Skip to main content

Full text of "Avenarius and the standpoint of pure experience"

See other formats


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Arciiive 

in  2010  with  funding  from 

University  of  Toronto 


http://www.archive.org/details/avenariusstandpoOObush 


r 

AVENARIUS 

AND  THE  STANDPOINT  OF 

PURE  EXPERIENCE 


BY 

WENDELL  T.  BUSH,  Ph.D. 

Lecturer  in  Philosophy  in  Columbia  University 


ARCHIVES  OF 
PHILOSOPHY,   PSYCHOLOGY  AND  SCIENTIFIC  METHODS 


BDITBD  BT 

.1.  McKEEN'  CATTELL  and  FBEDERICK  .J.   K.  WOODBHIDOK 


No.  2,  November,  1905 


Columbia  University  Contributions  to  Philosophy  and  Psycholofy,  Tol.  X.,  Mo.  4 


DLSSKRTATION 

Submitted  in  Partial  Fulfillment  of  the  Requirements  for  the  Deg^ree 

of  Doctor  of  Philosophy  under  the  Faoalty  of  Philosophy, 

Columbia  University 


NEW  YORK 
THE   SCIENCE    PRESS 


b 

320? 

£9  6? 


Pkiu  or 

Jul  Niw  En*  miMTiaa  CamntKT 

LANCASTIH,    Pk 


^-1 


10  0  6828 


CONTENTS 


PAGB 

INTRODUCTION  1 


APPRECIATIONS   OF   EXPERIENCE 

I.  The  independent  outer  world  is  an  object  not  of  reasoned 
belief  but  of  spontaneous  experience  which  philosophical 
theory  has  no  power  to  alter.  To  say,  however,  that  the 
independent  existence  of  the  outer  world  is  a  character- 
istic feature  of  normal  human  experience  is  to  say  noth- 
ing whatever  about  its  real  metaphysical  independence.  5 

II.     An  object  of  experience  need  not  be  of  the  sort  that  can 

be  presented  to  sense-perception 7 

III.  Avenarius:  his  way  of  describing  the  experience  of  know- 

ing something.     Knowledge  is  exf>erience  with  the  cog- 
nitive character 1) 

IV.  This   definition   of   knowledge   is    not   self-contradictory, 

since  it  makes  no  metaphysical  assumption  to  contradict. 

It  is  not  a  question-begging  term ]  4 

V.     Two  meanings  of  the  word  experience.     The  word  is  used 

here  to  mean  direct  cognition  of  fact 15 

VI.     There  is  a  natural  (not  necessarily  true)  view  of  the  world. 

This  is  naive  realism 16 

VII.  Distinction  between  the  Independent  and  the  Transcend- 
ent. Independence  is  a  character  of  objects  within  the 
field  of  experience.  Transcendence  means  existence 
without  necessary  reference  to  any  field  of  experience. 
The  outer  world  and  my  fellow  men  are  evidently  inde- 
pendent, and  they  are  characterized  in  normal  human 
experience  as  transcendent  also 22 

VIII.     Solipsism  can  not  be  logically  refuted,  but  this  makes  no 

difference  to  experience 25 

IX.  A  review  of  some  attempts  to  show  that  experience  guar- 
antees the  transcendent  object.  The  attempts  fail. 
Summary  of  the  discussion  thus  far 29 

iii 


»V  CONTENTS 

THE   DESCRIPTION   OF   EXPERIENCE 

I.  We  can  seek  to  give  a  psychophysical  account  of  pure 
cognitive  experience  and  this  will  not  be  a  metaphysical 
undertaking,  for  the  concepts  will  not  be  used  with  a 
metaphysical   purpose 34 

II.  The  concept  of  psychophysical  parallelism  is  employed  in 
the  interest  not  of  ultimate  explanation  but  of  descrip- 
tion   35 

III.  The  theories  of  Avenarius  are  not  concftrned  with  meta- 

physical problems w^i, 

IV.  Science    seeks    to    discover    the    *  How  *    of    experience. 

Metaphysics  seeks  to  discover  the  *  Why '  of  experience. 
The  experience  which  science  describes  and  metaphysics 
explains  is  experience  characterized  by  the  natural  view 
of  the  world 5f; 


THE  EXPLANATION  OF  EXPERIENCE 

I.  Explanation  in  metaphysics  differs  from  scientific  de- 
scription in  that  the  former  attaches  the  predicate  of 
existence  to  its  concept  of  reality.  The  demand  for  the 
existential  predicate  is  an  emotional  demand 60 

II.  The  new  epistemology  of  science  will  bring  it  to  pass  that 
reputable  philosophy  will  not  seek  reality  behind  and 
different  from  the  world  of  concrete  experience 61 


SUGGESTIONS   TOWARD   A   CONCEPT    OF   EXPERIENCE 

The  concept  suggested  is  that  of  the  historical  process 
which,  starting  from  animism,  has  led  to  the  modem 
concept  of  nature  elaborated  by  the  special  sciences. 
The  concept  is  suggested  in  the  interest  of  history 71 


AN   EMPIRICAL   DEFINITION   OF   CONSCIOUSNESS 

Consciousness  means  experience  that  can  belong  to  only 
one  observer.  Consciousness  thus  defined  ceases  to  be 
a  basis  for  idealism.  There  remains  the  natural  view 
of  the  world 73 


INTRODUCTION 

A  FEW  words  in  explanation  of  the  following  essay  may  not  be 
out  of  place.  AVhen  I  first  wrote  down  the  matter  of  the  essay,  some 
six  years  ago,  I  was  dissatisfied  with  the  metaphysical  alternatives 
from  which  the  student  of  philosophy  could  select.  The  study  of 
the  writings  of  Richard  Avenarius  heightened  my  dissatisfaction 
with  previous  metaphysics,  and  suggested  to  me  a  point  of  view 
for  a  fresh  start.  It  seems  to  me  that  discontent  with  established 
and  professional  metaphysics  has  become  quite  general  and  that 
a  fresh  start  is  very  generally  desired.  Well,  the  only  sound  thing 
to  start  from  is  actual  experience,  experience  not  viewed  through 
the  assumptions  and  dialect  of  previous  systems,  but  taken  in  an 
absolutely  empirical  fashion.  We  must  make  the  effort  to  beg  as 
few  questions  as  possible  at  the  outset.  If  we  are  rigorous  enough 
we  shall  discover  just  what  questions  we  have  to  bosr  and  why  we 
beg  them. 

This  return  to  the  empirically  given  is  the  standpoint  of  'pure 
experience.'  'Pure  experience'  means  at  present  a  point  of  view. 
It  is  premature  to  speak  of  a  philosophy  of  'pure  experience';  we 
do  not  yet  know  what  such  a  philosophy  will  have  to  say.  But 
there  can  be  no  question  that  the  point  of  view  is  the  right  one,, 
and  it  takes  something  of  a  struggle  to  win  it.  And  as  I  came  to 
the  point  of  view  through  Avenarius,  the  essay  includes  the  attempt 
to  restate,  in  a  relatively  independent  fashion,  what  seem  to  me  the 
essentials  of  his  doctrine. 

There  are  not,  however,  as  there  might  seem  to  be,  two  lines  of 
effort  neither  united  nor  clearly  distinguished.  I  think  I  may  claim 
to  express  the  views,  or  at  least  the  attitude,  of  Avenarius  all  the 
time.  An  account  of  the  philosophy  of  Avenarius  is  a  difficult 
matter,  not  because  the  thought  is  obscure  or  hard  to  follow,  but 
because  it  is  expressed  in  an  elaborate  and  novel  terminology  which 
can  hardly  be  omitted  altogether,  but  which,  if  introduced  to  any 
great  extent  into  an  exposition,  certainly  gets  between  the  reader 
and  the  thought. 

I  have  been  encouraged  in  this  undertaking  by  the  fact  that  no 
good  account  of  Avenarius  exists  for  English  readers.  The  article 
by   Carstanjen   in  Mind^    is   altogether   too   slight.      In   German, 

>  October,  1897. 
1  1 


2  AVENARIUB   A\D   PURE   EXPERIENCE 

Wundt's  criticism^  is  Miarked  by  a  hostile  polemical  K[)irit  that 
elfectually  interferes  with  its  usefulness.  In  French,  however,  the 
articles  by  Delacroix^  are  not  unsuccessful,  but  they  hardly  show 
how  much  can  be  f^otten  out  of  the  works  reviewed. 

I  have  spoken  of  this  essay  as  the  effort  to  reach  a  point  of  view, 
and  such  an  effort  must  have  reference  to  present  philosophical 
tendencies.  Every  student  of  metaphysics  has  pot  to  take  account 
of  idealism,  and  take  account  of  it  logically.  Idealism  claims  to 
rest  upon  demonstrable  facts  of  experience,  and  to  be  a  strictly 
logical  deduction.  The  really  candid  critic  must  inspect  experience 
as  impartially  as  he  can,  and  see  whether  the  premises  of  idealism 
are  really  all  that  they  claim  to  be.  That  is,  the  critic  must  place 
himself  at  the  standpoint  of  pure  experience,  and  putting  theories 
and  definitions  out  of  his  head,  mu.st  get  acquainted  directly  with 
those  aspects  of  experience  which  will  later  constitute  the  basis  of 
a  philosophy. 

This  effort  to  appreciate  experience  in  an  undistorted  way,  to 
take  it  as  it  comes,  not  checking  the  coming  by  a.sking  metaphysical 
questions,  but  simply  trying  to  see  what  comes,  is  what  concerns 
the  first  section  of  the  essay.  As  the  duty  of  squaring  myself  with 
idealism  looms  in  the  background,  it  is  the  independent  outer  world 
aspect  of  experience  that  interests  me  most.  The  thesis  of  my  first 
section  is  that  naive  realism  is  a  perfectly  correct  description  of 
experience  as  such,  but  that  this  does  not  make  it  a  true  meta- 
physical theory  of  existence.     It  may  be  true  and  it  may  not. 

As  experience  we  have  the  world  with  all  its  empirical  detail. 
It  interests  us  and  we  want  to  know  about  it.  We  can  feel  two 
kinds  of  curiosity  about  the  world.  We  can,  on  the  one  hand,  wish 
to  become  better  and  better  acquainted  with  its  empirical  character, 
or  we  can  conceive  it  as  a  whole  and  ask  what  is  the  cause  or  ground 
or  nature  of  the  whole  in  view  of  which  we  shall  interpret  and 
comprehend  the  parts  that  come  within  our  ken.  The  first  tyi)e  of 
interest  desires  description  of  experience,  the  second  desires  an  ex- 
planation of  experience,  and  the  second  and  third  sections  of  the 
paper  are  entitled,  respectively,  '  The  Description  of  Experience '  and 
'The  Explanation  of  Experience.' 

The  complete  description  of  experience  is  the  task  of  all  the 
special  sciences  working  together,  and  recently  there  has  arisen 
in  scientific  circles  a  point  of  view  which  regards  the  concepts  of 
science,  such  concepts  as  atom,  ether,  energy,  etc.,  as  conceptual 
instruments  for  effecting  convenient  descriptions  or  increasing  our 
fund  of  empirical  data,  but  it  is  not  regarded  as  of  the  smallest 

*  Philosophische  Studien,  Bd.  13,  Heft  1,  2  and  3. 

-  Kexme  de  M^taphysique  et  de  Morale,  Vol.  V.,  p.  764,  Vol.  VI.,  p.  61. 


INTRODUCTION  3 

consequence  for  the  purpose  in  hand,  that  anything  corresponding 
to  these  concepts  actually  exists.  If,  however,  one  asserts  that  atoms 
really  exist,  or  that  reality  is  constituted  in  one  way  or  another, 
then  one  has  passed  to  the  plane  of  metaphysics.  It  is  clear,  then, 
that  the  logical  distinction  between  science  and  metaphysics  appears 
in  this,  that  metaphysics,  the  endeavor  to  know  'reality,'  needs  the 
predicate  of  existence,  while  science  does  not. 

The  question  arises,  why  should  not  he,  to  whom  the  concept  of 
an  Absolute  seems  demanded  by  the  facts  of  experience,  treat  this 
concept  as  the  physicist  treats  the  concept  of  the  atom?  And  so 
far  as  I  can  see  there  is  only  an  emotional  reason  why  he  should 
not  do  so.  For  the  question  is  not  whether  there  is  reality,  but 
whether  in  a  given  concept  we  have  a  true  account  of  it. 

Now  metaphysics  is  anxious  to  be  'scientific*  in  every  possible 
way,  and  among  students  of  metaphysics  we  have  those  who  are 
cool-blooded  and  critical,  and  those  who  warm  to  their  tasks 
with  emotional  energy.  It  should  not  be  in  the  least  surprising 
if  the  former  type  of  philosopher  follows  the  example  of  science, 
and  the  second  type  alone  continues  to  cling  to  the  existential  predi- 
cate. And  in  view  of  the  great  and  increasing  prestige  of  science, 
metaphysics,  in  the  sense  above  explained,  may  become  of  less  and 
less  consequence  in  the  world  of  thought.  And  if  this  comes  to 
pass,  as  there  is  much  reason  to  expect,  we  shall  have  science  and 
the  natural  view  of  the  world  which  we  find  in  pure  experience. 
This  would  be  a  verification  of  the  predictions  of  Avenarius. 

The  fourth  section,  entitled  'Suggestions  toward  a  Concept  of 
Experience,'  proposes  a  point  of  view  which  might  be  of  service  to 
the  student  of  history,  particularly  the  student  of  the  history  of 
theories  of  reality.  This  follows  the  theory  that  Avenarius  has 
put  forward  in  his  essay  'Der  Menschliche  "NVeltbegriff. '  It  is  a 
concept  of  a  history  of  'pure  experience,'  beginning  in  an  animistic 
stage  of  culture  and  continuing  until  the  animism  which  at  the 
beginning  had  the  character  of  undoubted  fact,  has  been  entirely 
eliminated  from  experience  and  from  theory.  The  contention  of 
Avenarius  is  that  when  this  process  of  rejecting  animism  is  com- 
pleted, the  theory  of  idealism  must  disappear.  This  concept  is  the 
concept  of  a  genuine  history,  in  which  theories  of  reality  have  been 
determined  by  the  fund  of  animism  not  yet  rejected. 

Finally,  in  the  fifth  and  last  section,  I  take  up  some  contem- 
porary discussions  of  pure  experience.  Professor  William  James 
has  recently  published  his  conviction  that  consciousness  as  a  kind 
of  stuff  or  entity  does  not  exist.  He  believes  that  in  dropping  the 
idea  of  such  an  entity  he  is  getting  rid  of  the  last  remnant  of  the 
idea  of  the  soul.     To  one  who  has  in  mind  the  theories  of  Avenarius, 


4  AVENARWH    ASD    PURE    EXPERIENCE 

and  the  concept  of  a  history  of  pure  experience  such  as  that  just 
explained,  this  statement  from  Professor  James  must  seem  of  great 
consequence.  What  are  the  results  of  this  for  idealism?  is  the 
imperative  question.  I  have  done  what  I  can  to  indicate  the  results 
that  seem  to  me  likely  to  follow,  and  my  position  is  that  the  rejec- 
tion of  consciousness  from  the  position  it  has  hitherto  oeoupied 
in  metaphysics  must  follow  from  a  candid  iiLspeetion  of  pure  ex- 
perience, and  that  this  cuts  the  ground  from  under  the  argument 
for  idealism.  I  thus  exhibit  at  least  the  presumption  that  the 
conception  of  a  history  of  pure  ex[)erienee,  whieh  T  take  from 
Avenarius,  is  sound. 


APPRECIATIONS  OF  EXPERIENCE 


It  often  happens  in  philosophical  discussion  that  the  idea  of  an 
experience  that  is  valid  or  logically  justifiable  leads  us  to  forget 
or  ignore  our  actual  experience.  That  a  tjTpe  of  experience  should 
be  apparently  illogical  and  illusory  is  enough  oftentimes  to  dismiss 
it  from  consideration.  In  what  follows,  I  wish  to  speak  not  of  valid 
experience  as  such,  but  simply  of  average  human  experience  which 
may  be  naive  and  illusory  but  which  is  not  therefore  less  genuine. 

I  am  not  concerned  with  any  metaphysic.  I  do  not  purpose  to 
justify  any  experience  as  against  any  other,  but  simply  to  state 
some  of  the  commoner  characteristics  of  frankly  naive  and  spon- 
taneous experience,  and  to  mention  some  logical  considerations  that 
seem  relevant.  And  if  from  time  to  time  the  habits  of  language 
may  cause  it  to  appear  that  I  am  discussing  a  metaphysical  question, 
I  would  beg  the  reader  to  recall  that  my  real  interest  is  in  char- 
acteristics of  human  experience  simply,  detached  as  completely  as 
may  be  from  any  notion  of  reality. 

Each  one  of  us  can  say,  'Here  I  am  in  a  world  of  things,  among 
my  fellows.'  AVhether  in  our  philosophical  moments  we  believe  in 
a  world  of  independent  external  objects  and  of  different  external 
selves  is  another  matter.  However  illusory  its  appearance,  the 
outer  world  does  seem  to  be  a  world  of  facts,  whose  reality  is  not 
dependent  upon  our  cognition.  Reflection  may  show  that  this  ap- 
pearance is  highly  ambiguous,  and  that  such  an  independent  reality 
can  be  neither  comprehended  nor  described,— but  the  appearance 
persists.  All  sorts  of  things  happen  or  seem  to  happen  without  any 
help  from  humanity,— things  which  humanity  would  be  only  too 
glad  to  help  if  it  could.  Independent  facts  and  forces  there  seem 
to  be  which  man  can  take  advantage  of  to  his  profit.  The  farmer 
plants  his  crops  and  they  grow,  not  without  his  care,  to  be  sure,  but 
chiefly  by  virtue  of  something  which  he  does  not  seem  to  contribute. 
There  is  falling  water  to  turn  a  mill  wheel,  metals  there  are  to  be 
dug  from  the  earth,  heavenly  bodies  to  be  searched  out  with  the 
telescope,  germs  of  disease  to  be  avoided.  One  who  has  never  heard 
of  metaphysical  realism  has  nevertheless  a  completely  realistic 
attitude. 

This  is  the  attitude  of  the  'plain  man.'  The  philosopher  is  rather 
fond  of  contrasting  himself  with  the  'plain  man,'  and  since  he  is 
interested  in  the  contrast-effect,  he  is  apt  not  to  observe  how  much 

6 


6  AVENARJU8   AND   PURE   EXPERIENCE 

he  and  the  'plain  man'  have  in  common.  His  ideal  of  a  logical  or 
valid  experience  causes  him  often  enough  to  l>e  somewhat  indifferent 
to  important  characteristics  of  actual  experience. 

Both  the  philosopher  and  the  'plain  man'  are  obliged  to  take 
the  universe  very  much  in  the  same  way.  Whether  we  are  philos- 
ophers or  not,  our  adjustment  to  our  world  of  objects  is  as  though 
these  were  genuinely  independent  of  us.  This  seems  a  common- 
place that  scarcely  needs  even  to  be  alluded  to.  Yet  I  trust  I  may 
be  pardoned  for  dwelling  a  little  longer  on  the  'plain  man.'  He 
is  an  instructive  individual  who  seldom  comes  by  his  rights  in 
philosophy. 

The  'plain  man,'  if  asked  for  his  opinion  on  the  merits  of  realism, 
would  be  at  least  so  sure  of  its  case  that  he  would  be  unable  to  com- 
prehend any  other  point  of  view.  His  would  be,  indeed,  a  very 
poor  metaphysic,  and  likely  enough  quite  in  error,  but  this  humble 
realism  would  express  with  great  energy  how  the  world  comes  home 
to  the  natural  unsophisticated  man.  "You  ask  me,"  we  may 
imagine  him  saying,  "how  I  know  that  the  world  out  there  is  inde- 
pendent of  me  and  of  everybody  else.  I  know  it  by  experience. 
Don't  my  crops  grow,  whether  any  one  thinks  about  them  or  not? 
Do  you  suppose  I  have  anything  to  do  with  the  change  of  the  sea- 
sons? I've  never  seen  Spain  and  South  Africa,  but  I  know  there 
are  such  places,  and  it  wouldn't  make  any  difference  if  Spain  and 
South  Africa  didn't  contain  a  living  soul,  and  if  everybody  else, 
the  Lord  Almighty  included,  should  forget  there  ever  had  been  such 
places;  Spain  and  South  Africa  would  stay  just  where  they  are. 
You  needn't  try  to  tell  me  it's  all  in  my  mind's  eye."  Something 
like  this  the  'plain  man'  would  surely  say. 

And  then  we  might  talk  to  him  of  secondary  qualities  and  brain- 
states  and  categories.  To  all  of  which  he  would  reply  with  simple 
and  eloquent  disgust.  Most  of  his  reasons  might  be  as  poor  as  they 
could  be,  but  the  poorness  of  his  reasons  would  not  weaken  his 
sturdy  faith  precisely  because  they  have  little  or  nothing  to  do 
with  it.  He  never  inferred  or  demonstrated  to  himself  the  existence 
of  an  independent  external  world.  He  has  always  known  such  a 
world  because  he  has  always  lived  in  it,— it  is  the  world  of  his  ex- 
perience, that  is,  his  experience  is  characterized  in  that  way. 

One  of  the  first  and  most  important  steps  to  take  in  an  epistemo- 
logieal  discussion  of  experience  is  to  free  one's  terms,  experience, 
knowledge  and  the  like,  from  metaphysical  implications  which  solve 
in  advance  problems  which  might  be  later  proposed.  This  precau- 
tion is  so  important  that  I  will  illustrate  the  neglect  of  it  by  a  few 
sentences  from  an  article  by  Professor  Andrew  Seth.^ 

^Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  I.,  p.  511,  'The  Problem  of  Epistemology.' 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIEyCE  7 

Professor  Seth  has  been  stating  what  he  regards  as  the  most 
important  features  of  the  idealistic  theory  of  knowledge,  and  he 
declares  that  for  idealism,  the  object  of  knowledge  *is  nothing  be- 
yond the  cognitive  states  themselves.'  And  he  continues:  "Now 
on  such  a  theory  it  is  pretty  evident  that  the  distinction  of  knowing 
and  being,  of  subject  and  object,  would  never  have  arisen  and 
would  not  have  required,  therefore,  to  be  explained  away. ' ' 

It  seems  even  more  evident,  however,  that  if  the  distinction  of 
subject  and  object  were  not  a  primary  character  of  experience,  it 
could  not  play  the  role  it  does  in  theories  of  knowledge.  And  just 
as  the  subject-object  distinction  is  more  original  and  primitive  than 
any  theory  of  knowledge,  just  so  the  experience  of  the  outer  world 
is  more  original  and  primitive  than  any  metaphysic.  And  by  this 
I  mean,  not  that  the  outer  world  exists,  but  that  experience  has  a 
certain  characteristic  feature. 

II 

These  introductory  remarks  have  sought  to  separate  experience 
from  validity  in  the  ordinary  sense.  I  wish  now  to  consider  what 
we  may  fairly  mean  by  saying  that  a  thing  or  a  fact  is  given  in 
experience.  The  'plain  man'  says  he  knows  by  experience  that  the 
outer  world  has  its  own  independent  existence.  I  'know'  by  ex- 
perience all  sorts  of  facts  about  my  fellows,  and  I  know  by  experi- 
ence that  I  have  real  fellows.  At  the  same  time  I  admit  that  a  true 
metaphysic  might,  for  all  I  know,  show  me  that  quite  the  opposite 
is  true.  Still,  that  makes  no  difference  to  my  experience.  We  all 
know,  I  presume,  by  experience  what  happened  to  us  yesterday. 
These  various  facts  and  many  more,  we  say,  are  given  in  experience. 
But  they  may  not  be  'presented'  in  experience.  A  presented  ob- 
ject is  an  object  directly  and  immediately  perceived,  and  of  course 
must  be  an  object  'given'  in  experience,  but  many  objects  of  the 
class  I  call  'given  in  experience'  could  not  possibly  be  'presented.' 

Such  objects  are  the  thoughts  and  feelings  of  my  fellow  and  the 
past  event.  Yet  speaking  unphilosophically,  perhaps,  but  honestly, 
we  say  that  these  are  facts  of  our  experience  given  in  experience, 
known  through  experience. 

I  dwell  upon  the  point,  obvious  though  it  is,  because  when  we 
say  a  fact  is  given  in  experience  we  are  so  apt  to  mean  presented 
to  perception.  To  bring  something  to  the  test  of  experience  is  to 
produce  it  for  direct  inspection.  But  to  define  an  object  of  ex- 
perience in  this  way,  as  an  object  perceived  or  at  least  capable  of 
being  perceived,  is  to  divorce  the  concept  of  experience  hopelessly 
from  the  life  that  it  is  intended  to  describe.  There  is  no  ground 
for  denying  that  the  pious  mystic  may  know  God  and  the  Saints 


8  AVENAltWH   AND    PURE   EXPERIENCE 

as  facts  of  his  experience.  And  accepting  experience  in  thi»  large 
empirical  way,  we  in  list  admit  as  objects  of  it,  facts  which  could 
not  Iw  presented,  which  could  not,  perhaps,  even  exist.  And  be- 
cause the  point  is  so  fundamental,  let  me  repeat  myself. 

Every  one  would  say  that  the  presence  of  his  fellows  was  given 
to  hijn  in  experience.  We  should  all  instinctively  pronounce  it 
the  idlest  of  philosophical  va{j:aries,  were  I  to  devote  time  and  para- 
graphs to  proving  that  this  paper  is  addressed  to  a  real  circle  of 
readers,  and  if  I  wei*e  really  in  any  doubt  about  it  I  should  be  de- 
clared simply  insane. 

Yet  we  do  seriously  discuss  how  we  come  to  believe  in  the  pres- 
ence of  other  selves,  and  how  we  can  rationally  justify  the  belief. 
There  is  something  a  little  futile,  perhaps  even  a  little  insincere,  in 
such  discussion.  We  do  not  'come  to  believe'  in  other  selves  at  all. 
It  is  misleading  to  inquire  into  our  'belief  in  other  selves.  Other 
selves  are  simply  facts,— not  reality-facts,  perhaps,  but  experience- 
facts.  Our  belief  (if  I  may  still  use  the  word)  in  other  selves  is 
in  no  proportion  to  our  success  in  explaining  or  rationalizing  the 
belief.  In  this  elTort  we  may  succeed,  or  we  may  fail ;  our  neighbor 
is  in  either  case  an  equally  genuine  fact  in  our  experience.  Yet 
the  essential  part  of  this  fact,  the  life  of  feeling  and  ideas  and  will, 
all,  indeed,  that  makes  him  our  neighbor,  we  can  not  possibly  per- 
ceive. But  the  presence  of  it  all  about  us  is  so  much  a  fact  of 
experience  that  without  it  any  one  would  probably  go  mad.  What- 
ever the  psychological  process  may  be  by  which  human  experience 
becomes  social,  it  has,  from  the  earliest  times  we  can  remember,  the 
social  character. 

The  fellow  being  is  one  type  of  an  object  of  experience  that 
can  not  be  presented  to  perception.     Another  type  is  the  past  event. 

Suppose  I  say  to  some  one,  'Did  you  go  to  any  of  the  operas  last 
winter?'  And  I  receive  the  answer,  'Yes,  I  did  go';  and  I  reply, 
'Are  you  quite  sure?  Perhaps  you  didn't,'  I  may  be  answered 
as  follows:  *I  distinctly  remember  going.  I  remember  all  about 
it,  I  can  tell  you  just  who  sang  and  where  my  seat  was.'  The 
declaration  amounts  to  saying  that  it  is  a  fact  of  present  experience 
that  one  did  go  to  the  opera  some  time  ago.  Surely  it  is  a  fact 
of  present  experience  to  each  of  us  that  he  has  done  many  particular 
things  on  days  that  are  past.  Yet  we  are  not  now  doing  the  indi- 
vidual things  we  did  yesterday.  Facts  of  experience  these  past 
events  are.  Presented  immediate  facts  they  are  not.  We  have, 
to  be  sure,  immediate  data  about  them,  but  the  past  event  is  ob- 
viously never  presented  in  experience  at  all.  Mental  images,  recol- 
lections, echoes  of  its  sense,  character,  may  be  presented,  but  these 
are  not  the  original  event,  and  there  may  conceivably  have  been  no 
original  event. 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIEyCE  9 

It  may  seem  that  we  have  not  come  far  toward  stating  what  we 
may  fairly  mean  by  saying  that  a  fact  is  given  in  experience.  We 
have  at  least  made  out  that  the  test  of  perception  is  not  a  sufficient 
one.  Some  objects  seem  to  be  facts  of  experience,  when  the  ideas 
of  them  come  home  to  us  in  a  certain  way,  when  they  have  what 
has  been  called  'reality  feeling.'  Even  an  object  of  sense-percep- 
tion needs  the  tone  of  reality  in  order  to  be  quite  unambiguous. 
One  can  at  least  ask  the  question,  'Is  this  a  real  house  or  the  illusion 
of  a  house,  which  I  see?'  An  hallucination  may  be  all  but  per- 
fect, and  differ  from  a  genuinely  perceived  object  only  in  its  tone 
of  reality.  "An  hallucination,"  says  Professor  James,  "is  a  strictly 
sensational  form  of  consciousness,  as  good  and  true  a  sensation 
as  if  there  were  a  real  object  there."*  The  poor  tinker  Sly,  in 
Taming  of  the  Shrew,  who  for  a  jest  is  made  to  believe  himself  a 
lord,  is  the  victim  of  a  shifting  reality-feeling. 

"  Am  I  a  lord  ?     And  have  I  such  a  lady  ? 
Or  do  I  dream?     Or  have  I  dreamed  till  now? 
I  do  not  sleep:   I  see,  I  hear,  I  speak; 
I  smell  sweet  savours,  and  I  feel  soft  things: 
Upon  my  life  I  am  a  lord  indeed 
And  not  a  tinker,  nor  Christophero  Sly." 

To  sum  up.  For  a  fact  to  be  an  object  of  experience  it  is  not 
necessary  that  it  be  perceived  or  be  of  a  sort  that  could  possibly 
be  perceived.  It  is  not  necessary  that  it  exist  or  be  of  a  sort  that 
could  possibly  exist. 

Ill 

I  have  suggested  'reality-feeling'  as  the  sort  of  criterion  that 
may  help  us  to  characterize  an  object  of  experience.  In  spite  of  all 
the  uncertainties  of  experience  we  say  it  is  the  surest  basis  of 
knowledge  and  the  only  foundation  for  theory.  A  priori  knowl- 
edge, if  there  be  such,  I  include  within  experience.  To  have  an 
object  of  experience  is  to  know  that  object  in  some  respect.  The 
object  may  not  exist,  but  that  makes  no  difference  to  the  experience 
that  'knows'  it.  What  I  wish  now  to  examine  is  the  relation  of 
'reality-feeling'  to  knowledge  as  a  case  of  experience. 

The  discussion  thus  far  has  been  carried  on  from  the  point  of 
view  of  Avenarius  and  here  I  shall  attempt  some  account  of  the 
way  in  which  Avenarius  describes  the  experience  of  knowing  some- 
thing. His  opinions  will  illustrate  important  phases  of  our  prob- 
lem, and  bring  out  the  empirical  detail  of  the  situation  with  which 
we  have  to  deal. 

Avenarius  gives  an  elaborate  analysis  of  the  feeling-tones  which 


'William  James,  'Principles  of  Psychology,'  II.,  p.  115. 


10  AVENARIU8   AND   PURE    EXPERIENCE 

may  give  character  to  ideas,— such  feelings  as  conpruity  and  in- 
congruity, familiarity  and  strangeness,  the  various  ways  in  which 
an  idea  may  be  satisfactory  or  unsatisfactory.  Hig  gpeeial  purpose 
leads  him  to  bring  out  as  clearly  as  p(jssible  the  contrast  in  feeling- 
tone  between  a  problem  solved  and  a  problem  unsolved,  between  the 
sense  of  having  attained  insight,  and  of  being  still  baffled  and  barred 
from  insight. 

We  have  been  made  familiar  with  groups  of  terras  which  are 
used  to  characterize  what  we  call  the  'real.'*  Professor  Royce  has 
collected  such  terms  into  three  groups  expressive  of  three  attitudes 
toward  reality.  One  of  these  attitudes  lays  stress  on  the  aspect  of 
immediacy  as  characteristic  of  the  real.  The  real  is  what  we  can 
get  at,  and  test  and  get  directly  acquainted  with.  Another  attitude, 
as  Professor  Royce  describes  it,  emphasizes  the  character  of  perma- 
nence, of  substantial  self-sufficiency.  The  unreal  has  no  'depth'  or 
'interior  constitution,'  'but  the  real  abides  in  its  own  house.'  One 
may  detect  here  a  sense  of  independent  existence  as  giving  char- 
acter to  the  real.  I  hasten  to  say  that  I  am  alone  responsible  for 
this  interpretation.  In  a  sense,  however,  this  aspect  of  independ- 
ence is  the  aspect  of  existence  par  excellence.  Finally,  a  third  class 
of  terms  describes  the  real  as  what  can  be  depended  upon,  what  will 
not  leave  you  in  the  lurch.  We  can  be  sure  of  the  real,  but  the 
unreal  is  a  sham  and  not  to  be  trusted. 

In  a  similar  way  Avenarius  describes  three  feeling-tones  as 
characteristic  of  what  we  accept  as  real  and  true.'  These  he  calls 
the  'existential'  character,  the  'acquaintance'  character  and  the 
'security'  character.  The  references  just  made  to  the  analysis  given 
by  Professor  Royce  are  a  sufficient  explanation  of  these  three  very 
similar  aspects  which  Avenarius  has  picked  out. 

Avenarius  unites  these  three  characters  into  what  he  calls  the 
'fidential'  character.  His  meaning  seems  to  be  that  that  which  is 
felt  to  be  real  in  a  persuasive  and  convincing  way  is  that  with 
which  we  feel  ourselves  most  at  home.  The  real  is  reassuring,  we 
feel  that  we  understand  it  as  we  understand  an  old  friend.  It  is 
not  strange  and  baffling.  The  unreal  is  '  unheimlich,'  something  to 
which  we  can't  get  adjusted,  and  which,  therefore,  does  not  have 
a  place  in  our  world  of  truth,-  This  'fidential'  character  Avenarius 
explains  by  the  term  'HeimJiaftigkeit/  and  he  quaintly  says  that 
every  real  problem  is  a  kind  of  Heimweh,— the  desire  to  get  back 
into  the  region  where  we  feel  at  home,  by  reducing  our  uncompre- 
hended  data  to  terms  of  known  data. 

The  term  '  reality- feeling, '  with  which  we  are  so  familiar,  is  a 

1  Royce,  '  The  World  and  the  Individual,'  Vol.  I.,  p.  52. 
* '  Kritik  der  Reinen  Erfahrung,'  Vol.  II.,  p.  32. 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIEyCE  11 

sufficiently  good  equivalent  for  the  'fidential,'  and  in  our  discus- 
sion may  be  substituted  for  it.  The  important  thing  to  notice, 
however,  is  that  when  we  get  these  three  attitudes,  or  three  feeling- 
tones,  or  better,  when  we  get  all  the  reality-feeling  and  reality-atti- 
tude that  Professor  Royce  and  Avenarius  both  describe,  we  have 
got  what  we  were  looking  for.  At  least  experience  has  no  other 
test  by  which  thought  can  recognize  its  goal. 

Experience  means  for  Avenarius  what  I  have  attempted  to  mean 
by  it.  The  subject  of  the  experience  in  question  merely  observes 
the  situation  before  him  and  reports  it,  but  there  are  no  implications 
about  real  objective  facts  in  what  he  reports,  except  for  him  who 
reports  the  facts  of  experience.  The  facts  reported  may  be  wholly 
mythological,  but  to  be  objects  of  experience  they  must  characterize 
experience  by  their  apparent  reality,  and  the  observer  must  be 
quite  unaware  of  having  in  any  way  produced  the  facts  out  of 
himself  or  contributed  anything  to  determine  their  character.  He 
simply  observes  and  reports.^  This  account  of  an  object  of  experi- 
ence we  frequently  have  implied  in  the  insistence  of  people  who 
have  seen  apparitions,  that  they  were  not  dreaming,  that  they  tell 
simply  what  they  saw,  that  it  was  as  plain  as  day,  etc. 

Whether  Luther  ever  hurled  his  ink-bottle  at  the  devil  or  not, 
or  whether  *der  alt  hose  Feind'  ever  became  to  him  a  visual  object, 
Luther's  experience  may  well  have  been  characterized  by  the  reality 
of  the  devil  as  an  actual  person.  The  experience  of  many  thou- 
sands of  persons  is  no  doubt  characterized  by  the  efficiency  of  holy 
relics  to  cure  disease.  The  friendliness  of  disembodied  souls, 
miracles  of  the  saints,  the  existence  of  God,  can  all  be  objects  of 
experience.  That  is,  experience  is  adjusted  to  the  reality  of  these 
things,  just  as  our  experience  is  adjusted  to  the  reality  of  our  fellow 
of  whom  we  can  get  no  glimpse  whatever.  But  we  sometimes 
awaken  from  the  cognitive  dream.  We  do  so  all  the  time  in  trivial 
ways,  as  when  one  seeks  for  his  purse  or  his  keys,  and  finds  he  has 
left  them  at  home.  But  in  the  case  of  ideas  which  play  large  dra- 
matic roles  in  life  the  change,  when  it  occurs,  is  gradual.  But  the 
change  can  alivatjs  occur,  and  that  is  the  important  point. 

We  are  familiar  with  the  distinction  of  the  'What'  and  the 
'That.'  Avenarius  distinguishes  what  we  may  call  the  'What'  and 
a  variable  'That.'  There  is  a  certain  content,  imagined  or  per- 
ceived, and  there  is  my  attitude  toward  it,  by  which  I  characterize 
it  as  certainly  known,  or  as  believed,  or  as  probable,  or  as  doubted, 
or  as  disbelieved  and  rejected.  Every  cognitive  experience  includes 
these  two  factors.  There  is  a  content,  and  the  content  is  the  object 
of  an  attitude.     The  content,  Avenarius  designates  as  elements;  the 


* '  Kritik  der  Reinen  Erfahrung,'  Vol.  II.,  pp.  352  and  356. 


12  AVKSAIilUH    AS  It    I'llti:    l:M-l.l!l  i:SCE 

attitude  of  knowlodj^e,  doubt,  belief,  etc.,  he  calls  a  character.  "If 
I  observe  that  I  first  presumed  or  jn^essed  somethinj^f,  then  believed 
it  and  finally  knew  it,  I  have,  in  the  relation  content-character,  the 
content  as  constant  and  the  character  as  variable.  If  I  observe 
what  different  thin<,'s  1  have  believed  in  at  different  periods  of  my 
life,  I  have  the  character  as  constant  and  the  content  as  variable."' 
Evidently,  experience  appears  in  this  distinction  a«  a  character,  for 
in  the  question,  did  you  experience  tJiat,  or  did  you  imagine  it  or 
dream  it?  the  idea  of  experience  stands  for  certainty,  sure  knowl- 
edge of  fact. 

The  shifting  value  of  the  reality-feeling  is  readily  illustrated 
by  Uie  religious  questionings  and  doubts  of  many  persons.  At  the 
outset  there  is  frequently  no  question  about  God  at  all ;  everything  is 
sure,  and  as  yet  unquestioned.  No  question  has  ever  occurred, 
just  as  no  genuine  question  has  ever  occurred  about  the  reality  of 
my  fellow  being.  It  is  misleading  to  say  that  one  believes  in  this 
stage.  One  simply  knows.  There  is  perfect  adjustment,  perfect 
satisfaction ;  no  problem  appears  anywhere.  There  is  an  experience 
of  genuine  insight.  Many  persons  who  go  through  painful  religious 
experiences  start  from  a  situation  like  this,  others  always  remain  in 
it,— others  attain  to  it.  It  is  our  attitude  toward  our  intimate 
friends,— we  know  them,  we  are  sure  of  them,  they  are  the  most  real 
facts  in  our  lives. 

But  this  condition  of  perfect  mental  and  organic  stability  does 
not  always  continue.  The  time  comes  when  one  believes  in  God,— 
one  no  longer  claims  direct  insight  and  certain  knowledge.  God 
exists,  yes,— one  is  sure  of  that,  and  one  is  sure  of  God,— but  one 
doesn't  know  so  many  things  about  God.  The  'fidential'  is  be- 
ginning to  be  attenuated.  God  becomes  more  and  more  an  object 
of  doubt ;  if  not  less  knowable,  at  least  less  known,  and  known  about, 
and  therefore  not  to  be  depended  upon  with  the  same  quiet  assur- 
ance as  before.  Finally  one  asks  the  question  does  God  exist,  any- 
way? The  idea  began  as  the  idea  of  something  that  was  an  object 
of  experience  and  knowledge,  with  nothing  problematic  about  it. 
Then  the  reality-feeling  began  to  fade.  The  idea  took  on  a  slightly 
problematic  tone,  it  became  problematized,  and  this  problematic 
quality  became  more  and  more  'characteristic.  The  idea  is  different 
somehow,  a  little  strange.  A  quality  of  difference  or  otherness  has 
come  over  it.  Finally  what  was  known  and  experienced  as  real 
turns  completely  into  a  problem.  And  then  the  problem  gradually 
ceases  to  exist.  The  idea  of  God  is  at  last  understood  to  be  a  super- 
stition to  be  explained  on  historical  and  anthropological  grounds. 
The  idea  has  become  deproblematized.      And  yet  God  was  at  the 

'  Avenarius,  '  Der  Menschliche  Weltbegriff,'  p.  1. 


APPRECIATIOXS    OF   EXPERlEyCE  13 

Start  known  to  exist.  At  least  we  have  not  the  slightest  ground  for 
denying  that  experience  was  characterized  by  the  existence  of  God 
as  an  object  of  will  attitudes. 

Psychologically  this  means  probably  that  the  physiological  sys- 
tem comes  into  the  best  adjustment  to  its  environment  by  means 
of  this  idea,  or  else  that  the  idea  expresses  such  an  adjustment. 
Avenarius  likes  to  say  that  the  central  nervous  system  attains  a 
condition  of  stability,  poise,  rest,  and  that  a  complete  cognition 
is  the  expression  of  such  stability.  Into  his  elaborate  psycho- 
physical account  I  do  not  need  to  go,  but  it  is  important  to  notice 
how  an  idea  may  express  a  genuine  object  of  experience  and  how 
experience  may  become  less  and  less  characterized  by  this  object, 
until  it  is  no  longer  an  object  of  experience  but  has  become  an  ob- 
ject of  critical  reflection;  after  which  it  may  be  comprehended  in 
one  way  or  another,  as  fact  or  as  myth. 

Political  convictions  often  have  a  similar  history.  One  knows 
at  the  start  that  a  high  tarift',  perhaps,  is  the  only  salvation  of 
national  industries.  There  is  no  question  about  it,— one  can't  be 
said  to  believe,  for  one  actually  knows  all  about  it.  Presently  one 
thinks  one  doesn't  know  quite  so  much,  but  one  believes  the  former 
doctrine.  And  afterward  one  may  veer  quite  to  the  other  side,  and 
if  one  is  of  a  dogmatic  temperament  one  may  know  that  various 
things  are  so  which  one  formerly  knew  were  not  so.  And  in  each 
instance  it  is  a  genuine  case  of  knowledge.  Formerly,  the  soul  was 
an  object  of  experience  and  knowledge.  To-day  it  has  almost  ceased 
to  be  a  problem.  It  was  once  a  matter  of  experience  that  the  earth 
went  around  the  sun.  No  doubt  witchcraft  was  repeatedly  a  matter 
of  experience  in  early  New  England  histoiy.  There  is  really  no 
limit  to  the  impossible  things  that  may  be  objects  of  experience. 
They  may  not  continue  very  long  to  exhibit  this  empirical  certainty, 
but  while  they  pass  themselves  off  as  genuine  facts,  they  are  facts 
of  experience,  that  is,  experience  has  that  character.  One  of  the 
most  helpful  bits  of  terminology  that  Avenarius  has  hit  upon  is 
what  he  calls  the  problematization  of  an  idea.^  He  means  that  the 
idea  assumes  a  problematic  character  which  it  may  retain  or  it  may 
lose  by  being  again  understood,  in  which  case,  the  idea  is  said  to 
be  '  deproblematized. '  Any  idea,  any  fact  you  like,  may  become 
problematized  or  deproblematized. 

Let  me  give  one  more  illustration  of  the  cognitive  process,  in 
the  spirit  of  Avenarius.  We  are  in  a  street-car,  and  at  the  opposite 
end  of  the  car  is  a  man  whom  we  recognize  as  a  friend.  We  are 
just  about  to  go  to  speak  to  him  when  we  suddenly  hesitate.  Is 
it  really  our  friend  Smith?     Perhaps  it  isn't.     He  looks  like  Smith 

> '  Kr.  der  R.  Erf.,'  II.,  p.  225. 


14  AVENARIUS   AND   PURE   EXPERIENCE 

though,— but  he  doesn't  look  so  much  like  Smith  as  he  juBt  now  did. 
After  all,  he  doesn't  look  like  Smith,  it  can't  be  Smith,  it  isn't  Smith ; 
—but  who  is  it?  Perhaps  it's  Jones;  it  looks  like  Jones;  of  course 
it's  Jones. 

Now  whether  the  man  is  Smith  or  Jones  or  some  one  else  makes 
no  difference  to  the  process  of  arriving  at  the  judgment,  'That  is 
Jones.'  The  man  was  first  seen  and  he  had  a  familiar  look  about 
him,— he  was  characterized  by  a  quality  of  sameness,  he  is  the  same 
man  as  the  one  I  know  as  Smith,  Then  this  samenes.s  (juality 
diminishes,- the  man  feels  to  us  less  and  less  the  same,— he  takes 
on  a  problematic  character,  we  are  in  doubt  and  we  worry  over  the 
problem  who  it  can  be.  Then  we  reach  a  negative  certainty,— the 
man  is  certainly  not  Smith.  He  has  taken  on  a  quality  of  differ- 
ence or  otherness.  Gradually  this  negative  certainty  passes  over 
into  a  positive  attitude.  Another  quality  of  sameness  appears.  The 
man  may  be  Jones.  The  sameness  quality  grows  stronger  until  we 
are  certain  he  is  the  same  man  as  Jones.  With  this  certainty  the 
man  has  lost  the  problematic  character. 

At  this  point  either  motor  results  follow,  we  rise  and  speak  to 
the  man  Jones,  or  we  turn  our  thoughts  to  other  things.  We  do  not 
worry  any  longer  over  the  problem  of  the  man's  identity.  We  have 
found  that  out.  But  who  the  man  really  is,  is  a  fact  outside  the 
knowing  process  and  irrelevant  to  it. 

It  is  this  irrelevancy  of  outer  fact  that  I  want  to  insist  upon. 
If  it  makes  any  difference  to  the  kind  of  process  and  experience  of 
knowledge,  then  it  is  not  irrelevant,  but  so  long  as  that  experience 
which  claims  to  be  knowledge  is  quite  the  same  in  its  own  positive 
character,  whether  it  happens  to  be  in  error  or  not,  it  seems  like  a 
metaphysical  distinction  and  not  a  merely  descriptive  one,  to  call 
some  apparently  cognitive  experience  genuine  knowledge,  and  re- 
fuse this  name  to  other  such  experience  because  in  the  course  of 
events  it  has  to  be  recognized  as  error.  I  therefore  define  knowl- 
edge, provisionally  at  least,  as  experience  with  the  cognitive  char- 
acter. Other  cognitive  experience  may  drive  it  out,  but  it  does 
not  cease  to  be  knowledge  until  that  happens. 

IV 

One  is  perhaps  inclined  at  this  point  to  protest  against  a  misuse 
of  words.  We  do  not  normally  use  the  word  knowledge  to  mean 
merely  an  experience  which  has  a  cognitive  feeling.  By  knowledge 
we  mean  knowledge  and  not  perhaps  error  that  feels  like  knowledge. 
Truth  and  error,  it  is  held,  are  two  radically  different  things,  and 
knowledge  means  the  possession  of  truth  and  it  can  not  mean  the 
possession  of  error.     This  is  the  traditional  attitude. 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIENCE  15 

I  admit  that  the  point  of  view  I  here  defend  uses  the  word 
knowledge  in  a  novel  way,  which  may  be  a  little  confusing.  But 
the  habit  of  declaring  that  knowledge  must  be  knowledge  of  outer 
fact,  and  then  to  say  that  epistemology  investigates  knowledge,  is 
to  declare  an  important  problem  solved  by  a  mere  fiat  before  be- 
ginning. Or  put  differently,  there  must  be  a  transubjective  object 
of  knowledge,  otherwise  there  would  be  no  knowledge  for  epistem- 
ology to  investigate;  but  we  have  epistemology,  therefore  we  have 
knowledge,  therefore  we  have  the  transubjective  objects  of  knowl- 
edge. Perhaps  we  have,  but  it  is  to  beg  the  most  fundamental  of 
questions  to  assume  the  transubjective  objects  in  our  definition  of 
knowledge.  We  have  cases  of  experience  which  we  say  are  cases 
of  knowledge.  As  types  of  experience,  they  must  be  distinguished 
by  experience  qualities.  These  experience  marks  are  precisely  what 
they  are,  whether  there  is  any  knowledge  of  transubjective  things 
or  not. 

I  quote  a  few  sentences  from  Professor  Seth  for  the  sake  of  stating 
more  clearly  what  I  think  epistemology  ought  not  to  be.  He  says : 
"Epistemology  may  be  intelligibly  described  as  dealing  with  the 
relation  of  knowledge  to  reality."*  Again:  "This  reference  of 
ideas  to  a  world  of  reality  beyond  themselves  is  what  is  meant  when 
knowledge  is  contrasted  with  reality."  Also:  "  Now  it  is  the 
essential  function  of  epistemology  to  deal  with  this  very  relation, 
—to  investigate  it  on  the  side  of  its  validity,  its  truth.  "- 

All  this  is,  I  think,  what  epistemology  should  not  try  to  be,  at 
least  at  the  beginning.  It  all  follows,  however,  from  including  a 
metaphysical  validity  in  the  definition  of  knowledge.  It  should 
not  be  forgotten  that  our  total  data  are  experience  characterized  one 
way  or  another,  and  that  when  we  speak  of  truth  and  error  as 
something  secured,  we  can  mean  only  certain  types  of  experience. 
But  any  piece  of  experience  is  properly  described  by  pointing  out 
its  own  positive  characters,  and  not  by  a  subsequent  estimate  of  its 
value.  Actual  cases  of  knowledge  are  cases  of  experience  char- 
acterized as  cognitive.  And  to  the  experience  which  said,  *I  am 
knowledge,'  subsequent  observation  can  always  say,  'You  were 
error. '  But  from  the  point  of  view  of  a  strictly  empirical  account, 
the  experience  now  called  error  was,  so  long  as  it  retained  the 
cognitive  character,  a  genuine  case  of  knowing  something. 


No  doubt  I  seem  to  have  mixed  up  experience  and  knowledge  in 
a  confusing  way.      I  began  by  speaking  of  objects  of  experience, 

'  Philosophical  Review,  Vol.  T.,  p.  133. 
»L.  c,  p.  136. 


16  AVENAlfWfi    AND   PVHE    KXl'tllilESiK 

facts  ^iven  in  experience,  and  then  I  slipped  into  a  discussion  of 
knowledge,  and  it  may  seem  that  sometimes  I  used  knowledf?e  and 
experience  as  equivalent  terms,  and  ajrain,  I  spoke  of  knowUnlge 
as  a  special  type  of  experience,  namely  cognitive  experience. 

The  criticism  would  be  fair,  but  it  is  of  service  in  pointing  out 
that  there  are  two  meanings  of  the  word  experience,  and  llicsc  I 
must  now  try  to  separate. 

Most  often  we  mean  by  experience,  something  as  wide  as  the 
whole  of  consciousness.  There  is  no  defining  experience  in  this 
most  comprehensive  sense.  No  feeling,  however  elusive,  falls  out- 
side of  experience.  Experience  means  also,  however,  something 
more  limited  and  definite.  In  this  narrower  meaning,  experience 
is  the  experience  of  some  particular  object  or  fact.  We  express  this 
meaning  of  the  term  when  we  say  to  any  one,  'Did  you  experience 
that  or  did  you  imagine  it  or  invent  it  or  dream  it  or  postulate  it?' 
Experience  in  this  sense  is  the  cognition  of  apparently  real  fact. 
It  is  in  this  sense  that  Avenarius  uses  the  word.  lie  defines  it  as 
the  ' Kenntnissnahme  seiender  Sachen.'^ 

A  near-sighted  person  frequently  sees  some  one  across  the  street 
whom  he  thinks  must  be  an  acquaintance,  but  he  can  not  be  sure, 
owing  to  his  defective  eyesight.  In  this  case,  and  speaking  from 
the  point  of  view  of  the  narrower  definition,  the  object  of  his  ex- 
perience is  his  own  state  of  uncertainty.  He  can  not  say,  *I  per- 
ceive my  friend  A,  over  there,'  but  he  can  say,  'I  perceive  great 
uncertainty  in  myself.'  The  latter  judgment  is  a  complete  cogni- 
tion. His  uncertainty  is  fact  of  his  experience,  but  his  experience 
does  not  present  it  as  fact  that  the  man  across  the  street  is  really 
his  friend.  It  is  this  cognitive  character  of  experience  that  we 
have  in  mind  when  we  speak  of  experience  as  the  basis  of  science, 
when  we  speak  of  facts,  of  experience  and  objects  of  experience. 
Any  discussion  of  experience  as  a  criterion  of  certainty  must  con- 
ceive it  in  the  narrower  sense,  as  direct  cognition  of  fact,  without, 
however,  implying  that  the  fact  has  any  metaphysically  independ- 
ent existence.  It  may  or  it  may  not.  In  either  case  we  have  the 
same  empirical  situation.  I  shall  accordingly  use  the  word  experi- 
ence to  mean  experience  cognitive,  experience  having  an  object. 

I  trust  it  will  not  sound  either  dogmatic  or  excessively  common- 
place if  I  say  at  once  that  the  independent  outer  world  is  an  object 
of  experience. 

VI 

It  has  been  already  observed  how  we  meet  again  and  again  with 
the  declaration  or  the  insinuation  that  knowledge  of  a  real  tran- 
scendent is  the  only  knowledge  worth  the  name,  and  at  the  same 

> '  Kr.  der  R.  Erf.,'  II.,  p.  .3.59. 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIENCE  17 

time  it  is  admitted  that  we  can  not  understand  how  experience  can 
transcend  itself.  But  experience  has  got  to  do  so  somehow,  it  is 
argued,  or  else  knowledge  is  impossible. 

In  all  this,  a  philosophical  doctrine  is  seen  to  meet  resistance 
from  something  that  is  not  logical  thought.  The  problem  of  the 
transcendent  object  can  hardly  get  a  hearing  on  its  own  merits.  It 
is  met  by  thoroughly  realistic  prejudices,  which  seem  to  be  planted 
deep  down  in  our  nature.  This  attitude  of  resistance  to  certain 
perfectly  logical  points  of  view  is  something  deeper  than  the  senti- 
mental antipathies  to  a  criticism  of  cherished  ideas.  It  expresses 
that  law  of  experience  which  a  psychologist  is  trying  to  make  out 
when  he  seeks  to  discover  why  we  believe  in  an  out€r  world.  Cer- 
tain it  is  that  there  is  a  law  of  our  experience  which  makes  the  outer 
world,  whatever  we  may  say  about  it,  or  whatever  logical  dilemmas 
we  may  get  into  on  account  of  it,  always  an  equally  real  fact  as  a 
constant  character  of  experience. 

It  would  be  interesting  if  cases  of  experience  could  be  observed 
in  which  the  outer  world  should  lose  its  reality-feeling,  in  which 
the  subject  would  hesitate  to  say  whether  the  outer  world  were 
really  experienced  or  only  fancied  and  dreamed.  If  such  cases 
could  be  observed,  and  their  phenomena  connected  with  physiolog- 
ical disturbances,  we  might  see  our  way  clear  to  speak  with  great 
confidence  of  a  natural  view  of  the  world,  determined  by  organic 
conditions  and  expressing  the  natural  adjustment  of  the  organism 
to  its  conditions  of  life. 

Pathological  cases  of  this  type  have  in  fact  been  observed.^  I 
am  obliged  to  quote  at  second  hand.-  Dilthey  writes  as  follows: 
"There  is  in  dreams  a  shading  of  the  liveliness  of  the  sense  of 
reality.  This  occurs  in  the  experience  of  every  one,  and  by  it 
dream-images  can  come  very  close  to  reality.  For  a  long  time  I 
took  a  memory-image  for  the  image  of  an  actual  event,  until  I  was 
able  to  prove  that  it  was  the  recollection  of  a  dream-image.  From 
Krishaber  we  have  the  following  description,  given  by  an  educated 
patient,  of  his  condition  which  lasted  a  considerable  time.  The 
account  is  from  Krishaber 's  observations  of  a  certain  class  of  neuro- 
pathic conditions  of  which  profound  sense-disturbances  were  espe- 
cially characteristic:  'The  impression  of  being  in  a  dream  was  the 
most  trying  to  me  of  all.  A  hundred  times  I  touched  objects  about 
me,  I  spoke  out  loud  in  order  to  bring  back  the  reality  of  the  outer 
world  and  my  own  identity.  But  the  touching  of  objects  did  not 
correct  my  impression.'      Another  case  of  this  type  was  observed 

*  Krishaber,  '  De  la  Nervopathie  cerebro-cardiaque.* 

*  Observations  by  Krishaber  cited  by  Dilthey  in  Sitzungsberiehte  der  K.  P. 
Akadetnie  der  Wissenschaften  zu  Berlin  for  1890,  Vol.  2,  p.  1004. 

2 


18  AVENARIUS    ASD    PURE    EXI'KRIEyCE 

in  the  case  of  an  officer,  who  lost  at  the  same  time  th<»  lively  wnse 
of  his  own  identity  and  of  the  reality  of  the  outer  world,  and  had 
the  feeling  of  being  sunk  in  a  dream."  Again,  "In  all  the  ca«es 
collected  by  Krishaber,  the  patient  suddenly  fell  a  victim  to  dizzi- 
ness, roaring  in  the  eai*s,  and  disturbances  of  sight,  hearing  and 
touch.  An  especially  accurate  observer  of  himself  says:  'These  dis- 
turbances of  sight  reminded  me  of  how  things  look  when  seen 
through  powerful  concave  lenses,  or  when  one  stands  beside  a  very 
hot  furnace  and  looks  through  the  draft,  so  that  the  objects  beheld 
seem  to  tremble.  My  own  disturbances  of  sight  resemble  a  combi- 
nation of  these  two.'  The  disturbances  of  hearing  were  even  more 
pronounced.  And  every  time  there  proceeds  from  these  altered 
conditions,  especially  from  the  sense-disturbances,  an  alteration  in 
the  sense  of  the  reality  of  the  outer  world,  and  a  parallel  change 
in  self-consciousness." 

The  patient  first  observed  was  a  writer.  After  violent  sense- 
disturbances  he  seemed  to  be  dreaming  and  no  longer  the  same 
person.  Both  his  own  identity  and  the  outer  world  became  matters 
of  uncertainty  to  him.  Another  case  was  that  of  an  English  officer. 
"It  seemed  to  the  patient  that  something  was  wrapped  about  him 
and  stood  as  a  barrier  between  him  and  the  outer  world,  giving  him 
a  feeling  of  complete  isolation.  When  he  spoke,  his  voice  seemed 
strange,  he  did  not  recognize  it  or  believe  it  was  his  own.  .  .  .  He 
doubted  his  own  existence.  He  seemed  to  be  not  himself,  and  it 
cost  him  an  effort  to  believe  in  the  identity  of  his  own  person.  At 
times  he  was  not  sure  of  his  existence,  and  at  the  same  time  he 
lost  belief  in  the  reality  of  the  outer  world,  and  was  as  if  sunk  deep 
in  a  dream."  It  seemed  to  a  third  patient  as  though  persons 
about  him  were  figures  in  a  dream.  He  thought  he  was  no  longer 
the  same  person,  and  as  he  walked  he  w^as  unable  to  feel  the  floor. 

I  cite  these  cases  to  support  the  opinion  that  the  experience  of 
an  outer  world  is  rooted  in  the  very  organization  of  our  being. 
Just  what  these  deep-lying  roots  are  is  a  special  problem  for  psy- 
chology, but  the  fact  that  such  experience  does  express  some  essen- 
tial factor  in  our  organization  justifies  us  in  speaking  of  a  natural 
view  of  the  world  as  contrasted  with  the  idealistic  point  of  view. 
For  although  we  may  not  be  justified  in  comparing  crude  organic 
attitudes  with  any  reasoned  metaphysic,  still  these  natural  attitudes 
of  adjustment  give  rise  to  the  naive  realism  of  the  'plain  man,'  and 
this  it  is  on  which  a  reflected  realism  depends. 

The  proposal  of  the  problem,  how  we  come  to  know  an  outer 
world,  as  a  problem  for  empirical  psychology,  does  seem  to  contain 
the  implication  that  such  experience  expresses  the  natural  adjust- 
ment of  the  physiological  subject. 


APPRECIATIONS   OF   EXPERIENCE  19 

Helmholtz^  thinks  to  solve  the  problem  by  applying  his  doctrine 
of  unconscious  inferences,  and  in  this  opinion  he  is  followed  by 
Zeller.^  Dilthey,  in  the  article  from  which  I  have  quoted,  argues 
that  the  subject  meets  stubborn  resisting  facts  which  are  thereby 
characterized  as  other  than  self.  The  subject  gets  segmented  off, 
as  it  were,  from  the  rest  of  the  world.  Cornelius  explains  the  idea 
by  the  'principle  of  economy. '^ 

Of  these  various  efforts,  that  of  Dilthey  is  decidedly  the  best, 
—but  however  that  may  be,  all  I  wish  to  insist  upon  here  is  that 
experience  is  characterized  by  laws  of  its  own  in  a  profoundly 
realistic  way,  a  way  which  may  be  of  the  greatest  consequence  for 
the  actual  fate  of  metaphysical  theories.  By  no  amount  of  intel- 
lectual discipline  can  we  rid  our  world  in  experience  of  its  realistic 
character.  We  may  be  fully  convinced  that  this  character  is  a 
vicious  illusion,  but  the  character  remains.  Dr.  Johnson  did  not 
refute  Berkeley's  metaphysic,  but  he  did  testify  to  the  character  of 
experience  which  is  common  to  sane  humanity.  The  lecturer  who  is 
going  to  present  to  his  class  a  refutation  of  realism  at  least  takes 
naively  for  granted  that  his  lecture-room  is  waiting  for  him  in 
quite  a  realistic  way.  Realism  of  this  unreflective  sort  describes 
our  adjustment  to  our  world  of  experience.  It  is  our  natural  or- 
ganic attitude  toward  our  outer  world.  And  the  student  of  philos- 
ophy who  has  this  same  natural  attitude  along  with  the  rest  of  his 
fellows  may,  indeed,  vigorously  repudiate  any  charge  of  being  a 
realist  in  his  philosophy,  but  he  and  his  fellows  will  have  a  world 
of  common  objective  reference,  much  of  which  will  have  a  material 
character,  and  which,  emotional  values  being  neglected,  seems  pretty 
much  the  same  for  all  observers.  As  a  philosopher,  he  will  hardly 
be  so  sure  about  his  doctrine  as  the  unreflective  man  is  about  the 
world  of  his  experience.  But  although  he  may  pass  through  crises 
of  critical  philosophy,  he  has  to  reflect  about  a  world  that  persist- 
ently retains  its  realistic  character.  It  may  indeed  become  more 
or  less  ambiguous  in  certain  respects,  it  will  alter  with  regard  to  the 
emotional  values  in  it,  but  these  changes  do  not  affect  the  outer 
substantial  reality  as  a  characteristic  of  experience.  Such  realism 
as  this  can  hardly  be  called  a  metaphysical  realism.  It  is  certainly 
quite  independent  of  any  metaphysical  doctrine.  It  is  an  organic 
experiential  realism  that  seems  a  great  deal  more  fundamental  than 
realism  or  idealism  in  critical  philosophy. 

In  presenting  this  point,  the  chief  diflficulty  I  have  to  contend 
against  is  its  character  of  extreme  commonplace.     The  habit,  how- 

' '  Physiologische  Optik,'  Leipzig,  1867,  p.  447. 

' '  Vortrjige  iind  Abhandlungen,'  III.,  p.  253. 

*' Psychologic  als  Erfahrungswissenschaft,'  p.  114. 


20  AVENARIU8   AND   PURE   EXPERlEyCE 

ever,  of  seeking  reality  in  some  other  world  of  ideal  truth  cauaes  us 
to  leap  over  the  delusive  and  illogical  but  the  very  real  experience 
of  actual  life.  But  except,  perhaps,  for  the  mystic  in  his  momenta 
of  rapture,  this  seeking  a  beyond  does  not  change  the  character 
of  human  experience  that  I  have  laid  stress  upon,  so  that  as  a 
philosopher  a  man  may  be  anything  you  like,  but  as  a  man,  living 
the  life  of  a  human  being,  he  is  bound  to  be  a  realist  in  his  spon- 
taneous organic  attitudes.  These,  of  course,  are  not  philosophy,  but 
they  determine  the  character  of  experience,  which  is  the  basis  of 
philosophy. 

What  I  have  been  trying  to  bring  forward  is  the  fact  of  what 
has  been  called  a  natural  view  of  the  world,  a  natural  WeltbegrifP 
as  contrasted  with  a  relatively  artificial  one  resting  on  a  foundation 
of  dialectical  subtlety.  The  latter  we  may  believe  and  preach,  but 
the  former  we  live.  The  subtle  and  critical  doctrine  may  be  the 
true  one,  hut  it  makes  no  difference  to  experience  whether  it  is  true 
or  not. 

I  trust  this  will  not  appear  far-fetched  and  trivial.  To  me,  it 
appears  at  the  other  extreme  of  commonplace.  I  dwell  upon  it 
so  much  because  of  our  habits,  as  students  of  philosophy,  of  neglect- 
ing experience  which  seems  illusory  from  our  favorite  point  of  view. 

There  is  then  a  natural  view  of  the  world,  a  natural  attitude 
toward  it,  a  natural  illusion  if  you  like,  from  which  we  may  po.s8ibly 
be  delivered  by  moments  of  profounder  insight.  But  our  experi- 
ences of  philosophic  grace  are  like  many  other  experiences  of  grace ; 
one  comes  at  pretty  regular  intervals,  perhaps,  into  the  temple,  but 
one  continually  relapses  into  sin.  It  is  just  about  impossible  to 
continually  recognize  in  the  outer  world  the  garment  of  divinity. 
We  have  very  probably  our  'philosophy  of  clothes,'  but  it  is  pretty 
certainly  a  philosophy  of  Sunday  clothes. 

This  natural  view  of  the  world  which  seems  so  appropriate  to 
the  organism  in  a  biological  way  is  that  natural  attitude  which 
Avenarius  has  discussed  in  his  essay  *Der  Menschliche  Weltbegriff.' 

A  few  sentences  in  that  book  are  so  striking  that  I  venture  to 
quote  them.  He  has  been  speaking  of  the  idealistic  movement 
which  issued  in  the  proposition,  "The  world  is  my  idea"  {Vorstel- 
lung) ,  and  he  continues :  ' '  But  even  for  the  most  advanced  idealist 
who  seeks  to  limit  his  idea  of  the  world  to  this  minimum  of  content, 
there  remains  always  the  recollection  of  'things'  as  they  used  to 
be  before  his  conversion  to  idealism,— as  something  really  existent, 
or  as  he  used  to  call  them  real,  as  something  immediately  sure,  as 
immediately  cognized,  and  known  and  knowable,— as  parts  of  his 
environment  independent  of  his  thought,  in  contrast  with  himself 
and  set  over  against  his  thought, 

*  Avenarius. 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIENCE  21 

"This  recollection  is,  however,  not  so  void  of  significance  for 
the  most  critical  idealist  as  is  the  recollection  of  a  nurse's  tale  or 
a  belief  of  childhood;  it  plays  a  wholly  peculiar  role.  .  .  .  And 
this  means  that  the  'problem'^  which  arose  when  it  was  'discovered' 
that  the  perceptions  which  were  caused  by  the  'things'  of  the  earlier 
(realistic)  view  are  indeed  nothing  but  ideas,  and  that  the  'things' 
too  of  the  earlier  view  are  only  ideas,  this  means  that  the  'problem' 
which  arose  by  virtue  of  this  discovery  has  not  yet  found  its  final 
solution  by  our  becoming  accustomed  to  the  judgment,  everything 
is  my  idea,  is  in  my  consciousness. 

"And  why  not?  Because  of  the  despised  naive  realism  which 
always  lives  anew  because  it  is  always  being  experienced  (der  immer 
neu  aufleht  weil  er  immer  neu  erleht  wird).  And  so  the  ghost  of 
realism  stalks  by  day  in  the  proud  mansion  of  idealism,  and  will 
not  be  cast  forth."' 

Whatever  those  functions  are  which  cause  us  to  believe  so  in- 
stinctively in  the  outer  world,  we  must  assume  they  are  continuously 
active.  The  pathological  cases  mentioned  above  showed  that  the 
sense  of  reality  which  attaches  to  the  outer  world  is  a  product  of 
natural  human  functions,  and  these,  unless  disorganized,  must  cause 
our  experience  to  be  characterized  as  experience  in  a  real  inde- 
pendent world  of  objective  facts. 

The  above  considerations  show  that  at  least  one  view  of  the 
world  seems  to  have  a  functional  value  for  the  organism,  while 
others  are  functionally  less  suitable.  If  there  be  one  view  of  the 
world  which  surpasses  others  in  functional  value,  this  means  that 
the  organism  through  this  Welthegriff  secures  an  adjustment  to 
its  environment  and  a  stability  within  itself.  As  a  fact,  some 
points  of  view  do  seem  to  have  this  functional  value.  We  sometimes 
hear  it  said,  'That  point  of  view  would  turn  my  world  upside  down' 
or,  *I  could  not  get  ahead  on  that  supposition.'  But  whether  sug- 
gestions like  these  be  worth  anything  or  not,  there  is  evidently  a 
natural  view  of  the  world,  the  only  view  the  'plain  man'  knows,  and 
which  is  as  deeply  rooted  in  the  experience  of  the  critical  idealist 
as  in  that  of  any  one  else.  That  view  is  practical  naive  realism. 
As  metaphysic,  it  is  of  course  of  the  most  uncritical  type.  But  it 
can  be  a  stubborn  obstacle  in  the  way  of  idealism,  producing  a  sense 
of  incongruity,  and  occasioning  that  vague  discontent  with  a  doc- 
trine which  is  admitted  to  be  perfectly  logical.  "I  believe,"'  says 
Avenarius,  "from  personal  observations  that  there  is  a  large  class 
of  men  trained  in  natural  science  who  are  at  the  same  time  idealists, 

*  See  meaning  of  '  problem '  in  above  account  of  Avenarius,  pp.  12  and  13. 
« '  Der  Menschliche  Weltbegriff,'  p.  106. 
» L.  c,  p.  108. 


22  AVENARKJS    AMt    I'lJItE    KXPEIUKNCE 

who  would  fet'l  it  a  relief  to  return  to  their  earlier  realism,  and 
would  he  happy  to  have  it  occur  if  they  only  knew  how  to  escape 
from  idealism  logically,  with  a  good  conscience."  But  they  can 
not  escape  the  conclusion  that  consciousness  and  its  phenomena  are 
all  that  is  given  in  experience.  "And  yet  with  all  these  consistent 
deductions  there  is  usually  not  lacking  a  dualistic  discontent. 
Something  about  this  view  of  the  world  is  wrong  and  were  better 
got  rid  of.  One  can't  just  say  what  the  disturbing  factor  is,  in 
this  so  strictly  logical  Weltbcgri/f.*'^ 

Avenarius  has  his  own  explanation,  but  we  need  not  go  so  far  as 
his  theory  of  'introjection'  would  take  us  in  order  to  see  that 
idealism,  whether  it  be  true  or  not,  seeks  to  have  us  view  the  world 
in  a  way  that  is  opposed  to  our  organic  constitution,  Avenarius 
would  say  that  idealism  is  thus  biologically  uiitenablt?  (' biolofjisck 
unhaltbar'). 

There  is  then  a  natural  view  of  that  experience  which  we  call  the 
outer  world,  just  as  there  is  a  natural  view  of  that  experience  which 
stands  for  our  fellow  being.  And  it  is  not  strange  that  natural 
views  of  these  things  should  regard  them  as  being  really  what  they 
seem  to  be,  transcendent  realistic  facts. 

The  critical  philosopher  is  the  man  who  seeks  to  emasculate  his 
natural  view  of  the  world.  Of  course,  in  so  doing,  he  may  be 
getting  nearer  to  metaphysical  truth.  lie  will  have  a  greater  or 
a  less  success  in  obeying  the  commands  of  reason,  but  he  can 
hardly  eliminate  altogether  the  influence  of  his  natural  organic 
attitude.  So  that  the  'critical'  doctrine  which  results  will  be  a  com- 
promise between  nature  and  reason.  I  do  not  say  that  this  is  an 
interference  with  the  function  of  critical  doctrines ;  far  from  it. 

But  not  every  one  is  a  critical  philosopher;  relatively  few  do 
emasculate  their  natural  view  of  the  world.  I  venture  to  say  that 
even  the  majority  of  philosophers  have  the  same  quiet  assurance 
about  their  outer  world,  that  the  plain  man  has,  although  they  can 
state  more  problems  about  it.  For  the  greater  part  of  humanity, 
the  realistic  nature  of  the  world  is  a  simple  fact  of  experience,  and 
for  the  rest,  whatever  they  may  say  about  it,  it  is  a  fact  of  experi- 
ence, too.  Those  for  whom  it  is  not  a  fact  of  experience  are  the 
cases  referred  to  above  whose  reality-functions,  if  I  may  call  them 
so,  have  become  disorganized. 

VII 

We  mean  by  realism  a  conception  w^hich  describes  the  world  as 
consisting  of  mutually  independent  objects.  The  'independent'  as 
thus  used  has  a  metaphysical  meaning.     But  the  idea  of  metaphys- 

*  •  Der  Menschliche  Weltbegriff,'  p.  109. 


APPRECIATIO^H    OF   EXPERIESCE  23 

ieal  independence  has  its  origin  in  an  aspect  of  things  which  is 
found  in  experience,  and  which  is  called  their  independence.  There 
is  certainly  an  aspect  of  a  large  part  of  the  world  which,  as  an 
experience-character  must  be  called  independence,  and  in  order  to 
distinguish  between  this  empirical  character  and  the  metaphysical 
meaning,  I  shall  use  the  two  words  'independent'  and  'transcendent.' 
The  transcendence-character  is  a  metaphysical  character,  the  inde- 
pendence-character is  a  strictly  empirical  one.  We  instinctively  re- 
gard our  fellows  as  transcendent  objects.  They  may  be  or  may  not, 
but  they  are  certainly  independent  objects.  In  speaking  of  inde- 
pendent objects  I  shall  therefore  not  be  speaking  metaphysically. 
And  as  for  transcendent  objects,  I  shall  discuss  not  them  but  the 
idea  of  them. 

This  distinction  between  the  independent  and  the  transcendent 
is  an  important  one.  It  does  not,  however,  occur  at  all  to  the  'plain 
man,'  nor  does  it  occur  to  the  rest  of  us  most  of  the  time.  For  him 
who  is  unconcerned  with  philosophical  problems,  the  independent 
object  is  a  transcendent  object.  lie  will  not  doubt  that  the  church, 
the  city  hall  and  the  bank  stand  up  on  their  foundations  without 
any  assistance  from  experience,  finite  or  absolute. 

I  hope  this  will  not  seem  like  attributing  reflective  metaphysical 
opinions  to  the  man  who  is  understood  not  to  reflect  at  all  along 
these  lines.  lie  does  not,  of  course,  distinguish  the  independent 
and  the  transcendent  and  then  say  they  are  two  aspects  of  one  and 
the  same  object.  He  has  no  such  ideas  at  all  clearly  formulated, 
but  he  has  very  definite  ideas  about  'real  things'  which  are  not 
asking  his  permission  to  exist,  lie  has,  perhaps,  left  a  plough  up 
in  the  field.  He  is  certain  that  the  plough  is  just  where  he  left  it, 
unless  some  one  has  taken  it  away.  Doubts  about  the  transcendent 
reality  of  his  plough  would  be  quite  unintelligible  to  him.  And 
since  he  does  not  distinguish  the  independent  from  the  transcendent 
character,  his  plough  has  both  characters  undistinguished.  To  say 
that  he  does  indeed  accept  the  independence-character,  since  he 
must,  but  that  he  can  not  be  said  to  believe  in  the  transcendence- 
character,  is  to  say  that  he  understands  by  the  independence-char- 
acter the  limitations  we  have  in  mind,  when  we  describe  this  char- 
acter as  a  'merely'  empirical  character.  But  this  is  to  credit  him 
w^ith  a  distinction  which  not  many  writers  on  episteraology  have 
thought  of  making. 

I  think  we  may  be  sure  of  these  conclusions  because  there  is  so 
much  of  the  'plain  man'  in  each  of  us.  "When  we  talk  philosophy 
w^e  do  indeed  steer  a  very  different  course,  but  when  we  simply 
experience  the  world  we  are  all  plain  men  together.  That  is,  we 
are  all  thrown  back  on  those  natural  functions  which  determine 
experience  for  us  in  these  respects. 


24  AVENARWa    ASU    I'UUE    KXI'EUIESCE 

I  regard  it  then  as  no  betrayal  of  the  'plain  man'  to  say  that  for 
him  the  transcendent  object  is  an  object  of  experience.  But  this 
does  not  mean  that  there  need  be  anywhere  in  the  universe  a  meta- 
physically transcendent  object.  For  the  spontaneous  unreflective 
consciousness,  the  independent  object  has  not  been  denuded  of  the 
transcendence-character.  One  has  become  highly  sophisticated  l>e- 
fore  one  calls  n  tree  or  a  house  a  construct  of  cons<;iou8ness.  From 
the  naive  point  of  view,  there  is,  of  course,  consciousness,  but  that 
is  all  in  one's  head,  if  one  must  locate  it.  That  tree,  however,  is 
not  consciousness,  or  a  phenomenon  of  consciousness.  It  is  a  tree, 
and  trees  are  'known'  to  be  something  quite  different  from  con- 
sciousness. 

The  critical  onlooker  says,  to  be  sure,  that  the  tree  and  the 
house  are  independent  objects,  but  that  this  character  is  no  ground 
for  describing  them  as  transcendent  as  well.  The  critical  onlooker 
is,  however,  outside  of  the  situation,  and  his  observations  do  not, 
as  such,  alter  the  experience  which  he  criticizes. 

The  only  writer  who,  to  my  knowledge,  has  been  clear  and 
specific  as  well  as  just  on  this  point  is  Uphues.*  Uphues  does  not 
distinguish  the  independence  from  the  transcendence-character  in 
so  many  words,  but  he  implies  the  distinction.  Accordingly,  in  the 
quotation  from  him  which  I  shall  give,  'das  Transcendente'  is  to  be 
understood  in  the  above  -undifferentiated  sense  of  independent  ob- 
ject still  unreflectively  apperceived  as  transcendent. 

''Die  Natur,"  says  Uphues,  "ut  das  Jenseits  des  Beimisstseins, 
der  Gegensatz  desselben,  und  in  diesem  Sinne  hezeichnen  wir  sie  als 
das  Transcendente.'"^  A  littk  farther  on,  he  continues:  "It  de- 
pends upon  the  constitution  {Einrichtung)  of  consciousness,  that  in 
sensations,  and  in  ideas  and  thoughts  built  up  upon  them,  we  do 
present  to  ourselves  something  wholly  different  from  consciousness. 
.  .  .  The  direction  of  consciousness  upon  the  transcendent  object 
is  originally  the  only  one  that  can  be  observed.  The  child  makes 
no  reflections  upon  consciousness  and  its  processes.  The  world 
perceived  by  the  senses  is  the  only  object  with  which  it  is  at  all 
concerned.  This  direction  of  consciousness  upon  the  transcendent 
object  is  in  later  years,  if  not  the  only  one,  at  least  the  prevailing 
one.  Very  many  remain  on  the  child's  level;  reflections  about  the 
processes  of  consciousness  play  in  their  lives  no  role  whatever,  and 
even  for  the  others,  such  reflections  are  an  achievement  laboriously 
brought  about,  interrupting  at  times  the  practical  business  of  life 
with  the  outer  world.  More  important  it  is  that  when  we  make 
judgments  about  the  transcendent  object,  we  do  not  proceed  in  an 

*  *  Psychologie  des  Erkennens,'  Leipzig,  1893. 

*  Uphues,  I.  c,  p.  66. 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIEyCE  26 

arbitrary  way,  but  follow  the  laws  which  are  laid  down  by  our  own 
nature. '  '^ 

This  direction  of  consciousness  upon  the  'transcendent'  object 
is  certainly  one  of  the  most  fundamental  characteristics  of  human 
experience.  It  is  the  original  distinction  between  subject  and 
object  which  Professor  Seth  finds  so  inconsistent  with  an  idealistic 
theory  of  knowledge.  Uphues  repeatedly  observes,  however,  that 
to  describe  an  act  of  perception  as  characterized  by  the  presence 
of  an  (apparently)  transcendent  object  is  to  say  nothing  whatever 
about  the  transcendent  existence  of  such  an  object. 

This  should  suffice  to  make  clear  in  what  sense  the  transcendent 
object  can  be  an  object  of  experience.  Why  it  is  that  the  inde- 
pendent object  should  be  characterized  as  transcendent  as  well  is  a 
phychological  question.  But  the  fact  that  the  independent  object 
is  so  characterized  is  the  point  to  observe. 

VIII 

Of  all  our  independent  objects  the  one  that  is  most  stubbornly 
and  defiantly  transcendent  is  our  fellow.  It  is  just  the  transcend- 
ent side  of  him  which  seems  to  give  purpose  and  value  to  actual 
concrete  life,  and  which  gives  him  the  peculiar  position  of  fellow. 
Whether  he  is  really  a  transcendent  object,  I  do  not  inquire,  but 
human  experience  has  precisely  the  character  which  the  transcend- 
ent reality  of  fellow  beings  would  confer  upon  it,— that  is,  it  is 
characterized  as  a  social  experience.  It  has  a  history  of  develop- 
ment by  means  of  social  relations,  and  a  particular  method  of  profit- 
ing and  learning  by  these  relations,  which  the  psychology  of  imita- 
tion has  done  much  to  describe.  But  the  describer  of  this  social 
experience  is  in  the  same  position  as  he  who  describes  the  act  of 
peceiving  a  house  or  a  tree.  In  neither  case  are  we  logically  obliged 
to  assume  the  transcendent  object  otherwise  than  as  a  character  of 
experience,  the  experience  in  which  the  perception  takes  place. 

Assuming  the  reality  of  my  fellows,  they  form  with  myself 
something  more  nearly  comparable  to  a  colony  of  monads  than  to 
anything  else,  monads  which  have  no  windows  through  which  we 
can  get  direct  views  into  one  another's  habitations,  which  may, 
therefore,  conceivably  have  no  inside,  but  may  be  like  the  painted 
architecture  of  the  stage. 

This  is,  of  course,  a  solipsistic  account  of  the  matter,  a  solipsistic 
description  of  a  social  experience.  And  if  any  one  urge  that  a 
social  experience  must  needs  involve  at  least  two  currents  of  per- 
sonal experience,  I  think  he  has  misunderstood.      It  is  the  same 

' '  Psychologic  des  Erkennens,'  p.  69. 


26  AVENARIUS    AND    I'VHE    EXl'EIUESCE 

metaphysical  petiiio  that  lurks  in  the  usual  definitions  of  knowledge 
and  error. 

For  a  solipsistic  doctrine  is  a  very  different  thing  from  a 
solipsistic  experience.  Suppose  a  solipsistic  account  to  be  true,  and 
that  my  stream  of  consciousness  is  the  only  stream  of  consciousness. 
My  social  experience  is  quite  indifferent  to  the  truth  or  falsity  of 
solipsism,  just  as  my  experience  of  the  outer  world  is  quite  indif- 
ferent to  the  truth  or  falsity  of  idealism.  The  important  thing  for 
experience  is  how  it  is  characterized,  not  what  exists  outside  of  it. 
Our  human  experience  is  characterized  as  life  in  a  real  world  among 
real  fellows,  but  it  does  not  follow  from  this  merely  that  any  tran- 
subjective  outer  world  or  transcendent  fellow  beings  exLst  in  a  tran- 
subjective  way.  The  fact  remains  that  the  denial  of  solipsism  (and 
we  all  deny  it)  defines  the  fellow  being  as  metaphysically  tran- 
scendent and  this  is  to  put  him  in  the  same  logical  position  with 
relation  to  the  perceiving  subject  as  the  house  or  the  tree.  On  the 
other  hand,  the  experience  itself  must  be  described  as  equally  social, 
whatever  results  we  come  to  on  matters  of  theory. 

In  view  of  these  considerations  it  is  interesting  to  note  how 
writers  shy  away  from  solipsism.  They  appear  to  imagine  that  a 
solipsistic  doctrine  means  an  experience  in  which  fellow  beings  are 
represented  by  thin  ghostly  shapes,  phantoms,  which  have  the  char- 
acter of  phantoms.  What  I  insist  upon  is  that  a  solipsistic  doctrine 
implies  nothing  whatever  as  to  how  the  experience  under  discussion 
will  be  characterized.  One  who  was  sure  of  the  logical  correctness 
of  the  solipsistic  argument  would  discuss  his  doctrines  with  others, 
submit  to  social  tests  and  social  demands,  and  this,  I  maintain, 
would  not  be  any  repudiation  of  his  solipsism. 

The  fact  simply  is  that  his  experience  would  be  characterized  by 
the  natural  view  of  the  world,  the  natural  Weltbegriff  of  Avenarius. 
Whatever  doctrine  the  person  in  question  may  have,  the  reality 
of  fellow  beings  and  the  outer  world  is  a  fact  of  his  experience. 
He  adjusts  himself  to  them  as  thus  defined ;  that  is  his  natural  atti- 
tude, it  describes  his  experience,  although  it  may  not  describe  any- 
thing else. 

A  discussion  of  solipsism  is  always  a  thankless  task.  Both  the 
writer  and  the  reader  know  in  advance  that  nothing  can  be  said 
in  such  a  discussion  that  will  in  any  way  alter  their  actual  experi- 
ence. We  all  regard  it  inevitably  as  a  mere  vagary  of  dialectic  of 
which  the  absurdity  is  too  manifest  to  call  for  careful  statement. 

Of  the  'absurdity'  of  solipsism  I  am  w^ll  aware.  I  know  as  well 
as  any  one  that  a  solipsistic  doctrine,  however  faultless  its  logic, 
however  unquestionable  its  data,  would  make  no  difference  to  me 
as  an  interpretation  of  experience.      I  am  sure  that  others  would 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIENCE  27 

be  equally  indifferent.  This  fact,  however,  that  a  solipsistic  doctrine 
can  make  no  real  difference  to  us  points  to  an  aspect  of  experience 
which  deserves  examination.  I  feel  obliged,  therefore,  to  dwell  a 
little  longer  on  solipsism,  in  spite  of  its  uncongenial  character. 

Since  solipsism  is  so  manifestly  absurb,  its  refutation  ought  to 
be  easy  enough.  It  might  pursue  the  following  method:  AVhen 
you  argue  for  solipsism  observe,  pray,  the  kind  of  situation  you 
appeal  to.  You  admit  that  your  experience  has  the  character 
of  a  social  experience.  But  you  deny  that  there  is  a  genuine  sys- 
tem of  experience  which  proceeds  from  the  interaction  of  different 
selves.  You  maintain  that  in  your  universe  there  exists  only  one 
self  which  is  yourself.  At  least  you  insist  that  no  other  can  be 
observed.  Obviously  you  appeal  to  an  observation  which  is  not 
subject  to  the  limitations  of  your  own  observation.  You  place  your- 
self in  thought  above  the  entire  fact  to  be  observed,  and  then  you 
see  all  there  is  and  report  accordingly.  But  to  establish  the  correct- 
ness of  your  report  another  observation  will  be  necessary,  and  then 
this  observation  must  be  criticized  by  a  third,  and  so  on.  It  is  the 
infinite  process  with  the  last  judgment  not  a  bit  nearer  the  goal  than 
the  first  one.  To  establish  a  solipsistic  doctrine,  you  must  have  an 
observation  which  can  overlook  the  whole  situation,  and  then  one 
of  two  things  happens.  You  either  get  into  the  infinite  regress,  or 
you  admit  that  the  observation  you  appeal  to  is  really  an  observa- 
tion of  the  facts,  and  that  if  the  facts  include  a  system  of  different 
selves,  the  observation  can  be  a  recognition  of  that  fact.  But  your 
observation  must  not  be  a  kind  of  experience  which  we  know  noth- 
ing about.  When  you  appeal  to  an  imagined  observation,  it  must 
be  the  sort  of  fact  that  you  understand  and  apply  the  name  to  in 
your  own  experience.  But  such  an  observation  could  be  no  more 
authoritative  than  your  own  observations  every  day.  Your  social 
experience  is  a  continuous  observation  of  the  very  kind  you  would 
appeal  to  to  report  the  delusiveness  of  that  experience.  So  that  you 
either  admit  the  suffieiency  of  every-day  experience  as  a  refutation 
of  solipsism,  or  you  appeal  to  an  observation  which  can  not  observe. 

Now  we  all  'know'  that  the  case  against  solipsism  is  a  great  deal 
better  than  any  argument  like  this  makes  it  appear.  One  who  should 
try  to  argue  for  a  positive  solipsism  could  be  answered  in  the  above 
way.  But  solipsism  need  not  be  positive,  it  need  not  assume  any 
burden  of  proof.  The  defender  of  solipsism  may  proceed  as  follows : 
*'You  mistake  my  purpose;  I  am  not  trying  to  prove  the  truth  of 
solipsism.  I  say  merely  that  the  situation  is  ambiguous  and  capa- 
ble of  two  explanations,  and  I  see  nothing  but  sentiment  which 
obliges  me  to  reject  the  solipsistic  one.  I  insist  also  that  in  the 
reality  of  our  fellow  being  we  have  the  same  problem  of  a  transcend- 
ent object  that  we  have  in  the  case  of  a  house  or  a  tree." 


28  AVENARWH    AND    PURE    EXI'EIilENCE 

Now  if  you  admit  difficulties  in  the  way  of  knowinj?  the  tran- 
scendent as  such,  those  difficulties  as  difficulties  of  logic  apply  to  the 
fellow  being.  I  admit  readily  the  infinite  regress  as  the  result  of 
an  attempt  to  prove  a  positive  solipsistic  doctrine,  but  the  infinite 
regress  occurs  tliere  because  it  must  occur  with  every  attempt  to 
know  a  transcendent  object.  The  infinite  regress  simply  illustrates 
that  aspect  of  the  situation  which  I  call  attention  to.  AVhat  one 
gets  in  any  case  of  knowledge  is  experience  characterized  as  cognitive, 
and  the  presumed  agreement  between  such  cognitive  experience  and 
its  assumed  transcendent  object  can  not  be  got  at.  We  can  not  go 
back  of  the  cognitive  experience,  although  we  can  go  from  one 
cognitive  experience  to  another.  To  be  sure,  I  have  continually  a 
cognitive  experience  of  my  fellows,  but  this  does  not  settle  the  ques- 
tion of  their  transcendent  character  in  any  logical  way.  It  does 
satisfy  me  practically,— this  whole  discussion  is  academic  if  you  like, 
and  this  sort  of  practical  satisfaction  is  a  decidedly  important  phase 
of  experience.  But  logically  we  are  left  with  a  sort  of  negative 
solipsism  on  our  hands  which  we  can  not  get  rid  of.  Actually,  we 
simply  toss  it  away.  We  can  not  stand  that  kind  of  suggestion.  Our 
whole  being  rebels.  We  simply  banish  solipsism  out  of  court.  But 
I  submit  that  this  is  not  a  logical  nor  a  philosophical  way  of  escape. 

I  am  not  here,  however,  to  argue  the  claims  of  one  metaphysic 
or  another.  I  wish  simply  to  observe,  if  I  can,  what  motives  deter- 
mine our  philosophical  decisions. 

Perhaps  the  most  common  way  of  attacking  solipsism  is  to  enu- 
merate the  many  dreadful  consequences  which  ought  to  follow.  Such 
argument  does,  perhaps,  make  him  against  whom  it  is  directed  feel 
rather  foolish,  but  it  is  no  better  as  logic  than  the  argumentum  ad 
hominem  ever  is. 

It  seems  as  though  the  eonse-quence  of  defining  the  object  of 
knowledge  as  a  transcendent  object  whose  reality  does  not  depend 
on  being  known  brought  one  into  a  logical  impasse.  It  is  not  that 
I  think  I  am  the  only  self  in  the  universe,  but  that  I  do  not  see  any 
way  to  prove  that  I  am  not  the  only  self.  Of  course  I  know  there  are 
other  selves  all  about  me ;  that  is  the  way  my  experience  is  character- 
ized ;  but  if  I  once  realize  that  my  experience  can  not  go  beyond  itself, 
and  that  my  fellow  is  regarded  by  me  as  in  his  very  essence  a  tran- 
scendent fact,  I  then  observe  that  my  knowledge  of  other  selves  as 
transcendent  is  not  a  logical  knowledge,  but  rather  a  biological 
attitude. 

Meanwhile  this  discovery  makes  absolutely  no  difference  to  ex- 
perience. It  continues  to  be  as  social  as  ever.  One  goes  about 
one's  work  and  lives  out  one's  life  in  the  world  among  one's  fellows. 
One  has  observed,  perhaps,  that  one  can  not  prove  that  solipsism  is 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIENCE  29 

logically  impossible,  but  that  that  does  not  disturb  one.  One  does 
not  say  that  solipsism  as  a  logical  possibility  is  inconsistent  in  such 
and  such  respects.  One  says  it  is  absurd  and  revolting;  that  is,  one 
substitutes  esthetic  categories  for  logical  ones. 

I  have  raised  the  question  about  solipsism  in  order  to  bring  out 
the  way  in  which  the  experience  of  all  of  us  is  superior  to  logic.  We 
all  draw  the  line  with  great  emphasis  at  the  fellow  being.  His 
reality  must  not  be  brought  into  question.  We  can  perhaps  discuss 
it  as  a  problem,  but  we  know  that  it  will  not  be  a  real  problem.  We 
know  that  our  experience  is  characterized  in  a  social  way  and  that 
this  social  character  is  all-important  in  our  world  of  values.  The 
fact  that  a  character  of  experience  is  simply  a  character  of  experi- 
ence and  can  in  no  way  turn  into  a  transcendent  thing  is  not  allowed 
to  make  any  difference. 

IX 

Realists  do  not  take  kindly  to  considerations  like  the  preceding. 
Such  discussion  sounds  like  argument  for  subjectivism.  The  realistic 
prejudice  already  referred  to  demands  the  transcendent  object. 
What  I  have  called  the  independent  object  is  not  enough.  A  few 
attempts  to  support  this  demand  may  be  here  briefly  reviewed. 

Volkelt  writes  as  follows:  "If  pure  experience  were  the  only 
source  of  knowledge  we  should  have  to  give  up  all  claim  to  objective 
knowledge,  and  content  ourselves  with  mere  enumeration  and  de- 
scription of  our  own  processes  in  consciousness.  Every  attempt  to 
formulate  knowledge  must  end  in  failure. '  ''■ 

Here  we  have  the  initial  assumption  in  the  word  'knowledge' 
which  solves  a  problem  in  advance  by  a  mere  fiat.  If  pure  experience 
be  the  only  source  of  knowledge,  then  pure  experience  is  a  good  enough 
basis  for  all  the  science  we  have,  for  it  has  no  other  basis,  and  we 
can  continue  our  scientific  undertakings  on  that  one.  In  the  state- 
ment quoted,  the  idea  of  an  experience  valid  from  a  certain  point 
of  view  seems  to  get  in  the  way  of  a  frank  description  of  actual  ex- 
perience as  such.  It  is  felt  that  because  a  point  of  view  seems  so 
subjective,  therefore  the  experience  described  must  feel  equally  sub- 
jective.    But  this  is  pure  assumption. 

If,  however,  knowledge  is  to  be  a  cognition  of  the  real  transcend- 
ent, and  since  knowledge  we  must  have,  some  way  has  got  to  be  found 
to  lead  from  pure  experience  over  into  the  transubjective  region. 
Accordingly,  Volkelt  continues  as  follows:  "The  new  principle  is  to 
secure  me  a  knowledge  of  the  transubjective  region  which  is  closed 
to  experience.  The  certainty  of  this  principle  must,  however,  be 
grounded  in  experience,  must  find  an  experience  in  which  subjective 

*  •  Erfahrung  und  Denken,'  p.  133. 


30  AVENARIUS    AND    PURE    KIl'ERIESCE 

certainty  forces  me  to  conclude  that  in  that  experience  I  cognize 
something  that  experience  itself  can  not  reach."' 

This  is  a  frank  statement  of  the  situation.  It  is  an  appeal  to 
pure  experience  to  tell  something  about  facts  which  it  conf(?ssedly 
can  not  touch.  Suppose  experience  does  her  best  to  comply;  in 
that  case  we  have  experience  characterized  in  one  way  or  another, 
in  such  a  way,  in  fact,  as  to  satisfy  us.  As  Avenarius  would  say, 
our  new  experience  is  'deproblematized.' 

The  principle  by  which  Volkelt  thinks  we  gain  a  knowledge  of 
transubjective  things  is  the  necessity  one  is  under  to  make  a  par- 
ticular judgment  and  not  any  other,  if  one  wishes  to  tell  the  truth 
about  a  fact  with  which  one  is  acquainted.  He  testifies  to  a  con- 
straint, a  Zwang,  which  lies  in  the  very  nature  of  the  case,  a  demand 
that  the  ideas  be  related  so  and  not  otherwise.' 

One  understands  at  once  what  is  meant,  although  such  terms  as 
constraint  and  demand  are  a  little  misleading.  When  one  has  the 
insight  that  constitutes  perfect  knowledge  one  can,  of  course,  report 
it  only  one  way.  If  it  is  an  insight  which  one  would  have  been  glad 
to  avoid,  there  may  be  some  sense  of  compulsion  about  it,  but  unless 
the  observer  has  an  emotional  antipathy  to  the  truth  which  he  per- 
ceives, that  truth  is  simply  a  part  of  his  world  of  fact,  but  it  can  not 
be  said  to  assault  him  with  any  kind  of  imperative.  There  are  judg- 
ments, however,  judgments  of  insight,  which  claim  to  have  a  perfectly 
obvious  objective  validity.  There  is  a  test  of  such  validity,  the  test 
of  social  agreement.  Volkelt  tries  to  explain  that  it  is  this  social 
agreement  which  he  means  by  the  objective  validity  of  judgments. 
But  so  long  as  the  success  of  a  judgment  depends  upon  its  reporting 
correctly  the  facts  about  a  transubjective  object,  social  agreement 
may  be  the  test  of  such  judgments,  but  it  is  not  equivalent  to  their 
validity,  except  in  a  purely  practical  way.  If  we  are  to  accept 
social  agreement  as  validity,  we  must  throw  overboard  the  tran- 
scendent object.  This,  however,  will  be  a  mere  matter  of  theory ; — 
the  independent  objects  of  experience  will,  many  of  them  at  least, 
continue  to  be  characterized  as  transcendent. 

Volkelt  tries  to  describe  a  kind  of  transcendental  'Must.' 
Rickert,  with  a  much  less  realistic  attitude,  argues  for  a  'tran- 
scendental Ought.  ''^  His  argument  is  somewhat  as  follows :  Suppose 
I  see  a  tree,  and  I  perceive  it  to  be  a  green  tree.  That  perception  in- 
cludes the  judgment,  the  tree  is  green.  It  would  certainly  be  false 
to  say  that  no  judgment  occurs  until  I  happen  to  put  it  into  words. 
But  having  perceived  the  green  tree  I  am  not  now  at  liberty  to  de- 

* '  Erfahrung  und  Denken,'  p.  135. 

'L.  c,  p.  140. 

' '  Der  Gegenstand  der  Erkenntniss,'  Freiburg  i.  B.,  1892,  p.  66. 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIEXCE  31 

ceive  myself  about  it.  The  true  judgment  has  a  kind  of  value  which 
a  false  judgment  would  not  have.  That  to  which  the  judgment 
corresponds  is  this  ought,  which  is  authoritative  for  the  individual. 

It  is  enough  to  point  out  that  this  felt  imperative  is  in  the  first 
place  a  character  of  pure  experience,  whatever  else  it  may  be. 

Another  subjective  principle  of  a  similar  sort  is  Sigwart's  'Prin- 
ciple of  Agreement.'  If  any  one  question  the  validity  of  this 
principle,  Sigwart  admits  that  **We  can  only  fall  back  upon  our 
consciousness  that  the  unification  of  elements  which  agree  (viz.,  sub- 
ject and  predicate)  is  something  absolutely  self-evident,"^— or  in 
other  words,  that  it  is  a  fact  of  pure  experience.  But,  says  Sigwart, 
there  is  experience  that  is  obviously  subjective  and  individual,  and 
experience  which  has  all  the  character  of  universal  validity.  The 
latter  sort  of  experience  can  be  tested  by  certain  principles  such  as 
(1)  stability  in  the  character  of  objects,— they  are  not  found  with 
one  character  to-day  and  a  different  one  to-morrow;  and  (2)  social 
agreement.^  But  the  objective  validity  which  depends  upon  these 
tests  can  get  along  very  well  without  any  transcendent  object 
whatever. 

A  very  common  way  of  arguing  for  the  realistic  metaphysical 
existence  of  the  outer  world  is  to  call  in  the  concept  of  causality. 
There  must  be  an  outer  world,  it  is  said,  as  the  cause  of  our  sensa- 
tions, which  depend  upon  the  stimulation  of  a  sense  organ.  Sig- 
wart's  comment  upon  this  argument  is  the  right  one.  He  says: 
"No  doubt  scientific  reflection  upon  our  sense-perceptions,  which 
begins  by  assuming  that  they  are  occasioned  by  external  objects, 
finds  itself  confirmed  in  this  assumption  by  the  fact  that  it  is  thus 
enabled  to  explain  our  sensations.  .  .  .  But  it  is,  after  all,  con- 
vincing only  after  we  have  tacitly  presupposed  the  existence  of 
objects,  the  assumption  of  which  it  was  intended  to  explain."^ 

Objective  validity  in  the  realist's  sense  is,  then,  Sigwart  admits, 
not  so  obvious  in  any  character  of  experience.  "But,"  he  continues, 
"it  still  remains  open  to  us  to  acknowledge  the  existence  of  an  ex- 
ternal world,  which  is  the  same  for  all,  as  a  postulate  of  our  search 
for  science  and  knowledge,  which  we  can  not  avoid  believing, 
although  we  recognize  that  it  is  not  self-evident."* 

I  should  put  it  more  strongly  than  this.  We  can  not  help  having 
the  outer  world  as  a  fact  of  experience  because  our  experience  must 
needs  be  that  of  a  human  being.  We  may  say  that  we  doubt  or  that 
we  suspend  judgment,  but  we  have  all  the  time  our  natural  organic 

^  Sigwart,  '  Logic,'  English  translation,  Vol.  I.,  p.  296. 
*L.  c,  Vol.  I.,  p.  310. 
•L.  c,  Vol.  I.,  p.  321. 
*L.  c,  Vol.  I.,  p.  322. 


82  AVENARIUB   AfiD   PURE    EXPERIENCE 

attitudes.  Doubt  about  the  outer  world  may  express  a  theory,  a 
theory  that  is  true,  perhaps,  but  it  does  not  describe  the  fundamental 
character  of  experience. 

Let  me  summarize  briefly. 

There  is  what  we  may  call  a  natural  view  of  the  world,  by  which 
we  express  our  organic  adjustment  to  it.  That  view  asserts  that  a 
real  transcendent  outer  world  and  real  fellow  beings  are  objects  of 
experience.  It  asserts  this,  not  so  much  in  the  form  of  a  doctrine 
as  in  the  form  of  a  spontaneous  attitude.  It  is  not  to  be  assumed, 
however,  that  either  realism  or  idealism  is  therefore  true.  This 
natural  view  of  the  world  accepts  the  world  as  being  really  what  it 
seems  to  be,  so  far  as  it  can  be  observed,  and  not  the  illusory  appear- 
ance of  a  fundamentally  different  reality.  The  work  of  observing 
the  world  is  natural  science.  This  natural  view  of  the  world  is 
shared  more  or  less  unreflectively  by  all  normal  human  beings.  On 
this  point  I  would  not  be  dogmatic,  but  I  believe  the  proposition 
is  substantially  correct.  Some  of  us,  however,  have  elaborated  a 
doctrine  which  declares  that  the  world  as  observed  and  as  observable 
is  appearance  and  illusion,  and  that  reality  is  something  quite  dif- 
ferent. This  doctrine  may  be  true,  hut  it  makes  no  difference  to 
experience  whether  it  is  or  not.  Knowledge  is  a  type  of  experience; 
it  is  experience  with  the  cognitive  character.  Error  is  the  relation 
in  which  one  cognitive  experience  stands  to  a  subsequent  one  which 
contradicts  it.  Any  cognitive  experience  may  be  contradicted  by  a 
subsequent  cognitive  experience.  There  is  nothing  about  experi- 
ence which  prevents  such  things  as  a  personal  devil  or  the  Real 
Presence  being  objects  of  Knowledge.  There  may  be  insight  into 
the  future  without,  of  course,  implying  that  the  future  is  going  to 
conform  itself  to  the  insight.  Always  the  question  has  been,  How 
is  experience  characterized?  and  never.  Is  there  a  transcendent  ob- 
ject of  knowledge?  But  it  has  been  pointed  out  that  it  makes  no 
difference  to  experience  whether  there  is  a  transcendent  object  or 
not.  Experience  has  independent  objects  which  it  characterizes  as 
transcendent,  and  it  could  not  possibly  have  any  more.  But  this 
conclusion  involves  solipsistic  possibilities.  These  too,  however,  make 
no  difference  to  experience,  for  a  solipsistic  doctrine  is  a  very  dif- 
ferent thing  from  a  solipsistic  experience.  Experience,  whether  it 
be  one  or  many  in  the  world,  is  such  a  vital,  stubborn  thing  that  it 
resists  any  and  all  consequences  of  theory.  Where  it  seems  to  be 
affected,  the  theory  is  the  product  of  the  experience,  not  experience 
the  product  of  the  theory.  "We  do  escape  from  solipsism  in  theory, 
but  we  do  so  by  casting  it  out  of  court.  So  that  if  I  have  to  say  why 
I  am  convinced,  in  theory,  of  the  reality  of  my  fellows,  I  can  only 
say  it  is  on  the  basis  of  the  natural  view  of  the  world.      But  the 


APPRECIATIONS    OF   EXPERIENCE  33 

natural  view  of  the  world  is  not  logic,  so  that  the  philosophy  which 
we  finally  construct  is  a  compromise,  some  logic,  some  natural 
Weltbegriff'.  All  sorts  of  mythological  objects  may  be  objects  of  ex- 
perience. We  know  that  to  different  individuals  and  to  com- 
munities in  different  stages  of  culture,  very  different  objects  are 
objects  of  experience.  AVe  frequently  express  our  estimate  of  these 
by  calling  the  individual  insane  and  the  community  superstitious. 
In  doing  so,  however,  we  simply  set  our  experience  over  against  the 
one  which  we  criticize.  Both  are  equally  pure  experience,  though 
one  may  be  a  pure  experience  of  mythological  objects,  and  the  other 
such  an  experience  as  we  call  clarified  and  scientific.  In  the  growth 
from  childhood  to  intellectual  maturity  we  see,  in  some  measure, 
the  transition  from  the  former  to  the  latter.  In  the  historical 
growth  of  a  race  from  primitive  and  prehistoric  beginnings  to  a  high 
degree  of  civilization  of  the  modern  type,  we  see,  on  a  large  scale, 
the  movement  from  the  one  type  of  rehu  Erf  alining  to  the  other. 
Thus  we  may  describe  experience  as  a  form  with  a  variable  content, 
or  as  a  variable  character. 

This  is  to  advance  somewhat  beyond  the  discussion  as  above 
pursued,  but  it  brings  us  to  the  considerations  which  occupy  the 
second  section  of  this  paper. 

NOTE. 

The  term  '  Pure  Kxporience '  is  intended  to  translate  the  German  '  reine 
Erfahrung,'  but  the  German  word  *  rein '  suggests  '  mere,'  '  nothing  else  than ' 
which  the  English  word  '  pure '  less  readily  connotes.  The  English  term  at 
once  suggests  the  question,  What  is  an  unpure  experience?  Experience  con- 
ceived not  as  pure  is  conceived  not  as  experience  simply,  experience  as  such, 
but  as  interpreted  in  the  light  of  some  metaphysic.  Pure  experience  is  experi- 
ence taken  in  an  absolutely  empirical  way,  and  conceived  without  metaphysical 
presupposition.  The  previous  discussion  has  attempted  to  give  an  example  of 
taking  experience  in  the  sense  of  *  reine  Erfahrung,'  experience  without  meta- 
physical implications.  Transcendent  objects  may  or  may  not  exist.  It  is  a 
question  not  of  them,  but  of  experience  characterized,  in  this  discussion,  as 
cognitive.  For  the  most  recent  and  the  clearest  statement  of  the  '  pure  experi- 
ence '  position  see  Professor  William  James  in  the  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psy- 
chology and  Scientific  Methods,  Vol.  I.,  Nos.  18,  20,  21,  and  Vol.  II.,  Nos. 
2,  7,  11;  and  Professor  Dewey  in  Vol.  II.,  No.  15,  of  same  journal. 


THE    DESCRIPTION    OF    EXPERIENCE 


Pure  experience  means  mere  experience,  experience  just  as  it 
comes,  consisting  of  things,  thoughts  and  relations,  and  these  con- 
sisting of  it.  It  is  not  conceived  subjectively  nor  does  it  presume 
any  particular  metaphysic  of  an  objective  reality.  It  is  the  simple 
presence  or  absence  of  whatever  is  empirically  present  or  not  present. 
And  as  we  are  in  this  discussion  concerned  with  cognitive  experi- 
ence, by  pure  experience  we  shall  mean  experience  characterized  as 
the  immediate  cognition  of  facts,  which  facts  may  be  things  or 
relations,  thoughts,  feelings,  convictions  or  uncertainty, 

Avenarius  gives  a  long  list  of  examples  of  experience,  and 
although  some  account  was  given  above  of  his  way  of  describing 
experience,  a  few  illustrations  from  his  own  pages  may  serve  to 
introduce  a  consideration  of  his  general  undertaking:  "It  is  an 
experience  that  the  sun  shone  yesterday,  that  it  was  obscured 
on  the  day  before,  that  a  recent  year  was  perhaps  an  unusually 
rainy  one,  or  perhaps  unusually  dry.  .  .  .  Among  people  of 
primitive  culture  an  individual  will  declare  it  his  experience  that 
the  moon,  in  case  of  an  eclipse,  is  holding  her  child  in  her  arms, 
that  one  visits  distant  places  in  sleep,  that  a  shadowy  being 
with  a  character  something  like  a  breath  (hauchartig)  is  the 
source  of  feeling  and  movement  in  the  body;  and  that  a  body  can 
exist  with  a  soul  or  without  it,  and  that  a  soul  can  exist  both  em- 
bodied and  disembodied.  Stages  of  culture  not  so  far  from  our 
own  have  the  experience  that  shrieking  drives  away  the  monster 
that  darkens  the  sun,  and  that  incantations  drive  out  the  evil  spirit 
which  has  entered  into  a  body.  In  our  own  civilization,  the  de- 
mented patient  experiences  the  command  of  God  to  throw  himself 
out  of  the  window,— he  will  fly  like  a  bird  [if  he  does  so]."^ 

A  list  like  this  could  be  prolonged  indefinitely,  but  its  significance 
is  apparent  from  a  few  examples.  Every  such  case  of  experience 
is  a  case  of  insight.  The  person  who  has  the  insight  is  not  aware 
that  he  contributes  anything  toward  the  construction  of  what  he 
perceives.  He  is  sure  that  he  is  not  mutilating  any  facts.  He 
reports  the  truth  as  he  perceives  it.  The  command  of  God,  a  bit  of 
geometry,  excursions  of  the  soul,  facts  of  chemistry  or  mechanics 
are  all  facts  which  are  directly  observed  and  reported.     From  our 

^ '  Kr.  der  R.  Erf.,'  II.,  p.  342. 

34 


THE    DESCRIPTION    OF   EXPERIENCE  35 

point  of  view  some  reports  of  experience  may  be  true  reports  of 
fact  while  others  are  not,  but  this  is  to  say  that  experience  is  not 
necessarily  valid  experience.  And  the  charge  of  incorrect  observa- 
tion must  always  be  a  character  of  another  experience. 

Now  this  cognitive  experience  can  be  made  the  object  of  scientific 
study.  To  say  that  an  explanation  of  cognitive  experience  must  be 
wholly  futile  because  the  judgments  which  state  the  explanation 
will  themselves  express  only  other  cognitive  experience  is  to  mis- 
understand the  purpose.  The  real  effort  in  a  psychophysical  ac- 
count of  pure  experience  is  not  so  much  to  get  back  of  pure  experi- 
ence, as  to  get  a  larger  acquaintance  with  it— to  extend  cognitive 
experience  so  as  to  include  judgments  about  cognitive  experience 
itself.  Of  course  we  explain  cognitive  experience  by  reducing  it 
to  cognitive  experience,  but  this  is  our  way  of  getting  a  fuller  and 
richer  cognitive  experience.  Whether  we  employ  psychophysical 
concepts  or  mere  introspection  is  a  question  of  method.  Because 
psychology  makes  extensive  use  of  psychophysical  concepts,  and 
speaks  of  an  outer  world  as  the  source  of  stimuli,  psychology  is  not 
therefore  metaphysics.  Psychology  has  its  point  of  view  and  its 
favorite  method.  Its  data  are  observed  data.  Its  aim  is  to  observe 
other  data.  Any  instruments  which  lead  to  richer  observations  are 
legitimate,  and  do  not  commit  the  psychologist  to  a  metaphysic 
just  because  the  aim  is  to  come  around  again  to  another  observation, 
and  not  to  rest  in  the  concept  of  an  ultimate  ground  of  phenomena 
which  can  not  be  observed. 

II 

This,  however,  is  the  distinction  between  description  and  explana- 
tion as  ultimate  goals.  We  may  say  that  the  aim  of  science  is  the 
widest  possible  acquaintance  with  phenomena,  where  the  word  phe- 
nomena does  not  imply  the  metaphysical  distinction  of  appearance 
and  reality.  ^Methods  of  observation  appropriate  to  different  re- 
gions of  phenomena,  and  points  of  view  for  the  apperception  and 
orderly  synthesis  of  phenomena,  are  developed.  In  the  course  of 
this  work  of  observation  and  description  various  points  of  view  are 
elaborated  which  have  the  function  of  explaining  phenomena  rather 
than  of  synthesizing  and  describing  them,  although  both  explanation 
and  description  may  be  accomplished.  A  point  of  view  which  both 
explains  and  describes  is  the  principle  of  evolution.  A  point  of 
view  which  as  yet  can  be  said  only  to  explain  is  the  reference  of 
mental  states  to  physical  processes  in  the  brain  as  the  ground  of 
consciousness.  This  latter  point  of  view  it  is  which  has  brought 
forth  the  much-discussed  concept  of  psychophysical  parallelism.  At 
the  risk  of  digression,  a  brief  orientation  on  this  concept  will  clear 
the  ground  for  considering  the  application  which  Avenarius  has 
made  of  it  in  his  'Kritik  der  Reinen  Erfahrung.' 


36  AVENARILH    AM)    I'UUE    EXl'KItlESCB 

We  know  of  course  that  a  great  deal  of  consciousness  dep<3ndB 
upon  brain-conditions.  If  we  could  make  out  these  brain-condition* 
for  given  mental  states,  we  should,  to  the  extent  we  had  done  so, 
succeed  in  explaining  the  latter.  We  are  able  to  explain  many  phe- 
nomena of  consciousness  in  a  general  way.  It  is  an  explanation, 
though  a  very  incomplete  one,  to  say  that  a  sufficient  blow  on  the 
head  puts  an  end  to  consciousness,  to  say  that  the  sensations  of  sight 
or  hearing  or  the  power  of  speech  can  be  eliminated  by  accidents  of 
a  given  type  to  the  brain.  Well,— explanation  is  interesting.  No 
one  is  obliged  to  take  explanatory  points  of  view  if  he  does  not  wish 
to  explain,  but  if  he  cares  for  the  explanation  of  mental  states  he 
must  assume  that  they  are  explainable.  lie  must  look  for  causal  con- 
nections wherever  they  can  be  found,  and  not  conclude  that  on  the 
whole  he  will  not  look  for  causal  connections  in  precisely  tli*'  roirion 
where,  to  a  certain  extent,  they  leap  at  the  eyes. 

Just  why  certain  physical  processes  should  have  phenomena  of 
consciousness  as  sequences  no  one  pretends  to  say,— but  the  same 
mystery  exists  in  all  caudal  relations.  If  one  ask  why  the  stream 
of  consciousness  continues  to  flow,  why  it  didn't  stop  a  minute  ago 
instead  of  keeping  on,  one  can  only  say  it  is  because  the  heart  con* 
tinues  to  beat,  the  blood  to  circulate,  and  the  brain  to  function.  One 
can  ask,  if  one  has  the  courage,  why  the  earth  doesn't  stop  in  its 
orbit,  or  why  the  sun  doesn't  stop  shining.  The  fact  simply  is  that 
consciousness  keeps  on  in  its  dramatic  and  picturesque  career,  and 
if  we  wish  to  explain  some  details  of  that  career,  we  look  for  laws 
of  regularity  between  antecedent  and  consequent,  and  we  assume, 
as  a  point  of  view  that  clears  the  ground  and  simplifies  the  problem, 
that  consciousness  is  explainable  in  all  respects,  so  far  as  the  facta 
themselves  are  concerned.  And  whether  one  talks  of  antecedent 
and  consequent  or  of  parallel  states  seems  hardly  to  matter  at  all. 

In  consciousness,  such  phenomena  as  the  noon  whistle  of  a  neigh- 
boring factory,  the  sound  of  a  man  shoveling  coal,  a  bicycle-bell,  a 
piano  across  the  street,  the  rattle  of  a  wagon,  may  follow  one  after 
another.  All  sorts  of  sensations  are  continually  starting  up  in  con- 
sciousness in  the  most  chaotic  fashion.  Any  causal  connection  be- 
tween them  is  out  of  the  question.  But  this  means  that  if  sensations 
are  explainable  at  all,  they  are  explainable  by  something  that  is 
conceived  as  consisting  of  something  else  than  psychic  states.  But 
if  the  mental  states  are  conceived  as  depending  upon  physical  states, 
and  these  latter  as  causally  related,  we  get  the  mental  states  in- 
directly into  a  real  series,  and  get  rid  of  chance.^ 

This  is  a  point  on  which  psychologists  have  done  a  good  deal  of 
hedging,  no  doubt  because  psychology  is  still  open  to  the  suspicion 

*See  Mtinsterberg,  'Aufgaben  imd  Methoden  der  Psychologic,'  p.  117. 


THE    DESCIUPTIOS    OF    EXPERIENCE  37 

of  entertaining  metaphysical  motives.  AVundt  will  not  admit  any 
causal  connection  between  the  physical  and  psychical  series;  each 
seems  to  flow  on  regardless  of  the  other,  but  somehow  bound  to  take 
notice  of  the  other  after  the  fashion  of  a  preestablished  harmony.^ 
His  article,  'Ueber  psychische  Causalitat,'  etc.,*  is  a  polemic  against 
what  he  calls  the  materialistic  psychology,  in  which  a  causal  relation 
is  assumed  between  physical  states  and  states  of  consciousness. 

I  really  see  no  reason  why  one  should  not  be  frankly  and  out- 
spokenly materialistic  in  a  natural  science.  It  is  understood  that 
the  question  about  ultimate  reality  is  not  raised  at  all,  and  until 
this  question  is  raised  there  is  no  metaphysic. 

But  it  certainly  comes  to  the  same  thing  in  science  to  say  that  a 
physical  state  is  the  universal  antecedent,  or  the  universal  con- 
comitant, or  the  cause  of  a  given  mental  state.  When  consciousness 
is  disordered  because  of  an  observable  accident  to  the  brain,  one  says 
the  condition  of  the  brain  thus  introduced  is  the  cause  of  the  dis- 
ordered consciousness.  There  seems  no  more  purpose  in  speaking 
of  it  as  a  merely  parallel  physical  state  which  is,  however,  not  a 
cause  of  a  mental  state,  than  to  speak  of  a  stroke  of  apoplexy  and  the 
bursting  of  a  blood-vessel  as  parallel  physical  states,  but  not  to  be 
taken  as  causes  of  changes  in  consciousness.  Epistemology  and  the 
higher  criticism  of  concepts  may  ask  in  what  sense  the  word  'cause'  is 
here  used,  but  if  the  psychologist  can  say  that  without  the  physical 
state,  the  mental  state  would  not  have  occurred,  he  has  enough 
ground  for  using  the  word  'cause'  in  a  frank  and  practical  way. 
But  in  doing  so  he  will  be  raising  no  question  about  reality,  he 
will  simply  be  assuming  that  his  phenomena  are  explainable  by 
causal  relations. 

Thus  the  relations  which  the  psychophj'sical  point  of  view  as- 
sumes are  relations  for  the  purpose  of  explanation,  but  it  is  an  ex- 
planation within  the  limits  of  phenomena,  and  no  metaphysical  im- 
plications are  permitted.  The  explanation  is  not  an  ultimate  ex- 
planation ;  the  triumph  of  the  point  of  view  would  be  to  be  brought 
around  again  into  the  mental  series,  to  be  able  to  predict  the  mental 
states  from  the  physical  ones.  That  is,  the  triumph  would  lie  not 
in  an  explanation,  but  in  a  description,  and  this  hope,  this  possibility 
it  is  which  makes  explanations  important  parts  of  scientific  under- 
takings. The  explanation  which  confessedly  is  no  help  to  a  new 
observation  may  be  interesting,  but  it  hardly  seems  important.  And 
if  it  helps  to  a  new  observation  it  fulfills  its  function,  whatever  its 
concepts  may  be.  There  may  indeed  be  a  metaphysical  concept  of 
psychophysical  parallelism,  such  a  doctrine  as  that  of  Spinoza,  for 

» '  Logik,'  Vol.  II.,  2te.  Abtheilung,  pp.  255,  257,  259. 
*  Philosophische  Studien,  Bd.  X.,  Heft  1. 


38  AVENARIU8    AND   PURE    EXPERIENCE 

instance,  but  when  the  concept  appears  in  psychology  to-day,  the 
presumption  is  that  it  is  a  point  of  view  for  the  work  in  hand. 

As  an  illustration  of  psychophysical  parallelism  on  a  very 
elaborate  scale  and  of  the  distinction  between  description  and  ex- 
planation, I  purpose  to  go  somewhat  at  length  into  the  principle 
work  of  Richard  Avenarius,  his  'Kritik  der  Reinen  Erfahrung.'  I 
am  the  more  disposed  to  this  undertaking  since  Avenarius  has.  it 
seems  to  me,  been  very  generally  misunderstood,  and  I  think  un- 
justly. 

Ill 

I  will  say  at  once  that  the  aim  of  the  'Kritik  der  Reinen 
Erfahrung'  is  to  be  a  contribution  to  natural  science,  and  that  it  is 
not  a  system  of  metaphysics.  The  interest  that  it  appeals  to  is 
primarily  the  interest  in  psychology;  it  appeals  also  to  the  interest 
in  sociology  and  history. 

That  it  should  not  have  been  so  understood  is  explicable  enough. 
The  title  reminds  us  of  Kant.  A  'Kritik  der  Reinen  Erfahrung' 
must,  one  thinks,  have  a  good  deal  in  common  with  the  'Kritik  der 
Reinen  Vernunft.'  Also,  the  author  was  a  professor  of  philosophy 
at  Zurich;  his  earlier  works  were  a  monograph  on  Spinoza  and  an 
attempt  to  define  philosophy  as  the  effort  to  conceive  the  world  ac- 
cording to  a  mechanical  principle.  His  later  work,  'Der  Menschliche 
Weltbegriff,'  had  a  good  deal  to  say  about  idealism,  and  he  himself 
was  the  editor  of  one  of  the  principal  philosophical  quarterlies. 

In  view  of  these  facts,  one  took  up  the  'Kritik  der  Reinen 
Erfahrung'  expecting  to  find,  if  not  positive  metaphysics,  at  least 
a  criticism  of  metaphysical  concepts.  If  we  add  to  this  a  disposition 
to  skip  the  notes  in  fine  print,  we  have  reasons  enough  for  misunder- 
standing the  work  before  us. 

A  remark  which  Avenarius  makes  in  a  note  is  a  good  introduc- 
tion to  his  point  of  view.  "As  we  have  learned,"  he  says,  "to  think 
of  the  nourishment  of  organisms,  of  their  recovery  from  injuries  and 
sickness,  of  their  adaptations  to  changes  in  their  environment  with- 
out the  intervention  of  the  soul,  so  we  have  now  to  learn  to  think 
of  the  so-called  purposive  changes  in  the  central  nervous  system 
without  calling  in  a  soul  (Geist)  to  help  explain,  a  soul  whose  own 
psychic  changes  would  have  to  be  first  explained."^ 

We  may  like  this  point  of  view  or  we  may  not;  it  is,  in  either 
case,  an  important  psychological  point  of  view  at  the  present  time. 
Psychology  seeks  to  describe  those  mental  activities  which  are  its 
subject-matter  by  formulating  laws  of  their  occurrence  and  in  mak- 
ing out  psychophysical  relations  wherever  they  can  be  found,  and 

^ '  Kr.  der  R.  Erf.,'  I.,  p.  202. 


THE    DESCRIPTION    OF   EXPERIENCE  39 

it  is  felt  that  it  would  be  to  give  up  the  whole  task  to  admit  a  prin- 
ciple of  original  and  arbitrary  energy  as  a  faetor  in  the  explanation. 
We  constantly  hear  that  this  is  materialism,  and  for  one  who  does 
not  distinguish  between  science  and  metaphysics  it  is  materialism. 
But  that  distinction  should,  in  the  light  of  present-day  discussion, 
be  fairly  obvious, 

Avenarius  undertakes  to  write  a  psychology  of  the  processes  of 
knowledge.  Whether  his  psychology  is  a  good  one  is  a  point  for 
psychologists  to  decide.  The  important  thing  for  us  to  notice  is 
that  the  'Kritik  der  Reinen  Erfahrung'  is  psychology. 

There  is  at  the  outset  a  certain  fund  of  information  to  build  upon. 
Whatever  our  metaphysic  may  be,  we  'know'  in  psychology  that  con- 
sciousness depends  upon  processes  in  the  brain  of  some  sort,  that  the 
nervous  system  is  responsive  to  stimuli,  that  the  whole  body,  and  the 
nervous  system  as  part  of  it,  is  constantly  engaged  in  breaking  down 
tissue,  and  is  in  need  of  appropriate  nourishment  and  of  periodical 
repose.  We  know  that  the  organism  and  its  parts  are  capable  of 
exhaustion,  and,  within  limits,  of  recovery  from  exhaustion.  There 
is  a  teleological  aspect  of  the  reactions  which  the  organism  makes 
to  a  great  many  stimuli.  This  aspect  it  is  which  has  given  to  the 
soul  concept  such  a  stubborn  foothold  in  psychology.  But  though 
we  are  unable  to  make  a  psychological  use  of  this  concept,  we  may 
not,  therefore,  overlook  the  facts  which  it  was  intended  to  explain. 
We  can  observe,  too,  a  certain  rhythmical  character  in  life  as  a  whole 
and  in  many  particular  processes.  The  alternation  of  day  and  night 
occasions  regular  intervals  of  work  and  rest,  with  points  of  maximal 
vigor  and  fatigue,  and  transitions  back  and  forth  between  them. 

We  are  assured  also  that  there  is  a  region  which  we  call  the  cen- 
tral nervous  system  which  receives  stimuli  and  determines  reactions. 
We  know,  too,  that  the  physiological  system  acquires  habits  and  is 
capable  of  acquiring  skill.  These  things  depend  upon  processes  of 
some  sort  in  an  organ,  the  brain,  but  upon  what  processes  in  partic- 
ular we  know  hardly  at  all. 

Can  we  conceive  an  organ  of  such  a  type  as  to  account  for  enough 
of  such  phenomena  as  to  make  it  a  useful  concept  for  psychological 
purposes?  Avenarius  thinks  we  can,  and  he  proceeds  to  describe 
a  central  nervous  system  with  such  characters  as  would  explain,  he 
thinks,  a  great  many  phenomena  in  a  psychological  way. 

Avenarius  describes  a  way  of  apperceiving  the  central  nervous 
system.  Certain  phenomena  being  given,  there  is  wanted  a  concept 
to  make  them  intelligible.  Avenarius  is,  in  so  far,  in  the  same 
position  as  the  one  who  elaborates  a  system  of  atomic  relations  to 
account  for  chemical  phenomena. 

The  central  nervous  system  is  called  by  Avenarius  the  System 


40  AVENAIilUS    AND    I'UIiE    KXI'KlilKSCE 

C.  This  do.si*,'nati()n  is  cliosen  for  purposes  of  convfuience,  and  for 
limiting,'  the  discussion  of  the  system  C  to  those  characters  which 
he  wishes  to  lay  stress  upon.  The  system  C  appears  to  be  really  the 
brain,  but  the  word  brain  has  many  associations  and  suggestions 
which  Avenarius  wishes  to  leave  out  of  account. 

The  system  C  is  conceived  as  situated  in  the  world  amon*;  objects, 
from  which  it  receives  stimuli  of  various  sorts,  to  many  of  which 
the  reaction  is  a  cognition.  The  undertaking  is  chiefly  a  psychology 
of  cognitive  experience,  and  accordingly  non-cognitive  reactions  are 
left  out  of  account.  Avenarius  states  the  situation  as  follows: 
"Let  any  part  of  our  environment  be  in  such  a  relation  to  human 
individuals  that  when  the  former  is  a.s8umed,  the  latter  state  an 
experience;  'something  is  experienced,  something  is  an  experience 
or  is  a  product  of  experience,  or  depends  upon  experience.'  "^ 

The  statements  of  experience  are  called  J^-values,  the  stimuli 
themselves  are  called  i2- values  (Reiz).  An  J5J- value  depends  directly 
not  upon  any  i2-value,  but  upon  the  system  C,  and  any  particular 
jE'-value  is  a  consequence  primarily  of  the  constitution  of  C  at  the 
time  when  it  gave  expression  to  E. 

Changes  of  some  sort  certainly  take  place  in  the  brain.  We  say 
that  tissue  is  broken  down  and  built  up.  The  process  of  wear  and 
tear  we  believe  to  be  due  in  great  part,  at  least,  to  physiological 
excitations  due  to  the  world  without.  The  rebuilding  of  tissue  de- 
pends, we  are  sure,  upon  the  blood-supply  to  the  brain.  We  are 
familiar  with  feelings  of  exhaustion  and  of  recovery  of  vigor,  and 
we  are  reasonably  sure  that  these  feelings  depend  on  corresponding 
conditions  of  the  brain,  and  that  between  the  condition  which  accom- 
panies a  loss  of  vigor  and  that  which  accompanies  the  feeling  of 
restored  vigor  a  series  of  states  of  the  brain  intervenes.  We  know 
also  tliat  there  can  be  too  much  nourishment  of  the  whole  organism 
and  presumably  of  the  brain  and  we  know  that  the  excess  can  be 
worked  off,  that  is,  that  a  certain  destruction  of  brain  tissue  brings 
back  a  normal  condition  of  that  organ,  a  point  of  balance  between 
nourishment  and  work  which  we  would  preserve  if  we  could.  This 
ideal  point  of  balance  about  which  we  seem  continually  to  oscillate, 
Avenarius  calls  the  'Vitalerkaltiingsmaximum,'  or  the  point  of  com- 
plete vital  preservation.  When  that  point  is  reached,  the  system 
C  is  in  a  state  of  stability.  Such  a  point  we  do  seem  to  pass  and 
repass  continually. 

We  may  regard  this  condition  of  stability  within  C  as  the  balance 
of  two  factors,  one  of  them  all  those  influences  which  make  for  the 
exhaustion  of  C,  the  other,  the  influences  which  make  for  the  restora- 
tion and  nourishment  of  C.  The  former  of  these,  being  the  sum  of 
^ '  Kr.  der  R.  Erf.,'  I.,  p.  .3. 


THE    DESCRIPTIOy    OF   EXPERIENCE  41 

the  ^-values  which  play  upon  C  and  stimulate  it  to  reactions, 
Avenarius  calls  fiU).     The  other  he  calls  f{S). 

And  since  the  stability  of  C  means  that  these  two  opposing 
factors  are  equal  to  each  other  and  therefore  nullify  each  other, 
Avenarius  expresses  the  situation  by  the  equation  f{li)=  —  f{S), 
or  f{R)  4-/(5')  =0,  which  means  that  the  result  of  the  coopera- 
tion of  fiR)  and  f(S)  is  that  the  system  C  does  not  depart  from 
stability. 

But  if,  starting  with  the  system  C  in  stability,  we  vary  either 
f{R)  or  f{S),  then  it  will  no  longer  be  true  that  f{R)  -f  fi^)  =0. 
To  the  degree  to  which  one  of  the  factors  has  been  altered,  the 
system  C  has  departed  from  a  state  of  stability.  There  has  ensued 
a  'Vital  Difference'  and  this  vital  difference  is  the  dift'erence  between 
fiR)  and  f{S).  One  of  the  two  factors  is  more  effective  in  its  in- 
fluence than  the  other,  and  the  difference  between  the  two  opposed 
forces  is  the  vital  difference.  Since  one  of  the  factors  is  regarded 
as  negative  as  related  to  the  other,  the  difference  is  thus  expressed: 
fiR)  +  fiS)  >  0.  The  equation  fiR)  +  /(&')  =0  signifies  that  the 
vital  difference  has  a  value  of  zero,  while  the  equation  fiR)-{- 
fiS)  >  0  signifies  that  the  vital  difference  is  greater  than  zero. 

The  system  C,  however,  tends  always  to  return  to  stability,  and 
the  process  of  return  must  be  a  process  of  annulling  the  vital 
difference.  There  is  thus  a  transition  from  stability  through  a 
condition  of  instability  characterized  by  the  existence  of  a  vital 
difference  back  to  stability,  where  the  vital  difference  is  reduced  to 
zero.  This  series  of  states  from  stability  to  stability,  Avenarius 
calls  a  vital  series. 

The  vital  series  as  thus  described  is  a  series  of  changes  in  the 
system  C.  The  reason  for  assuming  such  series  of  changes  is  that 
parallel  series  of  conscious  states  can  be  observed.  The  process  of 
attention  is  an  example.  We  start  from  what  we  may  call  a  con- 
dition of  indifference,  or  rest,  or  stability,  then  something  awakens 
our  interest  and  we  begin  to  attend  to  some  sort  of  a  problem.  We 
continue  in  a  state  of  indecision  and  doubt  and  perplexity,  looking 
forward,  however,  toward  the  solution  which  we  hope  to  find.  At 
last  the  solution  comes,  and  we  are  at  peace  with  oui*selves  again. 

Now  if  to  the  changes  of  consciousness  there  is  a  parallel  series 
of  brain-events,  they  must  form  a  series,  and  since  each  term  of  the 
series  must  be  adequate  to  its  effect  in  consciousness,  the  physiolog- 
ical series  may  be  described  with  reference  to  its  dependent  mental 
states,  and  its  terms  considered  as  bearing  relations  to  one  another 
similar  to  the  relations  and  proportions  in  the  consciousness  series. 
This  is  not  so  empty  or  so  metaphysical  as  it  may  sound.  We  take 
it  for  granted,  in  a  general  way,  that  of  the  changes  in  brain  tissue 


42  AVEMARIUS    AND   PURE    EXPERIENCE 

which  produce  changes  in  consciousness,  the  greater  the  one  e)i;uige 
the  ^eater  the  other.  And  although  the  one  series  of  chani^es  is 
quantitative  and  the  other  qualitative,  we  do  speak  of  a  more  and 
less,  and  carry  on  a  good  deal  of  comparison  in  the  region  of 
qualities.  We  have,  in  any  case,  a  physiological  series,  and  depend- 
ent upon  this  a  series  of  mental  states,  or  rather  we  have  a  con- 
tinuous nervous  process  and  a  continuous  stream  of  conii<;iousne88 
depending  upon  the  former,  and  these  continuous  processes  we  can 
break  up  into  parallel  lengths,  called  vital  series.  The  physiological 
series  is  called  the  Independent  Vital  Series,  the  series  in  conscious- 
ness is  called  the  Dependent  Vital  Series. 

It  is  unfortunate  that  the  method  of  exposition  chosen  by 
Avenarius  makes  it  appear  superficially  that  the  dependent  vital 
series  is  deduced  from  the  concept  of  the  independent  series,  to- 
gether with  the  general  presuppositions,  and  that  therefore  nothing 
about  the  dependent  series  can  be  any  better  established  than  the 
concept  of  the  independent  series. 

Obviously,  however,  the  dependent  series  is  a  movement  in  con- 
sciousness which  can  be  observed,  and  it  is  to  account  for  these 
series  of  conscious  states,  which  are  data  of  experience,  that  the 
physiological  series  is  assumed. 

In  the  above  case  of  an  attention-process  as  a  dependent  vital 
series,  three  stages  can  be  observed:  first,  the  appearance  of  the 
problem,  the  awakening  of  interest  and  the  consequent  feeling  of 
restlessness  and  dissatisfaction  if  the  solution  does  not  immediately 
appear.  This  is  the  'Initial'  stage;  then  comes  the  continued 
effort  to  solve  the  problem,  the  'Medial'  stage;  and  finally  the  appear- 
ance of  the  solution,  characterized  by  satisfaction,  abating  anxiety, 
the  settling  down  upon  an  opinion  or  a  cognition.  This  is  the  'Final' 
stage.  Corresponding  Xo  these  three  stages  of  the  dependent  series 
are  three  stages  of  the  independent  series,— the  appearance  of  the 
vital  difference  and  a  departure  of  the  system  C  from  stability,  the 
continuance  for  a  longer  or  shorter  time  with  an  approximately  con- 
stant vital  difference,  and  then  the  reduction  of  the  vital  difference 
to  zero,  with  consequent  return  to  stability. 

The  system  C  maintains  itself  by  getting  back  to  stability  after 
disturbances.  This  functional  activity  can  be  performed  in  a  way 
that  is  better  or  worse  for  the  life  of  the  system  C  itself,  that  is, 
we  can  conceive  an  ideal  system  C.  Such  an  organ  would,  after  any 
disturbance,  return  to  stability  with  the  shortest  interval  of  a  vital 
series.  This  would  be  accomplished  if  the  system  C  were  trained 
to  recover  stability  by  means  of  well-learned  and  completely  habitual 
vital  series,  that  is,  if  the  system  C  by  virtue  of  its  liability  to  habit 
has  learned  to  recover  stability  with  maximum  facility. 


THE   DESCRIPTION    OF   EXPERIENCE  43 

Now  we  are  sure  that  the  nervous  system  is  subject  to  habit,  and 
that  this  is  one  of  the  factors  which  is  most  important  in  making 
life  well  organized,  in  simplifying  the  mental  outlook,  in  making 
experience  coherent  and  developing  a  consistent  will.  Our  point  of 
view  obliges  us,  therefore,  to  assume  a  parallel  physiological  develop- 
ment. 

Certain  independent  (physiological)  vital  series  thus  become 
habitual,  and  the  functional  excellence  of  the  system  C  is  in  pro- 
portion as  the  fund  of  habitual  series  is  adequate  to  all  the  reactions 
of  the  system.  Such  an  'eingeiihte'  series  Avenarius  calls  a  'vital 
series  of  the  first  order.'  Other  series  with  a  more  or  less  novel 
character  he  calls  'vital  series  of  a  higher  order.'  Evidently  the 
functional  development  of  the  system  C  lies  in  the  reduction  of  series 
of  higher  orders  to  series  of  the  first  order.  This  means  the  gradual 
introduction  of  order  into  the  behavior  of  the  system  C  by  means 
of  its  own  education,  if  we  may  so  describe  it. 

By  habit  we  reduce  the  complex  environment  to  its  simplest 
terms.  We  learn  to  ignore  large  masses  of  it,  or  rather  we  react 
upon  various  manifolds  according  to  certain  constant  characters  or 
values  which  we  find  in  them.  If  we  translate  this  into  physio- 
logical terms,  it  gives  us  a  sort  of  physiological  selection.  The 
nervous  system  has  become  responsive  to  certain  selected  portions 
of  its  environment.  That  is,  the  education  of  the  system  C  has 
been  controlled  by  certain  ^-values  to  the  exclusion  of  others.  This 
concept  of  physiological  habit  is  of  the  first  importance  in  the  theory 
of  Avenarius,  but  it  is  so  important  because  the  fact  of  habit  is  of 
such  great  importance  in  life. 

The  consequence  of  habit  is  that  experience  becomes  less  and 
less  diversified.  All  sorts  of  ^-values  no  longer  occur.  In  its 
effects  upon  experience,  growth  by  habit  is  a  process  of  exclusion, 
which,  so  far  as  the  character  of  the  sj'stem  C  is  concerned,  could 
go  on  indefinitely.  It  is  a  process  by  which  the  mind  comes  to  give 
a  final  definite  character  to  the  manifold  presented  to  it  by  the  world, 
—a  process  by  which  a  maximum  experience  of  the  world  expresses 
itself  in  a  resulting  apperception  of  the  world.  This  final  apper- 
ception of  the  world  depends  upon  the  possession  of  a  predicate 
which  is  applicable  to  every  fact  which  experience  testifies  to  as 
existent,  and  this  means,  in  the  terminology  of  Avenarius,  that  a 
final  stage  of  the  system  C  has  been  found  by  which  any  vital  dif- 
ference may  be  annulled.  By  virtue  of  its  capacity  for  acquiring 
habits,  the  system  C  has  found  an  answer  to  the  question,  'What  is 
everything  ? ' 

This  idea  of  a  limiting  stage  of  the  process  of  progressive  deter- 
mination of  experience  is,  of  course,  only  an  idea,  but  it  is  not. 


44  AVENARIU8   AND   PURE    EXPEFtlENCE 

therefore,  an  insignificant  idea.  It  is  the  e(>iic<*|)t  of  the  natural 
limit  of  that  kind  of  process  which  we  are  perfectly  familiar  with 
as  habit. 

It  is  easy  to  get  the  impression  that  every  vital  series  must  be 
started  by  an  outer  7)J- value.  This,  however,  is  not  the  case.  If  we 
recall  the  formula  for  stability,  f{K)  -\-  fiS)  =0,  we  perceive  that 
a  vital  series  can  be  initiated  by  a  variation  of  f{S)  as  well  as  of 

fiR). 

The  system  C  is,  after  all,  the  brain,— blood  is  being  constantly 
supplied  to  it  and  its  own  complex  constitution  and  energy  must 
be  a  continual  source  of  instability. 

A  judgment  is  an  A^-value.  Judgments  accordingly  follow  the 
same  law  of  habit  that  all  £J-values  follow.  There  is  a  progressive 
exclusion  of  possible  judgments,  a  progressive  definition  of  experi- 
ence in  the  narrower  sense,  an  evolution  of  pure  experience  by  virtue 
of  the  law  of  habit.  It  is  this  evolution  of  pure  experience  in 
which  Avenarius  is  primarily  interested. 

One  has  only  to  compare  different  civilizations  and  stages  of 
culture  to  observe  that  the  world  may  contain  for  one  race  and  for 
one  time  very  different  objects  of  experience  from  those  which  it 
contains  for  another  race  or  another  time.  Our  own  way  of  ex- 
periencing the  world  is  certainly  the  outcome  of  an  evolution.  The 
discussion  about  possible  objects  of  experience  in  the  first  section 
of  this  paper  sought  to  make  clear  that  almost  anything  can  be  an 
object  of  experience.  We  conceive  of  our  experience  to-day  as  being 
very  much  more  valid,  more  adjusted  to  the  facts  of  nature,  more 
*  scientific '  than  the  experience  of  our  ancestors  a  few  centuries  back. 
"We  are  disposed  to  think  that  we  have  awakened  from  credulity  and 
superstition,  and  that  we  look  out  upon  the  world  with  a  sane  and 
critical  observation.  Perhaps  we  do,  but  it  is  interesting  to  note 
that  experience  has  come  to  be  what  it  is  for  the  man  of  science 
among  us  as  the  result  of  the  continual  modification  of  a  primitive 
and  wholly  uncritical  experience. 

About  that  primitive  experience  we,  of  course,  know  very  little, 
but  there  is  reason  enough  to  suppose  that  it  had  a  decidedly  'ani- 
mistic' character.  In  that  primitive  stage  of  culture  in  our  own 
prehistoric  past  no  doubt  many  things  could  be  objects  of  experience 
which  could  not  be  objects  of  our  experience.  There  has  been  a 
progressive  elimination  of  certain  objects  of  experience,  and  a  pro- 
gressive enrichment  of  experience  by  the  acquisition  of  other  objects. 
When  we  are  in  an  imaginative  mood  we  sometimes  lament  that 
nature  has  lost  for  us  the  vivifying  presence  of  the  gods  of  the  soil, 
the  groves  and  the  streams.  But  in  a  rationalizing  mood,  we  say 
that  we  no  longer  introject  into  nature  the  likeness  of  ourselves. 


THE    DESCRIPTION    OF   EXPERIENCE  45 

We  hold  that  our  concept  of  nature  is  a  valid  concept,  the  product 
of  critical  and  unbiased  observation.  Translated  into  the  language 
of  Avenarius,  this  means  that  our  iJ-values  correspond  to  our 
ii?-values.  We  say  about  nature  only  what  she  says  about  herself. 
The  ^-values  which  express  primitive  animistic  experience  are  cer- 
tainly decidedly  different  in  some  respects  from  those  iJ-values 
which  express  the  experience  of  a  Helmholtz  or  a  Huxley.  Yet  they 
are  alike  in  being  all  J?-values.  Whether  justly  or  not,  we  do  speak 
of  an  enlightened  scientific  experience  and  contrast  it  with  one 
that  is  relatively  superstitious,  and  the  enlightened  experience,  as 
well  as  the  other,  has  its  roots  in  that  primitive  experience  which  we 
may  suppose  to  have  been  absolutely  imaginative  and  credulous. 

But  few  of  us  are  accomplished  men  of  science.  Not  everj'  one 
has  moved  so  far  from  the  starting-point.  And  yet  we  may  say  that 
there  is  a  large  group  of  minds  that  take  what  we  may  call  the 
scientific  point  of  view,  whose  experience  does  not  include  mytholog- 
ical objects.  Other  minds,  those  that  make  up  the  great  majority  in 
our  own  civilization,  while  not  distinguished  by  very  consciously  scien- 
tific points  of  view,  do  yet  have  an  experience,  more  resembling  the 
experience  of  a  scientific  mind  than  that  of  the  primitive  animistic 
mind.  Yet  there  still  remain,  Avenarius  thinks,  some  traces  of  the 
original  fund  of  animistic  objects.  The  further  development  of 
this  idea,  the  description  and  criticism  of  the  remnant  of  animism, 
has  for  Avenarius  a  special  polemical  interest,  which  would  lead  us 
too  far  aside  to  follow  up.  What  Avenarius  would  have  us  observe 
is  that  the  evolution  of  experience  is  still  in  progress,  and  that  what 
lies  ahead  must  be  a  continuation  of  what  lies  behind.  The  progress 
thus  far  has  been  the  development  of  that  concept  of  nature  which 
natural  science  has  come  to  regard  as  the  proper  one,  and  the  very 
general  elimination  of  animism.  The  continuance  of  the  same  proc- 
ess should  mean  the  complete  elimination  of  animism,  making  the 
modern  concept  of  nature  wholly  consistent  and  the  complete  ac- 
ceptance of  the  world  so  defined  as  an  object  of  experience. 

All  this  history  of  experience  can  be  made  the  matter  of  a  psycho- 
logical study  which  should  seek  to  describe  the  process  from  a  psycho- 
physical point  of  view.      This  is  what  Avenarius  has  done. 

The  line  of  thought  by  which  Avenarius  himself  approached  this 
problem  helps  somewhat  to  throw  light  on  the  definition  of  the  prob- 
lem itself  as  Avenarius  understood  it.  Avenarius  has  expressed 
great  indebtedness  to  ]\Iach,^  and  his  approval  of  the  latter 's  'Prin- 
ciple of  Economy.'  Mach  has  stated  this  principle  in  the  following 
terms:  "Science  itself,  therefore,  may  be  regarded  as  a  minimal 
problem,  consisting  of  the  completest  possible  presentment  of  facts 

»'Kr.  der  R.  Erf.,'  Vol.  I.,  p.  xiii;  Vol.  II.,  p.  492. 


46  AVENARIUB    AND    I'UJiE    EXl'EHIENCE 

with  the  least  possible  expenditure  of  thought.*'^  That  is,  the  aim 
of  science  is  to  give  such  a  conceptual  description  of  experience  as 
shall  be  most  comprehensive  and  readily  intelligible. 

"With  this  in  mind  let  us  make  science  the  object  of  a  psychological 
inquiry.  It  seems  evident  enough  that  the  mind  is  an  instrument 
for  accomplishing  purposes.  It  makes  a  difference  to  the  organism 
whether  the  mind  functions  well  or  ill.  But  in  attributing  this 
teleological  value  to  the  mind,  we  have  demanded  two  things.  Not 
only  must  there  be  an  organ  to  function  in  a  purposive  way,  but  this 
functioning  must  be  carried  out  as  well  as  the  given  conditions  make 
possible.  Other  things  being  equal,  that  functional  adjustment  will 
be  the  best  one  which  is  made  with  the  least  expenditure  of  energy. 

This  may  sound  like  an  effort  to  translate  psychology  into  pseudo 
mechanics,  but  I  think  there  is  really  no  mystery.  No  one  would 
deny,  I  fancy,  that,  other  things  being  equal,  that  adjustment  of  the 
organism  is  the  best  which  is  least  exhausting  to  it.  Vital  energy, 
whatever  that  may  be  or  depend  upon  (and  I  do  not  wish  to  imply 
any  unique  'vital  force'),  is  finite  in  quantity,  so  that  it  makes  a 
great  deal  of  dift'erence  whether  our  energy  is  wasted  or  not.  But 
if  we  banish  the  concept  of  a  'vital  force'  and  mean  by  force  only 
what  is  meant  in  mechanics,  and  then  undertake  to  give  a  psycho- 
physical account  of  the  way  in  which  Maeh's  'Principle  of  Economy' 
works,  remembering  that  the  idea  of  mechanical  force  is  due  to  the 
sense  of  effort  and  energy  in  experience,  it  seems  not  inappropriate 
to  find  the  mechanical  equivalent  of  the  principle  of  economy  in  the 
principle  of  least  resistance.  Accordingly,  an  early  essay  by  Aven- 
arius  is  entitled,  'Philosophy  as  Conceiving  the  World  according  to 
the  Principle  of  Least  Resistance. ' 

It  may  perhaps  be  said  that  this  is  an  attempt  to  describe  science 
itself  as  the  line  of  least  resistance,  whereas  science  means  effort, 
the  expenditure  of  force.  How  much  less  is  the  effort  involved  in 
being  indifferent  to  scientific  problems !  The  man  who  cares  nothing 
for  science  is,  other  things  being  equal,  more  economical,  as  regards 
his  energy,  than  the  eager  scientist.  Science  is  not,  this  view  would 
hold,  the  line  of  least  resistance,  but  a  line  of  very  great  resistance. 

This  objection  is,  however,  not  so  well  founded  as  it  seems  to  be 
at  first  glance.  We  find  ourselves  with  a  large  program  of  theo- 
retical interests  on  our  hands.  These  interests  are  more  or  less 
lively  attitudes  on  our  part.  We  find  ourselves  responding  to  what 
interests  us.  We  can  not  put  the  problems  aside  and  be  indifferent 
to  them ;  they  haunt  us,  and  demand  our  attention,  I  am  speaking, 
of  course,  of  the  men  who  care  for  problems,  of  the  men  who  have 


The  Science  of  Mechanics,'  translated  from  2d  ed.,  Chicago,  1893,  p,  490. 


THE    DESCRIPTION    OF   EXPERIENCE  47 

made  science  and  philosophy  and  are  making  it.  The  need  of  solv- 
ing a  problem  is  a  real  practical  need.  How  much  science  should 
we  at  present  have  if  there  had  not  been  a  large  amount  of  that 
human  restlessness,  which  we  call  interest,  on  matters  of  theory. 

This  scientific  uneasiness  depends  upon  a  capacity  for  discover- 
ing problems  and  being  worried  by  them.  The  presence  of  some 
unexplained,  uncomprehended  thing  is  a  cause  of  effort,  of  striving, 
of  using  up  energy.  The  energy  is  expended  for  a  purpose,  the 
solving  of  the  problem ;  and  of  various  solutions  that  may  offer  them- 
selves that  one  is  accepted  as  the  best  which  calls  for  the  smallest 
expenditure  of  energy.  The  elegant  demonstration  is  the  one  which 
makes  use  of  few  resources.  Clearness  and  transparency  of  method 
and  result  mean  usually  that  relatively  little  effort  is  needed  to 
understand  them. 

Let  us  admit  then,  for  the  purpose  of  this  discussion,  that  the 
principle  of  economy  is  the  guiding  principle  in  science,  and  that 
tlie  principle  of  least  resistance  is  its  parallel  principle  in  nerve- 
tissue. 

Every  special  science  seeks  to  get  what  it  might  call  a  valid  ex- 
perience of  its  objects,  and  this  means  that  it  tries  to  get  the  objects 
pure  and  uncontaminated  by  any  personal  equation.  No  doubt  the 
principle  of  economy  leads,  to  a  certain  extent,  to  a  misrepresenta- 
tion of  objects,  but  this  is  the  ignoring  of  what  is  regarded  as 
irrelevant  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  special  interests,  whereas  a 
subjective  enrichment  of  the  object  is  the  putting  into  it  of  what 
might  make  a  difference  in  the  description.  This  much  seems  clear, 
science  feels  at  liberty  to  ignore  as  much  detail  in  the  objects  as  it 
is  not  interested  in,  but  it  denies  the  right  to  add  anything. 

Now  if  we  admit  that  the  special  sciences  are  seeking  to  get  their 
objects  pure  and  if  we  imagine  that  there  is  a  special  science  for 
each  region  of  phenomena,  and  if  we  call  this  experience  of  pure 
objects  a  pure  experience,  then  the  special  sciences  are  collectively 
aiming  at  a  pure  experience  of  the  world. 

This  was  the  meaning  of  pure  experience  as  Avenarius  used  the 
term  in  his  'Philosophic  als  Denken  der  Welt  Gemass  dem  Princip 
des  Kleinsten  Kraftmasscs, '  and  it  is  one  of  the  meanings  of  the 
term  in  the  '  Kritik  der  Reinen  Erfahrung. '  But  since  such  a  pure 
experience  is  defined  from  an  epistemological  and  not  from  a  psycho- 
logical point  of  view,  the  concept  does  not  appear  in  the  same  form 
in  the  later  work. 

The  special  sciences  are  distributed,  each  to  its  own  field.  Within 
each  field,  novel  facts  are  comprehended  by  reducing  them  to  a  group 
of  known  facts,  which  group  undertakes  to  be  as  small  as  possible. 
In  the  same  way  the  effort  to  understand  the  world  would  be  the 


48  AVENARIUfi    AND    PUKE    KXI'I'JUESCE 

effort  to  reduce  to  ii  sin^^le  concept  the  cliariiclcrs,  coiiiiihiii  to  the 
pure  experience,  which  the  special  sciences  are  able  to  securr.  This 
effort,  based  upon  the  special  sciences,  to  describe  the  common  char- 
acter of  the  whole  world,  is,  says  Avenarins,  philosophy.  It  is  the 
effort  to  answer  the  question.  What  is  everything?  With  so  much 
in  mind,  we  are  prepared  to  understand  the  following  quotation: 
**In  accordance  with  the  principle  of  least  resistance  there  is  accom- 
plished the  reference  of  a  sin;;le  presentation  to  a  j;eneral  concept, 
and  in  so  far  as  this  presentation  is  strange  and  novel  it  is  made 
known  by  this  reference.  Accordinpfly,  conceptual  understanding  is 
a  force-economizing,  theoretical  apprehension  of  an  object,  and  the 
totality  of  objects  will  be  most  economically  conceived,  if  they  can 
be  apprehended  under  one  general  concept.  This  effort  to  conceive 
the  totality  of  objects  with  the  minimum  expenditure  of  force  is 
philosophy.  The  all-comprehending  concept  must  state  what  is 
common  to  all  particular  objects.  This  common  aspect  mast  be 
given  in  pure  experience.  Individual  cases  of  pure  experience  are 
secured  by  means  of  observation  in  the  special  sciences,  and  the 
purification  of  experience,  in  general,  results  from  the  elimination 
of  what  is  found  to  not  really  belong  to  the  objects  of  experience."* 

It  may  appear  that  we  are  getting  a  good  way  from  the  system 
C  and  its  vital  series.  The  digression  has  its  purpose,  however,  in 
that  it  will  help  us  to  understand  the  way  in  which  Avenarius  him- 
self viewed  his  problem,  by  seeing  that  problem  in  its  earlier  stages. 

Let  us  now  connect  the  essay  we  have  just  been  considering  with 
an  article  by  Avenarius  entitled  'The  Relation  of  Psychology  to 
Philosophy.'-  In  the  essay  just  considered,  Avenarius  describes 
philosophy  as  a  certain  kind  of  human  effort,  the  effort  to  get  a 
unified  conception  of  the  universe,  to  ask  the  question,  What  is  every- 
thing?  and  to  tell  what  it  is. 

This  question,  WTiat  is  the  nature  of  the  world  ?  How  is  the  world 
constituted?  is  the  question  of  philosophy.  When  this  question  is 
first  asked,  there  is  no  doubt  concerning  our  power  to  know  how  the 
world  is  constituted  if  we  can  only  find  it  out.  At  the  same  time, 
psychology  contributes  little  or  nothing  in  giving  shape  to  philos- 
ophy. Psychology  hardly  exists  as  an  independent  field,  but  forms 
a  chapter  in  some  sj'stem  of  metaphysics.  The  fate  of  metaphysical 
systems,  however,  contradictions  discovered  within  and  without, 
made  the  problem  of  knowledge  more  and  more  prominent,  so  that 
instead  of  the  question.  How  is  the  world  constituted?  we  have  the 
question,  How  is  the  w^orld  known?      W^hen  this  question  is  first 


^ '  Philosophic  als  Denken  der  Welt,'  p.  43. 

' '  Ueber  die  Stellung  der  Psychologic  zur  Philosophie,'  Vierteljahrschrift  fur 
Wissenschaftliche  Philosophie,  I.,  p.  471. 


THE    DESCRIPTION    OF   EXPERIENCE  49 

critically  asked  reality  is  still  attributed  to  objects  which  lie  outside 
of  experience,  but  great  emphasis  is  laid  upon  the  subjective  factor 
in  knowledge.  It  is  taken  for  granted  that  perception  does  not 
give  an  object  as  it  really  is,  that  the  whole  content  is  not  given  in 
perception,  but,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  assumed  that  the  whole  con- 
tent given  in  perception  does  not  really  belong  to  the  object.  Ob- 
jective reality  is  thus,  at  the  same  time,  more  and  less  than  ex- 
perience. 

The  original  question,  How  is  the  world  constituted!  demands 
now  a  distinction  between  what  can  be  taken  as  valid  experience  of 
objects  and  experience  which  misrepresents  its  objects.  By  this 
emphasis  laid  upon  the  problem  of  knowledge,  and  the  recognition 
that  the  mind  is  so  constituted  as  perhaps  to  interfere  with  its  own 
cognitive  purposes,  psychology  becomes  of  decided  importance  for 
philosophy,  and  it  is  not  long  before  the  world  of  real  objects  shrinks 
to  a  region  of  things  in  themselves,  set  over  against  forms  of  ex- 
perience. It  is  a  matter  of  recent  history  how  the  content  of  the 
world,  which  seemed  to  be  lost  on  the  objective  side,  was  brought 
back  from  the  subjective  side,  and  how  from  this  point  of  view  the 
great  systems  of  idealism  grew  up.  But  whether  deservedly  or  not, 
those  systems  have  fallen  into  disrepute,  one  factor  in  this  situation 
being  the  progress  of  physical  science.  And  to-day  if  one  asks  how 
we  know  the  world,  the  scientist  will  point  to  his  instruments  fur 
observation  and  experiment  and  say,  *  With  these  we  know  the  world. ' 

But  knowledge  secured  by  the  aid  of  instruments  for  exact  meas- 
urement is  not  the  less  subjective.  Truer,  perhaps,  it  would  have 
been  to  say,  'By  the  use  of  these  instruments  do  we  conceive  the 
world. ' 

The  question,  How  is  the  world  constituted?  has  become,  pro- 
visionally at  least,  the  question,  How  is  the  world  conceived!  And 
to  this  question  one  may  now  give  a  somewhat  unexpected  answer. 
The  world  is  conceived  by  a  nervous  organism  reacting  in  a  certain 
way  to  its  environment,  and  the  question,  How  is  the  world  conceived! 
becomes  the  question.  How  does  this  organism  behave  in  conceiving 
the  world?  or,  "What  kind  of  a  natural  process  is  philosophy! 
Philosophy  is  a  certain  type  of  human  activity,  and  if  one  agrees 
that  activities  of  thought  depend  upon  processes  in  nervous  tissue, 
one  has  a  ground  for  asking,  as  a  scientist,  what  sort  of  natural 
process  philosophy  is. 

Avenarius  undertakes  to  carry  out  frankly  the  psychophysical 
point  of  view.  He  conceives  that  t\T)es  of  experience  depend  upon 
typical  processes  within  an  organ.  The  organ  he  afterwards  called 
by  the  name  of  *  System  C '  and  its  processes  he  sought  to  describe  as 
'Vital  Series.' 

4 


50  AVENARIU8   AND   PURE   EXPERIENCE 

This  brings  us  back  to  the  'Kritik  der  Reinen  EJrfahning,*  but  it 
brings  us  back  prepared  to  observe  the  application  of  the  method 
of  the  'Kritik'  to  the  description  of  philosophy  as  a  natural  process. 
If  the  question,  'How  do  we  conceive  the  world!'  in  this  new  form 
can  be  answered  with  any  measure  of  success,  we  may  be  able  to 
reach  some  conclusions  about  the  conditions  on  which  the  fate  of 
systems  of  philosophy  depends,  and  be  able  to  state  what  conditions 
must  be  fulfilled  by  a  philosophy  which  shall  endure. 

It  was  remarked  above  that  the  appearance  of  a  problem  means 
a  certain  restlessness  on  the  part  of  him  who  sees  the  problem.  We 
ought  to  distinguish  between  real  problems  and  pretended  prob- 
lems. By  real  problems  I  mean  questions  that  strike  us  as  really 
problematic,  questions  whose  solution  one  way  or  another  makes 
a  difference  to  us,  questions  which  are  problems  not  merely  by  virtue 
of  a  definition,  but  by  virtue  of  the  kind  of  interest  they  arouse. 
Besides  the  genuine  problems  there  are  problems  which  do  not  show 
any  really  problematic  character.  The  problem  about  solipsism  is 
a  problem  of  this  sort.  A  healthy  man  can  not  possibly  find  any 
real  problem  here.  We  may  admit  that  the  reality  of  other  selves  is 
problematic,  but  we  shall  be  quite  unable  to  experience  the  prob- 
lematic character  which  we  admit. 

Progress  in  science  and  philosophy  is  largely  due  to  a  capacity 
for  discovering  real  problems.  Oriental  peoples  have  this  genius 
in  a  far  less  degree  than  Europeans.  The  problems  of  the  Oriental 
consciousness  are  solved.  Only  the  Western  con.sciousness  is  tor- 
mented with  doubts  about  reality,  duty,  the  past  and  the  future. 
Avenarius  loves  to  dwell  on  the  satisfaction  and  relief  which  the 
solution  of  a  real  problem  affords,  and  on  the  teasing,  restless,  un- 
satisfied state  which  accompanies  an  unsolved  real  problem. 

The  distinction  between  the  real  problem  and  the  artificial  prob- 
lem w^ould  appear  to  be  a  real  and  important  distinction  from  the 
psychological  point  of  view,  where  the  purpose  is  an  accurate  descrip- 
tion of  experience.  For  this  point  of  view,  the  so-called  artificial 
problem  is  no  problem  at  all.  That  is,  its  parallel  brain-proce.ss 
can  not  be  the  one  w-hich  gives  rise  to  the  problematic  character. 
Accordingly,  the  word  'problem'  will  designate,  in  what  remains  to 
be  said  about  Avenarius,  always  the  real  and  genuine  problem,  the 
problem  with  the  biological  disturbance  behind  it.  Evidently  a 
philosophy  which  is  to  endure,  which  shall  be,  as  Avenarius  puts  it, 
'  hiologisch  haltiar/  must  be  an  ^- value  or  a  group  of  ^-values  which 
express  a  permanent  stability  of  the  system  C.  These  E'-values  hare, 
in  the  process  of  physiological  selection  which  marks  the  evolution 
of  habit,  come  to  prevail  over  other  ^-values.  They  have  come  to 
prevail  because  they  represent  the  constant  character  of  nature. 


THE   DESCRIPTION    OF   EXPERIEXCE  61 

We  find  an  analogue  of  such  a  brain-condition  in  the  accom- 
plished man  of  the  world.^  He  is  adjusted  to  all  the  situations  he 
is  liable  to  meet.  Nothing  surprises  him  or  throws  him  out  of  com- 
posure. So  long  as  the  world  remains  the  sort  of  place  he  has  found 
it  to  be,  he  knows  how  to  live  in  it,  and  how  to  adjust  himself  to  its 
demands.  And  this  attitude  of  adjustment  is  not  a  theoretical 
attitude ;  he  does  not  have  a  theory  about  the  world  he  knows;  he  has 
the  certainty  of  reiiie  Erfahrung.  He  has  'sized  up'  the  world  and 
knows  what  it  is,  and  the  world,  as  he  understands  it,  is  the  world  of 
his  experience  with  nothing  problematic  about  it.  Such  a  final  and 
definite  comprehension  of  the  world  is,  in  the  above  case,  evidently 
arrived  at  by  a  process  of  growth  from  something  less  mature,  less 
aufgekldrt,  and  accordingly  not  well  fitted  to  maintain  itself  in  the 
face  of  a  large  and  varied  experience. 

We  have  here  an  evolution  of  experience,  and  at  the  beginning 
we  have  a  certain  fund  of  convictions  and  experience  and  'knowl- 
edge,' and  at  the  end  we  have  another  fund  of  experience.  Such 
a  fund  of  experience  Avenarius  calls  an  * Erkenntnissmenge.'  Evi- 
dently the  second  Erkenninissmenge  is  obtained  by  a  gradual  modi- 
fication of  the  first.  In  actual  experience,  we  know  well  enough  how 
this  happens.  The  world  does  not  correspond  to  our  expectations 
and  we  have  to  make  our  expectations  correspond  to  the  world. 

But  what  Avenarius  wants  is  a  comprehension  of  just  this  process 
in  psychophysical  terms.  And  the  process  to  be  comprehended  is 
not  the  history  of  an  individual  system  C. 

Whatever  Weltbcgriff'  our  remote  ancestors  may  have  had,  it  no 
doubt  expressed  their  assurance  about  the  world  and  not  their  doubts 
and  problems  concerning  it.  But,  as  we  can  observe,  doubts  and 
problems  arose;  the  iP-values  of  the  Welthegriff  lost  their  qualities 
of  existence,  acquaintance  and  security,  and  became  problematized. 
Or  as  Avenarius  puts  it,  the  'world  concept'  turned  into  the  'world 
problem.'  It  was  bound  to  do  this,  because  the  world  had  been 
conceived  animistically  by  the  imaginative  projection  into  it  of  char- 
acters which  it  did  not  possess,  while  the  system  C  has  got  to  be 
formed  by  the  real  ij'-values  and  not  by  mj-thical  ones. 

But,  as  in  the  case  of  the  man  of  the  world,  so  here  the  goal  of 
the  process  is  the  deliverance  from  illusion,  the  winning  of  a  clarified 
idea  of  the  world  which  is  in  accord  with  the  facts. 

But,  some  will  exclaim,  what  kind  of  a  system  C  will  that  be 
which  can  have  a  history  like  this,  beginning  in  the  dim  past  and 
reaching  into  the  future  ? 

At  this  point  I  take  leave  to  recall  the  social  basis  of  the  concept 
of  validity.     Validity  as  a  fact  in  actual  experience,  as  a  character 

*  I  owe  this  illustration  to  Professor  Royoe. 


52  AVENARIV8   AND   PURE   EXPERIENCE 

of  actual  judgments,  depends  upon  social  agreement.  If  only  one, 
or  only  a  very  few  astronomers  had  been  able  to  Htie  spots  on  the  sun, 
the  judgment  'there  are  sun-spots'  would  have  had  no  validity  in 
science.  The  crank  with  his  hobby  may  conceivably  be  right  all  the 
time,  but  such  validity  as  his  judgments  might  possess  is  something 
different  from  the  validity  which  characterizes  accepted  judgments. 

Just  as  science  is  not  the  private  possession  of  any  one  individual, 
so  a  primitive  view  of  the  world  is  share<l  in  common.  But  philo- 
sophical views  of  the  world  to-day  can  not  be  said  to  be  held  in 
common  to  any  great  extent.  In  so  far  philosophy  is  at  a  dis- 
advantage as  compared  with  science,  for  there  is  not  enough  agree- 
ment in  philosophical  judgments  to  give  them  the  character  validity. 

We  have  thus  a  cooperation  of  different  minds  as  the  basis  of 
validity.  But  from  a  psychophysical  point  of  view  this  means  the 
cooperation  of  different  nervous  systems,  or  a  social  system  C.  Such 
a  system  C  as  this  can  have  a  history  which  no  individual  could  have. 
Avenarius  calls  such  a  system  a  'Congregal  System,'  and  represents 
it  by  the  symbol  26'. 

Now  it  is  easy  to  ridicule  this  concept,  but  it  is  unquestionably 
a  perfectly  legitimate  one.  It  does  describe  the  situation.  The 
situation  involves  the  psychophysical  aspect  of  experience,  the  his- 
tory and  evolution  of  experience,  and  the  fact  that  the  education  of 
an  individual  depends  in  the  very  highest  degree  upon  his  relations 
with  other  individuals,  and  that  judgments  about  objective  things 
derive  their  validity  from  social  cooperation  in  these  judgments. 

It  seems  to  me  rather  a  proof  of  the  value  of  the  concept  of  the 
individual  system  C  that  it  can  be  so  readily  extended  to  include  all 
those  individual  systems  which  do  determine  one  another  in  their 
judgments,  and  thus  do  really  constitute  a  system. 

By  virtue  of  such  a  system  as  2C,  the  experience  of  one  genera- 
tion depends  upon  the  experience  of  previous  ones,  and  the  process 
of  eliminating  the  fc'-values  which  are  not  determined  by  ^-values 
is  made  possible.  These  i^-values  which  are  to  be  got  rid  of  repre- 
sent the  remnants  of  primitive  animism,  which  was,  of  course,  a 
falsification  of  nature  by  an  imaginative  introjective  process.  The 
heritage  of  animism  which  we  have  on  our  hands  is,  Avenarius 
thinks,  the  soul-concept  and  its  consequences  in  philosophy. 

The  soul  is  conceived  to  be  something  within  the  body,— it  is  the 
basis  of  a  literal  distinction  between  inner  and  outer.  The  concept 
of  the  soul  is,  indeed,  not  prominent  to-day,  but  the  distinction  be- 
tween inner  experience  and  outer  experience,  internal  sense  and 
external  sense,  is  common  enough.  If  there  had  been  no  soul-con- 
cept, the  course  of  philosophy  would  no  doubt  have  been  very  dif- 
ferent from  what  it  actually  has  been;  it  seems  very  probable  that 


THE    DESCRIPTION    OF   EXPERIENCE  53 

there  would  have  been  no  Kantian  theory  of  the  categories,  and  that 
we  should  not  have  seen  Schopenhauer  announcing  as  the  most  ob- 
vious of  truisms  that  the  world  is  my  representation.  By  thus 
explaining  idealism  as  the  final  result  of  the  soul-concept  which  was 
itself  a  bit  of  introjection  left  over  from  the  original  animistic  reine 
Erfahrung,  Avenarius  includes  it  among  the  i^-values  which  will 
be  eliminated  in  the  course  of  the  history  of  2C,  if  that  history  is 
not  interrupted. 

As  the  subjective  additions  to  nature  are  eliminated  from  our 
view  of  the  world,  we  approach  a  purely  descriptive  concept.  We 
no  longer  speak  of  the  world  of  our  experience  as  the  phenomenal 
world,  while  the  real  world  is  something  else,  we  know  not  quite 
what.  The  world  we  observe  is  accepted  as  the  real  world,  precisely 
as  the  plain  man  accepts  it.  And  if  we  ask  what  the  whole  world 
is,  our  answer  to  this  question  will  seek  to  state  what  the  whole 
world  has  in  common  as  the  object  of  our  clarified  experience  which 
has  at  last  got  the  world  pure.  The  judgment  about  the  whole 
world  will  then  state  merely  what  can  be  observed  by  any  one,  and 
not  what  is  the  product  of  the  poetic  imagination  of  a  few,— as  when 
one  says,  everything  is  a  bit  of  one  absolute  experience.  The  final 
Weltbegriff  will  express  a  knowledge  of  genuine  i^-values  only, 
which  affect  the  peripheral  nerves.  This  concept  of  nature  being 
the  product  of  maximum  experience  will  not  be  liable  to  variation. 

I  think  it  is  clear  enough  in  a  general  way  what  Avenarius  is 
trying  to  state,  although  it  is  not  always  clear  in  detail.  We  have 
a  historical  process,  the  evolution  of  experience.  This  historical 
process  has,  as  its  first  stage,  a  view  of  the  world,  which  if  put  into 
words  would  tell  simply  how  nature  is  experienced.  This  Welthegriff 
describes  what  is  I'cine  Erfahrung.  By  constant  variation  the  Welt- 
hegriff comes  to  describe  the  world  as  it  is  not  experienced.  The 
actual  experience  of  the  world  gives  the  lie  to  the  'critical*  theory 
of  it.  The  process  approaches  a  ^Yelthegriff  which  describes  the 
world  as  it  is  experienced.  The  experience  which  this  view  of  the 
world  asserts  is  an  £'-value  and  expresses  such  a  'final'  state  of  the 
system  C  as  can  follow  upon  the  presentation  of  any  i?- value. 

As  to  the  content  of  this  ^-value  Avenarius  can  say  only  that  it 
will  be  *Vorgefundenes.'^  This  may  seem  a  poor  outcome,  but  it 
means  that  the  world  is  whatever  it  is  observed  to  consist  of.  Trees 
are  trees  and  houses  are  houses  and  clouds  are  clouds.  They  are 
not  thoughts  of  God  nor  experience  of  the  absolute  nor  phantasms 
of  our  own.  There  will  be  no  effort  to  go  behind  what  experience 
offers.  Every  single  fact  will  be  just  this  that  we  observe,  the 
empirical  fact  before  us.     This  is  what  Avenarius  means  by  saying 

*'Der  Menschliche  Weltbegriff,'  p.  114. 


64  AVENARIUB   AND    PURE    EXPERIENCE 

that  the  clarified  and  pennanent  Welthegri/f  will  declare,  'Every- 
thing is  this.'*  And  is  not  this  precisely  the  philosophy,  or,  if  you 
prefer,  the  lack  of  it,  of  the  'plain  man'?  He  it  is  that  does  full 
justice  to  the  empirical  diversity  of  the  world.  Science  seeks  to  re- 
move diversity  by  reducing  things  to  common  denominators.  Meta- 
physics has  not,  since  Aristotle  at  least,  shown  and  disposition  to 
recognize  diversity.  Possibly  one  should  make  an  exception  of 
Leibniz,  but  speaking  generally,  metaphysics  has  usually  sought  to 
absorb  the  empirical  world  with  all  its  diversity  and  uniqueness  into 
some  form  of  an  existent  One,  and  there  is  much  to  suggest  that  thi« 
One  is  the  mystic  ONE  of  Neo-Platonism. 

But  the  'plain  man'  never  pretends  that  one  thing  is  like  an- 
other except  for  practical  purposes.  For  him  the  common  feature 
throughout  the  world  is  the  fact  that  everything  in  it  is  a  'this.'  And 
if  one  must  ask  the  question  'Was  ist  alles?'  one  can  answer  from 
the  point  of  view  of  pure  experience  only  *  Alles  ist  dies.  '* 

The  'Kritik  der  Reinen  Erfahrung'  really  undertakes  to  describe 
the  form  of  the  evolution  which  our  experience  of  the  world  has 
undergone  and  is  still  undergoing,— a  form  which  might  go  along 
with  one  content  or  another.  We  should  keep  in  mind  that  Aven- 
arius  is  dealing  with  fact  or  with  what  we  accept  as  equivalent  to 
fact.  We  have  the  kind  of  experience  that  is  expressed  in  what, 
following  Avenarius,  I  have  called  'the  natural  view  of  the  world.' 
We  have  also  the  idealistic  theory  of  reality,  and  this  claims  to  be 
a  scientific  theory,  and  one  which  is  more  scientifically  complete 
than  any  other  metaphysic.  But  it  describes  reality  in  a  way  that 
obliges  the  man  who  does  the  actual  work  of  making  us  acquainted 
with  the  world  to  assume  a  somewhat  apologetic  attitude. 

We  have  also  the  fact  that  the  actual  idealism  of  history  is  a  result 
of  the  fortunes  of  the  idea  of  the  soul  and  the  idea  of  God,  both  of 
which  must  be  assumed  to  have  had  entirely  natural  origins.  This 
is,  of  course,  no  refutation  of  idealism,  but  it  strengthens  the  pre- 
sumption that  something  is  wrong  somewhere  about  the  premises  of 
idealism.  The  difficulty  of  making  out  just  where  the  error  lies  may 
well  be  due  to  the  fact  that  we  are  all  bred  up  in  the  point  of  view 
which  leads  so  logically  into  idealism.  Avenarius  saw  on  all  hands 
a  discontent  with  idealism,  and  I  'think  it  is  fairly  evident  that  this 
discontent  has  increased  since  Avenarius  wrote,  and  is  increasing. 

>  '  Kr.  der  R.  Erf.,'  II.,  p.  376. 

^  L.  c.  Compare  Professor  Dewey  in  the  Journal  of  Philosophy.  Psychology 
and  Scientific  Methods,  Vol.  II.,  No.  15.  "  Experience  is  always  of  thats;  and 
the  most  comprehensive  and  inclusive  experience  of  the  universe  which  the 
philosopher  himself  can  obtain  is  the  experience  of  a  characteristic  that." 


THE    DESCRIPTION    OF   EXPERIENCE  OO 

The  key  to  the  logic  of  the  situation  has  not  yet  been  found,  although 
I  think  the  first  step  toward  finding  it  has  been  taken.^ 

'The  dualistic  discontent,'  as  Avenarius  calls  it,  expresses  a  de- 
sire to  conceive  the  world  in  a  way  corresponding  to  our  natural 
experience  of  it.  In  view  of  the  continuity  of  experience,  such  an 
evolution  as  that  described  by  Avenarius  seems,  then,  extremely 
plausible,  when  once  attention  is  called  to  it. 

We  can  not  cast  off  all  at  once  habits  of  mind  cultivated  by  cen- 
turies of  faith ;  they  bind  us  in  ways  we  can  not  name.  But  the  theo- 
logical tradition  is  giving  way,  and  in  proportion  as  it  does,  we  come 
more  and  more  to  feel  that  the  truth  about  the  world  is  to  be  found  in 
a  complete  description  of  its  empirical  content.  It  seems  not  at  all 
unlikely  that  the  theological  tradition  will  in  time  cease  to  affect 
metaphysics,  and  that  in  consequence  metaphysics  will  no  longer 
give  the  lie  to  common  sense.  Of  the  metaphysics  of  this  third 
stage  Avenarius  says  only  that  it  will  be  'biologisch  haltbar.'  He 
does  not  say  it  will  be  true. 

If  we  are  to  understand  by  metaphysics  the  speculation  which  puts 
such  stress  on  distinguishing  'appearance'  from  'reality,'  which  de- 
fines reality  as  the  source  of  appearance,  a  reality  to  some  extent 
knowable  but  mostly  unknowable,  if  metaphysics  means  this,  Aven- 
arius does  seem  to  cast  it  ruthlessly  overboard.  As  the  task  of 
philosophy  he  predicts  that  of  stating  the  character  common  to  all 
objects  of  experience.  And  for  one  who  really  occupies  the  pure 
experience  position,  and  is  not  concerned  with  polemical  attitudes 
toward  any  other,  the  common  character  of  all  objects  of  experience 
must  be  the  most  abstract,  the  most  unimportant  and  the  most 
uninteresting  of  predicates.  Far  more  important  and  interesting 
will  be  what  is  concrete  and  actual. 

To  come  back  into  the  terminology  of  the  'Kritik  der  Reinen 
Erfahrung,'  the  final  view  of  the  world  will  express  a  knowledge 
of  genuine  /?-values  only  such  as  affect  the  system  C.  This  concept 
of  nature  being  the  result  of  complete  determination  by  habit,  will 
not  be  liable  to  change. 

Of  course  it  is  not  meant  that  this  final  Welthegri/f  is  necessarily 
going  to  be  attained,  but  only  that  the  process  is  of  such  a  kind  as 
to  have  this  for  its  limit.  The  process  may  be  interrupted  by  a 
catastrophe  at  any  moment. 

I  beg  the  reader  not  to  accept  this  account  of  the  views  of  Aven- 
arius as  anything  more  than  a  fragmentary  one.  I  have  cared  very 
much  more  for  the  general  purpose  and  outcome  than  for  details  of 
method  and  the  system  of  terminology  that  is  so  characteristic. 

*  William  James  in  the  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology  and  Scientifio 
Methods,  Vol.  I.,  No.  18,  *  Does  Consciousness  Exist.' 


66  AVKSAItlLH    A.\U    I'URE    KXl'ERIENCE 

IV 

In  the  introduction  to  the  'Principles  of  Mechanics,'  of  Jlerz/ 
we  find  the  following  statement:  "In  endeavoring  thus  to  draw  in- 
ferences as  to  the  future  from  the  pant,  we  always  adopt  the  fol- 
lowing process.  We  form  for  ourselves  images  or  symbols  of  ex- 
ternal objects,  and  the  form  which  we  give  them  is  such  that  the 
necessary  consequents  of  the  images  in  thought  are  always  the 
images  of  the  necessary  consequents  in  nature  of  the  things  pictured. 
.  .  .  The  images  of  which  we  here  speak  are  our  conceptions  of 
things.  With  the  things  themselves  they  are  in  conformity  in  one 
important  respect,  viz.,  in  satisfying  the  above-mentioned  require- 
ment. For  our  purpose  it  is  not  necessary  that  they  should  be  in 
conformity  with  the  things  in  any  other  respect  whatever."  The 
concepts  must  be  'permissible,'  that  is,  logically  self -consistent;  they 
must  be  correct,  or  not  contradicted  by  experience ;  and  they  must  be 
appropriate,  that  is,  embody  the  'principle  of  economy.'* 

Herz,  thus,  in  agreement  with  Mach  and  Carl  Pearson,  describes 
the  scientific  concept  as  a  construction  of  the  investigator.  It  is  an 
instrument  with  a  function,  that  of  leading  to  new  observations  and 
predicting  sequences  of  phenomena. 

This  point  of  view  is,  however,  radically  opposed  to  the  older 
view  which  defined  its  aim  as  the  discovery  of  the  real  causes  of 
observable  phenomena.  It  was  taken  for  granted  that  the  phe- 
nomena of  nature  depended  upon  movements  of  matter,— and  that 
matter  in  motion  was  a  definite  transcendent  object  of  knowledge. 
The  following  from  Helmholtz  expresses  this  point  of  view.  "The 
theoretical  portion  of  physical  science  seeks  to  discover  the  unknown 
causes  of  events  from  their  observable  effects;  it  seeks  to  under- 
stand them  according  to  the  law  of  causality.  We  are  forced  to 
this  task  by  the  principle  that  every  change  in  nature  must  have  an 
adequate  cause.  .  .  .  The  final  goal  of  the  theoretical  sciences  is 
thus  to  discover  the  ultimate  unchanging  causes  of  changes  in 
nature. '  '^ 

Herz  himself  at  one  time  predicted  that  the  great  problem  of 
physical  science  would  be  the  nature  and  the  laws  of  the  space-filling 
ether.  "It  seems  more  and  more  probable  that  this  question  will 
take  precedence  of  all  others."*  'Herz  spoke  then  wholly  com- 
mitted to  old  preconceptions,'  says  Kleinpeter  in  the  article  from 
which  I  take  the  quotation;  and  it  goes  without  saying  that  Herz 

*  Translation  by  Jones  and  Walley,  p.  1. 

«  L.  c,  p.  2. 

»  Helmholtz,  'Ueber  die  Erhaltung  der  Kraft,'  p.  2,  Berlin,  1847. 

* '  Ueber  E.  Mach's  und  H.  Herz's  Principielle  AuflFassung  der  Physik,'  by 
Kleinpeter  in  Archiv  fur  Phil.,  II.  Abtheilung,  Bd.  V.,  Heft.  2,  p.  176. 


TEE    DESCRIP'1J<J.\     ut    EXPERIEyCE  ,  57 

had  assumed  a  fundamentally  different  point  of  view  when  he  wrote 
the  'Mechanics.' 

Kirehhoff  in  the  introduction  to  his  'Vorlesungen  iiber  Mathe- 
matische  Physik'  gives  expression  to  the  new  point  of  view.  He 
says:  "The  point  of  departure  which  I  have  chosen  is  not  the  ordi- 
nary one.  It  is  customary  to  define  mechanics  as  the  science  of 
forces,  and  forces  as  the  causes  which  produce  motion  or  strive  to 
produce  motion,  ...  In  the  cause  of  the  precision,  which  is,  in 
other  respects,  characteristic  of  conclusions  in  mechanics,  it  seems 
desirable  to  get  rid  of  ambiguous  terms  (Dunkelheiten)  even  if  we 
are  obliged  to  narrow  the  task  of  mechanics.  I,  therefore,  propose, 
as  this  task,  the  description  of  the  movements  which  occur  in  nature, 
a  description  as  complete  and  as  simple  as  possible."^ 

One  of  the  frankest  statements  that  the  scientific  concept  is  a 
construction  of  the  mind  and  not  necessarily  an  image  of  transub- 
jective  things,  is  the  prefatory  note  of  Herz  to  book  I.  of  his  'Me- 
chanics.' It  is  as  follows:  "The  subject-matter  of  the  fii*st  book  is 
completely  independent  of  experience.  All  the  assertions  made  are 
a  priori  in  Kant's  sense.  They  are  based  upon  the  laws  of  the  in- 
ternal intuition  of,  and  upon  the  logical  forms  followed  by,  the 
person  who  makes  the  assertion;  with  his  external  experience  they 
have  no  other  connection  than  these  intuitions  and  forms  may 
have.  "2 

The  second  book  contains  the  application  of  the  system  of  con- 
cepts to  the  phenomena  of  experience.  The  contrast  and  relation- 
ship between  volume  I.  and  volume  II.  of  the  'Kritik  der  Reinen 
Erfahrung'  are  almost  identical  with  that  between  books  I.  and  II. 
of  the  'Mechanics'  of  Herz.  Avenarius  would  not  and  could  not 
claim  that  the  concepts  and  definitions  which  fill  volume  I.  are  en- 
tirely a  priori  constructions.  But  they  are  psychological  inventions 
for  the  purposes  of  scientific  apperception,  inventions,  however, 
which  are  adapted  to  the  phenomena.  But  the  lines  of  procedure 
of  Herz  and  Avenarius  seem  very  similar.  Herz  described  scientific 
method  as  the  formation  and  use  of  images  or  sjinbols  of  external 
objects  such  that  'the  necessary  consequents  of  the  images  in  thought 
are  always  the  images  of  the  necessary  consequents  in  nature  of  the 
things  pictured.'  Now  critics  of  Avenarius  have  complained  of  the 
dialectical  way  in  which  his  'Kritik'  develops;  but  such  a  char- 
acter is  inevitable  if  there  are  to  be  any  consequences  of  the  sjimbol 
which  shall  be  symbols  of  facts.  Whether  Avenarius  has  met  with 
any  success  in  this  effort,  whether  his  outcome  is  really  a  logical 
consequence  of  his  symbol,  or  whether  it  could  have  been  stated  with- 

» Vol.  I.,  p.  iii. 
*P.  45. 


58  ^  AVEyARIUS    AND    PURE    EXPlJJaK.WB 

out  any  reference  to  a  system  C  and  its  determination  by  recurrent 
vital  series,  is  a  decision  which  lies  outside  the  present  undertakinjj. 
I  am  disposed  to  believe  that  the  results  which  Avenarius  finally 
reached  were  won  partly  by  means  of  his  symbol.  When  we  have 
all  three  groups,  the  concepts,  the  phenomena  of  experience  and 
the  final  conclusions  and  statements,  we  can,  perhaps,  say  that  the 
latter  group  needed  only  the  group  of  experience-facta  to  produce  it. 
But  if  a  group  of  concepts  are  of  assistance  of  any  sort  in  n-aching 
conclusions,  the  concepts  have  served  their  pui'j)<)Sf,  whatever  oritics 
may  think  of  them. 

The  efforts  of  KirchhofT,  of  Ilerz,  and  I  may  say  of  Avenarius, 
show  the  effort  to  eliminate  explanation  from  science  as  an  ultimate 
goal,  and  to  limit  its  task  to  description  which  shall  be  as  simple 
and  as  complete  as  possible.  But  from  this  point  of  view  it  is  not 
pretended  that  science  is  a  statement  of  nature's  eternal  truths,  and, 
as  Kleinpeter  observes,  it  follows  that  there  is  for  humanity  *no 
objective  truth  enthroned  above  gods  and  men,  as  the  ancient  Greeks 
imagined. ' 

We  admit  readily  the  wisdom  of  this  point  of  view,  and  yet  some 
of  us  are  sure  to  feel  not  quite  satisfied.  Science  does  well  indeed 
to  get  rid  of  metaphysics,  to  accept  its  method  as  method  and  not 
as  revelation.  Yet  a  Veritas  there  must  be,  we  say,  and  by  what 
right  does  science  forbid  us  to  seek  it  because  she  seeks  something 
else? 

If  we  look  for  the  essentially  logical  distinction  between  the  two 
points  of  view  above  indicated,  between  that  which  seeks  a  knowl- 
edge of  ultimate  causes,  and  that  which  seelcs  complete  and  econom- 
ical descriptions,  we  observe  that  it  is  in  the  existential  judgment, 
which  is  present  in  the  older  point  of  view,  while  absent  in  the  later 
one.  It  is  evident,  also,  that  the  older  point  of  view,  therefore,  is  a 
metaphysical  point  of  view.  The  great  role  which  materialism 
played  thirty  and  forty  years  ago  was  an  inevitable  result  of  the 
great  triumphs  of  physical  science,  when  physicists  defined  the  goal 
of  their  science  as  metaphysical  insight,  insight  into  the  eternal  laws 
of  the  movements  of  matter  of  which  all  change  in  the  world  is  the 
resulting  effect. 

It  is  no  doubt  more  intelligent  to  recognize  science  as  the  effort 
to  describe  experience  rather  than  to  try  to  regard  it  as  explaining 
experience  in  any  ultimate  sense.  Yet  many  will  feel  that  the  older 
point  of  view  had  a  more  substantial  purpose  than  the  new  one. 
It  at  least  was  seeking  the  Veritas  which  must  exist.  We  might  not 
like  materialism,  but  the  science  of  that  faith  was  a  courageous  sci- 
ence not  afraid  of  the  truth  wherever  it  might  be  found. 


THE   DESCRIPTION    OF   EJPERIEXCE  59 

He  who  feels  this  attitude  longs  for  the  existential  judgment. 
His  mood  is  not  satisfied  with  science  as  now  defined ;  description  is 
not  enough,  and  he  demands  the  explanation  of  experience.  The 
experience  which  is  to  be  explained  is  the  experience  with  some  of 
whose  aspects  we  became  acquainted  in  the  first  section  of  this  paper. 
It  is  experience  characterized  by  the  outer  world  and  the  fellow 
man  as  transcendent  objects,— in  a  word,  by  the  natural  view  of  the 
world. 


THE  EXPLANATION  OF  EXPERIENCE 


In  the  work  of  describing  experience,  by  far  the  greater  part  of 
the  subject-matter  belongs  to  the  outer  world.  The  complete  pro- 
gram of  the  undertaking  to  describe  all  experience  would  be  the 
classification  of  the  sciences,  which  provide  the  tasks  for  many  minds 
working  together. 

But  the  fellow  man  is  more  than  a  cooperator  in  description.  He 
has  the  peculiar  function  of  providing  the  basis  for  validity.  We 
are  accustomed  to  say  that  scientific  conclusions  must  have  universal 
validity,  by  which  we  mean  acceptability  to  all  observers  who  care 
to  verify  the  conclusions,  or  to  such  a  majority  of  them  that  the  dis- 
senters can  be  ignored. 

But  in  explanations  of  experience,  which  are  of  an  ultimate  type, 
the  fellow  being  appears  to  occupy  a  somewhat  different  position. 
In  philosophy,  the  postulate  is  still  made,  no  doubt,  that  agreement 
between  different  observers  of  the  given  situation  is  possible,  philo- 
sophical discussion  would  have  no  meaning  without  it;  but  prac- 
tically such  agreement  is  not  expected,  certainly  not  from  all  ob- 
servers of  the  situation,  even  though  they  be  all  pronounced  en- 
tirely competent.  Yet  every  philosophy  undertakes  to  be  valid,  and 
expects  to  secure  some  measure  of  validity  whether  it  meet  with 
approval  or  not. 

Science  aims  at  universally  verifiable  descriptions  of  phenomena. 
The  question  whether  the  description  is  a  valid  one  is  equivalent  to 
the  question  whether  the  description  fulfills  the  scientific  purpose, 
whether  it  is  universally  verifiable.  Metaphysics,  on  the  other  hand, 
asks  the  question,  What  is  reality?  What  is  the  ultimate  ground  of 
phenomena?  What  is  the  ultimate  cause  of  experience?  The  ques- 
tion. Does  reality  consist  of  matter  with  a  molecular  structure?  does 
not  mean,  Is  the  concept  of  the  molecule  so  useful  as  to  lead  to  uni- 
versally verifiable  descriptions  of  phenomena?  The  question  as  to 
the  molecular  constitution  of  reality  is  a  question  which  seeks  not 
acquaintance  with  phenomena,  but  a  knowledge  of  something  under- 
lying phenomena,  and  expressing  itself  through  phenomena.  The 
question  as  to  the  validity  of  a  metaphysical  judgment  is  a  question 
whether  the  judgment  fulfills  the  metaphysical  purpose  or  not,  and 
this  purpose  is  not  universal  verifiability,  but  a  true  report  about 
the  ultimate  ground  and  cause  of  experience. 

60 


THE   EXPLA^ATlOy    OF   EXPERIENCE  61 

Of  course  the  actual  fate  of  philosophical  systems  depends  upon 
the  degree  to  which  they  can  win  the  other  tj-pe  of  validity,  by  com- 
mending themselves  to  students  of  philosophical  problems.  Every 
philosophy  seeks  this  type  of  validity  and  is  fortunate  to  the  degree 
that  it  secures  it,  but  the  validity  it  aims  at  is  of  another  type,  al- 
though practically  this  validity  may  have  to  submit  to  the  same  test 
as  the  other  one. 

Philosophical  explanations  are  sure  to  be  determined  by  the 
aspect  of  experience  that  seems  most  significant,  most  interesting. 
Those  who  are  chiefly  interested  in  the  natural  and  exact  sciences, 
and  charmed  with  the  conceptual  regularity  and  order  which  is  char- 
acteristic of  large  i-egions  in  those  sciences,  have  usually  defined 
reality  from  the  point  of  view  of  this  prevailing  interest.  The  goal 
of  natural  science  as  described  by  Helmholtz  is  an  expression  of  this 
point  of  view. 

But  explanation  from  the  side  of  the  interest  in  natural  science 
is  giving  way  to  description,^  Statements  like  that  of  Helmholtz, 
quoted  above,  sound  already  a  little  antiquated.  Explanations  of 
experience  are,  therefore,  coming  more  to  be  determined  by  the  other 
chief  factor  in  the  natural  view  of  the  world,  namely,  the  fellow 
being.  Reality  must  be  so  understood  as  to  be  an  adequate  ground 
for  the  social  aspect  of  experience.  From  the  side  of  this  interest, 
the  dramatic  aspects  of  human  experience  and  human  history  are 
cared  for.  Moral  and  esthetic  experience,  the  problem  of  evil,  per- 
sonality, are  important  headings.  But  the  explanation  which  takes 
special  account  of  these  interests  must  not  do  too  great  violence  to 
the  other  feature  of  the  natural  Weltbegriff,  the  outer  world.  The 
significance  of  my  fellow  depends  largely  upon  the  fact  that  we  are 
supposed  to  have  common  interests  and  common  objects,  and  the 
sphere  for  these  must  be  preserved. 

II 

We  can  approach  the  explanation  of  experience  by  an  indefinite 
number  of  ways.  Every  metaphysic  is  an  attempt  to  explain  ex- 
perience. It  seeks  not  to  describe  phenomena,  but  to  get  behind 
phenomena  to  some  ultimate  ground,  and  the  experience  to  be  ex- 
plained presents  as  its  most  characteristic  feature  the  cognition  of 
apparently  transcendent  objects.  This  character,  which  comes  out 
most  frankly  in  the  naive  realism  which  I  have  called  the  natural 
view  of  the  world,  appears  to  determine  metaphysics  more  than  any 
other  character  of  experience.  Sir  W.  Hamilton  testifies  to  this 
character  in  the  following  vigorous  statement.    "We  are  immediately 

'  See  preface  to  second  edition  of  Carl  Pearson's  '  Grammar  of  Science.' 


62  AVENARIUS   AND   PURE   EXPERIENCE 

conscious  in  perception  of  an  ego  and  a  non-ego,  known  together  and 
known  in  contrast  to  each  other.  This  is  the  fact  of  the  duality  of 
consciousness.  It  is  clear  and  manifest.  When  I  concentrate  my 
attention  in  the  simplest  act  of  perception,  I  return  from  my  ob- 
servation with  the  most  irresistible  conviction  of  two  facts,  or  rather 
two  branches  of  the  same  fact;  that  I  am  and  that  something  dif- 
ferent from  me  exists."^  "The  ego  and  non-ego,  mind  and  matter, 
are  given  together."     This  fact  is  'clear  and  manifest.' 

I  am  not  now  asking  whether  there  is  any  truth  in  these  state- 
ments. I  simply  call  attention  to  the  fact  that  when  a  philosopher 
harks  back  to  the  plain  testimony  of  consciousness,  this  is  what  he 
harks  back  to.  I  think  Hamilton  was  prevented  by  a  philosophical 
theory  from  going  quite  far  enough.  Certainly  the  ego  which 
normal  consciousness  testifies  to  in  'the  simplest  act  of  perception* 
is  usually  just  the  body,  and  if  one  is  very  much  interested  in  some- 
thing objective,  the  perception  of  the  ego  will  not  form  part  of 
the  experience  at  all. 

Mill,  although  unable  to  be  quite  so  frank  as  Hamilton,  still 
retains  the  transcendent  object  as  something  whose  existence  is  too 
evident  to  be  questioned.  "I  believe  that  Calcutta  exists,"  he 
says,  "though  I  do  not  perceive  it,  and  that  it  would  still  exist  if 
every  percipient  inhabitant  were  suddenly  to  leave  the  place  or 
be  struck  dead."^  Calcutta  would  still  be  real  under  these  circum- 
stances, for  it  would  remain  'a  permanent  possibility  of  sensation.' 
If  the  inhabitants  return  or  come  to  life  again,  they  will  perceive 
Calcutta,  and  Calcutta  was  there  all  the  time  waiting  to  be  per- 
ceived.     So  Mill  reflects. 

This  'possibility  of  sensation'  is  the  classic  entrance  to  the 
idealism  which  claims  to  explain  experience  in  a  really  profound 
and  consistent  way.  What,  it  is  asked,  is  an  object  of  experience 
while  it  is  mere  possibility  of  sensation?  What  kind  of  a  positive 
fact  is  Calcutta  while  it  is  waiting  to  be  perceived?  It  appears  to 
be  taken  for  granted  that  it  is  all  the  time  a  'possibility'  of  experi- 
ence, but  that  if  it  is  really  anything  at  all,  it  must  be  something 
more.  The  same  sturdy  instinctive  realism  which  both  Hamilton 
and  Mill  represent,  appears  in  this  request  for  a  further  account  of 
the  possibility  of  sensation. 

Suppose  one  were  to  reply  that  not  even  the  possibility  of  sensa- 
tion exists  in  the  sense  in  which  Mill  spoke  of  it.  One  could 
answer,  experimentally  at  least,  that  so  long  as  Calcutta  is  not  per- 
ceived or  thought  about  by  human  minds,  Calcutta  simply  does  not 
exist.     One  who  made  this  answer  would,  no  doubt,  hasten  to  add 

*  *  Lectures  on  Metaphysics,'  Boston,  1859,  p.  200. 

* '  Examination  of  Hamilton,'  p.  246,  New  York,  1884. 


THE   EXPLAyATION    OF   EXPERIEyCE  63 

that  of  course  he  did  not  really  believe  it,  that  he  suggested  this 
reply  in  order  to  observe  what  the  logical  results  might  be.  And 
as  for  the  few  who  might  make  this  reply  in  all  sincerity,  some  of 
these  would  save  the  transcendent  character  of  Calcutta  by  declar- 
ing it  to  be  an  object  in  an  eternal  experience,  and  the  others  would, 
I  am  sure,  feel  that  something  was  wrong,  and  that  the  transcendent 
character  should  be  gotten  back  somehow.  The  'dualistic  discon- 
tent' makes  itself  felt  when  we  undertake  to  define  the  world  as  a 
series  of  dissolving  views.  And  yet  why  not?  That  is  the  way 
the  world  flows  by  before  us.  One  view  melts  into  another  with 
enough  consistency  and  a  good  deal  of  predictability. 

But  we  will  none  of  such  sophistry.  The  changing  view  is  all 
characterized  as  more  than  view.  The  realistic  bias  so  character- 
istic of  our  human  nature  demands  permanence  and  stability. 
Moreover,  one  might  feel  obliged  to  be  consistent  and  thorough- 
going, and  then  our  fellows  would  dissolve  away  together  with  the 
views  to  which  they  belong,  and  against  this  we  set  a  subborn  face. 
But  the  material  outer  world  is  probably  able  to  take  care  of  itself 
even  without  the  help  of  the  fellow  being;  our  reality- functions 
see  to  it  that  the  world  remains,  even  in  idealism,  a  transcendent 
object,  so  far  as  any  one  finite  mind  is  concerned. 

The  transcendence-character  must  somehow  be  preserved,  for 
it  is  preserving  it  to  translate  it  into  something  p)ermanent  in  an 
experience,  which  is  outside  the  limits  of  what  I  recognize  just 
now  as  mine.  This  motive  is  contributed  by  the  outer  world  char- 
acter of  experience.  Another  important  motive  there  is  in  the 
fellow  being,  not  so  much  in  the  external  aspect  he  presents  by  ap- 
pearing in  the  outer  world,  as  by  his  being  a  fellow.  As  such, 
he  is  the  condition  of  all  our  ethical  attitudes,  and  of  everything 
that  gives  the  deeper  value  and  significance  to  life.  His  presence 
lays  a  significant  demand  upon  the  outer  world.  External  objects 
must  be  the  same  objects  for  him  and  for  me.  That  is  made  the 
test  of  their  reality  as  external  objects.  But  most  important  of  all 
is  it  that  the  fellow  being  remain  a  transcendent  object.  Yet  how, 
then,  can  there  be  one  and  the  same  outer  world  for  us  both?  It 
would  seem  as  though  his  outer  world  must  exist  in  a  different 
space  from  mine  and  in  a  different  time.  In  fact,  it  seems  as  though 
in  one  universe  there  were  room  for  only  one  self.  This  is  really, 
it  seems  to  me,  the  clinching  argument  for  idealism,  and  it  is  one 
that  the  critics  of  that  doctrine,  and  those  who  prove  to  us  the 
actual  transcendent  existence  of  the  world,  hardly  notice.  These 
philosophers  take  all  their  illustrations  from  a  one-object-one-subject 
relation,  whereas  the  case  of  realism  can  not  be  proved  without 
making  clear  the  one-object-two-subjects  relation. 


04  A  yh'.\  A  HI  UN    A  .\  I)    I'UJfl.    i:\  I'l^KI  I^S  Ct' 

The  idealist  is  prepared  to  handle  this  difficulty,  by  declaring 
that  the  relation  of  one  object  to  two  subjects  is  a  mythical  rela- 
tion. Of  course  there  is  in  one  universe  room  for  only  one  self, 
and  when  your  experience  and  mine  and  the  object  are  all  abs<jrbed 
into  this  absolute  experience,  we  get  the  one-subject-one-object 
relation  back  again.  Do  we  indeed  know  of  any  experience 
analogous  to  the  absorption  of  the  experience  of  me  and  my  fellows 
into  one,  in  such  a  way  as  to  comprehend  them  both,  yet  leave  to 
each  its  individuality?  On  a  small  and  trivial  scale,  we  do.  If 
I  seize  some  object,  a  book,  with  both  hands,  the  book  which  I  grasp 
with  my  right  hand  is  the  same  book  as  the  one  I  grasp  with  my 
left.  There  is  for  the  experience  of  grasping  simply  the  one  ex- 
perienced object,  because  the  touch-sensations  of  both  hands,  and 
the  visual  elements  in  the  total  perception  are  all  brought  together 
in  one  experience.  For  the  same  reason,  the  space  through  which 
my  right  hand  swings  is  a  part  of  the  same  space  as  that  through 
which  my  left  hand  swings.  In  cases  of  alternating  personality, 
in  what  intelligible  empirical  sense  is  the  world  of  one  of  these 
selves  the  same  world  as  that  of  the  other  selft  The  illustration 
of  grasping  the  book  shows  that  any  external  object  can  be  kept 
one  by  defining  it  as  the  object  within  one  experience.  This  logical 
necessity  contradicts,  of  course,  the  plain  testimony  of  pure  experi- 
ence, and  as  pure  experience  is  the  sole  ground  of  good  theory,  and 
as  logical  contradictions  proceed  from  definitions,  one  is  justified 
in  suspecting  that  the  idealistic  implications  are  begged  somewhere 
in  a  definition.  But  realism  can  certainly  have  no  logical  standing 
until  this  petitio  is  pointed  out. 

But  whatever  means  we  resort  to  to  explain  experience,  we 
adopt  some  concept  and  attach  to  it  the  existential  predicate  and 
seek  thus  to  deproblematize  the  situation.  We  are  seeking  an 
experience  with  the  fidential-character,  the  character  of  ^Ileim- 
haftigkeit,'  as  Avenarius  called  it,  and,  in  fact,  the  presence  of  ulti- 
mate problems  is  often  testified  to  in  language  that  breathes  an 
acute  tone  of  ' lleimweh.'  The  search  for  truth  is  indeed  the  search 
for  a  satisfied  will,  but  the  truth  which  we  find  may  remain  the 
truth  for  ten  minutes  or  for  a  lifetime. 

But  science,  too,  seeks  to  deproblematize  a  situation  by  means 
of  a  concept,  only  science  does  not  attach  the  existential  predicate. 
Just  in  this  matter  of  the  existential  judgment,  metaphysics  goes 
beyond  science.  Science  does  not  deny  that  there  is  an  ultimate 
truth,  but  she  does  not  claim  to  have  found  it.  She  is  very  likely 
to  say  that  it  can  not  be  found.  Science  has  a  system  of  concepts 
of  which  the  necessary  consequences  are  images  of  the  actual 
effects  and  expressions  of  the  ultimate  ground  of  things.      Science 


TEE    EXPLAXATIOy    OF   EXPERIENCE  65 

says  that  phenomena  are  as  if  reality  were  thus  and  so,  as  if  the 
world  of  matter  had  a  molecular  structure,  as  if  space  were  filled  with 
a  vibrating  ether,  and,  with  the  attention  directed  upon  experience  of 
another  sort,  she  might  say,  as  if  each  finite  human  life  were  a 
moment  in  an  absolute  life  which  comprised  all  of  reality. 

If  such  a  concept  as  the  Absolute  were  a  useful  concept  in  getting 
a  synthetic  sense  of  experience  of  a  certain  type,  or  in  helping  to 
describe  it,  or  in  making  one  a  more  sensitive  and  appreciative  ob- 
server of  this  experience,  then  the  concept  of  the  Absolute  would  have 
precisely  the  same  validity  as  the  concept  of  the  atom.  Both  could 
dwell  side  by  side  in  science  very  well. 

Yet  anxious  ones  cry  out,  "But  the  Veritas!  The  reality  back  of 
phenomena !  The  something  which  completes  my  fragmentary  experi- 
ence and  answers  my  questions!  No  mere  acquaintance  with  phe- 
nomena, however  wide,  can  be  to  me  a  substitute  for  this  deeper 
insight." 

What,  precisely,  are  the  motives  because  of  which  we  search  for 
something  back  of  phenomena  and  demand  a  deeper  insight?  But 
before  taking  up  this  question  let  us  recall  what  actual  truth  and 
error  appear  to  be,  that  experience,  namely,  which  is  called  the  pos- 
session of  truth,  and  that  experience  which  is  called  the  possession  of 
erjor. 

There  is  no  test  of  truth  other  than  the  removal  of  the  problematic 
character  from  the  content  about  which  a  true  judgment  is  desired, — 
and  the  possession  of  truth,  as  a  case  of  experience,  can  be  in  no  wise 
distinguished  from  the  possession  of  a  deproblematized  content. 

If  this  content  happen  to  break  out  into  a  problem  again,  then  the 
temporary  peace  and  satisfaction  of  the  will  must  be  pronounced  an 
error.  And  then  another  truth  may  be  found,  or  the  same  truth  may 
turn  out  to  be  true  after  all.  Is  a  given  conclusion  a  valid  one? 
The  question  is  an  inquiry  whether  the  conclusion  has  got  rid  of  the 
problem-character  and  continues  deproblematized.  'Yes,  the  con- 
clusion is  valid,'  means  that  the  conclusion  has  not  yet  shown  itself 
to  be  unsatisfactory.  Or,  'No,  that  conclusion  was  an  error,'  means 
that  the  conclusion  in  question  has  lost  the  character  of  sameness 
which  made  it  appear  as  a  true  account  of  certain  facts,  the  same  as 
the  facts,  in  some  respects,  and  has  taken  on  a  quality  of  otherness, 
so  that  one  now  has  to  observe,  'No,  the  facts  are  certainly  not  like 
that,  it  was  an  erroneous  account  of  them. '  The  possibility  of  error 
thus  means  the  possibility  of  experience  which  shall  include  in  it  the 
contradiction  of  a  previous  cognitive  experience.  To  say  that  error 
is  or  is  not  possible  in  any  given  case  is  to  predict  something  about 
the  future. 

If  one  simply  observes  the  situation  one  is  obliged,  I  think,  to 

5 


66  AVENARIUS   AND   PURE   EJFERIENCE 

report  it  somewhat  as  I  have  done.  Of  course  it  takes  an  eflfort  to 
mean  by  truth,  error,  and  validity  merely  these  characters  of  experi- 
ence. The  primitive  realism  which  is  such  a  sturdy  growth  within 
us  causes  us  to  try  to  mean  something  very  different  by  truth,  error 
and  validity.  But  when  we  get  these  facts  into  our  experience,  what 
we  have  is  experience,  with  the  fidential  character. 

When  we  read  the  pages  of  certain  philosophers  of  the  past  we 
can  not  doubt  that  to  thera  some  objects  were  assured  experienced 
facts,  which  to-day  have  to  be  proved  by  elaborate  dialectical 
methods.  Thus  Descartes  appeals  to  his  idea  of  God  as  to  the  idea 
of  something  that  could  not  possibly  be  doubted  in  any  moment  of 
sanity.  Spinoza  gives  the  impression  even  more  strongly  of  being  a 
man  in  whose  experience  God  is  an  established  and  simply  unquestion- 
able reality.  He  could  probably  no  more  have  doubted  the  existence 
of  God  than  the  'plain  man'  doubts  the  existence  of  the  outer  world. 

It  seems  hardly  possible  that  the  concept  of  God  should  appear  in 
modern  philosophical  literature  with  the  complete  fidential  character 
which  it  appears  to  have  had  with  Descartes  and  Spinoza.  But  that 
does  not  mean  that  we  have  learned  to  question  the  existence  of  a 
ground  of  things  back  of  phenomena.  Philosophy  still  regards  the 
visible  and  tangible  world  as  a  secondary  quality  of  endless  variety. 
We  speak  of  change  and  the  necessity  of  some  ground  of  change,  of 
fragmentary  experience  and  the  necessity  of  its  completion,  of  thought 
and  its  'Other'  which  exists  even  now  before  it  is  found  as  deproblem- 
atized  experience. 

As  a  mere  suggestion,  a  hint,  I  recall  the  way  in  which  Avenarius 
accounts  for  Idealism  as  a  prevailing  point  of  view  in  philosophy. 
The  suggestion  is  that  the  search  for  an  ultimate  ground  of  experi^ 
ence,  especially  a  spiritual  ground  with  dramatic  consequences,  is  a 
stirring  of  the  old  animistic  habit  within  us. 

But  as  to  the  motives  which  cause  metaphysics  to  pass  beyond 
science  and  attach  the  existential  predicate  to  the  useful  concept,  these 
may  be  many  and  different.  We  still  hear  now  and  then  that  the 
existence  of  God  is  assured  in  the  necessity  of  a  first  cause.  In  rep- 
utable philosophical  literature  we  do  not  now  often  meet  with  the 
concept  of  an  eificient  cause  of  the  world,  but  the  idea  of  a  final  cause 
lurks  in  all  teleological  metaphysics.  The  historical  influence  of  the 
Christian  conception  of  God  would  provide  one  motive  for  still  seek- 
ing a  ground  of  phenomena. 

The  intellectual  interest  in  the  dialectical  problems,  the  exercise 
of  thinking  and  of  imagination,  which  is  always  attractive,  and  the 
sense  of  being  engaged  in  very  important  undertakings,  is  another 
motive  or  group  of  motives. 

As  a  statement  of  a  third  motive,  I  will  quote  a  sentence  from 


THE   EXPLANATlOy    OF   EXPERIENCE  67 

Professor  Ladd's  work.^  "The  construction  of  a  tenable  and  com- 
forting philosophy  is  a  work  of  good-will;  it  is  a  beneficent  deed,  a 
gift  of  blessing  to  humanity."  And  the  dedication:  "To  those  who 
have  the  faith  of  reason  in  its  strivings  to  know  the  deeper  truth  of 
things. ' ' 

Now  I  would  not  be  understood  as  not  sharing  in  the  faith  of 
reason  or  in  the  longing  for  the  existential  judgment.  But  at  present 
it  interests  me  to  stand  aside  and  view  the  varied  spectacle  of 
philosophical  effort.  Experience  itself  in  its  diversity,  the  descrip- 
tion of  experience,  and  the  explanation  of  experience,  help  to  make  up 
that  spectacle.  Even  he  who  enters  eagerly  into  the  work  of  descrip- 
tion or  explanation  can  but  observe  the  situation  before  him  and  re- 
port what  he  can  see.  If  he  does  more,  he  mutilates  the  facts  which 
he  has  undertaken  to  describe  in  their  integrity.  And  there  is  much 
to  suggest  that  the  philosopher  is  not  the  mere  spectator  nearly  so 
often  as  he  should  be. 

It  is  sometimes  said  that  the  function  of  idealism  is  to  make  men 
feel  at  home  in  the  world.  Some  lines  of  Professor  Seth  are  such  an 
apt  testimony  on  this  point  that  I  can  not  resist  quoting  them: 
*  *  Metaphysically,  idealism  is  opposed  most  ordinarily  to  materialism ; 
in  the  widest  sense  it  is  the  opposite  of  what  may  be  called  the  me- 
chanical and  atheistic  view  of  the  universe,  whatever  special  form  that 
may  take.  Is  self-conscious  thought  with  its  ideal  ends,— the  True, 
the  Beautiful,  the  Good,— the  self-realizing  End  that  works  in  changes 
and  makes  it  evolution?  or  are  these  but  the  casual  outcome  of  a 
mechanical  system?— a  system  in  its  ultimate  essence  indifferent  to 
the  results  which  in  its  gyrations  it  has  unwittingly  created,  and  will 
as  unwittingly  destroy?  Is  thought  or  matter  the  prius?  Is  the 
ultimate  essence  and  cause  of  all  things  only  'dust  that  rises  up  and 
is  lightly  laid  again,'  or  is  it  the  Eternal  Love  of  Dante's  Vision,— 
'the  love  that  moves  the  sun  and  the  other  stars'  ?  That  is  the  funda- 
mental metaphysical  antithesis.  If  we  embrace  the  one  alternative, 
however  we  may  clothe  it  in  detail,  we  recognize  the  universe  as  our 
home,  and  we  may  have  a  religion ;  if  we  embrace  the  other,  then  the 
spirit  of  man  is  indeed  homeless  in  an  alien  world. ' '  * 

We  have  here,  I  think,  a  sufficient  explanation  of  the  longing  for  the 
existential  judgment.  The  existential  judgment  is  needed  to  deprob- 
lematize  the  situation.  Of  course  the  emotional  need  is  not  always 
stated  quite  so  frankly,  but  it  frequently  appears  in  a  philosophy  as 
its  efficient  cause.  The  philosophy  of  Spinoza  is  as  clearly  an  adjust- 
ment to  the  emotional  values  of  his  world  as  were  the  deeds  of  Saint 

^ '  A  Theory  of  Reality,'  New  York,  1899,  p.  33. 
2  Phil.  Review,  Vol.  I.,  p.  140. 


08  AVEAAlilUii    ASD    I'LUL    LU'LJULSCE 

Francis.  Even  Kant,  who  nearly  always  displays  the  ideal  phil- 
osophical temper,  lets  one  see  that  his  course  is  determined  by  his 
valuation  of  moral  character.  Fichte  is  evidently,  in  all  his  work, 
responding  to  a  moral  enthusiasm,  defining  reality  so  as  to  adapt  it  to 
emotional  needs. 

Not  all  metaphysicians,  however,  have  been  determined  in  their 
philosophy  by  religious  cravings.  Many  an  imagination  loves  to  play 
with  cosmic  themes,  and  what  it  produces  is  a  work  of  art. 

Metaphysics  is,  like  all  knowledge  laboriously  attained,  the  re- 
sponse which  has  been  made  to  demands  for  cognitive  satisfaction. 
The  demand  is,  of  course,  the  expression  of  a  temperament  and  may 
show  a  religious  or  an  esthetic  character.  It  may  show,  too,  what  we 
are  obliged  to  call  the  purely  intellectual  character,  where  the  cogni- 
tive satisfaction  which  is  sought  is  a  deli«;lit  in  knowing,  in  rt'lating 
ideas,  in  building  up  an  ideal  system  of  thought  which  charms  by  its 
order  and  completeness.    A  superb  example  of  this  type  is  Aristotle. 

I  ask  above  for  the  motives  which  makes  metaphysics  iasist  upon 
the  existential  judgment,  and  I  have  indicated  certain  emotional 
needs  which  demand  this  satisfaction.  Actually,  however,  the  ex- 
istential judgment  is  so  characteristic  of  metaphysics  because  until 
very  recently  it  was  equally  characteristic  of  science,  and  the  motives 
which  are  driving  it  out  of  science  have  not  yet  made  themselves  felt 
in  philosophy.  This  critical  attitude  in  science  has  not  yet  become 
very  general,  but  we  can  not  doubt  that  it  will  become  rapidly  author- 
itative. A  point  of  view  which  leaves  to  science  full  scope  to  carry 
on  its  tasks,  and  defines  those  tasks  in  such  a  way  as  to  eliminate 
metaphysics,  or  at  least  to  reduce  the  metaphysical  presuppositions  to 
a  minimum,  is  sure  to  be  most  welcome.  And  this  point  of  view, 
when  it  comes  to  be  regarded  as  the  only  point  of  view  for  science, 
when  the  definition  of  the  goal  of  science  as  the  knowledge  of  the 
unchanging  original  causes  of  phenomena  comes  to  be  looked  back 
upon  as  something  quite  antiquated  and  outgrown,  may  have  impor- 
tant consequences  for  metaphysics. 

Metaphysics,  as  we  saw,  is  the  response  to  interests  of  rather  differ- 
ent types.  It  undertakes  to  satisfy  certain  emotional  needs  of  a 
religious  or  semireligious  character,  and  it  ministers  to  the  purely 
intellectual  and  esthetic  delight  in  noble  ideal  constructions.  To  the 
former  of  these  two  classes  of  interest,  the  existential  judgment  must 
always  be  indispensable.  It  is  not  evident  why  it  should  be  indis- 
pensable to  the  latter.  The  latter  type  of  mind  is  ever  admitted  to  be 
the  more  scientific  of  the  two.  And  supposing  that  the  concepts  of 
science,  the  atom,  the  molecule,  the  ether,  etc.,  are  recognized  and 
claimed  as  nothing  but  conceptual  instruments  for  extending  our  ac- 
quaintance with  nature,  and  the  idea  of  the  atom  or  of  the  ether  as  an 


THE    EXPLANATIOy    OF   EXPERIENCE  69 

image  of  'reality'  is  remembered  as  a  notion  surprisingly  naive,  is  it 
not  altogether  likely  that  minds  of  the  purely  intellectual  type,  which 
devote  themselves  to  problems  about  an  ultimate  reality,  may  feel  dis- 
posed to  regard  their  concepts  as  science  regards  hers? 

For  the  example  of  science  in  such  ways  is  authoritative.  Meta- 
physics has  become  very  eager  to  be  'scientific,'  in  all  possible  ways, 
and  there  is  no  reason  to  suppose  that  the  methods  of  science  will  be 
less  alluring  than  formerly. 

Well,— if  this  happens  (and  the  new  epistemology  of  science 
makes  it  seem  not  unlikely)— if  it  comes  to  pass  that  the  concepts 
of  God,  the  Absolute,  the  Unknowable,  the  concept  of  reality  itself 
as  something  distinguished  from  appearance,  should  be  looked  upon 
as  working  hypotheses,  then  a  long  step  would  have  been  taken  to- 
ward the  clarified  experience  which  Avenarius  sought  to  describe  as 
the  limit  of  the  evolution  of  experience. 

But  then  these  concepts  must  do  one  of  two  things.  They  must 
either  (1)  lead  to  new  observations  by  proving  convenient  instru- 
ments of  description,  for  a  working  hypothesis  must  work,  or  (2) 
they  must  attempt  to  describe  something  which  is  confessedly  re- 
moved from  all  possible  observation.  In  the  former  case  meta- 
physics becomes  a  natural  science,  in  the  latter  case  it  is  difficult  to 
see  that  metaphysics  remains  anything  at  all.  For  that  which  is  re- 
moved from  all  possible  observation  is  no  longer  accepted  without 
question  as  existing,  and  this  concept  of  reality  is  itself  a  working 
hypothesis  used,  it  may  be  said,  to  make  phenomena  intelligible,  by 
which  is  meant,  however,  to  make  them  dramatically  interesting. 

But,  it  may  be  said,  there  will  still  be  those  who  refuse  to  sur- 
render the  existential  judgment.  They  will  keep  metaphysics  true 
to  its  ancient  function,  the  search  for  reality  behind  appearance. 

No  doubt  they  will,  but  it  is  a  question  of  how  much  honor  will 
be  paid  to  their  literature.  Of  course  speculations  as  to  the  future 
are  generally  idle,  but  we  have  here  certain  definite  data.  We  have, 
I  think,  the  beginning  of  a  new  epistemological  situation  of  a  per- 
fectly statable  kind,  and  we  have  a  large  amount  of  experience  show- 
ing the  recent  growing  dependence  of  philosophy  upon  the  special 
sciences.  This  dependence  is  growing  ever  greater.  See  such  defi- 
nitions of  philosophy  as  that  given  by  Wundt,  in  which  philosophy 
is  expected  to  follow  behind  the  special  sciences,  collecting,  organ- 
izing and  criticizing  their  results.  And  if  the  existential  predicate 
as  applied  to  the  working  concept  comes  to  be  regarded  by  scientists 
as  an  evidence  of  medieval  simplicity,  it  will  be  but  natural,  the 
prestige  of  science  being  what  it  is,  and  growing  ever  greater,  that 
this  new  epistemology  should  be  adopted  by  the  more  critical  students 


70  AVENARIUa   AND   PURE   EXPERIENCE 

of  philosophy.  More  and  more  the  search  for  reality  behind  appear- 
ance would  seem  like  a  monkish  dream. 

This  might  be  a  great  catastrophe  for  human  knowledge  and 
experience,  but  nature  permits  catastrophes. 

And  if  it  should  come  to  pass?  Well,— we  should  then  have 
science  and  our  natural  view  of  the  world. 

To  put  it  as  briefly  as  possible,  science  is  interested  in  ccjntents, 
and  aims  at  getting  more  content.  The  existential  predicate  adds 
nothing  to  the  definable  content,  therefore  science  has  no  interest  in 
the  existential  predicate.  By  what  interest  then  is  the  existential 
predicate  demanded  ?  Not  by  an  interest  in  contents  that  are  in  any 
way  statable,  therefore  by  an  interest  in  contents  that  are  unutter- 
able. For  it  can  not  be  denied  that  the  predicate  of  existence  does 
enrich  the  total  content,  but  it  does  so  in  unutterable  ways.  And 
the  interest  in  the  unutterable  is  a  purely  emotional  interest. 

The  relation  between  science  and  metaphysics  as  above  described 
is  strikingly  like  that  situation  in  the  Middle  Ages  which  brought 
forth  the  doctrine  of  the  twofold  truth.  This  doctrine  was  first 
stated  in  the  interest  of  religion,  but  its  effect  was  to  liberate  scientific 
speculation,  and  to  protect  religion  so  well  that  theologj'  occupied, 
more  and  more,  a  position  of  dignified  but  somewhat  lonesome  aloof- 
ness. If  now  we  are  told  that  a  proposition  can  be  true  in  science  and 
false  in  metaphysics,  and  vice  versa,  one  really  can  not  be  blamed  for 
detecting  in  the  'fringe'  a  feeling  of  prophecy. 


SUGGESTIONS    TOWARD   A    CONCEPT    OF   EXPERIENCE 

Are  we  in  a  position  to  bring  together  any  suggestions  toward  a 
concept  of  experience  ?     Let  us  see. 

Experience  is,  for  our  purpose,  cognitive  experience  of  objects, — 
experience  in  the  narrower,  and  more  precise  sense.  And  the  objects 
of  experience  are  characterizations  of  experience,  objects  which  may 
or  may  not  be  mythological  objects. 

The  most  important  character  of  experience  is  the  real  outer  world 
as  a  permanent  transcendent  object,  or  totality  of  objects,  which  con- 
tains certain  objects  of  peculiar  interest,  my  fellows,  who  in  turn 
experience  the  same  outer  realities  that  I  do. 

This  presence  before  me  and  about  me  of  a  real  outer  world  and 
fellow  beings  like  myself  is  a  character  of  my  experience.  It  is  also 
a  character  of  my  experience  that  the  experience  of  my  fellows  (those 
who  are  sane)  has  the  same  character  as  mine. 

The  possibility  that  this  natural  view  of  the  world  should  ever 
cease  to  be  a  character  of  experience  seems  too  remote  to  make  it 
worth  entertaining ;  the  few  cases  we  can  observe  where  this  has  hap- 
pened have  been  cases  in  which  there  was  a  profound  disorganization 
of  functions. 

Other  objects  of  experience  are,  however,  observed  to  come  or  to 
disappear.  But  these  variable  objects  appear  to  depend  not  merely 
upon  the  individual,  but  upon  the  social  relations,  current  beliefs  and 
attitudes,  the  ' Erkenntnissmenge*  in  which  the  individual  grows  up. 

Experience  is,  therefore,  not  an  individual  fact,  but  a  social  fact, 
focussed  in  individuals  but  forming  a  system.  The  limits  of  this  sys- 
tem must  be  arbitrarily  defined,  but  within  the  system  the  experience 
of  the  individual  is  determined  as  regards  a  great  deal  of  its  cognitive 
character  by  the  ' E rkennt tiissmenge'  of  the  whole. 

This  social  system  of  experience  has  a  history ;  the  common  fund 
of  objects  of  experience  is  known  to  change.  Certain  objects  or  char- 
acters are  eliminated  by  other  objects  or  characters  which  replace 
them.  Thus  the  sun  as  an  object  of  experience  which  revolved  about 
the  earth  has  been  replaced  by  the  sun  as  an  object  of  experience 
about  which  the  earth  revolves  in  an  elliptical  orbit.  Other  objects 
or  characters  are  eliminated  and  not  replaced.  These  are  objects  of 
the  animistic  type.  I  know  an  Egyptian  dragoman  who  was  terrified 
at  hearing  a  lady  under  his  guidance  speak  slightingly  of  the  water  of 
the  Nile  for  drinking  purposes.     He  feared  the  Nile  would  hear  and 

71 


72  A^E^AI^u^  a.\i>  nin-:  i:xi'i:i(ii;.\vt: 

take  its  revenge.  The  historical  current  of  experience  to  which  we 
belong  has  no  doubt  included  objects  like  this,  but  they  have  disap- 
peared from  our  own  system  of  experience.  Mythological  objects 
have  been  eliminated  to  a  very  great  extent,  and  new  objects,  or  new 
characters  of  objects,  are  brought  into  the  system  and  described  as 
the  objects  of  a  scientific  knowledge  of  nature. 

All  experience  shows  the  psychophysical  aspect;  therefore  ex- 
perience as  a  social  system  must  show  the  same  aspect.  It  is  becoming 
more  and  more  plausible  that  con.sciousness  depends  upon  processes 
in  brain-tissue,  and  therefore  the  system  of  experience  must  be 
regarded  as  depending  upon  an  elaborate  system  of  nervous  sub- 
stance. This  physiological  system  has  been  represented  by  the 
symbol  5C  And  if  the  changes  in  the  ' Erkenntnissmenge'  of  a 
system  of  experience  are  the  effects  of  processes  in  2C  the  history 
of  experience  must  depend  upon  a  parallel  history  of  2C. 

The  psychophysical  aspect,  however,  is  an  aspect  with  which 
only  the  psychologist  need  be  especially  concerned.  But  to  the  extent 
that  the  psychophysical  aspect  of  experience  comes  under  considera- 
tion, actual  experience  must  be  regarded  as  depending  upon  20  in 
its  relations  with  outer  stimuli. 

The  evolution  of  experience  still  continues.  What  lies  ahead  may 
be  expected  to  render  the  concept  of  nature  more  complete  and  defi- 
nite and  to  further  the  elimination  of  mythological  objects. 

This  concept  of  experience  is  an  instrument  for  conceptual  syn- 
thesis. Other  concepts  are  equally  possible.  The  one  which  I  sug- 
gest proceeds  from  the  standpoint  of  the  natural  view  of  the  world, 
and  accepts  its  data  from  all  sources  whence  information  can  be 
obtained.  The  concept  is  suggested  in  the  interest  of  the  study  of 
history.     The  author  of  this  concept  is  Richard  Avenarius. 


AN   EMPIRICAL   DEFINITION   OF    CONSCIOUSNESS 

In  beginning  this  final  chapter  I  can  but  refer  to  certain  recent 
articles  which  seek  to  improve  our  empirical  accounts  of  perception 
and  knowledge.*  My  own  effort  is  in  the  spirit  of  the  writers  I  refer 
to,  and  especially  have  I  felt  encouraged  by  the  articles  of  Professor 
James. 

Professor  James  explains  at  the  outset  that  he  does  not  deny  the 
existence  of  everything  we  may  suitably  call  consciousness.  The 
function  of  knowing  is  not  to  be  denied,  and  for  this  function  the 
name  consciousness  can  be  retained.  He  does  deny  the  existence  of 
any  'entity'  or  'aboriginal  stuff  or  quality  of  being  contrasted  with 
that  of  which  material  objects  are  made,  out  of  which  our  thoughts 
of  them  are  made.'* 

Now,  it  is  a  merely  verbal  matter,  but  for  my  own  present  pur- 
pose I  am  going  to  call  this  function  of  knowing  simply  knowing  or 
knowledge,  and  I  am  going  to  use  the  word  consciousness  to  signify 
another  fact  or  group  of  facts  equally  real.  It  is  for  the  reader  to 
decide  whether  my  use  is  justified. 

As  creatures  of  habit  we  say  that  there  are  things  and  there  is 
awareness  of  things,  that  there  are  objects  and  that  there  is  conscious- 
ness of  objects.  Any  fact  to  which  I  attend  becomes  straightway  an 
object,  and  every  object,  we  say,  must  have  a  subject.  This  subject 
can  not  be  my  body,  for  that  is  another  object.  The  subject  must  be 
something  far  more  subtile,  namely,  consciousness. 

'Must  be,'  we  say,  not  'is.'  The  sincere  empiricist  may  well 
be  suspicious  of  *must-bes.'  His  first  business  is  to  see  what  the 
empirical  situation  contains,  not  what  a  definition  implies.  In 
what  follows  I  try  to  report  a  strictly  empirical  content.  leaviuLr  (nit 
all  'must-bes.' 

It  sounds  like  an  innocent  and  an  intelligible  proposition  tu  say 
that  I  see  the  chair  on  the  other  side  of  the  room.  If,  however,  I 
mean  that  an  inspection  of  the  situation  as  experienced  reveals  any 
detail  of  the  content  that  can  be  called  'seeing'  as  distinct  from  the 
visual  chair,  and  other  objects  in  the  shape  of  sensations  of  head, 

*  Professor  William  James  in  The  Journal  of  Philosophy,  Psychology  and 
Scientific  Methods,  Vol.  I.,  Nos.  18,  20,  21;  Vol.  II.,  No.  2.  Professor  Frederick 
J.  E.  Woodbridge,  in  the  same  journal,  Vol.  II.,  No.  5.  Ralph  Barton  Perry,  in 
The  Psychological  Review  for  July,  1904. 

*  Journal  of  Phil.,  Psy.  and  Sci.  Methods,  Vol.  I.,  p.  478. 

73 


74  AVENAKIUB   AND   PURE   EXPERIENCE 

throat  and  body,  this  commonplace  statement  is  false.  The  situation 
contains  not  seeing,  but  visual  and  other  objects,  and  if  I  am  inter- 
ested in  the  object  on  the  other  side  of  the  room  in  such  a  way  as  to 
make  me  oblivious  of  myself,  the  situation  m  just  then  experi<'nced 
by  me  contains  no  seer. 

It  is  easy  to  understand,  however,  why  we  say  'I  see  the  chair' 
and  think  we  have  a  feeling  of  doing  stjmething.  Owing  to  acts  of 
mine,  the  content  is  constantly  changing,  I  am  continually  doing 
things  in  order  that  particular  contents  may  exist,  as  when  I  travel 
and  take  great  pains  to  see  all  the  picture-galleries,  or  all  the  Gothic 
architecture,  that  I  can.  And  when  I  at  last  have  come  to  something 
that  I  have  long  and  eagerly  wished  to  see,  there  may  be  such  a  lively 
pleasure  and  such  a  sense  of  purpose  fulfilled  that  I  say  to  myself, 
'Now  you  are  beholding  it,  now  you  have  really  got  the  experience 
you  have  been  longing  for.'  In  these  cases  an  empirical  ego  is 
present,  but  it  is  another  object  in  the  field  of  experience. 

This  sense  of  personal  eflBciency  expresses  itself  in  a  sentence 
having  its  subject  in  the  first  person  and  a  verb  in  the  active  voice 
and,  in  the  example  used,  the  visual  object  in  the  accusative  case. 
And  now  applying  this  manner  of  words  to  the  simple  case  of  'seeing* 
the  chair,  we  get  what  seems  to  me  a  very  bad  piece  of  psychology. 
The  situation  may  contain  ego  elements  and  non-ego  elements,  but 
these  are  all  objects  within  the  content ;  and  anything  like  a  sense  of 
effort  or  strain  which  might  be  called  a  feeling  of  the  act  of  percep- 
tion is  simply  another  object  which  would  be  grouped  among  the 
ego  elements.  But  in  most  normal  cases  (introspection  is  an  ab- 
normal case)  there  is  simply  the  presence  of  the  thing  'perceived,' 
When  I  look  up,  there  is  the  chair  and  that  seems  to  be  the  whole 
story.  The  chair  is  there  before  me,  but  I  can  discover  no  conscious- 
ness of  it.  The  sound  of  the  electric  car  is  out  there  in  the  street, 
but  there  is  no  consciousness  of  it.  There  is  the  odor  from  a  lamp, 
but  consciousness  of  the  odor  does  not  accompany  it. 

The  field  of  experience  contains  objects  of  endless  variety,— trees, 
buildings,  sensations,  pains,  pleasures,  hopes,  fears,  mathematical 
relations  and  logical  necessities.  But  in  no  ease  of  knowledge  does 
an  empirical  inspection  discover  the  object  plus  consciousness  of  it. 
If  we  mean,  then,  by  consciousness  something  observable  over  and 
above  the  brute  fact  that  the  object  is  there  wherever  it  is,  we  cer- 
tainly mean  what  no  observation  can  discover. 

It  may  strengthen  this  conviction  to  reflect  that  the  idea  of  con- 
sciousness is  probably,  as  Professor  James  says,  'the  faint  rumor  left 
behind  by  the  disappearing  soul  upon  the  air  of  philosophy.'  We 
speak  of  states  of  consciousness ;  our  psychologizing  forefathers  spoke 


EMPIRICAL    DEFINITION    OF    CONSCIOUSNESS  75 

of  states  of  the  soul  and  meant  the  same  thing.  We  instinctively 
feel  that  consciousness  is  an  inner  thing  rather  than  an  outer  one, 
and  if  now  the  tendencies  pointed  out  by  Professor  James,  and 
his  own  declarations  mean  that  consciousness  as  a  metaphysical  con- 
cept is  on  the  point  of  being  dropped,  and  that  with  it  goes  the  last 
bit  of  animism,  does  it  not  seem  an  unexpected  verification  of  an 
important  part  of  the  theory  of  Avenarius?  Avenarius  calls  the 
metaphysical  idea  of  consciousness  the  last  stage  of  animism,^  and 
says,  *am  besten  wars  man  gabe  einen  so  verfanglichen  Ausdruck 
ganz  auf .  '*  Naturally  it  is  of  particular  interest  to  see  whether  eon- 
sequences  for  idealism  are  likely  to  follow  the  new  attitude  toward 
consciousness. 

And  first,  it  does  not  seem  to  me  that  we  should  regard  conscious- 
ness as  a  bad  word.  We  can  continue  to  use  it  to  mean  what  we  have 
really  always  meant  by  it,  namely,  what  is  essentially  private  to  one 
observer.  That  there  is  a  great  mass  of  experience  which  is  essen- 
tially private  and  is  thus  contrasted  with  what  is  public,  is  the  basis 
of  the  familiar  distinction  between  the  inner  and  the  outer  world. 
Private  objects  are  what  we  may  intelligibly  call  subjective  facts. 
For  an  object  to  be  subjective  is  for  it  to  be  private.  Now  by  any 
case  of  consciousness  we  mean  what  is  equivalent  to  a  mental  state, 
and  'the  fact  that  our  mental  states  are  incapable  of  observation  by 
anybody  but  ourselves  seems  to  be  not  an  accidental,  but  an  essential 
character  of  these  mental  states." 

In  adopting  this  criterion  of  privacy^  I  am  glad  to  find  myself  in 
agreement  with  Professor  Miinsterberg,  who  writes:  "The  most  gen- 
eral condition  which  characterizes  a  psychical  fact  is  that  it  can  be 
experienced  by  only  one,  and  that  as  object  it  stands  to  the  subject 
in  the  relation  of  mere  capacity  to  be  experienced  (Erfahrbarkeit) ; 
it  is  distinguished  from  physical  facts  by  the  circumstance  that  these 
can  be  experienced  by  more  than  one.  .  .  ."  * 

The  privacy  character  is,  I  think,  not  really  different  from  the 
one  advanced  by  Dr.  Perry  in  his  article  'Conceptions  and  Miscon- 
ceptions of  Consciousness.'  Dr.  Perry  describes  cognitive  experi- 
ence precisely  as  I  have  done. '  The  earlier  judgment  which  is  pro- 
nounced error  by  a  later  one,  is  thereby  viewed  as  idiosyncrasy  or 
confusion.  Such  rejected  convictions  are  'definitely  recognized  as 
my  experience.'*     "There  is  no  experience  of  which  one  may  not 

» '  M.  WeltbegriflF,'  p.  106. 

*  L.  c,  p.  132,  note  G7.     Compare  '  Kr.  der  R.  Erf.,'  I.,  p.  viii  and  p.  22. 
'  Royce,  '  Outlines  of  Psychology,'  p.  4. 

*  '  Grundziige  der  Psychologie,'  p.  202. 

'  Psychological  Beview  for  July,  1904,  pp.  285-6-7. 

*  Dr.  Perry's  article,  p.  284. 


76  AVENARIU8    AND    PURE    EXPERIENCE 

come  to  say  'it  is  my  state  or  it  is  your  state.'  "  "The  most  un- 
equivocal instance  is  the  dream.  "^ 

So  long  as  we  keep  within  the  limits  of  the  experience  of  one 
mind,  this  seems  to  me  a  very  adequate  account  of  the  matter,  l)ut 
the  judgments  with  which  scientists  as  such  are  concerned  are  judg- 
ments in  which  they  have  a  common  interest,  and  in  which  validity 
means  the  support  of  corroborative  agreement.  In  the  case  of  the 
single  mind,  the  earlier  judgment  loses  validity  as  soon  as  it  loses 
verification  by  subsequent  judgments.  The  individual  who  can  not 
obtain  the  assent  of  other  observers  finds  his  judgment  classified  as 
idiosyncrasy. 

It  seems  to  me  a  very  misleading  analysis  which  does  not  take 
into  account  the  necessity  of  verification  by  other  minds,  at  least,  if 
we  mean  to  be  empirical,  and  if  we  are  discussing  that  type  of  judg- 
ment which  is  a  judgment  in  science.  Now  that  cognitive  experience 
which  for  itself  is  rational  and  full  of  insight,  yet  which  a  later 
judgment  of  the  same  mind,  or  a  judgment  of  another  mind,  char- 
acterizes as  whimsical,  is  what  the  criticizing  mind  can  not  get  hold 
of  and  make  its  own.  It  remains  the  private  experience  of  another, 
a  mental  state,  a  state  of  consciousness.  The  experience  that  is  'defi- 
nitely recognized  as  my  experience'  and  presents  a  *for-me  relation,* 
and  is  best  illustrated  by  the  case  of  a  dream,  is  so  manifestly  char- 
acterized by  its  essential  privacy  and  limitation  to  one  observer,  that 
Dr.  Perry's  excellent  account  can  lose  nothing  by  accepting  privacy 
as  the  characteristic  property  of  consciousness  rather  than  idiosyn- 
crasy and  error,  and  idiosyncrasy  appears  naturally  as  privacy  as 
soon  as  other  minds  are  taken  into  account.  And  error,  in  science, 
is  the  fact  of  rejection  by  other  observers.  What  is  rejected  is  the 
decision  of  a  cognitive  experience,  and  it  is  rejected  simply  because 
it  is  not  shared,  for  if  it  were  shared  it  would  be  not  rejected,  but 
affirmed. 

In  what  I  said  above  about  the  great  variety  of  objects  and  the 
universal  absence  of  any  type  of  object  that  can  be  called  conscious- 
ness of  them,  I  find  myself  in  substantial  agreement  with  Professor 
"Woodbridge,^  and  I  can  not  see  that  I  really  differ  from  him  in  pro- 
posing to  use  the  word  consciousness  in  a  different  sense. 

Professor  Woodbridge  expresses  greater  confidence  in  saying  what 
consciousness  is  not  than  in  saying  what  it  is.  It  is  not  '  a  kind  of 
receptacle'  into  which  things  can  get.     It  is  not,  as  the  idealist  be- 


'  L.  c,  p.  289. 

2  L.  c,  p.  287. 

3  '  The  Nature  of  Consciousnesg.'  A  paper  read  before  the  American  Philo- 
sophical Association,  December  29,  1904,  and  published  in  the  Journal  of  Phil., 
Psy.  and  Sci.  Methods,  Vol.  II.,  No.  5. 


EMPIRICAL    DEFINITION    OF   CONSCIOUSNESS  <  t 

lieves,  the  stuff  and  matter  of  all  reality.  But  we  can  say  that 
things  exist  in  consciousness  and  express  an  intelligible  and  consistent 
meaning.  When  things  exist  in  consciousness  a  new  'type  of  connec- 
tion' is  established  between  them.  They  are  'connected  up  in  a  new 
way. '  ^  "  The  peculiar  way  in  which  consciousness  connects  the  ob- 
jects in  it  is  thus  the  way  of  knowledge  actual  or  possible.  "^  "  This 
peculiar  form  of  connection  .  .  .  simply  makes  them  known  or  know- 
able,  and  known  with  all  their  variety  of  distinctions  from  a  thing 
to  a  thought."'  And  there  is  'apparently  abundant  right  to  con- 
clude that  when  consciousness  exists,  a  world  hitherto  unknown  has 
become  known.'* 

Now,  I  do  not  see  why  in  the  sentences  I  have  quoted,  the  word 
knowledge  or  knowing  or  cognition  could  not  be  substituted  for  the 
word  consciousness,  and  express  even  more  clearly  what  is  meant. 
Of  course,  in  view  of  the  fact  that  the  article  expresses  a  greater  con- 
fidence in  its  negations  than  in  its  positive  aflfimiations,  I  do  not  wish 
to  interpret  these  with  undue  assurance,  but  the  meaning,  I  take  it, 
is  that  when  consciousness  occurs  real  objects  become  known,  and  the 
only  difference  it  makes  to  the  objects  is  that  they  are  related  in  ways 
to  which  they  themselves  are  indifferent,  but  which  constitute  knowl- 
edge.    These  relations  are  relations  of  mutual  implication. 

With  all  the  negations  of  Professor  Woodbridge  I  entirely  agree, 
and  I  can  not  see  that  any  of  these  suffer  from  substituting  the  word 
knowledge  for  the  word  consciousness.  The  question  whether  con- 
sciousness exists  is  simply  the  question  whether  these  cognitive  rela- 
tions exist,  and  the  suggestions  of  Professor  Woodbridge  toward  a 
definition  of  consciousness  really  seem  to  me  to  have  in  view  a  defini- 
tion of  knowledge. 

Professor  Woodbridge  recognizes  as  'an  important  aspect  of  con- 
sciousness,' the  'isolation'  of  the  'individual  consciousness.'*  It 
seems  to  me  that  he  would  simplify  the  statement  of  his  own  position 
and  certainly  admit  nothing  inconsistent  with  that  position  by  accept- 
ing the  criterion  of  privacy  and  isolation  as  giving  the  essential  prop- 
erty of  consciousness. 

I  shall,  accordingly,  use  the  word  consciousness  to  mean  experience 
that  is  essentially  the  private  and  unsharable  experience  of  one  per- 
son, and  I  shall  conceive  such  experience,  which  for  each  one  of  us 
is  a  certain  streaming  of  objects  of  the  private  tjT)e.  as  contrasted 
with  objects  that  are  public,  and  directly  observable  by  any  one  so 
far  as  their  own  nature  is  concerned.  This  is  the  ordinary  antith- 
esis of  subjective  and  objective,  mind  and  nature,  * Bewusstsein 


^Journal  of  Phil.,  II.,  No.  5,  p.  125  «       *L.  c,  p.  122.  »  L.  c,  p.  122. 

*L.  c,  p.  125.  «  L.  c,  p.  121. 


78  AVESAUIUH    AM)    I'UUM    EXPERIENCE 

and  Natursein. ' '  We  have  the  two  kinds  of  objects ;  the  distinction 
is  commonplace,  but  strictly  empirical. 

Let  us  now  see  whether  this  return  to  the  ungarbled  facts  of 
experience  has  any  consequences  for  transcendental  idealism.  My 
purpose  is  precisely  that  of  Dr.  Perry  in  the  article  I  have  referred 
to,  namely,  to  deal  logically  with  the  idealistic  theory  of  an  Absolute. 
The  success  of  Dr.  Perry's  criticism  depends,  it  seems  to  me,  on  the 
obligation  which  the  idealist  may  be  under  to  accept  Dr,  Perry's  defi- 
nition of  consciousness.  It  does  not  seem  to  me  that  the  idealist  is 
obliged  to  accept  this  definition,  but,  as  I  have  above  remarked,  all 
the  intentions  of  this  definition  seem  to  me  better  carried  out  when 
we  say  that  consciousness  is  private  experience,  and  the  idealist  cer- 
tainly would  not  deny  that  he  conceives  all  objects  as  mental  states 
and  that  these  are,  as  such,  essentially  private  and  exclusive. 

The  word  consciousness  is  so  wrapped  up  with  idealistic  implica- 
tions that  it  seems  to  me  most  desirable  to  get  rid  of  the  phrase 
'objects  exist  in  consciousness.'  Consciousness  is  subjective,  indi- 
vidual and  private,  and  if  we  intend  to  give  an  accurate  description 
of  the  empirical  situation,  it  is  wise  to  cease  using  phrases  that  have 
us  ensnared  before  we  know  it  in  a  metaphysical  tradition.  To  come 
back  to  the  chair,  the  actual  test  whether  my  visual  object  be  chair 
or  hallucination  would  be  to  find  out  whether  you  too  see  what  I  do. 
Meaning,  then,  by  consciousness  the  kind  of  objects  that  are  private 
and  exclusive,  there  is  no  motive  whatever  for  saying  the  chair  exists 
'in  consciousness.'  It  exists  in  the  room,  in  space,  in  time  (although 
here  I  think  we  begin  to  use  metaphors),  it  exists  in  the  system  of 
relations  that  constitutes  knowledge  of  it. 

From  the  point  of  view,  then,  of  an  accurate  description  of  the 
empirical  situation,  I  have  no  ground  for  claiming  the  chair  as  my 
private  object,  which  it  must  be  if  it  is  a  mental  state  or  a  ca.se  of 
consciousness.  If  the  privacy  of  consciousness  nowhere  comes  into 
play  that  identical  chair  can  be  your  object  and  my  object,  by  which 
we  mean  that  you,  I  and  the  chair  are  all  objects  in  one  situation. 

But  if  the  above  reasoning  is  sound,  how  fares  it  with  the  logic  of 
idealism  ? 

When  the  argument  for  idealism  can  be  stated  in  so  many  ways 
it  may  seem  futile  perhaps  to  pick  out  one.  The  one  I  give  is  not 
the  same  as  that  quoted  by  Dr.  Perry.  I  give  the  following  argument 
because  it  has  always  seemed  to  me  the  best  one,  and  because  it  is 
usually  ignored  by  critics. 

It  begins  by  explaining  that  specific  sense-qualities  exist  only  by 

*  Munsterberg,  '  Grundziige,'  p.  204. 


EMPIRICAL    DEFINITION    OF   CONSCIOUSNESS  79 

■"irtue  of  the  functional  activity  of  the  perceiving  subject,  and  that 
it  is  impossible  to  describe  or  conceive  an  object  in  other  terms  than 
those  of  consciousness,  and  that  consequently  to  assume  the  existence 
of  an  object  having  other  attributes  is  to  assume  nothing.  And  to 
assume  that  the  object  exists  as  consciousness  is  to  define  it  as  what 
is  the  private  experience  of  one  observer.  When  all  experience  and 
all  objects  of  experience  are  defined  as  consciousness,  no  common 
object  is  possible.  It  is  impossible  that  a  father  and  a  mother  could 
refer  to  their  child  and  each  refer  to  the  same  object.  Different 
selves  are  completely  sundered  existences. 

Now  this  flies  in  the  face  of  normal  experience,  but  it  is  perfectly 
logical,  granting  the  premises.  The  argument  proceeds:  different 
selves  can  not  come  together  in  any  way  or  have  any  common  objects. 
Two  selves,  therefore,  can  not  occupy  the  same  universe.  And  if  we 
are  to  claim  to  live  together  at  all  in  the  same  universe,  this  universe 
must  be  the  total  consciousness  of  one  self,  which  integrates  and  ab- 
sorbs all  our  various  individual  selves.  My  world  and  your  world 
are  the  same  because  we  are  of  it,  and  it  is  the  consciousness  of  one 
self. 

Now,  since  we  do  all  the  time  claim  to  have  objects  in  common, 
we  appeal  continually  to  a  situation  which,  when  examined,  shows 
that  every  concrete  human  life  is  a  fragment  of  an  absolute  con- 
sciousness. 

To  think  of  shattering  such  a  work  of  art!  It  is  like  looting  a 
temple.  And  yet,  if  the  chair  before  me  is  not  of  the  essentially 
private  portion  of  experience,  this  grand  and  really  spiritual  fabric 
of  the  imagination  dissolves  away  like  the  architecture  of  dreams. 

And  then  ?  Well,  there  is  pure  experience  and  the  task  of  science 
is  to  describe  it.  What  other  kind  of  a  world  there  could  be  except 
a  world  of  pure  experience  I  really  can  not  imagine. 

And  here  I  apprehend  disgust  and  disappointment.  Is  this 
idealism  ashamed,  or  agnosticism  skulking  under  a  better  name,  or 
realism  too  timid  to  speak  out?  It  is  hard  to  answer;  the  'radical 
empiricist'  has  learned  something  from  each  doctrine.  I  am  not  sure 
that  the  demand  for  existence  distinguished  from  experience  is  an 
intelligible  demand.  But  in  saying  that,  I  do  not  admit  any  flight 
to  idealism  or  to  any  other  of  the  traditional  alternatives  in  meta- 
physics. My  conviction,  which,  of  course,  I  can  not  prove,  is  that 
metaphysics,  in  the  sense  hitherto  most  customary,  has  nearly 
finished  its  career.  But  there  remains  precisely  the  same  kind  of 
data,  namely,  experience  characterized  in  one  way  or  another,  and 
the  only  legitimate  method  of  dealing  with  it,  namely,  minute  in- 
spection by  all  available  technique,  and  accurate  description. 


0 


B        Buih,  Wendell  T,  18r'^6- 
5208        Avenarius  and  the 
E9B8      standpoint  of  pure 

experience. 

The  Science  press 

([1905]) 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY