Skip to main content

Full text of "Aristotelous peri psuxes = Aristotle on the vital principle"

See other formats


Ex  Libris 
C.  K.  OGDEN    I 


QUOTCUNQUE     LIBROS     JUDEX     UNUM     JUDICEM    LEGO. 


JOSEPH   RIX,    M.D. 

ST.   NEOT'S, 


HUNTINGDONSHIRE. 


Cambri&ge : 
at  tfje  aSntoetsitg 

FOR   MACMILLAN   &   Co. 

lonOon:  D.  NUTT. 

©Ifort  :  J.  H.  PARKER. 

temnfiurflf) :  EDMONSTON  AND  DOUGLAS. 

Sutlln :  HODGES  AND  SMITH. 

©lasgoto:  JAMES  MACLEHOSE. 


I fBKAKY 
OF  CAUfOMW 

.-0  YS 


IIEPI    *YXH2. 
ARISTOTLE 

ON    THE    VITAL    PRINCIPLE. 


Crauslateb  from  %  original 


WITH   NOTES   BY 


CHARLES  COLLIER,  M.D.,  F.R.S. 

FELLOW  OF  THE  ROYAL  COLLEGE  OF  PHYSICIANS, 
AND  HONORARY  FELLOW  OF  THE  ROYAL  COLLEGE  OF  SURGEONS. 


ira'Aw  iSia  nev  nva  TOU  AoyncoC  <f>ri(rt  TTJ?  </o;x^S  iftidr;,  ISia 
Se  TOV  erv^i^vovs  xal  a'Adyou  tlvai,  piTrrafdfiei'OS  eirl  mivra  KOJ.  )//r)Aa- 

ifiiavTi  TrpotreoiKois  ras  Sia<]iopds. 

HKovTcipxov  Acii/rara  Trepi  i 


MACMILLAN   &    CO. 

LONDON:   D.  NTJTT. 

1855. 


PREFACE. 


HAVING,  after  careful  study  of  this  Treatise,  been  led 
to  the  conclusion  that  Aristotle's  object,  in  its  com- 
position, was  to  put  before  the  world  his  own  opi- 
nions as  well  as  those  of  former  and  contemporaneous 
writers  upon  the  Vital  Principle,  I  have  been  induced 
to  undertake  a  translation  of  it,  in  order  to  give  the 
general  reader  the  theories,  hypotheses,  and  opinions 
which  prevailed,  at  that  early  period  of  natural  and 
physiological  knowledge,  upon  life  and  its  manifes- 
tations. The  Treatise,  indeed,  records  all  the  pre- 
vailing opinions  upon  living  beings  and  sentient 
properties,  which  lie  scattered  through  Aristotle's 
other  physiological  writings;  and  it  displays,  per- 
haps more  than  any  other  of  his  works,  the  extent 
of  his  knowledge,  and  the  perspicacity  of  his  intel- 
lect. Should  it,  however,  be  questioned  whether  a 
work,  composed  at  a  time  when  the  special  sciences 
pertaining  to  its  subject  were  yet  in  their  infancy, 
can  be  now  of  any  value,  it  might  be  answered  that, 
irrespective  of  any  positive  result,  an  interest  must 
ever  be  taken  in  the  investigation,  truthfully  con- 
ducted, of  nature's  operations;  and  that  this,  brief 


1G76134 


VI  PREFACE. 

as  it  is,  comprises  many  of  the  dogmata,  of  an  other- 
wise enlightened  age,  upon  the  more  abstruse  topics 
of  natural  philosophy  and  physiology. 

It  is  scarcely  necessary  to  observe,  that  several 
versions  of  this  Treatise  are  extant,  but  as  they  have 
been  written  under  an  impression  that  its  design  is 
rather  psychological  than  physiological,  this  misap- 
prehension has  tended  to  vitiate,  or  render  unintelli- 
gible what  otherwise,  as  literary  productions,  might 
have  done  justice  to  the  original.  Some  of  the 
translators,  besides,  seem  to  have  been  but  imper- 
fectly acquainted  with  physiology,  and  this  want  of 
preliminary  knowledge  has  sometimes  led  to  a  mis- 
apprehension of  the  text,  and  sometimes  to  an  inad- 
equate appreciation  of  what  could  be  only  suggestive. 
Thus,  the  causes  which  have  contributed  to  make 
the  text  abstruse,  and  even  in  places  unintelligible, 
have  concurred  in  making  the  translations  obscure, 
and  occasionally  incomprehensible;  for  besides  in- 
dications of  imperfect  anatomical  knowledge,  the 
arguments  in  the  Treatise  can  be  regarded  but  as 
suggestions,  and  be  elucidated  only  by  reference  to 
the  more  matured  science  of  modern  times.  It  cannot 
derogate  from  what  is  due  to  Aristotle,  to  admit  that 
physiology,  in  his  age,  was  not  only  encumbered 
with  the  hypotheses  of  earlier  schools,  but  also 
dwarfed  and  distorted  by  imperfect  acquaintance  with 
those  systems  and  organs  of  the  living  body,  which 


PREFACE.  Vll 

he  perceived,  intuitively,  to  be  necessary  to  a  full 
comprehension  of  his  subject.  But  although  the 
opinions  and  conjectures  of  this  Treatise  may,  from 
the  advanced  state  of  anatomy  and  physiology,  have 
but  little  intrinsic  value,  the  method  adopted  by 
Aristotle  may  not  be  undeserving  the  attention  of 
those  who,  with  a  wider  range  of  special  knowledge, 
are  better  prepared  for  the  undertaking;  unless, 
indeed,  the  Vital  Principle  is  to  be  set  down  among 
those  final  causes,  which,  lying  beyond  the  human 
comprehension,  are  to  be  admitted  as  ultimate  facts. 
Although  this  may  be  the  case,  however,  some  in- 
terest must  be  taken  in  a  Treatise  which  is,  not  only 
indicative  of  Aristotle's  style  and  mode  of  argument, 
but  pregnant  also,  by  allusion,  with  collateral  infor- 
mation. 

This  version  has  been  made  with  the  inten- 
tion of  rendering  it,  in  so  far  as  the  analogies  of 
language  would  allow,  a  faithful  transcript  of  the 
opinions  and  manner  of  Aristotle;  and  notes  are 
added  for  the  elucidation  of  passages  which  by  no 
periphrasis  could  be  made  intelligible  to  the  general 
reader.  It  may  be  observed  that  the  mind,  (6  vovs), 
although  nowhere  denned,  appears,  in  this  Treatise, 
to  represent  the  abstract  immaterial  principle  usually 
attributed  to  the  ^vxn  '•>  f°r  it  alone  is  excluded  from 
all  direct  participation  in  corporeal  functions  or 
changes. 


Till  PREFACE. 

Although  the  title  given  to  this  version  embodies, 
as  I  believe,  Aristotle's  idea,  yet  it  is  not  pretended 
that  the  writers  cited  by  him  always  employed  the 
term  i/^xv  m  h*8  sense ;  or  even  that  he,  himself, 
was  always  consistent  in  the  use  of  it.  Plato  was 
certainly  not  engaged  upon  material  agencies  or  pro- 
perties in  his  Phcedo,  and  in  the  Timceus,  which 
partakes  of  a  physiological  character,  and  as  such 
has  been  criticised  in  this  Treatise,  the  animating 
motor  principle  is  treated  of  rather  as  an  abstraction 
than  as  the  originating  and  natural  cause  of  life, 
through  all  its  manifestations.  The  term  Vital 
Principle,  however,  has  been  retained  throughout, 
even  where  it  may  seem  to  be  less  apposite,  as  well 
to  avoid  the  misapprehension  which  might  be  occa- 
sioned by  the  substitution  of  another  term,  (that  of 
soul  I  mean,)  which  might  then  to  some  appear  to 
be  its  synonym,  as  on  account  of  the  extreme  dif- 
ficulty of  determining  the  point  where  the  metonymy 
might,  without  question,  be  adopted. 

This  Translation  is  from  the  Oxford  edition,  col- 
lated with  that  of  Trendelenburg ;  and  this  allusion 
to  that  eminent  scholar  affords  me  the  opportunity 
of  acknowledging  the  assistance  which  has  been 
derived  from  his  comments  upon  passages,  which 
require,  for  elucidation,  all  the  light  that  can  be 
thrown  upon  them  by  tradition  and  learning. 


INTEODUCTION. 


As  this  treatise  may  interest  some  who  have 
never  considered  the  subject  for  the  elucidation  of 
which  it  was  composed,  it  will  be  well  to  offer  a 
summary  of  that  which  Aristotle  had  undertaken  to 
delineate,  and  to  give,  at  the  same  time,  an  epitome 
of  the  opinions  which,  in  modern  times,  have  been 
entertained  concerning  it. 

It  is  then  that  principle,  which,  inherent  in  genial 
matter,  establishes  functions  distinctive  of  animated 
beings ;  and  those  functions  are  nutrition,  and,  through 
nutrition,  growth  or  development,  within  a  certain 
prescribed  range,  and  absorption  or  rather  change 
wrought  by  absorption,  that  is,  decay.  These  two 
functions  constitute,  in  fact,  animated  beings,  and 
distinguish  them  broadly  from  whatever  is  inanimate; 
and  as  those  functions  are  inherent  in  the  simplest 

1 


2  INTRODUCTION. 

forms  of  being,  it  is  in  such  that  we  might  expect  to 
find  a  clue  to  the  nature  of  that  something  which, 
whether  entity  or  mere  quality,  confers  upon  living 
matter  its  distinctive  properties.     But  whether  we 
examine  a  seed  before   development,  or  watch   the 
rudimental  forms  of  life,  that  something  lies  shrouded 
in  matter  which,  although  to  appearance  inanimate, 
is  yet,  through  its  influence,  under  genial  conditions, 
capable  of  developing  into  a  perfect  being;  and  of 
resisting,  for  a  stated  time,  the  agency  of  surrounding 
elements.     Thus,  growth  and  development  with  their 
antagonisms  absorption  and  decay,  effected  through 
the    actions   of  the    material  framework    of  living 
beings,  constitute,  essentially,  life;  and  the  subject 
of  this  essay  is  that  something  which  gives  to  matter 
those  attributes.    The  processes,  then,  of  reproduc- 
tion, growth,  and  decay,  that  is,  generation,  life,  and 
death,    are    the    essential    characteristics    of   living 
beings,  and  conferred  upon  them,  as  has  been  said, 
by  that  something  which  is  designated  Vital  Principle. 
Now,  to  homogeneous  forms  and  solitary  functions 
others  of  more  complex  nature  are  superadded,  and 
these  give  rise  to  that  long  chain  of  being  of  which 
man  may  be  regarded  as  the  head ;  but  yet,  amid  all 
the  simplicity  of  organs,  of  action,  and  of  reaction, 
those  two  functions  still  prevail,  and  constitute  life, 


INTRODUCTION.  3 

whatever  the  type  of  being,  in  its  strictest  significa- 
tion. This  is  the  teaching  of  Aristotle,  as  it  is  the 
doctrine  of  modern  physiologists ;  and  those  functions 
are  always  here  referred  to  as  the  essential  conditions 
of  whatever  is  animated,  although,  for  higher  forms 
of  being,  other  "organs  and  functions  are  required. 
The  nature,  however,  of  the  essence  or  principle 
which  originates  and  orders  those  living  functions  is 
hitherto  for  us,  as  it  was  for  Aristotle,  inscrutable ; 
and  it  may  be  that  the  wide  survey  which  he  took  of 
life,  by  complicating  simple  functions  with  sentient 
and  even  intellectual  faculties,  tended  only  to  disturb 
and  pervert  the  course  of  his  inquiry.  But  whether 
Aristotle's  mode  of  inquiry  was  or  not  faulty,  and 
whether  the  principle  which  animates  the  world  (it 
may  be  the  universe)  is  or  not  among  those  causes 
which  are  inscrutable,  it  will  be  ever  a  topic  of  deep 
interest  to  the  learned  and  the  thoughtful  of  every 
age. 

In  an  opening  chapter,  Aristotle  has  in  so  clear 
and  succinct  a  manner  reviewed  the  prevailing  doc- 
trines and  opinions  as  well  of  his  own  as  of  a  pre- 
ceding age,  that  that  summary  may  be  regarded  as 
the  exposition  of  all  that  was  then  most  authoritative; 
and  as,  from  that  time,  physiology  may  be  said  to 
have  declined,  it  would  be  almost  supererogatory  to 

1—2 


4  INTRODUCTION. 

allude  to  any  other  writer  before  the  rise  of  modern 
science.  It  may  be  mentioned,  however,  in  deference 
to  the  name,  that  Cicero1  has  alluded,  with  a  just 
appreciation  of  Aristotle's  superiority,  to  this  treatise ; 
but  as  the  topic  was  foreign  to  his  pursuits  and  little 
in  accordance  with  his  talents,  we  cannot  be  sur- 
prised if  he  mistook  the  scope  of  the  design,  and  per- 
verted thereby  the  tendency  of  the  argument. 

This  treatise  is,  it  may  be  added,  both  an  intro- 
duction and  a  sequel  to  the  other  physiological  trea- 
tises of  Aristotle ;  and,  as  it  treats  of  all  the  charac- 
teristics of  living  beings,  it  may  contribute  to  a 
clearer  understanding  of  them,  as  they,  in  their  turn, 
may  serve  to  elucidate  it ;  for  they  all  proceed  from 
the  same  hand,  maintain  the  same  doctrines,  and 
emanate  from  the  same  laborious  and  original 
intellect. 

This  topic  engaged  the  attention  of  eminent  ana- 
tomists and  physiologists  towards  the  opening  of  the 
present  .century,  and  their  writings  will  shew  the 
opinions  entertained  by  the  moderns  concerning  it; 
but  it  has,  generally,  been  made  an  incidental  rather 
than  a  special  subject  of  inquiry,  a  prelude,  aa  it 
were,  to  the  teaching  of  anatomy  and  physiology. 
The  opinions  entertained  concerning  vital  principle 

1  Tusc.  Disp.  Lib.  I.  i. 


INTRODUCTION.  5 

by  the  eminent  men  here  alluded  to  (Hunter  and 
Barclay,  Bichat  and  Cuvier)  may  well  be  collated 
with  those  of  Aristotle,  who  wrote  at  a  time  when 
science  was  in  its  infancy,  and  when,  for  profitable 
investigation,  he  had  to  depend  almost  exclusively, 
amid  so  much  hypothesis,  upon  his  own  laborious 
and  perspicacious  intellect. 

In  quoting  those  writers,  there  is  hardly  occasion 
for  observing  any  order  of  precedence,  as  they 
flourished  about  the  same  time,  and  contributed 
equally  to  the  present  development  of  physiological 
science. 

According  to  Hunter1,  "Animal  matter  is  en- 
dowed with  a  principle  called,  in  common  language, 
life.  This  principle  is  perhaps  conceived  of  with 
more  difficulty  than  any  other  in  nature,  which  arises 
from  its  being  more  complex  in  its  effects  than  any 
other;  and  it  is,  therefore,  no  wonder  that  it  is  the 
least  understood.  But,  although  life  may  appear 
compounded  in  its  effects  in  a  complicated  animal 
like  man,  it  is  as  simple  in  him  as  in  the  most  simple 
animal,  and  is  reducible  to  one  simple  property  in 
every  animal."  In  another  paragraph,  he  adds, 
"  the  first  and  most  simple  idea  of  life  is  its  being 
the  principle  of  self-preservation,  by  its  preventing 

1  On  Vital  Principle, 


6  INTRODUCTION. 

matter  from  falling  into  dissolution — for  dissolution 
immediately  takes  place  when  matter  is  deprived  of 
it;  the  second  is  its  being  the  principle  of  action. 
These  are  two  very  different  properties,  though  they 
arise  from  the  same  principle." 

Barclay1  observes  that,  "  in  every  living  organized 
structure  there  is  plainly  a  power  that  preserves, 
regulates,  and  controls  the  whole ;  directing,  at  first, 
the  different  processes  in  forming  one  part  of  the 
organs,  afterwards  employing  the  assistance  of  the 
organs  which  it  has  formed  to  produce  more,  till  at 
last  it  completes  the  whole  of  the  system  in  such  a 
manner  as  to  suit  its  future  conveniences  and  wants. 
This  power,  or  rather  this  agent,  physiologists  have 
named  Vital  Principle;  though  not  a  few  are  inclined 
to  suppose  it  to  be  the  effect,  rather  than  the  cause, 
of  the  organization.  But  in  all  operations  that  are 
performed  without  either  volition  or  consciousness,  it 
appears  subordinate  to  a  much  higher  power — to  that 
Almighty  and  Omniscient  Being,  who  dispenses  his 
laws  to  the  boundless  Universe,  and  whose  laws,  ex- 
cept by  himself,  can  never  be  improved,  altered,  or 
abrogated." 

Bichat2  makes  Vital  Principle  to  be  "the  assem- 
blage of  the  functions  which  resist  death ;"  and  this 

1  Introduction  to  Anatomical  Nomenclature. 

2  La  Vie  et  la  Mort, 


INTRODUCTION.  7 

definition  was  adopted  substantively  by  Cuvier,  who, 
in  his  introductory  lecture  to  the  "  Comparative  Ana- 
tomy," has  illustrated  the  influences  of  this  assumed 
principle,  by  a :  description,  alike  graphic  and  beauti- 
ful, of  what  takes  place  when  it  has  been  withdrawn 
or  extinguished.  "If1,"  he  observes,  "in  order  to 
have  a  correct  idea  of  life,  we  consider  it  in  simple 
forms  of  being,  we  shall  soon  perceive  that  it  consists 
in  the  faculty  possessed  by  particular  corporeal  com- 
binations of  lasting  for  a  given  time  and  under  a 
determined  form;  of  attracting,  incessantly,  into  their 
composition  a  portion  of  the  surrounding  substances, 
and  in  giving  back  to  the  elements  portions  of  their 
own  substance.  So  long  as  this  series  of  move- 
ments is  maintained,  the  body,  in  which  it  is  mani- 
fested, is  a  living  body;  and  when  it  is  irrecoverably 
arrested  it  is  dead." 

But  although  the  definition  of  Bichat  involves  a 
great  truth,  and  is  a  summary  of  all  that  has  been 
ever  said  upon  the  subject,  it  is  open  to  the  criticism 
of  M.  Magendie,  that,  by  its  admitting  the  idea  of 
death,  it  presupposes  life,  and  thus  establishes  a 
vicious  circle  of  reasoning.  It  is  criticised  also  by 
M.  Comte2,  as  a  fancied  antagonism  between  animate 
and  inanimate  matter,  a  chimerical  struggle  between 
1  Regne  Animal.  z  Science  Bwlogique. 


8  INTRODUCTION. 

living  beings  and  surrounding  influences;  for  "the 
idea  of  life,"  he  observes,  "presupposes  something 
able  to  live,  and  it  requires  no  less  a  certain  assem- 
blage of  external  influences  for  its  fulfilment." 

The  nature  of  Vital  Principle,  then,  is  still  for  us, 
as  it  was  for  Aristotle,  a  great  mystery;  and  as 
opinions  upon  it  are  at  best  but  speculations,  we  may 
proceed,  without  further  comment,  to  the  text,  which, 
besides  miscellaneous  matter,  will  be  found  to  contain 
suggestions  for  reflexion  and  inquiry. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  I. 

THIS  chapter  is  an  elaborate  statement  of  the  subject  as 
well  as  the  object  of  the  inquiry.  The  term  ^J/VXTJ, 
here  rendered  "Vital  Principle,"  has  several  signi- 
fications, as  was  observed  in  the  preface,  in  the 
course  of  this  and  the  other  physiological  treatises: 
in  one  passage,  it  implies  the  life  of  an  animal ;  in 
another,  the  nutritive  function ;  in  another,  a  vital 
part;  in  another,  a  motor  force;  and  in  another,  the 
visual  power  (rov  o^a-ros  »;  ^v-^tj1)  ;  some  writers, 
besides,  derived  the  term  ^v-^rj  from  -v^v^/ao?  or 
if/w^oi,  coolness  or  cold,  because  respiration  was  held 
to  be  a  cooling  process,  and  as  such  essential  to  life. 
The  object  of  Aristotle,  then,  in  this  treatise,  was  to 
learn  the  nature  of  that  essence  or  principle  which, 
under  whatever  denomination,  is  the  innate  source 
of  motion,  and,  consequently,  of  vital  actions  in  all 
bodies  capable  of  being  animated;  for  although,  in  the 
more  complicated  forms  of  being,  it  is  involved  in 

1  De  Sensu  et  Sens.  II.  16. 


10  PKELUDE  TO   CHAP.  I. 

the  manifestation  of  perceptions  and  passions,  its 
great  office  still  is  to  originate,  to  maintain,  and  to 
perpetuate  life,  through  all  its  gradations.  It  may  be 
that,  from  some  such  conclusion,  Aristotle  was  led  to 
regard  the  vital  principle  as  inferior  in  destiny  and 
office  to  the  faculty  which  he  has  designated1  mind 
(o  i/ovc),  and  made  to  be  impassive,  homogeneous, 
apart  from,  and  independent  of,  the  body.  These 
opinions  have  much  in  common  with  those  adopted 
by  Plato  in  the  Timaeus;  as,  while,  in  that  most 
beautiful  and  intellectual  disquisition,  the  senses, 
appetites,  and  passions,  the  mortal  framework,  that 
is,  of  the  sentient  being,  are  located  about  the  heart 
and  liver, — the  intellectual  faculty,  that  which  is 
divine,  and  intended  to  direct  and  control  the  animal 
powers,  is  placed  in  the  head.  The  life  is  repre- 
sented, in  fact,  by  ^v^tj,  which  is  bound  up  with 
corporeal  functions  and  appetites ;  and  reason  by 
i/ous,  which,  if  any  where,  is,  "as  the  divine  seed  of 
wisdom,"  in  the  brain ;  and,  being  homogeneous, 
does  not  depend,  for  existence,  upon  the  life  of  the 
body.  These  few  words  will  suffice  to  shew  that 
there  is  an  analogy  between  the  two  systems  of  phy- 
siology and  psychology. 

1  De  An.  i.  4 ;  i.  5  ;  in.  4,  6. 


BOOK    THE    FIRST. 


CHAPTER  I. 

IT  may  be  assumed  that  all  knowledge  is  beautiful 
and  estimable ;  but  as  one  branch  may  be  more  so 
than  another,  either  because  of  the  exactness  which 
is  requisite  for  its  examination,  or  from  its  treating  of 
objects  more  exalted  and  wonderful  than  any  others, 
so,  on  both  these  accounts,  we  may  reasonably  assign 
the  first  place  to  an  inquiry  into  Vital  Principle.  For 
the  knowledge  of  it  promises  to  contribute  largely  to 
all  truth,  and  most  especially  to  truth  in  relation  to 
nature,  since  it  is  the  origin,  as  it  were,  of  living 
beings.  The  object  of  our  inquiry,  then,  is  to  study 
and  ascertain  its  nature  and  its  essence,  as  well  as  its 
accidents,  of  which  some  seem  to  be  its  own  peculiar 
affections,  and  some  to  belong  to  living  beings,  as 
original  properties,  through  it. 

Let  us  premise,  however,  that  the  attempt  to  attain 
to  any  certainty  with  respect  to  it  is  beset  with  almost 
insuperable  difficulties;  for  as  this  has  much  in 


12  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  I. 

common  with  many  other  inquiries,  with  every  inquiry, 
I  mean,  instituted  for  ascertaining  the  essence  and 
the  thing  itself,  it  might  hastily  be  supposed  that,  as 
demonstration  is  the  method  for  studying  particular 
"bodies  in  their  accidents,  there  may  be  some  one  special 
method  of  investigation  when  our  object  is  to  learn 
what  is  the  essence  of  a  thing,  and  that  that  method 
ought  to  be  sought  for  on  this  occasion.  If,  however, 
there  is  no  one  common  method  for  ascertaining  what 
any  thing  in  itself  is,  the  systematic  treatment  of 
our  subject  is  rendered  still  more  difficult;  for,  in  that 
case,  it  will  be  necessary  to  adopt,  for  each  particular 
subject,  some  one  particular  method.  Although  it 
may  be  manifest,  besides,  that  the  inquiry  should  be 
by  some  kind  of  demonstration,  or  division,  or  other 
method,  there  will  still  remain  many  difficulties  and 
many  liabilities  to  error  in  fixing  upon  the  principles 
from  which  the  inquiry  should  set  out;  for  the  princi- 
ples of  different  subjects  differ,  as  those  of  number 
are  not  those  of  plane  surfaces. 

It  may  be  well,  perhaps,  before  proceeding  fur- 
ther, to  distinguish  the  "genus"  to  which  Vital  Prin- 
ciple belongs,  and  determine  what  it  is — determine,  I 
mean,  whether  it  is  a  something  and  essence,  or  quan- 
tity, or  quality,  or  any  other  of  the  classified  cate- 
gories; as  also,  a  distinction  of  no  small  importance, 
whether  it  is  among  entities  in  potentiality,  or  whether 
rather  it  is  a  reality.  We  have  to  consider  too  whether 


CH.  I.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  13 

Vital  Principle  is  divisible  or  without  parts,  and 
whether  every  Vital  Principle  is  or  is  not  the  same  in 
kind,  and,  if  not  the  same,  whether  the  difference  is 
generic  or  specific ;  but  they  who  now  are  engaged  in 
discussing  and  exploring  Vital  Principle  seem  to  give 
exclusive  attention  to  that  of  man.  We  must  be  on 
our  guard  against  this,  however,  so  that  it  may  not 
escape  us  whether  there  is  but  one  definition  for  Vital 
Principle  as  for  animal,  or  whether  it  must  be  differ- 
ent for  each  creature,  as  for  a  horse,  a  dog,  or  a  man. 
The  term  animal,  besides,  taken  in  an  universal 
sense,  is  either  without  meaning,  or  of  very  secondary 
value;  and  so  equally  is  every  other  common  term 
which  might  be  predicated  of  this  subject.  If,  on  the 
other  hand,  there  are  not  several  Vital  Principles,  but 
parts  only  of  a  single  Principle,  we  have  to  settle 
whether  we  should  commence  the  inquiry  with  the 
Principle  as  a  whole,  or,  contrariwise,  with  its  parts; 
and,  with  respect  to  the  parts,  it  is  difficult  to  deter- 
mine which  of  them  have  been  constituted  differently 
from  others ;  it  is  difficult  also  to  say  whether  we 
should  study  the  parts  before  their  functions,  as  the 
mind  before  thought,  or  sensibility  before  sensation ; 
and  so  for  other  faculties  and  functions.  If  it  be  ex- 
pedient to  commence  the  inquiry  with  functions,  it 
may  be  a  question  whether  it  would  not  be  better 
here  also  to  study  first  their  opposites ;  as  the  object 
of  perception  before  that  which  perceives,  and  thought 


14  ARISTOTLE   ON  THE  [BK.  I. 

before  that  which  thinks.  Now,  the  knowledge  of 
any  thing  in  itself  seems  to  be  useful  towards  a  right 
conception  of  the  causes  of  the  accidents  in  sub- 
stances ;  as,  in  mathematics,  the  knowledge  of  straight 
and  curve,  line  and  surface,  is  requisite  for  perceiving 
to  how  many  right  angles  the  angles  of  the  triangle 
are  equal.  But  the  knowledge  of  the  accidents  con- 
tributes, largely,  in  its  turn,  towards  knowing  what 
the  thing,  essentially,  is ;  for  whenever  we  may  be  able, 
from  the  appearance  of  any  substance,  to  recount  the 
whole  or  the  greater  number  of  its  accidents,  we  are 
then  best  prepared  to  say  what  its  essence  is.  Thus, 
the  essence  is  the  proper  beginning  for  every  demon- 
stration, so  that  all  the  definitions,  which  do  not 
make  known,  or  make  it  easy  to  conjecture  what 
may  be  the  accidents  of  any  substance,  are  to  be 
regarded  as  dialectic  and  unprofitable  subtleties. 

It  is  difficult  to  determine  whether  all  the  emo- 
tions of  Vital  Principle  are  common  to  it  and  its 
recipient,  or  whether  some  one  emotion  belongs  to  it 
exclusively ;  and  this  is  a  question,  which,  although 
not  easily  settled,  it  is  necessary  to  entertain.  There 
is  scarcely  one  of  the  many  emotions  which  are  de- 
rived from  the  Vital  Principle,  (as  anger,  or  courage, 
desire,  or  feeling,)  in  the  manifestation  of  which  the 
Vital  Principle  can  be  said  to  be  affected,  actively  or 
passively,  without  the  body;  the  faculty  of  thought 
seems  to  be  the  peculiar  property  of  the  Vital  Prin- 


CH.  I.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  15 

ciple,  but  whether  thought  be  imagination  of  some 
kind,  or  never  unaccompanied  by  imagination,  still 
we  must  admit  that  it  cannot  be  exercised  without  the 
body.  If,  then,  there  is  any  one  function  or  emotion 
which  is  peculiar  to  the  Vital  Principle,  we  should 
admit  that  it  might  be  isolated  from  the  body;  but,  if 
no  one  belongs  to  it,  exclusively,  then  we  say  that  it 
cannot  be  separate  from  one.  But,  just  as  many  acci- 
dents concur  in  the  quality  straightness,  in  so  far  as 
straightness  (as,  for  instance,  among  others,  to  touch 
a  brazen  sphere  at  a  point,  which,  were  it  apart  from 
some  kind  of  body,  it  could  not  do),  so  straightness  is 
inseparable  from  a  body,  since  it  is  ever  found  to- 
gether with  one.  In  the  same  way  all  the  emotions 
of  the  Vital  Principle  (such  as  courage,  gentleness, 
fear,  pity,  daring,  joy,  love  and  hatred,)  seem  to  be 
manifested  together  with  the  body;  for  the  body  is 
affected,  simultaneously,  by  them.  As  evidence  of 
which,  there  are  times  when  we  are  neither  excited 
nor  alarmed,  although  misfortunes  may  be  trying 
and  palpable,  while,  at  other  times,  when  the  body  is 
plethoric,  or  in  a  state  akin  to  that  of  anger,  we  are 
moved  by  incidents  which  are  trivial  and  unim- 
portant. And  what  makes  this  yet  more  apparent  is, 
that,  at  times,  without  the  occurrence  of  aught  to 
occasion  alarm,  we  are  thrown  into  the  state  of 
persons  under  terror;  and  if  this  be  true,  it  is  clear 
that  all  such  emotions  are  material  conditions.  So 


16  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  I. 

that  the  definition  of  any  one  of  them,  as  that  of 
anger  for  example,  may  be  said  to  be  the  motion  of  a 
body  of  particular  nature,  or  part  or  function  of  a 
body,  by  such  a  cause,  and  for  such  an  end. 

Thus,  for  these  reasons,  it  is  for  the  physiologist 
to  study  the  Vital  Principle,  either  as  a  whole,  or 
under  some  particular  manifestation.  But  the  phy- 
siologist and  the  metaphysician  would  differ  widely 
in  their  definition  of  any  one  of  those  emotions,  as 
that  of  anger,  for  example ;  which,  while  the  latter 
would  hold  to  be  desire  for  retaliation,  or  some  such 
motive,  the  former  would  maintain  to  be  ebullition  of 
blood,  or  excess  of  heat  about  the  heart.  The  one  of 
these,  in  fact,  accounts  for  the  passion  by  the  matter, 
and  the  other  by  the  form  and  cause ;  for  the  form  is 
the  cause  of  the  thing,  which,  if  it  is  to  be,  must,  of 
necessity,  be  in  a  special  matter.  Thus,  the  cause  of 
a  house,  for  instance,  is  such  as  this — "  to  be  a  shelter 
to  avert  injury  from  rain,  wind,  and  heat;"  and  here 
the  physiologist  will  speak  of  stones,  bricks,  and 
rafters,  while  the  metaphysician  will,  in  these  mate- 
rials, only  behold  the  form  to  be  adopted  for  those 
purposes.  Which,  then,  of  these  is  the  physiologist? 
Is  it  he  who  studies  only  the  matter  without  refer- 
ence to  the  cause,  or  he  who  is  occupied  with  the 
cause  only?  Or  is  it  rather  he  who  judges  both  from 
cause  and  matter ;  and  which  of  the  two  is  he  ?  May 
we  not  however  rather  say  that  there  is  one  who  is 


CH.  I.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  17 

engaged  upon  the  properties  which  are  inseparable 
and  only  in  so  far  as  they  are  inseparable  from  matter, 
while  to  the  physiologist  it  belongs  to  judge  of  such 
emotions  and  functions  as  emanate  from  particular 
bodies  and  peculiar  matter  ?  Properties  different  from 
these  belong  to  another ;  and  some  of  them  to  an 
artisan,  a  physician  or  builder,  as  the  case  may  be, 
while  the  mathematician  has  to  do  with  properties 
which  are  not  inseparable  from  matter,  but  which,  as 
they  do  not  belong  to  any  particular  body,  admit  of 
being  treated  as  abstractions ;  and  abstract  qualities, 
as  abstractions,  belong  to  the  transcendental  philo- 
sopher. 

Let  us,  however,  return  to  the  point  where  our 
discussion  broke  off,  and  repeat  that  the  emotions  of 
Vital  Principle,  such  as  anger  and  fear,  for  instance, 
in  so  far  as  they  are  innate,  are  inseparable  from  the 
material  frame-work  of  animals;  and  that  they  are 
not  to  be  regarded  as  a  line  or  a  surface. 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  II. 

THIS  chapter  is  a  review  of  the  opinions  of  earlier  and 
contemporaneous  writers  upon  the  Vital  Principle, 
and  as  Aristotle  has  never  failed  at  the  outset  of  each 
subject  of  inquiry  to  record  the  principal  writers  upon 
it,  he  may  be  regarded  as  the  founder  of  tradition  in 
science.  The  writers  here  cited  may  be  divided  into 
those  who  made  motion,  and  those  who  supposed 
feeling  to  be  the  essential  characteristic  of  that  which 
imparts  life  to  matter ;  although  there  were  some 
who  attributed  to  it  both  motion  and  feeling. 


CHAPTER  II. 

As  we  are  now  entering  upon  the  study  of  Vital 
Principle,  and  are  encompassed  with  doubts  which 
ought  to  be  resolved,  it  will  be  incumbent  upon  us  to 
gather  the  opinions  of  such  of  the  earlier  writers  as 
have  suggested  any  thing  concerning  it,  in  order  that 
we  may  be  able  as  well  to  adopt  their  happier  concep- 
tions as  to  be  on  our  guard  against  their  errors. 


CH.  II.]      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE   VITAL  PRINCIPLE.       19 

The  suitable  opening  for  this  inquiry  into  the 
Vital  Principle  is  to  lay  down  the  properties  which 
appear,  most  especially,  to  belong  to  it.  The  ani- 
mated being,  then,  seems  to  be  especially  distinguished 
from  whatever  is  inanimate  by  the  two  properties  of 
motion  and  feeling;  and  these  two  are  almost  the 
only  distinctions  which  have  been  transmitted  to  us 
by  the  earlier  writers  upon  the  subject.  Thus,  some 
of  them  maintain  that  the  Vital  Principle  is  in  the 
largest,  fullest  sense  a  motor  power;  and  as  they 
believed  that  nothing  can  impart  motion  unless  it  be 
self-motive,  they  assumed  that  the  Vital  Principle 
must  be  among  beings  which  are  self-moved.  Hence 
Democritus  says  that  it  is  a  kind  of  fire  and  heat,  and 
as  forms  and  atoms  are,  according  to  him,  infinite,  he 
speaks  of  those  which  are  spherical  and  apparent  in 
the  sun's  beams,  while  passing  through  chinks  in 
doors,  as  fire  and  Vital  Principle ;  and  further  says, 
that  those  atoms,  collectively,  are  the  elements  of 
universal  nature.  Leucippus,  in  like  manner,  is  dis- 
posed to  regard  the  spherical  atoms  as  Vital  Prin- 
ciple, both  on  account  of  those  forms  being  best 
adapted  for  penetrating  every  where,  and  best  able, 
from  being  self-motive,  to  give  motion  to  other  things ; 
and  thus  they  both  assume  that  it  is  Vital  Principle 
which  imparts  motion  to  living  beings.  Hence,  too, 
they  make  breathing  to  be  the  boundary  of  life — for 
they  maintain  that  the  envelopment  of  animal  bodies 

2—2 


20  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  I. 

crushes  by  its  contraction  those  forms  of  atoms  which, 
from  never  being  at  rest,  give  motion,  and  that  com- 
pensation is  afforded  for  their  exit  by  the  entrance  of 
other  like  forms,  during  inspiration;  and  that  these 
forms,  while  entering,  resist  the  contracting  and 
solidifying  power,  and  preclude  the  expulsion  of  all 
the  atoms  which  are  essential  to  life.  They  further 
maintain  that  animals  can  live  only  so  long  as  they 
can  support  this  process.  The  opinion  adopted  by 
the  Pythagoreans  seems  to  be  to  the  same  purport — 
for  some  of  them  have  maintained  that  Vital  Principle 
is  the  motes  in  the  air,  and  others  that  it  is  that  which 
gives  motion  to  the  motes ;  and  it  has  thus  been  said 
of  those  corpuscles,  because  of  their  appearing  to  be 
constantly  moving,  although  the  air  may  be  quite 
still. 

To  the  same  point  do  they  also  come  who  say  that 
the  Vital  Principle  is  self-motive ;  for  all  these  philo- 
sophers seem  to  have  assumed  that  motion  is  the  most 
characteristic  property  of  the  Vital  Principle ;  and 
that,  while  all  other  things  are  moved  by  it,  it  is  self- 
moved,  and  the  more  so,  as  they  do  not  see  any  motor 
which  is  not  self-moved. 

Anaxagoras,  in  like  manner,  says  that  the  Vital 
Principle  is  a  motive  force,  and  the  same  opinion  may 
be  attributed  to  any  one  who,  with  him,  may  have 
maintained  that  the  mind  has  given  motion  to  the 
universe;  and  yet  his  opinion  is  not  altogether  in 


CH.  II.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  21 

accordance  with  that  of  Democritus.  Democritus,  in 
fact,  maintains  that  Vital  Principle  and  mind  are 
absolutely  identical ;  that  the  apparent  is  the  true ; 
and  that  Homer,  therefore,  has  done  well  in  repre-» 
senting  Hector  as  "changing  his  mind  while  he  lay." 
Thus  he  does  not  employ  the  term  mind  as  a  faculty 
for  the  attainment  of  truth,  but  makes  mind  to  be 
identical  with  the  Vital  Principle.  Anaxagoras  is 
less  explicit  upon  these  points ;  for,  in  many  places, 
he  speaks  of  mind  as  the  source  of  the  beautiful  and 
the  true,  while,  elsewhere,  he  says  that  it  is  identical 
with  the  Vital  Principle,  and  innate  in  all  creatures, 
larger  or  smaller,  higher  or  lower,  in  the  scale  of 
being ;  but  it  is  manifest  that  mind,  in  the  sense  of 
intellect,  is  not  equally  allotted  to  all  animals,  nor 
even  to  all  men. 

Thus  they  who  have  looked  upon  living  beings 
with  respect  to  motion,  have  assumed  that  the  Vital 
Principle  is  the  most  motive  of  entities,  and  so  many 
as  have  looked  upon  them  with  respect  to  knowledge 
and  sentient  perception,  have  said  that  the  Vital 
Principle  comprises  all  first  causes ;  of  which,  while 
some  admit  of  several,  others  maintain  that  there  is 
only  this  one.  Empedocles,  for  instance,  seems  to 
maintain  that  the  Vital  Principle  is  derived  from 
all  the  elements,  and  that  each  element  is  Vital 
Principle,  as  he  says  that  "  by  earth  we  perceive 
earth,  by  water  water,  by  air  air,  by  fire  destructive 


22  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  I. 

fire,  by  attraction  attraction,  and  by  repulsion  dire 
repulsion." 

Plato,  in  a  like  manner,  in  the  Timaeus,  derives 
the  Vital  Principle  from  the  elements — for  like,  there- 
in, is  known  by  like,  and  things  are  derived  from 
first  causes ;  and  so,  likewise,  have  things  been  denned 
by  him  in  the  treatises  "  upon  philosophy."  Accord- 
ing to  them,  animal,  in  itself,  is  derived  from  the 
abstract  idea  of  unity,  and  primal  length,  and  breadth, 
and  depth ;  and  other  things  in  a  somewhat  similar 
manner.  It  is  besides  maintained,  but  in  a  different 
sense,  that  the  mind  is  unity,  and  knowledge  duality, 
although,  as  one  branch,  it  is  unity ;  and  that  the 
number  of  the  surface  is  opinion,  that  of  the  solid 
sensation,  for  numbers  were  spoken  of  by  him  as 
forms  and  first  causes,  and  as  derivatives  from  the 
elements.  Thus,  some  things  are  discriminated  by 
mind,  some  by  knowledge,  some  by  opinion,  and 
others  by  sensation ;  as  the  numbers  which  represent 
those  faculties  are  the  forms  of  things. 

Since  the  Vital  Principle  has  to  some  appeared  to 
be  both  motive  and  capable  of  knowing,  there  are 
writers  who  have  combined  motion  and  intelligence, 
and  then  represented  the  Vital  Principle  as  a  number 
endowed  with  self-motion. 

Philosophers  differ  with  respect  to  first  causes, 
both  as  to  their  nature  and  number ;  but  they  who 
make  them  corporeal  differ  most  from  those  who  hold 


CH.  II.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  23 

them  to  be  incorporeal;  and  from  these  again  they 
differ  who  make  them  to  be  a  combination  both  of 
corporeal  and  incorporeal  molecules.  They  differ 
also  with  respect  to  the  number  of  such  causes,  as 
some  adopt  only  one  while  others  admit  of  several ; 
and,  in  accordance  with  these  conclusions,  they  form 
their  estimate  of  the  Vital  Principle ;  but  yet  they 
have  all  assumed,  and  not  unreasonably,  that  it  is  of 
the  nature  of  first  causes  to  be  motive.  Hence,  the 
Vital  Principle  has  to  some  appeared  to  be  fire,  as 
fire,  besides  being  the  most  attenuated  and  most 
incorporeal  of  the  elements,  is  both  self-motive  and 
a  primal  cause  of  motion  in  other  things. 

Democritus  has  expressed  himself  more  clearly 
than  any  other  writer  in  specifying  the  causes  of  each 
of  those  properties :  for  he  says  that  the  Vital  Prin- 
ciple is  identical  with  the  mind,  and  to  be  placed 
among  primal  and  indivisible  bodies  ;  that  it  is  motive, 
owing  to  the  tenuity  of  its  parts  and  its  form ;  that 
of  forms  the  spherical  is  the  most  mobile,  and  that 
this  is  the  form  both  of  mind  and  fire. 

Anaxagoras  seems,  as  we  have  already  said,  to 
distinguish  the  mind  from  the  Vital  Principle,  although 
he  employs  both  terms  as  if  synonymous ;  excepting 
that  he  sets  down  the  mind  as  being,  in  the  fullest 
sense,  the  origin  of  all  things.  Thus  he  says  that  the 
mind  alone  of  all  entities  is  homogeneous,  unmixed, 
and  pure ;  and  to  the  same  principle  he  attributes 


24  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  I. 

the  properties  both  of  knowing  and  imparting  motion, 
as  he  maintains  that  it  is  the  mind  which  has  given 
motion  to  the  universe. 

Thales,  too,  from  what  has  been  recorded  of  him, 
seems  to  have  assumed  that  the  Vital  Principle  is 
something  motive,  since  he  said  that  the  loadstone 
must  have  a  Vital  Principle  because  it  gives  motion 
to  iron. 

Diogenes,  together  with  some  other  writers,  held 
the  Vital  Principle  to  be  air,  because  air  was  believed 
to  be  the  most  attenuated  of  the  elements,  as  well  as 
an  originating  cause ;  and  that,  through  these  proper- 
ties, the  vital  principle  is  able  both  to  recognise  things 
and  to  impart  motion  to  them.  They  argued  that 
Vital  Principle,  as  being  a  first  cause  and  the  origin 
of  other  things,  is  able  to  recognise  them ;  and  that, 
as  being  the  most  attenuated  of  entities,  it  is  motive. 

Heraclitus  also  maintains  that  the  Vital  Principle 
is  a  first  cause,  since,  in  his  system,  it  is  the  exhala- 
tion out  of  which  he  constitutes  every  thing  else ;  he 
regards  it  too  as  the  most  incorporeal  of  entities,  and 
as  being  "in  a  constant  state  of  flux;"  and  further 
says,  that  the  moved  must  be  known  to  the  motor. 
He  agreed,  in  fact,  with  most  others  in  believing  all 
things  to  be  in  motion. 

The  opinions  of  Alcmaeon  upon  the  Vital  Principle 
seem  to  be  very  like  those  just  cited — for  he  says  that 
it  is  immortal,  on  account  of  its  resemblance  to  the 


CH.  II.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  25 

immortals,  and  that  this  resemblance  is  manifested  by 
its  being  continuously  in  motion ;  for  all  divine  bodies, 
he  argues,  the  moon,  sun,  stars,  and  heavens,  are  con- 
tinuously moving. 

Some  writers  of  smaller  pretension — and  Hippo 
was  one  of  them — have  ventured  to  represent  the  Vital 
Principle  as  water ;  and  they  seem  to  have  been  led 
to  this  persuasion  by  the  nature  of  semen,  which,  in 
all  creatures,  is  fluid.  Hippo,  indeed,  reproves  those 
who  assert  that  the  Vital  Principle  is  blood,  because 
blood  is  not  semen ;  and  semen  is,  according  to  him, 
the  first  principle  of  life. 

Others  have  maintained,  as  did  Critias,  that  the 
Vital  Principle  is  blood,  from  their  assuming  that 
the  most  peculiar  property  of  blood  is  feeling,  and 
that  feeling  is  imparted  to  us  through  the  nature  of 
blood.  All  the  elements,  in  fact,  have  had  their 
partisans,  excepting  earth;  and  no  one  has  adopted 
it,  unless  such  an  opinion  may  be  attributed  to  those 
who  have  derived  the  Vital  Principle  from  all,  or 
made  it  to  be  all  the  elements. 

Thus,  all  these  philosophers  define  Vital  Principle 
by  the  three  properties,  motion,  feeling,  and  incorpo- 
reity,  each  of  which  is  referrible  to  first  causes.  Such 
of  them,  therefore,  as  define  it  by  the  faculty  of 
knowing,  make  it  to  be  an  element  or  a  derivative 
from  the  elements,  and,  with  one  exception,  their 
opinions  coincide ; — for  they  all  maintain  that  like  is 


26         ARISTOTLE   ON   THE    VITAL   PRINCIPLE.      [BK.  I. 

known  to  like,  and,  since  the  Vital  Principle  recog- 
nises all  things,  they  constitute  it  out  of  all  first 
causes.  But  such  as  admit  of  only  one  cause  and 
one  element,  set  down  Vital  Principle  as  being  that 
one,  be  it  fire  or  air ;  and  such  as  admit  of  several 
first  causes,  set  down  Vital  Principle  as  being  multi- 
ple also.  Anaxagoras  stands  alone  in  maintaining 
that  mind  is  impassive  and  without  anything  in  com- 
mon with  aught  else ;  but,  even  were  it  so,  he  has 
not  explained,  nor  is  it  easy  from  what  he  has  said  to 
explain,  how  or  for  what  purpose  it  is  to  recognise 
anything.  So  many  writers  as  admit  contraries 
among  first  causes,  constitute  the  Vital  Principle 
out  of  contraries,  and  so  many  as  admit  only  one 
contrary,  whether  hot  or  cold,  or  other  analogous 
contrast,  make  the  Vital  Principle  to  be  that  one. 
Hence,  led  by  the  terms,  some  maintain  that  Vital 
Principle  is  heat,  because  from  heat  the  term  life  has 
been  adopted;  and  others  affirm  that  it  is  cold,  because 
from  cold,  through  respiration,  the  term  Vital  Prin- 
ciple has  been  derived. 

Such,  then,  the  opinions  which  have  been  trans- 
mitted to  us  upon  Vital  Principle,  and  such  the 
reasons  upon  which  those  opinions  have  been 
grounded. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  III. 

THIS  chapter  is  upon  motion,  and  its  purport  is  to  learn 
whether  the  Vital  Principle  is  in  motion  or  at  rest, 
and  if  in  motion,  whether  self-moved  or  in  motion 
imparted  to  it ;  its  object  is  also  to  inquire  whether 
motion  proceeds  directly  from  Vital  Principle, 
whether,  that  is,  it  impels  to  move  while  it  is  itself 
at  rest,  or  whether  it  imparts  to  the  body  the 
motions  which  it  first  communicates  to  itself.  Aris- 
totle *  admits  of  the  six  following  modes  of  motion  : 
generation,  corruption,  growth,  decay,  change  and 
locomotion,  which  are  all  vital  processes ;  but  as,  in 
a  succeeding  passage  of  this  chapter,  he  speaks  of 
only  four  modes,  he  may  have  supposed  that  the  two 
first  are  included  in  the  four  last.  There  is  an 
incidental  allusion  to  movement  by  conveyance,  to 
movement,  that  is,  without  progression.  The  inquiry 
proceeds  to  the  question  whether  Vital  Principle  is 
•  self-motive,  and,  if  so,  whether  it  is  or  not  still 

1  Metaphys.  ill.  7. 


28  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [fiK.  I. 

subject  to  motion  by  impulse  from  without,  which 
seems  to  be  answered  in  the  negative ;  for  it  can 
scarcely  be  admitted  that  this  Principle  can  be 
subject  to  external  impulse,  since  its  movements,  if  it 
do  move,  must  result  from  sensual  impressions. 


CHAPTER  III. 

BEFORE  proceeding  farther,  let  us  consider  the  nature 
of  motion ;  for  it  may  not  only  be  untrue  that  Vital 
Principle  is,  as  some  affirm,  essentially  self-motive  or 
capable  of  producing  motion ;  but  it  may  be  one  of 
those  entities  to  which  motion  cannot  possibly  be- 
long ;  and  it  lias  already  been  said  that  the  motor  is 
not  necessarily  itself  in  motion. 

Everything  moved  admits  of  being  moved  in  two 
ways :  either  by  itself  or  by  something  else ;  and  by 
something  else  we  mean  whatever  is  moved  from 
being  in  something  which  is  moving,  as  sailors  for 
instance, — for  they  are  not  moved  as  is  the  vessel, 
since  it  is  moved  by  itself,  but  they  are  moved  from 
being  in  that  which  is  moved.  This  is  clear  by 
reference  to  their  limbs — a  particular  movement  of 
the  feet  is  walking,  and  walking  is  man's  progression; 
but  the  sailors  do  not  at  that  time  move  by  walking. 
Since  then  motion  may  be  spoken  of  in  this  two-fold 


CH.  III.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  29 

sense,  let  us  consider  whether  the  Vital  Principle 
moves  by  itself,  and  whether  it  partakes  also  of 
motion  communicated  to  it.  As  there  are  four  kinds 
of  movement,  tram  I  ition,  change,  growth,  decay,  it 
follows  that  the  Vital  Principle  should  move  accord- 
ing to  one,  or  more  than  one,  or  all  of  them ;  and 
if  it  do  not  move  by  chance,  then  motion  must  be 
natural  to  it;  and  if  so,  then  locality,  for  all  the 
movements  above  alluded  to  are  local. 

But  if  Vital  Principle  be  essentially  self-motive, 
then  accidental  movement  will  not  belong  to  it  as  to 
a  white  colour  or  a  length  of  three  cubits ;  for  these 
properties  do  move,  but  then  it  is  by  accident,  and 
owing  to  the  bodies  to  which  they  belong  happening 
to  be  in  motion.  Thus,  there  cannot  be  for  them  any 
locality  as  there  will  be  for  the  Vital  Principle,  if  it 
partakes  of  motion  by  its  own  nature.  Although, 
however,  it  may  be  in  motion  by  its  own  nature,  it 
may  still  be  moved  by  force,  and  if  by  force,  still  by 
nature;  and  the  same  holds  good  for  the  state  of 
rest.  Thus,  the  point  towards  which  anything  is  by 
its  nature  moved,  serves  also  by  nature  for  its  point 
of  rest,  as  equally  the  point  to  which  anything  is 
moved  by  force  serves  also,  by  force,  for  its  point  of  rest. 
It  is  not  easy,  however,  even  conjecturally  to  deter- 
mine what  will  be  the  forced  movements  and  forced 
states  of  rest  of  the  Vital  Principle — if  its  motion  be 
upwards  it  will  be  fire,  if  downwards,  earth,  for  such 


30  ARISTOTLE  ON   THE  [BK.  I. 

are  the  tendencies  of  those  elements ;  and  this  conclu- 
sion applies  equally  to  the  intermediate  movements. 
Since  the  Vital  Principle  besides  appears  to  give 
motion  to  the  body,  it  is  probable  that  it  communi- 
cates to  the  body  the  motions  which  it  imparts  to 
itself,  and,  if  so,  the  converse  may  be  true  that  it 
communicates  to  itself  the  motions  which  it  imparts 
to  the  body.  Now,  the  body  is  moved  by  translation, 
so  that  the  Vital  Principle  should  change  with  the 
body  and  be  set  free  from  it,  either  wholly  or  in  its 
parts ;  and  if  this  is  admitted,  it  should  follow  that 
the  Vital  Principle,  having  gone  forth  from  the  body, 
might  re-enter,  and  the  consequence  of  this  would  be 
that  the  dead  bodies  of  animals  rise  again. .  Could 
the  Vital  Principle  be  subject  to  casual  motion  com- 
municated by  some  other  power  than  its  own,  then 
an  animal  might  be  impelled  to  move  by  impulse 
from  without;  but  it  is  noway  necessary  that  that 
which  is  essentially  self-motive  should  be  moved  by 
something  else,  unless  by  mere  chance,  any  more 
than  that  which  is  good,  in  and  for  itself,  should  be 
so  by  or  for  the  sake  of  something  else.  It  may  be 
confidently  affirmed  besides,  that  the  Vital  Principle, 
if  it  do  move,  is  moved  by  objects  which  act  upon 
the  senses.  Although,  however,  Vital  Principle 
should  be  self-motive,  it  would  still  be  in  motion, 
and  thus,  as  all  motion  is  displacement  of  that  which 
moved,  as  being  moved,  the  Vital  Principle  might 


CH.  III.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  31 

be  displaced  from  its  essence,  unless  its  self-motion 
were  a  casual  property ;  but  self-motion  is  of  its  very 
essence. 

Some  philosophers  maintain  that  the  Vital  Prin- 
ciple moves  the  body  in  which  it  is,  as  it  is  itself 
moving, — and  this  is  the  opinion  of  Democritus,  who 
expresses  himself  almost  in  the  words  of  the  comic 
poet  Philippus,  who  charges  "  Daedalus  with  having 
made  a  wooden  Venus  to  become  movable,  when 
quicksilver  was  poured  into  it."  Democritus,  in  feet, 
says  much  the  same  thing  when  he  maintains  that 
indivisible  spheres  are  in  motion,  from  their  having 
been  by  nature  constituted  never  to  remain  at  rest, 
and  that  these  spheres  drag  along  with  them  and  give 
motion  to  all  things.  But  we  will  ask  Democritus 
whether  it  is  those  self-same  spheres  which  produce 
the  state  of  rest,  and  it  will  be  difficult  or  rather  im- 
possible for  him  to  explain  how  they  are  to  do  so.  It 
is  not  thus,  besides,  that  the  Vital  Principle  appears 
to  give  motion  to  an  animal,  as  it  acts,  generally 
speaking,  by  some  kind  of  election  and  thought. 

It  is  in  this  same  manner,  however,  that  Timseus 
physiologically  explains  how  the  body  is  moved  by 
the  Vital  Principle — that,  from  its  being  in  motion, 
the  body,  with  which  it  has  been  interwoven,  is 
moved  also ;  and  having  constituted  it  out  of  the  ele- 
ments, and  divided  it  according  to  harmonic  numbers, 
in  order  that  it  may  have  an  innate  sense  of  harmony, 


32  ARISTOTLE   ON  THE  [BK.  I. 

and  that  the  universe  may  move  in  accordant  orbits, 
he  bent  the  straight  line  into  a  circle,  and  dividing 
that  circle  into  two  united  in  two  parts,  he  again  di- 
vided the  single  circle  into  seven  others,  as  if  to  indi- 
cate that  the  orbits  of  the  sky  are  the  movements  of 
the  Vital  Principle. 

But,  in  the  first  place,  it  is  not  correct  to  say  that 
the  Vital  Principle  is  magnitude,  for  Timaeus  evi- 
dently means  that  this  Principle  of  the  universe  is 
such  as  is  the  so-called  mind ;  and,  then,  that  Principle 
of  the  universe  can  resemble  neither  the  sentient  nor 
the  concupiscent  faculty,  as  neither  of  these  moves  in 
a  circle.  The  mind  is  one  and  continuous  as  is  cogi- 
tation, and  cogitation  as  are  thoughts,  and  thoughts  are, 
by  concatenation,  one,  in  the  sense,  not  of  magnitude, 
but  of  number ;  and,  therefore,  the  mind  is  not  con- 
tinuous in  the  sense  of  magnitude,  but  either  it  is 
without  parts,  or,  at  all  events,  not  continuous  as 
magnitude.  How,  indeed,  were  it  magnitude,  is  it  to 
think — as  a  whole,  or  by  some  one  of  its  parts  ?  But 
parts  must  be  regarded  either  as  magnitude,  or  as 
points,  if,  indeed,  a  point  may  be  regarded  as  a  part; 
and,  if  parts  be  considered  as  points,  then,  as  points 
are  innumerable,  the  mind,  clearly,  will  never  be  able 
to  recount  them  all,  and  if,  as  magnitude,  the  mind 
will  have  to  dwell  very  often,  or  rather  continuously, 
upon  the  same  subject.  But  it  is  manifest  that  think- 
ing may  be  exercised  once  for  all.  If,  besides,  it 


GH.  III.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  33 

suffice  for  thinking,  that  there  should  be  contact  by 
some  one  of  its  parts,  why  should  it  move  in  a  circle, 
or  why  be  magnitude?  And  if  necessary  for  thinking 
that  there  should  be  contact  by  the  whole  circle,  then 
what  means  contact  by  its  parts?  How,  besides, 
shall  that  which  has  parts  think  by  that  which  is 
without  parts,  or  that  which  is  without  by  that  which 
has  parts  ?  Thus,  it  follows  that  the  mind  must  be 
that  circle:  for  thinking  is  the  movement  of  the  mind, 
as  the  periphery  is  the  movement  of  the  circle ;  and, 
if  thinking  be  the  periphery  of  the  mind,  the  mind 
may  be  regarded  as  the  circle,  of  which  thinking  is 
the  periphery.  But  then  the  mind  will  be  ever 
thinking,  and  necessarily  so,  since  the  peripheral 
movement  is  unceasing.  Now,  there  are  limits  to 
practical  thoughts,  (as  all  such  are  for  the  sake  of 
something  else,)  and  so  equally  there  are  to  specu- 
lative thoughts,  in  their  reasons ;  and  every  reason  is 
either  a  definition  or  a  demonstration.  Thus,  demon- 
strations set  out  from  a  principle,  and  are,  in  some 
way,  terminated  by  a  syllogism  or  a  conclusion;  and 
even  though  not  concluded,  they  do  not  revert  to 
their  principle,  but,  taking  up  another  mean  and  ex- 
treme, they  proceed  on  ward ;  but  the  periphery,  on 
the  contrary,  does  revert  to  its  point  of  departure. 
Definitions,  however,  are  always  limited.  If,  more- 
over, the  same  periphery  recur  often,  the  mind  will 
be  driven  to  think  often  upon  the  same  subject,  and 

3 


34  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  I. 

thinking,  besides,  seems  rather  to  be  a  kind  of  rest 
and  a  halt  than  motion ;  and  this  applies  equally  to 
the  syllogism.  As  every  condition,  besides,  which  is 
compulsory  and  ungenial  must  be  unhappy,  so  unless 
movement  be  an  essential  property  of  that  mind,  it 
must  be  moving  against  its  nature,  and  it  cannot  but 
be  painful  for  it  to  have  been  so  connected  with  the 
body  as  to  be  unable  to  free  itself  from  it;  nay  more, 
it  is  a  lot  to  have  been  avoided,  since  it  is  better  for 
the  mind,  as  is  commonly  said,  and  to  many  seems 
reasonable,  not  to  have  been  connected  with  a  body 
at  all.  The  cause  too,  of  the  circular  movement  of 
the  sky  is  obscurely  stated — for  the  essence  of  the 
Vital  Principle  is  not  the  cause  of  that  movement,  as 
it  never  does,  excepting  it  be  by  chance,  so  move,  nor 
can  the  body  be  the  cause,  as  it  is  the  Vital  Principle 
rather  which  gives  motion  to  it;  neither  is  it  ex- 
plained how  it  is  better  for  the  Vital  Principle  to  be 
so  circumstanced,  and  yet  it  ought  to  have  been 
shewn  that  God  had  caused  it  to  have  a  circular 
movement,  as  better  for  it  to  be  in  motion  than  at 
rest,  and  to  move  in  that  rather  than  in  any  other 
direction.  But  as  this  is  an  inquiry  which  belongs 
rather  to  other  studies,  it  may,  for  the  present,  be  laid 
aside. 

The  same  incongruity  which  occurs  in  most  of 
the  theories  upon  Vital  Principle  is  met  with  here,  in 
that  writers  join  Vital  Principle  to  and  place  it  in  a 


CH.  III.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  35 

body  without  having  first  settled  for  what  purpose  the 
body  is  to  receive  it,  or  how  it  is  fitted  for  the  office. 
It  would  seem,  however,  to  be  necessary  that  this 
should  be  settled,  as  it  is  through  this  connexion  that 
the  one  acts  and  the  other  is  acted  upon,  that  the  one 
moves  and  the  other  is  moved ;  and  these  are  relations 
which  cannot  be  attributed  to  casual  associations. 
There  are  writers  who  content  themselves  with  saying 
what  Vital  Principle  is,  without  determining  any 
thing  about  the  body  its  recipient,  as  if  it  were  ad- 
missible, according  to  Pythagorean  legends,  that  any 
kind  of  Vital  Principle  might  clothe  itself  with  any 
kind  of  body;  but  every  thing,  on  the  contrary,  seems 
to  have  its  own  particular  character  and  form.  Such 
opinions  are,  in  fact,  very  much  like  maintaining  that 
the  builder's  art  may  be  undertaken  with  musical  in- 
struments; but  we  affirm  that  as  each  art  must  employ 
its  own  instruments,  so  each  Vital  Principle  must 
employ  its  own  body. 


3—2 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  IV. 

THIS  chapter  opens  with  a  definition  of  harmony,  and 
proceeds  to  shew  that  the  then  prevailing  opinion 
concerning  the  Vital  Principle,  as  related  to  har- 
mony, is  not  maintainable ;  it  is  not  quite  agreed 
upon  whether  the  popular  disquisitions  here  alluded 
to  are  Aristotle's  commentary  upon  the  Phsedo ;  or 
his  dialogue  of  Endemus ;  or  a  digest  of  his  own 
oral  teachings.  The  words  in  the  original  (\6yov<:  2' 
oto-rrep  evQvvas,  K.T.X.),  which  are  rendered  "  found  to 
be  wanting"  (Gallice,  dont  nous  avons  deja  fait  justice), 
signify  strictly  the  scrutiny  or  passing  of  the  accounts 
of  magistrates  at  the  close  of  their  period  of  service, 
and  while  the  result  was  yet  on  the  balance  ;  but,  to 
judge  by  the  context,  they  seem  here  to  imply  rather 
an  unfavourable  issue,  and  this  is  the  purport  of 
other  versions — "  alia  qusedam  opinio  de  anima 
tradita  reprobata  tamen,  et  his  rationibus  quae  in 
communisms  sermonibus  fiunt"  The  chapter  closes 
with  a  confutation  of  the  opinion  of  Xenocrates,  that 
the  Vital  Principle  is  a  number  with  self-motion. 


CHAPTER  IV. 


ANOTHER  opinion  upon  the  Vital  Principle  has  been 
handed  down,  which  to  many  is  not  less  acceptable 
than  any  one  of  those  already  alluded  to,  but  which, 
having  been  scrutinized  in  our  popular  disquisitions, 
has  been  found  to  be  wanting.  The  supporters  of 
this  opinion  say,  that  the  Vital  Principle  is  some  kind 
of  harmony  ;  that  harmony  is  a  mixture  and  compound 
of  contraries,  and  that  the  body  is  constituted  of  con- 
traries. But  although  harmony  is  a  certain  propor- 
tion or  compound  of  particles  mixed  together,  it  is  not 
possible  that  the  Vital  Principle  should  be  the  one  or 
the  other ;  for  it  forms  no  part  of  harmony  to  produce 
motion,  but  all  writers  agree  in  assigning  motive 
power  to  the  Vital  Principle  as  its  most  characteristic 
property.  The  term  harmony,  besides,  is  applicable 
rather  to  health  and  the  corporeal  powers  in  general, 
than  to  the  Vital  Principle,  as  would  be  very  manifest 
to  any  one  who  should  undertake  to  account,  by  any 
harmony,  for  the  emotions  and  functions  of  the  Vital 
Principle  ;  for  it  would  be  scarcely  possible  to  recon- 
cile them  to  one  another.  If  harmony,  besides,  may 


38  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  I. 

be  spoken  of  with  reference  to  two  points — as  appli- 
cable, most  especially,  to  the  composition  of  particles 
in  masses  which  have  motion  and  proportion,  when- 
ever they  may  so  coalesce  as  not  to  admit  of  any 
which  are  homogeneous,  and  then  as  applicable  to  the 
proportion  of  the  commingled  particles,  yet  in  neither 
sense  can  it  be  reasonable  to  regard  Vital  Principle  as 
harmony,  nor  can  the  Vital  Principle  be  the  compo- 
sition of  the  parts  of  the  body :  for  the  composition  of 
the  parts  (and  many  and  various  are  the  compositions 
of  the  parts)  is  quite  open  to  examination — but  of 
what  can  we  suppose  that  the  mind,  or  the  sentient, 
or  the  appetitive  faculty  is  a  composition  ?  or  how  is 
any  one  of  them  to  be  composed  ?  It  is  equally 
absurd  to  think  that  the  Vital  Principle  can  be  the 
proportion  of  the  mixture,  since  the  mixture  of  the 
elements  which  forms  flesh  is  differently  proportioned 
from  that  which  forms  bone.  It  will  happen,  too, 
from  this  theory,  that  there  are  many  Vital  Principles, 
and  many  in  every  body,  if  all  bodies  are  from  the 
elements  in  combination,  and  if  the  proportion  of  the 
combination  is  harmony  and  Vital  Principle.  We 
might  inquire  too  of  Empedocles,  who  maintains  that 
each  of  those  bodies  exists  in  a  certain  proportion, 
whether  Vital  Principle  is  the  proportion  ?  or  whether 
rather  is  it  present  in  the  members,  as  something 
different  from  proportion?  Is  affinity,  besides,  the 
cause  of  a  fortuitous  or  a  definite  combination  of 


CH.  IV.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  39 

parts  ?  And  then,  again,  is  affinity  the  proportion, 
or  something  besides  the  proportion  ? 

Such  are  the  difficulties  which  present  themselves; 
but  if  the  Vital  Principle  is  something  different  from 
the  composition,  what  is  that  which  is  simultaneously 
destroyed  with  the  life,  in  the  flesh,  and  other  parts 
of  an  animal  ?  Besides  these  questions,  since  each  of 
the  parts  of  the  body  has  not  Vital  Principle,  unless 
the  Vital  Principle  is  the  proportion  of  the  composi- 
tion in  the  parts,  what  is  that  which  is  destroyed 
when  the  Vital  Principle  has  forsaken  the  body?  It 
is  then  clear,  from  what  has  been  adduced,  that  Vital 
Principle  can  neither  be  any  kind  of  harmony,  nor  be 
moving  in  a  circle. 

But  to  maintain  that  the  Vital  Principle  is  moved 
by  accident  is  to  maintain,  as  we  have  said,  that  it 
moves  itself  as  it  is  moved  in  that  in  which  it  is,  and 
which  is  moved  by  it;  and  that  it  cannot  possibly 
have  locomotion  in  any  other  way.  It  might,  how- 
ever, with  greater  probability  be  doubted,  and  for  the 
following  considerations,  whether  it  moves  at  all — 
for  we  are  accustomed  to  say  that  the  Vital  Principle 
is  daring  or  afraid,  is  angry  too,  and  both  feels  and 
thinks,  and  as  all  these  seem  to  be  motions,  it  might 
be  supposed  that  the  Vital  Principle  does  move.  But 
yet  this  is  no  necessary  consequence — for  if  to  grieve, 
to  rejoice  or  think  are  motions,  in  the  fullest  sense, 
then  each  of  them  is  motion,  and  motion  may  be  said 


40  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  I. 

to  emanate  from  the  Vital  Principle,  as  anger  or  fear 
is  produced  by  the  heart  being  moved  in  this  or  that 
manner,  and  thinking  may  be  some  analogous  or 
different  kind  of  motion ;  but  some  of  these  phseno- 
mena  are  produced  by  the  displacement  of  certain 
particles  in  motion,  and  others  by  change,  the  expla- 
nation of  the  quality  and  manner  of  which  is  foreign 
to  the  present  inquiry. 

Now  to  maintain  that  the  Vital  Principle  is  angry 
is  very  much  like  saying  that  it  weaves  or  builds,  and 
thus  it  would,  perhaps,  be  better  to  say,  not  that 
Vital  Principle  pities,  learns  or  thinks,  but  that  the 
man,  by  his  Vital  Principle,  is  so  affected  or  so 
engaged.  It  is  not,  however,  hereby  implied  that 
motion  is  in  the  Vital  Principle,  but,  on  the  contrary, 
that  sometimes  it  proceeds  to,  and  sometimes  comes 
from  it;  as  sentient  impression  is  from  external  objects, 
and  recollection  comes  from  it  to  the  movements  or 
impressions  abiding  in  the  sentient  organs.  The 
mind  seems  to  be  a  peculiar  innate  essence,  and  to  be 
indestructible ;  were  it  destructible,  however,  it  would, 
in  an  especial  sense,  be  so  by  the  dulness  attendant 
upon  age,  when  probably  that  happens  to  the  mind 
which  takes  place  in  the  sentient  organs ;  for  if  an 
aged  person  could  take  an  eye  of  a  certain  character, 
he  would  see  as  well  as  a  young  man.  Thus,  the 
infirmities  of  age  are  attributable,  not  to  the  Vital 
Principle  having  been  in  aught  affected,  but  to  its 


CH.  IV.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  41 

recipient  suffering,  as  it  does  from  drunkenness  or 
maladies.  Thus,  too,  thought  and  reflexion  languish 
when  any  thing  within  the  body  has  been  destroyed, 
but  that  which  thinks  is  impassive.  The  properties-, 
therefore,  of  thought,  love  and  hatred  belong,  not  to 
it,  but  to  that  which  contains  it,  and  as  it  contains  it; 
so  that  when  this  recipient  is  destroyed,  it  can  neither 
recollect  nor  love,  as  those  emotions  emanate  not  from 
it,  but  from  that  which  was  in  common  with  it,  and 
which  has  perished.  But  the  mind  is  probably  some- 
thing more  divine,  and  it  is  impassive. 

It  is,  then,  manifest  from  what  has  been  adduced, 
that  Vital  Principle  cannot  be  in  motion;  and  if 
altogether  without  motion,  it  cannot  clearly  be  self- 
moved. 

The  most  unreasonable  by  far  of  all  the  opinions 
upon  Vital  Principle  is  that  which  holds  it  to  be  a 
number  with  self-motion,  for  it  is  beset  with  insuper- 
able objections  ;  those,  in  the  first  place,  which  result 
from  the  idea  of  motion,  and  then  those  more  particu- 
lar objections  to  speaking  of  it  as  a  number.  How, 
indeed,  is  it  possible  to  think  of  an  unit  in  motion  ? 
by  what  or  how,  being  indivisible  and  homogeneous, 
is  it  to  be  moved?  If  said  to  be  both  motor  and 
moved,  it  must  have  distinction  of  some  kind.  Since, 
besides,  they  say  that  a  line  in  motion  forms  a  sur- 
face, and  a  point  in  line,  then  units  in  motion  will 
form  lines,  as  the  point  is  distinguished  from  the  unit 


42  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  I. 

only  by  position;  and  thus  the  number  of  Vital  Prin- 
ciple has  already  locality  and  position.  If,  again, 
from  any  number  there  be  subtracted  a  number  or  an 
unit,  there  remains  a  different  number;  but  plants 
and  many  creatures,  after  having  been  divided,  live 
on,  and  appear  still,  in  a  specific  sense,  to  possess  the 
same  Vital  Principle.  It  might  also  be  supposed  to 
make  no  difference  whether  we  speak  of  the  Vital 
Principle  as  formed  of  units  or  corpuscles ;  for  if 
points  are  substituted  for  the  spherules  of  Democritus 
and  quantity  alone  remains,  there  will  still  be  in  that 
quantity,  as  in  all  continuity,  a  motor  and  a  moved ; 
for  the  theory  takes  account  neither  of  greatness  or 
smallness,  but  only  of  quantity.  Thus,  there  must  of 
necessity  be  something  to  impart  motion  to  the  units. 
But  if  the  Vital  Principle  is  the  motor  in  an  animal, 
so  must  it  be  in  the  number,  and  thus  the  Vital 
Principle,  being  no  longer  motor  and  moved,  is  the 
motor  only.  Even  admitting  that  the  Vital  Prin- 
ciple may,  in  some  way,  be  an  unit,  there  must  still 
be  some  distinction  between  it  and  other  units ; 
but  what  distinction,  save  that  of  position,  can 
there  be  between  one  unit  and  another?  If  then 
the  units  and  points  which  are  in  the  body  are  dif- 
ferent, the  units  will  be  on  the  same  spot  as  the 
points,  for  the  unit  will  occupy  the  place  of  the  point; 
but  what  then  is  there  to  prevent  them  from  being 
infinite  in  number  on  the  same  spot,  even  if  there  be 


CH.  IV.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  43 

only  two,  as  things  are  indivisible  of  which  the 
locality  is  indivisible  ?  But  if  the  points  in  the  body 
are  the  number  of  the  Vital  Principle,  or  if  the  number 
formed  from  the  points  in  the  body  is  the  Vital  Prin- 
ciple, why  have  not  all  bodies  Vital  Principle  ?  Now 
there  seem  to  be  points  in  all  bodies,  and  those  infi- 
nite in  number.  How  besides  is  it  possible  for  the 
Vital  Principles  to  be  separated  and  set  free  from 
bodies,  since  lines  are  not  divisible  into  points  ? 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  V. 

THE  argument  against  the  opinion  of  Xenocrates  that 
the  Vital  Principle  is  "a  number  with  self-motion" 
is  continued,  and  Aristotle,  having  already  objected 
to  it  as  number,  proceeds  here,  after  a  brief  allusion 
to  what  had  been  advanced,  to  object  to  it  as  being 
motive.  If  the  Yital  Principle  be  some  kind  of  body, 
then  however  attenuated  its  parts,  there  must  be  two 
bodies  in  one ;  if  it  be  a  number,  then  as  the  unit  is 
a  point,  unless  that  number  be  innate  and  peculiar, 
every  kind  of  body  must  have  Vital  Principle,  and 
this  cannot  be  admitted.  With  respect  to  its  motion, 
it  had  been  shewn  that  the  unit,  being  homogeneous, 
that  is  without  parts,  cannot  be  so  acted  upon  as  to 
move  ;  if  it  be  motor  and  moved,  it  must,  as  entity, 
have  some  distinction,  and  then  it  is  no  longer  to  be 
regarded  as  an  unit.  The  resemblance  between  this 
theory  and  that  of  Democritus  is  again  alluded  to,  as 
the  same  objection  is  applicable  to  both  ;  for  it  mat- 
ters not  whether  the  motor  be  a  monad,  or  point,  or 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAP.  V.  45 

corpuscle  in  motion,  since  their  motion  is  the  cause  of 
motion  in  other  things  ;  thus,  both  systems  maintain 
a  blind  force,  and  ignore  the  influences  of  sensibility 
and  will.  It  will  probably  be  said  that  the  topic  has 
been  too  long  dwelt  upon,  but  it  should  be  recollected 
what  an  important  part  was  assigned  by  the  Pytha- 
goreans1 to  number,  which  they  derived  from  the 
monad  or  unit,  and  regarded  as  the  origin,  the  mat- 
ter, and  the  essential  properties  of  beings,  and  as  con- 
stitutive of  the  heavens.  It  has  already  been  said 
how,  as  numbers  were  the  first  entities  in  nature, 
they  perceived  resemblances  to  beings  and  qualities 
in  them  rather  than  in  the  elements  fire,  <fec. ;  and 
hence  made  one  combination  to  be  justice,  another 
mind,  and  so  on. 

1  Metapkys.  I.  4,  5. 


CHAPTER  V. 


THE  peculiar  incongruity  to  which  we  have  alluded, 
belongs  as  well  to  those  who  suppose  Vital  Principle 
to  be  some  kind  of  "body  with  tenuity  of  parts,  as  it 
does  to  those  who  with  Democritus  maintain  that  the 
body  is  moved  by  the  Vital  Principle;  for  if  the 
Vital  Principle  is  in  the  whole  sentient  body,  then, 
being  some  kind  of  body,  there  must  necessarily  be 
two  bodies  in  one  and  the  same  body.  And  it  may 
be  objected  to  those  who  speak  of  it  as  a  number, 
that  if  so,  there  must  be  many  points  in  a  single  point, 
or  every  kind  of  body  must  have  Vital  Principle, 
unless  it  is  a  number  innate  and  different  as  well  from 
other  numbers,  as  from  the  points  which  are  in  the 
body.  It  results  too  from  this  theory,  that  an  animal 
is  moved  by  a  number  much  in  the  same  way  that 
Democritus,  as  we  have  said,  gives  motion  to  it ;  for 
what  matters  it  whether  we  speak  of  spherules,  or 
large  units,  or  units  simply  in  motion?  In  either 
case,  the  animal  is  compelled  to  move  from  their  being 
in  motion. 


CH.  V.]      ARISTOTLE   ON   THE   VITAL   PRINCIPLE.        47 

Such  and  many  other  such  objections  may  be 
urged  against  those  who  represent  Vital  Principle  as 
an  intimate  combination  of  motion  and  number ;  as  it 
is  not  only  impossible  therefrom  to  give  any  definition 
of  Vital  Principle,  but  we  affirm  that  it  cannot  even 
account  for  one  of  its  accidents.  And  this  would  be 
evident  to  any  one  who  should  attempt,  by  this 
theory,  to  explain  the  affections  and  functions  of  the 
Vital  Principle, — its  reasonings,  sensations,  pleasures, 
pains,  and  other  such  manifestations ;  for  it  would  be 
difficult,  as  we  have  already  said,  to  form  even  a 
conjecture  concerning  them  from  it. 

Now  three  modes  of  defining  Vital  Principle  have 
been  transmitted  to  us :  some  have  represented  it  as 
the  most  mobile  of  entities  from  being  self-motive ; 
some  as  the  most  attenuated,  and  others  again  as  the 
most  incorporeal  of  entities;  but  we  have  already 
reviewed  those  opinions,  and  shewn  how  very  ques- 
tionable and  contradictory  they  are.  There  remains 
for  us  then  only  to  consider  in  what  sense  Vital 
Principle  can  be  said  to  be  derived  from  the  elements. 
This  opinion  has  been  adopted  in  order  to  explain 
how  the  Vital  Principle  can  perceive  and  recognise 
all  beings  and  things;  but  it  necessarily  involves 
many  and  weighty  objections.  The  supporters  of 
this  opinion  lay  it  down  as  a  fact  that  like  recognises 
like,  which  is  very  much  like  assuming  that  Vital 
Principle  is,  in  some  way,  the  things  themselves ; 


48  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  I. 

but  things  are  never  homogeneous,  as  they  contain 
many  other  particles  besides  their  own;  and  many  or 
rather  infinite  in  number  are  their  mutual  combina- 
tions. Thus  even  if  it  be  conceded  that  the  Vital 
Principle  may  recognise  and  perceive  the  elements  of 
which  anything  is  constituted,  by  what  is  it  to  per- 
ceive or  recognise  the  thing  as  a  whole,  whether  it 
be  a  man,  or  flesh  or  bone  ?  The  same  question  may 
be  put  for  any  other  compound  body ;  as  the  elements, 
constitutive  of  every  such  body  unite,  not  in  any 
fortuitous  manner,  but  in  a  certain  proportion  and 
combination,  just  as  Empedocles  expresses  himself 
with  respect  to  bone — "  The  bounteous  earth,  in  her 
vast  furnaces,  out  of  eight  parts  has  had  allotted  to 
her  two  of  liquid  light,  of  fire  four,  and  bones  were 
made  white."  It  would  be  to  no  purpose  then,  that  the 
elements  should  be  in  Vital  Principle,  unless  propor- 
tion and  combination  were  there  also ;  for  although 
each  element  may  recognise  its  like,  there  will  still 
be  nothing  whereby  to  recognise  a  bone  or  a  man, 
unless  such  things  be  present  with  it  also.  But  it  is 
scarcely  necessary  to  say  that  this  cannot  be;  for 
who  can  have  a  doubt  whether  a  stone  or  a  man  is 
or  is  not  present  in  Vital  Principle  ?  or  good  or  ill, 
or  any  other  quality?  As  the  term  being,  besides, 
admits  of  several  significations  (for  it  signifies  some- 
times a  particular  object,  sometimes  quantity  or  quality, 
or  other  one  of  the  specified  categories),  shall  it  or 


CH.  V.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  49 

not  be  said  that  Vital  Principle  is  derived  from  them 
all  ?  Now,  there  do  not  appear  to  be  any  elements 
which  are  common  to  all  the  categories.  Shall  it 
then  be  formed  only  from  such  elements  as  pertain  to 
the  essence?  How,  in  that  case,  is  it  to  recognise 
each  of  the  others?  Shall  it  be  said  that  there 
are,  for  each  genus,  elements  and  peculiar  principles 
wherewith  the  Vital  Principle  may  be  formed?  If 
so,  it  will  be  quantity,  and  quality  and  essence; 
but  it  is  impossible  that  from  the  elements  of 
quantity  there  should  be  eliminated  essence  without 
quantity. 

Such  and  other  such  difficulties  concur  to  oppose 
the  opinion  of  those  who  say  that  the  Vital  Principle 
is  formed  from  all  the  elements. 

It  is  absurd  to  maintain  that  like  is  unimpression- 
able by  like,  and  yet  assert  that  like  is  able  to  perceive 
and  recognise  like  by  like ;  and  the  more  so,  as  these 
writers  set  down  feeling  as  they  do  thinking  and 
recognising,  as  some  kind  of  impression  and  motion. 
But  to  shew  how  many  doubts  and  difficulties  beset 
the  opinion  adopted  by  Empedocles,  that  "objects 
are  recognised  by  the  corporeal  elements  in  the  rela- 
tion of  like;"  we  have  only  to  observe  that  all 
those  parts  in  animal  bodies,  which  are  simply  of 
earth,  as  bones,  sinews  and  hairs,  seem  to  be  alto- 
gether without  feeling,  and  consequently  without  any 
feeling  of  UJce,  and  yet,  according  to  the  theory,  they 

4 


50  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  I. 

ought  to  be  perceptive.  There  will  be  a  larger  amount 
of  unconsciousness  than  perception,  besides,  allotted 
to  each  principle,  as  each  will  recognise  its  own 
individuals,  but  be  unconscious  of  the  many  others — 
all  the  others,  in  fact,  which  are  unlike.  It  follows, 
too,  from  this  theory,  that  the  god  must  be  the  most 
senseless  of  beings,  as  he  alone  cannot  recognise  the 
element  "  repulsion,"  of  which  all  mortal  beings  can- 
not but  be  conscious,  since  each  of  them  is  derived 
from  all  the  elements. 

But  wherefore,  let  us  ask,  have  not  all  beings  a 
Vital  Principle,  since  every  thing  is  either  an  ele- 
ment, or  derived  from  one  or  from  more  than  one,  or 
from  all  the  elements  ?  Thus,  it  is  necessary  to  every 
being  that  it  should  recognise  some  one  thing,  or 
more  than  one,  or  all  things.  But  we  are  at  a  loss 
to  know  what  that  is  which  individualizes  things: 
the  elements  are  like  matter;  but  that,  whatever  it  be 
which  binds  the  others  together,  must  of  all  be  the 
most  influential.  Now,  it  is  scarcely  possible  that 
any  thing  should  be  more  influential  and  dominant 
than  the  Vital  Principle,  and  quite  impossible  that 
any  thing  should  be  more  so  than  the  mind;  for  it 
is  probable  that  the  mind  was  the  first-born  and 
sovereign  in  nature,  while  these  philosophers  main- 
tain that  the  elements  were  the  first  of  entities. 

None  of  these  philosophers,  however,  neither  they 
who  maintain  that  the  Vital  Principle  is  derived  from 


CH.  V.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  51 

the  elements,  on  account  of  its  recognising  and  per- 
ceiving things,  nor  they  who  regard  it  as  the  most 
motive  of  beings,  can  be  said  to  speak  of  every  Vital 
Principle ;  for  all  sentient  creatures  are  not  motive, 
as  there  are  animals  which  appear  to  be  fixed  abid- 
ingly to  the  same  spot,  and  yet  locomotion  seems, 
according  to  these  philosophers,  to  be  the  only  motion 
imparted  to  animals  by  the  Vital  Principle.  They, 
too,  equally  err  who  form  mind  and  sensibility  out  of 
the  elements — for  plants  appear  to  be  alive,  without 
partaking  either  of  locomotion  or  sensibility;  and 
many  animals  have  no  understanding.  But  even  if 
we  may  pass  over  these  objections,  and  admit  that 
the  mind  as  well  as  the  sensibility  may  be  a  part  of 
the  Vital  Principle,  still  no  general  theory  could  be 
framed  for  every  Vital  Principle,  or  for  it  as  a  whole, 
or  for  it  individually.  Thus,  the  reasoning  in  the 
so-called  Orphic  verses  has  been  stamped  with  this 
same  error,  for  the  poet  says  that  "  the  Vital  Prin- 
ciple, borne  by  the  winds,  enters  from  the  universe 
into  animals  during  respiration."  But  this  cannot 
possibly  be  applicable  to  plants  or  to  some  animals, 
since  there  are  some  which  do  not  breathe.  This 
fact,  however,  had  escaped  the  attention  of  those  who 
first  adopted  the  hypothesis. 

But  even  if  it  be  well  to  form  the  Vital  Principle 
out  of  the  elements,  it  by  no  means  follows  that  it 
should  be  out  of  them  all,  as  one  or  other  part  of  the 

4—2 


52  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  I. 

contraries  is  able  to  judge  both  itself  and  its  oppo- 
site. Thus,  by  the  straight  we  know  both  the 
straight  and  the  curve,  as  the  ruler  is  the  judge  of 
both,  while  the  curve  is  the  judge  neither  of  itself 
nor  the  straight. 

There  are  writers  who  maintain  that  the  Vital  Prin- 
ciple has  been  diffused  through  the  universe,  whence 
probably  Thales  was  led  to  think  that  all  things  are 
full  of  gods.  But  the  opinion  is  not  without  its  diffi- 
culties. Why,  it  may  be  asked,  does  not  the  Vital 
Principle,  when  in  the  air  .or  fire,  form  an  animal 
rather  than  when  in  the  elements  in  combination, 
although  seemingly  more  generally  situated  in  either 
of  those  elements  alone  ?  It  might  also  be  inquired 
why  the  Vital  Principle,  which  is  in  the  air,  is  more 
exalted  and  more  enduring  than  that  which  is  in 
animals.  On  either  side,  in  fact,  we  are  met  by 
absurdity  and  contradiction ;  for  it  is  very  unreason- 
able to  speak  of  air  and  fire  as  animals,  and  absurd 
to  say  that  they  are  not  so  when  Vital  Principle  is 
conceded  to  them.  Those  philosophers,  in  fact,  seem 
to  have  assumed  that  Vital  Principle  is  in  those 
elements,  because  the  whole  ought  to  be  specifically 
as  its  parts ;  and  so  it  was  forced  upon  them  to  admit 
that  Vital  Principle  must  be,  specifically,  the  same  as 
its  parts,  if  creatures  become  living  creatures  by 
taking  in  something  from  that  which  surrounds  them. 
But  if  the  air,  however  subdivided,  is  still  homogeneous, 


CH.  V.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  53 

and  the  Vital  Principle  heterogeneous,  it  is  clear  that 
some  one  of  its  parts  will,  and  some  other  will  not  be, 
in  the  air ;  and  thus  either  the  Vital  Principle  must 
be  homogeneous,  or  else  it  cannot  be  present  in  every 
part  of  the  universe.  It  is  manifest,  then,  from  what 
has  been  adduced,  that  the  faculty  of  recognising  does 
not  belong  to  Vital  Principle  by  virtue  of  its  being 
derived  from  the  elements ;  as  also  that  it  cannot  with 
accuracy  or  truth  be  said  to  be  self-motive. 

Since  the  faculties  of  knowing,  feeling  and  think- 
ing, together  with  desiring,  willing  and  the  appetites 
generally,  as  also  locomotion,  growth,  maturity  and 
decay,  are  properties  of  the  Vital  Principle,  let  us 
inquire  whether  or  not  each  of  those  properties  is 
imparted  to  us  by  the  Vital  Principle  as  a  whole — 
that  is,  does  each  of  those  faculties  emanate  from  the 
Vital  Principle  as  a  whole  ?  do  we  think,  feel,  act  and 
suffer  by  it  as  a  whole,  or  are  different  offices  assigned 
to  different  parts  ?  Is  life  in  one,  or  more  than  one, 
or  in  all  the  parts,  or  is  there  some  other  cause  for 
life  than  the  Vital  Principle  ? 

Some  writers  maintain  that  Vital  Principle  is 
divisible,  and  that  by  one  part  it  thinks,  and  by 
another  feels  desire ;  but  what  then,  if  it  be  naturally 
divisible,  holds  its  parts  together?  Not  the  body 
certainly,  we  answer ;  for  the  Vital  Principle,  on  the 
contrary,  appears  to  hold  it  together,  as  from  the 
moment  of  its  departure  the  body  expires  and  decays. 


54  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  T. 

If  there  be  a  something  which  makes  it  one,  that 
something  is,  in  the  strictest  sense,  Vital  Principle ; 
and  it  will  be  necessary  again  to  inquire  whether  that 
something  is  indivisible  or  with  parts ;  if  it  be  indi- 
visible, then  why  not  at  once  conclude  that  it  must 
be  Vital  Principle?  If  it  be  divisible,  reason  will 
again  seek  to  learn  what  that  is  which  holds  its  parts 
together ;  and  thus  may  the  inquiry  be  continued  in- 
terminably. With  respect  to  the  parts  of  the  Vital 
Principle,  it  is  difficult  to  determine  what  is  the  part 
which  has  been  assigned  to  each  of  them  in  the  body  ; 
for  if  it  is  the  whole  Vital  Principle  which  sustains 
the  whole  body,  it  is  probable  that  each  of  its  parts 
sustains  some  one  part  of  the  body.  But  this  is  very 
like  an  impossibility;  for  it  would  be  difficult  even  to 
conjecture  what  part  the  mind  could  connect  with 
others,  or  in  what  way  it  could  do  so  at  all.  Thus, 
plants,  when  divided,  appear  to  live,  and  so  do  some 
species  of  insects,  as  if  possessing  still  the  same  Vital 
Principle  in  a  specific,  although  not  in  a  numerical 
sense;  for  each  of  the  parts  has  sensation  and  loco- 
motion for  a  time,  and  there  is  no  room  for  surprise 
at  their  not  continuing  to  manifest  those  properties, 
seeing  that  they  are  without  the  organs  necessary  for 
the  preservation  of  their  nature.  Nevertheless,  in 
each  of  those  parts  coexist  all  parts  of  the  Vital  Prin- 
ciple, and  those  parts  are,  specifically,  the  same  with 
each  other,  and  with  the  whole — with  each  other,  as 


CH.  V.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  55 

being  inseparable,  and  with  the  whole  as  being  sepa- 
rable. But  the  living  principle  in  plants  seems  to  be 
a  kind  of  Vital  Principle,  for  animals  and  plants 
alike  partake  of  it ;  and  it  is  separable  from  the  sen- 
tient principle,  but  yet  without  it  no  creature  can 
possess  sensibility. 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  I. 

AFTER  haying  delineated  his  subject  and  quoted  and  com- 
mented on  the  leading  opinions  concerning  it,  Aris- 
totle here  reverts  to  the  definition  of  Vital  Principle, 
which  was  given  partially  at  the  commencement  of 
the  inquiry,  with  the  intent  of  giving  to  it  a  signifi- 
cation comprehensive  enough  to  include  all  living 
beings ;  for  he  had  guarded  us  against  limiting  the 
inquiry  to  the  human  family.  The  argument  com- 
mences as  usual  with  Aristotle,  ab  ovo, — he  attempts, 
that  is,  to  fix  the  meaning  of  essence,  matter  and 
form,  those  primordial  entities  or  conditions,  which 
make  up  and  serve  to  distinguish  all  the  beings  and 
things  of  the  external  world.  These  very  abstruse 
questions  have  been  alluded  to  in  a  former  note,  and 
passages  were  then  cited  from  the  Metaphysics  and 
other  works  for  the  purpose  of  obtaining,  if  possible, 
precise  notions  concerning  them ;  but  these  abstrac- 
tions are  so  shadowy,  and  words  so  fluctuating,  that 
they  seem  to  elude  even  the  perspicacity  of  Aristotle, 


PRELUDE   TO  CHAP.   I.  57 

and  the  ductility  of  his  language.  Essence  is  said 
to  be  a  genus,  to  be  constitutive,  that  is,  with  matter, 
which,  in  itself,  is  no  particular  thing,  of  each  genus 
of  beings  or  things ;  but  then  it  is  form,  which 
realises,  so  to  say,  that  combination  by  conferring 
upon  it  a  specific  character.  For  form  harmonises 
with  all  the  organisation  of  an  animal ;  and  every 
organised  body,  Cuvier  observes,  over  and  above  the 
common  qualities  of  its  tissues,  has  a  peculiar  form, 
not  only  generally  and  exteriorly,  but  even  down  to 
its  minutest  details  ;  and  it  is  "  this  form  which  de- 
termines the  direction  of  each  particular  movement, 
which  supports  the  complicity  of  its  life,  constitutes 
its  species,  and  makes  it  what  it  is1." 

1  Blainville,  i"*  ley  on. 


BOOK    THE    SECOND. 


CHAPTER  I. 

THUS  have  the  opinions  handed  down  by  former 
writers  upon  Vital  Principle  been  delineated ;  and 
now  let  us  retrace  our  steps,  and  again,  as  if  at  the 
outset  of  our  inquiry,  endeavour  to  define  what  it  is 
and  what  the  most  general  expression  for  it. 

We  say,  then,  that  essence  is  a  particular  genus 
of  entities,  and  that  of  it  part  is  matter,  which  in 
itself  is  not  any  one  particular  object,  as  it  is  other 
than  form  and  species  from  which  each  object  derives 
its  particular  denomination;  and  that,  in  the  third 
place,  there  is  the  derivative  from  both  these.  Now 
matter  is  potentiality,  species  reality,  and  that  in  a 
twofold  acceptation,  as  knowledge  and  as  reflexion ; 
but  bodies,  and  above  all  natural  bodies,  seem  to  be 
essences;  for  they  are,  in  fact,  the  origins  of  other 
bodies.  Among  natural  bodies  some  have  and  some 
have  not  life ;  and  by  life  we  mean  the  faculties  of 
self-nourishment,  self-growth  and  self-decay.  Thus, 


CH.  I.]        ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.       59 

every  natural  body  partaking  of  life  may  be  regarded 
as  an  essence ;  but  then  it  is  an  essence  in  combination, 
as^  has  been  said.  And  since  the  body  is  such  a 
combination,  being  possessed  of  life,  it  cannot  be 
Vital  Principle ;  for  as  it  is  itself  more  truly  subject 
and  matter,  it  cannot  be  among  the  subordinates  of  a 
subject.  It  follows,  then,  that  the  Vital  Principle 
must  be  an  essence,  as  being  the  form  of  a  natural 
body  holding  life  in  potentiality ;  but  essence  is  a 
reality, — the  reality,  that  is,  of  a  body  such  as  has 
been  described.  Now  reality  is,  in  the  twofold  signi- 
fication, either  of  knowledge  or  of  reflexion ;  and  that 
it  may  be  regarded  as  knowledge  is  manifest  in  that 
sleep  and  watching  co-exist  as  original  properties,  in 
Vital  Principle ;  and  equally  manifest  that  watching 
is  analogous  to  reflexion  upon  knowledge,  as  that 
sleep  represents  knowledge  possessed  but  not  em- 
ployed. But  knowledge  pre-exists  in  the  same  indi- 
vidual, and  the  Vital  Principle  is,  therefore,  the 
original  reality  of  a  natural  body  endowed  with  life 
in  potentiality ;  only  this  is  to  be  understood  of  a 
body  which  may  be  organised.  Thus,  the  parts  even 
of  plants  are  organs,  but  then  they  are  organs  which 
are  altogether  simple,  as  the  leaf  is  the  covering  of  the 
pericarp,  and  the  pericarp  of  the  fruit ;  and  the  roots 
are  analogous  to  the  mouth,  for  both  take  in  food. 
If,  then,  there  be  any  general  expression  for  every 
kind  of  Vital  Principle,  it  may  be  set  down  as  "  the 


60  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  II. 

incipient  reality  of  a  natural  body  which  is  orga- 
nised" 

It  is,  therefore,  to  no  purpose  to  inquire  whether 
Vital  Principle  and  the  body  are  one,  any  more  than 
whether  wax  and  the  impress  upon  it  are  one,  or 
whether  the  matter  formative  of  any  object  and  the 
object  formed  are  one ;  for  one  and  being  have  many 
significations,  but  they  are  correctly  designated  as 
reality. 

It  has  thus  been  explained  generally  what  the 
Vital  Principle  is,  and  shewn  that  it  is  an  essence, 
in  its  abstract  signification,  which  implies  the  par- 
ticular mode  of  being  in  any  particular  body,  as  if 
any  instrument,  an  axe,  for  instance,  were  a  natural 
body,  the  mode  of  being  in  the  axe  would  be,  at 
once,  both  its  essence  and  its  Vital  Principle;  for, 
were  it  once  to  be  withdrawn,  then,  save  in  name,  it 
could  be  an  axe  no  longer.  All  this,  however,  relates 
to  an  axe,  but  Vital  Principle  is  the  mode  and  the 
cause  of  being,  not  in  any  thing  like  an  axe  but, 
in  a  natural  body,  having  within  it  a  principle  of 
motion  and  of  rest. 

But  what  has  been  said  may  be  better  understood 
by  reference  to  the  parts  of  a  body.  Thus,  if  the  eye 
were  an  animal,  vision  would  be  its  Vital  Principle, 
as  vision,  abstractedly  considered,  is  the  essence  of 
the  eye ;  but  the  eye  is  the  matter  of  vision,  and  if 
vision  be  wanting,  then,  save  in  name,  it  is  an  eye  no 


CH.  I.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  61 

longer,  any  more  than  is  that  an  eye  which  is  repre- 
sented in  sculpture  or  painting.  All  that  has  here 
been  assumed  of  a  part  may  be  made  applicable  to 
the  whole  living  body;  for,  as  there  is  an  analogy 
between  part  and  part,  so  is  there  between  the  whole 
sensibility  and  the  whole  sentient  body,  in  the  ratio 
of  its  sensibility ;  but  this  must  be  understood  of  a 
body  which  yet  retains  its  Vital  Principle,  and  is,  in 
potentiality,  alive.  The  seed  and  the  fruit  are  the 
representatives  of  such  a  body  in  potentiality ;  and  as 
cutting  is  the  reality  of  an  axe,  vision  that  of  an  eye, 
so  watching  is  the  reality  of  Vital  Principle ;  which  is 
to  the  body  what  vision  is  to  an  eye,  and  its  own 
property  to  any  instrument ;  but  this  is  to  be  under- 
stood of  a  body  in  potentiality.  Thus,  as  an  eye  is  a 
pupil  and  vision,  so  an  animal  is  a  body  and  Vital 
Principle. 

It  is  then  obvious  that  neither  Vital  Principle  nor 
any  of  its  parts,  even  granting  that  it  may  be  divi- 
sible, can  be  separate  from  the  body ;  for  of  some  of 
its  parts  it  is  the  reality;  and  yet  there  is  nothing  to 
preclude  the  possibility  of  some  others  being  separate, 
as  there  are  some  which  do  not  contribute  to  the 
reality  of  any  body.  It  is  doubtful,  however,  whether 
the  Vital  Principle  is  the  reality  of  a  body  in  the 
sense  that  a  mariner  is  of  his  vessel. 

Thus  far,  then,  have  we  proceeded  in  our  attempt 
to  define  and  delineate  Vital  Principle. 


PKELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  II. 


As  the  purport  of  this  chapter  is  to  determine  the  essen- 
tial or  characteristic  properties  of  the  Vital  Principle 
in  order  to  attain  to  a  solid  definition,  it  commences, 
very  appropriately,  with  a  short  disquisition  upon 
that  form,  and  a  protest  against  any  deviation  from 
its  real  purport ;  and  thus  the  argument  of  the 
foregoing  chapter  is  continued.  The  opening  para- 
graph is  necessarily  obscure,  from  the  nature  of  its 
topic,  but  it  may  be  practically  at  least  elucidated, 
by  reference  to  similar  topics  in  the  other  works. 
It  is  observed  by  Aristotle1,  that  the  antecedent  is, 
absolutely  speaking,  more  apprehensible  than  the 
sequence,  as  a  point  e.  g.  is  than  a  line,  a  line  than  a 
surface,  and  a  surface  than  a  solid ;  so  too  an  unit  is 
more  apprehensible  than  a  number  (for  the  unit  is 
the  origin  of  all  number),  as  a  single  letter  is  than 
a  syllable.  But  sometimes,  on  the  other  hand, 
the  reverse  of  this  happens — for  as  it  is  the  solid, 

1  Topica,  vi.  4,  5. 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAP.  II.  63 

especially,  which  falls  under  the  senses,  so  the  twrface 
is  more  apprehensible  than  the  line,  and  the  line 
than  the  point;  as  the  multitude  (pi  iro\\o\)  are 
already  conversant  with  them,  while  the  sequences 
are  to  be  acquired  only  by  attention,  or  some  peculiar 
mental  faculty.  Thus,  to  speak  generally,  it  is  best 
to  gather  knowledge  concerning  sequences  through 
their  antecedents ;  for  this  is  by  far  the  most  scien- 
tific mode  of  conducting  an  inquiry.  In  fine,  what- 
ever falls  under  the  senses  seems,  from  being  familiar 
to  us,  to  be  more  apprehensible  than  principles  or 
causes,  which  are  more  or  less  abstractions ;  as,  the 
falling  of  a  stone  seems  to  be  more  apprehensible 
than  the  principle  of  Gravitation.  But  as  the  know- 
ledge of  any  subject  may  be  also  acquired  through 
the  study  of  its  accidents,  that  is,  its  essential  pro- 
perties, so  it  is  suggested  that  the  knowledge  of  Vital 
Principle  may  be  arrived  at  through  the  study  of 
its  faculties. 


CHAPTER  II. 


SINCE  that  which  is  evident  and,  when  abstract- 
edly considered,  more  apprehensible  may  be  derived 
from  particulars  which  are  by  their  nature  obscure, 
although  to  us  more  apparent,  let  us  again  attempt, 
bearing  this  in  mind,  to  attain  to  a  comprehensive 
view  of  Vital  Principle.  It  is  not  only  correct  that 
the  wording  of  a  definition  should  shew,  as  do  most 
definitions,  what  a  thing  is,  but  it  ought  also  to 
embody  and  make  apparent  the  cause  of  its  being 
what  it  is.  But  the  terms  usually  employed  make 
definitions  to  be  kinds  of  conclusions;  as  if,  for 
instance,  to  the  question  "what  is  a  quadrature?"  it 
be  answered,  that  it  is  to  find  an  equilateral  rectan- 
gular figure  equal  to  another  figure  with  unequal 
sides,  such  a  definition  is  the  statement  of  the  con- 
clusion; if  it  be  said  that  the  quadrature  is  "  the 
discovery  of  a  mean  proportional,"  this  conveys  the 
cause  of  the  thing. 

We  say,  then,  resuming  our  inquiry  at  its  outset, 
that  the  animate  is  distinguished  from  the  inanimate 
by  having  life.  Now  the  term  life  has  many  accepta- 


CH.  II.]      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE   VITAL  PRINCIPLE.       65 

tions,  but  if  one  only  of  the  following  properties, 
viz.  mind,  sensibility,  locomotion,  and  rest,  as  well 
as  the  motion  concerned  in  nutrition,  growth,  and 
decay  be  manifested  in  any  object,  we  say  that  that 
object  is  alive.  And,  therefore,  all  plants  seem  to  be 
alive,  for  they  all  appear  to  have  within  them  a 
faculty  and  a  principle  by  which  they  acquire  growth 
and  undergo  decay  in  opposite,  directions;  for  they  do 
not  grow  upwards  exclusively,  but  they  grow  equally 
in  both  these  and  all  other  directions,  and  are  alive 
throughout  so  long  as  they  are  able  to  imbibe  nourish- 
ment. It  is  possible  for  nutrition  to  subsist  inde- 
pendently of  the  other  functions,  but  the  others  cannot 
possibly,  in  mortal  beings,  subsist  without  it;  and 
this  is  manifest  in  plants,  since  no  other  than  it  has 
been  allotted  to  them.  Thus,  it  is  by  this  faculty  of 
nutrition  that  life  is  manifested  in  living  beings,  but  an 
animal  is  characterized  above  all  by  sensibility ;  for 
we  say  that  creatures  endowed  with  sensibility  are 
not  merely  living  beings  but  animals,  although  they 
may  neither  be  motive  nor  change  their  locality. 
Touch  is  the  sense  first  manifested  in  all  creatures, 
and,  as  the  nutritive  faculty  can  be  manifested  inde- 
pendently of  Touch  and  other  senses,  so  the  sense  of 
Touch  can  be  manifested  independently  of  any  other. 
We  call  nutritive  function  that  part  of  Vital  Principle 
of  which  plants  partake ;  but  all  animals  appear  besides 

5 


66  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  II. 

it  to  have  the  sense  of  Touch  ;  and  we  shall,  hereafter, 
explain  why  each  of  those  functions  has  been  allotted. 
Let  it  suffice,  for  the  present,  to  say  that  Vital  Prin- 
ciple is  the  source  of  the  nutritive,  the  sentient,  cogi- 
tative and  motive  faculties ;  and  that  by  them  it  has 
been  defined. 

It  is  easy,  with  respect  to  some  of  those  faculties, 
to  perceive,  whether  any  one  of  them  is  the  Vital 
Principle,  or  a  part  of  Vital  Principle,  and  if  a  part 
whether  it  is  distinct  from  other  parts  substantively, 
or  in  an  abstract  sense  only;  but  there  are  others 
which  seem  to  elude  investigation.  Thus,  as  some 
plants  appear,  after  having  been  divided,  and  after 
the  parts  have  been  separated,  still  to  be  alive,  as  if 
the  living  principle,  in  each  plant,  were  in  reality  one, 
in  potentiality  more  than  one,  so  we  see  the  same 
occurrence  in  other  distinctions  of  the  Vital  Principle, 
as  in  insects  which  have  been  divided ;  for  each  of 
the  parts  manifests  sensibility  and  locomotion,  and  if 
sensibility,  then  imagination  and  desire,  as  wherever 
there  is  feeling,  there  must  be  sense  of  pain  and  plea- 
sure, and  wherever  these,  there  must,  of  necessity,  be 
desire.  We  have  nothing  very  certain  to  offer  upon 
the  subject  of  the  mind  and  the  reflective  faculties; 
but  the  mind  seems  to  be  another  kind  of  Vital  Prin- 
ciple, and  alone  to  be  capable  of  existing  apart  from 
the  body,  as  the  everlasting  exists  apart  from  the 


CH.  II.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  67 

perishable.  Thus,  it  is  manifest,  from  what  has  been 
adduced,  that  the  other  parts  of  the  Vital  Principle 
are  not,  as  some  say,  distinct  from  the  body,  although 
it  is  clear  that,  when  considered  absolutely,  they  are 
different  from  it ;  for  the  mode  of  being  in  a  sentient 
must  differ  from  that  in  a  cogitative  being,  since 
feeling  differs  from  thinking,  and  this  applies  equally 
to  other  functions  and  faculties.  All  those  faculties 
besides  belong  to  some  animals,  particular  ones  only 
to  others,  and  there  are  others  to  which  one  only 
has  been  allotted,  and  this  constitutes  distinctions 
among  animals,  the  cause  of  which  shall  hereafter  be 
considered.  But  something  very  like  this  has  taken 
place  with  respect  to  the  senses,  for  some  animals 
have  them  all;  others  have  particular  ones  only, 
and  there  are  others  again  which  have  but  one ; 
but  that  one  is  Touch,  which  of  all  is  the  most 
necessary. 

As  that  by  which  we  live  and  feel,  like  that  by 
which  we  understand,  has  a  twofold  signification, 
since  we  speak  of  that  by  which  we  understand  some- 
times as  Knowledge,  and  sometimes  as  the  Vital  Prin- 
ciple, for  we  say  that  we  understand  by  either  of 
them ;  so  equally  does  this  apply  to  that  by  which 
we  are  in  health,  and  which  sometimes  refers  to  a 
particular  part  of  the  body,  and  sometimes  to  the 
whole  body.  Now,  the  two  faculties  alluded  to,  know- 

5—2 


68  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  II. 

ledge  and  health,  are  a  form,  a  " specific  something" 
a  "  relation,"  and  an  action,  as  it  were,  of  a  recipient, 
capable  in  the  one  case  of  knowing,  and  in  the  other 
of  maintaining  health  (for  the  action  of  creative  ener- 
gies seems  to  be  innate  in  the  impressionable  and 
suitably  constituted  subject),  but  the  Vital  Principle 
is  that  by  which  we  live,  feel  and  think,  from  life's 
outset;  so  that,  although  it  may  be  the  cause  and 
form,  it  cannot  be  matter  and  subject.  Thus,  the 
essence  has  a  threefold  signification,  as  we  have  said, 
in  the  sense  of  form,  of  matter,  and  the  compound  of 
the  two ;  and  of  these  matter  is  potentiality,  and  form 
reality  ;  and  since  the  living  being  is  a  compound  of 
the  two,  the  body  is  not  the  reality  of  the  Vital  Prin- 
ciple, but  it,  on  the  contrary,  is  the  reality  of  a  par- 
ticular kind  of  body.  On  which  account  it  is  happily 
assumed  by  some  that  the  Vital  Principle  can  neither 
be  without  the  body,  nor  be  itself  a  body  of  any  kind ; 
for  a  body  it  is  not,  but  yet  it  is  something  of  the 
body,  and,  therefore,  present  innately  in  the  body, 
and  that  peculiarly  constituted.  It  is  not,  that  is,  in 
any  kind  of  body,  as  the  earlier  writers  have  main- 
tained, when  they  attached  it  to  a  body  without  in 
the  least  defining  either  the  nature  or  quality  of  the 
body;  although  it  must  be  against  all  probability 
that  any  kind  of  recipient  should  receive  any  thing 
taken  by  chance.  But  here  all  takes  place  as  might 


CH.  II.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  69 

reasonably  be  expected — for  the  realising  influence 
exists  congenitally  in  its  own  subject,  while  yet 
potential,  and  constituted  of  matter  fitted  for  its 
agency.  It  is  then  manifest,  from  what  has  been 
adduced,  that  the  realising  influence  and  cause  can  act 
only  upon  that  which  is  potentially  capable  of  be- 
coming such  or  such  a  reality. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  III. 

THE  inquiry  into  the  faculties  and  functions  of  living 
beings  is  here  continued,  for  the  purpose  of  deter- 
mining, through  them,  the  source  from  which  life  is 
derived;  and  the  distinction  between  the  animal  and 
vegetable  kingdom  is,  incidentally,  alluded  to.  That 
distinction  is  placed  in  the  presence  or  absence  of 
sentient  properties;  and  so  Lamarck1  distinguishes 
plants,  by  their  want  of  irritability,  that  is  sensi- 
bility, from  animals. 

1  Hist.  Nat.  T.  i.  p.  77. 


CHAPTER  III. 

ALL  the  faculties  of  Vital  Principle  which  have  been 
enumerated  belong,  as  we  have  said,  to  some  crea- 
tures, some  only  of  them  belong  to  others,  and  there 
are  creatures  again  which  have  but  one ;  and  we  spoke 
of  those  faculties  as  the  nutritive,  appetitive,  sentient, 
locomotive  and  cogitative.  Of  these,  the  nutritive 
alone  belongs  to  plants ;  but  to  other  beings  both  it 
and  the  sentient  have  been  imparted;  and  if  the 
sentient,  then  the  appetitive,  for  appetite  is  desire, 
passion  and  volition ;  and  all  animals,  without  excep- 
tion, have  the  sense  of  Touch.  But  the  creature  to 
which  sensibility  has  been  imparted  cannot  but  be 
sensible  of  pleasure  and  pain,  of  what  is  grateful  and 
what  painful ;  and  if  sensible  of  these,  it  must  have 
desire,  as  desire  is  the  appetite  for  what  is  grateful. 
All  such  creatures,  moreover,  have  the  sense  for  food, 
as  they  have  Touch,  which  is  that  sense ;  for  all  ani- 
mals are  nourished  by  what  is  dry  and  moist,  warm 
and  cold,  and  Touch  is  the  sense  for  judging  of  these 
qualities.  But  it  is  only  by  chance  that  the  Touch 
can  judge  of  other  qualities,  as  neither  sound,  colour 
nor  odour  contribute  in  aught  to  nourishment;  and 


72  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  II. 

savour  is  among  tangible  qualities.  Hunger  and 
thirst  are  desires:  the  former  for  what  is  dry  and 
warm,  the  latter  for  what  is  liquid  and  cold ;  and 
savour  is  the  condiment,  as  it  were,  for  both.  As, 
however,  we  shall  be  more  explicit  upon  those  points 
hereafter,  it  may,  for  the  present,  suffice  to  say,  that 
all  such  creatures  as  have  the  sense  of  Touch  have 
appetite ;  it  is  uncertain  whether  or  not  they  have 
imagination,  but  this  also  shall  be  considered  here- 
after. There  are  creatures  to  which,  besides  those 
faculties,  locomotion  has  been  imparted ;  and  others 
again,  as  man,  to  which  have  been  allotted  both 
reflexion  and  mind,  together  with  any  other  and  yet 
nobler  faculty,  if  such  there  be,  than  mind. 

It  is  clear,  then,  that  there  can  be  but  one  defi- 
nition for  Vital  Principle,  as  there  is  but  one  for  a 
geometrical  figure;  for  as  in  geometry  there  is  no 
figure  but  the  triangle  and  its  sequences,  so  neither 
are  there  any  kinds  of  Vital  Principle  save  those 
which  have  been  enumerated.  Could  there,  however, 
be  any  such  common  expression  for  figures,  as  with- 
out being  peculiar  to  any  one,  should  yet  be  applica- 
ble to  all,  so  might  there  be  for  the  Vital  Principles 
alluded  to.  It  would  be  idle,  however,  to  seek  for 
any  such  expression,  in  the  case  either  of  Vital  Prin- 
ciples or  geometrical  figures,  as  should  neither  be 
applicable  to  any  one  of  them  individually,  nor,  put- 
ting aside  individuals,  be  applicable  to  them  as  an 


CH.  III.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  73 

individual  species.  But  still  there  is  an  analogy 
between  the  faculties  of  Vital  Principle  and  geometri- 
cal figures ;  for  as  in  vital  properties,  so  in  geometri- 
cal figures,  the  antecedent  is  ever  present  potentially 
in  the  sequences,  and  as  the  triangle  is  in  the  square, 
so  the  nutritive  is  in  the  sentient  faculty.  Thus,  the 
inquiry  must  be  conducted  with  reference  to  indi- 
viduals, in  order  to  learn  what  is  the  Vital  Principle 
of  each,  as  of  a  plant,  a  man,  or  a  brute ;  and  where- 
fore beings  are  thus  ranged  in  a  series. 

Without  the  nutritive  function  there  can  be  no 
sensibility,  but  in  plants  the  nutritive  exists  without 
the  sentient ;  so  again  without  the  Touch  there  can 
be  no  other  sense,  while  Touch  can  exist  alone,  for 
many  animals  have  neither  sight  nor  hearing,  and  are 
altogether  without  smell.  Among  sentient  creatures 
some  have  and  some  have  not  locomotion,  and,  finally, 
to  a  few  calculation  and  judgment  have  been  imparted; 
and  to  such  among  mortal  beings  as  are  so  endowed 
all  other  faculties  have  been  imparted  likewise.  But 
to  such  as  possess  some  one  only  of  the  faculties, 
calculation  has  not  been  allotted,  as  some  of  them 
have  not  even  imagination,  while  others  live  by  it 
alone ;  it  would  be  foreign  to  our  present  inquiry  to 
enter  upon  the  speculative  intellect. 

It  is,  then,  clear  that  the  definition  which  comes 
closest  to  each  one  of  those  faculties  is  also  the  fittest 
for  the  elucidation  of  Vital  Principle. 


I 
PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  IV. 


THE  opening  paragraphs  of  this  chapter  are  both  obscure 
and  apparently  contradictory ;  for  while  it  is  sug- 
gested that  it  might  be  well,  in  order  to  comprehend 
faculties  or  functions,  first  to  study  the  energies  or 
organs  from  which  they  emanate,  yet  the  inquiry 
reverts  to  nutrition  as  a  fact ;  without  reference, 
that  is,  either  to  vital  processes  or  to  food.  We 
may  assume  that  Aristotle  was  unacquainted  with 
the  rudimentary  forms  and  development  of  the 
corporeal  organs,  and  yet,  judging  from  this  exor- 
dium, he  seems  to  have  perceived  that  every  part 
must  advance  from  a  nascent  state  to  its  perfected 
condition;  and  thus  he  has  suggested  the  teaching 
of  developmental  anatomy.  As  the  inquiry  proceeds, 
we  are  reminded  of  the  obscurity  or  inaccuracy  of 
language,  in  portraying  the  impressions  upon  and 
the  functions,  so  to  say,  of  the  sentient  organs — 
even  now  the  external  object  is,  with  us,  in  common 
parlance,  a  sensible  object ;  sensation,  besides  its  own 


PEELUDE  TO   CHAP.  IV.  75 

sense,  implies  casual  feelings  from  within  ;  sight 
signifies  both  faculty  and  function ;  and  nourish- 
ment is  food  as  well  as  digestion.  It  is  somewhat, 
pei'haps,  objectionable  that  Aristotle  should  have 
bound  up,  so  to  say,  the  generative  with  the  nutri- 
tive function,  seeing  how  they  differ  both  in  the 
periods  of  development  and  duration ;  they  are 
equally  necessary,  no  doubt,  to  nature's  design,  but 
still  they  are  neither  contemporaneous  nor  identical. 
With  respect  to  spontaneous  generation  here  alluded 
to  Aristotle1  admitted  its  possibility,  and  for  obvious 
reasons,  in  the  case  of  eels  j  and,  although  he  denied 
that  all  mullets  (TOUC  K6<rTpe?e  (j)ve<r6ai  Trai/Tas)  are 
so  reproduced,  yet  he  believed  that  some  of  the 
species  spring  forth  (^U'CTOJ)  from  the  mud  and  sand 
on  the  sea-shore ;  and  thus  it  is  evident,  he  continues, 
that  some  creatures,  not  being  derived  from  others, 
may  be  the  product  of  spontaneous  generation.  This 
opinion  upon  reproduction  prevailed  for  many  ages, 
and  even  yet,  perhaps,  notwithstanding  the  advance- 
ment of  science,  it  may  not  be  altogether  discredited. 

1  Hist.  Ani.  vi.  14.  14.  15.  3. 


CHAPTER  IV. 


IT  is  necessary,  in  order  well  to  study  those  faculties, 
that  we  should  comprehend  what  each  of  them  indi- 
vidually is,  and  then,  in  like  manner,  carry  our  inquiry 
into  their  consequences  and  other  conditions.  But  if 
it  behove  us  to  say  what  each  of  them  is,  as  what  is 
the  cogitative,  sentient,  or  appetitive  faculty,  it  should 
previously  be  settled  what  that  is  which  thinks  and 
that  which  feels ;  for  energies  and  acts  are,  abstract- 
edly considered,  pre-existent  to  their  functions.  Grant- 
ing, however,  that  it  is  so,  and  that  we  ought,  before 
the  faculties  or  functions,  to  have  considered  their 
opposites,  it  might  be  fitting  here  also,  and  for  the 
same  reason,  first  to  define  the  opposites  of  the  func- 
tions— define,  that  is,  food  before  nutrition ;  the  object 
before  perception ;  and  the  intelligible  before  thought. 
Thus  we  must  first  speak  upon  nutrition  and 
generation,  for  the  nutritive  faculty  is  innate  in  other 
beings  besides  animals ;  it  is  the  primal  and  most 
universal  influence  of  the  Vital  Principle,  and  through 
it  life  is  manifested  in  all  beings.  Its  functions  are 
to  generate  and  to  employ  nourishment ;  for  the  most 


CH.  IV.]      ARISTOTLE   ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.      77 

natural  of  the  functions  in  beings  which  are  perfect, 
that  is,  which  are  neither  dwarfed  nor  spontaneously 
generated,  is  to  produce  another  such  as  itself,  an 
animal  an  animal,  and  a  plant  a  plant,  in  order  that 
they  may  partake,  to  the  extent  which  has  been 
allotted  to  them,  of  the  Everlasting  and  the  Divine. 
All  creatures  yearn  after  this,  and,  for  the  sake  of  it, 
they  do  all  that  they  do  naturally ;  but  since  such 
beings  cannot,  in  uninterrupted  continuity,  partake  of 
the  Everlasting  and  the  Divine,  because  no  perishable 
being  can  abidingly  continue  as  one  and  the  same ; 
yet  each  can  partake  thereof  in  its  own  allotted  por- 
tion, be  it  larger  or  smaller,  and  still  continue,  if  not 
the  same,  like  the  same,  and  one,  if  not  in  number,  as 
species. 

The  Vital  Principle  is  the  cause  and  the  origin  of 
a  living  body.  Now,  cause  and  origin  have  several 
significations ;  for  the  Vital  Principle  is  equally  a 
cause,  according  to  any  one  of  the  three  defined  modes 
of  causation :  as  that  whence  motion  proceeds ;  as 
that  for  which  motion  is  produced ;  and  cause,  again, 
as  the  essence  of  living  bodies.  It  is  evident  that  it 
is  a  cause  as  an  essence,  since  the  essence  is  in  all 
things  the  cause  of  their  being  what  they  are ;  and 
as  life  is  the  mode  of  being  in  living  beings,  so  Vital 
Principle  is  the  cause  and  the  origin  of  all  such.  It 
is  the  realizing  principle,  besides,  the  cause  that  is  of 
something  which  exists  in  potentiality  becoming  a 


78  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  II. 

reality.  It  is  manifest,  too,  that  Vital  Principle  is  a 
cause,  in  the  sense  of  a  final  cause ;  for  as  the  mind 
acts  for  some  end,  so  does  nature,  and  that  end  is  her 
aim ;  and  such  an  aim  has  the  Vital  Principle,  by  its 
nature,  in  living  bodies.  Thus,  all  natural  bodies, 
those  of  animals  as  well  as  those  of  plants,  are  its 
instruments,  and  are  what  they  are  for  its  purposes. 
The  term  final  cause  has  a  twofold  signification,  as 
it  implies  that  for  which,  as  well  as  that  by  which, 
any  result  is  obtained;  and  Vital  Principle  is  a, final 
cause,  as  that  whence  locomotion  is  derived,  although 
this  is  a  property  which  does  not  belong  to  all  living 
creatures.  Change  and  growth,  moreover,  are  depen- 
dent upon  Vital  Principle ;  for  sensation  seems  to  be 
a  change  of  some  kind,  and  whatever  is  sentient  has 
Vital  Principle ;  and  this  applies  equally  to  growth 
and  decay,  for  nothing  grows  or  decays  naturally 
unless  it  be  nourished,  and  nothing  is  nourished  which 
does  not  partake  of  life.  Empedocles  has  not  ex- 
pressed himself  happily  upon  this  point,  as,  after  other 
observations,  he  adds  that  plants  take  growth  down- 
wards, where  they  strike  root,  from  this  being  the 
natural  direction  of  earth,  and  upwards,  from  this 
being  the  natural  direction  of  fire.  Neither  has  he 
clearly  seized  the  import  of  the  terms  upwards  and 
downwards,  as  they  are  not  identical  for  all  creatures, 
or  for  the  universe ;  for  the  nead  is  to  animals  what 
the  roots  are  to  plants,  if  we  may  speak  of  organs 


CH.  IV.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  79 

after  their  functions,  although  in  other  respects  dif- 
ferent. But,  besides  these  objections,  what  is  that 
which  is  to  hold  fire  and  earth,  with  their  opposing 
tendencies,  together  ?  Now,  unless  there  be  a  restrain- 
ing force,  they  must  be  torn  asunder,  and  if  such 
there  be,  it  ought  to  be  regarded  as  Vital  Principle, 
and  the  cause  both  of  nourishment  and  growth. 

The  nature  of  fire  seems,  to  some  philosophers,  to 
be  the  absolute  cause  of  nutrition  as  well  as  growth, 
and  that  because  it  alone,  among  bodies  or  elements, 
appears  to  be  nourished  and  to  grow.  It  might, 
therefore,  be  assumed,  that  it  is  fire  which  works  out 
those  processes  in  plants  and  animals ;  but  although 
fire  is  possibly  a  joint  cause,  it  cannot  be  the  exclusive 
cause,  as  this  must  be  assigned  rather  to  the  Vital 
Principle.  The  increase  of  fire  is  infinite,  so  long  as 
there  is  any  thing  combustible,  but  to  all  the  bodies 
of  nature's  constitution  there  is  a  limit  and  a  relation 
both  as  to  bulk  and  increase ;  and  these  are  conditions, 
not  of  fire  but  of  Vital  Principle  ;  not  of  matter  but 
of  design. 

Since  the  same  faculty  of  Vital  Principle  is  at 
once  nutritive  and  generative,  it  is  necessary  first  to 
define  nutrition  ;  for  it  is  by  this,  compared  with  other 
faculties,  that  Vital  Principle  is  especially  distin- 
guished. Nutrition,  then,  appears  to  be  a  contrary 
acted  upon  by  a  contrary,  but  this  does  not  imply  any 
kind  of  contrary  by  any  other  contrary ;  it  refers  only 


80  ARISTOTLE   ON  THE  [BK.  II. 

to  such  contraries  as  can  generate  from  and  give 
growth  to  one  another.  Thus,  there  are  many  things 
derived  from  one  another  which  are  not  always  quan- 
tities, as  the  healthy,  for  instance,  is  derived  from  the 
unhealthy ;  neither  do  these  contraries  appear,  in  any 
manner,  to  be  nourishment  for  one  another,  as  water, 
for  instance,  is  nourishment  for  fire,  but  fire  is  not 
nourishment  for  water.  It  is  in  homogeneous  bodies 
especially,  that  the  contraries  seem  to  be  in  the  rela- 
tions of  nourishment  and  nourished.  But  here  there 
is  a  difficulty ;  for  while  some  maintain  that  like  is 
nourished  as  it  is  increased  by  like,  there  are  others 
who  maintain,  as  we  have  said,  that  it  is  contrary 
which  is  nourished  by  contrary ;  that  like  is  unim- 
pressionable by  like ;  that  food  undergoes  change  and 
is  digested,  and  that  all -change  implies  conversion  to 
an  opposite  or  an  intermediate  state.  Nourishment, 
besides,  is  affected  by  the  body  which  is  nourished, 
although  the  body  is  not  affected  by  the  nourishment, 
just  as  the  material  is  affected  by  the  artisan,  although 
he  is  not  affected  by  the  material ;  for  it  is  the  artisan 
alone  who  converts  the  material  from  a  raw  state  into 
one  of  usefulness.  There  is,  however,  a  distinction  to 
be  observed  in  nourishment,  between  its  last  and  ad- 
ventitious or  its  first  state ;  if  both  states  are  nourish- 
ment, distinguished  only  by  the  one  being  undigested, 
and  the  other  digested,  then  it  may  be  correct  to 
admit  of  both  explanations  for  nutrition;  for  in  so 


CH.  IV.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  81 

far  as  food  is  undigested,  it  is  contrary  nourished  by 
contrary,  and  in  so  far  as  it  is  digested,  it  is  like 
nourished  by  like.  Thus,  it  is  manifest  that  both 
these  opinions  are  in  one  sense  right,  and  in  another 
wrong.  But  as  nothing  can  be  nourished  which  does 
not  partake  of  life,  so  a  living  body  may  be  regarded 
as  a  body  which  is  nourished  from  having  life ;  and 
thus  nutrition  is  not  in  a  casual,  but  a  positive  rela- 
tion to  a  living  body.  There  is  an  obvious  distinc- 
tion between  nourishment  and  growth :  in  so  far  as  a 
living  body  is  quantity,  it  is  capable  of  growth,  and  in 
so  far  as  a  something  is  matter  and  essence,  it  is  nourish- 
ment ;  for  it  preserves  the  essence  of  the  body,  which 
exists  so  long  as  it  can  be  nourished.  Nourishment, 
however,  does  not  generate  that  which  is  nourished, 
as  it  is  the  same  as  it ;  for  it  is  already  itself  the 
essence,  and  nothing  can  generate,  although  it  may 
preserve  itself.  Thus,  it  is  the  same  faculty  of  Vital 
Principle  which  is  able  to  preserve  that,  such  as  it 
may  be,  which  contains  it,  and  it  is  nourishment 
which  renders  it  fit  for  its  office ;  and,  therefore,  when 
deprived  of  nourishment,  it  can  exist  no  longer. 

Now,  there  are  here  three  things  or  conditions — 
something  to  be  nourished,  something  by  which 
nourished,  and  something  which  nourishes.  That 
which  nourishes  is  the  primal  or  nutritive  faculty ; 
that  which  is  nourished  is  the  body ;  and  that  by 
which  nourished  is  food.  And  as  things  are  correctly 

6 


82         ARISTOTLE   ON   THE   VITAL   PRINCIPLE.     [BK.  II. 

designated  after  the  object  to  which  they  tend,  and 
as  the  object  here  is  to  generate  another  like  itself, 
so  the  primal  faculty  may  be  set  down  as  being 
generative  of  another  like  itself.  That  "by  which 
nourished"  has  a  twofold  signification,  as  has  that 
by  which  a  vessel  is  steered,  and  which  implies  hand 
and  rudder,  of  which  the  one  only  moves,  while  the 
latter  both  moves  and  is  moved.  It  is  necessary  to 
nutrition  that  food  should  admit  of  being  digested, 
and  as  it  is  heat  which  works  out  digestion,  so  all 
living  creatures  have  heat. 

It  has  thus  then  be  shewn,  although  but  super- 
ficially, what  nutrition  is ;  but  the  subject  shall  be 
further  elucidated  in  other  treatises  upon  the  subject. 


PKELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  V. 

ARISTOTLE,  having  fully  inquired  into  the  process  of  nutri- 
tion, here  enters  upon  the  investigation  of  the  sensi- 
bility or  sentient  system,  which  is,  as  he  said,  the 
line  of  separation  between  animal  and  vegetable 
existence ;  the  inquiry  includes,  of  course,  the  senses 
and  their  organs,  as  well  as  allusions  to  those  ex- 
ternal forces  or  qualities  which  by  their  action  pro- 
duce simultaneous  perception,  that  is,  sensation. 
Sensibility  is  one  of  the  great  mysteries  of  our 
mortal  nature,  but  its  investigation  was,  in  that  age, 
additionally  complicated  and  abstruse,  as  the  brain 
as  well  as  its  relation  to  the  spinal  cord  and  con- 
nexion with  the  organs  of  the  senses  were  unknown. 
But,  although  anatomy  has  detected  the  links  between 
the  brain  and  sentient  organs,  and  thus  shewn  that 
the  senses  are  emanations,  so  to  say,  from  it,  yet  this 
knowledge,  however  otherwise  valuable,  does  not 
explain  how  matter  has  been  constituted  thus  to 
produce  sensation,  and,  by  reflexion,  consciousness. 

6—2 


CHAPTER  V. 

LET  us  now  proceed,  as  those  subjects  have  been 
scrutinized,  to  speak  upon  sensation  in  its  widest 
acceptation. 

Sensation  is  the  combined  result,  as  has  been  said, 
of  a  motion  and  an  impression,  for  it  seems  to  be  some 
kind  of  change ;  and  some  writers  maintain  that  it  is 
only  like  which  is  impressionable  by  like,  but  we 
have  already,  in  our  treatises  "  upon  action  and  im- 
pression" shewn  how  far  the  opinion  is  or  is  not 
tenable.  But  it  is  difficult  to  understand  why  there  is 
no  sensation  from  the  senses  of  themselves,  that  is, 
why,  without  the  presence  of  external  objects,  the 
senses  do  not  give  out  sensation,  although  fire,  earth, 
and  the  other  elements,  from  which  or  the  accidents 
of  which  sensation  is  derived,  are  present  in  them.  It 
is  evident  that  it  is  because  the  sensibility  is  not  in  a 
state  of  activity,  but  is  only  in  potentiality;  and, 
therefore,  that  it  is  with  it  as  with  a  combustible  ma- 
terial, which  alone,  without  something  on  fire,  does 
not  burn ;  for  otherwise  it  might  set  fire  to  itself,  and 
would  stand  in  no  need  of  fire,  in  reality,  for  the  purpose. 
Since  we  speak  of  sentient  perception  in  a  two-fold 


CH.  V.]      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.        85 

sense,  (for  we  speak  of  one  who  hears  and  sees,  in  po- 
tentiality, as  "  one  hearing  and  seeing,"  although  he 
may  happen  to  be  asleep,  and  we  say  the  same  of 
one  who  is  actually  employing  those  senses,)  so  may 
sensation  be  spoken  of  in  two  ways,  as  subsisting  in 
potentiality  and  subsisting  in  activity.  Let  us,  how- 
ever, before  proceeding  further,  observe  that  impres- 
sion, motion,  and  action  are  for  us  equivalent  terms — 
for  motion  is  a  kind  of  action,  although  an  action 
which  is  incomplete,  as  has  been  elsewhere  explained. 
Now,  all  things  which  are  impressed  and  set  in  motion 
are  so  affected  by  something  capable  of  making  im- 
pression and  existing  in  activity;  so  that  impression 
is  in  one  sense  by  like,  and  in  another  sense  by  un- 
like, as  we  have  said — for  the  unlike  is  subject  to 
impression,  but,  having  been  impressed,  it  is  con- 
verted into  like.  A  distinction,  however,  must  be 
drawn  between  the  terms  potentiality  and  reality,  for 
we  are  now  going  to  employ  them  in  an  absolute 
sense — any  individual  whatever,  then,  may  be  learned, 
as  we  might  speak  of  any  man  as  learned,  because 
man  is  among  beings  capable  of  learning  and  being 
learned ;  and  so  we  speak  of  a  man  as  learned,  from 
his  actually  professing,  at  the  time,  grammatical  or 
other  knowledge. 

Thus,  each  of  these  individuals  is  learned  in  po- 
tentiality, although  in  a  different  manner — the  one 
is  so  because  he  is  of  a  certain  genus  and  peculiar 


86  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  IT. 

matter;  and  the  other,  because  he  can  when  he  will 
reflect  upon  his  knowledge,  provided  there  is  no  ex- 
ternal impediment  to  his  doing  so.  It  is  this  one  only, 
however,  when  actually  reflecting  upon  his  know- 
ledge, being  in  activity,  and  fully  acquainted  with 
some  one  subject,  as  A.  for  instance,  who  is  to  be  ac- 
counted learned  in  reality.  Both  those  first  men,  in 
fact,  are  learned  in  potentiality;  but  the  one  is  so 
from  having  been  modified  by  learning,  and  under- 
gone frequent  changes  from  one  habit  to  an  opposite 
one;  and  the  other  is  so  from  possessing  sensibility 
or  rudimentary  learning,  and  being  able,  although  in 
a  different  manner,  to  pass  from  inertia  to  activity. 

But  the  term  impression  is  not  absolute  in  signifi- 
cation, as  sometimes  it  implies  a  kind  of  destruction 
by  a  contrary,  and  sometimes  it  signifies  rather  pre- 
servation of  something  being  \n.  potentiality  by  some- 
thing which  is  in  reality  and  like,  in  the  relation  that 
potentiality  bears  to  reality.  Thus,  the  possession  of 
knowledge  implies  the  power  of  reflecting  upon  it, 
and  this  either  is  not  change,  being  but  an  increase  of 
knowledge  and  a  step  towards  its  completion,  or  it  is 
change  of  a  different  kind.  It  is  not  correct,  there- 
fore, to  say  that  an  individual,  when  thinking,  is  un- 
dergoing change,  any  more  than  that  a  builder,  when 
employed  in  building,  is  undergoing  change;  so  that 
the  process  by  which  an  individual  passes,  as  to  his 
thinking  and  reflecting  faculties,  from  potentiality  to 


CH.  V.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  87 

reality,  ought  to  have  some  other  appellation  than 
that  of  instruction.  We  may  not  then,  as  has  been 
observed,  say  of  the  individual  who,  from  being  in 
potentiality,  learns  and  receives  knowledge  from  one 
who  is  in  reality  and  able  to  teach,  that  he  suffers 
impression,  or  else  it  must  be  admitted  that  there  are 
two  modes  of  change,  one  in  privative  dispositions, 
and  another  over  habits  and  nature.  The  first  change, 
however,  of  this  kind  in  the  sentient  being  comes 
from  the  parent  at  the  moment  of  conception;  as 
from  that  moment  the  being  has,  as  it  were,  learning 
and  sensibility.  There  is  an  analogy  between  the 
state  of  activity  and  reflexion  just  alluded  to,  but 
with  this  difference,  that  the  impressions  productive 
of  activity,  as  the  audible,  the  visible,  and  others,  are 
all  derived  from  without;  and  the  cause  of  this  is 
that  sensation,  in  activity,  is  employed  upon  particu- 
lars, knowledge  upon  universals ;  and  universals  are, 
in  some  way,  in  the  Vital  Principle  itself.  The  act 
of  thinking,  therefore,  is  dependant  only  upon  the  will 
of  the  individual,  which  is  not  the  case  with  sentient 
perception,  as  for  it  there  must  of  necessity  be  ob- 
jects to  be  perceived;  and  this  holds  good,  and  for 
the  same  reason,  with  respect  to  the  sciences  which 
are  engaged  upon  external  objects,  because  all  such 
objects  are  among  particulars,  and  are  external  to  the 
percipient.  But  an  opportunity  may  hereafter  present 
itself  for  the  further  elucidation  of  the  subject. 


88       ARISTOTLE   ON  THE   VITAL  PRINCIPLE.      [BK.  II. 

Let  it,  for  the  present,  suffice  to  say,  that  the 
expression  being  in  potentiality  has  not  an  absolute 
signification,  for  it  may  be  understood  of  a  boy  as 
being  qualified  potentially  to  be  a  General,  and  also 
of  an  individual  of  suitable  age  for  the  office ;  and  the 
term  sensibility  is  subject  to  like  modifications  of 
meaning.  But  as  the  distinction  between  these  two 
states  of  sensibility  is  without  any  special  appellation, 
although  it  has  been  shewn  that  there  is  a  distinction 
between  them  and  what  the  distinction  is,  it  has  been 
found  necessary  to  employ  the  terms  impression  and 
change,  as  if  their  signification  were  unequivocal ;  but, 
as  has  been  said,  the  sentient  principle  is,  when  in 
potentiality,  analogous  to  the  external  object  when  in 
reality. 

The  sentient  principle,  in  fact,  suffers  impression 
when  unlike;  but,  having  been  impressed,  it  is  con- 
verted into  like,  and  becomes  the  same  as  that  by 
which  the  impression  is  made. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  VI. 


THIS  chapter,  adopting  a  former  suggestion,  commences 
with  the  nature  and  influences  of  the  objects  and 
properties  which  act  upon  the  senses.  As  those  pro- 
perties or  influences,  however,  whatever  their  denomi- 
nation, light,  sound,  odour,  savour,  motion,  number 
<kc.,  are  considered  in  their  relation  to  the  senses, 
respectively,  they  here  are  merely  characterized  under 
the  terms,  which  are  defined,  of  peculiar  and  common. 
Casual  or  chance  perception  is  exemplified  by  a  figure 
which  is  far  from  being  apparent. 


CHAPTER  VI. 


LET  us,  before  proceeding  further,  speak  upon  the  ob- 
jects of  perception  in  relation  to  each  of  the  senses. 
The  object  of  perception  is  spoken  of  in  a  three-fold 
manner,  as  there  are  two  ways  in  which  we  speak  of 
perceiving  objects  distinctly,  and  one  in  which  we 
speak  of  perceiving  them  accidentally;  and  of  those 
two  ways  one  signifies  the  property  which  is  peculiar 
to  each  sense,  and  the  other  the  property  which  is 
common  to  all  the  senses.  I  mean  by  peculiar  pro- 
perty that  which  cannot  be  perceived  by  any  other 
than  its  own  sense,  and  concerning  which  that  sense 
cannot  be  deceived — as  colour  for  sight,  sound  for 
hearing,  and  savour  for  taste.  The  touch,  indeed, 
discriminates  several  differences  of  quality,  but  every 
other  sense  distinguishes  only  its  own  subjects ;  and 
thus  sight  or  hearing  is  never  deceived  as  to  whether  it 
is  colour  or  sound  which  is  seen  or  heard,  although  it 
may  be  deceived  as  to  what  or  where  the  coloured, 
what  or  where  the  sonorous  body  may  be. 

Such  then  the   properties  which  are  said  to  be 
peculiar  and  to  belong  to  particular  senses ;  but  there 


CH.  VI.]      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.      91 

are  properties,  such  as  motion,  rest,  number,  form  and 
magnitude,  which  are  termed  common,  as  they  belong 
not  to  any  one  sense,  but  to  all  in  common.  Thus, 
there  is  a  movement  which  is  perceptible  both  by 
Touch  and  Sight.  An  object  is  said  to  be  perceived 
accidentally  when,  for  example,  something  white 
may  be  the  Son  of  Diares — for  the  percipient  is  sen- 
sible of  the  individual  accidentally,  because  of  his 
being  an  accident  of  that  which  is  perceived;  and, 
therefore,  no  impression  is  made  by  that  which  is 
perceived,  as  a  special  object,  upon  the  percipient. 

The  properties  of  bodies,  which  are  in  them- 
selves perceptible,  are,  strictly  speaking,  peculiar 
properties ;  and  to  such  each  particular  sense  is  natu- 
rally and  essentially  related. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  VII. 


THE  treatise  commences  the  examination  of  the  senses 
with  the  Sight,  and  closes  with  the  Touch,  which  is 
somewhat  contrary  to  Aristotle's  estimate  of  their 
relative  importance  ;  for  he  has  shewn  that  the  Touch 
is  the  first,  as  it  is  the  most  universal  of  all  the 
senses,  as  well  as  essential  to  animal  existence.  Thus, 
this  sense  is  to  sentient  creatures  what  nutrition  is 
to  other  beings ;  for  as  without  Touch  there  can  be 
no  animal,  so  without  nutrition  there  can  be  no  life. 
Descartes,  more  in  accordance  with  Aristotle's  teach- 
ing, begins  with  the  Touch,  and  then  proceeds  to  the 
Taste,  Smell,  Hearing  and  Sight ;  and  so  Grant '  makes 
"  all  the  other  senses  to  be  but  modifications  of  the 
Touch."  Cuvier,  however,  reverses  this  it  may  be 
general  order,  and  treats  of  the  special  senses  before 
the  Touch.  It  may  be  well  to  observe,  that  the 
senses  as  well  as  their  modes  of  excitation,  had  been 

1  Outlines  of  Comp.  Anat.  e.  vi. 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAP.  VII.  93 

treated  of  in  a  distinct  work ',  which  may  be  regarded 
as  supplementary  to  the  present  treatise ;  and  this 
will  explain  why  the  eye  and  vision  are  here  very 
briefly  alluded  to,  while  particular  attention  has 
there  been  given  to  the  ear  and  hearing. 


CHAPTER  VII. 

THE  visible  is  that  for  which  vision  is  the  sense,  and 
the  visible  is  both  colour  and  something  which  is  de- 
scribable  by  words,  although  it  happens  to  be  without 
a  name;  but  our  meaning  will  become  clear  to  those 
who  accompany  us  in  the  inquiry.  The  visible  is 
colour,  and  colour  is  that  which  is  upon  something 
visible  in  itself;  and  this  something  is  visible,  not 
only  after  its  appellation  but,  because  it  has  in  itself 
the  cause  of  being  visible.  All  colour  is  motive  of 
the  diaphanous,  in  activity,  and  to  be  so  motive  is  the 
nature  of  colour.  On  which  account  nothing  is  visi- 
ble without  light,  but  the  colour  of  each  object  is 
visible  in  the  light;  and  we  must,  therefore,  first  say 
what  light  is.  There  is  a  something  diaphanous,  and 
I  call  diaphanous  what  is  visible,  and  yet  not  visible, 

1  De  Sentu  et  Sens.  i.  10. 


94  AEISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  II. 

strictly  speaking,  in  itself,  but  made  visible  by  colour, 
which  is  foreign  to  it.  Such  is  air,  and  water,  and 
many  solid  bodies;  yet  neither  air  nor  water,  as  air  or 
water,  is  diaphanous,  but  the  same  nature  is  present 
in  both  those  elements,  which  is  in  the  eternal  super- 
nal body.  Light  is  the  active  state  of  that  same  dia- 
pkanous,  in  so  far  as  it  is  diaphanous,  and  darkness  is 
the  same  in  its  state  of  potentiality.  But  light  is  the 
colour,  as  it  were,  of  the  diaphanous,  when  made  dia- 
phanous in  reality  by  fire,  or  other  such  element  as 
the  supernal  body;  for  to  it  belongs  a  something 
which  is  identical  with  fire.  We  have  thus  said  what 
is  the  diaphanous  and  what  light,  and  have  shewn 
that  neither  of  them  is  fire,  nor  a  body,  strictly  speak- 
ing, nor  an  emanation  from  a  body,  (as,  in  that  case, 
they  would  be  corporeal),  but  that  they  are  the  pre- 
sence in  the  diaphanous  of  fire  or  something  analogous 
to  fire,  since  two  bodies  cannot  possibly  coexist  in 
one  and  the  same  body. 

Light  seems  to  be  the  opposite  to  darkness ;  and 
as  darkness  is  the  absence  of  a  particular  state  of  the 
diaphanous,  it  is  evident  that  the  presence  of  that 
state  must  be  light. 

Thus  Empedocles,  or  whoever  else  may  have  held 
the  same  opinion,  was  wrong  in  supposing  that  light 
was  transported  and  manifested,  without  our  con- 
sciousness, between  the  Earth  and  surrounding  space; 
for  the  opinion  is  opposed  as  well  to  sound  conclusion 


CH.  VII.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  95 

as  to  observation  of  the  phenomenon.  If  the  interval 
were  small,  the  fact  might,  indeed,  escape  us;  but, 
extended  as  it  is  from  the  East  to  the  West,  the  pos- 
tulate is  too  extravagant  to  be  admitted. 

Now  that  which  is  without  colour  is  receptive  of 
colour,  as  that  which  is  without  sound  is  receptive  of 
sound;  and  that  which  is  without  colour  is  the  dia- 
phanous  and  the  invisible  or  scarcely  visible,  such  as 
darkness  seems  to  be.  Such  too  is  the  diaphanous ; 
but  then  it  is  the  diaphanous,  not  in  potentiality  but, 
in  reality;  for  the  same  nature  is  sometimes  darkness 
and  sometimes  light.  But  all  objects  are  not  visible 
in  light,  as  there  are  some  of  which  the  peculiar 
colour  only  of  each  is  visible;  for  some,  not  visible 
in  light,  produce  sensation  in  the  dark,  as  certain 
fiery  brilliant  appearances  (which  have  no  special 
appellation,)  which  emanate  from  fungi,  horn,  scales 
and  eyes  of  fishes,  but  the  peculiar  colour  is  not  seen 
of  any  one  of  those  objects.  It  is  foreign  to  our  present 
purpose  to  explain  how  such  objects  become  visible ; 
but  this  much  is  manifest,  that  it  is  colour  which  is 
visible  in  light.  Therefore,  without  light  colour  is 
not  visible;  for  it  is  an  essential  property  of  colour  to 
be  motive  of  the  diaphanous  in  activity,  and  the 
reality  of  the  diaphanous  is  light.  As  proof  of  this, 
if  any  coloured  object  be  placed  over  the  sight,  the 
object  will  not  be  seen,  and  yet  there  is  colour,  which 
is  motive  of  the  diaphanous,  the  air,  that  is,  and,  by 


96  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  II. 

its  being  continuous  between  the  object  and  the  sense, 
it  is  able  to  give  motion  to  the  visual  organ.  Thus. 
Democritus  was  wrong  in  thinking  that  if  the  medium 
were  a  void,  vision  would  be  so  accurate  as  to  render 
an  ant  visible  in  the  sky.  The  opinion,  in  fact,  in- 
volves an  impossibility;  for  vision  is  produced  by 
some  kind  of  impression  upon  the  visual  organ,  and 
as  this  cannot  possibly  be  effected  by  the  colour  which 
is  visible,  there  remains  only  that  it  must  be  by  the 
medium,  and  thus  a  medium  there  must  be ;  so  that 
if  there  were  a  void,  vision  would  be,  not  to  say  in- 
accurate but,  altogether  precluded. 

It  has  thus  then  been  said  why  colour  must  be 
visible  in  the  light ;  but  fire  is  visible  both  in  dark- 
ness and  in  light,  and  necessarily  so,  since  it  is  by  fire 
that  the  diaphanous  becomes  diaphanous.  The  same 
reasoning  holds  good  for  sound  and  for  odour,  as 
nothing  sonorous  or  odorous  can  produce  sensation 
when  in  immediate  contact  with  the  sentient  organ ; 
but  by  odour  or  sound  the  medium  is  set  in  motion, 
and  by  it  the  organ  is  moved.  Thus,  when  any  thing 
sonorous  or  odorous  is  placed  immediately  upon  the 
sentient  organ,  no  sensation  is  given  out ;  and  this  is 
the  case  with  the  sense  of  Touch,  although  less  evi- 
dently so ;  but  the  cause  of  this  shall  be  explained 
hereafter.  The  air  is  the  medium  for  sounds,  while 
that  for  odour  has  no  special  appellation,  for  there  is 
a  particular  impression  common  to  air  and  water ;  and 


CH.  VII.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  97 

what  the  diaphanous  is  to  colour  that  which  is  in 
those  elements  is  to  odorous  bodies,  as  aquatic  ani- 
mals appear  to  be  sensible  of  odours.  But  neither 
man  nor  animals  which  breathe  can  smell  without 
inspiring;  and  the  cause  of  this  shall  be  spoken 
of  hereafter. 


PKELTJDE  TO  CHAPTER  VIII. 

THIS  chapter  is  upon  sound  and  hearing ;  and  as  these 
subjects  had  been  but  desultorily  alluded  to  in  the 
other  works,  they  are  treated  of  at  some  length  on 
this  occasion.  It  opens  with  the  distinction  of 
bodies  into  sonorous  and  insonorous,  and  after  tracing 
the  analogy  between  the  acute  and  grave,  and  the 
sharp  and  blunt  (of  touch),  it  passes  by  a  rapid 
transition  to  the  voice,  which  is  dwelt  upon  at  some 
length.  The  term  evtpycta,  which  had  been  used  in 
place  of  evT€\€-^fta,  to  express  the  active  as  opposed 
to  the  potential  or  negative  state  of  the  diaphaneity, 
is  again  employed  here  to  signify  the  analogous  and 
contrasting  quality  of  sound.  The  distinction  between 
the  terms  is  not  very  apparent  now,  although  this 
may  not  have  been  the  case  then ;  for  the  evepyeta 
may  have  conveyed  the  idea  of  action  in  the  transi- 
tion from  potentiality,  and  so  have  been  more 
expressive  of  actual,  as  opposed  to  virtual  light  or 
sound.  Thus,  if  sound  be  a  quality  or  condition,  it 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAP.  VIII.  99 

may  be  active,  and  it  may  be  only  virtual  or  faint ; 
but  although  to  us  inaudible,  it  is  not  to  be  supposed 
that  silence  any  more  than  darkness  is  ever  absolute ; 
so  that  the  text  has  limited  the  range  of  sound  too 
absolutely  by  the  activity  of  the  sense.  Aristotle1 
assigned,  as  has  been  said,  a  high  privilege  to  this 
sense,  because  through  it  instruction  is  orally  con- 
veyed, and  thus  the  blind  from  birth  are  more  intel- 
ligent ((ppovtutorepot),  he  observes,  than  "the  deaf 
and  dumb;"  but  the  argument  would  have  been 
more  correct  had  the  second  term  been  omitted,  as 
individuals  are  of  necessity  dumb  when  hearing  is 
quite  shut  out.  The  phraseology,  however,  is  still 
sanctioned  in  common  parlance. 

1  De  Sensu  et  sensili  i.  1 1. 


7—2 


CHAPTEE  VIII. 

LET  us  now  proceed  to  determine  the  nature  of  sound 
and  hearing.  Sound  is  double — one  actual  and  an- 
other potential ;  for  we  say  that  some  substances,  such 
as  sponge  and  wool,  are  without  sound ;  and  that 
others,  as  brass,  and  bodies  which  are  hard  and 
smooth,  have  sound,  because  such  objects  are  able  to 
sound ;  are  able,  that  is,  to  create  actual  sound  by  the 
action  of  the  medium  between  the  object  and  the 
hearing.  Sound  of  the  actual  kind  is  the  invariable 
result  of  something  in  relation  to  something  and  in 
something ;  for  its  producing  cause  is  percussion.  It 
is  impossible,  therefore,  that  sound  should  be  pro- 
duced when  there  is  only  one  substance,  as  that  which 
percusses  must  be  distinct  from  that  which  is  per- 
cussed; so  that  the  sonorous  object  sounds  by  its 
relation  to  another  object.  But  there  can  be  no  per- 
cussion without  movement,  and  sound  is  not  produced 
by  the  percussion  of  any  kind  of  substance,  as  we 
have  said,  (since  wool,  however  percussed,  does  not, 
while  brass  and  smooth  and  hollow  bodies — brass 
because  it  is  smooth — do  give  out  sound,)  and  hollow 
bodies  create,  by  reflexion,  many  percussions  after  the 


CH.  VIII.]    ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.      101 

first,  owing  to  the  medium  within  them  having  been 
set  in  motion  and  being  unable  to  make  its  escape. 
Sound  is  audible  in  air,  and  so  it  is  in  water,  although 
less  distinctly ;  but  neither  air  nor  water  is  the  efficient 
cause  of  sound,  as  for  it  there  must  be  percussion  of 
solid  bodies  against  each  other  and  against  the  air, 
and  this  is  effected  whenever  the  air,  having  been 
percussed,  remains,  is  not,  that  is,  dispersed.  Thus, 
if  the  air  be  struck  sharply  and  forcibly  it  gives  out 
sound ;  for  the  motion  of  that  which  percusses  should 
anticipate  the  dispersion  of  the  air,  as  if  any  one  were 
striking  a  rapidly  moving  heap  or  cloud  of  sand. 

An  echo  is  produced  whenever  the  external  air  has 
been  more  than  once  repelled  by  the  air  contained 
within  a  vessel,  by  the  sides  of  which  that  air  is  pre- 
cluded from  being  dispersed,  just  as  a  ball  rebounds. 
It  seems  as  though  an  echo  ought  to  be  a  constant 
occurrence,  although  it  may  not  be  audible,  since  that 
happens  to  sound  which  happens  to  light,  and  light  is 
continually  undergoing  reflexion  (for,  otherwise,  as 
light  could  not  be  everywhere,  darkness  would  pre- 
vail beyond  the  spot  illumined  by  the  sun),  but  yet  it 
is  not  everywhere  reflected,  as  it  is  from  water  or 
brass  or  any  other  smooth  body,  so  as  to  form  a 
shadow  whereby  we  are  able  to  distinguish  the  light 
itself. 

A  Void  is  rightly  said  to  be  the  sovereign  cause 
of  hearing; — for  the  air  seems  to  be  a  void,  and  the 


102  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  II. 

air,  when  moving  continuously  and  as  one  body,  is 
creative  of  hearing.  But,  owing  to  its  being  very  dif- 
fluent, it  gives  out  no  sound,  unless  that  which  is 
percussed  be  smooth ;  when  this,  however,  is  the  case, 
the  air  becomes  simultaneously  one  over  the  surface, 
as  the  surface  of  every  smooth  body  is  one.  Every 
sonorous  body  is  so  constituted  as  to  set  in  motion  the 
air  which,  by  continuity,  is  one  up  to  the  hearing, 
and  the  hearing  is  naturally  connected  with  the  air ; 
and  owing  to  sound  being  in  the  air,  the  air  which  is 
without  sets  in  motion  that  which  is  within.  An  ani- 
mal, therefore,  does  not  hear  everywhere,  neither  does 
the  air  penetrate  everywhere;  for  the  part  to  be  set 
in  motion  is  a  living  part,  and  does  not  everywhere 
contain  air.  The  air  itself,  owing  to  its  ready  diffusi- 
bility,  is  without  sound ;  but,  when  precluded  from 
being  dispersed,  its  motion  is  productive  of  sound. 
The  air  which  is  within  the  ears  has  been  so  immured 
as  to  be  immovable ;  and  this  in  order  that  the  sense 
may  perceive  accurately  all  variations  of  its  move- 
ment. It  is  for  these  reasons  that  we  are  able  to  hear 
when  in  the  water,  as  the  water  cannot  gain  access  to 
the  congenital  air,  or  pass  into  the  ear  through  the 
convolutions ;  when,  however,  this  does  happen,  there 
is  no  hearing,  any  more  than  there  is  when  the  mem- 
brane of  the  ear,  which  is  to  it  what  the  skin  over  the 
pupil  is  to  the  eye,  is  diseased.  But  proof  is  afforded 
whether  the  hearing  is  perfect  or  not,  in  that  the  ear 


CH.  VIII.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  103 

is  constantly  giving  out  sound,  just  as  a  horn  does ; 
for  the  air  within  the  ears  is  continually  moving  in 
some  peculiar  manner,  and  yet  sound  is  foreign  to 
that  air  and  forms  no  part  of  its  properties.  It  is  on 
this  account,  however,  that  we  speak  of  hearing  by  a 
void  and  something  resonant,  because  we  hear  by  the 
part  which  contains  the  air  confined  within  it. 

But  is  it  that  which  percusses,  or  that  which  is 
percussed,  which  gives  out  sound  ?  Or  do  both  con- 
tribute to  its  production,  each  in  its  own  way?  Now, 
sound  is  the  motion  of  something  which  admits  of 
being  moved  after  the  manner  of  bodies  rebounding 
from  smooth  surfaces,  whereon  they  may  have  been 
impelled.  But  every  kind  of  body,  whether  percussing 
or  percussed,  does  not,  as  has  been  said,  give  out 
sound ;  as  when  a  sharp  point,  for  example,  strikes  a 
sharp  point,  there  is  no  sound ;  but  in  order  to  pro- 
duce sound,  that  which  is  percussed  must  be  so 
smooth,  that  the  mass  of  air  upon  its  surface  may  re- 
bound from,  and  be  agitated  over  it.  The  distinctions 
among  sonorous  bodies  are  revealed  in  the  actual 
sounds  which  they  give  forth;  for  as  without  light 
colours  are  not  visible,  so  without  sound  the  acute 
and  grave  are  not  audible.  These  terms  (acute  and 
grave)  are  derived  from  tangible  properties,  and  em- 
ployed, in  a  metaphorical  sense,  for  sounds;  for  the 
acute  moves  the  hearing  quickly  and  sharply,  the 
grave  moves  it  slowly  and  dully ;  not,  however,  that 


104  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  II. 

the  acute  is  quick  or  the  grave  slow ;  but  that  such  is 
the  motion  of  the  one  from  the  celerity,  and  such  the 
motion  of  the  other  from  the  tardiness  of  its  operation 
upon  the  sense.  And  there  does  seem  to  be  an  ana- 
logy between  those  sounds  and  the  sharp  and  blunt, 
as  perceived  by  the  Touch ;  for  the  sharp  pricks,  and 
the  blunt  pushes,  as  it  were,  because  the  motion  ex- 
erted by  the  one  is  rapid,  by  the  other  tardy ;  and  it  is 
in  this  manner  that  the  terms  in  question  have  origi- 
nated. Let  us  here,  however,  close  our  observations 
upon  the  nature  of  sound. 

The  voice  is  a  sound  produced  by  a  living  crea- 
ture; for  nothing  inanimate  speaks,  although  there 
are  objects,  such  as  the  flute,  lyre,  and  others,  which, 
having  range  of  note,  harmony,  and  expression,  are 
said,  from  a  resemblance  between  their  tones  and  the 
voice,  to  do  so;  and  the  voice  does  seem  to  have  all 
the  variations  of  note  possessed  by  those  instruments. 
Many  creatures  have  no  voice  (as  all  the  insan- 
guineous,  for  instance,  and  some  of  the  sanguineous, 
as  fishes),  which  is  very  understandable,  seeing  that 
sound  is  a  certain  motion  of  the  air ;  and  with  respect 
to  those  fishes  which  are  found  in  the  Achelous  and 
said  to  speak,  they  produce  sound  by  their  gills,  or 
other  such  part.  But  although  the  voice  is  a  sound 
emanating  from  a  living  creature,  it  does  not  imply 
any  kind  of  sound,  or  a  sound  produced  by  any 
kind  of  part;  and  as  all  sound  is  produced  by  the 


CH.  VIII.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  105 

conditions  of  something  which  percusses,  something 
percussed,  and  a  something,  that  is  the  air,  in 
which  percussion  can  be  made,  it  might  reasonably 
be  assumed,  that  such  creatures  only  as  take  in  air  can 
have  a  voice.  Now,  nature  employs  simultaneously 
the  air  respired  for  two  functions,  just  as  she  employs 
the  tongue  for  taste  and  for  speech ;  and  of  these  the 
former  is  necessary  (and  therefore  imparted  to  most 
creatures),  and  the  latter,  as  an  organ  for  interpre- 
tation, is  for  their  higher  good ;  so  too  does  she 
employ  the  breath  both  as  necessary  for  tempering 
the  heat  within  (as  shall  be  explained  elsewhere),  and 
for  the  production  of  voice,  which  is  for  the  welfare 
of  the  individual.  The  pharynx  is  the  organ  of 
respiration,  for  the  sake  of  which  is  another  part,  the 
lung,  and  it  is  owing  to  this  part  that  quadrupeds 
have  more  heat  than  other  creatures. 

It  is  the  place  about  the  heart  which  first  needs 
respiration ;  and,  therefore,  it  is  necessary  that  the 
air,  during  inspiration,  should  pass  inwards;  and 
thus  the  percussion  of  the  air  respired  by  the  living 
principle  in  those  parts,  against  the  so-called  trachea, 
constitutes  the  voice.  But  every  sound  produced  by 
an  animal  is  not  voice,  as  we  have  said  (for  it  is  pos- 
sible to  produce  sound  by  the  tongue,  as  in  coughing), 
but  in  order  to  constitute  the  voice,  there  must  be  a 
percussing  living  force,  and  the  sound  produced  must 
be  expressive  of  something.  The  voice  is,  in  fact,  a 


106      ARISTOTLE   ON   THE   VITAL   PRINCIPLE.     [BK.  II. 

sound  expressive  of  something — it  is  not,  that  is,  as 
in  coughing,  a  mere  sound  of  the  air  inspired;  and 
speech  is  the  percussion,  by  the  living  principle,  of 
the  air  in  the  trachea,  against  the  trachea  itself.  As 
proof  of  which,  we  are  unable  to  speak  when  holding 
the  breath,  that  is,  when  we  neither  inspire  nor 
expire;  for  the  act  of  holding  the  breath  sets  in 
motion  the  air  which  is  inspired.  It  is  now  manifest 
why  fishes,  having  no  pharynx,  are  without  a  voice ; 
and  they  have  no  pharynx,  because  they  neither 
admit  the  air  nor  breathe.  It  is  foreign  to  our  present 
purpose,  however,  to  inquire  into  the  cause  of  their 
having  been  thus  constituted. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  IX. 


MODERN  science  confirms  Aristotle's  judgment  concerning 
the  nature  of  odour,  for  it  is  said  "to  be  a  curious 
and  interesting  problem,  requiring  much  more  investi- 
gation than  it  has  hitherto  received  ;"  and,  according 
to  Cuvier  *,  "  of  all  the  substances  which  act  upon  our 
senses,  those  which  produce  the  sensation  of  smell 
are  the  least  known,  although  their  impression  has 
the  liveliest  and  deepest  influence  upon  our  economy." 
But  the  reason  assigned  in  the  text  for  this  relative 
imperfection  of  our  smell  is  indefinite  and  question- 
able ;  for  "  although  man's  nostrils  are  less  compli- 
cated than  those  of  any  animals  save  the  quadrumana, 
he  is  the  only  creature  whose  smell  is  fine  enough  to 
be  affected  by  unpleasant  odours"  It  may  be  doubted, 
besides,  whether  any  sensation  can  be,  as  is  implied 
in  the  text,  so  pure  as  to  be  freed  from  all  mental 
or  corporeal  association ;  but  when  man's  smell  is 

1  R&gne  Animal,  T.  i.  73. 


108  PRELUDE   TO   CHAP.  IX. 

compared  with  that  of  birds  and  beasts  of  prey,  it 
may  be  granted  that,  within  a  certain  range  of  impres- 
sions, it  is  relatively  duller  and  coarser  than  with 
them.  It  is,  however,  assumed,  that  sight  and  smell, 
when  perfect,  have  the  faculty  of  perceiving  colours, 
and  odours  purely,  unassociated,  that  is,  with  any 
impression  grateful  or  otherwise  ;  and  thus,  as  man's 
smell  was  held  to  be  imperfect,  he  was  supposed  to 
be  sensible  of  odours  as  creatures  with  hard,  that  is, 
compound  eyes  are  of  colours.  For  such  creatures1 
(crustacea,  insects  and  others),  having  their  eyes 
uncovered,  being  without  lids  that  is,  see  objects 
which  are  at  a  distance  "  indistinctly,  and  as  if  they 
were  looking  through  congenitally  attached  eye-lids." 

1  Hist.  An.  i.  15.  16. 


CHAPTER  IX. 


IT  is  less  easy  to  define  smell  and  the  odorous  object, 
than  the  subjects  which  have  just  been  treated  of,  as 
the  nature  of  odour  is  not  so  clear  to  us  as  is  that  of 
either  sound  or  colour  ;  and  the  reason  of  this  is,  that 
our  sense  of  smell  is  inaccurate,  is  less  delicate,  in 
fact,  than  it  is  in  many  animals.  Thus,  man  has  but 
a  coarse  smell,  and  is  never  sensible  of  any  thing 
odorous  without  associating  therewith  an  impression 
of  something  painful  or  grateful ;  and  this  seems  to 
indicate  an  organ  imperfectly  constituted.  It  is  pro- 
bable that  colours  are  perceived  by  creatures  which 
have  hard  eyes  in  this  same  manner,  and  that  shades 
of  colour  invariably  make  upon  them  an  impression  of 
something  to  be  afraid  of  or  otherwise.  The  human 
race  is  circumstanced  in  a  like  manner  with  respect 
to  odours ;  and  there  seems  to  be  an  analogy  between 
taste  and  kinds  of  savours,  and  smell  and  kinds  of 
odours,  but  as  taste  is  a  kind  of  touch,  and  touch  of 
all  man's  senses  the  most  perfect,  his  taste  is  more 
delicate  than  his  smell.  With  respect  to  other  senses, 
man  is  far  behind  many  animals,  but  he  is  especially 


110  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  II. 

distinguished  from  them  all  by  the  accuracy  of  his 
Touch ;  and  to  this  he  is  indebted  for  being  of  all  the 
most  intelligent.  As  proof  of  which,  individuals  of 
the  human  race  are  according  to  the  constitution  of 
this  sense  and  nothing  else,  clever  or  dull — for  those 
with  hard  flesh  are  slow,  and  those,  on  the  contrary, 
with  soft  flesh  are  quick  of  understanding. 

As  one  savour  is  sweet  and  another  bitter,  so  it 
is  with  odours  ;  but  some  bodies  impart  an  analogous 
savour  and  odour,  impart,  I  mean,  a  sweet  odour  and 
a  sweet  savour,  while  other  bodies  give  out  their 
contraries.  Some  odours  equally  with  savours  are 
termed  pungent,  sour,  and  oily,  but,  as  we  have 
already  explained,  owing  to  their  not  being  so  dis- 
tinguishable by  us  as  savours,  odours  have  derived 
their  appellations  from  these,  on  account  of  the  simi- 
larity of  the  objects  from  which  they  both  proceed. 
Thus,  the  odour  from  saffron  and  honey  is  called  sweet, 
that  from  thyme  and  other  herbs  of  the  kind  pungent, 
and  so  for  other  bodies  and  odours. 

There  is  a  close  analogy  between  the  other  senses 
and  the  hearing :  for  as  it  is  sensible  of  the  audible 
and  the  inaudible,  so  is  vision  of  the  visible  and  invi- 
sible, and  smell  of  the  odorous  and  the  inodorous, 
and  by  inodorous  is  meant  whatever  is  either  alto- 
gether without  odour,  or  has  but  a  very  faint  odour ; 
and  a  sense  analogous  to  this  is  attached  to  the  term 
insapid. 


CH.  IX.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  Ill 

The  smell  is  perceptive  through  a  medium,  such 
as  air  or  water,  for  aquatic  animals  seem  to  be  sen- 
sible of  odour ;  and  so,  likewise,  are  sanguineous  and 
insanguineous  creatures,  as  well  as  those  which  wing 
the  air.  Thus,  some  of  these  are  to  be  seen  proceeding 
from  a  distance  towards  food,  of  which  they  have  been 
made  sensible  by  the  odour  emanating  from  it.  And 
hence  the  difficulty  of  determining  why,  if  other  crea- 
tures are  sensible  of  odours  in  a  like  manner,  man 
alone  can  smell  neither  when  expiring  nor  when 
holding  his  breath  but,  only  when  inspiring ;  and 
this  whether  the  odorous  object  be  at  a  distance  from 
or  close  to  him,  or  placed  immediately  within  the 
nostrils.  It  is  common,  it  is  true,  to  all  the  sentient 
organs  to  be  insensible  to  impressions  when  objects 
are  placed  immediately  upon  them  ;  but  it  is  peculiar 
to  man  (as  may  be  proved  experimentally),  to  be 
unable  to  perceive  odours  without  inspiring.  So  that 
as  insanguineous  creatures  do  not  breathe,  they  ought 
to  have  some  other  sense  besides  those  spoken  of, 
but  yet  this  cannot  be,  since  they  do  perceive  odour  ; 
for  the  perception  of  odour,  whether  agreeable  or 
disagreeable,  is  smell;  and  as  these  appear  to 
be  destroyed  by  the  same  powerful  odours  as  those 
which  destroy  man  (odours,  for  instance,  from  pitch, 
sulphur,  and  other  like  substances),  we  must  con- 
clude that  they  have  smell,  although  they  do  not 
breathe. 


112      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE   VITAL  PRINCIPLE.     [BK.  II. 

The  olfactory  organ  in  man  appears  to  differ  from 
that  in  other  animals  as  his  eyes  differ  from  those  of 
creatures  in  which  they  are  hard  ;  for  man's  eyes  are 
furnished  with  a  rampart,  and  a  kind  of  sheath  in 
lids,  without  the  elevation  and  drawing  asunder  of 
which  he  cannot  see,  while  hard  eyes,  having  no 
such  provision,  are  instantly  sensible  of  whatever  may 
be  present  in  the  diaphanous  medium.  In  accord- 
ance with  this,  the  olfactory  organ  is,  in  such  crea- 
tures, like  the  eye,  uncovered ;  but,  in  such  as  breathe, 
it  is  furnished  with  a  cover,  which  during  inspiration 
is  lifted  up,  as  the  veins  and  pores  are  then  dilated. 
On  which  account,  creatures  which  breathe  cannot 
smell  while  in  the  water,  as  in  order  to  smell  they 
must  inspire,  and  while  in  the  water  they  cannot 
possibly  inspire. 

In  fine,  odour  is  derived  from  what  is  dry,  as 
savour  is  from  what  is  moist ;  and  the  olfactory  organ, 
when  in  potentiality,  is  analogous  to  that  from  which 
odour  is  derived. 


PRELUDE  TD   CHAPTER  X. 

THIS  theory  of  taste  and  savour  is  adopted  substantively 
by  modern  physiology.  Cuvier '  says  that  "  Taste  is 
only  a  more  delicate  kind  of  Touch ;"  and  Miiller 2 

considers  fluid  essential  to  its  manifestations.     There 

f 

are  three  conditions  essential  to  Taste,  he  observes, 
the  specific  nerve,  the  excitation  of  that  nerve  through 
savour,  and  the  solution  of  the  savour  in  the  moisture 
of  the  sapid  organ ;  for  sapid  matter  to  be  tasted, 
must  either  be  moistened,  or  else  be  solvable  in  the 
tongue's  moisture.  All  which  implies  that,  if  an 
object  is  very  arid,  or  if  the  organs  of  Taste  are 
incapable  of  supplying  moisture,  the  percipient  will 
be  sensible,  not  of  sapid  but,  of  tangible  qualities  only, 
such  as  hot  and  cold,  hard  and  soft. 

1  Rbgne  Animal,  I.  31. 

3  Handbuch  der  Physiologic,  Lib.  II.  489. 


CHAPTER  X. 

THE  sapid  object  is  a  kind  of  tangible  object,  and 
this  is  the  reason  why  it  does  not  require,  in  order  to 
be  perceived,  any  other  medium  than  the  body,  for 
the  Touch  requires  no  other.  The  body  in  which  is 
savour,  is  the  gustable  body,  and  the  matter  of  savour 
is  in  fluid,  and  fluid  is  something  tangible.  Thus, 
were  we  in  the  water,  and  were  any  thing  sweet  cast 
into  the  water,  we  should  be  sensible  of  the  sweetness, 
not  through  the  water  as  a  medium  but,  from  its 
having  been  mixed  with  the  water  as  with  a  potable 
fluid.  Colour,  however,  is  not  thus  made  visible  from 
having  been  mixed  with  anything,  nor  is  it  made 
visible  by  emanations ;  and  as  the  medium,  in  the 
case  of  colours,  plays  no  part  and  colour  is  the  visible, 
so  is  savour  the  gustable.  No  object,  however,  with- 
out humidity  can  impart  the  sense  of  savour;  and, 
therefore,  every  sapid  object  contains  humidity,  in  an 
active  or  a  potential  state,  as  does  salt ;  for  salt  is 
readily  moistened  and  liquefied  by  contact  with  the 
tongue. 

Now,  vision  is  perceptive  of  the  visible  and  the 
invisible  (for  darkness,   although   invisible,  is   still 


CH.  X.]     ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.      115 

judged  of  "by  vision),  and  a  very  bright  light  (which 
is  also  invisible,  although  in  a  manner  different  from 
darkness),  and  so  hearing  is  equally  perceptive  of 
sound  and  silence,  of  which  that  is  audible  and  this 
inaudible,  as  well  as  a  very  loud  sound,  just  as  vision 
is  of  a  very  bright  light ;  for  as  a  very  low  sound  is, 
in  a  certain  sense,  inaudible,  so  is  a  very  loud  and 
crashing  sound.  On  the  other  hand,  the  term  in- 
visible, used  absolutely,  is  analogous  to  the  term  im- 
possible upon  other  subjects,  and  which  may  be  sig- 
nificant of  something  generated  without  parts  or  with 
parts  ill  formed  for  their  office,  as  an  animal  without 
feet,  or  a  fruit  without  a  kernel.  So,  too,  the  taste  in 
its  turn  is  perceptive  both  of  what  is  sapid  and  in- 
sapid;  and  the  insapid  implies  whatever  has  a  faint 
or  nauseous  savour,  or  a  savour  altogether  perversive 
of  taste.  The  potable  and  the  impotable  seem  alike 
to  be  the  origin  of  taste,  for  they  both  are  sapid ;  but 
then  the  first  has  a  nauseous  savour,  and  is  perversive 
of  taste,  while  the  last  is  genial  to  the  sense ;  the  po- 
table is  common,  besides,  to  the  touch  and  taste. 
Since  whatever  is  sapid  is  humid,  it  follows  that  the 
organ  of  taste  may  neither  be  humid  realty,  nor  yet 
be  incapable  of  becoming  humid ;  for  the  taste  suffers 
impression  by  the  sapid  body,  in  so  far  as  it  is  sapid. 
It  is,  therefore,  necessary  that  the  sentient  organ,  if 
not  moist,  should,  for  its  function,  be  capable  of  be- 
coming so :  and,  as  proof  of  this,  the  tongue,  when 

8—2 


116      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.     [BK.  II. 

very  dry  or  very  moist,  is  not  sensible  of  sapid  im- 
pressions— as  in  the  former  instance,  it  is  a  tangible 
rather  than  a  sapid  impression  which  is  made  by  a 
fluid  when  first  tasted;  and  when  very  moist,  it  is 
sensible  only  of  the  fluid  already  present,  just  as  it 
happens  when,  after  tasting  something  pungent,  we 
proceed  to  taste  a  different  fluid.  It  is  thus  that  all 
savours  appear  to  the  sick  to  be  bitter,  because  the 
tongue,  with  which  they  taste,  is  charged  with  a  mois- 
ture having  that  savour. 

Kinds  of  savour  are,  like  shades  of  colour,  simple 
when  in  broad  contrast — as  the  sweet  and  bitter  with 
their  sequences,  of  the  former  the  oily  and  of  the  lat- 
ter the  brackish ;  and  intermediate  to  these  are  the 
pungent,  rough,  astringent,  and  sour,  which  seem  to 
include  almost  all  the  varieties  of  savour. 

In  fine,  the  sapid  sense,  when  in  potentiality,  is 
such  as  is  the  sapid  object;  and  the  sapid  object, 
when  in  reality,  is  productive,  in  the  sense,  of  its  own 
savour. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  XL 


COMMENTATORS  have  differed  widely  in  their  interpretation 
of  Aristotle's  meaning  in  the  opening  passage  upon 
the  Touch.  But  it  may,  with  some  confidence,  be 
assumed  that,  from  being  unacquainted  with  the 
nervous  system,  and  observing  the  wide-spread  and 
varying  delicacy  of  the  sense,  he  was  led  to  suppose 
that  it  might  either  be  diffused,  so  to  speak,  as  several 
organs,  over  the  body,  or  be  somehow  identified  with 
or  included  in  the  flesh  which  covers  the  body.  l  The 
flesh  is  the  muscular  substance,  and  as  it  envelopes,  so 
to  say,  the  body,  it  was  probably  supposed  to  be  the 
seat  or  cause  of  the  sense,  as  every  part  is  sensible  to 
Touch;  and  the  analogue  of  flesh  is  the  colourless  sub- 
stance of  the  Insanguinea — insects,  <tc.  *And  there 
is  a  close  analogy  between  the  two  substances,  "as 
the  muscles  of  the  highest  class  of  animals,  during 
their  development  pass  through  the  soft,  colourless, 

1  De  Partib.  Aid.  i.  8.  i.  3. 

3  Grant's  Outlines  of  Comp.  Anat. 


118  PEELUDE  TO  CHAP.  XI.  [BK.  II. 

homogeneous  and  gelatinous  condition  of  the  Inverte- 
brata,  before  assuming  the  red  colour."  As  the 
Touch,  besides,  was  regarded  as  the  first  in  order  of 
the  senses  and  characteristic  of  animals,  so  the  flesh 
was  said  to  be  the  origin  of  all  other  parts  of  animal 
bodies,  bone  and  skin,  sinews,  veins,  hair  and  nails ; 
and  this  hypothesis  may  have  confirmed  the  opinion 
that  it  is  either  the  sense  or  the  seat  of  the  sense  of 
Touch. 


CHAPTER  XI. 

THE  same  reasoning  holds  good  for  the  tangible 
quality  as  for  the  Touch ;  for  if  the  Touch  be  not  a 
single  but  a  manifold  sense,  it  follows  that  tangible 
qualities  must  be  manifold  also.  Now,  it  is  difficult 
to  determine  whether  the  Touch  is  a  manifold  or  a 
single  sense,  and  difficult  also  to  say  what  the  organ 
may  be  which  is  percipient  of  tangible  qualities ;  that 
is,  whether  or  not  it  is  the  flesh,  and  that  which,  in 
other  creatures,  is  analogous  to  flesh;  but  yet  the 
flesh  is  only  the  medium,  and  the  essential  organ, 
therefore,  must  be  something  different  from  flesh,  and 
situated  internally. 

Each  sense  seems  to  be  perceptive  of  only  one 
contrary,  as  Sight  of  white  and  black,  Hearing  of 


CH.  XI.]      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.       119 

acute  and  grave,  and  Taste  of  bitter  and  sweet ;  but 
several  contraries  belong  to  the  sense  of  Touch,  as  hot 
and  cold,  wet  and  dry,  hard  and  soft,  with  others. 
There  is,  it  is  true,  a  kind  of  solution  for  this  diffi- 
culty, in  that  the  other  senses  also  admit  of  several 
contraries;  as  in  the  voice  there  are  not  only  the 
acute  and  grave  but  also  the  strong  and  weak,  the 
rough  and  smooth,  with  yet  other  contrasts;  and 
there  are  many  and  varied  shades  of  colour.  Still  it 
is  not  clear  what  that  subjacent  something  is,  which 
is  to  the  tangible  impression  what  the  Hearing  is 
to  Sound. 

Is  then  the  sentient  organ  placed  or  not  within 
the  flesh,  or  is  it  the  flesh  itself  which  is  immediately 
perceptive?  It  does  not  appear  that  any  indication 
can  be  obtained  upon  this  point  from  sensation  being 
simultaneous  with  the  tangible  impression ;  for,  situ- 
ated as  we  are,  were  any  one  to  extend  a  membrane- 
like  substance  over  his  flesh,  the  party  would  be 
equally  sensible  when  touched,  and  sensible  at  the 
moment  of  contact;  and  yet,  clearly,  the  sentient 
organ  cannot  be  in  that  membrane.  It  may  be,  how- 
ever, that  if  the  membrane  were  a  congenital  part  of 
the  body,  sensation  would  pass  through  it  more 
rapidly.  Thus,  this  part  of  the  body  appears  to  be 
disposed  towards  us  as  air  would  be,  had  air  been 
diffused  around  us ;  for  it  would  seem  to  us  as  thougli 
by  some  one  sense  we  perceive  sound,  colour,  and 


120  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  II. 

odour,  and  as  though  sight,  hearing,  and  smell,  are 
one  and  the  same  sense.  But  now,  as  the  motions 
emanating  from  external  objects  are  distinguishable 
by  the  medium  through  which  they  are  conveyed, 
the  sentient  organs  alluded  to  must  manifestly  be  dif- 
ferent also.  With  respect  to  the  Touch,  however, 
this  is  still  obscure,  for  it  is  impossible  that  a 
living  body  should  be  constituted  out  of  air  or  water, 
as  it  must  have  some  solidity;  and  there  remains 
only  this  conclusion,  that  it  must  be  a  mixture  of 
earth,  and  such  other  particles  as  have  affinity  with 
flesh,  and  the  analogue  of  flesh.  Thus,  the  body  has, 
of  necessity,  been  adapted  for  being  the  medium  for 
the  tangible  sense,  through  which  the  several  tangi- 
ble impressions  are  to  be  conveyed;  and  that  the 
impressions  are  manifold  is  shewn  in  the  tongue 
being  perceptive  of  tangible  as  well  as  sapid  qualities. 
We  are  sensible,  in  fact,  by  this  organ  of  all  tangible 
as  well  as  sapid  qualities ;  and  were  the  rest  of  the 
flesh,  like  the  tongue,  sensible  of  savour,  then  "  Taste" 
and  "  Touch"  would  seem  to  be  one  and  the  same 
sense ;  but  now  we  perceive,  since  they  are  not  con- 
vertible, that  they  must  be  distinct  senses. 

It  may  be  a  question  whether,  as  all  bodies  have 
depth,  that  is  the  third  magnitude,  any  two  bodies, 
which  have  between  them  another  body,  can  be  in 
contact ;  for  neither  the  humid  nor  the  liquid  is  incor- 
poreal, as  each  must,  of  necessity,  be  water  or  hold 


CH.  XI.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  121 

water ;  and  thus,  it  follows  that,  as  the  extreme  parts 
of  bodies  in  the  water  are  not  dry,  the  water,  with 
which  their  extremities  are  covered,  must  be  inter- 
posed between  them.  If  this  be  true,  then  it  is  im- 
possible that  one  body,  when  in  the  water,  should  be 
in  immediate  contact  with  another;  and  this  holds 
good  for  bodies  in  the  air ;  for  the  air  is  in  the  same 
relation  to  bodies  in  air  which  water  is  to  bodies  in 
water ;  but  owing  to  our  being  in  the  air,  the  fact  as 
readily  escapes  us,  as  it  does  aquatic  animals,  from 
their  being  in  water,  that  water  is  in  immediate 
contact  with  water.  It  may  then  be  asked  whether 
there  is  but  one  mode  of  impression  for  all  the  senses, 
or  whether  it  is  different  for  different  senses,  seeing 
that  taste  and  touch  are  acted  upon  by  contact,  and 
the  other  senses  from  a  distance  ?  But  yet  this  is  a 
seeming  difference  only,  for  we  perceive  the  hard  and 
the  soft,  as  we  do  the  odorous,  the  sonorous,  and  the 
visible,  through  media ;  with  this  difference,  that  the 
former  impressions  are  made  by  objects  close  to,  and 
the  latter  by  objects  at  a  distance  from  us.  On  which 
account,  as  we  perceive  all  things  through  a  medium, 
the  medium,  in  the  case  of  bodies  close  to  us,  escapes 
our  attention;  but  if,  as  we  have  already  said,  we 
could  be  sensible  of  all  tangible  impressions  through 
a  membraneous  substance,  without  our  being  con- 
scious of  their  having  been  so  transmitted,  we  should 
then  be  situated  as  we  now  are,  when  in  water  or  air; 


122  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  II. 

for  so  situated,  we  seem  to  touch  bodies  directly,  and 
to  have  no  impression  from  them  through  a  medium. 

But  tangible  differ  from  visible  and  sonorous  im- 
pressions, in  that  the  latter  are  perceived  by  the  me- 
dium acting  in  some  way  upon  us,  while  the  former 
are  perceived,  not  by,  but  together  with,  the  medium, 
like  a  man  who  is  struck  through  his  shield ; — for  it 
is  not  the  shield  which,  having  been  struck,  strikes 
him,  but  the  shield  and  he  are  simultaneously  struck 
together.  To  use  a  general  expression,  the  flesh  and 
the  tongue  seem  to  be  in  the  same  relation  to  the 
touch  which  air  and  water  are  to  sight,  hearing,  and 
smell ; — are  disposed  towards  that  organ,  that  is,  as 
each  of  those  elements  is  to  each  of  those  senses. 
When  the  sentient  organ  itself  is  touched,  no  sensa- 
tion can  there  or  then  be  produced,  any  more  than  a 
white  object  can  be  seen  when  placed  immediately 
over  the  surface  of  the  eye;  and  thus  it  is  evident 
that  the  part  perceptive  of  tangible  impressions  must 
be  within.  Thus,  it  should  be  with  the  touch,  as 
with  the  other  senses;  and  if  objects,  when  placed  upon 
an  organ,  are  not  perceived,  but,  when  placed  upon  the 
flesh,  they  are  perceived,  we  must  conclude  that  the 
flesh  is  only  the  medium  for  tangible  impressions. 

The  distinctions  of  the  body,  as  body,  are  tangible 
distinctions,  and  by  these  I  mean  distinctions  such  as 
distinguish  the  elements,  as  hot,  cold,  dry  and  moist, 
upon  which  we  have  heretofore  spoken  in  our  treatise 


CH.  XI.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  123 

upon  the  Elements.  The  organ  which  perceives  those 
distinctions  is  that  of  Touch ;  and  the  part  in  which 
resides,  primarily,  the  so-called  sense  of  Touch  is,  in 
potentiality,  what  tangible  impressions  are  in  re- 
ality; for  all  sensation  is  a  kind  of  impression.  So 
that  whatever,  by  its  agency,  makes  something  else  to 
be  as  itself,  can  do  so  only  from  that  something  being 
already,  as  itself,  in  potentiality.  Hence,  we  are  not 
sensible  of  hot  and  cold,  hard  and  soft,  when  mani- 
fested in  the  same  degree  as  in  ourselves,  but  perceive 
them  only  when  in  excess,  as  if  the  sensibility  were 
some  kind  of  mean  between  the  contraries  of  sentient 
impressions,  and  able,  as  such,  to  judge  of  sentient 
perceptions.  The  mean,  in  fact,  is  critical — for  it  is 
either  of  the  extremes  in  its  relation  to  the  other; 
and  as  that  which  is  to  perceive  white  and  black  may 
be  neither  one  nor  the  other  actually,  and  yet  both 
potentially,  so  it  is  with  the  other  senses,  and  with 
touch,  which  may  be  neither  hot  nor  cold. 

As  vision  was  said  to  be,  in  some  sense,  perceptive 
of  the  visible  and  the  invisible,  and  the  other  senses 
equally  of  their  opposites,  so  Touch  may  be  said  to  be 
perceptive  of  the  tangible  and  the  intangible ;  and  by 
intangible  is  meant  as  well  what  differs  but  slightly 
from  what  is  tangible,  as  air  for  instance,  as  what  is 
in  such  excess  as  to  be  destructive  of  all  sensation. 

We  have  thus  then  spoken,  although  but  super- 
ficially, upon  each  of  the  senses. 


PKELUDE  TO   CHAP.  XII. 

HAVING  treated  of  each  of  the  senses,  Aristotle  here 
proceeds  to  consider  the  source  of  sensation,  the 
sensibility,  that  is,  which  is  typified  as  plastic  wax, 
from  its  capability  of  receiving  the  form  of  an  object 
without  its  matter.  This  comparison  is  indeed  a 
happy  one ;  and  it  has  been  often  employed  by 
writers  in  modern  times,  and  "among  others  by 
Bossuet1."  The  chapter  shews  that  for  perception 
there  must  be  a  due  relation  between  impression  and 
sense,  and  that  plants  are  insentient  because  they 
have  no  faculty  for  the  reception  of  the  forms  of 
objects  ;  and  it  concludes  by  shewing  that  the  agency 
of  some  properties,  as  light,  sound,  <kc.,  is  confined 
to  the  sentient  organs. 

1  Connoissance  de  Dieu. 


CHAPTER  XII. 


IT  must  be  admitted,  for  the  senses  in  general,  that 
each   one  is   receptive   of  the   perceptible   forms   of 
things  without  the  matter,  as  wax  takes  the  impress 
from  a  seal-ring,  without  the  iron  or  gold  of  which 
the  ring  is  made ; — takes  the  device,  that  is,  without 
the  metal  on  which  the  device  is  inscribed.    In  like 
manner,  the  sense  is  impressed  by  each  object  having 
colour,  or  savour,  or  sound ;  not,  however,  after  the 
appellation  of  the  object  but,  according  as  it  is  of  a 
certain  quality,  and  in  a  given  relation  to  the  sense. 
It  is  the  primal  organ  in  which  this  faculty  exists ; 
and  it  is  identical  with  the  object  perceived,  although 
different  from  it  in  mode  of  being ;  for,  otherwise,  the 
percipient  would  be  some  kind  of  magnitude.    But  it 
cannot  belong  either  to  that  percipient  or  to  sensation 
to  be  magnitude,  as  they  are  rather  a  relation  to,  and 
a  faculty  for  the  perception  of  the  qualities  of  each 
object.    Thus,  it  is,  from  these  reasons,  made  manifest 
why  sentient  impressions  in  excess  destroy  the  sen- 
tient organs ;  for  if  the  motion  of  the  impression  be 
stronger  than  that  of  the  organ,  then  the  relation 


126  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [l3K.  II. 

which  constitutes  sensation  is  dissolved,  as  harmony 
and  tone  become  discordant,  when  the  chords  are 
struck  too  forcibly. 

But  why  do  not  plants  feel,  seeing  that  they  also 
possess  a  living  part,  and  are  impressionable  by  tan- 
gible qualities  ?  And  that  they  are  so  impressionable 
is  shewn  in  their  being  both  cooled  and  heated  ;  but 
the  cause  is  that  they  have  not  that  mediate  faculty, 
nor  any  such  principle  as  admits  of  their  receiving 
only  the  forms  of  things ;  that  along  with  forms  they 
are  affected  by  the  matter  also. 

It  may  be  questioned  whether  impressions  can  be 
made  by  odour  upon  what  may  be  without  smell,  or 
by  colour  upon  what  may  be  without  vision,  and  so 
for  other  qualities  and  senses.  But  if  that  which  is 
smelt  be  odour,  then  odour,  if  it  produce  anything, 
must  produce  smell,  and  thus  nothing  without  smell 
can  be  affected  by  odour,  and  the  same  holds  good 
for  the  other  senses;  neither  can  beings  which  are 
sentient  be  affected,  save  in  so  far  as  they  are  sen- 
tient. All  which  is  made  evident  in  that  neither 
light  nor  darkness,  sound  nor  odour,  can  act  upon 
bodies,  although  that  which  is  present  with  them 
may,  as  air  with  thunder  splits  wood.  But  yet  tan- 
gible and  sapid  qualities  do  act  upon  bodies;  for, 
otherwise,  by  what  could  inanimate  things  be  acted 
upon  and  changed  ?  Shall  it  then  be  said  that  those 
other  qualities  also  act  upon  bodies  ?  But  all  bodies 


CH.  XII.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  127 

are  not  impressionable  by  odour  and  sound,  and  those 
which  are  so  are  indefinite  and  mobile,  such  as  is  the 
air ;  for  the  air  gives  out  odour,  as  if  it  had  been  sub- 
ject to  impression.  What  then  is  smell  but  impres- 
sion of  some  kind?  But  smelling  is  a  sentient  per- 
ception ;  and  the  air  having  been  impressed  by  odour, 
becomes  quickly  sensible  to  us. 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  I. 

'Tms  book  has  been  by  one  commentator  held  to  be 
spurious,  even  while  admitting  that  all  the  opinions 
are  genuine,  because  of  imputed  solecisms  in  the 
style  and  phraseology,  which  seem  to  indicate  a 
foreign  hand.  But  were  any  one  capable,  as  Tren- 
dellenburg  observes,  of  adopting,  with  so  much  per- 
spicacity, the  reasoning  of  Aristotle,  he  would  be 
much  rather  inclined  to  put  forth  an  original  work, 
than  thus  to  shelter  his  productions  under  another's 
name.  The  opening  passages  involve  great,  it  may 
be,  insuperable  difficulties,  owing  rather  to  the  argu- 
ment than  to  the  wording,  although  this  is  obscure, 
for  it  seems  to  be  assumed  that  a  sense  would  be  felt 
to  be  wanting,  although  it  might  never  have  been 
possessed ;  and  that  the  consciousness  of  its  privation 
would  prove  whether  or  not  a  sense  were  wanting. 

•  According  to  this  theory,  in  fact,  if  the  Touch  were 
a  sense  for  every  impression  of  which  we  now  are 
1  Vide  Trendell.  Comment. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAP.  I.  129 

sensible,  and  if  there  were  any  property  not  percep- 
tible by  us,  we  should  perceive  that  another  sentient 
organ  was  required  ;  but  it  has  not  been  shewn  that 
such  a  want,  had  it  not  previously  been  satisfied, 
could  be  made  sensible  to  us.  And  even  for  the 
Touch  itself,  were  there  any  one  property,  of  which 
we  are  sensible,  say  that  of  hardness,  which  had 
never  been  perceived,  we  could  hardly  be  conscious 
of  the  want ;  and  there  may  be,  probably  are  pro- 
perties in  the  bodies  around  and  above  us  of  which 
we  are  unconscious,  and  yet  remain  without  the  feel- 
ing of  a  want.  Each  of  the  senses  seems  to  be  an 
ultimate  fact ;  for  we  are  satisfied  that  we  see  by 
the  eye  and  hear  by  the  ear,  and  that  with  so  little 
attention  or  will  that  the  sentient  organs  perform 
their  part  almost  irrespectively  of  the  percipient. 
In  the  succeeding  passages,  which  relate  to  media 
and  the  elementary  constitution  of  the  senses,  there 
is  ambiguity  or  confusion,  occasioned  by  the  then 
prevailing  dogmata  of  dements  and  like  by  like,  and 
perhaps,  it  may  be  added,  by  unacquaintance  with 
the  structure  of  the  sentient  organs. 


BOOK    THE    THIRD. 


CHAPTER  I. 

WE  may  be  satisfied,  from  the  observations  which 
follow,  that  there  is  no  sense  besides  the  five — be- 
sides, that  is,  Sight,  Hearing,  Smell,  Taste,  and 
Touch  ;  for  if  Touch  be  the  sense  for  every  impression 
of  which  we  are  sensible,  and  if  we  have  this  sense, 
then,  as  all  the  conditions  of  whatever  is  tangible,  in 
so  far  as  tangible,  are  made  perceptible  to  us  by  the 
Touch,  it  follows  that,  if  any  sensation  be  wanting, 
some  sentient  organ  must  be  wanting  to  us  also. 
Now,  all  the  bodies  which  are  perceived  by  touch- 
ing are  made  sensible  to  us  by  the  Touch  which  has 
been  allotted  to  us ;  and  all  those  which  are  perceived, 
not  by  touching  but,  through  media,  are  made  sensi- 
ble to  us  by  simple  bodies — that  is,  by  air  and  water. 
We  are  so  constituted,  in  fact,  that,  if  several  objects, 
differing  generically  from  one  another,  could  be  per- 
ceived through  one  medium,  an  individual,  having  a 
sentient  organ  such  as  that  medium,  would,  neces- 


CH.  I.]      ARISTOTLE   ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.      131 

sarily,  be  sensible  of  impressions  through  both  me- 
dia— as  if  the  sentient  organ  should  be  of  air,  then,  as 
air  is  the  medium  for  sound  and  colour,  the  individual 
would  be  sensible  of  both  impressions  through  the 
same  organ.  Should  there,  however,  be  more  than 
one  medium  for  the  transmission  of  the  same  impres- 
sion, as  air  as  well  as  water  (since  both  are  diapha- 
nous,) serves  for  the  transmission  of  colour,  then  an 
individual,  having  an  organ  constituted  of  either  of 
those  elements,  would  perceive  impressions  transmit- 
ted through  them  both.  The  sentient  organs,  how- 
ever, are  constituted  of  those  two  simple  bodies,  air 
and  water,  exclusively — for  the  pupil  is  of  water,  the 
hearing  of  air,  and  the  smell  either  of  one  or  other ; 
but  fire  forms  no  part  of  any  organ,  or  rather  it  is  an 
element  common  to  all,  as  there  is  nothing  sentient 
without  heat ;  and  earth  either  does  not  enter  at  all 
into  any  sentient  part,  or  it  has  been  in  some  especial 
and  peculiar  manner  combined  with  the  Touch. 
Thus,  there  can  remain  only  this  conclusion,  that, 
were  there  no  air  or  water,  there  could  be  no  sentient 
organ;  and  organs  so  constituted  are  actually  pos- 
sessed by  animals  now  living.  All  the  senses,  in  fact, 
are  possessed  by  animals  which  are  neither  imperfect 
nor  mutilated ;  for  the  mole  appears  to  have  eyes  be- 
neath its  skin.  So  that,  unless  there  is  some  kind  of 
body  hitherto  unknown  and  some  kind  of  impression 
unsuited  to  bodies  here  on  earth,  it  may  be  affirmed 

9—2 


132  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  III. 

that  no  sense  can  be  wanting  to  us.  But  neither  is  it 
possible  that  there  should  be  any  special  organ  for 
the  perception  of  common  properties,  (such  as  motion, 
rest,  magnitude,  form,  number  and  unity),  of  which 
we  are  made  sensible,  by  each  special  sense,  acci- 
dentally ;  for  we  perceive  all  such  by  motion  as  we  do 
magnitude,  and  as  we  do  form,  as  form  is  a  kind  of 
magnitude ;  the  state  of  rest  we  are  sensible  of  by  the 
absence  of  motion,  and  number  we  perceive  by  the 
want  of  continuity  and  by  particular  senses,  for  each 
sense  is  perceptive  of  unity.  So  that,  evidently,  there 
cannot  be  a  peculiar  sense  for  the  perception  of  any 
one  of  those  properties,  as  motion,  for  instance ;  with 
respect  to  which  we  shall  be  ever  situated  as  we  now 
are,  when,  by  sight,  we  judge  of  something  sweet. 
And  this  we  are  able  to  do  from  our  happening  to 
possess  a  sense  which  is  perceptive  of  double  impres- 
sions, and  by  the  way  in  which  those  impressions 
coincide,  we  recognise  what  the  thing  is ;  were  this 
not  the  case,  then,  in  no  wise,  except  by  chance, 
could  we  perceive  that  the  thing  was  sweet,  any 
more  than  we  could  tell  that  an  individual  is  the  son 
of  Cleon,  not  because  he  is  really  so,  but  because  he 
is  fair ;  and  fairness  is  an  accident  pertaining  to  the 
son  of  Cleon.  And  yet  we  have  a  common  sense  for 
the  perception  of  common  properties  and  that  not 
casually,  although  it  is  not  a  peculiar  sense ;  for,  were 
it  so,  then  in  no  otherwise  could  we  perceive  those 


CH.  I.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  133 

properties  than,  as  has  just  been  said,  we  see  that  an 
individual  is  the  son  of  Cleon.  The  senses,  however, 
do  perceive,  casually,  the  special  qualities  of  each 
other ;  but  then  they  do  so,  not  as  distinct  senses  but, 
as  becoming  one  sense,  as  when  double  impressions 
may  be  made  simultaneously  upon  the  same  organ, 
as  by  bile,  which  is  bitter  and  yellow.  But  as  it 
belongs  not  to  either  sense  to  say  that  both  qualities 
belong  to  one  substance,  we  are  exposed  to  error,  and 
led  to  think  that  if  a  fluid  be  yellow  it  must  be  bile. 

Should  any  one  inquire  why  we  have  been  fur- 
nished with  several  senses  in  place  of  having  only 
one,  it  might  be  answered,  "  that  we  have  so  been 
constituted  in  order  that  the  sequences  and  common 
properties  of  bodies,  as  motion,  magnitude,  and  num- 
ber, may  the  less  readily  escape  our  notice."  If 
vision,  in  fact,  were  our  only  sense  and  it  perceptive 
only  of  whiteness,  then  all  other  qualities  would  more 
readily  escape  our  notice  and  seem  to  be  identical,  on 
account  of  colour  and  magnitude  being  in  an  invariable 
sequence  to  one  another.  But  as  here  common  proper- 
ties are  manifested  in  different  bodies,  it  is  evident  that 
each  of  those  properties  (colour  and  magnitude)  must 
also  be  different. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  II. 

THIS  chapter  opens  with  a  continuation  of  the  discussion 
upon  the  senses,  and,  assuming  sensation  to  be  an 
ultimate  fact,  it  argues  that  vision  (taken  as  an  ex- 
ample), must  be  the  office  of  the  eye,  or  some  other 
sense;  if  the  office  of  some  other  sense,  then  it, 
unlike  every  other,  will  have  had  assigned  to  it  two 
different  modes  of  impression.  Add  to  this,  that 
like  the  visual  sense,  which  perceives  colour  only,  it 
must  be  imbued  with  colour,  and  this  would  inter- 
fere with  its  own  peculiar  office.  The  further  objec- 
tion to  another  than  its  own  sense  for  vision,  in  its 
requiring  an  infinite  series  of  perceptions,  is  neither 
clear  nor  apposite ;  for,  had  a  sense  been  made  per- 
ceptive of  double  impressions,  that  faculty  would  be, 
as  much  as  a  single  sense,  an  ultimate  fact.  The 
passage  has  been  a  fruitful  topic  for  commentators, 
as  might  be  supposed,  but  it  still  remains  the  subject 
of  conjecture. 


CHAPTER  II. 


SINCE  we  are  sensible  that  we  see  and  hear,  we  cannot 
but  be  sensible  that  we  see  by  sight  or  by  some 
other  sense ;  but,  if  we  see  by  some  other  sense,  then 
it  will  be  perceptive  of  sight  and  colour,  the  subject 
of  sight ;  and  thus  there  will  be  either  two  senses  for 
the  same  office,  or  the  sight  itself  will  be  the  percipient. 
If,  besides,  there  is  some  other  than  the  visual  sense 
for  sight,  we  shall  have  to  admit  an  infinite  series  of 
perceptions,  or  else  this  other  sense,  whatever  it  may 
be,  will  be  the  visual  percipient ;  and  this  might  as 
well  have  been  conceded  to  the  first  sense.  But  here 
there  is  a  difficulty — if  to  perceive  by  sight  is  seeing, 
and  if  that  which  is  seen  is  colour  or  something 
having  colour,  then,  if  any  sense  is  to  see  that  which 
sees,  that  sense  must  first  have  colour.  It  is  then 
manifest  that  perception  by  sight  is  not  a  single  per- 
ception ;  for  even  when  we  may  not  see,  it  is  still  by 
sight  that  we  judge  both  of  darkness  and  light,  al- 
though not  in  the  same  manner.  That,  moreover,  which 
sees,  must  have  been  already  imbued  with  colour,  since 
each  sentient  organ  must  be  receptive  of  the  object  of 


136  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  III. 

perception  without  its  matter ;  and  this  accounts  for 
impressions  and  images  being  still  present  in  the  sen- 
tient organs,  after  objects  have  been  withdrawn. 

The  action  of  the  object  of  perception  is  one  and 
the  same  with  that  of  the  sense,  although  they  differ 
in  mode  of  being — I  mean,  for  example,  sound  in 
action  and  hearing  in  action ;  for  it  may  be  that  an 
individual,  endowed  with  hearing,  does  not  hear,  as 
that  a  sonorous  body  does  not  give  out  sound.  But 
when  an  individual,  capable  of  hearing,  listens,  and 
when  that  which  is  sonorous  gives  out  sound,  then 
hearing  in  action  coincides  with  sound  in  action,  and 
the  one  may  strictly  be  termed  hearing,  the  other 
sound.  If  motion,  production,  and  impression,  are  in 
the  product,  it  follows  that  sound  and  hearing,  in  an 
active  state,  must  pre-exist  in  hearing  in  a  potential 
state;  for  the  action  of  the  creative  and  the  motive 
exists,  naturally,  in  that  which  is  to  be  acted  upon. 
It  is,  therefore,  no  way  necessary  that  the  motor 
should  be  itself  in  motion.  The  action,  then,  of  the 
sonorous  body  is  sound  or  sounding,  that  of  the  audi- 
tory sense  is  hearing  or  audition;  for  hearing  is 
double  as  sound  is  double,  and  the  same  applies  to 
other  senses  and  perceptions.  Since  production  and 
impression  are,  not  in  that  which  acts  but,  in  that 
which  is  impressed,  so  the  action  of  the  object  of  per- 
ception and  the  sensibility  is  in  the  sentient  being. 
But,  while  for  some  senses  these  two  states  have 


CH.  II.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  137 

been  specially  distinguished  by  names,  as  sound  and 
hearing,  there  are  others  for  which  one  or  other  state 
is  without  appellation — the  action  of  vision,  for  in- 
stance, is  called  sight,  but  the  action  of  colour  is 
unnamed ;  the  action  of  the  sapid  sense  is  called  taste, 
while  that  of  savour  is  without  appellation. 

Since  the  action  of  the  object  of  perception  and 
that  of  the  sentient  being  is  one  and  the  same, 
although  different  in  mode  of  acting,  it  follows  that 
hearing  and  sound,  in  this  sense,  must  together  be  lost, 
or  together  be  preserved;  and  this  is  true  of  taste 
and  savour,  and  other  senses  and  functions ;  but  yet  it 
does  not  hold  good  of  those  relations  in  potentiality. 

The  earlier  physiologists  have  expressed  them- 
selves ill  upon  the  subject,  as  they  thought  that  there 
can  be  neither  black  nor  white  without  sight,  nor 
savour  without  Taste.  And  yet  what  they  said  was 
in  part  right  and  in  part  wrong;  for  as  senses  and 
sentient  impressions  have  a  twofold  acceptation,  ac- 
cording to  their  state  of  potentiality  or  activity,  so 
what  was  advanced  by  them  may  be  applicable  to 
the  one  state,  and  inapplicable  to  the  other.  The  fact 
is,  those  writers  reasoned  absolutely  upon  conditions, 
which  do  not  admit  of  being  so  dealt  with.  If  a  voice 
of  any  kind  is  harmony,  and  if  voice  and  hearing  are, 
in  one  sense,  the  same,  and,  in  another  sense,  not  the 
same,  then,  as  harmony  is  proportion,  it  follows  that 
hearing  must  be  proportion  also.  And  hence  it  comes 


138  ABISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  III. 

that  every  sound  in  excess,  whether  acute  or  grave, 
perverts  the  hearing,  as  every  savour  in  excess  does 
the  taste ;  and  every  colour  over-bright  or  dark  dulls 
the  sight,  as  every  odour  excessively  pungent,  whether 
grateful  or  offensive,  does  the  smell,  as  if  shewing 
that  sensibility  is  a  kind  of  proportion.  Thus,  quali- 
ties, as  acid  or  sweet  or  saline,  are  agreeable  when- 
ever they  are  reduced,  pure  and  unmixed,  to  a  due 
proportion ;  for  it  is  this  only  which  renders  them 
grateful.  To  speak  generally,  harmony  is  a  combi- 
nation of  tones  rather  than  the  acute  or  the  grave 
singly,  as  for  the  Touch,  the  warmed  or  cooled  is 
genial,  rather  than  the  hot  or  cold,  simply;  for,  as 
sensibility  is  proportion,  so  qualities,  in  excess,  pain 
or  pervert  the  senses. 

Each  sense  is  perceptive  of  its  own  appointed 
subjects,  is  innate  in  its  own  organ,  as  a  op°nal 
organ,  and  judges  of  the  distinctions  of  qualities,  as 
sight  judges  of  white  and  black ;  taste  of  bitter  and 
sweet,  and  so  as  to  other  senses  and  qualities.  But 
since  we  judge  of  white,  sweet,  and  each  other 
quality  by  its  relation  to  each  sense,  by  what  do  we 
perceive  that  qualities  differ  ?  Now,  it  is  evident  that 
it  must  be  by  some  sense,  as  the  impressions  are  all 
sentient ;  and  equally  so  that  the  flesh  cannot  be  that 
final  organism,  as  in  order  to  judge  of  qualities  it 
must,  of  necessity,  first  touch  bodies.  Neither  is  it 
admissible  that,  by  different  senses,  we  judge  sweet 


CH.  II.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  139 

to  be  different  from  white,  as  both  qualities  must  be 
apparent  to  some  single  faculty;  for,  otherwise,  it  would 
be  as  if  I  should  perceive  one  quality  and  you  perceive 
another,  and  thus  make  it  evident  that  they  are  dif- 
ferent from  one  another.  But  it  is  here  required  that 
the  same  individual  should  perceive  that  they  are 
different,  for  the  sweet  is  different  from  the  white, 
and  what  he  perceives  that  he  says  ;  and  thus,  what 
he  says  that  he  thinks  and  perceives.  It  is  then  evi- 
dent that  we  cannot,  by  different  senses,  judge  of 
different  qualities,  as  also,  from  what  follows,  that  we 
cannot  judge  of  them  in  a  separate  portion  of  time. 
Neither  can  an  opinion  be  in  a  separate  portion  of 
time ;  for  just  as  it  is  the  same  individual  who  says 
that  good  is  other  than  bad,  so  when  he  says  that  the 
one  is  different  from  the  other,  he  implies  that  the 
other  is  equally  so,  and  does  not  employ  the  term 
when  loosely — he  does  not  use  it,  I  mean,  in  the 
sense  of  now,  in  the  phrase,  "now  I  say  that  the  object 
is  different,"  without  implying  that  it  is  different  now. 
But,  here,  it  is  the  same  individual  who  employs  the 
term  now,  and  says  that  objects  are  different  now  and 
because  now;  for  the  impressions  are  coincident,  as 
they  are  inseparable,  and  as  the  time  is  indivisible.  It 
cannot,  however,  be,  that  the  same  individual,  in  so 
far  as  indivisible,  should  be  subject  to  contrary  im- 
pulses in  time  which  is  indivisible ;  yet  if  sweetness 
move  sensation  or  thought  in  one  way,  bitterness 


140     ARISTOTLE  ON  THE   VITAL  PRINCIPLE.    [BK.  III. 

must  move  them  in  an  opposite,  and  whiteness  in 
some  other  direction.  Can,  then,  that  which  judges 
be,  numerically,  indivisible  and  inseparable,  yet  sepa- 
rable in  its  mode  of  being  ?  If  so,  then,  in  some  way, 
as  divisible,  it  may  perceive  divisible,  and,  in  some 
way,  as  indivisible,  it  may  perceive  indivisible  quali- 
ties ;  for  in  its  mode  of  being  it  is  separable,  but, 
locally  and  numerically,  it  is  inseparable.  But  is  not 
this  impossible  ?  The  same  may,  in  potentiality,  be 
indivisible  and  divisible  and  be  the  contraries;  but 
not  so  in  mode  of  being,  as  it  is  divisible  in  action, 
and  cannot  possibly  be  at  once  white  and  black,  nor 
be  simultaneously  impressed  by  the  forms  of  those 
colours,  provided  sensation  and  thought  are  such  as 
we  have  said  they  are.  But  it  is  with  this,  as  with 
that  which  some  call  a  point,  and  which,  in  so  far  as 
it  is  one  or  dual,  is  indivisible  or  divisible.  Thus,  in 
so  far  as  that  which  judges  is  one,  it  is  indivisible, 
and  its  perceptions  are  simultaneous ;  and  in  so  far  as 
it  is  divisible,  it  employs  the  same  point  twice,  simul- 
taneously. In  so  far,  then,  as  it  employs  the  boun- 
dary as  two,  it  judges  of  two  things  by  it  and  per- 
ceives that  they  are  distinct,  as  the  boundaries  of  the 
line  are  distinct ;  but  in  so  far  as  it  is  one,  it  judges 
by  one  act,  and  judges  simultaneously. 

Let  what  has  been  said  then  suffice  for  the  defi- 
nition of  that  principle,  by  which  we  maintain  that 
an  animal  is  made  a  sentient  being. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  III. 


THIS  chapter  may  be  regarded  as  a  metaphysical  disquisi- 
tion, since  its  purport  is  to  distinguish  mental  facul- 
ties from  corporeal  sensations  as  well  as  to  examine 
the  opinions  of  earlier  writers  who  had  maintained 
that  cogitation  is  some  kind  of  sensation;  and, 
finally,  the  nature  of  imagination,  as  lying  inter- 
mediately between  faculties  and  sensations,  is  investi- 
gated and  defined.  It  treats,  too,  although  but 
incidentally,  of  the  understanding,  knowledge,  opi- 
nion, and  other  topics  which  border  on  abstractions  ; 
and  closes  with  etymology  to  shew  the  sentient 
origin  of  imagination. 


CHAPTER  III. 


As  writers,  for  the  most  part,  define  Vital  Principle 
by  two  different  faculties,  by  locomotion  and  thought, 
judgment  and  sensibility,  it  would  seem  as  though 
thought  and  reflexion  are  by  them  considered  to  be 
some  kind  of  sensation ;  for,  in  both  cases,  the  Vital 
Principle  both  discerns  and  recognises  something. 
Thus,  the  ancients  affirm  that  reflexion  is  identical 
with  feeling;  and  Empedocles  has  said,  "man's  in- 
telligence is  enlarged  by  what  is  present,"  and,  else- 
where, "  hence,  man  derives  his  power  of  reflecting 
upon  different  subjects;"  so  Homer's  words,  "such  is 
the  mind"  do  but  express  the  same  idea.  All  these 
writers  assume,  in  fact,  that  thinking,  like  feeling,  is 
corporeal,  and  that  Like  is  perceived  and  compre- 
hended by  Like,  as  was  explained  in  our  opening 
chapters.  But  yet  it  was  incumbent  upon  them  to 
have  spoken,  at  the  same  time,  upon  the  liability  to 
error  through  the  senses ;  for  this  belongs,  more  pe- 
culiarly, to  animals,  and  Vital  Principle  remains  sub- 
ject to  it  during  the  greater  portion  of  existence.  On 
which  account,  either  all  appearances  are,  as  some  of 


CH.  III.]    AEISTOTLE   ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.     143 

those  writers  maintain,  necessarily,  true,  or  else  error 
is  caused  by  contact  of  the  unlike,  which  is  the  oppo- 
site of  the  opinion,  that  like  is  recognised  by  like;  and 
the  error  from  contraries  seems  to  be  identical  with 
the  knowledge  of  contraries.  It  is  manifest  that  feel- 
ing is  not  identical  with  reflexion;  for,  while  the 
former  belongs  to  all  creatures,  the  latter  has  been 
imparted  only  to  a  few.  Neither  is  thinking,  that 
faculty  to  which  belongs  the  sense  of  right  and  wrong, 
(the  right  comprehending  judgment,  knowledge,  and 
sound  opinion,  the  wrong  comprehending  their  con- 
traries,) to  be  confounded  with  feeling — for  sensation, 
being  derived  from  particulars,  is  ever  true,  and 
belongs  to  all  animals;  but  the  judgment  may  be 
wrong,  and  is  imparted  only  to  such  as  have  reason. 
Imagination,  in  fact,  is  neither  sensation  nor  judg- 
ment, and  yet  it  is  not  called  up  without  sensation, 
just  as,  without  sensation,  there  can  be  no  conception ; 
but  it  is  manifest  that  imagination  is  not  conception. 
Imagination  depends,  in  fact,  but  upon  ourselves,  as  we 
can,  at  will,  call  it  up  (since  it  is  in  our  own  power 
to  place  images  before  the  eyes,  as  do  they  who,  for 
mnemonic  aids,  by  laying  down  objects,  form  sym- 
bols) ;  but  to  form  an  opinion  does  not  depend  upon 
ourselves,  and  then  every  opinion  is,  of  necessity, 
either  true  or  false.  Whenever,  besides,  we  may  have 
an  opinion  upon  any  terrible  and  fearful  incident,  we 
are  straightway  affected  as  if  it  were  a  reality,  just  as 


144  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  III. 

we  are  when  we  think  upon  any  desperate  deed ;  but, 
under  imagination,  we  become  simple  spectators,  as  it 
were,  of  a  pictorial  representation  of  terrible  or  daring 
achievements.  There  are,  in  conception  itself,  the 
distinctions  of  knowledge,  opinion,  reflexion,  and  their 
contraries,  of  which  we  shall  speak  elsewhere.  With 
respect  to  thinking,  since  it  is  different  from  feeling, 
and  feeling  seems,  in  part,  to  be  imagination  and,  in 
part,  conception,  let  us  here  define  imagination,  and 
then  proceed  to  the  consideration  of  the  other  faculty. 

If  imagination  be  a  faculty  by  which  we  say  that 
an  image  of  some  kind,  and  that  not  merely  in  the 
sense  of  a  metaphor,  is  called  up  within  us,  then  it  is 
to  be  ranged  among  those  faculties  or  powers,  such  as 
feeling,  opinion,  knowledge,  mind,  by  which  we  form 
judgments  and  determine  what  may  be  true  or  false. 

It  is  clear  from  what  follows,  that  imagination  is 
not  sensation ;  for  sensation  is  either  a  faculty  or  an 
act,  such  as  sight,  and  seeing,  but  an  image  is  some- 
times apparent  to  us  without  either  faculty  or  act,  as 
phantoms  in  dreams  for  instance ;  and  then  sensation 
is  ever  present,  which  is  not  the  case  with  the  imagi- 
nation. If,  moreover,  imagination  were  in  act  identical 
with  sensation,  we  should  have  to  admit  that  it  must 
belong  to  all  irrational  creatures,  but  this  does  not  seem 
to  be  the  case  with  the  ant,  bee,  or  worm;  and  then 
sensations  are  always  true,  but  imaginings  are  for  the 
most  part  false.  Hence,  we  do  not  say,  when  accurately 


CH.  III.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  145 

examining  any  object,  that  we  imagine  to  be  so  or 
so,  a  man  for  instance,  but  we  so  express  ourselves 
rather  when  we  do  not  clearly  perceive  what  the 
object  is,  and  when  the  perception  may  be  true  or 
false;  when,  to  use  a  former  expression,  the  object 
appears  to  us  as  landscapes  do  to  the  purblind. 

Neither  can  imagination  be  regarded  as  one  ot 
those  faculties,  such  as  knowledge  and  mind,  which  are 
always  true,  for  it  admits  of  being  false  as  well ;  and 
it  remains  for  us  to  consider  whether  it  is  opinion, 
since  opinion  may  be  both  true  and  false.  But  belief 
follows  upon  opinion,  (as  it  is  not  admissible  that  an 
individual  should  not  believe  in  that  upon  which  he 
has  an  opinion,)  and  belief  belongs  to  no  irrational 
creature  although  imagination  is  imparted  to  many. 
Belief,  besides,  is  an  attendant  upon  every  opinion, 
as  persuasion  is  upon  belief,  and  reason  alone  can 
persuade ;  but  although  imagination  belongs  to  some 
irrational  creatures,  reason  has  been  given  to  none. 
It  is  manifest,  then,  that  imagination  can  neither  be 
opinion  with  or  through  sensation,  nor  a  combination 
of  opinion  with  sensation ;  and  for  the  same  reasons 
evident,  that  opinion  is  from  nothing  else  but  that 
from  which  sensation  is  derived.  By  which  I  mean, 
if  imagination  be  the  combination  of  an  opinion  of 
whiteness  and  a  sensation  of  whiteness,  and  not  of  an 
opinion  of  goodness  with  a  sensation  of  whiteness,  then 
to  imagine  is  to  think  upon  what  has  been  sensually ' 

10 


146  ARISTOTLE  ON   THE  [BK.  III. 

perceived,  and  that  not  accidentally.  But  there  are 
appearances  which  are  fallacious,  although  our  concep- 
tion of  them  at  the  time  may  be  true,  as  the  sun,  for 
instance,  appears  to  be  a  foot  in  diameter,  and  yet  we 
are  satisfied  that  it  is  larger  than  the  earth ;  and  in 
such  a  case  it  happens  either  that  the  true  opinion  of 
the  sun's  dimension  must  have  been  cast  aside,  or 
else,  while  the  sun  remains  as  it  was  and  the  true 
opinion  has  neither  been  forgotten  nor  changed,  that 
the  opinion  is  at  once  both  true  and  false.  But  the 
opinion  is  simply  false  when  it  escapes  us  that  the 
thing  seen  is  altered.  It  is  evident,  then,  that  ima- 
gination can  neither  be  any  one,  nor  be  derived  from 
any  one  of  those  faculties. 

Since  one  object  having  been  set  in  motion  can 
communicate  motion  to  another,  and  since  imagination 
seems  to  be  a  kind  of  motion,  and  never  to  be  produced 
without  sensation,  or  in  other  than  sentient  creatures, 
or  without  the  objects  of  sentient  perception,  and  since, 
on  the  other  hand,  motion  can  be  produced  by  the  act 
of  sensation,  and  this  motion  must  of  necessity  be 
equal  to  the  impression,  it  may  be  admitted  that  the 
motion  of  imagination  can  neither  be  produced  with- 
out sensation,  nor  in  other  than  sentient  beings ;  that 
beings  endowed  with  it  act  and  are  acted  upon  in 
many  ways,  and  that  its  manifestations  are  both  true 
and  false.  This  latter  alternative  happens  thus:  the 
sensation  which  is  derived  from  the  objects  peculiar 


CH.  III.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  147 

to  each  sense  is  true,  or  it  involves  the  smallest 
amount  of  error ;  but  when,  in  the  second  place,  such 
objects  are  perceived  in  their  accidents,  there  is  room 
for  fallacy;  when  for  instance,  something  is  said  to 
be  white,  there  is  no  fallacy,  but  when  that  object  is 
particularised  and  said  to  be  this  or  that,  the  percep- 
tion may  be  fallacious.  There  is,  in  the  third  place, 
liability  to  error  in  our  perception  of  common  proper- 
ties, and  sequences  in  the  accidents  referrible  to  parti- 
cular bodies — accidents,  I  mean,  such  as  motion  and 
magnitude,  which  are  referrible  to  all  bodies,  and 
from  which  there  is  peculiar  liability  to  error  through 
the  senses.  But  the  motion  produced  by  the  act  of  sen- 
sation will  differ  from  the  sensation  derived  from  these 
three  modes  of  sensation — the  first,  while  sensation  is 
yet  present,  must  be  true;  but  the  others,  whether  sen- 
sation be  present  or  not,  may  be  fallacious,  and  more 
especially,  when  the  objects  causative  of  sensation  may 
have  been  withdrawn.  If,  then,  imagination  alone 
fulfil  all  the  conditions  indicated,  and  if  it  be  all  that 
has  been  said,  it  may  be  defined  as  motion  produced 
by  sensation  in  action.  And  since  vision  is  a  sense 
above  all  others,  imagination  has  derived  its  appella- 
tion from  light,  because  without  light  there  is  no 
vision;  and  owing  to  its  being  an  abiding  faculty 
and  like  sensations,  animals  perform  many  of  their 
actions  through  it.  Some  animals  are  so  influenced  from 
being  irrational;  and  others,  as  man,  from  having 

10—2 


148      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE   VITAL  PRINCIPLE.    [BK.  III. 

their  understanding  eclipsed,  at  times,  by  passion, 
disorder,  or  sleep. 

Let  this  much,  however,  suffice  for  the  inquiry 
into  imagination,  for  shewing  what  it  is,  and  for  what 
purposes  it  has  been  imparted. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER   IV. 

THIS  chapter  is  upon  the  mind  (o  uous)  and  Aristotle's 
inquiry  is,  whether  it  is  part  of  that  principle  which 
gives  life  to  the  body,  or  altogether  distinct  from 
corporeal  relations.  It  seems  to  be  at  once  deter- 
mined that  there  is  no  affinity  between  the  mind 
and  sensibility,  the  ministrations  of  which  trench  so 
closely  upon  cogitation ;  and  that  the  mind,  there- 
fore, existing  independently  of  the  body,  is  related  to 
subjects  of  thought,  abstractions  that  is,  as  is  sensi- 
bility to  sensism  and  sensation.  Anaxagoras  re- 
garded all  things  as  combinations  save  mind,  which 
alone  he  held  to  be  homogeneous  and  pure.  Aris- 
totle1 makes  the  mind  to  be  receptive  of  the  subject, 
and  the  essence  of  the  subject  of  thought ;  to  be 
something  divine,  and  to  confer  upon  us  contempla- 
tion, which  is  our  sweetest,  best  enjoyment.  "  If  this 
faculty,  in  its  occasional  exercise,  as  by  ourselves,  is 
happiness,  it  is,  as  the  eternal  attribute  of  the  Deity, 

1  Metaphys.  I.  8,  13 ;  XI.  7,  8 ;  I.  3,  10  ;  m.  5,  12. 


150  PRELUDE  TO  CHAP.  IV. 

•wonderful,  and  more  wonderful  in  proportion  as 
more  enduring."  But  yet  Aristotle  quotes,  without 
objection,  that  the  mind  is  innate  in  animals.,  and 
the  cause,  in  nature,  of  the  world  and  its  order ;  and 
he  cites  the  verses  of  Parmenides,  which  seem  to 
imply  that  the  mind  is  present  in  the  limbs  of  man 
as  if  it  were  a  corporeal  agent.  To  judge,  however, 
from  observations  in  the  course  of  this  treatise,  he 
may  be  said,  although,  perhaps,  not  always  consist- 
ently, to  have  considered  this  great  principle  as 
impassive,  indiscerptible,  and  freed  from  all  corporeal 
ties ;  and  as  being  itself,  only  when  withdrawn  from 
matter  and  its  influences.  Thus,  as  matter  must 
tend  to  preclude  its  offices,  its  existence,  while  asso- 
ciated with  mortal  beings,  can  be  only  that  of  poten- 
tiality. 


CHAPTEK  IV. 

WITH  respect  to  the  part  of  Vital  Principle  by  which 
it  both  knows  and  reflects,  whether  that  part  be  sepa- 
rate, or  separate,  not  substantively  but,  in  an  abstract 
sense  only,  let  us  now  consider  in  what  it  is  distin- 
guished from  other  parts,  and  how  thinking  is  at  any 
time  exercised.  If  thinking  be  such  as  is  feeling, 
then  it  may  be  some  kind  of  impression  by  the  subject 
of  thought,  or  other  analogous  agency.  But  then 
that  which  thinks  must  be  impassive,  receptive  of  the 
form  of  objects,  and,  in  potentiality,  the  same  as  the 
object,  without  actually  being  so.  The  mind,  in  fine, 
must  be  related  to  subjects  of  thought  as  the  sensi- 
bility is  to  objects  of  perception.  It  is,  then,  necessary 
since  the  mind  thinks  upon  all  subjects,  that  it  should 
be  homogeneous,  in  order,  as  Anaxagoras  expresses 
himself,  that  it  should  domine,  that  is,  recognise 
things ;  and  as  whatever  is  foreign  to  it  precludes 
and  eclipses  its  inward  light,  so  it  can  have  no  other 
nature  than  that  of  potentiality.  Thus,  the  so-called 
mind  of  Vital  Principle  (and  by  mind  I  mean  that  part 
by  which  Vital  Principle  judges  and  compares),  is 
not  actually  any  one  of  the  subjects  of  thought  before 


152  ARISTOTLE   ON   THE  [BK.  III. 

thinking  upon  it.  It  is  very  improbable,  therefore, 
that  the  mind  should  have  been  commingled  with  the 
body;  for  were  this  the  case,  it  would  be  a  quality  of 
some  kind,  as  hot  or  cold,  or  it  would  have  some  kind 
of  organ  as  there  is  for  the  sensibility,  but  no  such 
organ  is  to  be  found.  It  is  well  said  by  some  that 
Vital  Principle  is  the  place  of  forms,  only  this  is  to 
be  understood  of  Vital  Principle,  not  as  a  whole  but 
as  a  cogitative  faculty,  and  of  forms,  not  in  reality 
but,  in  potentiality. 

It  is  manifest,  from  the  nature  of  the  sentient 
organs  and  sensation,  that  the  quiescent  state  of  the 
sentient  is  not  the  same  as  that  of  the  cogitative  part. 
For  the  sensibility  is  unable  to  distinguish  impressions 
in  excess,  as  a  sound  amid  loud  sounds,  or  a  colour  or 
odour  among  brilliant  colours  or  pungent  odours,  but 
the  mind,  on  the  contrary,  when  thinking  intensely 
upon  any  subject,  can  still  think  and  with  increased 
rather  than  diminished  intensity  upon  the  subordinate 
details ;  the  sensibility,  besides,  cannot  be  without  a 
body,  but  the  mind  is  separable.  When  thus  situated, 
the  mind  can  become  each  of  the  subjects  of  thought, 
as  an  individual  is  said  to  be  learned  actually  (and 
this  may  be  said  when  he  is  able  at  will  to  employ 
his  learning,)  because  he  is  at  the  same  time  equally 
learned  in  potentiality,  although  not  as  he  was  before 
he  had  learned  or  invented  something ;  for  when  so 
learned  he  is  able  to  reflect  upon  his  learning. 


CH.  IV.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  153 

There  is  a  distinction  between  positive  magnitude 
and  ideal  magnitude,  water  and  ideal  water,  and  so 
between  many  but  yet  not  all  substances,  as  with 
some  the  two  states  are  identical,  but  the  mind  judges 
of  flesh  and  ideal  flesh  either  by  some  different  faculty 
or  by  being  itself  differently  disposed ;  for  flesh  cannot 
be  without  matter,  but,  as  is  a  snub  nose,  it  is  some- 
thing in  something.  Now,  it  is  by  the  sensibility 
that  we  judge  of  hot  and  cold  and  other  properties  of 
which  flesh  is  the  standard ;  but  it  is  either  by  some 
distinct  faculty  or  as  a  curved  is  to  an  extended  line, 
that  we  judge  of  ideal  flesh.  Straightness,  on  the 
other  hand,  as  well  as  the  snub  nose  we  place  among 
abstractions,  for  each  is  associated  with  continuity; 
but  the  difference,  if  there  be  a  difference,  between 
positive  straightness  and  ideal  straightness,  the  mind 
judges  of  by  some  other,  perhaps  a  dual  faculty ; 
by  some  other  faculty,  at  least,  or  by  being  itself 
differently  disposed.  To  use  a  general  expression, 
as  are  things  abstracted  from  matter  so  are  subjects 
of  thought  with  respect  to  the  mind. 

It  is  difficult  to  determine  how  the  mind,  if  it  be 
as  Anaxagoras  supposes,  homogeneous,  impassive 
and  without  any  thing  in  common  with  aught  else, 
is  to  think,  if  thinking  be  some  kind  of  impression ; 
for  it  is  only  in  so  far  as  there  is  something  in  com- 
mon between  two  substances,  that  the  one  seems  to 
act  and  the  other  to  be  acted  upon.  And  there  is 


154      ARISTOTLE   ON   THE    VITAL   PRINCIPLE.    [BK.  III. 

the  same  difficulty  if  the  mind  itself  is  intelligible ; 
for  it  will  be  present  in  other  things,  unless  it  is 
itself,  intelligible  in  some  other  way  than  they  are, 
and  unless  the  subject  of  thought  is  some  one 
specific  subject ;  or  else  the  mind  will  be  some 
kind  of  combination,  and  this  reduces  thought  to  the 
nature  of  other  things.  But  to  suffer  impression 
according  to  some  common  relation  implies,  as  has 
been  just  explained,  that  the  mind,  in  potentiality,  is 
as  the  subjects  thought  upon,  and  yet  that,  in  reality, 
it  is  no  one  of  them  before  thinking  upon  it;  and 
thus  the  mind  is  to  be  regarded  as  a  tablet  on  which 
nothing  may  have  been  actually  inscribed.  The  mind 
is  a  subject  of  thought  to  itself  as  is  any  other  topic, 
since  that  which  thinks  and  the  subject  of  thought 
are  among  immaterialities ;  for  speculative  knowledge 
is  the  same  as  the  subject  which  is  so  known.  But 
we  have  to  consider  why  the  mind  is  not  always 
thinking,  as  each  subject  of  thought,  in  potentiality, 
is  among  materialities  ;  so  that  the  mind  will  not  be 
present  in  any  one  of  them  (for  the  mind  is  the 
immaterial  faculty  which  judges  of  them),  although 
each  of  them  will  be  subject  to  the  mind. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  V. 


THIS  chapter  assumes  the  existence  of  a  generic  matter, 
as  well  as  something  which  is  to  give  to  it  reality, 
and  thus  it  seems  to  admit  of  formative  conditions 
other  than  those  assigned  to  Vital  Principle ;  the 
mind  too,  although  said  to  be  immaterial,  is  likened 
to  a  material  agent.  Aristotle1  elsewhere,  somewhat 
in  conformity  with  this,  says,  "even  granting  that 
all  things  may  be  from  one,  or  more  than  one  primal 
element,  and  that  the  self-same  matter  may  be  the 
source  of  all  beings,  yet  there  is  a  peculiar  matter 
for  each  genus,  as  pituita  is  the  primal  matter  for 
sweet  and  oily,  as  the  matter  of  bile  is  for  bitter  and 
analogous  qualities."  An  early  commentator  observes, 
"matter  is  the  receptacle  and  subject  of  forms, 
without  having  in  itself  either  figure,  quality,  mag- 
nitude, or  place ;  nevertheless,  it  is  not  a  mere  name, 
but  truly  exists  as  the  basis  of  qualities.  Matter 

1  Metaphys.  vu.  4.  i. 


156  PRELUDE   TO   CHAP.  V.  [BK.  III. 

exists  potentially,  bodies  actually,  with  their  peculiar 
character ;  and  matter  cannot  be  separated  from 
form  and  real  existence." 


CHAPTER  V. 

SINCE,  throughout  all  nature,  there  is  a  matter  for 
each  genus  of  entities  (that  which  all  belonging  to 
that  genus  are  in  potentiality),  and  a  something  which 
is  causative  and  constitutive  from  its  making  things 
what  they  are,  as  art  impresses  its  forms  upon  matter, 
so  those  same  distinctions  must,  of  necessity,  co-exist 
in  the  vital  principle.  Such  also  is  the  mind,  from 
its  faculty,  on  the  one  hand,  of  becoming  all  things, 
and,  on  the  other,  of  creating  all  things,  as  if  it  were 
a  virtuality  like  light ;  for  light,  in  a  certain  sense, 
makes  colours,  being  in  potentiality,  to  become  colours 
in  reality ;  and  the  mind  here  meant  is  separate,  im- 
passive and  homogeneous,  being  essentially  an  ener- 
gizing influence. 

That  which  acts  is  ever,  in  fact,  more  influential 
than  that  which  is  acted  upon,  as  the  causative  prin- 
ciple is  than  the  matter.  Now,  knowledge  in  activity 
is  identical  with  the  subject ;  but  knowledge  in  poten- 
tiality pre-exists  in  the  individual ;  and  yet,  strictly 


CH.  V.]      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.          157 

speaking,  it  does  not  pre-exist,  as  that  cannot  be  said 
to  pre-exist  which  sometimes  is,  and  sometimes  is  not 
reflected  on.  But  that  alone,  whatever  it  be,  which 
thinks,  is  separate  from  all  else,  immortal  and  eternal ; 
and,  because  it  is  impassive,  we  derive  from  it  no 
memory.  But  the  impressionable  mind,  on  the  con- 
trary, is  perishable ;  and  without  it  there  can  be  no 
cogitation. 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  VI. 


THIS  chapter  does  but  repeat  what  has  already  been 
insisted  upon,  that  the  mind  or  the  sensibility,  when 
engaged  upon  indivisibles,  that  is,  single  ideas  or 
simple  sensations,  is  not  subject  to  error ;  and  that 
the  liability  to  error  commences  when  ideas  or  sensa- 
tions are  either  generalized,  or  judged  of  in  their 
relations.  It  may  be  added,  that  the  want  of  a 
sensorium  or  faculty  for  the  generalization  of  par- 
ticular sensations,  and  for  affording  to  the  mind, 
thereby,  terms  for  comparison,  is  felt  so  much 
throughout,  that  the  brain  alone  can,  for  some 
passages,  fully  explain  all  that  the  words  may  seem 
to  imply. 


CHAPTER  VI. 


WHENEVER  cogitation  is  employed  upon  what  may 
be  indivisible  it  is  not  subject  to  error,  but  when 
engaged  upon  topics  which  involve  both  error  and 
truth,  there  is  a  simultaneous  combination  of  thoughts, 
whereby  they  are,  so  to  say,  individualized ;  in  the 
way  that  Empedocles  expressed  himself,  "Now  the 
heads  of  many  creatures  budded  forth  without  necks, 
and  then,  heads  and  necks  were  by  affinity  made  one." 
It  is  thus  that  thoughts,  however  disconnected,  as 
the  incommensurable  and  the  diameter,  are  by  the 
intelligence  joined  together.  If  the  question  relate 
to  things  past  or  future,  the  mind,  thinking  upon 
time  besides,  adds  it  to  the  other  conditions;  for 
error  lies  ever  in  the  combination,  as  when  the  white 
is  said  not  to  be  white,  the  error  is  in  the  addition  of 
the  negative.  Now,  it  is  always  in  our  power  to 
speak  of  things  individually ;  but  then,  it  is  not  only 
true  or  false  that  Clem  is  fair,  but  equally  so  that  he 
ever  was  or  ever  will  be  fair.  It  is  the  mind  which 
individualizes  each  subject.  But  since  the  indivisi- 
ble is  in  the  twofold  state  either  of  potentiality  or 


160  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  III. 

actuality,  there  is  nothing  to  preclude  the  mind  when 
thinking  upon  extension,  from  thinking  upon  it  as 
indivisible,  for  it  is  indivisible,  actually,  and  in  time 
which  is  indivisible ;  as  time,  like  extension,  is  both 
divisible  and  indivisible.  It  may  not  then  be  said 
that  the  mind  thinks  upon  any  subject  in  each  half; 
for  extension  exists  only  in  potentiality,  unless  it  have 
been  divided.  But  the  mind,  when  thinking  upon 
each  of  the  halves  separately,  divides  the  time  simul- 
taneously, and  then  time  becomes  such  as  the  two 
extensions ;  and  if  the  mind  make  a  whole  of  the  two 
halves,  it  does  the  same  with  time  in  its  relation  to 
them.  The  mind,  however,  thinks  upon  the  indivisible 
as  species  and  not  as  quantity,  in  an  indivisible  portion 
of  time  and  by  an  indivisible  part  of  Vital  Principle ; 
and  this  neither  by  accident,  nor  in  so  far  as  the  sub- 
jects thought  upon,  or  the  part  by  which,  or  the  time 
in  which,  it  thinks,  are  divisible,  but  as  they  are  indi- 
visible. There  is,  in  fact,  in  such  cases  a  something 
indivisible,  although  it  may  not  be  separate,  which 
makes  time  and  extension  to  be  one;  and  which  holds 
good  for  all  continuity,  whether  of  time  or  extension. 
Now,  the  point  and  every  analogous  division,  and 
whatever  is  as  the  point  indivisible,  are  made  known 
as  being  privation  of  something.  The  reasoning  upon 
other  subjects  is  like  this,  for  were  it  asked  how  the 
mind  is  to  recognise  bad  or  black,  it  may  be  answered, 
that  it  recognises  them  in  some  way  by  their  contraries; 


CH.  VI.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  161 

but  that  which  recognises  them  must,  in  potentiality, 
be  the  thing  recognised,  and  be  present  also  in  it.  If 
to  any  one  of  the  senses  there  is  no  contrary,  then  that 
sense  recognises  itself,  is  in  activity  and  separate  from 
all  else.  An  affirmation,  like  a  negation,  is  something 
in  relation  to  something,  and  is  always  either  true  or 
false ;  but  not  so  with  the  mind,  as  it  is  true  when  it 
judges  of  any  thing  after  its  essence,  and  may  not  be 
true  when  it  judges  of  something  in  its  relation  to 
something  else.  Thus,  the  visual  perception  of  any 
particular  object  is  true,  but  whether  a  something 
white  which  is  seen  be  or  be  not  a  man  is  not  in- 
variably true ;  and  this  holds  good  for  abstractions. 


11 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  VII. 

COMMENTATORS  are  generally  agreed  in  regarding  this 
chapter  as  a  series  of  ill-connected  repetitions  of 
former  statements  and  doctrines ;  but,  although 
repetitions,  they  will  be  found  to  illustrate  or  tend 
to  the  completion  of  some  preceding  opinions.  It 
maintains,  in  fact,  the  same  dogmata,  adopts  the 
same  illustrations,  and  assumes  a  faculty,  the  repre- 
sentative of  a  sensorium,  which  physiology  could  not 
then  supply ;  and  thus,  although  the  wording  may 
differ,  the  purport  is  the  same.  The  term  evepyfia 
(which  was  before  alluded  to)  is  employed,  in  a  more 
especial  manner  in  this  chapter,  and  as  neither  its 
meaning  is  obvious  nor  its  equivalent  easily  selected, 
it  may  be  well  to  offer  a  few  words  in  explanation  of 
it.  Although  it  is  opposed,  like  the  e'i/xeA.e'^;eia,  to 
8i/i/a/ji<?,  still  the  two  terms  are  not  synonymous  ;  for 
the  former  (the  evepyeia)  seems  to  relate  to  action 
in  some  form,  and  the  latter  to  completion  or  deve- 
lopment of  something  out  of  an  imperfect  or  nascent 


PRELUDE   TO   CHAP.  VII.  163 

condition.  Action  must  be  implied,  it  is  true,  in 
completion  or  development,  and,  therefore,  the  evep- 
yeta  may  be  contained  in  the  evreXe-^eia,  although  this 
may  not  hold  good  reciprocally.  But  the  first  para- 
graph may  be  cited  as  an  example  of  what  apparently 
needs  elucidation — "knowledge,  is,  it  is  said,  w/ten 
active,  (latine,  in  actu,)  (tj  KOT'  evepjeiav  tTrumjpti), 
identical  with,"  &c. — "la  science  en  acte  est  iden- 
tique,"  &c. — "  scientia  autem,  ea  quae*  est  actu,  est 
idem  quod  res"  and  knowledge  or  science  here,  by 
metonymy,  may,  probably,  mean  the  faculty  by  which 
knowledge  is  acquired  or  exercised ;  but  what  means  this 
peculiar  state  which  identifies  the  knowledge  with  the 
reason?  All  function  presupposes  activity  and  inertia ; 
but  the  last  as  much  implies  identification  as  the  first, 
so  that  the  distinction  between  activity  and  complete- 
ness, although  present,  probably,  to  Aristotle,  is  not 
obvious  to  a  modern  student.  The  definition1  of  the 
term,  although  dwelt  upon  at  length,  fails,  it  may  be 
from  the  difficulty  inseparable  from  abstract  specula- 
tions, to  shew  either  what  is  strictly  implied  by  it, 
or  how  it  differs  from  the  eWeAc'^eja;  it  is  evident 
that  motion,  in  some  modified  sense,  in  the  process 
of  completion,  is  to  be  understood ;  but  beyond  this, 

1  Metaphytica,  vni.  6.  I. 

11-2 


164  PRELUDE  TO  CHAP.  VII.  [BK.  III. 

vague  as  it  may  be,  explanation  cannot  be  carried. 
Potentiality  is  related  to  it  as  to  the  evTe\i%eia,  but 
the  relation  is  too  dependent  upon  verbal  distinc- 
tions, which  cannot  be  transferred,  to  admit  of  being 
made  evident  even  to  the  student  of  the  original ; 
and  thus  it  may  be  asked,  what  is  meant  by  know- 
ledge is,  "when  active"  identical  &c.  or  the  same 
words  where  they  recur  ? 


CHAPTER  VII. 

KNOWLEDGE  is,  when  active,  identical  with  that  which 
is  known;  but  knowledge,  in  potentiality,  pre-exists  in 
the  individual,  and  yet,  strictly  speaking,  it  does  not 
pre-exist,  as  all  products  are  from  a  being  in  reality. 
Now,  it  is  the  object  of  perception,  which  appears,  by 
its  agency,  to  create  sensation  from  the  sensibility 
which  is  in  potentiality ;  for  it  suffers  neither  impres- 
sion nor  change.  So  that  this  is  a  different  kind  of 
motion ;  for  motion  was  said  to  be  the  act  of  something 
incomplete  ;  but  an  act  in  an  absolute  sense  is  different, 
as  it  is  the  act  of  something  complete.  Thus,  a  simple 
sensation  is  like  to  a  simple  affirmation  or  a  single 
idea ;  and  as  the  impression  may  be  grateful  or  pain- 
ful, it  is,  as  it  were,  affirmative  or  negative,  and  it  bids 


CH.  VII.]    ARISTOTLE  ON   THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.     165 

to  flee  from  or  pursue -after  something;  and  percep- 
tions of  pain  and  pleasure  emanate  from  the  sentient 
medium  in  its  relation  to  good  or  evil,  in  so  far  as 
things  may  be  one  or  other.  So  actual  flight  from 
something  is  identical  with  actual  appetite,  as  the 
fugitive  impulse  does  not  differ  from  the  appetitive 
stimulus,  for  they  differ  neither  from  one  another  nor 
from  the  sentient  medium ;  and  yet  they  do  differ  in 
mode  of  being.  Images  belong,  naturally,  to  the 
thinking,  as  sensations  do  to  the  sentient  principle ; 
and  as  it  may  affirm  or  deny  that  anything  is  good 
or  bad,  it  bids  to  flee  from  or  pursue  after  it.  The 
Vital  Principle,  therefore,  never  thinks  without  an 
image;  as  the  air  has  made  the  pupil  what  it  is,  the 
pupil  something  else,  and  so  with  the  hearing ;  but 
the  last  term  is  one,  as  the  mean,  to  which  belong 
several  modes  of  being,  is  one. 

It  has  already  been  said  by  what  faculty  the  mind 
discerns  that  sweet  differs  from  hot,  but  yet  it  may  be 
spoken  of  again  here.  It  is  then  an  unit  of  some  kind ; 
and  an  unit  in  the  sense  of  a  limit,  for  it  is  as  an  unit 
and  a  limit  in  the  relation,  considered  analogically  and 
numerically,  which  the  unit  bears  to  the  limit.  What 
matters  it,  besides,  whether  our  doubt  is  as  to  how 
the  faculty  judges  of  things,  generically,  the  same,  or 
opposite,  as  white  and  black  ? 

Let  A  =  white  be  in  relation  to  B  =  black,  and  let 
C  be  to  D  as  A  is  to  B,  and  so  reciprocally;  if  C,  D  be 


166  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  III. 

properties  of  some  one  body  they  will  be  as  the  pro- 
perties A,  B,  and  the  body  will  be  one  and  the  same 
with  the  other,  although  not  the  same  in  the  mode  of 
being;  and  the  same  reasoning  will  hold  good,  of 
course,  though  A  be  =  sweet  and  B  =  white.  Thus, 
the  cogitative  faculty  dwells  upon  ideas  in  images, 
and  by  images,  independently  of  sensation,  it  in  some 
way  determines  what  ought  to  be  pursued  after  or  fled 
from ;  but,  when  acted  upon  by  images,  it  is  moved 
to  think,  and,  perceiving  the  beacon  to  be  on  fire 
and  moving,  it  comprehends,  by  that  common  property 
(motion),  that  an  enemy  is  at  hand.  Sometimes,  too, 
by  images  or  thoughts  present  in  Vital  Principle,  that 
faculty,  as  if  seeing,  calculates  and  orders  things  future 
in  their  relation  to  things  present ;  and  when  it  sug- 
gests that  something  is  grateful  or  hurtful,  it  bids  to 
pursue  after  or  flee  from  it,  as  its  biddings  always  tend 
to  action.  And  with  respect  to  all  which  pertains  to 
inaction,  the  true  and  the  false  are  in  the  same  genus 
with  the  good  and  bad;  but  with  this  difference, 
that  the  former  have  an  absolute,  and  the  latter  only 
a  relative  signification.  The  mind  dwells  upon  abs- 
tractions, so  termed,  as  it  thinks  upon  a  snub  nose: 
in  so  far  as  it  is  a  nose  of  that  character  it  cannot  be 
thought  upon  abstractedly,  but  in  so  far  as  it  is  con- 
cave the  mind  can,  by  thinking  intensely  upon  the 
form,  realise  to  itself  the  nose  without  the  flesh  in 
which  the  form  is  embodied.  Thus,  too,  the  mind 


CH.  VII.]  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.  167 

thinks  upon  mathematical  questions  as  abstractions, 
although  they  are  not  really  so,  when  they  are  thought 
upon. 

In  fine,  the  mind  when  thinking,  is,  in  act,  the 
thing  thought  upon.  It  shall  hereafter  be  considered 
whether  or  not  it  can  be  admitted  that  the  mind, 
without  being  itself  apart  from  magnitude,  can  com- 
prehend abstractions. 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  VIII. 

THIS  chapter  is  a  brief  summary  of  the  principal  theories 
and  arguments  which  have  been  alluded  to,  and  it 
adds  but  little  for  comment.  The  opening  para- 
graphs are  rendered  less  definite  than  might  be 
wished  for,  by  the  recurring  particle  irto<;  and  by 
the  substitution  of  ovra  for  irpdynara,  although  the 
distinction  between  them  is  not  very  apparent.  It 
had  just  been  said  that  "knowledge,  in  act,  is 
identical  with  what  is  known,"  and  here  the  same 
is  predicated  of  Vital  Principle,  although  with  a 
qualifying  addition;  and  the  meaning,  in  either 
case,  is  dependent  upon  Aristotle's  two  sovereign 
conditions.  It  may  be  understood  how  the  intellect 
as  well  as  the  sentient  faculty  can  be  regarded  as 
identical  with  their  subjects,  in  the  way  that  a 
sentient  organ,  by  reception  of  the  form  without 
the  matter,  may  be  said  to  be  identified  with  the 
coloured  or  sonorous  object;  but  it  is  not  obvious 
how  this  can  apply  to  faculty  or  sense  in  poten- 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAP.  VIII.  169 

tiality,  unless,  indeed,  as  they  are  in  abeyance, 
•without  perception  that  is,  so  objects,  not  being 
perceived,  are  without  properties. 


CHAPTER  VIII. 

HAVING  thus  summarily  recounted  whatever  has  been 
said  upon  the  Vital  Principle,  let  us  repeat  that  it  is, 
in  some  sense,  all  things  which  are;  for  things  are  the 
subjects  either  of  sentient  perception  or  of  thought, 
and  knowledge  is,  in  some  sense,  things  known,  as 
sensation  is  things  sensually  perceived.  But  let  us 
inquire  how  this  is  to  be  understood — Knowledge, 
then,  like  sensation  is  divided,  when  in  potentiality, 
into  things  in  potentiality,  when  in  reality,  into  things 
in  reality  ;  and  the  sentient  and  the  cogitative  faculties 
of  Vital  Principle  are,  when  in  potentiality,  identical 
with  thoughts  and  objects  of  perception,  in  potentiality. 
But  the  question  here  must  necessarily  refer  either  to 
things  or  the  forms  of  things  ;  but  the  things  them- 
selves they  cannot  be,  as  it  is  not  a  stone  but  the 
form  of  a  stone  which  is  in  the  Vital  Principle.  Thus, 
the  Vital  Principle  is,  as  it  were,  a  hand,  for  as  a  hand 
is  the  instrument  of  instruments,  so  the  mind  is  the 
form  of  forms,  and  sensation  the  form  of  things  sensu- 
ally perceived.  Since  there  is,  seemingly,  nothing 


170      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.   [BK.  III. 

separate  from  perceptible  magnitude,  it  must  be  ad- 
mitted that  all  subjects  of  cogitation  are  in  per- 
ceptible forms,  as  well  those  termed  abstractions  as 
those  which  relate  to  the  conditions  and  changes  of 
the  objects  of  perception.  And,  therefore,  if  a  being 
were  without  sentient  perception,  he  could  neither 
learn  nor  understand ;  as  for  reflexion  the  individual 
must  be  able  to  call  up  an  image  of  some  sort,  and 
images  are  kinds  of  sensations,  excepting  that  they 
are  immaterial.  Imagination,  on  the  other  hand,  is 
something  different  from  affirmation  and  negation, 
for  the  true  or  the  false  is  but  a  complication  of 
thoughts.  But  by  what  are  primal  thoughts  to  be 
distinguished  from  such  as  are  derived  from  images  ? 
Other  thoughts,  however,  are  not  images,  and  yet 
without  images  they  could  not  be  produced. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  IX. 

THIS  and  the  two  following  chapters  are  upon  the  parts 
or  powers  rather,  which  give  to  animals  locomotion ; 
but,  as  the  nervous  even  the  muscular  system  had 
not  then  been  made  out,  the  text  is  encumbered, 
occasionally,  as  might  be  expected,  with  specula- 
tions which  may  now  seem  idle,  and  distinctions 
which  are  almost  futile.  Aristotle1  makes  "  animals 
to  move  and  be  moved  for  the  sake  of  something, 
which  is  the  limit  of  all  their  movements;  and  the 
moving  powers  of  an  animal  are,  perceptibly,  he 
adds,  thought  and  imagination,  election,  will  and 
desire,  which  are  all  referrible  to  mind  and  appetite, 
els  vovv  Ka\  5pe£tv.  Thus,  as  imagination  and  per- 
ception are  alike  able  to  direct  an  animal,  they  are 
in  one  and  the  same  relation  to  the  mind.  The 
argument,  in  fact,  dwells  upon  the  motive  as  well  as 
the  object  for  progression,  without  a  word  concerning 
the  agency  by  which  it  is  to  be  effected,  as  if  the 
muscular  power  of  the  body  were  unknown,  or 

1  De  Gen.  Animalm.  v.  16  ;  n.  6.  46. 


172  PRELUDE  TO   CHAP.  IX.  [BK.  III. 

regarded  only  as  the  seat  or  source  of  the  touch; 
and  yet  the  flesh  was  said  to  be  tJie  origin '  and  very 
body  of  an  animal.  The  strength2  of  all  animals  is, 
he  adds,  in  the  tendons  (ij  <<r^Js  ci/  TO??  vevpoi^),  and, 
therefore,  strength  is  greatest  when  they  are  full 
grown;  for  the  young  have  weak  joints  and  deficient 
sinews. 


CHAPTER  IX. 

SINCE  the  Vital  Principle  of  animals  lias  been 
defined  by  the  two  faculties  of  judgment  (which  is 
the  office  of  thought  with  sentient  perception),  and  of 
locomotion,  let  us  now,  having  dwelt  sufficiently 
upon  sensation  and  mind,  proceed  to  consider,  with 
respect  to  the  motor  power,  what  part  of  the  Vital 
Principle  it  may  be.  Let  us  consider,  that  is,  whether 
it  is  a  part  of  Vital  Principle  and  separate  from  it, 
substantively  or  abstractedly,  or  whether  it  is  Vital 
Principle  as  a  whole ;  and  if  it  be  a  part,  whether  it 
is  something  peculiar  and  exclusive  of  those  usually 
attributed  to  Vital  Principle,  and  which  have  been 
alluded  to,  or  whether  it  is  to  be  considered  as  one 
of  them. 

But  a  difficulty  at  once  presents  itself,  both  in 

1  De  Part.  Animalm.  ir.  8.  i.  a  De  Gen.  Animalm.  v.  7.  16. 


CH.  IX.]     ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PINCIPLE.       173 

determining  the  sense  in  which  we  are  to  speak  of 
the  parts  of  Vital  Principle,  and  in  settling  how  many 
of  them  there  may  be.  In  one  point  of  view,  in  fact, 
the  parts  appear  to  be  infinite  in  number  and  to  com- 
prise, not  only  those  which  some  speak  of  as  the 
reasoning,  passionate  and  appetitive,  and  others  as  the 
rational  and  the  irrational,  but  other  parts  also,  which 
by  the  distinctions  employed  in  those  classifications, 
are  brought  into  notice,  and  are  more  broadly  distin- 
guished from  one  another  than  are  any  of  those  to 
which  we  have  alluded.  Those  other  parts  are  the 
nutritive,  which  belongs  to  all  plants  and  animals, 
and  the  sentient,  which  cannot  readily  be  placed 
among  either  rational  or  irrational  parts ;  there  is 
the  imaginative,  besides,  which  differs  in  mode  of 
being  from  all  the  others,  and  yet  it  would  be  diffi- 
cult to  determine,  amid  the  several  parts  of  Vital 
Principle,  with  which  of  them  it  is  identical,  or  from 
which  it  differs.  Besides  these,  there  is  the  appeti- 
tive part,  which,  whether  considered  abstractedly  or 
functionally,  would  seem  to  differ  from  all  others, 
and  yet  it  would  be  absurd  to  separate  it  from  them ; 
for  volition  is  present  in  the  rational,  as  decire  and 
passion  are  in  the  irrational  part,  and  if  the  Vital 
Principle  be  made  up  of  these  three,  appetite  must  be 
present  in  each  of  them. 

But,  to  resume  the  more  especial  topic  of  this 
chapter,  what  is  that,  let  us  ask,  which  confers  upon 


174  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [fiK.  III. 

an  animal  locomotive  power  ?  Now,  it  may  be  sup- 
posed that  the  generative  and  the  nutritive  functions, 
which  are  innate  in  all  living  beings,  originate  the 
motion  concerned  in  the  processes  of  growth  and 
decay,  which  equally  belong  to  them  all ;  and  with 
respect  to  breathing  and  expiration,  sleep  and  watch- 
ing, which  are  subjects  of  much  difficulty,  we  shall 
enter  upon  the  consideration  of  them  hereafter.  Let 
us,  however,  consider  what  confers  upon  an  animal 
the  power  of  progression. 

Now,  it  clearly  is  not  the  nutritive  faculty — for 
the  movement  of  progression  is  ever  for  some  end, 
and  is  associated  either  with  imagination  or  appetite ; 
and  then  no  being  moves  unless  urged  to  it  by  desire 
or  fear,  excepting,  indeed,  there  be  impulse  from  with- 
out ;  plants,  besides,  were  nutrition  the  cause,  should 
be  locomotive,  and  possess  some  organ  to  fit  them  for 
that  kind  of  movement. 

Neither  can  it  be  the  sentient  faculty — for  there 
are  many  creatures  which  are  sentient,  and  yet  sta- 
tionary throughout  their  existence ;  and  if  nature  do 
nothing  in  vain,  and  never,  except  in  the  case  of 
beings  dwarfed  or  deformed,  omits  anything  neces- 
sary to  existence,  the  creatures  alluded  to  are  perfect 
creatures ;  and  as  proof  of  this  they  are  reproductive, 
are  capable  of  development  and  subject  to  decay,  so 
that  they  also  ought  to  have  organs  to  fit  them  for 
progression. 


CH.  IX.]  VITAL  PEINCIPLE.  175 

Neither  can  the  rational  faculty  or  the  so-called 
mind  be  the  motor  power,  for  the  speculative  intel- 
lect never  thinks  upon  what  is  to  be  done,  or  suggests 
aught  concerning  what  should  be  fled  from  or  pursued 
after ;  but  this  motion  is  the  act  of  one  fleeing  from 
or  pursuing  after  something.  Nor  does  that  faculty, 
even  when  reflecting  upon  any  such  object,  at  once 
bid  to  flee  from  or  to  follow  after  it,  as  it  often  dwells 
upon  something  terrible,  or  agreeable,  without  sug- 
gesting alarm,  although  the  heart  may  be  set  in 
motion  or  some  other  part  of  the  impression  be  agree- 
able. Add  to  this,  that  although  the  mind  may  bid, 
and  the  reason  suggest  that  something  should  be  fled 
from  or  pursued  after,  the  individual  does  not  neces- 
sarily move,  but  acts  as  does  an  intemperate  person, 
according  to  the  dictates  of  passion.  It  is  thus,  occa- 
sionally, we  see  that  a  physician,  although  versed  in 
medical  science,  does  not  cure,  as  if  there  were  some- 
thing other  than  the  science  which  had  the  power  of 
acting  according  to  the  precepts  of  the  science. 

It  may  be  affirmed  that  the  appetite  cannot  be 
the  positive  cause  of  this  motion ;  for  the  temperate, 
even  while  desiring  and  yearning  after  something,  do 
not  act  in  order  to  secure  that  for  which  they  feel 
appetite,  but  follow  their  understanding. 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  X. 

THE  subject  of  locomotion  is  continued,  and  the  motor 
principles  are  said  to  be  appetite  and  mind;  but 
mind  in  the  sense  rather  of  a  perceptive  or  sentient 
than  a  purely  intellectual  faculty;  and  yet  it  is 
neither  the  centre  of  sensibility  nor  imagination, 
although  it  partakes  of  the  nature  of  each  of  them. 
The  imagination,  which  many  are  said  to  follow 
against  judgment,  is  evidently  the  voluntary  species 
of  which  man  alone  partakes;  and  the  other,  which 
is  allotted  to  the  lower  animals,  may  be  regarded  as 
instinct.  The  mind,  as  a  practical  faculty,  is  to  be 
distinguished  from  the  theoretical  or  speculative 
intellect,  which  has  for  its  object  the  discovery  of 
truth,  as  the  other  has  the  preservation  of  the  body. 
The  argument  is  complicated,  and  made  less  appre- 
hensible by  the  technicality  and  great  precision 
of  its  wording :  thus,  TO  opf^rov,  or  object  desired, 
is  food,  and  appetite  is  the  stimulus  or  feeling 
of  hunger  which  compels  to  move;  the  practical 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAP.  X.  177 

mind  (Sidvota  irpaKTiKrj)  is  the  sentient  faculty,  and 
the  beginning  of  the  action,  which  is  the  satisfaction 
of  the  appetite,  completes  or  is  the  last  of  the 
series.  Thus,  these  two,  the  appetite  and  practical 
thought  (which  is  sentient  perception)  are  motors,  as 
being  both  stimulus  and  desire,  and  the  object 
desired  (food,  that  is),  acting  upon  the  sentient 
perception,  urges  to  locomotion  for  the  attainment 
of  it;  the  imagination,  as  an  instinctive  power,  is 
said  never  to  impel  to  move,  save  for  the  satisfaction 
of  necessary  wants. 


CHAPTER  X. 

THOSE  two  faculties,  the  appetite  and  the  mind,  appear 
to  be  the  motor  principles  in  animals — the  mind,  if 
the  imagination  might  be  set  down  as  being  a  kind 
of  thought ;  for  many  against  knowledge  follow  their 
imaginings,  and  other  animals  are  moved  neither  by 
thought  nor  calculation,  but  by  imagination.  Thus, 
those  two  faculties,  mind  and  appetite,  are  locomotive 
powers  ;  but,  then,  it  is  mind  in  the  sense  of  a  calcu- 
lating and  a  practical  faculty,  and  which  differs  from 
the  speculative  mind  by  the  object  to  which  it  tends. 

12 


178  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  III. 

Now,  every  appetite  tends  to  some  object,  for  the 
appetite,  which  is  the  beginning  of  the  practical  mind, 
has  ever  some  object  in  view,  and  that  object  is  the 
beginning  of  the  action.  So  that  these  two,  appetite 
and  practical  thought,  may  reasonably  be  regarded  as 
motor  powers — for  the  object  longed  for  impels  to 
move,  and  then,  through  it,  the  practical  intelligence 
impels,  because  its  origin  is  the  object  longed  for ; 
and  when  imagination  may  incite  to  move,  it  never 
does  set  in  motion  without  appetite.  Thus,  it  is  the 
object  longed  for  alone  which  produces  motion ;  for  if 
there  were  two  motives,  mind  and  appetite,  they 
would  produce  motion  according  to  some  common 
formula.  But  as  the  case  is,  the  mind  does  not 
appear  to  produce  motion  without  appetite,  for  voli- 
tion is  appetite ;  and  even  when  a  creature  may  move 
by  calculation,  it  still  moves  by  volition ;  the  appe- 
tite, on  the  contrary,  impels  to  move  against  calcula- 
tion, for  desire  is  a  kind  of  appetite. 

The  mind  then  is  always  right;  but  appetite  as 
well  as  imagination  may  be  right  and  may  be  wrong. 
It  is,  therefore,  the  object  desired  which  always  ex- 
cites to  move,  but  then  that  object  is  a  good  or  an 
apparent  good ;  not  however,  a  good  in  every  sense, 
but  a  practical  good,  and  a  practical  good  admits  of 
being  otherwise  than  good. 

It  is  manifest  then,  that  it  is  that  faculty  of  Vital 
Principle,  the  so-called  appetite  which  excites  to 


CH.  X.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  179 

move.  But  when  Vital  Principle  is  divided  into 
parts,  and  parts  are  distinguished  by  their  faculties, 
very  many  are  made  apparent,  as  the  nutritive,  the 
sentient,  the  cogitative,  the  deliberative,  and  the  ap- 
petitive, and  these  differ  from  one  another  more  than 
do  the  desiring  and  the  passionate. 

The  appetites  admit  of  being  opposed  to  one 
another,  and  this  occurs  when  reason  may  be  opposed 
to  desire,  but  the  opposition  can  be  manifested  only 
in  beings  with  a  sense  of  time;  for  the  mind  com- 
mands to  resist  on  account  of  the  future,  while  desire 
urges  to  immediate  compliance,  as  that  which  is  good 
appears,  as  the  future  is  unseen,  to  be  absolutely  good 
and  absolutely  grateful.  Thus,  the  appetitive  faculty, 
in  so  far  as  appetitive,  may,  in  a  specific  sense,  be  the 
motor,  but  it  is  the  object  desired  by  appetite  which 
is  the  first  to  set  in  motion ;  for  without  having  been 
itself  moved,  it  incites  to  move  from  having  been 
thought  upon  or  imagined;  and  there  are  several 
such  motors.  There  are  three  terms  here :  the  motor; 
then  that  by  which  it  moves ;  and  thirdly,  that  which 
is  moved.  But  the  motor  is  in  the  two-fold  sense  of 
unmoved,  and  both  motor,  and  moved — the  unmoved  is 
the  practical  good ;  the  motor  and  moved  is  the  appe- 
titive stimulus  or  appetition  (for  that  which  is  moved 
moves  only  in  so  far  as  it  desires,  and  appetite  is  a 
motion  or  an  act  of  some  kind) ;  and  the  moved  is 
the  animal.  As  the  organism  by  which  appetite 

12—2 


180     ARISTOTLE   ON   THE   VITAL   PRINCIPLE.    [BK.  III. 

effects  motion  is  obviously  corporeal,  its  nature  must 
be  studied  together  with  those  functions  which  are 
common  to  the  body  and  the  Vital  Principle.  But  to 
speak  summarily,  the  organism  whereby  motion  is 
effected,  is  as  a  hinge  in  which  coexist  the  beginning 
and  the  end  of  motion — for  herein  are  the  convex  and 
the  concave,  of  which  that  is  the  beginning,  and  this 
the  end  of  motion;  and  therefore  the  one  is  at  rest 
while  the  other  is  in  motion,  as  although,  rationally 
considered,  the  two  pieces  are  distinct,  yet,  substan- 
tively,  they  are  inseperable. 

In  fine,  then,  as  has  been  said,  an  animal  is  en- 
dowed with  self-motion  to  the  extent  of  its  appetition ; 
but  it  cannot  be  susceptible  of  appetite  without  ima- 
gination, and  all  imagination  is  either  rational  or 
sentient,  and  of  this  latter  kind  other  animals  partake 
also. 


PRELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  XL 


IT  is  by  no  means  obvious  what  may  have  been  meant  by 
"  imperfect  creatures,"  or  in  what  sense  desire, 
unless  it  be  as  instinct,  can  be  assigned  to  them; 
for  there  is  no  trace  throughout  the  zoology  of 
Aristotle,  extensive  as  it  is,  of  any  such  species  of 
being.  One  commentator  has  suggested  polypi  and 
mollusca;  but  the  former,  in  their  present  accepta- 
tion, (improperly  termed  zoophytes),  had  not  then 
been  observed,  and  the  latter1  could  not,  from  the 
description,  have  been  regarded  as  "  imperfect 
animals."  The  "polypus"  was  the  generic  term  for 
the  highest  forms  of  the  Cephalopoda,  or  "  cuttle 
fish." 

1  De  Part.  Animalm,  iv.  7.  4. 


CHAPTER  XI. 


LET  us  now  consider  the  motor  power  in  such  im- 
perfect creatures  as  have  only  the  sense  of  Touch ; 
and  learn  whether  or  not  it  is  admissible  that  imagi- 
nation and  desire  can  be  present  with  them.  Now, 
they  do  appear  to  be  sensible  of  pain  and  pleasure, 
and  if  so  far  sensible,  they  must  of  necessity  have 
desire.  But  how  can  imagination  be  present  in 
them  ?  It  may,  perhaps,  be  answered  that,  as  their 
movements  are  indeterminate,  so  those  sensations  are 
present,  but  present  in  some  indeterminate  manner. 

The  sentient  imagination  belongs,  as  has  been 
said,  to  other  animals,  but  that  which  is  voluntary 
is  found  only  in  such  as  are  rational ;  for  it  is  matter 
of  calculation  whether  this  or  that  shall  be  done,  and 
as  the  individual  is  to  pursue  what  is  larger  and 
better,  he  must  be  guided  by  a  rule  of  some  kind, 
and  thereby  be  enabled  to  individualize  several  diffe- 
rent images.  The  reason  why  these  creatures  do  not 
seem  to  be  capable  of  forming  opinions  is,  that  they 
are  without  the  faculty  for  drawing  inferences,  and 
this  includes  opinion.  But  the  appetite  has  no  deli- 


CH.  XI.]   ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.      183 

berative  will,  as  appetite  sometimes  overcomes  and 
impels  tlie  will,  and  sometimes  the  will  overcomes 
and  impels  the  appetite,  as  a  ball  is  bandied  to  and 
fro ;  or  appetite  rules  and  impels  appetite,  when  in- 
temperance has  the  ascendancy.  But  that  which  is 
superior  is  ever  naturally  more  dominant,  and  pro- 
ductive of  motion  in  three  different  directions ;  but 
the  intelligent  faculty  has  no  motion — it  remains 
at  rest.  Although  the  conception  of  the  universal 
is  to  be  distinguished  from  the  conception  of  the 
particular,  (for  while  the  former  says  that  such  an 
one  ought  to  perform  such  an  act,  the  latter  says 
that  such  an  one,  and  that  /  am  he,  ought  now  to 
perform  this  particular  act,)  yet  it  is  this  latter 
opinion  rather  than  the  former  which  impels  to 
move ;  and  although  both  may  be  motive,  the  one,  at 
least,  is  rather  at  rest,  and  the  other  is  rather  in 
motion. 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAPTER  XII. 

As  the  treatise  is  drawing  to  a  close,  this  chapter  again 
alludes  to  the  distinction  between  the  life  in  plants 
and  animals  from  the  presence  or  absence  of  sensi- 
bility— thus,  animals  are  distinguished  from  plants 
by  being  sentient,  as  plants  are  from  inanimate 
bodies  by  nutrition  and  growth.  Aristotle1  placed 
plants  immediately  after  inanimate  substances,  and 
says  that  they  are  distinguished,  generically,  by 
degrees  of  vitality;  that  compared  with  other 
bodies  they  appear  to  be  almost  alive  (<r^e8ov  iXa-nfp 
ev\^v^ov) ;  compared  with  animals,  to  be  inanimate ; 
and  that  the  transition  from  the  one  to  the  other 
is  in  an  unbroken  series.  Thus,  there  are  "  marine 
creatures,"  he  says,  "which  cannot  with  certainty  be 
ranged  among  either  animals  or  plants ;  and  sponge 
has  altogether  the  appearance  of  a  plant."  La- 
marck8 has  substantively  adopted  this,  as  he,  too, 

1  Hist.  Animedm,  vni.  i.  6. 
3  Introduction,  77.  96. 


PRELUDE   TO   CHAP.  XII.  185 

commences  with  inanimate  things  (which,  what- 
ever their  character,  he  distinguishes  broadly  from 
whatever  has  life)  and  then  passes  to  plants,  which 
he  distinguishes  from  animal  bodies,  by  being  non- 
irritable — incapable,  that  is,  of  contracting  any  of 
their  solids,  suddenly  and  repeatedly,  while  animal 
bodies  are,  on  the  contrary,  endowed  with  contrac- 
tile power.  Cuvier1  observes,  that  "living  and 
organised  beings  have,  from  the  earliest  times,  been 
subdivided  into  animated  beings — beings,  that  is, 
which  are  sentient  and  moveable,  and  beings  which 
are  inanimate ;  and  as  these  are  neither  sentient  nor 
moveable,  they  are  reduced  to  the  common  faculty 
of  vegetation  or  nutrition."  It  is  not  necessary, 
then,  as  Aristotle  remarks,  that  all  living  beings 
should  be  sentient. 

1  R&gne  Animal,  C.  I.  18. 


CHAPTER  XII. 


IT  is  necessary  to  every  living  creature  that  it  should 
have  a  nutritive  principle  in  order  that  it  may  live 
and  continue  to  live,  from  birth  to  death ;  for  it  is 
necessary  to  every  thing  generated  that  it  should  be 
capable  of  growth,  development  and  decay,  and  as  these 
cannot  be  carried  on  without  nourishment,  it  is  neces- 
sary to  all  reproductive  and  perishing  beings  that 
they  should  have  a  congenital  nutritive  function.  But 
it  is  not  necessary  to  all  living  beings  that  they  should 
be  sentient,  nor  can  it  be  admitted  that  such  as  have 
simple  or  homogeneous  bodies  can  have  Touch,  or 
that  there  can  be  an  animal  without  Touch ;  neither 
can  any  beings  be  sentient  but  such  as  are  receptive 
of  form  without  the  matter.  It  is  necessary  to  an 
animal,  however,  that  it  should  be  sentient,  if  nature 
do  nothing  in  vain — for  all  things  in  nature  are  for 
some  end,  or  else  they  are  accidents  of  things  for 
some  end ;  so  that  if  there  were  any  animal  body  fitted 
for  progression  without  being  sentient,  it  would  perish, 
and  could  not  attain  to  the  end  which  is  nature's 
design.  How,  in  fact,  is  such  a  body  to  be  nourished? 


CH.  XII.]   ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.    187 

As  to  creatures  which  are  fixed,  they  obtain  their 
nourishment  on  the  spot  where  they  have  been  pro- 
duced. It  is  not  possible  then,  that  a  body  which  is 
not  fixed  to  one  spot  and  which  has  been  generated, 
should  have  living  principle  and  judging  faculties 
without  being  sentient.  Nor  can  a  creature  sponta- 
neously generated  be  sentient ;  Why,  let  us  ask, 
should  it  be  so  ?  The  sensibility  is  for  the  greater 
good  either  of  the  Vital  Principle  or  the  body ;  but 
neither  of  these  can,  in  the  case  supposed,  be  effected 
by  it,  as  the  one  will  not  through  it  think  the  better, 
nor  the  other  be  better  fitted  for  its  offices.  Thus, 
there  is  no  living  body  free  to  move  which  is  not 
sentient.  But  if  a  body  be  sentient,  it  must  necessarily 
be  either  homogeneous  or  compound — Now,  homoge- 
neous it  cannot  be,  as  in  that  case  it  would  be  with- 
out Touch,  and  Touch  it  must  of  necessity  have.  All 
which  is  proved  thus — Since  an  animal  is  a  living 
body,  and  all  bodies  are  tangible,  and  tangible  im- 
plies whatever  is  perceptible  to  Touch,  it  follows  that 
the  body  of  an  animal  must  be  sensible  to  Touch,  if 
the  animal  is  to  preserve  its  existence.  The  other 
senses,  as  the  sight,  smell,  hearing,  perceive  through 
other  media;  but  if  an  animal  when  touching  were 
without  sensation,  it  could  have  no  guide  for  avoiding 
some  things  or  seizing  others,  and  so  circumstanced, 
it  would  not  be  possible  for  it  to  preserve  its  existence. 
The  taste,  therefore,  is  a  kind  of  Touch,  for  taste  is  the 


188  ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  [BK.  III. 

sense  for  food  and  food  is  a  tangible  body;  but  sound, 
colour  and  odour  neither  nourish  nor  contribute  to 
growth  or  decay.  Thus,  taste  must  of  necessity  be  a 
kind  of  Touch  from  its  being  the  sense  which  is  per- 
ceptive both  of  what  is  tangible  and  nutritive ;  and, 
as  these  two  senses  are  necessary  tD  animals,  it  is 
manifest  that  there  can  be  no  animal  without  Touch. 

The  other  senses,  being  for  the  higher  good  of 
animals,  are  allotted,  not  to  all  but,  only  to  particular 
genera,  as  they  are  necessary  to  none  but  such  as 
have  the  power  of  progression.  If,  indeed,  such  a 
creature  is  to  preserve  its  existence,  it  must  not  only 
be  sensible  of  objects  when  touching  them,  but  be  able 
also  to  perceive  them  when  at  a  distance;  and  this 
can  be  effected  if  it  be  sensible  through  a  medium, 
which,  having  been  impressed  and  set  in  motion  by 
the  objects  of  perception  reacts  upon  the  percipient. 
And  it  is  thus  that  the  locomotive  impulse  acts  until 
it  cease  in  rest — that  which  impels  something  else 
communicates  along  with  impulsion  impelling  power, 
and  the  motion  is  in  a  midspace ;  and  as  the  first 
motor  impels  without  having  been  impelled,  so  the 
last  is  impelled  without  impelling,  and  the  inter- 
mediate links,  of  which  there  are  several,  both  impel 
and  are  impelled.  So  is  it  too  with  respect  to  changes 
wrought  in  bodies,  excepting  that  they  are  effected 
without  change  of  locality — as  if  any  one  were  to 
tinge  a  portion  of  wax,  it  would  be  in  motion  until 


CH.  XII.]  VITAL   PRINCIPLE.  189 

it  should  be  saturated;  nothing  like  this,  however, 
can  happen  to  a  stone,  but  it  can  to  water,  and  that 
to  a  distance.  The  air  is  mobile  in  the  highest 
degree,  and,  provided  it  be  still  and  in  one  mass,  it 
both  acts  and  is  acted  upon.  It  is  better,  therefore, 
in  the  case  of  refraction,  to  assume  that  the  air,  in  so 
far  as  it  is  one  mass,  (and  it  is  so  over  every  smooth 
surface,)  is  impressed  by  form  and  colour,  rather  than 
that  visual  rays  issuing  from  the  eye  are  refracted. 
Thus,  the  air,  in  the  case  of  vision,  gives  motion 
to  the  sense,  as  if  the  impress  upon  wax  had  been 
transmitted  to  its  extremity. 


PKELUDE  TO   CHAPTER  XIII. 


THERE  were  four  admitted  elements,  fire  and  air,  earth 
and  water,  from  which  all  things  were  supposed 
to  be  formed;  and  the  object  here  is  to  shew  that 
an  animal  cannot  be  homogeneous,  connot  be  formed, 
that  is,  of  only  one  element.  Now,  earth  was 
supposed  to  give  solidity,  fire  to  be  diffused  through 
all  living  bodies,  and  thus  there  remained  only  air 
and  water  from  which  to  constitute  sentient  organs ; 
the  earth  was  assigned,  however,  more  particularly 
to  the  Touch,  but,  as  Touch  is  perceptive  of  other 
qualities  (as  hot  and  cold)  besides  those  of  mere 
Touch,  it  could  not  be  constituted  of  that  element 
alone.  The  organs  of  relation,  sight  and  hearing, 
were  formed,  principally,  of  water  and  air,  which 
are  the  media  for  the  transmission  of  visual  and 
sonorous  impressions;  and  the  smell  partook  more  of 
fire,  as  the  Touch  did  of  earth,  yet  not  exclusively. 
The  theory  is  superseded  by  the  increase  of  our 
knowledge  of  external  nature,  but,  in  assuming 


PRELUDE  TO  CHAP.  XIII.  191 

elements,  combination  and  proportion,  it  seems  to 
typify,  as  it  were,  an  atomic  theory.  Hippocrates1, 
also,  taught  that  the  human  body  cannot  be  exclu- 
sively, either  of  air  or  fire,  water  or  earth,  or  any 
single  element;  although,  he  adds,  "I  do  not  quarrel 
with  such  as  think  otherwise."  Plato2,  likewise, 
"  derived  all  things,  so  to  say,  from  these  four 
elements,  in  due  proportion  and  relation  to  one 
another ;  so  that  what  fire  is  to  air,  that  air  is  to 
water,  and  water  to  earth,  and  each  is,  by  affinity, 
united  with  others,  to  form  whatever  is  visible  and 
tangible." 

1  De  Natura  Hominis. 

2  Timceus,  y.,  B. 


CHAPTER  XIII. 


IT  is  manifest  that  an  animal  body  cannot  be  simple, 
cannot,  I  mean,  be  only  fire  or  air;  for  an  animal 
cannot  have  any  other  sense  without  having  Touch, 
and  every  living  body  is  sensible  to  Touch,  as  has 
been  said.  But  all  the  elements,  except  earth,  may 
constitute  sentient  organs,  as  these  all  receive  impres- 
sions through  something  foreign  to  themselves  and 
through  media ;  but  the  Touch  is  made  sensible  by 
touching  bodies,  and  hence  its  name.  And  yet  the 
other  sentient  organs  do  perceive  by  Touch,  but  then 
it  is  through  something  foreign  to  themselves  ;  while 
Touch  alone  seems  to  perceive  directly,  through  itself. 
So  that  an  animal  body  cannot  be  constituted  of  any 
one  of  the  other  elements  exclusively,  nor  can  it  be 
formed  only  of  earth;  for  the  Touch  is  the  medium,  as 
it  were,  for  tangible  impressions,  and  the  organ  is 
perceptive  not  only  of  the  distinctions  which  pertain 
to  earth,  but  of  hot,  cold,  and  all  other  tangible 
qualities.  Hence  it  is  that  we  have  no  feeling  in 
bones,  hair,  or  other  analogous  parts  because  they  are 
of  earth;  and  plants  for  the  same  reason,  being  of 


CH.  XIII.]     ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.     193 

earth  have  no  feeling.  It  is  impossible  then  that 
there  should  be  any  other  sense  without  that  of 
Touch ;  and  its  organ  is  neither  of  earth  nor  any  other 
element  exclusively.  Thus,  it  is  manifest  that  the 
Touch  is  the  only  sense  of  which  animals  cannot  be 
deprived  without  dying ;  that  animals  only  can  pos- 
sess it ;  and  that  it  alone  of  the  senses  is  necessary  to 
animal  existence.  On  which  account,  other  sentient 
impressions  in  excess  (as  those  of  colour,  sound  and 
odour)  may  injure  the  organs  but  do  not  destroy 
the  animal,  excepting  it  be  by  chance,  as  when  with 
sound  there  is  an  impulse  and  a  blow,  or  as  when,  by 
visual  or  odorous  impressions,  other  influences  are  set 
in  motion,  which  destroy  the  animal  through  the 
Touch ;  and  when  savour  destroys  life  it  does  so  by 
communicating  simultaneously  a  tangible  impression. 
But  the  excess  of  tangible  impression,  whether  hot, 
cold  or  hard,  destroys  the  animal,  because  as  every 
impression  in  excess  destroys  the  sentient  organ,  so 
the  tangible  destroys  that  of  Touch,  and  it  is  by  the 
Touch  that  animal  life  has  been  denned ;  and  it  has 
been  shewn  that  an  animal  cannot  possibly  exist 
without  the  Touch.  Thus,  the  excess  of  tangible 
impressions  destroys  not  the  organ  only  but  the 
animal,  as  that  sense  alone  is  necessary  to  its  exist- 
ence. Animals,  in  fact,  possess,  as  has  been  said,  the 
other  senses,  not  merely  for  existence  but,  for  higher 
enjoyment:  they  have  sight,  in  order  that,  as  they  live 

13 


194      ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  VITAL  PRINCIPLE.      [BK.  III. 

in  air  and  water,  in  a  transparent  medium  in  short, 
they  may  see ;  taste,  that  by  discerning  what  is  grate- 
ful or  nauseous  in  food  they  may  have  desire  for  and 
move  to  obtain  it ;  hearing,  that  others  may  signify 
something  to  them,  and  a  tongue  that  they  may 
signify  something  to  others. 


NOTES. 


13—2 


NOTES. 


BOOK    THE    FIKST. 

CHAPTER  I. 

Note  1,  p.  1 1.  Truth  in  relation  to  nature,  &c.]  Aristotle1 
says  that  some  beings  exist  by  nature,  and  some  by  other 
causes ;  those  by  nature  include  animals  and  their  parts, 
plants  and  elementary  bodies,  as  fire  and  air,  earth  and 
water,  for  all  such,  evidently,  exist,  and  exist  by  nature. 
The  objects,  in  fact,  of  nature's  constitution  are  broadly 
distinguished  from  whatever  does  not  emanate  from  her — 
"for  all  her  productions  appear  to  have  within  them  a 
principle  of  motion,  and  of  rest ;  some  for  locomotion, 
and  some  for  the  motions  of  growth,  decay,  and  change. 
But  neither  a  bed,  a  garment,  nor  any  other  similar  ob- 
ject, whether  formed  of  stone,  earth,  or  composition,  has 
any  such  innate  tendency  to  change ;  and  thus  nature  is 
to  be  regarded  as  the  source  and  first  cause  of  motion  and 
rest  in  something  which  has,  not  casually  but,  innately,  in 
itself,  from  its  origin,  the  capability  of  being  so  acted 
upon."  The  term  nature2,  besides,  is  applied  to  any  sub- 
stance which,  however  rude  and  unchangeable,  admits,  by 
its  own  properties,  of  being  converted  into  something,  as 
1  Nat.  AuscuU.  n.  i.  3  Metaphys.  iv.  4.  3.  5. 


198  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

bronze  is  said  to  be  the  nature  of  a  statue  or  of  bronze 
utensils,  wood  of  wooden,  articles,  and  so  of  other  materials 
and  products.  There  were  some  who  spoke  of  the  essence 
of  natural  bodies  as  nature,  and  as  they  made  the  primal 
combination  of  particles,  that  is  affinity,  to  be  essence, 
Empedocles  maintained  that  "the  nature  spoken  of  by 
men  is  only  the  combination  of  and  change  among  par- 
ticles." So  that  Aristotle  confined  the  term  nature  to 
existing  beings  and  the  processes  by  which  they  are  sup- 
ported and  perpetuated,  to  living  and  organised  matter 
that  is,  while  others  widened  its  acceptation,  and  made  it 
applicable  to  the  changes  continually  going  on  through 
and  by  elementary  substances.  With  him,  in  fact,  it  was 
a  living  principle ;  with  others,  a  property  or  force, 
whereby  change  is  a  law. 

"The  term  nature,"  says  Cuvier1,  "in  our  own  and  most 
other  tongues,  signifies,  sometimes  the  properties  which  a 
being  derives  from  its  birth  (hereditarily)  in  contradis- 
tinction to  those  which  it  may  derive  from  adventitious 
circumstances  ;  sometimes  the  whole  of  the  beings  which 
compose  the  universe,  and  sometimes,  again,  the  laws  to 
which  those  beings  are  subjected.  It  is  in  this  last  sense 
that  we  are  accustomed  to  personify  nature,  and  out  of 
respect  to  employ  its  name  for  that  of  its  author." 

Note  2,  p.  11.  Its  essence  as  well  as  its  accidents] 
Aristotle*  observes  that  essence  seems,  most  manifestly, 

1  R^yne  Animal,  Introduction. 
1  Metaphys.  VI.  2.  i. 


CH.  I.]  NOTES.  199 

to  be  an  innate  property  in  bodies ;  and,  therefore,  animals 
and  plants,  and  parts  of  animals  and  plants,  as  well  as 
natural  bodies,  as  fire  and  water,  air  and  earth,  the  ele- 
ments, in  fact,  are  essences ;  to  which  may  be  added  the 
bodies  which  are  derived  from  the  elements,  as  the 
heavens,  stars,  sun,  and  moon.  Some,  however,  regarded 
the  boundaries  of  bodies,  as  surface,  line,  point,  and  unit, 
as  essences,  rather  than  bodies  or  solids  themselves.  Thus, 
essence,  according  to  the  first  definition,  seems  to  be 
scarcely  distinguishable  from  nature.  Aristotle1,  how- 
ever, in  another  passage,  considers  it  under  four  heads :  as 
mode  of  being,  as  universal,  genus,  and  subject ;  and  sub- 
ject he  held  to  be  essence  in  a  fuller  sense  than  the 
others.  Plato  admitted  of  essence  in  forms,  mathematical 
abstractions,  as  also  in  sentient  bodies  ;  and  the  Pythago- 
reans first,  and  Plato  later,  adopted  unity  as  essence. 
Aristotle,  in  fact,  seems  to  confine  his  definitions  of  these 
abstract  powers  or  entities  to  the  outer  world ;  and  others 
to  comprehend,  under  the  term,  the  abstractions  of  pure 
science,  and  the  immediate  operations  of  general  laws. 

The  term  "  accident"  was  with  Aristotle2,  as  it  is  with 
us,  significant  of  chance  or  possibility,  as  well  as  what  is 
necessary  and  constant.  The  former  is  exemplified  by  an 
individual,  when  digging,  finding  a  treasure,  as  this  is  an 
occurrence  neither  necessary  nor  constant ;  and  thus  there 
can  be  no  assignable  cause,  save  chance,  which  itself  is 
undefinable,  he  adds,  for  an  incident  so  purely  casual. 
1  Metaphys.  VI.  3.  i  ;  ix.  2.  *  Ibid.  IV.  30. 


200  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

But  it  also  implies  properties  which,  although  not  essen- 
tial, are,  still,  inherent,  inalienable  from,  and  distinctive 
of  particular  bodies,  as  it  is  a  property  of  the  triangle  to 
contain  two  right  angles ;  these  properties  only  are  re- 
garded as  accidents  in  modern  science,  and  such  are 
implied  in  the  passage  alluded  to. 

Note  3,  p.  12.  Concerning  tlie  thing  itself,  &c.]  This 
stands  first  in  the  enumeration  of  the  categories1,  which 
comprize  the  ten  following — thing  itself;  (ri  eV-ri)  ;  quan- 
tity ;  quality  ;  relation  ;  when  ;  where  ;  position  ;  reci- 
piency ;  action  ;  and  impression.  They  are  so  designated, 
Aristotle  says,  because  there  must  ever  be,  in  some  one 
of  them,  accident  and  genus,  individual,  and  definition ; 
for  it  is  through  them  that  premisses  signify  either  indi- 
vidual, or  quantity,  or  quality,  or  other  one  of  those 
enumerated.  It  is  made  evident,  thus — when  it  is  said 
of  a  man  lying  down  that  it  is  a  man  or  an  animal,  the 
party  both  says  what  it  is,  and  points'  out  its  essence; 
when  it  is  something  white  which  is  lying  down,  then 
the  party  designates  its  quality,  as  well.  But  these  two 
exemplifications  seem  to  shew  that  the  terms  essence,  ac- 
cidents, category,  like  the  abstractions  of  which  they  are 
the  representatives,  cannot  be  clearly  distinguished  from 
one  another ;  so  that  they  may  almost  be  regarded  as 
derivatives  from  one  comprehensive  idea.  Essence  is,  in 
the  first  of  those  instances,  almost  confounded  with  the 
categories,  although  it  is  the  object8  of  a  special  inquiry; 
1  Topica,  I.  9.  i.  *  Catey.  5.  i. 


CH.  I.]  NOTES.  201 

and  this  seeming  incongruity  may  have  led  some  scholars 
to  set  it  down  among  them. 

Note  4,  p.  12.  Some  kind  of  demonstration  or  division, 
&c.]  Demonstration  is,  according  to  Aristotle1,  a  sci- 
entific syllogism,  and  by  scientific  is  meant,  he  says,  the 
method,  through  which  we  learn,  with  certainty,  what  a 
subject  may  be ;  and,  11  the  knowledge  be  such,  it  follows 
that  demonstrative  knowledge  must  be  derived  from  con- 
ditions which  are  original,  immediate,  and  more  appre- 
hensible and  causative,  than  the  conclusion  sought  for. 
Those  conditions  are,  in  fact,  the  suitable  principles  for 
ascertaining  that  which  is  to  be  demonstrated ;  as,  without 
them,  the  result  will  be,  not  demonstration  but,  a  syllogism, 
which  cannot,  with  certainty,  eliminate  truth.  Thus, 
while  demonstration*  is  a  kind  of  syllogism,  every  syllo- 
gism is  not  demonstration.  Division  is  said  by  Aristotle8 
to  be  an  imperfect  syllogism,  for  it  assumes  what  ought  to 
be  demonstrated,  and  draws  conclusions  from  a  priori 
reasonings.  In  this  allusion  to  division,  Aristotle  may 
be  supposed  to  have  had  Plato  in  view,  "  as  it  was  by 
a  process  of  dividing  and  subdividing  that  that  emi- 
nent man  conducted  his  inquiries  after  truth ;"  as,  how- 
ever, this  method  was  considered  by  him  to  be  a  faulty  or 
imperfect  syllogism,  it  may  be  that  he  alluded  to  it  as 
one  which  might  be  adopted,  without  altogether  approving 
of  it  as  a  mental  process. 

1  Analytic,  b.  I.  i.  2.  B  Ibid.  a.  I.  4.  i. 

3  Ibid.  a.  i.  31. 


202  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

Note  5,  p.  12.  As  those  of  number  are  not  those  of 
plane  surfaces,  &c.]  That  is,  the  science  of  number  dif- 
fers, generically,  from  that  of  Geometry.  The  nature,  so 
to  say,  of  numbers  had  been  a  subject  of  deep  and  curious 
speculation  long  before  and  during  the  age  of  Aristotle, 
and  there  lie  scattered  through  his  works  notices  of 
writers  and  systems  which,  although  in  themselves  inter- 
esting to  scholars,  would,  even  were  it  possible  to  give  a 
clear  summary  of  them,  be  foreign  to  the  present  inquiry. 
Aristotle1,  before  entering  upon  number,  denned  "quan- 
tity" as  being,  partly  definite,  and  partly  continuous — 
and  the  former. he  constituted  of  parts  which  have  no 
mutual  local  relation  to  each  other;  the  latter  of  parts 
which  have  that  relation.  The  "definite"  quantity  is 
represented  "  by  number  and  by  a  word  ;  the  continuous 
by  line,  surface,  solid,  and  time  and  place,  besides."  In 
order  to  shew  that  number  is  definite  or  discontinuous,  he 
observes,  "  there  is  no  common  boundary  whereon  the 
parts  of  any  number  conjoin ;  as  if,  for  instance,  five  or 
three  be  parts  of  ten,  there  is  no  common  boundary 
whereon  five  or  seven  can  conjoin  to  make  the  whole 
number,  but  each  part  is,  for  ever,  a  distinct  number, 
and  thus  number  is  among  definite  quantities."  "  Words 
are,  in  like  manner,  among  definite  quantities ;  and  it  is 
manifest  that  words,  uttered  by  the  voice,  are  quantity, 
in  that  they  are  measurable  by  long  and  short  syllables, 
and  manifest  too  that  there  is  no  common  boundary 
1  Categ.  6.  i. 


CH.  I.]  NOTES.  203 

whereon  the  parts  of  a  word,  that  is  syllables,  conjoin  to 
make  the  whole  sound,  and  thus  that  each  is  for  ever  a 
distinct  sound.  But  a  line,  on  the  contrary,  is  continuous, 
as  there  is  no  common  boundary  whereon  its  parts,  that  is 
points,  conjoin,  as  lines,  to  make  a  superficies,  whereon 
all  parts  of  the  solid  conjoin ;  so  too  time  is  con- 
tinuous, for  that  which  is  present  is  conjoined  with  that 
which  is  past,  as  it  is  with  that  which  is  future."  Aris- 
totle1, having  shewn  that  there  are  these  opposite  con- 
ditions of  quantity,  in  a  positive  as  in  an  abstract  sense, 
defines  an  unit  (tj  /xoVac)  as  being,  in  direct  opposition  to  a 
point,  without  position  or  place  ;  a  line  as  being  divisible 
only  in  one  way;  a  superficies  as  divisible  in  two,  and  a 
solid,  quantitatively  considered,  as  divisible  in  three,  and, 
indeed,  in  all  ways.  Number  is  still  regarded,  of  course, 
as  a  collection  of  units ;  the  superficies  as  that  which  has 
only  length  and  breadth  ;  and  the  solid  as  that  which  has 
length,  breadth,  and  depth. 

Note  6,  p.  12.  Among  entities  in  potentiality  or  whether, 
&c.]  These  terms  run,  like  a  golden  thread,  through  all 
the  physiological  works  of  Aristotle,  and  were  adopted  by 
him  in  order  to  distinguish  virtual  from  actual  condition 
or  existence,  the  capability,  that  is,  of  becoming,  by  in- 
nate force  or  power,  an  entelechy  or  reality,  which  is  the 
purport  of  the  last  term.  They  may  be  briefly  exempli- 
fied thus: — an  egg,  e.g.  is  alive  in  potentiality — it  has 
within  it,  that  is,  a  principle,  whereby,  under  genial 
1  Metaphys.  IV.  5.  24. 


204  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

circumstances,  it  can  develope  into  a  living  being ;  and 
so  a  seed,  while  alive,  is  capable  of  becoming  a  perfect 
living  plant,  as  the  egg  or  the  caterpillar  or  the  chrysalis 
is,  in  potentiality,  the  future  perfect  insect  or  butterfly. 
The  terms  comprehend,  in  fact,  all  the  metamorphic  con- 
ditions of  the  animal  and  vegetable  kingdoms,  and  have 
a  range  of  application  wide  enough  to  include  life  under 
all  degrees  and  forms.  This  was  the  first  great  idea  in 
their  adoption,  and  although  Aristotle  made  them  to  sig- 
nify an  analogous  transition  in  moral  or  mental  faculties, 
(as  when  he  speaks  of  a  boy  as  a  general,  in  potentiality,) 
yet  their  real  purport  is  to  distinguish  those  two  universal 
conditions  of  living  and  sentient  beings.  Cicero1  has  al- 
luded to  these  terms  or  rather  to  the  entelechy,  (as  was 
noted  in  the  preface,)  but,  from  not  having  contrasted  it 
with  the  potentiality,  he  seems  to  have  mistaken  its  gene- 
ral import ;  and  he  may  thus  have  been  led  to  suppose 
that  Aristotle's  intention,  in  this  novel  term,  was  to  desig- 
nate a  special  fifth  nature,  to  be  the  source  of  motion  and 
the  originating  cause  of  mental  faculties  and  natural 
emotions.  Montaigne*,  also,  in  modern  times,  following 
Cicero,  speaks  of  the  entelechy  only,  which  he  regards, 
erroneously,  as  the  motor  power  of  the  body — "ce  qui 
naturellement  fait  mouvoir  le  corps."  A  hot  dispute 
prevailed  among  scholars,  it  may  be  added,  before  and 
during  the  age  of  Rabelais8,  (and  which  he  has  alluded  to 

1  Tusc.  Disp.  I.  10.  a  Essai,  Lib.  n.  ch.  xii. 

3  La,  Vie  de  Gargantua,  Lib.  v.  ch.  xix. 


CH.  I.]  NOTES.  205 

with  all  his  wonted  wit  and  learning,)  whether  the  term 
should  be  eWeAe'^eia  or  eVSeAe'^eia  ',  he  was,  evidently 
himself,  one  of  the  entelechists,  as  he  says  that  the  Lady 
Quint-essence,  who  had  had  Aristotle,  "that  paragon  of 
all  philosophy,"  for  god-father,  had  been  truly  and  cor- 
rectly named  Entelechy  by  him. 

Note  7,  p.  13.  Wliether  t/te  difference  is  generic  or 
specific.]  "  The  term  Genus 1  implies  a  continuous  series 
of  individuals  having  a  like  species  or  form,  so  that  genus 
may  be  predicated  of  man,  so  long  as  there  may  be  a 
continuous  generation  of  human  beings ;  the  term  again 
may  be  applied  to  the  source  whence  individuals  may 
have  descended,  and  thus  some  Greeks  are  of  the  Hellenic, 
others  of  the  Ionic  genus,  on  account  of  their  direct  de- 
scent from  Hellenus  or  from  Ion.  And  this  applies  so 
much  more  to  the  progenitor  than  to  external  conditions, 
that  the  descendants  from  a  female  constitute  a  genus. 
Species8  implies  the  mode  of  being  of  the  individual,  to- 
gether with  the  primal  essence ;  and  as  the  matter  con- 
stitutive of  the  genus  is  in  the  species,  so  species  may  be 
regarded  as  parts  of  the  genus.  In  modern  classification, 
genus  signifies  "  a  distinct  but  subordinate  group,  which 
gives  its  name  as  a  prefix  to  that  of  all  the  species  of 
which  it  is  composed."  The  physical  sciences  have  been 
so  widely  developed,  however,  that,  as  those  terms  no 
longer  suffice  for  grouping  the  myriads  of  beings  which 
have  been  observed  since  Aristotle's  time,  naturalists 
1  Metaphys.  iv.  25.  28,  *  Ibid.  vi.  75. 


206  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

have,  in  addition,  adopted  kingdom  or  class,  order,  sub- 
genus,  individual,  and  variety. 

Note  8,  p.  13.  T/ie  term  animal,  however,  in  an  uni- 
versal sense,  &c.]  This  passage,  which,  in  the  original,  is 
even  more  elliptical  than  its  version,  has  engaged  much  of 
the  attention  of  commentators  without  having  been  satis- 
factorily elucidated — some  have  explained  it  as  a  criticism 
of  the  ideas  or  archetypes  of  Plato ;  and  others  as  an 
objection  to  every  universal  term,  which,  although  an 
abstraction,  is  to  typify  actual  beings;  and  this  is,  pro- 
bably, the  purport  of  the  criticism.  Thus1,  "the  origin 
of  the  controversy,  during  the  middle  ages,  between  the 
nominalists  and  realists,  may  be  traced  down  to  Aristotle 
and  his  followers."  Wording  so  elliptical  must,  of  course, 
be  subject,  according  to  the  bias  of  opinions,  to  different 
interpretations ;  but  if  it  imply  objection  to  every  abstract 
term  which  is  to  embody,  so  to  say,  realities,  this  version 
may  be  accepted  as  its  interpretation.  The  Latin  version*, 
however,  is,  "Animal  autem  universale  aut  nihil  est  aut 
posterius  est,  et  quicquid  itidem  aliud  communiter  prasdi- 
catur;"  and  the  French3,  "C'est  que  1'animal  pris  en  un 
sens  universel  ou  n'est  rien,  ou  bien  n'est  que  quelque 
chose  de  tres  ulterieur." 

Note  9,  p.  13.  The  mind  before  thought,  <fcc.]  Aris- 
totle* says  that  among  the  philosophers  who  were  engaged 

1  Trendel.  Comment.  *  Ed.  Acad.  Borriaica. 

3  J.  P.  Saint  Hilaire. 

4  Metaphys.  I.  3.  16 ;  xin.  3.  5  ;  xi.  7.  7. 


CH.  I.]  NOTES.  207 

upon  first  causes,  Anaxagoras  and  his  predecessor  Her- 
moticus  had  maintained  that,  as  in  animals  there  is  a 
motor  principle,  so  in  nature  there  is  mind,  and  that  it  is 
the  cause  as  well  of  the  universe  as  of  universal  order ; 
and  thus  "  they  assumed  at  once  that  mind  is  the  cause  of 
the  beautiful,  the  origin  of  being,  and  the  source  whence 
motion  is  derived  for  every  thing  living."  Anaxagoras, 
in  fact,  regarded  mind  as  the  first  cause  of  things  (which 
Ernpedocles  was  rather  disposed  to  assign  to  the  principle 
of  attraction,  which  he  designated  0iA«a,  and  held  to  be  an 
universal  element),  and  maintained  that,  while  all  else  is 
but  a  combination  of  particles,  it  is  homogeneous,  impas- 
sive, isolated,  and  pure.  We  are  incapable,  Aristotle 
observes,  in  his  comment  upon  these  opinions,  of  continu- 
ous thought  and  reflexion,  because  these  are  recreations  too 
lofty  to  be  continuously  maintained ;  but,  on  this  account, 
watching  (not  being  asleep,  that  is),  feeling  and  thinking 
are  our  most  genial  conditions,  because  from  and  through 
them,  we  derive  our  hopes  and  recollections.  Notwith- 
standing, however,  this  acknowledgement,  so  to  say,  of 
mind,  as  a  sovereign  principle,  and  its  attributes,  there  is 
no  attempt  to  define  its  nature  and  its  relations,  or  to 
shew  in  what  it  was  identified  with  or  different  from  the 
vital  principle ;  and  this  want  of  critical  distinction  be- 
tween them  is  the  more  apparent  as  several  epithets 
(trpoyevea-TaTo^ — 0eu)prjTino<: — irpanTtKos— 7ra0»/TiKo?)  are 
introduced  in  the  course  of  these  physiological  treatises, 
which  cannot  but  have  modified  the  parent  term. 


208  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

Note  10,  p.  15.  Whetfier  all  tJie  emotions  of  Vital  Prin- 
ciple, &c.]  These  passages  shew  clearly  the  suggestive  power 
and  perspicacity  of  Aristotle's  intellect,  and  they  point  so 
clearly  to  doctrines  which  had  yet  to  be  developed,  that  they 
cannot  be  studied  without  feelings  of  surprise  as  well  as 
admiration.  The  brain1  was,  in  that  age,  supposed  to  be 
merely  a  supplementary  organ  to  respiration ;  and,  from 
its  not  giving  out  sensation  when  touched,  and  from  im- 
perfect anatomy,  it  was  supposed  to  have  no  relation 
whatever  with  the  sentient  organs  or  spinal  cord.  The 
nerves,  as  cords  of  sensation,  were  unknown ;  the  very 
term  (yevpov),  which  has  been  transferred  to  them  as  nerve, 
meant  then  tendon  or  sinew.  Hence  it  is  that,  in  modern 
languages,  a  man  is  said  to  be  nervous  in  the  one  sense, 
and  a  delicate  female  to  be  nervous  in  the  other.  It  was 
thus,  from  intuition  and  study,  that  Aristotle  drew  this 
train  of  suggestive  reasoning  upon  the  influences  exercised 
over  our  passions  and  emotions  by  the  organs  of  the  body ; 
that  he  discerned,  that  is,  the  seat  and  source  of  the  tem- 
peraments. Bichat*,  having  a  far  wider  range  of  anato- 
mical knowledge,  was  able,  by  assigning  to  the  brain  and 
ganglionic  system  their  proper  offices,  to  distinguish  in- 
tellectual faculties  from  passions  and  emotions,  which 
although  human,  still  are  temperamental  and  functional — 
to  distinguish,  that  is,  the  animal  from  the  organic  life. 

Note  11,  p.  15.   In  tlie  same,  way  all  the  emotions,  &c.] 
These  passages  are  quite  in  accordance  with  all  that  phy- 
1  De  Part.  Animcdm,  n.  7.  4.  2  Recherches  physiologiqnes. 


CH.  i.]  NOTES.  209 

siology  now  teaches ;  for  although  but  repetition,  it  may 
be  said  that  Aristotle  places  the  passions  and  emotions  in 
the  organic  life,  and  shews  "  that  every  individual  must  be 
influenced  by  his  particular  temperament."  Thus,  as  organs 
predominate,  or  may  be  more  or  less  active,  individuals 
are  affected  and  modified,  so  to  say,  in  temper  as  in  cha- 
racter. The  temperaments  ought  to  be  subordinated,  of 
course,  to  the  higher  faculties ;  but  those  organs  are  abiding 
powers,  and  they  are  ever  exercising  an  influence  which 
it  is  for  reason  to  control  or  subdue.  Plato,  in  the  Timceus, 
has  discerned  this  great  truth — a  'mortal  principle  (ore  TO 
6injTov  eVeo-rcAAe  yevoi)  is  there  assigned  to  the  body,  as 
the  seat  of  the  passions  and  coarser  appetites,  while  the 
brain  is  represented  as  a  soil  fit  for  the  divine  seed  of 
wisdom  ;  and  this  will  suffice  to  shew  that  this  most  gifted 
man,  although  but  imperfectly  acquainted  with  physiology, 
had  perceived  the  co-existence  in  the  human  being  of  an 
intellectual  and,  so  to  say,  a  functional  existence.  Des- 
cartes1 seems  to  have  adopted  opinions  concerning  the 
"  passions  of  the  soul,"  which  have  much  in  common  with 
those  of  Aristotle  ;  but  although  so  well  acquainted  with 
his  writings,  he  does  not  appear  to  have  studied  this 
treatise. 

Note  12,  p.  16.    But  the  physiologist  and  t/te  metaphy- 
sician would,  &c.]     The  difference  here  dwelt  ^  upon  in 
the  mode  of  accounting  for  the  same  phenomena,  accord- 
ing to  the  bias  given  by  studies  or  pursuits,  will,  it  may 
1  Les  Passions  de  Fame. 

14 


210  NOTES.  [Ex.  i. 

be  assumed,  be  of  constant  recurrence ;  foi",  as  physical 
science  advances,  it  will  become  more  and  more  difficult 
for  the  same  party  to  attain  to  a  large  and  solid  acquaint- 
ance with  the  attributes  of  mind  (abstractions,  that  is), 
and  the  knowledge  of  "  external  nature."  The  self-same 
differences,  in  fact,  which  were  delineated  so  graphically 
by  Aristotle,  are  still  to  be  traced  in  our  almost  exclusive 
attention  to  the  physical  sciences,  and  our  disinclination 
to  admit,  in  our  inquiries,  of  any  proof  but  such  as  can  be 
tested  through  and  by  the  senses  and  observation.  The 
terms  here  rendered  physiologist  and  metaphysician  (terms 
unknown,  by  the  way,  to  Aristotle)  in  the  Latin  version 
are  naturalis,  and  disserendi  artifex ;  that  of  artisan  is 
faber ;  builder,  artifex ;  and  transcendental  philosopher  is 
primus  philosophus. 


CHAPTER  II. 

Note  1,  p.  19.  Hence  Democritus,  &c.]  None  of  the 
works  of  this  eminent  man  have  come  down  to  us ;  but 
notices  of  his  opinions  lie  scattered  through  the  writings 
of  Aristotle,  and  these  may  suffice  for  the  elucidation  of 
this  and  other  allusions  to  him.  Following  his  master 
Leucippus,  Democritus1,  abandoning  metaphysical  subtle- 
ties, looked  into  the  constitution  of  the  external  world  for 
1  Metaphys.  I.  4.  9. 


CH.  ii.]  NOTES.  211 

the  knowledge  of  natural  causes ;  and  he  was  thus  led  to 
adopt  the  hypothesis  of  indivisible  and  moving  corpuscles, 
in  order  to  account  for  the  universal  law  of  motion. 
"  Several  other  philosophers l  had,  before  their  time,  con- 
sidered matter  as  divisible  into  indefinitely  small  particles, 
but  as  they  were  the  first  who  taught  that  these  particles 
were  originally  destitute  of  all  qualities  except  figure  and 
motion,  they  may  well  be  regarded  as  the  founders  of  the 
atomic  system  of  philosophy."  Democritus8  maintained 
that  nothing  can  ever  be  produced  from  nothing,  and  that 
"  indivisible  atoms  (elementary  corpuscles,  that  is)  consti- 
tute the  essence  of  bodies."  He  adopted,  as  elements,  the 
plenum  and  vacuum,  making  the  former,  in  contradistinc- 
tion to  the  latter,  to  be  entity,  and  the  two  to  be,  as 
matter,  the  causes  of  things ;  he  maintained  too,  that  they 
are  equally  distributed  through  all  bodies.  He  agreed 
with  Anaxagoras  in  believing  that  throughout  all  nature 
there  is  a  principle  of  combination ;  and  with  his  master 
Leucippus,  in  regarding  form  arrangement  and  position  of 
particles,  as  causes  of  elementary  distinctions  among  bodies. 
But  in  some  of  this  reasoning  he  was  mistaken,  Aristotle 
observes,  from  not  distinguishing  the  condition  of  poten- 
tiality from  reality,  since  the  same  object  may  simultane- 
ously, when  in  potentiality,  be  and  not  be,  although  this 
cannot  hold  good  of  the  same  when  in  reality.  Democritus 
also  thought  that,  owing  to  the  difference  of  sensation 


1  Enfield's  Hist,  of  PhOos.  Vol.  I.  4«. 
3  Mctaphys.Vl.  13.  9  ;  m.  5.  5  ;  I.  4.  9. 


14—2 


212  NOTES.  [Ex.  i. 

produced  by  the  same  object  upon  the  same  individual, 
truth  either  has  no  existence,  or  else  it  can  hardly  ever  be 
attained  to  by  mortal  beings.  To  return,  however,  to  the 
doctrine  of  atoms,  Leucippus  and  Democritus  maintained 
that,  as  bodies  are  distinguished  by  forms,  and  forms  are 
infinite,  elementary  bodies  must  be  infinite  also ;  but  then, 
with  the  exception  of  fire,  which  was  said  to  be  spherical, 
they  forgot  to  specify  what  the  forms  are  ;  and  they  denned 
elementary  bodies  by  greatness  and  smallness  as  well  as 
form.  Thus,  form  motion  and  size  are,  according  to 
them,  the  constituents  of  these  formative  atoms,  and, 
accordingly,  the  larger  atoms  which  are  said  to  go  to  the 
formation  of  bodies,  are  distinguished  from  the  smaller 
ones  or  motes  (held  to  be  visible  only  in  the  sun-beams), 
which,  as  being  endowed  with  vital  properties,  are  alluded 
to,  in  a  succeeding  passage,  as  supporting,  through  respi- 
ration, the  life  of  the  animal.  In  fine,  this  doctrine  of 
atoms  varying  in  form  and  size,  constantly  moving,  and, 
through  attraction  and  repulsion,  combining  with  and 
separating  from  one  another,  prevailed  in  all  the  schools 
of  antiquity;  and  there  may  perhaps  be  traced  in  it  a 
faint  outline  of  the  present  matured  theory  of  atomic 
proportion. 

Note  2,  p.  19.  Hence,  too,  they  make  breathing, 
&c.]  This  description  conveys,  under  a  rude  exterior,  so 
to  say,  a  description  of  the  process  of  breathing  or  respi- 
ration, as  well  as  the  purposes  which  it  has  to  fulfil  in  the 
animal  economy — "  the  contraction  of  the  chest  (expiration) 


CH.  ii.]  NOTES.  213 

expels  particles  rendered  effete,  and  these  are  supplied  by 
others  from  without,  during  inspiration ;  and  this  alter- 
nation continues  so  long  as  life  endures."  It  emanates 
from  an  early  stage  of  physiology,  no  doubt,  but  yet  it 
does  clearly  intimate  that  without  such  an  alternation  life 
could  not  be  maintained — that  a  renewing  power  from 
without,  and  an  expulsion  of  something  prejudicial  from 
within,  are  necessary  to  animal  existence.  Democritus 
(of  Abdera),  Anaxagoras  and  Diogenes  are  cited  by  Aris- 
totle1 as  believing  respiration  to  be  necessary  for  all  crea- 
tures (in  opposition  to  himself,  who  limited  the  process  to 
air-breathing  animals),  and  he  has  given  their  account  of 
the  process  in  fishes  and  oysters  (molluscs).  "  Anaxagoras 
says  that  fishes,  during  respiration,  discharge  the  water 
through  the  branchise,  and  that  then,  as  there  may  not  be 
a  vacuum,  they  draw  in  air  which  is  in  the  mouth ;  and 
Diogenes  maintains  that,  when  fishes  discharge  the  water 
through  the  branchise,  they  draw  in,  by  means  of  the  void 
created  in  the  mouth,  the  air  which  is  ever  present  in 
water  and  encircling  the  mouth."  Democritus  advanced 
a  step  nearer  to  modern  teaching,  in  accounting  for  fishes 
dying  when  out  of  the  water  by  their  then  taking  in  too 
much  air ;  as,  when  in  the  water,  they  can  take  in  only 
a  moderate  quantity."  But  all  this  was  objected  to,  abso- 
lutely, by  Aristotle,  both  because  of  his  own  more  restricted 
views  of  respiration,  and  of  the  apparent  discrepance  of 
the  theories  with  common  sense,  and  thus  was  he  led,  in 
1  De  Eespirat.  i.  i. 


214  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

this  instance,  to  oppose  theories  pregnant  with  suggestion, 
and  advantageous  to  the  progress  of  science. 

Jfoie  3,  p.  20.  To  the  same  point  do  they  aho  come,  <fcc.] 
The  writers  here  alluded  to  are  said  by  Philoponus  to  be 
Plato,  Xenophanes  and  Alcmaeon.  Aristotle1  observes 
that,  as  nature  is  the  origin  of  motion  and  change,  it  is 
necessary,  in  order  to  comprehend  motion,  to  understand 
what  nature  is.  Motion  seems  to  be  the  property  only  of 
continuity,  and  the  infinite  is  displayed,  first  of  all,  in 
what  is  continuous ;  and,  therefore,  in  definitions  of  con- 
tinuity, there  is  frequent  reference  to  the  infinite,  as  if  all 
continuity  were  infinitely  divisibla  Besides  these  reasons, 
without  place  void  and  time,  there  cannot  be  motion. 
But  whatever  is  in  motion,  must  have  been  moved  by  its 
own  or  by  some  other  power,  and  this  motor  may  be  the 
second  or  third  of  a  series,  as  the  staff,  for  instance,  which 
moves  the  stone  is  moved  itself  by  the  hand,  which  is 
moved  by  the  man ;  and  although  the  last  of  these  may 
be  spoken  of  as  the  motor,  yet  the  term  is  applicable  rather 
to  the  man,  as  being  the  first  link  in  the  chain.  Thus, 
the  man  who  communicates  motion  by  bis  will  is,  himself 
at  rest ;  and,  therefore,  it  by  no  means  follows,  Aristotle 
contends,  that  the  motor  should  itself  be  in  motion. 

Note  4,  p.  21.    Homer  has  icell  represented,  <kc.]     The 

term  a\Xo<ppoveu>v,  rendered  "  changing  his  mind,"  occurs 

but  once  in  the  Iliad,  and  there  it  refers,  not  to  Hector, 

but  to  Euryalus  vanquished  in  the  funeral  games;  and 

1  Nat.  Auscutt.  m.  i.  vm.  5. 


CH.  ii.]  NOTES.  215 

signifies  stupefaction  of  the  faculties  rather  than  what  is 
here  attributed  to  it.  Thus,  either  Democritus  must 
hare  misquoted,  or  the  Iliad,  since  Aristotle's  time,  have 
suffered,  as  is  commonly  believed,  more  than  one  mutila- 
tion. The  purport  of  the  passage,  however,  is  sufficiently 
obvious. 

Note  5,  p.  21.  Thus  Democritus  does  not  employ  tfa 
term  mind,  &c.]  He  made  mind,  that  is,  to  be  a  sentient 
principle  and  identified  with  those  filings  and  emotions, 
which  Aristotle  held,  as  has  been  shewn,  to  be  but 
emanations  from  the  corporeal  organs  and  functions, 
to  be  manifestations,  that  is,  of  the  temperament.  An 
apology  has  been  offered  for  this  attribution  of  mind 
to  all  creatures,  in  that  such  a  principle  may  seem  to  be 
represented  by  the  consummate  order  which  prevails 
in  their  constitution  j  and  thus  that  Anaxagoras  mav 
have  meant  that,  while  it  may  be  present,  objectively, 
in  all  beings,  it  can  be  present,  subjectively,  (as  mind, 
that  is)  only,  in  a  few.  Plato1  seems  to  imply  something 
like  this  when  adopting  one  essence  or  faculty  which  is 
eternal  and  unbegotten,  and  another  which  has  no 
abiding  and  is  perishable — the  one  capable,  by  intellect 
with  cogitation,  of  comprehending  unchangeable  natures  : 
and  the  latter  capable,  by  opinion  with  sensual  percep- 
tions, of  comprehending  whatever  is  casual  and  ephemeral. 

Note  6,  p.  21.  Have  said  that  the  Vital  Principle 
comprises  alljirst  causes,  <fca]  Aristotle*  observes  that,  a<? 
1  Timceus,  27.  D.  8  Nat.  Avscult.  n.  3. 


216  NOTES.  [Bx.  i. 

every  investigation  is  for  the  purpose  of  knowing  some- 
thing, and  as  we  cannot  be  said  to  know  before  we  can 
comprehend  wherefore  a  thing  is  what  it  is,  (comprehend, 
that  is,  its  first  cause,)  so  it  is  evident  that  we  must  thus 
study  the  laws  of  reproduction  destruction  and  change, 
throughout  nature,  in  order  to  be  enabled  to  refer,  for 
each  subject  of  investigation,  to  the  first  causes  of  the 
phsenomena.  This  argument  seems  to  confine  causation 
to  natural  operations  in  particular,  that  is,  living  bodies  ; 
but  cause  had  then,  as  it  has  now,  a  far  wider  significa- 
tion— besides  essence,  individual  being,  elements,  and 
other  admitted  first  causes,  that  of  which  anything  is 
made,  was  said  to  be  its  cause,  as  bronze  of  a  statue, 
silver  of  a  goblet,  and,  in  a  general  sense  the  maker  is 
the  cause  of  the  production,  and  he  who  alters,  of  the 
change,  &c.  Thus,  there  was  great  latitude  in  the 
enumeration  of  first  causes.  Thales1,  the  founder  of 
this  branch  of  philosophy,  maintains  that  water  is  a 
first  cause,  because  the  earth  rose  from  water.  Anaxi- 
meues  and  Democritus  contend  that,  as  air  was  before 
water,  so  it  is  rather  to  be  regarded  as  the  first  cause  of 
everything. 

Hippasus  and  Heraclitus  set  it  down  as  being  fire ; 
and  Empedocles,  adding  earth,  adopted  four  elementary 
causes ;  for  he  maintained,  that  these  elements  are  un- 
changeable and  unproduceable,  although  capable  of  com- 
bining with  and  separating  from  one  another.  He  first 
1  Metaphysica,  i.  3.  5.  8. 


CH.  ii.]  NOTES.  217 

adopted  the  four  elements,  in  fact,  as  the  first  causes  of 
all  things,  although,  as  he  makes  fire  to  be  the  antagonism 
of  the  other  three,  which  he  held  to  be  of  one  nature,  he 
can  hardly  be  said  to  have  regarded  them  as  more  than 
two.  This  doctrine  of  elements  prevailed,  in  fact,  down 
to  the  time  of  Descartes1,  who  admitted,  however,  only 
of  three,  fire,  air,  and  earth ;  and  he  maintained  that  all 
the  forms  of  inanimate  bodies  may  be  accounted  for  by 
the  motion  form  size  and  arrangement  of  particles, 
without  the  aid  of  any  agent,  such  as  heat  or  cold, 
moisture  or  dryness.  Thus  all  elementary  particles  are, 
according  to  him,  first  causes. 

Note  7,  p.  21.  By  earth  we  perceive,  &c.]  The 
doctrine  of  elements  prevailed  even  to  the  constitution  of 
the  sentient  organs,  for,  as  sensibility  could  have  no  part 
in  the  theory  of  that  age,  philosophers  had  adopted  the 
dogma,  that  like  recognises  and  perceives  by  like,  that  air, 
that  is,  perceives  by  air,  water  by  water,  and  so  for  the 
other  elements ;  and  thus  the  organ  of  vision  was  supposed 
to  be  of  water,  that  of  hearing  to  be  of  air,  and  that  of 
smell  to  be  of  fire.  As  illustration  of  which,  Aristotle2 
describes  "  odour  as  being  a  vaporous  exhalation,  and, 
as  such,  necessarily  derived  from  fire  (heat) ;  and  the 
special  organ  of  smell  is  said,  on  this  account,  to  be 
located  about  the  brain,  for  the  matter  of  cold  (the  brain) 
is,  in  potentiality,  hot"  and,  therefore,  able  to  perceive 

1  Du  nombre  des  Elements. 

2  De  Sensu  et  Sen.  n.  1 1 .  20. 


218  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

what  is  derived  from  heat.  The  visual  organ  is  said  to 
be  of  water,  and  to  see  objects,  not  as  being  water  but,  as 
being  diaplianous,  as  this  quality  belongs  to  air  as  well  as 
water,  but  then  water  is  more  protective  and  condensed 
than  air,  and,  therefore,  the  pupil  and  the  eye  are  con- 
stituted of  water.  These  are  rude  theories,  no  doubt, 
and  sorry  substitutes  for  the  knowledge  of  the  brain  and 
its  system ;  but  philosophy  cannot  rest  upon  a  confession 
of  ignorance,  and  this  hypothesis,  unsatisfactory  as  it 
may  now  seem,  was  for  ages  the  admitted  theory  of 
sentient  perception.  But  this  theory  of  Empedocles, 
however  otherwise  faulty,  may  well  be  supposed,  without 
violence  to  the  text,  to  convey  in  the  terms  a-Topytj  and 
i/e?^o»,  a  knowledge,  or  perception  rather,  of  attraction 
and  repulsion;  and  an  assumption  of  these  principles 
may  be  traced  in  most  of  the  systems  of  that  time  con- 
cerning elementary  combinations.  This  must  be  main- 
tained with  some  reserve,  however,  as  some  have  given  a 
more  literal  version  of  the  terms  in  amor  and  discordia, 
or  lis,  which,  as  moral  or  sentient  qualities,  seem  to  be 
without  any  relation  to  elementary  combinations.  The 
latin  version  of  the  phrase  is,  Terrain  nam  terra,  lympha 
cognoscimus  undam,  setheraque  sethere;  sane  ignis 
dignoscitur  igne ;  sic  et  amore  amor,  ac  tristi  discordia 
lite ;  and  the  French  is,  "  Par  la  terre  nous  voyons  la 
terre ;  1'eau  par  1'eau ;  par  1'air,  1'air  divin  ;  par  le  feu,  le 
feu  qui  consume;  par  I 'amour,  T  amour;  et  la  discorde 
par  la  discorde  funeste." 


CH.  ii.]  NOTES.  219 

Note  8,  p.  22.  In  the  treatises  "  upon  philosophy,"  &c.] 
These  books  are  said  to  have  been  expositions  of  the 
teaching  of  Plato  and  the  Pythagoreans  upon  ideas  and 
the  nature  of  the  sovereign  good,  or  philosophy,  and  to 
have  been  gathered  by  Aristotle  from  the  oral  teaching  of 
his  great  preceptor.  It  is  generally  believed  that  they  have 
not  come  down  to  us ;  but  a  more  modern  commentator 
seems  to  have  been  persuaded  that  they  are  still  pre- 
served in  the  Metaphysics,  (that  store-house,  where  lie 
scattered  the  fragments  of  every  system  of  philosophy 
that  ever  had  any  authority, )  and  yet  there  is  no  passage  * 
in  that  work,  in  which  Aristotle  alludes  directly  to  the 
topics  here  cited  by  him.  If  a  digest  of  Plato's*  doctrine 
of  the  elements  may  be  offered,  he  makes  fire  and  earth 
to  have  been  the  first  of  created  elements,  because  what- 
ever is  produced  must  be  visible  and  tangible  and  corpo- 
real, and  nothing  can  be  visible  without  fire,  or  tangible 
without  solidity,  whence  the  body  of  the  universe  was,  in 
the  beginning,  constituted  out  of  fire  and  earth;  but 
since  it  is  scarcely  possible  for  two  elements  so  to  coalesce 
as  to  form  bodies  without  the  intervention  of  other 
combining  elements,  the  Creator  placed  water  and  air 
between  fire  and  earth,  and  made  them  to  be  in  the  same 
relation  to  the  first  elements  which  they  are  to  each 
other — and  thus  fire  is  to  air  as  ai/r  is  to  water,  and  air 
is  to  water  as  water  is  to  earth.  The  Pythagoreans*  were 

1  Vide  Trendelen.  Comment.  *  Timasus.  31.  B.  ct  seq, 

3  Metaphysica,  I.  5.  6 


220  NOTES.  [Bx.  i. 

the  first  who  devoted  themselves  to  mathematics,  and,  by 
exclusive  attention  to  that  study,  they  were  led,  at  first, 
to  consider  their  principles  as  the  principles  of  entities ; 
but  as  numbers  must  be  before  mathematics,  they  were 
brought  to  perceive  many  resemblances  to  beings  and 
conditions  in  numbers,  rather  than  in  fire  or  earth,  water 
or  air.  Thus,  they  assumed  that  a  particular  combination 
of  numbers  is  justice,  that  another  is  Vital  Principle  and 
mind,  another  proportion  or  fitness ;  and  further,  perceiving 
the  proportions  and  impressions  of  harmonic  sounds  to  be 
numbers,  and  other  things  appearing  to  bear  a  resem- 
blance to  numbers,  and  numbers  to  be  the  first  of  created 
entities,  they  assumed  that  the  elements  of  numbers  must 
be  the  elements  of  entities ;  and  that  the  heavens  and 
every  kind  of  harmony  must  be  numbers.  But  some? 
while  they  held  that  numbers  are  elements,  believed  odd 
and  even  to  be  the  origin  of  numbers,  and,  therefore, 
elements  in  a  stricter  sense ;  and,  as  the  unit  is  derived 
from  odd  and  even,  they  regarded  it  as  the  origin  of  all 
numbers.  Enough,  however,  has  been  said  for  rendering 
apprehensible  to  the  general  reader,  the  import  of  the  terms 
and  the  tenour  of  the  argument ;  and  it  would  be  idle,  even 
were  the  doctrine  fully  known,  to  attempt  any  such  dis- 
quisition as  would  be  required  for  a  full  elucidation  of  this 
the  most  abstruse,  perhaps,  of  all  the  topics  of  antiquity. 

Note  9,  p.  22.    There  are  writers  who  have  combined, 
&c.]   Simplicius1  and  Philoponus  attribute  this  opinion  to 
1  Vide  Trendel.  Comment. 


CH.  ii.]  NOTES.  221 

Xenocrates,  whom  they  praise  as  the  ablest  expositor  of 
the  doctrine  of  ideal  numbers.  He  maintained  that 
Vital  Principle  has  in  it  an  abiding  source  of  ideas 
congenial  with  a  mobile,  ever-changing  nature,  such  as 
pertains  to  the  external  world,  and  that  hence  it  is  a 
number  which,  while  unable  to  free  itself  from  the  nature 
of  things,  approximates  to  ideas ;  and  in  order  to  prevent 
faculties  so  ungenial  from  being  severed,  he  derived  from 
Vital  Principle  the  faculty  and  origin  of  motion,  by 
which,  as  by  a  link,  they  are  to  be  retained  together. 
Thus,  he  thought  to  reconcile  the  apparent  discrepance  of 
the  co-existence  of  ideas  and  things  in  the  same  being. 
Plato1  has  well  criticised,  in  one  of  his  writings,  the 
varying  theories  of  philosophers  upon  the  number,  nature 
and  relations  of  elementary  principles. 

Note  10,  p.  23.  Anaxagoras  seems,  as  we  have,  &c.j 
The  writing  of  Anaxagoras,  the  Clazomenian,  here 
alluded  to,  appeared,  according  to  Aristotle2,  after  those 
of  Empedocles,  although,  in  age  he  was  his  senior ;  and 
Anaxagoras  maintained,  he  says,  that  first  causes  are 
infinite  in  number.  Thus,  that  almost  all  homogeneous 
bodies,  such  as  water  or  air,  can  be  produced  or  destroyed 
only  by  combination  and  separation ;  and  that,  admitting 
of  no  other  origin  or  destruction  than  these,  they  must 
endure  for  ever.  From  all  which  it  might  be  inferred, 
that  he  admitted  of  but  one  cause,  and  that  in  the  form 
of  matter.  He  made  mind,  to  which  he  attributed 
1  Sophista.  8  Afetaphys.  i.  3.  9.  B.  xm.  4.  5. 


222  NOTES.  [Ex.  i. 

intelligence,  to  be  a  first  cause,  (as  Empedocles  made 
affinity  to  be  an  element,)  to  be  innate  in  and  the  source 
of  motion  in  animals,  as  well  as  the  cause,  in  nature,  of 
the  universe  and  its  order. 

Note  11,  p.  24.  Tholes,  too,  from  what,  &c.]  In  this 
allusion  to  the  influence  of  the  magnet,  Thales  may  have 
been  criticising  the  opinions  which  made  motion  de- 
pendent upon  life.  He  was  the  founder  of  the  school 
which  derived  all  things  from  one  or  more  material  and 
indestructible  elements;  he  believed  water  to  be  the 
sole  element,  (whence  he  demonstrated  that  the  earth  is 
from  water),  and  was  probably  led,  Aristotle  observes,  to 
this  conception,  from  perceiving  that  the  nutrition  of  all 
creatures  is  fluid ;  that  heat  is  produced  from  water,  and 
that  by  heat  animals  live ;  and,  then,  that  all  seminal 
particles  are  naturally  fluid. 

Note  12,  p.  24.  Diogenes,  togetJier  with  some  oilier 
writers,  &c.]  It  is  probable  that  this  opinion  was 
suggested  to  Diogenes  by  the  respiration,  which  he  knew 
to  be  essential  to  animal  existence  and  dependent  upon 
the  air ;  although  the  process  itself,  and  the  changes 
effected  by  it,  were  of  course  then  unknown.  Air,  how- 
ever, was  believed  to  be  necessary  for  the  maintenance  of 
life,  and  so  it  might  well  be  regarded  as  the  originating 
cause  of  all  things ;  and  more  especially  by  one  who  saw 
so  far,  as  was  shewn  in  a  former  note,  into  its  mode  of 
agency.  It  is  shewn  by  Aristotle1  that  he  had  well 
1  De  Part.  ni.  2.  6. 


CH.  ii.]  NOTES.  223 

studied  the  vascular  system ;  and  he  seems  to  have 
perceived  that  the  brain  is  the  seat  of  sensation.  In  fine, 
philosophers,  generally,  in  adopting  four  causes,  have 
been  divided  between  fire,  water,  and,  as  with  Diogenes, 
air;  which  he  held  to  be  the  origin  of  all  secondary 
operations. 

Note  13,  p.  25.  Others,  as  Critias.]  The  opinion  that 
blood  differs  from  the  other  fluids  and  has  an  independent 
vitality,  has  prevailed,  no  doubt,  in  all  ages  ;  but  Aristotle 1 
placed  it,  as  well  as  its  analogue,  the  ichor,  which  circu- 
lates in  molluscs,  insects,  <fec.,  among  insentient  and  excre- 
mentitious  parts,  such  as  bone,  nails,  cartilage,  and  other 
like  parts.  It  may  be  added,  too,  that  the  brain  was  so 
considered.  "To  conceive,"  Hunter *  observes,  "that the 
blood  when  circulating  is  endowed  with  life,  is  perhaps 
carrying  the  imagination  as  far  as  it  can  go,  but  the 
difficulty  arises  from  its  being  fluid,  as  the  mind  is 
not  accustomed  to  the  idea  of  a  living  fluid.  But  when 
all  the  circumstances  of  this  fluid  are  considered,  the  idea 
that  it  has  life  within  it,  may  not  appear  so  difficult  to 
comprehend,  for  every  part  is  formed,  as  we  grow,  out  of 
the  blood,  and  if  it  has  not  life  previous  to  this  operation, 
it  must  acquire  it  in  the  act  of  formation."  One  of  the 
great  proofs  of  the  blood's  vitality  is  to  be  found  in 
coagulation,  as  the  blood,  when  circulating,  is  not  subject 
to  certain  laws  to  which  it  is  subject  when  removed  from 
the  vessels. 

1  De  Part.  AnimdTii.  i.  4.  8.         a  Hunter's  Works,  T.  in. 


224  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

Note  14,  p.  26.  So  many  ivriters  as  admit.]     Heat  is 
the  antagonism  to  cold,  for  it  is  fixed1,  and  with  a  down- 
ward tendency,  while  heat  is  mobile,  and  has  an  inclina- 
tion upwards ;  heat,  again,  tends  to  dilate  bodies,  while 
cold  acts  by  contracting  them.     Thus,  as  heat2  separates, 
and  cold  consolidates,  they  came  to  be  looked  upon  as  the 
elements  or  causes  of  destruction,  (as  he^b  appears  to  be 
self-motive  and  a  cause  of  change?)  and  restoration.     But 
as  heat  (£eo>  to  boil  or  be  hot)  is  derived  from,  or  is  the 
synonym   of  life  or  living,   (£aw  contr.  £w,  £ae»i/  cqntr. 
tyjv,)  so  some  made  life,  from  this  supposed  identity,  to  be 
heat ;   and  others,  from  the  resemblance   between   cold 
(\l/vxpos  or  >^u^o<:)  and  the  Vital  Principle,  (v/^^*?)  as 
breathing  was  supposed,  by  all  the  physiologists,  to  be  a 
process  for  cooling  the  blood,  made  it  to  be  cold.     It  is 
hardly  possible  to  transfer  to  another,  and  that  not  a 
cognate  tongue,  the  full  sense  of  a  passage  which  depends 
upon   etymology ;   but  the  general  import  of  these  two 
opinions  may,  perhaps,  be  gathered  from  what   is   here 
said.      Thus,  Cervantes3  makes  his  knight  fix  upon  the 
name  Rocinante,  because  Rocin  is  a  horse,  or  nag  of  the 
ordinary  character;  but,  as  his  charger  is  to  have  wide- 
spread renown,  and  to  be  distinguished  from  all  other 
nags,  it  ought  to  have  a  sonorous  and  suitable  appellation, 
and   this  is  realised,  in  his  own  opinion,  by  the  suffix 
ante,  and  hence,  Rocinante. 

1  Metaphys.  xin.  5.  2  De  Gen.  et  Corr.  ix.  n. 

3  T.  I.  Cap.  i. 


CH.  III.]  NOTES.  225 


CHAPTER  III. 

Note  1,  p.  29.  It  is  not  easy,  hoioever,  <fec.]  That  is, 
if  the  Vital  Principle  be  a  first  cause  and  an  element  or 
combination  of  the  elements,  it  cannot  be  determined,  if 
subject  to  external  impulse,  what  its  movements  will 
be — if  it  be  of  fire,  it  must  move  upwards,  if  of  earth, 
downwards,  and  so  for  intermediate  movements.  Plato 
maintains,  as  was  said,  that,  as  there  can  be  nothing 
visible  or  tangible  without  Jire  or  solid  without  earth, 
tJiese  were  the  first  of  created  elements ;  and  that,  as 
there  can  be  no  enduring  combination  out  of  two  elements, 
avr  and  water  were  next  created  and  placed  between  the 
first  two. 

Note  2,  p.  30.  Now,  the  body  is  moved  by  translation.'] 
This  passage  has  been  the  subject  of  much  and  serious 
controversy,  both  as  to  its  meaning  and  its  genuineness ; 
and  yet,  although  an  argumentum  ad  absurdum,  it  is  a 
fair  conclusion  from  those  premises.  Thus,  if  the  Vital 
Principle  be  an  entity  distinct  from  the  body  which  it 
animates,  and  if  the  body  be  moved,  by  translation,  from 
it,  the  Vital  Principle,  having  also  that  movement,  may 
set  itself  free,  and  if  able  to  do  this,  it  may  re-enter  and 

15 


226  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

resuscitate  the  body  which  it  had  left.  The  assumption, 
in  fact,  is  an  evident  objection  to  the  opinion  that  Vital 
Principle  moves  itself  as  it  moves  the  body ;  and  seems  to 
be  necessary  to  the  completion  of  the  argument. 

The  passage,  however,  has  been  regarded  as  an  inter- 
polation introduced  by  some  Christian  writer,  (adeo  verba 
Christianum  seculum  referunt,)  in  order  to  support  the 
doctrine  of  the  resurrection  :  and  Trendelenberg,  while 
unwilling  to  suppress  the  passage,  seems  to  question  its 
authenticity.  The  subsequent  paragraphs  are  in  support 
of  Aristotle's  opinion  that  the  Vital  Principle,  if  self- 
motive,  cannot  be  subject  to  motion  by  other  impulse 
than  its  own,  (just  as  that  which  is  good  in  itself,  cannot 
be  so  by  or  for  the  sake  of  something  else,)  and  that,  if 
it  were  so  subject,  its  motion  would  be  due  to  sentient 
impressions. 

Note  3,  p.  31.  Some  philosopJwrs  maintain.]  This 
passage  is  a  covert  satire  of  the  doctrine  of  Democritus 
that  motion  is  transmitted  through  all  nature  by  atoms 
in  constant  motion ;  and  these  are  said  to  have  been 
likened  by  Philippus,  the  reputed  son,  according  to 
Meineke,  of  Aristophanes,  to  globules  of  quicksilver, 
which,  when  poured  in,  made  a  wooden  figure  to  become 
moveable.  It  is  uncertain,  by  the  way,  when  this  metal 
was  first  employed ;  it  is  here  alluded  to  as  a  well-known 
substance,  and  is  so  spoken  of  by  Theophrastus.  '  Pliny 

1  Hist.  Nat.  33.  32. 


CH.  III.]  NOTES.  227 

says  that  "  it  was  brought  from  the  silver  mines  of  Spain, 
in  the  form  of  cinnabar,  and,  when  freed  from  its  ore, 
used  in  metallurgy;"  further,  "that  it  is  always  fluid, 
and  an  universal  poison." 

Note  4,  p.  31.  It  is  in  this  same  manner,  &c.j  If  the 
Vital  Principle  be  to  the  body  what  Plato,  in  the  Timceus, 
made  the  great  animating  principle  to  be  to  the  Universe, 
a  source  of  intelligence  and  ordered  motion,  there  must  be 
an  accordance  between  terrene  and  celestial  bodies  and 
movements ;  but  as  earthly  bodies  are  moved  by  objects 
of  sense  and  perception,  and  as  their  movements  are  not, 
like  those  of  the  heavenly,  in  a  circle,  their  natures  must 
be  different.  It  would  be  idle  to  attempt  to  make  a 
digest  of  the  opinions  entertained  in  the  Timceus,  the 
most  abstruse  and  laboured  of  all  Plato's  works,  or  to 
trace  the  analogy  between  the  constitution  and  motions 
of  the  supernal  orbs,  and  the  constitutions  and  conditions 
of  earthly  bodies.  But  four  points  seem  to  be  evident 
— that  the  universe  moves  by  motions  communicated  by 
the  anima;  that  the  anima  is  from  the  elements;  that 
it  has  so  been  divided,  as  to  have  an  innate  sense  of 
harmonic  numbers ;  and  that  it  has  been  made  to  move 
in  the  same  circles  as  the  sky.  This  summary  is  adduced 
by  Aristotle  to  shew  how  scarcely  possible  it  could  be  to 
adjust  this  speculation  to  his  own  subject  of  inquiry,  and 
he  may  have  been  led  to  criticise  it  the  rather,  as  the 
great  principle  of  the  universe  is  synonymous  with  his 
own  treatise;  each  is,  in  fact,  -^v^tj.  But  to  quote  the 

15—2 


228  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

learned '  commentator,  "  Platonem  in  Timceo  quam 
maxime  obscurum  illustrare,  hujus  loci  non  est." 

Note  5,  p.  32.  But,  in  the  first  place.]  These  critical 
objections  cannot  be  fully  realised  without  reference  to 
the  leading  opinions  and  arguments  of  the  Timceus,  which, 
although,  perhaps,  at  the  time,  regarded  only  as  specula- 
tions and  now  stand  self-confuted  as  physics,  are  enshrined 
in  words  which  shall  endure,  until  mankind  cease  to 
find  delight  and  instruction  in  pure  and  abstract  studies. 
The  first  objection  raised  by  Aristotle  is  to  the  ascription 
of  magnitude  to  that  anima  (which  is  to  be  necessarily 
inferred  from  its  being  divisible,)  as  well  as  to  the 
intelligence  or  mind,  which  Ls  identified  with  it ;  for 
magnitude  would  imply  a  material  entity,  and  matter 
conjoined  with  form  and  essence  implies  parts,  and  what- 
ever has  parts  cannot  either  be  self-existent,  or  indefinite 
in  duration.  Another  objection,  much  insisted  upon,  is 
the  movement  in  a  circle,  which  cannot,  it  is  said,  be  the 
motion  produced  by  the  passions  or  appetites ;  but  the 
chief  topic  is  resumed,  and  the  mind  is  shewn  to  be, 
like  the  thoughts  which  emanate  from  it,  immaterial. 
Aristotle's  subject,  however,  unlike  that  of  the  Timceus, 
was  confined  to  the  agent  or  principle,  whatever  it  be, 
which  imparts  motion  and  other  vital  properties  to  organ- 
ised matter. 

Note  6,  p.  33.  Now,  there  are  limits  to  practical 
thoughts]  The  origin2  of  whatever  is  original  is  in  the 
1  Trendel.  Comment.  *  Metaphys.  V.  i.  5. 


CH.  III.]  NOTES.  229 

maker  or  creator,  whether  it  be  mind,  or  art,  or  a  special 
faculty — it  is  an  abstraction  that  is;  but,  whatever 
is  practical  is  dependent  only  on  an  agent,  or  his  choice, 
for  the  act  is  identical  with  what  is  chosen.  Thus,  prac- 
tical thoughts  are  confined  to  the  particular  faculties  and 
organs  which  are  required  for  securing  what  may  have 
been  chosen. 

Note  7,  p.  33.  Terminated  by  a  syllogism.]  The 
syllogism1  is  an  argument,  in  which,  from  given  premises, 
something  different  from  the  terms  laid  down  results, 
necessarily,  from  their  admission.  Modern  definition  is 
much  like  this — the  syllogism  is  said  to  be  an  argument 
of  three  propositions,  having  the  property,  that  the  con- 
clusion necessarily  follows  from  the  two  premises ;  so  that 
if  the  premises  be  true,  the  conclusion  must  be  true  ;  and 
a  conclusion  is  the  proposition  which  is  inferred  from 
certain  former  propositions,  termed  the  premises  of  the 
argument. 

Note  8,  p.  34.  The  same  incongruity]  This  is  an 
objection  by  Aristotle  to  the  doctrine  of  metempsychosis, 
adopted  by  the  Pythagoreans,  and,  being  placed  upon 
obvious  physical  relations,  it  may  be  considered  as  irre- 
fragable. Thus,  philosophers  held  numbers  to  be  elements, 
and  perceived  in  them  and  their  combinations  resem- 
blances to,  or  types  of  faculties  and  sentient  properties,  as 
has  been  observed.  Their  doctrine*  was,  "  that  man 
consists  of  an  elementary  nature,  and  a  rational  or  divine 
1  Analytic,  a.  I.  i.  6.  *  Hist,  of  Philos.  Vol.  i.  397. 


230  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

principle,  and  that  of  this  last,  the  divine  is  seated  in  the 
brain,  the  passions  and  appetites  in  the  liver  and  heart ; 
that  the  rational  part  is  immortal,  the  sentient  principle 
perishable."  They  further  taught,  that  the  imperishable 
part,  freed  from  the  chains  of  the  body,  assumes  a  new 
form,  passes  to  the  centre  of  the  earth  for  judgment, 
and,  if  not  deemed  worthy  of  associating  with  perfect 
spirits,  is  returned  to  earth  to  inhabit  another  body,  of 
higher  or  lower  nature,  according  to  its  former  deserts. 
This  doctrine  has  been  so  developed  and  exemplified  in 
the  final  teaching  of  Socrates,  before  his  death,  that  that 
dialogue1  may  be  regarded  as  a  faithful  exposition  of  the 
argument  and  its  merits.  Aristotle,  overlooking  eveiy 
supernal  cause  or  agency,  objects  to  the  doctrine,  not  on 
its  own  grounds  but,  by  reasonings,  which  are  purely 
deductive  ;  and  the  doctrine  is,  no  doubt,  when  tested  by 
physical  science,  incongruous. 

Note  9,  p.  35.  Such  opinions  are,  in  fact,  &c.]  This 
passage  is  apparently  abstruse  and  ambiguous,  owing  to  the 
terms  being  applicable  to  more  than  one  art  or  implement ; 
and  yet,  "  *  as  it  involves  a  kind  of  antithesis  between 
the  art  and  the  implements,  the  Vital  Principle  and  the 
body,"  the  general  sense  can  be  made  sufficiently  obvious. 
The  purport  of  the  phrase  is  well  given  in  the  Latin 
version  :  Perinde  igitur  dicunt  atqui  si  quispiam  artem 
fabrilem  fistulas  ingredi  dicat ;  etenim  ars  quidam  instru- 
mentis,  anima  vero  corpore  utatur  oportet.  The  French 
1  Ffuedo.  *  Trendel.  Comment. 


CH.  IV.]  NOTES.  231 

version  is  less  definite  :  "  C'est  absolument  comme  si  Ton 
pretendoit  que  1'architecture  peut  se  meler  de  fabriquer 
des  instruments  de  musique." 


CHAPTER  IV. 

Note  1,  p.  38.  It  is  equally  absurd  to  think,  &c.] 
This  is  an  unanswerable  objection  to  Empedocles  and  bis 
followers  who  made  all  bodies  to  be  combinations,  in 
differing  proportions,  of  the  elements — for  whether  the 
Vital  Principle  be  harmony  or  a  combination  of  particles, 
there  must,  as  combinations  are  various,  (since  that  which 
forms  bone  is  not  that  which  forms  flesh,)  be  several  prin- 
ciples in  each  member  of  the  body;  and  if  it  be  not  pro- 
portion, there  must  then  be  a  second  Vital  Principle  to 
maintain  that  relation.  The  succeeding  passages  are, 
necessarily,  from  the  absence  of  precise  knowledge  con- 
cerning atomic  proportion  and  relation,  obscure ;  but  they 
point  to  opinions  which,  although  not  based  on  experi- 
mental science,  anticipate,  when  closely  looked  into,  much 
that  is  now  admitted. 

Note  2,  p.  40.  Now,  to  maintain  that  Vital  Principle, 
&c.]  The  argument  reverts  to  the  question  whether  the 
Vital  Principle  can  be  subjected  to  motion  casually  pro- 
duced— be  subject,  that  is,  to  motion  through  the  body 
which  is  moved  by  it,  and  thus  partake  of  locomotion ;  but 


232  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

the  Vital  Principle,  being  an  essence,  cannot  be  subject 
to  casual  motion  ;  and  then  it  has  been) shewn  that  a 
motor  is  not,  necessarily,  itself  in  motion.  There  seems, 
however,  to  have  been  some  difficulty  in  refusing  all 
motion  to  the  Vital  Principle,  since  the  emotions  and 
passions  which  emanate  from  it  seem  to  be  motions,  or 
combined  with  motions, — as  passion  excites  and  fear  de- 
presses the  motions  of  the  heart,  and  deep  thought  furrows 
the  brow  ;  but  Aristotle,  in  order  to  reconcile  these  with 
his  own  opinion,  has  recourse  to  an  hypothesis  which  is 
left  for  future  inquiry.  It  is  well  said,  however,  that  the 
man  rather  than  the  Vital  Principle  is  moved  by  passions 
and  emotions ;  and  thus  motion  may  descend  from  it,  as 
the  first  motor,  and  at  rest,  to  the  several  organs,  (act,  that 
is,  upon  the  temperament,)  or  ascend  to  it,  by  perception 
of  the  external  world,  for  memoiy.  Philoponus,  comment- 
ing upon  this  passage,  observes,  as  proof  that  recollection 
originates  in  the  Vital  Principle  and  thence  permeates  to 
the  body,  that,  "when  reminded  of  any  fearful  incident 
we  turn  pale,  and  when  recalling  a  voyage  we  become 
qualmish." 

Note  3,  p.  40.  The  mind  seems  to  be  a  peculiar  innate 
essence,  &c.]  Aristotle  has  nowhere  denned  this  great 
faculty,  to  which  he  attributed  so  high  a  destiny  and  such 
lofty  privileges — "intellectus  nihil  patitur ;  est  atque 
manet ;"  but  the  opinion  was  not  exclusively  his,  nor  did 
it  originate  with  him,  for  Anaxagoras1,  and  before  him, 
1  Metapkys.  I.  3.  10. 


CH.  IV.]  NOTES.  233 

Hermoticus  made  the  "  mind  to  be  the  cause  as  well  of 
existence  in  animals  as  of  the  universe  and  universal  order." 
There  is,  evidently,  here  a  want  of  distinction  between 
mind  and  Vital  Priuciple ;  and  it  may  be  that,  in  order 
to  avoid  the  obvious  objection  of  two  bodies  in  one, 
Aristotle  has  always  delineated  this  faculty  as  homoge- 
neous and  pure  ;  that  is,  as  immaterial. 

Note  4,  p.  40.  For  if  an  aged  person.]  This  allusion 
to  diminished  perception,  by  changes,  from  the  influence 
of  time,  in  the  sentient  organs,  implies  all  that  can  now 
be  said ;  for  could  the  organ  be  restored  to  its  pristine 
form,  and  its  energies  be,  so  to  say,  revived,  the  aged 
person  would  see  or  hear  as  he  did  when  young.  The 
body  is  modified,  in  fact,  by  age,  just  as  it  is,  to  use 
Aristotle's  apposite  reflexion,  by  maladies  and  rioting, 
which  anticipate  the  otherwise  slower  processes  of  time ; 
"  Senectus  non  eo  existat,  quod  anima  sed  quod  id  patitur 
in  quo  inest,  i.  e.  corpus,  sicut  in  ebrietate  et  morbis." 

Note  5,  p.  41.  Thus,  too,  thought  and  reflexion  lan- 
guish] Quid  sit,  quod  intus  perire  dicatur,  commenta- 
tores  quaerunt ;  sed  nihil  definiendum,  nisi  quod  oculi 
similitudini  respondeat l ;  but  Philoponus,  who  is  here 
cited,  clearly  perceived  that  the  passage  pointed  to  the 
destruction  of  a  corporeal  organ,  and  not  to  a  mere  change 
of  form.  Whenever,  in  fact,  there  is  destruction,  however 
brought  about,  of  a  corporeal  organ,  there  is  almost 
universally  mental  disturbance  and  delirium. 
1  Trendel.  Comment. 


234  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

Note  6,  p.  41.  The  most  unreasonable  by  far  of  all  tJie 
opinions,  &c.]  These  passages  are  so  associated  with  the 
peculiar  doctrines  of  the  Pythagoreans ',  that  they  can 
hardly,  within  the  compass  of  a  note,  be  made  intelligible 
to  the  general  reader.  These  held  the  unit,  it  may  be 
said,  to  be  the  origin  of  number,  and  the  point  to  be  the 
origin  of  the  line ;  and  so  they  made  unit  and  point  to 
belong  to  one  common  genus.  But  the  unit  was  said  to 
be  a  point  without  position,  and,  therefore,  an  abstract 
entity,  which,  being  without  parts  or  distinctions,  cannot 
be  either  motor  or  moved,  and,  therefore,  cannot  represent 
the  principle  of  all  motion.  Thus,  the  opinion  is  objected 
to  as  making  the  Yital  Principle  a  number,  which  deprives 
it  of  locality  or  position,  and  then  as  attributing  motion 
to  it  which,  as  a  number,  it  is  not  susceptible  of.  The 
following  passages,  which  treat  of  the  division  of  plants 
and  insects,  further  prove,  by  analogy,  that  the  Vital 
Principle  cannot  be  a  number,  as,  unlike  a  number,  each 
part  seems  to  have,  after  division,  all  the  properties  which 
it  had  while  yet  conjoined  with  the  whole.  The  argument 
is  then  turned  against  the  doctrine  of  Democritus,  if  the 
corpuscles  be  regarded  as  points,  there  must  still  be  in 
each  point,  as  quantity,  a  motor  and  a  moved ;  and  the 
theory  depended  for  support  upon  quantity,  rather  than 
relations  of  size.  Unless,  then,  the  Yital  Principle  be 
both  motor  and  moved,  which  it  evidently  cannot  be, 
there  must  be  a  motor  power  for  those  corpuscles. 
1  Topica,  I.  1 8,  8. 


CH.  IV.]  NOTES.  235 

Note  7,  p.  41.  How,  indeed,  is  it  possible.]  This  pas- 
sage is  very  elliptical  and  obscure,  but  its  purport  seems 
to  be  an  objection  to  the  doctrine  of  Xenocrates,  a  follower 
of  Plato,  who  maintained  that  the  Vital  Principle  might 
be  separate  from  the  body.  The  argument  runs  thus  :  if 
the  Vital  Principle  be  a  number,  and  if  each  unit  be  a 
point,  how,  as  the  point  is  not  separable  from  the  line, 
can  the  Vital  Principle  be  separate  from  the  body? 
Although  the  point  may  be,  abstractedly,  apart  from  the 
line,  yet  as  the  line  is  not  divisible  into  points,  (since 
points  are  but  the  termination  of  the  line)  it  follows  that 
the  Vital  Principle,  when  regarded  as  a  point,  cannot  be, 
actually,  separate  from  the  body.  The  Latin  paraphrase  is, 
"  Insuper  qui  fieri  potest  ut  separentur  et  absolvantur  a 
corporibus,  ipsa  puncta  ?  siquidem  lineae  non  dividuntur  in 
puncta1; "  the  French  is,  "  Comment  est-il  possible  que  les 
ames  se  separent  et  se  delivrent  des  corps,  puisque  les 
lignes  ne  se  divisent  pas  en  points  1 " 

1  Acad.  Reg.  Sorussica. 


236  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 


CHAPTER  V. 

Note  1,  p.  47.  Now,  three  modes  of  defining  Vital 
Principle,  &c.]  There  is  here  a  want  of  conformity  with 
other  definitions  of  the  Vital  Principle,  which  points 
either  to  neglect  on  the  part  of  copyists,  or  to  want  of 
early  revision;  for,  in  one  place,  Aristotle  has  distin- 
guished the  animate  from  the  inanimate  by  "  motion  and 
sensibility,"  while  in  another  he  has  conjoined  with  them 
immateriality ;  and  here,  also,  he  has  three  terms,  but 
incorporeity,  as  if  to  approach  nearer  to  the  doctrines  of 
his  great  preceptor,  is  substitued  for  sensibility. 

Note  2,  p.  47.  This  opinion  has  been  adopted,  &c.] 
The  elements,  and  the  parts  assigned  to  them  in  the 
constitution  of  bodies,  by  the  schools  of  antiquity,  have 
been  noticed  in  a  former  note ;  but  the  notion  that,  as 
like  perceives  like,  the  Vital  Principle,  being  derived 
from  the  elements,  must  perceive  each  like,  cannot  account 
for  the  perception  of  compound  bodies,  unless,  (which  is 
an  absurdity)  it  contain,  essentially,  all  compounds  what- 
ever. This  is  all  very  hypothetical,  no  doubt,  but  then 
it  assumes  that  there  are  elements,  and  that  elements 
combine,  by  affinity,  in  different  proportions,  to  form 
different  bodies ;  and,  thus,  the  doctrine  may  be  regarded 
as  a  faint  outline  of  the  matured  theory  of  modern  times. 


CH.  V.]  NOTES.  237 

This  is  further  shewn  in  the  formation  of  bone,  as  given 
in  the  verse  quoted  from  Empedocles,  and  which,  besides 
proportion,  admits  heat  as  an  agent  in  combination.  The 
epithets  employed  by  that  eminent  writer  are  not  so  pre- 
cise as  might  be  desired,  and  it  cannot  now  be  determined 
what  was  meant  by  the  words  "liquid  light,"  or  fire, 
(i^'o-Tt?  a  17X17)  (was  it  phosphorus,  in  some  form  T) ;  but  yet 
proportion  and  combination,  under  high  temperature,  are 
quite  apparent — the  Latin  version  of  the  quotation  is  : 

"  Cceperat  ante  duas  tellus  justissima  vasis 
Aeris  ac  fontis  partes  :  Vulcanus  et  ipse 
Quatuor  ex  octo  adjunxit,  quis  Candida  magna 
Vis  fcecundaque  naturae  confecerat  ossa." 

Note  3,  p.  49.  It  is  absurd  to  maintain,  &c.]  We  have 
had  handed  down,  by  the  earliest  writers,  differences  of 
opinion,  Aristotle  l  says,  upon  "  action  and  impression ; " 
but  most  of  them  agree  in  making  like  unimpressionable 
by  like,  (since  the  one  is  not  more  active  or  passive  than 
the  other,)  and  the  unlike  and  different  alone  to  have 
been  so  constituted  as  to  act  and  re-act  upon  one  another. 
Democritus  stood  alone  in  maintaining  that  the  selfsame 
like  can  be,  at  once,  active  and  passive ;  for  he  would  not 
grant  that  things  which  are,  essentially,  different,  can 
mutually  act  and  re-act  upon  one  another.  And  even 
though  things  should  seem  to  be  different,  there  is  ever 
something  like,  he  maintains,  by  which  the  impression  is 
made.  The  difference  between  these  opinions,  however, 
1  De  Gen.  et  Corr.  i.  7.  r. 


238  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

when  followed  out,  is,  after  all,  formal  rather  than  sub- 
stantive ;  for,  in  either  case,  the  Vital  Principle,  whether 
like  or  unlike,  must  be  material,  as  the  opinion  still 
implies  some  kind  of  impression,  and  impression  implies 
material  properties. 

Note  4,  p.  49.  But  to  shew  how  many  doubts,  <kc.] 
The  earlier  philosophers  differed  widely,  as  has  been  said, 
upon  the  elements,  both  as  to  their  nature  and  number  ; 
but  those  writers  are  evidently  wrong,  Aristotle1  observes, 
who  admit  of  only  one  element  and  one  nature,  as  they 
take  no  account  of  incorporeal  entities.  Empedocles 
adopted  the  four  elements  as  constitutive  of  tlie  matter  of 
bodies,  and  hence  the  objection  to  his  opinion,  that  "  sen- 
sation is  produced  by  corporeal  elements  in  the  relation 
of  like ; "  for  those  parts  which  are  formed  of  earth  (hair, 
bones,  <fec.)  are  insensible ;  and,  therefore,  this  element 
cannot  be  perceptive  of  like.  This  assumption  of  insen- 
sibility is,  of  course,  too  absolute,  but  such  parts  are  no 
doubt  withdrawn,  more  or  less,  from  the  general  sensi- 
bility and  sympathy  of  the  living  body.  The  term  vevpa, 
it  may  be  observed,  by  the  way,  which  here  signifies 
tendon  or  sinew,  has  now  the  meaning  of  nerves,  the 
conductors,  that  is,  of  sentient  impressions ;  and  Galen, 
who  lived  so  many  ages  after  Aristotle,  and  was  well 
acquainted  with  the  brain,  optic  nerves,  and  office  of  the 
nerves,  still  employed  vevpov  as  a  muscular  chord. 

1  Metaphyt.  I.  8.  i  ;  xin.  4,  5. 


CH.  V.]  NOTES.  239 

Note  5,  p.  50.  It  follows,  too,  from  this  theory,  <tc.] 
Empedocles  regarded  affinity  (jtf>i\lav)  as  an  element,  but 
what  the  deity  to  which  he  refused,  so  to  say,  repulsion 
(TO  velicos)  is  uncertain ;  "  whether  Sphaerus  '  or  not,  it 
implies,  at  all  events  a  being,  to  which  '  repulsion '  (in 
quern  pugna  non  admittitur)  had  not  been  imparted."  If 
this,  like  affinity,  were  an  element,  then,  as  each  sentient 
being  was  supposed  to  be  constituted  of  all  the  elements, 
that  deity  must  have  been  less  favoured  than  other  beings, 
since  he  was  unconscious  of  antagonistic  properties,  and 
therefore,  relatively,  less  intelligent  than  they. 

Note  6,  p.  50.  But  we  are  at  a  loss  to  know,  &c.] 
Aristotle  here  inquires  what  the  particular  faculty  or 
force  may  be  which  individualises,  makes  one,  that  is,  of 
objects ;  and,  thereby,  gives  to  the  sentient  being  the 
consciousness  of  identity.  It  cannot  be  a  sense,  as  the 
senses  are  derived  from  the  elements,  and  the  elements 
are  akin  to  matter,  while  that,  whatever  it  be,  which 
combines  the  faculties  and  powers  of  the  body  must,  of 
all,  be  the  most  influential ;  and  it  may  be  inferred  rather 
than  gathered  from  what  is  said,  that  it  cannot  be  either 
the  Vital  Principle  or  the  mind.  But  do  not  all  these 
doubts  and  suggestions  point  to  a  central  organ  where 
the  sentient  impressions,  so  to  say,  meet,  and  where  con- 
sciousness has  its  seat  ?  Does  not  the  brain,  which,  as 
the  source  of  sensibility  was  then  it  may  be  said  un- 
known, fulfil  all  that  is  required  by  this  suggestion  1  The 
1  Trendel.  Comment. 


240  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

brain  is  the  organ  which  individualises  different  impres- 
sions, and  so  enables  the  mind  to  compare  and  judge  ;  it 
is  the  organ,  too,  which,  retaining  impressions,  is  the  seat 
of  memory,  and  the  source  whence  imagination  draws  its 
images.  The  mind  is  again  spoken  of  as  higher  in  nature 
than  aught  else,  and  thus  Aristotle  agrees  with  Anaxa- 
goras  who  held  that  the  "  mind  was  the  first  of  all 
created  entities  and  powers." 

Note  7,  p.  51.  Thus,  the  reasoning  in  the  so-called 
Orphic  verses,  &c.]  The  epithet,  "  so-called,"  seems  to  imply 
that  there  were  doubts  as  to  the  author  of  these  verses  ; 
be  this  as  it  may,  they  shew  that  animal  life  was  known 
to  be  especially  dependent  upon  respiration.  Aristotle's 
criticism  seems  to  imply  that  he  was  not  acquainted  with 
respiration  in  any  other  form  than  that  of  air-breathing 
animals,  and  therefore,  not  aware  that  the  influence  of 
the  air  upon  the  system  is  necessary  for  the  maintenance 
of  life  in  all  creatures.  Cicero  *  maintains  that  "  Aristotle 
denied  the  existence  of  the  poet  Orpheus ; "  and  that  the 
verses  under  that  name  were  attributed,  by  the  Pythago- 
reans, to  one  Cecrops. 

Note  8,  p.  51.  If  it  be  well  to  form  tlie  Vital  Prin- 
ciple, <fec.]  The  wording  as  well  as  the  meaning  of 
this  objection  to  the  opinion  that  "  Vital  Principle  must 
be  formed  from  all  the  elements"  is  embarrassed  and 
obscure ;  and,  owing  to  the  brevity  of  the  argument,  it 
cannot  be  expounded  with  certainty ;  but  it  seems  to 
1  De  Nat.  Dew.  I.  38. 


CH.  V.]  NOTES.  241 

imply  that  as  one  part  of  a  contrary  can  judge  itself  and 
the  other,  so  all  the  elements  cannot  be  necessary,  since 
nature  never  employs  means  in  vain.  '  "  TJnum  sufficit 
ex  contrariis,  ut  et  hoc  et  alterum  judicetur ;  ad  recti 
nonnam  etiam  curvum  exigitur;  veruin  sui  index  et  falsi, 
ut  Spinoza  loquitur." 

Note  9,  p.  52.  There  are  writers  who  maintain,  &c.] 
Aristotle  seems  to  have  interpreted  this  opinion  differently 
from  others,  and,  differently,  it  may  be,  (by  regarding  the 
beings  alluded  to  as  the  representatives  of  Yital  Proper- 
ties,) from  its  original  import.  Cicero2,  for  instance,  attri- 
butes to  Thales,  one  of  the  wisest  among  the  seven,  the 
opinion,  that  "  it  is  expedient  for  men  to  suppose  that 
whatever  can  be  perceived  is  full  of  gods,  for,  thereby, 
all,  as  if  placed  in  consecrated  shrines,  would  become 
purer."  Whatever  may  be  the  value  of  that  version, 
the  opinion  could  not  be  maintained  when  applied  to 
the  cause  of  living  actions,  the  origin,  that  is,  of  living 
beings ;  for,  as  bodies  were  supposed  to  be  formed  of 
elements,  and  elements  to  be  everywhere,  the  elements 
themselves  should  be  transformed  into  animals,  which 
involves  an  absurdity. 

Note  10,  p.  53.  Since  the  faculties  oj  knowing,  feeling, 
&c.]  Aristotle,  quitting  the  question  of  life  in  its  sim- 
plest form,  here  reverts,  after  enumerating  the  properties 
which  characterise  the  highest  forms  of  created  beings,  to 
the  question,  whether  or  not  all  the  properties  may  be 
1  Trendel.  Comment.  *  De  Leyibut,  II.  1 1. 

16 


242  NOTES.  [BK.  i. 

derived  from  one  and  the  same  principle ;  and  if  not  from 
one  and  the  same,  what  that  is  which  combines  the  parts, 
and  makes  them  to  be  one.  The  passage  which  follows 
is  an  evident  allusion  to  the  Timceus,  according  to  which, 
as  has  been  said,  reason  is  placed,  as  in  a  soil  fit  for 
the  heavenly  seed,  in  the  brain,  the  appetite  and  passions 
in  the  heart,  liver,  or  spleen ;  and  then  comes  the  ques- 
tion, what  so  connects  those  organs  as  to  make  them 
mutually  subsidiary  to  one  another?  not  the  body,  cer- 
tainly, it  may  be  answered,  as  the  body  itself  is  but  the 
instrument  of  the  Vital  Principle. 

Note  11,  p.  55.  But  the  living  principle  in  plants,  <kc.] 
This  passage  is,  to  appearance,  obscure,  owing  to  its  construc- 
tion and  scientific  wording,  but  yet  its  meaning  is  obvious : 
the  living  principle  in  plants,  that  which  constitutes  their 
vitality,  is  assimilation,  (growth,  through  nutrition,  that 
is,)  and  it  exists  in  plants  without  sentient  properties; 
but  sentient  properties  cannot,  of  course,  exist  without 
nutrition,  as  nutrition  is  essential  to  life,  and  present, 
therefore,  in  every  thing  which  lives. 


BOOK    THE     SECOND. 


CHAPTER  I. 

Note  1,  p.  58.  Now  matter  is  potentiality,  species 
reality.]  A  few  words  may  suffice  for  a  further  attempt 
to  elucidate  these  terms.  Matter,  then,  per  se,  has  no 
definite  existence,  but  with  essence  it  becomes  a  some- 
thing in  potentiality,  and  then  capable,  under  genial 
conditions,  of  becoming  a  reality,  the  specific  and  indi- 
vidual character  of  which  depends  upon  form.  Matter  is 
said  to  be  comprised  in  essence,  and  therefore  the  distinc- 
tion between  them  is  hardly  discernible,  but  Aristotle1, 
under  the  term  essence,  comprises  elements  (earth,  fire, 
water  and  air)  as  well  as  derivatives  from  the  elements, 
and  that  because,  while  all  other  bodies  are  to  be  con- 
sidered as  dependent  upon  them,  they  pre-existed  to,  and 
were  the  origin  of  all  others.  In  another  passage*  he 
assumes  one  universal,  primordial,  material  essence,  as 
the  source  whence  all  things  which  are  have  proceeded  ; 
yet  still  he  admits  of  a  peculiar  essence  for  each  genus,  as 
the  primal  matter  of  pituita  is  whatever  is  sweet  or  oily, 
1  Metaphys.  ry.  8.  i.  a  Ibid.  VII.  42. 

16—2 


244  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

and  as  whatever  is  bitter  is  the  primal  matter  of  bile. 
Although  essence  may  be  an  abstraction,  yet  a  generic 
character  is  clearly  assigned  to  it  in  the  text,  and  even  in 
recent  times  recourse  has  been  had  to  such  an  assumption 
in  order  to  explain  the  difference  between  the  secretions 
of  organs  supplied  with  the  same  fluids  and  animated  by 
the  same  nerves.  Thus,  it  was  assumed  that  there  must 
be  for  each  organ  a  peculiar  essence,  a  substantia  propria 
(v\i%tj  ova-ia),  for  the  fulfilment  of  its  functions  as  well  as 
the  maintenance  of  its  relations  and  sympathies  with  the 
other  parts  of  the  system.  The  text  seems  to  admit  of 
only  one  essence  and  one  matter  to  be  as  the  matrix  for 
all  things,  which  is,  of  course,  opposed  to  the  doctrine  of 
elements  and  the  formation  of  bodies  by  them ;  but  the 
hypothesis  could  treat  of  them  only  as  primordial 
entities,  however  diversified  by  form  their  manifestations 
may  be.  Aristotle  was  the  first,  however,  who  made  form 
to  be  the  realising  principle,  to  be  that  which  confers 
upon  matter  specific  character,  and  constitutes  the  series 
of  being ;  and  this  has  been  adopted  by  modern  physio- 
logists, as  Reil  makes  form '  together  with  variety  in  t/te 
combination  of  the  elements  "  to  be  the  cause  of  existing 
differences  in  organic  bodies  and  their  faculties." 

Note  2,  p.    58.      But  bodies,  and  above  all  natural 

bodies.]     Living  bodies,  that  is,  are  broadly  distinguished 

from   all   others   by   the   innate   power   of    reproducing 

similar  bodies,  (similar  in  a  specific  sense,  that  is,)  and 

1  Miiller  Handbuch  der  Phys.  i.  27. 


CH.  I.]  NOTES.  245 

which  are  the  material  for  most  of  the  works  of  man's 
hand;  as  the  human  intellect  can  confer  upon  its 
creations  nothing  save  newness  of  form.  Without  assert- 
ing that  all  which  is  has  emanated  from  living  bodies, 
modern  science  has  shewn  that  vast  masses  of  matter, 
now  inorganic,  were  the  product  of  what  once  had  life. 

Note  3,  p.  59.  Thus  every  natural  body  partaking  of 
life,  <fec.]  The  text  seems  to  be  in  accordance  with  what 
had  preceded,  but  it  has  been  objected  to  by  some  on 
account  of  its  supposed  obscurity ;  it  seems,  however,  to 
imply  that  the  three  primordial  conditions,  matter,  essence 
and  form,  are  necessary  to,  and  concur  in  the  formation  of 
every  specific  body. 

Note  4,  p.  59.  And  since  the  body  is  such  a  com- 
bination, &c.]  This  passage  is  obscure  both  in  word- 
ing and  purport,  but  it  seems  to  imply  that  the  living 
body,  being  what  it  has  been  said  to  be,  is  indepen- 
dent and  self-existent,  and,  as  such,  cannot  be  Vital 
Principle,  because  it  cannot  be  among  the  subordinates 
of  a  subject,  which  is  the  part  seemingly  ascribed  to 
Vital  Principle,  as  merely  realising  what  already  had 
existence  in  potentiality. 

Note  5,  p.  59.  Now  reality  is,  in  the  twofold  significa- 
tion, <kc.]  These  two  terms,  which,  as  has  been  said,  per- 
vade and  illustrate  Aristotle's  philosophical  writings,  are, 
themselves  illustrated,  as  it  were,  here,  \inder  the  forms  of 
sleep  and  watching — the  one,  being  the  analogue  of  poten- 
tiality, and  the  latter,  of  reality — and  thus  knowledge, 


246  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

although  possessed,  yet,  if  not  exercised,  is  only  in 
potentiality ;  but  when  actually  exercised,  it  is  raised 
up  and  converted  into  reality.  It  is  not  easy,  without 
periphrasis,  to  fix  upon  an  apposite  term  for  the  cVf"/- 
yopa-i^,  which  signifies,  of  course,  a  state  the  opposite  to 
sleep — watching,  adopted  here,  and  the  French  reveil  seem 
to  imply  a  forced  condition ;  and  "  being  awake"  is  hardly 
definite  enough. 

Note  6,  p.  59.  Only  this  is  to  be  understood  of  a  body 
which  may  be  organised,  &c.]  Organs  are  instruments 
subservient  to  the  purposes  of  the  living  body,  as  the 
living  body  is  subservient  to  the  Vital  Principle,  and 
Vital  Principle,  in  its  turn,  subservient  to  nature's  design 
in  creation.  So  that  even  plants,  although  insentient, 
have  organs,  but  organs  which,  in  contradistinction  to 
those  of  animals,  are  homogeneous ;  as  the  leaf  is  said  to 
be  formative  of  all  the  parts  of  the  fruit.  Aristotle1 
distinguished  the  parts  of  animals,  as  is  known,  as  homo- 
geneous (da-vvde-ra),  that  is  simple  or  of  one  nature, 
as  flesh,  bone  and  sinew,  and  compound  (a-vv6era)}  as  hand, 
foot,  &c.,  which  are  made  up  of  different  or  unlike  parts. 
Thus,  all  the  parts  which  are  heterogeneous  or  unlike,  are 
made  up  of  parts  which  are  homogeneous  or  like,  as  a  hand, 
for  example,  is  made  up  of  Jlesh,  tendons  and  bones ; 
while  the  parts  of  plants,  on  the  contrary,  are  but 
developments  of  one  simple  part,  that  is  the  leaf.  It  is 
manifest  that  Aristotle  here  points,  suggestively,  to  the 
1  Hist.  Animalm,  I.  r.  3. 


CH.  I.]  NOTES.  247 

development  of  organs  by  their  own  innate  powers,  and 
thus  he  may  be  said  to  have  originated  a  doctrine  which 
has  been  adopted,  and,  perhaps,  realised  as  homologous 
physiology,  by  modern  science.  Goethe1,  before  the 
present  century,  had  observed  that  "  whoever  looks  even 
casually  at  the  growth  of  plants,  cannot  but  perceive 
that  certain  outward  parts  often  change,  and  sometimes 
assume  wholly,  at  other  times,  partially,  the  form  of  parts 
lying  next  to  them.  The  secret  affinity  between  the 
different  outward  parts  of  plants,  as  leaves,  calix,  corolla, 
stamen,  which  are  naturally  developed  out  of  one  another, 
has  been  long  known  ;  and  this  process,  whereby  one  and 
the  same  organ  is  seen  to  undergo  manifold  changes, 
has  been  designated  Metamorphosis  of  Plants"  The 
pericarp  is,  of  course,  the  seed-vessel,  the  covering,  that 
is,  of  the  seed,  (as  the  pod  of  leguminosa,  the  hairy 
covering  of  the  chestnut,  or  the  pulpy  coat  of  fruit,)  and 
the  germinal  part  of  seeds  is  by  Aristotle2  compared  to 
the  prolific  end  of  the  egg  which  is  attached  to  the 
oviduct,  (rrj  vff-rfpa,)  as  the  seed  is  to  pods,  husks,  or  other 
forms.  The  seed  and  fruit  are  well  said  to  be  analogous 
to  an  animal  body  in  its  state  of  potentiality,  (which  may 
be  likened  to  a  state  of  hybernation,)  as  ages  may  pass 
away  without  extinguishing  that  latent  existence  which, 
under  favourable  conditions,  being  resuscitated,  can  re- 
sume the  actions  of  life. 

1  Goethe,  Einleitung  zur  Metamvrph.  der  Pflangen. 
8  De  General,  n.  i. 


248  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

Note  7,  p.  59.  And  the  roots  are  analogous  to  tJie 
mouth,  &c.]  This  is  one  of  those  suggestive  allusions 
which  characterise  Aristotle's  writings,  and  seem  to  have 
anticipated  knowledge  that  was  yet  to  be  realised ;  for 
had  it  been  worked  out,  science  might  long  since  have 
been  in  possession  of  the  doctrine  of  homology.  The 
passage  shews  that  Aristotle  had  perceived  that  parts 
might  be  designated  after  their  functions  rather  than 
their  forms,  for  it  is  the  same  process  in  plants,  he 
observes1,  only  they  take  in  food  by  their  roots,  out  of 
the  earth,  already  concocted,  and  hence  they  have  no 
excrementitious  matter ;  as  for  them,  the  soil  and  its 
warmth  are  as  a  stomach,  while  animals  have  within 
them  a  soil,  that  is  a  stomach,  from  which  they  draw 
nutrition,  as  plants  do  from  the  earth,  until  digestion 
have  been  completed." 

Note  8,  p.  60.  It  is,  therefore,  to  no  purpose.]  An 
exemplification  of  matter  and  form,  as  body  and  Vital 
Principle,  by  the  analogy  of  wax  and  the  impress  or  form 
given  to  it  by  the  seal ;  for  these  may  typify  a  reality,  as 
a  statue  may  typify  a  reality  in  the  form  given  to  the 
marble. 

Note  9,  p.  60.  It  has  thus  then  been  explained]  This 
is  a  wider  and  closer  exemplification  than  had  been  given, 
both  of  the  nature  and  influence  of  Vital  Principle  as 
the  essence  in  living  bodies — for  it  is  to  the  living  body, 

according  to  this  analogy,  what  the  special  property  is  to 
t 

1  De  Part.  Animalm.  n.  3. 


CH.  I.]  NOTES.  249 

the  instrument.  Thus,  vision  is  the  essence  of  an  eye,  as 
cutting  is  that  of  an  axe,  for,  could  the  organ  or  instru- 
ment be  deprived  of  those  faculties,  they  would  no  longer, 
save  in  name,  be  eye  or  axe ;  and  this  holds  good  of  the 
living  body,  which,  if  deprived  of  its  essence,  its  Vital 
Principle  that  is,  being  no  longer  able  to  fulfil  its 
purposes  in  creation,  is  not  to  be  regarded,  save  in  name, 
as  an  organised  body. 

Note  10,  p  61.  It  is  then  obvious  that  neither  Vital 
Principle,  <fec.]  There  is  an  apparent  contradiction  in  this 
passage,  owing  to  the  want  of  completeness  in  the  argu- 
ment— the  Vital  Principle,  as  the  essence,  cannot  be 
distinct  from  the  organs  of  the  body,  since  they  depend 
upon  it  for  their  functions ;  but  the  mind,  being  im- 
passive, (dira6tj<:  o  i/oiJ<;,)  and  the  cause  of  all  the  higher 
faculties,  may  exist  apart  from  all  which  is  corporeal  and 
even  sentient,  and  thus  survive  the  body's  death  and 
decay.  Thus,  Aristotle  has  elsewhere  observed  that  it  is 
scarcely  possible  for  anything  to  be  of  higher  value  or 
more  influential  than  the  Vital  Principle,  and  quite 
impossible  that  anything  should  be  more  so  than  the 
mind. 

Note  11,  p.  61.  It  is  doubtful,  however,  whether,  <fec.] 
Whether,  that  is,  the  Vital  Principle  is  separable  from 
the  body,  as  the  mariner  is  from  his  vessel — whether, 
as  he  is  not  necessarily  involved  in  its-  wreck,  so  it 
may  survive  the  death  of  the  body.  But  the  question 
evidently  pertains  to  psychology,  and  can  scarcely  be 


250  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

entertained  amid  inquiries  into  corporeal  functions  and 
sympathies ;  and  the  chief  object  of  this  treatise,  is  to 
ascertain  what  that  principle  is  which,  for  a  stated  time, 
animates  and  presides  over  the  functions  of  reproduction, 
nutrition,  growth  and  decay.  It  is  evident,  besides,  that 
Aristotle  has  annexed,  so  to  say,  this  high  privilege  to  the 
mind,  as  the  seat  and  source  of  all  moral  and  intellectual 
qualities  and  faculties. 


CHAPTER  II. 

Note  1,  p.  64.  It  is  not  only  correct  that  the  ivord- 
ing,  &c.]  Aristotle1  makes  a  definition  to  be  a  term 
significant  of  what  a  thing  essentially  is,  and,  thus  a  defi- 
nition may  be  employed  in  place  of  nouns,  or  one  defini- 
tion for  another;  but  a  noun  cannot  be  accepted  as  an 
adequate  definition,  since  every  definition  ought  to  involve 
some  kind  of  cause.  It  is  an  expression2,  in  fact,  which  so 
explains  any  term  as  to  distinguish  it  from  all  else,  as  a 
boundary  line  separates  fields.  Aristotle,  again,  makes  it 
to  be  something  laid  down  (dea-is  fnev  eV-n)  as  the  arithme- 
tician lays  down  the  unit  as  indivisible,  quantitatively 
considered;  and  yet  this  is  no  hypothesis,  since  the  unit, 

1  Topica,  I.  5.  i.  Analyt.  6.  1.2.  7. 
a  Trendel.  Comment. 


CH.  II.]  NOTES.  251 

in  itself,  is  not  the  same  as  the  unit  in  relation — that  is 
in  combination.  The  conclusion  is  the  close  of  a  syllogism, 
and  to  be  distinguished  from  description  which  proceeds 
from  particulars,  and  from  definition  which  is  a  summary 
derived  from  universals.  The  distinction  between  these 
terms  is  exemplified  in  the  text  by  a  geometrical  figure — 
if  we  say  that  the  "  quadrature  is  that  by  which  a  rect- 
angle with  unequal  sides  is  reduced  to  a  square,  this  is  a 
definition  but  a  definition  bordering  on  description,  as  it 
gives  no  account  of  how  the  operation  is  to  be  performed, 
or  whether  it  can  be  performed  at  all;"  and  if  we  say  that 
"  the  quadrature  is  the  finding  of  a  mean  proportional, 
the  definition  partakes  of  the  character  of  an  explanation 
rather  than  a  description ;"  for  if  there  be  found  "  a  mean 
proportional  between  any  two  lines  which  make  a  rect- 
angular figure,  that  proportional  is  the  side  of  the  required 
square." 

Note  2,  p.  64.  We  say . . .  that  the  animate,  &c.]  Nu- 
trition, or  the  faculty  by  which  matter  can  identify  other 
matter  with  itself  and  thereby  develop  and  grow  is  the 
rudimental  principle  of  life,  and  the  distinction  between 
living  and  inert  matter;  for  inert  unlike  living  matter, 
increases  in  bulk,  not  through  its  own  agency  but,  only 
by  the  casual  agglomeration  of  external  particles.  This 
was  assumed  to  be  the  sole  faculty  of  plants,  as  Touch  was 
supposed  to  be  the  first  and  the  only  sense  necessary  to 
animal  existence ;  but  it  may  be  questioned  whether 
nutrition  and  Touch  are  ever  thus  found  as  isolated  and 


252  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

independent  faculties.  Cuvier  *  also  looked  upon  nutrition 
as  the  characteristic  property  of  living  matter;  for  life 
consists,  he  observes,  in  the  faculty  possessed  by  certain 
corporeal  combinations  of  enduring  for  a  time  under  some 
determinate  form,  of  drawing  incessantly  into  their  com- 
position portions  of  surrounding  substances,  and  of  giving 
back  to  the  elements  portions  of  their  own  substance." 

Note  3,  p.  66.  With  respect  to  some  oftJwse  faculties, 
&c.]  It  is  the  purport  of  this  passage  to  shew  that,  by 
experiment  and  observation,  we  may  obtain  an  insight 
into  the  organs  and  functions  of  the  body;  but  that,  as 
the  mental  faculties  do  not  admit  of  being  so  scrutinized, 
the  investigation  of  them  is,  necessarily,  obscure  and  com- 
plicated. The  distinction  between  sentient  properties  and 
mental  faculties  is  further  exemplified  by  the  lower  forms 
of  animal  existence,  which  continue  to  live,  after  having 
been  divided,  in  each  of  the  parts;  and  as  each  part  has 
locomotion  and  manifests  feeling,  it  is  assumed  that  it 
must  also  have  imagination  (instinct  T)  and  desire.  But 
nothing  at  all  resembling  this  can  be  predicated  of  the 
mind,  since,  being  indiscerptible,  it  is  without  parts,  and, 
so  constituted,  it  cannot  be  subject  to  the  change  or  disso- 
lution of  the  body. 

Note  4,  p.  67.  But  something  very  like  this  has  taken 
place,  &c.]  Aristotle 2  is  everywhere  consistent  with  what 
is  advanced  here — for  an  animal  is  defined  by  him  as  a 

1  Rdgne  A  nimal,  T.  i.  1 1 . 
*  De  Part.  n.  8.  i. 


CH.  II.]  NOTES.  253 

being  furnished  with  senses,  and,  above  all,  with  that 
which  first  is  manifested — the  Touch ;  and,  elsewhere ',  he 
says,  that  every  animal,  as  such,  must  have  some  one  sense, 
since  it  is  by  sensibility  that  we  distinguish  what  is  from 
what  is  not  an  animal.  "It  is  further  suggested  that 
animals  may  be  distinguished,  grouped  that  is,  after 
sentient  and  reasoning  faculties,  and  that  Zoology  may 
thus  be  founded  on  universal  and  demonstrable  principles. 

Note  5,  p.  67.  As  that  by  which  we  live  and  feel.}  As 
life,  that  is,  implies  a  body  and  living  principle,  so  know- 
ledge implies  faculties  and  mind;  and  health  the  liability 
to  sickness ;  but  as  Vital  Principle  is  said  to  be  the  cause 
of  life  and  feeling,  it  is,  as  such,  a  creative  energy,  and 
cannot,  therefore,  be  matter  and  subject.  It  cannot,  that 
is,  be  a  mere  faculty  or  function,  or  be  subject  to  what  is 
termed  sickness. 

Note  6,  p.  68.  On  which  account  it  is  happily  assumed, 
&c.]  This  is  a  summary  of  what  had  been  said  concerning 
that  something,  whatever  it  be,  which  constitutes  a  living 
body  and  distinguishes  it  from  inert  or  inanimate  matter ; 
and,  although  very  indefinite,  it  still  is  all  which  can  be 
said  concerning  it.  Aristotle  guards  against  the  assump- 
tion, as  Vital  Principle  requires  for  its  manifestation 
peculiar  matter  and  exact  relation,  that  it  may  animate 
any  kind  of  body,  and  thus  the  argument  reverts  to  living 
matter  and  its  capability  of  organism,  as  the  germ,  so  to 
say,  of  animal  existence.  This  necessary  relation  between 
1  De  Senxu  ct  Sens.  I.  6.  7. 


254  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

the  matter  and  principle  is  then  advanced  to  refute  the 
doctrine  of  metempsychosis  maintained  by  the  followers 
of  Pythagoras ;  as  the  active  and  passive,  the  agent  and 
subject,  cannot  possibly  be  mere  casual  associations.  The 
subject  is  further  exemplified,  in  the  closing  paragraphs, 
by  those  two  conditions  which  pervade  all  Aristotle's 
writings — the  body  while  yet  in  potentiality  is,  by  the 
Vital  Principle,  realised,  converted,  that  is  into  reality ; 
for  Vital  Principle  can  act  only  upon  what  is  in  poten- 
tiality, and  capable,  under  its  influence,  with  form,  of 
becoming  a  specific  creature. 


CHAPTER  III. 

Note  1,  p.  71.  And  all  animals,  without  exception, 
have  the  sense  of  Touch,  &c.]  Aristotle,  having  observed 
that  plants  have  only  the  function  of  nutrition,  that  is, 
are  not  sentient,  proceeds  to  the  first  and,  therefore,  most 
universal  of  the  senses — that  which  may,  as  he  assumed, 
be  present  without  any  other,  although  there  can  be  no 
other  without  it.  Thus,  the  Touch,  as  perceptive  of  food, 
was  supposed  to  be  subservient  to  the  appetite,  and  the 
Taste,  as  discriminating,  by  tangible  qualities,  what  in 
food  may  be  genial  or  otherwise,  was  held  to  be  a  modi- 
fication of  the  Touch ;  but  the  Touch  alone  was  by 
Aristotle  regarded  as  distinctive  of  animal  in  contrast 


CH.  III.]  NOTES.  255 

with  vegetable  existence.  "  According  to  the  argument1, 
he  adds,  by  which  appetite  is  said  to  be  the  mediate  cause 
of  motion,  there  must,  in  living  animal  bodies,  be  some 
such  medium ;  and  the  being,  therefore,  which  by  its 
nature  is  incapable  of  motion,  is  impressionable  by 
appetite,  through  some  other  faculty."  Plants,  that  is, 
are  not  affected  by  the  appetitive  stimulus  as  are 
animals. 

Note  2,  p.  72.  As,  however,  we  shall  be  more  explicit, 
<fcc.]  The  Touch  being  the  earliest,  so  to  say,  of  the 
senses  and  distinctive  of  animal  existence,  is  here  held  to 
be  the  cause  of  appetite,  as  appetite  is  of  motion ;  and 
as  has  been  observed,  the  Touch  was  supposed  to  exist 
independently  of  the  other  senses.  This  sense  is  said  to 
be  especially  discriminative  of  food,  as  animals  are 
nourished  by  substances  which  are  hot  and  cold,  dry 
and  moist,  and  these  qualities  are  subject  to  it ;  but  it 
can  distinguish  only  by  chance  such  other  properties 
(odour,  colour,  sound,  for  instance)  as  do  not  contribute  to 
nutrition.  It  is  not  easy  to  attach  a  definite  notion  to 
the  imagination  here  alluded  to,  but  as  Aristotle  has 
elsewhere  distinguished  the  rational  from  the  sentient 
imagination,  and  as  instinct  only  can  be  assigned  to 
creatures  with  one  sense,  it  may  be  assumed  that  this  is 
its  meaning. 

Note  3,  p.  72.  It  is  clear,  then,  that  there  can  be  but 
one,  &c.]  The  triangle8  forms  all  rectilineal  figures, 
1  De  Matu  An.  10.  i.  *  Saint  ffilaire. 


256  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

which  have  more  than  three  sides,  that  is,  "  all  such 
figures  may  be  divided  into  triangles,  as  the  square  into 
two,  the  pentagon  into  three,  the  hexagon  into  four,  &c. ; 
and  geometry  has,  since  that  age,  reduced  this  to  a  special 
theorem." 

Note  4,  p.  73.  Thus,  tJte  inquiry  must,  <fec.]  The 
conclusion  here  arrived  at  enforces  the  necessity  of 
attention  to  individual  existences,  in  order  to  ascertain 
what  may  be  the  distinction,  if  such  there  be,  between 
Vital  Principles ;  so  that  the  question  reverts  to  former 
speculations,  whether  or  not  there  is  but  one  Principle 
variously  imparted,  or  whether  rather,  each  genus  of  being 
has  its  own  special  cause  of  vitality  and  motion.  It  belongs, 
also,  perhaps,  to  the  same  speculation,  to  ascertain  why 
beings  have  been  ranged  in  a  series — why,  that  is,  such 
manifold  gradations  of  existence  from  man  down  to  the 
zoophyte ;  unless,  indeed,  with  other  conditions  of  similar 
character,  it  is  beyond  the  pale  of  human  inquiry. 

Note  5,  p.  73.  But  to  such  as  possess  some  one  only  of 
tJie  faculties,  &c.]  It  is  far  from  easy  to  fix  upon  the  exact 
equivalents  of  the  original  terms  (XoyMr/tov,  3«a'i/oia,  ^ai/ra- 
<r('a,)  which  have  been  here  rendered  by  calculation,  judg- 
ment and  imagination;  but  the  speculative  intellect,  (0e«- 
ptlTiKo*:  vovs,')  implies  it  may  "be  assumed"  the  human 
mind  or  understanding,  which  was  said  to  be  impassive, 
homogeneous,  and  distinct  from  all  else.  It  might  well, 
therefore,  be  regarded  as  foreign  to  an  inquiry,  the 
purport  of  which  is  to  detect  the  animating  principle 


CH.  IV.]  NOTES.  257 

of  bodies  fitted  for  receiving  its  influences.  It  is  some- 
what strange  that  Aristotle,  whose  teaching  was  so 
didactic,  should  nowhere  have  given  a  definition  of  that 
principle  or  being,  to  which  he  has  assigned  so  exalted  a 
destiny. 


CHAPTER  IV. 

Note  1,  p.  77.  But  since  such  beings  cannot,  <fec.] 
The  purport  of  this  passage  is  almost  too  obvious  for 
comment,  embodying  the  great  fact  of  the  perpetuation 
of  the  species,  and  compensation,  by  reproduction,  for  the 
death  of  the  individuals  ;  and  number  refers,  of  course,  to 
individuals,  species  to  the  aggregate. 

Note  2,  p.  78.  The  term  final  cause,  &c.]  This  is  a 
kind  of  parenthetical  clause,  intended  merely  to  guard 
against  the  supposition  that  the  fact  of  some  animals 
having  a  fixed  habitat,  not  being  locomotive  that  is,  was 
unknown,  or  had  escaped  notice. 

Note  3,  p.  78.  And  this  applies  equally  to  growth  and 
decay.]  Aristotle1  perceived,  although  it  may  be  in- 
distinctly, that  the  source  of  nutrition  is  through  the 
blood — he  perceived,  that  is,  that  "  the  blood  is  replenished 
by  vessels,  which  arise  on  and  are  spread  over  the  mesen- 
tery, and  which  empty  themselves  into  the  cava  and  the 
1  De  Part.  Animalm,  IV.  3.  4. 

17 


258  NOTES.  [UK.  n. 

aorta;"  the  anatomy  is,  no  doubt,  imperfect,  but  it  still 
is  an  outline  of  the  knowledge  of  the  lacteals.  It  seems 
to  shew  that  veins  gather  fluid  from  the  intestines,  and 
convey  it  to  the  large  blood  vessels ;  but  there  was  no 
analogous  knowledge,  in  that  age,  whereby  the  process  of 
decay  that  is  absorption  could  be  accounted  for.  The 
term  decay,  therefore,  was  the  mere  expression  for  a 
general  fact. 

The  objection  to  the  terms  "  upwards  and  downwards," 
used  by  Empedocles  to  delineate  the  growth  of  plants, 
suggests  the  advantage  that  would  accrue  to  science,  if  its 
terms  were  made  sufficiently  precise  to  fix,  beyond  doubt, 
the  several  relations  and  positions  of  the  same  body,  or 
all  bodies.  And  in  the  analogy  between  the  heads  of 
animals  and  roots  of  trees,  we  cannot  but  perceive  the 
outline  of  a  doctrine  which  has  been  developed,  by  modern 
science,  into  homologous  physiology. 

Note  4,  p.  79.  The  nature  of  fire  seems  to  some 
philosophers,  &c.]  This  is  an  argument,  drawn  from  the 
agency  of  fire,  to  dispi-ove  the  then  prevailing  opinion, 
that,  as  it  alone  of  the  elements  appears  to  be  nourished 
and  to  grow,  it  may  be  the  source  of  life  and  the  origin 
of  living  actions ;  as  they  are  shewn,  by  the  contrast 
between  living  and  igneous  properties,  to  be  essentially 
distinct  from  one  another.  The  opinion  may  have 
originated  from  the  fact  that  heat  accompanies  digestion, 
and  as  fire  was  by  some  held  to  be  the  first  element,  it 
was  readily  supposed  to  be  the  agent  in  that  process.  As 


CH.  IV.]  NOTES.  259 

an  illustration  of  this  opinion,  it  was  maintained,  even  by 
Aristotle l,  that  "  food,  taken  into  its  appointed  receptacles, 
is  vaporised  and  transmitted  to  the  veins,  in  which, 
undergoing  change,  it  is  converted  into  blood,  and  car- 
ried onward  to  the  heart." 

Note  5,  p.  81.  T/tere  are  here  three  things,  <fec.]  The 
meaning  of  this  passage,  apart  from  its  scientific  wording, 
is  sufficiently  obvious — that  which  nourishes  is  food  when 
digested;  for  food  both  acts  and  is  acted  upon  by  the 
body,  and,  when  so  acted  upon,  it  is  assimilated  to  and 
incorporated  with  its  substance,  through  the  blood.  But 
food,  being  dead,  is  contrary  to  the  living  matter,  which 
has,  however,  power  to  convert  it  into  like,  to  assimilate 
it,  that  is,  to  the  living  system.  Thus,  food,  in  its  first 
state,  is  contrary  to  or  unlike,  and  in  its  last,  or  concocted 
state,  it  is  like  the  body ;  and,  therefore,  the  same  element 
is  in  one  sense  contrary,  and  in  another  sense  like,  acting 
upon  a  contrary  or  like.  So  too  the  rudder,  which  directs 
the  vessel,  represents  the  stomach,  which  converts  the 
food  into  nourishment  for  the  body;  and  the  sensibility, 
which  gives  power  to  the  stomach,  represents  the  hand 
which,  through  the  rudder,  directs  the  motion  of  the 
vessel ;  and  the  vessel  is  analogous  to  the  body  which 
is  nourished. 

1  De  Somno,  3.  3. 


17- 


260  NOTES.  [BK.  ir. 


CHAPTER  V. 

Note  1,  p.  84.  In  our  treatises  upon  action  and  im- 
pression, &c.]  Some  commentators  have,  in  the  treatises 
here  alluded  to,  seen  only  a  reference  to  other  disquisitions, 
as  those  upon  "  '  reproduction  and  destruction,'  or  decay," 
•7rfp\  yei/co-coK  KU\  <j)0opd<: ;  but  as  the  passages  which  are 
cited  do  not  meet  the  whole  question,  it  has  been  suggested 
by  Trendelenberg  that  the  allusion  may  be  to  some  other 
work  which  has  not  come  down  to  us. 

Note  2,  p.  84.  It  is  difficult  to  understand,  &c.]  In 
another  chapter  of  this  treatise,  Aristotle  has  alluded  to 
the  power  possessed  by  the  senses  of  recalling  former 
impressions  ;  of  realizing  images  at  will,  that  is,  without 
external  objects.  But  the  question  here  is  to  learn  why 
the  senses,  which  were  supposed  to  be  derived  from  the 
elements,  from  which  or  the  accidents  of  which  sensation 
itself  was  derived,  are  not  in  constant  activity.  The 
answer  is,  that  the  normal  state,  so  to  say,  of  the  sensi- 
bility is  potentiality,  and  that  it  is  insusceptible,  there- 
fore, of  perception,  without  impression  by  something 
from  without  to  call  it  into  action ;  just  as  the  combustible 
material  requires,  in  order  to  burn,  the  agency  of  fire. 
But  the  comparison  contains  a  converse  proposition,  as 
while  the  material  is  required  for  the  sensibility,  it  \sfire, 


CH.  V.]  NOTES.  261 

which  may  be  regarded  as  the  sensibility,  which  is  required 
for  the  material. 

Note  3,  p.  84.  Since  we  speak  of  sentient  perception, 
&c.]  These  passages  upon  perception  aud  sensation,  which, 
in  themselves,  when  deeply  inquired  into,  are  sufficiently 
obscure,  are  still  less,  if  possible,  apprehensible,  on  account 
of  the  wording  and  the  attempted  illustration  by  the 
leading  terms,  potentiality  and  reality.  It  is  obvious, 
however,  that  we  may  and  do  speak  of  an  individual  as 
one  who  hears  and  sees,  whether  or  not,  at  the  moment, 
conscious  of  sound  or  colour ;  whether  that  is,  awake  or 
asleep,  active  or  quiescent,  in  potentiality  or  reality. 
But  an  individual  is,  strictly  speaking,  only  then  seeing 
and  hearing  when  he  is  actually  sensible  of  colours  and 
sounds ;  just  as  an  individual,  to  use  Aristotle's  analogy, 
is  only  then  to  be  accounted  really  learned,  when  actually 
reflecting  upon  and  exercising  some  one  special  subject  of 
knowledge.  All  attempts,  however,  to  scrutinize  the  in- 
timate operations,  so  to  speak,  of  the  sensibility  under 
impression  from  without  or  excitation  from  within  soon 
lose,  even  with  the  advanced  knowledge  of  this  age,  the 
character  of  inductive  science,  and  are  lost,  as  in  the 
text,  in  the  maze  of  metaphysical  abstractions.  It  seems 
to  be  the  object  of  the  argument  to  prove,  that  the  sensi- 
bility, before  being  acted  upon  by  external  objects,  such  as 
light,  sound,  colour,  <fec.,  exists  in  potentiality  and  is  unlike; 
when  acted  upon,  it  is  raised  to  the  state  of  reality,  and 
thus  made  like  to  that  by  which  the  impression  is  made. 


262  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

Note  4,  p.  85.  Before  proceeding  further  let  us,  &c.] 
Tliis  and  the  following  passages  are  but  repetitions  of 
what  had  been  said,  and  further  attempts  at  elucidation ; 
they  all  too  depend  for  a  meaning  upon  the  two  great 
leading  terms.  For  motion  is  in  a  two-fold  state — when 
generated  by  impulse  from  without  it  is  passive,  when 
self-generated  it  is  active ;  and  that  may  be  regarded 
as  potential,  this  as  real.  Thus,  if  a  body  be  at  rest, 
l>efore  being  impelled,  the  agent,  by  which  it  is  im- 
pelled, is  unlike  and  active;  but,  when  so  moved,  it  is, 
by  the  very  act  of  motion,  made  active,  and  like  to  the 
agent. 

Note  5,  p.  85.  But  we  must  draw  a  distinction,  &c.] 
These  passages  embody,  in  examples,  the  two  terms  so 
often  alluded  to,  and  exhibit  the  opposite  conditions  of 
human  beings — every  man  is  learned,  potentially,  because 
man  is  naturally  so  constituted  as  to  be  able  to  become 
learned,  or,  being  learned,  is  subject  to  an  eclipse  of  his 
learning  by  sleep,  or  disease,  or  inattention;  and  every 
man,  endowed  with  the  faculties  of  his  nature,  may 
acquire  some  one  branch  of  learning,  and,  when  there  is 
no  impediment  to  his  doing  so,  by  the  exercise  of  that 
knowledge,  become  learned  in  reality. 

The  individual  who  is  learned  in  the  first  sense  cannot, 
without  a  succession  of  changes,  (while  passing,  that  is, 
from  ignorance  to  knowledge),  become,  at  will,  learned,  in 
reality ;  and  he  can,  therefore,  be  accounted  learned,  only 
in  potentiality. 


CH.  V.]  NOTES.  263 

Note  6,  p.  86.  The  term  impression,  <fec.]  The  same 
mode  of  illustration,  through  those  two  terms,  is  still 
continued — impression  may  be  to  an  extent  to  destroy 
sensibility,  and  obliterate,  of  course,  sensation,  or  it  may 
be  to  that  genial  extent  which  raises,  so  to  say,  potentiality 
to  reality,  and  renders  the  being  conscious  of  external 
objects.  So  an  individual,  with  knowledge  yet  potential, 
that  is,  possessed  but  not  exercised,  can,  by  reflecting 
upon  it,  without  any  change  being  wrought,  render  it 
a  reality ;  for  the  possession  of  knowledge,  like  the  endow- 
ment of  sensibility,  implies  the  self-same  two-fold  condi- 
tion. Thus,  the  state  of  reflection  is  to  acquired 
knowledge  what  external  impressions  are  to  sensibility  ; 
for,  in  either  case,  the  agencies,  when  genial,  occasion  the 
transition  from  potentiality  to  reality ;  and  so  eliminate 
practical  knowledge  or  perfect  consciousness. 

Note  7,  p.  87.  Thefrrst  change,  however,  of  this  kind, 
&c.]  It  is  not  easy  to  perceive  how  this  nascent  condition 
can  be  a  change,  unless  the  first  germ  of  being  may  be 
so  regarded ;  and,  indeed,  it  may  be  supposed,  from  the 
first  moment,  to  have  already,  in  potentiality,  the  powers 
which  are  yet  to  be  developed.  It  may  be,  too,  that  this 
mysterious  entity,  along  with  the  faculties  and  powers  of 
its  own  nature,  may  involve  the  idiosyncrasy  of  the 
parent,  for  good  or  for  ill ;  which  was  indeed  exemplified 
in  the  life  and  death  of  the  philosophical  Montaigne1. 

1  T.  n.  chap.  37. 


264  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

This  capacity  of  the  system  for  retaining  dormant  within 
it  a  something  to  be  developed,  by  iinknown  causes,  in 
time,  is  exemplified  in  the  atom  of  virus,  which,  after  an 
indefinite  period,  may,  by  mysterious  agency,  become  a 
reality  in  the  form  of  Hydrophobia.  Well  might  the 
philosopher,  when  reflecting  upon  these  incidents,  exclaim, 
"  Qui  m'eclaircera  de  ce  progres,  je  le  croirai  d'autant 
d'autres  miracles  qu'il  voudra." 

Note  8,  p.  86.  So  tliat  the  process  by  which  an  indi- 
vidual, &c.]  This  very  obscure  passage  seems  to  intimate 
that,  as  instruction  is  only  the  development  of  faculties 
pre-existing  and  in  potentiality,  it  is  not  to  be  regarded  as 
an  impression;  for  such  an  opinion  would  imply,  instead 
of  nature's  ordinary  process  (development),  a  change 
from  a  privative  state  (ignorance),  as  well  as  change  in 
habits  of  thought.  This  cannot,  however,  be  insisted 
xipon  with  much  confidence ;  the  French  version  is,  "  Done, 
ce  qui  fait  passer  1'etre  qui  est  en  puissance  a  la  realite 
parfaite,  &  1'entelechie,  en  fait  d'intelligence  et  de  pensee, 
doit  s'appeller,  non  du  nom  d'apprentissage,  mais  d'un 
tout  autre  nom." 

Note  9,  p.  87.  There  is  an  analogy  between,  &c.] 
Sensation,  that  is,  is  to  the  body  what  reflection  is  to  the 
mind,  save  that  the  one  is  produced  by  impression  from 
without,  and,  therefore,  not  subject  to  the  will,  while  the 
latter  is  the  operation  of  will  upon  internal  faculties. 
Thus,  sensation  admits  a  series  of  individual  impressions 
which  are  to  be  analyzed  and  compared  by  the  mental 


CH.  VI.]  NOTES.  265 

operation ;    and  as  the   former   becomes   the   parent   of 
inductive,  the  latter  is  the  source  of  deductive  science. 

Note  10,  p.  88.  Let  it  for  the  present  suffice,  &a]  An 
obvious  distinction  of  potentiality — a  boy  is,  potentially, 
qualified  to  be  a  general ;  that  is,  he  has,  by  nature, 
faculties  and  powers  which,  when  developed,  will  fit  him 
for  the  office  ;  and  so  is  one  who,  although  of  suitable  age, 
and  whose  faculties  and  powers  are  developed,  may  not 
yet  have  acquired  the  necessary  military  knowledge.  An 
analogous  distinction  may  be  traced  in  sentient  properties, 
but  it  is  too  evanescent  for  precise  description;  and  the 
closing  paragraph  is  a  kind  of  summary  of  the  conversion 
of  the  potential  and  unlike  into  the  real  and  like. 


CHAPTER  VL 

Note  1,  p.  90.  The  Touch  indeed,  &c.]  This  sense 
has  a  wider  range  of  perception  than  any  other — that  is, 
it  is  not  restricted,  like  the  Sight,  Hearing,  and  Smell,  to  a 
definite  organism  and  one  mode  of  impression ;  and,  besides 
being  extended  over  the  body,  it  is  essential  to  animal 
existence.  The  text  makes  no  allusion  to  the  Taste,  be- 
cause this  sense  was  regarded1  as  subsidiary  to  or  a  modi- 
fication of  the  Touch.  The  special  senses  are  Sight,  Hearing, 
and  Smell ;  Taste  is  less  definite,  as  the  tongue  is  sensible 
1  De  Semu  et  Sent.  iv.  i. 


266  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

of  tangible  as  well  as  sapid  qualities ;  and  Touch  is  ex- 
tended over  the  body.  Some  properties,  however,  wliich 
are  enumerated,  are  subject  to  all  the  senses,  and,  hence, 
termed  common;  but  the  attempted  illustration  of  them 
by  "a  kind  of  motion"  (K/W/O-K  TJS)  does  not,  owing  to  its 
vagueness,  assist  in  explaining  them. 

Note  2,  p.  91.  An  object  is  said  to  be  perceived,  <fec.] 
An  example  in  illustration  of  casual  or  accidental  percep- 
tion; but  it  is  by  its  wording  so  obscure  as  to  stand  itself 
in  need  of  elucidation.  The  purport,  however,  seems  to  be, 
that  the  percipient  does  not,  by  sight,  (as  sight  distinguishes 
only  colour  and  form)  discern  what  the  white  object  really 
is ;  but  the  other  senses,  by  some  accidental  perception, 
coming  in  aid  of  the  special  sense,  may  determine  that 
the  white  object  is  a  certain  individual.  There  may 
besides,  perhaps,  be  a  covert  allusion  to  the  two-fold 
acceptation  of  the  term  accident,  which  signified  then 
as  it  does  now  both  casual  incidents  and  the  real,  or 
inalienable  properties  of  bodies ;  and  if  so,  the  passage 
may  imply  that  the  individual  is  perceived  by  chance; 
detected,  that  is,  by  a  mere  guess.  It  is  of  little  moment, 
but  the  individual  alluded  to  is  said,  by  Philoponus,  to 
have  been  a  friend  of  Aristotle's  ;  and  that  letters  which 
had  passed  between  them  were  extant  in  his  time. 


CH.  VII.]  NOTES.  267 


CHAPTER  VII. 

Note  1,  p.  93.  TJie  visible  is  colour,  &c.]  Aristotle1 
says  that  the  faculty  of  Sight  announces  to  us,  dis- 
tinguishes, that  is,  the  manifold  and  various  shades  of 
colours,  on  account  of  all  bodies  partaking  of  colour,  and 
thus  by  Sight,  especially,  we  are  able  to  perceive  common 
properties,  such  as  form,  magnitude,  motion  and  number  ; 
but  the  Hearing,  on  the  contrary,  is  perceptive  only 
of  distinctions  of  sounds  from  sonorous  bodies  and  the 
variations  of  voice  from  such  as  have  speech  2.  The  sense 
of  "  Hearing,  however,  contributes  more  than  any  other, 
since  speech  is  the  channel  for  instruction,  to  the  cultiva- 
tion of  the  understanding." 

Note  2,  p.  93.  All  colour  is  motive  of  the  diaphanous, 
&c.]  These  passages  seem  almost  to  indicate  a  presenti- 
ment of  the  modern  or  undulatory  theory  of  light,  for 
they  assume  the  existence  of  a  diaphanous,  that  is,  a 
subtle  medium  which,  by  its  motion,  is  creative  of  vision. 
So  too,  the  modern  theory  assumes  a  subtle  elastic  ethei*, 
which  has  inertia  without  gravity,  which  fills  space,  per- 
meates all  bodies,  and  admits  of  being  set  in  motion  by 
the  agitation  of  the  particles  of  ponderable  matter,  and 
which  particles,  when  set  in  motion,  communicating  a  like 
1  De  Sensu  et  Sen*.  \.  10.  2  I.  n. 


268  NOTES."  [BK.  u. 

motion  to  the  molecules  adjacent,  act  upon  others,  and 
thus  motion  is  propagated  further  and  further  in  all 
directions.  The  theory  of  Aristotle  is  much  the  same — 
there  is  a  diaphanous  medium  which  may  well  represent 
the  subtle  ether,  and  which,  when  potential,  that  is 
quiescent,  is  darkness,  and  when  set  in  motion  by  colour, 
(the  property  of  which  is  to  render  it  motive),  is  light, 
renders  objects  visible,  that  is.  Thus,  the  same  diaphaneity 
when  passive,  that  is,  potential,  is  darkness,  when  active, 
that  is,  in  reality,  is  light,  and  the  cause  of  objects  being 
visible.  The  value  of  the  hypothesis  is  diminished  by 
the  identification  of  the  "  diaphaneity"  with  air  and  water 
and  solid  bodies,  because  of  their  affinity  with  the 
supernal  region  or  firmament  above,  which,  together  with 
all  the  heavenly  bodies,  was  supposed  to  be  of  igneous1 
nature ;  and  to  be  corporeal,  circular,  and  in  constant 
motion. 

Note  3,  p.  94.  LigJit  is  the  active  state,  &c.]  The 
diaphaneity  which,  when  passive,  is  darkness,  when  set  in 
motion  and  made  active,  is  light,  is  made  visible,  that  is  ; 
and  thus  light,  being  a  mere  condition  of  the  diaphaneity, 
"is  not  a  body,  for,  were  it  so,  there  would  be  two  bodies 
in  one,  which  is  an  impossibility."  It  may  now  seem 
strange  that  Aristotle  should  have  paid  so  little  attention 
to  the  opinion  of  Empedocles*,  "  that  light  arrives  midway 
from  the  sun,  before  it  reaches  the  sight,  or  the  earth ;" 
for  although  it  differed  from  his  own,  in  regarding  the  sun 
1  Meteoroloffica,  3.  i.  2  De  Ccdo,  ?.  3. 


CH.  VII.]  NOTES.  269 

as  the  source  of  light  and  the  distinction  of  day  from 
night,  yet,  in  transmitted  light,  it  supplied  a  motor, 
which  was  required  for  the  completion  of  his  own  theory 
of  sensation  through  the  agency  of  a  medium  acted  upon 
by  impulsion. 

Note  4,  p.  95.  Now  that  which  is  without  colour,  &c.] 
The  diaphaneity,  that  is,  when  passive,  is  receptive  of 
colour  and  made  active,  just  as  the  air,  when  quite  still, 
is  more  readily  set  in  motion  and  made  sonorous  by  per- 
cussion ;  and  this  leads,  amid  some  confusion  of  thought, 
to  the  consideration  of  those  luminous  appearances  (ignes 
fatui)  which  are  visible  only  in  the  dark,  by  their  colour. 
'The  precise  nature  of  these  appearances  is  still  only 
conjectural,  notwithstanding  the  advance  of  chymistry  ; 
but  they  are  supposed  to  be  due  to  phosphyretted 
hydrogen  eliminated,  under  favouring  circumstances,  from 
decaying  animal  and  vegetable  matter,  and  ignited  by 
contact  with  the  atmosphere." 

Note  5,  p.  95.  Therefore,  witliout  light  colour  is  not 
visible.]  Colour,  that  is,  by  imparting  motion  to  the 
diaphaneity,  renders  it,  from  being  potential  and  dark, 
actual  and  visible,  that  is,  light ;  and  thus,  as  without 
light  there  is  no  colour,  so  without  colour  there  is  no 
light ;  and  this  lends  support  to  the  opinion,  that  the  air, 
as  being  a  diaphanous  medium,  is  essential  to  sight. 
Aristotle  had  indeed  maintained,  in  opposition  to 
Empedocles1  and  others,  that  vision  is  not  caused  by  the 
1  De  Sensu  et  Sens.  II.  15,  16. 


NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

emanation  of  luminous  rays  from  the  eye  as  light  proceeds 
from  a  torch  or  lamp ;  and  he  ridiculed  the  notion  that 
vision  is  precluded  in  the  dark  owing  to  the  extinction  of 
those  rays  therein.  It  is  probable  that  this  theory  first 
led  him  to  adopt  a  medium  and  its  successive  motion,  as 
the  immediate  cause  of  vision  ;  as  he  had  accounted  for 
hearing  by  the  propagation  of  the  impulse  given  to  the 
air  by  the  sonorous  body.  Aristotle  was  unacquainted 
with  the  structure  of  the  eye ;  but  he  was  aware,  of 
course,  that  it  contains  humours,  and  these  he  held  to  be 
necessary,  not  as  being  aqueous  that  is  elementary  but, 
as  being  diaphanous,  for  this  property  seemed  to  be  as 
requisite  for  vision  within  the  eye,  as  it  is  for  the  trans- 
mission of  light  to  the  eye.  It  was  this  assumed  succes- 
sion of  action,  after  impression  upon  a  diaphanous  medium, 
which  led  to  the  conclusion  that  the  eye  itself  must  be 
diaphanous,  and,  therefore,  that  the  visual  power  must  be 
somewhere  on  the  inside  of  the  eye ;  and  this  is  the  only 
approximation  to  a  right  knowledge  of  the  retina  and  its 
relations. 

Note  6,  p.  96.  It  has  thus  then  been  said,  <fcc.]  The 
cause  of  colour  being  visible  is  sufficiently  obvious  from 
what  has  been  said ;  but  fire  was  said  to  be  visible  both 
in  darkness  and  in  light,  owing  to  its  being,  as  fire,  of 
the  nature  of  the  firmament  above,  which  was  believed 
to  be  fire,  or  something  identical  with  fire.  It  may  be 
presumed  that  the  subject  was  here  introduced,  in  order 
to  notice  and  account  for  those  luminous  appearances, 


CH.  VII.]  NOTES.  271 

which  have  been  alluded  to,  and  which,  in  that  age,  could 
not  but  have  been  topics  of  wonder  and  speculation ; 
they  were  irreconcilable  besides,  with  the  prevailing 
notions  of  colour  and  light. 

Note  7,  p.  96.  The  air  is  the  medium  for  sounds,  &c.] 
The  air  was  by  Aristotle  held  to  be  essential  to  sound ; 
but  it  is  not  apparent  why  odour  was  supposed  to  be 
transmitted  by  some  modified  condition  of  air  or  water, 
unless,  indeed,  it  was  required  in  order  to  account  for  the 
perception  of  odours  by  fishes  and  aquatic  animals. 
There  was  a  difficulty,  in  fact,  in  accounting  for  the 
transmission  of  odour  through  air  and  water,  because 
odour1  was  held  to  be  a  vaporous  exhalation  eliminated 
by  fire ;  and  the  "  special  organ  of  smell  was  said  to  be 
located  about  the  brain*"  the  coldest  of  all  parts  of  the 
body,  in  order  that  the  exhalation  might  there  be  con- 
densed and  made  productive  of  smell.  Thus,  it  might 
seem  to  be  irreconcilable  with  odour,  that  it  should  be 
transmissible  in  air  or  water,  and  this  may  have  led  to 
the  hypothesis  of  a  modified  condition  of  the  elements 
for  smell. 

Note  8,  p.  97.  But  neitfter  man  nor  animals  which 
breatJte,  &c.]  The  term  in  the  text  (avairvet),  like  our 
own  term  breathing,  is  expressive  both  of  inspiration 
and  expiration,  whereas  it  is  evident  that  the  sense  of 
the  passage  requires  the  former  process  only.  And  yet 

1  De  Sensu  et  Sens.  II.  19,  20. 

2  De  Part.  Animalm,  u.  7. 


272  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

elsewhere l,  Aristotle,  in  his  criticism  of  the  theory  adopted 
by  Diogenes  and  Anaxagoras  to  account  for  the  respira- 
tion of  fishes,  has  clearly  distinguished  the  one  from  the 
other.  He  objected  also  to  Timseus  and  some  others  who 
had  maintained  that  expiration  must  precede  the  other. 
Enough,  however,  that  he  perceived,  although  unac- 
quainted with  the  parts  on  which  odours  impinge,  or  the 
organ  by  which  they  are  made  sensible,  that  they  could 
gain  access  to  the  sense  only  through  inspiration. 


CHAPTER  VIII. 

Note  1,  p.  100.  Sound  of  the  actual  kind  is  tJie,  &c.] 
As  sound  is  the  result  of  percussion,  the  passage  implies 
something  to  be  percussed,  as  well  as  something  in  which 
that  which  percusses  is  to  move ;  but  what  that  some- 
thing is  in  which  percussion  is  to  be  made  is  not  explained. 
Some  commentators,  as  Simplicius,  have  considered  the 
words  ev  TIVI  to  imply,  "  the  air  which  is  interposed 
between  the  sonorous  body  and  the  sense,"  and  which, 
but  for  the  contradictory  opinions  of  that  age  with 
respect  to  the  air,  might  be  at  once  accepted  as  its 
meaning ;  and  even  taken  as  some  special  medium,  as  has 
been  suggested,  it  still  may  signify  a,  body  of  air.  We 
1  De  Respiraticme,  2.  3. 


CH.  VIII.]  NOTES.  273 

may  consider  the  voice,  Plato1  observes,  as  percussion 
(sound,  that  is,)  transmitted,  by  the  air,  through  the  ears, 
brain  and  blood,  to  the  sentient  principle.  But  as  the 
nature  and  properties  of  the  air  were  then,  from  the 
want  of  experimental  science,  unknown,  they  were  avail- 
able for  any  hypothesis ;  and  yet  there  is  evidence  that 
Aristotle,  not  to  add  Plato,  did  regard  the  air  as  essential 
to  sound  and  voice.  Aristotle2,  while  agreeing  with  most 
philosophers  in  ranking  air  among  the  four  elements,  "sees 
a  difficulty  in  determining  what  its  nature  may  be  in  the 
universe  around  the  earth,  or  what  its  order  in  relation  to 
the  other  elements  of  bodies."  He  was  aware  of  the  air 
holding  water  in  solution,  and  observes  that,  whether 
water  be  or  be  not  produced,  equally,  from  the  whole  air, 
that  which  is  around  the  earth  must  be  not  air  only  but 
vapour,  which  is  again  to  be  condensed  and  become 
water.  Thus,  "  we  maintain,"  he  adds,  "  that  fire  and  air, 
water  and  earth  are  producible  out  of  one  another,  and 
that  each  of  them  is  present,  in  potentiality,  in  each  of 
the  others ;  as  is  the  case  with  all  bodies,  which  have 
a  base  into  which  each  of  them  is  ultimately  reducible." 
He  has  distinguished  the  air  we  inspire  from  that  which 
we  send  forth  (eWe'jUTeii/)  and  to  which  he  has  given  a 
specific  appellation  (TO  irvev^a) ;  but  owing  to  the  diffi- 
culty of  determining  either  its  nature  or  its  office, 
(although  it  is  the  subject  of  a  special3  treatise,)  no 

1  Timceus,  67  B.  a  Meteorologica,  I.  3.  3.  i. 

3  irepl  Trvev/j.a.Tos. 

IS 


274  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

unexceptionable  equivalent  for  it  can  be  offered.  These 
quotations  shew,  amid  many  suggestive  observations,  that 
knowledge  concerning  the  air  was  then  very  unsettled ; 
and  yet  they  prove,  it  may  be  assumed,  that  air  was 
implied  in  the  passage  referred  to. 

Note  2,  p.  101.  An  eclw  is  produced  w/tenever,  &c."j 
This  passage  is  obscure,  both  from  its  elliptical  wording 
and  the  want  of  adequate  exemplification ;  but,  in 
attributing  to  the  air  elasticity  and  capability  of  being 
reflected,  it  seems  to  suggest  that  the  atmosphere  only  is 
the  cause  of  sound  and,  therefore,  of  echoes.  So,  accord- 
ing to  modern  science1,  "an  echo  is  sound  reflected  from 
a  distant  surface  and  repeated  to  the  ear ;  although 
several  other  conditions  are  required  for  its  production." 
In  another  treatise2,  it  is  assumed  that  reflexion  of  the  air 
(»/'  araicA.atrtt)  is  the  immediate  cause  of  an  echo;  and 
since  an  echo  is  reflexion,  "must  there  not  be,  for  its 
production,  air  confined,  impacted  and  communicating,  as 
one  mass,  with  that  which  is  to  be  reflected?"  But  an 
echo,  whether  or  not  audible,  ought,  as  the  text  states, 
looking  at  the  properties  of  the  air,  to  be  a  constant 
occurrence ;  for  as  light  is  continually  reflected  from 
bodies,  and  thereby  casting  shadows  by  which  light 
is  distinguished,  so  sound,  owing  to  the  air's  elasticity, 
must  be  often  reflected  and,  therefore,  repeated,  in  varying 
degrees  of  intensity,  according  to  the  nature  of  the  surface 
on  which  it  may  have  impinged.  That  age,  in  fine,  wa.s 
1  Brande's  Hist,  of  Science.  a  Problemota,  XI.  8. 


CH.  VIII.]  NOTES.  275 

acquainted  with  several  of  the  properties  of  the  air,  but, 
as  they  had  not  been  tested  experimentally,  its  acquaint- 
ance with  them  was  but  conjectural,  and  could  lead  to  no 
positive  inference ;  it  was  reserved  for  modern  science  to 
ascertain  what  the  air  is,  and  what  its  properties  in  rela- 
tion to  the  world,  its  productions  and  inhabitants. 

Note  3,  p.  101.  A  void  is  rightly  said,  &c.]  It  would 
be  difficult  even  to  conjecture  what  could  have  been 
meant  by  a  void  in  that  age ;  for  although  it  had  been 
perceived1,  it  may  be  but  obscurely,  that  the  air  rises  by 
fire  (heat)  to  the  upper  regions  and  becomes  ether,  (as  in 
the  Timceus,  expiration  is  accounted  for  by  the  rising  up 
from  within  of  the  heated  breath,)  yet  it  is  not  to  be 
supposed  that  rarefaction  was  an  admitted  property  of 
the  air,  or  that  any  condition  like  rarefaction  was  implied 
in  the  void.  Aristotle*  observes,  upon  this  topic,  that, 
"according  to  some  philosophers,  a  plenum  is  a  space  or 
vessel  when  full,  and  a  vacuum  or  void  is  the  same  when 
empty,  thus  making,  as  he  says,  the  plenum  to  be  identical 
with  the  vacuum  and  space,  excepting  in  conditions  of 
relation."  In  all  this  it  is  evident  that  no  account  was  taken 
of  the  air ;  and  he  objects  to  Anaxagoras,  (who  had  shewn, 
experimentally,  that  the  air  is  substance  of  some  kind,)  that 
he  argues  against  what  had  never  been  contended  for — the 
advocates  for  a  void  maintain,  he  says,  that  it  is  a  space 
in  which  there  is  no  tangible  body,  and,  holding  every 

1  Meteoroloyica,  II.  i. 
8  Xat.  AutcuU.  iv.  6.  I. 

18—2 


276  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

thing  to  be  corporeal,  they  consider  that  only  to  be  a  void 
in  which  there  is  absolutely  nothing ;  so  that  it  can  be  to 
no  purpose  to  shew  that  the  air  is  something.  This 
epitome  shews  sufficiently  how  widely  apart  from  one 
another  are  the  antient  and  modern  significations  of  a 
void,  since  it  now  implies  such  a  rarefaction  of  the  air  as 
can  be  obtained  through  the  air-pump;  and,  as  rarefaction 
cannot  be  carried  beyond  300  times,  no  proof  can  be 
afforded  of  the  possible  existence  of  a  void.  Aristotle1 
objects  to  those  who  maintained  that  the  void  is  identical 
with  any  space  filled  with  air,  "  for,  if  the  air  be  driven 
out,  the  space  will  clearly,  he  observes,  be  a  void,  in  a 
stricter  sense  than  it  was,  since  it  will  no  longer  be  full 
of  air."  But  it  would  be  foreign  to  the  purport  of  these 
notes  to  inquire  further  into  the  opinions  of  that  age ; 
it  may  be  inferred,  however,  from  what  has  been  adduced, 
that  Aristotle,  although  he  refused  corporeity  to  the  air, 
was  not  a  very  consistent  supporter  either  of  the  plenum 
or  vacuum. 

Note  4,  p.  102.  Every  sonorous  body,  <kc.]  This 
passage  is  a  summary  of  all  that  physiology  has  now  to 
offer  upon  sound  and  hearing ;  but  although  it  might 
have  been  surmised  that  sound  is  vibration  of  the  air, 
caused  by  a  sonorous  body  and  conveyed,  by  successive 
undulations,  to  the  organ  of  hearing,  yet,  as  the  internal 
ear  was  then  unknown,  it  is  a  surprising  assumption  that 
air  must  be  contained  within  the  organ,  in  order  that  the 
1  Topica,  vn.  i.  ii. 


CH.  VIII.]  NOTES.  277 

vibration  may  be  communicated  to  the  sense.  Aristotle 
may  perhaps  have  been  led,  notwithstanding  the  unstable 
opinions  of  his  age  upon  the  air,  to  conclude  that,  as 
sound  "  is  present  in  the  air,"  air  must  be  connected  with 
the  hearing,  and,  if  so,  be  contained,  naturally,  within  its 
organ.  The  succeeding  passages  hardly  admit  of  comment, 
on  account  of  their  evident  want  of  anatomical  know- 
ledge ;  but  they  prove  that  the  tympanic  membrane  had 
been  made  out,  as  also  that  it  may  be  so  injured,  as  to 
admit  fluid  from  without  into  the  ear.  And  this  disease 
of  the  membrane  is  aptly  compared  to  ulceration  and 
consequent  opacity  of  the  eye's  membrane,  (the  cornea,) 
whereby  the  rays  of  light  are  precluded  from  entering 
the  eye  and  producing  vision. 

Note  5,  p.  102.  But  proof  is  afforded,  &c.]  This 
somewhat  puerile  experiment  is  still  extant.  It  seems 
strange  that  the  very  obvious  cause  of  this  phenomenon 
did  not  occur  to  one  who  had  surmised,  without  ana- 
tomical proof,  that  there  is  air  within  the  tympanum ;  it 
had  escaped  Aristotle,  besides,  that,  in  a  former  passage, 
he  had  made  the  air  which  is  immured  vnthin  the  ear  to 
be  immovable. 

Note  6,  p.  104.  The  voice  is  a  sound,  <fec.]  This 
passage  is  a  clear  definition  of  the  voice,  and  it  points, 
although  indistinctly,  to  the  parts  and  functions  concerned 
in  its  formation.  The  voice '  is  said  to  be  different  from 
sound,  and  speech  to  be  different  from  either;  and,  as 
1  Hist.  Animalm,  iv.  9.  r. 


278  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

speech  can  be  produced  by  no  other  part  than  the  pharynx, 
those  creatures  only  can  speak  which  have  lungs,  as  speech 
is  the  articulation  of  the  voice  by  the  tongue.  Where- 
fore, the  voice  and  larynx  send  forth  vowels,  the  tongue 
and  lips  consonants,  and  these  together  make  up  speech. 
So,  too l,  Cuvier  says,  that  "  man  alone  among  animals  can 
articulate  sounds,  owing  probably  to  the  form  of  his 
mouth  and  the  mobility  of  his  lips."  The2  pharynx,  so 
called,  and  trachea,  are  of  cai*tilaginous  nature,  and  this 
because  they  are  for  the  sake  of  the  voice  as  well  as 
breathing ;  and  it  is  necessary  that  that,  which  is  to  give 
out  sound,  should  have  firmness  as  well  as  smoothness. 
But  the  larynx  and  pharynx  are  here  alluded  to  as  if 
they  were  one  and  the  same  organ,  and  it  may  be,  that 
owing  to  the  complicity  of  the  parts  and  their  multiplied 
relations  to  one  another,  they  were  then  so  considered ; 
but  yet  passages3  might  be  cited,  which  seem  to  shew  that 
they  were  known,  both  by  function  and  position,  to 
be  different  organs. 

Note  7,  p.  105.  Nature  employs,  simultaneously,  the  air, 
&c.]  It  was  assumed  by  the  physiologists  of  that  and, 
indeed,  many  subsequent  ages,  that  the  office  of  respira- 
tion is  merely  to  cool  the  blood,  or  rather  to  temper  its 
heat,  which  was  supposed  to  be  constantly  tending  to  an 
excess  incompatible  with  life.  In  modern  times,  on  the 

1  Anatomic  Comp.  t.  I.  15. 
8  De  Part,  Animalm,  vn.  3.  5. 
3  Ibid.  ii.  3.  9 ;  in.  3.  i. 


CH.  VIII.]  NOTES.  279 

contrary,  the  action  of  the  air  which  is  inspired  upon  the 
venous  blood  has  been  by  some  regarded  as  a  process  of 
combustion,  and  the  source,  through  combustion,  of  the 
special  temperature  which  characterises  all  organised  and 
living  bodies.  Respiration  is  said,  by  Grant1,  to  be 
essential  to  the  constitution  of  animal  bodies  ;  for  by  this 
function  "  the  vital  fluids  are  purified  and  replenished,  the 
muscular  system  is  furnished  with  its  capability  of  action, 
and  the  high  temperature  of  the  mammalia  is  preserved 
in  every  condition  of  the  surrounding  element." 

Note  8,  p.  106.  As  proof  of  which  we  are,  unable,  <fec.] 
The  meaning  of  this  passage,  owing  in  part  to  the 
unsettled  knowledge  of  that  age,  is  by  no  means  evident ; 
but  it  can  be  readily  admitted,  that  the  act  of  holding 
the  breath  must  set  in  motion,  disturb,  that  is,  the  air 
which  has  been  inspired,  and  produce  coughing  rather 
than  articulation.  The  French  commentator  makes  the 
text  (mvet  xai  TOVTO)  to  imply  "  disturbance  of  the 
function;"  Trendelenburg,  however,  sanctions  the  version 
here  given.  It  will  be  apparent,  from  what  has  been 
adduced,  that  the  word  pharynx  (of  fishes)  should  have 
been  larynx,  for  this,  being  the  upper  part  of  the  trachea, 
is  the  tube  which  conveys  air  to  the  lungs,  as  the  other, 
being  the  upper  part  of  the  cesophagus,  is  the  tube 
which  conveys  food  to  the  stomach ;  and  all  fishes  have  a 
pharynx,  of  course,  but,  as  they  do  not  breathe,  they  are 
without  a  larynx. 

1  Outlines,  p.  592. 


280  NOTES.  [BK.  u. 


CHAPTER  IX. 

Note  1,  p.  109.  And  there  seems  to  be  an  analogy, 
<fec.]  Aristotle  \  in  thus  making  Touch  superior  to,  and 
more  influential  than  any  other  sense,  (for  it  is  the  most 
perfect,  he  observes,  of  man's  senses,  although  with  respect 
to  some  others  he  is  inferior  to  many  animals,)  is  sup- 
ported by  Cuvier2,  who  says,  "that  Touch  is  the  most 
important  of  all  the  senses,  and  that  its  several  degrees  of 
perfection  exercise  a  surprising  influence  over  the  nature 
of  different  animals ;  and  that  of  all  the  vertebrata  man 
has  the  most  perfect  Touch."  It  is  difficult  to  attach  a 
sense  to  the  term  hard  or  soft  applied  to  flesh,  which, 
by  anatomical3  description,  corresponds  with  the  muscular 
substance  of  the  body ;  but  man  is  said  to  have  softer 
flesh  than  any  animal 4,  and  on  this  account,  through  the 
delicacy  of  his  sense  of  Touch,  to  be  of  all  creatures  the 
most  intelligent.  It  is  presumable  that  Aristotle  was  led 
to  suppose,  from  this  sense  being  spread,  so  to  say,  like 
the  muscular  substance,  over  the  surface  of  the  body,  that 
its  organ  lies  somewhere  in  or  beneath  the  flesh,  and  thus 
to  have  concluded  that  a  relative  hardness  or  density  of 
that  substance,  by  impeding  tangible  impressions,  may  be 

1  Hist.  Animalm,  I.  15.  14.  *  Anat.  Comp.  t.  ni.  569. 

3  Hist.  Animalm,  in.  16.  r.  4  De  Part.  n.  16.  16. 


CH.  IX.]  NOTES.  2S1 

the  cause  of,  or  concomitant  with  dulness  of  the  faculties. 
The  nervous  system  was  then  unknown,  and  Aristotle,  so 
fond  of  analogies,  might  readily  suppose  that  the  Touch 
had,  like  other  senses,  its  appointed  organism ;  and,  if 
there  were  such  an  organ,  that  it  is  extended  over  the 
body,  and  thus  must  be  in  or  beneath  the  flesh.  The 
Taste,  as  being  a  modification  of  Touch,  was  said  to  be 
more  delicate  in  man  than  animals. 

Note  2,  p.  110.  There  is  a  close  analogy^  A  similar 
observation  is  made  in  the  following  chapter,  and,  besides 
bringing  sentient  perceptions  under  some  general  law,  it 
was,  probably,  intended  to  shew  that  colour,  sound,  and 
odour,  although  inappreciable  by  our  senses,  may  still  be 
present.  It  shews,  in  fact,  that  our  senses,  being  limited 
in  their  capacity  of  perception,  are  not  to  be  relied  upon 
when  impressions  are  very  greatly  in  excess  or  propor- 
tionally faint. 

Note  3,  p.  111.  Tlie  smell  is  perceptive.]  "That  fishes 
smell,"  Aristotle1  observes,  "is  shewn  in  their  being  taken 
by  baits  which  have  the  particular  odour,  foul  or  grateful, 
to  which  they  are  attached."  But  modern  science  has,  of 
course,  determined  both  the  seat  and  the  structure  of  the 
olfactory  organ  in  fishes ;  and  shewn  "  how  it  is  protected 
from  the  violent  and  incessant  action  of  the  currents  of 
water  required  for  respiration."  Sanguineous*  creatures 
are  all  such  as  have  red  blood,  and  insanguineous,  those 
which,  in  place  of  red  blood,  have  a  pale  bluish  fluid 
1  Hist.  Animalm,  TV.  8.  19.  J  Ibid.  I.  4.  3. 


NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

circulating  in  their  veins.     These  last  include  "insects, 
molluscs,  Crustacea,  and  creatures  with  more  than  four 


Note  4,  pi  111.  And  htnce  Ae  dijflmlty  of  detcr- 
iMjy,  ic.]  If  the  site  amd  structure  of  the  olfactory 
sense,  in  the  lower  forms  of  life,  are  still  somewhat  con- 
jectural, it  may  well  be  supposed  that  the  smell  in  non- 
breathing  animals  was,  in  that  age,  although  seen  to  be  a 
feet,  inexplicable.  But  yet,  although  anatomy  could  not 
then  determine  the  seat  of  the  sense,  it  might  have  been 
conjectured  that,  as  such  creatures  are  obviously  affected 
by  odours,  there  must  be  some  other  inlet  for  them  than 
that  through  which  impression  is  made  upon  animals  ; 
and  the  detection  of  this  mode  of  perception,  would  have 
been  another  instance  of  homologous  physiology.  Aris- 
totle1, following  Plato,  placed  the  seat  of  the  smell  and 
other  senses  in  the  neighbourhood  of  the  heart  ;  but 
"  the  organ  was  said  to  be  located,  suitably,  between  the 
eyes." 

Note  5,  p.  1  12.  Tke  olfactory  organ  in  man,  appear* 
to  differ,  <fcc.]  The  analogy  is  obviously  faulty,  as  it 
seems  to  imply  that  the  olfactory,  like  the  respiratory 
organs,  are  furnished  with  a  cover,  by  the  raising  of  which 
odours  gain  access  to  the  sense  ;  or  rather,  owing  to  the 
intricacy  of  the  parts  and  imperfect  anatomical  know- 
ledge, the  epiglottis  has  been  associated  with  the  velum 
and  posterior  fauces.  It  could  answer  no  purpose,  then, 
1  De  Part.  Animalm,  n.  30.  9.  17. 


CH.  IX.]  NOTES.  283 

to  inquire,  as  some  have,  what  animals  have  an  operculum 
for  the  smell,  of  that  kind  ?  or  what  mean  those  veins 
and  pores?  As  although  the  operculum,  that  is,  the 
epiglottis,  was  known  to  be  protective  of  the  larynx  and, 
therefore,  the  respiratory  organs,  the  relations  of  the 
larynx  with  the  parts  associated  with  it  had  not  been 
made  out ;  and  the  veins  and  pores  refer,  probably,  to  the 
bronchi  and  vessels  within  the  chest. 

Note  6,  p.  112.  In  fine,  odour  is  derived,  <fec.]  Aris- 
totle here  differs  from  Plato,  who  held  that  odorous 
particles  are  in  a  state  rather  of  fluidity ;  and  Cuvier ' 
says,  that  "  the  organ  of  smell  is  moistened  with  abundant 
viscosity,  which  arrests  the  odorous  particles  contained  in 
air  or  water ;  as  fishes  are  sensible  of  odours.  But  odour, 
being  regarded  as  exhalation,  was  assumed  to  be  of  fiery 
nature  and,  therefore,  like  the  element,  dry,  and  this 
required,  for  the  conformity  of  the  hypothesis  of  like 
upon  like,  that  the  organ  of  the  sense,  when  in  potenti- 
ality, should  be  also  dry,  and  so,  in  due  relation  to 
odour. 

1  Anal.  Comparee,  15™*  kfon. 


284  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 


CHAPTER  X. 

Note  1,  p.  114.  Colour,  however,  is  not  thus  made 
visible.]  The  opinion  here  objected  to  originated  with 
Democritus.  Aristotle1  held  it  to  be  absurd  to  suppose 
that  colour  and  vision  could  be  a  process  of  emanation 
from  the  eyes ;  for  colour  produces  sensation,  he  observes, 
not  by  emanation  but,  by  contact,  and  so  it  is  better,  at 
once,  to  admit  that  vision  is  produced  by  the  action  of  the 
medium.  There  are2,  it  is  said,  seven  distinctions  of  colour 
and  as  many  of  savour ;  and  in  another  work 3  seven 
vowels,  seven  pleiads,  and  seven  chords. 

Note  2,  p.  114.  No  object,  however,  which  is  without 
humidity.]  This  is  little  more  than  a  repetition  of  what 
had  been  said  concerning  sapid  substances.  Aristotle4 
seems  to  have  adopted  a  theory,  derived  from  mechanics, 
for  explaining  the  solubility  of  objects — Whence  comes  it, 
he  asks,  that  an  earth  is  both  melted  and  moistened  by 
fluid  (KCLI  TtjKeTai  KOI  reyyerai)  while  soda  (TO  Be  v'npov)  is 
melted  but  not  moistened  ?  The  answer  is,  because  there 
are  pores  throughout  the  soda  which  cause  its  parts  to 
be,  at  once,  separated  by  the  fluid ;  while  the  pores  in 

1  De  Sensu  et  Sens.  3.  15.  3  De  Sensu  et  Sens.  4.  18. 

3  Metapkysica,  xm.  6.  5.  4  De  Meteorol.  iv.  9.  4. 


CH.  X.]  NOTES.  285 

the  earth  are  in  alternate  rows,  so  that  the  influence  of 
the  fluid,  in  whatever  way  it  may  gain  access,  cannot  but 
be  different. 

Note  3,  p.  114.  As  vision  is  perceptive,  &c.]  The 
argument  here  is  interrupted  and  obscured  by  parentheti- 
cal explanations;  but  the  purport  is,  that  the  senses  are 
the  sole  judges  of  sentient  impressions  through  all  their 
degrees  of  intensity,  and  that,  as  sensibility  is  a  mean, 
they  cannot  discriminate  such  as  are  far  above  or  below 
the  allotted  medial  standard.  There  is  a  seeming  discre- 
pance, however,  in  employing  the  term  invisible  as  ana- 
logous to  impossible  on  other  subjects,  as  vision  is  not 
altogether  lost  in  any  darkness;  but  a  creature  without 
feet  could  not  continue  its  existence,  nor  a  fruit  without 
the  kernel  continue  its  species. 

Note  4,  p.  115.  The  impotable  as  well  as  the  potable, 
<fec.]  The  impotable  implies,  of  course,  whatever  is  neither 
moist  nor  capable  of  becoming  moist,  and  every  such  sub- 
stance must,  necessarily,  pain — be  very  disagreeable  to,  that 
is — and  pervert  the  Taste.  All  these  passages,  however, 
while  proving  that  moisture  is  required  for  savour,  point  to 
a  want  of  knowledge  of  the  salivary  and  mucous  glands 
which  were  yet  to  be  discovered.  But  over  and  above  the 
due  conditions  of  moisture,  there  was  still  required  the 
knowledge  of  the  nervous  sysbem  to  account  for  the  many 
perversions  of  Taste  which  are  manifested,  both  in  sick 
and  well ;  and  manifested,  at  times,  without  any  apparent 
cause.  It  will  occur  to  many,  besides,  how  differently  the 


286  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

Taste  is  affected  by  the  same  substance,  as  sugar  for  in- 
stance, in  different  persons,  and  even,  at  times,  in  the 
same  person. 

Note  5,  p.  116.  Kinds  of  savour  are  like  shades  of 
colour,  &c.]  There  must  ever  be  difficulty  in  fixing 
upon  terms  for  savours  or  other  sentient  qualities,  and 
still  greater  difficulty  in  settling  what  are  the  exact 
equivalents  for  such  terms  in  another,  and  that  not 
a  cognate  tongue ;  for  although  some  savours,  as  bitter 
and  sweet,  may  be  supposed  to  have  an  universal  accep- 
tation, there  are  others  which,  being  far  less  definite, 
are  subject  to  variation,  according  to  climate  and  race. 
So  that,  with  the  exception  of  bitter  and  sweet,  it  can 
hardly  be  pretended  that  the  other  terms,  as  oily,  pungent, 
rough,  astringent,  <fec.,  are  perfect  representatives  of  those 
in  the  text. 

Note  6,  p.  116.  In  fine  tJie  sapid  sense,  &c.]  This 
passage  does  but  repeat  what  has  been  already  insisted 
upon,  that  the  sense,  in  potentiality,  that  is,  when  inactive, 
is  identical  with  that  which  is  to  act  upon  it;  but  that, 
having  been  acted  upon,  it  is  brought  into  the  state  of 
reality,  and  then  becomes  perceptive  of  the  qualities  of  the 
excitant. 


CH.  XI.]  NOTES.  287 


CHAPTER  XI. 

Note  1,  p.  118.  Each  sense  seems  to  be  perceptive, 
<tc.]  This  passage  seems  to  imply  that  all  sentient  im- 
pressions may,  in  a  strict  sense,  be  tangible  impressions. 
Aristotle1,  in  another  treatise,  observes  that  sentient 
bodies  are  bodies  sensible  of  tangible  impressions,  and  that 
tangible  impressions  only  have  contraries,  which,  in  kind, 
are  specific  and  causative.  And,  "thus,  neither  white- 
ness and  blackness,  sweetness  and  bitterness,  or  any 
other  contraries  save  those  alluded  to,  can  form  element- 
ary distinctions."  All  which  implies,  perhaps,  that  the 
Touch  is  either  the  origin  of  or  coeval  with  animal 
existence ;  and  that  the  other  senses  are  but  for  the 
higher  forms  of  being.  The  properties,  besides,  which 
are  attributed,  so  to  say,  to  the  Touch  are,  in  con- 
tradistinction to  those  of  the  organs  of  relation,  mainly 
concerned  in  the  changes  continually  going  on  in  inert 
bodies ;  and  this  consideration  may  have,  in  part,  con- 
tributed to  the  speculative  opinion  just  quoted. 

Note  2,  p.  120.  It  may  be  a  question  whether  as  all 
bodies,  <fec.]  This  is  an  argument  to  prove  that,  as  there 
cannot  be  absolute  contact  of  bodies  in  water,  so  neither 
1  De  Gen.  el  Corr.  n.  i.  i. 


288  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

can  there  be  in  air ;  and  thus  that  the  flesh  can  be  only 
the  medium  for  tangible  impressions — that  there  must 
ever  be  air  interposed,  that  is,  between  the  object  and  the 
surface  of  the  body.  It  may  seem  now  to  be  supereroga- 
tory, but,  as  the  atmosphere  had  not  then  been  experi- 
mentally investigated,  crude  and  contrary  opinions,  as 
might  be  supposed,  were  entertained  concerning  it,  and 
its  manifold  relations1.  The  term  "third  magnitude"  is 
derived  from,  or  associated  with  the  Pythagorean  doc- 
trine of  number — as  of  magnitude,  continuous  length  is 
referrible  to  one,  breadth  to  two,  and  depth  to  three  ;  and, 
thus,  depth  is  the  "  third  degree  "  of  or  relation  to 
magnitude. 

Note  3,  p.  122.  But  tangible  differ  from  visible,  &c.] 
"It  will  be  evident  that  whatever  may,  in  these  passages, 
be  erroneous,  is  traceable  to  the  flesh  being  regarded  as 
the  sense  or  the  medium  for  the  sense  of  Touch,  as,  in 
either  case,  the  Touch,  differing  from  every  other  sense, 
would,  from  what  has  been  maintained,  require  two  media. 
There  seems  to  be  something  like  forgetfulness  in  with- 
drawing, so  to  say,  the  medium  in  the  example  given  of 
tangible  impression,  and  supposing  that  the  man  and  his 
shield  can  be  simultaneously  transfixed. 

Note  4,  p.  122.      The  different  states  of  the  body  as  a 

body,  &c.]     As  the  Touch  was  regarded  as  a  primal  or 

elementary  sense,  so  the  qualities,  of  which  it  is  perceptive, 

(as  hot  and  cold,  dry  and  moist,  <fec.)  were  also  regarded 

1  Metaphysica,  IV.  13.  i. 


CH.  XI.]  NOTES.  289 

as  elementary  qualities  ;  and  distinguished  from  visual  or 
sonorous  impressions,  by  being  necessary  to  animal  exist- 
ence. It  is  uncertain  whether  the  work  "upon  the 
Elements"  here  alluded  to  was  a  distinct  work,  or  a 
chapter  in  one  of  the  treatises  which  have  been  cited ; 
but  the  question  is  of  little  consequence,  and  foreign, 
besides,  to  the  purpose  of  these  notes. 

Note  5,  p.  123.  TJie  mean,  in  fact,  is  critical,  &c.]  This 
is  a  transfer,  so  to  say,  of  moral  to  physical  relations. 
"Whatever  is  continuous  and  divisible  comprehends,"  Aris- 
totle '  says,  "  the  three  terms,  more,  less,  and  equal,  which 
all  bear  a  relation  either  to  the  thing  itself  or  to  our- 
selves ;  for  the  equal  is  a  given  mean  between  excess  and 
deficiency.  Now,  the  mean  implies  that  which  is  equi- 
distant from  either  of  the  extremes,  and  it  is  one  and  the 
same  in  all  material  conditions ;  but  the  mean,  in  relation 
to  us,  implies  a  state  in  which  there  is  neither  excess  nor 
deficiency."  Thus,  temperance  nourishes  and  preserves 
the  body,  while  excess  or  deficiency  of  food  and  drink 
tends  to  destroy  it.  Moderate  exercise  increases,  while 
immoderate  or  insufficient  exercise  impairs  the  strength  ; 
and  so  for  other  conditions  which  are  readily  adducible. 

Note  6,  p.  123.  As  vision  was  said  to  be  in  tome 
sense,  &c.]  The  passage  is  obscure,  but  it  seems  to  repeat 
a  former  observation,  that,  as  the  senses  can  judge  of  sen- 
tient properties  only  in  their  mediate  state,  the  terms 
invisible  and  intangible  are,  strictly  speaking,  incorrect 
1  Ethica  Nicom.  II.  6.  5. 

19 


290  NOTES.  [BK.  n. 

and  inapplicable.  "  The  air ',  moving  in  currents,  was  said 
to  be  wind ; "  and,  when  at  rest,  it  was  supposed,  like 
all  else,  when  either  in  excess  or  deficiency,  to  be  with- 
drawn from  sentient  perception. 


CHAPTER  XII. 

Note  1,  p.  125.  It  is  the  primal  organ,  &c.]  Philo- 
ponus  and  Simplicius,  according  to  some  commentators, 
believed  that  the  "mind"  was  the  organ  or  principle 
here  alluded  to ;  but  Saint  Hilaire  is  disposed  to  regard 
it  as  "sensibility,  irrespective  of  any  thinking  principle." 
Trendelenburg  inquires,  what  means  the  term  '  primal ' 
quid  hoc  »y>irror?  He  seems,  however,  to  consider  the 
mind  as  the  special  seat  of  the  faculty  in  question — "  quod 
primum  dicitur,  id  tacite  mentem  spectari  videtur,  quse 
propria  est  hujus  facultatis  sedes ;  et  ea  prima  quidem, 
si  ab  intimo  fonte  projidscaris."  It  may,  however,  with 
some  confidence,  be  assumed  that  this  primal  organ  points, 
suggestively,  to  the  brain ;  for  it  evidently  implies  a  cen- 
tral organ  connected  with  each  of  the  senses,  and  receptive 
of  all  sentient  impressions.  Thus,  such  an  organ,  -while 
receptive  of  form,  may  well  be  said  to  be  identical  with 
the  object ;  and  yet,  seeing  how  opposed  are  the  manifes- 

1  Jfeteoroloffica,  L  13.  2. 


CH.  XII.]  NOTES.  291 

tations  of  the  sensibility  to  the  properties  of  matter,  not 
be  so,  in  an  absolute  sense.  The  organ,  like  the  brain,  in 
fact,  being  perceptive  of  forms  and  properties  through 
the  senses,  is  identified,  pro  tanto,  with  objects ;  although 
it  cannot  but  differ  from  them  absolutely,  in  mode  of 
being,  that  is  in  essence. 

Note  2,  p.  126.  But  why  do  not  plants  feel,  &c.]  The 
answer  to  this  question,  by  assigning  to  the  organ  a  defi- 
nite locality  and  function,  seems  to  lend  support  to  the 
explanation  offered  in  the  foregoing  note.  The  passage 
in  the  original  TO  /*>/  e^eii/  /xe<roT»/Ta  is  rendered  too 
freely,  perhaps,  in  this  version,  as  mediate  faculty ;  but 
the  French  "qualite  moyenne"  is  to  the  same  purport. 
The  Latin  is,  "  neque  id  medium,  tanquam  mensuram  et 
modum  habent,  quo  sensus  quasi  judicant."  It  may  be 
that  as  Aristotle  had  refused,  so  to  say,  sensibility  to  the 
brain,  he  found  himself  constrained,  in  order  to  explain 
the  function  of  the  senses  and  their  power  of  recalling 
images,  to  adopt  a  central  organ,  to  be  as  well  the  source 
of  sensibility  as  the  sensorium  or  store-house,  for  the 
mind  and  memory.  He  had  been  led,  in  fact,  to  regard 
the  brain  as  insentient,  because  of  its  not  imparting 
sensation  when  touched,  and  as  subsidiary  to  the  respira- 
tion for  tempering  the  internal  heat,  because  of  its  appa- 
rent coldness.  All  this  was  the  settled  conviction  of  this 
great  man ;  Democritus,  however,  seems  to  have  perceived 
that  the  brain  is  either  the  organ  or  the  seat  of  sensi- 
bility, although  the  opinion  was  not  generally  admitted. 

19—2 


292  NOTES.  [BK.  u. 

Plato  agreed  with  physiologists  in  making  the  seat  of 
the  senses  to  be  the  liver  and  neighbourhood  of  the  heart, 
but  he  differed  from  Aristotle  in  believing  the  brain  to  be 
continuous  with  the  spinal  chord,  and  to  be  the  source  of 
the  intellectual  faculties.  He  held  the  brain,  in  fact,  to  be 
the  seat  if  not  the  source  of  the  higher  faculties,  while  he 
assigned  the  appetites  and  coarser  passions  to  the  viscera. 
Hippocrates ',  who  lived  some  years  before  him,  assigns  to 
the  brain  the  guardianship  of  the  mind,  and  makes  it  to 
be  not  only  the  first  percipient  of  all  the  changes  of  the 
seasons,  but  also  the  source  and  seat  of  all  the  more  deadly 
and  complicated  maladies. 

Note  3,  p.  126.  It  may  be  questioned,  &c.j  The 
argument,  in  these  passages,  is  to  account  for  the  changes 
which  are  constantly  going  on  in  bodies,  and  for  which 
•that  age  could  assign  no  adequate  cause  ;  but  still  it  was 
perceived  that  tangible  and  sapid  qualities  (hot  and  cold, 
wet  and  dry,  acid,  saline,  astringent,  and  others)  must  be 
the  agents  principally  concerned  in  their  production. 
Thus,  although  neither  light  nor  darkness,  sound  nor 
odour,  can  act  upon  bodies,  yet  something  present  with 
them  may,  and  this  seems  to  point,  suggestively,  to  those 
imponderable  and  invisible  forces  (heat,  magnetism,  elec- 
tricity, &c.),  for  which,  as  yet,  even  "  no  plausible  theory 
has  been  adopted." 

Note  4,  p.  126.     But  all  bodies  are  not  impi-essionable, 
&c.]     These  passages  are  very  obscure  ;  but  their  purport 
1  Epistola,  T.  in.  824  ;  T.  i.  614. 


CH.  XII.]  NOTES.  293 

seems  to  be,  that  odour  and  sound  can  act  only  upon  such 
bodies  as,  like  the  air  and  water,  are  neither  limited 
nor  stationary — are  made  to  be  the  carriers,  as  it  we're, 
of  delicate  emanations  and  vibrations  to  sentient  organs. 
Thus,  it  is  added,  the  air,  having  been  impressed  by  odour, 
readily  gives  it  out,  and,  then,  through  the  smell,  becomes 
perceptible  to  the  sentient  being.  But  neither  odour  nor 
sound,  as  such,  can  in  aught  contribute  to  the  changes  to 
which  all  inert  bodies  are  subject ;  and  the  actions  of 
sound  and  odour,  therefore,  seem  to  be  limited  to  sen- 
tient, that  is,  living  properties.  This  may  be  to  us  a 
truism,  but  it  must  be  recollected  that  even  to  Aristotle 
the  olfactory  passages  were  but  imperfectly  known  ;  that 
the  opinions  upon  the  Atmosphere  were  hypothetical ;  and 
that  the  processes  by  which  changes  are  wrought  in 
inert  matter  were  still  to  be  detected. 


BOOK    THE    THIKD. 


CHAPTER  I. 

Note  1,  p.  131.  The  sentient  organs,  however,  are  con- 
stituted, &c.]  The  senses  were  formed,  according  to  that 
age,  from  the  elements — as  the  hearing  from  air,  and  the 
eye,  which  alone  was  supposed  to  have  a  special  organ, 
from  the  purest  part  of  the  fluid  secreted  by  the  brain ;  and 
vision  is  the  result,  according  to  Aristotle,  of  refraction. 
Thus,  Democritus '  was  held  to  be  right  in  saying  that  the 
eye  is  water  but  to  be  wrong  in  supposing  vision  to  be 
caused  by  reflection,  (jo  opav  elvm  Ttjv  £^0a<r<i/)  as  vision 
is,  not  in  the  eye  but,  in  the  percipient;  for  "vision  is  re- 
fraction "  (a'i»aK\a<r<?  jap  TO  irdBoi).  Aristotle  shews  that, 
according  to  the  admitted  doctrines,  these  two  elements 
only  constitute  the  sentient  organs  of  all  animals  which 
are  perfect ;  and  adds,  as  if  to  guard  against  a  possible 
objection,  that  the  mole  has  eyes  although  they  may  not 
be  very  apparent.  It  is  then  argued  that,  unless  there  is 
some  kind  of  body  or  mode  of  impression  different  from  all 

1  De  Sensu  et  Sens.  2.  10. 


CH.  I.]  NOTES.  295 

with  which  we  are  acquainted,  no  sense  can  be  wanting; 
and  Cuvier1  adopted  a  similar  argument  to  prove  that  no 
animal,  unknown  to  Zoology,  remains  to  be  discovered. 

Note  2,  p.  132.  And  this  ive  are  able  to  do,  &c.] 
This  passage  is  elliptical  and  obscure  ;  but,  as  "  the  rela- 
tive is  too  closely  connected  with  the  example  something 
sweet  to  admit  of  being  separated,"  it  may  imply  that  the 
sight  may,  by  colour  and  refraction,  determine  the  quality 
of  a  particular  fluid.  But,  as  no  sense  can  judge,  excepting 
indirectly,  of  compound  qualities,  the  perception  of  such 
is  accidental,  a  kind  of  guess,  that  is,  just  as  it  would  be 
in  the  case  of  a  fair  individual,  in  the  example  of  Cleon's 
son. 

Note  3,  p.  133.  The  senses,  however,  do  perceive  casu- 
ally, &c.]  This  passage  remains,  according  to  its  wording, 
unintelligible,  notwithstanding  the  attention  bestowed  upon 
it  by  commentators,  because  of  the  difficulty  of  attaching 
any  sense  to  the  assumption,  that  the  senses  can  become 
as  one.  The  comment  "  si  unum  et  idem  uno  et  eodem 
tempore  a  diversis  sensibus  percipitur,  ni  sensus  in  unum 
coalescunt,"  assumes  but  does  not  shew  that  the  senses  can 
so  coalesce,  and  then  judge  of  impressions  made  upon  them 
individually.  And  thus  here  again  is  required  a  central 
organ,  the  common  origin  of  the  perceptive  power  of  the 
senses,  to  which  all  impressions  are  to  be  referred  and  by 
which  they  are  to  be  compared;  and  such  an  organ  is  the 
brain.  But  still,  from  the  moment  that  we  judge  of  more 
1  Discours  sur  lea  Revolutions  de  la  terre,  66 — 67. 


296  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

than  a  simple  impression  or  a  single  idea,  there  is  liability 
to  error,  as  was  observed  and  exemplified  in  the  case  of  a 
fluid,  which,  from  being  bitter  and  yellow,  is  at  once 
assumed  to  be  bile  because  those  are  the  known  qualities 
of  that  fluid.  Many  of  our  errors  arise,  no  doubt,  in  like 
manner,  from  our  not  sufficiently  scrutinising  the  impres- 
sions derived  from  external  objects. 


CHAPTER  II. 

Note  1,  p.  135.  It  is  then  manifest  that  perception 
&c.]  This  is  a  conclusion  drawn  from  the  reasoning 
of  a  former  chapter,  and  its  purport  is  to  shew  that  our 
senses  enable  us  to  judge  even  of  privative  conditions,  as 
darkness  and  silence ;  and,  further,  that,  being  receptive 
of  forms  without  matter,  they  can  retain  images,  and  so, 
through  the  sensorium  recall  objects  after  their  with- 
drawal. 

Note  2,  p.  136.  The  action  of  the  object  of  percep- 
tion, &c.]  It  has  been  attempted,  by  some  of  the 
ancient  commentators,  to  annex  this  to  the  preceding 
argument,  and  shew  that,  as  sight  must  first  be  imbued 
with  colour,  so  the  hearing  must,  in  order  to  perceive 
sounds,  be  first  sensible  of  the  actions  of  sonorous  bodies. 
But  the  more  obvious  signification,  and  which  is  equally 
supported  by  the  text,  is,  that  there  must  be  simultaneous- 


CH.  II.]  NOTES.  297 

ness  of  action  between  the  object  and  the  sense,  although 
the  modes  of  that  action  are  as  different  as  material  are 
from  living  properties.  The  succeeding  passage  is,  by  its 
wording,  obscure,  but  yet  it  admits  of  being  elucidated 
by  the  term  on  which  its  meaning  chiefly  depends ;  for 
hearing,  when  in  potentiality,  must  involve  both  sound 
(as  without  hearing  there  is  no  sound,)  and  hearing,  in 
reality,  just  as  the  Vital  Principle  must  exist,  innately 
in  the  body  in  potentiality,  but  which,  under  genial 
circumstances,  is  to  be  acted  upon  and  made  a  reality  ; 
and  thus,  too,  the  power  which  impels  may,  itself,  be 
at  rest. 

Note  3,  p.  136.  But  while  for  some  senses  tfiese  two 
states,  &c.]  It  is  scarcely  possible,  owing  to  the  difficulty 
of  fixing  upon  synonyms,  to  make  this  passage  clear  to 
the  general  reader — the  text  instances  two  terms  (\//o0>;- 
<ri?  KCCI  tj  ciKovo-i?),  as  potential  conditions  of  sound  and 
hearing  (-v|^o'0os  KO.\  tj  awtf),  and  it  may  be  assumed  that 
they  conveyed  a  modified  signification  of  the  action  and 
sensation,  which  another  language,  even  were  the  meaning 
quite  evident,  may  fail  in  imparting.  But  even  the 
plastic  Greek  fails,  in  many  instances,  in  discriminating, 
without  periphrasis,  the  two  conditions ;  for  vision, 
although  potential,  is  still  vision,  nor  has  it  any  other 
designation  when  made  reality  by  colour,  and  this  applies 
equally  to  the  taste  ami  savour.  In  this  version,  the 
double  condition  of  sound  is  rendered  by  sound  and 
sounding,  that  of  the  sense  by  hearing,  and  audition  for 


298  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

want  of  a  vernacular  term ;  the  French  version  gives 
them  as  "  le  son  et  la  resonnance,  et  1'acte  de  ce  qui  pent 
entendre  est  Fouie  ou  £  audition."  It  is  clear  that  hearing 
and  sound,  and  other  senses  and  actions,  in  reality,  must 
coincide  to  eliminate  sensation ;  although  this  does  not, 
of  course,  apply,  as  the  text  observes,  to  the  senses  in 
potentiality.  And,  hence,  in  this  state,  there  are,  for  a 
sentient  being,  no  such  qualities  as  white  or  black,  bitter 
or  sweet,  as  they  depend,  for  their  reality,  upon  a  given 
condition  of  the  sensibility,  which  depends  again,  in  part, 
upon  the  will. 

Note  4,  p.  137.  If  a,  voice  of  any  kind  is  harmony, 
&c.]  This  deviation  from  the  immediate  subject  of  the 
chapter,  which  was  to  prove  that  the  five  senses  satisfy 
all  our  wants  as  sentient  creatures,  and  that,  therefore, 
there  can  be  no  other  sense  besides  them,  is,  no  doubt, 
episodical,  although  it  is  annexed,  by  the  extremes  of 
sounds,  to  the  general  argument  upon  sensibility.  But 
the  phrase  itself  is  by  its  wording  obscure,  and,  by  its 
conclusion  unsatisfactory,  for  it  may  not  follow  that, 
because  voice  may  be  harmony  and  harmony  proportion, 
the  hearing  must  be  proportion  also.  It1  has  been 
suggested  that,  by  a  slight  change  of  position  in  the 
words,  and  so,  instead  of  the  present  wording,  making 
harmony,  voice  to  be  (el  S* »;'  <pwv^  (rv/icptovia  vice  el  %rj  o-uju- 
(fxatiia  (pwvti  -m)  of  any  kind,  it  might  be  assumed  that 
hearing  should  be  harmony.  Aristotle2,  by  allotting 
1  Vide  Trendel.  Comment.  a  De  Part.  Animalm,  iv.  9.  i. 


CH.  II.]  NOTES.  299 

"  vowels  and  consonants,  which  constitute  speech,  to  the 
larynx,  tongue  and  lips,"  seems,  by  this  variety  of  sounds, 
to  consider  voice  as  a  kind  of  harmony  ;  and  Cuvier  says, 
that  all  the  modifications  of  sound  which  are  expressible 
by  the  letters  of  the  alphabet,  "  take  place  in  the  mouth, 
and  depend  on  the  relative  mobility  of  the  tongue,  and 
still  more  the  lips,  whence  the  perfection  of  man's  speech 
is  derived." 

Note  5,  p.  138.  But  since  we  judge  of  white,  sweet, 
and  each  other,  &c.]  The  only  answer  to  this,  as  it  was 
to  a  former  inquiry,  is,  that  the  brain  is  that  general- 
ising faculty,  and  that  it  fulfils  all  the  conditions,  however 
enigmatically  described,  which  are  required  in  the  text. 
It  is  impossible  to  refuse  to  the  brain  the  property  of 
receiving  and  comparing  contrary  impressions,  simultane- 
ously, and  receiving  them,  therefore,  in  the  words  of  the 
text,  as  an  indivisible  principle,  just  as  the  mind  can 
compare  opposite  ideas ;  and  all  the  speculations  upon 
impulses  and  the  divisibility  and  indivisibility  of  that 
which  is  to  perceive  and  judge  only  shew  the  want  of  a 
central  organ  for  the  reception  and  comparison  of  indi- 
vidual sensations.  And  many  of  these  passages  are 
necessarily  obscure,  owing  to  their  partaking  of  the 
character  of  inquiry  or  suggestion,  rather  than  didactic 
statement ;  but  their  obscurity  may  be,  in  part,  seen 
through  by  the  introduction  of  that  source  of  sensibility, 
which  is  said,  in  the  closing  paragraph,  to  constitute 
animal  in  contradistinction  to  mere  vegetive  life. 


300  NOTES.  [BK.  HI. 


CHAPTER  III. 

Note  1,  p.  142.  Thus,  t/ten  the  ancients  affirm,  &c.] 
Parmenides,  Anaxagoras,  Empedocles  and  Democritus, 
are  cited  by  Aristotle1  as  maintaining  the  doctrine 
alluded  to  in  the  text ;  but  as  Homer8  can  hardly  be 
said  in  the  passage  quoted  to  have  adopted  it,  there  is 
probably  an  error  in  the  reference.  The  arguments  of 
these  writers,  in  support  of  the  doctrine,  are  derived  from 
the  uncertain  and  varying  nature  of  sentient  impressions 
which,  as  they  depend  upon  individual  organisms,  cannot, 
for  the  attainment  of  truth,  be  brought  under  any  absolute 
law.  Thus,  they  held  that  it  belongs  not  to  the  many 
nor  even  the  few  to  judge  of  truth,  since  the  selfsame 
fluid,  when  tasted,  seems  to  some  to  be  sweet,  to  others 
bitter ;  so  that  if  all  were  sick  or  mad,  and  two  or  three 
only  well  or  sane,  then  these  and  not  the  others  would 
seem  to  be  in  that  state.  Many  things,  besides,  appear 
to  have  for  many  animals  opposite  qualities  from  what 
they  have  for  us;  and  even  for  the  same  individual, 
similar  substances  do  not  always  produce  the  same 
sensation.  So  that  it  is  uncertain  which  of  these  are  true 
or  false,  since  these  are  neither  more  nor  less  true  than 

1  Metaphysica,  III.  4.  8.  9.  *  Odyss.  xvm.  135. 


CH.  III.]  NOTES.  301 

those ;  and  this  made  Democritus  say,  that  either  nothing 
is  true,  or  else  that  truth  is  for  us  uncertain  (alri\ov). 
From  their  assuming,  as  a  general  proposition,  that 
reflection  is  sensation,  they  maintained  that  reflection 
is  change,  and  that  the  apparent,  through  sensation,  is,  of 
necessity,  true ;  and  it  is  from  such  conclusions,  Aristotle 
adds,  that  Empedocles  and  Democritus  as  well  as  their 
followers  became  fettered  by  those  opinions.  For  Em- 
pedocles affirmed,  that  men,  by  changing  their  habit 
(ef«?)  change  also  their  judgment,  "  for  man's  wisdom  is 
enlarged,"  &c. ;  and  elsewhere  he  says,  that  "  in  so  far  as 
men  are  capable  of  change,  in  so  far  they  are  capable  of 
forming  different  judgments."  The  opinion  of  Parmenides 
is  to  the  same  purport ;  and  there  is  a  recorded  saying  of 
Anaxagoras  to  some  of  his  followers,  that  "beings  will 
be  to  them  such  as  they  may  suppose  them  to  be."  These 
writers  attribute  the  same  opinion  to  Homer,  (but  it  was 
shewn  in  a  former  note  that  this  reference  is  faulty,) 
because  he  made  "  Hector,  as  if  beside  himself  under  the 
blow,  to  lie  thinking  differently,"  (d\\o<f)poveovTa).  But 
it  was  incumbent  upon  these  writers,  as  is  observed  in  the 
text,  to  have  dwelt  upon  the  liability  to  error  to  which 
we  are  all  ever  subject  through  the  senses;  for  if  all 
appearances  are  to  be  held  as  true,  then  the  same  impres- 
sion may  be  at  once  true  and  false ;  which  is  to  admit  an 
impossibility.  The  doctrine,  in  fine,  of  this  school,  as 
given  in  the  text  was,  that  the  power  by  which  animals 
move  is  corporeal,  and  like  to  the  faculty  which  thinks, 


302  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

as  also  that  the  faculty  of  conclusions  (judgment)  is 
some  form  of  sensibility ;  and  thus,  it  reduced,  so  to 
say,  the  faculties  of  thought  to  sensual  impressions  and 
conditions. 

Note  2,  p.  142.  On  which  account,  eitJier  all  appear- 
ances, <fec.]  This  is  a  dilemma,  as  an  objection  to  their 
doctrine,  in  that,  "  either  all  appearances  are,  as  they 
maintain,  necessarily  true,  or  else  (in  opposition  to  their 
dogma,  that  like  is  recognised  by  like,)  there  is  recognition 
by  unlike;"  and  thus  the  error  from  contraries  is  made 
identical  with  the  knowledge  of  contraries.  The  objection 
is  then  placed  upon  the  obvious  ground  that,  while 
sensation  is  allotted  to  all  creatures,  reflection,  which 
implies  reason,  belongs  but  to  few ;  and  next,  as  a  general 
argument,  it  shews  that  mental  faculties,  being  derived 
from  other  sources  than  feeling,  cannot  be  identical  with 
sentient  perceptions. 

Note  3,  p.  143.  But  it  is  manifest  that  imagination, 
<kc.]  The  argument  next  proceeds  to  the  subject  of 
imagination,  and  as  has  been  well  observed,  it  is  thus 
appropriately  placed  between  sentient  perceptions  and 
thoughts,  "  as  imagination  cannot  be  without  senses, 
or  the  mind  without  imagination."  For  "  imagination 
is  not  identical  with  sensation,"  Aristotle1  observes, 
and  yet  "  it  is  called  up  either  through  thought  or 
through  sensation."  Imagination  then,  is  neither  sensa- 
tion nor  conception,  as  the  former  depends  upon  external 
1  Metaphysica,  in.  5.  23.  De  Motu  Animalm,  8.  5. 


CH.  III.]  NOTES.  303 

influences,  and  the  latter,  which  is  a  result  from  reason- 
ing, being  true  or  false,  is  removed  from  the  will ;  but 
imagination  on  the  contrary,  can  be  exercised  how  and 
when  we  please.  It  is  difficult  either  to  represent 
graphically  the  process  here  alluded  to,  or  to  determine 
the  precise  import  of  the  text ;  and  other  versions  seem 
to  be  equally  indefinite.  The  Latin  is,  "licet  Hamque, 
cum  libet,  fingere  quicquid  volumus,  atque  ante  oculos 
ponere,  perinde  atque  ii  faciunt  qui,  in  artificiosse  memorise 
comparatis  atque  dispositis  locis,  imaginis  fingunt  atque 
simulacra  collocant,"  and  the  French,  "  et  Ton  peut  s'en 
mettre  1'objet  devant  les  yeux,  comme  le  pratiquent  ceux 
qui  traduisent  les  choses  en  signes  mnemoniques,  et 
inventent  des  symboles."  Hence,  an  opinion,  arrived  at 
by  a  chain  of  reasoning  drawn  from  particulars  which  we 
hold  to  be  true,  cannot  but  affect  us  differently  from 
imaginings  which  are  of  our  own  coining,  and  which  we 
know  to  be  fictitious.  A  succeeding  passage,  which  shews 
that  imagination  cannot  be  opinion,  is  to  the  same  purport 
— for,  being  derived  from  particulars,  its  issue  is,  so  to 
say,  independent  of  us ;  but  imagination  may  be  exercised 
upon  any  combinations  which  the  will  may  choose  to 
recalL 

Note  4,  p.  147.  But  the  motion  produced  by  the  act, 
&c.]  The  wording,  by  the  act,  is  but  an  indifferent 
representative  of  the  original  VTTO  rfj<:  cvepyeias,  and  yet 
its  exact  signification,  or  its  relation  to  the  eWe/Ve^ia  is 
by  no  means  obvious ;  the  phrase,  besides,  notwithstanding 


304  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

its  repetitions,  is  still  vague  and  obscure.  It  seems, 
however,  to  embody  former  assertions — that  a  single  sen- 
sation from  a  special  organ,  that  is,  must  be  true ;  and 
that  there  is  room  for  fallacy  when  other  qualities  are  added 
to  that  sensation,  and  still  more  so  when  common  pro- 
perties, as  motion,  magnitude,  or  number,  are,  for  ex- 
planation, to  be  taken  into  the  account. 

Note  5,  p.  147.  And  since  vision  is  a  sense,  &c.]  It 
will  be  apparent  that  this  passage  depends,  for  its  mean- 
ing, upon  etymology — (j)avTa<ria.  (fancy  or  imagination) 
may  be  derived,  if  not  from  <£a'oe,  yet,  from  the  same 
root  as  0a'o?,  which  probably  is  0w?  (light),  as  light  is 
essential  to  vision ;  and  0a'oe  may  have  formed  (palvio, 
which  is  an  approximation  to  (pavraa-ia.  The  Latin 
version  is,  "  cum  autem  visus  maxime  sit  sensus,  hinc  est 
quod  nomen  imaginatio  ab  ipso  lumine  sumpsit,  phan- 
tasiaque  dicitur,  quia  sine  lumine  visio  fieri  nequit." 
Imagination  or  the  mental  perception  of  images,  that  is, 
being  regarded  as  an  inward  sight,  and  sight  as  the  most 
precious  of  the  senses,  was  derived  from  the  same  root  as 
light,  because  light  is  essential  to  sight. 


CH.  IV.]  NOTES.  305 


CHAPTER  IV. 

Note  1,  p.  153.  T/wre  is  a  distinction  between  posi- 
tive, &c.]  All  the  passages,  under  this  head,  are  obscure, 
if  not  incomprehensible  ;  their  purport  seems  to  be  whe- 
ther the  mind  judges,  by  one  and  the  same  faculty,  of 
realities,  (qualities,  that  is,  perceived  through  the  senses) 
and  realities  viewed,  abstractedly,  in  their  essence.  Thus, 
the  inquiry  seems  to  be  whether  the  mind  is  sensibility 
or  associated,  so  to  say,  with  sensibility,  or  altogether 
distinct  from  it ;  whether  the  sentient  perception  which 
is  engaged  upon  particulars,  can  ever  be  capable  of  the 
abstract  reasoning  which  detects  the  essence  of  things, 
and  so  generalises  and  groups  them  for  universal  laws. 
This  does  not,  however,  apply,  it  is  said,  to  all  subjects, 
as,  with  some,  "the  two  states  are  identical;"  and  this 
is  the  case  with  abstractions  or  immaterialities,  which  fall 
within  the  province  of  the  mind  apart  from  sense. 

Note  2,  p.  153.  Now,  it  is  by  tfte  sensibility  that  we 
judge,  &c.]  This  phrase  seems  to  allude  to  the  then 
admitted  doctrine  that  the  sense  of  Touch  either  is  flesh  or 
in  the  flesh,  and  that  it,  therefore,  directly  or  indirectly,  is 
perceptive  of  hot  and  cold,  and  other  such  qualities ;  and 
this  assumed  sentient  property  may  have  led  to  this  com- 

20 


306  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

plicated  argument,  which  makes  flesh  to  be  rather  an 
abstract  than  a  positive  substance.  Trendelenburg,  in  the 
allusion  to  curved  and  straight  lines,  sees  a  reference  to 
Plato's  opinions  upon  intellectual  processes  :  "  Sane  Plato 
actiones  intellectus  circulis  primum  recto,  mox  circinato 
recurrentique  interius  comparat  :  Aristoteles  linese  expli- 
catse  et  replicatse,  sive  porrectse  et  curvatse."  It  may, 
however,  be  assumed  that,  whatever  the  figures  or  analo- 
gies employed,  the  operations  of  the  mind  will  still  remain 
as  mysterious  as  those  of  the  sensibility ;  and,  thus,  that 
all  such  inquiries  are,  as  final  causes,  beyond  our  research 
and,  so  far,  unprofitable. 

The  Latin  version  of  the  phrase  is,  "  Sensitiva  igitur 
parte  calidum  discernit  et  frigidum,  quorum  qusedam  est 
ratio  caro,  alia  vero  esse  carnis  discernit,  aut  separabile 
aut  se  habente  ad  se  ipsam  perinde  atque  se  habet  cum 
extensa  fuerit  linea  flexa."  That  of  the  French,  "  Mais 
c'est  certainement  par  une  autre  faculte  qui  est  separee,  ou 
qui  du  moins  devient  a  elle-meme  ce  que  la  ligne  brisee 
est  £  elle-mfeme  aussi  quand  on  la  redresse,  que  nous 
jugeons  ce  que  signifie  etre  la  chair." 

Note  3,  p.  154.  But  we  have  to  consider  why  the 
mind,  <fec.]  The  chapter  is  closed  rather  abruptly  with 
this  passage,  which,  by  some,  is  said  to  be  spurious ;  but, 
although  obscure  in  its  wording,  it  is  in  keeping  with  the 
general  tone  of  the  inquiry  and  argument.  The  main 
purpose  of  the  inquiry  is  why,  as  every  subject  of  thought, 
in  potentiality,  is  among  material  substances,  the  mind  is 


CH.  V.]  NOTES.  307 

not  constantly  thinking,  just  as  it  has  been  asked  why 
the  sensibility,  which  is  ever  acted  upon  by  external  in- 
fluences, is  not  constantly  made  percipient.  The  answer 
seems  to  be,  that  the  sensibility,  being  in  potentiality,  is 
incapable  of  perception  without  the  agency  of  external 
influences,  while  the  mind,  being  immaterial,  is  able  to 
judge  of  the  relations  of  things,  without  being  identified 
with  them;  and  thus,  that,  although  every  object,  as  a 
subject  of  thought,  may  be  said  to  belong  to  the  mind,  it 
cannot  belong  to  any  one  of  them.  It  may  well,  however, 
be  said,  with  respect  to  this,  among  other  passages  of 
this  chapter,  "  est  enim  Aristotelis,  liberum  cogitationis 
cursum  sequi  neque  anxia  perspicuitatis  causa  deflecti" 


CHAPTER  V. 

Note  1,  p.  156.  As  if  it  were  a  virtuality  like  light.']  The 
original  «'?  ef  is  TIC  is  ill  represented  by  virtuality,  and 
yet  neither  habit,  state,  nor  condition  would  represent 
the  agency  of  the  mind  as  a  realising  principle ;  as  that 
which  can  collect,  compare,  and  so  give  reality,  in  gene- 
ralisations, to  perceptions  received  through  the  senses. 
"  Sicut  colores  expectant,  ut  appareant,  (i.  e.  ut  colorum 
vice  vere  fungantur)  ita  sensuum  notitiae  et  quidquid  ad 
intellectum  patientem  pertinet  mentem  agentem  requirunt, 

20—2 


308  _  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

ut  omnes  veritatis  numeros  habeant,  et  verse  notioiiis  vim 
consequantur." 

Note  2,  p.  156.  Knowledge  in  activity  is  identical 
with,  &c.]  This  passage  seems  to  be  the  complement  of 
what  had  just  been  asserted,  that  the  agent  is  ever  more 
influential  than  the  subject,  and  the  originating  cause 
than  the  matter ;  for  the  intellect,  in  activity,  may  be 
said  to  create,  to  identify  with  itself  that  is,  the  know- 
ledge which  it  acquires  concerning  external  things  through 
abstract  reasoning.  Knowledge  pre-exists,  however,  as 
has  been  said,  in  every  well-constituted  individual,  be- 
cause each  is  furnished,  at  birth,  with  faculties  for 
acquiring  knowledge  ;  but  yet  it  cannot  strictly  be  said  to 
pre-exist,  since  it  may,  or  may  not  be  developed  by  edu- 
cation or  reflection  ;  as  the  mind,  moreover,  is  impassive, 
it  is  not  impressionable,  and  cannot,  therefore,  be  the  seat 
of  memory.  But  what  means  the  impressionable  mind 
which  is  perishable  ?  may  it  not  be  again  said  that, 
suggestively,  the  brain  is  here  implied  ;  since  this  organ 
is  the  sensorium,  the  seat  of  memory,  and  dependent, 
besides,  like  all  other  organs,  upon  life,  for  its  functions 
and  its  continuance. 


CE.  VI.]  NOTES.  309 


CHAPTER  VI. 

Note  1,  p.  159.  In  the  way  that  Empedocles,  &c.]  The 
passage  cited  in  support  of  the  above  opinion  is  not  very 
apposite;  for  Empeclocles1,  who  had  made  "nature  to  be 
nothing  more  than  the  combination  of  (yu  <£"«<?)  and  change 
among  commingled  particles,"  (attraction  and  repulsion, 
in  other  words),  is  quoted  by  Aristotle  *  in  the  words, 
"  many  heads  of  creatures  without  necks  budded  forth  ;" 
and,  as  if  to  turn  against  him,  as  it  were,  his  own  doc- 
trine, it  is  added,  "  they  were  by  affinity  joined  together." 
This  led  Aristotle  to  the  simile  in  the  text,  as  Empedo- 
cles3  formed  things  in  nature  by  the  combination  of 
individual  particles,  so  may  the  mind  eliminate  new  by 
the  association  of  former  or  admitted  ideas ;  and  as,  in 
the  verse  cited,  head  and  neck  lie  dissevered,  so,  in  the 
idea  of  quantity,  there  is  nothing  in  common  between 
the  measure  of  the  diagonal  and  the  side  of  the  square. 
Thus,  as  there  is  no  common  measure  for  the  diagonal 
and  the  side  of  the  square,  they  are,  in  so  far,  distinct ; 
but  although,  in  themselves,  distinct,  they  can,  in  thought, 
be  combined  and  made  one.  "  By  diameter  may  be 

1  De  Gen.  et  Corr.  i.  i.  7.  *  De  Ccdo,  in.  2.  7. 

3  Vide  Trendel.  Comment. 


310  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

understood  the  diagonal  which  divides  the  square  into 
two  equal  triangles ;  or  it  may  mean  the  diameter  of  the 
circle  which  is  incommensurate  with  the  circumference." 
In  a  word,  it  is  by  combination  that  error  creeps  into  our 
judgments,  and  falsifies  our  perceptions. 

Note  2,  p.  159.  It  is  the  mind,  &c.]  The  question 
of  a  fact,  such  as  that  in  the  example,  is  dependent 
upon  the  brain  rather  than  the  mind,  as  that  organ  can 
combine  the  individual  notices  obtained  through  the 
senses ;  but  when  the  mind  intervenes,  so  to  say,  and 
judges  from  what  is,  of  what  was  or  is  to  be,  there  is 
room  for  error.  It  is  almost  puerile  to  explain  that  the 
assertion  "  something  is  not  white "  is  not,  necessarily, 
fallacious ;  and  that,  if  the  object  be  white,  the  fallacy 
comes  from  the  addition  of  the  negative.  The  double 
sense  of  indivisibility  is  to  the  same  purport ;  extension 
is  clearly  divisible,  and,  therefore,  divisibility  is  made, 
actually,  apparent  as  a  fact ;  but  the  mind  can  realise  to 
itself  extension  without  parts,  as  indivisible,  that  is,  and 
in  potentiality. 

Note  3,  p.  160.  It  may  not  then  be  said,  &c.]  In 
this  version,  the  term  mind  is  used,  and  in  another,  "  in- 
telligence," (which  is  its  synonym),  as  that  which  thinks, 
(rl  €woei),  but  the  text  does  not  so  specify  it ;  and  any 
allusion  to  halves  would  but  ill-accord  with  the  notion  of 
homogeneity  and  impassibility  assigned  to  the  thinking 
principle.  But  no  theory  which  could  be  framed  of  the 
mind  would  aid  in  explaining  the  train  of  reasoning 


CH.  VII.]  NOTES.  311 

here ;  for,  independently  of  the  abstruse  nature  of  all 
mental  processes,  there  is,  evidently  about  it,  confusion, 
arising  from  the  assumption  of  a  something  associated 
with  sensibility,  which  the  brain  only  could  rectify. 

Note  4,  p.  160.  The  point  and  every  analogous  divi- 
sion, &c.]  With  respect  to  quantity l,  in  relation  to  indi- 
visibility, "a  point  which  has  position,  (KO!  Qiaiv  e%ov 
<rT«7/ui;')  is  indivisible,  but  a  line  is  divisible  in  one,  surface 
in  two,  and  body  in  several  directions;"  and  by  privation 
is  implied  that  the  point  is  without  length,  depth,  or 
breadth ;  the  line  without  either  breadth  or  depth ;  and 
the  surface  without  depth.  It  is  obvious,  from  what  has 
been  said,  that  every  affirmation  or  negation  must,  as 
depending  upon  sentient  impressions,  be  either  true  or 
false  ;  but  that  the  judgment,  when  deciding  upon  essen- 
tial or  abiding  qualities,  may  be  true,  and  that,  when 
drawing  its  inferences  from  accidental  qualities  or  rela- 
tions of  bodies,  it  may  be  erroneous. 


CHAPTER  YIL 

Note  1,  p.  165.    Images  belong,  naturally,  to  the  think- 
ing principle,    <kc.]       This   very   suggestive   comparison 
between  intellectual  and  sentient  perceptions,  seems,  even 
in  the  absence  of  knowledge  of  the  brain,  to  assume  that 
1  Metaphysica,  iv.  6.  24. 


312  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

practical  thoughts  must  be  derived  from  the  senses,  and, 
therefore,  through  a  sensorium ;  and  as  impressions  may 
be  genial  or  otherwise,  the  faculties  suggest  pursuit  or 
flight.  The  practical  mind,  in  fact,  never  thinks  without 
an  image  which  acts,  in  its  turn,  so  to  say,  upon  it,  as  the 
air,  which  has  been  impressed  by  colour,  does  upon  the 
pupil  and  the  pupil  upon  something  else  (that  is,  the 
retina),  and  so  sound  upon  the  hearing ;  but  the  last 
term,  that  is,  the  visual  or  auditory  sense,  is  one,  as  the 
mean  or  medium,  however  modified  in  condition,  is  one. 
It  will  be  evident,  with  but  little  consideration,  that  the 
obscurity  which  is  palpable  in  the  succeeding  passages  is 
occasioned  by  the  absence  of  the  brain,  and  can  be  cleared 
away  only  by  its  introduction;  and  that,  with  it,  the 
analogies  of  unit  and  limit  acquire  some  kind  of  signifi- 
cation. 

Note  2,  p.  166.  Thus  tlie  cogitative  faculty  dwells, 
&c.]  Aristotle  seems  here  to  consider  images  or  thoughts, 
present  in  memory,  as  necessary  to  ratiocination,  and  he 
has  elsewhere  said  that  an  individual  without  senses 
could  neither  learn  nor  understand ;  but  he  is  evidently 
alluding  to  a  higher  faculty  than  the  sensibility,  and 
•which  is  able,  by  abstract  reasoning,  to  draw,  from  present 
appearances  or  images,  conclusions  as  to  future  occur- 
rences, and,  by  that  prevision,  to  determine  what  should 
or  should  not  be  done. 

Note  3,  p.  166.  And  with  respect  to  all  which,  &c.] 
This  passage  seems,  although  obscure  from  its  brevity,  to 


CH.  VII.  NOTES.  313 

imply  that  without  action,  when  thoughts  are  not  carried 
out  that  is,  there  can  for  us  be  neither  good  nor  bad,  as 
these  are  relations  pertaining  to  individuals,  and  dependent, 
not  upon  any  universal  law  but,  upon  social  institutions  ; 
but  that  tmth,  being  the  same  for  ever,  is,  even  when  not 
exercised,  in  an  absolute  relation  to  all  men,  and  in  oppo- 
sition to  all  falsehood. 

Note  4,  p.  166.  The  mind  dwells  upon  abstractions, 
&c.]  The  term  abstractions  here,  as  in  an  earlier  passage, 
signifies  mathematical  questions,  which,  from  not  being 
referrible  to  any  particular  body,  admit  of  being  treated  as 
such ;  and  so  a  snub- nose,  as  the  realisation  of  a  particular 
form,  may,  by  that  form  apart  from  matter,  be  regarded 
as  an  abstraction.  The  argument  is  then  resumed  that 
the  mind,  when  thinking,  is,  wJien  active  or  in  act,  the 
subject  thought  upon.  The  closing  passage,  by  its  ques- 
tioning whether  "  the  mind,  witliout  being  itself  imma- 
terial, can  comprehend  abstractions,"  seems  to  militate 
against  the  arguments  adduced  to  prove  that  it  is  impassive 
and  homogeneous,  freed,  that  is,  from  all  the  conditions  of 
matter ;  but  it  is  yet  doubtful  where  (whether  or  not  in 
"the  metaphysics")  this  argument  may,  according  to 
promise,  have  been  continued. 


314  NOTES.  [BK.  m. 


CHAPTER  VIII. 


Note  1,  p.  169.  But  tJie  question  here  must  necessarily 
refer,  &c.]  This  argument,  while  maintaining  the  opinion 
that  sensibility  is  receptive  of  form  without  matter,  is  an 
objection  to  the  doctrine  of  Empedocles  and  others,  who, 
having  derived  the  Vital  Principle  from  material  elements, 
made  perception  to  be  material  also,  in  the  relation  of 
like  by  like.  But  here  it  is  said  that,  as  the  hand  is  the 
instrument  for  making  instruments,  so  the  mind  is  the 
archetype  of  forms,  and  sensibility  the  recipient  of  the 
forms  of  things  without  their  matter,  perceived  through 
the  senses.  Aristotle,  however,  does  make  imagery,  the 
power  that  is,  of  recalling  forms,  to  be  essential  to  cogi- 
tation, and,  consequently,  to  reflection ;  although  doubting 
whether  there  may  not  be  thoughts  which  cannot  have  a 
sentient  origin. 

Note  2,  p.  170.  Imagination,  on  the  other  hand, 
&c.]  Imagination,  or  the  faculty  which  calls  up  images 
is,  necessarily,  different  from  that  which  determines  the 
truth  or  falsehood  of  any  proposition,  and  which  affirms 
or  denies ;  for  affirmation  or  negation,  as  the  predicant 
of  something  held  to  be  true  or  erroneous,  is,  as  was  said, 
a  combination  of  thoughts ;  and  thoughts,  being  made  up 


CH.  IX.]  NOTES.  315 

of  simple  ideas,  are  not,  like  the  imagination,  under  our 
own  control.  Thus,  while  the  former  may  be  regarded  as 
a  single  faculty,  and,  in  some  sense,  independent  of  the 
judgment,  the  latter  involves  many  and  opposing  ideas 
and  perceptions.  But  what  is  here  meant  by  primal 
thoughts  (TO.  2e  -n-pw-ra  vo^aTa)1  Do  the  words  imply 
innate  ideas,  or  conceptions  of  pure  abstraction,  such  as 
creation,  virtue,  responsibility,  and  others'?  Or  must  it 
be  admitted  that  no  definite  sense  can  be  attached  to 
them  1  If  primal  mean  innate  thoughts,  (thoughts,  that 
is,  no  way  dependent  upon  sentient  properties,)  then  such 
are  distinguishable  at  once  from  those  which  are  derived 
from  images,  although  these  are  not,  themselves,  images 
in  reality. 


CHAPTER  IX. 

Note  1,  p.  173.  But  a  difficulty  at  once  presents  itself, 
&c.]  There  is  an  apparent  want  of  discrimination  here 
between  the  faculties  which  are  the  privilege  and  dis- 
tinction of  higher  creatures  and  the  functions  which  are 
essential  to  life,  and  without  which  there  can  be  neither 
animal  nor  living  being.  In  a  subsequent  paragraph  the 
rational  faculty  or  mind  («al  o  KaXov/jLevus  i/oi/s)  is  ex- 
cluded from  all  participation  in  corporeal  movements, 
and  held  to  have  no  part  in  sentient  perception.  It  is 


316  NOTES.  [BK.  in, 

supposed,  in  fact,  never  to  be  engaged  upon  what  is  prac- 
tical as  its  office  is  contemplation,  so  that,  "  when  dwelling 
upon  what  may  be  fearful,  or  otherwise,  it  does  not,  at 
once,  suggest,  flight  or  pursuit ; "  although,  independently 
of  its  influence,  "the  heart  or  some  other  organ  of  the 
body  maybe  accelerated  or  depressed."  But  in  all  this,  as 
no  allusion  is  made  to  a  moving  force,  whether  the 
motive  be  imagination  or  the  stimulus  of  appetite,  the 
inquiry  may  be  said  to  be  defective. 

Note  2,  p.  173.  But  to  resume  the  more  especial,  &c.] 
Although  these  passages,  which  allude  both  to  physical 
and  moral  causes  of  motion,  are  sufficiently  obvious,  yet,  as 
they  do  not  explain  how  locomotion  is  effected,  they  fail 
in  the  object  of  the  inquiry ;  and  then  the  motion  con- 
cerned in  nutrition,  growth  and  decay,  is  almost  in  the 
same  category,  so  to  say,  with  that  of  progression.  It 
may  be  mentioned  that  the  "  motion  and  progression  of 
animals,"  "  breathing  and  expiration,"  "  sleep  and  watch- 
ing," "youth  and  age,"  are  special  treatises,  and  probably 
composed  for  the  elucidation  of  this  particular  work  upon 
"  life."  The  comparison  between  the  intemperate  man 
who,  although  rational,  acts  against  his  reason,  and  the 
physician  who,  although  versed  in  medical  science,  does 
not  cure,  seems  to  exemplify  the  adage,  that  to  advise  is 
one  thing,  to  do,  another ;  or  to  confirm  the  solemn  words 
of  Johnson,  "that  teachers  of  morality  discourse  like 
angels,  but  they  live  like  men." 


CH.  X.]  NOTES.  317 


CHAPTER  X. 

Note  1,  p.  178.  Thus  it  is  the  object  longed  for  alone, 
&c.]  Food,  that  is,  being  necessary  both  for  stilling  the 
appetite  and  preserving  the  body,  is  the  first  motor ;  for, 
were  there,  as  the  text  says,  two  motors,  then,  as  the 
practical  mind  never  impels  to  move  without  appetite, 
appetite  could  not  impel  to  move  without  the  mind, 
which  is  not  the  case.  This  is  the  argument ;  but  it  is 
less  distinct  than  might  be  wished  for  owing  to  the 
nature  of  the  practical  mind  not  having  been  defined, 
and  to  insufficient  knowledge  concerning  both  muscular 
agency  and  the  brain  and  nervous  system. 

Note  2,  p.  178.  The  mind  then  is  always  right,  &c.] 
The  intellect,  that  is,  when  neither  moved  by  appetite 
nor  perverted  by  imagination,  (for  both  may  be  wrong)  is, 
when  freed  from  those  influences,  always  right ;  but  food 
incites  to  move  because  it  is  either  good  or  appears  to  be 
a  good,  in  the  sense,  not  of  a  moral  but,  of  a  practical 
good,  and,  as  such,  it  may,  by  abuse,  be  the  opposite  of 
good. 

Note  3,  p.  179.  The,  appetites  admit  of  being  opposed, 
&c.]  "Appetite  and  reason  are  not  always  in  accord- 
ance," Aristotle1  observes,  and  as,  when  any  one  desire  is 
1  Eih.  End.  n.  8.  5. 


318  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

subdued  another  may  arise  and  strive  for  the  mastery,  so 
appetite  may  well  be  opposed  to  appetite.  But  resistance 
to  desire  can  be  manifested  only  in  such  beings  as  have  a 
sense  of  time,  have,  that  is,  powers  of  abstraction,  by 
which,  withdrawing  themselves  from  what  is  present,  and 
foreseeing  consequences  in  the  future,  they  are  enabled  to 
resist  the  immediate  compliance  which  desire  or  passion 
is  urging  upon  them.  For  "the1  portion  of  time  now 
present,  is  a  portion  of  that  which  is  future  and  indi- 
visible." 

Note  4,  p.  179.  For  loithout  having  been  itself -moved, 
&c.]  Owing  to  the  wording  there  is  obscurity  about 
this  passage,  but  yet  it  may  be  elucidated — the  object 
desired,  food,  that  is,  although  at  rest,  may,  acting 
upon  the  appetitive  sense,  incite  to  move,  and  so  be 
regarded  as  a  motor;  and  there  are,  of  course,  as  many 
such  motors  as  there  are  kinds  of  food.  These  then  are 
the  three  terms — first,  the  motor  or  food;  then  the 
muscular  agency  by  which  locomotion  is  effected ;  and 
lastly,  that  which  is  moved,  or  the  animal. 

Note  5,  p.  180.  £ut  to  speak  summarily,  &c.]  The 
passage  has,  in  this  version,  been  rendered  with  a  bias 
that  the  analogy  was  drawn  from  the  structure  of  the 
knee-joint,  which,  in  all  times,  has  been  likened  to  a 
hinge,  and  hence  termed  "  ginglymoid ; "  and  concholo- 
gists,  following  Aristotle1,  have  so  termed  the  hinge  of 

1  Nat.  Ausc.  rv.  ro. 

3  Hist.  Animalm,  IV.  4.  11. 


CH.  XI.]  NOTES.  319 

the  bivalves.  The  Latin  is,  "  nunc  ut  in  summa  dicamus, 
id  quod  movet  ut  instrumentum,  ibi  est  collocandum  ubi 
idem  piincipii  rationem  finisve  subit  ut  in  cardine  fit — 
hinc  enim  convexum  et  concavum  est ;  quorum  alterum 
finis,  alterum  principium  est ;  quapropter  alienum  quiescit 
alterum  movetur."  The  closing  paragraph  seems  to  con- 
firm what  has  been  assumed,  that  sentient  imagination  is 
analogous  to  "  animal  instinct." 


CHAPTER  XL 

Note  1,  p.  182.  The  sentient  imagination  belongs, 
&c.]  Instinct  is  the  fixed  but  unerring  guide  of  the 
lower  animals ;  the  voluntary  imagination,  on  the  other 
hand,  the  faculty,  that  is,  which  can,  at  will,  be  called  up 
and  supply  images  for  selection  and  combination  by  the 
judgment,  can  belong  only  to  beings  endowed  with 
reason — that  is,  to  man.  The  faculties  associated  with 
this  imagination,  enable  the  individual,  by  idealising  a 
measure,  to  select  what  may  be,  relatively,  larger  and 
better,  and  out  of  several  impressions  or  sensations,  to 
form  general  notions.  It  is  unnecessary  to  follow  the 
argument  which  explains  why  these  creatures,  so  low 
in  the  scale,  cannot  form  opinions. 

Note  2,  p.  182.  But  appetite  has  no  deliberative 
icill,  &c.]  The  meaning  of  this  passage  is,  seemingly,  too 


320  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

obvious  to  require  comment ;  but  some  commentators 
have  in  the  term  o-QaTpa  seen  an  allusion  to  the  celestial 
spheres,  rather  than  a  ball,  because,  as  the  upper  controls 
in  its  movements  the  lower  sphere,  so  reason,  being 
superior  to  appetite,  is  to  control  inordinate  desires. 
"  Quibus  collatis,  non  temerarium  erit,  o-^a/pa?  similitu- 
dinem  ita  interpretari :  consilium  tanquam  superius 
(»/  ai/co)  ita  appetitum  in  suum  motum  convertere,  sicut 
superior  sphsera  eas,  quce  inferiores  volvuntur."  The 
words  which  follow  "  that  which  is  superior  is  ever 
naturally  more  dominant,"  may  require  some  such 
interpretation,  for  they  seem  to  imply  that  motion,  by 
translation,  may  be  derived  from  the  motions  of  the 
spheres  above,  which  were  said  to  be  in  three  directions ; 
but  the  knowing  faculty,  the  mind,  that  is,  like  the  first 
motor,  is,  for  ever,  at  rest. 

Note  3,  p.  183.  Although  tfte  conception  of  tlie  uni- 
versal, &c.]  This  abstruse  passage  can  only  be  under- 
stood by  reference  to  the  special  treatise  upon  "  the 
motion  of  animals,  wherein  this  topic  is  considered;"  it 
is  asked,  "  whence  comes  it,  that  an  individual,  after 
thinking,  sometimes  acts  and  sometimes  does  not  act, 
sometimes  moves  and  sometimes  does  not  move?"  and 
the  answer1  is,  that  "action  or  motion  is  the  conclusion 
of  a  syllogism,"  of  which  "  the  conception  of  the  universal 
is  the  major,  that  of  the  particular,  the  middle,  and  the 
action  following  it  the  minor." 

1  De  Motu  Animalm,  5.  f.  i. 


CH.  XII.]  NOTES.  321 


CHAPTER  XII. 

Note  1,  p.  186.  Simple  or  homogeneous  bodies,  <fec.] 
There  is  no  clue  in  Aristotle's  writings  to  the  meaning 
of  "simple  (or  homogeneous)  bodies"  (TO  o-w/ua  aVAoi/i/), 
unless  it  be  the  Acalepha ',  "  the  body  of  which,  like 
that  of  the  oyster,  is  said  to  be  altogether  fleshy,  but, 
unlike  the  oyster,  to  be  without  a  shell ;  and  it  is  further 
said  to  belong  rather  to  plants  than  animals."  But 
as  in  the  following  chapter  it  is  shewn  that  an  animal 
body,  if  homogeneous,  cannot  exist,  so  the  tenor  of  the 
whole  argument  may  be,  to  shew  that  no  animal  body 
can  be  homogeneous. 

Note  2,  p.  187.  As  to  creatures  which  are  fisced,  &c.] 
These  include  such  species  of  the  Testacea  as  are  fixed 
to  one  habitat,  and  derive  nutriment  from  the  water  with 
which  they  are  surrounded ;  but  it  is  not  easy  to  deter- 
mine what  is  meant  by  the  term  dyevinjrov,  (spontaneously 
generated,)  as  this  mode  of  reproduction  was  attributed, 
by  Aristotle,  to  some  fishes  and  eels,  which  are  certainly 
neither  homogeneous  nor  insentient. 

Note  3,  p.  188.  The  otlter  senses,  being  for,  &c.]  It  may 
be  questioned  whether  this  description  is  absolutely  true, 

1  Hist.  Animalm,  iv.  6.  6.    vui.  i.  7. 

21 


3'2'2  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

as  there  are  creatures  •which,  although  fixed  to  one 
habitat,  not  capable  of  progression  that  is,  are  endowed 
with  all  the  senses,  although  it  may  be  in  some  modified, 
or  less  active  form  than  in  the  higher  animals.  For 
"  the  l  nervous  system  has  been  detected  in  every  division 
of  the  animal  kingdom,  and  almost  in  every  class,  and  it  is 
everywhere  connected  with  sensation  and  motion." 

Xote  -4,  p.  188.  Be  sensible  through  a  medium,  etc.] 
The  medium,  that  is,  made  diaphanous  and  motive  by 
colour  or  sound,  acts,  by  a  succession  of  undulations, 
upon  the  eye  or  the  ear,  and  finally,  through  the  humours 
of  the  former  and  the  air  in  the  latter,  upon  the  sentient 
part  of  these  organs ;  so  that  there  is  an  evident  analogy 
between  these  undulations  and  the  impulses  which  main- 
tain locomotion  until  lost  in  the  state  of  rest.  This 
succession  of  impulses  may  well  apply  to  the  changes 
which,  without  change  of  locality,  are  slowly  and  silently 
going  on  in  bodies,  and  be  compared  to  colouring  matter 
which  permeates  and  gradually  combines  with  each 
molecule  of  wax  up  to  saturation ;  but  every  substance 
cannot,  of  course,  be  thus  affected — a  stone,  for  instance, 
owing  to  the  condensation  of  its  particles,  cannot  be 
made  receptive  of  colour. 

Note  5,  p.  189.     The   air  if  mobile  in   the  highest 

degree,  <kc.]    The  nature  and  properties  of  the  atmosphere 

were  imperfectly  known,  as  has  been  said,  in  the  age  of 

Aristotle.      It  was  deemed  necessary  to  sensation  that 

1  Grant's  Outline*,  179. 


CH.  XII.]  NOTES.  323 

the  air  should  be  still  (for,  when  in  motion,  it  was  con- 
verted, according  to  opinion,  into  wind),  and  as  one  mass  ; 
and  as  this  aggregation  of  the  air  could  be  only  over 
smooth  surfaces,  the  outer  coat  of  the  eye  (the  cornea) 
seemed,  by  its  smoothness,  to  favour  Aristotle's  doctrine, 
that  vision  is  through  a  medium,  and  completed,  by 
refraction,  at  the  bottom  of  the  organ.  The  medium,  set 
in  motion,  by  colour,  was  said  to  give  motion,  by  successive 
impulses,  to  the  air  over  the  cornea,  which  communicated 
the  impulse  to  the  organ  within ;  and  this  superseded 
the  doctrine  that  vision  is  produced  by  rays  emanating 
from  the  eya  Thus,  "  the  air  (that  over  the  cornea),  in 
its  turn,  sets  vision  in  motion ;"  but  the  last  clause  of 
the  sentence  is  very  obscure,  and  offers,  as  some  com- 
mentators have  said,  "great  difficulties."  It  may,  per- 
chance, be  a  continuation  of  the  analogy  and  suggest 
that,  as  colouring  matter  acts,  successively,  until  each 
particle  is  saturated,  so  the  impulse  is  transmitted  to  the 
cornea,  and  finally,  from  it,  to  the  visual  faculty  within. 


324  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 


CHAPTER  XIII. 

Note  1,  p.  192.  The  Touch  is  made  sensible... aiid 
lience  its  name,  &c.]  The  text  refers  to  etymology  to 
shew,  that  as,  in  all  times,  it  had  been  noticed  that  the 
impression  upon  other  senses  is  different  from  that  upon 
Touch,  it  had  hence  obtained  its  appellation  a$»/,  which, 
being  derived  from  OTTTW,  (to  fasten  or  bind,)  signifies 
fastening  or  binding,  and  so  (by  touching,)  immediate 
contact ;  as  contact  is  necessary  for  the  sensation  of 
Touch.  This  may  suffice  for  the  explanation  of  the 
term  in  the  original,  but  it  may  not,  of  course,  be 
applicable  to  its  synonym  in  a  modern  language,  since  its 
origin  may  be  from  another  idea,  and,  therefore,  a  dif- 
ferent root. 

Note  2,  p.  192.  And  yet  the  other  sentient  organs,  <fec.] 
It  had  been  proved  analogically,  that,  as  bodies  in  the 
water  are  separated  by  the  water,  (as  was  supposed  to  be 
proved  by  their  extremities  being  wet,)  so  bodies  in  the 
air  are  separated  by  air,  and  therefore,  that,  as  no  one 
body  is  in  immediate  contact  with  another  body,  sensa- 
tion can  be  effected  only  through  a  medium ;  and  this 
was  supposed  to  hold  good  even  for  the  Touch.  Thus, 
the  medium,  acted  upon  and  acting  in  its  turn,  reduces 


CH.  XIII.J  NOTES.  325 

all  sensual  impressions  to  the  one  impression  by  contact, 
and  this  generalisation  is  supported  by  some  modern 
writers  and  regarded  as  the  theory  of  Sensation.  "  There  * 
may,  however,  be  many  other  impressions  derived  from 
outward  bodies,  for  which  the  sensitive  nerves  of  the 
lower  animals  are  adapted,  besides  those  which  affect  us, 
and  we  cannot  always  be  certain  of  the  identity  of  the 
feelings  communicated  to  them  by  organs  which  appear 
analogous  to  our  own." 

Note  3,  p.  193.  On  which  account,  other  sentient,  <fec.] 
This  is  consonant  with  the  opinion  that  the  Touch  is  the 
only  sense  necessary  to  animal  existence;  although  the 
organs  of  relation  are  required  for  the  higher  forms  of 
being.  Thus,  impressions  in  excess  upon  those  organs, 
whether  by  colour,  sound,  or  odour,  may  injure  or  pervert 
the  senses,  but  cannot  further  affect  the  individual ; 
while  tangible  impressions,  hot,  cold,  or  hard,  can 
together  with  the  sense  destroy  the  animal. 

Note  4,  p.  193.  Animals,  in  fact,  possess... the  other 
senses,  <fec.]  This  is  referrible,  of  course,  only  to  the 
higher  orders  of  animals,  as  they  alone  require  such 
organs  for  the  exercise  of  their  faculties,  and  the  enjoy- 
ment of  their  existence.  The  Tongue  is  here  introduced, 
whether  by  inadvertence  or  in  submission  to  common 
opinion,  as  if  it  were  a  sense,  or  the  sole  organ  for 
speech;  and  yet,  as  the  chief  of  the  organs  for  taste 

1  Grant's  Outlinet,  p.  248. 


326  NOTES.  [BK.  in. 

and  speech,  it  may  be  said  to  constitute  one  of  the 
distinguishing  features  of  humanity.  As  no  creature, 
however,  is  without  a  tongue,  it  can  scarcely  be  supposed 
to  be  wanting,  and  yet,  as  it  would  not  seem  to  be  so 
essential  as  some  other  parts,  life  might,  perhaps,  for  a 
time,  be  maintained  without  it.  But  speech  is,  of  course, 
nowise  necessary  to  life,  as  the  learned  commentator 
observes:  "Nam  etiam  linguae  sermone,  si  vitam,  de- 
tractis  ornamentis,  ad  necessitatis  angustias  redigere  velis, 
vitse  conservatio  carere  potest.:' 


Classical   Works  published  by  Macmittan 
and  Co. 


53SCHYLI  Eumenides. 

The  Greek  Text  with  English  Notes :  with  an  Introduction, 
containing  an  Analysis  of  C.  O.  Muller's  Dissertations ;  and 
an  English  Metrical  Translation-  By  BERNARD  DRAKE, 
M.A.,  Fellow  of  King's  College,  Cambridge ;  Editor  of  "  De- 
mosthenes de  Corona."  8vo.  cloth,  Is.  6d. 

DEMOSTHENES.— Translation  of  Demosthenes  on 

the  Crown.  By  the  Rev.  J.  P.  NORRIS,  M.A.,  Fellow  of 
Trinity  College,  Cambridge,  and  one  of  Her  Majesty's  Inspectors 
of  Schools.  Cloth,  3». 

FROST.— Thucydides,  Book  VI.    The  Greek  Text, 

and  English  Notes  ;  with  a  Map  of  Syracuse.  By  PERCIVAL 
FROST,  Jun.  M.A.,  late  Fellow  of  St.  John's  College,  Cam- 
bridge. 8vo.  cloth,  7*.  6rf. 

HUMPHREYS.  —  Exercitationes  lambicae  ;   or, 

Progressive  Exercises  in  Greek  Iambic  Verse.  To  which  are 
prefixed,  the  Rules  of  Greek  Prosody,  with  copious  Notes  and 
Illustrations  of  the  Exercises.  By  E.  R.  HUMPHREYS, 
LL.D.,  Head  Master  of  the  Cheltenham  Grammar  School. 
Second  Edition.  Fcap.  cloth,  5s.  6d. 


2 
JUVENAL— Juvenal:   chiefly  from  the  Text  of 

Jahn.  With  English  Notes  for  the  use  of  Schools.  By  J .  E.  B. 
MAYOR,  ;M.A.,  Fellow  and  Classical  Lecturer  of  St.  John's 
College,  Cambridge.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  10s.  6d. 

PLATO— The  Republic  of  Plato. 

Translated  into  English,  with  Notes.  By  Two  Fellows  of 
Trinity  College,  Cambridge,  (J.  LI.  Davies,  M.A.,  and  D.  J. 
Vaughan,  M.A.)  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  7s.  6d. 

SALLUST.— Sallust. 

The  Latin  Text,  with  English  Notes.  By  CHARLES  MERI- 
VALE,  B.D.,  late  Fellow  and  Tutor  of  St.  John's  College, 
Cambridge,  &c.,  Author  of  a  "  History  of  Rome,"  &c.  Crown 
8vo.  cloth,  5s. 

WRIGHT.— Hellenica ;  or,  a  History  of  Greece  in 

Greek,  beginning  with  the  Invasion  of  Xerxes ;  as  related  by 
Diodorus  and  Thucydides.  With  Explanatory  Notes,  Critical 
and  Historical,  for  the  use  of  Schools.  By  J.  WRIGHT,  M.A., 
of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge,  and  Head  Master  of  Sutton 
Coldfield  Grammar  School.  12mo.-  cloth,  3s.  6d. 

*,*  This  book  is  already  in  use  in  Rugby  and  other  Schools. 

WRIGHT.— A  Manual  of  Latin  Grammar;  or,  the 

Form  and  use  of  Words,  with  Progressive  Exercises  for  Be- 
ginners. By  J.  WRIGHT,  M.A.,  Head  Master  of  Sutton 
Coldfield  Grammar  School.  Crown  8vo.  In  the  Press. 


CAMBRIDGE,  May  1855. 

MACMILLAN    &   CO.'S 

PUBLICATIONS. 


JJSCHYLI  Eumenides. 

The  Greek  Text  with  English  Notes :  with  an  Introduction,  containing  an 
Analysis  of  C.  O.  Miiller's  Dissertations ;  and  an  English  Metrical  Translation. 
By  BERNARD  DRAKE,  M.A.,  Fellow  of  King's  College,  Cambridge;  Editor 
of  "  Demosthenes  de  Corona."  8vo.  cloth,  7».  6d. 

"AL-ADJRUMIIEH."— Elementary  Arabic  Grammar,  with  a 

Translation.  By  J.  J.  S.  PEROWNE,  M.A.  Fellow  of  Corpus  Christ!  College, 
Cambridge,  and  Lecturer  in  Hebrew  in  King's  College,  London.  8vo.  cloth,  5s. 

ANTHOLOGIA  Latina  Selecta. 

In  2  vols.    Small  8vo. 

Vot.  I. — Containing  select  Epigrams  of  Catullus,  Virgil,  Claudian,  Ausonius, 

•with  others  from  the  Anthologia  Latina.  • 

VOL.  II. — Containing  select  Epigrams  of  Martial. 

Edited  with  English  notes,  by  J.  E.  B.  MAYOR,  M.A.,  Fellow  and  Classical 
Lecturer  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge,  Editor  of  Juvenal. 

[Preparing. 

ARISTOPHANES.    The  Greek  Text  revised,  with  a  Com- 

•    mentary.    By  W.  G.  CLARK,  M.A.,  Fellow  and  Assistant  Tutor  of  Trinity 
College.  [Preparing. 

ARISTOTELES  de  Rhetorica.    The  Greek  Text,  with  English 

Notes.     By  A  FELLOW  OF  TRINITY  COLLEGE.  [Preparing. 

ARISTOTLE  on  the  Vital  Principle.    Translated  from  the 

Original  Text,  with  Notes.    By  CHARLES  COLLIER,  M.D.,  F,R.S. 

[In  the  Pren. 

BACON   AND   RALEIGH— Lord   Bacon  and    Sir   Walter 

Raleigh:  Critical  and  Biographical  Essays.  By  MACVEY  NAPIER,  late 
Editor  of  the  Edinburgh  Review  and  of  the  Encyclopedia  JBritannica.  Post 
8vo.  cloth,  7s.  6d. 

BENGELII  GNOMON  NOVI   TESTAMENTI,  in  quo  ex 

Nativa  Verborum  vi  simplicitas,  profunditas,  concinnitas,  salubritas  sen- 
suum  ccelestium  indicatur.  EDITIO  TERTIA.  Per  filium  superstitem 
M.  ERNESTUM  BENGELIUM,  quondam  curata,  quarta  recusa  adjuvante 
Johanne  Steudel.  Imperial  8vo.  cloth,  18*. 


2  MACMILLA.N  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 

BOLTON'S  Evidences  of  Christianity. 

The  Evidences  of  Christianity  as  exhibited  in  the  Writings  of  its  Apologists 
down  to  Augustine.  An  Essay  which  obtained  the  Hulsean  Prize  for  the 
Year  1852.  By  W.  J.  BOLTON,  of  Gonville  and  Caius  College,  Cambridge. 
8vo.  cloth,  6*. 

BOOLE.— The  Mathematical  Analysis  of  Logic. 

By  GEORGE  BOOLE,  Professor  of  Mathematics,  Cork.    8vo.  sewed,  5*. 

BRAVE  WORDS  for  BRAVE  SOLDIERS  and  SAILORS. 

Tenth  Thousand.     16mo.  sewed,  2d. ;  or  10*.  per  100. 

[Printed  for  Distribution. 

BUTLER  (Professor  Archer).— Sermons,  Doctrinal  and  Prac- 
tical. By  the  Rev.  WILLIAM  ARCHER  BUTLER,  M.A.  late  Professor 
of  Moral  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Dublin.  Edited,  with  a  Memoir  of 
the  Author's  Life,  by  THOMAS  WOODWARD,  M.A.  Vicar  of  Mullingar. 
With  Portrait.  Third  Edition.  8vo.  cloth,  12«. 

BUTLER  (Professor  Archer).— A  Second  Series  of  Sermons. 

Edited  from  the  Author's  Manuscripts,  by  J.  A.  JEREMIE,  D.D.  Regius 
Professor  of  Divinity  in  the  University  of  Cambridge.  [In  the  Preti. 

• 

BUTLER  (Professor  Archer).— Lectures  on  the  History  of 

Ancient  Philosophy.  By  the  Rev.  W.  ARCHER  BUTLER,  late  Professor 
of  Moral  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Dublin.  Edited,  from  the  Author's 
Manuscripts,  by  WILLIAM  HEPWORTH  THOMPSON,  M.A.  Regius  Professor 
of  Greek  in  the  University  of  Cambridge.  2  vols.  8vo. 

[Nearly  ready. 

BUTLER  (Professor  Archer).— Letters   on  Romanism,  in 

Reply  to  Mr.  NEWMAN'S  Essay  on  Development.    8vo.  cloth,  10*.  6d. 

CAMBRIDGE— Cambridge  Theological  Papers.    Comprising 

those  given  at  the  Voluntary  Theological  and  Crosse  Scholarship  Examina- 
tions. Edited,  with  References  and  Indices,  by  A.  P.  MOOR,  M.A.  of  Trinity 
College,  Cambridge,  and  Sub-warden  of  St.  Augustine's  College,  Canterbury. 
8 vo.  cloth,  7*.  6d. 

CAMBRIDGE  PROBLEMS.— Solutions  of  the  Senate-House 

Riders  for  Four  Years  (1848  to  1851).  By  F.  J.  JAMESON,  M.A.  Fellow 
of  Caius  College,  Cambridge.  8vo.  cloth,  7s.  6d. 

CAMBRIDGE    PROBLEMS.— Solutions    of    Senate-House 

Problems  for  Four  Years  (1848  to  1851).  By  N.  M.  FERRERS,  and 
J.  S.  JACKSON,  Fellows  of  Caius  College,  Cambridge.  8vo.  cloth,  15*.  6d. 


MACMILLA.N  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS.  3 

CAMBRIDGE   PROBLEMS,   1854— Solutions  of  the  Pro- 

blems  proposed  in  the  Senate  House  Examination,  January  1854.  By  the 
Moderators  (W.  WALTON,  M.A.  Trinity  College,  and  C.  F.  MACKENZIE, 
M.A.  Fellow  of  Caius  College).  In  8vo.  cloth,  10s.  Gd. 


CAMBRIDGE  IN  THE  SEVENTEENTH  CENTURY: 

Part.  I.  containing — Lives  of  NICHOLAS  FERRAU,  Fellow  of  Clare  Hall. 
By  His  BROTHEK  JOHN  and  hy  DR.  JEBB.  Edited,  with  Notes,  from  the 
MSS.  in  the  Public  Lihrary  and  in  St.  John's  College,  by  J.  E.  B.  MAYOR, 
M.A.  Fellow  and  Assistant  Tutor  of  St.  John's  College.  Fcp.  8vo.  7s.  6d. 


CAMBRIDGE.— Cambridge  Guide:  Including  Historical  and 

Architectural  Notices  of  the  Public  Buildings,  and  a  concise  Account  of  the 
Customs  and  Ceremonies  of  the  University,  with  a  Sketch  of  the  Places  most 
worthy  of  Note  in  the  County.  A  New  Edition,  with  Engravings  and  a  Map. 
12mo.  cloth,  5*.  6d. 

CAMBRIDGE   FITZWILLIAM  MUSEUM.-A  Hand-Book 

to  the  Pictures  in  the  Fitzwilliam  Museum,  Cambridge.  Crown  8vo.  sewed, 
Ts.  6d.;  or  in  cloth  elegant,  2*.  6d. 

CAMBRIDGE.  — Cambridge  Mathematical  Journal.    Vol.  I. 

Second  Edition,  8vo.  cloth,  18*. 

CAMBRIDGE.— Cambridge  and  Dublin  Mathematical  Journal. 

The  Complete  Work,  in  Nine  Vols.  8vo.  cloth,  71.  4s. 

ONLY   A   FEW   COPIES   OF   THE   COMPLETE    WORK   REMAIN  ON   BAND. 

CHRISTMAS    DAWN  and    NEW   YEAR'S  EVE  1854-5. 

Second  Edition.    Crown  8vo.  Is. 

CICERO.  -Cicero  on  Old  Age,  literally  Translated  by  an  M.A. 

12mo.  sewed,  2s.  Gil. 

CICERO.— Cicero  on  Friendship,  literally  Translated  by  an 

M.A.     12mo.  sewed,  2s.  6d. 

COLENSO.— Ten  Weeks  in  Natal.    A  Journal  of  a  First 

Tour  of  Visitation  among  the  Colonists  and  Zulu  Kafirs  of  Natal.    By  the 
Right  Rev.  JOHN  WILLIAM  COLENSO,  D.D.  Bishop  of   Natal,   with  a 
Map  and  Illustrations.    Fcap.  8vo.  cloth,  5». 
A  2 


4  MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 

COLENSO.— An  Ordination  and  Three  Missionary  Sermons. 

By  the  Right  Rev.  JOHN  WILLIAM  COLENSO,  D.D.  Bishop  of  Natal.    Is. 

COLENSO— Village  Sermons.  By  the  Right  Rev.  JOHN  WIL- 
LIAM COLENSO,  D.D.  Bishop  of  Natal.  Second  Edition.  Fcp.  8vo. 
cloth,  2*.  6d. 

COLENSO— The   Communion   Service,  'from  the  Book  of 

Common-Prayer,  with  Select  Readings  from  the  writings  of  the  Rev.  F.  D. 
MAURICE,  M.A.  Edited  by  the  Right  Rev.  JOHN  WILLIAM  COLENSO, 
D.D.,  Bishop  of  Natal.  Fine  Edition,  rubricated  and  bound  in  cloth, 
2s.  6d.  Common  Paper,  limp  cloth,  \s. 

COOPER.— A  Geometrical  Treatise  on  Conic  Sections.    By 

the  Rev.  J.  E.  COOPER,  M.A.  late  Fellow  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge. 

[Preparing. 

COTTON.— Sermons  on  Public  Events  of  1854.    By  G.  E. 

LYNCH  COTTON,  M.A.  Head  Master  of  Marlborough  College,  Wilts, 
formerly  Fellow  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge.  [Nearly  ready. 

DEMOSTHENES.— Demosthenes  de  Corona. 

The  Greek  Text,  with  English  Notes.  By  BERNARD  DRAKE,  M.A. 
Fellow  of  King's  Coll.  Cambridge,  Editor  and  Translator  of  the  "  Eumenides 
of  jEschylus."  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  5». 

DEMOSTHENES.  — Translation   of  Demosthenes    on  the 

Crown.  By  the  Rev.  J.  P.  NORRIS,  M.A.  Fellow  of  Trinity  College,  Cam- 
bridge, and  one  of  Her  Majesty's  Inspectors  of  Schools.  Cloth,  3s. 

DRAKE.— Notes  Explanatory  and  Critical  on  the  Books  of 

Jonah  and  Hosea.  By  the  Rev.  W.  DRAKE,  M.A.  late  Fellow  of  St.  John's 
College,  Cambridge.  8vo.  cloth,  9s. 

EUCLID.— Enunciations  and  Corollaries  of  the  Propositions 

of  the  First  Six  Books  of  Euclid,  together  with  the  Eleventh  and  Twelfth. 
18mo.  sewed,  1«. 

EVANS— Sonnets  on  the  Death  of  the  Duke  of  Wellington, 

by  SEBASTIAN  EVANS.    8vo.  sewed,  1*. 

FROST.— The  First  Three  Sections  of  Newton's  Principia. 

With  Notes  and  Problems  in  illustration  of  the  subject.  By  PERCIVAL 
FROST,  M.A.  late  Fellow  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge,  and  Mathe- 
matical Lecturer  of  Jesus  College.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  10s.  6d. 

FROST— Thucydides,  Book  VI.    The  Greek  Text,  and  English 

Notes  :  with  a  Map  of  Syracuse.  By  PERCIVAL  FROST,  Jun.  M.A.  late 
Fellow  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge.  8vo.  cloth,  7i.  6d. 


MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS.  6 

GODFRAY.— An  Elementary  Treatise  on  the  Lunar  Theory. 

With  a  brief  Sketch  of  the  History  of  the  Problem  up  to  the  time  of  Newton. 
By  HUGH  GODFRAY,  B.A.  of  St.  John's  CoTlege,  Cambridge".  8vo.  cloth, 
5s.  Gd. 

GRANT.— Plane  Astronomy. 

Including  Explanations  of  Celestial  Phenomena,  and  Descriptions  of  Astrono- 
mical Instruments.  By  A.  R.  GRANT,  M.A.  Fellow  of  Trinity  College, 
Cambridge.  Svo.  boards,  6s. 

GRIFFIN— The  Theory  of  Double  Refraction.    By  W.  N. 

GRIFFIN,  M.A.  late  Fellow  and  Assistant  Tutor  of  St.  John's  College,  Cam- 
bridge. Svo.  sewed,  2s. 

HALLIFAX.— Bishop  Hallifax's  Analysis  of  the  Civil  Law.   In 

which  a  comparison  is  occasionally  made  between  the  Roman  Laws  and  those 
of  England.  A  new  Edition,  with  alterations  and  additions,  being  the  heads 
of  a  Course  of  Lectures  publicly  delivered  in  the  University  of  Cambridge,  by 
.T.  W.  GELDART,  LL.D.  Svo.  bds.  8s.  6d  ;  interleaved,  10s.  6d.;  double  in- 
terleaved, 12*.  i>il. 

HARDWICK.— A  History  of  the  Christian  Church,  during  the 

Middle  Ages.  By  CHARLES  HARDWICK,  M.A.  Fellow  of  St.  Catha- 
rine's Hall,  and  late  Cambridge  Preacher  at  the  Chapel  Royal,  Whitehall. 
Author  of  "  A  History  of  the  XXXIX.  Articles."  With  Four  Maps  con- 
structed for  this  Work  by  A.  KEITH  JOHNSTON.  Crown  Svo.  cloth, 
10s.  6d. 

HARDWICK.— A  History  of  the  Christian  Church  during  the 

Reformation .  By  CHARLES  HARDWICK,  M.A.  Fellow  of  St.  Catharine's 
Hall,  Divinity  Lecturer  of  King's  College,  and  Christian  Advocate  in  the 
University  of  Cambridge.  [/«  the  Press. 

»«*  These  two   Books  are  part  of  a  Series  of  Theological  Manuals 
now  in  progress. 

HARDWICK.— Twenty  Sermons  for  Town  Congregations.   By 

CHARLES  HARDWICK,  M.A.  Fellow  of  St.  Catharine's  Hall,  Cambridge. 
Crown  Svo.  cloth,  6s.  6d. 

HARE.— Two  Sermons  preached  in  Herstmonceux  Church, 

on  Septuagesima  Sunday,  February  4,  1855,  being  the  Sunday  after  the 
Funeral  of  the  Venerable  Archdeacon  Hate.  By  the  Rev.  H.VENN  ELLIOTT, 
Perpetual  Curate  of  St.  Mary's,  Brighton,  late  Fellow  of  Trinity  College, 
Cambridge,  and  the  Rev.  J.  N.  SIMPKINSON,  Assis'tant  Master  of  Harrow 
School,  formerly  Curate  of  Herstmonceux.  Svo.  1*.  Gd. 


6  MACMILLA.N  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 

HELLENICA;  or,  a  History  of  Greece  in  Greek,  beginning 

with  the  Invasion  of  3fcrxes ;  as  related  by  Diodorus  and  Thucydides.  With 
Explanatory  Notes,  Critical  and  Historical,  for  the  Use  of  Schools.  By 
J.  WRIGHT,  M.A.  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge,  and  Head  Master  of  Suttun 
Coldfield  Grammar  School.  12mo.  cloth,  3s.  6d. 

HEMMING.— An  Elementary  Treatise  on  the  Differential 

and  Integral  Calculus.  For  the  Use  of  Colleges  and  Schools.  By  G.  W. 
HEMMING,  M.A.  Fellow  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge.  Second 
Edition,  with  Corrections  and  Additions.  8vo.  cloth,  9*. 

HERVEY.— The  Genealogies  of  our  Lord  and  Saviour  Jesus 

Christ,  as  contained  in  the  Gospels  of  St.  Matthew  and  St.  Luke,  reconciled, 
with  each  other  and  with  the  Genealogy  of  the  House  of  David,  from  Adam  to 
the  close  of  the  Canon  of  the  Old  Testament,  and  shown  to  be  in  harmony  with 
the  true  Chronology  of  the  Times.  By  Lord  ARTHUR  HERVEY,  M.A. 
Rector  of  Ickworth  with  Horringer.  8vo.  cloth,  10».  6d. 

HOWARD.— Genesis.     The  Septuagint  Version   translated 

into  English,  with  Notes,  critical  and  explanatory.  By  the  Hon.  HENRY 
E.  J.  HOWARD,  D.D.  Dean  of  Lichfield,  Succentor  and  Prebendary  of  York. 
Crown  8vo.  [In  the  Press. 

HOWES— A  History  of  the  Christian  Church  during  the  First 

Six  Centuries.    By  J.  G.  HOWES,  M.A.  Fellow  of  St.  Peter's  Coll.  Camb. 

[Preparing. 
*»*  This  is  part  of  a  Series  of  Theological  Manuals  now  in  progress. 

HUMPHREYS.— Exercitationes  lambicae;    or,  Progressive 

Exercises  in  Greek  Iambic  Verse.  To  which  are  prefixed,  the  Rules  of  Greek 
Prosody,  with  copious  Notes  and  Illustrations  of  the  Exercises.  By  E.  R. 
HUMPHREYS,  LL.D.  Head  Master  of  the  Cheltenham  Grammar  School. 
Second  Edition.  Fcap.  cloth,  St.  6d. 

HULBERT— The  Gospel  Revealed  to  Job:   or  Patriarchal 

Faith  and  Practice  illustrated.     By  C.  A.  HULBERT,  M.A.    8vo.  ctoth,  12*. 

JEWELL.— An  Apology  of  the  Church  of  England,  and  an 

Epistle  to  Seignior  Scipio  concerning  the  Council  of  Trent,  translated  from  the 
original  Latin,  and  illustrated  with  Notes,  chiefly  drawn  from  the  Author's 
"  Defence  of  the  Apology."  By  A.  T.  RUSSELL.  Fcp.  8vo.  bds.  5*. 

JUSTIN    MARTYR.— S.    Justini    Philosophi    et    Martyris 

Apologia  Prima.  Edited,  with  a  corrected  Text,  and  English  Introduction 
and  explanatory  Notes,  by  W.  TROLLOPE,  M.A.  Pembroke  College,  Cam- 
bridge. 8vo.  bds.  Is.  6d. 

JUSTIN  MARTYR.— Justin  Martyr's  Dialogue  with  Trypho 

the  Jew.  Translated  from  the  Greek  Text,  with  Notes,  chiefly  for  the  ad- 
vantage of  Engfish  Readers.  A  preliminary  Dissertation  and  a  short  Analysis. 
By  HENRY  BROWN,  M.A.  8vo.  bds.  9s. 


MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS.  7 

JUVENAL.— Juvenal :  chiefly  from  the  Text  of  Jahn. 

With  English  Notes  for  the  Use  of  Schools.    By  J.  E.  B.  MAYOR,  M.A. 

Fellow  and  Classical  Lecturer  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge.  "Crown  8vo. 

cloth,  105.  6d. 

• 

KINGSLEY.— "  Westward  Ho !"  or,  the  Voyages  and  Adven- 
tures of  Sir  Amyas  Leigh,  Knight,  of  Burrough,  in  the  County  of  Devon,  in 
the  Reign  of  Her  Most  Glorious  Majesty  Queen  Elizabeth.  Rendered  into 
modem  English  by  CHARLES  KINGSLEY.  3  vols.  post  8vo.  II.  lit.  6d. 

KINGSLEY.— Glaucus ;  or,  the  Wonders  of  the  Shore.   By 

CHARLES  KINGSLEY.    Fcap.  8vo.  cloth.  [Nearly  ready. 

KINGSLEY.— Alexandria  and  Her  Schools :  being  Four  Lec- 
tures delivered  at  the  Philosophical  Institution,  Edinburgh.  With  a  Preface. 
By  CHARLES  KINGSLEY,  Canon  of  Middleham,  and  Rector  of  Eversley  ; 
Author  of  "  Phaethon."  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  5». 

KINGSLEY.— Phaethon ;    or    Loose    Thoughts    for    Loose 

Thinkers.  By  CHARLES  KINGSLEY,  Canon  of  Middleham  and  Rector 
of  Eversley;  Author  of  "The  Saint's  Tragedy,"  &c.  Second  Edition. 
Crown  8vo.  boards,  '2s. 

LATHAM.— Geometrical  Problems  in  the  Properties  of  Conic 

Sections.  By  H.  LATHAM,  M.A.  Fellow  and  Tutor  of  Trinity  Hall.  8vo. 
sewed,  St.  Cd. 

LE  BAS.   Prize  Essay. 

1849.    SCOTT  (C.  B.)  2*.  6d. 

LETTERS  from  Italy  and  Vienna. 

Small  Svo.  cloth,  5s.  Gd. 

LUND.- A  Short  and  Easy* Course  of  Algebra. 

Chiefly  designed  for  the  use  of  the  Junior  Classes  in  Schools,  with  a  numerous 
collection  of  Original  easy  Exercises.  By  THOMAS  LUND,  B.D.  late  Fellow 
of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge.  Second  Edition.  12mo.  cloth,  3s.  Gd. 

LUSHINGTON.— Points  of  War,  I.  II.  III.  IV. 

By  FRANKLIN  LUSHINGTON,  Fellow  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge. 
Second  Edition.  Crown  Svo.  sewed,  Gd. 

LUSHINGTON. -Two    Battle-pieces.    By  HENRY  and 

FRANKLIN  LUSHINGTON.    Crown  Svo.  sewed,  I/. 

MACKENZIE— The  Beneficial  Influence  of  the  Clergy  during 

the  first  Thousand  Years  of  the  Christian  Era.  By  the  late  HENRY 
MACKENZIE,  B.A.  Scholar  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge.  Crown  Svo. 
cloth.  [In  tht  Prett. 


8  MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 

M  COY. — Preparing  for  Publication;  to  be  completed  in  about  Five  Parts, 
price  5*.  each,  forming  One  Volume  8vo.  of  about  500  pages,  with  nearly  1,000 
illustrations  in  the  text,  drawn  and  engraved  by  the  Author, 

A  Manual  of  the  Genera  of  British  Fossils. 

Comprising  Systematic  Descriptions  of  all  the  Classes,  Orders,  Families,  and 
Genera  of  Fossil  Animals  found  in  the  Strata  of  the  British  Isles ;  with 
figures  of  all  the  Generic  Types.  By  FREDERICK  M'COY,  F.G.S.,  Hon. 
F.C.P.S.,  Professor  of  Natural  History  in  the  University  of  Melbourne,  Author 
of  "  Characters  of  the  Carboniferous  Limestone  Fossils  of  Ireland,"  "  Synopsis 
of  the  Silurian  Fossils  of  Ireland,"  one  of  the  Authors  of  "  Sedgwick  and 
M'Coy's  British  Palaeozoic  Rocks  and  Fossils,"  &c. 

M  COY. — Preparing  for  Publication,  in  One  Volume,  crown  8vo.  with  numerous 
Illustrations, 

An  Elementary  Introduction  to  the  Study  of  Palaeontology. 

With  numerous  Figures  illustrative  of  Structural  Details. 

*»*  This  little  Work  is  intended  to  supply  all  that  elementary  information  on  the 
Structure  of  Fossil  Animals,  with  reference  to  the  most  nearly  allied  existing 
types,  illustrated  explanation  of  technical  terms,  &c.  which  the  beginner  may 
require,  but  which  would  be  out  of  place  in  the  Author's  systematic  volume 
on  the  Genera. 

M'COY.— Contributions  to  British  Palaeontology;  or,  First  De- 
scriptions of  several  hundred  Fossil  Radiata,  Articulata,  Mollusca,  and  Pisces, 
from  the  Tertiary,  Cretaceous,  Oolitic,  and  Palaeozoic  Strata  of  Great  Britain. 
With  numerous  Woodcuts.  8vo.  cloth,  9*. 

*»•  This  forms  a  complete  Series  of  the  Author's  Papers  from  the  "  Annals  of 
Natural  History." 

M'COY    AND    SEDGWICK'S    British    Paleozoic    Fossils. 

Part  I.  4to.  sewed,  16». 


Part  II.  4to.  sewed,  10*. 
Part  III.  just  ready. 


MAURICE.— Lectures  on  the  Ecclesiastical  History  of  the 

First  and  Second  Centuries.     By   FREDERICK    DEN1SON   MAURICE, 
M.A.  Chaplain  of  Lincoln's  Inn.    8vo.  cloth,  10*.  GU. 

MAURICE.— The  Unity  of  the   New  Testament,  being  a 

Synopsis  of,  and  Commentary  on,  the  first  three  Gospels,  and  the  Epistles  of 
S.  James,  S.  Jude,  S.  Peter,  and  S.  Paul.     8vo.  cloth,  Us. 

MAURICE— On  the  Old  Testament. 

Second  Edition.  [In  the  Presi. 


MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS.  9 

MAURICE— The  Prophets  and  Kings  of  the  Old  Testament. 

Crown  Svo.  cloth.    Second  Edition.    10*.  6d. 

MAURICE.— Theological  Essays. 

Second  Edition,  with  a  new  Preface  and  other  additions.  Crown  Svo. 
cloth,  10*.  6d. 

MAURICE.— The  Doctrine   of  Sacrifice  deduced  from  the 

Scriptures.  With  a  Dedicatory  Letter  to  the  Young  Men's  Christian  Associa- 
tion. Crown  Svo.  cloth,  It.  6d. 

MAURICE— On  the  Epistle  to  the  Hebrews. 

Svo.  7s.  6d. 

MAURICE.— Christmas  Day,  and  other  Sermons. 

Svo.  cloth,  10i.  6d. 

MAURICE.— The  Religions  of  the  World,  and  their  relations 

to  Christianity.    Third  Edition.    Fcap.  Svo.  cloth,  5*. 

MAURICE.— The  Prayer-Book  considered,  especially  in  re- 
ference to  the  Romish  System.  Second  Edition.  Fcap.  Svo.  cloth,  5s.  6d. 

MAURICE.— The  Church  a  Family.    Twelve  Sermons  on  the 

Occasional  Services  of  the  Prayer-Book.    Fcap.  Svo.  cloth,  4*.  6d. 

MAURICE— On  the  Lord's  Prayer. 

Third  Edition.    Fcap.  Svo.  cloth,  2s.  6d. 

MAURICE— On  the  Sabbath  Day:    the  Character  of  the 

Warrior;  and  on  the  Interpretation  of  History.    Fcap.  STO.  cloth,  2*.  6d. 

MAURICE.— Learning  and  Working.— Six  Lectures  delivered 

in  Willis's  Rooms,  London,  in  June  and  July,  1854.  The  Religion  of 
Rome,  and  its  influence  on  Modern  Civilization.— Four  Lec- 
tures delivered  in  the  Philosophical  Institution  of  Edinburgh,  in  December 
1854.  In  One  Volume,  Crown  Svo.  cloth.  5s. 

MAURICE —Has  the  Church  or  the  State  the  Power  to 

Educate  the  Nation  I  A  Course  of  Lectures  delivered  in  June  and  July,  1839. 
Crown  Svo.  cloth,  6s.  6d. 


10  MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 

MAURICE.— An  Essay  on  Eternal  Life  and  Eternal  Death, 

and  the  Preface  to  the  new  Edition  of  "  Theological  Essays."  Crown  8vo. 
sewed,  Is.  6<J. 

*»*  Published  separately  for  the  purchasers  of  the  first  edition. 

MAURICE.— The  Word  "Eternal,"  and  the  Punishment  of 

the  Wicked.  A  Letter  to  the  Rev.  Dr.  Jelf,  Principal  of  King's  College. 
London.  Fifth  Thousand.  8vo.  Is. 

MAURICE.— The  Name  "Protestant:"  the  Seemingly  Double 

Character  of  the  English  Church;  and  the  English  Bishopric  at  Jerusalem. 
Three  Letters  to  the  Rev.  Wm.  Palmer,  Fellow  and  Tutor  of  Magdalen 
College,  Oxford.  Second  Edition.  8vo.  3s. 

MAURICE.— On  Right  and  Wrong  Methods  of  Supporting 

Protestantism.    A  Letter  to  Lord  Ashley.     8vo.  1*. 

MAURICE.— Thoughts  on  the  Duty  of  a  Protestant,  in  the 

Oxford  Election  of  1847.     8vo.  Is. 

MAURICE.— The  Case  of  Queen's  College,  London. 

A  Letter  to  the  Lord  Bishop  of  London,  in  reply  to  the  "  Quarterly  Review." 
8vo.  Is. 

MAURICE.  — Lectures  on    Modern  History    and  English 

Literature.  [Preparing. 

MAURICE.— Law's  Remarks  on  the  Fable  of  the  Bees,  with 

an  Introduction  of  Eighty  Pages  by  FREDERICK  DEN1SON  MAURICE, 
M.A.  Chaplain  of  Lincoln's  Inn.  Fcp.  8vo.  cloth,  4i.  6d. 

"This  introduction  discusses  the  Religious,  Political,  Social,  and  Ethical  Theories  or  our 
day,  and  shows  the  special  worth  of  Law's  method,  and  how  far  it  is  applicable  to  our  cir- 


MERIVALE.-Sallust. 

The  Latin  Text,  with  English  Notes.  By  CHARLES  MERIVALE,  B.D. 
late  Fellow  and  Tutor  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge,  &c.  Author  of  a 
"  History  of  Rome,"  &c.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  5*. 

MINUCIUS  FELIX —The  Octavius  of  Minucius  Felix. 

Translated  into  English  by  LORD  HAILES.    Fcp.  8vo.  cloth,  3s.  6d. 

MOOR.— Cambridge  Theological    Papers,   comprising  those 

given  at  the  Voluntary  Theological  and  Crosse  Scholarship  Examinations. 
Edited,  with  References  and  Indices,  by  A.  P.  MOOR,  M.A.  of  Trinity  Col- 
lege, Cambridge,  and  Sub-Warden  of  St.  Augustine's  College,  Canterbury. 
8vo.  cloth,  Ji.  6d. 


MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS.  11 

NAPIER.— Lord  Bacon  and  Sir  Walter  Raleigh. 

Critical  and  Biographical  Essays.  By  MACVEY  NAPIER,  late  Editor 
of  the  Edinburgh  Review  and  of  the  Encyclopaedia  Britannica.  Post  8vo. 
cloth,  It.  6d. 

NIND.-Sonnets  of  Cambridge  Life.  By  Rev.  W.  NIND,  M.A. 

Fellow  of  St.  Peter's  College.    Post  8vo.  boards,  2s. 

NORRIS.— Ten  School-Room  Addresses. 

Edited  by  J.  P.  NORRIS,  M.A.  Fellow  of  Trinity  College,  and  one  of  Her 
Majesty's  Inspectors  of  Schools.  18mo.  sewed,  8rf. 

PARKINSON.— A  Treatise  on  Elementary  Mechanics. 

With  numerous  Examples.  By  S.  PARKINSON,  M.A.  Fellow  and  Assistant 
Tutor  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge.  [Preparing. 

PAYN.— Poems. 

By  JAMES  PAYN.    Fcp.  8vo.  cloth,  5s. 

PEARSON.    Elements  of  the  Calculus  of  Finite  Differences, 

treated  on  the  Method  of  the  Separation  of  Symbols.  By  J.  PEARSON,  M.A. 
Rector  of  St.  Edmund's  Norwich,  Mathematical  Master  of  Norwich  Grammar 
School,  and  formerly  Scholar  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge.  Second 
Edition,  enlarged.  8vo.  5*.  . 

PHEAR.— Elementary  Mechanics. 

Accompanied  by  numerous  Examples  solved  Geometrically.  By  J.  B. 
PHEAR,  M.A.,  Fellow  and  Mathematical  Lecturer  of  Clare  Hall,  Cambridge. 
8vo.  cloth,  106.  6d. 

PHEAR.— Elementary  Hydrostatics. 

Accompanied  by  numerous  Examples.    Crown  8vo.  cloth,  5*.  6d. 

PLATO— The  Republic  of  Plato. 

Translated  into  English,  with  Notes.  By  Two  Fellows  of  Trinity  College, 
Cambridge,  (J.  LI.  Davies  M.A.,  and  D.  J.  Vaughan,  M.A.)  Crown  8vo. 
cloth,  It.  Cut. 


PRATT— The     Mathematical    Principles    of    Mechanical 

Philosophy.    By  J.  H.  PRATT,  M.A.,  Fellow  of  Caius  College. 

»»»  The  abore  work  ii  now  out  of  Print:  but  the  Part  on  STATICS  has  been  re- 
edited  by  Mr.  Todhunter,  with  numerous  alterations  and  additions:  the  Part  on 
DYNAMICS,  by  Messrs.  Tail  andSteele,  is  preparing.  The  other  parts  will  be  pub- 
lished in  separate  forms,  improved  and  altered  as  may  seem  needful. 


12  MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 

PROCTER.— A  History  of  the  Book  of  Common  Prayer:  with 

a  Rationale  of  its  Offices.   By  FRANCIS  PROCTER,  M.A.,  Vicar  of  Witton, 
Norfolk,  and  late  Fellow  of  St.  Catharine  Hall.     Crown  8vo.  cloth,  10«.  6d. 
%*  This  is  part  of  a  series  of  Theological  Manuals,  now  in  progress. 

PUCKLE.— An  Elementary  Treatise  on  Conic  Sections  and 

Algebraical  Geometry.  With  a  numerous  collection  of  Easy  Examples  pro- 
gressively arranged,  especially  designed  for  the  use  of  Schools  and  Beginners. 
By  G.  HALE  PUCKLE,  M.A.,  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge,  Mathematical 
Master  in  the  Royal  Institution  School,  Liverpool.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  7*.  6d. 

QUINTILIAN— Quintilian,  Book  X. 

With  a  literal  Translation.    12mo.  sewed,  2s.  Gd. 

RAMSAY.— The  Catechiser's  Manual;  or,  the  Church  Cate- 
chism illustrated  and  explained,  for  the  use  of  Clergymen,  Schoolmasters, 
and  Teachers.  By  ARTHUR  RAMSAY,  M.A.  of  Trinity  College, 
Cambridge.  18mo.  cloth,  3*.  6U. 

REICHEL.—  The  Lord's  Prayer  and  other  Sermons. 

By  C.  P.  REICHEL,  B.C.,  Professor  of  Latin  in  the  Queen's  University 
Assistant  Preacher  in  the  Parish  Church,  Belfast;  and  Chaplain  tohis  Excel- 
lency the  Lord  Lieutenant  of  Ireland.     Crown  8vo.  [Nearly  Ready. 

THE  RESTORATION  OF  BELIEF. 

Complete  in  One  Volume,  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  8s  6d. 

CONTENTS. — Part  I.    Christianity  in  relation  to  its  Ancient  and  Modern  Anta- 
gonists.   2s.  6d. 

CONTENTS. — Part  II.   On  the  Supernatural  Element  contained  in  the  Epistles, 
and  its  bearing  on  the  argument.     '2s.  Gd. 

CONTENTS. — Part  III.    The  Miracles  of  the  Gospels  considered  in  their  rela- 
tion to  the  principal  features  of  the  Christian  Scheme.     3». 
• 

ROBINSON.— Missions  urged  upon  the  State  on  grounds 

both  of  Duty  and  Policy.  An  Essay  which  obtained  the  Maitland  Prize  in 
the  year  1852.  By  C.  K.  ROBINSON,  M.A.,  Fellow  and  Assistant  Tutor  of 
St.  Catharine's  Hall,  Cambridge.  Fcp.  8vo.  cloth,  3s. 

ROSE  (Henry  John).— An  Exposition  of  the  Articles  of  the 

Church  of  England.  By  HENRY  JOHN  ROSE,  B.D.  late  Fellow  of  St. 
John's  College,  and  Hulsean  Lecturer  in  the  University  of  Cambridge. 

[Preparing. 
*»*  This  is  part  of  a  Series  of  Theological  Manuals  now  in  progress. 

SALLUST— Sallust. 

The  Latin  Text,  with  English  Notes.  By  CHARLES  MERIVALE,  B.D., 
late  Fellow  and  Tutor  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge,  &c.,  Author  of  a 
"History  of  Rome,"  &c.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  5s. 


MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS.  13 

SELWYN.— The  Work  of  Christ  in  the  World.  Four  Sermons, 

preached  before  the  University  of  Cambridge,  on  the  four  Sundays  preceding 
the  Advent  of  our  Lord,  1854.  By  the  Right  Rev.  GEORGE  AUGUSTUS 
SELWYN,  D.D.  Bishop  of  New  Zealand,  and  formerly  Fellow  of  St.  John's 
College.  Third  Edition.  Crown  8vo.  2«. 

SIMPSON —An  Epitome  of  the   History  of  the  Christian 

Church  during  the  first  Three  Centuries  and  during  the  Time  of  the  Refor- 
mation, adapted  for  the  use  of  Students  in  the  Universities  and  in  Schools. 
By  WILLIAM  SIMPSON,  M.A.  With  Examination  Questions.  2d  Edition, 
Improved.  Fcp.  8vo.  cl'oth,  5s. 

SMITH.— Arithmetic  and  Algebra,  in  their  Principles  and 

Application:  with  numerous  systematically  arranged  Examples,  taken  from 
the  Cambridge  Examination  Papers.  With  especial  reference  to  the  ordinary 
Examination  for  B.A.  Degree.  By  BARNARD  SMITH,  M.A.,  Fellow  of  St. 
Peter's  College,  Cambridge.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  lOj.  6d. 

SMITH —Arithmetic  for  the  use  of  Schools.    By  BARNARD 

SMITH,  M.A.  Fellow  of  St.  Peter's  College.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  4s.  6d. 
*»*  This  has  been  published  in  accordance  with  very  numerous  requests  from 
Schoolmasters  and  Inspectors  of  Schools.  It  comprises  a  complete  reprint  of  the 
Arithmetic  from  Mr.  Smith's  larger  work,  with  such  alterations  as  were  necessary 
in  separating  it  from  the  Algebra ;  with  many  additional  Examples,  and  references 
throughout  to  the  Decimal  System  of  Coinage. 

SMITH.— Mechanics  and  Hydrostatics,  in  their  Principles 

and  Application :  with  numerous  systematically  arranged  Examples,  taken 
from  the  Cambridge  Examination  Papers.  With  a  special  reference  to  the 
Ordinary  Examination  for  B.A.  Degree.  By  BARNARD  SMITH,  M.A. 
Fellow  of  St.  Peter's  College,  Cambridge.  [Preparing. 

SNOWBALL— The    Elements    of    Plane    and    Spherical 

Trigonometry.  Greatly  improved  and  enlarged.  By  J.  C.  SNOWBALL,  M.A. 
Fellow  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge.  A  New  and  Cheaper  (THE  EIGHTH) 
Edition.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  7s.  6d. 

TAIT  and  STEELE  —  A  Treatise  on  Dynamics,  with  nume- 
rous Examples.  By  P.  G.  TAIT,  Fellow  of  St.  Peter's  College,  and  Professor 
of  Mathematics  in  Queen's  College,  Belfast,  and  W.  J.  STEELE,  Fellow  of 
St.  Peter's  College.  [Preparing. 

This  will  be  a  new  Edition  of  that  part  of  Pratt's  Mechanical  Philosophy 
which  treats  of  Dynamics,  with  all  the  additions  and  improvements  that 
seem  needful. 

THEOCRITUS.-Theocritus. 

The  Greek  Text,  with  English  notes,  Critical  and  Explanatory,  for  the  use  of 
Colleges  and  Schools.  By  E.  H.  PEROWNE,  M.A.,  Fellow  of  Corpus 
Christi  College.  Crown  8vo.  [Nearly  Ready. 


14,  MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 

THEOLOGICAL  Manuals. 

Just  published  : — 

CHURCH  HISTORY:  THE  MIDDLE  AGES.  By  CHARLES  HARD- 
WICK.  With  Four  Maps.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  price  10*.  Crf. 

THE  COMMON  PRAYER:  ITS  HISTORY  AND  RATIONALE.  By 
FRANCIS  PKOCTER.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  10s.  6d. 

A  HISTORY  OF  THE  CANON  OF  THE  NEW  TESTAMENT.  By 
B.  F.  WESTCOTT.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  10*.  6d. 

In  the  Press  :— 

CHUnCH  HISTORY,  THE  REFORMATION.  By  CHARLES  HARD- 
WICK. 

The  following  will  shortly  appear: — 

INTRODUCTION  TO  THE  STUDY  OF  THE  OLD  TESTAMENT. 
NOTES  ON  ISAIAH. 
INTRODUCTION  TO  THE  STUDY  OF  THE  GOSPELS. 

EPISTLES. 

NOTES  ON  THE  GOSPELS  AND  ACTS. 

• EPISTLES  AND  APOCALYPSE. 

CHURCH  HISTORY,  THE  FIRST  SIX  CENTURIES. 

17m  CENTURY  TO  THE  PRESENT  TIME. 

THE  THREE  CREEDS. 

THE  THIRTY-NINE  ARTICLES. 

*»*  Others  are  in  progress,  and  will  he  announced  in  due  time. 

THRING  —  1.  The  Elements  of  Grammar  taught  in  English, 

By  the  Rev.  E.  THRING,  M.A.  late  Fellow  of  King's  College,  Cambridge, 
Head  Master  of  the  Royal  Grammar  School,  Uppingham.  Second 
Edition.  18mo.  bound  in  cloth,  2s. 

THRING- 2.    The  Child's  Grammar. 

Being  the  substance  of  the  above,  with  Examples  for  Practice.  Adapted  for 
Junior  Classes.  A  New  Edition.  18mo.  limp  cloth,  \s. 

THRUPP.— Psalms  and  Hymns  for  Public  Worship.    Selected 

and  Edited  by  JOSEPH  FRANCIS  THRUPP,  M.A.  Vicar  of  Barrington, 
late  Fellow  of  Trinity  College.  18mo.  cloth,  2t.  Second  paper  in  limp 
cloth,  la.  id. 

THRUPP.— Antient  Jerusalem:  a  New  Investigation  into  the 

History,  Topography,  and  Plan  of  the  City,  Environs,  and  Temple.  Designed 
to  illustrate  the  records  of  Scripture,  and  including  Remarks  on  several  of  the 
Prophecies,  and  especially  on  the  Prophetical  Temple  of  Ezekiel.  With  Map 
and  Plans.  By  JOSEPH  FRANCIS  THRUPP,  M.A.  Vicar  of  Barrington, 
Cambridge,  and  late  Fellow  of  Trinity  College.  8vo.  cloth,  15*. 

TODHUNTER.— A  Treatise  on  the  Differential  Calculus ;  and 

the  Elements  of  the  Integral  Calculus.  With  numerous  Examples.  By 
I.  TODHUNTER,  M.A.,  Fellow  and  Tutor  of  St.  John's  College,  Cambridge. 
Crown  8vo.  cloth,  10*.  6d. 


MACMILLAN  &  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS.  15 

TODHUNTER.  —  A  Treatise  on  Analytical   Statics,  with 

numerous  Examples.    Crown  8vo.  cloth,  10s.  6d. 

TODHUNTER.-A  Treatise  on  Plane  Coordinate  Geometry. 

With  numerous  Examples.    For  the  Use  of  Colleges  and  Schools. 

[Nearly  ready. 

TODHUNTER.  — A  Treatise   on  Algebra,  for  the  Use  of 

Students  in  the  Universities,  and  of  the  Higher  Classes  in  Schools. 

[Preparing. 

Also  by  the  tame  Author, 

An  Elementary  Work  on  the  same  subject,  for  the  use  of 

Beginners. 

TRENCH— Synonyms  of  the  New  Testament. 

By  RICHARD  CHENEVIX  TRENCH,  B.D.,  Vicar  of  Itchenstoke.  Hants, 
Professor  of  Divinity,  King's  College,  London,  and  Examining  Chaplain  to 
the  Bishop  of  Oxford.  Second  Edition,  revised.  Fcp.  8vo.  cloth,  5s. 

TRENCH— Hulsean  Lectures  for  1845—46.    Third  Edition. 

CONTENTS.  1. — The  Fitness  of  Holy  Scripture  for  unfolding  the  Spiritual  Life 
of  Man.  2.— Christ  the  Desire  of  all  Nations  ;  or  the  Unconscious  Pro- 
phecies of  Heathendom.  Foolscap  8vo.  cloth,  at, 

For  VERIFYING  DATES. 

A  perpetual  Almanac  for  determining  Dates  past,  present,  and  future;  wit  h 
a  Lunar  Kalendar  and  Tables  of  the  more  important  Periods,  ^ras,  Festivals, 
and  Anniversaries.  Price  6d. 

***  This  is  so  printed,  that  if  the  margin  be  cut  off  it  may  be  carried  in  a 
pocket-book. 

WESTCOTT.— A  general  View  of  the  History  of  the  Canon  of 

the  New  Testament  during  the  First  Four  Centuries.  By  BROOKE  FOSS 
WESTCOTT,  M.A.,  late  Fellow  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge,  Assistant 
Master  of  Harrow  School.  Crown  8vo.  cloth,  10*.  6d. 

WESTCOTT —An  Introduction  to  the  Study  of  the  Gospels ; 

Including  a  new  and  improved  Edition  of  "  The  Elements  of  the  Gospel 
Harmony."  With  a  Catena  on  Inspiration,  from  the  Writings  of  the  Ante- 
Nicene  Fathers.  Crown  8vo.  cloth.  [SAor/fj. 

>*  These  two  books  are  part  of  a  series  of  Theological  Manuals  which  are  now  in 
progress. 


16  MACMILLAN  4  CO.'S  PUBLICATIONS. 

WESTCOTT.— An  Introduction  to  the  Study  of  the  Canonical 

Epistles ;  including  an  attempt  to  determine  their  separate  purposes  and 
mutual  relations.  By  BROOKE  FOSS  WESTCOTT,  M.A.,  late  Fellow  of 
Trinity  College,  Assistant  Master  in  Harrow  School.  [Shortly. 

«,*  This  book  is  part  of  a  series  of  Theological  Manuals  which  are  now  in  progress. 

WILSON.— A  Treatise  on  Dynamics. 

By  W.  P.  WILSON,  M.A.,  Fellow  of  St.  John's,  Cambridge,  and  Professor  of 
Mathematics  in  the  University  of  Melbourne.  8vo.  bds.  9*.  6d. 

% 

WRIGHT.— Hellenica ;  or,  a  History  of   Greece  in'  Greek, 

beginning  with  the  Invasion  of  Xerxes ;  as  related  by  Diodorus  and  Thucy- 
dides.  With  Explanatory  Notes,  Critical  and  Historical,  for  the  use  of 
Schools.  By  J.  Wright,  M.A.,  of  Trinity  College,  Cambridge,  and  Head- 
Master  of  Sutton  Coldneld  Grammar  School.  12mo.  cloth,  3*.  6d. 

*»*  This  book  is  already  in  use  in  Rugby  and  other  Schools. 


THE  JOURNAL 


CLASSICAL  AND  SACRED  PHILOLOGY. 

No.  ir.for  March  1855,  4*. 
Volume  I.   for  1854,   now  ready,  cloth  lettered,   12*.  6<J. 

CASES   CAN    BE    RAD   FOR    BINDING   VOL.  I. 

*»*  Three  Numbers  published  annually,  at  4*.  each. 


Camtrrtge:  MACMILLAN  !c  Co. 
lonfion  :  BELL  &  DALDT,  ISC,  FLEET-STREET. 

Dublin  :  HODGES  &  SMITH.          «?Binburgt) :  EDMONSTON  &  DOUGLAS. 
GlasgotD :  JAS.  MACLEHOSE. 


K.  CLAT,  PRINTER,  BREAD  STREET  HILL. 


UC  SOUTHERN  REGIONAL  LIBRARY  FACILITY 


A     000  085  839     9