Skip to main content

Full text of "Bradleys Dialectic"

See other formats


CO CO 

g]<OU 164679 g 
~ 



OSMANIA UNIVERSITY LIBRARY 

Call No. 111.5/C56B Accession No. 23495 

Author Church, R.^ r . 

Title Bradley 's dialectic 

This book should be returned on or before the dale last marked below. 



Bradley's Dialectic 



By the same Author 



A STUDY IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF 
MALEBRANGHE 

HUME'S THEORY OF THE UNDERSTANDING 
AN ESSAY ON CRITICAL APPRECIATION 



BradleyY Dialectic 

by 

Ralph Withington 
Church 

D.Phil.(Oxon.) 

Sometime Lecturer In Philosophy at 

Balliol College 

Associate Professor oj Philosophy in 
Cornell University 



LONDON 



George Allen & Unwin Ltd 



First published in 1942 



All rights reserved 

Printed in Great Britain by 
Billing and Sons Ltd.* Guildford and Esher 



Preface 



THE main aim of this work is two-fold. The primary object- 
ive is to bring out in somewhat simple terms the essential 
character of Bradley's dialectic. To that end, criticism of 
the dialectic is, for the most part, confined to a chapter oh 
some basic difficulties in it, in order that excursions in 
criticism may not unduly complicate exposition of the 
central doctrine. Perhaps it ought to be said in passing 
&Eat the difficulties considered in that chapter are not the 
only ones with which Bradley's dialectic seems to me to be 
infected. They were selected for emphasis because some 
selection was unavoidable and these difficulties seem to 
have been too generally neglected. 

A parenthetical few words may be called for as to the 
sense in which the term " dialectic" is here used. In some 
quarters "dialectic" has been given a perverse significance. 
Thus it is frequently used to mean what is meant by "verbal". 
A line of argument that is considered to be no more than a 
matter of words is dismissed as being "dialectical". There 
would appear to be no etymological justification for this 
usage. In its most radical sense, "dialectic" means what is 
meant by "elucidation". A dialectic is a method or way of 
elucidation. The history of philosophy alone makes it 
clear that there are diverse methods of elucidation. But 
Hegel, and Bradley after him, claim there can be only one, 
the dialectic of relational essence; what Bradley calls "the 
relational way of thought". Bradley's dialectic is his method 
of elucidation. 

It is rather difficult to avoid the unpalatable conclusion 

5 



Preface 

that those who, by virtue of temperament and training, 
are foreign to any form of systematic Idealism, find it easier 
to call down criticisms on Bradley than to follow him. And 
that is no more than natural, so long as the reader of a 
philosophy of Hegelian origins insists that it must square 
with Aristotelian logic. Hegel, and Bradley after him, 
repudiate the logic of contradictories and seek to replace 
it with the dialectic of contraries, which they call the true 
logic. Bradley denounces the Law of Identity as being a 
tautology and therefore inane. He then identifies the 
contradictory with the contrary, thus to proscribe the Law 
of Excluded Middle. 

Now anyone who has the patience to examine this repu- 
diation of the Law of Identity will see that it is no mere shift 
in doctrine. Rather it is a radical innovation in principle. 
For consider: on this view there may be no contradictories, 
as the contradictory is formulated by the Law of Non- 
contradiction. The Law of Identity being repudiated, the 
contradictory is identified with the contrary. That is why, 
in a word, there is on this view a middle term between any 
two co-opponents. And Bradley assumes, as would a thinker 
out of the tradition from which he largely derives, that 
Appearance, or everything short of Absolute Reality, is in 
process. Thus the middle term between any two differences 
is a moment of mediation in process, not a self-identical, 
static being. This moment of mediation Bradley calls rela- 
tion; and the terms mediated he calls qualities. 

For several reasons this repudiation of the Law of Identity 
and the identification of the Contradictory with the Contrary 
entail the consequence that the identity of no matter what is 
"relational". The theory of relational identity is the burden 
of the neglected chapter on Relation and Quality in Appearance 
and Reality. That neglected chapter of Bradley's "meta- 
physical essay 55 is the subject of the first chapter of the 
present work. In that chapter it is brought out that quality 

6 



Preface 

and relation mutually contribute to constitute the identity 
of each other. And this conception of relational identity as 
the essence of the internality of relations in Bradley is con- 
trasted with each one of the ten senses of ''internal relations" 
which have been made out by Dr. Ewing. This is followed 
by a brief chapter on Bradley's treatment of Space and 
Time, thus to afford an illustration of how Bradley applies 
the dialectic of relation and quality to two categories of 
Appearance. 

At the end of the chapter on Relation and Quality ', Bradley 
writes as follows, "The reader who has followed and has 
grasped the principle of this chapter, will have little need 
to spend his time upon those which succeed it. He will have 
seen that our experience, where relational, is not true; and 
he will have condemned, almost without a hearing, the 
great mass of phenomena." Accordingly, after reviewing 
Bradley's treatment of Space and Time, further considera- 
tion of the contrariety with which Appearance is infested 
"everywhere and always", as that is elucidated by Bradley 
in the remaining chapters of Part I, is omitted. Thus 
chapter III of the present work is concerned with the 
opening chapters of Part II the Part of Appearance and 
Reality in which emphasis is laid on degrees of Reality. 
Bradley's arguments to his criterion of Reality, and the 
ways in which the dialectic of relation and quality yields his 
monism, are the main topics of this chapter, which leads us 
in chapter IV to the Internality of Thought and Reality. 

In this chapter Bradley's conception of the nature of 
thought is considered in some detail. To that end, the work- 
ing of thought in and through stages of judgement into more 
and more comprehensive degrees of Reality is emphasized 
in order to bring out the cardinal sense in which thought 
and Reality are internal to each other. In order that this 
conception of thought may be grasped, we must see the 
source of thought as being what Bradley calls "the this" 

7 



Preface 

and "the mine", or virtual immediacy. For in Bradley's view, 
thinking develops out of virtual immediacy into "the ideality 
of the finite" by virtue of the inherent self-transcendence of 
all psychical fact. Indeed, the " ideality" of the finite is the 
inherent self-transcendence of the finite, in so far as that self- 
transcendence is ideational in character. Moreover, the self- 
transcendence of psychical fact is seen to be the very process 
of fission in sentience by virtue of which differentiation or 
relation occurs. Thus, since thinking is the ideality of the 
finite, or moment of differentiation in experience, thinking 
is relational. The consummation of a process of thinking 
in judgement is the fulfilment of a thought. This is achieved 
in a synthesis of the initial content of the thought within a 
context of relations and qualities which differ from those 
wherein the thought thus consummated in judgement had 
its inception. 

These considerations bring us to the coherence theory of 
truth and Reality, which is the main concern of chapter V. 
The nature of error as the relative privation of coherence 
in judgement, and the sense in which error is both unreal as 
a privation and real as some (however slight) degree or 
other of coherence, are brought out as a preface to Bradley's 
theory of truth. 

On that theory, a judgement is more or less true as it is more 
or less self-coherent. And it is self-coherent to the degree 
to which it is internally related within the systematic Whole 
that is reality. The criterion of truth is comprehensiveness. 
The more comprehensive the scope of the qualities and 
relations that are the content of a judgement, the more fully 
the judgement is true. 

The criterion of degrees of truth is likewise the criterion 
of degrees of Reality. An Appearance that is more com- 
prehensively self-fulfilling and self-fulfilled than another 
appearance is the more real. Questions as to the explicit 
sense in which judgements and appearance are more or 

8 



Preface 

less coherent bring us to the principle of identity in difference 
which is the topic of the next chapter. 

This principle arises out of the identification of the con- 
tradictory with the contrary, between whose terms there is 
a middle term. This middle term is the moment of media- 
tion, differentiation, or partial identity between and in the 
terms thus mediated. The principle of identity in difference 
is the principle of the dialectic of relation and quality. For 
the moment of mediation the middle term is the moment 
of differentiation that is relation. And the terms mediated 
are the qualities that are thus related. 

Since Appearance is everywhere and always relational, 
and the Absolute may not be a term in relation and remain 
Absolute, Bradley's relational dialectic poses a question 
as to what may be the relation of Appearance to Reality. 
That question is examined in chapter VII, on the relational 
and the Absolute, which is followed by a chapter on some 
basic difficulties in Bradley's dialectic. These difficulties 
converge on the radical point in principle that, for Bradley, 
identity is relational (in his sense of the term), not absolute 
or tautological, as in A is A. And that brings us to the second 
main objective of this work. 

That aim is, in a word, to point out the disjunction between 
identity as relational, and identity as an absolute A is A. 
Since identity may not be both relational and absolute: 
since we may not both affirm and deny the Law of Identity: 
this is truly a disjunction, not a pair of alternatives. 

It is a necessary condition of any coherent understanding 
of the dialectic, and of the concrete universal which it 
elucidates, that the notion of relational identity, or identity 
in difference, be borne in mind. For unless it be understood 
that by contradiction Bradley means what (to a non- 
Hegelian) is meant by contrariety, only bemused irrelevan- 
cies, such as Dr. Broad's monstrous assertions about Bradley's 
theory of relations, can result. And moreover, unless that 

9 



Preface 

cardinal point in principle be taken into account, a necessary 
condition of an understanding of the relational way of thought 
in any of its expressions, whether dialectical, political, or in 
economics, is thus ignored. 

Something strangely like a creed of exclusive party 
loyalty seems to have infected students of philosophy in 
some quarters. The doctrinaire bigotry thus engendered is not 
the less deplorable because it professes to be intellectual. 
As a consequence of this single-minded devotion to non- 
Hegelian modes of philosophy, otherwise sensible men, 
who have avowedly steered clear of Hegel, take his name in 
vain with some abandon. These same men apparently 
sit down to read Appearance and Reality upon the thoughtless 
assumption that its major doctrine could only have originated 
on either or both sides of Didcot Junction. The misunder- 
standings that result from such cavalier procedure have 
made Bradley, in these same quarters, a synonym for non- 
sense. 

Yet the dialectic that Bradley calls "the relational way of 
thought" formulates a mentality an almost hopelessly 
romantic way of imagination and evaluation that is abroad 
today in force, and we badly need to take account of it. 

This commentary was commenced some eleven years ago 
during a memorable and very pleasant sojourn at Balliol. 
Since theto, it has been recast several times, and each time 
the more severely limited in scope and detail in an endeavour 
to arrive at a comparative simplicity of treatment. The 
reader will find that Bradley's theory of relations is re- 
iterated at certain junctures in the course of the com- 
mentary. In view of the basic significance of that theory 
in Bradley's dialectic, some repetition of it in certain 
contexts was deemed advisable. 

The work owes more than could be even indicated to the 
Seminar of the late Professor H. H. Joachim on Hegel, and 

10 



Preface 

on Bradley, which it was my good fortune to attend through- 
out two years. It owes no less to the tutorial skill and kind- 
ness of Mr. J. D. Mabbott of St. John's. And it owes much 
to the benevolent ministrations of the late Professor J. A. 
Smith, whose frequent alarums and excursions over the 
perils lurking and working in the writings of his friend 
Bradley would have aroused the curiosity of a Bourbon. 
An acknowledgement of gratitude in this regard could only 
be so inadequate as to be virtually meaningless. 

Students at Harvard, in the Seminar on Metaphysics 
with which I was charged during a visiting Lectureship in 
1935, gave me many helpful criticisms of parts of the essay 
as it stood at that time. In that connection, I am par- 
ticularly indebted to Dr. Milton Gross, now of Columbia 
University. 

As in many other ways, I am gratefully and deeply 
indebted for critical instruction in systematic Idealism to 
discussions over a period of years with my colleagues, 
Professor G. Watts Cunningham and Dean George H. 
Sabine, as well as with Professor W. R. Dennes, of the 
University of California. These friends were also kind enough 
to criticize the work in manuscript form. 

I wish to express my gratitude to the Oxford University 
Press for their kindness in allowing me to make extensive 
quotations from Bradley's works. 

R. W. G. 

SANTA BARBARA, 

December, 1940 



II 



Contents 

CHAPTER PAGE 

Preface 5 

I The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 15 

II Space and Time 56 

III The General Nature of Reality 62 

IV The Internality of Thought and Reality 81 

V The Coherence Theory of Truth and 

Reality 94 

VI Identity in Difference 109 

VII The Relational and the Absolute 119 

VIII Some Basic Difficulties 133 

IX Relational and Absolute Identity 161 

Index i 88 



"But I clearly recognize that, if 
Not-A were taken as a pure negation, 
no compromise would be possible. 
You would then have to choose be- 
tween the axiom of contradiction and 
the dialectical method." 

F. H. BRADLEY 



CHAPTER I 

The Dialectic of 
Relation and Quality 



IN the course of the first three chapters of his "metaphysical 
essay". Appearance and Reality, Bradley reaches a conclusion 
that is fundamental to his entire metaphysics. This conclu- 
sion, moreover, is valid for, and is variously illustrated by, 
the several arguments which constitute the succeeding 
chapters of Part I of that essay. "The reader who has followed 
and has grasped the principle of this chapter (Relation and 
Quality), will have little need to spend his time upon those 
which succeed it. He will have seen that our experience, 
where relational, is not true; and he will have condemned, 
almost without a hearing, the great mass of phenomena." 29 * 
Bradley arrives at the principle that is expounded in the 
chapter on relation and quality by way of an examination 
of the distinction between primary and secondary qualities, 
and that between substantive and adjective; two of "the 
many ways in which we try to understand the universe." 
However fundamental, or however footless for such an 
attempt these ways be deemed, is a matter of but little 
moment, in Bradley's view. "From whatever point we had 
begun we should have found ourselves entangled in the 
same puzzles, and have been led to attempt the same way 
of escape." This way of escape is afforded by the principle 

* Unless it is otherwise indicated, all numerical references are to 
Appearance and Reality, and edn., Oxford University Press. 

15 



Bradley's Dialectic 

of the internality of relations. Bradley arrives at this 
principle in chapter III of Part I. In Part II of Appearance 
and Reality the internality of quality and relation turns out 
to be the Janus-faced principle at once of Appearance and 
of degrees of Truth and Reality. 

Bradley takes it that the distinction between primary and 
secondary qualities is made in order to reconcile changing 
appearances with a belief in a changeless reality. This 
distinction is " easily disposed of." For those who make it 
admit that qualities appear only as conditioned in their 
existence. How, then, may we expect to say anything at all 
about qualities alleged to be unconditioned, as are those 
designated "primary" and " independent"? To call the 
changing and relative qualities "appearance", in contrast 
with a reality that is alleged to be permanent and absolute, 
is to accomplish nothing at all: for nothing is actually re- 
moved from existence by being labelled "appearance". 
"What appears is there, and must be dealt with; . . . ," 12 
Moreover, extension, taken as devoid of secondary quality, 
is inconceivable: it "cannot be presented, or thought of, 
except, as one with quality that is secondary." 14 The alleged 
reality of extension, as something independent of the 
qualities called secondary, is thus seen, Bradley thinks, to 
derive from a distinction in theory that is repelled by fact. 

Then again, the line of reasoning by which the qualities 
called secondary are alleged to deserve the name holds 
with no less force of those qualities that are distinguished 
as being real in their own right. This means, to give the 
main point here but one illustration, that the example of 
the square tower which looks round at a distance, illustrates 
the conditional character of perceived extension quite as 
well as the example of the piece of wax illustrates the in- 
constancy of the temperature, odour, and colour of wax. 
Taken as a serious attempt at even a partial view of experi- 
ence, any doctrine on which anything like the distinction 

16 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

between primary and secondary qualities would be a valid 
distinction between reality and appearance can hardly 
survive even a light attack of Berkeleian criticism. 

The distinction between the substantive and the adjective, 
to which Bradley turns next, also is found to be of no avail 
as a satisfactory way of interpreting our experience. " We 
may take the familiar instance of a lump of sugar. This is 
a thing, and it has properties, adjectives which qualify it. 
It is for example, white, and hard, and sweet. The 
sugar, we say, is all that; but what the is can really mean 
seems doubtful." 18 A lump of sugar plainly is not any one, 
nor yet any set, or group, of its qualities. It is neither 
sweetness, taken alone, nor is it that quality and whiteness, 
and hardness, etc., taken in bare conjunction. 16 ' 17 The 
view that "the secret of the thing" 16 lies in the co-existence 
of these adjectives "in a certain way", 16 wholly fails to dis- 
cover any real unity existing in and throughout them. 
Either the nature of a lump of sugar is exhausted in the 
sum of the co-existing adjectives which are in question, or 
that nature involves a substantive which is their persisting 
unity. Yet where, or how, is this substantive to be found ? 
A substantive would be that which may not be a predicate. 
And whatever appears, it would seem, may be predicable 
of something else. 

So much as this may suffice to indicate vyhy Bradley 
concludes here that "we can discover no real unity existing 
outside these qualities, or again, existing within them." 16 
He proceeds to suggest an alternative to any further search 
for a satisfactory conception of substance. On this alternative, 
the qualities which constitute a thing are held together, not 
by a substance in which they would inhere, but rather by 
their relations. "One quality, A, is in relation with another 
quality, B. But what are we to understand by 'is' ?" 17 Surely 
not that "being in relation with B" is (identical with) A. 
Bradley does not here distinguish between the "is" of 

17 B 



Bradley's Dialectic 

identity and the u is" of predication. For where there is 
no degree of identity in the constituent terms of a judgement, 
those terms stand together in bare conjunction. As so 
arranged, the terms would be related quite externally, the 
one to the other, were such an external relation possible 
at all. Since, as we shall find Bradley urging in detail, any 
external relation whatever can only fail to relate its alleged 
terms, the "is" of predication, taken as a (verbal) sign of 
conjunction, is ruled out by the rejection of all merely 
external relations. 

Yet, in the judgement, "A is in relation with B", we surely 
do not mean that "being in relation with B" is A. Neither 
do we mean that "being in relation with B" is different from 
A. "And we seem unable to clear ourselves from the old 
dilemma. If you predicate what is different, you ascribe to 
the subject what it is not\ and if you predicate what is not 
different, you say nothing at all." 17 Any conception of the 
thing on which it is a substantive complex of related qualities 
will thus fail to elucidate both the way in which the qualities 
may be predicated of relations, and relations may be predi- 
cated of qualities. 

The way to resolve this dilemma, it may be suggested, 
is an evident and simple one: let us regard the relation of 
inherence as an external relation. In thus taking "is" to be 
the sign of a relation that is separate from, or independent 
of, its terms, we cease to regard that relation as being in any 
sense inherent in the terms it is said to relate. "Let us abstain 
from making the relation an attribute of the related, and 
let us make it more or less independent. 'There is a relation 
C in which A and B stand; and it appears with both of them.' 
But here again we have made no progress. The relation G 
has been admitted different from A and B, and no longer 
is predicated of them. Something, however, seems to be 
said of 'this 5 relation C, and said, again, of A and B. And 
this something is not to be the ascription of one to the 

18 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

other. If so, it would appear to be another relation, D, in 
which C, on one side, and, on the other side, A and B, 
stand. But such a makeshift leads at once to the infinite 
process." 17 ' 18 On this alternative, the phrase "stand in" 
takes the place of the term "is". Now we say not, "A is in 
relation with B," but rather, "A and B stand in relation C." 

And so the question is raised as to the meaning of the 
phrase "to stand in" as that phrase is used in this state- 
ment. For, to say that A and B "stand in" a relation G, 
would seem to say something about A, and B, and C. "And 
this something is not to be the ascription of one to the 
other." 18 For, by hypothesis, any conception of a relation 
as inhering in its terms is excluded on this alternative. Still, 
it may be urged, the fact is that the phrase in question adds 
nothing to the meaning of the statement "A and B stand in a 
relation C." For that statement refers to no more than the 
relational complex A C B. That C relates A and B is a 
matter of fact which neither can nor need be explained. 

On such a view of the matter as this, the relation G would 
be conceived of as quite independent of its terms. For to say 
that those terms (or any others) stand in that relation (or in 
any other), we are told, is not to say anything about A, C, and 
B: it is to say merely that we have A, and G, and B: where 
"and" is the enumerative, not the conjunctive "and". This 
being so, C is not even conjoined with A and B. It is quite 
independent of A and B. And as thus independent, the 
so-called relation C might as well be enumerated with 
other independent relations, such as R, and R'. For, as 
independent, the relation G requires no terms that it may 
be a relation. To such a relation, terms would be accidental: 
it could have no terms at all and still be a relation; for it is 
something that has its being independently of all terms. 
Yet this something is merely verbal. For to speak of a relation 
that is without terms is to speak of a relation that relates 
nothing, and so is not a relation at all. 

19 



Bradley's Dialectic 

But why take it, one may ask, that the relational complex 
A C B is exhaustively described in and through an enumera- 
tion of its constituents, regarded as merely independent? 
To be sure, it may be said, A, and G, and B are independent 
of one another: yet they are so only in the sense that each 
one is what it is in its own right. The term A is A absolutely, 
rather than relatively; and that is all it means to say that 
A is A independently of all else. The intrinsic self-identity 
of A, of C, and of B, is not their separation from one another. 
For in the relational complex A C B you have A and B 
related by C. In other words, in the enumeration, A, and 
C, and B, the "and" is the conjunctive, not merely the 
enumerative "and". 

Such an objection only raises all over again the question 
which we have been trying unsuccessfully to evade. For we 
must either deny or else affirm that this conjunctive "and" 
contributes to constitute the relational complex in question. 
If our attitude be that of denial, we are left with the bare 
complex A C B, whose constituents can only be enumerated. 
But if, on the other hand, we affirm that A C B are con- 
joined, then they are conjoined somehow, arid not merely 
compresent. 

Moreover, to say that the constituents of the relational 
complex A C B are conjoined, is to say something more than 
that there is the relational complex A C B; for it is to say 
something about those constituents, viz., that they are con- 
joined. "Something, however, seems to be said cf this rela- 
tion C, and said, again, of A and B. And this something is not 
to be the ascription of one to the other. If so, it would appear 
to be another relation, D, in which C, on one side, and on 
the other side, A and B, stand. But such a makeshift leads at 
once to the infinite process. The new relation can be pre- 
dicated in no way of C, or A and B; and hence we must have 
recourse to a fresh relation, E, which comes between D and 
whatever we had before. But this must lead to another, F; 

20 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

and so on, indefinitely. Thus the problem is not solved by 
taking relations as independently real." 18 The relation C, 
regarded as quite independent of its terms, A and B, is then 
viewed as being merely compresent with them. As thus 
independent, C does not require A and B, or any other 
terms, that it may be a relation. Hence C would be a relation 
were it without any terms at all. And yet a "relation" that 
relates nothing is surely no more than a mis-use of the word. 

The attempt to .take relations as real independently of 
their terms, while at the same time their "connexity" is held 
to be their being joined with their terms, also is futile. For 
either this "being joined with" is something more than the 
independent relation, or else we are back where we were 
before. Yet it is precisely this "something more" for which 
the notion of independent relations cannot provide. And 
so, in a foredoomed attempt to supply the deficiency, 
another independent relation is posited in the relational 
complex. But this too can only fail to relate; hence the infinite 
process, and "we are forced to see, when we reflect, that 
a relation standing alongside of its terms is a delusion". 18 
The attempt to understand experience through the notion 
of the thing and its qualities breaks down, no less when the 
thing is taken as a set of qualities related by an independent 
relation, than when a thing is taken to consist of qualities 
inhering in a substance, of which no positive definition, 
or description, can be given. 

In view of the fact that Bradley's argument to his rejection 
of external relations has been taken for and quoted from 
as his positive theory of relations (as, for example, by Dr. 
Broad and Dr. Ewing), it may be well at this juncture to 
point out that such is not the case. The conclusion of the 
argument in question is negative, and the text of it is part 
of the chapter on Substantive and Adjective, not of the 
following chapter on Relation and Quality, in which the 
basic content of Bradley's theory of relations is brought out. 

21 



Bradley's Dialectic 

Bradley thinks it will be "evident" that the problem dis- 
cussed in the chapter on substantive and adjective "really 
turns on the respective natures of quality and relation." 21 
The notion of a substantive and its adjectives proves to be of 
no avail: that of a relational complex raises the question, 
what, if not a relation independently real, may relate the 
qualities of a complex ? 

At the outset of his elucidation of the meaning of "rela- 
tion" and "quality" for his essay in metaphysics, Bradley 
foreshadows his main conclusion in that regard. "Our con- 
clusion briefly will be this. Relation presupposes quality, 
and quality relation. Each can be something neither together 
with, nor apart from, the other; and the vicious circle in 
which they turn is not the truth about reality." 21 In follow- 
ing Bradley's main arguments to this conclusion, it may make 
our course the easier if we remind ourselves that Bradley, 
in his Logic., is constrained to reject any view of identity as 
absolute, and to adopt a theory of identity in difference. 
That conception of identity is to be the topic of a subsequent 
chapter. Nevertheless, the fact that Bradley denies the Laws 
of Identity andTT^iPContradiction, as those laws are under- 
stood on an Aristotelian Logic, is fundamental to the nature 
of his dialectic. For that reason, it may be well to consider 
the point, albeit briefly, at this juncture. 

In the Logic, Bradley writes: "The principle of Identity 
is often stated in the form of a tautology, C A is A 5 . If this 
really means that no difference exists on the two sides of the 
judgement, we may dismiss it at once. It is no judgement 
at all. As Hegel tells us, it sins against the very form of judge- 
ment; for, while professing to say something, it really says 
nothing. It does not even assert identity. For identity without 
difference is nothingat all. It takes two 15 makeTEe^ same, 
and the least we can have is some change of event in a self- 
same thing, or the return to that thing from some suggested 
difference. For, otherwise, to say 'It is the same as itself 

22 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

would be quite unmeaning. We could not even have the 
appearance of judgement in 'A is A', if we had not at least 
the difference of position in the different A's; and we can not 
have the reality of judgement, unless some difference actually 
enters into the content of what we assert."* 

Any genuine judgement, we are then told, will assert 
unity in diversity, not the barren identity of the tautology 
"A is A". Judgement may not exist in the absence of either 
the differences or the unity. Unless the different constituents 
of a judgement are in some sense united in it, there is no 
judgement but, at best, an association of ideas. And unless 
it be differences that are said to be in union there is no judge- 
ment, but rather the utterance of mere tautology, and so 
no movement in thought at all. 

If the formula of judgement may not be A is A, no more may 
it be A is B. For in this latter form, we assert (it is assumed) 
that A is identical with, or strictly the same as, B. Therefore 
we are confronted by a dilemma: on the one alternative we 
assert about A nothing at all; on the other, we say that A 
is what it is not viz., B. 

The error that sustains this dilemma and from which it 
derives may be brought to light by considering the nature of 
the contradictory. "We have to avoid, in dealing with Con- 
tradiction, the same mistake that we found had obscured 
the nature of Identity. We there were told to produce 
tautologies, and here we are by certain persons forbidden to 
produce anything else. C A is not not-A' may be taken to 
mean that A can be nothing but what is simply A. This is, 
once again, the erroneous assertion of mere abstract identity 
without any difference."! That assertion is erroneous 
because it rests upon the assumption of pure negation. In- 
deed, that false assumption is at the basis of the entire 
erroneous matter. For the assumption that A simply is not 
B brings us ineluctably to the conclusion that A is A, irrespec- 
* Logic, and edn., p. 141. f Ibid. p. 146. 

23 



Bradley's Dialectic 

live of its relations. And that conclusion entails the above- 
mentioned dilemma. 

For this reason, among several others, there can be no 
place in logic for the notion of mere negation. "The con- 
tradictory idea, if we take it in a merely negative form, must 
be banished from logic. If not-A were solely the negation 
of A, it would be an assertion without a quality, and would 
be a denial without anything positive to serve as its ground. 
A something that is only not something else, is a relation 
that terminates in an impalpable void, a reflection thrown 
upon empty space. It is a mere nonentity which can not be 
real.' 5 * In short, mere negation is groundless verbiage. 
Every significant negation presupposes a positive ground. 
We can not and do not deny a predicate of a nothing; rather, 
we deny it of a subject on the ground that this subject pos- 
sesses a quality which is incompatible with the predicate 
of our negative judgement. \x 

Thus, for Bradley, the negative judgement does not express 
bare otherness, or mere negation, between the terms of 
which there would be no middle ground. Hence Bradley 
denies that the logical form of the contradictory, within 
which no middle term is possible, and the logical form of the 
contrary, within which a middle term is always at least 
possible, are distinct; and he largely identifies them. 
"But then this positive ground, which is the basis of negation, 
is not contradictory. It is merely discrepant, opposite, incom- 
patible. It is only contrary"* 

The notion of the contradictory, as that term is customarily 
understood with reference to the square of opposition, must 
be banished from logic. The contradictory means very largely 
what is meant by the contrary. No rule that would compre- 
hend the scope of the contrary could be formulated. For 
"contrary opposition is indefinitely plural. The number of 
qualities that are discrepant or incompatible with A, can- 

* Ibid., p. 123. 
24 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

not be determined by a general rule. It is possible of course 
to define a contrary in some sense which will limit the use 
of the term; but for logical purposes this customary restric- 
tion is nothing but lumber. In logic the contrary should be 
simply the discrepant."* The contradictory is in the main 
one with .the contrary, and that is simply the discrepant. 
Thus, wherever Bradley writes of a relational situation as 
being self-contradictory he means not what a reader steeped 
hi the Aristotelian tradition would erroneously take him to 
mean; rather, he means that the terms and relations in 
question are respectively contraries, and that by virtue of 
these contrarieties the relational situation i self-discrepant. 
It may help to avert another misunderstanding if, at this 
juncture, we pause to ask how we are to take the term 
"appearance", as used by Bradley. Is it the name of a static 
veil of qualities and relations which stands between us and 
the really real ? Now it will be recalled that there is a tradi- 
tion on which what is in becoming is appearance and appear- 
ance is what is in becoming. Readers of Bradley will recall 
how he writes of an ' 'infinite process" in relations; of a 
"principle of fission which conducts us to no end," 26 of 
relations that "break out", and "fall between" qualities in 
appearance; and of a "what" being "in collision" with 
another such. Again, appearance is "taken up into" the 
eternal Absolute. These samples of Bradley's idiom could 
easily be multiplied ad nauseam. If one were to take it that, 
for Bradley, "appearance" is the name of a static veil, one 
would have to take this idiom as mere metaphor. In the 
static there may be neither process, infinite or otherwise; 
nor fission, whether endless or not. The static excludes 
whatever might "break out", or "fall" no matter where, or 
be in a "collision". And to take Bradley as writing meta- 
physical irrelevance; would be to beg the question of the 
meaning of his writing altogether. Appearance is not static: 

* Ibid., p. 124. 

25 



Bradley's Dialectic 

rather appearance is in becoming; in it there is, Bradley 
finds, an infinite process > an unending fission, in and through 
which relations do* break out and fall between qualities. As 
contrasted with the eternal, self-identical Absolute, appear- 
ance is what is becoming. 

On the view that identity is absolute, the question as to 
how self-consistent judgements about becoming may be 
made is, to be sure, an old one. If A is A absolutely (rather 
than relatively), it is hard to see how A could become Y. 
For in the course of the process A, Ay, Ayy, . . . Y, there 
would finally be a point at which A is no longer A, and is 
not yet Y. On a view of identity as absolute, there could be 
no middle term in and through which the contradiction in 
judgements about change might be sublated. In Hegel's 
smaller Logic the initial middle term is becoming; i.e. the 
synthesis of being and non-being. * 'Being is the notion 
implicit only": no case of mere being is to be taken alone, 
but only as the contrary of non-being. The resulting alterna- 
tion in thought between being and non-being discloses itself 
as a process of becoming determinate, and so we find these 
primary contraries taken up into the category of Becoming. 

Bradley not only rejects Hegel's "ballet of bloodless 
categories", he finds the dialectic of contraries incompetent 
to achieve a self-consistent elucidation of the two contraries 
that are for him the characteristics of Appearance everywhere 
and always; viz., quality and relation. Now, for reasons to 
which we proceed, should we attempt to illustrate Bradley's 
conception of relation by thinking of a relation defined as 
a universal that requires at least two particulars for its 
illustration, our attempt could only be irrelevant. And were 
a sense-quality, thought of as self-identical, taken to illustrate 
Bradley's view of quality, this again would be a mistake. 
For self-identical relations and qualities may not become; 
they are what they are. Therefore they may not be taken 
as illustrations of Bradley's view of relation and quality. 

26 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

On that view, "quality" is the name of any moment of 
experience wherein immediacy is dominant and differentia- 
tion is recessive. The main point here may be illustrated 
by the process of cell-fission. If we attend mainly to the 
new cells that are thus emerging, what is then most immediate 
or qualitative will be dominant in our experience. If, on the 
contrary, our attention emphasizes the mediation or differen- 
tiation thus in process, then relation will be dominant, 
while quality is recessive. 

Thus conceived of, "Qualities are nothing without rela- 
tions. In trying to exhibit the truth of this statement, I will 
lay no weight on a considerable mass of evidence 5 ': 21 all that 
evidence, indeed, which goes to show how qualities are 
varied in fact by changes in their relations. "But I will not 
appeal to such an argument, since I do not see that it could 
prove wholly the non-existence of original and independent 
qualities." 21 ' 22 Instead of an appeal to extensive matters of 
fact, Bradley proceeds to offer a demonstration a priori. 

Any attempt to arrive at a relationless quality by abstrac- 
tion could only fail. The process of abstraction is a process 
of differentiation, and so that process, like any other, is 
relational. 

Again, we should be thwarted were we to "appeal to a 
lower and undistinguished state of mind, where in one feeling 
are many aspects. ... I admit the existence of such states 
without any relation, but I wholly deny there the presence 
of qualities". 22 For these felt aspects are not qualities if they 
are quite undifferentiated, and if they are differentiated, 
then, by that very fact, they are related. "In short, if you go 
back to mere unbroken feelings, you have no relations and 
no qualities. But if you come to what is distinct, you get 
relations at once." 22 Where there are no distinctions in 
feeling, there are no qualities: where there are qualities, 
there are distinctions; and, by that very fact, relations. 

To this, Bradley thinks it will be answered that though 

27 



Bradley's Dialectic 

the process of distinguishing qualities be relational, still that 
process of making these distinctions is not essential to the 
qualities thus distinguished. It will be acknowledged, Bradley 
thinks, that "as you say, what is different must be distinct, 
and in consequence, related." 22 ' 23 But, it will be objected, 
the relation that is the process of making distinctions does 
not belong to the qualities that result. They are differentiated 
by relations which depend in no wise on the respective 
characters of the qualities they relate. And so these qualities 
and their relations are in no sense determined or conditioned 
by each other. Moreover, these qualities, though different 
from each other, are different intrinsically, each one in its 
own inalienable right. 

For such reasons as these, it may be urged that relation- 
less qualities may exist in abstraction. For the process of 
abstraction, even though it be relational, is not essential 
to the quality abstracted. And the quality itself is not altered 
by being abstracted. "But such an answer depends on the 
separation of product from process, and this separation seems 
indefensible. The qualities, as distinct, are made so by an 
action which is admitted to imply relation. They are made 
so, and, what is more, they are emphatically kept so. And 
you cannot ever get your product standing apart from its 
process. Will you say, the process is not essential ? But that 
is a conclusion to be proved, and it is monstrous to assume 
it." 23 The force of this reply begins to be felt as Bradley goes 
on to develop his argument that the being of quality implies 
relation. 

Bradley assumes that a difference is a relation and that 
a relation is a difference. His main point here is that where 
there are different qualities, there are qualities related by 
their differences. "For consider, the qualities A and B are to 
be different from each other; and, if so, that difference must 
fall somewhere. If it falls, in any degree or to any extent, 
outside A or B, we have relation at once. But, on the other 

28 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

hand, how can difference and otherness fall inside ? If we 
have in A any such otherness, then inside A we must dis- 
tinguish its own quality and its otherness. And, if so, then 
the unsolved problem breaks out inside each quality, and 
separates each into two qualities in relation. In brief, 
diversity without relation seems a word without meaning." 24 
Either the difference between A and B, in virtue of which 
they are distinct, "falls outside A or B," thus to relate them; 
or, that difference ' 'falls within" A and B respectively, thus 
to differentiate each one of them within itself. On the latter 
alternative, the moment of relation would break out within 
A, and within B. Hence the difference that differentiates A 
and B must fall "outside", or "between" 24 them; and thus 
"we have relation at once." 24 

For exstmple, in the very incipience of a process of cell- 
fission the incipient differentiation "must fall somewhere". 
And it falls "outside" or "between" the incipient cells in 
the observable sense that it is their differentiation. As soon 
as we notice this, then (on the assumption that differentia- 
tion, or difference, is relation), we are aware of relation at 
once. For we are then aware of the difference in virtue of 
which the incipient qualities are differentiated, or related. 
Were a quality without relations in this sense of "relation", 
it would be in no wise different from anything else, and so 
would fail to be a quality at all. 

To be sure, no fixed line between a differentiation, and 
what is thus differentiated, can be drawn and maintained in 
experience. For any relation, and any quality, will be in 
process. As the incipient qualities become more and more 
determinate, their differentiation alters; and, as their 
differentiation becomes the more marked, the qualities 
alter. "Hence the qualities must be, and must also be related. 
But there is hence a diversity which falls inside each quality. 
Each has a double character, as both supporting and as 
being made by the relation." 28 In order that a quality may 

29 



Bradley's Dialectic 

be distinct, it must be differentiated from other qualities. 
This differentiation is no separate relation: rather, it con- 
tributes to constitute what it differentiates. Thus, in so far 
as A i quality, A is not relation; and yet, that it may be 
distinct, A must be both itself and its differentiation. "A is 
both made, and is not made, what it is by relation; and these 
different aspects are not each the other, nor again is either A. 
If we call its diverse aspects a and a, then A is partly each 
of these. As a, it is the difference on which distinction is 
based, while as a it is the distinction that results from 
connection. A is really both somewhere together as A 
(a a). But (as we saw in chapter II) without the use of a 
relation it is impossible to predicate this variety of A. And, 
on the other hand, with an internal relation A's unity disap- 
pears, and its contents are dissipated in an endless process of 
distinction. We, in brief, are led by a principle of fission 
which conducts us to no end." 26 Without a relation, A 
would be undifferentiated, and so would be nothing at all. 
With a relation, A is at once the a that is differentiated, and 
the a that is the differentiation. Thus "A is partly each of 
these". Neither a nor a is the other, "nor again is either A"; 
for oc is what is differentiated, while a is the differentiation. 
And this differentiation, a, is essential to the a that it 
differentiates. 

That is why "A is both made, and is not made, what it is 
by relation. ... It may be taken as at once condition and 
result, and the question is as to how it can combine this 
variety. For it must combine this variety. For it must com- 
bine the diversity, and yet it fails to do so". 26 A must be 
at once a, the aspect differentiated, and a, the aspect of 
differentiation. Without a there is nothing differentiated, 
and so no quality: without a there is no differentiation and 
so nothing at all. 

A is at once itself a, and its differentiation a: and this 
identity of A, which is a, implies its differentiation, which is 

30 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

a. Thus the quality A is the moment of immediacy a, and 
the moment of mediation a, by which that moment of 
immediacy is differentiated from other qualities and 
relations. In brief, that A may be at all, it must be at once 
what falls within itself, and what falls between itself and 
all else. Thus A both is itself, and is transcendent of itself. 
No quality, then, will be self-sufficient or self-contained; 
no quality will be self-identical. For that in virtue of which 
a quality is distinct will fall beyond that quality. Yet, at the 
same time, that differentiation will be essential to that 
quality. For without that differentiation, the quality would 
not be differentiated, as it is differentiated, and thus would 
not be the quality it is. Hence no quality is wholly self- 
consistent; and that means, for Bradley, that no quality is 
wholly intelligible by the relational way of thought that is 
ineluctably ours. 

Thus, "we have found that qualities, taken without 
relations, have no intelligible meaning. Unfortunately, 
taken together with them, they are equally unintelligible". 26 
So far, we have noticed that relations without qualities 
would be relations that relate nothing, and so fail to be 
relations at all. And we have noticed that qualities without 
relations would be undifferentiated, and so would be not 
many, but one. That there might be a plurality of qualities 
without relation is impossible. Yet, taken together with its 
relations, we have seen that no quality is wholly self- 
consistent, or intelligible. 

The same difficulty appears when experience is "taken 
from the side of relations. They are nothing intelligible, 
either with or without their qualities". 27 As relations apart 
from qualities are a delusion, so together with quality they 
are in no finite context completely intelligible. For that a 
relation may differentiate its terms, it must * 'penetrate 
and alter" them, and so be implicated in their respective 
natures. Yet, that this differentiation may not disappear 

3 1 



Bradley's Dialectic 

altogether, it must "fall" to some extent "between" the 
qualities which it differentiates, and so relates. A relation 
thus involves within itself a contrariety: it must be at once 
implicated in and transcendent of its qualities. And so 
"again we are hurried off into the eddy of a hopeless process, 
since we are forced to go on finding relations without 
end." 28 Then again, and on the other hand, in so far 
as a relation or differentiation is implicated in its quali- 
ties, it does not fall between them. In this respect a differen- 
tiation fails to be a relation at all. Yet in so far as a 
differentiation falls between qualities, it is outside them 
both, and so again fails to relate them. 27 ' 28 

Hence no moment of differentiation may be absolute. 
In a process of fission, no absolute distinction is to be found 
between the moments of quality and the moments of 
differentiation. There is "a diversity which falls inside each 
quality. Each has a double character, as both supporting and 
as being made by the relation." 26 Likewise, each relation 
has a double character, as both supporting and as being made 
by its terms. Qualities taken without relations or as absolute, 
and relations as absolute or without qualities, are both, 
Bradley finds, inconceivable. Yet qualities, taken as moments 
of immediacy that are at once made by and essential to their 
differentiations, are in no case absolutely self-identical; 
for they are differentiated by their relations. And so their 
respective identities are relational, not absolute. Likewise, 
relations taken as moments of differentiation that are at once 
implicated in and transcendent of their qualities, are in no 
case absolute (or separate) relations, for they involve within 
themselves that infinite regress in relational identity which is 
the principle and content of degrees of truth and reality. * 

In a posthumously published essay, Relations, Bradley 
reverts to his point about relations being less than wholly 
self-consistent and intelligible. "A relation (we find) holds 
* Collected Essays, pp. 634-5. 
32 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

between its terms, and no term (we find) can itself be or 
become a 'between. 1 On the contrary, in order to be related, 
a term must keep still within itself enough character to make 
it, in short, itself and not anything diverse. And again, while 
the relations are not the terms and the terms are not the 
relations, neither the terms nor the relations can make that 
whole, in which nevertheless we find them. For the terms 
and the relations (we have seen) cease as such to exist, 
unless each maintains itself against whatever is not itself 
but is outside. And the attempt to find the required unity 
and totality in the terms and the relations taken somehow 
together must end obviously in failure."* The attempt in 
question can end only in failure because neither the terms 
of a relational situation, nor their relation, may be self- 
consistent, or self-identical. For each one of the two terms 
will be a moment of immediacy, while, at the same time, it 
will transcend itself in being continuous with the differen- 
tiations by which these terms are differentiated. 

Likewise, these differentiations will be internal to, or 
confluent with the terms they relate; while, at the same time, 
they will fall between and thus transcend them. This is 
why "relation both is and is not what may be called the 
entire relational situation, and hence in this respect contra- 
dicts itself." A relation is the whole relational situation in 
the sense that it is what differentiates the qualities of that 
situation. These qualities, were they differentiated otherwise, 
would be different qualities. Conversely, were the qualities 
of the situation different, their differentiation also would 
be different. As thus determining the qualities of the situa- 
tion, and so its own character as a differentiation, "a relation 
to be actual cannot itself be less than all and everything that 
makes the entire relational fact".| For it is in virtue of the 
relation that the qualities which it differentiates are the 
distinct moments in process which they are. In a case of 
* Ibid., pp. 634-5. t Ibid., p. 636. 

33 c 



Bradley's Dialectic 

cell-fission, the qualities which are being differentiated are 
confluent with their differentiation; as, likewise, that relation 
is continuous with those qualities. At any two points in the 
process of fission, this relation may be marked off from its 
qualities, and its qualities thus will be marked off from their 
relation; but no such distinctions may be final for theory. 
For the distinctions in question would themselves be differen- 
tiations. These relations would break out, on the one hand, 
between the moments of fission which we had marked off 
as qualities, and, on the other, between what of the process 
would then be marked off as the differentiation of those new 
qualities. This "what" thus would become a quality in its 
own right: for it would itself be differentiated by the distinc- 
tions in question. Plainly such distinctions might be multi- 
plied indefinitely within a process of becoming. Since to make 
distinctions ipso facto is to relate, there can be no limit to the 
relational constituents of a relational situation. 

Yet "This on the other hand must be denied. For a rela- 
tion is not its terms, but, on the contrary, it is between them. 
And though the terms may 'enter into the relation 9 , yet, if 
they were nothing beyond it, they obviously would no longer 
be terms."* In this sense, relations pervade and determine 
the character of that partial whole; and thus they may be 
said to be not less than "all . . . that makes the entire 
relational fact." Still, in no case is the differentiation identical 
with the differentiated. The qualities differentiated are to be 
sure continuous with their relation. Yet that either quality 
or relation may be at all, each must be distinct, y 7 

That there may be qualities at all, distinctions must occur 
or be made, and no distinction in appearance may be 
ultimate. Once the differentiation is marked off, it is itself 
thus distinguished in being singled out; and hence between 
it and the initial qualities, fresh relations break out with 
their qualities. 

* Ibid., p. 636. 
34 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

No distinction, no differentiation in process, may be 
self-sustaining or absolute. For a differentiation will be at 
once continuous with its qualities and distinct from them. 
In virtue of that distinction, and no matter where in the 
process it may break out, or where it be discriminated, a 
fresh relation, with its own qualities, then appears. This new 
relation, though continuous with its own qualities, neverthe- 
less is different from them. And so, again, there appear fresh 
relations with their new qualities. 

The notion of independent relations, we have seen, 
yields an "infinite process" in relations that do not relate: 
the dialectic of relations which differentiate their terms 
exhibits a process wherein neither the differentiation itself, 
nor the quality differentiated, is absolute in its own right, 
or self-identical. Hence the conclusion that no relational 
situation is wholly self-consistent, or intelligible. 

Thus we may come to see that "Every relation (unless our 
previous inquiries have led to error) has a connexion with 
its terms which, not simply internal or external, must in 
principle be both at once".* A relation must be internal 
to its terms in the sense that, as their differentiation, it con- 
tributes to constitute their qualitative character: yet, if it is not 
to disappear altogether, a relation must, to some extent, "fall 
between" its terms. And in that sense a relation is at once 
internal and external to the qualities which it differentiates. 

It is sometimes said that the "internality of relations" 
means for Bradley simply this: any alteration in a relation 
ipso facto is an alteration in its terms, and any alteration in 
either term ipso facto is an alteration in the relation and in 
the other term. To be sure, it would be difficult (without 
achieving flat irrelevance) to take Bradley as meaning less 
than this. Since a relation is what differentiates its qualities, 
those qualities are what they are in virtue of that differentia- 
tion. That is why any alteration in the relation ipso facto 

* Ibid., p. 641. 
35 



Bradley's Dialectic 

is an alteration in the qualities thus differentiated. And 
since the differentiation is what it is in virtue of the qualities 
which it differentiates, an alteration in either of these quali- 
ties ipso facto is an alteration in their differentiation, and in 
the other quality. 

Yet, if this is the least that may be said in this connection, 
so much is far from enough. For such a bare statement 
of the matter might be taken badly amiss. It would allow 
one to think that for Bradley relations are "absolutely and 
merely internal"; i.e. exhausted in the character of their 
terms, as is the philosophical relation of resemblance for 
Hume. A difference or a resemblance which was absolutely 
internal would be wholly intrinsic to the different, or the 
resembling, terms themselves. A, in being A, would be dif- 
ferent from B; and B, in being B, would be different 
from A, not in virtue of any differentiation or process 
that partially fell between them, but rather in virtue of the 
intrinsic character of A and of B. Yet in being intrinsically 
what they are, A and B are self-identical absolutely; and 
their being different is not a differentiation at all: rather, 
their being different is exhausted in the respective beings 
that are the intrinsically different qualities A and B. 

The several ways in which Bradley elucidates his theory 
of relations, in the course of the dialectic of Relation and 
Quality, surely ought to suffice to make it clear that this is 
not his view of the matter. Moreover, in his unfinished essay 
on Relations, Bradley is at some pains to tell us what he 
considers to be the meaning of "external relation", and 
what he does not mean by the phrase "internal relation". 
"What should we mean (I will ask first) by a relation asserted 
as simply and barely external? We have here, I presume, 
to abstract so as to take terms and relations, all and each, 
as something which in and by itself is real independently. 
And we must, if so, assume that their coming or being 
together in fact, and as somehow actually in one, is due in 

36 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

no way to the particular characters of either the relations or 
the terms. From neither side will there be anything like a 
contribution to, or an entrance into, the other side or 
again to, or into, that union of both which we experience 
as a relational fact. Undeniably the fact is somehow there, 
but in itself it remains irrational as admitting no question 
as to its 'how' or 'why'. Or, if you insist on a reason, that 
would have to be sought neither in the terms nor the rela- 
tion, but in a third element once more independently real 
and neither affecting, nor again affected by, either the 
relation or the terms. This, I suppose, is the way in which 
relations have to be understood, if you take them as external 
merely and also as ultimately and absolutely real."* As so 
conceived of, external relations would merely coexist with 
their terms. Moreover, that such a relation should coexist 
with any terms at all, rather than simply exist without 
terms altogether, would be a merely fortuitous happening. 
Then again, this so-called relation might as well be taken 
along with other termless relations, once the absurdity of a 
relation without terms is admitted. Yet the relational situa- 
tion, A C B, is a unitary fact. And when A and C and B are 
taken respectively as external to each other, they do and 
may afford no explanation of the unity in which, neverthe- 
less, they exist. Any resort to an intermediary, itself external, 
by which to relate A and C, and B and C, fails to explain 
the unity and leads at once to an infinite regress in relations 
that fail to relate anything at all. 

Those of a positive turn of mind may object that in all 
this there is no unity that requires explanation. They may 
urge that the unity of A C B is exhausted in the coexistence of 
A and C and B. There are the terms; there is the relation; 
they coexist; and that is all there is to it. Yet, on any such 
view of the matter, the relation C still might be taken without 
any terms whatever. And to speak of such an entity as a 

* Ibid., p. 642. 

37 



Bradley's Dialectic 

"relation", would surely be to mis-use that word. "What 
(I ask next) should, on the other hand, be meant by a 
relation viewed as absolutely and merely internal? You, 
I presume, still in this case would continue to take the terms 
each one as, so far, in and by itself real, and as independent 
absolutely of any whole that could be said to contain them. 
And you would go on to attribute to the particular character 
of the terms, as so taken, some actual relation or relations 
which you find, as you say, to fall between them. Something 
like this, I suppose, is or ought to be meant by a relation 
which is asserted to be real ultimately and internal merely."* 
Such a view of relations Bradley rejects as "ludicrous" 
when ascribed to his view of the matter. 

One fundamental reason for this rejection derives from 
the theory of relations that is explained in chapter III of 
Appearance and Reality. There we find that a relation differen- 
tiates its terms and thus contributes to constitute their 
character; as in a process of fission, the growing differentia- 
tion is confluent with the developing cells thus related. 
Therefore, when there is alteration in the relation, there is 
ipso facto alteration in the cells or qualities that are differen- 
tiated by the relation. For it is in virtue of this differentia- 
tion that the qualities thus related are respectively what 
they are. 

A quality would be "ultimately and absolutely reaP'j 
were its nature quite self-contained. Such an entity would 
be what it is in virtue of itself alone : and so it would be itself 
absolutely, without relation to anything beyond its own 
absolute nature. If two such entities were posited, it would 
follow, in Bradley's view, that any relation between them 
would be wholly exhausted in the respective characters of 
the two qualities posited. "Relations would be merely 
internal if, the terms being taken as real independently, each 
in itself, the relations between them (as a class, or in this or 
* Ibid., p. 642. t 

38 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

that particular case) in fact arose or were due merely to the 
character of the terms as so taken."* This sentence is quoted 
from a note on the point in question made by Bradley for 
an earlier draft of his essay on relations. It expresses briefly 
Bradley 's lengthier statement of what he means by "a 
relation viewed as absolutely and merely internal". To that 
lengthier statement he adds: "The idea, I would add, that I 
myself accept any such doctrine as the above seems to myself 
even ludicrous. And to whom, if to any one, it should be 
attributed in fact, I will not offer to discuss. In any case, 
to assume it as the necessary alternative, when the mere 
externality of relations is denied, is (I submit) an obvious, if 
perhaps a natural, mistake. "t 

The mistake here consists in taking the terms of a relation 
as if those qualities were real absolutely, each one in its 
own right. Such a view is in flagrant opposition to the 
doctrine that is made out in the chapter Relation and Quality. 
To be a quality at all, is to be differentiated by a relation 
which thus contributes to constitute the quality which it 
differentiates. The identity of that quality implies this 
difference. But not this difference alone. In the relational 
situation A C B, the relation C differentiates A and B. That 
relation is implicated in their respective identities, and those 
qualities A and B imply that difference: were it otherwise, 
they too would be different. And the qualities A and B do not 
exhaust the content of experience. They will differ from 
qualities D, E, . . . n, as well as from the relation by which 
these other qualities are differentiated among themselves, 
and from all else. And so with B, D, E, . . . n: hence 
"identity implies difference". 

It may be objected that this well-known dictum is but 

a truism, almost obvious and no less empty. To be sure, 

identity implies difference: for A must be numerically 

different from other items, in order that A may be an item 

* Ibid., p. 665. t Ibid., pp. 642-3. 

39 



Bradley's Dialectic 

at all that could be identified by attention as that item. 
Such an objection is not wholly irrelevant, for it affords an 
example of a relation that is "merely internal". The items in 
question are different simply in virtue of themselves alone. 
Thus their difference from each other is merely internal 
to each one of them. 

Again, if "resemblance" be taken to mean any case of a 
qualitative identity distributed in enumerably different cases 
of itself, then we have another illustration of a merely 
internal relation. For the resemblance here is the qualitative 
identity which is exhibited in two cases of itself. Were 
numerical difference, and resemblance, in this sense of the 
term, regarded as relations, the terms of those relations would 
be self-identical. For the numerically different items are 
what they are in virtue of each respective item itself; and 
the several cases of resemblance are qualitatively identical 
absolutely, without reference to anything beyond themselves. 
Moreover, were it suggested that all of the relations of which 
a quality might be possessed are "merely internal", then the 
identity of that quality could only be absolute, not relational. 
Since it would contain within itself all of its relations (so- 
called), that quality would be an entity quite in its own 
right: its identity would be not relative to anything beyond 
itself, but absolute. 

What is absolutely self-identical is changeless and may not 
become. Yet Appearance is not changeless: it is in process of 
becoming. Now were we to attempt to view the differentia- 
tions within a process of fission as being merely internal 
to their terms, we could only succeed in ignoring altogether 
the becoming there in process. For such an attempt would 
end in seeing the terms as self-sufficient, each one within 
itself, and so without the existence of any differentiation 
or relation between them. Such terms would be self- 
contained; their identity not relational, but absolute; and 
their becoming in any sense would be impossible. And thus 

40 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

we see that "Every relation (unless our previous inquiries 
have led to error) has a connection with its terms which, 
not simply internal or external, must in principle be both 
at once".* Relations must fall to some extent or to some 
degree between the qualities of a process. Otherwise those 
relations would fall wholly within their qualities, and so 
they would fail to connect them. If such relations were 
regarded not as differentiations at all, then they would be 
"merely internal"; as is the philosophical relation of 
resemblance for Hume; and so they would be in no wise 
distinct from the respective characters of their self-identical 
terms. If, on the other hand, the relations which a mistaken 
opinion allowed to fall within their qualities, still were taken 
to be differentiations, then fission would break out within 
each quality, and the old issue would be raised all over 
again. 24 - 26 

A relation, taken as a differentiation, will differentiate 
qualities, and so will fall to some degree between them. 
A relation will be at once internal and external; the former 
in so far as it contributes to constitute, or is confluent with 
what it differentiates; the latter, in so far as it falls between 
these qualities. Thus a relation will be at once involved in 
and transcendent of its terms. Likewise, a quality, in being 
differentiated, will be involved in its differentiation, while, 
in being a quality differentiated, it will transcend its relation. 

And so a relation will have a being proper to itself only 
in so far as it transcends, and so is not, the very terms without 
which it is not a relation at all. Hence the contrariety, or 
"contradiction", which Bradley finds in the nature of 
relation. Likewise, a quality is immediate or qualitative 
only in so far as it transcends the very differentiations without 
which it would not be a quality at all. Thus, alike in its 
mediations or differentiations, and its immediacies or quali- 
ties, experience is found self-discrepant, or incoherent. 

* Ibid., p. 641. 
41 



Bradley's Dialectic 

Yet this incoherence is in no case absolute; for nowhere is 
an appearance self-identical. The identity of every quality, 
we have seen, implies its difference from all else. Any experi- 
ence is thus related with all different experiences. In virtue 
of the unrestricted internality of relations and qualities, 
experience is a systematic whole within which there may be, 
and are, degrees of coherence in truth and reality. 

II 

The characteristic nature of Bradley's theory of relations 
can be emphasized, perhaps, by comparing it with certain 
other views about relations which have been, and are, 
called "internal relations". The admirable elucidation of 
ten senses in which the phrase "internal relations" either is or 
may be used which Dr. Ewing gives us in his critical survey 
of Idealism, affords a convenient and comprehensive text 
for comparison. Moreover, sweeping and acute as is that 
elucidation, it would seem unduly to neglect what is, for 
British Idealism, the most germane sense of the phrase in 
question. "Bradley's actual argument against relations," 
Dr. Ewing says, "I need not discuss at length because it has 
already been answered by several different writers, and I 
do not think I have anything really fresh to add."* Yet the 
fact that Dr. Ewing considers this one of Bradley's arguments 
to have been refuted, does not explain to us what Dr. Ewing 
takes to be Bradley's own theory of internal relations. He 
does say that "Bradley is commonly included among the 
supporters of internal relations". But of which one, if any, 
of Dr. Ewing's ten senses of "internal relations" Bradley is a 
supporter, we are left to find out for ourselves. 

Now, though it be found that Bradley's theory of relations 
is radically different from any of the senses of "internal 
relation" with which Dr. Ewing is concerned, that contrast 

* Idealism, p. 147. 

42 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

in theory is not and is not to be taken as a criticism of Dr. 
E wing's own account of the matter. Dr. Ewing gives the fol- 
lowing statement of the first one of his ten senses of the 
phrase "internal relation". "In the first place it is sometimes 
said that all relations are internal in the sense that they all 
Tall within the nature of the related terms'. This definition, 
while etymologically more justifiable than most, involves 
many ambiguities and confusions. If we mean by the nature 
of a thing its full nature and do not include only its essential 
characteristics, this may be interpreted as including every- 
thing which is predicable of it and so all its relational charac- 
teristics without exception, however unimportant they may 
seem. We may then say that any relation falls within the 
nature of both or all the terms that it relates, if by this is 
meant simply that, whenever r relates A to B, A has the 
characteristic of standing in the relation r to B and B has 
the characteristic of standing in the converse relation to A; 
but this will not carry us very far. It is an important fact 
about relations that no instance of a relation can occur as a 
self-subsistent entity, but only in conjunction with terms 
which possess the characteristic of standing in that relation; 
but if by 'nature' be meant essential nature it does not 
follow, at least without further argument, that relations 
fall within the nature of either or both related terms."* 
Dr. Ewing goes on to point out still more ambiguities in this 
sense of the phrase in question. So much as this, however, 
may suffice for purposes of comparison. It is, presumably, 
clear that relations which "fall within the nature of the 
related terms" would be what Bradley calls "merely internal 
relations". We have seen that Bradley rejects this view, on 
which relations would be merely internal, as a relevant 
interpretation of his own theory of relations. The distinction 
between the essential and the accidental characteristics of a 
thing's nature, which Dr. Ewing goes on to make, is excluded 

* Ibid., p. 119. 

43 



Bradley's Dialectic 

on Bradley's view of the matter. The identity of A implies its 
difference from all else: the question of the importance, or 
the unimportance of many, if not almost all, of these dif- 
ferences for a given step in practical or theoretical life, is 
irrelevant to the wholly relational identity of no matter 
what. In this first sense of the phrase "internal relations", 
such relations would "fall within the nature of the related 
terms." Therefore they would be very like the merely internal 
relations which Bradley rejects. And as emended by a dis- 
tinction between essential and non-essential relational 
characteristics, this definition is no less incompatible with a 
doctrine on which no relations are non-essential to the 
identity of any moment of appearance, or degree of Reality. 

There is, moreover, a difference in principle between this 
sense of the phrase "internal relations", and Bradley's view 
of the matter. As an illustration of this, let us consider the 
following texts: "The contradictions which he (Bradley) 
alleges seem to arise through supposing that a relation must 
be treated either as a quality or as a third term. For in the 
former case it will qualify but not relate its terms, and in 
the latter case it needs a fresh relation to link it to each term 
and so ad infinitum." Thus, Dr. Ewing finds the ground of 
Bradley's arguments to the conclusion that any relational 
situation will be incoherent to some degree or other, in one 
of two alternatives, both of which fail to treat relations as 
relating anything. This would seem to say that Bradley 
ignored the question at issue; for he is alleged to have been 
concerned solely with entities (to call them that) which 
were not, and could not be, proper relations at all. 

Dr. Ewing may think that the notion of relations treated 
as qualities is both self-evident in its bearing on Bradley, 
and transparently false on any view. His procedure at this 
point, however, is not that he goes on to justify his assertion 
of that notion as an alternative ground for Bradley's theory 
of relations, but rather that he proceeds at once to advance 

44 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

an alleged refutation of Bradley's rejection of independent 
relations. Thus, with regard to the point that such a "rela- 
tion" can only fail to relate its terms, Dr. Ewing writes: 
"One might similarly argue that it was impossible to tie two 
things together with string because you would need another 
piece of string to tie the string to each object and so on for 
ever. The argument would be valid if each piece of string 
were so defective that it broke in the middle; similarly 
Bradley's objection would be valid of relations if and only 
if they did not fulfil their function of relating. Only then 
would they need another relation to do the relating for 
them. But in that case they would not be relations."* Dr. 
Ewing's piece of string may well be a good illustration of a 
relation regarded as being a third term. But Dr. Ewing's 
opinion that Bradley's argument to the conclusion that any 
notion of such independent entities leads to an infinite 
process of relations that fail to relate, "would be valid if each 
piece of string used were so defective that it broke in the 
middle; similarly Bradley's objection would be valid if and 
only if they did not fulfil their function of relating", is 
difficult to accept. In his first sentence here, Dr. Ewing 
appears to be saying that relations, as separate entities or 
third terms, fail to be relations because they break in the 
middle, like pieces of defective string. In his second sentence, 
Dr. Ewing asserts that "similarly Bradley's objection would 
be valid if and only if" relations failed to relate. The two 
sentences together would appear to say that, as a relation 
will fail to relate if it is like a piece of string that breaks in 
the middle, so "similarly Bradley's objection" will be valid 
only on the assumption that relations fail to fulfil their 
function of relating. Thus, whereas in the first of these two 
sentences, Dr. Ewing is concerned with relations as separate 
entities, in the second of them he refers to relations without 
qualification. Yet he says that, as he argues in his first 
* Ibid., p. 147. 
45 



Bradley's Dialectic 

sentence, so "similarly* 5 he may argue in his second sentence. 
But that would mean that the relations referred to in the 
first sentence are similar to those spoken of in the second. 
And, indeed, the two sorts of relation are similar: for like 
relations as third terms, the relations on which the validity 
of "Bradley's objection" is alleged to depend are relations 
which fail to relate. 

Thus, immediately after the sentences in question, Dr. 
Ewing writes: "only then would they need another relation 
to do the relating for them. But in that case they would 
not be relations."* It would seem that Dr. Ewing takes 
"Bradley's actual argument against relations", and "the 
contradictions which he alleges", to rest mainly, if not 
altogether, on a version of Bradley's argument to the rejec- 
tion of separate relations. These "relations", we have noticed, 
may not relate anything, and so they fail to be relations at all. 
Yet this negative argument surely is not the substance of 
Bradley's "actual argument against relations" as real in 
their own right. Were it so, Bradley would hardly have 
found it necessary to follow up his argument showing the 
impossibility of separate relations (which falls in chapter II 
of Appearance and Reality), with the elucidation, in chapter III, 
of the contrariety that is of the essence of the relational 
situation. This positive dialectic depends on no assumptions 
about relations which do not relate, but rather on the charac- 
ter of relations which do relate the qualities they differentiate 
and thus contribute to constitute. 

Directly after his statements last quoted above, Dr. Ewing 
goes on to offer a refutation, not of anything in chapter III, 
but of the notion which he has asserted to be the basis of 
Bradley's actual argument against "relations"; viz., that of 
relations which do not relate anything. "If, in A and B, r 
is really a relation, it relates A and B itself and does not 
require new relations to connect it to either, for the relational 

* Ibid. 
46 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

characteristic of standing in the relation is not itself a rela- 
tion. To say that, because A is related to B by r, A must 
stand in the relation r to B, and therefore must be charac- 
terized by (i.e. stand in the relation of 'having as charac- 
teristic' "to) the relational characteristic of standing in the 
relation r to B, and be characterized further by having the 
characteristic of being characterized by the relational charac- 
teristic of standing in the relation r to B, is only to say the 
same thing over again in different words, so that the so-called 
different relations which are supposed to constitute the 
infinite regress are really only more and more cumbersome 
ways of expressing the same relation."* However sound this 
may be as a view about relations and terms that are self- 
identical, as a difficulty for Bradley's elucidation of the 
relational situation it is inane. For, as stated by Dr. Ewing, 
this view offers no explanation of how it is that r relates A and 
B. To say that r relates A and B because r is a relation, and 
that it is the nature of a relation to relate, is to be un- 
reflectively assertoric. And that is not quite what Dr. Ewing 
says. He says that r "relates A and B itself and does not 
require new relations to connect it to either, for the relational 
characteristic of standing in the relation is not a relation".* 
Thus in A r B, A has the relational characteristic of standing 
in r to B, and (that) B is characterized by the relational 
characteristic of standing in the relation r to A. "But what 
are we to understand here by c is' ?" 

And that is Bradley's initial question at the outset of his 
arguments to show that the meaning of the statement, 
"one quality, A, is in relation with another quality, B", is 
not altogether explicit. We do not mean that "being in 
relation with B" is something different from B. Hence the 
dilemma of predication; a dilemma which may not be 
resolved by any distinction between the "is" of predication, 
and the "is" of identity. Thus we are forced to abandon the 

* Ibid. 
47 



Bradley's Dialectic 

attempt to predicate relations of terms, or terms of relation. 
"Let us abstain from making the relation an attribute of the 
related," Bradley goes on to suggest, "and let us make it 
more or less independent. 'There is a relation C in which 
A and B stand; and it appears with both of them.' But here 
again we have made no progress. The relation G has been 
admitted different from A and B, and no longer is predicated 
of them. Something, however, seems to be said of this 
relation C, and said, again, of A and B. 5 ' 18 In Dr. Ewing's 
view, what is thus said about A is that A is characterized by 
the relational characteristic of standing in C to B; and B is 
characterized by the relational characteristic of standing 
in C to A. Yet on this view the dilemma of predication 
remains. And the step which Bradley takes beyond his futile 
attempt to regard relations as attributes is not, by Dr. 
Ewing's view of the matter, even begun. Thus the explana- 
tion of the connexity of relations, by the notion of relational 
characteristics which characterize the terms which stand in 
those relations, does not so much as tend to refute Bradley's 
elucidation of the self-contradictory character of the rela- 
tional situation, for it does not begin to follow through his 
reasoning in that regard. 

In Dr. Ewing's immediately subsequent paragraph in 
this connection, he writes: "The same fallacy in a subtler form 
appears in Bradley's argument that each term 'has a double 
character, as both supporting and as being made by the 
relation', 26 so that these two aspects will be again related 
and so on ad infinitum. The distinction, so far as I can under- 
stand it, is between A .as abstracted from the relation and 
A as related. But what is the relation between these two 
aspects of A? Simply that the second includes besides the 
other characteristics of A the characteristic of standing in the 
relation, while the first does not do so. But this will not 
generate a second distinct relation between them and so on 
ad infinitum, unless it is assumed as before that A must have 

48 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

a relation to the characteristic of standing in any particular 
relation and that this relation must in turn be related to A 
by another relation."* Here again, the theory of relational 
characteristics is made to explain the connexity of relations. 
Since, however, that theory leaves unanswered Bradley's 
initial question about the relational situation, it can hardly 
bear on Bradley's actual views in the matter. We have 
noticed that a quality has a double character in that any 
quality is itself and transcends itself. The quality A is itself 
in so far as A is not the relations by which it is differentiated 
and made itself. Yet without those relations A could not be 
differentiated, and so A could be nothing at all. Hence, 
that A may be differentiated, it must transcend itself in the 
relations in virtue of which it is A. And there is no absolute 
line between the moment of immediacy that is the quality A, 
and the moments of mediation by which A is differentiated 
by its relations. Wherever the emphasis in feeling may dis- 
tinguish immediacy from mediation, quality from relation, 
there a distinction is made. This distinction will be a fresh 
differentiation in appearance; a differentiation which will 
contribute to constitute the qualities thus differentiated. 
Thus we may find a relational regress in any relational 
situation. 

Dr. Ewing has explained that, in his work on Idealism, 
"I did not say of which of my senses of 'internal relations' 
Bradley is a supporter because Bradley denied the reality of 
relations and therefore can not have held that relations 
really were internal in any of my senses or in any other 
sense" t Thus Dr. Ewing reaffirms the statement, made in 
his Idealism^ that "Bradley regards relations as unreal. ..." 
One would have thought it common property that Bradley 
denies reality to relations solely in the sense of the term 

* Ibid., pp. 147, 148. 

t Journal of Philosophy, Vol. XXXII, No. 10, p. 273. 
.: P. 123. 

49 D 



Bradley's Dialectic 

"reality" in which the Absolute alone may be real. To say? 
flatly that Bradley "denied the reality of relations", is tojj 
ignore Bradley's theory of degrees of reality. No relational 
situation is ultimate reality: but any relational situation will 
be real to the degree to which it is self-coherent and compre- 
hensive. 

Dr. Ewing has explained also that he did not consider 
Bradley's theory of relational identity in connection with his 
own account of internal relations, because that account 
threatened to become unwieldy.* And therein lies the 
difference in principle between the internal relations with 
which Dr. Ewing is concerned, and Bradley's theory of 
relations. In Dr. Swing's treatment of the matter, the 
identity of a relation, and of a term, is absolute, not rela- 
tional, as is the case in Bradley's view. This is to say simply 
that such relations, and such terms, are taken by Dr. Ewing 
to be what they are, not in virtue of their respective dif- 
ferences from all else, but in virtue of what they severally 
and respectively are in and of themselves alone. As thus self- 
identical absolutely, and not relationally, such relations will 
be internal in senses that can only be as different from 
Bradley's view of the matter as are absolute and relational 
identity. This difference, moreover, is that of a disjunction: 
the identity of A may not be both absolute and relational. 

This same difference in principle is again illustrated by 
the second of Dr. Ewing' s senses of the phrase in question. 
"The second meaning of 'internal relation' is 'a relation 
essential to its terms.' This sense can easily be derived 
from the first if we interpret 'the nature of a thing' more 
strictly so as to exclude all characteristics which seem super- 
ficial." f Here again, and throughout Dr. Ewing's discussion 
of this sense, relations and terms are regarded as self- 
identical each one in its own right. It is only to be expected, 
therefore, that we find in this discussion no explanation of 
* Jour, of Phil., XXXII, p. 273. f Ibid <> P- I22 

50 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

"being essential to" as meaning that relations contribute to 
constitute their terms; and that, in so far as they do so, 
relations transcend themselves as relations. 

Dr. Ewing's third sense need not detain us. In this sense 
of the phrase in question, internal relations are implicitly 
reduced to qualities;* and that is a "definite error".f 
It is repudiated as an error by Bradley. "Fourthly, the 
internal view of relations may be taken as simply asserting 
the fact that relations involve some kind of genuine unity 
between their terms." As Professor Laird says, J "Ultimately, 
. . . the question is whether a relation between things can 
describe a genuine connection or unity between the things. 
If it can, there is no mystery; for the fact, ex hypothesi, is 
intelligible. If it cannot, such relations do not relate and 
are unintelligible if they pretend to do what they cannot 
do." It is plain that on Bradley' s theory of relations, this 
view of the matter is not ultimate at all. For it offers no eluci- 
dation of how and why it is that relations relate their terms. 
A mere set of facts is not even its own description, much 
less any analysis which might explain the "genuine unity" 
of internal relations. For our main purpose in this connection, 
however, it is enough to notice that, with regard to the rela-. 
tions and the terms here in question, nothing is said which 
so much as suggests that their identity is relational. 

This is also pretty plain in the case of Dr. Ewing's fifth 
sense of the phrase in question. "Professor Laird also criti- 
cizes strongly a certain interpretation of the internal relations 
view, which we may take as our fifth sense. 'It is possible 
to assert with some confidence,' he says, 'that if A has some 
relation r to B, it is not only logically conceivable that A 
and B retain their character unmodified in the relation; 
but it is logically inconceivable that they should not do so. 

* A. G. Ewing, Idealism, p. 122. 

| Ibid., p. 122. 

J Knowledge, Belief and Opinion, p. 214. 

51 



Bradley's Dialectic 

Relations hold between terms, and form or express a tie 
between those very terms. Thus, in the propositions '3 is greater 
than 2' and '3 is greater than i', one and the same 3 occurs 
in both propositions, not a 3 modified by its relation to 2 in 
the first instance and a different 3 modified by its relation 
to i in the second instance. Either the whole relational way of 
regarding things is mythopoeic, or this identity of terms must 
be preserved."* <c Clearly he is right (Dr. Ewing continues) 
in holding that no tolerable view of relations can be incom- 
patible with the fact that the same term may stand in 
different relations, and he is also, as I contend elsewhere, 
right in holding that it cannot be true that all relations alter 
or modify their terms, if by this is meant that they cause a 
change in their terms. If A and B are to stand in a relation 
at all they must first have a certain character of their own, 
and this character is not made by the relation in question. 
Relation!?, we may say then, are all external in the sense 
that any relation presupposes a certain character in the 
terms related which is itself not due to and not modified or 
constituted by the relation in question. But for all that it 
might still well be the case that the relation was internal 
in the different senses, discussed later, that its character 
followed from the character of the terms, and that the terms 
could not be the same if the relation were different."! 
On a logic of contradictories or of absolute identity, it would 
seem to be plain that, as Professor Laird says, it is "logically 
inconceivable" that A and B should be modified by r, or 
by anything else. For, as intrinsically self-identical, A and B 
are changeless, and therefore not to be modified. For the 
same reason the number 3 of Professor Laird's first proposi- 
tion would be qualitatively identical with the 3 of his second 
proposition. 

* Knowledge, Belief and Opinion, pp. 78, 79; cf. also Cook Wilson's 
Statement and Inference, Vol. I, p. 71. 
f Idealism, pp. 125, 126. 

52 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

In Bradley's view, however, finite identity is not absolute 
but relational. Therefore, on this view, it is logically incon- 
ceivable that A and B should not be modified by their rela- 
tions. For it is in virtue of those differences that A and B 
are differentiated from all else; and it is thus that their 
respective identities imply their difference from all else. 
This would have to be true likewise of the number 3 in 
Professor Laird's first proposition and the number 3 in the 
second proposition of his illustration. Since the two contexts 
are different the relations are different: hence the meaning of 
3 in "3 is greater than 2" will be different from the meaning 
of 3 in "3 is greater than i". 

Again, if the view of identity as relational be left out of 
account (and we have noticed above Dr. Ewing's reason for 
not considering that view in connection with his discussion 
of internal relations), one may agree "that any relation 
presupposes a certain character in the terms related which 
is itself not due to and not modified or constituted by the 
relation in question". It would be impossible that they should 
be unmodified in any respect by the relations which differ- 
entiate them. For those terms would be what they are in 
every respect in virtue of their relations by which they were 
differentiated. 

Dr. Ewing derives his sixth sense from a phrase taken 
from Bosanquet, who "defines internal relations as relations 
grounded in the nature of the related terms". It might be 
expected that any elucidation of this definition would be 
carried out in the light of Bosanquet' s doctrine of the concrete 
universal. Yet Dr. Ewing says of the phrase in question: 
"By this must presumably be meant that their presence 
depends on and is determined, either causally or logically, 
by characteristics of their terms. This is undoubtedly true 
of some relations, e.g. the mathematical relations, also 
similarity and difference. That 7 is half 14 or that something 
blue differs in colour from something red can undoubtedly 

53 



Bradley's Dialectic 

be deduced from the intrinsic nature of the terms/' In view 
of these illustrations, and of what Dr. Ewing says about them, 
it would appear that he understands internality in this sense 
to be the "mere" internality of intrinsic similarity and. 
intrinsic difference. This view of internality is, presumably, 
of fundamental importance on a logic of contradictories; 
but it is, as we have noticed above, ruled out by Bradley's 
conception of identity as relational. 

Of the remaining four of Dr. Ewing's ten senses, the seventh 
is that in which a relation is said to make a difference in its 
terms. A relation is internal "in this sense if it is such that 
both of the terms could not have been what they are without 
the relation holding between them".* In the eighth sense 
in question, a relation is internal if it is such that from "a 
knowledge of one term and the relation in which it stands to 
the other term", the second term may be inferred to possess 
necessarily a certain characteristic "other than the charac- 
teristic of standing in the relations in question".")" A relation 
R is internal in the ninth sense "when A could not exist 
unless B existed andwas related to it by R". J And a term that 
is not only causally but logically dependent on its relation 
to the other term and vice versa is related internally in Dr. 
Ewing's tenth sense. 

It may be said that since, for Bradley, relations differen- 
tiate the qualitative character of their terms, no terms could 
be what they are had they been otherwise differentiated. 
Nor could A exist as the quality it is without its being 
differentiated from B by R. It is also the case that, for Bradley, 
any term is logically dependent for its qualitative character 
on the relations by which it is differentiated from all other 
terms. This can hardly mean, however, that Dr. Ewing's 
seventh, ninth and tenth senses are equivalent to Bradley's 
theory of relations. Though on that theory no quality could 

* Ibid., p. 131. t N>id. 9 p. 135. 

$ Ibid., pp. 135-6. 

54 



The Dialectic of Relation and Quality 

be or exist as the quality it is were its relations different in 
any respect, and though this dependence of quality on rela- 
tion and vice versa is logical in being the nature of implication 
(as opposed to "linear inference"), this is so because 
relations contribute to constitute the identity of their quali- 
ties. Thus the internality of relations in Bradley's sense 
requires that relations be viewed as the moments of differen- 
tiation in a process wherein the identity of each moment 
implies its difference from every other. This would be to 
assume a view of identity on which no single term or relation 
could be repeated unaltered in diverse contexts; a view of 
identity that nothing in Dr. Ewing's analysis of relations 
would seem even to suggest. 



55 



CHAPTER II 



Space and Time 



BRADLEY assures the reader of Appearance and Reality that 
once he has grasped the main argument of the chapter on 
relation and quality, "he will have little need to spend his 
time upon those which succeed it". For he will have seen that 
our experience, everywhere and always, is self-discrepant to 
some degree or other. Nevertheless, it may serve to illustrate 
the main conclusions of chapter III if we consider the ways 
in which Bradley finds that those conclusions about relation 
and quality are exhibited by his conception of space and time. 

At the outset of his very brief chapter on that subject, 
Bradley explains: "The object of this chapter is far from 
being an attempt to discuss fully the nature of space or of 
time. It will content itself with stating our main justification 
for regarding them as appearance. It will explain why we 
deny that, in the character which they exhibit, they either 
have or belong to reality. I will show this first of space." 30 
To that end, Bradley proceeds to show that space must be 
more than relational, and that space may be no more than 
relational, in nature. 

This "puzzle", as Bradley calls it, he sets forth anti- 
thetically, (i) "Space is not a mere relation. For any space 
must consist of extended parts, and these parts clearly are 
spaces. So that, even if we could take our space as a collection 
it woufd be a collection of solids. The relation would join 
spaces which would not be mere relations. And hence the 
collection, if taken as a mere inter-relation, would not be 
space. We should be brought to the proposition that space 

56 



Space and Time 

is nothing but a relation of spaces. And this proposition 
contradicts itself." 31 Space must be more than relation, for 
relations must have terms. And space must consist of extended 
parts. These will be homogeneous solids, not relations at all. 
Thus the relation in question, if it were the very nature of 
space, would relate spaces which are not mere relations. To 
take space as being no more than relational would be to 
take it as consisting of relations and so of relations without 
terms. Once the terms related are taken into account, it is 
seen that space cannot consist of a relation of relations. 
For that relation would not relate spaces. 

Therefore, space must be more than a relation. (2) "But 
space is nothing but a relation. For, in the first place, any 
space must consist of parts; and, if the parts are not spaces, 
the whole is not space. Take, then, in a space any parts. 
These, it is assumed, must be solid, but they are obviously 
extended. If extended, however, they will themselves consist 
of parts, and these again of further parts, and so on without 
end. A space, or a part of space, that really means to be 
solid, is a self-contradiction. Anything extended is a collec- 
tion, a relation of extendeds, which again are relations of 
extendeds, and so on indefinitely. The terms are essential 
to the relation, and the terms do not exist. Searching without 
end, we never find anything more than relations, and we 
see that we cannot. Space is essentially a relation of what 
vanishes into relations, which seek in vain for their terms. 
It is lengths of lengths of nothing that we can find." 

"And, from the outside again, a like conclusion is forced 
on us. We have seen that space vanishes internally into 
relations between units which never can exist. But, on the 
other side, when taken itself as a unit, it passes away into the 
search for an illusory whole. It is essentially the reference 
of itself to something else, a process of endless passing beyond 
actuality. As a whole it w, briefly, the relation of itself to a 
non-existent other. 5 ' 31 ' 32 Space is no more than relational 

57 



Bradley's Dialectic 

because space consists of parts and these parts consist of 
parts, and so on indefinitely. Thus space consists of the 
differences by which it is internally divided without limit. 
The notion that space consists of extended parts is an illusion 
that springs from the assumption that the parts of space are 
solid. Rather, those parts consist of divisions that are them- 
selves divisible indefinitely. Those divisions or differentiations 
are relations. That is why, "Searching without end, we never 
find anything more than relations; and we see that we cannot. 
Space is essentially a relation of what vanishes into relations, 
which seek in vain for their terms". 32 This is so because space 
is divided into parts that are divided into parts and so on 
without end. Thus space consists of divisions or differentia- 
tions, and they are relations. Hence we have it that space 
is no more than the relations that are the parts of which 
space consists. 

And, when we attempt to understand space not as a 
matter of parts, but as a unit, we are brought to much the 
same conclusion. "We have seen that space vanishes intern- 
ally into relations between units which never can exist." 32 
Yet, as we attempt to consider space as a whole, we find that 
it cannot be one. For consider, either space itself has bound- 
aries, or else it has none. On the first alternative, space has 
boundaries. They are its limits, and they differentiate it from 
all that is not space. These boundaries, then, relate space 
to whatever is different from space. Therefore, the non- 
spatial terms of those relations are not spatial, and so we have 
spatial relations that lack terms at one end. On the second 
alternative, space has no boundaries: it is not differentiated 
from anything else. On both alternatives, then, space is 
"the relation of itself to a non-existent other". 32 The whole 
of space with boundaries posited is differentiated by relations 
which, at one end, have no terms. Thus the posited bound- 
aries fail to bound; for they carry with them no termini for 
the relations or differentiations which those boundaries 

58 



Space and Time 

would be were they possessed of terms. And the whole of 
space taken without boundaries obviously is not even a 
specious whole. 

Thus we may see that "Space is not a mere relation". 
It is more than a matter of relations for the reason that space 
is extended as well as divided and therefore must consist 
of extended parts, not of mere divisions or relations. " But 
space is nothing but a relation." For the parts in question 
consist of parts, and so on indefinitely. As infinitely divided, 
space is an infinity of divisions or relations. Therefore, space 
is no more than relations. And these relations would be 
hopelessly self-discrepant; for they would be relations 
without terms. 

With regard to time, Bradley thinks that "the reader who 
has followed the dilemma which was fatal to space, will 
not require much explanation. If you take time as a relation 
between units without duration, then the whole time has 
no duration, and is not time at all. But, if you give duration 
to the whole time, then at once the units themselves are 
found to possess it; and they thus cease to be units. Time in 
fact is before and after in one; and without this diversity 
it is not time. But these differences cannot be asserted of 
the unity; and, on the other hand and failing that, time is 
helplessly dissolved. Hence they are asserted under a rela- 
tion. Before m relation to after is_JLhe character of time; 
and here the old difficulties about relation and quality 
recommence. The relation is not a unity, and yet the terms 
are nonentities, if left apart. Again, to import an independent 
character into the terms is to make each somehow in itself 
both before and after. But this brings on a process which 
dissipates the terms into relations, which, in the end, end 
in nothing." 33 ' 34 Time, like space, is at once "a relation 
and, on the other side, it is not a relation; and it is, again, 
incapable of being anything beyond a relation". 33 Time as 
a relation has to be a relation between terms of some sort. 

59 



Bradley's Dialectic 

If these terms have no duration, then the whole- time has 
no duration, and hence it is timeless. If, on the contrary, the 
terms have duration, then they cease to be distinct moments, 
for they are all contemporaneous with their duration. In 
order that they may remain distinct, they must be before 
and after each other. Without that inner asymmetrical 
diversity a duration is not temporal. Hence time is a relation 
the relation of before and after. Yet these differences in 
before and after cannot be asserted of a single duration 
without thereby denying its unity. Therefore, time cannot 
be a relation. Nevertheless, if those differences are not 
asserted of that unity, the duration in question remains 
timeless. Hence time can only be the relation of before and 
after by virtue of which a duration is temporal. Thus we see 
that, despite the dilemma whose horns were touched upon 
just above, time "is, again, incapable of being anything 
beyond a relation.' 533 

The relation of before and after is the nature of time; 
"and here the old difficulties about relation and quality 
recommence." 34 Without their diverse relations the diverse 
moments would not be differentiated, and so would not be 
before and after each other. Yet, with their diverse relations, 
each moment is infected with self-discrepancy. For each 
moment, as it stands before and after other moments, is a 
"now". Within each now either there is no process, or there 
is process. 

On the first alternative, a now would not be a moment 
of duration in process. On the second alternative, the pre- 
sumed integrity of the now is destroyed from within. "Before 
and after are diverse, and their incompatibility compels us 
to use a relation between them. Then at once the old 
wearisome game is played again. The aspects become parts, 
the 'now' consists of 'nows', and in the end these c nows' 
prove undiscoverable. For as a solid part of time, the 'now 5 
does not exist." Midday is after morning and before after- 
Go 



Space and Time 

noon. But in this process there is no self-sustaining point at 
which a final line may be drawn between before and after. 
No matter how broadly that process be measured, or how 
minutely, the unit of process measured will contain within 
itself processes, and these will be before and after one another. 
"Pieces of duration may to us appear not to be composite; 
but a very little reflection lays bare their inherent fraudu- 
lence. If they are not duration, they do not contain an after 
and before, and they have, by themselves, no beginning or 
end, and are by themselves outside of time." 35 Moments of 
duration are themselves in process of becoming; theyjxmtain 
within themselves not barren^ simplicity butjprocesses^ which 
are likewise durations ^^tjiT^^^r^and_a^r_ojie another.. 
To deny this is tantamount to affirming that the moments 
of duration you started with have no beginning and no end, 
no before and no after. But without beginning or end, these 
moments would fall outside of time. And, "if so, time becomes 
merely the relation between them; and duration is a number 
of relations of the timeless, themselves also, I suppose, related 
so as to make one duration. But how a relation is to be a 
unity, of which these differences are predicable, we have 
seen is incomprehensible. And, if it fails to be a unity, time 
is forthwith dissolved. But why should I weary the reader 
by developing in detail the impossible consequences of 
either alternative ?" 35 A relation cannot be a unity of any 
sort, for, as we have seen, a relation is any aspect of differen- 
tiation in a process. This aspect is no static, vacuous being; 
a differentiation is itself in process, and so contains within 
itself differentiations and the moments of relative immediacy, 
or quality, which they differentiate or relate. Yet if the 
relation which allegedly relates the timeless units fails to 
effect somehow a unity among them, we are left with the 
notion of a time that would consist of timeless terms with- 
out relations. Any such "time" would consist of "timeless 
moments" that were not even differentiated, but simply one. 

61 



CHAPTER III 



The General Nature of Reality 



IN the course of the several remaining chapters of Book I, 
Bradley illustrates his conclusion that "a relational way of 
thought ... is a makeshift, a device, a mere practical 
compromise, most necessary, but in the end most indefens- 
ible". 28 The contradiction or contrariety essential to the 
relational situation is likewise found in space and time, 
motion and change, causation, activity, and the self. 
Nowhere in appearance do we find a relational situation, 
whatever its character, that is altogether self-coherent. 
"The result of our First Book has been mainly negative. We 
have taken up a number of ways of regarding reality, and 
we have found that they all are vitiated by self-discrep- 
ancy." 119 Yet this very negation requires a positive ground; 
and it is to a consideration of this that Bradley turns in the 
opening chapters of Book II. 

When you condemn the self-discrepant as appearance, 
and hold that appearance is not absolute reality, either you 
have some notion or other, however dim and vague, of 
what you mean by the reality which you say the self-dis- 
crepant is not, or else your condemnation of appearance 
as being not reality is groundless. For, on the second alterna- 
tive, you have not the least notion of what it is that you say 
appearance is not. 

Even so, it may be rejoined, surely the ultimacy of the 
relational and self-discrepant must be suspect, whether or 
not a man be cognizant of the grounds of that suspicion. 

62 



The General Nature of Reality 

And no less surely, about reality in itself, the sensible man 
can be only agnostic. "To know the truth, we shall be told, 
is impossible, or is, at all events, wholly impracticable. 
We cannot have positive knowledge about first principles; 
and, if we could possess it, we should not know when actually 
we had got it. What is denied is, in short, the existence of a 
criterion." 119 Yet, with no criterion of reality, how can you 
deny that anything, however incoherent, is real ? 

Bradley insists there can be but one answer to this question: 
in condemning the inconsistent as appearance, we are 
contrasting all this with what is not inconsistent; and this, 
the self-consistent, is ultimate reality. "Our standard denies 
inconsistency, and therefore asserts consistency. If we can 
be sure that the inconsistent is unreal, we must, logically, 
be just as sure that the reality is consistent. The question 
is solely as to the meaning to be given to consistency." 119 
If, by definition, the inconsistent is unreal, then by the 
contradictory (or contrary) of the same definition the self- 
consistent is real. A denial of the conclusion of this immediate 
inference would deny the definition from which it follows. 

Still, it may be objected, this is a barren conclusion. 
To know, if we do, that the ultimate nature of things excludes 
contradiction or contrariety is only to know that much; and 
this is not to know anything positive about absolute reality. 
"The denial of inconsistency, therefore, does not predicate 
any positive quality. But such an objection is untenable." 122 
In his Logic (Vol. I, chapter III), to which Bradley here 
refers us, the reasons why such an objection as this one is 
not tenable are given at length. 

In the negative judgment "A is not B" the negation may 
not be a merely external relation. Neither may the negation 
be said to affect only the copula: nor may it be said to 
belong only to the predicate. For then the judgment "A is 
not B" would read "A is not-B"; and we should be judging 
A to be qualified by not-Bness. In short, * 'negation presup- 

63 



Bradley's Dialectic 

poses a positive ground".* This ground will be that in virtue 
of which A is not, or excludes B. "Every negation must have 
a ground, and this ground is positive. It is that quality x 
in the subject which is incompatible with the suggested 
idea. A is not B because A is such that, if it were B, it 
would cease to be itself. ... In other words, its quality x 
and B are discrepant. And we can not deny B without 
affirming in A the pre-existence of this disparate quality." 
Thus the redness of a rose here and now is incompatible 
with its being yellow. And that very determinate red 
would be the positive ground of the judgement "this rose 
is not yellow". 

But more often than not, perhaps, this positive ground 
is not made explicit in the mind of the subject who makes 
the judgement. He might assume, and without thinking 
about it, that as an extended thing, the rose recognized at 
a distance has some colour or other, and so judge signifi- 
cantly, "that rose is not yellow" whatever the perceived 
colour of it might turn out to be. Yet were a negative judge- 
ment without any such ground, however far to seek, or 
difficult to discriminate, it would be groundless altogether, 
and so not a judgement at all. 

Thus, even though our objector should take it that 
Bradley's criterion here is fairly stated, "reality is not 
self-discrepant", still he must acknowledge that (on Bradley's 
theory of negation) this negative judgement requires a 
positive ground. And, at the very least, this ground can 
only be the self-consistency of the real. Even so, it may still 
be urged, "the criterion is a basis, which serves as the founda- 
tion of denial; but, since this basis cannot be exposed, we are 
but able to stand on it and unable to see it". 122 If, at this 
stage, more than a criterion of the nature of reality were 
in question, such an objection as this one might seem 
plausible: "and there is a sense in which I am prepared to 
* Lovic> Vol. I, p. 114. f Ibid., p. 117. 



The General Nature of Reality 

admit that it is valid". 122 The plausibility here would derive 
from the assumption that the criterion of reality, as opposed 
to appearance, is taken to be more than a criterion. As such 
it does indeed afford no detailed knowledge of reality. 
"But that is very far from being the point here at issue. 
For the objection denies that we have a standard which 
gives any positive knowledge, any information, complete 
or incomplete, about the genuine reality. And this denial 
assuredly is mistaken." 122 It is assuredly mistaken, because 
appearance is not blank nothing and is, therefore, in some 
sense real. The real, we have found, is the self-consistent. 
And so we know "that everything, which appears, is some- 
how real in such a way as to be self-consistent. The character 
of the real is to possess everything phenomenal in a har- 
monious form". 123 How this may be so, it is the burden of 
Bradley's theory of degrees of truth and reality to explain 
in some detail. 

To find that no relational situation is wholly self-consistent 
is not to find that any situation is entirely or absolutely 
incoherent. For the absolutely incoherent would be not a 
unitary situation at all, but rather a mere aggregation of 
items. These items would be other than each other; and, by 
hypothesis, each one would be incompatible with, and so 
would exclude, every other one. Such a process would 
be not a process at all, but a fixed set of incompatibles. 

The internality of relations .rules out any plurality of 
reals as merely other than each other. "Otherness" would 
be the name of what (in his essay on Relations) Bradley calls 
a "merely external relation". For it would in no wise 
differentiate its intrinsically diverse terms. Such terms, 
intrinsically other than each other, would be what they were 
respectively in virtue of themselves alone. They would be 
self-identical, and therefore changeless. For that reason alone, 
such terms would be, at best, the merest abstractions from 
process. 

65 E 



Bradley's Dialectic 

That there may be different qualities in appearance, 
there must be distinct differentiations by which those distinct 
moments of immediacy in process are differentiated. The 
character of any and every quality requires the differentia- 
tions in virtue of which the quality is what it is. This is 
to say that "identity implies difference". Since identity 
everywhere and always implies difference, this oft-quoted 
dictum may not be taken in a restricted sense. Were there 
some qualities, X, Y, Z, whose identity were not relational 
but intrinsic, their being different likewise would be intrinsic 
to those qualities themselves. This difference would be 
what Bradley calls a ' 'merely internal" relation. Such a 
relation would be not a connection or differentiation at all; 
for an intrinsic difference could be nothing distinct from the 
intrinsically different terms themselves. And terms that were 
intrinsically individuated, or differentiated, would be self- 
identical and so changeless. A relation, to be a differentia- 
tion at all, and not a merely internal relation, must be dis- 
tinguishable from its terms.* 

But more than this: were the identity of X, Y, and Z not 
relational but intrinsic, those terms would be absolute, 
each one in its own right. No one of them would be related 
with those terms whose identity is not absolute, but rela- 
tional. And so X, Y, and Z would stand in a merely external 
relation to those terms whose identity implies their respective 
difference from all else. But any such externality is ruled 
out by Bradley's elucidation in the Chapter on Relation and 
Quality of how it is that differentiations in process are 

* What is the difference between a merely internal and merely external 
relation ? Neither the one nor the other is a differentiation. Intrinsic 
difference is internal because any alteration in the terms ipso facto 
is an alteration in their intrinsic difference : and that difference is merely 
internal because it is intrinsic. Such is not the case with a merely external 
relation. If the otherness of a hue and a figure be taken to be relation, 
then as a merely external relation it does not relate them. And so there 
could be nothing in that merely external relation to be altered by an 
alteration in the hue or the figure. 

66 



The General Nature of Reality 

internal to the qualities thus differentiated. The internality 
of relations holds not at all, or it holds everywhere and always. 
To object that it holds not at all, is to invite oneself to expose 
as fallacious the dialectic by which Bradley finds the intern- 
ality of relations to be the outcome of his initial elucidation 
of appearance in process. 

The quality A is A, not in virtue of its difference from 
some other qualities and relation, but in virtue of its difference 
from all else. And A is any quality: where and whenever a 
moment of immediacy is differentiated there will be a 
quality whose character is what it is in virtue of its difference 
from all else. Thus, by its differentiations from all that is 
not itself, any quality is related with the indefinite variety 
of appearances from which it differs. And any attempt to 
maintain the reality of relations as merely external must 
fail. "For if, wrongly and for argument's sake, we admit 
processes and arrangements which do not qualify their terms, 
yet such arrangements, if admitted, are at any rate not 
ultimate." 125 For nothing short of the whole system of 
internally related qualities, and internally qualified rela- 
tions, can be ultimate. Anything less could be final in its 
own right only if it were absolute, and so external to the 
system of internal relations. But that this is not a real alter- 
native, the dialectic of the internality of relations makes 
plain. 

Whatever is distinct is different; and to be different is 
to be differentiated, and so we have relation at once. ' 'Rela- 
tions are unmeaning except within and on the basis of a 
substantial whole, and related terms, if made absolute, 
are forthwith destroyed." 125 For absolute terms would be 
non-relational, and therefore not differentiated, and so 
nothing at all. Thus identity implies difference, everywhere 
and always. Any case of appearance will be what it is in 
virtue of its differences from all else. Thus, by the considera- 
tion of any form of process, we are led at once to the conclu- 



Bradley's Dialectic 

sion that reality cannot be less than a systematic whole of 
qualities and relations. That absolute Reality is more than 
this, the essential (although relative) incoherence of the 
relational situation indicates: Reality is the absolutely self- 
within which the various ^degrees of in- 



coherence in Appearance are resolved. 

How, even in principle, this resolution of degrees of 
coherence into an absolute reality is made out by Bradley, 
is a topic to be dealt with in its proper place. "Our result 
so far is this. Everything phenomenal is somehow real; 
and the absolute must at least be as rich as the relative. 
And, further, the absolute is not many; there are no indepen- 
dent reals. The universe is one in this sense that its differences 
exist harmoniously within one whole, beyond which there 
is nothing. Hence the absolute is, so far, an individual and a 
system, but, if we stop here, it remains but formal and 
abstract." Can we then, the question is, say anything about 
the concrete nature of the system? Bradley answers that 
reality Jis jsentient experience^ For everywhere and always 
what we have is the felt content of consciousness. Any attempt 
to deny this, say by way of a distinction between the experi- 
encing and the experience, which held the "ing" and the 
"ed" to be not distinct merely, but independent, could only 
ignore the internality of relations. 

The Cogito surely illustrates a truth; viz, the truth that no 
content of consciousness may deny its own reality. And 
the identity, or character, of any content implies its difference 
from all else. In virtue of the relations by which any content 
is differentiated continuously within the whole, any content 
will be continuous with the whole; and the whole thus will 
be continuous with any content. Anything other than tht 
systematic whole of internal relations would stand in an 
external relation to that whole. Yet this something or other 
is but a verbal fraud. For, as standing out of all relation 
to the system of internal relations, there would be nothing 

68 



The General Nature of Reality 

by which it could be differentiated and made different and 
itself: such an "it" could be nothing at all. 

The conclusion that the real is sentient experience follows 
from an acknowledgement of the fact of sentient experience 
in any form, and an understanding of Bradley's theory of 
relations. In his conclusion here, Bradley fears he "may be 
understood to endorse a common error. I may be taken first 
to divide the percipient subject from the universe; and then, 
resting on that subject, as on a thing actual by itself, I may 
be supposed to urge that it cannot transcend its own states. 
Such an argument would lead to impossible results, and 
would stand on a foundation of faulty abstraction. To set 
up the subject as real independently of the whole, and to 
make the whole into experience in the sense of an adjective 
of that subject, seems to me indefensible. And when I contend 
that reality must be sentient, my conclusion almost consists 
in the denial of this fundamental error. For if^/seeking for 
reality, we go to experience, what we certainly do not find 
is a subject or an object, or indeed any other thing whatever, 
standing separate and on its own bottom. What we discover 
rather is a whole in which distinctions can be made, but in 
which divisions do not exist. And this is the point on which 
I insist, and it is the very ground on which I stand, when I 
urge that reality is sentient experience". 128 That there must 
be distinctions, and that there may be no separations, follows 
from the doctrine of relations that is elucidated in the course 
of chapters II and III of Appearance and Reality. Appearance, 
whatever its form, is systematic: there are to be found, and 
may be, no isolated and self-contained appearances existing 
out of relation with the systematic whole of internal relations. 
The real is sentient experience, not because reality is the 
adjective oi a sell-Identical finite subject Jbut ratherjjecause 
tKereTT^entient experience, and because ^nything^jother 
^Kan~6r~ merely external to it, the _injternality_^.jel.ations 
rules out. It may^be that solipsism is implied by any subjective 



Bradley's Dialectic 

Idealism: certainly it is impossible within Bradley's meta- 
physics. For no finite centre of experience may be absolute: 
it is what it is in virtue of its relations with all else. Any 
attempt to posit a self that is a finite individual alone and 
in its own right can only ignore the theory of relations in 
virtue of which there is but one individual that is Absolute. 

The dialectic or elucidation of relation and quality leads 
to a monism at once. A "some- what" that were not dif- 
ferentiated from all else could be nothing at all. And once 
differentiated from all else, any content whatever will be 
related with all that is not that relational content. The 
character of the content of reality may not be other than 
sentient experience. For the reality of sentient experience 
may not be denied. And anything other than sentient 
experience would be the verbiage of a term standing in a 
merely external relation. 

Bradley is well aware that the concrete nature of reality 
is thus hardly more than indicated, and not made out. 146 
Yet a conclusion about the general nature of reality has 
been reached. "Our conclusion, so far, will be this, that the 
absolute is one system, and that its contents are nothing 
but sentient experience. It will hence be a single and all- 
inclusive experience, which embraces every partial diversity 
in concord. For it cannot be less than appearance, and hence 
no feeling or thought, of any kind, can fall outside its limits. 
And if it is more than any feeling or thought which we know, 
it must still remain more of the same nature. It cannot pass 
into another region beyond what falls under the general 
head of sentience. For to assert that possibility would be in 
the end to use words without a meaning. We can entertain 
no such suggestion except as self-contradictory and as 
therefore impossible." 129 We may reject this conclusion, 
I submit, only if we reject Bradley's dialectic of relation 
and quality. And to that elucidation of the contraries which 
constitute process, any alternative on which relations and 

70 



The General Nature of Reality 

their terms respectively are intrinsically self-identical, and 
so absolute, each one in its own right, is of no avail. For 
such self-identical terms and relations may not become. 
Hence, to adopt any such alternative would be to deny 
not only Bradley's dialectic of relation and quality, but 
also, and altogether, the very possibility of becoming 
itself. 

That, it may be urged, is what ought to have been done 
in the first place. It is an old story that what is called 
becoming is unintelligible, and an error to suppose that 
any case of development exists. Hume, for example, was a 
sensible man: he considered what we actually have in 
appearance; viz. succession: not development, or becoming. 
And if he did little or nothing toward elucidating the nature 
of succession, still that is not difficult to do in terms of the 
substitution of items in a compact series. 

This hearty optimism would not be easy to uphold under 
criticism. For in a case of succession such as A, and then b, 
and then C, where is the successiveness to be found? By hypo- 
thesis, A and B and C are respectively self-identical and 
therefore changeless. Evidently, then, the succession of 

A, B, G is not to be found either in A or in B or in C. The 
change in virtue of which B is substituted for A, and C for 

B, may not exist within those items themselves. Where then 
does it exist ? And what is its nature ? To these questions 
our optimism affords no answer. And if, consistently with the 
self-identity of each one of the successive items, we try to 
think of the change in virtue of which they are successive 
as self-identical, we are faced with a flat impossibility. 
A self-identical change could only be changeless; and a 
changeless change is a contradiction in terms. 

The change, in virtue of which successive items succeed 
one another, can hardly be a self-identical nature or form 
of any sort. And since no change may be self-identical, no 
change may be the contradictory of, or merely other than, 



Bradley's Dialectic 

any different change. Thus but one logical alternative 
remains: we must seek to elucidate the nature of process, not 
by any method for which identity is absolute, but rather by 
a dialectic of contraries. This allows us to notice that the 
identity of any moment of process is not absolute but 
relational. The quality A is not moment B in any sense in 
which the "not" here would be the sign of pure negation. 
Rather, the quality A is a contrary of moment B; and one 
middle term which falls between A and B is C. By this middle 
term they are differentiated; but not by it alone. And, since 
there is nowhere pure negation, this differentiation will be 
not external to, or other than its qualities: rather it will 
contribute to constitute their character, and so be internal 
to them. The respective identities of A and B imply that very 
differentiation, as the identity of that differentiation implies 
those qualities. And the conclusion that identity is relational 
that identity implies difference holds without exception. 
For the identity of any exception would not be relational 
but absolute. And for that reason, any alleged exception 
to the conclusion that identity implies difference could have 
no existence in process. The identity of A implies its differ- 
ence from all else; and so at once we have a systematic whole 
of internal relations. 

The use of the term implication in this context does not 
introduce a new factor into the dialectic of relations. No case 
of systematic implication (as distinguished from "linear 
inference", and from the implication which "linear infer- 
ence" requires that it may be a priori) is anything distinct 
from the relational situation which is that implication. To 
say that qualities imply relations, and that relations imply 
qualities, means that qualities are internal to their dif- 
ferentiations, which are internal to those qualities. And this 
means that the quality contributes to constitute the differen- 
tiation, and the differentiation the quality: where the 
phrase "contributes to constitute" designates nothing in the 

72 



The General Nature of Reality 

relational situation distinct from the moments of immediacy 
and mediation which are the process itself. 

The absolute to which this relational process leads we 
may know not concretely and in detail, but rather in abstract 
terms; and in a certain intimation of its character which our 
experience affords us. And our position here is ineluctable. 
So long as the relational way of thought is ours, then no 
matter to what level of concreteness we may attain, still we 
fall short of the Absolute. In order to know the Absolute, 
we should have to be absolute, and so cease to be relational 
and finite and ourselves. "What is impossible is to construct 
absolute life in its detail, to have the specific experience in 
which it consists. But to gain an idea of its main features 
an idea true so far as it goes, though abstract and incomplete 
is a different endeavour. And it is a task, so far as I 
see, in which we may succeed. For these main features, to 
some extent, are within our own experience; and again the 
idea of their combination is, in the abstract, /quite intelligible. 
And surely no more than this is wanted for a knowledge of 
the Absolute. It is knowledge which of course differs enor- 
mously from the fact. But it is true, for all that, while it 
respects its own limits; and it seems fully attainable by the 
finite intellect." 140 The source of this imperfect knowledge 
is two-fold: on the one hand, there is "mere feeling or 
immediate presentation", 140 > 141 on the other, there is the 
relational character of process, which "implies a substantial 
totality beyond relations and above them, a whole endeavour- 
ing without success to realize itself in their detail". 140 How 
it is that these two aspects of the matter may be taken 
together as affording an intimation of the character of the 
Absolute is a question to which we may now turn. 

In immediate presentation we have what Bradley calls 
"the This and the Mine". For in the moment of immediacy 
that is quality, there is an immediacy of feeling in virtue of 
which the quality is this moment, and mine. "The 'this 5 and 

73 



Bradley's Dialectic 

the c mine' are names which stand for the immediacy of 
feeling, andr each serves to call attention to one side of that 
fact. There is no 'mine' which is not 'this', nor any 'this' 
which fails, in a sense, to be 'mine 5 . " 197 

Any experience, in being mine, will be also this experience. 
And the "this" has a quite general referent: for, as so used, 
the term refers to the immediacy of feeling with which any 
moment of experience will 'be suffused. This immediacy 
of feeling "brings a sense of superior reality, a sense which is 
far from being wholly deceptive and untrue. For all our 
knowledge, in the first place, arises from the 'this'. It is the 
one source of our experience, and every element of the world 
must submit to pass through it. And the 'this', secondly, 
has a genuine feature of ultimate reality. With however great 
imperfection and inconsistency it owns an individual charac- 
ter. The 'this' is real for us in a sense in which nothing else 
is real." 198 Any moment of process will be this moment, so 
that any knowledge we may have will "arise from the this". 
Again, any moment of process will be internally related with 
my finite centre and thus, in that sense, any "this will also 
be mine". 

It is in Bradley's explanation of his second point here that 
we have an account of the sense in which the "this" affords 
us some intimation of the character of the Absolute. Ultimate 
reality is not self- transcendent; for it is not relational. The 
Absolute, that is to say, is self-identical: it is not mediated, 
or in process in any sense of the term. Now "the 'this' 
possesses to some extent the same wholeness of character. 
Both the 'this' and reality, we may say, are immediate". 
Yet whereas the Absolute is above relations and wholly 
self-identical, the this is immediate "because it is at a level 
below distinctions", 198 ' 199 and not absolutely immediate. 
For the "this" is the aspect of undiscriminating feeling(which 
is the felt immediacy of any moment of sentient process. 
As undiscriminating, such feeling exhibits no differentiations 

74 



The General Nature of Reality 

within itself; it is almost mere sentience; it is the freshness 
or the apathy or the dullness or the vivacity, and so on, of 
an experience. Yet the "this", though it be the undiscrim- 
inating feeling tone of any experience, is not itself undis- 
criminated. And in being discriminated, however slightly, 
the this is differentiated, and so it is relational. 

Again, if within the immediate feeling that is a this there 
be a tendency toward discrimination, and so toward internal 
differentiation, still such a "this" remains below the level 
of fully explicit differentiation. As thus at a level in process 
below that of explicit distinctions, the "this" is such that 
"Its elements are but conjoined, and are not connected. 
And its content, hence, is unstable, and essentially tends to 
disruption, and by its own nature must pass beyond the 
being of the e this s . But every 'this' still shows a passing aspect 
of undivided singleness. In the mental background specially 
such a fused unity remains a constant factor, and can never 
be dissipated." 199 Although the "this" is never absolutely 
stable, and tends to pass over into differentiation, still at the 
same time no "this" fails to present a momentary aspect of 
undivided unity. And it is in this momentary phase of 
undifferentiated unity which any momentjbf experience, 
no matter how elaborate, will bear with it, that we have our 
intimation of the character of the absolute whole. That is 
why "The 'this 5 is real for us in a sense in which nothing 
else is real". 198 For the "this", though never absolutely 
stable, and still relational in virtue of its differentiations 
from all else, is more nearly absolute in its identity than is 
anything else to be found in process. 

Yet if we take the "this" less narrowly, and in something 
of its context, we find that the phase of passing unity, which 
is its content, may be but fugitive. For "this" excludes 
"that"; and this exclusion may not be an external relation. 
Hence we see that the "this", taken negatively or as exclud- 
ing a "that", is relational and therefore not ultimate. But if 

75 



Bradley's Dialectic 

we take the "this" quite narrowly and as no more than a bare 
moment of immediacy, then the "this" excludes nothing and 
is merely positive. "We have found that the 'this', taken as 
exclusive, proclaims itself relative, and in that relation for- 
feits independence. And we have seen that, as positive, the 
'this' is not exclusive at all. The 'this 5 is inconsistent always, 
but so far as it excludes, so far already has it begun internally 
to suffer dissipation." 203 The "this" is always inconsistent 
because, like any other quality in process, it is at once imme- 
diate and self- transcendent: yet taken as it occurs in process, 
and so with its differentiations, the "this" is relational. 
Again, as sheer immediacy, the "this", Bradley holds, is 
without content. For content implies distinction; 203 and, 
within utter immediacy, there are no distinctions at all. 

Even so, it may be urged, the "this" is surely something 
more than the content of a moment of process. For any such 
content may be this content and mine; so that there is no 
specific content that is proper and peculiar to the "this" 
and the "mine". "In the 'this 5 . . . there is something 
more than content. For by combining qualities indefinitely 
we seem unable to arrive at the 'this 5 . The same difficulty 
may be stated perhaps in a way which points to its solution. 
The 'this 5 on one hand, we may say, is nothing at all beside 
content, and on the other hand the 'this 5 is not content 
at all. For in the term 'content 5 there lies an ambiguity. It 
may mean a what that is, or again is not, distinct from 
its 'that'. And the 'this 5 , we have already seen, has incon- 
sistent aspects. It offers, from one aspect, an immediate 
undivided experience, a whole in which 'that 5 and 'what' 
are felt as one. And here content, as implying distinction, 
will be absent from the 'this 5 . " 203 Within a whole devoid 
of distinctions, plainly there may be no distinct content that 
might be proper and peculiar to the "this 55 . Thus, in an 
immediate undivided experience there will be a passing 
aspect of singleness, in virtue of the undifferentiated charac- 



The General Nature of Reality 

ter of the immediacy thus presented. Within this undivided 
aspect there are no distinctions; for it is internally undifferen- 
tiated,ythe bare immediacy in question exhibits no differen- 
tiations within itself; and so it offers no distinct content which 
might belong to the "this". Yet any such utter immediacy 
may be this immediacy and mine; and so we notice that the 
"this" designates no content proper and peculiar to itself. 
"If, on the other hand, we use content generally, and if 
we employ it in the sense of 'what' without distinction from 
'that' if we take it to mean something which is experi- 
enced then, most emphatically the 'this' is not anything 
but content." 203 In this content, taken as in no wise trans- 
cending itself, there will be no distinction between what 
the content is and the fact that the content is this somewhat. 
So taken, this content will be immediate. In the sense that 
this content, so taken, is in no wise distinct from this same 
content, the "this" is nothing other than content. 

In short, there is no sense of the term "this" in which it 
designates a content proper and peculiar to itself. If this 
content be taken in point of its immediacy, then there are 
to be found within that immediacy no distinctions whatever. 
And this is to say that the content, so taken, exhibits nothing 
that could be proper and peculiar to the "this", other than 
the single content itself. Yet we have noticed that any content 
may be this content, and that this content may be any con- 
tent. There is, and could be, no content which would be the 
proper and peculiar referent of the term "this". "If we are 
asked what content is appropriated by the 'this', we may 
reply that there is none. There is no inalienable/content 
which belongs to the 'this' or the 'mine'." 206 The term 
"this" is not the proper name of any quality or relation. It has 
no proper and peculiar connotation of its own. And in every 
case of its use, the significance of the term "this" derives 
from the connotation of its context. The context will describe 
a content, and will describe it as being partially, at least 

77 



Bradley's Dialectic 

immediate. In so far, then, as the context conveys the felt 
immediacy of the content, the "this" is significant of that 
immediacy. Yet, since such a content in its felt immediacy 
may be any content, there is no inalienable content which 
belongs to the "this" or the "mine". No content is proper 
and peculiar to the "this", simply because any content may 
be this content. "We have found that, in a sense, the 'this' 
is not, and does not own, content. But, in another sense, 
we have seen that it contains, and is, nothing else." 206 If 
/it be undeniable that the referent of the term "this" may be 
no matter what, then the referent of the term^rhis" may not 
be something distinct from any content; something which 
as distinct, would belong only to the "this"; and so the 
referent of the term "this" is nothing else than content, or 
just any content in its felt immediacy. 

Were the "this" and the "mine" not exclusive of the 
"that" and the "yours", it might be urged that they are 
real in isolation from all else. To be sure Bradley writes of the 
"this" and the "mine" as being below the level of relations. 
But to be below the level of distinctions is not to be by that 
very fact unrelated altogether. Within the aspect of the 
"this" that is its bare immediacy, there are no distinctions, 
and, therefore, no relations. Yet the question, it may be 
urged, is how this aspect which, within itself, is below the 
level of relations, is related to the content of which it is 
a passing aspect ? And the answer here could only be that it 
is by virtue of the difference of this aspect from the rest 
of the content that the aspect is related to or continuous 
with the content. For within itself the aspect is devoid of 
relations: so taken it is immediate, and thus different from 
what of the content is relational. And by virtue of that 
difference, the passing aspect of immediacy is continuous 
with its content. 

Moreover, to point out that the "this" is below the level 
of relations is not to say that the "this" is relationless, "An 

78 



The General Nature of Reality 

immediate experience, viewed as positive, is so far not 
exclusive. It is, so far, what it is, and it does not repel any- 
thing. But the 'this' certainly is used also with a negative 
bearing. It may mean 'this one', in distinction from that 
one and the other one. And here it shows obviously an ex- 
clusive/aspect, and it implies an external and negative 
relation." But every such relation, we have found, is incon- 
sistent with itself (chapter III). For it exists within, and by 
virtue of an embracing unity, and apart from that totality 
both itself and its terms would be nothing. And the relation 
also must penetrate the inner being of its terms. " 'This', in 
other words, would not exclude 'that', unless in the exclusion 
'this', so far, passed out of itself. Its repulsion of others is thus 
incompatible with self-contained singleness, and involves 
subordination to an including whole. But to the ultimate 
whole nothing can be opposed, or even related." 201 The 
contrariety in all process is presented in its most immediate 
and crucial form in the "this" and the "mine". As positive, 
the "this" is unmediated within itself. Yet, that it may be 
"this" rather than "that", a "this" must be different from 
a "that". By virtue of that difference a "this" will transcend 
itself. And that self-transcendence, which is the very process 
of becoming, is not consistent with the positive immediacy 
of the "this". For as positive, "It is, so far, what it is, and it 
does not repel anything." 201 Yet any "this", while yc is 
immediate, is also relational; it is at once both itself[and 
self-transcendent in virtue of the very differentiation by 
which its immediacy is this immediacy and not that one. 
Thus we may come to see that even immediate experience 
is related within the systematic whole of sentience that is the 
content of Reality, and of whose Absolute immediacy the 
"this" affords us an intimation. 

The other source of our knowledge of the absolute, which 
Bradley mentions, is that of the relational character of 
experience. "And, again, the relational form, as we saw, 

79 



Bradley's Dialectic 

pointed everywhere to a unity. It implies a substantial 
totality beyond relations and above them, a whole endeavour- 
ing without success to realize itself in their detail." 141 The 
sense, if any, in which the internality of relations may imply 
a whole that would be different from, and over and above, 
the system of internally related qualities itself, remains to be 
seen. Yet, whether or not the internality of qualities and 
relations leads to an Absolute whose identity is not relational, 
it does supply the nexus in virtue of which we may know that 
the relational way of thought, though it be never more than 
an ineluctable compromise, is always thinking what is some 
degree or other of reality. 



80 



CHAPTER IV 



The Internality of Thought 
and Reality 



AT the outset of his elucidation of how thought and reality 
are related, Bradley distinguished between the "what" 
and the "that"; and this distinction is fundamental for his 
theory of how it is that we know the real. "If we take up 
anything considered real, no matter what it is, we find in 
it two aspects. . . . There is a 'what' and a 'that', an 
existence and a content, and the two are inseparable." 143 1 
We can say of anything we choose to consider both that it 
is and what it is; where the "that" marks the existence of the 
what, and the "what" refers to the quality or character of 
that existent. These two aspects of anything are distinct and 
distinguishable, but they are not separate or separable. 
A bare existent: one that were without a character or content 
of any sort: would be nothing at all. Again, a content that 
were without character of any sort would be nothing at all. 
Again, a content that were not that content, or this content, 
would be nothing distinct from anything else, and so it 
would be nothing at all. 

Yet, in the process of thinking, a "what" will be differen- 
tiated from its "that". "For thought is clearly, to some extent 
at least, ideal. Without an idea there is no thinking, and an 
idea implies the separation of content from existence. It is a 
what which, so far as it is a mere idea, clearly is not, and if 
it also were, could, so far, not be called ideal. For ideality 
lies in the disjoining of quality from being." 142 ' 143 This tells 
us what Bradley means by the "ideality of the finite". 

81 F 



Bradley's Dialectic 

Thinking is ideal in that the content of thought will be a 
"what" partially prescinded from its "that". This abstrac- 
tion may in no case be more than partial. For if a what were 
wholly abstract and quite independent of any context of 
relations whatever, it would be differentiated by nothing, 
and so "it" would be nothing at all. "If we try to get the 
'what' by itself, we find at once that it is not alJL/It points 
to something beyond and cannot exist by itself and as a bare 
adjective. Neither of these aspects, if you isolate it, can be 
taken as real, or indeed in that case is itself any longer. 
They are distinguishable only and are not divisible." 142 
As we abstract, we progressively alter the relations in which 
the content initially stood. A "what" which were quite 
prescinded from its "that" would be a content cut off from 
all relations. Any such what would be a "floating idea"; a 
something that were external to the internality of relations. 
We have seen above the reasons why nothing real may be 
external to all relations. Without relations, "it" would not 
be differentiated from anything and so "it" would be 
nothing at all. The "what" and the "that" are distinguish- 
able, not separable. 

Bradley warns us against the error of taking it that the 
ideal may be mere psychical fact, such as an image or a 
sense-perception. Since the ideal consists of a "what" which 
is partially transcending its "that," "the common view which 
identifies image and idea is fundamentally in error. For an 
image is a fact, just as real as any sensation; it is merely a 
fact of another kind and it is not one whit more ideal. But 
an idea is any part of the content of a fact, so far as that works 
out of immediate unity with its existence. And an idea's 
factual existence may consist in a sensation or perception, 
just as in an image. The main point and the essence is that 
some features in the 'what' of a given fact should be alienated 
from its/ c that' so far as to work beyond it, or at all events 
loose from it. Such a movement is ideality, and, where it is 

82 



The Internality of Thought and Reality 

absent, there is nothing ideal. " 14 ^/The psychical fact that is 
an image of imagination, is a fact which is no more ideal 
than is the psychical fact that is a sense perception. It is in 
the movement by which moments of sentience are in processes 
of differentiation, or self-transcendence, that ideality con- 
sists. The ideality of the finite, or the partial transcendence 
of a "that" by its "what", is in no respect different from the 
process of the internality of relations. 

We have noticed that the "what", or the character of a 
quality, inevitably transcends itself in and through the very 
differentiation, or relation, by virtue of which it is that 
quality, and not a different one. Likewise, any differentia- 
tion, or relation, will transcend itself in so far as what falls 
between the qualities thus differentiated is internal to, or 
in and of the terms thus related by that "what". Thfs move- 
ment of self-transcendence is everywhere the nature of 
process. In the "this" and the "mine" self-transcendence is 
but incipient, to be sure; yet, as we noticed above, it is there 
present. And in explicit thinking the ideality of the content 
is realized to a discriminable degree. This ideality of the 
finite is the very same as the self-transcendence of moments 
of process or Appearance. This self-transcendence of content 
arises by virtue of the incessant internal differentiation, or 
relation of moments of Appearance. 

In the moment of differentiation that is thought, as dis- 
tinguished from judgement, we have no more than the 
partial transcendence of a "that" by its "what", without 
the consummation of the reference of this "what" to a 
"that" which lies beyond the context from which that 
"what" is passing. With the consummation of that process, 
we have judgement, which is "thought in its completed 
form". And in considering the nature of judgement, we may 
see more fully why it is that no psychicaHact is an idea. 
"We can understand this most clearly if we consider the 
nature of judgement, for there we find thought in its com- 

83 



Bradley's Dialectic 

pleted form. In judgement an idea is predicated of a reality. 
Now, in the first place, what is predicated is not a mental 
image. It is not a fact inside my head which the judgement 
wishes to attach to another fact outside. The predicate is a 
mere 'what', a mere feature of content, which is used to 
qualify further the 'that' of the subject. And this predicate 
is divorced from its psychical existence in my head, and is 
used without any regard to its being there. When I say 'this 
horse is a mammal', it is surely absurd to suppose that I am 
harnessing my mental state to the beast between the shafts. 
Judgement adds an adjective to reality, and this adjective 
is an idea, because it is a quality made loose from its own 
existence, and is working free from its implication with that. 
And, even when a fact is merely analysed when the 
predicate i appears not to go beyond its own subject, or to 
have been imported divorced from another fact outside 
our account still holds good. For here obviously our syn- 
thesis is a re-union of the distinguished, and it implies a 
separation, which, though it is over-ridden, is never un- 
made. The predicate is a content which has been made loose 
from its own immediate existence and is used in divorce from 
that first unity." 144 In a judgement, the "what" which is its 
content, exists not in a stage of mere self-transcendence 
referring to a subject beyond itself. Rather, the "what" of 
a judgement exists as referred to a subject. This is to say 
that the moment of mediation or self-transcendence or 
relation that is thinking, is, in judgement, fully referred 
to the subject which, in and through that judgement, this 
thinking comes to qualify. Thus the initial partial estrange- 
ment of the "what" from its "that" is healed in the union 
of that "what" with the further psychical fact which is the 
proximate subject of the thought thus completed in judge- 
ment. "Judgement is essentially the re-union of two sides, 
'what' and 'that', provisionally estranged. But it is the 
alienation of these aspects in which thought's ideality con- 



The Internality of Thought and Reality 

sists." 176 In the re-union of "what" and "that," however, 
the what need not be re-united with the very same psychical 
fact from which initially it was estranged. For the whati 
may be referred to, and finally joined with, new psychical 
fact which would be quite different from the old. 

Indeed, once it be considered that any case of the ideality 
of thought is a case of the self-transcendence that is of the 
essence of the internality of relations, it is then difficult to 
see how the reunion that is judgement could be a mere 
repetition of the psychical fact in which the content of the 
judgement had its origins. For the "what", in passing beyond 
its "that", is altering its context of relations. This is to say 
that the "relations", by which the what is differentiated, 
are being altered. And in any alteration of its relations the 
"what" itself is being altered. Therefore, the "what" that is 
re-united in judgement may not be qualitatively identical 
with what it was at the inception of the moment of ideality; 
nor, for that matter, at any stage in the course of the passing 
of that moment of thinking over into the fulfilment of it in 
judgement. It would seem, then, that both the "what" which 
is re-united in judgement and the relational context of this 
consummation could only be different from the initial "what" 
and its "that". Indeed, since identity implies qualitative as 
distinguished from numerical difference, a mere repetition 
of content would be impossible. 

The sharpness of the contrast drawn by Bradley between 
the ideality of self-transcendence, and the comparative 
inanition of psychical fact, might suggest that most psychical 
fact is congealed sentience, barely alive. Worse still, the 
suggestion might be conveyed that the ideal is a light that 
never was on sea or land, except as a sort of aura diffused 
here and there on earth by precious minds. This sort of 
misunderstanding of the matter Bradley takes up as "a 
most important point". "There exists a notion that ideality 
is something outside of facts, something imported into them, 

85 



Bradley's Dialectic 

or imposed as a sort of layer above them; and we talk as if 
facts, when let alone, were in no sense ideal. But any such 
notion is illusory. For facts which are not ideal, and which 
show no looseness of content from existence, seem hardly 
actual. They would be found, if anywhere, in feelings 
without internal lapse, and with a content wholly single." 146 
Within a content without internal lapse there would be no 
differentiations. Hence there would be within it no relations, 
no process of fission through which it would transcend itself. 
Any such content would be hardly actual; it would be this 
content and mine, but at a level of sentience almost below 
that of discrimination. 

Nevertheless, and no matter how lethargic any such 
moment of sentience might be within itself, it would be 
that lethargic moment and different from all else. Although 
barely actual or definite, or hardly explicit, that content 
would differ from its relational context. To that extent 
it would be ideal. And any moment of sentience, however 
lethargic and smug, will be a different moment. Hence any 
content, even though it be almost devoid of differentiation 
within itself as immediacy or quality, still will be incipient 
with change. For it will be the quality it is by virtue of its 
relations. These will be neither lethargic nor smug, but 
actively alive. As those relations change, the content they 
differentiate will change also. 

This much is true of any content or fact. That is why 
any fact, however subliminal and undifferentiated within the 
immediacy of it, nevertheless is in change and so in a refer- 
ence beyond itself that is incipient at least. 

Hence Bradley continues with the text quoted above as 
follows: "But if we keep to fact which is given, this changes 
in our hands, and it compels us to perceive inconsistency of 
content. And then this content cannot be referred merely 
to its given 'that', but is forced beyond it, and is made to* 
qualify something outside. But, if so, in the simplest change 

86 



The Internality of Thought and Reality 

we have at once ideality the use of content in separation 
from its actual existence." 146 There is ideality in the simplest 
change because any change in any content ipso factcTis a 
changeTn the relations which differentiate it, and by which 
it transcends itself. The change that is this self-transcen- 
dence is ideal, for the ideality of the finite consists in the 
self-transcendence of psychical fact. And this transcendence 
consists in the process of relational becoming that is Appear- 
ance. Through that self-transcendence the content of a 
psychical fact comes to be referred beyond its "that". "For 
the content of the given is for ever relative to something 
not given, and the nature of its 'what' is hence essentially 
to transcend its 'that'. This we may call the ideality of the 
given finite. It is not manufactured by thought, but thought 
itself is its development and product. The essential nature of 
the finite is that everywhere, as it presents itself, its character 
should slide beyond the limits of its existence." 146 Such is 
the character of the finite because everywhere and always 
the finite is relational and in process: it is Appearance. The 
ideality of the finite is anything but intellectual and factitious; 
rather it is the very nature of the incessant fission in sentience 
which issues in the self-transcendence of psychical fact that 
is thought. Hence the sense in which thought is thought, the 
sense in which thought is ideal, and the sense in which the 
internality of relations is in process, are all one and the same. 
Having thus explained briefly the sense in which thought 
is properly said to be ideal, and how it is that thinking is 
completed in judgement, Bradley now proceeds to indicate 
what is for him the nature of truth. "Truth is the predication 
of such content as, when predicated, is harmonious, and 
removes inconsistency and with it unrest. And because the 
given reality is never consistent, thought is compelled to 
take the road of immediate expansion. If thought were 
successful, it would have a predicate consistent in itself and 
agreeing entirely with the subject. But, on the other hand, 

87 



Bradley's Dialectic 

the predicate must be always ideal. It must, that is, be a 
'what' not in unity with its own 'that', and therefore, in and 
by itself, devoid of existence. Hence, so far as in thought 
this alienation is not made good, thought can never be more 
than merely ideal." The truth attainable by thought, and 
attained in judgement, may not be absolute. Thought and 
judgement are ineluctably relational. A thought, that is, 
to be non-relational or^absolute, would require "a pre- 
dicate consistent in itself and agreeing entirely with the 
subject". Such a thought would be a tautology; for the 
predicate A would "agree entirely with," i.e. would repeat, 
the subject A. And such a thought would be intrinsically 
tautologous. For A p , in being itself absolutely, would be 
intrinsically individuated; and thus would be true also of A s . 
Therefore A p and A s would be no more than numerically, 
or enumerably, different from each other. Numerical 
difference would be a merely external relation, and any such 
notion is excluded by the internality of relations. 

Thus thought may not choose to be tautological: it is 
ineluctably relational; which is to say that in thought 
"the predicate must be always ideal". What is predicated 
in a process of thinking may be only a "what" which is in the 
process of self-transcendence. This process of self-transcend- 
ence is the very process of predication which is completed 
in the re-union of the "what" with a new "that". Without 
this fact of self-transcendence, there would be no process in 
sentience at most there would be only changeless states of 
feeling in succession. Indeed, within any such changeless 
sentience, there would hardly be even a plurality of states. 
For as changeless, sentience could not become differentiated 
at all, and so it would remain everywhere and always 
homogeneous and undifferentiated. No such sentience could 
give rise to so much as a vague question about itself, much 
less a thought, or a judgement. For in being altogether 
unmediated, such sentience could only be undifFerentiated, 

88 



The Internality of Thought and Reality 

or relationless, and hence mere psychical fact devoid of 
all thought. 

In the absence of all becoming or self-transcendence, there 
could be no thinking, but only mere psychical fact. But 
change is an experience whose actuality can hardly be 
questioned. Where there is change at all there is differentia- 
tion and thus "inconsistency of content," or self-transceh- 
dence. And the "what" which thus is transcending its 
"that" "cannot be referred merely to its given 'that' but is 
forced beyond it, and is made to qualify something outside." 
And that is why it is that "in the simplest change we have 
ideality "; for within no matter what sort of change there will 
be differentiation, and we have noticed that in any quality 
or relation there is self-transcendence. Indeed, self-tran- 
scendence is but another name for the relational character 
of appearance. Qualities transcend themselves as qualities 
in so far as they are related: relations likewise transcend 
themselves as relations in so far as they contribute to con- 
stitute their qualities. 

Yet, no matter how elaborate the origins of a thought, 
and no matter how comprehensive and self-consistent the 
resulting judgement may be, this judgement will fall short of 
absolute truth. "For the content of the given is for ever 
relative to something not given, and the nature of its 'what' 
is hence essentially to transcend its 'that'. This we may call 
the ideality of the finite. It is not manufactured by thought, 
but thought itself is its development and product. The 
essential nature of the finite is that everywhere, as it 
presents itself, its character should slide beyond the limits of 
its existence." 146 Even so, it may be asked, why is thought 
not able through the internality of relations to arrive at the 
positive nature of the Absolute? For the internality of rela- 
tions is the very being in process of thought and of judgement. 
And to this the answer is again the same in principle. 

Absolute knowledge of the Absolute would be either (i) a 



Bradley 's Dialectic 

knowledge that were related to, and by virtue of that very 
relation, differentiated from the object known, or (2) this 
knowledge would be not relational at all, but rather identical 
with what thus would be known. On the first alternative 
the knowledge in question still would be relational and 
therefore not absolute knowledge. Moreover, were anything 
whatever held to be related to or with the Absolute, that 
Being itself would forthwith become relational, and thus it 
would cease to be Absolute. 

On the second alternative, the knowledge in question 
would be one with its object. Such alleged knowledge 
would consist of a judgement in which the subject and the 
predicate were qualitatively identical. And this tautology 
would be the suicide of thought and judgement. ' ' If_ there 
is no judgement, there is no thought; and if there is no 
difference, there is no judgement, nor any self-consciousness. 
But if, on the other hand, there is a difference, then the 
subject is beyond the predicated content." Were there no 
differences anywhere in sentience, there could be no self- 
consciousness and no thinking; for all would be one and 
homogeneous. And this differentiation which is the 
self-transcendence of process must be a difference between 
qualities: it may not be the mere numerical difference of 
two qualitatively identical items. For such items would be 
self-identical, and therefore changeless. The differentiation 
or self-transcendence which is the active nerve of thinking 
and judging must be qualitative. Consequently and inevit- 
ably in thought and in judgement there will be a difference 
between the subject of thinking and what is predicated of 
that subject in the completed judgement. An absolute, or 
non-relational, judgement is a tautology; and in the bare 
repetition of tautology we have the suicide of judgement. 

In whatever form we may have sentience, it will be in 
becoming; differentiations will be breaking out within it, 
and the qualities thus emerging will be related by those very 

90 



The Internality of Thought and Reality 

differentiations. Qualities as qualities, we have seen, are the 
moments of immediacy in sentient process. And relations 
are the moments of differentiation in that process. The 
self-transcendence of quality by relation is the ideality of 
thought and the content of judgement. It is because thought 
and judgement are thus essentially relational that, no matter 
how comprehensive and internally coherent a judgement 
may become, it can only fall short of being absolutely 
self-coherent. "Thought is relational and discursive, and, 
if it ceases to be this, it commits suicide; and yet, if it remains 
thus, how does it contain^immediate presentation?" 150 The 
conclusion to which we are driven is that if, by "immediate 
presentation", we mean something absolute in its own right, 
then thought neither contains nor attains immediate presen- 
tation. The immediacy of the "this" and the "mine" is, we 
have noticed, at once immediate and relational, thus 
illustrating in an acute form the essential incoherence of 
any partial whole of quality and relation. Any whole in 
judgement, however elaborate and comparatively self- 
coherent, will still fall short of the absolutely self-coherent 
Individual. Yet, again it may be urged, "A harmonious 
system of content predicating itself, a subject self-conscious 
in that system of content, this is what thought should 
mean." 150 But this system would be simply the systematic 
whole of internal relations. For, since that whole would be 
sentience, it would be a systematic whole conscious of itself. 
Yet, here again, no advance has been made. What is 
conscious "of" the content of the systematic whole either 
is somehow different from that content, or it is not different 
from it. The first alternative gives us self-consciousness, 
but it gives it to us as the feding of a systematic whole from 
which that feeling remains distinct; and, so far, excluded 
from that whole. The second alternative gives us no self- 
consciousness at all no consciousness, that is to say, distinct 
from that of the systematic whole of sentience itself. 



Bradley's Dialectic 

Though any attempt to exhibit the positive character of 
the Absolute in and through thought be fore-doomed to 
failure by the essentially relational nature of judgement, 
still the theory of predication which Bradley presents in 
Note A affords another clue to the function of the Absolute 
in judgement, and so in Appearance itself. If, in thinking, 
we would have more than a mere association of ideas, there 
must be in some sense the assertion of "unity in diversity." 
Differences in no sense united are merely different; and, on 
the other hand, it is an old story that the formula of thought 
may not be "A is A". Yet the requirement that thought 
must unite differences is not an easy one to fulfil. If the 
formula for significant thinking may not be A is A, neither 
may it be A is Y. For here the predicate Y, being different 
from A, is not A. Since this would be to assert and to deny 
in the same thought, the process of uniting differences in 
judgement may not be expressed in the form "A is Y". 

The alternative that, in thinking A is Y, we are really 
meaning "A has Y", is of no avail. For either "A has Y" 
means no more than "A is A and has Y", where the "has" 
expresses bare conjunction; or "A has Y" means that "A 
is-such-as-to-have Y". On the first alternative the connec- 
tion of Y with A remains unexplained; on the second, the 
copula is again introduced, and the original dilemma 
remains. The one possible method of resolving this dilemma, 
Bradley concludes, is afforded by the notion of identity in 
difference. Judgements uniting differences are themselves 
adjectives of Reality, which is a systematic Whole. The 
absolute identity of this Whole is the ultimate identity in all 
differences. Hence, it is ultimately in virtue of this identity 
that A and Y are united in thought. 

In the statement of a judgement the subject will be 
grammatically distinct from the predicate. But nothing in 
judgement itself corresponds to this grammatical distinction. 
For both of the terms which contribute to constitute a 

92 



The Internality of Thought and Reality 

judgement are adjectival. This means that the subject and 
predicate terms are alike in qualifying a reality which lies 
beyond those constituents of the judgement itself. Nor may 
it be otherwise within the internality of relations. For the 
two terms in question will be related in virtue of their 
qualitative difference. Again, in virtue of their difference 
from their proximate subject that to which they initially 
refer they are related with that subject of their reference. 
And their reference, or their being referred to that proximate 
subject, will consist in the very differentiations by which those 
terms are related to that subject. Moreover, the respective 
identities of those terms imply their differences from, and 
so their relations to, all else. This is true also of the identity 
of the relational situation which is their proximate subject. 
Thus the ultimate subject of reality is the absolute identity 
of the systematic whole. It is to this, ultimately, that every 
judgement refers. Nor can there be any mystery as to the 
nature of that reference. For it is in virtue of the internality 
of the relations of its contents to all else, that the final 
subject of any judgement is ultimate Reality. 

Thus we may see that on any view of the nature of 
relations that is cognate with that of Bradley, the question, 
what is the nature of the relation between thought and 
reality? would be a meaningless question. It would be 
meaningless because there is and could be no single or 
unique relation that were "the relation" between thought and 
reality. The object of thought is not in any sense independent 
of what is thought. With Bradley's dialectic of relations in 
mind, the internality of thought and reality will be plain 
enough. For the content of any judgement, in virtue of its 
difference from its proximate subject, is related with that 
subject. And the proximate subject, with that related content, 
likewise are related within and to the whole of the systematic 
whole that is Appearance. 



93 



CHAPTER V 



The Coherence Theory of 
Truth and Reality 



BRADLEY deals with the problem of error on his way to his 
theory of truth, and we shall examine his theory of error as a 
preface to the main topic of this, chapter. "Error is without 
any question a dangerous subject, and the chief difficulty is i 
as follows: We cannot, on the one hand, accept anything 
between non-existence and reality, while, on the other hand, 
error obstinately refuses to be either. It persistently attempts; 
to maintain a third position, which appears nowhere to) 
exist, and yet somehow is occupied. In false appearance 
there is something attributed to the real which does not 
belong to it. But if the appearance is not real, then it is 
not false appearance, because it is nothing. On the other 
hand, if it is false, it must therefore be true reality, for it is 
something which is. And this dilemma at first sight seems 
insoluble." 164 ' 165 

Error, it would seem, must be real in some sense: yet an 
error neither may belong to the Absolute, nor may it 
qualify, nor contribute to constitute any erroneous judge- 
ment; for all judgements^are m and of the Real. Yet it is 
being erroneous That is the defining characteristic of the 
erroneous judgement. Thus it would seem that error both 
must be, and yet may not be real. 

Accordingly, the two main questions with which Bradley 
is here concerned are (i) why error may not be real, and 
(2) the sense in which error is (as it must be) real. 166 Error "is 
at any rate one kind of false appearance. Now appearance is 

94 



The Coherence Theory of Truth and Reality 

content not at one with its existence, a 'what 5 loosened from 
its 'that 5 ." 168 And, "appearance will be truth when a 
content, made alien to its own being, is related to some fact 
which accepts its qualification. The true idea is appearance 
in respect of its own being as fact and event, but is reality 
in connection with other being which it qualifies. 55166 As 
ideal, a true idea is an appearance in that the ideality of the 
finite is the process of self- transcendence that is Appearance. 
But a true idea, as a content of completed thinking or 
judgement, is real to the degree to which it coheres with the 
proximate subject that it qualifies. "Error, on the other hand, 
is content made loose from its own reality, and related to a 
reality with which it is discrepant. It is the rejection of an 
idea by existence which is not the existence of the idea as 
made loose. It is the repulse by a substantive of a liberated 
adjective.' 5166 And in a footnote to v this passage, Bradley 
adds that "whether the adjective has been liberated from 
this substantive or from another makes no difference 55 . 
An erroneous judgement will be one whose content is, to a 
degree, incoherent with the proximate subject to which that 
content is referred. 

But this is not to be taken to mean that the content qua 
content is erroneous. To be sure, the identity of the content 
is relational, and so the content itself will illustrate the 
comparative incoherence of any relational reality. Yet this 
comparative incoherence is not error. Nor will error result 
before judgement is attempted and completed. For it is in 
the predication of a content which is not compatible with 
its proximate subject that error exists. Thus it is not the 
relational incoherence or self-discrepancy of the content 
itself that is error; rather it is the failure of the content 
predicated of the proximate subject to cohere (to any but a 
slight degree) with the subject it is judged to qualify. 

The proximate subject, S, will be a certain relational 
situation. As such it will be a relational concretion having a 

95 



Bradley's Dialectic 

certain character, which will be different from that of any 
other relational situation. Now predicate A, let us say, will 
be more fully coherent with the character of S than will 
predicate Z. This is to say that all the differentiations by 
which A is related with S are indefinitely more elaborate 
than are those by which Z is thus related. That being the 
case, the predication of A of S would result in a judgement 
whose content were elaborately relevant to, and therefore 
coherent with, the subject thus qualified. Such a judgement 
would be true to a high degree. If, on the contrary, predicate 
Z were predicated of S, then there would be but little 
coherence of that predicate with the subject of the judgement. 
To be sure Z could not be out of all relation to S; for nothing 
may be quite external to anything else. But Z has so little 
bearing on (i.e. so few, or such tenuous relations with) S, 
that the character of S repels Z when it is judged to qualify 
S with a relevance of which Z is not capable in that 
connection. 

Lest the meaning of the term "relevance" here seem to be 
in need of a definition which, it may seem, could only be 
circular, it may be well to take up that point before going 
on. The term "relevant", it may be urged, is not definable 
without circularity; for any definition offered would have 
to be relevant. The force of this objection is specious, on 
Bradley's theory of appearance and reality.* For the relevant 
is the internally related. All appearances are internally 
related: hence Bosanquet's dictum, "all is relevant to all". 
Nor does this bi-verbal definition beg the question. For by 
this definition the meaning of "relevance" is simply identified 
with that of the internality of relations; and (as is even 
obvious) the meaning of that doctrine is not thus called in 
question. 

In an erroneous judgement, some content or other is 

* It is also specious on other grounds that need not be entered into 
in this connection. 

96 



The Coherence Theory of Truth and Reality 

alleged to be relevant to a subject in respects in which that 
content is not thus relevant. " Suppose that when William 
has been hung, I assert that it was John. My assertion will 
then be false, because William is certain. And if so, then after 
all my error surely will consist in giving to the real a self- 
discrepant content. For otherwise, when John is suggested, 
I could not reject the idea." 163 Here the error lies in the 
discrepancy between the relevance of the living character 
of John and the nature of William's being hung. And 
taking the judgement as being completed in its alleged 
reference* to its subject, this discrepancy between the 
adjective and substantive terms of the judgemental situation 
will be the self-discrepancy of the judgement, taken as the 
total situation. It is this discrepancy between asserted 
relevance, and the actual substantive situation, that is at 
once error in judgement and, seemingly, a flat inconsistency 
in monistic theory. 

Turning to the "second main problem of the chapter", 169 
that "about the relation of error to the Absolute", 169 
Bradley gives the following statement of the matter to be 
explained: "There is no way but in accepting the whole 
mass of fact, and in then attempting to correct it and make 
it good. Error is truth, it is partial truth that is false only 
because partial and left incomplete. The Absolute has 
without subtraction all those qualities, and it has every 
arrangement which we seem to confer upon it by our mere 
mistake. The only mistake lies in our failure to give also the 
complement. The reality owns the discordance and the 
discrepancy of false appearance; but it possesses also much 
else in which this jarring character is swallowed up and is 
dissolved in fuller harmony. I do not mean that by a mere 
re-arrangement of the matter which is given to us, we could 
remove its contradictions. For, being limited, we cannot 
apprehend all the details of the whole. And we must remem- 

* Where the term "reference" means what is meant by "relevance". 

97 o 



Bradley's Dialectic 

her that every old arrangement, condemned as erroneous, 
itself forms part of that detail. To know all the elements of 
the universe, with all the conjunctions of those elements, 
good and bad, is impossible for finite minds. And hence 
obviously we are unable throughout to reconstruct our 
discrepancies. But we can comprehend in general what we 
cannot see exhibited in detail." 169 ' 17 The statement that 
"error is truth" may seem merely paradoxical; yet it 
expresses literally a part of Bradley's theory of error. 

We have noticed how error arises. When a content, Z, is 
almost irrelevant to S, and yet is asserted to qualify S, then 
we have error. This error is not a nature or form that is 
distinct from the internally related content which is the 
adjective, and the relational situation which is the sub- 
stantive, of the judgement. For the error will consist of the 
almost complete failure of the content Z to qualify S. And 
this failure is no nature or form of any sort. Rather it is 
almost complete irrelevance. 

Now, any case of relevance will be some case or other of 
the internality of relations realized in a judgement. This 
judgement will be an appearance; and it will be real to the 
degree to which it is self-coherent. But irrelevance, taken as 
utter irrelevance, has no referent anywhere in appearance 
or reality. The utterly irrelevant would be the non-relevant. 
This verbiage would have no bearing (beyond that of its 
existence as a verbal construction) within the internality of 
relations, and so it would have no logical bearing (as 
distinguished from a merely verbal ontological standing) 
at all. Thus, in so far as the content of an erroneous judge- 
ment is logical or coherent with the subject of that judgement, 
to that extent the judgement is true. The rest of it is verbiage. 
For whatever of a judgement is not true is irrelevant, and 
what is irrelevant may have no referent within the realm 
of the internality of relations. Short of the very best that 
Rimbaud, Peguy, and Stein have produced, there will be 

98 



The Coherence Theory of Truth and Reality 

no utter irrelevance, and so no absolute error. Failure in 
relevant qualification will usually be but partial: when 
utter meaninglessness is achieved, this will be utterly non- 
logical. Such achievements in the use of language, however, 
are very rare. Almost always the erroneous judgement will 
be more than irrelevant and merely verbal. However 
slightly, it will still qualify the real; and, to that degree, it 
will be, not the irrelevance that is mere error; rather, it will 
be true to a certain degree. 

By the emendation of its content, an erroneous judgement 
may be made less erroneous, or more coherent with its sub- 
ject, and so more true. Thus "error is truth, it is partial truth, 
that is false only because partial and left incomplete." 169 
As the truth of a judgement becomes less partial, less in- 
complete, the content of the judgement will be more 
fully related to the subject. The judgement will be the 
more relevant, or the more true. It is in this failure to be 
relevant that error lies, and that failure is nothing positive: 
it is not in any sense a quality or a relation. "The only 
mistake lies in our failure to give also the complement." 170 
For by any emendation of the original content of an 
erroneous judgement, the initial error is transcended. And 
by an emendation that were almost all-comprehensive, we 
would arrive at a judgement that were but slightly erroneous. 
But to accomplish so much as this would be practically 
impossible. "I do not mean that by a mere re-arrangement 
of the matter which is given to us, we could remove its 
contradictions." 170 Since our outlook is limited, we may not 
apprehend anything like all of the details of the systematic 
whole of internal relations. Moreover, as Bradley reminds us, 
we must not forget "that every old arrangement, condemned 
as erroneous, itself forms part of that detail." This brings 
us to the third and final one of the main topics of Bradley' s 
chapter on error. 

Up to this point, we have noticed that error lies in the 

99 



Bradley's Dialectic 

conflict between the relevance (or the internal relations) 
of a content predicated of a subject, and the character of 
the subject which repels the predication of that content. 
We have noticed also that, in so far as error is a failure in 
relevance and so is irrelevance, error is nothing real. An 
erroneous judgement is significant, and a judgement at all, 
only in so far as it is true. And by a progressive emendation 
of an erroneous judgement, the initial coherence of it with 
the real may be deepened and widened. Thus, so far, it 
would seem that error is merely negative, or unreal. "But 
our account, it will fairly be objected, is untenable because 
incomplete. For error is not merely negative." 172 Because the 
content, predicated as thoroughly relevant, fails to fulfil the 
intended predication. This failure is nothing real, to be sure. 
But the difference between Z (the jhredicate which is mainly 
irrelevant to S) and A (the predicate which is almost fully 
relevant to the character of S) is a relation. And this relation 
(this difference between Z and A), like any other relation, 
is not unreal. It constitutes the reason why it must be 
admitted that error is not merely negative. For though 
irrelevance is verbiage, still the difference between the 
predicate of a judgement that is largely irrelevant, and any 
other content that is relevant to the subject of that judge- 
ment, is real. 

Error is not a special sort of appearance; taken as a 
characteristic of some (and only some) judgements, error is 
unreal. Any judgement, in being less than wholly self- 
coherent, will be less than wholly true. Hence any judgement 
will be erroneous to a degree. 

But if error is no peculiar disease, amenable to a logical 
cordon sanitaire, none the less any error is real. The reality of 
it consists of the relations that are the differences between the 
predicate predicated by a judgement that is erroneous and 
the quality of the subject that repels that predicate. Those 
relations are as real as any others. And they may be any 

100 



The Coherence Theory of Truth and Reality 

relations whatever; not relations or differences of a peculiar 
sort. 

The relations that constitute the reality of an error are 
of no special brand; the difference between those relations 
as they contribute to constitute that judgement, rather than 
any other, is a difference of degree. For the difference 
between a judgement that is erroneous and one that is true 
is a difference not of kind. Any judgement is at once true 
and erroneous. A judgement that is more comprehensively 
self-coherent than not, is properly called true. A judgement 
that is more fully self-discrepant than coherent, is properly 
called an error. 

Far from being a peculiarity of some judgements only, 
error is of the nature of all judgements, to some degree or 
other. For a judgement is a relational situation, and the 
relational is everywhere and always self-discrepant: not 
absolutely, of course; that would be the blank of a pure 
negation; but self-discrepant to a degree. 

Error, then, is all-pervasive in appearance; for the self- 
discrepant reality of error consists of the degrees of self- 
discrepancy that are the differentiations in the process of 
becoming. Thus, in reality error is not different in kind from 
truth. An error is a judgement that is more comprehensively 
self-discrepant a judgement in which more contrarieties 
break out between the proximate subject and the predicate 
than our aspiration to self-coherence can tolerate. 

And the reality of any error itself is self-discrepant 
because, taken as degrees of contrariety, errors are not self- 
sufficient. Our aspiration to the attainment of complete 
self-coherence makes us discriminate between degrees of 
self-discrepancy and self-coherence. " Error is truth, it 
is partial truth, that is false only because partial and left 
incomplete. The Absolute has without subtraction all those 
qualities, and it has every arrangement which we seem to 
confer upon it by our mere mistake. The only mistake lies 

101 



Bradley's Dialectic 

in our failure to give also the complement. ... I do not 
mean that by a mere re-arrangement of the matter which is 
given to us, we could remove its contradictions. For, being 
limited, we cannot apprehend all the details of the whole. 
And we must remember that every old arrangement, 
condemned as erroneous, itself forms part of that detail. 
To know all the elements of the universe, with all the 
conjunctions of those elements, good and bad, is impossible 
for finite minds. And hence obviously we are unable through- 
out to reconstruct our discrepancies. But we can comprehend 
in general what we cannot see exhibited in detail." 169 ' 17 
We can understand in principle that, through progressive 
emendation, we can render our judgements less self- 
discrepant and thus more self-coherent. "Error is truth when 
it is supplemented." 170 An erroneous judgement is true to the 
degree to which it is self-coherent, and the truth of it is 
increased as the scope of that coherence is enlarged. 

Bradley' s insistence on the continuity of error with truth 
might well lead an ill-disposed reader of Appearance and 
Reality to the conclusion that there is no difference between 
error and ignorance. Our judgements are always as coherent 
as we can make them; where we fail to make them more so 
than they are, our failure is in no sense a mistake, but 
merely a matter of ignorance. 

This would be to overlook die point that in an erroneous 
judgement there is present an insistence that the judgement 
is true, not efroneous. "For the point of error, when all is 
said, lies in this very insistence on the partial and discrepant, 
and this discordant emphasis will fall outside of every 
possible rearrangement. I admit this objection, and I 
endorse it. The problem of error cannot be solved by an 
enlarged scheme of relations." 172 That could not be the 
whole of the solution, because it is just the insistence on 
what is self-discrepant that sustains the conviction that an 
erroneous judgement is not in error, or is, at least, not as 

102 



The Coherence Theory of Truth and Reality 

erroneous as it is. Any emendation of the judgement in the 
direction of more self-coherence will dissipate that insistence, 
to be sure; but the fact of the past existence of it will remain. 

Thus Bradley recognizes that it is not enough to explain the 
ontological nature of error. Take any view of that question 
you prefer, and a further question still remains; namely, 
why a man who is in error feels or insists that he is in the 
right ? Bradley answers that "Error is, but is not barely 
what it takes itself to be. And its mere onesidedness again is 
but a partial emphasis, a note of insistence which contributes, 
we know not how, to the greater energy of life. And, if so, 
the whole problem has, so far, been disposed of." 173 This 
follows because the insistence itself, in being but a one-sided 
emphasis, ipso facto is differentiated from, and thereby 
related to, all else. Thus while the fatuous insistence charac- 
teristic of any erroneous judgement is real and forcible, still, 
at the same time, the relational status of it within Appear- 
ance is in no wise peculiar, but simply that of any other 
appearance. 

However, the question of the status of error in Bradley's 
metaphysics is thus dealt with only "so far", and not com- 
pletely. So far we have seen why Bradley holds that "error" 
is not the name of any special sort of appearance. -The 
question remains as to how the self-discrepant may be taken 
up into the Absolute. For, as Bradley reminds us in this 
connection, "the Absolute is not, and cannot be thought as, 
any scheme of relations. If we keep to these, there is no har- 
monious unity in the whole. The Absolute is beyond a mere 
arrangement, however well compensated, though an arrange- 
ment is assuredly one aspect of its being. Reality consists, 
as we saw, in a higher experience, superior to the distinc- 
tions which it includes and overrides." 172 Yet, since relations, 
however badly mistaken and mixed up in judgement, still 
are relations, there remains the question as to how such judge- 
ments, along with all appearances, stand to the x Absolute. 

103 



Bradley 5 s Dialectic 

We shall follow Bradley in deferring consideration of this 
question to a subsequent chapter. At the close of his discus- 
sion of Error (ch. XVI), Bradley foreshadows the answer 
he gives to the question thus deferred. "We have pointed out 
that it is at least possible for errors to correct themselves, 
and, as such, to disappear in a higher experience. But, if^ 
so, we -must affirm that they are thus absorbed and made 
good. For what is possible, and what a general principle 
compels us to say must be, that certainly is." 178 

With the nature and status of error and irrelevance thus 
considered and partially, at least, accounted for in Bradley's 
view of the matter, we may now turn to the dialectic of 
degrees of truth and reality. That truth for us may be in 
no case absolute, we have noticed in several connections; 
and here, at the beginning of his theory of truth, Bradley 
reminds us that there may be no degrees in the Absolute. 
"The Absolute, considered as such, has of course no degrees; 
for it is perfect, and there can be no more or less in perfection 
(chapter XX). Such predicates belong to, and have a 
meaning only in the world of appearance." 318 What is itself 
absolutely, may not be itself "more or less". On the contrary, 
no relational fact ever is less than absolutely self-coherent. 
Hence, in no judgement, properly so called, may the con- 
notation of the predicate term coincide wholly with that of 
the subject term. No matter how fully self-coherent the 
terms of a judgement may be, "there is still a difference, un- 
removed, between the subject and the predicate, a difference 
which, while it persists, shows a failure in thought, but 
which, if removed, would wholly destroy the special think- 
ing". 319 For were there no self-discrepancy in sentient 
process, there would be no self-transcendence. And without 
the transcendence of the "that" by the "what", there would 
be no thinking. "We have already perceived the main 
nature of the process of thinking. Thought essentially 
consists in the separation of the 'what' from the 'that'. 

104 



The Coherence Theory of Truth and Reality 

It may be said to accept this dissolution as its effective 
principle." 311 

Consequently, no judgement may but fall short of full 
self-coherence. "We may put this otherwise by laying down 
that any categorical judgement must be false. The subject 
and the predicate, in the end, cannot either be the other. 
If however we stop short of this goal, our judgement has 
failed to reach truth; while, if we attained it, the terms 
and their relations would have ceased. And hence all our 
judgements, to be true, must become conditional. The 
predicate, that is, does not hold unless by the help of some- 
thing else. And this 'something else' cannot be stated, so as 
to fall inside even a new and conditional predicate." 320 * 
No matter how elaborately a judgement might be expanded 
by the progressive emendation of it, still there would remain 
"something else" which fell beyond that judgement; for 
no judgement may be more than relational, or less than 
absolute. The conditional nature of judgement is the rela- 
tional nature of process. And the scope of the relational re- 
gress in virtue of which any relational situation is itself, we 
have seen to be endless for the way of thought that is in- 
eluctably ours. Although a given judgement, J 1 , may be so 
expanded as to exhibit, in J 2 , many qualities and relations 
relevant to (and, therefore, conditions of) J 1 , still the truth of 
J 2 can only fall short of being absolute. \/ 

To be sure, on Bradley's view, it is not inconceivable that 
this process of expansion, by the progressive emendation of 
increasingly comprehensive judgements, might lead to a 
concrete universal that fell but little short of being absolutely 
self-coherent. Even so, there would remain a "something 
else" not comprehended by that ail-but omniscient judge- 
ment. This something else would be, of course, reality not 
as relational and self-coherent more or less, but reality as 

* "Even metaphysical statements about the Absolute, I would add, 
are not strictly categorical." P. 320 n. 

105 



Bradley's Dialectic 

unconditioned and absolute. "But with this we have arrived 
at the meeting ground of error and truth. There will be no 
truth which is entirely true, just as there will be no error 
which is totally false. With all alike, if taken strictly, it will 
be a question of amount, and will be a matter of more or 
less. Our thoughts certainly, for some purposes, may be taken 
as wholly false, or again as quite accurate; but truth and 
error, measured by the Absolute, must each be subject 
always to degree. Our judgements, in a word, can never 
reach as far as perfect truth, and must be content to enjoy 
more or less of Validity"* 321 The criterion of absolute 
truth being the Absolute, truth unqualified would exist in a 
judgement whose subject and predicate terms were identical. 
Absolute truth would be the knowing and the being in one 
of an omniscient tautology. 

If, out of carelessness, haste in speaking, or in virtue of 
habitual references to a set of partial standards, we advance 
judgements as though they were quite true or wholly false, 
this is permissible only in so far as it may prove useful 
and convenient. But no such usage is admissible in meta- 
physics; nor is it in any way a comment on metaphysical 
principles. Judgements are true as appearances are real. 
To the degree, or to the extent, to which a judgement 
is comprehensively self-coherent, it is true; and, mutatis 
mutandis ', this is so of any appearance whatever. 

There is but one absolute individual, the Absolute. 
Ultimate reality alone is wholly individual; for it alone 
is absolute in its identity with itself. "Perfection of truth 
and reality has in the end the same character. It consists 
in positive, self-subsisting individuality. . . . Truth must 
exhibit the mark of internal harmony, or again, the mark 
of expansion and all-inclusiveness. And these two charac- 
teristics are diverse aspects of a single principle. That which 
contradicts itself, in the first place, jars, because the whole, 
immanent within it, drives its parts into collision. And the 

106 



The Coherence Theory of Truth and Reality 

way to find harmony, as we have seen, is to redistribute 
these discrepancies in a wider arrangement. But, in the 
second place, harmony is incompatible with restriction and 
finitude. For that which is not all-inclusive must by virtue 
of its essence internally disagree; and if we reflect the reason 
of this becomes plain. That which exists in a whole has 
external relations. Whatever it fails to include in its own 
nature, must be related to it by the whole, and related 
externally. Now these extrinsic relations, on the one hand, 
fall outside of itself, but, upon the other hand, cannot do so. 
For a relation must at both ends affect, and pass into, the 
being of its terms. And hence the inner essence of what is 
finite itself both is, and is not, the relations which limit it. 
Its nature is hence incurably relative, passing, that is, beyond 
itself, and importing, again, into its own core a mass of 
foreign connections. Thus to be defined from without is, in 
principle, to be distracted within." 321 ' 322 

The length of this quotation may be justified in so far as 
in it we find the internality of relations to be the content 
of judgement and so of truth. Anything less than the sys- 
tematic whole of qualities in relation will have relations 
which fall beyond that relational situation; relations which 
are " external " to (but not separate from) the contents of that 
situation. Since these extrinsic relations contribute to the 
identity of that situation no less than do those which lie 
within it, the situation, in being limited from without, is 
distracted within itself. And so, here again we have the 
contrariety that is of the being or essence of relational 
experience. Any quality, however comparatively simple or 
however elaborate it may be, will be at once itself as felt 
immediacy, while, at the same time, it transcends itself in 
being the relations by which it is differentiated from all 
else. It is not surprising, then, that the internality of relations 
should constitute the content of judgement and so of truth. 
For the identity of any appearance, however coherent it be, 

107 



Bradley's Dialectic 

still is relational. But for all that, the internality of relations 
does not supply us with a criterion of truth: rather, it carries 
that criterion with it, therein to be found and understood. 
And, since the criterion of absolute reality is an Individual 
that is absolutely self-sustaining, the criterion of truth and 
reality, for Bradley, is not far to seek. The more compre- 
hensive in intension and extension a relational situation 
becomes, the more fully real it is. For to the degree to which 
it is inclusive, a relational situation approaches absolute, 
self-sustaining reality. Likewise, as a judgement is expanded 
in relevance, it loses in irrelevance in becoming thus more 
fully coherent. This "internal harmony", or self-coherence, 
is the truth of that judgement. "Comprehensiveness" and 
"internal self-coherence", or "harmony", are different names 
not of as many difference criteria, but rather of a single 
principle, that of degrees of coherence within and among the 
concrete universals that constitute the self-fulfilling processes 
that are Appearance at every level short of their absolute 
self-fulfilment in the Absolute harmony that is Reality. 



1 08 



CHAPTER VI 



Identity in Difference 



THE title of this chapter designates the logical principle 
of the internality of quality and relation that is the coherence 
of degrees of truth and reality. Some understanding of that 
principle will carry us further into Bradley's theory of truth, 
and it will also prepare us the better to ask about how, in 
Bradley's own metaphysics, the relational stands to the 
Absolute. 

Bradley holds that philosophy is an attempt to gain a 
view of reality that will satisfy the intellect. He finds, we 
have seen, one mark, albeit a negative one, of what is 
intellectually satisfactory. The intellect rejects the self- 
contradictory, and accepts the self-consistent. But just 
what is the contradictory? We have seen something of the 
answer Bradley gave to that question in the Logic. Now we 
turn to his most extensive discussion of the matter; namely, 
Note A appended to Appearance and Reality. 

Contradiction is not explicable in terms of opposites. 
"If we are asked 'What is contrary or contradictory ?' (I 
do not find it necessary here to distinguish between these), 
the more we consider the more difficult we find it to answer. 
'A thing cannot be or do two opposites at once and in the 
same respect' this reply at first sight may seem clear, but on 
reflection may threaten us with an unmeaning circle. For 
what are 'opposites' except the adjectives which the thing 
cannot so combine ? Hence we have said no more than that 
we in fact find predicates which in fact will not go together, 
and our further introduction of their 'opposite' nature 

109 



Bradley's Dialectic 

seems to add nothing." 500 To say of predicates that they 
are "opposites" is to explain nothing about those predicates 
or about anything else. 

The view that opposites are predicates that cannot be 
united is shortsighted. For "if one arrangement has made 
them opposite, a wider arrangement may perhaps unmake 
their opposition, and may include them all at once and 
harmoniously." 500 The mistake that takes opposites to be 
opposed eternally is the mistake that takes diverse beings 
to be merely other than each other, unmediated by any 
common ground. But no beings are thus merely external 
to each other; no beings are wholly themselves and simply 
not each other. Rather, beings are different, and different 
beings may and do exist in a unity. 

If there is to be a unity of any sort, then "otherness" 
must be a word without a referent; and the fact of unity is 
a fact whose actuality is beyond dispute. But a whole can 
hardly be the blank of vacuous homogeneity. Without 
internal distinction, there would be nothing within the whole 
that it could unite. " 'A thing cannot without an internal 
distinction be (or do)* two different things, and differences 
cannot belong to the same thing in the same point unless 
in that point there is diversity. The appearance of such a 
union may be fact, but is for thought a contradiction.' 
This is the thesis which to me seems to contain the truth 
about the contrary, and I will now try to recommend this 
thesis to the reader." 601 Were a whole without internal 
diversity, there would be nothing in it to be united; and 
that there may be a union of differences, there must be 
diversity within that unity. 

This thesis is not a statement of the Law of (abstract) 

Identity. That law states no more than the emptiest of 

tautologies, A is A. "Thought most certainly does not 

demand mere sameness, which to it would be nothing. A 

* "This addition is superfluous," Footnote, p. 501. 

110 



Identity in Difference 

bare tautology (Hegel has taught us this, and I wish we could 
all learn it) is not even so much as a poor truth or a thin 
truth. It is not a truth in any way, in any sense, or at all. 
Thought involves analysis and synthesis, and if the Law of 
Contradiction forbade diversity, it would forbid thinking 
altogether. And with this too necessary warning I will turn 
to the other side of the difficulty. Thought cannot do without 
differences, but on the other hand it cannot make them. 
And, as it cannot make them, so it cannot receive them 
merely from the outside and ready-made. Thought demands 
to go proprio motu, or, what is the same thing, with a ground 
and reason. Now to pass from A to B, if the ground remains 
external, is for thought to pass with no ground at all. But if, 
again, the external fact of A's and B's conjunction is offered 
as a reason, then that conjunction itself creates the same 
difficulty. For thought's analysis can respect nothing, nor is 
there any principle by which at a certain point it should arrest 
itself or be arrested. Every distinguishable aspect becomes 
therefore for thought a diverse element to be brought to unity. 
Hence thought can no more pass without a reason from A or 
from B to its conjunction, than before it could pass ground- 
lessly from A to B. The transition, being offered as a mere 
datum, or effected as a mere fact, is not thought's own self- 
movement. Or in other words, because for thought no ground 
can be merely external, the passage is groundless. Thus A and 
B and their conjunction are, like atoms, pushed in from the 
outside by chance or fate; and what is thought to do with 
them, but either make or accept an arrangement which to 
it is wanton and without reason or, having no reason for 
anything else, attempt against reason to identify them 
simply?" 501 This lengthy passage contains the gist of 
Bradley's theory of identity and predication. 

In the course of all thinking whatever there is the assertion 
of unity in diversity. Judgement cannot dispense with unity; 
for, without it, there would be at best a bare association of 

in 



Bradley's Dialectic 

ideas. And the barren unity of repetition in tautology is 
not thought at all, but mental inanity that is "filled in with 
the verbiage C A is A'." Hence judgement also cannot 
dispense with differences, for without differences there is 
bare tautology, and thus no movement of thought at all. 
Hegel has taught us this, and Bradley wishes that all of us 
would learn it. 

The formula of judgement cannot be A is A, for thought 
must unite differences if there is to be any movement or 
transition in thought at all. But if A is A cannot be the , 
formula of judgement, can that formula be A is B? Evidently 
not. For B is different from A. Therefore B is not-A. Thus 
the formula in question appears to say, A is not-A; it 
yields abstract contradiction, utterly unsatisfactory to the 
intellect. 

But, it may be objected, this is a pseudo-problem which 
arises out of your failure to distinguish between the "is" 
of identity and the "is" of predication. When we say "A is 
B", surely no one takes us to mean that A is identical with 
B. Rather, we are understood to mean what in fact we do 
mean; namely, that B is a predicate of A, or in a word, that 
A has B. 

Yet this comment on the matter is fatuous. For to mean 
that A has B is to mean that A is such-as-to-have-B. The 
alleged distinction between the "is" of predication and the 
"is" of identity enables us to do no more than change our 
verbal symbol for the copula, and thus merely evade the 
central question as to how the copula may in logic as in 
existence unite differences. 

That question, it may be objected, so far from being 
central, is quite unreal. But " 'This is not so 5 , I shall be told, 
'and the whole case is otherwise. There are certain ultimate 
complexes given to us as facts, and these uJtimates, as they 
are given, thought simply takes up as principles and employs 
them to explain the detail of the world. And with this process 

112 



Identity in Difference 

thought is satisfied.' To me such a doctrine is quite erroneous. 
For these ultimates (a) cannot make the world intelligible, 
and again (b) they are not given, and (c) in themselves they 
are self-contradictory, and not truth but appearance." 501 502 
These ultimates cannot be used to explain the world at all, 
because no one of them bears on anything other than itself. 
In being each one final and, as it were, all there at once: 
ultimate and given: each ultimate is self-contained, and 
thus isolated in experience and logic from every other one. 
Such ultimates, and the complexes they constitute without 
residuum, are external to each other. No one of them 
contributes anything at all to any other one; hence they are 
respectively without bearing on each other. 

Then again, these alleged complexes are not given. "The 
transition from A to B, the inherence of b and c as adjectives 
in A, the union of discretion and continuity in time and 
space 'such things are facts,' it is said. 'They are given to an 
intellect which is satisfied to accept and to employ them.' 
They may be facts, I reply, in some sense of that word, but 
to say that, as such and in and by themselves, they are given 
is erroneous. What is given is a presented whole, a sensuous 
total in^hjgl^j^hese characteris are found; and beyond 
and beside these characters there is always given something 
else. And to urge 'but at any rate these characters are there,' 
is surely futile. For certainly they are not, when there, as 
they are when you by an abstraction have taken them out. 
Your contention is that certain ultimate conjunctions of 
elements are given. And I reply that no such bare conjunction 
is or possibly can be given. For the background is present, 
and the background and the conjunction are, I submit, 
alike integral aspects of the fact. The background therefore 
must be taken as a condition of the conjunction's existence, 
and the intellect must assert the conjunction subject in this 
way to a condition. The conjunction is hence not bare but 
dependent, and it is really a connection mediated by 

113 H 



Bradley's Dialectic 

something falling outside it." 502 ' 503 Facts given u in and by 
themselves" would be facts without background; without 
relations beyond themselves. We have looked into the 
dialectic of quality and relation which constrains Bradley 
to deny the reality of any such unrelated collocation of 
(what are for him) fictions. And now we find him reminding 
us that any set of "facts" we may hit upon or select stands in 
a context of relations, not stark and alone. With his theory 
of relations in mind, we can understand the force of the 
"must" in his statement that this context must be taken as 
a condition of the existence of any set of facts. They could 
not be what they are without their context. For that context 
of relation and quality, which, ultimately, is the systematic 
whole that is appearance, is the relational situation in 
virtue of which those "facts" are differentiated from all 
else and thereby made the qualities and relations that 
they are. 

That is why the mere conjunction of characteristics is a 
self-contradictory notion. "And any mere conjunction, I 
go on to urge, is for thought self-contradictory. Thought, I 
may perhaps assume, implies analysis and synthesis and 
distinction in unity. Further, the mere conjunction offered 
to thought cannot be set apart itself as something sacred, 
but may itself properly, and indeed must, become thought's 
object. There will be a passage therefore from one element 
in this conjunction to its other element or elements. And 
on the other hand, by its own nature, thought must hold 
these in unity. But, in a bare conjunction, starting with A, 
thought will externally be driven to B, and seeking to unite 
these it will find no ground of union. Thought can of itself 
supply no internal bond by which to hold them together, 
nor has it any internal diversity by which to maintain them 
apart. It must therefore seek barely to identify them, though 
they are different, or somehow to unite both diversities 
where it has no ground of distinction and union. And this 

114 



Identity in Difference 

does not mean that the connection is merely unknown and 
may be affirmed as unknown, and also, supposing it were 
known, as rational. For, if so, the conjunction would at 
once not be bare, and it is as bare that it is offered and not 
as conditional. But, if on the other hand it remains bare, 
then thought to affirm it must unite diversities without any 
internal distinction, and the attempt to do this is precisely 
what contradiction means." 504 

So long as the differences in question are taken as self- 
contained units, thought can only recoil from the affirmation 
of their identity. For as respectively different and self- 
contained, they have no common ground; there is nothing 
internal to them in virtue of which they could be at one. 
Such self-contained units are self-identical; the formula 
for them is the empty truth A is A. And on this, to Bradley 
a wholly perverse view of the matter, the formula for the 
Law of Non-Contradiction is no less familiar and no less 
inane. But if, instead of trying to take experience as a 
complex of self-contained units, we see it as diverse expres- 
sions of a system of mutually related qualities, the whole 
matter is altered in principle. For now we see that to 
predicate B of A is not to affirm that A per se is B per se. A is 
not A intrinsically and independently of all else, and no 
more is B. Rather A is what it is by virtue of its differentiations 
from B and all else. These differentiations are relations by 
which A is related throughout the systematic whole of 
appearances, as B also is thus related by its differences from 
all else. 

Thus when we judge that A is B, there now is and could 
be no question of our affirming that A is identical with B. 
For neither A nor B is such that they could be merely 
identical with each other. The identity of A 3 we have seen, 
implies its difference from all else, and that of course 
includes and also applies to B. By virtue of the differentiations 
by which A is related throughout within the Whole, A is a 



Bradley's Dialectic 

relational adjective of the Whole. And, mutatis mutandis, so 
also is B. 

Within the verbal terms of a judgement, it is grammatically 
correct to distinguish a predicate term and a subject term. 
But this is a distinction in point of terms verbal; a distinction 
to which nothing in judgement proper corresponds. For in 
truth both of the constituents of the judgement proper, as 
distinguished from the statement of it in words, are 
adjectives of the Whole. 

This means that the constituents of a judgement proper* 
are related at once to their proximate subject a perceived 
hammer, say and also to the Whole itself. For the con- 
stituent terms of the judgement that is expressed by the 
sentence, "that is a hammer," are not the same as, but 
rather are different from, that instrument. In virtue of their 
differences from it, those terms are related with and so 
refer to that hammer. And we must not forget that those 
terms and that hammer are different from and ipso facto 
related to all else. This "all" will be the systematic Whole 
of Appearances. 

So much follows from the conclusion that relations and 
qualities are mutually internal. Every aspect of experience 
is related throughout the Whole in virtue of its differences 
from everything else within that Whole. For this reason, 
among others, the subject term in every judgement no less 
than the predicate term is an adjective of the real. The 
subject and the predicate, S and P, in being different 
content are related to each other by the very fact of their 
differences; and since S and P are different also from all 
other moments of process, ipso facto S and P are related to 
every single moment of the Whole. 

Thus the judgement S is P asserts a diversity of connota- 
tion in the adjectives S and P; while, at the same time, that 
judgement asserts an identity in the denotation of those 
adjectives through which the ultimate referent of that 

116 



Identity in Difference 

judgement is organic Reality. In Bradley's view, this must 
be so, for S and P are internally related throughout that 
Whole. Thus in every judgement there is an identity in the 
differences that are the content of that judgement. This 
identity is the Absolute Reality that is the supra-relational 
fulfilment of the development of process in appearance. 

Thus we may see that ' 'Things are not contrary because 
they are opposite, for things by themselves are not opposite. 
And things are not contrary because they are diverse, for 
the world as a fact holds diversity in unity. Things are self- 
contrary when, and just so far as, they appear as bare 
conjunctions, when in order to think them you would have 
to predicate differences without an internal ground of 
connection and distinction, when, in other words, you would 
have to unite diversities simply, and that means in the same 
point. This is what contradiction means, or I at least have 
been able to find no other meaning." 605 

Things qua things are not contrary; contrariety breaks out 
as unity among difference develops. This contrariety is 
diversity, not the otherness of blank negation between two 
unrelated conjuncts. That bare negation yields self-con- 
trariety: "Things are self-contrary when, and just so far as, 
they appear as bare conjunctions." 505 For such self-identical 
ultimates are "without an internal ground of connection and 
distinction"; and we have seen something of the logical 
results of attempting to unite any such fictions in judgement. 
u Thought cannot accept tautology and yet demands unity 
in diversity. But your offered conjunctions on the other side 
are for it no connections or ways of union. They are them- 
selves merely other external things to be connected. . . . 
How can thought unite except so far as in itself it has a 
mode of union? To unite without an internal ground of 
connection and distinction is to strive to bring together 
barely in the same point, and that is self-contradiction." 505 
That is self-contradiction for the reason that to assert the 

117 



Bradley's Dialectic 

identity of S and P is to contradict their difference. And to 
affirm that difference is to contradict the attempted assertion 
of identity. 

Thus we see that the true formula of judgement is not 
A is A, nor A is B, nor A has B. Rather the formula is Xa is 
Xb; where X stands for the systematic Whole throughout 
which a and b are related, and to which they refer by virtue 
of those relations. To take it that A per se is B per se yields, 
we have seen, the flat contradiction of a judgement which 
affirms unity of contents which are posited as merely different. 
Diverse contents may be united only as they are adjectives 
of the systematic Whole that is the unity or principle of 
identity in all differences. 



118 



CHAPTER VII 

The Relational and the 
Absolute 



*!T is a central conclusion of Bradley's dialectic, and one 
which he frequently emphasizes, that appearances are 
sublated or taken up into the Absolute. How this sublation 
of the relational by the Absolute is to be explained is the 
topic of the present chapter. 

Bradley writes, not once but again and again, that the 
Absolute is in some sense beyond and superior to the 
relational. For example, in writing of the correction of 
errors and the relation of erroneous judgements to the 
Absolute, he says, "But on the other side the Absolute is not, 
and cannot be thought as, any scheme of relations. If we 
keep to these, there is no harmonious unity in the whole. 
The Absolute is beyond a mere arrangement, however well 
compensated, though an arrangement is assuredly one aspect 
of its being. Reality consists, as we saw, in a higher experience, 
superior to the distinctions which it includes and over- 
rides." 172 The Absolute, then, is "beyond" relations; it is a 
"higher experience", which "overrides" the distinctions to 
which it is "superior". 

Before going on to ask about what it means to say even 
this much of the Absolute, it may be well to remind our- 
selves of what Bradley elucidates as being the relational 
nature of Appearance. As a propaedeutic to the dialectic of 
Relation and Quality in chapter III, Bradley urges in 
chapter II that because relations can be neither attributes of, 
nor independent of, their terms, they must be internal to 



Bradley's Dialectic 

them. Relations can not be attributes because predication 
is either tautological or flatly self-contradictory. "If you 
predicate what is different, you ascribe to the subject what 
it is not\ and if you predicate what is not different, you say 
nothing at all." A distinction between the "is" of identity 
and the "is" of predication is not mentioned as an alternative 
on which this dilemma would be resolved, because that 
distinction would beg the question of the reality of external 
relations. Rather, it is suggested that the relation in question 
be regarded as "more or less" independent of its terms/ 
"But such a makeshift leads at once to the infinite process." 
For on it the question, "what relates the independent 
relation to its terms?", remains and breaks out afresh at 
each attempted answer. It is thus concluded that only one 
alternative remains: "A is in relation to B" means neither 
that "A" is identical with nor independent of "in relation 
with B"; rather it means that A and B stand in a relation 
that differentiates the qualitative characters of A and B 
respectively. 

The assumption that every difference is a difference in 
quality, and that numerical difference is not an alternative 
at all, underlies the argument of chapter III, "Relation and 
Quality." We have seen that in chapter III Bradley goes 
on to urge that relations and qualities are not found apart 
in fact, and that they can not be separated by any process of 
abstraction. Mere separateness or otherness is not possible: 
where there is separation there is difference; and difference, 
to be at all, must be difference in quality. "For consider, the 
qualities A and B are to be different from each other; and, 
if so, that difference must fall somewhere. If it falls, in any 
degree, or to any extent, outside A or B, we have relation 
at once. But, on the other hand, how can difference and 
otherness fall inside? If we have in A any such otherness, 
then inside A we must distinguish its own quality and its 
otherness." 24 Either the difference between A and B, in 

120 



The Relational and the Absolute 

virtue of which they are distinct, differentiates A from B and 
so "falls outside" A or B, or that difference "falls within'' 
A and B respectively thus to differentiate them within 
themselves indefinitely. Hence the difference that differ- 
entiates A and B must fall outside or between them. This 
difference can not be numerical merely, for that would be 
a difference that in no way contributes to qualify what it 
differentiates. And on Bradley 5 s assumption that "difference" 
is the name of a relation, a difference that in no way con- 
tributed to the character of its qualities would be a relation 
"separate" from its terms, and so not a genuine differ- 
entiation at all. 

It could hardly be denied that distinct qualities cannot 
be distinct unless they are different in some sense. This 
difference, if we be constrained to say so, "must fall some- 
where"; and this "somewhere" must be "outside" A or B. 
Thus "we have relation at once". 24 For in falling outside 
A or B, their difference falls between them, and thus that 
differentiation relates A and B. 

In a synoptic way, the main conclusions of chapters II 
and III of Appearance and Reality may be seen to derive from 
a pair of alleged disjunctions In the first of these, that of 
chapter II, it is urged that relations cannot be both separate 
entities on the one hand, and capable of relating terms on 
the other. And since any view of relations as separate 
entities entails an infinite regress in separate entities that 
can only fail to relate terms, this alternative is a delusion, 
or worse. Hence we are forced to conclude, on what is 
assumed to be the sole alternative remaining to us, that 
relations are internal to their terms; where "being internal 
to" means "affecting" or "making a difference in" the 
qualitative character of the terms thus related. What is 
meant in this connection by "affecting" or "making a 
difference in" is explained in the course of the statement of 
the second disjunction. 

121 



Bradley's Dialectic 

Just as (in chapter II) there may be no relations without 
qualities, so also (in chapter III) there may be no distinct 
qualities without relations. Qualities without relations 
would be not diverse qualities at all, but undifferentiated 
and at one. In chapter III ("Relation and Quality") the 
alleged disjunction is between an infinite regress of differ- 
ences within the character of every single quality, on the 
one hand, and relations internal to the character of the 
qualities they differentiate, on the other; where "being 
internal to" means being the very differences by which* 
qualities are differentiated. Therefore relations (i.e. 
differentiations) must "fall somewhere". They cannot be 
and yet have no status. Now the differentiations that rela- 
tions are can not fall wholly within qualities. For that results 
in the indefinite differentiation of qualities within them- 
selves. Hence relations must fall at once within and between 
the qualities they differentiate. An example of the meaning 
of relation as thus making a difference in the terms that 
conversely make a difference in their relations is afforded 
by cell-fission. In this sense of the term relation, "difference 
implies relation" for the reason that to relate is to differen- 
tiate. As the differentiation of the moments of fission alters, 
the moments themselves alter; and, conversely, as the 
moments of fission alter, their differentiation also alters. 

The question which concerns us here is how the relational 
is taken up into the Absolute. In some quarters it is some- 
times suggested that the theory of the "this" and the 
"mine" affords an intimation, which is all we can have, of 
how this question is answered in the fact of feeling. It may 
be well, then, to consider first the nature of this alleged 
intimation. 

We are told that "The 'this' and the 'mine' are names 
which stand for the immediacy of feeling, and each serves 
to call attention to one side of that fact. There is no 'mine' 
which is not 'this', nor any 'this' which fails, in a sense, 

122 



The Relational and the Absolute 

to be 'mine'. The immediate fact must always come as 
something felt in an experience, and an experience always 
must be particular, and, in a sense, must be unique." 197 
Moreover, "all our knowledge, in the first place, arises from 
the 'this'. It is the one source of our experience, and every 
element of the world must submit to pass through iy And 
the c this', secondly, has a genuine feature of ultimate 
reality. With however great imperfection and inconsistency 
it owns an individual character." 198 The "this" is also "mine" 
for the same reason that any experience of yours is at once 
that experience and yours. Such feelings are immediate in 
that no feelings are less differentiated internally, or more 
self- transcendent; this feeling of mine is compelling largely 
in and through its sentient focus, with little felt fringe of 
prehensions into the sentient context of it. Nevertheless, the 
"this" and the "mine", the "that" and the "yours" are self- 
transcendent. "And the self- transcendent character of the 
'this' is, on all sides, open and plain. Appearing as immediate, 
it, on the other side, has contents which are not consistent 
with themselves, and which refer themselves beyond. Hence 
the inner nature of the 'this' leads it to pass outside itself 
toward a higher totality. And its negative aspect is but one 
appearance of this general tendency. Its very exclusiveness 
involves the reference of itself beyond itself, and is but a 
proof of its necessary absorption in the Absolute." 201 ' 202 The 
"this" and the "mine", though immediate, are less than the 
Whole, and are in process. Therefore the "this" and the 
"mine" exhibit, albeit in its incipience, that self-transcend- 
ence which is the principle of differentiation and thus of 
relation. Nevertheless, the "this" and the "mine" afford "the 
sense of immediate reality" wherein, it is sometimes urged, 
there is intimated the answer to our question about the rela- 
tional and the Absolute. 

Now there are at least two difficulties in the way of our 
accepting this suggestion. In the first place, it would seem 

123 



Bradley's Dialectic 

that the theory of the this and the mine denies what it also 
affirms. Consider that the this and the mine "is at a level 
below distinctions". "Both the 'this' and reality, we may say, 
are immediate. But reality is immediate because it includes 
and is superior to mediation. It develops, and it brings to 
unity, the distinctions it contains. The 'this' is immediate, 
on the other side, because it is at a level below distinc- 
tions." 198 ' 199 Now below the level of distinctions there are 
no distinctions. Where there are no distinctions there are no 
differences. At a level below distinctions, the "this" could 
not be distinct from the "that". 

This is not to forget that the immediate experience in 
question is also self-transcendent. The "this" and the 
"mine" has two sides, "positive" and "negative".* On its 
negative side the "this" and the "mine" is self-transcendent, 
as is any other relational situation. But on its positive side 
it is below the level of distinctions. And where there are no 
distinctions there are no differences. Therefore it is impos- 
sible that there should be a plurality of positive sides. 
Without that plurality of positive sides there cannot be a 
plurality of immediate experiences. In so far as the "this" 
and the "mine" is below the level of distinctions it is in- 
determinate because it is not distinct from anything else. 
And it is only in so far as the "this" and the "mine" is 
below the level of relations that it is immediate. 

* "An immediate experience, viewed as positive, is so far not exclusive. 
It is, so far, what it is, and it does not repel anything. But the 'this' 
certainly is used also with a negative bearing. It may mean 'this one*, 
in distinction from that one and the other one. And here it shows ob- 
viously an exclusive aspect, and it implies an external and negative 
relation. But every such relation, we have found, is inconsistent with 
itself (ch. III). For it exists within, and by virtue of an embracing unity, 
and apart from that totality both itself and its terms would be nothing. 
And the relation also must penetrate the inner being of its terms. 'This', 
in other words, would not exclude 'that', unless in the exclusion 'this', 
so far, passed out of itself. Its repulsion of others is thus incompatible 
with self-contained singleness, and involves subordination to an includ- 
ing whole. But to the ultimate whole nothing can be opposed, or even 
related." 201 

124 



The Relational and the Absolute 

In the second place, why does the " this" and the "mine", 
and no other mode of the relational, give us an intimation 
of the nature of Absolute Reality? Because "the 'this' and 
the 'mine' express the immediate character of feeling, and 
the appearance of this character in a finite centre." 198 As 
immediate experience, "the 'this' is real for us in a sense in 
which nothing else is real". 198 It has " a genuine feature of 
ultimate reality", for in its immediacy the "this" "owns 
an individual character". 198 The ownership is transitory, 
5^et the individuality thus possessed is alleged to be genuine 
and felt. 

But it is only on the positive, unmediated side of the "this" 
that it is immediate experience; on the negative side of it, 
the "this" is self-transcendent. The "this" is immediate 
experience, and possessed of a feature of ultimate reality, 
only in so far as it is unmediated, or "below the level of 
distinctions". And at that level of experience there would be 
sentience that were wholly homogeneous. The "this" could 
not be distinct from the "that"; there could not be even 
two contents, for below the level of distinctions all would 
be one. 

This homogeneity of sentience could hardly be the 
Absolute into which all differences are sublated. "Both the 
'this' and reality, we may say, are immediate. But reality 
is immediate because it includes and is superior to media- 
tion. It develops, and it brings to unity, the distinctions it 
contains." 198) 199 Thus Reality is said at once to comprehend 
and be superior to the distinctions it contains. But the "this" 
contains no distinctions. "The 'this' is immediate, on the 
other side, because it is at a level below distinctions." 199 
The contrast is fairly broad. Reality includes in its superiority 
the distinctions it contains. The "this" contains no distinc- 
tions; it is below them all. 

Nevertheless, it may be urged, the "this" does afford 
an intimation by analogy of the nature of the real, In so 

125 



Bradley's Dialectic 

far as the "this" is unmediated by distinctions it is immediate 
and homogeneous and therefore one. The Absolute is one. 
Thus we may see that Appearance is to Reality as the nega- 
tive or mediated side of the "this" is to the positive or 
unmediated side of it. But this suggestion is anything but 
helpful. How does the relational, the mediated, the self- 
transcendent aspect of the "this" stand to the aspect of 
it that is undifFerentiated, homogeneous, and wholly one? 
How can any such immediacy be at once devoid of internal 
differences and possessed of internal relations by which it 
could transcend itself and exist at a relational level? Without 
differentiation or mediation there are and can *be no rela- 
tions. At a level below distinctions, sentience would be 
below relations. It would be out of all relation; it could not 
stand to anything at all. On the side of the "this" and the 
"mine" the proposed analogy is vitiated by the nature of 
the case. 

On the side of Appearance and the Absolute the analogy 
is likewise unavailing. For "to the ultimate whole nothing 
can be opposed, or even related". 201 The Absolute, being 
absolute, is not relational. But what is the analogy proposed 
if not a relation? Appearance is to the Absolute as the 
mediated is to the immediate in the "this" and the "mine". 
And even if this analogy were instructive, it still would be 
fatal to the character of the Absolute as absolute. For if the 
Absolute stood in any relation at all, ipso facto it would be 
relational and appearance, and thus fail to be absolute. 
The proposed analogy can only fail to answer the question 
as to how Appearance can be taken up into, resolved, 
made one with, or comprehended in the Absolute. For the 
analogy in question would establish a relation between 
Appearance and the Absolute. That would destroy the 
absolute nature of ultimate reality. 

There are those who urge that the main question at issue 
in this connection is unreal; that it arises out of a failure to 

126 



The Relational and the Absolute 

understand. The Absolute is no supra-relational being. 
Rather it is nothing more than the systematic whole that is 
exhaustively constituted by the internality of qualities and 
relations. There is no relevant question about how Appear- 
ance stands to the Absolute. For Appearance, not as self- 
fulfilling, but as self-fulfilled, is the Absolute. The Absolute 
is nothing distinct from the systematic totality of relation 
and quality in the mutual harmony which their self-fulfil- 
ment would realize and internally sustain. 
This interpretation, and others cognate with it, were 
anticipated by Bradley, and he flatly rejected it. The antici- 
pation runs as follows: Writing of the "infinite process" in re- 
lation and quality, Bradley says: u The remedy might lie here. 
If the diversities were complementary aspects of a process 
of connection and distinction, the process not being external 
to the elements or again a foreign compulsion of the intellect, 
but itself the intellect's own proprius motus, the case would be 
altered. Each aspect would of itself be a transition to the 
other aspect, a transition intrinsic and natural at once to 
itself and to the intellect. And the Whole would be a self-evident 
analysis and synthesis of the intellect itself by itself. Synthesis here 
has ceased to be mere synthesis and has become self-completion, 
and analysis, no longer mere analysis, is self -explication. And the 
question how or why the many are one and the one is many 
here loses its. meaning. There is no why or how beside the self- 
evident process, and towards its own differences this whole is at once 
their how and their why, their being, substance and system, their 
reason, ground, and principle of diversity and unity."* This passage 
would seem to make it clear that Bradley foresaw the inter- 
pretation that is in question. The Absolute would be one 
with the self-completing and self-explicating whole of rela- 
tional quality. That systematic whole, in its self-fulfilment, 
would be its own rationale. Thus there could be no question 
about the relation of the relational to the real. For the real 
* P. 507. My italics. 

127 



Bradley's Dialectic 

is the relational, as the relational is self-fulfilling and self- 
fulfilled. 

But Bradley not only anticipated this interpretation of 
the matter in one paragraph, he also rejected it in the 
next. "Has the Law of Contradiction anything here to 
condemn? It seems to me it has nothing. The identity of which 
diversities are predicated is in no case simple. There is no 
point which is not itself internally the transition to its 
complement, and there is no unity which fails in internal 
diversity and ground of distinction. In short 'the identity 
of opposites,' far from conflicting with the Law of Contra- 
diction, may claim to be the one view which satisfies its 
demands, the only theory which everywhere refuses to 
accept a standing contradiction. And if all that we find were 
in the end such a self-evident and self-complete whole, 
containing in itself as constituent processes the detail of 
the Universe, so far as I can see the intellect would receive 
satisfaction in full. But for myself, unable to verify a solution 
of this kind, connections in the end must remain in part mere 
syntheses, the putting together of differences external to 
one ^another and to that which couples them. And against 
my intellectual world the Law of Contradiction has there- 
fore claims nowhere satisfied in full. And since, on the other 
hand, the intellect insists that these demands must be and 
are met, I am led to hold that they are met, in and by a whole 
beyond the mere intellect. And in the intellect itself I seem to find an 
inner want and defect and a demand thus to pass itself beyond itself. 
And against this conclusion I have not yet seen any tenable objection" 

"Self-existence and self-identity are to be found, I would 
urge, in a whole beyond thought, a whole to which thought 
points and in which it is included, but which is known 
only in abstract character and could not be verified in its 
detail." 607 ' 508 The Absolute, then, is a whole not merely of, 
but also beyond thought; it is supra-relational.* 
* Cf . Appearance and Reality, pp . 159-161. 
128 



The Relational and the Absolute 

Yet the interpretation of his metaphysics that Bradley 
discards is not rejected by him because it is self-stultifying. 
He does not find it absurd that the real be viewed as a 
systematic whole of mutually implicative qualities and rela- 
tions; an organic whole that is self-fulfilling and therefore 
self-fulfilled. Nor does he think it absurd that within that 
systematic whole analysis and synthesis in judgement would 
be respectively self-explicative and self-completed. Rather 
he concludes that the intellect finds no such logically 
stable systematic whole, or concrete universal that is fully 
concrete. 

Everywhere and always judgement falls short of ultimate 
self-coherence. Any judgement will transcend itself by virtue 
of the relational way of thought that is ineluctably ours. 
Bradley finds in the intellect "an inner want and defect and 
a demand to pass beyond itself" 508 because, as he has 
explained over and over again, self-transcendence is of the 
essence of thought. That is why for the intellect to go beyond 
the relational to the Absolute would be for the intellect to 
commit suicide. 

The Absolute is not to be discerned in any view of relation 
and quality as a systematic whole. No more is it to be found 
in any one aspect of Appearance. "We have seen that the 
various aspects of experience imply one another, that all 
point to a unity which comprehends and perfects them. 
And I would urge next that the unity of these aspects is 
unknown. By this I certainly do not mean to deny that it 
essentially is experience, but it is an experience of which, 
as such, we have no direct knowledge. We never have, or 
are, a state which is the perfect unity of all aspects: and we 
must admit that in their special natures they remain in- 
explicable. An explanation would be the reduction of their 
plurality to unity, in such a way that the relation between 
the unity and the variety was understood. And everywhere 
an explanation of this kind in the end is beyond us. If we 

129 i 



Bradley's Dialectic 

abstract one or more of the aspects of experience, and use 
this known element as a ground to which the others are 
referred, our failure is evident." 414 ' 415 For the aspects 
abstracted would remain abstractions, no matter how we 
went about insisting that they were the ground of all Appear- 
ance. Each aspect would remain an aspect; thus it would 
be incomplete, unstable, inherently self-transcendent. No 
aspect of experience could be absolute, if only because it 
is an aspect. 

Thus we may see that, in Bradley's own judgement, the 
Absolute is to be discerned neither in any phase of experi- 
ence, nor in Appearance taken as a systematic whole. 
Nevertheless he urges repeatedly that the relational is taken 
up into a higher unity of logical harmony in which the 
inherent self-discrepancy of appearance is fully resolved and 
thus healed. And yet, it may be asked, what grounds has 
Bradley for this insistence ? They are not afforded by any 
one aspect, or any range of aspects, of Appearance. And the 
systematic totality of appearances is less than self-grounded, 
or self-contained. But those grounds are supplied by the 
theory of negation upon which Bradley stands. 

The result of Book I of Appearance and Reality is "mainly 
negative", 119 we are assured. The aspects of Appearance 
therein examined reveal the self-contrariety that is the 
fission of relational quality through which this quality 
that is also mine is differentiated from all else. The "this" 
and the u mine" is any quality. Thus we are constrained to 
conclude that Appearance throughout is self-discrepant 
or self-contrary. By this very same conclusion, Bradley 
argues, we are constrained to pronounce the contrary 
of Appearance self-consistent. Thus, in finding that every 
appearance is self-contrary to some degree or other, ipso 
facto we posit the contrary of our negation; namely, a self- 
consistent, and therefore absolute Reality. 

This conclusion is truly inescapable on the theory of 

130 



The Relational and the Absolute 

negation that is characteristic of systematic Idealism. On 
that theory, we have seen, every negation presupposes a 
positive ground. "Pure negation", "mere otherness", 
"external relations", these phrases are alike without meaning, 
for there is no mere negation. "The contradictory idea, if 
we take it in a merely negative form, must be banished from 
logic. If Not- A were solely the negation of A, it would be an 
assertion without a quality, and would be a denial without 
anything positive to serve as its ground. ... It is impossible 
for anything to be only Not-A. It is impossible to realize 
Not-A in thought."* The contradictory of A cannot be a 
mere not-A. Any such conception must be abandoned, and 
with it the empty, wholly verbal distinction between the 
contradictory and the contrary. In truth they are one; 
and in that fact we see that every opposition in psychical 
fact, in thought, and in judgement is mediated by a third 
term. This mediation of the differentiation that is a negation 
is the positive ground of that negation. 

Now every relation is a differentiation, and every dif- 
ferentiation is a negation, and every negation requires 
a positive ground. Consequently, the relational requires a 
ground that is positive. Thus, both Bradley's criterion of 
Appearance: namely, self-contrariety: and his theory of 
negation, entail a ground that is self-coherent or wholly 
positive. 

Yet it is difficult to see how the Absolute that is the 
identity in all differences may be in any sense related to 
those appearances. For were the Absolute in any relation 
whatever, ipso facto it would cease to be absolute; by the 
very fact of that relation, the Absolute would be the term 
of a relation, and therefore it would be relational, not 
absolute. The notion of the Absolute as the identity in 
differences: as the positive ground of the negations which 
those differentiations are, to put the same thing in another 

* Logic, p. 123. 



Bradley's Dialectic 

way: is as basic to Bradley' s metaphysics as is his theory of 
negation. And without that conception of negation, the 
Hegelian identification of the contradictory with the 
contrary would lose its basis in theory. Nevertheless, it is 
more than difficult to see how the Absolute can be in any 
relation at all and remain absolute. 



132 



CHAPTER VIII 

Some Basic Difficulties 



BRADLEY'S monism is derived from his theory of relation and 
Duality. The validity of that theory is a necessary condition 
of the validity of his monism. It is the conception of relations 
as internal to the terms they differentiate that excludes the 
possibility of a plurality of externally related realities. It is 
that same conception of relation that constrains us to con- 
clude that every single reality is internally related to all else. 
And it is the theory of relation as the aspect of self-transcend- 
ence or self-differentiation that compels us to see thought, and 
the consummation of thought in judgement, as the ideality 
of the finite, ineluctably relational and hence for ever falling 
short of the Absolute that is, nevertheless, implied by the 
dialectic of quality and relation. 

It may be well then to ask first about some of the more 
obtrusive difficulties in Bradley' s theory of relations. These 
initial questions will lead us in a natural order to some other 
basic difficulties in Bradley's dialectic. 

We have seen that, for Bradley, "quality" is the name of 
any moment of experience wherein mediation or differen- 
tiation is recessive, while immediacy is dominant. Con- 
versely, "relation" is the name of any moment of experience 
in which differentiation is dominant, while immediacy is 
recessive. In this matter, the principal point is illustrated 
by the process of cell-fission. If, while regarding this, we 
attend mainly to the new cells that are emerging, then what 
is most immediate, or qualitative, in that situation will 
be dominant within the focus of our attention. If, to 

133 



Bradley's Dialectic 

the contrary, our attention emphasizes the mediation 
or differentiation there in process, then relation will be 
dominant, while quality is recessive. 

Thus conceived of, "qualities are nothing without 

relations". 21 Should we attempt to arrive at a relationless 

quality by abstraction, we could only fail. The process of 

abstraction is a process of differentiation; therefore it is 

relational. Again, we should be balked were we to "appeal 

to a lower and undistinguished state of mind, where in one 

feeling are many aspects. ... I admit the existence of such 

states without any relation, but I wholly deny there the 

presence of qualities". 22 For these felt aspects, if undifferen- 

tiated, are not qualities; and if they are differentiated, then, 

by that very fact, they are related. "In short, if you go 

back to mere unbroken feelings, you have no relations and 

no qualities. But if you come to what is distinct, you get 

relations at once." 22 Where there are no distinctions, there 

are no qualities: where there are qualities, there are 

distinctions or differences and, by that very fact, relations. 

Thus, on the assumption that a difference is a relation 

and a relation is a difference, or differentiation, Bradley 

submits that, where we find different qualities, there we 

find qualities which are related by their differences. "For 

consider, the qualities A and B are to be different from each 

other; and, if so, the difference must fall somewhere. If it 

falls, in any degree or to any extent, outside A or B, we have 

relation at once. But on the other hand, how can difference 

and otherness fall inside? If we have in A any such otherness, 

then inside A we must distinguish its own quality and its 

otherness. And if so, then the unsolved problem breaks out 

inside each quality, and separates each into two qualities 

in relation. In brief, diversity without relation seems a word 

without meaning." 24 Either the difference between A and B, 

in virtue of which they are distinct, "falls outside A or B", 

thus to relate them; or else that difference falls within A 

134 



Some Basic Difficulties 

and B respectively, thus to differentiate each one of them 
within itself; and so the moment of relation would break 
out within A, and within B. Hence the difference that 
differentiates A and B can only fall "outside", or between 
them, and so "we have relation at once". 24 

Thus, to return again to our example, in the incipience 
of a process of cell-fission, the incipient differentiation 
"must fall somewhere". And it falls "outside" or "between" 
the incipient cells in the observable sense that it is what 
differentiates them. As soon as we see this, then (on the 
assumption that differentiation, or difference in process, 
is relation), we are aware of relation at once. For we are 
then aware of the difference in virtue of which the incipient 
qualities are differentiated, or related. In this sense of the 
term "relation", were a quality without relations, it would 
be in no wise different from anything else, and so would 
fail to be anything at all. 

To be sure, no fixed line can be drawn between a differ- 
entiation and what is thus differentiated. For any relation 
and any quality will be in process. As the incipient qualities 
become more and more determinate, their differentiation 
alters; and, conversely, as their differentiation becomes 
more and more marked, the qualities likewise are altered. 
"Hence the qualities must be, and must also be related. But 
there is hence diversity which falls inside each quality. 
Each has a double character, as both supporting and as 
being made by the relation." 26 

In order that a quality may be distinct, it must be differ- 
entiated from other qualities. This differentiation is no 
separate relation: rather, it contributes to constitute what it 
differentiates. Thus, in so far as A is quality, A is not 
relation; and yet, that it may be distinct, A must be both 
itself and its differentiation. This is the reason why no 
quality, however concrete and comprehensive,, may be 
wholly self-coherent. That is why, as we have seen, "A is 

135 



Bradley's Dialectic 

both made, and is not made, what it is by relation; and 
these different aspects are not each the other, nor again is 
either A. If we call its diverse aspects V and a, then A is 
partly each of these. As V it is the difference on which 
distinction is based, while as a it is the distinctness that 
results from connection. A is really both somehow together 
as A (a a). But (as we saw in chapter II) without the use of a 
relation it is impossible to predicate this variety of A. And, 
on the other hand, with an internal relation ^4's unity 
disappears, and its contents are dissipated in an endless 1 
process of distinction. . . . We, in brief are led by a prin- 
ciple of fission which conducts us to no end". 26 Without a 
relation, A would be undifferentiated, and so it would be 
nothing at all. With a relation, A is at once the a that is 
differentiated, and the ' V that is the differentiation. Thus 
'M is partly each of these". Neither "a", nor "<z", is the other; 
"nor again is either ^4"; for a is what is differentiated, while 
"#" is the differentiation. And this differentiation, 'V, is 
essential to the a which it differentiates. 

That is why "A is both made, and is not made, what it 
is by relation. ... It may be taken as at once condition 
and result, and the question is as to how it can combine this 
variety. For it must combine the diversity, and yet it fails 
to do so". 26 A must be at once "a", the aspect differentiated, 
and V, the phase of differentiation. Without V nothing is 
differentiated, and so there is no quality: without V there is 
no differentiation, and so there is nothing at all. Thus we may 
see that it is divided within itself. It is at once itself as "a" 
and not itself as the "<z" in virtue of which a is differentiated. 
The same difficulty appears when experience is "taken 
from the side of relations. They are nothing intelligible, 
either with or without their qualities". Just as relations 
apart from qualities are a delusion, so together with their 
qualities relations are in no finite context completely intel- 
ligible. For that a relation may differentiate its terms, it 

136 



Some Basic Difficulties 

must "penetrate and alter" them, and so be implicated in 
their respective natures. Yet, that this differentiation may 
not disappear altogether, it must "fall" to some extent 
"between" the qualities which it differentiates, and ipso 
facto relates. That is why a relation involves within itself 
a contrariety: a relation must be at once implicated in and 
yet transcendent of its terms. And so "again we are hurried 
off into the eddy of a hopeless process, since we are forced 
to go on finding relations without end". 27 ' 28 For, in so far as 
a relation or differentiation is implicated in its qualities, 
it does not fall between them; and, in this respect, it fails to 
be a relation at all: in so far as a differentiation falls between 
qualities, it is outside them both, and so again fails to relate 
them. Thus we may notice that relations, taken as moments 
of differentiation which are at once implicated in and 
transcendent of their qualities, are in no case self-consistent 
realities; for they involve within themselves that "infinite 
process" in relational identity which is the moving principle 
and content of degrees of truth and reality. 

In an unfinished, posthumously published essay on 
Relations that was written some thirty years after chapter III 
of Appearance and Reality was composed, Bradley reverts to 
the "infinite process" of self-discrepant quality and relation. 
"A relation (we find) holds between its terms, and no term 
(we find) can itself simply be or become a 'between'. On 
the contrary, in order to be related, a term must keep still 
within itself enough character to make it, in short, itself and 
not anything diverse. And again, while the relations are not 
the terms and the terms are not the relations, neither the 
terms nor the relations can make that whole, in which 
nevertheless we find them. For the terms and the relations 
. . . cease as such to exist, unless each maintains itself 
against whatever is not itself but is outside. And the attempt 
to find the required unity and totality in the terms and the 
relations taken somehow together must end obviously in 

137 



Bradley's Dialectic 

failure."* The attempt in question can end only in failure 
because neither the terms of a relational situation, nor their 
relation, may be self-consistent, or self-identical. For each 
one of the two terms will be a moment of immediacy, while, 
at the same time, it will transcend itself in being continuous 
with the differentiation by which the two terms are differ- 
entiated. Likewise, that differentiation will be internal to, 
or confluent with, the terms which it relates; while, at the 
same time, it will fall between them, and thus transcend 
them. 

This is why "A relation both is and is not what may be 
called the entire relational situation, and hence in this 
respect contradicts itself". t A relation is the whole relational 
situation in the sense that it is what differentiates the 
qualities of that situation. These qualities, were they differ- 
entiated otherwise, would be different qualities. Conversely, 
were the qualities of the situation different, their differ- 
entiation would be different. As thus determining the 
qualities of the situation, and so its own character as 
a differentiation, "A relation to be actual cannot itself 
be less than all and everything that makes the entire 
relational fact."* For it is in virtue of the relation that the 
qualities which it differentiates are the distinct moments 
which they are. In a case of cell-fission, the qualities 
which are being differentiated are confluent with their 
differentiation; as, likewise, that relation is continuous with 
those qualities. At any two points in the process of fission, 
this relation may be marked off from its qualities, and its 
qualities thus will be marked off from their relation. To do 
this may well serve a purpose in practice, but it can establish 
no final distinction; for, on this theory, no distinction short 
of that between Appearance and the Absolute may be final. 
Any distinctions, which were marked off, would themselves 

* Collected Essays, p. 634 /. f Ibid., p. 635. 

J Ibid., p. 636. 

138 



Some Basic Difficulties 

be differentiations. These relations would break out, on the 
one hand, between the moments of fission which we had 
marked off as qualities, and, on the other, between what of 
the process would then be marked off as the differentiation 
of those new qualities. This "what" thus would become a 
quality in its own right: for it would itself be differentiated 
by the distinctions in question. Plainly, such distinctions 
might be multiplied indefinitely within process. Since to 
make distinctions is ipso facto to relate, no limit to the 
relational constituents of a relational situation may be 
established in judgment. 

Yet we have seen that "This on the other hand must be 
denied. For a relation is not its terms, but, on the contrary, 
it is between them. And though the terms may 'enter into 
the relation, 3 yet, if they were nothing beyond it, they 
obviously would no longer be terms".* Within a relational 
situation, differentiations may be found wherever distinctions 
break out. It is in this sense that relations pervade and 
determine the character of that partial whole; and it is in 
this sense that they may be said to be not less than "all ... 
that makes the entire relational fact". Still, in no case is the 
differentiation identical with what is differentiated. The 
qualities differentiated are, to be sure, continuous with their 
relation. Yet, that either the quality or the relation may be 
at all, each one must be distinct. 

That there may be qualities at all, distinctions must 
occur, or be made, and no distinction in Appearance may be 
ultimate. Once the differentiation is marked off it becomes 
distinct in thus being singled out; and hence, between it 
and the initial qualities, fresh relations break out with 
their qualities. No distinction, no differentiation in process, 
may be self-sustaining or absolute. For a differentiation 
will be at once continuous with its qualities and distinct 
from them. In virtue of that distinction, and no matter 
* Ibid., p. 636. 

139 



Bradley's Dialectic 

where in the process it may break out, or where it be dis- 
criminated, a fresh relation, with its own qualities, then 
appears. This new relation, though continuous with its 
qualities, yet is different from them. And thus, again, 
there appear fresh relations with their new qualities. The 
notion of ' 'independent relations" yields an "infinite process" 
in relations that do not relate: the dialectic of relations 
which differentiate their terms exhibits a process wherein 
neither the differentiation, nor the quality differentiated, 
is absolute in its own right, or self-identical. Hence the con- 
clusion that no relational situation is wholly self-consistent, 
or intelligible. 

And so we may come to see that "Every relation (unless 
our previous inquiries have led to error) has a connexion 
with its terms which, not simply internal or external, must 
in principle be both at once."* A relation must be internal 
to its terms in the sense that, as their differentiation, it 
contributes to constitute their qualitative character: yet, 
if the relation is not to disappear altogether, it must, to some 
extent, "fall between" its terms. And, in that sense, a rela- 
tion is external to the qualities which it differentiates. 
The central point for Bradley' s theory of the matter, that 
relations are at once internal and external, is made out at 
length in his unfinished essay. This is done not only in an 
extended discussion of the point itself, but also in an explana- 
tion of why Bradley thinks it "ludicrous" to suppose that, 
on his view, relations could be merely internal. We shall 
revert to this latter point in the next chapter. 

With this body of doctrine freshly in mind, it will be the 
easier to see why it is for Bradley that "identity implies 
difference". We have noticed more than once that the 
identity of a quality is what it is by virtue of the relations 
that differentiate it that make it the quality it is. And since 
a quality is that quality and no other one by virtue of 

* Ibid., p. 641. 
140 



Some Basic Difficulties 

its relations, any alteration in those differentiations ipso 
facto is an alteration in the quality they differentiate. For 
those relations constitute the context which determines 
the identity of that quality. 

We have also noticed that the nature or character of a 
relation is what it is by virtue of the qualities that are 
differentiated by that relation. The infinite process is recip- 
rocal. Just as qualities are determined by their differ- 
entiations to be what respectively they are, so those rela- 
tions are determined to be the differentiations they are by 
the qualities they differentiate. That is why any altera- 
tion in those qualities ipso facto alters those relations. 

Now this is held to be true of all qualities, and of all rela- 
tions, not of only some of either, or of both. Nor is Bradley's 
position here at all arbitrary. That all relations are internal 
everywhere and always follows from the exclusion of external 
relations. Were it suggested that some relations only are 
internal, whereas some are external, the suggestion would 
fly in the face of the conclusion of chapter II of Appearance 
and Reality. 

It follows from the universality of internal relations that 
no limits to the differences that differentiate a quality may 
be prescribed. Any quality is differentiated from all else, 
not merely from some other realities. Identity implies dif- 
ference because where there were no difference there would 
be no distinction and therefore nothing distinct from any- 
thing else.* This difference cannot be the bare numerical 

* "I am not urging that quality without difference is in every sense 
impossible. For all I know, creatures may exist whose life consists, for 
themselves, in one unbroken simple feeling. . . . And if you want to 
call this feeling a quality, by all means gratify your desire. But then 
remember that the whole point is quite irrelevant. For no one is con- 
tending whether the universe is or is not a quality in this sense; but the 
question is entirely as to qualities. And a universe confined to one feeling 
would not only not be qualities, but it would fail even to be one quality, 
as different from others and as distinct from relation." 24 

"I rest my argument upon this, that if there are no differences, there 
are no qualities, since all must fall into one. But, if there is any difference, 

141 



Bradley's Dialectic 

or existential difference of two qualities that would be in- 
discernibly the same. Identity implies qualitative difference. 
"All identity then is qualitative in the sense that it all must 
consist in content and character. There is no sameness of 
mere existence, for mere existence is a vicious abstraction." 527 
Again, "numerical distinction is not distinction without 
difference, that once more is senseless . . . " 531 "Without 
difference in character there can be no distinction, and the 
opposite would seem to be nonsense." 532 Two indiscernible 
qualities would be not two but one. A quality that were not* 
different from all other qualities would be indiscernibly 
the same as some other quality, or qualities. The only 
alternative to this (if there be qualities at all) is that every 
quality should be differentiated from all else. 

The same considerations, mutatis mutandis, apply to 
relations. It follows that every quality and every relation 
are unique. No two qualities, no two relations, can be the 
same or indiscernible. Were it true that all difference is 
difference in quality, it would be the case that every quality 
and every relation is unmatched. The contradictory of this 
consequence, viz., that some qualities and relations are 
not unique but numerically different merely, is incompatible 
with the conclusion that identity implies qualitative dif- 
ference. For were there two simple qualities A x and A 2 
that differed solo numero, there then would be one quality, 
A 23 that did not imply its qualitative difference from all 
else. 

The suggestion that two qualities may be merely numer- 
ically different (or qualitatively the same) in one respect 
(e.g., hue) and qualitatively different in another respect 



then that implies a relation. Without a relation it has no meaning; 
it is a mere word, and not a thought, and no one would take it for 
a thought if he did not, in spite of his protests, import relation into it. 
And this is the point on which all seems to turn. Is it possible to think 
of qualities without thinking of distinct characters?" Bradley answers 
(p. 25) that this is not possible. 

142 



Some Basic Difficulties 

(e.g., saturation), plainly fails to meet the requirement that 
all difference be difference in quality. On that requirement 
every difference would be unique; no quality or relation 
could be matched. In his Logic, Bradley says that the first 
of the principles of reasoning is that what is true in one 
context is true in another context.* His relational view of 
identity on which identity implies qualitative difference is, 
then, absurd; for on it what is true in one context may not 
be so in any other. The attempt to maintain that a quality 
or a relation in this context may be partially the same in that 
context, can hardly succeed. The "part" or "respect" or 
"aspect" that is said to be the same in this context and in 
that one, is enumerably different in the two contexts; and 
yet, by hypothesis, it is qualitatively identical in them both. 
Hence the "part" or "respect" or "aspect" that is in question 
in the second context does imply its qualitative difference 
from that given in the first context. Thus the notion of 
partial sameness affords no escape from the conclusion that 
identity implies qualitative difference, and the converse of 
it that qualitative difference implies uniqueness. 

To those who find in their experience qualities and rela- 
tions that are strictly speaking the same or exactly matched, 
this consequence of the conclusion that identity implies 
qualitative difference will be a difficulty in Bradley's 
dialectic. That difficulty, or the exclusion by Bradley's 
doctrine of qualities and relations that are the same in the 
sense that they differ solo numero, raises a question about the 
validity of his alleged demonstration that all relations are 
internal. 

At the outset of the preceding chapter, we noticed that 
the main arguments of that demonstration stem from a pair 
of proposed disjunctions. The first of these is that presented 

* "What is true in one context is true in another, and what holds of 
a subject within an experiment is valid also beyond that experiment.** 
p. 470. 

143 



Bradley's Dialectic 

in chapter II of Appearance and Reality. On the one hand, 
it is there argued that relations cannot be both separate 
and capable of relating terms. And this alternative is rejected 
because any view of relations as separate entities entails an 
infinite regress in entities that can only fail to relate terms. 
On the other hand, it is argued, on what is assumed to be 
the sole remaining alternative, that relations are internal 
to their terms. Bradley's explanation of what this means 
is given in the course of the statement of the second one of 
the two disjunctions that are in question. 

After having shown there can be no relations that are 
without qualities, Bradley proceeds (in chapter III) to urge 
that distinct qualities without relations are impossible. 
In this connection, the alleged disjunction is between the 
alternative of an infinite process of differences "within" 
every single quality on the one hand, and relations that 
are internal to qualities, on the other hand; where being 
"internal to" means what is meant by being the difference 
that differentiates the qualities thus related. Differentiations 
must "fall somewhere". They may not fall wholly "within" 
the qualities they relate, for that would be to differentiate 
qualities within themselves in an indefinite "process of 
fission". The sole remaining alternative, it is alleged, is that 
on which relations partially would "fall between" the 
qualities they relate and thus be a difference between them. 
In this sense of the term "relation", relations are qualitative 
differences, and qualitative differences are relations. 

Even though the exclusion in chapter II of the alternative 
of separate relations be regarded as final, still the alternative 
on which relations would be internal to their terms, in the 
sense that any alteration in a relation must make a qualitative 
difference in its terms, is not the sole alternative that remains. 
For there is the further alternative on which an altera- 
tion in a relation might entail a merely numerical difference 
in its terms. On this alternative, a relation might be altered 

144 



Some Basic Difficulties 

in character while its new terms would remain no more than 
numerically different from the old ones. The disjunction 
of chapter II between relations as separate, termless entities, 
on the one hand, and relations as making a qualitative 
difference in their terms, on the other, is thus vitiated by the 
fact of an alternative which it does not exclude; namely, 
that on which relations make a difference in their terms that 
is not qualitative, but numerical merely. ^ 

The disjunction of chapter II likewise fails to exclude the 
alternative of numerical difference. The truism that distinct 
qualities must be different does not imply that distinct 
qualities can only be different in nature. Thus, although 
relations without terms, and qualities in no sense different 
are indeed delusions, the exclusion of them by the arguments 
of chapters II and III does not suffice to establish as the 
final alternative that on which terms and their relations 
mutually differentiate themselves in point of quality. For 
there remains the further alternative on which a relation 
requires terms that may be no more than numerically 
different from other qualities, while at the same time terms 
are related by relations that may be no more than numeric- 
ally different from other relations. This would seem to satisfy 
the logic of Bradley's requirement that relations relate terms, 
and that distinct qualities should be different. 

Some Idealists will reply to this that any notion of mere 
numerical difference is nonsensical on Bradley's theory of 
identity as relational. And that is even obvious. But it ought 
to be clear enough to students of Bradley that his doctrine 
of relational identity is no absolute fulguration of spirit. 
Relational identity is the moment of immediacy in the process 
of mediation that is the internality of relations. The doctrine 
that identity is relational is one with the internality of 
relations: it designates and lays emphasis on the essentially 
mediated character of the identity of any appearance. 

If an "external relation" be considered not as a "separate" 

145 K 



Bradley's Dialectic 

entity, but as a universal that requires at least some pair 
of terms or other for its illustration, then Bradley begs the 
question of external relations by his doctrinaire assumption 
that all differences are differences in quality. Now to say 
this is not even to question, much less to deny, the validity 
of the arguments of chapter II against the reality of relations 
as separate, termless entities. Any such notion about relations 
would be a delusion indeed. The point is simply that a 
denial of reality to such entities and their exclusion from 
theory constrains us to accept Bradley's theory of relations 
if and only if it is the sole remaining alternative. And that is 
not the case. 

Let us acknowledge that relations require terms. External 
relations as separate, termless entities are the merest of 
chimeras. How much follows from this? At least that any 
relation requires some terms or other. A relation with no 
terms of any sort would be verbiage. But this much falls far 
short of what Bradley is concerned to demonstrate by the 
method of exclusion; namely, that relations and qualities 
mutually differentiate and thus determine the qualitative 
character of each other with the consequence that identity 
implies qualitative difference. 

Bradley's arguments do indeed exclude the alternative 
of separate relations, either as found in experience or as 
produced there by abstraction. But that much leaves 
something more to the matter than the alternative that is 
elucidated by Bradley. Before the view that qualities and 
relations are such that the identity of any quality (or any 
relation) implies its qualitative difference from all else, 
our position is not ineluctable For all that the exclusion 
of separate relations proves to the contrary, a quality and, a 
relation may be no more than numerically different from 
other qualities and relations. 

We are assured by Bradley that * 'numerical difference" 
is nonsense. That it surely is, within the system of Bradley's 

146 



Some Basic Difficulties 

dialectic. Two qualities differing solo numero would violate 
the requirement that identity imply qualitative difference. 
And "numerical difference" would be misguided nonsense 
in any case if the alternative view of relations that Bradley 
elucidates showed the alternative of qualities and relations 
that are enumerably, not qualitatively, different to be self- 
stultifying. That much is shown in the matter of relations 
as separate entities. But Bradley's dialectic of relations 
excludes the alternative of numerical difference, not by 
'stultifying it, but by the assumption that all difference is 
difference in quality. 

So far, the requirement that identity imply qualitative 
difference has been referred to as a consequence of Bradley's 
theory of quality and relation. That requirement can be 
brought out as a consequence of the dialectic of relations 
because the dialectic must assume it to be the dialectic it is. 
The reason why there could not be two processes of cell- 
fission that were in every qualitative respect the same is that 
Bradley takes it for granted that to differentiate is to make 
a difference that is a qualitative difference. This presup- 
position excludes the very possibility of two processes of 
development that would differ solo numero. For the quali- 
ties and relations constituting those processes would be 
enumerably different merely; they would not differ in 
character. 

Consider that in two processes which were the same in 
character, the qualities could be differentiated by differences 
that fell at once within and between those qualities. Thus 
we would "have relation at once". 24 And in that unity of 
immanence within quality and transcendence of quality 
which is the very being of relation we would have the self- 
discrepancy of all relations. On the other hand, qualities 
would be both within and transcendent of their relations. 
And this would yield the self-discrepancy in the aspect of 
immediacy that is the fate also of quality. "We have found 

147 



Bradley's Dialectic 

that qualities, taken without relations, have no intelligible 
meaning. Unfortunately, taken together with them, they are 
equally unintelligible. They cannot, in the first place, 
be wholly resolved into the relations." 25 "Hence the qualities 
must be, and must also be related. But there is hence a 
diversity which falls inside each quality. Each has a double 
character, as both supporting and as being made by the 
relation. It may be taken as at once condition and result, 
and the question is as to how it can combine this variety. 
For it must combine the diversity, and yet it fails to do so." 26 ' 
Bradley's elucidation of the principle of this failure has been 
quoted above. Because self-transcendence is self-discrepancy, 
and because quality transcends itself in relation, quality is 
self-discrepant. Quality must be "both made, and not made, 
what it is by relation". 26 It must be made by relation in that 
without relations a quality would be undifFerentiated. It 
must be not made by relation in that the relations must fall 
beyond the quality and be something in their own right. 
That is why quality is self-transcendent. And whatever is 
self-transcendent ipso facto is self-discrepant. ,/ 

Bradley brings out the same consequences on the side of 
relation. The burden of chapter III is the mutual self- 
transcendence of quality and relation. Quality without 
relation would be nothing, for it would be undifFerentiated. 
Were the relation contained wholly within the quality, the 
relation would be merely internal to the quality. In. that 
case, the relation would be wholly quality, and so it would 
fail to be relation. Therefore, relations must fall between 
the qualities they relate. In so far as relations are the self- 
transcendent aspect of quality they are relations and 
not sdf-discrepant. But in so far as they are in and of the 
qualities they differentiate, relations transcend themselves 
and thus they are self-discrepant. Now in the course of the 
entire elucidation of the mutual self-discrepancy of quality 
and relation, no demonstration that all difference is differ- 

148 



Some Basic Difficulties 

ence in quality is advanced. The thesis of the argument is 
the two-edged dialectic of quality and relation. 

It would be futile to attempt to demonstrate that all 
difference is difference in character or quality. Consider that, 
for familiar reasons, you could not demonstrate it by 
induction. That leaves deduction, and intuition. Your 
premises have to contain anything you demonstrate by 
deduction, so that method would beg this question. And 
your intuition or mine demonstrates nothing to the other 
fellow. 

If Bradley assumes that all difference is difference in 
quality, this is not to say that the assumption is made 
arbitrarily. It was forced upon Bradley by his view of 
appearance as a process of becoming or development, 
wherein qualities or moments of immediacy are being related 
by their differences. That differences may be no more than 
enumerably different is not an alternative for Bradley 
because, on that alternative, becoming is perforce left out 
of account. Qualities and relations no more than numerically 
different would be the same in character. Hence the self- 
same quality and the self-same relation might be repeated 
in different contexts without thereby being altered. This is 
to say, that a set of qualities and a set of relations which 
differed respectively solo numero would exhibit (say) ten 
cases of a single quality, and (say) ten cases of a single 
relation. These qualities and these relations would be the 
same, regardless of their contexts. Therefore the qualities 
would be respectively self-identical absolutely, as would be 
also the relations; their identity would be absolute, not 
relative. Hence those qualities and relations could only be 
changeless; they could be in change or in succession, but they 
themselves could not be changing. Therefore they could not 
be moments of any process of becoming. 

It is because of his assumption that experience is becoming 
that Bradley implicitly excludes the alternative of numerical 



Bradley's Dialectic 

difference from the relational way of thought, and that he 
explicitly denounces it as the nonsense it is on the pre- 
supposition 'of his dialectic of experience as becoming. It is 
also because of that same assumption that Bradley is 
constrained (e.g., in the Logic and in Note A of Appearance 
and Reality) to deny the validity of the Laws of Thought and 
to identify the contradictory with the contrary. For so long 
as the validity of the Law of Non-Contradiction is not 
denied, the validity of the Law of Identity of course is not 
denied, and the identity of A is absolute, not relational. If 
the identity of A be absolute, then A may not be a moment 
in any process of becoming. 

Since, for Bradley, Appearance is in becoming, and no 
process of becoming may be elucidated^onsistently_b)^ a 
logic of contradictories, the contradictory must be identified 
with the contrary, if Appearance is not to remain, in his 
view, a succession of atomic mysteries. This way of repudiat- 
ing logic yields a middle term between any two opposites. 
Once this middle term is construed as being the moment of 
mediation that differentiates the qualitative characters of 
its terms, the necessary condition of the internality of 
relations is laid down. The middle term has become the 
moment of mediation or differentiation that Bradley calls 
relation; and the terms thus differentiated are the moments 
of immediacy or quality in the process that is Appearance. 
If only because this repudiation of logic, made by identifying 
the contradictory with the contrary, excludes the Law of 
Excluded Middle, ipso facto it denies the very possibility of a 
difference that were merely numerical. Some questions as 
to how this procedure in philosophy may be justified will be 
considered in the last chapter of this essay. 

The relational way of thought, we have seen, carries us 
on to the notion of the absolute Whole. This is something 
that transcends any moment of mediation in an Identity that 
is absolute. Since this Identity is absolute, not relational, 

150 



Some Basic Difficulties 

we cannot attain it by the relational way of thought that is 
ours without choice. No aspect of this Whole, no coherence 
of aspects, however comprehensive, may be the ultimate and 
absolute subject of any judgement. "We never have, or are, a 
state which is the perfect unity of all aspects; and we must 
admit that in their special natures they remain inexplicable. 
An explanation would be the reduction of their plurality to 
unity, in such a way that the relation between the unity and 
the variety was understood. And everywhere an explanation 
bf this kind in the end is beyond us." 415 It is beyond us 
because we never arrive at the end of the relational way of 
thought. To do so would be to commit intellectual suicide. 
For we are finite centres,, "The internal being of everything 
finite~3epends on that which is beyond it. Hence everywhere, 
insisting on a so-called fact, we have found ourselves led by 
its inner character into something outside itself. And this 
self-contradiction, this unrest and ideality of all things 
existing is a clear proof that, though such things are, their 
being is but appearance." 404 The being of the finite depends 
on its context; it is essentially self-transcendent, or self- 
discrepant, and that is the mark of appearance. Yet the self- 
discrepant posits its contrary; namely, self-coherence. Thus 
the degree to which an appearance is self-coherent the 
extent to which its self-discrepancies are resolved is the 
degree to which it is real. The internality or coherence of 
quality and relation carries judgement ineluctably to the 
notion of a Unity that is absolute, not relational. 

This Unity can only be single and unmatched. Two 
Absolutes would stand to each other in external, empty 
relation; and any such "relation" is verbiage. "Reality is 
one. It must be single, because plurality, taken as real, 
contradicts itself. Plurality implies relations, and, through its 
relations, it unwillingly asserts always a superior unity. To 
suppose the universe plural is therefore to contradict oneself 
and, after all, to suppose that it is one. Add one world to 



Bradley's Dialectic 

another, and forthwith both worlds have become relative, 
each the finite appearance of a higher and single Reality. 
And plurality as appearance (we have seen) must fall 
within, must belong to, and must qualify the unity." 460 
Any attempt to assert the reality of a plurality of ultimates 
would be in effect an attempt to resuscitate the delusion of 
separate relations. 

That the Absolute is one and single, that it is sentient, 
that it is a trans-relational harmony wherein all self- 
discrepancy is resolved, these are conclusions to which w6 
are carried by Bradley's dialectic. Matters of final detail are 
questions about which Bradley expresses ultimate doubts. 
But he denies that the finality of the notion of the Absolute 
is open to doubt. "With regard to the main character of that 
Absolute our position is briefly this. We hold that our 
conclusion is certain, and that to doubt it logically is 
impossible. There is no other view, there is no other idea 
beyond the view here put forward. It is impossible rationally 
even to entertain the question of another possibility." 459 
These are very strong claims indeed. But in the next sentences 
Bradley goes on to give reasons why they must be made. 
As we should expect, he goes right on to say that "Outside 
our main result there is nothing except the wholly un- 
meaning, or else something which on scrutiny is seen really 
not to fall outside. Thus the supposed Other will, in short, 
turn out to be actually the same; or it will contain elements 
included within our view of the Absolute, but elements 
dislocated and so distorted into erroneous appearance. 
And the dislocation itself will find a place within the limits 
of our system." 459 ' 460 

"Our result, in brief, cannot be doubted, since it contains 
all possibilities. Show us an idea, we can proclaim, which is 
hostile to our scheme, and we will show you an element 
which really is contained within it. And we will demonstrate 
your idea to be a self-contradictory piece of our system, an 

152 



Some Basic Difficulties 

internal fragment which only through sheer blindness can 
fancy itself outside. We will prove that its independence and 
isolation are nothing in the world but a failure to perceive 
more than one aspect of its own nature." 460 The proposed 
alien would be foreign to and therefore different from the 
Whole. On that account alone the alleged alien could not 
be a separate entity, out of all relation to all else. For by 
virtue of its differences it would be in relation with all that 
from which it is different. So long as Bradley's dialectic of 
(Duality and relation be regarded as irrefragable, his monism 
is beyond successful denial. 

It may be well to add that Bradley expresses himself ex- 
plicitly in the matter of the strength and scope of his claims. 
"And the shocked appeal to our modesty and our weakness 
will not trouble us. It is on this very weakness that, in a 
sense, we have taken our stand. We are impotent to divide 
the universe into the universe and something outside. We 
are incapable of finding another field in which to place our 
inability and give play to our modesty. This other area for 
us is mere pretentious nonsense; and on the ground of our 
weakness we do not feel strong enough to assume that non- 
sense is fact. We, in other words, protest against the sense- 
less attempt to transcend experience. We urge that a mere 
doubt entertained may involve that attempt, and that in 
the case of our main conclusion it certainly does so. Hence 
in its outline that conclusion for us is certain; and let us 
endeavour to see how far the certainty goes." 460 Bradley's 
claim for the finality of his main conclusion is forced upon 
him by the nature of his case. The internality of relations 
prevents us from dividing the universe into itself and some- 
thing beyond it. The alleged Other could only be different 
from its foil, and that difference would be the relation of 
the asserted Other with and so within the Whole. That is 
why anything whatever we may mention will "be included 
in our view of the Absolute". For that it may be mentionable 

153 



Bradley's Dialectic 

at all it must be distinguishable, and therefore somehow 
distinct, or related. The assertion of an ultimate, intrin- 
sically individuated plurality of reals contradicts the assump- 
tion that relation means what is meant by difference, where 
difference is difference in quality. 

Bradley's main conclusion about the Absolute is certain 
in that before it Bradley has no redress. But if that conclusion 
"cannot be doubted, since it contains all possibilities", at the 
same time it does not exhibit many actualities. Each chapter 
of Appearance and Reality elucidates a phase of appearance ill 
as much detail, presumably, as Bradley discerns and can 
muster in discourse. That this falls far short of a realization 
in any judgement of the self-fulfilling and self-fulfilled is 
insisted upon as inevitable. Our relational way of thought 
cannot even pretend to omniscience and not thereby deny 
its own nature. The claim to certainty about the main charac- 
ter of the Absolute affirms no more than a notion of 
absolute identity in differences; and this is affirmed under a 
constraint that is without choice within Bradley's doctrine 
of relations. 

This constraint does not carry us very far into the self- 
coherent details of the matter. For Bradley's " endeavour 
to see how far the certainty goes" is unrelenting but not 
self-stultifying. He takes up aspects of experience in some 
detail, and presses them hard enough to make them disclose 
the self-discrepancy of their content that is at once the 
development of all thought and the ultimate defeat of any 
judgement, no matter how self-coherent. The immediate 
referent of any judgement is a finite centre of qualities and 
relations. This focus of the judgement is real to the degree 
to which it is coherent with the Absolute. We have repeatedly 
noticed that every distinct content is related within the 
Whole by its very differences from everything else within 
the Absolute. For this reason, among others, the subject 
term of every judgement is an adjective of the Real no less 

154 



Some Basic Difficulties 

than is the predicate. The subject term and the predicate 
term, in being different content, are thus related to each 
other; and, in being different from all other qualities and 
relations, S and P ipso facto are related to every other content 
of the organic Whole. For that reason the Absolute is the 
ultimate,* but unattainable, referent of every judgement. 
The Absolute is the ultimate referent because it is the prin- 
ciple of identity in the differences, or adjectives of the Whole; 
and they are the content of judgements. Yet it is unattain- 
eible by the relational way of thought. For to attain to the 
Absolute would be to transcend the relational, and that 
would be the suicide of the finite mind. 

Nevertheless, it is urged that we are not lost in a relativism 
that is without an attainable principle of survey and com- 
parison. For the criterion of comparative degrees of reality in 
Appearance, and of comparative degrees of truth in judge- 
ment, is that of being comprehensive. "Hence to be more 
or less true, and to be more or less real, is to be separated 
by an interval, smaller or greater, from all-inclusiveness or 
self-consistency. Of two given appearances the one more 
wide, or more harmonious, is more real. It approaches 
nearer to a single, all-containing individuality. To remedy its 
imperfections, in other words, we should have to make a 
smaller alteration. The truth and the fact, which, to be 
converted into the Absolute, would require less re-arrange- 
ment and addition, is more real and truer. And this is what 
we mean by degrees of reality and truth. To possess more the 
character of reality, and to contain within oneself a greater 
amount of the real, are two expressions for the same thing.'* 
322, 323 The earmark of degrees of individuality and so of 
reality and truth is comparative self-coherence. Since the 
identity of any finite experience implies the qualitative differ- 
ence of it from all else, the identity or individuality of that 
single experience is determined by its relations within the 
* See above, pp. 126-129. 
155 



Bradley's Dialectic 

systematic Whole of which it is an appearance. As the focus 
of a judgement is enlarged, the scope of the coherence of its 
constituent qualities and relations within the Whole is thus 
rendered the more comprehensive. For with that enlarge- 
ment in focus, the judgement has become a less partial aspect. 
And with that increase in comprehension, the judgement 
has become less erroneous, or truer. "Truth must exhibit 
the mark of internal harmony, or, again, the mark of 
expansion and all-inclusiveness. And these two characteris- 
tics are diverse aspects of a single principle. That which 
contradicts itself, in the first place, jars, because the whole, 
immanent within it, drives its parts into collision. And the 
way to find harmony, as we have seen, is to re-distribute these 
discrepancies in a wider arrangement. But, in the second 
place, harmony is incompatible with restriction and finitude. 
For that which is not all-inclusive must by virtue of its 
essence internally disagree; and, if we reflect, the reason of 
this becomes plain. That which exists in a whole has external 
relations. Whatever it fails to include within its own nature, 
must be related to it by the whole, and related externally. 
Now these extrinsic relations, on the one hand, fall outside 
of itself, but, upon the other hand, cannot do so. For a 
relation must at both ends affect, and pass into, the being 
of its terms. And hence the inner essence of what is finite 
itself both is, and is not, the relations which limit it. Its 
nature is hence incurably relative, passing, that is, beyond 
itself, and importing, again, into its own core a mass of 
foreign connections. Thus to be defined from without is, 
in principle, to be distracted within." 321 ' 322 For to be 
defined externally or extrinsically is to be differentiated by 
the relations that thus define their qualities from without. 
Since these relations fall at once without and within their 
qualities, those qualities are distracted within by the 
internality in process of their relations, or aspects of self- 
transcendence. This element of inner distraction is the 

156 



Some Basic Difficulties 

principle of growth in degrees of individuality. "By growth 
the element becomes, more and more, a consistent individual, 
containing in itself its own nature; and it forms, more and 
more, a whole inclusive of discrepancies and reducing them 
to system. The two aspects, of extension and harmony, are 
thus in principle one. . . ," 322 That is why to be more and 
more true, or more and more real, is to be deprived less and 
less of all-inclusiveness or self-coherence. 

The ultimate resolution of discrepancies is fulfilled in an 
Fdentity that is not relational, but Absolute. We have 
noticed that the Absolute may stand in no relations. For 
were the Absolute a term in any relation whatever, ipso 
facto the Absolute would be relational, not absolute. It is 
an emphasized, not incidental, conclusion of Bradley's 
dialectic that the Absolute is not available to finite minds. 
There are, then, at least two reasons why we may not 
avail ourselves of the Absolute as a criterion of truth and 
reality. The Absolute may not stand in a relation, cognitive 
or otherwise, without thereby falling from ultimacy. And 
the finite mind could attain to the Absolute only by trans- 
cending the relational, thereby committing suicide. 

These consequences of Bradley's dialectic carry with 
them further basic difficulties. For they leave us with no 
criterion of degrees of truth and reality. To be sure, Bradley 
writes of inclusiveness and harmony, or coherence, as being 
the standard in question. Yet this does (and could) not 
mean that this standard is anything distinguishable from the 
very degrees of truth and reality themselves of which that 
standard is the criterion. The degree to which any finite 
whole is coherent is in no sense distinct from that appearance 
itself. For the coherence of that finite whole is that whole 
itself that very appearance, which is self-coherent to the 
degree that it is individual, and is the individual it is in 
virtue of that self-coherence. 

It might well be urged that the Absolute is the criterion 

157 



Bradley's Dialectic 

of degrees of coherence if that Being were, or could be, 
available to finite minds. Yet the Absolute is something 
distinct from any appearance, no matter how highly self- 
coherent it be. Therefore, the Absolute could not have its 
being at any level of degrees of truth and reality. And the 
relational way of thought could not attain to the Absolute 
and remain relational, just as the Absolute could stand in 
no relation whatever and remain absolute. Willy nilly, with- 
out choice, we are confined to the degrees of reality that 
are appearance. This means that we have no criterion 
of degrees of truth and reality that would be distinct from 
those very appearances themselves. And that is tantamount 
to having no criterion at all. 

This is not intended to lead up to practical difficulties 
that might be met with in the course of any attempt to apply 
a criterion of comparison in point of coherence. Often 
enough that may be very difficult to do. The second draft 
of Hyperion, as read by Amy Lowell, is more coherent in her 
interpretation of it than the first draft. Yet that comparison 
was realized and made out in discourse by one who was a 
poet in felt imagery and ambition. The difficulty in question, 
however, lies far deeper down than any difficulty in the 
application of a criterion in practice. Since there is no avail- 
able standard of coherence, how are we to compare this 
appearance as being more coherent than that one ? More- 
over, in the absence of any available criterion, we cannot 
determine just how coherent any single appearance may be. 
If we cannot decide that much in some case or other, how 
can we compare this Appearance as being more coherent 
than that one ? 

Surely, though, Wuthering Heights is more coherent than 
An American Tragedy, we may be told. And on assignable 
grounds that comparison might be easily made out.* But 

* For example, on the grounds laid down by E. M. Forster in Aspects 
of the Novel. 

158 



Some Basic Difficulties 

in that case we have posited our criteria of comparison. 
On Bradley's dialectic it is a repeatedly emphasized con- 
clusion that knowledge of the Absolute is not available to us. 
Now we may agree that we do see how, on the coherence 
theory of truth and reality, it must be that an appearance 
becomes the more true and real as it becomes the more 
coherent. But still we are obliged to ask, how true, how 
real is it at any stage of this expansion ? 

Short of the Absolute, we have only appearances. The 
degree to which an appearance is coherent is in no respect 
or sense distinct from that appearance or concrete universal 
itself. Therefore, either the coherence of an appearance is 
its own index, or we have no index of degrees of coherence. 
The suggestion that comprehensiveness is the test, and that 
it can be applied by setting up a certain very comprehensive 
appearance as a norm under which the comparative degrees 
of other appearances might be decided upon, is really of no 
avail. For it begs the question. Either the superior coherence 
of the norm is its own index, or, again, we have no index. 
And if, in the case of the norm, we assume that coherence 
is its own index, then by the same token we should have to 
make the same assumption about the coherence of any other 
appearance; and so the suggested norm would be useless. 
On the other hand, if we have no index of degrees of coher- 
ence, then the selection of the norm could only be arbitrary. 

It would seem that, in Bradley's view, coherence is its 
own index. The coherence of a relational situation involves 
satisfaction for the intellect. This satisfaction diminishes or 
grows as there is a decrease or increase in coherence. And 
Bradley holds that any growth in intellectual satisfaction 
is the index of fuller coherence in judgement. Yet the 
validity of this converse is at least doubtful. Even though it 
be established by Bradley's arguments in that regard that 
the higher the degree of coherence the fuller the intellectual 
satisfaction, it would hardly follow (or appear to follow, 

159 



Bradley's Dialectic 

except by illicit conversion) that the fuller the satisfaction 
the higher the coherence. Degrees of coherence may be an 
index of degrees of satisfaction. But if the coherence theory 
about the nature of truth is to afford a criterion of degrees 
of truth, what we need is an index of degrees of coherence. 
And that we do not and cannot have, short of the unavailable 
Absolute. 



1 60 



CHAPTER IX 

Relational and Absolute 
Identity 



i 

WE have seen why it is, for Bradley, that identity implies 
qualitative difference. Since qualitative differences, or 
differentiations, are relations, to say that identity implies 
difference is to say that identity implies relation. Indeed, 
the dialectic of quality and relation elucidates the mutually 
relative character or identity of the aspect of quality and 
the aspect of differentiation which together constitute "the 
relational situation." 

In being thus relational, the identity or character of any 
experience or appearance is in process. If an experience 
were self-identical absolutely and in its own ontological 
right, it would be difficult indeed to see how it could be in 
process. If A were A absolutely, rather than relatively, 
it could not change into, or become, Y. For in the course 
of the process A, Ay, Ayy, . . . Y, there would finally be a 
point at which A was no longer A and was not yet Y. On a 
view of identity as absolute, there could be no middle term 
by which this gap in becoming might be mediated. Thus 
one apparent virtue of a dialectic of contraries is that between 
contraries there is a middle term in and through which the 
contrarieties in becoming are incessantly sublated. 

A failure to see that for Bradley appearance is process 
wherein the identity or character of an experience is relational 
and, short of the Absolute itself, never absolute, would 

161 L 



Bradley's Dialectic 

blind us to the nature of his dialectic. Should we attempt 
to illustrate Bradley's conception of relation as differentiation 
by thinking of a relation as a universal that requires at 
least two particulars, our attempt could only be irrelevant. 
Defined as an abstract universal, a relation would be self- 
identical and therefore changeless. Evidently such beings 
could not be moments of differentiation in process. Then 
again, were a sense-quality, conceived of as self-identical, 
taken to illustrate Bradley's view of quality as the moment 
of immediacy in the process that is appearance, this too 
would be a mistake. For no such being as a self-identical and 
therefore changeless sense-quality could be in process at all. 
When largely irrelevant matters are taken to illustrate 
Bradley's theory of relations, rather unfriendly criticism 
sometimes results. Let us consider the following passage 
from Professor C. D. Broad's Examination of McTaggarfs 
Philosophy. In reply to his own question, "Is there any valid 
objection to there being relations?"* Professor Broad 
considers two lines of argument. The first of these is drawn 
from Leibnitz, the second is ascribed to Bradley. It runs as 
follows: "The second argument against relations is that of 
Bradley. The argument is that, if A is to be related by R to B y 
A must be related by a relation R l to /?, and R must be 
related by a relation R l to B. On the same grounds A must 
be related by a relation R n to R l9 R l must be related by a 
relation R 12 to R, R must be related by a relation R 2 i to R 2> 
and R 2 must be related by a relation R 22 to B. Similar 
remarks will apply to all these four relational facts, and so 
at the next stage there will be eight relational facts, at the 
next to this sixteen, and so on without end. Bradley's 
contention is that this series could not have a first term unless 
it had a last term, which it plainly does not. McTaggart 
admits that there is this endless series in connection with 
any relational fact, but he denies that it is vicious. His 

* P. 84. 
162 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

answer amounts to saying that the first term, i.e. that A 
has R to 5, is a fact in its own right, and that the rest of the 
series consists merely of further consequences of this fact. 
I think it might fairly be said that, whilst Leibniz's 
argument depends on insisting that relations shall behave 
as if they were qualities, Bradley's argument depends on 
insisting that they shall behave as if they were particulars 
like the terms which they relate. It is plain that Bradley 
thinks of A and B as being like two objects fastened together with a 
Bit of string, and he thinks of R as being like the bit of string. He 
then remembers that the objects must be glued or sealed 
to both ends of the bit of string if the latter is to fasten them 
together. And then, I suppose, another kind of glue is needed 
to fasten the first drop of glue to the object A on the one side 
and to the bit of string on the other; and another kind of 
glue is needed to fasten the second drop of glue to the object 
B on the one side and to the string on the other. And so on 
without end. Charity bids us avert our eyes from the 
pitiable spectacle of a great philosopher using an argument 
which would disgrace a child or a savage. 55 * 

Professor Broad makes no reference to the text that he 
calls in disgrace. But he would seem to have in mind, more 
or less, the argument in the chapter on Substantive and 
Adjective by which Bradley is brought to his denial of the 
reality of relations as independent entities. In several ways, 
Professor Broad misconstrues that argument. // is not an 
argument against the reality of relations ; it is an argument against 
the reality of relations as independent entities. Yet Professor 
Broad introduces it as one reply to his own question, "Is 
there any valid objection to there being relations? 55 not, 
is there any valid objection to there being relations taken as 
separate entities? In this latter form, the question has a 
restricted bearing: it is a question about the reality of 
relations tout court. And that one sense of the term relation 
* Pp. 84, 85. My italics. 
163 



Bradley's Dialectic 

is the concern of Bradley's argument to the conclusion that 
any notion of relations as independent entities leads to an 
"infinite process" 1 * (my italics) in relations that do not 
relate. 

Yet Professor Broad writes of this argument as though it 
were Bradley's aim to show by it that there are no relations; 
that there is a "valid objection to there being relations". 
That this is so no one who has followed and remembered 
the dialectic of chapter III, Relation and Quality, is likely to 
agree. Bradley's argument against the possible reality df 
independent entities as relations is just that, and not itself 
an argument against anything more than that. 

Professor Broad asserts: "It is plain that Bradley thinks of 
A and B as being like two objects fastened together With a bit 
of string, and he thinks of R as being like the bit of string." 
If one wanted to one could adduce "the bit of string" as an 
illustration of relations as independent entities. In that 
connection also one could write with Professor Broad of the 
glue, and that Bradley "remembers" that glue would have 
to be introduced into an intellectual conclusion; perhaps in 
order to make it at home in certain quarters. That way of 
taking Bradley's argument against relations as independent 
entities might be less objectionable were it restricted to that 
argument, not presented as reasoning by him against the 
reality of relations. 

But pieces of string and bits of glue would hardly afford 
an illustration of moments of differentiation in process. So 
long as Bradley's critics take it that his argument to the 
"infinite process" that results from the notion of relations as 
independent entities is his constructive theory of relations, 
they will criticize that argument of the chapter Substantive 
and Adjective, and neglect the content of the chapter Relation 
and Quality. That is what has happened in the past. There 
are more than a few criticisms of the argument against 
separate relations; but discussion and criticism of the 

164 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

positive doctrine of chapter III is comparatively scarce and 
far to seek. 

And so long as Bradley's unfriendly critics concentrate 
on the chosen argument in chapter II, it is likely they will 
take a relation for Bradley as being something that is real 
independently of its context in process or Appearance; as 
something static, or as a piece of string and bits of glue. 
For in that argument Bradley is concerned with something 
that would be independently real, static, and so almost 
anything different from a moment of differentiation. The 
notion of that something is what involves the "infinite 
process" in relations that do not relate simply because they 
are ex hypothesi independent, disconnected entities. And 
it is to that notion that Bradley denies any validity whatever, 
not to the doctrine that is elucidated in the next chapter, 
Relation and Quality. 

To be sure, the validity of that theory of relations is not 
regarded as absolute. That theory itself is a judgement; 
albeit one to which we are brought by the elucidation of 
the matter which Bradley has worked out. And short of the 
unattainable Absolute Idea, any judgement will be con- 
tingent upon factors lying beyond its scope, even though 
that mental synthesis be carried out to a rather preternatural 
extreme. As judgement is contingent and true to a degree, 
so any appearance is contingent and real to some degree 
or other. Short of the Absolute nothing is absolutely real. 
But everything is real to a degree. 

Yet we have seen that Dr. A C. Ewing, writing in answer 
to a question as to which, if any, of his senses of "internal 
relations" were appropriate to Bradley's theory of the 
matter, asserts that Bradley denies the reality of relations. 
"I did not say of which of my senses of 'internal relations' 
Bradley is a supporter because Bradley denied the reality of 
relations and therefore can not have held that relations 
really were internal in any of my senses or in any other 

165 



Bradley's Dialectic 

sense."* Apparently Dr. Ewing is at one with Professor 
Broad in taking it that Bradley denies the reality of relations. 
The consequence of this, that "Bradley cannot have held 
that relations really were internal in ... any sense",! 
Dr. Ewing does not boggle at pointing out himself. 

It is the case that Bradley denies the reality of relations 
as independent entities. And it is the case that he denies the 
absolute reality of relations as differences. He denies also the 
absolute reality of qualities. As relations independent of 
qualities are a delusion, so together with their qualities 
they are not completely intelligible in any finite context. 
For that a relation may be internal, it must contribute to 
constitute its qualities: yet, that it may not disappear 
altogether, it must "fall" to some extent "between" them. A 
relation thus involves within itself a contrariety. A relation 
must be at once implicated in and transcendent of its 
qualities. For in so far as a relation contributes to constitute 
its qualities it does not fall between them, and so far it 
fails to be a relation at all; on the other hand, in so far as a 
relation falls between its qualities it is outside them both and 
so again fails to relate them. 26 " 28 

Hence no moment of differentiation could be absolute. 
In a process of fission no absolute distinction is there to be 
found between the moments of quality and the moments of 
differentiation. Rather there is "a diversity which falls 
inside each quality. Each has a double character, as both 
supporting and as being made by the relation". 26 Likewise, 
each relation has a double character, as at once making and 
being made by its terms. Qualities taken without relations 
(i.e., as absolute), and relations without qualities (i.e., 
independent or absolute), are both, Bradley finds, quite 
unintelligible by the relational way of thought. These 
extremes of abstraction are wholly verbal. Their reality is 

* The Journal of Philosophy) Vol. XXXII, No. 10, May 9, 1935, p. 273. 
My italics. f Ibid. 

166 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

entirely a matter of words. Otherwise they are unreal. 
For their "designations" refer to nothing. But a quality 
that is a moment of immediacy which is at once making 
and made by its differentiations or relations is not an 
absolute. The self-identity of the character of it is relational, 
not absolute. And a relation or differentiation that is at 
once in and of its qualities and transcendent of them is 
no absolute, no isolated entity, but rather a copula in 
process. 

'Appearance, as distinguished from Absolute reality, is 
relational; any appearance is as unreal as it is inconsistent, 
and as real as it is self-coherent. We have seen this much in 
Bradley's view, but in view of the opposition, it may be well 
to cause him to repeat it. At the outset of chapter XIII, 
The General Nature of 'Reality, he writes, "Whatever is rejected 
as appearance is, for that reason, no mere nonentity. It 
cannot bodily be shelved and merely got rid of, and, there- 
fore, since it must fall somewhere, it must belong to reality. 
To take it as existing somehow and somewhere in the unreal, 
would surely be quite meaningless. For reality must own and 
cannot be less than appearance, and that is the one positive 
result which, so far, we have reached." 119 "Is there an abso- 
lute criterion?" Bradley goes on to ask. "This question, to 
my mind, is answered by a second question: How otherwise 
should we be able to say anything at all about appearance? 
For through the last Book, the reader will remember, we 
were for the most part criticizing. We were judging pheno- 
mena and were condemning them, and throughout we 
proceeded as if the self-contradictory could not be real. 
But this was surely to have and to apply an absolute criterion. 
. . . Ultimate reality is such that it does not contradict 
itself; here is an absolute criterion. And it is proved absolute 
by the fact that, either in endeavouring to deny it, or even 
in attempting to doubt it, we tacitly assume its validity." 120 
"We may say that everything, which appears, is somehow 



Bradley's Dialectic 

real in such a way as to be self-consistent. The character of the 
real is to possess everything phenomenal in a harmonious 
form." 123 

Relations are the differences that differentiate the pheno- 
mena of appearance. A relational situation is unreal to the 
degree that it is self-contradictory or self-discrepant; it is 
real to the degree to which it is self-consistent or self- 
coherent. Nothing short of Absolute reality is real without 
qualification. But to argue that the unreality of relations 
(and qualities) means for Bradley that they are nothing at 
all would be to argue that for him Appearance is nothing 
at all. And that would be silly, at best. Moreover, any such 
misunderstanding would ignore the doctrines of The General 
Nature of Reality (chapters XIII and XIV), Thought and 
Reality (chapter XV), Error (chapter XVI), The This and 
the Mine (chapter XIX), Degrees of Truth and Reality (chapter 
XXIV) and The Absolute and its Appearances; in short, the 
notion that Bradley denies reality to relations leaves out of 
account the basic passages of his dialectic. 

The phases of Appearance that are examined in Book I 
of Appearance and Reality are shown to be infected with the 
self-discrepancy of their constituent qualities and relations 
which is elucidated in detail in chapter III. Thus space 
and time are less than absolutely real. But it would be mis- 
leading to say that Bradley denies the reality of time. 
He denies, over and over again, the self-consistency, the 
absolute reality of any and every form of appearance. 
How could he do otherwise? Appearances are processes, 
whether they be motions,* causes, f activities,^ things, 
or selves; || every process is self-transcendent, and, we have 
seen, the self- transcendent is not to be nothing. "Whatever is 
rejected as appearance is, for that very reason, no mere 

* Chapter V. t Chapter VI. 

J Chapter VII. Chapter VIII. 

|| Chapters IX and X. 

1 68 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

nonentity. ... To take it as existing somehow and some- 
where in the unreal, would surely be quite meaning- 
less." 119 Any phase of appearance a spatio-temporal 
system, for example is real to the degree to which it is 
self-coherent. And the degree to which a system is self- 
coherent is held to be the extent to which it is com- 
prehensive. 

Those who would make Bradley a synonym for their own 
mistakes appear to take it that by an appearance he means 
something static and self-contained. Thus they find it con- 
venient to concentrate on one of his arguments against 
relations as separate entities (which would be static and 
self-contained, if there were any such entities in Bradley 5 s 
viev). They carry out that concentration with such single- 
minded emphasis that this argument alone is made to seem 
Bradley's positive theory of relations. Standing on that 
misunderstanding, they make the monstrous assertion that 
he defied reality to relations. 

To take it that for Bradley relations are static, self-con- 
tained entities, like pieces of string, and to leave out of 
account tl\e dialectic of relational fact, or quality and 
relation, that is set forth in chapter III, would be perforce 
to ignore the relational identity of every being short of the 
Absolute. It would be to take it that relations are self- 
identical. Ten of the possibly many senses which "relation", 
used to designate a self-identical entity, might have are 
made out br Dr. Ewing. He acknowledges that none of 
them is gernane to Bradley's theory of the matter. Two 
general sense* of the term in question, used to designate 
self-contained entities, are considered in detail and rejected 
roundly by Bradley himself. "I will now deal briefly with 
relations, takm as what may be called 'external 5 or 'internal' 
merely. And, jthough at the cost of some repetition, I will 
show how sucii a distinction, if we insist on it as ultimately 
valid, involve* us again in contradiction. It exhibits once 

169 



Bradley's Dialectic 

more the discrepancy inseparable from all relational 
thought."* 

"What should we mean (I will ask first) by a relation 
asserted as simply and barely external? We have here, I 
presume, to abstract so as to take terms and relations, all 
and each, as something which in and by itself is real inde- 
pendently. And we must, if so, assume that their coming 01 
being together in fact, and as somehow actually in one, fe 
due in no way to the particular characters of either thfe 
relations or the terms. From neither side will there te 
anything like a contribution to, or an entrance into, the 
other side or again to, or into, that union of both which 
we experience as a relational fact. Undeniably the fact is 
somehow there, but in itself it remains irrational as admitting 
no question as to its 'how' or 'why'. Or, if you insist !>n a 
reason, that would have to be neither in the terms nor the 
relation, but in a third element once more independently 
real and neither affecting, nor again affected by, either the 
relation or the terms. This, I suppose, is the way in which 
relations have to be misunderstood, if you take them as 
external merely and also as ultimately and absolutely real. 

"What (I ask next) should, on the other hand, be meant 
by a relation viewed as absolutely and merely internal? 
You, I presume, still in this case would continue to take the 
terms each one as, so far, in and by itself real, ind as inde- 
pendent absolutely of any whole that could be said to contain 
them. And you would go on to attribute to tlje particular 
characters of the terms, as so taken, some acfual relation 
or relations which you find, as you say, to fall between them. 
Something like this, I suppose, is or ought to be meant by 
a relation which is asserted to be real ultimately; and internal 
merely. j 

"The idea, I would add, that I myself accept aty such doctrine 
as the above seems to myself even ludicrous. And tf whom, if to 
* Collected Essays, p. 641. 
170 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

any one, it should be attributed in fact, I will not offer to 
discuss. In any case, to assume it as the necessary alternative, 
when the mere externality of relations is denied, is (I 
submit) an obvious, if perhaps a natural, mistake."* Having 
given this detailed statement of the matter, Bradley proceeds 
to deny reality to merely external relations on the familiar 
grounds that, as quite external to their terms, such alleged 
relations fail to relate anything. Therefore mediating rela- 
tions would be required and so on indefinitely. He then turns 
to his statement of the nature of a merely internal relation. 
This alleged relation, like a piece of string in need of glue, 
simply falls between its terms. The assumption that any such 
view is the sole alternative to his denial of external relations 
he terms an obvious mistake, and the notion that he accepts 
it Bradley finds ludicrous. 

Relations for Bradley are at once internal and external. 
As the dialectic of chapter III makes out in detail, a rela- 
tion is internal to its qualities in so far as it contributes to 
constitute them; it is external to its qualities in so far as it 
transcends them; "every relation (unless our previous 
inquiries have led to error) has a connection with its terms 
which, not simply internal or external, must in principle 
be both at once."t The connection must be both at once 
because if it fell wholly without the terms (and so were 
wholly external) it would not connect them; and if it fell 
wholly within the terms (and so were wholly internal) it 
would be exhausted in them, and thus fail to be a nexus. 

We have seen that the self-transcendence of quality through 
relation is the relational identity of the character of any 
appearance. Relational identity is other than the absolute 
identity of A is A. In judgement the one yields degrees of 
truth and error, in propositions the other gives barren 
tautologies. The disjunction here is that between an identity 

* Ibid., pp. 642, 643. My italics. 
f Ibid., p. 641. 

171 



Bradley's Dialectic 

differentiated by its context, on the one hand, and an 
identity that is intrinsic, or differentiated by nothing extrinsic 
to itself. 

We have seen that on Bradley's doctrine of relations 
identity implies qualitative difference. Any relational situa- 
tion is different in character from any other one. This 
excludes the possibility of two beings that differ solo numero. 
The two symbols A, and A, could not be strictly the same. 
On the other side of the disjunction between relational and 
absolute identity, numerical difference is affirmed, and the 
merest possibility that all beings are different in character 
is excluded. This disjunction is the principle that divides the 
relational dialectic from any form of procedure in thought 
for which " A is A " is valid by virtue of the Law of Non- 
Contradiction. 

For Bradley, we have noticed, "A is A" is a barren verbal- 
ism, as is "A is not both A and not-A". In Appearance 
there are no absolute identities and there are no absolute 
contradictories. Any identity is the result of differentiation, 
and the differentiation mediates between that identity and 
its opposite. Thus, in the process that Appearance is, there is 
a middle term between any two moments of becoming. 
Any phase of process will be intelligible to the extent that 
this mediation of moments is realized in judgement. For 
that mediation or differentiation of quality is the relational 
identity of any appearance, any judgement, any degree 
of reality however abstract, or however concrete. 



II 

In conclusion, let us ask whether or not Bradley can 
answer Hume. A discussion of this question will afford an 
illustration of the disjunction between relational and abso- 
lute identity. We shall see that Bradley can no more answer 

172 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

Hume than Hume can answer Bradley. Reduced to its 
simplest terms, the main reason why this is so is that not-p 
means something for Bradley that is radically different 
from what it means in Hume. 

We have seen that Bradley denies the validity of the Law 
of Non-Contradiction and identifies the contradictory with 
the contrary. The issue of this union we have seen to be 
a theory of negation and identity as relational. In this matter 
of dialectical principle Bradley is following Hegel. "Hegel 
has taught us this and I wish we could all learn it." 

There is no evidence that it ever occurred to Hume to 
deny the validity of the Law of Non-Contradiction as it is 
explained, for example, in the Port Royal Logic. For Hume 
identity and negation are absolute, not relational. Any 
impression, any idea, is what it is by virtue of its own intrinsic 
nature, not by virtue of any context of relations whatever. 
Thus for Bradley identity is relational; for Hume identity 
is absolute. 

The difference here is that of a disjunction: no qualita- 
tive identity may be both relational and absolute. This is to 
say that the dialectic of Bradley is utterly different in prin- 
ciple from the logic in Hume. Hence neither one could be 
expected to answer (as distinguished from condemn) the 
other. They do not speak the same language. Bradley and 
Hume can be and are opposed to each other, but neither 
one can properly be taken to be a refutation of the 
other. 

This is not to forget that those who derive their philosophy 
from Hegel, either directly or by way of Bradley and 
Bosanquet, take it that they can and do refute Hume and 
his kind. Following the lead of T. H. Green, they first 
demolish the theory of impressions and ideas, and then 
assume that Hume's negative analysis of causal inference 
depends, both in point of the text and of the logic of it, on 
that indefensible psychological theory. On two counts the 

173 



Bradley's Dialectic 

assumed dependence in question may be seen to be ground- 
less. 

One of these counts is historical in nature. Hume's 
failure to find a necessary connection between anything 
designated cause and anything designated effect did not 
begin with him. He drew it from Malebranche, as his 
reference in the Treatise to the relevant portions of Recherche 
would suffice to make plain, if there were no other evidence 
in the matter.* And Malebranche derived the conclusion 
from Cordemoy, to whom he refers in that connection. 4 
Malebranche and Cordemoy were Rationalists and their 
views in psychology do not comprise a theory of impressions 
and ideas as copies of impressions. The line of argument 
for which Hume is perhaps best known developed in- 
dependently of Hume's psychology, if only because Hume 
did not discover or develop it in the first place. 

The other count in question is of a textual nature. The 
relevant text of the Treatise does not bear out the assumption 
that Hume's negative analysis of causal inference depends 
on his dogmatic psychology.! Rather it constrains us to 
conclude that (to put the matter in too few words) Hume 
applied the tests of apagogic reasoning and sense-perception 
to two well-known questions about experience: why is a 
cause always necessary? and why must the same cause 
produce the same effect? 

Nevertheless, it may be urged in some quarters, Bradley's 
dialectic does constitute an answer to Hume. For it shows 
his faith in absolute identity and apagogic reasoning to be 
groundless. Since apagogic reasoning proceeds to demon- 
stration by showing that the contradictory of a given state- 
ment is itself self-contradictory, to show a faith in that to 
be misguided would be to explain that the Law of Non- 

* See my Malebranche and Hume. Revue Internationale de philosophic, 
Vol. I, No. i. 

f See my Hume's Theory of the Understanding) London, 1935, Chapters 
II and III. 

174 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

Contradiction is a snare and a delusion. Yet that is the basic 
issue as between the Hegelian dialectic and logic. Is the 
contradictory one with the contrary or are they radically 
distinct? These alternatives constitute a disjunction: both 
of them cannot be true. 

Bradley denounces A is A and A is not both A and not-A 
as being tautologies and therefore empty. They do not and 
cannot represent any advance in thought; therefore they 
are not judgements. Now any tautology in thought will be 
as empty or as full as it is. That depends wholly on what a 
mind puts into it. Whenever A is A is construed in no sense 
whatever, but is merely parroted, it is quite empty indeed. 
Yet ordinarily A is A is used to designate the logical structure 
of whatsoever is self-identical. This may be an analogy; 
and it is fair to presume that no one denies that an analogy 
may give information to anyone who thinks it out. 

To denounce any case of A is A as a tautology is to object 
to it for being what it is. And the categorical principle A 
is A is invalid if and only if it be true that identity is 
relational. The alleged truth of this latter statement is in 
no wise brought to light by the denial of its opposite. 
No more is it established by the identification of the con- 
tradictory and the contrary. For to identify them is by 
that very fact to assume that negation and identity are 
relational. 

If and only if the contradictory be identified with the 
contrary does it follow that every opposition, every fission, 
in experience is mediated by a third moment, or is relational. 
That conclusion is a necessary condition of the dialectic of 
relation and quality. Without the mediation of any process 
of differentiation by a third moment, the mutual internality 
of relation and quality would disappear. 

Presumably the protagonist of the Idealist dialectic will 
reply that his position is not a matter of assumption. His 
dialectic elucidates what is the truth. The Law of Non- 
175 



Bradley's Dialectic 

Contradiction is false because it would affirm mere or pure 
negation. Any such notion is intolerable because it entails 
the infinite judgement. "Wisdom is not blue" is a case in 
point. Now, plainly, that judgement is silly; but that it is so on 
the grounds advanced by Bradley is doubtful. "A something 
that is only not something else, is a relation that terminates 
in an impalpable void, a reflection thrown upon empty space. 
It is a mere nonentity which cannot be real." Some of the 
confusions, at least, that are basic to the notion that the Law 
of Non-Contradiction entails the infinite judgement have 
been exposed by W. E. Johnson. Moreover, Bradley's own 
statements about the matter would seem to beg the question; 
as is done, for example, in the passage quoted above. 
Therein "a something that is only not something else" is 
identified with "a relation ..." Now anything that were 
"only not something else" a mere not would be something 
outlandish indeed. But it is not in the least to defend the 
reality of a something that were merely not something else, 
to go on to point out that, by assuming this negative some- 
thing to be a relation, Bradley begs the question whether 
negation is relational or not. 

Just as any negation that does not entail a common ground, 
a third term, between its contents is rejected by Bradley 
as being empty, so he condemns any statement of absolute 
self-identity as being inane. We have seen that Bradley 
writes in this connection that "The principle of Identity is 
often stated in the form of a tautology, 'A is A'. If this really 
means that no difference exists on the two sides of the 
judgement, we may dismiss it at once. It is no judgement at 
all. As Hegel tells us, it sins against the very form of judge- 
ment; for while professing to say something, it really says 
nothing. It does not even assert identity. For identity without 
difference is nothing at all." Now this too begs the question 
at issue. If and only if this conception of identity be true are 
we constrained to dismiss the Law of Identity. In the passage 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

quoted above, Bradley makes plain his belief that what 
Hegel tells him on this score is indeed the truth. Yet 
that is the question at issue. And that question is merely 
begged by the assumption that all identity is identity in 
difference. 

Moreover, in order that he might show that all identity 
is identity in difference, Bradley would have to show that 
some cases of identity are not properly represented by A is A. 
This could not be established by any appeal to experience, 
for no one could so canvass experience as to be sure that 
no case of identity (such as that of two cases of the same hue) 
is properly represented by A is A. Consequently, Bradley is 
obliged to arrive at the truth of his principle by assuming it. 
And that is what in fact he does. His theory of negation, his 
dialectic of quality and relation, his theory of predication, 
and the coherence theory of truth are not proofs of the 
principle of identity in difference; rather, they are elucida- 
tions of it. 

Something of the bearing of the disjunction between 
absolute and relational identity on the opposition between 
Hume and Bradley may be indicated in the following way: 
It has been pointed out elsewhere that "The five major 
assumptions of Hume's epistemology would seern to be (i) 
that experience may be exhaustively analyzed into elements; 
(2) that every simple idea is the copy of a simple impres- 
sion; (3) that resemblance and difference (taken ' 'philo- 
sophically") are neither qualifying predicates nor relations; 
(4) that what is distinguishable is separable; and (5) the 
attraction of association."* 

In the same connection, it was pointed out that the 
second and fifth of these assumptions state the main content 
of the first, and also that the third and the fourth assump- 
tions express Hume's own view of his so-called atomism in 
philosophy. For Hume held that the elements of his 

* Hume's Theory of the Understanding, London, 1935, p. 218. 

177 M 



Bradley's Dialectic 

philosophy are not connected by their being the same, or 
by their being different. 

This is to say that the resemblance of any simple ideas 
to each other is not "a point or circumstance" distinct from 
the respective ideas themselves. Their resemblance is not 
"a common circumstance"; for it is in no wise distinct from 
those very ideas. To find that two simple ideas pi and ps 
are resembling is to find that pi and ps are the same in 
quality or character. In Hume's view, this is to find that 
they are the same not in point of "a common circumstance' ' 
that would be distinct from those simple ideas, but rather in 
virtue of their being qualitatively the same in and of them- 
selves alone. 

Thus we may see that for Hume "resemblance" means 
what is meant by the qualitative identity of simple ideas. 
A resemblance is any case of a qualitative identity (e.g., a 
perceived middle C) that exists in at least two cases of itself; 
and any case of a qualitative identity that exists in two or 
more cases of itself is properly called a "resemblance". 
This holds likewise of complex experiences. Experience 
MNOPj and experience P 2 QRST are respmbling or the 
same in respect of their constituent P, for P is the same in 
P l and P 2 . Thus it may be noticed that Hume assumed that 
"resemblance" designates a qualitative identity that is 
distributed in at least two cases of itself. And this is to assume 
that a single quality or character (e.g., perceived azurite) 
may be repeated in two or more cases of itself. 

Thus, on Hume's theory of resemblance, the elements of 
experience are intrinsically self-identical, and not what they 
respectively are by virtue of any context whatever. This is 
to say that those elements (as distinguished from the 
"perceptions of the mind" which they contribute to con- 
stitute) are self-contained, each one intrinsically and in its 
own right. That is why, on this view, any difference is the 
mere "negation" of a resemblance. Consequently any com- 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

plex may be analyzed into its elements without remainder, 
and without thereby altering those elements. "Whatever is 
distinguishable is separable," on this view, because wherever 
there is a distinction a separation may occur. For whatever 
is distinct from anything else is a distinct being whose 
identity is intrinsic, not relational. Since this self-identity is 
intrinsic or absolute, it is not alterable. No more is it con- 
tingent, in any sense of the term. This is why, on Hume's 
view, any distinct and therefore distinguishable element of 
experience is separable from any other without the effect 
of any alteration whatever in either one. In virtue of the 
intrinsic self-identity of it, no element can be altered. And 
since resembling elements are no more than the qualitatively 
identical elements themselves, no analysis of a complex can 
either alter, or find anything above, the elements of the 
complex altered. 

We saw that Bradley denounces as quite fatuous any 
notion of relations as "merely internal". In that connection 
it was remarked in passing that Hume's analysis of the basic 
philosophical relations of resemblance affords a good 
example of a "merely internal" relation. In this connection, 
we saw, Bradley writes: "What (I ask next) should, on the 
other hand, be meant by a relation viewed as absolutely 
and merely internal? You, I presume, still in this case 
would continue to take the terms each one as, so far, 
in and by itself real, and as independent absolutely 
of any whole that could be said to contain them."* A 
quality as "ultimately and absolutely real" would be a 
quality whose character or nature were quite self-con- 
tained. 

Any such entity would be what it is in virtue of itself 

alone. This is to say that it would be itself absolutely, not 

by virtue of any relations to anything ulterior to itself. If 

we take two such entities, and notice that their being 

* Collected Essays , p. 642. 

179 



Bradley 's Dialectic 

"related" derives from and is exhausted by the respective 
entities themselves, then we have merely internal relations. 
"Relations would be merely internal if, the terms being 
taken as real independently, each in itself, the relations 
between them (as a class, or in this or that particular case) 
in fact arose or were due merely to the character of the 
terms as so taken."* This view of the matter is condemned 
roundly by Bradley as a "ludicrous" if "natural" mistake. 

The theory of relations as merely internal to or exhausted 
in and by the terms that constitute a relation could only be' 
mistaken, in Bradley's view, because it fails to see that a 
relation, to be at all, must be at once internal and external 
to its terms. A relation must be partially internal to its 
terms in order that it may relate them: it must be partially 
external to them in order that it may be anything at all in 
its own right. 

Consequently, any theory of relations as merely internal 
is in stark opposition to the doctrine that is elucidated in 
the chapter Relation and Quality. To be a quality at all is to 
be distinct, and to be distinct is to be differentiated. This 
differentiation or relation contributes to constitute what it 
differentiates. So far, then, a relation is internal to its 
qualities. But no relation is internal merely. Any relation 
will to some extent fall between the qualities it differentiates. 
In this respect a relation is the third moment in the un- 
ending fission that is process. The third moment is the 
middle term by which the fission is at once differentiated 
and mediated. We have seen that the necessary (though 
of course not sufficient) principle of this dialectic of quality 
and relation is that the contradictory be identical with the 
contrary. That principle yields negation and identity as 
relational, or mediated by a third term. 

We have noticed that for Hume the identity of simple 
elements of experience is absolute. Any element of experience 

* Ibid., p. 665. 
180 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

either resembles or is different from any other, and a 
difference is merely the "negation" of a resemblance. For 
Hume a resemblance is any qualitative identity that is 
distributed in at least two cases of itself. Thus a resemblance 
is merely internal to or wholly exhausted in its terms: it is an 
example of what Bradley calls a "merely internal" relation. 
Thus we may see how it is that Hume and Bradley stand on 
the opposite sides of the disjunction between absolute and 
relational identity. 

Since this point would seem to be easily accessible, it is 
the more surprising that it is so frequently slurred over, or 
missed altogether. As a recent example of this, consider the 
following statements made by Professor H. H. Price. "I now 
turn to the contention, that Hume errs by being an Atomist. 
This is an even more extraordinary muddle, and I shall not 
attempt to unravel it in detail. I will simply ask, what is 
the positive alternative to Atomism? What do non-atomistic 
philosophers assert? I suppose they assert that what we are 
aware of is always a continuum of some sort, a continuous 
stream of events, or of presentations, or what not."* Now 
this is indeed an extraordinary muddle. One would have 
thought that in Oxford it would be remembered that 
"what (some) non-atomistic philsophers assert" is monism, 
and a monism that derives from the internality of relations. 
For those who identify the contradictory and the contrary 
Hume's atomism is perforce an error, as is the logical 
atomism of every other thinker for whom A is not both A 
and not-A. The Bradleian dialectic condemns Hume's 
atomism and all logically cognate doctrine as a sin against 
the very principle of thinking. This condemnation may be 
mistaken; the principle it would defend may entail difficul- 
ties of a very discouraging nature; but it is anything but 
muddled. Bradley knew what he was doing. And he carried 
it through to the bitter end of Ultimate Doubts. 
* Philosophy, Vol. XV, No. 57, p. 27. 

181 



Bradley's Dialectic 

To see that absolute identity and relational identity are 
wholly opposed is to see that neither Bradley nor Hume 
is or could be a refutation of the other. For neither one of the 
two terms of a disjunction is a refutation of the other one. 
It is open to Bradley to demonstrate his first principle of 
identity in difference if and only if the contradictory be 
identical with the contrary. For then and only then will 
differences be mediated by a third term. 

The asserted identity of the contradictory with the 
contrary can be known to be true if and only if the Law of 
Non-Contradiction is known to be invalid. How is this 
knowledge to be arrived at? Not by induction, surely. And 
any attempt to arrive at it by deduction could only beg the 
question. Since, according to the proponents of it, identity 
in difference is the principle of all thought, perforce it would 
be the principle of the extirpation of the Law of Non- 
Contradiction. And it is so employed as the two-edged 
discursus of a dialectic which seeks and claims to be self- 
justifying. The Law of Non-Contradiction is held to be 
invalid not because it is inconsistent, but because it stands 
as an inane and sterile obstacle in the way of the fertility of 
dialectic. 

To this it must be replied that a method of elucidation 
may be as fertile as anyone likes to deem it, or cares to make 
it. This would recommend it to a man interested in elucida- 
tion for its own sake. But it would not even tend to show the 
Law of Non-Contradiction to be invalid. The principle of 
identity in difference can be instituted only by assuming that 
the laws of thought are invalid, not by an appeal to the 
dialectic that denies them. 

It has been pointed out above that absolute and relational 
identity stand opposed as the terms of a disjunction. We may 
be free to elect the one or the other; we may not adopt both 
without confusion. There are those who suggest that any 
choice between these two disjuncts will be more or less 

182 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

unconscious, and dictated almost entirely by matters of 
temperament. As some men are born little Platonists and 
others little Aristotelians, so in some men there is a predilec- 
tion for the relational dialectic of imagination, while others 
are bound by logic. 

It would seem to be fairly clear that no rational grounds 
for a choice between these disjuncts can be demonstrated 
a priori. The hackneyed point that you cannot contradict 
the Law of Non-Contradiction without thereby reinstating 
it is not free from confusion, and is of no avail at all against 
Bradley's position. Bradley does not first affirm the Law of 
Non-Contradiction and then turn around and deny it, 
thus to fall into contradiction. He denounces what is to him 
no law but a delusion, and proclaims as basic to elucidation 
the Law of Contrariety. This excludes the Law of Excluded 
Middle and affirms the reality of a middle term between 
any two beings. The oft-repeated point in question assumes 
(among other things) that any denial of the Law of Non- 
Contradiction will be a contradiction. Yet this is hardly the 
case. A denial may be the rejection of a proposal; not the 
unsaying of something previously affirmed by the person 
who rejects a proposal. 

Since the logic of contradictories, as distinguished from a 
dialectic of contraries, could hardly exclude the Law of 
Non-Contradiction, any attempt to find by or in logic 
grounds for a choice between absolute and relational 
identity could only beg the question. For any such attempt, 
consistently carried out, perforce would involve the Law of 
Identity. 

No more is it open to a follower of Bradley to avail himself 
of the dialectic of contraries to prove the primacy of rela- 
tional identity. We have noticed that Bradley does not 
make the attempt. Rather, he denounces the laws of thought 
as tautologies; upon the assumption that to be a tautology 
is to be inane; and proceeds to identify the contradictory 

183 



Bradley's Dialectic 

with the contrary. Yet this is done without benefit of either 
logic or dialectic. Clearly logic could not sanction that 
union. No more could the dialectic. For if and only if the 
contradictory be identical with the contrary is the dialectic 
of contraries valid. To appeal to that dialectic for a demon- 
stration of the assumption that identity is relational could 
only beg the question. 

So much, it may be objected, is even obvious. And in 
some quarters it will be urged that in the matter before us 
the touchstone of rational decision is supplied by experience* 
In the sentience that is perception or imagination the 
incipient workings of the dialectic may be discerned. Once 
this process has passed over into the stage of elucidation that 
is judgement, the inherent logic of experience is made 
explicit to some extent. This logic is (as the coherence 
theory of degrees of reality and truth makes plain) self- 
fulfilling and self-fulfilled. Anyone who understands it at all 
will realize its justification to be internal and not a matter 
of "linear" demonstration. For the binding constraint of the 
relational way of thought derives from the coherence of it 
with itself. And that self-coherence derives from the intern- 
ality of relations which is the essence of process or experience 
everywhere and always. 

The appeal to experience, considered so hard-headed and 
sensible by its proponents whether they be Idealists, Positiv- 
ists, Neo-Realists, Pragmatists, or members of other philo- 
sophical sects, is a hardy and widely variegated perennial. 
Men have been appealing to experience for a long time. In 
her name they have castigated their opponents; men no 
less sensible than themselves, perhaps, who then replied in 
the name of their experience. Thus Idealists pour scorn on 
the "atomism" of views of experience not their own. 
And those who seek to elucidate the content of their 
perceptions in terms of (say) sensa declare Idealists to be 
dim, thoughtless, or merely unintelligible. 

184 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

Presumably it is fairly plain that to appeal to experience 
is to appeal to it as it is understood in one way or another. 
There is more than a little evidence that some Idealists 
emphasize this point in the course of their criticism of their 
precritical opponents. Those thinkers construed experience 
wrongly because they were imbued with an epistemology 
that is false. Now Hume's conception of experience, it may 
well be agreed, is crudely mistaken. This has been made out 
on a score of grounds; grounds that are internal to Hume's 
assertions in that regard, and have no connection with "the 
relational way of thought". Such criticism is one thing, and 
exigetical; but to argue that the notion of impressions and 
ideas, or any other view, is false because contrary to Hegelian 
tenets, is another, and doctrinaire. Yet this is a practice to 
which some proponents of the Idealist dialectic are prone. 
They make the assumptions upon which the dialectic of the 
Phenomenology can be elucidated, and then proceed to 
establish those presumptions by showing that contrary views 
are not in accord with them. If and only if you adopt the 
relational view of thought may you correctly construe 
experience. For that is the only way in which you may 
construe experience in accordance with the relational way 
of thought. 

This question-begging procedure is not improved upon, 
of course, by those who use it on the opposite side of the 
disjunction between relational and absolute identity. The 
assumption that experience consists of self-identical "atomic" 
constituents, rather than "relational situations", is shot 
through with presumptions. The main point is simply that 
to appeal to a doctrine about experience for grounds upon 
which to decide between logic and dialectic is perforce 
futile. The validity of the Law of Non-Contradiction could 
hardly be made out by any appeal to the conception of 
experience that is developed in the Phenomenology. No more 
could the dialectic be justified by any one or more of the 

185 



Bradley 5 s Dialectic 

conceptions of experience which the relational way of thought 
denies. In short, either you adduce an empiricism that is in 
accord with logic, or that is in accord with the dialectic, as 
the case may be, and so beg the question; or else you adduce 
a contrary empiricism, and so perforce miss the point of 
your attempted justification. 

Any appeal to the given can only beg the question for 
the other fellow. For it will assume that what for you is 
given (in the innocuous but quite wholesome sense made 
out by Professor Price) is likewise given for soijieone else*. 
But in philosophy no one is obligated to decide questions 
for the other fellow. And it is presumptuous or worse to 
make the attempt. If he is capable of following your argu- 
ments, he is competent to make up his own mind in taking 
basic decisions. 

It would seem that there is no rigorous means by which 
logic or Hegelian dialectic can justify as distinguished 
from explain itself to the other fellow. Each student of 
philosophy can only ask himself about the relevance of the 
one or the other to what he himself finds for examination 
and elucidation. To do this is indeed to appeal to experience. 
But it is to appeal to his own experience as being his own, 
not as something that imposes a philosophical obligation on 
his fellow men. 

If a man finds in his experience any two respects that 
are strictly the same, then he finds something that is incom- 
patible with the conclusion of the dialectic of relation and 
quality that identity implies qualitative difference. We have 
seen above (chapter VIII) that if identity implies qualitative 
difference, then every difference, however slight, is unique. 
Thus no two experiences could be strictly the same in any 
respect; for every experience would be unmatched in every 
respect. It might be suggested that the difference between 
this case of perceived middle C and that one is infinitesimal 
in some rather ambiguous sense or other of that term. This 

1 86 



Relational and Absolute Identity 

would be a singularly inappropriate suggestion in this con- 
nection. For the differences that are relations are constituent 
differences. They are actual differentiations in sentience, not 
ideal distinctions. If identity implies qualitative difference, 
then no two experiences can be strictly the same in any 
respect. 

Protagonists of the relational way of imagination are 
constrained by doctrine to deny that any two experiences, 
whether perceptual, imaginative, or intellectual, are in any 
icspect tb~ same. This is to say that for these protagonists 
every experience, however comprehensive or merely tenuous, 
is quite unique. To be sure, they sometimes deal with this 
stark consequence by saying that every experience is in part 
unique. But then the parts that would not be unique or 
unmatched would be matched by something else. And this 
would fly in the face of the conclusion that identity implies 
qualitative difference. The doctrine of relational identity 
is categorical; it admits of no exceptions. That is why it can 
only be rejected by anyone in whose consciousness there are 
ever two or more experiences that are in any respect strictly 
the same. 



INDEX 



ABSOLUTE, the, and our imperfect 

knowledge of it, 73 
as beyond Appearance, 1 i g 

passim 

as allegedly not supra-rela- 
tional, 127-129 
Bradley's conclusion about, 

152 
And, the enumerative vs. the 

conjunctive, 19-21 
" Appearance," meaning of, for 

Bradley, 25, 26 

Appearance and succession, 71, 72 
as relational throughout, 15- 
42, 119-122, 167-169 

Bradley, can he answer Hume ?, 

172-181 
Broad, G. D., 162-164 

Consistency, or self-coherence, the 
standard of Reality, 63, 64 

Contradiction, Law of, 22, 23 
true meaning of, 117 

Contradictory, the, and the Con- 
trary, 23-25, 117, I74"i79 

Contrariety and identity, 109-118 

Contrary, the, 109 passim 

Degrees of individuality, 1 55 
of truth and reality, 157-160 

Differentiations as relations, 28-31 
relations, and judgement, 83 
passim 

Error, 94-104 

and irrelevance, 96-99 

and truth, 97-99 
Ewing, A. C., 42-55, 165, 1 66, 169 



Hegel, 22 
Hume, 172-181 



Ideal, the, and the " what " and 

the " that," 81-87 
Ideality and self-transcendence, 

85-87 

of the finite, 81-91 
Identity and difference/ 22 

implies difference, 67, 68, 

147-150, 161 
in difference, 1 09- 1 1 8 
relational vs. absolute, 150, 

151, 175-181 

Immediacy as quality, 26-29 
Individuality, degrees of, 155 
Internality of relations, 28-31, 
35-42 

Judgement, 23, 83-93, 112, 115, 
1 16, 1 18 

Knowledge of the " this " and the 
" mine," 73-79 

Laird, Professor John, on internal 
relations, 51, 52 

Monism, Bradley's, 133 

Negation, self - coherence, and 

Reality, 63-65 

Negation and the Absolute, 1 3 1 
NonrContradiction, Law of, 182- 

183 
Numerical difference, 144-146, 



Predication, judgement, and the 

Absolute, 92, 93 
Price, Professor H. H., 181 
Psychical fact, 82 



Qualities, primary and secondary, 
i5 16 



1 88 



Index 



" Quality," meaning of; for 

Bradley, 26, 27 

Quality and relation, 22 passim 
as immediacy, 26-29 

Reality and the Absolute, 68-75 
the standard or criterion of, 

63-65 

and Monism, 70-73 
as against pluralism, 65-70 
" Relation," meaning of, for 

Bradley, 26, 27 

Relational way of thought, the, 
"62, 81% , 
Relations, as independently real, 

17-22 

as differentiation, 28-31 
and Quality, 22-40, 73-78 
and the " this " and the 

" mine," 73-79 I 

as " merely internal," 170- ! 

172 I 



Space and time, 56-61 

Tautology and judgement, 22, 23 
The " this " and the " mine," 73- 

79 
as affording an intimation of 

the Absolute, 122-126 
Thought, the relational way of, 

62, 81-93 

as the moment of differentia- 
tion, 83 

Time and space, 56-61 
Truth and the Absolute, 104-107 
and coherence, 104-108 
and judgement, 105, 106 
and Reality, 104-108 

Ultimate complexes, an erroneous 

view, 112-114 
Unity in diversity, 1 1 i-i 18 

"What," the, and the "that," 
81-91 



Printed in Great Britain by 
Billing and Sons Ltd., Guildford and Esher