Skip to main content

Full text of "Aristotle"

See other formats


CD 


■CNJ 
■CD 


•CD 


CO 


B 

485 

T27 
1919 

cop. 2 


Presented  to  the 
LIBRARY  of  the 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO 

by 
The  Estate  of  -ttie  late 
Professor  A.S.P.  Woodhouse 
Head  of  the  English 
Dept. 
19U-1964 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2007  with  funding  from 

IVIicrosoft  Corporation 


http://www.archive.org/details/aristotleOOtayluoft 


THE 
^  PEOPLE'S 

^^        BOOKS 


ARISTOTLE 


ARISTOTLE 


BY 


A.  E.  TAYLOR,  M.A.,  D.Litt.,  F.B.A. 


REVISED  EDITION 


T.  C.  &  E.  C.  JACK,  LTD.  |  T.  NELSON  &  SONS,  LTD. 

1919 


h2^ 


^  JAN  2  6  iSSo 


CONTENTS 

I.    LIFE   AND   WORKS 9 

II.    THE       CLASSIFICATION       OF       THE       SCIENCES  : 

SCIENTIFIC   METHOD  .  .  .  .19 

III.    FIRST    PHILOSOPHY 49 

IV.    PHYSICS 70 

V.    PRACTICAL   PHILOSOPHY  .  .  •  .99 

BIBLIOGRAPHY 125 


ARISTOTLE 

CHAPTER  I 

LIFE   AND   WORKS 

It  has  not  commonly  been  the  lot  of  philosophers,  as 
it  is  of  great  poets,  that  their  names  should  become 
household  words.  We  should  hardly  call  an  English- 
man well  read  if  he  had  not  heard  the  name  of 
Sophocles  or  Moliere.  An  educated  man  is  expected 
to  know  at  least  who  these  great  writers  were,  and 
to  understand  an  allusion  to  the  Antigone  or  Le  Mis- 
anthrope. But  we  call  a  man  well  read  if  his  mind 
is  stored  with  the  verse  of  poets  and  the  prose  of 
historians,  even  though  he  were  ignorant  of  the 
fame  of  Descartes  or  Kant.  Yet  there  are  a  few 
philosophers  whose  influence  on  thought  and  lan- 
guage has  been  so  extensive  that  no  one  who  reads 
can  be  ignorant  of  their  names,  and  that  every  man 
who  speaks  the  language  of  educated  Europeans  is 
constantly  using  their  vocabulary.  Among  this  few 
Aristotle  holds  not  the  lowest  place.  We  have  all 
heard  of  him,  as  we  have  all  heard  of  Homer.  He 
has  left  his  impress  so  firmly  on  theology  that  many 
of  the  formulae  of  the  Churches  are  unintelligible 


10  AKISTOTLE. 

without  acquaintance  with  his  conception  of  the 
universe.  If  we  are  interested  in  the  growth  of 
modern  science  we  shall  readily  discover  for  ourselves 
that  some  knowledge  of  Aristotelianism  is  neces- 
sary for  the  understanding  of  Bacon  and  Galileo  and 
the  other  great  anti- Aristotelians  who  created  the 
"  modern  scientific  "  view  of  Nature.  If  we  turn  to 
the  imaginative  literature  of  the  modern  languages, 
Dante  is  a  sealed  book,  and  many  a  passage  of 
Chaucer  and  Shakespeare  and  Milton  is  half  un- 
meaning to  us  unless  we  are  at  home  in  the  outlines 
of  Aristotle's  philosophy.  And  if  we  turn  to  ordi- 
nary language,  we  find  that  many  of  the  familiar 
turns  of  modern  speech  cannot  be  fully  understood 
without  a  knowledge  of  the  doctrines  they  were  first 
forged  to  express.  An  Englishman  who  speaks  of 
the  "  golden  mean "  or  of  "  liberal  education,"  or 
contrasts  the  "  matter "  of  a  work  of  literature  with 
its  "  form,"  or  the  "  essential "  features  of  a  situation 
or  a  scheme  of  policy  with  its  "accidents,"  or 
"theory"  with  "practice,"  is  using  words  which 
derive  their  significance  from  the  part  they  play  in 
the  vocabulary  of  Aristotle.  The  unambitious  object 
of  this  little  book  is,  then,  to  help  the  English  reader 
to  a  better  understanding  of  such  familiar  language 
and  a  fuller  comprehension  of  much  that  he  will  find 
in  Dante  and  Shakespeare  and  Bacon  and  Milton. 

Life  of  Aristotle. — The  main  facts  of  Aristotle's 
life  may  be  briefly  told.  He  was  born  in  385-4  b.c. 
at  Stagirus,  a  little  city  of  the  Chalcidic  peninsula, 
still  called,  almost  by  its  ancient  name,  Chalcis,  and 
died  at  the  age  of  sixty-two  at  Chalcis  in  Euboea. 
Thus  he  is  a  contemporary  of  Demosthenes,  his  man- 
hood witnessed  the  struggle  which  ended  in  the 
establishment  of  the  Macedonian  monarchy   as   the 


LIFE  AND  WOEKS.  11 

dominant  power  in  Hellas,  and  his  later  years  the 
campaigns  in  which  his  pupil  Alexander  the  Great 
overthrew  the  Persian  Empire  and  carried  Greek 
civilisation  to  the  banks  of  the  Jumna.  In  studying 
the  constitutional  theories  of  Aristotle,  it  is  necessary 
to  bear  these  facts  in  mind.  They  help  to  explain 
certain  limitations  of  outlook  which  might  otherwise 
appear  strange  in  so  great  a  man.  It  throws  a  great 
deal  of  light  on  the  philosopher's  intense  conviction 
of  the  natural  inferiority  of  the  "barbarian"  in- 
tellect and  character  to  remember  that  he  grew  up 
in  an  outlying  region  where  the  "barbarian"  was 
seen  to  disadvantage  in  the  ordinary  course  of  life. 
Hence  the  distinction  between  Greek  and  "bar- 
barian" came  to  mean  for  him  much  what  the 
"  colour-line "  does  to  an  American  brought  up  in  a 
Southern  State.  So,  again,  when  we  are  struck  by 
his  "provincialism,"  his  apparent  satisfaction  with 
the  ideal  of  a  small  self-contained  city-state  with  a 
decently  oligarchical  government,  a  good  system  of 
public  education,  and  no  "  social  problems,"  but 
devoid  alike  of  great  traditions  and  far-reaching 
ambitions,  we  must  remember  that  the  philosopher 
himself  belonged  to  just  such  a  tiny  community  with- 
out a  past  and  without  a  future.  The  Chalcidic  cities 
had  been  first  founded,  as  the  name  of  the  peninsula 
implies,  as  colonies  from  the  town  of  Chalcis  in 
Euboea ;  Corinth  had  also  been  prominent  in  estab- 
lishing settlements  in  the  same  region.  At  the 
height  of  Athenian  Imperial  prosperity  in  the  age 
of  Pericles  the  district  had  fallen  politically  under 
Athenian  control,  but  had  been  detached  again  from 
Athens,  in  the  last  years  of  the  Archidamian  war,  by 
the  genius  of  the  great  Spartan  soldier  and  diplomat 
Brasidas.     Early  in  the  fourth  century  the  Chalcidic 


12  AKISTOTLE. 

cities  had  attempted  to  form  themselves  into  an 
independent  federation,  but  the  movement  had  been 
put  down  by  Sparta,  and  the  cities  had  fallen  under 
the  control  of  the  rising  Macedonian  monarchy,  when 
Aristotle  was  a  baby.  A  generation  later,  a  double 
intrigue  of  the  cities  with  Philip  of  Macedon  and 
Athens  failed  of  its  effect,  and  the  peninsula  was 
finally  incorporated  with  the  Macedonian  kingdom. 
It  is  also  important  to  note  that  the  philosopher  be- 
longed by  birth  to  a  guild,  the  Asclepiadae,  in  which 
the  medical  profession  was  hereditary.  His  father 
Nicomachus  was  court  physician  to  Amyntas  III., 
the  king  for  whose  benefit  the  Spartans  had  put 
down  the  Chalcidic  league.  This  early  connection  with 
medicine  and  with  the  rough -living  Macedonian 
court  largely  explains  both  the  predominantly  bio- 
logical cast  of  Aristotle's  philosophical  thought  and 
the  intense  dislike  of  "  princes  "  and  courts  to  which 
he  more  than  once  gives  expression.  At  the  age  of 
eighteen,  in  367-6,  Aristotle  was  sent  to  Athens  for 
"higher"  education  in  philosophy  and  science,  and 
entered  the  famous  Platonic  Academy,  where  he 
remained  as  a  member  of  the  scientific  group  gathered 
round  the  master  for  twenty  years,  until  Plato's 
death  in  347-6.*  For  the  three  years  immediately 
following  Aristotle  was  in  Asia  Minor  with  his  friend 
and  fellow-student  Hermeias,  who  had  become  by 
force  of  sheer  capacity  monarch  of  the  city  of 
Atarneus  in  Aeolis,  and  was  maintaining  himself 
with  much  energy  against  the  Persian  king.  Pythias, 
the  niece  of  Hermeias,  became  the  philosopher's  wife, 

*  It  is  perhaps  significant  that  Aristotle's  entry  into  the  school 
fell  in  the  year  when  Plato  was  absent  on  his  political  mission 
in  Syracuse.  Thus  he  probably  did  not  get  his  first  introduc- 
tion to  Platonism  from  the  lips  of  Plato. 


I 


LIFE  AND  WORKS.  13 

and  it  seems  that  the  marriage  was  happy.  Exami- 
nation of  Aristotle's  contributions  to  marine  biology 
has  shown  that  his  knowledge  of  the  subject  is 
specially  good  for  the  Aeolic  coast  and  the  shores 
of  the  adjacent  islands.  This  throws  light  on  his 
occupations  during  his  residence  with  Hermeias,  and 
suggests  that  Plato  had  discerned  the  bent  of  his  dis- 
tinguished pupil's  mind,  and  that  his  special  share  in 
the  researches  of  the  Academy  had,  like  that  of 
Speusippus,  Plato's  nephew  and  successor  in  the 
headship  of  the  school,  been  largely  of  a  biological 
kind.  We  also  know  that,  presumably  shortly  after 
Plato's  death,  Aristotle  had  been  one  of  the  group 
of  disciples  who  published  their  notes  of  their 
teacher's  famous  unpublished  lecture  On  the  Good. 
In  343  Hermeias  was  assassinated  at  the  instigation 
of  Persia ;  Aristotle  honoured  his  memory  by  a  hymn 
setting  forth  the  godlikeness  of  virtue  as  illustrated 
by  the  life  of  his  friend.  Aristotle  now  removed  to 
the  Macedonian  court,  where  he  received  the  position 
of  tutor  to  the  Crown  Prince,  afterwards  Alexander 
the  Great,  at  this  time  (343  B.C.)  a  boy  of  thirteen. 
The  association  of  the  great  philosopher  and  the  great 
king  as  tutor  and  pupil  has  naturally  struck  the 
imagination  of  later  ages ;  even  in  Plutarch's  Life  of 
Alexander  we  meet  already  with  the  full-blown 
legend  of  the  influence  of  Aristotle's  philosophical 
speculations  on  Alexander.  It  is,  however,  im- 
probable that  Aristotle's  influence  counted  for  much 
in  forming  the  character  of  Alexander.  Aristotle's 
dislike  of  monarchies  and  their  accessories  is  written 
large  on  many  a  page  of  his  Ethics  and  Politics  ;  the 
small  self-contained  city-state  with  no  political  am- 
bitions for  which  he  reserves  his  admiration  would 
have  seemed  a  mere  reHc  of  antiquity  to  Philip  and 


14  ARISTOTLE. 

Alexander.  The  only  piece  of  contemporary  evidence 
as  to  the  relations  between  the  master  and  the  pupil 
is  a  sentence  in  a  letter  to  the  young  Alexander  from 
the  Athenian  publicist  Isocrates,  who  maliciously 
congratulates  the  prince  on  his  preference  for 
"rhetoric,"  the  art  of  efficient  public  speech,  and 
his  indifference  to  "logic-choppers."  How  little 
sympathy  Aristotle  can  have  had  with  his  pupil's 
ambitions  is  shown  by  the  fact  that,  though  his 
political  theories  must  have  been  worked  out  during 
the  very  years  in  which  Alexander  was  revolutionising 
Hellenism  by  the  foundation  of  his  world-empire, 
they  contain  no  allusion  to  so  momentous  a  change 
in  the  social  order.  For  all  that  Aristotle  tells  us, 
Alexander  might  never  have  existed,  and  the  small 
city-state  might  have  been  the  last  word  of  Hellenic 
political  development.  Hence  it  is  probable  that  the 
selection  of  Aristotle,  who  had  not  yet  appeared 
before  the  world  as  an  independent  thinker,  to  take 
part  in  the  education  of  the  Crown  Prince  was  due 
less  to  personal  reputation  than  to  the  connection  of 
his  family  with  the  court,  taken  together  with  his 
own  position  as  a  pupil  of  Plato,  whose  intervention 
in  the  public  affairs  of  Sicily  had  caused  the  Academy 
to  be  regarded  as  the  special  home  of  scientific  interest 
in  politics  and  jurisprudence.  It  may  be  true  that 
Alexander  found  time  in  the  midst  of  his  conquests 
to  supply  his  old  tutor  with  zoological  specimens ;  it 
is  as  certain  as  such  a  thing  can  be  that  the  ideals 
and  characters  of  the  two  men  were  too  different  to 
allow  of  any  intimate  influence  of  either  on  the  other. 
When  Alexander  was  suddenly  called  to  the 
Macedonian  throne  by  the  murder  of  his  father  in 
336  B.C.,  Aristotle's  services  were  no  longer  needed ; 
he  returned  to  Athens  and  gave  himself  to  purely 


I 


LIFE  AND  WORKS.  lb 

scientific  work.  Just  at  this  juncture  the  presidency 
of  the  Academy  was  vacant  by  the  death  of  Speu- 
sippus,  Aristotle's  old  associate  in  biological  research. 
Possibly  Aristotle  thought  himself  injured  when  the 
school  passed  him  over  and  elected  Xenocrates  of 
Chalcedon  as  its  new  president.  At  any  rate,  though 
he  appears  never  to  have  wholly  severed  his  connec- 
tion with  the  Academy,  in  335  he  opened  a  rival 
institution  in  the  Lyceum,  or  gymnasium  attached  to 
the  temple  of  Apollo  Lyceus,  to  which  he  was  followed 
by  some  of  the  most  distinguished  members  of  the 
Academy.  From  the  fact  that  his  instruction  was 
given  in  the  peripatos  or  covered  portico  of  the 
gymnasium  the  school  has  derived  its  name  of  Peri- 
patetic. For  the  next  twelve  years  he  was  occupied 
in  the  organisation  of  the  school  as  an  abode  for  the 
prosecution  of  speculation  and  research  in  every 
department  of  inquiry,  and  in  the  composition  of 
numerous  courses  of  lectures  on  scientific  and  philo- 
sophical questions.  The  chief  difference  in  general 
character  between  the  new  school  and  the  Academy 
is  that  while  the  scientific  interests  of  the  Platonists 
centred  in  mathematics,  the  main  contributions  of  the 
Lyceum  to  science  lay  in  the  departments  of  biology 
and  history. 

Towards  the  end  of  Alexander's  life  his  attention 
was  unfavourably  directed  on  his  old  teacher.  A 
relative  of  Aristotle  named  Callisthenes  had  attended 
Alexander  in  his  campaigns  as  historiographer,  and 
had  provoked  disfavour  by  his  censure  of  the  King's 
attempts  to  invest  his  semi-constitutional  position 
towards  his  Hellenic  subjects  with  the  pomp  of  an 
Oriental  despotism.  The  historian's  independence 
proved  fatal.  He  was  accused  of  instigating  an 
assassination    plot    among    Alexander's   pages,    and 


16  AEISTOTLE. 

hanged,  or,  as  some  said,  thrown  into  a  prison  where 
he  died  before  trial  Alexander  is  reported  to  have 
held  Aristotle  responsible  for  his  relative's  treason, 
and  to  have  meditated  revenge.  If  this  is  so,  he  was 
fortunately  diverted  from  the  commission  of  a  crime 
by  preoccupation  with  the  invasion  of  India 

On  the  death  of  Alexander  in  323  a  brief  but 
vigorous  anti-Macedonian  agitation  broke  out  at 
Athens.  Aristotle,  from  his  Macedonian  connections, 
naturally  fell  a  victim,  in  spite  of  his  want  of 
sympathy  with  the  ideals  of  Philip  and  Alexander. 
Like  Socrates,  he  was  indicted  on  the  capital  charge 
of  "  impiety,"  the  pretext  being  that  his  poem  on  the 
death  of  Hermeias,  written  twenty  years  before,  was 
a  virtual  deification  of  his  friend.  This  was,  how- 
ever, only  a  pretext ;  the  real  offence  was  political, 
and  lay  in  his  connection  with  the  Macedonian 
leader  Antipater.  As  condemnation  was  certain, 
the  philosopher  anticipated  it  by  withdrawing  with 
his  disciples  to  Chalcis,  the  mother  city  of  his  native 
Stagirus.  Here  he  died  in  the  following  year,  at  the 
age  of  sixty-two  or  sixty-three. 

The  features  of  Aristotle,  familiar  to  us  from  busts 
and  intaglios,  are  handsome,  but  indicate  refinement 
and  acuteness  rather  than  originality,  an  impression 
in  keeping  with  what  we  should  expect  from  a  study 
of  his  writings.  The  anecdotes  related  of  him  reveal 
a  kindly,  affectionate  character,  and  show  little  trace 
of  the  self-importance  which  appears  in  his  works. 
His  will,  which  has  been  preserved,  exhibits  the  same 
traits  in  its  references  to  his  happy  family  life  and  its 
solicitous  care  for  the  future  of  his  children  and 
servants.  He  was  twice  married,  first  to  Pythias, 
and  secondly  to  a  certain  Herpyllis,  by  whom  he  left 
a  son  Nicomachus  and  a  daughter.     The  "  goodness  " 

(1,994) 


LIFE  AND  WORKS.  17 

of  Herpyllis  to  her  husband  is  specially  mentioned  in 
the  clauses  of  the  will  which  make  provision  for  her, 
while  the  warmth  of  the  writer's  feelings  for  Pythias 
is  shown  by  the  direction  that  her  remains  are  to  be 
placed  in  the  same  tomb  with  his  own.  The  list  of 
servants  remembered  and  the  bequests  enumerated 
show  the  philosopher  to  have  been  in  easier  circum- 
stances than  Plato. 

The  Works  of  Aristotle. — The  so-called  works  of 
Aristotle  present  us  with  a  curious  problem.  When 
we  turn  from  Plato  to  his  pupil  we  seem  to  have 
passed  into  a  different  atmosphere.  The  Discourses 
of  Socrates  exhibit  a  prose  style  which  is  perhaps  the 
most  marvellous  of  all  literary  achievements.  No- 
where else  do  we  meet  with  quite  the  same  combina- 
tion of  eloquence,  imaginative  splendour,  incisive 
logic,  and  irresistible  wit  and  humour.  The  manner 
of  Aristotle  is  dry  and  formal  His  language  bristles 
with  technicalities,  makes  little  appeal  to  the  emotions, 
disdains  graces  of  style,  and  frequently  defies  the 
simplest  rules  of  composition.  Our  surprise  is  all 
the  greater  that  we  find  later  writers  of  antiquity, 
such  as  Cicero,  commending  Aristotle  for  his  copious 
and  golden  eloquence,  a  characteristic  which  is  con- 
spicuously wanting  in  the  Aristotelian  writings  we 
possess.  The  explanation  of  the  puzzle  is,  however, 
simple.  Plato  and  Aristotle  were  at  once  what  we 
should  call  professors  and  men  of  letters ;  both  wrote 
works  for  general  circulation,  and  both  delivered 
courses  of  lectures  to  special  students.  But  while 
Plato's  lectures  have  perished,  his  books  have  come 
down  to  us.  Aristotle's  books  have  almost  wholly 
been  lost,  but  we  possess  many  of  his  lectures.  The 
"works"  of  Aristotle  praised  by  Cicero  for  their 
eloquence  were  philosophical  dialogues,  and  formed 

(1,994)  2 


18  ARISTOTLE.  ' 

the  model  for  C5icero's  own  compositions  in  this  kind. 
None  of  them  have  survived,  though  some  passages 
have  been  preserved  in  quotations  by  later  writers. 
That  our  "works "  are  actually  the  MSS.  of  a  lecturer 
posthumously  edited  by  his  pupils  seems  clear  from 
external  as  well  as  from  internal  evidence.  In  one 
instance  we  have  the  advantage  of  a  double  recension, 
Aristotle's  Ethics  or  Discourses  on  Conduct  have  come 
down  to  us  in  two  forms — the  so-called  Nicomachean 
Ethics,  a  redaction  by  the  philosopher's  son,  Nico- 
machus,  preserving  all  the  characteristics  of  an  oral 
course  of  lectures  ;  and  a  freer  and  more  readable 
recast  by  a  pupil,  the  mathematician  Eudemus,  known 
as  the  Eudemian  Ethics.  In  recent  years  we  have 
also  recovered  from  the  sands  of  Egypt  what  appears 
to  be  our  one  specimen  of  a  "work "of  Aristotle, 
intended  to  be  read  by  the  public  at  large,  the  essay 
on  the  Constitution  of  Athens.  The  style  of  this 
essay  is  easy,  flowing,  and  popular,  and  shows  that 
Aristotle  could  write  well  and  gracefully  when  he 
thought  fit. 


I 


CHAPTER  II 

THE   CLASSIFICATION   OF   THE    SCIENCES  :   SCIENTIFIC 
METHOD 

Philosophy,  as  understood  by  Aristotle,  may  be  said 
to  be  the  organised  whole  of  disinterested  knowledge, 
that  is,  knowledge  which  we  seek  for  the  satisfaction 
which  it  carries  with  itself,  and  not  as  a  mere  means 
to  utilitarian  ends.  The  impulse  which  receives  this 
satisfaction  is  curiosity  or  wonder,  which  Aristotle 
regards  as  innate  in  man,  though  it  does  not  get  full 
play  until  civilisation  has  advanced  far  enough  to 
make  secure  provision  for  the  immediate  material 
needs  of  life.  Human  curiosity  was  naturally  directed 
first  to  the  outstanding  "marvellous  works"  of  the 
physical  world,  the  planets,  the  periodicity  of  their 
movements,  the  return  of  the  seasons,  winds,  thunder 
and  lightning,  and  the  like.  Hence  the  earliest  Greek 
speculation  was  concerned  with  problems  of  astronomy 
and  meteorology.  Then,  as  reflection  developed,  men 
speculated  about  geometrical  figure  and  number,  the 
possibility  of  having  assured  knowledge  at  all,  the 
character  of  the  common  principles  assumed  in  all 
branches  of  study  or  of  the  special  principles  assumed 
in  some  one  branch,  and  thus  philosophy  has  finally 
become  the  disinterested  study  of  every  department 
of  Being  or   Reality.     Since  Aristotle,   like  Hegel, 


20  AEISTOTLE. 


,  the  ■! 


I 


thought  that  his  own  doctrine  was,  in  essentials, 
last  word  of  speculation,  the  complete  expression  of 
the  principles  by  which  his  predecessors  had  been  un- 
consciously guided,  he  believes  himself  in  a  position 
to  make  a  final  classification  of  the  branches  of  science, 
showing  how  they  are  related  and  how  they  are  dis- 
criminated from  one  another.  This  classification  we  ^1 
have  now  to  consider.  ^| 

Classification  of  the  Sciences. — To  begin  with,  we 
have  to  discriminate  Philosophy  from  two  rivals  with 
which  it  might  be  confounded  on  a  superficial  view, 
Dialectic  and  Sophistry.  Dialectic  is  the  art  of 
reasoning  accurately  from  given  premisses,  true  or; 
false.  This  art  has  its  proper  uses,  and  of  one  of 
these  we  shall  have  to  speak.  But  in  itself  it  is 
indifierent  to  the  truth  of  its  premisses.  You  may 
reason  dialectically  from  premisses  which  you  believe 
to  be  false,  for  the  express  purpose  of  showing  the 
absurd  conclusions  to  which  they  lead.  Or  you  may 
reason  from  premisses  which  you  assume  tentatively 
to  see  what  conclusions  you  are  committed  to  if  you 
adopt  them.  In  either  case  your  object  is  not  directly 
to  secure  truth,  but  only  to  secure  consistency. 
Science  or  Philosophy  aims  directly  at  truth,  and 
hence  requires  to  start  with  true  and  certain  premisses. 
Thus  the  distinction  between  Science  and  Dialectic 
is  that  Science  reasons  from  true  premisses,  Dialectic 
only  from  "probable"  or  "plausible"  premisses.* 
Sophistry  differs  from  Science  in  virtue  of  its  moral 
character.  It  is  the  profession  of  making  a  living 
by  the  abuse  of  reasoning,   the  trick  of  employing 

*  A  proposition  is  regarded  as  "probable  "  if  it  is  held  either 
(1)  by  the  great  majority  of  men,  or  (2)  by  one  or  more  men  of 
special  eminence  in  a  subject.  This  is  the  ultimate  origin  of  the 
"  Probabilism  "  of  "moraJ  theologians." 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     21 

logical. skill  for  the  apparent  demonstration  of  scientific 
or  ethical  falsehoods.  "  The  sophist  is  one  who  earns 
a  living  from  an  apparent  but  unreal  wisiom."  (The 
emphasis  thus  falls  on  the  notion  of  making  an  "  un- 
real wisdom  "  into  a  trade.  The  sophist's  real  concern 
is  to  get  his  fee.)  Science  or  Philosophy  is  thus  the 
disinterested  employment  of  the  understanding  in 
the  discovery  of  truth. 

We  may  now  distinguish  the  different  branches  of 
science  as  defined.  The  first  and  most  important 
division  to  be  made  is  that  between  Speculative  or 
Theoretical  Science  and  Practical  Science.  The  broad 
distinction  is  that  which  we  should  now  draw  between 
the  Sciences  and  the  Arts  {i.e.  the  industrial  and 
technical,  not  the  "  fine "  arts).  Speculative  or 
Theoretical  Philosophy  differs  from  Practical  Philos- 
ophy in  its  purpose,  and,  in  consequence,  in  its  sub- 
ject-matter, and  its  formal  logical  character.  The 
purpose  of  the  former  is  the  disinterested  contempla^ 
tion  of  truths  which  are  what  they  are  independently  of 
our  own  volition;  its  end  is  to  hiow  and  only  to  know. 
The  object  of  "  practical "  Science  is  to  know,  but  not 
only  to  know  but  also  to  turn  our  knowledge  to  account 
in  devising  ways  of  successful  interference  with  the 
course  of  events.  (The  real  importance  of  the  dis- 
tinction comes  out  in  Aristotle's  treatment  of  the 
problems  of  moral  and  social  science.  Since  we 
require  knowledge  of  the  moral  and  social  nature  of 
men  not  merely  to  satisfy  an  intellectual  interest,  but 
as  a  basis  for  a  sound  system  of  education  and  govern- 
ment. Politics,  the  theory  of  government,  and  Ethics, 
the  theory  of  goodness  of  conduct,  which  for  Aristotle 
is  only  a  subordinate  branch  of  Politics,  belong  to 
Practical,  not  to  Theoretical  Philosophy,  a  view 
which  is  attended  by  important  consequences.) 


22  ARISTOTLE. 

It  follows  that  there  is  a  corresponding  difference 
in  the  objects  investigated  by  the  two  branches  of 
Philosophy.     Speculative  or   Theoretical  Philosophy 
is  concerned  with   "that  which  cannot  possibly  beHl 
other  than  it  is,"  truths  and  relations  independent^' 
of  human  volition  for  their  subsistence,  and  calling 
simply  for  recognition  on  our  part.     Practical  Philos- 
ophy has  to  do  with  relations  which  human  volition 
can  modify,  "  things  which  may  be  other  than  they 
are,"  the   contingent.     (Thus   e.g.  not   only   politics, 
but  medicine  and  economics  will  belong  to  Practical^! 
Science.)  ^ 

Hence  again  arises  a  logical  difference  between 
the  conclusions  of  Theoretical  and  those  of  Practical 
Philosophy.  Those  of  the  former  are  universal  truths 
deducible  with  logical  necessity  from  self-evident* 
principles.  Those  of  the  latter,  because  they  relate 
to  what  "can  be  otherwise,"  are  never  rigidly  uni- 
versal ;  they  are  general  rules  which  hold  good  "  in 
the  majority  of  cases."  but  are  liable  to  occasional 
exceptions  owing  to  the  contingent  character  of  the 
facfs  with  which  they  deal.  It  is  a  proof  of  a  phi- 
losopher's lack  of  grounding  in  logic  that  he  looks  to 
the  results  of  a  practical  science  {e.g.  to  the  detailed 
precepts  of  medicine  or  ethics)  for  a  higher  degree  of 
certainty  and  validity  than  the  nature  of  the  subject- 
matter  allows.  Thus  for  Aristotle  the  distinction 
between  the  necessary  and  the  contingent  is  real  and 
not  merely  apparent,  and  "probability  is  the  guide" 
in  studies  which  have  to  do  with  the  direction  of  life. 

*  Self-evident,  that  is,  in  a  purely  lo^cal  sense.  When  you 
apprehend  the  principles  in  question,  you  see  at  once  that  they 
are  true,  and  do  not  require  to  have  them  proved.  It  is  not 
meant  that  any  and  every  man  does,  in  point  of  fact,  always 
apprehend  the  principles,  or  that  they  can  be  apprehended 
without  preliminary  mental  discipline. 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     23 

We  proceed  to  the  question  how  many  subdivisions 
there  are  within  "  theoretical "  Philosophy  itself. 
Plato  had  held  that  there  are  none.  All  the  sciences 
are  deductions  from  a  single  set  of  ultimate  principles 
which  it  is  the  business  of  that  supreme  science  to 
which  Plato  had  given  the  name  of  Dialectic  to 
establish.  This  is  not  Aristotle's  view.  According 
to  him,  "  theoretical "  Philosophy  falls  into  a  number 
of  distinct  though  not  co-ordinate  branches,  each  with 
its  own  special  subjects  of  investigation  and  its  own 
special  axiomatic  principles.  Of  these  branches  there 
are  three,  First  Philosophy,  Mathematics,  and  Physics. 
First  Philosophy — afterwards  to  be  known  to  the 
Middle  Ages  as  Metaphysics* — treats,  to  use  Aris- 
totle's own  expression,  of  "  Being  qub,  Being."  This 
means  that  it  is  concerned  with  the  universal  char- 
acteristics which  belong  to  the  system  of  knowable 
reality  as  such,  and  the  principles  of  its  organisation 
in  their  full  universality.  First  Philosophy  alone  in- 
vestigates the  character  of  those  causative  factors  in 
the  system  which  are  without  body  or  shape  and 
exempt  from  all  mutability.  Since  in  Aristotle's 
system  God  is  the  supreme  Cause  of  this  kind,  First 
Philosophy  culminates  in  the  knowledge  of  God,  and 
is  hence  frequently  called  Theology.  It  thus  includes 
an  element  which  would  to-day  be  assigned  to  the 
theory  of  knowledge,  as  well  as  one  which  we  should 
ascribe  to  metaphysics,  since  it  deals  at  once  with  the 
ultimate  postulates  of  knowledge  and  the  ultimate 
causes  of  the  order  of  real  existence. 

*  The  origin  of  this  name  seems  to  be  that  Aristotle's  lectures 
on  First  Philosophy  came  to  be  studied  as  a  continuation  of  his 
course  on  Physics.  Hence  the  lectures  got  the  xvaxcMSiMeta'physica 
because  they  came  ajter  (meta)  those  on  Physics.  Finally  the 
name  was  transferred  (as  in  the  case  of  Ethics)  from  the  lectures 
to  the  subject  of  which  they  treat. 


24  ARISTOTLE. 

Mathematics  is  of  narrower  scope.  What  it  studies 
is  no  longer  "real  being  as  such,"  but  only  real  being 
in  so  far  as  it  exhibits  number  and  geometrical  form. 
Since  Aristotle  holds  the  view  that  number  and  figure 
only  exist  as  determinations  of  objects  given  in  per- 
ception (though  by  a  convenient  fiction  the  mathe- 
matician treats  of  them  in  abstraction  from  the 
perceived  objects  which  they  qualify),  he  marks  the 
difference  between  Mathematics  and  First  Philosophy 
by  saying  that  "  whereas  the  objects  of  First  Philos- 
ophy are  separate  from  matter  and  devoid  of  motion, 
those  of  Mathematics,  though  incapable  of  motion, 
have  no  separable  existence  but  are  inherent  in 
matter."  Physics  is  concerned  with  the  study  of 
objects  which  are  both  material  and  capable  of  motion. 
Thus  the  principle  of  the  distinction  is  the  presence 
or  absence  of  initial  restrictions  of  the  range  of  the 
different  branches  of  Science.  First  Philosophy  has 
the  widest  range,  since  its  contemplation  covers  the 
whole  ground  of  the  real  and  knowable ;  Physics  the 
narrowest,  because  it  is  confined  to  a  "  universe  of 
discourse  "  restricted  by  the  double  qualification  that 
its  members  are  all  material  and  capable  of  displace- 
ment. Mathematics  holds  an  intermediate  position, 
since  in  it  one  of  these  qualifications  is  removed, 
but  the  other  still  remains,  for  the  geometer's  figures 
are  boundaries  and  limits  of  sensible  bodies,  and  the 
arithmetician's  numbers  properties  of  collections  of 
concrete  objects.  It  follows  also  that  the  initial 
axioms  or  postulates  of  Mathematics  form  a  less  simple 
system  than  those  of  First  Philosophy,  and  those  of 
Physics  than  those  of  Mathematics.  Mathematics 
requires  as  initial  assumptions  not  only  those  which 
hold  good  for  cdl  thought,  but  certain  other  special 
axioms  which  are  only  valid  and  significant  for  the 


I 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     25 

realm  of  figure  and  number  ;  Physics  requires  yet  fur- 
ther axioms  which  are  only  applicable  to  "  what  is  in 
motion."  This  is  why,  though  the  three  disciplines 
are  treated  as  distinct,  they  are  not  strictly  co-ordinate, 
and  "  First  Philosophy,"  though  "  first,"  is  only  prima 
inter  pares. 

We  thus  get  the  following  diagrammatic  scheme 
of  the  classification  of  sciences  : — 

Science 
I 


Theoretical  Practical 

I 

1  1  I 

First  Philosophy  Mathe-  Physics 

or  matics 
Theology 

Practical  Philosophy  is  not  subjected  by  Aristotle 
to  any  similar  subdivision.  Later  students  were 
accustomed  to  recognise  a  threefold  division  into 
Ethics  (the  theory  of  individual  conduct),  Economics 
(the  theory  of  the  management  of  the  household), 
Politics  (the  theory  of  the  management  of  the  State). 
Aristotle  himself  does  not  make  these  distinctions. 
His  general  name  for  the  theory  of  conduct  is  Politics, 
the  doctrine  of  individual  conduct  being  for  him  in- 
separable from  that  of  the  right  ordering  of  society. 
Though  he  composed  a  separate  course  of  lectures  on 
individual  conduct  (the  Ethics),  he  takes  care  to  open 
the  course  by  stating  that  the  science  of  which  it 
treats  is  Politics,  and  offers  an  apology  for  dealing 
with  the  education  of  individual  character  apart  from 
the  more  general  doctrine  of  the  organisation  of 
society.     No  special  recognition  is  given  in  Aristotle's 


26  AKISTOTLE. 


own  classification  to  the  Philosophy  of  Art.  Modern 
students  of  Aristotle  have  tried  to  fill  in  the  omission 
by  adding  artistic  creation  to  contemplation  and 
practice  as  a  third  fundamental  form  of  mental 
activity,  and  thus  making  a  threefold  division  of 
Philosophy  into  Theoretical,  Practical,  and  Pro- 
ductive. The  object  of  this  is  to  find  a  place  in  the 
classification  for  Aristotle's  famous  Poetics  and  his 
work  on  Rhetoric,  the  art  of  effective  speech  and 
writing.  But  the  admission  of  the  third  division  of 
Science  has  no  warrant  in  the  text  of  Aristotle,  nor 
are  the  Rhetoric  and  Poetics,  properly  speaking,  a 
contribution  to  Philosophy.  They  are  intended  as 
collections  of  practical  rules  for  the  composition  of  a 
pamphlet  or  a  tragedy,  not  as  a  critical  examination 
of  the  canons  of  literary  taste.  This  was  correctly 
seen  by  the  dramatic  theorists  of  the  seventeenth 
century.  They  exaggerated  the  value  of  Aristotle's 
directions  and  entirely  misunderstood  the  meaning 
of  some  of  them,  but  they  were  right  in  their  view 
that  the  Poetics  was  meant  to  be  a  collection  of  rules 
by  obeying  which  the  craftsman  might  make  sure  of 
turning  out  a  successful  play.  So  far  as  Aristotle 
has  a  Philosophy  of  Fine  Art  at  all,  it  forms  part  of 
his  more  general  theory  of  education  and  must  be 
looked  for  in  the  general  discussion  of  the  aims  of 
education  contained  in  his  Politics. 

The  Methods  of  Science. — No  place  has  been  as- 
signed in  the  scheme  to  what  we  call  logic  and  Aris- 
totle called  Analytics,  the  theory  of  scientific  method, 
or  of  proof  and  the  estimation  of  evidence.  The 
reason  is  that  since  the  fundamental  character  of 
proof  is  the  same  in  all  science,  Aristotle  looks  upon 
logic  as  a  study  of  the  methods  common  to  all  science. 
At  a  later  date  it  became  a  hotly  debated  question 


lo-i^i-k    ^^^ 


I 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     27 

whether  logic  should  be  regarded  in  this  way  as  a 
study  of  the  methods  instrumental  to  proof  in  all 
sciences,  or  as  itself  a  special  constituent  division  of 
philosophy.  The  Aristotelian  view  was  concisely  in- 
dicated by  the  name  which  became  attached  to  the 
collection  of  Aristotle's  logical  works.  They  were 
called  the  Organon,  that  is,  the  "instrument,"  or  the 
body  of  rules  of  method  employed  by  Science.  The 
thought  imphed  is  thus  that  logic  furnishes  the  tools 
with  which  every  science  has  to  work  in  establish- 
ing its  results.  Our  space  will  only  permit  of  a 
brief  statement  as  to  the  points  in  which  the  Aris- 
totelian formal  logic  appears  to  be  really  original, 
and  the  main  peculiarities  of  Aristotle's  theory  of 
knowledge. 

{a)  Formal  Logic. — In  compass  the  Aristotelian 
logic  corresponds  roughly  with  the  contents  of  modem 
elementary  treatises  on  the  same  subject,  with  the 
omission  of  the  sections  which  deal  with  the  so-called 
Conditional  Syllogism.  The  inclusion  of  arguments 
of  this  type  in  mediaeval  and  modern  expositions  of 
formal  logic  is  principally  due  to  the  Stoics,  who  pre- 
ferred to  throw  their  reasoning  into  these  forms  and 
subjected  them  to  minute  scrutiny.  In  his  treatment 
of  the  doctrine  of  Terms,  Aristotle  avoids  the  mistake 
of  treating  the  isolated  name  as  though  it  had  signi- 
ficance apart  from  the  enunciations  in  which  it  occurs. 
He  is  quite  clear  on  the  all-important  point  that  the 
unit  of  thought  is  the  proposition  in  which  something 
is  affirmed  or  denied,  the  one  thought-form  which  can 
be  properly  called  "true"  or  "false."  Such  an  asser- 
tion he  analyses  into  two  factors,  that  about  which 
something  is  affirmed  or  denied  (the  Subject),  and 
that  which  is  affirmed  or  denied  of  it  (the  Predicate). 
Consequently   his   doctrine    of    the   classification   of 


28  AEISTOTLE. 

Terms  is  based  on  a  classification  of  Predicates,  or  of 
Propositions  according  to  the  special  kind  of  con- 
nection between  the  Subject  and  Predicate  which 
they  affirm  or  deny.  Two  such  classifications,  which 
cannot  be  made  to  fit  into  one  another,  meet  us  in 
Aristotle's  logical  writings,  the  scheme  of  the  ten 
"Categories"  or  "Predicaments,"  and  that  which 
was  afterwards  known  in  the  Middle  Ages  as  the  list 
of  "  Predicables,"  or  again  as  the  "  Five  Words." 
The  list  of  "  Categories  "  reveals  itself  as  an  attempt 
to  answer  the  question  in  how  many  different  senses 
the  words  "  is  a "  or  "  are "  are  employed  when  we 
assert  that  "a;  is  3/"  or  "cc  is  a  y"  or  "a;s  are  ys." 
Such  a  statement  may  tell  us  (1)  what  x  is,  as  if  I 
say  "  cc  is  a  lion  "  ;  the  predicate  is  then  said  to  fall 
under  the  category  of  Substance ;  (2)  what  x  is  like, 
as  when  I  say  "  a:  is  white,  or  x  is  wise," — the  category 
of  Quality ;  (3)  how  much  or  how  many  x  is,  as  when 
I  say  "  there  are  five  xs  "  or  "  x  is  five  feet  long," — the 
category  of  Quantity ;  (4)  how  x  is  related  to  some- 
thing else,  as  when  I  say  "  x  is  to  the  right  of  y"  "  x  is 
the  father  of  y," — the  category  of  Relation,  These 
are  the  four  chief  "  categories  "  discussed  by  Aristotle. 
The  remainder  are  (5)  Place,  (6)  Time,  (7)  and  (8) 
Condition  or  State,  as  when  I  say  "  x  is  sitting  down  " 
or  "x  has  his  armour  on," — (the  only  distinction 
between  the  two  cases  seems  to  be  that  (7)  denotes  a 
more  permanent  state  of  x  than  (8)) ;  (9)  Action  or 
Activity,  as  when  I  say  "  x  is  cutting,"  or  generally 
"x  is  doing  something  to  y" ;  (10)  Passivity,  as 
when  I  say  "  x  is  being  cut,"  or  more  generally,  "  so- 
and-so  is  being  done  to  x."  No  attempt  is  made  to 
show  that  this  list  of  "  figures  of  predication  "  is  com- 
plete, or  to  point  out  any  i)rinciple  which  has  been 
followed  in  its  construction.     It  also  happens  that 


II 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     29 

much  the  same  enumeration  is  incidentally  made  in 
one  or  two  passages  of  Plato.  Hence  it  is  not  un- 
likely that  the  list  was  taken  over  by  Aristotle  as  one 
which  would  be  familiar  to  pupils  who  had  read  their 
Plato,  and  therefore  convenient  for  practical  purposes. 
The  fivefold  classification  does  depend  on  a  principle 
pointed  out  by  Aristotle  which  guarantees  its  com- 
pleteness, and  is  therefore  likely  to  have  been  thought 
out  by  him  for  himself,  and  to  be  the  genuine  Aristo- 
telian scheme.  Consider  an  ordinary  universal  affirm- 
ative proposition  of  the  form  "all  x^  are  2/s."  Now 
if  this  statement  is  true  it  may  also  be  true  that  "all 
ys  are  ccs,"  or  it  may  not.  On  the  first  supposition 
we  have  two  possible  cases,  (1)  the  predicate  may 
state  precisely  what  the  subject  defined  is ;  then  y  is 
the  Definition  of  £c,  as  when  I  say  that  "men  are 
mortal  animals,  capable  of  discourse."  Here  it  is 
also  true  to  say  that  "mortal  animals  capable  of  dis- 
course are  men,"  and  Aristotle  regards  the  predicate 
"mortal  animal  capable  of  discourse"  as  expressing 
the  inmost  nature  of  man.  (2)  The  predicate  may 
not  express  the  inmost  nature  of  the  subject,  and  yet 
may  belong  only  to  the  class  denoted  by  the  subject 
and  to  every  member  of  that  class.  The  predicate  is 
then  called  a  Proprium  or  property,  an  exclusive 
attribute  of  the  class  in  question.  Thus  it  was  held 
that  "all  men  are  capable  of  laughter"  and  "all 
beings  capable  of  laughter  are  men,"  but  that  the 
capacity  for  laughter  is  no  part  of  the  inmost  nature 
or  "real  essence"  of  humanity.  It  is  therefore 
reckoned  as  a  Proprium. 

Again  in  the  case  where  it  is  true  that  "  all  x%  are 
2/s,"  but  not  true  that  aU  "  2/s  are  ics,"  y  may  be  part 
of  the  definition  of  x  or  it  may  not.  If  it  is  part  of 
the  definition  of  x  it  will  be  either  (3)  a  Genus  or 


30  ARISTOTLE. 


wider  class  of  which  x  forms  a  subdivision,  as  when 
I  say,  "All  men  are  animals,"  or  (4)  a  Difference, 
that  is,  one  of  the  distinctive  marks  by  which  the  xs 
are  distinguished  from  other  sub-classes  or  species  of 
the  same  genus,  as  when  I  say,  "  All  men  are  capable 
of  discourse."  Or  finally  (5)  y  may  be  no  part  of  the 
definition  of  cc,  but  a  characteristic  which  belongs 
both  to  the  oos  and  some  things  other  than  ocs.  The 
predicate  is  then  called  an  Accident.  We  have  now 
exhausted  all  the  possible  cases,  and  may  say  that  the 
predicate  of  a  universal  affirmative  proposition  is 
always  either  a  definition,  a  proprium,  a  genus,  a 
difference,  or  an  accident.  This  classification  reached 
the  Middle  Ages  not  in  the  precise  form  in  which  it 
is  given  by  Aristotle,  but  with  modifications  mainly 
due  to  the  ^N'eo-Platonic  philosopher  Porphyry.  In 
its  modified  form  it  is  regarded  as  a  classification  of 
terms  generally.  Definition  disappears  from  the  list, 
as  the  definition  is  regarded  as  a  complex  made  up  of 
the  genus,  or  next  highest  class  to  which  the  class  to 
be  defined  belongs,  and  the  differences  which  mark  off 
this  particular  species  or  sub-class.  The  species  itself 
which  figures  as  the  subject-term  in  a  definition  is 
added,  and  thus  the  "  Five  Words  "  of  mediaeval  logic 
are  enumerated  as  genus,  species,  difference,  proprium, 
accident. 

The  one  point  of  philosophical  interest  about  this 
doctrine  appears  alike  in  the  scheme  of  the  "Cate- 
gories "  in  the  presence  of  a  category  of  "  substance," 
and  in  the  list  of  "  Predicables "  in  the  sharp  dis- 
tinction drawn  between  " definition "  and  "proprium." 
From  a  logical  point  of  view  it  does  not  appear  why 
any  proprium,  a7iy  character  belonging  to  all  the 
members  of  a  class  and  to  them  alone,  should  not  be 
taken   as   defining    the    class.     Why   should    it    be 


hen  ^^ 


1 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     31 

assumed  that  there  is  only  one  predicate,  viz.  man, 
which  precisely  answers  the  question,  "What  is 
Socrates  ? "  Why  should  it  not  be  equally  correct  to 
answer,  "a  Greek,"  or  "a  philosopher'"?  The  ex- 
planation is  that  Aristotle  takes  it  for  granted  that 
not  all  the  distinctions  we  can  make  between  "  kinds  " 
of  things  are  arbitrary  and  subjective.  Nature  herself 
has  made  certain  hard  and  fast  divisions  between 
kinds  which  it  is  the  business  of  our  thought  to 
recognise  and  follow.  Thus  according  to  Aristotle 
there  is  a  real  gulf,  a  genuine  difference  in  kind, 
between  the  horse  and  the  ass,  and  this  is  illustrated 
by  the  fact  that  the  mule,  the  offspring  of  a  horse  and 
an  ass,  is  not  capable  of  propagating.  It  is  thus  a 
sort  of  imperfect  being,  a  kind  of  "  monster  "  existing 
contra  naturam.  Such  differences  as  we  find  when 
we  compare  e.g.  Egyptians  with  Greeks  do  not 
amount  to  a  difference  in  "  kind."  To  say  that  Socra- 
tes is  a  man  tells  me  what  Socrates  is,  because  the 
statement  places  Socrates  in  the  real  kind  to 
which  he  actually  belongs ;  to  say  that  he  is' wise,  or 
old,  or  a  philosopher  merely  tells  me  some  of  his 
attributes.  It  follows  from  this  belief  in  "real"  or 
"natural"  kinds  that  the  problem  of  definition 
acquires  an  enormous  importance  for  science.  We, 
who  are  faccustomed  to  regard  the  whole  business  of 
classification  as  a  matter  of  making  a  grouping  of  our 
materials  such  as  is  most  pertinent  to  the  special 
question  we  have  in  hand,  tend  to  look  upon  any 
predicate  which  belongs  universally  and  exclusively 
to  the  members  of  a  group,  as  a  sufficient  basis  for 
a  possible  definition  of  the  group.  Hence  we  are 
prone  to  take  the  "nominalist"  view  of  definition,  i.e. 
to  look  upon  a  definition  as  no  more  than  a  declara- 
tion of  the  sense  which  we  intend  henceforward  to 


32  ARISTOTLE. 

put  on  a  word  or  other  symbol.*  And  consequently 
we  readily  admit  that  there  may  be  as  many  defini- 
tions of  a  class  as  it  has  different  propria.  But  in  a 
philosophy  like  that  of  Aristotle,  in  which  it  is  held 
that  a  true  classification  must  not  only  be  formally 
satisfactory,  but  must  also  conform  to  the  actual  lines 
of  cleavage  which  Nature  has  established  between 
kind  and  kind,  the  task  of  classificatory  science  be- 
comes much  more  diflacult.  Science  is  called  on  to 
supply  not  merely  a  definition  but  the  definition  of 
the  classes  it  considers,  the  definition  which  faithfully 
reflects  the  "lines  of  cleavage"  in  Nature.  This  is 
why  the  Aristotelian  view  is  that  a  true  definition 
should  always  be  per  genus  et  differentias.  It  should 
"  place  "  a  given  class  by  mentioning  the  wider  class 
next  above  it  in  the  olDJective  hierarchy,  and  then 
enumerating  the  most  deep-seated  distinctions  by 
which  Nature  herself  marks  off  this  class  from  others 
belonging  to  the  same  wider  class.  Modern  evolu- 
tionary thought  may  possibly  bring  us  back  to  this 
Aristotelian  standpoint.  Modern  evolutionary  science 
differs  from  Aristotelianism  on  one  point  of  the  first 
importance.  It  regards  the  difference  between  kinds, 
not  as  a  primary  fact  of  Nature,  but  as  produced  by 
a  long  process  of  accumulation  of  slight  differences. 
But  a  world  in  which  the  process  has  progressed  far 
enough  will  exhibit  much  the  same  character  as  the 
Nature  of  Aristotle.  As  the  intermediate  links  be- 
tween "species"  drop  out  because  they  are  less 
thoroughly  adapted  to  maintain  themselves  than  the 
extremes  between  which  they  form  links,  the  world 
produced  approximates  more  and  more  to  a  system  of 
species  between  which  there  are  unbridgeable  chasms ; 

*  All  mathematical  definitions  are  of  this  kind,  and  are  thus 
purely  "nominal." 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     33 

evolution  tends  more  and  more  to  the  final  establish- 
ment of  "  real  kinds,"  marked  by  the  fact  that  there 
is  no  permanent  possibility  of  cross-breeding  between 
them.  This  makes  it  once  more  possible  to  distin- 
guish between  a  "  nominal "  definition  and  a  "  real " 
definition.  From  an  evolutionary  point  of  view,  a 
"real"  definition  would  be  one  which  specifies  not 
merely  enough  characters  to  mark  ofi"  the  group  de- 
fined from  others,  but  selects  also  for  the  purpose 
those  characters  which  indicate  the  line  of  historical 
development  by  which  the  group  has  successively 
separated  itself  from  other  groups  descended  from 
the  same  ancestors.  We  shall  learn  yet  more  of  the 
significance  of  this  conception  of  a  "  real  kind  "  as  we 
go  on  to  make  acquaintance  with  the  outlines  of  First 
Philosophy.  Over  the  rest  of  the  formal  logic  of 
Aristotle  we  must  be  content  to  pass  more  rapidly. 
In  connection  with  the  doctrine  of  Propositions, 
Aristotle  lays  down  the  familiar  distinction  between 
the  four  types  of  proposition  according  to  their  quan- 
tity (as  universal  or  particular)  and  quality  (as  affir- 
mative or  negative),  and  treats  of  their  contrary  and 
contradictory  opposition  in  a  way  which  still  forms 
the  basis  of  the  handling  of  the  subject  in  elementary 
works  on  formal  logic.  He  also  considers  at  great 
length  a  subject  nowadays  commonly  excluded  from 
the  elementary  books — the  modal  distinction  between 
the  Problematic  proposition  (x  may  be  y),  the  Asser- 
tory {x  is  2/)j  and  the  Necessary  (x  must  be  y),  and 
the  way  in  which  all  these  forms  may  be  contradicted. 
For  him,  modality  is  a  formal  distinction  like  quantity 
or  quality,  because  he  believes  that  contingency  and 
necessity  are  not  merely  relative  to  the  state  of  our 
knowledge,  but  represent  real  and  objective  features 
of  the  order  of  Nature. 

(1,994)  3 


34  ARISTOTLE. 

In  connection  with  the  doctrine  of  Inference,  it  is 
worth  while  to  give  his  definition  of  Syllogism  or 
Inference  (literally  "  computation  ")  in  his  own  words. 
"Syllogism  is  a  discourse  wherein  certain  things 
(viz.  the  premisses)  being  admitted,  something  else, 
different  from  what  has  been  admitted,  follows  of 
necessity  because  the  admissions  are  what  they 
are."  The  last  clause  shows  that  Aristotle  is  aware 
that  the  all-important  thing  in  an  inference  is  not 
that  the  conclusion  should  be  novel  but  that  it  should 
be  proved.  We  may  have  known  the  conclusion  asj 
a  fact  before;  what  the  inference  does  for  us  is 
connect  it  with  the  rest  of  our  knowledge,  and  thi 
to  show  why  it  is  true.  He  also  formulates  th« 
axiom  upon  which  syllogistic  inference  rests,  ths 
"  if  A  is  predicated  universally  of  B  and  B  of  C,  A  il 
necessarily  predicated  universally  of  C."  Stated 
the  language  of  class-inclusion,  and  adapted  to  in-j 
elude  the  case  where  B  is  denied  of  C,  this  become 
the  formula,  "whatever  is  asserted  universally^ 
whether  positively  or  negatively,  of  a  class  B 
asserted  in  like  manner  of  any  class  C  which  is  wholly 
contained  in  B,"  the  axiom  de  omni  et  nullo 
mediaeval  logic.  The  syllogism  of  the  "  first  figure,* 
to  which  this  principle  immediately  applies,  is 
cordingly  regarded  by  Aristotle  as  the  natural  and^ 
perfect  form  of  inference.  Syllogisms  of  the  second 
and  third  figures  can  only  be  shown  to  fall  under  the 
dictum  by  a  process  of  "  reduction  "  or  transformation 
into  corresponding  arguments  in  the  first  "figure," 
and  are  therefore  called  "imperfect"  or  "incom- 
plete," because  they  do  not  exhibit  the  conclusive 
force  of  the  reasoning  with  equal  clearness,  and  also 
because  no  universal  affirmative  conclusion  can  be 
proved  in  them,  and  the  aim  of  science  is  always  to 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     35 

establish  such  affirmatives.  The  list  of  '*  moods  "  of 
the  three  figures,  and  the  doctrine  of  the  methods  by 
which  each  mood  of  the  imperfect  figures  can  be  re- 
placed by  an  equivalent  mood  of  the  first,  is  worked 
out  substantially  as  in  our  current  text-books.  The 
so-called  "  fourth  "  figure  is  not  recognised,  its  moods 
being  regarded  merely  as  unnatural  and  distorted 
statements  of  those  of  the  first  figure. 

Induction. — Of  the  use  of  "induction"  in  Aristotle's 
philosophy  we  shall  speak  under  the  head  of  "  Theory 
of  Knowledge."  Formally  it  is  called  "  the  way  of 
proceeding  from  particular  facts  to  universals,"  and 
Aristotle  insists  that  the  conclusion  is  only  proved  if 
all  the  particulars  have  been  examined.  Thus  he 
gives  as  an  example  the  following  argument :  "  x,  y,  z 
are  long-lived  species  of  animals  ;  x^  y,  z  are  the  only 
species  which  have  no  gall ;  ergo  all  animals  which 
have  no  gall  are  long-lived."  This  is  the  "  induction 
by  simple  enumeration  "  denounced  by  Francis  Bacon 
on  the  ground  that  it  may  always  be  discredited  by 
the  production  of  a  single  "  contrary  instance  " — e.g.  a 
single  instance  of  an  animal  which  has  no  gall  and  yet 
is  not  long-lived.  Aristotle  is  quite  aware  that  his 
"  induction  "  does  not  establish  its  conclusion  unless 
all  the  cases  have  been  included  in  the  examination. 
In  fact,  as  his  own  example  shows,  an  induction  which 
gives  certainty  does  not  start  with  "  particular  facts  " 
at  all.  It  is  a  method  of  arguing  that  what  has  been 
proved  true  of  'each  sub-class  of  a  wider  class  will  be 
true  of  the  wider  class  as  a  whole.  The  premisses  are 
strictly  universal  throughout.  In  general,  Aristotle 
does  not  regard  "  induction  "  as  p7'oqf  a.t  all.  Histori- 
cally '*  induction  "  is  held  by  Aristotle  to  have  been 
first  made  prominent  in  philosophy  by  Socrates,  who 
constantly  employed  the  method  in  his  attempts  to 


36  AEISTOTLE. 

elicit  universal  results  in  moral  science.  Thus  he 
gives,  as  a  characteristic  argument  for  the  famous 
Socratic  doctrine  that  knowledge  is  the  one  thing 
needful,  the  "induction,"  "he  who  understands  the 
theory  of  navigation  is  the  best  navigator,  he  who 
understands  the  theory  of  chariot-driving  the  best 
driver  ;  from  these  examples  we  see  that  universally 
he  who  understands  the  theory  of  a  thing  is  the  best 
practitioner,"  where  it  is  evident  that  all  the  relevant 
cases  have  not  been  examined,  and  consequently  that  the 
reasoning  does  not  amount  to  proof.  Mill's  so-called 
reasoning  from  particulars  to  particulars  finds  a  place 
in  Aristotle's  theory  under  the  name  of  "  arguing  from 
an  example."  He  gives  as  an  illustration,  "  A  w^ar 
between  Athens  and  Thebes  will  be  a  bad  thing,  for 
we  see  that  the  war  between  Thebes  and  Phocis  was 
so."  He  is  careful  to  point  out  that  the  whole  force  of 
the  argument  depends  on  the  implied  assumption  of  a 
universal  proposition  which  covers  both  cases,  such  as 
"  wars  between  neighbours  are  bad  things."  Hence  he 
calls  such  appeals  to  example  "  rhetorical "  reasoning, 
because  the  politician  *  is  accustomed  to  leave  his 
hearers  to  supply  the  relevant  universal  consideration 
for  themselves. 

Theory  of  Knowledge. — Here,  as  everywhere  in 
Aristotle's  philosophy,  we  are  confronted  by  an  initial 
and  insuperable  difficulty.  Aristotle  is  always  anxious 
to  insist  on  the  difference  between  his  own  doctrines 
and  those  of  Plato,  and  his  bias  in  this  direction 
regularly  leads  him  to  speak  as  though  he  held  a 
thorough-going  naturalistic  and  empirical  theory  with 
no  "transcendental  moonshine"  about  it.  Yet  his 
final  conclusions  on  all  points  of  importance  are  hardly 

*  We  must  remember  that  "  rhetorician  "  or  "  orator,"  in  the 
Greek  of  Aristotle's  day,  means  "  politician." 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     37 

distinguishable  from  those  of  Plato,  except  by  the 
fact  that,  as  they  are  so  much  at  variance  with  the 
naturalistic  side  of  his  philosophy,  they  have  the 
appearance  of  being  sudden  lapses  into  an  alogical 
mysticism.  We  shall  find  the  presence  of  this  "  fault " 
more  pronouncedly  in  his  metaphysics,  psychology, 
and  ethics  than  in  his  theory  of  knowledge,  but  it  is 
not  absent  from  any  part  of  his  philosophy.  He  is 
everywhere  a  Platonist  malgre  lui,  and  it  is  just  the 
Platonic  element  in  his  thought  to  which  it  owes  its 
hold  over  men's  minds. 

Plato's  doctrine  on  the  subject  may  be  stated  with 
enough  accuracy  for  our  purpose  as  follows.  There 
is  a  radical  distinction  between  sense-perception  and 
scientific  knowledge.  A  scientific  truth  is  exact  and 
definite,  it  is  also  true  once  and  for  all,  and  never 
becomes  truer  or  falser  with  the  lapse  of  time.  This 
is  the  character  of  the  propositions  of  the  science 
which  Plato  regarded  as  the  type  of  what  true  science 
ought  to  be — pure  mathematics.  It  is  very  different 
with  the  judgments  which  we  try  to  base  on  our 
sense-perceptions  of  the  visible  and  tangible  world. 
The  colours,  tastes,  shapes  of  sensible  things  seem 
different  to  different  percipients,  and  moreover  they 
are  constantly  changing  in  incalculable  ways.  We  can 
never  be  certain  that  two  lines  which  seem  to  our 
senses  to  be  equal  are  really  so ;  it  may  be  that  the 
inequality  is  merely  too  slight  to  be  perceptible  to  our 
senses.  No  figure  which  we  can  draw  and  see  actually 
has  the  exact  properties  ascribed  by  the  mathematician 
to  a  circle  or  a  square.  Hence  Plato  concludes  that  if 
the  word  science  be  taken  in  its  fullest  sense,  there  can 
be  no  science  about  the  world  which  our  senses  reveal. 
We  can  have  only  an  approximate  knowledge,  a 
knowledge  which  is  after  all,  at  best,  probable  opinion. 


38  AKISTOTLE. 

The  objects  of  which  the  mathematician  has  certain, 
exact,  and  final  knowledge  cannot  be  anything  which 
the  senses  reveal.  They  are  objects  of  thought,  and 
the  function  of  visible  models  and  diagrams  in  mathe- 
matics is  not  to  present  examples  of  them  to  us,  but 
only  to  show  us  imperfect  approximations  to  them,  and 
so  to  "  remind "  the  soul  of  objects  and  relations 
between  them  which  she  has  never  cognised  with  the 
bodily  senses.  Thus  mathematical  straightness  is 
never  actually  beheld,  but  when  we  see  lines  of  less 
and  more  approximate  straightness  we  are  "  put  in 
mind"  of  that  absolute  straightness  to  which  sense- 
perception  only  approximates.  So  in  the  moral 
sciences,  the  various  "  virtues  "  are  not  presented  in 
their  perfection  by  the  course  of  daily  life.  We  do 
not  meet  with  men  who  are  perfectly  brave  or  just, 
but  the  experience  that  one  man  is  braver  or  juster 
than  another  "  calls  into  our  mind  "  the  thought  of  the 
absolute  standard  of  courage  or  justice  implied  in  the 
conviction  that  one  man  comes  nearer  to  it  than  an- 
other, and  it  is  these  absolute  standards  which  are 
the  real  objects  of  our  attention  when  we  try  to  define 
the  terms  by  which  we  describe  the  moral  life.  This 
is  the  "  epistemological  "  side  of  the  famous  doctrine  of 
the  "  Ideas."  The  main  points  are  two  :  (1)  that  strict 
science  deals  throughout  with  objects  and  relations 
between  objects  which  are  of  a  purely  intellectual  or 
conceptual  order,  no  sense-data  entering  into  their 
constitution ;  (2)  since  the  objects  of  science  are  of 
this  character,  it  follows  that  the  "  Idea  "  or  "  concept " 
or  "universal"  is  not  arrived  at  by  any  process  of 
"  abstracting  "  from  our  experience  of  sensible  things 
the  features  common  to  them  all.  As  the  particular 
fact  never  actually  exhibits  the  "universal"  except 
approximately,   the    "universal"   cannot    be    simply 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     39 

disentangled  from  particulars  by  abstraction.  As 
Plato  puts  it,  it  is  "  apart  from "  particulars,  or,  as 
we  might  reword  his  thought,  the  pure  concepts  of 
science  represent  "  upper  limits  "  to  which  the  com- 
parative series  which  we  can  form  out  of  sensible 
data  continually  approximate  but  do  not  reach  them. 
In  his  theory  of  knowledge  Aristotle  begins  by 
brushing  aside  the  Platonic  view.  Science  requires  no 
such  "  Ideas,"  transcending  sense-experience,  as  Plato 
had  spoken  of ;  they  are,  in  fact,  no  more  than 
"  poetic  metaphors."  What  is  required  for  science  is 
not  that  there  should  be  a  "  one  over  and  above  the 
many  "  (that  is,  such  pure  concepts,  unrealised  in  the 
world  of  actual  perception,  as  Plato  had  spoken  of), 
but  only  that  it  should  be  possible  to  predicate  one 
term  universally  of  many  others.  This,  by  itself, 
means  that  the  "universal"  is  looked  on  as  a  mere 
residue  of  the  characteristics  found  in  each  member  of 
a  group,  got  by  abstraction — i.e.  by  leaving  out  of  view 
the  characteristics  which  are  peculiar  to  some  of  the 
group  and  retaining  only  those  which  are  common  to 
all.  If  Aristotle  had  held  consistently  to  this  point 
of  view,  his  theory  of  knowledge  would  have  been  a 
purely  empirical  one.  He  would  have  had  to  say  that, 
since  all  the  objects  of  knowledge  are  particular  facts 
given  in  sense-perception,  the  universal  laws  of  science 
are  a  mere  convenient  way  of  describing  the  observed 
uniformities  in  the  behaviour  of  sensible  things.  But 
since  it  is  obvious  that  in  pure  mathematics  we  are 
not  concerned  with  the  actual  relations  between  sen- 
sible data  or  the  actual  ways  in  which  they  behave, 
but  with  so-called  "pure  cases"  or  ideals  to  which 
the  perceived  world  only  approximately  conforms,  he 
would  also  have  had  to  say  that  the  propositions  of 
mathematics  are  not  strictly  true.     In  modern  times 


40  ARISTOTLE. 

consistent  empiricists  have  said  this,  but  it  is  not  a 
position  possible  to  one  who  had  passed  twenty  years 
in  association  with  the  mathematicians  of  the  Academy, 
and  Aristotle's  theory  only  begins  in  naturalism  to  end 
in  Platonism.  We  may  condense  its  most  striking 
positions  into  the  following  statement.  By  science  we 
mean  proved  knowledge.  And  proved  knowledge  is 
always  "  mediated " ;  it  is  the  knowledge  of  con^ 
elusions  from  premisses.  A  truth  that  is  scientifi- 
cally known  does  not  stand  alone.  The  "  proof  "  is 
simply  the  pointing  out  of  the  connection  between  the 
truth  we  call  the  conclusion  and  other  truths  which 
we  call  the  premisses  of  our  demonstration.  Science 
points  out  the  reason  why  of  things,  and  this  is  what 
is  meant  by  the  Aristotelian  principle  that  to  have 
science  is  to  know  things  through  their  causes  or  reasons 
why.  In  an  ordered  digest  of  scientific  truths,  the 
proper  arrangement  is  to  begin  with  the  simplest 
and  most  widely  extended  principles  and  to  reason 
down,  through  successive  inferences,  to  the  most 
complex  propositions,  the  reason  why  of  which  can 
only  be  exhibited  by  long  chains  of  deductions.  This 
is  the  order  of  logical  dependence,  and  is  described  by 
Aristotle  as  reasoning  from,  what  is  "  more  knowable 
in  its  own  nature,"  *  the  simple,  to  what  is  usually 
"  more  familiar  to  ws,"  because  less  removed  from  the 
infinite  wealth  of  sense-perception,  the  complex.  In 
discovery  we  have  usually  to  reverse  the  process  and 
argue  from  "  the  familiar  to  us,"  highly  complex  facts, 
to  "  the  more  knowable  in  its  own  nature,"  the  simpler 
principles  implied  in  the  facts. 

It    follows    that   Aristotle,    after   all,    admitjs   the 

*  This  simple  expression  acquires  a  mysterious  appearance 
in  mediaeval  philosophy  from  the  standing  mistranslation  notiora 
natures,  "  better  known  to  nature." 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     41 

disparateness  of  sense-perception  and  scientific  know- 
ledge. Sense-perception  of  itself  never  gives  us  scien- 
tific truth,  because  it  can  only  assure  us  that  a  fact  is 
so;  it  cannot  explain  the  fact  by  showing  its  con- 
nection with  the  rest  of  the  system  of  facts,  "  it  does 
not  give  the  reason  for  the  fact."  Knowledge  of 
perception  is  always  "  immediate,"  and  for  that  very 
reason  is  never  scientific.  If  we  stood  on  the  moon 
and  saw  the  earth  interposing  between  us  and  the 
sun,  we  should  still  not  have  scientific  knowledge 
about  the  eclipse,  because  "we  should  still  have  to 
ask  for  the  reason  why"  (In  fact,  we  should  not 
know  the  reason  why  without  a  theory  of  light  includ- 
ing the  proposition  that  light-waves  are  propagated 
in  straight  lines  and  several  others.)  Similarly 
Aristotle  insists  that  Induction  does  not  yield  scien- 
tific proof.  "  He  who  makes  an  induction  points  out 
something,  but  does  not  demonstrate  anything." 

For  instance,  if  we  know  that  each  species  of 
animal  which  is  without  a  gall  is  long-lived,  we  may 
make  the  induction  that  all  animals  without  a  gall  are 
long-lived,  but  in  doing  so  we  have  got  no  nearer  to 
seeing  why  or  how  the  absence  of  a  gall  makes  for 
longevity.  The  questions  which  we  may  raise  in 
science  may  all  be  reduced  to  four  heads :  (1)  Does 
this  thing  exist  1  (2)  Does  this  event  occur  1  (3)  If  the 
thing  exists,  precisely  what  is  it  ?  and  (4)  If  the  event 
occurs,  why  does  it  occur?  and  science  has  not  com- 
pleted its  task  unless  it  can  advance  from  the  solution 
of  the  first  two  questions  to  that  of  the  latter  two. 
Science  is  no  mere  catalogue  of  things  and  events ;  it 
consists  of  inquiries  into  the  "  real  essences "  and 
characteristics  of  things  and  the  laws  of  connection 
betw^een  events. 

Looking  at  scientific  reasoning,  then,  from  the  point 


42  AEISTOTLE. 

of  view  of  its  formal  character,  we  may  say  that  all 
science  consists  in  the  search  for  "  middle  terms "  of 
syllogisms,  by  which  to  connect  the  truth  which 
appears  as  a  conclusion  with  the  less  complex  truths 
which  appear  as  the  premisses  from  which  it  is  drawn. 
When  we  ask,  "  does  such  a  thing  exist  ? "  or  "  does  such 
an  event  happen  ? "  we  are  asking,  "  is  there  a  middle 
term  which  can  connect  the  thing  or  event  in  question 
with  the  rest  of  known  reality  1 "  Since  it  is  a  rule  of 
the  syllogism  that  the  middle  term  must  be  taken 
universally,  at  least  once  in  the  premisses,  the  search 
for  middle  terms  may  also  be  described  as  the  search 
for  universals,  and  we  may  speak  of  science  as  know- 
ledge of  the  universal  interconnections  between  facts 
and  events. 

A  science,  then,  may  be  analysed  into  three  con- 
stituents. These  are :  (1)  A  determinate  class  of 
objects  which  form  the  subject-matter  of  its  inquiries. 
In  an  orderly  exhibition  of  the  contents  of  the 
science,  these  appear,  as  in  Euclid,  as  the  initial 
data  about  which  the  science  reasons.  (2)  A  number 
of  principles,  postulates,  and  axioms,  from  which  our 
demonstrations  must  start.  Some  of  these  will  be 
principles  employed  in  all  scientific  reasoning ;  others 
will  be  specific  to  the  subject-matter  with  which  a 
particular  science  is  concerned.  (3)  Certain  charac- 
teristics of  the  objects  under  study  which  can  be 
shown  by  means  of  our  axioms  and  postulates  to 
follow  from  our  initial  definitions,  the  accidentia  'per 
se  of  the  objects  defined.  It  is  these  last  which  are 
expressed  by  the  conclusions  of  scientific  demonstra- 
tion. We  are  said  to  know  scientifically  that  B  is 
true  of  A  when  we  show  that  this  follows,  in  virtue 
of  the  principles  of  some  science,  from  the  initial 
definition  of  A.     Thus  if  we  convinced  ourselves  that 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     43 

the  sum  of  the  angles  of  a  plane  triangle  is  equal  to 
two  right  angles  by  measurement,  we  could  not  be 
said  to  have  scientific  knowledge  of  the  proposition. 
But  if  we  show  that  the  same  proposition  follows 
from  the  definition  of  a  plane  triangle  by  repeated 
applications  of  admitted  axioms  or  postulates  of 
geometry,  our  knowledge  is  genuinely  scientific.  We 
now  know  that  it  is  so,  and  we  see  why  it  is  so  j  we 
see  the  connection  of  this  truth  with  the  simple  initial 
truths  of  geometry. 

This  leads  us  to  the  consideration  of  the  most 
characteristic  point  of  Aristotle's  whole  theory. 
Science  is  demonstrated  knowledge — that  is,  it  is  the 
knowledge  that  certain  truths  follow  from  still  simpler 
truths.  Hence  the  simplest  of  all  the  truths  of  any 
science  cannot  themselves  be  capable  of  being  known 
by  inference.  You  cannot  infer  that  the  axioms  of 
geometry  are  true  because  its  conclusions  are  true, 
since  the  truth  of  the  conclusions  is  itself  a  consequence 
of  the  truth  of  the  axioms.  Nor  yet  must  you  ask  for 
demonstration  of  the  axioms  as  consequences  of  still 
simpler  premisses,  because  if  all  truths  can  be  proved, 
they  ought  to  be  proved,  and  you  would  therefore 
require  an  infinity  of  successive  demonstrations  to 
prove  anything  whatever.  But  under  such  condi- 
tions all  knowledge  of  demonstrated  truth  would  be 
impossible.  The  first  principles  of  any  science  must 
therefore  be  indemonstrable.  They  must  be  known, 
as  facts  of  sense-perception  are  known,  inmaediately 
and  not  mediately.  How  then  do  we  come  by  our 
knowledge  of  them?  Aristotle's  answer  to  this 
question  appears  at  first  sight  curiously  contradictory. 
He  seems  to  say  that  these  simplest  truths  are  ap- 
prehended intuitively,  or  on  inspection,  as  self- 
evident   by    Intelligence   or   Mind.     On    the    other 


44  AEISTOTLE. 

hand,  he  also  says  that  they  are  known  to  us  as  a 
result  of  induction  from  sense-experience.  Thus  he 
seems  to  be  either  a  Platonist  or  an  empiricist,  ac- 
cording as  you  choose  to  remember  one  set  of  his 
utterances  or  another,  and  this  apparent  inconsistency 
has  led  to  his  authority  being  claimed  in  their  favour 
by  thinkers  of  the  most  widely  different  types.  But 
more  careful  study  will  show  that  the  seeming  con- 
fusion is  due  to  the  fact  that  he  tries  to  combine 
in  one  statement  his  answers  to  two  quite  different 
questions :  (1)  how  we  come  to  reflect  on  the  axioms, 
(2)  what  evidence  there  is  for  their  truth.  To  the 
first  question  he  replies,  *'  by  induction  from  experi- 
ence," and  so  far  he  might  seem  to  be  a  precursor 
of  John  Stuart  Mill.  Successive  repetitions  of  the 
same  sense-perceptions  give  rise  to  a  single  experience, 
and  it  is  by  reflection  on  experience  that  we  become 
aware  of  the  most  ultimate  simple  and  universal 
principles.  We  might  illustrate  his  point  by  con- 
sidering how  the  thought  that  two  and  two  are  four 
may  be  brought  before  a  child's  mind.  We  might 
first  take  two  apples,  and  two  other  apples,  and  set  the 
child  to  count  them.  By  repeating  the  process  with 
different  apples  we  may  teach  the  child  to  dissociate 
the  result  of  the  counting  from  the  particular  apples 
employed,  and  to  advance  to  the  thought,  "  any  two 
apples  and  any  two  other  apples  make  four  apples." 
Then  we  might  substitute  pears  or  cherries  for  the 
apples,  so  as  to  suggest  the  thought,  "  two  fruits  and 
two  fruits  make  four  fruits."  And  by  similar  nvethods 
we  should  in  the  end  evoke  the  thought,  "  any  two 
objects  whatever  and  any  other  two  objects  whatever 
make  four  objects."  This  exactly  illustrates  Aristotle's 
conception  of  the  function  of  induction,  or  comparison 
of  instances,  in  fixing  attention  on  a  universal  prin- 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     45 

ciple  of  which  one  had  not  been  conscious  before  the 
comparison  was  made. 

Now  comes  in  the  point  where  Aristotle  differs 
wholly  from  all  empiricists,  later  and  earlier.  Mill 
regards  the  instances  produced  in  the  induction  as 
having  a  double  function  :  they  not  merely  fix  the 
attention  on  the  principle,  they  also  are  the  evidence 
of  its  trutL  This  gives  rise  to  the  greatest  difficulty 
in  his  whole  logical  theory.  Induction  by  imperfect 
enumeration  is  pronounced  to  be  (as  it  clearly  is) 
fallacious,  yet  the  principle  of  the  uniformity  of 
Nature  which  Mill  regards  as  the  ultimate  premiss  of 
all  science,  is  itself  supposed  to  be  proved  by  this 
radically  fallacious  method.  Aristotle  avoids  a  simi- 
lar inconsistency  by  holding  that  the  sole  function 
of  the  induction  is  to  fix  our  attention  on  a  principle 
which  it  does  not  prove.  He  holds  that  ultimate 
principles  neither  permit  of  nor  require  proof.  When 
the  induction  has  done  its  work  in  calling  attention 
to  the  principle,  you  have  to  see  for  yourself  that  the 
principle  is  true.  You  see  that  it  is  true  by  im- 
mediate inspection,  just  as  m  sense-perception  you 
have  to  see  that  the  colour  before  your  eyes  is  red  or 
blue.  This  is  why  Aristotle  holds  that  the  know- 
ledge of  the  principles  of  science  is  not  itself  science 
(demonstrated  knowledge),  but  what  he  calls  intelli- 
gence, and  we  may  call  intellectual  intuition.  Thus 
his  doctrine  is  sharply  distinguished  not  only  from 
empiricism  (the  doctrine  that  universal  principles  are 
proved  by  particular  facts),  but  also  from  all  theories 
of  the  Hegelian  type  which  regard  the  principles  and 
the  facts  as  somehow  reciprocally  proving  each  other, 
and  from  the  doctrine  of  some  eminent  modem 
logicians  who  hold  that  "self-evidence"  is  not  re- 
quired in  the  ultimate  principles  of  science,  as  we 


46  ARISTOTLE. 

are  only  concerned  in  logic  with  the  question  what 
consequences  follow  from  our  initial  assumptions, 
and  not  with  the  truth  or  falsehood  of  the  assumptions 
themselves. 

The  result  is  that  Aristotle  does  little  more  than 
repeat  the  Platonic  view  of  the  nature  of  science. 
Science  consists  of  deductions  from  universal  prin- 
ciples which  sensible  experience  "  suggests/'  but  into 
which,  as  they  are  apprehended  by  a  purely  intellec- 
tual inspection,  no  sense-data  enter  as  constituents. 
The  apparent  rejection  of  "transcendental  moon- 
shine "  has,  after  all,  led  to  nothing.  The  only  differ- 
ence between  Plato  and  his  scholar  lies  in  the  clear- 
ness of  intellectual  vision  which  Plato  shows  when  he 
expressly  maintains  in  plain  words  that  the  universals 
of  exact  science  are  not  "  in "  our  sense-perceptions 
and  therefore  to  be  extracted  from  them  by  a  process 
of  abstraction,  but  are  "apart  from"  or  "over" 
them,  and  form  an  ideal  system  of  interconnected 
concepts  which  the  experiences  of  sense  merely 
"  imitate  "  or  make  approximation  to. 

One  more  point  remains  to  be  considered  to  com- 
plete our  outline  of  the  Aristotelian  theory  of  know- 
ledge. The  sciences  have  "principles"  which  are 
discerned  to  be  true  by  immediate  inspection.  But 
what  if  one  man  professes  to  see  the  self-evident  truth 
of  such  an  alleged  principle,  while  another  is  doubtful 
of  its  truth,  or  even  denies  it?  There  can  be  no 
question  of  silencing  the  objector  by  a  demonstration, 
since  no  genuine  simple  principle  admits  o/  demon- 
stration. All  that  can  be  done — e.y.  if  a  man  doubts 
whether  things  equal  to  the  same  thing  are  equal  to 
one  another,  or  whether  the  la,w  of  contradiction  is 
true — is  to  examine  the  consequences  of  a  denial  of  the 
axiom  and  to  show  that  they  include  some  which  are 


CLASSIFICATION  OF  THE  SCIENCES.     47 

false,  or  which  your  antagonist  at  least  considers  false. 
In  this  way,  by  showing  the  falsity  of  consequences 
which  follow  from  the  denial  of  a  given  "  principle," 
you  indirectly  establish  its  truth.  Now  reasoning  of 
this  kind  differs  from  "science"  precisely  in  the 
point  that  you  take  as  your  major  premiss,  not  what 
you  regard  as  true,  but  the  opposite  thesis  of  your 
antagonist,  which  you  regard  as  false.  Your  object 
is  not  to  prove  a  true  conclusion  but  to  show  your 
opponent  that  his  premisses  lead  to  false  conclusions. 
This  is  "dialectical"  reasoning  in  Aristotle's  sense  of 
the  word — i.e.  reasoning  not  from  your  own  but  from 
some  one  else's  premisses.  Hence  the  chief  philosoph- 
ical importance  which  Aristotle  ascribes  to  "dialec- 
tic" is  that  it  provides  a  method  of  defending  the 
undemonstrable  axioms  against  objections.  Dialectic 
of  this  kind  became  highly  important  in  the  mediaeval 
Aristotelianism  of  the  schoolmen,  with  whom  it 
became  a  regular  method,  as  may  be  seen  e.g.  in  the 
Summa  of  St.  Thomas,  to  begin  their  consideration  of 
a  doctrine  by  a  preliminary  rehearsal  of  all  the  argu- 
ments they  could  find  or  devise  against  the  conclusion 
they  meant  to  adopt.  Thus  the  first  division  of  any 
article  in  the  Summa  Theologiae  of  Thomas  is  regularly 
constituted  by  arguments  based  on  the  premisses  of 
actual  or  possible  antagonists,  an,d  is  strictly  dialec- 
tical. (To  be  quite  accurate  Aristotle  should,  of 
course,  have  observed  that  this  dialectical  method  of 
defending  a  principle  becomes  useless  in  the  case  of  a 
logical  axiom  which  is  presupposed  by  all  deduction. 
For  this  reason  Aristotle  falls  into  fallacy  when  he 
tries  to  defend  the  law  of  contradiction  by  dialectic. 
It  is  true  that  if  the  law  be  denied,  then  any  and 
every  predicate  may  be  indifferently  ascribed  to  any 
subject.     But  until  the  law  of  contradiction  has  been 


48  ARISTOTLE. 

admitted,  you  have  no  right  to  regard  it  as  absurd  to 
ascribe  all  predicates  indiscriminately  to  all  subjects. 
Thus,  it  is  only  assumed  laws  which  are  riot  ultimate 
laws  of  logic  that  admit  of  dialectical  justification.  If 
a  truth  is  so  ultimate  that  it  has  either  to  be  recog- 
nised by  direct  inspection  or  not  at  all,  there  can  be 
no  arguing  at  all  with  one  who  cannot  or  will  not 
see  it.) 


CHAPTER  III 

FIRST     PHILOSOPHY 

First  Philosophy  is  defined  by  Aristotle  as  a  "  science 
which  considers  What  Is  simply  in  its  character  of 
Being,  and  the  properties  which  it  has  as  such."  That 
there  is,  or  ought  to  be,  such  a  science  is  urged  on  the 
ground  that  every  "  special "  science  deals  only  with 
some  restricted  department  of  what  is,  and  thus  con- 
siders its  subject-matter  not  universally  in  its  char- 
acter of  being,  or  being  real,  but  as  determined  by 
some  more  special  condition.  Thus,  First  Philosophy, 
the  science  which  attempts  to  discover  the  most 
ultimate  reasons  of,  or  grounds  for,  the  character  of 
things  in  general  cannot  be  identified  with  any  of  the 
"  departmental "  sciences.  The  same  consideration 
explains  why  it  is  "  First  Philosophy  "  which  has  to 
disentangle  the  "  principles  "  of  the  various  sciences, 
and  defend  them  by  dialectic  against  those  who  im- 
pugn them.  It  is  no  part  of  the  duty  of  a  geometer 
or  a  physicist  to  deal  with  objections  to  such  universal 
principles  of  reasoning  as  the  law  of  contradiction. 
They  may  safely  assume  such  principles ;  if  they  are 
attacked,  it  is  not  by  specifically  geometrical  or  physi- 
cal considerations  that  they  can  be  defended.  Even 
the  "principles  of  the  special  sciences  "  have  not  to  be 
examined  and  defended  by  the  special  sciences.     They 

(1,994)  4 


50  ARISTOTLE. 

are  the  starting-points  of  the  sciences  which  employ 
them;  these  sciences  are  therefore  justified  in  re- 
quiring that  they  shall  be  admitted  as  a  condition  of 
geometrical,  or  physical,  or  biological  demonstrations. 
If  they  are  called  in  question,  the  defence  of  them  is 
the  business  of  logic. 

First  Philosophy,  then,  is  the  study  of  **  What  Is 
simply  as  such,"  the  universal  principles  of  structure 
without  which  there  could  be  no  ordered  system  of 
knowable  objects.  But  the  word  "is "  has  more  than 
one  sense.  There  are  as  many  modes  of  being  as 
there  are  types  of  predication.  "Substances,"  men, 
liorses,  and  the  like,  have  their  own  specific  mode  of 
being — they  are  things ;  qualities,  such  as  green  or 
sweet,  have  a  different  mode  of  being — they  are 
not  things,  but  "  affections  "  or  "  attributes  "  of  things. 
Actions,  again,  such  as  building,  killing,  are  neither 
things  nor  yet  "  affections  "  of  things ;  their  mode  of 
being  is  that  they  are  processes  which  produce  or 
destroy  things.  First  Philosophy  is  concerned  with 
the  general  character  of  all  these  modes  of  being,  but 
it  is  specially  concerned  with  that  mode  of  being  which 
belongs  to  substances.  For  this  is  the  most  primary 
of  all  modes  of  being.  We  had  to  introduce  a  refer- 
ence to  it  in  our  attempt  to  say  what  the  mode  of 
being  of  qualities  and  actions  is,  and  it  would  have 
been  the  same  had  our  illustrations  been  drawn  from 
any  other  "categories."  Hence  the  central  and 
special  problem  of  First  Philosophy  is  to  analyse  the 
notion  of  substance  and  to  show  the  causes  of  the 
existence  of  substances. 

Next,  we  have  to  note  that  the  word  "  substance  " 
itself  has  two  senses.  When  we  spoke  of  substance  as 
one  of  the  categories  we  were  using  it  in  a  secondary 
sense.     We  meant  by  substances  "  horse,"  "  mafi,"  and 


FIRST  PHILOSOPHY.  51 

the  rest  of  the  "  real  kinds  "  which  we  find  in  Nature, 
and  try  to  reproduce  in  a  scientific  classification.  In 
this  sense  of  the  word  "  substances  "  are  a  special  class 
of  predicates,  as  when  we  affirm  of  Plato  that  he  is 
a  man,  or  of  Bucephalus  that  he  is  a  horse.  But  in 
the  primary  sense  a  substance  means  an  absolutely 
individual  thing,  "  this  man,"  or  "  this  horse."  We 
may  therefore  define  primary  substances  from  the 
logician's  point  of  view  by  saying  that  they  can  be 
only  subjects  of  predication,  never  predicates.  Or^' 
again,  it  is  peculiar  to  substances,  that  whUe  remain- [ 
ing  numerically  one  a  substance  admits  of  incom-J 
patible  determinations,  as  Socrates,  remaining  one/ 
and  the  same  Socrates,  is  successively  young  and  old. 
This  is  not  true  of  ** qualities,"  "actions,"  and  the 
rest.  The  same  colour  cannot  be  first  white  and  then 
black ;  the  same  act  cannot  be  first  bad  and  then 
good.  Thus  we  may  say  that  individual  substances 
are  the  fixed  and  permanent  factors  in  the  world  of 
mutability,  the  invariants  of  existence.  Processes 
go  on  in  them,  they  run  the  gamut  of  changes  from 
birth  to  decay,  processes  take  place  among  them,  they 
act  on  and  are  acted  on  by  one  another,  they  fluctuate 
in  their  qualities  and  their  magnitude,  but  so  long  as 
[a  substance  exists  it  remains  numerically  one  and  the 
/same  throughout  all  these  changes.  Their  existence 
is  the  first  and  most  fundamental  condition  of  the 
existence  of  the  universe,  since  they  are  the  bearers 
of  all  qualities,  the  terms  of  all  relations,  and  the 
agents  and  patients  in  all  interaction. 

The  point  to  note  is  that  Aristotle  begins  his  in- 
vestigation into  the  structure  of  What  Is  and  the 
causes  by  which  it  is  produced  by  starting  from  the 
existence  of  individual  things  belonging  to  the  physical 
order  and  perceived  by  the  senses.     About  any  such 


52  ARISTOTLE. 


thing  we  may  ask  two  questions,  (1)  into  what  con 
stituent  factors  can  it  be  logically  analysed?  (2)  and 
how  has  it  come  to  exhibit  the  character  which  our 
analysis  shows  it  to  have?  The  answer  to  these 
questions  will  appear  from  a  consideration  of  two 
standing  antitheses  which  run  through  Aristotle's 
philosophy,  the  contrast  between  Matter  and  Form, 
and  that  between  Potential  and  Actual,  followed  by 
a  recapitulation  of  his  doctrine  of  the  Four  Causes, 
or  four  senses  of  the  word  Cause. 

Matter  and  Form. — Consider  any  completely  de- 
veloped individual  thing,  whether  it  is  the  product  of 
human  manufacture,  as  a  copper  bowl,  or  of  natural 
reproduction,  as  an  oak-tree  or  a  horse.  We  shall 
see  at  once  that  the  bowl  is  like  other  articles  made 
of  the  same  metal,  candlesticks,  coal-vases,  in  being 
made  of  the  same  stuff,  and  unlike  them  in  having 
the  special  shape  or  structure  which  renders  it  fit 
for  being  used  as  a  bowl  and  not  for  holding  a  candle 
or  containing  coals.  So  a  botanist  or  a  chemist  will 
tell  you  that  the  constituent  tissues  of  an  oak  or 
horse,  or  the  chemical  elements  out  of  which  these 
tissues  are  built  up  are  of  the  same  kind  as  those  of 
an  ash  or  an  ox,  but  the  oak  differs  from  the  ash  or 
the  horse  from  the  ox  in  characteristic  structure. 
We  see  thus  that  in  any  individual  thing  we  can 
distinguish  two  components,  the  stuff  of  which  it 
consists — which  may  be  identical  in  kind  with  the 
stuff  of  which  things  of  a  very  different  kind  consist 
— and  the  structural  law  of  formation  or  arrangement 
which  is  peculiar  to  the  "  special "  kind  of  thing  under 
consideration.  In  the  actual  individual  thing  these 
two  are  inseparably  united ;  they  do  not  exist  side 
by  side,  as  chemists  say  the  atoms  of  hydrogen  and 
oxygen  do  in  a  drop  of  water ;  the  law  of  organisa- 


nnn.    ^^ 


FIRST  PHILOSOPHY.  53 

tion  or  structure  is  manifested  in  and  through  the 
copper,  or  the  various  tissues  of  the  living  body. 
Aristotle  expresses  this  by  saying  that  you  can  dis- 
tinguish two  aspects  in  an  individual,  its  Matter, 
{hyhy  'materia)  and  its  Form  (eidos,  forma).  The 
individual  is  the  matter  as  organised  in  accord  with 
a  determinate  principle  of  structure,  the  form.  Of 
these  terms,  the  former,  hyle  {materia^  matter)  means 
literally  timber,  and  more  specifically  ship's  timbers, 
and  the  selection  of  it  to  mean  what  is  most  exactly 
rendered  by  our  own  word  "stuff"  may  perhaps  be 
due  to  a  reminiscence  of  an  old  Pythagorean  fancy 
which  looked  on  the  universe  as  a  ship.  The  word 
for  form  is  the  same  as  Plato's,  and  its  philosophical 
uses  are  closely  connected  with  its  mathematical  sense, 
"regular  figure,"  also  a  Pythagorean  technicality 
which  still  survives  in  certain  stereotyped  phrases  in 
Euclid.  Aristotle  extends  the  analysis  into  Matter 
and  Form  by  analogy  beyond  the  range  of  individual 
substances  to  everything  in  which  we  can  distinguish 
a  relatively  indeterminate  "  somewhat "  and  a  law  or 
type  of  order  and  arrangement  giving  it  determina- 
tion. Thus  if  we  consider  the  relatively  fixed  or 
"formed"  character  of  a  man  in  adult  life,  we  may 
look  upon  this  character  as  produced  out  of  the  "  raw 
material "  of  tendencies  and  dispositions,  which  have 
received  a  specific  development  along  definite  lines, 
according  to  the  kind  of  training  to  which  the  mind 
has  been  subjected  in  the  "  formative  "  period  of  its 
growth.  We  may  therefore  speak  of  native  disposi- 
tion as  the  matter  or  stuff  of  which  character  is  made, 
and  the  practical  problem  of  education  is  to  devise  a 
system  of  training  which  shall  impress  on  this  matter 
precisely  the  form  required  if  the  grown  man  is  to 
be  a  good  citizen  of  a  good  state.     Since  a  man's 


54  ARISTOTLE. 

character  itself  is  not  a  substance  but  a  complex  of 
habits  or  fixed  ways  of  reacting  upon  suggestions  coming 
from  the  world  around  him,  this  is  a  good  instance 
of  the  extension  of  the  antithesis  of  Matter  and  Form 
beyond  the  category  of  substance.  We  see  then  that 
Matter  in  the  Aristotelian  sense  must  not  be  con- 
founded with  body;  the  relatively  undetermined  fac- 
tor which  receives  completer  determination  by  the 
structural  law  or  Form  is  Matter,  whether  it  is  cor- 
poreal or  not.  This  comes  out  with  particular  clear- 
ness in  the  metaphysical  interpretation  put  on  the 
logical  process  of  definition  by  genus  and  difference. 
When  I  define  any  real  kind  by  specifying  a  higher 
and  wider  class  of  which  it  is  a  sub-kind,  and  adding 
the  peculiar  characteristics  which  distinguish  the  sub- 
kind  under  consideration  from  the  other  sub-kinds 
of  the  same  genus,  the  genus  may  be  said  to  stand  to 
the  "  differences  "  as  Matter,  the  relatively  indetermi- 
nate, to  the  Form  which  gives  it  its  structure. 

We  further  observe  that  Matter  and  Form  are 
strictly  correlative.  The  matter  is  called  so  relatively 
to  the  form  which  gives  it  further  determination. 
When  the  words  are  used  in  their  strictest  sense, 
with  reference  to  an  individual  thing,  the  Form  is 
taken  to  mean  the  last  determination  by  which  the 
thing  acquires  its  complete  character,  and  the  Matter 
is  that  which  has  yet  to  receive  this  last  determination. 
Thus  in  the  case  of  a  copper  globe,  the  spherical 
figure  is  said  to  be  its  Form,  the  copper  its  material. 
In  the  case  of  the  human  body,  the  Matter  is  the 
various  tissues,  muscles,  bones,  skin,  &c.  But  each 
of  these  things  which  are  counted  as  belonging  to  the 
Matter  of  the  globe  or  the  human  body  has,  accord- 
ing to  Aristotle,  a  development  behind  it.  Copper 
is  not  an  "element"  but  a  specific  combination  of 


FIRST  PHILOSOPHY.  55 

"  elements,"  and  the  same  thing  is  even  more  true  of 
the  highly  elaborate  tissues  of  the  living  body.  Thus 
what  is  Matter  relatively  to  the  globe  or  living  body 
is  Matter  already  determined  by  Form  if  we  consider 
it  relatively  to  its  own  constituents.  The  so-called 
"  elements  "  of  Empedocles,  earth,  water,  air,  fire,  are 
the  matter  of  all  chemical  compounds,  the  Form  of 
each  compound  being  its  specific  law  of  composition ; 
the  immediate  or  "  proximate  "  Matter  of  the  tissues 
of  the  animal  body  is,  according  to  Aristotle's  biology, 
the  "  superfluous  "  blood  of  the  female  parent,  out  of 
which  the  various  tissues  in  the  ofi*spring  are  de- 
veloped, and  the  Matter  of  this  blood  is  in  turn  the 
various  substances  which  are  taken  into  the  body  of 
the  parent  as  food  and  converted  by  assimilation  into 
blood.  Their  Matter,  once  more,  is  the  earth,  air, 
fire,  and  water  of  which  they  are  composed.  Thus  at 
every  stage  of  a  process  of  manufacture  or  growth  a 
fresh  Form  is  superinduced  on,  or  developed  within, 
a  Matter  which  is  already  itself  a  combination  of 
Matter  and  Form  relatively  to  the  process  by  which 
it  has  itself  been  originated.  Fully  thought  out,  such 
a  view  would  lead  to  the  conclusion  that  in  the  end 
the  simple  ultimate  matter  of  all  individual  things  is 
one  and  the  same  throughout  the  universe,  and  haa 
absolutely  no  definite  structure  at  all.  The  intro- 
duction of  Form  or  determinate  structure  of  any 
kind  would  then  have  to  be  thought  of  as  coming 
from  an  outside  source,  since  structureless  Matter 
cannot  be  supposed  to  give  itself  all  sorts  of  specific 
determinations,  as  has  been  demonstrated  in  our  own 
times  by  the  collapse  of  the  "  Synthetic  Philosophy." 
Aristotle  avoids  the  diflficulty  by  holding  that  "  pure 
Matter  "  is  a  creation  of  our  thought.  In  actual  fact 
the  crudest  form  in  which  matter  is  found  is  that  of 


56  ARISTOTLE. 


m 

'.   theflj 


the  "elements."  Since  the  transmutability  of 
"elements"  is  an  indispensable  tenet  in  Aristotle's 
Physics,  we  cannot  avoid  regarding  earth,  water,  fire, 
air,  as  themselves  determinations  by  specific  Form  of 
a  still  simpler  Matter,  though  this  "  prime  Matter " 
"  all  alone,  before  a  rag  of  Form  is  on,"  is  never  to  be 
found  existing  in  its  simplicity.* 

The  Potential  and  the  Actual. — So  far  we  have 
been  looking  at  the  analysis  of  the  individual  thing,  m 
as  the  current  jargon  puts  it,  statically ;  we  have  ^1 
arrived  at  the  antithesis  of  Matter  and  Form  by  con- 
trasting an  unfinished  condition  of  anything  with 
its  finished  condition.  But  we  may  study  the  same 
contrast  dynamically,  with  special  reference  to  the 
process  of  making  or  growth  by  which  the  relatively 
undetermined  or  unfinished  becomes  determined  or 
finished.  The  contrast  of  Matter  with  Form  then 
passes  into  the  contrast  between  Potentiality  and 
Actuality.  What  this  antithesis  means  we  can  best 
see  from  the  case  of  the  growth  of  a  living  organism. 
Consider  the  embryos  of  two  animals,  or  the  seeds  of 
two  plants.  Even  a  botanist  or  a  physiologist  may 
be  unable  to  pronounce  with  certainty  on  the  species 
to  which  the  germ  submitted  to  him  belongs,  and 
chemical  analysis  may  be  equally  at  a  loss.  Even  at 
a  later  stage  of  development,  the  embryo  of  one 
vertebrate  animal  may  be  indistinguishable  from  that 
of  another.  Yet  it  is  certain  that  one  of  two 
originally  indistinguishable  germs  will  grow  into  an 
oak  and  the  other  into  an  elm,  or  one  into  a  chim- 
panzee and  the  other  into  a  man.     However  indis- 

*  Hudibras,  Pt.  1,  Canto  1,  560. 

"  He  had  First  Matter  seen  undressed ; 
He  took  her  naked  all  alone, 
Before  one  rag  of  Form  was  on. " 


FIRST  PHILOSOPHY.  57 

tinguishable,  they  therefore  may  be  said  to  have 
different  latent  tendencies  or  possibilities  of  develop- 
ment within  them.  Hence  we  may  say  of  a  given 
germ,  "  though  this  is  not  yet  actually  an  oak,  it  is 
potentially  an  oak,"  meaning  not  merely  that,  if  un- 
interfered  with,  it  will  in  time  be  an  oak,  but  also 
that  by  no  interference  can  it  be  made  to  grow  into 
an  elm  or  a  beech.  So  we  may  look  upon  all  pro- 
cesses of  production  or  development  as  processes  by 
which  what  at  first  possessed  only  the  tendency  to 
grow  along  certain  lines  or  to  be  worked  up  into  a 
certain  form,  has  become  actually  endowed  with  the 
character  to  which  it  possessed  the  tendency.  The 
acorn  becomes  in  process  of  time  an  actual  oak,  the 
baby  an  actual  man,  the  copper  is  made  into  an  actual 
vase,  right  education  brings  out  into  active  exercise 
the  special  capacities  of  the  learner.  Hence  the  dis- 
tinction between  Matter  and  Form  may  also  be  ex 
pressed  by  saying  that  the  Matter  is  the  persisten\ 
underlying  substratiim  in  which  the  development  of 
the  Form  takes  place,  onthat  the  individual  when  finally 
determined  by  the  Form  is  the  Actuality  of  which  the 
undeveloped  Matter  was  the  Potentiality.  The  process 
of  conception,  birth,  and  growth  to  maturity  in  Nature, 
or  of  the  production  of  a  finished  article  by  the  "  arts  " 
whose  business  it  is  to  "  imitate  "  Nature,  may  be  said 
to  be  one  of  continuous  advance  towards  the  actual 
embodiment  of  a  Form,  or  law  of  organisation,  in  a 
Matter  having  the  latent  potentiality  of  developing 
along  those  special  lines.  When  Aristotle  is  speaking 
most  strictly  he  distinguishes  the  process  by  which  a 
Form  is  realised,  which  he  calls  Energeia,  from  the 
manifestation  of  the  realised  Form,  calling  the  latter 
Entelechy  (literally  "finished"  or  "completed"  con- 
dition).    Often,  however,  he  uses  the  word  Energeia 


58  AKISTOTLE. 

more  loosely  for  the  actual  manifestation  of  the  Form 
itself,  and  in  this  he  is  followed  by  the  scholastic 
writers,  who  render  Energeia  by  actus  or  actus  purus. 

One  presupposition  of  this  process  must  be  specially 
noted.  It  is  not  an  unending  process  of  development 
of  unrealised  capacities,  but  always  has  an  End  in 
the  perfectly  simple  sense  of  a  last  stage.  We  see 
this  best  in  the  case  of  growth.  The  acorn  grows  into 
the  sapling  and  the  sapling  into  the  oak,  but  there  is 
nothing  related  to  the  oak  as  the  oak  is  to  the  sapling. 
The  oak  does  not  grow  into  something  else.  The  pro- 
cess of  development  from  potential  to  actual  in  this 
special  case  comes  to  an  end  with  the  emergence  of  the 
mature  oak.  In  the  organic  world  the  end  or  last  state 
is  recognised  by  the  fact  that  the  organism  can  now 
exercise  the  power  of  reproducing  its  like.  This  ten- 
dency of  organic  process  to  culminate  in  a  last  stage  of 
complete  maturity  is  the  key  to  the  treatment  of  the 
problem  of  the  "  true  end  "  of  life  in  Aristotle's  Ethics. 

The  Four  Causes. — The  conception  of  the  world 
involved  in  these  antitheses  of  Form  and  Matter, 
Potential  and  Actual,  finds  its  fullest  expression  in 
Aristotle's  doctrine  of  the  Four  Causes  or  conditions 
of  the  production  of  things.  This  doctrine  is  looked 
on  by  Aristotle  as  the  final  solution  of  the  problem 
which  had  always  been  the  central  one  for  Greek 
philosophy,  What  are  the  causes  of  the  world-order  1 
All  the  previous  philosophies  he  regards  as  inadequate 
attempts  to  formulate  the  answer  to  this  question 
which  is  only  given  completely  by  his  own  system. 
Hence  the  doctrine  requires  to  be  stated  with  some 
fullness.  We  may  best  approach  it  by  starting  from 
the  literal  meaning  of  the  Greek  terms  aitia,  aition, 
which  Aristotle  uses  to  convey  the  notion  of  cause. 
Aition  is  properly  an  adjective  used  substantivally, 


I 


FIEST  PHILOSOPHY.  59 

and  means  "  that  on  which  the  legal  responsibility  for 
a  given  state  of  affairs  can  be  laid."  Similarly  aitia, 
the  substantive,  means  the  "  credit "  for  good  or  bad, 
the  legal  "  responsibility,"  for  an  act.  Now  when  we 
ask,  "  what  is  responsible  for  the  fact  that  such  and 
such  a  state  of  things  now  exists?"  there  are  four 
partial  answers  which  may  be  given,  and  each  of 
these  corresponds  to  one  of  the  "causes."  A  complete 
answer  requires  the  enumeration  of  them  all  We 
may  mention  (1)  the  'matter  or  material  cause  of  the 
thing,  (2)  the  law  according  to  which  it  has  grown  or 
developed,  the  form  or  formal  cause,  (3)  the  agent 
with  whose  initial  impulse  the  development  began — 
the  "starting-point  of  the  process,"  or,  as  the  later 
Aristotelians  call  it,  the  efficient  cause,  (4)  the  com- 
pleted result  of  the  whole  process,  which  is  present  in 
the  case  of  human  manufacture  as  a  preconceived 
idea  determining  the  maker's  whole  method  of  hand- 
ling his  material,  and  in  organic  development  in 
Nature  as  implied  in  and  determining  the  successive 
stages  of  growth — the  end  ov  final  cause.  If  any  one 
of  these  had  been  different,  the  resultant  state  of 
things  would  also  have  been  different.  Hence  aU 
four  must  be  specified  in  completely  accounting  for 
it  Obvious  illustrations  can  be  given  from  artificial 
products  of  human  skill,  but  it  seems  clear  that  it 
was  rather  reflection  on  the  biological  process  of  re- 
production and  growth  which  originally  suggested 
the  analysis.  Suppose  we  ask  what  was  requisite  in 
order  that  there  should  be  now  an  oak  on  a  given 
spot.  There  must  have  been  (1)  a  germ  from  which 
the  oak  has  grown,  and  this  germ  must  have  had 
the  latent  tendencies  towards  development  which  are 
characteristic  of  oaks.  This  is  the  material  cause  of 
the  oak.    (2)  This  germ  must  have  followed  a  definite 


60  ARISTOTLE. 

law  of  growth ;  it  must  have  had  a  tendency  to  grow 
in  the  way  characteristic  of  oaks  and  to  develop  the 
structure  of  an  oak,  not  that  of  a  plane  or  an  ash. 
This  is  form  or  formal  cause.  (3)  Also  the  germ  of 
the  oak  did  not  come  from  nowhere;  it  grew  on  a 
parent  oak.  The  parent  oak  and  its  acorn-bearing 
activity  thus  constitute  the  efficient  cause  of  the 
present  oak.  (4)  And  there  must  be  a  final  stage  to 
which  the  whole  process  of  growth  is  relative,  in 
which  the  germ  or  sapling  is  no  longer  becoming  but 
is  an  adult  oak  bearing  fresh  acorns.  This  is  the  end 
of  the  process.  One  would  not  be  going  far  wrong  in 
saying  that  Aristotle's  biological  cast  of  thought  leads 
him  to  conceive  of  this  "end"  in  the  case  of  repro- 
duction as  a  sub-conscious  purpose,  just  as  the  work- 
man's thought  of  the  result  to  be  attained  by  his  action 
forms  a  conscious  directing  purpose  in  the  case  of 
manufacture.  Both  in  Nature  and  in  *'  art "  the 
"  form,"  the  *'  efficient  cause,"  and  the  "  end  "  tend  to 
coalesce.  Thus  in  Nature  "a  man  begets  a  man," 
organic  beings  give  birth  to  other  organic  beings  of 
the  same  kind,  or,  in  the  technical  language  of  the 
Aristotelian  theory  of  Causation,  the  efficient  cause 
produces,  as  the  "  end  "  of  its  action,  a  second  being 
having  the  same  "  form  "  as  itself,  though  realised  in 
different  "matter,"  and  numerically  distinct  from 
itself.  Thus  the  efficient  cause  {i.e.  the  parent)  is  a 
"form"  realised  in  matter,  and  the  "end"  is  the 
same  "  form  "  realised  in  other  matter.  So  in  "  prod- 
ucts of  art"  the  true  "source  of  the  process"  is  the 
"  form  "  the  realisation  of  which  is  the  "  end  "  or  final 
cause,  only  with  this  difference,  that  as  efficient  cause 
the  "  form  "  exists  not  in  the  material  but  by  way  of 
"  idea  "  or  "  representation  "  in  the  mind  of  the  crafts- 
man.    A  house  does  not  produce  another  house,  but 


> 


FIRST  PHILOSOPHY.  61 

the  house  as  existing  in  "  idea  "  in  the  builder's  mind 
sets  him  at  work  building,  and  so  produces  a  corre- 
sponding house  in  brick  or  stone.  Thus  the  ultimate 
opposition  is  between  the  "  cause  as  matter,"  a  passive 
and  inert  substratum  of  change  and  development  and 
the  "  formal "  cause  which,  in  the  sense  just  explained, 
is  one  with  both  the  "  efficient "  or  starting-point,  and 
the  "end"  or  goal  of  development.  It  will,  of 
course,  be  seen  that  individual  bearers  of  "forms" 
are  indispensable  in  the  theory ;  hence  the  notion  of 
activity  is  essential  to  the  causal  relation.  It  is  a 
relation  between  things,  not  between  events.  Aris- 
totle has  no  sense  of  the  word  cause  corresponding  to 
Mill's  conception  of  a  cause  as  an  event  which  is  the 
uniform  precursor  of  another  event. 

Two  more  remarks  may  be  made  in  this  connection. 
(1)  The  prominence  of  the  notion  of  "end"  gives 
Aristotle's  philosophy  a  thorough-going  "  teleological " 
character.  God  and  Nature,  he  tells  us,  do  nothing 
aimlessly.  We  should  probably  be  mistaken  if  we 
took  this  to  mean  that  "  God  and  Nature  "  act  every- 
where with  conscious  design.  The  meaning  is  rather 
that  every  natural  process  has  a  last  stage  in  which 
the  "  form "  which  was  to  begin  with  present  in  the 
agent  or  "  source  of  change "  is  fully  realised  in  the 
matter  in  which  the  agent  has  set  up  the  process  of 
change.  The  normal  thing  is  e.g.  for  animals  to  re- 
produce "  their  kind " ;  if  the  reproduction  is  im- 
perfect or  distorted,  as  in  monstrous  births,  this  is  an 
exception  due  to  the  occasional  presence  in  "  matter  " 
of  imperfections  which  hinder  the  course  of  develop- 
ment, and  must  be  regarded  as  "contrary  to  the 
normal  course  of  Nature."  So  hybrid  reproduction 
is  exceptional  and  "against  Nature,"  and  this  is 
shown  by  the  sterility  of  hybrids,   a  sort  of  lesser 


62  AEISTOTLE.  ^^M 

monstrosity.  Even  females,  being  *'  arrested  deveio^^^ 
ments,"  are  a  sort  of  still  minor  deviation  from  prin- 
ciple. (2)  It  may  just  be  mentioned  that  Aristotle 
has  a  classification  of  efficient  causes  under  the  three 
heads  of  Nature,  Intelligence  (or  Man),  and  Chance. 
The  difference  between  Nature  and  Man  or  Intelli- 
gence as  efficient  causes  has  already  been  illustrated. 
It  is  that  in  causation  by  Nature,  such  as  sexual  re- 
production, or  the  assimilation  of  nutriment,  or  the 
conversion  of  one  element  into  another  in  which 
Aristotle  believed,  the  form  which  is  superinduced  on 
the  matter  by  the  agent  already  exists  in  the  agent 
itself  as  its  form.  The  oak  springs  from  a  parent 
oak,  the  conversion  of  nutriment  into  organic  tissue 
is  due  to  the  agency  of  already  existing  organic  tissue. 
In  the  case  of  human  intelligence  or  art,  the  "  form  " 
to  be  superinduced  exists  in  the  agent  not  as  his 
characteristic  form,  but  by  way  of  representation,  as 
a  contemplated  design.  The  man  who  builds  a  house 
is  not  himself  a  house ;  the  form  chara.cteristic  of  a 
house  is  very  different  from  that  characteristic  of  a 
man,  but  it  is  present  in  contemplation  to  the  builder 
before  it  is  embodied  in  the  actual  house.  A  word 
may  be  added  about  the  third  sort  of  efficient  causality, 
causation  by  chance.  This  is  confined  to  cases  which 
are  exceptions  from  the  general  course  of  Nature, 
remarkable  coincidences.  It  is  what  we  may  call 
"simulated  purposiveness."  When  something  in 
human  affairs  happens  in  a  way  which  subserves  the 
achievement  of  a  result  but  was  not  really  brought 
about  by  any  intention  to  secure  the  result,  we  speak 
of  it  as  a  remarkable  coincidence.  Thus  it  would ,  be 
a  coincidence  if  a  man  should  be  held  to  ransom  by 
brigands  and  his  best  friend  should,  without  knowing 
anything  of  the  matter,  turn  up  on  the  spot  with  the 


FIEST  PHILOSOPHY.  63 

means  of  ransoming  him.  The  events  could  not  have 
happened  more  opportunely  if  they  had  been  planned, 
and  yet  they  were  not  planned  but  merely  fell  out 
so;  and  since  such  a  combination  of  circumstances 
simulating  design  is  unusual,  it  is  not  proper  to  say 
that  the  events  happened  "in  the  course  of  Nature." 
We  therefore  say  it  happened  by  chance.  This 
doctrine  of  chance  has  its  significance  for  mediaeval 
Ethics.  In  an  age  when  the  Protestant  superstition 
that  worldly  success  is  proof  of  nearness  to  God  had 
not  yet  been  invented,  the  want  of  correspondence 
between  men's  "deserts"  and  their  prosperity  was 
accounted  for  by  the  view  that  the  distribution  of 
worldly  goods  is,  as  a  rule,  the  work  of  Fortune  or 
Chance  in  the  Aristotelian  sense ;  that  is,  it  is  due  to 
special  coincidences  which  may  look  like  deliberate 
design  but  are  not  really  so.  (See  the  elaborate 
exposition  of  this  in  Dante,  Inferno^  vii  67-97.) 

Motion. — We  have  seen  that  causation,  natural 
or  artificial,  requires  the  production  in  a  certain 
"matter"  of  a  certain  "form  "  under  the  influence  of 
a  certain  "agent."  What  is  the  character  of  the 
process  set  up  by  the  agent  in  the  matter  and  culmi- 
nating in  the  appearance  of  the  form^  Aristotle 
answers  that  it  is  Motion  (kii/iesis).  The  effect  of  the 
agent  on  the  matter  is  to  set  up  in  it  a  motion  which 
ends  in  its  assuming  a  definite  form.  The  important 
point  to  be  noted  here  is  that  Aristotle  regards  this 
motion  as  falling  wholly  within  the  matter  which  is 
to  assume  the  form.  It  is  not  necessary  that  the 
agent  should  itself  be  in  motion,  but  only  that  it 
should  induce  motion  in  something  else.  Thus  in  all 
cases  of  intentional  action  the  ultimate  efficient  cause 
is  the  "idea  of  the  result  to  be  attained,"  but  this 
idea  does  not  move  about.     By  its  presence  to  the 


64  AKISTOTLE. 

mind  it  sets  something  else  (the  members  of  the  body) 
moving.  This  conception  of  an  efficient  cause  which, 
not  moving  itself,  by  its  mere  presence  induces  move- 
ment in  that  to  which  it  is  present,  is  of  the  highest 
importance  in  Aristotle's  theology.  Of  course  it 
follows  that  since  the  motion  by  which  the  transition 
from  potentiality  to  actuality  is  achieved  falls  wholly 
within  the  matter  acted  upon,  Aristotle  is  not  troubled 
with  any  of  the  questions  as  to  the  way  in  which 
motion  can  be  transferred  from  one  body  to  another 
which  were  so  much  agitated  in  the  early  days  of  the 
modem  mechanical  interpretation  of  natural  pro- 
cesses. Aristotle's  way  of  conceiving  Nature  is 
'thoroughly  non-mechanical,  and  approximates  to 
what  would  now  be  called  the  ascription  of  vital  or 
quasi-vital  characteristics  to  the  inorganic.  As,  in 
the  causality  of  "art"  the  mere  presence  of  the 
"form"  to  be  embodied  in  a  given  material  to  the 
mind  of  the  craftsman  brings  about  and  directs  the 
process  of  manufacture,  so  in  some  analogous  fashion 
the  presence  of  an  efficient  cause  in  Nature  to  that 
on  which  it  works  is  thought  of  as  itself  constituting 
the  "efficiency"  of  the  cause.  As  Lotze  phrases  it, 
things  "take  note  of"  one  another's  compresence  in 
the  universe,  or  we  might  say  the  efficient  cause  and 
that  on  which  it  exercises  its  efficiency  are  en  rapport. 
''Matter"  is  sensitive  to  the  presence  of  the  "effi- 
cient cause,"  and  in  response  to  this  sensitivity,  puts 
forth  successive  determinations,  expands  its  latent 
tendencies  on  definite  lines. 

The  name  "  motion  "  has  a  wider  sense  for  Aristotle 
than  it  has  for  ourselves.  He  includes  under  the 
one  common  name  all  the  processes  by  which  things 
come  to  be  what  they  are  or  cease  to  be  what  they  have 
been.     Thus  he  distinguishes  the  following  varieties  of 


FIRST  PHILOSOPHY.  65 

"  motion  "  :  generation  (the  coming  of  an  individual 
thing  into  being),  with  its  opposite  decay  or  comqytion 
(the  passing  of  a  thing  out  of  being),  alteration  (change 
of  quality  in  a  thing),  augmentation  and  diminution 
(change  in  the  m^ugnitude  of  a  thing),  motion  through 
space  (of  which  latter  he  recognises  two  sub-species, 
rectilinear  transference  and  rotation  in  a  circular  orbit 
about  an  axis).  It  is  this  last  variety,  motion  through 
space,  which  is  the  most  fundamental  of  aD,  since  its 
occurrence  is  involved  in  that  of  any  of  the  other 
types  of  process  mentioned,  though  Aristotle  does 
not  hold  the  thorough-going  mechanical  view  that  the 
other  processes  are  only  apparent,  and  that,  as  we 
might  put  it,  qualitative  change  is  a  mere  disguise 
which  mechanical  motion  wears  for  our  senses. 

The  Eternity  of  Motion. — Certain  very  important 
consequences  follow  from  the  conception  of  efficient 
causation  which  we  have  been  describing.  Aristotle 
has  no  sympathy  with  the  "  evolutionist "  views  which 
had  been  favoured  by  some  of  his  predecessors. 
According  to  his  theory  of  organic  generation,  "  it 
takes  a  man  to  beget  a  man  "  ;  where  there  is  a  baby, 
there  must  have  been  a  father.  Biological  kinds 
representing  real  clefts  in  Nature,  the  process  of  the 
production  of  a  young  generation  by  an  already  adult 
generation  must  be  thought  of  as  without  beginning 
and  without  end.  There  can  be  no  natural  "  evolu- 
tion "  of  animals  of  one  species  from  individuals  of  a 
diflferent  kind.  Nor  does  it  occur  to  Aristotle  to  take 
into  account  the  possibility  of  "  Creationism,"  the 
sudden  coming  into  being  of  a  fully  fledged  first 
generation  at  a  stroke.  This  possibility  is  excluded 
by  the  doctrine  that  the  "  matter  "  of  a  thing  must 
exist  beforehand  as  an  indispensable  condition  of  the 
production  of  that  thing.     Every  baby,  as  we  said, 

(1.994)  5 


66  AKISTOTLE. 

must  have  had  a  father,  but-  that  father  must  also 
have  been  a  baby  before  he  was  a  full-grown  man. 
Hence  the  perpetuation  of  unchanging  species  must  be 
without  beginning  and  without  end.  And  it  is  implied 
that  all  the  various  processes,  within  and  without  the 
organism,  apart  from  which  its  life  could  not  be  kept  up, 
must  be  equally  without  beginning  and  without  end. 
The  "  cosmos,"  or  orderly  world  of  natural  processes,  is 
strictly  "  eternal "  ;  "  motion  "  is  everlasting  and  con- 
tinuous, or  unbroken.  Even  the  great  Christian  theo- 
logians who  built  upon  Aristotle  could  not  absolutely 
break  with  him  on  this  point.  St.  Thomas,  though 
obliged  to  admit  that  the  world  was  actually  created  a 
few  thousand  years  before  his  own  time,  maintains  that 
this  can  only  be  known  to  be  true  from  revelation, 
philosophically  it  is  equally  tenable  that  the  world 
should  have  been  "  created  from  all  eternity."  And 
it  is  the  general  doctrine  of  scholasticism  that  the  ex- 
pression "creation"  only  denotes  the  absolute  de- 
pendence of  the  world  on  God  for  its  being.  When 
we  say  "  God  created  the  world  out  of  nothing,"  we 
mean  that  He  did  not  make  it  out  of  pre-existing 
matter,  that  it  depends  for  its  being  on  Him  only ; 
the  expression  is  purely  negative  in  its  import. 

God. — With  the  doctrine  of  the  eternity  of  the 
world  and  the  processes  which  make  up  its  life  we 
come  close  to  the  culminating  theory  of  Aristotelian 
First  Philosophy,  its  doctrine  of  God,  as  the  eternal, 
unchanging  source  of  all  change,  movement,  and 
process.  All  motion  is  a  process  within  matter  by 
which  the  forms  latent  in  it  are  brought  into  actual 
manifestation.  And  the  process  only  takes  place  in 
the  presence  of  an  adequate  efficient  cause  or  source 
of  motion.  Hence  the  eternity  of  natural  processes 
involves  the  existence  of  one  or  more  eternal  sources 


FIRST  PHILOSOPHY.  67 

of  motion.  For,  if  we  do  not  admit  the  existence  of 
an  unoriginated  and  ever-present  source  or  sources  of 
motion,  our  only  alternative  is  to  hold  that  the  world- 
process  is  due  to  a  series  of  sources  of  motion  existing 
successively.  But  such  a  view  would  leave  the  unity 
and  unbroken  continuity  of  the  world-process  un- 
accounted for.  It  would  give  us  a  succession  of 
processes,  temporally  contiguous,  not  one  unbroken 
process.  Hence  we  argue  from  the  continuity  of 
motion  to  its  dependence  on  a  source  or  sources  which 
are  permanent  and  present  throughout  the  whole  ever- 
lasting world-process.  And  when  we  come  to  the 
question  whether  there  is  only  one  such  ultimate 
source  of  movement  for  the  whole  universe,  or  several, 
Aristotle's  answer  is  that  the  supreme  "Unmoved 
Mover  "  is  one.  One  is  enough  for  the  purpose,  and 
the  law  of  parsimony  forbids  us  to  assume  the  super- 
fluous. This  then  is  the  Aristotelian  conception  of 
God  and  God's  relation  to  the  world.  God  is  the  one 
supreme  unchanging  being  to  whose  presence  the  world 
responds  with  the  whole  process  of  cosmic  development, 
the  ultimate  educer  of  the  series  of  "  forms  "  latent  in 
the  "  matter  "  of  the  world  into  actual  manifestation. 
Standing,  as  He  does,  outside  the  whole  process  which 
by  His  mere  presence  He  initiates  in  Nature,  He  is 
not  Himself  a  composite  of  "  form  "  and  "  matter,"  as 
the  products  of  development  are.  He  is  a  pure 
individual  "  form  "  or  "  actuality,"  with  no  history  of 
gradual  development  behind  it.  Thus  He  is  a  purely 
immaterial  being,  indispensable  to  the  world's  exist- 
ence, but  transcending  it  and  standing  outside  it 
How  His  presence  inspires  the  world  to  move  Aristotle 
tries  to  explain  by  the  metaphor  of  appetition.  Just 
is  the  good  I  desire  and  conceive,  without  itself 
"moving"  "moves"  my  appetition,   so   God   moves 


68  ARISTOTLE. 

the  universe  by  being  its  good.  This  directly  brings 
about  a  uniform  unbroken  rotation  of  the  whole 
universe  round  its  axis  (in  fact,  the  alternation  of  day 
and  night).  And  since  this  rotation  is  communicated 
from  the  outermost  "  sphere  "  of  heaven  to  all  the 
lesser  "  spheres "  between  it  and  the  immovable 
centre,  the  effects  of  God's  presence  are  felt  uni- 
versally. At  the  same  time,  we  must  note  that 
though  God  is  the  supreme  Mover  of  the  Universe, 
He  is  not  regarded  by  Aristotle  as  its  Creator,  even  in 
the  sense  in  which  creation  can  be  reconciled  with  the 
eternity  of  the  world.  For  the  effect  of  God's  presence 
is  simply  to  lead  to  the  development  of  "  form  "  in  an 
already  existing  "  matter."  Without  God  there  could 
be  no  "  form  "  or  order  in  things,  not  even  as  much  as 
is  implied  in  the  differentiation  of  matter  into  the 
four  "elements,"  yet  "primary  matter"  is  no  less 
than  God  a  precondition  of  all  that  happens. 

It  is  characteristic  of  Aristotle  that  his  God  is  as 
far  from  discharging  the  functions  of  a  Providence  as 
He  is  from  being  a  Creator.  His  "  activity  "  is  not, 
as  Plato  had  made  it,  that  of  the  great  "  Shepherd  of 
the  sheep."  As  far  as  the  world  is  concerned,  God's 
only  function  is  to  be  there  to  move  its  appetition.  For 
the  rest,  the  unbroken  activity  of  His  life  is  directed 
wholly  inward.  Aristotle  expressly  calls  it  an  "  activity 
of  immobility."  More  precisely,  he  tells  us,  it  is  activ- 
ity of  thought,  exercised  unbrokenly  and  everlastingly 
upon  the  only  object  adequate  to  exercise  God's  contem- 
plation. Himself.  His  life  is  one  of  everlasting  self- 
contemplation  or  "  thinking  of  thought  itself."  Like  all 
unimpeded  exercise  of  activity,  it  is  attended  by  pleas- 
ure, and  as  the  activity  is  continuous,  so  the  pleasure  of 
it  is  continuous  too.  At  our  best,  when  we  give  our- 
selves up  to  the  pure  contemplative  activity  of  scientific 


FIEST  PHILOSOPHY.  69 

thought  or  aesthetic  appreciation,  we  enter  for  a  while 
into  this  divine  life  and  share  the  happiness  of  God. 
But  that  is  a  theme  for  our  chapter  on  the  Ethics. 

It  is  a  far  cry  from  this  conception  of  a  God  un- 
troubled by  care  for  a  world  to  which  He  is  only 
related  as  the  object  of  its  aspiration  to  the  God  who 
cares  even  for  the  fall  of  the  sparrow  and  of  whom  it 
is  written,  Sic  Deus  dilexU  mundutn^  but  it  was  the 
standing  task  of  the  philosophical  theologians  of  the 
Middle  Ages  to  fuse  the  two  conceptions.  Plato's 
God,  who,  if  not  quite  the  Creator,  is  the  "  Father 
and  Fashioner "  of  us  all,  and  keeps  providential 
watch  over  the  world  He  has  fashioned,  would  have 
lent  Himself  better  to  their  purposes,  but  Plato  was 
held  by  the  mediaeval  church  to  have  denied  the  re- 
surrection of  the  body.*  The  combination  of  Aris- 
totle's Theism  with  the  Theism  of  early  Christianity 
was  effected  by  exquisitely  subtle  logical  devices,  but 
even  in  St.  Thomas  one  cannot  help  seeing  the  seams. 

Kor  can  one  help  seeing  in  Aristotle's  own  doctrine 
the  usual  want  of  coherence  between  an  initial  anti- 
Platonic  bias  and  a  final  reversion  to  the  very  Platonic 
positions  Aristotle  is  fond  of  impugning.  We  are 
told  at  the  outset  that  the  Platonic  "  separate  forms  " 
are  empty  names,  and  that  the  real  individual  thing  is 
always  a  composite  of  matter  and  a  form  which  only 
exists  "  in  matter."  We  find  in  the  end  that  the  source 
of  the  whole  process  by  which  "  matter  "  becomes  im- 
bued with  "  form  "  is  a  being  which  is  *'  pure ''  form  and 
stands  outside  the  whole  development  which  its  presence 
sets  up.  And  the  issue  of  Aristotle's  warning  against 
"  poetic  metaphors "  is  the  doctrine  that  God  moves 
the  world  by  being  "the  object  of  the  world's  desire." 

*  Because  in  the  Pkaedo  he  makes  Socrates  speak  of  the 
"saints  "  as  living  "wholly  freed  from  the  body." 


CHAPTER  lY 

PHYSICS 

There  is  no  part  of  Aristotle's  system  which  has  been 
more  carefully  thought  out  than  his  Physics ;  at  the 
same  time  it  is  almost  wholly  on  account  of  his 
physical  doctrines  that  his  long  ascendancy  over 
thought  is  so  much  to  be  regretted.  Aristotle's 
qualifications  as  a  man  of  science  have  been  much 
overrated.  In  one  department,  that  of  descriptive 
natural  history,  he  shows  himself  a  master  of  minute 
and  careful  observation  who  could  obtain  unqualified 
praise  from  so  great  a  naturalist  as  Darwin.  But  in 
Astronomy  and  Physics  proper  his  inferiority  in 
mathematical  thinking  and  his  dislike  for  mechanical 
ways  of  explaining  facts  put  him  at  a  great  dis- 
advantage, as  compared  with  Plato  and  Plato's 
Pythagorean  friends.  Thus  his  authority  was  for 
centuries  one  of  the  chief  influences  which  prevented 
the  development  of  Astronomy  on  right  lines.  Plato 
had  himself  both  taught  the  mobility  of  the  earth  and 
denied  correctly  that  the  earth  is  at  the  centre  of  the 
universe,  and  the  "Copernican"  hypothesis  in  As- 
tronomy probably  originated  in  the  Academy.  Aris- 
totle, however,  insists  on  the  central  position  of  the 
earth,  and  violently  attacks  Plato  for  believing  in  its 
motion.     It  is  equally  serious  that  he  insists  on  treat- 


PHYSICS.  71 

ing  the  so-called  "four  elements"  as  ultimately  un- 
analysable forms  of  matter,  though  Plato  had  not  only 
observed  that  so  far  from  being  the  ABC  {stoicheia 
or  eleinenta^  literally,  letters  of  the  alphabet)  of  Nature 
they  do  not  deserve  to  be  called  even  "  syllables,"  but 
had  also  definitely  put  forward  the  view  that  it  is  the 
geometrical  structure  of  the  "corpuscles"  of  body 
upon  which  sensible  qualities  depend.*  It  is  on  this 
doctrine,  of  course,  that  all  mathematical  physics 
rests.  Aristotle  reverts  to  the  older  theory  that  the 
differences  between  one  "element"  and  another  are 
qualitative  differences  of  a  sensible  kind.  Even  in 
the  biological  sciences  Aristotle  shows  an  unfortunate 
proneness  to  disregard  established  fact  when  it  con- 
flicts with  the  theories  for  which  he  has  a  personal 
liking.  Thus,  though  the  importance  of  the  brain  as 
the  central  organ  of  the  sensori-motor  system  had 
been  discovered  in  the  late  sixth  or  early  fifth  century 
by  the  physician  Alcmaeon  of  Crotona,  and  taught  by 
the  great  Hippocrates  in  the  fifth  and  by  Plato  in 
the  fourth  century,  Aristotle's  prejudices  in  favour  of 
the  doctrines  of  a  different  school  of  biologists  led 
him  to  revert  to  the  view  that  it  is  the  heart  which 
is  the  centre  of  what  we  now  call  the  "nervous 
system."  It  is  mainly  on  account  of  these  reactionary 
scientific  views  that  he  was  attacked  in  the  early 
seventeenth  century  by  writers  like  our  own  Francis 
Bacon,  who  found  in  veneration  for  Aristotle  one  of 
the  chief  hindrances  to  the  free  development  of 
natural  science.  The  same  complaints  had  been 
made  long  before  by  critics  belonging  to  the  Platonic 
Academy.  It  is  a  Platonist  of  the  time  of  Marcus 
Aurelius   who   sums   up   a   vigorous   attack  on   the 

*  Plato  does  not  even  claim  to  be  the  author  of  the  doctrine, 
«'hich  he  ascribes  to  the  Pythagoreans  of  the  age  of  Socrates. 


72  ARISTOTLE. 

Aristotelian  astronomy  by  the  remark  that  Aristotle 
never  understood  that  the  true  task  of  the  physicist 
is  not  to  prescribe  laws  to  Nature,  but  to  learn  from 
observation  of  the  facts  what  the  laws  followed  by 
Nature  are. 

In  determining  the  scope  of  Physics,  we  have  to 
begin  by  considering  what  is  the  special  characteristic 
of  things  produced  by  Nature  as  contrasted  with  those 
produced  by  "art."  The  obvious  distinction,  inti- 
mated by  the  very  etymology  of  the  word  "  Nature  " 
(physisy  connected  with  phyesthai,  to  grow,  to  be 
born,  as  natura  is  with  nasci),  is  that  "  what  is  by 
Nature"  is  bom  and  grows,  whereas  what  is  as  a 
result  of  artifice  is  made.  The  "  natural "  may  thus 
be  said  to  consist  of  living  bodies  and  of  their  con- 
stituent parts.  Hence  inorganic  matter  also  is 
included  in  "Nature,"  on  the  ground  that  living 
tissue  can  be  analysed  back  into  compounds  of  the 
"elements."  Now  things  which  are  alive  and  grow 
are  distinguished  from  things  which  are  made  by  "  a 
source  of  motion  and  quiescence  within  themselves  "  ; 
all  of  them  exhibit  motions,  changes  of  quality,  pro- 
cesses of  growth  and  decline  which  are  initiated  from 
within.  Hence  Nature  may  be  defined  as  the  totality 
of  things  which  have  a  source  of  motion  internal  to 
themselves  and  of  the  constituent  parts  of  such  things. 
Nature  then  comprises  all  beings  capable  of  spon- 
taneous change.  Whatever  either  does  not  change 
at  all,  or  only  changes  in  consequence  of  external 
influences,  is  excluded  from  Nature.* 

Thus  the  fundamental  fact  everywhere  present  in 
Nature   is   "change,"  "process,"    "motion."      Since 


process, 


*  Even  the  "element8,"accordingto  Aristotle,  exhibit  "spon- 
taneity." Earth  e.g.  spontwneoualy  falls  dowmoards,  fire  and  air 
rise  uptoards. 


PHYSICS.  73 

motion  in  the  literal  sense  of  change  of  position  is 
involved  as  a  condition  of  every  such  process,  and 
such  motion  requires  space  through  which  to  move 
and  time  to  move  in,  the  doctrine  of  space  and  time 
will  also  form  part  of  Physics.  Hence  a  great  part 
of  Aristotle's  special  lectures  on  Physics  is  occupied 
with  discussion  of  the  nature  of  space  and  time,  and 
of  the  continuity  which  we  must  ascribe  to  them  if 
the  "  continuous  motion  "  on  which  the  unbroken  life 
of  the  universe  depends  is  to  be  real.  Aristotle 
knows  nothing  of  the  modem  questions  whether 
space  and  time  are  "real"  or  only  "phenomenal," 
whether  they  are  "  objective  "  or  "  subjective."  Just 
as  he  simply  assumes  that  bodies  are  things  that 
really  exist,  whether  we  happen  to  perceive  them  or 
not,  so  he  assumes  that  the  space  and  time  in  which 
they  move  are  real  features  of  a  world  that  does  not 
depend  for  its  existence  on  our  perceiving  it. 

His  treatment  of  space  is  singularly  naif.  He 
conceives  it  as  a  sort  of  vessel,  into  which  you  can 
pour  different  liquids.  Just  as  the  same  pot  may 
hold  first  wine  and  then  water,  so,  if  you  can  say, 
"there  was  water  here,  but  now  there  is  air  here," 
this  implies  the  existence  of  a  receptacle  which  once 
held  the  water,  but  now  holds  the  air.  Hence  a  jug 
or  pot  may  be  called  a  "place  that  can  be  carried 
about,"  and  space  or  place  may  be  called  "an  immov- 
able vessel."  Hence  the  "place"  of  a  thing  may  be 
defined  as  the  boundary,  or  inner  surface,  of  the 
body  which  immediately  surrounds  the  thing.  It 
follows  from  this  that  there  can  be  no  empty  space. 
In  the  last  resort,  "absolute  space"  is  the  actual 
surface  of  the  outermost  "heaven"  which  contains 
everything  else  in  itself  but  is  not  contained  in  any 
remoter  body.     Thus  all  things  whatever  are   "in" 


74  ARISTOTLE. 

this  "heaven."  But  it  is  not  itself  "in"  anything 
else.  In  accord  with  the  standing  Greek  identifica- 
tion of  determinate  character  with  limitation,  Aris- 
totle holds  that  this  outermost  heaven  must  be  at  a 
limited  distance  from  us.  Actual  space  is  thus  finite 
in  the  sense  that  the  volume  of  the  universe  could  be 
expressed  as  a  finite  number  of  cubic  miles  or  yards, 
though,  since  it  must  be  "  continuous,"  it  is  infinitely 
divisible.  However  often  you  subdivide  a  length,  an 
area,  or  a  volume,  you  will  always  be  dividing  it  into 
lesser  lengths,  etc.,  which  can  once  more  be  divided. 
You  will  never  by  division  come  to  "points,"  i.e. 
mere  positions  without  magnitude  of  divisibility.  i 
The  treatment  of  time  is  more  thoughtful.  Time  ifl  3 
inseparably  connected  with  movement  or  change.  We 
only  perceive  that  time  has  elapsed  when  we  perceive 
that  change  has  occurred.  But  time  is  not  the  same 
as  change.  For  change  is  of  difierent  and  incom- 
mensurate kinds,  change  of  place,  change  of  colour, 
etc. ;  but  to  take  up  time  is  common  to  all  these 
forms  of  process.  And  time  is  not  the  same  as 
motion.  For  there  are  difierent  rates  of  speed,  but 
the  very  fact  that  we  can  compare  these  different 
velocities  implies  that  there  are  not  different  velocities 
of  time.  Time  then  is  that  in  terms  of  which  we 
measure  motion,  "the  number  of  motion  in  respect  of 
before  and  after,"  i.e.  it  is  that  by  which  we  estimate 
the  duration  of  processes.  Thus  e.g.  when  we  speak 
of  two  minutes,  two  days,  two  months  as  required  for 
a  certain  process  to  be  completed,  we  are  counting 
something.  This  something  is  time.  It  does  not 
seem  to  occur  to  Aristotle  that  this  definition  implies 
that  there  are  indivisible  bits  of  time,  though  he 
quite  correctly  states  the  incompatible  proposition 
that   time   is    "made   up   of   successive    nows"   i.e. 


PHYSICS.  75 

moments  which  have  no  duration  at  all,  and  can  no 
more  be  counted  than  the  points  on  a  straight  line. 
He  recognises  of  course  that  the  "continuity"  of 
motion  implies  that  of  time  as  well  as  of  space. 
Since,  however,  *'  continuity  "  in  his  language  means 
the  same  thing  as  indefinite  divisibility,  it  ought  not 
to  be  possible  for  him  to  regard  time  as  "  made  up  of 
nows "  ',  time,  like  linear  extension,  ought  for  him  to 
be  a  "  length  of  "  something. 

The  Continuous  Motion  and  the  **  Spheres." — The 
continuous  world-process  depends  upon  a  continuous 
movement  set  up  in  the  universe  as  a  whole  by  the 
presence  of  an  everlasting  and  unchangeable  "First 
Mover,"  God.  From  the  self-sameness  of  Grod,  it 
follows  that  this  most  universal  of  movements  must 
be  absolutely  uniform.  Of  what  precise  kind  can 
such  a  movement  be  1  As  the  source  of  the  move- 
ment is  one,  and  the  object  moved  is  also  one — viz. 
the  compass  of  the  "heaven,"  the  movement  of  the 
primum  mobile  or  "first  moved" — the  object  im- 
mediately stimulated  to  motion  by  God's  presence  to 
it,  must  be  mechanically  simple.  Now  Aristotle, 
mistakenly,  held  that  there  are  two  forms  of  move- 
ment which  are  simple  and  unanalysable,  motion 
of  translation  along  a  straight  line,  and  motion  of 
rotation  round  an  axis.  He  is  at  pains  to  argue  that 
rectilinear  motion,  which  we  easily  discover  to  be 
that  characteristic  of  bodies  near  the  earth's  surface 
when  left  to  themselves,  cannot  be  the  kind  of  move- 
ment which  belongs  to  the  "heaven"  as  a  whole. 
For  continuous  rectilinear  movement  in  the  same 
direction  could  not  go  on  for  ever  on  his  assumption 
that  there  is  no  space  outside  the  "heaven,"  which 
is  itself  at  a  finite  distance  from  us.  And  motion 
to  and  fro  would  not  be  unbroken,  since  Aristotle 


76  AEISTOTLE. 

argues  that  every  time  a  moving  body  reached  the 
end  of  its  path,  and  the  sense  of  its  movement  was 
reversed,  it  would  be  for  two  consecutive  moments  in 
the  same  place,  and  therefore  at  rest.  Reversal  of 
sense  would  imply  a  discontinuity.  Hence  he  decides 
that  the  primary  unbroken  movement  must  be  the 
rotation  of  the  "first  moved" — that  is,  the  heaven 
containing  the  fixed  stars — round  its  axis.  This  is 
the  only  movement  which  could  go  on  for  ever  at  a 
uniform  rate  and  in  the  same  sense.  Starting  with 
the  conviction  that  the  earth  is  at  rest  in  the  centre 
of  the  universe,  he  inevitably  accounts  for  the  alter- 
nation of  day  and  night  as  the  effect  of  such  a 
revolution  of  the  whole  universe  round  an  axis  pass- 
ing through  the  centre  of  the  earth.  The  universe  is 
thus  thought  of  as  bounded  by  a  spherical  surface,  on 
the  concave  side  of  which  are  the  fixed  stars,  which 
are  therefore  one  and  all  at  the  same  distance  from 
us.  This  sphere,  under  the  immediate  influence  of 
God,  revolves  on  its  axis  once  in  twenty-four  hours, 
and  this  period  of  revolution  is  absolutely  uniform. 
Next  the  apparently  irregular  paths  of  the  "  planets  " 
known  to  Aristotle  (i.e.  the  moon,  Mercury,  Venus, 
the  sun.  Mars,  Jupiter,  Saturn)  are  resolved  into  com- 
binations of  similar  uniform  rotations,  each  planet 
having  as  many  "  spheres "  assigned  to  it  as  are 
requisite  for  the  analysis  of  its  apparent  path  into 
perfectly  circular  elementary  motions.  Altogether 
Aristotle  holds  that  fifty-four  such  rotating  spheres 
are  required  over  and  above  the  "  first  moved  "  itself, 
whose  rotation  is,  of  course,  communicated  to  all  the 
lesser  "  spheres  "  included  within  it.  As  in  the  case 
of  the  "  first  moved,"  the  uniform  unceasing  rotation 
of  each  "  sphere  "  is  explained  by  the  influence  on  it 
of  an  unchanging  immaterial  "  form,"  which  is  to  its 


PHYSICS.  77 

own  "  sphere  "  what  God  is  to  the  universe  as  a  whole. 
In  the  Aristotelianism  of  the  mediaeval  Church  these 
pure  forms  or  intelligences  which  originate  the  move- 
ments of  the  various  planetary  spheres  are  naturally 
identified  with  angels.  It  is  e.g.  to  the  angelic  in- 
telligences that  "  move  "  the  heaven  of  Venus,  which 
comes  third  in  order  counting  outward  from  the 
earth,  that  Dante  addresses  his  famous  Canzone, 
Voi  cK  intendendo  il  terzo  del  movete.  The  mediaeval 
astronomy,  however,  differs  in  two  important  respects 
from  that  of  Aristotle  himself.  (1)  The  number  of 
"  spheres  "  is  different.  Increasing  knowledge  of  the 
complexity  of  the  paths  of  the  planets  showed  that  if 
their  paths  are  to  be  analysed  into  combinations  of 
circular  motions,  fifty-four  such  rotations  must  be  an 
altogether  inadequate  number.  Aristotle's  method  of 
analysis  of  the  heavenly  movements  was  therefore 
combined  with  either  or  both  of  two  others  originated 
by  pure  astronomers  who  sat  loose  to  metaphysics. 
One  of  these  methods  was  to  account  for  a  planet's 
path  by  the  introduction  of  epicycles.  The  planet 
was  thought  of  not  as  fixed  at  a  given  point  on  its 
principal  sphere,  but  as  situated  on  the  circumference 
of  a  lesser  sphere  which  has  its  centre  at  a  fixed  point 
of  the  principal  sphere  and  rotates  around  an  axis 
passing  through  this  centre.  If  need  were,  this  type 
of  hypothesis  could  be  further  complicated  by  im- 
agining any  number  of  such  epicycles  within  epicycles. 
The  other  method  was  the  employment  of  "  eccentrics," 
i.e.  circular  movements  which  are  described  not  about 
the  common  centre  of  the  earth  and  the  universe,  but 
about  some  point  in  its  neighbourhood.  By  com- 
binations of  epicycles  and  eccentrics  the  mediaeval 
astronomers  contrived  to  reduce  the  number  of 
principal  spheres  to  one  for  each  planet,  the  arrange- 


78  ARISTOTLE. 

ment  we  find  in  Dante.  (2)  Also  real  or  supposed 
astronomical  perturbations  unknown  to  Aristotle  led 
some  mediaeval  theorists  to  follow  the  scheme  devised 
by  Alphonso  the  Wise  of  Castile,  in  which  further 
spheres  are  inserted  between  that  of  Saturn,  the 
outermost  planet,  and  the  "  first  moved."  In  Dante, 
we  have,  excluding  the  "empyrean"  or  immovable 
heaven  where  God  and  the  blessed  are,  nine  "  spheres," 
one  for  each  of  the  planets,  one  for  the  fixed  stars,  and 
one  for  the  "first  moved,"  which  is  now  distinguished 
from  the  heaven  of  the  stars.  In  Milton,  who  adopts 
the  "Alphonsine"  scheme,  we  have  further  a  sphere 
called  the  "  second  movable  "  or  "  crystalline  "  intro- 
duced between  the  heaven  of  the  fixed  stars  and  the 
"first  moved,"  to  account  for  the  imaginary  pheno- 
menon of  "trepidation."*  In  reading  Dante,  Shake- 
speare, and  Milton,  we  have  always  to  remember  that 
none  of  these  reproduces  the  Aristotelian  doctrine  of 
the  "  spheres "  accurately ;  their  astronomy  is  an 
amalgam  of  Aristotle,  Ptolemy,  and  Hipparchus. 

So  far,  the  doctrine  of  the  fifty-five  "spheres" 
might  be  no  more  than  a  legitimate  mathematical 
fiction,  a  convenient  device  for  analysing  the  com- 
plicated apparent  movements  of  the  heavenly  bodies 
into  circular  components.  This  was  originally  the 
part  played  by  "  spheres "  in  ancient  astronomical 
theory,  and  it  is  worth  while  to  be  quite  clear  about 
the  fact,  as  there  is  a  mistaken  impression  widely 
current  to-day  that  Aristotle's  astronomy  is  typical 
of  Greek  views  in  general.  The  truth  is  that  it  is 
peculiar  to  himself.  The  origin  of  the  theory  was 
Academic.  Plato  proposed  to  the  Academy  as  a 
♦  Paradise  Lost,  iii.  481. 

"  They  pass  the  planets  seven,  and  pass  the  fixed, 
And  that  crystalline  sphere  whose  balance  weighs 
The  trepidation  talked,  and  that  first  moved." 


I 


PHYSICS.  79 

subject  of  inquiry,  to  devise  such  a  mathematical 
analysis  of  astronomical  motions  as  will  best  ''save 
the  appearances,"  i.e.  will  most  simply  account  for  the 
apparent  paths  of  the  planets.  The  analysis  of  these 
paths  into  resultants  of  several  rotations  was  offered 
as  a  solution  by  the  astronomer  Eudoxus  of  Cnidus. 
So  far,  the  "  spheres,"  then,  were  a  mere  kinematical 
hypothesis.  What  Aristotle  did,  and  it  is  perhaps 
the  most  retrograde  step  ever  taken  in  the  history 
of  a  science,  was  to  convert  the  mathematical  hypo- 
thesis into  physical  fact.  The  "spheres"  become 
with  him  real  bodies,  and  as  none  of  the  bodies  we 
are  familiar  with  exhibit  any  tendency  to  rotate  in 
circles  when  left  to  themselves,  Aristotle  was  forced 
to  introduce  into  Physics  the  disastrous  theory,  which 
it  was  a  great  part  of  Galileo's  life-work  to  destroy, 
that  the  stuff  of  which  the  spheres  are  made  is  a 
"fifth  body,"  different  from  the  "elements"  of  which 
the  bodies  among  which  we  live  are  made.  Hence  he 
makes  an  absolute  distinction  between  two  kinds  of 
matter,  "celestial  matter,"  the  "fifth  body,"  and 
"terrestrial"  or  "elementary"  matter.  The  funda- 
mental difference  is  that  "terrestrial"  or  "ele- 
mentary" matter,  left  to  itself,  follows  a  rectilinear 
path,  "celestial"  matter  rotates,  but  it  is  further 
inferred  from  the  supposed  absolute  uniformity  of 
the  celestial  movements  that  "celestial  matter"  is 
simple,  uncompounded,  incapable  of  change,  and  con- 
sequently that  no  new  state  of  things  can  ever  arise 
in  the  heavens.  The  spheres  and  planets  have  always 
been  and  will  always  be  exactly  as  they  are  at 
the  present  moment.  Mutability  is  confined  to  the 
region  of  "  terrestrial "  or  "  elementary  "  matter,  which 
only  extends  as  far  as  the  orbit  of  the  moon,  the 
"lowest  of  the  celestial  bodies,"  because  it  is  only 


80  AKISTOTLE. 

"terrestrial"  things  which  are,  as  we  should  say, 
chemical  coropounds.  This  is  the  doctrine  which 
Galileo  has  in  mind  when  he  dwells  on  such  newly- 
discovered  astronomical  facts  as  the  existence  of  sun- 
spots  and  variable  stars,  and  the  signs  of  irregularity 
presented  by  the  moon's  surface.*  The  distinction 
is  peculiar  to  Aristotle.  No  one  before  him  had  ever 
thought  of  supposing  the  heavenly  bodies  to  be  made 
of  any  materials  other  than  those  of  which  "  bodies 
terrestrial "  are  made.  In  the  Academic  attack  on 
Aristotle's  science  of  which  we  have  already  spoken 
the  two  points  singled  out  for  reprobation  are  (1)  his 
rejection  of  the  principle  that  all  moving  bodies,  left 
to  themselves,  follow  a  rectilinear  path,  and  (2)  his 
denial  that  the  heavenly  bodies  are  made  of  the  same 
"elements"  as  everything  else.  (It  may  just  be 
mentioned  in  passing  that  our  word  quintessence  gets 
its  sense  from  the  supposed  special  "  nobility  "  of  the 
incorruptible  "  fifth  body.") 

Terrestrial  Bodies. — As  we  have  seen  already, 
Aristotle  was  out  of  sympathy  with  the  tendency  to 
regard  the  sensible  differences  between  bodies  as  con- 
sequences of  more  ultimate  differences  in  the  geomet- 
rical structure  of  their  particles.  Hence  his  whole 
attitude  towards  the  problems  of  that  branch  of 
natural  science  which  we  call  physics  is  quite  unlike 
any  view  to  which  we  are  accustomed.  He  roA^erts 
from  the  mathematical  lines  of  thought  current  in 
Plato's  Academy  to  the  type  of  view  more  natural  to 
the  "  plain  man,"  and,  like  the  earliest  sixth-century 
men  of  science,  regards  the  qualitative  differences 
which  our  senses  apprehend  as  fundamental.  Among 
these,  particular  stress  is  laid  on  the  difference  in 

*  For  a  mediaeval  "  Aristotelian  "  explanation  of  the  "face  in 
the  moon,"  see  Dante  Paradiso,  ii.  46-105. 


PHYSICS.  81 

sensible  temperature  (the  hot — the  cold),  in  saturation 
(the  dry — the  moist),  and  in  density  (the  dense — the 
rare).  If  we  consider  the  first  two  of  these  opposi- 
tions, we  can  make  four  binary  combinations  of  the 
elementary  "opposite"  characters,  viz,  hot  and  dry, 
hot  and  moist,  cold  and  moist,  cold  and  dry.  These 
combinations  are  regarded  as  corresponding  respec- 
tively to  the  sensible  characteristics  of  the  four  bodies 
which  Empedocles,  the  father  of  Greek  chemistry,  had 
treated  as  the  ultimate  components  of  everything. 
Fire  is  hot  and  dry,  air  hot  and  moist,  water  moist 
and  cold,  earth  cold  and  dry.  This  reflection  shows 
us  why  Aristotle  held  that  the  most  rudimentary 
form  in  which  *'  matter  "  ever  actually  exists  is  that 
of  one  of  these  "elements."  Each  of  them  has  one 
quality  in  common  with  another,  and  it  is  in  virtue  of 
this  that  a  portion  of  one  element  can  be  assimilated 
by  and  transmuted  into  another,  a  process  which 
seems  to  the  untutored  eye  to  be  constantly  recurring 
in  Nature.  We  also  observe  that  the  order  in  which 
the  "  elements "  appear,  when  so  arranged  as  to  form 
a  series  in  which  each  term  has  one  quality  in  com- 
mon with  each  of  its  neighbours,  is  that  of  their 
increasing  density.  This  would  help  to  make  the 
conception  of  their  transmutability  all  the  more 
natural,  as  it  suggests  that  the  process  may  be  effected 
by  steady  condensation.  We  must  remember  care- 
fully that  for  Aristotle,  who  denies  the  possibility  of 
a  vacuum,  as  for  the  mediaeval  alchemists,  condensa- 
tion does  not  mean  a  mere  diminution  of  the  distances 
between  corpuscles  which  remain  unchanged  in  char- 
acter, but  is  a  process  of  real  qualitative  change  in 
the  body  which  undergoes  it.  Incidentally  we  may 
remark  that  all  changes  of  quality  are  regarded  by 
Aristotle  as  stages  in  a  continuous  "  movement "  from 

(1,994)  6 


82  AEISTOTLE. 

one  extreme  of  a  scale  to  another.  For  example, 
colours,  with  him  as  with  Goethe,  form  a  series  of 
which  the  "  opposites  "  white  and  black  are  the  end- 
points.  Every  other  colour  is  a  combination  of  white 
and  black  according  to  a  definite  proportion. 

The  Aristotelian  doctrine  of  weight  was  one  of  the 
chief  obstacles  which  seventeenth-century  science  had 
to  contend  with  in  establishing  correct  notions  in 
dynamics.  It  is  a  curious  feature  of  Greek  science 
before  Aristotle  that,  though  the  facts  connected  wit' 
gravity  were  well  known,  no  one  introduced  th 
notion  of  weight  to  account  for  them.  The  differem 
between  heavy  bodies  and  light  bodies  had  been 
previously  treated  as  secondary  for  science.  Plato's 
treatment  of  the  matter  is  typical  of  the  best  fourth- 
century  science.  We  riiust  not  try  to  explain  why 
the  heavier  bodies  tend  to  move  towards  the  earth's 
surface  by  saying  that  they  have  a  "downward" 
motion  ;  their  motion  is  not  downward  but  "  towards 
the  centre  "  (the  earth,  though  not  fixed  at  the  centre 
of  the  universe,  being  nearer  to  it  than  the  rest  of  the 
solar  and  sidereal  system).  Plato  then  explains  the 
tendency  in  virtue  of  which  the  heavier  bodies  move 
towards  the  "  centre  "  as  an  attraction  of  like  for  like. 
The  universal  tendency  is  for  smaller  masses  of 
"earth,"  "water,"  "air,"  "fire"  to  be  attracted 
towards  the  great  aggregations  of  the  same  materials. 
This  is  far  from  being  a  satisfactory  theory  in  the 
light  of  facts  which  were  not  yet  known  to  Plato,  but 
it  is  on  the  right  lines.  It  starts  from  the  conception 
of  the  facts  of  gravity  as  due  to  an  "  attractive  force  " 
of  some  kind,  and  it  has  the  great  merit  of  bringing 
the  "  sinking  "  of  stones  and  the  "  rising  "  of  vapours 
under  the  same  explanation. 

Aristotle,  though  retaining  the  central  idea  that  a 


ce 

I 


PHYSICS.  83 

body  tends  to  move  towards  the  region  where  the 
great  cosmic  mass  of  the  same  kind  is  congregated, 
introduced  the  entirely  incompatible  notion  of  an 
absolute  distinction  of  "up"  and  "down."  He 
identified  the  centre  of  the  universe  with  that  of  the 
earth,  and  looked  on  motion  to  this  centre  as  "  down- 
ward." This  led  him  to  make  a  distinction  between 
"  heavy "  bodies,  which  naturally  tend  to  move 
"down,"  and  "light"  bodies,  which  tend  to  move 
"  up "  away  from  the  centre.  The  doctrine  works 
out  thus.  The  heaviest  elements  tend  to  be  massed 
together  nearest  the  centre,  the  lightest  to  be  furthest 
from  it.  Each  element  thus  has  its  "  proper  place," 
that  of  water  being  immediately  above  earth,  that  of 
air  next,  and  that  of  fire  furthest  from  the  centre,  and 
nearest  to  the  regions  occupied  by  "  celestial  matter." 
(Readers  of  Dante  will  recollect  the  ascent  from  the 
Earthly  Paradise  through  the  "sphere  of  fire"  with 
which  the  Paradiso  opens.) 

In  its  own  "proper  region"  a  body  is  simply 
quiescent;  as  we  should  say,  any  fluid  loses  its 
weight  when  immersed  in  itself.  When  a  portion 
of  an  element  is  out  of  its  own  region  and  sur- 
rounded by  the  great  cosmic  aggregate  of  another 
element,  either  of  two  cases  may  occur.  The  body 
which  is  "  out  of  its  element "  may  be  below  its  proper 
place,  in  which  case  it  tends  to  move  perpendicularly 
upwards  to  its  place,  or  it  may  be  above  its  proper 
place,  and  then  it  tends  to  move  perpendicularly 
"down"  until  it  reaches  its  place.  Hence  the  two 
elements  whose  "  proper  place  "  is  "  below,"  earth  and 
water,  are  absolutely  heavy;  those  whose  "proper 
place  "  is  "  above,"  air  and  fire,  are  light.  It  was  this 
supposed  real  distinction  between  motion  "  up  "  and 
motion  "  down "  which  made  it  so  hard  for  the  con- 


84  ARISTOTLE. 


i 

iflated 


temporaries  of  Galileo  to  understand  that  an  in 
bladder  rises  for  the  same  reason  that  a  stone  sinks. 

Biology. — Of  Aristotle's  biology  reasons  of  space 
forbid  us  to  say  much  here.  But  a  remark  or  two 
may  be  made  about  his  theory  of  reproduction,  since 
it  is  constantly  referred  to  in  much  modern  literature 
and  has  also  played  its  part  in  theology.  An  inter- 
esting point  is  the  distinction  between  "  perfect "  an 
"  imperfect "  animals.  "  Perfect "  animals  are  thoi 
which  can  only  be  reproduced  sexually.  Aristot 
held,  however,  that  there  are  some  creatures,  ev( 
among  vertebrates,  which  may  be  produced  by  the 
vivifying  effect  of  solar  heat  on  decomposing  matter, 
without  any  parents  at  all.  Thus  malobservation  of 
the  facts  of  putrefaction  led  to  the  belief  that  flies 
and  worms  are  engendered  by  heat  from  decaying 
bodies,  and  it  was  even  thought  that  frogs  and  mice 
are  produced  in  the  same  way  from  river-slime.  In 
this  process,  the  so-called  "aequivocal  generation," 
solar  heat  was  conceived  as  the  operative  efficient 
cause  which  leads  to  the  realisation  of  an  organic 
"  form  "  in  the  decaying  matter. 

In  sexual  reproduction  Aristotle  regards  the  male 
parent  as  the  agent  or  efficient  cause  which  contributes 
the  element  of  form  and  organisation  to  the  offspring. 
The  female  parent  supplies  only  the  raw  material  of 
the  new  creature,  but  she  supplies  the  whole  of  this. 
No  material  is  supplied  by  the  male  parent  to  the 
body  of  the  offspring,  a  theory  which  St.  Thomas  found 
useful  in  defending  the  dogma  of  the  Virgin  Birth. 

Psychology. — Since  the  mind  grows  and  develops, 
it  comes  under  the  class  of  things  which  have  a 
"  source  of  motion  internal  to  themselves,"  and  psy- 
chology is  therefore,  for  Aristotle,  a  branch  of  Physics. 
To  undei-stand  his  treatment  of  psychological  ques- 


er- 

I 


PHYSICS.  85 

tions  we  need  bear  two  things  in  mind.  (1)  Psyche 
or  "soul"  means  in  Greek  more,  and  less,  than  "con- 
sciousness "  does  to  us.  Consciousness  is  a  relatively 
late  and  highly  developed  manifestation  of  the  prin- 
ciple which  the  Greeks  call  "soul."  That  principle 
shows  itself  not  merely  in  consciousness  but  in  the 
whole  process  of  nutrition  and  growth  and  the  adap- 
tation of  motor  response  to  an  external  situation. 
Thus  consciousness  is  a  more  secondary  feature  of  the 
"soul"  in  Greek  philosophy  than  in  most  modern 
thought,  which  has  never  ceased  to  be  affected  by 
Descartes'  selection  of  "thought"  as  the  special 
characteristic  of  psychical  life.  In  common  language 
the  word  psyche  is  constantly  used  where  we  should 
say  "life"  rather  than  "soul,"  and  in  Greek  philos- 
ophy a  work  "  on  the  Psyche  "  means  what  we  should 
call  one  on  "  the  principle  of  life."  * 

(2)  It  is  a  consequence  of  this  way  of  thinking  of 
the  "soul"  that  the  process  of  bodily  and  mental 
development  is  regarded  by  Aristotle  as  one  single 
continuous  process.  The  growth  of  a  man's  intellect 
and  character  by  which  he  becomes  a  thinker  and  a 
citizen  is  a  continuation  of  the  process  by  which  his 
body  is  conceived  and  born  and  passes  into  physical 
manhood.  This  comes  out  in  the  words  of  the  defini- 
tion of  the  soul.  "The  soul  is  the  first  entelechy 
(or  actual  realisation)  of  a  natural  organic  body." 
What  this  means  is  that  the  soul  stands  to  the  living 
body  as  all  form  realised  in  matter  does  to  the  matter 
of  which  it  is  the  form,  or  that  the  soul  is  the 
"  form  "  of  the  body.  What  the  "  organic  body  "  is 
to  the  embryo  out  of  which  it  has  grown,  that  soul 
is  to  the  body  itself.     As  the  embryo  grows  into  the 

*  In  particular  the  importance  of  self -consciousness  is  a  dis- 
covery of  the  Neo-Platonist  Plotinus. 


86  AEISTOTLE. 

actual  living  body,  so  the  living  body  grows  into  a 
body  exhibiting  the  actual  directing  presence  of  mind. 
Aristotle  illustrates  the  relation  by  the  remark  that 
if  the  whole  body  was  one  vast  eye,  sight  would  be 
its  soul.  As  the  eye  is  a  tool  for  seeing  with,  but  a 
living  tool  which  is  part  of  ourselves,  so  the  body  is 
a  like  tool  or  instrument  for  living  with.  Hence  we 
may  say  of  the  soul  that  it  is  the  "  end  "  of  the  body, 
the  activity  to  which  the  body  is  instrumental,  as 
seeing  is  the  "  end  "  to  which  the  eye  is  instrumental 
But  we  must  note  that  the  soul  is  called  only  the^H 
"first"  or  initial  "entelechy"  of  the  body.  The^ 
reason  is  that  the  mere  presence  of  the  soul  does  not 
guarantee  the  full  living  of  the  life  to  which  our  body 
is  but  the  instrument.  If  we  are  to  live  in  the  fullest 
sense  of  the  word,  we  must  not  merely  "  have "  a 
soul ;  we  "  have "  it  even  in  sleep,  in  ignorance,  in 
folly.  The  soul  itself  needs  further  to  be  educated 
and  trained  in  intelligence  and  character,  and  to 
exercise  its  intelligence  and  character  efficiently  on 
the  problems  of  thought  and  life.  The  mere  "pre- 
sence" of  soul  is  only  a  first  step  in  the  progress 
towards  fullness  of  life.  This  is  why  Aristotle  calls 
the  soul  the  Ji^'st  entelechy  of  the  living  body.  The 
full  and  final  entelechy  is  the  life  of  intelligence  and 
character  actively  functioning. 

From  this  conception  of  the  soul's  relation  to  the 
body  we  see  that  Aristotle's  "  doctrine  of  body  and 
mind  "  does  not  readily  fall  into  line  with  any  of  the 
typical  theories  of  our  time.  He  neither  thinks  of 
the  soul  as  a  thing  acting  on  the  body  and  acted  on 
by  it,  nor  yet  as  a  series  of  "states  of  mind"  con- 
comitant with  certain  "states  of  body."  From  his 
point  of  view  to  ask  whether  soul  and  body  interact, 
or  whether  they  exhibit  "  parallelism,"  would  be  much 


PHYSICS.  87 

the  same  thing  as  to  ask  whether  life  interacts  with 
the  body,  or  whether  there  is  a  "  parallelism  "  between 
vital  processes  and  bodily  processes.  We  must  not 
ask  at  all  how  the  body  and  soul  are  united.  They 
are  one  thing,  as  the  matter  and  the  form  of  a  copper 
globe  are  one.  Thus  they  are  in  actual  fact  insepa- 
rable. The  soul  is  the  soul  of  its  body  and  the  body 
the  body  of  its  soul.  We  can  only  distinguish  them 
by  logical  analysis,  as  we  can  distinguish  the  copper 
from  the  sphericity  in  the  copper  globe. 

Grades  of  Psychical  Life. — If  we  consider  the  order 
of  development,  we  find  that  some  vital  activities 
make  their  appearance  earlier  than  others,  and  that 
it  is  a  universal  law  that  the  more  highly  developed 
activities  always  have  the  less  highly  developed  as 
their  basis  and  precondition,  though  the  less  highly 
developed  may  exist  apart  from  the  more  highly  de- 
veloped. So  we  may  arrange  vital  activities  in  general 
in  an  ontogenetic  order,  the  order  in  which  they  make 
their  appearance  in  the  individual's  development. 
Aristotle  reckons  three  such  stages,  the  "nutritive," 
the  "  sensitive,"  and  the  *'  intelligent."  The  lowest 
form  in  which  life  shows  itself  at  all,  the  level  of 
minimum  distinction  between  the  living  and  the  life- 
less, is  the  power  to  take  in  nutriment,  assimilate  it, 
and  grow.  In  vegetables  the  development  is  arrested 
at  this  point.  With  the  animals  we  reach  the  next 
highest  level,  that  of  "  sensitive  "  life.  For  all  animals 
have  at  least  the  sense  of  touch.  Thus  they  all  show 
sense-perception,  and  it  is  a  consequence  of  this  that 
they  exhibit  "  appetition,"  the  simplest  form  of 
conation,  and  the  rudiments  of  feeling  and  "temper." 
For  what  has  sensations  can  also  feel  pleasure  and 
pain,  and  what  can  feel  pleasure  and  pain  can  desire, 
since  desire  is  only  appetition  of  what  is  pleasant. 


88  ARISTOTLE.  i 

Thus  in  the  animals  we  have  the  beginnings  of  cogni- 
tion, conation,  and  affective  and  emotional  life  in 
general.  And  Aristotle  adds  that  locomotion  makes 
its  appearance  at  this  level;  animals  do  not,  like 
plants,  have  to  trust  to  their  supply  of  nutriment 
coming  to  them  ;  they  can  go  to  it. 

The  third  level,  that  of  "intelligence,"  i.e.  the 
power  to  compare,  calculate,  and  reflect,  and  to  order 
one's  life  by  conscious  rule,  is  exhibited  by  man. 
What  distinguishes  life  at  this  level  from  mere 
"  sensitive  "  life  is,  on  the  intellectual  side,  the  ability 
to  cognise  universal  truths,  on  the  conative,  the  power 
to  live  by  rule  instead  of  being  swayed  by  momentary 
"  appetition."  The  former  gives  us  the  possibility  of 
science,  the  latter  of  moral  excellence.* 

Sensation. — Life  manifests  itself  at  the  animal 
level  on  the  cognitive  side  as  sense-perception,  on 
the  conative  as  appetition  or  desire,  on  the  affective 
as  feeling  of  pleasure  or  pain,  and  in  such  simple 
emotional  moods  as  "temper,"  resentment,  longing. 
Aristotle  gives  sensation  a  logical  priority  over  the 
conative  and  emotional  expression  of  "  animal "  life. 
To  experience  appetition  or  anger  or  desire  you  must 
have  an  object  which  you  crave  for  or  desire  or  are 
angry  with,  and  it  is  only  when  you  have  reached  the 
level  of  presentations  through  the  senses  that  you  can 
be  said  to  have  an  object.  Appetition  or  "  temper  " 
is  as  real  a  fact  as  perception,  but  you  cannot  crave 
for  or  feel  angry  with  a  thing  you  do  not  apprehend. 

Ai'istotle's  definition  of  sense-perception  is  that  it 
is  a  "capacity  for  discerning"  or  distinguishing  be- 

*  Cf.  Dante's  "Fatti  non  foste  a  viver  come  bniti, 

Ma  per  seguir  virtute  e  conoscenza  " 

— that  is,  to  follow  practical  [virtute]  and  speculative  [conoscenza) 
reason. 


PHYSICS.  89 

tween  "the  sensible  qualities  of  things."  His  con- 
ception of  the  process  by  which  the  discernment  or 
distinguishing  is  effected  is  not  altogether  happy. 
In  sense-perception  the  soul  "takes  into  itself  the 
form  of  the  thing  perceived  without  its  matter^  as 
sealing-wax  receives  the  shape  of  an  iron  seal-ring 
without  the  iron."  To  understand  this,  we  have  to 
remember  that  for  Aristotle  the  sensible  qualities  of 
the  external  world,  colour,  tones,  tastes,  and  the  rest, 
are  not  effects  of  mechanical  stimulation  of  our  sense- 
organs,  but  real  qualities  of  bodies.  The  hardness 
of  iron,  the  redness  of  a  piece  of  red  wax  are  all 
primarily  "in"  the  iron  or  the  wax.  They  are 
"forms,"  or  determinations  by  definite  law,  of  the 
"  matter  "  of  the  iron  or  the  wax.  This  will  become 
clearer  if  we  consider  a  definite  example,  the  red 
colour  of  the  wax.  In  the  wax  the  red  colour  is  a 
definite  combination  of  the  colour-opposites  white  and 
black  according  to  a  fixed  ratio.  Now  Aristotle's 
view  of  the  process  of  sense-perception  is  that  when  I 
become  aware  of  the  red  colour  the  same  proportion 
of  white  to  black  which  makes  the  wax  red  is  repro- 
duced in  my  organ  of  vision ;  my  eye,  while  I  am 
seeing  the  red,  "  assimilated  "  to  the  wax,  is  itself  for 
the  time  actually  "reddened."  But  it  does  not  be- 
come wcux  although  the  red  thing  I  am  looking  at  is 
a  piece  of  red  wcux.  The  eye  remains  a  thing  com- 
posed of  living  tissues.  This  is  what  is  meant  by 
saying  that  in  seeing  the  colours  of  things  the  eye 
receives  "forms"  without  the  "matter"  of  the  things 
in  which  those  forms  are  exhibited.  CThus  the  process 
of  sense-perception  is  one  in  which  the  organ  of  sense 
is  temporarily  assimilated  to  the  thing  apprehended 
in  respect  of  the  particular  quality  cognised  by  that 
organ,  but  in  respect  of  no  other.^  According  to  Aris- 


90  AKISTOTLE. 


1 


totle  this  process  of  "assimilation"  always  requires 
the  presence  of  a  "  medium."  If  an  object  is  in  im- 
mediate contact  with  the  eye  we  cannot  see  its  colour ; 
if  it  is  too  near  the  ear,  we  do  not  discern  the  note  it 
gives  out.  Even  in  the  case  of  touch  and  taste  there 
is  no  immediate  contact  between  the  object  perceived 
and  the  true  organ  of  perce^Dtion.  For  in  touch  the 
"  flesh "  is  not  the  organ  of  apprehension  but  an 
integument  surrounding  it  and  capable  of  acting  as 
an  intermediary  between  it  and  things.  Thus  per- 
ception is  always  accomplished  by  a  "  motion  "  set  up 
in  the  "medium"  by  the  external  object,  and  by  the 
medium  in  our  sense-organs.  Aristotle  thus  contrives 
to  bring  correct  apprehension  by  sense  of  the  qualities 
of  things  under  the  formula  of  the  "  right  mean  "  or 
"  right  proportion,"  which  is  better  known  from  the 
use  made  of  it  in  the  philosopher's  theory  of  conduct. 
The  colour  of  a  surface,  the  pitch  of  the  note  given 
out  by  a  vibrating  string,  etc.,  depend  on,  and  vary 
with,  certain  forms  or  ratios  "  in  "  the  surface  or  the 
vibrating  string;  our  correct  apprehension  of  the 
qualities  depends  on  the  reproduction  of  the  samfie 
ratios  in  our  sense-organs,  the  establishment  of  the 
"  right  proportion  "  in  us.  That  this  "  right  propor- 
tion "  may  be  reproduced  in  our  own  sense-organs  it 
is  necessary  (1)  that  the  medium  should  have  none  of 
the  sensible  qualities  for  the  apprehension  whereof  it 
serves  as  medium,  e.g.  the  medium  in  colour-perception 
must  be  colourless.  If  it  had  a  colour  of  its  own,  the 
"  motion  "  set  up  by  the  coloured  bodies  we  apprehend 
would  not  be  transmitted  undistorted  to  our  organs ; 
we  should  see  everything  through  a  coloured  haze. 
It  is  necessary  for  the  same  reason  (2)  that  the  per- 
cipient organ  itself,  when  in  a  state  of  quiescence, 
should  possess  none  of  the  qualities  which  can  be  in- 


PHYSICS.  91 

duced  in  it  by  stimulation.  The  upshot  of  the  whole 
theory  is  that  the  sense-organ  is  "  potentially  "  what 
the  sense-quality  it  apprehends  is  actually.  Actual  per- 
ceiving is  just  that  special  transition  from  the  potential 
to  the  actual  which  results  in  making  the  organ  for 
the  time  being  actually oi  the  same  quality  as  the  object. 
The  Common  Sensibles  and  the  Common  Sense- 
organ. — Every  sense  has  a  range  of  qualities  con- 
nected with  it  as  its  special  objects.  Colours  can  only 
be  perceived  by  the  eye,  sounds  by  the  ear,  and  so 
forth.  But  there  are  certain  characters  of  perceived 
things  which  we  appear  to  apprehend  by  more  than 
one  sense.  Thus  we  seem  to  perceive  size  and  shape 
either  by  touch  or  by  sight,  and  number  by  hearing 
as  well,  since  we  can  count  e.g.  the  strokes  of  an 
unseen  bell.  Hence  Aristotle  distinguishes  between 
the  "special  sensible  qualities"  such  as  colour  and 
pitch,  and  what  he  calls  the  "common  sensibles,"  the 
characters  of  things  which  can  be  perceived  by  more 
than  one  organ.  These  are  enumerated  as  size,  form 
or  shape,  number,  motion  (and  its  opposite  rest), 
being.  (The  addition  of  this  last  is,  of  course,  meant 
to  account  for  our  conviction  that  any  perceived 
colour,  taste,  or  other  quality  is  a  reality  and  not  a 
delusion.)  The  list  corresponds  very  closely  with  one 
given  by  Plato  of  the  "  things  which  the  mind  per- 
ceives hy  herself  without  the  help  of  any  organ"  i.e. 
of  the  leading  determinations  of  sensible  things  which 
are  due  not  to  sense  but  to  understanding.  It  was 
an  unfortunate  innovation  to  regard  the  discernment 
of  number  or  movement,  which  obviously  demand  in- 
tellectual processes  such  as  counting  and  comparison, 
as  performed  immediately  by  "sense,"  and  to  assign 
the  apprehension  of  number,  movement,  figure  to  a 
central  "  organ."     This  organ  he  finds  in  the  heart. 


92  ARISTOTLE. 

The  theory  is  that  when  the  "  special  organs  "  of  the 
senses  are  stimulated,  they  in  turn  communicate 
movements  to  the  blood  and  "animal  spirits"  {i.e. 
the  vapours  supposed  to  be  produced  from  the  blood 
by  animal  heat).  These  movements  are  propagated 
inwards  to  the  heart,  where  they  all  meet.  This  is 
supposed  to  account  for  the  important  fact  that, 
though  our  sensations  are  so  many  and  diverse,  we 
are  conscious  of  our  own  unity  as  the  subjects  appre- 
hending all  this  variety.  The  unity  of  the  perceiving 
subject  is  thus  made  to  depend  on  the  unity  of  the 
ultimate  "organ  of  sensation,"  the  heart.  Further, 
when  once  a  type  of  motion  has  been  set  up  in  any 
sense-organ  at  the  periphery  of  the  body  it  will  be 
propagated  inward  to  the  "common  sensorium"  in 
the  heart.  The  motions  set  up  by  stimulation,  e.g.  of 
the  eye  and  of  the  skin,  are  partly  different,  partly 
the  same  (viz.  in  so  far  as  they  are  determined  by  the 
number,  shape,  size,  movement  of  the  external 
stimuli).  Hence  in  the  heart  itself  the  stimulation 
on  which  perception  of  number  or  size  depends  is  one 
and  the  same  whether  it  has  been  transmitted  from 
the  eye  or  from  the  skin.  Awareness  of  lapse  of 
time  is  also  regarded  as  a  function  of  the  "  common 
sense-organ,"  since  it  is  the  "  common  sensory  "  which 
perceives  motion,  and  lapse  of  time  is  apprehended 
only  in  the  apprehension  of  motion.  Thus,  in  respect 
of  the  inclusion  of  geometrical  form  and  lapse  of  time 
among  the  "common  sensibles,"  there  is  a  certain 
resemblance  between  Aristotle's  doctrine  and  Kant's 
theory  that  recognition  of  spatial  and  temporal  order 
is  a  function  not  of  understanding  but  of  "pure" 
sense.  It  is  further  held  that  to  be  aware  that  one 
is  perceiving  (self-consciousness)  and  to  discriminate 
between  the  different  classes  of  "special"  sense-per- 


PHYSICS.  93 

ception  must  also  be  functions  of  the  "  common  sense- 
organ."  Thus  Aristotle  makes  the  mistake  of  treating 
the  most  fundamental  acts  of  intelligent  reflection  as 
precisely  on  a  par,  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  theory 
of  knowledge,  with  awareness  of  colour  or  sound. 

A  more  legitimate  function  assigned  to  the 
"  common  sensorium  "  in  the  heart  is  that  "  fantasy," 
the  formation  of  mental  imagery,  depends  on  its 
activity.  The  simplest  kind  of  "image,"  the  pure 
memory-image  left  behind  after  the  object  directly 
arousing  perception  has  ceased  to  stimulate,  is  due  to 
the  persistence  of  the  movements  set  up  in  the  heart 
after  the  sensory  process  in  the  peripheral  organ  is 
over.  Since  Aristotle  denies  the  possibility  of  thinking 
without  the  aid  of  memory-images,  this  function  of 
the  "  common  sensorium "  is  the  indispensable  basis 
of  mental  recall,  anticipation,  and  thought.  Neither 
"experience,"  i.e.  a  general  conviction  which  results 
from  the  frequent  repetition  of  similar  perceptions, 
nor  thought  can  arise  in  any  animal  in  which  sense- 
stimulation  does  not  leave  such  "traces"  behind  it. 
Similarly  "  free  imagery,"  the  existence  of  trains  of 
imagination  not  tied  down  to  the  reproduction  of  an 
actual  order  of  sensations,  is  accounted  for  by  the 
consideration  that  "  chance  coincidence  "  may  lead  to 
the  stimulation  of  the  heart  in  the  same  way  in 
which  it  might  have  been  stimulated  by  actual  sensa- 
tion-processes. Sleeping  and  waking  and  the  ex- 
periences of  dream-life  are  likewise  due  to  changes 
in  the  functioning  of  the  "common  sense-organ," 
brought  about  partly  by  fatigue  in  the  superficial 
sense-organs,  partly  by  qualitative  changes  in  the 
blood  and  "animal  spirits"  caused  by  the  processes 
of  nutrition  and  digestion.  Probably  Aristotle's  best 
scientific  work  in  psychology  is  contained  in  the  series 


94  AKISTOTLE. 

of  small  essays  in  which  this  theory  of  memory  and 
its  imagery  is  worked  out.  (Aristotle's  language 
about  the  "common  sensibles"  is,  of  course,  the 
source  of  our  expression  "common  sense,"  which, 
however,  has  an  entirely  different  meaning.  The 
shifting  of  sense  has  apparently  been  effected  through 
Cicero's  employment  of  tlie  phrase  sensus  communis 
to  mean  tactful  sympathy,  the  feeling  of  fellowship 
with  our  kind  on  which  the  Stoic  philosophers  laid  so  ^m 
much  stress.)  ^| 

Thought. — Though  thinking  is  impossible  except  by 
the  use  of  imagery,  to  think  is  not  merely  to  possess 
trains  of  imagery,  or  even  to  be  aware  of  possessing^! 
them.  Thinking  means  understanding  the  meaning  ^| 
of  such  mental  imagery  and  arriving  through  the 
understanding  at  knowledge  of  the  structure  of  the 
real  world.  How  this  process  of  interpreting  mental 
imagery  and  reaching  truth  is  achieved  with  greater 
and  greater  success  until  it  culminates  in  the  appre- 
hension of  the  supreme  principles  of  philosophy  we 
have  seen  in  dealing  with  the  Aristotelian  theory  of 
knowledge.  From  the  point  of  view  of  the  "physicist" 
who  is  concerned  with  thinking  simply  as  a  type  of 
natural  process,  the  relation  of  "understanding"  to 
the  mental  imagery  just  described  is  analogous  to  that 
of  sensation  to  sensible  qualities.  The  objects  which 
thinking  apprehends  are  the  universal  types  of  rela- 
tion by  which  the  world  of  things  is  pervaded.  The 
process  of  thinking  is  one  in  which  this  system  of 
universal  relations  is  reproduced  "by  way  of  idea"  in 
the  mind  of  the  thinker.  The  "  understanding  "  thus 
stands  to  its  objects  as  matter  to  form.  The  process 
of  getting  actually  to  understand  the  world  is  one  in 
which  our  "thought"  or  "understanding"  steadily 
receives  completer  determination  and   "form"  from 


PHYSICS.  95 

its  contemplation  of  reality.  In  this  sense,  the  pro- 
cess is  one  in  which  the  understanding  may  be  said  to 
be  passive  in  knowledge.  It  is  passive  because  it  is 
the  subject  which,  at  every  fresh  stage  in  the  progress 
to  knowledge,  is  being  quite  literally  "  informed  "  by 
the  action  of  the  real  world  through  the  sensation  and 
imagery.  Hence  Aristotle  says  that,  in  order  that 
the  understanding  may  be  correctly  "informed"  by 
its  contact  with  its  objects,  it  must,  before  the  process 
begins,  have  no  determinate  character  of  its  own.  It 
must  be  simply  a  capacity  for  apprehending  the  types 
of  interconnection.  "  What  is  called  the  intelligence 
— I  mean  that  with  which  the  soul  thinks  and  under- 
stands— is  not  an  actual  thing  until  it  thinks."  (This 
is  meant  to  exclude  any  doctrine  which  credits  the 
"  understanding "  with  either  furniture  of  its  own 
such  as  "  innate  ideas,"  or  a  specific  structure  of  its 
own.  If  the  results  of  our  thinking  arose  partly 
from  the  structure  of  the  world  of  objects  and  partly 
from  inherent  laws  of  the  "structure  of  mind,"  our 
thought  at  its  best  would  not  reproduce  the  universal 
"forms"  or  "types"  of  interconnection  as  they  really 
are,  but  would  distort  them,  as  the  shapes  of  things 
are  distorted  when  we  see  them  through  a  lens  of  high 
refractive  index.)  Thus,  though  Aristotle  differs 
from  the  modem  empiricists  in  holding  that  "  uni- 
versals"  really  exist  "in"  things,  and  are  the  links 
of  connection  between  them,  he  agrees  with  the  em- 
piricist that  knowledge  is  not  the  resultant  of  a  com- 
bination of  "  facts  "  on  the  one  side  and  "  fundamental 
laws  of  the  mind's  working "  on  the  other.  At  the 
outset  the  "  understanding "  has  no  structure ;  it 
develops  a  structure  for  itself  in  the  same  process, 
and  to  the  same  degree,  in  which  it  apprehends  the 
"  facts."     Hence  the  "  understanding  "  only  is  real  in 


96  AEISTOTLE. 

the  actual  process  of  understanding  its  objects,  and 
again  in  a  sense  the  understanding  and  the  things  it 
understands  are  one.  Only  we  must  qualify  this  last 
statement  by  saying  that  it  is  only  "potentially" 
that  the  understanding  is  the  forms  which  it  appre- 
hends. Aristotle  does  not  mean  by  this  that  such 
things  as  horses  and  oxen  are  thoughts  or  "ideas." 
By  the  things  with  which  "  understanding  "  is  said  to 
be  one  he  means  the  "forms"  which  we  apprehend 
when  we  actually  understand  the  world  or  any  part 
of  it,  the  truths  of  science.  His  point  then  is  that 
the  actual  thinking  of  these  truths  and  the  truths 
themselves  do  not  exist  apart  from  one  another. ^^ 
"  Science  "  does  not  mean  certain  things  written  dow^H 
in  a  book ;  it  means  a  mind  engaged  in  thinking  and^™ 
knowing  things,  and  of  the  mind  itself,  considered  out 
of  its  relation  to  the  actual  life  of  thinking  the  truths 
of  science,  we  can  say  no  more  than  that  it  is  a  name 
for  the  fact  that  we  are  capable  of  achieving  such 
thought. 

The  Active  Intelligence. — So  far  Aristotle's  account 
of  thought  has  been  plain  sailing.  Thought  has  been 
considered  as  the  final  and  highest  development  of 
the  vital  functions  of  the  organism,  and  hence  as 
something  inseparable  from  the  lower  functions  of 
nutrition  and  sensitive  life.  The  existence  of  a 
thought  which  is  not  a  function  of  a  living  body,  and 
which  is  not  "  passive,"  has  been  absolutely  excluded. 
But  at  this  point  we  are  suddenly  met  by  the  most 
startling  of  all  the  inconsistencies  between  the  natu- 
ralistic and  the  "spiritualist"  strains  in  Aristotle's 
philosophy.  In  a  few  broken  lines  he  tells  us  that 
there  is  another  sense  of  the  word  "thought"  in 
which  "  thought "  actually  creates  the  truths  it  under- 
stands, just  as  light  may  be  said  to  make  the  colours 


PHYSICS.  97 

which  we  see  by  its  aid.  "  And  this  intelligence,"  he 
adds,  "is  separable  from  matter,  and  impassive  and 
unmixed,  being  in  its  essential  nature  an  activiiy.  .  .  . 
It  has  no  intermivssion  in  its  thinking.  It  is  only  in 
separation  from  matter  that  it  is  fully  itself,  and  it 
alone  is  immortal  and  everlasting  .  .  .  while  the 
passive  intelligence  is  perishable  and  does  not  think 
at  all,  apart  from  this."  The  meaning  of  this  is' 
not  made  clear  by  Aristotle  himself,  and  the  inter- 
pretation was  disputed  even  among  the  philosopher's 
personal  disciples. 

One  important  attempt  to  clear  up  the  difficulty  is 
that  made  by  Alexander  of  Aphrodisias,  the  greatest 
of  the  commentators  on  Aristotle,  in  the  second 
century  a.d.  Alexander  said,  as  Aristotle  hsid  not 
done,  that  the  "  active  intelligence "  is  numerically 
the  same  in  all  men,  and  is  identical  with  God.  Thus, 
all  that  is  specifically  human  in  each  of  us  is  the 
"  passive  intelligence  "  or  capacity  for  being  enlight- 
ened by  God's  activity  upon  us.  The  advantage  of 
the  view  is,  that  it  removes  the  "  active  intelligence  " 
altogether  from  the  purview  of  psychology,  which 
then  becomes  a  purely  naturalistic  science.  The 
great  Arabian  Aristotelian,  Averroes  (Ibn  Roshd) 
of  Cordova,  in  the  twelfth  century,  went  still  further 
in  the  direction  of  naturalism.  Since  the  "active" 
and  "  passive  "  intelligence  can  only  be  separated  by 
a  logical  abstraction,  he  inferred  that  men,  speaking 
strictly,  do  not  think  at  all ;  there  is  only  one  and  the 
same  individual  intelligence  in  the  universe,  and  all 
that  we  call  our  thinking  is  really  not  ours  but  God's. 
The  great  Christian  scholastics  of  the  following  cen- 
tury in  general  read  Aristotle  through  the  eyes  of 
Averroes,  "^Ae  Commentator,"  as  St.  Thomas  calls 
him,  "  Averrois  che  il  gran  commento  feo,"  as  Dante 

(1,994)  7 


98  AKISTOTLE. 

says.  But  their  theology  compelled  them  to  disavow 
his  doctrine  of  the  "  active  intelligence,"  against  which 
they  could  also  bring,  as  St.  Thomas  does,  the  telling 
argument  that  Aristotle  could  never  have  meant  to 
say  that  there  really  is  no  such  thing  as  hurtmn  in- 
telligence. Hence  arose  a  third  interpretation,  the 
Thomist,  according  to  which  the  "  active  intelligence  " 
is  neither  God  nor  the  same  for  all  men,  but  is  the 
highest  and  most  rational  "part"  of  the  individual 
human  soul,  which  has  no  bodily  "  organ."  Aristotle 
had  said  of  it  that  it  is  the  only  thing  in  us  which 
is  not  contributed  by  our  parents,  but  comes  "from 
outside."  In  Christian  theology  this  becomes  the 
doctrine  that  the  "  rational  soul "  is  directly  created 
by  God. 


I 


CHAPTER  Y 

PRACTICAL    PHILOSOPHY 

Hitherto  we  have  been  concerned  with  the  specu- 
lative branches  of  knowledge ;  we  have  now  to  turn 
to  practice.  Practice,  too,  is  an  activity  of  thought, 
but  an  activity  which  is  never  satisfied  by  the  process 
of  thinking  itself.  In  practice  our  thinking  is  always 
directed  towards  the  production  of  some  result  other 
than  true  thought  itself.  As  in  engineering  it  is  not 
enough  to  find  a  solution  of  the  problem  how  to  build 
a  bridge  over  a  given  river  capable  of  sustaining  a 
given  strain,  so  in  directing  our  thought  on  the 
problems  of  human  conduct  and  the  organisation  of 
society  we  aim  at  something  more  than  the  under- 
standing of  human  life.  In  the  one  case  what  we 
aim  at  is  the  construction  of  the  bridge ;  in  the  other 
it  is  the  production  of  goodness  in  ourselves  and  our 
fellow-men,  and  the  establishment  of  right  social 
relations  in  the  state.  Aristotle  is  careful  to  insist 
on  this  point  throughout  his  whole  treatment  of 
moral  and  social  problems.  The  principal  object  of 
his  lectures  on  conduct  is  not  to  tell  his  hearers  what 
goodness  is,  but  to  make  them  good,  and  similarly  it 
is  quite  plain  that  Politics  was  intended  as  a  text-book 
for  legislators.  In  close  connection  with  this  practical 
object  stands  his  theory  of  the  kind  of  truth  which 


100  ARISTOTLE. 

must  be  looked  for  in  ethics  and  politics.  He  warns 
us  against  expecting  precepts  which  have  the  exact 
and  universal  rigidity  of  the  truths  of  speculative 
science.  Practical  science  has  to  do  with  the  affairs 
of  men's  lives,  matters  which  are  highly  complex  and 
variable,  in  a  word,  with  "what  may  be  otherwise." 
Hence  we  must  be  content  if  we  can  lay  down  precepts 
which  hold  good  in  the  main,  just  as  in  medicine  we 
do  not  expect  to  find  prescriptions  which  will  effect  a 
cure  in  all  cases,  but  are  content  with  general  direc- 
tions which  require  to  be  adapted  to  special  cases  by 
the  experience  and  judgment  of  the  practitioner.  The 
object  of  practical  science  then  is  to  formulate  rules 
which  will  guide  us  in  obtaining  our  various  ends. 
Now  when  we  consider  these  ends  we  see  at  once  that 
some  are  subordinate  to  others.  The  manufacture  of 
small-arms  may  be  the  end  at  which  their  maker 
aims,  but  it  is  to  the  military  man  a  mere  means  to 
his  end,  which  is  the  effective  use  of  them.  Success- 
ful use  of  arms  is  again  the  end  of  the  professional 
soldier,  but  it  is  a  mere  means  among  others  to  the 
statesman.  Further,  it  is  the  military  men  who  use 
the  arms  from  whom  the  manufacturer  has  to  take  his 
directions  as  to  the  kind  of  arms  that  are  wanted,  and 
again  it  is  the  statesman  to  whom  the  professional 
soldiers  have  to  look  for  directions  as  to  when  and 
with  what  general  objects  in  view  they  shall  fight. 
So  the  art  which  uses  the  things  produced  by  another 
art  is  the  superior  and  directing  art ;  the  art  which 
makes  the  things,  the  inferior  and  subordinate  art. 
Hence  the  supreme  practical  art  is  politics,  since  it  is 
the  art  which  uses  the  products  turned  out  by  all  other 
arts  as  means  to  its  ends.  It  is  the  business  of  poli- 
tics, the  art  of  the  statesman,  to  prescribe  to  the 
practitioners  of  all   other   arts  and   professions  the 


PKACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  101 

lines  on  which  and  the  conditions  under  which  they 
shall  exercise  their  vocation  with  a  view  to  securing 
the  supreme  practical  end,  the  well-being  of  the  com- 
munity. Among  the  other  professions  and  arts  which 
make  the  materials  the  statesman  employs,  the  pro- 
fession of  the  educator  stands  foremost.  The  states- 
man is  bound  to  demand  certain  qualities  of  mind  and 
character  in  the  individual  citizens.  The  production 
of  these  mental  and  moral  qualities  must  therefore 
be  the  work  of  the  educator.  It ,  thus  becomes  an 
important  branch  of  politics  to  specify  the  kind  of 
mental  and  moral  qualities  which  a  statesman  should 
require  the  educator  to  produce  in  his  pupils. 

It  is  this  branch  of  politics  which  Aristotle  discusses 
in  his  Ethics.  He  never  contemplates  a  study  of  the 
individual's  good  apart  from  politics,  the  study  of  the 
good  of  the  society.  What  then  is  the  good  or  the 
best  kind  of  life  for  an  individual  member  of  society  1 
Aristotle  answers  that  as  far  as  the  mere  name  is  con- 
cerned, there  is  a  general  agreement  to  call  the  best 
life,  Eudaimonia,  Happiness.  But  the  real  problem 
is  one  of  fact.  What  knicT^of  life  deserves  to  be  called 
happiness  1  Plato  had  laid  it  down  that  the  happy 
life  must  satisfy  threfLHonditions.  It  must  be  desir- 
able for  its  own  sake,  it  must  be  sufficient  of  itself  to  '^ 
^ia|istX-^'  ^^^  ^*  must  be  the  life  a  wise  man  would 
'prefer  to  any  other.  The  question  is,'  W  hat  general 
~fofmTila"  can  we  fin3  which  will  define  the  life  that 
satisfies  these  conditions?  To  find  the  answer  we 
have  to  consider  what  Plato  and  Aristotle  call  the 
work  or  function  of  man.  By  the  work  of  anything 
we  mean  what  can  only  be  done  by  it,  or  by  it  better 
than  by  anything  else.  Thus  the  work  of  the  eye  is 
to  see.  You  cannot  see  with  any  other  organ,  and 
when  the  eye  does  this  work  of  seeing  well  you  say  it 


102  ARISTOTLE. 

is  a  good  eye.  So  we  may  say  of  any  living  being 
that  its  work  is  to  live,  and  that  it  is  a  good  being 
when  it  does  this  work  of  living  efficiently.  To  do  its 
own  work  efficiently  is  the  excellence  or  virtue  of  the 
thing.  The  excellence  or  virtue  of  a  man  will  thus 
be  to  live'^efficientiy,  but  slntin^  life  can  be  manifested 
at  HiHereht  levels,"if  we  would  know  what  man's  work 
is  we  must  ask  whether  there  is  not  some  form  of  life 
which  can  only  be  lived  by  man.  Now  the  life  which 
consists  in  merely  feeding  and  growing  belongs  to  all 
organisms  and  can  be  lived  with  equal  vigour  by  them 
all.  There  is,  however,  a  kind  of  life  which  can  only 
be  lived  by  man — the  life  which  consists  in  conscious 
direction  of  one's  actions  by  a  rule.  It  is  the  work  of 
man  to  live  this  kind  of  life,  and  his  happiness  consists 
in  living  it  efficiently  and  well.  So  we  may  give  as 
the  definition  of  human  well-being  that  it  is  "an 
acti^aJife  in  accord!~wltTriexcelIe'nce,  or  if  there  Sre^ 
"more  forms  oi  excellence  than  one,  in  accord  with  the 
bestand  completest  of  them";  and  we  mugTadd  ''in' 
aoraiplete  life*^To  ^Eow*  that  mere  promise  not 
crowned  by  performance  does  not  suffice  to  entitle 
man's  life  to  be  called  happy.  We  can  see  that  this 
definition  satisfies  Plato's  three  conditions.  A  vigor- 
ous and  active  living  in  a  way  which  calls  into  play 
the  specifically  human  capacities  of  man  is  desirable 
for  its  own  sake,  and  preferable  to  any  other  life  which 
could  be  proposed  to  us.  It  too  is  the  only  life  which 
can  permanently  satisfy  men,  but  we  must  add  that 
if  such  a  life  is  to  be  lived  adequately  certain  advan- 
tages of  fortune  must  be  presupposed.  We  caimot 
fully  live  a  life  of  this  kind  if  we  are  prevented  from 
exercising  our  capacities  by  lack  of  means  or  health 
or  friends  and  associates,  and  even  the  calamities 
which  arise  in  the  course  of  events  may  be  so  crush- 


PEACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  103 

mg  as  to  hinder  a  man,  for  a  time,  from  putting  forth 
his  full  powers.  These  external  good  things  are  not 
constituents  of  happiness,  but  merely  necessary  con- 
ditions of  that  exercise  of  our  own  capacities  which  is 
the  happy  life. 

In  our  definition  of  the  happy  life  we  said  that  it 
was  one  of  activity  in  accord  with  goodness  or  ex- 
cellence, and  we  left  it  an  open  question  whether 
there  are  more  kinds  of  such  goodness  than  one. 
On  consideration  we  see  that  two  kinds  of  goodness 
or  excellence  are  required  in  living  the  happy  lifa 
ThfiJiapjgWife  for  man  is  a  life  of  consciaus-i^llewiHg- 
ofja  rula  To  live  it  well,  then,  you  need  to  know 
whaFtKe  right  rule  to  follow  is,  and  you  need  also 
to  follow  it.  There  are  persons  who  deliberately 
follow  a  wrong  rule  of  life — the  wicked.  There  are 
others  who  know  what  the  right  rule  is  but  fail  to 
follow  it  because  their  tempers  and  appetites  are  un- 
ruly— the  morally  weak.  To  live  the  happy  life, 
then,  two  sorts  of  goodness  are  required.  You  must 
have  a  good  judgment  as  to  what  the  right  rule  is 
(or  if  you  cannot  find  it  out  for  yourself,  you  must 
at  least  be  able  to  recognise  it  when  it  is  laid  down 
by  some  one  else,  the  teacher  or  lawgiver),  and  you 
must  have  your  appetites,  feelings,  and  emotions 
generally  so  trained  that  they  obey  the  rule.  Hence 
excellence,  goodness,  or  virtue  is  divided  into  good- 
ness of  intellect  and  goodness  of  character  (moral 
goodness),  the  word  character  being  used  for  the  com- 
plex of  tempers,  feelings,  and  the  affective  side  of 
human  nature  generally.  In  education  goodness  of 
character  has  to  be  produced  by  training  and  dis- 
cipline before  goodness  of  intellect  can  be  imparted. 
The  young  generally  have  to  be  trained  to  obey  the 
right  rule  before  they  can  see  for  themselves  that  it 


104  AEISTOTLE. 

is  the  right  rule,  and  if  a  man's  tempers  and  passions 
are  not  first  schooled  into  actual  obedience  to  the 
rule  he  will  in  most  cases  never  see  that  it  is  the 
right  rule  at  all.  Hence  Aristotle  next  goes  on  to 
discuss  the  general  character  of  the  kind  of  goodness 
he  calls  goodness  of  character,  the  right  state  of  the 
feelings  and  passions. 

The  first  step  towards  understanding  what  goodness 
of  character  is  is  to  consider  the  way  in  which  it  is 
actually  produced.  We  are  not  born  with  this  good- 
ness of  tempers  and  feelings  ready  made,  nor  yet  do 
we  obtain  it  by  theoretical  instruction ;  it  is  a  result 
of  a  training  and  discipline  of  the  feelings  and  im- 
pulses. The  possibility  of  such  a  training  is  due 
to  the  fact  that  feelings  and  impulses  are  rational 
capacities,  and  a  rational  capacity  can  be  developed 
into  either  of  two  contrasted  activities  according  to 
the  training  it  receives.  You  cannot  train  stones  to 
fall  upwards,  but  you  can  train  a  hot  temper  to  dis- 
play itself  either  in  the  form  of  righteous  resentment 
of  wrong-doing  or  in  that  of  violent  defiance  of  all 
authority.  Our  natural  emotions  and  impulses  are 
in  themselves  neither  good  nor  bad  ;  they  are  the  raw 
material  out  of  which  training  makes  good  or  bad 
character  according  to  the  direction  it  gives  to  them. 
The  effect  of  training  is  to  convert  the  indeterminate 
tendency  into  a  fixed  habit.  We  may  say,  then,  that 
moral  goodness  is  a  fixed  state  of  the  soul  produced 
by  habituation.  By  being  trained  in  habits  of  endur- 
ance, self-mastery,  and  fair  dealing,  we  acquire  the 
kind  of  character  to  which  it  is  pleasing  to  act  bravely, 
continently,  and  fairly,  and  disagreeable  to  act  un- 
fairly, profligately,  or  like  a  coward.  When  habitua- 
tion b»s  brought  about  this  result  the  moral  excel- 
lences in  question  have  become  part  of  our  inmost 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  105 

self  and  we  are  in  full  possession  of  goodness  of 
character.  In  a  word,  it  is  by  repeated  doing  of 
right  acts  that  we  acquire  the  right  kind  of  character. 
But  what  general  characteristics  distinguish  right 
acts  and  right  habits  from  wrong  ones  ?  Aristotle  is 
guided  in  answering  the  question  by  an  analogy  which 
is  really  at  the  bottom  of  all  Greek  thinking  on 
morality.  The  thought  is  that  goodness  is  in  the 
soul  what  health  and  fitness  are  in  the  body,  and 
that  the  preceptor  is  for  the  soul  what  the  physician 
or  the  trainer  is  for  the  body.  Now  it  was  a  well- 
known  medical  theory,  favoured  by  both  Plato  and 
Aristotle,  that  health  in  the  body  means  a  condition 
of  balance  or  equilibration  among  the  elements 
of  which  it  is  composed.  When  the  hot  and  tlie 
cold,  the  moist  and  the  dry  in  the  composition  of 
the  human  frame  exactly  balance  one  another, 
the  body  is  in  perfect  health.  Hence  the  object  of 
the  regimen  of  the  physician  or  the  trainer  is  to 
produce  and  maintain  a  proper  balance  or  proportion 
between  the  ingredients  of  the  body.  Any  course 
which  disturbs  this  balance  is  injurious  to  health  and 
strength.  You  damage  your  health  if  you  take  too 
much  food  or  exercise,  and  also  if  you  take  too  little. 
The  same  thing  is  true  of  health  in  the  soul.  Our 
soul's  health  may  be  injured  by  allowing  too  much  or 
too  little  play  to  any  of  our  natural  impulses  or  feel- 
ings. We  may  lay  it  down,  then,  that  the  kind  of 
training  which  gives  rise  to  a  good  habit  is  training 
in  the  avoidance  of  the  opposite  errors  of  the  too 
much  and  the  too  little.  And  since  the  effect  of 
training  is  to  produce  habits  which  issue  in  the  spon- 
taneous performance  of  the  same  kind  of  acts  by 
which  the  habits  were  acquired,  we  may  say  not 
merely  that  goodness  of   character   is   produced   by 


106  ARISTOTLE. 

acts  which  exhibit  a  proper  balance  or  mean,  but 
that  it  is  a  settled  habit  of  acting  so  as  to  exhibit 
the  same  balance  or  proportion.  Hence  the  formal 
definition  of  goodness  of  character  is  that  it  is  ''^^|{ 
settled  condition  of  the  soul  which  wills  or  chooses^^B 
the  mean  relatively  to  ourselves,  this  mean  being 
determined  by  a  rule  or  whatever  we  like  to  call 
that  by  which  the  wise  man  determines  it."  ^|l 

There  are  several  points  in  this  definition  of  the^" 
mean  upon  which  moral  virtue  depends  of  which  we 
must  take  note  unless  we  are  to  misunderstand 
Aristotle  seriously.  To  begin  with,  the  definition 
expressly  says  that  "  moral  goodness  is  a  state  of  will 
or  choice."  Thus  it  is  not  enough  that  one  should 
follow  the  rule  of  the  mean  outwardly  in  one's  actions ; 
one's  personal  will  must  be  regulated  by  it.  Good- 
ness of  character  is  inward ;  it  is  not  merely  outward. 
Next  we  must  not  suppose  that  Aristotle  means  that 
the  "just  enough"  is  the  same  for  all  our  feelings, 
that  every  impulse  has  a  moral  right  to  the  same 
authority  in  shaping  our  conduct  as  any  other.  How 
much  or  how  little  is  the  just  enough  in  connection 
with  a  given  spring  of  action  is  one  of  the  things 
w^hich  the  wise  man's  rule  has  to  determine,  just  as 
the  wise  physician's  rule  may  determine  that  a  very 
little  quantity  is  the  just  enough  in  the  case  of  some 
articles  of  diet  or  curative  drugs,  while  in  the  case 
of  others  the  just  enough  may  be  a  considerable 
amount.  Also  the  right  mean  is  not  the  same  for 
every  one.  What  we  have  to  attain  is  the  mean 
relatively  to  ourselves,  and  this  will  be  different  for 
persons  of  different  constitutions  and  in  different 
conditions.  It  is  this  relativity  of  the  just  enough 
to  the  individual's  personality  and  circumstances 
which  makes  it  impossible  to  lay  down  precise  rules 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  107 

of  conduct  applicable  alike  to  everybody,  and  renders 
the  practical  attainment  of  goodness  so  hard.  It  is 
my  duty  to  spend  some  part  of  my  income  in  taking 
a  yearly  holiday,  but  no  general  rule  will  tell  me 
what  percentage  of  my  income  is  the  right  amount 
for  me  to  spend  in  this  way.  That  depends  on  a  host 
of  considerations,  such  as  the  excess  of  my  income 
above  my  necessary  expenses  and  the  like.  Or  again, 
the  just  enough  may  vary  with  the  same  man  accord- 
ing to  the  circumstances  of  the  particular  case.  No 
rule  of  thumb  application  of  a  formula  will  decide 
such  problems.  Hence  Aristotle  insists  that  the  right 
mean  in  the  individual  case  has  always  to  be  deter- 
mined by  immediate  insight.  This  is  precisely  why 
goodness  of  intellect  needs  to  be  added  to  goodness  of 
character.  His  meaning  is  well  brought  out  by  an 
illustration  which  I  borrow  from  Professor  Burnet. 
"On  a  given  occasion  there  will  be  a  temperature 
which  is  just  right  for  my  morning  bath.  If  the 
bath  is  hotter  than  this,  it  will  be  too  hot ;  if  it  is 
colder,  it  will  be  too  cold.  But  as  this  just  right 
temperature  varies  with  the  condition  of  my  body,  it 
cannot  be  ascertained  by  simply  using  a  thermometer. 
If  I  am  in  good  general  health  I  shall,  however, 
know  by  the  feel  of  the  water  when  the  temperature 
is  right.  So  if  I  am  in  good  moral  health  I  shall 
know,  without  appealing  to  a  formal  code  of  maxims, 
what  is  the  right  degree,  e.g.  of  indignation  to  show 
in  a  given  case,  how  it  should  be  shown  and  towards 
whom."  Thus  we  see  why  Aristotle  demands  good- 
ness of  character  as  a  preliminary  condition  of  good- 
ness of  intellect  or  judgment  in  moral  matters. 
Finally,  if  we  ask  by  what  rule  the  mean  is  deter- 
mined, the  answer  will  be  that  the  rule  is  the  judg- 
ment of  the  legislator  who  determines  what  is  the 


108  ARISTOTLE. 


right  mean  by  his  knowledge  of  the  conditions 
which  the  well-being  of  the  community  depends.  He 
then  embodies  his  insight  in  the  laws  which  he  makes 
and  the  regulations  he  imposes  on  the  educators  of 
youth.  The  final  aim  of  education  in  goodness  is  to 
make  our  immediate  judgment  as  to  what  is  right 
coincide  with  the  spirit  of  a  wise  legislation. 

The  introduction  of  the  reference  to  will  or  choice 
into  the  definition  of  goodness  of  character  leads 
Aristotle  to  consider  the  relation  of  will  to  conduct. 
His  main  object  is  to  escape  the  paradoxical  doctrine 
which  superficial  students  might  derive  from  the 
works  of  Plato,  that  wrong-doing  is  always  well- 
meaning  ignorance.  Aristotle's  point  is  that  it  is 
the  condition  of  will  revealed  by  men's  acts  which  is 
the  real  object  of  our  approval  or  blame.  This  is 
because  in  voluntary  action  the  man  himself  is  the 
efficient  cause  of  his  act.  Hence  the  law  recognises 
only  two  grounds  on  which  a  man  may  plead  that  he 
is  not  answerable  for  what  he  does.  (1)  Actual 
physical  compulsion  by  ybrcema/6«^e.  (2)  Ignorance, 
not  due  to  the  man's  own  previous  negligence,  of  some 
circumstances  material  to  the  issue.  When  either  of 
these  pleas  can  be  made  with  truth  the  man  does  not 
really  contribute  by  his  choice  to  the  resulting  act, 
and  therefore  is  not  really  its  cause.  But  a  plea  of 
ignorance  of  the  general  laws  of  morality  does  not 
excuse.  I  cannot  escape  responsibility  for  a  murder 
by  pleading  that  I  did  not  know  that  murder  is 
wrong.  Such  a  plea  does  not  exempt  me  from  having 
been  the  cause  of  the  murder ;  it  only  shows  that  my 
moral  principles  are  depraved. 

More  precisely  will  is  a  process  which  has  both  an 
intellectual  and  an  appetitive  element.  The  appetitive 
element  is  our  wish  for  some  result.     The  intellectual 


}  on^l 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  109 

factor  is  the  calculation  of  the  steps  by  which  that 
result  may  be  obtained.  When  we  wish  for  the 
result  we  begin  to  consider  how  it  might  be  brought 
about,  and  we  continue  our  analysis  until  we  find 
that  the  chain  of  conditions  requisite  may  be  started 
by  the  performance  of  some  act  now  in  our  power 
to  do.  Will  may  thus  be  defined  as  the  deliberate 
appetition  of  something  within  our  power,  and  the 
very  definition  shows  that  our  choice  is  an  efiicient 
cause  of  the  acts  we  choose  to  do.  This  is  why  we 
rightly  regard  men  as  responsible  or  answerable  for 
their  acts  of  choice,  good  and  bad  alike. 

From  the  analysis  of  goodness  of  character  we 
proceed  to  that  of  goodness  of  intellect.  The  im- 
portant point  is  to  decide  which  of  all  the  forms  of 
goodness  of  intellect  is  that  which  must  be  combined 
with  goodness  of  character  to  make  a  man  fit  to  be  a 
citizen  of  the  state.  It  must  be  a  kind  of  intellectual 
excellence  which  makes  a  man  see  what  the  right 
rule  by  which  the  mean  is  determined  is.  Now  when 
we  come  to  consider  the  different  excellences  of 
intellect  we  find  that  they  all  fall  under  one  of  two 
heads,  theoretical  or  speculative  wisdom  and  practical 
wisdom. 

Theoretical  wisdom  is  contained  in  the  sciences 
which  give  us  universal  truths  about  the  fixed  and 
unalterable  relations  of  the  things  in  the  universe,  or, 
as  we  should  say,  which  teach  us  the  laws  of  Natura 
Its  method  is  syllogism,  the  function  of  which  is  to 
make  us  see  how  the  more  complex  truths  are  implied 
in  simpler  principles.  Practical  wisdom  is  intelligence 
as  employed  in  controlling  and  directing  human  life  to 
the  production  of  the  happy  life  for  a  community,  and 
it  is  this  form  of  intellectual  excellence  which  we 
require  of  the  statesman.     It  is  required  of  him  not 


110  ARISTOTLE. 

only  that  he  should  know  in  general  what  things  are 
good  for  man,  but  also  that  he  should  be  able  to  judge 
correctly  that  in  given  circumstances  such  and  such 
an  act  is  the  one  which  will  secure  the  good.  He 
must  not  only  know  the  right  rule  itself,  which 
corresponds  to  the  major  premiss  of  syllogism  in 
theoretical  science,  but  he  must  understand  the 
character  of  particular  acts  so  as  to  see  that  they 
fall  under  the  right  rule.  Thus  the  method  of  prac- 
tical wisdom  will  be  analogous  to  that  of  theoretical 
wisdom.  In  both  cases  what  we  have  to  do  is  to  see 
that  certain  special  facts  are  cases  of  a  general  law  or 
rule.  Hence  Aristotle  calls  the  method  of  practical 
wisdom  the  practical  syllogism  or  syllogism  of  action, 
since  its  peculiarity  is  that  what  issues  from  the 
putting  together  of  the  premisses  is  not  an  assertion 
but  the  performance  of  an  act.  In  the  syllogism  of 
action,  the  conclusion,  that  is  to  say,  the  performance 
of  a  given  act,  just  as  in  the  syllogism  of  theory,  is 
connected  with  the  rule  given  in  the  major  premiss 
by  a  statement  of  fact ;  thus  e.g.  the  performance  of 
a  specific  act  such  as  the  writing  of  this  book  is  con- 
nected with  the  general  rule  that  what  helps  to  spread 
knowledge  ought  to  be  done  by  the  conviction  that 
the  writing  of  this  book  helps  to  spread  knowledge. 
Our  perception  of  such  a  fact  is  like  a  sense-perception 
in  its  directness  and  immediacy.  We  see  therefore 
that  the  kind  of  intellectual  excellence  which  the 
statesman  must  possess  embraces  at  once  a  right  con- 
ception of  the  general  character  of  the  life  which  is 
best  for  man,  because  it  calls  into  play  his  specific 
capacities  as  a  human  being,  and  also  a  sound  judg- 
ment in  virtue  of  which  he  sees  correctly  that  par- 
ticular acts  ai-e  expressions  of  this  good  for  man. 
This,  then,  is  what  we  mean  by  practical  wisdom. 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  Ill 

So  far,  then,  it  would  seem  that  the  best  Kfe  for 
man  is  just  the  life  of  co-operation  in  the  life  of  the 
State,  which  man,  being  the  only  political  animal  or 
animal  capable  of  life  in  a  State,  has  as  his  peculiar 
work,  and  as  if  the  end  of  all  moral  education  should 
be  to  make  us  good  and  efficient  citizens.  But  in  the 
Ethics,  as  elsewhere,  the  end  of  Aristotle's  argument 
has  a  way  of  forgetting  the  beginning.  We  find  that 
there  is  after  all  a  still  higher  life  open  to  man  than 
that  of  public  affairs.  Affairs  and  business  of  all 
kinds  are  only  undertaken  as  means  to  getting  leisure, 
just  as  civilised  men  go  to  war,  not  for  the  love  of  war 
itself,  but  to  secure  peace.  The  highest  aim  of  life, 
then,  is  not  the  carrying  on  of  political  business  for 
its  own  sake,  but  the  worthy  and  noble  employment 
of  leisure,  the  periods  in  which  we  are  our  own 
masters.  It  has  the  advantage  that  it  depends  more 
purely  on  ourselves  and  our  own  internal  resources 
than  any  other  life  of  which  we  know,  for  it  needs 
very  little  equipment  with  external  goods  as  compared 
with  any  form  of  the  life  of  action.  It  calls  into 
play  the  very  highest  of  our  own  capacities  as  in- 
telligent beings,  and  for  that  very  reason  the  active 
living  of  it  is  attended  with  the  purest  of  all  pleasures. 
In  it,  moreover,  we  enter  at  intervals  and  for  a  little 
while,  so  far  as  the  conditions  of  our  mundane  exist- 
ence allow,  into  the  life  which  God  enjoys  through 
an  unbroken  eternity.  Thus  we  reach  the  curious 
paradox  that  while  the  life  of  contemplation  is  said 
to  be  that  of  our  truest  self,  it  is  also  maintained  that 
this  highest  and  happiest  life  is  one  which  we  live, 
not  in  respect  of  being  human,  but  in  respect  of  having 
a  divine  something  in  us.  When  we  ask  what  this 
life  of  contemplation  includes,  we  see  from  references 
in  the  Politics  that  it  includes  the  genuinely  aesthetic 


112  ARISTOTLE. 

appreciation  of  good  literature  and  music  and  pictorial 
and  plastic  art,  but  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  what 
bulks  most  largely  in  Aristotle's  mind  is  the  active 
pursuit  of  science  for  its  own  sake,  particularly  of 
such  studies  as  First  Philosophy  and  Physics,  which 
deal  with  the  fundamental  structure  of  the  universe. 
Aristotle  thus  definitely  ends  by  placing  the  life  of 
the  scholar  and  the  student  on  the  very  summit  of 
felicity. 

It  is  from  this  doctrine  that  mediaeval  Christianity 
derives  its  opposition  between  the  vita  contemplativa 
and  vita  activa  and  its  preference  for  the  former,  though 
in  the  mediaeval  mind  the  contemplative  life  has  come 
to  mean  generally  a  kind  of  brooding  over  theological 
speculations  and  of  absorption  in  mystical  ecstasy 
very  foreign  to  the  spirit  of  Aristotle.  The  types 
by  which  the  contrast  of  the  two  lives  is  illustrated — 
Rachel  and  Leah,  Mary  and  Martha — are  familiar  to 
all  readers  of  Christian  literature. 

The  Theory  of  the  State. — Man  is  by  nature  a 
political  animal,  a  being  who  can  only  develop  his 
capacities  by  sharing  in  the  life  of  a  community. 
Hence  Aristotle  definitely  rejects  the  view  that  the 
State  or  Society  is  a  mere  creature  of  convention  or 
agreement,  an  institution  made  by  compact  between 
individuals  for  certain  special  ends,  not  growing 
naturally  out  of  the  universal  demands  and  aspira- 
tions of  humanity.  Mankind,  he  urges,  have  never 
existed  at  all  as  isolated  individuals.  Some  rudi- 
mentary form  of  social  organisation  is  to  be  found 
wherever  men  are  to  be  found.  The  actual  stages 
in  the  development  of  social  organisation  have  been 
three — the  family,  the  village  community,  the  city 
State.  In  the  very  rudest  forms  of  social  life  known 
to  us,  the  patriarchal  family,  not  the  individual,  is 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  113 

the  social  unit.  Men  lived  at  first  in  separate  families 
under  the  control  of  the  head  of  the  family.  Now  a 
family  is  made  up  in  its  simplest  form  of  at  least 
three  persons — a  man,  his  wife,  and  a  servant  or  slave 
to  do  the  hard  work ;  though  very  poor  men  often 
have  to  replace  the  servant  by  an  ox  as  the  drudge  of 
all  work.  Children  when  they  come  swell  the  number, 
and  thus  we  see  the  beginnings  of  complex  social 
relations  of  subordination  in  the  family  itself.  It 
involves  three  such  distinct  relations,  that  of  husband 
and  wife,  that  of  parent  and  child,  that  of  master  and 
man.  The  family  passes  into  the  village  community, 
partly  by  the  tendency  of  several  families  of  common 
descent  to  remain  together  under  the  direction  of  the 
oldest  male  member  of  the  group,  partly  by  the  associa- 
tion of  a  number  of  distinct  families  for  purposes  of 
mutual  help  and  protection  against  common  dangers. 
Neither  of  these  forms  of  association,  however,  makes 
adequate  provision  for  the  most  permanent  needs  of 
human  nature.  Complete  security  for  a  permanent 
supply  of  material  necessaries  and  adequate  protection 
only  come  when  a  number  of  such  scattered  com- 
munities pool  their  resources,  and  surround  them- 
selves with  a  city  wall.  The  city  State,  which  has 
come  into  being  in  this  way,  proves  adequate  to 
provide  from  its  own  internal  resources  for  all  the 
spiritual  as  well  as  the  material  needs  of  its  members. 
Hence  the  independent  city  State  does  not  grow  as 
civilisation  advances  into  any  higher  form  of  organi- 
sation, as  the  family  and  village  grew  into  it.  It  is 
the  end,  the  last  word  of  social  progress.  It  is 
amazing  to  us  that  this  piece  of  cheap  conservatism 
should  have  been  uttered  at  the  very  time  when  the 
system  of  independent  city  States  had  visibly  broken 
down,  and  a  former  pupil  of  Aristotle  himself  was 

(1,994)  8 


114  ARISTOTLE. 

founding  a  gigantic  empire  to  take  their  place  as  the 
vehicle  of  civilisation. 

The  end  for  which  the  State  exists  is  not  merely  its 
own  self-perpetuation.  As  we  have  seen,  Aristotle 
assigns  a  higher  value  to  the  life  of  the  student  than 
to  the  life  of  practical  affairs.  Since  it  is  only  in  the 
civilised  State  that  the  student  can  pursue  his  voca- 
tion, the  ultimate  reason  for  which  the  State  exists 
is  to  educate  its  citizens  in  such  a  way  as  shall  fit 
them  to  make  the  noble  use  of  leisure.  In  the  end 
the  State  itself  is  a  means  to  the  spiritual  cultivation 
of  its  individual  members.  This  implies  that  the 
chosen  few,  who  have  a  vocation  to  make  full  use  of 
the  opportunities  provided  for  leading  this  life  of 
noble  leisure,  are  the  real  end  for  the  sake  of  which 
society  exists.  The  other  citizens  who  have  no  quali- 
fication for  any  life  higher  than  that  of  business  and 
affairs  are  making  the  most  of  themselves  in  devoting 
their  lives  to  the  conduct  and  maintenance  of  the 
organisation  whose  full  advantages  they  are  unequal 
to  share  in.  It  is  from  this  point  of  view  also  that 
Aristotle  treats  the  social  problem  of  the  existence 
of  a  class  whose  whole  life  is  spent  in  doing  the  hard 
work  of  society,  and  thus  setting  the  citizen  body  free 
to  make  the  best  use  it  can  of  leisure.  In  the  condi- 
tions of  life  in  the  Greek  world  this  class  consisted 
mainly  of  slaves,  and  thus  the  problem  Aristotle  has 
to  face  is  the  moral  justifiability  of  slavery.  We 
must  remember  that  he  knew  slavery  only  in  its  com- 
paratively humane  Hellenic  form.  The  slaves  of 
whom  he  speaks  were  household  servants  and  assistants 
in  small  businesses.  He  had  not  before  his  eyes  the 
system  of  enormous  industries  carried  on  by  huge 
gangs  of  slaves  under  conditions  of  revolting  degrada- 
tion which  disgraced  the  later  Roman  Republic  and 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  115 

the  early  Roman  Empire,  or  the  Southern  States  of 
North  America.  His  problems  are  in  all  essentials 
much  the  same  as  those  which  concern  us  to-day  in 
connection  with  the  social  position  of  the  classes  who 
do  the  hard  bodily  work  of  the  community.  As 
against  social  revolutionaries  who  regard  all  slavery 
as  wrong,  Aristotle  holds  that  it  would  certainly  be 
wrong  if  it  meant  the  condemnation  of  the  slave  to 
a  worse  life  than  the  best  of  which  he  is  capable.  But 
it  does  not  really  mean  this.  Non-Greeks,  "bar- 
barians," do  not  really  possess  the  capacity  for  being 
their  own  masters  or  for  living  either  the  life  of  the 
civilised  man  of  affairs  or  that  of  the  student.  They 
attain  the  highest  mental  and  moral  development  of 
which  they  are  capable,  not  when  left  in  their  native 
"  barbarism,"  but  when  they  occupy  the  position  of 
servants  in  a  civilised  Greek  society.  A  Thracian 
who  is  the  slave  of  a  decent  and  kindly  Greek  master 
is  living  a  worthier  life  than  a  Thracian  who  runs 
wild  on  his  "native  heath."  It  is  thus  really  for  his 
own  good  and  for  his  own  happiness  that  he  should 
make  the  best  of  himself;  he  is  not  wronged  by 
losing  a  "  freedom  "  of  which  he  is  incapable  of  mak- 
ing the  proper  use.  Much  in  the  same  way  evan- 
gelical Protestants  used  at  one  time  to  defend  negro 
slavery  in  our  own  colonies  by  the  plea  that  the  slave 
got  opportunities  of  salvation  which  he  could  not 
have  enjoyed  as  a  free  heathen  in  his  native  Africa. 

Much  consideration  is  given  in  the  Politics  to  the 
classification  of  the  different  types  of  constitution 
possible  for  the  city  State.  The  current  view  was 
that  there  are  three  main  types,  distinguished  by  the 
number  of  persons  who  form  the  sovereign  politi- 
cal authority :  monarchy,  in  which  sovereign  power 
belongs  to  a  single  person ;  oligarchy,  in  which  it  is 


116  AKISTOTLE. 

in  the  hands  of  a  select  few ;  democracy,  in  which 
it  is  enjoyed  by  the  whole  body  of  the  citizens. 
Aristotle  observes,  correctly,  that  the  really  funda- 
mental distinction  between  a  Greek  oligarchy  and  a 
Greek  democracy  was  that  the  former  was  govern- 
ment by  the  propertied  classes,  the  latter  government 
by  the  masses.  Hence  the  watchword  of  democracy 
was  always  that  all  political  rights  should  belong 
equally  to  all  citizens  ;  that  of  oligarchy,  that  a  man's 
political  status  should  be  graded  according  to  his 
"stake  in  the  country."  Both  ideals  are,  according 
to  him,  equally  mistaken,  since  the  real  end  of 
government,  which  both  overlook,  is  the  promotion 
of  the  "  good  life."  In  a  State  which  recognises  this 
ideal,  an  aristocracy  or  government  by  the  best,  only 
the  "best"  men  will  possess  the  full  rights  of  citizen- 
ship, whether  they  are  many  or  few.  There  might 
even  be  a  monarch  at  the  head  of  such  a  State,  if  it 
happened  to  contain  some  one  man  of  outstanding 
intellectual  and  moral  worth.  Such  a  State  should 
be  the  very  opposite  of  a  great  imperial  power.  It 
should,  that  its  cultivation  may  be  the  more  intensive, 
be  as  small  as  is  compatible  with  complete  independ- 
ence of  outside  communities  for  its  material  and 
spiritual  sustenance,  and  its  territory  should  only 
be  large  enough  to  provide  its  members  with  the 
permanent  possibility  of  ample  leisure,  so  long  as 
they  are  content  with  plain  and  frugal  living. 
Though  it  ought  not,  for  military  and  other  reasons, 
to  be  cut  off  from  communication  with  the  sea, 
the  great  military  and  commercial  highroad  of  the 
Greek  world,  it  ought  not  to  be  near  enough  to 
the  coast  to  run  any  risk  of  imperilling  its  moral 
cultivation  by  becoming  a  great  emporium,  like  the 
Athens   of   Pericles.      In   the   organisation   of    the 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  117 

society  care  should  be  taken  to  exclude  the  agricul- 
tural and  industrial  population  from  full  citizenship, 
which  carries  with  it  the  right  to  appoint  and  to  be 
appointed  as  administrative  magistrates.  This  is 
because  these  classes,  having  no  opportunity  for  the 
worthy  employment  of  leisure,  cannot  be  trusted  to 
administer  the  State  for  the  high  ends  which  it  is 
its  true  function  to  further. 

Thus  Aristotle's  political  ideal  is  that  of  a  small 
but  leisured  and  highly  cultivated  aristocracy,  with- 
out large  fortunes  or  any  remarkable  differences  in 
material  wealth,  free  from  the  spirit  of  adventure  and 
enterprise,  pursuing  the  arts  and  sciences  quietly 
while  its  material  needs  are  supplied  by  the  labour 
of  a  class  excluded  from  citizenship,  kindly  treated 
but  without  prospects.  Weimar,  in  the  days  when 
Thackeray  knew  it  as  a  lad,  would  apparently  re- 
produce the  ideal  better  than  any  other  modern  State 
one  can  think  of. 

The  object  of  the  Politics  is,  however,  not  merely 
to  discuss  the  ideal  State,  but  to  give  practical  advice 
to  men  who  might  be  looking  forward  to  actual 
political  life,  and  would  therefore  largely  have  to  be 
content  with  making  the  best  of  existing  institutions. 
In  the  absence  of  the  ideal  aristocracy,  Aristotle's 
preference  is  for  what  he  calls  Polity  or  constitutional 
government,  a  sort  of  compromise  between  oligarchy 
and  democracy  in  which  political  power  is  in  the 
hands  of  the  "  middle  "  classes.  Of  course  a  practi- 
cal statesman  may  have  to  work  with  a  theoretically 
undesirable  constitution,  such  as  an  oligarchy  or  an 
unqualified  democracy.  But  it  is  only  in  an  ideal 
constitution  that  the  education  which  makes  its 
subject  a  good  man,  in  the  philosopher's  sense  of  the 
word,  will  also  make  him  a  good  citizen.      If  the 


118  AEISTOTLE. 

constitution  is  bad,  then  the  education  best  fitted  to 
make  a  man  loyal  to  it  may  have  to  be  very  different 
from  that  which  you  would  choose  to  make  him  a 
good  man.  The  discussion  of  the  kind  of  education 
desirable  for  the  best  kind  of  State,  in  which  to  be 
a  loyal  citizen  and  to  be  a  good  man  are  the  same 
thing,  is  perhaps  the  most  permanently  valuable  part 
of  the  Politics.  Though  Aristotle's  writings  on 
"practical"  philosophy  have  been  more  read  in 
modern  times  than  any  other  part  of  his  works,  they 
are  far  from  being  his  best  and  most  thorough  per- 
formances. In  no  department  of  his  thought  is  he 
quite  so  slavishly  dependent  on  his  master  Plato  as 
in  the  theory  of  the  "  good  for  man  "  and  the  char- 
acter of  "  moral "  excellence.  No  Aristotelian  work 
is  quite  so  commonplace  in  its  handling  of  a  vast 
subject  as  the  Politics.  In  truth  his  interest  in  these 
social  questions  is  not  of  the  deepest.  He  is,  in 
accordance  with  his  view  of  the  superiority  of  "  theo- 
retical science,"  entirely  devoid  of  the  spirit  of  the 
social  reformer.  What  he  really  cares  about  is 
"  theology "  and  "  physics,"  and  the  fact  that  the 
objects  of  the  educational  regulations  of  the  Politics 
are  all  designed  to  encourage  the  study  of  these 
"theoretical"  sciences,  makes  this  section  of  the 
Politics  still  one  of  the  most  valuable  expositions  of 
the  aims  and  requirements  of  a  "  liberal "  education. 

All  education  must  be  under  public  control,  and 
education  must  be  universal  and  compulsory.  Public 
control  is  necessary,  not  merely  to  avoid  educational 
anarchy,  but  because  it  is  a  matter  of  importance 
to  the  community  that  its  future  citizens  should  be 
trained  in  the  way  which  will  make  them  most  loyal 
to  the  constitution  and  the  ends  it  is  designed  to 
subserve.     Even  in  one  of  the  "  bad  "  types  of  State, 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  119 

where  the  life  which  the  constitution  tends  to  foster 
is  not  the  highest,  the  legislator's  business  is  to  see 
that  education  is  directed  towards  fostering  the  "  spirit 
of  the  constitution."  There  is  to  be  an  "  atmosphere  " 
which  impregnates  the  whole  of  the  teaching,  and  it 
is  to  be  an  "  atmosphere  "  of  public  spirit.  The  only 
advantage  which  Aristotle  sees  in  private  education 
is  that  it  allows  of  more  modification  of  programme 
to  meet  the  special  needs  of  the  individual  pupil  than 
a  rigid  State  education  which  is  to  be  the  same  for 
all.  The  actual  regulations  which  Aristotle  lays  down 
are  not  very  different  from  those  of  Plato.  Both 
philosophers  hold  that  "primary"  education,  in  the 
early  years  of  life,  should  aim  partly  at  promoting 
bodily  health  and  growth  by  a  proper  system  of 
physical  exercises,  partly  at  influencing  character 
and  giving  a  refined  and  elevated  tone  to  the  mind 
by  the  study  of  letters,  art,  and  music.  Both  agree 
that  this  should  be  followed  in  the  later  "  teens  "  by 
two  or  three  years  of  specially  rigorous  systematic 
military  training  combined  with  a  taste  of  actual 
service  in  the  less  exhausting  and  less  dangerous 
parts  of  a  soldier's  duty.  It  is  only  after  this,  at 
about  the  age  at  which  young  men  now  take  a 
"  university  "  course,  that  Plato  and  Aristotle  would 
have  the  serious  scientific  training  of  the  intellect 
begun.  The  Politics  leaves  the  subject  just  at  the 
point  where  the  young  men  are  ready  to  undergo 
their  special  military  training.  Thus  we  do  not  know 
with  certainty  what  scientific  curriculum  Aristotle 
would  have  recommended,  though  we  may  safely 
guess  that  it  would  have  contained  comparatively 
little  pure  mathematics,  but  a  great  deal  of  astronomy, 
cosmology,  and  biology. 

With  respect  to  the  "  primary  "  education  Aristotle 


120  AEISTOTLE. 

has  a  good  deal  to  say.  As  "  forcing  "  is  always  in- 
jurious, it  should  not  be  begun  too  soon.  For  the 
first  five  years  a  child's  life  should  be  given  up  to 
healthy  play.  Great  care  must  be  taken  that  children 
are  not  allowed  to  be  too  much  with  "  servants,"  from 
whom  they  may  imbibe  low  tastes,  and  that  they  are 
protected  against  any  familiarity  with  indecency. 
From  five  to  seven  a  child  may  begin  to  make  a  first 
easy  acquaintance  with  the  life  of  the  school  by  look- 
ing on  at  the  lessons  of  its  elders.  The  real  work 
of  school  education  is  to  begin  at  seven  and  not 
before. 

We  next  have  to  consider  what  should  be  the 
staple  subjects  of  an  education  meant  not  for  those 
who  are  to  follow  some  particular  calling,  but  for  all 
the  full  citizens  of  a  State.  Aristotle's  view  is  that 
some  "useful"  subjects  must,  of  course,  be  taught. 
Reading  and  writing,  for  instance,  are  useful  for  the 
discharge  of  the  business  of  life,  though  their  com- 
mercial utility  is  not  the  highest  value  which  they 
have  for  us.  But  care  must  be  taken  that  only  those 
"  useful "  studies  which  are  also  "  liberal "  should  be 
taught;  "illiberal"  or  "mechanical"  subjects  must 
not  have  any  place  in  the  curriculum.  A  "  liberal " 
education  means,  as  the  name  shows,  one  which  will 
tend  to  make  its  recipient  a  "  free  man,"  and  not  a 
slave  in  body  and  soul.  The  mechanical  crafts  were 
felt  by  Aristotle  to  be  illiberal  because  they  leave  a 
man  no  leisure  to  make  the  best  of  body  and  mind ; 
practice  of  them  sets  a  stamp  on  the  body  and  narrows 
the  mind's  outlook.  In  principle,  then,  no  study 
should  form  a  subject  of  the  universal  curriculum  if 
its  only  value  is  that  it  prepares  a  man  for  a  pro- 
fession followed  as  a  means  of  making  a  living. 
General  education,  all-round  training  which  aims  at 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  121 

the  development  of  body  and  mind  for  its  own  sake, 
must  be  kept  free  from  the  intrusion  of  everything 
which  has  a  merely  commercial  value  and  tends  to 
contract  the  mental  vision.  It  is  the  same  principle 
which  we  rightly  employ  ourselves  when  we  maintain 
that  a  university  education  ought  not  to  include 
specialisation  on  merely  "technical"  or  "profes- 
sional" studies.  The  useful  subjects  which  have  at 
the  same  time  a  higher  value  as  contributing  to  the 
formation  of  taste  and  character  and  serving  to 
elevate  and  refine  the  mind  include,  besides  reading 
and  writing,  which  render  great  literature  accessible 
to  us,  bodily  culture  (the  true  object  of  which  is  not 
merely  to  make  the  body  strong  and  hardy,  but  to 
develop  the  moral  qualities  of  grace  and  courage), 
music,  and  drawing.  Aristotle  holds  that  the  real 
reason  for  making  children  learn  music  is  (1)  that  the 
artistic  appreciation  of  really  great  music  is  one  of 
the  ways  in  which  "leisure"  may  be  worthily  em- 
ployed, and  to  appreciate  music  rightly  we  must  have 
some  personal  training  in  musical  execution ;  (2)  that 
all  art,  and  music  in  particular,  has  a  direct  influence 
on  character. 

Plato  and  Aristotle,  though  they  differ  on  certain 
points  of  detail,  are  agreed  that  the  influence  of  music 
on  character,  for  good  or  bad,  is  enormous.  Music, 
they  say,  is  the  most  imitative  of  all  the  arts.  The 
various  rhythms,  times,  and  scales  imitate  different 
tempers  and  emotional  moods,  and  it  is  a  fundamental 
law  of  our  nature  that  we  grow  like  what  we  take 
pleasure  in  seeing  or  having  imitated  or  represented 
for  us.  Hence  if  we  are  early  accustomed  to  take 
pleasure  in  the  imitation  of  the  manly,  resolute,  and 
orderly,  these  qualities  will  in  time  become  part  of 
our  own  nature.     This  is  why  right  musical  education 


122  AKISTOTLE. 

is  so  important  that  Plato  declared  that  the  revolu- 
tionary spirit  always  makes  its  first  appearance  in 
innovations  on  established  musical  form. 

There  is,  however,  one  important  difference  between 
the  two  philosophers  which  must  be  noted,  because 
it  concerns  Aristotle's  chief  contribution  to  the  phi- 
losophy of  fine  art.  Plato  had  in  the  Republic  pro- 
posed to  expel  florid,  languishing,  or  unduly  exciting 
forms  of  music  not  only  from  the  schoolroom,  but 
from  life  altogether,  on  the  ground  of  their  unwhole- 
some tendency  to  foster  an  unstable  and  morbid 
character  in  those  who  enjoy  them.  Por  the  same 
reason  he^  had  proposed  the  entire  suppression  of 
tragic  drama.  Aristotle  has  a  theory  which  is  directly 
aimed  against  this  overstrained  Puritanism.  He 
holds  that  the  exciting  and  sensational  art  which 
would  be  very  bad  as  daily  food  may  be  very  useful 
as  an  occasional  medicine  for  the  soul.  He  would 
retain  even  the  most  sensational  forms  of  music  on 
account  of  what  he  calls  their  "purgative"  value. 
In  the  same  spirit  he  asserts  that  the  function  of 
tragedy,  with  its  sensational  representations  of  the 
calamities  of  its  heroes,  is  "by  the  vehicle  of  fear 
and  pity  to  purge  our  minds  of  those  and  similar 
emotions."  The  explanation  of  the  theory  is  to  be 
sought  in  the  literal  sense  of  the  medical  term  "  pur- 
gative." According  to  the  medical  view  which  we 
have  already  found  influencing  his  ethical  doctrine, 
health  consists  in  the  maintenance  of  an  equality 
between  the  various  ingredients  of  the  body.  Every 
now  and  again  it  happens  that  there  arise  superfluous 
accretions  of  some  one  ingredient,  which  are  not 
carried  away  in  the  normal  routine  of  bodily  life. 
These  give  rise  to  serious  derangement  of  function, 
and   may   permanently   injure    the   working   of   the 


PRACTICAL  PHILOSOPHY.  123 

organism,  unless  they  are  removed  in  time  by  a 
medicine  which  acts  as  a  purge,  and  clears  the  body 
of  a  superfluous  accumulation.  The  same  thing  also 
happens  in  the  life  of  the  soul.  So  long  as  we  are  in 
good  spiritual  health  our  various  feelings  and  emo- 
tional moods  will  be  readily  discharged  in  action,  in 
the  course  of  our  daily  life.  But  there  is  always  the 
possibility  of  an  excessive  accumulation  of  emotional 
"  moods  "  for  which  the  routine  of  daily  life  does  not 
provide  an  adequate  discharge  in  action.  Unless  this 
tendency  is  checked  we  may  contract  dangerously 
morbid  habits  of  soul.  Thus  we  need  some  medicine 
for  the  soul  against  this  danger,  which  may  be  to  it 
what  a  purgative  is  to  the  body. 

Now  it  was  a  well-known  fact,  observed  in  con- 
nection with  some  of  the  more  extravagant  religious 
cults,  that  persons  suffering  from  an  excess  of  religious 
frenzy  might  be  cured  homoeopathically,  so  to  say,  by 
artificially  arousing  the  very  emotion  in  question  by 
the  use  of  exciting  music.  Aristotle  extends  the 
principle  by  suggesting  that  in  the  artificial  excite- 
ment aroused  by  violently  stimulating  music  or  in  the 
transports  of  sympathetic  apprehension  and  pity  with 
which  we  follow  the  disasters  of  the  stage-hero,  we 
have  a  safe  and  ready  means  of  ridding  ourselves  of 
morbid  emotional  strain  which  might  otherwise  have 
worked  havoc  with  the  efficient  conduct  of  real  life. 

The  great  value  of  this  defence  of  the  occasional 
employment  of  sensation  as  a  medicine  for  the  soul 
is  obvious.  Unhappily  it  would  seem  to  have  so 
dominated  Aristotle's  thought  on  the  functions  of 
dramatic  art  as  to  blind  him  to  what  we  are  accus- 
tomed to  think  the  nobler  functions  of  tragedy.  No 
book  has  had  a  more  curious  fate  than  the  little 
manual  for  intending  composers  of  tragedies  which 


124  AEISTOTLE. 

is  all  that  remains  to  us  of  Aristotle's  lectures  on 
Poetry.  This  is  not  the  place  to  tell  the  story  of  the 
way  in  which  the  great  classical  French  playwrights, 
who  hopelessly  misunderstood  the  meaning  of  Aris- 
totle's chief  special  directions,  but  quite  correctly 
divined  that  his  lectures  were  meant  to  be  an  actual 
Yade  Mecum  for  the  dramatist,  deliberately  con- 
structed their  masterpieces  in  absolute  submission  to 
regulations  for  which  they  had  no  better  reasons  than 
that  they  had  once  been  given  magisterially  by  an 
ancient  Greek  philosopher.  But  it  may  be  worth 
while  to  remark  that  the  worth  of  Aristotle's  account 
of  tragedy  as  art-criticism  has  probably  been  vastly 
overrated.  From  first  to  last  the  standpoint  he 
assumes,  in  his  verdicts  on  the  great  tragic  poets,  is 
that  of  the  gallery.  What  he  insists  on  all  through, 
probably  because  he  has  the  purgative  effect  of  the 
play  always  in  his  mind,  is  a  well-woven  plot  with 
plenty  of  melodramatic  surprise  in  the  incidents  and 
a  thoroughly  sensational  culmination  in  a  scene  of 
unrelieved  catastrophe  over  which  the  spectator  can 
have  a  good  cry,  and  so  get  well  "purged"  of  his 
superfluous  emotion.  It  is  clear  from  his  repeated 
allusions  that  the  play  he  admired  above  all  others 
was  the  King  Oedipus  of  Sophocles,  but  it  is  equally 
clear  that  he  admired  it  not  for  the  profound  insight 
into  human  life  and  destiny  or  the  deep  sense  of  the 
mystery  of  things  which  some  modern  critics  have 
found  in  it,  but  because  its  plot  is  the  best  and  most 
startling  detective  story  ever  devised,  and  its  finale  a 
triumph  of  melodramatic  horror. 


BIBLIOGRAPHY 

The  English  reader  who  wishes  for  further  information 
about  Aristotle  and  his  philosophy  may  be  referred  to  any 
or  all  of  the  following  works  : — 

E.  Zaller. — Aristotle  and  the  Earlier  Peripatetics.  English 
translation  in  2  vols,  by  B.  F.  C.  Costelloe  and  J.  H. 
Muirhead.     London.     Longmans  &  Co. 

*E.  Wallace. — Outlijies  of  the  Philosophy  of  Aristotle.  Cam- 
bridge University  Press. 

G.  Grote. — Aristotle.     London.     John  Murray. 

*"W.  D.  Ross. — The  Works  of  Aristotle  translated  into  English, 
vol.  viii.,  Metaphysics.     Oxford.     Clarendon  Press. 

*A.  E.  Taylor. — Aristotle  on  his  Predecessors.  {Metaphysics^ 
Bk.  L,  translated  with  notes,  &c.)  Chicago.  Open 
Court  Publishing  Co. 

E..  D.  Hicks. — Aristotle  de  Anima.  (Greek  text,  English 
translation.  Commentary.)  Cambridge  University 
Press. 

*D.  P.  Chase.— TVie  Ethics  of  Aristotle.     Walter  Scott  Co. 

*J.  Burnet. — Aristotle  on  Education.  (English  translation  of 
Ethics,  Bks.  L-III.  5,  X.  6  to  end;  Politics,  VII.  17, 
VIII.)     Cambridge  University  Press, 

*B.  Jowett. — The  Politics  of  Aristotle.  Oxford.  Clarendon 
Press. 

*I.  By  water. — Aristotle  on  the  Art  of  Poetry.  (Greek  text, 
English  translation.  Commentary.)  Oxford.  Claren- 
don Press. 


126  ARISCCOTLE. 

J.  I.  Beare  and  G.  T.  Ross. — The  Works  of  Aristotle  trans- 
lated into  English^  Pt.  I.  {Parva  NaturcUia,  the 
minor  psychological  works.)  Oxford.  Clarendon 
Press. 

J.  I.  Beare. — Greek  Theories  of  Elementary  Cognition  from 
Alcmaeon  to  Aristotle.     Oxford.     Clarendon  Press. 

The  works  marked  by  an  asterisk  will  probably  be  found 
most  useful  for  the  beginner.  No  works  in  foreign  languages 
and  no  editions  not  accompanied  by  an  English  translation 
have  been  mentioned. 

There  is  at  present  no  satisfactory  complete  translation  of 
Aristotle  into  English.  One,  of  which  two  volumes  have 
been  mentioned  above,  is  in  course  of  production  at  the 
Clarendon  Press,  Oxford,  under  the  editorship  of  J.  A.  Smith 
and  G.  T.  Ross. 


THE   END. 


PBINTED    IN    GREAT    BRITAIN    AT 
THE  PRESS  OF  THE  PUBLISHERS. 


"  We  have  nothing  but  the  highest  praise  for  these  httle  books,  and  no 
e  who  examines  them  will  have  anything  else." — Westminster  Gazette. 

THE   PEOPLE^S  BOOKS 


The  Foundations  of  Science    . 
Embryology— The  Beginnings  of  Life  . 

Biology 

Zoologry :  The  Study  of  Animal  Life    . 

Botanjr:  The  Modern  Study  of  Plants. 

Bacteriology 

The  Structure  of  the  Earth 

Evolution    .... 

Heredity      .... 

Inorganic  Chemistry 

Organic  Chemistry   . 

The  Principles  of  Electricity 

Radiation    .... 

The  Science  of  the  Stars 

The  Science  of  Light 

Weather-Science 

Hypnotism  and  Self-Education 

The  Baby:  A  Mother's  Book  by  a  Mother 


By  W.  C.  D.Whetham,  M.A.,  F.R.S. 

By  Prof.  Gerald  Leighton,  M.D. 

By  Prof.  W.  D.  Henderson,  M.A. 
/By  Prof.  E.  W.  MacBride,  M.A., 
(.     F.R.S. 

By  M.  C.  Stopes,D.Sc.,Ph.D.,F.L.S. 

By  W.  E.  Carnegie-Dickson,  M.D. 

By  Prof.  T.  G.  Bonney,  F.R.S. 

By  E.  S.  Goodrich,  M.A.,  F.R.S. 

By  J.  A.  S.  Watson,  B.Sc. 

By  Prof.  E.  C.  C.  Baly,  F.R.S. 

By  Prof.  J.  B.  Cohen,  B.Sc,  F.R.S. 

By  Norman  R.  Campbell,  M.A. 

By  P.  Phillips,  D.Sc. 

By  E.  W.  Maunder,  F.  R.A.S. 

By  P.  Phillips,  D.Sc. 

By  R,  G.  K.  Lempfert,  M.A. 

By  A.  M.  Hutchison,  M.D. 

By  a  University  Woman. 


Youth  and  Sex— Dangers   and    Safe- \ By  Mary  Scharlieb,  M.D.,  M.S 
'     "      ~  ■  "■  '  /     F.  Arthur  Sibly 


M.A.,LL.D. 
Davidson,    M.B., 


gTiards  for  Boys  and  Girls 
Marriage  and  Motherhood— A  Wife's  \  By  H.   S. 

Handbook /     F.R.C.S.E. 

Lord  Kelvin By  A  Russell,  D.Sc,  M.I. E.E. 

Huxley By  Prof.  G.  Leighton,  M.D. 

Sir    William    Huggins    and    Spectro-\ByE.  W.  Maunder,  F.R.A.S.,  of  the 

scopic  Astronomy /     Roj^I  Observatory,  Greenwich. 

Emanuel  Swedenborg      .        .        .        .     By  L.  B.  De  Beaumont,  D.Sc. 
"chinglT°°;    '^^'^    Philosophy    of}ByH.WildonCarr. 
Psychology'        .**.!!!!     By  H.  J. Watt,  M.A,  Ph.D.,  D.Phil. 
Ethics ByCanonRashdall,  D.Litt.,  F.B.A. 


Kant's  Philosophy 
Christianity  and  Christian  Science 
Roman  Catholicism  .... 
The  Oxford  Movement     . 


The  Bible  and  Criticism  . 

The  Growth  of  Freedom . 

Bismarck  and  Origin  of  German  Empire 

Oliver  Cromwell 

Mary  Queen  of  Scots  .... 
Cecil  Rhodes,  1853-1902  .... 
JuHus^Caesar :  Soldier.  Statesman,  Em- 1  g'^  ^^^^^  Hardinge 

/By  Prof.F.J.C.  Hearnshaw,  M.A 

•I     LL.D. 

.     By  E.  O'Neill,  M.A. 


By  A.  D.  Lindsay,  M.A.,  Oxford. 
,     By  M.  C.  Sturge. 

By  H.  B.  Coxon. 
,     By  Wilfrid  Ward. 
/By  W.   H.   Bennett,  M.A.,  D.D., 
•  \     LittD.,&W.  F.  Adeney,  M.A.,D.D. 

By  H.  W.  Nevinson, 

By  Prof.  F.  M.  Powicke. 

By  Hilda  Johnstone,  M.A. 

By  E.  O'Neill,  M.A 

By  Ian  D.  Colvin. 


England  in  the  Making   . 

England  in  the  Middle  Ages  . 
The  Monarchy  and  the  People 
The  Industrial  Revolution  . 
Empire  and  Democracy  .  . 
Women's  Suffrage  ,  ,  , 
A  History  of  Greece  ,  , 
Shakespeare      .... 

Wordsworth By  Rosaline  Masson. 

Pure  Gold-A  Choice ofLyricsft  Sonnets    By  H.  C.  O'Neill. 

Francis  Bacon By  Prof.  A.  R.  Skemp,  M.A, 

The  Brontes By  Flora  Masson. 

Carlyle By  L.  Maclean  Watt. 

Dante By  A.  G.  Ferrers  Howell. 


By  W.  T.  Waugh,  M.A. 

By  Arthur  Jon«s,  M.A 

By  G.  S.  Veitch,  M.A.,  Litt.D. 

By  M.  G.  Fawcett,  LL.D. 

By  E.  Fearenside,  B.A. 

By  Prof.  C.  Herford,  Litt.D. 


THE  FHOPLE'S  BOOKS— (Con/inMd).m\ 

..'il 

58.  Charles  Dickens By  Sidney  Dark. 

60.  A  Dictionary  of  Synonyms    .        ,        .  By  Austin  K.  Gray,  B.  A. 

61.  Home  Rule By  L.  G.  Redmond  Howard. 

62.  Practical  Astronomy      ....  By  H.  Macpherson,  Jr.,  F.R.A 

63.  Aviation By  S.  F.  Walker,  R.N.,  M.I.E. 

64.  Navigation By  William  Hall,  R.N.,  B.A. 

65.  Pond  Life By  E.  C  Ash,  M.R.A.C. 

66.  Dietetics By  Alex.  Bryce,  M.D.,  D.P.H. 

67.  Aristotle By  Prof.  A.  E.Taylor,  M. A.,  F.I 

68.  Friedrich  Nietzsche        .        .        .        .  By  M.  A.  Mugge. 

69.  Eucken :  Philosophy  of  Life .        .        .  By  A.  J.  Jones,  M.A.,  B.Sc.,  Pt 

70.  Experimental  Psychology  of  Beauty  .  By  C.  W.  Valentine,  B.A. 

71.  The  Problem  of  Truth    .        .        .        .  By  H.  Wildon  Carr. 

72.  Church  of  England By  Rev.  Canon  Masterman. 

73.  Anglo-Catholicism By  A.  E.  Manning- Foster. 

74.  Hopeand  Mission  of  the  Fr-ee  Churches  By  Rev.  Edward  bhillito,  M.A 

75.  Judaism By  Ephraim  Levine,  M.A. 

76.  Theosophy By  Annie  Besant. 

78.  Wellington  and  Waterloo     ...  By  Major  G.  W.  Redway. 

79.  Mediaeval  Socialism       ....  By  Bede  Jarrett,  O.P.,  M.A. 

80.  Syndicalism By  J.  H.  Harley,  M.A. 

82.  Co-operation By  Joseph  Clayton. 

83.  Insurance  as  a  Means  of  Investment .  By  W.  A.  Robertson,  F.F.A. 
85.  A  History  of  English  Literature .        .  ByA.Conipton-Rickett,M.A, 

87.  Charles  Lamb By  Flora  Masson. 

88.  Goethe By  Prof.  C.  H.  Herford,  Litt. 

92.  Training   of  the  Child:   A    Parents' \ r>„  r-   c«;tu. 

Manual |ByG.  Spiller. 

93.  Tennyson By  Aaron  Watson. 

94.  The  Nature  of  Mathematics         .        .  By  P.  E.  B.  Jourdain,  M.A. 

'=•  *¥iifh„"SV/aferr"f*^'"  .'""':}  By  Al=..„d=rOgilvi.,  B.Sc 

96.  Gardening By  A.  Cecil  Bartlett. 

97.  Vegetable  Gardening     ,        .        ,        .  By  J.  S.  Chisholm. 

98.  Atlas  of  the  World By  J,  Bartholomew,  F.R.G.S. 

loi.  Luther  and  the  Reformation         .        ,  By  Leonard  D.  Agate,  M.A. 

103.  Turkey  and  the  Eastern  Question       .  By  John  Macdonald,  M.A 

104.  Architecture  (108  Illustrations)     .        .  By  Mrs.  Arthur  Bell. 

105.  Trade  Unions By  Joseph  Clayton. 

106.  Everyday  Law By  J.  J.  Adams. 

107.  Robert  Louis  Stevenson        .        .        .By  Rosaline  Masson. 

108.  Shelley .By  Sydney  Waterlow,  M.A. 

110.  British  Birds By  F.  B.  Kirkman,  B.A. 

111.  Spiritualism By  J-  Arthur  Hill. 

XX2.  Kindergarten  Teaching  at  Home        .  {  %^^^,,%';^lr  °';^''  "" 

113.  Schopenhauer  .... 

114.  The  Stock  Exchange     . 

115.  Coleridge 

116.  The  Crusades  .... 

117.  Wild  Flowers  (209  Illustrations) 

118.  Principles  of  Logic 


119.  Foundations  of  Religion 

120.  A  History  of  Rome.        .     ^  . 

121.  Land,  Industry,  and  Taxation 

122.  Canada 

123.  Tolstoy 

124.  Greek  Literature     . 

125.  The  Navy  of  To-day 

128.  A  French  Self-Tutor 

129.  Germany    . 

130.  Treitschke 

131.  The  HohenzoUerns.  • 
X32.  Belgium  .... 
133.  The  British  Army   , 


By  Margrieta  Beer,  M.A. 

By  J.  F.  Wheeler. 

By  S.  L.  Bei&usan. 

By  M.  M.  C.  Calthrop. 

By  Macgregor  Skene,  B.Sc. 

By  Stanley  Williams,  B.A. 

By  Stanley  A.  Cook,  M.A. 

By  A.  F.  Giles,  M.A.(Edin.  &Ox 

By  Fredk.  Verinder. 

By  Ford  Fairford. 

By  L.  Winstanley,  M.A. 

By  H.  J.  W.  Tillyard,  M.A. 

By  Percival  H  islam. 

By  W.  M.  Conacher. 

By  W.  T.  Waugh,  M.A. 

By  M.  A.  Miigge. 

By  A.  D.  Innes. 

By  A.  W.  Evans. 

By  Captain  A.  H.  Atteridge. 


003604812020 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY 


B 

T27 
1919 
cop.  2 


Taylor,  Alfred  Edward 
Aristotle    Rev.  ed