Skip to main content

Full text of "Aristotle's criticisms of Plato"

See other formats


tL 


ἐθορς 


48 


ALISHSAINN VIHOLOIA 


VICTORIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARY 


TORONTO, ONTARIO 


SOURCE: 


ν᾿ τ 

Ἢ ‘ 
AN τις 

65 RR 
Date 


ARISTOTLE’S 
CRITICISMS OF PLATO 


BY THE LATE 


J. M. WATSON 


GUTHRIE SCHOLAR IN THE UNIVERSITY OF ST. ANDREWS 
HONORARY SCHOLAR OF ORIEL COLLEGE OXFORD 


HENRY FROWDE ) 
OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS 
LONDON NEW YORK TORONTO & MELBOURNE 


1009 


NOTE 


Tuts essay is published after much hesitation; for it 
is certain that Watson would not have wished it to appear 
in print. I discussed it with him shortly before his death 
in 1903, and I know that he regarded it as only a sketch, 
which he intended to work up during the next year or 
two. It must be remembered that he was only twenty- 
four when'‘he wrote it. Even so, however, it will be 
admitted that, if he has not answered the question with 
which he deals, he has asked it in the right way. Some 
readers will note stray indications of a solution rather 
different from the main position of the essay. 

Watson’s friends have decided to print his work, in 
order that some memorial may remain of a singularly 
gifted young man, to whom they were deeply attached. 
If he had lived, there can be no doubt that he would have 
been one of the first scholars of his day. 


JOHN BURNET. 


Witte tar 
aye, 
Oa oa 


ARISTOTLE’S CRITICISMS OF PLATO 


From the days of the Greek commentators onward, it 
_ has been a-standing charge against Aristotle that he did 
not understand his master’s philosophy. Syrian,’ for 
example, representing the Neoplatonists in general, says in 
grandiloquent language that Aristotle’s criticisms ‘no more 
affect the divine doctrines of Plato than the Thracian shafts 
reached the gods of heaven’. Similar reproaches are to be 
found in Simplicius and Philoponos. In modern times— 
to pass over the controversies before the eighteenth century 
—it has been repeatedly maintained that Aristotle first 
misunderstands his master’s teaching and then criticizes 
the result of his own misunderstandings. On the other 
hand, champions of Aristotle have not been wanting, though 
they are perhaps ina minority. Hegel,? the founder of all 
modern study of Aristotle, treats the supposition that 
Aristotle did not understand Plato as an altogether 
arbitrary and unfounded assumption ‘in view of Aristotle’s 
fine deep thoroughness of mind, perhaps no one knows 
him better’. 

The origin of this diversity of opinion is not far to seek. 
On the one hand, as ancient and modern commentators 
alike point out, Aristotle is constantly ‘ Platonizing*’. In 
his every work may be found, if not explicit approval or 
quotation of his master, at least innumerable reminiscences, 
conscious or unconscious, of Plato’s doctrine or language. 
But, on the other hand, Aristotle seems to criticize Plato 

* Syrian on Met. B. 997 Ὁ 5 sqq. (Aristotelis opera Berol. 1870, v, p. 849 a 32). 

* Hegel, Werke, xiii, p. 180. 


° Cf. Aristotelis Fragmenta, Rose, p. 432 (Teubner, 1886) ἤδη δὲ καὶ ἐν οἷς 
ἀντιλέγει Πλάτωνι πλατωνίζειν αὐτὸν φήσομεν κτλ, 


6 Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 


unfairly and pedantically. He misconceives the mythical 
character of the Z7maeus; he treats poetry as though it 
were science; he denies to Plato the credit of investigations 
and metaphysical discoveries in which, nevertheless, the 
master had at least foreshown the way to the pupil. More- 
over, in his attack on the Ideal theory especially, he has 
been thought to set up a straw man of his own making 
before proceeding to demolish it. It would seem then to 
be well worth inquiry, (a) how far such charges of mis- 
understanding and unfair criticism are justified; and (δ) how 
far the peculiar nature of Aristotle’s criticisms can be 
naturally and rationally explained. 

In entering on these questions, it would be of great 
service to know the exact order in which the works of 
Aristotle were written. Thus the chronological accuracy 
with which we can now’! trace the various utterances of 
Leibnitz in relation to Spinoza are most illuminating for 
the criticisms passed by the former on his great predecessor. 
But in the case of the Aristotelian Corpus a historico- 
chronological inquiry is complicated by cross-references 
and other difficulties, and as yet the few writers who have 
undertaken such an inquiry have been able to arrive only | 
at probabilities and approximations. The application of | 
stylistic methods could hardly be so important or fruitful 
here as it has been in the case of the Platonic dialogues: 
still the researches begun by Blass? are in the right 
direction. 

The dialogue Eudemus may be taken as one of Aristotle’s 
earliest writings. It seems to have been thoroughly 
Platonic, defending indeed, in the spirit of the Phaedo, a 
doctrine of personal immortality which Aristotle in maturer 


? Since Stein, Letbuits und Spinoza. 
2 F. Blass in Rhein, Mus. 30. He applies to Aristotle the test of avoidance 
of hiatus. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 7 


years, after his physical studies, did not see his way to 
accepting. The Eudemus and the Περὶ Φιλοσοφίας were 
probably written, though not necessarily published, while 
Plato still lived, and already in the latter dialogue we find 
Aristotle up in arms against the Platonic theory of Ideas. 
It is true that he is profoundly conscious of the enormous 
advance made in mathematics and philosophy during the 
Platonic age; such progress, he thinks, had been made in 
afew years that philosophy in a short time would be 
‘absolutely complete’. But even at this early period he 
has definitely broken away from the Platonic position ; he 
‘protested in the plainest terms that he could have no 
sympathy with this doctrine, even should his opposition be 
put down to a contentious spirit of rivalry’. Another 
passage, quoted by Syrian, shows that Aristotle had also 
already made up his mind on the untenability of the theory 
of Ideal numbers.?. Here too he decisively declared the 
world to be not only unending, but also without beginning 
intime.? Obviously ‘the reader’, ‘the mind of the school’, 
was to be no mere disciple in philosophy. 

To the same period must belong the notes which were 
taken by Aristotle, as by other pupils, of Plato’s lectures 
‘On the Good’ (Περὶ Τἀγαθοῦ). Even Aristotle seems to 
have found them obscure ὁ (ῥηθέντα αἰνιγματωδῶς) ; So we can 
well believe what he used to tell (del διηγεῖτο) of the utter 
perplexity with which an audience, that had come eagerly 
expecting to hear about happiness and human good, found 
itself listening to a lecture ‘on mathematics, numbers, 
geometry, astronomy, and finally that Good was One’.® 

1 Rose (Teubner), p. 27. 

2 Rose, p. 2]. This passage also is from the Second Book, which contained 
the criticism of Plato. The remarks on the advances in philosophy probably 
came in the First, though Rose gives them under the ‘ ndbnisudy cote v. Bywater 


in Journ. of Phil. vii. 
3 Rose, p. 33. * Rose, p. 41. δ Rose, p. 24. 


8 Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 


Aristotle had little sympathy with the later mathematical. 


The criticisms of Plato’s Ideal theory in the Metaphysics 
would probably be less perplexing had Aristotle’s Περὶ ᾿Ιδεῶν 
come down to us. Syrian,! it is true, says Aristotle had 
no arguments additional to those set forth in (ez. A and M, 
but the testimony of such a partisan is worth nothing ; and 
Alexander, commenting on Met. A. 9, has a different tale to 
tell.2 Unfortunately little or nothing is known as to the 
date of this ‘ Critique of Idealism’, though probably it too 
belongs to the first Athenian period. 

Perhaps the first work of the Aristotelian Corpus, as we 
now have it, is the Zopics. Here, at least in Books II-VI, 
we find everywhere Platonic expressions (e.g. μετέχειν») and a 
Platonic standpoint, not merely the Platonic soul-division, 
but even the Ideas (ἰδέαι) employed for the positive purpose 
of testing definitions. But, as has appeared above, he is 
already the antagonist of the Platonic theory of Ideas, and 
we find him in the Zofics supplying ‘points’ (τόποι) or 
‘ready arguments against the Idealists’ (τόποι χρήσιμοι πρὸς 
τοὺς τιθεμένους ἰδέας εἶναι). One of these, which occurs in 
the Soph. Εἰς is the famous argument of the ‘third man’ ® 
(τρίτος ἄνθρωπος) which Aristotle shows has no relevancy 
except where (as in the Ideal theory) the common predicate 
(τὸ κοινῇ κατηγορούμενον), e.g. ‘man’, is hypostasized into a 
particular (τόδε τὴ. Plato is mentioned by name four times 


1 Rose, p. 148, 

3 Vide especially on 991 a8 sqq., where Alexander reproduces from the Second 
Book of the Περὲ ᾿Ἰδεῶν a number of Aristotle’s arguments against the Ideal theory 
as held by Eudoxos, Some of these apply equally to the παρουσία of the Ideas 
on Plato’s theory. 

8. Top. 137 Ὁ ἃ, 147 a 5. * Ib. 143 Ὁ 11 544.) 148 a 14, 154 a 18. 

5 ¢, 22. 178 Ὁ 36. 

5 That we have here really the familiar ‘third man’ and not merely a sophistic 
quibble against the concept in general has been shown by Baumker, Rhein. Mus. 
34; ΡΡ. 73 544. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 9 


in the Tofics, but nowhere else in the whole Organon. In 
Post. An.‘ there is an explicit attack on the ἕν παρὰ τὰ πολλά, 
and the Ideas are once impatiently dismissed as mere 
Teperiopara,” 1. 6. they have more sound than sense. 

It is disputed whether the Organon is followed by the 
ethical or by the physical treatises. The former, Rose’s 
opinion, is more probable than Zeller’s, and at all events 
Eth. i. 6 reads as if it were early. Plato is referred to 
approvingly in the L/¢hics three times by name, twice 
without name,® while whatever may be thought of 
the criticism in i. 6, its intention obviously is to 
be conciliatory. MWe. A. g is the only passage where 
Aristotle, in speaking of the Academy, uses the first 
person plural and ranks himself as a Platonist,* and this 
probably means that he had not yet developed his own 
system. Met. A.g is known to be a rechauffé of the 
arguments of the Περὶ ᾿Ιδεῶν, and the latter is at all events 
quite early. 

There is no need to dwell on the later works. Three 
remarks may be made: (a) There are no direct criticisms 
whatever in the Rhetoric or Poetics, though in the latter 
especially they might be expected. The Ahetoric has an 
interesting notice of the exasperation felt bythe ‘partisans of 
the Idea’ (οἱ ἐπὶ τῇ ἰδέᾳ, sc. φιλοτιμούμενοι) at attacks on this 
favourite doctrine.’ (b) The relation of Metaphysics A. 9 
to its duplicate in M. 4 and 5 is still an unsolved problem. 
A. 9 has been thought later and more mature, because (e. g.) 
instead of saying that the Ideas are ‘ more in number’ ᾽ (πλείω) 
than the particular things of sense, A. 9 contents itself with 


ei, 1%. 77 a 5. 2 Ib. i. 22. 83 a 32. 

3 A. 4. 1095a 32. B.3.1104b12. Κ. 2. 1172b 28. Cf. E. τ. 1129a 6sqq., 
K. 9. 1180a 5 sqq. 

* τίθεμεν, οἰόμεθα, οὔ φαμεν, &c.: in Eth. i, 6 τὰ οἰκεῖα ἀναιρεῖν. The first 


person plural occurs also twice in Met. B. 997 Ὁ 3 and 1002 Ὁ 14, as if simply by 
reminiscence of A. . 


® Rhet. ii. 2. 1379 a 34. 


10 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


the more guarded phrase ‘just as many or at all events no 
fewer’ (ἴσα ἢ οὐκ ἐλάττω); still, even if in A. 9 we have the 
criticism of the Ideal theory in its final form, this does not 
exclude the very early date of most of the arguments. (ὦ It 
might be thought that the references to Plato would in all 
probability grow sharper and more unsympathetic as Aris- 
totle’s own system took definite shape. Thus the criticism 
of Plato in the last chapter of Book VIII of the Polttics is 
rather more direct, downright, and unceremonious than 
usual (e.g. 1316b 17 τοῦτο δ᾽ ἐστὶ ψεῦδος), and this chapter 
Newman thinks is of a ‘somewhat later date than the rest 
of the book’. Nevertheless, even in the Metaphysics, 
there is no perceptible change of tone, and Plato is 
mentioned by name and with approval no less than four 
times.' Chronology, in short, seems able on this question 
to yield little definite result. 


A. Aristotles Metaphysical Criticisms 


We pass at once then to the metaphysical criticisms, 
which are the most numerous and the most important. 
The difficulties here may be resolved into the following 
five problems :— 

(1) In Met. A. 6 Aristotle states as Plato’s a doctrine we 
should never have extracted from the Platonic dialogues 
alone. 

(2) The doctrine which Aristotle controverts is sometimes 
directly at variance with that of the Dialogues. Thus 
Aristotle says Plato made Ideas of natural things (ὁπόσα 


a κα Ἢ toro b 12, A. II. toga 4, E. 2. 1026b 14, A. 3. 1070 a 18, 

5 Certain methods of statistical inquiry might be useful, in answer e.g. to the 
questions :—(a@) what is the comparative frequency of Aristotle’s criticisms of 
Plato and of the Platonists, and also of the direct and the indirect references to 
Plato himself? (4) in what parts of Aristotle’s philosophy is the criticism 
sharpest, and where, if at all, is it silent? (c) how far are the criticisms in all 
¢ases, and in all the branches of philosophy, dialectical ? 


Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato II 


φύσει) to the exclusion of artificial products; he states, 
moreover, that orthodox Platonism? rejected Ideas of 
negations and (according to the usual interpretation) also 
of relations (ra πρός rx ).3 

(3) He attributes to Plato a doctrine of Ideal numbers, 
which (at least in the form stated) critics have found it 
hard to ascribe to Plato as a serious philosophical theory. 

(4) The centre of Aristotle’s attack is the transcendence 
of the Ideas (ἀδύνατον εἶναι χωρὶς τὴν οὐσίαν καὶ οὗ ἡ οὐσία)." 
Now it has been maintained (a) that Plato never held such 
a doctrine at all in Aristotle’s sense; or (6) that in a later 
stage of his thinking he recognized this defect in his meta- 
physic, and himself overcame and rejected the dualistic 
severance (τὸ χωρίζειν Met. M. 9. 1086b 4) of universal and 
particular. 

(5) Aristotle denies to Plato the recognition of final and 
efficient causes,° which nevertheless seem in the Dialogues 
to be ‘laid down with as much emphasis as by Aristotle 
himself ’.® 

The fourth problem deserves fuller statement. In the 
Parmenides the aged philosopher of that name criticizes 
with great earnestness a theory of Ideas which is unmis- 
takably that of the Republic and Phaedo. The difficulties 
urged against it are so serious that the Parmenides has 
again and again been declared spurious,’ on the ground 
that it is not given to any philosopher, however great, to 
overleap the limits of his own system, and that to ascribe 
it to Plato is to make of a single philosopher both Plato 


1 Met. A, 3. 10704 18. 2 Met. Α. 9. 990 Ὁ 11. 3 ggo b τό. 

#991 Ὁ τ. Cf. De Caelo i. 9, 278 a 16 εἴτε γὰρ ἔστιν εἴδη, καθάπερ φασίν τινες 
κτλι, εἴτε καὶ χωριστὸν μηθὲν τῶν τοιούτων, where the Platonic Idea and ὁ self- 
subsistence’ are interchangeable terms. 

5 Met. A. 9. 9928 24. δ R. G, Bury, Philebus, Introd., p. li. 

* Notably by Ueberweg and Ribbeck, the latter of whom says the Parm., 
signifies ‘den Umsturz der gesammten Platonischen Ideenlehre ’ (Phil. Monats- 
hefte xxiii, 1887). 


12 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


and Aristotle at once. But to waive this question for the 
moment, two points are all-important to notice for the 
present inquiry. (1) All the difficulties urged in the 
Parmenides arise from the absolute transcendence of the 
Ideas, their complete severance from the world of sense.’ 
This, in the first place (a) makes μέθεξις impossible ; for, 
whether participation takes place by whole or part, in 
either case the self-dependent unity of the Idea is sacri- 
ficed. Moreover, since αὐτομέγεθος e.g. is severed (xwpis) 
from τὰ πολλὰ μεγάλα, the latter may be compared with the 
former, and, it is asserted, another εἶδος μεγέθους is needed 
to make αὐτομέγεθος great.2 Secondly (6) it makes μίμησις 
also impossible ; for, if the Ideas are a second world (χωρὶς 
αἰτὰ καθ᾽ αὑτά, Parm. 129 4) and yet dike the particulars, there 
must be a third Idea or παράδειγμα to explain this likeness, 
and again we get an infinite regress.’ Thirdly (ὦ it makes 
knowledge impossible. A really noumenal world is 2250 
facto unknowable ; i. e. we cannot know God, and moreover 
the converse also is true, God cannot know us.* 

(2) The second point to be noted is the striking fact that 
Aristotle uses most of these identical arguments of the 
Parmenides, and yet never once refers to this dialogue, 
either when he reproduces its objections in Met. Aand Z, or 
in the whole course of his works. He twice employs the 
τρίτος ἄνθρωπος argument,®> he says the same Idea will be 
at once copy and type,® he points out by arguments similar 
to those of the Parmenides the impossibility of μέθεξις or 
mapovota,’ he asserts that the Ideas, being transcendent, do 
not explain knowledge.’ His contention that the Ideas 


: Cf. Parm. 129 ἃ, 130 Ὁ, d, 131 Ὁ, 133 a. * Parm, 132 a-b, 
: Parm., 132 d-e. * Parm. 133 Ὁ sqq. 
Met, A. 9. 990 b 17, Ζ. 13. 1039 a 2. δ Met. A. 9. 991 a 31. 


7 
Z. 14. 1039 a 26 sqq. ; cf. Parm. 131 a sqq., also Alexander on Met. A. 9. 
99" a 8 (Hayduck, p, 97. 27-98. 23) reproducing the Περὶ ᾿Ιδεῶν, 
A. 9. 991 a 12. 


A ristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 13 


contribute nothing whatever as the causes of phenomena! 
is merely a summing up of Plato’s conclusion that neither 
μέθεξις nor μίμησις is possible, if the Idea is χωρὶς αὐτὸ 
καθ᾽ ard. In fact, the chief Aristotelian objections are 
simply based on the absurdity in all its consequences of a 
common predicate which is at the same time substance 
(οὐσία), the absurdity of a ‘umztversal thing’, a καθόλου which 
is at the same time χωριστόν3 We seem forced, then, on 
the horns of a dilemma. Either Plato, in spite of the 
‘annihilating assaults’ (erundstirzende Linwdande*) of the 
Parmenides, did not, in his later system of metaphysics, 
abandon the transcendence of the Idea, or Aristotle is not 
merely guilty of plagiarism, but has grossly and unpardon- 
ably misrepresented his master’s teaching. It must appear 
in the sequel whether this dilemma is simply another 
instance of the dichotomous ‘ether... or’, which works 
so much havoc in philosophy. 

Doubtless the easiest method of solving all the problems 
is to assert that Aristotle misunderstood Plato and that 
there is no more to be said. But even were this asser- 
tion admitted, it would at least be necessary, following 
his own constant example, to show some plausible 
αἴτιον τῆς ἐκτροπῆς, Some reason for the ‘aberrations’ of an 
Aristotle.* The problem is not solved by ignoring it. We 
pass on then to consider various theories, which, in different 
ways, really attack the difficulty. 


First Problem 


It is natural to begin with Zeller’s Platontsche Studien, 
which, though published in 1839, still remains the best 
essay on this subject as a whole. Zeller is most helpful 
on the first of the problems above propounded. No one, 

ΟΣ ao. |: 3 Vide especially Met. M. 9. 1086 a 31 sqq. 


3 The phrase is Ueberweg’s. 
* Met. N. 2. 1089 a1. Cf. Politics ii. 5. 1263 b 30 αἴτιον τῆς παρακρούσεως, 


14 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


even after a complete course of the Platonic dialogues, 
including the Philebus and Timaeus, can come to Aristotle’s 
account of Plato’s philosophy in Me#. A. 6 without ex- 
periencing a shock of surprise, and it was Zeller’s great 
service to show that this chapter implied no esoteric 
Platonic doctrine, but could be explained partly from 
the dialogues themselves, partly from the precise and 
logical character of Aristotle’s thinking, which constantly 
strives after definite and clear connexion. 

On one particular point, according to Zeller, Aristotle 
has misinterpreted Plato. He has identified the matter of 
the world of sense (Space, the Unlimited, the ‘Great and 
the Small’) with the multiplicity, the non-being, the other- 
ness, which forms the material principle of the Idea. That 
is, he makes the One and the ‘Great and Small’ the ele- 
ments (στοιχεῖα) of the Ideas, and says they are at the same 
time the principles of reality (ἐπεὶ δ᾽ αἴτια τὰ εἴδη τοῖς ἄλλοις, 
τἀκείνων στοιχεῖα πάντων φήθη (Sc. Πλάτων) τῶν ὄντων εἶναι 
στοιχεῖα ἢ. This mistake, according to Zeller, is easily 
intelligible for two reasons. (1) Plato himself had talked 
of the Unlimited or ‘Great and Small’ in reference to the 
Ideas, and had not explained how this Unlimited was 
related to corporeal matter. (2) Aristotle’s view is meant 
to offer a solution of the fundamental difficulty in Plato’s 
philosophy, viz. that, from Plato’s standpoint, there is no 
possible way of deriving phenomena from the Ideas. 
But Aristotle’s solution—that Idea and phenomenon are 
composed of the same elements (crovyeia)—really cuts away 
the ground from under the whole Ideal theory. It renders 
the Ideas a superfluous second world, and makes easy 
Aristotle’s criticisms of the transcendence of the Ideas 
and the ‘Mathematicals’ (τὰ μεταξύ). In short, ‘this 
single alteration of Plato’s doctrine once admitted, we 

1 Met, A. 6. 987 b 18. 


oe = 


Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 15 


have the key to unlock all the more important differences’ 
between the metaphysical system of the dialogues and 
that of Mer, A. 6.1 

Dr. Jackson, in his valuable contributions towards the 
understanding of Plato’s later doctrine, seeks to disprove 
the opinion of Zeller that ‘ Aristotle has somewhat mis- 
apprehended Plato’.2, He comes to the rescue with a new 
interpretation of the Philebus.? It has long been a problem 
of Platonic interpretation where we are to find the Ideas 
in the division of all reality (πάντα τὰ νῦν ὄντα ἐν τῷ παντί, 
Phil. 23 c) given in that dialogue. Dr. Jackson proposes 
to find them in the third class of the division—the μικτὸν 
γένος, the same class as that in which the particular pheno- 
menon is included. This original suggestion is not so 
paradoxical as it might at first sight appear. The Philebus 
states explicitly that in all being there is present Limit 
(πέρας) and Unlimitedness (ἀπειρία) ; these, therefore, must 
appear in the Idea as well as in the sensible particulars, 
and the only question is, How is Idea differentiated from 
particular? Jackson answers that ‘while the indefinite 
matter (τὸ μᾶλλον καὶ τὸ ἧττον) is the same for the Idea and 
the particular, the πέρας or limitant quantity (τὸ ποσόν) of 
the particular differs from, but at the same time more or 
less approximates to, the limitant quantity (τὸ μέτριον) of the 
Idea, and the more sae the πέρας of the particular 
approximates to the πέρας of the Idea, the more closely 
the particular resembles the Idea’.® 

It will be seen that the special feature in this interpreta- 
tion is the distinction (in the exposition of Phil. 24 C sqq.) 


1 Zeller, Platonische Studien, p. 300, pp. 291 sqq. Also in Plato (E. T.), 
PP. 319 sqq. 

2 Plato (E.T.), p. 327. 

* Jackson’s articles are to be found in Journ, of Phil, x-xv, xxv. His treat- 
ment of the Philebus comes in vol. x, pp. 253-98, 

* Phil. τὸς. 5 Journ of Phil. x, p, 283. 


16 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


between τὸ ποσόν and τὸ μέτριον, the latter being the formal 
element of Ideas, and ra ocd the various formal elements 
ofthe particulars. Jackson finds this reading of the Philebus 
confirmed by Me. A. 6. By inventive exegesis and emen- 
dation of one refractory passage, he makes out (1) that 
τὸ μέγα καὶ τὸ μικρόν are the equivalent of the ‘more and 
less’ of the Philebus: (2) that τὸ ἐν καὶ of ἀριθμοί correspond 
to τὸ μέτριον καὶ τὰ ποσά : (3) that the ἐξ ὧν γίγνεται of Philebus 
(27 A) are the same as the στοιχεῖα of Met. A, and ‘ the ele- 
ments of the Ideas are the elements of all things’: (4) 
that the two elements are, both in Philebus and Met., the 
origin of good and evil respectively. In short, ‘the doctrine 
ascribed to Plato in Met. A. 6 is precisely the doctrine of 
the Philebus,’ 


It will be admitted that Jackson’s interpretation of this; 


one of the most abstract chapters in the whole Metaphysics, 
is much more ingenious than convincing. In fact it is 
a tour de force, and is at once seen to be so on any inves- 
tigation ofall the relevant passages.! Still this applies only 
to statement (2) in the above summary, and though for it 
little can be said, in his other identifications Jackson is, 
with certain reservations, entirely justified. One result he 
has certainly brought out with clearness. The Idea, which 
is usually thought of as simple and indivisible, undoubtedly 
appears in the classification of the Philebus—if it is meant 
to appear at all—as a compound, a result of μῖξις just as 
the concrete particular is. This is precisely how the Idea 
appeared to Aristotle, a compound of elements (στοιχεῖα). 


* In 987 Ὁ 21 he adds καὶ τοὺς ἀριθμούς after ὡς δ᾽ οὐσίαν τὸ ἕν, bracketing τοὺς, 
ἀριθμούς in Ὁ 23. His other emendations (Journ. of Phil. X, Pp. 294) are improve- 
ments, but the important one in b 21 contradicts the sense and the connexion. The 
στοιχεῖα are not the Great and Small, the One, and the numbers, but simply the 
Great and Small and the One (=the Idea of Good). He is further quite wrong 


in the assertion (x, p. 291 sq.) that the Idea in A. 6 except ὃ 9 (988 a ro) is not 
the formal cause but the type of the particular. 


se ee Ora Se 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 17 


And further, it seems incontrovertible that the Philebus 
favours Aristotle’s statement that the elements of the Ideas 
are in some sense or other the elements of all reality. 

But we must now consider Zeller’s theory more directly. 
Several objections may be urged against it :— 

τ, Aristotle asserts that the elements of the Ideas were 
to Plato the elements of all things. But he nowhere says 
these elements are identical for the Ideas and for pheno- 
mena. Not one of the passages adduced by Zeller can be 
said to prove this ; some of them are decisively against any 
such supposition. Thus in Phys. A. 2, after showing that 
Plato identified space with matter, and remarking that the 
matter (ὕλη) of the 77zmaeus is different from that described 
in the ‘unwritten doctrines’ (ἄγραφα δόγματα), Aristotle pro- 
ceeds: ‘Plato however... must state why the Ideas, i.e. 
the numbers, are not in space. For his teaching is that the 
participant and space are interchangeable terms, whether 
the participant be the great and small’ (according to the 
᾿ ἄγραφα δόγματα) or ὕλη, ‘as he has written in the 7zmaeus’. 

According to Zeller, this reproach presupposes that the 
matter of the Ideas is identical with the matter of the 
material world, i.e. space. But surely had Aristotle ever 
meant that space was the matter of the Ideas, he would 
have said so, and not taken the roundabout method of the 
above quotation in order to establish his point. He would 
not have introduced the objection in the way he does, as 
if it were a consideration that might have escaped Plato’s 
notice, but would simply have said, ‘Space is a στοιχεῖον of 
the Ideas: hence the Ideas must be spatial’. As it is, he 
proceeds to justify his reproach, which on Zeller’s view he 
certainly would not require todo. His proof is as follows: 
Plato identifies τὸ μεταληπτικόν with space: now τὸ μεταλη- 
πτικόν participates in the Ideas; .-. space participates in the 
Ideas ; ,". the Ideas must be spatial. In fact, therefore, this 

B 


18 Artstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


passage, so strongly relied on by Zeller, really goes against 
his view. It expressly distinguishes the ‘space’ of the 
Timaeus from the later material principle, viz. ‘the Great 
and the Small’, which Plato had laid down in his lectures. 

Similarly in Phys. iii. 6," we read: ‘If the Great and 
Small is the encompassing principle in the sensible and 
intelligible world alike, then it ought to comprehend the 
intelligible world’. Simplicius? explains quite satisfac- 
torily. According to Aristotle, the infinite οὐ περιέχει ἀλλὰ 
περιέχεται, and qua infinite, it is ἄγνωστον. Now Plato 
admits that ‘the Great and the Small’ in the sensible 
world (i.e. space) περιέχει τὰ αἰσθητά, and therefore makes 
them unknowable. He ought to admit then that the 
‘Great and Small’ in the intelligible world also περιέχει 
(sc. τὰ vonré) and therefore makes the intelligible world 
‘unknowable’. This conclusion is absurd, since it is the 
very nature of νοητά to be knowable. 

The tentative tone of both of these passages would be 
quite unintelligible had Aristotle believed in the identity of 
‘the unlimited’ in sensibles with ‘the unlimited’ in Ideas. 
Consequently when in Phys. ill. 4,3 we read that Plato’s 
ἄπειρον ‘existed both in the world of sense and in the 
Ideas’, there is no reason to conclude that this ἄπειρον is 
for both numerically the same. In Met. A. 6. 988 a το, 
Aristotle states that the Ideas result from two causes: 
formal—ro ἕν, material—the Great and the Small. Pheno- 
mena also arise from two causes: formal—the Ideas, 
material—the Great and the Small. Now, were the 
material cause identical for both Idea and phenomenon, 
this passage would mean that the Ideas, which determine 
the Great-and-Small, are yet themselves partly the result 
of that Great-and-Small, a contradiction which there is as 
little reason for attributing to Aristotle as to Plato. 

207 ἃ 29. 2 Schol. 368 a 28. 5 203 a 9. 


| 


᾿ 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 19 


2. Further, it has not escaped notice that while Aristotle 
speaks of ‘the Indeterminate Dyad’ as the material prin- 
ciple of numbers, he never applies this phrase to the 
material principle either of geometrical magnitudes or of 
the physical world. Zeller, indeed, while admitting this, 
says the Indeterminate Dyad is simply the Great-and- 
Small ‘numerically expressed’. But here is the whole 
point. Aristotle expressly distinguishes species? of the 
Great and Small; one of these species (a) (rd πολὺ καὶ τὸ 
ὀλίγον, Met. N. 1. 1088 a 19) is the material principle of the 
Ideal, as also of the mathematical numbers, and is other- 
wise called ‘the Indeterminate Dyad’. Another species 
(ὁ), the ‘ Great-and-Small’ properly speaking, is the material 
element of geometrical magnitudes. As ‘Great and Small’ 
is also the generic name for the material principle, Aristotle 
can use the phrase both for (a) the indeterminate dyad, and 
for (6) the Great-and-Small of magnitudes ;? but he never 
conversely uses the phrase ‘the Indeterminate Dyad’ in 
reference to both. 

still another species (c) of the Great-and-Small might be 
looked for, viz. the material principle of phenomena, the 
empty space (τὸ τῆς χώρας) of the Zzmaeus. But the his- 
torian of the problem of matter in Greek philosophy ὃ has 
shown that Plato in his later thinking, under Pythagorean 
influence, probably subsumed the space of the Zimaeus 
under the more comprehensive category of τὸ ἄπειρον, or, 
as he said in his lectures, ‘the Great and the Small’. ‘The 
Platonic system advances ever further in the way of 

1 Met. M. 9. 1085 a 9-12. 

? The passage (Met. N. 2. 1089 a 35 οὐ γὰρ δὴ ἡ δυὰς ἡ ἀόριστος αἰτία οὐδὲ τὸ μέγα 
καὶ τὸ μικρὸν τοῦ δύο λευκὰ κτλ.) would be conclusive that Aristotle was careful to 
distinguish these two, were it not for the unfortunate ambiguity by which οὐδὲ 
like «at may merely be explicative ‘that is’, As it is, therefore, we should 
render : ‘It is not the indeterminate dyad (species) nor in short the great-and- 


small (genus) that can explain’ &c. 
" Ὁ, Baumker, Das Problem der Materie, p. τοῦ sqq. 


B 2 


20 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


resolving the physical and the concrete into metaphysical 
and mathematical abstractions.’ In the striking phrase 
of one of the Greek commentators, Plato had completely 
‘mathematicized nature’ ᾽ (κατεμαθηματικεύσατο τὴν pvcw).? This 
is why Aristotle objects to Plato’s ‘great and small’ that it 
is ‘too mathematical a substrate’ (μαθηματικωτέρα ὕλη) ; it 
may explain mathematical magnitudes but not physical 
bodies (ὕλη ἀσώματος). ὃ 

Aristotle, then, cannot be charged, in his account of 
Plato, with annulling ‘the distinction between the Un- 
limited in Space and that plurality which is also in the 
Ideas ’.* 

3. Again it should be noted that one of Zeller’s main 
reasons for rejecting Aristotle’s testimony about the de- 
rivation of all things from the principles of the Ideas, is 
simply his own preconceived theory as to the relation 
of particular and Idea in the Platonic system. Zeller 
thinks the particular is, or was meant to be, ‘absolutely 
immanent in the Idea,’ the latter being the sole reality. 
This, according to Zeller, enables Plato to escape such 
difficulties as those raised in the Parmenides.© But now 
comes the question: Whence the distinction of things 
from the Ideas? and to this ‘the Platonic system, as 
such, contains no answer’.6 There is an ‘inextricable 
contradiction’ between the absolute reality of the Idea 
alone, and the admission, nevertheless, of ‘a kind of 
existence that cannot be derived from the Idea’. 

Now this view seems but one result of the radical mis- 
conception which vitiates Zeller’s account of the whole 
Platonic philosophy. He attempts, that is, to deal with 

* Ibid. p, 197. 

* Quoted by Gomperz, Griechische Denker, vol. ii (on Plato’s Matter, p. 606 n.). 

* A. 9. 992 b2; A, 7. 988 a 25; cf. N. 2. 1089 a 32- 1. 


* Zeller, Plato, E. T., p. 332. 5 Plato, E. T., p. 333. 
® Plato, p. 319. " Plato, p. 333. Similarly in Plat. Stud. 296 sqq. 


Artstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 21 


the dialogues as one whole, and as furnishing one fixed 
and immutable system. He still does not accept a later 
date for the great metaphysical dialogues—Parmenides, 
Sophist, Philebus. Yet in these later dialogues there seem 
to be various attempts made at a derivation of the sensible 
from the Idea, and one of these is by the method of identity 
of elements. We have seen this already in the case of the 
Philebus ; in more abstract phraseology a similar doctrine 
appears already in Parmenides 142 D. Here Plato shows 
that the whole universe contains as aspects (μόρια) unity 
and existence (τὸ ἐν καὶ τὸ εἶναι), and so likewise does every 
smallest part of the universe contain these same two ele- 
ments, or ‘parts’, of ideality and reality. This whole 
question belongs strictly to a history of Plato’s later 
metaphysics; all that need here be insisted on is that 
Aristotle has not been proved guilty of any such funda- 
mental misapprehension as is implied by Zeller’s theory. 
4. Finally, it should be noted that Xenokrates, ὁ γνησιώ- 
τατος τῶν Πλάτωνος ἀκροατῶν, accepted the doctrine of first 
principles which Aristotle ascribes to Plato, and derived 
all things from Unity and Indeterminate Duality. Speu- 
sippos, indeed, derived merely numbers from Unity and 
plurality, and, unlike Plato, for the explanation of everything 
else he set up several distinct principles. But it was 
precisely for this reason that Aristotle reproached him 
with making the Universe like a bad tragedy ‘fragmentary 
and ‘ episodic’ (ἐπεισοδιώδη τὴν τοῦ παντὸς οὐσίαν ποιοῦσιν). 


Second Problem. 


To turn now to the second main problem. Zeller, in 
_ Platonische Studien, had treated Aristotle’s statements as 
to the contents of the world of Ideas as merely mistaken. 
Similarly Bonitz on Met. A. 9, where Aristotle is thought 
to state that orthodox Platonism did not admit Ideas of 


22 Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 


relations, is highly indignant with Aristotle for alleged 
unfairness in argument.1 Zeller, by the time he wrote his 
History, had come to see that the only satisfactory way of 
accounting for Aristotle’s words in the Metaphysics was to 
suppose Plato had actually made these changes. But 
even there Zeller suggests no rationale of them; ‘the 
original point of view was in these cases abandoned’; 
in other words, they were arbitrary modifications.’ 

Now Dr. Jackson seeks to make good this deficiency in 
Zeller by showing how Plato, in a ‘radical reconstruction 
of his system’ initiated by the Parmenides, was led naturally 
and inevitably in his ‘second theory of Ideas’ not only to 
the doctrine of Met. A. 6, and the transcendency (ἰδέαι 
xeptorat) of which Aristotle complains, but also to the 
retrenchment and revision of his list of Ideas. According 
to Jackson, in Plato’s later theory there are no Ideas of 
relations (6. g. ὅμοιον ἀνόμοιον, &c.) ‘nor presumably of ἀγαθόν, 
xaxdv’.® ‘Accordingly the Zimaeus recognizes αὐτὰ καθ᾽ 
αὑτὰ εἴδη of the four elements and of the several species of 
animal and vegetable, but of nothing else.’ 

That the Ideal theory of the Phaedo and Republic under- 
went considerable modification after the Parmenides can 
no longer be regarded as doubtful. But as to the parti- 
cular form of the reconstruction, Jackson is, in some 
respects, unfortunate. We must consider briefly his two 
central positions (1) the substitution by Plato of μίμησις 
and transcendence for μέθεξις and immanence, and (2) the 
retrenchment by Plato of the list of εἴδη. 


As to (1) at least three insuperable difficulties have been 
pointed out. 


* Bonitz, Metaph. ii, p. 111. He thinks Aristotle is refuting Plato by means 
of contemporary Platonism. Really this is one among many passages which 
show conclusively that Aristotle is not thinking directly of Plato at all. 

? Zeller, Plato, E. T., p. 275. 


* Jackson, Journ. of Phil. xiii, p. 271. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 23 


(2) The metaphor of μέθεξις is not altogether dropped in 
dialogues admittedly later than the Parmenides.' It is 
true that Jackson’s theory does allow of μέθεξις to a certain 
extent, but only because he makes an arbitrary and 
untenable distinction between εἴδη and αὐτὰ καθ᾽ αὑτὰ εἴδη.2 

(ὁ) The substitution of the Idea as παράδειγμα or archetype 
does not, as Jackson supposes, avert the objections urged 
against the Ideal theory in the Parmenides. The relation 
between archetype and copy cannot possibly be any other 
than that of resemblance, and hence the attempted solution 
by μίμησις (ὁμοιοῦσθαι, ἐοικέναι, εἰκασθῆναι) lends itself (equally 
with the metaphor of μέθεξις) to the objection of the ‘third 
man’. Moreover, for describing the relation of particular 
to universal, μίμησις is, as Hegel says, a ‘more figurative, 
childish, and untutored expression’ than μέθεξις. 

(c) The new view of the Idea as archetype is not a theory 
alternative to that of μέθεξις, but is clearly described, in 
Parmenides 132 1), as merely a special case of it. Aristotle 
also joins them both in a single condemnation. 

(2) Jackson’s theory that Plato restricted Ideas to 
‘natural kinds’ is (in Aristotelian phrase) ‘still more im- 
possible’. In the first place (a2) such a theory is directly 
opposed to the natural interpretation of Parmenides 130B-E. 
In this, one of the most striking passages of the dialogue, 
Ideas of relations are postulated first in order, even before 
Ideas of qualities, and it is precisely with organic types 
(e.g. man) and the primary forms of matter (fire, water) 
that doubt and difficulty (ἀπορία) first arise. The explicit 
testimony of this passage must far outweigh a mere 

1 e.g. Soph. 255 A; Tim. 51 A. 


? It will be found stated by Jackson in Journ. of Phil. xi, p. 322 n. ; cf. xiv, 
4. 
Ρ 3 Η, \ ἈΝ Υ͂ “ > \ ν 2 \ , + OSE | 
et. A. 9. 991 a 20 τὸ δὲ λέγειν παραδείγματα αὐτὰ εἶναι Kal μετέχειν αὐτῶν 
τἄλλα κενολογεῖν ἐστίν κτλ. 
* ἔτι ἀδυνατώτερον. 


24 Aristoile’s Criticisms of Plato 


inference from Jackson’s interpretation of the difficult sen- 
tence with which the Parmenides closes.’ 

Morover this, the natural interpretation of the Parmenides, 
is alone consonant with the whole course of Plato’s Idealism. 
As has been pertinently said,’ the ‘Auto-bug’ was not of 
more importance in Plato’s scheme of the universe than 
the αὐτόκαλον or the αὐτοάγαθον. The αὐτοκολοκύντη or the 
adroddyavor,s which the comic poets or a Stilpo took as ex- 
amples for the ridicule or the refutation of the Ideal theory, 
were not, we may be certain, put by Plato on the same 
level as Ideas of relations and qualities. 

Secondly (ὁ) the dialogues later than the Parmenides 
present various difficulties on Jackson’s theory. Thus in 
Philebus 15 A, besides Ideas of man and ox, we have also 
those of τὸ καλόν and τὸ ἀγαθόν, and in the Zzmaeus the 
words εἶδος ἑκάστου νοητόν (51 C) naturally mean ‘an Idea for 
every universal ’.4 | 

Thirdly (c) there is absolutely no warrant for refusing to 
recognize as Ideas the categories or γένη of the Sophist. 

Certainly not then by this theory can Plato’s later doc- 
trine be brought into line with the Aristotelian references. 

The very antithesis of Jackson’s view, in many ways, is 
that maintained by the late Professor D. G. Ritchie.® 
According to it also, the Parmenides ushers in a ‘second 


1 Journ. of Phil. xi, p. 322. 

? A. E. Taylor in Mind 1896, p. 304. 

* Epikrates, in his amusing description of a Platonic διαίρεσις. 

* Cf. Parm, 135 Β εἶδος ἑνὸς ἑκάστου, 135 E ἰδέαν τῶν ὄντων ἑκάστους It is 
mere dogmatism in support of a theory when Archer-Hind says of the words in 
the Timaeus ‘we are to understand by ἑκάστου only every class naturally 
determined, τῶν ὁπόσα pice’. It is only a natural extension of such subjective 
interpretation when he thinks Ideas ought to be confined to classes of living 
things, and therefore says of the Idea of fire (Zim. 51 B) “we have in this 
passage a relic of the older theory which Plato... would have eliminated had his 
attention been drawn to the subject’. ' 

5 Plato in the ‘World’s Epoch Makers’ Series. Also in a paper on the 
Parmenides in ‘ Bibliothéque du Congrés International de Philosophie’. 


A ristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 25 


theory of Ideas’. But in this second theory the Ideas are 
not cut down ; rather they are extended to the whole field 
of the knowable, according to the philosophic advice of 
Parmenides to ‘despise none of these things’ (οὐδὲν αὐτῶν 
ἀτιμάζειν, Parm. 130 E). Further, the transcendence of the 
Ideas is not increased ; it is recognized as the defect of the 
earlier theory, and endeavours are made to overcome it. 

How then does this theory explain the hostile criticism 
of Aristotle? The answer is: (a) It was probably owing 
to the objections of his brilliant pupil (who had come to 
the Academy in 367, and to whom there is perhaps a kindly 
allusion in the Parmenides itself!) that Plato was led to 
reconsider his earlier theory. The criticisms in the 
Parmenides were those of Aristotle to start with; hence 
he can dispense with referring to that dialogue, while using 
its arguments. 

(ὁ) It is not Plato himself that is attacked, but disciples 
of Plato, who had not advanced along with him after his 
self-criticism in the Parmenides. 

(c) The criticism of the Ideal numbers is directed against 
Speusippos, to whose Pythagorizing tendencies Aristotle 
makes express allusion. 

(zd) It is in the main not the later but the earlier form of 
the Ideal theory that is attacked. As for the remark about 
Ideas of relations, Aristotle has been misinterpreted. 

Σκεπτέον δὲ πάλιν τί τούτων λέγεται καλῶς καὶ τί od KadGs.2 Of 
the theory as a whole it may be said, as by Aristotle on 
the community of goods in the Republic, that it ‘wears 
a plausible look’ and ‘the student welcomes it with delight’ 
(ἄσμενος ἀποδέχεται).. Nevertheless, though it may not, in 


ἵν, Parm. 135 D, 137 B-C (ὁ vewraros) on the other hand, while Aristotle is 
, still alluded to, the words ἥκιστα γὰρ ἂν πολυπραγμονοῖ may be regarded as a fine 
stroke of irony on Plato’s part. 

* De Coelo i. 9. 278 a 23. 


26 Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 


Aristotle’s phrase, be πόμπαν ἀδύνατος, it must be admitted 
to leave as many difficulties as it solves. Though at the 
risk of considerable digression, its main propositions have 
here been stated together. 

The first of these (a) does not admit of definite proof or 
disproof. Aristotle’s complete silence on the Parmenides 
certainly demands explanation; nor is it adequate to say 
either (like Apelt) that Aristotle did not attach to that 
dialogue the same exaggerated importance as the Neo- 
platonists and the moderns, or even (with Zeller’) that ‘the 
writings of Plato had’ not ‘ the same significance, as sources 
of his doctrine, for Aristotle as for us’.? Zeller’s remark, 
as we shall see, is perfectly correct, and must always be 
borne in mind. But surely it is more than a mere coinci- 
dence that the only important dialogue—indeed almost the 
only dialogue of Plato—to which no reference can be found 
in Aristotle, should be precisely the work which contains 
several of Aristotle’s own arguments against that Ideal 
theory of which he was the life-long opponent. 

In any case, however, whatever solution of Aristotle’s 
silence be accepted, he can at once be acquitted of any 
charge of plagiarism. All the ἀπορίαι against the Ideas 
are perfectly natural, once phenomenon and Idea are set 
over against each other as two independent ‘things’. The 
τρίτος ἄνθρωπος, whichis the one distinctive argument common 
to both Parmenides and Metaphysics, would arise inevitably 
among Greek thinkers, who had a horror of the infinite 
process and a passion for refutation by means of it. More- 
over, the honour of excogitating the ‘third man’ seems to 


1 Plato, E. T., p. 77. 

κ The criticisms in the Parmenides may be regarded as suggested by Aristotle, 
but it may be held that Plato was so far from being convinced by them that he 
occupies himself in this and later dialogues with criticizing his critic. v. Siebeck, 


‘ Platon als Kritiker aristotelischer Ansichten, in Zeitschrift fiir Philosophie etc., 
vol. cvii, cviii (1896 e¢ sqq.). 


Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 27 


belong neither to Plato nor to Aristotle.1 Alexander, 
commenting on 7716’. A. 9, tells us that ‘ Polyxenos the 
Sophist’ introduced this argument, and he proceeds to 
state it in Polyxenos’ own words. Now Baumker? has 
shown that it is just the argument of the Parmenizdes, and 
that the reason why, according to Polyxenos, a ¢hird man 
must be assumed is exactly the ground which induced 
Plato himself to set up a second or Ideal man. Polyxenos 
was a contemporary of Plato; the latter takes up his 
argument in the Parmenides, and shows it is valid as 
against one form of the Ideal theory; and the very method 
of allusion to it in Aristotle shows it had long been common 
property and a familiar argument of the schools.® 

The second contention of the theory (0) is in part a 
familiar one. Already Lotze had said :—‘ we are justified 
. .. in assuming that Aristotle’s attack is in part directed 
against certain misunderstandings of the Platonic doctrine 
which had gained hold in the Academy at an early period ’.* 
It has, however, the advantage over Lotze’s view that it 
does not force us to ascribe to the Platonists a doctrine 
which their master had never held at all.6 It is a theory 
which certainly represents a part of the truth. But as a 
complete explanation it is open to the insuperable objection 
that Aristotle himself is totally unaware of any such 
‘divergence between the master and his school’. Had he 

1 In Rep. x and Tim. 31A it is proved that there can be only one Ideal bed 
and one αὐτόζῳον because a second would involve a third, and soon. But in 
the Parmenides (τρίτος ἄνθρωπος) it is not Ideas themselves that are spoken of but 
Ideas are compared with ‘things’. 

2 Rhein. Mus. xxxiv, p. 73 544. (1879). 

3 Moreover Aristotle nowhere claims any of the objections as senecdaili his 
own, and it is of the very essence of ἀπορίαι to be σύγκλυδες, v. infra, pp. 121-2. 

* Logic, E. T., p. 444 (ed. 1884). 

5 Jackson finds an appeal from the Platonists to Plato in A. 9. 990 b 15 
οἱ ἀκριβέστεροι τῶν λόγων κτλ. But he does not explain (@) why the Republic, 


Phaedo, and Parmenides should be honoured with the description of ἀκρι- 
βέστεροι, nor (δ) how λόγοι in the context can mean ‘expositions’. 


28 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


known of such, it is incredible that he could have missed 
the opportunity of appealing from the Platonists to Plato 
himself, from the εἰδῶν φίλοι to the author of the Parmenides 
and the Sophist. This is precisely what he does do on 
the question of the Ideal numbers; he commends the 
doctrine of the master as against those who denied the Ideas 

and retained only the ‘ Mathematicals’ (ra μαθηματικα).1 
The third proposition (c) must be rejected 7 foto. How- 
ever difficult this problem of the Ideal numbers, there is 
no doubt whatever that Aristotle assigns the theory to 
Plato. Itis true that in Metaphysics M. 4, Aristotle proposes 
first to examine the doctrine of Ideas by itself, without the 
Ideal numbers, ‘in the form it assumed originally (os 
ὑπέλαβον ἐξ ἀρχῆς) with those who first asserted the existence 
of the Ideas’. But this only proves that the theory belongs 
to Plato’s later development ; and from De An. A. 2 (where 
τὰ περὶ φιλοσοφίας λεγόμενα 2 have no reference to any work of 
Aristotle, but are simply notes of Plato’s lectures, of the 
same nature as the ἄγραφα δόγματα) we see that Aristotle, as 
usual, is speaking from personal reminiscence of Plato’s 
teaching. Not to insist on Met. A. 6, where Plato is 
compared with the Pythagoreans for making ‘the numbers’ 
(τοὺς ἀριθμούς) ‘causes of the existence of other things’, or 
on the similar passage at the end of A. 8, the locus classicus 
in Met. M. 8. 1083 a 32 sqq. is quite conclusive. Here 
Plato is mentioned by name, the Ideal numbers (οὐ συμβλητοί) 
are ascribed to him, and his opinion expressly distinguished 
from that of ἕτεροί τινες (perhaps Xenokrates) who maintained 
the existence simply of the mathematical numbers. Plato 
is named also in Phys. iii. 6, where it is said that though 
aa ὀβρηερῦ (ἄπειρο) ἃ ἄγβο, ΒΕ ὅσον a ee 
7 Maen oe ie ; me Ameria there is neither the infinite 
; er one being the smallest, nor the 

} Met, M. 8. 1083 a 22. 2 404 Ὁ 19. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 29 


infinite of increase, since he makes number go only as 
far as ten’. The reference here must be to the Ideal 
numbers. The evidence, therefore, that Plato held such 
a view is ample, even though there be no trace of the 
Ideal numbers in the dialogues. 

The fourth position (d) as a whole falls to be examined 
later. Here we are only concerned strictly with Aristotle’s 
statements about the contents of the world of Ideas. 
Obviously if Aristotle says his antagonists do not recognize 
Ideas of relations, negations or arfe facta, it can hardly be 
the earlier theory of Ideas he is attacking, and Professor 
Ritchie’s contention would fall to the ground, 

(1) As to Aristotle’s supposed statement, however, about 
Ideas of relations, the theory is justified in suggesting a 
new interpretation. The more this alleged dictum of 
Aristotle (Jet. A. 9. 990 Ὁ 15, 16) is considered in the light 
not merely of the Platonic dialogues, but even more in 
reference to other passages of Aristotle himself, the more 
strange it will appear. 

(2) The Platonic Ideal theory, after the vision of αὐτὸ 
τὸ καλόν in the Symposium, had been extended, in the 
Phaedo, to Ideas of relation. They at all periods form 
Plato’s favourite type of example to illustrate his theory 
(Phaedo, Republic, Theaetetus, Sophist), and in the all-impor- 
tant passage of the Parmenides’ they are selected by 
Socrates as examples of the first class of εἴδη, those in 
which he has the most implicit confidence. Moreover, since 
Aristotle, with his table of categories, does not avoid 
confusing relations with qualities,’ it is certain that Plato 
would not escape this confusion, and this is confirmed by 


1 130 B-E. 
2 Modern logic tends to see in qualities nothing but disguised relations; to 
Aristotle relations are a special kind of qualities. But he does not keep them 


apart, v. Zeller, Aristotle, E. T., i, p. 287. 


30 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


the dialogues. Consequently, once reject the αὐτόισον and 
the αὐτόκαλον will hardly escape the same condemnation. 
Is it then credible that Plato or even the Platonists should 
ever have rejected Ideas of relation ? 

But (4) even greater difficulties are suggested by 
Aristotle’s own writings. In Categories 7, we find as 
examples of τὰ πρός τι such concepts as τὸ μέγα, τὸ 
διπλάσιον, τὸ ἴσον, ἀρετή, ἐπιστήμη, δεσπότης, δοῦλος. To pass 
over the fact that Ideas of every one of these concepts are 
to be found in the Platonic dialogues, is it not more than 
strange, on the ordinary interpretation of the passage Med. 
A.g. 990 b 16, that Aristotle after stating that the Platonists 
reject Ideas of relations should, only a few lines further on, 
take as an example of the Ideas he is combating, no other 
than the αὐτοδιπλάσιον 1 ὃ Further, the object of the whole 
discussion from A. 9. 990 Ὁ 22 to ggt a 8 is to show that, on 
the basis of what the Platonists say about μέθεξις, there can 
be Ideas only of οὐσία. Had the Platonists repudiated 
Ideas of relations, Aristotle, as has been indicated above, 
would scarce have needed all this elaborate argument to 
show that Ideas of qualities ought to be likewise dis- 
carded. 

In an interesting passage of the Physics (B. 2. 193 b 34 
sqq.) Aristotle, discussing how the mathematician differs 
from the physicist, says the former uses abstractions (χωρίζει) 
but is justified in so doing (οὐδὲ γίνεται ψεῦδος χωριζόντων), 
The advocates of the Ideas (οἱ rds ἰδέας λέγοντες), Aristotle 
continues, fail to see that they too are guilty of abstraction, 
only without the excuse of the mathematician. They 
abstract, that is, the objects of Physics.2 Now odd and 
even, straight and curved, number, line, &c., can be 
abstracted from motion and sense perception, but this 


? 990 Ὁ 32. 
2 \ Ν , Μ 
τὰ φυσικὰ χωρίζουσιν ἧττον ὄντα χωριστὰ τῶν μαθηματικῶν. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 31 


ceases to be possible in dealing with bone, flesh, man. 
This passage makes it almost unthinkable that the con- 
temporary Academy had given up Ideas of relations. 
Moreover, it can be parallelled by at least two other 
passages in the Metaphysics. In ©. 8 Aristotle says the 
Platonic dialecticians (οἱ ἐν rots λόγοις) are easily convicted of 
philosophic ineptitude by the very fact of their positing 
Ideas of κίνησις and ἐπιστήμη. To crown all, in Met. N. 1. 
1088 a 21 sqq., the Platonists are sharply taken to task for 
turning relations into substances.... ‘It is absurd, 
nay rather it is impossible, to make the non-substantial a 
principle of, and prior to, the substantial; for all other 
categories are posterior to substance.’ 

These passages seem to show that in JMe#. A. 9, where 
Aristotle says ‘Some of the more precise arguments to 
prove the existence of Ideas result in the setting up of 
Ideas of τὰ πρός τι, Sv οὔ φαμεν εἶναι καθ᾽ αὑτὸ yévos’, these last 
words cannot be translated (as by Jackson) ‘relations, 
whereof we Platonists do not recognize Ideas’. The 
authority of Alexander’! cannot be appealed to on this 
passage, as his commentary here is not only obscure and 
extremely doubtful otherwise, but also self-contradictory. 
He asserts that the Platonists denied Ideas of relations, 
because, whereas the Ideas were οὐσίαι and self-subsistent, 
relations had their being only in ἡ πρὸς ἄλληλα σχέσις. This, 
however, is after reproducing an argument (presumably 
Platonic) which ‘establishes Ideas of relations’, an argument, 
in fact, which proves the existence of an αὐτόισον, just as 
Plato himself might have done. The Platonists (it would 
seem to follow from Alexander’s explanation) took no little 
pains to establish the existence of Ideas of relations by an 
ἀκριβέστερος λόγος, and at the same time extruded all such 


1 p. 82, 11-83. 33 (Hayduck). 


32 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


Ideas from their system. Obviously a new interpretation 
is demanded. 

The clue seems to be supplied by a comparison of our 
passage with 7h. Nic. i. 6, taken in connexion with the 
fact known about Xenokrates that he admitted only two 
categories, the absolute and the relative? In Eu. i. 6. 
1096 b 8 Aristotle ‘describes a possible objection’ to his 
previous criticisms. The objection may be represented 
thus : ‘You overlook the fact’ (the Platonists retort on 
Aristotle) ‘that we do not acknowledge Ideas of relative 
goods (e. g. fire, clothing, wine) but only Ideas of absolute 
goods’, — 

Now with this passage in mind, Aristotle’s argument in 
Met. A.9, may be paraphrased thus: ‘Some of the more 
unimpeachable and rigorous arguments (ἀκριβέστεροι λόγοι) 
of the Platonists to prove the existence of Ideas are forced 
to include, among the Ideas thus established, Ideas of 
things that belong to the Academic category of ‘the relative’ 
(τῶν πρός τι), and therefore, though these arguments may be 
perfectly correct and have at least the merit of consistency, 
they are in contradiction with the opinion of the main body 
ofthe ‘school’. In a dialectical argument, suchas we shall 
see most of Aristotle’s refutations are, this revelation of a 
discrepancy within the school is all that is required. The 
passage is an argumentum ad Platonicos, and has no refer- 
ence whatever either to Plato or to Ideas of relations.® 


1 It has been seen above that Bonitz is unsatisfactory on the passage. The 
interpretation here given is suggested by Professor Ritchie in his Plato. 

* Like Plato, v. Zeller, Plato, E. T., p. 2425. ; cf. Philebus 53 D. 
* No doubt it will at first seem conclusive against the above view that Aristotle 
is here nevertheless held to be right in what he says of ὁπόσα φύσει. But if 
even Aristotle’s own use of the phrase includes ‘ geometrical magnitudes’ 
(μεγέθη, e.g. lines, triangles, &c., ν. De Coelo i. 1. 68 ἃ 4) might not Plato’s use 
of Φύσις, especially in later life when the idea of ‘ Nature’ grew more and more 
important to him, have included also qualities and relations? Moreover, 
Aristotle in A. 8 does not say that Plato admitted Ideas only of ὁπόσα φύσει, but 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 33 


(2) But Aristotle’s remark about ὁπόσα φύσει cannot be 
explained on the theory that Aristotle is attacking the 
earlier Platonism of the Republic or Phaedo. It is said 
that this remark (Met. A. 3) does not necessarily imply 
any real divergence from the position of Aes. x, where 
there is postulated an ‘Ideal bed’. There is no science of 
beds or houses in the same sense as there is of man or of 
the good, and consequently Plato cannot have placed Ideas 
of arte facta on the same level as other Ideas. But he need 
not have rejected them. We can think a house scientifi- 
cally by thinking of the end attained by it were it perfect. 
Now, in Aristotle’s phrase, ἡ φύσις τέλος καὶ οὗ ἕνεκα, and 
therefore as soon as a house attains its real end it can be 
included among ὁπόσα φύσει. 

This interpretation, which can appeal to ἡ ἐν τῇ φύσει οὖσα 
κλίνη made by the φυτουργός in Fep. x (597 B, D), overlooks 
two points : (a) in the passage of Mev. A ‘natural things’ (ra 
φύσει, ὁπόσα φύσει 1070 a 18, 19) are expressly distinguished 
from arte facta, e. g. house (a 14, 15); (ὁ) there is evidence 
independent of Aristotle that the Academy rejected Ideas of 
artificial products. Xenokrates, 6. g., seems to have defined 
the Idea as ‘archetypal cause of the eternal existences of 
nature’ (αἰτίαν παραδειγματικὴν τῶν κατὰ φύσιν ἀεὶ συνεστώτων), 
This view, if it was ever held by Plato, must be later 
than that of the Republic, and therefore Aristotle’s remark 
applies not to an earlier theory which Plato had rejected, 
but to a later view represented in his lectures (ἔφη A. 
1070 a 18). 

(3) As to Ideas of negations, the theory we are consider- 
ing suffers from an internal inconsistency ; for it admits that 
when Aristotle, in a reductio ad absurdum argument against 
the Platonists, implies that the latter reject Ideas of 
only that ‘natural things’ to Plato did have Ideas, whereas artificial eoveuees 
did not, v. infra, p. 34. 

ς 


34 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


ἀποφάσεις (Met. A. 9. 990 Ὁ 12), this can apply only to the 
‘final theory of Plato’. In the Republic we find Ideas of 
the bad and the unjust, in the Theaefetus of κακόν, αἰσχρόν, 
and βίος ἄθεος, in the Parmenides of ἀνισότης, in the Sophist 
of μὴ ὄν (ἱ. φ. ἕτερον. If he finally rejected them, it was 
because the perfect and the beautiful, having more of πέρας, 
can be known more completely than the imperfect and 
the ugly. The conception of evil as deviation from a 
type appears clearly in the Philebus. 

It will now be possible to sum up the positive results 
of the discussion on the content of the world of Ideas. 
(a) There is some Platonic warrant for the rejection of the 
Ideas of negations, and no reason for doubting that, as 
Aristotle implies, Plato’s followers at least discarded them. 
(6) That Plato dropped Ideas of arte facta is supported by 
the silence of all the later dialogues. (c) Aristotle is further 
right in saying that Plato’s Ideas extended to all ‘natural 
things’ (ὁπόσα φύσε). These words, however, must not be 
interpreted more strictly than the context warrants ; thus 
they do not exclude concepts like health, triangle, line." 
(α) The statement that Plato banished from his system Ideas 
of relations would be very difficult of acceptance, but 
Aristotle does not make such a statement. 


Third Problem. 


In passing to the third and fourth of our problems, we 
must take account of the recent work by M. Milhaud, 
Les Philosophes Géométres de la Gréce, the second book 
of which, dealing with Plato, is, at least in its fifth chapter, - 
one of the most original contributions of recent years to 
the literature of the Platonic question. The theory of 
Ideal numbers has long been a mystery to students of 


Ὁ In Δ, 3 Aristotle speaks of ὑγίεια as an example of ‘ things that come to be by © 
; a , . . , . . 
art (πᾶν τὸ κατὰ τέχνην), yet it also of course exists φύσει, and Aristotle himself 
gives av rovyie.a as an example of a Platonic Idea (v. Bonitz, Index, 5. v. avrds). 


Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 35 


ancient Greek philosophy. Aristotle’s statements about 
these numbers may be reduced to the following: (1) The 
Ideas, according to Plato, are numbers. This is stated 
without qualification: (2) As tothe nature of these numbers, 
they are heterogeneous and cannot be added together 
(ἀσύμβλητοι, διάφοροι," qualitatively different). (3) As to their 
function, they are causes of things (αἴτιοι Met. A. 9. 991 Ὁ 9, 
τῶν ὄντων αἰτίαι πρῶται M. 6. 1080 a 14).3 Critics have not, 
as a rule, been ready to accept Aristotle’s testimony; they 
regard the numbers as intended by Plato to be at most 
symbols of Ideas. Zeller doubts whether Plato ever 
actually identified the Ideas with numbers; he thinks 
Aristotle has here allowed himself an ‘inversion ’(Umstellung) 
of the true Platonic doctrine. Plato regarded the numbers 
as ‘fallen Ideas’ (depotenzirte Ideen); Aristotle regards the 
Ideas as ‘sublimated numbers’. Zeller modifies but does 
not give up this idea in his Hzsfory,’ and he would still 
agree with Bonitz in considering the Ideal-rnumber theory 
in the light of a ‘mere appendix’ δ to the Platonic system. 

Very different are the conclusions reached by Milhaud 
regarding the Ideal numbers. He shows’ how Plato in 
his later philosophy came more and more, like Kant, to 
a ‘synthetic’ way of thinking. That is, in seeking to solve 
the paradox of μέθεξις propounded in the Parmenides, Plato 
gives up all material analogies of whole and part, and after 
transferring the question to the world of Ideas, and show- 


1 Met. A. 9. 991 Ὁ 9 and passim, esp. 1081 a 12. In the difficult sentence 
A. 6. 987 b 22 (‘ out of the great and small by participation of these in the one 
come τὰ εἴδη τοὺς ἀριθμούς") there is no reason to dispute Alexander's inter- 
pretation, that τὰ εἴδη and τοὺς ἀριθμούς are put simply side by side in apposition. 

2 Met, M. 6-7. 

% As to how they are causes, v. Met. A. 9.991 b 9, N. c. 6; De An. i. 2. 404 Ὁ 
19 sqq.; Eth. Eud, i. 8. 1218 a 18 sqq. 

* ‘quasi symbola notionum,’ Bonitz, ii, p. 544 ; Zeller, Plat. Stud., pp. 298, 263. 

5 v. for Plato’s later theory p. 517; contrast p. 255 (Plato, E. T.). 

§ Bonitz, ii, p. 540. 7 Milhaud, pp. 327 sqq. 


C2 


36 Arrtstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


ing that there some union of specifically different kinds is 
absolutely essential, he finally solves his problem by the 
union in every Idea of the heterogeneous elements, being 
and non-being. The Idea is a meeting point of the finite 
and the infinite, the one and the dyad of Great and Small ; 
i.e. the principle of fixity, equality, determination (é), and 
the principle of variation, of indeterminate multiplicity 
(ἀόριστος duds). But now, corresponding with this spirit of 
synthesis, and helping to promote it, a great development 
had taken place in the conception of quantity." Incommen- 
surables cannot be explained by the old conception of number 
as a mere putting together of homogeneous units. In the 
case of two incommensurable magnitudes there is no longer 
identity of quantitative composition ; one is not part of the 
other. Yet there is a relation between them; quantity can 
still fix their mode of dependence, though they are not only 
not identical but are in a sense irreducible, one to the other. 
In short, what has taken place is ‘a radical transformation of 
the idea ofnumber’ ; its significance has now been enlarged 
by the introduction of quality, the heterogeneous. It can 
still continue to be called ‘number’, no longer, however, 
in the sense of σύστημα μονάδων, but as fixing the mode of 
dependence of the most heterogeneous elements. And of 
this new number the only principles that can be assigned 
are the principle of variation and the principle of fixity; 
hence at once the identity of Idea and Ideal number. 

Now here is the central point of Milhaud’s theory.2. The 
later Platonic doctrine of Ideas was expressed solely in a 
mathematical form ; the Ideas had become Ideal numbers, 
‘intimate unions of quantity and quality,’ ‘ quantities deter- 


mining unique and specifically different qualities.’ Aristotle — 
‘had not in the same degree come under the influence of the _ 


ee ee ee eee oe eee ee eee ee = 


a 


new geometry’ ;* he saw in number nothing but a total of — 


* Milhaud, pp. 179 sqq. 3 Cf. Taylor in Mind, 1903, pp. rsqq. * Milhaud, Ρ. 358. 


Sy LN oe 


7, q 
ee μ᾿ 
EE παν 


ΑΕ τσὶ ς 
ae Σ 
τ μας ἐυτς 


Arisiotle’s Criticisms of Plato 37 


units in juxtaposition. As a natural consequence he mis- 
understood the Ideal numbers, and in misunderstanding 
them has misunderstood the whole Platonic theory. For the 
Idea is related to the particular in a peculiar way which can 
only be grasped by bearing in mind its character as an Ideal 
number. Once we see that Plato was thinking through- 
out of mathematics and mathematical analogies, the relation 
of Idea to particular no longer presents any difficulty. 

Such, in brief, is the theory of M. Milhaud. Before 
criticism it will be necessary to look at the nature of Aris- 
totle’s objections to the Ideal numbers. 

In Met. Μ. 6 Aristotle takes up the word ‘numbers’ 
and, treating number as a whole of units, asks in how many 
possible ways these units can be conceived. He answers, 
they may be thought of in three different ways. (1) Every unit 
may be combinable with every other, as in the mathematical 
number. (2) Every unit may be incombinable with and 
qualitatively distinct from every other. Aristotle admits 
in the next chapter that no thinker had actually put forward 
a theory of units thus incapable of all combination,’ but he 
says that impossible though it may be, it is the theory which 
the Platonists in consistency ought to hold. (3) The units 
in any one number may be combinable with each other, 
but not combinable with the units in any other number. 
Thus the Ideal number two, the auto-dyad, is not reached 
by adding a unit to the primal one; instead of this, there 
are at once two fresh units produced; similarly the auto- 
triad is formed without the aid of the auto-dyad, the units 
in the former being quite different from those in the latter. 
This is the opinion Aristotle ascribes to Plato and the 
Platonists.? 

Now obviously if the Platonists did not admit that their 
Ideal numbers were made up of units (μονάδες) at all, the 


1M, 7. 1081 a 35 544. 3 Μ. 7. 1081 a 23-5, 6. 1080 a 23. 


38 Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 


whole of this elaborate subdivision of Aristotle is entirely 
beside the mark. Similarly, when he asks how it is possible 
that the dyad should be a single essence (φύσιν td) exist- 
ing independently of its two units, or the triad indepen- 
dently of its three units, and proceeds to show exhaustively 
that it cannot be the independent unity formed either by 
subject and attribute,! or by genus and difference, or by 
contact or chemical combination or position, again one is 
impatiently tempted todemur. If the Platonists made each 
nuniber a closed concept different from every other, is it 
likely they would have granted that such numbers were 
mere wholes of units ? 

This is the first difficulty that suggests itself. Aristotle 
assumes that every number is made up of μονάδες and 
remains fettered in this orthodoxy? throughout his whole 
exposition. He brings to bear the whole artillery of 
dialectic against the absurdities which attend the postulate 
of qualitative differences in the unit. ‘We see that a unit 
differs from another unit neither in quantity nor in quality ’;° 
units have no difference in kind. But would not Plato have 
admitted all this at once, merely adding that as regards 
the Ideal numbers such objections were entirely irrelevant ? 

Still graver misgivings arise on the perusal of M. 7. 
1081 b 1, 12 sqq. ‘Whether the units are indistinguishable 
or differ each from each, number must of necessity be num- 
bered by way of addition, e. g. the dyad by the addition of 
another one to the unit, and the triad by the addition of 
another one to the two, and similarly with thetetrad. This 


1 1082 a 15 sqq. 


* So it appears to M. Milhaud. But the case of ἄτομοι ypappat discussed 
below (pp. 48 sqq.) suggests the probability that here too Aristotle is really for 
the first time dogmatically establishing the subsequent (Euclidean) view 
(cf. M. 7. 1082 Ὁ 15) which was already used by mathematicians in practice 
(1080 a 30). Plato, if he did disclaim all notion of μονάδες (infra, p. 41), must have 


been arguing against the perceptual unit of the Pythagoreans. 
> 1082 Ὁ 4. 


es aH ee eee ee eee ot 


A ristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 39 


being so, it is impossible that the genesis of numbers should 
be as they describe, when they generate them out of the 
dyad and the one. Really when a dyad is produced it is a 
part (μόριον) of the number three, and this in turn a part of 
the number four, and so on with the following numbers.’ 
In other words, since all number is κατὰ πρόσθεσιν, and 
the Ideal numbers are not, “herefore the Ideal numbers are 
impossible, 

Aristotle, it is true, proceeds to note an objection which 
might be made by the Platonists to the above argument.! 
It may be said (and this actually was their doctrine) that 
the Ideal numbers can be produced in a manner that does 
not involve addition; e.g. four is a product of the Ideal 
dyad and the indeterminate dyad, and not simply 3+1. 
Aristotle answers that, if so, the Platonists will have to 
admit the existence of three Ideal dyads instead of one, 
since there will be not only the original Ideal dyad but 
also the two dyads in the tetrad. 

Even here Aristotle’s commonplace notion of number 
seems to obtrude. He first makes as an objection against 
the Platonists exactly the dogma which they must have 
made a merit of repudiating, viz. that one number is a 
part of another; and then, in refutation of their own 
doctrine that the indeterminate dyad ‘lays hold of the 
determinate dyad and produces the tetrad’ (rod yap ληφθέντος 
ἣν δυοποιός), he seems to think of the tetrad as simply the 
dyad repeated two times, 1. 6. 2 -Ἐ 2. 

In short, to prove there are no Ideal numbers, Aristotle 
shows that the Ideal numbers are not arithmetical numbers ; 
and to prove that the Ideal numbers do not come from the 
one and the indeterminate dyad, he reiterates that the 
arithmetical numbers come from addition. It is a plain 
case of ignoratio elencht and of the futility of argument 


1 τοδὶ Ὁ 21. 


40 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


where there is no common ground. All Aristotle can be 
said to show is that Plato ought not to have called his ἰδέα 
ἀριθμός by the name of ‘number’ at all. He admits that for 
what the Platonists wanted to prove, the ὑπόθεσις, namely, 
that the Ideas are numbers, their substitution for addition 
of multiplication and derivation from first principles is 
sound enough? Where there is no addition one Idea 
will not be contained in another Idea asa part. But this 
difficulty is avoided only at the cost of a demolition of the 
nature of number (πολλὰ ἀναιροῦσιν, Met. M. 7. 1082 Ὁ 33). 
The following sentence quoted by Syrian from Aristotle’s 
early work ‘on Philosophy’ puts the whole question in a 
nutshell: ‘If it is any number other than the mathematical 
that the Ideal numbers are, we could have no apprehension 
of it. Not one man of us in a thousand understands any 
other number than the mathematical’ (ris γὰρ τῶν ye πλείστων 
ἡμῶν ovvinow ἄλλον ἀριθμόν ;) 8 

The novelty, then, of Milhaud’s theory of the Ideal 
numbers lies not in pointing out the inadequacy of Aristotle’s 
criticism. Bonitz* had shown already how unsatisfactory 
was the method of refutation adopted. Aristotle, according 
to Bonitz, ought to have pointed out at once that ἀριθμοὶ ἀσύμ- 
βλητοι is a plain contradiction in terms; as it is, he has only 
darkened obscurity. Nor again was it a new suggestion 
to trace the identity of Idea and number to the participation 
by the former in unity and plurality.° What Milhaud has 
shown, however, is that Plato might just be the one ‘man in 
a thousand’ who cou/d ‘understand a number different from 
the mathematical number’. No other, it is true, seems to 
be recognized even by modern mathematics, but it is 
acknowledged that quantities like 7, /2 cannot be ex- 
pressed numerically by any combination of units, and it is 


1082 b 32. 2 1082 Ὁ 24, 5 Rose, p. 27. * ii, Ρ. 553 ne 
v. Zeller, Ρ. 517 Plato, E.T.). Cf. Met. Μ. 7. 1081 a 12-14. 


A ristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 41 


therefore only natural if a mathematician like Plato, who 
was at the same time equally great as a metaphysician, 
should not merely have been dissatisfied with the ordinary 
account of number as σύνθεσις μονάδων, but have made an 
attempt to replace it by another. 

Milhaud’s theory, however, is suggestive rather than 
final. Three points may be noted in connexion with it. 

(x) Aristotle expressly attributes to his antagonists—often 
using the words ὥσπερ daci—the view that number is made 
up of povddes,? though these are not the same as in the 
mathematical number. Thus in M.7. 1081 a 23-5 he says 
of the units of the Ideal dyad that on the theory of Plato 
(6 πρῶτος εἰπών) their production is due to ‘the equalization 
of the great and small by the one’. Hestates explicitly that 
all theorists, with the sole exception of the Pythagoreans, 
based their number on the unit (sovadicods . . . πάντες 
τιθέασι *), 

The acceptance of Milhaud’s theory therefore involves 


_ acknowledgement of a very serious misunderstanding on 


the part of Aristotle. Such total misrepresentation is not 
altogether unintelligible in view of (a) the sentence above 
quoted from the Περὶ Φιλοσοφίας, which shows Aristotle’s 
perfect conviction that the only possible number was based 
on the unit, and (δὴ) the probability or rather certainty that 
Plato’s later mathematical speculations were mixed up with 
a great deal of Pythagorean fancy and symbolism.* Still 
it is very hard indeed to suppose that had the Platonists 
rejected all notion of μονάδες they would not have made 
this clear. And this objection has especial weight if we 


1 Cf. Euclid, Book VII, def. 2 number is τὸ ἐκ μονάδων συγκείμενον πλῆθος. 

2 So too Aristotle frequently asks: Whence, on Platonic principles, comes 
the Unit? How do they derive it from the One and the Indeterminate Dyad? 

3 1080 b 30. 

* This is admitted even by Milhaud, pp. 309, 320, 326. It would account for 
Aristotle’s failing to distinguish the wheat from the chaff. 


42 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


are to assign so important a place to the Ideal numbers as 
Milhaud would have us do. Milhaud’s view, indeed, seems 
to come perilously near to the old esoteric theory of 
Platonism, unless more definite allusions to the Ideal 
numbers be discovered in the dialogues.’ 

(2) On the other hand, the important passage Met. H. 
3. 1043 b 32 seems to lend support on the whole to Milhaud’s 
hypothesis. Aristotle here asks in what sense substances 
can be compared with numbers, for points of comparison 
there undoubtedly are. His answer is, that if Ideas are in 
any sense numbers, they must be so as closed concepts 
(οὕτως 1043 b 33), and ‘not, as some philosophers say, as each 
a number of units.’ . . . ‘Every substance must be an 
actuality and a definite thing (ἐντελέχεια καὶ φύσις tts), not, 
as some Say, in the sense that it is a kind of unit or point.’ 

Now this passage shows clearly enough that Aristotle 
objects to the Platonic identification of substance and 
number simply because (as he thought) this was equivalent 
to making substance like a unit or point. Since στιγμαί or 
μονάδες are all qualitatively alike, whence on such a theory 
(Aristotle asks) comes the uniqueness of things ? If number 
can have a qualitative aspect, can be in any sense ἀσύμβλητος, 
Aristotle’s query is answered. The Idea of the Good, as 
described in the Phzlebus, is a unity of multiplicity, a one of 
heterogeneous elements; it cannot be compared (as Aristotle 
correctly enough points out) with the ordinary arithmetical 
number, but why not with an ἀριθμὸς ἀσύμβλητος ? Aristotle, 
in his strenuous opposition to the Pythagoreanism in Plato, 
certainly seems to have ignored that ‘ synthetic’ aspect of 
number which his master had endeavoured to elucidate. 

But (3) even if Milhaud’s theory be accepted, Aristotle, 


5 Cf. Zeller, Plat. Stud., there is ‘almost no trace’ of the Ideal numbers in 
the dialogues ; History (Plato, E. T., p. 254), the Ideal number theory ‘has no 


place in Plato’s writings’. Ideas of numbers are common enough ; cf. ἡ τῶν 
ἀριθμῶν φύσις (Rep. 525C). 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 43 


though wrong in what he denies, is right in what he 
affirms. With his insistence on definite and clear cut 
conceptions, he will have nothing to do with any qualitative 
aspect of number ; and it will be granted that on trying to 
work out Milhaud’s conception of a ‘union of quantity and 
specific quality’ many perplexities are involved. On 
the other hand, however, (1) Aristotle is quite sound in his 
own view of number, and (2) with his interest in biology and 
development, he is really in all his attacks on the number 
philosophy of the Academy—where philosophy, as he says, 
had been reduced to mathematics—implicitly asserting that 
there are aspects and departments of the universe, e. g. life 
and mind, in which ἡ μετρητική, Plato’s sovereign science of 
measurement, is, if applicable at all, altogether inadequate 
to reality. For even if we go to the opposite extreme from 
Aristotle, and instead of ignoring the truth of Plato’s theory 
read into it the fullest possible significance, it is a theory 
which reduces all the sciences to one—that of quantity.” 
Besides pointing out that mathematics and numbers can give 
no account of causality,’ Aristotle insists on their abstract 
nature, and holds that whereas the animate is prior to the 
inanimate * the Platonists reverse this order. At one time he 
seems to have been carried away by the mathematical ideal 
of exactness (ἀκρίβεια), but by the time he writes the De 


Anima and the Metaphysics ὅ he sees that after all Psycho- 


logy, as a ‘concrete’ study, has really more claim to be 
called an ‘ exact science’ than mathematics. 


Fourth Problem. 


The investigation of the rest of Milhaud’s theory leads 
straight to the problem of the Transcendence of the Idea 
in the Platonic system. We have seen above that the 


1 Met. A. 9. 992 ἃ 32. 2 v. A. E. Taylor in Mind, 1903. 
3 Met. A. 9. 991 Ὁ 9. * Met. M. 2, 1077 a 20. 
> Contrast Fost, An. i. 27 with De An, i. 1. 402 a 2 and Met. Ε. τ. 10256 7. 


44 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


weight of Aristotle’s critique is directed against the χωριστὸν 
καθόλου, a universal predicate that is at the same time a 
particular. Aristotle could not understand how the general 
Idea could at the same time have all kinds of other 
properties—individuality, completeness, perfection. Now, 
according to Milhaud,! he would have understood, had he 
seen what Plato was thinking of in his Ideal theory, viz. 
the analogies of mathematics. Plato’s Ideas are not muti- 
lated and abstract universals, but, in one word, the ‘pure 
essences of the mathematician’. The Ideal circle, 6. g., is 
the circle as defined by its equation in the general form ; 
it is at once ἕν καὶ πολλά, since it synthesizes in accord with 
one definite law a great multiplicity of positions. It is 
‘participated in’ by particular circles, but this mode of 
participation cannot be represented by any metaphor 
borrowed from addition. Further, it is in a sense χωρίς, 
outside the world of sense, for it is never adequately 
realized even in the particular circles obtained by giving 
numerical values to the terms of the general equation, 
much less in the material circles of nature, which are but 
feeble and imperfect adumbrations of the Idea. As for the 
οὐσία of the Idea, of which Aristotle makes so much, it is 
simply the ‘being’ of all eternal and immutable truths; it 
is a priort objectivity. Milhaud further tries to show, in 
support of his identification of the Ideas with the essences 
of geometry, that Aristotle is wrong in placing τὰ μαθηματικὰ 
intermediate between the Ideas and the world of sense, 
and that the Platonic dialogues afford no real justification 
for his doing so.? 

It will be seen that this theory is not altogether new. 
Lotze, as is well known, was convinced that by ‘reality’ 
Plato meant ‘ validity’, and that when he spoke of the Ideas 


: Cf. A. E. Taylor in Mind, 1903. 
The opposite view is maintained by Adam, Republic ii, pp. 159-62. 


ra fee See eee a Ὡ 2:--. 


x 
᾿ 
ν 
2 
5 
: 
ᾷ 
‘ 
4 
Ὶ 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 45 


as χωρίς he meant ‘their eternally self-identical significance ’, 
The εἶδος was ‘valid before we thought about it, and will 
continue so without regard to any existence of whatever 
kind, of things or of us, whether or not it ever finds 
manifestation in the reality of existence, or a place as an 
object of knowledge in the reality of a thought’. Plato’s 
transcendence, in short, means nothing but ‘independent 
validity’. The advantage of Milhaud’s theory is that it 
explains the blunder of Aristotle in a much more plausible 
way than as the result of a mere ambiguity of the Greek 
language. Xenokrates told an intending pupil who had no 
mathematics that he could not enter the portals of philo- 
sophy—aAaBas γὰρ οὐκ ἔχεις φιλοσοφίας. The only question 
is: Can Milhaud’s supposition be admitted here? Has 
Aristotle’s supposed failure to follow the mathematical 
thinking of Plato really led him on this question of 
‘transcendence’ to a caricature of his master’s philosophy? 

(1) The answer must be, in the first place, that such a 
supposition is refuted by the testimony of Plato himself. 
An unprejudiced reading of the Phaedo or Republic or 
Phaedrus will unquestionably confirm Aristotle in that 
interpretation of Idea and particular which, with his usual 
terseness, he sums up in a word or two in the early part of 
A. 6 of the AZetaphysics. The particulars of sense are 
‘outside of the Ideas’, though receiving their common name 
because of them (τὰ αἰσθητὰ παρὰ ταῦτα καὶ κατὰ ταῦτα λέγεσθαι 
πάντα). The Ideas are ‘definite natures and substances 
separate from other things’. 

It may be granted to Lotze that even in the first draft of 
his theory the οὐσία which Plato aimed at expressing was 
being in the sense of ‘universal and eternal validity’, and 
that if (in the Aristotelian phrase)? we look to his intention 


1 Met, I. 2, 1053 Ὁ 21 φύσεις τινὲς καὶ οὐσίαι χωρισταὶ τῶν ἄλλων. 
2 Cf. Met. A. 3. ο85 ἃ 5; 8. 989 bs. 


46 Antstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


rather than to his words we shall not quarrel with any 
such conclusion. But, as Lotze himself really admits, 
Plato does not succeed in distinguishing Reality (Sezm, οὐσία) 
from Validity (Geltung), and what was meant to be simply 
independent of individual thought becomes (notably in the 
Republic) a reality independent of all thought whatever. 
When Plato, therefore, talks of the Ideas as ἐν τόπῳ 
ὑπερουρανίῳ or as ἑστῶτα ἐν τῇ φύσει, he means precisely what 
Aristotle expresses in more prosaic language by οὐσία 
κεχωρισμένη τῶν aloOnrav.* 

It need only be noted in a sentence that the natural 
interpretation of the Parmenides is directly opposed to any 
such theory as that of Lotze or Milhaud. ‘The unre- 
generate Socrates’ of that dialogue, i. 6. Plato himself, had 
previously, it is indicated, held a doctrine in which the 
Ideas were (a) αὐτὰ καθ᾽ αὑτά, which can only mean transcen- 
dent and self-subsistent; and (6) χωρίς, which describes 
them in a negative way but means the same thing. 

(2) Secondly, that Aristotle, who had the benefit of Plato’s 
own conversation and instruction for twenty years, should 
never once have seen what Plato meant (according to 
Milhaud) by the transcendence of the Idea and the par- 
ticular’s participation therein, is simply incredible. Even 
an utter distaste for mathematics would not explain such 
a misunderstanding. Aristotle was the acutest mind of the 
school, and where the fundamental problem of μέθεξις was 
concerned his universal curiosity was not such as to be 
repelled even by the abstractions of the higher mathematics. 
Yet he says in explicit terms that the nature of participation 


vA. 7. 1073 a 4, 5. It is curious that few have been found to dispute 
Aristotle’s statement that the μόρια χωριστά of the Platonic soul-division means 
actual and not merely ideal severance (De. An. 413 Ὁ 28 χωριστὰ καθάπερ τινές 


φασιν), yet this ‘separation’ is quite as much a ‘hard saying’ as the self-depen- 
dent existence of the Idea. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 47 


was left by Plato ‘an open question’, and this is borne out 
by the dialogues themselves. 

(3) Moreover Milhaud’s theory seems (a) unduly to de- 
preciate the mathematical intelligence of Aristotle, and 
(ὁ) conversely to modernize the thought of Plato to the 
neglect of the historical development. 

(a) Is it so certain, as is often assumed, that Aristotle 
was a weakling in mathematics? The very fact of his 
being a member of the Academy already implies that he 
could not have neglected the subject. Cantor, who refers 
to his ‘fine mathematical intellect’ (fermen mathematischen 
Gerst), notes his separation of Geometry from Geodesy,? 
just as Plato had previously distinguished Arithmetic 
from Logistic.? Though the specially mathematical works 
ascribed to him are lost, and though the Mechanics are 
spurious and the Problems not to be relied on as evidence, 
still even in the authentic works we have ample evidence. 
that he took the keenest interest in all the problems of 
mathematics. Further it is curious that he seems to have 
understood the famous ‘ Nuptial number ’,* the obscurity 
of which has been proverbial from the days of Cicero 
onward. In the Metaphysics’ Aristotle says the ‘uni- 
versal circle’ or circle in general (6 καθόλου κύκλος) is 


1 Met. A. 6.987 Ὁ 14. The phrase ἀφεῖσαν ἐν κοινῷ ζητεῖν is often mistrans- 
lated. It cannot be rendered (as by Ueberweg) ‘omitted to investigate’ (cf. 
Gomperz, diese Frage haben ste unerledigt gelassen ; Bonitz in medio reliquerunt 
[Index 400 a 5; differently at 128 ἢ 38]). It means ‘they left over for subse- 
quent inquiry’. Now this actually describes with complete accuracy what we 
find in the dialogues. Cf. Parm,. 133 a ἀλλά τι ἄλλο δεῖ ζητεῖν ᾧ μεταλαμβάνει. 
This ‘other way’, however, is not to be found, and can at most only be 
read into the dialogues. Why indeed may not the above words of Aristotle be 
the missing reference to the Parmenides? Cf. also Plato, Phil. 15b, where again 
the problem of μέθεξις is raised but not solved. 

4 Met. B. 2. 997 b 32 sqq. * Cantor, i, p. 239. 

* Pol. v. 12. 1316 a. 

ἢ Z. το. 1035 a 33-b 2 (in a 34 we should read τις ὅς with E); cf. rr. 1037 
a 2 Sqq. ὁ ἁπλῶς λεγόμενος κύκλος has no ὕλη : individual circles have νοητὴ ὕλη. 


48. Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


a concept that has no ‘matter >, not even ὕλη νοητή, and 
this would seem to be exactly what Milhaud makes of 
Plato’s Ideal circle, simply an algebraical equation. It 
is a pity M. Milhaud did not think it worth while to con- 
tinue his mathematical researches as far as Aristotle.’ 

(ὁ) Interpretation of the old in the light of the new is 
the very life of all philosophical exegesis. But where the 
question is an historical one, as to how far one thinker 
has understood another who was his contemporary, it is 
a primary necessity that interpretation should be as closely 
literal and objective as possible. Now Milhaud is not 
only less than just to Aristotle in his desire to make the 
most of Plato, but also tends to put the latter out of per- 
spective by crediting him with mathematical concepts that 
are essentially modern. 

We may illustrate this by means of the theory of ‘ indi- 
visible lines’ (ἄτομοι ypayuat), which will show that Aristotle — 
may be a sound critic even of Plato’s geometry, and there- 
fore unlikely to misinterpret his master’s philosophy owing 
to alleged sciolism in Mathematics. This interesting theory 
is usually ascribed to Xenokrates, but Aristotle had often 
heard Plato himself state it to his pupils in lecture (πολλάκις 
ἐτίθει, Met. Α. 9. 992 a 22). ‘This genus (that of points) was 
one of which Plato disputed the very existence. He said 
the point was a geometer’s assumption, and though he was 
ready to call it the starting point of the line, the real starting 
point, as he often used to lay down, consisted of indivisible 
lines. It was a theory that was found very hard of com- 
prehension by the Greek commentators; thus Simplicius 


ΤΑ work by Gérland on Aristotle’s Mathematics seems unfortunately, at least 
to judge by Gomperz’s review in Archiv of 1903, to be useless for purposes of 
objective study. 

* The passage is a difficult one to render and difficult in itself. A very 
different translation and application of the passage will be found in Milhaud, 
PP. 340-3, whose treatment however seems far from satisfactory. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 49 


is lost in wonder that it should have been put forward 
by such a ‘mathematical man’ as Xenokrates. Aristotle 
brings an argument against it in the passage from which 
we have just quoted, and it is refuted at length in a treatise 
(rept ἀτόμων γραμμῶν) written by one of Aristotle’s pupils— 
probably Theophrastos. 

Now a modern mathematician coming to this theory 
might be able (in Aristotle’s phrase) to ‘ give it an up-to-date 
interpretation 1 He might say that Aristotle and his pupil 
had misconceived and traduced a very important doctrine 
—no less, in fact, than a rough anticipation of modern 
infinitesimals. Just as in modern mathematics zero = 
a quantity smaller than any assignable quantity, so if the 
line be conceived as diminished till it is smaller than any 
assignable line, it becomes an ἄτομος γραμμή, 1.e.a point; 
not, however, an Euclidean point, but one from which, by 
taking an indefinite number of them, it will be possible to 
construct a line (ἀρχὴν γραμμῆς, A. 9. 992 a 22). It might be 
admitted that the view of Plato and Xenokrates was defec- 
_ tive compared with that of the moderns, because while the 
modern view, with its phrase ‘smaller than any assignable 
quantity’, does not deny the Euclidean conception of in- 
 finity but simply dispenses with it, Plato, on the other 
hand, by definitely talking of ‘indivisible’ (ἄτομος) de- 
liberately puts in the place of Euclid’s point without parts 
something which actually has parts, but of which the parts 
are practically denied.? 

Such a theory might quite conceivably be put forward, 
and would not be refuted by an appeal to the authority of 
Aristotle. For, it would be said, Aristotle and his pupil 


1 καινοπρεπεστέρως λέγειν, Met. A. 8. 989b 6. 

2 A very close parallel might be found in Herbart, who, distinguishing s¢arre 
Linie and stetige Linie, constructs the former out of points in just this non- 
Euclidean way (cf. Marcel Mauxion, La Métaphysique d’Herbart, pp. 115-16. 
Paris, 1894), 


D 


50 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


had not to the same degree as Plato ‘come under the 
influence of the new geometry’. They assumed the 
complete validity and sufficiency of the orthodox view 
according to which the line is divisible ad tnfinitum. But 
surely Plato knew this as well as Aristotle. The latter’s 
whole refutation consists, it would be said, in the ‘ appeal 
to Euclid’; he says the Platonists ‘do not speak the 
language of orthodox mathematics’, their views being 
quite ‘peculiar to themselves ’.* | 

Such a theory might be made very plausible. But it 
would undoubtedly be shattered on a careful consideration 
of the development of geometrical thought after the time of 
Zeno.2. Zeno had shown once for all that the line was not 
made up of an infinite number of points: consequently it 
devolved on Plato to make a fresh start. He frankly 
accepted Zeno’s results. The point was simply a ‘geo- 
metrical assumption’, i.e. the ‘mere mathematician’ may 
talk of the points of a line, but the philosopher sees that the 
line is something quite different from the point and cannot 
be explained as made up of them. It may be explained, 
however, if it is made up of something homogeneous with 
itself, 1. 6. of Anes. Only they must be very small lines— 
so small, in fact, that they cannot be cut into smaller; they 
must be ‘ indivisible lines’. Plato’s view was partly right, 
and marked a clear advance on the Pythagorean view. It 
contained, however, a contradiction ; for, though a line can 
be made by adding smaller lines, these smaller lines can 
always be divided into yet smaller. It only remained for 
Aristotle to point out this contradiction, and establish, 


* ob μαθηματικῶς, Met. M. 6. 1080 b 29; ἴδιαί τινες δόξαι, Met. N. 3. τορο b 20. 
i Περὶ ar. Ὑραμμ., which begins by giving some of the reasons which led to 
the doctrine. One of these is connected with the Ideal theory, 968 a 9 sqq. ; 


another is the demolition by Zeno of the Pythagorean conception of the line, 
968 a 18 sqq. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 51 


thenceforward the Euclidean view—zra@v συνεχὲς διαιρετὸν 
els ἀεὶ διαιρετά." 

As illustrating Aristotle’s method of criticism, however, 
one of his refutations of the ‘indivisible line’ deserves 
a little examination, It is in the chapter above quoted— 
Metaphysics A. 9. Aristotle is pointing out the difficulties 
that attend the derivation of lines, surfaces and solids from 
the Platonic first principles—the one and the great and 
small. After showing that their attempted derivation is 
inconsistent with their own belief that the line ‘inheres’ 
in the surface, and the surface in the solid, Aristotle comes 
next to the point. How, he asks, will the Platonist deri- 
vation show that the point ‘inheres in’ the line? Plato, 
it is true, tried to evade the difficulty by saying there is 
no such thing as the point. The line, according to Plato, 
was not made up of points at all, but of ‘indivisible lines’, 
and therefore, if the line is derived from first principles, 
nothing more is needed. 

Then follows Aristotle’s objection. ‘The point must 
exist; for lines, even if they are indivisible lines, must 
have an end (πέρας) 3, i.e. a point. Bonitz says this is 
a petitio principit. So it would be, were not Aristotle all 
through this passage arguing from the Platonic standpoint. 
As he is himself careful to add, ‘the same argument as 
_ proves the existence of the line proves also the existence 
_ of the point.’* In other words, Plato says that surface is 
the ‘end’ of a solid and the line the ‘end’ of a surface, 
therefore, he ought, in consistency, to admit that the point 
is the ‘end’ of the line. Plato had seen that lines were 
not made up of points, but unfortunately he had not gone 
on to say that similarly planes could not be made out of 
lines, nor solids out of planes. Aristotle’s argument, 
therefore, is dialectical, but perfectly justified. 

: 1 Physics vi. 1, ν. passim. 2 9924 23. 8 992 a 24. 
D2 


52 Aritstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


Itis unnecessary then to consider the details of Milhaud’s 
theory. It may be held as incontestable that Plato did at 
one stage of his thinking hold a doctrine of transcendent 
Ideas, such as we find refuted in Aristotle. But now 


comes the problem of the Parmenides. If there is one ~ 


thing which that dialogue attacks in every conceivable 
and possible way, it is just this transcendence of the Idea. 
And we have seen that this is the centre also of Aristotle's 
attack. The proposition ‘Substance cannot be separated 
(χωρίς) from that of which it is the substance’ summarizes, 
according to Zeller, the whole difference between the 
Platonic and Aristotelian systems ; it furnishes, according 
to Bonitz, the ‘summum ac praecipuum Artstoteleae et Plato- 
nicae philosophiae discrimen’, Here then we are face to 
face with the fundamental dilemma already mentioned— 
what we may call the Parmenides-Aristotle dilemma. 

Of this dilemma it has been usual for historians of philo- 
sophy to accept the first horn—that Plato never abandoned 
the self-subsistence of the Idea. This view must commit 
itself to unnatural interpretations of the Parmenides?; it 
tends to minimize either the force of the arguments there 
stated or the importance of the whole dialogue ; or again— 
an easy solution which is no solution—it declares the 
dialogue spurious. 

Further, the Parmenides does not stand alone. If it did 
Plato might be regarded, though unwarrantably, as a ‘ meta- 
physical Ariel’, writing the Parmenides in an ‘hour of 
insight’. But in the Sophist also Plato criticizes ‘the 


* Not of course that he consciously held it in the definite and dogmatic form 


to which Aristotle, with his preciser terminology, reduces it. Every philosophy ~ 


necessarily suffers injustice in being thus restated. 

πε Such e.g. as that of Zeller, Plat. Stud., pp. 159-94. Apelt, again, has 
triumphantly vindicated the genuineness of the dialogue, but he does so only at 
the cost of ranking its philosophical importance quite low: he calls it ‘ein 


wahres Arsenal von Erschleichungen und Sophi: τ A Vere erp ede 
Sabbath’, &c, δ᾽ phismen’, a ‘dialectical wi 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 53 


friends of the Ideas’, with their doctrine of transcendence 
(οὐσίαν χωρίς που διελόμενοι) and their severance of Being and 
Becoming (οὐσία and γένεσις), and in the declaration of the 
same dialogue that ‘to go about to separate off (ἀποχωρίζειν) 
one thing absolutely from every other is the very anti- 
thesis of true philosophy’, we seem to find, though the 
immediate reference is logical, the spirit of the later 
Platonic metaphysic as a whole. Plato seems to have 
got beyond the sharp antithesis of the Republic between 
‘seeing’ and ‘thinking ’,’ and to have come to recognize 
that the world of knowledge was not a different world from 
that of perception, existing independently of it. 

But there are difficulties equally great in the way of 
accepting the second horn—that Aristotle had not the 
ability to understand Plato’s later Idealism and attributed 
to him the crudest form of the theory as the form most 
easy to refute. Such a view might indeed appeal to the 
many supposed cases of unfair argument used by Aristotle 
in his strictures on the Ideas. It is said that he argues 
from his own point of view and thus unfairly attributes to 
opponents the result of his own deductions. But even if 
this were established,” it does not make it any the more 
intelligible that Aristotle should, from the very first, have 


1 Rep. vi. 507 B τὰ μὲν δρᾶσθαί φαμεν, νοεῖσθαι δ᾽ οὔ, τὰς δ᾽ αὖ ἰδέας νοεῖσθαι μέν, 
ὁρᾶσθαι δ᾽ οὔ ; cf. in Bk. vii ἡ δι᾿ ὄψεως φαινομένη ἕδρα )( 6 νοητὸς τόπος. 

2 A very clear case might be supposed to be afforded by “οί. Z. 6. 1031 Ὁ 15, 
where Aristotle says that ‘if the Ideas are such as some people assert them to 
be, then the substrate—in other words the particular—cannot be substance 
(otcia)’, This is urged by way of objection, though it is obvious that Plato (at 
least in the first stage of his thinking) would not have admitted the οὐσία of the 
particular. But even here is it not the case that Aristotle is refuting the 
Platonists from their own premises? His argument is directed against that 
view of the Ideas which makes them like the gods of the popular religion, only 
differing from the men in whose image they are made in being 4 διοι. 
Such a view of the Ideas might well commit itself to the assertion attributed to 
the Platonists by Aristotle that the ‘non-sensible substances are more substan- 
tial than the sensible, because they are elernal’ (Met. Z. 1). 


54 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


set himself in opposition to the ‘otherworldness’ of the 
Platonic philosophy, had it really ceased to present that 
character. The obscurity of Plato’s later teaching drove 
many from his lectures,! and has left traces of itself in 
certain passages of Aristotle’; but surely the latter, if 
any one, was qualified to understand him. 

Other theories finally have sought to avoid the necessity 
of taking either side of the antithesis. Plato did abandon 
the self-existence of the Ideas and yet Aristotle has xot 
misrepresented him. Here the most attractive view is one 
already partly discussed—that which holds Aristotle to 
have been aware of Plato’s disavowal of transcendence 
and to be attacking consequently only the earlier theory 
of Ideas. The criticism, it is noted, takes place within the 
school, and attacks a doctrine which has several different 
and contradictory forms. The arguments are served up 
afresh from the περὶ ἰδεῶν, because that doctrine of exag- 
gerated transcendence, which even Plato had found it 
necessary to censure in some of his pupils, was. still 
rampant in the Academy at the time when Aristotle put 
together his Metaphysics.* 

Now it may be perfectly correct to say that Aristotle is 
attacking an ‘earlier theory of Ideas’, but the great diffi- 
culty is just that he knows of no later theory. He constantly 
mentions Plato’s theory of first principles (στοιχεῖα), but so 
far is he from the knowledge of any change of front with 
regard to the Ideas that, on the one hand, Platonists who 
might certainly be described as ‘friends of the Ideas’ are 
represented as holding the later doctrine of the One and the 

1 Rose, p. 24. 2 e.g. De An. i. 2. 404 Ὁ το sqq. 

ὁ A. 9. 990 Ὁ 9, Ὁ ΤΙ, Ὁ 21, 992 a 32. 

* From the Platonic side this theory has to face two difficulties : (a) that of the 
Timaeus, 51C sqq., where the Ideas, regarded from the point of view of the 


Parmenides, are everything they should xo? be (51 C, E, 52 A); (8) the difficulties 
of identifying the Ideas in the Philebus with the class of τὸ πέρας. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 55 


Indeterminate Dyad,! and, on the other hand, conversely, 
Plato in his later philosophy of first principles is still credited 
with a pre-Parmenidean doctrine of Ideas.? 

Moreover, though Plato himself is not once mentioned 
in the criticisms of Met. A.g and Ethics i. 6, it is impos- 
sible to suppose he is not included in the refutation.® 
Similarly, though in Me#. B and Z Aristotle is clearly 
attacking the contemporary Academy and a crude doctrine 
of ‘eternalized sensibles’ (ἀΐδια αἰσθητά) which was never 
held by the master himself, yet Aristotle nowhere says 
anything to indicate that the Platonic view in its logical 
consequences would not be open to the same difficulties. 
He gives it explicitly as Plato’s doctrine that he believed 
in three orders of existence (οὐσίαι), and nowhere is it 
stated that he changed this view. In short, the theory 
only acquits Aristotle of direct injustice by exposing him 
to the same charge indirectly. 

Our fourth problem then has evidently reduced itself to 
the problem of the Parmenides, which is a standing enigma 
in the Platonic philosophy. The interpretation here adopted 
of that dialogue seems the natural one, and if accepted it 
is impossible to suppose that Plato ever recanted his own 
recantation. But there is as yet no agreement as to how 
he modified his doctrine, nor is it certain that he ever 
found himself in a position to meet satisfactorily the 
difficulties of the Parmenides and the ‘innumerable others 
in addition to them ’.° 


1 Met. A. 9. 990 b 18. 2 Met. A. 6. 

3. Aristotle begins the refutation in A. 9 with the words οἱ δὲ τὰς ἰδέας αἰτίας 
τιθέμενοι, but he uses the past tense ἐκόμισαν Ὁ 2, προῆλθον Ὁ 6. This may of 
course refer still to none but the Platonists, but it is forced, especially as it is 
the case that Aristotle frequently refers to Plato in the plural. Nevertheless it 
may be admitted that a single mention of Plato by name (for his view of the 
point) and a reference to a single dialogue (the Phaedo) are not what we should 
have expected had Aristotle been really attacking a doctrine of Plato’s. 

* Z. 2. 1028 b 2o.. 5 Parm. 135 A, 


56 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


So much for the “hes7s; the antithesis is that Aristotle’s 
criticism cannot be adequately explained unless the an- 
tagonists he is refuting actually held a doctrine of tran- 
scendent Ideas.! It is meaningless except as against the 
theory of a noumenal world which is a timeless reproduction 
of the phenomenal but does not explain it, seeing that the 
two are ‘divorced’ from each other. There is no difficulty 
in attributing such a view to members of the Academy ; for 
the doctrines of Speusippos and others on the separate 
and independent existence of numbers are obviously 
a heritage from, and to be paralleled with, the early 
Platonic theory of Ideas. But can it be attributed also 
to the Plato who wrote the Parmenides and the Sophist 
and the Philebus ? 

We have here a case of conflicting evidence, and the 
data seem hardly sufficient for a solution. The Aristo- 
telian method of ‘ working through the difficulties’? has in 
this case led to little positive result. The dilemma above 
stated has of itself no necessary cogency,? but the difficulties 
which lead up to it have been neither evaded nor solved. 
The problem is still sub cudice.* 


1 On any other theory not one of his criticisms but would fall lamentably 
flat, and Aristotle was too keen a dialectician not to have noticed this at once. 
Thus take the amusing chapter (Z. 14) in the Metaphysics in which Aristotle turns 
the tables on the Platonists. The latter held the Idea was the sole definable ; 
Aristotle, however, after showing that of particulars there can be no definition, 
proceeds : ‘ Neither then can any Idea be defined. For it is a particular, as they 
say (@s .. » φασι), and separable.’ Nothing could be more unlikely than that 
Aristotle here attributes to the Platonists a mere unwarranted deduction of his 
own. So again in Eth. i. 6 it is the Platonists (as Stewart says) who confound 
the true with the spurious eternity—didiov with πολυχρόνιον. 

* De Caelo iv. τ. 308 a5 iddyres οὖν πρῶτον τὰ παρὰ τῶν ἄλλων εἰρημένα, καὶ 
διαπορήσαντες κτλ., ib. i. ro, 

Ἢ Thus we have shown above that the talk of ‘ plagiarism” has no relevancy. 

Its solution will to some extent depend on the possibility or otherwise of 
extracting a consistent doctrine from the very difficult chapter A. 6 of the 
Metaphysics, Two ἀπορίαι in connexion with the chapter may be noted: (1) if the 
inhering principles of all things (στοιχεῖα) are the Good and Matter, why the 


ee te a ee ee 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 57 


But whatever the solution of these difficulties, the essence 
of Aristotle’s criticism will still be justified. There is 
a very fundamental difference between master and pupil 
in their doctrine of the real. The real had been for Plato 
τὰ ὄντως ὄντα, the Ideas; Aristotle surprisingly, inconsis- 
tently, and yet naturally enough, agrees that this is so 
in the case of the highest οὐσία, the Deity.’ But in the 
concrete world the spirit of the observer and student of 
nature predominates over the metaphysical tendency to 
dualism which he had inherited from his master; and the 
merit of grasping firmly and clearly that ‘the universal 
exists in and through the particular, and that the existence 
of the particular is in and for the universal ’,? and of carry- 
ing this doctrine consistentlythrough the whole phenomenal 
world, indubitably belongs to Aristotle. 


Fifth Problem. 


The fifth and last problem brings us to what Aristotle 
has to say on the subject of Plato’s aetiology. 

(1) His main charge in the indictment of Transcendent 
Idealism is, that it cannot furnish any explanation of the 
world of change and becoming (τῶν φανερῶν τὸ αἴτιον). 
Thus, after giving his own explanation of γένεσις in the 
Metaphysics,t he proceeds to show that the Ideas (ἡ τῶν 
εἰδῶν αἰτία) do not contribute at all to bring about generation 
and substances. For (a) ‘if the form were a self-subsistent 
(Platonic) Idea, and existed in shat sense, no “this” would 
ever have been coming to be. The form signifies the 
“such ” or the “ what”, but it is not a “this” or a “ deter- 


need of the Ideas as formal causes? (2) if this be satisfactorily solved, what is 
the relation between the One or the Good to the Ideas (Formal Causes) ? 
1 Who is pure Form, τὸ τί ἣν εἶναι τὸ πρῶτον (A, 8. 1074 a 35). 
2 R. B. Haldane, The Pathway to Reality, p. 52. 
3 Met. A. 9. 992 a 24; cf. 991 ἃ ὃ πάντων δὲ μάλιστα διαπορήσειεν ἄν τις κτλ. 
* Z. 8. 


58 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


minate something ”’.2 (ὁ) In some cases, viz. the birth of 
natural objects, it is matter of plain experience that the 
Ideas have nothing to do with the generation. In nature 
like is generated by like, man by man, not by the Idea of 
man; and yet, since natural objects are especially οὐσίαι, it 
is here that the Ideas would be most required. Similarly 
it is the doctor, not the Idea of health, that produces health ; 
the scientific teacher, not the Idea of knowledge, that pro- 
duces knowledge. And if Ideas were the causes, why are 
they not constantly in operation? Aristotle sums up his case 
in Met. A. το: ‘The Ideas are not causes at all, but even 
granting that they are, at least they are not the causes 
of motion (οὔτι κινήσεως γε) In short, just as Leibnitz 
misses final cause in Spinoza, so Aristotle misses efficient 
cause in Plato. 

Apart from Lotze’s remark on the non-efficiency of the 
Ideas that neither do our Laws of Nature contain in them- 
selves a beginning of motion, it might be retorted to 
Aristotle by the Platonists that their master had never 
said the Ideas could supply an ἀρχὴ (κινήσεως) γενέσεως. In 
all Plato’s later writings, at all events, the efficient cause 
is soul, mind, creator.2 But (1) as against the Phaedo, 
where the Ideas are made the sole efficient causes, 
Aristotle’s argument is valid, and (2) it is extremely 
probable that Plato in his later lectures had made no 
mention of efficient causes. He seems to have used no 


* Pseudo-Alexander here remarks that on the Platonic view (a) there might be 
σύνθεσις, as of the bricks that go to build a house, but no γένεσις ; (δ) just as this 
particular wine and this particular honey, if separate existences, may make up 
mead but cannot be found in any other mixture, so if αὐτοάνθρωπος is χωριστόν, 
it may in combination with this particular matter produce Socrates, but can 
give rise to no other individual till severed from the matter of Socrates 
(Hayduck, 496. 20). With Aristotle there is a growth of form into matter 
(= formed matter) ; he no longer, like Plato, makes the cause of phenomena 
something different from them. 


- ~ 
Cf, Laws 896 a ψυχὴ... μεταβολῆς τε καὶ κινήσεως ἁπάσης αἰτία ἅπασιν. 


Aritstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 59 


other causes than his two first principles, the One or the 
Ideas, and the Indeterminate Dyad; he probably said 
nothing of the ‘Demiurge’ so often mentioned in the 
dialogues, nor even of soul as source of motion. Other- 
wise Aristotle’s objection, that Plato’s ‘mathematical matter’ 
cannot explain motion, would lose all its point." 

It is no doubt surprising to find that notwithstanding 
his attack on Plato, Aristotle himself reduces his four 
causes to two, and on the principle of always finding the 
‘ultimate ground’ should trace back the efficient cause to 
the formal.? But though the efficient cause of a house to 
Aristotle is ultimately the form of the house in the mind of 
the builder, still he does not absorb the efficient cause in 
the formal; he recognizes the efficiency of the art of 
building or of the builder. 

Again Aristotle is justified in the strictures he passes 
on Plato’s use of the term ‘participation’. He says that 
Plato cannot tell the cause of the ‘participation’; and if 
we answer, with Bonitz, that ‘the cause’ is the efficient 
cause, it must be further asked: In what way is Plato’s 
efficient cause an αἴτιον τῆς μεθέξεως ? Only as a deus ex 
machina. Aristotle substitutes for the static conception of 
‘participation’ and ‘conjunction’ (μέθεξις, συνουσία, Met. 
H. 6) his own idea of growth and development. 

(2) After his exposition of Platonism in Met. A. 6, 
Aristotle considers it ‘obvious from what he has said’ 
(φανερὸν ἐκ τῶν εἰρημένων) that Plato recognizes only two 
causes—formal and material. From the Platonic dia- 
logues themselves a very different impression results. 
Already Alexander asks the question why Aristotle 
refuses to allow to Plato efficient and final causes. But, 


1 Met. A. 9. 992 Ὁ 7 περί τε κινήσεως, εἰ wey... εἰ δὲ μή, πόθεν ἥλθεν᾽; cf. also 
Phys. T. 2. 201 Ὁ 20 ἔνιοι, ἑτερότητα καὶ ἀνισότητα καὶ τὸ μὴ ὃν φάσκοντες εἶναι 
τὴν κίνησιν. 


2 Phys. ii. 3. τοῦ b 21. 


6o Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


to illustrate Plato’s recognition of them both, Alexander 
might have appealed to much more telling passages than 
those he quotes from the 77maeus and the Seventh Epistle. 
Thus (a) in the statement at least of universal efficient 
cause, no one could be more emphatic than Plato. In 
the Sophist the production of animals, vegetables, and 
minerals is assigned to ‘God the Artist’ (θεὸς δημιουργῶν). 
In the Philebus the cause of the mixture of Limit and 
Unlimitedness (τῆς συμμίξεως ἡ αἰτία) is thereby the cause 
also of genesis, and may be identified with active power 
and ‘artist’ (δημιουργός). Sophist, Timaeus, Philebus, Laws 
are in this respect alike." 

Similarly (ὁ) as to final cause, not to mention the descrip- 
tion of the Ideas as Archetypes (παραδείγματα) and of the 
Idea of Good in the Republic as not merely highest efficient 
but also final cause of the universe, there is to be found in 
the Philebus, where Plato completes his theory of causation, 
both divine and human, and indicates the four Aristotelian 
causes, the very closest parallel to Aristotle’s description 
of the Deity as the final cause of the universe for which all 
the rest of creation yearns and strives.?, And in Plato’s 
latest writing, in one and the same passage along with 
universal efficient cause (ὁ τοῦ παντὸς ἐπιμελούμενος), We have 
the following explicit assertion of final cause*: ‘Each 
part of the universe ... has the whole in view. This 
and every other creation is for the sake of the whole, and 
in order that the life of the whole may be blessed. You 
are created for the sake of the whole and not the whole 
for the sake of you. Every physician and skilled artist 
does all things for the sake of the whole, directing his 


ἦν. Campbell, Sophist, Introd., p. 76. 
, Even here, however, it is noteworthy that the distinctive note of Aristotle’s 
conception is wholly lacking—xive? ds ἐρώμενον. 


* Laws 903 B-C. For explicit assertion of soul as αἰτία μεταβολῆς τε καὶ 
κινήσεως ἁπάσης, ν. 896 A-B. 


A ristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 61 


effort toward the common good, executing the part for 
the sake of the whole.’ 

Aristotle then does not do justice to Plato’s aetiology. 
At the same time, if the following considerations be taken 
into account, it will be seen that it is in no spirit of grudg- 
ing depreciation that he finds deficiencies in his master’s 
doctrine. 

(2) As appears from the words φανερὸν ἐκ τῶν εἰρημένων, 
Aristotle is thinking not of the Platonic dialogues but of 
Plato’s lectures—especially those ‘On the Good’. Now 
in these the dynamical interest seems to have been entirely 
overshadowed by the ontological.! 

(ὁ) Aristotle does not wholly deny Plato’s recognition 
of final and efficient causes. As to the former, Aristotle 
says that in a sense it was postulated by Plato, only not 
gua final. ‘That is, Plato identifies it with the formal cause, 
and it is only an ‘accident’ of the formal cause that it 
happens at the same time to be good. The Ideas are 
final causes, not ἁπλῶς, but only κατὰ συμβεβηκός. As to 
efficient cause, Plato, like other philosophers, ‘saw it as it 
were in dream.’? In other words, Plato wished indeed to 
make his Ideas efficient powers, but seeing that this is 
what in Aristotle’s opinion they cannot be, Aristotle can 
on occasion deny to Plato’s system the recognition of any 
efficient cause whatever. In a similar vein he says that 
no one has clearly assigned even the formal cause,® though 
the Idea-philosophers (οἱ τὰ εἴδη τιθέντες) come nearest it. 
This simply means that Plato’s formal cause is not quite 
the same as his own. It will be obvious, therefore, that 
(1) Aristotle’s account of the system presupposes his criti- 
cism of it, and (2) he refuses to recognize Plato’s ‘maker 
and father of the universe’ as any scientific explanation, 


1 y, Alexander on A, 6. 988 a τι (Rose, p. 42). 
2 De Gen, Corr. ii. 9. 335 Ὁ 8 544. ® Met. A. 7. 


E2 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


and thus eliminates efficient cause from the Platonic 
metaphysic.' 

(Ὁ Finally, it is easy for us now to see in the Dialogues, 
notably the Philebus, anticipations of Aristotle’s doctrine of 
the four causes, but only because Aristotle himself has 
brought to clear and definite expression the various scat- 
tered hints of his master’s teaching. Nor can it be denied 
that the Platonic exposition leaves much to be desired, as 
regards both clearness and adequacy. Aristotle feels this 
so strongly with reference to Plato’s external, as contrasted 
with his own immanent, teleology that, forgetting his own 
concession elsewhere, he once roundly asserts that the 
final cause is ‘not touched by the Ideas’.2 Again, what 
is the relation of the Idea of the Good to other ends 
(Ideas) or to the special functions (épya)* of things? 
Efficient causes Plato attributes at one time to Ideas, at 
another to soul: which is his real doctrine? and what is 
the relation of Idea to soul? Aristotle, therefore, while 
willing to admit that Plato made ‘stammering’ efforts 
in the direction of efficient and final causes,* was _per- 
fectly justified in thinking that he had not ‘fully worked 
them out’. | 

It is now possible to sum up the positive results arrived 
at :- 

1. The evidence is against the supposition that Aristotle 
has misapprehended the Platonic first principles. 


* If 6 θεός is simply popular in Plato for the highest Idea (cf. Zeller, Plato, 
E, Το p. 267), then since Aristotle holds there is no efficiency in the Ideas, 
efficient cause will naturally in his view disappear from the Platonic system as 
a whole, 

; A. 9. 992 a 32. 5. Cf. Eth, Eud., i. 8. 1218 a 30. 

Met. A. το. 993 a 15. In Aristotle’s ‘ favourite phrase’ (cf. A. 4. 1070 
Ὁ 10) τρόπον μέν τινα πᾶσαι (sc. αἱ αἰτίαι) πρότερον εἴρηνται, τρόπον δέ τινα 
οὐδαμῶς. 


ἢ Alexander on A. 6. 988 a 11 (Hayduck, p. 59. 30-60. 2), Rose, p. 42 ἀλλ᾽ 


> 2 
οὐδὲ ἐξειργάσατό τι περὶ αὐτῶν. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 63 


2. Aristotle is correct in what he says of the contents of 
the Ideal world. 

3. On the Ideal numbers Aristotle is at cross purposes 
with Plato. Each is right in asserting what the other 
denies. | 

4. Aristotle has exaggerated, but not caricatured, the 
transcendent objectivity of the Platonic Idea. The Par- 
menides problem is still unsolved. 

5. Aristotle is severe on the Platonic aetiology, but not 
without justification. 

Before completion of the inquiry, by showing how far 
the peculiar characteristics of Aristotle’s censure of Plato 
admit of explanation on general principles, it will be well 
to consider very briefly a few of the main criticisms in the 
field of Physics, Ethics, and Politics.’ 


B. Aristotle’s Criticisms of the ‘ Timaeus’. 


As to Physics, a volume might be written on the criticisms 
of the Zzmaeus alone. Aristotle paid particular attention 
to this dialogue, not for its metaphysics and its mysticism— 
like the Neoplatonists—but because it contained all that 
Plato had to say on Aristotle’s favourite subject—the 
natural sciences and biology. With its myths and its 
mystical mathematics it must have roused all the scientific 
spirit of Aristotle into opposition, and that no radical mis- 
understanding, and certainly no conscious unfairness, can 
be proved against him even here is strong proof of the 
painstaking consideration? which Aristotle gave to all 
Plato’s opinions, and of the deep respect which he always 
paid to the memory of his great master. 


+ For Aristotle’s criticism of Plato’s Logic, especially of the method of 
διαίρεσις, v. H. Maier, Die Syllogistik des Aristoteles, ii. 2, chapter 1, § 3 (‘ Die 
Entdeckung des Syllogismus’), pp. 56 sqq. 

* Bacon misconceived this when he compared Aristotle to the Turk (sore 
Ottomanorum), 


64 Antstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


τ. Thus it is at first surprising that Aristotle, in pro- 
ceeding to discuss growth and qualitative change,’ should 
say that Plato’s investigations extended only to generation 
and destruction, and not even to all generation but only to 
the generation of the elements. ‘As to how flesh or bones 
or anything of that kind came into being, he has made no 
investigation.’ Now these latter subjects certainly are 
considered in the Zzmaeus,2 and Plato has also there 
treated—though very briefly—of growth and decay (αὔξησις 
and φθίσις), but if we look at what Plato says about them 
Aristotle’s language is easily explained. Aristotle could 
have no sympathy with an account which, he might have 
said, made marrow out of tiny triangles ὃ and ‘imported ’* 
the Deity (ὁ θεός) ὅ into a scientific explanation. In fact it 
is clear that Aristotle passes over Plato’s account deliber- 
ately, for he goes on to say, ‘ Not one of these subjects 
(qualitative change and growth) has been treated in any- 
thing but a superficial way by any one except Demokritos 

. no one has said anything about growth which might 
not equally well have been said by anybody’ (ὅτι μὴ κἂν 
ὃ τυχὼν εἴπειεν), Moreover, in other works, Aristotle does 
nete Plato’s view of respiration and his theory on the 
absence of flesh from the cranium, both of which come in 
the passage of the Zimaeus which is here overlooked. 
Aristotle, it is plain, never minces words, but it is only 
a very abstract view that can discover detraction or un- 
fairness in this passage, and in the implied contrast of 
Demokritos with Plato and the Pythagoreans. 


1 De Gen. Corr. i. 2, 315 a 26. ? 973 566. 

ὅ Tim. 73 B. As Aristotle had already refuted Plato’s derivation of the 
elements, he might well in any case think himself able to dispense with special 
notice of his theory here (De Gen. Corr. i. 2). 

* Eth. i. 6 εἰσαγαγ εἴν τὰ εἴδη. " Tim. 73 B, 74 D, ὅς. 

® 315 234 ὅλως δὲ παρὰ τὰ ἐπιπολῆς περὶ οὐδενὸς οὐδεὶς ἐπέστησεν ἔξω Δημοκρίτου 
κτλ, The phrase ὃ μὴ κὰν ὁ τυχὼν εἴπειεν recurs in Meteor, i. 13. 349 a 16. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 65 


2. As is well known, Aristotle takes the TJimaeus 
literally almost throughout,! and an interesting passage 
in the De Caelo* shows him to have been perfectly aware 
of the reproaches that might be made against him for 
doing so. According to Xenokrates and other defenders 
of Plato (τινες), Plato’s declaration that the world had ‘come 
into existence’ was intended merely ‘for purposes of 
exegesis’ (διδασκαλίας χάριν), just as a geometrical in- 
structor may represent the gradual ‘coming into exis- 
tence’ of a geometrical figure. Aristotle replies that the 
parallel will not hold. It is possible to showa geometrical 
figure in the making, but there all the parts can exist simul- 
taneously. In the question at issue, however, ‘when they 
say that out of chaos there comes to be a cosmos, these 
cannot be simultaneous ; they are prior and posterior, and 
to separate off what are prior and posterior there must 
necessarily be generation and time.’* This objection, 
which is perfectly valid as against Xenokrates, only proves, 
according to Zeller,* that not only Aristotle, but even 
Plato’s defenders as well, did not recognize the full 
extent of the mythical in the 77maeus, the chaos itself 
being simply part of the allegory. 

Now this illustrates admirably the difficulty of ever 
coming to an anchor when once embarked on the sea of 
mythical interpretation. Every one will allow it to be 
mythical when the ‘Demiurge’ in the T7zmaeus® mixes 

various ingredients in a mixing-bowl. But soon real diffi- 
culties begin. Aristotle, with his usual acumen, pointed 


1 The one exception seems to be the δημιουργός, on whom Aristotle is silent, 
The word in the Platonic sense occurs only once in all his writings—in one of 
the early dialogues (Rose, p. 29). 

2 i, 10, 279 Ὁ 33. 

3 Whereas in the case of διαγράμματα, οὐδὲν τῷ χρόνῳ κεχώρισται. Cf. on the 
whole passage Simplicius (Schol. 468 b 42), 

* Plat. Stud., p. 211. 5 41D. 


E 


66 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


out as a contradiction in the 77maeus that Plato ‘ generates. 
time intime’! Xenokrates, to meet Aristotle, puts forward 
an attempted solution. Aristotle refutes this and straight- 
way others, to meet the refutation, declare that the chaos 
also is ‘pure allegory’. Zeller does not agree with the 
Neoplatonists in taking ‘ figuratively’*® Plato’s derivation 
of the elements, Yet, as Simplicius naturally asks, When 
so much of the 7imaeus must be taken metaphorically, why 
not this also? 

In short, even had Aristotle adopted this method of criti- 
cism with full deliberation, he would still have been justified. 
Better the literal interpretation of Aristotle than the 
allegorical methods of the Neoplatonists. Whichever 
method be adopted, the words are still true which Aristotle 
uses of the Zzmaeus on another question, that what is 
written there ‘has no explicitness’.2 The Z7imaeus, as 
Hegel puts it, is ‘the most difficult and most obscure 
among the Platonic dialogues’, and though the authority 
of Aristotle need not establish zs way of taking the 
Timaeus to be the only one, that he did take it literally is 
certainly no proof of his inability to read aright the strictly 
philosophic doctrines of Plato.* 

3. Again, in Psychology, Plato’s doctrines of the world- 
soul meets with no gentle treatment. His ‘ probable tale’ 
(which Plato himself had admitted might not be found 


1 Physics Θ. 1. 251 Ὁ 17 566. 

* συμβολικῶς, Simplicius, De Caelo iii. 252 Ὁ 23 (v. Baumker, Das Problem der 
Maiterie, p. 169), Why not also ‘the diremption of the soul’. 

ὃ οὐδένα ἔχει διορισμόν, De Gen. Corr, B. 1.329a138qq. Aristotle is saying that 
it is impossible to make out from the Timaeus whether Plato’s matter can exist 
otherwise than in the form of the four elements. He is thinking of the so-called 
‘secondary matter’, which certainly does introduce a difficulty into the question 
Aristotle is discussing, whether matter can exist χωριστή. Archer-Hind miscon- 
ceives the passage (Timaeus, Ὁ. 179). 

* Cf. Gomperz, Griechische Denker, vol. ii, pp. 483 sqq., on the difficulties of the 
Timaeus. He finds Aristotle justified. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 67 


‘everywhere and in all respects consistent and accurate’)? 
is taken by Aristotle with complete literalness and criticized 
accordingly. ‘In the first place then,’ he begins, ‘it is not 
correct to say that the soul is a magnitude’ (μέγεθος). 
This sounds at first extremely unfair, as we know that to 
Plato the soul is immaterial. By magnitude, however, it 
must be remembered, Aristotle means geometrical magni- 
tude, ‘quantity gua measurable’® (e.g. a mathematical 
line). 

Now the Platonists, as is known from various evidence, 
disputed as to whether the soul was arithmetical or 
geometrical, a number or a magnitude, but they had no 
doubt as to its being one of the two. Zeller thinks Plato 
had not expressed himself definitely in favour of one view 
or the other, and left the relation of soul to his mathematical 
principle (τὰ μαθηματικά) undetermined *; hence the diver- 
gence on this question between Speusippos and Xeno- 
krates, the latter defining soul as ‘a self-moving number’, 
Consequently Aristotle has not grossly misinterpreted 
the mathematical description of the Zzmaeus, and his 
‘amusing literalness’® may, after all, be no great injustice, 
though we feel that Plato does\not bear at any time to be 
interpreted so literally and dogmatically.® 


Still the chapter in De Anima’ is by no means open to 
the charge of ‘quibbling commonplaceness’.® It is not a 
sympathetic criticism (since it does not allow for possible 
development of opinion on Plato’s part), but it is nevertheless 
perfectly correct to point out that there is a fundamental 


1 Tim, 29 C. 2 De An. i. 3. 407 ἃ 2. 3 Met. Δ. 13. 1020 a 9. 

ἐν, Zeller, Plato (E. T.), p. 355 n. 5 Archer-Hind, Timaeus, p. 114. 

6 A more indulgent critic than it was Aristotle’s nature to be would have 
hesitated before ascribing to a great thinker such a patent contradiction as exists 
‘between the Phaedrus (245 E) and the Timaeus (34 B)in regard to eternal motion, 
v. Met. A. 1071 Ὁ 37 sqq. He would have asked: May not Plato’s meaning’ be 
other than the narrative form of the Z7smaeus compels his words to be 2 

7 406 Ὁ 25-407 Ὁ 26. 8. Wallace, De Anima, Introd., p. 36. 


ΕΞ 2 


68 Artstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


contradiction between the view of the 7zmaeus and that of 
the earlier Phaedo! in regard to the union of soul and 
body. When Aristotle further says on the perpetual 
motion of the world soul that this will be ‘ violent’? and that 
consequently the soul will enjoy no opportunity for ‘leisure 
or rational amusement’, but will have ‘the lot of an Ixion 
on his wheel’ (Ἰξίονος μοῖραν), there is here no unfairness 
whatever. Aristotle is careful to exclude all Matter from 
his own conception of the ‘transcendent mind’ or of Deity, 
and simply makes his point here in the most vivid way at 
his disposal. 

Further, Aristotle is strongly opposed to the Platonic 
view that movement is a predicate of soul, or that soul 
is the selfmovent.t Again, his fundamental objection to 
all theories of the class to which Plato’s belongs is that 
they assume it as possible for any soul to clothe itself in 
any body ‘after the manner of the stories of the Pytha- 
goreans’. As well expect a carpenter, says Aristotle, to 
do his work with a flute. Aristotle’s real criticism of Plato 
is simply his great conception of soul as the ‘form’ or 
‘realization’ of the body, and his real difference from 
Plato, here as elsewhere, comes out not so much in his 
dialectical criticisms as in the course of his own scientific 
exposition. Every one, nevertheless, will acknowledge the 
applicability of his criticism of Plato’s ‘faulty psychology’, 
however Aristotle himself may have failed to maintain the 
organic unity of soul.® 
_ 4. Asto the nature of Platonic matter, Aristotle’s opinion 
is that Plato gives space as its essential definition, i.e. 
identifies matter and space. ‘This interpretation, though 
often called in question,’ still holds the field. 


᾿ 407 Ὁ 1-5. 3207 Β., 3 De Caelo Β. τ. 284 ἃ 27. 
i 407 a 32. ὶ 5 407 Ὁ 13 564. ® 4rrbs. 
One of the difficulties is that Plato strenuously rejects ‘the void’ and so 


A ristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 69 


In one passage,' however, Aristotle’s method of reading 
philosophy backwards results in a considerable variation 
from his usual account. He says that Plato identified 
Matter with ‘privation’, i.e. the direct contrary of Form. 
Teichmiiller stigmatizes this ‘unheard-of reproach’ as a 
‘crying injustice’? to Plato. But Aristotle’s statement is 
very easily explicable, and he has himself (even in this very 
passage) supplied us with the means of checking his own 
deductions.? He is discussing Plato’s Matter from the 
point of view of his own system, according to which 
Matter and privation are differentiated from each other. 
Now Aristotle is correct in saying that Plato had not " 
distinguished these two, and the Platonic Matter, more- 
over, is certainly not that of Aristotle, whose concep- 
tion was very different. But to say therefore that 
Plato identified his Matter with Aristotle’s privation is 
—while a natural enough conclusion—plainly quite un- 
justifiable. 

Connected with this is the question whether Aristotle 
means to include Plato among those who said Matter was 
‘the bad’. If he did, this would be another injustice to 
Plato, arising from the above identification. For if, in 
Plato’s system, Matter is simply the ‘ privation’ of the One, 
i.e. the Good, plainly Matter is identical with Evil. But 
though Aristotle states that Plato makes Matter ‘the ground 
of evil’ and refers to its ‘baneful power’ on the Platonic 
theory, it is almost certainly Xenokrates alone to whom he 
alludes as identifying Matter with ‘the evil principle’, and 


often uses its impossibility to explain certain phenomena that he may be 
called the author of the theory of horror vacui; v. Baéumker, pp. 179-80, on 
this difficulty. 

1 Physics i. 9. 

2 ‘eine schreiende Ungerechtigkeit’ (Studien zur Geschichte der Begniffe). 

3 192 a 10 μέχρι μὲν yap δεῦρο προῆλθον ὅτι δεῖ τινὰ ὑποκεῖσθαι φύσιν «KTd., 
which means that the Platonic matter after all is more than ‘non-being’. 


70 Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 


therefore of this further misconstruction of Plato Aristotle 
stands acquitted.’ 

4. Still less reason is there for impugning the value of 
the authority of Aristotle on the question of Plato’s deri- 
vation of the elements. According to Mr. Archer-Hind, 
‘Plato was presumably as well aware as any one else of the 
impossibility of forming solids by an aggregation of mathe- 
matical planes... it is entirely preposterous to suppose 
that the most accomplished mathematician of his time was 
not fully alive to a truth which, as Aristotle himself admits, 
ἐπιπολῆς ἐστὶν idciv.”? But not only have we the plain 
evidence of the 7zmaeus that in this respect Plato was still 
under Pythagorean influence; the Academy after him, as 
we learn from Aristotle,? and as we have seen above, 
maintained the same doctrine, viz. that solids could be 
built up out of planes. As Zeller says, ‘Aristotle here 
understands the Platonic doctrines quite correctly.’ * Even 
M. Milhaud, who is not disposed to underrate the Platonic 
mathematics and on this point suggests a new explanation 
by taking Plato’s space as ‘full space’, admits that Plato’s 
theory is ‘an extremely curious one’.’ Milhaud is cer- 
tainly wrong, however, in saying that Aristotle in this 
connexion ‘confounds Demokritos with Plato’*® In a 

? A. 10,1075a35 τὸ κακὸν αὐτὸ θάτερον τῶν στοιχείων ; cf. Θ. 9; Ν. 4.τορῖ Ὁ 35 
τὸ ἄνισον = ἡ τοῦ κακοῦ φύσις. Bonitz (p. 588) thinks Plato alluded to as well as 
Xenokrates in this last passage. He refers in proof however merely to 
A. 6 fin. (988 a 14), which says that according to Plato evil is caused by ὕλη ; cf. 
τὸ κακοποιὸν αὐτῆς (Phys, i. 9. 192 a 15). It is expressly said to be Pythagorean 
to set up κακόν and ἀγαθόν as absolute opposites (Met. A. 5. 986 a 26). Baumker 
(pp. 205-6) thinks this doctrine of Matter as ‘the bad’ can be ascribed to the 
oe Plato, but it has not been shown even that Aristotle does so. 

Archer-Hind, Timaeus, p.202n. This is but one among many instances of 
the partisan spirit in which throughout his edition of the Zimaeus he champions 
Plato at the expense of Aristotle. Cf. p. 184, where Aristotle is declared to 


ty ‘no right’ to contradict the nineteenth-century hypothesis of Dr. Jackson. 
Met. A. 9. 992 a 10-23 with Alexander ad loc. 


4 
: Zeller, Plato (E. T.), p. 375 n. > Milhaud, pp. 299, 320. 
Milhaud, p. 303, 


Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 71 


striking passage! Aristotle expressly distinguishes the 
logical atomism of Plato and Xenokrates from the physical 
atomism of Demokritos. The latter, he says, put his trust 
in theories that were ‘physical, i.e. appropriate to his 
subject’; Plato, on the other hand, had never been ‘at 
home in the physical sciences’.? 

5. Finally, a very interesting problem is presented by 
a passage in Aristotle’s De Caelo.* Aristotle is discussing 
the question ‘Is the earth stationary or not ?’ and, 
according to the reading of Simplicius and the best 
manuscripts, writes as follows: ‘Some say that the earth 
rests on its centre and is piled up about and revolves 
around the axis of the universe, as we read in the 77maeus,’ 
It is now universally admitted that Plato thought of the 
earth as stationary, and the only question is, How explain 
the remark of Aristotle? Has he misread the 7imaeus 
and misrepresented Plato ? 

Gomperz‘ thinks Aristotle is alluding to Plato’s conver- 
sation or lectures after the date of the 7zmaeus, and finds 
a confirmation of his view in a passage of the Laws® where 
Plato alludes in a mysterious way to the newly promulgated 
doctrine of the youngest Pythagoreans, that the earth 
revolves on its axis. The passage, however, does not 
support this hypothesis,* and had Aristotle heard the 
doctrine from Plato personally he would have said so. 
Undoubtedly the right explanation is that Aristotle is here 


1 De Gen. et Corr. i. 2. 315 Ὁ 30sqq. With equal explicitness Plato is con- 
trasted with Leukippos in i. 8. 325 Ὁ 25. 

2 ὅσοι ἐνῳκήκασι μᾶλλον ἐν τοῖς φυσικοῖς KTA., 316 a 6. 

8 De Caelo ii. 13. 293 Ὁ 30 εἱλεῖσθαι καὶ κινεῖσθαι περὶ κτλ, The above trans- 
lation would be the literal one (εἱλεῖσθαι, ‘formed into a ball,’ “ globed round’) ; 
but probably the two words are used synonymously, καί being explicative. 
The Berlin text gives ἴἔλλεσθαι περὶ, omitting καὶ κινεῖσθαι. 

* Griechische Denker, ii, p. 609 n. > vii. 821 sqq. 

6 Moreover, Aristotle says nothing about the earth’s own axis, but, like the 
Timaeus (40 C), uses the phrase ὁ διὰ παντὸς τεταμένος πόλος, i. €. ‘ the axis of the 
universe’. 


72 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


speaking of the interpretation given to the words in the 
Timaeus by the later Platonists, who returned to the old 
Pythagorean doctrine that the earth with the other heavenly 
bodies revolved around the central ‘fire’. The Platonists 
misinterpreted the semi-obsolete? word which had been 
used by Plato in the 77maeus; and Aristotle, whether he 
made this mistake himself or not, gives to the passage the 
interpretation of contemporary Platonism. 


C. Criticisms in the Polttics. 


Hegel’s fine remark, that Plato was ‘not ideal enough’, 
applies to his metaphysics when he is compared with 
Aristotle, but hardly to his Ethics and Politics. Here 
we feel that of the two great philosophers the deeper 
mind was Plato’s. Hence it is no mean testimony to the 
fairness and ability of Aristotle as a critic that his discus- 
sion of Plato’s Republic in the second book of the Politics? 
is generally admitted to be not merely the best of all his 
criticisms of his master, but at the same time one of the 
most interesting and trenchant passages in the whole of 
the Politics. The crispness of the language, the neatness 
of the rejoinders, the practical common sense with the philo- 
sophic penetration that goes beyond it, the judicious sanity 
of its estimate of revolutionary schemes, have made it 
a model of criticism for all time. It is a thoroughly 
gentlemanly criticism,’ and the odd nature of certain of 

1 Semi-obsolete, i.e. in the sense which Plato still gave to it. On the 
whole passage, v. Journ. of Phil. v, p. 206 (Campbell), The Platonists natu- 
rally took the word εἱλλομένην to mean ‘rolling’; cf. Arist. Meteor. 356 a 5, 
where it is used in this sense; v. further on the passage, Zeller, Plato (E. T.), 


pp. 380-1 n., and Archer-Hind’s note on Timaeus 40 B (pp. 132-3). 

* Politics ii. 1 sqq. 

* Its real philosophic character may be better appreciated if it is compared 
with the attitude of others who have taken it in hand to castigate Plato, 
whether in the tone of rabid abuse or ridicule which Plato himself anticipated 


(Rep. v) or in the narrow, prejudiced and offensive manner of De Quincey 
(v. his collected works, Masson, vol. Vili). 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 73 


the objections, coupled with the presence of one or two 
at first sight inexplicable misapprehensions, admits, we 
shall see, of very easy explanation. 

The tone of the chapter on the Laws is different.’ It is 
occupied exclusively—apart from the question of over- 
population—with what are, comparatively speaking, details, 
and has been excellently called a ‘somewhat grumbling 
criticism’.? The reason is fairly obvious; the constitution 
of the Laws—though the mathematics and religion of that 
work give it a wholly different appearance from the 
Politics—is really very close to that of the ideal state of 
Aristotle himself. He had reason enough for being dis- 
satisfied with the Laws* and his real criticism is the 
Politics itself. But, whereas in the case of the Republic 
he could easily point out a sufficient number of ἀπορίαι 
to justify him in constructing a new ideal state, this is not 
so easy with the Laws. Hence the criticisms in general 
are trivial and in some cases unjustified.* 


D. Criticisms in the Ethics. 


As for the famous criticism in £v¢hics i. 6 only three 
brief remarks may here be made :— 

(a) This is one of the clearest of the cases in which 
Aristotle’s arguments, when compared with the exposition 
of his own doctrine as a whole, are seen to be mere 
Socratic fence. There is a great difference between the 
two philosophers, both on the special question of teleology, 
and on the connexion of Ethics with Metaphysics, and 
morality with religion. But this is not brought out in the 
criticism at all. 

(5) The contention® that the Aristotelian categories 


1 Politics ii. 6. 2 Newman, ii, p. 264. * Newman, i, pp. 449-54. 

ἐν, Newman’s notes, ii, pp. 264-81, especially on 1265 a 39, 1265 Ὁ 19 and 22, 
1265 Ὁ 31, 1266 a I, a 13, a 17. 

5 y, Burnet, Evhics, Introd., p. 1. 


74 Aritstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


were accepted by the contemporary Academy would 
certainly make the arguments less unreal, and bring the 
passage more into accordance with Aristotle’s favourite 
method of refutation. But the evidence for such a sup- 
position is of the smallest, and Aristotle constantly 
elsewhere uses his logical engine of the Categories for 
purposes of overthrow. 

(c) It must be admitted at once that, as against the Plato 
of the dialogues, the criticism is a failure. The main 
point of the chapter seems to come, so to speak, in the 
postscript: the universal good is abstract and transcendent, 
χωριστὸν αὐτό τι καθ᾽ αὑτό. This might apply to the Republic : 
it certainly does not to the Philebus. But Aristotle is 
probably thinking little of either ; he has in view the Idea 
of the Good as it had become in the treatment of the 
Platonists, or indeed in the later treatment of Plato him- 
self, when he reduced the Ideas to Ideal numbers, and 
therefore naturally identified the Good with the One. 
To this One, Aristotle tells us, as also to the numbers, 
Plato attributed an existence independent of real things 
(παρὰ τὰ mpdypara),! ι 

The only other important criticism of Plato in the Ethics 
concerns the doctrine of pleasure. Aristotle has here also 
been supposed unfair to Plato, but in this case without 
reason. For (a) Zeller,? who talks of Aristotle’s ‘ perverse 
apprehension’ of Plato’s utterances on this subject, does 
not distinguish between Aristotle’s criticism in Book X of 
the Ev¢hics and that in Book VII. In the latter there is no 
reference to Plato whatever ; Aristotle attacks Speusippos 
or other theorists who had used the arguments of the 
Phaedo or Philebus to support an indictment against 
pleasure. (ὁ) In Ethics x. 3% Plato’s theory of pleasure 
as a γένεσις is attacked, and Aristotle at first sight conveys 


1 Met. A. 6. 987 Ὁ 29. 2 Plat. Siud., p. 283. 8 1173 a 31 566. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 75 


the impression that in his account of the ‘ painless’ delights 
of knowledge, sight, &c., he is stating an important new 
truth. But the explanation is that Plato had certainly 
attempted to explain even the ‘pure pleasures’ as πληρώ- 
ces! and so had supported the theory of pleasure as 
a γένεσις all along the line. The pure pleasures, though 
not preceded by pain, certainly are preceded by κένωσις 
and ἔνδεια, so long as these are imperceptible. Odours, 
on this theory, would be the food of the nostrils, and 
there would be pain felt at the absence of smell did not 
the κένωσις or depletion of the nostrils happen to be imper- 
ceptible. Aristotle simply asks if Plato can point out the 
ἔνδεια in the pleasures of knowledge, smell, sight, music, 
memory or hope. Plato would have to answer that it 
could not be shown, it was merely hypothetical, an assump- 
tion in order to make his theory consistent throughout. 
There is consequently nothing at all ‘disingenuous’? in 
Aristotle’s criticism. And though the other arguments are 
slighter, there is no excuse whatever for the remark that 
‘as usual, Aristotle’s objections miss the point’.® 


Conclusion. 


Nothing is easier than to cry out against Aristotle’s 
misunderstandings and perversions of his master’s meaning, 
but it is much more profitable to try what can be done by 
way of explaining them. As this explanation has already 
unavoidably formed great part of our inquiry as to how 
far Aristotle has actually misrepresented Plato, it only 

1 Tim. 65 A; cf. Phil. 51 B and Rep, 584 C. _ 

2 very disingenuous,’ Stewart, Ethics ii, p. 417, but his note on 1173 Ὁ 13 at 
once explains this statement and disproves it. 

8 Archer-Hind (Z7imaeus, p. 236), who mistranslates the passage Eth. x. 3. 
1173 b 5 (v. Burnet) and does not say a word of Aristotle’s most important 
argument. This is one of many cases in which it might be found that Aristotle 


is at a much less remove from ‘ King and Truth’ than his critics, and more 
correctly apprehends Plato’s thought than the Jatter’s would-be champions. 


76 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


remains to sum up under a few general heads some of the © 
main reasons which lend to the criticisms an appearance 
of perversity, captiousness or unfairness, which is really 
quite foreign to Aristotle’s intention. 

Fortunately there is here no question of any of the 
motives which actuated either Leibnitz’s criticisms of 
Spinoza or Schelling’s of Hegel. There is here nothing 
of that acrimonious hostility which has sometimes dis- 
graced the philosophy of the moderns; none of the 
systematic depreciation by Leibnitz of the arch-heretic 
Spinoza, to whom he owed so much; none of the bitter 
rancour with which Schelling pursues Hegel; none of the 
scurrilous abuse lavished on the latter by Schopenhauer. 
Of impatience in the criticisms, of causticity, of the pun- 
gency’ which is illustrated for us bythe surviving specimens 
of his wit, there is certainly no lack*; but of acrimony or 
personal ill-feeling a review of all the passages reveals no 
trace or shadow. Zeller has shown how little weight is 
to be attributed to the gossip of the ‘little men’ of a later 
age. Against the tales of an Aelian we have not only 
better evidence on the other side, we have the express 
testimony of Aristotle himself. In a famous sentence of 
the Ezhics he tells us that Plato and Plato’s friends were 
his friends, but not to the prejudice of the sacred claims of 
truth. In the Politics* he pays a graceful tribute to his 

ἦν. Stein, Leibnits und Spinoza, pp. 229, 252 sqq., &c., and for the relations 


of Hegel to Schelling v. Lecture on this subject included in Hutchison Stirling's 
What is Thought, &c., pp. 249 sqq. 


2 ν. the κάλλιστα ἀποφθέγματα in Diog. Laert. Bk. v. 11, §§ 17-20. 

ὃ τὰ γὰρ εἴδη χαιρέτω, κενολογεῖν, ἄτοπον καὶ ἀδύνατον, κενόν ἔστι παντελῶς 
(De Sensu 437 Ὁ 15) : Πλάτωνι μέντοι λεκτέον (Phys. iv. 2. 209 b 33): Met. Δ 
29. 1025 a 6 6 ἐν τῷ ‘Inmig λόγος παρακρούεται : Ν, 3. 1091 a 10: N. 4. τορι b 26 
πολλή τις εὐπορία ἀγαθῶν. 

* Politics ii. 6. 1265 a 11. We may compare one of Spinoza’s references to his 
father in philosophy, Descartes. In his theory of the ‘ Affects’, according to 


Spinoza, the ‘celebrated Descartes’ nihil practer magni sui ingenit acumen 
ostendit (Ethics-iii, Preface), 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 77 


master’s writings: ‘All the discourses of Socrates alike 
are characterized by brilliancy, grace, originality and the 
spirit of inquiry.’ 

Aristotle then might at least say that he ‘loved the man 
and did worship his memory this side idolatry as much as 
any’. But not only so, we have actually some evidence 
that Aristotle and Eudemos worshipped Plato as a god,} 
whom a bad man could not mention even in praise without 
blasphemy, and to whom even a worthy pupil, such as 
Aristotle, preferred to allude indirectly, so as not to ‘take 
his name in vain’. For what other reason does he so 
often criticize Plato in the plural number or as ‘ Socrates’, 
if not to avoid calling attention to the differences between 
himself and his revered master ? 2 

No explanation, therefore, can be accepted which refers 
to personal reasons, the constant sharpness or occasional 
unfairness of the criticisms. The theory of deliberate or 
purposive misunderstanding can at once be ruled out 
of court. 

To come then to verae causae. (1) Aristotle, some thir- 
teen years after Plato’s death, appeared at last as the head 
of anew school. As against the rival Academy he had to 
justify himself to the world for doing so, and he is therefore 
inevitably concerned to find differences from his master 
just where there was most appearance of indebtedness or 
similarity. In Leibnitz’s criticisms of Spinoza we find 
exactly the same thing ; only Leibnitz makes the assertion 


ἵν, Wilamowitz-Méllendorf on the well known elegy to Eudemos (‘ Aristo- 
teles und Athen’ sub fin.), . 

2 Similarly Aristotle (after the Topics) seems consistently to avoid express 
mention of Xenokrates, who was at the head of the contemporary Academy. 
We know that Aristotle and Xenokrates were great friends; yet the latter is 
certainly not spared in attack, e.g. in De An. i. 4. 408 b 32 his opinion is, of 
all those discussed, πολὺ ἀλογώτατον. Simplicius observes (Schol. 488 b 3) 
that it is always simply Plato’s δόξα which is the object of Aristotle’s attack. 


78 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


that there is no ‘Spinozism’ in any part of his teaching’ 
Aristotle, on the contrary—though for the above reason 
his direct expressions of agreement with Plato are fewer 
than they otherwise might have been—has yet, considering 
the impersonal nature of all his work,? rendered in the 
most unequivocal terms his τροφεῖα of gratitude for the 
master’s teaching. 

Teichmiiller,® it is true, holds that if Aristotle had been 
quite just to Plato he would have put his own services to 
philosophy in the shade, seeing that his own doctrine is 
nothing but a systematized Platonism. But neither state- 
ment is adequate, and certainly not the latter. Aristotle 
does advance beyond Plato, and he is mot ‘ throughout his 
works ’—if indeed he is at any time—‘a mere Eristic seek- 
ing to prove these advances against his predecessor.’ 
Teichmiiller exaggerates the element of opposition to 
Plato,* and takes one single explanation of it as by itself 
sufficient. 

(2) (a) Aristotle is arguing against contemporaries (of viv). 
The master had been dead for over fourteen years, but his 
more commonplace pupils in the Academy were living and 
active, and Aristotle, the founder of the biological sciences, 
had little sympathy with their Pythagorizing substitution 
of mathematics for concrete philosophy. 

(ὁ) It is Plato’s lectures rather than his written dialogues 
of which Aristotle is mainly thinking in his references. 
In the Tofics,® e.g. he cites three instances of novelty of: 

1 Stein, Leib. und Spin., p. 230. 

* καθάπερ καὶ 5 γενναῖος Πλάτων φησίν in De Mundo 7. 401 Ὁ 24 is just one 
of the indications that this work is spurious. It is felt at once that Aristotle 
could no more have written like this than Thucydides, 

* Studien zur Geschichte der Begriffe, Berlin 1874. 

* Thus it is nothing but the wish clearly to define his position that leads to 
the phrase ἡμεῖς δέ φαμεν after the statement or refutation of a theory of the 


Platonists or Plato (cf. De Genn. et Corr. 329 a 24, Phys, 192 a 3). 
5 vi. 2. 139 b 32. 


Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 79 


epithet from Plato, and not one of these is to be found in 
the dialogues.! Again, it is a very striking fact, that with 
all Aristotle’s attacks on the Ideal theory, only a single one 
of the Dialogues is ever alluded to in connexion with it. 
This is the Phaedo, and here he appeals no less than three 
times? to one identical passage* which seems to have 
strongly (and unfavourably) impressed itself on his memory. 
(c) Some of the misunderstandings are probably simply 
due to confused and imperfect recollection of passages 
which he did not trouble to refer to. Just as in his fre- 
quent quotations from Homer he may sometimes be very 
wide of the mark, as when he attributes to Calypso words 
which are not even those of Circe but are actually spoken 
by Odysseus to his pilot,* so in quoting Plato he constantly 
forgets the connexion. Thus in the sole reference that 
can be found in Aristotle to the Politicus® he has not only 
carelessly misquoted the passage, but alludes vaguely even 
to its author by the very extraordinary phrase ‘Some one 
in former time’ (Tis... τῶν πρότερον). Zeller® does not do 
justice to the strangeness of these words when he says 
that here ‘the definite person whom Aristotle is thinking 
about is more distinctly and clearly referred to’ than in 
the other anonymous mentions of Plato. "Ἔνιοι and τινες 
and οἱ λέγοντες are regular : TLS TOV πρότερον is unique. The 
reference remains ‘ singular though not unaccountable’.’ 
Again we are told that Aristotle had made abstracts or 


1 Cf. De Gen. Corr. ii. 3.330 Ὁ 16 καθάπερ Πλάτων ἐν ταῖς διαιρέσεσιν, and De Part. 
Anim, i. 2 (Zeller, Plato, E. T., pp. 46-7). 

- 2 One of these (Met. M. 5. 1080 a2) is a duplicate of A. 9. 991 b3. Theother 
is De Gen. Corr. ii. 9. 335 Ὁ το. 

8 Phaedo too B sqq. * Ethics ii. 9. T109 a 31. 

5 Politics iv. 2. 1289 Ὁ 5; cf. Polit. 303 A, B. 

δ Plato (E. T.), p.63 n. As we have seen, Aristotle’s mode of anonymous 
mention is not the indirectness of disparagement, as it is e. g. in Leibnitz’s 
‘Scriptor quidem subtilis at profanus’ (of Spinoza). 

7 Campbell, Introd, to Polit. p. 55. 


80 Artstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


epitomes of the Republic and Timaeus,' If, after doing so, 
he thought he might in future consult his memory in 
preference to documentary evidence, we have an explana- 
tion of occasional perversities of allusion.” Aristotle leaves 
us with the impression that he did not know the Republic 
so well as he ought to have done. 

(3). We have already seen traces of Aristotle’s intense 
dislike of the mythical in philosophy. In a passage of the 
Meteorologica* he says it is ridiculous (γελοῖον) to suppose, 
like Empedocles, that one has given any explanation by 
talking of the sea as ‘the sweat of the earth’, ‘For 
purposes of poetry, no doubt, this is adequate enough 
(metaphor being an adjunct of poetry), but for a scientific 
knowledge of nature it is not.’ This feeling appears already 
in the Zofics,t where, in the censure of some metaphorical 
definitions (all of them seemingly Platonic), it is remarked: 
‘Everything said metaphorically is obscure.’ Consequently 
he has a very real objection to Plato’s ‘ poetic metaphors ’.® 
Of Plato he might have reversed his dictum on Empedo- 
kles and said he was ‘a poet rather than a physicist ’,® just 
as even his language was half-way between poetry and 
prose.’ Aristotle for the first time introduces a definite 
philosophical style; so too he is for maintaining the 
independence and severity of science. He thought it high 
time that the mythical should be banished from philosophy. 
Its only raison a’étre is that the true facts are unknown or 
uncertain. And in such a case Aristotle thinks that the 
scientific procedure is to say 50---οὐδέν πω pavepov.® 


1 For the Zimaeus v. Simplicius on De Caelo 284 a 27 (the passage on the 
world soul), Schol. 491 Ὁ ; cf. Zeller, Arist, (E. T.), i. 62. 

2 e. g. Politics ii. 5. 1264 a 11, 36, b 15. But v. a/fra, pp. 86 and 87. 

3 ii. 3. 357 a 24. 4 yi. 2. 1396 Ὁ 32. 

5 He missed σπουδὴ ἀποδεικτική, A. 8. 1073 a 22. Ί 

5 φυσιολόγον μᾶλλον ἢ ποιητήν of Empedokles (Poetics i. 1447 b 19). 

Τ᾿ Diog. Laert. iii. 37 (Rose, p. 78). 

8 De An, ii. 2. 413 Ὁ 25; cf. 403 a 8 and Rodier ad loc, 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 81 


In spite of all this it still no doubt remains unfair to 
treat Plato’s poetry as though it were science. But if 
Aristotle (conformably with his own principles) had refused 
to take any notice at all of Plato’s ‘fairy tale of science’, he 
would have been thought still more unjust. As it is he 
never says of any of Plato’s opinions what he does say of 
the Pythagorean notion of time, that it is ‘too ridiculous 
to investigate its impossibilities ’. 

Parallel with the dislike of the metaphorical and the 
mythical is Aristotle’s objection to @ priori deductions in 
the field of Politics. This explains the sharpness of his 
criticism! on Plato’s ‘ideal history of evil’ in Books VIII 
and IX of the Republic. It is not the case that Aristotle 
‘seems to have understood Plato’s account as an attempt 
to describe the actual facts of Greek history’. This would 
be incredible in itself (for Aristotle could not suppose Plato 
to have been ignorant of the history of his own native 
Athens) and is refuted by a careful reading of the passage, 
_ Most of the objections are really on the basis of Plato’s own 
theory, though Aristotle follows them up at once with 
a statement of the actual facts. Aristotle, as he admits 
himself, is never an ‘indulgent’ critic,? and his concrete 
“mind is not satisfied with Platd’s attempt at a ‘ philosophy 

of history’. It is sound, he thinks, neither as the one nor 
as the other. 

(4) The great philosopher may write a valuable and 
_ excellent history of philosophy, as is proved by the first 
_ Book of Aristotle’s Metaphysics, and by its modern parallel, 
_ Hegel’s Lectures. But such histories will not be so reliable 
_ objectively as had they been written by lesser men; con- 
_ sequently we are not surprised to find the same charges 
made against Aristotle as have also been made against 


1 Politics v. τῷ. ἘΝ, 3. 1090 Ὁ 14. 


82 Aritstotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


Hegel. Aristotle, in a word, discusses previous thinkers 
from the standpoint of his own system. 

An excellent example is furnished by his investigation of 
the concept of Space.!' Plato had nowhere in the Zzmaeus 
expressly discussed the nature of Space as such. But 
Aristotle has asked himself as usual: ‘What have my 
predecessors taken Space to be?’ And the answer is 
perfectly natural and inevitable: Plato identifies it with 
Matter (ὕλη). Zeller, therefore, is quite correct in saying 
that ‘while Plato asks the question What is Matter? and 
answers Space, Aristotle asks the question What is Space ? 
and makes Plato answer Matter’.? Aristotle would himself 
have admitted that Plato’s problem after all had been differ- 
ent from his own; he says before beginning his inquiry, 
that he has no previous discussions to go upon.® 

Aristotle more than once in this way discusses under 
Physics what had been given by Plato as rather of meta- 
physical interest. A curious and somewhat different case 
is where Aristotle in the Meteorologica,* after discussing 
why the sea does not swell in volume with the mass of 
river water that flows into it, roundly declares that ‘what 
is written in the Phaedo® about rivers and the sea is im- 
possible’, and proceeds to ‘show how. This, as has been 
said, is like ‘testing the geography of Dante’s Jujerno 
by the laws and discoveries of physical science’. Still 
in a sense it is really more of a tribute to his master 
than a criticism. Aristotle is aware that Plato has no 
scientific theory on the question he is discussing, but 
he thinks it worth while giving an exposition. and 


criticism even of his mythical or probable account in the 
Phaedo. 


1 Phys. iv. 2. 2 Platonische Studien, p. 212. 
5 Phys. iv. τ. 208 a 35. * 355 b 34. 5 yr C, 
ον. Ὁ. Geddes, Phaedo, p. 151. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 83 


Still another example may be taken, this time from the 
Metaphysics. Aristotle says that Plato in the Sophist 
identifies ‘ Not-being’ with falsehood (τὸ ψεῦδος). Now 
Plato in that Dialogue proves that 2f τὸ μὴ ὄν is existent, 
then such a thing as ψεῦδος (ψευδὴς δόξα, ψευδὴς λόγος) 
becomes possible. But Aristotle, seeking to find an answer 
as to which of the three (Aristotelian) kinds of Not-being 
Plato had been thinking of when he used the word, has 
naturally but wrongly been led by the words of the Sophist 
to identify Plato’s ‘ Not-being’ with his own ‘not-being in 
the sense of the false’ (τὸ μὴ dv ὡς ψεῦδος). 

It is obvious that this ‘accommodating’ procedure will 
sometimes lend an appearance of great caprice to Aristotle’s 
interpretations of Plato. But even yet whole histories of 
philosophy are written under the shadow of the fallacy 
that the problems of one age or thinker are present in the 
same way to every other. 

(5) Aristotle is the analyst par excellence, and, aiming at 
definiteness and clearness of doctrine, he is not content till 
he has reduced every theory to the special yévos to which 
it belongs. This is a natural result of his subdivision and 
systematization of all the departments of philosophy. In 
Plato’s Republic we find together (even in the same book) 
Physics, Psychology, Ethics, Politics, Metaphysics; Aris- 
totle has separate compartments for all of them. The 
difference between the two minds comes out very clearly 
in a well-known passage of the Polttics,2 where Aristotle 
alludes to the ‘extraneous discourses’ with which Socrates 
has filled the Republic. We here, if anywhere, catch a 
glimpse of the real Aristotle from under his mask of 
impersonality, and the pupil who compiled the Magna 
Moralia reproduces the genuine spirit of his master when 


ΕΝ, 2. 1089 a 19. 
2 Politics ii. 6. 1264 Ὁ 39 τοῖς ἔξωθεν λόγοις πεπλήρωκε τὸν λόγον κτλ. 


F 2 


84 Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 


he says: Plato was wrong in mixing up virtue with his 
treatment of the Good—od yap oix eto.) 

This frame of mind will obviously not be the best for 
doing complete justice to Plato. Further it goes along 
with an attention to details and individual results, which 
lends to some of Aristotle’s remarks on Plato an appearance 
of very carping criticism—what Teichmiiller calls Krcttelez. 
But this only means that in the words of the Parmenides, 
philosophy has now taken a ‘ firm grip’,? and the philosophic 
thinker no longer fears the falling into some ‘ bottomless 
pit of absurdity’® by discussion of the seemingly trivial 
and unimportant. Plato in his later dialogues had him- 
self here shown the way. 

Nor again is it any discredit to Aristotle that his anim- 
adversions should often take the form of a criticism of 
language. Himself the creator of a technical philosophic 
vocabulary, he could not neglect the terminology of others. 
Thus his first few arguments against the Republic of Plato 
are ‘footnotes’ on the ambiguity of the words ‘unity’ and 
‘all’.* He was reproached for this tendency even in 
antiquity ; thus Philoponus® says (wrongly) that in re- 
proaching Plato for identifying space with ‘the participant’ 
and yet not locating the Ideas in space, Aristotle ‘as usual, 
attacks the mere word’ (viz. space). Similarly the modern 
critic, speaking of Aristotle’s discussion of Plato’s theory - 
of vision, says it is ‘impossible to exonerate it from the 
charge of ὀνομάτων Onpevois’.® But if so, the case in point 
would prove that philosophy was nothing else than the 
kind of ‘word-catching’ which Aristotle is here accused of. 
The passage (De Sensu c. 2) is quite fair. Plato had 
attempted to explain why we do not see in the dark.’ It 


1 Mag. Mor. i. τ. 1182 a 28. 2 Parm, 130 E. 3. Parm, 130 D. 
4 Politics ii. 2. 5 Quoted in Baumker, p. 1817. 
5 Archer-Hind on Timaeus, p. 157. 7 Timaeus 45 Ὁ sqq. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 85 


is because the light issuing from the eye is changed and 
‘extinguished’ when the air it meets has no fire in it. 
Aristotle replies that ‘extinction’ is here a wholly irre- 
levant concept; it applies to fire or flame, but neither of 
these terms can be predicated of light.) His own explana- 
tion makes no use of fire.” 

(6) Lastly, and most important of all, comes the fact we 
have so often had occasion to notice, that Aristotle’s criti- 
cisms are dialectical. This means strictly that they are argu- 
ments based not on true premises, but on premises admitted 
by the other side. But the word can be used loosely of 
all difficulties (ἀπορίαι) ὁ that rest on popular premises in 
general. The ‘aporetic’ method proceeds on the principle 
that if a sufficient number of shafts be levelled at a target, 
some of them at least are bound to hit the mark. In the 
Platonic dialogues Plato contrives to let us see when his 
arguments are not serious; in Aristotle, however, the 
method has stiffened, the procedure looks more dogmatic 
and more of an insult to the reader’s intelligence. Yet 
Aristotle himself tells us what to expect; his method is to 
register ‘all possible objections’ (ras ἐνδεχομένας dzopias).* 
And that he is true to this plan is easily proved. 

For (1) it is impossible otherwise to explain the frequency 
with which objections good, bad, and indifferent are heaped 
up together or jotted down in parenthesis with no regard 
for order and system, and no link of connexion except his 
favourite particle ἔτι. One excellent example among many 
is afforded in Metaphysics M, where after his main refutation 
of the Ideal numbers, the attack is renewed in c. 8, and 
a fusillade of varied objections follows, some of them of an 


1 437 Ὁ 15 sqq. 2 ν, De An. ii. 7; De Sensu c. 3. 

5 Also δυσχερῆ, δυσχέρειαι, ταραχή, δυσκολίαι. Syrian (in Met. 1080 a 9) calls 
the arguments against the Ideas ἐπιχειρηματικοὶ τόποι. 

* Met. A. 7. 988 b 21 τὰς ἐνδεχομένας ἀπορίας διέλθωμεν περὶ αὐτῶν. Then follows 
the criticism of the earlier philosophers (c, 8) and of the Academy (c. 9). 


86 Aristotle's Criticisms of Plato 


extremely questionable character. So again in the Podzttcs* 
Aristotle assumes in one passage that Plato’s community 
in women and children is to be limited to the guardians ; 
in another,? after propounding it as an open question 
whether, according to Plato, women, children, and property 
are to be held in common also by the agriculturists, he 
proceeds to set forth the difficulties on either supposition.® 
(2) Not only, for this reason, is it true that many of the 
criticisms are weak and do not seem to bite; others actually 
contradict Aristotle’s own rulings or remarks elsewhere. 
Thus one of the proposals of Plato’s Laws—that of the 
double homestead—which Aristotle criticizes in the Polizics* 
as fatal to domestic economy, is, after all, adopted by 
himself. So again he objects to the Platonists that they 
make matter the source of multiplicity, for ‘probabilities’, 
‘analogies’, and ‘first appearances’ are against such a 
ει view.’ At first one wonders if this passage is not a deser- 
tion of Aristotle’s own first principles, till it is remembered 
that Aristotle need not himself believe in the validity of 
the objections he presents to opponents. One more ex- 
ample may be cited, from a chapter which is full of 
argumenta ad homines as also ad Platonicos. ‘The doctor 
does not consider health in general, but the health of man, 
or rather of this particular man; it is the individual that 
the doctor cures.” Aristotle’s own doctrine recognizes 
both the particular and the universal side of the art of 
medicine, as of all arts*; but it is easy to see which side 


will be emphasized when he is making a point against the 
Platonists. 


1 1262 a 40. 2 1262 a 14. 

* There is therefore no unfairness: Plato’s position is being surveyed on all 
sides. Moreover the Laws shows Plato to have believed in communism as the 
true ideal for the whole state, v. Newman, Politics, Introd., p. 159. 

* 1265 b 25. 5 1330 a 14 566. 6 Met. A. 6. 988 a 1-7. 

7 Eth, i, 6. to97 ait. 8. Rhet. i. 1356 b 29, Eth. 1180 b 20, Mei, A. 981 a 15-20. 


Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 87 


Finally, under this head may be brought certain other 
arguments, of which we can only say that they are dictated 
by pure eagerness to score a point. We must allow for 
the combined pugnacity and pertinacity of Aristotle’s 
nature ; he was a very militant philosopher, and all is fair 
in the war against the Platonists. Thus, in reference to 
the Ideal numbers, he asks whence come the units that 
make up the Indeterminate Dyad?! Zhey must come from 
a Dyad also, and, as Alexander adds, it is a strange 
doctrine indeed that would make one come from two 
instead of vice versa. So again in the Evhics,? Aristotle 
‘plays the Philistine’ in his well-known gibe about ‘the 
weaver and the carpenter’. Similarly, in the Politics,’ 
Aristotle need not have been unaware of Plato’s real 
opinion as to the happiness of the guardians. It was a 
point in which his opinion really differed from that of his 
master ; and he simply yields to the natural temptation of 
quoting Plato in his own support. 

It may readily be admitted that Aristotle does not show 
to the best advantage in his criticisms of Plato. He is too 
full of his own point of view to be a sympathetic critic, and 
sometimes too near his master to be an effective one. 
Moreover, the thought of Plato refuses to be fettered 
within the categories of any system; the whole is more 
than the sum of its parts, the spirit of Platonism is more 
than the totality of its doctrines. But nothing could have 
been more wisely ordered by the ‘time spirit’ of Greek 
thought than that Plato’s work should be continued and 

1 Met. A. 9.991 b 31 with Alexanderadloc. Similarly he is perfectly well aware 
of the real nature of Plato’s ‘ great and small’, but at M. 8. 1083 b 23 he treats 
them as though they could be separated. 

2 i, 6. 1097 a 8. 

3 Politics ii. 5, § 27. ‘It seems incredible that any one who has read the 
beginning of Rep. Bk. iv should have so utterly misunderstood it’ (Campbell 


and Jowett, iii, pp. 162-3). It zs incredible. Aristotle in his ἀπορίαι need no 
more be taken always au pied de la lettre than Plato in the dialogues. 


88 Aristotle’s Criticisms of Plato 


extended by one so different in temperament, yet so like 
in universality of mind and enthusiasm for philosophy. 
It is not proved that Aristotle is guilty towards Plato of 
any fundamental misrepresentation; and Plato cannot be 
said to be fully known till he is re-read in the light of 
Aristotle. 


hed 
bene 


OOP ae ee ee eee eee 


Se eee, ee 


MPV ab eh ons ty 
a - 


OS ame vette aL 
- ‘ 


Aap δον ὁ ian 
ὩἝ τ 1 ae 
ina ei 
p Ὁ δ o 
MOM Hie ὦ, 4. 
ee 5 ῥ » ΓῚ 2m 
TAR ieee. : oa 
‘aber - “ξδιοθοκῶ ἡ a e 
ses ; 


τα 
"Φ namy 


95000.» onan 
~. kent, 

ν᾿ ene 

athere: cay 


φῆϑεέθ δόο, nae Tor ehteb. νὰ 


qenhandneanye 
+e eee, 
et eee 


SD ane anes » 
+ aA, 


1 One moni anne, 
> APO one ia, 
TPE ane. 


Neen 
ΩΝ 
. Melee ΡΝ 
7 . ἢ . 4). Ν 
᾿ : ate 
sqm ges 
ene a) 


᾿ Mn, “ 
ites J Melani Wevacmimn vat 
~ es ρέμα αν 
ΠΥ ῊΝ “,» « a — 4 
PM Ν 
ra 


HO OAD Bm ie aR wae, 


μ“ς 


μωμδονν οι 
ee Tee 
Ἂ i 
ἣ pee Mahia a ct » r . 
A Oe Rees M0698 tek, le, κι 


289 ἀπ. 


και neha AVON ONS conse 
Mme inhale Ane