAS OF SUCCESSION. 195 

prietary rights. No such consequences as these ap- 
pear in fact to have been associated with the Testa- 
mentary power even by the latest Roman lawyers. 
It will be found that Wills were never looked upon 
in the Roman community as a contrivance for part- 
ing Property and the Family, or for creating a 
variety of miscellaneous interests, but rather as a 
means of making a better provision for the members 
of a household than could be secured through the 
rules of Intestate succession. We may suspect in- 
deed that the associations of a Roman with the 
practice of will-making were extremely different 
from those familiar to us nowadays. The habit of 
regarding Adoption and Testation as modes of con- 
tinuing the Family cannot but have had something 
to do with the singular laxity of Roman notions as 
to the inheritance of sovereignty. It is impossible 
not to see that the succession of the early Roman 
Emperors to each other was considered reasonably 
regular, and that, in spite of all that had occurred, 
no absurdity attached to the pretension of such 
Princes as Theodosius or Justinian to style them- 
selves Csesar and Augustus. 

When the phenomena of primitive societies emerge 
into light, it seems impossible to. dispute a propo- 
sition which the jurists of the 17th century con- 
sidered doubtful, that Intestate Inheritance is a more 
ancient institution than Testamentary Succession. 

o 2 



196 RARITY OP TESTAMENTARY POWER, chap, vi. 

As soon as this is settled, a question of much in- 
terest suggests itself, how and under what conditions 
were the directions of a will first allowed to regulate 
the devolution of authority over the household^ and 
consequently the posthumous distribution of pro- 
perty. The difficulty of deciding the point arises 
from the rarity of Testamentary power in archaic 
communities. It is doubtftd whether a true power 
of testation was known to any original society except 
the Roman. Rudimentary forms of it occur here 
and there, but most of them are not exempt from 
the suspicion of a Roman origin. The Athenian 
wiU was, no doubt, indigenous, but then, as will 
appear presently, it was only an inchoate Testament. 
As to the Wills which are sanctioned by the bodies of 
law which have descended to us as the codes of the 
barbarian conquerors of Imperial Rome, they are 
almost certainly Roman. The most penetrating Ger- 
man criticism has recently been directed to these 
leges Barharorum^ the great object of investigation 
being to detach those portions of each system which 
formed the customs of the tribe in its original home 
from the adventitious ingredients which were bor- 
rowed from the laws of the Romans. In the course 
of this process, one result has invariably disclosed 
itself, that the ancient nucleus of the code contains 
no trace of a Will. Whatever testamentary law 
exists, has been taken from Roman jurisprudence. 



CHAP. Yi. PRIMITIVE OPERATION OP WILLS. 197 

Similarly, the rudimentary Testament which (as I 
am informed) the Rabbinical Jewish law provides 
for, has been attributed to contact with the Romans. 
The only form of testament, not belonging to a Ro- 
man or Hellenic society, which can reasonably be 
supposed indigenous, is that recognised by the usages 
of the province of Bengal; and the testament of 
Bengal is only a rudimentary Will. 

The evidence, however, such as it is, seems to 
point to the conclusion that Testaments are at first 
only allowed to take effect on failure of the persons 
entitled to have the inheritance by right of blood 
genuine or fictitious. Thus, when Athenian citizens 
were empowered for the first time by the Laws of 
Solon to execute Testaments, they were forbidden to 
disinherit their direct male descendants. So too, 
the Will of Bengal is only permitted to govern 
the succession so far as it is consistent with certain 
overriding claims of the family. Again, the original 
institutions of the Jews having provided nowhere 
for the privileges of Testatorship, the later Rabbini- 
cal jurisprudence, which pretends to supply the casus 
omissi of the Mosaic law, allows the Power of Testa- 
tion to attach when all the kindred entitled under 
the Mosaic system to succeed have failed or are 
undiscoverable. The limitations by which the ancient 
German codes hedge in the testamentary jurispru- 
dence which has been incorporated with them are 

o 3 



1S8 OLD GERMANIC WILLS. chap. vi. 

also Significant, and point in the same direction. It 
is the peculiarity of most of these German laws, in the 
only shape in which we know them, that, besides the 
allod or domain of each household, they recognise 
several subordinate kinds or orders of property, each 
of which probably represents a separate transfusion 
of Roman principles into the primitive body of 
Teutonic usage. The primitive German or allodial 
property is strictly reserved to the kindred. Not 
only is it incapable of being disposed of by testa- 
ment but it is scarcely capable of being alienated 
by conveyance inter vivos. The ancient German 
law, like the Hindoo jurisprudence, makes the male 
children co-proprietors with their father, and the 
endowment of the family cannot be •parted with 
except by the consent of all its members. But the 
other sorts of property, of more modem origin and 
lower dignity than the allodial possessions, are 
much more easily alienated than they, and follow 
much more lenient rules of devolution. Women and 
the descendants of women succeed to them, obviously 
on the principle that they lie outside the sacred pre- 
cinct of the Agnatic brotherhood. Now, it is on 
these last descriptions of property, and on these 
only, that the Testaments borrowed from Rome were 
at first allowed to operate. 

These few indications may serve to lend additional 
plausibility to that which in itself appears to be the 



CHAP. yi. THE COMITIA CALATA. 199 

most probable explanation of an ascertained fact in 
the early history of Roman Wills. We have it stated 
on abundant authority that Testaments, during the 
primitive period of the Roman State, were executed 
in the Comiti^ Calata, that is, in the Comitia Curiata, 
or Parliament of the Patrician Burghers of Rome, 
when assembled for Private Business. This mode 
of execution has been the source of the assertion, 
handed down by one generation of civilians to an- 
other, that every WiU at one era of Roman history 
was a solemn legislative enactment. But there is 
no necessity whatever for resorting to an explanation 
which has the defect of attributing far too much 
precision to the proceedings of the ancient assembly. 
The proper key to the story concerning the execu- 
tion of WiUs in the Comitia Calata must no doubt 
be sought in the oldest Roman Law of intestate 
succession. The canons of prhnitive Roman juris- 
prudence regulating the inheritance of relations from 
each other were, so long as they remained unmodified 
by the Edictal Law of the PraBtor, to the following 
effect : — First, the sui or direct descendants who had 
never been emancipated succeeded. On the failure 
of the fim, the Nearest Agnate came into their place, 
that is, the nearest person or class of the kindred 
who was or might have been under the same Patria 
Potestas with the deceased. The third and last de- 
gree came next, in which the inheritance devolved 

o 4 



200 JURISDICTION OF THE COMITIA. chap. yi. 

on the gentiles that is on the collective members of 
the dead man's gens or House. The House, I have 
explained already, was a fictitious extension of the 
family, consisting of all Roman Patrician citizens 
who bore the same name, and who, on the ground of 
bearing the same name, were supposed to be de- 
scended from a common ancestor. Now the Patri- 
cian Assembly called the Comitia Curiata was a 
Legislature in which Gentes or Houses were exclu- 
sively represented. It was a representative assembly 
of the Roman people, constituted on the assumption 
that the constituent unit of the state was the Gens. 
This being so, the inference seems inevitable, that the 
cognizance of Wills by the Comitia was connected 
with the rights of the Gentiles, and was intended to 
secure them in their privilege of ultimate inherit- 
ance. The whole apparent anomaly is removed, if 
we suppose that a Testament could only be made 
when the testator had no gentiles discoverable, or 
when they waived their claims, and that every 
Testament was submitted to the General Assembly 
of the Roman Gentes, in order that those aggrieved 
by its dispositions might put their veto upon it if 
they pleased, or by allowing it to pass might be 
presumed to have renounced their reversion. It is 
possible that on the eve of the publication of the 
Twelve Tables this vetoing power may have been 
greatly curtailed or only occasionally and capriciously 



CHAP. Ti. PLEBEIAN WILLS. 201 

exercised. It is much easier, however, to indicate 
the meamng and origin of the jurisdiction confided 
to the Comitia Calata, than to trace its gradual de- 
velopment or progressive decay. 

The Testament to which the pedigree of all modem 
Wills may be traced is not, however, the Testament 
executed in the Calata Comitia, but another Testa- 
ment designed to compete with it and destined to 
supersede it. The historical importance of this 
early Roman Will, and the light it casts on much 
of ancient thought, will excuse me for describing it 
at some length. 

When the Testamentary power first discloses itself 
to us in legal history, there are signs that, like 
ahnost all the great Roman institutions, it was 
the subject of contention between the Patricians 
and the Plebeians. The effect of the political 
maxim, Plehs Gentem non habet, " a Plebeian 
cannot be a member of a House," was entirely to 
exclude the Plebeians from the Comitia Curiata. 
Some critics have accordingly supposed that a 
Plebeian could not have his Will read or recited 
to the Patrician Assembly, and was thus deprived 
of Testamentary privileges altogether. Others have 
been satisfied to point out the hardships of having 
to submit a proposed Will to the unfriendly juris- 
diction of an assembly in which the Testator was not 
represented. Whatever be the true view, a form 



202 THE PLEBEIAN WILL. chap. vi. 

of Testament came into use, which has all the cha- 
racteristics of a contrivance intended to evade some 
distasteful obligation. The Will in question was a 
conveyance inter vivosy a complete and irrevocable 
alienation of the Testator's family and substance to 
the person whom he meant to be his heir. The 
strict rules of Roman law must always have per- 
mitted such an alienation, but, when the transaction 
was intended to have a posthumous effect, there may 
have been disputes whether it was valid for Testa- 
mentary purposes without the formal assent of the 
Patrician Pariiament. If a difference of opinion 
existed on the point between the two classes of the 
Roman population, it was extinguished, with many 
other sources of heartburning, by the great Decem- 
viral compromise. The text of the Twelve Tables 
is still extant which says, " Pater familias uti de 
pecunid tuteldve ret suce legdssit^ ita jus esto — a law 
which can hardly have had any other object than the 
legalisation of the Plebeian Will. 

It is weU known to scholars that, centuries after 
the Patrician Assembly had ceased to be the legis- 
lature of the Roman State, it still continued to hold 
formal sittings for the convenience of private busi- 
ness. Consequently, at a period long subsequent 
to the publication of the Decemviral Law, there is 
reason to believe that the Comitia Calata still as- 
sembled for the validation of Testaments. Its pro- 



CHAP. VI. END OF THE COMITIA CALATA. 208 

bable fiinctions may be best indicated by 8a3dng 
that it was a Court of Registration, with the under- 
standing however that the Wills exhibited were not 
enrolled^ but simply recited to the members, who 
were supposed to take note of their tenor and to 
commit them to memory. It is very likely that 
this form of Testament was never reduced to writing 
at all, but at all events if the WiU had been ori- 
ginally written, the office of the Comitia was cer- 
tainly confined to hearing it read aloud, the docu- 
ment being retained afterwards in the custody of 
the Testator, or deposited under the safeguard of. 
some religious corporation. This publicity may have 
been one of the incidents of the Testament executed 
in the Comitia Calata which brought it into popular 
disfavour. In the early years of the Empire the 
Comitia stiU held its meetings, but they seem to 
have lapsed into the merest form, and few Wills, or 
none, were probably presented at the periodical 
sitting. 

It is the ancient Plebeian Will — the alternative of 
the Testament just described — which in its remote 
effects has deeply modified the civilisation of the 
modem world. It acquired at Rome all the popu- 
larity which the Testament submitted to the Calata 
Comitia appears to have lost. The key to all its 
characteristics lies in its descent from the mancipium^ 
or ancient Roman conveyance, a proceeding to 



204 THE MANCIPATION. chap. vi. 

which we may unhesitatingly assign the parentage 
of two great institutions without which modem 
society can scarcely be supposed capable of holding 
together, the Contract and the Will. The m andpiunij 
or as the word would exhibit itself in later Latinity, 
the Mancipation, carries us back by its incidents 
to the infancy of civU society. As it sprang from 
times long anterior, if not to the invention, at all 
events to the popularisation, of the art of writing, 
gestures, symbolical acts, and solemn phrases take 
the place of documentary forms, and a lengthy and 
. intricate ceremonial is intended to caU the atten- 
tion of the parties to the importance of the trans- 
action, and to impress it on the memory of the wit- 
nesses. The imperfection too of oral, as compared 
with written, testimony necessitates the multipli- 
cation of the witnesses and assistants beyond what 
in later times would be reasonable or intelligible 
limits. 

The Roman Mancipation required the presence 
first of all of the parties, the vendor and vendee, 
or we should perhaps rather say, if we are to use 
modern legal language, the grantor and grantee. 
There were also no less than Jive witnesses; and an 
anomalous personage, the Libripens, who brought 
with him a pair of scales to weigh the uncoined copper 
money of ancient Rome. The Testament we are 
considering — the Testament per ces et libram^ " with 



CHAP. vi. WILL WITH COPPER AND SCALES. 205 

the copper and the scales," as it loDg continued to 
be technically called — was an ordinary Mancipa- 
tion with no change in the form and hardly any in 
words. The Testator was the grantor j the five 
witnesses and the libripens were present; and the 
place of grantee was taken by a person known 
technically as the familicB emptor^ the Purchaser 
of the Family. The ordinary ceremony of a Man- 
cipation was then proceeded with. Certain formal 
gestures were made and sentences pronounced. The 
Emptor familicB simulated the payment of a price 
by striking the scales with a piece of money, and 
finally the Testator ratified what had been done 
in a set form of words called the " Nuncupatio " or 
publication of the transaction, a phrase which, I 
need scarcely remind the lawyer, has had a long 
history in Testamentary jurisprudence. It is ne- 
cessary to attend particularly to the character of 
the person called familice emptor. There is no' 
doubt that at first he was the Heir hinaself. The 
Testator conveyed to him outright his whole / 

" familia," that is, all the ^hts he enjoyed n^ I ^ 
over and through the family; his property, his 
slaves, and all his ancestral privileges, together 

on the other hand with all his duties and obliga- 
tions. 

With these data before us, we are able to note 
several remarkable points in which the Mancipatory 



200 MANCIPATORY WILLS. chap. vi. 

Testament, as it may be called, differed in its primi- 
tive form from a modem will. As it amounted to a 
conveyance out-and-out of the Testator's estate, it 
was not revocable. There could be no new exercise 
of a power which had been exhausted. 

Again, it was not secret. The Familiae Emptor, 
being himself the Heir, knew exactly what his 
rights were, and was aware that he was irreversibly 
entitled to the inheritance ; a knowledge which the 
violences inseparable from the best-ordered ancient 
society rendered extremely dangerous. But perhaps 
the most surprising consequence of this relation of 
Testaments to Conveyances was the immediate vesting 
of the inheritance in the Heir. This has seemed so 
incredible to not a few civilians, that they have spoken 
of the Testator's estate as vesting conditionally on 
the Testator's death, or as granted to him from a 
time uncertain, i. e. the death of the grantor. But 
down to the latest period of Roman jurisprudence 
there were a certain class of transactions which never 
admitted of being directly modified by a condition, 
or of being limited to or from a point of time. In 
technical language they did not admit conditio or dies. 
Mancipation was one of them, and therefore, strange 
as it may seem, we are forced to conclude that the 
primitive Roman Will took effect at once, even 
though the Testator survived his act of Testation. 
It is indeed likely that Roman citizens originally 



CHAP. VI. ANCIENT WILLS NOT WRITTEN. 207 

made their Wills only in the article of death, and that 
a provision for the continuance of the Family effected 
by a man in the flower of life would take the form 
rather of an Adoption than of a Will. Still we must 
believe that, if the Testator did recover, he could only 
continue to govern his household by the sufferance of 
his Heir. 

Two or three remarks should be made before I ex- 
plain how these inconveniences were remedied, and 
how Testaments came to be invested with the charac- 
teristics now universally associated with them. The 
Testament was not necessarily written: at first, it 
seems to have been invariably oral, and, even in later 
times, the instrument declaratory of the bequests was 
only incidentally connected with the Will and formed 
no essential part of it. It bore in fact exactly the 
same relation to the Testament, which the deed lead- 
ing the uses bore to the Fines and Recoveries of old 
English law, or which the charter of feofiinent bore 
to the feoffment itself. Previously, indeed, to the 
Twelve Tables, no writing would have been of the 
slightest use, for the Testator had no power of giving 
legacies, and the only persons who could be advan- 
taged by a will were the Heir or Co-heirs. But the 
extreme generality of the clause in the Twelve Tables 
soon produced the doctrine that the Heir must take 
the inheritance burdened by any directions which the 
Testator might give him, or, in other words, take it 



208 THE PURCHASER OF THE FAMILY. chap. vt. 

subject to legacies. Written testamentary instru- 
ments assumed thereupon a new value, as a security 
against Ihe fraudulent refusal of the heir to satisfy 
the legatees; but to the last it was at the Testator's 
pleasure to rely exclusively on the testimony of the 
witnesses, and to declare by word of mouth the 
legacies which the familice emptor was commissioned 
to pay. 

The terms of the expression Emptor familice demand 
notice. " Emptor" indicates that the Will was literally 
a sale, and the word " familise," when compared with 
the phraseology in the Testamentary clause in the 
Twelve Tables, leads us to some instructive conclu- 
sions. " Familia," in classical Latinity, means always 
a man's slaves. Here, however, and generally in the 
language of ancient Roman law, it includes all per- 
sons under his Potestas, and the Testator's material 
property or substance is understood to pass as an 
adjunct or appendage of his household. Turning to 
the law of the Twelve Tables, it will be seen that it 
speaks of tutela rei auce^ *' the guardianship of his sub- 
stance," a form of expression which is the exact reverse 
of the phrase just examined. There does not therefore 
appear to be any mode of escaping from the conclu- 
sion, that, even at an era so comparatively recent as 
that of the Decemviral compromise, terms denoting 
"household" and *' property" were blended in the 
current phraseology. If a man's household had been 



CHAP. VI. THE PR^TORIAN WILL. 209 

spoken of as his property we might have explained 
the expression as pointing to the extent of the Patria 
Potestas, but, as the interchange is reciprocal, we 
must allow that the form of speech carries us back to 
that primeval period in which property is owned by 
the family, and the family is governed by the citizen, 
so that the members of the community do not own 
their property and their family, but rather own their 
property through their family. 

At an epoch not easy to settle with precision, the 
Roman Praetors fell into the habit of acting upon 
Testaments solemnised in closer conformity with the 
spirit than the letter of the law. Casual dispensations 
became insensibly the established practice, till at 
length a wholly new form of Will was matured and 
regularly engrafted on the Edictal Jurisprudence. 
The new or PrcBtorian Testament derived the whole 
of its impregnability from the Jtis Honorarium or 
Equity of Rome. The Praetor of some particular 
year must have inserted a clause in his Inaugural 
Proclamation declaratory of his intention to sustain 
all Testaments which should have been executed with 
such and such solemnities; and, the reform having 
been found advantageous, the article relating to it 
must have been again introduced by the Praetor's 
successor, and repeated by the next in office, till at 
length it formed a recognised portion of that body of 
jurisprudence which from these successive incorpora- 

p 



210 THE PRJETORIAN WILL. chaf. tx, 

tions was styled the Perpetual or Continuous Edict. 
On examining the conditions of a valid Praetorian 
Will they will be plainly seen to have been deter- 
mined by the requirements of the Mancipatory Tes- 
tament, the innovating Praetor having obviously pre- 
scribed to himself the retention of the old formalities 
just so far as they were warrants of genuineness or 
securities against fraud. At the execution of the 
Mancipatory Testament seven persons had been pre- 
sent besides the Testator. Seven witnesses were 
accordingly essential to the Praetorian Will: two of 
them corresponding to the libripens and famUice 
emptor^ who were now stripped of their symbolical 
character, and were merely present for the purpose of 
supplying their testimony. No emblematic ceremony 
was gone through; the WiU was merely recited; but 
then it is probable (though not absolutely certain) 
that a written instrument was necessary to perpetuate 
the evidence of the Testator's dispositions. At all 
events, whenever a writing was read or exhibited as a 
person's last Will, we know certainly that the Praeto- 
rian Court would not sustain it by special intervention, 
unless each of the seven witnesses had severally affixed 
his seal to the outside. This is the first appearance 
of sealing in the history of jurisprudence, considered 
as a mode of authentication. It is to be observed 
that the seals of Roman Wills, and other documents of 
importance, did not simply serve as the index of the 



CHAP. VI. THE BONORUM POSSESSIO. 2U 

presence or assent of the signatary, but were literally 
fastenings which had to be broken before the writing 
could be inspected. 

The Edictal Law would therefore enforce the dispo- 
sitions of a Testator, when, instead of being symbo- 
lised through the forms of mancipation, they were 
simply evidenced by the seals of seven witnesses. 
But it may be laid down as a general proposition, that 
the principal qualities of Roman property were in- 
communicable except through processes which were 
supposed to be coeval with the origin of the Civil Law. 
The Praetor therefore could not confer an Inheritance 
on anybody. He could not place the Heir or Co-heirs 
in that very relation in which the Testator had him- 
self stood to his own rights and obligations. All he 
could do was to confer on the person designated as 
Heir the practical enjoyment of the property be- 
queathed, and to give the force of legal acquit- 
tances to his payments of the Testator's debts. 
When he exerted his powers to these ends, the 
Praetor was technically said to communicate the 
Bonorum Possessio. The Heir specially inducted 
under these circumstances, or Bonorum Possessor^ 
had every proprietary privilege of the Heir by the 
Civil Law. He took the profits and he could alienate, 
but then, for all his remedies for redress against 
wrong, he must go, as we should phrase it, not to the 
Common Law, but to the Equity side of the Praetorian 

p 2 



212 IMPROVEMENTS IN THE OLD WILL. chap, ti. 

Court. No great chance of error would be incurred 
by describing him as having an equitable estate in the 
inheritance; but then, to secure ourselves against 
being deluded by the analogy, we must always recol- 
lect that in one year the Bonorum Possessio was 
operated upon a principle of Roman Law known as 
Usucapion, and the Possessor became Quiritarian 
owner of all the property comprised in the in- 
heritance. 

We know too little of the older law of Civil Pro- 
cess to be able to strike the balance of advantage 
and disadvantage between the different classes of 
remedies supplied by the Praetorian Tribunal. It is 
certain, however, that, in spite of its many defects, the 
Mancipatory Testament by which the universitas juris 
devolved at once and unimpaired was never entirely 
superseded by the new Will; and at a period less 
bigoted to antiquarian forms, and perhaps not quite 
alive to their significance, all the ingenuity of the 
Jurisconsults seems to have been expended on the 
improvement of the more venerable instrument. At 
the era, of Gains, which is that of the Antonine Caesars, 
the great blemishes of the Mancipatory Will had been 
removed. Originally, as we have seen, the essential 
character of the formalities had required that the 
Heir himself should be the Purchaser of the Family, 
and the consequence was that he not only instantly 
acquired a vested interest in the Testator's Property, 



CHAP. VI. IMTROVEMENTS IN THE OLD WILL^ 2ia 

but was formally made aware of his rights. But the 
age of Gaius permitted some unconcerned person to 
oflB.ciate as Purchaser of the Family. The Heir, 
therefore, was not necessarily informed of the succes- 
sion to which he was destined; and Wills thence- 
forward acquired the property of secrecy. The sub- 
stitution of a stranger for the actual Heir in the 
functions of "Familiae Emptor" had other ulterior 
consequences. As soon as it was legalised, a Roman 
Testament came to consist of two parts or stages, — a 
Conveyance, which was a pure form, and a Nuncu- 
patio, or Publication. In this latter passage of the 
proceeding, the Testator either orally declared to the 
assistants the wishes which were to be executed after 
his death, or produced a written document in which 
his wishes were embodied. It was not probably till 
attention had been quite drawn off from the imaginary 
Conveyance, and concentrated on the Nuncupation 
as the essential part of the transaction, that Wills 
were allowed to become revocable. 

1 have thus carried the pedigree of Wills some 
way down in legal history The root of it is the 
old Testament "with the copper and the scales,** 
founded on a Mancipation or Conveyance. This 
ancient Will has, however, manifold defects, which are 
remedied, though only indirectly, by the Prgetorian 
law. Meantime the ingenuity of the Jurisconsults 
effects, in the Common-Law WiU or Mancipatory 

p 3 



214 THE ROMAN WILL. chap. vi. 

Testament, the very improvements which the Praetor 
may have concurrently carried out in Equity. These 
last ameliorations depend, however, on mere legal dex- 
terity, and we see accordingly that the Testamentary 
Law of the day of Gains or Ulpian is only transi- 
tional. What changes next ensued we know not; 
but at length just before the reconstruction of the 
jurisprudence by Justinian, we find the subjects of 
the Eastern Roman Empire emplojdng a form of Will 
of which the pedigree is traceable to the Praetorian 
Testament on one side, and to the Testament " with 
the copper and the scales" on the other. Like the 
Testament of the Praetor, it required no Mancipa- 
tion, and was invalid unless sealed by seven witnesses. 
Like the Mancipatory Will, it passed the Inheritance 
and not merely a Bonorum Possessio. Several, how- 
ever, of its most important features were annexed by 
positive enactments, and it is out of regard to this 
threefold derivation from the Praetorian Edict, from 
the Civil Law, and from the Imperial Constitutions, 
that Justinian speaks of the Law of Wills in his own 
day as Ju^ Tripertitum. The new Testament thus 
described is the one generally known as the Roman 
Will. But it was the Will of the Eastern Empire 
only ; and the researches of Savigny have shown that 
in Western Europe the old Mancipatory Testament, 
with aU its apparatus of conveyance, copper, and 
scales, continued to be the form in use far down in 
the Middle Ages. 



cuAP. vu. DISINUESISOX OF CUILDREN. 215 



CHAP. VIL 

ANCIENT AND MODERN IDEAS RESPECTING WILLS AND 
SUCCESSIONS. 

Although there is much in the modem European 
Law of Wills which is intimately connected with the 
oldest rules of Testamentary disposition practised 
among men, there are nevertheless some important 
differences between ancient and modem ideas on the 
subject of Wills and Successions. Some of the points 
of difference I shall endeai^ur to illustrate in this 
chapter. 

At a period, removed several centuries from the era 
of the Twelve Tables, we find a variety of rules en- 
grafted on the Roman Civil Law with the view of 
limiting the disinherison of children; we have the ju- 
risdiction of the Praetor very actively exerted in the 
same interest; and we are also presented with a new 
remedy, very anomalous in character and of uncer- 
tain origin, called the Querela Inofficiosi Testament!, 
" the Plaint of an Unduteous Will," directed to the 
reinstatement of the issue in inheritances from which 
they had been unjustifiably excluded by a father's 
Testament. Comparing this condition of the law 

p 4 



216 DISINHERISON OF CHILDREN. chap. vu. 

with the text of the Twelve Tables which concedes 
in terms the utmost liberty of Testation, several 
writers have been tempted to interweave a good deal 
of dramatic incident into their history of the Law 
Testamentary. They tell us of the boundless 
license of disinherison in which the heads of families 
instantly began to indulge, of the scandal and injury 
to public morals which the new practices engendered, 
and of the applause of all good men which hailed 
the courage of the Praetor in arresting the progress 
of paternal depravity. This story, which is not 
without some foundation for the principal fact it 
relates, is often so told as to disclose very serious 
misconceptions of the principles of legal history, 
The Law of the Twelve^Tables is to be explained by 
the character of the age in which it was enacted. 
It does not license a tendency which a later era 
thought itself bound to counteract, but it proceeds 
on the assumption that no such tendency exists, or, 
perhaps we should say, in ignorance of the possi- 
bility of its existence. There is no likelihood that 
Roman citizens began immediately to avail them- 
selves freely of the power to disinherit. It is 
against all reason and sound appreciation of history 
to suppose that the yoke of family bondage, still 
patiently submitted to, as we know, where its pres- 
sure galled most cruelly, would be cast off in the 
very particular in which its incidence in our own 



CHAP. vn. DISINHERISON OF CHILDREN 217 

day is not otherwise than welcome. The Law of 
the Twelve Tables permitted the execution of Testa- 
ments in the only case in which it was thought 
possible that they could be executed, viz. on failure 
of children and proximate kindred. It did not 
forbid the disinherison of direct descendants, inas- 
much as it did not legislate against a contingency 
which no Roman lawgiver of that era could have con- 
templated. No doubt, as the offices of family aflPec- 
tion progressively lost the aspect of primary personal 
duties, the disinherison of children was occasionally 
attempted. But the interference of the Praetor, so 
far from being called for by the universality of the 
abuse, was doubtless first prompted by the fact that 
such instances of unnatural caprice were few and 
exceptional, and at conflict with the current mo- 
rality. 

The indications furnished by this part of Roman 
Testamentary Law are of a very diffisrent kind. It 
is remarkable that a Will never seems to have been 
regarded by the Romans as a means of disinheriting 
a Family, or of effecting the unequal distribution of 
a patrimony. The rules of law preventing its being 
turned to such a purpose, increase in number and 
stringency as the jurisprudence unfolds itself; and 
these rules correspond doubtless with the abiding 
sentiment of Roman society, as distinguished from 
occasional variations of feeling in individuals. It 



218 FEELING RESPECTING INTESTACY. chap. vu. 

would rather seem as if the Testamentary Power 
were chiefly valued for the assistance it gave in 
making provision for a Family, and in dividing the 
inheritance more evenly and fairly than the Law of 
Intestate Succession would have divided it. H this 
be the true reading of the general sentiment on the 
point, it explains to some extent the singular horror 
of Intestacy which always characterised the Roman. 
No evil seems to have been considered a heavier 
visitation than the forfeiture of Testamentary pri- 
vileges; no curse appears to have been bitterer than 
that which imprecated on an enemy that he might 
die without a Will. The feeling has no counterpart, 
or none tha;^ is easily recognisable, in the forms of 
opinion which exist at the present day. All men at 
all times will doubtless prefer chalking out the desti- 
nation of their substance to having that oflBice per- 
formed for them by the law; but the Roman passion 
for Testacy is distinguished from the mere desire 
to indulge caprice by its intensity; and it has of 
course nothing whatever in common with that 
pride of family, exclusively the creation of feudal- 
ism, which accumulates one description of property 
in the hands of a single representative. It is pro- 
bable, h priori^ that it was something in the rules of 
Intestate Succession which caused this vehement pre- 
ference for the distribution of property under a Testa- 
ment over its distribution by law. The difficulty, 



CHAP. VII. ROMAN INTESTATE SUCCESSION. 219 

however, is, that on glancing at the Roman law of In- 
testate Succession, in the form which it wore for 
many centuries before Justinian shaped it into that 
scheme of inheritance which has been almost univer- 
sally adopted by modem lawgivers, it by no means 
strikes one as remarkably unreasonable or inequitable. 
On the contrary, the distribution it prescribes is so 
fair and rational, and differs so little from that with 
which modem society has been generally contented, 
that no reason suggests itself why it should have 
been regarded with extraordinary distaste, especially 
under a jurisprudence which pared down to a 
narrow compass the testamentary privileges of per- 
sons who had children to provide for. We should 
rather have expected that, as in France at this mo- 
ment, the heads of families would generally save 
themselves the trouble of executing a WiU, and allow 
the Law to do as it pleased with their assets. I 
think, however, if we look a little closely at the pre- 
Justinianean scale oC Intestate Succession, we shall 
discover tlie key to the mystery. The texture of the 
law consists of two distinct parts. One department 
of rules comes from the Jus Civile, the Common-Law 
of Rome; the other from the Edict of the PrsBtor. 
The Civil Law, as I have already stated for another 
purpose, calls to the inheritance only three orders of 
successors in their turn ; the Unemancipated children, 
the nearest class of Agnatic kindred, and the Gentiles. 



220 ANCIENT INTESTATE SUCCESSION. chap. yii. 

Between these three orders, the Praator interpolates 
various classes of relatives, of whom the Civil Law 
took no notice whatever. Ultimately, the combination 
of the Edict and of the Civil Law forms a table of 
succession not materially different from that which 
has descended to the generality of modern codes. 

The point for recollection is that there must an- 
ciently have been a time at which the rules of the 
Civil Law determined the scheme of Intestate Suc- 
cession exclusively, and at which the arrangements 
of the Edict were non-existent, or not consistently 
carried out. We cannot doubt that, in its infancy, 
the Praetorian jurisprudence had to contend with 
formidable obstructions, and it is more than probable 
that, long after popular sentiment and legal opinion 
had acquiesced in it, the modifications which it 
periodically introduced were governed by no certain 
principles, and fluctuated with the varying bias of 
successive magistrates. The rules of Intestate Suc- 
cession, which the Romans must at this period have 
practised, account, I think — and more than account 
— for that vehement distaste for an Intestacy to 
which Roman society during so many ages remained 
constant. The order of succession was this : on the 
death of a citizen, having no will or no valid will, his 
XJnemancipated children became his Heirs. His 
emancipated sons had no share in the inheritance. 
If he left no direct descendants living at his death, 



CHAP. VII. ANCIENT INTESTATE SUCCESSION. 221 

the nearest grade of the Agnatic kindred succeeded, 
but no part of the inheritance was given to any rela- 
tive united (however closely) with the dead man 
through female descents. All the other branches of 
the family were excluded, and the inheritance es- 
cheated to the Gentiles^ or entire body of Roman 
citizens bearing the same name with the deceased. 
So that on failing to execute an operative Testament, 
a Roman of the era under examination left his eman- 
cipated children absolutely without provision, while, 
on the assumption that he died childless, there was 
imminent risk that his possessions would escape from 
the family altogether, and devolve on a number of 
persons with whom he was merely connected by the 
sacerdotal fiction that assumed all members of the 
same gens to be descended from a common ancestor. 
The prospect of such an issue is in itself a nearly 
sufficient explanation of the popular sentiment; but, 
in point of fact, we shall only half understand it, if 
we forget that the state of things I have been de- 
scribing is likely to have existed at the very moment 
when Roman society was in the first stage of its 
transition from its primitive organisation in detached 
families. The empire of the father had indeed re- 
ceived one of the earliest blows directed at it through 
the recognition of Emancipation as a legitimate 
usage, but the law, still considering the Patria 
Potestas to be the root of family connection, perse- 



222 FEELING RESPECTING INTESTACT. chap. th. 

vered in looking on the emancipated children as 
strangers to the rights of Kinship and aliens from 
the blood. We cannot, however, for a moment sup- 
pose that the limitations of the family imposed by 
legal pedantry had their counterpart in the natural 
affection of parents. Family attachments must still 
have retained that nearly inconceivable sanctity and 
intensity which belonged to them under the Pa- 
triarchal system; and, so little are they likely to 
have been extinguished by the act of emancipation, 
that the probabilities are altogether the other way. 
It may be unhesitatingly taken for granted that 
enfranchisement from the father's power was a de- 
monstration, rather than a severance, of affection — a 
mark of grace and favour accorded to the best-beloved 
and most esteemed of the children. If sons thus 
honoured above the rest were absolutely deprived of 
their heritage by an Intestacy, the reluctance to in- 
cur it requires no farther explanation. We might 
have assumed h priori that the passion for Testacy 
was generated by some moral injustice entailed by 
the rules of Intestate succession; and here we find 
them at variance with the very instinct by which 
early society was cemented together. It is possible 
to put all that has been urged in a very succinct 
form. Every dominant sentiment of the primitive 
Romans was entwined with the relations of the family. 
But what was the Family? The Law defined it one 



CHAP. vn. FEELING RESPECTING. INTESTACY. 223 

way — natural affection another. In the conflict be- 
tween the two, the feeling we would analyse grew up, 
taking the form of an enthusiasm for the institution 
by which the dictates of affection were permitted to 
determine the fortunes of its objects. 

I regard, therefore, the Roman horror of Intes- 
tacy as a monument of a very early conflict between 
ancient law and slowly changing ancient sentiment 
on the subject of the Family. Some passages in 
the Roman Statute-Law, and one statute in parti- 
cular which limited the capacity for inheritance 
possessed by women, must have contributed to keep 
alive the feeling; and it is the general belief that 
the system of creating Fidei-Commissa, or bequests 
in trust, was devised to evade the disabilities im- 
posed by those statutes. But the feeling itself, in 
its remarkable intensity, seems to point back to some 
deeper antagonism between law and opinion; nor 
is it at all wonderful that the improvements of 
jurisprudence by the Praetor should not have extin- 
guished it. Everybody conversant with the philo- 
sophy of opinion is aware that a sentiment by no 
means dies out, of necessity, with the passing away 
of the circumstances which produced it. It may 
long survive them; nay, it may afterwards attain 
to a pitch and climax of intensity which it never 
attained during their actual continuance. 

The view of a WiU which regards it as conferring 



224 MODERN WILLS. chap. yu. 

the power of diverting property from the Family, 
or of distributing it in such uneven proportions as 
the fancy or good sense of the Testator may dictate, 
is not older than that later portion of the Middle 
Ages in which Feudalism had completely con- 
solidated itself. When modem jurisprudence first 
shows itself in the rough, Wills are rarely allowed to 
dispose with absolute freedom of a dead man's assets. 
Wherever at this period the descent of property 
was regulated by WiU — and over the greater part 
of Europe moveable or personal property was the 
subject of Testamentary disposition — the exercise 
of the Testamentary power was seldom allowed to 
interfere with the right of the widow to a definite 
share, and of the children to certain fixed propor- 
tions, of the devolving inheritance. The shares of 
the children, as their amount shows, were deter- 
mined by the authority of Roman law. The pro- 
vision for the widow was attributable to the exer- 
tions of the Church, which never relaxed its solicitude 
for the interest of wives surviving their husbands — 
winning, perhaps, one of the most arduous of its tri- 
umphs when, after exacting for two or three centuries 
an express promise from the husband at marriage to 
endow his wife, it at length succeeded in engrafting 
the principle of Dower on the Customary Law of 
all Western Europe. Curiously enough, the dower 
of lands proved a more stable institution than the 



CHAP. VII. widow's SHABE op moveables. 225 

analogous and more ancient reservation of certain 
shares of the personal property to the widow and 
children. A few local customs in France maintained 
the right down to the Eevolution, and there are traces 
of similar usages in England ; but on the whole the 
doctrine prevailed that moveables might be freely 
disposed of by Will, and, even when the claims of 
the widow continued to be respected, the privi- 
leges of the children were obliterated from juris- 
prudence. We need not hesitate to attribute the 
change to the influence of Primogeniture. As the 
Feudal law of land practically disinherited all the 
children in favour of one, the equal distribution even 
of those sorts of property which might have been 
equally divided ceased to be viewed as a duty. Tes- 
taments were the principal instruments employed 
in producing inequality, and in this condition of 
things originated the shade of difference which shows 
itself between the ancient and the modem con- 
ception of a Will. But, though the liberty of 
bequest, enjoyed through Testaments, was thus an 
accidental fruit of Feudalism, there is no broader 
distinction than that which exists between a system 
of free Testamentary disposition and a system, like 
that of the Feudal land-law, under which property 
descends compulsorily in prescribed lines of devolu- 
tion. This truth appears to have been lost sight of 
by the authors of the French Codes. In the social 

Q 



326 FRENCH LAW OF WILIi(« chap. vn. 

fabric whiclL they detennined to destroy, they saw 
Primogeniture resting chiefly on Family settle- 
ments, but they also perceived that Testaments 
were frequently employed to give the eldest son 
precisely the same preference which was reserved 
to him under the strictest of entails. In order, 
therefore, to make sure of their work, they not 
only rendered it impossible to prefer the eldest 
son to the rest in marriage-arrangements, but they 
almost expelled Testamentary succession from the 
law, lest it should be used to defeat their funda- 
mental principle of an equal distribution of pro- 
perty among children at the parent's death. The 
result is that they have established a system of 
small perpetual entails, which is infinitely nearer 
akin to the system of feudal Europe than would be 
a perfect liberty of bequest. The land-law of Eng- 
land, " the Herculaneum of Feudalism," is certainly 
much more closely allied to the land-law of the 
Middle Ages than that of any Continental country, and 
Wills with us are frequently used to aid or imitate 
that preference of the eldest son and his line which 
is a nearly universal feature in marriage settlements 
of real property. But nevertheless feeling and 
opinion in this country have been profoundly affected 
by the practice of free Testamentary disposition ; and 
it appears to me that the state of sentiment in a 
great part of French society, on the subject of the 



CHAP. vn. PBIMOGENITUBE. 227 

conservation of property in families, is much liker 
that which prevailed through Europe two or three 
centuries ago than are the current opinions of Eng- 
lishmen. 

The mention of Primogeniture introduces one of 
the most difficult problems of historical jurispru- 
dence. Though I have not paused to explain my 
expressions, it may have been noticed that I have 
frequently spoken of a number of " co-heirs " as 
placed by the Boman Law of Succession on the 
same footing with a single Heir. In point of fact, 
we know of no period of Roman jurisprudence at 
which the place of the Heir, or Universal Succes- 
sor, might not have been taken by a group of co- 
heirs. This group succeeded as a single unit, and 
the assets were afterwards divided among them in a 
separate legal proceeding. When the Succession was 
ah intestatOj and the group consisted of the children 
of the deceased, they each took an equal share of 
the property; nor, though males had at one time 
some advantages over females, is there the faintest 
trace of Primogeniture. The mode of distribution 
is the same throughout archaic jurisprudence. It 
certainly seems that, when civil society begins and 
families cease to hold together through a series of 
generations, the idea which spontaneously suggests 
itself is to divide the domaia equally among the mem- 
bers of each successive generation, and to reserve no 

Q 2 



328 PBIMOGENITUBE. chap. vii. 

privilege to the eldest son or stock. Some pecu- 
liarly significant hints as to the close relation of this 
phenomenon to primitive thought are furnished by 
systems yet more archaic than the Roman. Among 
the Hindoos, the instant a son is bom, he acquires a 
vested right in his father's property, which cannot 
be sold without recognition of his joint ownership. 
On the son's attaining full age, he can sometimes 
compel a partition of the estate even against the 

. ,^.v^., consent of the parent; and, should the parent ac- 

^<\^ ^-«^ quiesce, one son can always have a partition even 

..V '^••'^' against the will of the others. On such partition 

v.o>^'«^ taking place, the father has no advantage over his 
children, except that he has two of the shares in- 
stead of one. The ancient law of the German 
tribes was exceedingly similar. The allod or domain 
of the family was the joint-property of the father 
and his sons. It does not, however, appear to have 
been habitually divided even at the death of the 
parent, and in the same way the possessions of a 
Hindoo, however divisible theoretically, are so rarely 
distributed in fact, that many generations constantly 
succeed each other without a partition taking place, 
and thus the Family in India has a perpetual tendency 
to expand into the Village Community, under condi- 
tions which I shall hereafter attempt to elucidate. 
All this points very clearly to the absolutely equal 
division of assets among the male children at death as 



CHAP. VII. PBIMOGENITUEB. 229 

the practice most usual with society at the period 
when family-dependency is in the first stages of dis- 
integration. Here then emerges the historical diffi- 
culty of Primogeniture. The more clearly we perceive 
that, when the Feudal institutions were in process of 
formation, there was no source in the world whence 
they could derive their elements but the Roman law 
of the provincials on the one hand and the archaic 
customs of the barbarians on the other, the more are 
we perplexed at first sight by our knowledge that 
neither Roman nor barbarian was accustomed to give 
any preference to the eldest son or his line in the 
succession to property. 

Primogeniture did not belong to the Customs which 
the barbarians practised on their first establishment 
within the Roman Empire. It is known to have had 
its origin in the benefices or beneficiary gifts of the 
invading chieftains. These benefices, which were 
occasionally conferred by the earlier immigrant kings, 
but were distributed on a great scale by Charlemagne, 
were grants of Roman provincial land to be holden 
by the beneficiary on condition of military service. 
The allodial proprietors do not seem to have followed 
their sovereign on distant or difficult enterprises, and 
all the grander expeditions of the Prankish chiefs and 
of Charlemagne were accomplished with forces com- 
posed of soldiers either personally dependent on the 
royal house or compelled to serve it by the tenure of 

q3 



230 BENEPICBS AND FIEFS. chap. vii. 

their land. The benefices, however, were not at 
first in ^ any sense hereditary. They were held at 
the pleasure of the grantor, or at most for the 
life of the grantee ; but still, from the very outset, 
no eflfort seems to have been spared by the bene- 
ficiaries to enlarge the tenure, and to continue their 
lands in their family after death. Through the 
feebleness of Charlemagne's successors these attempts 
were universally successful, and the Benefice gradu- 
ally transformed itself into the hereditary Fief. But, 
though the fiefs were hereditary, they did not neces- 
sarily descend to the eldest son. The rules of suc- 
cession which they followed were entirely determined 
by the terms agreed upon between the grantor 
and the beneficiary, or imposed by one of them 
on the weakness of the other. The original tenures 
were therefore extremely various ; not indeed so 
capriciously various as is sometimes asserted, for all 
which have hitherto been described present some 
combination of the modes of succession familiar to 
Romans and to barbarians, but still exceedingly mis- 
cellaneous. In some of them, the eldest son and his 
stock undoubtedly succeeded to the fief before the 
others, but such successions, so far from being uni- 
versal, do not even appear to have been general. 
Precisely the same phenomena recur during that 
more recent transmutation of European society which 
entirely substituted the feudal form of property for 



CHAP. VII. ALLODS AND FIEFS. 231 

the domainial (or Roman) and the allodial (or Ger- 
man). The allods were wholly absorbed by the fiefs. 
The greater allodial proprietors transformed them- 
selves into feudal lords by (conditional alienations of 
portions of their land to dependants; the smaller 
sought an escape from the oppressions of that terrible 
time by surrendering their property to some powerful 
chieftain, and receiving it back at his hands on con- 
dition of service in his wars. Meantime, that vast 
mass of the population of Western Europe whose 
condition was servile or semi-servile — the Roman 
and German personal slaves, the Roman coloni and 
the Germdi^ lidi — were concurrently absorbed by 
the feudal organisation, a few of them assuming a 
menial relation to the lords, but the greater part 
receiving land on terms which in those centuries 
were considered degrading. The tenures created 
during this era of universal infeudation were as vari- 
ous as the conditions which the tenants made with 
their new chiefs or were forced to accept from them. 
As in the case of the benefices, the succession to 
some, but by no means to all, of the estates followed 
the rule of Primogeniture. No sooner, however, has 
the feudal system prevailed throughout the West, 
than it becomes evident that Primogeniture has some 
great advantage over every other mode of succession. 
It spread over Europe with remarkable rapidity, the 
principal instrument of diflFusion being Family Settle- 

Q 4 



232 DIFFUSION OF PBIMOGEKITUBE. chap. vir. 

ments, the Pactes de Famille of France and Haus- 
Gesetze of Germany, which universally stipulated 
that lands held by knightly service should descend to 
the eldest son. XJltimately the law resigned itself 
to follow inveterate practice, and we find that in all 
the bodies of Customary Law, which were gradually 
built up, the eldest son and stock are preferred in the 
succession to estates of which the tenure is free and 
military. As to lands held by servile tenures (and 
originally all tenures were servile which bound the 
tenant to pay money or bestow manual labour), the 
system of succession prescribed by custom differed 
greatly in different countries and different provinces. 
The more general rule was that such lands were 
divided equally at death among all the children, but 
stiU in some instances the eldest son was preferred, 
in some the youngest. But Primogeniture usually 
governed the inheritance of that class of estates, in 
some respects the most important of all, which were 
held by tenures that, like the English Socage, were 
of later origin than the rest, and were neither alto- 
gether free nor altogether servile. 

The diffusion of Primogeniture is usually accounted 
for by assigning what are called Feudal reasons for 
it. It is asserted that the feudal superior had a bet- 
ter security for the military service he required when 
the fief descended to a single person, instead of being 
distributed among a number on the decease of the 



CHAP. VII. DIFFUSION OF PRIMOGENITURE. 2S3 

last holder. Without denying that this consideration 
may partially explain the favour gradually acquired 
by Primogeniture, I must point out that Primogeni- 
ture became a custom of Europe much more through 
its popularity with the tenants than through any ad- 
vantage it conferred on the lords. For its origin, 
moreover, the reason given does not account at all. 
Nothing in law springs entirely from a sense of con- 
venience. There are always certain ideas existing 
antecedently on which the sense of convenience works, 
and of which it can do no more than form some new 
combination ; and to find these ideas in the present 
case is exactly the problem. 

A valuable hint is furnished to us from a quarter 
fruitful of such indications. Although in India the 
possessions of a parent are divisible at his death, and 
may be divisible during his life, among all his male 
children in equal shares, and though this principle of 
the equal distribution of property extends to every 
part of the Hindoo institutions, yet wherever public 
office ov political power devolves at the decease of the 
last Incumbent, the succession is nearly universally 
according to the rules of Primogeniture. Sovereign- 
ties descend therefore to the eldest son, and where 
the afiairs of the Village Community, the corporate 
unit of Hindoo society, are confided to a single 
manager, it is generally the eldest son who takes up 
the administration at his parent's death. All offices, 



234 SUCCESSION TO POLITICAL TOWEE. chap. yu. 

indeed, in India, tend to become hereditary, and, when 
their nature permits it, to vest in the eldest member 
of the oldest stock. Comparing these Indian succes- 
sions with some of the ruder social organisations 
which have survived in Europe almost to our own 
day, the conclusion suggests itself that, when Patri- 
archal power is not only domestic but political^ it is 
not distributed among all the issue at the parent's 
death, but is the birthright of the eldest son. The 
chieftainship of a Highland clan, for example, followed 
the order of Primogeniture. There seems, in truth, to 
be a form of family-dependency still more archaic 
than any of those which we know from the primitive 
records of organised civil societies. The Agnatic 
Union of the kindred in ancient Roman law, and a 
multitude of similar indications, point to a period at 
which all the ramifying branches of the family tree 
held together in one organic whole ; and it is no pre- 
sumptuous conjecture, that, when the corporation thus 
formed by the kindred was in itself an independent 
society, it was governed by the eldest male of the 
oldest line. It is true that we have no actual know- 
ledge of any such society. Even in the most ele- 
mentary communities, family-organisations, as we 
know them, are at most imperia in imperio. But the 
position of some of them, of the Celtic clans in parti- 
cular, was sufficiently near independence within his- 
torical times to force on us the conviction that they 



CHAP. Yii. ANCIENT FORMS OP PRIMOGENITURE. 235 

were once separate imperia^ and that Primogeniture 
regulated the succession to the chieftainship. It 
is, however, necessary to be on our guard against 
modem associations with the term of law. We are 
speaking of a family-connection still closer and more 
stringent than any with which we are made acquainted 
by Hindoo society or ancient Roman law. If the 
Roman Paterfamilias was visibly steward of the fa- 
mily possessions, if the Hindoo father is only joint- 
sharer with his sons, still more emphatically must the 
true patriarchal chieftain be merely the administrator 
of a common fund. 

•The examples of succession by Primogeniture which 
were found among the Benefices may, therefore, 
have been imitated from a system of family-govern- 
ment known to the invading races, though not 
in general use. Some ruder tribes may have still 
practised it, or, what is still more probable, society 
may have been so slightly removed from its more 
archaic condition that the minds of some men spon- 
taneously recurred to it, when they were called upon 
to settle the rules of inheritance for a new form of 
property. But there is still the question. Why did 
Primogeniture gradually supersede every other prin- 
ciple of succession ? The answer, I think, is, that 
European society decidedly retrograded during the 
dissolution of the Carlovingian empire. It sank a 
point or two back even from the miserably low degree 



236 FALL OF CARLOVINGUN EMPIRE. chap. rit. 

A* - 

which it had marked during the early barbarian 
monarchies. The great characteristic of the period 
was the feebleness, or rather the abeyance, of kingly 
and therefore of civil authority; and hence it seems 
as if, civil society no longer cohering, men univer- 
sally flung themselves back on a social organisation 
older than the beginnings of civil communities. The 
lord with his vassals, during the ninth and tenth 
centuries, may be considered as a patriarchal house- 
hold, recruited, not as in the primitive times by Adop- 
tion, but by Infeudation; and to such a confederacy, 
succession by Primogeniture was a source of strength 
and durability. So long as the land was kept together 
on which the entire organisation rested, ^t was power- 
ful for defence and attack; to divide the land was to 
divide the little society, and voluntarily to invite 
aggression in an era of universal violence. We may 
be perfectly certain that into this preference for 
Primogeniture there entered no idea of disinheriting 
the bulk of the children in favour of one. Everybody 
would have suffered by the division of the fief. 
Everybody was a gainer by its consolidation. The 
Family grew stronger by the concentration of power 
in the same hands; nor is it likely that the lord who 
was invested with the inheritance had any advantage 
over his brethren and kinsfolk in occupations, inte- 
rests, or indulgences. It would be a singular ana- 
chronism to estimate the privileges succeeded to by 



CHAP. Til. EABUEB AND LATEB PRIMOGENITUIU)^. 237 

the heir of a fief, by the situation in which th^<^ldes^ 
son is placed under an .English strict settlement. 

I have said that I regard the early feudal con- 
federacies as descended from an archaic form of the 
Family, and as wearing a strong resemblance to it. 
But then in the ancient world, and in the societies 
which have not passed through the crucible of feu- 
dalism, the Primogeniture which seems to have pre- 
vailed never transformed itseKinto the Primogeniture 
of the later feudal Europe. When the group of kins- 
men ceased to be governed through a series of genera- 
tions by a hereditary chief, the domain which had 
been managed for all appears to have been equally 
divided among all. Why did this not occur in the 
feudal world? If during the confusions of the first 
feudal period the eldest son held the land for the be- 
hoof of the whole family, why was it that when feudal 
Europe had consolidated itself, and regular commu- 
nities were again established, the whole family did 
not resume that capacity for equal inheritance which 
had belonged to Roman and German alike ? The key 
which unlocks this difficulty has rarely been seized 
by the writers who occupy themselves in tracing the 
genealogy of Feudalism. They perceive the materials 
of the feudal institutions, but they miss the cement. 
The ideas and social forms which contributed to the 
formation of the system were unquestionably bar- 
barian and archaic, but, as soon as Courts and lawyers 



238 MODEEN VIEW OP CHIEFTAINSHIP. chap. vn. 

were called in to interpret and define it, the principles 
of interpretation which they applied to it were those 
of the latest Roman jurisprudence, and were therefore 
excessively refined and matured. In a patriarchally 
governed society, the eldest son may succeed to the 
government of the Agnatic group, and to the absolute 
disposal of its property. But he is not therefore a 
true proprietor. He has correlative duties not in- 
volved in the conception of proprietorship, but quite 
undefined and quite incapable of definition. The 
later Roman jurisprudence, however, like our own 
law, looked upon uncontrolled power over property 
as equivalent to ownership, and did not, and, in fact, 
could not, take notice of liabilities of such a kind, 
that the very conception of them belonged to a period 
anterior to regular law. The contact of the refined 
and the barbarous notion had inevitably for its effect 
the conversion of the eldest son into legal proprietor 
of the inheritance. The clerical and secular lawyers 
so defined his position from the first; but it was only 
by insensible degrees that the younger brother, from 
participating on equal terms in all the dangers and 
enjoyments of his kinsman, sank into the priest, the 
soldier of fortune, or the hanger-on of the mansion. 
The legal revolution was identical with that which 
occurred on a smaller scale, and in quite recent times, 
through the greater part of the Highlands of Scotland. 
When called in to determine the legal powers of the 



CHAP. VII. POEMS OP PRIMOGENITUEE. 239 

chieftain over the domains which gave sustenance to 
the dan, Scottish jurisprudence had long since passed 
the point at which it could take notice of the vague 
limitations on completeness of dominion imposed by 
the claims of the clansmen, and it was inevitable 
therefore that it should convert the patrimony of 
many into the estate of one. 

For the sake of simplicity I have called the mode 
of succession Primogeniture whenever a single son 
or descendant succeeds to the authority over a house- 
hold or society. It is remarkable, however, that in 
the few very ancient examples which remain to us of 
this sort of succession, it is not always the eldest son, 
in the sense familiar to us, who takes up the repre- 
sentation. The form of Primogeniture which has 
spread over Western Europe has also been per- 
petuated among the Hindoos, and there is every 
reason to believe that it is the normal form. Under 
it, not only the eldest son, but the eldest line is always 
preferred. If the eldest son fails, his eldest son has 
precedence not only j>ver brothers but over uncles; 
and, if he too fails, the same rule is followed in the 
next generation. But when the succession is not 
merely to civil but to political power, a difficulty may 
present itself which wiU appear of greater magnitude 
according as the cohesion of society is less perfect. 
The chieftain who last exercised authority may have 
outlived his eldest son, and the grandson who is 



\ 



240 FORMS OF PRIMOGENITUEE. CHAP.vir. 

primarily entitled to succeed may be too young and 
immature to undertake the actual guidance of the 
conununity, and the administration of its affairs. In 
such an event, the expedient which suggests itself to 
the more settled societies is to place the infant heir 
under guardianship till he reaches the age of fitness 
for government. The guardianship is generally that 
of the male Agnates ; but it is remarkable that the 
contingency supposed is one of the rare cases in 
which ancient societies have consented to the exercise 
of power by women, doubtless out of respect to the 
overshadowing claims of the mother. In India, the 
widow of a Hindoo sovereign governs in the name of 
her infant son, and we cannot but remember that the 
custom regulating succession to the throne of France 
— which, whatever be its origin, is doubtless of the 
highest antiquity — preferred the queen-mother to all 
other claimants for the Regency, at the same time 
that it rigorously excluded all females from the 
throne. There is, however, another mode of ob- 
viating the inconvenience attending the devolution of 
sovereignty on an infant heir, and it is one which 
would doubtless occur spontaneously to rudely or- 
ganised communities. This is to set aside the infant 
heir altogether, and confer the chieftainship on the 
eldest surviving male of the first generation. The 
Celtic clan-associations, among the many phenomena 
which they have preserved of an age in which civil 



CHAP. VII. CELTIC PRIMOGENITURE. 241 

and political society were not yet even rudimentarily 
separated, have brought down this rule of succession 
to historical times. With them, it seems to have 
existed in the form of a positive canon, that, failing 
the eldest son, his next brother succeeds in priority 
to all grandsons, whatever be their age at the moment 
when the sovereignty devolves. Some writers have 
explained the principle by assuming that the Celtic 
customs took the last chieftain as a sort of root or 
stock, and then gave the succession to the descend- 
ant who should be least remote from him ; the uncle 
thus being preferred to the grandson as being nearer 
to the common root. No objection can be taken to 
this statement if it be merely intended as a descrip- 
tion of the system of succession ; but it would be a 
serious error to conceive the men who first adopted 
the rule as applying a course of reasoning which 
evidently dates from the time when feudal schemes of 
succession begun to be debated among lawyers. 
The true origin of the preference of the uncle to the 
grandson is doubtless a simple calculation on the part 
of rude men in a rude society that it is better to be 
governed by a grown chieftain than by a child, and 
that the younger son is more likely to have come 
to maturity than any of the eldest son's descendants. 
At the same time, we have some evidence that the 
form of Primogeniture with which we are best 
acquainted is the primary form, in the tradition that 



242 MAHOMETAN RULE. chap. vit. 

the assent of the clan was asked when an infant heir 
was passed over in favour of his uncle. There is a 
tolerably well authenticated instance of this ceremony 
in the annals of the Macdonalds. 

Under Mahometan law, which has probably pre- 
served an ancient Arabian custom, inheritances of 
property are divided equally among sons, the daugh- 
ters taking a half share ; but if any of the children 
die before the division of the inheritance, leaving 
issue behind, these grandchildren are entirely ex- 
cluded by their uncles and aunts. Consistently with 
this principle, the succession, when political autho- 
rity devolves, is according to the form of Primo- 
geniture which appears to have obtained among the 
Celtic societies. In the two great Mahometan 
families of the West, the rule is believed to be, that 
the uncle succeeds to the throne in preference to the 
nephew, though the latter be the son of an elder 
brother; but though this rule has been followed 
quite recently in Egypt, I am informed that there 
is some doubt as to its governing the devolution of 
the Turkish sovereignty. The policy of the Sultans 
has in fact hitherto prevented cases for its applica- 
tion from occurring, and it is possible that their 
wholesale massacres of their younger brothers may 
have been perpetrated quite as much in the interest 
of their children as for the sake of making away 
with dangerous competitors for the throne. It is 



CHAP. VII. POLYGAMY. 243 

evident, however, that in polygamous societies the 
form of Primogeniture wiU always tend to vary. 
Many considerations may constitute a claim on the 
succession, the rank of the mother, for example, or 
her degree in the affections of the father. Accord- 
ingly, some of the Indian Mahometan sovereigns, 
without pretending to any distinct testamentary 
power, claim the right of nominating the son who 
is to succeed. The blessing mentioned in the 
Scriptural history of Isaac and his sons has some- 
times been spoken of as a will, but it seems rather 
to have been a mode of naming an eldest son. 



R 2 



244 NATURAL MODES OF ACQUISITION. chap. vm. 



CHAP. VIII. 

THE EARLY HISTORY OF PROPERTY. 

The Roman Institutional Treatises, after giving their 
definition of the various forms and modifications of 
ownership, proceed to discuss the Natural Modes of 
Acquiring Property. Those who are unfamiliar with 
the history of jurisprudence are not likely to look 
upon these "natural modes" of acquisition as pos- 
sessing, at first sight, either much speculative or 
much practical interest. The wild animal which is 
snared or kiUed by the hunter, the soil which is 
added to our field by the imperceptible deposits of a 
river, the tree which strikes its roots into our ground, 
are each said by the Roman lawyers to be acquired 
by us naturally. The older jurisconsults had doubt- 
less observed that such acquisitions were universally 
sanctioned by the usages of the little societies around 
them, and thus the lawyers of a later age, finding 
them classed in the ancient Jus Gentium, and per- 
ceiving them to be of the simplest description, allotted 
them a place among the ordinances of Nature. The 
dignity with which they were invested has gone on 
increasing in modem times till it is quite out of pro- 



CHAP. vni. OCCUPANCY. 245 

portion to their original importance. Theory has 
made them its favourite food, and has enabled them 
to exercise the most serious influence on practice. 

It will be necessary for us to attend to one only 
among these " natural modes of acquisition," Occu- 
patio or Occupancy. Occupancy is the advisedly 
taking possession of that which at the moment is the 
property of no man, with the view (adds the technical 
definition) of acquiring property in it for yourself. 
The objects which the Roman lawyers called res nvl- 
lius — things which have not or have never had an 
owner — can only be ascertained by enumerating 
them. Among things which never had an owner are 
wild animals, fishes, wild fowl, jewels disinterred for 
the first time, and lands newly discovered or never 
before cultivated. Among things which have not an 
owner are moveables which have been abandoned, 
lands which have been deserted, and (an anomalous 
but most formidable item) the property of an enemy. 
In all these objects the full rights of dominion were 
acquired by the Occupant^ who first took possession 
of them with the intention of keeping them as his 
own — an intention which, in certain cases, had to be 
manifested by specific acts. It is not difficult, I 
think, to understand the universality which caused 
the practice of Occupancy to be placed by one gene- 
ration of Roman lawyers in the Law common to all 
Nations, and the simplicity which occasioned its being 

R 3 



246 LAW OF CAPTUBE IN WAR. chap. tiii. 

attributed by another to the Law of Nature. But 
for its fortunes in modem legal history we are less 
prepared by h priori considerations. The Roman 
principle of Occupancy, and the rules into which the 
jurisconsults expanded it, are the source of all modem 
International Law on the subject of Capture in War 
and of the acquisition of sovereign rights in newly dis- 
covered countries. They have also supplied a theory 
of the Origin of Property, which is at once the 
popular theory, and the theory which, in one form or 
another, is acquiesced in by the great majority of 
speculative jurists. 

I have said that the Roman principle of Occupancy 
has determined the tenor of that chapter of Interna- 
tional Law which is concerned with Capture in War. 
The Law of Warlike Capture derives its rules from 
the assumption that communities are remitted to a 
state of nature by the outbreak of hostilities, and that, 
in the artificial natural condition thus produced, the 
institution of private property falls into abeyance so 
far as concerns the belligerents. As the later writers 
on the Law of Nature have always been anxious to 
maintain that private property was in some sense 
sanctioned by the system which they were expound- 
ing, the hypothesis that an enemy's property is res 
nullius has seemed to them perverse and shocking, 
and they are careful to stigmatise it as a mere fiction 
of jurisprudence. But, as soon as the Law of Nature 



CHAP. vni. ANCIENT LAW OP CAPTURE. 247 

is traced to its source in the Jus Gentium, we see at 
once how the goods of an enemy came to be looked 
upon as nobody's property, and therefore as capable 
of being acquired by the first occupant. The idea 
would occur spontaneously to persons practising the 
ancient forms of Warfare, when victory dissolved the 
organisation of the conquering army and dismissed 
the soldiers to indiscriminate plunder. It is probable, 
however, that originally it was only moveable pro- 
perty which was thus permitted to be acquired by 
the Captor. We know on independent authority that 
a very different rule prevailed in ancient Italy as to 
the acquisition of ownership in the soil of a con- 
quered country, and we may therefore suspect that 
the application of the principle of occupancy to land 
(always a matter of difficulty) dates from the period 
when the Jus Gentium was becoming the Code of 
Nature, and that it is the result of a generalisation 
effected by the jurisconsults of the golden age. Their 
dogmas on the point are preserved in the Pandects of 
Justinian, and amount to an unqualified assertion 
that enemy's property of every sort is res ntdlius to 
the other belligerent, and that Occupancy, by which 
the Captor makes them his own, is an institution of 
Natural Law. The rules which International juris- 
prudence derives from these positions have sometimes 
been stigmatised as needlessly indulgent to the fero- 
city and cupidity of combatants, but the charge has 

B 4 



248 OCCUPANCY AND WARLIKE CAPTURE. chap. viii. 

been made, I think, by persons who are unacquainted 
with the history of wars, and who are consequently 
ignorant how great an exploit it is to command 
obedience for a rule of any kind. The Roman prin- 
ciple of Occupancy, when it was admitted into the 
modem law of Capture in War, drew with it a number 
of subordinate canons, limiting and giving precision 
to its operation, and if the contests which have 
been waged since the treatise of Grotius became an 
authority, are compared with those of an earlier date, 
it will be seen that, as soon as the Roman maxims 
were received, Warfare instantly assumed a more 
tolerable complexion. If the Roman law of Occu- 
pancy is to be taxed with having had pernicious in- 
fluence on any part of the modem Law of Nations, 
there is another chapter in it which may be said, with 
some reason, to have been injuriously affected. In 
applying to the discovery of new countries the same 
principles which the Romans had applied to the find- 
ing of a jewel, the Publicists forced into their service 
a doctrine altogether unequal to the task expected 
from it. Elevated into extreme importance by the 
discoveries of the great navigators of the 15th and 
16th centuries, it raised more disputes than it solved. 
The greatest uncertainty was very shortly found to 
exist on the very two points on which certainty was 
most required, the extent of the territory which was 
acquired for his sovereign by the discoverer, and the 



cnAP. VIII. RULE OP DISCOVERY. 249 

nature of the acts which were necessary to complete 
the adprehensio or assumption of sovereign posses- 
sion. Moreover, the principle itself, conferring as it 
did such enormous advantages as the consequence of 
a piece of good luck, was instinctively mutinied 
against by some of the most adventurous nations 
in Europe, the Dutch, the English, and the Portu- 
guese. Our own countrymen, without expressly 
denying the rule of International Law, never did, in 
practice, admit the claim of the Spaniards to engross 
the whole of America south of the Gulf of Mexico, or 
that of the King of France to monopolise the valleys 
of the Ohio and the Mississippi. From the accession 
of Elizabeth to the accession of Charles the Second, 
it cannot be said that there was at any time thorough 
peace in the American waters, and the encroach- 
ments of the New England Colonists on the territory 
of the French King continued for almost a century 
longer. Bentham was so struck with the confusion 
attending the application of the legal principle, that 
he went out of his way to eulogise the famous Bull 
of Pope Alexander the Sixth, dividing the undis- 
covered countries of the world between the Spaniards 
and Portuguese by a line drawn one hundred leagues 
West of the Azores ; and, grotesque as his praises may 
appear at first sight, it may be doubted whether the 
arrangement of Pope Alexander is absurder in prin- 
ciple than the rule of Public law, which gave half a 



250 ORIGIN OP PROPERTY. chap. vin. 

continent to the monarch whose servants had fulfilled 
the conditions required by Koman jurisprudencQ for 
the acquisition of property in a valuable object which 
could be covered by the hand. 

To all who pursue the inquiries which are the 
subject of this volume Occupancy is pre-eminently 
interesting on the score of the service it has been 
made to perform for speculative jurisprudence, in 
furnishing a supposed explanation of the origin of 
private property. It was once universally believed 
that the proceeding implied in Occupancy was iden- 
tical with the process by which the earth and its 
fruits, which were at first in common, became the 
allowed property of individuals. The course of 
thought which led to this assumption is not difficult 
to understand, if we seize the shade of difference 
which separates the ancient from the modem con- 
ception of Natural Law. The Roman lawyers had 
laid down that Occupancy was one of the Natural 
modes of acquiring property, and they undoubtedly 
believed that, were mankind living under the institu- 
tions of Nature, Occupancy would be one of their 
practices. How far they persuaded themselves that 
such a condition of the race had ever existed, is a 
point, as I have already stated, which their language 
leaves in much uncertainty; but they certainly do 
seem to have made the conjecture, which has at all 
times possessed much plausibility, that the institution 



CHAP. VIII. ORIGIN OF PROPERTY. 251 

of property was not so old as the existence of man- 
kind. Modem jurisprudence, accepting all their 
dogmas without reservation, went far beyond them 
in the eager curiosity with which it dwelt on the 
supposed state of Nature. Since then it had re- 
ceived the position that the earth and its fruits were 
once res mUlitts^ and since its peculiar view of Na- 
ture led it to assume without hesitation that the 
human race had actually practised the Occupancy 
of res nullius long before the organisation of civil so- 
cieties, the inference immediately suggested itself that 
Occupancy was the process by which the " no man's 
goods" of the primitive world became the private 
property of individuals in the world of history. It 
would be wearisome to enumerate the jurists who 
have subscribed to this theory in one shape or an- 
other, and it is the less necessary to attempt it 
because Blackstone, who is always a faithful index 
of the average opinions of his day, has summed them 
up in his 2nd book and 1st chapter. 

" The earth," he writes, " and all things therein 
were the general property of mankind from the imme- 
diate gift of the Creator. Not that the communion of 
goods seems ever to have been applicable, even in the 
earliest ages, to aught but the substance of the thing; 
nor could be extended to the use of it. For, by the 
law of nature and reason he who first began to use 
it acquired therein a kind of transient property that 



252 BLACKSTONE S THEORY. cbap. vut. 

lasted so long as he was using it, and no longer; 
or to speak with greater precision, the right of pos- 
session continued for the same time only that the 
act of possession lasted. Thus the ground was in 
common, and no part was the permanent property 
of any man in particular; yet whoever was in the 
occupation of any determined spot of it, for rest, for 
shade, or the like, acquired for the time a sort of 
ownership, from which it would have been unjust 
and contrary to the law of nature to have driven 
him by force, but the instant that he quitted the use 
of occupation of it, another might seize it without 
injustice." He then proceeds to argue that " when 
mankind increased in number, it became necessary 
to entertain conceptions of more permanent domi- 
nion, and to appropriate to individuals not the imme- 
diate use only, but the very substance of the thing 
to be used." 

Some ambiguities of expression in this passage 
lead to the suspicion that Blackstone did not 
quite understand the meaning of the proposition 
which he found in his authorities, that property in 
the earth's surface was first acquired, under the law 
of Nature, by the occupant ; but the limitation 
which designedly or through misapprehension he has 
imposed on the theory brings it into a form which it 
has not infrequently assumed. Many writers more 
famous than Blackstone for precision of language 



CHAP. VIII. BLACKSTONE S THEORY. 253 

have laid down that, in the beginning of things, 
Occupancy first gave a right against the worid to an 
exclusive but temporary enjoyment, and that after- 
wards this right, while it remained exclusive, became 
perpetual. Their object in so stating their theory 
was to reconcile the doctrine that in the state of 
Nature res nvllius became property through Occu- 
pancy, with the inference which they drew from the 
Scriptural history that the Patriarchs did not at 
first permanently appropriate the soil which had been 
grazed over by their flocks and herds. 

The only criticism which could be directly applied 
to the theory of Blackstone would consist in in- 
quiring whether the circumstances which make up 
his picture of a primitive society are more or less 
probable than other incidents which could be ima- 
gined with equal readiness. Pursuing this method 
of examination, we might fairly ask whether the 
man who had occupied (Blackstone evidently uses 
this word with its ordinary English meaning) a par- 
ticular spot of ground for rest or shade would be 
permitted to retain it without disturbance. The 
chances surely are that his right to possession would 
be exactly coextensive with his power to keep it, 
and that he would be constantly liable to disturbance 
by the first comer who coveted the spot and thought 
himself strong enough to drive away the possessor. 
But the truth is that all such cavil at these positions 



254 APHORISM OP SAVIGNY. chap. viii. 

is perfectly idle from the very baselessness of the 
positions themselves. What mankind did in the pri- 
mitive state may not be a hopeless subject of inquiry, 
but of their motives for doing it it is impossible to 
know anything. These sketches of the plight of 
human beings in the first ages of the world are 
effected by first supposing mankind to be divested of 
a great part of the circumstances by which they are 
now surrounded, and by then assuming that, in 
the condition thus imagined, they would preserve 
the same sentiments and prejudices by which they 
are now actuated, — although, in fact, these senti- 
ments may have been created and engendered by 
those very circumstances of which, by the hypo- 
thesis, they are to be stripped. 

There is an aphorism of Savigny which has been 
sometimes thought to countenance a view of the 
origin of property somewhat similar to the theories 
epitomised by Blackstone. The great German jurist 
has laid down that all Property is founded on Ad- 
verse Possession ripened by Prescription. It is only 
with respect to Koman law that Savigny makes this 
statement, and before it can fully be appreciated 
much labour must be expended in explaining and 
defining the expressions employed. His meaning 
will, however, be indicated with sufficient accuracy 
if we consider him to assert that, how far soever we 
carry our inquiry into the ideas of property received 



CHAP. VIII. APHORISM OP SAVIGNY. 255 

among the Romans, however closely we approach in 
tracing them to the infancy of law, we can get no 
farther than a conception of ownership involving the 
three elements in the canon — Possession, Adverse- 
ness of Possession, that is a holding not permissive 
or subordinate, but exclusive against the world, and 
Prescription, or a period of time during which the 
Adverse Possession has uninterruptedly continued. 
It is exceedingly probable that this maxim might 
be enunciated with more generality than was allowed 
to it by its author, and that no sound or safe con- 
clusion can be looked for from investigations into 
any system of laws which are pushed farther back 
than the point at which these combined ideas con- 
stitute the notion of proprietary right. Meantime, 
so far from bearing out the popular theory of the 
origin of property, Savigny's canon is particularly 
valuable as directing our attention to its weakest 
point. In the view of Blackstone and those whom 
he follows, it was the mode of assuming the exclusive 
enjoyment which mysteriously affected the minds of 
the fathers of our race. But the mystery does not re- 
side here. It is not wonderful that property began 
in adverse possession. It is not surprising that the 
first proprietor should have been the strong man 
armed who kept his goods in peace. But why it was 
that lapse of time created a sentiment of respect for 
his possession — which is the exact source of the 



256 TRUE OEIGIN OP OCCUPANCY. chap. viii. 

universal reverence of mankind for that which has 
for a long period de facto existed— are questions really 
deserving the profoundest examination, but lying far 
beyond the boundary of our present inquiries. 

Before pointing out the quarter in which we may 
hope to glean some information, scanty and un- 
certain at best, concerning the early history of 
proprietary right, I venture to state my opinion that 
the popular impression in reference to the part 
played by Occupancy in the first stages of civilisa- 
tion directly reverses the truth. Occupancy is the 
advised assumption of physical possession ; and the 
notion that an act of this description confers a title 
to " res nullius," so far from being characteristic 
of very early societies, is in all probability the 
growth of a refined jurisprudence and of a settled 
condition of the laws. It is only when the rights of 
property have gained a sanction from long prac- 
tical inviolability, and when the vast majority of 
the objects of enjoyment have been subjected to 
private ownership, that mere possession is allowed 
to invest the first possessor with dominion over 
commodities in which no prior proprietorship has 
been asserted. The sentiment in which this doctrine 
originated is absolutely irreconcilable with that 
infrequency and uncertainty of proprietary rights 
which distinguish the beginnings of civilisation. 
Its true basis seems to be, not an instinctive bias 



CHAP. VIII. OBJECJTIONS TO POPULAR THEORY. 257 

towards the institution of Property, but a presump- 
tion, arising out of the long continuance of that 
institution, that everything ought to have an owner. 
When possession is taken of a " res nuUius," that is, 
of an object which is not, or has never been, reduced 
to dominion, the possessor is permitted to become 
proprietor from a feeling that all valuable things 
are naturally the subjects of an exclusive enjoyment, 
and that in the given case there is no one to invest 
with the right of property except the Occupant. 
The Occupant in short, becomes the owner, because 
all things are presumed to be somebody's property 
and because no one can be pointed out as having 
a better right than he to the proprietorship of this 
particular thing. 

Even were there no other objection to the de- 
scriptions of mankind in their natural state which 
we have been discussing, there is one particular in 
which they are fatally at variance with the authentic 
evidence possessed by us. It will be observed, that 
the acts and motives which these theories suppose 
are the acts and motives of Individuals. It is each 
Individual who for himself subscribes the Social 
Compact. It is some shifting sandbank in which 
the grains are Individual men, that according to 
the theory of Hobbes is hardened into the social 
rock by the wholesome discipline of force. It is 
an Individual who, in the picture drawn by Black- 

s 



258 OBJECTIONS TO POPULAR THEORY. chap. viii. 

stone, " is in the occupation of a determined spot 
of ground for rest, for shade, or .the like." The vice 
is one which necessarily afflicts all the theories de- 
scended from the Natural Law of the Romans, 
which differed principally from their Civil Law in 
the account which it took of Individuals, and which 
has rendered precisely its greatest service to civilisa- 
tion in enfranchising the individual from the autho- 
rity of archaic society. But Ancient Law, it must 
again be repeated, knows next to nothing of In- 
dividuals. It is concerned not with Individuals, but 
with Families, not with single human beings, but 
groups. Even when the law of the State has suc- 
ceeded in permeating the small circles of kindred 
into which it had originally no means of penetrating, 
the view it takes of Individuals is curiously different 
from that taken by jurisprudence in its maturest 
stage. The life of each citizen is not regarded as 
limited by birth and death; it is but a continuation 
of the existence of his forefathers, and it will be 
prolonged in the existence of his descendants. 

The Roman distinction between the Law of Per- 
sons and the Law of Things, which though extremely 
convenient is entirely artificial, has evidently done 
much to divert inquiry on the subject before us from 
the true direction. The lessons learned in discussing 
the Jus Personarum have been forgotten where the 
Jus Rerum is reached, and Property, Contract, and 
Delict, have been considered as if no hints concern- 



CHAF. vni. INFLUENCE OF BOMAN CLASSIFICATIONS. 259 

iiig their original nature were to be gained from the 
facts ascertained respecting the original condition 
of Persons. The ftitility of this method would be 
manifest if a system of pure archaic law could be 
brought before us, and if the experiment could be 
tried of appljdng to it the Roman classifications. 
It would soon be seen that the separation of the 
Law of Persons from that of Things has no meaning 
in the infancy of law, that the rules belonging to 
the two departments are inextricably mingled to- 
gether, and that the distinctions of the later jurists 
are appropriate only to the later jurisprudence. 
From what has been said in the earlier portions 
of this treatise, it will be gathered that there is 
a strong a priori improbability of our obtaining 
any clue to the early history of property, if we 
confine our notice to the proprietary rights of in- 
dividuals. It is more than likely that joint-owner- 
ship, and not separate ownership, is the really 
archaic institution, and that the forms of property 
which will aflford us instruction will be those 
which are associated with the rights of families and 
of groups of kindred. The Roman jurisprudence 
will not here assist in enlightening us, for it is 
exactly the Roman jurisprudence which, transformed 
by the theory of Natural Law, has bequeathed to the 
moderns the impression that individual ownership 
is the normal state of proprietary right, and that 

8 2 



260 I>T)IA5 TILLAGE COMMUXITIES. cdap. viii. 

ownership in common by groups of men is only 
the exception to a general rule. There is, however, 
one community which will always be carefully ex- 
amined by the inquirer who is in quest of any lost 
institution of primeval society. How far soever any 
such institution may have undergone change among 
the branch of the Indo-European family which has 
been settled for ages in India, it will seldom be found 
to have entirely cast aside the shell in which it was 
originally reared. It happens that, among the 
Hindoos, we do find a form of ownership which ought 
at once to rivet our attention from its exactly fitting 
in with the ideas which our studies in the Law of 
Persons would lead us to entertain respecting the 
original condition of property. The Village Com- 
munity of India is at once an organised patriarchal 
society and an assemblage of co-proprietors. The 
personal relations to each other of the men who 
compose it are indistinguishably confounded with 
their proprietary rights, and to the attempts of 
English functionaries to separate the two may be 
assigned some of the most formidable miscarriages of 
Anglo-Indian administration. The Village Com- 
munity is known to be of immense antiquity. In 
whatever direction research has been pushed into 
Indian history, general or local, it has always found 
the Community in existence at the farthest point of 
its progress. A great number of intelligent and 



CBAP. viir. CO-OWNEBSHIP. 261 

observant writers, most of whom had no theory of 
any sort to support concerning its nature and origin, 
agree in considering it the least destructible institu- 
tion of a society which never willingly surrenders 
any one of its usages to innovation. Conquests and 
revolutions seem to have swept over it without disturb- 
ing or displacing it, and the most beneficent systems 
of government in India have always been those which 
have recognised it as the basis of administration. 

The mature Roman law, and modern jurisprudence 
following in its wake, look upon co-ownership as 
an exceptional and momentary condition of the 
rights of property. This view is clearly indicated in 
the maxim which obtains universally in Western 
Europe, Nemo in communione potest invitus detineri 
(" No one can be kept in co-proprietorship against his 
will"). But in India this order of ideas is reversed, 
and it may be said that separate proprietorship is al- 
ways on its way to become proprietorship in common. 
The process has been adverted to already. As soon 
as a son is born, he acquires a vested interest in his 
father's substance, and on attaining years of dis- 
cretion he is even, in certain contingencies, permitted 
by the letter of the law to call for a partition of the 
family estate. As a fact, however, a division rarely 
takes place even at the death of the father, and the 
property constantly remains undivided for several 
generations, though every member of every genera- 



262 VILLAGE COMMUNITIES. chap. yiii. 

tion has a legal right to an undivided share in it. 
The domain thus held in common is sometimes ad- 
ministered by an elected manager, but more generally, 
and in some provinces always, it is managed by the 
eldest agnate, by the eldest representative of the 
eldest line of the stock. Such an assemblage of 
joint proprietors, a body of kindred holding a domain 
in common, is the simplest form of an Indian Village 
Community, but the Community is more than a 
brotherhood of relatives and more than an association 
of partners. It is an organised society, and besides 
providing for the management of the common fund, 
it seldom fails to provide, by a complete staff of 
functionaries, for internal government, for police, for 
the administration of justice, and for the apportion- 
ment of taxes and public duties. 

The process which I have described as that under 
which a Village Community is formed, may be regarded 
as typical. Yet it is not to be supposed that every 
Village Community in India drew together in so 
simple a manner. Although, in the North of India, 
the archives, as I am informed, almost invariably 
show that the Community was founded by a single 
assemblage of blood-relations, they also supply infor- 
mation that men of alien extraction have always, 
from time to time, been engrafted on it, and a mere 
purchaser of a share may generally, under certain 
conditions, be admitted to the brotherhood. In the 
South of the Peninsula there are often Communities 



CHAP. VIII. VILLAGE COMMUjS'ITIES. 268 

which appear to have sprung not from one but from 
two or more families; and there are some whose 
composition is known to be entirely artificial; indeed, 
the occasional aggregation of men of different castes 
in the same society is fatal to the hypothesis of a com- 
mon descent. Yet in all these brotherhoods either the 
tradition is preserved, or the assumption made, of an 
original common parentage. Mountstuart Elphinstone, 
who writes more particularly of the Southern Village 
Communities, observes of them {History of India^ 
i. 126) : ** The popular notion is that the Village 
landholders are all descended from one or more indi- 
viduals who settled the village ; and that the only 
exceptions are formed by persons who have derived 
their rights by purchase or othermse from members 
of the original stock. The supposition is confirmed 
by the fact that, to this day, there are only single 
families of landholders in small villages and not many 
in large ones; but each has branched out into so 
many members that it is not uncommon for the whole 
agricultural labour to be done by the landholders, 
without the aid either of tenants or of labourers. 
The rights of the landholders are theirs collectively, 
and, though they almost always have a more or less 
perfect partition of them, they never have an entire 
separation. A landholder, for instance, can sell or 
mortgage his rights ; but he must first have the con- 
sent of the Village, and the purchaser steps exactly 

9 4 



264 TYPE OF THE COMMUNITY. chap. vui. 

into his place and takes up all his obligations. If a 
family becomes extinct, its share returns to the com- 
mon stock.*' 

Some considerations which have been offered in the 
fifth chapter of this volume will assist the reader, I 
trust, in appreciating the significance of Elphinstone's 
language. No institution of the primitive world is 
likely to have been preserved to our day, unless it has 
acquired an elasticity foreign to its original nature 
through some vivifying legal fiction. The Village 
Community then is not necessarily an assemblage of 
blood-relations, but it is either such an assemblage or 
a body of co-proprietors formed on the model of an 
association of kinsmen. The type with which it 
should be compared is evidently not the Roman 
Family, but the Roman Gens or House. The Gens 
was also a group on the model of the family; it was 
the family extended by a variety of fictions of which 
the exact nature was lost in antiquity. In historical 
times, its leading characteristics were the very two 
which Elphinstone remarks in the Village Community. 
There was always the assumption of a common origin, 
an assumption sometimes notoriously at variance with 
fact; and, to repeat the historian's words, "if a family 
became extinct, its share returned to the common 
stock." In old Roman law, unclaimed inheritances 
escheated to the Gentiles. It is further suspected 
by all who have examined their history that the 



CHAP. VIII. TYPE OF THE COMMUNITY. 265 

Communities, like the Gentes, have been very gene- 
rally adulterated by the admission of strangers, but 
the exact mode of absorption cannot now be ascer- 
tained. At present, they are recruited, as Elphin- 
stone tells us, by the admission of purchasers, with 
the consent of the brotherhood. The acquisition of 
the adopted member is, however, of the nature of a 
universal succession ; together with the share he has 
bought, he succeeds to the liabilities which the vendor 
had incurred towards the aggregate group. He is an 
Emptor Familiae, and inherits the legal clothing of 
the person whose place he begins to fill. The consent 
of the whole brotherhood required for his admission 
may remind us of the consent which the Comitia 
Curiata, the Parliament of that larger brotherhood 
of self-styled kinsmen, the ancient Roman common- 
wealth, so strenuously insisted on as essential to the 
legalisation of an Adoption or the confirmation of a 
Will. 

The tokens of an extreme antiquity are discover- 
able in almost every single feature of the Indian 
Village Communities. We have so many independent 
reasons for suspecting that the infancy of law is 
distinguished by the prevalence of co-ownership, by 
the intermixture of personal with proprietary rights, 
and by the confusion of public with private duties, 
that we should be justified in deducing many im- 
portant conclusions from our observation of these 



266 RUSSIAN VILLAGES. chap. yiit. 

proprietary brotherhoods, even if no similarly com- 
pounded societies could be detected in any other 
part of the world. It happens, however, that much 
earnest curiosity has been very recently attracted to 
a similar set of phenomena in those parts of Europe 
which have been most slightly affected by the feudal 
transformation of property, and which in many 
important particulars have as close an affinity with 
the Eastern as with the Western world. The re- 
searches of M. de Haxthausen, M. Tengoborski, and 
others, have shown us that the Russian villages are 
not fortuitous assemblages of men, nor are they 
unions founded on contract ; they are naturally 
organised communities like those of India. It is true 
that these villages are always in theory the patrimony 
of some noble proprietor, and the peasants have within 
historical times been converted into the predial, and 
to a great extent into the personal, serfs of tlie 
seignior. But the pressure of this superior owner- 
ship has never crushed the ancient organisation of 
the village, and it is probable that the enactment of 
the Czar of Russia, who is supposed to have introduced 
serfdom, was really intended to prevent the peasants 
from abandoning that co-operation without which the 
old social order could not long be maintained. In 
the assumption of an agnatic connection between the 
villagers, in the blending of personal rights with pri- 
vileges of ownership, and in a variety of spontaneous 



CHAP. viii. RUSSIAN AND CROATIAN VILLAGES. 267 

provisions for internal administration, the Russian 
Village appears to be a nearly exact repetition of the 
Indian Community ; but there is one important dif- 
ference which we note with the greatest interest. 
The co-owners of an Indian village, though their pro- 
perty is blended, have their frights distinct, and this 
separation of rights is complete and continues indefi- 
nitely. The severance of rights is also theoretically 
complete in a Russian village, but there it is only 
temporary. After the expiration of a given, but not 
in all cases of the same, period, separate ownerships 
are extinguished, the land of the village is thrown 
into a mass, and then it is re-distributed among the 
families composing the community, according to their 
number. This repartition having been effected, the 
rights of families and of individuals are again allowed 
to branch out into various lines, which they continue 
to follow till another period of division comes round. 
An even more curious variation from this type of 
ownership occurs in some of those countries which 
long formed a debateable land between the Turkish 
empire and the possessions of the House of Austria. 
In Servia, in Croatia, and the Austrian Sclayonia, 
the villages are also brotherhoods of persons who are 
at once co-owners and kinsmen ; but there the inter- 
nal arrangements of the community differ from those 
adverted to in the last two examples. The substance 
of the common property is in this case neither divided 



268 VARIETIES OP THE COMMUNITT. chap. viii. 

in practice nor considered in theory as divisible, but 
the entire land is cultivated by the combined labour 
of all the villagers, and the produce is annually dis- 
tributed among the households, sometimes according 
to their supposed wants, sometimes according to rules 
which give to particular persons a fixed share of the 
usufruct. All these practices are traced by the jurists 
of the East of Europe to a principle which is asserted 
to be found in the earliest Sclavonian laws, the prin- 
ciple that the property of families cannot be divided 
for a perpetuity. 

The great interest of these phenomena in an in- 
quiry like the present arises from the light they 
throw on the developement of distinct proprietary 
rights inside the groups by which property seems to 
have been originally held. We have the strongest 
reason for thinking that property once belonged 
not to individuals nor even to isolated families, but 
to larger societies composed on the patriarchal model ; 
but the mode of transition from ancient to modem 
ownerships, obscure at best, would have been infi- 
nitely obscurer if several distinguishable forms of 
Village Communities had not been discovered and 
examined. It is worth while to attend to the varieties 
of internal arrangement within the patriarchal groups 
which are, or were till recently, observable among 
races of Indo-European blood. The chiefs of the 
ruder Highland clans used, it is said, to dole out 



CHAP. VIII. VARIETIES OP THE COMMUNITY. 269 

food to the heads of the households under their juris- 
diction at the very shortest intervals, and sometimes 
day by day. A periodical distribution is also made 
to the Sclavonian villagers of the Austrian and 
Turkish provinces by the elders of their body, but 
then it is a distribution once for all of the total 
produce of the year. In the Russian villages, how- 
ever, the substance of the property ceases to be looked 
upon as indivisible, and separate proprietary claims 
are allowed freely to grow up, but then the progress 
of separation is peremptorily arrested after it has 
continued a certain time. In India, not only is there 
no indivisibility of the common fund, but separate 
proprietorship in parts of it may be indefinitely 
prolonged and may branch out into any number of 
derivative ownerships, the de facto partition of the 
stock being, however, checked by inveterMe usage, 
and by the rule against the admission of strangers 
without the consent of the brotherhood. It is not of 
course intended to insist that these different forms of 
the Village-Community represent distinct stages in a 
process of transmutation which has been everywhere 
accomplished in the same manner. But, though the 
evidence does not warrant our going so far as this, it 
renders less presumptuous the conjecture that private 
property, in the shape in which we know it, was 
chiefly formed by the gradual disentanglement of the 
separate rights of individuals from the blended rights 



270 PHOBLEM AS TO ORIGIN OP PROPERTY, chap. viir. 

of a community. Our studies in the Law of Persons 
seemed to show us the Family expanding into the 
Agnatic group of kinsmen, then the Agnatic group 
dissolving into separate households ; lastly the house- 
hold supplanted by the individual; and it is now 
suggested that each step in the change corresponds to 
an analogous alteration in the nature of Ownership. 
If there be any truth in the suggestion, it is to be 
observed that it materially affects the problem which 
theorists on the origin of Property have generally 
proposed to themselves. The question — perhaps an 
insoluble one — which they have mostly agitated is, 
what were the motives which first induced men to 
respect each other's possessions? It may still be put, 
without much hope of finding an answer to it, in the 
form of any inquiry into the reasons which led one 
composite group to keep aloof from the domain of 
another. But, if it be true that far the most im- 
portant passage in the history of Private Property is 
its gradual elimination from the co-ownership of 
kinsmen, then the great point of inquiry is identi- 
cal with that which lies on the threshold of all 
historical law — what were the motives which origi- 
nally prompted men to hold together in the family 
union? To such a question, Jurisprudence, unas- 
sisted by other sciences, is not competent to give a 
reply. The fact can only be noted. 

The undivided state of property in ancient so- 



CHAP. VIII. ANCIENT DIFFICULTIES OF ALIENATION. 271 

cieties is consistent with a peculiar sharpness of 
division, which shows itself as soon as any single 
share is completely separated from the patrimony of 
the group. This phenomenon springs, doubtless, 
from the circumstance that the property is supposed 
to become the domain of a new group, so that any 
dealing with it, in its divided state, is a transaction 
between two highly complex bodies. I have already 
compared Ancient Law to Modem International 
Law, in respect of the size and complexity of the 
corporate associations, whose rights and duties it 
settles. As the contracts and conveyances known to 
ancient law are contracts and conveyances to which 
not single individuals, but organised companies of 
men, are parties, they are in the highest degree cere- 
monious ; they require a variety of symbolical acts 
and words intended to impress the business on the 
memory of all who take part in it; and they de- 
mand the presence of an inordinate number of wit- 
nesses. From these peculiarities, and others allied 
to them, springs the universally unmalleable charac- 
ter of the ancient forms of property. Sometimes the 
patrimony of the family is absolutely inalienable, as 
was the case with the Sclavonians, and still oftener, 
though alienations may not be entirely illegitimate, 
they are virtually impracticable, as among most of 
the Germanic tribes, from the necessity of having the 
consent of a large number of persons to the transfer. 



272 ANCIEKT DIFFICULTIES OF ALIENATION, chap. viu. 

Where these impediments do not exist, or can be 
surmounted, the act of conveyance itself is generally 
burdened with a perfect load of ceremony, in which 
not one iota can be safely neglected* Ancient law 
uniformly refuses to dispense with a single gesture, 
however grotesque; with a single syllable, however 
its meaning may have been forgotten ; with a single 
witness, however superfluous may be his testimony. 
The entire solemnities must be scrupulously com- 
pleted by persons legally entitled to take part of it, 
or else the conveyance is null, and the seller is 
re-established in the rights of which he had vainly 
attempted to divest himself. 

These various obstacles to the free circulation of 
the objects of use and enjoyment, begin of course to 
make themselves felt as soon as society has acquired 
even a slight degree of activity, and the expedients 
by which advancing communities endeavour to over- 
come them form the staple of the history of Property. 
Of such expedients there is one w^iich takes prece- 
dence of the rest from its antiquity and universality. 
The idea seems to have spontaneously suggested 
itself to a great number of early societies, to classify 
property into kinds. One kind or sort of property 
is placed on a lower footing of dignity than the 
others, but at the same time is relieved from the 
fetters which antiquity has imposed on them. Sub- 
sequently, the superior convenience of the rules go- 



CHAP. VIII. KINDS OF PEOPERTY. 273 

veming the transfer and descent of the lower order 
of property becomes generally recognised, and by a 
gradual course of innovation the plasticity of the 
less dignified class of valuable objects is communi- 
cated to the classes which stand conventionally 
higher. The history of Roman Property Law is the 
history of the assimilation of Res Mancipi to Res Nee 
Mancipi. The history of Property on the European 
Continent is the history of the subversion of the 
feudalised law of land by the Romanised law of 
moveables; and, though the history of ownership in 
England is not nearly completed, it is visibly the law 
of personalty which threatens to absorb and anni- 
hilate the law of realty. 

The only natural classification of the objects of 
enjoyment, the only classification which corresponds 
with an essential difference in the subject-matter, is 
that which divides them into Moveables and Immove- 
ables. Familiar as is this classification to juris- 
prudence, it was very slowly developed by Roman 
law, from which we inherit it, and was only finally 
adopted by it in its latest stage. The classifications 
of Ancient Law have sometimes a superficial resem- 
blance to this. They occasionally divide property 
into categories, and place immoveables in one of them ; 
but then it is found that they either class along 
with immoveables a number of objects which have 
no sort of relation with them, or else divorce them 



274 ANCIENT KINDS OF PROPERTY. chap. vni. 

from various rights to which they have a close affi- 
nity. Thus, the Res Mancipi of Roman Law included 
not only land, but slaves, horses, and oxen. Scottish 
law ranks with land a certain class of securities, and 
Hindoo law associates it with slaves. English law, 
on the other hand, parts leases of land for years from 
other interests in the soil, and joins them to per- 
sonalty under the name of chattels real. Moreover, 
the classifications of Ancient Law are classifications 
implying superiority and inferiority; while the dis- 
tinction between moveables and immoveables, so long 
at least as it was confined to Roman jurisprudence, 
carried with it no suggestion whatever of a difference 
in dignity. The Res Mancipi, however, did certainly 
at first enjoy a precedence over the Res Nee Man- 
cipi, as did heritable property in Scotland and realty 
in England, over the personalty to which they were 
opposed. The lawyers of all systems have spared no 
pains in striving to refer these classifications to some 
intelligible principle ; but the reasons of the severance 
must ever be vainly sought for in the philosophy of 
law: they belong not to its philosophy, but to its 
history. The explanation which appears to cover 
the greatest number of instances is, that the objects 
of enjoyment honoured above the rest were the forms 
of property known first and earliest to each particular 
community, and dignified therefore emphatically with 
the designation of Property. On the other hand, the 



CHAP. VIII. ANCIENT CLASSIFICATIONS. 275 

articles not enumerated among the favoured objects 
seem to have been placed on a lower standing, be- 
cause the knowledge of their value was posterior to 
the epoch at which the catalogue of superior property 
was settled. They were at first unknown, rare, li- 
mited in their uses, or else regarded as mere appen- 
dages to the privileged objects. Thus, though the 
Roman Res Mancipi included a number of moveable 
articles of great value, still the most costly jewels 
were never allowed to take rank as Res Mancipi, be- 
cause they were unknown to the early Romans. In 
the same way chattels real in England are said to have 
been degraded to the footing of personalty, from the 
infrequency and valuelessness of such estates under 
the feudal land-law. But the grand point of interest 
is, the continued degradation of these commodities 
when their importance had increased and their num- 
ber had multiplied. Why were they not successively 
included among the favoured objects of enjoyment? 
One reason is found in the stubbornness with which 
Ancient Law adheres to its classifications. It is a 
characteristic both of uneducated minds and of early 
societies, that they are little able to conceive a 
general rule apart from the particular applications of 
it with which they are practically familiar. They 
cannot dissociate a general term or maxim from the 
special examples which meet them in daily experi- 
ence; and in this way the designation covering the 

T 2 



276 DEGRADATION OF INFERIOR PROPERTY, chap. rat. 

best-known forms of property is denied to articles 
which exactly resemble them in being objects of en- 
joyment and subjects of right. But to these influ- 
ences, which exert peculiar force in a subject-matter 
so stable as that of law, are afterwards added others 
more consistent with progress in enlightenment and 
in the conceptions of general expediency. Courts 
and lawyers become at last alive to the inconvenience 
of the embarrassing formalities required for the 
transfer, recovery, or devolution of the favoured 
commodities, and grow unwilling to fetter the 
newer descriptions of property with the technical 
trammels which -characterised the infancy of law. 
Hence arises a disposition to keep these last on a 
lower grade in the arrangements of Jurisprudence, 
and to permit their transfer by simpler processes 
than those which, in archaic conveyances, serve as 
stumbling-blocks to good faith and stepping-stones 
to iraud. We are perhaps in some danger of under- 
rating the inconveniences of the ancient modes of 
transfer. Our instruments of conveyance are writ- 
ten, so that their language, well pondered by the 
professional draftsman, is rarely defective in accu- 
racy. But an ancient conveyance was not written, 
but acted. Gestures and words took the place of 
written technical phraseology, and any formula mis- 
pronounced, or symbolical act omitted, would have 
vitiated the proceeding as fatally as a material mis- 



CHAP.viii. DEFINITION OF RES MANCIPI. 277 

take in stating the uses or setting out the remainders 
would, two hundred years ago, have vitiated an 
English deed. Tndeed, the mischiefs of the archaic 
ceremonial are even thus only half stated. So long 
as elaborate conveyances, written or acted, are re- 
quired for the alienation of land alone, the chances 
of mistake are not considerable in the transfer of a 
description of property which is seldom got rid of 
with much precipitation. But the higher class of 
property in the ancient world comprised not only 
land but several of the commonest and several of the 
most valuable moveables. When once the wheels of 
society had begun to move quickly, there must have 
been immense inconvenience in demanding a highly 
intricate form of transfer for a horse or an ox, or for 
the most costly chattel of the old world — the Slave* 
Such commodities must have been constantly and 
even ordinarily conveyed with incomplete forms, and 
held, therefore, under imperfect titles. 

The Res Mancipi of old Roman law were, land — 
in historical times, land on Italian soil, — slaves and 
beasts of burden, such as horses and oxen. It is 
impossible to doubt that the objects which make up 
the clas's are the instruments of agricultural labour, 
the commodities of first consequence to a primitive 
people. Such commodities were at first, I imagine, 
called emphatically Things or Property, and the mode 
of conveyance by which they were transferred was 

T 3 



278 RES NEC MANCIPI. chap. viii. 

called a Mancipium or Mancipation ; but it was not 
probably till much later that they received the dis- 
tinctive appellation of Res Mancipi, " Things which 
require a Mancipation/^ By their side there may 
have existed or grown up a class of objects, for which 
it was not worth while to insist upon the full cere- 
mony of Mancipation. It would be enough if, in 
transferring these last from owner to owner, a part 
only of the ordinary formalities were proceeded with, 
namely, that actual delivery, physical transfer, or 
tradition^ which is the most obvious index of a change 
of proprietorship. Such commodities were the Res 
Nee Mancipi of the ancient jurisprudence, "things 
which did not require a Mancipation," little prized 
probably at first, and hot often passed from one group 
of proprietors to another. While, however, the list of 
the Res Mancipi was irrevocably closed, that of the 
Res Nee Mancipi admitted of indefinite expansion; 
and hence every fresh conquest of man over material 
nature added an item to the Res Nee Mancipi, or 
effected an improvement in those already recognised* 
Insensibly, therefore, they mounted to an equality 
with the Res Mancipi, and the impression of an 
intrinsic inferiority being thus dissipated, men began 
to observe the manifold advantages of the simple 
formality which accompanied their transfer over the 
more intricate and more venerable ceremonial. Two 
of the agents of legal amelioration. Fictions and 
Equity, were assiduously employed by the Roman 



CHAP. VIII. TRADITION. 279 

lawyers to give the practical eflfects of a Mancipation 
to a Tradition ; and, though Koman legislators long 
shrank from enacting that the right of property in a 
Res Mancipi should be immediately transferred by 
bare delivery of the article, yet even this step was at 
last ventured upon by Justinian, in whose jurispru* 
dence the difference between Res Mancipi and Res 
Nee Mancipi disappears, and Tradition or Delivery 
becomes the one great conveyance known to the law. 
The marked preference which the Roman lawyers 
very early gave to Tradition caused them to assign 
it a place in their theory which has helped to blind 
their modern disciples to its true history. It was 
classed among the " natural " modes of acquisition, 
both because it was generally practised among the 
Italian tribes, and because it was a process which 
attained its object by the simplest mechanism. If 
the expressions of the jurisconsults be pressed, they 
undoubtedly imply that Tradition, which belongs to 
the Law Natural, is more ancient than Mancipation, 
which is an institution of Civil Society; and this, I 
need not say, is the exact reverse of the truth. 

The distinction between Res Mancipi and Res Nee 
Mancipi is the type of a class of distinctions to which 
civilisation is much indebted, distinctions which run 
through the whole mass of commodities, placing a few 
of them in a class by themselves, and relegating the 
others to a lower category. The inferior kinds of 

T 4 



280 OTHER ANCIENT CLASSIFICATIONS. chap. viii. 

property are first, from disdain and disregard, re- 
leased from the perplexed ceremonies in which primi- 
tive law delights, and thus afterward^, in another state 
of intellectual progress, the simple methods of transfer 
and recovery which have been allowed to come into 
use serve as a model which condemns by its conve- 
nience and simplicity the cumbrous solemnities in- 
herited from ancient days. But, in some societies, the 
trammels in which Property is tied up are much too 
complicated and stringent to be relaxed in so easy a 
manner. Whenever male children have been bom to 
a Hindoo, the law of India, as I have stated, gives 
them all an interest in his property, and makes their 
consent a necessary condition of its alienation. In 
the same spirit, the general usage of the old Germanic 
peoples — it is remarkable that the Anglo-Saxon cus- 
toms seem to have been an exception — forbade aliena- 
tions without the consent of the male children ; and 
the primitive law of the Sclavonians even prohibited 
them altogether. It is evident that such impediments 
as these cannot be overcome by a distinction between 
kinds of property, inasmuch as the difficulty extends 
to commodities of all sorts; and accordingly. Ancient 
Law, when once launched on a course of improvement, 
encounters them with a distinction of another charac- 
ter, a distinction classifying property, not according 
to its nature but according to its origin. In India, 
where there are traces of both systems of classifica- 



CHAP. VIII. INHERITANCES AND ACQUISITIONS. 281 

tion, the one which we are considering is exempli- 
fied in the difference which Hindoo law establishes 
between Inheritances and Acquisitions. The inherited 
property of the father is shared by the children as 
soon as they are bom; but according to the custom 
of most provinces, the acquisitions made by him 
during his lifetime are wholly his own, and can be 
transferred by him at pleasure. A similar distinction 
was not unknown to Roman law, in which the earliest 
innovation on the Parental Powers took the form of 
a permission given to the son to keep for himself 
whatever he might have acquired in military service. 
But the most extensive use ever made of this mode of 
classification appears to have been among the Ger- 
mans. I have repeatedly stated that the allod^ though 
not inalienable, was commonly transferable with the 
greatest difficulty; and moreover, it descended ex- 
clusively to the agnatic kindred. Hence an extraor- 
dinary variety of distinctions came to be recognised, 
all intended to diminish the inconveniences insepara- 
ble from allodial property. The wehrgeld^ for ex- 
ample, or composition for the homicide of a relative, 
which occupies so large a space in German jurispru- 
dence, formed no part of the family domain, and 
descended according to rules of succession altogether 
different. Similarly, the reipus^ or fine leviable on 
the re-marriage of a widow, did not enter into the 
aUod of the person to whom it was paid, and followed 



282 INHERITANCES AND ACQUISITIONS, chap. vui. 

a line of devolution in which the privileges of the 
agnates were neglected. The law, too, as among 
the Hindoos, distinguished the Acquisitions of the 
chief of the household from his Inherited property, 
and permitted him to deal with them under much more 
liberal conditions. Classifications of the other sort 
were also admitted, and the familiar distinction 
drawn between land and moveables ; but moveable 
property was divided into several subordinate cate- 
gories, to each of which diflferent rules applied. This 
exuberance of classification, which may strike us as 
strange in so rude a people as the German conquerors 
of the Empire, is doubtless to be explained by the 
presence in their systems of a considerable element of 
Roman law, absorbed by them, during their long 
sojourn on the confines of the Roman dominion. It 
is not difficult to trace a great number of the rules 
governing the transfer and devolution of the commo- 
dities which lay outside the aUodj to their source in 
Roman jurisprudence, from which they were pro- 
bably borrowed at widely distant epochs, and in 
fragmentary importations. How far the obstacles to 
the free circulation of property were surmounted by 
such contrivances, we have not the means even of 
conjecturing, for the distinctions adverted to have no 
modem history. As I before explained, the allodial 
form of property was entirely lost in the feudal, and 
when the consolidation of feudalism was once com- 



CHAP. viir. LAND AND GOODS. 283 

pleted, there was practically but one distinction left 
standing of all those which had been known to the 
western world— the distinction between land and 
goods, immoveables and moveables. Externally this 
distinction was the saine with that which Roman law 
had finally accepted, but the law of the middle ages 
differed from that of Rome in distinctly consider- 
ing immoveable property to be more dignified than 
moveable. Yet this one sample is enough to 
show the importance of the class of expedients 
to which it belongs. In all the countries governed 
by systems based on the French codes, that is, 
through much the greatest part of the Continent of 
Europe, the law of moveables, which was always 
Roman law, has superseded and annulled the feudal 
law of land. England is the only country of import- 
ance in which this transmutation, though it has gone 
some way, is not nearly accomplished. Our own, too, 
it may be added, is the only considerable European 
country in which the separation of moveables from 
immoveables has been somewhat disturbed by the same 
influences which caused the ancient classifications to 
depart from the only one which is countenanced by 
nature. In the main, the English distinction has been 
between land and goods ; but a certain class of goods 
have gone as heir-looms with the land, and a certain 
description of interests in land have from historical 
causes been ranked with personalty. This is not the 



284 PRESCRIPTION. chap. viii. 

only instance in which English jurisprudence, stand- 
ing apart from the main current of legal modification, 
has reproduced phenomena of archaic law. 

I proceed to notice one or two more contrivances 
by which the ancient trammels of proprietary right 
were more or less successfully relaxed, premising that 
the scheme of this treatise only permits me to men- 
tion those which are of great antiquity. On one of 
them in particular it is necessary to dwell for a mo- 
ment or two, because persons unacquainted with the 
early history of law will not be easily persuaded that 
a principle, of which modem jurisprudence has very 
slowly and with the greatest difficulty obtained the 
recognition, was really familiar to the very infancy of 
legal science. There is no principle in all law which, 
the modems, in spite of its beneficial character, have 
been so loath to adopt and to carry to its legitimate 
consequences as that which was known to the Romans 
as Usucapion, and which has descended to modem 
jurisprudence under the name of Prescription. It 
was a positive rule of the oldest Roman law, a rule 
older than the Twelve Tables, that commodities 
which had been uninterruptedly possessed for a cer- 
tain period became the property of the possessor. 
The period of possession was exceedingly short — 
one or two years according to the nature of the 
commodities — and in historical times Usucapion 
was only allowed to operate when possession had 



CHAP. VIII. INFLUENCE OP CANON LAW. 285 

commenced in a particular way; but I think it 
likely that at a less advanced epoch possession was 
converted into ownership under conditions even less 
severe than we read of in our authorities. As I 
have said before, I am far from asserting that the 
respect of men for de facto possession is a pheno- 
menon which jurisprudence can account for by itself, 
but it is very necessary to remark that primitive 
societies, in adopting the principle of Usucapion, 
were not beset with any of the speculative doubts 
and hesitations which have impeded its reception 
among the modems. Prescriptions were viewed by 
the modem lawyers, first with repugnance, afterwards 
with reluctant approval. In several countries, in- 
cluding our own, legislation long declined to advance 
beyond the rude device of barring all actions based 
on a wrong which had been sufiered earlier than 
a fixed point of time in the past, generally the first 
year of some proceeding reign; nor was it till the 
middle ages had finally closed, and James the First 
had ascended the throne of England, that we ob- 
tained a true statute of limitation of a very im- 
perfect kind. This tardiness in copying one of the 
most famous chapters of Roman law, which was no 
doubt constantly read by the majority of European 
lawyers, the modem world owes to the influence of 
the Canon Law. The ecclesiastical customs out of 
which the Canon Law grew, concerned as they were 



2«6 INFLUENCE OF CANON LAW. chap, vui, 

with sacred or quasi-sacred interests, very naturally 
regarded the pririleges which they conferred as in- 
capable of being lost through disuse however pro- 
longed; and in accordance with this view, the spiri- 
tual jurisprudence, when afterwards consolidated, was 
distinguished by a marked leaning against Prescrip- 
tions. It was the fate of the Canon Law, when held 
up by the clerical lawyers as a pattern to secular legis- 
lation, to have a peculiar influence on first principles. 
It gave to the bodies of custom which were formed 
throughout Europe far fewer express rules than did 
the Roman law, but then it seems to have communi- 
cated a bias to professional opinion on a surprising 
number of fundamental points, and the tendencies 
thus produced progressively gained strength as each 
system was developed. One of the dispositions it 
produced was a disrelish for Prescriptions; but I do 
not know that this prejudice would have operated as 
powerfully as it has done, if it had not fallen in 
with the doctrine of the scholastic jurists of the 
realist sect, who taught that, whatever turn actual 
legislation might take, a right^ how long soever neg- 
lected, was in point of fact indestructible. The 
remains of this state of feeling stiQ exist. Wherever 
the philosophy of law is earnestly discussed, ques- 
tions respecting the speculative basis of Prescription 
are always hotly disputed ; and it is still a point of 
the greatest interest in France and Germany, whether 



CHAP. VIII. ROMAN USUCAPION. 287 

a person who has been out of possession for a series 
of years is deprived of his ownership as a penalty 
for his neglect, or loses it through the summary inter- 
position of the law in its desire to have a, finis litium. 
But no such scruples troubled the mind of early 
Roman society. Their ancient usages directly took 
away the ownership of everybody who had been out 
of possession, under certain circumstances, during 
one or two years. What was the exact tenor of the 
rule of Usucapion in its earliest shape, it is not 
easy to say ; but, taken with the limitations which 
we find attending it in the books, it was a most 
useful security against the mischiefs of a too cumbrous 
system of conveyance. In order to have the benefit 
of Usucapion, it was necessary that the adverse pos- 
session should have begun in good faith, that is, with 
bdief on the part of the possessor that he was law- 
fully acquiring the property, and it was farther re- 
quired that the commodity should have been trans- 
ferred to him by some mode of alienation which, 
however unequal to conferring a complete title in 
the particular case, was at least recognised by the law. 
In the case therefore of a Mancipation, however 
slovenly the performance might have been, yet if it 
had been carried so far as to involve a Tradition or 
Delivery, the vice of the title would be cured by 
Usucapion in two years at most. I know nothing in 
the practice of the Romans which testifies so strongly 



288 COLLUSIVB RECOVERIES. chap. vin. 

to their legal genius as the use which they made of 
Usucapion. The difficulties which beset them were 
nearly the same with those which embarrassed and 
still embarrass the lawyers of England. Owing to 
the complexity of their system, which as yet they 
had neither the courage nor the power to recon- 
struct, actual right was constantly getting divorced 
from technical right, the equitable ownership from 
the legal. But Usucapion, as manipulated by the 
jurisconsults, supplied a self-acting toiachinery, by 
which the defects of titles to property were always 
in course of being cured, and by which the owner- 
ships that were temporarily separated were again 
rapidly cemented together with the briefest possible 
delay. Usucapion did not lose its advantages till 
the reforms of Justinian. But as soon as law and 
equity had been completely fused, and when Manci- 
pation ceased to be the Roman conveyance, there was 
no further necessity for the ancient contrivance, and 
Usucapion, with its periods of time considerably 
lengthened, became the Prescription which has at 
length been adopted by nearly all systems of modem 
law. 

I pass by with brief mention another expedient 
having the same object with the last, which, though it 
did not immediately make its appearance in English 
legal history, was of immemorial antiquity in Roman 
law; such indeed is its apparent age that some 



CHAP. VIII. COLLUSIVE RECOVERIES. 289 

German civilians, not sufficiently aware of the light 
thrown on the subject by the analogies of English 
law, have thought it even older than the Mancipa- 
tion. I speak of the Cessio in Jure, a collusive 
recovery, in a Court of law, of property sought to 
be conveyed. The plaintiff claimed the subject of 
this proceeding with the ordinary forms of a litiga- 
tion; the defendant made default; and the commodity 
was of course adjudged to the plaintiff. I need 
scarcely remind the English lawyer that this ex- 
pedient suggested itself to our forefathers, and pro- 
duced those famous Fines and Recoveries which did 
so much to undo the harshest tranmiels of the feudal 
land-law. The Roman and English contrivances 
have very much in common and illustrate each other 
most instructively, but there is this difference be- 
tween them, that the object of the English lawyers 
was to remove complications already introduced into 
the title, while the Roman jurisconsults sought to 
prevent them by substituting a mode of transfer 
necessarily unimpeachable for one which too often 
miscarried. The device is in fact one which suggests^ 
itself as soon as Courts of Law are in steady opera- 
tion, but are nevertheless stiU under the empire of 
primitive notions. In an advanced state of legal 
opinion, tribunals regard collusive litigation as an 
abuse of their procedure; but there has always 
been a time when, if their forms were scrupu-. 

u 




290 PROPERTY AND POSSESSION. chap. viii. 

lously complied with, they never dreamed of looking 
further. 

The influence of Courts of Law and of their proce- 
dure upon Property has been most extensive, but thy 
subject is too large for the dimensions of this treatise, 
and would carry us further down the course of 1 
history than is consistent with its scheme. It is 
desirable, however, to mention, that to this influence 
we must attribute the importance of the distinction 
between Property and Possession — not, indeed, the 
distinction itself, which (in the language of an eminentv 
English civuian) is the same thing as the distinction 
between the legal right to act upon a thing and the 
physical power to do so — ^but the extraordinary im- 
portance which the distinction has obtained in the 
philosophy of law. Few educated persons are so 
little versed in legal literature as not to have heard 
that the language of the Roman jurisconsults on the 
subject of Possession long occasioned the greatest 
possible perplexity, and that the genius of Savigny 
is supposed to have chiefly proved itself by the solu- 
tion which he discovered for the enigma. Possession, 
• 

in fact, when employed by the Roman lawyers, ap- 
pears to have contracted a shade of meaning not 
easily accounted for. The word, as appears from its 
etymology, must have originally denoted physical 
contact or physical contact resumeable at pleasure ; 
but, as actually used without any qualifying epithet, 



ciiAP. viu. PllOrERTY AND POSSESSION. 291 

it signifies not simply physical detention, but physical 
detention coupled with the intention to hold the thing 
detained as one's own. Savigny, following Niebuhr, 
perceived that for this anomaly there could only be a 
historical origin. He pointed out that the Patrician 
burghers of Rome, who had become tenants of the 
greatest part of the public domain at nominal rents, 
were, in the view of the old Roman law, mere posses- 
sors, but then they were possessors intending to keep 
their land against all comers. They, in truth, put 
forward a claim almost identical with that which has 
recently been advanced in England by tne lessees of 
Church lands. Admitting that in theory they were the 
tenants-at-will of the state, they contended that time 
and undisturbed enjoyment had ripened their holding 
into a species of ownership, and that it would be 
unjust to eject them for the purpose of redistributing 
the domain. The association of this claim with the 
Patrician tenancies, permanently influenced the sense 
of " possession." Meanwhile the only legal remedies of 
which the tenants could avail themselves, if ejected 
or threatened with disturbance, were the Possessory 
Interdicts, summary processes of Roman law which 
were either expressly devised by the Prastor for their 
protection, or else, according to another theory, had 
in older times been employed for the provisional 
maintenance of possessions pending the settlement of 
questions of legal right. It came, therefore, to be 

u 2 



29i PROPERTY AND POSSESSION. chap. viif. 

^inderstood that everybody who possessed property 
as his own had the power of demanding the Interdicts, 
and, by a system of highly artificial pleading, the 
Interdictal process was moulded into a shape fitted 
for the trial of conflicting claims to a disputed pos- 
session. Then commenced a movement which, as 
Mr. John Austin pointed out, exactly reproduced 
itself in English law. Proprietors, domini, began to 
prefer the simpler forms or speedier course of the 
Interdict to the lagging and intricate formalities of 
the Real Action, and for the purpose of availing 
themselves of the possessory remedy fell back upon 
the possession which was supposed to be involved in 
their proprietorship. The liberty conceded to persons 
who were not true Possessors, but Owners, to vindicate 
their rights by possessory remedies, though it may 
have been at first a boon, had ultimately the efiect of 
seriously deteriorating both English and Roman juris* 
prudence. The Roman law owes to it those subtleties 
on the subject of Possession which have done so much 
to discredit it, while English law, after the actions 
which it appropriated to the recovery of real property 
had fallen into the most hopeless confusion, got rid 
at last of the whole tangled mass by a heroic remedy. 
No one can doubt that the virtual abolition of the 
English real^actions which took place nearly thirty 
years since was a public benefit, but still persons sensi- 
tive to the harmonies of jurisprudence will lament 



CHAP. viir. LAW AND EQUITY. f^i 

that, instead of cleansing, improving, and simplifying . 
the true proprietary actions, we sacrificed them all to 
the possessory action of ejectment, thus basing our 
whole system of land recovery upon a legal fiction. 

Legal tribunals have also powerfully assisted to 
shape and modify conceptions of proprietary right by 
means of the distinction between Law and Equity, 
which always makes its first appearance as a distinc- 
tion between jurisdictions. Equitable property in 
England is simply property held under the jurisdic- 
tion of the Court of Chancery. At Rome, the Prae- 
tor's Edict introduced its novel principles in the guise 
of a promise that under certain circumstances a par- 
ticular action or a particular plea would be granted; 
and, accordingly, the property in bonis^ or Equitable 
Property, of Roman law was property exclusively 
protected by remedies which had their source in the 
Edict. The mechanism by which equitable rights 
were saved from being overridden by the claims of 
the legal owner was somewhat dificrent in the two 
systems. With us their independence is secured 
by the Injunction of the Court of Chancery. Since 
however Law and Equity, while not as yet consoli- 
dated, were administered under the Roman system 
by the same Court, nothing like the Injunction was 
required, and the Magistrate took the Simpler course 
of refusing to grant to the Civil Law Owner those 
actions and pleas by which .alone he could obtain the 

u 3 



294 EQUITABLE PROPERTY. chap. viu. 

property that belonged in equity to another. But 
the practical operation of both systems was nearly 
the same. Both, by means of a distinction in proce- 
dure, were able to preserve new forms of property in 
a sort of provisional existence, until the time should 
come when they were recognised by the whole law. 
In this way, the Roman Praetor gave an immediate 
right of property to the person who had acquired a 
Res Mancipi by mere delivery, without waiting for 
the ripening of Usucapion. Similarly he in time re- 
cognised an ownership in the Mortgagee who had at 
first been a mere " bailee " or depositary, and in the 
Emphyteuta, or tenant of land which was subject to 
a fixed perpetual rent. Following a parallel line of 
progress, the English Court of Chancery created a 
special proprietorship for the Mortgagor, for the 
Cestui que Trust, for the Married Woman who had 
the advantage of a particular kind of settlement, and 
for the Purchaser who had not yet acquired a com- 
plete legal ownership. All these are examples in 
which forms of proprietary right, distinctly new, 
were recognised and preserved. But indirectly Pro- 
perty has been affected in a thousand ways by equity 
both in England and at Rome. Into whatever corner 
of jurisprudence its authors pushed the powerful in- 
strument in their command, they were sure to meet, 
and touch, and more or less materially modify the 
law of property. When in the preceding pages I have 



CHAP. VIII. FEUDAL VIEW OF OWNERSHIP. 295 

spoken of certain ancient legal distinctions and expe- 
dients as having powerfully affected the history of 
ownership, I must be understood to mean that the 
greatest part of their influence has arisen from the 
hints and suggestions of improvement infused by them 
into the mental atmosphere which was breathed by 
the fabricators of equitable systems. 

But to describe the influence of Equity on Owner- 
ship would be to write its history down to our own 
days. I have alluded to it principally because several 
esteemed contemporary writers have thought that in 
the Roman severance of Equitable from Legalproperty 
we have the clue to that difference in the conception 
of Ownership, which apparently distinguishes the law 
of the middle ages from the law of the Roman Em- 
pire. The leading characteristic of the feudal con- 
ception is its recognition of a double proprietorship, 
the superior ownership of the lord of the fief coexist- 
ing with the inferior property or estate of the tenant. 
Now, this duplication of proprietary right looks, it is 
urged, extremely like a generalised form of the Ro- 
man distribution of rights over property into Quiri- 
tartan or legal, and (to use a word of late origin) 
Bonitarian or equitable. Gains himself observes 
upon the splitting of dominion into two parts as a 
singularity of Roman law, and expressly contrasts it 
with the entire or allodial ownership to which other 
nations were accustomed. Justinian, it is true, re- 

u 4 



*296 ROMAN AND BARBARIAN LAW. chap. viii. 

consolidated dominion into one, but then it was the 
partially reformed system of the Western Empire, 
and not Justinian's jurisprudence, with which the 
barbarians were in contact during so many centuries. 
While they remained poised on the edge of the Em- 
pire, it may well be that they learned this distinction, 
which afterwards bore remarkable fruit. In favour 
of this theory, it must at all events be admitted that 
the element of Roman law in the various bodies of 
barbarian custom has been very imperfectly ex- 
amined. The erroneous or insufficient theories which 
have served to explain Feudalism resemble each other 
in their tendency to draw off attention from this par- 
ticular ingredient in its texture. The older investiga- 
tors, who have been mostly followed in this country, 
attached an exclusive importance to the circumstances 
of the turbulent period during which the Feudal 
system grew to maturity ; and in later times a new 
source of error has been added to those already exist- 
ing, in that pride of nationality which has led Grerman 
writers to exaggerate the completeness of the social 
fabric which their forefathers had built up before 
their appearance in the Roman world. One or two 
English inquirers who looked in the right quarter 
for the foundations of the feudal system, failed never- 
theless to conduct their investigations to any satis- 
factory result, either from searching too exclusively 
for analogies in the compilations of Justinian, or from 



CHAP. VIII. ROMAN AND BARBARIAN LAW. 297 

confining their attention to the compendia of Roman 
law which are found appended to some of the extant 
barbarian codes. But, if Roman jurisprudence had 
any influence on the barbarous societies, it had pro- 
bably produced the greatest part of its effects before 
the legislation of Justinian, and before the prepara- 
tion of these compendia. It was not the reformed 
and purified jurisprudence of Justinian, but the 
undigested system which prevailed in the Western 
Empire, and which the Eastern Corpus Juris never 
succeeded in displacing, that I conceive to have 
clothed with flesh and muscle the scanty skeleton of 
barbarous usage. The change must be supposed 
to have taken place before the Germanic tribes had 
distinctly appropriated, as conquerors, any portion 
of the Roman dominions, and therefore long before 
Germanic monarchs had ordered breviaries of Roman 
law to be drawn up for the use of their Roman 
subjects. The necessity for some such hypothesis 
will be felt by everybody who can appreciate the 
difference between archaic and developed law. Rude 
as are the Leges Barharorum which remain to us, 
they are not rude enough to satisfy the theory of 
their purely barbarous origin; nor have we any 
reason for believing that we have received, in written 
records, more than a fraction of the fixed rules which 
were practised among themselves by the members of 
the conquering tribes. If we can once persuade our- 



298 THE EMPHYTEUSIS. chap, yuu 

selves that a considerable element of debased Roman 
law already existed in the barbarian systems, we 
shall have done something to remove a grave diffi- 
culty. The German law of the conquerors and the 
Roman law of their subjects would not have com- 
bined if they had not possessed more affinity for each 
other than refined jurisprudence has usually for the 
customs of savages. It is extremely likely that the 
codes of the barbarians, archaic as they seem, are 
only a compound of true primitive usage with half- 
understood Roman rules, and that it was the foreign 
ingredient which enabled them to coalesce with a Ro- 
man jurisprudence that had already receded some- 
what from the comparative finish which it had 
acquired under the Western Emperors. 

But, though all this must be allowed, there are 
several considerations which render it unlikely that 
the feudal form of ownership was directly suggested 
by the Roman duplication of domainial rights. The 
distinction between legal and equitable property 
strikes one as a subtlety little likely to be appre- 
ciated by barbarians; and, moreover, it can scarcely 
be understood unless Courts of Law are contemplated 
in regular operation. But the strongest reason 
against this theory is the existence in Roman Law of 
a form of property — a creation of Equity, it is true 
— which supplies a much simpler explanation of the 
transition from one set of ideas to the other. This 



CHAP. VIII. SYSTEMS OF TENANCY. / -209 V ?4'liOOLl 

is the Emphyteusis, upon which the Fief ofvttiteJ-^'^? ART. 
middle ages has often been £Eithered, though withot 
much knowledge of the exact share which it had in 
bringing feudal ownership into the world. The 
truth is that the Emphyteusis, not probably as yet 
known by its Greek designation, marks one stage in 
a current of ideas which led ultimately to feudalism. 
The first mention in Roman history of estates larger 
than could be farmed by a Paterfamilias, with his 
household of sons and slaves, occurs when we come 
to the holdings of the Roman patricians. These 
great proprietors appear to have had no idea of any 
system of farming by free tenants. Their latifundia 
seem to have been universally cultivated by slave- 
gangs, under bailiffs who were themselves slaves or 
freedmen; and the only organisation attempted ap- 
pears to have consisted in dividing the inferior slaves 
into small bodies, and making them the peculium of 
the better and trustier sort, who thus acquired a kind 
of interest in the efficiency of their labour. This 
system was, however, especially disadvantageous to 
one class of estated proprietors, the Municipalities. 
Functionaries in Italy were changed with the rapid- 
ity which often surprises us in the administration of 
Rome herself; so that the superintendence of a large 
landed domain by an Italian corporation must have 
been excessively imperfect. Accordingly, we are 
told that with the municipalities began the practice 



800 THE COLONI. cuap. viii. 

of letting out agri vectigtUes, that is, of leasing land 
for a perpetuity to a free tenant, at a fixed rent, and 
under certain conditions. The plan was afterwards 
extensively imitated by individual proprietors, and 
the tenant, whose relation to the owner had origin- 
ally been determined by his contract, was subse- 
quently recognised by the Praetor as having himself 
a qualified proprietorship, which in time became 
known as an Emphyteusis. From this point the his- 
tory of tenure parts into two branches. In the course 
of that long period during which our records of the 
Eoman Empire are most incomplete, the slave-gangs 
of the great Roman families became transformed 
into the colonic whose origin and situation constitute 
one of the obscurest questions in all history. We 
may suspect that they were formed partly by the ele- 
vation of the slaves, and partly by the degradation of 
the free farmers ; and that they prove the richer classes 
of the Roman Empire to have become aware of the 
increased value which landed property obtains when 
the cultivator has an interest in the produce of the 
land. We know that their servitude was predial ; that 
it wanted many of the characteristics of absolute sla- 
very, and that they acquitted their service to the 
landlord in rendering to him a fixed portion of the 
annual crop. We know further that they survived 
all the mutations of society in the ancient and modem 
worlds. Though included in the lower courses of the 



CHAP. vin. THE EMPHYTEUSIS. 301 

feudal structure, they continued in many countries to 
render to the landlord precisely the same dues which 
they had paid to the Roman dominus^ and from a 
particular class among them, the coloni medietarii 
who reserved half the produce for the owner, are 
descended the metayer tenantry, who still conduct 
the cultivation of the soil in almost all the South of 
Europe. On the other hand, the Emphyteusis, if we 
may so interpret the allusions to it in the Corpus 
Juria^ became a favourite and beneficial modification 
of property; and it may be conjectured that wherever 
free farmers existed, it was this tenure which regu- 
lated their interest in the land. The PrsBtor, as has 
been said, treated the Emphyteuta as a true proprietor. 
When ejected, he was allowed to reinstate himself by 
a Real Action, the distinctive badge of proprietary 
right, and he was protected from disturbance by the 
author of his lease so long as the canon^ or quit-rent, 
was punctually paid. But at the same time it must 
not be supposed that the ownership of the author of 
the lease was either extinct or dormant. It was kept 
alive by a power of re-entry on non-payment of the 
rent, a right of pre-emption in case of sale, and a 
certain control over the mode of cultivation. We 
have, therefore, in the Emphyteusis a striking ex- 
ample of the double ownership which characterised 
feudal property, and one, moreover, which is much 
simpler and much more easily imitated than the 



302 ORIGIN OF TENURE. chap. vin. 

juxtaposition of legal and equitable rights. The 
history of the Roman tenure does not end, however, 
at this point. We have clear evidence that between 
the great fortresses which, disposed along the line of 
the Rhine and Danube, long secured the frontier of 
the Empire against its barbarian neighbours, there 
extended a succession of strips of land, the agri 
limitrophij which were occupied by veteran soldiers of 
the Roman army on the terms of an Emphyteusis. 
There was a double ownership. The Roman State 
was landlord of the soil, but the soldiers cultivated 
it without disturbance so long as they held themselves 
ready to be called out for military service whenever 
the state of the border should require it. In fact, a 
sort of garrison-duty, under a system closely resem- 
bling that of the military colonies on the Austro- 
Turkish border, had taken the place of the quit- rent 
which was the service of the ordinary Emphyteuta. 
It seems impossible to doubt that this was the 
precedent copied by the barbarian monarchs who 
founded feudalism. It had been within their view 
for some hundred years, and many of the veterans 
who guarded the border were, it is to be remembered, 
themselves of barbarian extraction, who probably 
spoke the Germanic tongues. Not only does the prox- 
imity of so easily followed a model explain whence 
the Prankish and Lombard Sovereigns got the idea 
of securing the military service of their followers 



CHAP. viu. FEUDAL SERVICES. 803 

by granting away portions of their public domain ; 
but it perhaps explains the tendency which imme- 
diately showed itself in the Benefices to become here- 
ditary, for an Emphyteusis, though capable of being 
moulded to the terms of the original contract, never- 
theless descended as a general rule to the heirs of the 
grantee. It is true that the holder of a benefice, and 
more recently the lord of one of those fiefs into which 
the benefices were transformed, appears to have owed 
certain services which were not likely to have been^ 
rendered by the military colonist, and were certainly 
not rendered by the Emphyteuta. The duty of 
respect and gratitude to the feudal superior, the 
obligation to assist in endowing his daughter and 
equipping his son, the liability to his guardianship 
in minority, and many other similar incidents of 
tenure, must have been literally borrowed from the 
relations of Patron and Freedman under Roman law, 
that *-, of quondam-master and quondam-slave. But 
thill i^ is known that the earliest beneficiaries were 
'iic ] >' rsonal companions of the sovereign, and it is 
indisputable that this position, brilliant as it seems, 
\va? at first attended by some shade of servile debase- 
m?Tit. The person who ministered to the Sovereign 
ill his Court had given up something of that absolute 
p ^rsonal freedom which wks the proudest privilege of 
1 Le allodial proprietor. 



304 SPHERE OF CONTRACT. cbap. ix. 



CHAP. IX. 
THE EARI.Y HISTOEY OF CONTRACT. 

There are few general propositions concerning the 
age to which we belong which seem at first sight 
^likely to be received with readier concurrence 
than the assertion that the society of our day is 
mainly distinguished from that of preceding gene- 
rations by the largeness of the sphere which is 
occupied in it by Contract. Some of the phenomena 
on which this proposition rests are among those 
most frequently singled out for notice, for comment, 
and for eulogy. Not many of us are so unobservant 
as not to perceive that in innumerable cases where old 
law fixed a man's social position irreversibly at his 
birth, modern law allows him to create it for himself by 
convention ; and indeed several of the few exceptions 
which remain to this rule are constantly denounced 
with passionate indignation. The point, for instance, 
which is really debated in the vigorous controversy 
still carried on upon the subject of negro servitude, 
is whether the status of the slave does not belong 
to by-gone institutions, and whether the only relation 
between employer and labourer which commends 



CHAP. IX. CONTRACT AND POLITICAL ECONOMY. 305 

itself to modern morality be not a relation deter- 
mined exclusively by contract. The recognition of 
this difference between past ages and the present 
enters into the very essence of the most famous 
contemporary speculations. It is certain that the 
science of Political Economy, the only department 
of moral inquiry which has made any considerable 
progress in our day, would fail to correspond with 
the facts of life if it were not true that Imperative 
Law had abandoned the largest part of the field 
which it once occupied, and had left men to settle 
rules of conduct for themselves with a liberty never 
allowed to them till recently. The bias indeed of most 
persons trained in political economy is to consider 
the general truth on which their science reposes as 
entitled to become universal, and, when they apply 
it as an art, their efforts are ordinarily directed to 
enlarging the province of Contract and to curtailing 
that of Imperative Law, except so far as law is 
necessary to enforce the performance of Contracts. 
The impulse given by thinkers who are under the 
influence of these ideas is beginning to be very 
strongly felt in the Western world. Legislation has 
nearly confessed its inability to keep pace with the 
activity of man in discovery, in invention, and in the 
manipulation of accumulated wealth; and the law 
even of the least advanced communities tends more 
and more to become a mere surface-stratum having 

X 



306 CURRENT OPINIONS AS TO CONTRACT, chap. ix. 

under it an ever-changing assemblage of contractual 
rules with which it rarely interferes except to 
compel compliance with a few fundamental principles 
or unless it be called in to punish the violation of 
good faith. 

Social inquiries, so far as they depend on the con- 
sideration of legal phenomena, are in so backward 
a condition that we need not be surprised at not 
finding these truths recognised in the commonplaces 
which pass current concerning the progress of so- 
ciety. These commonplaces answer much more to 
our prejudices than to our convictions. The strong 
disinclination of most men to regard morality as 
advancing seems to be especially powerful when the 
virtues on which Contract depends are in question, 
and many of us have an almost instinctive reluctance 
to admitting that good faith and trust in our fellows 
are more widely difiused than of old, or that there 
is anything in contemporary manners which parallels 
the loyalty of the antique world. From time to 
time, these prepossessions are greatly strengthened 
by the spectacle of frauds, unheard of before the 
period at which they were observed, and astonishing 
from their complication as well as shocking from 
criminality. But the very charactel* of these frauds 
shows clearly that, before they became possible, the 
moral obligations of which they are the breach ipust 
have been more than proportionately developed. It 



CHAP. IX. THEFT AND BREACH OF TRUST. S07 

is the confidence reposed and deserved by the many 
which aflfords facilities for the bad faith of the few, 
so that, if colossal examples of dishonesty occur, 
there is no surer conclusion than that scrupulous 
honesty is displayed in the average of the trans- 
actions which, in the particular case, have supplied 
the delinquent with his opportunity. If we insist 
on reading the history of morality as reflected, in 
jurisprudence, by turning our eyes not on the law 
of Contract but on the law of Crime, we must be 
carefiil that we read it aright. The only form of 
dishonesty treated of in the most ancient Roman 
law is Theft. At the moment at which I write, 
the newest chapter in the English criminal law is 
one which attempts to prescribe punishment for 
the frauds of Trustees. The proper inference from 
this contrast is not that the primitive Romans 
practised a higher morality than ourselves. We 
should rather say that, in the interval between their 
days and ours, morality has advanced from a very 
rude to a highly refined conception — from viewing 
the rights of property as exclusively sacred, to 
looking upon the rights growing out of the mere 
unilateral reposal of confidence as entitled to the 
protection of the penal law. 

The definite theories of jurists are scarcely nearer 

• the truth in this point than the opinions .of the 

multitude. To begin with the views of the Roman 

X 2 



308 THEORIES OF CONTRACT. chap. ix. 

lawyers, we find them inconsistent with the true 
history of moral and legal progress. One class 
of contracts, in which the plighted faith of the con- 
tracting parties was the only material ingredient, 
they specifically denominated Contracts ^wm gentium^ 
and though these contracts were undoubtedly the 
latest bom into the Roman system, the expression em- 
ployed implies, if a definite meaning be extracted from 
it, that they were more ancient than certain other 
forms of engagement treated of in Roman law, in 
which the neglect of a mere technical formality was as 
fatal to the obligation as misunderstanding or deceit. 
But then the antiquity to which they were referred 
was vague, shadowy, and only capable of being 
understood through the Present; nor was it until 
the language of the Roman lawyers became the 
language of an age which had lost the key to their 
mode of thought that a " Contract of the Law of 
Nations " came to be distinctly looked upon as a 
Contract known to man in a State of Nature. 
Rousseau adopted both the juridical and the popular 
error. In the Dissertation on the effects of Art and 
Science upon Morals, the first of his works which at- 
tracted attention and the one in which he states most 
unreservedly the opinions which made him the founder 
of a sect, the veracity and good faith attributed to the 
ancient Persians are repeatedly pointed out as traits 
of primitive innocence which have been gradually 



CHAP. IX. THE SOCIAL COMPACT. 809 

obliterated by civilisation; and at a later period 
be found a basis for all bis speculations in the 
doctrine of an original Social Contract. The So- 
cial Contract or Compact is the most systematic 
form which has ever been assumed by the error 
we are discussing. It is a theory which, though 
nursed into importance by political passions, de- 
rived all its sap from the speculations of lawyers. 
True it certainly is that the famous Englishmen, for 
whom it had first had attraction, valued it chiefly 
for its political serviceableness, but, as I shall pre- 
sently attempt to explain, they would never have 
arrived at it, if politicians had not long conducted 
their controversies in legal phraseology. Nor were 
the English authors of the theory blind to that 
speculative amplitude which recommended it so 
strongly to the Frenchmen who inherited it from 
them. Their writings show they perceived that it 
could be made to account for all social, quite as well 
as for all political, phenomena. They had observed 
the fact, already striking in their day, that of the 
positive rules obeyed by men, the greater part were 
created by Contract, the lesser by Imperative Law. 
But they were ignorant or careless of the historical 
relation of these two constituents of jurisprudence. 
It was for the purpose, therefore, of gratifying their 
speculative tastes by attributing all jurisprudence 
to a uniform source, as much as with the view of 

X 3 



310 ANALYSIS OF SOCIAL PHENOMENA, chap. ix. 

eluding the doctrines which claimed a divine parentage 
for Imperative Law, that they devised the theory that 
all Law had its origin in Contract, In another stage 
of thought, they would have been satisfied to leave 
their theory in the condition of an ingenious hypo- 
thesis or a convenient verbal formula. But that age 
was under the dominion of legal superstitions. The 
State of Nature had been talked about till it had 
ceased to be regarded as paradoxical, and hence it 
seemed easy to give a fallacious reality and definite- 
ness to the contractual origin of Law by insisting 
on the Social Compact as a historical fact. 

Our own generation has got rid of these erroneous 
juridical theories, partly by outgrowing the intel- 
lectual state to which they belong, and partly by 
almost ceasing to theorise on such subjects altogether. 
The favourite occupation of active minds at the pre- 
sent moment, and the one which answers to the 
speculations of our forefathers on the origin of the 
social state, is the analysis of society as it exists and 
moves before our eyes ; but, through omitting to call 
in the assistance of history, this analysis too often de- 
generates into an idle exercise of curiosity, and is 
especially apt to incapacitate the inquirer for compre- 
hending states of society which differ considerably 
from that to which he is accustomed. The mistake 
of judging the men of other periods by the morality 
of our own day has its parallel in the mistake of sup- 
posing that every wheel and bolt in the modem social 



CHAP. IX. MONTESQUIEU'S APOLOGUE. 311 

machine had its counterpart in more rudimentary 
societies. Such impressions ramify very widely, and 
masque themselves very subtly, in historical works 
written in the modem fashion ; but I find the trace 
of their presence in the domain of jurisprudence in 
ihe praise which is frequently bestowed on the little 
apologue of Montesquieu concerning the Troglodytes, 
inserted in the Lettres Persanea. The Troglodytes 
were a people who systematically violated their Con- 
tracts, and so perished utterly. K the story bears 
the moral which its author intended, and is em- 
ployed to expose an anti-social heresy by which this 
century and the last have been threatened, it is most 
unexceptionable ; but if the inference be obtained 
from it that society could not possibly hold together 
without attaching a sacredness to promises and agree- 
ments which should be on something like a par with 
the respect that is paid to them by a mature civilisa- 
tion, it involves an error so grave as to be fatal to all 
sound understanding of legal history. The fact is 
that the Troglodytes have flourished and founded 
powerful states with very small attention to the 
obligations of Contract. The point which before all 
others has to be apprehended in the constitution of 
primitive societies is that the individual creates for 
himself few or no rights, and few or no duties. The 
rules which he obeys are derived first from the sta- 
tion into which he is bom, and next from the impera- 

X 4 



312 EARLY NOTIONS OF CONTRACT. chaf. ix 

tive commands addressed to him by the chief of the 
household of which he forms part. Such a system 
leaves the very smallest room for Contract. The 
members of the same family (for so we may interpret 
the evidence) are wholly incapable of contracting 
with each other, and the family is entitled to "disre- 
gard the engagements by which any one of its subor- 
dinate members has attempted to bind it. Family, it 
is true, may contract with family, chieftain with 
chieftain, but the transaction is one of the same na- 
ture, and encumbered by as many formalities, as the 
alienation of property, and the disregard of one iota 
of the performance is fatal to the obligation. The 
positive duty resulting from one man's reliance on 
the word of another is among the slowest conquests 
of advancing civilisation. 

Neither Ancient Law nor any other source of evi- 
dence discloses to us society entirely destitute of the 
conception of Contract. But the conception, when it 
first shows itself, is obviously rudimentary. No 
trustworthy primitive record can be read without 
perceiving that the habit of mind which induces us 
to make good a promise is as yet imperfectly deve- 
loped, and that acts of flagrant perfidy are often 
mentioned without blame and sometimes described 
with approbation. In the Homeric literature, for in- 
stance, the deceitful cunning of Ulysses appears as a 
virtue of the same rank with the prudence of Nestor 



CHAP. IX. ANQENT CONTRACTS. 313 

the constancy of Hector, and the gallantry of Achilles. 
Ancient law is still more suggestive of the distance 
which separates the crude form of Contract from its 
maturity. At first, nothing is seen like the interpo- 
sition of law to compel the performance of a promise. 
That which the law arms with its sanctions is not a 
promise, but a promise accompanied with a solemn 
ceremonial. Not only are the formalities of equal 
importance with the promise itself, but they are, if 
anything, of greater importance ; for that delicate 
analysis which mature jurisprudence applies to the 
conditions of mind under which a particular verbal 
assent is given appears, in ancient law, to be trans- 
ferred to the words and gestures of the accompanying 
performance. No pledge is enforced if a single form 
be omitted or misplaced, but, on the other hand, if 
the forms can be shown to have been accTirately pro- 
ceeded with, it is of no avail to plead that the promise 
was made under duress or deception. The transmu- 
tation of this ancient view into the familiar notion of 
a Contract is plainly seen in the history of jurispru- 
dence. First one or two steps in the ceremonial 
are dispensed with; then the others are simplified 
or permitted to be neglected on certain conditions ; 
lastly, a few specific contracts are separated from the 
rest and allowed to be entered into without form, the 
selected contracts being those on which the activity 
and energy of social intercourse depends. Slowly, 




i-iriiA. 



814 EARLY ROMAN CONTRACTS. chaf. ix- 

but most distinctly, the mental engagement isolates 
itself amid the technicalities, and gradually becomes 
the sole ingredient on which the interest of the juris- 
consult is concentrated. Such a mental engagement, 
signified through external acts, the Romans called a 
Pact or Convention; and when the Convention has 
once been conceived as the nucleus of a Contract, it 
soon becomes the tendency of advancing jurispru- 
dence to break away the external shell of form and 
ceremony. Forms are thenceforward only retained 
so far as they are guarantees of authenticity, and 
securities for caution and deliberation. The idea of 
a Contract is fully developed, or, to employ the Ro- 
man phrase, Contracts are absorbed in Pacts. 

The history of this course of change in Roman law 
is exceedingly instructive. At the earliest dawn of 
the jurisprudence, the term in use for a Contract was 
one which is very familiar to the students of historical 
Latinity. It was nexunij and the parties to the con- 
tract were said to be neai^ expressions which must be 
carefully attended to on account of the singular 
durableness of the metaphor on which tfcey are 
founded. The notion that persons under a contrac- 
tual engagement are connected together by a strong 
bond or chain^ continued till the last to influence the 
Roman jurisprudence of Contract; and flowing thence 
it has mixed itself with modem ideas. What then 
was involved in this nexum or bond ? A definition 



CHAP IX. THE NEXUM. 815 

which has descended to us from one of the Latm anti- 
quarians describes nexum as omne quod geritur per ces 
€t libramj "every transaction with the copper and 
the balance," and these words have occasioned a good 
deal of perplexity. The copper and the balance are 
the well-known accompaniments of the Mancipation, 
the ancient solemnity described in a former chapter, 
by which the right of ownership in the highest form 
of Roman Property was transferred from one person 
to another. Mancipation was a conveyance^ and hence 
has arisen the difficulty, for the definition thus cited 
appears to confound Contracts and Conveyances, 
which in the philosophy of jurisprudence are not 
simply kept apart, but are actually opposed to each 
other. The jus in re, right in rem^ right " availing 
against all the world," or Proprietary Right, is sharply 
distinguished by the analyst of mature jurisprudence 
from the jus ad rem^ right in personam^ right " avail- 
ing a single individual or group," or Obligation. 
Now Conveyances transfer Proprietary Rights, Con- 
tracts create Obligations — how then can the two be 
included under the same name or same general con- 
ception? This, like many similar embarrassments, 
has been occasioned by the error of ascribing to the 
mental condition of an unformed society a faculty 
which preeminently belongs to an advanced stage of 
intellectual development, the faculty of distinguish- 
ing in speculation ideas which are blended in practice. 



316 SPECIALISING PROCESS IN ANCIENT LAW. chap. ix. 

We have indications not to be mistaken of a state of 
social aflfairs in which Conveyances and Contracts 
were practically confounded; nor did the discrepance 
of the conceptions become perceptible till men had 
begun to adopt a distinct practice in contracting and 
conveying. 

It may here be observed that we know enough of 
ancient Roman law to give some idea of the mode .of 
transformation followed by legal conceptions and by 
legal phraseology in the infancy of Jurisprudence. 
The change which they undergo appears to be a 
change from general to special; or, as we might 
otherwise express it, the ancient conceptions and the 
ancient terms are subjected to a process of gradual 
specialisation. An ancient legal conception corre- 
sponds not to one but to several modem conceptions. 
An ancient technical expression serves to indicate 
a variety of things which in modem law have 
separate names allotted to them. If however we 
take up the history of Jurisprudence at the next 
stage, we find that the subordinate conceptions have 
gradually disengaged themselves and that the old 
general names are giving way to special appellations. 
The old general conception is not obliterated, but it 
has ceased to cover more than one or a few of the 
notions which it first included. So too the old 
technical name remains, but it discharges only one of 
the functions which it once performed. We may 



CHAP. IX, SPECIALISING PROCESS IN ANCIENT LAW. 317 

exemplify this phenomenon in various ways. Patri- 
archal Power of all sorts appears, for instance, to 
have been once conceived as identical in character, 
and it was doubtless distinguished by one name. The 
Power exercised by the ancestor was the same 
whether it was exercised over the family or the ma- 
terial property — over flocks, herds, slaves, children, 
or wife. We cannot be absolutely certain of its old 
Roman name, but there is very strong reason for be- 
lieving, from the number of expressions indicating 
shades of the notion of power into which the word 
manus enters, that the ancient general term was 
maniLS. But, when Roman law has advanced a 
little, both the name and the idea have become spe- 
cialised. Power is discriminated, both in word and 
in conception, according to the object over which it 
is exerted. Exercised over material commodities or 
slaves, it has become dominium — over children it is 
Potestas — over free persons whose services have 
been made away to another by their own ancestor, it 
is mancipium — over a wife, it is still manus. The 
old word, it will be perceived, has not altogether 
fallen into desuetude, but is confined to one very 
special exercise of the authority it had formerly 
denoted. This example will enable us to compre- 
hend the nature of the historical alliance between 
Contracts and Conveyances. There seems to have 
been one solemn ceremonial at first for all solemn 



318 THE NEXUM. chap. ix. 

transactions, and its name at Rome appears to have 
been nexum. Precisely the same forms which were 
in use when a conveyance of property was eflFected 
seem to have been employed in the making of a con- 
tract. But we have not very far to move onwards 
before we come to a period at which the notion of a 
Contract has disengaged itself from the notion of a 
Conveyance. A double change has thus taken place. 
The transaction " with the copper and the balance/' 
when intended to have for its office the transfer of 
property, is known by the new and special name of 
Mancipation. The ancient Nexum still designates 
the same ceremony, but only when it is employed for 
the special purpose of solemnising a contract. 

When two or three legal conceptions are spoken of 
as anciently blended in one, it is not intended to im- 
ply that some one of the included notions may not 
be older than the others, or, when those others 
have been formed, may not greatly predominate over 
and take precedence over them. The reason why 
one legal conception continues so long to cover 
several conceptions, and one technical phrase to do 
instead of several, is doubtless that practical changes 
are accomplished in the law of primitive societies 
long before men see occasion to notice or name them. 
Though I have said that Patriarchal Power was not 
at first distinguished according to the objects over 
which it was exercised, I feel sure that Power over 



CHAP. IX. CHANGES IN THE NEXUM. 819 

Children was the root of the old conception of Power ; 
and I cannot doubt that the earliest use of the 
Nexum, and the one primarily regarded by those who 
resorted to it, was to give proper solemnity to the 
alienation of property. It is likely that a very slight 
perversion of the Nexura from its original functions 
first gave rise to its employment in Contracts, and 
that the very slightness of the change long prevented 
its being appreciated or noticed. The old name re- 
mained because men had not become conscious that 
they wanted a new one ; the old notion clung to the 
mind because nobody had seen reason to be at the 
pains of examining it. We have had the process 
clearly exemplified in the history of Testaments. A 
Will was at first a simple conveyance of property. It 
was only the enormous practical difference that gra- 
dually showed itself between this particular convey- 
ance and all others which caused it to be regarded 
separately, and even as it was, centuries elapsed 
before the ameliorators of law cleared away the use- 
less encumbrance of the nominal mancipation, and 
consented to care for nothing in the Will but the 
expressed intentions of the Testator. It is unfortu- 
nate that we cannot track the early history of Con- 
tracts with the same absolute confidence as the early 
history of Wills, but we are not quite without 
hints that contracts first showed themselves through 
the nexum being put to a new use and after- 



820 CHANGES IN THE NEXUM. chap. ix. 

wards obtained recognition as distinct transactions 
through the important practical consequences of 
the experiment. There is some, but not very violent, 
conjecture in the following delineation of the process. 
Let us conceive a sale for ready money as the 
normal type of the Nexum. The seller brought the 
property of which he intended to dispose — a slave, 
for example — the purchaser attended with the rough 
ingots of copper which served for money — and an in- 
dispensable assistant, the libripens^ presented himself 
with a pair of scales. The slave with certain fixed 
formalities was handed over to the vendee — the 
copper was weighed by the libripens and passed to 
the vendor. So long as the business lasted it was a 
nexum^ and the parties were nexi ; but the moment 
it was completed, the nexum ended, and the vendor 
and purchaser ceased to bear the name derived from 
their momentary relation. But now, let us move a 
step onward in commercial history. Suppose the 
slave transferred, but the money not paid. In that 
case, the nexum is finished, so far as the seller is 
concerned, and when he has once handed over his 
property, he is no longer nexus ; but, in regard to the 
purchaser, the nexum continues. The transaction, as 
to his part of it, is incomplete, and he is still consi- 
dered to be nexus. It follows, therefore, that the 
same terra described the Conveyance by which the 
right of property was transmitted, and the personal 



CHAP. IX. CONVEYANCES AND CONTRACTS. 321 

obligation of the debtor for the unpaid purchase- 
money. We may still go forward, and picture to 
ourselves a proceeding wholly formal, in which nothing 
is handed over ^ndi nothing paid; we are brought at 
once to a transaction indicative of much higher com- 
mercial activity, an executory Contract of Sale. 

If it be true that, both in the popular and in the 
professional view, a Contract was long regarded as an* 
incomplete Conveyance, the truth has importance for 
many reasons. The speculations of the last century 
concerning mankind in a state of nature, are not un- 
fairly summed up in the doctrine that " in the primi- 
tive society property was nothing, and obligation 
everything; " and it will now be seen that, if the pro- 
position were reversed, it would be nearer the reality. 
On the other hand, considered historically, the 
primitive association of Conveyances and Contracts 
explains something which often strikes the scholar 
and jurist as singularly enigmatical, I mean the 
extraordinary and uniform severity of very ancient 
systems of law to debtors, and the extravagant powers 
which they lodge with creditors. When once we un- 
derstand that the nexum was artificially prolonged to 
give time to the debtor, we can better comprehend 
his position in the eye of the public and of the law. 
His indebtedness was doubtless regarded as an ano- 
maly, and suspense of payment in general as an artifice 
and a distortion of strict rule. The person who had 



322 CONVEYANCES AND CONTRACTS. chap. ^x. 

duly consammated his part in the transaction must, 
on the contrary, have stood in peculiar favour; and 
nothing would seem more natural than to arm him 
with stringent facilities for enforcing the completion 
of a proceeding which, of strict right, ought never to 
have been extended or deferred. 

Nexum, therefore, which originally signified a C!on- 
veyance of property, came insensibly to denote a 
Contract also, and ultimately so constant became the 
association between this word and the notion of a 
Contract, that a special term, Mancipium or Mancipa- 
tio, had to be used for the purpose of designating the 
true nexum or transaction in which the property was 
really transferred. Contracts are therefore now 
severed from Conveyances, and the first stage in their 
history is accomplished, but still they are far enough 
from that epoch of their development when the pro- 
mise of the contractor has a higher sacredness than 
the formalities with which it is coupled* In attempt- 
ing to indicate the character of the changes passed 
through in this interval, it is necessary to trespass a 
little on a subject which lies properly beyond the 
range of these pages, the analysis of Agreement 
effected by the Roman jurisconsults. Of this ana- 
lysis, the most beautiful monument of their sagacity, 
I need not say more than that it is based on the 
theoretical separation of the Obligation from the Con- 
vention or Pact. Bentham and Mr. Austin have 



CHAP. IX. ROMAN ANALYSIS OF AGREEMENT. 323 

laid down that the " two main essentials of a contract 
are these: first, a signification by the promising 
party of his intention to do the acts or to observe the 
forbearances which he promises to do or to observe. 
Secondly, a signification by the promisee that he 
expects the promising party will fulfil tha proferred 
promise." This is virtually identical with the doctrine 
of the Roman lawyers, but then, in their view, the 
result of these " significations," was not a Contract, 
but a Convention or Pact. A Pact was the utmost 
product of the engagements of individuals agreeing 
among themselves, and it distinctly fell short of a 
Contract. Whether it ultimately became a Contract 
depended on the question whether the law annexed 
an Obligation to it. A Contract was a Pact (or 
Convention) plus an Obligation. So long as the Pact 
remained unclothed with the Obligation, it was called 
nude or naked. 

What was an Obligation? It is defined by the 
Roman lawyers as " Juris vinculum, quo necessitate 
adstringimur alicujus solvendaBrei." This definition 
connects the Obligation with the Nexum through the 
common metaphor on which they are founded, and 
shows us with much clearness the pedigree of a pecu- 
liar conception. The Obligation is the " bond " or 
" chain," with which the law joins together persons 
or groups of persons, in consequence of certain volun- 
tary acts. The acts which have the effect of attracting 

T 2 



324 OBLIGATION. chaf. ix. 

an Obligation are chiefly those classed under the 
heads of Contract and Delict, of Agreement and 
Wrong ; but a variety of other acts have a similar 
consequence which are not capable of being comprised 
in an exact classification. It is to be remarked, 
however, that the act does not draw to itself the 
Obligation in consequence of any moral necessity; it 
is the law which annexes it in the plenitude of its 
power, a point the more necessary to be noted, because 
a different doctrine has sometimes been propounded 
by modem interpreters of the Civil Law who had 
moral or metaphysical theories of their own to sup- 
port. The image of a vinculum juris colours and 
pervades every part of the Roman law of Contract 
and Delict. The law bound the parties together, and 
the chain could only be undone by the process called 
solutio^ an expression still figurative, to which our 
word " payment " is only occasionally and incidentally 
equivalent. The consistency with which the figura- 
tive image was allowed to present itself, explains an 
otherwise puzzling peculiarity of Roman legal phra- 
seology, the fact that " Obligation " signified rights as 
well as duties, the right, for example, to have a debt 
paid as well as the duty of paying it. The Romans 
kept in fact the entire picture of the "legal chain" 
before their eyes, and regarded one end of it no more 
and no less than the other. 

In the developed Roman law, the Convention, as 



CHAP. IX. CONVENTION AND CONTRACT, 325 

soon as it was completed, was, in almost all cases, 
at once crowned with the Obligation, and so became 
a Contract; and this was the result to which contract- 
law was surely tending. But for the purpose of this 
inquiry, we must attend particularly to the interme- 
diate stage — that in which something more than a 
perfect agreement was required to attract the Obliga- 
tion. This epoch is synchronous with the period at 
which the famous Roman classification of Contracts 
into four sorts — the Verbal, the Literal, the Real, 
and the Consensual — had come into use, and during 
which these four orders of Contracts constituted the 
only descriptions of engagement which the law would 
enforce. The meaning of the fourfold distribution is 
readily understood as soon as we apprehend the 
theory which severed the Obligation from the Con- 
vention. Each class of contracts was in fact named 
from certain formalities which were required over and 
above the mere agreement of the contracting parties. 
In the Verbal Contract, as soon as the Convention 
was effected, a form of words had to be gone through 
before the vinculum juris was attached to it. In the 
Literal Contract, an entry in a ledger or table-book 
had the effect of clothing the Convention with the 
Obligation, and the same result followed, in the case 
of the Real Contract, from the delivery of the Res or 
Thing which was the subject of the preliminary en* 
gagement. The contracting parties came, in short| 

T 3 



326 ROMAN CONTRACTS. chap. ix. 

to an understanding in each case; but, if they went 
no further, they were not obliged to one another, and 
could not compel performance or ask redress for a 
breach of faith. But let them comply with certain 
prescribed formalities, and the Contract was imme- 
diately complete, taking its name from the particular 
form which it had suited them to adopt. The excep- 
tions to this practice will be noticed presently. 

I have enumerated the four Contracts in their his- 
torical order, which order, however, the Roman 
Institutional writers did not invariably follow. There 
can be no doubt that the Verbal Contract was the 
most ancient of the four, and that it is the eldest 
known descendant of the primitive Nexum. Several 
species of Verbal Contract were anciently in use, but 
the most important of aU, and the only one treated of 
by our authorities, was eflFected by means of a stipxda- 
tion^ that is, a Question and Answer; a question ad- 
dressed by the person who exacted the promise, and 
an answer given by the person who made it. This 
question and answer constituted the additional ingre- 
dient which, as I have just explained, was demanded 
by the primitive notion over and above the mere 
agreement of the persons interested. They formed 
the agency by which the Obligation was annexed. 
The old Nexum has now bequeathed to maturer juris- 
prudence first of all the conception of a chain uniting 
the contracting parties, and this has become the Obli- 



CHAP. IX. THE VERBAL CONTRACT. 327 

gation. It has further transmitted the notion of a 
ceremonial accompanying and consecrating the en- 
gagement, and this ceremonial has been tAnsmuted 
into the Stipulation. The conversion of the solemn 
conveyance, which was the prominent feature of the 
original Nexum, into a mere question and answer, 
would be more of a mystery than it is if we had not 
the analogous history of Roman Testaments to en- 
lighten us. Looking to that history, we can under- 
stand how the formal Conveyance was first separated 
from the part of the proceeding which had immediate 
reference to the business in hand, and how afterwards 
it was omitted altogether. As then the question and 
answer of the Stipulation were unquestionably the 
Nexum in a simplified shape, we are prepared to find 
that they long partook of the nature of a technical 
form. It would be a mistake to consider them as 
exclusively recommending themselves to the older 
Roman lawyers through their usefulness in furnishing 
persons meditating an agreement with an opportunity 
for consideration and reflection. It is not to be dis- 
puted that they had a value of this kind, which was 
gradually recognised; but there is proof that their 
function in respect to Contracts was at first formal 
and ceremonial in the statement of our authorities, 
that not every question and answer was of old suffi- 
cient to constitute a Stipulation, but only a question 

T 4 



328 CONVENIENCE OF VERBAL CONTRACT, chap. ix. 

and answer couched in technical phraseology specially 
appropriated to the particular occasion. 

But although it is essential for the proper apprecia- 
tion of the history of contract-law that the Stipulation 
should be understood to have been looked upon as a 
solemn form before it was recognised as a useful 
security, it would be wrong on the other hand to 
shut our eyes to its real usefulness. The Verbal 
Contract, though it had lost much of its ancient im- 
portance, survived to the latest period of Roman 
jurisprudence; and we may take it for granted that 
no institution of Roman law had so extended a 
longevity unless it served some practical advantage. 
I observe in an English writer some expressions of sur- 
prise that the Romans even of the earliest times were 
content with so meagre a protecticm against haste and 
irreflection. But on extnninmg the Stipulation e 
and remembering that we have to do with 
of society in which writMto^vidence was no 



procurable, I think we 
and Answer, had it b* 
the purpose which it 
designated a highly in 
promisee who, in the c 
the terms of the contrut-^ 
and the answer was Bive 
promise that you will di 
slave, at such and such a 




t that this C 

ly devised to 

d have beei 

sdient. It 

stipulator^ 

fcnii of a c 




CHAP. IX. CONVENIENCE OP VERBAL CONTRACT. S29 

day?" "I do promise." Now, if we reflect for a 
moment, we shall see 4ihat tHis obligation to put the 
/promise interrogatively inverts the natural position 
of the parties, and, by effectually breaking the teiior • 
of the conversation, prevents the attention from 
gliding -over a dangerous pledge. With us, a verbal 
promise is, generally speaking, to be gathered exclu- 
sively from the words of the promisor. In old Roman 
law, another step was absolutely required; it was 
necessary for the promisee, after the agreement had 
been made, to sum up all its terms in a solemn inter- 
rogation; and it was of this interrogation, of course, 
and of the assent to it, that proof had to be given at 
the trial — not of the promise, which was not in itself 
binding. How great a difference this seemingly in- 
significant peculiarity may make in the phraseology of 
contract-law is speedily realised by the beginner in 
Koman jurisprudence, one of whose first stumbling- 
blocks is almost universally created by it. When we 
in English have occasion, in mentioning a contract, 
to connect it for convenience' sake with one of the 
parties, — for example, if we wished to speak generally 
of a contractor, — it is always the promis(>r at whom 
our words are pointing. But the general language of 
Roman law takes a different turn ; it always regards 
the contract, if we may so speak, from the point of 
view of the promises ; in speaking of a party to a 
contract, it is always the Stipulator, the person who 



330 THE LITERAL CONTRACT. chap. ix. 

asks the question, who is primarily alluded to. But 
the serviceableness of the stipulation is most vividly 
illustrated by referring to the actual examples in the 
pages of the Latin comic dramatists. If the entire 
scenes are read down in which these passages occur 
(ex. gra. Plautus, Pseudolus^ Act I. sc. 1 ; Act IV. 
sc. 6; Trinummus^ Act V. sc. 2), it will be perceived 
how effectually the attention of the person meditating 
the promise must have been arrested by the question, 
and how ample was the opportunity for withdrawal 
from an improvident undertaking. 

In the Literal or Written Contract, the formal act 
by which an Obligation was superinduced on the Con- 
vention, was an entry of the sum due, where it could 
be specifically ascertained, on the debit side of a 
ledger. The explanation of this Contract turns on a 
point of Roman domestic manners, the systematic 
character and exceeding regularity of book-keeping 
in ancient times. There are several minor difficulties 
of old Roman law, as, for example, the nature of the 
Slave's Peculium, which are only cleared up when we 
recollect that a Roman household consisted of a num- 
ber of persons strictly accountable to its head, and 
that every single item of domestic receipt and expen- 
diture, after being entered in waste books, was trans- 
ferred at stated periods to a general household ledger. 
There are some obscurities, however, in the descrip- 
tions we have received of the Literal Contract, the 



CHAP. IX. THE REAL CONTRACT- 331 

fact being that the habit of keeping books ceased to 
be universal in later times, and the expression 
" Literal Contract," came to signify a form of engage- 
ment entirely different from that originally under- 
stood. We are not, therefore, in a position to say, 
with respect to the primitive Literal Contract, whether 
the obligation was created by a simple entry on the 
part of the creditor, or whether the consent of the 
debtor or a correspondent entry in his own books was 
necessary to give it legal effect. The essential point 
is however established that, in the case of this Con- 
tract, all formalities were dispensed with on a condi- 
tion being complied with. This is another step down- 
wards in the history of contract-law. 

The Contract which stands next in historical suc- 
cession, the Real Contract, shows a great advance in 
ethical conceptions. Whenever any agreement had 
for its object the delivery of a specific thing — and this 
is the case with the large majority of simple engage- 
ments — the Obligation was drawn down as soon as 
the delivery had actually taken place. Such a result 
must have involved a serious innovation on the oldest 
ideas of Contract ; for doubtless, in the primitive times, 
when a contracting party had neglected to clothe his 
agreement in a stipulation, nothing done in pursuance 
of the agreement would be recognised by the law. 
A person who had paid over money on loan would 
be unable to sue for its repayment unless he had 



832 THE CONSENSUAL CONTRACTS. chap. ix. 

formally stipulated for it. But, in the Real Con- 
tract, performance on one side is allowed to impose 
a legal duty on the other — evidently on ethical 
grounds. For the first time then moral consider- 
ations appear as an ingredient in Contract-law, and 
the Real Contract differs from its two predecessors in 
being founded on these, rather than on respect for 
technical forms or on deference to Roman domestic 
habits. 

We now reach the fourth class, or Consensual 
Contracts, the most interesting and important of all. 
Four specified Contracts were distinguished by this 
name : Mandatum, i. e. Conunission or Agency ; So- 
cietas or Partnership; Emtio Venditio or Sale; and 
Locatio Conductio or Letting and Hiring. A few 
pages ago, after stating that a Contract consisted of a 
Pact or Convention to which an Obligation had been 
superadded, I spoke of certain acts or formalities by 
which the law permitted the Obligation to be attracted 
to the Pact. I used this language on account of the 
advantage of a general expression, but it is not 
strictly correct unless it be understood to include the 
negative as well as the positive. For, in truth, the 
peculiarity of these Consensual Contracts is that no 
formalities are required to create them out of the 
Pact. Much that is indefensible, and much more that 
is obscure, has been written about the Consensual 
Contracts, and it has even been asserted that in them 



ciiAF. IX. THE CONSENSUAL CONTRACTS. 333 

the consent of the Parties is more emphatically given 
than in any other species of agreement. But the 
term Consensual merely indicates that the Obligation 
is here annexed at once to tl\e Consensus. The Con- 
sensus, or mutual assent of the parties, is the final and 
crowning ingredient in the Convention, and it is the 
special characteristic of agreements falling under one 
of the four heads of Sale, Partnership, Agency, and 
Hiring, that, as soon as the assent of the parties has 
supplied this ingredient, there is at once a Contract. 
The Consensus draws with it the Obligation, per- 
forming, in transactions of the sort specified, the 
exact functions which are discharged, in the other 
contracts, by the Bes or Thing, by the Verba stipula- 
tionis, and by the Literce or written entry in a ledger. 
Consensual is therefore a term which does not involve 
the slightest anomaly, but is exactly analogous to 
Real, Verbal, and Literal. 

In the intercourse of life the commonest and most 
important of all the contracts are unquestionably the 
four styled Consensual. The larger part of the col- 
lective existence of every community is consumed in 
transactions of buying and selling, of letting and 
hiring, of alliances between men for purposes of 
business, of delegation of business from one man to 
another; and this is no doubt the consideration which 
led the Romans, as it has led most societies, to relieve 
these transactions from technical incumbrance, to 



334 THE CONSENSUAL CONTRACTS. chap. ix. 

abstain as much as possible from clogging the most 
efficient springs of social movement. Such motives 
were not of course confined to Rome, and the com- 
merce of the Romans .with their neighbours must 
have given them abundant opportunities for observing 
that the contracts before us tended everywhere to 
become Consensual^ obligatory on the mere significa- 
tion of mutual assent. Hence, following their usual 
practice, they distinguished these contracts as contracts 
Juris Gentium, Yet I do not think that they were 
so named at a very early period. The first notions 
of a Jus Gentium may have been deposited in the 
minds of the Roman lawyers long before the appoint-, 
ment of a PraBtor Peregrinus, but it would only 
be through extensive and regular trade that they 
would be familiarised with the contractual system of 
other Italian communities, and such a trade would 
scarcely attain considerable proportions before Italy 
had been thoroughly pacified, and the supremacy of 
Rome conclusively assured. Although, however, 
there is strong probability that the Consensual Con- 
tracts were the latest-born into the Roman system, 
and though it is likely that the qualification, Juris 
Gentium^ stamps the recency of their origin, yet this 
very expression, which attributes them to the " Law 
of Nations," has in modern times produced the notion 
of their extreme antiquity. For, when the " Law of 
Nations" had been converted into the "Law of 



CHAP. IX. THE CONSENSUAL CONTRACTS. 335 

Nature," it seemed to be implied that the Consensual 
Contracts were the type of the agreements most 
congenial to the natural state; and hence arose the 
singular belief that the younger the civilisation, the 
simpler must be its forms of contract. 

The Consensual Contracts, it will be observed, were 
extremely limited in number. But it cannot be 
doubted that they constituted the stage in the history 
of Contract-law from which all modern conceptions of 
contract took their start. The motion of the will 
which constitutes agreement was now completely 
insulated, and became the subject of separate con- 
templation ; forms were entirely eliminated from the 
notion of contract, and external acts were only 
regarded as symbols of the internal act of volition. 
The Consensual Contracts had, -moreover, been classed 
in the Jus Gentium, and it was not long before this 
classification drew with it the inference that they 
were the species of agreement which represented the 
engagements approved of by Nature and included in 
her code. This point once reached, we are prepared 
for several celebrated doctrines and distinctions of the 
Roman lawyers. One of them is the distinction 
between Natural and Civil Obligations. When a 
person of full intellectual maturity had deliberately 
bound himself by an engagement, he was said to 
be under a natural obligation^ even though he had 
omitted some necessary formality, and even though 



836 NATURAL AND CIViL OBLIGATIONS. chap. ix. 

through some technical impedunent he was devoid 
of the formal capacity for making a valid contract. 
The law (and this is what the distinction implies) 
would not enforce the obligation, but it did not 
absolutely refuse to recognise it ; and natural obli- 
gations differed in many respects from obligations 
which were merely null and void, more particularly 
in the circumstance that they could be civiUy con- 
firmed, if the capacity for contract were subsequently 
acquired. Another very peculiar doctrine of the 
jurisconsults could not have had its origin earlier than 
the period at which the Convention was severed from 
the technical ingredients of Contract. They taught 
that though nothing but a Contract could be the 
foundation of an actiorij a mere Pact or Convention 
could be the basis of a plea. It followed from this, 
that though nobody could sue upon an agreement 
which he had not taken the precaution to mature into 
a Contract by complying with the proper forms, never- 
theless a claim arising out of a valid contract could 
be rebutted by proving a counter-agreement which 
had never got beyond th^ state of a simple conven- 
tion. An action for the recovery of a debt could be 
met by showing a mere informal agreement to waive 
or postpone the payment. 

The doctrine just stated indicates the hesitation of 
the PrflBtors in making their advances towards the 
greatest of their innovations. Their theory of Natural 



CHAP. IX. CHANGES IN CONTRACT-LAW. 337 

law must have led them to look with especial favour on 
the Consensual Contracts and on those Pacts or Con- 
ventions of which the Consensual Contracts were only 
particular instances ; but they did not at once venture 
on extending to all Conventions the liberty of the 
Consensual Contracts. They took advantage of that 
special superintendence over procedure which had 
been confided to them since the first beginnings of 
Roman law, and, while they still declined to permit a 
suit to be launched which was not based on a formal 
contract, they gave full play to their new theory of 
agreement in directing the ulterior stages of the pro- 
ceeding. But, when they had proceeded thus far, it 
was inevitable that they should proceed farther. 
The revolution of the ancient law of Contract was 
consummated when the Praetor of some one year 
announced in his Edict that he would grant equitable 
actions upon Pacts which had never been matured at 
all into Contracts, provided only that the Pacts in 
question had been founded on a consideration (causa). 
Pacts of this sort are always enforced under the 
advanced Roman jurisprudence. The principle is 
merely the principle of the Consensual Contract 
carried to its proper consequence ; and, in fact, if the 
technical language of the Romans had been as plastic 
as their legal theories, these Pacts enforced by the 
Praetor would have been styled new Contracts, new 
Consensual Contracts. Legal phraseology is, how- 

z 



338 PROGRESS OF CONTRACT-LAW. chap. ix. 

ever, the part of the law which is the last to alter, 
and the Pacts equitably enforced continued to be 
designated simply PraBtorian Pacts. It will be re- 
marked that unless there were consideration for the 
Pact, it would continue nude so far as the new juris- 
prudence was concerned; in order to give it effect, it 
would be necessary to convert it by a stipulation into 
a Verbal Contract. 

The extreme importance of this history of Con- 
tract, as a safeguard against almost innumerable 
delusions, must be my justification for discussing it 
at so considerable a length. It gives a complete 
account of the march of ideas from one great land- 
mark of jurisprudence to another. We begin with 
the Nexum, in which a Contract and a Conveyance 
are blended, and in which the formalities which ac- 
company the agreement are even more important 
than the agreement itself. From the Nexum we pass 
to the Stipulation, which is a simplified form of the 
older ceremonial. The Literal Contract comes next, 
and here all formalities are waived, if proof of the 
agreement can be supplied from the rigid observances 
of a Roman household. In the Real Contract a 
moral duty is for the first time recognised, and 
persons who have joined or acquiesced in the partial 
performance of an engagement are forbidden to 
repudiate it on account of defects in form. Lastly, 
the Consensual Contracts emerge, in which the 



CHAP. IX. PROGRESS OF CONTRACT-LAW. 389 

mental attitude of the contractors is solely regarded, 
and external circumstances have no title to notice 
except as evidence of the inward undertaking. It is 
of course uncertain how far this progress of Roman 
ideas from a gross to a refined conception exemplifies 
the necessary progress of human thought on the 
subject of Contract. The Contract-law of all other 
ancient societies but the Roman is either too scanty 
to furnish information, or else is entirely lost; and 
modem jurisprudence is so thoroughly leavened with 
the Roman notions that it furnishes us with no con- 
trasts or parallels from which instruction can be 
gleaned. From the absence, however, of everything 
violent, marvellous, or unintelligible in the changes I 
have described, it may be reasonably believed that 
the history of ancient Roman Contracts is, up to a 
certain point, typical of the history of this class of 
legal conceptions in other ancient societies. But it 
is only up to a certain point that the progress of 
Roman law can be taken to represent the progress of 
other systems of jurisprudence. The theory of Na- 
tural law is exclusively Roman. The notion of the 
vinculum juris^ so far as my knowledge extends, is 
exclusively Roman. The many peculiarities of the 
mature Roman law of Contract and Delict which 
are traceable to these two ideas, whether singly or in 
combination, are therefore among the exclusive pro- 
ducts of one particular society. These later legal 

z 2 



340 INFLUENCE OF BOMAN CONTRACT-LAW. chap. ix. 

conceptions are important, not because they typify 
the necessary results of advancing thought under all 
conditions, but because they have exercised perfectly 
enormous influence on the intellectual diathesis of the 
modem world. 

I know nothing more wonderful than the variety 
of sciences to which Roman law, Roman Contract- 
law more particularly, has contributed modes of 
thought, courses of reasoning, and a technical lan- 
guage. Of the subjects which have whetted the 
intellectual appetite of the modems, there is scarcely 
one, except Physics, which has not been filtered 
through Roman jurisprudence. The science of pure 
Metaphysics had, indeed, rather a Greek than a Roman 
parentage, but Politics, Moral Philosophy, and even 
Theology, found in Roman law not only a vehicle of 
expression, but a nidus in which some of their pro- 
foundest inquiries were nourished into maturity. For 
the purpose of accounting for this phenomenon, it is 
not absolutely necessary to discuss the mysterious 
relation between words and ideas, or to explain how 
it is that the human mind has never grappled with 
any subject of thought, unless it has been provided 
beforehand with a proper store of language and with 
an apparatus of appropriate logical methods. It is 
enough to remark, that, when the philosophical inte- 
rests of the Eastern and Western worlds were sepa- 
rated, the founders of Western thought belonged to 



CHAP. IX. STATE OF THOUGHT IN THE EMPIRE. 341 

a society which spoke Latin and reflected in Latin. 
But in the Western provinces the only language which 
retained sufficient precision for philosophical purposes 
was the language of Roman law, which by a singular 
fortune had preserved nearly all the purity of the 
Augustan age, while vernacular Latin was degene- 
rating into a dialect of portentous barbarism. And 
if Roman jurisprudence supplied the only means of 
exactness in speech, still more emphatically did it 
furnish the only means of exactness, subtlety, or 
depth in thought. For at least three centuries, 
philosophy and science were without a home in the 
West; and though metaphysics and metaphysical 
theology were engrossing the mental energies of 
multitudes of Roman subjects, the phraseology em- 
ployed in these ardent inquiries was exclusively Greek, 
and their theatre was the Eastern half of the Empire. 
Sometimes, indeed, the conclusions of the Eastern 
disputants became so important that every man's 
assent to them, or dissent from them, had to be re- 
corded, and then the West was introduced to the 
results of Eastern controversy, which it generally 
acquiesced in without interest and without resistance. 
Meanwhile, one department of inquiry, difficult 
enough for the most laborious, deep enough for the 
most subtle, delicate enough for the most refined, 
had never lost its attractions for the educated classes 
of the Western provinces. To the cultivated citizen 

z 3 



342 EASTERN AND WESTERN IDEAS. chap. ix. 

of Africa, of Spain, of Gaul, and of Northern Itely, 
it was jurisprudence, and jurisprudence only, which 
stood in the place of poetry and history, of philosophy 
and science. So far then from their being anything 
mysterious in the palpably legal complexion of the 
earliest eflPbrts of Western thought it would rather be 
astonishing if it had assumed any other hue. I can 
only express my surprise at the scantiness of the at- 
tention which has been given to the diflFerence between 
Western ideas and Eastern, between Western theology 
and Eastern, caused by the presence of a new ingre- 
dient. It is precisely because the influence of juris- 
prudence begins to be powerful that the foundation 
of Constantinople and the subsequent separation of 
the Western Empire from the Eastern, are epochs in 
philosophical history. But continental thinkers are 
doubtless less capable of appreciating the importance 
of this crisis by the very intimacy with which notions 
derived from Roman Law are mingled up with their 
everyday ideas. Englishmen, on the other hand, are 
bKnd to it through the monstrous ignorance to which 
they condemn themselves of the most plentiful source 
of the stream of modem knowledge, of the one intel- 
lectual result of the Roman civilisation. At the same 
time, an Englishman, who will be at the pains to 
familiarise himself with the classical Roman law, is 
perhaps, from the very slightness of the interest 
which his countrymen have hitherto taken in the 



CHAP. IX. QUASI-CONTRACT. 343 

subject, a better judge than a Frenchman or a Ger- 
man of the value of the assertions I have ventured to 
make. Anybody who knows what Roman jurispru- 
dence is, as actually practised by the Romans, and 
who will observe in what characteristics the earliest 
Western theology and philosophy diflfer from the 
phases of thought which preceded them, may be safely 
left to pronounce what was the new element which 
had begun to pervade and govern speculation. 

^e part of Roman law which has had most exten- 
sive influence on foreign subjects of inquiry has been 
the law of Obligation, or what comes nearly to the 
same thing, of Contract and Delict. The Romans 
themselves were not unaware of the offices which the 
copious and malleable terminology belonging to this 
part of their system might be made to discharge, and 
this is proved by their employment of the peculiar 
adjunct qu(xsi in such expressions as Quasi-Contract 
and Quasi-Delict. " Quasi," so used, is exclusively 
a term of classification. It has been usual with 
English critics to identify the Quasi-contracts with 
implied contracts, but this is an error, for implied 
contracts are true contracts, which quasi-contracts 
are not. In implied contracts, acts and circum- 
stances are the symbols of the same ingredients 
which are symbolised, in express contracts, by 
words; and whether a man employs one set of 
symbols or the other must be a matter of indiffer- 

z 4 



344 



QUASI-CONTRACT. chap. ix. {"j 



ence so far as concerns the theory of agreement. 
But a Quasi-Contract is not a contract at all. The 
commonest sample of the class is the relation sub- 
sisting between two persons one of whom has paid 
money to the other through mistake. The law, 
consulting the interests of morality, imposes an obli- 
gation on the receiver to refund, but the very nature 
of the transduction indicates that it is not a contract, 
inasmuch as the Convention, the most essential ingre- 
dient of Contract, is wanting. This word " qu||fi," 
prefixed to a term of Roman law, implies that the 
conception to which it serves as an index is con- 
nected with the conception with which the com- 
parison is instituted by a strong superficial analogy 
or resemblance. It does not denote that the two 
conceptions are the same or that they belong to the 
same genus. On the contrary, it negatives the 
notion of an identity between them; but it points 
out that they are sufficiently similar for one to be 
classed as the sequel to the other, and that the 
phraseology taken from one department of law may 
be transferred to the other, and employed without 
violent straining in the statement of rules which 
would otherwise be imperfectly expressed. 

It has been shrewdly remarked, that the con- 
fusion between Implied Contracts, which are true 
contracts, and Quasi Contracts, which are not con- 
tracts at all, has much in common with the famous 



Ji 



CBAP. IX. THE SOCIAL COMPACT. 845 

error which attributed political rights and duties to 
an Original Compact between the governed and the 
governor. Long before this theory had clothed 
itself in definite shape, the phraseology of Roman 
contract-law had been largely drawn upon to de- 
scribe that reciprocity of rights and duties which 
men had always conceived as existing between 
sovereigns and subjects. While the world was full 
of maxims setting forth with the utmost positiveness 
the claims of kings to implicit obedience — maxims 
which pretended to have had their origin in the 
New Testament, but which were really derived from 
indelible recollections of the Caesarian despotism — 
the consciousness of correlative rights possessed by 
the governed would have been entirely without the 
means of expression if the Roman law of Obligation 
had not supplied a language capable of shadowing 
forth an idea which was as yet imperfectly de- 
veloped. The antagonism between the privileges 
of kings and their duties to their subjects was never, 
I believe, lost sight of since Western history began, 
but it had interest for few except speculative writers 
so long as feudalism continued in vigour, for feudal- 
ism eflfectually controlled by express customs the 
exorbitant theoretical pretensions of most European 
sovereigns. It is notorious, however, that as soon as 
the decay of the Feudal System had thrown the me- 
diaeval constitutions out of working order, and when 



346 F0LITIC8 AND ROMAN LAW. chap. u. 

the Reformation had discredited the authority of the 
Pope, the doctrine of the divine right of Kings rose 
immediately into an importance which had never 
before attended it. The vogue which it obtained en- 
tailed still more constant resort to the phraseology of 
Roman law, and a controvert which had originally 
worn a theological aspect assumed more and more 
the air of a legal disputation. A phenomenon then 
appeared which has repeatedly shown itself in the 
history of opinion. Just when the argument for 
monarchical authority rounded itself into the definite 
doctrine of Filmer, the phraseology, borrowed from 
the Law of Contract, which had been used in defence 
of the rights of subjects, crystallised into the theory 
of an actual original compact between king and 
people, a theory which, first in English and afterwards, 
and more particularly, in French hands, expanded 
into a comprehensive explanation of all the pheno- 
mena of society and law. But the only real connec- 
tion between political and legal science had consisted 
in the last giving to the first the benefit of its pecu- 
liarly plastic terminology. The Roman jurispru- 
dence of Contract had performed for the relation of 
sovereign and subject precisely the same service 
which, in a humbler sphere, it rendered to the rela- 
tion of persons bound together by an obligation of 
" quasi-contract." It had furnished a body of words 
and phrases which approximated with sufiicient 



CHAP. K. ETHICS AND ROMAN LAW 347 

accuracy to the ideas which then were from time to 
time forming on the subject of political obligation. 
The doctrine of an Original Compact can never be put 
higher than it is placed by Dr. Whewell, when he 
suggests that, though unsound, " it may be a conve- 
nient form for the expression of moral truths." 

The extensive employment of legal language on 
political subjects previously to the invention of the 
Original Compact, and the powerful influence which 
that assumption has exercised subsequently, amply 
account for the plentifiilness in political science of 
words and conceptions, which were the exclusive 
creation of Roman jurisprudence. Of their plentifal- 
ness in Moral Philosophy a rather different explana- 
tion must be given, inasmuch as ethical writings have 
laid Roman law under contribution much more 
directly than political speculations, and their authors 
have been much more conscious of the extent of their 
obligation. In speaking of moral philosophy as 
extraordinarily indebted to Roman jurisprudence, I 
must be understood to intend moral philosophy as 
imderstood previously to the break in its history 
effected by Kant, that is, as the science of the rules 
governing human conduct, of their proper interpre- 
tation and of the limitations to which they are 
subject. Since the rise of the Critical Philosophy, 
moral science has almost wholly lost its older mean- 
ing, and, except where it is preserved under a debased 



\ 



348 ETHICS AND ROMAN LAW. chap. rx. 

form in the casuistry still cultivated by Roman 
"Oatholic theologians, it seems to be regarded nearly 
universally as a branch of ontological inquiry. I do 
not know that there is a single contemporary English 
writer, with the exception of Dr. Whewell, who un- 
derstands moral philosophy as it was understood 
before it was absorbed by metaphysics and before the 
groundwork of its rules came to be a more important 
consideration than the rules themselves. So long, 
however, as ethical science had to do with the 
practical regimen of conduct, it was more or less 
saturated with Roman law. Like all the great 
subjects of modem thought, it was originally incor- 
porated with theology. The science of Moral Theo- 
logy, as it was at first called, and as it is still 
designated by the Roman Catholic divines, was un- 
doubtedly constructed, to the full knowledge of its 
authors, by taking principles of conduct from the 
system of the Church, and by using the language and 
methods of jurisprudence for their expression and 
expansion. While this process went on, it was in- 
evitable that jurisprudence, though merely intended 
to be the vehicle of thought, should communicate its 
colour to the thought itself. The tinge received 
through contact with legal conceptions is perfectly 
perceptible in the earliest ethical literature of the 
modern world, and it is evident, I think, that the Law 
of Contract, based as it is on the complete reciprocity 



CHAP. IX. ETHICS AND ROMAN LAW. 

and indissoluble connection of rights and duti 
acted as a wholesome corrective to the predispositioffi 
of writers who, if left to themselves, might have ex- 
clusively viewed a moral obligation as the public 
duty of a citizen in the Civitas Dei. But the amoimt 
of Koman Law in moral theology becomes sensibly 
smaller at the time of its cultivation by the great 
Spanish moralists. Moral theology, developed by the 
juridical method of doctor commenting on doctor, 
provided itself with a phraseology of its own, and 
Aristotelian peculiarities of reasoning and expression, 
imbibed doubtless in great part from the Disputa- 
tions on Morals in the academical schools, take the 
place of that special turn of thought and speech 
which can never be mistaken by any person conversant 
with the Roman law. If the credit of the Spanish 
school of moral theologians had continued, the juridi- 
cal ingredient in ethical science would have been 
insignificant, but the use made of their conclusions 
by the next generation of Roman Catholic writers on 
these subjects almost entirely destroyed their influence. 
Moral Theology, degraded into Casuistry, lost all inte- 
rest for the leaders of European speculation; and the 
new science of Moral Philosophy, which was entirely 
in the hands of the Protestants, swerved greatly aside 
from the path which the moral theologians had fol- 
lowed. The efifect was vastly to increase the influence 
of Roman law on ethical inquiry. 




350 MORAL PHILOSOPHY. chap. ix. 

" Shortly* after the Reformation, we find two great 
schools of thought dividing this class of subjects 
between them. The most influential of the two was 
at first the sect or school known to us as the Casuists, 
all of them in spiritual communion with the Roman 
Catholic Church, and nearly all of them affiliated to 
one or other of her religious orders. On the other 
side were a body of writers connected with each other 
by a common intellectual descent from the great 
author of the treatise De Jure BeUi et PaciSy Hugo 
Grotius. Almost all of the latter were adherents of 
the Reformation, and though it cannot be said that 
they were formerly and avowedly at conflict with 
the Casuists, the origin and object of their system 
were nevertheless essentially difl^erent from those 
of Casuistry. It is necessary to call attention to 
this difiference, because it involves the question of 
the influence of Roman law on that department of 
thought with which both systems are concerned. 
The book of Grotius, though it touches questions of 
pure Ethics in every page, and though it is the pa- 
rent immediate or remote of innumerable volumes of 
formal morality, is not, as is well known, a professed 
treatise on Moral Philosophy; it is an attempt to 
determine the Law of Nature, or Natural Law. Now, 
without entering upon the question, whether the con- 

* The passage quoted is transcribed with slight alterations from a 
paper contributed by the author to the Cambridffe Essays for 1860. 



CHAP. IX. GROTIUS AND HIS SCHOOL. S51 

ception of a Law Natural be not exclusively a crea- 
tion of *the Roman jurisconsults, we may lay down 
that, even on the admission of Grotius himself, the 
dicta of the Roman jurisprudence as to what parts of 
known positive law must be taken to be parts of the 
Law of Nature, are, if not infallible, to be received 
at all events with the profoundest respect. Hence 
the system of Grotius is implicated with Roman law 
at its very foundation, and this connection rendered 
inevitable — what the legal training of the writer 
would perhaps have entailed without it — the free 
employment in every paragraph of technical phraseo- 
logy, and of modes of reasoning, defining, and illus- 
trating, which must sometimes conceal the sense, and 
almost always the force and cogency, of the argument 
from the reader who is unfamiliar with the sources 
whence they have been derived. On the other hand, 
Casuistry borrows little from Roman law and the 
views of. morality contended for have nothing what- 
ever in common with the undertaking of Grotius. 
All that philosophy of right and wrong which has 
become famous, or infamous, under the name of 
Casuistry, had its origin in the distinction between 
Mortal and Venial Sin. A natural anxiety to escape 
the awful consequences of determining a particular act 
to be mortally sinful, and a desire, equally intelligible, 
to assist the Roman Catholic Church in its conflict 
with Protestantism by disburthening it of an incon- 



952 CASUISTRY. chap. ix. 

venient theory, were the motives which impelled the 
authors of the Casuistical philosophy to the invention 
of an elaborate system of criteria, intended to remove 
immoral actions, in as many cases as possible, out of 
the category of mortal ofiences, and to stamp them as 
venial sins. The fate of this experiment is matter of 
ordinary history. We know that the distinctions of 
Casuistry, by enabling the priesthood to adjust spiri- 
tual control to all the varieties of human character, 
did really confer on it an influence with princes, 
statesmen, and generals, unheard of in the ages 
before the Keformation, and did really contribute 
largely to that great reaction which checked and nar- 
rowed the first successes of Protestantism. But 
beginning in the attempt, not to establish, but to 
evade — ^not to discover a principle, but to escape a 
postulate — not to settle the nature of right and 
wrong, but to determine what was not wrong of a 
particular nature, — Casuistry went on with its dex- 
terous refinements till it ended in so attenuating 
the moral features of actions, and so belying the 
moral instincts of our being, that at length the con- 
science of mankind rose suddenly in revolt against it, 
and consigned to one common ruin the system and its 
doctors. The blow, long pending, was finally struck 
in the Provincial Letters of Pascal, and since the ap- 
pearance of those memorable Papers, no moralist of 
the smallest influence or credit has ever avowedly 



CHAP. IX. ETHICS AND ROMAN LAW. 353 

conducted his speculations in the footsteps of the 
Casuists. The whole field of ethical science was thus 
left at the exclusive command of the writers who fol- 
lowed Grotius ; and it still exhibits in an extraordi- 
nary degree the traces of that entanglement with 
Roman law which is sometimes imputed as a fault, 
and sometimes the highest of its recommendations, to 
the Grotian theory. Many inquirers since Grotius's 
day have modified his principles, and many, of course, 
since the rise of the Critical Philosophy, have quite 
deserted them; but even those who have departed 
most widely from his fundamental assumptions have 
inherited much of his method of statement, of his 
train of thought, and of his mode of illustration ; and 
these have little meaning and no point to the person 
ignorant of Roman jurisprudence." 

I have already said that, with the exception of the 
physical sciences, there is no walk of knowledge 
which has been so slightly affected by Roman law as 
Metaphysics. The reason is that discussion on me- 
taphysical subjects has always been conducted in 
Greek, first in pure Greek, and afterwards in a dialect 
of Latin expressly constructed to give expression to 
Greek conceptions. The modem languages have only 
been fitted to metaphysical inquiries by adopting 
this Latin dialect, or by imitating the process which 
was originally followed in its formation. The source 
of the phraseology which has been always employed 

A A 



854 METAPHYSICS AND ROMAK LAW. chap. ix. 

for metaphysical discussion in modem times was the 
Latin translations of Aristotle, in which, whether 
derived or not firom Arabic versions, the plan of the 
translator was not to seek for analogous expressions 
in any part of Latin literature, but to construct anew 
from Latin roots a set of phvases equal to the expres- 
sion of Greek philosophical ideas. Over such a 
process the terminology of Roman law can have 
exercised little influence ; at most, a few Latin law 
terms in a transmuted shape have made their way 
into metaphysical language. At the same time it is 
worthy of remark that whenever the problems of 
metaphysics are those which have been most strongly 
agitated in Western Europe, the thought, if not the 
language, betrays a legal parentage. Few things in 
the history of speculation are more impressive than 
the fact that no Greek-speaking people has ever felt 
itself seriously perplexed by the great question of 
Free-will and Necessity. I do not pretend to offer 
any summary explanation of this, but it does not 
seem an irrelevant suggestion that neither the Greeks, 
nor any society speaking and thinking in their lan- 
guage, ever showed the smallest capacity for produc- 
ing a philosophy of law. Legal science is a Roman 
creation, and the problem of Free-will arises when we 
contemplate a metaphysical conception under a legal 
aspect. How came it to be a question whether in- 
variable sequence was identical with necessary con- 



CHAP. IX. THEOLOGY AND ROMAN LAW. 355 

nection ? I can only say that the tendency of Roman 
law, which became stronger as it advanced, was to 
look upon legal consequences as united to legal causes 
by an inexorable necessity, a tendency most markedly 
exemplified in the definition of Obligation which I 
have repeatedly cited, "Juris vinculum quo neces- 
sitate adstringimur alicujus solvendae rei.'' 

But the problem of Free-will was theological before 
it became philosophical, and, if its terms have been 
affected by jurisprudence, it will be because Jurispru- 
dence has made itself felt in Theology. The great 
pdint of inquiry which is here suggested has never 
been satisfactorily elucidated. What has to be 
determined, is whether jurisprudence has ever served 
as the medium through which theological principles 
have been viewed ; whether, by supplying a peculiar 
language, a peculiar mode of reasoning, and a peculiar 
solution of many of the problems of life, it has ever 
opened new channels in which theological speculation 
could flow out and expand itself. For the purpose 
of giving an answer it is necessary to recollect what 
is already agreed upon by the best writers as to the 
intellectual food which theology first assimilated. It 
is conceded on all sides that the earliest language of 
the Christian Church was Greek, and that the pro- 
blems to which it first addressed itself were those for 
which Greek philosophy in its later forms had pre- 
pared the way. Greek metaphysical literature con* 

A A 2 



356 GREEK AND LATIN CHURCHES. chap. ix. 

tained the sole stock of words and ideas out of 
which the human mind could provide itself with the 
means of engaging in the profound controversies as 
to the Divine Persons, the Divine Substance, and 
the Divine Natures. The Latin language and the 
meagre Latin philosophy were quite unequal to the 
undertaking, and accordingly the Western or Latin- 
speaking provinces of the Empire adopted the con- 
clusions of the East without disputing or reviewing 
them. " Latin Christianity," says Dean Milman, 
"accepted the creed which its narrow and barren 
vocabulary could hardly express in adequate terms. 
Yet, throughout, the adhesion of Rome and the West 
was a passive acquiescence in the dogmatic system 
which had been wrought out by the profounder theo- 
logy of the Eastern divines, rather than a vigorous 
and original examination on her part of those mys- 
teries. The Latin Church was the scholar as well as 
the loyal partizan of Athanasius." But when the 
separation of East and West became wider, and the 
Latin-speaking Western Empire began to live with 
an intellectual life of its own, its deference to the 
East was all at once exchanged for the agitation of 
a number of questions entirely foreign to Eastern 
speculation. " While Greek theology (Milman, Latin 
Christianity^ Preface, 5) went on defining with still 
more exquisite subtlety the Godhead and the nature 
of Christ " — " w-hile the interminable controversy stlQ 



CHAP. IX. PROBLEMS OF WESTERN CHURCH. 357 

lengthened out and cast forth sect after sect from the 
enfeebled community" — ^the Western Church threw 
itself with passionate ardour into a new order of dis- 
putes, the same which from those days to this have 
never lost their interest for any family of mankind at 
any time included in the Latin communion. The 
nature of Sin and its transmission by inheritance — 
the debt owed by man and its vicarious satisfaction 
— the necessity and sufficiency of the Atonement — 
above all the apparent antagonism between Free-will 
and the Divine Providence — these were the points 
which the West began to debate as ardently as ever 
the East had discussed the articles of its more special 
creed. Why is it then that on the two sides of the 
line which divides the Greek-speaking from the 
Latin-speaking provinces there lie two classes of 
theological problems so strikingly different from one 
another? The historians of the Church have come 
close upon the solution when they remark that the 
new problems were more " practical," less absolutely 
speculative, than those which had torn Eastern 
Christianity asunder, but none of them, so far as I 
am aware, has quite reached it. I affirm without 
hesitation that the difference between the two theo- 
logical systems is accounted for by the fact that, in 
passing from the East to the West, theological specu- 
lation had passed from a climate of Greek metaphysics 
to a climate of Roman law. For some centuries 

A A 3 



358 ROMAN LAW IN THE WEST. chap. ix. 

before these controversies rose into overwhelming 
importance, all the intellectual activity of the Western 
Romans had been expended on jurisprudence exclu- 
sively. They had been occupied in applying a pecu- 
liar set of principles to all the combinations in which 
the circumstances of life are capable of being arranged. 
No foreign pursuit or taste called off their attention 
from this engrossing occupation, and for carrying it 
on they possessed a vocabulary as accurate as it was 
copious, a strict method of reasoning, a stock of 
general propositions on conduct more or less verified 
by experience, and a rigid moral philosophy. It was 
impossible that they should not select from the ques- 
tions indicated by the Christian records those which 
had some affinity with the order of speculations to 
which they were accustomed, and that their manner 
of dealing with them should borrow something firom 
their forensic habits. Almost everybody who has 
Jcnowledge enough of Eoman law to appreciate the 
Roman penal system, the Roman theory of the obli- 
gations established by Contract or Delict, the Roman 
view of Debts and of the modes of incurring, extin- 
guishing, and transmitting them, the Roman notion 
of the continuance of individual existence by Universal 
Succession, may be trusted to say whence arose the 
frame of mind to which the problems of Western 
theology proved so congenial, whence came the phra- 
seology in which these problems were stated, and 



cHAr. IX. THEOLOGY AND ROMAN LAW. 859 

whence the description of reasoning employed in their 
solution. It must only be recollected that the Roman 
law which had worked itself into Western thought 
was neither the archaic system of the ancient city, 
nor the pruned and curtailed jurisprudence of the 
Byzantine Emperors ; still less, of course, was it the 
mass of rules, nearly buried in a parasitical over- 
growth of modem speculative doctrine, which passes 
by the name of Modem Civil Law. I speak only of 
that philosophy of jurisprudence, wrought out by 
the great juridical thinkers of the Antonine age, 
which may still be partially reproduced from the 
Pandects of Justinian, a system to which few faults 
can be attributed except it perhaps ahned at a 
higher degree of elegance, certainty and precision 
than human affairs will permit to the limits within 
which human laws seek to confine them. 

It is a singular result of that ignorance of Roman 
law which Englishmen readily confess, and of which 
they are sometimes not ashamed to boast, that many 
English writers of note and credit have been led by 
it to put forward the most untenable of paradoxes 
concerning the condition of human intellect during 
the Roman Empire. It has been constantly asserted, 
as unhesitatingly as if there were no temerity in ad- 
vancing the proposition, that from the close of the 
Augustan era to the general awakening of interest 
on the points of the Christian faith, the mental ener- 

A A 4 



360 GREEK AND LATIN-SPEAKING PROVINCES, ch. ix. 

gies of the civilised world were smitten with a para- 
lysis. Novv there are two subjects of .thought — the 
only two perhaps with the exception of physical 
science — which are able to give employment to aU 
the powers and capacities which the mind possesses. 
One of them is Metaphysical inquiry, which knows no 
limits so long as the mind is satisfied to work on 
itself ; the other is Law, which is as extensive as the 
concerns of mankind. It happens that, during the 
very period indicated, the Greek-speaking provinces 
were devoted to one, the Latin-speaking provinces to 
the other, of these studies. I say nothing of the fruits 
of speculation in Alexandria and the East, but I con- 
fidently affirm that Rome and the West had an occu- 
pation in hand fully capable of compensating them 
for the absence of every other mental exercise, and I 
add that the results achieved, so far as we know 
them, were not unworthy of the continuous and ex- 
clusive labour bestowed on producing them. Nobody 
except a professional lawyer is perhaps in a position 
completely to understand how much of the intellectual 
strength of individuals Law is capable of absorbing, 
but a layman has no difficulty in comprehending why 
it was that an unusual share of the collective intellect 
of Rome was engrossed by jurisprudence. " The 
proficiency * of a given community in jurisprudence 
depends in the long run on the same conditions as its 

• Cambridge Ea&mfSj 1866. 



CH. IX. CAUSES OF IMPROVEMENT IN ROMAN LAW. 361 

progress in any other line of -inquiry; and the chief 
of these are the proportion of the national intellect 
devoted to it, and the length of time during which it 
is so devoted. Now, a combination of all the causes, 
direct and indirect, which contribute to the advancing 
and perfecting of a science continued to operate on the 
jurisprudence of Kome through the entire space be- 
tween the Twelve Tables and the severance of the two 
Empires, — and that not irregularly or at intervals, 
but in steadily increasing force and constantly aug- 
menting number. We should reflect that the earliest 
intellectual exercise to which a young nation devotes 
itself is the study of its laws. As soon as the mind 
makes its first conscious efforts towards generalis- 
ation, the concerns of every-day life are the first to 
press for inclusion within general rules and com- 
prehensive formulas. The popularity of the pursuit 
on which all the energies of the young common- 
wealth are bent is at the outset unbounded; but 
it ceases in time. The monopoly of mind by law 
is broken down. The crowd at the morning au- 
dience of the great Roman jurisconsult lessens. 
The students are counted by hundreds instead of 
thousands in the English Inns of Court. Art, 
Literature, Science, and Politics, claim their share 
of the national intellect; and the practice of juris- 
prudence is confined within the circle of a profes- 
sion, never indeed limited or insignificant, but at- 



363 CAUSES OF IMPROVEMENT IN ROMAN LAW. ch. ix. 

tracted as much by the rewards as by the intrinsic 
recommendations of their science. This succession 
of changes exhibited itself even more strikingly at 
Rome than in England. To the close of the Republic 
the law was the sole field for all ability except the 
special talent of a capacity for generalship. But a 
new stage of intellectual progress began with the 
Augustan age, as it did with our own Elizabethan 
era. We all know what were its achievements in 
poetry and prose; but there are some indications, it 
should be remarked, that, besides its efflorescence in 
ornamental literature, it was on the eve of throwing 
out new aptitudes for conquest in physical science. 
Here, however, is the point at which the history of 
mind in the Roman State ceases to be parallel to the 
routes which mental progress had since then pursued. 
The brief span of Roman literature, strictly so called, 
was sii^enly closed under a variety of influences, 
which though they may partially be traced it would 
be improper in this place to analyse. Ancient intel- 
lect was forcibly thrust back into its old courses, and 
law again became no less exclusively the proper 
sphere for talent than it had been in the days when 
the Romans despised philosophy and poetry as the 
toys of a childish race. Of what nature were the ex- 
ternal inducements which, during the Imperial period, 
tended to draw a man of inherent capacity to the 
pursuits of the jurisconsult may best be understood 



CHAP. IX. ROMAN LAW m THE EAST. 363 

by considering the option which was practically before 
him in his choice of a profession. He might become 
a teacher of rhetoric, a commander of frontier-posts, 
or a professional writer of panegyrics. The only 
other walk of active life which was open to him was 
the practice of the law. Through that lay the 
approach to wealth, to fame, to office, to the council- 
chamber of the monarch — it may be to the very 
throne itself." 

The premium on the study of jurisprudence was so 
enormous that there were schools of law in every part 
of the Empire, even in the very domain of Metaphy- 
sics. But, though the transfer of the seat of empire 
to Byzantium gave a perceptible impetus to its culti- 
vation in the East, jurisprudence never dethroned 
the pursuits which there competed with it. Its lan- 
guage was Latin, an exotic dialect in the Eastern half 
of the Empire. It is only of the West that we can 
lay down that law was not only the mental food of 
the ambitious and aspiring, but the sole aliment of 
all intellectual activity. Greek philosophy had never 
been more than a transient fashionable taste with the 
educated class of Rome itself, and when the new 
Eastern capital had been created, and the Empire 
subsequently divided into two, the divorce of the 
Western provinces from Greek speculation, and their 
exclusive devotion to jurisprudence, became more de- 
cided than ever. As soon then as they ceased to sit 



964 ROMAN LAW IN WESTERN THEOLOGY, chap. ix. 

at the feet of the Greeks and began to ponder out a 
theology of their own, the theology proved to be per- 
meated with forensic ideas and couched in a forensic 
phraseology. It is certain that this substratum of 
law in Western theology lies exceedingly deep. A 
new set of Greek theories, the Aristotelian philosophy, 
made their way afterwards into the West and almost 
entirely buried its indigenous doctrines. But when 
at the Reformation it partially shook itself free from 
their influence, it instantly supplied their place with 
Law. It is difficult to say whether the religious sys- 
tem of Calvin or the religious system of the Armi- 
nians has the more markedly legal character. 

The vast influence of the specific jurisprudence of 
Contract produced by the Romans upon the corre- 
sponding department of modem Law belongs rather 
to the history of mature jurisprudence than to a 
treatise like the present. It did not make itself felt 
till the school of Bologna founded the legal science 
of modern Europe. But the fact that the Romans, 
before their Empire fell, had so ftilly developed the 
conception of Contract becomes of importance at a 
much earlier period than this. Feudalism, I have 
repeatedly asserted, was a compound of archaic bar- 
barian usage with Roman law; no other explanation 
of it is tenable, or even intelligible. The earliest 
social forms of the feudal period differ in little from 
the ordinary associations in which the men of primi-' 



CHAP. IX. CONTRACT-LAW AND FEUDALISM. 365 

tive civilisations are everywhere seen united. A 
Fief was an organically complete brotherhood of 
associates whose proprietary and personal rights were 
inextricably blended together. It had much in com- 
mon with an Indian Village Community and much 
in common with a Highland clan. But still it pre- 
sents some phenomena which we never find in the asso- 
ciations which are spontaneously formed by beginners 
in civilisation. True archaic communities are held 
together not by express rules, but by sentiment, or, 
we should perhaps say, by instinct; and new comers 
into the brotherhood are brought within the range of 
this instinct by falsely pretending to share in the 
blood-relationship from which it naturally springs. 
But the earliest feudal communities were neither 
bound together by mere sentiment nor recruited by a 
fiction. The tie which united them was Contract, 
and they obtained new associates by contracting with 
them. The relation of the lord to the vassals had 
originally been settled by express engagement, and a 
person wishing to engraft himself on the brotherhood 
by commendation or infeudation came to a distinct 
understanding as to the conditions on which he was 
to be admitted. It is therefore the sphere occupied 
in them by Contract which principally distinguishes 
the feudal institutions from the unadulterated usages 
of primitive races. The lord had many of the cha- 
racteristics of a patriarchal chieftain, but his pre- 



3e6 CONTRACT-LAW AND FEUDALISM. chap. ix. 

rogative was limited by a variety of settled customs 
traceable to the express conditions which had been 
agreed upon when the infeudation took place. Hence 
flow the chief differences which forbid us to class the 
feudal societies with true archaic communities* They 
were much more durable and much more various; 
more durable, because express rules are less destruc- 
tible than instinctive habits, and more various, be- 
cause the contracts on which they were founded were 
adjusted to the minutest circumstances and wishes of 
the persons who surrendered or granted away their 
lands. This last consideration may serve to indicate 
how greatly the vulgar opinions current among us 
as to the origin of modem society stand in need of 
revision. It is often said that the irregular and 
various contour of modem civiKsation is due to the 
exuberant- and erratic genius of the Germanic races, 
and it is often contrasted with the dull routine of 
the Roman Empire. The truth is that the Empire 
bequeathed to modem society the legal conception 
to which all this irregularity is attributable; if the 
customs and institutions of barbarians have one 
characteristic more striking than another, it is their 
extreme uniformity. 



LAW IN ANQENT CODES. 367 



CHAP. X. 

THE EARLY HISTORY OF DELICT AND CRIME. 

The Teutonic Codes, including those of our Anglo- 
Saxon ancestors, are the only bodies of archaic 
secular law which have come down to us in such 
a state that we can form an exact notion of their 
original dimensions. Although the extant fragments 
of Roman and Hellenic codes suffice to prove to us 
their general character, there does not remain enough 
of them for us to be quite sure of their precise mag- 
nitude or of the proportion of their parts to each 
other. But still on the whole all the known collections ( 
of ancient law are characterised by a feature which 
broadly distinguishes them from systems of mature 
jurisprudence. The proportion of criminal to civil 
law is exceedingly different. In the German codes, the 
civil part of the law has trifling dimensions as com- 
pared with the criminal. The traditions which speak 
of the sanguinary penalties inflicted by the code of 
Draco seem to indicate that it had the same charac- 
teristic. In the Twelve Tables alone, produced by a 
society of greater legal genius and at first of gentler 
manners, the civil law has something like its modem 
precedence ; but the relative amount of space given 



368 PENAL LAW IN ANCIENT CODES. chap. x. 

to the modes of redressing wrong, though not enor- 
mous, appears to have been large. It may be laid 
down, I think, that the more archaic the code, the 
fuller and the minuter is its penal legislation. The 
phenomenon has often been observed, and has been 
explained, no doubt to a great extent correctly, by 
the violence habitual to the communities which for 
the first time reduced their laws to writing. The 
legislator, it is said, proportioned the divisions of his 
work to the frequency of a certain class of incidents 
in barbarian life, I imagine, however, that this 
account is not quite complete. It should be recol- 
lected that the comparative barrenness of civil law 
in archaic collections is consistent with those other 
characteristics of ancient jurisprudence which have 
been discussed in this treatise. Nine-tenths of the 
civil part of the law practised by civilised societies 
are made up of the Law of Persons, of the Law of 
Property and of Inheritance, and of the Law of 
Contract. But it is plain that all these provinces 
of jurisprudence must shrink within narrower boun- 
daries, the nearer we make our approaches to the 
infancy of social brotherhood. The Law of Persons, 
which is nothing else than the Law of Status, wQl 
be restricted to the scantiest limits as long as all 
forms of status are merged in common subjection to 
Paternal Power, as long as the Wife has no rights 
against her Husband, the Son none against his 



CHAP. X. CRIMES AND WRONGS. 369 

Father, and the infant Ward none against the Ag- 
nates who are his Guardians. Similarly, the rules 
relating to Property and Succession can never be 
plentiful, so long as land and goods devolve within 
the family, and, if distributed at all, are distributed 
inside its circle. But the greatest gap in ancient 
civil law will always be caused by the absence of 
Contract, which some archaic codes do not mention at 
all, while others significantly attest the immaturity 
of the moral notions on which Contract depends by 
supplying its place with an elaborate jurisprudence 
of Oaths. There are no corresponding reasons for 
the poverty of penal law, and accordingly, even if it 
be hazardous to pronounce that the childhood of 
nations is always a period of ungovemed violence, 
we shall still be able to understand why the modern 
relation of criminal law to civil should be inverted 
in ancient codes. 

I have spoken of primitive jurisprudence as giving 
to criminal law a priority unknown in a later age. 
The expression has been used for convenience' sake, 
but in fact the inspection of ancient codes shows that 
the law which they exhibit in unusual quantities is 
not true criminal law. All civilised systems agree 
in drawing a distinction between ofifences against the 
State or Community and ofifences against the Indi- 
vidual, and the two classes of injuries, thus kept 
apart, I may here, without pretending that the terms 

B B 



870 CRIMES AND WRONGS. chap. x. 

have always been employed consistently in jurispru- 
dence, call Crimes and Wrongs, crimina and delicta. 
Now the penal law of ancient communities is not 
the law of Crimes; it is the law of Wrongs, or, to 
lise the English technical word, of Torts. The person 
injured proceeds against the wrong-doer by an ordi- 
nary civil action, and recovers compensation in the 
shape of money-damages if he succeeds. If the 
Commentaries of Gaius be opened at the place where 
the writer treats of the penal jurisprudence founded 
on the Twelve Tables, it will be seen that at the 
head of the civil wrongs recognised by the Roman 
law stood Furtum or Theft Offences which we are 
accustomed to regard exclusively as crimes are 
exclusively treated as torte, and not theft only, but 
assault and violent robbery, are associated by the 
jurisconsult with trespass, libel and slander. All 
alike gave rise to an Obligation or vinculum juris, 
and were all requited by a payment of money* This 
peculiarity, however, is most strongly brought out 
in the consolidated Laws of the Germanic tribes. 
Without an exception, they describe an immense 
system of money compensations for homicide, and 
with few exceptions, as large a scheme of compensa- 
tions for minor injuries. " Under Anglo-Saxon law," 
writes Mr. Kemble (Anglo- Saxons y i. 177), "a sum 
was placed on the life of every free man, according 
to his rank, and a corresponding sum on every wound 



CHAP. X. WRONGS AND SINS. 871 

that could be inflicted on his person, for nearly every 
injury that could be done to his civil rights, honour 
or peace ; the sum being aggravated according to 
adventitious circumstances." These compositions are 
evidently regarded as a valuable source of income; 
highly complex rulfes regulate the title to them and 
the responsibility for them; and, as I have already 
had occasion to state, they often follow a very 
peculiar line of devolution, if they have not been 
acquitted at the decease of the person to whom 
they belong. If therefore the criterion of a delict^ 
wrotiffj or tort be that the person who suflfers it, and 
not the State, is conceived to be wronged, it may be 
asserted that in the infancy of jurisprudence the 
citizen depends for protection against violence or 
fraud not on the Law of Crime but on the Law of 
Tort. 

Torts then are copiously enlarged upon in primi- 
tive jurisprudence. It must be added that Sins are ; 
known to it also. Of the Teutonic codes it is almost 
unnecessary to make this assertion, because those 
codes, in the form in which we have received them, 
were compiled or recast by Christian legislators. But 
it is also true that non-christian bodies of archaic 
law entail penal consequences on certain classes of 
acts and on certain classes of omissions, as being 
violations of divine prescriptions and commands. The 
law administered at Athens by the Senate of Areo- 

B B 2 



372 CONCEPTION OF CRIME. chap. il. 

pagus was probably a special religious code, and at 
Rome, apparently from a very early period, the Pon- 
tifical jurisprudence punished adultery, sacrilege and 
perhaps murder. There were therefore in the Athe- 
nian and in the Roman States laws punishing sins. 
There were also laws punishing torts. The concep- 
tion of offence against God produced the first class 
of ordinances ; the conception of offence against one's 
neighbour produced the second ; but the idea of offence 
against the State or aggregate community did not at 
first produce a true criminal jurisprudence. 

Yet it is not to be supposed that a conception 
so simple and elementary as that of wrong done to 
the State was wanting in any primitive society. It 
seems rather that the very distinctness with which 
jthis conception is realised is the true cause which at 
[first prevents the growth of a criminal law. At all 
events, when the Roman community conceived itself 
to be injured, the analogy of a personal wrong received 
was carried out to its consequences with absolute 
literalness, and the State avenged itself by a single 
act on the individual wrong-doer. The result was 
that, in the infancy of the commonwealth, every 
offence vitally touching its security or its interests 
was punished by a separate enactment of the legis- 
lature. And this is the earliest conception of a 
crimen or Crime — an act involving such high issues 
that the State, instead of leaving its cognisance 



CHAF. X. ANCIENT CONCEPTION OF CRIME. 373 

to the civil tribunal or the religious court, directed 
a special law or privilegium against the perpetrator. 
Every indictment therefore took the form of a bill 
of pains and penalties, and the trial of a criminaA 
was a proceeding wholly extraordinary, wholly irreJ 
gular, wholly independent of settled rules and fixed! 
conditions. Consequently, both for the reason that 
the tribunal dispensing justice was the sovereign 
state itself and also for the reason that no classifi- 
cation of the acts prescribed or forbidden was pos- j 
sible, there was not at this epoch any Law of crimes, 
any criminal jurisprudence. The procedure was 
identical with the forms of passing an ordinary 
statute; it was set in motion by the same persons 
and conducted with precisely the same solemnities. 
And it is to be observed that, when a regular 
criminal law with an apparatus of Courts and officers 
for its administration had afterwards come into 
being, the old procedure, as might be supposed 
from its conformity with theory, still in strictness 
remained practicable; and, much as resort to such 
an expedient was discredited, the people of Rome 
always retained the power of punishing by a special 
law oflfences against its majesty. The classical 
scholar does not require to be reminded that in 
exactly the same manner the Athenian Bill of 
Pains and Penalties, or 6i<rayysx/a, survived the esta- 
blishment of regular tribunals. It is known too 

,B B 3 



374 ANCIENT PROCEDURE. chap. x. 

that when the freemen of the Teutonic races assem- 
bled for legislation, they also claimed authority to 
punish offences of peculiar blackness or perpetrated 
by criminals of exalted station. Of this nature was 
the criminal jurisdiction of the Anglo-Saxon Witen- 
agemot. 

It may be thought that the difference which I have 
asserted to exist between the ancient and modem 
view of penal law has only a verbal existence. 
The community, it may be said, besides inter- 
posing to punish crimes legislatively, has from the 
earliest times interfered by its tribunals to compel 
the wrong-doer to compound for his wrong, and, 
if it does this, it must always have supposed that 
in some way it was injured through his offence. 
But, however rigorous this inference may seem to 
us now-a-days, it is vevj doubtful whether it was 
actually drawn by the men of primitive antiquity. 
How little the notion of injury to the community 
had to do with the earliest interferences of the State 
through its tribunals^ is shown by the curious circum- 
stances that in the original administration of justice, 
the proceedings were a close imitation of the series 
of acts which were likely to be gone through in 
private life by persons who were disputing, but who 
afterwards suffered their quarrel to be appeased. 
The magistrate carefully simulated the demeanour 
of a private arbitrator casually called in. 



CHAP. X. THE ROMAN LEGIS ACTIO. 375 

In order to show that this statement is not a mere 
fanciful conceit, I will produce the evidence on 
which it rests. Very far the most ancient judicial 
proceeding known to us is the Legis Actio Sacra- 
menti of the Romans, out of which all the later 
Roman Law of Actions may be proved to have 
grown. Gaius carefully describes its ceremonial. 
Unmeaning and grotesque as it appears at first 
sight, a little attention enables us to decipher and 
interpret it. 

The subject of litigation is supposed to be in 
Court. If it is moveable, it is actually there. If it 
be immoveable, a fragment or sample of it is brought 
in its place; land, for instance, is represented by a 
clod, a house by a single brick. In the example 
selected by Gaius, the suit is for a slave. The pro- 
ceeding begins by the plaintiff's advancing with a 
rod, which, as Gaius expressly tells, symbolised a 
spear. He lays hold of the slave and asserts a right 
to him with the words, " Hunc ego hominem ex Jure 
Quirittum meum esse dico secundum suam causam 
sicutdixi; " and then saying, " Ecce tibi Vindictam im- 
posui" he touches him with the spear. The de- 
fendant goes through the same series of acts and 
gestures. On this the Praetor intervenes, and bids 
the litigants relax their hold, ^^ Mittite ambo ho- 
minem.*^ They obey, and the plaintiff demands from 
the defendant the reason of his interference, ^'Pos- 

B B 4 



S76 MEANING OF THE LEGIS ACTIO. chaf. x. 

tulo anne dicas qud ex caitsd vindicaveris" a question 
which is replied to by a fresh assertion of right, 
" Jus peregi sicut vindictam imposuL On this, the 
first chiimant offers to stake a sum of money, called 
a Sacramentum, on the justice of his own case, 
" Quando tu injurid provocastij D ceris Sacramento te 
provoco" and the defendant, in the phrase " Similiter 
ego fe," accepts the wager. The subsequent proceed- 
ings were no longer of a formal kind, but it is to 
be observed that the Praetor took security for the 
Sacramentum, which always went into the coffers of 
the State. 

Such was the necessary preface of every ancient 
Roman suit. It is impossible, I think, to refuse 
assent to the suggestion of those who see in it a 
dramatization of the Origin of Justice. Two armed 
men are wrangling about some disputed property. 
The Praetor, vir pietate gravis^ happens to be going 
by, and interposes to stop the contest. The dis- 
putants state their case to him, and agree that 
he shall arbitrate between them, it being arranged 
that the loser, besides resigning the subject of the 
quarrel, shall pay a sum of money to the umpire 
as remuneration for his trouble and loss of time. 
This interpretation would be less plausible than it 
is, were it not that, by a surprising coincidence, the 
ceremony described by Gains as the imperative 
course of proceeding in a Legis Actio is substantially 



CHAP. X. ANCIENT SUIT IN HOMER. 377 

the same with one of the two subjects which the 
God HephaBstus is described by Homer as moulding 
into the First Compartment of the Shield of Achilles. 
In the Homeric trial-scene, the dispute, as if ex- 
pressly intended to bring out the characteristics of 
of primitive society, is not about property but about 
the composition for a homicide. One person asserts 
that he has paid it, the other that he has never 
received it. The point of detail, however, which 
stamps the picture as the counterpart of the archaic 
Roman practice is the reward designed for the 
judges. Two talents of gold lie in the middle, to 
be given to him who shall explain the grounds of the 
decision most to the satisfaction of the audience. 
The magnitude of this sum as compared with the 
trifling amount of the Sacramentum seems to me 
indicative of the indifference between fluctuating 
usage and usage consolidated into law. The scene 
introduced by the poet as a striking and character- 
istic, but still only occasional, feature of city-life in the 
heroic age has stiffened, at the opening of the history 
of civil process, into the regular, ordinary formalities 
of a lawsuit. It is natural therefore that in the 
Legis Actio the remuneration of the Judge should 
be reduced to a reasonable sum, and that, instead 
of being adjudged to one of a number of arbitrators 
by popular acclamation, it should be paid as a 
matter of course to the State which the Praetor 



378 ANCIENT VIEW OF PROCEDUKE. chap. x. 

represents. But that the incidents described so 
vividly by Homer, and by Gains with even more 
than the usual crudity of technical language, have 
substantially the same meaning, I cannot doubt; 
and, in confirmation of this view it may be added 
that many observers of the earliest judicial usages 
of modem Europe have remarked that the fines 
inflicted by Courts on oflfenders were originally 
sacramenta. The State did not take from the 
defendant a composition for any wrong supposed 
to be done to itself, but claimed a share in the 
compensation awarded to the plaintifi^ simply as the 
fair price of its time and trouble. Mr. Kemble, 
expressly assigns this character to the Anglo-Saxon 
hannum ov fredum. 

Ancient law furnishes other proofs that the earliest 
administrators of justice simulated the probable acts 
of persons jengaged in a private quarrel. In settling 
the damages to be awarded, they took as their guide 
the measure of vengeance likely to be exacted by an 
aggrieved person under the circumstances of the 
case. This is the true explanation of the very dif- 
ferent penalties imposed by ancient law on ofifenders 
caught in the act or soon after it and on oflfenders 
detected after considerable delay. Some strange ex- 
emplifications of this peculiarity are supplied by the 
old Roman law of Theft. The Laws of the Twelve 
Tables seem to have divided Thefts into Manifest and 



CHAP. X. OLD ROMAN LAW OP THEFT. 379 

Non-Manifest, and to have allotted' extraordinarily 
different penalties to the offence according as it fell 
under one head or the other. The Manifest Thief 
was he who was caught within the house in which 
he had been pilfering, or who was taken while making 
off to a place of safety with the stolen goods; the 
Twelve Tables condemned him to be put to death if 
he were already a slave, and, if he was a freeman, they 
made him the bondsman of the owner of the pro- 
perty. The Non-Manifest Thief was he who was 
detected under any other circumstances than those 
described ; and the old code simply directed that an 
offender of this sort should refund double the value 
of what he had stolen. In Gaius's day the excessive 
severity of the Twelve Tables to the Manifest Thief 
had naturally been much mitigated, but the law still 
maintained the old principle by mulcting him in 
fourfold the value of the stolen goods, while the 
Non- Manifest Thief still continued to pay merely thS 
double. The ancient lawgiver doubtless considered 
that the injured proprietor, if left to himself, would 
inflict a very different punishment when his blood 
was hot from that with which he would be satisfied 
when the Thief was detected after a considerable 
interval; and to this calculation the legal scale of 
penalties was adjusted. The principle is precisely 
the same as that followed in the Anglo-Saxon and 
other Germanic codes, when they suffer a thief chased 



380 ANCIENT MEASURE OF PUNISHMENT, chap. x. 

down and caught with the booty to be hanged or 
decapitated on the spot, while they exact the full 
penalties of homicide from anybody who kills him 
after the pursuit has been intermitted. These archaic 
distinctions bring home to us very forcibly the 
distance of a refined from a rude jurisprudence. 
The modern administrator of justice has confessedly 
one of his hardest tasks before him when he under- 
takes to discriminate between the degrees of crimin- 
ality which belong to offences falling within the same 
technical description. It is always easy to say that 
a man is guilty of manslaughter, larceny, or bigamy, 
but it is often most difficult to pronounce what 
extent of moral guilt he has incurred, and conse- 
quently what measure of punishment he has deserved. 
There is hardly any perplexity in casuistry, or in the 
analysis of motive, which we may not be called upon 
to confront, if we attempt to settle such a point with 
{)recision ; and accordingly the law of our day shows 
an increasing tendency to abstain as much as pos- 
sible from laying down positive rules on the subject. 
In France, the jury is left to decide whether the 
offence which it finds committed has been attended 
by extenuating circumstances ; in England, a nearly 
unbounded latitude in the selection of punishments is 
now allowed to the judge ; while all States have in 
reserve an ultimate remedy for the miscarriages of law 
in the Prerogative of Pardon, universally lodged with 



CHAP. X. TRUE CRIMINAL JURISPRUDENCE. 381 

the Chief Magistrate. It is curious to observe how 
little the men of primitive times were troubled with 
these scruples, how completely they were persuaded 
that the impulses of the injured person were the 
proper measure of the vengeance he was entitled to 
exact, and how literally they imitated the probable rise 
and fall of his passions in fixing their scale of punish- 
ment. I wish it could be said that their method of 
legislation is quite extinct. There are, however, 
several modem systems of law which, in cases of 
graver wro]Qg, admit the fact of the wrong doer having 
been taken the act to be pleaded in justification of 
inordinate punishment inflicted on him by the 
sufferer — an indulgence which, though superficially 
regarded it may seem intelligible, is based, as it 
seems to me, on a very low morality. 

Nothing, I have said, can be simpler than the con- 
siderations which ultimately led ancient societies to 
the formation of a true criminal jurisprudence. The' 
State conceived itself to be wronged, and the Popular 
Assembly struck straight at the oflFender with the 
same movement which accompanied its legislative 
action. It is further true of the ancient world — 
though not precisely of the modem, as I shall have 
occasion to point out — that the earliest criminal 
tribunals were merely subdivisions, or committees, of 
the legislature. This, at all events, is the conclusion 
pointed at by the legal history of the two great 



382 CRIMINAL JURISDICTION OF LEGISLATURE, chap. x. 

states of antiquity, with tolerable clearness in one 
case, and with absolute distinctness in the other. 
The primitive penal law of Athens entrusted the 
castigation of offences partly to the Archons, who 
seem to have punished them as torfe, and partly to 
the Senate of Areopagus, which punished them as 
sins. Both jurisdictions were substantially trans- 
ferred in the end to the Heliaea, the High Court of 
Popular Justice, and the functions of the Archons 
and of the Areopagus became either merely minis- 
terial or quite insignificant. But "Heliaea" is only 
an old word for Assembly; the Heliasa of classical 
times was simply the Popular Assembly .convened 
for judicial purposes, and the famous Dikafiteries of 
Athens were only its subdivisions or panels. The 
corresponding changes which occurred at Rome are 
still more easily interpreted, because the Romans 
confined their experiments to the penal law, and did 
not, like the Athenians, construct popular courts 
with a civil as well as a criminal jurisdiction. The 
history of Roman criminal jurisprudence begins with 
the old Judicia Populi, at which the Kings are said 
to have presided. These were simply solemn trials 
of great offenders under legislative forms. It seems, 
however, that from an early period the Comitia had 
occasionally delegated its criminal jurisdiction to a 
Qua3stio or Commission, which bore much the same 
relation to the Assembly which a Committee of the 



CHAP. X. THE QU^STIONES. 383 

House of Commons bears to the House itself, except 
that the Roman Commissioners or QuaBstores did not 
merely report to the Comitia, but exercised all powers 
which that body was itself in the habit of exercising, 
even to the passing sentence on the Accused. A 
Quaestio of this sort was only appointed to try a par- 
ticular offender, but there was nothing to prevent 
two or three Quaestiones sitting at the same time; 
and it is probable that several of them were ap- 
pointed simultaneously, when several grave cases of 
wrong to the community had occurred together. 
There are also indications that now and then these 
Quaestiones approached the character of our Standing 
Committees, in that they were appointed periodi- 
cally, and without waiting for occasion to arise in 
the commission of some serious crime. The old 
Quaestores Parricidii, who are mentioned in connec- 
tion with transactions of very ancient date, as being 
deputed to try (or, as some take it, to search out 
and try) all cases of parricide and murder, seem to 
have been appointed regularly every year; and the 
Duumviri Perduellionis, or Commission of Two for 
trial of violent injury to the Commonwealth, are also 
believed by most writers to have been named pe- 
riodically. The delegations of power to these latter 
functionaries bring us some way forwards. Instead 
of being appointed when and as state-offences were 
committed, they had a general, though a temporary 



884 QU-ffiSTIONES PERPETU-E. chap. x. 

jurisdiction over such as might be perpetrated. Our 
proximity to a regular criminal jurisprudence is also 
indicated by the general terms " Parricidium" and 
" Perduellio," which mark the approach to some- 
thing like a classification of crimes. 

The true criminal law did not however come into 
existence till the year B.C. 149, when L. Calpumius 
Piso carried the statute known as the Lex Calpumia 
de Repetundis. The law applied to cases Repetun- 
darum Pecuniarum, that is, claims by Provincials to 
recover monies improperly received by a Governor- 
General, but the great and permanent importance of 
this statute arose from its establishing the first Quaestio 
Perpetua. A Quaestio Perpetua was a Permanent 
Commission as opposed to those which were occasional 
and to those which were temporary. It was a re- 
gular criminal tribunal, whose existence dated from 
the passing of the statute creating it and continued 
till another statute should pass abolishing it. Its 
members were not specially nominated, as were the 
members of the older Quaestiones, but provision was 
made in the law constituting it for selecting from 
particular classes the judges who were to offi- 
ciate, and for renewing them in conformity with 
definite rules. The oflfences of which it took cog- 
nisance were also expressly named and defined in 
this statute, and the new Quaestio had authority to 
try and sentence all persons in future whose acts 



CHAP.x. HISTORY OF CRIMINAL LAW. 385 

should fall under the definitions of crime supplied by 
the law. It was therefore a regular criminal judica- 
ture, administering a true criminal jurisprudence. 

The primitive history of criminal law divides 
itself therefore into four stages. Understanding that 
the conception of Crime^ as distinguished from that 
of Wrong or Tort and from that of Sin^ involves the 
idea of injury to the State or collective community, 
we first find that the commonwealth, in literal 
conformity with the conception, itself interposed 
directly, and by isolated acts, to avenge itself on the 
author of the evil which it had suffered. This is the 
point from which we start ; each indictment is now 
a bill of pains and penalties, a special law naming the 
criminal and prescribing his punishment. A second 
step is accomplished, when the multiplicity of crimes 
compels the legislature to delegate its powers to 
particular Quaestiones or Commissions, each of which 
is deputed to investigate a particular accusation, and 
if it be proved, to punish the particular offender. 
Yet another movement is made when the Legislature, 
instead of waiting for the alleged commission of a 
crime as the occasion of appointing a Quaestio, periodi- 
cially nominates Commissioners like the Quaestores 
Parricidii and the Duumviri Perduellionis, on the 
chance of certain classes of crimes being committed, 
and in the expectation that they will be perpetrated. 
The last stage is reached when the Quaestiones 

c n 



386 THE QU-ESTIONES PERPETCJ^. chap. x. 

from being periodical or occasional become permanent 
Benches or Chambers — when the judges, instead of 
being named in the particular law nominating the 
Commission, are directed to be chosen through all 
future time in a particular way and from a particular 
class — and when certain acts are described in general 
language and declared to be crimes, to be visited, in 
the event of their perpetration, with specified penal- 
ties appropriated to each description. 

If the QuaBstiones Perpetuse had had a longer his- 
tory, they would doubtless have come to be regarded 
as a distinct institution, and their relation to the 
Comitia would have seemed no closer than the connec- 
tion of our own Courts of Law with the Sovereign, 
who is theoretically the fountain of justice. But the 
Imperial despotism destroyed them before their 
origin had been completely forgotten, and, so long 
as they lasted, these Permanent Conmiissions were 
looked upon by the Romans as the mere depositaries 
of a delegated power. The cognisance of crimes 
was considered a natural attribute of the legislature, 
and the mind of the citizen never ceased to be carried 
back from the Quaestiones to the Comitia which had 
deputed them to put into exercise some of its own 
inalienable functions. The view which regarded the 
QusBstiones, even when they became permanent, as 
mere Committees of the Popular Assembly — as 
bodies which only ministered to a higher authority 



cHAP.x. THEORY OF THB QUiESTIONES. 387 

— had some important legal consequenees which left 
their mark on the criminal law to the very latest 
period. One immediate result was that the Comitia 
continued to exercise criminal jurisdiction by way of 
bill of pains and penalties, long after the Quaestiones 
had been established. Though the legislature had 
consented to delegate its powers for the sake of con- 
venience to bodies external to itself, it did not follow 
that it surrendered them. The Comitia and the 
QuaBstiones went on trying and punishing offenders 
side by side; and, any unusual outburst of popular 
indignation was sure, until the extinction of the 
Republic, to call down upon its object an indictment 
before the Assembly of the Tribes. 

One of the most remarkable peculiarities of the 
institutions of the Republic is also traceable to this 
dependance of the Quaestiones on the Comitia. The 
disappearance of the punishment of Death from 
the penal system of Republican Rome used to be a 
very favourite topic with the writers of the last 
century, who were perpetually using it to point some 
theory of the Roman character or of modern social 
economy. The reason which can be confidently assigned 
for it stamps it as purely fortuitous. Of the three forms 
which the Roman legislature successively assumed, 
one, it is well known — the Comitia Centuriata — was 
exclusively taken to represent the State as embodied 
for military operations. The Assembly of the Cen- 

c c 2 



388 PUNISHMENT OF DEATH. chap. x. 

turies, tlierefore, had all powerB which may be sup- 
posed to be properly lodged with a General com- 
manding an army, and, among them, it had authority 
to subject aU offenders to the same correction to 
which a soldier rendered himself liable by breaches 
of discipline. The Comitia Centuriata could there- 
fore inflict capital punishment. Not so, however, 
the Comitia Curiata or Comitia Tributa. They were 
fettered on this point by the sacredness with which 
the person of a Roman citizen, inside the walls of the 
city, was invested by religion and law; and, with 
respect to the last of them, the Comitia Tributa, we 
know for certain that it became a fixed principle that 
the Assembly of the Tribes could at most impose a 
fine. So long as criminal jurisdiction was confined 
to the legislature, and so long as the assemblies of 
the Centuries and of the Tribes continued to exercise 
co-ordinate powers, it was easy to prefer indictments 
for graver crimes before the legislative body which 
dispensed the heavier penalties ; but then it happened 
that the more democratic assembly, that of the Tribes, 
almost entirely superseded the others, and became 
the ordinary legislature of the later Republic. Now 
the decline of the Republic was exactly the period 
during which the QusBstiones Pepetuae were esta- 
blished, so that the statutes creating them were all 
passed by a legislative assembly which itself could 
not, at its ordinary sittings, punish a criminal with 



CHAP. X. PUNISHMENT OF DEATH. 389 

death. It followed that the Permanent Judicial Com- 
missions, holding a delegated authority, were cir- 
cumscribed in their attributes and capacities by the 
limits of the powers residing with the body which 
deputed them. They could do nothing which the 
Assembly of the Tribes could not have done; and, 
as the Assembly could not sentence to death, the 
Quaestiones were equally incompetent to award 
capital punishment. The anomaly thus result- 
ing was not viewed in ancient times with anything 
like the favour which it has attracted among the 
modems, and indeed, while it is questionable whether 
the Roman character was at all the better for it, it is 
certain that the Roman Constitution was a great deal 
the worse. Like every other institution which has 
accompanied the human race down the current of its 
history, the punishment of death is a necessity of 
society in certain stages of the civilising process. 
There is a time when the attempt to dispense with it 
baulks both of the two great instincts which lie at 
the root of all penal law. Without it, the commu- 
nity neither feels that it is sufficiently revenged 
on the criminal, nor thinks that the example of 
his punishment is adequate to deter others from 
imitating him. The incompetence of the Roman 
Tribunals to pass sentence of death led distinctly and 
directly to those frightful Revolutionary intervals, 
known as the Proscriptions, during which all law was 

c c 3 



390 RESULTS TRACEABLE TO THE QUiESTIONES. ch. x. 

formally suspended simply because party violence 
could find no other avenue to the vengeance for 
which it was thirsting. Ne cau«e contributed so 
powerfully to the decay of political capacity in the 
Roman people as this periodical abeyance of the 
laws; and, when it had once been resorted to, we 
need not hesitate to assert that the ruin of Roman 
liberty became merely a question of time. If the 
practice of the Tribunals had aflTorded an adequate 
vent for popular passion, the forms of judicial pro- 
cedure would no doubt have been as flagrantly per- 
verted as with us in the reigns of the later Stuarts, 
but national character would not have sufiered as 
deeply as it did, nor would the stability of Roman 
institutions have been as seriously enfeebled. 

I will mention two more singularities of the 
Roman Criminal System which were produced by 
the same theory of judicial authority. They are, 
the extreme multiplicity of the Roman criminal tri- 
bunals, and the capricious and anomalous classifica- 
tion of crimes which characterised Roman penal 
jurisprudence throughout its entire history. Every 
Qucestio^ it has been said, whether Perpetual or other- 
wise, had its origin in a distinct statute. From 
the law which created it, it derived its authority; 
it rigorously observed the limits which its charter 
prescribed to it, and touched no form of criminality 
which that chartQr did not expressly define. As 



CH. X. RESULTS TRACEABLE TO THE QU^STIONES. 891 

then the statutes which constituted the various 
Quasstiones were all called forth by particular emer- 
gencies, each of them being in fact passed to punish 
a class of acts which the circumstances of the time 
rendered particularly odious or particularly dan- 
gerous, these enactments made not the slightest 
reference to each other, and were connected by no 
common principle. Twenty or thirty different cri- 
minal laws were in existence together, with exactly 
the same number of Quaestiones to administer them; 
nor was any attempt made during the Republic to 
fuse these distinct judicial bodies into one, or to give 
symmetry to the provisions of the statutes which 
appointed them and defined their duties. The state 
of the Roman criminal jurisdiction at this period, 
exhibited some resemblances to the administration of 
civil remedies in England at the time when the 
English Courts of Common Law had not as yet 
introduced those fictitious averments into their writs 
which enabled them to trespass on each other's 
peculiar province. Like the Quaestiones, the Courts 
of Queen's Bench, Common Pleas, and Exchequer, 
were all theoretical emanations from a higher autho- 
rity, and each entertained a special class of cases 
supposed to be committed to it by the fountain of its 
jurisdiction; but then the Roman Quaestiones were 
many more than three in number, and it was infinitely 
less easy to discriminate the acts which fell under 

c c 4 j/ 



I T.T 






392 TRIAL BY THE QUiESTIONES. chap. x. 

the cognisance of each Quajstio, than to distinguish 
between the provinces of the three Courts in West- 
minster Hall. The difficulty of drawing exact lines 
between the spheres of the different Quaestiones made 
the multiplicity of Roman tribunals something more 
than a mere inconvenience ; for we read with astonish- 
ment that when it was not immediately clear under 
what general description a man's alleged oflFences 
ranged themselves, he might be indicted at once or 
successively before several different Commissions, on 
the chance of some one of them declaring itself 
competent to convict him ; and, although conviction 
by one Quaestio ousted the jurisdiction of the rest, 
acquittal by one of them could not be pleaded to an 
accusation before another. This was directly con- 
trary to the rule of the Roman civil law ; and we 
may be sure that a people so sensitive as the Romans 
to anomalies (or, as their significant phrase was, to 
inelegancies) in jurisprudence, would not long have 
tolerated it, had not the melancholy history of the 
QuaBstiones caused them to be regarded much more 
as temporary weapons in the hands of factions than as 
permanent institutions for the correction of crime. 
The Emperors soon abolished this multiplicity and 
conflict of jurisdiction ; but it is remarkable that they 
did not remove another singularity of the criminal 
law which stands in close connection with the number 
of the Courts. The classifications of crimes which 



CHAP. X. CLASSIFICATIONS OP CRIMES. 398 

Are contained even in the Corpus Juris of Justinian 
are remarkably capricious. Each Quaestio had, in 
fact, confined itself to the crimes committed to its 
cognisance by its charter. These crimes, however 
were only classed together in the original statute 
because they happened to call simultaneously for 
castigation at the moment of passing it. They had 
not therefore anjrthing necessarily in common; but 
the fact of their constituting the particular subject- 
matter of trials before a particular Quaestio impressed 
itself naturally on the public attention, and so in- 
veterate did the association become between the 
offences mentioned in the same statute that, even 
when formal attempts were made by Sylla and by 
the Emperor Augustus to consolidate the Roman 
criminal law, the legislator preserved the old group- 
ing. The Statutes of Sylla and Augustus were the 
foundation of the penal jurisprudence of the Empire, 
and nothing can be more extraordinary than some of 
the classifications which they bequeathed to it. I 
need only give a single example in the fact that 
perjury was always classed with cutting and wounding 
and with poisoning^ no doubt because ft law of Sylla, 
the Lex Cornelia de Sicariis et Veneficis, had given 
jurisdiction over all these three forms of crime to the 
same Permanent Commission. It seems too that 
this capricious grouping of crimes affected the ver- 
nacular speech of the Romans. People naturally 



394 LATER LAW OF CRIMES. ch/lp. x. 

fell into the habit of designating all the offences enu- 
merated in one law by the first name on the list, 
which doubtless gave its style to the Law Court 
deputed to try them all. All the offences tried by 
the Quaestio De Adulteriis would thus be called 
Adultery. 

I have dwelt on the history and characteristics of 
the Roman Quaestiones because the formation of a 
criminal jurisprudence is nowhere else, so instruc- 
tively exemplified. The last QusBstiones were added 
by the Emperor Augustus, and from that time the 
Romans may be said to have had a tolerably com- 
plete criminal law. Concurrently with its growth, 
the analogous process had gone on, which I have 
called the conversion of Wrongs into Crimes, for, 
though the Roman legislature did not extinguish the 
civil remedy for the more heinous offences, it offered 
the sufferer a redress which he was sure to prefer* 
Still, even after Augustus had completed his legis- 
lation, several offences continued to be regarded as 
I Wrongs, which modem societies look upon exclu- 
; sively as Crimes; nor did they become criminally 
punishable till some late but uncertain date, at 
which the law began to take notice of a new de- 
scription of offences called in the Digest crimina 
extraordinaria. These were doubtless a class of acts 
which the theory of Roman jurisprudence treated 
merely as wrongs; but the growing sense of the 



CHAP. X. LATER LAW OF CRIMES. 895 

majesty of society revolted from their entailing no- 
thing worse on their perpetrator than the payment 
of money damages, and accordingly the injured 
person seems to have been permitted, if he pleased, 
to pursue them as crimes extra ordinem^ that is by a 
mode of redress departing in some respect or other 
from the ordinary procedure. From the period at 
which these crimina extraordinaria were first recog- 
nised, the list of crimes in the Roman State must 
have been as long as in any community of the 
modern world. 

It is unnecessary to describe with any minuteness 
the mode of administering criminal justice under the 
Roman Empire, but it is to be noted that both its 
theory and practice have had powerful effect on 
modem society. The Emperors did not immediately 
abolish the Quaestiones, and at first they committed 
an extensive criminal jurisdiction to the Senate, in 
which, however servile it might show itself in fact, 
the Emperor was no more nominally than a Senator 
like the rest. But some sort of collateral criminal 
jurisdiction had been claimed by the Prince from the 
first ; and this, as recollections of the free common- 
wealth decayed, tended steadily to gain at the ex- 
pense of the old tribunals. Gradually the punish- 
ment of crimes was transferred to magistrates 
directly nominated by the Emperor and the pri- 
vileges of the Senate passed to the Imperial Privy 



896 SOVEREIGN THE FOUNTAIN OF JUSTICE, chap. x. 

Council, which also became a Court of ultimate 
criminal appeal. Under these influences the doc- 
trine, familiar to the modems, insensibly shaped 
itself that the Sovereign is the fountain of all Justice 
and the depositary of all Grace. It was not so much 
the fruit of increasing adulation and servility as of 
the centralisation of the Empire which had by this 
time^erfected itself. The theory of criminal justice 
had, in fact, worked round almost to the point from 
which it started. It had begun in the belief that it 
was the business of the collective community to 
avenge its own wrongs by its own hand; and it 
ended in the doctrine that the chastisement of crimes 
belonged in an especial manner to the Sovereign as 
representative and mandatary of his people. The 
new view differed from the old one chiefly in the air 
of awfulness and majesty which the guardianship of 
justice appeared to throw around the person of the 
Sovereign. 

This later Roman view of the Sovereign's relation 
to justice certainly assisted in saving modem societies 
from the necessity of travelling through the series 
of changes which I have illustrated by the history of 
the Quaestiones. In the primitive law of almost all 
the races which have peopled Western Europe there 
are vestiges of the archaic notion that the punish- 
ment of crimes belongs to the general assembly of 
freemen; and there are some States — Scotland is 



CHAP. X. MODERN HISTORY OF CRIMES. 897 

said to be one of them — in which the parentage of 
the existing judicature can be traced up to a Com- 
mittee of the legislative body. But the development 
of the criminal law was universally hastened by two 
causes, the memory of the Roman Empire and the 
influence of the Church. On the one hand traditions 
of the majesty of the Caesars, perpetuated by the 
temporary ascendency of the House of Charlemagne, 
were surrounding Sovereigns with a prestige which a 
mere barbarous chieftain could never otherwise have 
acquired and were conmiunicating to the pettiest 
feudal potentate the character of guardian of so- 
ciety and representative of the State. On the other 
hand, the Church, in its anxiety to put a curb on 
sanguinary ferocity, sought about for authority to 
punish the graver misdeeds, and found it in those 
passages of Scripture which speak with approval of 
the powers of punishment committed to the civil ma- 
gistrate. The New Testament was appealed to as 
proving that secular rulers exist for the terror of 
evil-doers; the Old Testament, as laying down that 
" whoso sheddeth man's blood, by man shall his blood 
be shed." There can be no doubt, I imagine, that 
modem ideas on the subject of crime as based upon 
two assumptions contended for by the Church in the 
Dark Ages — first, that each feudal ruler, in his de- 
gree, might be assimilated to the Roman Magistrates 
spoken of by Saint Paul; and next, that the offences 



898 DOCTRINE OF THE CHURCH AS TO CRIMES, ce. x. 

which he was to chastise were those selected for 
prohibition in the Mosaic Commandments, or rather 
such of them as the Church did not reserve to her 
own cognisance. Heresy, supposed to be included 
in the First and Second Commandments, Adultery 
and Perjury were ecclesiastical offences, and the 
Church only admitted the co-operation of the secular 
arm for the purpose of inflicting severer punishment 
in cases of extraordinary aggravation. At the same 
time, she taught that murder and robbery with their 
various modifications were under the jurisdiction of 
civil rulers, not as an accident of their position but 
by the express ordinance of God. 

There is a passage in the writings of King Alfred 
(Kemble, ii. 209) which brings out into remarkable 
clearness the struggle of the various ideas that pre- 
vailed in his day as to the origin of criminal juris- 
diction. It will be seen that Alfred attributes it 
partly to the authority of the Church and partly 
to that of the Witan, while he expressly claims for 
treason against the lord the same immunity from 
ordinary rules which the Roman Law of Majestas 
had assigned to treason against the Caesar. " After 
this it happened," he writes, " that many nations 
received the faith of Christ, and there were many 
synods assembled throughout the earth, and among 
the English race also after they had received the faith 
of Christ, both of holy bishops and of their exalted 



CH. X. KING ALFRED ON CRIMINAL JURISDICTION. 399 

Witan. They then ordained that, out of that mercy 
which Christ had taught, secular lords, with their 
leave, might without sin take for every misdeed the 
hot in money which they ordained ; except in cases 
of treason against a lord, to which they dared not 
assign any mercy because Almighty God adjudged 
none to them that despised Him, nor did Christ 
adjudge any to them which sold Him to death ; and 
He commanded that a lord should be loved like 
Himself." 



INDEX 



INDEX. 



ADOPTION. 

Adoption, fiction of, 1 30. 

influence of the sacra gentUiein on 

the law of, 6, 7, 27. 

in Hindoo law, 193. 

Adprehensio; or assumption of sove- 
reign power in a newly discovered 
country, 249. 

JEquitas, the term, 58. See Equity. 

iEquus, the word, 59. 

Agnatic and Cognatic relationship, dif- 
ference between, 59, 146. 

Agnation described, 147, 148. 

Agreement, Roman analysis of, 322. 

Agri vectigales, Roman practice of 
letting out, 300. 

■— limitrophi of the Romans on the 

bankJs of the Rhine and Danube, 
502. 

Alexander the Sixth, Pope, his Bull, 
249. 

Alfred, King, his remarks on criminal 
jurisdiction quoted, 398. 

Alienation of property, ancient diffi- 
culties of, 271. 

— archaic ceremonies of, 272. 

Allodial property, of the ancient Ger- 
mans, 228, 281. 

America, United States of. Declaration 
of Independence of, 95. 

Anglo-Saxons, character of their King- 
ship, 108. 
■ their l&w of succession, 280. 

their penal law, 370, 374, 379. 

Archon of Athens, office of the, 1 0. 

Aristocracies, origin of the rule of, 10. 

i those of Greece, Italy, and Asia 

Minor, 10. 

■ difference between those of the 
Eastand West, 11. 

. aristocracies, the depositaries and 
administrators of the law, 11,12. 



BURGUITDIAKS. 

Aristocracies, importance of judicial, be- 
fore the invention of writing, 12. 

foundation of aristocracies, 132. 

Aristotle, his <* Treatise on Rhetoric" 
referred to, 75. 

Assignees in Bankruptcy, succession of, 
180. 

Athenian wills, 1 96. 

Athens, primitive penal law of, 382. 

Augustus, the Emperor, his alterations 
in the Roman law, 41, 42. 

Austin's ** Province of Jurisprudence 
determined,** referred to, 7. 

Bayle referred to, 87. 

Benefices of the invading chiefs of the 

Roman Empire, 229. 
— .- transformation of the Benefice into 

the hereditory Fief, 230. 
Bengalee Wills, 197. 
Bentham, his " Fragment on Govern* 

ment ** referred to, 7. 
causes of bis influence in England, 

78. 
— ^ the Roman counterpart of Ben- 

thanism, 79. 

his theory of Jurisprudence, 117. 

his eulogy of the Bull of Pope 

Alexander the Sixth, 249. 
Bentham and Austin's rules as to 

the essentials of a contract, 323. 
Blackstone, Sir William, his theory of 

the first principles of law, 1 1 4. 
his justification for the exclusion 

of the half-blood, 152. 
his theory of the origin of pro- 
perty quoted, 251. 

his theory criticised, 253. 

Bonorum Possessio of the Romans, 211. 
Braoton, hu plagiarisms, 82. 
Burgundians, the, referred to, 104. 



p s S 



404 



mDEX. 



Caesar, Julius, his contemplated addi- 
tions to the Roman Statute Law, 42. 
Capet, Hugh, character of his sove- 
reignty, 108. 
Capture in War, sources of the modern 
International Law of, 246. 

ancient Law of, 247. 

Caracalia, effect of his constitution in 

enlarging the Patria Potestas, 144. 
Casuists, the, 350. 

comparison of their system with that 

of Grotius and his school, 351. 

origin of Casuistry, 351. 

blow struck at Casuistry by Pas- 
cal, 352. 
Cessio in Jure of Property, in Roman 

and in English law, 289. 
Cestui que Trust, special proprietor- 
ship created for the, 294. 
Chancellor, the Lord, compared with a 

Roman Praetor, 64, 65. 
Chancery, Court of, in England, re- 
marks on the, 44. 
^— origin of its system, 44, 45. 
Charlemagne, his claim to universal do- 
minion, 104. 

his distribution of Benefices, 229. 

Children, disinherison of, under the 

Romans, 215. 
China, cause of the arrest of progress 

in, 25. 
Churches, Eastern and Western, con- 
clusions of the East on theological 
subjects accepted by the West with- 
out dispute or review, 356. 

— problems of the Western Church, 

357. 
Cicero referred to, 61. 

his allusions to the ancient Roman 

Sacroy 193. 
Code Napol6on, restraints imposed by 

it on the testamentary power, 176. 
Codes, Ancient, 1. 

sources of knowledge afforded by 

the Greek Homeric poems, 2. 
» Themistes, 4. 

Hindoo Laws of Menu, 6. 

difference between Case-law and 

Code law, 1 4. 
era of Codes, 14, 

the Twelve Tables, 1, 2, 14. 

—-the Codes of Solon and Draco, 

14. 
» importance of Codes to ancient so- 
cieties, 16—19. 



CONTRACT. 

Co-emption, or higher form of civil 
marriage of the ancient Romans, 154. 

Cognatic relationship described, 146, 
147. 

Co-heirs, rights and duties of, 181. 

rights of, under the Roman Law, 

2*^7. 

Coloni of the Romans, 231 . 

origin and situation of the, 300. 

Comitia Calata, ancient Roman execu* 
tion of Wills in the, 199. 

end of the, 203. 

Comitia Centuriata, power of the, 387. 

Curiata, powers of the, 318. 

Tributa, powers of the, 388. 

Commentaries of the Roman lawyers, 35. 
Common law of England, formerly an 

unwritten law, 1 3. 

difference between Case-law and 

Code law, 14. 
Case-law and its anomalies, 3 1 . 

■ similarity between English Case- 

law and the Respousa Pruden- 
tum of the Romans, 33. 
Confarreation, or religious marriage of 

the ancient Romans, 154. 
Constantiue, the Emperor, his improve- 
ments in the Law, 42. 

— his modification of the Patria Po- 

testas, 143. 
Contract, movement of societies from 
Status to, 170. 

early history of, 304. 

Contract and Political Economy, 

305. 

Rousseau*s doctrine of an original 

Social Contract, 308, 309. 
Montesquieu's apologue of the 

Troglodytes, 311. 

early notions of Contract, 312. 

Roman Contracts, 314. 

■ specialising process in ancient law, 

816. 

historical alliance between Con- 
tracts and Conveyances, 31 7. 

changes in the Nexum, 318. 

Executory Contracts of Sale, 

321. 

primitive association of Convey- 
ances and Contracts, 321. 

ancient and modem ^doctrine of 

Contracts, 323. 

•— the Roman Obligation, 323. 

— Roman classification of Contracts 

325. • 



raDEX. 



C»NTRACT. 



TiGTPT. 



Contract, the Verbal Contract; 327. 

tbe Literal or Written Contract, 

330. 

the Real Contract, 331. 

Consensual Contracts, 332. 

— changes in Contract law, 337. 
^— history of the progress of Con- 
tract law, 338. 

Quasi- Contracts, 343. 

Contract law and Fiefs, 365. 

ConTeyances, relation of Wills to, under 

the Roman Uw, 204. 

consequence of this relation, 206. 

remedies, 207. 

— — historical alliance between Con- 
tracts and Conveyances, 317. 
Co-ownership of property, amongst the 

Hindoos, 260, 26 U 
regarded by the Roman law as ex- 
ceptional and momentary, 261. 
Corporations aggregate, 1 87. 

sole, leading attribute of, 187. 

** Corpus Juris CiWlis*' of Justinian, 68. 

resorted to by English Chancery 

judges, 44. 

Creation, Greek philosophical explana- 
tion of the fabric of, 55, 

Creditors, cause of tbe extravagant 
powers given to, by ancient laws, 321. 

Crimes and Wrongs. See Delict and 
Crime. 

Croatia, co-ownership of the villagers 
of, 267. 

Curatores of male Orphans under the 
Roman law, 161. 

Curse, inherited, Greek notion of an, 127. 

Customary Law, 5. 

Homeric terms for customs, 5. 

origin of customary law, 9. 

epoch of customary law and its 

custody by a privileged order, 1 3. 

Cyclops, Homer's account of, quoted, 
124. 

Death, disappearance of, from the penal 
system of republican Rome, 387. 

— causes for this, 387, 388. 

death-punishment a necessity in 

certain stages of society, 389. 
Debtors, cause of the severity of ancient 

laws against, 321. 
Decretals, forged, motives of the author 

of the, 82. 
Delict and Crime, early history of, 367. 

Penal law in ancient codes, 367. 



Delict and Crime, Crimes ant 
erimina and delicta, 370. 

and Crime, Furtum or Theft" 

Roman law, 370, 379. 

Wrongs and Sins both known to 

primitive jurisprudence, 371. 

difference between the ancient and 

modern conception of Crime,S73. 

— ^ the Roman Legis Actio Sacra- 
ment i, 375. 

Homer's description of an ancient 

law-suit, 377, 

primitive penal law of Athens, 382. 

<— — old Roman criminal jurisprudence! 

382. 

the Quaestiones, 382, 383. 

Qusstores Parricidii, 583. 

Duumviri Perduellionis, 383. 

the first true Roman Criminal law, 

384. 
the primitive history of criminal 

law, 385. 
. extreme multiplicity of Roman 

criminal tribunals, 390. 
capricious classification of crimes, 

392, 393. 

- statutes of Sylla and Augustus, 

393. 

later law of crimes, 394. 

— ^ erimina extraordinaria, 394. 

-^— mode of administering criminal jus- 
tice under the Roman Empire, 
395. 

modern history of crimes, 397. 

King Alfred on criminal jurisdie- 

tion quoted, 398. 

Discovery, considered as a mode of ac- 
quiring dominion, 248. 

Dominion, its nature, limitation, and 
mode of securing it, 102. 

of the Romans, 317. 

Dower, the principle of, engrafted on 
the Customary Law uf Western Eu- 
rope, 224. 

Draco, rudeness of the Code of, 16. 

-^— penal laws of. 367, 

Dumoulin referred to, 86. 

Dumont's ** Sophismes Anarchiques** 
remarks, 92. 

Duumviri Perduellionis, the, 383. 

Edict of the Roman Prstor, 41,57, 

63, 64. 66, 209, 293. 
Egypt, Modern, rule of succession to 

the throne of, 24t2. 




D D 3 



406 



INDEX. 



ELDOK. 

Eldon, Lord, hii Chaocellonbip, 69. 
Elphinstone's *< Historj of India " 

quoted, 263. 
Emphyteusis, system of, 299, et teq, 

— rights of the Emphyteuta, 301. 
Emptor FamiiisB. See FamilUe Emptor. 
England, the Land-law of, at the pre- 
sent time, 226. 

English Common law, formerly an un- 
written law, 13. 

■ law, hesitation of our Courts in 
declaring principles of, 40. 
Equality of men, doctrine of the, 92. 
-^— as understood by the Roman juris- 
consults, 93. 
»^ its meaning in its modem dress, 
93. 

ordinance of Louis Hutin quoted, 

94. 
^ declaration of American Indepen- 

dence, 95. 
I assumpdon of the Grotian school, 

101. 
Equity, early history of, 25. 

equity considered as an agent by 

which the adaptation of law to 
social wants is carried on, 28. 

— meaning of the term equity, 28. 

■ difference between equity and legal 

fictions, 28. 
— — between equity and legis* 

lation, 28, 29. 
--— remarks on the law of nature and 

equity, 44, et§eq. 
— - the English Court of Chancery, 44. 

origin of ^ts system, 44, 45. 

the equity of Rome, 45. 

origin and history of the term 

•« Equity," 58. 
the terms 2£quitas and *I<r^j, 

58. 
picture presented to the Roman 

mind by the word <' Equity,'* 60. 

— the English Chancellor compared 

with the Roman Prastor, 65. 

— exhaustion of the power of growth 

in Roman Equity, 68. 
— ^ features common to English and 

Roman Equity, 68, et wq, 
^-^ distinction between Law and 

Equity in their conceptions of 

proprietary right, 293. 
Ethics, obligations o^ to the Roman 

law, 347. 
the Casuists*, 350. 



FRANCE. 

Ethics, Grotius and his school, 350l 
Famtlia, meaning oi^ in the language of 

the ancient Roman law, 208. 
FamiUn Emptor, office of the, 205. 
■ rights and duties of the, 206. 

remarks on the expression Familiar 

Emptor, 208. 
Family, the, of Archaic society, 133. 

disintegration of the Family, 169. 

regarded as a corporation, 1 84. 

organisations of elementary com- 
munities, 234. 
— ^ Highland chieftainship, 234. 

— Families, not Indiriduals, known 
- to ancient law, 258. 

' Indian, Russian, Croatian, and 
Sclavonisn laws respecting the 
property of Families, 260 — 
269. 
Feudal view of the ownership of pro- 
perty, 295. 
Feudal services, 303. 
Feudalism, its connection with territorial 
sovereignty, 107. 

feudUtl organisation, 107, 108. 

the modern Will an accidental 

fruit of, 224, 225. 

Feudalism and Contract law, 365. 

Fictions, legal, 21, 23. 

— early history of, 23. 

meaning of /ietio in old Roman 

law, 25. 
-— — object of the ficHones^ 26. 

instances cited from the English 

and Roman law, 26. 
their former importance and mo- 
dern uselessness, 27, 28. 
difference between legal fictions 
and equity, 28. 

and between legal fictions and 

legislation, 29. 
' instances of legal fictions, 31. 

Case-law and its anonwlies, 31. 

Fidei-Commissa, or Bequests in Trust, 

of the Roman Law, 223. 
Fiefs, hereditary, gradual transformation 
of Benefices into, 230. 

— original tenures, 230, 231. 
laws of fiefs, 365. 

Foreigners, causes of immigration of, 

into ancient Rome, 46, 47. 
exclusion of, under the early Ro- 
man republic, 48. 
France, lawyers and juridical science 

o^ 80, et teq. 



INDEX. 



407 



FRANCE. 

France, eflTecte of the alliance between 
tbe lawyers and the kings, on the 
fortunes of, 80^ 81. 

difference between the Pays du 

^ Droit Coutumier and the Pays 
du Droit ^crit, 84. 
— — pre-eminence giren in France to 
Natural Law, 85. 

Rousseau, 87. 

the Revolution, 89. 

Franks, the, referred to, 104. 

— Roman institution of the Patria 

Potestas not known to the, 1 43. 
Freewill and Necessity, question o^ 

unknown to the Greeks, 304. 
Furtum, or Theft, of the Roman Law, 

370. 

Gaius referred to, 52. 
■ his description of the institution 

of the Patria Potestas, 133. 

— his information respecting the Per- 

petual Tutelage of Women, 153. 

on the duplication of proprietary 

right, referred to, 295. 

Galatae, the Patria PotesUs of the, 136. 

Gens, or House, of the Romans com- 
pared with the Village Community 
of India, 264. 

Gentiles, Roman, their rights in cases 
of Intestate Succession, 221. 

German law of Succession, 280. 

Germans, Wills of the ancient, 196, 1 98. 

penal laws of the, 367. 

Patria Potestas of, 143. 

— primitive property of, 1 98. 

' the ancient law of allodial pro- 
perty, 228. 
" Germany" of Tacitus, its value, 120. 
— — suspicions as to its Odelity, 121. 

— allodial property of, 281. 
Greece, aristocracies of, 10. 

Greek theory of a Law of Nature, 52, 

53. 
Greeks, equality of laws on which they 
prided themselves, 58. 

their tendency to confoutid law 

and fact, 75. 

their notion of an inherited curse, 

127. 
-— - assistance afforded by, in tbe for- 
mation of the Roman codes, 15. 
— .- limited Patria Potestas of the^ 

136, 137. 
metaphysics of the, 300. 



HINDOOS. 

Greeks, their want of capacity for pro- 
ducing a philosophy of law, 354. 

Grote, Mr., his •« History of Greece,** 
referred to, 5, 9. 

Grotius, Hugo, and his successors on 
International law, 96. 

■ his doctrines, 100. 

success of his treatise « De Jure 

Belli et Pacis,** 111. 

— his theory of a Natural State and 

of a system of principles con- 
genial to it, 114. 

— his moral philosophy and that of 

his school, 350. 

comparison of his system with 

that of the Casuists, 351. 
Guardianship, Perpetual, of Women* 

under the Roman law, 153. 
— ^ amongst the Hindoos, 153. 
-' ■ amongst the Scandinavians, 153, 

Haereditas, or Inheritance, definitioni 

181. 
Hanres or Heir, his rights and duties, 

181, 190, 227. 
Half>blood relationship, 151.' 

the rule according to the customs 

of Normandy, 151. 
Haus-Gesetae of Germany, 232. 
Heirs, rights of, under the Roman Law, 

131,190,227. 
Highland chieftainship hereditary, 234. 

■ form of Primogeniture, 240. 
Hindoo laws of Menu, 6, 17, 18. 
Customary Law, 7. 

law of Successioif, 280. 

difference between Inheritances 

and Acquisition8,281. 
—' Perpetual Tutelage of Women 

amongst the, 1 53. 
right amongst the, to inherit a 

dead man's property, 191. 
•^— the Hindoo aacra, 192. 

the Suttee, 193. 

the place of Wills amongst the 

Hindoos occupied by Adoptions, 

193. 

— rights of the first-bom son amongst 

the, 228. 

primogeniture of the Hindoos in 

public office or political power, 
but not in property, 233. 
Hindoos, form of Ownership of Pro- 
perty amongst the,— the Village Com- 
munity, 260. 



D D 4 



408 



INDEX. 



JtlNDOOS. 

Hindoos, Co-ownership, 261. 

■ simplest form of the Village Coxn- 

muDity, 262, 265. 
Acquisitions of Property and In- 
heritances, Hindoo distinction 
between, 281 . 
Hobbes, his theory of the origin of law, 

114. 
Homer, his account of the Cyclops 

quoted, 124. 
his description of an ancient law- 
suit, 877. 
Homeric poems, rudimentary jural 
ideas afforded by the, 2, 3. 

■ Themis and Themistes, 4, 5. 

— Homeric words for Custom, 5. 

India, heroic and aristocratic eras of the 
races of, 10. 

— laws of Menu, 6, 17, 18. 
Customary law of, 7. 

-^— stage beyond which India has not 

passed, 23. 
Inheritance a form of universal succes- 
sion, 177. 

Roman definition of an Inherit- 

ance, 181. 

i— old Roman law of, 189. 

and Acquisition, Hindoo differ- 
ences between, 281. 

Injunction of the Court of Chancery, 293. 

Institutes of the Roman lawyers, 35. 

International law, modern confusion be- 
tween it and Jus Gentium, 53. 

function of the law of Nature in 

giving birth to modern Interna- 
tional Law, 96. 

postulates forming the foundation 

of International Law, 96. 

Grotius and his successors, 96. 

— Dominion, 102. 

territorial Sovereignty, 103. 

the ante-Grotian system of the 

Law of Nations, 109. 

< preparation of the public mindfor 

the reception of the Grotian 
system, 110. 

success of the treatise " De Jure 

Belli et Pacis," 111. 

■ points of junction between modern 
public law and territorial sove- 
reignty, 112. 

■■■ sources of the mode in case of Cap- 
ture in War, 46. 

Intestacy. See Succession, Intestate. 



JUS NATUBiXE. 

*I<r^f, the Greek principle of, 58, 61. 
Italy, aristocracies of, 10. 

codes of, 17. 

instability of society in ancient, 47. 

territorial sovereignty of the princes 

of, 108. 

Jews, Wills of the, 197. 

Julianus, Salvlus, the Praetor, his Edict, 

64. 
»— - effect of his measures on the Pnc^ 

torian Edicts, 66. 
Jurisconsults, early Roman, 37—39. 

later, 41. 

Natural Law of the, 76. 

Jurisprudence, golden age of Roman, 55. 
Jurists, Roman, period of, 66, 68. 
Jus Gentium, origin of, 47, ei §eq. 
• circumstances of the origin of, 50. 
' how regarded by a Roman, 51. 

■ and by a modern lawyer, 51. 

difference between the Jus Gen- 
tium and the Jus Naturale, 52, 
53. 

■ point of contact between the old 

Jus Gentium and the Jus Na- 
turale, 58. 
difference between the Jus Gen- 
tium and the Quiritarian law, 5 9. 

— — influence of the, on modern civili- 
sation, 103. 

Jus Feciale, or International Law of 
the Romans, 53. 

Jus Naturale, or Law of Nature, 52. 
■ difference between the Jus Na- 
turale and the Jus Gentium, 
53. 

Greek conceptions of Nature and 

her law, 53. 

■ point of contact between the old 

Jus Gentium and the Law of 
Nature, 58. 

modern history of the Law of 

Nature, 73. 

Natural law of the Roman Juris- 
consults, 76. 

ancient counterpart of Bentham- 
ism, 79. 

vastness of the influence of the 

Law of Nature on modem so- 
ciety, 80. 

— history of the Law of Nature, 80, 
tt Beg. 

pre-eminence given to Natural 

law in France^ 85. 



INDEX. 



40S> 



JUS NATURALE. 

Jus N«turale, its condition at the mid- 
dle of the 18th century, 86. 

Rousseau, 87. 

the French Revolution, 89. 

equality of men, 92. 

function of the law of Nature in 

giving birth to modern Interna- 
tional Law, 96. 

sources of the Modern Interna- 

national Law of Capture in 

War, 246. 
Justinian's *< Institutes*' quoted, 46. 
--— referred to, 57. 

" Pandecte " of, 67. 

" Corpus Juris Civilis " of, 68. 

his modifications of the Patria 

Potestas, 14S. 
his scale of Intestate Succession, 

219. 

Kings, origin of the doctrine of the 

divine right of, 346. 
Kingship, heroic, origin of, 9. 

Lacedaemonian kings, authority of the, 

10. 
Land-law of England at the present day, 

226. 
Land and goods, English disiinction 

between, 283. 
Latifundia, Roman, mode of cultivating 

the, 299. 
Law, social necessities and opinions 
always in advance of, 24. 

agencies by which law is brought 

into harmony with society, 25. 

ancient, 113. 

theories of a natural state and of a 

system congenial to it, 113. 

Grotius, Blackstone, Locke, and 

Hobbes,114. 

theory of Montesquieu, 115. 

Bentham, 117. 

dissatisfaction with existing theo- 
ries, 118. 
^— proper mode of inquiry, 119. 

the Patriarchal theory, 1 22. 

fiction of Adoption, ISO. 

the archaic Family, 133. 

the Pairia Potestas of the Ro- 
mans, 133. 
■ agnatic and cognatic relationships, 
146. 

Guardianship of Women, 153. 



MORTGAGOn. 

Law, ancient Roman Marriage, 1 54. 

Master and Slave, 162. 

Leges Barbarorum, 297. 
Leges Corneliae of Sylla, 41, 42. 
Leges Juliae of Augustus, 41, 42. 
Legis Actio Sacrament! of the Romans 

described, 375. 
Legislation, era o^ 25. 

considered as an agent by which 

the adaptation of law to the 
social wints is carried on, 29. 

difference between it and legal 

fictions, 28, 29. 
Lex Calpumia de Repetundis, the first 

true Roman Criminal Law, 384. 
Lex PUetoria, purport of the, 161. 
Lidi of the Germans, 231. 
Local Contiguity as the condition of com« 

munity in political functions, 1 32. 
Locke, John, referred to, 87. 

his theory of the origin of law, 

114. 
Lombards, referred to, 114. 
Louis Hutin, King of France, his ordi- 
nance quoted, 94. 

Mahometan Law of Succession, 242. 
Majority and Minority, meaning of the 

terms in Roman Law, 162. 
Mancipation, Roman, 50, 204, 278, 

317. 
mode of giving the effect of Man- 
cipation to a Tradition, 279. 
Manus of the Romans, 317. 
Marriagre, ancient Roman, 1 54. 

later Roman, 155. 

Master and Slave, 1 62. 

" under the Romans, 163. 

in the United States, 163. 

Menu, Hindoo laws of, 6, 17, 18. 
Merovingian kings of the Franks, 104. 
Metayers, the, of the south of Europe, 

301. 

*< Moniteur," the, during the period of 
the French Revolution, 92. 

Montesquieu's " Esprit des Lois," re- 
marks on, 86. 

- his Theory of Jurisprudence, 115. 

Apologue of Montesquieu con- 

cerning the Troglodytes, in the 
** Lettres Persanes." 311. 
Moral doctrines, early, 127. 
Mortgagor, special proprietorsliip cre- 
ated by the Court of Chancery for the. 
294. 



410 



INDEX. 



MOSES. 

Moses, testamentary power not provided 
for by the Laws o( 197. 

Naples, territorial sovereignty of the 
monarchs ot, 108. 

Nations, Law of, 96, et uq. See Inter- 
national law and Jus Gentium. 

Nature and ber law, Greek conceptions 
of, 53. 

Ntxvm, of the ancient Romans, 48, 315. 

changes in the, 518. 

Normandy, customs of, referred to, 151. 
N^/nos, the word not known to the Ho- 
meric poems, 5. 

Nuncupatio, of the Romans, 205. 

Obligations of the Roman law, 323. 

rights and duties of, 324. 

Occupatio, or Occupancy, of the Roman 

Law, a ** natural mode of acquiring 

property," 245, 25a 
— ^ things which never had an owner, 

245. 
things which have not an owner,24 5. 

- Capture in war, 246. 
— ^ Discovery, 248. 

»-~ objections to the popular theory 

of Occupancy, 256. 
Ordinance of Louis Hutin quoted, 94. 
Orphans, Guardianship of male, under 
the Roman law, 160. 

Pactes de FamtUe of France, 232. 
Pascal, his ** Lettres Provinciales,** 352. 
Paterfamilias in elementary communi- 
ties, 234, 235. 
Patria Potestas, the, of the Romans, 133. 

of the Galatae, 136. 

of the Greeks, 136, 137. 

causes which helped to mitigate 

the stringency of the father's 
power over the persons of his 
children, 141. 

liabilities of the Paterfamilias, 145. 

unity of person between the Paterfa- 

milias and the Filius&milias, 1 45. 

rights and duties of the Paterfami- 

lias, 145, 146,234,235. 

- the Patria Potestas not a durable 

institution, 146. 
Patriarchal theory of primeval jurispru- 
dence, 122. 

- chief points from Scriptural ac- 

counts, 123. 
Homer's account of the Cyclops, 124. 






PRIH0GE3IITUftB. 

Pays du Droit fecrit and Paysdu Droit 
Coutuuiier, difference between the 
84. 

Peculium, the, of the Romans, 142. 

Castrense Peculium, 142. 

Quasi-castrense Peculium, 142. 

Penal law in ancient codes, 867. 

Perjury, how punished by the ancient 
Romans, 893. 

Persian monarchy, heroic and aristocra- 
tic eras of the races composing the, 
11. 

Persiant, the ancient, their veracity, 
308. 

^iMTif of the Greeks, meaning of the;, 
53. 

Plebeian Wills of the Roman;, 201. 

legalised by at the Twelve Tables, 

202. 

their influence on the civEisation 

of the modern world, 203. 

Political ideas, early, 128. 

— foundation of aristocracies, 1 32. 
Political Economy and Contract, 305. 
Polygamy, its influence on Primogeni- 
ture, 243. 

Possessory interdicts of the Roman law, 
291. 

Prastor, origin of the oflice of, 62. 

Edict of the, 41, 57, 63, 66. 

the Roman, compared with au En- 
glish Chancellor, 64, 65. 

^— restraints on the Praetor, 65. 

the Praetor the chief equity judge 

as well as the great common law 
magistrate, 67. 

Prffitor Peregrinus, oflSce of the, 63. 

Praetorian Edict of the Romans, 41, 57, 
65, 66. 

the Edictum Perpetuum, 63. 

that of Sttlvius Julianus, 64, 66. 

— remedies given by the, 293. 
Praetorian Will, the, 209. 

described, 210. 

Prescription of Property, history of, 
284, ttKq. 

Primogeniture, changes in Law of Suc- 
cession, caused by, 225. 

almost destroyed by the authors of 

the French code, 225, 226. 

results of the French system, 226. 

rights of the first-born son amongst 

the Hindoos, 228. 

early history of Primogeniture, 229. 

Benefices, 2i?9. 



INDEX. 



411 



PRIMOGENITUBE. 

Primogeniture, gradual transformation 
of Benefices into hereditary Fiefs, 
SSO. 

— the Paotes de Famille of France 

and the Uaus-Gesetze of Ger- 
many, 232. 

■ causes of the diffusion of Primo- 

geniture, 232. 

— Primogeniture in public offices or 

political pover amongst the 
Hindoos, but not in prpperty, 
233. 

■ ancient forms of Primogeniture, 

235. 

— vhy did Primogeniture gradually 

supersede every other principle 
of Succession ? 235. 

earlier and later Primogeniture, 

257. 

Hindoo rule of the eldest son and 

of the eldest line also, 239. 

Celtic form of Primogeniture, 240. 

Mahometan form, 242. 

influence of polygamy on Primo- 
geniture, 243. 

Progress, causes of the arrest of, of the 
greater part of mankind, 77. 

Property, early history of, 244. 

^-^*' natural modes" of acquisition, 
244. 

— — Occupancy, 245. 

Capture in War, 246. 

' rule of Discovery, 248. 

— ^ history of the origin of property, 
250. 

Blackstone on the theory of Occu- 
pancy as the origin of property, 
251. 

■■ aphorism of Savigny on the origin 
of property, 254. 

objections to the popular theory of 

Occupancy, 256. 

Co-ownership amongst tbeHindoos, 

260. 

the Gens, or House, of the Ro^ 

mans compared with the Village 
Community of India, 264. 

Russian village co-ownership, 266. 

Croatian and Sclavonian Laws re- 
specting the property of Fami- 
lies, 269. 

I ancient difficulties of Alienation, 
271. 

— ^- natural classification of property, 
273. 



QU2ESTI0NES PERPETUiE. 

Property, ancient modes of transfer of 
property, 276. 

— definition of the Res Maneipi, 

277. 
— »- tradition of property, 578. 
distinction between Res Maneipi 

and Res nee Maneipi, 279. 
*'— Hindoo law of Inheritances and 

Acquisitions, 281, 282. 

— law of moveables and law of land, 

according to the French Codes, 
283. 

and in England, 283. 

Usucapion, or Prescription, 284. 

■ C^ssio in Jure, or recovery, in a 

Court of Law, of property 
sought to be conveyed, 289. 

— » influence of Courts of T^aw and of 
their procedure opon Property, 
290. 

distinction between Property and 

Possession, 290. 

and between Law and Equity in 

their conceptions of proprietary 
right, under the Roman and 
English Law, 293. 

feudal view of Ownership, 295. 

" Roman and barbarian law of Own- 
ership, 296. 

Romiu) system of Tenancy, 299. 

the Coloni of the Romans and the 

Metayers of the South of Eu- 
rope, 300, 301. 

rights of the Emphyteuta, 301. 

the Agri Limitrophi of the Rhine 

and the Danube, 302. 

Proscriptions, Roman, origin of the, 
389. 

Pupilage or Wardship in modem juris- 
prudence, 162. 

-^-» compared with the Guardianship 
of Orphans under the Roman 
Law, 162. 

Quasi- Contract, 343. 

meaning of, in Roman law, 344. 

Quasi, meaning of the word, in Roman 
law, 344w 

QusBstores Parricidii of the ancient Ro- 
mans, 383. 

Qusestiones Perpetuse of the Romans, 
384. 

theory of the Qusstiones, 386. 

results traceable to the Quapstiones, 

391. 



412 



DTOEX. 



QUERELA INOFFICIOSI. 

Querela Inoffictoai Testamenti of the 

old Roman law, 215. 
Quiritarian Liaw, the, 48. 
. principles of the, 59. 

difference between it and the Jus 

Gentium, 59. 

Recoveries, collusive, of property in the 
Roman and English Law, 289. 

Regency, form of, according to the 
French custom regulating the suc- 
cession to the throne, 240. 

Reipus, the, of Germany, 281. 

Res Manclpi and Res nee Mancipi, 274, 
279. 

definition of the Res Mancipi, 

277. 

Res nulHus of the Roman Law, 246. 

Responsa Prudentium of the Romans, 
described, 33. 

— ^ similarity between them and Eng- 
lish Case-law, 33. 

■ decline and extinction of the Re- 

sponses, 40, 41. 
Revolution, French, effects of the theory 

of the state of Nalure on the, 91. 
Rex Sacrorum, or Rex Sacrificulus, office 

of the, 10, 62. 
Roman law, 1. 

the Twelve Tables, 1, 2, 14, 33. 

— — influence of the taera on the law 
of Adoption and of Wills, 6« 7. 

■ class of codes to which the Roman 

code belongs, 15. 

■ probable assistance afforded by 

Greeks, 15. 
. meaning of Jtciio^ 25. 

— instances of Ji(Aione$ cited, 26. 

■ the Responsa Prudentium de- 

scribed, 33. 
' judicial functions of the liTagis* 
trates of Republican Rome, 36. 

reasons why the Roman law was 

not popularised, 36. 

sources of the characteristic excel- 
lence of the Roman law, 38. 

■ decline and extinction of the Re- 

sponses, 40, 41. 
the Praetorian Edict, 4 1 , 57, 63, 66, 

— the Leges Cornelias, 41, 42. 
— ^ later jurisconsults, 4 1 . 

remarks on the Statute Law of the 

Romans, 41—43. 
•— ^ and on the Equity of the Romans, 

44, 45. 



ItOHAN LAW. 

Roman law, golden age of Roman 
jurisprudence, 55. 

Roman Equity, 58, 67. 

features common to both English 

and Roman Equity, 68, ef neq. 

International law largely indebted 

to Roman law, 97. 

the Patria Potestas of the Roman 

law, 137, et teq* 

Agnatic and Cognatic Relation- 
ship, 146. 

Perpetual TutelageofWomen,l 53. 

Roman Marriage, 154, 155. 

Guardianship of male Orphans, 1 60. 

Law ofPersoos,— Master and Slavey 

162. 

— Testamentary Law, 172, ef seq. 

— Wills anciently executed in the Co- 

mitia Calata, 199, 201. 

— — ancient Roman law of Intestate 
Succession, 199. 
■ Roman Wills described, 201. 

the Mancipation, 204. 

the Nuncupatio, 205. 

the Prstorian Will, 209. 

first appearance of Sealing in the 

history of jurisprudence as a 
mode of authentication, 210. 

Querela Inofficioei Testamenti ,2 1 5. 

Disinherison of Children under, 

215. 

Intestate Succession under, 218. 

Fidei-Commissa, or bequests in 

trust, 223. 

rights of Co-heirs, '227. 

■ Occupancy, 245. 

Roman distinction between the 

Law of Persons and the Law of 
Things, 258. 

influence of Roman classifications, 

259. 

Co-ownership of property regarded 

by the mature Roman law as 
exceptional and momentary, 
261. 

^-^ the Gens of the Romans compared 
with an Indian Village Commu- 
nity, 264. 

— Res Mancipi, and Res nee Man- 
cipi, 274, 277. 

Mancipation, 278. 

Usucapion, or Prescription, 284. 

the Cessio in Jure, 289. 

' distinction between Property and 
Possession^ 290. 



INDEX. 



413 



EOK AN LAW. 

Roman law, Roman and barbarian law, 
296. 

• Roman Contracts, 314, «^ »eq, 

the Four Contracts, 325. 

^— — connection between Tlieology and 
Roman law, 355. 

causes of improvement in Roman 

law, 361. 

Roman law in the Eastern Em- 
pire, 363. 

— ^ Civil Wrongs of the Roman law, ' 
370. 

the Legis Actio Sacramenti, 375. 

old Roman Criminal Jurispru- 
dence, 382. 

extreme multiplicity of Roman 

criminal tribunals, 390. 

•^— results traceable to the Quaes- 
tiones, 391. 

Romans causes of the rapid progress of 
the Stoical philosophy amongst the, 55. 

their progress in legal improve- 
ment, 57. 

Rome, immigration of foreigners into, 
46, 47. 

exclusion of, under the early Re- 
public, 46. 

' See of, origin of the tendency to 

attribute secular superiority to 
the, 108. 

^— decline of ecclesiastical influence 
in international questions, 110. 

early political ideas of, 130. 

Rousseau, J. J., influence of his writ- 
ings, 87. 

his doctrine of an original Social 

Compact, 308, 309. 

Russian villages. Co-ownership of the 
occupiers of, 266. 

Sacra, or Family Rites, of the Romans, 
6,7,27, 191, 192. 

of the Hindoos, 192. 

Sacramental Action of the ancient Ro- 
mans, 48. 

Salic law, origin of the, 157. 

Savigny, on Possession and Property, 
290, 291. 

his aphorism on the origin of 

property, 254. 

Scaevola, Q. Mucins, his Manual of the 
Civil Law, 40, 41. 

Scandinavian nations, their laws respect- 
ing the Perpetual Tutelage of Wo- 
men, 153, 159. 



SOVEREIGN. 

Sclavonian laws respecting the property 
of families, 268. 

Sealing, first appearance of, in jurispru- 
dence, as a mode of authentication, 
210. 

Sin, mortal and venial, casuistical dis- 
tinction between, 351. 

Sins known to primitive jurisprudence, 
371. 

Slavery, ancient, 162. 

- under the Romans, 163. 

in the United States of America, 

163. 
Socage, English law of, 232. 
Social Compact, Rousseau's doctrine of 
an original, 308, 309, 345. 

Dr. Whewell quoted, 347. 

Societies, stationary and progressive , 22. 
■ difference between stationary and 

progressive societies, 23. 
■ agencies by which Law is brought 

into harmony with Progressive 

Societies, 25. 

perils of early, 75. 

primitive, 1 20. 

early moral doctrines, 127. 

early political ideas, 128. 

fiction of Adoption, 130. 

foundation of Aristocracies, 132. 

principle of Local ConUguity, 1 32, 

the ancient Family, 153. 

the Patria Potestas, 133. 

agnatic and cognatic relationsliips, 

146. 

Guardianship of Women, 1 53. 

ancient Roman Marriage, 154. 

Master and Slave, 162. 

- uniformity of movement of the 

progressive societies, 168. 

disintegration of the Family, 169. 

■ movement of societies from status 
to contract, 1 70. 

Universal Succession, 1 77, 1 79, 181. 

primitive society and universal 

succession, 183. 

-— - the ancient family a corporation,! 84. 

Society in primitive times not a collec- 
tion of individuals, but an aggregation 
of families, 126. 

Solon, Attic code of, 16. 

** Sophismes Anarchiques " of Dumont, 
remarks on, 92. 

Sovereign, origin of the doctrine that 
the monarch is the fountain of justice, 
396. 



414 



INDEX. 



SOVEREIGNTY. 

Sovereignty, territorial, propodtion of 

International Law on, 109, 103. 
^— Tribe-soyereignty, 104. 
— ^- Charlemagne and uniyeiaal domi- 
nion, 106. 

— Territorial sovereignty an oflEbhooC 

of feudalism, 107. 

the See of Rome, 108. 

Hugh Capet, 108. 

— the Anglo-Saxon princes, 108. 

• Naples, Spain, and Italy, 108. 

Venice, 109. 

— points of junction between terri- 

torial sovereignty and modern 
publiclaw, 112. 

Spain, territorial sovereignty of the mo- 
narchs of, 106. 

Status, movement of sooieties from, to 
contract, 170. 

Statute law of the Romans, 41, 45. 

Stoic philosophy, principles of the, 54. 

— ^ its rapid progress in Roman so- 
ciety, 55. 

alliance of the Roman lawyers with 

the Stoics, 55. 

Succession, rules of, according to the 
Hindoo customary law, 7. 

— ~~ Testamentary, 171. 

— early history, 171. 

*— influence of the Church in enforc- 
ing the sanctity of Wills, 173. 

English law of, 173. 

— — «- qualities necessarily attached to 
Wills, 174. 

natural right of testation, 175. 

restraints imposed by the Code 

Napoleon, 176. 

nature of a Will, 177. 

rights and duties of universal suc- 
cessor, 177. 

— usual Roman definition of an In- 

heritance, 181. 

difference between modern testa- 
mentary jurisprudence and the 
ancient law of Rome, 182. 

■ the Family regarded as a Corpora- 
tion, 184. 

old Roman law of Inheritance 

and its notion of a Will, 189. 

ancient objects of Wills, 190. 

Saenif or Family Rites, of the 

Romans, 191. 

and of the Hindoos, 191» 192. 

the invention of Wills due to Ro* 

mans, 194. 



SUCCESSION. 

SueeeMion, Roman ideas of SuccessioD» 

195. 
Testamentary Succession less an* 

cientthan Intestate Succession, 

195. 
primitive operation of Wills, 196. 

— Wills of the ancient Germans, 196. 

Jewish and Bengalee Wills, 197. 

mode of execution of ancient Ro- 

num wills, 199. 
"—> description of ancient Roman Wills^ 

201. 
~— influence of ancient Plebeian Wills 

on the civilisation of the modem 

world, 203. 
the Mancipation, 204. 

— relation of Wills to conveyances. 

204. 
the TesUment per met Hbram, 204, 

213, 214. 
consequence of this relation of Tes- 
taments to conveyances, 206. 

remedies, 207. 

ancient Wills not written, 207. 

remarks on the expression Emptor 

Familis, 208. 

the Prajtorian Will, 209. 

->^ the Bonorum Possessio and the 

Bonorum Possessor, 211. 
improvements in the old Will, 212, 

213. 
— — ancient and modem ideas respect- 
ing Wills and successors, 2 1 5. 

Disinherison of Children, 215. 

the age of Wills coeval with that 

of feudalism, 224. 
introduction of the prinaple of 

Dower, 224. 
rights of Heirs and Co-heirs under 

the Roman law, 227. 

Intestate, 195. 

ancient Roman law of, 199, 

218. 
the Justinianean scale of Intestate 

Succession, 219. 
order of Intestate Succession among 

the Romans, 220. 
horror of intestacy f^t by the 

Romans, 222, 223. 
rights of all the children of the 

deceased under the Roman law, 

227. 

Universal, 177, 189. 

-*-» in what it consists, 179. 
-«- the universal successor, 181 « 



INDEX. 



415 



SUCCESSION. 

Succession, formula of old Roman in- 
vestiture referred to» 190. 

Suttee of the Hindoos, 193* 

Sylla, L. Cornelius, his improvements in 
the Roman law, 41, 42. 

Tables, the Twelve Decemviral, 1, 2» 
14, 33. 

collections of opinions interpreta- 
tive of the, 83. 

their legalisation of Plebeian Wills, 

202. 

Law of the Twelve Tables re- 
specting Testamentary Disposi- 
tions, 216. 

Tablets, laws engraven on, 1 4. 

Tacitus, value of his " Germany ** as a 
record of primitive history, 120. 

suspicions as to its fidelity, 121. 

Tarquins, change in the administration 
of the law after the expulsion of the, 
61, 62. 

Tenancy, Roman system of, 299. 

Testaments. See Succession, Testamen- 
tary. 

Theft, ancient Roman law of, 307, 37 8> 
379. 

-^-» modern breaches of trust, 307. 

Themis and Themistes of the Greek 
Homeric poems, 4, 5, 125. 

Theology, connection between it and 
Roman law, 355. 

Tliiity Years* War, influence of the hor- 
rors of the, on the success of the 
treatise •< De Jure Belli et Pads'* of 
Grotius, 111. 

Torts, law of, 370. 

Tradition of property amongst the Ro- 
mans, 278. 

^— — practical effect of a Mancipation 
given to a Tradition, 278. 

Transfer of property, ancient modes of, 
276. 

Troglodytes, the, 311. 

Turkey, rule of succession to the throne 
of, 242. 

Ulpian, his attempt to distinguish be- 
tween the Jus Naturale and the Jus 
Gentium, 52. 



ZEUS. 

(Jniversitas juris, in what it consists, 

178. 
Usucapion, principle of Roman law 

known as, 212. 

history of, 284. 

Usus, or lower form of civil marriage of 
the ancient Ronoans, 154. 

Vandals, the, referred to, 104. 

Venetians, their lapse from tribe sove- 
reignty to territorial sovereignty, 109. 

Village Communities of India, 260, 262, 
et Meg, 

Visigoths, the, referred to, 104. 

Voltaire, referred to, 87. . 

Warfare, ancient forms of, 247. 

Wehrgeld, the, of Germany, 281. 

Whewell, Dr., on original Social Com- 
pact, quoted, 347. 

his view of Moral Philosophy, 348. 

Widow's share of her husband's estate, 
224. 

the reipus, or fine leviable on the 

remarriage of a widow in Ger- 
many, 281. 

Wills, influence of ihe Sacra GeMtilieia on 
the law of, 6, 7. 

See Succession, Testamentary. 

Women, laws respecting the status of 
152. 

Roman law of the Perpetual Tu- 
telage of, 1 53. 

-*-» amongst the Hindoos, 158. 

^^ and amongst the Scandinavians, 
155. 

— Guardianship of Women under 

the Roman law, 153. 
tutelage o^ amongst the Hindoos, 

153. 
tutelage of, amongst the Scandina-' 

vians, 153. 

ancient Roman Marriage, 154. 

later Roman marriage, 155. 

-^-» special Proprietorship created by 

the Court of Chancery for, 295. 

Zeus, not a lawmaker, but a judge, 
•4, 5. 



THE END. 






LONDOir 

PRINTED BT 8P0TTI8W00DB AND CO. 

NBW-STRBBT SQUARE 





DATE DUE 




■vfe^^rN 


m^ 








m^ 






















































I 








^ 








B 








^ 








^ft 








^H 




1 




1 
































^ 










i ~\ 







iiiPEi»»i 



"-•-:^i^''v^pfei^r!':^:-^^£^^