Skip to main content

Full text of "Aristophanes and the political parties at Athens; translated by James Loeb"

See other formats


Digitized  by  tine  Internet  Arciiive 

in  2008  witii  funding  from 

IVIicrosoft  Corporation 


littp://www.arcliive.org/details/aristoplianespoliOOcroiuoft 


ARISTOPHANES   AND   THE   POLITICAL 
PARTIES   AT   ATHENS 


MACMILLAN  AND  CO.,    Limited 

LONDON    BOMBAY  •  CALCUTTA 
MELBOURNE 

THE    MACMILLAN   COMPANY 

NEW    YORK    •    BOSTON    •    CHICAGO 
ATLANTA    •    SAN    FRANCISCO 

THE  MACMILLAN   CO.    OF  CANADA.  Ltd. 

TORONTO 


ARISTOPHANES 

AND 

THE    POLITICAL    PARTIES 
AT    ATHENS 


BY 

MAURICE    CROISET 


TRANSLATED    BY 

JAMES   LOEB,   A.B. 


MACMILLAN    AND    CO.,    LIMITED 

ST    MARTIN'S    STREET,    LONDON 

1909 


)^P7     197Z     // 

— — '...x'"' 


GLASGOW  :    PRINTED   AT   THE    UNIVERSITY    PRESS 
BY   ROBERT   MACLEBOSE   AND   CO.    LTD. 


THE    TEANSLATOR'S    PREFACE 

My  English  version  of  the  late  Monsieur  Paul  Decharme's 
Eurijpide  et  I'esprit  de  sou  Theatre  met  with  so  friendly  a 
reception  at  the  hands  of  both  public  and  press,  that  I  felt 
encouraged  to  translate  the  present  excellent  work  by  Mon- 
sieur Maurice  Croiset,  who  very  courteously  gave  me  per- 
mission to  do  so. 

In  this  volume  the  attentive  reader  will  find,  not  only  a 
very  scholarly  treatment  of  the  difficult  question,  so  often 
discussed,  of  Aristophanes'  attitude  toward  the  political  parties 
of  his  time  and  of  the  political  purpose  of  his  comedies,  but 
also  a  very  vivid  account  of  many  of  the  phases  of  Athenian 
life  which  he  has  satirized  or  held  up  to  ridicule. 

I  cherish  the  hope  that  this  book  will  lead  some  of  its 
readers  to  refresh  their  school-day  memories  of  Attica's  brilliant 
comic  poet,  and  others  to  make  the  acquaintance,  at  first  hand, 
or  through  translation,  of  one  of  the  most  original  and  enter- 
taining geniuses  that  ancient  culture  can  boast  of. 

In  rendering  the  quotations  from  the  plays  into  English  I 
have  made  frequent  use  of  Mr.  Benjamin  Bickley  Rogers' 
masterly  metrical  translation  and  of  the  refreshing  notes  to 
Dr.  W.  W.  Merry's  edition  of  the  plays. 

To  my  friend  and  teacher,  Professor  John  Williams  White, 
of  Harvard  University,  I  am  greatly  indebted  for  generously 
contributing  an  introduction  to  this  volume.  He  has  placed 
me  under  an  additional  obligation  by  making  a  critical  revision 
of  my  translation,  and  I  owe  him  thanks  for  constant  encour- 
agement in  the  performance  of  a  pleasant  task. 

JAMES  LOEB,  A.B. 

Ml'xiCH,  August,  1909. 


PREFACE   BY   THE   AUTHOR 

The  political  history  of  Athenian  comedy  in  the  fifth  century 
has  yet  to  be  written.  Not  that  the  connection  of  this  form 
of  literature  with  contemporary  events  has  not  been  fully 
recognized.  All  writers  of  the  history  of  ancient  Greece,  with- 
out exception,  have  profited  by  the  very  varied  and  interesting 
information  which  is  scattered  through  Aristophanes'  extant 
plays  and  in  the  fragments  of  contemporary  writers  of  comedy. 
Some  of  them,  indeed,  have  done  so  with  an  erudition  and 
an  acamen  which  leave  nothing  to  be  desired.  From  this 
point  of  view,  Athenian  comedy  appears  to  have  supplied 
all  the  material  that  one  could  expect  of  it,  at  least  for  the 
present.  It  should  be  remarked,  however,  that,  in  the  works 
to  which  I  have  alluded,  it  has  quite  naturally  been  treated  as 
a  simple  collection  of  documents.  This  amounts  to  saying 
that,  in  these  works,  Athenian  comedy  is  not  studied  by  itself 
and  for  its  own  sake — in  its  tricks  and  turns,  in  its  relations 
to  the  life  of  the  people,  in  the  personality  and  special  gifts 
of  its  writers. 

The  history  of  literature,  it  is  true,  busies  itself  with  just 
some  of  those  phases  of  the  investigation  which  are  more  or 
less  neglected  by  political  history.  It  seems  to  portray  the 
psychology  of  the  writers  and  of  their  audience ;  it  shows  the 
development  of  the  various  styles  and  analyses  their  diverse 
forms ;  it  notes  and  discriminates  traditions  that  l)ecame 
fixed  as  laws,  and  describes  the  special  characteristics  of  each 
mind.  These  methods,  when  applied  to  the  political  part  of 
Athenian   comedy,  may  lead   to   its   better  appreciation.     In 


viii  PREFACE   BY  THE   AUTHOR 

fact,  they  have,  in  no  mean  degree,  contributed  toward  making 
our  knowledge  of  it  increasingly  sound  and  exact.  But,  after 
all,  politics  is  only  a  secondary  consideration  in  the  study  of 
literature,  and  has  only  incidental  relation  to  it. 

A  proper  political  history  of  Athenian  comedy  should  there- 
fore be  based  both  upon  general  history  and  upon  literary 
history,  and  yet  be  different  from  either.  Its  special  object 
should  be  to  study  to  what  extent  comedy  as  a  whole,  and 
each~]poet  in  particular,  was  influenced  by  political  events, 
customs,  public  opinion  and  society,  considered  in  its  divisions 
into  classes  and  factions ;  and,  on  the  other  hand,  to  what 
extent  society,  customs  and  public  opinion  were  influenced  by 
comedy  and  its  authors.  It  should  follow  the  comic  style  from 
year  to  year,  let  us  witness  the  composition  of  each  of  its  great 
creations,  tell  us  of  the  suggestions  received  by  the  poet,  and  of 
his  intentions  and  of  his  likes  and  dislikes.  It  should  take  us 
to  the  theatre  and  make  us  onlookers,  as  it  were,  at  the  per- 
formances, acquaint  us  with  the  impressions  gained  by  the 
audience,  with  the  intrigues,  the  verdict  of  the  judges,  and 
finally,  it  should  discuss  and  explain  what  may  have  been  the 
effect  of  it  all.  One  can  readily  imagine  how  greatly  such 
an  account  would  interest  a  person  who  cared  to  become 
acquainted  with  the  inner  workings  of  political  life  at  Athens 
during  the  fifth  century. 

Unfortunately  it  must  be  admitted  that  such  a  plan  cannot 
be  carried  out  at  this  late  day.  Most  of  the  comic  poets 
of  that  time  are  merely  names  to  us.  Their  works  are  lost, 
barring  a  few  titles  and  fragments,  which,  in  most  cases,  are 
not  sufficient  even  to  enable  us  to  determine  the  subjects  of 
the  plays  to  which  they  belong.  The  dates  of  these  plays  are 
nearly  all  unknown.  We  know  practically  nothing  of  the 
relations  of  the  authors,  either  among  themselves  or  with  their 
contemporaries.  Under  such  conditions,  an  attempt  at  history 
could  be  naught  else  than  a  tissue  of  guesswork  or  a  series  of 
avowals  of  ignorance. 

I  hardly  need  say  that  I  have  never  for  a  moment  dreamed 
of  imdertaking  it.  Aristophanes  is  really  the  only  one  of  the 
comic  poets  of  that  period  of  whom  we  can  speak  with  due 


PREFACE   BY  THE   AUTHOR  ix 

knowledge,  and  it  is  only  with  him  that  I  have  thought 
it  possible  to  deal.  But  it  is  evident  that  what  is  said 
about  one  poet  in  particular,  may  often  chance  to  apply  to 
others  of  his  contemporaries  who  cultivated  the  same  style. 
So  regarded,  this  series  of  essays  may  serve  as  a  contribution 
to  a  history  written  on  a  much  larger  scale,  of  which  an  out- 
line has  just  been  given.  But  it  must  be  understood,  at  the 
outset,  that  it  does  not  claim  in  itself  to  constitute  even  a 
complete  chapter  in  such  a  history.  "We  are  ignorant  of  too 
many  important  facts  about  Aristophanes  himself.  Only 
eleven  of  his  plays  have  come  down  to  us  ;  he  wrote  forty.^ 
Of  his  biography  and  his  personality  we  know  merely  what 
he  has  told  us  here  and  there  in  his  parabases  or  in  the  words 
of  his  dramatis  personae.  It  is  with  such  very  insufificient 
documents  that  the  attempt  must  be  made  to  answer  difficult 
and  necessarily  obscure  questions. 

Those  which  constitute  the  real  subject  of  this  book  bear 
almost  exclusively  upon  Aristophanes'  relations  with  the  poli- 
tical parties  that  were  active  at  Athens  in  his  day.  A  rapid 
perusal  of  his  plays  is  sufficient  to  reveal  him  as  an  adversary 
of  the  men  who,  at  that  time,  exerted  a  preponderating  influ- 
ence on  the  foreign  and  domestic  politics  of  his  country. 
Does  it  follow  that  he  was,  properly  speaking,  an  enemy  of 
democracy  as  such,  or  even  of  the  democracy  which  existed 
in  the  city  at  that  period  ?  It  is  true  that  he  attacked  it 
when  he  attacked  its  leaders  ?  And  if  he  effectively  criticised 
it  in  some  instances  at  least,  what  was  the  meaning  of  his 
criticism  and  from  what  did  it  arise  ?  Did  he  wish  to  discredit 
democracy,  with  a  view  to  bringing  about  its  complete  trans- 
formation, or  simply  to  warn  it,  with  a  view  to  aiding  it  in 
correcting  some  of  its  shortcomings  ?  And  again,  was  he,  when 
writing  his  plays,  the  interpreter  or  mouth-piece  of  an  organized 
opposition  that  was  aware  of  his  views  and  of  the  means  he 
employed  ?  Or,  on  the  contrary,  did  he  take  counsel  of  him- 
self only  ?     Such,  approximately,  are  the  questions  which  the 

^  This  excludes  the  four  plaj's  which,  even  in  antiquity,  were  considered 
apocryphal :  Uoi-rjais,  'Savayos,  N^crot,  Nio/3os.  Vid.  Kaibel,  art.  "Aristophanes," 
12,  in  Pauly-Wissowa. 


X  PREFACE  BY   THE  AUTHOR 

reader  will  encounter  and  that  I  have  tried  to  solve  in  the 
following  chapters. 

These  questions,  of  course,  have  not  been  ignored  hitherto. 
Indeed  nearly  all  the  scholars,  historians,  or  writers  who 
have  occupied  themselves  with  Aristophanes,  have  made  a 
point  of  saying  what  they  thought  about  them.  The  prin- 
cipal works  in  which  these  opinions  have  been  stated  or 
vindicated  will  be  found  in  the  notes  to  this  volume.  It  is 
not  necessary  to  quote  their  titles  here.  I  need  hardly  say 
that  if  these  opinions  had  completely  satisfied  me,  it  would 
not  have  occurred  to  me  to  write  another  book  on  the  same 
subject.  On  the  other  hand,  I  am  far  from  considering  them 
as  generally  incorrect.  Truth,  in  historical  and  literary 
studies,  gains  its  full  value  only  through  nicety  in  the  dif- 
ferentiation of  the  facts  that  reveal  it.  It  is  only  to  the  task 
of  better  pointing  out  these  differentiations  and  of  arranging 
them  in  a  better  manner  that  I  thought  I  could  profitably 
devote  myself.  My  conclusions,  as  will  subsequently  appear, 
take  issue  only  with  preconceived  opinions  and  unqualified 
statements. 

The  first  suggestion  of  this  undertaking  came  with  the 
perusal  of  the  book  written  some  years  ago  by  my  lamented 
comrade  and  friend  Auguste  Couat — Aristophane  et  I'ancicnne 
ComMie  attique}  In  this  work,  which  is  replete  with 
facts  and  stimulating  ideas,  I  had  met  with  several  opinions, 
on  the  subject  under  discussion,  that  aroused  my  serious 
doubts.  Frequent  reflection  intensified  these  doubts  and 
led  me  to  write  this  book.  As,  in  substance,  it  records  a 
difference  of  opinion  between  Couat  and  myself,  I  am  par- 
ticularly desirous  of  minimizing  this  difference,  as  far  as  may 
be,  by  here  rendering  sincere  homage  to  the  great  value  of  his 
work. 

October  1905. 

^  Paris,  Lec^iie  et  Oudin,  1SS9;  second  edition,  1903. 


INTEODUCTION    TO    THE    ENGLISH    VERSION 

Aristophanes  is  an  elusive  poet.  The  main  religious  convic- 
tions of  Aeschylus  may  be  determined  with  certainty  from  his 
extant  plays ;  attentive  study  of  the  dramas  of  Euripides 
reveals  his  cardinal  opinions  on  politics,  society  and  religion, 
and  his  philosophic  attitude ;  but  who  can  affirm  with  con- 
fidence that  he  has  penetrated  the  comic  mask  of  Aristophanes 
and  knows  his  beliefs  ?  The  poet's  mocking  irony  baffles  and 
perplexes  his  reader  at  almost  every  turn. 

puvr]Kau   o  Aeyet  ; — /ma  rov   KiroWw    yw  jmev  ou. 

One  element  of  the  poet's  irony  is  his  apparent  frankness. 
He  has  at  times  the  air  of  desiring  to  be  taken  seriously  and 
seems  to  be  expressing  honest  convictions.  He  is  very  sug- 
gestive and  provokes  reflection,  but  the  attempt  to  reduce  his 
opinions  to  system  reveals  the  illusion.  We  become  uneasily 
conscious  that  the  great  satirist  is  laughing  behind  his  mask. 

A  proof  of  this  deceptive  quality  of  the  poet's  humor  is 
found  in  the  diversity  of  the  opinions  that  have  been  held  as 
to  his  purpose  in  writing.  It  was  once  the  fashion  among 
modern  interpreters  to  take  him  very  seriously, — the  comic 
poet  disappeared  in  the  reformer.  He  was  eulogized  as  a 
moralist  and  patriot,  whose  lofty  purpose  was  to  instruct  his 
fellow-countrymen ;  as  an  earnest  thinker,  who  had  reflected 
deeply  on  the  problems  of  society  and  government  and  had 
made  Comedy  simply  the  vehicle  of  his  reforming  ideas ;  as  a 
wise  and  discerning  counsellor,  who  was  competent  to  advise 
the  citizens  of  Athens  at  a  critical  time  on  political  questions 


xii    INTRODUCTION  TO  ENGLISH  VERSION 

and  whose  juclgnieni  of  men  and  measures  was  sound ;  as  a 
stern  man  withal,  resohite  in  the  performance  of  duty,  the 
implacable  and  victorious  foe  of  all,  wherever  found,  who 
undermined  the  glory  of  Athens.  This  view,  which  Grote 
combated  {History  of  Greece,  Ixvii.),  finds  vigorous  expression 
in  the  Apology  of  Eobert  Browning  : 

"  Next,  whom  thrash  ? 
Only  the  coaise  fool  and  the  clownish  knave  ? 
No  !  strike  malpractice  that  atfects  the  State, 
The  common  weal — intriguer  or  poltroon. 
Venality,  corruption,  what  care  I 
If  shrewd  or  witless  merely  ? — so  the  thing 
Lay  sap  to  aught  that  made  Athenai  bright 
And  happy,  change  her  customs,  lead  astray 
Youth  or  age,  play  the  demagogue  at  Pnux, 
The  sophist  in  Palaistra,  or — what's  worst, 
As  widest  mischief, — from  the  Theatre 
Preach  innovation,  bring  contempt  on  oaths. 
Adorn  licentiousness,  despise  the  Cult.   .  .  . 

But  my  soul  bade  Tight ! 
Prove  arms  efficient  on  real  heads  and  hearts  ! '  .  .  . 
I  wield  the  Comic  weapon  rather — hate  ! 
Hate  !  honest,  earnest  and  directest  hate — 
Warfare  wherein  I  close  with  enemy.  .  .  . 
Such  was  my  purpose  :  it  succeeds,  I  say  ! 
Have  we  not  beaten  Kallicratidas, 
Not  humbled  Sparte  ?     Peace  awaits  our  word. 
Since  my  previsions, — warranted  too  well 
By  the  long  war  now  waged  and  worn  to  end — 
Had  spared  such  heritage  of  misery. 
My  after-counsels  scarce  need  fear  repulse. 
Athenai,  taught  pi'osperity  has  wings. 
Cages  the  glad  recapture." 

Thus  vaunts  the  poet,  as  Browning  interprets  him,  just 
after  the  great  victory  won  at  Arginusae.  '  Sparta  is  at  our 
feet,  a  new  day  dawns,  the  "War  is  at  an  end.  For  Athens 
has  at  length  learnt  the  bitter  lesson  she  might  have  been 
spared  had  she  yielded  to  my  pleas  for  peace.'  The  actual 
history  of  the  next  twelve  months  is  pathetic.  The  battle  at 
Arginusae,  in  which  Callicratidas  fell,  restored   the  maritime 


INTRODUCTION  TO  ENGLISH  VERSION   xiii 

supremacy  of  Athens,  but  peace  was  not  secured.  The  Spar- 
tans made  overtures,  but  the  Athenian  people,  paying  small 
lieed  to  the  '  good  counsels '  that  their  Poet  had  given  them 
in  the  Acharnians,  the  Peace,  the  Lysistrata,  and  in  other 
comedies  no  longer  extant,  followed  the  lead  of  drunken 
Cleophon  and  rejected  the  Spartan  proposals,  just  as  five 
years  before  they  had  committed  the  grave  error  of  accepting 
liis  advice  after  the  Athenian  victory  at  Cyzicus.  Sparta 
bestirred  herself,  Lysander  was  sent  out,  and  within  a  year 
Athenian  arms  suffered  irretrievable  reverse  at  Aegospotami. 

The  poet's  counsels  of  peace  were  rejected.  Peace  came 
only  with  disaster.  His  '  sage '  solutions  of '  many  other 
burning  Cjuestions  were  equally  ineffective.  i^Jf  Aristophanes 
was  working  for  reform,  as  a  long  line  of  learned  interpreters 
of  the  poet  have  maintained,  the  result  was  lamentably  dis- 
appointing :  he  succeeded  in  effecting  not  a  single  change.  ^ 
He  wdngs  the  shafts  of  his  incomparable  wit  at  all  the  popular 
leaders  of  the  day — Cleon,  Hyperbolus,  Peisander,  Cleophon, 
Agyrrhius,  in  succession,  and  is  reluctant  to  unstring  his  bow 
even  when  they  are  dead.  But  he  drove  no  one  of  them  from 
power :  there  is  little  evidence,  indeed,  that  he  damaged  their 
influence  or  even  disturbed  their  brazen  self-confidence.  Cleon, 
when  the  poet's  libellous  personal  abuse  became  even  in  his 
judgment  indecent,  promptly  brought  him  to  his  knees.  "When 
Cleon  pressed  me  hard  and  tanned  my  hide,  and  outsiders 
laughed  to  see  the  sport,  I  confess  " — Aristophanes  says  in  the 
"Wasps — "  I  played  the  ape  a  bit."  He  adds  significantly  that 
he  failed  to  get  popular  support  in  this  quarrel.  The  inference 
is  that  the  people  did  not  think  1)adly  of  Cleon ;  but  modern 
opinion  of  the  popular  leaders  in  Athens,  formed,  on  the 
evidence  that  Aristophanes  is  supposed  to  furnish,  has  Ijeen 
persistently  unfavorable,  and  Cleon's  rehabilitation  as  a  saga- 
cious, if  turbulent,  statesman  who  consistently  maintained  the 
imperial  policy  of  Pericles  has  been  slow. 

The  poet  vehemently  protested,  it  has  been  said,  against 
the  New  Education,  and  viewing  the  whole  intellectual  ten- 
dency of  his  time  with  alarm,  pleaded  for  a  restoration  of  the 
simple  discipline  that  had  moulded  the  morals  and  minds  and 


xiv    INTRODUCTION  TO   ENGLISH  VERSION 

manners  of  the  hardy  men  who  fought  at  Marathon,  Further- 
more, he  clearly  apprehended  the  evils  inherent  in  the  Athenian 
system  of  judicature,  which  committed  the  administration  of 
justice  to  a  horde  of  common  men,  ignorant  of  the  law,  swayed 
by  the  impulse  of  the  moment,  '  monsters  of  caprice  and  in- 
justice,' and  ruthlessly  exposed  the  unrighteousness  of  its 
proceedings.  Finally,  reverent  of  the  best  traditions  of  the 
stage,  he  stood  forth,  it  is  alleged,  as  their  uncompromising 
defender,  and  sternly  resisted  the  innovations  that  were  gradu- 
ally changing  the  spirit  and  the  form  of  tragedy  during  the 
last  third  of  the  century  and  for  a  generation  relentlessly 
pursued  their  chief  exponent,  concealing  an  attack  that  was 
meant  to  ruin  him  under  the  veil  of  caricature,  parody,  bur- 
lesque, and  satire.  But  Socrates  still  frequented,  winter  and 
summer,  the  gymnasia,  the  market  and  the  schools,  and  the 
Sophists  continued  to  discourse  and  draw  their  pay;  Philocleon, 
after  a  single  experience  of  the  pleasures  of  polite  society, 
again  foregathered  with  his  cronies  before  the  dawn  of  day 
and  trudged  away  to  Court;  and  Euripides,  calmly  disregarding 
the  malicious  strictures  of  his  youthful  critic,  continued  to 
write  tragedy  in  his  own  manner  and  to  present  on  the  stage 
plays  that  were  heard  by  the  young  men  of  Athens  with  wild 
acclaim. 

This  extreme  conception  of  the  function  of  Greek  comedy 
as  chiefly  censorial  and  monitory  has  been  modified  with  larger 
and  more  exact  knowledge  of  the  times  in  which  the  poet  lived 
and  of  the  conditions  of  life  under  which  he  wrote,  but  it  has 
had  unfortunate  consequences.  These  plays  have  been  regarded 
as  a  trustworthy  source  of  information  in  establishing  the  facts 
of  Greek  history,  biography,  and  institutions.  So  serious  an 
interpretation  of  a  form  of  literature  of  which  the  primary 
intention  must  always  be  entertainment  and  amusement 
inevitably  obscured  the  poet's  elusive  humor.  A  jest  became 
a  statement  of  fact,  a  caricature  a  portrait,  a  satire  a  document. 
The  poet's  conception,  clothed  in  a  fantastical  disguise  that 
rivalled  the  grotesque  dress  of  his  own  actors,  has  been  essen- 
tially misapprehended  in  an  entire  play. 

On    the    other    hand    the    mistaken    disposition,    recently 


INTRODUCTION  TO   ENGLISH  VERSION    xv 

manifested,  to  regard  Aristophanes  simply  as  a  jester  and  '' 
to  deny  that  he  had  any  other  purpose  than  to  provoke 
laughter  is  an  extreme,  though  natural,  reaction.^  This  view 
denies  at  the  same  time,  as  might  have  been  expected,  the 
cathartic  efficacy  of  Greek  tragedy.  The  highest  comedy, 
typed  in  the  earlier  plays  of  Aristophanes,  and  in  some  of 
the  comedies  of  Moliere,  is  regenerative.  The  purpose  of 
Aristophanes  in  the  Acharnians,  in  which  the  action  turns 
upon  the  impossible  and  fantastic  whimsey  of  an  Athenian 
farmer  securing  peace  with  Sparta  for  himself  and  his  family 
alone,  is  to  ridicule  the  war-party.  Nobody  would  have  been 
more  amused  than  the  poet,  if  he  had  been  told  that  his  play 
was  to  stop  the  fighting,  but  he  did  believe  that  the  War  was 
an  evil  and  so  far  his  heart  was  honestly  in  his  theme ;  and  I 
have  no  doubt  that  many  a  man  who  had  laughed  uproariously 
at  the  peace-loving  farmer  set  single-handed  in  the  comedy 
against  a  quarrelsome  chorus,  a  powerful  general,  the  whole 
tribe  of  sycophants,  and  the  demagogue  Cleon  in  the  back- 
ground, went  home  from  the  play  less  content  w"ith  the  course 
of  his  political  leaders  and  longing  in  his  heart  for  the  good, 
old  days  of  peace.  The  instrument  by  which  the  poet  probed 
the  popular  discontent  was  that  most*  effective  of  all  means 
when  skilfully  used — a^ laugh. 

To  regard  Aristophanes  as  merely  a  jester  is  to  mistake 
the  man.  Eidicule  of  contemporary  persons,  that  is  generally 
good-natured,  or  systems  or  prevailing  ideas  is  his  main  pur- 
pose, I  think,  in  his  plays.  His  praise  is  for  the  dead.  This 
ridicule,  which  ranges  from  satire  to  airy  conceit,  is  made 
humorous  by  centering  it  in  a  far-fetched  fantastic  conception 
that  is  not  the  less  available  if  it  is  impossible.  Facts  are 
exaggerated  or  invented  with  superb  nonchalance  and  be- 
wildering semblance  of  reality.  In  these  mad  revels  of 
unrestrained  fancy  it  is  difficult  to  lay  hands  upon  Aristo- 
phanes the  man.  Nevertheless  we  do  discover  probable 
indications  of  his  attachments  and  beliefs.  He  lived  in  an 
age  of  intellectual  unrest  when  many  vital  questions  pressed 
for  solution.  Jhat  a  man  of  his  intelligence  did  not  give 
them    consideration    and     reach     conclusions     is     impossible. 


xvi    INTRODUCTION  TO   ENGLISH  VERSION 

No  doubt  he  detested  a  debauchee — let  Ariphrades  bear 
witness, — but  he  must  have  sympathized  with  the  revolt 
of  the  young  men  of  his  day  against  the  severe  and  meagre 
discipline  in  which  youth  were  trained  during  the  first  half 
of  the  century,  and  must  have  shared  in  their  eager  interest 
in  the  new  subjects  of  knowledge.  No  doubt  he  deprecated 
the  vicious  use  of  the  skill  for  which  Strepsiades  clamors  in 
the  Clouds,  but  he  had  too  keen  a  mind  to  fail  to  distinguish 
between  the  right  and  the  wrong  use  of  this  power  or  to  reject 
all  study  of  the  art  of  persuasion  because  it  might  be  abused. 
He  was  himself  a  skilful  dialectician,  as  the  Debates  found  in 
nearly  all  his  comedies  prove.  He  was  acquainted  with 
Socrates  and  must  have  known  that  he  never  misused  his 
wonderful  dialectical  power  and  must  have  felt  an  expert's 
special  thrill  of  pleasure  in  observing  with  what  skill  he 
employed  it.  Furthermore,  the  times  in  which  the  poet  lived 
were  troublous,  the  fate  of  Athens  again  and  again  stood  on 
the  razor's  edge.  He  was  not  indifferent  to  the  welfare  of 
his  country  nor  of  his  fellow-countrymen.  There  is  a  serious 
undertone  in  the  Acharnians  that  gives  it  an  indescribable 
elevation,  and  in  the  Lysistrata,  a  Eabelaisian  play,  written 
after  the  disaster  to  Athenian  arms  in  Sicily  in  which, 
Thucydides  records,  fleet  and  army  utterly  perished  and  of 
the  many  who  went  forth  few  returned  home,  there  are 
verses  of  intensest  pathos  that  betray  the  poet's  poignant 
sympathy, 

"oi'/c  ear IV  aviip  ev  rtj  yjipa]   jua  A/'  ov  Stjr',  elcj)'  eTepo^  T19." 

Aristophanes,  then,  was  a  man  of  quick  sympathies  and 
settled  convictions,  although  positive  expression  of  belief  and 
feeling  is  naturally  rare  in  his  plays,  since  he  was  a  writer 
of  comedy.  Despite  this  reticence,  it  is  both  interesting  and 
important  to  determine,  so  far  as  this  may  be  done,  his 
opinions  on  the  questions  that  in  his  day  were  pressing  for 
answer,  and  among  these  especially  his  political  position. 
Was  he  an  aristocrat  ?  Was  he,  in  particular,  as  M.  Couat 
believed,  a  pamphleteer  in  the  pay  of  the  aristocrats  ?  Or 
was  he  a  democrat  ?     And  if  a  democrat,  how  is  the  satirical 


INTRODUCTION  TO   ENGLISH  VERSION  xvii 

— but  extremely  comical — characterization  of  Athenian  Demus 
in  the  Knights,  which  his  countrymen  viewed  with  good- 
natured  amusement,  to  be  interpreted  ?  To  these  weighty  and 
significant  questions  M.  Croiset  makes  convincing  answer  in 
the  book  which  Mr.  Loeb  now  publishes  in  an  English  version. 

JOHN   WILLIAMS   WHITE. 


Harvard  Uxiversitt, 

September  1,  1909. 


CONTENTS 


PAOK 

The  Translator's  Preface v 


Preface  by  the  Author vii 

Introduction  to  the  English  Version  .        .        .        .         xi 

INTRODUCTION  ....  1 

CHAPTER   I. 

THE   BEGINNING  OF  ARISTOPHANES'   CAREER 

The   Banqueters,    427.     The   Babylonians,    426.    The 
6  acharnians,  425 29 

CHAPTER  n. 

The  Knights,  424 61 

CHAPTER  HI. 
The  Clouds,  423.    The  Wasps,  422.    The  Peace,  421  .        89 


XX  CONTENTS 

CHAPTER   IV. 

SECOND  PERIOD.     THE   SICILIAN   AND 
DECELEIAN   WAKS 

PAGE 

The   Bikds,    4U.    The   Lysistrata   and   the   Thesmo- 

PHORIAZUSAE,    411.      ThE  FrOGS,    405  .  .  .  .115 

CHAPTER  V. 

LAST  PERIOD 

The  Ecclesiazusae,  392.     The  Plutus,  388    .        .        .164 

jf  Analytical  Index    ....  187 


ARISTOPHANES    AND    THE    POLITICAL 
PARTIES    AT    ATHENS 

INTRODUCTION 


Athenian  comedy  was  essentially  rural  in  its  origin.  How- 
ever great  the  obscurity  of  its  primitive  history,  we  do  at 
least  know  that  it  took  form,  in  the  sixth  century  B.C.,  in  the 
country  districts  of  Attica. 

It  had  its  beginning  in  the  rustic  masquerades  that 
travelled  from  village  to  village  with  their  songs,  during  the 
festivals  of  Dionysus,  the  god  of  wine.  Sooner  or  later, 
grotesque  actors  seem  to  have  associated  themselves  with 
these  choruses,  wearing  the  costume  and  imitating  the 
indecent  buffoonery  of  the  Peloponnesian  peasants  who  had 
long  been  representing  in  dance  and  pantomime  the  exuberant 
life  of  certain  deities  of  nature.  It  was  from  them,  perhaps, 
that  comedy  adopted  also  the  imitation,  in  caricature,  of  real 
life,  which  it  was  not  slow  to  develop  in  an  original  manner. 
At  all  events  the  mixture  of  the  most  extravagant  imagina- 
tion and  the  most  daring  satire  was  its  strength  and  assured 
its  future. 

As  long  as  comedy  served  merely  as  a  pastime  of  the 
peasants,  this  satire,  however  free  it  may  have  been,  had  little 
influence ;  it  did  not  spread  beyond  the  village,  or  at  most 
the  district.  But  when  it  penetrated  into  those  demes  half 
urban,  half  rustic,  which,  in  the  time  of  Peisistratus  and  hie 
sons,  constituted  suburban  Athens,  and  later,  when  toward  ths 
beginning  of  the  fifth  century  it  was  admitted  to  the  festivals 
of  Dionysus  that  were  celebrated  in  the  city  proper,  and 
the    State    gave    it    a    place    in   the   official   contests,   things 


2  INTRODUCTION 

necessarily  changed.  Thereafter  comedy  had  to  take  cog- 
nizance of  the  events  and  of  the  men  who  engaged  attention 
in  these  new  surroundings.  It  retained  its  fertile  imagination 
and  its  bufibonery,  but  it  aimed  its  shafts  against  people  of 
more  importance.  At  first  it  did  so  in  what  Aristotle  calls 
the  "  iambic "  form :  that  is  to  say,  by  attacking,  apparently, 
persons  rather  than  ideas,  as  Archilochus  had  done  in  earlier 
days,  and  without  binding  itself  to  the  regular  development  of  a 
dramatic  theme.  Later  on,  and  bit  by  bit,  it  learned  the  art  of 
construction,  and  attempted,  with  increasing  success,  to  invent 
comic  ideas  and  to  exploit  them ;  it  constructed  regular  stories 
or  plots  and  endowed  them  with  a  certain  logical  quality,  and, 
as  a  consequence,  with  a  degree  of  unity.  It  even  ventured 
on  arguments  and  maintained  theses  on  politics  and  morals.  It 
is  at  this  stage  of  its  development  that  comedy  appears  in  the 
hands  of  Aristophanes,  in  the  first  period  of  the  Peloponnesian 
war,  shortly  after  431. 

The  spirit  that  pervaded  it  was  naturally  that  of  the  majority 
of  its  audience.  We  must  therefore  try  to  picture  to  ourselves 
the  elements  of  which  this  majority  was  constituted,  and  like- 
wise the  relations  existing  between  it  and  its  favorite  poets. 

Thucydides,  in  his  account  of  the  beginnings  of  the  war  in 
431,  has  given  us,  with  his  customary  precision,  a  description 
of  the  kind  of  life  the  greater  part  of  the  Athenians  led  at 
that  time.  He  informs  us  that  they  followed  the  advice  of 
Pericles  and  decided  to  abandon  their  rural  habitations,  even  to 
destroy  them  in  part,  to  convey  their  flocks  and  their  cattle 
either  into  Euboea  or  to  the  neighboring  islands,  and  to  take 
refuge  themselves,  with  their  wives  and  children,  within  the 
fortified  enclosure  of  Athens.  "  This  change,"  he  adds,  "  was 
very  painful  to  them,  for  the  greater  'part  of  the  Athenians 
had  been  acctistomed  for  generations  to  live  in  the  country."^ 
That  was,  as  he  points  out,  an  immemorial  tradition  in  Attica, 
and  even  the  destruction  of  the  earlier  political  and  religious 
centres,  credited  to  Theseus,  had  not  altered  it.  From  the 
time  that  Athens  had  become  the  only  city,  the  ancient  towns 
of  the  district  were  transformed  into  hamlets,  but  habits 
1  Thucydides,  ii.  cap.  xiv. 


INTRODUCTION  3 

remained  the  same.  Families  continued  to  reside  on  their 
estates,  large  or  small,  grouped  in  domestic  communities  which 
rarely  sliifted  their  sites.  The  second  Persian  war  had  passed 
over  these  country  districts  like  a  destructive  cyclone,  but 
when  the  region  was  again  free,  the  burned  or  ruined  houses 
were  rebuilt  and  the  accustomed  life  was  resumed.  "  For  this 
reason,"  says  the  historian,  "  it  was  very  hard  for  them  to 
abandon  their  dwellings  and  those  local  forms  of  worship  which, 
since  the  ancient  towns  had  existed,  had  ever  been  handed 
down  from  father  to  son ;  besides,  it  was  a  sore  trial  to  them 
to  find  themselves  obliged  to  change  their  manner  of  life,  and 
it  seemed  to  each  one  of  them  as  though  he  were  deserting  from 
his  native  town."  ^  This  statement  is  of  very  great  interest, 
and  has  not  been  sufficiently  considered  in  its  bearings  on 
comedy.  It  clearly  shows  that,  during  the  whole  period  in 
which  comedy  was  developing,  the  greatest  part  of  the 
Athenian  democracy  was  ruial  in  fact  as  well  as  in  its  way  of 
thinking.^ 

Thus,  prior  to  the  Peloponnesian  war,  the  urban  democracy 
really  constituted  a  minority,  and  this  minority  was  not  even 
absolutely  compact.  Its  most  active  part  consisted  of  those 
who  lived  at  the  Piraeus.^  Here  were  assembled  the  sea- 
faring folk,  and  all  those  who  furnished  them  with  what 
they  neecled,  or  who  helped  them  in  their  various  tasks — 
builders,  longshoremen,  manufacturers  and  merchants  of  every 
description,  pedlars,  bankers — a  population  without  tradi- 
tions, without  attachment  to  the  soil,  with  a  considerable 
admixture  of  resident  aliens  (fxeroiKoi)  and  in  constant  con- 
tact with  foreigners.  Life  there  was  necessarily  more  agitated, 
more  subject  to  chance,  and,  in  a  word,  quite  untouched  by 
conservative  traditions. 

^  Thucydides,  ii.  c.  xvi. 

-  These  rural  dwellings  were  naturally  much  more  comfortable  than  those  in 
the  city.  There  was  ample  room,  and  life  was  agreeable.  See,  on  this 
subject,  Isocrates,  Areopagit.  52 ;  cf.  G.  Gilbert,  Beitrdge  zur  mnertn 
Geachichte  Athena  im  Zeitalter  des  Pelopon.  Krieges,  p.  98  et  seq.,  Leipzig, 
1877. 

^Busolt,  Griechische  Geschichle,  vol.  iii.  first  part,  p.  489. 


4  INTRODUCTION 

The  city  proper,  which  was  rapidly  growing  larger  round 
about  the  Acropolis,  formed  a  bridge,  as  it  were,  between  this 
turbulent  maritime  democracy  and  the  peaceful  rural  demo- 
cracy. Here  a  certain  number  of  rich  citizens  had  their  city 
houses  in  which  they  resided  part  of  the  year.  Kound  about 
them  dwelt  a  population  of  moderate  means — merchants, 
business  men,  owners  of  factories — who  together  made  up  that 
class  so  precious  to  the  prosperity  of  the  state,  whose  praises 
Euripides  has  sung  in  a  celebrated  passage  in  his  Suppliants} 
But  in  proportion  as  Athenian  industry  had  developed,  there 
had  grown  up,  in  that  large  city,  a  proletariat  that  lived  from 
hand  to  mouth  on  the  gains  of  their  daily  toil.  These  earners 
of  small  wages  were  naturally  often  inclined  to  espouse  the 
cause  of  the  radicals  of  the  Piraeus.  Thus,  there  were  in 
close  proximity  to  one  another  two  very  different  elements, 
which  were  either  counterbalanced,  or  gained  ascendancy  in 
turn,  according  to  circumstances. 

To  return  to  the  rural  democracy — there  is  no  room  for 
doubt  that  it  likewise  was  very  devoted  to  Athenian  institu- 
tions. Solon's  laws,  in  the  beginning  of  the  sixth  century, 
had  enfranchised  it  and  secured  it  in  the  quiet  possession  of 
its  estates.  The  reign  of  Peisistratus  and  of  his  sons  had 
afforded  a  long  period  of  domestic  peace,  and  had  concen- 
trated in  its  hands  the  possession  of  landed  property,  and  had 
favored  its  division  into  parcels,  At  the  end  of  the  sixth 
century,  Attica  probably  contained  a  larger  number  of  small 
rural  estates  than  any  other  country  in  Greece.  Cleisthenes' 
reforms  had  abolished  the  old  naucraries  and  had  organized 
the  demes,  and  by  so  doing  had  spread  the  spirit  of  liberty 
throughout  the  rural  centres.  All  these  small  farmers  had 
become  accustomed  to  deliberate,  to  reach  decisions,  to  run 
their  own  affairs ;  they  were,  in  the  true  sense  of  the  word, 
free  men,  and  they  had  no  desire  whatever  to  cease  to  be 
such.     Democracy  had,  without  doubt,  taken  quite  as  firm  a 

^Euripides,  Suppliants,  1.  244:  "Of  the  three  classes  of  citizens,  it  is  the 
middle  class  which  ensures  the  public  weal,  for  it  is  they  who  preserve  the 
order  established  by  the  state."  These  words  the  poet  attributes  to  Theseus, 
the  legendary  founder  of  the  Athenian  State. 


INTRODUCTION  5 

hold  on  them  as  on  the  people  of  the  city  or  of  the  Piraeus, 
but  they  had  a  different  conception  of  it.^ 

Quite  naturally,  they  were  much  more  attached  to  the  old 
customs,  to  their  ancient  rites  of  worship,  to  tradition  in  all 
its  forms.  They  were  slow  to  adopt  new  ideas,  and  when  they 
enconntered  them  unexpectedly,  they  thought  them  scandalous 
or  ridiculous.  The  hereditary  nobility,  which  was  either  hated 
or  eyed  with  suspicion  by  the  democrats  of  the  city,  continued, 
on  the  contrary,  to  enjoy  the  inborn  respect  of  these  peasants. 
For  the  representatives  of  the  old  families,  scattered  through 
the  denies,  were  the  guardians  and  hereditary  priests  of  many 
of  those  local  cults  to  which  the  country  folk  remained  so 
much  attached.  Besides,  the  city  politicians  had  little  influ- 
ence over  them.  They  were  kept  busy  with  their  work,  and 
had  neither  time  nor  inclination  to  lend  an  ear  to  the 
denunciations  that  gained  credence  among  the  common  people 
of  the  city,  and  they  held  themselves  aloof  from  fruitless 
agitation.- 

Euripides,  in  his  Orestes,  performed  in  408,  took  pleasure  in 
drawing  a  picture,  probably  idealized,  but  surely  true  in  its 
essential  features,  of  the  peasant,  as  he  appeared  to  his  eyes. 
The  countryman,  whom  he  depicts  attending  a  popular 
assembly,  is  engaged  in  defending  precisely  the  cause  of 
hereditary  principles  against  the  attacks  of  a  demagogue : 
"  Then  another  citizen  arose  ;  his  exterior  was  rough,  but  he 
was  a  true  man.  He  spent  his  time  neither  in  the  city  nor 
in  the  rounded  market-place  ;  he  worked  in  the  fields.  He  was 
one  of  those  who  assure  the  welfare  of  a  state.  Besides,  his 
mind  was  open  to  discussion,  when  he  chose  to  discuss ;  an 
honest  man,  who  led  an  irreproachable  life."  ^     This  peasant, 

^  Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  821,  seems  to  me  to  confound  the 
rural  democracy  quite  too  much  with  the  oligarchy.  The  fact  that  they 
joined  forces  under  certain  circumstances,  does  not  warrant  the  conclusion 
that  they  were,  as  a  rule,  animated  by  the  same  feelings. 

-Aristophanes,  Peace,  1.  190.  Trj'gaeus  informs  us  of  his  name  and  character 
in  two  lines  :  "  Trygaeus  of  Athmone,  a  clever  vine-drcsser,  no  sycophant,  nor 
fond  of  meddling  in  other  people's  affairs. " 

^  Euripides,  Orestes,  1.  917. 


6  INTRODUCTION 

the  poet  tells  us,  spent  his  time,  neither  in  the  city  nor  in  the 
agora,  which  here  means  the  assembly.  Here  we  have,  if  we 
properly  interpret  this  precious  testimony,  the  explanation  of 
a  fact  which  is  of  the  greatest  importance  to  our  subject. 
[The  rural  democracy,  though  numerous,  had  but  little  influence 
in  the  assembly  and  in  the  courts,  because  the  majority  did 
not  take  part  in  them.  Indeed,  this  was  the  evil  from  which 
Athens  suffered  most,  and  which  she  was  never  able  to  remedy 
by  the  organization  of  a  representative  government,  or  by  the 
creation  of  a  referendum  for  certain  questions  of  supreme 
importance.  These  dwellers  in  the  villages  did  not,  as  a  rule, 
care  to  abandon  their  work,  to  make  a  long  journey  and  to 
incur  expense,  in  order  to  go  to  the  city  and  make  use  of 
their  rights  of  citizenship.  Thus  it  happened  that  the  Athe- 
nians in  the  city  and  those  of  the  Piraeus  found  that  they 
made  up  the  majority  in  the  Pnyx  as  well  as  in  the  courts, 
except  perhaps  in  some  special  cases.^ 

Of  course  it  was  different  when  there  was  a  question  of 
taking  part  in  the  Lenaean  or  the  great  Dionysiac  festivals. 
These  were  considered  the  most  beautiful,  the  most  joyful  and 
the  noisiest  that  were  celebrated  at  Athens.^  From  all  the 
suburbs  of  the  city,  and  even  from  distant  parts  of  Attica, 
people  must  have  come  in  throngs.^  These  rustic  spectators 
brought  with  them  their  habits  of  mind,  their  tastes,  their 
ideas,  and  as,  either  by  themselves  or  together  with  that  part 
of   the  city's  population  that  shared  their  views,  they  were 

1  See  on  this  subject  G.  Gilbert,  Beitrage,  p.  98  et  seq.,  and  J.  Beloch,  Die 
attische  Politih  seit  Perikles,  p.  7  et  seq.,  Leipzig,  1884;  cf.  Xenophon,  Memor. 
vii.  §  6. 

-Aristophanes,  Clouds,  1.  311. 

^  Isocrates,  Areopag.  52,  says,  regarding  these  times  :  koL  ttoWovs  tCiv 
ttoKltCov  fjir}8'  eis  ras  eoprds  ets  darv  Kara^aivetv,  d\\'  aipeiaOai  fiiveiv  iirl  tois 
idiots  dyadois  /^iSXXoc  rj  tQv  koivQv  aTrdXaveiv.  Of  course  it  is  quite  clear  that 
all  the  Athenian  country  folk  did  not  come  to  join  in  the  urban  celebrations 
of  the  festivals  of  Dionysus ;  many  of  them  necessarily  stayed  at  home ;  but 
while  the  orator  puts  down  this  fact  as  a  proof  that  they  were  comfortably  off 
there,  he  admits  by  implication  that  the  attractions  of  these  festivals  were  felt 
throughout  the  whole  of  Attica,  and  that  a  large  part  of  the  rural  population 
came  to  see  them. 


INTRODUCTION  7 

probably  in  the  majority,  they  impressed  these  views  on  the 
poets  and  on  the  judges. 

They  adored  the  tragedies  of  Aeschylus,  who  told  them  of 
the  gods  and  heroes  in  noble  language ;  and  if,  by  chance, 
they  did  not  always  exactly  grasp  his  meaning,  the  sound  of 
the  words  and  the  loftiness  of  the  sentiments  sufficed  to  move 
them  profoundly.^  Sophocles  also  delighted  them  ;  they  loved 
the  noble  pathos  of  his  dramas,  the  glowing  beauty  of  his  lyric 
songs,  the  strength  of  his  characters,  and  the  god  invisible,  but 
present,  behind  the  human  tragedy."  On  the  other  hand, 
they  gave  a  cold  welcome  to  the  writings  of  Euripides,  in 
which  there  was  too  much  subtle  rhetoric  to  suit  them,  and 
besides  a  disquieting  predominance  of  uncontrolled  impulse 
that  upset  the  robust  simplicity  of  their  morals. 

But  comedy  delighted  them  even  more  perhaps  than 
tragedy,  because  it  was  their  true  spokesman.  It  was  the 
style  in  which  ancient  Attica,  in  its  joyous  rusticity,  found 
amplest  expression.  The  country,  simple  and  contemptuous, 
used  it  to  take  revenge  on  the  city  and  on  those  whom  the 
city  admired.  To  please  them,  the  clever  poets  caricatured, 
on  the  stage,  the  men  of  the  day — shrewd  and  selfish  politicians, 
subtle  philosophers,  full  of  revolutionary  theories,  infatuated 
sophists,  fashionable  authors,  musical  composers  of  the  new 
school,  with  all  their  notions, — in  a  word,  all  those  who  were 
the  pets  of  the  city  folk,  but  who  appeared  prodigiously 
grotesque  to  these  honest  peasants  of  Athmone  or  of  Chollidae. 
The  country  folk  knew  no  greater  pleasure  than  to  overwhelm 
them  with  their  shouts  of  revengeful  derision. 


II 

This  tacit  alliance  between  the  rural  democracy  and  comedy 
would  doubtless  appear  much  more  clearly,  did  we  still  possess 
a  number  of  plays  that  were  performed  in  Athens  in  the  first 
two-thirds  of  the  fifth  century.      It  is,  in  fact,  quite  probable 

1  Aristophanes,  Achamiana,  1.  10 ;  Clouds,  11.  1364-1368 ;  cf.  Froys,  1.  1413. 
'^Aristophanes,  Peace,  1.  531. 


8  INTRODUCTION 

that  the  peasant,  who  was  the  original  actor  and  the  official 
choreutes  of  comedy,  must  have  continued  to  play  an  important 
part  in  the  plays  of  Chionides  and  Ecphantides,  of  Magnes 
and  Cratinus,  of  Crates  and  Hermippus.  Unfortunately  all 
these  plays  are  lost,  and  what  little  we  know  of  them  does 
not  lend  itself  to  conjectures  of  sufficient  probability.  It  is 
therefore  better  to  limit  ourselves  to  Aristophanes,  the  only 
comic  poet  of  whom  we  can  speak  with  knowledge. 

It  is  impossible,  in  our  day,  in  view  of  contradictory  and 
untrustworthy  evidence,  to  determine  whether  or  not  he  was 
the  son  of  an  Athenian  father  and  an  Athenian  mother.  This 
was  the  condition  indispensable  to  bearing  the  title  of  citizen, 
by  right  of  birth.  An  anonymous  biographer  does  indeed  tell 
us  that  he  belonged  to  the  deme  of  Cydathenaeon,  and  was 
of  the  tribe  Pandionis.^  This  is  a  definite  statement  that 
must  be  based  on  official  documents,  and  must  therefore  be 
regarded  as  authentic.^  But  it  does  not  help  us  decide  the 
question  how  Aristophanes  acquired  the  rights  of  citizenship. 
Was  he,  as  other  traditions  assert,  of  alien  birth,  and  were  the 
rights  of  citizenship  conferred  upon  his  father,  or  upon  him, 
by  a  decree  of  naturalization,  as  one  of  his  biographers 
affirms  ?  ^  We  do  not  know,  and  the  various  theories  of 
modern  scholars  have  not  succeeded  in  harmonizing  these 
divergent  views.  The  same  may  be  said  of  the  poet's 
relations  to  Aegina,  for  the  evidence  bearing  on  that  ques- 
tion, found  in  the  Aeharnians,  has  been  variously  inter- 
preted.*      However    the    matter    may    have    stood,    we    are 


7.  anon.  Didot,  xi.  lines  1  and  3 ;  cf.  xv. 

^Kaibel,  art.  "Aristophanes,"  No.  12,  p.  971,  in  Pauly-Wissowa. 

^  Biofjr.  anon.  Didot,  xi.  lines  30-35  ;  cf .  xiv. 

*  Aeharnians,  11.  651-653.  Some  commentators  claim  that  this  passage 
refers,  not  to  Aristophanes,  but  to  Callistratus,  under  whose  name  the  play 
was  performed.  This  seems  to  me  to  be  inadmissible.  The  true  author  was 
certainly  known  to  the  majority  of  the  audience,  and  it  is  altogether  impro- 
bable that  Aristophanes  should  have  given  to  the  man,  who  allowed  him  to 
use  his  name,  the  role  and  the  importance  wliich  these  verses  attribute  to 
him.  It  is  Aristophanes  who  speaks  here,  and  what  he  says  can  only  be 
said  about  himself.  Thus  there  is  reason  to  believe  that  Aristophanes  had 
received  an  allotment  of  land  at  Aegina,   as  a  colonist   (kX»;poOxos),   at  the 


INTRODUCTION  9 

almost  sure  that,  at  the  time  when  Aristophanes  made  his 
appearance  as  a  comic  poet,  he  was  considered  an  Athenian 
citizen  and  was  entered  on  the  register  of  the  deme  Cyda- 
t?ienaeon. 

This  deme  was  one  of  the  subdivisions  of  Athens,  but  it  is 
well  known  that  registry  in  a  deme  did  not  imply  residence 
there.^  Certain  indications,  found  in  Aristophanes'  own  plays, 
preclude  all  doubt  that,  in  his  childhood  at  least,  he  lived 
much  in  the  country,  among  the  peasants  of  Attica.  His 
father,  Philippus,  must  have  been  one  of  those  hard-working, 
small  landowners  who,  with  the  help  of  a  few  slaves,  culti- 
vated their  farms,  planted  with  vines  and  olive-trees,  in  the 
environs  of  Athens.  It  was  men  of  this  class  that  the  poet 
liked  to  put  upon  the  stage,  under  the  guise  of  a  Dicaeopolis, 
a  Strepsiades  or  a  Trygaeus ;  of  them  he  constituted  his 
chorus  in  the  Feace,  and  in  the  Lohoiirers.  It  is  evident  that, 
especially  in  the  early  part  of  his  life,  he  had  a  predilection 
for  them.  His  comedies  are  full  of  allusions  to  their  customs, 
their  work  and  their  pastimes,  and  these  allusions  are  so 
concise,  so  varied,  and  portray  so  vividly  conditions  as  they 
actually  were,  that  they  certainly  seem  to  imply  a  personal 
knowledge  of  the  things  portrayed.  One  feels  that  the  poet 
must,  from  childhood,  have  seen  the  peasant  in  his  home, 
sitting  in  the  inglenook  in  winter,  before  his  house  in 
summer,  near  the  bubbling  brooks  and  the  well,  encircled  by 
violets.  He  is  well  posted  about  the  ways  of  the  country,  the 
cultivation  of  the  fields  and  of  the  gardens — about  everything 
that  the  husbandman  hopes  or  fears  from  fair  or  foul  weather. 

time  of  the  expulsion  of  the  Aeginetans  in  431.  His  age  is  not  an  obstacle, 
because  we  neither  know  exactly  how  old  he  was  in  431,  nor  whether  law  or 
usage  forbade  the  allotment  of  land  to  a  minor.  As  for  the  legal  quibble 
of  Miiller-Striibing  {Aristophanes,  p.  607),  it  seems  to  me  to  be  quite  without 
value.  Aristophanes  is  joking ;  it  is  puerile  to  discuss  his  words  as  one 
would  a  legal  document.  Aristophanes  is  cited  as  a  K\r]povxos  of  Aegina  by 
Theogenes  in  his  work  irepl  Aiylvris  (Schol.  Plato,  Apolocjia,  19  c). 

^  Alcibiades,  who  belonged  to  the  deme  Scambonidae,  had  his  estate  in  the 
deme  Erchia  (Ps.  Plato,  Alcih.  maj.  p.  123  C).  The  Kk-qpovxoi  continued  to 
be  regarded  as  members  of  their  deme  (Schoemann-Lipsius,  Griech.  Alter- 
thumtr,  ii.  p.  100). 


10  INTRODUCTION 

He  knows  the  names  of  trees,  of  plants  and  tools,  of  the  birds 
that  hide  in  the  hedges  or  that  fly  over  the  fields.  He  also 
knows  the  season  when  the  grapes  swell  and  turn  golden,  earlier 
or  later,  according  to  their  variety  and  to  changes  of  tempera- 
ture.^ Not  only  does  he  know  all  these  things,  but  we  feel  that 
he  has  a  liking  for  them  and  loves  to  speak  of  them ;  he  is 
imbued  with  a  lively  appreciation  of  nature,  which  is  not  the 
dream  of  a  tired  city  man,  but  seems  to  be  made  up  of 
personal  memories  and  impressions.  How  can  we  avoid 
drawing  the  conclusion  that  the  future  poet  must  have  lived 
a  rustic  life  at  the  age  when  we  observe  everything,  and 
when  those  keen  impressions  are  gathered  that  determine  the 
turn  our  imagination  is  to  take  ? 

Thus,  everything  tends  to  make  us  believe  that  this  pre- 
dilection for  the  rural  democracy  must  have  been  due,  in  the 
first  instance,  not  to  study  nor  to  influences  met  with  at  the 
beginning  of  his  career  as  a  poet,  but  to  the  very  circumstance 
of  his  birth.  He  loved  it  because  he  was  one  of  its  sons, 
because  he  had  seen  it  with  his  own  eyes  and  felt,  in  his  own 
heart,  all  its  virtues. 

But  here  we  must  take  note  of  the  fact  that  this  rural 
democracy  never  constituted  an  organized  political  party  in  the 
Athenian  state,  and  that,  as  a  consequence  of  not  having  a 
programme  of  reform,  it  could  not  supply  one  to  the  poets 
who  voiced  its  views.  At  no  time  during  the  fifth  century  do 
we  see  it  appoint  a  leader  or  take  a  part  in  public  affairs  as  a 
separate  and  disciplined  power.  As  a  rule  it  held  aloof.  When 
it  did  take  action,  it  was  in  the  nature  of  support,  by  offering 
its  co-operation  to  the  factions  which,  in  a  given  case,  best 
represented  its  views.  But  it  did  so  only  when  there  existed 
urgent  reasons  to  persuade  it  to  shake  off  its  natural  in- 
difference. 

Aristophanes,  like  the  other  comic  poets  of  the  time,  could, 
at  best,  only  have  borrowed  from  the  rural  democracy  some 
vague  suggestions,  or  rather  some  instinctive  tendencies,  which 
he  put  into  preciser  formulae  of  his  own  accord  and  on  his 

^Acharnians,  11.  32-.36,  241-279,  872  et  seq.  ;  Clouds,  43-50;  Peace,  535-538, 
556-600,  1000-1006,  1128-1170;  Birds,  227-304,  576  et  seq. 


INTRODUCTION  11 

own  responsibility.  In  order  properly  to  appreciate  this  per- 
sonal element  in  his  work,  we  must  make  a  study  of  his  city 
education  and  of  his  relations  to  the  political  parties  which  at 
that  time  played  a  role  in  public  life. 


Ill 

It  was  from  about  431  to  427,  that  is  to  say  in  the  first 
years  of  the  Peloponnesian  war,  that  he  got  the  special  training 
without  which  no  comic  poet  of  that  time  could  get  on. 

It  was  in  427  that  he  made  his  first  appearance  as  an 
author — still  a  very  young  man — and  his  first  play  appears  to 
have  won  at  least  the  approbation  and  encouragement  of  some 
good  judges.^  Moreover,  it  would  not  even  have  been  admitted 
to  the  competition,  had  it  been  the  work  of  a  wholly  inexperi- 
enced beginner.  Even  at  this  time,  then,  Aristophanes  knew 
much  about  his  calling;  and  this  proves  beyond  doubt  that, 
for  some  time  previous,  he  must  have  moved  in  circles  in  which 
a  man  could  gain  this  knowledge. 

What  circles  were  these  ?  They  were  certainly  not  to  be 
found  in  the  rustic  surroundings  of  which  we  have  been 
speaking,  and  among  which  his  childhood  was  doubtless  spent. 
Comedy  had  at  this  time  become  a  very  complex  work  of  art, 
which  had  its  traditional  forms  and  regular  devices.  Even  its 
flights  of  imagination  were  bounded  by  certain  conventions. 
Besides  the  versified  text,  it  contained  songs,  dances,  changing 
scenes,  a  complete  equipment  of  masks  and  of  stage-settings. 
However  great  his  genius,  Aristophanes  could  not  have  become 
thoroughly  acquainted  with  these  observances  of  his  art  with- 
out associating  with  people  who  had  the  necessary  experience, 
and  without  apprenticing  himself  to  them. 

Now,  it  is  not  doubtful  that  there  existed,  at  this  time, 
regular  specialists  in  comedy :  on  the  one  hand,  those  who 
were  at  once  poets  and  actors ;  on  the  other,  those  who  were 
merely  actors.  Still  others  were  singers,  dancers,  costumers, 
impressarios  and  organizers  of  shows.     In  a  word,  there  was  a 

1  CloMs,  1.  528. 


12  INTRODUCTION 

whole  company  of  low  comedians  and  Thespians,  who  mutually 
supported  one  another  with  their  varied  talents,  and  through 
whose  unceasing  collaboration  comedy  had,  notwithstanding  its 
medley  of  paradoxes,  gradually  become  the  truly  harmonious 
work  of  art  that  we  still  admire  in  the  extant  texts.  In  a 
town  like  Athens,  these  people,  who  had  the  same  tastes  and 
followed  the  same  profession,  must  of  course  have  met  and 
known  one  another,  either  as  friends  and  collaborators,  as 
teachers  and  pupils,  or  as  rivals  and  enemies.  Our  very 
scant  knowledge  of  these  friendships  and  enmities  is 
gleaned  from  a  few  allusions  of  Aristophanes,  and  from  the 
notes  of  ancient  commentators  who  explained  them,  often 
without  themselves  fully  understanding  what  they  meant,  and 
who  tried  to  guess  what  they  did  not  know.  From  lack  of 
letters,  memoirs  and  detailed  bibliographies,  these  under- 
currents of  the  literary  life  of  Athens  are,  as  a  general  rule, 
beyond  our  ken.  That  is  no  reason  why  we  should  underrate 
the  importance  which  they  had  in  Aristophanes'  mental  and 
moral  make-up. 

This  world  of  comedians  was  by  no  means  shunned  by  the 
best  Athenian  society — the  most  open-hearted,  most  variously 
constituted  and  most  liberal  society  that  has  ever  existed. 

There  is  precious  evidence  on  this  subject  in  Xenophon  and 
in  Plato.  Xenophon's  Symposium  is  supposed  to  have  taken 
place  in  421,  in  the  house  of  the  wealthy  Callias,  son  of 
Hipponicus,  that  is  to  say  in  the  house  of  a  member  of  one  of 
the  great  and  rich  Athenian  families.  In  it  we  meet  all 
sorts  of  people,  rich  and  poor,  philosophers  and  ignoramuses. 
Seated  at  the  same  table,  they  converse  familiarly ;  a  pro- 
fessional buffoon  comes  without  being  invited,  but  is  generously 
admitted  and  joins  in  their  conversation.  Even  a  Syracusan 
mime,  called  in  to  give  a  lewd  performance,  begins  chatting 
with  the  banqueters,  gives  his  views  on  the  subject  under 
discussion,  and  finally  is  so  bold  as  to  make  very  unfitting 
pleasantries  at  Socrates'  expense,  but  is  neither  thrown  out  nor 
even  called  to  order.  Here  we  have  equality  and  liberty 
carried  to  a  point  which  it  is  hard  for  us  to  understand. 

The  Memorabilia   and  the   Oeconomicus  show  us  the  same 


INTRODUCTION  13 

customs.  In  them  Socrates  talks  to  whomsoever  he  chooses, 
questions,  discusses,  makes  himself  heard  in  all  places.  His 
manner  of  life,  as  it  is  there  pictured  to  us,  would  have  been 
impossible  in  any  other  surroundings. 

Plato  presents  the  same  picture.  The  Athens  that  he  shows 
us  is  a  sort  of  talking  place,  where  everybody  is  supposed 
to  know  everybody  else,  and  where  each  person  has  a  perfect 
right  to  make  acquaintance  with  those  he  meets.  His  Sym- 
posium, in  particular,  the  portrayal  of  a  more  or  less  imaginary 
reunion  held  at  the  house  of  Agathon  in  416,  is  of  quite 
special  interest,  because  it  lets  us  see  Aristophanes  himself  in 
an  Athenian  social  gathering.  Though,  it  is  true,  we  do  not 
know  the  standing  of  all  the  guests,  we  do  here  discover  the 
same  intermixture  of  classes  and  professions — and  Aristophanes 
is  by  no  means  represented  as  belonging  to  an  inferior  rank. 

Thus,  we  can  be  sure  that  he  was  not  at  all  isolated  nor 
limited  to  a  particular  circle,  either  at  the  beginning  of  his 
career  or  in  later  life.  From  youth  on,  he  certainly  lived  in 
Athens,  at  the  centre  of  intellectual  life,  enjoying  perfect 
freedom  of  speech  and  unhampered  exchange  of  views.  This 
is  not  the  place  to  enlarge  on  the  influence  that  city  life,  with 
its  effervescence  and  its  constant  changes,  had  on  his  art.  No 
reader  of  Aristophanes  can  help  feeling,  in  every  page  of  his 
plays,  what  he  owed  to  the  streets,  the  agora,  the  harbor,  to 
chance  encounter  and  to  social  gatherings.  All  that  there  is  of 
actual  life  in  his  comedies  hails  from  there,  and  even  his  fancy, 
in  large  measure,  draws  its  inspiration  thence.  But  at  present 
we  are  intent  only  upon  his  connection  with  political  parties, 
and  it  is  from  this  point  of  view  only  that  we  wish  to  consider 
his  contact  with  society  in  the  city. 

The  Athenians,  critical  and  acute  by  nature,  were  bound 
to  discover  the  hidden  meaning  of  things,  to  invent  novel 
explanations,  to  impute  secret  motives  to  men  who  were  active 
in  politics.  A  man  acquired  a  reputation  for  cleverness  and  far- 
sightedness only  by  outdoing  his  fellows  in  matters  of  this  sort. 
And  it  was  not  the  avowed  enemies  of  the  constitution  nor 
the  open  adversaries  of  the  popular  leaders  who  took  the 
greatest  delight  in  these  insinuations.     The  oligarchical  party, 

c 


14  INTRODUCTION 

properly  speaking,  counted  among  its  members  theorists  and 
statesmen,  who  met  doctrine  with  doctrine  and  policy  with 
policy.  But  these  personal  slanders  and  invidious  explanations 
did  not  come  from  them  in  particular  ;  they  originated  in 
daily  gossip  at  the  clubs,  without  difference  of  party.  It  was 
from  this  source  that  a  number  of  accusations  sprang  that 
were  lodged  against  Pericles  and  his  friends,  and  that  circulated 
and  gained  strength  especially  from  443  on,  when,  after  the 
exile  of  Thucydides,  son  of  Melesias,  Pericles  was  no  longer 
confronted  by  an  organized  opposition.  At  that  time  people 
began  to  say  that  the  statesman  obeyed  the  caprices  of  Aspasia, 
even  that  the  fair  woman  from  Miletus  wrote  his  speeches  for 
him.  One  spoke  of  Phidias'  misappropriation  of  funds,  com- 
mitted with  his  knowledge ;  another  held  him  responsible  for 
the  bold  theories  of  Anaxagoras ;  and  when  he  made  war  on 
Sparta,  the  report  was  spread  that  he  had  done  so  in  order  to 
conceal  his  fallen  fortunes  and  to  escape  certain  condemnation.-^ 
True  or  false,  or  even  true  and  false  at  once,  we  see  that 
this  talk  passed  from  mouth  to  mouth — that  it  was  generally 
believed,  and  that,  in  the  end,  it  had  grave  consequences. 

Comedy  in  general,  and  that  of  Aristophanes  in  particular, 
battened  on  it  by  preference,  but  this  fact  does  not  warrant 
our  considering  comedy  as  the  recognized  mouthpiece  of  an 
anti-constitutional  opposition.  Living  on  satire,  it  merely 
repeated,  on  the  stage,  what  was  constantly  being  said 
throughout  the  city.  True,  by  thus  repeating  this  gossip, 
comedy  lent  it  much  added  force  and  authority,  so  that,  in 
some  instances,  it  imposed  it  on  history.  It  is  the  privilege 
of  true  works  of  art  to  perpetuate  whatever  they  have  once 
held  up  to  our  gaze ;  but  the  elements  which  they  appropriate 
and  immortalize  were  originally  very  far  from  having  the 
importance  imputed  to  them,  later  on,  on  account  of  these  works 
of  art. 

^Plutarch,  Pericles,  c.  xiii.  Plutarch  traced  these  slanders  to  the  comic 
poets,  but  he  fully  understood  that  they,  in  turn,  had  gathered  them  from 
daily  gossip :  de^d/xtvoi  d^  rov  \6yov  ol  kw/j.ikoI  troWrjv  acriXyeiai'  airov  Kareun^daaav. 


INTRODUCTION  15 


IV 

We  must  not,  however,  ignore  the  fact  that,  when  Aristo- 
phanes wrote  his  first  comedies,  there  existed  at  Athens  an 
oligarchical  faction,  which  detested  democracy;  that  this  faction 
counted  among  its  adherents  men  who  were  distinguished  in 
society ;  that  our  poet  may  have  known  them,  have  heard 
them  speak  and  have  adopted  at  least  some  of  their  views, 
and  that  he  may  have  had  friends  and  patrons  among  them. 
There  is,  therefore,  good  reason  for  examining  his  relations 
with  them  as  closely  as  we  can  at  this  late  date.^ 

The  Athenian  aristocracy  constituted,  for  a  considerable 
time  after  the  Persian  wars,  an  organized  party,  of  which 
Cimon,  the  son  of  Miltiades,  was  the  principal  leader.  This 
party  accepted  the  democracy  of  Solon  and  of  Cleisthenes, 
but  it  brought  its  own  traditions  into  the  management  of 
public  affairs,  and  endeavored  to  make  a  conservative  policy 
prevail. 

We  know  how  it  was  defeated  by  the  democratic  reforms  of 
Ephialtes  and  of  Pericles,  by  the  curtailing  of  the  powers  of 
the  Areopagus  and  by  the  exile  of  Cimon.^  Notwithstanding 
all  this,  it  seems  to  have  regained  strength  in  the  years 
following  the  death  of  Cimon — between  449  and  443.  This 
was  the  time  of  those  memorable  debates  on  the  rostrum 
between  Pericles,  the  undisputed  leader  of  the  popular  party, 
and  Thucydides,  the  son  of  Melesias,  the  chief  orator  of  the 
opposition,  of  which  Plutarch  has  preserved  us  a  record. 
'<These  contests  ended,  in  the  year  443-442,  in  the  triumph 
of  Pericles,  who  secured  a  sentence  of  ostracism  against  his 
adversary.^ 

^Augusts  Couat,  Ariatophane  et  Vancienne  Com6die  attique,  has  sought  to 
prove  that  the  comic  poets  at  Athens  were  really  the  clients,  if  not  indeed 
the  parasites,  of  the  aristocracy,  who,  according  to  him,  held  them  in  a 
position  of  complete  dependence.  It  is  on  this  point  chiefly  that  I  disagree 
with  him. 

-Aristotle,  Constitution  of  Athens,  cc.  xxiii.-xxvi. 

'  Ed.  Meyer,  Oeschichte  des  Alterthums,  iv.  pp.  407-409. 


16  INTRODUCTION 

/The  aristocratic  party  was  for  a  long  time  disorganized  by 
this  occurrence.^  Neither  during  the  last  years  of  Pericles' 
government,  nor  even  after  his  death,  when  the  ship  of  state 
was  guided  by  men  who  were  greatly  his  inferiors,  did  it  again 
succeed  in  figuring  in  public  debate.  Nicias,  who  sometimes 
voiced  its  ideas  on  the  rostrum,  was,  properly  speaking,  neither 
a  man  of  affairs  nor  a  leader.  In  point  of  fact,  the  latent 
power  of  the  party  was  then  concentrated  in  a  few  men,  who 
held  aloof  and  bided  their  time.  The  orator  Antiphon  may 
be  mentioned  as  the  best-known  among  them. 

From  time  to  time  there  issued  from  this  circle  some 
trenchant  pamphlet,  in  which  the  party's  views  were  expressed 
with  the  somewhat  dry  rigor  which  at  that  time  was  charac- 
teristic of  Attic  prose.  We  possess  a  remarkable  example  in 
The  Polity  of  the  Athenians,  erroneously  attributed  to  Xeno- 
phon.  The  author  is  a  haughty  and  uncompromising  aristocrat, 
who  sets  out  to  destroy  by  his  pitiless  logic  what  he  considers 
to  be  the  illusions  of  the  moderate  wing  of  his  party.  He 
most  emphatically  opposes  those  who  assumed  that  the 
Athenian  democracy  could  be  reformed.  With  imperturbable 
calmness,  he  demonstrates  that  it  merely  follows  its  natural 
laws,  that  it  is  what  it  ought  to  be — what  force  of  cir- 
cumstances demands  it  should  be — and  that  it  cannot  be 
other  than  it  is.  This  is  the  hardest,  the  most  inflexible, 
the  most  insolent  piece  of  reasoning  that  has  ever  been  put 
on  paper.^ 

It  is  very  hard  to  believe  that  Aristophanes  should  have 
been  able  to  gain  and  to  enjoy  the  intimacy  of  such  people. 
His  playful  temper,  his  exuberant  fancy,  his  droll  sallies,  could 
not  have  suited  these  theorists,  nor  was  their  doctrinaire 
gravity  of  a  kind  to  delight  this  young  poet,  so  full  of 
sparkling  and  capricious  spirit.  Furthermore,  when  one  takes 
the  trouble  to  compare  the  few  ideas,  or  outlines  of  ideas, 
which  constitute  the  entire  political  doctrine  of  his  plays,  with 
such  oligarchical  theories  as  we  can  in  part  reconstruct,  one 

1  Plutarch,  Pericles,  c.  xiv, 

*We  shall  revert  to  this  work  in  greater  detail,  in  connection  with  the 
Knights,  in  chapter  ii. 


INTRODUCTION  17 

soon  perceives  that  these  ideas  and  theories  differ  considerably 
from  one  another.     This  comparison  must  be  made  for  each 
play  separately,  and  must   be  reinforced  by  quotations ;  but 
the  general  result  may  be  put  down  here.     Here  and  there  an     u^e*'i*- 
indirect  influence,  exerted  by  some  of  these  theories  on   the    -  om9* 
thought  of  our  poet,  is  undoubtedly  to  be  found ;   but  invari-    •'        ^  -i^ 
ably  these  theories,  scattered  through  his  plays,  appear  very 
noticeably  modified,  not   only  in    form — which  goes   without 
saying — but  even  in  spirit. 

In  fact,  if,  as  is  likely,  Aristophanes  held  close  relations 
with  a  number  of  members  of  the  Athenian  aristocracy,  it  was 
certainly  not  with  these  theorists,  and  we  must  by  no  means 
imagine  him  as  receiving  commands  from  the  leaders  of  their 
party,  or  as  their  chosen  official  spokesman.  Comedy  had 
nothing  to  do  with  plots ;  and  we  can  unhesitatingly  declare 
that  it  never  joined  forces  with  the  revolutionary  associations 
(eraipiai). 

"We  must  not  forget,  however,  that  this  aristocracy,  together 
with  its  foremost  spirits,  or  rather  under  their  lead,  included 
a  large  number  of  people  of  very  different  turn  of  mind ; 
and  foremost  among  these,  many  cheerful  young  men,  fond  of 
pleasure  and  noisy  gatherings,  and  ready  to  give  a  warm 
welcome  to  those  who  afforded  them  entertainment.  It  was 
just  this  youthful  company  that  Aristophanes,  himself  young, 
overflowing  with  gaiety  and,  no  doubt,  free  in  his  morals  and 
speech,  must  chiefly  have  sought ;  they  are  the  people  he  has 
put  on  the  stage  in  his  Knights.  Whatever  views  on  politics 
are  expressed  in  his  comedies,  are  due  much  more  to  their 
conversation  than  to  the  theories  above  referred  to.  And  if 
these  theories  are  nevertheless  to  some  extent  reflected  in  his 
plays,  it  is  because  these  young  men,  in  the  course  of  their 
heated,  ill-regulated  and  indiscreet  talk,  cannot  have  avoided 
occasionally  repeating  to  one  another  what  they  had  heard 
from  the  serious  persons  who  were  their  masters  and  teachers. 
They  repeated  these  views  with  the  vivaciousness,  the  para- 
doxical exaggeration  and  the  extravagant  fancies  of  youth. 
They  derived  from  them  a  thousand  taunts  against  the  leaders 
of  the  people,  against  the  democratic  politicians ;  and  this  bit 


18  INTRODUCTION 

of  theory  gave  support  to  their  hostile  gossip  and  to  their 
satirical  personal  attacks.  It  is  only  fair  to  assume  that  they 
did  not  sound  the  depths  of  these  theories,  but  rather  that 
they  delighted  in  all  invidious  reports,  scandalous  stories,  and 
in  the  whole  range  of  occurrences,  true  or  false,  that  made 
their  adversaries  ridiculous  or  deserving  of  hatred.  ;  This  was 
the  hearth  on  which  the  burning  flame  of  comedy  found  its 
fuel.  It  was  from  this  fire,  incessantly  fanned  by  Attic  wit, 
that  those  sparks  shot  forth  plentifully  which  we  still  see 
scintillating  in  the  comedies  of  Aristophanes. 

At  the  same  time,  the  deduction  is  not  warranted  that 
Aristophanes  was  the  docile  mouthpiece  of  this  youthful 
band.  His  untrammelled  nature  rebelled  against  subserviency, 
perhaps  even  more  on  account  of  the  spontaneity  of  his 
imagination  and  spirit  than  because  of  his  independence  of 
character.  Moreover,  the  suggestions  he  received  in  aristo- 
cratic circles  were  assimilated  in  his  mind  with  the  traditions 
and  instincts  of  the  rural  democracy,  which  was  discussed  above. 
We  may  be  sure  that  from  such  a  process  no  stable,  well- 
considered  and  definitive  combination  can  have  resulted,  but 
rather  an  unstable  medley,  very  original  and  very  personal, 
subject  not  only  to  the  influence  of  passing  events  and  of 
changing  moods,  but  also  to  that  peculiar  power  of  dramatic 
creations,  which  occasionally  gain  the  mastery  over  their  own 
creators  and  insensibly  lead  on  the  poet,  just  when  he  seems 
to  be  very  wisely  guiding  them. 

Did  Aristophanes  have  any  patrons  at  all,  in  the  real  sense 
of  the  word,  among  his  friends  in  the  best  Athenian  society  ? 
We  may  as  well  admit  that  we  know  nothing  about  it,  and 
that,  on  this  point,  there  is  a  regrettable  blank  in  our  informa- 
tion. In  a  general  way  it  would  seem  not  at  all  improbable 
that  the  comic  poets  at  Athens  should,  at  the  beginning  of 
their  career,  have  tried  to  secure  patronage  among  the  persons 
who  were  capable  of  giving  them  aid.  They  may  have  needed 
it  either  to  secure  a  recommendation  to  the  archon  who  supplied 
the  comic  chorus,  or  in  order  to  guarantee  themselves  against 
the  disagreeable  consequences  which  too  bold  a  satire  was 
always  in  danger  of  bringing  upon  them.     In  his  young  days 


INTRODUCTION  19 

Cratinus  appears  to  have  sought  the  patronage  of  Cimon.^ 
Telecleides,  at  a  later  time,  represented  himself  as  the  friend 
of  Nicias.-  As  far  as  Aristophanes  is  concerned,  there  is 
nothing  to  indicate  that  he  was  the  client  of  any  known 
person,  but  he  may  very  well  have  had  a  patron  without 
our  knowing  it.  The  question  must  be  raised,  although  there 
is  no  means  to-day  of  solving  it.^ 


As  opposed  to  the  aristocratic  faction,  which  was  vaguely 
defined  and  liable  to  change  in  its  organization,  the  democracy 
did  not  properly  constitute  a  "  political  party."  It  was  the 
state  itself,  the  entire  body  of  citizens ;  but,  as  we  have  already 
said,  there  existed  in  this  democracy  groups  with  different 
tendencies  and  of  different  character,  which,  without  centraliza- 
tion and  without  organization,  in  turn  exerted  a  more  or  less 
powerful  influence  on  the  public  actions  of  the  city. 

This  state  of  affairs  was  favorable  to  ambitious  men  who 
knew  how  to  gain  the  goodwill  of  the  masses.  A  regular, 
organized  party  presupposes  a  certain  amount  of  discipline. 
Now,  all  discipline  holds  in  check,  at  least  in  a  measure,  the 
free  play  of  eager  individuals  who  would  encroach  upon  it. 
But  in  dealing  with  a  disintegrated  and  so  to  speak  inorganic 
throng,  anybody,  if  he  possessed  clear  intelligence,  a  degree  of 

'Cratinus,  The  Archilochians,  fragment  1,  Kock. 

^Telecleides,  fragment  41,  Kock. 

^G.  Gilbert,  Beitrdge,  p.  74,  likewise  considers  comedy  at  the  time  of  the 
Peloponnesian  war  as  the  "  organ  of  a  party,"  the  party  of  the  great  and  rich 
families  who  kept  it  under  obligations  by  the  fact  that  they  furnished  the 
choruses.  It  already  appears,  after  what  has  been  said,  and  it  will  appear 
more  clearly  later  on,  wherein  my  point  of  view  differs  from  his,  which  is  not 
entirely  incorrect,  but  seems  to  me  to  lack  the  finer  distinctions.  The  learned 
historian  forgets  that  the  leaders  of  the  democratic  party,  Pericles,  for 
example,  and  certainly  many  others  as  well,  had  charge  of  equipping  choruses, 
and  yet  we  cannot  put  our  finger  on  a  line  in  the  comedies  that  would  appear 
to  be  favorable  to  them.  Moreover,  the  choice  of  the  plays  rested  with  the 
archon,  and  not  with  the  choregi. 


20  INTRODUCTION 

boldness,  some  power  or  skill  in  speech,  and  few  scruples  into 
the  bargain,  could  become  a  great  man  in  a  day.  It  was 
merely  a  question  of  grasping  an  opportunity,  of  striking  an 
unexpected  blow,  of  suddenly  securing  attention  and  favor. 
And  Athens,  at  the  time  of  the  Peloponnesian  war,  became  a 
theatre  of  action  exceptionally  suited  to  politicians. 

It  was  among  them  that  was  found  the  man  upon  whom 
Aristophanes,  during  the  first  part  of  his  career  as  a  dramatist, 
made  the  most  incessant  war — Cleon,  the  son  of  Cleaenetus. 
He  is  the  best-known  of  the  demagogues  of  this  time.  His 
career  furnishes  the  means  by  which  one  may  most  readily 
explain  and  sum  up  what  Aristophanes  thought  of  politicians 
during  the  early  years  of  his  career.^ 

By  birth  Cleon  belonged  to  that  city  democracy  whose 
character  we  have  described  above.  His  father  appears  to 
have  been  successful  in  business ;  we  are  told  that  he  was  a 
tanner,  which  no  doubt  means  that  he  had  one  or  more 
currier's  shops,  in  which  slaves  worked  for  his  profit.  His 
house,  therefore,  must  necessarily  have  had  commercial  rela- 
tions with  some  of  the  principal  hide-markets  from  which  the 
Attic  industry  secured  its  supplies — for  example,  with  Gyrene 
and  southern  Italy.^  Manufacturers  such  as  he,  consequently, 
must  have  had  offices  and  warehouses  at  the  Piraeus,  and  have 
lived  in  touch  with  the  people  of  the  harbor.  These  are  the 
surroundings  in  which  the  young  Cleon  grew  up.  Moreover, 
there  is  no  doubt  that  he  received  the  education  common  among 
young  Athenians  belonging  to  families  possessed  of  comfortable 
means ;  but  his  nature  seems  to  have  been  hard,  hasty  and 
imperious,  and  he  was  a  stranger  to  that  light  grace  which  was 
characteristic  of  Attic  culture. 

According  to  the  testimony  of  Theopompus,  unreliably 
cited  by  a  scholiast,  he  desired  to  serve  among  the  Athenian 
knights,  but  met  with  an  unfriendly  reception  and  was  perhaps 

^In  Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.,  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  988,  note  3,  there  is  a  concise 
and  sufficiently  complete  resum^  of  the  principal  modern  articles  on  Cleon  and 
of  the  different  opinions  that  have  been  held  about  him.  However  some  traits 
of  his  character  do  not  seem  to  me  to  be  distinctly  stated. 

-  Ilermippus,  fragment  63,  11.  4  and  6,  Kock. 


INTRODUCTION  21 

rejected ;  at  any  rate  was  humiliated  by  the  snubbing  of  some 
aristocrat,  and  from  that  moment  threw  his  lot  in  with  the 
popular  party,  in  order  to  have  his  revenge.^  Nothing  is  more 
uncertain  than  this  story,  in  which  the  malicious  interpretation 
of  the  opposition  is  too  evident. 

We  do  know  that  he  entered  public  life  toward  the  end  of 
Pericles'  life.  At  that  time  he  appeared  among  those  who  daily 
harassed  and  denounced  the  aged  statesman — a  bitter  and 
untiring  opposition  that  drew  together  men  of  diverse  views. 
As  for  Cleon,  a  democrat  by  birth,  he  espoused  the  suspicions, 
the  hatreds  and  the  jealousies  of  the  advanced  democracy. 
Plutarch  tells  us  that,  helped  by  the  discontent  which  at  that 
time  was  troubling  the  masses,  "  he  advanced  step  by  step  to 
the  possession  of  power."  ^  From  431,  the  time  of  the  first 
invasion  of  Attica  by  the  Peloponnesians  under  the  Spartan 
king  Archidamus,  he  was  one  of  those  who  violently  attacked 
Pericles'  temporizing  policy,  and  in  430  the  poet  Hermippus 
could  say  that  the  latter  "  had  been  finely  bitten  by  the  mad 
Cleon."  ^  In  the  same  year,  430,  when  the  people,  in  a  fit  of 
anger,  gave  themselves  the  satisfaction  of  putting  their  leader 
on  trial  and  of  sentencing  him,  Cleon  was  perhaps  one  of  the 
accusers.*  In  fact,  it  was  in  bringing  charges  against  persons 
in  power  that  ambitious  young  men  evidenced  their  zeal  for 
the  public  good  and  recommended  themselves  to  the  favor  of 
the  people. 

1  Schol.  Knights,  225,  226. 

*  Plutarch,  Pericles,  c.  xxxiii. ,  probably  based  on  Ephorus.  Perhaps  he  had 
already  been  one  of  those  who  accused  Anaxagoras,  the  chief  accuser  being 
Thucydides,  son  of  Melesias  (Sotion,  in  Diogenes  Laertius,  ii.  3,  12).  The 
evidence  is  not  very  trustworthy,  but  the  arguments  against  it  are  weak. 
Ed.  Meyer,  Geschichte  des  Alterthums,  iv.  §531,  note. 

^  Hermippus,  fragment  46,  Kock.     Cf.  Plutarch,  loc.  cit. 

^Plutarch,  Pericles,  c.  xxxv.  according  to  the  testimony  of  Idomeneus 
(Ed.  Meyer,  Geschichte  des  Alterthums,  iv.  §  556),  regards  this  testimony  as 
devoid  of  authority ;  Busolt,  Griechische  Geschichte,  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  953, 
note  5,  leans  to  the  same  opinion.  Idomeneus  is  certainly  a  doubtful  authority; 
at  the  same  time,  his  assertion  is  not  in  itself  improbable.  The  fact  that  Theo- 
phrastus  and  Heracleides  Pontius  name  other  accusers  (see  Busolt,  loc.  cit.), 
does  not  imply  a  contradiction. 


n  INTRODUCTION 

Pericles'  sentence,  shortly  followed  by  his  death  in  429, 
opened  the  door  to  second-rate  politicians.  Cleon  was  among 
those  who  made  a  headlong  rush  for  power.-^ 

He  seems  to  have  been  endowed  with  certain  gifts  of 
oratory,  and  even  of  statesmanship,  which  came  to  the  aid  of 
his  shortcomings,  and  not  only  partly  hid  the  latter  from  view 
but  occasionally  even  rendered  them  agreeable  to  the  people — 
imperturbable  self-assurance,  a  powerful  voice  that  stirred  the 
masses,  effrontery  of  a  kind  that  scandalized  proper  folks  but 
did  not  displease  the  multitude.  His  very  clamors,  his 
violent  gestures,  the  insults  he  heaped  upon  his  opponents, — 
all  these  traits  combined  made  him  different  from  everybody 
else.  And  besides  he  had  a  clear  head  which  was  clever  at 
simplifying  things,  a  trenchant  logic  which  readily  made  its 
way  by  incontrovertible  deductions,  and  which  imposed  its 
conclusions  through  its  systematic  severity.  Thucydides  tells 
us  that  he  was  of  a  very  violent  disposition,  and  that  he  knew 
better  than  anyone  else  how  to  persuade  the  masses.^  Even 
his  persuasiveness  had  soriiething  violent  about  it.  It  sprang 
from  the  brutal  impulsiveness  of  his  method  of  arguing,  which 
clung  to  a  few  positive  ideas  and  brushed  aside  a  multitude 
of  considerations  at  which  deliberate  and  reflecting  minds 
halted.  He  had  the  actual  advantage  over  his  moderate  and 
diplomatic  adversaries  that  falls  to  the  lot  of  intransigent 
dogmatists,  when  they  address  a  public  which  has  no  decided 
views,  and  is,  besides,  enamored  of  ideas  that  appear  to  be 
clear.  He  understood  how  to  pick  out  from  among  the  con- 
fused views  of  the  masses  certain  principles  which  he  formu- 

^  The  scholiast  of  Lucian,  Timon,  30,  says  of  him :  6  5^  kX^uv  drifiaycoybs  ^v 
'Adrjvaluv,  irpocTTat  avTuiv  iirTo,  ^tt).  As  Cleon  died  in  422,  the  period  of  seven 
years  must  have  begun  in  429.  The  originator  of  this  surmise  must  have 
taken  the  death  of  Pericles  as  his  starting-point,  and  not,  as  Busolt  thinks 
(Griechische  Geschichte,  2nd  part,  p.  998,  note  1),  the  year  428-427,  in  which 
Cleon  is  supposed  to  have  entered  the  Senate.  After  a  lapse  of  time  Cleon 
must  have  appeared  as  the  immediate  successor  of  Pericles,  and  he  may  in  fact 
have  succeeded  him.  One  should  not  attach  too  much  importance  to  the 
"succession  of  the  three  merchants,"  which  has  been  so  meekl}^  accepted  on 
the  testimony  of  Aristophanes  (Knights,  129). 

2  Thucydides,  ii.  36. 


INTRODUCTION  23 

la  ted  ill  imperious  terms;  and  by  thus  expressing  them  he  gave 
substance  to  the  prevailing  passions,  whose  servant  he  made 
himself  in  order  to  rule  the  state.^ 

In  domestic  affairs,  his  policy  tended  to  destroy  what  little 
influence  the  upper  classes  still  retained.  Aristotle  passes  a 
very  expressive  judgment  on  him.  He  says :  "  It  is  he  who 
seems  to  have  done  most  to  corrupt  the  people  by  means  of 
their  own  instincts."  -  This  opinion  was,  no  doubt,  that  of 
Cleon's  adversaries ;  but  we  can  hardly  doubt  that,  upon  the 
whole,  it  is  a  fairly  just  one.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  the  history 
of  this  period  shows  that  during  this  time  democracy,  as  an 
institution,  changed  more  and  more,  through  the  development 
of  the  dangerous  instincts  which  it  harbored  in  itself.  And 
as  Cleon  was  at  this  time  the  statesman  to  whom  the  public 
lent  a  more  willing  ear  than  to  all  others,  it  is  certain  that  he 
contributed  largely  to  these  changes.  Moreover,  Thucydides 
says  the  same  thing  when  he  characterizes  the  politicians  who 
succeeded  Pericles :  he  calls  attention  to  the  fact  that  the 
latter  truly  led  the  people  instead  of  allowing  himself  to  be 
led  by  them.  "  On  the  contrary,"  he  adds,  "  as  those  who 
came  after  him  had  no  marked  superiority  to  distinguish  them, 
and  yet  were  anxious  to  surpass  one  another,  they  forced 
themselves  to  please  the  masses  and  allowed  them  to  manage 
public  affairs."  ^  True,  this  is  not  said  especially  of  Cleon,  but 
there  is  no  room  for  doubt  that  Cleon  is  the  first  person  aimed 
at  by  this  trenchant  observation.  To  flatter  the  democracy 
by  becoming  the  pander  to  its  instincts,  which  besides  were 
probably  also  his  own — such  was  the  sum  and  substance  of  his 
policy.*     We  may  add  to  this  the  incessant  accusations  in  the 

^  These  characteristics  of  a  hard  and  brutal  logician  seem  to  me  to  come  out 
very  vividly  in  the  speeches  that  Thucydides  imputes  to  him  in  the  affair  of 
the  Mj'tileneans.     I  shall  refer  to  them  again. 

'^Aristotle,  Constitution  of  Athens,  c.  xxviii. 

» Thucydides,  ii.  65.  10. 

^  This  is  what  is  apparent  from  the  few  facts  that  are  definitely  known  to 
us.  The  increase  of  the  judges'  salaries,  whatever  may  have  been  said  about 
it,  was  not  inspired  by  anj'  other  motive  (Aristophanes,  Knights,  1.  255  ; 
Schol.  Wasps,  1.  88).  Remember  also  the  part  Cleon  played  in  the  negotia- 
tions of  the  j'ear  425  (Thucydides,  iv.  22). 


24  INTRODUCTION 

courts,  by  means  of  which  he  gained  a  reputation  for  vigilance 
and  devotion  to  the  public  weal,  while  at  the  same  time  he 
fostered  the  suspicions  to  which  the  people  were  only  too 
much  inclined.^ 

In  foreign  affairs,  he  sought  incessantly  to  arouse  the 
imprudent  ambition  of  Athens.  Supremacy  at  sea,  with 
which  Pericles  would  have  had  it  content,  did  not  suffice  for 
him.  Falling  in  with  the  secret  wishes  of  the  people,  and 
particularly  of  the  inhabitants  of  Piraeus,  he  held  up  before 
their  eyes  the  glittering  vision  or  the  delusive  dream  of  a 
great  empire ;  and  to  the  discussion  of  these  questions,  in 
which  prudence,  moderation  and  a  clear  recognition  of  what 
was  possible,  would  have  been  necessary,  he  brought  his  usual 
absolutism.  He  admitted  neither  compromise  nor  failure. 
Thucydides  formally  declares  that,  to  the  end,  he  remained 
the  chief  obstacle  to  the  declaration  of  peace  by  the  Athenians.^ 
"  My  aim,"  says  the  Paphlagonion  to  Demos  in  the  Knights, 
"is  to  make  you  rule  over  all  the  Greeks."  ^  Even 
though  this  utterance  be  not  historic,  it  at  least  sums  up 
the  policy  that  Cleon  must  have  professed.  The  seafarers  and 
all  those  who  made  their  livelihood  at  Athens  from  commerce 
with  foreign  parts  had,  at  bottom,  the  desire  and  the  need  of 
constant  expansion,  which  seems,  as  though  by  a  law  of  nature, 
to  be  inherent  in  great  maritime  powers.  Cleon  flattered  this 
tendency,  just  as  he  was  wont  to  flatter  all  popular  instincts. 
He  declared  that  this  dream  could  surely  be  realized,  if  only 
they  would  agree  never  to  yield,  and  would  not  allow  vain 
scruples  or  the  plea  of  humanity  to  induce  them  to  relax  that 
"  imperial "  authority,  which  had  been  created  by  the  very 
course   of   events    and    by    the    force    of    circumstance.      He 

^Aristophanes,  Knights,  1.  256.  It  seems  to  me  to  be  of  secondary  impor- 
tance whether  Cleon  acted  in  good  or  in  bad  faith,  from  self-interest  or 
disinterestedly.  History  sits  in  judgment  not  upon  his  motives  but  upon 
his  acts.  Those  who  have  sought  to  vindicate  him  should  have  tried 
to  show  one  occasion  at  least  on  which  he  exerted  a  beneficial  influence  on  the 
people.  If,  on  the  contrary,  he  always  impelled  them  to  the  side  to  which 
they  secretly  inclined,  the  judgment  of  Aristotle  and  that  of  Thucydides 
are  justified. 

*  Thucydides,  v.  16.  ^Aristophanes,  Knights,  1.  797. 


INTRODUCTION  25 

maintained  the  theory   of  an  ever-growing   domination,  esta- 
blished and  upheld  with  inflexible  energy. 


VI 

Aristophanes  could  not  but  be  the  avowed  enemy  of  such  a 
man  and  of  those  who  were  like  him.     He  was  their  enemy 
by  nature,  independently  of  all  personal  grievances  and  almost 
without  reflection.     They  disagreed,  in  the  first  place,  about 
essential   matters    in   politics.     For   reasons    which   we   have  , 
already  set  forth,  Aristophanes  belonged,  heart  and  soul,  to  a  ) 
moderate  democracy,  which  was  attached  to  the  soil  and  to  its   ) 
traditions,  was  opposed  to  violence  and  foolhardiness,  had  little  ; 
sympathy  with  idle  talkers,  and  was  very  hostile  to  the  inces- 
sant lawsuits  that  upset  the  city  and  were  advantageous  only  | 
to  the  politicians.     The  ambition  for  conquest  that  animated 
the  people  of  Piraeus  was  entirely  foreign  to  him.     In  common 
with  all  the  country  folk,  war  meant  to  him  defensive  war 
only,  limited  to  the  protection  of  one's  territory.^     To  their    "^ 
minds,  distant  expeditions,  in  which  Athens  wasted  her  blood 
and  her  money,  appeared  as  a  kind  of  criminal  folly.     In  a 
word,  every  part  of  Cleon's  policy  was  hateful  to  them.     This 
was  their  chief  and  most  serious  difference  of  opinion,  which 
the  lively  imagination  of  Aristophanes,  the  sensitiveness  of  his 
poetic  nature  and  his  bitter  satire  constantly  provoked  and 
fanned  into  flame. 

Underlying  this  difference  of  view  there  was  still  another 
and  even  deeper  element  of  discord,  a  conflict  less  political  in 
its  nature  than  moral  and  national.  The  character  of  the 
Athenians,  such  as  race,  tradition  and  history  had  made  it, 
was  undergoing  a  crisis  at  the  beginning  of  the  Peloponnesian 
war. 

Thucydides,  in  the  speech  which  he  attributes  to  Pericles 
and  which  he  says  the  latter  made  in  the  winter  of  the  year 
431-430,  defined  this  character,  while  idealizing  it.     Wliat 

^Aristophanes,  Ecclesiazusae,  I.   197;   cf.  J.  Beloch,  Die  aitische  Politik, 
pp.  13  and  14. 


26  INTRODUCTION 

,  the  statesman  praises  above  all  is  the  charming  suavity  of 
Athenian  manners,  the  absence  of  constraint,  the  freedom  of 
private  life,  untroubled  by  any  jealous  surveillance,  the  fair 
exercise  of  justice,  a  taste  for  simple  elegance  that  lent  beauty 
to  life,  a  confiding  hospitality,  the  amiable  grace  and  ease  of 
intercourse, — in  a  word,  a  sort  of  inborn  adaptability,  which 
enabled  everyone  to  realize  all  his  natural  gifts,  without 
submitting  himself  to  a  severe  and  trying  discipline.'-  All 
this  seems  to  have  been  noted  at  first  hand  by  a  close 
observer,  who  had  lived  in  various  parts  of  Greece  and  was 
thus  able  to  judge  by  comparison.  And  even  though,  in  point 
of  fact,  these  qualities  were  mingled  with  faults  which  the 
historian  himself  has  mentioned  elsewhere,  there  is,  at  any 
rate,  no  doubt  that  the  picture,  viewed  as  a  whole,  is  faithful. 
This  was,  indeed,  substantially  the  character  of  Athens  about 
431,  and  it  made  Athens  the  only  city  of  its  kind  in  the 
Greek  world.  And  now  the  policy  of  the  demagogues  tended 
to  change  it  seriously.  .This  policy  brought  with  it  suspicion, 
hatred  and  a  factional  spirit,  and  rapidly  spread  them  abroad  in 
the  city.  By  means  of  the  corruption  of  the  judiciary  it 
annoyed  and  exasperated  some  people,  while  among  others  it 
engendered  a  spirit  of  selfish  illwill.  By  granting  excessive 
powers  to  the  popular  assembly,  it  transformed  democracy  into 
despotism ;  and  finally,  by  its  unbounded  imperialism,  it  made 
the  people  tyrannical  and  sometimes  cruel.  \ 
•  Nobody  was  more  of  an  Athenian  of  the  pM- Jype  than 
i  Aristophanes,  albeit  he  was  very  modern  in  some  respects,  and 
'  nobody  can  have  felt  more  keenly  than  he  the  existence  of 
this  crisis.  How  could  his  free  and  expansive  nature,  gay  and 
vivacious,  fond  of  merry-making,  of  a  good  time  and  of  an 
easy-going  life,  have  failed  to  abhor  this  factional  spirit  that  it 
saw  growing  up  about  it  ?  Demagogues  filled  with  hatred, 
corrupt  courts,  a  war  protracted  for  the  benefit  of  private 
interests,  and  carried  on  at  public  expense,  was  this  not 
enough  to  outrage  so  devoted  a  representative  of  ancient 
liberty  and  one  so  attached  to  his  peace-loving  and  kindly 
Attica  ?      Hence   came    his    disposition   to  hostile   criticism ; 

(  ^  Thucydides,  ii.  cap.  xxxvii.-xli. 


INTRODUCTION  27 

indeed,  one  may  say  that  it  is  entirely  traceable  to  this 
source.  For,  at  bottom,  when  he  attacks  Euripides,  Socrates, 
and  even  the  new  style  of  music  with  almost  as  much  virulence 
as  he  attacks  Cleon  or  Lamachus,  the  reason  for  his  wrath  is 
doubtless  always  the  same.  It  is  the  Athenian  temperament, 
such  as  he  imagines  it,  as  he  feels  it  in  his  own  person,  as 
he  sees  it  in  tradition,  that  he  champions,  rightly  or  wrongly, 
against  innovators.  More  than  all  others,  he  loved  its  lively 
spontaneity,  its  inherited  straightforwardness,  its  gracious 
simplicity  and  the  inborn  kindliness  that  lay  hidden  behind 
its  mocking  ways. 

One  must  keep  this  constantly  in  mind  in  order  to  get  a 
proper  understanding  of  his  relations  with  political  parties.  It 
is  quite  certain  that  in  the  course  of  the  fight  in  which  he 
engaged,  he  underwent  transient  inliuences,  that  he  sought 
useful  alliances,  even  that  he  may  have  lent  himself  to  cer- 
tain political  schemes.  All  these  questions  need  be  studied 
and  discussed  at  close  range  and  in  connection  with  each  of 
his  plays.  But,  from  the  very  outset,  it  is  essential  to  appre- 
hend clearly  that,  properly  speaking,  Aristophanes  belonged  to 
no  party.  Child  of  the  country  and  of  Athenian  tradition — it 
is  in  the  name  of  his  native  land  that  he  speaks,  and  it  is  the 
soul  of  Athens  that  he  defends  against  those  whom  he  regards 
as  its  corruptors.  _ 


ARISTOPHANES   AND   THE   POLITICAL 
PARTIES   AT   ATHENS 

CHAPTER  I 

THE  BEGINNING  OF  ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER 

THE  BANQUETERS.      THE  BABYLONIANS. 
THE  ACHARNIANS 


In  the  beginning  Aristophanes  wrote  comedy  of  a  satirical 
order.  Later  on  he,  as  well  as  other  comic  poets,  wrote 
plays,  in  which  either  mythological  parody  or  fancy,  pure  and 
simple,  predominated.  If  I  am  not  mistaken,  this  was  a  con- 
cession that  he  made  to  circumstances.  His  vocation  led  him, 
from  the  very  beginning,  to  pass  censure  on  morals  and  on 
politics ;  and  he  returned  to  this  practice  as  often  as  he  could. 
Nothing  is  more  likely  than  that  a  certain  desire  for  popular 
success  prompted  this  choice  of  subject.  This  style  of  comedy 
had  a  much  greater  chance  of  arousing  the  enthusiasm  of  the 
public,  which  was  already  somewhat  tired  of  simple  buffoonery. 
Through  it  an  author  could  quickly  gain  a  reputation  for 
courage  and  rise  to  the  level  of  a  moralist,  nay,  almost  of  a 
statesman.  It  was  by  this  means  that  Cratinus  had  become 
hors  de  conconrs,  although  imitators  and  rivals  swarmed  about 
him.  But  ambition  alone  did  not  suffice  in  order  to  play  this 
part.  Evidently  it  demanded  a  special  aptitude  which  could 
not  have  been  developed  in  a  mind  that  was  superficial  and 
indifferent   to   social   questions.     AVe  may,  therefore,  as  well 

D 


30  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

recognize  that  the  youthful  Aristophanes  possessed  a  "  certain 
philosophy,"  and,  underlying  his  playful  fancy,  more  seriousness 
than  would  appear  at  first  sight.^ 

The  first  play  he  gave  to  the  public  was  performed  in  the 
beginning  of  the  year  427.^  It  was  called  The  Banqueters 
(ol  A(«TaXJ79).  In  order  to  have  it  accepted  by  the  archon,  our 
poet,  who  was  still  unknown,  had  placed  it  in  the  hands  of  a 
certain  Callistratus,  who  presented  it  to  the  magistrate  as  his 
own,  and,  consequently,  took  upon  himself  the  responsibility  of 
instructing  the  actors.^ 

This  Callistratus  must  have  been  a  poet  and  comic  actor 
himself.  The  confidence  with  which  he  seems  to  have  inspired 
not  only  various  archons,  but  also  his  friend  Aristophanes, 
leaves  no  room  for  doubt  that,  at  all  events,  he  possessed,  to 
an  unusual  degree,  aptitude  and  experience  in  the  usages  of 
the  theatre.  The  archon  knew  in  advance  that  a  play  which 
such  a  man  took  up  was  pretty  sure  to  amuse  the  public ;  and 
that  was  all  that  was  necessary.  As  for  Aristophanes,  we 
must  assume  that  he  had  largely  profited  by  Callistratus' 
counsels  in  the  writing  of  his  play,  and  that  he  was  still  in 
great  need  of  assistance  from  him  in  its  actual  preparation  for 
performance.  This  is  indeed  about  what  he  himself  says  at  a 
later  time  in  metaphorical  language,  in  the  parabasis  of  his 
Knights} 

His  comedy  was  awarded  the  second  prize  ^ — in  itself  a 
creditable  success,  and  even  more  than  that  for  a  beginner. 
Its  leading  idea  and  a  few  fragments  are  all  that  is  known  to 
us  of  this  play. 

^  This  is  what  Plato  said  of  Isocrates  :  (ptjcrei.  yap  ^veari  ns  (fiCKocTocpla  rrj  toO 
dvdpbs  diavoLq.  (Phaedrus,  p.  279  b).  This  saying,  with  its  careful  shades  of 
meaning  and  its  reservations,  seems  to  me  to  fit  Aristophanes  well.  Neither 
the  comic  poet  nor  the  orator  was  really  a  philosopher,  but  there  was  in  each 
of  them  "a  certain  philosophy,"  consisting  chieily  of  perceptions,  each  in 
their  way  incomplete. 

"  Clouds,  11.  528-532  ;  Sehol.  Clouds,  1.  529  ;  Anonymous  author.  De  Comoedia 
{Com.  graec.  fragm. ,  Kaibel,  i.  p.  8). 

'  Anon.  De  Com. ,  loc.  cit. 

*  Knights,  11.  512-515  and  541-544.     Cf.   Wasps,  1018-1020. 

^  Schol.  Clotids,  1.  529,  Sevrepos  iKpiSr). 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  31 

Taken  as  a  whole,  it  was  a  satire  on  the  new  customs.    The 
poet  placed  upon  the  stage  an  Athenian  of  the  old  days,  a  man 
fond  of  tradition,  very  much  attached  to   the  past — and  to- 
gether with  him,  two  young  men,  his  sons.    The  one  submitted 
willingly  to  paternal  discipline ;    the  other  was   full  of  new 
ideas,  a  votary  and  follower  of  the  sophists,  a  fine  talker,  a 
sycophant  and  a  debauchee.     The  moral  interest  of  the  play 
arose  from  the  contrast  between  the  two  brothers.     This  is 
what  Aristophanes  himself  points  out,  when,  in  the  parabasis 
of  the  Clouds,  he  makes  allusion  to  this  first  attempt  of  his 
Muse,  and  reminds  the  audience  of  the  day  "  when  his  two 
characters,  the  good  young  man  and  the  debauchee  were  well 
received "   by  them.^     The   details   of    the   plot  are   entirely 
unknown  to  us.     From  the  title  of  the  play  itself,  and  from 
rather  obscure  evidence,  the  conclusion  seems  warranted  that 
the  chorus  was  made  up  of  a  religious  brotherhood,  who  met 
to  offer  a  sacrifice  to  Heracles  and  then  to  feast  at  a  banquet 
in  his  honor. -^     What   part  did  they   take  in  the  dialogue  ? 
There  is  nothing  to  indicate  it.     The  most  important  fragments 
bring   before   us  either  the  father   and   his  sons  or  the  two 
brothers.      In  one  passage  the  youthful  innovator  uses  words 
that  are  in  fashion,  in  which  his  father  immediately  recognizes 
the  mark  of  certain  popular  rhetoricians  and  demagogues,  or 
that   of   Alcibiades,    the   leader   of  the   gilded   youth   (fragm. 
198,  Kaibel).     Elsewhere,  the  same  "bad  lot"  shows  that  he 
has  neglected  the  study  of  Homer  and  that  he  knows  nothing 
of  the  national  poets,  such  as  Alcaeus  and  Anacreon,  but  that 
he  is   past  master  of  sharp  practice  (fragm.  222  and  223). 
He  knows  how  to  play  the  lyre  and  is  proud  of  it,  but  it  is 
clear  that  the  music  he  cares  for  is  of  the  popular  kind  (fragm. 
221).     What  did  the  old  Athenian  gentleman  do  to  reform 
this  scamp  ?     He  seems  to  have  intended  to  send  him  out  to 
the  country  to  dig  (fragm.  221).    We  do  not  know  whether  he 

1  Clouds,  1.  528. 

'^ Comic,  graec.  fragm.,  Kock,  i.  p.  438.  Suidas  :  AatraXerj"  5aiTviJ.6vfs  khI 
dLaaQrai  Kal  avfXTrdTai  /cat  olov  ffvv8aiTa\eh'  oiirws  ^Apiarocpdvris.  Orion,  49.  10: 
AairaXetj,  8p5.fia'ApiaTO<pdpovi'  eirtLor}  ev  tep^  ' HpaxX^ovs  heiirvovvris  Ka.1  avaVTivTH 
Xopol  eyevoyro. 


32  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

succeeded.  Certain  fragments  give  us  a  glimpse  of  a  law-suit, 
real  or  fictitious  (fragm.  210,216,217,218,219).  In  another 
passage  the  father  probably  called  upon  the  ancient  kings  of 
Athens,  Erechtheus  and  Aegeus,  as  witnesses  (fragm.  211). 
This  enumeration  must  be  incomplete,  for  he  could  not  have 
failed  to  summon  to  his  aid  also  the  popular  king  Theseus, 
who  was  inseparable  from  the  other  two.  From  all  this  we 
gather  nothing  definite  about  composition  and  general  plan. 

We  do,  however,  see  quite  plainly  that  the  play  was  much 
more  than  a  mere  collection  of  gibes  at  individuals.  It  was 
controlled  by  a  consistent  thought,  which  served  to  bind  together 
its  various  parts.  This  thought  was  a  censure,  undoubtedly  a 
moral  one,  and  probably,  at  least  to  some  extent,  a  political  one. 

The  character  of  the  old  Athenian,  of  whom  we  get  rather 
vague  glimpses,  was  in  itself  a  living  profession  of  faith.  The 
very  essence  of  his  nature  was  attachment  to  the  old-time 
manner  of  living  and  thinking.  Whatever  his  role  in  the 
play  may  have  been,  and  even  granting  that  he  suffered  many 
rebuffs,  we  may  be  sure,  at  any  rate,  that  the  poet  allowed  his 
own  sympathy  for  him  to  be  felt,  and  that  he  sought  to  gain 
for  him  that  of  the  audience.  On  the  other  hand,  there  is  no 
indication  that  this  person  manifested  any  leaning  toward 
oligarchy.  As  far  as  we  can  judge,  it  was  the  intriguing  and 
the  laziness  of  the  youths  of  his  day  that  he  abhorred  above 
all  things.  Such  other  reproaches  as  he  could  heap  upon 
them,  sprang  from  that  source.  As  a  consequence,  he  must 
have  loved  the  country,  and  he  firmly  believed  in  its  value  as 
an  educator  and  maker  for  good  morals ;  it  was  for  this  reason 
that  he  wished  to  force  his  son  to  work  as  a  peasant.  He 
must  also  have  loved  the  old  religious  cults — the  subject- 
matter  of  the  play  itself  seems  to  make  this  clear — and  we 
may  picture  to  ourselves  this  good  fellow,  in  the  midst  of  his 
companions  in  the  worship  of  Heracles,  making  common  cause 
with  them  of  his  devoutness  and  of  his  protests  against  the 
spirit  of  innovation.  In  a  word,  it  is  easy  to  think  of  him  as 
a  somewhat  less  rustic  Strepsiades  with  this  or  that  distin- 
guishing peculiarity,  about  which  it  would  be  over-bold  to 
make  conjectures  at  this  late  day. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  33 

The  virtuous  son  is  merely  a  shadow,  and  it  seems  impos- 
sible, taking  into  account  the  state  of  the  fragments,  to  form 
any  idea  of  his  personality.  It  is  even  somewhat  difficult  to 
conceive  that  he  should  have  played  an  important  part  in  the 
comedy,  for,  at  best,  he  could  not  have  been  other  than  his 
father's  double,  and  a  very  mediocre  double  at  that.  Aristo- 
phanes, who  was  so  intelligent  in  matters  relating  to  the 
theatre,  must  instinctively  have  felt  what  a  bore  reasonable 
and  reasoning  young  men  are  on  the  comic  stage.  When,  in 
speaking  of  his  play,  he  summed  it  up  in  the  contrast  between 
the  two  brothers,  he  no  doubt  alluded  more  to  an  isolated  scene 
(fragm.  199),  or  to  the  underlying  scheme  of  the  composition, 
than  to  its  dramatic  form. 

We  cannot  doubt,  on  the  other  hand,  that  the  "  bad 
young  man  "  was  the  main  attraction  of  the  play.  It  would 
not  have  been  amusing  without  him.  His  deep-rooted  dislike 
of  discipline  was  its  mainspring.  Whatever  the  plot  may 
have  been,  it  was  assuredly  he  who  kept  it  moving.  From 
sheer  necessity  Aristophanes  had  given  him  that  exuberance 
of  life,  that  kind  of  bold  confidence  and  unrestrainable  activity, 
which  we  shall  meet  with  again  in  his  Dicaeopolis,  Cleon, 
Strepsiades,  Trygaeus,  Pisthetairos,  Lysistrata,  and  generally  in 
those  of  his  characters  who  are  the  authors  of  a  comic  enter- 
prise. Moreover,  this  fellow  was  typical  of  young  Athens ;  of 
course  he  represented  it  in  an  exaggerated  form  and  with  the 
extravagance  that  was  indispensable  in  this  style  of  composi- 
tion. It  seems  that  the  poet,  by  hints  let  fall  here  and 
there,  must  in  some  sort  have  reviewed  the  young  man's  life 
hitherto.  From  the  time  that  he  grew  up  his  father,  who  was 
probably  astounded  at  his  talents,  had  apprenticed  him  to 
learned  masters,  with  the  intention  of  assuring  him  a  brilliant 
future.  "  But,"  said  he,  "  he  learned  none  of  those  things  that 
I  wanted  him  to  learn.  Instead  of  doing  so,  he  learned  how 
to  drink,  to  sing  in  topsy-turvy  manner,  to  love  nothing  but 
Syracusan  cookery,  the  pleasures  of  the  Sybarites  and  bumpers 
of  Chian  wine  from  Laconian  cups"  (fr.  216).  Notwithstand- 
ing all  this,  he  had,  as  we  have  already  seen,  become  initiated 
in    rhetoric    and    in    sharp    practice    (fr.    198,    222).      Once 


34  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

equipped  with  these  means  of  attaining  success,  he  had 
become  a  sycophant,  a  public  denunciator,  and  had  grown  rich 
on  threats  and  cahimny  (fr.  219,  225).  At  the  same  time 
he  had  acquired,  in  one  fell  swoop,  all  the  vices  of  that  pro- 
fession. He  was  a  gambler,  a  toper,  a  debauchee,  an  impudent 
fellow  (fr.  202,  205,  206,  209,  213).  He  boasted  of  all  this, 
and  treated  his  own  father  with  cynical  insolence  (fr,  198). 

Incomplete  as  these  portrayals  are,  they  do  nevertheless 
enable  us  to  determine  approximately  the  drift  of  the  Aristo- 
phanic  satire.  It  was  against  the  professional  politicians  that 
the  poet  inveighed,  and  by  this  term  we  mean  those  who  at 
that  time  were  beginning  to  transform  politics  into  a  lucrative 
trade  in  Athens.  But  he  directed  his  attacks  neither  against 
their  views  nor  against  their  way  of  conducting  affairs,  nor 
even  against  that  exploitation  of  the  courts  of  justice  which 
they  had  organized  for  their  own  profit;  all  that  was  to  come 
in  due  time.  For  the  moment,  it  was  their  moral  perverseness 
that  he  placed  on  the  boards.  He  showed  it  in  a  concrete 
example,  in  living  guise,  as  a  composite  of  a  group  of  tendencies 
which  seemed  to  him  to  be  about  to  corrupt  the  character  of 
(,  ^0^      the  Athenians.      It  was  no  business  of  his  to  seek  for  what 

yj^.V^    ^  \  was  cause  or  effect  in  this  group  of  tendencies.     Probably  he 
jj^^vw'  '  did  not  even,  in  the  secrecy  of  his  heart,  ask  himself  whether 

^     -^  this  rapid  growth  of  unscrupulous  ambition  and  selfish  indi- 

vidualism was  a  result,  say,  of  the  constitution  of  Athens  itself, 
or  of  the  way  in  which  it  was  carried  into  effect.  The  tem- 
perament of  the  poet  made  him  more  susceptible  to  what  can 
be  seen  than  to  things  that  must  be  guessed  at,  and  he  was 
content  to  embody  the  existing  evils  in  his  fictions.  He 
did  so  with  remarkable  power  from  the  very  beginning  of  his 
career.  .. 

In  so  doing  he  did  not  act  as  an  adherent  of  a  party,  and 
he  had  to  wait  on  no  man's  word  of  command.  The  men 
whom  he  took  to  task,  belonged  rather  to  the  middje,  or  to 
the  well-to-do  class,  than,  strictly  speaking,  to  the  people. 
Sons  of  country  landowners,  sprung  from  families  that  were 
attached  to  the  soil,  they  exploited  the  new  teaching  and  the 
democratic  radicalism  and  made  both  alike  serve  their  passions. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  35 

It  was  a  real  service  to  the  democracy  to  chastise  them,  and 
by  showing  it  the  canker  from  which  it  suffered,  to  invite  it  to 
purify  itself. 

II 

The  Banqueters  was  followed,  in  426,  by  the  Bahyloiiians, 
j^rformed  at  the  city  festival  of  Dionysus.^  It  is  not  very 
likely  that  any  of  the  undated  plays  was  performed  between 
these  two  comedies.  It  was  quite  enough  for  a  beginner  to 
have  had  one  of  his  works  accepted  each  year. 

Though  this  second  comedy  is  likewise  lost,  we  have 
somewhat  more  information  about  it.  It  was  a  political 
satire  of  a  much  bitterer,  much  bolder  and  far  more  personal 
kind  than  the  first  play.  Success  had  heightened  the  young 
poet's  confidence  as  well  as  his  literary  ambition.  He  ardently 
desired  to  distinguish  himself  by  a  brilliant  success,  and  besides 
this,  certain  occurrences  in  the  year  427  appear  to  have  greatly 
increased  his  dissatisfaction  as  well  as  that  of  a  good  part  of 
the  Athenian  populace.     Let  us  review  them  briefly. 

During  the  year  428-427  Athens  was  profoundly  agitated 
by  the  Lesbian  revolt  and  by  the  consequences  that  grew 
from  it.^ 

~~Mytilene,  one  of  the  most  important  states  of  the  maritime 
league,  had  openly  withdrawn,  and  had  formed  an  alliance  with 
the  Lacedaemonians.  This  defection  was  peculiarly  grave  in  itself, 
but  was  even  more  so  because  it  might  have  become  the  signal 
for  an  uprising  of  all  the  oppressed  and  discontented  allies. 
Athens  gave  proof  of  its  determination  and  energy.  Mytilene 
w^as  blockaded,  reduced  to  starvation  and  forced  to  sue  for 
mercy,  before  the  Peloponnesian  fleet  could  come  to  her  aid. 
After  her  subjugation  was  accomplished,  it  became  necessary  to 
decide  upon  her  punishment.  In  this  connection  the  question 
of  the  policy  to  be  pursued  towards  the  allies  was  raised  and 
passionately  debated  in  the  popular  assembly.      Should  a  reign 

"^  Achamians,  1.  50.3,  and  scholia. 

^For  a  detailed  account  of  what  happened,  see  Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.  iii. 
2nd  part,  p.  1002  ei  seq. 


36  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

of  terror  be  inaugurated  ?  Or  did  wisdom  and  humanity  alike 
enjoin  moderation  ?  Thucydides  has,  in  his  usual  manner, 
given  us  a  sort  of  abridged  and  ideal  account  of  the  discussion 
that  took  place  at  this  juncture ;  ^  he  does  not  describe  in 
detail  the  passionate  changes  of  opinions.  Two  consecutive 
meetings  of  the  assembly  were  held.  On  the  first  day  the 
advocates  of  unmerciful  severity  carried  all  before  them : 
notwithstanding  the  energetic  opposition  of  a  certain  Diodotus, 
son  of  Eucrates,^  Cleon's  proposal  was  adopted,  and  it  was 
decided  to  put  to  death  all  the  Mytileneans  who  were  old 
enough  to  bear  arms,  and  to  sell  the  women  and  children  as 
slaves.  Subsequently,  in  the  course  of  the  evening,  and  during 
the  night,  a  moral  reaction  set  in.  People  thought  about  the 
horror  of  such  a  slaughter — a  more  humane  view  prevailed.  The 
Mytilenean  envoys,  who  were  then  in  Athens,  took  advantage 
of  this  disposition,  and  urged  their  friends  to  plead  with  the 
magistrates.  The  latter  called  a  second  assembly  on  the  fol- 
lowing day,  and  asked  for  a  fresh  discussion.  In  it,  Cleon  and 
Diodotus  supported  the  same  views  as  on  the  previous  day,  but 
this  time  it  was  Diodotus  who  prevailed,  though  his  majority 
was  small.  One  thousand  of  the  Mytileneans  who  were  most 
heavily  implicated  were  put  to  death,^  the  rest  were  ejected 
from  the  best  part  of  their  land  for  the  benefit  of  Athenian 
colonists.^ 

Cleon's  attitude  in  this  crisis  was  the  same  as  usual.  His 
imperious  and  violent  temperament  instinctively  sought  the 
simplest  solution,  though  it  was  the  most  brutal  and  the  most 
inhuman.  Thucydides,  who  reproduces  the  spirit,  if  not  the 
form,  of  the  speeches  he  made  at  this  time,  has  brought  out 
their  character  in  bold  relief.  In  them  we  see  a  hard-hearted 
man  of  narrow  and  biassed  intelligence,  who  converts  politics 
into  a  sort  of  rigid,  imperious  and  inflexible  mathematics.  He 
sets  up  the  thesis  that  the  sovereignty  of  Athens  over  her 

1  Thucydides,  iii.  c.  xxxvi.  et  seq.         '^Thucydides,  iii.  cc.  xxxvi.  and  xli. 

*  Even  this  number  has  been  questioned ;  several  scholars  think  there  is  an 
error  in  the  text  of  Thucydides  (Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.,  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1030); 
but  their  arguments  are  far  from  conclusive. 

*  Thucydides,  iii.  50. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  37 

allies  is  a  "  tyranny," — that  is,  an  absolute  and  arbitrary 
power ;  and  this  sovereignty  must  be  maintained  by  means 
that  fit  tyrannies — that  is,  by  terror  and  force.  His  whole 
policy  is  contained  in  this  syllogism ;  and  this  rampant  dema- 
gogue is  well  aware  that  it  is  contrary  to  the  very  spirit  of 
democracy.  But  this  contradiction,  instead  of  checking  him, 
drives  him  to  increase  his  harsh  demands,  for  it  might,  unless 
care  were  taken,  place  his  system  in  jeopardy.  He  therefore 
advises  the  democracy  to  be  distrustful  of  itself,  that  is, 
in  this  instance,  of  justice,  of  humanity ; — and,  since  it  is  in 
fact  a  tyranny,  so  far  as  its  allies  are  concerned,  he  demands 
that  it  act  according  to  the  rule  of  tyrannies.  Such  is  the 
essence  of  his  speech ;  the  rest  of  it  merely  aimed  at  accentuating 
the  aggravating  circumstances  that  were  charged  against  the 
Mytileneans. 

Diodotus'  reply  presents  this  furious  radicalism  in  even  a 
clearer  light  by  refuting  it.  Diodotus  does  not  meet  Cleon's 
arguments  with  considerations  of  humanity,  but  of  politics. 
In  contrast  to  Cleon's  uncompromising  and  abstract  logic,  he 
holds  up  to  view  the  complexity  of  real  life.  In  substance  he 
says,  "  Cleon  reduces  everything  to  force,  which  amounts  to  an 
admission  that  fear  alone  has  complete  power  over  mankind. 
Now,  this  is  not  the  case.  Many  other  feelings  sway  them, 
force  them  into  action  and  frequently  make  them  overcome 
fear  itself,  be  it  that  they  scorn  danger,  or  that  they  hope  to 
escape  from  it.  Politics  is  the  art  of  reckoning  with  these 
feelings,  and  its  essence  is  compromise.  By  nature  it  is 
opposed  to  extreme  measures,  which  permit  of  no  other  out- 
come for  revolt  than  despair." 

There  can  be  no  doubt  that  these  ideas,  in  their  essential 
parts,  were  actually  expressed  on  the  platform  in  these  two 
memorable  assemblies.  Not  only  is  the  good  faith  of  Thucy- 
dides  a  guarantee  of  this,  but  it  may  be  said  that  they  were 
in  the  natural  order  of  things.  Without  this  conflict  of 
opinions,  without  this  combat  between  two  opposite  theories, 
the  two  successive  votes  of  the  Athenian  Assembly  would  not 
be  intelligible. 

If,  on  that  day,  these  ideas  were  expressed  with  special 


38  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

forcefulness,  it  was  because  the  crisis  demanded  it ;  but  they 
most  certainly  had  been  in  people's  minds  for  a  long  time, 
because  they  must,  of  necessity,  have  been  engendered  by  the 
very  situation  of  Athens  as  regards  her  allies.  There  can 
be  no  doubt  that,  even  outside  of  the  Assembly,  they  were 
matter  for  discussion  in  the  clubs,  and  that  they  agitated 
Athenian  society. 

It  is  inconceivable  that  these  ideas  should  not  have  taken 
alvvMvvvV''  a,  new  lease  of  life  at  the  close  of  the  summer  of  427  as  a 
l\,y^^  .,%■  consequence  of  these  impassioned  and  much-talked-of  discus- 
sions. The  better  part  of  Athenian  society,  the  most  intelli- 
gent, discreet  and  humane  part,  could  not  help  subjecting  its 
conscience  to  a  somewhat  distressing  examination.  Had  not 
this  rebellion  of  Mytilene,  this  unuttered  but  universal  discon- 
tent, that  was  so  pregnant  with  future  unrest, — had  it  not 
been  provoked  ?  Had  not  the  allies  been  treated  with  a 
severity  that  could  not  fail  to  drive  them  into  open  revolt  ? 
Their  contributions  had  been  increased,  they  had  been  forced 
to  bring  their  lawsuits  to  Athens,  they  had  been  deprived  of 
all  power,  they  had  been  reduced  to  a  state  of  subjection. 
And  even  if  all  this  was  a  necessity  from  the  point  of  view  of 
a  majority  of  the  Athenians,  sagacious  and  moderate  men 
were  certainly  convinced  that  the  burden  might  have  been  made 
less  heavy.  Instead  of  doing  so,  the  politicians  of  the  day 
made  it  heavier  through  their  severity.  When  the  people 
fixed  the  amount  of  the  contributions,  it  was  the  politicians 
who  proposed  and  discussed  it ;  besides,  rightly  or  wrongly, 
they  were  accused  of  exacting  money  from  the  parties  in 
interest  and  of  crushing  those  who  refused  to  buy  them  off. 
Again,  it  was  the  politicians  who  appeared  as  accusers  before  the 
courts,  in  suits  brought  against  the  leading  men  of  the  allied 
cities,  and  people  did  not  shrink  from  saying  that  they  drove 
bargains  with  the  fear  that  they  inspired  and  that  they  grew 
rich  on  threats.  Probably  this  sort  of  talk  was  sometimes 
true  and  often  false.  But  such  truth  as  there  was  in  it 
sufficed  to  make  people  who  were  already  restless  and  discon- 
tented accept  it  without  question.  And  so  it  finally  came 
about  that  the  entire  responsibility  for  a  state  of  affairs  that 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  39 

was  attributable  to  them  in  part,  but  in  part  only,  was  placed 
\ipon  the  leaders  of  the  people,  and  especially  upon  Cleon. 

But  was  Diodotus  the  mouthpiece  of  the  oligarchical  opposi- 
tion at  this  juncture  ?  We  have  really  no  reason  to  think 
this,  but  quite  the  contrary.  Thucydides  does  not  say  a  single 
word  that  would  warrant  us  in  suspecting  it,  and  nowhere  else 
in  the  history  of  the  period  do  we  again  find  this  man  engaged 
in  factional  intrigue.  Cleon  himself  makes  no  allusion  what- 
ever to  anything  of  the  kind  in  the  speeches  that  the  historian 
attributes  to  him.  The  contest  which  Thucydides  describes  is 
purely  a  struggle  between  two  moral  tendencies,  the  one  more 
humane,  the  other  more  severe,  but  both  independent  of  party. 
If  we  may  trust  his  adversary,  Diodotus  would  appear  to  be 
a  man  who  wished  to  oppose  a  subtle  policy  to  a  necessary 
policy,  not  in  the  interests  of  a  faction,  but  in  order  to  increase 
liis  own  prestige.^  The  question  suggests  itself  whether  his 
father,  Eucrates,  is  identical  with  the  demagogue  and  hemp- 
dealer  of  whom  Aristophanes  made  fun  in  the  Knightsl'^  This 
is  not  at  all  impossible  or  improbable.^  In  any  event,  there 
is  absolutely  no  authority  for  connecting  him  with  the  aristo- 
cracy. Indeed,  it  is  more  likely  that  the  view  which  was 
supported  by  the  majority  in  the  affair  of  Mytilene  was 
oligarchical  neither  in  its  origin  nor  in  its  development.  It 
may  be  that  it  brought  together  some  of  the  oligarchs  because 
they  detested  Cleon,  but,  in  fact,  it  was  really  Athenian,  and 
it  is  the  Athenian  character  that  deserves  credit  for  it.^ 

Let  us  now  picture  to  ourselves  Aristophanes,  young  poet 
as  he  was  at  this  time,  in  the  midst  of  this  society  and  in 
the  uproar  of  these  discussions.  His  play  was  ready  in  the 
lieginning  of  426,  and  must  have  been  written  at  the  close  of 
427 — that  is  under  the  immediate  influence  of  the  events  of 
which  we  have  just  spoken.     In  those  days  of  political  comedy 

1  Thucydides,  iii.  37.  '^  Knights,  11.  129,  254. 

^  Modern  scholars,  for  reasons  that  are  not  clear  to  me,  as  a  rule  reject  this 
identification  (Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.  iii.  2ud  part,  p.  807,  note  4).  All 
that  one  can  say  is  that  there  were  several  men  named  Eucrates  at  Athens  at 

that  time. 

*  Thucydides,  iii.  34.  4  and  37.  2. 


40  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

the  great  concern  of  the  competitors  for  the  prize  was  to  put 
their  finger  upon  the  topic  of  the  day.  There  was,  in  fact, 
always,  or  nearly  always,  a  topic  that  arose  from  actual 
occurrences,  and  which  was  to  be  found  latent  in  the  minds 
■of  all.  The  difficulty  lay  in  seizing  upon  it,  in  disengaging  it 
and  in  giving  it  shape.  Quite  often  it  happened  that  several 
poets  seized  upon  it  at  the  same  time ;  and  this  is  not  surpris- 
ing when  we  consider  that  these  poets  lived  -in  identical 
surroundings  and  got  their  inspirations  from  identical  sources. 
Naturally  each  one  of  them,  in  working  up  the  topic  in 
dramatic  form,  gave  his  own  version  of  it  by  inventing  a 
comical  fancy  that  was  his  own.  We  do  not  know  what 
comedies  competed  with  Aristophanes'  play,  either  at  the 
Lenaean  festival  of  426  or  at  the  Great  Dionysia  of  that  year. 
It  is  not  improbable  that  the  question  of  the  allies  served  as 
*  a  theme  for  several  competitors ;   it  certainly  was  the  topic 

indicated  or  suggested   by   what  was   uppermost   in   people's 
minds. 

At  all  events,  whether  others  dealt  with  it  or  not,  Aristo- 
phanes seems  to  have  made  it  his  very  own  by  treating  it 
in  a  way  that  was  bold  to  the  point  of  being  scandalous. 
The  Banqueters  touched  only  indirectly  upon  politics.  In  the 
Babylonians  he  handled  it  openly,  and,  from  the  very  start,  his 
temerity  outdid  that  of  men  like  Cratinus,  Hermippus  and 
Telecleides,  who  had  already  gained  a  reputation  in  this  style 
of  composition. 

Ill 

,  Unfortunately  our  knowledge  of  this  play  is  very  meagre ; 

Btife-NiA  1^^^  ^|-^g  little  that  we  do  know  is  not  without  literary  interest 

or  historical  value. 

The  first  evidence  to  be  noted  is  that  given  by  the  poet 
himself.  In  the  parabasis  of  the  Acharnians  he  boasts  of  the 
service  he  rendered  the  people  by  his  comedy  of  the  preced- 
ing year,  and  by  this  he  means  the  Babylonians.  He  says  that 
he  taught  them  to  distrust  the  hollow  flattery  of  strangers, 
and  not  to  be  deceived  by  "  envoys  from  the  states,"  and  that 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  41 

finally  he  showed  them  ""  how  democracy  is  practised  in  the 
states,"  Kol  TOi/?  ^?/^iOf9  eV  Tai^  iroXea-iv  oei^a?  Trcog  orj/noKpa- 
TovvTai  (Acharn.  1.  642).  "  Moreover,"  he  adds,  "  the  allies  are 
all  anxious  to  know  this  worthy  poet,  who  has  dared  to  tell 
the  Athenians  the  truth  openly."  Elsewhere  he  reminds  us 
that,  as  a  consequence  of  this  declaration,  he  was  charged  with 
"  having  ridiculed  the  Eepuhlic  and  derided  the  people."  ^ 
These  various  bits  of  information  give  at  least  a  general  out- 
line of  the  play.  In  the  first  place,  we  learn  from  them  that 
its  subject  was  the  oppression  of  the  allies  and  the  tyranny  to 
which  they  were  subjected  under  the  guise  of  democracy.  The 
poet  had  dared  to  speak  of  justice  and  had  pleaded  the  cause 
of  humanity."  Furthermore,  we  see  that  he  had  introduced 
envoys  who  fooled  the  Athenian  people  by  means  of  flattery 
and  falsehoods. 

A  second  authority  amplifies  this  statement.  An  ancient 
commentator  tells  us  that  in  this  same  play  Aristophanes 
"made  fun  of  the  magistrates,  of  those  chosen  by  lot  as  well 
as  those  who  were  elected,  and  of  Cleon  also."  ^  The  only 
elected  magistrates  to  whom  this  can  possibly  have  referred, 
were,  first  the  generals  (arrpaTijyol)  who  were  constantly 
dealing  with  the  allies,  and  next  those  prefects  or  governors 
whom  Athens  sent  with  the  title  of  ap)(ovTeg  into  the  cities 
under  its  sway.*  As  for  officials  chosen  by  lot,  this  designa- 
tion may  refer  to  members  of  the  Athenian  Senate,  or  to  the 
judges  who  constituted  the  courts,  or  perhaps  to  the  Archon 
Polemarchus,  who  was  especially  entrusted  with  jurisdiction 
over  foreigners. 

^  Achaniians,  1.  631. 

'  Peace,  11.  759,  760 :  toiovtov  ISuv  r^pas  (Cleon)  ov  (caWSetcr',  dX\  iitrip 
vfiQv  troXeiJ.i^wv  avrelxof  "i^'  '^li  tCop  EWuiv  v-^auv.  This  play  was  aimed  against 
Cleon,  in  the  interests  of  Athens  and  of  the  islands. 

^Schol.  Achamians,  1.  378. 

*0n  this  subject  consult  Dittenberger,  Sylloge  Inscriptionum  Oraecnnim, 
2nd  edition,  No.  54,  note  5,  and  No.  2.3,  where  he  shows  that  the  creation  of 
these  archons  appears  to  antedate  the  Peloponnesian  war.  There  seems  to  be 
no  doubt  that  these  officials  were  elected,  because  Aeschines  (i.  107)  accuses 
Timarchus  of  having  "  purchased"  a  position  of  this  kind  "  for  thirty  minae." 
It  was  evidently  a  case  of  corrupting  voters. 


42  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

Wherein  did  the  comical  idea  on  which  the  plot  of  the  play- 
was  based  consist  ?  On  this  point,  we  must  admit,  there  is 
hardly  anything  but  uncertainty  and  guesswork. 

The  title,  it  is  true,  indicates  with  almost  complete  certainty 
that  the  chorus  was  composed  of  "  Babylonians.  "^  Of  these 
Babylonians  we  know,  moreover,  that  they  were  forced  to 
tread  the  mill ;  therefore  they  were  slaves,  and  supposed  to  be 
of  barbarian  origin.^  It  has  been  surmised  that  these  slaves 
represented  the  allies.^  There  is  absolutely  nothing  to  justify 
this  supposition,  which  would  have  precluded  all  dramatic 
action.  For,  if  the  allies  had  been  so  represented  from  the 
very  beginning  of  the  play,  one  fails  to  see  what  worse  fate 
could  subsequently  have  befallen  them.  All  that  it  is  safe  to 
conclude  from  this  account  of  the  chorus  is  that  the  scene  of 
the  play  probably  was  a  mill.  This  being  settled,  we  can 
imagine,  from,  what  has  been  said  above,  what  its  essential 
features  must  have  been.  Apparently  this  mill  was  supposed 
to  represent  the  Athenian  Republic,  and  as  the  play  was 
directed  against  Cleon,  there  is  reason  to  believe  that  Cleon 
was  represented  as  being  the  manager,  who  ran  the  mill  for 
the  people.  The  allies  may  have  appeared  as  farmers,  who 
were  obliged  to  bring  a  part  of  their  produce  to  their  master, 
under  control  of  the  manager  and  his  appointed  agents.  Here 
was  a  good  chance  to  show  up  the  manager  as  a  sort  of  tyrant, 
who  robbed  his  master,  besides  demanding  money  from  the 
farmers  and  exacting  the  hardest  terms  from  them. 

It  is  not  easy,  it  is  true,  to  see  how  a  plot  of  this  kind 
could  have  admitted  envoys,  nor  what  business  the  god 
Dionysus  pursued  by  sycophants  had  in  it,  to  whom  reference 

1 H.  Schrader,  ijber  den  Ghor  in  Aristophanes  Babyloniern,  Philologus,  vol. 
xlii.,  1884. 

'  Hesj'chius,  'Ea/j.iuv  6  5^/xos  and  BajSvXdivioi.  Cf .  Suidas,  Ba/SuXwi'ioi.  Fritzsehe 
{De  Bahyloniis  Aristophanis  Commentatio,  p.  17)  refuses  to  believe  that  a 
comic  chorus  could  have  been  composed  of  slaves.  But  do  we  not  know  that 
a  large  number  of  tragic  choruses  represented  slaves  ?  Why  should  the  same 
not  have  been  the  case  in  comedy  ?  Cf .  fragments  64,  66,  79,  88  and  97  of  the 
Babylonians  in  the  Comic,  att.  fragm.  i.  of  Kock. 

3  H.  Schrader,  loco  citat.  p.  580.  Gilbert  already  held  this  opinion,  Beitrage, 
p.  148. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  43 

is  made  in  two  fragments.^  But  it  must  not  be  forgotten  that 
ancient  comedy  was  essentially  fanciful  in  its  conceits,  and 
that  its  episodes  frequently  bore  little  or  no  relation  to  the 
main  subject.  Had  the  Acharnians  or  the  Knights  been  lost, 
and  if  we  merely  knew  that  the  former  play  represented  an 
Athenian  peasant  who  had  made  a  treaty  of  peace  for  himself 
alone,  or  that  the  latter  play  placed  the  house  of  Demus  and 
the  rivalries  of  his  servants  upon  the  stage,  two  things  would 
be  hard  for  us  to  understand.  First,  how  it  was  possible,  in 
the  Acharnians,  to  see  Euripides  at  home,  surrounded  by  his 
cast-off  tragic  garments  ;  and,  secondly,  how,  in  the  Knights, 
the  poet  had  managed  to  introduce  the  account  of  a  debate 
before  the  Senate.  In  compositions  of  this  kind  severe  logic 
has  no  place.  It  is  enough  that  the  hypothesis  as  to  the  plot 
of  the  Balylonians  just  suggested  seems  to  fit  in  best  with  the 
general  facts  of  which  we  have  knowledge.  We  need  not 
seek  to  guess  how  the  plot  was  developed  from  scene  to  scene, 
nor  what  inconsistencies  it  contained. 

It  is  true  that  some  scholars  have  thought  that  Aristophanes 
alludes  to  a  scene  of  his  Babylonians  in  a  passage  in  the 
AcharniaTis,  which  was  performed  in  the  year  following. 
Dicaeopolis  there  speaks  of  the  joy  he  felt  "  a  year  ago " 
when  he  saw  Cleon  "  disgorge  the  five  talents,"  and  he  adds 
that  he  loves  the  Knights  for  this  good  deed.'^  According  to 
a  rather  too  ingenious  critic,  this  passage  recalled  a  scene  in 
the  Babylonians,  in  which  Cleon,  hard-pressed  by  the  Knights, 
actually  and  coram  publico,  vomited  five  talents  that  he  had 
wrung  from  the  allies.^  I  think  this  interpretation  is  aljso- 
lutely  inadmissible.  Not  only  is  it  difficult  to  imagine  such  a 
scene,  but  this  interpretation  also  assumes  that  the  Knights 

^Fragm.  70  and  71,  Kock.  So  far  as  the  envoys  are  concerned,  there  is 
nothing  to  prevent  our  assuming  that  the  trembling  farmers  came  to  beseech 
the  manager  to  procure  them  a  reduction  of  their  dues,  and  that,  in  order  to 
succeed,  they  indulged  in  the  basest  of  flattery.  Neither  of  the  fragments 
justifies  the  opinion  according  to  which  these  envoys  were  a  parody  on  the 
embassy  of  Gorgias  in  behalf  of  Leontini  (Bergk,  Ranke,  Gilbert).  And  yet 
it  is  not  wholly  inadmissible. 

*  A  chamians,  11.  5-8. 

'Van  Leeuwen,  Acharnians,  The  Hague,  1901,  note  to  v.  6. 


44  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

were  given  an  important  part  in  it,  of  whom  no  mention  is 
anywhere  made ;  and  if  the  Knights  had  played  this  part  in 
the  Babylonians,  it  is  rather  surprising  that  not  a  word  should 
be  said  about  this  in  the  Knights.  Now,  quite  to  the  contrary, 
the  parabasis  of  the  latter  play  seems  to  indicate  clearly  that 
the  poet's  friendly  relations  with  the  young  aristocrats  were 
at  that  time  quite  recent,  and  had  not  previously  existed. 
The  allusion  in  the  Acharnians  must  therefore  be  to  another 
occurrence,  which  I  shall  try  to  explain  later. 

Though  there  are  various  ways  of  conceiving  the  part  given 
to  Cleon  in  the  play,  neither  the  fact  that  he  had  a  part  nor 
its  importance  is  to  be  doubted.  So  much  is  certain.  On  this 
point  the  testimony  of  the  scholiast  quoted  above  is  confirmed 
by  that  of  Aristophanes  in  the  Peace}  The  influence  that  Cleon 
exerted  at  this  time,  first  acquired  in  the  affair  of  the  Myti- 
leneans,  must  have  made  a  profound  impression  on  the  youthful 
poet.  From  this  time  on,  he  began  to  regard  him  as  the  man 
who  instigated  and  was  responsible  for  all  the  evils  from  which 
the  Athenian  democracy  appeared  to  be  suffering.  Or  rather, 
with  his  vivid  imagination,  Aristophanes  saw  in  him  the  per- 
sonification of  these  evils,  and  presently  arrived  at  the  very 
sincere  conviction  that,  by  overthrowing  the  one,  he  could 
remove  the  other. 

The  play  was  performed  at  the  Great  Dionysia,  as  we  have 
said.  This  was  the  time  when  the  allies  brought  their  annual 
tribute  to  Athens,  and  they  did  not  fail  to  attend  the 
celebrations  of  the  season.^  We  can  understand  with  what 
feelings  they  welcomed  this  virulent  satire  on  their  oppressors. 
We  do  not  know  positively  how  Aristophanes,  or  rather 
Callistratus,  who  lent  his  name  to  the  play,  ranked  in  the 
competition,  but  it  appears  certain  that,  had  he  received  a 
prize,  he  would  not  have  failed  to  boast  of  it  later  on.  It  is, 
therefore,  most  probable  that  he  was  awarded  neither  a  first 
nor  a  second  prize.  This  was  not  for  lack  of  support  given  to 
his  play  by  a  large  and  influential  party ;  without  it,  however 
great  his  courage,  the  poet  would  not  have  dared  to  run  the 

1  Peace,  11.  759-760. 

"^Acharnians,  11.  643-644,  and  scliolia  to  1.  377. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  45 

risk  to  which  he  exposed  himself.  Such  a  comedy  was  possible 
only  where  a  certain  consensus  of  public  opinion  backed  it  up. 
Doubtless  it  owed  its  existence  to  the  majority  that  had  sup- 
ported Uiodotus  in  the  affair  of  the  Mytileneans.  On  that 
day  a  powerful  sentiment  had  manifested  itself,  and  the  poet, 
encouraged  by  the  circles  in  which  he  moved,  thought  to  find 
in  them  a  bulwark  upon  which  he  could  count.  Perhaps  he 
had  not  been  entirely  mistaken.  There  is  every  reason  to 
believe  that,  on  the  day  of  the  competition,  he  was  vigorously 
supported  in  the  theatre  by  his  friends,  by  a  considerable 
part  of  the  audience,  especially  by  the  country-folk,  who  were 
hostile  to  the  demagogues,  and  finally  by  the  strangers  who 
were  present.  On  the  other  hand,  how  could  such  a  satire  on 
the  Republic  have  failed  to  call  forth  violent  protests,  not- 
withstanding the  buffoonery  in  which  the  poet  had  been 
careful  to  clothe  it  ?  Without  doubt,  his  chief  attack  was 
directed  against  Cleon ;  it  was  at  his  door  that  he  laid  all  the 
horrors  of  the  policy  that  he  condemned,  but,  in  substance, 
this  policy  had  been  approved  by  the  people,  and  it  was  hardly 
avoidable  that  they  should  feel  somewhat  offended. 

This  was  enough  to  induce  Cleon  to  believe  that  he  could 
get  his  aggressor  punished.  Everything  led  him  to  make  the 
attempt :  his  own  interest,  in  the  first  place,  and  then  his 
quite  natural  resentment.  He  could  not  have  been  indifferent 
to  the  rebuff  he  had  received  in  the  affair  of  the  Mytileneans. 
At  that  juncture  he  had  encountered  an  unforeseen  opposition, 
which  was  not  accidental  but  systematic,  for  it  sprang  from  a 
policy  opposed  to  his  own.  And  therein  lay  cause  for  anxiety. 
Now  Aristophanes'  comedy  proved  to  him  that  this  opposition 
was  seeking  to  organize,  that  it  was  growing  bolder  and  that  it 
aimed  at  spreadmg.  It  had  to  be  checked  by  vigorous  measures. 
Moreover,  in  this  instance,  considerations  of  state  seemed  to 
fall  in  with  his  personal  interests.  While  the  policy  pursued 
against  the  allies  could  be  freely  discussed  in  the  assembly  of 
the  people,  was  it  not  culpable  leniency  to  allow  accusations  to 
be  brought  against  it  in  their  very  presence  ?  And  was  not 
the  man  who  thus  denounced  the  oppression  practised  by 
Athens,  in  the  presence  of   the  very  people  who  were  being 

E 


46  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

oppressed  and  at  the  risk  of  forcing  them  into  open  rebellion 
— was  he  not  acting  like  a  disloyal  citizen  ? 

These  considerations  decided  Cleon ;    he  resolved  to  avenge 
the  Eepublic  and  to  revenge  himself. 


IV 

Just  how  did  he  go  about  it  ?  The  best  way  to  discover 
this  seems  to  be  to  turn  to  Aristophanes'  own  testimony. 

In  the  Acharnians'^  Dicaeopolis  says :  "  I  have  not  forgotten 
what  I  suffered  at  Cleon's  hands  for  last  year's  comedy.  He 
dragged  me  before  the  Senate,  and  there  he  made  outrageous 
charges  against  me,  overwhelmed  me  with  calumnies,  came 
down  roaring  on  me  like  a  torrent  and  lathered  ^  me  in  such 
a  way  that  I  almost  perished  in  that  unsavory  affair." 

Farther  on  ^  the  same  person  adds  :  "  To-day,  at  least,  Cleon 
will  not  be  able  to  say  that  I  insult  the  Eepublic  in  the 
presence  of  strangers,  for  we  are  just  among  ourselves  at  the 
Lenaea,  and  the  strangers  have  not  yet  arrived." 

These  two  passages,  taken  together,  seem  to  be  of  a  kind  to 
inform  us  quite  accurately  of  what  took  place.  But  at  the 
very  outset  a  difficulty  presents  itself,  about  which  the  com- 
mentators hold  various  views.  Dicaeopolis,  who  says  these 
things,  quits  his  role  for  a  moment  and  speaks  in  the  name  of 
the  poet.  Who  is  the  poet  ?  Is  it  Callistratus,  who  lent 
Aristophanes  his  name  ?     Is  it  Aristophanes  himself  ? 

Several  scholars  think  that  the  defendant  must  have  been 
Callistratus ;  they  call  attention  to  the  fact  that  the  play  was 
regarded  as  his,  that  he  had  accepted  responsibility  for  it 
when  he  brought  it  out  as  his  own  in  the  competition,  and 
that,  in  all  probability,  the  great  mass  of  the  public  did  not 
know  the  name  of  its  real  author.      Others  again  are  of  the 

^  Acharniaiis,  1.  377  et  seq. 

2  For  "  came  down  roaring  on  me  like  a  torrent "  and  for  "  lathered  "  I  am 
indebted  to  Mr.  W.  W.  Merry's  note  to  verse  .381.  I  have  repeatedly  borrowed 
from  that  editor's  excellent  English  versions.     [Translator.] 

^  Acharnians,  1.  502  et  seq. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  47 

opinion  that,  in  a  case  like  this,  the  secret  was  an  open  one, 
that  Aristophanes  was  certainly  known  as  the  author  of  the 
Acharnians  as  soon  as  the  play  was  performed,  and  that  he 
had  likewise  been  known  as  the  author  of  the  Bahyloniayis 
in  the  preceding  year ;  so,  they  contend,  he  was  the  person 
with  whom  Cleon  had  to  deal  directly.^  This  second  opinion 
seems  to  me  to  be  correct,  but  it  calls  for  some  explanation. 

Aristophanes  borrowed  the  names  of  others,  for  a  certain 
number  of  his  plays  at  least,  during  the  greater  part  of  his 
life.  It  appears  that  his  reasons  for  doing  this  were  not 
always  the  same ;  but  it  would  be  a  hard  task  to  discover 
them,  and  here  we  have  to  deal  only  with  his  first  plays. 
Now,  as  far  as  these  are  concerned,  he  has  himself  given  a  very 
concise  explanation  of  his  motives  in  the  parabasis  of  the 
Knights — the  first  comedy  he  brought  out  under  his  own 
name,  in  424.  In  speaking  of  the  Banqueters,  he  says,  in 
allegorical  language,  that,  as  he  was  at  that  time  still  too 
young  to  acknowledge  his  child,  he  had  abandoned  it,  and  that 
somebody  else  had  taken  it  up.  He  adds  that,  if  he  has  not 
yet  produced  anything  under  his  own  name — and  this,  of 
course,  applies  also  to  the  Babylonians — it  is  because  he  knew 
the  exacting  taste  of  the  Athenians  and  also  how  hard  a  task 
it  was  to  write  a  successful  comedy.  So  he  had  preferred  to 
serve  his  apprenticeship  as  a  rower,  before  taking  the  helm  of 
the  ship  himself .2  It  appears  at  once  that  none  of  these 
reasons  implies  the  existence  of  any  secret. 

If  he  thought  himself  "  too  young,"  he,  no  doubt,  meant  too 
young  to  brave  the  decision  of  the  archon,  whose  duty  it  was 
to  make  a  choice  among  the  competitors,  and  to  allow  only 
three  of  them  to  produce  their  plays.  We  can  readily  under- 
stand that  this  official,  who  had  to  arrange  the  celebration  of 
the  feast,  and  was  responsible  for  its  success,  would  not  be 
much  inclined  to  take  up  a  beginner,  who  was  still  a  very 
young  man.     But  as  soon  as  the  beginner's  play  was  offered  by 

1  Kaibel,  art.  "Aristophanes,"  No.  12,  Pauly-Wissowa,  pp.  973-974,  by  whom 
the  principal  earlier  writings  on  this  subject  are  mentioned.  Cf.  Busolt, 
Oriech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1060,  note  1. 

^Knights,  1.  512  et  seq. 


48  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

a  well-known  poet,  who  made  himself  responsible  for  it  and 
who  consented  to  offer  his  name  as  guarantee,  it  immediately 
became  a  different  matter.  The  archon  was  quite  indifferent 
to  questions  of  literary  ownership,  and  cared  very  little  about 
knowing  who  the  real  author  was ;  the  less  so,  as  collaboration 
seems  to  have  been  quite  frequent  in  the  writing  of  comedies. 
The  name  of  Callistratus  was  in  itself  a  guarantee,  and  that 
was  all  that  he  required. 

When  once  Aristophanes  had  officially  transferred  the 
ownership  of  his  work  to  the  man  who  lent  it  his  name, 
there  was  no  reason  whatever  to  make  a  secret  of  the  true 
facts,  especially  when  the  play  had  already  been  accepted. 
The  other  motive  he  mentions  occasioned  just  as  little  need 
for  doing  so.  The  apprenticeship  of  which  he  speaks  seems  to 
refer  chiefly  to  the  technical  part  of  his  task.  Evidently  con- 
siderable experience  in  the  usages  of  the  theatre  was  necessary 
in  order  to  stage  a  comedy  after  the  fashion  of  the  day.  A 
young  man,  lacking  both  authority  and  experience,  even  if 
endowed  with  the  most  undoubted  dramatic  talent,  would  not 
be  equal  to  the  task  of  devising  the  costumes  and  the  masks, 
of  arranging  the  stage  setting,  regulating  the  entries  and  the 
exits,  the  action  and  pantomime  of  the  actors,  and,  above  all, 
the  dances  and  songs  of  the  chorus — in  a  word,  of  instructing 
this  whole  array  of  artists,  exacting  their  obedience,  and 
making  them  subordinate  themselves  to  a  single  interpretation 
of  the  play.  In  all  this  difficult  and  fatiguing  business 
Aristophanes  must  needs  have  given  Callistratus  precedence ; 
but  evidently  that  does  not  imply  that  he  was  not  present  at 
the  rehearsals,  or  that  he  hid  behind  the  scenes  during  their 
progress.  It  is  even  likely  that  he  himself  acted  in  his  plays, 
and  it  has  been  surmised,  not  without  probability,  that  he 
must  personally  have  taken  the  part  of  Dicaeopolis,  who  spoke 
in  his  name.  Even  if  this  was  not  the  case,  it  must,  at  any 
rate,  be  admitted  that  he  took  part  in  the  preparations  for  the 
performance,  and  that  as  a  consequence  he  could  not  have 
failed  to  be  known  as  the  real  author  to  the  whole  theatrical 
company,  such  as  the  actors,  the  members  of  the  chorus, 
the  supernumeraries   and   the   slaves  employed  on  the  stage. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  49 

Surely  it  is  hard  to  believe  that  all  these  people  would  have 
kept  the  secret. 

It  is  clear  too  that  this  secret  was  kept  even  less  carefully  in 
the  clubs  of  Athens.  It  is  a  strange  misconception  to  imagine 
that  a  comic  poet  of  that  day,  and  especially  that  Aristo- 
phanes, wrote  his  plays  after  the  fashion  of  Euripides,  at  home, 
in  his  study  and  without  telling  anybody  a  word  about  them. 
Nay,  the  comedies  themselves  seem  to  reveal  to  us  that  they 
had  their  first  origin  in  merry  gatherings,  at  which  it  was  the 
fashion  to  joke,  to  make  fun  of  people,  and  to  invent  all  sorts 
of  nonsense.  Of  course  they  were  not  written  in  such  sur- 
roundings ;  but  many  a  scene  must  have  been  sketched  in  this 
way,  among  friends,  as  one  idea  suggested  another.  Even  if 
the  political  plays,  such  as  the  Babylonians  and  the  Knicjhts, 
were  not,  properly  speaking,  conceived  at  these  gatherings,  they 
were  certainly  tried  there,  and  perhaps  read  aloud  and  applauded 
before  their  performance.  And  he  who  read  them  was  of 
course  the  poet,  a  born  pamphleteer,  who  found  there,  and 
there  alone,  the  surroundings  which  he  needed  for  the  production 
of  his  masterpieces.  Indeed,  does  he  not  make  this  clear 
himself  when,  in  his  Knights,  he  tells  us  ^  that  many  people 
had  long  been  surprised  that  he  had  not  yet  produced  anything 
under  his  own  name,  and  that  they  were  urging  him  to  com- 
pete openly  ?  Who  were  these  people,  if  not  his  companions  ? 
And  how  would  this  idea  have  occurred  to  them  if  the  young 
poet  had  not  been  known  as  the  author  of  the  plays  that  he 
had  entrusted  to  Callistratus  ? 

This  being  the  case,  we  cannot  doubt  that  Cleon  made  a 
direct  attack  on  his  real  adversary.  The  evidence  which  the 
ancient  commentators  collected  does  not  give  us  any  more 
precise  information  about  these  attacks  than  do  the  above 
cited  passages  from  Aristophanes'  own  writings.  One  of 
them,  however,  adds  that  Cleon  brought  a  suit  impugning  the 
genuineness  of  the  poet's  citizenship.^  If  this  is  correct,  it  is 
clear  that  there  is  at  least  a  confusion  of  dates  in  this  state- 
ment. This  second  suit  cannot  be  contemporaneous  with  the 
first,  that  is,  earlier  than  the  Acharnians,  for  in  the  passages  of 
^Knights,  1.  512.  ^gchol.  Acharnians,  1.  377. 


50  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

that  play  in  which  Aristophanes  alludes  so  explicitly  to  his 
troubles  with  Cleon,  there  is  not  a  word  bearing  on  this 
matter.  In  point  of  fact,  this  suit  was  brought,  not  only 
after  the  performance  of  the  Acharnians,  but  even  after  that 
of  the  Kniyhts.  For  the  present  we  do  not  need  to  deal 
with  it. 

To  make  an  accusation  before  the  Senate  was  an  unusual 
proceeding,  applicable  to  certain  offences  which  had  not  been 
formally  defined  by  law.  In  such  cases  the  Senate  did  not 
pass  judgment  according  to  a  fixed  written  law,  but  according 
to  the  best  interests  of  the  people.^  We  can  understand  that 
Aristophanes  was  alarmed.  The  passage  above  quoted  shows 
how  great  he  thought  his  danger  and  how  violent  the  attacks  of 
Cleon  were.  The  latter  seems  very  shrewdly  to  have  ignored 
his  personal  grievances.  He  accused  the  poet  of  "  having 
spoken  ill  of  the  city  in  the  presence  of  strangers,"  and  of 
having  "  insulted  public  officials,  elected  or  chosen  by  lot." 
We  do  not  know  positively  what  penalty  Aristophanes  would 
have  suffered  had  he  been  found  guilty.  An  ancient  authority 
informs  us  that  it  was  one  of  the  severest,  without  further 
defining  it.^  The  penalty  probably  varied  within  certain 
limits,  but  the  poet  most  certainly  ran  a  heavy  risk. 

It  is  a  great  pity  that  the  various  stages  of  this  affair  are 
not  known.  All  that  we  can  say  is  that  Aristophanes  came 
out  of  it  unscathed :  his  tone  in  the  Acharnians  gives  decisive 
proof  of  this.  If  we  choose,  we  may  surmise  that  the  influence 
of  some  powerful  friends  stood  him  in  good  stead.  But  even 
so,  it  must  not  be  forgotten  that  the  Athenian  Senate  was  not 
at  this  time  at  all  an  aristocratic  body.     As  its  members  were 

^  Harpocration,  WirayyeKla,  Pollux,  viii.  51.  The  passage  in  Hie  Polity 
of  the  Athenians  attributed  to  Xenophon  (ii.  18),  in  which  he  says  "the 
Athenians  do  not  permit  the  people  to  be  made  the  subject  of  comedy  nor  to 
be  ill  spoken  of,"  does  not  seem  to  refer  to  a  formal  written  law.  At  any 
rate,  such  a  law  did  not  exist  in  426,  for,  had  it  existed,  Cleon  would  have 
prosecuted  Aristophanes  before  a  court  and  not  before  the  Senate. 

^  Harpocration,  loc.  cit.  Aristotle's  account,  Constitution  of  Athens,  45, 
indicates  that  before  the  introduction  of  the  appeal  to  the  people,  the  Senate 
could,  in  certain  cases,  even  pronounce  sentence  of  death.  It  is  clear  that 
this  cannot  apply  here. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  51 

simply  chosen  by  lot  every  year,  it  seeins  certain  that  it  was  at 
that  time  open  to  all  classes  of  society,  even  to  the  very  poorest.^ 
[Therefore  if  the  Senate  showed  a  friendly  disposition  toward 
Aristophanes,  we  may  be  sure  it  was  not  owing  to  any  veiled 
sympathy  with  the  opposition.  It  is  more  likely  that  the  poet, 
or  his  patrons,  succeeded  in  showing  that  the  prosecution  mis- 
interpreted his  intentions,  and  that,  in  fact,  he  had  not  wished 
to  attack  the  people,  but  the  politicians.  Furthermore,  the 
Athenian  people  as  a  whole,  and  without  distinction  of  party, 
seem  to  have  been  kindly  disposed  toward  comedy.  They 
liked  it  just  as  it  was,  with  its  unbridled  license,  and  they  did 
not  care  to  have  it  made  tiresome  under  the  pretext  of  dis- 
ciplining it.  The  restrictive  law  which  Pericles  had  passed  in 
440  was  enforced  for  three  years  only;  since  its  abrogation 
the  people  had  become  so  well  accustomed  to  all  the  auda- 
cities of  comedy  that  they  no  longer  attached  great  importance 
to  them. 

So  it  probably  came  about  that  CI  eon's  high-sounding  wrath 
was  all  in  vain.  The  words  of  Aristophanes,  "  I  almost 
perished,"  appear  simply  to  indicate  that  his  adversary 
managed  to  get  together  a  fairly  strong  minority.  And  yet 
the  argument  drawn  from  the  presence  of  strangers  must  have 
made  an  impression.  The  poet  had  observed  this,  and  when, 
in  the  Acharnians,  he  was  about  to  renew  his  attacks  upon 
the  prevailing  policy,  he  took  care  to  call  attention  to  the  fact 
that  he  was  speaking  to  the  citizens  only,  at  a  time  when  the 
strangers  had  not  yet  arrived. 

Indeed,  this  was  the  only  lesson  he  learned  from  this  trying 
experience,  which  might  have  turned  out  badly.  To  change 
his  style,  to  renounce  political  comedy,  to  forget  Cleon — of  this 
he  was  incapable.  His  impetuous  nature  urged  him  on  to  the 
combat,  his  friends  summoned  him  to  it,  his  interest  and  his 
honor  as  a  poet  were  involved  in  it.  He  waited  for  an 
opportunity  to  renew  the  fight,  and  the  opportunity  soon  pre- 
sented itself,  because  he  was  waiting  for  it. 

^  Schoemann-Lipsius,  Griechische  AltertliiLmer,  i.  p.  396. 


^il 


52  THE  BEGINNING  OF 


Still,  it  did  not  come  immediately.  Indeed,  it  is  worth 
noting  that  in  the  following  year,  425,  Aristophanes  neither 
attacked  Cleon  personally  nor  even  the  demagogues  as  a  class. 

At  the  Lenaean  festival  of  that  year  he  brought  out  the 
,  ^  Acharnians,  an  ardent  declaration  in  favor  of  peace.^  It  may 
i^"*!^  be  that  one  of  his  lost  j)lays  was  performed  at  the  Great 
Dionysia  of  the  same  year.  We  cannot  affirm  that  this  was 
the  case.  The  Acharnians,  therefore,  affords  us  the  only  clue 
in  our  attempt  to  gain  an  idea  of  what  was  in  his  mind  at 
that  time.  In  this  instance,  we  have  to  deal  with  a  play  which 
is  still  extant,  and  consequently  we  can  at  least  argue  from 
well-established  evidence. 

The  first  thing  that  strikes  one  in  this  play  is  that 
Cleon  does  not  appear  in  it.  A  few  satirical  allusions  to  his 
misfortunes,  or  to  his  vices,  would  hardly  deserve  to  be  men- 
tioned, were  it  not  that  one  of  them  calls  for  an  explanation. 
I  have  already  cited  this  in  a  previous  chapter,  in  order  to 
point  out  that  one  of  the  methods  of  interpreting  it  must 
be  regarded  as  incorrect. 

What  is  the  significance  of  the  joy,  which,  at  the  beginning 
of  the  play,  Dicaeopolis  declares  he  felt  in  the  preceding  year 
when,  thanks  to  the  knights,  Cleon  was  compelled  to  "  dis- 
gorge his  five  talents  "  ?  ^  One  of  the  scholiasts,  following  the 
historian  Theopompus,  tells  us  that  Cleon  had  received  five 
talents  from  the  allies  for  proposing  to  the  people  a  reduction 
of  tribute  in  their  favor,  and  that  the  knights  got  wind  of 
this  bargain  and  obliged  him  to  return  the  money .^  Taken 
literally,  this  explanation  seems  inadmissible ;  and  indeed  it  is 
so.^  We  cannot  imagine  that  a  suit  was  brought  against 
Cleon  by  the  knights  as  a  class,  for  they  did  not  constitute  a 

^Argument  of  the  Acharnians. 

"^Acharnians,  1.  5,  rois  irivre  roKavTois,  oh  WKiuv  i^-rjfiecre  .   .   . 
^Schol.  Acharnians,  1.  6. 

■•  MuUer-Striibing,  Aristophanes  tmd  die  historische  Kritik,  Leipzig,  1873, 
pp.  119-181. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  53 

body  possessing  a  civic  personality.  It  is  quite  as  difficult  to 
believe  that  some  of  their  number,  secretly  supported  by  the 
rest,  should  have  charged  Cleon  with  venality,  and  that 
they  should  have  brought  about  his  conviction.  Such  a  con- 
viction would,  at  least  for  a  long  time,  have  destroyed  Cleon's 
authority,  which,  quite  on  the  contrary,  seems  to  have  been 
more  firmly  established  than  ever  in  425.  Moreover,  we  meet 
with  no  allusion  whatever  to  such  an  outcome  in  the  later 
plays  of  Aristophanes. 

Still,  these  considerations  do  not  warrant  us,  as  fair  critics, 
in  purely  and  simply  rejecting  the  statement  of  Theopompus. 
Most  probably  the  commentator  misunderstood  this  statement, 
and  attached  greater  importance  to  it  than  it  really  had. 

The  allusion  of  Aristophanes  and  that  of  the  historian  are 
sufficiently  explained,  if  we  assume  that,  after  Cleon  had  in 
that  year  proposed  to  reduce  the  contributions  of  some  of  the 
allies,  his  proposal  was  rejected  owing  to  the  representations  of 
some  orator  belonging  to  the  class  of  the  knights.  Cleon's 
ill-wishers  were  sure  to  insinuate  that  he  had  demanded  pay 
from  the  interested  parties  for  the  position  he  took,  and  that, 
thanks  to  the  vigilance  of  his  adversaries,  he  had  been  forced 
to  return  the  money.  This  is  the  tale  which  Aristophanes 
took  up  and  interpreted  after  his  own  fashion,  and  which 
Theopompus  perhaps  likewise  accepted  as  the  truth.^ 

Further  on  in  the  play  the  same  Dicaeopolis  defies  Cleon : 
"  Let  him  scheme  and  intrigue  against  me  as  much  as  he 
likes.  Eight  is  on  my  side  and  justice  will  be  my  ally. 
I,  at  any  rate,  need  not  fear  that  I  shall  be  convicted  of  being 
a  bad  citizen  and  a  debauchee,  as  he  has  been."  -  Does  this 
defiance  refer  to  a  renewal  of  hostilities  ?  That  is  hardly  pro- 
bable. It  merely  proves  that  at  this  time  Aristophanes  felt 
sufficiently  reassured  to  taunt  his  adversary. 

^  Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  994,  note  6,  has  suggested  another 
explanation.  He  surmises  that  Cleon  was  the  chief  of  the  treasurers 
('EWyivoTa/xiai)  in  427-426,  and  that,  in  this  capacity,  he  withheld,  an  account 
of  his  hostility  to  the  Knights,  the  sum  which  the  state  allowed  them  for 
forage,  and  which  amounted  to  five  talents.  This  would  then  be  the  sum  the 
Knights  forced  him  to  give  up. 

^  Achamians,  11.  659-664. 


54  THE  BEGINNING  OF 

But  these  words  were  uttered  casually  and  these  taunts 
were  of  no  consequence.  In  a  word,  Cleon  is  not  directly 
attacked  in  the  Archarnians ;  and  this  is  the  more  surprising 
when  we  recall  that  the  object  of  the  play  is  to  ridicule  the 
advocates  of  war  to  the  bitter  end,  and  that,  according  to  the 
formal  statement  of  Thucydides,  Cleon  was  the  most  decided 
opponent  of  all  proposals  making  for  peace.^  Shall  we  infer 
that  the  poet  was  moved  to  take  this  attitude  by  considerations 
of  prudence  ?  A  mere  semblance  of  probability  might  lead  us 
to  think  so ;  but  a  close  examination  of  the  play  affords  quite 
a  different  view  of  the  case,  and  gives  us  an  insight  into  the 
conflict  of  public  opinion  and  into  Aristophanes'  own  relation 
to  political  parties. 

And  first  let  us  observe  how  the  party  which  advocated  war 
to  the  bitter  end  is  impersonated  in  his  comedy.  Therein  lies, 
unless  I  am  mistaken,  the  decisive  point,  and  one  that  has  not 
yet  been  given  all  the  attention  it  merits. 

The  champions  of  war  are,  on  the  one  hand,  the  chorus, 
consisting  of  charcoal-burners  from  Acharnae,  and  on  the 
other,  the  taxiarch  Lamachus.  What  are  we  to  think  of 
them  respectively  ? 

Lamachus  cannot  be  regarded  as  a  representative  of  any  party. 
Neither  his  father,  Xenophanes,  nor  he  himself,  appears  to  have 
played  any  important  part  in  the  politics  of  the  day.  No- 
where does  Aristophanes  picture  him  as  being  associated  with 
the  demagogues,  and  nothing  in  his  play  indicates  a  desire 
to  decry  him  as  a  soldier-politician  or  as  the  tool  of  the 
popular  leaders.  The  man  he  seems  to  have  in  view  is  the 
professional  officer,  who  makes  a  livelihood  by  the  pursuit  of 
arms  and  who  would  not  amount  to  anything  in  the  state 
were  it  left  without  a  standing  army  after  the  re-establish- 
ment of  peace.  He  humorously  calls  him  "  Spoudarchides  "  ("a 
man  whose  ambition  it  is  to  command  "),  and  "  Mistharchides  " 
("  a  man  of  lucrative  commands  ").^     These  two  words  sum  up 

1  Thucydides,  v.  16.    This  statement  refers,  it  is  true,  to  the  year  422 ;  but  there 
is  every  reason  to  believe  that  Cleon's  attitude  in  this  matter  had  never  varied. 

^Acharnians,    11.    595  and   597.      For   the   word   (nrov8apxl87]s   cf.    Gilbert, 
Beitrdge,  p.  14,  note  1. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  55 

his  satirical  conception  of  this  type  of  man.  The  peasant 
Dicaeopolis,  speaking  for  the  poet,  is  set  against  this  class  of 
professional  men-at-arms,  to  whom,  in  case  of  war,  well-paid 
positions  are  given,  and  who  frequently  are  appointed  ambas- 
sadors, on  account  of  their  prominence  or  of  their  technical 
knowledge.^  He  abhors  the  very  profession  ;  those  who  follow 
it  are,  in  his  eyes,  the  natural  enemies  of  peace.  The  fact 
that,  in  this  passage,  Lamachus  has  the  honor  of  representing 
all  his  colleagues  is  probably  due  to  his  name,  which  smacks  of 
battle,  or  perhaps  to  some  other  personal  reason  of  which  we 
know  nothing.  At  all  events,  Aristophanes  made  no  attempt 
to  individualize  him.  Even  his  raillery  is  of  a  general 
character.  The  absurd  traits  which  he  imputes  to  him  are 
the  absurdities  of  the  profession,  and  he  carries  them  to  the 
point  of  caricature :  love  of  martial  array,  braggadocio,  and  a 
loud  voice,  fit  to  scare  children.  This  applies  also  to  the 
misfortunes  of  the  poor  taxiarch :  they  are  those  that  befall 
the  profession.  Thus  we  see  that  the  comedy  deals  harshly 
not  with  a  political  faction,  as  such,  but  with  that  liking  for 
war,  which  a  certain  class  of  citizens  entertained  from  purely 
personal  motives. 

The  Acharnians  who  constitute  the  chorus  are  true  pea- 
sants, just  such  as  Dicaeopolis ;  by  turns  wood-choppers, 
charcoal-burners  or  vintners.  In  time  of  peace  they  lived 
at  quite  a  distance  from  Athens,  in  their  big  village  of 
Acharnae  and  its  suburbs,  at  the  foot  of  Mt.  Parnes,  whose 
underwood  and  brakes  of  green  oak  they  exploited.  We  may 
be  sure  that  they  did  not  constitute  Cleon's  regular  supporters, 
and  that  these  honest  folk  had  nothing  in  common  with  the 
famished  clients  of  the  demagogues  who  battened  on  lawsuits 
and  delighted  in  the  debates  of  the  ecclesia.  Besides,  they 
formally  declare  that  they  detest  him."  Had  Aristophanes 
wished  to  represent  the  advocates  of  war  to  the  bitter  end  as 
the  mere  tools  of  those  politicians  whom  he  had  flayed  to  the 
very  quick  in  the  Babylonians,  he  would  not  have  brought  them 

^  Achatiiians,  11.  599-619. 

^A  charnians,  1.  300 :  ws  fxefiicrriKd  ae  KXiuivos  ^ti  fj.aWoi',  6v  Karare^iu)  toTctiv  Imriuffi 
KaTTVfxara. 


56  THE   BEGINNING  OF 

before  his  audience  in  the  costume  and  with  the  characteristics 
of  these  honest,  vigorous  labourers. 

His  train  of  thought  was  quite  different.  He  appraised 
the  situation  with  that  intuitive  acumen  which  he  more  than 
once  disphiyed.  Much  as  he  personally  abhorred  war,  he  felt 
at  this  juncture  that,  although  it  was  not  exactly  popular, 
it  was,  to  say  the  least,  accepted  with  faith  and  ardor 
by  a  very  large  number  of  Athenians,  without  distinction  of 
class  or  opinion,  and  perhaps  even  by  a  part  of  the  rural 
population  which  suffered  from  it  more  particularly.  Doubtless 
this  ardor  occasionally  showed  signs  of  lagging ;  people  longed 
for  peace,  complained  bitterly  of  all  the  hardships  they  had  to 
endure,  dreamed  of  their  fields,  of  a  quiet  and  easy  life,  of 
their  beautiful  rustic  festivals,  of  well-stocked  markets,  of 
smiling  and  bounteous  peace.  But  these  dreams  touched  the 
imagination  without  penetrating  into  the  depths  of  the  soul,  or 
reaching  the  mainsprings  of  the  will.  The  will  remained  firm; 
for  all  the  grievances  of  yesterday  were  always  present,  like  so 
many  fresh  wounds  that  the  war  inflamed  with  each  year 
that  passed.  To  have  pictured  on  the  stage  this  national 
struggle  as  the  work  of  a  political  party,  and,  above  all,  as  that 
of  a  politician  whom  no  one  esteemed  in  his  heart,  would  have 
meant  running  the  risk  of  gravely  ofifending  public  opinion. 
Aristophanes  was  much  too  shrewd  to  make  such  a  mistake. 

His  Acharnians  are  honest  in  their  convictions.  They 
instinctively  detest  Lacedaemon  as  the  hereditary  and  perfidious 
enemy  of  their  country.^  And,  what  is  more,  they  are  furious 
because  the  invader  has  devastated,  torn  up,  and  burnt  their 
vineyards.-  These  are  not  ridiculous  sentiments,  and  the  poet 
never  could  have  thought  of  making  fun  of  them.  If  the 
members  of  the  chorus  provoke  laughter,  it  is  only  in  their 
external  aspect.  It  was  the  fashion  among  the  Athenian  city 
folk  to  joke  about  these  rustics,  who  were  seen  in  the  streets 
of  the  town,  stick  in  hand,  driving  before  them  their  donkeys 
laden  with  great  bags  of  charcoal.^     Aristophanes  knew  how 

^Acharnians,  11.  290,  .308  :  o'iaiv  oSre  /3co/i6s  oiire  -wla-Tis  ovd'  SpKos  fx^vei. 
^Acharnians,  1.  226  :  o'icrL  Trap'  e/xoO  TrdXe/xos  ex^o^oToj  ay^erai  ruiv  ifxCiv  x'-'-'pl^^''- 
^Hesychius,  'Ax°-P'"-'^o'^  ^"O'- 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  57 

to  put  this  disposition  to  jest  about  them  to  good  use.  He 
drew  a  humorous  picture  of  them,  as  raging  old  men  armed 
with  cudgels,  who  shout,  run  about  and  carry  on ;  he  was 
careful  not  to  forget  the  bag  of  charcoal ;  he  calls  it  their 
beloved  child  which  they  will  save  at  any  cost.^  Add  to  this 
their  make-up,  their  gestures,  their  by-play  and  dances,  and 
you  have  all  that  is  needed  to  delight  a  popular  audience.  IJut 
this  buffoonery  was  not  directed  against  the  sound  morals  of 
these  peasants,  whom  the  poet  loved  and  whom  he  had  not  the 
slightest  intention  of  treating  as  enemies.  And  besides,  their 
warlike  rage  is  nothing  but  a  folly  of  short  duration,  or  rather 
a  misunderstanding.  They  have  been  duped.  Dicaeopolis 
needs  but  to  open  their  eyes,  and  we  shall  again  see  their 
peaceable  nature  assert  itself. 

Thus,  according  to  Aristophanes,  the  war  party  consists,  in 
the  first  place,  of  a  lot  of  honest  and  sincerely  patriotic  people, 
instinctive  friends  of  peace  and  fruitful  labor,  but  for  the 
moment  carried  away  by  quite  legitimate  feelings  which  they 
exaggerate,  and  led  astray  by  false  ideas  which  others  have 
foisted  upon  them.  The  same  party,  furthermore,  consists  of 
certain  professional  military  men,  whom  the  war  supplies 
with  a  livelihood  and  heaps  with  honors,  and  who  would  be 
nobodies  without  it.  He  jokes  pleasantly  about  the  former 
group,  but  takes  good  care  not  to  lash  them.  The  second 
group  meet  with  harsher  treatment :  in  Aristophanes'  eyes  the 
valiant  Lamachus  is  nothing  but  a  contemptible  fellow  who 
plays  the  bully.  But  even  this  is  of  no  great  consequence  : 
this  pygmy  is  too  pitiable  a  figure  to  bear  the  weight  of 
satire.  The  poet's  satire  strikes  other  people,  of  whom  we 
must  now  speak. 

Aristophanes'  real  adversary  in  the  Acharnians,  the  chief 
butt  of  his  satire,  is  the  instigator  of  the  war,  Pericles,  who 
had  died  four  years  previously,  but  still  survived  in  his 
opinions,  which  were  always  present  to  the  minds  of  the 
Athenians,  where  they  had  taken  root  and,  as  it  w^ere, 
hardened   into   dogma. 

How  does  the  poet  make  his  attack  on  the  famous  statesman  ? 
1  Acharnians,  11.  326-340. 


58  THE   BEGINNING  OF 

He  does  not  put  him  on  the  boards  in  person ;  perhaps  there 
were  many  reasons  for  this  which  one  might  guess  at, 
but  I  beUeve  the  chief  consideration  was  that  it  would  have 
been  impossible,  unless  he  were  to  be  made  grotesquely  insig- 
nificant, to  bring  him  before  an  audience  without  making  him 
defend  his  political  attitude.  Now  that  would  have  been 
tantamount  to  introducing  an  appeal  to  sentiments  which 
comedy  had  above  all  to  avoid  awakening.  His  attack  is 
therefore  made  merely  by  means  of  speeches  and  narrative, 
while  Pericles  is  purposely  left  in  the  background  of  the  past. 
The  poet  takes  good  care  to  say  nothing  of  the  more  or  less 
cogent  or  specious  reasons  which,  in  fact,  he  might  have 
alleged.  Dicaeopolis  speaks  in  the  name  of  the  poet.^  We 
know  how  guardedly  he  does  it,  and  what  buffoonery  he  is 
careful  to  employ,  in  order  first  to  put  his  hearers  in  good 
humor.  But  let  us  examine  the  matter  more  closely.  Is 
Pericles  represented  in  this  speech  either  as  a  leader  of  the 
people  or  as  the  spokesman  of  a  political  party  ?  Not  at  all. 
He  appears  as  the  toy  of  a  woman,  as  the  slave  of  Aspasia's 
caprice;  and  the  very  disproportion  between  the  cause  and  the 
effect  casts  ridicule  on  his  eloquence.  The  thunder  of  his 
words  reverberated  through  peaceful  Greece,  his  speeches  let 
loose  a  tempest  and  upset  the  world ;  and  why  ?  Because  a 
few  courtesans  had  been  kidnapped !  Then  came  the  decree 
forbidding  the  Megarians  to  trade  with  Athens,  a  decree  which 
the  poet  succeeds  in  making  ridiculous  by  playing  upon  its 
very  provisions.  Thereupon  Lacedaemon  espoused  the  cause 
of  her  allies.  Would  not  Athens  have  done  as  much  had  her 
allies  been  interfered  with  ?  In  a  word,  all  the  motives  for 
war  amount  only  to  slight  and  insignificant  grievances,  rendered 
bitter  by  a  redoubtable  orator,  who,  purely  from  selfish  interest, 
managed  to  keep  the  Athenians  from  seeing  things  in  their 
true  light. 
-  j^e     Vln  its  form  the  attack  does  not  look  very  serious ;  but  we 

g;^*v5l^*'  "^^f  %«  must   grasp   the  intention  that  underlay  this  sportive   form. 
%,ix^^^ '  ■        Granted  that  the  facts  just  recited  are  mere  gossip,  the  infer- 

"     ^      -     ■     ence,  to  the  poet's  thinking,  is  that  war  was  actually  begun  on 

^  Acharjiians,   1.  496  e<  seg. 


ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER  59 

account  of  idle  bickerings,  which  a  true  statesman  would  have 
disregarded  with  contempt.  '  That  is  what  he  conveys  after  his 
own  fashion  in  the  language  of  comedy.  Little  does  he  care 
whether  the  details  are  true  or  false;  he  occupies  himself  with 
their  essential  truth.  In  his  eyes,  the  important  thing  is  that 
they  should,  in  a  humorous  way,  represent  the  kind  of  grievances 
that  brought  about  the  fatal  vote.  As  for  the  more  serious 
reasons,  those,  for  instance,  that  alone  struck  a  Thucydides, 
there  is  nothing  to  prove  that  he  did  not  perceive  them.  But 
then  these  reasons  would  have  justified  an  eternal  war,  for 
they  arose  from  the  very  conditions  that  governed  the  existence 
of  the  two  rival  states,  and  they  were  bound  to  endure  until 
one  or  the  other,  or  both  of  them  at  once,  were  completely 
exhausted.  Thus  there  was  the  choice  of  fighting  for  an  inde- 
finite time  or  of  making  peace  as  soon  as  possible,  and  seeking 
to  live  on  good  terms,  notwithstanding  the  permanent  causes 
of  conflict.  Aristophanes  thought  that  the  second  alternative 
was  the  better,  and  to-day  the  impartial  historian  apparently 
thinks  he  was  right.  This  being  the  case,  he,  no  doubt,  judged 
that  it  was  wiser  to  let  the  serious  grievances  slumber,  and  to 
speak  of  them  as  little  as  possible.  Indeed  he  did  not  speak 
of  them  at  all,  and  he  acted  wisely. 

Unless  I  am  mistaken,  this  feeling  of  patriotic  prudence  had 
a  great  deal  to  do  with  the  exceptional  reserve  which,  in  this 
instance,  he  maintained  toward  the  demagogues.  The  same 
considerations  that  had  kept  him  from  attributing  too  much 
importance  to  the  policy  of  Pericles,  even  though  he  openly 
opposed  it,  must  also  have  kept  him  from  letting  either  Cleon 
or  any  of  his  companions  appear  on  the  stage ;  they  even  kept 
him  from  directly  discussing  them.  He  did  not  wish  to  be 
obliged  to  impute  to  them  speeches  which  would  have  to  be  of 
a  kind  to  stir  up  a  part  of  his  audience,  if  they  were  to  retain 
any  degree  of  probability.  He  did  not  even  wish,  by  attacking 
them  too  savagely,  to  awaken  the  passions  that  divided  the 
Athenian  public  on  this  national  question.  The  feelings  to 
which  he  appealed  were  such  as  were  shared  by  all  to  a  greater 
or  less  degree.  Leaving  it  to  the  past  to  take  care  of  the 
burning  question  on  whom  the  true  responsibility  rested,  he 


(0^.<^• 


60  BEGINNING  OF  ARISTOPHANES'  CAREER 

let  it  appear  that  it  was  not  on  a  party,  but  on  a  single  man 
who  was  no  longer  alive.  He  purposely  ignored  prudent 
consideration  of  the  future,  of  deep-seated  and  lasting  rival- 
ries, of  the  inevitable  conflict  between  Athenian  democracy 
and  Spartan  oligarchy,  and  chose  to  insist  only  on  the  benefits 
of  peace  and  on  the  insignificance  of  the  sacrifice  of  self-esteem 
that  it  would  call  for  in  the  present  emergency. 

Thus  it  came  about  that,  by  way  of  exception,  he  wrote  a 
play  which  had  nothing  to  do  with  the  strife  of  parties,  and 
which  was  simply  and  solely  inspired  by  what  he  considered 
the  interests  of  the  nation.  It  even  happened  that,  as  if  to 
make  his  intentions  clearer,  he  pictured  his  habitual  allies  as 
momentarily  at  odds  :  he  made  the  peasants  of  Acharnae  oppose 
the  peasant  Dicaeopolis.  But  he  set  them  at  odds  merely 
for  a  moment,  so  that  he  might  presently  reconcile  them  and 
finally  bring  them  together  in  a  joyful  exodus,  celebrating 
the  pleasures  of  peace  which  they  had  re-established. 


\>^.i,^r  ^^^ 


CHAPTER    II 
THE  KNIGHTS 


Aristophanes'  war  upon  the  leaders  of  the  demagogical  party, 
which  had  apparently  been  suspended  while  he  was  writing 
the  Acharnians,  is  directly  afterwards  renewed  with  violence 
in  the  comedy  of  the  Knights,  performed  at  the  Lenaean 
festival  of  the  year  424,  and  consequently  written  in  the  last 
months  of  425.  So  far  as  its  pervading  spirit  is  concerned, 
this  play  is  a  sort  of  continuation  of  the  Babylonians ;  but  it 
appears  to  have  exceeded  the  latter  play  in  virulence.  At 
all  events  it  was  to  have  a  very  different  scope,  whether  this 
was  due  to  existing  circumstances  or  to  the  more  advanced 
thought  of  the  poet.  In  the  Bahylonians  the  rule  of  the 
demagogues  had  been  attacked  by  the  brilliant  pamphleteer  as 
the  instrument  of  a  hateful  tyranny  that  lay  heavily  upon  the 
allies  of  Athens.  In  that  play  it  was  merely  a  question  of 
excesses  of  a  very  special  sort,  such  as  are  closely  connected 
with  the  existence  of  a  maritime  confederacy.  In  the  Knights 
he  censures,  and  even  more  boldly,  the  domestic  government 
of  these  same  demagogues,  the  means  they  adopt  to  influence 
the  people,  indeed  all  the  principles  or  passions  that  animate 
them.  Although  he  speaks  only  of  Athens  and  of  his  own 
contemporaries,  he  is,  perforce,  led  to  touch  upon  certain 
matters  that  recur  more  or  less  at  all  periods  and  in  all  places, 
because  they  are  part  and  parcel  of  that  human  nature  on 
which  all  social  life  hinges. 

F 


62  THE  KNIGHTS 

What  led  Aristophanes  to  write  this  dramatic  pamphlet, 
perhaps  the  most  audacious  that  was  ever  put  upon  the  stage? 
This  is  the  question  which  it  is  our  duty  to  study  first.  We 
shall  thus  see  how  much  influence  it  is  proper  to  attribute  to 
the  various  political  parties  in  the  plot  of  his  play. 

A  glance  at  this  plot  reveals  that  it  is  based,  on  the  one 
hand,  upon  certain  political  incidents  of  the  day,  and,  on  the 
other,  upon  a  whole  array  of  reflections  that  have,  as  it  were, 
crystallized  about  these  incidents.  It  is  important  to  note 
this  distinction  at  the  very  outset.  / 

As   to   the   incidents,   they   were   the   deeds   and/political 
/-   successes  of  Cleon  in   425.     In  that  year   Cleon  was   for  a 
second  time  chosen  by  lot  to  exercise  the  functions  of  senator. 
This  made    it    possible    for    him   to   exert  a   preponderating 

/^  influence  on  the  grand  council  of  the  repviblic,  which  super- 

/  vised  the  administration  of  the  navy  and  that  of  the  treasury, 
discussed  with  the  generals  the  measures  to  be  undertaken, 
and  worked  out,  in  advance,  all  the  deliberations  of  the 
assembly.     It   was   probably   at   this  time  that  he   had   the 

K  pay  of  the  heliasts  raised  to  three  obols,  and  that  he  induced 
the  people  to  increase  the  tribute  imposed  upon  the  allies.^ 

But  his  influence  chiefly  manifested  itself  in  the  affair  at 
Pylus  and  Sphacteria.     There  is  no  need  to  recall  it  here  in 

//  detail.^  It  will  be  remembered  how  Demosthenes,  one  of  the 
most  energetic  and  intelligent  soldiers  of  this  period,  hit  upon 
the  happy  idea  of  occupying  a  position  on  the  west  coast  of 
Peloponnesus,  which  was  to  gather  about  an  Athenian  garrison 
the  numerous  enemies  that  Sparta  had  m  that  region,  and 
particularly  the  oppressed  Messenians  and  the  fugitive  helots. 
The  point  he  occupied  was  Pylus,  and  not  only  were  the 
Athenians  able  subsequently  to  repel  the  attempt  made  by  the 
Spartans  to  dislodge  them,  but,  what  was  more,  the  Pelopon- 
nesian  fleet  was  destroyed  by  the  Athenian  fleet.  Besides,  a 
body  of  Lacedaemonian  troops  was  blockaded  in  the  harbor  of 
Pylus,  on  the  little  island  Sphacteria,  and  it  was  not  very  long 
before  its  situation  became  desperate.     Since  the  beginning  of 

1  For  these  facts  consult  the  description  of  G.  Gilbert,  Beitriige,  pp.  177-194. 

2  For  the  entire  account  consult  Thucydides,  iv.  cap.  4-41. 


THE  KNIGHTS  63 

the  war  Athens  had  never  gained  so  decided  an  advantage. 
The  glory  of  it  fell,  in  the  first  instance,  to  Demosthenes,  who 
had  conceived  and  carried  out  the  successful  venture,  and  in 
the  next,  to  Nicias,  who  appears  to  have  been  sent  as  general 
to  conduct  the  campaign,  and  who  had  successfully  organized 
the  defence  of  Pylus  and  the  blockade  of  Sphacteria. 

Sparta  was  struck  with  consternation,  and  made  overtures 
.of  peace.  Cleon  prevented  their  being  accepted.  ISTo  doubt 
he  thought  Athens  could  be  more  exacting,  when  she  had  once 
forced  her  beleaguered  enemy  to  surrender.  But  the  campaign 
which  had  begun  so  brilliantly  was  prolonged  through  the 
Summer.  The  Spartans  who  were  blockaded  on  the  island 
secretly  received  provisions  and  refused  to  surrender.  The 
Athenian  generals  dared  not  make  an  attack  across  the  dense 
brakes  which  encircled  the  island  like  a  natural  rampart. 
Public  opinion  at  Athens  was  disturbed.  The  bad  weather 
was  sure  to  incapacitate  the  cruisers,  and  therefore  to  put  an 
end  to  the  blockade,  thus  permitting  the  Spartans  to  escape. 
People  began  to  wonder  how  the  matter  would  end. 

It  was  at  this  juncture  that  Cleon  interfered  in  a  decisive 
manner.  One  day,  after  publicly  finding  fault  with  the 
incapacity  and  the  inertness  of  the  generals,  he  declared,  with 
his  habitual  braggadocio,  that,  if  he  had  been  in  their  place,  he 
would  have  brought  the  whole  business  to  an  end  long  since. 
He  was  taken  at  his  word,  and  found  himself  entrusted,  by  a 
decree  of  the  assembly,  with  the  command  of  the  expedition, 
in  place  of  Nicias.  The  latter,  delighted  at  the  chance  of 
getting  even  with  him,  had  willingly  resigned  in  his  favor. 
The  demagogue  was  at  first  disconcerted,  but  he  accepted  the 
appointment,  and,  once  in  command,  he  displayed  intelligence 
and  energy.  He  collected  a  body  of  light  troops,  such  as  were 
needed  for  the  attack,  and  proceeded  to  Pylus,  where  he  made 
a  complete  plan  of  campaign  with  the  help  of  Demosthenes. 
An  accidental  fire  on  the  island  had  just  destroyed  a  part  of  the 
woods — a  lucky  chance  for  Cleon.  He  had  the  good  sense  to 
take  advantage  of  it.  The  assault,  under  his  lead,  had  the  best 
possible  success.  All  the  Spartans  who  did  not  perish  in  the 
ficfht  fell  into  the   hands  of   the  victors.     Cleon's  return  to 


64  THE   KNIGHTS 

Athens  was  a  triumph  ;  he  brought  with  him  nearly  three 
hundred  prisoners,  of  whom  a  hundred  and  twenty  were 
Spartans — precious  hostages  for  subsequent  negotiations.  The 
people  thought  that  now  they  were  in  a  safe  position  to 
dictate  their  own  terms  of  peace.  The  deeds  of  Demosthenes 
and  of  Mcias  were  forgotten.  Cleon  was  the  hero  of  the 
hour,  had  honors  heaped  upon  him,  and  gained  all  the  credit 
of  this  magnificent  success. 

The  unfairness  of  this  popular  verdict  seems  to  have  sug- 
gested to  Aristophanes  the  first  idea  of  his  play ;  at  all  events 
he  derived  from  it  the  conception  of  the  initial  scheme  upon 
which  the  plot  is  built  up.  But  this  scheme,  based,  as  we  have 
seen,  on  a  simple  incident,  could  at  best  have  produced  only  a 
play  of  transient  interest,  had  it  not  been  enriched  by  a  mass 
of  reflections  that  went  far  beyond  it. 

Cleon's  astonishing  good  luck  did  not  begin  at  Sphacteria. 
We  have  already  seen  what  manner  of  man  he  was  and  how 
he  began  his  career.  He  had  already  emerged  from  obscurity 
during  the  lifetime  of  Pericles,  and  a  few  years  had  suificed  to 
make  him  the  real  leader  of  Athenian  politics.  Success  of 
this  kind  must  have  seemed  scandalous  to  the  circles  in  which 
Aristophanes  moved.  If  they  had  used  calm  judgment,  they 
would  perhaps  have  recognized  that  it  had  a  partial  explanation 
in  certain  qualities  of  the  demagogue,  who  was  by  no  means  an . 
ordinary  man.  But  resentment  and  hatred,  whether  they  were 
warranted  or  not,  blinded  the  best  minds,  or  rather,  when 
they  discussed  his  successes,  their  natural  perspicacity  was 
directed  solely  to  laying  bare  the  viciousness  of  the  man  and  of 
the  whole  regime.  Moreover,  their  estimates,  fair  and  profound 
as  they  often  were,  but  incomplete  and  ex  parte,  became,  as  it 
were,  an  ever-growing  nucleus  about  which  base  slander  and 
insulting  innuendo  gathered.  And  so  it  came  about  that  the 
clubs  developed  a  caricatured  portrait  of  the  man  who  was  the 
object  of  universal  anger,  and,  together  with  it,  a  strong  anti- 
democratic doctrine.  We  shall  see  presently  with  how  great 
power  of  invention  the  comic  poet  managed  to  complete  this 
portrait,  to  make  an  issue  of  it,  to  adapt  it  for  the  comic  stage, 
how,  in  a  word,  he  stamped  it  with  his  own  mark.    As  for  the 


THE  KNIGHTS  65 

anti-democratic  doctrine,  we  must  not  seek  for  it  in  his  play,     ^i^^,-,  c. 
for,  in   its  complete   form,  it  does  not   appear   there   at   all.^ 
Indeed,  in  order  to  appreciate  to  what  extent  and  for  what 
reasons  he  gave  it  so  wide  a  berth,  it  is  necessary  to  gain  as 
exact  a  picture  of  it  as  possible  from  the  records  that  still 
permit  us  to  study  it. 

II 

This  doctrine  was  based  on  the  idea,  common  to  all  the  old 
Greek  aristocracies,  that  the  people  were  incapable  of  self- 
government.  We  know  the  insulting  acrimony  with  which 
Theognis  expressed  it  as  early  as  the  sixth  century.  "Trample 
underfoot,"  he  cried,  "  crush  with  thy  heel  the  empty-headed 
commons!"^  Beneath  this  cry  of  anger  and  vengeance  there  lay 
even  at  that  time  a  well-defined  conviction.  In  the  fifth  century 
it  was  to  be  formally  stated  by  the  earliest  political  theorists. 
Herodotus,  at  any  rate,  attributes  it  to  the  Persian  prince 
Megabazus,  when  he  rejected  the  democratic  projects  of  Otanes: 
"  The  masses  have  no  practical  sense ;  there  exists  nothing  less 
intelligent,  nothing  more  insolent.  It  would  be  folly  to  give 
oneself  over  to  the  tyrannical  caprice  of  an  undisciplined 
people,  in  order  to  escape  that  of  a  monarch.  The  tyrant  at 
least  knows  what  he  is  doing  when  he  acts ;  the  people  do  not 
know.  How  can  they  be  expected  to  know,  since  they  have 
neither  education  nor  an  inborn  appreciation  of  the  beautiful  ? 
They  rush  headlong  into  action,  and  then  carry  it  on  without 
reflecting,  like  a  torrent  let  loose."-  Here  we  see  opinion 
developing  into  theory.  The  speaker  states  reasons  which  he 
derives  from  a  summary  observation  of  the  facts.  The 
champion  of  oligarchy  declares  that  the  people,  as  he  sees 
them,  are  not  only  without  the  rudiments  of  education,  but 
also  lack  what  might  make  up  for  it — that  instinct  which 
comes  of  inherited  discipline.  He  may  have  come  across  these 
ideas  (which,  by  the  way,  Herodotus  does  not  lay  up  against 
him)  in  Greece,  among  those  aristocracies  which  were  imbued 
with  the  Pythagorean  spirit. 

^Theognis,  847:  \a^  evi^a  Stj/jlo)  Kev€6<ppovL.  ^^  Herodotus,  iii.  81. 


66  THE  KNIGHTS 

That  they  were  current  in  Athens  in  aristocratic  circles 
is  attested  both  by  history  and  by  literature. 

Nowhere  do  we  find  them  stated  with  more  acrimony  than 
in  the  work,  The  Polity  of  the  Athenians,  wrongly  attributed  to 
Xenophon,  but  probably  written  at  Athens  by  a  political 
theorist  and  partisan  of  oligarchy,  about  the  year  424.^  This 
little  work,  which  has  neither  a  beginning  nor  an  end,  seems 
to  be  a  detached  fragment  of  a  composition  in  the  form  of  a 
treatise,  which  may  possibly  have  dealt  with  democracy  in 
general,  or  with  certain  democracies  in  particular.  When  he 
reaches  the  Athenian  democracy,  the  author  constrains  himself 
to  examine  it  in  a  philosophical  spirit,  without,  it  is  true, 
disguising  his  aversion  to  it,  but  also  without  allowing  his 
judgment  to  be  obscured  by  that  aversion.  He  forcefully 
attacks  certain  opinions  that  were  evidently  current  round 
about  him.  Hearing  people  say  that  democracy  is  absurd,  and 
that  corrupt,  impetuous  and  hostile  as  it  is  to  every  form  of 
justice  and  to  all  decency,  it  needs  must  presently  be  trans- 
formed or  go  under — he  methodically  proceeds  to  prove  that, 
far  from  being  absurd,  the  Athenian  democracy  lives  up  to  its 
principles,  and  consequently  acts  in  a  rational  and  logical 
manner.  He  also  maintains  that  it  cannot  be  transformed, 
nor  even  appreciably  modified,  without  losing  its  democratic 
character ;  and,  lastly,  that  the  people  it  harms  are  too  few  in 
number  to  be  a  serious  menace  to  it.  In  a  way,  this  statement, 
as  strange  as  it  is  interesting,  is  an  apology,  but  an  apology 
that  amounts  to  an  accusation,  as  the  orator  finds  the  only 
justification  for  democracy  in  its  complete  adherence  to  its 
principles.     He  sits  in  judgment  on  them  and  declares  them 

^  Few  works  have  been  studied  more,  and  more  discussed.  All  these  discus- 
sions have  been  clearly  and  conveniently  summed  up  in  Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch. 
iii.  2nd  part,  pp.  609-616.  None  of  the  opinions  hitherto  expressed  completelj' 
satisfies  me.  The  work  gives  me  the  impression  of  being  a  fragment.  I  shall 
explain,  in  the  course  of  this  discussion,  what  I  conceive  to  be  its  general  pur- 
pose. The  author  must  have  belonged  to  the  faction  of  Antiphon.  He  is  a 
thinker  who  aims  at  precision,  who  wishes  to  see  and  to  show  things  as  they 
really  are  ;  he  has  something  of  the  spirit  of  Thucj'dides  in  him.  His  seeming 
incoherence  arises,  in  part,  from  the  defective  state  of  the  manuscripts.  As  a 
matter  of  fact,  and  notwithstanding  a  certain  stiffness  and  an  occasional 
clumsiness,  this  thinker  is  a  literary  man. 


THE  KNIGHTS  67 

abominable.  The  very  vehemence  that  lurks  under  his  as- 
sumed coolness,  speaks  for  the  force  of  the  opinions  which  he 
(Uscusses.  We  divine  them,  nay,  we  see  them  behind  his 
refutation.  More  instructive  historical  evidence  than  this  is 
rarely  found. 

He  is  of  the  same  mind  with  those  whom  he  wishes  to 
enlighten,  and  he  begins  by  openly  declaring  that  all  respec- 
table people  are  quite  right  in  abhorring  popular  government. 
He  says :  "  In  every  country  the  best  elements  are  opposed  to 
democracy.  And  who  constitute  the  best  elements  ?  Are 
they  not  those  in  whose  circles  there  exists  the  least  dissolute- 
ness or  wrong-doing,  and  who  devote  themselves  most  seriously 
to  honest  pursuits  ?  Now,  it  is  among  the  common  people 
that  we  find,  in  highest  degree,  ignorance,  moral  depravity, 
dishonesty.  More  than  all  others,  they  are  driven  to  dis- 
graceful acts  by  poverty,  by  lack  of  education,  by  ignorance, 
and  some  of  them  in  particular  by  impending  destitution."  ^ 
Here  we  have  the  first  fact  which  he  thinks  evident,  nay, 
incontestable.  This  fact  once  recognized,  what  room  is  there 
for  surprise  that  the  government  of  a  democratic  state  is  in 
the  hands  of  the  very  worst  elements  in  the  city  ?  "  If  the 
respectable  people  could  gain  a  hearing,  if  their  advice  were 
taken,  the  result  would  doubtless  be  advantageous  to  those 
who  are  of  their  own  kind,  but  not  to  the  common  people. 
On  the  other  hand,  anybody,  any  worthless  fellow,  getting  up 
to  speak  as  he  pleases,  is  sure  to  discover  what  is  advantageous 
to  himself  and  his  fellows.  Can  you  expect  such  a  person  to 
be  a  competent  judge  of  his  own  and  the  people's  interests  ? 
The  fact  is,  the  common  people  think  that  the  ignorance  and 
dishonesty  of  such  a  counsellor,  who  is  in  entire  sympathy 
with  them,  avail  them  better  than  the  sagacity  and  the  excel- 
lence of  a  respectable  man,  who  feels  only  antipathy  for 
them."  ^  Of  course  they  would  make  a  mistake  if  they  wished 
to  be  well  governed ;  but  they  have  not  the  slightest  disposition 
so  to  be  governed.  "  The  people  are  not  anxious  that  the  city 
have  good  laws,  if,  as  a  result,  they  are  forced  to  obey  them. 
They  want  to  be  free  and  to  rule.     That  the  laws  happen  to 

'  Polity  of  the  Athenians,  cap.  v.  -Ibid.  c.  vi. 


68  THE  KNIGHTS 

be  bad,  is  a  matter  of  indifference  to  them."  ^  Thus,  power 
in  the  hands  of  the  most  disreputable  elements  is,  in  the  eyes 
of  the  writer,  the  necessary  concomitant,  and,  as  it  were,  the 
basic  law  of  democracy,  and  to  his  mind  this  lies  in  the  nature 
of  things.  All  that  follows  is  merely  the  development  of  this 
idea.  From  beginning  to  end  of  his  treatise  he  shows  us  the 
people  doing  evil,  not  by  chance,  not  from  a  momentary 
impulse,  not  because  they  are  misled,  but  because  evil-doing  is 
their  special  province.  The  choice  of  their  counsellers  or  of 
their  governors  is  therefore  dictated  by  a  selfish,  but  correct, 
appreciation  of  their  interests.  And  this  quite  naturally  leads 
up  to  the  idea,  already  touched  upon,  that  democracy  cannot 
be  reformed  without  ceasing  to  be  democracy. 

Doubtless  this  doctrine  was  not  accepted,  in  this  extreme 
form,  by  all  who  constituted  the  opposition  at  Athens  in  424. 
The  treatise  with  which  we  are  dealing  would  have  had  no 
object,  had  all  those  to  whom  it  is  addressed  been  convinced 
in  advance  of  what  it  proclaims.  Yet  it  is  just  the  certainty 
of  its  conclusions  that  it  presents  in  a  manner  hitherto  not 
understood.  It  takes  up  ideas  that  are  vague,  scattered  and 
partially  apprehended,  analyses  them,  makes  them  clear  by 
citing  facts  of  daily  occurrence  and  assembles  them  in  groups. 
No  doubt  all  who  belonged  to  the  militant  oligarchical  party 
were  in  the  main  of  the  same  opinion  as  the  author.^  The 
platform  of  the  hetairies  was  based  on  these  ideas.  People 
did  not  believe  in  the  possibility  of  an  honest  democracy. 
As  a  matter  of  politics,  they  pretended  to  wish  to  reform  it,  as 
it  existed ;  in  fact  they  strove  to  replace  it  by  an  oligarchy, 
which  some  wished  to  be  moderate,  and  others  absolute  and 
clothed  with  authority. 

Our  question  is  whether  these  ideas  are  to  be  found  in 
Aristophanes'  Knights,  and  whether,  if  their  influence  is  felt  in 
one  part  or  another  of  the  play,  it  was  profound  enough  to 
suggest  to  the  poet  what  was  essential  in  his  thesis.     In  other 

'^Polity  of  the  Athenians,  c.  viii. 

^Cf.  Thucydides,  vi.  89.  6.  Alcibiades'  speech  at  Sparta:  iirei  8r]fx.oKpaTiav 
ye  Kal  iyiyvdiaKO/Mev  oi  (j>povovvTis  ti  .  .  .  dWd,  Trepl  bfi6\oyovix€vq%  dvoLas  ovdiv  Av 
Kaivbv  \iyoiTO, 


THE   KNIGHTS  69 

words,  did  he  wish  to  portray  democracy  as  condemned  by  its 
very  nature  to  wrong-doing,  or  did  he  strive  to  reform  the 
Athenian  people  by  pointing  out  to  them  the  faults,  not  of 
their  constitution,  but  of  their  current  policies,  and  by  inspir- 
ing them  with  disgust  for  the  men  who  enjoyed  their 
confidence  ? 


HI 

"We  know  the  general  outline  of  the  plot.  A  Paphlagonian 
slave,  a  rascally  and  vulgar  fellow,  recently  purchased  by  old 
Demos,  has  become  the  favorite  of  his  master,  owing  to  his 
gift  of  flattery.  He  reigns  supreme  in  the  house ;  everybody 
trembles  before  him.  The  audience  had  no  difficulty  in  recog- 
nizing Cleon.  Two  old  servants,  molested  and  robbed  by  this 
intruder,  plot  to  put  him  out.  They  produce  a  rival  in  the 
person  of  a  peddling  sausage-seller,  a  rascal  without  scruples 
and  up  to  anything.  Prompted  by  them,  this  rustic  begins  by 
trying  to  frighten  the  Paphlagonian.  Denounced  by  him 
before  the  Senate  as  a  public  enemy,  he  eludes  his  attack. 
Subsequently,  when  old  Demos,  attracted  by  their  noisy  dis- 
pute, looks  in  upon  them,  the  sausage-seller  harangues  him 
and  brings  accusations  against  his  favorite.  The  old  man 
agrees  to  judge  between  them.  Then,  in  his  presence,  they 
vie  in  eloquence  and  vie  in  flattery,  in  attentions  and  even  in 
gifts,  during  a  long  series  of  ever  varying  scenes,  composed  in 
a  spirit  of  buffoonery.  Finally  the  sausage-seller  wins  the 
day  :  Demos  withdraws  his  confidence  from  the  Paphlagonian 
and  bestows  it  upon  the  newcomer.  This  fellow,  becoming  in 
turn  undisputed  master  of  the  situation,  by  means  of  a  magic 
operation  restores  the  old  man  to  youth,  who  forswears  his 
errors  and  allows  him  who  has  thus  transformed  him  to  dictate 
the  principles  of  his  future  conduct.  The  Paphlagonian  is  driven 
off,  and  condemned  to  take  the  tray  of  his  successful  rival  and 
to  ply  his  trade  at  the  city  gates,  just  as  the  latter  used  to  do. 

Accessory  to  this  plot  is  a  chorus  which  has  given  the 
piece  its  name,  the  chorus  of  the  knights ;  and  towards  them 
we  must  now  turn  our  attention. 


70  THE  KNIGHTS 

Is  it  necessary  to  accept  the  view  sometimes  expressed,  that, 
on  the  day  of  performance,  this  chorus  was  actually  composed 
of  young  men  belonging  to  the  class  from  which  the  Athenian 
cavalry  was  recruited  ?  ^  Why  should  we  assume  so  strange  a 
departure  from  what  was  customary  ?  This  error  arose  from  a 
too  literal  interpretation  of  an  ancient  authority."  The  chorus, 
it  is  true,  represents  itself  as  being  a  chorus  of  young  knights ; 
but  all  comic  choruses  similarly  lay  claim  to  a  character  which 
is,  of  course,  a  pure  fiction.  For  example,  are  we  to  believe 
that  the  chorus  of  the  Acharnians  was  actually  made  up  of 
people  from  Acharnae  ?  There  is  not  the  slightest  difference 
between  the  two  cases. 

Moreover  this  question  is  of  quite  secondary  importance  for 
us.  Whatever  was  the  real  nature  of  the  members  of  Aristo- 
phanes' chorus  at  the  Lenaean  festival  of  424,  they  represented 
the  young  Athenian  knights  on  the  stage,  and  consequently, 
as  far  as  the  audience  was  concerned,  for  whom  the  dramatic 
fiction  was  created,  it  was  these  young  knights  who  appeared 
in  person  to  take  part  in  the  action. 

Now,  it  is  rather  hard  to  believe  that  the  poet  would  have 
dared  to  give  them  the  part  that  he  made  them  j)lay,  without 
having  first  secured  their  consent.  It  was  surely  an  unusual 
thing  thus  to  introduce  upon  the  stage,  in  a  more  or  less  grotesque 
disguise,  the  flower  of  Athenian  aristocracy,  and  particularly  in 
the  military  function  in  which  lay  their  greatest  pride.  The 
Athenian  cavalry  had  at  that  time  probably  not  been  organized 
more  than  about  thirty  years.^  Enlarged  from  time  to  time, 
in  Aristophanes'  day  it  consisted  of  a  thousand  members,  who 
were  recruited  from  among  the  young  men.  It  was  divided 
into  two  troops,  each  of  five  squadrons,  commanded  by  two 

^Gilbert,  Beitrdge,  p.  190;  cf.  Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1123. 

-  Knights,  Argura.  i.  :  avrol  ol  'AdvvaLwv  iinrels  cvWa^ivres  ef  xop°^  crx^Mi''"' 
Trapa<paivovTai.  Argum.  ii.  :  6  5^  x°P^^  f*^  ■'"<^''  'ttt^wj'  iarlv.  Cf.  Schol.  1.  247  : 
rov  x^P°^  ^'"'^  ■'"<*'''  '^TTTriuv  <7v/j.Tr\7]povn^vov.  I  do  not  believe  that  any  of  these 
passages  has  the  precise  meaning  attributed  to  it.  Even  if  it  had,  that  would 
establish  nothing  beyond  the  antiquity  of  the  misinterpretation. 

^  Albert  Martin,  Les  Cavaliers  atli6iiiens,  Paris,  Thorin,  1SS7  ;  Helbig,  Les 
Iinrels  atMniens,  Paris,  Klineksieck,  1902. 


THE  KNIGHTS  71 

hipparchs  and  ten  phylarchs.^  Proud  of  their  horses,  of  their 
arms,  of  their  appearance,  these  dashing  cavahymen  liked  to 
attract  attention,.and  with  their  defiling  and  drilling  they  added 
beauty  to  the  festivals  of  the  city.  This  brilliant  band  of  — > 
youths  were  the  ornament  of  Athens.  Phidias  had  just  / 
finished  portraying  them  on  the  frieze  of  the  Parthenon,  which 
had  been  completed  shortly  before  the  Peloponnesian  war. 
Later  on,  another  artist,  Xenophon,  was  to  describe  them  in 
his  Hi'pimrchus,  at  the  same  time  teaching  them  clever  evolu- 
tions, of  a  kind  to  bring  out  their  best  points.  The  common 
people  liked  to  make  fun  of  the  airs  of  these  young  men,  of 
their  vanity  and  of  their  affected  elegance,  but  this  did  not 
prevent  their  admiring  them  on  holidays.  Besides,  they  had 
repeatedly  distinguished  themselves  since  the  beginning  of  the 
war.  In  431,  at  the  time  of  the  first  invasion  by  the  Pelopon- 
nesians,  they  did  their  share  in  harassing  the  enemy  and  in 
driving  them  away  from  the  walls  of  Athens.  In  430  Pericles 
embarked  four  hundred  of  them,  a  quite  novel  thing  at  that 
time,  and  they  helped  him  ravage  the  coast  of  Peloponnesus. 
Quite  recently  again,  in  425,  in  the  assault  made  by  Nicias  on 
the  territory  of  Corinth,  the  two  hundred  knights  who  took 
part  in  the  expedition  had  rendered  valuable  service.'  In 
brief,  they  had  an  excellent  reputation  in  the  city  at  this  time, 
and  they  were  by  nature  not  inclined  to  underestimate  their 
own  importance.  We  have  already  seen  that  if  Cleon  had 
had  a  bone  to  pick  with  them,  he  would  probably  have  been 
the  worse  for  it.  Their  influence  must  have  been  felt  in  the 
theatre  more  than  elsewhere,  for  their  families  controlled  a 
large  number  of  dependents  in  the  city  itself,  and  were  influ- 
ential in  the  country  districts.  They  themselves  were  young, 
bold  and  noisy,  and  were  not  inclined  to  hide  their  feelings,  _ 
nor  to  allow  themselves  to  be  ridiculed  without  protest. 

How,  then,  could  Aristophanes  have  brought  them  into  con- 
tact with  his  ambitious  sausage-seller,  had  he  not  had  some 
sort  of  assurance  that  his  temerity  would  be  agreeable  to  them  ? 
We  may  assume  that  at  least  he  acquainted  some  of  them  with 


^Aristotle,  Constitution  of  AtheTia,  61. 
-  Thucydides,  ii.  22  and  56  ;  iv.  42. 


72  THE  KNIGHTS 

his  plans,  and  that  they  undertook  to  mform  the  others  and  to 
guarantee  their  consent.  Even  though  there  may  not  have  been 
co-operation,  properly  speaking,  nor  authority  expressly  given, 
there  certainly  was  an  agreement  and  even  some  preliminary 
encouragement.  This  is  indeed  what  the  poet  intimates  quite 
plainly  in  the  words  he  gives  to  the  corypheus,  whose  function 
it  is  to  introduce  the  chorus  to  the  audience  and  to  recite  the 
traditional  anapaests :  "  If  any  comic  poet  of  former  times  had 
tried  to  force  us  thus  to  appear  before  the  audience  and  make 
an  address  to  them,  he  would  not  easily  have  succeeded.  But 
this  poet  of  ours  well  deserves  that  we  do  something  for  him, 
for  he  hates  those  whom  we  ourselves  hate,  and  he  has  the 
courage  to  speak  the  truth.  Courageously  he  assaults  the 
whirlwind  and  tornado."  ^  Common  grievances  were  thus 
loudly  proclaimed.  There  was  an  alliance  between  the  knights 
and  the  poet  against  the  Paphlagonian,  that  is  Cleon.  What 
were  these  grievances  ?  Was  it  a  question  merely  of  the 
quarrels,  already  referred  to,  between  the  demagogue  and 
certain  members  of  the  aristocratic  class  ?  Or  does  the 
chorus  here  refer  also  to  an  obscure  accusation  which  Cleon, 
according  to  a  scholiast,  launched  against  the  young  knights, 
charging  them  with  having  failed  to  do  their  duty  as  soldiers, 
an  accusation  that  has  been  variously  interpreted  by  modern 
scholars?^  Without  doubt  the  chorus  had  in  mind  not  only  all 
this,  but  other  more  general  grievances  as  well.  What  people 
in  all  quarters  detested  in  Cleon  was  his  very  method  of 
governing,  the  influence  he  exerted  upon  the  people  and  the 
use  to  which  he  put  that  influence.  It  is  known  that  the 
poet  Eupolis,  who  was  at  that  time  one  of  the  masters  of 
comic  style,  collaborated  with  Aristophanes,  and  it  is  probable 
that  he  wrote  a  considerable  bit  of  the  second  parabasis  for 
him.^  And  in  this  fact  we  have  a  clue,  added  to  those  which 
precede,  that  brings  out  the  true  character  of  the  play.  From 
these  clues  we  may  infer  that  it  was  not  the  audacious  attack 
of  an  individual,  prepared  in  solitary  meditation.     People  must 

^Knights,  11.  507-511.  ^gc^ol   Knights,  1.  226. 

=»  Cratimis,  fr.  200,  Kock  ;   Eupolis,  f r.  78,  Kock   (Schol.  Clouds,  1.  554) ; 
Kirchotf,  Hermes,  xiii.  1878. 


THE  KNIGHTS  73 

have  spoken  about  it  beforehand  in  the  circles  where  the  poet 
was   sure   to  meet   with    the   most   favor.     It   may  be   that 
he  told  them  of  some  of  his  conceits ;  they  approved  of  them 
md  suggested  others  to  him.      In  a  word,  the  work  took  on    / 
somewhat  of  the  character  of  a  collective  manifesto,  but  still  / 
remained  his  own  to  carry  out ;  and  Aristophanes  had  reason  ' 
to  believe  that,  in  case  of   danger,  he   would   have   vigorous 
support.     Herein   he   was   rather  mistaken,  as  we   shall   see 
later  on.     But  what  influence  did  this  alliance  between  the 
poet  and  the  aristocracy,  of  whose  existence  there  can  really 
1)6  no  doubt,  have   upon    the   composition  of   the   play,   and, 
above  all,  on  the  role  alloted  to  the  chorus  ?     That  is  quite 
a  different  question. 

The  more  enterprising  of  the  two  slaves  has  just  given 
the  sausage-seller  his  instructions  and  has  promised  him  the 
support  of  the  thousand  knights  and  of  all  respectable  people.^ 
Just  at  this  moment  Cleon  comes  out  of  the  house,  and 
his  terrible  looks,  his  thundering  voice,  his  frightful  threats, 
promptly  create  consternation  among  the  conspirators.  The 
only  one  who  remains  cool  is  the  slave.  He  calls  his  allies, 
the  knights,  to  his  rescue,  and  suddenly  they  come  galloping 
in  furiously.  Divided  into  two  squadrons  and  commanded 
by  the  two  hipparchs,  Simon  and  Panaetios,  they  charge 
full  tilt  into  the  orchestra  and  attack  the  Paphlagonian, 
who  flees  headlong  before  them.^  His  foes  are  relentless  and 
chase  him  from  place  to  place,  and,  at  the  same  time,  heighten 
their  own  excitement  by  heaping  abuse  upon  him.  They 
reproach  him  for  his  plunderings,  his  greed,  his  shameless 
extortion  in  dealing  with  those  who  have  accounts  to  render, 
and  with  timid  rich  people  who  tremble  at  the  very  mention 
of  a  lawsuit.  Subsequently,  when  the  sausage-seller  is  re- 
assured and  once  more  takes  the  leading  part,  they  encourage 
him  throughout  his  dispute  with  his  rival,  they  admire  and 

^  Knights,  1.  226  :  dXX'  ehlv  'Itttt^s  di/Spes  dyaOol  x^X'ot 
Kal  tQv  ttoXltuiv  ol  KoKoi  re  Kayadoi. 

-  The  action  here  has  been  carefully  studied  and  is  particularly  well  explained 
in  the  work  of  P.  Mazon,  Essai  sur  la  composition  des  comedies  d' Aristophane, 
Paris,  Hachette,  1905. 


74  THE  KNIGHTS 

extol  his  audacity  and  keep  tally  of  the  points  in  his  favor. 
They  are  delighted  to  see  that  Cleon  has  met  his  master  in 
impudence.  Finally,  when  the  demagogue  hurries  off  to  lay 
his  charges  before  the  Senate,  it  is  the  chorus  that  launches 
his  adversary  on  his  track  and  invokes  for  him  the  protection 
of  Zeus  Agoraios. 

There  is  no  trace  of  general  politics  in  all  this.  The  knights 
do  not  express  a  single  thought  peculiar  to  a  party.  Their 
remarks  are  those  of  a  spiteful  opposition,  exasperated  against 
an  enemy ;  they  tear  him  to  pieces  in  their  speeches,  but  their 
attacks  do  not  go  beyond  his  person.  Not  a  word  about  the 
serious  defects  laid  at  the  door  of  a  democratic  constitution  by 
the  advocates  of  an  oligarchy. 

Does  the  spirit  of  caste  become  more  noticeable  in  the 
parabasis  ?  In  the  anapaests  the  knights  proclaim  their 
alliance  with  the  poet,  but  it  is  an  alliance  against  a  rascal 
and  nothing  more.  The  strophic  songs  and  the  epirrhemes 
have  quite  another  character.  Here  we  do  find  opinions 
peculiar  to  the  youthful  aristocrats,  expressed  in  various  w^ays. 
At  the  start,  they  invoke  Poseidon  Hippios,  the  god  who 
presides  at  horse-races,  and  rejoices  when  he  sees  the  youthful 
drivers  of  chariots  in  their  brilliant  attire.  Then  they  extol 
the.  virtues  of  their  fathers,  the  representatives  of  the  old 
families,  valiant  hoplites  who  have  guarded  and  brought  honor 
to  the  city,  generals  of  former  days,  glorious  and  unselfish.  Like 
them,  they  ask  for  a  little  glory  only,  and,  into  the  bargain, 
the  right  to  wear  their  hair  long  when  once  peace  has  been 
made.  Their  second  invocation  is  addressed  to  Pallas,  and  is 
made  in  the  name  of  the  entire  city.  But,  in  conclusion,  they 
once  more  speak  of  themselves,  when  they  jokingly  recall  the 
exploits  of  their  horses,  that  is  their  own  exploits.  In  a  word, 
this  parabasis — and  this  is  true  of  almost  the  whole  of  it — is 
certainly  that  part  of  the  play  in  which  they  best  appear  as  a 
distinct  group  and  express  their  own  views.  These  views  have 
a  dashing  quality,  an  unchecked  pride  and  naivete,  a  bold  and 
even  somewhat  haughty  frankness  which  was  well  suited  to 
these  distinguished  young  men.  Who  would  have  dreamed  of 
taking  offence  at  them  ?     Even  here  their  language  was  in  no 


THE   KNIGHTS  75 

sense  that  of  a  party ;  it  was  the  language  of  their  age,  with 
a  slight  touch  of  impertinence  which  must  have  amused  the 
audience. 

One  may  say  that,  from  this  point  on,  they  take  no  further 
active  part.  They  are  merely  witnesses  of  the  second  part  of 
the  play,  in  which  from  time  to  time,  in  a  few  words,  they 
show  the  same  disposition  as  in  the  first  part,  without  how- 
ever really  taking  a  hand  in  the  action.  This  is  in  agreement 
with  the  practice  of  comedy.  It  would  therefore  serve  no 
purpose  to  mention,  one  by  one,  the  short  remarks,  spoken  or 
sung,  which  they  intersperse  between  the  scenes.  We  may, 
however,  note  the  scornful  criticism  which  they  make  of  Demos 
after  the  scene  of  the  oracles  :  "  Oh  people,  it's  a  fine  empire 
you've  got ;  everybody  dreads  you  as  though  you  were  a  tyrant. 
^',;^utyou  are  too  easily  led.  You  like  to  be  flattered  and  fooled, 
t  You  always  turn  open-mouthed  toward  him  who  happens  to 
speak,  and  your  mind,  though  present,  journeys  afar."  ^  One 
could,  if  one  chose,  recognize  here  somewhat  of  the  opinion  of  the 
Herodotean  Megabyzus  and  of  the  pseudo-Xenophon  about  the 
ignorance  and  thoughtlessness  of  the  people.  It  is,  however, 
introduced  with  an  airy  and  scornful  grace  which  curiously 
lessens  its  import.  And,  above  all,  it  must  not  be  forgotten 
that  the  Athenian  people  were  accustomed  to  hear  themselves 
much  more  rudely  spoken  of  by  their  favorite  orators. 
Pericles  did  his  full  share  of  it,  and  Cleon  himself,  nay,  Cleon 
in  particular,  seems  to  have  taken  a  certain  pride  in  repeating 
such  things  with  intentional  brutality,  as  he  was  one  of  those 
who  excel  in  the  art  of  concealing  their  cowardly  complaisance 
under  the  rudeness  of  their  utterances. 

The  second  parabasis  (1264-1315)  is  nothing  more  than  a 
series  of  satirical  attacks  that  have  no  connection  with  the 
plot,  against  Ariphrades  and  Cleonymos,  obscure  personages,^ 
and  finally  against  Hyperbolos.     This  last  episode,  an  amusing 

^Knights,  11.  1110- 11 19. 

^Cleonymos  appears  to  have  been  the  author  of  a  reform  concerning  the 
tribute  to  be  paid  by  the  allies,  which  became  a  law  in  426  and  resulted  in 
increasing  it  [CIA,  iv.  1,  p.  141,  No.  39a;  cf.  Busolt,  Griech.  Oesch.  iii.  2nd 
part,  p.  1118). 


76  THE  KNIGHTS 

and  fantastic  protest  by  the  triremes,  young  and  old,  against 
the  plans  for  distant  expeditions,  is  the  one  that  tradition 
attributes  to  Eupolis.  While  singing  or  reciting  the  whole  of 
this  parabasis,  the  chorus  in  nowise  plays  the  part  of  a  social 
group  or  of  a  political  party. 

We  must,  however,  especially  note  how  little  importance  is 
attached  to  the  chorus  in  the  cUnoucmcnt.  When  Demos, 
rejuvenated  and  transformed  by  Agoracritos,  appears  before 
the  audience  in  the  costume  of  former  times,  the  knights 
enthusiastically  greet  the  resurrection  of  old  Athens ;  aside 
from  this,  they  take  no  part  whatever  in  this  peaceful  revolu- 
tion. Agoracritos  alone  prescribes  the  rules  for  Demos'  future 
conduct;  during  this  time  the  chorus  does  not  utter  a  single 
word,  and  this  new  policy  ignores  the  interest  of  the  class 
which  they  represent.  Demos  makes  no  promise  that 
especially  affects  them.  Of  course  it  may  be  that,  as  they 
withdrew,  they  gave  vent  to  their  joy  in  a  final  song  that 
has  been  lost.  If  this  was  the  case,  the  whole  scene  warrants 
the  conclusion  that  they  merely  expressed  general  views. 

And  so  we  see  that  Aristophanes  did  represent  the  knights 
as  his  allies,  but  solely  in  his  personal  fight  against  Cleon. 
As  for  Agoracritos'  political  reforms,  he  wished  to  have  them 
instituted  apart  from  the  knights — with  their  approbation,  no 
doubt,  but  without  their  active  participation,  and  in  nowise 
at  their  instigation  or  for  their  benefit.  He  introduced  the 
knights  into  his  play  chiefly  as  elements  of  glowing  life  and 
humor.  They  bring  with  them  their  passions,  their  youth, 
their  lyric  note  of  patriotism  or  mockery ;  but  if  there  is  a 
political  theory,  or  even  the  outline  of  a  political  theory, 
underlying  the  extravagant  inventions  of  the  poet,  it  is  not  in 
the  role  of  the  chorus  that  we  must  look  for  it.  This  is  the 
first  point  that  had  to  be  made  clear. 


IV 

Let  us  now  take  up  the  di^amatis  personae  and  attempt  to 
discover  just  what  they  represent. 


THE  KNIGHTS  77 

It  can  hardly  be  claimed  that  the  two  slaves  who  concoct 
and  organize  the  attack  on  Cleon  typify  either  a  party  or  a 
class  of  society,  or  even  represent,  in  the  proper  sense  of  the 
word,  political  personages  of  the  day.  The  names  of  Demos- 
thenes and  Nicias,  which  are  given  them  in  the  manuscripts, 
do  not  appear  in  the  dialogue.  These  names  were  probably 
inserted  into  the  list  of  characters  at  the  beginning  of  the 
play  by  Alexandrian  editors.^  This  was  done  on  account  of 
an  allusion  in  the  text  to  the  expedition  to  Pylus  (line  54  ct 
seq.).  But  this  allusion  would  at  best  warrant  us  in  recogniz- 
ing Demosthenes  in  the  first  slave ; '  the  second  slave  would 
in  any  event  have  to  remain  nameless.  In  fact,  even  the  first 
slave  is  Demosthenes  only  for  an  instant,  in  which  he  happens 
to  be  in  a  similar  situation,  and  by  no  means  throughout  his 
role.  Mere  characters  of  the  prologue  and  necessary  adjuncts 
to  the  plot,  the  two  slaves  lack  all  historical  individuality. 

As  for  the  intrigue  that  is  imputed  to  them,  we  find  no 
trace    of    it    in    the    occurrences    of    the    time.     Cleon    had 
opponents,  but  it  does  not  appear  that  any  party  put  forward,  r:4' 
or  thought  of  putting  forward  a  rival  who  was  taught  to  fight| 
him  with  his  own  weapons. 

Still,  in  the  words  of  these  two  buffoons  are  found  the  only 
utterances  of  the  play  that  can  really  be  characterized  as 
anti-democractic ;  but,  as  they  refer  to  the  sausage-seller 
Agoracritos,  their  import  will  have  to  be  examined  when  we 
study  that  character. 

Agoracritos  is  inseparable  from  the  Paphlagonian,  namely 
Cleon.  Together  they  make  an  indissoluble  group,  in  which 
the  poet's  thought  is  really  revealed. 

This  thought  is  in  the  main  very  simple.  Cleon,  as  the 
poet  conceives,  is  a  man  whose  power  lies  solely  in  anticipating 
and  satisfying  all  the  desires  of  the  multitude.  As  soon  as 
another  politician  of  the  same  stamp  dares  to  apply  the  same 

^  See  argument  No.  2  and  Dindorf  s  note  in  his  edition. 

-  It  is  worth  noticing  that  it  is  reproduced  in  line  742,  and  that  here  it  no 
longer  applies  to  the  slave.  We  must  not  forget  that  ancient  comedy  is  the 
freest,  most  extravagant  form  of  composition,  and  that,  in  dealing  with 
an  Aristophanes,  we  must  never  take  things  too  exactly. 

G 


78  THE  KNIGHTS 

system  of  government  with  still  greater  impudence  and  vulgarity, 
that  politician  is  bound  to  oust  Cleon.  This  is  practically 
a  moral  necessity.  It  was  the  function  of  comedy  to 
translate  it  into  action  and  to  lend  it  that  kind  of  obviousness, 
striking  though  vulgar,  which  is  peculiar  to  dramatic  demon- 
stration. The  idea  itself  is  not  of  Aristophanes'  own  creating. 
There  can  be  no  doubt  that  he  repeatedly  heard  it  expressed 
in  opposition  circles.  The  germ  of  it  is  found  in  the  above - 
cited  passages  from  pseudo-Xenophon,  and  it  is  virtually 
formulated  in  the  sentence  where  Thucydides  shows  us  the 
successors  of  Pericles  trying  to  outdo  one  another  and  vying  in 
favors  to  the  people  (ii.  65.  10).  Of  course,  there  is  a  bare 
possibility  that  Thucydides  remembered  the  Knights  of  Aristo- 
phanes when  he  wrote  this  passage,  but  it  is  much  more  likely 
that  he  simply  recorded  the  talk  of  Athenian  society  shortly 
before  his  exile.  But  among  those  who  upheld  the  theory  of 
oligarchy,  this  idea  was  accepted  as  a  law  inherent  in  the  very 
nature  of  democracy.  Our  task  is  to  learn  whether  Aristo- 
phanes thus  conceived  and  presented  the  case. 

We  know  how  the  slave  reveals  to  the  amazed  sausage-seller 
his  vocation  as  a  statesman :  "  Yes,  it  is  just  the  fact  that  you 
are  a  scoundrel,  and  that  you  come  from  the  market,  and  that 
you  blush  at  nothing,  that  will  make  a  great  man  of  you." 
When  the  rogue,  attracted  and  distrustful  at  the  same  time, 
seems  to  hesitate,  "  Come  now,"  he  asks  him,  "  are  you  per- 
chance conscious  in  your  own  mind  of  something  honorable  ? " 
No,  nothing  of  the  kind :  he  is  born  of  parents  who  belong  to 
the  dregs  of  the  people,  and  he  himself  is  as  ignorant  and 
vulgar  as  one  could  desire,  besides  being  dishonest  when 
occasion  arises — he  is  the  very  man  that  is  wanted.  "  Mark 
my  words,"  says  his  mentor,  "nowadays  the  guiding  of  the 
people  is  no  longer  the  business  of  an  educated  or  of  a  respect- 
able man;  it  rightfully  belongs  to  him  who  is  ignorant  and  low- 
in  every  way  "  (ek  aimaOrj  koi  ^SeXvfjov)} 

This  is  certainly  a  sharp  verdict  and  a  severe  arraignment. 
At  the  same  time,  we  must  recall  that  the  poet  here  employs 
the  words  of  one  of  his  characters  to  criticise  an  existing  state 
^Knights,  11.  180-19.3. 


THE  KNIGHTS  79 

of  affairs.  He  does  not,  by  any  means,  say  that  it  was  always 
thus,  and  that  it  cannot  be  corrected  so  long  as  the  people 
remain  masters.  We  must  therefore  look  to  the  rest  of  the 
play  for  explanation  and  elucidation  of  this  initial  verdict. 

The  fight  is  on  between  the  two  rivals.  Had  the  poet  clung 
to  his  first  notion,  Agoracritos  would,  in  due  course,  have  to 
appear  _tp  be  worse  than  Cleon — not  only  more  impudent,  more 
vulgar,  a  greater  flatterer  and  a  greater  hypocrite,  but,  above 
all,  more  intensely  selfish  and  wicked.  Just  as  Cleon,  while 
professing  to  love  the  people,  really  loves  only  himself  and 
seeks  solely  his  own  advantage,  so  his  rival  should  likewise 
strive  only  to  enrich  himself,  to  live  luxuriously  and  merrily 
at  the  expense  of  his  dupe.  Indeed,  that  would  be  the  neces- 
sary condition  for  verifying  the  law  just  enunciated.  If,  on 
the  contrary,  Agoracritos  is  only  apparently  ambitious,  if  for 
all  his  vulgarity  he  is  a  respectable  man,  if  he  really  desires 
the  welfare  of  the  people,  and  if  he  actually  succeeds  in 
correcting  their  ways,  it  must  follow  that  the  democracy  is  not 
irretrievably  doomed  to  fall  through  its  own  defects,  and  that 
itmay  after  all  be  reformed.  Now,  it  is  this  second  conception 
that  prevails  in  the  play,  and  we  have  only  to  inquire  to 
what  extent  it  may  have  been  influenced  either  by  the  style 
of  comedy,  or  by  the  need  of  dealing  gently  with  the  audience. 

The  first  group  of  scenes,  in  which  the  two  rivals  are  at 
loggerheads,  has  only  slight  interest  for  us.  In  them  Agora- 
critos appears  as  a  rustic,  uses  Billingsgate  with  raucous  voice, 
just  as  we  saw  him  above.  Cleon,  on  the  other  hand,  is 
nothing  more  than  a  sort  of  live  scarecrow  with  a  hideous 
mask,  accustomed  to  make  everybody  tremble  at  his  threats. 
Each,  in  turn,  defies  or  even  jostles  the  other,  but,  apart  from 
a  few  scattered  allusions,  there  is  no  political  satire,  except  in 
so  far  as  it  lies  in  the  situation  itself  and  in  the  means  of 
defence  employed  by  the  chief  character.  His  most  effective 
weapon  is  denunciation.  He_threatens  to  bring  charges 
against  whoever  opposes  him ;  indeed,  it  is  with  an  accusation 
that  this  first  encounter  ends.  Cleon,  derided  and  thrashed 
by  Agoracritos,  who  is  helped  by  the  Knights,  hurries  to  the 
hall  where  the  Council  meets  in  order  to  denounce  their  plot. 


80  THE  KNIGHTS 

There  is  no  need  to  delay  here  in  order  to  give  an  account 
of  the  meeting  of  the  Council,  for  in  fact  satire  here  ceases 
completely  and  makes  way  for  the  play  of  fancy.  At  the 
outset  we  do  undoubtedly  feel  that  the  poet  is  making  fun  of 
democracy's  distrust,  when  he  shows  us  its  senators  ever  ready 
to  accredit  rumors  of  conspiracy,  and  that  subsequently  he 
finds  diversion  in  their  fickleness  of  mind,  and  in  the  ingenuous 
ease  with  which  they  swallow  the  empty  rumors  brought  by 
anybody  that  happens  along.  Satire  and  ridicule,  assuredly, 
but  so  airy  and  so  cleverly  turned  into  nonsense,  that  it  is 
impossible  to  take  it  seriously. 

The  contest  of  the  two  rivals  before  the  populace,  which 
follows  upon  these  scenes,  deserves  much  closer  attention. 
This  contest  is  provoked  by  the  Paphlagonian,  because  he 
thinks  himself  absolute  master  of  the  spirit  of  Demos.  He 
declares  that  "  he  fools  him  as  much  as  he  chooses,"  and  that 
"he  knows  the  sops  with  which  he  is  fed"  (11.  713,  715) — 
statements  by  which  the  poet  seems  to  wish  to  make  clear  at 
the  outset  that  he  means  to  attack  Cleon's  craftiness  and 
mendacity.  On  the  other  hand,  the  sausage-seller,  in  his 
initial  profession  of  faith,  forgetting  for  a  moment  who  he  is, 
quite  clearly  gives  himself  the  airs  of  a  representative  of  the 
respectables :  "  For  a  long  time,  0  people,  I  have  loved  you 
and  wished  to  do  you  a  good  turn,  and  many  others,  honor- 
able and  well-educated  people,  share  my  desire.  But  this 
fellow  here  prevents  us.  You  are  like  boys  who  have  lovers. 
You  reject  respectable  and  swell  people,  but  abandon  your- 
selves to  such  people  as  lamp-sellers,  cobblers,  catgut-stitchers 
and  tanners"  (11.  734-740).  It  is  evident  that  the  poet, 
wittingly  or  unwittingly,  betrays  himself  in  this  passage.  His 
stage  character  for  a  moment  lifts  the  mask  of  impudence  and 
vulgarity  under  which  he  has  been  hiding,  and  we  see  who  he 
really  is.  In  unmasking  himself,  he  also  unmasks  his  rival. 
If  Agoracritos  represents  "  the  respectable  people,"  which 
doubtless  means  the  middle  class,  as  distinguished  from  the 
common  people,  it  is  clear  that  this  Paphlagonian  not  only  is 
Cleon,  but  that,  in  a  general  way,  he  represents  the  demagogues 
of  low  birth,  or  those  who  act  like  the  populace  in  order  to 


THE  KNIGHTS  81 

rule  it.     This  hint  deserves  to  be  borne  in  mind,  but  we  must 
not  exaggerate  its  importance. 

Indeed,  were  we  to  follow  it  without  reservation  we  should 
be  misled  at  once.  The  decisive  scene — the  one  in  which 
Agoracritos  denounces  Cleon  before  Demos — does  not  afford 
what  might  have  been  expected  of  it  in  this  particular.  We 
should  think  that  the  enemy  of  demagogy  would  here  lay  bare 
the  whole  policy  with  which  he  was  wont  to  charge  it.  But 
this  is  far  from  being  the  case.  Agoracritos'  attack  on  Cleon 
has  not  the  character  of  a  vigorous  and  violent  demonstration. 
It  is  inconsequential,  incoherent  and  interspersed  with  inten- 
tional absurdities.  Far  from  seeking  to  bring  out  the  general 
facts,  it  rather  avoids  them.  It  takes  issue  with  the  man, 
with  some  of  his  personal  doings,  with  his  selfish  schemes. 
Agoracritos  devotes  himself  chiefly  to  depriving  him  of  his 
seeming  good  qualities,  of  his  high-sounding  titles  which  make 
him  popular.  He  denies  the  service  that  Cleon  claims  to  have 
done  the  people,  makes  every  effort  to  show  up  the  selfish 
interest  of  his  whole  conduct,  even  goes  so  far  as  to  question 
his  victory  at  Sphacteria,  and,  in  order  to  encompass  his  ruin, 
humorously  parodies  his  habitual  resort  to  slanderous  insinua- 
tion. Can  it  be  said  that  there  is  complete  absence  of  general 
reflections  ?  No,  there  is  at  least  one,  which  appears  toward 
the  end  of  the  scene,  in  the  passage  where  Agoracritos  com- 
pares agitators  of  Cleon's  stripe  to  fishers  of  eels  :  "  You  do 
just  what  those  do  who  fish  for  eels.  When  the  water  is  calm 
they  catch  nothing ;  but  stir  up  the  mvid  and  there  is  a  good  ; 
catch.  So  you  are  sure  of  gain  when  you  stir  up  the  town  " 
(11.  864-867).  This,  we  must  admit,  goes  beyond  Cleon's 
person — political  methods  and  a  whole  class  of  men  are  aimed 
at  in  this  shaft  of  satire,  chiefly  the  advocates  of  war  to  the 
bitter  end — and  here  again  it  is  not  Agoracritos  that  speaks, 
but  the  poet.  Still,  it  is  merely  a  group  of  men  whose  names' 
might  then  have  been  mentioned  that  the  poet  has  in  mind. 
Democratic  institutions  themselves  are  no  more  involved  here 
than  before. 

And  now,  what  are  we  to  think  of  the  scene  of  the  oracles 
and    that   of    the    presents  ?     The    former   deals   in   a    most 


82  THE  KNIGHTS 

amusing  way  with  one  of  the  intellectual  maladies  of  the  time 
— the  grovelling  superstitiousness  of  the  people — as  well  as  with 
the  cleverness  of  those  who  exploited  it.  The  second  scene 
exhibits,  with  humorous  conceits  and  in  extravagant  caricature, 
the  lawless  rivalry  of  the  politicians  who  at  that  time  fawned 
upon  the  people.  Beneath  all  this  tomfoolery,  we  can  clearly 
discern  the  satire — and  it  is  as  quick  and  sharp  as  it  is  apt  to 
provoke  laughter.  We  may  even  say  that  it  is  not  without  a 
certain  depth,  as,  in  the  second  scene,  it  evidently  touches 
upon  one  of  the  permanent  dangers  that  placed  the  Athenian 
democracy  in  jeopardy.  It  is,  however,  worth  noting  that 
this  is  one  of  the  dangers  that  are  inherent  in  every  absolute 
power.  Of  course  some  may  think  that  democracy,  when  it 
entirely  lacks  the  restraint  of  established  customs,  is  peculiarly 
menaced  by  it.  But  it  cannot  be  said  that  this  is  a  necessary 
interpretation  of  Aristophanes'  scene.  Taken  by  itself,  it  is 
merely  an  arraignment  of  prevailing  conditions.  On  the  one 
hand,  it  attacks  the  unscrupulous  politicians  who  take  for  their 
plan  of  action,  not  what  they  believe  is  best  for  the  people, 
but  what  they  think  is  most  apt  to  please.  On  the  other 
hand,  it  attacks  the  excessive  ingenuousness  of  the  masses, 
who  are  the  dupes  of  the  politicians'  empty  protestations.  Let 
the  masses  become  more  discerning,  and  the  evil  will  be  cured 
by  that  very  fact.  This  is  just  what  happens  at  the  close  of 
the  play. 

Cleon  is  in  fact  definitively  beaten  by  his  rival.  We  witness 
the  crumbling  of  his  power.  Is  a  form  of  government  involved 
in  his  downfall  ?  Surely  the  Athenians  did  not  so  under- 
stand it ;  and  they  were  right.  Indeed,  the  Cleon  of  the 
Knights  could  not  in  any  way  be  regarded  as  a  typical  per- 
sonification of  the  leaders  of  the  Athenian  democracy.  Though 
comedy  had  violently  attacked  Pericles  during  his  lifetime, 
surely  after  his  death  no  one  could  have  been  induced  to  recog- 
nize him  in  this  hateful  and  wicked  buffoon.  The  caricature 
was  really  too  personal  to  admit  of  its  being  given  a  general 
application.  In  creating  this  character,  Aristophanes  did 
not  even  portray  the  psychology  of  an  inferior  class  of 
demagogues.    At  best  he  pointed  out  with  forceful  satire,  as 


THE  KNIGHTS  83 

was  his  wont,  some  of  the  most  patent  and  characteristic 
features  of  the  part  they  played.  He  has  shown  us  their 
methods  of  procedure,  their  grimaces,  their  outward  appearance, 
because,  without  doing  so,  he  could  not  have  put  his  Cleon 
upon  the  stage ;  but  he  had  not  actually  studied  their  souls. 
It  may  be  that  the  nature  of  comedy  at  that  time  did  not  very 
well  admit  of  this  kind  of  study.  Yet  there  are  much  more 
real  and  human  characters  than  Cleon  in  plays  by  the  same 
poet^  They  are  those  for  which  he  had  a  certain  sympathy, 
such  as  Dicaeopolis,  Strepsiades,  Lysistrata,  Chremylus.  Here, 
hatred  and  violent  prejudice  obscure  his  vision.  His  concep- 
tion is  a  personal  vengeance.  He  is  neither  able  nor  willing 
to  see  anything  but  what  is  hateful  in  his  enemy.  His  Cleon 
is  a  malevolent  force,  a  "  Typho "  let  loose,  to  use  his  own 
words,  a  monstrous  composite  of  vice  and  impudence,  a  sort  of 
mythological  monster.  He  is  emphatically  not  a  human  being, 
and  for  this  very  reason  he  cannot  really  be  the  personification 
of  a  class  of  real  men. 

His  rival  is  even  less  so.  While  Cleon,  at  least,  is  the  same 
from  beginning  to  end  of  the  play,  Agoracritos  changes  inces- 
santly, now  outdoing  Cleon  in  vulgarity,  in  impudence  and 
vileness,  but  presently  appearing  as  a  cautious  counsellor,  a 
sagacious  critic,  a  sincere  friend  of  the  people,  whom  he  seeks 
to  instruct.  Are  these  transformations  of  his  the  cover  for 
the  pursuit  of  some  ambitious  selfish  end  ?  What,  in  a  word, 
is  the  object  of  all  his  efforts  ?  This  is  what  we  must  now 
discover  through  a  study  of  the  cUnouement  and,  at  the  same 
time,  of  the  role  of  Demos,  which  latter  can  only  be  properly 
appreciated  in  the  final  stage  of  its  development. 


Agoracritos  has  supplanted  the  Paphlagonian  ;  Demos  gives 
him  his  confidence  and  puts  him  in  charge  of  his  affairs. 
What  is  the  result  ? 

Had  the  poet  bodily  adopted  the  ideas  of  the  advocates  of 
the  oligarchical  theory,  and  had  he  developed  them  dramati- 


84  THE  KNIGHTS 

cally  with  all  their  consequences,  the  rule  of  Agoracritos  would 
have  had  to  be  worse  than  that  of  Cleon.  Under  his  influence 
Demos  would  have  become  more  capricious,  more  suspicious, 
more  tyrannical ;  in  a  word,  more  of  a  dupe  than  he  was 
previously.  And  in  the  exodos  Agoracritos  would  have  had  to 
celebrate  his  ephemeral  triumph  in  a  brutal  way,  even  while 
he  had  to  fear  the  new  rival  who,  in  turn,  was  destined  by 
fate  shortly  to  oust  him  by  the  same  methods.  Thus  con- 
ceived, the  play  would  have  been  logical  and  quite  in 
conformity  with  the  doctrine  of  the  intransigeant  aristocracy. 
As  a  matter  of  fact  it  is  intentionally  illogical,  even  to  the 
point  of  extreme  improbability  ;  and  we  must  seek  the  reason 
for  this. 

In  the  course  of  the  play  Demos  has  been  depicted  in 
general  outlines.  He  is  an  old  rustic,^  and  such  he  must  be, 
for  to  the  poet's  mind  he  stands  for  a  democracy  the  best  part 
of  which  consisted  of  peasants.  But  this  characteristic,  which 
reappears  at  the  close  of  the  play,  seems  to  be  forgotten  in  the 
course  of  the  action.  His  slaves  tell  us  that  he  has  a  testy 
disposition,  that  he  is  easily  irritated,  and  somewhat  deaf." 
But  of  this  side  of  his  nature  also  we  witness  no  manifestation. 
Indeed,  his  role  consists  merely  in  listening  to  the  flattering 
remarks  that  are  addressed  to  him,  and  in  accepting  the  gifts 
that  are  offered  him.  When  Cleon  speaks  of  him  in  liis 
absence,  he  treats  him  as  an  imbecile.^  In  the  presence  of 
those  who  flatter  him  he  does  seem  to  be  credulous  to  the 
point  of  silliness.  True,  he  himself  warns  us  not  to  trust 
appearances.  He  says  that  his  outward  demeanor  hides  a 
very  deliberate  policy.  "  I  intentionally  play  the  fool ;  I 
delight  in  feasting  every  day,  and  that  is  why  I  like  to 
nourish  a  statesman  who  is  a  thief ;  when  he  is  satiated,  I 
catch  him  and  crush  him."  *  So  this  simpleton  is  in  reality  a 
slyboots ;  at  least  he  persuades  himself  that  he  is.  But  his 
cleverness  is  short-sighted,  for  it   does   not   look   beyond   an 

^  Knights,  1.  41 :  dypoiKos  opyfiv. 

^Knights,  1.  41  :  d/cpdxoXos,  SvctkoXov  yepbvnov,  virbKWcpov . 
^Knights,  1.  396  :  /cat  rh  tov  binj-ov  irpdcrbiwov  fxaKKoa  Kadi^p.ei>ov. 
*  Knights,  \l  1123-1130. 


THE  KNIGHTS  85 

immediate  advantage,  which  in  the  long  run  is  to  be  his 
perdition.  The  design  he  boasts  of  is  not  only  immoral,  but 
also  absurd,  based  on  a  false  conception  of  his  own  real 
interests,  and  this  is  shown  by  the  transformation  he  under- 
goes at  the  close  of  the  play. 

Eejuvenated  by  the  magical  operation  of  Agoracritos,  he 
appears  handsome  and  brilliant  in  the  costume  of  former  days, 
such  as  he  was  at  the  time  of  Aristides  and  Miltiades.^  Thus 
transformed,  he  is  ashamed  of  his  former  self.  He  cannot 
understand  that  he  should  have  allowed  himself  to  be  fooled 
by  those  who  flattered  him.  How  then  can  we  take  seriously 
the  clever  design  of  which  he  boasted  before  ?  He  recognizes 
that  he  had  lost  his  senses,  and  he  blushes  at  his  mistakes.^ 
When  he  puts  himself  into  the  hands  of  his  benefactor, 
Agoracritos,  for  the  future,  he  commits  the  management  of 
his  affairs  not  to  a  shameless  politician,  but  to  a  wise  and 
disinterested  reformer,  who  is  to  assure  his  glory  and  make 
him  happy. 

If  this  outcome  expresses  the  real  thought  of  Aristophanes, 
it  is  clear  that  this  thought  is  quite  different  from  the 
intransigeant  theory  with  which  it  seemed  to  be  mingled  at 
the  outset.  We  have  seen  that  the  doctrinaire  supporters  of 
oligarchy  like  pseudo-Xenophon,  thought  that  the  Athenian 
democracy  could  not  be  reformed,  that  it  was  even  destined  by 
its  very  nature  more  and  more  to  carry  its  principles  to 
extremes  ;  and  at  first  it  seemed  as  though  the  poet  had  appro- 
priated this  idea,  when  he  created  the  character  of  Agoracritos. 
But  behold,  his  character  was  transformed  in  its  making — his 
victory,  by  whatever  means  secured,  had  for  its  immediate 
result  that  the  democracy,  which  he  had  reformed,  was  entirely 
changed,  and  that  it  mapped  out  a  new  destiny  for  itself.  Our 
entire  understanding  of  Aristophanes'  political  views  depends 
upon  the  importance  we  attach  to  this  denouement. 

Is  not  the  temptation  great,  at  first  blush,  to  consider  this 
as  a  mere  bit  of  cleverness  on  the  part  of  the  poet,  who  was, 
above  all,  anxious  to  assure  the  success  of  his  play  ?     One  thing 

^  Knujhts,  1.  1325  :  Or6s  Trep'  'ApiiTTfi5r]  irpoTepov  Kal  MtXTidSj;  ^vvecrlrei. 
-Knights,  11.  1349,  1354  :  Xic-xyvofxai  tol  rais  irporepov  a/xapTiai^. 


86  THE  KNIGHTS 

is  certain :  if  Agoracritos  were  what  he  ought  to  be,  the  satire 
would  be  much  more  stinging.  Can  it  be  maintained  that  even 
in  this  form  it  would  not  have  been  acceptable  to  the  Athenian 
audience  ?  I  do  not  think  so.  There  was  a  way  for  a  poet 
of  Aristophanes'  ingenuity  so  to  arrange  matters  that  the 
people  would  have  been  amused  at  this  fight  to  the  finish 
between  two  equally  ambitious  rascals.  The  general  thought, 
obscured  by  the  uproar  of  a  humorous  plot,  would  only  have 
been  revealed  to  a  few  thoughtful  minds,  on  the  day  after  the 
victory.  In  fact,  however,  the  general  structure  of  the  play 
which  we  are  considering,  the  very  details  of  the  closing  scene, 
and  finally  such  other  knowledge  as  we  have  about  Aristo- 
phanes— all,  in  a  word,  must  lead  us  to  believe  that  its 
(Unouement  is  really  a  true  expression  of  his  belief. 

If  he  had  regarded  the  transformation  of  Demos  merely  as 
a  concession  to  his  audience,  it  ought  to  have  been  presented 
as  a  humorous  fancy,  without  any  relation  to  the  events  of  the 
day.  Instead  of  this,  we  see  that  it  leads  to  a  perfectly 
concise  programme  of  reforms.  Agoracritos  virtually  subjects 
his  reclaimed  master  to  an  examination  in  which  he  pre- 
scribes his  future  conduct  for  him  by  indirection.  " '  What 
will  you  do  if  some  accuser  urges  you  to  sentence  a  defendant 
on  the  pretext  that  lawsuits  and  sentences  are  your  chief 
means  of  livelihood?'  'I  shall  hurl  him  into  the  abyss.' -^  'And 
what  other  policies  will  you  pursue?'  'I  shall  give  the  rowers 
on  our  triremes  their  exact  wages,  instead  of  wasting  the 
treasury's  money  in  useless  expenses.  I  shall  oblige  everybody 
to  serve  regularly  in  the  army,  not  allowing  people  to  escape 
through  intrigue  or  favor.  I  shall  expel  from  the  Agora  the 
young  chaps  who  indulge  in  subtle  talk,  and  I  shall  force  them 
to  go  ahunting.' "  Thereupon  Agoracritos  assures  Demos  of  a 
truce  of  thirty  years,  and  he  takes  him  out  to  the  country, 
there  quietly  to  enjoy  the  peace  which  has  thus  been  restored.' 

Careful  consideration  will  show  us  that  here  we  have,  under 
the  guise  of  more  or  less  sketchy  and  comical  suggestions,  the 

^  Bdpa^/jof ,  the  chasm  in  the  ground  behind  the  Acropolis,  into  which  the 
corpses  of  criminals,  convicted  on  a  capital  charge,  were  thrown. 
"Knights,  11.  1340-1395. 


THE  KNIGHTS  87 

outline  of  a  policy,  capable  of  immediate  application,  which 
may  be  formulated  as  follows :  make  peace  with  Lacedaemonia, 
reform  the  education  of  the  young  people  by  taking  them  out 
of  the  schools  of  the  sophists,  diminish  the  importance  of 
oratory  by  reducing  the  number  of  lawsuits,  above  all  stop 
giving  a  livelihood  to  several  thousand  useless  judges ;  and  to 
this  end  send  the  people  back  to  the  country,  let  them  once 
more  take  up  their  work,  their  habits,  their  peaceful,  regular 
life :  in  a  word,  remove  them  from  the  baneful  influence  of 
the  city  and  from  the  domination  of  the  politicians.^ 

Let  us  now  compare  this  policy  with  that  of  the  men  of 
411,  as  we  know  it  from  trustworthy  documents.^  Though 
the  two  policies  may  be  similar  in  some  particulars,  the 
differences  are  very  much  more  striking.  The  chief  object  of 
the  latter  was  to  shift  the  centre  of  gravity  of  the  state  and  to 
change  the  character  of  the  body  of  the  citizens — a  real  poli- 
tical revolution.  The  poet  aims  solely  at  moral  reform.  Demos 
remains  himself,  or  rather  he  returns  to  his  former  self.  He 
needs  only  open  his  eyes  and  allow  himself  to  be  enlightened 
by  a  good  adviser,  and  regain  his  strength  in  a  healthy  and 
laborious  life  in  the  country.  The  main  cause  of  his  temporary 
perversion  lies  not  in  his  own  nature,  but  rather  in  an  initial 
mistake,  a  silly  and  misplaced  trustfulness  which  is  itself  the 
result  of  the  confusion  caused  by  the  war.  Here  again  we 
meet  the  fundamental  idea  of  the  Acharnians.  At  heart, 
Aristophanes  is  always  in  sympathy  with  Dicaeopolis,  and  he 
does  not  dream  of  robbing  him  of  his  rights.  But  he  is  not 
willing  that  Dicaeopolis  should  forget  his  country  home  and 
come  to  live  on  the  Pnyx  or  in  the  law-courts.  All  the 
trouble  appears  to  him  to  come  from  this  fatal  change  of 
habits,  and  Cleon,  the  hateful  Cleon,  is  at  once  its  product  and 
its  cause. 

This,  I  believe,  is  the  exact  thought  of  the  poet.     When  we 

^  Aristotle,  Polit.  iv.  62 :  "Orav  jxiv  ovv  rb  yeupyiKbv  Kal  rb  KeKTrjuivov  /xerplav 
ovaiav  Kvpiov  ^  rrji  ■jroKireias,  TroXtreiJovTai  /card  j'6^ioi'S.  ix°^'^'-  7"P  ipya^bfiefoi.  j^TJv, 
ov  dvvavTai.  Si  (rxoXdfeiv,  (jcrre  rbv  vbnov  i-m<TTr]cravTei  iKKXrjcnd^ovffi  ras  dvajKalai 
eKKKTjaia^. 

2  Especially  through  Aristotle,  Constitution  of  Athens,  ce.  xxix.  and  xxx. 


88  THE   KNIGHTS 

free  it  from  all  extraneous  matter,  it  becomes  clear  that 
although  in  the  various  stages  of  its  development  it  may  have 
reflected  some  of  the  ideas  of  the  aristocratic  opposition,  it  is 
by  no  means  an  exact  rendering  of  it,  and  that  it  did  not  have 
the  same  objects  in  view.  The  Athenians  made  no  mistake 
about  it.  The  judges  awarded  the  first  prize  in  the  competi- 
tion to  Aristophanes.  After  the  foregoing  explanations,  that  is 
not  at  all  surprising.  His  play,  variously  interpreted  by  the 
several  parties,  could,  in  its  general  tendency,  meet  with  the 
approval  of  a  large  majority.  Even  those  who  recognized 
Cleon  as  their  leader,  and  who  were  not  inclined  to  desert  him, 
did  not  think  so  well  of  his  character  as  to  take  offence  at 
seeing  him  thus  publicly  chastised.  Indeed,  they  probably 
greatly  enjoyed  watching  the  maltreatment  of  this  vulgar 
and  imperious  man,  who  had  imposed  himself  upon  them, 
but  to  whom,  after  all,  they  were  much  pleased  to  give 
occasional  evidence  of  their  independence.^  It  is  possible  that 
the  granting  of  the  prize  to  Aristophanes  gave  them  a  twofold 
satisfaction:  that  of  rewarding  the  gifted  poet  and  of  humilating 
a  disagreeable  master. 

To-day  we  interpret  matters  rather  differently.  All  that 
was  of  immediate  interest  at  the  time  of  the  performance  has 
lost  its  importance  for  us.  Many  personal  allusions  either 
escape  us  or  are  hardly  noticed.  On  the  other  hand,  we 
unwittingly  exaggerate  the  general  features  which  crop  up 
here  and  there.  And  perhaps  we  are  right  in  doing  so,  for 
nothing  can  prevent  enduring  works  from  manifesting  in  an 
ever-growing  degree  what  is  most  enduring  in  them.  But 
when  the  problem  is  to  gain  an  exact  understanding  of  the 
poet's  intentions,  and  to  set  his  work  in  its  former  surround- 
ings and  time,  there  is  certainly  no  tendency  that  needs  to  be 
more  guarded  against  than  this. 

^  Pseudo-Xenophon,  Polity  of  the  Athenians,  c.  xviii. 


CHAPTEE    III 

THE   CLOUDS.     THE  WASPS 
THE   PEACE 


What  did  Cleon  do  when  he  was  thus  derided  ?  It  is  very 
probable,  if  not  certain,  that  he  attempted  to  take  revenge  on 
the  poet  by  making  a  false  accusation  against  him.  The  most 
important  anonymous  biography  of  Aristophanes  informs  us 
that  Cleon  brous-ht  a  suit  at  law  against  him  for  fraudulent  use 
of  the  title  citizen  (ypacpr]  ^ewa?),^  but  through  an  evident 
error,  as  we  have  seen  above,  it  confuses  this  accusation  with 
the  denunciation  before  the  Senate  which  followed  the  produc- 
tion of  the  Babylonians.  In  fact,  it  is  impossible  that  the 
accusation  should  have  been  made  earlier  than  424,  for, 
though  the  poet  recounts  at  length  Cleon's  hostile  actions,  he 
makes  no  reference  to  it  whatever  either  in  the  Acliarnians 
or  in  the  Knights.  On  the  contrary,  there  is  every  reason  to 
believe  that  it  must  have  followed  close  upon  the  success  of 
the  latter  play.^ 

Without  exaggerating  the  influence  of  comedy  upon  public 
opinion,  we  must  recognize  that  a  work  of  so  much  importance, 
performed  before  the  entire  people,  was  not  an  indifferent 
matter.  Not  only  must  Cleon  have  been  humiliated  and  made 
furious  by  it,  but  he  may  have  feared  a  weakening  of   his 

^Proleg.  Didot,  xi.  ;  reproduced  in  No.  xii.,  which  gives  an  abridgment  of 
the  above,  but  with  the  difference  that  No.  xii.  puts  this  accusation  after  the 
performance  of  the  Knights  ;  cf.  Schol.  Acharn.  1.  378. 

*  Gilbert,  Beiirdye,  pp.  193-4. 


90   THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE 

authority  by  so  audacious  and  well-directed  an  attack.  On 
the  other  hand,  it  was  impossible  for  him  to  resort  once  more 
to  a  denunciation  before  the  Senate.  The  first  had  been 
unsuccessful ;  this  one  would  have  been  even  surer  to 
fail.  It  was  an  easy  matter  for  the  poet  to  show,  book  in 
hand,  that  Cleon  was  the  sole  object  of  his  attacks.  The 
irritated  politician  resorted  to  a  subterfuge.  He  brought  a 
charge  against  Aristophanes  of  having  illegally  used  the  title 
citizen. 

Nothing  was  more  dangerous  than  such  an  accusation,  for, 
on  the  one  hand,  Athenian  citizens,  and  especially  the  poorest 
among  them,  those  who  constituted  the  majority  in  the  law- 
courts  and  lived  at  the  expense  of  the  republic,  were  extremely 
jealous  of  their  privileges.  They  dreaded  the  intruders  who 
had  a  share  in  all  sorts  of  salaries.  On  the  other  hand,  it  was 
always  rather  difficult  to  prove  one's  right  to  the  possession  of 
this  enviable  title.^  And  when  the  accuser  enjoyed  good 
standing  in  the  law-courts,  when  he  had  complaisant  witnesses 
at  his  disposal,  and  was  sufficiently  powerful  to  intimidate 
others,  when,  in  fine,  he  knew  how  to  arrange  matters  cleverly 
and  to  draw  up  a  captious  brief,  the  best-established  titles 
might  appear  weak.  As  has  already  been  stated,  we  do  not 
know  how  valid  Aristophanes'  title  was.  There  is  no  room 
for  doubt  that  he  enjoyed  the  rank  of  citizen,  and  of  this 
Cleon's  charge  is  an  unimpeachable  proof,  as  it  sought  to 
deprive  him  of  it.  But  was  he  quite  sure  of  establishing 
its  entire  validity  in  the  face  of  a  very  exacting  law  and  of  a 
very  distrustful  tribunal  ?     Of  this  we  may  have  our  doubts. 

The  only  evidence  that  we  have  in  this  matter  is  derived 

1  The  legal  requirement  for  citizenship  was  that  a  man  should  be  the  legiti- 
mate son  of  an  Athenian  citizen  and  an  Athenian  woman,  and  have  been 
inscribed  at  the  age  of  eighteen  on  the  register  of  a  deme  and  of  a  phratry  ; 
or  else  have  established  a  valid  claim  to  a  regular  naturalization.  But  the 
prosecution  could  maintain  that  the  registration  had  been  wrongfully  secured, 
that  the  father  or  the  mother  was  not  really  an  Athenian,  or  that  the 
defendant  was  not  born  in  wedlock.  As  all  this  had  to  be  proved  by  the 
testimony  of  witnesses  and  this  testimony  could  always  be  contested,  and 
as  it  brought  up  questions  of  evidence,  there  was  ample  room  for  sharp 
practice. 


THE   CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE   PEACE    91 

from  a  passage  in  the   Wasi)s,  which  is  far  from  clear.      In 
that  play,  performed    two   years   after  the    Knights,  in  422, 
Aristophanes  lets  his  Coryphaeus  say :  "  There  are  those  who 
say  that  I  came  to  terms  with  Cleon  when  he  attacked  me  so 
furiously  and  harried  me  and  stung  me  with  his  calumnies. 
And  while  he  flayed  me,  the  outsiders  looked  on  and  laughed 
when    they    heard    me    cry    out    lustily.     They    were    quite, 
indifferent  to  me,  curious  only  to  see  whether  I  would   sayj 
something  clever  when  squeezed  and  pressed.     I  noticed  this, 
and  did  play  the  ape  a  little  hit.     Thus,  then,  the  vine-prop : 
proved  unfaithful  to  the  vine."  ^ 

Let  us  examine  this  evidence  more  closely.  There  is  no 
room  for  doubt  that  at  a  particular  moment  there  was 
semblance  of  a  truce  between  Aristophanes  and  Cleon.  This 
truce  cannot  have  existed  previous  to  the  Knights ;  that  much 
is  clear  from  the  account  above  given  and  from  the  spirit  of 
the  play  itself.  So  it  must  have  been  after  the  year  424. 
And  finally,  as  we  have  seen,  it  was  forced  upon  the  poet 
through  fear,  when  he  had  been  left  in  the  lurch  by  those  on 
whom  doubtless  he  had  relied.  We  can  accordingly  surmise 
with  fair  accuracy  what  must  have  happened. 

Accused  by  Cleon  of  having  usurped  the  title  citizen,  Aris- 
tophanes did  not  feel  strong  enough  for  a  successful  defence. 
His  friends,  the  young  knights,  were  either  powerless  to  help 
him  or  did  not  concern  themselves  about  the  danger  he  was 
in.  The  populace,  frivolous  as  ever,  enjoyed  seeing  the  fearless 
satirist  tremble,  who  ordinarily  made  others  tremble,  and  did 
not  choose  to  regard  him  otherwise  than  as  a  buffoon,  who  was 
obliged  to  get  out  of  a  scrape  by  aid  of  jokes.  The  danger 
was  grave.  Had  he  been  condemned,  Aristophanes  would 
probably  have  been  subjected  to  a  ruinous  fine,  expelled  from 
the  city,  and  thus  deprived  of  the  right  further  to  occupy 
himself  with  public  affairs.  His  prospects  as  a  poet  would 
have  been  ruined.  To  what  means  did  he  resort  to  save 
himself  ?  His  own  testimony  proves  beyond  doubt  that  Cleon 
withdrew  his  charge,  but  that  he  withdrew  it  only  after  an 
apparent  settlement   had  been   reached,  which,  in  any  case, 

1  Wasps,  11.  1284-1291. 


92  THE  CLOUDS.  THE  WASPS.  THE  PEACE 

could  not  fail  to  be  very  disagreeable  to  Aristophanes.  He 
found  himself  obliged  to  conciliate,  by  hook  or  by  crook,  the 
man  whom  he  had  cruelly  offended.  Apparently  he  could  not 
do  so  without  disavowing  his  intentions,  and  without,  at  the 
same  time,  treating  his  own  play  as  a  mere  piece  of  buffoonery ; 
and  besides,  he  probably  had  to  agree  not  to  publish  it,  and  to 
promise  that  henceforward  he  would  practise  more  restraint 
After  all,  it  may  be  that  Cleon  too  was  not  entirely  sure  of  his 
accusation ;  at  all  events,  he  saw  a  real  advantage  to  himself 
in  this  submission  of  his  adversary,  who  thereby  himself 
destroyed  the  effect  of  his  comedy — an  advantage  he  would 
not  have  secured,  had  he  succeeded  in  depriving  him  of  the 
title  of  citizen.  This  is  no  doubt  the  reason  why  he  withdrew 
his  charge,  after  having  thoroughly  frightened  Aristophanes,  and 
after  having  exulted  in  his  humiliation.  It  may  be  regarded 
as  certain  that  the  case  was  not  brought  to  trial,  and  that 
Aristophanes  was  not  deprived  of  the  title  of  citizen.^ 

^  A  contrary  opinion  is  maintained  by  M.  van  Leeuwen,  De  Arisfophane 
peregrmo,  Mnemosyne,  1888 ;  cf.  edition  of  the  Wasps,  Proleg.  pp.  xii. 
and  xxiii.  It  is  based  on  appearances  merely.  We  do  know  from 
precise  evidence  that  several  of  Aristophanes'  plays  were  performed  under 
borrowed  names,  but  we  have  no  warrant  whatever  for  concluding  from  this 
circumstance  that  he  was  not  entitled  to  have  them  played  under  his  own 
name,  because  he  was  a  foreigner.  In  the  first  place,  it  is  by  no  means  sure 
that  a  foreigner  did  not  enjoy  the  privilege  of  having  comedies  performed 
under  his  own  name ;  and  then,  we  find  poets,  who  were  indisputably 
Athenians,  using  borrowed  names,  just  as  Aristophanes  did.  In  the  year  420 
Eupolis  had  his  Autolycos  performed  as  the  work  of  Demostratos  (Athenaeus, 
V.  216  D).  This  custom  maj'  be  explained  by  many  very  simple  reasons, 
which  we  cannot  enlarge  upon  here,  and  which  must  have  varied  according  to 
the  circumstances.  As  for  the  other  alleged  evidence,  it  has  not  the  meaning 
that  is  arbitrarily  imputed  to  it.  Moreover,  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  if 
Aristophanes  had  been  deprived  of  the  title  citizen,  after  having  once  borne 
it,  his  rivals  and  enemies  would  not  have  been  satisfied  to  inform  us  of 
that  fact  in  obscure  allusions.  They  would  have  shouted  it  from  the 
housetops,  and  the  Alexandrian  scholars  would  not  have  remained  ignorant 
of  it.  This  hypothesis  is  impossible  in  itself,  and,  besides,  it  is  formally 
contradicted  by  the  passage  in  the  Wasps,  which  is  our  most  trustworthy 
document  in  this  case. 


THE   CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE    93 


^'  At  about  the  same  time,  in  April,  424,  Cleon  was  chosen 
"general.^  There  is  no  better  proof  that  the  people  were  far 
from  being  guided  by  the  same  opinions  in  the  theatre  and  at 
the  elections. 

This  election  was  another  triumph  for  Cleon.  Aristophanes 
could  not  refrain  from  showing  his  annoyance  at  it.  At  the 
close  of  the  year  424  his  comedy,  the  Clouds,  was  written, 
which  seemed  to  give  evidence  of  his  intention  temporarily  to 
hold  aloof  from  politics ;  in  it  there  was  no  mention  of  the  war 
nor  of  the  statesmen  of  the  day.  But  at  the  last  moment,  no 
doubt,  just  as  the  comedy  was  about  to  be  performed,  that  is 
shortly  before  the  Dionysia  of  423,  he  inserted  into  the  parabasis 
(1.  581  et  seq.)  a  trenchant  allusion  to  Cleon's  election  and  an 
appeal  to  the  people  to  get  rid  of  this  "  robber,"  as  quickly  as 
possible,  by  putting  his  neck  in  the  pillory.  He  was  evidently 
aware  that  the  danger  was  over.  By  withdrawing  his  charge, 
Cleon  had  thrown  away  his  weapons.  Besides,  being  satisfied 
for  the  moment  with  his  success,  and  being  busy  with  quite 
another  matter,  he  could  give  but  little  attention  to  a  sort  of 
insult  which  had  long  since  lost  its  sting,  because  it  was  so 
freely  used. 

Apart  from  this  isolated  attack,  the  Clouds  contains  no  trace 
of  political  satire.^  Can  we  be  sure,  however,  that,  while 
writing  this  play,  the  author  kept  clear  of  party  manoeuvres  ? 
At  any  rate  this  question  deserves  to  be  examined. 

The  substance  of  the  plot  is,  as  we  know,  a  lively  attack  on 
Socrates.  In  it  we  see  a  peasant,  the  worthy  Strepsiades, 
who  has  run  into  debt  through  the  fault  of  his  wife  and  his 
son.     Hard  pressed  by  his  creditors,  he  appeals  to  the  philo- 

'  Clouds,  1.  581  et  seq.  and  the  note  of  J,  van  Leeuwen.  Cf.  Busolt,  Griech. 
Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1124. 

-Siivem's  opinion  {Uber  Aristophanes  Wolken,  p.  33  et  seq.),  followed  by 
Gilbert  (Beitrdrje,  p.  218),  that  Pheidippides  represents  Alcibiades,  ought,  I 
think,  to  be  entirely  discarded,  notwithstanding  the  reference  contained  in  the 
second  argument.  There  is  no  definite  allusion  to  lend  it  the  slightest 
semblance  of  probability. 

H 


94  THE  CLOUDS.  THE  WASPS.  THE  PEACE 

sopher,  as  to  the  possessor  of  a  wonderful  secret,  thanks  to 
which  one  may  be  relieved  of  paying  one's  debts.  Socrates, 
the  atheist  and  sophist,  in  a  trice  upsets  all  the  good  fellow's 
moral  ideas  and  religious  convictions.  But  as  he  is  too  thick- 
headed to  learn  the  arts  of  quibbling  himself,  he  sends  his 
son  Pheidippides  to  school  in  his  stead.  The  new  pupil  is  too 
highly  gifted,  and  promptly  becomes  an  impudent  boaster  and 
a  rebellious  son.  The  father,  enlightened  at  last,  sets  fire  to 
the  school. 

The  general  thought  which  stands  out  from  this  plot  is  very 
clear.  The  poet  wished  to  show  how  the  Athenian  character, 
simple  and  honest  under  the  influence  of  tradition,  might  be 
changed  and  even  depraved  by  philosophy  and  rhetoric.  This 
character  he  finds  here,  as  elsewhere,  in  an  inhabitant  of  the 
country.  Strepsiades  had  remained  an  honest  man,  as  long  as 
he  lived  in  the  fields,  on  his  little  farm.  In  those  days  he 
lived  happily  and  even  prosperously  in  his  small  way,  without 
worries  and  without  ambition,  just  as  his  fathers  had  lived. 
His  first  misfortune  was  an  ill-assorted  marriage  which  obliged 
him  to  live  in  the  city  for  the  greater  part  of  his  time.  By 
this  he  has  jeopardized  his  fortune  and  contracted  debts,  and 
so  become  subject  to  the  temptations  of  sopliistry,  which 
corrupts  him  at  least  temporarily.  And  though  its  fatal 
influence  does  not  last  with  the  father,  whose  better  nature 
promptly  gains  the  upper  hand,  there  is  every  reason  to  believe 
that  it  will  endure  with  the  son,  of  whom  it  makes  a  perfect 
rascal. 

This  is  about  the  same  idea  that  had  inspired  the  poet's  first 
play,  the  Banqueters,  only  he  seems  here  to  have  embodied  it 
in  a  stronger  plot,  and  so  to  have  given  it  greater  importance. 
Was  it  of  aristocratic  origin  ?  A  certain  number  of  old  families, 
who  clung  to  the  past,  must  certainly  have  been  in  favor  of 
it  since  the  middle  of  the  century.  But  why  should  not  the 
rural  democracy,  very  tenacious,  as  it  was,  of  its  moral  and 
religious  convictions,  and  rather  uncharitable  toward  every- 
thing that  came  from  elsewhere,  have  been  equally  in  favor  of 
it  ?  A-t  all  events,  in  Aristophanes'  day  the  militant  aristo- 
cracy were  far  from  accepting  it ;  on  the  contrary,  they  were, 


THE  CLOUDS.  THE  WASPS.  THE  PEACE  95 

without  doubt,  the  strongest  supporters  of  sophistry.     It  was    -|- 

they  who  welcomed  the  sophists,  who  paid  for  their  teacliing, 

who  supplied  them  with  the  patronage    they  needed.     Their 

leading  theorists,  men  like  Antiphon,  Theramenes,  and  Critias, 

were  among  those  who  were   attracted    by  the   new  culture. 

It  was  among  the  upper  classes  that  the  adepts  in  rhetoric 

were  chiefly  to  be  found,  as  well  as  the  great  wits  and  the 

dialecticians  who  inquired  into  the  why  and  wherefore  of  things, 

at  the  risk  of  overthrowing  and  destroying  religious  and  social 

beliefs.      The  disciples  of  Socrates  were  regarded  as  enemies  of 

democracy.^     Several  of  them  belonged  by  birth  to  the  best 

families  of  Athens,  and  so  it  may  be  regarded  as  quite  certain 

that  when  Aristophanes  wrote  his   Clouds,  he  did  not  make  \^\^,.^..f,^y, 

himself  the  mouthpiece  of  those  whom  he  had  taken  as  allies, 

the  year  before,  in  the  Knights. 

In  his  play,  it  is  true,  Aristophanes  has  in  no  way  brought 
out,  or  even  indicated,  this  aristocratic  side  of  sophistry  in 
general,  and  in  the  Socratic  school  in  particular.  It  is  hard  to 
say  whether  he  would  have  found  any  advantage  in  doing  so, 
for,  while  he  might  have  flattered  certain  popular  feelings,  he 
would  have  run  the  risk  of  offending  some  of  his  friends.  But, 
in  fact,  there  is  no  evidence  that  he  had  a  very  clear  appre- 
ciation of  this  phase  of  sophistry.  It  admitted  many  fine 
distinctions,  which  a  contemporary  would  apprehend  only  with 
ditiiculty. 

Though  sophistical  teachings,  in  the  proper  sense  of  the 
word,  like  those  of  Protagoras,  Prodicus,  Gorgias,  and  a  few 
others,  found  favor  chiefly  among  the  aristocracy,  it  must  be 
admitted  that  they  tended  directly  to  ruin  the  principles  with- 
I'Ut  which  it  could  not  exist.  The  influence  of  an  aristocracy 
necessarily  depends  upon  an  instinctive  respect  for  tradition. 
Whatever  weakens  this  respect  is  a  direct  menace  to  it — a  very 
evident  truth  to  our  minds,  of  which,  however,  the  ambitious 
uligarchs  of  the  fifth  century  do  not  seem  to  have  had  the 
slightest  conception.  They  did  perceive  that  dialectics  and 
rhetoric  afforded   them   effective  means  of   persuasion  in  the 

1  Plato,  Apology,  c.  x.  and  especially  e.  xxi.  .   .  .  tovtuv  .   .  .  ,  oOs  oi  dia^dX- 
Xoi'Tes  /j,€  (pacLv  ifioiis  /MadrjTas  elvai. 


96  THE  CLOUDS.  THE  WASPS.  THE  PEACE 

law-courts  and  political  gatherings.  That  sufficed  to  delude 
them.  Engrossed  in  their  immediate  success,  they  did  not 
dream  of  the  latent  influence  which  the  new  rationalism  could 
not  fail  to  exert  on  the  mentality  of  the  people,  to  the  detri- 
ment of  their  own  former  social  standing.  Besides,  they  were 
themselves  saturated  with  the  new  philosophy.  They  were 
utilitarians  and  positivists  in  their  way  of  thinking,  and  had 
lost  faith  in  their  hereditary  role  and  in  all  that  could  serve  to 
ennoble  it.  The  majority  of  them  regarded  their  political 
power  as  an  individual  satisfaction,  as  a  means  of  enjoyment, 
and  not  as  a  conservative  social  force,  transmitted  from  genera- 
tion to  generation,  for  the  common  weal  of  the  city.  Had  the 
poet  really  cared  for  the  interests  of  the  aristocracy,  so  far  as 
they  were  connected  with  the  interests  of  society,  or  had  any 
of  his  patrons  made  them  clear  to  him,  he  ought  to  have  tried 
to  open  the  eyes  of  his  fellow-citizens  to  this  serious  and  really 
fatal  error.  And  then  he  would  have  had  to  represent,  not  a 
good  fellow  from  the  country,  as  the  victim  of  the  sophists,  but 
rather  the  descendant  of  some  great  family,  as  seduced  by 
them,  and  undermining  the  moral  inheritance  of  his  race 
through  selfish  ambition.  Such  was  indeed  the  most  serious 
and  portentous  social  phenomenon  that  could  attract  the  atten- 
tion of  an  observer  at  that  time.  Aristophanes  does  not  seem 
to  have  had  an  inkling  of  it,  and  if  some  of  those  with  whom 
he  associated  saw  it  or  suspected  it,  he  did  not,  in  any  sense, 
constitute  himself  their  spokesman. 

As  for  Socrates,  if  Aristophanes  had  known  him  well,  and 
if  he  had  been  devoted  to  the  interests  of  the  aristocracy, 
everybody  agrees  to-day  that,  instead  of  combating  him,  he 
ought  to  have  considered  him  his  strongest  ally.  In  a  society 
which,  more  and  more,  felt  the  need  of  reasoning,  Socrates' 
task  consisted  in  endeavoring  to  re-establish  by  logic  what 
logic  had  first  upset — namely,  precisely  that  which  the  comedy 
defended.     This  task  Aristophanes  misunderstood  completely. 

But  we  must  observe  that  this  misunderstanding  was 
certainly  not  due  to  his  aristocratic  surroundings,  which  have 
sometimes  been  thought  to  have  had  a  strong  influence  upon 
him.     The  prejudices  which  appear  in  his  comedy  must  have 


THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE    97 

prevailed  mucii  more  among  the  common  people  than, among 
the  intellectual  elite  of  Athenian  society.  Of  course,  it  is 
possible  that  in  those  days  the  aristocratic  tendencies  of 
Socrates'  ideas  were  not  so  clearly  discerned  as  at  a  somewhat 
later  time,  when,  among  many  others,  he  won  over  Xenophon 
and  the  sons  of  Ariston.  The  philosopher  himself,  sprung 
from  the  people,  whose  manners  and  habits  he  pretended  to 
retain,  probably  did  not,  at  that  time,  or  possibly  at  any  time, 
think  that  he  was  an  opponent, of  democracy.  But,  whatever 
he  may  have  thought  about  it,  he  was"  such,  on  account  of  his 
profound  way  of  thinking,  which  considered  capacity  as  the 
condition  of  power,  and  recognized  no  right  that  was  not 
accompanied  by  the  ability  necessary  for  its  exercise.  He 
made  no  attempt  to  disguise  this  tendency  in  his  talks,^  and  it 
had  no  small  share  in  giving  rise  to  opinions  unfavorable  to 
him.  He  must  have  had  enemies  in  every  class  of  society, 
but  it  was  certainly  among  the  people  that  he  called  forth 
most  distrust  and  hostility.  His  trial  clearly  showed  this,  and 
nothing  was  really  more  natural. 

Let  me  recall  his  conversation  with  Charmides  in  Xeno- 
phon's  Memorabilia.  The  noble  and  wealthy  Charmides  keeps 
aloof  from  public  affairs,  owing  to  an  unconquerable  sense  of 
shyness.  What  does  Socrates  do  in  his  attempt  to  reassure 
him  and  to  encourage  him  to  take  a  more  active  part  ?  He 
shows  him  what  the  Athenian  people  are :  a  mass  of  artisans, 
masons,  cobblers  and  fullers,  ignorant  and  vulgar.  Should 
such  judges  frighten  an  educated  man  ?  The  theme  is  appro- 
priate to  the  circumstances,  but  it  is  not  an  accidental  one ;  in 
it  Socrates  expresses  his  inmost  conviction — to  his  mind 
proper  conduct  was  always  conditioned  on  knowledge,  and  he 
spent  his  life  in  making  people  see  that  they  did  not  under- 
stand the  A  B  C  of  things  in  which  they  presumed  to  interfere.^ 

At  best,  only  cultivated  minds  could  comprehend  this,  and 
there  is  much  evidence  to  show  that  the  most  intelligent  men 

1  Plato,  Apology,  c.  xviii.  p.  30  e. 

2  Plato,  Apology,  cc.  vi.-viii.  The  last  chapter  shows  that  Socrates,  after 
having  made  famous  statesmen,  poets,  or  artists  recognize  their  ignorance, 
did  not  meet  with  less  infatuation  or  presumptuous  folly  among  the  artisans. 


98    THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE 

came  back  to  him,  and  became  subject  to  his  influence,  after 
having  at  first  been  annoyed  by  his  teachings.      In  spite  of 
their  vexation,  the  lofty  quality  of  his  intellectual  and  moral 
nature  could  not  entirely  escape  them,  and  in  the  circles  in 
which  a  degree  of   mental  activity  prevailed,  a  very  strong 
recognition  of  his  superiority  became  general.      But  among  the 
common  people  nothing  of  the  kind  took  place.     To  them  his 
curious   appearance,  his    peculiar   manners,   his    ironical    and 
indiscreet    questions,  and   finally,  his    offensive    candor,  must 
have  made  him  appear   like   an  ill-natured  fanatic.     People 
naturally  classed  him  with  the  sophists,  because,  like  them,  he 
/busied  himself  with  subtle  matters  and,  like  them,  discussed 
/all  sorts  of  subjects.     They  credited  him  with  ideas  that  were 
1  vaguely  attributed  to  all  of  them  indiscriminately,  made  him 
I  out  an  atheist  and  a  dangerous  dialectician,  because  he  thought 
'  he   had  a  right  to  subject  all  beliefs  and  all  doubts  to  the 
closest  scrutiny ;  and  they,  no  doubt,  hated  him  much  more 
than  other  philosophers  just  because  he  took  issue  with  every- 
body, instead  of  confining  himself  to  a  circle  of  chosen  disciples. 
It    is    probable    that   Aristophanes    adopted    this    popular 
opinion,  and  that  he   constructed   the  character  in  his  play 
according  to  it.     If  he  was  the  interpreter  of  borrowed  views 
when  he  constructed  it  as  he  did,  he  certainly  borrowed  them 
rather  from  the  prejudices  of  the  democracy  than  from  those 
of  the  aristocracy.      It  is  most  likely,  however,  that  he  asked 
nobody  for  inspiration.      Socrates  must  have  been  antipathetic 
to   him.     The  philosopher   did  not  refuse  to  join  in  playful 
conversation,  but  he  had  a  thinker's  contempt  for  whatever 
seemed  to  him  like  buffoonery.      Xenophon  gives  us  proof  of 
this  in  his  Symposium.    It  is  more  than  likely  that  in  this  regard 
he  made  no  distinction  between  legitimate  comedy  and   the 
jests   of   professional    buffoons.l    Everything    in    this   strange 
style  must  have  offended  him — the  vulgar  caricatures,  the  lack 
of  dignity,  the  unfair  severity  of  the  satire  ;   and  he  was  not 
the  man  to  disguise  his  thoughts.      Of  course,  the  fiction  of 
Plato's  Symposium  does  not  suflftce  to  establish  that  Aristophanes 
ever  met  Socrates,  nor  that  he  had  direct  dealings  with  him. 
It  must,  however,  be  admitted  that  this  is,  to  say  the  least. 


THE   CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE   PEACE    99 

very  probable.  At  all  events,  the  philosopher's  opinions  had 
only  to  be  reported  to  the  poet  in  order  to  call  forth  a  certain 
animosity  against  him.  And  how  could  they  have  failed  to 
be  reported  in  a  society  of  idlers  who  spent  their  time  in 
chatting  ?  But  these  personal  grievances,  if  they  existed  at 
all,  grew  to  be  of  such  importance,  merely  because  they  coin- 
cided with  Aristophanes'  more  general  and  profounder  views, 
upon  which  they  acted  like  leaven. 

The  poet  hated  the  very  name  of  philosophy,  and  thought 
it  detestable.  He  thought  that  it  not  only  cast  a  gloom 
over  happy  and  energetic  Athens,  but  also  perverted  it. 
Through  it  the  young  people  grew  morose  and  pale,  studied 
a  thousand  useless  things,  instead  of  gaily  taking  part  in  active 
life.  Through  it,  furthermore,  they  learned  to  doubt  or  to 
abjure  the  traditional  principles  of  life,  and  became  babblers 
and  dialecticians.  It  seemed  to  him  that  the  very  safeguards 
of  domestic  and  public  morality  were  being  lost,  little  by 
little,  in  this  disquieting  transformation.  Of  course  there  is 
no  use  in  demonstrating  here  what  elements  of  exaggeration 
there  were  in  these  views,  and,  above  all,  how  they  erred  in 
failing  to  take  into  account  the  most  apparent  demands  of  the 
changes  which  were  taking  place  at  that  period.  But,  on 
the  other  hand,  it  would  be  very  thoughtless  not  to  recognize 
the  amount  of  correct  observation  and  of  truth  that  they 
contained,  Aristophanes  felt  that  he  was  witnessing  a  pro-j 
found  crisis.  His  mind  was  neither  broad  enough  non 
deliberate  enough  to  in(j[uire  whether  it  was  inevitable.  He 
did  see  that  it  was  dangerous  for  Athens,  that  it  would  t 
probably  result  in  impairing  her  virtue,  in  the  broadest  sense  \ 
of  the  word ;  and  one  can  hardly  say  that  he  was  mistaken. 

The  Clouds  was  not  a  success,^  and  at  this  Aristophanes 
was  both  surprised  and  hurt.  It  seemed  to  hun,  and  not 
without  reason,  that  he  had  never  written  anything  better; 
and  it  would  certainly  have  been  difhcult  to  clothe  so  serious 
a  thought  in  a  series  of  more  amusing  conceits.  Regarded  as 
a  work  of  art,  his  play  gave  evidence  of  a  really  new  species  of 
composition.     In  its  fundamental  idea   it  touched   upon  the 

^  Argument  v. 


100   THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE 

most  important  question  of  the  time.  He  remodelled  his  play, 
more  or  less  completely,  with  the  intention  of  producing  it 
once  more.  This  is  shown  by  the  first  part  of  the  existing 
parabasis,  which  was  written  with  a  view  to  this  second 
performance.^  This  performance  seems  not  to  have  taken 
place ;  but  the  poet,  no  doubt,  persisted  in  his  view,  and 
posterity  has  agreed  with  him. 

What  was  the  cause  of  this  failure  ?  One  would  be  rather 
simple-minded  to  seek  it,  as  some  have  done,  in  a  sense  of 
justice  on  the  part  of  the  Athenian  people,  who  were  disgusted 
by  the  way  in  which  the  poet  treated  Socrates.  Plato's 
Apology  would  prove,  if  there  were  need,  that  this  was  not 
the  case.  It  declares  formally  that  Aristophanes'  comedy 
contributed  to  Socrates'  unpopularity,  and  this  obliges  us  to 
believe  that  it  did  not  call  forth  any  protest  of  the  sort 
mentioned  from  the  people.  We  may  even  infer  from  this 
evidence  that  the  comedy  produced  its  effect,  slowly,  but 
surely.  It  is,  therefore,  probable  that  it  was  published,  and 
that,  in  default  of  an  audience,  it^found  many  readers.  More- 
over, the  silence  of  the  scholiasts  does  not  prevent  us  from 
assuming  that  it  may  have  had  a  second  performance,  either 
at  Piraeus,  or  in  the  suburbs  of  the  city,  or  on  the  rustic  stage 
of  some  deme.  Such  a  performance  would  not  leave  any  trace 
in  literary  history.  However  this  may  be,  the  fact  of  his 
failure  in  the  official  competition  of  423  stands  on  record; 
but  it  can  be  explained  only  on  purely  literary  grounds. 
Accustomed  as  we  are  to  legitimate  comedy,  Aristophanes' 
play  appears  very  amusing  to  us ;  and  so  it  is  when  read. 
The  Athenian  audience  must  have  thought  it  dreary  and 
^Vere.  The  chorus  was  not  at  all  funny  or  gay,  there  was 
no  absurd  dance,  no  jostling,  no  extravagant  gambols  and 
contortions.  While  watching  it,  the  audience  had  not  been 
convulsed   with   that    irresistible    laughter   which   seemed   to 

iThe  statements  contained  in  Arguments  v.  and  vii.  regarding  the  re- 
modelling of  the  play  have  given  rise  to  considerable  controversy.  See  J.  van 
Leeuwen,  ed.  of  the  Clouds,  Prolegomena,  p.  ix,  and  p.  6  note  2.  But  nobody 
denies,  or  can  deny,  that  the  first  part  of  the  parabasis  was  added  subse- 
quently. 


THE   CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE    101 

them  to  be  the  chief  essential  of  a  good  comedy.  The  judges 
were  actuated  by  the  common  opinion  when  they  ^jreferred 
the  Bottle  by  Cratinus  and  the  Connos  by  Ameipsias. 


ni 

The  failure  of  the  Clouds  probably  had  much  to  do  with  a 
renewal  of  Aristophanes'  hostility  to  Cleon.  Hitherto  he  had 
succeeded  best  in  political  comedies.  He  decided  to  return  to 
them  at  whatev^er  risk,  and  he  could  not  return  to  them 
without  attacking  Cleon  directly  or  indirectly. 

It  is  chiefly  Cleon,  indeed,  among  the  demagogues  that  is 
again  made  the  butt  of  his  satire  in  the  comedy  of  the  Wasjos, 
performed  at  the  Lenaea  of  the  year  422,  and  consequently 
written  at  the  close  of  the  year  423.  It  is  well  known  that 
the  play  seeks  to  point  out  what  may  be  called  the  corruption 
of  the  judicial  system  at  Athens.  The  principle  itself  of  this 
system  is  not  attacked,  but  rather  the  changes  in  this  principle, 
wrought  by  the  politicians  of  the  advanced  democracy.  That 
is  the  reason  why  the  person  in  whom  this  corruption  is 
incarnated  is  called  the  "friend  of  Cleon"  (Philocleon),  whereas 
his  son,  who  wishes  to  reform  him,  is  called  the  "  enemy  of 
Cleon  "  (Bdelycleon). 

Here,  as  before,  it  behoves  us  to  get  a  clear  view  of  the 
fundamental  idea  of  the  play,  in  order  to  determine  accurately 
the  nature  of  Aristophanes'  opposition  and  its  relation  to  the 
theories  of  the  time. 

We  know  how  far  the  organization  of  the  Athenian  law-courts 
in  the  fifth  century  conformed  to  the  highest  conception  of 
democracy.^  Every  citizen  wh(j  was  at  least  thirty  years  of 
age  was  entitled  to  act  as  judge,  and  there  were  no  other 
judges,  save  in  exceptional  cases.  Together  they  constituted 
what  was  known  as  the  'BXiala,  and  in  their  quality  as  judges 
they  were  called  heliasts.  Lots  were  drawn  among  the  heliasts 
to  determine  which  of  them  were  to  sit  in  each  court.     Thus 

1  Aristotle,  Constitution  of  Athens,  c.  Ixiii.  ;  Schoeraann-Lipsius,  Griech. 
AUerthUmer,  i.  p.  506. 


102   THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE 

these  courts  were  actually  juries,  often  very  numerous,  easily 
swayed,  as  passionate  as  all  assemblies,  and  entirely  lacking  in 
legal  knowledge.  The  heliasts  who  were  chosen  to  sit  received 
compensation  from  the  state,  which  Cleon  had  recently  caused 
to  be  increased  to  three  obols,  in  order  to  make  himself 
popular^ — surely  a  moderate  sum,  but  one  that  probably,  at 
that  time,  sufficed  to  support  a  family  for  a  day.  One  can 
readily  understand  that  wealthy  citizens,  men  of  affairs,  active 
and  busy  artisans,  little  cared  to  lose  their  time,  listening  to 
the  pettifogging  of  lawyers,  for  so  meagre  a  compensation. 
But  small  tradesmen,  the  poor,  the  lazy,  as  well  as  aged  or 
idle  artisans,  there  found  a  very  convenient  means  of  earning 
a  living.  And  so  it  was  they  who  eagerly  attended  the  draw- 
ing of  names,  while  the  others  stayed  away,  thanks  to  the  laxity 
of  law  or  custom. 

Courts  thus  constituted  could  not  fail  to  be  permeated  with 
all  the  prejudices  and  all  the  passions  of  the  lower  classes. 
They  were  suspicious  and  severe  toward  the  rich,  tyrannical 
toward  the  allies,  ever  ready  to  listen  to  the  denunciator,  full 
of  sympathy  for  professional  accusers  who,  by  increasing  the 
number  of  lawsuits,  secured  the  judges  an  opportunity  to  sit. 
Trials  were  actually  their  daily  bread,  and  the  demagogues 
were  well  aware  of  this,  and  had  no  greater  means  of  influence 
than  the  frequency  with  which  charges  were  brought.  Kadical 
politicians  on  the  Pnyx,  they  became  sycophants  in  the  courts : 
these  were,  in  a  way,  the  two  phases  of  one  and  the  same  role, 
or  rather  the  two  halves  of  one  and  the  same  whole. 

Such  law-courts  could  not  fail  to  be  an  object  of  fear  and  I 
at  the  same  time  of  ridicule  to  the  citizen  of  the  upper  classes.  I 
When  Charmides,  in  Xenophon's  Banquet,  congratulates  himself 
on  having  become  poor,  he  says  that  one  of  the  chief  advan- 
tages he  has  derived  from  his  ruin  is  that  he  is  rid  of  the 
sycophants.^  Pear  of  denunciation  must  indeed  have  been  a 
constant  anguish  for  people  who  knew  what  sort  of  judges 
they  would  have  to  appear  before  in  case  they  were  accused. 
The  aristocratic  doctrinaire  who  wrote  the  treatise  on  the 
Polity  of  the  Athenians,  quoted  above,  has  but  one  sentence 
^Gilbert,  Beitrdge,  p.  187.  -Xenophon,  Banquet,  iv.  30. 


THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE    103 

about  the  courts,  but  it  is  a  cruel  arraignment :  "  As  for  the 
law-courts,  the  people  bring  to  them  thoughts,  not  of  justice, 
but  of  their  personal  interests."  ^  Such  was  the  accepted 
opinion  in  the  circles  from  which  this  book  issued. 

Did  this  opinion  find  expression  in  a  programme  of  reforms  ? 
There  can  be  no  doubt  that  it  did.  The  doctrine  of  the 
moderate  aristocracy,  or  even  of  the  conservative  democracy, 
necessarily  tended  at  least  toward  a  modification  of  the 
personnel  of  the  courts.  Aristotle  suggests,  as  one  means  of 
escaping  the  evils  that  have  just  been  pointed  out,  a  law 
obliging  every  citizen  to  sit  as  judge  when  he  is  drawn  by  lot, 
and  imposing  fines  proportionate  to  their  fortunes  on  those 
who  remain  away,  with  exemption  for  the  poor.  In  this  wise, 
he  says,  the  wealthy  are  forced  to  sit,  while  freedom  of  choice 
is  given  to  the  poor.^  He  also  informs  us  that  this  was  a 
provision  in  the  laws  of  Charondas,  so  that  it  went  back 
beyond  the  fifth  century.  No  doubt  it  was  known  and 
admired  by  those  at  Athens  who  desired  to  reform  the 
republic ;  besides,  it  could  be  made  to  agree  perfectly  with 
the  letter,  at  least,  of  existing  institutions,  if  not  with  their 
spirit.  The  oligarchy,  properly  speaking,  went  still  further. 
We  do  not  know  precisely  what  disposition  the  revolution  of 
the  year  411  made  of  the  courts,  but  perhaps  the  most 
important  principle  by  which  it  was  inspired  was  that  all 
public  offices  should  be  without  salaries.^  There  is  every 
reason  to  believe  that  it  did  not  propose  to  except  the  salary 
of  the  judges.  A  few  years  later,  at  all  events,  the  oligar- 
chical government  of  404,  even  during  the  time  when  it  was 
relatively  moderate,  took  great  care  to  break  the  power  of  the 
courts.*  "We  may  be  sure  that  in  doing  so  it  merely  put  into 
operation  a  programme  which  had  long  since  been  elaborated  , 
in  the  hetairies. 

Therefore,  the   question    for   us    to   solve  is   whether  this 
programme,  which    had    certainly  been  discussed  since  422, 

^Ps.-Xenophon,  Polity  of  the  Athenians,  i.  c.  xiii. 

^Aristotle,  Politics,  iv.  13.  2,  Bergk. 

^Aristotle,  Constitution  of  Athens,  29.  5  :  ras  5'dpxas  d/UiV^ous  &pxeiv  aTrdaas. 

*  Ibid.  35.  2 :  /cai  rb  Kvpos  5  rjv  iv  tois  Si/caorats  KaTi\v(Tav. 


104   THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE 

had  any  influence  on  Aristophanes'  comedy,  and  whether  he 
ought,  to  a  certain  extent,  to  be  regarded  as  the  interpreter 
of  the  views  of  a  party,  with  whom  we  have  already  found 
him  holding  relations,  but  relations  of  an  independent  kind. 

The  prologue  of  the  Wasps  shows  us  the  aged  Philocleon, 
closely  watched  in  his  house  by  his  son  Bdelycleon  and  by  his 
slaves,  who  wish,  at  all  costs,  to  prevent  him  from  going  to 
\sit  as  a  judge.  Why  do  they  prevent  him  ?  Solely  for  his 
Igood.  His  mania  for  being  a  judge  is  characterized  as  a 
"strange  malady"  (1.  71),  which  Bdelycleon  wishes  to  cure  at 
any  cost.  From  the  description  given  us  of  this  malady  (11. 
87-135),  we  do  indeed  recognize  that  it  was  real  insanity,  and 
painful  at  that.  Racine  has  translated  a  considerable  part  of 
this  description  in  his  Plaideurs.  Philocleon  cannot  sleep,  or, 
when  he  does  succumb  to  fatigue  for  a  moment,  his  sleep  is 
disturbed  by  dreams  that  refer  to  the  law-court.  This  mania 
turns  into  malice — he  condemns  everybody.  At  the  same 
time,  it  leads  him  to  commit  countless  extravagances.  His 
son  is  sincerely  grieved  by  it, — he  has  tried  to  argue  with 
him,  but  to  no  purpose.  Then  he  puts  him  into  the  hands  of 
the  Cory  ban  tes,  but  still  without  success.  He  has  made  him 
lie  down  in  the  temple  of  Asclepius,  and  this  does  no  good 
either.  Finally,  he  has  had  to  lock  him  up  in  his  house  and 
carefully  close  all  the  doors.  Such  is  the  opening  scene,  and, 
as  we  see,  it  is  not  the  higher  interests  of  justice  that  are  at 
stake ;  it  is  the  personal  interests  of  Philocleon,  but  of  Philo- 
cleon considered  as  the  representative  of  a  whole  class  of 
Athenians. 

We  may  pass  over  his  attempts  to  escape  ;  they  are  mere 
tomfoolery.  And  now  comes  the  entrance  of  the  chorus. 
This  chorus  consists  of  aged  heliasts,  who  are  on  their  way  to 
court  before  daybreak.  Cleon  has  advised  them  to  bring  a 
supply  of  anger  because  they  are  to  sit  in  judgment  on  the 
general  Laches,  whom  he  has  accused  of  embezzlement  and 
corruption  after  his  campaign  in  Sicily  (11.  240-245).  Evi- 
dently the  poet  is  anxious  to  expose  this  sort  of  agreement 
or  tacit  understanding  between  the  demagogues  and  the 
heliasts.      He   is   their   purveyor,  but   they   obey    him.     The 


THE   CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE    105 

politician  feeds  the  judges,  the  judges  do  the  bidding  of 
the  politician. 

These  heliasts  wonder  at  Philocleon's  delay.  Is  he  ill  ? 
Does  he  not  know  that  grave  matters  are  to  be  dealt  with  ? 
While  asking  one  another  such  questions  as  these,  they  get 
on  as  fast  as  they  can  ;  for  if,  by  chance,  the  archon  fails 
to  put  their  names  into  the  ballot  box,  what  are  they  to  live 
on  ?  Philocleon  hears  them,  calls  them  and  explains  how  and 
why  he  is  held  captive.  And  they  urge  him  to  escape. 
We  see  him  gnawing  at  the  meshes  of  the  net,  stretched  across 
one  of  his  windows ;  he  slips  through  the  gap.  Is  he  free  ? 
No,  Bdelycleon  has  heard  him.  The  watchers  come  running 
—the  fugitive  is  seized  and  beaten.  The  old  men  utter  cries, 
they  make  threats  of  informing  their  protector,  Cleon.  Bdely- 
cleon keeps  his  temper  and  implores  them  to  hear  his  reasons. 
At  first  they  refuse  to  do  so,  shout  and  cry  tyranny ;  then 
they  calm  themselves  little  by  little,  and  finally  permit  him  to 
speak  to  them. 

As  may  be  conjectured,  this  is  the  principal  scene,  or,  at 
all  events,  the  one  that  is  most  important  for  the  argument. 
And  what  precisely  is  the  purpose  of  this  argument  ?  Before 
entering  into  it,  Bdelycleon  concisely  defines  its  import. 
What  he  wishes  to  prove  is  that  his  father  is  mistaken  in 
thinking  that  the  office  of  heliast  secures  him  any  advantage, 
whereas,  in  fact,  it  makes  him  "  the  slave  of  the  demagogue  " 
(11.  504-507;  514-517).  As  before,  the  selfish  interests  of 
the  judge  are  the  real  and  chief  object  of  the  argument,  and 
yet,  back  of  these  interests,  still  another  matter  may  be  dis- 
cerned, and  this  is  the  question  of  the  independence  of  justice 
and  consequently  of  its  value. 

Philocleon  is  the  first  to  speak,  and  to  show  all  the  advan- 
tages he  owes  to  the  ^Xiala,  and  naturally  enough,  the  audience 
would  regard  his  speech  as  a  very  lively  and  amusing  satire 
on  the  Athenian  judge.  To  begin  with,  this  judge  is  a  sort 
of  king,  a  king  who  has,  as  his  courtiers  and  flatterers,  all  the 
accused,  however  important  they  may  be.  We  may  point  out 
that  this  thought  is  also  met  with  in  the  treatise  of  pseudo- 
Xenophon   on   the  Polity   of  the   Athenians,  which   has   been 


106   THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE 

repeatedly  quoted.^  It  is  therefore  likely  that  it  was  current 
in  the  aristocratic  circles,  from  whom  Aristophanes  may  well 
have  borrowed  it.  But,  at  best,  it  is  nothing  more  than  a 
mocking  characterization  of  no  great  consequence.  The  same 
may  be  said  of  almost  everything  that  Philocleon  says. 
He  gives  us  a  detailed  picture  of  what  may  be  called  the 
comedy  of  the  courts — the  tears  of  the  defendants,  the  appeals 
of  parents  and  friends,  the  introduction  of  small  children  and 
wives,  all  means  by  which  attempts  are  made  either  to  soften 
the  heart  of  the  judge,  or  to  enliven  him,  or  to  seduce  him. 
An  actor  recites  verses,  a  flute-player  plays  the  flute;  the 
judge  listens,  enjoys  himself  and  decides  as  suits  him,  for  he  is 
responsible  to  nobody  (1.  587).  Moreover,  his  power  extends 
beyond  the  law-court.  In  the  assembly  also  the  politicians 
make  themselves  popular  by  promising  the  heliasts  more  pay 
and  less  work  (11.  592-602). 

In  a  word,  if  this  satire,  which  is  so  pleasantly  hidden 
beneath  apparent  praise,  has  a  serious  meaning,  it  lies  in  two 
things.  In  the  first  place,  it  gives  us  a  clear  understanding 
of  the  psychology  of  the  heliast,  and  so  explains  with  great 
spirit  and  insight  why  the  small  tradesmen  of  Athens  found 
so  much  pleasure  in  acting  as  judges,  and  why  honest  folk  as 
they  were  in  everyday  life,  they  became  thoroughly  perverse  in 
the  law-courts.  In  the  second  place,  it  reinforces  a  suggestion 
to  which  allusion  is  made  above,  by  showing  us  the  politicians 
absorbed  in  pleasing  the  judges.  Apart  from  this,  there  is 
only  one  serious  word  to  be  noted,  namely  the  "  irresponsible," 
uttered  quite  casually.  Already  in  the  Kidglits  the  people 
had  been  called  a  "  tyrant,"  that  is  to  say,  an  absolute  ruler. 
The  same  idea  is  here  applied  to  the  tyKiaia,  but  with  much 
less  insistence  and  forcefulness. 

When  Philocleon  has  finished  his  argument,  Bdelycleon 
replies  to  him.  Aristophanes  has  given  him  the  task  of 
thoroughly  exposing  "  the  old  canker  that  has  taken  root  in 
the  republic"  (1.  651).  It  looks  as  if  he  wished  to  refute  his 
father's  brief,  point  by  point;  he  really  does  nothing  of  the 

1  Pseudo-Xenophon,  Polity  of  the  Athtnians,  i.  18.  The  similaritj' is  noticed 
in  the  edition  of  J.  van  Leeuwen. 


THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE    107 

sort.  What  is  the  use  of  refuting  an  argument  which  is,  in 
itself,  the  best  satire  on  him  who  makes  it  ?  What  he  does 
refute  is  the  fundamental  error  which  is  at  the  root  of  Philo- 
cleon's  reasoning.  The  latter  has  declared  that  he  is  convinced 
that  the  practice  of  justice  redounds  to  his  personal  benefit. 
Bdelycleon  shows  clearly  that  it  redounds  to  the  benefit  of 
certain  politicians.  As  public  accusers,  and  owing  to  their 
popularity,  the  latter  make  the  tributary  cities  and  the  most 
highly  respected  citizens  in  those  cities  tremble ;  for  it  rests 
with  them  to  secure  the  sentence  of  whomsoever  they  desire. 
And  thus  these  politicians,  being  masters  of  the  courts,  which 
depend  on  their  zeal  for  their  existence,  sell  their  favor,  or 
else  their  silence ;  and  while  they  get  rich  by  such  means,  the 
small  fry,  the  horde  of  judges  who  look  to  them  for  their 
daily  pay,  obey  them  servilely.  In  theory,  the  democracy  is 
sovereign ;  in  reality,  it  is  in  the  hands  of  its  masters. 

As  always  in  comedy,  certain  fanciful  elements  are  added 
to  this  forceful  and  serious  argument.  Bdelycleon  pretends  to 
accept  the  principle  of  the  demagogues,  namely,  that  the 
money  of  the  tributary  cities  ought  to  be  used  to  feed  the 
sovereign  people,  which,  according  to  him,  has  no  other 
function  than  to  rule  and  to  judge.  They  proclaim  this  prin- 
ciple when  it  suits  them ;  but  do  they  put  it  into  effect  when 
they  have  the  government  in  their  hands  ?  A  simple  calcula- 
tion proves  that  this  money,  thus  used,  would  suffice  to  support 
twenty  thousand  Athenian  citizens.  But  the  bulk  of  it  does 
not  reach  the  people — it  remains  in  the  hands  of  the  politicians 
and  their  friends.  Fancies  aside,  Bdelycleon's  figuring  remains 
as  an  amusing  satire  at  least,  well  suited  by  its  very  absurdity 
to  expose  the  lie  from  which  the  demagogues  draw  their 
strength. 

The  rest  is  known,  and  we  need  not  recall  it  in  detail  here. 
The  aged  heliasts  are  enlightened  by  this  instructive  debate ; 
they  forswear  their  errors,  that  is  to  say,  their  confiding 
admiration  for  Cleon  and  his  ilk.  Philocleon  sees  clearly 
that  his  son  is  right,  but  in  his  heart  habit  is  stronger  than 
reason.  He  loves  to  be  a  judge,  he  cannot  get  on  without 
being  a  judge. 


108    THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE 

In  order  to  satisfy  him,  a  law-court  has  to  be  installed  in 
his  house,  and  a  domestic  trial  has  to  be  held  in  it.  It  is  the 
trial  of  the  dog  Labes,  so  well  known  to  us  through  Eacine's 
imitation  of  it  in  his  Plaideurs.  The  historical  allusions  in  the 
original  text  add  nothing  to  the  general  purpose  of  the  play. 
The  last  act  rather  disconcerts  us.  Bdelycleon,  who  has,  no 
doubt,  become  rich  by  working  while  his  father  was  acting 
as  judge,  wishes  him  to  live  in  idleness  and  pleasure  hence- 
forth.-^ He  takes  his  father  out  into  society,  after  having 
made  a  futile  attempt  to  teach  him  good  manners.  There  the 
old  maniac  gets  atrociously  drunk  and  gets  into  all  sorts  of 
scrapes.  We  see  him  come  back  reeling  and  singing,  chased 
by  the  people  whom  he  has  jostled  or  insulted ;  and  the  play 
ends  with  a  grotesque  dance,  in  which  he  joins  some  profes- 
sional dancers  whom  he  has  challenged.  At  this  late  day  it 
seems  to  us  that  this  transformation  did  not  improve  him. 
But  in  the  first  place,  we  must,  no  doubt,  take  into  account 
the  requirements  of  the  style  to  which  Aristophanes  thought 
himself  obliged  to  conform — it  was  necessary  to  conclude  the 
play  with  a  show  that  would  amuse  the  people.  And  besides, 
this  ending,  with  its  comic  exaggeration,  gives  us  a  good  picture 
of  the  Athenian  people  returning  to  their  normal  ways. 
They  were  an  amiable  race,  cheerful,  of  kindly  and  benevolent 
disposition,  of  easy  manners,  unschooled  by  severe  discipline, 
without  harshness — such,  in  a  word,  as  Thucydides  has  described 
them  in  the  famous  speech  which  he  attributes  to  Pericles ; 
and  in  the  play  we  have  seen  them  unnaturally  corrupted  by 
the  influence  of  the  demagogues,  when  they  had  once  yielded 
to  the  mania  of  sitting  as  judges  and  passing  sentence. 

In  order  to  appreciate  this  comedy  as  a  political  satire,  one 
must  really  pay  special  attention  to  the  middle  part,  which,  so 
to  speak,  contains  its  entire  lesson.  And  what  is  its  drift  ? 
We  now  see  clearly  that  the  poet  has  no  thought  whatever  of 

^  The  play  does  not  make  it  quite  clear  why  Philocleon  is  poor,  while  his  son 
Bdelycleon  seems  to  be  very  well  off.  This  difference  in  their  state  was 
necessary  for  the  comedy.  The  real  heliast  was  poor.  On  the  other  hand, 
it  was  necessary  that  Bdelycleon  should  not  be  poor,  in  order  that  he 
might  assure  his  fatlier  of  a  comfortable  livelihood  when  once  he  was  cured.  ^ 
It  is  a  pity  that  the  play  fails  to  explain  how  Bdelycleon  became  wealthy.     V)*^  ^ 


THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE    109 

a  thorough-going  reform  of  the  judicial  system,  on  the  lines  of 
one  of  the  programmes  above  stated.  There  is  nothing  in  his 
play  to  suggest  the  idea  that  it  would  be  well  to  reduce  the 
number  of  judges,  or  to  exclude  the  lower  classes  from  the 
courts,  or  to  use  coercive  measures  against  those  who  neglected 

\  to  appear  there.     He  ridicules  the  credulous  confidence  of  the 

people   in   their   regular  leaders  and  the  generally  accepted 

'notion  that  their  zeal  as  denunciators  was  for  the  public  good. 

Were  we  to  seek  to  derive  some  practical  advice  to  his  fellow 

citizens  from  his  play,  it  might,  perhaps,  be  formulated  thus : 

/"  Athenians,  you  may  be  sure  that  you  have  no  real  interest 

'  m   this  heaping-up  of  lawsuits  instigated  by  the  politicians. 

'  It  is  for  their  own  benefit  that  they  bring  them  and  not  for 
yours.  Do  not,  therefore,  encourage  their  denunciatory  zeal 
by  your  propensity  to  condemn.  On  the  contrary,  reduce  the 
number  of  lawsuits  by  discouraging  the  accusers,  and,  at  the 
same  time,  refuse  the  support  furnished  by  the  judge's  pay ; 
return  to  your  normal  ways  of  life,  to  your  business  and  to 
your  pleasures.  This  would  make  Athens  more  prosperous  and 
a  more  agreeable  place  to  live  in." 

Thus  conceived,  the  comedy  of  the  Wasjjs  may  be  regarded 
as  the  concluding  part  of  a  sort  of  satirical  ■  tetralogy,  whose 
real  unity  now  becomes  clear.  In  426,  in  the  Babylonians, 
Aristophanes  had  pictured  the  demagogues  oppressing  the 
allied  cities,  and  making  Athens  disliked  elsewhere.  In  425, 
in  the  Acharnians,  he  did  not  directly  denounce  them,  but 
Pericles,  from  whom  they  took  their  lead,  as  the  real  insti- 
gator of  a  fruitless  war,  that  was  rending  Greece  and  ruining 
Athens,  but  that  was  making  them  rich;  in„_424,.Jli-the 
Knights,  he  attacked  the  very  foundation  of  their  power, 
namely  their  flattery,  which  had  become  a  principle  of  govern- 
ment; and  finally  in  422,  in  the  Wasps,  he  exposed  one  of 
their  most  effective  and,  at  the  same  time,  most  dangerous 
means  of  influence — their  specious  zeal  as  denunciators,  which 
tended  to  corrupt  the  Athenian  character,  because  it  trans- 
formed a  people,  naturally  kind-hearted,  humane  and  cheerful, 
into  a  body  of  suspicious,  selfish  and  ill-natured  judges. 

Thus,  the  same  spirit  animated  Aristophanes  from  beginning 

I 


no    THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE 

to  end ;  nowhere  did  he  appear  as  the  enemy  of  democracy. 
No  doubt,  he  had  had  friendly  relations  with  its  opponents, 
and  had  even  borrowed  some  of  their  ideas,  but  the  funda- 
mental tendency  of  his  political  views  differed  essentially 
from  theirs.  They  sought  to  destroy  the  democracy ;  he 
appears  merely  to  have  sought  to  forewarn  and,  if  possible,  to 
reform  it. 

IV 

In  the  very  year  in  which  Aristophanes  had  produced  his 
Wasps,  and  only  a  few  months  after  its  performance,  in  the 
summer  of  422,  Cleon  fell  under  the  walls  of  Amphipolis  in 
Thrace.^  His  death  assured  the  temporary  preponderance  of 
the  moderate  peace-party,  of  which  Nicias  was  then  the  leader; 
and  in  the  following  year  peace  between  Athens  and  Sparta 
was  finally  concluded,  after  ten  years  of  war. 

Aristophanes  wrote  and  produced  his  comedy  entitled  The 
Peace  during  the  days  just  preceding  the  treaty,  at  a  moment 
when  the  outcome  of  the  negotiations  was  no  longer  doubtful.^ 
Thucydides  portrays  with  his  usual  precision  the  feelings  that 
prevailed  in  Athens  during  the  negotiations :  "  At  that  time 
the  Athenians  desired  peace  (irpo?  rh^  eiptjvrjv  fioXXov  t>)v 
yvcofitjv  el-^ov),  for,  after  their  recent  defeat  at  Delium,  and 
again  at  Amphipolis,  they  no  longer  had  that  confidence  in 
themselves  which  had  previously  kept  them  from  accepting  all 
offers  of  compromise  so  long  as  present  success  made  them 
believe  in  their  decided  superiority.  Besides,  they  feared  lest 
their  allies,  encouraged  by  their  failures,  might  fall  away  from 
them  more  and  more,  and  they  regretted  not  having  made 
a  treaty  after  the  expedition  to  Pylus,  when  the  occasion  was 
favorable."  ^     This  analysis  is  manifestly  correct,  but  it  does 

1  Thucydides,  v.  10. 

'^Argument  No.  1  merely  gives  the  year.  The  allusions  to  political  events, 
contained  in  the  play,  establish  its  relation  to  them  in  point  of  time. 
Peace  was  declared  immediately  after  the  city  Dionysia,  for  it  is  from  this 
festival  that  Thucydides  dates  back  in  counting  the  ten  years  which  the  war 
lasted,  V.  20, 

^  Thucydides,  v.  14. 


THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE    111 

not  give  us  a  sufficient  idea  of  the  heartfelt  delight  with  which 
the  rural  population  of  Attica  beheld  the  return  of  happy  and 
tranquil  days.  And  this  is  just  what  Aristophanes  has 
pictured  with  marvelous  fidelity.  This  treaty  fulfilled  all  the 
poet's  hopes ;  nobody  had  wished  for  peace  more  ardently  and 
more  sincerely  than  he ;  nobody  could  have  welcomed  it  with 
sincerer  joy.  As  a  consequence  his  play  is  noticeable  for  its 
exalted  lyrical  character.  Through  it  there  resounds,  as  it 
were,  the  triumph  of  the  rural  democracy,  which  was  at  last 
getting  what  it  then  longed  for  above  all  else. 

The  plot  is  altogether  allegorical  and  does  not  amount  to 
much.  Trygaeus,  a  vine-dresser  and  owner  of  a  small  farm,  is 
exasperated  by  the  prolongation  of  the  war,  just  as  Dicaeopolis 
had  been  previously.  He  scales  Olympus  on  his  dung-beetle, 
and  there,  with  Hermes  as  his  accomplice,  and  with  the  help  of 
the  sturdy  peasants  who  constitute  the  chorus,  he  hoists  Peace 
out  of  a  cave  in  which  war  had  confined  her.  Thereupon,  when 
he  has  once  more  put  her  in  possession  of  her  authority,  he 
descends  to  earth,  bringing  with  him  his  amiable  companions, 
Opora,  the  goddess  of  fruits,  and  Theoria,  the  goddess  of 
festivals.  Once  back  in  his  deme  Athmonon,  he  marries 
Opora,  and  joyfully  celebrates  his  wedding  with  the  help  of 
the  chorus.  During  these  festivities  he  proudly  assumes  the 
role  of  the  liberator  of  the  demes  and  of  the  country  folk, 
whose  victory  over  the  politicians  he  celebrates.^ 

From  the  special  point  of  view  of  this  study,  our  chief 
interest  in  the  exuberant  joy  of  this  victory  centres  about  the 
retrospective  judgment  which  Aristophanes  passes  on  Cleon 
and  on  the  policy  of  the  demagogues. 

At  the  very  outset,  in  the  parabasis  (1.  749  et  seq.)  he 
proudly  recalls  the  fight  he  has  made  against  him,  brags  about 
its  audaciousness  and  magnificence,  and  represents  it  as  an 
innovation  which   transformed  comedy.     It  may  be  that   he 

1  Peace,  1.  919  :  woWCiv  yap  vfitv  fiftoj, 

Tpuyatos  'Ad/j-ovevs  iyob, 

/cat  Tov  yewpyiKbv  Xewv 
'Tirip^o\6v  re  TraiVas. 


112  THE  CLOUDS.  THE  WASPS.  THE  PEACE 

exaggerates  his  deserts,  but  not  to  such  an  extent  as  entirely 
to  pervert  the  truth  of  the  matter.  It  is  quite  certain  that 
others,  before  him,  had  made  a  fight  against  the  men  in  ques- 
tion, and  that  they  had  created  political  comedy,  but  the 
continuity  of  his  attacks,  their  variety  and  their  close  connection 
with  one  another,  and  the  significance  of  some  of  them,  had  in 
fact  lent  his  manner  of  fighting  something  unusual  and  novel. 
Cratinus,  Hermippus  and  Telecleides  may  have  hurled  some 
trenchant  shafts  at  Pericles  ;  it  does  not  appear,  however,  that 
they  attacked  the  very  principle  of  his  government.  But,  in 
his  fight  against  Cleon,  Aristophanes  had  exposed  some  of  the 
serious  vices  of  the  demagogy  of  his  day. 

Of  this  he  was  well  aware ;  and  this  is  why,  in  the  Peace,  he 
forcefully  reminds  us  of  some  of  the  lofty  moral  considerations 
that  had  made  him  hate  the  war.  He  had  considered  this  war 
as  anti-Hellenic,  as  having  been  begun  and  prolonged  for  the 
selfish  interests  of  a  few  men.  To  his  mind,  Cleon  was  the 
pestle  with  which  the  war  brayed  the  Greek  cities  in  its 
mortar.^  And  so  the  restoration  of  peace  becomes  a  veritable 
festival  of  Hellenic  brotherhood  and  deserves  to  be  celebrated 
in  hymns  of  joy.^  "See,"  exclaims  Hermes,  "how  the  reconciled 
cities  greet  one  another  and  how  they  laugh  for  joy ! "  ^ 

But  there  is  more  to  the  story.  The  war  had  altered  the 
character  of  Athens ;  when  it  took  the  rural  democracy  from 
the  farms,  it  gave  them  vicious  and  servile  habits.  The  same 
god  says :  "  When  the  laboring  folk  had  abandoned  their 
fields  and  flocked  into  town,  they  did  not  see  that  they  were 
being  sold  for  gain.  As  they  no  longer  had  olives  to  eat,  and 
as  they  were  fond  of  figs,  they  had  no  choice  but  to  turn  to 
the  orators,  who,  knowing  full  well  that  the  poor  devils  were 
powerless  as  long  as  they  had  nothing  to  eat,  kept  shouting 
and  driving  Peace   away,  who  nevertheless  showed  her  face 

^  Peace,  1.  269  :         d7r6XwX'  'Ad-rjvaloLS  aXerpl^avos 

6  ^vpaoTTiliX-qs,  6s  eKVKa  tt]v  'EXXdSa. 
"^  Tbid.  1.  291  :  ws  ijSo/j.aL  /cat  ripiro/xai  Kal  xo^^pofiat. 

vuv  etrrlv  7jfj.iv,  S)v5p€s"EW7]V€s,  KoXdv  ,   .   .   K.r.i. 
'^Ihid.  1.  538  :  Wl  vvv,  Hdpn, 

olov  Trpos  dXXTjXaj  XcCKovaiv  ol  TrdXeis 

oiaWayetcFat.  Kal  yeXwaiv  da/nepai. 


THE  CLOUDS.    THE  WASPS.    THE  PEACE    113 

again  and  again,  because  she  longed  for  this  land.  At  the 
same  time,  they  harassed  those  of  the  allies  who  were  fat  and 
rich,  first  accusing  one  of  them  and  then  another  of  sympathy 
with  Brasidas.  And  then  you  would  tear  the  unlucky  one  to 
pieces,  like  a  pack  of  hounds,  for  the  city  sat  pale  and  terrified, 
and  eagerly  devoured  all  calumnies  that  were  cast  to  her. 
Then,  when  the  aliens  saw  what  blows  the  accusers  could  deal, 
they  shut  their  mouths  by  stuffing  them  with  gold ;  and  thus 
the  accusers  grew  rich,  but  Greece  was  on  the  road  to  ruin 
without  your  knowing  it.  Now  the  man  to  blame  for  this 
was  a  tanner."  ^ 

What  the  god  says  with  trenchant  and  vigorous  eloquence 
is  confirmed  by  the  chorus  of  peasants,  who  explain  how  peace 
has  brought  them  back  to  their  former  habits.  "  I  shall  no 
longer  be  seen  to  be  an  irritable,  ill-natured  judge ;  I  shall  no 
longer  seem  severe  and  harsh,  as  I  did  formerly ;  but  you  will 
see  me  good-natured  and  tender-hearted,  because  I  am  free 
from  worry."  ^ 

Nothing  could  better  bring  out  the  true  nature  of  Aristo- 
phanes'  thought.      In   Cleon,   he  had   furiously  persecuted  a 
corruptor    of    Athenian    spirit,    and    he     believed,    somewhat ' 
ingenuously  perhaps,  that,  thanks  to  the  peace  and  to  Cleon's 
death,  it  would  be  restored  to  its  former  vigor. 

Aristophanes  seems  to  have  been  appeased  as  soon  as  he  was 
rid  of  his  enemy,  as  we  shall  see  in  the  chapters  which  follow. 
[And  so  we  may  say  that  his  hostility  to  Cleon  is  the 
characteristic  mark  of  one  period  of  his  life. 

During  this  period  he  appears  violent,  bitter,  and  even 
unjust,  if  one  may  speak  of  jvistice  with  respect  to  a  style  of 
composition  whose  very  nature  tends  to  distort  whatever  it 
deals  with.  Engaged  in  a  passionate  combat,  in  which  the 
most  serious  moral  and  political  ideas  were  at  stake,  he 
occasionally  sided  with  the  various  parties  of  the  opposition 
and  may  have  profited  by  their  encouragement ;  but  it  is  now 
clear,  from  the  foregoing  study  of  the  subject,  that  he  never 
entered  their  service,  and  that  he  was,  in  no  sense  of  the 
word,  a  party-man.     Two  sentiments  above  all  inspired  him, 

^  Peace,  11.  631-647.  ^Ibid.  1.  349. 


114  THE  CLOUDS.  THE  WASPS.  THE  PEACE 

both  of  which  had  to  do  with  his  antecedents  and  social  rank 
and  very  nature — a  Hellenic  sentiment  and  an  Athenian 
sentiment.  He  could  never  admit  either  that  the  Greeks 
should  engage  in  internecine  war  or  that  the  Athenian  people 
should  allow  their  kindly,  amiable,  and  sprightly  natures  to  be 
spoiled  by  selfish  demagogues.  His  opposition  was  not  always 
loyal,  but  at  bottom  it  remained  sincere  and  generous,  and  it 
was  far-seeing  as  well.  There  was  no  political  platform,  pro- 
perly speaking,  back  of  his  plays,  but  only  a  few  hasty  and 
incomplete  outlines ;  as  a  consequence,  we  cannot,  at  this  late 
day,  extract  a  precise  doctrine  from  them.  And  yet,  beneath 
their  levity  they  conceal  a  sort  of  general  philosophy,  which 
still  retains  its  value  and  even  its  application,^^ 


CHAPTEK   IV 

SECOND  PEEIOD 

THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

THE  BIRDS,  414.     LYSISTRATA  AND  THESMOPHORIAZUSAE,  411. 
THE  FROGS,  405. 


The  chronological  continuity  of  the  extant  plays  of  Aristo- 
phanes is  interrupted  after  the  Peace  (421);  it  begins  again 
with  the  Birds  (-414),  followed  by  the  Lysistrata  and  the 
Thesmoplioriazitsae  (411),  and  then,  after  an  interval  of  six 
years,  by  the  Frogs  (405).  Together,  these  four  plays  make  a 
second  group,  quite  different  from  the  first,  in  several  respects, 
but  particularly  when  regarded  from  the  special  point  of  view 
of  this  study. 

Indeed,  it  appears  that  between  421  and  415,  Aristophanes 
experienced  a  certain  change  of  mind  as  regards  politics. 
And  first,  it  must  be  observed  that  in  his  earlier  plays 
he  had  exhausted  the  chief  objects  of  satire  that  the 
Athenian  democracy  could  afford  him.     There  was  no  longer  \ 

reason  why  he  should  devote  his  attention  and  his  inventive       \  aV^^ 
genius  so  persistently  to  ideas  of  this  kind.     In  the  second  k^v^v 
place,  Cleon  had  fallen  in  422.     His  death  had  rid  the  poet  » 
of  a  formidable  enemy,  and  had  removed  from  the  scene  the 
man  in  whom  he  saw  concentrated  all  the  vices  and  malignant 
influences  which  menaced  the  city  at  that  time.     His  mind, 


116    THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

which  was  by  nature  elastic  and  quick  to  relax,  must  have 
been  somewhat  restored  to  serenity  thereby.  Indeed,  such  a 
disposition  manifests  itself  in  the  passage  he  substituted,  pro- 
bably in  the  year  418,  for  the  original  anapaests  of  which  the 
first  part  of  the  parabasis  of  the  Clouds  must  have  consisted, 
when  it  was  performed  in  42 3. ^  In  this  passage  he  declares 
that  he  did  not  wish  to  trample  upon  his  enemy's  corpse,  and 
blames  his  rivals,  Eupolis  and  Hermippus  among  others,  for 
the  bitterness  they  show  toward  Hyperbolus.^  As  a  contrast 
to  such  vulgar  violence,  he  offers  the  style  of  composition 
shown  in  his  Clouds,  a  play  for  which  he  seems  to  show  a 
deliberate  preference,  as  a  type  of  a  comedy  that  is  really 
worthy  of  a  thinking  public.^ 
jj.  I .  Moreover,  after  Cleon's  death,  the  turbulent  democracy  did 
not  again  meet  with  a  man  who  was  able  to  rule  them  so 
completely,  through  their  own  passions.  We  know  very  little 
of  the  domestic  history  of  Athens  between  421  and  414,  but 
so  much  at  least  is  clear,  that  no  one  was  able  to  lord  it  over 
the  assembly.  Her  foreign  policy  was,  at  one  time,  influenced 
by  the  advocates  of  peace,  and  at  another,  by  the  instigators 
of  war  and  adventure ;  it  oscillates  between  Nicias  and 
Alcibiades ;  neither  of  them  succeeds  in  giving  it  a  firm  and 
continuous  direction.  Men  of  lesser  ability,  like  Hyperbolas, 
Theramenes,  Demostratus,  Androcles,  to  name  only  a  few  of 
them,  attempt  to  play  an  important  part  and  flit  about 
the  rostrum.  Intrigue  is  everywhere  rampant,  and  in  this 
confusion  and  excitement,  the  oligarchy,  which  perceives  the 
weakness    of    the    predominant    party,   and    observes    its   in- 

^This  passage  (11.  518-562),  written  in  Eupolidean  measure,  clearly  reveals 
the  date  of  its  composition.  It  contains  an  allusion  (1.  553)  to  the  Maricas  of 
Eupolis,  performed  in  421,  and  another  to  a  play  by  Hermippus  which 
followed  it  (1.  557,  eW  aSdis),  and  finally  to  other  and  even  more  recent  plays 
(1.  558,  &\\oL  t'  Tjd-r)  Trdi/res).  The  passage  cannot,  therefore,  have  been  written 
before  418.  On  the  other  hand,  it  seems  to  antedate  the  exile  of  H}T)erbolus, 
of  which  it  makes  no  mention  ;  he  was  exiled  in  April,  417,  at  the  very  latest 
(Curtius,  Hist.  gr.  translated  into  English  by  Ward  (1872),  iii.  pp.  314-15,  and 
Busolt,  Oriech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1257,  note  1). 

2  Clouds,  11.  553-559. 

Ubid.  11.  560-562. 


THE   SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS    117 

coherent  conduct,  gradually  regains  confidence  and  matures  its 
plans. 

Indifferent  material  this  for  political  comedy,  which  de-, 
manded  something  distinct,  vigorous  and  consistent  as  the 
object  of  attack.  Ordinary  occurrences,  fluctuating  ideas,  a| 
capricious  and  dissembling  policy,  were  hardly  fit  subjects  toji 
be  represented  on  the  comic  stage.  Spent  on  such  subjects, 
dramatic  satire  must  needs  lose  its  genera,l  application  and  its 
philosophical  value,  and  become  more-^iersonal.  Indeed,  this 
is  just  what  we  get  a  hint  of  in  the  altogether  too  rare 
and  very  incomplete  records.  Eupolis  appears  to  have  been 
supreme  in  this  style.  His  Maricas  and  his  Flatterers,  which 
were  both  produced  in  421,^  no  doubt  supplied  particularly 
startling  examples  of  its  furious  and  ill-natured  violence.  In 
the  former  of  these  two  plays,  by  way  of  scourging  the 
demagogue  Hyperbolus,  he  brought  his  mother  upon  the  stage 
in  the  guise  of  a  repulsive,  drunken  old  woman,  who  danced 
the  KopSa^  (an  indecent  dance).  In  the  second  play  he  makes 
fun  of  the  private  hfe  of  Callias,  the  son  of  Hypponicus,  and 
takes  pleasure  in  exposing  him  to  the  insulting  derision  of  the 
people,  by  exhibiting  him  surrounded  by  parasites,  li\'ing  in 
debauchery,  and  rapidly  squandering  his  patrimony.  In  the 
following  year,  42 0,^  he  had  his  Autolysis  performed,  in  which 
he  attacked  one  of  the  distinguished  families  of  Athens,  and  at 
the  same  time  discredited  and  insulted  the  young  victor  of  the 
Panathenaea  of  422,  his  father  Lycon,  and  his  mother  Rhodia.^ 
And  finally,  his  Baptae  (Bd-Trraf),  which  was  probably  per- 
formed in  415,'*  seems  to  have  been  directed  against  the 
celebration  of  a  strange  cult  by  Alcibiades  and  his  friends. 

^  Argument  of  Aristophanes'  Peace  and  scholia  to  the  Clouds,  1.  552.  The 
words  varepov  rpirif)  h-ei  in  this  scholium  seem  to  me  to  be  correctly  interpreted 
by  Kock  (Fragm.  com.  gr.  i.  p.  307):  their  meaning  is  "two  years  later." 
Meineke  misunderstood  them,  and  Gilbert  followed  him  in  his  mistake 
[Beitrdge,  p.  212). 

-Athtnaeus,  v.  216  d. 

^Sehol.  to  Aristophanes'  Lysistrata,  1.  270.  Cf.  Pauly-Wissowa,  "Auto- 
lykos,"  4,  art.  by  Judeich,  who  regards  the  name  Rhodia  as  indicating  her 
birthplace.     This  does  not  agree  with  the  scholium. 

■*  Meineke,  Hist.  crit.  com.  p.  125. 


118    THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

These  few  examples  are  conclusive.^  It  was  really  the  spirit 
of  Archilochus  that  animated  Athenian  comedy  at  this  time, 
at  least  in  the  case  of  those  poets  who  preferred  not  to 
devote  themselves  to  mythological  parody  or  to  extravaganza 
pure  and  simple.  Political  comedy,  properly  speaking,  such  as 
had  been  known  during  the  war  against  Archidamus,  which 
mingled  philosophy  with  satire,  and  aimed  at  giving  the  people 
general  instruction,  was  changed  under  the  influence  of  circum- 
stances ;  but  the  change  was  not  for  the  better. 

Aristophanes  seems  not  to  have  shared  in  this  tendency. 
To  tell  the  truth,  we  do  not  know  what  plays  he  produced 
between  421  and  414,  but  we  have  no  warrant  for  the  belief 
that  he  wrapt  himself  in  silence  after  the  period  of  active 
production  which  had  gone  before.  On  the  other  hand,  how- 
ever, had  he  written  an  important  work  of  political  satire 
during  this  time,  it  is  rather  unlikely  that  it  would  have  been 
entirely  forgotten.  We  must  rather  assume  that  the  plays  he 
jWrote  during  these  few  years  touched  only  incidentally  on 
[topics  of  the  day,  and  that,  as  a  rule,  they  partook  of  the 
character  of  literary  criticism,  or  of  mythological  parody,  or 
else  of  pure  extravaganzaj    This  is  the  way  the  Birds  begins. 

Shortly  before  the  time  this  play  was  performed,  a^law  had 
been  enacted — if  we  may  trust  ancient  authorities — which 
limited  the  license  of  comedy.  Its  author  was  a  certain 
Syracosius,  an  obscure  politician,  who,  by  the  way,  is  known 
only  through  the  derisive  allusions  of  his  contemporaries. 
The  most  interesting  of  these  allusions  is  found  in  a  fragment 
of  the  Hermit  by  Phrynichus,  performed  in  414.  In  it  the 
poet  expressed  the  wish  that  Syracosius  might  get  the 
mange.     "  For,"  said  he,  "  he  has  deprived  me  of  the  liberty  of 

'  We  may  probably  add  also  the  Hyperholus  by  Plato,  one  of  the  plays  to 
which  Aristophanes  apparently  makes  allusion  in  the  parabasis  added  to  the 
Clouds  in  418.  Cf.  Schol.  Thesmoph.  1.  808  and  see  Kock,  Fr.  com.  gr.  i. 
p.  643.  The  Demes  by  Eupolis  was  apparently  of  the  same  character  ;  the  play 
was  directed  against  the  recently  elected  generals.  Gilbert,  Beitrdge,  p.  222 
et  seq.,  assumes  that  it  dealt  with  Alcibiades,  and  dates  this  satire  in  the  year 
419.  The  fragments,  however,  do  not  afford  any  solid  ground  for  this  con- 
jecture. Therefore,  the  general  import  of  the  play  remains  uncertain,  and 
this  is  why  I  do  not  include  it  in  the  above  enumeration. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS    119 

putting  those  into  my  comedy  whom  I  wished  to  "  (acpeiXeTo 
yap  KioiuteSetv  01/9  eiredvixovv).  The  scholiast  of  Aristophanes 
who  quotes  this  fragment  adds :  "  It  seems  that  Syracosius 
passed  a  decree  which  forbade  the  introduction  of  any  person 
by  name  in  comedy."^  We  see  that  this  statement  is  based 
on  a  conjecture,  which  appears  to  have  the  lines  of  Phrynichus 
as  its  only  foundation.  They  evidently  allude  to  an  actual 
occurrence,  but  we  do  not  know  what  this  occurrence  was.  It 
would  be  necessary  to  know  who  were  the  men  whom  Phryni- 
chus wished  to  deride,  before  we  could  attempt  to  discover 
how  Syracosius  could  have  thwarted  his  desire  and  deprived 
him  of  the  means  of  doing  this.  In  any  event,  the 
alleged  decree  is  very  improbable  in  itself.  Comedies  per- 
formed about  the  year  414  abound  in  proper  names  and 
satirical  allusions  to  contemporaries ;  the  few  extant  fragments 
of  Phrynichus'  Hermit  are  full  of  them  (fr.  20,  21,  22). 
The  text  of  the  alleged  decree,  in  the  form  in  which  it  is 
given  by  the  scholiast,  is  therefore  certainly  incorrect ;  more- 
over, it  is  only  a  reproduction  of  the  decree  of  440.  What, 
then,  is  left  of  his  testimony  ?  Nothing,  or  very  little  ;  and 
it  will  no  doubt  be  best,  for  a  proper  appreciation  of  Aristo- 
phanes' tendencies  at  this  period,  to  disregard  it  entirely.- 


II 

No  play  has  given  rise  to  more  differences  of  opinion  than 
the  Birds,  not,  however,  in  regard  to  its  poetic  value,  for  by 

^  Scholia  to  the  Birds,  1.  1297  :  ^oKel  5k  (!Si'pa/c6(Ttoj)  /cat  \l/-q(pi(Tna.  reOeLKivai  /jlt] 
Kcj/Jiijideiadai  dvofJUcrTi  Tiva. 

-The  absurd  testimony  of  the  scholiast  on  Aclius,  Aristides  (ed.  Dindorf, 
iii.  p.  444),  who  knows  nothing  of  Syracosius,  and  attributes  a  law  of  this 
kind  to  Cleon,  surely  in  no  way  confirms  the  trustworthiness  of  the  testimony 
we  have  already  refused  to  accept.  Nevertheless,  modern  scholars,  as  a  rule, 
admit  the  authenticity  of  Syracosius'  decree  :  Curtius  (Hist.  gr.  translated  by 
Ward,  iii.  p.  365  ff.)  attributes  this  decree  to  the  influence  of  the  oligarchs; 
Ed.  Meyer  [Gesch.  d.  Alterth.  iv.  p.  52.3)  regards  it  as  the  work  of  the  radical 
party,  and  this  view  is  shared  by  Busolt  {iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1349).  So  many 
risky  hypotheses,  based  on  a  conjecture  of  a  perplexed  grammarian  ! 


120    THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

common  consent,  it  is  recognized  as  one  of  the  most  charming 
creations  of  Aristophanes'  genius.  Eegarding  the  author's 
intentions,  however,  there  is  controversy  among  the  critics, 
and  this  controversy,  begun  in  antiquity,  does  not  yet  seem 
near  settlement.  Without  entering  here  upon  a  detailed 
statement,  which  would  be  endless  and  tedious,  we  may 
simply  say  that  these  divergent  opinions  can  be  reduced  to 
three,  which,  however,  in  turn  admit  of  many  shades  of /^ 
meaning.^  Some  of  the  critics  regard  the  play  as  a  purev[J 
extravaganza,  containing  only  occasional  derisive  allusions  to 
men  and  events  of  the  day,  but  without  general  import. 
Others,  on  the  contrary,  descry  in  it  a  political  and  moral 
allegory,  cleverly  constructed  on  a  very  deliberate  satirical  plan, 
which,  in  turn,  they  interpret  in  various  ways.  And  finally, 
others  try  to  hold  a  middle  course  between  these  two  opposite^ 
views.  It  is  not  possible  to  deal  with  this  play  without 
taking  sides  in  the  controversy.  But,  after  all  that  has  been 
said  about  it,  this  may  be  done  briefly,  if  we  confine  our 
observations  to  its  really  important  aspects. 

First  of  all  we  must  eliminate  an  a  priori  idea  which  is 
of  a  sort  to  mislead  us. 

Some  critics  have  either  laid  down  the  principle  or  have 
tacitly  assumed  that  every  comedy  of  Aristophanes  must  have 
a  satirical  thought  as  its  foundation.^  This  amounts  to  remov- 
ing the  difficulty  by  solving  it  in  advance.  In  fact,  what  we 
know  about  ancient  comedy  gives  us  no  warrant  whatever  for 
so  absolute  a  statement.  On  the  contrary,  it  seems  incontest- 
able that  in  the  second  half  of  the  fifth  century  a  number  of 
comedies  were  produced  at  Athens  which  were  purely  imagina- 
|tive,  intended  merely  to  amuse  the  public ;  and  we  have  no 

^  A  short  review  of  this  discussion  up  to  the  year  1874  may  be  found  in 
an  article  by  Bursian,  "  Uher  die  Tendenz  der  Vogel  des  Aristoj^hanes," 
Sitzungsberichte  der  Miincher  Akad.,  Histor.  phil.  Klasse,  1875,  p.  375.  His 
account  must  be  supplemented  by  citing  the  Histories  of  Greek  Literature, 
chiefly  those  of  Bernhardy,  Sittl,  Bergk,  Christ,  the  work  of  J.  Denis,  La 
ComMie  grecque,  the  Greek  Histories  of  Curtius  and  Busolt,  the  Beilrdge  of 
Gilbert,  the  Geschichfe  des  Alterthums  by  Ed.  Meyer.  I  have  myself  touched 
on  this  subject  in  I'Histoire  de  la  littdrature  grecque,  2nd  ed.  1898,  iii.  p.  546. 

-  J.  Denis,  La  comMie  grecque,  i.  p.  437. 


THE   SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS    121 

proof  that  Aristophanes'  plays  were  an  exception  in  this  respect. 
This  self-styled  principle  is  therefore  worthless  in  itself,  and 
it  is  only  by  a  study  of  the  play  that  we  can  get  light  on 
its  meaning. 

First  we  must  consider  the  opening  action.  Two  Athenians, 
Peithetaerus  and  Euelpides,  leave  Athens  and  have  no  desire 
to  return ;  they  declare  they  cannot  live  there  longer.  Never- 
theless, they  admit  that  the  city  is  glorious  and  prosperous.^ 
What  fault  have  they  to  find  with  it,  then  ?  Only  one — 
there  are  too  many  lawsuits  there.  One  of  them  says : 
'"  The  cicadae  sit  chirping  on  the  boughs  only  a  month  or  two  ; 
but  the  Athenians  chirp  over  their  lawsuits  all  their  lives 
long.     That  is  why  we  are  leaving,"  ^ 

When  we  remember  that  this  must  have  been  written 
toward  the  close  of  the  year  415,  it  is  hard  to  avoid  comparing 
this  statement  with  Thucydides'  testimony  about  the  state  of 
mind  of  the  Athenians  at  that  time.  It  was  in  the  summer 
of  415  that  the  affairs  of  the  Hermae  and  of  the  Mysteries 
successively  startled  the  city.  The  suspicious  spirit  of  the 
Athenian  democracy  had  been  aroused  by  these  events.  The 
historian  says  :  "  The  people  saw  in  them  an  organized  plot  to 
overthrow  the  state  and  to  abolish  the  democracy."  ^  "  Far 
from  being  allayed  by  the  people's  absorption  in  the  prepara- 
tions for  the  Sicilian  War,  these  misgivings  only  grew  for 
several  months  after  the  departure  of  the  fleat,  which  took 
place  in  midsummer."  ^  Thucydides  goes  on  :  C  Ii^  their  uni- 
versal distrust  they  accepted  all  evidence  indiscriminately  and 
arrested  and  imprisoned  men  of  the  highest  respectability 
on  the  faith  of  irresponsible  people."  ^j  And  again :  "  The 
exasperation  of  the  masses  and  the  number  of  arrests 
increased  day  by  day."  '^  "  It  is  true  that  one  of  the 
prisoners  finally  declared  himself  guilty  and  made  revela- 
tions, true  or  false,  about  the  aff'air  of  the  Hermae,  and  this 
somewhat  calmed  the  anxiety  of  the  people  on   that  score. 

^  Birds  1.  36  :  avrrju  /xiv  ov  nicrovvr'  €K€Lv7]v  Tr]v  iroXiv, 

rb  /JLT)  ov  fj.iya.\y)v  ilvai  tpiiffei  Kevoaljxova. 

=^/?mZ.  11.  39-42.  » Thucydides,  vi.  27.  *  Rid.  vi.  30. 

'^Ibid.  vi.  53.  ^  Ihid.  vi.  60. 


122   THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

But  the  affair  of  the  Mysteries  remained  unexplained  for  some 
time  longer  and  kept  excitement  alive.  The  people  clung  to 
the  conviction  that  this  was  likewise  the  result  of  a  plot 
against  the  democracy,  hatched  with  the  connivance  of  the 
enemies  of  the  country.  At  one  time,  the  citizens  spent 
the  night  in  arms  in  the  temple  of  Theseus,  evidently  pre- 
pared for  a  surprise  by  the  oligarchs ;  and  at  the  same  time 
the  Athenians  handed  over  some  oligarchs  of  Argos,  whom 
they  had  held  as  hostages,  to  the  Argive  democrats  to  be 
slain."  ^  We  may  be  sure  that,  after  this,  the  political  trials 
must  have  been  continued  during  all  the  last  part  of  the  year 
415,  and  perhaps  even  beyond  that  date — that  is,  during  just 
the  time  when  Aristophanes  was  writing  his  play.  If  this  is 
true,  the  allusion  appears  incontestable.^  The  word  SIkui  in 
the  lines  quoted  is  not  contrasted  with  ypacpai;  it  is  not  the 
special  designation  of  private  suits.  It  applies,  indirectly  at 
least,  to  all  legal  proceedings  then  under  way,  even  to  those 
which  did  not  come  to  trial.  Aristophanes  may  have  seen 
several  of  his  friends  denounced,  imprisoned  and  examined. 
[It  was  this  prevalence  of  suspicion,  denunciation,  investigation 
and  arbitrary  severity,  that  gave  him  the  idea  of  the  fantastic 
departure  of  these  two  Athenians.  In  the  same  year  and  at 
the  same  competition,  another  comic  poet,  Phrynichus,  pro- 
duced his  Hermit  (Moi/ot^otto?),  whose  title  clearly  enough 
reveals  his  intention.  The  hermit,  too,  must  have  fled  from 
Athens  for  similar  reasons.  In  the  circles  in  which  the  two 
poets  moved,  people  no  doubt  thought  that  Athens  was  no 
j  longer  fit  to  live  in.  This  is  what  each  of  them  conveyed  in 
/  two  different  Hctions  that  were  inspired  by  the  same  thought. 
And  so  politics  do  figure  at  the  beginning  of  the  plot. 
But  this  does  not  mean  that  the  entire  plot  is  a  logical 
and  continuous  development  of  the  idea  indicated  at  the 
beginning.  Have  we  not  seen  that  in  the  Kniglits  the 
opening  incident  of  the  play  is  borrowed  from  the  expedition 
to  Sphacteria  and  that  nevertheless  this  expedition  plays  no 

^  Tliucydides,  vi.  61. 

"^  Birds,  11.  40-41        .   .   .   'Adijva'ioi  5'  del 

(irl  Twv  Si,KU)v  adovjt.  iravTa  tqv  ^iov. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS    123 

r 

part  in  the  development  of  the  plot  ?  A  comedy  of  Aristo- 
phanes should  not  be  treated  like  a  deductive  argument  nor 
like  a  mathematical  demonstratioiij 

What  are  our  two  self -constituted  exiles  after  ?  A  place 
where  one  may  live  in  peace  (tottov  airpayiuova,  1.  44).  They 
mean  to  ask  an  ancient  King  of  Thrace,  Tereus,  who,  as  we 
know,  was  changed  into  a  hoopoe,  to  be  good  enough  to  point 
it  out  to  them.  As  a  bird,  he  has  had  opportunity  to  see 
many  countries,  and  as  a  man,  he  is  in  a  position  to  have  an 
opinion.  And  now  they  stand  before  him.  Tereus  asks  them: 
"  '  From  what  country  do  you  come  ? '  '  From  the  land  of  the 
brave  triremes.'  '  So  you  are  heliasts  ? '  '  Nay,  quite  the  con- 
trary ;  we  are  anti-heliasts '  {onrriXiaa-Td).  '  Grows  that  seedling 
there?'  'Aye,  you  could  find  a  bit  in  the  country.'"^  The  idea 
which  we  just  hinted  at  here  appears  in  a  somewhat  more  precise 
form.  The  two  friends  have  rustic  minds.  The  seedling  of  law- 
suits is  grown  only  in  the  city.     That  is  why  they  hate  the  city. 

But  how  do  they  describe  the  ideal  city  for  which  they  are 
searching  ?  If  the  poet  has  a  serious  project  of  a  really  political 
nature  to  propose,  this  is  clearly  the  place  where  it  ought  to 
appear.  But  note  their  first  declaration :  at  no  price  will  they 
accept  an  aristocratic  state  (11.  125-126).  Is  this  mere  empty 
talk,  meant  to  reassure  the  audience  ?  We  should  be  justified 
in  so  interpreting  it  only  in  case  other  ideas  were  suggested 
in  what  follows.  This  is  not  the  case.  The  life  for  which 
Peithetaerus  yearns,  is  a  life  of  comfort,  of  pleasure,  of  easy 
intercourse — a  rather  vulgar  ideal,  if  you  choose,  but  by  no 
means  a  revolutionary  one  (11.  127-142).  He  is  anxious,  it  is 
true,  that  his  new  home  should  not  be  on  the  sea-shore,  for 
fear  that  some  fine  day  the  trireme,  called  "  The  Salaminia," 
may  heave  in  sight  with  a  process-server  on  board  (1.  147). 
Granting  that  this  allusion  to  the  recall  of  Alcibiades  implies 
a  blame  or  a  regret,  it  is  at  best  nothing  more  than  a  word 
casually  spoken  which  has  no  influence  on  the  plot. 

The  decisive  moment  in  the  plot  is  Peithetaerus'  proposal 
and  the  series  of  speeches  by  which  he  leads  the  birds  to 
accept  it.     In  other  words,   it  is  the  construction  of  Cloud- 

^  Birds,  11.  108-111. 


124   THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

cuckootown.  Those  who  have  imputed  revohitionary  intentions 
to  the  poet,  Hke  Koechly,  for  example,^  have  been  struck  by 
this  conceit,  which  seemed  to  them  to  be  significant.  Was 
not  the  imaginary  building  of  a  new  city  tantamount  to  a 
plain  declaration  that  the  existing  city  ought  to  be  abolished 
and  reorganized  from  foundation  to  turret  ?  This  would,  in 
fact,  be  probable,  if  Cloudcuckootown  had  a  constitution ;  but 
however  closely  we  examine  and  dissect  Aristophanes'  extrava- 
ganza, we  cannot  find  anything  of  the  sort  in  it.  Cloudcuckoo- 
town has  no  constitution.  Not  a  word  about  the  future 
organization  of  offices,  of  elections,  of  balloting  for  magistrates, 
of  pay  for  the  judges,  or  of  the  restriction  of  civic  rights — in 
a  word,  of  all  the  questions  about  which  the  Athenian  parties 
differed  at  that  time.  Not  one  of  these  flighty  fellows  manifests 
the  slightest  personal  ambition,  nor  the  slightest  leaning 
toward  oligarchy.  Even  if  we  wished,  by  hook  or  crook,  to 
give  these  fancies  the  names  of  real  things,  the  winged  people 
would  look  to  us  like  a  democracy — one  would  almost  be 
tempted  to  say  like  a  giddy-brained  democracy."  And  their 
leader,  Peithetaerus,  has  no  other  means  of  action  than  his 
speeches,  just  like  the  ordinary  Athenian  demagogues.  He  is 
the  people's  leader,  7rpo(TTUTi](;  rod  Si'ijixou,  not  at  all  an  aggressive 
reformer,  nor  a  man  who  aspires  to  tyranny. 

When  once  the  city  is  built,  it  is  true  that  he  excludes 
quite  a  number  of  people  of  the  sort  that  swarmed  at  Athens : 
a  lyric  poet,  a  dealer  in  oracles,  a  scheming  geometrician,  also 
an  inspector  with  a  vague  mission,  and  a  manufacturer  of 
decrees.  Only  the  last  two  have  a  semblance  of  political 
character.  Somewhat  further  along  there  comes  a  second 
lot :  a  prodigal  and  needy  son  who  thinks  of  strangling  his 
father,  the  poet  Cinesias,  and  finally  a  sycophant.  If  this  is 
to  serve  as  an  indication  of  the  reforms  contemplated  by 
Aristophanes,  they  would  have  consisted  in  ousting  the  bores 
and  the  rascals,  among  whom  he  counted  only  three  special 

^  Uber  die  Vogel  des  Aristophanes,  Zurich,  1857. 

^In  line  1581  we  learn  that,  among  the  birds,  those  who  are  suspected  of 
evil  designs  against  the  democracy  are  roasted  on  a  fork.  What  more  need 
we  ask  ? 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     125 

products  of  the  Athenian  democracy :  the  inspector,  whose 
particular  business  it  was  to  fleece  those  whom  he  inspected, 
the  manufacturer  of  decrees,  a  discreet  ally  of  perplexed 
politicians,  and  finally  the  sycophant  who  makes  a  living  out 
of  denunciations.  Projects  of  reform  such  as  these  may  have 
appeared  chimerical,  but  they  were  not  of  a  kind  to  disturb 
any  political  party. 

Need  we  attach  any  greater  importance  to  the  marriage  of 
Peithetaerus  and  Eoyalty  with  which  the  play  ends  ?  And 
need  we,  by  chance,  be  tempted  to  assume  that  Aristophanes 
employed  this  fiction  in  order  to  suggest  to  the  Athenians  the 
idea  of  the  advantages  of  a  monarchy  ?  Had  this  been  the 
case,  he  would  have  been  the  whole  monarchical  party  in 
Athens,  for  we  do  not  elsewhere  find  any  trace  of  such  a 
party  in  the  history  of  the  time.  This  absurdity  should 
suffice  to  doom  all  such  assumptions,  even  if  the  play  did  not 
give  a  sufficiently  clear  indication  of  the  poet's  real  thought. 
The  Eoyalty  whom  Peithetaerus  marries  is  naught  else  than  the 
Government  of  the  universe.  She  is  the  daughter  of  Zeus, 
and  when  Zeus  transfers  his  sceptre  to  the  birds,  who  have 
become  the  masters  of  the  world,  he  takes  their  representative 
as  his  son-in-law,  in  order  to  sanction  that  transfer.^  Thus, 
this  marriage   is  a  part   of  the   entirely   fantastic   fiction  of 

'  In  1.   1534  fF.  Prometheus  says  to  Peithetaerus  : 

vfiets  5i  ixr)  cTrivSecrO',  4av  firj  napadiScS 
TO  aKriirrpov  6  Zei)s  ro'icriv  6pvicnv  jraXiv 
Kal  T7]u  BaaiXeidv  aoL  yvvaiK^  ^X^"*  StS^J. 

It  is  clear  that  here  the  sceptre  and  Royalty  are  two  equivalent  symbols. 
What  may  have  misled  some  readers  is  the  definition  that  Prometheus 
subseqiiently  gives  of  Royalty.  "Who  is  she?"  asks  Peithetaerus.  Pro- 
metheus replies,  "  A  very  beautiful  j'oung  girl,  vi^ho  manufactures  Zeus' 
thunder,  and  everything  else  as  well — good  advice,  good  laws,  wisdom, 
arsenals,  insults,  the  paymaster  of  the  dicasts  (KuXaKpiTrtv),  the  three  obols." 
"So  she  is  his  steward  of  everything,"  saj'S  Peithetaerus.  "That  is  just 
what  I  meant  to  say."  Here  the  poet's  rather  subtle  thought  seems  to  be 
to  define  the  absolute  power  of  Zeus  by  amusing  examples  that  would  readily 
be  understood  by  the  people.  And  that  is  why,  after  having  given  Royalty 
abstract  and  philosophical  attributes,  he  unexpectedly,  in  line  1539,  represents 
her  as  disposing  at  will  of  everything  which  at  Athens  depended  on  the 
popular  leaders. 

K 


126     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

the  claims  the  birds  made  against  the  gods  ;  it  has  no  other 
meaning. 

The  foregoing  observations  show  that  Aristophanes'  play 
certainly  did  not  have  an  important  reform  of  the  Athenian 
Q  constitution  as  its  object,  and  that  it  does  not  even  make  pre- 
tence of  suggesting  one.  Does  it  not,  however,  contain  some 
satirical  elements  of  a  general  character  ?  This  question 
remains  to  be  studied. 

Ill 

A  great  many  critics  have  found  in  this  comedy  a  more  or 
less  direct  allusion  to  the  Sicilian  expedition,  and  to  the  state 
of  mind  which  had  brought  it  to  pass.^  To  their  minds,  tlie 
bird  folk  represent  the  Athenian  people ;  they  possess  their 
Mightiness,  their  proneness  to  over-excite  themselves,  their 
credulous  enthusiasm,  and  they  make  and  carry  out  huge 
projects.  Only,  some  of  these  critics  think  that  this  picture 
is  satirical,  while  others  believe  that,  in  making  it,  the  poet 
shared  in  the  aspirations  of  his  fellow-citizens. 

This  very  diversity  of  opinion  shows  how  greatly  we  must 
distrust  these  summary  and  sweeping  interpretations.  The 
fact  is  that,  if  Aristophanes  did  wish  to  make  fun  of  the 
ambitions  of  Athens,  he  fails  to  make  his  intention  clear,  for 
the  birds  of  his  comedy  have  complete  success  in  their  under- 
taking. And  it  cannot  be  said  that  it  is  their  success  alone 
that  is  fantastic,  for  there  is  just  as  much  that  is  fantastic  in 
the  original  notion  of  their  project  as  in  the  development  that 
ensues.  Moreover,  is  the  intention  which  is  imputed  to  him 
probable  ?  In  truth,  we  know  absolutely  nothing  of  what 
Aristophanes  may  have  thought  about  the  Sicilian  expedition. 
But  if  we  assume  that  he  regarded  it  as  an  acfiDf  folly — and 
this  assumption  is  by  no  means  unreasonable — would  he  have 

1  Bemhardy,  Griech.  Litterat.  2nd  part,  ii.  p.  657  ;  Denis,  Com.  grecqne, 
p.  457  :  "And  so  with  airy  grace  and  charm  he  makes  fun  of  the  loft}"  hopes 
and  unbounded  ambitions  of  Athens,  that  are  out  of  all  proportion  to  her 
actual  strength."  On  the  other  hand,  K.  Kock  ("Die  Vogel  des  Aristophanes," 
Jahrh.f.  Klass.  PhiloL,  1865,  1st  supplementary  volume,  pp.  373-402),  regards 
the  poet  as  a  convert  to  a  warlike  and  adventurous  policy. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     127 

employed  such  means  to  criticise  it  ?     The  great  imprudence 

of  the  Athenians — and  this  might  be  called  the  characteristic 

feature  of  their  policy  in  415 — lay  in  forgetting  the  enemies 

at  their   gates  when    they  went  abroad  in  searcIPof^others.^ 

Now,    the    birds    do    nothing    of    that    sort.      Quite    on     the 

contrary,   if    one    enters    into    the    spirit   of   the   play,  their 

undertaking  is  very  well  conceived  and  perfectly  adapted  to 

its    ends.     But    let    us    go    still    further.     How    could    the 

Athenian  people  recognize  themselves,  in  the  spring  of  414,  in 

these  merry  and  light-hearted  people,  in  whom  these  critics  dis- 1 

cover  their  image  ?     Surely  the  Sicilian  expedition  had  aroused  1 

and  still  aroused  great  hopes.     Thucydides  expressly  declares  • 

that  such  was  the  case."     But  the  year  415  had  been  a  dreary 

and  anxious  one.     The  first  engagements,  in  the  autumn  and 

during  the  winter,  without  being  disastrous,  had  revealed  some 

serious   difficulties.     Alcibiades   was    at    Sparta,   and    in    the 

spring  of  414  the  Lacedaemonians  were  preparing  to  go  to 

the   rescue    of    Syracuse   and   to   renew  the  war.     This  was 

known   at  Athens,  as  Nicias'  reports  disguised  nothing,^  and 

though  courage  remained  undiminished,  idje   fa,ncies  must  at 

least  have   given  way   to   deliberate   resolve.     Therefore   the*^    A   O 

satire  imputed  to  Aristophanes  would  have  been  a  year  behind    \   P 

time.    Up-to-date  comedies  are  not  composed  of  antiquated  jokes.  -^ 

There  remain  the  roles  of  Peithetaerus  and  Euelpides.  Is 
there  a  political,  or  even  a  moral  purpose  in  this  association 
of  "  Persuasive  "  and  "  Confiding  "  ?  Critics  have  generally 
thought  so,  but  here  again  they  differ  when  they  seek  to  make 
the  interpretation  more  precise. 

In  the  eyes  of  some,'Peithetaeru3  is  the  concocter  of  scheme's^ 
boastful   and   daring,  who  at   that  time  held  sway  over  the  \ 
oligarchical  hetaeries — the  organizer  of  plots  and  of  revolution.  I 
Euelpides  stands  for  those  who  approved  of  him,  admired,  and  J 
followed    him.     Like    some    who    belonged    to    these    circle&r 
Peithetaerus   is  audacious    even    toward   the   gods,  whom   he 
finally  sets  aside  by  making  the  birds  their  successors.*     In 

1  Thucydides,  vi.  10.  "^Ibid.  vi.  24.  ^Ibid.  vii.  8. 

'•Biirsian,  "  tjber  die  Tendenz  der  Vogel  des  Aristophanes,"  Sitzungsberichte 
der  Miinchntr  Akad.,  Histor.  philos.  Klaase,  1875,  p.  375. 


&■ 


Govi 


128     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

the  eyes  of  others,  the  same  character  represents  both  the 
I  exiled  Alcibiades  and  Gorgias.  Just  as  Alcibiades  was  then 
advising  the  Spartans  to  occupy  and  fortify  Deceleia  against 
the  Athenians,  so  Peithetaerus  advises  the  birds  to  build 
Cloudcuckootown  as  a  protection  against  the  gods.  Or  again, 
his  promises  are  thought  to  recall  those  which  Alcibiades  made 
to  the  Athenians  in  order  to  urge  them  on  to  Sicily.^  As  for 
Gorgias,  a  reminder  of  his  eloquence  is  thought  to  be  found 
in  the  adroit  and  subtle  loquacity  of  this  fine  talker,  and, 
in  support  of  this  conjecture,  the  quite  episodical  ode  is 
cited  that  speaks  of  the  pernicious  "  tongue  bellying "  race 
(eyyXcoTToyacTTopcov),  a  barbarian  people,  who  are  also 
known,  the  poet  tells  us,  as  the  Gorgiases  and  the  Philips?' 
All  these  hypotheses  are  based  on  the  idea  that  Peithetaerus 
Dossesses  a  peculiar  gift  of  persuasion.  Is  this  idea  correct  ? 
I  fn  fact,  a  great  many  of  Aristophanes'  characters  are  strikingly 
like  him  in  this  respect.  Dicaeopolis,  Agoracritus,  Bdelycleon, 
Trygaeus,  Lysistrata,  Praxagora,  all  have  the  same  enterprising 
disposition,  the  same  direct  and  decided  will-power,  and 
practically  the  same  fertile  subtlety  in  argument,  the  same 
executive  talent.  The  differences  arise  from  the  plot,  and 
are  insignificant  in  comparison  with  the  traits  possessed  in 
common,  beneath  which  we  seem  to  discover  the  poet's  own 
personality.  As  for  the  play  which  we  are  now  studying,  it  is 
hard  to  see  how  this  character  could  have  been  other  than  it 
is,  the  nature  of  the  comedy  being  once  admitted. 
"  ~  As  for  an  irreligious  spirit,  if  indeed  there  is  any  such  in 
this  comedy,  it  is  not  to  be  found  specially  in  the  role  of 
Peithetaerus,  but  rather  in  the  plot  itself,  and  in  the  way  in 
which  the  gods  are  represented.  The  plot  is  based  on  the 
idea  that  the  alleged  power  of  the  gods  is  at  the  mercy  of  a 
bold  rebellion ;  the  gods  themselves  are  travestied  as  ridiculous 
persons.  Slaves  to  their  wants,  they  cannot  get  on  without 
men,  nor  without  women,  and  for  their  negotiations  with  the 
rebels,  they  choose  as  their  ambassadors,  first,  a  stupid  barbarian, 

^Siivern,  "Uber  Aristoph.  Vogel,"  Abhandlung  der  Berliner  Akad.,  1827, 
Hieior.  philos.  Klasse,  pp.  1-109 ;  Blaydes,  Aves,  ed.  major,  1882,  p.  xiii. 
■^  Birds,  1694-1705. 


THE   SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     129 

who  does  not  understand  anything  and  cannot  make  himself 
understood,  next,  Heracles,  a  sort  of  heavy  and  greedy  athlete, 
and  finally,  Poseidon,  who  is  obliged  to  follow  them,  although 
he  is  their  leader.  All  this  appears  very  irreverent  to  us. 
But  is  it  really  a  satire  on  the  audaciousness  of  contemporary 
thought  ?  In  order  to  decide  this  question,  let  us  compare 
Aristophanes'  own  utterances  with  one  another. 

In  the  Clouds  we  see  him  pointing  out  to  his  audience  the 
bold  impiety  of  the  philosophers  of  the  day  and  the  conse- 
quences wliich  he  foresees  from  it.  Here  there  can  be  no 
doubt  about  his  purpose,  which  is  manifestly  satirical.  The 
theories  he  imputes  to  Socrates  are  really  those  of  a  few  con- 
temporary philosophers,  more  or  less  altered,  mixed  up  and 
caricatured,  but  recognizable  as  a  whole.  As  for  their  con- 
sequences, they  are  as  plain  as  day,  in  the  acts  of  Pheidippides 
as  well  as  in  the  pleadings  of  the  "  Unjust,"  and  they  are 
formally  imputed  to  Socrates.  In  the  Birds  there  is  nothing 
of  this  kind — no  theory  and  no  philosophical  theology.  The 
cosmogony  of  the  parabasis  is  nothing  but  an  amusing  conceit 
in  which  are  mingled  reminiscences  of  Orphism,  but  which  , 
cannot  be  regarded  as  a  satire  on  any  system.  It  is  mythology 
itself  that  affords  the  poet  matter  for  joking,  and  not  the 
theories  of  those  who  were  regarded  as  atheists  at  the  tune,  7 
And  so  it  happens  that  the  impiety  which  we  might  be"^ 
tempted  to  discover  in  the  play,  far  from  being  properly  con- 
sidered as  the  object  of  his  censure,  should  on  the  contrary  be 
laid  at  his  own  door.  In  fact,  there  is  no  such  impiety.  It 
recalls  the  manner  of  treating  the  gods  which  was  accepted  by 
the  Athenian  public,  however  devout  it  may  have  been  in 
other  respects.  But  this  is  not  the  place  to  insist  on  this 
point.  The  only  thing  that  interests  us  is  the  evident  fact 
that  Aristophanes'  attitude  towards  religious  matters  in  the 
Birds  cannot,  in  any  way,  be  traced  to  a  satirical  purpose,  nor, 
consequently,  to  a  mental  reservation  of  a  political  nature. 
On  the  contrary,  his  spirit  seems  at  no  time  to  have  shown 
itself  so  free,  so  little  affected  by  practical  considerations,  in 
this  delicate  matter. 

It   is  easy  to  draw  a  conclusion  from  these  observations. 


130     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

The  Birds  certainly  is  full  of  scattered  allusions.  At  every 
turn  the  poet  hurls  shafts  of  derision  at  people  and  things. 
It  cannot  even  be  denied  that  some  of  this  derision  is  of  a 
general  character.  Nobody  will  gainsay  that  the  giddy, 
tlighty,  credulous  birds  often  remind  one  of  the  Athenians. 
Peithetaerus,  too,  has  some  of  the  characteristics  of  the 
politicians  of  the  day.  And  finally,  as  we  have  seen,  the 
underlying  motive  of  the  plot  is  a  criticism  of  the  moral 
condition  of  the  city,  of  its  propensity  to  suspicions  and  to 
lawsuits.  So  much  must  be  conceded  to  satire.  But  satire 
does  not  enter  into  the  essentials  of  the  fiction  itself,  and  it  is 
not  incorporated  in  the  plot.  No  governing  purpose  guides 
the  poet's  imagination ;  on  the  contrary,  his  imagination  is 
mistress  and  guides  his  conceits. 

Even  these  scattered  allusions  are  not  traceable  to  a 
uniform  tendency  nor  to  a  controlling  prejudice.  Aristophanes 
makes  epigrams  on  certain  demagogues  and  on  certain  demo- 
cratic vagaries,  he  makes  them  on  Gorgias  and  Philip  and 
their  disciples,  but  he  also  makes  them  on  the  aristocracy, 
on  those  who  favor  Sparta,  and  on  the  temporizing  tactics 
of  Nicias.-^  On  the  other  hand,  he  exhorts  the  young  people 
1EoT!uiy,  and  even  to  military  duty.'^  All  this  seems  to 
signify  remarkable  liberality  of  mind,  a  liberality  that  cannot 
be  explained  by  a  prohibitive  law,  if  we  admit  the  existence 
of  such  a  law.  Surely  the  democracy-  had  done  nothing 
since  421  to  disarm  criticism;  but  the  oligarchy,  for  its 
part,  does  not  seem  during  this  period  to  have  succeeded  in 
exerting  any  permanent  influence,  nor  in  proclaiming  a  political 
platform  that  was  worthy  of  discussion.  Its  most  ardent 
adherents  much  rather  thought  of  organizing  secretly  and  of 
preparing  for  an  emergency.  The  others,  and  above  all  the 
younger  ones,  amused  themselves  by  scandalizing  the  people 
with  fantastic  outbursts  of  impiety.  Neither  this  dangerous 
childishness,  nor  this  policy  of  plotting  can  have  pleased  the 
judicious  mind  of  Aristophanes.  As  he  advanced  in  years,  he 
was  always  less  in  touch  with  the  noisy  set.  His  thoughts,  as 
well  as  his  wit,  inclined  to  moderation.  He  judged  men  and 
^  Birds,  11.  637-8,  765,  813-815.  "Ihid.  11.  1363-1369. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     131 

events  from  a  higher  point  of  view,  and  he  was  swayed  by 
more  general  ideas.  Unless  I  am  mistaken,  this  may  be  seen 
in  the  comedy  of  the  Birds,  and  is  even  more  noticeable  in  the 
LTjsistrata,  which  was  performed  two  years  later. ^^^^ 


IV 

Ancient  authorities  place  two  of  Aristophanes'  extant  plays, 
the  Lysistrata  and  the  Thesmophoriazusae,  in  the  year  411,  but 
they  do  not  tell  us  which  of  them  was  performed  first.'^  It  is, 
however,  generally  admitted  that  the  Lysistrata  was  performed 
at  the  Lenaea  and  the  Thesmophoriazusae  at  the  Dionysia.^ 
This  conclusion  rests  chiefly  on  a  passage  in  the  Lysistrata  in 
which  the  poet  charges  Peisander  with  theft.^  Indeed,  it 
seems  impossible  to  believe  that  this  insult  was  offered  on  the 
stage  under  the  oligarchical  regime,  when  Peisander  was  at  the 
height  of  his  power. 

If  the  Lysistrata  was  performed  at  the  end  of  January,  411, 
it  must  have  been  written  in  the  second  half  of  the  year  412. 
It  is,  therefore,  in  the  events  of  that  year,  or  in  those  which 
slightly  preceded  it,  that  a  probable  explanation  of  the  inten- 
tion and  dispositions  of  the  poet  must  be  sought. 

When  word  came  to  Athens  of  the  disaster  that  had  befallen 
the  army  in  Sicily  toward  the  end  of  September,  413,*  it  pro- 
duced an  explosion  of  anger,  which  was  followed  by  a  profound 
stupor.^  And  yet,  the  energetic  spirit  of  Athens  reacted  almost 
at  once.  It  does  not  appear  that  anybody  at  that  time  pro- 
posed to  make  peace.  By  common  consent,  preparations  were 
made  for  vigorous  resistance,  although  nobody  dared  any  longer 

^  Lysistrata,  Argument,  p.  4,  Blaydes  :  iSiddxOv  iiri  KaWiov  apxovTos  rod  fMera 
KXedKpiTov.  Thesmoph.  schol.  11.  190,  804,  8-41  ;  cf.  Wilamowitz-Moellendorff, 
Aristoteles  mid  Athen,  ii.  p.  343. 

-Suvem,  Comm.  de  2^ubibus,  p.  44;  cf.  Blaydes,  Lysistrata,  Argumentum, 
p.  5. 

■*  Lysistrata,  11.  490-492 ;  iVa  yap  Iletcravopos  ^x"'  KX^irTdv  x^'  '''^■^^  dpxaU 
evixovres,  det  Tiva  KopKopvyrjv  eKiiKuv. 

••  Thucydides,  vii.  79.  3.  ^  Ibid.  viii.  1-2. 


132     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

count  on  victory.^  Moreover,  the  sense  of  danger  had  the 
effect  of  allaying  discussion,  and  of  making  the  masses  more 
reasonable.  An  extraordinary  office  was  created — that  of  the 
Probouloi — whose  duty  it  was  to  take  such  measures  as  the 
exigency  might  call  for,  and  ten  aged  men,  whose  experience 
no  doubt  recommended  them,  were  chosen  to  fill  it.^ 

This  state  of  mind  appears  to  have  lasted  during  the  whole 
of  the  year  412.  The  former  parties  had,  so  to  say,  dis- 
appeared. Though  the  people,  as  a  whole,  remained  attached 
to  their  institutions,  they  had  at  least  grown  to  hate  their 
regular  leaders.  They  distrusted  the  fine  talkers,  the  wild 
enthusiasts  and  the  makers  of  promises ;  they  felt,  in  a  con- 
fused way  perhaps,  but  strongly,  the  need  of  firmer  and  more 
consistent  guidance,  and  instinctively  turned  to  those  who 
offered  them  better  guarantees  of  moderation  and  prudence. 
Consequently  the  most  circumspect  of  the  radical  politicians 
were  in  a  fair  way  to  become  conservatives.  Peisander,  in 
particular,  was  preparing  to  become  one  of  the  restorers  of  the 
oligarchy,^  when  occasion  should  offer.  But  the  moderate 
party,  who  for  the  moment  retained  authority,  no  more 
dreamed  of  coming  to  terms  with  the  enemy  than  did  the 
erstwhile  demagogues,  probably  because  they  felt  that  it  was 
impossible.*  The  military  events  of  412  did  not  alter  the 
situation.  Athens  was  able  to  confront  the  immediate  danger. 
She  saw,  it  is  true,  a  threatening  alliance  concluded  between 
her  enemies  and  the  king  of  Persia,  Darius  II. ;  she  also  saw 
serious  defections  take  place  among  her  allies  and  her  subjects 
— those  of  "Chios,  of  Erythraea  and  Clazomenae,''  of  Miletus  ^* 

^  Thucydides,  viii.  1.  3,  and  24.  5:  toi)s 'A^T^i/a/oi'j  .  .  .  ovb' avroii^  avrCKi- 
yovras  'iri  /jLera  ttjv  "LLKiKiKrjv  ^vpLcpopav  cIis  ov  ttclvv  Tr6vr]pa  acpQv  ^ejBalws  ra 
irpdyfiara  etr]. 

^Thucydides,  viii.  1.  3-4.  Aristotle,  Constitution  of  Athens,  29.  2.  Bekker, 
Anecd.  i.  p.  298  ;  ef.  Ed.  Meyer,  Gesch.  d.  Alterth.  iv.  p.  558. 

^Lysias,  Oration,  26.  9. 

■*The  oligarchical  party  itself  at  first  thought  of  continuing  the  war  (Thuc. 
viii.  53.  63).  It  was  only  after  the  execution  of  the  coup  d'etat,  when  all 
thought  of  reconciliation  with  Alcibiades  and  at  the  same  time  of  support  from 
Persia  had  to  be  abandoned,  that  an  attempt  was  made  to  come  to  terms. 
Beitrage,  pp.  315-316. 

^Thucydides,  viii.  14.  '^' Ihid.  viii.  17. 


THE   SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     133 

and  of  other  places  besides.  But  these  defections  did  not  all 
take  place  at  the  same  time,  and  she  succeeded  in  checking  or 
in  forestalling  several  of  them,  notably  that  of  Lesbos.^  Solidly 
intrenched  in  Samos,  she  did  not  permit  herself  to  be  expelled 
from  Ionia,  and  kept  her  foes  in  awe.  When  winter  came, 
her  affairs  were,  as  a  whole,  in  a  better  state  than  was  to  have 
been  expected.  Persia,  the  source  of  greatest  anxiety,  was 
supporting  the  Peloponnesians  with  its  subsidies,  and  was 
promising  them  the  co-operation  of  its  fleet.  And  it  was  just 
this  that  kept  careful  politicians  from  believing  in  the  possi- 
bility of  negotiating  a  peace.  Sparta's  position  was  too  favor- 
able for  her  to  consent  to  abandon  it  before  having  completely 
deprived  her  adversary  of  power. 

How  did  it  happen  then  that  Aristophanes,  just  at  this 
time,  conceived  the  idea  of  writing  a  comedy  in  favor  of 
peace  ?  A  comic  poet  might,  in  case  of  need,  antagonize  a 
prevailing  opinion,  but  evidently  only  if  he  cpuld  rely  upon  at 
least  a  considerable  and  influential  minority;  In  January,  411 
we  cannot  discover  in  the  Athenian  masses  a  minority  of  the 
sort  that  would  have  been  inclined  to  propose  peace. 

A  comedy,  and  even  a  comedy  with  a  distinct  tendency, 
cannot  be  likened  to  the  draft  of  a  law,  nor  to  a  definite 
argument.  It  is  rather  in  the  nature  of  a  suggestion,  which 
does  not  necessarily  lead  to  a  practical  result.  The  poet  may 
appeal  to  deep-seated  opinions  which  are  for  the  moment  kept 
back  and  restrained  by  urgent  considerations,  but  which  only 
await  an  opportunity  to  gain  the  upper  hand,  and  even  await 
it  impatiently.  And  if  he  personally  shares  those  opinions  as 
fully,  or  even  more  fully,  than  anybody  else,  it  is  natural  that 
he  should  wish  to  encourage  them,  or  to  strengthen  them,  or 
that  he  should  even  try  to  show,  in  his  own  fashion,  that  their 
realization  is,  after  all,  not  so  far  distant,  nor  so  impossible,  as 
people  about  him  commonly  think.  This  is  just  what  it  seems 
to  me  Aristophanes  tried  to  do  in  his  Lysistrata.  That  he  did 
so  independently  of  all  party  influence,  appears  from  the  con- 
ception of  the  play  and  from  its  development ;  and  this  is  what 
we  must  try  to  make  clear. 

1  Thucydides,  viii.  22-23. 


134     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 


One  of  the  first  facts  to  be  noted  is  that  in  this  comedy  he 
-^did  not  put  any  party  nor  any  political  group  upon  the  stage. 
There  is  no  aristocratic  chorus,  as  in  the  Knights,  nor  a 
representative  of  the  rural  democracy,  like  Dicaeopolis  or 
Trygaeus,  nor  a  decided  enemy  of  influential  politicians,  like 
Bdelycleon.  Who  are  the  mouthpieces  of  the  poet  ?  They 
are  women,  and  foremost  of  all  LysiStrata,  the  leader  in  the 
conspiracy,  the  organizer  of  the  enterprise,  who  regulates  its 
progress  with  such  clever  decision  ;  and  her  companions  are 
^Athenian,  Boeotian  and  Lacedaemonian  women.  They  are 
drawn  together  by  a  common  interest,  which  is  not  that  of 
any  party,  nor  of  any  city  in  particular,  but,  properly  speak- 
ing, a  feminine  interest.  They  abhor  war,  because  war 
/destroys  family  life,  separates  them  from  their  husbands  and 
their  sons,  keeps  the  young  girls  from  getting  married, 
occasions  them  all  alarm,  anguish  and  mourning,  and  finally, 
because  it  ruins  their  special  work,  which  consists  in  making 
the  home  prosper,  and  through  the  home,  the  city,  and 
through  the  city,  the  whole  of  Greece.  Presently  we  shall 
come  back  to  this  very  interesting  Hellenic  sentiment.  Here 
we  need  only  observe  that,  as  women,  they  have  this  sentiment 
as  the  result  of  the  painful  anxiety  which  affects  their  domestic 
life.  As  for  the  means  they  adopt  to  bring  the  scheme  to  a 
successful  issue,  we  know,  without  having  to  insist  upon  it, 
that  it  is  the  most  feminine'^imaginable.  For  the  capture  of 
the  Acropolis  is  merely  an  amusing  conceit,  necessary  to  keep 
the  plot  going,  and  the  poet  almosts  neglects  it  in  the  course 
of  the  play.  These  women  are  intrenched  in  their  resolve 
much  more  than  they  are  intrenched  in  the  citadel,  and  this 
resolve  really  has  nothing  to  do  either  with  oligarchy  or 
democracy. 

Thus,  the  poet,  at  the  outset,  places  himself  above  party 
considerations  by  the  choice  of  his  representatives,  and  seems 
to  give  us  to  understand  that  he  is  devoted  to  a  more  general 
and   truly  human   interest.     Do   the  allusions  which   appear 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     135 

here  and  there  throughout  the  scenes  contlict  with  such  a 
purpose  ?  By  no  means ;  for  they  are  directed  indiscrim- 
inately against  all  those  who  harass  the  city  for  the  benefit  of 
their  ambition  or  of  their  greed. 

When  the  old  men  get  ready  to  storm  the  gate  of  the 
Acropolis  with  battering  rams,  they  clamor  for  the  aid  of  the 
generals,  who  are  at  Samos :  "  Which  of  the  Samian  generals 
will  give  us  a  hand?"^  The  allusion  is  very  obscure.  The 
best  ancient  commentators,  especially  Didymus,  referred  it  to 
Phrynichus,  but  without  explaining  it,  or,  if  they  did  explain 
it,  their  explanation  has  been  lost.  What  we  lack  here  is  a 
detailed  chronicle,  by  month  and  day.  I  think  it  most  likely 
that  the  Athenians  had  got  wind  of  the  intrigues  that  were 
ripe  in  the  army  at  Samos,  of  the  negotiations  with  Alcibiades, 
of  the  differences  among  the  generals,  and  that  the  poet  intended 
these  old  men  to  say :  "  On  which  of  the  generals  can  we 
rely  to  defend  solely  the  public  interest  ? "  It  would,  at  best, 
be  hard  to  discover  in  such  a  question  any  semblance  of  a 
profession  of  political  faith.' 

The  scene  in  which  the  discussion  between  Lysistrata  and 

the  Proboulos  takes  place,  is  the  most  important  one  of  the 

play,  from  the  point  of  view  of  ideas.     At  the  very  outset 

Lysistrata   declares    that    she    has    taken    possession    of    the 

Acropolis,  in  order  to  put  the  money  in  security,  "  so  that," 

she  says  to  the  magistrate,  "  it  may  no  longer  afford  you  a 

\  reason  for  war."     "  What  I"  exclaims  the  astonished  Proboulos, 

I  "  is  money  the  cause  of  our  fighting  ? "     "  Yes,"  replied  Lysi- 

/  strata,  "  and  it  is  on  account  of  the  money   that   the  whole 

'   trouble  arose.     For  Peisander  and  those  who  have  their  minds 

^  Lysistrata,    1.    313   and  schol.  :    rts   ^vWd^oir'   Slv  tov  ^v\ov  twu   iv  Hdfup 

-C4ilbert,  Beitrdge,  p.  299,  thinks  that  the  generals  all  belonged  to  the 
"  war  partj',"  and  that,  consequently,  the  old  men  who  come  to  the  Acropolis 
in  search  of  money  to  conduct  the  war,  must  have  regarded  them  as  allies. 
Could  the  audience  have  guessed  such  a  riddle  ?  Besides,  we  have  absolutely 
no  knowledge  as  to  whether  all  the  generals  were  known  for  their  specially 
warlike  dispositions,  and  it  must  be  admitted  that  this  is  very  unlikely  a 
priori.  As  a  rule,  they  belonged  to  the  moderate  party  or  even  to  the 
oligarchy  (see  Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.   1412). 


136     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

bent  on  office  needed  a  chance  to  steal.  In  future  let  them 
do  whatever  they  choose ;  the  money,  at  all  events,  they 
cannot  have."  ^ 

We  know  who  Peisander  was :  an  ambitious  demagogue, 
who  at  this  very  moment  scented  the  change  in  the  wind, 
and  became,  as  we  have  already  said,  one  of  the  promoters  of 
the  oligarchical  revolution.^  Does  the  poet  attack  the  demo- 
crat or  the  oligarch  here  ?  It  seems  clear  that,  at  the  time 
when  the  play  was  performed,  the  assembly  to  which  Peisander 
came,  at  the  instigation  of  the  oligarchs  of  Samos,  to  preach  a 
change  of  constitution  to  the  people,  had  already  been  held.^ 
But  Peisander  did  not  pretend  to  be  an  oligarch.  In  pul)lic 
he  doubtless  professed  that  he  was  still  devoted  to  the  radical 
democracy,  and  he  merely  proposed  his  scheme  of  reform  as 
a  temporary  concession  to  an  urgent  necessity.  And  Aristo- 
phanes could,  if  he  chose,  insist  on  seeing  only  the  demagogue 
in  him.^  But  it  is  well  worth  observing  that  he  is  named  in 
connection  with  a  group  of  ambitious  men  "  whose  minds  are 
bent  on  office  "  (ot  rat^  ap-^alg  eTre-^ovTe^).  Whom  does  Aristo- 
phanes mean  by  this  ?  Another  passage  gives  us  light  on 
this  point.  Later  on  (11.  574  et  seq.)  Lysistrata  proclaims 
her  policy.  If  the  men  want  to  act  properly,  they  need  only 
treat  politics  just  as  women  treat  the  wool  which  they  wish 
to  spin.  "  First  of  all,  just  as  they  wash  the  wool  to  get  rid 
of  the  grease,  so  the  rascals  should  be  driven  from  the  city 
energetically,  under  the  whip ;  these  '  burrs '  must  be  got  rid 
of;  then  they  should  thoroughly  card  the  people  who  stick  to 
one  another,  who  herd  together  and  press  about  the  offices, 
and  they  should  pluck  off,  one  by  one,  the  matted  heads." 
Theee  metaphors,  which  it  is  hard  to  render  into  English, 
become  clear  when  we  study  them  closely,  and  they  were 
specially    clear    to    the    Athenians.      The    poet    attacks    the 

^Lysistrata,  11.  488-492.  ^Lysias,  Oration  25.  9. 

^  Tlmcydides,  viii.  53.  The  historian  does  not  give  the  date.  His  account 
seems  to  show  that  there  were  several  sessions  of  the  assembly.  But  Busolt 
(Griech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1468,  note  2,  and  p.  1471,  note  1)  has  shown,  in  a 
convincing  manner,  that  these  sessions  were  held  in  the  course  of  Januarj'. 

•*  Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1461,  note  1. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     137 

political  associations,  which  were  organized  with  a  view  to 
intlueucing  the  elections  and  the  verdicts  of  the  courts,  and 
which  Thucydides  has  described  in  more  explicit  terms.^ 
They  are  commonly  known  as  hetaeries.  Now,  these  hetaeries 
were  nearly  all  oligarchical  groups,  and  so  it  is  quite  probable 
that,  in  the  former  of  the  two  passages  quoted,  it  was  these 
politicians  among  the  oligarchs  whom  the  poet  attacked,  when 
he  spoke  of  ambitious  men  "  whose  minds  are  bent  on  office." 
At  any  rate,  they  are  certainly  meant  in  the  second  passage. 
Consequently,  it  appears  that,  in  the  words  of  Lysistrata,  he 
attacks  all  ambitious  persons,  without  distinction  of  party. 
Had  he  been  a  partisan  and  an  abettor  of  the  revolution 
which  was  then  on  foot,  such  utterances  could  not  be  under- 
stood. 

Even  the  part  given  to  the  Proboulos  well  shows  how  little 
Aristophanes  was  under  the  influence  of  the  oligarchical  party 
at  this  time.  We  have  already  seen  under  what  circumstances 
and  for  what  purposes  the  Frobouloi  had  been  created.  In  no 
sense  did  they  constitute  a  democratic  magistracy.  Indeed, 
Aristotle  informs  us  that,  when  the  oligarchical  revolution 
took  place,  twenty  newly  elected  Probouloi  were  added  to  the 
ten  already  in  office,  and  that  together  they  formed  the 
college.^  Thus,  the  original  Probouloi  were  in  the  confidence 
of  the  men  who  brought  about  the  revolution  even  before  it 
took  place.  Had  Aristophanes  been  with  them  heart  and 
soul,  he  ought  to  have  had  due  regard  for  the  feelings  of  these 
moderators,  who  stood  for  prudence.  Does  he  act  in  this 
manner  ?  His  Proboulos  is  a  pompous  and  absurd  sort  of  a 
chap,  whom  people  impudently  mock  and  hold  up  to  ridicule, 
and  whom  Lysistrata  even  muffies  up  in  her  hood,  before 
proving  to  him  that  he  knows  nothing  of  _publig  affairs. 
Horseplay  by  a  poet  in  a  jolly  mood,  if  you  choose,  but  very 
well  suited,  nevertheless,  to  show  us  that  this  poet  was  not  a 
devout  worshipper  at  the  shrine  of  oligarchy. 

The  decisive  argument  of  the  revolutionists  is  known  to 

^  Thucydides,  viii.  54  :  tAj  Iww^iotr/as,  aiwep  irvyx'^^o^  ^v  ry  iroXtt  ovcrai  iirl 
SlKait  Kal  dpxo-U. 

"Aristotle,  Constitution  of  Athens,  c.  xxix.  2. 


138    THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

have  been  that  the  doings  of  the  radical  democracy  deprived 
Athens  of  all  possibility  of  foreign  help,  that  they  frightened 
the  great  king  and  jeopardized  the  good-will  of  Alcibiades. 
Indeed,  this  is  the  substance  of  the  speech  which  Thucydides 
imputes  to  Peisander.^  It  may  be  that  a  comic  poet  would 
still  have  hesitated  to  introduce  such  an  argument  on  the 
stage  in  January,  411,  even  though  he  shared  the  views  of  the 
party.  But  surely  it  was  not  impossible  to  hint  at  it,  to  give 
it  a  hearing  in  some  ingeniously  devised  scene,  provided  always 
that  he  took  proper  precautions.  There  is  nothing  of  the  sort 
in  Aristophanes'  play — not  even  the  slightest  suggestion  of  the 
sort. 

Thus,  everything  combines  to  characterize  his  political 
tendency  as  absolutely  independent,  and  if  it  aims  at  any 
domestic  reform,  it  is  only  the  allaying  of  hatred,  the  surrender 
of  prejudices,  and  the  co-operation  of  citizens  in  a  spirit  of 
mutual  good-will.  After  saying  how  she  meant  to  card  the 
wool,  Lysistrata  adds :  "  And  then  they  must  tumble  mutual 
good-will  into  the  basket  and  mingle  there  the  resident  aliens 
(jueroiKoi)  and  even  the  foreigners,  if  they  are  our  friends ;  in 
fact,  everybody,  including  even  those  who  owe  money  to  the 
public  treasury,  for  they  too  must  be  mingled  with  the  others ; 
and  also,  by  Zeus,  the  cities  which  are  colonies  of  this  land 
must  be  recognized,  for  they  are  the  scattered  flocks  that  have 
fallen  here  and  there.  Let  us  gather  them  all  and  bring  them 
here  and  put  them  together ;  and  then  we'll  make  a  great 
heap  of  them  from  which  to  weave  a  cloak  for  the  people."  ^ 
\  Here  we  have  in  brief  all  that  there  is  of  Aristophanes'  politics 
lin  the  Lysistrata^  It  suggests  a  man  who  desires  peace  and 
harmony,  tired  by  reciprocal  animosities,  not  at  all  anxious  for 

r^       revolution,  but   rather  longing  for  quiet,  and  very  sincerely 
devoted  to  the  greatness  of  his  country. 

Furthermore,  in  411   the  question  of  reform  was  subordi- 

__  nated  to  the  question  of  war  or  peace.  The  latter  dominated 
everything.  How  is  it  conceived  and  treated  in  the  Lysis- 
trata ?  The  whole  play  is  inspired  and  pervaded  with  a 
spirit  of  HelleiiiaJEatfixnity  which  calls  for  description. 

1  Thucydides,  viii.  58.  ^Lysistrata,  11.  579-586. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     139 

Without  going  back  to  the  historical  origin  of  this  senti- 
ment, we  need  only  recall  that  it  had  been  strongly  manifested 
during  the  fifth  century,  notwithstanding  secret  or  open 
differences  during  the  Persian  wars,  and  the  twenty  or  thirty 
years  that  followed.  During  the  first  period  of  its  existence, 
at  least,  the  maritime  confederacy  of  Delos  was  really  a 
national  coalition  of  a  large  number  of  Greek  cities  against  the 
barbarians.  The  rivalries  which  subsequently  arose  crowded 
out  this  sentiment,  but  did  not  entirely  stifle  it.  Having  lost 
its  influence  in  the  domain  of  politics,  it  maintained  itself  in 
that  of  literature  and  art,  because  poetry,  oratory,  philosophy 
and  higher  culture  generally,  were  historically  connected  with 
various  parts  of  Greece,  and  appealed  to  all  the  Greeks.  Even 
during  the  Peloponnesian  war  we  see  that  Athens  was  visited 
by  philosophers,  artists  and  leaders  in  every  field.  In  the 
circles  in  which  they  moved  they  must  necessarily  have  made 
evident  the  deep-seated  community  of  the  intellectual  and 
moral  ideals  of  the  Greeks,  and,  consequently,  the  advantages 
that  would  come  to  them  by  living  in  harmony.  We  may  add 
that,  by  encouraging  a  kindly  spirit  and  humane  feelings,  they 
also  did  their  share  toward  making  people  hate  a  war  which 
was  causing  widespread  ruin  and  desolation.  Aristophanes, 
who  was  admired  as  a  poet  and  known  as  a  warm  friend  of 
peace,  could  not  remain  a  stranger  to  these  influences.  We 
have  already  seen  that  as  early  as  421,  in  his  comedy  of  the 
Peace,  an  undeniably  Hellenic  feeling  was  part  and  parcel  of 
the  dominant  sentiment  of  the  play — the  joy  of  seeing  the 
Athenian  peasant  at  work  and  secure  in  his  former  state.  But 
if  we  compare  the  Lysistrata  and  the  Peace,  we  immediately 
perceive  how  strong  this  same  Hellenic  sentiment  had  grown 
in  the  poet's  soul  between  421  and  411. 

At  the  very  outset,  we  see  that  national  unity  exists  among 
the  women.^  The  conspirators  are  not  recruited  from  Athens 
alone.  They  comprise  Boeotian  and  l*eloponnesian  women, 
and  the  robust  Lacedaemonian  Lampito,  who  is  not  the  least 
emphatic  among  them.  Their  avowed  aim  is  to  "  save  the 
whole  of  Greece,"  oX;;?  ri]9  'EXXa't^o?  »7  awTijpia}     This  formula 

^Lysistrata,  11.  29-30,  41  :  koiv^  adiao/xev  rrjf'EWada ;  cf.  1.  525. 


140     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

recurs  several  times,  because  it  really  expresses  the  gist  of 
their  thought ;  it  is  a  question  of  rescuing  the  men  from  a 
murderous  folly  which  would  end  in  the  destruction  of  the 
Hellenic  name.^  The  chorus  of  women,  it  is  true,  consists  of 
Athenians,  and  these  Athenians  appeal  to  the  patron  divinity 
of  the  city^  and  they  proclaim  their  patriotism.^  Their 
greatest  desire  is  to  help  their  native  city  by  good  counsels — 
the  city  to  which  they  owe  so  much,  and  with  whose  festivals 
they  have  been  identified  since  their  childhood/  But,  in  their 
eyes,  the  interests  of  Athens  are  inseparable  from  the  common 
interests  of  the  Greeks.  It  is  in  peace,  in  concord,  and  not  in 
war,  that  they  must  find  their  realization. 

Such  are  the  principles,  and  it  now  remains  to  apply  them. 
In  practice  the  desire  for  peace  takes  the  form  of  diplomatic 
negotiations,  that  is,  of  compromised/What  sort  of  a  compro- 
mise does  Aristophanes  recommend  to  the  rival  cities  as  the 
price  of  peace  ? 

It  must  be  admitted  that  the  poet  is  far  from  explicit  on 
this  point.  The  closing  scene  of  the  play  represents  an  ideal 
sort  of  congress,  in  which  sentiment  plays  a  larger  part  than 
negotiations,  properly  speaking.  Lysistrata  is  chosen  as 
arbiter,  and  begs  the  deputies  of  Sparta  and  those  of  Athens 
to  approach.  It  is  Diallage,  Reconciliation,  personified  as  a 
woman,  who  takes  them  by  the  hand.  She  does  so  with  a 
feminine  gentleness,  which  the  poet  points  out  as  a  great 
innovation,^  and  Lysistrata  herself  uses  gentle  and  touching 
words  in  order  to  obtain  her  object :  "  Since  I  have  you  here, 
I  wish  to  reproach  you  both,  for  you  have  deserved  it.  You 
who  pour  a  common  libation  upon  the  altars,  like  brothers — 
and  you  are  brothers — at  Olympia,  at  Thermopylae,  at  Pytho 
(how  many  other  sacred  places  could  I  name,  did  I  not  wish 

^  Lysistrata,  1.  342  :  ttoX^/xou  nal  /j.aviwv  pucra/x^vas  'EXXdSa  (cat  TroXlras.  Cf.  11. 
523-526. 

^Ihid.  1.  341  etseq. 

^  Ibid.  1.  347  :  ^vi  5^  <^iX6fl-oXts  dperrj  <ppovLixos. 

*Ihid.  11.  637-648. 

^  Tbid.  1.  1116:  fir]  xaXeTr^  ry  x^'P^  f^V'^  avdaSiKrj,  fj.7]6'  icfftrep  ruiQiv  dvSpts 
dfia6u)s  tout'  ^dpwv. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     141 

to  be  brief !) ;  and  to-day,  when  the  barbarians,  our  true 
enemies,  are  at  our  gates,  you  with  your  armies  slay  Greeks 
and  destroy  Greek  cities."  ^  Identity  of  race  and  community 
of  interests,  a  national  religion,  union  against  the  barbarians, 
all  themes  which  oratory  was  soon  to  make  its  own,  and 
which  we  again  meet,  three  years  later,  in  the  famous  oration 
delivered  by  Gorgias  at  Olympia,  probably  in  the  year 
408.^^  The  coincidence  is  instructive,  because  it  enables  us 
to  surmise  in  what  surroundings  these  themes  originated. 
Lysistrata  also  recalls  the  services  that  Sparta  and  Athens 
have  rendered  one  another.  Sparta  drove  out  the  Peisistra- 
tidae ;  Athens  gave  help  to  Sparta  when  she  was  in  danger 
through  the  revolt  of  the  Messenians.  These  memories,  these 
thoughts  must  prepare  men's  minds  and  incline  them  to 
reconciliation. 

Then  comes  the  agreement  proper,  which  is  treated  jestingly. 
Athens  is  to  give  up  Pylus ;  this  is  the  only  thing  that  seems 
serious.^  As  for  the  concessions  demanded  by  Sparta,  they 
refer  to  the  Maliac  gulf,  to  Echinus,  and  to  Megara,  but  they 
are  travestied  in  equivocal  and  absurd  obscenities,  and  it 
is  hard  to  say  whether  there  is  anything  worth  recalling. 
This  is  evidently  done  because  the  comic  poet  does  not  think 
himself  competent  to  settle  the  conditions  of  peace.  He  is 
satisfied  with  a  few  names,  by  way  of  suggestion  or  example ; 
it  would  have  been  ridiculous  for  him  to  go  still  further,  and 
to  wish  to  substitute  himself  for  the  future  negotiators,  when 
neither  side  had  as  yet  made  any  overtures. 

It  is  the  moral  preparation  for  peace,  the  appeal  to  senti- 
ments which  are  to  make  it  possible,  that  interests  him,  and 
that  he  regards  as  his  task.  "We  have  just  seen  that  he  does 
not  make  this  appeal  in  the  name  of  any  party.  He  conceived 
it  under  the  influence  of  a  sentiment  that  was  more  Hellenic 
than  Athenian,  and  perhaps  more  human  than  Hellenic.      At 

1  LysLstrata,  11.  1128-1135. 

-Ed.  Meyer,  Gesch.  des  Alterth.  v.  p.  333. 

^  At  first  sight  lines  698-705  might  be  regarded  as  advice  to  annul  the  pro- 
hibitive decrees  against  the  importation  of  the  goods  of  neighboring  countries. 
But  this  advice  is  turned  into  buffoonerj'. 

L 


142     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

this  period  of  his  life  he  seems  to  have  been  painfully  conscious 
of  the  harmMGreece  was  doing  to  herself  by  dismembering 
herself  with  ner  own  hands^  and  we  seem  to  divine  that,  in 
addition  to  his  old,  instinctive  repugnance  to  war,  he  had  a 
still  deeper  and  nobler  sentiment,  that  was  called  forth  by 
what  he  regarded  as  a  crime  against  humanity. 

But  at  this  point  a  doubt  naturally  arises  about  the  practical 
value,  and  even  about  the  morality  of  his  proposal — a  doubt 
which  it  is  impossible  to  avoid  entertaining.  Was  it  to 
Athens  that  these  suggestions  should  have  been  made  ?  And 
was  the  moment  well  chosen  to  incline  people's  minds  to  peace, 
when  the  situation  appeared  to  call  for  a  desperate  effort  ? 

It  is  a  delicate  matter  to  answer  questions  of  this  sort 
when  one's  information  is  necessarily  insufficient.  As  far  as 
we  can  judge,  it  was  not  the  Athenians  who  were  most  anxious 
to  continue  the  war.  They  did  not  regain  confidence  until 
somewhat  later,  after  Alcibiades'  victory.  In  411  they  would 
probably  have  agreed  to  treat  for  peace,  if  their  enemies  had 
offered  them  conditions  compatible  with  their  honor.  But 
the  latter,  conscious  of  their  superiority,  and  supported  by 
Persia,  wished  to  crush  them  by  destroying  their  naval  supre- 
macy. This  was  a  demand  to  which  Athens  could  not  consent, 
as  long  as  there  remained  any  hope  of  regaining  the  upper 
hand.  Aristophanes  surely  cannot  have  thought  otherwise,  for 
in  his  play  Lysistrata  certainly  appears  desirous  of  maintaining 
the  maritime  confederacy.  Is  that  not  the  meaning  of  the 
passage,  quoted  above,  in  which  she  likens  the  cities  "  sprung 
from  Athens "  (ra?  ye  TroXei?  oiroa-ai  t>/?  7^9  Tticr^'  ^'O'''^ 
airoLKoi)  to  scattered  flocks  of  wool  which  it  was  necessary  to 
collect  and  reunite,  in  order  to  weave  them  into  a  cloak  for 
the  people  ?  But  these  very  cities  were  at  that  time  seeking 
to  detach  themselves  from  the  confederacy ;  Chios,  Miletus, 
and  Lesbos  had  seceded  in  412.  The  poet  does  not  seem  to 
have  appreciated  the  gravity  of  these  facts.  His  advice  is  y 
to  bring  them  back  and  to  unite  them  through  kindliness,  r 
He  may  have  had  reason  to  l^elieve  that  the  arrogance  and 
severity  of  the  Athenian  people  had  made  their  domination 
hateful  to  them.      But  the  harm  had  been  done,  and  it  was 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS    143 

certainly  a  great  delusion  to  think  that  it  could  be  made  good 
by  a  kindly  policy  while  war  was  in  full  swing.  In  fact,  we 
can  hardly  decide  at  this  late  day  whether  the  establislinient 
of  a  confederation  of  states  with  equal  rights  and  under  the 
nominal  leadership  of  Athens  would  ever  have  been  feasible. 
But  we  can  affirm  that,  once  separated  from  the  metropolis, 
the  cities  in  question  would  never  have  rejoined  it  of  their 
own  free  will.  The  sense  of  autonomy  was  much  too  strong 
in  these  small  repulilics,  whether  they  were  organized  as 
democracies  or  as  oligarchies.^  Unless  I  am  mistaken,  this  is 
what  Aristophanes  failed  to  understand  sufficiently.  The 
spirit  which  pervades  the  Lysistrata  is  generous  and  noble,  but 
it  is  the  spirit  of  a  somewhat  fanciful  poet,  who  unconsciously 
fashioned  hard  reality  in  the  mould  of  his  hopes  and  dreams. 


VI 

We  have  already  said  that  another  play  by  Aristophanes, 
the  Thesmophoriazusae,  was  performed  in  the  same  year,  411, 
at  the  city  Dionysia,  and  consequently  toward  the  end  of 
March.  This  was  the  moment  when  Athens,  on  the  brink 
of  oligarchical  revolution,  was  smitten  by  the  dread  which 
Thucydides  has  described.-  Does  the  comedy  in  question  give 
evidence  of  the  poet's  sympathy  with  the  party  that  prepared 
the  way  for  the  revolution  ? 

The  play  is  directed  chiefly  against  Euripides  and  inci- 
dentally against  Agathon,  and  has  nothing  to  do  with  politics. 
It  cannot  even  be  said  to  touch  upon  it  on  its  ethical  side,  for 
Aristophanes  does  not  charge  Euripides  with  exerting  harmful 
intluence  on  the  society  of  the  day.  He  simply  represents 
him  as  the  object  of  women's  hatred,  on  account  of  the  evil  he 

^This  is  also  the  opinion  of  Busolt,  Cfriech.  Gesch.  iii.  2^6.  part,  p.  1414.  He 
ver\'  correctly  remarks  that,  after  the  Sicilian  war  the  allies  thought  only  of 
regaining  their  liberty  by  freeing  themselves  from  the  domination  of  Athens, 
and  that  a  policy  of  kindliness  would  at  that  time  have  been  regarded  as  a 
sign  of  weakness. 

-  Thucvdides,  viii.  66. 


144     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

has  spoken  of  them.  Moreover,  far  from  treating  Euripides' 
utterances  as  calumnies,  he  seems  rather  to  set  them  to  his 
credit,  so  that  all  his  mockery  of  Euripides  is  reduced  simply 
to  making  him  play  a  ridiculous  part  and  to  entertaining  us 
with  his  attempts  to  save  his  father-in-law,  Mnesilochus,  who 
has  sacrificed  himself  for  him,  from  the  women's  vengeance. 
The  satire  itself,  which  at  first  appears  to  be  aimed  at  him,  is 
really  aimed  at  womankind.  This  satire,  moreover,  is  of  small 
import,  as  it  deals  with  well-known  grievances  and  contem- 
plates no  reform. 

We  might,  therefore,  pass  over  this  play  in  complete  silence, 
if  it  were  not  for  the  fact  that  it  contains  a  few  allusions 
which  we  shall  have  to  discuss  very  briefly,  in  order  that  we 
may  at  least  correct  certain  interpretations  that  have  been 
given  of  them. 

The  meeting  which  is  held  by  the  women  is  represented  as 
an  assembly  of  the  people.  It  is,  therefore,  opened,  just  as  the 
assemblies  were,  with  a  solemn  prayer  pronounced  by  the 
herald.  The  scholiast  tells  us  that  this  prayer  contains 
certain  formulae,  borrowed  from  the  maledictions  against  the 
Peisistratidae  and  from  the  decrees  once  issued  against 
Hippias.^  It  seems  rather  hard  to  believe  that  the  Athenian 
public  were  sufficiently  well  posted  about  their  own  history  to 
grasp  a  parody  of  such  ancient  matters  at  a  casual  hearing. 
We  must  rather  suppose  that  these  formulae  were  still  in 
common  use  in  Aristophanes'  time,  for  certain  purposes,  and 
that  the  poet  parodies  usages  of  his  own  day.  But  it  is 
surprising  to  find  here  a  curse  "  on  whoever  treats  with  the 
Medes."^  We  know,  in  fact,  that  in  the  spring  of  411  the 
Athenian  policy  was  to  detach  the  satraps  of  Asia  Minor,  and 
consequently  the  king  of  Persia,  from  the  Peloponnesian 
Alliance,  in  order  to  obtain  a  subsidy  from  them — in  other 
words,  to  form  an  alliance  with  them.  The  argument  which 
Peisander  employed  in  order  to  prepare  the  people  for  the 
oligarchical  revolution  was  precisely  this  necessity  of  recourse 

1  Schol.  TJiesmoph.  1.  339. 

^  Thesmoph.  1.  336  (et  tis)  .   .   .   ij  'in.K7]pvKe6eTai.  Evpiirldr)  Mi^Soiy  r'  (wi  ^Xd^ri 
Tivi  rrj  Twv  yvvalKuv. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND   DECELEIAN  WARS     145 

to  Persia  and  the  distrust  with  which  the  democratic  govern- 
ment inspired  the  great  Asiatic  monarchy.^  This  argument 
impressed  the  people  and  brought  about  the  first  reforms.^  In 
consequence  of  this  the  Athenians  no  longer  dreamed  of 
cursing  those  who  "  wished  to  treat  with  the  Medes,"  at  the 
time  Aristophanes'  play  was  performed.  What  then  was  the 
poet's  meaning  ?  Prof,  von  Wilamowitz,  in  a  very  interesting 
essay  on  the  date  of  the  ThesmopJioriazusae,^  has  expressed 
the  opinion  that  a  majority  of  the  citizens — those  who  were  ,' 
actively  engaged  in  the  politics  of  the  day — leaned  towards  : 
Persia,  but  that  there  were  still  some  who  were  undecided, 
people  with  moderate  views,  sincere  and  honest  patriots,  who 
remained  true  to  the  opinions  of  earlier  days ;  and  it  is  in  this 
category  that  he  places  Aristophanes.* 

This  explanation  would  be  sufficient,  if  it  were  necessary. 
But  it  makes  the  mistake  of  taking  seriously  what  is  mani- 
festly meant  for  a  joke.  The  herald  curses  "  whoever  shall 
treat  with  the  Medes  in  order  to  harm  the  tribe  of  woman." 
This  addition  is  the  keynote  of  the  sentence.  At  this  very 
moment  when  it  was  proposed  to  treat  with  the  Mede,  the 
poet  thought  it  would  be  amusing  to  revive,  in  a  humorous 
way,  a  formula,  which  had  perhaps  been  abandoned  for  a  time 
but  had  not  yet  been  forgotten,  and  which  was  in  amusing 
contrast  to  the  feeling  of  the  day.  Had  he  wished  to  make 
the  people  regret  the  abandonment  of  this  formula,  he  surely 
would  have  gone  about  it  in  a  different  w^ay.  The  attempt, 
therefore,  to  find  an  indication  of  his  political  views  in  this 
sentence  should  be  abandoned. 

A  second  allusion,  which  has  likewise  been  taken  seriously, 
seems  to  me  to  be  of  the  same  order.  In  the  parabasis  the 
women  maintain,  through  the  coryphaeus,  that  they  are  much 
superior  to  the  men.  "  If  you  wish  proof  of  it,"  they  say, 
"compare  a  few  of  our  names  with  a  few  of  yours."  There 
follows  a  series  of  preposterous  comparisons,  based  on  plays 

1  Thucydides,  viii.  53.  ^  Ibid.  viii.  54. 

^Wilamowitz-Moellendorfif,  Aristoteles  und  Afheii,  ii.  p.  343,  "Die  Zeit  der 
Thesmophoriazusen. " 
^Ibid.  p.  .351. 


146     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

on  words,  which  lash  the  general  Charminus,  the  demagogue 
Cleophon  and  others.  Then  comes  this  question :  "As  for 
EubouM,  which  of  last  year's  senators  that  turned  his  duties 
over  to  another  is  better  than  she  ?  "  ^  The  same  scholar  sees 
in  these  words  an  allusion  to  the  senate  of  the  year  413-412, 
which  had,  in  fact,  allowed  itself  to  be  divested  of  its  authority 
in  favor  of  the  "  Probouloi "  who  have  been  mentioned  above.^ 
If  this  were  the  case,  Aristophanes  would  be  retrospectively 
censuring  the  artlessness  or  the  weakness  of  the  democrats. 
But  does  the  text  permit  this  ingenious  interpretation  ?  It 
speaks  of  a  handing  over  of  power  (irapaSovs),  by  no  means  of 
an  abandonment  of  it,  and  this  handing  over  was  done  not  by 
one  regularly  constituted  body  to  another,  but  rather  by  one 
individual  to  another  individual  (irapaSovg  erepo}).  Therefore 
the  allusion  is  simply  to  the  handing  over  of  a  yearly  office, 
by  which  each  retiring  senator  gave  his  place  to  his  successor. 
At  this  juncture  the  retiring  senators  had  completed  their 
term  of  office,  and  could  either  themselves  judge  or  have  others 
judge  how  well  they  had  performed  their  duties.  Did  they 
deserve  to  be  likened  to  Euboule,  that  is,  to  be  characterized 
as  ev^ovXoi  ?  This  is  the  ironical  question  asked  by  the 
coryphaeus,  and  if  he  chooses  the  last  retiring  senate  as  an 
example,  his  only  reason  is  probably  the  desire  to  give  his  joke 
more  aptness  by  making  it  refer  to  a  quite  recent  occurrence. 
Here  again  there  is  nothing  to  show  that  Aristophanes  leaned 
one  way  more  than  another. 

Aside  from  these  scattered  allusions,  there  is  nothing  in  the 
Thesmophoriazusac  that  savors  of  politics.  From  this  we  may, 
to  say  the  least,  conclude  that  Aristophanes  did  not  wish  to 
take  sides  in  the  grave  and  painful  questions  which  were  then 
disturbing  Athens.  And  this  seems  to  show  that  the  revolu- 
tionary endeavors  of  the  oligarchy  did  not  suit  him  any 
better  than  had  the  earlier  policy  of  the  radical  democracy.^ 

1  Thesmoph.  1.  808, 

2  Wilamowitz-Moellendorff,  Aristot.  und  Athen,  ii.  p.  344. 

'Busolt  (Griech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1476,  note  2)  says  that  "the  heavy 
atmosphere  which  precedes  the  storm  is  reflected  in  the  Thei^nophoriazusae" 
I  confess  that  I  do  not  understand  to  what  this  view  can  well  refer. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     147 


VII 

Was  there  any  change  in  Aristophanes'  political  views 
between  the  years  411  and  405,  between  the  Thesmophoriazusae 
and  the  Frogs  ?  The  only  document  by  which  we  are  able 
to  judge  of  this  is  the  comedy  of  the  Frogs  itself,  performed 
at  the  Lenaea  under  the  Archon  Callias,  toward  the  end  of 
January,  405.^  For  its  proper  interpretation,  however,  we 
must  briefly  recall  the  events  of  the  preceding  years. 

If  Aristophanes,  as  it  would  seem,  did  not  share  the 
oligarchical  ardor  of  411,  it  is  quite  probable  that  he  must 
have  been  well  satisfied  with  the  government  of  the  Five 
Thousan:!,  which  in  the  autumn  of  that  year  succeeded  that  of 
the  Four  Hundred.  It  is  well  known  how  Thucydides  praised 
it,  though  it  is  not  his  usual  practice  to  express  approval  or 
blame  in  his  austere  and  sober  chronicle.  He  says :  "  In  its 
earlier  stages,  this  Government  seems  to  me  to  have  been  the 
best  that  Athens  had  known  within  my  memory,  for  it  was 
a  happy  mixture  of  oligarchy  and  democracy.-  This  much/ 
admired  constitution  granted  full  rights  of  citizenship  only  to 
such  as  were  able  to  equip  themselves  (ottoctoi  /cat  ottXo, 
Trape-^ovrm)  and  forbade  pay  for  the  exercise  of  any  office.^ 
In  short,  the  control  of  the  state  was  thus  given  almost  exclu- 
sively to  the  landed  proprietors,  not  the  wealthiest  among 
them,  but  that  conservative  and  moderate  rural  democracy, 
whose  opinions  and  even  illusions  or  somewhat  artless  pre- 
judices Aristophanes  had  never  ceased  to  voice  from  the  very 
beginning  of  his  career. 

This  government  lasted  but  a  short  while.  The  next  year, 
in  410,  and  probably  in  consequence  of  the  destruction  of  the 
Peloponnesian  fleet  by  Alcibiades  at  Cyzicus,  the  reassured 
people  re-established  the  democracy  in  its  previous  form.*  The 
radical   party  again   grew  influential,  and   its    most    striking 

'Argument  i.  at  the  close.  ^ thucydides,  viii.  97.  ^Ibid. 

■*Ed.  Meyer,  Gesch.  des  AUerth.  iv.  §  712-713;  Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.  iii. 
2nd  part,  p.  1538.  "Decree  of  Demophantus,  in  Andocides,"  Mysteries,  96. 
For  the  date  see  Busolt,  loco  cit.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1541,  note  I. 


l^ 


...  y 


148     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

orator  was  Cleophon,  a  manufacturer  of  lyres.  He  was  the 
true  successor  of  Cleon,  and  very  much  like  him  in  his 
violence,  and,  twelve  years  after  his  death,  now  assumed  the 
same  role  which  he  had  played,  and  held  it  to  the  downfall  of 
Athens  in  404.^  At  this  time,  the  passions  that  had  seemed 
dead  revived.  Those  who  had  belonged,  intimately  or  remotely, 
to  the  oligarchy  of  the  Four  Hundred,  those  who  had  served  it, 
or  who  were  thought  to  have  favored  it,  were  accused  hj  eager 
informers.  Many  of  them  were  condemned  to  pay  heavy 
fines,  and  were  either  ruined  or  deprived  of  their  rights  as 
citizens.^  And  thus  precisely  that  state  of  affairs  again  pre- 
vailed which  Aristophanes  had  so  courageously  criticised  at  an 
earlier  time  and  which  he  continued  to  regard  as  odious. 

Outside  of  Athens  everything  was  slowly  tending  toward 
the  final  catastrophe.  Athenian  successes  at  sea,  though  they 
were  sometimes  brilliant  and  unexpected,  were  not  followed 
up,  because  there  no  longer  existed  either  the  firmness  of  will 
or  the  resources  necessary  to  continue  them.  Alcibiades,  on 
his  triumphant  return  to  his  native  land,  in  408,  after  having 
placed  the  Hellespont  once  more  under  the  dominion  of 
Athens,  had  seen  his  forces  dissipated  by  the  clever  policy 
of  Lysander,  backed  by  Cyrus.  Furthermore,  the  defeat  of  his 
lieutenant,  Antiochus,  at  Notium  before  Ephesus,  in  the  spring 
of  407,  had  ruined  his  popularity,  and  at  the  same  time 
destroyed  the  hopes  of  Athens.  Following  upon  this  reverse, 
the  Athenian  fleet  was  forced,  during  the  year  407,  to  split 
up  into  light  squadrons,  in  order  to  conduct  a  campaign  of 
privateering  and  pillage,  which  at  least  assured  the  pay  and 
support  of  her  armament.  In  406,  it  is  true,  Athens  made  a 
great  and  successful  effort  to  succor  Conon  when  he  was 
besieged  at  Methymna,  and  the  fleet  which  she  organized  on 
this  occasion  won  a  brilliant  victory  in  September  of  the  same 
year,  near  the  islands  of  Arginusae,  between  Lesbos  and  the 
coast  of  Asia.  But  even  this  victory  only  put  off  the  catas- 
trophe.    A  few  months  after  this,  Lysander,  entrusted  with 

lEd.  Meyer,  Gesch.  des  Altertli.  iv.  §  713. 

^  One  of  the  most  instructive  documents  on  this  subject  is  the  Oration  for 
Polystrattis,  in  the  collection  of  legal  speeches  attributed  to  Lysias. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     149 

the  task  of  making  good  the  defeat  of  Callicratidas,  had  re- 
organized the  Peloponnesian  fleet,  while  the  Athenian  generals, 
uncertain  about  their  armament,  dared  not  take  the  initiative. 
And  yet  the  Athenian  democracy,  under  the  influence  of 
Cleophon,  was  more  intractable  than  ever.  It  had  rejected 
the  overtures  of  peace  which  Sparta  had  made  after  the  battle 
of  Arginusae,  and,  not  satisfied  with  sacrificing  the  victorious 
generals  to  a  fanatical  superstition  which  certain  politicians 
basely  stirred  up,  it  made  itself  odious  by  the  inhuman 
measures  which  it  decreed  against  those  of  the  enemy  who  had 
been  taken  as  prisoners.^ 

It  is  at  this  juncture,  in  the  autumn  of  406,  that  Aristo- 
phanes must  have  written  his  Frogs. 

The  three  competitors  who  took  part  in  the  comic  com- 
petition at  the  Lenaea  in  January  405  were  Aristophanes,  who 
got  the  first  prize ;  Phrynichus,  who  got  second  place  with  a 
play  entitled  the  Muses ;  and  finally  Plato,  who  only  secured 
the  third  place  with  his  Cleo2Jho7i.  The  title  of  this  last 
comedy,  of  which  we  know  very  little  else,  is  worthy  of  note. 
It  proves  that,  notwithstanding  the  prevailing  exasperation,  a 
poet  could  then,  as  previously,  level  his  attacks  directly  against 
the  real  head  of  the  government,  against  the  inspirer  of  the 
politics  of  the  day ;  and  the  rare  fragments  of  the  Cleophon 
certainly  show  how  insulting  its  contents  were.  It  is  impor- 
tant that  we  take  this  fact  into  consideration,  in  order  to 
appreciate  the  comparative  moderation  of  Aristophanes. 

It  is  not  to  be  denied  that  the  Fror/s  contains  bitter  personal 
attacks  on  the  demagogues ;  the  play,  indeed,  as  a  whole,  has 
a  satirical  tone  that  must  not  be  ignored.  But  these  personal 
attacks  are  scattered — they  are  shafts  hurled  in  passing,  and 
the  satire  in  general  is  aimed  at  the  moral  condition  of  the 
entire  city  and  not  at  its  leaders  or  advisers. 

Let  us  note  first  the  poet's  attitude  toward  Cleophon. 
Twenty  years  earlier  the  play  would  undoubtedly  have  been 
directed  against  him  personally  or  against  his  policy.  In  the 
Frogs  he  is  mentioned  only  casually.  In  the  beginning  of  the 
parabasis  (11.  674-685)  the  chorus  makes  fun  of  his  babbling, 

1  Ed.  Meyer,  Gesch.  des  Alterth.  iv.  §  733. 


150     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

and  of  his  foreign  birth,  which  is  shown  by  his  speech,  and 
prophesies  that  he  will  shortly  be  sentenced,  an  outcome  which 
it  evidently  longs  for  with  its  whole  heart.  At  the  end  of 
the  play,  Aeschylus  is  entrusted  with  the  task  of  ridding  the 
ity  of  him  (1,  1500  et  seq.).  That  is  all.  Other  demagogues, 
Archedemus,  Archinus,  Agyrrhius,  are  incidentally  attacked  in 
satirical  allusions  of  a  similar  kind  (11.  367-368,  416,  588). 
In  another  passage  Cleon,  who  has  been  dead  sixteen  years, 
and  Hyperbolus,  who  has  been  dead  five,  are  humorously 
represented  as  being,  in  Hades,  the  protectors  of  insignificant 
folk.  On  the  whole,  all  this  is  rather  inoffensive.  On  the 
other  hand,  Aristophanes  hurls  some  bitter  shafts  at  Thera- 
menes,  whose  political  leanings  must  nevertheless  have  been 
much  the  same  as  his  own,  but  who,  like  a  coward,  had  thrown 
upon  his  superiors  his  own  responsibility  in  the  affair 
at  Arginusae  (11.  540  and  967-970).  These  passages,  and 
a  few  others  that  are  of  the  same  kind  but  more  obscure,  are 
indications  of  personal  opinions  that  should  be  noted,  but  the 
fact  that  they  are  of  relatively  small  importance  suggests  the 
reflexion  that  Aristophanes  was  at  this  time  less  disposed  than 
formerly  to  regard  this  or  that  politician  as  chief  author  of 
public  misfortunes,  whatever  else  he  may  have  thought  of  him. 
Behind  the  acts  of  individuals  he  descried  more  general  and 
more  deep-seated  causes,  and  these  his  play  sought  to  expose. 

He  no  longer  attacks  even  institutions  or  their  abuses,  as 
he  had  formerly  done  in  the  Knights  or  in  the  Wasps.  At 
most,  we  might  call  attention  to  a  sharp  word  about  the  "  two 
obols,"  and  this  is  more  of  a  joke  than  of  a  criticism  (1.  141).^ 
This  is  a  mere  detail,  without  consequence.  The  underlying 
intention  of  the  play  is  of  quite  a  different  nature. 

It  appears  chiefly  in  the  comparison  between  Aeschylus 
and  Euripides,  which  forms  the  subject  of  the  play.  As  we 
know,  this  comparison,  which  is  entirely  to  the  disadvantage 

^  In  this  the  scholiast  mistakenly  discovers  an  allusion  to  the  salary  of  the 
judges,  with  which  we  have  nothing  to  do  here.  Moreover,  the  poet  merely 
remarks  what  great  power  this  little  sum  has  among  the  dead,  just  as  it  has 
among  the  living.  For  the  two  obols  see  Busolt,  Gnech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part, 
p.  1544.  It  was  a  daily  grant  of  two  obols,  accorded  by  the  state  to  poor 
citizens  ;  this  grant  was  made  in  410  at  Cleophon's  suggestion. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN   WARS     151 

of  Euripides,  is  at  the  same  time  literary  and  moral ;  l)ut  the 
-  moral  part  seems  to  be  of  greater  consequence  to  the  poet 
than  the  literary,  and  precisely  herein  lies  the  novelty  of  his 
point  of  view.  For  a  very  long  time  he  had  shown  himself  an 
emphatic  opponent  of  Euripides ;  he  had  already  made  fun  of 
him  in  the  Acharnians,  the  earliest  of  his  extant  comedies. 
He  continued  to  make  fun  of  him  in  the  Clouds,  the  Peace,  and 
in  the  Thesmophoriazusae,  to  say  nothing  of  the  plays  that 
have  been  lost.  In  all  this  ridicule  it  was  especially  Euripides' 
art,  his  dramatic  effects  that  were  made  fun  of.  His  moral 
influence  was  referred  to  only  incidentally.  Here,  quite  the 
contrary  is  the  case.  From  the  point  of  view  of  art,  the 
comedy  might  make  us  hesitate  between  the  two  poets. 
Although  Aristophanes  appears  to  prefer  Aeschylus,  he  is  not 
above  making  his  audience  laugh  at  his  archaic  style  and  his 
obscure  grandiloquence.  On  the  other  hand,  again,  even 
though  he  ridicules  certain  of  Euripides'  methods,  he  shows, 
by  the  utterances  of  Dionysus,  that  he  recognizes  the  fascina- 
tion he  had  for  people.  But  so  far  as  moral  influence  is 
concerned,  the  comparison  is  as  decidedly  as  possible  in  favor 
of  Aeschylus.  If  we  listen  to  the  comic  poet,  it  would  almost 
seem  as  if  the  victories  of  the  Persian  wars  had  been  of  his 
making,  whereas  the  mournful  state  of  Athenian  affairs  in  405 
must  be  laid  at  Euripides'  door. 

"  Consider,"  says  Aeschylus  to  Dionysus,  "  what  style  of 
men  he  received  from  me  when  he  began  to  write — heroic 
six  foot  fellows,  citizens  who  did  not  shirk  their  duty  (/u>7 
SiaSpacniroXiTa^),  not  mercenary  souls,  deceitful  and  wily,  such 
as  they  are  now."  And  he  reminds  him  of  the  WBrlike_spirit 
which  the  tragedy  of  the  Seven  breathed.  "  Whoever  saw  it 
longed  to  be  a  warrior."  In  this  wise  he  taught  the  Athenians 
how  to  vanquish  their  foes,  by  implanting  in  their  hearts  the 
desire  to  do  noble  deeds  (11.  1026-1027).  He  presented  on 
the  stage  for  their  imitation  heroes  whom  each  of  the 
spectators  strove  to  outdo  at  the  first  call  of  the  trumpet 
(11.  1041-1042).  That  is  what  Athenians  loved  then,  and 
what  they  ought  to  have  kept  on  loving  (1.  1025).  Instead  of 
that,  they  have  lent  their  ears  to  the  seductive  and  corrupting 


v^- 


152    THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

fictions  of  Euripides.  And  he,  by  portraying  to  them  a  race 
that  was  morally  lower,  has  also  lowered  and  impaired  their 
souls  (1.  1062  et  seq.) ;  the  rich  are  no  longer  willing  to 
sacrifice  their  wealth  for  their  country  (11.  1065-1066);  now' 
the  young  think  of  nothing  but  learning  the  art  of  talking — 
they  have  abandoned  the  palaestra  for  the  debauch ;  and  even 
the  sailors,  who  formerly  were  rugged  and  subject  to  discipline, 
have  become  subtle  talkers  who  know  how  to  refute  their 
captains  (11.  1069-1073).  So  the  city  is  overrun  with 
hireling  scribes  and  buffoons,  who  fool  the  people  with  their 
apish  tricks  (11.  1083-1086). 

This  brutal  description  given  by  the  aged  Aeschylus  forms 
the  centre  of  the  play.  There  is  no  doubt  that,  with  due 
allowance  for  comic  exaggeration,  it  expresses  the  poet's  own 
thought.  But  the  harshness  and  the  seriousness  of  these 
reproaches  are  such  as  to  occasion  surprise.  Between  413 
and  404  Athens  appears  to  have  displayed  a  desperate  energy. 
One  might  think  that  she  would  have  been  downcast  after  her 
reverses  in  Sicily.  She  had  neither  fleet  nor  army  left.  And 
yet  she  held  the  foe  at  bay  for  nine  years  after  that.  Neither 
defeat  nor  defection  could  force  her  to  surrender.  On  two 
occasions,  in  408  and  in  406,  she  seemed  to  be  almost  on  the 
point  of  regaining  the  upper  hand,  and  she  maintained  this 
indomitable  resistance  to  the  point  of  utter  exhaustion  and  at 
the  cost  of  the  most  painful  sacrifices.  At  no  time,  perhaps, 
in  her  entire  history,  did  she  display  a  stronger  will  or  a  more 
obstinate  courage. 

Shall  it  be  said,  then,  that  Aristophanes  was  mistaken,  that 
under  the  influence  of  a  prejudice  he  pointed  out  imaginary 
failings  ?  This  is  hardly  credible  of  a  mind  which  had  re- 
peatedly shown  itself  to  be  singularly  perspicacious.  We 
must  be  on  our  guard  against  permitting  ourselves  to  be 
misled  by  appearances. 

Nothing  is  more  striking  in  the  behavior  of  the  Athenians 

at    this    time    than    the    brusque    and,   so    to  speak,  sudden 

character  of  their  decisions.     As  soon  as  they  are  in  imminent 

,  danger  a  sort  of  desperate  exaltation  possesses  them,  and  they 

make  an  extraordinary  effort  which  saves  them  for  the  time  ; 


1 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     153 

but  this  effort  is  never  sustained.  In  the  main,  it  almost 
seems  as  if  they  had  never  had  a  clear  conception  of  the 
conditions  of  success.  Was  success  possible  ?  There  is  room 
for  doubt.  At  all  events,  there  was  no  chance  of  securing  it 
save  on  one  condition :  its  enormous  difficulties  must  first  be 
appreciated,  and  if  an  earnest  attempt  was  to  be  made  to 
•overcome  them,  this  policy  must  be  backed  up  by  continuity 
of  effort  and  of  sacrifice,  which  could  be  secured  only  by  the 
absolute  and  unswerving  devotion  of  every  citizen  to  the 
common  cause.  It  was  just  such  devotion  that  was  lacking. 
In  days  of  exceptional  peril,  those  who  were  most  energetic  or 
most  violent  in  the  assembly,  carried  the  others  with  them, 
partly  through  enthusiasm,  partly  by  intimidation.  In  this 
way  desperate  resolutions  were  taken  which  had  to  be  carried 
c»ut  subsequently,  notwithstanding  regrets  and  attempts  at 
evasion.  These  were,  in  a  manner,  the  convulsions  of  patrio- 
tism. Moreover,  many  private  interests  were  thus  satisfied, 
for  the  prevailing  destitution  led  many  poor  people,  who  were 
driven  to  desperation  by  misery,  to  take  advantage  of  the 
opportunity  to  earn  a  penny  at  the  expense  of  allies  on  whom 
contributions  were  levied  and  of  the  enemy  who  were  pillaged. 
Notwithstanding  all  this,  it  must  be  admitted,  that  true  civic 
spirit  was  degenerating. 

The  testimony  of  Thucydides,  Xenophon  and  Plato  would 
have  to  be  absolutely  rejected,  were  we  disposed  to  deny  the 
extent  to  which  individualism  had  been  developed  in  Greece, 
and  especially  at  Athens,  since  the  beginning  of  the  Pelopon- 
nesian  war.  It  had  at  first  spread  through  the  better  classes, 
under  the  influence  of  the  sophists.  Many  independent  minds, 
in  their  search  for  the  foundations  of  law  and  ethics,  had 
thought  that  they  rested  upon  selfish  interest.  When  they 
sought  to  make  their  principles  harmonize  with  their  discovery, 
they  even  constituted  selfish  interest,  which  was  often  under- 
stood in  a  rather  gross  sense,  their  rule  of  life.  Ideas,  such  as 
these,  when  they  have  once  been  proclaimed,  quickly  spread 
from  class  to  class.  Without  this  quiet  revolution,  which  took 
place  in  the  days  of  Aristophanes,  there  would  be  no  historical 
explanation  for  the  rather  lax  morality  of  the  century  that 


154     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

followed.     Demosthenes  hints  at  it,  the  new  comedy  pictures 

it,  and  it  became  crystallized  in  Epicureanism.     Aristophanes 

witnessed  its  growth,  and  he,  at  least,  vaguely  understood  its 

seriousness    and    the    causes    that    led    to    it.      In   his    eyes, 

Aeschylus  and  Euripides,  as  they  are  represented  in  the  Frogs, 

/  stand  for  the  two  states  of  mind  through  which  Athens  had 

I     passed  successively.     In  this  concise  and  necessarily  exaggerated 

\    comparison,  Euripides  stands  for  restless  Intellectualism,  bent 

1       on  analysis,  incapable,   at   bottom,  of  finding  satisfaction,  but 

undermining  moral  discipline  because  of  its  inability  to  assign 

an  indisputable   reason    for    its    existence,  and    consequently 

giving   free   scope   to  the  egotistical   instincts  which  fret   at 

social  exigencies. 

But,  after  all,  did  the  poet  in  the  Frogs  wage  war  on 
democracy  ?  It  seems  impossible  to  maintain  that  he  did. 
The  tendency  which  he  criticises  was  really  of  aristocratic 
origin.  Little  by  little  it  had  become  universal.  Aristophanes 
criticised  it  freely,  without  discriminating  between  classes ;  but, 
in  fact  the  Athenian  aristocracy  might  have  come  in  for  its 
share  of  his  criticism  quite  as  much  as  the  common  people. 
On  the  other  hand,  when  considered  in  the  light  of  its  con- 
sequences, this  tendency  was  quite  as  much  out  of  keeping 
with  the  democracy  as  with  the  aristocracy,  if  the  rule  of  the 
majority  is  indeed  the  form  of  government  which  can  least  of 
all  get  on  without  the  devotion  of  all  to  the  common  cause. 
The  underlying  spirit  of  the  Frogs,  then,  is  essentially  rather 
ethical  and  social  than,  properly  speaking,  political. 


VIII 

It  is  true  that,  side  by  side  with  this  general  thesis,  the 
same  play  contains  some  more  precise  and  directly  practical 
counsels  of  a  slightly  different  character,  which  finally  demand 
examination. 

First,  then,  there  is  the  famous  parabasis,  which,  according 
to  the  anonymous  author  of  the  argument,  was  so  much 
admired  by  Aristophanes'  contemporaries.     He  informs  us,  on 


THE   SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS     155 

the  testimony  of  Dicaearchus/  that  it  secured  the  play  the 
exceptional  honor  of  a  second  performance.     The  band  of  the 
initiated   address   the  audience  through  their  spokesman,  the 
coryphaeus,  and  their  very  character  imparts  something  serious 
and  religious  to  their  counsels ;   the  poet  chooses  to  make  a 
point  of  this  fact.      Evidently  he  does  not  wish  to  have  his 
thoughts  appear  to  be  the  programme  of  a  party.     He  offers  i 
them   as  a   sort  of  solemn   instruction,  inspired   by  unselfish    Jr 
patriotism,  to  men  who  piously  preserve  their  country's  holiest 
traditions — an  instruction  which  is  even,  as  it  were,  associated  j 
with  the  celebration  of  the  mysteries. 

They  say,  "  It  is  right  that  the  sacred  chorus  {top  Upov 
Xopov)  should  give  the  city  good  counsels  and  wise  instruction. 
In  the  first  place,  we  believe  in  re-establishing  equality 
between  citizens,  and  in  putting  an  end  to  terror  (i^iawcrai 
Tov^  TroXiTug  KCKpeXeiv  Ta  oe/yaara).  And  if  any  have  done 
wrong,  misled  by  the  intrigues  of  Phrynichus,  I  declare  that 
they  should  be  allowed  to  discharge  the  accusations  against 
them  and  atone  for  their  former  mistakes  (alrlav  eKOela-i  Xvcrai 
ra?  irporepoi'  ajuaprla';).'^  The  purport  of  this  first  injunction 
is  clear.  Aristophanes  here  puts  in  a  claim  in  the  name  of  a 
large  class  of  citizens  who  were  at  that  time  treated  as\ 
suspects,^  all  those,  namely,  who  were  suspected  of  having  \ 
favored  the  oligarchy  of  411.  No  charges  were  lodged] 
against  them  on  this  score,  which  was  not  of  a  kind  to 
warrant  a  legal  process  ;  but  they  were  excluded  from  public 
functions,  or  even  summoned  to  court  on  some  pretext,  and 
the  democratic  tribunals  loaded  them  down  with  fines.  And 
so,  incessantly   threatened  with  ruin,  imprisonment  and  dis- 

^  Argument  i.  oirrui  Se  edavfj-affdrj  dia  rrjv  if  avTc^  Trapd^acnp  uiare  Kai  dvediddx^Vt 
oj?  (prjai  ALKaiapxos. 

"^  Froys,  11.  686-690  Alriav  iKdeivai  is  obscure.  This  verb  is  properly  applied 
to  a  ship  which  disembarks  its  passengers  or  its  freight  (Sophocles,  Philoctetes, 
I.  5).  I  believe  that  Aristophanes  compares  suspected  persons,  who  are  under 
I  he  cloud  of  vague  charges  which  they  are  not  able  to  get  rid  of,  to  ships 
which  have  not  received  permission  to  discharge  their  freights. 

'See  orations  20  and  25  of  Lysias  and  Gilbert,  Btitrdge,  p.  353.  I  think, 
as  may  be  gathered  from  the  translation  given  above,  that  Gilbert  has  not 
quite  caught  the  exact  meaning  of  tlie  passage. 


156     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

honor,  without  ever  bemg  able  to  clear  themselves  of  the 
fundamental,  but  unavowed,  grievance  which  weighed  them 
down,  they  endured  a  veritable  reign  of  terror.  It  is  this 
odious  and  lamentable  state  of  affairs,  which  was  well  adapted 
to  perpetuate  enmity  and  to  keep  alive  dissensions  in  the  city, 
that  the  poet  courageously  censures  in  this  passage,  with  a 
moderation  and  a  candor  which  do  him  great  honor.  There 
can  be  no  doubt  that  he  had  friends  in  this  persecuted  class ; 
but  that,  after  all,  is  of  no  great  consequence  for  the  appre- 
ciation of  his  words,  for  he  merely  asks  for  justice  and 
equality.  What  he  claims  lor  them,  is  the  right  to  clear 
themselves,  the  right  once  more  to  become  citizens  like  other 
people.      Unless,  indeed,  we  assume  that  hatred  and  distrust 

must  be  the  moral  temper  of  a  democracy,  it  is  hard  to  deny  ^ 

that  his  advice  was  compatible  with  the  public  weal.  i 

The  coryphaeus  goes  on :  "  In  the  second  place,  I  say  that 
no  man  who  is  a  citizen  of  the  state  should  have  his  civic 
rights  curtailed  (efr  arimov  (pj]/uu  xp^vai  jUiTjSeu  elv  ev  tu 
TTo'Xei).  For  is  not  the  situation  disgraceful  ?  Certain  people 
here,  who  were  formerly  slaves,  are  ranked  among  the 
Plataeans,  because  they  took  part  in  a  single  naval  battle.  I 
approve  of  this  reward,  to  be  sure,  and  have  not  a  word  to 
say  against  it ;  indeed,  it  is  the  only  sensible  thing  you  have 
done.  But  ought  you  not,  after  that,  pardon  a  single  unfor- 
tunate act  of  those  who  have  so  many  times  fought  with  you 
at  sea,  as  their  fathers  have  done  before  them,  and  who  are  of 
your  own  race,  when  they  beg  for  forgiveness  ? "  ^  This 
passage  refers  to  the  citizens  who  had  served  as  hoplites  in 
411,  under  the  Four  Hundred,  and  who  had  then  remained  at 

T^  Athens.  We  know  from  a  statement  of  Andocides  that  they 
had  been  placed  under  a  partial  ctTijULia,  and  had  been  deprived 
of  the  right  of  speaking  in  the  assembly  and  of  being  elected 
into  the  senate.^     What  Aristophanes  asks  for,  therefore,  is 

1  Frogs,  11.  693-699. 

'^Andocides,  Mysteries,  75,  1.  693,  seems  to  me  to  have  been  commonly 
misunderstood,  and  especially  by  Gilbert,  Beitrdge,  pp.  352-354.  Aristophanes 
cannot  ask  that  there  should  no  longer  be  any  S.ri/ioi  at  Athens  ;  for  dn/jLla  was 
frequently  declared  for  causes  in  which  he  had  no  reason  to  take  an  interest. 


^  > 


THE  SICILIAN  AND   DECELEIAN  WARS     157 

the  abolition  of  this  punishment,  for  which,  in  fact,  there  was 

110   possible  justification   after  an   interval  of  six  years,  and 

which   could  only  serve  to  keep  the  memory  of  former  dis-       i     t    if 

sensions  painfully  alive.      Sincere  and  cordial  reconciliation  in     of  <:^^  v^ 

the  presence  of  imminent  danger — that  is  the  essential  feature    o^  ''^'^  "' 

')f   his   programme,  which   he   expresses   at  the  close  of  this     ,^'""^"  ''^ 

exhortation:    "Do  ye  then,  whom  nature  has  made  so  clever,    '  *t>*»i 

allay  your  anger.     Let  us  seek  heartily  to  win  over  all  our 

brothers  by  recognizing  them  as  citizens,  without  restriction, 

as  long  as  they   fight  with   us   on   Athenian  ships.      For   if 

we  go  on  humiliating  them,  if  we  encourage  our  city  in  its 

arrogance    and    senseless    pride,    now    when    we    are    at    the 

mercy  of  the  raging  waves,  I  greatly  fear  that  posterity  will 

condemn  us."  ^ 

The  second  part  of  the  same  parabasis  goes  still  further ;  it 
may  be  regarded  as  constituting  a  regular  claim  in  favor  of  a 
political  party.  I  translate  it  in  full :  "  Many  a  time  we  have 
said  to  ourselves  that  the  city  treated  her  best  educated 
citizens  {rov^  koXov?  re  KayaOov^)  as  she  treats  her  old  coins  in  ^^^^ 
relation  to  her  newly  minted  gold  pieces.  We  no  longer  use 
our  old  coins,  whose  alloy  was  surely  not  bad,  but  which  were 
(juite  the  best  of  all — the  only  ones  that  were  honestly  struck 
and  were  recognized  as  excellent  everywhere,  among  Greeks 
and  barbarians,  and  we  prefer  this  poor  copper,  coined  quite 
recently  and  so  badly  struck.  Just  so  we  treat  with  disdain 
those  of  our  fellow-citizens  whom  we  know  to  be  of  good  stock 
and  conduct,  just  and  cultured  men,  who  were  educated  in  the 
palaestra,  in  the  choruses  and  in  the  service  of  the  Muses.  But 
\ve  make  every  possible  use  of  men  of  bad  alloy,  of  strangers, 
(if  a  race  of  slaves,  worthless  sons  of  worthless  fathers, 
Athenians  of  yesterday,  whom  the  city  formerly  would  never 
have  stooped  to  use  as  expiatory  victims.  Believe  me,  ye 
foolish  people !  Mend  your  ways  and  make  use  once  more  of 
respectable  men.     If  you  succeed,  they  will  bring  you  honor. 

He  demands  something  quite  different :  that  there  should  no  longer  be  any 
cLTiixoi  among  the  citizens  (^i'  ttj  v6\eL),  that  is,  that  it  should  not  be  possible  to 
be  placed  under  partial  anixia  while  at  the  same  time  remaining  a  citizen. 

1  Frogs,  11.  700-705. 

M 


r 


158     THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

If  you  fail,  good  judges  will  at  least  say  of  you  that,  if  you 
had  to  be  shipwrecked,  you  did  not  cling  to  bad  timber  while 
you  were  drowning."  ^ 

For  an  entirely  clear  understanding  of  the  purport  of  these 
words,  we  should  have  to  be  much  better  acquainted  than  we 
are  with  the  details  of  the  domestic  history  of  Athens  at  this 
time.  But,  in  default  of  precise  facts,  there  are  at  least 
probabilities  that  we  must  consider. 

Aristophanes  in  this  passage  reproaches  the  people  for 
systematically  excluding  an  entire  class  of  citizens  from  parti- 
cipation in  public  affairs,  and  that  on  account  of  their  good 
qualities.  Eightly  or  wrongly,  he  alleges  that  the  democracy 
of  405  had  a  preconceived  distrust  of  well-educated  men,  and 
a  sort  of  instinctive  leaning  toward  politicians  of  the  opposite 
kind.  As  for  the  advice  he  gives,  he  does  not  challenge 
institutions,  but^  merely  the  manner  in  which  they  are 
administered.  He  would  have  the  people  lend  a  more  willing 
ear,  in  the  assemblies,  to  men  who  were  attached  to  their 
native  soil  by  solid  family  interests,  by  old  domestic  traditions 
and  inborn  affection,  and  would  have  them  choose  such  men  to 
be  their  generals  or  their  negotiators.  Had  his  purpose  been 
revolutionary,  had  he  conceived  the  secret  plan  of  substituting 
an  oligarchy  for  the  democracy,  it  is  hard  to  believe  that  he 
would  thus  have  brought  it  forward  in  a  versified  speech, 
openly  delivered  in  the  theatre.  His  counsels  could  have  a 
practical  effect  only  on  two  conditions :  in  the  first  place,  they 
would  have  to  respond  to  a  latent  sentiment  that  was  enter- 
tained by  a  large  part  of  his  audience ;  and,  in  the  second 
place,  they  would  haveto  be  such  as  could  be  adopted  without 
too  great  difficulty.  |  We  may,  therefore,  conclude  that,  on  the 
one  hand,  the  facts  which  he  criticises  were  at  least  tacitly 
admitted  to  be  true  by  a  large  part  of  his  audience,  and,  on 
the  other  hand,  that  his  suggestion  contained  nothing  which 
appeared  offensive  to  them  or  shocked  them.  For  all  these 
reasons  I  think  the  passage  just  cited  ought  to  be  interpreted 
with  the  same  simplicity  with  which  it  is  written.  We  ought 
not  to  see  anything  more  in  it  than  the  poet  has  put  into  it. 

^  Frogs,  \l.  718-737. 


THE   SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS    159 

Freely  and  in  merry  mood  he  gives  the  people  good  counsel, 
he  does  his  duty  as  a  conservative  and  friend  of  harmony,  and 
warns  the  democracy  against  an  exclusive  and  intolerant 
temper.  By  speaking  thus,  he  virtually  urged  them  to  avoid 
the  catastrophe  by  which  they  were  to  be  overwhelmed. 


IX 

It  will  be  recalled  that  the  play  ends  with  a  sort  of  political 
consultation.  After  each  of  the  two  rival  poets,  Aeschylus 
and  Euripides,  has  pleaded  his  own  cause  and  has  disparaged 
his  adversary,  Dionysus,  at  a  loss  how  to  decide,  asks  them 
their  opinion  about  the  political  situation  at  Athens. 

The  first  question  concerns  Alcibiades,  who  at  that  time 
stayed  away  from  Athens  of  his  own  free  will  "  In  the 
first  place,"  says  the  god,  "  what  does  each  of  you  think  of 
Alcibiades  ?  For  the  city  is  laboring  hard  to  bring  forth  a 
decision  about  him."  "  But  what  does  she  think  of  him  ? " 
says  Euripides.  "  What  she  thinks  of  him  ? "  replies  Dionysus. 
"  She  longs  for  him,  but  she  hates  him,  and  yet  would  much 
like  to  have  him  back.  But  do  you  tell  us  what  you  propose." 
Thereupon  Euripides  makes  a  severe  reply :  "  I  hate  the 
citizen  who  is  slow  to  serve  his  country  but  quick  to  injure  it, 
full  of  resources  for  himself  but  powerless  to  serve  his  state." 
As  for  Aeschylus,  he  expresses  a  proverbial  thought  in  oracular 
form :  "  It  is  the  wisest  course  not  to  let  a  lion  grow  to 
strength  in  a  state ;  but  if  one  has  let  him  grow,  one  must 
humor  him  "  (Toh  Tpoiroi^  vTrrjperelv)} 

To  what  extent  should  either  of  these  opinions  be 
regarded  as  that  of  the  poet  himself  ?  Euripides,  it  is 
said,  is  his  adversary  and  represents  the  corrupt  ideas  of 
the  day ;  Aristophanes  makes  every  effort  to  render  him 
ridiculous ;  the  severe  opinion  of  Alcibiades  which  he  here  I 
attributes  to  him  must  be  just  the  opposite  of  his  own.  This  I 
is  treating  the  matter  much  too  simply.     In  fact,  Euripides  is 

1  Fror/8,  11.  1422-1433. 


160    THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

very  far  from  talking  nothing  but  nonsense  in  this  play ; 
many  of  his  criticisms  of  Aeschylus  undeniably  contain  a 
measure  of  truth.  This  is  true  also  of  the  opinion  which  he 
expresses  here.  Had  Aristophanes  wished  to  constitute  himself 
an  advocate  of  Alcibiades,  he  would  have  been  very  careful 
not  to  allow  him  to  be  criticised,  in  terms  so  just  and  of  such 
import,  even  by  an  adversary.  He  has  given  us  a  drastic 
picture  of  his  absolute  selfishness,  his  lack  of  patriotism,  his 
vain  and  chimerical  promises,  and  he  has  pictured  them 
without  introducing  any  apologetic  reply  to  destroy  or  diminish 
the  effect  of  the  reproach.  And  so  this  reproach  remains  in 
its  entirety.  Now  Aeschylus,  whom  we  are  willing  to  regard 
as  the  mouthpiece  of  Aristophanes,  nevertheless  advises  his 
fellow-citizens,  in  metaphorical  but  sufficiently  clear  terms,  to 
put  up  with  this  bad  citizen.  This  was  probably  the  poet's 
opinion.  Doubtless  he,  like  many  others,  thought  that  in  the 
prevailing  supreme  danger  Alcibiades  was  the  only  man  who, 
by  his  talent  as  general  and  diplomat,  by  his  courage  tempered 
with  prudence,  in  a  word,  by  his  genius  could  still  save  Athens. 
And  herein  he  probably  was  right.^  We  know  that  the 
decisive  battle  at  Aegospotami  was  lost  because  the  Athenian 
generals  refused  to  listen  to  the  warning  of  Lysander's  clear- 
headed adversary.  If  Alcibiades  had  been  in  command  at 
that  time,  Athens  might  have  saved  her  fleet,  and  perhaps  even 
once  more  have  destroyed  that  of  her  enemy,  and  she  would 
thus  have  been  in  position  to  make  peace  on  honorable  terms, 
assuming  that  she  had  possessed  the  good  sense  to  do  so.  It 
should  also  be  observed  that  Aristophanes,  with  Aeschylus 
for  spokesman,  by  no  means  advised  the  people  to  prostrate 
themselves  before  Alcibiades,  and  to  make  him  their  master. 
At  this  time  Alcibiades  was  neither  an  exile  nor  beyond  the 
pale  of  the  law ;  he  was  under  suspicion,  and,  as  he  was  aware 
of  this  fact,  he  stayed  securely  in  his  Thracian  stronghold.^ 
The  poet  limited  himself  to  suggesting  the  idea  of  entrusting 

^Busolt,  Griech.  Gesch.  iii.  2nd  part,  p.  1579,  "The  deposition  of  Alcibiades 
was  a  mistake  which  essentially  contributed  in  leading  Athens  on  shortly  to 
her  ruin."    Cf.  Thucydides,  vi.  15,  4. 

^Lysias,  Against  Alcibiades,  i.  38.     Ed.  Meyer,  Gesch.  des  Alterth.  iv.  §  723. 


THE   SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS    161 

him   with    the    command    of   the  army  on  legitimate  terms, 
without  subjecting  him  to  too  rigorous  a  moral  test.^ 

The  consultation  is  not  yet  finished.  Dionysus  puts  a 
second  question  to  the  two  rivals :  "  What  measures  of  safety 
have  you  for  the  city  ? "  Euripides  replies  :  "  It  would  be  our 
salvation  to  trust  that  which  to-day  inspires  us  with  distrust, 
and  to  distrust  that  which  inspires  us  with  confidence."  The 
idea,  as  such,  is  not  all  obscure  notwithstanding  its  enigmatical 
form.  Moreover,  at  the  request  of  the  god,  Euripides  expresses 
it  still  more  clearly :  "  If  we  were  to  distrust  the  citizens 
whom  we  now  trust,  and  if  we  were  to  make  use  of  those 
whom  we  do  not  make  use  of,  we  might  possibly  be  saved."  ^ 
Aristophanes  here  merely  repeats  what  he  had  said  before. 
To  distrust  the  regular  demagogues,  Cleophon  and  a  few  others,  1  \ 
to  listen,  on  the  contrary,  to  those  who  were  then  regarded  I  \ 
with  suspicion,  themoderates,  the  old  adherents  of  the  limited 
democracy  of  the  Five  Thousand — herein  he  saw,  if  not  the 
guarantee  of  salvation,  yet  at  least  the  best  chance  of  it.  It 
is  worth  noticing  that  this  excellent  advice  is  given  by 
Euripides,  a  fact  which  supports  the  observations  made  above. 
Aeschylug  goes  on  uttering  oracles :  "  The  city  will  be  saved 
when  the  citizens  shall  consider  the  enemy's  country  as  their 
own  and  their  country  as  that  of  the  enemy — their  ships  as 
their  true  wealth,  and  their  so-called  wealth  a  delusion."  ^  As 
the  scholiast  observes,  these  words,  with  their  intentional 
obscurity,  appear  to  be  nothing  else  than  a  repetition  of  the 
formula  in  which  Pericles'  policy  was  summed  up :  leave  the 
territory  of  Attica  to  the  invader,  but  as  an  offset  devastate 
his  territory  by  constant  raids ;  gain  all  means  of  subsistence 
through  the  fleet,  by  employing  it  either  to  exact  tribute  from 
the  allies  or  to  ensure  the  arrival  of  provisions.  As  for  the 
last  phrase,  "  regard  wealth  as  a  delusion  "  {airoplav  top  Tropov), 
if  it  has  any  meaning  at  all,  it  must  mean  that  Athens  would 
make  a   mistake  were  she   to  rely  upon  her  own  resources 

^  The  popular  assembly  of  408  had  bestowed  a  kind  of  dictatorship  npon  him 

(Xenophon,  Helhnica,  i.  4,  20).     Aristophanes,  at  any  rate,  did  not  demand 

as  much  as  that. 

"^  Frogs,  11.  1443-1448.  »/6id.  11.  1463-1465. 


162    THE   SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS 

once  she  allowed  her  power  at  sea  to  decline.  But  I,  for  my 
part,  should  be  more  inclined  to  believe  that  it  is  simply  an 
empty  antithesis,  intended  to  imitate  an  oracular  formula. 

Should  Aeschylus'  counsels  be  regarded  as  those  of  Aristo- 
phanes' ?  At  any  rate,  there  was  nothing  new  or  personal  in 
them ;  the  chief  criticism  that  can  be  made  of  them  is  that 
they  were  very  hard  to  put  into  practice  at  a  time  when 
Athens  saw  the  confederation  breaking  up  through  the  defec- 
tion of  her  allies,  and  when  she  was  no  longer  sufficiently 
powerful  to  carry  the  war  into  her  enemy's  territory.  Why 
should  we  not  rather  assume  that  it  amused  Aristophanes  to 
allot  to  the  old  poet  a  magniloquent  judgment,  but  one  that 
did  not  apply  to  current  events  ?  He  makes  him  speak,  on 
the  eve  of  Aegospotami,  as  Themistocles  spoke  on  the  day 
after  Salamis,  and,  if  I  am  not  mistaken,  he  indicates  his  real 
thought  in  Dionysus'  observation :  "  Perfect !  But  this  is  the 
sort  of  thing  that  only  the  judge  can  swallow."  This  means : 
"  That  is  very  fine,  but  I  should  be  the  only  one  who  would  care 
for  this  advice.  I  doubt  whether  the  Athenian  people  would 
have  the  desire  or  the  means  to  take  advantage  of  it."  ^  If 
this  view  is  correct,  the  only  serious  part  of  the  consultation 
is  Euripides'  answer.  We  have  seen  that  it  amounts  merely 
1  to  a  protest  against  the  extremists,  quite  in  harmony  with 
Aristophanes'  customary  views. 


X 


Here,  then,  we  have  Aristophanes'  political  attitude  as  it 
manifests  itself  in  405  in  the  Frogs;  we  got  a  glimpse  of  it  in 
414  in  the  Birds,  in  411  in  the  Lysistrata,  and,  up  jfco  a  certain 
point,  in  the  Thesmophoriazusae.  In  its  essential  features  it 
conforms  with  the  attitude  he  had  taken  at  the  time  of  the 

^  Frogs,  1.  1466.  The  interpretation  which  I  adopt  is,  I  believe,  that  of 
the  second  scholiast  ('E7W  ixAvot  6  SiKdfwc  vfuv  Kara  voOv  ravra  Xa/ajSavw  Kai 
dToS^xo/J-ai).  But  he  admits,  like  the  first  scholiast,  that  there  is  another 
meaning  nap'  iirbvoiav.  This  line  would  then  be  a  criticism  of  the  Athenian 
courts,  which  absorbed  all  the  resources  of  the  state.  This  would  be 
admissible  only  if  the  word  xp^y^taTa  were  found  in  the  preceding  sentence. 


THE  SICILIAN  AND  DECELEIAN  WARS    163 

war  of  Archidamus.  His  ideal  does  not  appear  to  have 
changed :  it  is  always  that  of  a  frankly  democratic  city,  but 
one  in  which  the  greatest  influence  would  have  been  in  the 
hands  of  a  moderate  element,  of  the  class  of  the  hoplites  who 
were  able  to  furnish  their  own  equipment  or  of  the  small 
landowners — in  a  word,  of  the  rural  democracy.  But  while 
this  ideal  always  remains  the  same,  it  shows  itself  in  rather 
a  different  way  in  this  period  from  the  preceding.  While  the 
poet  continues  to  fight  the  influential  demagogues,  he  does  not 
attribute  to  any  of  them  the  baneful  importance  which  he 
formerly  attributed  to  Cleon,  nor  does  he  aim  at  any  particular 
reform  in  the  state.  ~What  painfully  engages  his  attention  is 
the  prevailing  state  of  mind,  the  blind  exaltation  which 
possesses  the  people  in  the  assembly,  the  violent  hatred 
bebween  citizens,  the  profound  schism  which  threatens  to 
be3ome  irretrievable.  The  idea  of  harmony,  of  sincere  recon- 
ciliation, of  close  union  with  a  view  to  the  common  good,  is 
what  constantly  inspires  him  and  what  suggests  to  him  some 
of  the  best  passages  he  ever  wrote.  As  we  know,  this  policy 
prevailed  for  a  moment,  but  it  was  after  the  reverse  of 
Aegospotami,  when  Lysander's  fleet  blockaded  Piraeus  and 
Agis'  army,  having  advanced  from  Deceleia,  shut  off  all  roads 
on  land.  It  was  then  that  the  people  at  last  decided  to 
revoke  the  extreme,  vindictive  measures  which  they  had 
maintained  up  to  that  time.^  They  recognized  too  late  what 
harm  they  had  done  themselves.  At  all  events,  on  that  day 
the  author  of  the  Lysistrata  and  of  the  Frogs  was  vindicated. 
He  had  not  possessed  sufficient  influence  to  force  his  passionate 
and  thoughtless  fellow-citizens  into  useful  activity  at  the 
opportune  moment,  but  he  did  have  the  merit  of  discovering 
what  was  .right  and  of  saying  it  frankly  and  in  beautiful 
words. 


^  Decree  of  Patroclides  (Andocides,  Mysteries,  73-79  ;  Xenophon,  Hellmkay 
ii.  2,  §  2) ;  Gilbert,  Beitrcige,  p.  396. 


CHAPTER  V 

LAST  PERIOD 

ECCLESIAZUSAE.    PLUTUS 

The  events  of  the  year  404  and  403 — the  crumbling  of  the 
power  of  Athens,  the  tyranny  of  the  Thirty,  the  restoration  of 
the  democracy — seem  to  have  changed  the  position  of  the 
political  parties  at  Athens  very  profoundly.  Or  rather,  if  o:ie 
gives  the  name  of  party  only  to  a  political  group  organized 
with  a  view  to  a  definite  activity,  there  were  no  longer  any 
parties,  properly  so  called,  m  that  city  after  this  time.  Not 
only  did  a  restoration  of  the  oligarchy  henceforth  appear 
impossible  to  the  very  people  who  would  have  desired  it,  but 
they  did  not  even  think  any  longer  of  seriously  reforming  the 
democracy.  After  the  trials  it  had  victoriously  endured,  it 
had  become  the  only  possible  form  of  government  for  the  city 
of  Athens.  "Whether  people  liked  it  or  not,  there  remained  no 
other  course  than  to  accept  it,  such  as  it  was,  and  to  put  up 
with  it  as  best  they  could.  Henceforward  schemes  for  con- 
stitutional reforms  were  devoid  of  all  practical  influence,  and 
had  no  place  save  in  the  discussions  of  philosophers.  On  the 
stage  they  would  have  appeared  ridiculous,  or  would  not  have 
been  listened  to. 

It  is  not  surprising  that  the  last  plays  of  Aristophanes 
should  reflect  this  state  of  mind.  To  this  period  we  may  refer 
four  of  his  comedies :  the  Ecdesiazusae  and  the  Phdus,  which 
may  still  be  read  in  our  day,  and  the  Aeolosicon  and  the 
Cocalos,  which  have  been  lost.  We  know  that  the  last  two  plays 
were  mythological  parodies.     How  shall  we  define  the  others  ? 


LAST  PERIOD  165 

They  both  treat  of  social  questions, — respectively,  the  organi- 
zation of  the  family  and  the  division  of  wealth,  and  so  it  seems 
that  we  might  properly  call  them  social  comedies.^  And  yet, 
one  consideration  deters  us  from  doing  this.  To  call  them  by 
that  name  virtually  implies  the  idea  of  a  more  or  less  defined 
doctrine.  Now,  do  these  plays  contain  a  doctrine  ?  It  must 
be  admitted  that  there  is  reason  to  doubt  it.  We  search  for 
the  poet's  dominant  idea  behind  his  fanciful  creation  without 
much  assurance  of  finding  it,  so  quickly  does  he  abandon  the 
arguments  which  he  seemed  to  promise  us.  Many  of  the 
scenes  evidently  have  no  other  aim  than  to  amuse  the  audience. 
(3ne  has  the  feeling  that  it  would  be  rather  foolish  to  take 
them  seriously.  And  yet,  other  scenes  throw  a  vivid  light  on 
certain  aspects  of  the  problem  advanced,  they  reveal  the 
interest  the  poet  takes  in  them,  and  make  plain,  in  part  at 
least,  what  he  thinks  about  them.  If,  therefore,  the  name 
social  comedy  appear  too  ambitious  for  this  vague  and  confused, 
nay,  even  contradictory  and  incomplete  style  of  composition, 
let  us,  at  least,  say  that  we  here  see  a  comedy  with  a  social 
tendency,  doubtless  more  imaginative  than  philosophical,  but 
yet  not  devoid  of  a  certain  philosophy. 

Moreover,  of  whatever  kind  the  comedy  is,  our  task  should 
be  to  determine  its  aims  as  closely  as  possible,  and  to  show 
what  relation  they  bear  either  to  the  known  views  of  the 
poet  or  to  the  circumstances  and  the  surroundings  in  which 
they  arose. 


It  is  fairly  certain  that  the  Ecclesiazusae  was  performed  in 
392,  at  the  Lenaea.- 

^For  the  former  of  these  plays  consult  Poehlmann,  Geschichte  des  antiken 
Kommunismua  und  Sozialiamus,  Miinchen,  1901,  ii.  Ch.  i.  section  1,  from 
whom  I  have  borrowed  several  observations.  For  the  whole  question  see 
Auguste  Couat,  Aristophane  et  rancienne  Com6die  attique,  Paris,  1889,  Ch.  v. 

2  We  no  longer  have  the  didascalia  of  the  play.  But  in  line  193  Aristo- 
phanes alludes  to  a  confederation  which  Athens  has  recently  joined ;  the 
scholiast  refers  to  Philochoros,  and  explains  that  the  allusion  is  to  the  alliance, 
concluded  two  years  before,  between  the  "  Lacedaemonians  "  and  the  Boeotians. 
The  word  "Lacedaemonians"  should   evidently  be  emended,   for   the   poet 


166  LAST  PERIOD 

At  the  opening  of  the  play  the  circumstances  have  a  certain 
analogy  with  those  of  the  Lysistrata.  The  women  of  Athens, 
having  made  up  their  minds  that  the  men  are  badly  mis- 
managing the  affairs  of  state,  have  made  a  plot  at  the 
Scirophoria  to  get  control  into  their  own  hands.  At  the  very 
beginning  of  the  play  they  carry  out  their  plan  under  the 
leadership  of  Praxagora.  Disguised  as  men,  they  slip  into 
the  assembly,  occupy  almost  all  the  seats  before  daybreak,  and 
after  having  thus  become  mistresses  of  the  ballot,  they  pass  a 
decree  which  turns  over  the  government  to  them.  "What 
use  are  they  going  to  make  of  it  ?  Praxagora,  their  leader, 
establishes  community  of  goods  and  community  of  women ;  the 
latter  are  to  belong  to  all,  according  to  regulations  which  are 
to  ensure  equality  among  them.  We  expect  to  see  how  the 
consequences  of  this  twofold  decision  work  out.  In  fact  we 
see  only  a  few  of  them  very  vivaciously  pictured,  but  they 
are  more  or  less  in  the  nature  of  special  cases.  A  silly  fellow 
hastens  to  get  rid  of  all  that  he  owns,  in  order  to  obey  the  law  ; 
a  sceptic  is  more  cautious  and  prefers  to  wait.  Both  characters 
are  amusingly  true  to  life.  But  what  is  to  be  the  outcome  of 
their  conduct  ?  We  are  not  told.  The  other  kind  of  com- 
munism is  dealt  with  in  the  same  way,  in  the  form  of  an 
incident :  furious  rivalry  between  an  old  woman  and  a  young 
girl.  The  old  woman  has  the  regulations  in  her  favor,  the 
young  girl  has  youth  in  hers,  and  it  seems  certain  that  the 
regulations  will  not  be  the  stronger ;  but  even  this  outcome  is 
evaded  as  soon  as  it  has  been  suggested.  As  for  other  con-j 
sequences,  which  would  concern  the  family,  the  city,  morality 
— the  comedy  entirely  ignores  them. 

speaks  of  an  alliance  made,  not  against  Athens,  but  by  her.  "Athenians" 
has  therefore  properly  been  substituted  for  ' '  Lacedaemonians. "  The  alliance 
here  referred  to  is  that  of  the  year  395,  concluded  between  Athens,  Thebes, 
Corinth,  and  Argos,  against  the  Lacedaemonian  hegemony.  It  follows  that 
the  play  was  performed  in  the  year  393-392.  On  the  other  hand,  the  state- 
ment is  made  in  two  passages  (11.  18  and  59)  that  the  conspiracy  of  the 
women  was  made  at  the  Scira :  from  this  fact  the  conclusion  has  been  drawn 
that  the  play  was  performed  at  the  Lenaea,  the  first  festival  after  the 
Scira  which  would  admit  of  a  competition  of  comedies ;  but  this  is  not  so 
certain. 


LAST  PERIOD  167 

This  brief  outline  is  sufficient  to  show  how  far  the  play  is 
from  being  a  social  comedy,  in  the  true  sense  of  the  word. 
But  let  us  go  somewhat  more  into  detail. 

It  is  worthy  of  remark,  first  of  all,  that  there  is  no  mention 
whatever  of  communism  in  the  entire  first  part.  When  we 
compare  the  Ecdesiazusae  with  the  Lysistrata  in  this  regard, 
the  difference  is  striking.  In  the  Lysistrata  the  purpose  of  the 
women's  conspiracy  is  promptly  made  clear  (11.  30-40,  50); 
the  object  of  their  plot  is  to  put  an  end  to  the  war.  The 
whole  action  of  the  play,  from  the  very  start,  tends  toward 
ihat  end  only.  In  the  Ecdesiazusae  the  case  is  quite  different. 
The  women  seek,  by  a  ruse,  to  have  a  discretionary  power 
given  them.  But  to  what  use  is  that  power  to  be  put  ?  They 
do  not  seem  to  know  themselves.  It  is  not  before  line  590, 
that  is,  before  the  second  half  of  the  play,  that  Praxagora 
suddenly  reveals  her  plan  of  action :  and  it  is  only  in  the 
last  third  of  the  play  that  we  see  it  applied.  As  a  result  the 
discussion  of  this  plan  of  action  and,  above  all,  the  portrayal 
of  its  effects  are  necessarily  curtailed.  What  is  the  reason  for 
this  curious  structure,  which  forced  the  poet  to  sacrifice  many 
phases  of  his  subject,  and  perhaps  some  of  the  most  comical 
ones  ? 

AVe  discover  the  reason  for  it  when  we  examine  this  first 
part  more  closely.  In  reality,  it  is  of  much  greater  importance 
to  the  author  than  one  would  at  first  be  tempted  to  believe, 
and  it  owes  this  importance  to  the  fact  that  it  is  a  trenchant 
satire  on  contemporary  life.  Later  on  will  follow  fancy  and 
the  representation  in  caricature  of  certain  Utopias,  whose 
nature  we  shall  have  to  determine.  Here  we  are  in  the  midst 
of  Athenian  life,  and  the  men  and  the  events  of  the  day  are 
the  chief  material  of  the  comedy. 

Athens,  which  had  been  so  sorely  tried  in  404,  was  then 
once  more  engaged  in  a  distressing  war  with  Sparta.  With 
Thebes,  Corinth  and  Argos  as  her  allies,  she  had  been 
struggling  for  more  than  two  years  to  rid  herself  of  the 
hegemony  of  her  rival.  The  fortunes  of  war  had  varied. 
After  defeating  Lysander  at  Haliartus,  the  allies  had  been 
defeated  at  Nemea  and  at  Coronea  in  394.     From  that  time 


168  LAST  PERIOD 

on  hostilities  were  prolonged  in  the  neighborhood  of  Corinth 
without  decisive  advantage  to  either  side.  The  alliance  with 
Persia  and  with  King  Evagoras  of  Cyprus,  as  well  as  the  naval 
victory  of  Conon  at  Cnidus,  had  seemed  to  indicate  an 
unexpected  return  of  Athens'  good  fortune.  Thanks  to  the 
king's  subsidies,  she  had  been  enabled  to  rebuild  the  walls  of 
Piraeus  and  the  long  walls ;  she  had  even  built  a  few  new 
ships,  and  she  began  once  more  to  cut  a  figure  in  the  Aegean 
Sea.  Notwithstanding  all  this  her  position  remained  very 
precarious.  The  Peloponnesian  war  had  exhausted  her.  Many 
of  her  rich  citizens  had  grown  poor ;  almost  everybody  suffered 
from  lack  of  means,  and  yet  the  crushing  cost  of  the  war  had 
to  be  met.  The  disbursements  weighed  heavily  on  the  landed 
proprietors  and  on  the  manufacturers :  on  the  other  hand, 
they  constituted  about  the  only  means  of  subsistence  for  the 
mass  of  the  people,  in  the  form  of  salary  or  pay;  and,  as  a 
consequence,  the  latter  were  not  at  all  anxious  for  peace.  In 
order  to  continue  the  war,  they  kept  increasing  forced  con- 
tributions and  confiscations.  This  resulted  in  profound  distress 
and  in  material  as  well  as  moral  discomfort.^  Precisely  such 
is  the  city  that  Aristophanes  presents  to  our  view. 

It  is  governed  in  a  deplorable  manner — that  is  the  essential 
point.  "  When  we  consider  them,  the  decisions  of  the 
assembly,"  says  one  of  the  women,  "  are  as  incoherent  as  those 
of  drunken  men."  ^  And  so  the  conspirators  are  going  to  try 
to  take  the  management  of  affairs  into  their  own  hands,  "  in 
order  that  the  city  may  enjoy  a  bit  of  prosperity.  For  at 
present,"  says  Praxagora,  "  we  are  sailing  with  neither  sails 
nor  oars."^  They  rehearse  the  part  they  are  to  play  in  the 
assembly.  After  various  episodes,  we  see  Praxagora  improvis- 
ing a  model  speech,  by  way  of  setting  an  example.  This  is 
the  principal  episode  of  the  first  part. 

This  whole  speech  is  nothing  but  a  series  of  allusions  to  the 
domestic  and  foreign  policy  of  Athens  which  are  often  rather 

^  The  position  of  Athens  at  this  time  has  been  especially  well  set  forth  by 
Ed.  Meyer  (Gesch.  des  AUerthums,  v.  11.  847-866)  who  follows  Xenophon, 
Diodorus,  Plutarch,  and,  above  all,  Andocides  and  Lysias. 

^  Ecdesiazusae,  11.  137-139.  Ubid.  11.  108-109. 


LAST  PERIOD  169 

unintelligible  to  us.     The  lirst  of  them  are  general.     "  I  see,"  > « 

says  the  orator,  "  that  our  city  has  very  bad  leaders.     If  by 

chance    one   of   them   behaves   himself   for   a   day,   he    turns 

detestable  for  ten.     Do  you  trust  another  ?     He  will  do  even  '  otj- 

worse.     It  is  not  easy  to  give  good  advice  to  those  who  will 

not  accept  it,  to  a  people  like  you,  who  always  distrust  those 

who  wish  to  do  you  a  good  turn,  and  are  always  ready  to  pay 

court  to  those  who  do  not  care  for  you."  ^      It  appears  that,  in 

these  trenchant,  though  obscure,  words,  Aristophanes  doubtless 

wished  to  criticise  Jihe  statesmen  of  the  restored  democracy, 

and  more  particularly  the  incoherency  of  the  people,  their  lack 

of  logical  thought,  their  sudden  changes  of  humor,  all  which, 

to  his  mind,  made  impossible  all  continuity  of  view  and  action. 

He  makes  fun  of  the  zeal  which  the  citizens  display  in  coming 

to  the  assembly  since  the  demagogue  Agyrrhius  has  allotted  a 

daily  payment  of  three  obols  to  each  that  attends.     "  There 

was  a  time  when  we  did  not  hold  assemblies  at  all,  and  in 

those   days   we    thought    Agyrrhius    a    thorough    blackguard. 

Nowadays  we  hold  them,  and  those  who  draw  their  pay  cannot 

find  words  enough  to  praise  him,  while  those   who  get  none 

declare  that  the  penalty  of  death  would  not  be  too  severe  for 

those  who  demand  pay  for  their  attendance."^     It  is  plain  that 

Aristophanes  rather  shares  the   views   of   the  latter.     Those 

assemblies  of  the  poor  and  unemployed,  who  were  attracted  by 

the  three  obols,  did  not  please  him  at  all,  and  we  feel  that  he 

was  very  ready  to  speak  his  mind  about  them  casually  and  in 

a  humorous  way — a  clever  way  of  extenuating  a  satire  which 

nevertheless  retained  its  import. 

Incoherent  at  home  and  equally  incoherent  abroad,  Athens 
was,  for  rather  more  than  two  years,  the  ally  of  three  powerful 
states  ;  but  she  was  not  able  to  profit  even  by  such  an  alliance. 
Divided  against  herself,  she  vacillates  between  two  opinions. 
'  When  we  discussed  the  present  alliance,"  says  Praxagora,  "  it 
was  said  that  the  city  was  lost  if  we  did  not  make  it.  It  was 
made,  and  people  disliked  it ;  the  orator  who  put  it  through 
suddenly  took  to  flight  and  disappeared.  As  for  sending  ships 
to  sea,  the  poor  man  advises  that,  not  the  rich  nor  the  farmery.  -  •  ^j>?^ 
^  Ecdesiazusae,  11.  176-182.  ^Ibid.  11.  183-188.  f-lk  ^-v  i 


170  LAST  PERIOD 

You  hated  the  Corinthians  and  they  you.  Now  they  are  friendly 
to  you.  Do  you  be  friendly  too."'^  The  few  lines  which  follow 
are  unfortunately  corrupt,  and  in  those  which  precede  many 
details  still  vex  the  commentators.  But  their  general  purport, 
at  least,  is  sufficiently  clear.  Praxagora's  criticisms  lead  to 
their  own  logical  conclusion.  The  whole  trouble  arises  from 
the  fact  that  too  many  of  the  citizens  think  of  nothing  but 
getting  money  at  expense  of  the  state,  either  by  multiplying 
meetings  of  the  assembly,  or  by  promoting  war.  In  the  keen- 
ness of  their  private  interests  all  these  famished  people  forget 
the  interests  of  the  state.  The  remedy  will  be  found  in  giving 
the  women  control,  for  they  are  by  nature  endowed  with 
talent  for  administration  and  economy,  and  while  the  men  of 
Athens  are  content  only  when  they  can  introduce  changes 
each  day,  Athenian  women,  on  the  contrary,  remain  thoroughly 
attached  to  custom  and  tradition.  Moreover,  their  sentiments 
and  their  instincts  constitute  the  best  guarantee  of  what  they 
will  do :  "  The  women  will  not  let  their  soldier-sons  perish. 
Who  could  supply  them  with  rations  so  well  as  those  who 
bore  them  ?  To  raise  money,  again,  is  women's  business,  and 
when  once  they  are  in  power,  never  fear  that  anybody  will 
cheat  them :  they  themselves  are  too  well  used  to  cheating. 
Many  other  reasons  I  omit.  But  believe  me,  and  you  shall 
live  in  perfect  happiness  henceforth."^ 

We  now  see  why  Aristophanes  expressed  himself  at  length 
in  this  first  part.  It  seemed  to  him  to  be  the  appropriate 
place  for  such  political  satire  as  he  wished  to  put  into  his 
play.  But  the  very  disposition  he  makes  of  this  satu"e,  in 
relegating  it  to  a  sort  of  prologue  and  m  entrusting  it  to 
women,  clearly  shows  that,  from  this  time  forward,  it  did  not 
count  for  much  in  his  opinion.  He  made  use  of  a  privilege 
l/v^p  that  was  his  by  tradition,  and  he  gave  vent  to  his  displeasure 
by  satirizing  the  things  that  were  going  on  about  him,  but 
he  no  longer  thought  of  vigorously  attacking  some  par- 
ticular statesman  or  some  particular  abuse.  Content  with 
momentarily  being  the  spokesman  of  the  best  citizens  in 
an  airy  and  trenchant  way,  he  doubtless  knew  only  too 
^  Ecclesiaziisae,  11.  193-200.  ^Ibid.  11.  232-240. 


Le11«- 


ixA'^nt' 


LAST  PERIOD  171 

well  how  impotent  comedy  was  to  struggle  against  the  stress 
of  events. 


1^' 


II 


This  introduction  serves  another  useful  purpose.  It  indi- 
cates the  true  character  of  Praxagora's  programme  of  reform. 
The  special  merit  of  this  chimerical  reform  consists  in  the 
fact  that  it  affords  a  strong  and  complete  contrast  to  the 
actual  life  of  the  day.  In  this  anxious  city,  among  these 
embittered  and  distrustful  men,  who  fight  hard  for  their  daily 
l»read,  behold,  the  poet  conjures  up  a  dream  of  communism 
which  is  to  do  away  with  all  competition,  of  an  ample,  easy, 
and  careless  life,  of  an  Utopia  of  universal  good-will ! 

Athens  was  always  fond  of  these  golden  dreams,  so  harm- 
less and  soothing.  Again  and  again,  during  the  misery  of 
the  Peloponnesian  war,  her  poets  had  held  up  to  her  vision 
lands  flowing  with  milk  and  honey.^  Was  it  not  the  proper 
function  of  these  servants  of  Dionysus  to  carry  away  the 
iniagmation  in  their  train,  far  from  suffering  and  misery,  or 
even  to  pour  a  drop  of  joy  into  the  bitter  cup  of  life  ? 
Aristophanes  had  very  often  fulfilled  this  function  in  his 
youth ;  he  continued  to  fulfil  it  as  he  grew  older.  For,  after 
all,  as  life  did  not  grow  better,  it  was  surely  needful  that 
poetry  should  go  on  with  its  beneficent  work  of  amusing 
people.  He,  too,  represents  it  in  this  way.  Let  us  recall  the 
words  spoken  by  the  chorus,  when  Praxagora  is  about  to  make 
her  argument.  "  Now  is  the  time  to  stir  your  sagacious  mind, 
to  rouse  the  power  of  philosophic  thought,  and  help  your 
women- comrades.  This  new  plan  that  you  defend  makes  for  our 
happiness  and  will  adorn  the  people  of  this  state  with  count- 
less blessings  in  their  lives.  Time  it  is  to  show  us  what  you 
can  do,  for  surely  it  is  some  clever  device  our  state  demands. 
But  you  must  invent  something  never  done  nor  proposed  here- 

^  See  Poehlmann,  Geschichte  des  antiken  Kommunismus  und  Sozialiamus, 
ii.  p.  11  et  seq.,  and  Augusta  Couat,  Aristophane  el  Vancienne  com6die 
attique,  pp.   198-200. 


172  LAST  PERIOD 

tofore,  for  our  people  hate  the  old,  stale  things  they  have 
often  seen."^ 

Is  it  possible  to  say  in  a  more  agreeable  and  at  the  same 
time  clearer  manner  that  one  is  about  to  take  flight  for  the 
land  of  fancy  with  the  sole  purpose  of  securing  a  few  happy 
moments  for  the  good  people  ?  Are  we  to  believe  that  these 
fancies  are  meant  to  be  satires  at  the  same  time,  and  that  the 
roguish  poet,  while  entertaining  his  audience,  has  in  mind  to 
make  fun  of  this  or  that  contemporary  philosopher  ?  Are  we 
in  particular  to  admit  that  he  is  about  to  have  a  good  time 
at  the  expense  of  Plato  ?  The  question  is  worth  a  moment's 
study .^  Not  only  had  Plato  not  yet  published  his  BcpuUic 
in  892,  but  the  Academy  did  not  exist.  At  best,  therefore, 
Aristophanes  could  only  have  attacked  theories  which  were  in 
process  of  formulation,  outlined  in  private  conversation,  and 
then  repeated  and  spread  abroad,  unless  indeed,  Plato  later  on 
appropriated  ideas  originated  by  others  and  expressed  either  in 
public  addresses  or  in  writings  that  are  now  lost.^ 

Evidently  this  is  a  possible  hypothesis,  whose  correctness 
we  no  longer  have  the  means  of  precisely  determining ;  all 
that  can  be  said  of  it  is  that  Praxagora's  speeches  do  not  seem 
to  confirm  it. 

In  the  first  place,  the  ideas  she  expresses  are  represented 
by  the  poet  himself  as  being  absolutely  new.*  There  is  not 
the  slightest  allusion  to  a  philosopher  whom  he  might  have 
intended  to  ridicule — very  surprising  discretion  on  the  part 
of  a  man  who  did  not  shrink  from  using  proper  names.  And 
then  these  ideas  themselves  have  not  a  shade  of  philosophy  in 
them.     When   Plato,   in   his  Bepuhlic,  proposes   to    establish 

^  Ecclesiazusae,  11.  571-581. 

2  On  this  subject  see  Zeller,  Phil,  der  Greichen,  ii.  3,  p.  466,  note  1.  I  have 
not  had  a  chance  to  consult  the  more  recent  essay  of  Dietzel,  Zeitschrift  fiir 
Litteratur  und  Geschichte  der  Staatswissenscliaft,  i.  382,  whose  conclusions  are 
of  the  same  negative  character. 

2  Aristotle,  Politics,  ii.  5  and  6,  mentions  two  Utopians,  Phaleas  of  Chalcedon 
and  Hippodamus  of  Miletus,  who  had  both  outlined  schemes  for  communistic 
cities.  This  proves  that  these  ideas  were  discussed  among  the  cultured 
classes  of  the  time  at  least,  if  not  among  the  common  people. 

*  Ecdesiazusae,  11.  578-580  and  583-585. 


LAST  PERIOD  173 

communism  among  the  citizens  of  the  upper  classes,  the 
reason  he  gives  is  the  necessity  of  destroying  individualism 
for  the  benefit  of  social  unity.  Here  we  have  the  earmarks 
of  the  thinker.  Praxagora  is  not  troubled  by  any  such  lofty 
considerations.  She  merely  wishes  to  secure  material  comfort 
for  everybody.  If  she  desires  to  create  community  of  land 
and  money  and  of  property  in  general,  it  is  in  order  to 
establish  a  commonalty  that  is  to  be  administered  by  the 
women  and  in  which  everybody  shall  live  on  equal  terms.^ 
Her  ideas  hardly  go  beyond  food  and  drink — a  conception  as 
simple  as  it  is  material.  The  poet  evidently  is  addressing 
an  audience  in  which  there  are  many  poor  people,  and  he 
ironically  flatters  their  secret  desires  with  the  mad  dream  of 
a  state  of  things  in  which  the  stress  of  poverty  would  no 
longer  be  felt. 

That  it  is  a  dream  appears  also  from  the  very  indifference 
he  displays  to  the  practical  and  insurmountable  difficulties 
which  necessarily  arise.  Who  is  to  feed  this  horde  that  is  to 
depend  on  public  support  ?  Who  is  to  see  to  the  renewal  of 
supplies  ?  The  slaves  (1.  651).  So  there  will  have  to  be  slaves 
iu  order  that  this  republic  may  live !  We  may  let  the  curious 
moral  contradiction  involved  in  this  notion  pass :  it  may  have 
escaped  the  Greeks.  But  we  ought,  at  least,  to  be  told  how 
these  slaves  are  to  be  obtained  when  commerce  has  been  done 
away  with,  and  who  is  to  make  them  work  when  nobody  will 
care  to  toil.  This  question  is  not  even  discussed.  In 
Praxagora's  opinion,  industry  seems  to  reduce  itself  to  the 
making  of  clothes.  Who  is  to  have  charge  of  this  ?  She 
declares  that  it  is  the  women  (1.  654).  Thus  the  entire  social 
fabric  practically  rests  upon  the  goodwill  of  the  slaves  and 
the  supposed  self-denial  of  the  women.  The  latter  are  to 
continue  to  toil  as  in  the  past,  they  are  of  course  to  have 
complete  control  and  surveillance  of  the  servants,  and  in 
addition  to  all  this  they  are  to  administer  the  public  funds. 
They  are  to  do  all  this  of  their  own  free  will  and  in  perfection. 
This  is  the  basis  of  the  system.  We  need  only  glance  at  it, 
in  order  to  see   how  far  Aristophanes  was  from  wishing  to 

^  Ecdesiaztisae,  11.  597-600. 
N 


174  LAST  PERIOD 

outline  a  consistent  and  thoroughly  matured  theory.  The 
programme  that  he  imputes  to  Praxagora  is  one  of  those 
amusing  paradoxes  which  were  regarded  as  part  of  the  stock- 
in-trade  of  ancient  comedy.  The  only  thing  that  is  real  in 
it  is  its  resemblance  to  certain  vague  desires  which  arose  in 
the  imaginations  of  the  poor,  then  as  always,  when  life 
seemed  especially  hard  to  them.  The  poet  takes  pleasure 
in  giving  them  a  certain  consistency,  he  pretends  to  take 
them  seriously,  he  makes  them  real  with  the  full  license  of 
an  imagination  that  laughs  at  all  probability.  In  order  better 
to  play  his  game,  he  gives  this  paradox  the  semblance  of  an 
argument,  and  he  endows  her  who  offers  it  with  all  the 
resources  of  mind  and  language  that  he  possesses.  The 
Athenians,  no  doubt,  laughed  at  it.  We  must  see  to  it  that 
we  are  not  more  naif  than  they  were. 

The  second  part  of  the  programme  is  equally  devoid  of 
philosophy.  Though  Plato's  theory  of  the  community  of 
women  seems  strange  and  profoundly  anti-social  to  us,  it  is  at 
least  based  upon  a  logical  conception.  Convinced  that,  in 
order  to  belong  entirely  to  the  state,  the  citizens  ought  to  have 
neither  affection  nor  selfish  interests,  the  philosopher  did  away 
with  the  family  with  a  view  to  strengthening  society.  For 
Praxagora  this  doing  away  with  the  family  is  merely  an 
incidental  consequence  of  the  community  of  goods.  There 
being  no  money,  nothing  would  remain  for  mankind  but  dis- 
interested love.  Blepyrus  appears  to  fear  that  that  might  not 
be  enough.^  In  order  to  reassure  him,  Praxagora  reveals  the 
second  part  of  her  programme,  the  community  of  women. 
Here,  again,  it  is  merely  a  matter  of  gratifying  desire.  She 
curbs  it,  in  truth,  rather  more  than  she  gratifies  it.  We 
know  how  severe  are  her  regulations.  But  observe  that  these 
regulations  are  entirely  foreign  to  Plato.^     For  Aristophanes, 

^  Ecdesiazusae,  1.  611  et  seq. 

2  The  only  really  striking  coincidence  is  that  of  11.  635-637  with  the  Republic, 
V.  p.  461:  "How,"  asks  Blepyrus,  "shall  each  of  us  recognize  his  own 
children  in  a  life  of  that  kind?"  "Why  not?"  replies  Praxagora,  "the 
children  will  regard  all  the  older  men,  as  measured  by  time,  as  their  fatliers." 
Plato  also  says  this,  but  this  fact  does  not  imply  a  common  source  ;  it  is  clear 
that  the  theory  calls  for  the  objection  and  that  the  objection  calls  for  the  repl3\ 


LAST  PERIOD  175 

on  the  contrary,  they  are  the  chief  thing.  The  sole  reason 
that  can  be  given  for  this  is  that  they  are  eminently  pro- 
ductive of  comical  effects,  so  long  at  least  as  comedy  obeys  no 
laws  of  propriety.  This  entire  part  of  the  plot  is  characterized 
by  merry  and  gross  buffoonery,  and  therein  lies  its  sole  raison 
cVetre.  We  should  not  search  for  satire  in  these  airy  jokes. 
They  never  had  any  other  purpose  than  to  provoke  the 
laughter  of  an  audience  whom  no  indecency  could  shock. 


Ill 

If  this  twofold  programme  of  Praxagora's  is  merely  fanciful, 
the  series  of  scenes  with  which  the  play  ends  should  not  be 
regarded  as  a  refutation,  properly  speaking.  They  are  likewise 
fanciful  conceits,  whose  main  object  is  to  provoke  laughter. 
Whatever  refutation  they  contain  arises  less  from  design  on 
the  part  of  the  poet  than  from  the  inborn  fairness  of  his  mind. 
Wlien  thus  regarded  these  scenes  also  appear  to  have  greater 
justification.  As  a  refutation  they  would  be  strangely  incom- 
plete. As  comical  scenes  they  fully  respond  to  the  intentions 
of  their  author. 

In  our  opinion,  the  best  of  these  scenes  undeniably  is  that 
of  the  two  citizens  who  are  asked  to  bring  their  possessions  to 
the  common  fund.  There  is  nothing  more  amusing,  nor  truer 
to  life,  than  the  contrast  between  their  characters.  The  one, 
entirely  ingenuous,  is  convinced  that  there  is  actually  to  be  a 
division  of  goods,  and  thinks  he  cannot  be  in  too  much  of 
a  hurry  to  collect  his  bits  of  property,  his  few  articles  of 
furniture,  his  scanty  clothes,  lest  he  get  to  the  appointed 
place  too  late.  The  other  knows  what  decrees  amount  to, 
especially  when  they  undertake  to  exact  any  sacrifice  whatever, 
and  so  he  does  not  believe  in  the  division  of  goods.  He  thinks 
also  that  if  it  is  to  take  place,  there  is  nothing  to  be  gained 
by  getting  there  ahead  of  the  others ;  he  has  fully  made  up 
his  mind  to  be  the  last  to  arrive.  But  when  the  herald 
invites  the  citizens  to  dinner,  nobody  is  in  a  greater  hurry 
than  he. 

n2 


176  LAST  PERIOD 

These  scenes  very  vividly  expose  the  chief  impracticability 
of  communism — the  resistance  offered  by  selfish  interest.  They 
also  very  neatly  suggest  the  thought  that  in  every  imaginable 
form  of  society,  indeed  as  long  as  men  exist,  there  will  be 
dupes.  And  yet,  if  this  thought  were  meant  to  serve  as  a 
refutation,  it  would  manifestly  be  too  briefly  expressed  and  not 
sufficiently  carried  to  its  logical  consequence.  It  leaves  us  in 
suspense  and  settles  nothing.  Under  such  circumstances,  the 
poet  ought  to  have  transported  us  to  the  public  square,  into 
the  very  midst  of  the  division  of  goods.  And  there  he  ought 
to  have  shown  us  the  conflict  of  interests,  arising  from  the 
very  measure  which  was  meant  to  reconcile  them.  But  what 
need  had  he  of  a  refutation,  since  he  had  not  put  forward 
any  serious  theory  ?  Praxagora's  mad  paradox,  as  it  unfolded 
itself,  was  its  own  refutation,  or  rather,  it  was  offered  as  a 
witty  conceit  and  nothing  more.  Furthermore,  this  delightful 
scene  is  itself  a  fanciful  conceit,  a  simple  source  of  amusement, 
but  so  much  the  better  a  conceit  because  it  contains  fine 
psychological  truths. 

The  last  scenes  do  not  please  our  modern  taste  as  well :  in 
them  we  see  the  women  quarrelling  about  the  love  of  a  young 
man.  The  grossness,  or  even  repulsiveness  of  these  scenes, 
forbid  our  fully  enjoying  either  the  cleverness  which  abounds 
in  them  or  the  truthfulness  with  which  the  poet  lets  nature 
speak  in  them.  But  what  we  observe  here  is  that  they  do 
not  constitute  a  refutation  of  the  theory  of  free  love,  for  what 
the  poet  shows  us  is  just  the  opposite  of  freedom.  Suppress 
Praxagora's  amusing,  but  absurd  regulations,  and  the  whole 
conception  falls  to  pieces.  It  was,  therefore,  with  a  view  to 
this  funny  conception  that  the  poet  worked  out  her  regula- 
tions, which  were  by  no  means  a  necessary  part  of  Praxagora's 
constitution.  This  very  fact  demonstrates  that,  in  working 
them  out,  he  merely  intended  to  give  full  rein  to  his  rollicking 
spirit,  and  to  gratify  his  listeners'  taste  for  the  most  licentious 
jokes. 

From  all  this  we  gain  a  very  clear  idea  of  the  true 
character  of  the  play,  considered  as  a  whole.  At  the  outset,  a 
political  satire,  but  a  discursive  and  capricious  satire  devoid  of  I 


LAST  PERIOD  177 

;i  well- arranged  plan,  it  subsequently  rushes  headlong  into  a 
series  of  mad  conceits,  which  it  delights  in  prolonging  for  the 
entertainment  of  the  audience.  It  seeks  neither  to  construct 
theories  nor  to  overthrow  them ;  abandoning  itself  to  the 
caprices  of  poetic  imagination,  it  freely  makes  paradoxes, 
which  it  lustily  supports  with  ingenious  and  amusing  bits  of 
sophistry,  and  upon  which  it  founds  an  imaginary  society. 
Finally,  it  chooses  some  of  the  most  laughable  from  among  the 
eonsequences  of  this  revolution,  in  order  to  make  of  them  a 
series  of  uproarious  scenes,  in  the  usual  manner  of  comedy. 
In  a  word,  it  is  a  fairly  incoherent  poetical  structure,  which 
we  must  beware  of  taking  for  the  work  of  a  philosopher  in 
disguise. 

IV 

The  study  we  have  made  of  the  Ecdesiazusae  applies  in 
large  part  to  the  Flutns,  which  was  performed  four  years  later 
in  388.'  This  will  make  it  possible  for  us  to  deal  with  it 
more  briefly. 

The  two  plays,  indeed,  resemble  one  another  in  their  con- 
ception and  in  the  purpose  which  suggested  it.  The  latter 
play  is  no  more  an  argument  than  the  former,  but,  like  the 
former,  it  is  much  more  a  sort  of  poetical  dream,  characterized 
by  an  amusing  fancy  which  affords  an  agreeable  contrast  to 
real  life,  and  which  furnishes  opportunity  for  many  a  satire  on 
its  details. 

The  impoverished  state  of  that  class  of  small  landowners 
to  whom,  as  we  have  seen,  the  poet  was  so  much  attached 
from  the  very  beginning  of  his  career  appears  to  have  sug- 
gested the  idea  of  the  play  to  him.     The  Peloponnesian  war, 

1  Didascalia  to  argument  No.  iv.  In  connection  with  1.  173  one  of  the 
scholiasts  mentions  an  earlier  Plulus,  performed  twenty  years  before,  that  is 
in  409-408;  and  the  scholiast  of  the  Frogs,  1.  1093,  quotes  three  lines  of  this 
earlier  Plutus.  Furthermore,  eight  insignificant  fragments  are  regarded  as 
belonging  to  it ;  they  are  quoted  in  Bekker's  Anecdota  and  in  Pollux  as  coming 
from  the  Piuttis,  and  they  are  not  found  in  the  extant  play.  Comic,  graec. 
fragm.  Kock,  i.  pp.  505-507.  We  know  nothing  more  of  this  comedy,  which 
was  perhaps  very  diSerent  from  the  play  that  we  know  by  the  same  name. 


178  LAST  PERIOD 

especially  in  its  last  years,  had  left  complete  ruin  behind  it. 
It  had  been  necessary,  little  by  little,  by  painful  effort  and 
dint  of  privation  and  labor,  to  accumulate  working  capital 
and  farming  material  again.  The  fifteen  or  sixteen  years 
which  had  passed  since  that  time  had  been  years  of  hard  work 
and  suffering.  Moreover,  the  war  had  begun  again  in  395, 
and,  although  Attica  was  not  invaded  this  time,  the  burdens 
resulting  from  the  war  were  terribly  hard.  They  crushed 
those  poverty-stricken  people,  the  product  of  whose  labor 
found,  at  best,  but  a  poor  market.  Athens  was  deriving  her 
means  of  subsistence  more  and  more  from  foreign  countries. 
Manufacture  and  commerce  were  decidedly  outstripping  agri- 
culture. Wealth  was  passing  into  the  hands  of  manufacturers, 
bankers,  and  shipowners.  It  was  found  also  in  the  hands  of 
merchants  and  intriguers,  of  paid  scribes,  of  unscrupulous 
politicians  who  exacted  an  ever  renewed  tithe  from  all 
fortunes.  This  was  perhaps  the  feature  which  seemed  most 
unendurable  to  countrymen,  who  were  always  toiling  and  who 
were  always  uncertain  what  the  morrow  might  bring  forth. 
They  could  not  but  be  irritated  when  they  compared  their 
honest  and  fruitless  toil  with  the  clever  dodges,  the  equivocal 
and  lucrative  rascality  of  those  bold  men,  who  were  not  held 
in  high  regard,  but  were  feared  or  could  not  be  dispensed  with. 
This  is  the  feeling  from  which  sprang  the  comedy  that  we  are 
now  examining. 

Chremylus  is  the  exact  type  of  these  Athenian  farmers  who 
lead  a  hard  life.  He  sees  that  old  age  is  coming  on  apace, 
and  he  goes  forth  to  consult  the  oracle  of  Apollo,  in  order  to 
learn  what  he  must  do  with  his  son.  Ought  he  to  condemn 
him  to  the  honest  and  wretched  existence  which  he  himself 
has  led  ?  Or  ought  he  to  determine  to  make  a  rascal  of  him 
like  so  many  others,  in  order  that  he  may,  at  least,  become 
rich  ?  The  god  refuses  an  answer,  but  commands  him  to 
follow  the  first  person  he  meets,  and  to  take  him  home  with 
him.  Thus  the  first  scene  opens.  Chremylus  and  his  slave 
doggedly  follow  a  mysterious  person,  who  refuses  to  tell  his 
name  and  who  is  blind  to  boot.  Finally,  overwhelmed  with 
questions  and  even  threatened,  he  admits  that  he  is  Plutus, 


LAST  PERIOD  179 

the  god  of  wealth.  Zeus  had  deprived  him  of  his  eyesight, 
because  he  instinctively  went  straight  toward  just  and  upright 
men,  of  whom  that  god  is  jealous.  Were  he  to  regain  his 
eyesight,  he  would  do  as  he  had  done  before.  Thereupon 
Chremylus  promises  to  restore  his  sight  if  he  will  agree  to 
stay  with  him.  Plutus  is  afraid — afraid  of  Zeus,  afraid  of 
everybody.  But  Chremylus  and  Carion  reassure  him ;  they 
have  as  allies  all  the  people  of  their  deme,  honest  and  poor, 
like  Chremylus  himself.  We  see  them  come  in  reply  to 
Carion's  summons ;  they  form  the  chorus,  and  are  quite  like 
the  leading  character.  After  them  there  comes  a  neighbor, 
Blepsidemus,  attracted  by  the  public  uproar.  At  first  he  is 
suspicious,  but  as  soon  as  he  is  better  informed,  he  is  quite 
willing  to  take  part  in  the  enterprise,  as  well  as  in  its 
profits.  Together  they  proceed  to  escort  Plutus  to  the 
temple  of  Aesculapius,  in  order  that  the  god  may  restore 
his  eyesight. 

All  of  a  sudden  there  appears  an  unexpected  person,  Penia 
(Poverty),  furious  and  terrifying.  Do  they  intend  to  banish 
her  ?  She  screams,  she  threatens ;  and  then  she  attempts  to 
prove  that  she  is  not  what  people  think.  It  is  she,  in  fact, 
who  benefits  mankind,  while  riches  harm  them.  But  her 
arguing  is  in  vain ;  neither  Chremylus  nor  Blepsidemus  allows 
himself  to  be  convinced  by  it,  and  Poverty  finally  withdraws, 
declaring  that  it  will  not  be  long  before  they  call  her  back. 
If  we  omit  from  her  speech  all  that  is  preposterously  para- 
doxical or  mere  matter  for  laughter,  her  argument  amounts 
merely  to  this — that  deprivation  frequently  is  a  spur  to  energy, 
whereas  wealth  may  become  a  source  of  effeminacy. 

However  that  may  be,  Poverty  is  expelled,  at  least  from  the 
homes  of  decent  people.  Carion  tells  us  that  Plutus  has  been 
cured  of  his  blindness,  and  we  see  him  coming  to  stop  with 
Chremylus,  ready  to  heap  benefits  on  him  and  on  his  neighbors. 
The  honest  farming  folk  are  suddenly  made  rich.  Were  the 
play  an  argument  in  favor  of  slender  fortunes,  the  author 
ought  to  have  shown  us  in  this  passage  what  is  lost  by 
becoming  rich.  On  the  contrary  he  appears  to  welcome  this 
outcome  with  satisfaction,  and  merely  seeks  to   entertain  us 


180  LAST  PERIOD 

with  the  spectacle  of  some  unexpected  transformations  that 
take  place  in  the  social  fabric. 

A  varied  array  of  personages  passes  before  our  view.  First, 
a  just  man  who  has  grown  wealthy  and  comes  to  thank  the 
god,  and  explains  to  Chremylus  how  he  had  been  ruined  by 
obliging  ungrateful  people.  Then,  a  sycophant  whose  business 
no  longer  thrives,  and  who  gives  vent  to  his  rage  in  impreca- 
tions. The  cause  of  his  misfortune  is  not  quite  clear ;  we 
may  assume  that,  after  respectable  people  have  grown  rich, 
they  have  no  further  use  for  lawsuits.  But  there  would  still 
remain  disreputable  people  who  had  grown  poor,  and  he  ought 
to  be  satisfied  with  them.  Has  not  the  poet  somewhat  lost 
his  bearings  ?  We  might  be  led  to  think  so,  for  the  scene 
with  the  sycophant  is  not  easy  to  understand,  unless  all  the 
Athenians,  without  discrimination,  have  grown  rich.  At  all 
events,  this  rascal  is  scoffed  at  by  Chremylus,  thrashed  by 
Carion,  and  finally  runs  away,  exclaiming  that  Plutus  means 
to  overthrow  the  democracy. 

After  the  sycophant  there  comes  a  very  aged  woman.  She 
is  rich,  and  has  been  loved  by  a  poor  young  man,  but,  as  he  is 
now  favored  by  Plutus,  he  has  suddenly  changed  his  mind. 
It  is  very  nearly  the  same  situation  as  that  which  we  have 
already  seen  in  the  JEcclesiazusae,  except  that  we  ask  ourselves 
why  Plutus  has  enriched  the  young  man,  and  whether  it  is  on 
account  of  his  good  qualities.  At  best,  the  situation  remains 
obscure  and  uncertain.  The  fourth  to  come  is  Hermes,  hungry 
and  begging.  As  honest  people  have  nothing  left  to  wish  for, 
they  no  longer  offer  sacrifices ;  Olympus  is  suffering  from 
famine.  Hermes  makes  threats  in  the  name  of  Zeus ;  when 
he  sees  that  his  threats  no  longer  frighten  anybody,  he 
changes  his  tone  and  turns  suppliant.  But  what  service  can 
he  render  ?  He  piteously  enumerates  all  his  titles.  Finally, 
he  fortunately  remembers  that  he  is  the  god  of  games  and 
competitions,  and  now  that  honest  people  have  grown  rich 
they  cannot  indulge  in  too  many  festivals,  and  he  will  help 
them  to  celebrate  them.  Carion  accepts  his  help,  and,  to 
initiate  him,  sends  him  to  wash  entrails  at  the  fountain.  The 
last  to  come  is  the  priest  of  Zeus  Soter,  who  is  also  in  great 


LAST  PERIOD  181 

danger  of  dying  of  hunger.  But  how  is  this  ?  Is  not  Plutus 
the  real  Zeus  Soter  now  ?  So  the  priest  shall  be  his  servant. 
Promptly  the  whole  company  leaves  in  procession,  to  conduct 
riutus  solemnly  to  the  Acropolis,  into  the  opisthodomus  of 
Athena's  temple,  where  he  had  ceased  to  dwell  long  ago. 

This  short  summary  shows  clearly  how  far  the  play  is  from 
being  a  serious  argument,  and  from  containing  or  declaring  a 
social  doctrine. 

If  we  seek  to  discover  the  poet's  intentions,  without  indulg- 
ing in  venturesome  hypotheses,  the  following  are  doubtless 
the  least  controvertible.  In  substance,  Aristophanes  protests 
at  first  in  the  words  of  Chremylus,  and  then  in  those  of 
Plutus  himself,  against  the  unfair  distribution  of  wealth  which 
he  saw  prevailing  about  him.  He  is  irritated  at  the  fact  that 
it  falls  by  preference  into  the  hands  of  sycophants,  professional 
orators,  and  intriguers ;  he  deplores  the  hard  lot  of  that  rural 
population  which  had  formerly  been  the  mainstay  of  Attica, 
and  which  appeared  to  him  to  be  the  true  guardian  of  the 
people's  safety.  But  he  no  longer  feels  himself  capable  of 
making  any  suggestions  for  the  cure  of  this  evil.  All  that  he 
can  offer  his  fellow-citizens  is  a  dream,  such  as  he  had  offered 
them  four  years  before — an  avenging  dream,  as  it  were,  which 
gives  respectable  people  the  imaginary  satisfaction,  while  the 
play  lasts,  of  beholding  rascals  derided  and  intriguers  reduced 
to  declaring  that  they  are  famished. 

Such  is  the  chief  purpose.  As  for  Poverty's  argument, 
which  has  misled  very  many  commentators  on  Aristophanes, 
we  have  already  pointed  out  what  should  be  thought  of  it. 
As  a  whole,  it  is  purely  and  simply  an  amusing  paradox,  in 
which  the  poet  enjoys  displaying  the  resources  of  an  ingenious 
mind — a  paradox  which  was  perhaps  borrowed  from  some 
Praise  of  Poverty,  written  by  some  sophist  of  that  day,  and 
which  conformed  to  the  traditions  of  ancient  comedy.  It  is 
true  that  in  nearly  all  the  extant  plays  the  traditional  paradox 
contains  a  bit  of  truth,  or,  what  amounts  to  the  same  thing, 
some  of  the  ideas  that  the  poet  considers  true.  This  applies 
exactly  to  the  present  case.  Aristophanes'  "  Poverty  "  defines 
itself :     it    is    not   destitution,   but   rather   enforced   economy 


182  LAST  PERIOD 

(11.  550-555).  When  this  distinction  is  once  made,  it  is  easy 
for  the  poet  to  show  how  strong  a  stimulant  men  find  in  the 
necessity  of  gaining  a  livelihood,  and  how  all  activity  would 
come  to  an  end  if  they  were  no  longer  obliged  to  provide  for 
their  wants.  But,  to  tell  the  truth,  notwithstanding  all  the 
cleverness  he  displays,  this  is  at  best  nothing  more  than  a 
commonplace  school  demonstration,  without  practical  value. 
For  it  is  only  too  clear  that  the  conception  of  such  universal 
well-being,  and  of  such  complete  gratification  of  all  desires,  is 
absolutely  beyond  the  reach  of  human  possibility.  At  best,  it 
may  be  thought  that  Aristophanes  desired,  by  means  of  some 
of  these  observations,  to  make  his  hard-working  and  poverty- 
striken  fellow-citizens  more  content  with  their  hard  lot,  by 
making  them  appreciate  that  it  was  unavoidable  as  well  as 
that  it  had  its  place  in  the  social  fabric.  If  he  did  have  this 
thought,  he  himself  must  have  felt  that  all  his  arguments 
would  have  little  effect,  and  that,  in  such  matters,  instinct 
would  always  stand  its  ground  against  reflection.  Indeed,  the 
prettiest  phase  of  the  scene  is  precisely  the  very  human 
prejudice  of  the  two  rustics,  which  is  summed  up  in  the 
famous  statement  of  Chremylus  to  his  opponent :  "  Nay,  nay, 
thou  shalt  not  convince  me,  even  though  thou  do  convince  me." 

ov  yap  Trelcrei?,  ovS'  dv  Treia-rji. 

All  this  proves  that  the  social  lesson  of  the  Phdus  amounts 
to  very  little.  As  a  political  satire,  the  play  is  of  little  more 
importance.  One  might  pick  out  a  series  of  epigrams  or  jeers 
directed  against  various  more  or  less  obscure  persons,  such  as 
the  demagogues  Pamphilus  and  Agyrrhius,  or  against  the  man 
whom  he  calls  the  "  needle-seller  "  and  whose  name  we  do  not 
even  know,  or  even  a  whole  scene  referred  to  above,  in  which 
he  gives  vent  to  his  animosity  against  the  sycophants.  But 
there  is  really  nothing  which  would  indicate  a  political 
purpose  that  is  worthy  of  further  remark. 


LAST  PERIOD  183 


These  last  two  plays  of  Aristophanes  are,  therefore,  very  far 
from  manifesting  either  a  renewal  of  his  art  or  a  new  aspect 
of  his  political  attitude.  What  they  do  let  us  surmise, 
however,  is  much  more  a  sort  of  tacit  acceptance  of  a  state 
of  affairs  which  he  did  not  relish,  but  which,  from  this  time 
forward,  it  appeared  to  him  impossible  to  change. 

As  far  as  he  is  concerned,  politics,  properly  so-called, 
reduces  itself  to  epigrams  in  this  last  period  of  his  life.  His 
words  retain  their  candor,  he  levels  keen  shafts  against  those 
who  displease  him,  with  the  same  freedom  as  ever — and  those 
who  displease  him  are  above  all,  now  as  formerly,  the  people's 
favorites,  the  usual  advisers  of  the  democracy — but  he  is 
content  with  attaching  some  insulting  allusion  to  their  name, 
or  with  casting  an  unexpected  gibe  at  them  at  a  convenient 
turn  of  the  dialogue.  He  no  longer  dreams  of  writing  a  play 
against  any  one  of  them,  nor  against  the  causes  or  the  results 
of  their  influence. 

On  the  other  hand,  it  would  not  be  correct  to  say  that  he 
attacked  the  social  theories  which  were  being  formulated 
round  about  him.  We  have  not  found  it  possible  to  regard 
either  the  Ecclesiazusac  or  the  Phttus  as  direct  or  indirect 
refutations  of  doctrines,  which  may  have  taken  form  at  the 
time,  in  the  schools  or  in  a  part  of  Athenian  society.  Both 
these  plays  are  fanciful  inventions,  which  are,  moreover, 
arranged  to  fit  the  situation  of  Athens  at  the  time,  and  are 
replete  with  the  every-day  views  of  the  people.  These 
views  are  pretty  nearly  those  which  he  appears  to  have 
entertained  during  his  whole  life.  They  are  full  of  instinctive 
sympathy  with  the  honest  rustic  folk,  who  preferred  a  life  of 
toil  to  debates  in  the  assembly  or  to  the  lucrative  and 
iujmious  idleness  of  the  courts.  Aristophanes  appears  to  have 
loved  these  people,  the  guardians  of  pure  Athenian  tradition, 
very  sincerely,  to  the  very  end  of  his  life,  and  through 
various  trials  and  revolutions.  Only,  that  in  his  youth  he 
loved   them  not  merely  for  their  good  qualities  but  also  for 


184  LAST  PERIOD 

their  happy  disposition,  for  their  light-heartedness,  their  fond- 
ness for  holidays  and  pleasure,  their  artless  malice,  and  that  he 
hated  those  who  appeared  to  him  to  be  trying  to  change  their 
good  nature.  Later  on,  when  he  saw  them  ruined,  humiliated, 
and  embittered,  there  was  less  joy  in  his  love.  In  the  Lysis- 
trata  and  in  the  Frogs  his  chief  object  is  to  allay  the  hatred 
which  he  feels  is  growing  more  intense,  and  beneath  all  his 
merry  conceits  we  seem  to  see  this  task  cast  a  shadow  of 
sadness  over  him.  The  Ecclesiazusae  and  the  Plutus  reveal 
still  another  phase  of  the  same  feeling — a  secret  desire  to 
escape  from  a  painful  reality,  or,  in  default  of  any  quite 
definite  hope,  to  impart  to  it,  as  far  as  he  may,  something  at 
least  of  the  nature  of  a  dream,  with  the  privilege  of  laughing 
at  it  the  next  moment. 

It  was  Aristophanes'  misfortune  that  events  went  against 
his  natural  tendencies.  Had  Athens  grown  mighty  and 
prosperous  at  the  same  rate  at  which  his  genius  unfolded,  it  is 
likely  that  his  art  would  have  risen  to  heights  which  it  was 
kept  from  attaining.  The  type  of  comedy  which  he  had 
realized  in  his  Knights  and  his  Frogs  lent  itself  to  further 
development.  Let  us  suppose  for  a  moment  that  Pericles  had 
lived  long  enough  to  assure  his  country  of  victory  and  to 
select  his  successor.  Would  not  political  comedy  have  played 
a  brilliant  part  in  this  great  city,  after  it  had  become  the  most 
prominent  in  Greece  and  had  been  obliged  to  adapt  its 
institutions  to  the  new  part  it  was  destined  to  play  ? 

Aristophanes,  who  was  by  no  means  hostile  to  the 
democracy,  but  who  was  so  keenly  alive  to  its  inherent 
dangers,  and  saw  its  shortcomings  so  clearly,  would  have  been 
able  to  employ  his  genius  to  warn  it  and,  to  a  certain  degree, 
to  set  it  right.  His  natural  bent  would,  no  doubt,  have  been 
to  point  out,  with  his  clear  perception  and  his  frank  fearless- 
ness, the  elements  of  anarchy  which  manifested  themselves 
therein,  and  which  destroyed  its  effectiveness.  Directly  or 
indirectly,  he  would  have  recommended  what  might  be  called 
"  ideas  of  government."  And  perhaps  in  this  controversy  he 
would  not  have  been  able  to  free  himself  entirely  from  certain 
prejudices  against  city  life  and  its  necessary  outgrowths.    Very 


LAST  PERIOD  185 

few  men,  as  they  grow  old,  are  able  to  rid  themselves  of  the 
deep-seated  prejudices  of  their  youth.  But  there  was  so  much 
fairness  in  his  views,  regarded  as  a  whole,  that  even  such  part 
of  them  as  were  mistaken  did  not  constitute  too  large  a  factor 
of  error.  On  the  whole,  we  must  regret  that  the  natural 
evolution  of  political  comedy  should  thus  have  been  prematurely 
checked  in  the  hands  of  the  greatest  poet  that  ever  pro- 
duced it. 

Apart  from  this  regret,  what  shall  we  set  down  as  our  final 
idea  of  the  part  Aristophanes  played  in  politics  ? 

The  essential  point  is  not  to  regard  him  as  a  party-man. 
The  substance  of  his  political  attitude  was  rather  a  sentiment, 
in  part  instinctive,  than  a  conviction.  The  chief  basis  of  this 
sentiment  was  a  conception  of  Athenian  character  and  of 
Athenian  society  which  might  have  been  formulated  somewhat 
as  follows:  kindliness  in  manners,  joy  in  freedom  from  restraint, 
ease  of  approach,  attachment  to  ancient  customs,  respect  for  the 
farmer's  work,  preservation  of  the  family  spirit,  keen  and  lively 
affection  for  the  fields,  for  the  rural  deme,  where  life  was  easier 
and  more  wholesome  ;  and,  with  all  this,  great  interest  in  social 
gatherings,  in  celebrations,  in  art  itself,  as  the  spontaneous 
expression  of  either  a  happy  or  a  lofty  ideal ;  and,  on  the  other 
liand,  pronounced  aversion  to  sterile  ambition,  to  unfeeling  and 
malicious  selfishness,  as  well  as  to  purely  intellectual  curiosity, 
whether  legitimate  or  otherwise. 

This  conception  gave  Aristophanes'  patriotism  its  special, 
and  sometimes  aggressive,  character.  He  loved  Athens  in- 
tensely ;  he  hated  those  whom  he  accused  of  corrupting  and 
ruining  her,  as  though  they  were  his  personal  enemies. 
Convinced  that  they  were  spreading  and  fostering  hatred 
among  her  citizens  within  her  walls,  it  was  really  harmony, 
good-will,  and  mutual  confidence  whose  cause  he  defended 
against  their  attacks  with  bitter  vehemence,  and,  it  must  be 
admitted,  without  scruples  or  fairness.  The  more  this  harmony 
was  jeopardized  in  his  eyes,  the  more  resolutely  did  he  come 
to  its  rescue.  The  Lysistrata  and  the  Frogs  bear  testimony  to 
the  great  hold  this  task  had  taken  upon  him  in  the  latter  part 
of  his  life.     In  foreign  affairs,  he  was  no  less  keenly  desirous 


186  LAST  PERIOD 

of  peace  among  the  Greeks.  We  have  no  means  of  determin- 
ing by  what  sacrifices  he  would  have  been  willing  to  attain  it, 
especially  as  he  himself  may  possibly  never  have  been  quite 
clear  about  it.  His  rather  vague  ideal  seems  to  have  been 
that  of  a  fair  settlement  between  Athens  and  her  allies  and  of 
an  agreement  with  Sparta,  based  on  mutual  good-will.  As  he 
was  not  a  statesman,  he  did  not  attempt  to  state  exact  terms, 
but  in  his  heart  he  had  a  very  intense  Hellenic  sentiment,  that 
made  him  alive  to  the  fatal  nature  of  those  fratricidal  wars 
which  paved  the  way  for  the  ruin  of  Greece.  The  mad 
internecine  struggle,  under  the  very  eyes  of  the  enemy  who 
rejoiced  at  it,  appeared  to  him  as  the  worst  of  all  evils,  and  it 
was  in  their  quality  as  advocates  of  the  war  that  Cleon  and 
the  other  demagogues  inspired  him  with  especial  horror. 

These  sentiments,  be  it  well  understood,  were  not  peculiar  to 
Aristophanes.  "We  meet  them  variously  blended  and  in  varying 
degrees  in  many  men  of  that  time,  and,  of  course,  they  were 
the  food  and  substance  of  party  politics.  As  a  consequence, 
when  Aristophanes  gave  expression  to  these  sentiments  in  his 
comedies,  he  necessarily  joined  hands  with  those  who  shared 
them  and  those  who  made  use  of  them.  Thence  arose  certain 
passing  affiliations  which  might  mislead  us,  were  we  not  on  our 
guard.  A  priori  it  must  appear  improbable  that  so  spontaneous, 
so  vigorous,  and  so  original  a  genius  should,  so  to  speak,  have 
lived  on  the  suggestions  of  others.  Such  an  hypothesis  could 
only  be  admitted  if  supported  by  decisive  proofs.  But  not 
only  do  we  lack  such  proofs,  but  the  facts,  when  closely 
examined,  afford  us  evidence  of  quite  the  contrary.  In  each 
of  the  great  poet's  plays  we  have  found,  together  with  a 
personal  conception  of  facts,  a  freely  chosen  purpose,  which 
seems  to  have  sprung  directly  from  current  events  and  from 
his  own  decided  opinions.  And  therefore  he  alone  must  be 
held  responsible  for  his  unfairness  and  for  his  prejudices,  and 
get  credit  for  certain  views  as  truly  large  and  generous  as  they 
are  far-sighted. 


d 


INDEX 


Achamiaiis,  The: 

Aegina,  question  as  to  reference  to, 

8  n.* 
Babylonians  referred   to   in,  40-1 ; 

supposed  reference,  43-4. 
Cleon's    attack     on    Aristophanes 

referred  to  in,  46. 
Date  of,  52. 

Dramatis  personae  of,  54-5. 
Estimate  of,  xvi. 
"Five  talents"  reference  in,  43-4, 

52-3  and  n} 
Idea  of,  xiii,  xv,  54-60,  87. 
Tetralogy,  satirical,  place  in,  109. 
Aegospotami,  xiii,  160,  163. 
Aeolosicon,  164. 

Aeschylus,    estimate    of,    xi ;     popu- 
larity  of,    with   Athenian    rural 
democracy,  7  ;  The  Frogs  as  con- 
cerned with,  150-2,  154,  159-62. 
Agis,  163. 

Agyrrhius,  xiii,  150,  169,  182. 
Alcibiades,   The  Frogs  as  concerned 
with,  159-61;  estimate  of,  159-60; 
otherwise  mentioned,  9  n.^,  116, 
117,    127,    128,    135,    138,    142, 
147. 
Ameipsias,  101. 
Andocides  cited,  156  and  n.^ 
Androeles,  116. 
Antiochus,  148. 
Antiphon,  16,  66  n.,  95. 
Archedemus,  150. 
Archilochus,  118. 
Archinus,  150. 
Arginusae,  xii,  148,  150. 
Aristophanes : 

Career,  chronological  sequence  of : 
Childhood,  9-10  ;  social  surround- 
ings in  early  life,  11,  13;  pro- 
duction of  The  Banqueters  (427), 
30;  of  The  Babylonians  (426), 
35,  39 ;  attacked  by  Cleon,  45-6, 


49-51 ;  production  of  The  Achar- 
nians  (425),  52 ;  collaboration 
with  Eupolis  in  The  Knights.  72 ; 
production  of  The  Knights  (424), 
61  ;  second  suit  brought  by  Cleon, 
49-50,  89-92  and  n. ;  writing  of 
The  Clouds,  93 ;  production  of 
The  Peace  (421),  110;  of  The 
Birds  (414),  115;  of  Lysistrata 
and  of  The  Thesmophoriazusae 
(411),  131,  143;  of  The  Frogs 
(405),  147  ;  of  The  Ecclesiazusae 
(392),  165  ;  of  Plutus  (388),  177. 
Characteristics  of : 

Capricious  playfulness  and  exu- 
berant fancy,  16. 
Dialectical  skill,  xvi. 
Effects  rather  than  causes,  pre- 
occupation with,  34. 
Elusiveness,  xi. 

Frankness  and  fearlessness,  184. 
Gaiety  and  vivacity,  26. 
Hellenic  and  Athenian  sentiment, 

strength  of,  114,  186. 
Originality  and  vigour  of  genius, 

186. 
Patriotism,  26-7,  185. 
Perspicacity,  152,  184. 
Philosophic    bent,    30    and   n.^ ; 

hatred  of  philosophy,  99. 
Rural  pursuits,  familiaritj'  with, 

and  predilection  for,  9-10. 
Spontaneity  of  imagination,   18, 
186. 
Comedies  of  {see  also  their  titles)  : 
Collaboration  in  writing  of,  30, 72. 
Composition  of,  circumstances  of, 

49. 
Number  of,  existing,  ix. 
Personality  of  poet  reproduced  in 

characters  of,  128. 
Production     of,     under     others' 
names,  47-8,  92  n. 


188 


INDEX 


Aristophanes — Comedies  of  : 

Satirical  foundation  in,  erroneous 
view  as  to  necessity  of,  120-1. 
Democracy,  attitude  towards,  57, 

109-10,  163,  177,  181,  183-4. 
Independence  of,  from  party  ties, 
10,  17,  18,  27,  34,  113,  138,  141, 
155,  185,  186. 
Interpretations      of     pixrpose     of, 

various,  xi-xv. 
Naturalization  of,  question  as  to,  8. 
Oligarchical  party,  relations  with, 

15-18,  95-6,  110,  113,  130,  137. 
Parentage  of,  question  as  to,  8. 
Philosophy,    attitude    towards,    30 

and  n.^,  99. 
Political  ideal  of,  163;   later  atti- 
tude towards  politics,  183. 
Aristotle  : 

Constitution  of  Athens  quoted,  23  ; 

cited,  50  n.^,  103  and  jm.S'^ 
Politics  quoted,  87  n.i ;  cited,  103. 
Athenians  : 

Characteristics  of : 

Aristophanes'  view  of,  184,  185. 
Incoherency,  169. 
Individualism,  growth  of,  153-4. 
Thucydides'  definition  of,  25-6. 
Utopian  dreams,  attitude  towards, 
171. 
Local  cults  of,  3,  5. 
Athens : 

Accusations,  bringing  of,  21,  23-4, 
102,  107,  109,  148,  155  and  n.^; 
political  trials  (415),  122. 
Alliances  of : 

Persia   and   Cyprus,   with,    168, 

169. 
Thebes,  Corinth,  and  Argos,  with 
(395),  166  71.,  167,  169. 
Allies  of  : 

Autonomy,   sense  of,   strong   in, 

143. 
Babylonians  as  concerned  with, 

40-2,  61. 
Defections    among    (428-7),    35 ; 

(412),  132-3,  142. 
Policy  towards,  35-9,  142 ;  Aris- 
tophanes'    attitude      towards 
policy,  41. 
Tribute  paid  by — proposed  reduc- 
tion of,  52-3;   increase  of,  62, 
75  vi.2 
Aristocracy    of,     see     Oligarchical 

party. 
Assemblies,  payment  for  attendance 

at,  169. 
City     proper,    conditions     of     life 
among  inhabitants  of,  4. 


Athens : 

Citizenship  of,  90  a7id  n. ;  curtail- 
ment  of   civic   rights  [dn/xla), 
156-7  and  n. 
Demes : 

Institution  of,  4. 
Registry  in  a  deme  not  implying 
residence  there,  9  and  n.^ 
Democracy,  see  that  title. 
Dionysiac  festival,  6  and  n.^,  7. 
Downfall  of  : 

Events  tending  to,  148,  160  and 

n.\  163. 
Political    conditions    subsequent 
to,  164. 
Five  Thousand,  government  of  the, 

147,  161. 
Heliasts  (see  also  sub-heading  Law- 
courts)  : 
Pay  of,  increase  in,  62,  102. 
Status  and  functions  of,  101-2. 
Wasps  as  concerned  with,  104-7. 
Hermae  affair  (415),  121. 
Hetaeries : 

Comedy  not  in  league  with,  17. 
Composition  of,  1.37  and  n.^ 
Platform  of,  68,  103. 
Knights,     position     and     achieve- 
ments of,  70-1. 
Law-courts,  organisation  of,  in  fifth 
century,  xiv,  101-2  ;  suggested 
reforms  of,  103.     {See  also  sub- 
heading  Heliasts. ) 
Leuaean  festival,  6-7. 
Mysteries  affair  (415),  121-2. 
Naucraries,  abolition  of,  4. 
Oligarchical  party,  see  that  title. 
Peloponnesian  War,  see  that  title. 
Persian  alliance  against  (412),  132-3. 
Persian  alliance  with,  168,  169. 
Piraeus,  inhabitants  of : 
Cleon's  relations  with,  24. 
Conditions  of  life  among,  3. 
Political  parties  in,  see  Democracy 

and  Oligarchical  party. 
Politicians,  professional,  moral  per- 
verseness  of,   pilloried  in   The 
Banqueters,  34. 
Probouloi  : 
Allusion  to,  alleged,  in  Thesmo- 

phoriazusae,  146. 
Creation  of,  132. 
Oligarchical  proclivities  of,  137. 
Reverses   and   difficulties   of   (408- 
406),  148;  desperate  courage  in 
faceof  disasters  (413-404),  152-3. 
Sicilian  expedition,  see  that  title. 
Society  of : 

Constituents  of,  12,  15-17. 


I 


INDEX 


189 


Athens — Society  of  : 
Estimate  of,  12. 
Evidence  as  to,  12-13. 
Gossip  rife  in,  13-14,  18. 
Sparta,  wars  with,  xii-xiii,  147-50, 
160,     163,     167-8.       (.S'ee    also 
Peloponnesian  War.) 
Thirty,  tyranny  of  the,  137,  164. 
Trials,  political  (415),  122. 
Autolycus  (Eupolis),  117. 

Bahylonians,  The : 

Callistratus'  production  of,  44,  46-8. 

Date  of,  35,  39. 

Events  during  composition  of,  35-9. 

Idea  of,  42,  61. 

Nature  of,  35,  40. 

Tetralog3%  satirical,  place  in,  109. 
Banqueters,  The: 

Callistratus  responsible  for,  30, 47-8. 

Clouds  compared  with,  94. 

Date  of,  30. 

Idea  and  characters  of,  31-5. 
Baptae  (Eupolis),  117. 
Bekker — Anecdota  cited,  177  n. 
Bemhardy  cited,  126  n. 
Birds,  The: 

Date  of,  115. 

Democracy,  attitude  towards,  124 
and  n." 

Estimates  of,  differences  of  critical 
opinion  in  regard  to,  119-20,  124, 
126  and  n.,  127. 

Imagination  supreme  in,  130. 

Irreligious  spirit  in,  alleged,  128-9. 

Peithetairus,  character  of,  123-5, 
127-8,  130. 

Plot  of,  121,  123-5.  128,  130. 
Browning,  R.,  quoted,  xii. 
Bursian  cited,  120?i.\  127  ti.-* 
Busolt  cited,  5  and  n.^,  20  n^,  53  n.^, 
66  n.,   143  n.^,  147  n.*;   quoted, 
146  n:\  160  7i.i 

Callias  (son  of  Hypponicus),  117. 
Callistratus,     Banqueters    performed 

under  name  of,    30,   47-8 ;    also 

Bahylonians,  44,  46-8  ;   also  Ach- 

arnians,  8. 
Charondas,  laws  of,  103. 
Chios,  defection  of,  from  Athens,  132, 

142. 
Cimon,  15,  19. 
Clazonienae,  defection  of,  from  Athens, 

132. 
Cleisthenes'  reforms,  4,  15. 
Cleon,   career  of,    20-2,    64 ;    on   the 

Mytilenean    affair,    23  nJ,    36-7, 

39 ;  The  Bahylonians  as  concerned 


with,  41-5  ;  affair  of  the  five 
talents,  43,  52-3  and  n.'^ ;  adopts 
punitive  measures  against  Aristo- 
phanes, 45-6,49-51 ;  opposes  peace 
with  Sparta,  54,  63 ;  a  second 
time  chosen  senator  (425),  62 ; 
leads  successful  assault  on  Pylus, 
63-4 ;  The  Knights  as  concerned 
with,  77-83  ;  second  suit  against 
Aristophanes,  xiii,  49-50,  89-92 ; 
chosen  general,  93  ;  The  Wa^s 
as  concerned  with,  101,  104-5 ; 
The  Frogs  as  concerned  with,  150 ; 
death  of,  110;  characteristics  of, 
20,  22,  28  nJ;  insolence,  75; 
policy  and  methods  of,  22-5 ; 
policy  detested,  25,  72 ;  anti- 
democratic doctrine  inspired  by 
opposition  to,  64-5 :  Aristophanes' 
attitude  towards,  xiii,  20,  25,  44, 
87,  91-2,  101,  111-13,  186;  esti- 
mates of,  20n.\  64;  by  Thucy- 
dides,  22 ;  by  Aristotle,  23 ; 
attempted  rehabilitation  of,  xiii. 
Cleonj'mos,  75  and  n.^ 
Cleophon,  xiii,  14:8-50  and  n.,  161. 
Cleophon  (Plato),  149. 
Clouds,  The: 

Aristophanes'  estimate  of,  99-100, 
116. 

Banqueters  compared  with,  94. 

Cleon  referred  to  in,  93. 

Failure  of,  99-101. 

Idea  of,  94. 

Plot  of,  93-4. 

Socrates  as  referred  to  in,  93-5,  129. 

Substituted  passage  in  (?418),  116 
and  n.^ 
Cnidus,  168. 
Cocalos,  164. 

Comedy,  Athenian  (see  also  Aristo- 
plianes — Comedies) : 

Change     in,    after    Peloponnesian 
War,  118. 

Choice  of,  authority  responsible  for, 
19  7iJ,  30,  47. 

Choruses  for,  furnishing  of ,  18, 19;i.^ 

Content  of,  11. 

Form  of,  77  n."^ 

Kinds  of,  118,  120. 

Nature  of,  43. 

"Organ  of  a  partj'"  theor}'  as  to, 

l0  7l.\    19  7t.=* 

Origin  of,  1. 
Popularitj'^  of,  7,  51. 
Production  of,  method  of,  30. 
Specialists  in,  11-12. 
Syracosius'decree  restraining  license 
of,  118-19  andnn. 


190 


INDEX 


Conon,  148,  168. 

Coronea,  167. 

Couat,  Auguste  —  Aristophane  et 
I'ancienne  Comidie  attique,  esti- 
mate of,  x;  cited,  xvi,  15  n.^, 
165  n.^ 

Cratinus,  19,  29,  40,  101,  112. 

Curtius — Greek  History  cited,  116  7k^ 

119  n.  2,  120  n.^ 
Cyzieus,  xiii,  147. 

Deceleia,  fortification  of,  128, 
Delos,  confederacy  of,  139. 
Z)e»ies  (Eupolis),  118  ?i. 
Democracy,  Athenian  : 
Absolutism  of,  106. 
Aristophanes'     attitude     towards, 
109-10,  184.    (See  also  under  sub- 
heading Rural. ) 
2?zVc?s  as  concerned  with,  124  and  w.^ 
Groups  of,  2-4,  19. 
Knights  as  concerned   with,   68-9, 

75-7. 
Oligarchical    view    of,     16,    65-8, 

8H-5. 
Political    condition    of     (422-414), 

116. 
Restoration  of  government  of  (410), 

147. 
Rural : 

Aristophanes'  attitude   towards, 

57,  163,  177,  181,  183-4. 
Characteristics   of,    94 ;     conser- 
vatism, 4-5. 
Conditions  of  life  among,  2-3,  5-6. 
Oligarchy,  relations  with,  5n.^ 
Peace  with  Sparta,  attitude  to- 
wards, 111. 
Political     assemblies,     aloofness 

from,  6. 
Political  organisation,  lack  of,  10. 
Urban : 
City   proper,    conditions  of   life 

among  inhabitants  of,  4. 
Piraeus,  at : 

Cleon's  relations  with,  24. 
Conditions  of  life  among,  3. 
Demosthenes  (Athenian  general),  62- 

3,  77. 
Demosthenes  (orator)  cited,  154. 
Demostratus,  116. 
Denis,  J. — La  Comidie  grecque  cited, 

120  ?m.,  126  n. 
Dicaearchus  cited,  155  and  n.^ 
Didymus  cited,  135. 

Diodotus  (son  of  Eucrates),  36-7,  39, 

45. 
Dionysiac  festival,  6  andn.^,  7. 
Dittenberger  cited,  41  ?i.* 


Ecclesiazusae : 

Character  of,  165,  170-7,  183. 
Date  of,  165. 

Lysistrata  compared  with,  166-7. 
Plato  in  relation  to,  172,  Hi:  and n.^ 
Plot  of,  166,  168-76. 
Ephialtes,  reforms  of,  15. 
Epicureanism,  154. 
Erythraea,  defection  of,  from  Athens, 

132. 
Eupolis,    Aristophanes'  collaboration 
with,  72,  76;    plays   by,   92  n., 
118  71.  ;    bitterness  of  satire  by, 
116  and  n.^,  117. 
Euripides : 

Frogs  as   concerned    with,    150-2, 

154,  159-62. 
Orestes  quoted,  5. 
Popularity  of,   xiv ;    unpopularity 

with  rural  democracy,  7. 
Suppliants  quoted,  4  n. 
Thesmophoriazusae    as     concerned 

with,  143-4. 
mentioned,  xi. 

Flatterers  (Eupolis),  117. 
Fritzsehe  cited,  42  Jt." 
Frogs,  The: 

Alcibiades  alluded  to  in,  159-61. 

Chorus  of,  155. 

Date  of,  147. 

Euripides  and  Aeschylus   as  por- 
trayed in,  150-2,  154,  159-62. 

Object  of,  184,  185. 

Parabasis  of,  154-5  and  n.^ 

Practical  counsels  of,  154-9. 

Tone  of,  148. 

Gilbert,   G. — Beitrage  cited,    19  n.^, 
118  71.,  120  71.S  135  71.2,  155  71.3, 

156  71.2 

Gorgias,  128,  130. 
Grote  cited,  xii. 

Haliartus,  167. 
Harpocration  cited,  50  nn. 
Hellenic  sentiment,  138-9,  163,  186. 
Heracleides  Pontius  cited,  20  ?i.* 
Hermippus,    40,    112 ;    bitterness   of 

satire  by,  \\%andn.^ ;  quoted,  21. 
Hermit  (Phrynichus),  118,  119,  122. 
Herodotus  quoted,  65. 
Hyperbolus,  xiii,  75,  116  and  n.^,  117, 

150. 
Hyperhohis  (V\a,to),  \\%n. 

Idomeneus  cited,  21 7i.* 
Isocrates  cited,  6  n.^ 


INDEX 


191 


Knights,  The: 

Chorus  of,  70-5. 

Date  of,  61. 

Dramatis  personae  of,  76-7,  82-7. 

Estimate  of,  62. 

Idea  of,  61. 

Opening  incident  of,  122. 

Plot  and  action  of,   69,   73-4,  76, 
78-86. 

Political  reforms  sketched  in,  86-7. 

Prize  allotted  to,  88. 

Second  parabasis  of,  72,  75. 

Tetralogy,  satirical,  place  in,  109. 
Kock,  K.,  cited,  117  ».S  126?!.,  177  ?^. 
Koechly  cited,  124. 

Lamachus,  54. 

Lenaean  festival,  6-7. 

Lesbos,   secessions   of,   from  Athens, 

35,  133,  142. 
Lysander,  xiii,  148,  163,  167. 
Lysias  cited,  148  n.^ 
lyysistrata : 
Date  of,  131. 
Dramatis   personae    of,    134,    137, 

1.39-40. 
Ecdesiazusae  compared  with,  166-7. 
Estimate  of,  xvi. 
Events  during  composition  of,  131-3, 

141. 
Idea  of,  133-4 ;  pervading  spirit  of 
fraternity,    138,   141,  143;    ques- 
tion   as    to    appropriateness    of 
peace  advocacy,  142-3. 
Object  of,  xiii,  184,  185. 
Peace  compared  with,  139. 
Plot  of,  134-8,  140-1. 

Maricas  (Eupolis),  116?i.S  117. 
Mazon,  P. — Essai  sur  la  composition 

des  comedies  d' Aristophane  cited, 

73  nJ 
Merry,  W.  W. ,  cited,  46  n.^ 
Meyer,  Ed.,  cited,  168  ?i.' 
Mifetus,  defection  of,   from  Athens, 

132,  142. 
Muses  (Phrynichus),  148. 
Mytileneans,  affair  of  the,  23  n.^,  35-9. 

Nemea,  167. 

Nicias,  success  of,  at  Pylus  and 
Sphacteria,  63  ;  position  of,  after 
Cleon's  death,  110,  116;  concludes 
peace  with  Sparta,  110;  reports 
on  Sicilian  expedition,  127;  Birds 
as  concerned  with,  130;  other- 
wise mentioned,  16,  19,  71. 

Xotium,  148. 


Oligarchical  party,  Athenian  : 

Aristophanes'  attitude  towards,  and 

relations  with,  15-18,  95-6,  110, 

113,  130,  137. 
Birds  as  concerned  with,  130. 
Cimon's  leadership  of,  15. 
Constitution  of,  14. 
Democracy,   attitude  towards,    16, 

65-8,  83-5 ;   relations  with  rural 

democracy,  5  and  n.^ 
Four  Hundred,  government  of,  147, 

148,  155-7. 
Hetairies  composed  of,  137. 
Individualism      originating     with, 

153-4. 
Pamphleteering  by,  16. 
Political  power,  attitude  towards, 

96  ;  activities  after  Cleon's  death 

(422-414),  116^7,  130. 
Prohouloi  of,  137. 
Revolution  by,  137. 
Sophistry,  attitude  towards,  94-6. 
Thirty,  tyranny  of  the,  137,  164. 
Orion  quoted,  31  n.'^ 

Pamphilus,  182. 
Patroclides,  Decree  of,  163  n. 
Peace,  The: 

Date  of,  WO  and  n? 
Hellenic  sentiment  in,  112,  139. 
Lysistrata  compared  with,  139. 
Object  of,  xiii. 
Plot  of,  111. 
Peisander,  xiii,  131,  135-6,  138. 
Peisistratus,  reforms  of,  4. 
j3^eloponnesian  War : 

Acharnians     as     concerned     with, 

56-60. 
Advocates  of —Athenian  war  party, 

25,  54,  57,  63. 
Aristophanes'  attitude  towards,  56, 

59,  109,  111,  112. 
Causes  of,  deep-seated,  59-60. 
Conclusion  of,  110  and  n."^.  111. 
Effects  of,  112-13,  168,  177-8. 
Intellectual  intercourse  during,  139. 
Pericles,   policy  of,   161  ;   democratic 
reforms  of,  15  ;  law  of,  regulating 
comedy  (440),  51  ;  opposition  to, 
towards  end  of  his  life,   14,  21  ; 
slanders     against,    14     and     n.  ; 
comedians' attacks  on,  112;  death 
of,   22 ;    estimate  of,   by  Thucy- 
dides,  23  ;  Acharnians  aimed  at, 
57-8,  109 ;  otherwise  mentioned, 
2,  71. 
Pheidias,  14,  71. 
Philip,  130. 
Philippus  (father  of  Aristophanes),  9. 


192 


INDEX 


Phrynichus,  118,  119,  122,  135,  149. 
Plato  (philosopher) : 

Ecclesiazusae  in  relation   to,    172, 

174  and  n.^ 
Works    of,    cited,    153 ;     Apology 
quoted,  95  n.  ;  cited,  97  nn.,  100  ; 
Symposium  cited,  13,  98. 
Plato  (playwright),  118  «.,  149. 
Plutarch — Pericles     quoted,      14  ».  ; 

cited,  15-16,  21 7m. 2. 4 
Pluttis  (409-8),  177  n. 
Plutus  (388) : 

Character  of,  165,  177,  183. 

Date  of,  177. 

Idea  of,  181-2,  184. 

Plot  and  dramatis  personae  of,  178- 

81. 
Poverty's  argument  in,  179,  181-2. 
Poehlmann  cited,  165  ?i.^  171  ti. 
Polemarchus,  41. 

Political  parties  in  Athens,  see  Demo- 
cracy and  Oligarchical  party. 
Politicians,     professional     Athenian, 

perverseness  of,  34. 
Pseudo-Xenophon  —  Polity  of  the 
Athenians  cited,  16,  66-8,  85, 
105-6;  quoted,  50  7i.i,  102-3; 
estimate  of,  66  n.,  67. 
Pylus,  occupation,  defence,  and  storm 
of,  62-4. 

Samoa,  133,  135. 

Sicilian    expedition,    xvi ;    Athenian 
attitude  towards  (415),  127 ;  (413), 
131;  (411),  142. 
Socrates  : 

Aristophanes'    acquaintance    with, 
xvi ;  his  attitude  towards,  98-9  ; 
his   attack   on,    in    The    Clouds, 
93-4;  harmlessnessof  attack,'xiv. 
Popular  attitude  towards,  97-100. 
Teaching  of,  96-7. 
Xenophon's  references  to,  12-13. 
Solon,   achievements  of   laws  of,  4  ; 
democracy   of,    accepted   by  oli- 
garchy, 15. 
Sophists : 

Aristocratic  patronage  of,  95-6. 
Clouds  attack  on,  94. 
Position  of,  unaffected  by  Aristo- 
phanes, xiv. 
Sophocles,  7. 


Sparta  : 

Athenian  wars  with,  xii-xiii,  147- 
50,    160,    163,    167-8.      (^-ee  also 
Peloponnesian  War. ) 
Persian  alliance  with  (412),  133. 
Sphacteria,  blockade  of,  62-3. 
Suidas  quoted,  31  ?i.^ 
Syracosius,  118-19  a7id  nn. 

Telecleides,  19,  40,  112. 
Theogeues  cited,  9  n. 
Theognis  quoted,  65  and  n.^ 
Theophrastus  cited,  21  n.* 
Theopompus  cited,  20,  52-3. 
Theramenes,  95,  116,  150. 
Thesmophoriazusae  : 
Date  of,  131,  143. 
Idea  of,  143-4. 
Medes,  allusion  to,  144-5. 
Prohoidoi,  allusion  to,  146. 
Thucydides : 

Cited— on  Sicilian  expedition,  xvi, 
127  ;  on  Cleon,  22 ;  on  Athenian 
character  and  temperament,  25-6 ; 
on  Athenian  individualism,  153  ; 
on  Mytilenean  affair,  36  and  nn. 
Quoted — on  habits  of  Athenian 
rural  democracy,  2-3 ;  on  the 
peace  with  Sparta,  110;  onHermae 
and  Mysteries  afifairs,  121  ;  on 
Sicilian  expedition,  132  ?i.^ ;  on 
government  of  the  Five  Thousand, 
147. 
Thucydides  (son  of  Melesias),  14,  15, 

21  71.2 

van  Leeuwen,  J.,  cited,  92  ti.,  l(K)7i. 

Wasps,  The: 
Cleon  as  referred  to  in,  91,   101, 

104-5. 
Date  of,  101. 
Idea  of,  101,  109. 
Plot  of,  104-8. 
Wilamowitz-Moellendorf — Aristoteles 
und  Athen  cited,  145  and  n.^ 

Xenophon,  works  of,  cited,  153 ; 
Memorabilia,  12-13,  97  ;  Oecono- 
micus,  12-13  ;  Symposium,  12,  98, 
102  ;  Hellenica,  161  n.^  [See  also 
Pseudo-Xenophon. ) 


OLA8OOW  :    PBINTKB   AT  THE    UNIVERSITY    PRESS  BY  ROBERT   MACLEHOSK    AND  CO.    LTD. 

Q   3 


pll>ll-»ll^« 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 


UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY 

1 

PA    Croiset,  Maurice 

3879    Aristophanes  and  the 

C7    political  parties  at  Athens 

cop.  2